URIS LIBRARY B 2787.E5C3279i2""'''-'''"'^ ^'"mmmSM^"^ *" ^"* '"*"™ metaphy 3 1924 011 523 168 The original of tliis bool< is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31 924011 5231 68 KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS EDITED IN ENGLISH DR. PAUL CARUS THIRD EDITION WITH AN ESSAY ON KANT'S PHILOSOPHY, AND OTHER SUPPLEMENTARY MATERIAL FOR THE STUDY OF KANT CHICAGO THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY 1912 TRANSLATION COPYRIGHTED BY The Open Court Publishing Co. igo2. CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY GIFT OF Professor Stuart M. Brovm, Jr. UNDERGRADUATE TRANSLA- The Open C PUBLISHERS' PREFACE. "jy" ANT'S Prolegomena} although a small book, is indubitably the most important of his writings. It furnishes us with a key to his main work, The Critique of Pure Reason ; in fact, it is an extract containing all the salient ideas of Kant's system. It approaches the subject in the simplest and most direct way, and is therefore best adapted as an introduction into his philosophy. For this reason, The Open Court Publishing Company has deemed it advisable to bring out a new edition of the work, keeping in view its broader use as -a. preliminary survey and explanation of Kant's philosophy in general. In order to make the book useful for this broader purpose, the editor has not only stated his own views concerning the problem underlying the Prolegomena (see page 167 et seq.), but has also collected the most important ma- terials which have reference to Kant's philosophy, or to the recep- tion which was accorded to it in various quarters (see page 241 et seq. ). The selections have not been made from a partisan stand- point, but have been chosen with a view to characterising the atti- tude of different minds, and to directing the student to the best literature on the subject. It is not without good reasons that the appearance of the Critique of Pure Reason is regarded as the beginning of a new era in the history of philosophy ; and so it seems that a compre- hension of Kant's position, whether we accept or reject it, is indis- pensable to the student of philosophy. It is not his solution which 1 Prolegomena means literally prefatory or introductory remarks. It is the neuter plural of the present passive participle of irpoAe'-yetv, to speak he/ore^ i.e., to make introductory remarks before beginning one's regular discourse. iv PREFACE. makes the sage of Konigsberg the initiator of modern thought, but his formulation of the problem. The present translation is practically new, but it goes without saying that the editor utilised the labors of his predecessors, among whom Prof. John P. Mahaffy and John H. Bernard deserve special credit. Richardson's translation of 1818 may be regarded as super- seded and has not been consulted, but occasional reference has been made to that of Prof. Ernest Belfort Bax. Considering the diflSculties under which even these translators labored we must recognise the fact that they did their work well, with painstaking diligence, great love of the subject, and good judgment. The editor of the present translation has the advantage of being to the manor born ; moreover, he is pretty well versed in Kant's style ; and wherever he differs from his predecessors in the interpretation of a construction, he has deviated from them not without good rea- sons. Nevertheless there are some passages which will still re- main doubtful, though happily they are of little consequence. As a curiosum in Richardson's translation Professor Mahaffy mentions that the words widersinnig ge-wundene Schnecken, which simply means "symmetric helices,"' are rendered by "snails rolled up contrary to all sense " — a wording that is itself contrary to all sense and makes the whole paragraph unintelli- gible. We may add an instance of another mistake that misses the mark. Kant employs in the Appendix a word that is no longer used in German. He speaks of the Cento der Metafhysik as having neue Laffen and einen verdnderten Zuschnitt. Mr. Bax trans- lates Cento by "body," La^^en by "outgrowths," and Zuschnitt by "figure." His mistake is perhaps not less excusable than Richardson's ; it is certainly not less comical, and it also destroys the sense, which in the present case is a very striking simile. 1 Mahaffy not incorrectly translates "spirals winding opposite ways," and Mr, Bax follows him verbatim even to the repetition of the footnote. PREFACE. V Cento is a Latin word* derived from the Greek nhirpm),^ meaning "a garment of many patches sewed together, " or, as we might now say, "a crazy quilt." * * • In the hope that this book will prove useful, The Open Court Publishing Company offers it as a help to the student of philosophy. p. c. IThe French centon is still ia use. ZjcEi'Tpfoi', (z) one that hears the marks of the fcevrpoi', goad; a rogue, (2) a patched cloth ; {3) any kind of patchwork, especially verses made up of scraps from other authors. TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE Kant's Prolegomena 1-163 Essay on Kant's Philosophy by Dr. Paul Carus. (With Por- traits of Kant and Garve) 167-240 Supplementary Materials for the Study of Kant's Lite and Philosophy : Introductory Note 243 Kant's Life and Writings. (After Windelband) 245 The Critique of Practical Reason and the Critique of Judgment. (After Weber) 250 Kant's Views on Religion. (After Schwegler) 258 Kant and Materialism. (After Lange) 261 Kant and Deism. (After Heinrich Heine.) With Fac- simile of the Title-page of the Critique of Pure Reason 264 The Kantian Philosophy. (After Arthur Schopenhauer) 279 Hostile Estimate of Kant by a Swedenborgian. (After Theodore F. Wright) 283 Facsimile and Translation of a Letter of Kant to His Brother 285 Chronology of Kant's Life and Publications. (After Paulsen) 287 Index to Kant's Prolegomena 293 Index to the Article on Kant's Philosophy 299 KANT'S PROLEGOMENA. INTRODUCTION. THESE Prolegomena are destined for the use, not of pupils, but of future teachers, and even the latter should not expect that they will be serviceable for the systematic exposition of a ready-made science, but merely for the discovery of the science itself. There are scholarly men, to whom the history of philosophy (both ancient and modern) is philosophy itself; for these the present Prolegomena are not written. They must wait till those who endeavor to draw from the fountain of reason itself have com- pleted their work ; it will then be the historian's turn to inform the world of what has been done. Unfor- tunately, nothing can be said, which in their opinion has not been said before, and truly the same proph- ecy applies to all future time ; for since the human reason has for many centuries speculated upon innu- merable objects in various ways, it is hardly to be ex- pected that we should not be able to discover anal- ogies for every new idea among the old sayings of past ages. My object is to persuade all those who think Meta- physics worth studying, that it is absolutely necessary to pause a moment, and, neglecting all that has been done, to propose first the preliminary question, 'Whether such a thing as metaphysics be at all pos- sible?' 2 rant's prolegomena. If it be a science, how comes it that it cannot, like other sciences, obtain universal and permanent recognition ? If not, how can it maintain its preten- sions, and keep the human mind in suspense with hopes, never ceasing, yet never fulfilled? Whether then we demonstrate our knowledge or our ignorance in this field, we must come once for all to a definite conclusion respecting the nature of this so-called sci- ence, which cannot possibly remain on its present footing. It seems almost ridiculous, while every other science is continually advancing, that in this, which pretends to be Wisdom incarnate, for whose oracle every one inquires, we should constantly move round the same spot, without gaining a single step. And so its followers having melted away, we do not find men confident of their ability to shine in other sciences venturing their reputation here, where everybody, how- ever ignorant in other matters, may deliver a final verdict, as in this domain there is as yet no standard weight and measure to distinguish sound knowledge from shallow talk. After all it is nothing extraordinary in the elabora- tion of a science, when men begin to wonder how far it has advanced, that the question should at last occur, whether and how such a science is possible? Human reason so delights in constructions, that it has several times built up a tower, and then razed it to examine the nature of the foundation. It is never too late to become wise ; but if the change comes late, there is always more difficulty in starting a reform. The question whether a science be possible, pre- supposes a doubt as to its actuality. But such a doubt offends the men whose whole possessions consist of this supposed jewel ; hence he who raises the doubt INTRODUCTION. 3 must expect opposition from all sides. Some, in the proud consciousness of their possessions, which are ancient, and therefore considered legitimate, will take their metaphysical compendia in their hands, and look down on him with contempt ; others, who never see anything except it be identical with what they have seen before, will not understand him, and everything will remain for a time, as if nothing had happened to excite the concern, or the hope, for an impending change. Nevertheless, I venture to predict that the inde- pendent reader of these Prolegomena will not only doubt his previous science, but ultimately be fully persuaded, that it cannot exist unless the demands here stated on which its possibility depends, be satis- fied ; and, as this has never been done, that there is, as yet, no such thing as Metaphysics. But as it can never cease to be in demand,' — since the interests of common sense are intimately interwpven with it, he must confess that a radical reform, or rather a new birth of the science after an original plan, are un- avoidable, however men may struggle against it for a while. Since the Essays of Locke and Leibnitz, or rather since the origin of metaphysics so far as we know its history, nothing has ever happened which was more decisive to its fate than the attack made upon it by David Hume. He threw no light on this species of knowledge, but he certainly struck a spark from I Says Horace ; " Rusticus expectat, dum defluat amnis, at ille Labitur et labetur in omne volubilis aevum; " ' ' A rustic fellow waiteth on the shore For the river to flow away. But the Txver flows, and flows on as before, And it flows forever and aye," 4 KANT'S PROLEGOMENA. which light might have been obtained, had it caught some inflammable substance and had its smouldering fire been carefully nursed and developed. Hume started from a single but important concept in Metaphysics, viz., that of Cause and Effect (in- cluding its derivatives force and action, etc.). He challenges reason, which pretends to have given birth to this idea from herself, to answer him by what right she thinks anything to be so constituted, that if that thing be posited, something else also must necessarily be posited ; for this is the meaning of the concept of cause. He demonstrated irrefutably that it Was per- fectly impossible for reason to think a priori and by means of concepts a combination involving necessity. We cannot at all see why, in consequence of the ex- istence of one thing, another must necessarily exist, or how the concept of such a combination can arise a priori. Hence he inferred, that reason was alto- gether deluded with reference to this concept, which she erroneously considered as one of her children, whereas in reality it was nothing but a bastard of im- agination, impregnated by experience, which sub- sumed certain representations under the Law of Asso- ciation, and mistook the subjective necessity of habit for an objective necessity arising from insight. Hence he inferred that reason had no power to think such combinations, even generally, because her concepts would then be purely fictitious, and all her pretended a priori cognitions nothing but common experiences marked with a false stamp. In plain language there is not, and cannot be, any such thing as metaphysics at all. 1 1 Nevertheless Hume called this very destructive science metaphysics and attached to it great value. Metaphysics and morals [he declares in the INTRODUCTION. 5 However hasty and mistaken Hume's conclusion may appear, it was at least founded upon investiga- tion, and this investigation deserved the concentrated attention of the brighter spirits of his day as well as determined efforts on their part to discover, if pos- sible, a happier solution of the problem in the sense proposed by him, all of which would have speedily resulted in a complete reform of the science. But Hume suffered the usual misfortune of meta- physicians, of not being understood. It is positively painful to see how utterly his opponents, Reid, Os- wald, Beattie, and lastly Priestley, missed the point of the problem ; for while they were ever taking for granted that which he doubted, and demonstrating with zeal and often with impudence that which he never thought of doubting, they so misconstrued his valuable suggestion that everything remained in its old condition, as if nothing had happened. The question was not whether the concept of cause was right, useful, and even indispensable for our knowledge of nature, for this Hume had never doubted ; but whether that concept could be thought by reason a priori, and consequently whether it pos- sessed an inner truth, independent of all experience, implying a wider application than merely to the ob- jects of experience. This was Hume's problem. It was a question concerning the origin, not concerning the indispensable need of the concept. Were the former fourth part of his Essays] are the most important branches of science ; math- ematics and physics are not nearly so important. But the acute man merely regarded the negative use arising from the moderation of extravagant claims of speculative reason, and the complete settlement of the many endless and troublesome controversies that mislead mankind. He overlooked the posi- tive injury which results, if reason be deprived of its most important pro- spects, which can alone supply to the will the highest aim. for all its en- deavor. 6 KANT'S PROLEGOMENA. decided, the conditions of the use and the sphere of its valid application would have been determined as a matter of course. But to satisfy the conditions of the problem, the opponents of the great thinker should have penetrated very deeply into the nature of reason, so far as it is concerned with pure thinking, — a task which did not suit them. They found a more convenient method of being defiant without any insight, viz., the appeal to common sense. It is indeed a great gift of God, to pos- sess right, or (as they now call it) plain common sense. But this common sense must be shown prac- tically, by well-considered and reasonable thoughts and words, not by appealing to it as an oracle, when no rational justification can be advanced. To appeal to common sense, when insight and science fail, and no sooner — this is one of the subtile discoveries of modern times, by means of which the most superficial ranter can safely enter the lists with the most thorough thinker, and hold his own. But as long as a particle of insight remains, no one would think of having re- course to this subterfuge. For what is it but an ap- peal to the opinion of the multitude, of whose ap- plause the philosopher is ashamed, while the popular charlatan glories and confides in it ? I should think that Hume might fairly have laid as much claim to common sense as Beattie, and in addition to a critical reason (such as the latter did not possess), which keeps common sense in check and prevents it from speculating, or, if speculations are under discussion, restrains the desire to decide because it cannot satisfy itself concerning its own arguments. By this means alone can common sense remain sound. Chisels and hammers may suffice to work a piece of wood, but for INTRODUCTION. 7 Steel-engraving we require an engraver's needle. Thus common sense and speculative understanding are each serviceable in their own way, the former in judg- ments which apply immediately to experience, the latter when we judge universally from mere concepts, as in metaphysics, where sound common sense, so called in spite of the inapplicability of the word, has no right to judge at all. I openly confess, the suggestion of David Hume was the very thing, which many years ago first inter- rupted my dogmatic slumber, and gave my investiga- tions in the field of speculative philosophy quite a new direction. I was far from following him in the conclusions at which he arrived by regarding, not the whole of his problem, but a part, which by itself can give us no information. If we start from a well- founded, but undeveloped, thought, which another has bequeathed to us, we may well hope by continued reflection to advance farther than the acute man, to whom we owe the first spark of light. I therefore first tried whether Hume'^s objection could not be put into a general form, and soon found that the concept of the connexion of cause and effect was by no means the only idea by which the under- standing thinks the connexion of things a priori, but rather that metaphysics consists altogether of such connexions. I sought to ascertain their number, and when I had satisfactorily succeeded in this by starting from a single principle, I proceeded to the deduction of these concepts, which I was now certain were not deduced from experience, as Hume had apprehended, but sprang from the pure understanding. This de- duction (which seemed impossible to my acute prede- cessor, which had never even occurred to any one 8 KANT'S PROLEGOMENA. else, though no one had hesitated to use the concepts without investigating the basis of their objective val- idity) was the most difficult task ever undertaken in the service of metaphysics ; and the worst was that meta- physics, such as it then existed, could not assist me in the least, because this deduction alone can render metaphysics possible. But as soon as I had succeeded in solving Hume's problem not merely in a particular case, but with respect to the whole faculty of pure reason, I could proceed safely, though slowly, to de- termine the whole sphere of pure reason completely and from general principles, in its circumference as well as in its contents. This was required for meta- physics in order to construct its system according to a reliable method. But I fear that the execution of Hume's problem in its widest extent (viz., my Critique of the Pure Rea- son) will fare as the problem itself fared, when first proposed. It will be misjudged because it is mis- understood, and misunderstood because men choose to skim through the book, and not to think through it — a disagreeable task, because the work is dry, ob- scure, opposed to all ordinary notions, and moreover long-winded. I confess, however, I did not expect to hear from philosophers complaints of want of popu- larity, entertainment, and facility, when the existence of a highly prized and indispensable cognition is at stake, which cannot be established otherwise than by the strictest rules of methodic precision. Popularity may follow, but is inadmissible at the beginning. Yet as regards a certain obscurity, arising partly from this diffuseness of the plan, owing to which the principal points of the investigation are easily lost sight of, the INTRODUCTION. 9 complaint is just, and I intend to remove it by the present Prolegomena. The first-mentioned work, which discusses the pure faculty of reason in its whole compass and bounds, will remain the foundation, to which the Prolegomena, as a preliminary exercise, refer ; for our critique must first be established as a complete and perfected sci- ence, before we can think of letting Metaphysics ap- pear on the scene, or even have the most distant hope of attaining it. We have been long accustomed to seeing anti- quated knowledge produced as new by taking it out of its former context, and reducing it to system in a new suit of any fancy pattern under new titles. Most readers will set out by expecting nothing else from the Critique; but these Prolegomena may persuade him that it is a perfectly new science, of which no one has ever even thought, the very idea of which was unknown, and for which nothing hitherto accom- plished can be of the smallest use, except it be the suggestion of Hume's doubts. Yet even he did not suspect such a formal science, but ran his ship ashore, for safety's sake, landing on scepticism, there to let it lie and rot ; whereas my object is rather to give it a pilot, who, by means of safe astronomical principles drawn from a knowledge of the globe, and provided with a complete chart and compass, may steer the ship safely, whither he. listeth. If in a new science, which is wholly isolated and unique in its kind, we started with the prejudice that we can judge of things by means of our previously acquired knowledge, which is precisely what has first to be called in question, we should only fancy we saw everywhere what we had already known, the expres- lo rant's prolegomena. sions, having a similar sound, only that all would ap- pear utterly metamorphosed, senseless and unintelli- gible, because we should have as a foundation our own notions, made by long habit a second nature, in- stead of the author's. But the longwindedness of the work, so far as it depends on the subject, and not the exposition, its consequent unavoidable dryness and its scholastic precision are qualities which can only benefit the science, though they may discredit the book. Few writers are gifted with the subtilty, and at the same time with the grace, of David Hume, or with the depth, as well as the elegance, of Moses Mendels- sohn. Yet I flatter myself I might have made my own exposition popular, had my object been merely to sketch out a plan and leave its completion to others, instead of having my heart in the welfare of the sci- ence, to which I had devoted myself so long ; in truth, it required no little constancy, and even self-denial, to postpone the sweets of an immediate success to the prospect of a slower, but more lasting, reputation. Making plans is often the occupation of an opu- lent and boastful mind, which thus obtains the repu- tation of a creative genius, by demanding what it cannot itself supply; by censuring, what it cannot improve ; and by proposing, what it knows not where to find. And yet something more should belong to a sound plan of a general critique of pure reason than mere conjectures, if this plan is to be other than the usual declamations of pious aspirations. But pure reason is a sphere so separate and self-contained, that we cannot touch a part without affecting all the rest. We can therefore do nothing without first determin- ing the position of each part, and its relation to the INTRODUCTION. 1 1 restj for, as our judgment cannot be corrected by anything without, the validity and use of every part depends upon the relation in which it stands to all the rest within the domain of reason. So in the structure of an organized body, the end of each member can only be deduced from the full conception of the whole. It may, then, be said of such a critique that it is never trustworthy except it be perfectly complete, down to the smallest elements of pure reason. In the sphere of this faculty you can determine either everything or nothing. But although a mere sketch, preceding the Critique of Pure Reason, would be unintelligible, unreliable, and useless, it is all the more useful as a sequel. For so we are able to grasp the whole, to examine in de- tail the chief points of importance in the science, and to improve in many respects our exposition, as com- pared with the first execution of the work. After the completion of the work I offer here such a plan which is sketched out after an analytical method, while the work itself had to be executed in the synthetical style, in order that the science may present all its articulations, as the structure of a pe- culiar cognitive faculty, in their natural combination. But should any reader find this plan, which I publish as the Prolegomena to any future Metaphysics, still obscure, let him consider that not every one is bound to study Metaphysics, that many minds will succeed very well, in the exact and even in deep sciences, more closely allied to practical experience,^ while they IThe term Anschauung here used means sense-perception. It is that which is given to the senses and apprehended immediately, as an object is seen by merely looking at it. The translation intuition^ though etymolog- ically correct, is misleading. In the present passage the term is not used in its technical significance but means "practical experience." — Ed, 12 rant's prolegomena. cannot succeed in investigations dealing exclusively with abstract concepts. In such cases men should apply their talents to other subjects. But he who undertakes to judge, or still more, to construct, a sys- tem of Metaphysics, must satisfy the demands here made, either by adopting my solution, or by thor- oughly refuting it, and substituting another. To evade it is impossible. In conclusion, let it be remembered that this much-abused obscurity (frequently serving as a mere pretext under which people hide their own indolence or dullness) has its uses, since' all who in other sci- ences observe a judicious silence, speak authorita- tively in metaphysics and make bold decisions, be- cause their ignorance is not here contrasted with the knowledge of others. Yet it does contrast with sound critical principles, which we may therefore commend in the words of Virgil : "Ignavum, fucos, pecus a praesepibas arcent." 'Bees are defending their hives against drones, those indolent creatures." PROLEGOMENA. PREAMBLE ON THE PECULIARITIES OF ALL META- PHYSICAL COGNITION. §1. Of the Sources of Metaphysics. IF it becomes desirable to formulate any cognition as science, it will be necessary first to determine accurately those peculiar features which no other sci- ence has in common with it, constituting its charac- teristics ; otherwise the boundaries of all sciences become confused, and none of them can be treated thoroughly according to its nature. The characteristics of a science may consist of a simple difference of object, or of the sources of cogni- tion, or of the kind of cognition, or perhaps of all three conjointly. On this, therefore, depends the idea of a possible science and its territory. First, as concerns the sources of metaphysical cognition, its very concept implies that they cannot be empirical. Its principles (including not only its maxims but its basic notions) must never be derived from experience. It must not be physical but meta- physical knowledge, viz., knowledge lying beyond experience. It can therefore have for its basis neither external experience, which is the source of physics proper, nor internal, which is the basis of empirical 14 rant's prolegomena. psychology. It is therefore a priori ]inowledge, com- ing from pure Understanding and pure Reason. But so far Metaphysics would not be distinguish-, able from pure Mathematics; it must therefore be called pure philosophical cognition; and for the meaning of this term I refer to the Critique of the Pure Reason (II. "Method of Transcendentalism," Chap. I., Sec. i), where the distinction between these two employments of the reason is suiBciently ex- plained. So far concerning the sources of metaphysi- cal cognition. § 2. Concerning the Kind of Cognition which can alone be called Metaphysical. a. Of the Distinction between Analytical and Syn- thetical Judgments in general. — The peculiarity of its sources demands that metaphysical cognition must consist of nothing but a priori judgments. But what- ever be their origin, or their logical form, there is a distinction in judgments, as to their content, accord- ing to which they are either merely explicative, add- ing nothing to the content of the cognition, or expan- sive, increasing the given cognition : the former may be called analytical, the latter synthetical, judgments. Analytical judgments express nothing in the predi- cate but what has been already actually thought in the concept of the subject, though not so distinctly or with the same (full) consciousness. When I say : All bodies are extended, I have not amplified in the least my concept of body, but have only analysed it, as ex- tension was really thought to belong to that concept before the judgment was made, though it was not ex- pressed ; this judgment is therefore analytical. On the contrary, this judgment, All bodies have weight. METAPHYSICAL COGNITION. I5 contains in its predicate something not actually thought in the general concept of the body ; it ampli- fies my knowledge by adding something to my con- cept, and must therefore be called synthetical. b. The Common Frinciple of all Analytical Judgments is the Law of Contradiction. — All analytical judgments depend wholly on the law of Contradiction, and are in their nature a priori cognitions, whether the con- cepts that supply them with matter be empirical or not. For the predicate of an affirmative analytical judgment is already contained in the concept of the subject, of which it cannot be denied without contra- diction. In the same way its opposite is necessarily denied of the subject in an analytical, but negative, judgment, by the same law of contradiction. Such is the nature of the judgments : all bodies are extended, and no bodies are unextended (i. e., simple). For this very reason all analytical judgments are a priori even when the concepts are empirical, as, for example. Gold is a yellow metal ; for to know this I require no experience beyond my concept of gold as a yellow metal : it is, in fact, the very concept, and I need only analyse it, without looking beyond it else- where. c. Synthetical Judgments require a different Principle from the Law of Contradiction. — There are synthetical a posteriori judgments of empirical origin; but there are also others which are proved to be certain a priori, and which spring from pure Understanding and Rea- son. Yet they both agree in this, that they cannot possibly spring from the principle of analysis, viz., the law of contradiction, alone ; they require a quite different principle, though, from whatever they may be deduced, they must be subject to the law of con- 1 6 KANT'S PROLEGOMENA. tradiction, which must never be violated, even though everything cannot be deduced from, it. I shall first classify synthetical judgments. 1. Empirical Judgments a.xe&lvis.yssyri.ihetlca\. For it would be absurd to base an analytical judgment on experience, as our concept suffices for the purpose without requiring any testimony from experience. That body is extended, is a judgment established a priori, and not an empirical judgment. For before appealing to experience, we already have all the con- ditions of the judgment in the concept, from which we have but to elicit the predicate according to the law of contradiction, and thereby to become conscious of the necessity of the judgment, which experience could not even teach us. 2. Mathematical Judgments are all synthetical. This fact seems hitherto to have altogether escaped the observation of those who have analysed human rea- son ; it even seems directly opposed to all their con- jectures, though incontestably certain, and most im- portant in its consequences. For as it was found that the conclusions of mathematicians all proceed accord- ing to the law of contradiction (as is demanded by all apodeictic certainty), men persuaded themselves that the fundamental principles were known from the same law. This was a great mistake, for a synthetical prop- osition can indeed be comprehended according to the law of contradiction, but only by presupposing another synthetical proposition from which it follows, but never in itself. First of all, we must observe that all proper math- ematical judgments are a priori, and not empirical, because they carry with them necessity, which cannot be obtained from experience. But if this be not con- METAPHYSICAL COGNITION. 17 ceded to me, very good ; I shall confine my assertion to pure Mathematics, the very notion of which implies that it contains pure a priori and not empirical cogni- tions. It might at first be thought that the proposition 7 + 5 = 12 is a mere analytical judgment, following from the concept of the sum of seven and five, accord- ing to the law of contradiction. But on closer exam- ination it appears that the concept of the sum of 7-I-5 contains merely their union in a single number, with- out its being at all thought what the particular num- ber is that unites them. The concept of twelve is by no means thought by merely thinking of the combina- tion of seven and five ; and analyse this possible sum as we may, we shall not discover twelve in the con- cept. We must go beyond these concepts, by calling to our aid some concrete image (Anschauung"), i.e., either our five fingers, or five points (as Segner has it in his Arithmetic), and we must add successively the units of the five, given in some concrete image (^Anschau- ung), to the concept of seven. Hence our concept is really amplified by the proposition 7 -}- 5 = 12, and we add to the first a second, not thought in it. Arith- metical judgments are therefore synthetical, and the more plainly according as we take larger numbers; for in such cases it is clear that, however closely we analyse our concepts without calling visual images {Anschauun^ to our aid, we can never find the sum by such mere dissection. All principles of geometry are no less analytical. That a straight line is the shortest path between two points, is a synthetical proposition. For my concept of straight contains nothing of quantity, but only a quality. The attribute of shortness is therefore alto- i8 kant's prolegomena. gether additional, and cannot be obtained by any analysis of the concept. Here, too, visualisation {Anschauung') must come to aid us. It alone makes the synthesis possible. Some other principles, assumed by geometers, are indeed actually analytical, and depend on the law of contradiction ; but they only serve, as identical prop- ositions, as a method of concatenation, and not as principles, e. g., a = a, the whole is equal to itself, or a-\-d>a, the whole is greater than its part. And yet even these, though they are recognised as valid from mere concepts, are only admitted in mathematics, be- cause they can be represented in some visual form {Anschauung'). What usually makes us believe that the predicate of such apodeictic^ judgments is already contained in our concept, and that the judgment is therefore analytical, is the duplicity of the expression, requesting us to think a certain predicate as of neces- sity implied in the thought of a given concept, which necessity attaches to the concept. But the question is not what we are requested to join in thought to the given concept, but what we actually, think together with and in it, though obscurely ; and so it appears that the predicate belongs to these concepts necessa- rily indeed, yet not directly but indirectly by an added visualisation {AnscJiauung'). § 3. /4 Remark on the General Division of Judgments into Analytical and Synthetical. This division is indispensable, as concerns the Critique of human understanding, and therefore de-- IThe term apodetctic is borrowed by Kanl from Aristotle who uses it in the sense of "certain beyond dispute." The word is derived from airoSei/ci/u/iii [=Ishaw) and is contrasted to dialectic propositions, i. o,, such statements as admit of controversy.— £ and unconditional necessity must be sought only in the unity of a cause different from the world of sense. But as the causality of this cause, in its turn, were it merely nature, could never render the existence of the contingent (as its consequent) comprehensible, reason frees itself by means of the Theological Idea from fatalism, (both as a blind nat- ural necessity in the coherence of nature itself, with- out a first principle, and as a blind causality of this HOW IS METAPHYSICS IN GENERAL POSSIBLE? 1 37 principle itself), and leads to the concept of a cause possessing freedom, or of a Supreme Intelligence. Thus the transcendental Ideas serve, if not to instruct us positively, at least to destroy the rash assertions of Materialism, of Naturalism, and of Fatalism, and thus to afford scope for the moral Ideas beyond the field of speculation. These considerations, I should think, explain in some measure the natural predisposition of which I spoke. The practical value, which a merely speculative science may have, lies without the bounds of this sci- ence, and can therefore be considered as a scholion merely, and like all scholia does not form part of the science itself. This application however surely lies within the bounds of philosophy, especially of philos- ophy drawn from the pure sources of reason, where its speculative use in metaphysics must necessarily be at unity with its practical use in morals. Hence the unavoidable dialectics of pure reason, considered in metaphysics, as a natural tendency, deserves to be explained not as an illusion merely, which is to be re- moved, but also, if possible, as a natural provision as regards its end, though this duty, a work of super- erogation, cannot justly be assigned to metaphysics proper. The solutions of these questions which are treated in the chapter on the Regulative Use of the Ideas of Pure Reason^ should be considered a second scholion which however has a greater affinity with the subject of metaphysics. For there certain rational principles are expounded which determine a priori the order of nature or rather of the understanding, which seeks nature's laws through experience. They seem to be I Critique of Pure Reason, II., chap. III,, section 7, 138 rant's prolegomena. constitutive and legislative with regard to experience, though they spring from pure reason, which cannot be considered, like the understanding, as a principle of possible experience. Now whether or not this har- mony rests upon the fact, that just as nature does not inhere in appearances or in their source (the sensibil- ity) itself, but only in so far as the latter is in relation to the understanding, as also a systematic unity in applying the understanding to bring about an entirety of all possible experience can only belong to the un- derstanding when in relation to reason ; and whether or not experience is in this way mediately subordinate to the legislation of reason: may be discussed by those who desire to trace the nature of reason even beyond its use in metaphysics, into the general prin- ciples of a history of nature ; I have represented this task as important, but not attempted its solution, in the book itself. ^ And thus I conclude the analytical solution of the main question which I had proposed : How is meta- physics in general possible? by ascending from the data of its actual use in its consequences, to the grounds of its possibility. ^Throughout in the Criiiqite 1 never lost sight of the plan not to neglect anything, were it ever so recondite, that could render the inquiry into the nature of pure reason complete. Everybody may afterwards carry his re- searches as far as he pleases, when he has been merely shown what yet re- mains to be done. It is this a duty which must reasonably be expected of him who has made it his business to survey the whole field, in order to con- sign it to others for future cultivation and allotment. And to this branch both the scholia belong, which will hardly recommend themselves by their dryness to amateurs, and hence are added here for connoisseurs only. SCHOUA. SOLUTION OF THE GENERAL QUESTION OF THE PROLEGOMENA, "HOW IS METAPHYSICS POSSIBLE AS A SCIENCE?" METAPHYSICS, as a natural disposition of rea- son, is actual, but if considered by itself alone (as the analytical solution of the third principal ques- tion showed), dialectical and illusory. If we think of taking principles from it, and in using them follow the natural, but on that account not less false, illu- sion, we can never produce science, but only a vain dialectical art, in which one school may outdo an- other, but none can ever acquire a just and lasting approbation. In order that as a science metaphysics may be en- titled to claim not mere fallacious plausibility, but in- sight and conviction, a Critique of Reason must itself exhibit the whole stock of a priori concepts, their di- vision according to their various sources (Sensibility, Understanding, and Reason), together with a com- plete table of them, the analysis of all these concepts, with all their consequences, especially by means of the deduction of these concepts, the possibility of synthetical cognition a priori, the principles of its ap- plication and finally its bounds, all in a complete sys- tem. Critique, therefore, and critique alone, contains in itself the whole well-proved and well-tested plan. 140 rant's prolegomena. and even all the means required to accomplish meta- physics, as a science ; by other ways and means it is impossible. The question here therefore is not so much how this performance is possible, as how to set it going, and induce men of clear heads to quit their hitherto perverted and fruitless cultivation for one that will not deceive, and how such a union for the common end may best be directed. This much is certain, that whoever has once tasted Critique will be ever after disgusted with all dogmati- cal twaddle which he formerly put up with, because his reason must have something, and could find noth- ing better for its support. Critique stands in the same relation to the com- mon metaphysics of the schools, as chemistry does to alchemy, or as astronomy to the astrology of the for- tune-teller. I pledge myself that nobody who has read through and through, and grasped the principles of, the Critique even in these Prolegomena only, will ever return to that old and sophistical pseudo-science; but will rather with- a certain delight look forward to metaphysics which is now indeed in his power, re- quiring no more preparatory discoveries, and now at last affording permanent satisfaction to reason. For here is an advantage upon which, of all possible sci- ences, metaphysics alone can with certainty reckon : that it can be brought to such completion and fixity as' to be incapable of further change, or of any aug- mentation by new discoveries; because here reason has the sources of its knowledge in itself, not in ob- jects and their observation (Anschauung), by which latter its stock of knowledge cannot be further in- creased. When therefore it has exhibited the funda- mental laws of its faculty completely and so definitely HOW IS METAPHYSICS POSSIBLE AS A SCIENCE? I4I as to avoid all misunderstanding, there remains noth- ing for pure reason to cognise a priori, nay, there is even no ground to raise further questions. The sure prospect of knowledge so definite and so compact has a peculiar charm, even though we should set aside all its advantages, of which I shall hereafter speak. All false art, all vain wisdom, lasts its time, but finally destroys itself, and its highest culture is also the epoch of its decay. That this time is come ior metaphysics appears from the state into which it has fallen among all learned nations, despite of all the zeal with which other sciences of every kind are pros- ecuted. The old arrangement of our university studies still preserves its shadow ; now and then an Academy of Science tempts men by offering prizes to write essays on it, but it is no longer numbered among thorough sciences ; and let any one judge for himself how a man of genius, if he were called a great meta- physician, would receive the compliment, which may be well-meant, but is scarce envied by anybody. Yet, though the period of the downfall of all dog- matical metaphysics has undoubtedly arrived, we are yet far from being able to say that the period of its regeneration is come by means of a thorough and complete Critique of Reason. All transitions from a tendency to its contrary pass through the stage of in- difference, and this moment is the most dangerous for an author, but, in my opinion, the most favorable for the science. For, when party spirit has died out by a total dissolution of former connexions, minds are in the "best state to listen to several proposals for an or- ganisation according to a new plan. When I say, that I hope these Prolegomena will excite investigation in the field of critique and afford 142 rant's prolegomena. a new and promising object to sustain the general spirit of philosophy, which seems on its speculative side to want sustenance, I can imagine beforehand, that every one, whom the thorny paths of my Critique have tired and put out of humor, will ask me, upon what I found this hope. My answer is, upon the irre- sistible law of necessity. That the human mind will ever give up metaphys- ical researches is as little to be expected as that we should prefer to give up breathing altogether, to avoid inhaling impure air. There will therefore always be metaphysics in the world ; nay, every one, especially every man of reflexion, will have it, and for want of a recognised standard, will shape it for himself after his own pattern. What has hitherto been called meta- physics, cannot satisfy any critical mind, but to forego it entirely is impossible.; therefore a Critique of Pure Reason itself s.iust now be attempted or, if one exists, investigated, and brought to the full test, because there is no other means of supplying this pressing want, which is something more than mere thirst for knowledge. Ever since I have come to know critique, when- ever I finish reading a book of metaphysical contents, which, by the preciseness of its notions, by variety, order, and an easy style, was not only entertaining but also helpful, I cannot help asking, " Has this author indeed advanced metaphysics a single step?" The learned men, whose works have been useful to me in other respects and always contributed to the culture of my mental powers, will, I hope, forgive me for saying, that I have never been able to find either their essays or my own less important ones (though self-love may recommend them to me) to have ad- HOW IS METAPHYSICS POSSIBLE AS A SCIENCE? I43 vanced the science of metaphysics in the least, and why? Here is the very obvious reason : metaphysics did not then exist as a science, nor can it be gathered piecemeal, but its germ must be fully preformed in the Critique. But in order to prevent all misconcep- tion, we must remember what has been already said, that by the analytical treatment of our concepts the understanding gains indeed a great deal, but the science (of metaphysics) is thereby not in the least advanced, because these dissections of concepts are nothing but the materials from which the intention is to carpenter our science. Let the concepts of sub- stance and of accident be ever so well dissected and determined, all this is very well as a preparation for some future use. But if we cannot prove, that in all which exists the substance endures, and only the ac- cidents vary, our science is not the least advanced by all our analyses. Metaphysics has hitherto never been able to prove a priori either this proposition, or that of sufficient reason, still less any more complex theorem, such as belongs to psychology or cosmology, or indeed any synthetical proposition. By all its analysing therefore nothing is affected, nothing obtained or forwarded, and the science, after all this bustle and noise, still remains as it was in the days of Aristotle, though far better preparations were made for it than of old, if the clue to synthetical cognitions had only been discovered. if any one thinks himself offended, he is at liberty to refute my charge by producing a single synthetical proposition belonging to metaphysics, which he would prove dogmatically a priori, for until he has actually 144 KANT'S PROLEGOMENA. performed this feat, I shall not grant that he has truly advanced the science ; even should this proposition be sufSciently confirmed by common experience. No de- mand can be more moderate or more equitable, and in the (inevitably certain) event of its non-perform- ance, no assertion more just, than that hitherto meta- physics has never existed as a science. But there are two things which, in case the chal- lenge be accepted, I must deprecate : first, trifling about probability and conjecture, which are suited as little to metaphysics, as to geometry ; and secondly, a decision by means of the magic wand of common sense, which does not convince every one, but which accommodates itself to personal peculiarities. For as to the former, nothing can be more absurd, than in metaphysics, a philosophy from pure reason to think of grounding our judgments upon probability and conjecture. Everything that is to be cognised a priori, is thereby announced as apodeictically certain, and must therefore be proved in this way. We might as well think of grounding geometry or arithmetic upon "conjectures. As to the doctrine of chances in the latter, it does not contain probable, but perfectly certain, judgments concerning the degree of the prob- ability of certain cases, under given uniform condi- tions, which, in the sum of all possible cases, infallibly happen according to the rule, though it is not suffi- ciently determined in respect to every single chance. Conjectures (by means of induction and of analogy) can be suffered in an empirical science of nature only, yet even there the possibility at least of what we as- sume must be quite certain. The appeal to common sense is even more absurd, when concept and principles are announced as valid. HOW IS METAPHYSICS POSSIBLE AS A SCIENCE? 145 not in so far as they hold with regard to experience, but even beyond the conditions of experience. For what is common sense? It is normal good sense, so far it judges right. But what is normal good sense? It is the faculty of the knowledge and use of rules in concreto, as distinguished from the speculative under- standing, which is a faculty of knowing rules in ab- stracio. Common sense can hardly understand the rule, " that every event is determined by means of its cause," and can never comprehend it thus generally. It therefore demands an example from experience, and when it hears that this rule means nothing but what it always thought when a pane was broken or a kitchen-utensil missing, it then understands the prin- ciple and grants it. Common sense therefore is only of use so far as it can see its rules (though they actu- ally are a priori^ confirmed by experience; conse- quently to comprehend them a priori, or independently of experience, belongs to the speculative understand- ing, and lies quite beyond the horizon of common sense. But the province of metaphysics is entirely confined to the latter kind of knowledge, and it is cer- tainly a bad index of common sense to appeal to it as a witness, for it cannot here form any opinion what- ever, and men look down upon it with contempt until they are in difficulties, and can find in their specula- tion neither in nor out. It is a common subterfuge of those false friends of common sense (who occasionally prize it highly, but usually despise it) to say, that there must surely be at ail events some propositions which are immediately certain, and of which there is no occasion to give any proof, or even any account at all, because we other- wise could never stop inquiring into the grounds of 146 KANT'S PROLEGOMENA. our judgments. But if we except the principle of contradiction, which is not sufficient to show the truth of synthetical judgments, they can never adduce, in proof of this privilege, anything else indubitable, which they can immediately ascribe to common sense, except mathematical propositions, such as twice two make four, between two points there is but one straight line, etc. But these judgments are radically different from those of metaphysics. For in mathe- matics I myself can by thinking construct whatever I represent to myself as possible by a concept : I add to the first two the other two, one by one, and myself make the number four, or I draw in thought from one point to another all manner of lines, equal as well as unequal ; yet I can draw one only, which is like itself in all its parts. But I cannot, by all my power of thinking, extract from the Concept of a thing the con- cept of something else, whose existence is necessarily connected with the former, but I must call in experi- ence. And though my understanding furnishes me a priori (yet only in reference to possible experience) with the concept of such a connexion (i. e., causation), I cannot exhibit it, like the concepts of mathematics, by (^Anschauung) visualising them, a priori, and so show its possibility a priori. This concept, together with the principles of its application, always requires, if it shall hold a priori — as is requisite in metaphysics -^a justification and deduction of its possibility, be- cause we cannot otherwise know how far it holds good, and whether it can be used in experience only or beyond it also. Therefore in metaphysics, as a speculative science of pure reason, we can never appeal to common sense, but may do so only when we are forced to surrender HOW IS METAPHYSICS POSSIBLE AS A SCIENCE? I47 it, and to renounce all purely speculative cognition, which must always be knowledge, and consequently when we forego metaphysics itself and its instruction, for the sake of adopting a rational faith which alone may be possible for us, and sufficient to our wants, perhaps even more salutary than knowledge itself. For in this case the attitude of the question is quite altered. Metaphysics must be science, not only as a whole, but in all its parts, otherwise it is nothing; because, as a speculation of pure reason, it finds a hold only on general opinions. Beyond its field, how- ever, probability and common sense may be used with advantage and justly, but on quite special principles, of which the importance always depends on the refer- ence to practical life. This is what I hold myself justified in requiring for the possibility of metaphysics as a science. APPENDIX. ON WHAT CAN BE DONE TO MAKE METAPHYSICS ACTUAL AS A SCIENCE. SINCE all the ways heretofore taken have failed to attain the goal, and since without a preceding critique of pure reason it is not likely ever to be at- tained, the present essay now before the public has a fair title to an accurate and careful investigation, ex- cept it be thought more advisable to give up all pre- tensions to metaphysics, to which, if men but would consistently adhere to their purpose, no objection can be made. If we take the course of things as it is, not as it ought to be, there are two sorts of judgments: (i) one a judgment which precedes investigation (in our case one in which the reader from his own metaphysics pronounces judgment on the Critique of Pure Reason which was intended to discuss the very possibility of metaphysics); (2) the other a judgment subsequent to investigation. In the latter the reader is enabled to waive for awhile the consequences of the critical researches that may be repugnant to his formerly adopted metaphysics, and first examines the grounds whence those consequences are derived. If what common metaphysics propounds were demonstrably certain, as for instance the theorems of geometry, the former way of judging would hold good. For' if the APPENDIX. 149 consequences of certain principles are repugnant to established truths, these principles are false and with- out further inquiry to be repudiated. But if meta- physics does not possess a stock of indisputably cer- tain (synthetical) propositions, and should it even be the case that there are a number of them, which, though among the most specious, are by their conse- quences in mutual collision, and if no sure criterion of the truth of peculiarly metaphysical (synthetical) propositions is to be met with in it, then the former way of judging is not admissible, but the investigation of the principles of the critique must precede all judg- ments as to its value. ON A SPECIMEN OF A JUDGMENT OF THE CRITIQUE PRIOR TO ITS EXAMINATION. This judgment is to be found in the Gottingischen ge- lehrten Anzeigen, in the supplement to the third divi- sion, of January 19, 1782, pages 40 et seq. When an author who is familiar with the subject of his work and endeavors to present his independent reflexions in its elaboration, falls into the hands of a reviewer who, in his turn, is keen enough to discern the points on which the worth or worthlessness of the book rests, who does not cling to words, but goes to the heart of the subject, sifting and testing more than the mere principles which the author takes as his point of departure, the severity of the judgment may indeed displease the latter, but the public does not care, as it gains thereby ; and the author himself may be contented, as an opportunity of correcting or ex- plaining his positions is afforded to him at an early date by the examination of a competent judge, in such a manner, that if he believes himself fundamen- 150 KANT'S PROLEGOMENA. tally right, he can remove in time any stone of offence that might hurt the success of his work. I find myself, with my reviewer, in quite another position. He seems not to see at all the real matter of the investigation with which (successfully or un- successfully) I have been occupied. It is either im- patience at thinking out a lengthy work, or vexation at a threatened reform of a science in which he be- lieved he had brought everything to perfection long ago, or, what I am unwilling to imagine, real narrow- mindedness, that prevents him from ever carrying his thoughts beyond his school-metaphysics. In short, he passes impatiently in review a long series of prop- ositions, by which, without knowing their premises, we can think nothing, intersperses here and there his censure, the reason of which the reader understands just as little as the propositions against which it is di- rected ; and hence [his report] can neither serve the public nor damage me, in the judgment of experts. I should, for these reasons, have passed over this judg- ment altogether, were it not that it may afford me oc- casion for some explanations which may in some cases savfe the readers of these Prolegomena from a miscon- ception. In order to take a position from which my reviewer could most easily set the whole work in a most un- favorable light,' without venturing to trouble hirhself with any special investigation, he begins and ends by saying : "This work is a system of transcendent (or, as he translates it, of higher) Idealism. "^ IBy no means ^^higher" High towers, and metaphysically-great men resembling them, round both of which there is commonly much wind, are not for me. My place is the fruitful bathos^ the bottom-land, of experience ; and the word transcendental, the meaning of which is so often explained by me, APPENDIX. 151 A glance at this line soon showed me the sort of criticism that I had to expect, much as though the re- viewer were one who had never seen or heard of geom- etry, having found a Euclid, and coming upon various figures in turning over its leaves, were to say, on being asked his opinion of it : "The work is a text-book of drawing ; the author introduces a peculiar terminol- ogy, in order to give dark, incomprehensible direc- tions, which in the end teach nothing more than what every one can effect by a fair natural accuracy of eye, etc." Let us see, in the meantime, what sort of an ideal- ism it is that goes through my whole work, although it does not by a long way constitute the soul of the system. The dictum of all genuine idealists from the Eleatic school to Bishop Berkeley, is contained in this for- mula: "All cognition through the senses and experi- ence is nothing but sheer illusion, and only, in the ideas of the pure understanding and reason there is truth." The principle that throughout dominates and de- termines my Idealism, is on the contrary: "All cog- nition of things merely from pure understanding or pure reason is nothing but sheer illusion, and only in experience is there truth. " But this is directly contrary to idealism proper. but not once grasped by my reviewer (so carelessly bas he regarded every- thing), does not signify something passing beyond all experience, but some- thing that indeed precedes it a priori, but that is intended simply to make cognition of experience possible. If these conceptions overstep experience, their employment is termed transcendent, a word which must be distinguished from transcendental, the latter being limited to the immanent use, that is, to experience. All misunderstandings of this kind have been sufficiently guarded against in the work itself, but my reviewer found his advantage in misunderstanding me. 152 rant's prolegomena. How came I then to use this expression for quite an opposite purpose, and how came my reviewer to see it everywhere? • The solution of this difficulty rests on something that could have been very easily understood from the general bearing of the work, if the reader had only desired to do so. Space and time, together with all that they contain, are not things nor qualities in them- selves, but belong merely to the appearances of the latter : up to this point I am one in confession with the above idealists. But these, and amongst them more particularly Berkeley, regarded space as a mere empirical presentation that, like the phenomenon it contains, is only known to us by means of experience or perception, together with its determinations. I, on the contrary, prove in the first place, that space (and also time, which Berkeley did not consider) and all its determinations a priori, can be cognised by us, because, no less than time, it inheres in our sensibility as a pure form before all perception or experience and makes all intuition of the same, and therefore all its phenomena, possible. It follows from this, that as truth rests on universal and necessary laws as its cri- teria, experience, according to Berkeley, can have no criteria of truth, because its phenomena (according to him) have nothing a priori at their foundation ; whence it follows, that they are nothing but sheer illusion ; whereas with us, space and time (in conjunction with the pure conceptions of the understanding) prescribe their law to all possible experience a priori, and at the same time afford the certain criterion for distin- guishing truth from illusion therein.^ 1 Idealism proper always has a mystical tendency, and can have no other, but mine is solely designed for the purpose of comprehending the possibility APPENDIX. 153 My so-called (properly critical) Idealism is of quite a special character, in that it subverts the ordinary idealism, and that through it all cognition a priori, even that of geometry, first receives objective reality, which, without my demonstrated ideality of space and time, could not be maintained by the most zealous realists. This being the state of the case, I could have wished, in order to avoid all misunderstanding, to have named this conception of mine otherwise, but to alter it altogether was impossible. It may be per- mitted me however, in future, as has been above inti- mated, to term it the formal, or better still, the crit- ical Idealism, to distinguish it from the dogmatic Idealism of Berkeley, and from the sceptical Idealism of Descartes. Beyond this, I find nothing further remarkable in the judgment of my book. The reviewer criticises here and there, makes sweeping criticisms, a mode prudently chosen, since it does not betray one's own knowledge or ignorance ; a single thorough criticism in detail, had it touched the main question, as is only fair, would have exposed, it may be my error, or it may be my reviewer's measure of insight into this spe- cies of research. It was, moreover, not a badly con- ceived plan, in order at once to take from readers (who are accustomed to form their conceptions of books from newspaper reports) the desire to read the book itself, to pour out in one breath a number of pas- sages in succession, torn from their connexion, and ot Qiir cognition a friori as to objects of experience, which is a problem never hitherto solved or even suggested. In this way all mystical idealism falls to the ground, for (as may be seen already in Plato] it inferred from our cognitions a priori (even from those of geometry) another intuition different from that of the senses (namely, an intellectual intuition), because it never occurred to any one that the senses themselves might intuite a. priori. 154 kant's prolegomena. their grounds of proof and explanations, and which must necessarily sound senseless, especially consider- ing how antipathetic they are to all school-metaphys- ics ; to exhaust the reader's patience ad nauseam, and then, after having made me acquainted with the sen- sible proposition that persistent illusion is truth, to conclude with the crude paternal moralisation : to what end, then, the quarrel with accepted language, to what end, and whence, the idealistic distinction? A judgment which seeks all that is characteristic of my book, first supposed to be metaphysically hetero- dox, in a mere innovation of the nomenclature, proves clearly that my would-be judge has understood noth- ing of the subject, and in addition, has not under- stood himself.'- My reviewer speaks like a man who is conscious of important and superior insight which he keeps hid- den ; for I am aware of nothing recent with respect to metaphysics that could justify his tone. But he should not withhold his discoveries from the world, for there are doubtless many who, like myself, have not been able to find in all the fine things that have for long past been written in this department, anything that has advanced the science by so much as a finger- breadth; we find indeed the giving a new point to definitions, the supplying of lame proofs with new crutches, the adding to the crazy-quilt of metaphysics iThe reviewer often fights with his own shadow. When 1 oppose the truth of experience to dream, he never thinks that 1 am here speaking simply of the well-lcnown somnio objective sutnto of the Wolffian philosophy, which is merely formal, and with which the distinction between sleeping and waking is in no way concerned, and in a transcendental philosophy indeed can have no place. For the rest, he calls my deduction of the categories and table of the principles of the understanding, " common well-kiiown axioms of logic and ontology, expressed in an idealistic manner." The reader need only consult these Prolegojnena upon this point, to convince himself that a more miserable and historically incorrect, judgment, could hardly be made. APPENDIX. 155 fresh patches or changing its pattern ; but all this is not what the world requires. The world is tired of metaphysical assertions; it wants the possibility of the science, the sources from which certainty therein can be derived, and certain criteria by which it may distinguish the dialectical illusion of pure reason from truth. To this the critic seems to possess a key, other- wise he would never have spoken out in such a high tone. But I am inclined to suspect that no such require- ment of the science has ever entered his thoughts, for in that case he would have directed his judgment to this point, and even a mistaken attempt in such an important matter, would have won his respect. If that be the case, we are once more good friends. He may penetrate as deeply as he likes into metaphysics, without any one hindering him ; only as concerns that which lies outside metaphysics, its sources, which are to be found in reason, he cannot form a judgment. That my suspicion is not without foundation, is proved by the fact that he does not mention a word about the possibility of synthetic knowledge a priori, the special problem upon the solution of which the fate of meta- physics wholly rests, and upon which my Critique (as well as the present Prolegomena) entirely hinges. The Idealism he encountered, and which he hung upon, was only taken up in the doctrine as the sole means of solving the above problem (although it received its confirmation on other grounds), and hence he must have shown either that the above problem does not possess the importance I attribute to it (even in these Prolegomena), or that by my conception of appear- ances, it is either not solved at all, or can be better solved in another way ; but I do not find a word of 156 kant's prolegomena. this in the criticism. The reviewer, then, understands nothing of my work, and possibly also nothing of the spirit and essential nature of metaphysics itself ; and it is not, what I would rather assume, the hurry of a man incensed at the labor of plodding through so many obstacles, that threw an unfavorable shadow over the work lying before him, and made its funda- mental features unrecognisable. There is a good deal to be done before a learned journal, it matters not with what care its writers may be selected, can maintain its otherwise well-merited, reputation, in the field of metaphysics as elsewhere. Other sciences and branches of knowledge have their standard. Mathematics has it, in itself; history and theology, in profane or sacred books ; natural science and the art of medicine, in mathematics and experi- ence ; jurisprudence, in law books ; and even matters of taste in the examples of the ancients. But for the judgment of the thing called metaphysics, the standard has yet to be found. I have made an attempt to de- termine it, as well as its use. What is to be done, then, until it be found, when works of this kind have to be judged of? If they are of a dogmatic character, one may do what one likes ; no one will play the mas- ter over others here for long, before some one else appears to deal with him in the same manner. If, however, they are critical in their character, not in- deed with reference to other works, but to reason it- self, so that the standard of judgment cannot be as- sumed but has first of all to be sought for, then, though objection and blame may indeed be permitted, yet a certain degree of leniency is indispensable, since the need is common to us all^ and the lack of the neces- APPENDIX. 157 sary insight makes the high-handed attitude of judge unwarranted. In order, however, to connect my defence with the interest of the philosophical commonwealth, I pro- pose a test, which must be decisive as to the mode, whereby all metaphysical investigations may be di- rected to their common purpose. This is nothing more than what formerly mathematicians have done, in establishing the advantage of their methods by competition. I challenge my critic to demonstrate, as is only just, on a priori grounds, in his way, a single really metaphysical principle asserted by him. Being metaphysical it must be synthetic and cognised a priori hova. conceptions, but it may also be any one of the most indispensable principles, as for instance, the principle of the persistence of substance, or of the necessary determination of events in the world by their causes. If he cannot do this (silence however is confession), he must admit, that as metaphysics with- out apodeictic certainty of propositions of this kind is nothing at all, its possibility or impossibility must before all things be established in a critique of the pure reason. Thus he is bound either to confess that my principles in the Critique are correct, or he must prove their invalidity. But as I can already foresee, that, confidently as he has hitherto relied on the cer- tainty of his principles, when it comes to a strict test *he will not find a single one in the whole range of metaphysics he can bring forward, I will concede to him an advantageous condition, which can only be expected in such a competition, and will relieve him of the onus probandi by laying it on myself. He finds in these Prolegomena and in my Critique (chapter on the "Theses and Antitheses of the Four 158 kant's prolegomena. Antinomies ") eight propositions, of which two and two contradict one another, but each of which necessarily belongs to metaphysics, by which it must either be accepted or rejected (although there is not one that has not in this time been held by some philosopher). Now he has the liberty of selecting any one of these eight propositions at his pleasure, and accepting it without any proof, of which I shall make him a pres- ent, but only one (for waste of time will be just as little serviceable to him as to me), and then of attack- ing my proof of the opposite proposition. If I can save this one, and at the same time show, that ac- cording to principles which every dogmatic meta- physics must necessarily recognise, the opposite of the proposition adopted by him can be just as clearly proved, it is thereby established that metaphysics has an hereditary failing, not to be explained, much less set aside, until we ascend to its birth-place, pure rea- son itself, and thus my Critique must either be ac- cepted or a better one take its place ; it must at least be studied, which is the only thing I now require. If, on the other hand, I cannot save my demonstration, then a synthetic proposition a priori from dogmatic principles is to be reckoned to the score of my oppo- nent, then also I will deem my impeachment of ordi- nary metaphysicsas unjust, and pledge myself to recognise his stricture on my Critique as justified (although this would not be the consequence by a long way). To this end it would be necessary, it seems to me, that he should step out of his incognito. Otherwise I do not see how it could be avoided, that instead of dealing with one, I should be honored by several problems coming from anonymous and un- qualified opponents. APPENDIX. 159 PROPOSALS AS TO AN INVESTIGATION OF THE CRI- TIQUE UPON WHICH A JUDGMENT MAY FOLLOW. I feel obliged to the honored public even for the silence with which it for a long time favored my Cri- tique, for this proves at least a postponement of judg- ment, and some supposition that in a work, leaving all beaten tracks and striking out on a new path, in which one cannot at once perhaps so easily find one's way, something may perchance lie, from which an important but at present dead branch of human knowledge may derive new life and productiveness. Hence may have originated a solicitude for the as yet tender shoot, lest it be destroyed by a hasty judg- ment. A test of a judgment, delayed for the above reasons, is now before my eye in the Gothaischen ge- lehrten Zeitung, the thoroughness of which every reader will himself perceive, from the clear and un- perverted presentation of a fragment of one of the first principles of my work, without taking into con- sideration my own suspicious praise. And now I propose,, since an extensive structure cannot be judged of as a whole from a hurried glance, to test it piece by piece from its foundations, so thereby the present Prolegomena may fitly be used as a gene- ral outline with which the work itself may occasionally be compared. This notion, if it were founded on nothing more than my conceit of importance, such as vanity commonly attributes to one's own productions, would be immodest and would deserve to be repudi- ated with disgust. But now, the interests of specula- tive philosophy have arrived at the point of total ex- tinction, while human reason hangs upon them with i6o kant's prolegomena. inextinguishable affection, and only after having been ceaselessly deceived does it vainly attempt to change this into indifference. In our thinking age it is not to be supposed but that many deserving men would use any good oppor- tunity of working for the common interest of the more and more enlightened .reason, if there were only some hope of attaining the goal. Mathematics, natural science, laws, arts, even morality, etc., do not com- pletely fill the soul ; there is always a space left over, reserved for pure and speculative reason, the vacuity of which prompts us to seek in vagaries, buffooneries, and myticism for what seems to be employment and entertainment, but what actually is mere pastime ; in order to deaden the troublesome voice of reason, which in accordance with its nature requires some- thing that can satisfy it, and not merely subserve other ends or the interests of our inclinations. A con- sideration, therefore, which is concerned only with reason as it exists for it itself, has as I may reason- ably suppose a great fascination for every one who has attempted thus to extend his conceptions, and I may even say a greater than any other theoretical branch of knowledge, for which he would not willingly exchange it, because here all other cognitions, and even purposes, must meet and unite themselves in a whole. I offer, therefore, these Prolegomena as a sketch and text-book for this investigation, and not the work itself. Although I am even now perfectly satisfied with the latter as far as contents, order, and mode of presentation, and the care that I have expended in weighing and testing every sentence before writing it down, are concerned (for it has taken me years to APPENDIX. l6l satisfy myself fully, not only as regards the whole, but in some cases even as to the sources of one par- ticular proposition) ; yet I am not quite satisfied with my exposition in some sections of the doctrine of ele- ments, as for instance in the deduction of the concep- tions of the Understanding, or in that on the paral- ogisms of pure reason, hecaupe a certain diffuseness takes away from their clearness, and in place of them, what is here said in the Prolegomena respecting these sections, may be made the basis of the test. It is the boast of the Germans that where steady and continuous industry are requisite, they can carry things farther than other nations. If this opinion be well founded, an opportunity, a business, presents it- self, the successful issue of which we can scarcely doubt, and in which all thinking men can equally take part, though they have hitherto been unsuccess- ful in accomplishing it and in thus confirming the above good opinion. But this is chiefly because the science in question is of so peculiar a kind, that it can be at once brought to completion and to that en- during state that it will never be able to be brought in the least degree farther or increased by later dis- coveries, or even changed (leaving here out of account adornment by greater clearness in some places, or additional uses), and this is an advantage no other science has or can have, because there is none so fully isolated and independent of others, and which is con- cerned with the faculty of cognition pure and simple. And the present moment seems, moreover, not to be unfavorable to my expectation, for just now, in Ger- many, no one seems to know wherewith to occupy himself, apart from the so-called useful sciences, so i62 rant's prolegomena. as to pursue not mere play, but a business possessing an enduring purpose. To discover the means how the endeavors of the learned may be united in such a purpose, I must leave to others. In the meantime, it is my intention to per- suade any one merely to follow my propositions, or even to flatter me with the hope that he will do so ; but attacks, repetitions, limitations, or coniirmation, completion, and extension, as the case may be, should be appended. If the matter be but investigated from its foundation, it cannot fail that a system, albeit not my own, shall be erected, that shall be a possession for future generations for which they may have reason to be grateful. It would lead us too far here to show what kind of metaphysics may be expected, when only the princi- ples of criticism have been perfected, and how, be-^ cause the old false feathers have been pulled out, she need by no means appear poor and reduced to an in- significant figure, but may be in other respects richly and respectably adorned. But other and great uses which would result from such a reform, strike one im- mediately. The ordinary metaphysics had its uses, in that it sought out the elementary conceptions of the pure understanding in order to make them clear through analysis, and definite by explanation. In this way it was a training for reason, in whatever direction it might be turned ; but this was all the good it did ; service was subsequently effaced when it favored con- ceit by venturesome assertions, sophistry by subtle distinctions and adornment, and shallowness by the ease with which it decided the most difficult problems by means of a little school-wisdom, which is only the more seductive the more it has the choice, on the one APPENDIX. 163 hand, of taking something from the language of sci- ence, and on the other from that of popular discourse, thus being everything to everybody, but in reality nothing at all. By criticism, however, a standard is given to our judgment, whereby knowledge may be with certainty distinguished from pseudo-science, and firmly founded, being brought into full operation in metaphysics ; a mode of thought extending by degrees its beneficial influence over every other use of reason, at once infusing into it the true philosophical spirit. But the service also that metaphysics performs for theology, by making it independent of the judgment of dogmatic speculation, thereby assuring it com- pletely against the attacks of all such opponents, is certainly not to be valued lightly. For ordinary meta- physics, although it promised the latter much advan- tage, could not keep this promise, and moreover, by summoning speculative dogmatics to its assistance, did nothing but arm enemies against itself. Mysti- cism, which can prosper in a rationalistic age only when it hides itself behind a system of school-meta- physics, under the protection of which it may venture to rave with a semblance of rationality, is driven from this, its last hiding-place, by critical philosophy. Last, but not least, it cannot be otherwise than important to a teacher of metaphysics, to be able to say with universal assent, that what he expounds is Science, and that thereby genuine services will be rendered to the commonweal. KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. By dr. PAUL CARUS. KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. PHILOSOPHY is frequently regarded as idle ver- biage ; and the great mass of the average produc- tions of this branch of human endeavor would seem to justify the statement. Nevertheless, philosophy has exercised a paramount influence upon the history of mankind, for philosophy is the quintessence of man's conception of the world and the view he takes of the significance of life. While philosophical books, essays, lectures, and lessons may be intricate and long- winded, there is at the core of all the questions under discussion a public interest of a practical nature. The problems that have reference to it are, as a rule, much simpler and of more common application than is ap- parent to an outsider, and all of them closely consid- ered will be found to be of a religious nature. KANT'S SIGNIFICANCE IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. When we try to trace the erratic lines of the his- tory of philosophy, the advance seems slow, but the results, meagre though they sometimes may be, can be summarised in brief statements. Thus the sophistic movement in Greece in contradistinction to the old najlve naturalists, Thales, Anaximander, and Anaxi- menes, is characterised by the maxim : itavTav lUrpav avOpanroi, [Man is the measure of all things], which is the simple solution of a series of intricate problems. i68 rant's philosophy. In spite of its truth, it was misused by unscrupulous rhetoricians, who disgraced the profession of sophists and degraded the noble name of their science, called Sophia, i. e., wisdom, to such an extent that the term ' ' sophist " became an epithet of opprobrium. Socrates opposed the sophists, but in all theoretical points he was one of them. There was only this difference, that he insisted on the moral nature of man and thus became the noblest exponent of the sophistic prin- ciple. It indicates a new departure that he changed the name sophia to philosophia ot philosophy, i. e., love of wisdom, which was universally accepted as more modest and better becoming to the teachers and spir- itual guides of mankind. While he granted that man is the measure of all things, he pointed out the duty of investigating the nature ot man, and he selected the Delphic maxim : yvfifli o-towov, "know thyself," as a motto for his life. It would lead us too far to show how Plato worked out the Socratic problem of the hu- man soul, which led him to a recognition of the sig- nificance of forms, as expressed in his doctrine of ideas, and how Aristotle applied it to natural science. The Neo-Platonists developed Plato's mystical and supernatural tendencies and prepared thereby for the rise of a dualistic religion. When Christianity became a dominating power in the world, philosophy disappeared for a while, being replaced by the belief in a divine revelation as the sole source of all wisdom; but in the Middle Ages philosophy was revived as scholasticism, the impulse to the movement being due to the revival of Aristote- lianism, through an acquaintance with the writings of cultured Arabian sages. In the era of scholasticism we have two authori- kant's philosophy. 169 ties, Revelation and Science, the former conceived to be identical with the verdicts of the Church, the latter being a blind acceptance of a second-hand and much distorted knowledge of the philosopher's works. The Platonic problem of the eternal types of things was revived, and Nominalists and Realists contended with one another on the question of the reality of ideas. In their methods, however, these two conflicting schools were on the same level, for both were in the habit of appealing to certain authorities. With them proof consisted in quotations either of church doctrines or of passages from Aristotle. There was no genuine science, no true philosophy, the efforts of the age consisting in vain attempts at reconciling the two conflicting sources of their opinions. Modern philosophy is a product of the awakening spirit of science, beginning with Descartes who pro- posed to introduce method into philosophy, as ex- pressed in his Discourse on Method. He abolished the implicit belief in book authority. Falling back upon the facts of life, he bethought himself of the signifi- cance of Man's thinking faculty, and so, starting again from the subjective position of the sophists, he defined his solution of the basic problem with great terseness in the sentence : Cogito ergo sum, [I think, therefore I am]. The latest phase in philosophy begins with Kant, and it is his immortal merit to have gone to the bot- tom of the philosophical problem by reducing its diffi- culties to a system. In the Cartesian syllogism he saw a fallacy if it was interpreted to mean "Cogito ergo ego sum." The subject ego, implied in "sum," is implicitly contained in "cogito," and thus if the sentence is 170 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. meant to prove the existence of a metaphysical ego, the argument is a fallacy, being merely a deduction derived from the assumption that the ego does the thinking. In spite of its syllogistic form the sentence was not meant as a syllogism but as a statement of fact. Kant's objection, however, holds good in either case, for though the thinking be a fact, it is an assumption to take for granted that the thinker is an ego, i. e., a soul-entity that exists independently of its thinking. Lichtenberg therefore said that we ought to replace the sentence "/ think" by "// thinks." Yet even if we allow the statement ^^ I think" to pass, the ques- tion arises: What do we understand by "/"? Is it a collective term for all the thought-processes that take place in one and the same personality, or is there a separate soul-being which does the thinking and con- stitutes the personality? In other words, the exist- ence of the thinking subject, called the /, does not imply that it is a spiritual thing in itself, nor even that it constitutes a unity. Mystic tendencies of a religious nature such as found a classical exposition in Kant's contemporary and namesake, Emanuel Swedenborg, rendered some of the problems of philosophy more complicated by laying special stress upon the difference between mat- ter and spirit, and discussing the possibility and prob- able nature of purely spiritual beings ; but all philoso- phising on the subject consisted in declamations and unproved propositions. Wolf, a clear-headed thinker, though void of origi- nality, reduced the metaphysical notions from Aris- totle down to the eighteenth century into an elaborate rant's philosophy. 171 system, and thus became to Kant the typical exponent of dogmatism. In contrast to the metaphysical school, the sen- sualists had risen. They are best represented by Locke who denied the existence of innate ideas (ex- cept the idea of causation) and tried to prove that all abstract thought had its origin in sensation. Hume, taking offence even at the claims of causation as a necessary connexion, declared that, accustomed to the invariable sequence of cause and effect, we mis- take our subjective necessity of thinking them to- gether for an objective necessity, which remains un- proved. Thus he turned skeptic and gave by his doubts regarding the objective validity of causation .as a universal principle and a metaphysical truth the suggestion to Kant to investigate the claims of all metaphysics, of which the notion of causality is only a part. Here Kant's philosophical reform set in, which consists in rejecting both the skepticism of Hume and the dogmatism of Wolf and in offering a new solution which he called criticism. Kant took the next step in seeking for the prin- ciple that determined all thinking, and discovered it in the purely formal laws of thought, which in their complete unity constitute pure reason. The investi- gation of the conditions of thought, he called "criti- cism." He insisted that the dogmatical declamations of all the various systems of metaphysics were idle and useless talk. He said they were vain attempts at building a mighty tower that would reach to Heaven. But at the same time he claimed to prove that the supply of building materials was after all sufficient for 172 rant's philosophy. a dwelling-house spacious enough for the needs of life and high enough to survey the field of experience. ^ In place of the old metaphysics which used to de- rive from pure concepts a considerable amount of pretended knowledge concerning God, the world, and man, concerning substance, as the substratum of ex- istence, the soul, the future state of things, and im- mortality, Kant drew up an inventory of the posses- sions of Pure Reason and came to the conclusion that all knowledge of purely formal thought is in itself empty and that sense-experience in itself is blind ; the two combined form the warp and woof of experience, which alone can afford positive information concern- ing the nature of objects. Empirical knowledge of the senses furnishes the material, while formal thought supplies the method by which perceptions can be or- ganised and systematised into knowledge. Kant's aim was not to produce glittering generalities, but to offer critique, that is to say, a method of, and norm for, scientific thought ; and he said, conscious of the sig- nificance of his philosophy : ' ' This much is certain, that whoever has once tasted critique will be ever after disgusted with all dogmatical twaddle." Dogmatism in metaphysics is the dragon which Kant slew. But Kant's criticism was not purely nega- tive. He recognised in the world as an undeniable fact the demand of the moral "ought" which he called "the categorical imperative," and while he insisted upon the determinism of natural law he would not deny the freedom of the will establishing it upon 1 See Critique of Pure Reason in the chapter "Transcendental Doctrine of Method," Max Miiller's translation, p. 567, Meicklejohn's, p. 431, original edition, p. 707. rant's philosophy. 173 man's moral responsibility. He declared : "I shall, therefore I can." PERSONAL TRAITS. Kant, the son of simple but rigorously pious parents of Scotch extraction, lived at Konigsberg in Prus- sia under the rule of Frederick the Great. ^ His moral sense was stern and unalloyed with sentimentality. He never married, and his relation to his relatives was regulated strictly according to his views of duty.' In his philosophy as well as in his private life he was duty incarnate. While he had imbibed the sense of duty that characterises the system of education in Prussia, he was also swayed by the ideals of liberty and fraternity so vigorously brought to the front by the French revolution.^ His influence on the German nation, on science, religion, and even politics cannot be underrated, although his ideas did not reach the people directly in the form he uttered them, but only indirectly through his disciples, the preachers, teach- ers, and poets of the age. His main works which em- body the gist of his peculiar doctrines are the Critique of Pure Reason, the Critique of Practical Reason, and the Critique of Judgment. Among them the Critique IFor a good condensed statement of Kant's life see page 245 of this vol- ume, where Professor Windelband's account is reproduced. For a convenient chronological table of the data of Kant's life and publications see pages 287- 2gi of the present volume. 2We have had reproduced at p. 285 of this volume a specimen of Kant's handwriting, a letter of his to his brother, plainly characterising his business- like conception of duty which regulated his life with machine-like preci- sion. SHeinrich Heine described Kant to the French most drastically in an essay on German philosophy, of which an English translation has been re- printed in this volume at page 264, 174 KANX'S PHILOSOPHY. kant's philosophy. 175 of Pure Reason is by far the most important one.^ It is a pity that the Critique of Pure Reason, from the appearance of which the historian dates the beginning of the latest period in the evolution of philosophy, is a ponderous and almost unintelligible work, — a book with seven seals to the average reader ; and it might have remained ineffectual had not Kant been necessi- tated to rectify this defect by giving to the public a popular explanation concerning his intentions. The Critique of Pure Reason was published in 1781. In the Gottingenschen Gelehrten Anzeigen of January 19, 1782, there appeared a review of the book, written by Garve and modified by Feder, which irritated Kant considerably, because the review treated his criticism as a revival of Berkeley's idealism, which was com- monly regarded as pure subjectivism. ^ There is no need here of protesting in Berkeley's name against this interpretation of his philosophy, for we are con- cerned here with Kant, not with Berkeley. But even Kant misunderstood Berkeley,^ and for our present 1 A splendid analysis of the three Critiques is given by Prof. A, Weber in his History 0/ Pkiloso^hy,tx3i.ns\3.ied from the fifth French edition by Prof. Frank Tilly, pp. 436-472, We have reprinted part of this analysis at p. 250. The compilation of Kant's ipihiloso-phy in a. ICantlexikon by Gustav Wegner (Berlin, 1893) is not very serviceable. The book is unhandy and lacks the main requisite of a lexicon, a good index. The exposition of Kant's philosophy by G. H. Lewes in his Biographical History <^ Philosophy is an excellent sketch and worth a careful perusal. But Lewes leaves the problem where Kant left it, saying : "There is, in truth, no necessity in causation, except the necessity of our belief in it,' ' But whence does this necessity come, and what is its authority ? SGarve's letter to Kant and Kant's answer contain the whole material of the history of this garbled review. They are interesting reading but mainly of a personal nature, consisting of explanations, excuses, and polite words. For 3t reproduction of this correspondence see Reclam's text edition of Kant's Prolegomena^ Appendix, pp. 2x4-230. S For a condensed statement of Berkeley's idealism see Thomas J. Mc- Cormack's preface to Berkeley's Treatise Concerning the Principles i^ Human Knowledge^ Chicago, The Open Court Pub. Co,, xgoz, especially pp. xii-siv« 176 kant's philosophy. purpose it is sufficient to say that Berkeley's idealism meant to Kant and his contemporaries pure subjec- tivism. Kant was irritated because his philosophy was dis- posed of as an old error, a method which (as Paulsen says) has been developed into a regular system among a certain class of Roman Catholic critics who regard the possibilities of philosophising as exhausted in the rant's philosophy. 177 history of philosophy. Claiming to be in possession of the whole truth, they are naturally disinclined to believe that new truths can be brought to light. Thus they have developed the habit of associating every new idea with some one of the systems of the past which to them are nothing but a catalogus errorum, and serve them as so many coffins in which to bury any doctrine that does not receive their approbation. Kant's indignation was perhaps exaggerated, for he ought to have considered the difficulty of under- standing a doctrine that was at the same time utterly new and presented in a most unattractive, pedantical form ; but the result was happy, for he felt urged to write a popular explanation of his work, to offset Garve's misconception, which would serve the reader as Prolegomena, i. e , as prefatory remarks to the Cri- tique of Pure Reason. These Prolegomena insist on the newness of Kant's proposition and emphasise his adhesion to realism (or the doctrine that the objective world is actual) in con- trast to the subjectivism of Berkeley, or what was sup- posed to be Berkeley. At the same time they possess the charm of wonderful vigor and directness. Here Kant does not write in the pedantic, dignified style of a professor, but with the boldness of a resentful author who, conscious of his title to careful considera- tion and believing himself to be wrongly criticised, is anxious to be properly understood by the public. While the Critique of Pure Reason is synthetic, the Prolegomena are (as says Kant himself) analytic. In the Critique of Pure Reason Kant discourses as one who speaks ex cathedra, sitting in the professorial chair ; he propounds his doctrine deductively, and I 1 See Friedrich Paulsen's Kant, p. Z29, 178 kant's philosophy. for one can very well understand that his expositions appear to an uninitiated reader bewilderingly orac- ular. In the Prolegomena his stj'le is not stilted but rather careless and though his periods are long they are fluent and easily understood. KANT'S TERMS. The main difficulty of understanding Kant, to later generations, and also to foreigners not to the manner born as regards the German vernacular, lies in his terminology. Simple though his terms are when once understood, they afford unsurmountable difficulties to those who are not familiar with their significance. Familiarity with the following terms is indispen- sable for a comprehension of Kant: "metaphysics"; "understanding" and "reason"; "empirical" and "experience"; "noumenon" and "phenomenon"; a priori z.-aA a posteriori ; " transcendental " and "tran- scendent"; and "intuition" ox Anschauung. First, above all, there is the term "metaphysics," which is the science of first principles. Aristotle, who discusses the subject of dpx(i'> or first principles, in books placed after the physical treatises (hence the name to, ^era ra. ^vo-iko, sc. ^iPXia, corrupted into meta- physics), calls it First Philosophy, i. e., the Essence or basis of Philosophy, and identifies it with Theol- ogy, because he finds in God the ultimate raison d'etre of all metaphysical concepts such as being and be- coming, space and time, multiplicity and unity, things and the world, cause and effect, substance and qual- ity, God and soul and immortality. Kant defines metaphysics as : "A system of all the principles of pure theo- retical reason-cognition {^Vernunfterkenniniss) in kant's philosophy. 179 concepts, — briefly the system of pure theoretical philosophy. " ' In another place Kant (IV., p. 236) speaks of metaphysics simply as "pure philosophy limited to the objects of the understanding," a definition which almost identifies it with Logic. ^ He insists that meta- physics is based upon man's faculty of thinking and not pure imagination. Being a priori, it deals with the acts of pure thought, which reduce the manifold sense-impressions to unity bylaw. (Vol. IV., p. 362.) The sources of metaphysics are limited by Kant to the a priori (Vol. IV., p. 13); its possibility stands and falls with the possibility of synthetical judgments a priori (Vol. IV., p. 14); pre-Kantian metaphysics is declared to be uncritical and unscientific (IV., p. 23); as a science metaphysics must be a systematic presentation of all a priori concepts, including above all the synthetical propositions of man's philosophical cognition; and its final purpose (IV., p. 19) consists in the cognition of the Supreme Being as well as of the life to come {die zukUnftige WeW). The latter expression had perhaps better be replaced by the broader idea of the mundus intelligibilis, the intelligible world, constituting the purely formal in contrast to the material, the Platonic ideas or types of things as distinguished from their accidental relations in space and time, exhibiting the abiding in the transcient and thus making it possible to view the world (as Spinoza has it) under the aspect of eternity, — sub specie ceterni. Kant started a new line of investigation and kept in view his main aim. . So it was natural that he did lEd. Hartenstein, Vol. VIH., p. 52i. 2 Logic is defined by Kant (IV., p. 236) as " the pure philosophy which is purely formal." i8o rant's philosophy. not feel the need of certain discriminations before his work was pretty well advanced. This accounts for a few inaccuracies in the use of his terminology, cover- ing the terms "understanding," "reason," and "ex- perience." He distinguishes in his Prolegomena be- tween reason and understanding, but the discrimination is by no means thoroughly carried out. The under- standing is defined as the use of the categories, and reason the faculty of forming ideas. The understand- ing accordingly represents the logical functions, and reason the domain of abstractions and generalisations. The understanding draws conclusions and attends to the machinery of thinking, reason seeks oneness in plurality, aims at a systematical comprehension of things apparently different and establishes laws to ex- plain the variety of phenomena by one common rule. By "empirical" Kant understood all those judg- ments that contain sensory elements. They were either mere perceptions, i. e., a taking cognisance of sense- impressions, or experience, i. e., the product of thought and perceptions, resulting in empirical state- ments that are universally valid, ^ The contrast of perceptions, as the sense-woven pictures of things, and ideas or the mind-begotten concepts of them, is expressed in the two terms "phenomenon" or appearance, and "noumenon" or thought. Kant translates the former by the word Sin- neswesen, i. e., creature of the senses, and the latter by the word Gedankenwesen, i. e., creature of thought.' 1 That Kant's use of the term " experience " was not always consistent I have endeavored to explain elsewhere. See Primer of Philosophy, pp. 30 ff. 2 Pronounce no-oomenon, not noomenon. The original Greek reads yooi!- Iievov. Theou in the German transcription, **No-ume7ion^' was misinterpreted as a French ou: hence the erroneous pronunciation of some English lexicog- raphers as ''noomenon." rant's philosophy. i8i Noumenon should not mean "thing in itself," as which it is actually used by Kant contrary to his own definition, but man's subjective conception of the thing in itself. If the phenomenon is subjective ap- pearance, the noumenon, far from being objective, is, according to Kant, still more subjective, being a mere subjective digest of the materials furnished by the subjective phenomenon. The term "noumenon," however,is not limited to its original meaning. Kant understands by it, not oply the subjective concept of things, but also the objective "thing in itself." The terms a priori zxiA a posteriori are of special significance. They mean "before" and "afterwards," but we must bear in mind that they should be under- stood, not as a temporal succession, but in a logical sense. A priori cognitions are the principles which the naturalist uses in his investigations ; but his in- vestigations themselves, consisting of sense-experi- ence, are a posteriori. Before he begins his investiga- tion, the naturalist must know that 2X2^4, that there can be no effect without a cause, that he can rely on the rule of three and on the syllogisms of logic. The knowledge of these truths is the condition of science, and all these truths are universal, i. e., they apply to all possible cases. A priori knowledge has developed through the practice of sense-experience. Indeed, sense-experience came first in temporal order ; but sense-impressions would forever remain a mass of iso- lated things were they not systematised with the as- sistance of a priori principles. A priori does not mean innate, for neither mathe- matics, nor arithmetic, nor logic is innate; but the theorems of these sciences can be deduced in our thoughts without calling upon sense-experience to aid 1 82 rant's philosophy. us. Innate ideas would mean inherited notions, like the instincts of animals. The characteristic feature of a priori conceptions is not that we know them well nor that we find them ready-made in our minds, but that they have a universal application and are there- fore necessary truths. The contrast between a priori and a posteriori truths is easily explained when we consider that the former are purely formal, the latter sensory. The for- mer therefore cannot give us any information concern- ing the substance, the matter, the thingish nature of things (as Kant expresses it, "they are empty"), but they can be used for determining the relations and forms of things, and this renders them uniquely valu- able, for science is nothing but a tracing of the changes of form, an application of the laws of form, a measur- ing, a weighing, a counting ; and their paramount im- portance appears in this that our knowledge of the laws of form will in consideration of their universal validity, result in the possibility of predetermining future modifications under given conditions. There, are two synonyms of a priori, the word "pure" and the term "transcendental." Reason unalloyed with notions derived from sense- experience, and therefore limited to conceptions a pri- ori, is called pure reason. "Transcendental" means practically the same as pure and a priori. By tran- scendental discourses Kant understands those which transcend experience and consider its a priori condi- tions. Thus, transcendental logic is pure logic in so far as pure logic is the condition of applied logic. Transcendental psychology is the doubtful domain of abstract notions concerning the unity of the ego, its substantiahty and permanence, etc. Transcendental KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. I83 cosmology consists of the ideas of existence in gene- ral and the universe in particular. Then the questions arise as to the world's infinitude or limitedness, its eternity or beginning and end. Further, whether or not causality is absolute, viz., is there contingency only, or is an uncaused will possible? Here the oracle of pure reason fails and Kant formulates the result in his strange doctrine of contradictions, or, as he calls it, antinomies of pure reason. Transcendental cosmology, transcendental psy- chology, transcendental theology, are not sciences, but the dreams of metaphysics. As such they tran- scend experience to the extent of becoming hazy. They cease to be accessible to comprehension and are then in Kant's terminology called "transcendent." Mark the difference between the two terms : the word "transcendental" denotes the subjective condi- tions of all experience, consisting in the recognition of such truisms as logical, arithmetical, and geometri- cal theorems, which are the clearest, most indisput- able, and most unequivocal notions we have. Tran- scendent, however, means that which lies beyond the ken of all possible knowledge within the nebulous do- main in which we can as well affirm as deny the pos- sibility of assumptions. Consider at the same time that in the English language "transcendental" is a synonym of "transcendent," and the difference made by Kant has been slurred over by many of his exposi- tors. What a heap of confusion resulted from this carelessness ! We need not wonder that his radical system of transcendental criticism was transformed into that uncritical metaphysicism, or dabbling in un- warranted transcendental notions which Kant so vig- orously and effectually combated. 184 rant's philosophy. The confusion which English interpreters produced by their neglect of distinguishing between "transcen- dent" and "transcendental" was increased by their misconception of the term Anschauung, which, being properly but not adequately translated by its Latin equivalent "intuition," became tinged with all the mysticism and metaphysicism of intuitionalism. "In- tuition," according to the commonly accepted use of the word, means in the English as well as in German "the power of the mind by which it immediately per- ceives the truth of things without reasoning or analy- sis." As such intuitions signify not only the images of sense-perception, but also, and indeed mainly, ec- static visions in which the soul is face to face with presences spiritual, supernal, or divine; and thus it happened that under the guarantee of Kant's criticism the most extravagant speculations could gain admis- sion to the philosophical world as genuine philosoph- ical ideas. Anschauung, like the Latin intuitio, signifies the act of looking at an object ; it denotes the sensation of sight. However, its use is not restricted to sight, but extends to all sense-perception. The peculiar feature of sense-perception consists in its directness and im- mediate appearance in our organs of sense as sensa- tion. When we look at a tree we do not argue ; we simply see the tree. We need not know anything about the physical processes that take place both outside in the domain of ether-waves which are re- flected on the sighted object, and within our eye where the lens produces an image that is thrown upon the surface of the retina, in the same way in which the photographer's camera produces a picture on the sensitive plate. The picture seen is the result of the kant's philosophy. 185 process, and all epistemological considerations are after-thoughts. The same is true of all sensations. Sensations, though the result of complicated pro- cesses, are given facts ; they are the data of experi- ence and there is no argument in them, no reasoning, no deliberation, no hesitation, as to their truth ; they are the realities of life, and from them we construct our notions of the world in which we live. It is a pity that we have not a Saxon equivalent for the German Anschauung. We might coin the word "atsight," which (in contrast to insight) would de- note the act of perceiving a sighted object ; but the word, in order to make the same impression, ought to be current, which the term atsight is not. The translation "intuition" is admissible only on the con- dition that we exclude from it all mystical notions of subjective visions and define it as visualised percep- tion. There are passages where Anschauung is an ex- act synonym for "sense-experience" or "perception," and we might translate it thus were it not for the ex- tended use Kant makes of the term by speaking of reine Anschauung, meaning thereby the pure forms of sense-experience which are as much immediate data of perception as are the sense-elements of sensation. If we had to recast the exposition of Kant's phi- losophy we could avoid the term "pure intuition" and replace it by the pure forms of sense-experience, but if we would render Kant in his own words we can- not do so. The translator must reproduce Kant in his own language, and thus must either invent a new word such as atsight, or must cling to the traditional term intuition?- 1 Mr. Kroeger's proposition, made in the Journal of Speculative Philos- ophy, 11., p. igi, to translate Anschauung by contemplation seems inadmis- 186 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY". KANT'S IDEALISM. The contrasts in Kant's terminology, a priori and a posteriori, formal and material, pure reason and ex- perience, etc., do not yet imply the conclusion at which he arrives, the main result being the ideality of space and time and of all pure forms of thought. Kant was led to it by a strange fallacy, the error of which we intend to trace in the subsequent pages. First let us try to understand the point of view which Kant took. The pure form of our sense-perception is the rela- tional in the domain of sensory elements, viz., their juxtaposition, or space, and their succession, or time, their shape, their causal intercatenation, etc. In his discourse on the pure forms of sense-per- ception (called "Transcendental .^Esthetics"), Kant points out first of space, then of time, that they are notions which are : 1. Insuppressible (viz., we can think or assume in thought the non-existence of all objects, but not of space or time). 2. Necessary a priori (viz., they are of universal application' and transcendental, i. e., the condition of all sense-perceptions.) 3. Unique (viz., there is but one space and one time ; all spaces, so called, are parts only of, or rooms in, that one space ; and different times are periods of that one time). 4. Infinite (viz., all concrete objects are finite; sible. Compare for further details of the use of the word the author's pam- phlet Kant and Spemer^ pp. 76 ff. In the present translation of Kant's Frolegomsna we have rendered it a few times by sense-perception and msuali- sation, but mostly by intuitwn, and have (wherever it is not translated by "intuition ") alway added in parenthesis the German original. KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. 1 87 but time and space, not being concrete entities, are limitless). He concludes that space and time are not proper- ties of objects as things-in-themselves, but the forms of their phenomenal existence. It is obviously a mistake to regard space and time as concrete objects. Infinite objects would be mon- ster-existences the reality of which cannot but pass our comprehension. They are the forms of things, indispensable not only for their existence in general but also for determining their several individual and characteristic types; for that which constitutes the difference of things, so far as science has been able to penetrate into the mysteries of being, is always due to a difference of form. Kant guardedly grants em- pirical reality to space and time ; he ascribes space and time to things as phenomena, and denies only their being properties of things as things-in-them- selves. But he adds the explicit statement that space as well as time are "the subjective conditions of the sensibility under which alone external intuition {An- schauung, i. e., sense-perception) becomes possible." Thus, Kant concludes space and time are a priori in- tuitions ; they do not belong to the external domain of reality or objectivity, but to the sphere of subjec- tivity ; and being forms of the sensibility of the in- tuitive mind they are (says Kant) ideal. Kant does not deny the reality of things, but hav- ing established the ideality of space and time he be- lieves that, " If we regarded space and time as properties which must be found in objects as things-in-themselves, as sine quibus non of the possibility of their existence, and reflect on the absurdities in which we then find ourr-slves involved, inasmuch as we are com- i88 kant's philosophy. pelled to admit the existence of two infinite things, which are nevertheless not substances, nor anything really inhering in sub- stances, nay, to admit that they are the necessary conditions of the existence of all things, and moreover, that they must continue to exist, although all existing things were annihilated, — we cannot blame the good Berkeley tor degrading bodies to mere illusory ap- pearances. Nay, even our own existence which would in this case depend upon the self-existent reality of such a mere nonentity as time, would necessarily be changed with it into mere appearance — an absurdity which no one has as yet been guilty of." ' Thus, Kant believes that if space and time were objective they would impart their ideality to the ob- jective world and change it to mere appearance ; by conceiving space and time (and ia addition to the forms of our sensibility also the forms of our think- ing) as purely ideal, viz., as subjective properties of the mind, he assures us that the world, our own ex- istence included, will be saved from the general col- lapse which it otherwise in his opinion must suffer, KANT AND SWEDENBORG. The development of Kant's theory of the ideality of space and time coincides with his investigation of Swedenborg's philosophy, if that word be applicable to a world-conception which afterwards was denom- inated by Kant himself as "dreams of A visionary." Swedenborgians claim that Kant was influenced by Swedenborg in the formulation of his critical ideal- ism ; and Mr. Albert J. Edmunds discusses the sub- ject in an article which appeared in the J^ew Church Review, Vol. IV., No. 2, under the title: Time and Space : Hints Given by Swedenborg to Kant. While it appears that there is less borrowing on the part of Kant than can be made out by Swedenborg's adher- 1 Critiqut o/Fure Reason, Supplement VI. of snd edition. kant's philosophy. i8g ents, there is more justice in the claim of Sweden- borg's influence over Kant than seems to be palatable to such Kant scholars as is Professor Vaihinger. Frank Sewall, the editor of the New Church Review, goes over the field in an article entitled : Kant ana Swedenborg on Cognition, in which he makes out a good case scarcely less favorable for Swedenborg than does Edmunds. The fact is that the mystical ideas on space and time which permeate religious thought had their effect on Swedenborg as much as on other thinkers, mystics as well as philosophers, and among the latter, on Kant ; and certain formulations of the problem which can be found in Swedenborg, did not strike Kant as much as may appear by a mere com- parison of the passages. Mr. Edmunds quotes the following passages from Leibnitz, on space and time : ' ' Since space in itself is an ideal thing like time, it must nec- essarily follow that space outside the world is imaginary, as even the schoolmen have acknowledged it to be. The same is the case with empty space in the world — which I still believe to be imagin- ary, for the reasons which I have set forth." (V. 33.) "There is no space at all where there is no matter." (V. 62.) "Space . . . is something ideal." (V. 104.) "The immensity of God is independent of space, as the eter- nity of God is independent of time." (V. 106.) ' ' Had there been no creatures, space and time would only have existed in the ideas of God." (Paper IV. 41.) Here Leibnitz uses the very word "ideal," of both space and time. Incidentally we must add that natu- ralists of to-day will no longer countenance Leibnitz's view of the non-existence of empty space. There is even the religious mysticism displayed by Leibnitz which makes God independent of space and time. Swedenborg says the same about the angels : igo kant's philosophy. ' ' The angels have no idea of time. Such is the case in the world of spirits and still more perfectly in heaven: how much more before the Lord." {Arca?ia Ccelestia, 1274.) It is a fact that Kant had read Swedenborg, but the coincidences as to the ideality of space and time and the theory of cognition are trivial as compared with the coincidences with former philosophers, such as Leibnitz. The truth is, we have in Swedenborg the type of a religious thinker who formulates his conception of space and time and other metaphysical doctrines in the shape of mystical allegories, after the fashion of Jacob Boehme and other religious vision- aries. It is wrong on the one side to overestimate his mystical expressions, which are commonplace among authors of his ilk, and, on the other hand, to ridicule them as purely visionary, devoid of philosophical value. It is characteristic of the human mind at a certain stage of its development to formulate in mys- tical language philosophical conceptions which lie beyond the grasp of the intellect of that peculiar stage of growth. It is the religious attitude of approaching philosophical problems in mystical expressions. While it is natural for a scientist to ridicule the mystic for claiming to have solved the world-problem though producing nothing but air-bubbles, it is at the same time a one-sidedness to see in mysticism nothing but wild and worthless hallucinations. Mysticism is a solution of the world-problem by sentiment, and it affords the great advantage of determining and estab- lishing the moral attitude of its devotees. Considered as science it is absolutely worthless, considered as a guide in life its worth is determined by the spirit of which it is born. Where the religious sentiment is serious, deep, and noble, mysticism will find a poeti- rant's philosophy. 191 cal expression full of significance, depth, and aspira- tion. Kant as a religious man was attracted by Swe- denborg, but when he weighed his revelations as phi- losophy he was so disappointed that he felt ashamed of having been caught among the credulous investi- gators of occult phenomena. Swedenborg is one of the most representative mys- tics, and while his books may be worthless as philo- sophical treatises, they are not only interesting to the scientist because typical of a certain phase in the reli- gious development of human nature, but also classi- cal as mystical literature. The appreciation which he has found among a number of adherents proves too well how deeply his way of presenting metaphysical problems in the shape of allegorical dreams is founded in the peculiar constitution of man's spiritual system. Those who took the trouble to investigate his miracles and prophecies found that, however much might be surmised, nothing could be definitely proved, except the fact that there are people of fair and sometimes even extraordinary intelligence who have a decided inclination to believe in occult phenomena, that they, though subjectively honest, can easily become con- vinced of things which they are anxious to believe, and finally that in minds where a vivid imagination checks the development of critical acumen, the poeti- cal conceptions of religious faith grow so definite and concrete as to become indistinguishable from actual life and reality. Now, what are the lessons of the relation of mysti- cism to science? We ought to consider that certain metaphysical truths (as to the nature of space, time, our mode of cognition, causation, infinity, eternity, etc.), when iga kant's philosophy. stated in abstract formulas, seem dry and unmeaning to unscientific minds, yet they possess a deep religious significance which finds allegorical expression in the various religious systems in myths, ceremonial insti- tutions, and dogmas. By sensual natures who cling to the allegorical feature of the allegory, they can be appreciated only if they are expressed in a sensual way, if spiritual truths are told in parables of concrete instances as if they were material facts of the material world. It is characteristic of mystical minds to live in an atmosphere of sensual symbolism in such a way that they believe their own dreams, and their assur- ance makes their statement so convincing that they easily find followers among those who are kin to them in their mental constitution. As soon as a critical reader tries to verify the statements of such men, he finds himself irritated by a heap of worthless evidence, and the result is an indignation such as Kant showed after his perusal of Swedenborg's Arcana. The following summarised statement of Sweden- borg's world-conception is given by Kant in his Essay on Swedenborg, which appeared in 1766 -^ "Each human soul has in this life its place in the spirit-world, and belongs to a certain society, which in every case is in harmony with its internal condition of truth and good, that is, of under- standing and will. But the location of spirits among themselves has nothing in common with space in the material world. The soul of one man, therefore, in India can be next-door neighbor to that of another in Europe, so far as spiritual position is con- cerned ; while those who, as to the body, live in one house, may be quite far enough distant from one another as to those [that is, spiritual] conditions. When man dies his soul does not change its place, but only perceives itself in the same wherein, with regard to other spirits, it already was in this life. Besides, although the 1 We quote from Mr. Albert ]. Edmunds's essay in the New Church Review, Vol. IV., p. J61. kant's philosophy. 193 mutual relation of spirits is not in real space, yet it has to them the appearance of space, and their relations are represented, irith their accompanying conditions, as nearnesses ; their differences as dis- tances, even as the spirits themselves have not really extension, yet present to one another the appearance of a human form. In this imaginary space there is a plenary community of spiritual natures. Swedenborg speaks with departed souls whenever he pleases, etc." Now, if we comprehend that besides the causal connexion of things in space and time there is a logical interrelation which appertains to pure reason, we shall come to the conclusion that Swedenborg's ideas are quite legitimate, if they are but understood to be poet- ical and if we are permitted to conceive them in a strictly scientific sense. We read : ''The soul of one man in India can be next-door neighbor to that of another in Europe so far as spiritual position is concerned; while those who as to the body live in one house may be quite far enough distant from one another as to those (that is, spiritual) conditions. " Now, it is obvious that this sympathy of souls, which is not according to space and time, but accord- ing to spiritual kinship, is quite legitimate and very important to those who understand it. The sensual man will find difficulty in grasping its significance, ex- cept that it be stated to him in a sensual way. Ob- viously, it is true that "spirits themselves have not really extension." Their interrelation is of a different kind. But if we imagine them, as Swedenborg does, "to present to one another the appearance of a hu- man form," we conceive of their existence as though it were in space, another kind of space than that filled by matter, and "in this imaginary space there is a plenary community of spiritual natures." Thus logi- cians represent the interrelation between genus and 194 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. species by geometrical figure, the one including the other. Swedenborg is simply a man whose imagination is so vivid and whose scientific criticism is so little de- veloped that the imaginary space invented to repre- sent the interrelations of spiritual realities which are in neither space nor time, becomes an actual space to him ; his spirits become materialised shapes, and thus it happens that he can speak "with departed souls whenever he pleases." A scientist too, a his- torian or a naturalist, can consult the wisdom of the departed spirits. He can make himself acquainted with the views of Newton, of Goethe, of Kant; he can incorporate their souls in his own being, but being - of a critical nature, he will not see them as bodily shapes. It is characteristic of mystics that their im- agination outruns their sobriety, and thus the flights of their fancy become real to them. While it is not impossible that Swedenborg be- came the fulcrum on which Kant elaborated his meta- physics, we may at the same time justify the oppo- site statement that Kant's relation to Swedenborg is purely incidental and without significance. The elab- oration of his theories as to space and time and cogni- tion, Kant made at the time when he read Sweden- borg's works, but we must be aware of the fact that Kant was familiar with mystic views in general, and Swedenborg's expressions did not strike him as much as it might appear to those who compare Swedenborg and Kant only, but have no reference to Leibnitz and other thinkers. Certainly, Kant would have come to the same conclusion if he had dealt with any other thinker of a similar type, Jacob Boehme, or even spirits on a lower level in the line of mysticism. want's philosophy. 19S While Kant's statements show a certain resem- blance to those of Swedenborg, we find that their agreement with Leibnitz (a philosopher whom both Immanuels, the great mystic as well as the great critic, had studied carefully) is much closer. We shall at the same time understand why Kant exhibited a de- cided contempt and scorn for the dreamy haziness of these visionaries, which, when dealing with scientific problems, is sterile and unprofitable. In contrasting the philosophical study of metaphysics with those vague fancies of religio-philosophical dreams, Kant compared the latter to the intangible shade of a de- parted spirit, quoting Virgil's well-known verses where ^neas in the under-world tries to embrace the soul of his departed father, Anchises.^ Kant says : ' ' Metaphysics, with whom it is my destiny to be in love, offers two advantages, although I have but seldom been favored by her : the £rst is, to solve the problems which the investigating mind raises when it is on the track of the more hidden properties of things through reason. But here the result very frequently de- ceives hope, and has also in this case escaped our longing bands. "Ter frustra comprensa manus efEugit imago, Par levibus ventis volucrique simillima somno." — (Virgil.) [Thrice I tried to embrace and thrice it escaped me, the image, Airy and light as the wind, and to volatile dreams to be likened.] KANT'S ANTINOMIES. After this digression we revert to Kant's idealism and will now point out the result to which it leads. Kant, as we have seen, protests against being an idealist in the sense that the reality of the external world of objects or things be denied. His idealism insists only on the ideality of space and time ; and by ideality he understands subjectivity. But together l^neas. Book VI., Verses 701-70Z. 196 rant's philosophy. with time and space all our forms of thought are as- sumed to be purely ideal. Hence there is a rift rend- ing asunder form and substance, thought and reality, representa,tive image or phenomenon and the repre- sented objects. We know phenomena, not noumena. Things in themselves are unknowable, for the laws of pure form have reference to appearances only. If purely formal thought has no objective value, it can be used merely to decide problems that lie within the range of experience — the domain of appearance ; but things in themselves, the domain of transcendent existence, lies without the pale of any possible knowl- edge. Kant's method of dealing with these subjects is peculiar. He neither leaves them alone nor solves them, but formulates the affirmations as well as the negations of a series of contradictory statements in what he calls "the antinomies." Here the weakness of Kant's philosophy comes out, indicating that there must be a flaw in it somewhere. It is interesting to notice that as to Kant's Antino- mies of Pure Reason the great Kfinigsberg philosopher has been anticipated by Buddhism in which (accord- ing to Neumann's ^^^«« Gauiamo's, Vol. II., Nos. 60 and 72) the antinomies are taught in a similar, partly literally in the same, form. But there, too, the con- tradiction belongs to the formulation of the statement of facts, not to the facts themselves. In a certain sense we can say, the world must have had a beginning, and must come to an end ; and the world had no beginning and can have no end. If we speak of this definite nebular system of stars compris- ing the entire milky way we are compelled to admit that it began and will at some definite though distant rant's philosophy. 197 future be dissolved again ; but If wo mean by world the totality of existence in all its shapes, prior forms and causes of origin, we must own that it has existed and ever will exist. We could go back in thought to the time before the present cosmos started, when other worlds were evolving or dissolving and a differ- ent kind of universe or condition of things prevailed and so on without coming to an end. But these con- ditions being the causes of the present world are in- cluded in our concept of the universe. The antino- mies are due to the equivocal significance of our words, not to a fault of reason ; nor do they indicate that existence itself is self-contradictory. The con- tradiction is not in the things but in our conception of things.^ Schopenhauer has vigorously attacked Kant on account of his antinomies, insinuating weakness and hypocrisy. But it seems to us, while by no means agreeing with Kant on this particular point, that granting his premises his conclusion was justified. The four points of the antinomies, viz., the eternity and infinite divisibility of the world, the contrast of freedom to causation and the existence of God, are no longer of a purely formal nature ; some notions of experience are inevitably mixed up in them, and thus 1 That the antinomies cannot be regarded as true antinomies or contra- dictions of reason, but as the result of a misconception and laclc of clearness in our formulation of the several problems, becomes apparent in the antin- omy of freedom versus necessity. Kant's definition of freedom (§ 53) as a fac- ulty of starting a chain of events spontaneously without antecedent causes and bis way of reconciling freedom and nature (or as we would say "deter- minism ") is subject to serious criticism. Compare the author's solution of the problem in Fundamental Problems^ pp. igi-196.; Ethical Problems^ pp. 45- 50, 152-156; Primer of Philosophy ^ pp. 159-164; Soulof Man^ pp. 389-397. See also The Monist, Vol. III., pp. 611 ff., "The Future in Mental Causation." Concerning the ought and its assumed mysterious nature compare the chap-' ters "The Is and the Ought," and "An Analysis of the Moral Ought," in The Ethical Problem, pp. 279-295. igS KANT'S PHILOSOPltY. pure reason is unable to decide either way. We might as well try to determine by a priori considerations as to whether or not electricity can be produced by fric- tion, or whether or not by rubbing an old metal lamp the genii of the lamp will appear. Hence, before the tribunal of pure reason either side, the affirmative as well as the negative, is defensible, and thus we should be obliged to settle the question with other methods j other methods, however, according to Kant's notions concerning the nature of metaphysical questions, would not be admissible, because he insists that all metaphysical notions must be derived from pure con- cepts alone. KANT'S PROBLEM. Kant's philosophy has become the beginning of a new epoch in the evolution of human thought through a formulation of its basic problem and by starting out in the right direction for its solution ; but Kant has not spoken the final word. Kant was awakened from his dogmatic slumber by Hume's scepticism, and it was Hume's problem as to the nature of causation which prompted him to strike a new path in the conception of philosophical prob- lems. Kant threw light on Hume's problem by general- ising it and recognising the kinship of the concep- tion of causation to mathematics and logic, all of them being purely formal knowledge. The significance of formal thought and its power of affording a priori cog- nitions is Kant's peculiar problem. It is generally conceded that Kant solved Hume's problem, but he failed to solve his own. KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. 1 99 By a strange misapprehension of the nature of form and its non-objectivity, he has switched off into an idealism (so called by himself) which it will be hard to distinguish from that subjectivism which he as- sumed Berkeley's philosophy to be. The difference between the two (in Kant's opinion) consists in this, that according to Kant, the world itself is real but in the form in which it represents itself in space and time it is phenomenal, while he declares that accord- ing to Berkeley the world itself is " illusory appear- ance." Further Kant insists that the world as appear- ance, though purely phenomenal, is not an arbitrary illusion, but governed by laws which render it neces- sary in all its details. The great merit of Kant is his wonderfully keen discrimination between the purely formal and the sen- sory, showing that the former is throughout universal and necessary in its principles, while the latter is in- cidental and concrete or particular; but he fails to apply the same discrimination to his conception of experience and to the objects of experience, and thus he limits the formal to the subject, while it is obvi- ously the universal feature of all existence, objective as well as subjective, constituting between them the connecting link that makes science, i. e., objective cognition, possible. Before we examine Kant's position, we must first discuss, at least briefly, Hume's problem and offer the solution in the form which Kant, in our opinion, ought to have given it. It will then be easy to point out the error that led him astray and prevented him from offering a definite and final doctrine as to the nature of form which should become the basis of all scientific inquiry, and enable philosophy to become a science as 200 ■ KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. definite, or nearly so, as are mathematics and logic, or even physics. HUME'S PROBLEM. Locke objected to the doctrine of innate ideas, claiming that all ideas were the products of sense- impressions, and he excepted only one idea, viz. , the principle of necessary connexion, i. e., causality. Hume accepted Locke's sensualism, but, endeavoring to be more consistent, drew its last consequence by denying even the idea of cause and effect as a neces- sary connexion. He argued that we meet with con- stant conjunctions in experience, but not with neces- sity. By habit we are compelled to expect that upon every cause its due effect will follow, but there is no reason to assume that causation is due to a universal and necessary law of objective validity. Hume saw in the relation between cause and effect a synthesis, calling it "the sequence of two objects"; and if it were a synthesis, or a mere sequence, he would be right that the connexion between cause and effect is accidental and our belief in its necessity a mere habit. The truth is that causation is not a sequence of two objects following one another, but one process, a motion, or a change of place ; and the simplest kind of motion implies that there are at least three phases or states of things in the system in which the motion takes place : first the original condition (which for sim- plicity's sake we may assume to be in a relative equi- librium); secondly, the motion disturbing the equi- librium so as to make one or several elements in the system seek new places ; and thirdly, the new adjust- ment (which for simplicity's sake we will again regard as being in equilibrium). The first phase is called KANT's philosophy. 20I the conditions or circumstances, the second is the cause, and the third the effect. Cause and effect are not combined into a unity by the compulsion of a law of necessary connexion ; they are two phases of one and the same process. The duality is a product of abstraction ; the unity of the two is the original fact, and we know now that causality is but another ex- pression for the law of the conservation of matter and energy. The naturalist assumes that matter and en- ergy are indestructible, and thus every process that takes place in nature is only a transformation. Ac- cordingly, our belief in causation is after all, although Hume denied it, finally based upon the logical prin- ciple of identity A=A. It is an extension of this prin- ciple to a state of motion. Cause, accordingly, is never an object, but always an event, viz., a motion of some kind. We cannot call the bullet the cause and death the effect ; or mer- cury the cause and paralysis the effect ; or worse still (as says George Lewes) that whiskey, water, sugar, and lemon are the causes of punch. We distinguish between cause and reason, reason being the law under which a single event is subsumed for the sake of explaining the effectiveness of the cause. * IThe instinct of language has here proved wiser than the scholarship of philosophers. All European languages (the Greek, the Latin, together with its derivatives the French, Italian, etc., the German, the English) distin- guish between " alria, causa, Ursache (from the same root as the English verb 'to seek') cause," and *^ apxri (i. c, first principle) ratio, Grund, reason," the former being the particular incident that starts a process, the latter the raison d'Stre, the principle, or general rule, the natural law that explains it. When the two ideas are confounded as has been done frequently by philoso- phers, the greatest confusion results leading to such self-contradictory no- tions as "causasui" "first cause," "ultimate cause," etc., which lead either to agnosticism or to mysticism. For further details see the author's Primer of Pkilosophy, the chapter on Causation, pp. 30-34, and Fundamental Prob- lems, pp. 29-30. 202 KANT S PHILOSOPHY. Kant, following the suggestion of Hume, devoted special attention to the problem of causality, but he solved it by simply declaring that it was a concept a priori, and thus belonged to the same class of truths as mathematical, arithmetical, and logical the- orems. He never attempted to explain its truth, let alone to prove it, or to demonstrate its universality and necessity. Mathematicians deem it necessary to prove their theorems, but Kant, strange to say, neg- lected to deduce the law of causation from simpler truths or analyse it into its elements. If Kant had made attempts to analyse causation for the sake of proving its validity after the fashion of logicians and mathematicians, he might, with his keen insight into the nature of physical laws and natural sciences, have- anticipated the discovery of the law of the conserva- tion of matter and energy, and might furthermore have been preserved from the error of his subjectivism which affected the whole system of his thought and twisted his philosophy out of shape. KANT'S PROLEGOMENA. In the Critique of Pure Reason Kant's position re- mains unintelligible; we understand his arguments and may even approve the several statements from which they proceed, but we are astonished at the bold- ness of the conclusion, and fail to be convinced. His objections to the belief in space and time as objective things hold good only if space and time are assumed to be things or objects ; but not if they are thought to be mere forms of objects. They are thinkable as forms of thought not less than as forms of objects. When assumed to be solely forms of thought to the exclu- sion of the idea that there are any objective relations kant's philosophy. 203 corresponding to them, they become mysterious and quite mystical, and here lies the reason why Kant's Critique of Pure Reason is actually mystifying. He bewilders the reader. We become acquainted with his argument but do not feel sure that we have rightly apprehended his meaning. In the Prolegomena Kant is, at least, not unintelligible. The Prolegomena are not deductive, but inductive. In them Kant leads us the way he travelled himself, and this is the reason of the importance of the Prolegomena. Kant embodied their contents in various places into the second edi- tion of his Critique of Pure Reason. But the passages are scattered and lose the plainness and power which they possess in the context of the Prolegomena. Here we are face to face with Kant as a man ; he gives us a personal reply, as if he were interviewed ; and while we grant the significance of transcendentalism and the truth of many of his observations and deductions, we can at the same time understand how Le arrived at errors. We can lay our finger on the very spot where he went astray, and I cannot but wonder at the cour- age of this undaunted thinker who abided by the con- sequences of an apparently trivial fallacy, due to the neglect to investigate one feature of the problem to which he devoted many years of his life in profound reflexion and close study. Kant was puzzled that we could know anything a priori concerning the formal constitution of things. The celestial bodies obey laws which man develops out of his mind. That the highest (i. e., the most general or universal) laws of nature should happen to be the same as the highest (i. e., the formal) laws of the thinking mind, and yet should be of an indepen- dent origin, seemed absurd to Kant. He saw only 204 kant's philosophy. two possibilities ; either, he said, we have derived our formal knowledge from the things by experience, or we ourselves have put it into the things to which it really does not belong. The former possibility is ex- cluded, because, says Kant {Prolegomena, § 9), "The properties of a thing cannot migrate into my faculty of representation," while on the other hand the purely formal truths are not derived from experience, but produced by the mind as cognitions a priori. Thus, Kant accepts the other horn of the dilemma, declar- ing {Prolegomena, § 36) that our faculty of cognition does not conform to the objects, but contrariwise, that the objects conform to cognition. Objects, he claimed, do not in themselves possess form, but our mind is so constituted that it cannot help attributing form and everything formal to the object of our experience. IDEALITY NOT SUBJECTIVITY. Now, it is true that our purely formal notions of mathematical and logical truths are ideal (made of the stuff that ideas consist of), but being purely formal they are definitely determined, that is to say that, wherever the same constructions are made, either by the operations of other minds or of natural conditions in the facts of objective reality, they will be found, to be the same. Thus, our mental constructions can re- construct the processes and formations of nature, and we can learn to predetermine the course of natural events. Kant did not see that form might be a property of all existence and that, in that case, the purely formal in things would be of the same nature as the purely formal in man's mind. It is true that the properties rant's philosophy. 205 of things do not migrate from the objects into the sub- ject, but they make impressions upon the senses and these several impressions possess analogies to the qualities by which they are caused. The analogies between matter and sensation seem much more arbi- trary than those between the shapes of things and the outlines of our sense-images. Nevertheless even here we grant that the reduction of the latter to universal laws is purely subjective, for there are no laws, qua formulated laws, in the objective world, there are only uniformities. But if we understand by the term law a description of uniformities we must see at once that there are objective realities (or rather features of real- ity) corresponding to our correct notions of the sev- eral formal laws. If the uniformities of nature are not transferred to the mind directly, but if the purely formal con- cepts are developed independently of sense- experience a priori, how is it possible that the two present the v/onderful a:greement that puzzled Kant? Nature is throughout activity, and so is our exist- ence. Nature is constantly combining and separating ; we observe transformations; things move about; and their constituent parts change places. Similar ope- rations are inalienable functions of the mind. The subtlest analysis as well as the most complicated com- position and every investigation, be it ever so intri- cate, are mere combinations and separations, activi- ties given together with our existence. The arguments of Kant by which he proves the apriority of purely formal laws must be granted to be true. The source of all purely formal thought is the mind, and not sense- perceptions. They are ideal. But the mind has been built up by experience, viz., 2o6 kant's philosophy. by sense-impressions of different but definite forms, and the formal order of objective nature is the mould in which the mind has been formed. The brute can- not as yet analyse sensations into their forms and ma- terials, i. e., into the purely relational and the purely sensory features ; but man can ; and when he has ac- quired the power of abstraction he can build models of forms, exhausting the entire scope of all possible cases, and these models serve him as examples of the several analogous formations of nature. Accordingly, our mental constitution, though a subjective construc- tion, is built up with materials quarried from the formal uniformities of objective nature. Thus the spider undoubtedly weaves his web from his own bod- ily self, but the materials have first been deposited there by nature. Man's mind is not less than the spi- der's silken thread, produced by, and remaining a part and an expression of, that great All-Being in which all creatures live and move and have their being. There is this difference between the spider's web and formal thought : the former consists of matter, the pure forms of mathematical, logical, and other ideas are immaterial ; they are abstracts made of the purely relational features of sense-impressions. They are ideal, viz., mental pictures, and as such they are subjective. But they are not purely subjective. The sensory part of a retinal image is purely subjective, but the formal preserves in a reduced size the projec- tion of the shape of the object. Form belongs to the object as well as to its subjective image, and thus the subjective conception of form possesses an objective value. Everything ideal is subjective, but it need not be purely subjective. Because the rational is ideal, it by rant's philosophy. 207 no means follows that it is not, and cannot be, objec- tive. When we construct some purely formal configura- tion with our nature-given mental operations, it will be the same as any other construction which has been made in the same way, be it in the domain either of things or of other minds. Nature performs the same operations which appear in man's mental activity. Man being a part of existence, what is more natural than that his bodily and mental constitution partakes of the same form as all the other parts of the world that surrounds him? A great and important part of our knowledge con- sists of purely formal theorems ; they are a priori. And these purely formal theorems contain actual informa- tion concerning the formal aspect of the real world. And why? Because they are systematic reconstruc- tions of the formal features of reality by imitating operations of motion which take place throughout the universe. All formal theorems have a general application, hence, whenever applicable, they afford a priori in- formation and can be employed as a key to unlock the mysteries of the unknown. By the rule of three we calculate the distance from the earth to the sun, and map out the paths of the several celestial bodies. When Kant says: Our mind "dictates" certain laws to the objects of experience, he uses a wrong ex- pression or takes a poetical license seriously. The mind "dictates" nothing to reality. Reality includ- ing its form is such as it is independently of what we think it to be. That which Kant calls dictating is a mere determining, a des.cription, implying at the same 2o8 kant's philosophy. time a foretelling or predicting of natural events which (as we saw) is done by constructing in our mind anal- ogous models. The agreement between our model and reality proves only that the scheme on which the model has been constructed is correct; it does not prove that the model does any dictating. The model dictates as little to reality as a barometer dictates what air-pressure there is to be in the atmosphere. THE FORMAL AND THE SENSORY. While we must object to Kant's doctrine that everything ideal is subjective and that what is directly derived from the mind cannot be objective, we must not (with the Sensualists) place the formal and the sensual on the same level. Kant is right that space and time are not objects or things or entities ; they are forms, and as forms they possess the quality of being empty. There is no particularity about them anywhere. Thus, space is space anywhere ; it is not like matter, denser here and looser there; nor like energy, here intense, there weak. Considered in it- self, space is the mere potentiality of existence. It is a description of the condition of granting motion to move in all directions. Its very indifference and ab- sence of anything particular implies uniformity ; and thus the laws of potentiality (i. e., the qualities of possible forms) are mere schedules ; they are empty in themselves, but possess universal application.^ The formal aspect of reality is its suchness ; the material element is its thisness. All suchness can be 1 These truths hav'e been felt by philosophers of all nations, and it is sur- prising to find them in the writings of Lao Tze and the Buddhist scriptures in both of which the absence of materiality, the not-being, plays an impor- tant part and is endowed with religious sanctity. rant's philosophy. 2og formulated in general, and even in universal, descrip- tions ; all thisness is individual and particular. State- ments of a general nature, such as are formulated by employing the methods of formal thought, are not single and concrete facts, but omnipresent and eter- nal laws ; they are true or untrue, correct or incor- rect. Facts of thisness are always in a special time and in a special spot in space. They are definite nunc and hie, not a semper and ubique. They are not true or untrue, but real or unreal. The essential feature of things is their form ; for their form, which is their suchness, viz., their exter- nal shape as wejl as internal structure, constitutes their character, their soul, their spiritual, significance, making them what they are. Their thisness is their concrete presence which actualises the thing as a stubborn fact of the material universe. It is true that the sense-pictures in which the world is represented to us are subjective; they are appearances or phenomena; it is further true that these pictures are radically different from the things which they represent. The color-sensation red has no similarity (as Kant rightly observes) to the physi- cal qualities of Vermillion ; and physicists have suffi- ciently penetrated into the constitution of matter of any kind (though most of the problems remain still unsolved) to convince us that matter as it is in itself is radically different from the subjective picture as which it presents itself to the senses. But the scien- tist assumes form to be objective, and all the theories as- to the constitution of matter, in chemistry as well as in the several branches of physics, are based on the principle of eliminating the subjective element, that is to say. the properly sensory ingredients of our 2IO KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. experience, by reducing them to statements in purely formal terms, which is done by measuring, by count- ing, by weighing, by defining their proportions, by describing their shape and structure, by determining their relations ; and if we have succeeded in doing so, we claim to have understood the objective nature of things. How can Kant's statement be upheld, that the sensation red is not an objective quality of Ver- million ? Is it not because physics has taught us that difference of color depends upon a difference of wave- length in ether vibration ? Kant's argument is based upon a tacit but indispensable recognition of the ob- jectivity of form and formal qualities. Therefore, while granting that the sense-begotten world-picture of our intuition is subjective appear- ance (cf. footnote on page 232), we claim in contrast to Kant that its formal elements represent a feature that inheres in existence as the form of existence. In making form purely subjective, Kant changes — notwithstanding his protestations — all ideas, all thoughts, all science, into purely subjective conceits. He is more of an idealist than Berkeley. Science can be regarded as an objective method of cognition only if the laws of form are objective features of reality THE MORAL ASPECT. An incidental remark on the moral aspect of the contrast between the purely formal and the sensory would not seem out of place here. Man has risen from the sensual plane into the abstract realms of reason, and morality becomes possible only by man's ability to make general principles the basis of his actions. Thus it happens that at a certain period of man's develop- ment the sensory is regarded as the lower, and gen- KANT's philosophy. 211 eralisations with what they imply, ideals, maxims, abstract thought, as the higher. The sensory is thus discriminated against and even denounced as the en- emy of the spiritual. Hence the dualistic phase in the religious and philosophical evolution of mankind in which sensuality is branded as sin and salvation sought in asceticism, i. e., the mortification of the body. We must consider, however, that the contrast be- tween form and matter, general law and particular existence, the ideal and sensory, spirit and matter, does not imply a contradictory antithesis, let alone any hostility or exclusivity of the two. That the spir- itual, viz., the conception of the purely formal with reason and its generalisations, develops only on a higher plane, cannot be used to incriminate the sen- sory and the bodily. On the contrary, the spiritual justifies the sensory and points out the higher aims which it can attain. And how indispensable is the sensory in religion! Consider but love, so much insisted on by the preach- ers of almost all higher faiths. Is it not even in its present form a sentiment, i. e., a sensory emotion? The truth is that morality consists in the sanctifica- tion of the sensory, not in its eradication ; and sancti- fication means setting aside and devoting to a special purpose, to the exclusion of a general use. Particu- larity is the nature of bodily existence and particu- larity demands exclusiveness. Any general use of bodily functions will prostitute them. Reason, on the contrary, is meant for general use and can never suffer from a general application. Kant's conception of morality is based upon rea- son, to the exclusion of sentiment. Reason makes 212 KANt'S philosophy. action according to principles or maxims possible, and all those maxims are moral which can become universally established. Thus the basis of ethics is the golden rule, pronounced by Confucius, Christ, and other religious leaders of mankind. Lao-Tze says of the sage : "His methods invite requital. " ^ FORM BOTH SUBJECTIVE AND OBJECTIVE. We believe we have satisfactorily explained the problem of the a priori, of the purely formal, which puzzled Kant ; we have further shown how and why the laws of purely formal thought agree with the highest laws of nature ; why being devoid of particu- larity they are universal (implying necessity); and there remains only to be pointed out that the validity of science rests upon the assurance of the identity of the subjective and the objective laws of form. Form, being common to both domains, the objectivity of things and the subjectivity of the mind, serves as a bridge on which cognition can advance into the un- known realms of objective existence, and thus the formal sciences constitute our organ of cognition, the objective reliability of which depends upon form be- ing an objective feature of things. It goes without saying that all that Kant says concerning their infinity, uniqueness, universality, and necessity as being against the belief that space and time are objects or things holds good; it proves that they are forms. Yet though they must not be regarded as objects, they are objective ; they are the forms of intuition but also of the objects intuited. Further, what Kant says (relying on symmetry as in- I Tao-Teh-King, Chapter 30. kant's philosophy. 213 tuitively perceived) to prove that they are forms of intuitions and not concepts, holds as well tp prove that they are sighted forms of existence, not inter- nally hidden qualities of a stuffy, thingish nature to be distilled from sense-perception in the alembic of the observation before its existence can be known. It is true that the world as it appears to us is a sense- woven, subjective picture ; things as we perceive them are phenomena. Further, our concepts, including the world-conception of science, which is built up with the help of the purely formal laws of thought, is a mental construction ; they are noumena. Both worlds, that of sense and that of thought, are subjective; but they represent reality ; the senses picture the world in the beauteous glow of sensations, and the mind de- scribes it in the exact measures of formal determina- tions ; but the latter, if true, offers an objectively valid model of the constitution of things, explaining their suchness without, however, giving any information as to the nature of reality in itself, i. e., what matter is in itself ; whether it is eternal or not ; why it exists ; and if it came into being, or how it happened to orig- inate. It is obvious that things are not matter, but matter of a definite form; the form is cognisable, while matter is simply the indication of their concrete reality as objects in the objective world. SUBJECTIVE CONSTRUCTIONS OF OBJECTIVE VALIDITY. Kant in discriminating between empirical percep- tion (viz., the sense-impressions possessing only sub- jective validity) and experience (viz. , the product of sense-impressions worked out by the a priori methods of pure reason imparting to our judgments universal- 214 kant's philosophy. ity and necessity)^ goes far in refuting himself and his pet theory. He speaks of universality and necessity as the only means by which the subjective elements can become objectively valid. He claims, e. g., to "have, amply shown that they (the concepts of the pure understanding, causality, including also mathe- matics, etc.) and the theorems derived from them are firmly established a priori, or before all experience, and have their undoubted objective value, though only with regard to experience." If the concepts of the pure understanding have objective value, why are they not objective? Why must they be regarded as purely subjective? We grant the strength of Kant's argument that, being un- equivocally creations of the mind independent of sense-experience, or, as Kant calls them, a priori, they are subjective. But is not the question legiti- mate that they may be at once subjective and objec- tive? Kant disposes of this question too quickly, and here lies his mistake : instead of investigating how certain uniformities of law may be at once indigen- ously subjective, i. e., originated by purely mental operations, and at the same time objective, i. e., ac- tualised by the operations of material bodies in the concrete world of real existence, he jumps at the con- clusion that all things ideal are necessarily purely subjective. The ideal, viz., all that belongs to the realm of ideas, is subjective, but it has objective va- lidity, and that which gives it objective validity is the mind's power of forming universal and necessary judgments. In fact, the terms universal and neces- sary would have no sense if they were limited to the realm of subjectivity and if objective validity did not 1 Prolegomena^ g 2 ff. rant's philosophy. 215 imply true objectivity. Hence our aim is to explain tlje correspondence between the subjective and the objective, and we come to the conclusion that the a priori judgments are based upon the conditions of pure form, and form is a quality of the object as well as of the subject. Thus while Kant's doctrine implies that the forms of intuition (space and time) and the formal laws are a priori in the mind ; therefore they are purely subjective and the intuiting and thinking subject transfers them upon the objec- tive world ; our position is the reverse. What Kant calls a priori is purely formal ; there- fore the mind can produce its laws and theorems by purely mental operations, yet at the same time, being purely formal, they apply to objective reality as the formal conditions of all objects, and thus the opera- tions of objects, as far as their formal conditions are conce,rned, bear a close analogy to the a priori theo- rems. We construct the purely formal in our mind, but we do not create it. Nor are the propositions of mathematics a quality of space. We do not deduce the Pythagorean theorem from space, but we con- struct a right-angled triangle and investigate the re- sults of our construction. Accordingly the theorems thus evolved are products of our mental operations executed on conditions given in our space conception. There are no mathematical theorems in the stellar universe, but there are conditions in the starry heav- ens which make it possible to calculate distances or other relations with the help of arithmetical computa-~ tions and geometric constructions. And the condi- 2l6 rant's tHILOSOPHV. tions which make this possible can only be the objec- tivity of form implying that the a priori laws of subjective form as constructed in our mental models possess an objective validity. THE OBJECTIVE ANALOGUES OF MENTAL CON- STRUCTIONS. Zeno's paradox and the difficulties which Clifford found in the continuity conception of space, it seems to me, arise from a direct identification of the mental construction of space with the objective formal fea- tures of things that constitute what may be called ob- jective space. Objective space is an inherent quality of things as the relational of their parts and is not, as in subjective space, a construction. The path of a body can be represented by a mathematical line, and a line is infinitely divisible ; but for that reason it is not composed of infinite parts. Nor has a moving body to construct a line of an infinite number of in- finitely minute parts by adding them piecemeal. The mental analysis and construction of a line is different from traversing it. For moving over a definite stretch of ground it is not necessary to go through the pro- cess of separately adding the imaginary infinitely small parts of which it is supposed to consist and into which it may be divided. It has not actually been divided, it is only infinitely divisible. It is true that time (as time) is purely subjective, but there is a reality that corresponds to time. Time is the measure of motion. We count the running sand of the hour-glass, we divide the face of the sun-dial, we build a clock to determine the lapse of time. There is no time (as time) in the objective world, but there are motions, such as the revolutions of the rant's philosophy. 217 earth round its axis, or round the sun, and these mo- tions possess succession with definite duration, ren- dering time, viz., their determination, possible. Dura- tion with succession of events in the world of things is the objective equivalent of time. The measurement of time is a subjective device. The same is true of space as a conception of the extended world of things. There is no space concep- tion in things, but bodies are extended ; and their re- lation among themselves is an arrangement of in- numerable juxtapositions. Extension, juxtaposition, direction of motion, is the objective quality of things that corresponds to the purely mental concept of space. The untrained and philosophically crude man transfers subjective conceptions of things directly upon the objective world. He speaks of light and colors, of sounds, of time and numbers and things as existing outside of his mind ; but a close inspection of the origin of mind will teach us to discriminate be- tween sound and air waves, between colors and the cause of colors (produced by a commotion in the ether, — a reality whose .existence is directly imper- ceptible and can only be deduced indirectly by argu- ment). We shall learn by reflexion that geometrical lines are purely mental constructions, but that the paths of the stars possess qualities (viz., all those which depend upon purely formal conditions) that closely correspond to the conic sections of mathe- matics. Further, it becomes obvious that our division of the world into separate things is artificial, for things are only clusters of predicates which impress us as being units. The truth is that the world is so consti- 2i8 kant's philosophy. tuted as to render a perfect separation impossible. Things, are in a perpetual flux, and the limits between them are arbitrary. As the whole atmosphere and its pressure belong to our lungs, so the gravity of the sun is an integral part of the weight of the earth. Thus we can truly say that there are no separate things ex- cept in our minds where they are artificial divisions invented for the practical purpose of describing the world, of mapping out its parts, of comprehending its actions and having a means of adjusting ourselves to our surroundings. Logic is purely mental, but there is something in the objective world that tallies with logic ; we call it natural law, but the term law is misleading. There are no laws in nature, but only uniformities resulting from the condition that the purely formal is the same everywhere and that the same formal conditions will produce the same formal effects. Purely formal laws are; universally valid only as purely formal laws. Twice two will be four in all arithmetical systems of any possible rational being, and the statement is universally valid so far as pure forms are concerned. If we deal with actualities pos- sessed of additional qualities where multiplication ceases to have its strict mathematical sense, the state- ment will no longer be tenable. The accumulation of power on a definite occasion may have results that cannot be calculated by addition or multiplication. The associated wealth of twice two millions may far exceed four millions; and twice one half will never be one when we deal with living organisms. All this is conceded. Ideal operations are purely mental and as such subjective, but for all that they possess objec- tive validity which implies that there are objective KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. 219 features exhibiting close analogies, by being products of a fundamental sameness of conditions. This funda- mental sameness is the universality of form which is common to both the domain of the objective world and the ideal realm of the mind, the thinking subject. There are neither categories nor classes in the ob- jective world, but the different modes of existence are classified by sentient beings and the scheme of the classification is the result. A reflexion upon our modes of thought objectifies them as modes of existence. The Platonic ideas, i. e. , the eternal types of the vari- ous beings, do not possess a concrete existence as do, e. g., the moulds of a potter, but there are uniformi- ties among the living forms which are obviously ap- parent. The doctrine of evolution proves that the lines of division between the types of beings are not so distinct in reality as they seem to be, and before a strictly scientific inspection they fade away as imag- inary ; yet they remain and are indispensable for our method of classification ; and the unities which they represent justify us in speaking of objective features as corresponding to the mental conception of Platonic ideas. THE ORIGIN OF GENERALISATIONS. The sense-impressions of things are registered ac- cording to their difference of form. Every sense-im- pression runs along in the groove prepared for it by a former sense-impression. Thus the same is registered with the same, and similar ones are correlated. The result is a systematisation of sensory impressions, and the relations that obtain in this system which is built up in the natural course of growth, may appropriately be compared to the pigeon-holes of a methodically 220 KANT'S philosophy. arranged cabinet. The difference between the cabinet with pigeon-holes and the human mind is this, that the former is artificial, the latter natural. The human mind with its rationality has been developed accord- ing to mechanical law and the classification of sense- impressions is done by it as automatically as the dis- tribution of the different letters in a type-distributing machine. Our ideas, our names of things, our system of classification is purely subjective, but there is an ob- jective analogue of the eternal types, which consists in the uniformities of all possible formations. This is true of living creatures as well as of machines and other concepts of human fancy. In the domain of invention we know very well that the inventor some- times .creates a combination of parts never actual- ised before on earth ; but the inventor is a finder : he is as much a discoverer as Columbus who found a new continent, or the scientist who succeeds in formu- lating an unknown law. America existed before Co- lumbus, the law of gravitation held good before New- ton, and the idea of a steam engine was a realisable combination before James Watts. It is a feature of objective existence that certain functions can be per- formed in perfectly definite interrelations. Such con- ditions which are actualised by a certain combination and disappear as soon as the combination is destroyed, are the objective features in things which justify the subjective idea of unities finding expression in con- cepts of things and beings. THE IDEAS OF PURE REASON. Kant grants the objective applicabihty of the cate- gories but he denies the validity of the ideas of pure KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. 221 reason, especially the cosmological, the psychological, and the theological idea. We are unable to follow Kant and are inclined to consider his three ideas of Pure Reason in the same light as time and space and the categories. The concept of unity is not a mere assumption but it has its correspondent analogue in reality' and has its practical use; only we must be- ware of treating unities as concrete objectivities, as separate and discrete entities, as things in themselves which have an objective existence apart from and in- dependently of their constituent parts. Thus the soul of man is as real on the assumption of an ego entity as on the theory of its denial. Life is as true whether or not vitalism can be established. The world is a great interrelated system, whether or not the uniform- ities of nature are called laws. There is a creation of the world, a formation of its life, a dispensation of its destinies, taking place, whether or not this ulti- mate norm of being be called God ; the facts of the cosmic order remain the same on the assumptions of both theism and atheism. But obviously, this deci- sion is not an endorsement of Kant's antinomies, but an explanation of his reasons for formulating them. While we grant that there is a reality correspond- ing to Kant's three ideas of pure reason, we do not mean to say that there is a God such as the crude Re- lief of an untrained mind represents him to be, nor further that there is a soul such as it is assumed to exist in the annals of superstition, nor finally that the crude notions of a cosmos, the limits of the world or its infinitude, its composition, its determinedness, and IThus not only all organisms are unities, but also steam-engines, dy- namos, or any machinery that would not work unless it were constructed of interacting parts in a definite way. 222 KANT'S philosophy. its absolute existence should be such as abstract rea- son might arbitrarily construct : we only mean to say that there are factors in life which caused man to con- struct such mental images or ideas as are called God, soul, and world. The ideas may be wrong, but the factors which produced them are real, and the duty devolves upon theology, psychology, and cosmology to eliminate error and bring out the truth. My objection to Kant's doctrine is not an objection to his terminology nor to idealism in general. We may form our world-view in an idealistic as well as a realistic nomenclature. Object may mean either the sense-woven picture or the outside thing which it sig- nifies. We may say that the objective world is ideal, for such it is, meaning by objects the things as we see them. We may say that the objective world is real, meaning by objects the actual things represented in our sense-images. The nomenclature of a philosoph- ical system is important but it is arbitrary. We may criticise it as impractical, but we cannot on its account reject a philosophy as untrue. REALISM OR IDETALISM. We object to Kant's doctrine of limiting form to the subject and thus denying the objective value of the ideal. We may define terms as we please but we must remain consistent. If the objects are ideal, I gladly grant that the forms of the objects are ideal ; but for all that, being forms of the objects, they are objective, as much as the objects themselves. The sense-woven pictures of things, though sub- jective images, are the realities of life, and our con- cepts of things are symbols of them in terms of their formal features expressed according to schedules rant's philosophy. 223 which we construct a priori. Time and space, the forms of our sense- world (of our Anschauung), accord- ingly are as real as these things, and I cannot say that the things themselves are real while the forms of things are purely ideal, i. e., not real. Schopenhauer, a one-sided but nevertheless one of the most prominent and faithful disciples of Kant, de- fends Kantian idealism against the misinterpretations of the so-called realists in these sentences : " In spite of all that one may say, nothing is so persistently and ever anew misunderstood ^5 Idealism, because it is interpreted as meaning that one denies the empirical reality of the external world. Upon this rests the perpetual return to the appeal to com- mon sense, which appears in many forms and guises ; for example, as an ' irresistible conviction ' in the Scotch school, or as Jacobi's faith in the reality of the external world. The external world by no means presents itself, as Jacobi declares, upon credit, and is accepted by us upon trust and faith. It presents itself as that which it is, and performs directly what it promises. " ' THE SUBJECT AS ITS OWN OBJECT. The quarrel between the idealists so called and the realists of Jacobi's stamp is purely a question of termi- nology. It is a vicious circle to ask whether the real is real; the question is, "What do we understand by real ? " Now we agree with Kant in accepting An- schauung as real. Our perceptions are the data of experience, they are the facts of life about which there is no quibbling and the question of unreality originates only in the realm of abstract thought, viz., in the do- main of interpretation. Perceptions are classified ; perceptions of the same kind are subsumed under the general conception of their class and if a perception is misinterpreted, our notion concerning it is errone- IFrom Schopenhauer's The World as Will and Idea, 224 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. ous. An after-image is as real as the original per- ception, but it is called an illusion when it suggests the presence of an object; in other words when its cause is misinterpreted. Perceptions accordingly are what we define as real, and space and time are, abstractly stated, the forms of perception. Time and space, accordingly, are as real as perceptions. Now we may ask what are the objects of the per- ceptions, defining objects this time not as the sense- woven images of our perception inside our senses, but as the external presences which are supposed to cause them. Since it is impossible here to enter into a detailed epistemological discussion of the subject, we state the answer for brevity's sake dogmatically as follows: The objects (viz., the external presences which are supposed to cause perceptions) are, ulti- mately, i. e., in their inmost constitution, of the same nature as are the perceptions themselves. The per- ceptions in their totality are called the subject — which is a sentient body, an intricate organism consisting of different organs of sense and a superadded organ of thought for preserving the sense-images, collating them, classifying them, and interpreting them. We are a system of perceptions and impulses, guided by memories and , thoughts, but we represent ourselves in our own perception as a body in time and space. Thus our representation of ourselves is our self-per- ception, i. e., a representation of the subject as its own object, and our self-perception is as real as are perceptions in general. Succession of sense-impres- sions and reactions thereupon, accordingly, form part and parcel of our subject as its own object ; and in the same way, juxtaposition of organs is an attribute of kant's philosophy. 225 our self, not as it is as a subject in itself, but of our self as it represents itself as its own object. Other objects are in the same predicament and partake of the same nature. If time and space are the forms of the objectified subject, viz., of our own bodily exist- ence we have good reasons to ascribe objectivity to the facts from which the ideas of time and space are derived, viz., to extension and succession. THE OBJECTIVE ORIGIN OF SPACE AND TIME. It is true that the factors which generate in the mind our conceptions of time and space, together with the entire formal aspect of being, lie in the subject, in the sentient thinking being, but they lie not in the ab- stract subject in itself, not in the subjectivity of the subject, not in the quality of the subject which re- mains when all other qualities, i. e., the objective features of its own actualisation as a concrete being, are omitted by the process of abstraction, i. e., when they have been cancelled in thought. The subject in itself will be found to be an empty generalisation which contains nothing but a product of our analysis of perception, the bare idea of the perceiving in con- trast to the perceived. It contains nothing either a priori or a posteriori ; merely itself, the shadow of a thing. But the actual subject, which is an object in the objective world, exists somewhere in space and in a given time. It moves, i. e., it changes its position. It consists of juxtaposed organs and its experiences exhibit a definite succession, each act having its own definite duration. Therefore we do not hesitate, when drawing a line of demarcation between the subjective and the objective features of the thinking subject, to include its form together with its bodily objectivation 226 rant's philosophy. in the realm of objectivity. In this way it happens that time and space may be called subjective, because the objectified subject finds them a priori in itself, but their ultimate root lies in the domain of objectivity, and we can therefore just as well call them objective, because they are the forms of the objective world and originate in the subject only because it is an object belonging to the objective world. UNIVERSALITY DUE TO SYSTEMATISATION. Kant was puzzled mainly by the subjective aprio- rity of the laws of time and space and of all other for- mal relations, but this puzzling apriority is, closely considered, nothing but their general applicability to all possible experience, which is due to the fact that all formal relations admit of systematisation. Formal possibilities can be exhausted and purely formal state- ments apply to all pure forms. Hence they possess universality, and universality admits of no exception, hence it implies necessity, which involves a priori ap- plicability. It is true (as Kant says) that purely formal knowl- edge is empty ; but we know at the same time that the purely formal knowledge gives system to the em- pirical, to the sense-given facts of our experience. If we could not classify sense-impressions, they would remain a useless chaos, and human reason would not have developed. Kant expresses this truth by say- ing that the sensory impressions without the guidance of the purely formal are blind. But as the formative norms of the objective world shape things and make them such as they are, our formal cognition classifies sense-impression according to their forms and thus makes a knowledge of objects Kant's philosophy. 227 possible. Our formal cognition is not the cause of the objective uniformities (as Kant suggests) but one of their applications only, being, as it were, their own reflexion in the consciousness of a sentient being. By being systematised in the shape of formulas, they ap- ply a priori to experience and become in this way a key, with the help of which we can unlock the closed doors of the mysteries of nature and decipher the riddles of the universe. THE REAL AND THE SUPERREAL. We may call the eternal norms of existence which condition the formation of things "being" or "San" and the concrete actualisation of the types of being their "becoming," Werden or Dasein. We become acquainted with the norms of existence, part of which ■ are formulated as natural laws, by abstraction and generalisation, but for that reason they are not mere glittering generalities, abstract nonentities, or unreal inventions, but significant features of objective exist- ence, depicting not accidental but necessary uniformi- ties. While we concede that the world of becoming is real, we must grant that the realm of being is super- real. Both Sein and Werden, Being and Becoming, are real ; but the reality of the two is different in kind. The latter's reality is actualisation, the reality of the* former is eternality. Thus the former is immutable, the latter a perpetual flux. The fleeting realities of sense are definite objects in the objective world, but the norms of eternal being are the formative factors which shape them. Obviously the eternal norms of existence, which are identical with the purely formal laws constituting the cosmic order, though not material facts, are the 228 kant's philosophy. most efiective presences of the world. They are not only real, they are superreal. They remain the same whether realised or not in the actual world. They produce the cosmic order, render the rise of rational beings possible, they are the condition of the intelli- gibility of things, they are the prototype of mind and spirituality, they are the corner-stone of both science and ethics and constitute Kant's mundus intelligibilis — the realm of spiritual being ; Swedenborg's sphere of spirits, of angels, and archangels; the kingdom of God, to be realised on earth ; yea, God himself, for God is all these norms in their totality and systematic unity. In Lao-Tze's philosophy.it is the eternal Tao, the world-reason or primordial Logos. In Buddhist metaphysics it corresponds to Afvaghosha's Tatha- gatagarbha, i. e., the womb of Buddhahood and the origin of all things; to Amitsibha, the source of all light and wisdom, and also to the deathless, the un- create, the non-corporeal existence {arApd), the Nir- vana of the older Buddhists. NOUMENA. The data of experience are sensations, or sense- perceptions, which represent themselves as images of things in time and space. The sensory element of the images, which is conditioned by the material com- position of the sentient subject, is purely subjective and need not be uniform. Thus we know that colors are perceived differently by different eyes ; the color- blind see the world like a steel-engraving, or rather a wash-picture, gray in gray. To the red-blind red ap- pears green, to the green-blind red appears dark yel- low and green pale yellow. If all men were color- blind, the gray image would have to be regarded as Kant's philosophy. ^29 normal. The forms of things, too, are conditioned to. some extent by the material composition of our sense- organs, as much so as the picture on the sensitive plate of a photographer's camera depends upon the ,lens. Further, we see not things as they are, but as they are projected according to the laws of perspec- tive. But we can from the given data of the projected images and additional considerations of other data of experience reconstruct the .form and structure of things as they are in space and of the events as they and their accelerations take place in time. This con- struction, of things is called in Kant's terminology things as creations of thought, or noumena, and the noumena are intended as models of the objects them- selves, for they mean to depict things in their objec- tive nature, as they are after the elimination of all subjective elements of cognition. Accordingly nou- mena (as noumena) are scientific notions, products of reasoning, and subjective in a higher degree even than sense-perceptions. They are the interpretations of the sense- perceptions and are as such ideal, i. e., representations not things. But they represent things as they are, independent of the senses of the sentient subject. Noumena would be unmeaning, if they did not represent objective realities, if they were purely fictitious, if they did not portray the things as objects in the objective world. We may fitly call the realities for whose designation noumena (i. e., scientific con- cepts) have been invented objects, or more definitely, objects in themselves. Jhey constitute the realm of experience, and time and space are the generalised modes of their existence by which we determine their formal qualities. Noth- ing is real in the sense of concrete existence, except 230 rant's philosophy. it be in time and space. Accordingly time and space (though not objects but mere forms) are objective qualities of things, and without time and space con- crete things cease to be concretely real and become either mere ideas or nonentities. We may with Kant distinguish between thing and thing in itself and may understand by the latter the eternal foundation of the thing, its metaphysical raison d'etre, whatever that may mean (either its Platonic idea, its eternal type, or the Schopenhauerian con- ception of its "will to be," or the general and abstract idea of its existence), but under all conditions space and time belong (as Kant says) to the things as ap- pearances, viz., the things as objects in the objective world which implies (the contrary to that which Kant says) that they are not purely subjective, but objec- tive. THE OBJECTIVITY OF SPACE AND TIME. Now we may call the perpetual flux of concrete objects "appearance," and the domain of eternal being ' ' the real things " : in that case the real things come to appearance by becoming actual in time and space. In this sense we agree with Kant, that time and space are real for our experience, thpugh not for our experience alone, but for any experience. Every sentient sub- ject, in so far as it is sentient, every individual man, is not a subject pure and simple, but an actualised subject, an objectified thing, for all acts of cognition are acts of an objective significance, taking place in the domain of objective existence, as an interrelation between two or several objects. One party to this interrelation (viz., my bodily organisation) happens to be the sentient and thinking subject, but that alters kant's philosophy. 231 nothing in the case, for all its actions take place in time, and the concrete corporeality of its organs is somewhere in space. Again therefore we come to the conclusion that space and time appertain (as Kant says) to the appearances of things. They appertain to the subject, not in itself, but to the appearance of the subject, viz., to its objectivation ; accordingly they are (as opposed to what Kant says) objective, not purely subjective, and may be called subjective only in a spe- cial sense, viz., in so far as they appertain to the objec- tified subject, which, however, is an object like any other object in the objective world. The subject does not transfer time and space into the objective world, but anything that becomes actual thereby makes its appearance in time and space. In other words. Time, Space, and all the norms of purely formal relations, are the forms of any possible concrete existence. Whatever the metaphysical raison d'etre of things may be, the "why there is anything," reality, when, ac- tualised, represents itself objectively as being in time and space. The thinking subject does not represent things in time and space, but in so far as it is an actual object in the objective world, it represents itself (i. e., it appears) in time and space. So do all other things : hence the concurrence of the formal notions of the objectified subject with the formal conditions of the objectified things of our surroundings. Kant says (§520 = "Space and time together with the appear- ances in them are nothing existing in themselves and outside of my representations but are them- selves only modes of representation. " ^ 1 It is very strange that the same Kant who says that space (viz., exten- sion) is only a mode of representation declares (in § 2) that the sentence 232 kant's philosophy. He should have said (and here we use purposely Kant's own term " appearance " i) : Time and space are modes of appearance, viz., of self-representation. Being modes of appearance they are inside every subject in so far as it has made its appearance in the objective world. They are in all objects as those re- lational features which determine the juxtaposition of things. It is the actualised appearance that needs extension (i. e., space) for the distribution of the sev- eral organs of the thinking subject. We feel our limbs as being in different places, as moving about, as touch- ing, as separating, etc., and these feelings are parts of our soul : they are the inside of the subject which is objectified (or comes to appearance) in our bodily existence. Our body (viz., our self as appearance) is extended, and the space, needed for it, is limited by the skin. The remainder of extension which accomo- dates the other objects of the surrounding world is designated as the outside ; and if the extension within our skin is real, the outside must also be real. Both together constitute space. "bodies are extended" is analytical; accordingly he regards extension or space as the essential feature of a thing, of an object. Why then does he not recognise Space as the mark of objectivism, which might have led him to concede the objective nature of the operations of the thinking subject? lAppearance or phenomenon means originally the picture of objects as it appears on the retina and generally all the data of sense-perception ; but the word is used in contrast to noumenon, or abstract thought, denoting the concrete object as it is given to the senses distinguished from its general and abstract idea. Thus, the world of appearances means the concrete world of objects that affect our senses, though the term might be interpreted, to stand for the retinal picture as a mere subjective image in contrast to the material world of objective reality. Indeed, there are authors who do use the word in the latter sense, while in the minds of most readers the two conceptions are mixed and the former is imperceptibly affected by the latter. It would not be difficult to point out what an interminable confusion the use of this word has produced in philosophy. rant's philosophy. 233 When Kant denies that space and time are objec- tive, he becomes confused and self-contradictory. For he would either have to say that space and time are limited within the boundary of the body of the think- ing subject, which is nonsense, or he must attribute them to the subject as a thing in itself, which contra- dicts his own theory according to which time and space do not refer to things in themselves, but to ap- pearances only. Thus even from Kant's own premises and when employing his own terminology the theory becomes untenable that space and time are purely subjective attributes. Their very nature is objectivity, and if objects are appearances, time and space as the forms of all appearance must be regarded as features of existence which in their very nature are objective. It appears that Kant was not sufficiently careful to distinguish between space-conception, which is sub- jective, and space itself, which, being the juxtaposi- tion of things and their parts, is objective. Space- conception originates from within sentient organisms, viz., in the mind, by its adjustment to the surround- ing world through the use of its organs. Its ultimate sources are of a physiological nature consisting in the motion of the limbs and especially the eyes. This is what Ernst Mach calls physiological space.^ Mathe- matical space is a higher abstraction than physiolo- gical space. In mathematical space all incidental fea- tures, the differences of right and left, of high and low, etc., are dropped, and space is regarded as homa- loidal, viz., as constituted alike throughout. The homaloidality of space is the simplest way of depriv- ing space of all positive attributes, of rendering it the ISee Ernst Mach's article "On Physiological, as Distinguished from Geometrical Space," in The Monist, Vol. XI., No. 3., April, 1901. 234 kant's philosophy. "same" throughout. At any rate it is a mental con- struction as much as the idea of a straight line and all geometrical figures. The construction has been made without any concrete building material, with mere men- tal operations, simply by proceeding on the assump- tion of logical consistency, where the same procedure yields the same result. That other space construc- tions are possible need not concern us here. At any rate, our space-conception is built up in the thinking subject by operations of which it is possessed in its capacity as an object moving about in the objective world. Our space-conception is a noumenon (a pro- duct of thought), and like all noumena, it is intended to describe features of objective reality; and these features of objective reality intended to be delineated in our space-conception is objective space — viz., the extension of the world and of its parts, the juxtaposi- tion of bodies, and the range of directions all around every moving point. Our space-conception is subjective, but for that reason space itself remains as objective as any object in space. Moreover, the data from which our space- conception has been constructed are as objective as are all the acts and facts of our bodily organism. THINGS IN THEMSELVES. Where, then, are the things in themselves, which, according to Kant, remain unintelligible ? There is a truth in the idea that our mind is so constituted as to transfer to the phenomenal world its a priori notions of time and space and its thought- forms. The world of our senses which appears to us as the objective world that surrounds us, is truly a construction of our organs of sense ; the construction kant's philosophy. 235 is as necessary as is for example the reflexion of a pic- ture in a mirror ; things in themselves remain outside. In this sense Kant's doctrine of idealism is undeniably true. But Kant goes further in saying that things in themselves, meaning things viewed independently of our sense-perception, do not partake of form and are ■ therefore unknowable. But what is knowledge if not a correct description of things? Things are mirrored in our eyes, and abstract notions are formed to rep- resent them in mental symbols. It would be absurd to expect that things should bodily migrate into our heads. It is the ideal of science to eliminate the subjec- tivity of the thinking subject and construct a world- picture in terms of formal laws, by the guidance of the several sciences of formal thought; this is the noumenal world, the world of thought ; but this nou- menal world is nothing but a picture (more or less ac- curate) of the objective world as things are indepen- dently of sense-perception. .Here everything changes into motion of a definite form ; the rainbow with the warm beauty of its colors becomes the reflexion of ether waves of a definite angle with definite wave- lengths. Though the noumenon is a subjective con- struction, it is an analogue of the objects as they are in themselves, describing their suchness. Accord- ingly, this would be a cognition of things in them- selves, for Kant defines things in themselves as the ground which determines our sensibility to have sense- perceptions, or briefly the causes of phenomena. Cognition is nothing more nor less than the con- struction of analogous symbols of things by which we can know their nature for the sake of determining 236 rant's philosophy. their action, thus enabling us to direct the course of events by adaptation partly of ourselves to conditions, partly of our surroundings to our wants. Unless we denounce science as a vagary of the human mind, we must grant thaf in spite of the shortcomings of the individual scientist, the ideal of science (which con- sists in describing things in their objective existence) is justified, and can be more and more realised. And what becomes of things in themselves? If things in themselves cannot be described with the assistance of formal thoughts, they degenerate into dim chimerical and contradictory notions, such as unextended bodies, or substances without quali- ties, or unmaterial entities, or causes which remain outside the pale of causation. The conception of things in themselves is a vagary of pre-Kantian metaphysics, the empty shell of which, as an irrational quantity, transcendent and unknow- able, was by some mishap suffered to remain in Kant's philosophy. If things in themselves mean objective things, viz., things as they are, independently of our sensi- bility, we must deny, that they are unknowable. If they mean that which constitutes the essential char- acter of the things, making them what they are, they will be seen to be determined by their suchness ; they are what Plato called the eternal types of being, or ideas; and we ought to call them not "things in themselves," but "forms in themselves." Schopenhauer interprets the Kantian conception of things in themselves as the metaphysical raison d^etre of their existence, but he denies that its nature cannot be known and discovers its manifestation in "the Will." According to him it is the Will that kant's philosophy. 237 makes every one what he is, and Schopenhauer's Will is not the physiological process of willing, the con- scious effort of causing an idea to pass into an act, but the tendency to motion such as it inheres in all exist- ence, in the stone as gravity, in chemicals as affinity, in sentient beings as desire. He expressly excludes that feature which distinguishes will from unconscious motions, viz., intelligence, and speaks of the blind Will. The blind Will is practically deified by him, for it is supposed to be above time and space and credited with creative omnipotence. In reality it is nothing but the widest generalisation of motion. Clifford offers another interpretation of the terni '•thing in itself," viz., the sentiency of organised be-, ings, constituting their subjectivity and corresponding to what in man is called his "soul." But, again, this subjectivity, the spiritual inside, is always the sentient accompaniment of the organisation, the bodily out- side ; and its nature can be determined by studying the visible exponents of its objective expression in which it is realised. Thus Clifford's things in them- selves are as little unknowable as Schopenhauer's. Agnosticism, the egg-shell of metaphysicism, pre- vented Rant from taking the last step suggested by his doctrine of the necessity and universality of the laws of pure form. He lost himself in contradictions and became satisfied with his statement of the antino- mies of pure reason, according to which we may prove with equal plausibility that God exists or that he does not. THE GOD PROBLEM. If Kant had followed the course which we here, under the guidance of the principles laid out by him, 238 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY. have briefly sketched out, his philosophy not only would have become less artificial and remained in close touch with the natural sciences, but it would also have helped theology to develop purer, truer, and nobler religious ideals. With the egg-shell of agnosticism on its back, Kantism was satisfied with the existing state of beliefs and things ; not that Kant endorsed the various irrationalities of the Christianity of his day, the literalism of dogma, the implicit belief in the very text of the Bible, the Creation story, pa- ternalism of the Prussian State Church, etc. ; he criti- cised them occasionally in mild terms ; but instead of going to work to purify religion (not in the narrow and prosaic spirit of his disciples, the Rationalists, but with due reverence for the poetry of dogma and legend, and at the same time with a consideration for the practical needs of the heart): he simply justified them in general terms on account of their moral use- fulness in his Critique of Practical Reason. As an instance, let us point out his unsatisfactory solution of the God problem. Kant accepted in his conception of God the tradi- tional views of the Church, and discussed it as one of the several metaphysical notions, the result being that the idea is pronounced to be transcendent, and we can with equally plausible reasons both affirm and deny his existence. It is one of Kant's four antino- mies of Pure Reason. But God unknown to pure reason and not discoverable in the domain of experi- ence and resuscitated only as a postulate of practical reason is a poor substitute even for the mythological conception of the god of the uneducated masses. An hypothetical go^ cannot help; he is sicklied over with the pale cast of thought ; he is hot real ; he is rant's philosophy. 239 paralysed. I am far from blaming Kant, who has done so much for philosophy, for not having done more and performed a reformer's work for religion ; but I would suggest that he might as well from his own principles have investigated the nature of formal laws, which in the subjective sphere of reason appear as transcendental ideas, and have come to the conclu- sion that a truer God-conception could be derived therefrom, which then would commend itself as the higher ideal. The popular notions of the several re- ligions and also of a primitive theology are dim fore- shadowings of a scientific God-conception, the purity of which is increasing with the progress of scientific truth. The world-order, that purely formal law in the objective world whic^i forms and creates, shaping the stellar universe (as Kant set forth so forcibly in his General Natural History and Theory of the Heavens), and revealing itself in the social development of man as the power that makes for righteousness, must have made its influence felt in the life of mankind at the very beginning, and would naturally, according to the practical needs of the intelligence of the successive ages, assume the shape of a conception of God, more or less crude in the beginning, and more or less phil- osophical in the mind of the wise. The world-order, this superpersonal spirituality that acts as the divine dispensation in the world, is hyperphysical (I pur- posely avoid the much-abused term "supernatural," but I might as well say supernatural). It is intrinsi- calljr necessary, it is omnipresent, it is unerring in the truth of its various applications which form as it were a grand system, comparable to the articulated differ- entiation of a spiritual organism, — a personality; it 240 kant's philosophy. is as unfailingly just as the law of causation is rigid ; and every God-conception is but an attempt at com- prehending its moral significance. The fetishist's notion of a power to which he must conform is not absolutely wrong. It contains a truth, but is alloyed with superstitions. The idea of think- ing of God as a king of kings, as a supreme judge, is more advanced, inasmuch as God henceforth repre- sents a moral maxim, the principle of justice in the world. The God-father idea of Christianity surpasses the theology of the prophets of the Old Testament, but it, too, falls short of the truth in all its perfection. All we have to do is to be serious in scientifically thinking the divine attributes of omnipresence, of eternality, of infinitude, of omniscience, of all-justice, of the irrefragability of law in the physical, the psy- chical, and the social spheres of existence, which, re- flected in the instructive growth of his conscience, become to man the moral norm of life, and the ulti- mate authority of conduct. Kant cited the religious notions of the theology of his age before the tribunal of pure reason and dis- missed the suit as offering no issue, leaving the ques- tion in the state in which he had found it. He would have served his age better had. he worked out the philosophical significance of the idea of God, on the basis of the practical significance of his Transcenden- talism ; he would then, instead of leaving the problem unsolved, have boldly propounded the gospel of the superpersonal God as coming, not to destroy the old theology, but to fulfil its yearnings and hopes, with- out in the least doing violence to the demands of crit- icism and scientific exactness. SUPPLEMENTARY MATERIALS FOR THE STUDY OF KANT'S LIFE AND PHILOSOPHY. INTRODUCTORY NOTE. THESE materials, culled from Kantian literature, are intended as specimens of the various opinions which prevail concern- ing Kant, and have been arranged and added to this book for the purpose of enabling the student to study Kant in the impressions ■which he made upon the philosophical public. The selection has at the same time been offered with the intention of giving a brief synopsis of Kant's work, at least so far as the systematic con- struction, or Ausbau, of his transcendental criticism is concerned. It is understood that Kant's merits as a thinker and inquirer are not limited to metaphysics, but it would have led us too far, and would have swelled the book to too bulky a size, without doing justice to the subject, if we had also attempted to consider here Kant's re- searches in physics, mechanics, astronomy, and the other natural sciences. That Kant had a clear idea, not only of evolution and of the descent of man from lower forms of life, but also of the dif- ficulties of the evolution theory, is well attested by many remark- able passages, collected by Fritz Schultze'. We have only to add that we have selected Windelband as a representative historian of philosophy, in preference, say, to Erd- mann and Ueberweg, solely because of the terseness of his state- ments. Schwegler is a Hegelian, Weber an Alsatian under French influence. Lange represents the large class' of agnostics who grant that materialism is untenable as a philosophy but deem it to be the best working hypothesis in science. Schopenhauer is one of the most original disciples of Kant, and set up a philosophy of his own, conceiving the world under the double aspect of Will and Idea. He hates Hegel and all ' ' school-philosophy, '' saying that he himself, the true philosopher, lives for philosophy, while the pro- fessors appointed to teach philosophy live on philosophy. Heine IJCani und Darwin, e£n Beiirag ziir Geschichte der Entinickelungslehre Jena, 1873. 244 kant's life and philosophy. is peculiarly interesting, being brilliant and cynical at the same time. He speaks sometimes as if he were an atheist, and again advocates a theism verging on pantheism. Theodore F. Wright's digest of Stiickenberg is cavilling and spiteful. His is the most unfavorable vievf of Kant, and we quote it on that account. Paul- sen's chronological table will be welcome as a useful synopsis of the data of Kant's life. f. c. KANT'S LIFE AND WRITINGS. (after winde'lband.') IMMANUEL KANT was born April 2Z, 1724, at Konigsberg, Prussia, the son of a saddler. He was educated at the Pietistic Collegium Fridericianum, and attended in 1740 the University of his native city to study theology ; but subjects of natural science and philosophy gradually attracted him. After concluding his studies, he became a private teacher in various families in the vicinity of KQnigsberg from 1746 to 1755 ; in the autumn of 1755 he habilitated as Privatdocent in the philosophical faculty of Konigs- berg University, and was made full Professor there in 1770. The cheerful, brilliant animation, and versatility of his middle years gave place with time to an earnest, rigorous conception of life and to the control of a strict consciousness of duty, which manifested itself in his unremitting labour upon his great philosophical task, in his masterful fulfilment of the duties of his academic profession, and in the inflexible rectitude of his life, which was not without a shade of the pedantic. The uniform course of his solitary and modest scholar's life was not disturbed by the brilliancy of the fame that fell upon his life's evening, and only transiently by the dark shadow that the hatred of orthodoxy, which had obtained control under Frederick William II. , threatened to cast upon his path by a prohibition of bis philosophy. He died from the weak- ness of old age on the izth of February, 1804. Kant's middle and later life and personality has been drawn most completely by Kuno Fischer ( Geschichte der neueren Philo- soj>hie. III. and IV., 3d ed., Munich, 1882); E. Arnoldt has treated of his youth and the first part of his activity as a teacher (Konigs- berg, 1882). See also J. H. W. Stuckenberg, Life of Kant (Lon- don, 1882). IHistory of Philosophy. Translated from the German by James H. Tufts, New York : Macmillan, 1893. Price 15. 00. This work is especially valuable as a comparative treatment of the history ol thought. 246 kant's life and philosophy. The change which was taking place in the philosopher toward the end of the seventh decade of the eighteenth century appears especially in his activity as a writer. His earlier " pre-critical " works are distinguished by easy-flowing, graceful presentation, and present themselves as admirable occasional writings of a man .of fine thought who is well versed in the world. His later works show the laboriousness of his thought and the pressure of the con- tending motifs, both in the form of the investigation, with its cir- cumstantial heaviness and artificial architectonic structure, and in the formation of his sentences, which are highly involved, and frequently interrupted by restriction. Minerva frightened away the graces ; but instead, the devout tone of deep thought and earnest conviction, which here and there rises to powerful pathos and weighty expression, hovers over his later writings. For Kant's theoretical development, the antithesis between the Leibnizo-Wolffian metaphysics and the Newtonian natural philos- ophy was at the beginning of decisive importance. The former had been brought to his attention at the University by Knutzen, the latter by Teske, and in his growing alienation from the philo- sophical school-system, his interest for natural science, to which for the time he seemed to desire to devote himself entirely, co- operated strongly. His first treatise, 1747, was entitled Thoughts u;pon the True Measure of Vis Viva, a controverted question be- tween Cartesian and Leibnizian physicists ; his great work upon the General Natural History and Theory of the Heavens was a natural science production of the first rank, and besides small articles, his promotion-treatise, De Igne (1755), which propounded a hypothesis as to imponderables, belongs here. His activity as a teacher also showed, even on into his later period, a preference for the subjects of natural sciences, especially for physical geography and anthropology. In theoretical philosophy Kant passed through many reversals (mancherlei Umkifpungen) of his standpoint. At the beginning (in the Physical Monadology) he had sought to adjust the opposi- tion between Leibniz and Newton, in their doctrine of space, by the ordinary distinction of things-in-themselves (which are to be known metaphysically), and phenomena, or things as they appear (which are to be investigated physically) ; he then (in the writings after 1760) attained to the insight that a metaphysics in the sense of rationalism is impossible, that philosophy and mathematics must have diametrically opposed methods, and that philosophy as the KANT'S LIFE AND PHILOSOPHY. 247 empirical knowledge of the given cannot step beyond the circle of experience. But while he allowed himself to be comforted by Voltaire and Rousseau for this falling away of metaphysical in- sight, through the instrumentality of the "natural feeling" for the right and holy, he was still working with Lambert at an improve- ment of the method of metaphysics, and when he found this, as he hoped, by the aid of Leibniz's Nouveaux Essais, he constructed in bold lines the mystico-dogmatic system of his Inaugural Dis- sertation. The progress from this point to the System of Criticism is obscure and controverted. For this development, and for the time in which he was influenced by Hume, as well as for the direction which that influence took, consult the following works : Fr. Michelis, Kant vor und nach lyyo (Braunsberg, 1871) ; Fr. Paulsen, Ver- such einer Entivictdungsgeschichte der JCantischen Erkennt- nisstheorie (L,ei-psic, 1875); A. Riehl, Geschichte und Methode des fhiloso^hischen Kriticismus (Leips. 1876) ; B. Erdmann, Kant's Kriticismus (Leips. 1878) ; W. Windelband, Die verschiedenen Phasen der Kantischen Lehre vom Ding-an-sich ( Vierteljahrs- schrift far ivissensctiaftliche Philoso^hie, 1876). Cf. also the writings by K. Dieterich on Kant's relation to Newton and Rous- seau under the title Die Kantische Philoso^hie in ihrer inneren Entwicklungsgeschichte , Freiburg i. B. 1885 ; also A. Wreschner, Ernst Plainer und Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Leipsic, 1893) ; E. Adickes, Kant-Studien (Kiel and Leipsic, 1895) ; F. Paulsen, Immanuel Kant (Stuttgart, 1898). For Kant on Evolu- tion, see P. Cams, Kant and S;pencer (Chicago, 1900). From the adjustment of the various tendencies of Kant's thought proceeded the "Doomsday-book" of German philosophy, the Critique of Pure Reason (Riga, 1781). It received a series of changes in the second edition (1787), and these became the objec, of very vigorous controversies after attention had been called to them by Schelling (W., V. 196) and Jacobi (W., II. 291). Cf. con- cerning this, the writings cited above. H. Vaihinger, Commentar zu Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Vol. I. , Stuttgart, 1887, Vol. II., 1892), has diligently collected the literature. Separate editions of the Kritik, by K. Kehrbach, upon the basis of the first edition, and by B. Erdmann and E. Adickes upon the basis of the second edition, have been published. There is an English translation of the Critique (2d ed.), by Meiklejohn, in the Bohn Library, and also one by Max MuUer 248 kant's life; and philosophy. (text of ist ed. with supplements giving changes of 2d ed.), Lond. 1881. We have further a Paraphrase and Commentary by Mahaffy and Bernard, 2d ed., Lond. and N. Y. 1889; and partial transla- tions in J. H. Stirling's Text-book to Kant, and in Watson's Selec- tions, Lond. and N. Y. 1888. This last contains also extracts from the ethical wrritings and from the Critique of Judgment. The additional main writings of Kant in his critical period are : Prolegomena zu einer jeden htinftigen Meta;physiJi, 1783; Grund- legung zur Metafhysik der Sitten, 1783 ; Metafhysische An- fangsgrilnde der Naturivissenschaft, 1783 ; Kritik der frah- tischen Vernunft, 1788; Kritik der Urtfieilskraft, 1790; Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft, 1793; Zum eTJuigen Frieden, 1793 ; Metafhysische AnfangsgrUnde der Rechts- und Tugendlehre, 1797 ; Der Streit der Fakultaten, 1798. There is an English translation of the Prolegomena, by Mahaffy and Bernard, Lond. and N. Y., 1889 ; of the Prolegomena and Metaphysical Foundation of Natural Science, by Bax, Bohn Library ; of the ethical writings, including the first part of the Religion tvithin the Bounds of Pure Reason, by T. K. Abbott, 4th ed., Lond. 1889; of the Critique of Judgment, by J. H. Bernard, Lond. and N. Y. 1892 ; of ^& Philosophy of Law , by W. Hastie, Edin. 1887 ; Principles of Politics, including the essay on Perpetual Peace, by W. Hastie, Edin. 1891 ; of Kant's Inaugural Dissertation, W. J. Eckoff, (New York, 1894). The contents of Kant's Essays and Treatises, 2 vols., Lond. 1798, is given in Ueberweg, II. 138 (Eng. tr.). Complete editions of his works have been prepared by K. Rosenkranz and F. W. Schubert (12 vols., Leips. 1833 ff.) ; by G. Hartenstein (10 vols., Leips. 1838 f. ; more recently 8 vols., Leips. 1867 £f.); and by J. v. Kirchmann (in the Philos. Biblioth.). They contain, besides his smaller articles, etc., his lectures upon logic, pedagogy, etc. , and his letters. A survey of all that has been writ- ten by Kant (including also the manuscript of the Transition from Metaphysics to Physics, which is without value for the inter- pretation of his critical system) is found in Ueberweg-Heinze, III, § 24 ; there, too, the voluminous literature is cited with great com- pleteness. Of this we can give here only a choice of the best and most instructive ; a survey of the more valuable literature, ar- ranged according to its material, is offered by the article Kant, by W. Windelband in Ersch und Gruber's Enc. The journal of Speculative Philosophy contains numerous articles upon Kant. KANT'S LIFE AND PHILOSOPHY. 249 We may mention also Adamson, The PhilosofJiy of Kant, Edin, 1879 ; art. Kant, in Enc. Brit. , by the same author ; arts, in Mind, Vol. VI., by J. Watson, and in Philos. Review, 1893, by J. G. Schurmann. — E. Adickes has published an exhaustive bibliography of the German literature in the Philos. Review, 1893 ff. THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON, AND THE CRITIQUE OF JUDGMENT. (after WEBER.') I. THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON.* ALTHOUGH the Critique of Pure Reason reduces us to a scepticism which is all the more absolute because it is rea- soned, proved, cientifically established, and legitimised, it would be a grave mistake to consider the sage of Koenigsberg as a sceptic in the traditional sense, and to impute to him a weakness for the mate- rialism of his age. Scepticism is the upshot of the Critique of Pure Reason; it is not, however, the ultimatum of Kantianism. To assert the contrary is completely to misunderstand the spirit of the philosophy of Kant and the final purpose of his critique. This is by no means hostile to the moral faith and its transcendent object, but wholly in its favor. It is, undoubtedly, not Kant's intention to "humiliate" reason, as TertuUian and Pascal had desired to do, but to assign to it its proper place among all our faculties, its true r61e in the complicated play of our spiritual life. Now, this place is, according to Kant, a subordinate one ; this function is re- gulative and modifying, not constitutive and creative. The Will, and not reason, forms the basis of our faculties and of things. that is the leading thought of Kantian philosophy. While reason becomes entangled in inevitalble antinomies and involves us in doubts, the will is the ally of faith, the source, and therefore, the natural guardian of our moral and religious beliefs. Observe that "i-VroTaWeher^s History of Pkilosophy, Translated by Frank Thilly. New York : Scribner*s. Price, 83.30. Weber's book is one of the clearest, con- cisest, and most readable of the histories of philosophies, 2H. Cohen, Kant's Begrilndung der Ethik, Berlin, 1877; E. Zeller, Ueher das Kantische Moralprincip, Berlin, 1880; J. G. Schurman, Kantian Ethics and the Ethics of Evolution, London, 1881; N. Vorier, Kant's Ethics, Chicago, 1886; F. W. FQrster, Der Entuuickelungsgang der Kantischen Ethik, etc., Ber- lin, 1894; Piinjer, Die Religionslehre Kant's, Jena, 1874. KANT S LIFE AND PHILOSOPHY. 25I Kant in no wise denies the existence of the thing-in-itself , of the soul, and of God, but only the possibility of proving the reality of these Ideas, by means of reasoning. True, he combats spirit- ualistic dogmatism, but the same blow that brings it down over- throws materialism ; and though he attacks theism, he likewise de- molishes the dogmatic pretensions of the atheists. What he combats to the utmost and pitilessly destroys is the dogmatism of theoretical reason, under whatever form it may present itself, whether as theism or atheism, spiritualism or materialism ; is its assumption of authority in the system of our faculties ; is the prejudice which attributes metaphysical capacity to the understanding, isolated from the Tvill and defending' on its ozun resources. By way of retaliation— an(l here he reveals the depth of his philosophic faith — he concedes a certain metaphysical capacity io practical reason, i. e,, to Tvill. Like the understanding, the will has its own character, its original forms, its particular legislation, a legislation which Kant calls "practical reason." In this new domain, the problems raised by the Critique of Pure Reason change in aspect ; doubts are dis- sipated, and uncertainties give way to practical certainty. The moral law differs essentially from physical law, as conceived by theoretical reason. Physical law is irresistible and inexorable ; the moral law does not compel, but bind ; hence it implies free- dom. Though freedom cannot be proved theoretically, it is not in the least doubtful to the will : it is a postulate of practical reason, an immediate fact of the moral consciousness.' Here arises one of the great difficulties with which philosophy is confronted : How can we reconcile the postulate of practical rea- son with the axiom of pure reason that every occurrence in the phenomenal order is a necessary effect, that the phenomenal world is governed by an absolute determinism? Kant, whose belief in free-will is no less ardent than his love of truth, cannot admit an absolute incompatibility between natural necessity and moral liberty. The conflict of reason and conscience, regarding freedom, can only be a seeming one ; it must be possible to resolve the an- tinomy without violating the rights of the intelligence or those of the will. The solution would, undoubtedly, be impossible, if the Cri- tique of Pure Reason absolutely denied liberty, but the fact is, it 1 Gnindlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, p. 80 (Rosenkranz) ; Kritik ttU$ti 3o^ann ^riebrid; JQattinoi} 1781. 266 kant's life and philosophy. longer giving vent to fierce wrath and vengeance, at least no longer thundering at every trifle. We have seen him migrate to Rome, the capital, where he abjures all national prejudices and proclaims the celestial equality of all nations, and with such fine phrases establishes an opposition to the old Jupiter, and intrigues ceaselessly till he attains supreme authority, and from the Capitol rules the city and the world, urbem et orbem. We have seen how, growing still more spiritualised, he becomes a loving father, a universal friend of man, a benefactor of the world, a philanthro- pist ; but all this could avail him nothing ! Hear ye not the bells resounding? Kneel down. They are bringing the sacraments to a dying god ! *. * * It is related that an Knglish mechanician, who had already in- vented the most ingenious machines, at last took it into his head to construct a man ; and that he succeeded. The work of his hands deported itself and acted quite like a human being ; it even contained within its leathern breast a sort of apparatus of human sentiment, differing not greatly from the habitual sentiments of Englishmen; it could communicate its emotions by articulate sounds, and the noise of wheels in its interior, of springs and es- capements, which was distinctly audible, reproduced the genuine English pronunciation. This automaton, in short, was an accom- plished gentleman, and nothing was wanting to render it com- pletely human except a soul. But the English mechanician had not the power to bestow on his work this soul, and the poor creature, having become conscious of its imperfection, tormented its creator day and night with supplication for a soul. This re- quest, daily repeated with growing urgency, became at last so in- supportable to the poor artist that he took to flight in order to es- cape from his own masterpiece. But the automaton also took the mail coach, pursued him over the whole continent, travelled in- cessantly at his heels, frequently overtook him, and then gnashed and growled in his ears. Give me a soul! These two figures may now be met with in every country, and he only who knows their peculiar relationship to each other can comprehend their unwonted haste and their haggard anxiety. But as soon as we are made aware of their strange relationship, we at once discover in them something of a general character ; we see how one portion of the English people is becoming weary of its mechanical existence, and is demanding a soul, whilst the other portion, tormented by such a KANT'S LIFE AND PHILOSOPHY. 267 request, is driven about in all directions, and that neither of them can endure matters at home any longer. The story is a terrible one. It is a fearful thing when the bodies we have created demand of us a soul ; but it is a far more dreadful, more terrible, more awful thing when we have created a soul, to hear that soul demanding of us a body, and to behold it pursuing us with this demand. The thought to which we have given birth is such a soul, and it leaves us no rest until we have endowed it with a body, until we have given it sensible reality. Thought strives to become action, the word to become flesh, and, marvellous to relate, man, like God in the Bible, needs only to ex- press his thought and the world takes form ; there is light or dark- ness ; the waters separate themselves from the dry land ; or it may even be that wild beasts are brought forth. The world is the sign- manual of the word. Mark this, ye proud men of action ; ye are nothing but un- conscious hodmen of the men of thought who, often in humblest stillness, have appointed you your inevitable task. Maximilian Robespierre was merely the hand of Jean Jacques Rousseau, the bloody hand that drew from the womb of time the body whose soul Rousseau had created. May not the restless anxiety that troubled the life of Jean Jacques have caused such stirrings within him that he already foreboded the kind of accoucheur that was needed to bring his thought living into the world ? Old Fontenelle may have been right when he said : "If I held all the truths of the universe in my hand, I would be very careful not to open it." I, for my part, think otherwise. If I held all the truths of the world in ray hand, I might perhaps beseech you in- stantly to cut off that hand ; but, in any case, I should not long hold it closed. I was not born to be a gaoler of thoughts ; by Heaven ! I would set them free. What though they were to in- carnate themselves in the most hazardous realities, what though they were to range through all lands like a mad bacchanalian pro- cession, what though they were to crush with their thyrsus our most innocent flowers, what though they were to invade our hos- pitals and chase from his bed the old sick world — my heart would bleed, no doubt, and I myself would sufier thereby ! For alas ! I too am part of this old sick world, and the poet says truly, one may mock at his crutches yet not be able to walk any better for that. I am the most grievously sick of you all, and am the more to be pitied since I know what health is ; but you do not know it, you 268 kant's life and philosophy. whoa I envy ; you are capable of dying without perceiving your dying condition. Yea, many of ydu are already long since dead, though maintaining that your real life is just beginning. When I try to dispel such a delusion, then you are angry with me and rail at me, and, more horrible still, the dead rush upon and mock at me, and more loathsome to me than their insults is the smell of their putrefaction. Hence, ye spectres ! I am about to speak of a man whose mere name has the iriighf of an exorcism ; I speak of Immanuel Kant. It is said that night-wandering spirits are filled with terror at sight of the headsman's axe. With what mighty fear, then, must they be stricken when there is held up to them Kant's Critique of Pure Reason ! This is the sword that slew deism in Ger- many. To speak frankly, you French have been tame and moderate compared with us Germans. At most, you cfould but kill a king, and he had a:lready lost his head before you guillotined him. For accompaniment to such deed you must needs cause such a drum- ming and shrieking and stamping of feet that the whole universe trembled. To compare Maximilian Robespierre with Immanuel Kant is to coAfer too high an honour upon the former. Maximil- lian Robespierre, the great citizen cif the Rue Saint Honor^, had, it is true, his sudden attacks of destructiveness when it was a ques- tion of the monarchy, and his frame was violently convulsed when the fit of re'gicidal epilepsy was on ; but as soon as it came to be a question about the Supreme Being, he wiped the white froth from his lips, washed the blood from his hands, donned his blue Sunday coat with silver buttons, and stuck a nosegay in the bosom of his broad vest. The history of Immanuel Kant's life is difficult to portray, for he had neither life nor history. He led a mechanical, regular almost abstract bachelor existence in a little retired street of Ko- nigsbefg, an old town on the north eastern frontier of Germany. I do not believe that the great clock of the cathedral performed in a more passionless and methodical manner its daily routine than did its townsman, Immanuel Kant. Rising in the morning, coSee- drinking, writing, reading lectures, dining, walking, everything had its appointed time, and the neighbours knew that it was exactly half-p&sft three o'clock when Immanuel Kant stepped forth from his house in his grey, tight-fitting coat, with his Spanish cane in his hand, and betook himself to the little linden avenUe called after kant's life and philosophy. 269 him to this day the "Philosopher's Walk." Summer and winter he walked up and down it eight times, and when the weather was dull or heavy clouds prognosticated rain, the townspeople beheld his servant, the old Lampe, trudging anxiously behind him with a big umbrella under his arm, like an image of Providence. What a strange contrast did this man's outward life present to his destructive, world-annihilating thoughts ! In sooth, bad the citizens of Konigsberg bad the least presentiment of the full signifi- cance of his ideas, they would have felt a far more awful dread at the presence of this man than at the sight of an executioner, who caU but kill the body. But the worthy folk saw in him nothing more than a Professor of Philosophy, and as be passed at his customary hour, they greeted him in a friendly manner and set their watches by him. But though Immanuel Kant, the arch-destroyer in the realm of thought, far surpassed in terrorism Maximilian Robespierre, he had many similarities with the latter, which induce a comparison between the two men. In the first place, we find in both the same inexorable, keen, poesyless, sober integrity. We likewise find in both the same talent of suspicion, only that in the one it manifested itself in the direction of thought and was called criticism, whilst in the other it was directed against mankind and was styled re- publican virtue. But both presented in the highest degree the type of the narrow-minded citizen. Nature had destined them for weighing out coffee and sugar, but fate decided that they should weigh out other things, and into the scales of the one it laid a king, into the scales of the other a God And they both gave the correct weight ! The Critique of Pure Reason is Kant's principal work; and as none of his other writings is of equal importance, in speak- ing of it we must give it the right of preference. This book ap- peared in 1781, but, as already said, did not become generally known till 1789. At the time of its publication it was quite over- looked, except for two insignificant notices, and it was not till a later period that public attention was directed to this great book by the articles of Schiitz, Schultz, and Reinhold. The cause of this tardy recognition undoubtedly lay in the unusual form and bad style in which the work is written. As regards his style, Kant merits severer censure than any other philosopher, more especially when we compare this with his former and better manner of writ- ing. The recently published collection of his minor works con- 270 rant's life and philosophy. tains his first attempts, and we are surprised to find in these an ex- cellent and often very witty style. These little treatises were trilled forth while their author ruminated over his great work. There is a gleefulness about them like that of a soldier tranquilly arming for a combat in which he promises himself certain victory. Espe- cially remarkable amongst them are his Universal Natural His- tory and Theory of the Heavens, composed as early as 1753 ; Observations on the Emotions of the Sublime and Beautiful written ten years later ; and Dreams of a Ghostseer, full of admirable humour after the manner of the French essay. Kant's wit as displayed in these pamphlets is of quite a peculiar sort. The wit clings to the thought, and in spite of its tenuity is thus enabled to reach a satisfactory height. Without such support wit, be it ever so robust, cannot be successful ; like a vine-tendril wanting a prop, it can only creep along the ground to rot there with all its most precious fruits. But why did Kant write his Critique of Pure Reason in such a colourless, dry, packing-paper style ? I fancy that, having rejected the mathematical form of the Cartesio-Leibnitzo-Wolfian school, he feared that science might lose something of its dignity by expressing itself in light, attractive, and agreeable tones. He therefore gave it a stiff, abstract form, which coldly repelled all familiarity on the part of intellects of the lower order. He wished haughtily to separate himself from the popular philosophers of his time, who aimed at the most citizen-like clearness, and so clothed his thoughts in a courtly and frigid official dialect. Herein he shows himself a true philistine. But it might also be that Kant needed for the carefully measured march of his ideas a language similarly precise, and that he was not in a position to create a better. It is only genius that has a new word for a new thought. Immanuel Kant, however, was no genius. Conscious of this de- fect, Kant, like the worthy Maximilian, showed himself all the more mistrustful of genius, and went so far as to maintain, in his Critique of the Faculty of Judgment, that genius has no busi- ness with scientific thought, and that its action ought to be rele- gated to the domain of art. The heavy, buckram style of Kant's chief work has been the source of much mischief ; for brainless imitators aped him in his external form, and hence arose amongst us the superstition that no one can be a philosopher who writes well. The mathematical form, however, could not, after the days of Kant, reappear in kant's life and philosophy. 271 philosophy ; he has mercilessly passed sentence of death upon it in his Critique of Pure Reason. The mathematical form in phi- losophy, he says, is good for nothing save the building of houses of cards, in the same way that the philosophic form in mathe- matics produces nothing but twaddle, for in philosophy there can be no definitions such as those in mathematics, where the defini- tions are not discursive but intuitive, that is to say, capable of be- ing demonstrated by inspection ; whilst what are called definitions in philosophy are only tentatively, hypothetically put forth, the real definition appearing only at the close, as the result. How comes it that philosophers display so strong a predilec- tion for the mathematical form ? This predilection dates from the time of Pythagoras, who designated the principles of things by numbers. This was the idea of a genius : all that is sensible and finite is stripped off in a number, and yet it denotes something determined, and the relation of this thing to another determined thing, which last, designated in turn by a number, receives the same insensible and infinite character. In this respect numbers re- semble ideas that preserve the same character and relation to one another. We can indicate by numbers in a very striking manner ideas, as they are produced in our mind and in nature ; but the number still remains the sign of the idea, it is not the idea itself. The master is always conscious of this distinction, but the scholar forgets it, and transmits to other scholars at second hand merely a numerical hieroglyph, dead ciphers, which are repeated with par- rot-like scholastic pride, but of which the living significance is lost. This applies likewise to the other methods of mathematical de- monstration. The intellect in its eternal mobility suffers no arrest ; and just as little can it be fixed down by lines, triangles, squares, and circles, as by numbers. Thought can neither be calculated nor measured. As my chief duty is to facilitate in France the study of German philosophy, I always dwell most strongly on the external difficulties that are apt to dismay a stranger who has not already been made aware of them. I would draw the special attention of those who desire to make Frenchmen acquainted with Kant to the fact, that it is possible to abstract from his philosophy that portion which serves merely to refute the absurdities of the Wolfian philosophy. This polemic, constantly reappearing, will only tend to produce confusion in the minds of Frenchmen, and can be of no utility to them. 272 kant's life and philosophy. The Critique of Pure Reason is, as I have said, Kant's principal work, and his other writings are in a measure super- fluous, or may at least be considered as commentaries. The social importance that attaches to his chief work will be apparent from what follows. The philosophers who preceded Kant reflected, doubtless, on the origin of our cognitions, and followed, as we have seen, two different routes, according to their view of ideas as a priori or as a posteriori; but concerning the faculty of knowing, concerning the extent and limits of this faculty, they occupied themselves less. Now this was the task that Kant set before himself ; he submitted the faculty of knowing to a merciless investigation, he sounded all the depths of this faculty, he ascertained all its limits. In this in- vestigation he ceftainly discovered that about many things, where- with formerly we supposed ourselves to be most intimately ac- quainted, we can know nothing. This was very rhortifying ; but it has always been useful to know of what things we can know noth- ing. He who warns us against a useless journey performs as great a service for us as be who points out to us the true path. Kant proves to us that we know nothing about things as they are in and by themselves, but that we have a knowledge of them only in so far as they are reflected in our minds. We are therefore just like the prisoners of whose condition Plato draws such an afSicting picture in the seventh book of his Republic. These wretched be- ings, chained neck and thigh in such a manner that they cannot turn their heads about, are seated within a roofless prison, into which there comes from above a certain amount of light. This light, however, is the light from a fire, the flame of which rises up behind them, and indeed is separated from them only by a little wall. Along the outer side of this wall are walking men bearing all sorts of statues, images in wood and stone, and conversing with one another. Now the pofir prisoners can see nothing of these men, who are not tall enough to overtop the wall ; and of the statues,' which rise above the wall, they see only the shadxjws flit- ting along the side of the wall opposite them. The shadows, how- ever, they take for real objects, and, deceived by the echo of their prison, believe that it is the shadoi*s that are conversing. With the appearance of Kant former systems of philosophy, which had merely sniffed about the external aspect of things, as- semblitig and classifying their characteristics, ceased to exist. Kant led investigation back to the human intellect, and inquired what KANT'S LIFE AND PHILOSOPHY. 273 the latter had to reveal. Not without reason, therefore, did he compare his philosophy to the method of Copernicus. Formerly, when men conceived the world as standing still, and the sun as re- volving round it, astronomical calculations failed to agree ac- curately. But when Copernicus made the sun stand still and the earth revolve round it, behold ! everything accorded admirably. So formerly reason, like the sun, moved round the universe of phenomena, and sought to throw light upon it. But Kant bade reason, the sun, stand still, and the universe of phenomena now, turns round, and is illuminated the moment it comes within the region of the intellectual orb. These few words regarding the task that presented itself to Kant will 5u£5ce to show that I consider that section of his book wherein he treats of phenomena and noumena as the most im- portant part, as the central point, of his philosophy. Kant, in effect, distinguishes between the appearances of things and things themselves. As we can know nothing of objects except in so far as they manifest themselves to us through their appearance, and as objects do not exhibit themselves to us as they are in and by them- selves, Kant gives the name phenomena to objects as they appear to us, and noumena to objects as they are in themselves. We know things, therefore, only as phenomena; we cannot know them as noumena. The latter are purely problematic ; we can neither say that they exist nor that they do not exist. The word noumena has been correlated with the word phenomena merely to enable us to speak of things in so far as they are cognisable by us, without oc- cupying our judgment about things that are not cognisable by us. Kant did not therefore, as do many teachers whom I will not name, make a distinction of objects into phenomena and noumena, into things that for us exist and into things that for us do not exist. This would be an Irish bull in philosophy. He wished merely to express a notion of limitation. God, according to Kant, is a noumenon. As a result of his argu- ment, this ideal and transcendental being, hitherto called God, is a mere fiction. It has arisen from a natural illusion. Kant shows that we can know nothing regarding this noumenon, regarding God, and that all reasonable proof of his existence is impossible. The words of Dante, "Leave all hope behind ! " may be inscribed over this portion of the Critique of Pure Season. My readers will, I think, gladly exempt me from attempting a popular elucidation of that portion of bis work in which Kant 274 kant's life and philosophy. treats ' ' of the arguments of speculative reason in favour of the ex- istence of a Supreme Being. " Although the formal refutation of these arguments occupies but a small space, and is not taken in hand till the second part of the book is reached, there is already a very evident intention of leading up to this refutation, which forms one of the main points of the work. It connects itself with the Critique of all Speculative Theology, wherein the last phan- toms of deism are put to flight. I cannot help remarking that Kant, in attacking the three principal kinds of evidence in favour of the existence of God, namely, the ontological, the cosmological, and the physico-theological, whilst successful, according to my opinion, in refuting the latter two, fails with regard to the first. I am not aware whether the above terms are understood in this country, and I therefore quote the passage from the Critique of Pure Reason in which Kant formulates the distinction between them. ' ' There are but three kinds of proof possible to speculative reason of the existence of God. All the routes that may be selected with this end in view start, either from definite experience and the peculiar properties of the external world, as revealed by experi- ence, and ascend from it according to the laws of causality up to the supreme cause above the world ; or, they rest merely on an indefinite experience, as, for example, on an existence or being of some kind or other ; or, lastly, they make an abstraction from all experience, and arrive at a conclusion entirely a priori from pure ideas of the existence of the supreme cause. The first of these is the physico-theological proof, the second the cosmological, and the third the ontological. Other proofs there are none, nor can other proofs exist." After repeated and careful study of Kant's chief work, I fan- cied myself able to recognise everywhere visible in it his polemic against these proofs of the existence of God ; and of this polemic I might speak at greater length were I not restrained by a religious sentiment. The mere discussion by any one of the existence of God causes me to feel a strange disquietude, an uneasy dread such as I once experienced in visiting New Bedlam in London, when, for a moment losing sight of my guide, I was surrounded by mad- men. " God is all that is," and doubt of His existence is doubt of life itself, it is death. The more blameworthy any dispute regarding the existence of God may be, the more praiseworthy is meditation on the nature of Kant's life and philosophy. 275 God. Such meditation is a true worship of God ; the soul is thereby detached from the perishable and finite, and attains to consciousness of innate love and of the harmony of the universe. It is this consciousness that sends a thrill through the heart of the emotional man in the act of prayer or in the contemplation of the sacred symbols ; and the thinker realises this holy fervour in the exercise of that sublime faculty of the mind called reason, a faculty whose highest function is to inquire into the nature of God. Men of specially religious temperament concern themselves with this problem from childhood upwards ; they are mysteriously troubled about it even at the first dawnings of reason. The author of these pages is most joyfully conscious of having possessed this early primitive religious feeling, and it has never forsaken him. God was always the beginning and the end of all my thoughts. If I now inquire : What is God ? what is his nature ? — as a little child I had already inquired : How is God ? what is he like ? In that childish time I could gaze upwards at the sky during whole days, and was sadly vexed at evening because I never caught a glimpse of God's most holy countenance, but saw only the grey silly gri- maces of the clouds. I was quite puzzled over the astronomical lore with which in the "enlightenment period" even the youngest children were tormented, and there was no end to my amazement on learning that all those thousand millions of stars were spheres as large and as beautiful as our own earth, and that over all this glittering throng of worlds a single God ruled. I recollect once seeing God in a dream far above in the most distant firmament. He was looking contentedly out of a little window in the sky, a devout hoary-headed being with a small Jewish beard, and he was scattering forth myriads of seed-corns, which, as they fell from heaven, burst open in the infinitude of space, and expanded to vast dimensions till they became actual, radiant, blossoming, peopled worlds, each one as large as our own globe. I could never forget this countenance, and often in dreams I used to see the cheerful- looking old man sprinkling forth the world-seeds from his little window in the sky ; once I even saw him clucking like our maid when she threw down for the hens their barley. I could only see how the falling seed-corns expanded into great shining orbs : but the great hens that may by chance have been waiting about with eager open bills to be fed with the falling orbs I could not see. You smile, dear reader, at the notion of the big hens. Yet this childish notion is not so very different from the view of the most 276 KANT'S LIFE AND PHILOSOPHY. advanced deists. In the attempt to provide a conception of an ex- tra-mundane God, orient and Occident have exhausted themselves in hyperbole. The imagination of deists has, however, vainly tor- mented itself with the infinitude of time and space. It is here that their impotence, the inadequacy of their cosmology, and the unten- ableness of their explanation of the nature of God becomes fully ap- parent. We are not greatly distressed, therefore, at beholding the subversion of their explanation. Kant has actually wrought this affliction upon them by refuting their demonstration of the' exist- ence of God. Nor would the vindication of the ontological proof specially benefit deism, for this proof is equally available for pantheism. To render my meaning more intelligible, I may remark that the ontological proof is the one employed by Descartes, and that long before his time, in the Middle Ages, Anselm of Canterbury had ex- pressed it in the form of an affecting prayer. Indeed, St. Augustine may be said to have already made use of the ontological proof in the second book of his work, De Libera Arhitrio. I refrain, as I have said, from all popular discussion of Kant's polemic against these proofs. Let it suffice to give an assurance that since his time deism has vanished from the realm of specu- lative reason. It may, perhaps, be several centuries yet before this melancholy notice of decease gets universally bruited about; we, however, have long since put on mourning. De Profundis! You fancy, then, that we may now go home ! By my life, no 1 there is yet a piece to be played; after the tragedy comes the farce. Up to this point Immanuel Kant has pursued the path of inexorable philosophy ; he has stormed heaven and put the whole garrison to the edge of the sword ; the ontological, cosmological, and physico-theological bodyguards lie there lifeless; Deity itself, deprived of demonstration, has succumbed ; there is now no All- mercifulness, no fatherly kindness, no other-world reward for re- nunciation in this world, the immortality of the soul lies in its last agony — you can hear its groans and death-rattle ; and old Lampe is standing by with his umbrella under his arm, an afflicted spec- tator of the scene, tears and sweat-drops of terror dropping from his countenance. Then Immanuel Kant relents and shows that he is not merely a great philosopher but also a good man ; he reflects, and half good-naturedly, half ironically, he says : ' ' Old Lampe must have a God, otherwise the poor fellow can never be happy. Now, man ought to be happy in this world ; practical reason says kant's life and philosophy. 277 so ; — well, I am quite willing that practical reason should also guarantee the existence of God." As the result of this argument Kant distingnishes between the theoretical reason and the practi- cal reason, and by means of the latter, as with a magician's wand, he revivifies deism, which theoretical reason had killed. But is it not conceivable that Kant brought about this resur- rection, not merely for the sake of old Lampe, but through fear of the police ? Or did he act from sincere conviction ? Was not his object in destroying all evidence for the existence of God to show us how embarrassing it might be to know nothing about God ? In doing so, he acted almost as sagely as a Westphalian friend of mine, who smashed all the lanterns in the Grohnder Street in Got- tingen, and then proceeded to deliver to us in the dark a long lecture on the practical necessity of lanterns, which he had the- oretically broken in order to show how, without them, we CQuld see nothing. I have already said that on its appearance the Critique of Pure Reason did not cause the slightest sensation, and it was not till several years later, after certain clear-sighted philosophers had written elucidations of it, that public attention was aroused regard- ing the book. In the year 1789, however, nothing else was talked of in Germany but the philosophy of Kant, about which were poured forth in abundance commentaries, chrestomathies, inter- pretations, estimates, apologies, and so forth. We need only glance through the first philosophic catalogue at hand, and the innumer- able works having reference to Kant will amply testify to the in- tellectual movement that originated with this single man. In some it exhibited itself as an ardent enthusiasm, in others as an acrid loathing, in many as a gaping curiosity regarding the result of this intellectual revolution. We had popular riots in the world of thought, just as you had in the material world, and over the dem- olition of ancient dogmatism we grew as excited as you did at the Storming of the Bastille. There was also but a handful of old pen- sioners left for the defence of dogmatism, that is, the philosophy of Wolf. It was a revolution, and one not wanting in horrors. Amongst the party of the past, the really good Christians showed least indignation at these horrors. Yea, they desired even greater, in order that the measure of iniquity might be full, and the coun- ter-revolution be more speedily accomplished as a necessary re- action. We bad pessimists in philosophy as you had in politics. As in France there were people who maintained that Robespierre 278 kant's life and philosophy. was the agent of Pitt, with us there were many who went so far in their wilful blindness as to persuade themselves that Kant was in secret alliance with them, and that he had destroyed all philo- sophic proofs of the existence of God merely in order to convince the world that man can never arrive at a knowledge of God by the help of reason, and must therefore hold to revealed religion. Kant brought about this great intellectual movement less by the subject-matter of his writings than by the critical spirit that pervaded them, a spirit that now began to force its way into all sciences. It laid hold of all constituted authority. Even poetry did not escape its influence. Schiller, for example, was a strong Kantist, and his artistic views are impregnated with the spirit of the philosophy of Kant. By reason of its dry, abstract character, this philosophy was eminently hurtful to polite literature and the fine arts. Fortunately it did not interfere in the art of cookery. The German people is not easily set in motion ; but let it be once forced into any path and it will follow it to its termination with the most dogged perseverance. Thus we exhibited our char- acter in matters of religion, thus also we now acted in philosophy. Shall we continue to advance as consistently in politics ? Germany was drawn into the path of philosophy by Kant, and philosophy became a national cause. A brilliant troop of great thinkers suddenly sprang up on German soil, as if called into be- ing by magical art. If German philosophy should some day find, as the French revolution has found, its Thiers and its Mignet, its history will afford as remarkable reading as the works of these authors. Germans will study it with pride, and Frenchmen with admiration. THE KANTIAN PHILOSOPHY. (after ARTHUR SCHOPENHAUER.') KANT'S greatest merit is the distinction of the phenomenon from the thing in itself, based upon the proof that between things and us there still always stands the intellect, so that they cannot be known as they may be in themselves. He was led into this path through Locke (see Prolegomena, § 13, Note 2). The latter had shown that the secondary qualities of things, such as sound, smell, color, hardness, softness, smoothness, and the like, as founded on the affections of the senses, do not belong to the objective body, to the thing in itself. To this he attributed only the primary qualities, i. e., such as only presuppose space and im- penetrability; thus extension, figure, solidity, number, mobility-. But this easily discovered Lockeian distinction was, as it were, only a youthful introduction to the distinction of Kant. The lat- ter, starting from an incomparably higher standpoint, explains all that Locke had accepted as primary qualities, i. e., qualities of the thing in itself, as also belonging only to its phenomenal ap- pearance in our faculty of apprehension, and this just because the conditions of this faculty, space, time and causality, are known by ■asafriori. Thus Locke had abstracted from the thing in itself the share which the organs of sense have in its phenomenal ap- pearance; Kant, however, further abstracted the share of the brain-functions (though not under that name). Thus the distinc- tion between the phenomenon and the thing in itself now received an infinitely greater significance and a very much deeper meaning. For this end be was obliged to take in hand the important separa- tion of our a priori from our a posteriori knowledge which be- fore him had never been carried out with adequate strictness and completeness, nor with distinct consciousness. Accordingly this iProm the World as Will and Idea. Trans, by Haldane and Kemp. 3 vols. Third edition. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Triibner & Co. i8g6. 28o kant's life and philosophy. now became the principal subject of his profound investigations Now here we would at once remark that Kant's philosophy has a threefold relation to that of his predecessors. First, as we have just seen, to the philosophy of Locke, confirming and extending it ; secondly, to that of Hume, correcting and making use of it, a relation which is most distinctly expressed in the Prolegomena (that most beautiful and comprehensible of all Kant's important writings, which is far too little read, for it facilitates immensely the study of his philosophy); thirdly, a decidedly polemical and destructive relation to the Leibnitz- Wolfian philosophy. All three systems ought to be known before one proceeds to the study of the Kantian philosophy. Now as Kant's separation of the plienome- non from the thing in itself, arrived at in the manner explained above, far surpassed all that preceded it in the depth and thought- fulness of its conception, it was also exceedingly important in its results. For in it he propounded, quite originally, in a perfectly new way, found from a new side and on a new path, the same truth which Plato never wearies of repeating, and in his language generally expresses thus : This world which appears to the senses has no true being, but only a ceaseless becoming ; it is, and it is not, and its comprehension is not so much knowledge as illusion. This is also what he expresses mythically at the beginning of the seventh book of the Republic, which is the most important passage in all his writings. He says: "Men, firmly chained in a dark cave, see neither the true original light nor real things, but only the meagre light of the fire in the cave and the shadows of real things which pass by the fire behind their backs ; yet they think the shadows are the reality, and the determining of the succession of these shadows is true wisdom." The same truth, again quite differently presented, is also a leading doctrine of the Vedas and Pnranas, the doctrine of M4yi, by which really nothing else is understood than what Kant calls the phenomenon in opposition to the thing in itself ; for the work of MSyd is said to be just this visible world in which we are, a summoned enchantment, an in- constant appearance without true being, like an optical illusion or a dream, a veil which surrounds human consciousness, something of which it is equally false and true to say that it is and that it is not. But Kant not only expressed the same doctrine in a com- pletely new and original way, but raised it to the position of proved and indisputable truth by means of the calmest and most tempe- rate exposition ; while both Plato and the Indian philosophers had rant's life and philosophy. 281 founded their assertions merely upon a general perception of the world, had advanced them as the direct utterance of their con- sciousness, and presented them rather mythically and poetically than philosophically and distinctly. In this respect they stand to Kant in the same relation as the Pythagoreans Hicetas, Philolaus, and Aristarchus, who already asserted the movement of the earth round the fixed sun, stand to Copernicus. Such distinct knowl- edge and calm, thoughtful exposition of this dream-like nature of the whole world is really the basis of the whole Kantian philoso- phy ; it is its soul and its greatest merit. He accomplished this by taking to pieces the whole machinery of our intellect by means of which the pihantasmagoria of the objective world is brought about, and presenting it in detail with marvellous insight and abil- ity. All earlier Western philosophy, appearing in comparison with- the Kantian unspeakably clumsy, had failed to recognise that truth, and had therefore always spoken just as if in a dream. Kant first awakened it suddenly out of this dream ; therefore the last sleepers (Mendelssohn) called him the "all-destroyer." He showed that the laws which reign with inviolable necessity in ex- istence, i. e., in experience generally, are not to he applied to de- duce and explain existence itself; that thus the validity of these laws is only relative, i. e. , only arises after existence ; the world of experience in general is already established and present ; that consequently these laws cannot be our guide when we come to the explanation of the existence of the world and of ourselves. All earlier Western philosophers had imagined that these laws, ac- cording to which the phenomena are combined, and all of which — time and space, as well as causality and inference — I comprehend under the expression "the principle of sufficient reason, " — were absolute laws conditioned by nothing, ceternce veritates ; that the world itself existed only in consequence of and in conformity with them ; and therefore that under their guidance the whole riddle of the world must be capable of solution. The assumptions made for this purpose, which Kant criticises under the name of the Ideas of the reason, only served to raise the mere phenomenon, the work of M&yd, the shadow world of Plato, to the one highest reality, to put it in the place of the inmost and true being of things, and thereby to make the real knowledge of this impossible; that is, in a word, to send the dreamers still more soundly to sleep. Kant exhibited these laws, and therefore the whole world, as conditioned by the form of knowledge belonging to the subject ; from which it 282 kant's life and philosophy. followed, that however far one carried investigation and reasoning under the guidance of these laws, yet in the principal matter, i. e., in knowledge of the nature of the world in itself and outside the idea, no step in advance was made, but one only moved like a squirrel in its wheel. Thus, all the dogmatists may be compared to persons who supposed that if they only went straight on long enough they would come to the end of the world ; but Kant then circumnavigated the world and showed that, because it is round, one cannot get out of it by horizontal movement, but that yet by perpendicular movement this is perhaps not impossible. We may also say that Kant's doctrine affords the insight that we must seek the end and beginning of the world, not without, but within us. AN ESTIMATE, OF KANT BY A SWEDEN- BORGIAN. (after THEODORE F. WRIGHT.') IN all bis metaphysical work Kant was not pursuing a religious course and was in fact becoming less and less of a Christian. He was, however, no more contracted in his philosophical view of the limits of reason than he was in all the ways of his life. " His body was extremely emaciated, and at last it was dried like a pot- sherd," said one who knew him well. He was hollow-chested, and one shoulder was too low. Not five feet high, his bones were small and weak, and his muscles still weaker (Stiickenburg, p. 93). He had strong prejudice against the Jews {Jbid., p. 116). He took no interest in other philosophers {Ibid., p. 124). Though he wrote much in the field of theology, he knew almost nothing of theolo- gians (Ibid., p. 359). He did not answer letters {Ibid., p. 127). He held to bis views after rebutting facts were shown him, and would contradict foreigners who spoke of their own countries in a manner to interfere with his preconceived ideas {Ibid., p. 141). He lived in the same small city with his two sisters, yet did not speak to them for twenty-five years because of their inferior posi- tion (Ibid., p. 182). He spoke contemptuously of women and was especially hostile to those of any mental power (Ibid. , p. 784). One of his jokes was that there can be no women in heaven, for it is written that there was silence there for the space of half an hour (Ibid., p. 187), — and this from a man who always did the talking wherever he was and who listened to another with marked impa- tience (Ibid., p. 141). He did not desire friendships, for "it is a great burden to be tied to the fate of others and to be loaded with their needs" (Ibid., p. 193). He said that he did not know the meaning of the word "spirit" (Ibid., p. 240). With Hume he held iThis amusing compilation of data concerning Kant's lite and personal- ity appeared in tlaeNew Church Review (Boston) of January, igoi. 284 KANT'S LIFE AND PHILOSOPHY. that we have no knowledge of God (Ibid., p. ago). He saw no use in revelation {Ibid., p. 335). He identified religion with mere morality (Ibid., p. 338). He never attended church and spoke of prayer as ridiculous (Ibid. , p. 354). His views against religion led students to become mockers (Ibid., p. 358). His old age was unhappy (Ibid., p. 425), and his rigidity of habits became repul- sive in the last degree (Ibid., p. 435). He died February 12, 1804, after fifteen years of mental decline. KANT'S LETTER TO HIS BROTHER.i TRANSCRIPTION OF THE ORIGINAL. Lieber Bruder ! Bei dem Besuche, den Ueberbringer dieses, Herr Reimer, ein Verwandter von Deiner Fran, meiner werthen SchwSgerin, bei mir abgelegt hat, ermangle ich nicht, wassich meiner iiberh^uf ten Besch^tigungen wegen nur in ausserordentlicben Fallen thun lasst, mich bei Dir durch einen Brief in Erinnerung zu bringen. Unerachtet dieser scheinbaren Gleicbgultigkeit babe ich an Dicb, nicht allein so lange wir beiderseitig leben, oft genug, sondern auch fiir meinen Sterbefall, der in meinem Alter von 68 Jahren doch nicht mehr sehr entfernt sein kann, briiderlich gedacht. Unsere zwei ubrigen, beide verwittweten, Schwestern sind, die alteste, welche fiinf erwachsene und zum Theil schon verhei- rathete Kinder hat, ganzlich durch mich, die andere, welche im St. Georgenhospital eingekauft ist, durch meinen Zuschuss ver- sorgt. Den Kindern der ersteren babe ich, bei ihrer anfanglichen b^uslichen Einrichtung und auch nachher, meinen Beistand nicht versagt ; so dass, was die Pflicht der Dankbarkeit, wegen der uns von unsern gemeiuschaftlichen Eltern gewordenen Erziehung for- dert, nicht versaumt wird. Wenn Du mir einmal von dem Zu- stande Deiner eigenen Familie Nachricht geben willst, so wird es mir angenehm sein. Uebrigens bin ich, in Begrussung meiner mir sehr werthen Schwagerin, mit unveranderlicher Zuneigung Dein treuer Bruder K6NIGSBERG, den 26. Januar 1792. I. Kant. TRANSLATION. Dear Brother : — Taking advantage of the visit which the bearer of this letter Herr Reimer, a relative of your wife, my esteemed sister-in-law ISee the facsimile of the GermaQ original on the opposite page. 286 kant's letter to his brother. has paid me, I do not omit to recall myself to your memory, although owing to my over-burdening labors this is something that I allow myself only in extraordinary cases. Notwithstanding this apparent indifference, I have, however, frequently thought of you with brotherly regard, not only for this present life, but also in case of my death, which at my age of 68 years cannot be far dis- tant. Of our two remaining widowed sisters, the eldest, who has five adult children, some of whom are married, has been entirely supported by me, and the younger, for whom admission to the St. George's Hospital has been purchased, is also provided for. I have also not refused assistance to the children of the former, on their establishing their first homes, and even afterwards ; so that there has been no neglect of the duty of gratitude that we owe to our common parents for the education they gave us. If you will inform me of the condition of your own family, I shall be gratified. With regards to my much-esteemed sister-in-law, I remain, with constant affection. Your Faithful Brother, I. Kant. KoNiGSBERG, January 26, 1792. CHRONOLOGY OF KANT'S LIFE AND PUB- LICATIONS.! 1724 Immanuel Kant born on April 22. 1728 Lambert born. 1729 Lessing born. 1729 Mendelssohn born. 1730 Hamann born. 1732 Kant enters the Frideri- cianum, an academy in Konigsberg. 1735 Kant's brother Johann Heinrich born. 1737 Kant's mother dies. 1740 Kant matriculates at the University of Konigsberg 1740 Frederick II. ascends the throne. 1740 Feder born. 1742 Garve born. 1744 Herder born. 1746 Kant's first publication : Gedanken von der -wah- ren Schdtzung der leben- digen Krafte (Thoughts on the True Measure- ment of Living Forces). 1746 Kant's father dies. 1749 Goethe born. 1751 M. Knutzen dies. 1754 Christian Wolff dies. 1754 Investigation of the ques- tion, Whether the earth in its rotation about its axis has suffered any al- terations. 1754. Investigation of the ques- tion, Whether the earth is growing old. (Both questions treated in the KSnigsberger Nachr.). 175s Allgem. Naturgeschichte und JTieorie des Him- mels (General ilatural History and Theory of the Heavens). 1755 Kant takes his degree with the treatise De Igne, and qualifies as a university lecturer with the treatise, Princifiorumfrimorum cognitionis meta^hysicce nova dilucidatio. 1756 -1763 Seven Years War. The Russians in Konigsberg. 1756 Disputation on the treatise Moncuiologia ^hysica. 1756 Three small essays in the KSnigsberger Nachr., 1 From Paulsen's Life if Kant, Fromann's Klassiker der Fhilosafhie, Stutt- gart, 1898. 288 CHRONOLOGY. on Earthquakes. (Evoked by the Lisbon earthquake of I75S-) 1756 New notes in elucidation of the Theory of the Winds. 1757 Outline and Announcement of a. course of Lectures on Physical Geography, with a brief supplemen- tary consideration of the question whether the west winds in our locality are moist because of hav- ing passed over a broad stretch of sea. 1758 New Scientific Conception of Motion and Rest. 1759 Some Tentative Considera- tions of Optimism. 1759 Schiller born. 1762 Fichte born. 1762 Publication of Rous- seau's Amile and Contrat social. 1762 Die falsche S^itzfindig- keit der vier s^Uogisti- schen Figuren erwiesen (The Erroneous Sophis- try of the Four Syllogistic Figures Demonstrated). 1762 Der einzig m'dgliche Be- uieisgrund zu einer De- monstration vom Da- sein Gottes (The Only Possible Basis of a Dem- onstration of the Exist- ence of God). 1762 Untersuchung ilber die Deutlichkeit der Grund- sdtze der natUrlichen Theologie und Moral (Researches on the Dis- tinctness of the Princi- ples of Natural Theology and Morals). (Preis- schrift der Berliner Akademie, printed in 1764.) 1763 Versuch, den Begriff der negativen Grffssen in die Weltuieisheit einzu- fuhren (Attempt to In- troduce the Notion of Negative Quantities into Philosophy). 1763 F. A. Schultz dies. 1764 Versuch ilber die Krank- heiten des Koffes (Essay on the Diseases of the Head.) {KSnigsh. Ztg.). 1764 Beobachtungen aber das Gefilhl des Schonen und Erhabenen. (Observa- tions on the Feeling of the Beautiful and the Sublime). 1765 Information on the Plan of his Lectures. 1766 Tr&ume eines Geister- sehers, erlSutert durch Trdume der Meta^hysik (Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, etc.). 1766 Gottsched dies. 1768 Von dem ersten Grunde des Unterschiids der Gegenden im Raum (On the Fundamental Reason for the Difference of Lo- calities in Space). (Kiin. Nachr.) CHRONOLOGY. 289 1770 Kant obtains his full pro- fessorship in logic and metaphysics. 1770 Disputatio de mundi sen- sibilis atque intelligi- bills forma et ;principiis. 1770 (Holbach) Syst^me de - la nature. 1775 Von den verschiedenen Racen des Menschen (Ankiindigung der Vor- lesungen liber fhysische Geografhie). (On the Different Races of Men.) 1776 Ueber das Dessauer Phi- lanthrofie. (KSn. Ztg.J 1776 North American Dec- laration of Independence. 1776 Hume dies. 1778 Voltaire dies. 1778 Rousseau dies. 1780 Joseph II. ascends the throne. 1 78 1 Lessing dies. 1781 Kritik der reinen Ver- nunft (Critique of Pure Reason. 1783 Prolegomena su einer jeden kunftigen Meta- ^hysik, die als Wissen- schaft uiird auftreten kSnnen (Prolegomena to Every Future Metaphys- ics, etc.). 1784 Idee zu einer allgemeinen Gesch. in ■weltbilrger- Ucher Absicht (Ideas for a Universal History, etc.). 1784 Beantwortung der Frage Was ist Aufkldrung? (Both the preceding ar- ticles in the Berliner Monalsschrift. ) 178s Criticisms of Herder's Ideen zur Philos. der Geschichte. (Jenaische Litter aturztg.) 1785 Ueber Vulkane im Monde (On Volcanoes in the Moon). 1785 Von der Unrechtmdssig- keit des Bilchernach- drucks (On the Illegality of Literary Piracy). 1785 Bestimmung des Begriffs einer Menschenrace (De- termination of the Con- cept of a Race of Men). 1783 Grundlegung zur Meta- fhysik der Sitten (Foun- dation of the Metaphys- ics of Morals). 1786 Mutmasslicher Anfang der Menschengeschichte (Presumable Origin of Human History). {Berl Monalsschrift. ) 1786 Was heisst sich im Den- ken orientieren? (What is the Meaning of Orien- tation inThinking?) (Ber- liner Monalsschrift. ) 1786 Meta;physische Anfangs- grilnde der Natur-wis- senschaften (Metaphys- ical Rudiments of the Natural Sciences). 1786 Frederick the Great dies, Frederick William II. ascends the throne. 1788 W5llner's religious edict. 2 go CHRONOLOGY. 1788 Ueber den Gebrauch teleo- logischer Prinzipien in der Philoso^hie (On the Use of Teleological Prin- ciples in Philosophy). (Deutsch. Merk.). 1788 Kritik der fraktischen Vernunft (Critique of Practical Reason). 1789 French Revolution. 1790 Kritik der Urteilskraft (Critique of the Judg- ment). 1790 Ueber Pkilosofihie Uber- hau^t (erste Einl. zur Kr. d. Urt.) (On Philos- ophy in General). 1790 Ueber eine Entdeckung, nach der alle neue Kri- tik der reinen Vernunft durch eine altere ent- hehrlich gemacht Tjuer- den soil (On a Discovery by which, etc.). (Against Eberhard). 1790 Ueber Schuiarmerei und die Mittel dagegen (On Gushing and the Means for its Prevention). 1 79 1 Ueber das Misslingen alter ^hilos. Versuche in der Theodicee (On the Failure of all Philosoph- ical Attempts in Theod- icy). (Bert. Mon.) 1792 Vbm radikalen BSsen (On the Radically Bad). {Berl. Mon.) 1792 The continuation of the foregoing articles is prohibited by the Berlin censorship. 1793 Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Ver- nunft (Religion within the Bounds of Mere Rea- son). 1793 Ueber den Gemeinsfruch. Das mag in der Theorie rzchtig sein, taugt aber nichtfilr die Praxis (On the Maxim : Good in Theory, but Bad in Prac- tice). (Berl. Mon.) 1794 Etivas liber den Einjluss des Mondes auf die Witterung (On the In- J9uence of the Moon on the Weather). [Berliner Mon.) 1794 Das Ende alter Dinge (The End of all Things). (Berl. Mon.) 1794 Cabinet order of the King and Kant's promise to write nothing more on re- ligion. 1795 Peace of Basel. 1795 Zum ewigen Frieden (On Universal Peace). 1796 Kant discontinues his lec- tures. 1796 Von einem neuerdings er- hobenen, vornehmen Ton in der Philosofhie (On a Recent Aristocratic Tone in Philosophy). {Berl. Mon.) 1796 Announcement of the ap- proaching completion of CHRONOLOGY. 291 a' tract on Universal Peace in Philosophy. 1797 Metafhysische Anfangs- grUnde der Rechtslehre (Metaphysical Rudiments of Jurisprudence). 1797 Metafhysische Anfangs- grllnde der Tugendlehre (Metaphysical Rudiments of Morals). 1797 Ueber ein vermeintes Recht aus Menschenliebe zu lilgen (On a Supposed Right to Lie out of Love for Man). 1797 Frederick William II. dies and is succeeded by Frederick William III. WSlIner dismissed. 1798 Ueber die Buchmacherei. Zvjei Brief e an Fr. Ni- colai (On Bookmaking Two Letters to Fr. Nico- lai). 1798 Der Streit der Fakultaten (The Battle of the Facul- ties). 1798 Anthropologic in frag- tnatischer Hinsicht. 1800 Logic, edited by Jasche. 1802 Physical Geography, ed- ited by Rink. 1803 Pedagogy, edited by Rink. 1804 On the Prize Question of the Berlin Academy : What Real Progress has Metaphysics made inGer- many, since the Times of Leibnitz and Wolff? Edited by Rink. 1804 Kant dies on February 12. INDEX TO KANT'S PROLEGOMENA. (Pages 1-163.) Accidents, 99. Actions as appearances subject to necessity, 113. Actuality, 66. Addition and arithmetic, 36. Air is elastic, 57-59. Alchemy, 140. Analogy, cognition by, 129. Analytical and synthetical, 14-15, 17, 18, 22, 23, 25, 26, 27. Analytics and dialectics, 27. Anschauung (visualisation), 17, 18, 21, 30, 34, 120, 126, X40, 146 ; and mathe- matics, 32. Antecedent, 53 ; and consequent, 72. Anthropomorphism, 128, 130; avoided, 131. Antinomy, 105 et seq., 108. Apodeictic, 18, 33; and necessary, 35; and a priori, 144 ; certainty of meta- physics, 157. Appearance, properties of a body be- long to, 44 ; and insufficiency, 126. Appearances, space the form of, 40; geometry prescribes to, 41; objects are mere, 42 ; and sensuous per- ception, 45; and things in them, selves, 75 ; actions as, subject to necessity, 113. Application oia^rioriio experience, 34. A priori^ 70; knowledge and meta- physics, 14 ; and synthetical, 15, 26, S9, 33 ; judgment (body is extended), 16; necessity, x6 ; and pure mathe- matics, 17, 32; the materials of metaphysics, 23 ; and necessity^aS; at the bottom of metaphysics, 31 ; and its application to experience, 34; anticipating actuality, ■ 35 ; at the basis of the empirical, 36 ; apo- deictically certain, 37; intuition and three dimensions, 37 ; is it a phantasm ? 47; things not cognised, 50; principles, 60; rules, 64; origin of pure concepts, 73 ; basis of the possibility of laws, 80; laws, basis of the possibility of nature, 81; geometrical laws, 83 ; and system; 85 ; understanding determined, 137; concepts, sources of, 139; definite and compact, 141 ; and apodeicti- cal, 144; transcendent and tran- scendental, 150, 151 ; missing in Berkeley, 152. Aristotle, 86. Arithmetic and addition, 36. Association, law of, 4. Astrology, 140. Axioms, 60. Baumgarten, ig. Beattie, 5, 6. Beginning, the world has a, 105. Being, a, conceived for comprehend- ing the connexion, order, and unity of the world, X17. Beings of understanding, Z12. Berkeley, 151, 152; his idealism, 49; a Priori missing in, 152; dogmatic idealism of, 153. Bodies, primary qualities of, 43-44; mere representations, 43, Body, thing in itself, as, 103. Boundary, theology (natural) looks beyond, 134 ; and limits, 133. Bounds, not limits, 123 ; and limits, Z2S ; of pure reason, 120, 124. 294 INDEX TO KANT'S PROLEGOMENA. Categories, 86j 87, 88, 89, go, Z05 ; of deeper meaning, 76; and under- standing, 92; and logical functions, 94. Causality, 22; and succession, iii. Cause, 4, 53, gS ; a pure concept of the understanding, 58; is super- added, 59; and effect, 66; of con- nexions in the world, 131. Challenge, 144. Challenging the critic, 157. Chimeras, ^. Chisels and engraver's needle, 6-7. Circle, law of the, 82. Cognition, 45 ; of the understanding, 93 ; analogy, 129 ; insufficiency of the, Z36. Common sense, 6, 27, 29, 145; no right to judge in metaphysics, 7 ; appeal to, Z44; and metaphysics, 146. Community, 66. Composite, everything is, 106. Concepts, of reason, 95 ; having their origin in reason, zi8. Conflict of reason, 116. Congruent, the two hands not, 39. Connexions in the world, cause of, 131. { Consciousness, subject of, 103. Consequent and antecedent, 72. Construction and experiencef 146. Contradiction, law of, 16, 22, 27; and synthetical judgments, 15. Contrast of right and left, 39. Cosmological idea, X04, 105, Crazy-quilt of metaphysics, 154. Criteria of truth, universal and nec- essary laws, 152. Criterion of truth, Z03. Critical idealism, 49, 153. Critical question, 24. Criticism, standard given by, 163; and metaphysics, 162. Critique, contains plan of metaphys- ics, 139; justified, 158; whoever has once tasted, etc., 140. Crusius's compromise,' 81. Degree, 66, 68. Descartes, 48 ; his sceptical idealism, 153. Determinabiltty and necessity, 114 Dialectics and analytics, 27. Difference of equal figures, 38-39. Diffuseness of the plan, 8. Dogmatics, downfall of, 141. Dogmatic slumber, Kant's, 7. Dogmatic twaddle, 140. Dogmatism and scepticism, 24, 132. Dreaming idealism, 49. Effect and cause, 66. Effect happens in time, izi. Ego, 100, Z03. Eleatic school, 151. Empirical idealism, 48, Empirical intuition, 33. Empirical judgments, z6, S4i 55- Engraver's needle, chisels and, 6-7. Equal figures, difference of, 38-39, Experience, 16, 57, 58, 63 ; geometry holds all possible, 46; illusion in transgressing, 48; and things in themselves, 51; objects of pos- sible, 53 ; judgments of, 54, 55, 57. 62, 63; possibility of, 60; intuitions and judgments, 62 ; understanding makes it possible, 84; analogy of, zoz ; and the real, zo2 ; things in themselves the basis of, X24, and ' construction, Z46; truth in, 151, Facility of solution, 28. Faculty of beginning from itself, freedom a, ii2-xz5. Fiction, previous to our acquaint- ance, space would be mere, 41. Foam, metaphysics like, 21. Formal, 104. Form, of intuition, a priori^ 35 ; of sensibility, pure intuition a, 36; without perception remains, Z27. Four ideas of reason, Z07. Freedom, ZZ4; and nature, 106, a faculty of beginning from itself, X12-X15 ; and reason, X13 ; rescued, practical, IZ4 ; natural necessity and, 1Z5. Functions of the understanding, 60. Fundamental principles, 64. Geometry, and space, 36; necessarily valid of space, 40 : objects coincide INDEX TO rant's PROLEGOMENA. 295 with, 41; prescribes to appear- ances, 41 ; holds all possibler expe- rience, 46. Geometrical laws, 83. Geometrical sources, 83. Gesetztttassigkeit, 52. God. {Sbb Being.) Gotkaische gelehrte Zeiiutig; 156. Gdttingensche gelehrten Anzeigen^ 149. Hand, right and left, 39, 40. Helices, symmetric, 40. History of philosophy, 1. Horace, 3, 27. Hnme, David, 3, 4, 6, 7, zo, it), 21, 28, 71,121,127, 130, 132; his problem, 5i 8i 73; his spark of Ueht, 7; his doubts, 9, 70. Hyperphysical, 52. Idealism, 44, 150, 151 ; Kant's, 43-44 ; charges of, 48 ; empirical, 48 ; tran- scendental, 4S, 49 ; critical, 49, 153 ; dreaming, 49 ; of Berkeley, 49, 153 ; visionary, 49; Cartesian or mate- rial, 103, 104 ; mystical, 152 ; of Descartes, sceptical, 153. Ideality of space and time, 47, Idea of nnity system, 1x9, Ideas, reason the source of, 92 ; theo- logical, 117; transcendental, their origin in reason, 118, 137. Illusion and truth, 152. Illusion in transgressing experience, 48. Illusory metaphysics, 139. Imagination, 78. Immaterial being, 125. Incidental and necessary, xo6. Incomprehensibility, 118 ; of causal- ity, 70. Infinite, the world is, 106. Infinite number of parts, zio. Insufficiency and appearance, 126, Intelligence, supreme, 137. Intelligible world, 'jy. Internal constitution of things never revealed, 123. Internal sense and soul, 104. Intuited, everything as it appears, 38. Intuite, how to, apriorU 34- Intuition, 33, 35, 37; at the founda tion of mathematics, 35, 38; afri- ori, and three dimensions, 37; space the form of the external, 40; ob- jects given in, 42; of space and time, appearance, 48 ; none beyond sensibility, 77; universal form of, 84. Intuitive, 33. Judgment defined, 63 ; empirical, 54 55 ; of experience, 54, 55, 57, 62, 63; of perception, 55, 57; synthetical 59 ; two sorts, X48. Kant's dogmatic slumber, 7. Labor of research, 28. Law, conformity to, 52 et seq., 103; of the circle, 82; reason prescribes the, 118; reason's production, 118. Laws, subjective, 53 ; of nature, their sources, 54; universal, 54; of na- ture, particular and universal, 81; of nature, not in space, 83 ; univer- sal and necessary, criteria of truth, 152. Legislation of nature in ourselves, 80. Legislative, the a priori is, Leibnitz, 3. Limits, not bounds, 123 ; contain ne- gations, 125 ; and bounds, 125 ; and boundary, I33- Locke, 3, zg. 43. Logical functions and categories, 94. Logical table, 6x. Longwindedness of the work, zo. Materialism, rash assertions destroy, 137- Mathematical judgments, z6. Mathematicians were philosophers, 41. Mathematics, nature of, 33; apriori, 32; and Ansckauung^ 32; and vis- ual form, 32 ; how possible, 32 et seq. ; intuitions at the foundation of 35t 38; applied to nature, 69; must be referred to appearances, 73; and metaphysics, 9z. 2g6 INDEX TO KANT'S PROLEGOMENA. Maxims, 114. Mental space renders physical space possible, 42. Metaphysicians, oratory of, zg ; sus- pended, 29. Metaphysics, 135 ; whether possible, 1-3, 20, 24 ; impossible according to Hume, 4; not every one is bound to study, II ; must satisfy the de- mands, 12; knowledge of, lying be- yond experience, 13 ; and a priori knowledge, 14; sources of, 13-14; like foam, 21; the materials of , a priori^ 23 ; and synthetical proposi- tions, 24 ; and synthetic a priori propositions, 26-27; difficulty of, 28; and transcendental philosophy, 30; aPriori^X the bottom of, 31 ; as a science, 31, 147 ; young thinkers partial to, 78; and mathematics, 91; how possible? gz; grounds of, 138; critique contains plan of, 139 ; illu- sorji 139; of decay, 141; will never be given up, 142 ; and common sense, 146; crazy-quilt of, 154; as- sertions of, world tired of, 155; standard of, 156; apodeictic cer- tainty of, 157; and criticism, 162. Nature, defined, 50, 52, 54; science of, precedes physics, 51, 65; sources of its laws, 54; system of, 64; its uni- versal laws cognised a priori^ 64; mathematics applied to, 6g ; how possible, 7g ; the totality of rules, 79; legislation of, in ourselves, 80; fz j^rzidW laws basis of the possibil- ity of, 81; laws of, particular and universal, 81; its laws not in space, 83 ; and freedom, ic6. Necessary, 62; and apodeictic, 35; universality and objective validity, 56 ; and incidental, zo6. Necessary Being, zi6. Necessity, 67; of habit, 4; (according to Hume) a long habit, 28 ; and a. priori^ 28 ; actions as appearances subject to, Z13; and determinabil- ity, ZZ4; natural, and freedom, ZZ5; unconditional, 136. Noumena, (things in themselves), 72, 76, 97 ; and creations of the under- standing, 75 ; as the void, 123. Objective, 55 et seq. Objective validity and necessary uni- versality, 56. Objects, coincide with geometry, 41; are mere appearances, 42; given in intuition, 42; of possible experi- ence, 53; and things in themselves, zii ; unknown, 56. Obscurity, 12. Ontology, go. Oratory of metaphysicians, 29. Oswald, 5. Ought and reason, 1Z3. Particular ia^ 60. Perception, judgments of, 55, 57. Permanence of substances, ioi-jo2. Phantasm, is the a priori a? 47, Phenomena, subjective basis of, 42; in space, 102. Philosophers, mathematicians were 41. Philosophy, history of, 1. Physical space, mental space renders it possible, 42. Physics, preceded by Science of Na- ture, 51. Physiological table, 6z. Plan of the work, analytical, 11. Plainer, zi8. Plurativa judicia^ 60. Popular, I might have made my ex- position, zo. Popularity and Prolegomena, 8-9. Possibility, 66. Practical freedom rescued, Z14. Predicables, 87. Predicates, 99 ; belonging to appear- ance, 43. Priestley, S' Primary qualities of bodies, 43-44. Prolegatnena, for teachers, z ; and popularity, 8-9; analytical, 25; prep- aratory, 25 ; as an outline, Z59. Properties of a body belong to ap- pearance, 44. INDEX TO KANT's PROLEGOMENA. 297 Property, similarity of sensation to, 44. Pseudo-science, 140. Pure concepts, of the understanding, 60, 63, 64 ; table of the, 61 ; a priori origin of, 73 ; of reason, 93. Pure intuition, 33 ; a form of sensi- bility, 36. Pure reason, 94, 97. Quantity, 65, 68 ; and things in them- selves, 67 ; of the world, log. Questions, four, 31. Real and experience, the, xo2. Reason, the source of ideas, 92 ; and understanding, 92; pure concepts of, 93i 94i 9Si 97 ; divided with it- self, 107 ; four ideas of, 107 ; and freedom, 113; and ought, 113; con- flict of, 116 ; concepts having their origin in, iiS; prescribes the law, Z18 ; at variance with itself, 1x9; bounds of pure, 120, 124, 128; finds no satisfaction in itself, 124; teaches nothing concerning the thing in it- self 134 ; freed by the theological idea, 136. Red and vermillion, 44. Reid, 5. Rules, 64; a priori, 64. Scepticism, 21, 121; and dogmatism, 24. Science of nature, 65. Scholia, 13S, 139 et seq. Self, the thinking, 100. Sensation, similarity of, to property, 44. Senses, business of the, 62. Sensibility, form of, and a priori^ 35; time and space conditions of our, 37; no intuition beyond, ']'^. Sensible world no sham. 44. Sensuous perception and appear- ances, 45. Similart^ty of sensation to property, 44- Simple and composite, 106. Skepticism and dogmatism, 132. Solution, facility of, 28, Soul, 96, 100; as a substance, loi, 102, IDS ; and internal sense* Z04 ; the nature of, Z2i, 136 ; vacuity in the, 160. Sources of a/^'wrz" concepts, 139. Space, 122; and Time, 35; and geom- etry, 36 ; and time conditions of our sensibility, 37 ; three dimen- sions, 37; and time, mere forms, 38 ; and time presupposed, 38 ; the form of appearances, 40; the form of the external intuition, 40; would he mere fiction previous to our ac- quaintance, 41 ; mental renders physical possible, 42; and time and things in themselves, 47; and time, ideality of, 47; and time, intuitions of, appearance, 48 ; not a store of laws, 84 ; phenomena in, 102 ; and time belong to appearances, 15a. Spark of light, Hume's, 7. Standard given by criticism, 163. Subjective basis of phenomena, 42. Subjective laws, 53. Subsistence, 70. Substance, 66, 98, lOo; of things, 99; permanence of, X01-102; soul as a, zoi, 102, zos. Succession, 66, 72 ; and causality, zzz. Sufficient reason, never been proved, 143. Sun, shining on stone, 59, 63 ; the cause of heat, 72. Superadded, cause is, 59. Supreme Being, 96, 125, 126, Z27, X2g, 130, Z3Z, Supreme Cause, zsz, 132. Supreme intelligence, Z37. Supreme Reason, 132. Symmetric helices, 40. Synthetical, and analytical, Z4-1S, z8, 22, 23, 25, 26, 27 ; and apriori, z5 26, 29, 33 ; Judgments and the law of Contradiction, Z5, 59; of 7-I-5 = 12, 17 ; propositions and meta- physics, 24. System, of nature, 64; and a priori, 85 ; idea of unity, Z19. Teachers, Prolegomena for, i. Test, Z57, z6i. 298 INDEX TO rant's PROLEGOMENA. Theological idea, 117; reason freed by the, 136. Theology (natural) looks beyond the boundary, 134. Thing in itself, as body, 103 ; reason teaches nothing concerning, 134. Things in themselves, 53, 70, 120, i!i, 122 ; and space and time, 47 ; cog- nition of impossible, so; under- standing must conform to, 50 ; and experience, 51; and quantity, 67; (noumena), 72, 76; serve to deci- pher appearances, 73 ; and appear- ances, 7s; and objects, ill; the basis of experience, 124. Things, unknown in themselves, 43 ; substance of, gg ; never revealed, internal constitution of, X23. Thinking defined, 62. Thinking self, the, 100. Time and Space, 35; conditions of our sensibility, 37; mere forms, 38 ; presupposed, 38 ; belong to appear- ances, IJ2. Transcendent, 92, 104; transcenden- tal, a priori and, 150, 151, Transcendental, philosophy and met- apbysics, 30; problem, 32 et seq,; idealism, 48, 49 ; philosophy, sys- tem of, 87; ideas, their origin in reason, 1x8; a. priori and tran- scendent, 150, X5X, Truth, and dreaming, 45 ; criterion of, 103, 149 ; in experience, 151 ; and illusion, i;2. Understanding, must conform to things in themselves, 50 ; functions of the, 60; pure concepts of the, 60, 63 ; table of the pure concepts of the, 61 ; business of the, 62 ; crea- tions of, and noumena, 75; vaga- ries of the, 78 ; constitution of our, 79; prescribes laws to nature, 82; laws inhere in the, 83 ; makes ex- perience possible, 84; and cate- gories, 92; and reason, 92; cogni- tions of the, 93; beings of, ii2; - world of, I2S ; systematic unity be- longs to, 13S. Unity a mode of cognition, iig. Universality, necessary, 55, Universal laws, 54 ; laws of nature, cognised a priori, 64. Universal validity, 69. Universally valid, 62. Vacuity in the soul, x6o. Vagaries of the understanding, 78. Virgil, 12. Visionary idealism, 49. Visual form and mathematics, 32. Visualisation {Anschauung) , 18, 2X. Void, the, that of which we can know nothing, 125. Weckjelwirkung, 66. Wisdom incarnate, 2. Wolf, xg. World, X28 ; questions of its duration and quantity, 122. INDEX TO THE ARTICLE ON KANT'S PHI- LOSOPHY. (Pages 167-240.) A^aghosha, 228. After-image, 224. Agnosticism, 237. Amit&bba, 228. Ansckauungt 184, 187. Antinomies, 221, 237 ; Kant's, 195 et seq.; not true antinomies, 197. A posteriori s^nd a priori, 181, 182. Appearance, two meanings of, 232; time and space appertain to, 231, 232. Apriort, ig8; not innate, 181; and a posteriori, x8i, 182; purely formal, 207; has objective value, 214. Apriority, general applicability, 226, Aristotle, 169, X78. Ar0pa, 228. Asceticism, 211. Berkeley, 177 ; bis idealism, 175 ; bis philosophy, 199; and Kant, 210, Cartesian syllogism, the, x6g. Categories and modes of existence, 219' Causation, 200 et seq. Cause and reason, 201 et seq. Christ, 212. Clifford, 2x6 ; on the thing in itself, 237. Clusters, things are, 217. Color-blind, 228. Confucius, 212. Constructions and mathematical theorems, 2is> Construction, world of senses is a, 334. Cosmos, 221 et seq. Critique o/Pure Reason^ 175. Dasein and Sein, 227. Delphic maxim, x68. Descartes, 169. Dictates of our mind, 207. Divisibility of line, infinite, 2x6. Dogmatism, 172. Edmunds, Albert J., x88, X89, xg2. Ego, metaphysical, X70. Empirical, 180. Extension, 225. Feder, 175. Flux of things, 218. Formal, and the sensory, the, 208; constructed, the purely, 2x5. Formal cognition the key to mys- teries, 227. Formal knowledge gives system, purely, 226. Formal sciences, the organ of cogni- tion, 212. Formal theorems, general, 207. Form both subjective and objective, 2x2 et seq. Garve, 175. Generalisations, origin of, 2ig. God, Z78, 221 et seq., 228; the world- order, 239. God problem, 237 et seq. Golden Rule, 2x2. GSttingenscke Gelehrien Anseigen, 175. 300 INDEX TO "KANT'S PHILOSOPHY," Heine, Heinrich, 173. Homaloidal, 233. Hume, 171 ; his problem, 198, xgg, ^0 at seq. Ideal and subjective, 206, 214. Idealism and realism, 222-223. Ideality, of space and time, 187; not subjectivity, 204 et seq. Image, 184 ; after-, 224. Infinite divisibility of line, 216. Innate ideas. 182, 200. Innate not aprtorit z8i. Intuition, 184. Inventor a finder, the, 220. Jacobi, 223. Kant, his philosophical reform, 171; his personal traits, 173; his indig- nation, 177; his terms, 178; on meta- physics, 178-179, 195; on reality,i87; and Swedenborg, x88 et seq.; his antinomies, 195 et seq.; his prob- lem, xg8; puzzled by the a priori ^ 203 et seq,; and Berkeley, 210 ; his conception of morality, 211 ; on space and time, 231 ; his definition of things in themselves, 235. Kantism, moral aspect of| 210 et seq, Lao-Tze, 212, 228. Laws, 218, Leibnitz, 189, zgo, 195. Lichtenberg, 170. Locke, 171, 200. Logos, 228. Mach, Ernst, 233. Mathematical theorems and con- structions, 215. Measure of motion (Time}, 216. Mental construction and straight line, 234. Metaphysics, 178 ; the old, 172 ; Kant on 178-179, 195 ; sources of, 179. Mind dictates, our, 207, Mind, like the spider's thread, 206. Modes of existence and categories, 2ig. Morality, Kant's conception of, 211, Mundus intelligibilis, 179, 228. Naturalists of Greece, 167. Nature, uniformities of, 205. Neumann, 196. Nirv3.na, 228. Nomenclature is arbitrary, 222. Norms of superreal, 227 et seq, Noumena, 228 et seq.; represents things, 229, Noumenon, and phenomenon, 180- 181 ; space-conception a, 234. Objectified, every sentient suibject, 230; subject, the, 225, 226, 231. Objective and subjective, 216, 217. Objectivity of space and time, 230 et seq. Objects, what are they ? 224. Organ of cognition, formal sciences the, 212. Paulsen, 173, 176, 177, Phenomenon and noumenon, 180-181 Philosophy, love of wisdom, 168; practical, 167, Photographer's camera, 184, Physiological space, 233. Plato, 236. Fi'olegomena, 177, 202 et seq. Pure, 182. Real, 224, Realism and idealism, 222-^23. Real time and space, 229. Reason, and cause, 201 et seq.; and understanding, z8o. Red and vermillion, 209 et seq. Religion, the sensory in, 211. Scholasticism, 168-169. Schopenhauer, 197, 223, 236 ; his Will, 237. Sein and Dasein^ 227. Self-perception, 224. Sensations, subjective, 228, Senses, world of, a construction, 234. Sensory, the formal and the, 208; in religion, the, 21X. Sewall, Frank, 189. INDEX TO "KANt's PHILOSOPHY." 301 Socrates, x68. Sophists, the, 16S. Soul, 221 etseq.; Swedenborg on the, 193- Space and time, not objects, 1S7; ideality of, 187; objectivity of, 225, 226, 230 et seq.; real, 229 ; forms of any existence, 131; Kant on, 231; appertain to appearances, 231, 232. Space-conception, and space, 233 ; a noumenon, 234. Space, physiological, 233 ; and space- conception, 233- Spider's thread, mind like the, 206. Spinoza, 179. Straight line and mental construc- tion, 234> Subject, 229; representation of the, 224; in itself empty, 225; the ob- jectified, 226; objectified, every sentient, 230, 231. Subjective, and ideal, 206, 214 ; and objective, 2x6, 217. Subjectivity, not ideality, 204 et seq.; science eliminates, 235* Succession, 217, 225. Suchness, 208 et seq. Superreal, norms of, 227 et seq. Swedenborg, "Emanuel, 170, 228; and Kant, 188 et seq.; on the soul, 193. Terms, Kant's, 178. Theology, 178. Thing in itself, Clifford on the, 237. Things in themselves, 234 et seq.; Kant's definition of, 235 ; a vagary 236. Things, represented by noumena 229 : are clusters, 217 ; flux of, 2x8; and unities, 221. Thisness, 208 et seq. Tilly, Frank, 175. Time and space, ideality of, 187; not objects, 1S7; objectivity of, 223, 226, 230 et seq.; real, 229 ; appertain to appearances, 231, 232; forms of any existence, 231 ; Kant on, 231. Time (measure of motion), 216. Transcendental, 182 ; and transcend- ent, X83. Transcendent and transcendental, 183. Tufts, James H., 173. Twaddle, dogmatical, 172. Twice two, not one, 2x8. Understanding and reason, 180. Uniformities, 218; of nature, 205. Unities and things, 221. Vaihinger, 189. Vermillion and red, 2og et seq. Watts, James, 220. Weber, Prof. A., 175. Windelband, 173. Wolf, 170. Zeno, 2x6.