GJontell JtnuiEraUy Htljaca, Men) Jfnrlt LIBRARY OF THE SAGE SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY Date Due MftRg" ^2 ^ -Nt -PES- DW— 5" warn ^ i^E rr^ fi^UggW" 4S&3 ,J Y 9 80 Klf ' 5 raSeM • .'-'i »PH^963 3 ^jsosiea tt OECT^" ^a^nrr *=F +4-( ; 3 19^4 U»£^1 2™ Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31 924092291 1 1 5 KANT'S CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY KANT'S CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY FOR ENGLISH READERS JOHN P. MAHAFFY, D.D. FELLOW AND TUTOR OF TRINITY COLLEGE, DUBLIN PROFESSOR OF ANCIENT HISTORY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF DUBLIN JOHN H. BERNARD, B.D. FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, DUBLIN ARCHBISHOP KING'S LECTURER IN DIVINITY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF DUBLIN A NEW AND COMPLETED EDITION VOL. I. THE KRITIK OF THE PURE REASON EXPLAINED AND DEFENDED iLon&Ott MACMILLAN AND CO. AND NEW YORK I889 PREFACE TO THE NEW EDITION The able co-operation of one of my colleagues, to- gether with class-room criticisms of others, has en- abled this work to appear in a new edition, not only purged of many defects, but completed by the addition of several chapters on the Dialectic and Methodology of the Pure Reason. It is also offered to the public in a cheaper form, one volume containing the whole Kritik, while the second gives a revised translation of the Prolegomena. Without the help of Mr. Bernard, who has written the whole commentary from p. 237 onward, and who corrected and improved all the rest, it is not likely that this, my third declaration upon Kant, would ever have seen the light ; and indeed I will here add, that I am not responsible for certain Hegelianisms which appear in his notes on the Dialectic. But haec hactcnns. It is my desire to state candidly and unreservedly what my younger colleague has done to help me. For to make such PREFACE acknowledgment is a duty not always recognised among literary men of established standing. The plan of this commentary is to adhere much more faithfully than Kuno Fischer, or indeed any other Commentator we have met, to Kant's text, which we have followed paragraph by paragraph, shortening and simplifying, but shirking no diffi- culties. We have also marked all our own reflec- tions with a 1, which refers only to the paragraph or chapter to which it is prefixed. It seems more advisable to do this than to encumber the book with foot-notes, which interrupt the reader's train of reading. But though this Commentary claims to be clear and consistent, it is not, and cannot be, either easy or short. It is not easy, because the subject is not easy, and deals with notions exceedingly abstract, and only familiar to those who have made mental science a subject of special study. It is not short, because Kant's book, if worth reading at all, is worth reading and knowing accurately, and no pains are misplaced if they result in a full and comprehensive grasp of the greatest metaphysical system the world has yet seen. We are too much accustomed to general histories in which a few pages are devoted to each thinker, so PREFACE that the impressions left on the reader's mind, even if true (which is seldom the case) are at all events vague and misty. The greater lights in the philo- sophical firmament can only be understood by special study, and should therefore be made the subject of separate monographs. We have endeavoured to do this for Kant, being convinced that of all meta- physicians he is certainly the greatest, and perhaps the most imperfectly understood. In the preface to the former edition I spoke of the fancy for philosophical novelties in England, and endeavoured to call attention to Kant, as of all modern Germans the greatest philosopher, and certainly the best adapted for practical minds. At all events it is absurd to begin the study of Schelling or Hegel without a prior intimacy with Kant, and how many men are there now in England who thoroughly understand the Critical Philosophy ? It is also a remarkable fact that within the last few years, philosophy even in Germany has reverted, as I ventured to predict, from modern extravagance to the soberness of Kant. His works are being reprinted, illustrated, and attacked, on all sides. The sensual school have discovered that the refutation of Kant alone will give them a lawful victory, and to this task they are applying all their energies. PREFACE The influence of Grote and J. S. Mill, and the con- stant appointment of Mr. Bain as a State Examiner in Philosophy, brought this way of thinking into undue prominence. All the youth of the country have been crammed with Mr. Bain's handbooks, and have neither time nor inducement to read an antidote. We must therefore look to the Universities for a fair hearing, and trust that there at least enlightened teachers will not accept as true what the State has made fashion- able. A polemical chapter on the Association School, which appeared in the former edition of this work, has been omitted, as the controversy may now be regarded as obsolete. The most important contribution to the better understanding of Kant, in my edition of Kuno Fischer's Comment- ary, was the true explanation of Kant's refutation of idealism. A patent absurdity had been universally attributed to him, and I showed that his attitude had been totally misconceived. My argument was candidly accepted by competent critics, and mio-ht now be called a commonplace, did not Prof. Kuno Fischer's recent declaration (a Critique of Kant, 1882) show that it has not yet penetrated into his mind. As the work is intended for English readers, we have referred uniformly to the translation of Kant's Kritik in Bonn's Library, still the most serviceable PREFACE and to my own edition of Kuno Fischer's Comment- ary. I may add that my other references are to the following editions of the respective books, viz. the ninth edition of Mr. Mill's Logic, and the third of his Examination of Hamilton, and the fourth edition of Mr. Lewes' History of Philosophy. The references to the Prolegomena of Kant are to the pages of my former edition, which will be indicated in the new edition appended as a second volume to the present. I conclude this Preface as I did the last, seventeen years ago, with the earnest hope that the many readers of my former books on Kant will find in this a maturer and clearer exposition of the same views. J. P. MAHAFFY. Trinity College, Dublin, March \6th, 1889. CONTEXTS CHAPTER I THE TWO PREFACES TO THE KRITIK PAGE I."! On Kant's Style . . I 2. Analysis of the First Preface . i 3.5 Contrast of the two Prefaces . 6 4. The Second Preface . .8 $.% Consistency of the Two Editions of the Kritik . 19 CHAPTER II THE INTRODUCTION Preliminary Considerations — The Distinction in Kind between the Faculties . ... 24 1. Pure and Empirical Cognition . . 27 2. We possess a priori Cognitions, even in Ordinary Ex- perience . . .28 3. We require a Science to determine these Systematically 3 1 4. Analytical and Synthetical Judgments . . . .32 5. All Theoretical Sciences contain Synthetical Judgments a priori . . • • • 37 6. The General Problem of the Pure Reason . . . 39 7. General Conception of a Science called Kritik of the Pure Reason .... .41 8.H History of Kant's Discoveries . . 42 CONTENTS QHAPTER III THE TRANSCENDENTAL AESTHETIC PAGE I. Definitions ... 47 2 & 4. Metaphysical Exposition of Space and Time . 48 3 & 5. Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time 51 6. Deductions • 54 7. Objections Answered 57 S. General Remarks on the Aesthetic . 60 CHAPTER IV INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC I. Of Logic Generally 7° II. Of Transcendental Logic . 73 III. Division of General Logic into Analytic and Dialectic . 74 IV. Division of Transcendental Logic similarly . 77 CHAPTER V TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC, PART I The Transcendental Analytic ... 78 Of the clue to discover the Categories .... 79 Of the Logical Use of the Understanding ... 81 On the term Function . . . . 83 9. Of the Logical Function of the Understanding in Judgments 85 10. Of the Categories. ....... 88 H Note on Mr. Mill's Derivation of the External World 91 Table of the Categories . 94 11. Remarks on the Table . 96 12. Quodlibet ens est unum verum bonum . 98 1i Kant and the Critics of his Categories . 100 Contents CHAPTER VI INTRODUCTION TO THE DEDUCTION OF THE PURE CONCEPTS OF THE UNDERSTANDING, SECTION I l'AUE 13. Of the Principle of Transcendental Deduction . . . 105 Transition to the Deduction . 109 CHAPTER VII THE DEDUCTION OF THE CATEGORIES. THE FIRST EDITION AND THE PROLEGOMENA 'i Various forms of the Deduction . 112 The Prolegomena . . . 114 The First Edition . 117 CHAPTER VIII THE DEDUCTION OF THE CATEGORIES. THE SECOND EDITION OF THE KR1TIK The Deduction in the Second Edition 123 Nature of Synthesis . . . . 125 The Transcendental Apperception . 127 Production of Objects . . . 129 Application of the Categories .... 130 Office of the Imagination . . . 132 Results . 135 Supplement to the Aesthetic . 137 CHAPTER IX THE TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC, BOOK II. THE ANALYTIC OF PRINCIPLES The Transcendental Faculty of Judgment . . 143 Of the Schematism of the Pure Understanding 144 If Schopenhauer Criticised . 15 J 15- 16, 1/ IS, 19. 20, 23' 24. 27. 24-; CONTENTS CHAPTER X SECOND CHAPTER OF THE ANALYTIC OF PRINCIPLES PAGE 1. The system of all the Principles of the Understanding . 155 The Highest Principle of all Analytical Judgments 156 2. The Highest Principle of all Synthetical Judgments 157 3. Systematic Exposition of the Principles . 160 Note, Analysis of Combination 162 CHAPTER XI THE MATHEMATICAL PRINCIPLES 1. The Axioms of Intuition ... 1 63 2. The Anticipations of Perception . . 165 Proof of Continuity . 168 CHAPTER XII THE DYNAMICAL PRINCIPLES I . Analogies of Experience . 171 A. First Analogy — of Substance 174 Its bearing on Kant's Idealism 177 B. Second Analogy — of Causality . 180 The Empirical Criterion of Substance . 185 C. Third Analogy — of Co-existence 1S9 CHAPTER XIII THE POSTULATES OF EMPIRICAL THINKING GENERALLY 1. The Postulates of Empirical Thinking . 193 2. The Postulate of Possibility . 194 3. The Postulate of Actuality . . . . . 195 CONTENTS I'AGE 4. The Postulate of Necessity . . . .196 5. Relation of Possible and Actual 197 6. General Remarks . . 199 1 CHAPTER XIV KANT'S ATTITUDE TOWARDS IDEALISM 1. Kant's Attitude on Idealism . . 202 2. Collation of Passages . 203 3. His View of Things per se , 206 4. His Critique of Berkeley . 209 5. His Critique of Descartes . . . 214 6. Refutation of Kant's Critics 219 CHAPTER XV THIRD CHAPTER OF THE ANALYTIC OF PRINCIPLES 1. The Contrast of Phenomena and Noumena . 222 2. The Categories only of Empirical Use 223 3. Cause of the Belief in Noumena . 225 CHAPTER XVI APPENDIX ON THE AMBIGUITY OF THE CONCEPTS OF REFLECTION 1. The Nature of Transcendental Reflection . 229 2. Identity and Diversity . . 230 Agreement and Opposition . 231 Internal and External 231 Matter and Form . . . . 232 3. The Transcendental Topic . . 234 4. Analysis of Something and Nothing . . . . 235 CONTENTS CHAPTER XVII TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC, PART II PAGE I. Of Transcendental Illusion . 2 37 II. A. Of Reason in General . .240 B. Of the Logical Use of Reason 2 4' C. Of the Pure Use of Reason • 242 CHAPTER XVIII THE CONCEPTS OF PURE REASON 1. Of Ideas in General . . 245 2. Of Transcendental Ideas ... . 246 3. System of Transcendental Ideas . . • 251 CHAPTER XIX THE DIALECTICAL SYLLOGISMS OF PURE REASON 1. The Transcendental Paralogism • ■ 254 2. The Transcendental Antinomy . . 254 3. The Transcendental Ideal . • 254 11 The Categorical Syllogism and the Absolute Subject . 255 CHAPTER XX SYNTHETICAL TREATMENT OF THE PARALOGISMS First Paralogism — of Substantiality . 260 Second Paralogism — of Simplicity . . 262 Third Paralogism — of Personality . 265 Fourth Paralogism — of Ideality (of external relation) . 267 Discussion in Second Edition . . . 269 CONTENTS CHAPTER XXI ANALYTICAL TREATMENT OF THE PARALOGISMS PAGE Dicta of Rational Psychology , . . . . .271 Critique thereon ...... 272 Mendelssohn's Argument for Immortality . 274 Transition from Rational Psychology to Cosmology . 277 CHAPTER XXII THE ANTINOMY OF PURE REASON Cosmical Concepts . . .281 1. System of Cosmological Ideas . . 282 2. Antithetic of Pure Reason . 286 CHAPTER XXIII THE ANTINOMIES Of Quantity . 289 Of Quality 291 Of Relation . 294 Of Modality . 297 U Remarks on Fourth Antinumy 300 CHAPTER XXIV THE INTEREST OF REASON IN THESE CONFLICTS 3. Interest on Side of Dogmatism . 3°3 4. Necessity of a Solution . . 3°6 5. Sceptical Account of the Cosmological Questions . 308 6. Transcendental Idealism supplies the Key 3 10 b CONTENTS CHAPTER XXV THE CRITICAL SOLUTION I'AOli 7. Critical Decision of the Cosmological Conflict . 312 8. Regulative Principle .... 3>5 9. Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle . . • 3 J 7 Transition from Mathematical to Dynamical Antinomies 319 Possibility of Causality through Freedom ... 321 CHAPTER XXVI THE IDEAL OF PURE REASON 1. The Ideal in General . . . 330 2. Prototypon Transcendentale 331 CHAPTER XXVII PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD 3. Three Possible Proofs ... . 336 4. The Ontological Proof 338 5. The Cosmological Proof . . . 341 6. The Physico-Theological Proof . 346 7. Kritik of all Speculative Theology . 348 CHAPTER XXVIII THE REGULATIVE USE OF THE IDEAS Negative Conclusion of the Analytic . . . . • 3SI 1. The Principle of Homogeneity .... 3c, 2. The Principle of Specification . . . . . • 3 S4 3. The Principle of Continuity of Forms . . . • 3S4 Ultimate Aim of the Natural Dialectic of Human Reason . 3 c 7 CONTENTS CHAPTER XXIX TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF METHOD l'AGE The Discipline of Pure Reason . . 36 1 1. In the Sphere of Dogmatism . 362 2. In Polemics . 367 3. In Hypothesis . . 371 4. In Proofs . • 373 CHAPTER XXX CANON, ARCHITECTONIC, AND HISTORY The Canon of Pure Reason . . . -377 1. The Ultimate End of the Pure Use of our Reason . 378 2. The Ideal of the Supreme Good . . 379 3. Opinion, Knowledge, and Belief . 381 The Architectonic of Pure Reason 384 The History of Pure Reason .... . 3^8 CHAPTER I THE TWO PREFACES § i. IT The philosophical student who has been discouraged from opening the Kritik of the Pure Reason, by its reputa- tion for obscurity and difficulty, will be agreeably surprised by the clearness and the elegance of Kant's first Preface. So easy is the flow of thought, so felicitous the choice of expression, that we can only find stray hints of the arduous task that awaits us. The explanations of a commentator are almost needless, and his analysis cannot do better than adhere as closely as possible to the rich and suggestive lan- guage of the great philosopher himself. 1 § 2. Among the various branches of human knowledge, says Kant, there is one in regard to which our reason is condemned to a very strange lot, being troubled with questions which we cannot decline, seeing that they are forced upon us by our very nature, but which, nevertheless, we cannot answer, since they transcend all our faculties. Our reason falls into these perplexities unawares. It 1 Mr. Lewes's remarks [History of Philosophy, vol. ii. p. 458) are, in the first place, too severe, and in the second place unjust, as they omit to mention the genuine and even sublime eloquence of some of Kant's writings. We may notice that Kuno Fischer's Commentary is silent on these Prefaces, the second of which utterly destroys his theory as to Kant's idealism. I E 2 THE FORTUNES OF METAPHYSIC chap. commences from principles whose use in the field of ex- perience is inevitable. From these it proceeds, according to its nature, to ascend higher, and to approach more remote conditions. But we soon discover that such a pur- suit will never end, because fresh questions are ever starting up. Under these circumstances, nothing remains but to take refuge in first principles, which transcend all experience, and which, nevertheless, excite so little suspicion that even the common sense of mankind does not quarrel with them. These, however, lead the reason into such obscurities and contradictions that we cannot but infer the presence of some hidden errors. Yet the discovery of these errors is impossible ; because the principles adopted by the reason, as they transcend completely the bounds 1 of experience, will neither acknowledge nor submit to any test which originates within it. This arena of endless dispute is called Metaphysic. There was a time when her claims to be called Queen of the Sciences were admitted by all. It is now the fashion to despise her, and, like the mourning Hecuba, she sits forgotten and forlorn ; in the words of Ovid : Modo maxima rerum, tot generis natisque potens — nunc trahor exid inops ! At first her rule, under the administration of the Dog- matists, was despotic. But this barbarous form of govern- ment degenerated through internal dissensions into complete anarchy ; and the Sceptics, a sort of nomads who hate all settled conditions, periodically scattered the community. But they were too few in number to prevent mankind from continually attempting a reconstruction, though without any fixed or consistent principle. It seemed indeed once 1 We uniformly translate Grenu, bound, reserving the term limit for Schranke. Cf. Kant's Proleg. p. 154, for the distinction— an im- portant one, though confused in all the translations. INDIFFERENTISM NO SOLUTION in later times, as if the celebrated Locke's Physiology of the Human Understanding would put an end to the dis- putes, and settle for ever the lofty claims of Metaphysic. But no sooner had the descent of the pretended queen been traced to the low origin of common experience, and her assumptions accordingly questioned, than this genealogy was found out to be fictitious, and accordingly she persisted in her claims. And so things returned to the antiquated and rotten dogmatism, and to the consequent contempt in which the science was held. Now that men think every path has been tried in vain, disgust prevails, and total indifference, the mother of chaos and of night in the sciences, but the prelude of a better day. For it is vain to assume an artificial indifference on subjects which cannot be indifferent to human nature ; and the pretended indifferentists, though they may endeavour to disguise it by assuming a popular garb, are ever falling back into the metaphysical assertions which they profess to despise. Nevertheless, this indifferentism is a phenomenon deserving our deepest attention. It is the result of the ripe judgment of our age, which will no longer tolerate insecurity or false pretence. We hear, 1 indeed, complaints of shallowness, and of the decay of sound science. But well-founded sciences, such as Mathematic and Physic, refute this calumny, not merely by holding their ground, but even by making great onward strides. So would other branches of knowledge progress also, were their principles placed on a firm basis. ' In default of this indispensable requisite, doubt, indiffer- ence, and severe criticism are rather evidences of a thorough- going spirit. Our age is the proper age of Kritik (criticism), to which everything must submit. Religion desires to escape by its sanctity, Legislation by its majesty.' They con- 1 Cf. the first note to this Preface. PROVINCE OF THE KRITIK chap. sequently excite just suspicion, when contrasted with those sciences which have freely and fairly met the test. Reason is therefore challenged to begin afresh that most difficult task, the knowledge of itself, and establish its claims, not by oracular dicta, but according to fixed and unchange- able laws. The court which must decide this issue is the Kritik of the Pure Reason itself. This does not mean a Kritik of books and systems, but of the faculty of reason, as regards what knowledge it may attain, apart from all experience. It is in other words the deciding of the possibility or impossibility of metaphysic in general, and the determining of its sources, extent, and bounds, exclusively from principles. This path, says Kant, I have pursued, and flatter myself I have discovered the source of all the errors which divided reason against itself. I have not evaded these questions by falling back upon the impotence of the human reason, but have determined them completely from principles, and, after discovering the point at which reason fell into a misunder- standing with itself, have completely and satisfactorily solved them. I have aimed at completeness above all things, and I venture to say there is not a single metaphysical problem which is not either solved or provided with a key for its solution in this book. Pure reason being a unity complete in itself, any analysis which fails to solve a single question fairly suggested concerning it must be cast aside as perfectly idle. The reader need not wonder at these pretensions as boastful and impertinent. They are infinitely more modest than the programme of any ordinary system that pretends to prove the simple nature of the soul, or the necessity of a first origin of the world. For these things far transcend all the bounds of experience, whereas the present work merely analyses the reason and its pure thinking. It is in i ITS' CERTAINTY AND CLEARNESS 5 fact to be compared to common Logic, which analyses completely all the simple operations of thought, 'except that the question here proposed is, How much can we attain through these operations if deprived of all the materials and the assistance of experience ? ' If, then, the matter of the book must be complete and explicit, it may also fairly be demanded that the form of its demonstrations should be certain and dear. Of course all mere opinion is worthless, when we seek to establish a priori knowledge. But it is for the reader to judge whether the grounds advanced by the author are certain, and equal to his pretensions. He has already asserted that he considers this quality absolutely indispensable. Some few points, however, which are not essential to the work might possibly excite suspicion, and may, therefore, be pointed out before- hand. 1 There is no investigation more important, or that has given the author more trouble, than the so-called Deduction of the Pure Categories. This investigation has two sides. The first concerns the objects of the pure understanding, and is intended to explain the objective validity of its a priori concepts concerning them. This is an essential part of Kant's plan, since it shows what the understanding and the reason can know, apart from all experience. It stands upon a basis perfectly independent of the second side of the deduction, which considers the understanding subjectively, and endeavours to analyse its faculties. ' As the question, How is the faculty of thought itself possible ? can only be answered by inferring a cause from its effects, my solution,' says Kant, ' may seem (though this is not really the case) 1 As the reader can hardly understand them, before he has mastered the passages in question, he will be reminded of these explanations at the proper places. c CLEARNESS to be a mere hypothesis, and the reader may think himself at liberty to differ from me.' But this will not invalidate the former side of the argument. 1 As to clearness, the reader has a right to expect logical and discursive clearness in the arguments, which has been carefully attended to, and sesthetical and intuitive clearness, by means of sufficient examples and illustrations. The length and intricacy of the discussion have compelled the author to dispense with these to an extent he did not originally intend. A general survey of a system is often impeded by these illustrations, and ' many a book would have been far dearer if the author had not endeavoured to make it so clear? Metaphysic is the only science, as we shall show, which is capable of absolute completion within a short time, by means of united efforts : for it is nothing but the systematic inventory of what we possess by pure reason. Nothing can here escape us ; nor can any experience increase our know- ledge. By means of the present Kritik the ground has been cleared and prepared, and here the reader must perform the part of an impartial judge. When we proceed to build up the system of pure reason, under the title, ' Metaphysic of Nature,' he should join us as a zealous co-operator, especially as the investigation of these details is easy, and more a recreation than a difficult task. §3.H Such in substance, and to a great extent in words, was the remarkable Preface with which Kant introduced his great treatise to the philosophic world. It bears a strong family likeness to the utterances of other intellectual reformers, and suggests the mental attitude of Bacon and of Descartes, of Locke and of Hume. There is the same boldness in 1 The reader should bear in mind that this passage refers to the First Edition of the Kritik. THE SECOND PREFACE asserting the discovery, and the same modesty in attributing it not to genius, but to method. There are the same hopes of a speedy termination of error, the same conviction that even ordinary minds, when armed with proper weapons, can help in the victory. Kant's analogy to Bacon was indeed so striking, that he prefixed to his second edition a memorable motto from the Preface to the Instauratio Magna- — ' De nobis ipsis silemus. De re autem, quae agitur, petimus, ut homines earn non opinionem sed opus esse cogitent : ac pro certo habeant, non sectae nos alicuius, aut placiti, sed utilitatis et ampli- tudinis humanae fundamenta moliri. Deinde ut suis com- modis aequi — in commune consulant, et ipsi in partem veniant. Praeterea ut bene sperent, neque instaurationem nostram ut quiddam infinitum et ultra mortale fingant et animo concipiant : quum revera sit infiniti erroris finis et terminus legitimus.' In his first Preface, therefore, Kant explained the his- torical position of the Kritik, and announced that he was about to revolutionise philosophy by a new method. And yet similar claims had often before been made, and had hitherto failed. What was the peculiar novelty of Kant's method which inspired him with such extraordinary con- fidence ? How did he discover it ? In the Preface to the Second Edition, published in 1787, six years after the First, these questions are fully answered ; and, furthermore, the positive practical results of his apparently negative and speculative system are brought before the reader. This second Preface is therefore a material improvement to the work, and is of peculiar interest, as disclosing to us the line of thought that led Kant to his discoveries. 1 1 Thus, at the very outset, those are in error who affirm that this Second Edition is no improvement on the first. HISTORY OF THE SCIENCES § 4. ' We can easily determine,' says Kant, ' whether we are pursuing any branch of knowledge scientifically by our success in attaining results. If after much preparation, we are constantly coming to a standstill, and are obliged to recommence, and if our fellow-labourers cannot agree with us how our common object is to be pursued, our proceeding is no science, but a mere groping in the dark, which we shall do well to abandon, even with the sacrifice of many lofty aspirations.' The history of any recognised science will prove this position. Consider Logic. Since Aristotle it has never lost one inch of ground. But what is far stranger, it has never gained anything either, and appears to be complete and settled. If modern writers have attempted to enlarge it by psychological chapters on the human faculties, or metaphysi- cal on the origin of knowedge or the nature of certainty, or anthropological on human prejudices, they have merely shown their ignorance of its nature. ' We do not enlarge, but disfigure the sciences, by confusing their boundaries.' And the boundaries of Logic are strictly determined as the science which expounds the formal laws of all thought, and nothing but thought. The success of Logic is, however, owing to its narrow scope ; for Logic is forbidden to con- sider any of the objects of knowledge, and must confine itself to the understanding and its form. It is accordingly but the outer court of those proper sciences which add to our real knowledge. With far more difficulty did reason enter upon the strict path of science, when objects also were concerned. If such sciences are to be rational, they must contain a priori knowledge, 1 and this knowledge of the reason may be related to the object in two ways — either as merely deter- 1 So far as this means power of prediction, no one will dispute it. THE TURNING-POINT mining it and the concept of it (when given from elsewhere) or as also making it actual. This latter is the practical cognition of the reason [as when it produces from itself, for example, the idea of duty.] The former is theoretical cogni- tion. In either case the direst confusion must result if the pure part, in which the reason determines its object alto- gether a priori, be not separately treated. 1 Mathematic and Physic are the two theoretical branches of rational knowledge which aim at determining their objects a priori — the former quite purely, the later partly so. Mathematic attained the safe position of a science long since among the Greeks. Yet this does not prove that its safe highway was constructed easily, as in Logic. Kant thinks that for centuries, especially among the Egyptians, it consisted in mere groping, and that the great change was owing to a Revolution, produced by a happy thought of some forgotten genius. He notices that even in later times the discoverers of special principles were remembered though these principles were unimportant ; and this he ascribes to the indelible effect produced by the first great Revolution. In what did this Revolution consist ? ' Whoever it was,' says Kant, 'that first demonstrated the equality of the [base] angles of an isosceles triangle found 2 new light dawn- ing upon him ; for he found that he could not trace out and learn the properties of the figure from what he saw in it, or from mere thinking about it, but rather from what he had added to 1 Kant in no way implies that these different parts of cognition are given separately, but says that if we confuse them in our treatment, we are like men spending money without keeping accounts, and then un- able to ascertain what part of their outlay can be diminished when economy becomes necessary. 2 ' Who first demonstrated the right-angled triangle ' is Mr. Lewes's translation, which makes no sense. He was probably misled by n clerical error (equilateral) noticed by Kant himself in one of his letters. io THE HISTORY OF EXPERIMENTAL SCIENCE chap. the figure according to concepts a priori, and had then repre- sented by a construction. He also found that all the safe a priori knowledge he could attain about it was merely the necessary consequence of what he had himself introduced into it, according to his own concepts." 1 This statement may well be regarded as the very corner-stone of all Kant's discoveries. In natural philosophy progress was far slower, and it is only since the days of Bacon that it has attained the high- way of science. But even from an empirical point of view there is a close analogy in its history to Mathematic. When Galileo and Torricelli and Stahl began to make their well-known experiments, the same light dawned upon them also. They comprehended that reason discovers what it produces according to its own plans ; that it must, so to speak, take the initiative, according to fixed principles sup- plied by itself, and compel nature to reply, instead of wait- ing upon her for instruction, since chance observations are not connected by such necessary laws as the reason seeks and requires. Those phenomena alone that agree with some fixed principle of the reason can be regarded as the laws of nature. ' Armed with such principles, then, in one hand, and with experiments framed according to them in the 1 Mr. Lewes's translation of this passage (Hist, of Phil. vol. ii. p. 467) appears, through some oversight, not to be even grammatical, and, more- over, obscures the point of the argument. Mr. Meiklejohn's translation would here have afforded him a fair version. His interpretation of the passage is equally erroneous ; for he thinks Kant is insisting on the metaphysical method as opposed to the experimental, and is highly in- dignant at the proposal to study nature through our ideas. But Kant is really showing the vast superiority of the experimental method over that of mere observation. In the latter case the mind can only note down occurrences ; in the former it approaches the facts with a theory of its own construction, and compels nature to say whether the facts conform to it or not. Surely this just difference is acknowledged by every scien- tific inquirer. The next paragraph should have made the point plain to any careful critic. METAPHYSIC BEHINDHAND other, our reason must approach nature to learn from her not in the capacity of a scholar, but in that of a judge, who compels his witnesses to give their evidence. And so even Physic owes its happy revolution to the idea of seeking from (not inventing for) nature that information, of which reason coidd know nothing of itself, according to what reason had itself introduced into nature.' 1 Up to this discovery physical philosophers were merely groping in the dark. 2 Metaphysic has not hitherto been so fortunate. It is a peculiar and isolated branch of knowledge, aiming at what lies beyond experience, and that through mere concepts, 3 without representing them in figures, like Mathematic. And here men have been constantly meeting with checks, and endeavouring to begin afresh, so that the science may be compared to the arena of a tournament, in which none can establish any lasting possession. This is evidently mere groping in the dark, and among pure concepts too, where verification is not easy. Why has the high road of science not been discovered in this branch of our knowledge ? Is it imaginary ? Then why has our nature been visited with such unavoidable and restless longing ? and can we trust it in other things, if it here proves a delusion and a snare ? Or is it our fault, and have we hitherto failed to discover the right way, for want of the proper method ? Surely the examples of Mathematic and Physic, re- modelled by a sudden revolution, are sufficiently remark- able to induce us to make a similar attempt in Metaphysic, 1 I have marked the italics by way of answer to Mr. Lewes's criticism. - Cf. Bacon, "mera palpatio." De Aui^. Sci. v. 2. 3 Cr. Kritik, p. 435, for the difference between the mathematical and philosophical methods. We refer throughout to Mr. Meiklejohn's Translation. THE ANALOGY OF ASTRONOMY chap. for they are obviously analogous to it as rational cognitions. Hitherto it was assumed that our knowledge of objects must conform to them, and all attempts to extend it a priori, by means of concepts, have failed. Let us attempt the problem of Metaphysic under the assumption that the ob- jects must conform to our faculty of knowing them, — an assumption which at first sight agrees better with the re- quired possibility of knowing objects a priori — that is, of determining something concerning them before they are given to us. ' This idea resembles that of Copernicus, who, when he found that the motions of the stars could not be explained by assuming them to revolve round the spectator, tried the effect of making the spectator revolve, and the stars remain at rest.' In Metaphysic a similar attempt can be made as regards the intuition of objects. And Kant made this attempt successfully some years before he discovered how to make it in the other parts of the science. If our intui- tion must conform to the nature of its objects, how can we know anything a priori about these objects ? If the object must conform to the peculiar nature of our intuiting faculty, we may easily do so. But we cannot stop at intuitions, and are compelled to consider them as representations of some object which we endeavour to determine through them. This object then must be conceived. I may either assume that the concepts by which I determine the object conform to it, and then arises the old difficulty of obtaining any a priori knowledge ; or I may assume that the objects conform to these con- cepts. If I change the expression, and say that experience conforms to my concepts, the result is the same. For in and through experience alone do the objects become known to us. This assumption then seems to promise good results, KANTS METHOD 13 for experience is a species of knowledge, and knowledge pre- supposes the Understanding that knows. The Understand- ing again presupposes certain rules, by which it acts, and these rules must be considered logically prior to the objects given through them. If we wish to express these rules, we can only do so by a priori concepts, to which, accordingly, the objects of experience must necessarily conform. Such is the result attained by Kant's Analytic, and these a priori rules, by which the Understanding proceeds, when it applies itself to experience, are the Kantian Categories. There are other objectors of which the Reason alone forms Ideas, and indeed is bound to do so, but which cannot be given in experience, or at least given as they are thought by the Reason. In our attempts to think these objects we shall find an excel- lent test of our new way of regarding the problem, which is founded on the principle that we can only know that a priori of objects which we have ourselves introduced into them. 1 This method, Kant adds, in a note, is borrowed from physicaTscience, and consists in seeking the elements of the pttreTeason in such a way that our results can be confirmed or refuted by an experiment. We cannot indeed make ex- periments with the objects of the pure reason (as in natural philosophy), for they are ever beyond the bounds of all ex- perience. But we can do it with the con cepts and principles which we assume a priori, by so arranging them that the same objects can be regarded from two different aspects — first, as objects of Sense and Understanding suited to our experience; secondly, as objects that are only thought, and suited to the isolated Reason, transcending all experience. If we find that, when things are regarded from this double point of view, our reason is at harmony with itself, but if 1 Mr. Mill, in citing this passage {Exam, of Hamilton, pp. 31, 32), omits the important words a priori. 14 PLACE OF THE UNCONDITIONED chap. from a single point, unavoidable contradictions arise, then the experiment has proved the justice of our distinction. 1 Our attempt succeeds perfectly, and promises Metaphysic the sure path of science in its first part, which is concerned about such pure concepts as can. have corresponding ob- jects given in experience. The possibility of a priori knowledge can now be perfectly explained, and the laws which lie a priori at the basis of nature (in the sense above explained) can now for the first time be satisfactorily proved. But there results a conclusion very adverse to the second part of Metaphysic, which is that we can never advance beyond the bounds of experience, and yet this was the chief object of the science. ' Nevertheless, this very result tests the truth of our first estimate of rational knowledge a priori, which was that it concerns phenomena, and abandons the thing per se as actual indeed in itself, but unknown to us.' The Reason, indeed, necessarily requires the Unconditioned to complete the series of conditions we find in phenomena. [We cannot comprehend our mental phenomena without presupposing necessarily a substance called Mind, beyond and beneath all its various manifestations. This illustration will explain what Kant means by the necessary belief in the Unconditioned.] Supposing that as long as we assume our empirical know- ledge to conform to objects per se, the Unconditioned cannot possibly be thought without contradictions, but that assuming objects, as mere phenomena, to conform to our manner of representing them to ourselves, the contradiction vanishes [by confining the Unconditioned to things per se], then the 1 Kant's second Preface was written in answer to the criticism and controversies excited by the First Edition, and therefore implies a gene- ral knowledge of the book, without which the following observations are necessarily obscure. I AIM AND VALUE OF THE KRITIK 15 latter assumption is established. We may, however, be able, on practical grounds, to re-establish a priori what has been shown to be unattainable by the speculative reason. In fact, the ground may have been only cleared for such a result. (This test, as Kant's note says, is similar to that employed in chemistry, where the elements which have been separated by analysis are again combined to reproduce the original substance. Our Analytic separates pure a priori knowledge into two heterogeneous elements, viz. things as phenomena, and things per se. Our Dialectic combines them again into harmony with the necessary idea of the Unconditioned, and finds that this can only be done by adopting the distinction.) Kant expressly tells us he has adopted this hypothetical way of stating his conclusions, in order to show the train of thought by which he arrived at them. He insists that they have been perfectly established in his work, by the nature of Space and Time, and of the Categories. Copernicus's theories were at first mere hypo- theses ; they ended not only by being demonstrated, but by leading to the establishment of Newton's Law of Gravitation, which could never have been discovered had they not been assumed. In this attempt, then, made after the model of geometers and physical inquirers, consists the Kritik of the pure reason. It is a treatise on the method, and not a com- pleted system, of the science known as Metaphysic. But owing to the unity and completeness of reason within itself, the outline of the science is indicated by our method ; and for the same reason Metaphysic, like Logic, is capable of completion once for all, when the faculties of the human mind have been surveyed in their nature and their use. But what, it may be asked, is the value of this Kritik ? It appears to be at first sight only negative, prohibiting our 16 KNOWING AXD THIXKIXG chap. speculative reason from transgressing the bounds of ex- perience. This is indeed its first use. But this use becomes f-csifizc, when we consider that previous attempts have, as a necessary consequence, so extended the bounds of mere sense, as to interfere seriously with the proper practical use of the reason. For if such a practical use be necessary to morality, though it cannot be assisted by speculation, it must be secured against interference. You might as well say the police were of no positive use, because it is their negative duty to prevent peaceable citizens from being molested in the pursuit of their business. The analytical part of the Kritik shows that we cannot possiblv have any speculative knowledge beyond the bounds of experience But it must be carefully observed, that though we cannot kncu- objects as things per se, we are able to think them. (In order to know a thing, I must be able to prove its possibility either from its actuality in experience or a priori through reason. But I can think what I like, provided I do not contradict myself Such a thought is only logically possible, and requires something additional to make it really possible : however, this addition need not be sought only in theoretical sources, but in practical also.) ' If we ^ere unab'.e to think things per se there would follow the absurdity of an appearance, without anything to appear.' Xow let us suppose our distinction of things per se and phenomena had not been made. If so, the law of causality must bmd all beings absolutely. It would follow that the kLT™ T "r^ P ° int ° f ™ W ' COUld not * "^ed a thing - r wd as „ pheno^rir t^ti po.nt of vtew ,ts v 1S ible actions cannot i ndee d bei^ bm i THE USE OF IDEAS 17 the result is different when we regard it from the former. Without, therefore, being able to know my soul as free, I liberate my attempt to think it such from an apparent contradiction. 1 Suppose, now, that the freedom of the will were one of the conditions, without which practical morality were impossible, but that the speculative reason had proved such an idea contradictory to itself, then freedom must give way, and with it morality, to make place for the necessity of natural causes. From such a result we are saved by the Kritik. The same great positive uses can be shown in our ideas of God and of immortality. These cannot even be assumed without checking the impertinences of the speculative reason, which, by applying its empirical principles where they are inapplicable, asserts all practical extension of the reason to be impossible. Such knowledge is the real source of immoral unbelief, and must be ordered to make way for faith. We aim then at improving the reason of our pos- terity by setting them to study a sober science, and saving them from wasting time and trouble on idle groping and pretentious dogmatism. Above all, we hope to dispose of all objections against morality and religion after the manner of Socrates, by proving clearly the ignorance of the objectors. And if there be any supposed loss in the surrender of the claims made by the reason, the loss affects the monopoly of the schools, not the interests of humanity. Were the doctrines of the immortality of the soul, and of the existence 1 It must be carefully remembered that in this remarkable discussion (Antinomy, sec. 9) Kant professed to prove, not the existence of freedom, nor its probability, nor even its possibility, but simply that it was not necessarily contradictory to causality. (See Kritik, p. 345.) This guarded attitude has not been transferred to Mr. Lewes's exposition (Hist, of Phil. ii. p. 519). I C CLAIMS OF THE KRITIK of God, ever really established by the subtile arguments and distinctions of the schools ? Has it not been confessed that the public are unable to grasp such refinements, and that the former was rather proved by the profound inade- quacy of the present life to satisfy our aspirations, and the latter by the harmony, beauty, and mercy of nature ? These proofs rather gain than lose, for the schools are taught to pretend to no deeper knowledge, and to confine themselves to the arguments that are accepted by the many, instead of arrogating to themselves the sole possession of such truths. But the schools remain in the possession of a science most useful to the public, though the fact is not recognised ; a science which cannot and need not ever be popular, which refutes the arguments of the philosophers who mystify the public, by objections equally subtile, but saves them from drifting unconsciously into the assumptions and the quarrels that have hitherto disgraced metaphysic. ' Only by means of this science — the Kritik of the Pure Reason — can Materialism, Atheism, Fatalism, Enthusiasm, and Superstition be disarmed. We also cut away the very roots of idealism and scepticism, but this rather affects the schools than the mass of mankind. It would be far more rational of governments to support such a science, than to countenance the ridiculous dogmatism of the schools, which raise an alarm about the public safety, when their cobwebs are torn in shreds, though the public neither notice nor miss them.' The reader will not fail to remember how very similar, even in expression, was the design of Bishop Berkeley. 1 Our Kritik is not opposed to the dogmatic procedure of the reason in its pure cognition as a science, for every pure 1 Cf. Kritik, p. 265, for a like distinction between scepticism and the sceptical method. CHANGES IN THE SECOND EDITION 19 science must demonstrate dogmatically — that is to say, from sure principles strictly a priori. It is opposed to dogmatism, which is the dogmatic procedure of the reason without pre- vious criticism of its faculties} But we do not therefore support shallow talking, which pretends to be popular, or scepticism, which abolishes all Metaphysic. We rather establish this science on a sound and systematic, not on a popular, basis ; and in its future development we must fol- low the steps of the great dogmatic philosopher, Wolff, who may be regarded the originator of thoroughgoing and sys- tematic inquiry in Germany. Had his ground been critically prepared, he might indeed have established metaphysic as a science. § 5. IT These reflections, which agree closely with the analytical and popular account Kant has given of his dis- coveries in the Prolegomena (published in 1783), conclude the exposition of his method and its results. There remains an explanation of the changes introduced into his Second Edition, a subject of less importance, had not Schopenhauer made his pretended discovery that these two Editions differed very materially, not only in exposition, but in doctrine. It was said that Kant had become afraid of the idealistic conclusions drawn from his principles, and had suppressed the passages which resolve the whole external object into our own sensations, and their form (imposed by the mind also). More particularly, there was one paragraph inserted into the Deduction of the Categories which dis- tinctly states that the matter of our intuitions is given by a source apart from, and independent of, the understanding; 1 and a refutation of Idealism was introduced into the Prin- ciples of the pure understanding, in which Kant attempted to prove that the objective existence of things in space is 1 Cf. JCritik, p. 89. 20 THE PREFACES COMPARED chap. the condition of our internal experience. Above all, in the First Edition the distinction between soul and body was explained to be a difference, not of substance (of which we know nothing), but of representation ; and from this point of view the community or relation of both was discussed (cf. Appendix C, vol. ii. of this work). This was supposed to be contradicted or extenuated 1 in the Second and follow- ing Editions, for the purpose, Kuno Fischer thinks, of gaining adherents. The question therefore assumes con- siderable importance ; for it must determine, in the first place, the degree of Kant's own conviction as to the truth of his doctrine ; and, secondly, the real import of his system. Let us then first of all consult the author himself, and consider what he says in his second and more elaborate Preface 2 : — 'As regards this Second Edition, I naturally did not wish to let the opportunity escape of remedying, as far as possible, the difficulties and the obscurity from which may have arisen the sundry misapprehensions that have occurred to many acute men (perhaps without my fault) in their estimate of this work. In the positions themselves, and the grounds of proof , as well as in the form and completeness of the plan, I have found nothing to alter : a fact which must be ascribed partly to the long consideration to which I sub- mitted my work previous to its publication, partly to the nature of the subject itself, — I mean the constitution of a purely speculative reason, which contains a veritable system of members, where everything is organic — that is, where 1 In this particular case we have an exactly parallel statement in the Second Edition. Compare Proleg. p. 234, with Kritik, p. 252. This passage in the Second Edition does not seem to have been noticed by critics. 2 The silence of Kuno Fischer as to these two Prefaces is very re- markable. CHANGES OF DETAIL the whole is for the sake of each individual part, and each individual part for the sake of the whole; so that any defect, however trifling, whether it be a positive error, or a mere deficiency, is certain to betray itself in use. 1 . . . But in the exposition much remains to be done, and in this respect I have attempted to improve this Second Edition, with the intention of clearing away partly the misappre- hensions of the Aesthetic, especially of the concept of Time; 2 partly the obscurity in the Deduction of the Categories ; 3 partly to supply the supposed want of sufficient evidence in the demonstrations of the Principles of the Pure Under- standing ; 4 partly, in fine, to remove misapprehension as to the Paralogisms laid to the charge of Rational Psychology. 5 . . . But the necessary consequence of this improvement, except we made the work altogether too long, is a slight loss to the reader, since a good deal (that did not indeed belong substantially to the completeness of the whole) must be omitted, or put into a shorter form, 6 which, nevertheless, many readers might not wish to lose. This was done to 1 Cf. Kritik, p. xxxix. 2 Kant added Section i. § 6, on Time, and the General Remarks, ii.- iv. (pp. 41-43). In his Introduction, Sections i. and ii. were greatly expanded, and v. and vi. added. 3 From Section ii. § n, of the Transcendental Logic to the end of the Deduction it was completely rewritten. 1 Under each of the Definitions of the Principles (with the exception of the Postulates) the first paragraph, headed 'proof,' was added; as well as two Appendices, entitled, ' General Remarks on the System of Principles,' and the Refutation of Idealism, on which he also adds a note in the second Preface. 6 From the words, ' but we shall for brevity's sake' (p. 241), the whole discussion was rewritten. The third chapter of the Analytic (on Phenomena and Noiimena), and the Refutation of Rational Psychology, were considerably shortened, part of the latter reappearing in the Refutation of Idealism. The De- duction of the Categories is likewise abbreviated. 22 NO REAL CHANGES chap. make room for my present, and I venture to hope now intelligible exposition, which in substance, as regards the propositions, and even in their method of proof, changes absolutely nothing ; but still varies [from the former] here and there in the method of the exposition in such a manner as could not be managed by interpolation. This slight loss, which, by the way, can be supplied, if any one chooses, by a compariso7i with the First Edition, is, I hope, more than counterbalanced by the greater clearness ' [of the present Edition]. 1 In the face of this declaration, which explicitly asserts that nothing whatever has been altered in the system, and which invites the reader to compare the two Editions, we are told that the Second Edition is a mutilated, distorted, and depraved work, caused by the weakness of old age, and the fear of public opinion in Kant ! It can be proved by the theological attitude of this, and of his later works, that these charges are perfectly absurd. It will be also shown in the course of this work that the supposed evidence of the theory is derived from a series of blunders and oversights (if not actual suppressions) in the interpretation of Kant's very clear, though not dogmatic declarations. As Schopenhauer's opinion is fashionable in Germany, we do not wish to open the discussion without giving the reader the means of judging for himself, by comparing the two Editions ; he will find, accordingly, in the footnotes and in the appendices to the second volume of this work, all the passages of any importance which appear in the First Edition only. The results of such a comparison are simply these : that we may safely defy the advocates of the First Edition to find any doctrine there stated to which there is not a corresponding assertion in the Second ; or to 1 Cf. A'ritik, p. xli. NO REAL CHANGES point out a supposed alteration in the Second Edition which we cannot prove to be supported by quotations from the original work. 1 The assertion of the honest author is most decidedly true ; in the propositions themselves, and even in their proof, absolutely nothing has been changed. 1 In Appendix C are added short footnotes, showing the special points of agreement ignored by the critics, and explaining the sup- posed points of difference ; and these will save us in this place from quotations, as well as from the discussion of them. The vacillating attitude of Mr. Mill and Mr. Lewes on this question has been noted in the Preface : they seem unable to resist the force of the argument, but at the same time they will not accept thoroughly the conclusions which these arguments justify. The long note in the second Preface, which refers to the Refutation of Idealism, and endeavours to improve the form of his proof, will best be discussed in connection with the passage to which it refers. The reader may therefore pass it by for the present. Since the first appearance of this work a great deal has been written on the question of the divergence between Kant's First and Second Editions ; in particular, Mr. Stirling has given a valuable history of the controversy in Mind, vol. viii. pp. 525 sqq. His conclusion is, that Kant, ' being scandalised by certain misrepresentations of his doctrine as mere Berkeleianism,' 'allowed the idealistic standpoint somewhat to recede.' 'The passages most loudly idealistic in sound have been omitted from the Second Edition.' But this latter statement cannot be accepted without caution, in the face of the very passages quoted by Mr. Stirling himself. It may be that Kant was somewhat frightened at the charge of Berkeleianism ; but it still appears true, that though he altered his language here and there, he did not at all alter his opinions. This is the view of Ueberweg in his short Latin tract on the subject, and is substantially the view originally put forward in the text. CHAPTER II For the benefit of the reader we here give a general analysis of the Kritik. Its main divisions are called respectively Elementology (pp. 1-430) and Methodology (pp. 431-517). The former is subdivided thus : — sthetic (Sensibility) I. External intuition Internal intuition Logic (Understanding) I I I Analytic (of Concepts) Analytic (of Principles) Dialectic (Understanding) (Judgment) (Reason) I • „ I I a. Categories a. Schematism a. Psychology b. their Deduction b. Principles b. Cosmology 1. Theology THE INTRODUCTION — -PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS The Distinction in Kind between the Cognitive Faculties IT It is evident from the considerations urged in the Pre- face, that a precise theory of the human faculties lies at the basis of Kant's inquiry. He investigates the object through the subject and its conditions. What then are the faculties which teach us all we know of things ? The general answer was given long ago, according to which they have been unanimously divided by philosophers into two classes : on the one hand, sense, sensation, external intuition or impressions from without ; on the other, intellect, reflection, chap, ii THE FIRST DISTINCTION 25 internal intuitio n. though t. 1 But while this distinction was generally admitted, there had ever been an a prioi'i fallacy afloat (as Mr. Mill would say) that only one kind of know- ledge could be true, and that all the information given us from other sources than this must be either illusory or defective. Hence Kant, who discussed the subject in several shorter treatises prior to his Kritik, notices, that under this assumption sensibility and understanding had been in turn exalted into the sole source of true knowledge. 2 The idealists, from Plato to Leibnitz, had mistrusted the senses, and considered sensibility a mere vague and con- fused copy of the reality attained by thought. The sensual- ists, from Epicurus to Condillac, had considered the senses as the primary source from which the understanding com- pounded or abstracted a faint reproduction of the external reality. While, therefore, idealists and realists 3 are opposed diametrically as to the true cognitive faculty, they agree in one point, that Sensibility and Understanding differ in degree only. If Kant had joined either party it would certainly have been that of the idealists. But he perceived that the clearest of all our knowledge, that of geometrical figures, was given by Sense, and that many concepts of the Under- standing, such as the notion of right, could only be appre- hended with great difficulty. He concluded that there 1 It will be seen, however, that Kant distinguishes between internal intuition and thought, as, indeed, Locke had done before him. Internal intuition belongs to sensibility, not to understanding. 2 Cf. Kritik, p. 516. 3 It has been customary in English Philosophy to confine the term Realist to those among the schoolmen who asserted the separate exist- ence of general ideas, as opposed to Nominalists. There is no reason for this restriction. The term is here used to mean the philosophers who assert the separate existence of our external percepts, as opposed to the idealists. 26 THE THREE FACULTIES chap. wer^.tw^^ognitiyeTaculties^JiatalLy distinct,. ancL -differing in kind — Sensibility and Understanding. This^ position is the basis of the whole critical philosophy. Kant himself has explicitly argued this point, and asserted this generic distinction, and any commentator who endeavours to refine it away, by speaking of these faculties as mere laws of development, 1 or by insisting that it is after all the same mind that knows in either case, 2 must be rejected as a misleading guide. It is even questionable whether we should designate them both under the same name of faculty; for we shall see that Sensibility is. a _ passive recep- tivity, whilst Understanding is an active spontaneity. We find, indeed, at a later stage of the Kritik, a_ third faculty introduced, and called the Reason, as distinguished from the Understanding. But if we attend to Kant's own explanation, 3 he tells us ' that the Reason does not give birth to any [new] concept, but only frees the concepts of the understanding from the limits of experience.' In fact, it differs from the understanding not in its essential nature, but in its aim, which is the unconditioned. This second distinction, then, though very important, is by no means so fundamental or so trenchant as that which has just been explained. In accordance with the latter, Kant divides his Kritik of the reason into the Transcendental Aesthetic, or Kritik of the Sensibility, and the Transcendental Logic, or Kritik of the Understanding. The former had been sketched, completely enough, in his earlier treatises, and seems to have cost him far less labour to discover (as it also costs us far less to understand) than the latter. 4 1 Dr. Webb, Intellectual: sm of Locke, p. 168, note. This question 1ms been fully discussed by Dr. Ingleby and Pro- fessor Sylvester. See Sylvester's Laws of Verse, Appendix. 3 Kritik, p. 256. 4 In pointing out the relation between Reason and Understanding in THE SECOND DISTINCTION 27 We can now follow Kant's Introduction, observing closely the order of his exposition. He claims particularly to have been the first who understood, and who therefore stated correctly, the Problem of Mctaphysic. We are about to investigate the human faculties. We can only do this by analysing the effects which they produce, and these effects are know ledge or cognition. 1 The q n flstion, th erefore, of t he Krit ik isthlsT How is the fact of cognition possible ? and more particularly, ho w is syntheti cal a priori cognition possible? 2 Kant's Introduction § 1 . Of the Distinction of Pure and Empirical Cognition. — There can be no doubt that our knowledge begins chrono- logically with experience. For our senses are first affected by external objects, and our understanding is first occupied in 3 comparing or arranging the materials so obtained. But though all knowledge begins with experience, this does not imply that it originates * from experience. For it might, even when obtained from experience, be a composite thing, consisting partly of impressions, partly of additions made (in the act of receiving them) by our understanding. And the Kritik, it must be observed that Kant uses the latter term in two distinct meanings — ( 1 ) as the general faculty of thought, as opposed to Sensibility ; (2) as the special faculty of concepts, as distinguished from Judgment and Reason. The word concept also is used ambiguously, generally being opposed to intuition, but is sometimes used in a wide sense, to signify any mental state [Cf. infra, p. 31, note]. Cf. the analytical table on p. 24. 1 These terms are in the following work used synonymously. - As Kuno Fischer puts it, there are three questions to be answered in the sequel — (1) What is cognition ? (2) Does it exist? (3) How is its existence to be explained, or how is it possible ? 3 Cf. Locke, Essay, book ii. chap. 12, § 1. 4 Cf. the distinction between origo and exordium. 28 A PRIORI COGNITIONS chap. it may be very difficult to separate these additions, and recognise them as such. The question, whether there be cognitions independent of all the impressions of the senses, is not therefore to be lightly decided. [It may be objected, that elements added by the cognitive faculties cannot pro- perly be called cognitions, for they do not teach us to know things different from the mind, but rather interfere with such knowledge. We may admit this objection so far as to allow that if our understanding fuses its own conditions with the impressions received from without, these things, as they are apart from us, cannot be known. But surely, in things as they appear to us, these elements must be of the last importance.] The cognition of these elements is called a priori, as distinguished from that which is derived from experience, which is a posterioi'i. The popular meaning of a priori is simply that our knowledge is derived, as opposed to special experience, from a general rule, which may have been itself originally derived from experience. You say that a man who undermines the foundations of his house might have known a priori that it would fall. Yet he must have learned from experience that bodies are heavy, before he could make this inference. We intend, then, to use the phrase a priori cognition of such as is absolutely independent of all experience. A priori cognitions are pure, if they have no empirical elements mixed with them ; if they have, they are mixed. So the assertion : every change has a cause, is a mixed cognition, because change is a notion that can only be obtained from experience. § 2. We possess certain a priori cognitions, and even the ordinary undej-standifig always contains them. — By what mark, says Kant, can we surely know that we possess any pure, as opposed to empirical, knowledge ? Firstly, Should THEIR CRITERIA 29 there be a proposition which is thought together with its necessity, then it is an a priori judgment, and if underived from any other x not itself necessary, absolutely a priori. Secondly, Experience never gives us strict and absolute, but only comparative universality, gained by induction, and which asserts merely that so far we have found no exception. Should any judgment be thought in strict universality, i.e. so that no exception is regarded possible, it cannot be derived from experience, but is valid absolutely a priori. Empirical universality is then but an arbitrary or contingent exaggeration from the cases we and others know, to all cases ; whereas strict universality is essential to the judgment in which it is found, and points to a peculiar source of knowledge, which we have designated a priori. Necessity and strict universality are certain marks of an a priori cognition, and are inseparable. But as empirical limitation is at times more easily shown than contingency, and it is often more convincing to show the unlimited universality of a judgment than its necessity, we may use these two criteria separately, each of them being in itself infallible. ft This view of the criteria of a priori knowledge has not met with general acceptance. Kant says indeed very justly, that exceptions in experience are more easily shown than abstract contingency in judgments, but many philo- sophers would demur to having necessity proved by uni- versality. Sir W. Hamilton, indeed, distinctly deduces the latter from the former. But the school of Mr. Mill, while admitting the importance of universality, hold that it can prove only a subjective necessity, or conviction, stronger in degree than empirical conviction, but not differing from it in kind. We cannot enter now into the details of this con- 1 Mr. Stirling, in his translation, omits the important words, 'not itself necessary. ' — Text Book to Kant, p. 117. 30 OBJECTIVE NECESSITY CHAr. troversy ; but the important point to be noticed is that the necessary judgment is thought as necessary and exception- less ; in thinking that A is B in such a case, we simul- taneously think that it could not be otherwise. That there are strictly universal and necessary, and there- fore a priori judgments in human knowledege, says Kant, is easily shown in science, by mathematical judgments, in ordinary life, by the assertion that every change must have a cause ; so plainly indeed does the latter concept contain these criteria, that it would be altogether lost were we to deduce it, as Hume did, from mere frequent association, and so allow it only a subjective necessity. But Kant thinks that without any examples, pure a priori principles can be shown indispensable to experience. For experience must deduce its certainty from some fixed principles, and not from rules, which are themselves all empirical and con- sequently contingent. These, he adds, could hardly count as first principles. [Had Kant expanded this proof, it would have been an instance of what he calls his transcen- dental proof, which, from the existence of a fact in our cognition, proves the existence of the necessary conditions from which alone the fact can result. 1 ] He is ' content however, in this place, to note the existence of a pure use of our cognitive faculties, and its attributes.' We must remember that they belong, not only to judgments, but some- times to notions. So the space occupied by a body, or what we consider its substance, cannot be abstracted from it. IT It is, I think, much to be regretted, that Kant did not give more weight to the force of custom, or subjective necessity, as he calls it, and show clearly that it may in all cases be distinguished from real or objective necessity. And this omission in the Kritik is the more remarkable, as he 1 Cf. Kritik, p. 478. MATHEMATIC HERE MISLEADING had before him the writings of Hume, in which the effacing of this distinction was a capital feature. § 3. Philosophy requires a (special) science to determine the possibility, the principles, and the extent of all a priori cog- nitions. — We have seen in the Preface how certain cognitions attempt to transcend all experience, and to enlarge our knowledge independently of it. Nay, this very knowledge is generally regarded as the most noble and important. Such are the problems that concern God, Freedom, and Immortality. But it might naturally have been expected that we should have determined accurately the origin, validity, and value of the principles we have applied in these re- searches. If we mean by naturally, what ought to be, this remark is just ; but if we mean what usually happens, there are solid reasons for expecting this investigation to be long delayed. 1 For the recognised security of mathematical knowledge leads us to expect the same from other a priori cognitions, though they are quite different in nature. And these we pursue with such ardour, that only clear contradic- tions will check us. Unfortunately the facts of experience, which in other sciences test idle theories strictly, have here no application. We ignore the fact that Mathematic, which has made brilliant advances in a priori knowledge, is strictly confined (as we shall see) to intuition. But the intuitions with which Mathematic deals are given a priori, and are therefore hardly distinguishable from pure concepts. 2 This example then excites us with the hope of great results. The fleet dove, that cuts the resisting air in her flight, might think to increase her speed if space were a vacuum. So 1 Cf. Kritik, p. 434. 2 This remark shows why Kant vacillates in his language about space and time, calling them, in an earlier treatise, even conceplus spatii et temporis. He also speaks of the ' ' Begriff des Raumes, " at the beginning of the Metaphysical Exposition of Space. Cf. note, p. 24, supra. 32 THE THIRD DISTINCTION chap. Plato left the world of Sense, and ventured on the wings (as it were) of Ideas, into the vacuum of the pure Under- standing. He failed to perceive that he could make no way, for want of a resisting medium, in which to apply his powers. Speculation is ever hastening to complete her structure, and only then begins to consider the soundness of the foundation. Our suspicions are generally lulled during the construction by this fact, that perhaps the greater part of the work of our reason consists in the mere analysis, in formal explication of the concepts we already (though perhaps confusedly) possess. This sober and useful process seduces the reason to make unwittingly quite a different sort of assertion about given concepts, in which new matter is joined to them a priori, without questioning our right to do so. This distinction must be forthwith explained at greater length. § 4. The distinction between analytical and synthetical judgments. — Though this distinction has become a house- hold truth in philosphy, Kant's analysis has never been accurately expounded. The reader must pay particular attention to it, if he wishes to understand clearly the objective necessity of mathematical judgments. If I assert, says Kant, of a body, that it is extended, I only assert an attribute necessarily contained in the notion. It is by an analysis of the notion that I form the judgment, and it is hence called analytical or explicative, as enumerat- ing clearly elements contained obscurely or confusedly in the concept. But if I assert of a body, that it has weight, I assert what cannot be discovered by any analysis of my notion of a body. This judgment is therefore synthetical or ampliative, enriching our notion by the addition of a new attribute. n LOCKE AND KANT 33 H It was pointed out in a former work x that Locke had completely anticipated this celebrated distinction. Mr. Lewes 2 thinks that a glance at the Prolegomena (p. 24) would have shown any one that Kant fully recognised Locke's priority. We do not know what a glance at the passage might 1 have done, but a careful perusal of it has convinced us that • Kant (who was not 'fully alive to Locke's priority ') did not know the really decisive passage. It is not that cited by Mr. Lewes (Locke, Essay iv. 8, 8) and Kant (iv. 3, 9), but that cited by Dr. Webb in the first chapter of the 4th book of the Essay, where Locke enumerates the four kinds of agreement and disagreement between our ideas: (1) Identity and diversity, viz. 'blue is not yellow;' (2) Relation, viz. ' the three angles of a triangle are equal to two right ; ' (3) Co-existence : ' gold is soluble in aqua regia ; ' (4) Real existence, viz. ' God is.' Here are Kant's analytical, his synthetical a priori, and synthetical a posteriori judgments accurately distinguished, and his very examples almost anticipated ; and in the fourth the distinctness of existential judgments is asserted, which, as we shall see, Kant proved to be synthetical, but sttbjectively so, by the addition, not of an attribute, but of a relation to ourselves, and therefore he also distinguished them from other synthetical judgments. It may be noted, however, that Locke nowhere gives an ex- ample of a proposition which would correspond to Kant's synthetical a priori in Physic, e.g. every event has a cause. That a proposition such as this might be synthetical and yet a priori was perhaps Kant's greatest discovery. 3 1 Fischer's Comm. p. 28, note. ' Op. cit. vol. ii. p. 475, note. 3 Indeed, though the distinction between analytical and synthetical may have occurred to Locke, he does not consistently uphold it — e.g. in iv. 3, 18, when discussing the possibility of an a priori science of ethics, the propositions that he suggests as its basis are only analytical. — Cf. Essay i. 2, 9-20, and iv. 8, 13, on this subject. I D 34 DESCARTES AND KANT chap. U I agree with Kant that mere hints are not anticipations, and do not, therefore, claim any exaggerated importance for a curious passage in Descartes's 14th Regie pour la direction de F esprit, though in it he lays down the Kantian distinction of analytical and synthetical as plainly as it can well be ex- pressed, and shows how previous philosophers had confused these judgments, and consequently fallen into errors. Here is the passage : — ' Passons maintenant a ces paroles : un corps a de V etendue; bien que nous comprenions que dans cette phrase etendue signifie. autre chose que corps, cependant nous ne formons pas dans notre imagination deux idees distinctes, l'une d'un corps et l'autre de l'etendue, mais une seule, celle d'un corps qui a de l'etendue. Au fond c'est comme si je disais: un corps a de F etendue; ou plutot ce qui a de Vetendue a de l'etendue; cela est particulier a tout etre qui n'existe que dans un autre et qui ne peut etre compris sans un sujet; il en est autrement pour les etres qui se distinguent rdellement des sujets. Si je dis, par exemple, Pierre a des richesses, l'idee de Pierre est entitlement differente de celle de richesses; de meme si je dis : Paul est riche, je m'imagine tout autre chose que si je disais, le riche est riche. Faute d'apercevoir cette difference, la plupart pensent a tort que l'etendue contient quelque chose de distinct de ce qui a de l'etendue, comme les richesses de Paul sont autre chose que Paul.' Descartes, however, in trying to evolve the existence of God out of our idea of Him, asserts, at least in this particular case, that existential judgments are analytical. The truth is, though other philosophers may have hinted at the distinction, Kant was the first to grasp it thoroughly. It is also approached by Hume, Essays, vol. ii. p. 165 : — ' That the square of the hypotenuse is equal to the squares of the other two sides, cannot be known, let the terms be ever so exactly II PRINCIPLE OF SYNTHETICAL JUDGMENTS 35 defined, without a train of reasoning and inquiry. But to convince us of this proposition, that where there is no pro- perty there is no injustice, it is only necessary to define the terms and explain injustice to be a violation of property.' But to return. All analytical judgments depend upon the Laws of Identity and Contradiction. 1 You cannot deny to a con- cept any of its parts, without at once contradicting your own act of conception. All analytical judgments are also a priori, however empirical the concept concerned may be, for they require no additional experience, but a mere dissection of given notions. But here a priori is used in the popular sense explained above. Synthetical judgments must of course conform to the logical law of Contradiction also, but still they can never be obtained from it alone, and require some distinct principle in addition. What can this prin- ciple be ? All empirical judgments are synthetical. For it were idle to apply to experience for any information that could be obtained by analysis of our concepts. But if these judgments join new elements to our previous concepts, what guarantee have we that these elements ought to be so joined? We must know that the predicate belongs to the subject, or we have no cognition. Kant has replied to this difficulty very fully, especially in his First Edition. Let us first take the case of a posteriori judgments, such as ' all bodies are heavy.' How do we know this ? From experience. The concepts body and heavy are distinct from each other, and can only be brought into connection by comparing them both with some third thing (x, as Kant calls it) with which they will both agree. For all synthetical a posteriori judg- ments this x is our past experience. ' Both concepts (al- 1 Cf. Proleg. p. 17- 36 PRINCIPLE OF SYNTHETICAL JUDGMENTS chai\ though the one is not contained in the other) still belong to one another (though only contingently) as parts of the whole experience, which is itself a synthetic combination of intuitions.' 1 A more difficult problem remains. All synthetical judg- ments are not a posteriori, for many of them are universal and necessary. If they be synthetical, and also a priori, what is the x, which affords us the real synthesis ? 2 When we assert of an effect, that it must have some cause, this never could be obtained from the analysis of the concept of effect ; where then did we find the combination a priori of effect and cause ? for as this judgment is absolutely univer- sal and necessary, we could not as before have recourse to our complete experience, of which it is indeed one of the very conditions. The answer to this question was one of Kant's greatest discoveries. But he made it first in the field of Mathematic. 1 The question whether propositions can ever pass from the class of synthetical to that of analytical has been much debated. The truth seems to be this : & judgment must be one or the other ; either the pre- dicate is thought in the subject, or it is thought out of it: there is no alternative. At the same time, a proposition (i.e. a judgment expressed in words) may be analytical for one man, and synthetical for another ; but then it does not represent the same judgment for both individuals, for they are using terms in different senses. And even for the same in- dividual a proposition may at one time be synthetical, and at a later period, when larger experience has added to his concepts, analytical. For omniscience all true propositions are analytical, but for a finite in- telligence the distinction is fundamental. Cf. Monck, Logic, pp. 122 sgq., for a discussion of this question. 2 Kant's answer to this question is, we shall see, briefly this : In a priori synthetical judgments in Mathematic, the x is the a priori in- tuition ; in those in Physic it is the possibility of experience ; in Meta- physic such judgments are impossible, for no x can be found. II SYNTHETICAL JUDGMENTS AS PRINCIPLES 37 § 5. All theoretical Sciences contain Synthetical Judgments a priori as Principles 1. While Philosophy 1 is satisfied with discursive judg- ments about concepts, Mathematic insists on proving each step by intuition, and this observation gives us the clue to its first condition. This condition must be intuition, and it must be a priori. For though mathematical, like all other true judgments, must conform to the Law of Contradiction, such mere analysis does not explain their real nature. Consider the judgment 7+5 = 12. All previous philo- sophers considered this a mere analytical inference. But Kant denies that the concepts of 7, of 5, and of their addition, actually contain 12 as a necessary element. 'We must go beyond these concepts, and obtain the assistance of the intuition corresponding to either of them — suppose the fingers of a hand, or five points in a space — and add the units of the five given by intuition successively to the concept of 7.' 2 When this operation is completed, and then only, do we see the result to be 1 2. All such arith- metical judgments are therefore synthetical, as may be easily proved by considering the addition of large numbers. We there find that no analysis of our concepts will give us the required result. 3 Geometrical judgments are equally 1 Cf. Proleg. p. 36. 3 The reader will observe that Kant proposes to add the intuition of 5 to the concept of 7, the very expression repeated verbatim in the Pro- legomena. He appears to mean that the 7 is a made up group, whereas the 5 units are added seriatim. 3 It is curious to find, in a book published in 1886, a reiteration of the opinion that mathematical judgments are analytical ; and yet Pro- fessor Knight in his Hume falls into this blunder (p. 164), and remarks that the difference between mathematical judgments and the law of causality is practically that the first are analytical, the second synthe- tical. This, he says, ' leads straight to Kant's reply to Hume ! ' As to 38 THE PRINCIPLES OF MATHEMATIC chap. synthetical. If I say that a right line is the shortest pos- sible between two points, I cannot elicit anything about its shortness, which is quantity, from the mere concept of its straightness, which is quality. 1 (There are indeed, 2 Kant parenthetically observes, in geometry and also in arithmetic analytical judgments de- pending on the Law of Contradiction, such as a = a and a + b> a, but neither are these the principles on which the demonstration is based, nor would they be admissible in mathematics were they not capable of being expressed in intuition.) What misleads us about the synthetical judg- ments of mathematic, and makes us regard them as analy- tical, is an ambiguity of expression. To have a synthetical a priori judgment we must necessarily join the predicate in thought to the subject, the given concept. But the question is not, what we must join in thought to the given concept, but what we actually think in it, though only obscurely ; and then it becomes manifest, that the predicate in synthetical a priori judgments pertains to the concept, necessarily indeed, yet not as thought in the concept itself, but by virtue of an intuition, which must be added to it. 3 the nature of the judgment, 7 + 5 = 12, which Kant regards as synthetical, the curious reader may find a long controversy in Mind, vol. viii. — Mr. Sidgwick, in opposition to Mr. Monck, upholding the opinion of Ueber- weg, that such a judgment may be regarded as analytical if we go back to the definitions of 7, 5, &c 1 In the Prolegomena Kant adds a still clearer example. All the proofs of equal triangles resolve themselves ultimately into super-position, which is no logical analysis, but a direct appeal to intuition. 2 Professor Max Midler, in his Translation, puts this sentence in~a parenthesis, ; and [remarks (Preface, p. lviii.) that Dr. Vaihinger first gave this explanation of the passage. But that these words are parenthetical was pointed out long ago by Mr. Monck, and they were placed in brackets in the first edition of this book. 3 The ambiguity is in the words, ' we must join the predicate to the subject.' This, in synthetical judgments, says Kant, does not mean THE PRINCIPLES OF METAPHVSIC 39 2. Physical science contains a priori synthetical judg- ments as its principles. The examples which Kant gives are not the principle of causality [as Kuno Fischer alleges], 1 but the assertions that the quantity of matter in nature is constant, and that action and reactio?i are always equal. Permanence is not part of our concept of matter ; Reaction is not so either, and so these propositions are synthetical. 3. Metaphysic, whether we grant its scientific value or not, at all events pretends to occupy itself not about analys- ing concepts, but about extending our a priori knowledge, and it employs such a priori synthetical principles as our experience cannot even grasp. We can take as an example, the world must have had a beginning. Metaphysic then aims, at all events, at consisting of nothing but synthetical a priori judgments. [When Kuno Fischer gives as an example judgments asserting existence, he forgets that the synthetical nature of such judgments is only established in the latter part of the Kritik by a long and difficult discussion, and could therefore not be here quoted as a commonly re- ceived truth.] § 6. The general Problem of the Pure Reason. — It is very useful to comprehend a number of investigations under a single formula. Both the proof and the refutation are thereby simplified. A single question expresses the problem of the pure reason, how are synthetical a priori judgments possible ? By the solution of this problem or the proof that such judgments are not possible, Meta- physic must stand or fall. David Hume, of all previous philosophers, approached nearest to this problem, but that the predicate is a part of the subject, but that it must be necessarily added to it. 1 Ueberweg goes wrong in giving the Law of Causality as an ex- ample of a synthetical a priori judgment in Metaphysic (Hist, of Phil. vol. ii. p. 156). 40 HUME AND KANT did not state it to himself either distinctly or universally enough. He confined his attention to the Principle of Causality, 1 and exploded Metaphysic as in truth borrowed from experience, though decked out with an apparent necessity engendered by habit. A larger consideration of the question would have shown him that his conclusion, viz. that no synthetical proposition could be a priori? disproved the possibility of Mathematic, a result at which his good sense must have revolted. 3 Kant tells us, in his Prolegomena, that this scepticism of Hume was the exciting cause that prompted his first critical doubt. The solution of the above problem explains the possi- bility of all sciences which contain a theoretical cognition of objects a p7-iori, and therefore answers the questions : How is pure Mathematic and how is pure Physic possible ? That they are possible, their actual existence proves. As to Metaphysic, its want of success excites reasonable doubts as to its possibility. Yet as a fact in human nature, a certain spontaneous Metaphysic cannot be denied. The reason is irresistibly impelled to discuss those questions which transcend the bounds of experience, and in this sense there has been since the dawn of speculation, and there will ever be, Metaphysic. The question therefore ' Kant did not know Hume's Treatise, in which substance is dis- cussed at length, or he would not have said this. His knowledge of Hume was confined to the Enquiry. - But, of course, as Mr. Stirling points out {Text Book, p. 359), the notion of a priori in this reference never occurred to Hume. 3 Kant says that Hume regarded the propositions of mathematics as analytical {Proleg. p. 28 ; Theory of Ethics, Abbott's Translation, p. 142). This, however, is not so certain. The passage Kant seems to have had in his mind is at p. 22, vol. ii. of the Essays, viz. ' Mathe- matical propositions are discoverable by the mere operation of thought, without dependence on what is anywhere existent in the universe.' (See p. 34, supra.) TRANSCENDENTAL PHILOSOPHY remains : How can this impulse be explained from the nature of the reason, or how is spontaneous mctaphysic possible 2 But as it has confessedly led to perpetual contradictions, we must insist upon the further and last issue : how is Metaphysic as a science possible ? J These are the strictly scientific, and closely defined limits of the Kritik, which is concerned, not with objects, but with reason itself, and its problems. All previous dogmatic attempts at Metaphysic may be completely ignored, as either affording a mere analysis of concepts, which though useful is not Metaphysic, or as consisting of assumptions which have long since become suspicious, owing to the contradictions which they originated. § 7. The general Conception and Subdivisions of a special Science, called Kritik of the Pure Reason. — The reason is the faculty which gives us the principles of a priori know- ledge. An organon of the pure reason would then be a summary (Inbegriff) of these principles, and its detailed application would be the system of the pure reason. The present work is a mere preliminary (or propadetitic 2 ) to this system, of negative use, and devoted to clearing and puri- fying our reason from errors on the subject, by means of searching criticism. ' I call all knowledge transcendental which is not directly concerned with objects, but with the way in which we cog- nise them, so far as it is possible to do so a priori! A system of such knowledge is properly called transcendental philosophy. Yet even this exceeds our design, as it should contain a complete account of our analytical, as well as our synthetical knowledge; whereas we shall only carry our analysis as far as is absolutely necessary to the understand- 1 Considered in the Methodology. ' TpoiraiSevru:-/i. 42 SUBDIVISIONS OF THE KRITIK CHAr. ing of the principles of the a priori synthesis. This work is then merely a transcendental criticism, or Kritik of the Pure Reason. The main point in subdividing such a science is to admit no concepts that have the smallest empirical element. Thus the principles of morality, though they are by no means based on pleasure and pain, or on desires and inclinations, all of which are empirical in origin, yet imply them necessarily either as obstacles to duty, or incitements to action. They must therefore be excluded. Our science must of course contain first Stoicheiology, 1 and next Methodology. Each of these will be subdivided according to principles explained in the sequel. One point must here be mentioned : that there are two stems or trunks of human knowledge which perhaps spring from a common, but to us unknown, root, and these are Sensibility 'and Understanding ; through the former of which objects are given to us, through the latter they are thought. So far as the sensibility may contain a priori representations that are the conditions of objects being given to us, so far does it enter into transcendental philosophy. And as objects must be given to us, before they can be thought, this transcendental doctrine of Sensibility, or Aesthetic, must be our first con- sideration. If Concluding Reflections on the Introduction § 8. The History of Kanfs Discoveries, and his peculiar Method of Proof. — Kuno Fischer has given, in his Com- mentary on the Kritik, 2 a very interesting sketch of the chronological development in Kant's earlier writings. This sketch is particularly valuable, because it shows that the 1 Or Doctrine of Elements, ffroix«ti. 2 Pp. 28-33. Cf, also Kant's Proleg. (Introduction.) n KANT S PRELIMINARY STEPS 43 critical philosophy was not adopted by Kant till he had actually supported some of the most popular solutions adopted in the present day. They were tried by him, and found wanting. As early as the year 1762, Kant declared that all logical judgments were analytical and a priori. The following year he contrasted with them the connection of cause and effect, which he declared to be synthetical. He had then discovered that real cognitive judgments, as opposed to logical, were synthetical. But a few years after- wards he declared with Hume, that the concept of cause was obtained empirically. He did not yet perceive how synthetical judgments could be a priori. This is in fact the attitude of Mr. Mill, and his school, who explain the apparent necessity of judgments by association. It cannot be said therefore of Kant, as has been said of Sir William Hamilton and of Dean Mansel, that he ' ignored ' insepar- able association, and did not give that theory his serious consideration. But a deeper reflection on mathematical judgments altered his views. Surely these cannot be empirical, and yet they most certainly give us real knowledge. As early as 1764, Kant saw that they depended upon intuition, and he declared space to be that intuition. But still he ascribed to it ' a reality proper to itself,' which lay at the basis of all matter. This was the view of Hamilton and his school. But if space were thus given from without, how could its judgments be anything but empirical, and hence how could they be universal and necessary ? If they are such, space must be an intuition not given with objects from without, but a priori. This step he made between 1768 and 1770. By maintaining the a priori and yet synthetical character of mathematical judgments Kant parted company with 44 A PRIORI PHYSIC ESTABLISHED chap. Hume, and entered upon his critical path. It was obvious when the existence of such judgments was ascertained in one science, that the same problem must be solved in other sciences. How about Metaphysic ? If it means the science of things in themselves, all judgments whatever about such things are rendered impossible by our late dis- covery. For if space and time are necessarily imposed by the mind upon all the objects it can know, how can things apart from these conditions ever be brought before the mind ? How can we speak of things as they are in them- selves, when we only know them under these all-important modifications ? There is only one other sense in which a metaphysic of things is possible — in the sense of phenomena. Is there any universal and necessary knowledge of phenomena pos- sible ? Is there such a thing as a priori Physic ? This was the last and by far the most subtle of all Kant's dis- coveries. He would not publish his Kritik, or consider his system complete, till he had ascertained that as we intuite phenomena under a priori conditions, so we also think and connect them under a priori conditions. As the a priori conditions of intuition give us synthetical a priori judgments in Mathematic, so the a priori conditions of thought give us similar judgments in Physic. But we only mean thought about phenomena — thought applied to experience. The cog- nition of the things of sense need not itself be sensuous cognition} Ten years of thought brought him to this conclusion. The critical philosophy therefore, like most great discoveries, was 1 See Kritik, p. 238. There is a curious analogy in Descartes's great discovery — the application of mathematics to nature, which con- sisted of two steps : first, the solution of figure-problems by algebraic symbols ; secondly, the principle that all nature is reducible to figures, i.e. modes of extension. Cf. 'Descartes' in Blackwood' 's Philosophical Series. n KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL PROOFS 45 not the offspring of a happy guess, or a sudden inspiration, but the slow and gradual result of a long life of labour. We are left in no darkness as to all these points. Not only the chronological sequence of Kant's works but the general account of his discoveries given in the second Pre- face, and in his Prolegomena, are explicit. In this latter work, published for the use of teachers in expounding the Critical Philosophy, he gives the analytical or regressive view of the system synthetically constructed in the Kritik. We have endeavoured to combine both in the preceding Commentary. One point, however, deserves special atten- tion, before we enter upon our task. The nature of Kant's demonstration throughout the Kritik may appear at first sight illogical, inasmuch as he argues from the position of the consequent to the position of the antecedent, and this he calls his transcendental proofs (p. 478). But this argu- ment is only illogical on account of the plurality of causes. Given a cause, its effect will follow ; but given the effect, we cannot infer the particular cause, except we are certain that no other cause could have produced the effect. We may safely argue from the effect to its only possible cause. And such is Kant's investigation, which infers from the fact of cognition the only possible conditions under which it could exist. When these conditions are established, they show not the existence of the fact, by which they were themselves proved, but its legitimacy. Thus the legitimacy of Mathematic and Physic, and the illegitimacy of Meta- physic, as a science of things per se, are demonstrated from the conditions they involve. It may be objected that if Metaphysic be a fact, its conditions must be as real as those of any other science : how then can it be rejected ? In answer it may be observed, firstly, that the conditions of 1 Cf. Kuno Fischer, pp. 24-28. 46 SUBDIVISIONS OF THE KRITIK chap, ii Metaphysic are absolutely inconsistent with those of mathe- matic. This raises a strong presumption against the more doubtful science. Secondly, if it be found that from the conditions of Mathematic and Physic the possibility of an illusory science of Metaphysic can be explained, whereas from those of Metaphysic the very existence of Mathematic and Physic can be shown impossible — in such a sense, we cannot hesitate as to our decision. The Aesthetic shows the legitimacy of Mathematic, the Analytic that of Physic; the Dialectic proves the illegitimacy, as well as the apparent existence of Metaphysic. These are the main divisions of the Kritik. CHAPTER III THE TRANSCENDENTAL AESTHETIC § I. [Definitions.] — The immediate knowledge we have of objects is intuition. This only occurs if an object is given us — that is to say, if it produces an affection or modification of our minds. The faculty of obtaining representations through this affection produced by objects, is sensibility. Kant notices that this so-called faculty is properly a recep- tivity, as opposed to the spontaneity of thought. Sensibility alone gives us intuitions : when these are thought by the understanding, we obtain concepts. All thinking must refer either mediately or immediately to sensibility. In no other way can an object be given us. The effect of an object on our sensibility, so far as we are affected by it, is sensation. So far as an intuition is of this sort, it is empirical. ' The undetermined object of an empirical intuition is called an appearance, or phenomenon.' The element in it that corresponds to sensation is the matter; the element that renders its variety reducible to fixed relations is the form of the phenomenon. The form differs completely from the matter in this, that while the matter is given a posteriori, the form exists a priori, as it were, ready in the mind, and can therefore be considered quite separately. 1 Representa- ■ 1 Kant says expressly (Kritik, p. 98, note) that there are elements THE AESTHETIC tions are therefore pure, in the transcendental sense, if nothing belonging to sensation is to be found in them, and the pure form of intuition, that reduces the variety of phenomena to order, is in the mind, and may be called pure intuition?- Abstract from a body what the understanding thinks about it, such as substance, force, and divisibility ; abstract also what belongs to sensation, such as incompressibility, hardness, colour, etc., and there, still remain extension and figure. These belong to the pure a priori intuition which exists in the mind, even without an actual object of sense, as a mere form of sensibility. The science of all a priori principles of sensibility may be called transcendental aesthetic, using this word not in the sense of the philosophy of taste, but in the Greek sense of cucr^o-is, as opposed to vo?;o-is. Our investigation shows that there are two such forms, space and time, which we proceed to consider. §§ 2 and 4. Metaphysical Exposition of Space and Time. — Although Kant considers the two forms separately, we may combine them, so far as the same observations apply strictly to both. This is the case with the metaphysical exposition, 2 defined by Kant, as ' containing the description of a notion, as given a priori. ' By means of our external sense, which is a property of not given by sensibility included in his Aesthetic, so difficult is it to separate in treatment what is one in nature. But many of his critics have assumed, in direct opposition to this statement, that Kant made a sharp separation between the two faculties in their actual use, and have proceeded to charge him with want of psychological insight. Cf. also Kritik, p. 84, note. 1 It is very misleading to find Mr. Stirling telling us (p. 352, Joe. cit.) that Anschauung by itself means pure intuition. Surely Kant's lan- guage is plain enough ; and Mr. Stirling himself admits on p. 358 that Anschauung is also used of empirical intuition. - Cf. Kritik, p. 444. SPACE AND TIME 49 our minds, we represent objects as without us, and their form and relations are determined in what we call Space. The internal sense, by means of which the mind intuites itself or its own internal states, gives us frideed no intuition of the soul itself, as an object, but has nevertheless a form, viz. Time, without which no such internal experience is possible. What then are Space and Time ? Are they actual beings ? [This is the popular belief.] Or are they mere relations, that belong however to things in themselves, whether we intuite them or not ? [This was the view of many previous philosophers, e.g. Leibnitz and Wolf.] Or do they belong merely to the subjective nature of our mind, as forms of its intuition, through which alone they can be added to things ? U Kant does not consider the possibility of their coming under more than one of these three heads. For in the first place, if any one of these suppositions satisfies all the phenomena, the philosophical law of Parcimony forbids us to assume an additional one without a?iy reason at all. Secondly, if the subjective origin of space and time be established, it is specially absurd to assume that the peculiar element added to objects by the mind, which constitutes in fact the essential difference between the phenomenon and the thing per se — that this element is added by the mind to objects which have it already in themselves. Recent contro- versies will make it necessary to revert to this subject, when we have considered Kant's express utterances on the point. (1) Space and time are not empirical concepts, deduced from our experience. For we cannot refer our sensations to anything without us (that is, in space), nor can we assert them to be simultaneous or successive, unless the representa- tions of space and time were already in the mind. (2) Space and time are necessary a priori representations, lying at the basis of external and internal intuitions respect- 1 E 50 SPACE AND TIME ively. It is impossible to conceive either of them annihi- lated, though we can easily conceive all objects in them removed. They are therefore the necessary conditions of this very possibility of phenomena. 1 (3) Space and time are not general concepts of the relations of things, but pure intuitions. For there is but one space and one time, of which all separate spaces and times are parts. 2 And these parts are not considered as constituent elements, composing space and time, and there- fore prior to them, but rather as limitations of space and time, and existing in them. Hence an a priori intuition lies at the base of all our notions of space and time. (4) Space and time are represented as unlimited quan- tities. 3 [And the infinite parts which they contain are neither constituent elements chemically fused to produce them, nor logical parts contained under them. J Every concept indeed is represented as comprising a possibly 1 (1) shows that Space and Time are a priori and not empirical, i.e. not products of special sense ; (2), shows that they are not only a priori, but that they are the necessary conditions of all intuitions. - Cf. note, Kritik, p. 98 and p. 274. We now go on to show that they are intuitions, not concepts, from the peculiar nature of their unity in (3), of their infinity in (4) ; they being integral not universal wholes. 3 Kant says of space that it is represented as an infinite given quantity, a statement justly attacked by his German critics (especially Montgomery), who deny that on his own principles infinity can be given to sense, or indeed given at all (cf. Kritik, p. 270). Possibly he meant to say unlimited, for he is far more cautious in the parallel remark on time, where he says the ' infinity of time means but this, that all definite quantities of time are only possible by limiting the single (total) time lying at their basis ' (cf. also Kritik, pp. 257, 262). Hence time is ori- ginally given as unlimited. A knowledge of the absence of limits may be given, though positive infinity cannot. Kant's opponents should have given him the benefit of this reasonable explanation. Even as to space, he spoke of its infinity, in the first Edition, as the absence of bounds in the extension of intuition (die Grenzenlosigkeit im Fortgange der Anschauung). in THE TRANSCENDENTAL EXPOSITION 51 infinite number of individuals under itself, but it cannot be conceived as containing them within itself. The parts of space and time are in infinite space and time, not contained under our concepts of them. Our original representation of space and time is therefore not concept, but intuition. [Kant had added, in his first Edition, that no general con- cept of relations (in space) could of itself imply the endless- ness of these relations, as our notion of space certainly does.] §§ 3 and 5. Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time. — Kant defines this to be ' the explanation of a concept as a principle from which the possibility of other synthetical a priori cognitions can be understood.' It is necessary to show (a) that such cognitions actually flow from the given concept ; (b) that these cognitions are only possible by presupposing this particular explanation of the concept. Geometry is a science that determines the properties of space synthetically, and yet a priori. What then must our representation of space be, to produce such cognitions ? It must obviously be intuitive, for from mere concepts we can- not obtain synthetical propositions ; and also a priori, for these propositions are apodeictic, and carry with them necessity, such as the statement that space has but three dimensions. 1 So also there are axioms concerning the relation of time equally demonstrable and necessary : e.g. Time has but one dimension, different times cannot be simultaneous (as different spaces are), but successive. So also the concept of Change, and with it of Motion (change 1 Briefly, the propositions in geometry are synthetical — therefore space is an intuition ; they are necessary — therefore space is a priori. Mr. Watson puts the argument thus : ' As specifications of the forms of intuition mathematical judgments are a priori, and as specifications of those forms they are synthetical.' {Kant and liis English Critics, p. 41.) 52 THE BASIS OF ARITHMETIC chap. of place), are only possible through our notion of time ; and through this latter only as an a priori intuition, for no con- cept could possibly make us understand the possibility of change, which is, in fact, the combination of contradictory predicates — the existence and non-existence of the same thing in the same place. It is only in time — that is to say successively — that this is possible. All the synthetical pro- positions, therefore, derived from our idea of motion in general (and they are not a few) are wholly dependent on our idea of time. 11 The expositors of Kant 1 have uniformly derived the science of Arithmetic from the intuition of Time — a deri- vation so important, if true, that he could not possibly have omitted to mention it. If Arithmetic be based on Time, it would be natural to make use of the propositions of Arithmetic to prove that Time is an intuition, in the Transcendental Exposition. But although in his Prole- gomena? he has (perhaps in deference to his critics, and seduced by his passion for symmetry) conceded en passant, that this view is possible, he has left us in no doubt, from several passages in his Kritik, that the units of the science of arithmetic, being essentially simultaneous, and not successive units, are given us primarily in space, and not in time. The original intuition of 5, for example, is not a group of five successive thoughts or intuitions, but the immediate perception, through sight, and perhaps through touch also, of five simultaneous, adjacent units. The fact that we can, if we choose, apprehend them successively in five separate acts of attention, makes us apply arithmet- ical laws to sensations in time also ; but we do not see how a summation, or subsumption of several units under a 1 E.g. K. Fischer, Dean Mansel, Sir Wm. Hamilton, Ueberwe? and many others. 2 p , _ m THE BASIS OF ARITHMETIC 53 higher number, regarded as a unit itself — how this would ever have been accomplished, were we not aware intuitively of the simultaneous presence of the units within a small definite portion of space. There is no other practical way of teaching arithmetic to a child or savage, than by appeal- ing to space intuitions. Let us add that the subdivision of units into fractions is equally unattainable, originally, through intuition of time, but is easily obtained through space, where all the units assumed are intuitively divisible. It has been pointed out in another work 1 how the opinion appears to have arisen. Our only way of exemplifying quantity in time is by the act of adding (mentally) units to 1 Cf. Fischer's Commentary on Kant' s Kritik, p. 95, note. Dr. Tarle- ton has an able paper in Hermathena No. I., in which he develops a positive theory of the growth of arithmetic from subdivisions of Time. As he observes, we can conceive a mind ignorant of space distinguishing units and their addition by the striking of a clock. And if any given number of strokes were gathered, he thinks, by means of some longer division of time under a larger unity, an acute reasoner might even under such conditions construct an arithmetic. This is, we believe, the only attempt yet made ;to meet the difficulty in a full and scientific manner. We are not disposed to deny the possibility of arithmetic being so obtained in the absence of spatial data, as, for instance, in blindness or perpetual darkness ; but we are certain that, as a matter of fact, ordinary human beings do not learn it so, and that Kant felt this, and intended to derive our ordinary notions of number from space, though he admitted the other. The apprehension of units may no doubt be successive, and so involve time, but we deny that in the early counting of small numbers, which the eye can take in simultaneously, this succession is a conscious element, and except it be explicitly present in consciousness, it has of course no claim to be regarded as the basis of arithmetic. We must add that Dr. Tarleton has supplied solutions to some of the difficulties which have been raised, but surely his derivations are too subtle for ordinary use. In any case it is doubtful whether similar representations repeated in time would have given the same notion of different units, which we derive from co-ordinated units in space. The units in time may be the same thing reproduced; this cannot be the case with separate units in space. 54 DEDUCTIONS one another, in other words by number. But this schema of quantity, which will be discussed in its proper place, is expressly contrasted by Kant^ with any representation which can be reduced to an image. The derivation of arithmetic from the intuition of space has never yet, so far as we know, been refuted, and though not definitely stated hitherto, was distinctly implied as far back as Descartes. 2 § 6. Deductions from the preceding Notions. — {a and b) Neither time nor space represents any properties of things in themselves, nor do they express any relations of such things to one another which still exist, if we abstract from things the subjective conditions of intuition. For in no case can properties, absolute or relative, be intuited a priori, prior to the existence of the things which they deter- mine. To assert then the absolute reality of space and time is to assert that we know a priori the properties or relations of things which we do not know. Such an asser- tion has no meaning whatever, unless we assume that space and time belong to the conditions imposed on the mind, and are, therefore, logically prior to the cognition of objects. 3 Upon this supposition the necessary and universal judgments obtained from the intuitions of space and time follow as a matter of course. Also our external image of time is an endless right line, which expresses all its relations in an intuition, and, therefore, proves it to be such. It is then only from the human point of view that we can speak of extended beings, or of events in time. If we abandon the subjective conditions, under which alone we 1 Kritih, p. no. 2 See his Highs pour la Direction de P 'Esprit, xiv. and xv. 3 Space is nothing more than the ' formal capacity of the subject to be affected by objects' {Kritik, p. 25). Time is ' the mode in which the mind is affected by its own activity' (p. 41). RESULTS 55 can be affected by objects, then both space and time have absolutely no meaning. These forms are a necessary part of every intuition which we can have, because we intuite through them. But we may not impose the conditions which limit our cognition of things on things themselves. Space and time then include all things which appear to us, but beyond this we can give neither of them any reality. For as they are not things, but our particular way of look- ing at things, it is absurd to imagine that they can belong to things per se as qualities. Again, as we cannot possibly investigate the conditions which limit the intuition of other beings than ourselves, we cannot say whether any of them are obliged to look at things as we do. We are, therefore, incompetent to affirm the existence of space and time, even in this sense, which is the only possible sense in which they can be conceived beyond our own experience without absurdity. But when thus limited, nothing can be more objectively certain. There is no possible intuition which we can have apart from space and time. We hold, there- fore, as strongly as possible, their empirical reality, but assert their transcendental ideality, — that is, that they are nothing, if we omit the conditions of experience, and regard them as belonging to things in themselves. [We also deny their absolute reality, which can never be revealed to us, and which is in some senses absurd. 1 ] 1 When Trendelenburg says that Kant forgot to inquire whether space and time might not be both subjective and objective, as a third possibility, he shows by his very statement of the question his ignorance of Kant's system. To say, as Trendelenburg does {Beitra^e, pp. 215 sq.), that Kant made them purely subjective is equally false. Kant would never have conceded such a statement of his views. He denied the subjectivity in the usual sense of space and time. He asserted them expressly, in the sense which Trendelenburg desires, to be both subjective and objective. He never denied their objectivity except in an absurd sense. 56 SPACE AND TIME OBJECTIVE chap. Space is the only one of our subjective representations relating to what is without us which can be called objective a priori. For synthetical a priori propositions cannot be deduced from any other of them, so that such sensations as heat, colour, and sound can claim no ideality at all, accurately speaking. 1 They agree, indeed, with space in belonging to the subjective nature of sensibility, but being sensations and not intuitions, they in themselves give no object, not to say an object a priori. ( infra, for the parallel to the law of Contradiction. viii TRANSCENDENTAL UNITY OF APPERCEPTION 129 still be required for the understanding attached to such an intuition. When we speak of the understanding, or the faculty of cognitions, we regard the latter as referring to objects. But an object implies a group or combination of intuitions. This combination, as we have seen, can only be made by the synthesis of our consciousness. It follows that the unity of our consciousness is the necessary condition of our forming any notion of objects. Here is an illustration : mere space gives us no object, but only the materials for an object. In order to know something in space, as for example a line, I must draiv it, and so produce a synthetical unity of parts. The unity of this act, as comprising several suc- cessive acts, is the unity of my consciousness, which gives me the notion of a line, and so only can I obtain such an object. The synthetical unity of consciousness is therefore an absolutely necessary or objective condition of all cogni- tion, for not only do I require it in order to know an object, but every intuition must come under it, before it can even become to me an object. § 1 8. This transcendental unity of apperception is (as we have said) the unity by means of which we combine the variety of intuition into the notion of an object. For this reason we call it objective, to contrast it with such determi?ia- tions of our internal sense as are merely suggestive and empirical, and therefore not necessary. Every man makes some of these combinations for himself a posteriori. But the pure form of intuition (given a priori), considered as mere presented variety, must stand under the original and primitive / think, which alone contains an objectively valid unity, viz. valid for every understanding. It is under this objective unity (§ 19) that intuitions are brought in the act of judgment. When we say a body is heavy, we do not 130 RELATION OF CATEGORIES TO APPERCEPTION CH. merely assert what seems to us by association subjectively combined, but we make an assertion which, whether true or false, is only possible by understanding what necessary unity of apperception is, and consequently bringing two representations under it. We assert these notions to be necessarily combined into unity, not in our empirical in- tuition, but by the synthesis of our perceptions in our pure consciousness. Thus the first step in the Deduction has been reached. It has been shown that objects of intuition can only be obtained by a combination of multiplicity. This combina- tion is not given in a sensuous intuition, which is pure receptivity. It is therefore added by the understanding, which is a faculty whose function is to combine. But all the several acts of combining are recognised by us as belong- ing to one and the same consciousness. The importance therefore of the unity of apperception, and its objective character, are manifest. § 20. But what have the Categories to do with this argu- ment ? What relation have they to the pure apperception ? It is this. The intuitions can only be brought under it by the logical function of judging. Whatever variety therefore is given in intuition can only be brought under the pure apperception by being brought under one of the functions of judging (as exhibited in the table, p. 86). But the Cate- gories are these very forms of judging, so far as they merely combine the variety of intuition (§ 13). This variety therefore stands under the Categories as various phases, or ways, of reducing it under the unity of apperception. § 21. We have now proved that the Categories, which arise in the understanding, quite apart from sensibility, can introduce unity into intuitions quite generally, for this might still be the case, even were our faculty of intuition different vm NEGATIVE SIDE OF THE DEDUCTION 131 from what it now is, provided it were receptive. We have not yet considered how empirical objects are actually given- us, or whether we can identify the unities given in them with the unity imposed by the Category. ) When this is done, our deduction will be complete. But though we have hitherto abstracted from the way in which intuitions are given us, we could not abstract from the fact that they are given to us — that is, given from some other (here unde- termined) source than our understanding, and independent of it. If our understanding possessed a power of intuiting, the Categories, which are mere acts of combining variety given to it, would be idle, for the objects would then be given directly to it in the act of intuiting. This peculiarity of our understanding, as opposed to an intuitive understand- ing, is, of course, a primitive fact, and inexplicable. § 22. Bqt before we consider how empirical intuitions are given to us, as contrasted with other possible sensuous faculties of intuition, it is important to limit the other side of the process, and show that the Category is of no use in cognising things, except when applied to objects of experience. For thinking and knowi?ig (cognising) an object are not the same. To know it, we want both a Category, or concept, and also an intuition, without which the former is mere form, or possibility of knowledge. But we can have none but sensuous intuitions either of pure space and time, or of sensations in space and time ; and, moreover, the objects given by the former (mathematical figures) are mere forms, which do not prove the existence of things corresponding to them. Things in space and time must be representations accompanied by sensations, or empirical perceptions. Hence the Categories, even when applied to pure intuition, give us no knowledge of things, till we appeal further to empirical intuition, or experience. Our assertion is therefore proved. 1 32 SYNTHESIS SPECIOSA chap. §23. It was easy to perceive the corresponding limita- tion in the case of space and time, for we cannot carry them beyond our senses. The pure Categories are not so restricted, and may apply to the objects of any sensuous [or receptive] intuition, whether it be in other respects like ours or not. But this extension proves vain. For beyond our sensuous intuitions they are mere empty forms of objects, since there is no actual intuition at hand, to which they can apply their synthesis to produce an unity of apperception, and this is the only function they can exercise. We can only then describe an object of an intuition different from ours by negative predicates — by judging, for example, that it is not in space and time, or subject to change. But these negations contain no positive cognition whatever. And even if they did, we should still not have the least notion what Category to apply to such an object, for empirical intuition must determine this point also, as will appear when we con- sider the schematism. § 24. In this paragraph Kant comes to explain the office of the imagination, as intermediate between the pure under- standing and the sensuous intuitions. He anticipates to some extent the schematism, but this is nevertheless requisite to the full comprehending of the Deduction. The pure Categories, referring to the combination of the data of intuition generally, are mere forms of thought, and not only transcendental, but purely intellectual. But as the form of sensuous intuition lies a priori within us, the understanding can act upon this, and through it upon sensuous intuitions. By this means the purely intellectual synthesis of the naked Category passes into an intuitible or figurative synthesis {synthesis speciosd), though still a priori and transcendental. 1 1 The synthesis inteilectualis would then be the same for all rational beings, but the character of the synthesis sfcciosa depends on the peculiar viii THIRD STAGE OF THE DEDUCTION 133 Kant regards this latter synthesis as the work of the imagi- nation, which therefore performs a transcendental synthesis, to be distinguished from that of the mere understanding. As reproductive of intuitions, it is indeed a faculty belonging to sensibility ; but as exercising a spontaneity which actively determines intuitions in harmony with the Categories, it is allied to the understanding, and may be called the product- ive imagination, which performs a transcendental synthesis under the direction of the understanding. Omitting for the present the Appendix to the Aesthetic here inserted by Kant, we proceed at once to the conclusion and summary of the whole deduction. § 26. In the metaphysical Deduction (or exposition, as he calls it in the Aesthetic), the a priori origin of the Cate- gories was proved generally by their perfect coincidence with the general functions of thinking (§ 10). In the tran- scendental (§§ 20, 21) their possibility was shown as a priori cognitions of the objects of intuition generally — that is to say, of any sensuous or receptive intuition. We now pro- ceed to complete the deduction by showing the possibility of cognising « priori, according to the laws of their com- bination, whatever objects can be presented to our senses. Our combination of variety in space and time, an act of the imagination, called by Kant (above, p. 118) the synthesis of apprehension, must obviously conform and correspond to the forms of space and time. But space and time are not mere forms of sensuous intuition, but themselves intuitions — that is to say, their variety is represented a priori as com- bined into unity?- It appears then that unity in the synthesis nature of the sensibility and its forms. The former is the skeleton, as it were, of the latter. 1 Cf. Kritilt, p. 98, n. "Space represented as an object contains more than the mere form of the intuition : namely, a combination of the 134 EXAMPLES CHAP - of variety, both within us (in time), and without (in space), is given as the first condition of sensuous apprehension along with the very act. This can be no other unity than the combination of sensuous intuitions in general, which takes place in pure consciousness, according to the Cate- gories, as above explained (p. 127); it is here applied to our sensuous intuitions. As, therefore, experience is nothing but a knowledge of connected perceptions, and these are shown to stand under the condition of the Categories, the Categories are fully proved to be the conditions of the pos- sibility of experience. Here are some examples showing that the conformity of the objective synthesis to the unity (1) of space and (2) of time is equivalent to its conformity to the Categories. When I perceive a house, the necessary unity of space, and of my external intuition generally, must be presupposed. It is in accordance with this that I, as it were, draw its figure, and separate it from surrounding perceptions. 1 This is the synthesis of apprehension. But abstracting from space, we find that the understanding exercises the same spontaneity more generally by the synthesis of homogeneous manifold given according to the form of sensibility into a representation that can be intuited ; so the form of the intuition gives us merely the manifold, but the formal intuition gives unity of representation . . . and as by means of this unity alone, space and time are given as intui- tions, it follows that the unity of this intuition a priori belongs to space and time, and not to the concept of the understanding.' 1 That is to say, to perceive a house implies that we know it as a single object, separated from the surrounding perceptions given at the same time ; also that it exists in space, in which the surrounding percep- tions also exist. Two unities, the larger one of space, the lesser one of the house, are both implied in our knowledge of it as an object. Kant further states that we separate the house from its surroundings by a spon- taneous act, which he calls drawing the figure, or mentally marking it out from the rest. EPIGENESIS OF THE PURE REASON 135 parts in any intuition, which is the Category of quantity. The former synthesis must correspond with this latter. When I perceive the freezing of water, I apprehend two states of water standing in a time relation. But time is an internal intuition (as well as a form) with a necessary syn- thetical unity of parts, and the necessary condition of perceiving this relation. This is the synthesis of apprehen- sion. But apart from time, the unity under which the understanding combines such varieties in intuition gener- ally, is the Category of cause, which, when applied to my sensibility, determines all events in time according to its relation. Therefore the apprehension of the event, and therefore the event itself, stands under the relation of cause and effect. The conclusion of the paragraph repeats the argument already (ii. pp. 206, 215) developed, that as the Categories prescribe laws for phenomena, or objects of nature (materi- a/iter spectata), they must consequently legislate for the legitimacy or order of nature (formaliter spectata). There is no difficulty whatever in the argument, and as we have explained it already, 1 we shall not weary the reader with repetitions. § 27. We have come to the strange conclusion that for us no cognition a priori is possible, except of objects of possible experience. Yet though thus limited, it is nevertheless not borrowed from experience, but as regards both pure intui- tions and pure Categories, found in us a priori. As, there- fore, experience and the Categories are in harmony, and experience is not the ground of possibility of the Categories, the reverse must be the case. This Kant calls the Epi- genesis of the pure reason, which begets the frame and order of nature by means of its Categories. 1 Above, p. 115. 136 PRE-ESTABLISHED HARMONY chap. Another alternative 1 has been proposed : That we are so organised as to have subjective dispositions implanted in us, corresponding to the independent laws of nature. This is a sort of pre-established harmony. In the first place, Kant argues in reply, if we once begin to postulate such hypo- theses, there is no limit to their further use in explaining other difficulties. But it is still more decisive, that in such case the Categories must lack that necessity, which belongs to their very nature. He thinks that the law of Causality, for example, which asserts the necessity of certain conse- quences, would be false. For we should only be entitled to say : I am so constituted that I cannot think the effect and cause except thus conjoined. This is just what the sceptic wants, for then all our supposed objective judgments would be mere illusion ; and when men were found, as there surely would be, who denied the necessity, though they must feel it, we could, at all events, never dispute with them about a matter depending on the peculiar constitution of their thinking subject. 11 The reader will at once perceive the close analogy between this reply and that of Locke to the idealist sceptics of his day [Locke's Essay, iv. 2, § 14]. It is too, like that passage in Locke, one of the weakest passages in the great work of a great author. Surely if we are all agreed that the laws of nature are a mental relation superadded to the bare successive feelings given to our nerves of sense, then the only question which remains is this : Did the mind impose them originally, or abstract them from repeated sensations ? That there should be an unknown order of nature, in addi- tion to and corresponding with the order which our under- standing is, on either theory, competent to impose on its 1 Cf. vol. ii. p. 101, note, where we see that he is alluding to the opinions of Crusius. APPERCEPTION AND INTERNAL SENSE 137 sensations — to require this is so perfectly otiose and gratui- tous, as to be wholly inadmissible in any reasonable theory of human knowledge. We might as well assume a real space and time, after all the phenomena have been perfectly and adequately explained by the Kantian theory. If the reader has been able to follow this long and intricate discussion, he has mastered perhaps the greatest difficulty in the Kritik. We may conclude this chapter with an account of the supplement to the Aesthetic, which is inserted in the middle of the discussion on the Categories, in §§ 24, 25. 'This,' Kant says, ' is the place to explain the paradox which must have struck every one in the exposition of the internal sense ' (§ 6), where it is said, ' that our internal sense represents us to ourselves as phenomena, not as we exist per se,' — in other words, that we only intuite our internal affections, not our internal being (self). As this puts us into a passive relation as regards ourselves, it has been usual to identify the faculty of apperception with the internal sense, whereas we distinguish them carefully. In order to know ourselves, as in the knowledge of any other object, our understanding must employ its primitive faculty of combining the variety given in internal sense, and bringing it under the unity of apperception. "We have seen that our understanding is not a faculty of intuiting, and must regard such a faculty, when acting in the sensibility, as a faculty differing from itself, and the variety given in it as a variety not obtained by its own direct action. If, then, we turn our attention to the synthesis of the understanding, regarded purely by itself, it is nothing but the unity of the action, of which we are conscious even without sensibility, and which binds up the variety of sense, given internally, according to the form of internal intuition. So it is that i 3 S CONDITIONS OF FORMING OBJECTS our understanding, by a transcendental synthesis of the ima- gination, as it is called, being one of this subject's faculties, acts upon the passive subject, and thus affects the internal sense. Apperception and its unity, as the source of all combination, act upon all intuitions in general, under the title of Categories, before they act upon objects in sensuous intuition ; in other words, the unity of apperception is neces- sary to obtain the frame, or Category, which is logically prior to our knowledge of any object (whether internal or external) in this frame. The internal sense is the mere form of intuition, which does not give us a definite intuition, or object, till its variety has been combined by that tran- scendental action of the imagination above called the figurative synthesis. We can easily observe this in ourselves. We cannot conceive a line, or circle, or other figure, without drawing it in thought, or conceive even time, without drawing its external image, a right line. This means that we direct our attention merely to the action of combining multiplicity, by which we determine our internal sense successively, and so observe the succession in that sense. This motion, as an act of the subject 1 (not as a determination of an object), if we attend to the mere action by which we determine the internal sense according to its form, is what produces in us the very notion of succession. The understanding does not find the combination in sense ; but produces it by acting upon sense. The difficulty as to how the thinking self can 1 Kant notices that the motion of an object in space belongs not to pure science, and therefore not to Geometry, as it requires experience to know that anything is movable. But motion, as the act of drawing figures, which is presupposed by Geometry, is a pure act of successively combining multiplicity in external intuition generally by our productive imagination ; it therefore takes its place even in transcendental philo- sophy. Cf. above, p. 59. OUR MINDS NO EXCEPTION 139 be regarded as different from the self-intuiting self, and yet identical with it, cannot be avoided or diminished by any other theory, if we regard ourselves (as we must) as objects of our own internal perception. That this letter is an intuition is plain, when we consider that the only image we can form of time, in which we represent ourselves, is a line in space, and that all measures of time are imaged by changes in external things ; in fact, that the determinations of the internal sense in time are strictly analogous to those of the external in space. But we only intuite external objects, when we are affected through the external sense ; we only intuite internal when we are affected through the internal sense ; in other words, we know ourselves as pheno- mena in time, not directly, as to our real nature. Every act of attention gives us an example of this internal relation. Here anybody can perceive how his understanding, as an active faculty, determines his internal sense, as a passive state ; in other words, we actively choose that our minds (here controlled as passive) shall attend to something dif- ferent from the natural succession of ideas. § 25. But the phenomenal self given in internal intuition by the synthetical action of our understanding, is not the only datum we have. This very transcendental synthesis implies a consciousness, not of what we are, but that we exist. This representation we reach by thought, not by intuition. Now, every human cognition, or knowledge, requires (a) a combining action of the understanding, which unites (/3) the multiplicity given in some kind of intuition. It follows that this consciousness that we exist, as it wants the second element, is not a cog- nition of itself. This self is indeed no phenomenon, far less an illusion, but can only become an object by an appeal to internal sense. All the thinking in the world, all the Categories, will not supply this element. I exist therefore i 4 o THE EGO APART FROM INTUITION as an intelligence, conscious merely of its faculty of com- bining, but subject to a limiting condition in the things combined, viz. that they must be obtained by the internal sense, and therefore in time. This time modifies all the data we receive through it, and thus makes them pheno- mena, that cannot inform us of things per se. To obtain these latter we should possess an intellectual intuition. The / think, gives us the act of determining our own existence, but no determination of our existence. As I have no self-intuiting faculty, to intuite the subject, prior to its act of determining, like as I have a pure sensuous intuition in time, prior to objects in time, it is impossible for me to determine my existence, as a self-acting being. I represent myself, therefore, as spontaneous in thought, but with an existence determined only, as other phenomena are, sensu- ously. It is the consciousness of spontaneity, however, which enables me to call myself an intelligence. H Probably this long and difficult parenthesis has been one of the main reasons why the Deduction was not better understood. It really does not bear on the argument of the Deduction, but on the Aesthetic, and was inserted here, because Kant could not treat it till he had explained pure apperception and the transcendental synthesis of the ima- gination. It is a direct refutation of the theory propounded by Dean Mansel, that we are presented with ourselves directly, or intuitively, as substances, in contrast to the indirect presentation of external things through their attributes. His theory shows how little Mansel had appre- hended this part of the Kritik, as he seems to have fol- lowed Kant pretty closely whenever he could understand him. It is bad enough to say that we have an intuition of self, when, as a matter of fact, we cannot make a single assertion about the intuition, or explain it, but merely MANSEL S THEORY reiterate the assertion — unmeaning in itself — for the sake of a philosophical theory. But surely the further collocation of words, ' intuiting ourselves as substance,' might have made Mansel pause. How is it conceivable that we should intuite substance, as distinguished from its attributes ? Surely if such a thing were conceivable, the substance which we postulate for external things would not be such an utterly negative, inconceivable representation ? In a private communication, as regards this criticism, he defended himself by saying, that if we were conscious of self as a cause, which Kant has explained just now, we must necessarily be conscious of ourselves as substance, as substance and cause are in this case identical. We hold, on the contrary, that we may be conscious of causation, or action, without knowing anything more of the substance which is the subject of the action. We hold the present case to be a very striking instance of this fact. The ulti- mate appeal is to each man's consciousness, and in this appeal the great majority of readers will probably agree with the great majority of modern philosophers, who, when- ever they have avoided amplifications of language, and stated the facts clearly, have plainly denied the immediate presentation of self as a substance. CHAPTER IX THE TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC, BOOK II. THE ANALYTIC OF PRINCIPLES General Logic is built on a basis agreeing perfectly with the higher faculties of knowledge, which are understanding, [the faculty of] judgment, and reason. We have accord- ingly the doctrine of concepts, judgments, and syllogisms arranged on this plan. As this formal Logic merely dis- cusses the form of thinking, it can even comprise in its Analytic the canon of the reason, for this faculty, apart from the peculiar nature of the cognitions used, must have its proceedings prescribed and fixed. Transcendental Logic, which is limited to a definite content, viz. pure a priori cognitions, cannot follow in its wake. For it appears that the transcendental use of Reason is not objectively valid, and so not the Logic of Truth, or Analytic, but occupies, as a Logic of illusion, a separate place, under the title of transcendental Dialectic. It is then Understanding and Judging only that have a canon of their objectively valid use in Transcendental Logic. The Analytic of Principles is simply a canon for the proper use of the faculty of judgment, and teaches it to apply to phenomena the Categories, which contain the a priori con- ditions for rules. Taking then the proper principles of the chap, ix THE FACULTY OF JUDGMENT 143 understanding for his subject, Kant indicates his scope by the title Doctrine of the Faculty of Judging. Introduction. — Of the transcendental Faculty of Judgment generally. 1 If the understanding be the faculty of rules, the judging faculty is the power of subsuming under rules, or distinguish- ing whether a given case comes under the rule. General Logic cannot possibly give any rules for this faculty. For as Logic abstracts altogether from the content of knowledge, and adheres to the pure form only, were we to attempt to show generally what should come under its general rules, this could only be done by another general rule, and the application of this would raise the same difficulty. The faculty of judging is then a special talent, which can be practised, but not imparted. It is, in fact, that mother- wit, which no schooling can replace, for even though we cram our minds with any quantity of rules derived from other sources, the faculty of using them must belong to our- selves naturally, and no learning can cure stupidity. But it is very useful to exercise this faculty by examples, especi- ally as they seldom conform exactly to the rule, and so teach us to apply it in a wider sense ; from this point of view they are specially requisite to men whose natural talent for judging is weak. We have seen above that general Logic can prescribe no 1 The reader will observe that throughout this chapter Kant uses the word "judgment" in a sort of practical every-day sense, not merely as the general faculty of comparing representations. In this latter sense he stated above (p. 82), " that judging and thinking were coextensive." He now uses it as we do, when we speak of a " man of judgment," viz. a man who knows how to apply his principles, or bring (subsume) particular cases under the right principles. This ambiguity was first noticed by Dr. Toleken. i 4 4 THE SCHEMATISM chap. rules for the faculty of judgment. It is so very different a case with transcendental Logic, that it appears to be its special business to direct and secure the use of the pure understanding by fixed rules. For in obtaining extension for our field of knowledge a priori, or as Doctrine, to use Kant's word, philosophy appears ill equipped, and has done nothing ; but as Kritik, to prevent errors of judgment in the few pure concepts that we possess — in this negative duty it must exercise all its skill and acuteness. But transcendental philosophy has this peculiarity, that beyond the rule (or better, the general condition of rules) given in the Categories, it can also show a priori the case to which the rule should be applied. It shares this advan- tage with Mathematic alone of other sciences, because it treats of concepts which are to refer a priori to objects ; consequently its objective validity, as well as the general conditions under which objects can be given, in conformity with these Categories, can only be shown a priori. Were this not done, they would be mere logical forms, and not Categories. Our transcendental theory of judging contains two parts — first, the Schematism, treating of the sensuous condition, under which Categories must be used ; secondly, the Principles of the pure understanding, or the synthetical judgments, which flow from the Categories under these conditions, and lie a priori at the basis of all the rest of our knowledge. The Transcendental Theory of Judging, or Analytic of Principles. Chap. I. Of the Schematism of the Pure Understanding. — When- ever we subsume an object under a concept, the two repre- sentations must be homogeneous, as a matter of course. IX THE TRANSCENDENTAL SCHEMA 145 Thus the concept of a plate is homogeneous with the purely Geometrical notion of a circle, for the roundness thought in the former, can be intuited in the latter. But the pure Categories are completely heterogeneous from all sensuous intuitions. How then can the latter be subsumed under the former, and how is, consequently, the application of the Categories to objects of sense possible ? For surely none will assert that any Category, such as Causality, can be intuited in phenomena and contained in them. Here then the necessity of the Theory of Judgment, or applica- bility of the pure Categories to experience, becomes apparent. In other sciences this divergence between the general con- cepts and their concrete representation does not exist. There must obviously be something intermediate, homo- geneous on the one hand with the Category, on the other with the phenomenon, and this must make the application possible. This mediating representation must be pure, and yet not only intellectual but sensuous. We shall call it the transcendental schema. We saw that the concept of the understanding produces pure synthetical unity of various parts generally. Now time, as the formal condition of the variety given in internal sense, and so of the combination of all our representations, also affords us an a priori multiplicity in pure intuition ; that is to say, the (pure) times, in which a series of various representations are given and combined by the mind, may themselves be regarded as an a priori multiplicity, com- bined, or combinable a priori into a pure unity. Therefore a transcendental determination of time must have this in common with the Category (which brings this time-deter- mination into unity), that it is universal, and depends on an a priori rule. But, on the other hand, it is also in con- formity with the phenomenon, inasmuch as time is contained 1 1. 146 THE SCHEMA CHAr - in every empirical representation of variety. Here then we have the schema we require. The deduction has already taught us that the Categories are only applicable to objects of experience, as distinguished from things per se ; that they consequently must require modifications of our sensibility, and this implies that formal conditions of sense (especially internal sense) are also necessary, as constituting the universal condition under which alone we can apply the Category to an object. This last condition is the schema of the Category, 1 and the proceeding of the under- standing as regards these schemata we call the schematism of the pure understanding. The schema in itself is indeed, like the image, the pro- duct of our imagination, but also differs in not being an individual picture, as it merely aims at representing the general way in which the unity of intuition is produced. Thus I can place five points together thus , and they produce a picture of one number 5. But when I think of what number in general means, I have before me the pecu- liar way in which the imagination proceeds to form such an arrangement of points. "When we represent to our- selves the general procedure of the imagination, in procuring an image for a concept, I call this the schema belonging to this concept." IT The illustration used by Kant shows that he was a Conceptualist, as regards the object of the mind in part at least of its thinking concerning general ideas, as they were called by the schoolmen. It also shows that, as usual, he took a deeper and fuller view of the mental state which was once the subject of such bitter controversy. Locke's abstract idea of a triangle, which had roused the ire and 1 I.e. the schema is the way in which we determine time in onler tu apply the Category. ix LOCKE S ABSTRACT IDEA 147 the laughter of so many critics, is here shown to be not only free from absurdity, but even the truest account of the matter contained in any previous philosophy. But Locke's fault had been to attend to the unimportant part of the process. It is the act of the mind in putting together the image of a triangle, not the completed image, which affords us the proper object in general thinking. 1 For the actual images are in every case different, and even inconsistent, but the act of making them in general is one and the same in all cases. It is what Kant calls a 'unity of action.' ' In fact,' he says, ' not images, but schemata, lie at the basis of our pure sensuous concepts. No image could ever be adequate to the general concept of a triangle, as it can- not embrace right-angled, scalenon, etc. The schema of a triangle can exist in thought only, and means a rule of the synthesis of the imagination, when applied to pure objects in space.' The same is the case with empirical concepts. My notion (schema) of a dog means a rule followed by my imagination in drawing the general features of a certain quadruped, without confining myself to any particular figure. This schematism of the understanding, as regards the pure form of objects, is a hidden craft in the secrets of the human mind, which we can hardly expect ever plainly to discover and to expound. But so much seems certain : the image is the product of the empirical working of the pro- ductive imagination ; the schema of sensuous concepts, such as figures in space, is as it were a sketch (monogram) of the pure imagination a priori, through which alone images can be brought into agreement with the concept. The schema of a pure concept of the understanding (Category), on the contrary, can never be reduced to an image, but is only a 1 On this view of the schema as an act, cf. Kritik, pp. 1 10, 435. THE SCHEMATA OF QUANTITY pure synthesis, according to a rule of unity supplied and expressed by the Category. This schema is, of course, a transcendental product of imagination, affecting the deter- mining of our internal sense generally, as to its form — Time. It produces that unity expressed by the concept, which is a phase of the transcendental unity of apperception. Let us proceed to details. The pure image of all quantities {quanta) in external sense is space ; for all objects of the senses generally, it is time. But the pure schema of quantity [guantifos], as a Category, is number, or the successive addition of homo- geneous units. The act of numbering is nothing but the unity of combining the variety of a homogeneous intuition ; in fact, I generate time itself in the successive apprehending of my intuition. [Kant here means that the Category of Unity is exemplified or imitated by the mind considering the perception in a single act, or moment of time, to indi- cate unity. The Category of Plurality is exemplified by the mind requiring several successive moments to apprehend a perception, of which the parts are separate but homo- geneous, and therefore the several acts appear as separate units. Totality implies the adoption of a large unit, under which many smaller are combined.] Reality in the Category is that which corresponds to sensation generally, that of which the concept indicates being in time, as opposed to Negation, or non-being in time. Their opposition is therefore that of the same time full (of sensation) and empty. ' As time is only the form of intuition, or of objects as phenomena, that which in these objects corresponds to sensation is the transcend- ental matter of all objects, as things per se, x in fact their 1 Not ' actual things,' as Mr. Watson renders {Selections from Kant, p. 88). THE SCHEMA OF REALITY 149 reality.' 1 We must judge of this reality bythe amount of sensa- tion produced upon us. But every sensation has a degree, or quantity, by which it can affect our faculty of representation during the same length of time, more or less, varying from the maximum of sensation down to its complete absence, or negation. Thus a continuous transition from reality to negation is possible, which enables us to regard every reality as a quantum (of sensation). The schema of a reality, in this sense, is its continuous and uniform genera- tion in time, when we pass from total absence of sensation in time to some particular degree of sensation. [As we before had several successive homogeneous perceptions in successive moments, giving us number, so we must here suppose several successive perceptions homogeneous in their character, but differing in the increasing intensity of the sensation they produce. Kant considers that we must conceive the maximum of sensation as made up of all the lesser degrees which we could apprehend successively in time. But as the sum of them is given to us in an equally short time as each of the lesser degrees, we come to know the difference between the same subdivision of time as either full or empty. So it is that an object which affects even three different senses together has more reality than an object which affects only one. The moment in which it affects us is a full time, and the fulness may be measured by three times of equal length, each filled by one of the sensations. The same fact is implied when we speak of one object being ten shades darker than another 1 This statement, occurring in the First Edition, as well as the suc- ceeding ones, is a strange way of preaching the absolute idealism which Schopenhauer and Fischer ascribe to Kant ! He regards sensation here as directly suggesting something apart from our cognition, though we have no means of studying it save through our sensation. ijo THE SCHEMATA OF RELATION chap. of the same kind. Quality is, after all, a quantity of reality.] x ' The schema of substance is the permanence of the real in time, or the representation of it, as the substratum of an empirical time-determination generally, which remains, while all else changes. Time does not elapse, but rather the existence of changeable things elapses in it.' Consequently substance, or the permanent in existence, is what corre- sponds in phenomena to time, itself unchangeable and per- manent. It is therefore by substance alone that we can determine sequence and co-existence of phenomena in time. 2 The schema of Causality consists in the succession of various phenomena, so far as it is subject to a rule [invari- able sequence]. The schema of community or reciprocal causation of substances as regards their accidents, is the necessary simitltaiieity of the determinations of both. The schema of possibility is the agreement of our synthesis of various representations with the conditions of time gener- ally. For example, contradictory attributes can only exist in a thing successively ; consequently possibility determines the existence of a thing at some time. The schema of 1 Cf. Prokg, p. 86, n. 2 As he tells us afterwards that impenetrability is the empirical criterion of substance {Kritik, p. 169), we may take this as a specimen of a permanent reality (of sensation), which remains the same, and so enables us to determine changes in other qualities. So the chameleon remains a solid body while its colours change, and we accordingly talk of its substance remaining the same, while its accidents vary. But were there not a permanent phenomenon of some kind, corresponding to the general lapse of time, we should not know that other sensations occupied shorter time, and changed while the cause of them is conceived un- changeable. We may add, that these illustrations of the various schemata are developed and explained by the succeeding chapters on the Prin- ciples which embody them, and that it is impossible to make them clear to the reader till he has studied the theory of the Principles. SUMMARY 151 actuality is its existence at a definite time ; that of necessity its existence at all times. We can now see the relation of all the schemata. That of quantity is the putting together (synthesis) of portions of time, in our successive apprehension of an object or objects. That of quality is the putting together of (feebler) sensations in time, or filling time with them. The schema of relation is the attitude of perceptions to one another in all time (either as transient and permanent, as necessarily conse- quent, or as necessarily simultaneous). The schema of modality represents to us time itself, regarded generally as the correlate for determining an object, when we consider how or whether it belongs to time. The schemata affect therefore respectively a priori, and according to rules — 1, the succession of time ; 2, the content of time ; 3, the order in time ; and 4, the sum total (Inbegriff) of time, as regards all possible phenomena. Kant concludes the discussion by reiterating what he had said above (§§ 22, 23), as to the use of the Categories being only empirical, and that they have no meaning except as applied to objects of sense. The discussion of the schematism has shown this more plainly, in that it proves that the transcendental synthesis of the imagination is wholly employed in time and its determinations. The schema is only the sensuous concept of an object in accordance with the Category. If we lay aside this restriction, the Category preserves nothing but a logical meaning, and can determine no object, not to say a thing per se. IT It will tend to put this schematism as well as the deduction of the Categories in a clearer light, if we consider Schopenhauer's criticism, which at first sight appears some- what plausible. Kant's plan (he tells us) was to find for 152 SCHOPENHAUER'S OBJECTIONS chap. every empirical l function of the understanding its tran- scendental parallel. Now when we use a very abstract empirical concept symbolically (as Leibnitz would say), we often glance back towards the empirical intuitions from which we have obtained the concept, and we call up in imagination a sort of imperfect image momentarily, merely to assure ourselves that our thinking is possible in intuition — a psychological fact which any one will discover for him- self easily by reflection. This fugitive phantasm, inter- mediate between abstract concepts and clear intuitions, Kant called a schema, and thence concluded that between the pure intuitive faculty of sensibility and the pure faculty of thought there are similar schemata of the pure Categories. But what is the use of this schematism in empirical think- ing ? Merely to secure that the content of the concept be correct. The matter has been abstracted from empirical intuition : we refer to it occasionally, to make sure that our thinking is about reality. But Schopenhauer objects that the pure a priori concepts come from within, and are not derived from intuition ; hence, such concepts cannot be referred to any intuition to guarantee their reality. It was, then, upon the misapplication of this psychological fact above mentioned, that Kant based his elaborate schematism of the pure understanding. IT Although Schopenhauer's criticism is unsound, it has been here stated, as the refutation of it will bring the real doctrine of Kant into a clearer light. Schopenhauer has well described the ' abstract idea ' of Locke as a fugitive phantasm, which gives reality to our symbolical concepts. What is the exact office of this schema ? To insure to us that our (empirical) concepts are applicable in experience ; to show us that they are not merely logically possible, but 1 He should have said logical, when he refers to Kant. REFUTED 153 objectively real.. Now, in empirical concepts this require- ment is satisfied, if the content of the concept answers to the schema, as the law of contradiction secures its possi- bility, or logical correctness. But all our objects of experi- ence stand not only under representative concepts (genus, species, etc.), but also under assertative concepts (substance, cause, etc.). These are the Categories, which were already proved to be part of the (transcendental) content of repre- sentations. Hence, such concepts must be shown to be applicable to objects of experience just as generic concepts are. These latter establish their claim by means of the schema just mentioned — how can the Categories do so ? IT Let us look back to the deduction of the Categories. All phenomena were found to agree in one point at all events — they must be my phenomena. It is this unity which makes us speak of Nature as a unity, and yet as consisting of many lesser units, called objects. For there is no unity in our experience except what is imposed by our minds. Accordingly this highest and most general syn- thetical unity of consciousness acts upon phenomena by imposing upon them various phases of its unity, various lesser unities, all dependent upon the highest synthetical unity. These lesser unities are the Categories. They are imposed by the mind upon phenomena, which thus become objects. But how ? The sensations which are the com- ponent elements of the object, being received into the mind successively, are reproduced, but not simply ; the imagination moulds them, and so produces, not only the received phenomena, but also the form of a concept along with them ; so that, owing to this addition (which is the transcendental content of the representation), that faculty is properly called productive. But what is the form added to the received elements by the imagination and under- 1 54 THE PSYCHOLOGICAL PROCESS chap, ix standing in this its action ? Surely no additional sensation, no heterogeneous intellectual something, called a Category. The imagination can only arrange or regulate the relations to time of all our sensations. This is the point upon which the imagination fixes ; for all our thoughts whatsoever must be in time. The Categories must be thought under this condition. The Categories then are imitated (so to speak) or exemplified in time-determinations, which are imposed by the productive imagination upon phenomena. Thus the pure Category of substance is that which can only be subject — and not predicate. An image of such a concept is impossible ; but the nearest sensuous representation we can get is something which is absolutely permanent in time. This, then, is the schema under which the imagina- tion brings certain phenomena, which are accordingly declared to be substance, and it is only by means of such schemata that we can assure ourselves that our thought is applicable to experience. In Mr. Monck's briefer words : — Sense or experience has its formal as well as its material conditions. The office of the schema of an empirical con- cept is to show that the material part is right ; that of the schema of a pure concept to show that the formal part is so also. Such is, in brief, the general notion of the schema- tism, which follows necessarily from the productive imagin- ation, and which forms one of the most remarkable claims of Kant for originality and acuteness. CHAPTER X SECOND CHAPTER OF THE ANALYTIC OF PRINCIPLES § i. Of the System of all the Principles of the Pure Under- standing. — So far we have only considered the general con- ditions, which alone justify the transcendental judgment in using the Categories for synthetical 'judgments. We now proceed to give a systematic sketch of the judgments thus actually produced. Of course, our clue will still be the table of the Categories, since it is their relation to experi- ence which constitutes all pure rational cognition. A priori Principles (lit. fiiTidamental principles J ) are not so called, merely because they contain the foundation of others, but also because they themselves are not based on higher and more universal cognitions. Yet this property does not free them from requiring to be proved. Such proof cannot, indeed, be objective, being rather the founda- tion of all knowledge of its object. But a proof from the subjective sources, which make it possible to produce cog- nition of objects in general, is not only itself possible, but even necessary, for otherwise such assertions must run the risk of being considered mere assumptions. Furthermore, we here confine ourselves to the Principles 1 To avoid cumbrousness, we uniformly translate Gnmdsatz by Prin- ciple. 156 PRINCIPLE OF ANALYTICAL JUDGMENTS chap. which refer to the Categories. We therefore exclude the Principles of the transcendental Aesthetic, that space and time are the conditions of the possibility of phenomena, and of phenomena only. For the same reason, mathe- matical Principles are not part of this system. Yet still their necessity, since they are synthetical and a priori, must find place in it, not to prove their accuracy or necessity, but merely to explain and justify (deduce) the possibility of such pure cognitions. We shall first discuss the Principle of analytical judgments, in order to free the synthetical, with which they are contrasted, from misapprehension, and illustrate their real nature. Of the highest Principle of all Analytical Judgments. — The highest, though but negative, condition of all our judgments, quite irrespective of their objects, is that they shall not contradict themselves. It is negative, because judgments may conform to it, and yet be either false, as combining concepts otherwise than the objects direct, or baseless, as having no foundation either a priori ox posteriori. This proposition, then : no thing can have a predicate which contradicts it, is the Law of Contradiction, is an universal but negative criterion of all truth, and is merely logical, referring to cognitions as such, apart from their content. We may, however, make a positive use of it, not merely to avoid error, but to know truth. In analytical judgments whether affirmative or negative, the truth can always be adequately known according to this principle. For that which is already thought in the concept of an object, must be rightly affirmed of that object, and its contradictory denied, else the object would contradict our concept of it. The law, is, therefore, the universal and adequate principle of all analytical knoivledge, but here its use as a sufficient criterion ends. It is, of course, a sine qua non of all judg- x THE LAW OF CONTRADICTION 157 ments, but cannot determine their truth generally. And as we are concerned only with the synthetical part of our knowledge, we must, of course, beware of violating it, but cannot expect from it any light as to the truth of this kind of knowledge. But there is a formula for this celebrated, though purely formal law, which does contain a synthesis, unnecessarily imported into it through inadvertence. Here it is : It is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be at the same time. Here apodictic certainty, which is implied of course, is superfluously added by the word impossible, and, what is more important, the proposition is affected by the condition of time. It affirms a thing A, which is something = B, cannot at the same time be not-B ; but it can be both B and not-B successively. For example : a man who is young, cannot at the same time be old, but becomes so in the lapse of years. It is quite wrong to make the purely logical law of contradiction depend on time-relations, and such a course obscures its real import. The mistake arises from first separating the predicate of a thing from our con- cept of it, and then connecting its contradictory with that predicate. This produces no contradiction with the sub- ject, but only with the former predicate, which we had connected synthetically with the subject, and even then only when the two predicates are posited simultaneously. If I say a man who is unlearned, is not learned, I must add, at the same time, or it may be false. But if I say, No unlearned man is learned, the proposition is analytical, and is evident without the addition of at the same time. For this reason, then, Kant alters the formula, in order to express clearly the analytical nature of the law. § 2. Of the highest Principle of all Synthetical Judgments. — To determine the possibility of synthetical judgments is, 158 PRINCIPLE OF SYNTHETICAL JUDGMENTS chap. as we have seen, the duty not of general but of transcend- ental Logic, and is indeed its most important function, for thus alone can the compass and limits of the pure under- standing be determined. As, in synthetical judgments, I must pass out of the concept {subject) to consider something quite different in relation with it — this is never a relation of identity or contradiction, and so in the judgment, per se, we cannot see either truth or error. Granted, then, that we must pass out of a given con- cept, to compare something else synthetically with it, some third thing, or medium, is necessary, to contain the syn- thesis of two concepts. What is this medium ? There is but one envelope (Inbegriff) which embraces all our repre- sentations, viz. — the internal sense, and its form, Time. The synthesis of these our representations depends on the Imagination, their synthetical unity on the unity of apper- ception. Here, then, we must seek the possibility of syn- thetical judgments, — nay, more, of synthetical a priori judgments, which will be shown necessary from these sources, if a cognition of representations can be accom- plished, resting exclusively on the synthesis of repre- sentations. If a cognition is to have objective reality — that is, to refer to an object, and have in it significance, the object must of course be" somehow given. To have an object given immediately, by representing it in intuition, means nothing but to refer its representation to experience, either actual or possible. Even space and time, pure and cer- tainly a priori as they are, would have no objective validity, and no meaning, were not their necessary use exhibited in objects of experience ; nay, our very representation of them is a mere schema, ever referring to the reproductive imagination for matter to fill it, without which they would x THE POSSIBILITY OF EXPERIENCE 159 bear no signification. So it is with every one of our concepts. The possibility of experience, then, or of being experienced, is what gives all our a priori cognitions objective validity. Experience again is based on a synthetical unity — a syn- thesis of phenomenal objects according to the Categories, or principles of its form, which lie a priori at the basis of experience. These are indeed universal rules of the unity of phenomena, but their objective reality, nay, even their possibility, can only be shown in experience. This is the medium in which synthetical a priori propositions can exhibit their objective reality. We do, indeed, in the case of space, and of the figures which the productive imagination draws in it, discover a great deal a priori by way of synthetical judgments, and actually without requiring any experience ; but such know- ledge would be occupation with what is a mere chimera, were not space considered as the condition of phenomena, which are the materials of external experience. Hence, even the pure synthetical judgments of Mathematic refer to possible experience, or rather to its very possibility, and on this alone is based the objective validity of their synthesis. ' As, therefore, experience as an empirical synthesis is, in its possibility, the only sort of cognition which gives to all other syntheses reality, so experience as a cognition a priori can only have truth, or agreement with its object, by containing nothing more than what is necessary for the synthetical unity of experience genera]]) - . Here, then, is the highest Principle of all synthetical judgments : even- object comes under the necessary conditions of the syn- thetical unity of the manifold of intuitions in a possible experience ' Thus the possibility of (the general faculty of) experience, and the possibility of (there being) objects of ex- 160 UNDERSTANDING AS SOURCE OF PRINCIPLES chap. perience, lie under the same conditions, and thus our syn- thetical a priori judgments about the former obtain (through the latter) objective reality. 1 § 3. Systematic Exposition of all the synthetical Principles of the pure Understanding. — We must ascribe it purely to the understanding that there exists such a thing as prin- ciples. For the pure understanding is not only a faculty of rules, but the very source of Principles, according to which every possible object stands necessarily under rules, which add to phenomena the cognition of an object corresponding to them. Even laws of nature, regarded as principles of our ordinary experiences, carry with them the expression of necessity, or at least the suggestion of being determined by grounds valid for all experiences. But such laws again stand under the higher Principles of the understanding, which they merely apply to particular cases. There is no danger of confusing these two classes of Principles, for the absence of that necessity according to concepts, which the latter have, is easily perceived in the former, however uni- versally valid. But there are pure a priori Principles, which are not properly to be attributed to the pure under- standing, because they are drawn (not from pure concepts, but) from pure intuitions, by means of the understanding ; such are those of Mathematic. Still, their objective reality in experience, and the deduction of their possibility, must rest on the pure understanding. Hence, says Kant, I shall not enumerate among my Principles those of Mathematic, but only such as Mathe- matic requires for an a priori basis of its possibility and objective validity. These are the principles on which 1 The reader should compare the corresponding discussion in the Prolegomena (pp. 63 sqq.), entitled, Hoiv is a pure Science of A T atnre (Physic) possible? x TABLE OF THE PRINCIPLES 161 Mathematical judgments are based, and proceed from con- cepts to intuitions, not vice versa (as the ordinary Mathe- matical axioms do). In applying the Categories to possible experience we may use them either mathematically or dynamically, for as they may refer merely to the intuition, so they may also refer to the existence of a phenomenon. 1 The a priori conditions of intuition as regards possible experience are absolutely necessary ; those of the existence of objects of a possible empirical intuition are, as such, only contingent. Hence the Principles of Mathematical use must be uncon- ditionally necessary, and be apodictical in form ; those of dynamical use, though also (of course) necessary a priori, are so mediately, under the condition of empirical thinking in some experience. The latter have not therefore such immediate evidence, though equally certain, as generally applied to experience. The table of the Categories is of course our natural clue to the Principles, inasmuch as these are merely the rules of objectively applying them. These Principles are therefore — r. Axioms of Intuition. 2 3- Anticipations Analogies of Perception. of Experience. 4- Postulates of Empirical thinking in general. These terms are carefully chosen, to indicate distinctions of evidence and use. It will soon appear that the determining 1 Cf. p. 97, supra. I M 1 62 ANALYSIS OF COMBINATION chap, x of phenomena by the Categories of Quantity and Quality (regarding merely the Form of the latter) differs from that of the others, one being intuitively, the other discursively certain. Hence they are distinguished as Mathematical and Dynamical Principles.^ At the same time, they are not the Principles of Mathematic, nor of general Dynamic (Physic), but the Principles of the understanding in respect of our internal sense, upon which depends the possibility of both these more special classes of axioms. Kant's Prin- ciples are therefore so called on account of their application, not their content. 1 Kant adds a note in the Second Edition, giving a sketch of the various classes of combination. — All combination {conjujictio) is either composi- tion or nexus. The former is the synthesis of multiplicity not necessarily inseparable, as, for example, the two triangles formed by the diagonal of a square. This is the nature of all synthesis of homogeneotts parts that can be mathematically estimated. It is aggregation, if extensive ; coalition, if intensive. Nexus again is the synthesis of inseparable parts, such as accident and substance, effect and cause, which are heterogeneous, though combined a priori. This combination, as being arbitrary \_will- kuhrlich, he means that no reason can be assigned why these particular heterogeneous elements are combined], I call dynamical, because it concerns the combination of the existence of multiplicity, and this again is either physical, of phenomena among one another, or metaphysical, of phenomena in the cognitive faculty a priori. These four kinds of combination evidently answer to the four classes of Principles. CHAPTER XI THE MATHEMATICAL PRINCIPLES (i.) Axioms of Intuition. — Their Principle is: All intui- tions are extensive Quantities} Proof. All phenomena contain as to form an intuition in space and time, which is their a priori basis. They cannot there- fore be empirically apprehended except by combining mul- tiplicity, and so generating the representation of a definite space or time, the parts of which are homogeneous, and conceived as a synthetical unity. This is the notion of a 1 See what he says about the relation of this Principle to axioms proper in his more special discussion in the Methodology, Kritik, p. 446. Kant, with that habit of repetition and variation of statement common to the books of almost all great discoverers, has in his Second Edition inserted after the Definition of each of the first three classes of Principles an additional paragraph, entitled Proof or Demonstration. With one exception (that of Community) these inserted paragraphs merely repeat in varying language what follows them, and what had stood in the original edition. The reader who compares our Comment- ary with Kant's text will therefore find that we have curtailed the arguments considerably, but only by leaving out repetitions. We trust there is no distinct point, however small, omitted. The parallel dis- cussion in the Prolegomena, §§ 24-32, will be found in vol. ii. pp. 81 sqq. 1 64 EXTENSIVE QUANTITY quantity (quanti). As therefore the perception of an object as phenomenon is only possible through this synthetical unity of multiplicity, all phenomena are extensive quantities, because they must be represented by the same synthesis which determines space and time generally as quantities. Kant defines an extensive quantity as that in which the notion of the part precedes and renders possible the notion of the whole. So I cannot conceive a line without drawing it in thought, and thus generating successively all the parts which make up the whole intuition. It is so also with every time, even the shortest. As every phenomenon must be intuited through space and time, it must also be an aggregate, or combination of given parts, and this is only the case with those quantities which we apprehend as extensive. ' On the successive synthesis of the productive imagina- tion in generating figures is based Geometry and its axioms, which express the a priori conditions of intuition under which alone the schema of a pure concept of an external intuition can exist ; e.g. between two points only one right line is possible ; two right lines cannot enclose a space. These axioms properly concern only quanta as such.' But as to determining the quantitas of a thing, and answering the question, How large is it ? — though there are various synthetical and indemonstrable propositions about it, yet they cannot be called axioms. For that equals added to equals make equals is an analytical proposition, whereas axioms must be synthetical. On the other hand, the self-evident propositions about particular numbers are synthetical, but not universal, like geometrical axioms. They should therefore be called numerical formulae. 7 + 5 = 12, as has been already seen (above, p. 37), is synthet- xi REALITAS PHENOMENON 165 ical. 1 But it is also singular. For this synthesis of unities can only be made in one way, though the use of the num- bers is afterwards universal. The construction of a triangle, as a pure function of the productive imagination, may be produced in a thousand ways, but 7 and 1 2 only in one way. Were such propositions, then, axioms, they would be infinite in number. This transcendental Principle of the Mathematic of pheno- mena extends our a priori cognition widely. For now we see why pure Mathematic in all its precision is applicable to objects of experience. Empirical intuition is only possible through pure intuition. What Geometry says of the latter must therefore be true of the former. All evasions of the laws of construction of space (such as the endless divisi- bility of lines and angles) must vanish. For these theories, which deny the objective validity of space and of the Mathematic based on it, are only the devices of a mis- guided reason, which endeavours to free the objects of the senses from the formal conditions of our sensibility, in which case nothing whatever could be asserted of them a priori, and Geometry itself would become impossible. (2.) Anticipations of Perception. — Their principle is : In all phenomena the Real, which is an object of sensa- tion, has intensive quantity, or degree. 2 1 Kant (and Mansel) seem to have overlooked such numerical axioms as a (b + c) = ab + ac, and ab = ba, which are both synthetical and general. 2 This Principle was worded in a slightly different way in the First Edition. ' The Principle, which anticipates all perceptions as such, is thus expressed : In all phenomena sensation and the real, which corre- sponds to it in the object (realitas phenomenon) has a degree, or intensive quantity.' It will be seen that the form of the First Edition is more realistic here than that of the Second. At the same time, we should be most cautious not to suppose that the real, which corresponds to sensa- 1 66 THE PROLEPSIS OF EPICURUS chap. Proof. Perception is empirical consciousness, in which there is sensation. Phenomenal objects of perception are more than mere formal intuitions (of space and time). They con- tain in addition the materials for some object, represented as existing in space and time. This is the real (element) of sensation, and accordingly a mere subjective representation, which makes us conscious of being affected, and which we refer to an object in general. Now from this empirical consciousness down to pure consciousness a gradual change is possible till we reach a mere formal intuition of space and time. So we may also regard sensation as a gradual pro- duction, beginning with o, in pure intuition, and rising to a certain quantity. Thus, while it is not an objective re- presentation containing space and time, it still has an intensive quantity, or a degree of influence on our sensibility, which must accordingly be attributed to all objects of per- ception. All cognition, which determines empirical cognition a priori, may be called irp6Xr]t(/i