%i 5 W. M. FAHN>«TOCK. | I The horrorjtr icill (Aease to retxtan. | " *»^^l»^ 4^ ^l. ^M l M .l»l' M (*^i | «*^M* » ^' * '^ **w *^ "«• ' ^ ** 5:^^5:3 5:^^ i:^ <£^ o^ ^2- F. L P 11 1 A . PA. y7vf7A/c^ ydi^'/§5'X)ICATIOX. AMtli the highest esteem for your pcrsonul cha- racters, though you arc probably unkno\\n tr» each otlier. I am Gentlemen, Your brother in the faith, and hope of the Gospel. J. PRIESTLEY. Northu mberland 1 804. PREFACE. WHEN I wrote the Pamphlet entitled Socrates and Jesus Compared^ which I was led to do fi-om the perusal of Xeiiophon's Memorabilia, in order to form a more distinct idea than I then rctamed of the subjects and the manner of the teaching of So- crates, and from seeing his character in a diiTercnt light from that in which it had bee« usually re- presented, I had no thoughts of doing any cbing more in the same way. But my friends in gene- ral approving of the pamphlet, and seeing in the same light with myself the great superiority v» hich it exhibited of the character and teaching of Jesus to that of this most moral, and most celebrated, of all the Grecian philosophers, I was urged to give a similar view of all the Grecian moralists, con:ipar- ing their principles with those of revelation in f^-e- neral. At first diis appeared to me too great an under- taking at my age, and with increasing infirmities* But finding that my library, notwithstandiiig the a iv. destruction vi PREFACE. dcbtnictlou ofu tp-cat part of it at the riots in rJir- minghain, \\a.s bO fur restored as to contain almoit every book that I wanted for the puq^ose, hm-ing a predileclion for die Mork, and abniidant leisure in my present retired situation, I reperused tlie \\ rit- ings of all the Grecian moralists that have come to us, making all the extracts that I thought ne- ecissarv, a!id then composed the difiercnt paits of the work \viti\ v/hich I nov/ present the reader ; It uas hoAvcver not done in the order in w hich tJiey are now arranged, but as they appeared to me of the most importance, giving directions to ni}- son, that if I div-^d before the work ^vas compleated, he would publish what I had iinished ; having taken the precan 'ion to transcribe, and prepare for the jjress., each of the separate parts before I under- look anv other. In this manner, with much more case, and I will add, more to my satisfaction, than I expected, I compleated my design. My labour w as the shorter, as I had nothing to do with the l(»gic, the metaphysics, or the physics, of the writeis all equally trifling and absurd, but only with such passages in their writings as related to the being, die attributes, and tlie providence of God, their sentiments concerning the human soul, ind especially its destination after dcadi, and tlicir geueial PREFACE. vii general principles of morals. For with these sub- jects only codld they be brought into comparison with the doctrines o^ the scriptures. Also, my comparison extended no farther than till Christia- nity became the religion of the Roman Emperors. For after this the tenets of the philosojihers and those of the christians v.ere strangely mixed, so that it might be said they borrowed from eacli o- ther. I have therefore confined myself to the pe- riod in which they were entirely separate. For though after the promulgation of Christianity the heathen philosophers had sufficient opportunity of acquainting themselves with its principles, tlicy appear to have been entirely ignorant of them, or to have given litde attention to them. Tiiis ap- pears to me to have been the case with Marcus Antoninus, and others who lived long enough af- ter the time of Christ. If they had any know- ledge of christian principles, their bias was rather against than in favour of them. There are several subdivisions of the Grecian philosophers which I have not noticed, but they were such as made only some small variation in some of the general systems of which I have gi^-en a particular account. I'he most considerable of them were Sceptics, and the Academics ; but they a V. advanced viii PREFACE. advanced nothing new, and only doubted, and dis- puted, in diiTcrentways about thcpositions of others. For a more particular account of all the Grecian philosophers than it was to my purpose to give, I refer the reader to the excellent History of Philo- sophy by Dr. Enfield^ most judiciously compiled from the tla!)orate \\ork of Brucker. As the sen- timents of the Grecian j)hilosophers have been re- presented \'cry differentl}-, by writers m ho had dif- ferent views in charaeterizing them, I thought it nccessar\ to give numerous extracts from their o^\i\ >\'orks ; so that the reader may be confident that I have not made any mistvike of importance in 7ny account of them. I once thought of adding another part, on the sentiments of Cicero, forthouglihe was the found- er of no sect, he A\as ^^ell acquainted with the principles of them all, and no doubt made his se- lection of those w hich he most ajiprovcd. But be- sides th?.t dicre is nothing of his oun in any thing he has advanced on the scAcral subjects, it is not easy to ascertain what his real sentiments were. His preference may in general be pretty \\cll dis- tinguished amon;^ the different speakers in his dia- loc:ueb ; l)ut it was too great an object with him to cmbeliisl) ^\ hate\ er he undertool^ to defend ; so that PREFACE ix that there is often more of the orator, than of the philosopher, even in his philosophical works. I can by no means persuade myself to tliiiik so highly of the religious sentiments of Cicero, and of their having been the real principles of his con- duct, as Dr. Middleton does. He gives him every thing that is most essential in chrislianit}', or what was by himself thought to be so ; and among the rest a belief in the immortality of the soul, aiid its separate existence in a state of happiness or mise- ry after death ; ^\■hereas he expressly says there could hardly be found a foolish old yronian w ho feared what had formerly been believed of the dreadful things in the shades belou\ De Natu- ra deorum. (Lib. ii. cap. 2.) Yet on this subject, among others, Middleton says. ( Life of Cicero Vol. Hi. p lAfd.J " that Cicero has largely and *' clearly declared his mind in many parts, of his " writings." Any person, however, may see in Dr. Middleton's work a large account of what is contained in the writings of Cicero on this subject j and to tliis elaborate, entertaining, and truly valu- able work I refer the reader. I have litde doubt, but that the opinion expressed by Caesar, in his speech, as given by Sallust, in the X PREFACE. the debate concerning the punishment of the Asso- ciates oi Cataline, vas that \vhich was maintained by the senators in general, and all persons of rank and education at Rome ; as it \\as not delivered by Cjcsar as his own in particular, but evidently as V. h.at he apprehended would be that from ^^hich his hearers would not dissent. Cato, ^\ ho spake after him, did not express any disapprobation of whc'it lie had said. Indeed as a stoic, he could not. Cicero himself was present, and did not contra- dict him. " In sorrow and distress," Caesar said, " Death is a state of rest from all trouble, and not *' of torment. It puts an end to all the evils to *' which men ai'e subject, and beyond it there is no " room for care or joy." The result of the whole of this work, even to the most superficial observer, must be a sense of the infinite superiority of the doctrines of Revela- tion, and especially of those of Christianity, to those of any heathen system whatever ; and w'tth this great ad\'antage, that the principles of revelation are perfectly intelligible to the bulk of mankind, and die same with those which actually influence men in the common conduct of life ; giving them a knowledge of what they have to hope from the practice of virtue, and what tliey have to feai- in couse. PREFACE. Ki consequence of vice. Moreover, these rules of life, coming Immediately from the author of their being, have a great advantage in point of v/eight, and authority, far more than any inere reasoning, though ever so clear and satisfactory, could have given them. Accordingly, the precepts of IMoses were not, like the teachings of the Greek philosophers, con- fined to a fe^v, but calculated for the use of the whole nation, the lowest as much as the highest among them. The doctrines and precepts of Christianity are also equally intelligible to all man- kind ; and they are represented as of equal impor- tance and concern to all, the slave as much as his master. Such a plan of general instruction was ne- ver practiced, nor, as far as appears, did the verv ideaof it ever occur to any of the Greek moralists. The lectures of the philosophers were given to se- lect disciples, who generally paid for their instruc- tion. With the common people they had nothing to do, while at the same time they encouraged them in their absurd and abominable religious rites, founded on that polytheism and idolatry which they themselves held in contempt ; and this was founded on as groundless an opinion as any that was ever entertained by the lowest of the pco- ple» xH PREFACE* p!e» VIZ. that thcMeHlirc of the state depended up- on the observance of them. The ottenlion I have given to tliis sul)ject has increased t'ne sense I had before of the great \ alue of rtvelaiion to the virtue and happiness of man- kiiid, a::d my gratitude to die universal parent, that I was bom in a chiustian country, and in an age so njuch enlightened as the present. I re- joice also that 1 have been led, in the course of liis providence, to do so much as I have done to- wards illustrating and defending the evidences of revelation, and towards purging it from those doc- trines and practices w hich were discordant v\ ith it, and prevented its reception Mith man}', I am willing to think thiat my comparison of the instituti- ons of the Hindoos^ and other antient nations^ with t/iose oj Moses, and this work, which extends the comparison to all the sects of the Grecian philoso- phers, \\ ill eminently contribute to this end. Last- 1}', I am thankful to die author of my being that my life lias been prolonged so far as to have been able to compleat my design. I could not ha\e closed my life widi more satisfaction than after a work of this kind. May tlie great Lord of the har- vest send more, more zealous, and more able, la- bourers into his harvest.. THE Principles of the Grecian PHILOSOPHY. [part I.] ON The state of religious and moral prin- ciPLEs IN Greece before the TIME OF Pythagoras. INTRODUCTION. XN comparing the moral maxims of the heathcji world with those of revelation, a\ Inch Is the object of this work, it is desirable to go as far back as we can, with any sufficient evidence, ofwhat men real- ly thought and did ; and though with respect to Greece we cannot go so far back as we can with re- spect to Hindostan, and other oriental nations, '^ve have two early WTiters on whom we may depend, viz. the poets Hesiod and Homer; and they flourished, according to Ne\vton, about eight hun- dred years before the christian aera : A, We y. THE PRINCIPLES 0# We have also a poem of considerable length, contaiiiing precepts for the conduct of life, by Th E G N I s , which does not appear to ha\e suffered by interpolation ; and he flourished more than four liundred years before Christ ; and also a shorter po- em of Phocylides of the same age, thought by some to contain christian sentiments, and therefore to have been interpolated ; we have also a collecti- on ofsayings of those who are generally called Md* se^eti wise men of Greece, who lived about six hun- dred years before Christ, presen'cd by Diogenes Lacrtiu s. Thou gh all these are not of equal autho- rity, I shall quote nothing from any of them but what will appear, by a comparison with others the antiquity of which is unquestionable, to be suffici- ently to my purpose. It is something remarkable that, near as Greece is to Palestine and Egypt, not only all science, pro- perly so called, but a knowledge of the common and most useful arts, seems to have been unknown for ages in that couiUry, "till they were brought to tliem by the Phenicians or Egyptiiuis, who came a- mong them to find settlements, after flying from their q>\w\ countries, and who found them in a state of the greatest barbaiism, and divided into a great number THE GRECIAM PHILOSOPHY. 3 number of clans ; for nations or states they did not deserve to be called ; and in a state of hostility \\ ith each other, as mankind in a similar situation are al- ways found to be. These wandering tribes of Greece, shvillar to those in North America at present (for they were a lojig time in no better, but rather in a ^\orsc state with respect to ciAilization,) m.ust no doubt, have had some notions of religion ; since no pco]}Ie in die world have been intirely without them ; Init wliat they were in that rude state of the country it is im- possible to trace. The sacred rites aiid modes of worship that we find accounts of in their \\ riters were acknowledged to have been borrowed from Egypt, and odier countries. And even this ^vas in so early a period, before they had any writers, that the observance of them had been from time imme- morial ; so that the veneration they had acquired from their antiquity was not to be shaken. Whatever they were, and they were dlfFcrcnt in every part of the countr}?-, and more or less in every different town and hamlet, they w^re supposed to ^ be connected with the well-being of the place ; so that it would have been thought hazardous to make any change in them. Nor do v.e find that this was A 2. ever 4 THE PRINCIPLES OF ever done in any heathen countr}^ They might a- dopt new gods, and new modes of ^^ orship, but they never abandoned their own antient ones. This partial eiviUzation of Greece must have been a considerable time after the ^eatest part of the kno^vledge derived from revelation had been lost in the East, as will be evident to any person who compares what he finds on this subject in the earliest of the Greek wTiters with the book of Job, to say nothing of the writings of Moses. Job and his friends, though probably not themselves favour- ed w ith any revelation, appear to have had a clear knowledge of the being, and the righteous govern- ment of the one true God, the maker of the world, and of all things in it, and also of a future state of righteous retribution. At least so it clearly ap- pears tome, though of late, and only of late, some christian writers Iiave questioned tliis. But how misembly be^^ ildcred were the wisest of the Greeks Mith respect to these subjects. Of die knowledge of a future state, on the only principle of reason, as well as re\elation, ^iz. that of a proper resurrection^ we do not percei^ c the least trace among them. Instead of tliis, they had adopted a notion of a sepa- rate souij or a ghosts descending after deadi into a region THl GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY, 5 region below the surface of the eai-th, and the most absurd fables relating to their condition there; though these, do not appear to have had any credit with the writers, nor probably with any persons of much thought and reflection among them. Section I. Of the Obligation to the Worship of the Gods in general. The general and established opinion of a superi- or power, or powers, governing the affairs of the world and of men, and the obligation that men were under to Morship them, according to the customaiy rites of each people, was uni^'ersal. And this ^\-as not only the persuasion of the vulgar, but of all the writers without any exception. lu a later period it is probable enough that what several of the writers advance on this subject might arise from a Avish not to shock the prejudices of the populace, but witli respect to the period of which I am now treating, there seems to be no reason to doubt of their sincer- ity; the precepts on this subject are so numerous, and urged in so emphatical a manner by them all. The obligation to worship the gods is urged by So- A 3. Ion, 6 THE PRINCrrLES OF loii, one of whose sayings \\as, " honour the gods, Tcver- ence thy parents." Nor.e of tlie seven wise men of Greece, ea:i be said to liave been ^Titers, and therefore we have not sufficient authority for iheir real opinions. But Theognis imd Phoc) lides m ere ; and in the poem of the former, we find (^ . 170.) " Pray to the gods " \\lio have great power, for \\ itliout the gods men " have neither good nor evil." Here we see the belief of tliis writer in the pro^idence, as well as in the existence, of the gods ; but we shall have more abundant evidence of this hereafter. Phocylides s:ivs(v. 7.) " In the first place Avorship die gods, " then honour thy parents, judge no man unjusUy, " for afterwards God will judge thee." Indeed, Vv hat this poet says of God may w ith some reason be suspected to have been drawn from tlie principles of revelation, and therefore to be an interpolation. For he says, v. 48, *' There is one God, w ise, pow- " crful, and self sufficient." Hesiod, tl:ough in liis Theogony he retails all the Grecian fables concerning the origin and de- scent of tlie gods, all of wliom he derives from the ^'<7;7/?, which was therefore prior to tliem all, }-et his poem intided On Ji'orks contains excellent senti- ments THE GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. 7 ments, and good ad\'ice on this subject, as well as on many others. Addressing his brother, he says, (Lib. I. V 334.) " According to thy ability, sacii- *' ficc to tlie immortal gods morning and evening, *' that they may shew thee favour, and that thou may- " est purchase the possesions of others, and others " not purchase tliine. Pray (Lib. U. v. 84.) to Ju- " piter and Ceres, that you may have a good in- *' crease." According to Hesiod Jupiter destroy- ed a whole race of men, because they did not give due honour to the gods, (Lib. L v. 138.) Many of Hesiod's precepts relating to religion, and the business of husbandly too, savour of a ridi- culous superstition ; but at tiiis we cannot wonder, considering in how earl)^ and ignorant an age he lived. *' Do not," says he (Lib. IL v. 343.) " make libation, to Jupiter with unwashen hands, " nor to the other immortal gods ; for they will not " hear, but abominate, such prayers." His poem On Days contains hardly any diing besides directi- ons of the most superstitious and absurd kind, but his two books On IVorks contain many excellent precepts, botli of morality, and coramon pru- dence. A 4. Sect I- THE FRINCIPLES OF Section II. Of the Superiority of Jupiter^ the principal God of the Greeks. Notwithstanding the polytheism of the Greeks, they retained so much of the primitive doctrine of one supreme God, that they gave this pre-eminence to their Jupiter ; and indeed seem to have ascribed to him universal dominion, and every attribute requi- site for the exercise of it. We see tliis even in Ho- mer, notwithstanding his account of such actions of the same Jupiter as sink him far below the level of many men. But a strolling bard, ^^ ho got liis liv- ing by accommodating himself to all kinds of peo- ple, could not conti'adict the popular tales of his countrymen, absurd as he might think them ; and they, served, as a ver}' convenient machinery ^ as it is now called, for his poem. Besides that one of the epithets of Jupiter in Ho- mer {fjLrjTisIa) implies wisdom, he is expressly said, (Iliad, Lib. XIII. v. 631.) to "excel all the gods ** and men in wisdom" ; and when the wisdom of Ulysses and also that of Hector, is praised, it is compar- I ^ THE GRECIAN PHILOS OIHV. compared to that of Jupiter (Iliad. Lib. II. 168. Lib. VII. V. 74) He is also stiled the omnipotent (Iliad. Lib. II. V. 115.) and said "to command mortals " and immortals" ( Lib. XII. v. 242.) He is repre- sented as asserting his own superiority to all the gods and goddesses, both in wisdom and power, and they all allow it (Iliad, Lib. VIII. v 9 ) &c. When the demolition of several cities, particularly named, is ascribed to him, it is added, " whose power is the *' greatest." (Iliad, Lib. IX. v. 25.) Theognis had the same idea of the great superi- ority of Jupiter, when he says (v 802.) " not even * ' Jupiter, who rules over moitals and immortals, " can please all men." With respect to the issue of the Trojan war, Ho- mer says, " the will of Jupiter was done." (Iliad, Lib. I. V 5.) as if the whole had depended upon him ; and yet there remains some doubt whether there was not, even in the opinion of Homer himself, an- other power in some respects superior to him, and which he could not control, viz. Fate as we shall see hereafter. We could not expect such attributes as these of the gi-eatest wisdom and power in the son of Saturn, though called the father of gods and men (Iliad, A5. Lib. to THE PRINCIPLES OF Lib, XV. V. 47.) for according to HesiocI, this Sa- turn was only the youngest son, or production, of the earth and the l^icavens, and had no higher epidiet dian diat of crafty (aixi^>.c/^-,/7fjr) and the hcoveiis^ one of his parents, ^vas die oft"s]7ring of the earthy tlie odicr of them. ITiis universal opinion of the great superiority of Jupiter had certainly a higher origin than Hesiod's Theogony gives him, and must have been die re- mains of a much purer system of theolog}', which taught the doctrine oloiie God, infinitely w ise, po\\'- crful, and good, a flivourer of virtue, and superin- tending all the affairs of men, as we sliall see this Jupiter to do. Section III. Of Providence* The faithcr wc proceed in this examination, tht>?pa) ** and die black Pare oe {gaptoiJi) and death, without " the concurrence of any deity and die fatiJ " goddesses, and cruel Parcce, Clotho, Lachesis, ''and THE GRECIAN THILOSOPHY. 2i •* and Atropos, \vho appoint good and evil to men ** tliat are born, vvlio revenging the offences of men *■■ and gods, never remit of their anger till they have punished the offender." Here the same powers have a different origin, and are altogether indepen- dent of Jupiter, or any of the gods, and superior to them all. Besides the sovereign power over life and death, and external advantages of eveiy kind, the affecti- ons and characters of men are sometimes ascribed to these fates. " The Fates," says Homer, (Iliad, Lib. XXIV. V. 49.) "give a patient mind to man." However, with respect to the important article of life or death, their decision a\ iis never violated ; and the time, and all the circumstances, of a man's death we^-e determined by them, as wtW as the death itself. Thus Neptune assures Achilles, who knew that he was never to return from the siege of Troy, tliat i^ was not his fate to be drowned in the river, when he apprehended that he was in great danger from it. (Iliad, Lib. XXI. v. 291.) He wishes that he might die by the hand of Hector, a brave man, but he knew that he should fall b^- a less noble hand. (Iliad, Lib. XXI. v. 278.) Whatever tJic gods might wish, tliey never fail. B 3. ea j22 TJIE PRINCIPLES OF eel to acquiesce in the known decision of the lutes, ' Achilles, lamenting his destiny, says that " Hercu- " les, though most dear to Jupiter, was conquered " by Fate, and tlie anger of Juno (Iliad, Lib. XVIII. V. 118.) *^ It was in the fates,'* he says, (Iliad. Lib. XVIII. v. 328.) ^' that two friends of *' his should die before Troy, as ^vcll as that he *' was not to return to Greece." It was one of the sayings of Pittacus. '' The Gods cannot op- *•' pose Fate.'' On several occasions the gods express some de- gree of fear least the orders of tlie fates should be violated. Neptune, expressing his regard for JEneas, advises him not to fight before the death of Achilles (Iliad, Lib. XX. v. 336.) though he kneA\' that it was not in the fates that he should die by his hand. Both Apollo and Jupiter express dieir concern lest the Greeks should take Troy be- fore the time ordained by the fiites. (Iliad, Lib. XXL V. 516. XX. V. 30.) On some occasions Jupiter, who is said to ha\« gi^ en this great power to the fates, seems to think it was in his power to control them, and to have been half inclined to do it ; but he yielded to t!ie |env)Uijtrances of Uie other i$ods, who opposed his THE GRECIAN PlIILOSOril Y. 23 his resolution. When Hector was driven by A- chillcs round the walls of Troy, Jupiter expressed an inclination to save him from death. But Mi- nerva says to him, (Iliad, Lib. XXII. v. 180.) " Would you deliver from death a mortal man, *' destined to die by the fates ? Do ^^ hat jou *' please, but vvc, the rest of the gods, will not give *' our consent." He acknowledged that it was i.i the fates that Sarpcdon should die by tlie hand of Patroclus, and wished to con\ ey him to a pkce of safety ; but Juno expostulating with him on the subject, he acqu iesccd. (Iliad. Lib. XVI. v. 432.) The independence of the decision of these fates on the will of the gods seems not to have been a fixed principle. For Ulysses, speaking to Tii-esias in the Elysian fields says, according to Homer, (O- dyssey, Lib. XI. v. 138. ) " Perhaps the gods them- *' selves have decreed these things. {.'Tr-KKMa-ocv) At what time this decision of the fates ^Aas made, is not said in these writers ; but it uas commonly supposed to be at the birth of every particular per., son. It was, however, considered as so in'cvocar ble, that these fates, though goddesses, were never prayed to, it being taken for granted that w hatever they had advanced it \\'ould never be altered. B 4. Thero 24 THE PRINCIPLES O? There ^^ as another celestial pow cr acknowledg- ed by the Greeks, but seemmgly not so early as the times of Hesiod and Homer, as they make no mcntifjn of her. This ^^ as Fortune. For whate- ver was afterwards ascribed to her, is by him, and all the other writers that I ha\e quoted, ascribed to Jupiter, or some other of the gods. Neither of these pow crs arc, however, known in the scriptures. According to them, everj^ thing in the \\ orld, life and death, riches and poverty, success, orde want of it, in war, and undertakings of any odier kind, are ascribed to the providence of that one Gody who created and governs all things, and whose w^ill, independently of any such powers as those of Fate or Fortune, decides upon every thing. To him we arc taught to look for ever)- thing, as being whoU}* dependant upon him, and accounta- ble to him. This frees the mind from tliat per- plexity, to which the wisest of the heatliens must have been subject, w hile they had any apprehensi- on of this hl'ind Jate to which, whether willingly or unwillingly, their gods themselves, widiout except- ing even Jupiter, submitted. Secti- THE GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. 25 Section VI. Of Moral Duties, and also of Death and the Con- sequences of'U. Almost all the writers that I have quoted in tliis part of my work deliver excellent precepts both respecting morals properly so called, and the pru- dent conduct of life, similar to the Proi^erbs of So- lomon, to which they will often well bear to be compared. Many parts of Hesiods poem On Works, and the sentences of Theognis, ai-e particularly va- luable on this account, though the superstition of the former, or rather that of the age and the coun- try in which he lived, as appears in the second piut of the poem viz. On Days, is extreme. On the subject of death, and its consequences, there is a remarkable silence in all the serious wri- ters of this period. The knowledge of the doc- trine of a resurrection was completely lost, but there are traces of a belief that the soul survives the gra^'e, though not of any state of righteous re- tribution, in which the righteous will be rewarded, and the wicked punished for their actions here, ex- B 5. cept 26 tiife prvixciPLE3 0? cept in those fables of Homer concerning the state of ghosts in tartarus and elysium, probably not se- riously believed by himself; so that the great sanc- tion of virtue, familiar to Jews and Cliristians was unknomi to them. In Fhocylidcs are some sentences which express a clear 1:)elief of souls surviving the grave. " Im- *' mortal souls," he says (v. 110.) " free from old *' age, li^e for ever. All the dead are equal," (v. 105.) "but God governs souls. Wc hope to " see the remains of the dead come out of the eai'tli *' into light, after which they will be gods. For *' incorruptible Souls remain in the dead. The *' spirit is the image of God given to mortals," (v. 100.) According to this the soul continues at- tached to the body some time after it is dead, which was the opinion of the Egyptians, and the cause, as it is thought of their endeavouring to presciTC the bodies so long by embalming them, and keep- jnsrthem in their houses. o After tlie perusal of this, how happy ought we to think ourselves for enjoyingdie glorious light of die Gospel, by which, and by which alone, life aiidim- mortality are brought to lights Without this light, the r^'ii'^oOTo/'/^^ujrA/avaik'd but little to the mo- ral THE GRECIAN PHILOSOPHY. 27 pal improvement and happiness of man. And as we proceed we shall find no increase of light, but rather of darkness, with respect to this subject. • F F THE PHILOSOPHY of PYTHAGORAS. INTRODUCTION. X^ YTHAGORASappeiirs to have been the first of all the Greeks who gave his m hole time to philosophy either in die acquisition of know ledge or in die com- munication of it to odiers. He is said to have been a native of Samos, and after having had some instiuc- tion from Pherec}des of Scyros, (of whom litUe is known, except that he liad some knowledge of Ori- ental philosoph}',) he wtnX. to Kg}-pt ; where, hav- ing the patronage of the king Aniasis, he obtained leave to be initiated into the religion and philoso- phy of die Egyptians. The priests made him un- dergo a \Qry severe discipline, including circumci- sion, but he submitted to everj^ thing they enjoin- ed ; and, continuing in the countiy twenty tM o years, may be presumed to ha^•e acquired all the know- OF THE PHILOSOPHY, 8%a)- Harmony supports tl:c world, " aiid ihc cause {aijs^ ) of this is God." Frag- menta. " God," he says, " placed the soul of the world " in its center, and also produced it externally,'* probably meaning that, diough seated in the center, its operation goes beyond it. The world is not the only inferior deity in this system. " In every part of die world," sa)s Ocel- lus ©P PYTHAGORAS. 37 Ins Lucanus (cap. 3.) "there are inhabitants of a nature proper to it, as gods in the heavens, men up- on the earth, in tlie higher regions demons, and of course the race of man must always continue. Matter these philosophers seem to have consider- ed as having always existed, independently of the deity, and as having been subject to laws which he could not wholly control. " Whence," Timoeus says, though with some degree of obscurity, *' There are two causes of all things, m'mdo^ those " things which are produced with reason, and ne- " cesshy of those which exist by a kind of force, *' according to the powers and properties of body.'* They, therefore, did not want any other cause of evil besides matter. Section III. Of the Human Soul. According to these Pythagoreans, the human soitl is not of a nature so distinct from the body, but that it has both some connection with it, and some properties in common with it, " The source of [^ vice," says Timoeus, is in pleasure and grief, C 3. " desire 53 OF THE PiriLOSOPHY *' desire and fear, ^vliich being excited in tlie bo- " dy, get mixed '\\ith the soul, and have obtained " various nhmes from their various effects, as love, ** desire," he. so that the passions are common to the soul and the lx)dy, though they are first excited in tlje latter. They maintained, however, the supcriorit}- of tlie mind to the body as when Archytas (Gale's, Op. myth. p. 732.) says, " In ail human ihingswis- *' dom is most excellent, as the sight is more so " than the otlier senses, the mind (vcvg) than the soul " (J'^X^) and the sun than the stai's." Here wc liave two parts of tlie soul, cr of tlie man, dis- til, guished b}' their respecti\e names, the former, signifying the seat of intelligence, and the other that of mere animal life. Tlmoeus explains tliis di\ision of die soul far- tlier when he sa}^, " One part of the human soul is * endued \nth reason ahd intelligence, but the o- *' the^Ii- vithout reason, and stuj/ul. Tlie former *' is the r.^iore excellent, but botli have their seat a- *' bout the head, that the other parts of the soul, *' and of the body too, mij^ht be subser\ient to it, *' as being under the same tabernacle of die body. *' But that part of the soul which is witliout reason, and or PYTHAGORA-S. 39 *' and which is prone to anger, has its seat about " the heart ; and that m hrch has concupiscence *' has its seat about the Hver. But the brain is the " principle, and root, of the spinal TnaiTovv ; and *' in it the soul has the seat of itsgovcrmncnt.,'' (Gale's, opus, mytli. p. 556. 557.) Theages divides the soul in the same manner. " One of the pai'ts," he says, *' has reason, another ** anger, andtlie third desire. The virtue of pru- *' dence," he says, " belongs to the first part, for- *' titude to the second, and temperance to the third, *' and justice is the virtue of the whole souL" (Ibid. p. 688.) How much more simple and satisfactory is the short account that Moses gives of tlie formation and constituent principles of man. After giving an act count of the formation of all other aniinals, he says that in the last place, God made man oft/ie dust of the ground., and then breathed into him the breada of life, after which he was a living soul, or being ; that is, after the mail was completely made, w ith all his powers, those of the mind, as ^^^ell as those of the body, God enabled him to breath, by which all his powers were excitcd^id brought into actual f :^ercise. Nothing is here said of any division of C4. tlie 40 0? THE rnii.osoPHY the principle of life, but he adds, that man ivas made in tlic Ukeiies" ofGod^ meaning probably hav- injr capacity of knoA\ in*:^. and of having intercourse ^\ith him, which other animals have not ; and that lie ff^atie him dominion over all the other animals^ proir:rties v;hicll he has, and fully exercises. TliC accort given by these Pythagoreans of the sLite of J le sou i afier deatli, is still more unsatisfactoiy ;and inconsistent. According to the golden verses, the roul isnnmortal. '* If,"saystlicautlior (v. 70.) " when you have left the l)ody, you arrive at tlic " fiee edicr, you \\ ill be \\\\\\ the incorruptible *•*■ immortal gods, and be no longer mortal." Tim- CKUS gives the followdng more detailed account Of the power of man to attain this state, as well as of the punishment of those whose \ices disqualify them for it ; but it isMith a sufficient intimation, that he considered it a:s founded on mere foble, calculated for the use of the \ ulgar, and by no means agreea- ble to truth , so that it is probable that at diis time the Pythagoreans had wholly abandoned all belief in a future state, "Music," he says, "and the " directiix of !t philosophy, are adapted by God, *' and die laws, for the improvement of the mind, *' and they accustom, persuade, and compel, that part of the soul which has no reason to be gendc, free • F PYTHAGORAS, 41 ** free from anger, arid desire Science, *' and antient and venerable philosophy, free the ** mind from false and vain opinions, and gieat ig- *' norance, and raise it to the contemplation of hea- *' venly things, in the knowledgeof which, if a man *' so conduct himself as to be content with his lot, *' and with the accidents of life, and dms aspire af- *' ter a moderate and temperate life', he is in the " way to true felicity. And certainly he to whom " God has given this lot is led by the truest opini- *' onsto the most happy life. But if on the other " hand any be refractoiy, and will not obey diese *' sacred precepts, he will be amenable to those *' la\vs which denounce both celestial and infernal -** punishments. Unrelenting punishments await " the unhappy manes, and other tilings mentioned *' by the Ionic poet, as derived from tradition, by " the hearing of which he wished to draw the minds " of men to religion and purity. On this account " I approve of his conduct. As we cure diseased " bodies by unwholesome medicines if they will not " yield to those that are wholesome, so we restrain *' minds with deceitful discourses, if they will not *' yield to true ones. On this account, too, fo- */ reign punishments are denounced," (tjiat is, C 5? such 4i9 Op THE PIIILOSOPKY such as were believed by foreign natioub,) '' a^tlic " transmii^ations of souls into \'arious bodies, ** viz. those of the idle into the bodies of women, " murderers into those of wild beasts, of the libicli- " nous into those of hogs or beara, of tlie light an4 *' rash into fowls, of ihc idle and foolish into aqua- " tic uiiimalb" (Gale's, Op. Myth. p. 565. 566.) &c. Certainly the man a\ ho cotild write this' could have no belit f of any future punishment of the wicked, ^\hateA er he might think of the state of the virtuous after death. But when the question luhat is death was put to Secundus, his answer is decisively against any fu- ture state at all. >' It is," he says, *' an eternal *' sleep, the dread of the rich, the desire of the poor, *' the inevitable event, the robber of man, the flight ** of life, and the dissolution of all things." (Gale's, Op. M}-th p. Gil.) Such were the comfortless prospects of this philosophy in its most advanced state. "What a \\ retched choice ^\■ould a christjan make by exchanging liis religion for tins. S£CTI-' ^F PYTHAGORAS. 45 Section IV. Of Got)d afid Eijil., Virtue and Vke. The writings of the Pythagoreans contain num- berless excellent m'oral maxims and precepts^ ex- pressed in the most forcible language, and their ac- count of what is good IS agreeable to common sense, %vhich we shall see was not the case ^^■ith many of the philosophers who came after them. " Some goods,*" says Archytas, " are desired *' on tlicir own account, some on the account of o- *' ther things, and a third bodi for their omti sake, *' and that of other things. What then is that *' good which is desired on its outi account, and " not for the sake of any thing else ? It is happi- *' ness. For the sake of this we desire every thing *' else, but diis for the sake of nothing further. " (Gale's, Op. Myth. p. 674.) A good man is not *' immediately and necessarily happy, but a happy *' man must be good. You musj not," says De- mophilus, " hastily pronounce that man happy f who depends upon any thing that is liable to '' change and decay, but on himself, and on God. f' This only is firm and stable." (lb. p. 624.) There 44 CJT THE PiEiLoscyriiy There was a gicat dcj^rcc of aiistenty in the dis- cipline, and p^enera] maxims of the Pjthagoreans, vvhicli forljade all unncccssar\' £.;n 'ifications. Vv'ith respect to theeommerre of the sexes, OeelKis Lu- canus, (Ch. 4. Gale's Op. Myth. 531.) says, *' God " gave pioper instruments, and appetites, to men ** not forthe sake of pleasure, but for the propagation "of the species. Iftherebeany commerce with " women with any other view, the offspring will be *' the banc of society. They will be ^\icked and " miserable, hateful to God, to demons, and to *' men, and also to families and states. For this *' reason," he adds, " laws were made in Greece *' that men should have no commerce with their " own mothers, daughters, or sisters, nor in any *' sacred place, or in public." He also says that " all commerce eontrar\'^ to nature" by which he no doubt meant sodomy, " must be prevented." Many of the Sentences of Dcmopliilus breathe such a spirit of devotion, lliat they iire justly sus- pected of a purer source than any heathen pliiloso- phy. On this account I shall quote but few of them. '' Do not ;isk of God what you cannot ** keep ; for no gill of God can be taken from you. <•' He, therefore, will not ^ve what you cannot " keep. OF PYTHA.CORAS. ^S ketp No .gift of God is greater llian vir- ' tiie A frugal and poor plilosopher lives a < life like to that ofGod/and he considers it as the ' greatest wealth, that he possesses nothing exter- * nal (tliat is out of his control) nothing unneces- ' sary. For the acquisition of riches inflames co- ' vetousness, but to live well and happily nothing 'is requisite but to act justly Being born ' of Grod, and lia\ing our root in him, ^ve should ' adliere to it. For springs of A^^ater, and the pro- * ductions of the earth, dry up, or putrefy, when ' cut off from their respective sources ' It is impossible that the same person should be ' addicted to pleasure, or the acquisition of riches, ' and be devoted to God. And though he should ' sacrifice hecatombs, he is the more impious, and ' farther removed from religion and God." (Gale's, Op. Mydi. p. 620, 625.) But what are the best maxim.s, precepts, or e- yen laws, without proper sanctions ? They will be admired, and respected, by those who are previous- ly disposed to observe them ; but on others, which is the tiling principally to be aimed at, they will have no effect whatever ; but may even be ridicul- ed, and openly disregarded. And what are the pro- per aeiKtions of virtue and piety, wbacii evidently h^ve 40 or THE PHILOSOPHY, &C. not always any rewiird in this life, but that provi- dence of Cod which extends to another, and with this the P} thagoreaji philosophy ^\as not pro* vidcd. SOCRATES 47 SOCRATES AND JESUS COMPARED. INTRODUCTION. X HE history of Socrates is so singular a pheno- menon in the heathen world, and his general beha- viour, and the manner of life to which he devoted himself, have in tliem so much that resemble those of the ancient prophets, and e\'en of our Saviour, that they ha-'/e alwaj^s drawn the particular attenti- on of the friends of diA'ine revelation , tliough these have formed very different opinions on the subject. If we look into any account of the Grecian phi- losophers who preceded Socrates* or who followed him (and some of the most eminent of the latter were his professed disciples) we shall find none of them to resemble him, even in the general features of his conduct, though his education as a philoso- pher was in all respects the same with theirs ; and they all fell far short of him with respect to purity o/ moral character. If we may depend upon what is transmitted to 4S tOCRATES AK» US concerning him by Xenophon and Plato, who were his cotcmporaries and disciples, both men of great eminence, (and there were no writer* in the hcatlien w orld whose characters stand higher than theirs) he was a very extraordinary man ^vith re- spect both to wisdom and \irtiic. And as Socrates had enemies as well as friends, imd his accusers must have had their friends too, had the accounts of Xenophon or Plato not been in the main agreea- ble to truth, it would have been in our power, ^as the age abounded with writers) to perceive some trace of their objections. But nothing of this kind appears. From both these accounts we must conclude 4 that Socrates was a man who, from early life, not only abstained from vice himself: and practised e- very thing that he thought to be a virtue, but one who devoted himself to tlie promoting of virtue in others ; continually throwing himself in the waV of every person whom hetlioughthe could benefit by his exhortations or instructions ; that by this means a considerable number of young men, espe- cially those of die best families, of much consider- tionand wealdi, intlie city of Athens, were strong- 1}^ attached to him ; and yet, that tliough he was poor JESUS COMPARED 49 poor, and many of them were rich, he never accept- ed of any reward for his instructions. In his conduct as a citizen he was most uncor- rupt and fearless, risking his popularity, and even Iiis life, rather than consent to any tiling that ap- peared to him unjust. When he was falsely ac- cused he behaved with the greatest magnanimity at hjs trial, and when sentence of death was passed up- on him he yielded to it with the greatest calmness. He refused to solicit for any abatement of the sen- tence as a favour, and declined all the offers of his friends to assist him in an escape from prison. When the fatal cup was brought to him, he di'ank it with the greatest readiness and composure, and died with much apparent satisfaction. The sentiments and principles of such a man as this, who lived in the most polished city of Greece, at u period the most distinguished for every thing that can contribute to fame, in arts, science, or po- licy, and yet the most addicted to idolatry of any city in Greece, certainly deserves to be investiga- ted, and his conduct to be scrutinized ; and this I shall endeavour to do in the best manner that the materials we are furnished with will enable me. D. £0 SOCRATES ANU Section I. Of the Polytheism and Idolatry of Socrates. That Socrates was an idolater, or a x\ orshipjx^r of a multiplicity of Gods, and such as were ac- knowledged by his countrymen, and that he con. formed in all respects to tlic popular modes of wor- ship, cannot be denied. " He sacrificed, says Xe- *' nophon, (p. 2.) both on the public altars of the ci- '* ty, and often at his own house ; and he also prac- ♦* ticed divination intlie most public manner." On trial he said, (p. 377.) " he had never sacrificed " to, or acknowledged, or sworn by, or even made *' mention of, any gods but Jupiter, Juno, and o- *' thers that wqyc received by his fellow citizens. " Do not I believe," says he, (p. 3.) " that the "sun, and the moon, are gods as well as odiers ?" *' Do we not suppose demons" (and one of these he acknowledged to have giAcn particular attention to him) " to be either gods, or the sons of gods, " (p. 21.) And in his last moments, after he had drunk the poison, recollecting a vow that he had made to sacrifice a cockto.i'Esculapius, he desired Crito, a pupil and particular friend of liis, to dis- charge JESUS COMPARED 51 charge it for him, and begged that he would not neglect to do it, (p. 186.) Though on one occa- sion he speaks of one God that constructed and pre- serves the world, (p. 318.) he does not say that he was the only God. All heathens and idolaters, civilized or uncivili- zed, were addicted to divination , imagining tliat by this means they could pry into futurit}^, and find out what their gods signified by certain signs, as the flight of birds, the form of the livers of the ani- mals tliey sacrificed, and many other things, which are generally considered as accidents. Socrates was so far from seeing the folly of these observan- ces, that he was to an immoderate degree assidu- ous in his attention to them. Being of opinion, (p. 8.) that " the gods signified their will by divina- " tion to those M^hom they were disposed to fa- " vour." Whenever he was in doubt about any thing of importance, he sent some of his friends to consult the oracle (p. 5.) and he advised his friends, if they had occasion for the knowledge of any thing that they could not attain to themselves, to apply to the gods in the modes of divination, (p. 352 ;) Say- ing, that " they who would regulate either their " own affairs, or those of the state, stood in need of " tliese practices." (p. 5.) D 2. Besides 52 SOCKATJiS A\D Besides ha\ ing Rcoursc to tlie usual modes of divination, Socrates believed tliat, iii)on e\ery oc- casion of importance, the n ill of the gods was signi- fied to himself in particular, but in what manner he does not cleai'ly say. He sometimes calls it a i-n'ice ((I>a;r<) p. 28. At his trial he said he had of- ten been heard to sa}' that a divine voice was fre- quently present Avith liim. Notw ithstanding all this evidence of the polythe- istic sentiments, and corresponding practice, of So- crates, Rollin and others suppose him to b^Ac been a believe r in the dhhie unity ^ and to have been sen- sible of the absurdity and folly of all the popular superstitions, and of the popular ^\orship of his country. But I am far from seeing any suffici- ent evidence of this. If he had had the -w eakness, which however is never ascribed to him, to conceal this before his judges, he might have avowed it be- fore his death, bearing a dying and most honoura- ble testimony to important truth; \\hereas, on both these occasions, his language and conduct were the very reverse of ^\ hat, on the supposition of this superior knowledge, they ought to have been. Indeed I much question whedier any per- son educated aj, Socrates A\as, among pol}Uieists imd JES-trs COMPARED. 5j. unci idolaters, could possibly, by the mere light of nature, have attained to a firm belief of the divine u - 'nity, though he might in some degi-ee, have been sensible of the folly and absurdity of the prevailing superstitions. Section II. I'he Sentiments of Socrates concerning the Gods, and their Pvffvidence. A polytheist and idolater as Socrates was, he had just and honourable sentiments concepii^S the di- vine power and providence, and of the obedience that men owe to the gods. And though his ideas on these subjects are far short of what ^ve find in the Psalms of David, and the writings of the He- brew prophets, the}' are much more rational and sublime than the opinions of the heathens in gene- ral, or those of the philosophers that followed him. We have seen that Socrates ascribed to a god the formation and government of the ^vorid, where- as, according to Hesiod (^hose iheogony was, no doubt, that which was generally received by the Greeks) the world had been from^ eternity, and the origin of the gods was subsequent to it. Socrates JD 3. point 54 SOCRATES AND points out in particular the wisdom and goodness of providence in the disposition of the different sen- ses andtlie several paits of the human body, as that of the eyes, the eye-lashes, and eye-lids ; and in the structure of the teeth, A\hich in tlie different animals are shaped and situated in the most conve- nient manner, the best adapted to their resix;ctive uses (p. 62.) He had, no doubt, the same opinion of the wisdom and goodness displayed in the structure and disposition ofever}^ tiling else in nature. He, moreover, believed that the gods know eve- ry thing that is not only said or done, but that is even thought and intended, though ever so private- ly ; being present in all palaces ; so that, whenever they think proper, they can give intimations to man of every thing relating to them, (p. 14.). *' The " deity" (T<3 5--/ov)hesays, (p. 65.) " sees and hears " all things, is every where present, and takes care *' of all tilings." And he makes this obvious and practical use of tlie doctrine, viz. that "if men be- *' lieved it, they would abstxiin from all base acti- *' ons even in pri\^ate, persuaded tliat nothing that *' they did was unkno\\'n to the gods." (p. 70.) The gods, he also thought, know ever}' thing that is future, though they conceal the knowledge of those things fi om men in general ; so tliat, *' though JESUS COMTARED. SB " though a man built a house, he could not be ecr- " tain that he should inhabit it, nor could a general *' be sure whether it would be proper for him to " march his army, &c." (p. 6.) Agreeably to this, it was his custom, in his prayer to the godb, to re- quest that they would grant him Avhat \vas good, without specifying what he wished for ; since they best knew what was so. (p. 45.) Like the hea- thens in general, he considered lightning as com ing more immediately from the gods, as one mode of giving intimations to men. (p. 312.) According to Socrates, it is tlie gods that have made the distinction between men and the inferior animals, having given them rational souls, so that they only know that there are gods, and can wor. ship them. *' There is no such principle and ex- *' cellent quality," he said " in the brutes ; and in " consequence of this superiority, men are like *' gods with respect to other animals," (p. 66.) Speaking of the goodness of the gods to man, he says, (p. 306.) *' they supply us not only with ne- " cessaries, but with things that are adapted to give " us pleasuae." He mentions particularly as their gifts, water and fire, the grateful and useful change 9f the seasons, and our various senses, adapted to D 4. peculiar 56 SOCRATEo ANB peculiar species of good. "This," he says, (p. 310.) " shews their concern for us." Socrates eoasidered all unwritten laws, obligato- rv on man in society, the origin of which cannot be traced, as having the gods for their authors. A- mong these he mentions the universal maxim, that the gods ought to be worshipped, (p. 327.) that gratitude is due to benefactors, that parents ought not to have sexual commerce \\ ith their children, ' and all other universally acknowledged principles of morality. In answer to the objection from our not seeing the gods, he mentions several things in nature, the existence and po\vers of which cannot be denied, and which are invisible or inscrutable by us, as lightning, the wind, and the intellectual powers of man; " Thus," says he, (p. 313.) " when we see *' the powers of ihe gods, we must reverence tlicm, *' though we do not see them." Nothing can exceed the respect that Socrates en- tertained for the authority and will of the gods, whenever, and in ^vhatever manner, it w as made known. " If," says he, (p. 51.) " the gods signi- *' fy their will, wc must no more depart from it, " and take other counsel, thmi wc should prefer tlie "conduct of a blind man, who did not know die *' road, JESUS COMPARED. 57 ** road, to that of one who saw it and knew it ; al- ** ways prefering the direction of the gods, to that ** of men.'* Agreeable to this, when he was addressing his judges, he said, (p. 40.) that "ifthey would acquit *' him on condition that he would discontinue his " instructions to young persons, \A'hich he bcliev- " edthe gods had enjoined him, or suffer death, he " would answer that he must obey god rather than " man ; and that if they should bani'sh him to an}'- *' other countiy, he should think it his duty, to do ** there what he had done at Athens." (p. 40.) *' Whatever be the situation in which a man is piac- " ed, there, he said, he should remain at an}- risk, " even of life, (p. 23.) dreading baseness more " than any thing else. So the gods having, as, I ** believe, placed me where I have been, and order- ** edme to remain philosophizing, and scrutuil zing " myself and others, I must not desert that station, " for fear of death, or any thing eke. " When Aristodemus, with whom he was dis- coursing on this subject, said that he did not deny tliat that there were gods, but he thought the}^ were too great to stand in need of his worship, Socrates replied, (p. 64.) that the greater tliey were, the more they were to be honoured. D 5. As 58 SOCRATES AND As to tlic manner in which the gods were to be honoured, he, like other hcatlicns, thought it Avas to be determined by the laws of ever}- particular coun- try. But he justly thought that the satisfaction the gods received from these markr, of respect did not depend upon the costliness of the sacrifice. " The oifering of a poor man," he said, (p. 49.) ** is as acceptable to the gods, as the more expen- ** sive ones of the rich.'* Section III. Of the excellent moral Character of Socrates. These, it cannot be denied, are excellent senti- ments, and much to be admired, considering the little light that Socrates had, \iz. that of nature only, uninstructcd by any revalation. And with him these sentiments were not merely speculative. His whole life seems to have been strictly conform- able to them, being eminently virtuous, and whol- ly devoted to the service of his fellow citizens. Xenophon, who knew him well (diough, hav- ing been his pupil, we may suppose him to ha\e been prejudiced in liis favour) gives tlie following general account of his character and conduct, (p. 359.) JESUS COMPARFD. 59 359.) " He was so religious that he did nothing " without the advice of the gods. He was so *'just, that he never injured any person in the ** smallest matter, but rendered every service in ** his power to those with whom he had any con- *' nection. He was so temperate that he never " preferred what was grateful to what was useful. *' He was so prudent, that he never mistook the " the worse for the better ; nor did he want the " advice of others, but always judged for himself. *' In his conversation, he excelled in defining what *' was right, and in shewing it to otliers, reprov- *' ing the vicious, and exhorting to the practice ** of virtue." 'riiough the circumstances of Socrates were the reverse of affluent, he would never receive any gratuity for the lessons that he gave, as all other philosophers and public teachers did ; and by this means, as he said, (p. 74.) he preserved his free- dom and independence. When upon his trial he was urged by his friends to supplicate the judges, as was tlie universal custom, in order to move their compassion, he refused to ask any favour even of them ; being of opinion that this was contrary to the laws^ according to a^ hich, and not according tofavour, judges ought to decide, (p. 317.) In 60 SOCRATES AND In all the changxis in the political state of the tur- bulent city of Athens, which were many in the time of Socrates, he adhered inflexibly to what he thought to be just, \\idiout being influenced by hope or fear. This was particularly conspicuous on two occasions. The fii-st was v. hen, being one of the judges in the case of the ten generals who wei'e ti'icd for tlieir li^ es on account of tlieir not col- lecting am.! bunting the dead after a naval engage- ment, and all tlie rest (influenced, no doubt, by the popuLu* clamour against tliem) condemned them to di ?, he alone refused to concur in the sen- tence. Soon after the citizens in general, convin- ced of the injustice of the sentence, though after it had been canicd into execution, appro>cd of his conduct. The other w as during the government of the tliirty tyrants, when, though in manifest danger of his life, he refused to appi^ove of their measures ; and he escaped by notliing but their o- verthrow , and the cit}* recovering its liberty-. That Socrates at the close of life expressed his satisfaction in his own conduct Cv\nnot be thought extraordinaiT. It was, he observed, (p. 366.) in concurrence widi the general opinion of his coun- trymen, and with a declaiiuion of the oracle at Delphi in his favour. For when it was consulted JESUS COMPARED. 61 by Ch?ert'phon, one of his disciples, llic answer was, tliat there \v'as no person iiiorc honorable (sXsvBepoTioov) more just, or more wise * tluu he, (p. 371.) He put, however, a veiy modest construction on this oracle ; w hich was that, though he kticw no more than other men, he did not, like them, pretend to know more. (p. 9. 12.) so that he only knew himself, and his own ignorance, better than other men. His reputation in consequence of it, and of his conduct in general, had no other dian tlic happiest influence upon him. For, address- ing his judges (p. 34.) he observed, that "itbe- ^' ing a generally received opinion, that he was wi- " ser than other men," he said that " whether diat *' opinion \vas well founded or not, he thought he " ought not to demean himself by any unworthy " action." Notwithstanding Socrates's consciousness of in- tegrity, and genemi merit, and the good opinion of the wise and virtuous, he was so sensible of the malice * In Xenophon the response of t/ic oracle Is ex- pressed by cra;(ppo!/cfT£p(^, but Plato always uses the ivord ver lo be of use to you." And when- she dcsiird him to come often to sec her, he only jestingly said^ that lie was not sufficiently at leisure from other engagements, (p. 251.) Ready as So- crates was to give ^ood ad>ice to young men, he said JESUS COMPARED. 69 said nothing to her to recommend a more viitKous and reputable course of life than that which he knevV she led. It was not in this manner that Jesus and his a- postles would have conversed witli such a person. He did not decUne all intercourse with women oi her character, but it was not at their houses ; and what he said was intended to instruct and reclaim them. He considered tliem ds the sick, iuid him- self as tlie physician. Women of the profession of this Theodota, if they had been M^ell educated, were resorted to in the most open manner by men of the first character at Athens, as Aspasia by Socrates himself, and by Pericles, who afterwards mamed her. Nor Avas fornication in general, with women of that profes- sion, at all disreputable, either in Greece, or at Rome. How miich more pure are the morals of Christi- anity in this respect. So great, however, was the prevalence of this vice, and so little had it been con- sidered as one, in the heathen world, that the apos- tle Paul, waiting to the christian churches \\\ Greece, and especially at Corinth, the richest and most voluptuous city in that part of the world, is urgent to dissuade his converts from it. See E 3. i particu- 70 SOCRATES AND t particularly (1. Cor. vi. 9. ^c.) where amongr those who would, be excluded from the king^Jom of hc-ivcn, lie mentions fornicators in chf first place. Knoll) ye not^ that the unrighteous shall not inherit the kingdom of God. Be not decei'ved; neitlier for- nicators^ nor idolaters^ nor adulterers^ nor effemi- nate^ nor abusers of themselves with mankind, nor thieves, nor covetous, nor drunkards y nor revilers, nor extortioners, shall inherit the kingdom of God. Section V. Of Socrates'* s Belief in a future State. Though Socrates had more just idea? concerning tlie nature and character of deity, and also of the nature and obligations of virtue, than tlie generali- ty of his countrymen, and even of the pliilosophers, he docs not appear to ha\ c had any more know- ledge than others concerning the great sanction of virtue, in the doctrine of a future state. In none of his conversations recorded by Xcnophon oa the subject of virtue with young men and others, is there the least mention of it, or allusion to it; which was certainly unavoidable if he had been real- ly acquainted with it, imd believed it. Speak- JESUS COMPARED. 71 Speaking of tlie happiness of his virtuous pu- pils, he mentions the pleasure the\^ would have in this life, and the respect that would be paid to them; and says that, " when they died tlicy would not be *' without honour, consigned to oblivion, but "would be for ever celebrated, (p. 111.") Hav- ing said tliis, could he have forborne to add their happier condition after death, if he had had any he lief of it? All his dissuasives from vice are grounded on some na,tural and necessary inconvenience to which men expose themselves by it in this life, but none of them have any respect to another. Thus he re- presents intemperate persons ^s slaves to their ap- petites, (p, 322.) and treating of w hat lie consider- ed as being the laws of nature, and therefore as those of the gods, as the prohibition of marriage be- tween parents an(^ their children, (p. 828.) he only says that " the offspring of such a mixture is bad; *' one of the parties being too old to produce " healthy children ;" and this reason does not ap- ply to the case of brothers and sisters. Another law of nature, he says, is to do good in return for good received *, but the penalty of not doing it he makes to be nothing more than being deserted by a E 4. mm\'^ 72- SOCRATES AND man's friends when he w ill have the most want of them, and to be forced to appl}' to tliose who have no friendship for him. {p. 329.) It is particularly remarkable that notliing th:it Xenophon says as coming from Socrates, not only in his conversations witli his pupils, but even at his ti-ial, and the scenes before his death, implies a belief of a future state. All tliat we have of this kind is from Plato ; and though he was present at the trial, and therefore what he says is, no doubt, entitled to a considerable degree of credit, it wants the attestation of anot/i^r witness ; and the want o^ that of Xenophon is something more than nega- tive; especiall}- as it is well known that Plato did not scruple to put into the mouth of Socrates lan- guage and sentiments that ne\er fell from him i as it is said Socrates himself observed, w hen he was shewn the dialogue entitled Lysis^ m ^^•hich lie is the principal speaker, as he is in many others. In Plato's celebrated dialogue intiiled Phosdo, in which he makes Socrates advance arguments in proof of a future state, wc w.mi tlie evidience of some person who ^\•as present ; for Plato himself was at that time confined by sickness, (P. p. 74.) so tliat it is ver}- possible, as nodiing is siiid of it by Xeno. JESUS COMPARED. 73 Xenophon, that he might not have held any dis- course on the subject at all. Besides, all that Socrates is represented by Plata to have said on this subject is far from amounting to any thing like certain knowledge, and real bdief^ with respect to it, such as appears in the discourses of Jesus, and the writings of the apostles. Socra- tes, according to Plato, generally speaks of a future state, and the condition of men in it, as ihi^ popular belief, wliich might be true or false. " If" says he (p. 46) " what is said be true, we shall in ano- *' ther state die no more. In deatii " he says to " his judges*' (p. 44.) " we either lose all sense of *' things, or, as it is said, go iuto soilie other place ; ** and if so, it will be much better ; as we shall be *' out of the power of partial judges, and come be- *' fore those that are impartial. Minos, Rhada- *' manthus, ^acus, Triptolemus, and others, who ** were demigods." Taking his leave; of them, he " says, 1 must now depart to die, while you conti- ^' nue in life ; but which of these is better, the gods '* only can tell ; for ill my opinion no man can *' know this." This certainly implies no faith on which to gi-ouhd real practice, from which a man could, with the apostle, line as seeing things invisible ^ be- E 5. ing 74 SOCRATES AN'D ing governed by a regaixl to thcin more than to things present, jhe one as ccrtuin as the other, and infinitel}- superior in vahie, t/ic things that are seen hcin^ temporary^ luh'iU those t hit arc unseen arc e- ternal. {2. Cor. iv. 10.) Notwithstanding tliis uncertainty of Socrates >\ith respect to a future state, he died \\ ith great composure and dignity ; considering liis death at tliat time as, on the whole, better for him than to live any longer in the circumstances in which, at his time of life (being seventy years old) he must have lived ; especially as a coward, discovering un- TJianly dread of death, in exile and disgrace ; dy- ing also without torture, surroundedby his friends, and admirers, who would ensure his fame to the latest posterity. That such arguments in proofof a future state as Plato puts into the mouth of Socrates should really have been advanced, and have have any stress laid upon them, by him, in so serious a time as just be- fore his death, is exceedingly improbable, from the extreme futility of them. They arc more like the mere play of imagination, Uian die deductions of reason. His first argument is, that as every thing else in nature has its contrary, death must have it also, iyid JESUS COMPARED. 75 and If so, it must be followed by life, as da}- follows night, and a state of mgiiaiice alwaj^s follows sleep. (p. 56.)- Bat might it not be said that, for the same reason, every thing that is bitter must some time or other become sweet, and eveiy thing that is sweet become bitter ? His second argument is, that all our present ac- quired knowledge is only the recollection of what we knew before in a former state, (p. 100.) But what evidence is tliere of this ? His third argument is, that only compound sub- stances are liable to corruption, by a separation of the parts of which they consist ; but the mind is a simple substance, and therefore cannot be affected by the dissolution of the body in death, (p. 111.) This is certainly the most plausible aigument of the three, but it is of too subtle a nature to give much satisfaction. If the mind have several pow- ers and affections, and be furnished with 4 multi- plicity of ideas, there is the same evidence of its be- ing a compound as there is withrespect to the body; and if the power of thinking, or mental action, bear any resemblance to corporeal motion, it may cease, and be suspended, though the substance remain. Are these sufficient arguments for a man at the point 76 SOCRATES AND point of death to build his faith and hope upon? As this appears to ha\-c been all that the most sa- gacious of the heatlicns could attain to by the light of nature, what reason have \vc to tx- thankful for the superior light of revelation, and csjjccially for the gospel, \vhich i^nrigs life and immortality to light. (2. Tim. i. 10.) Socrates does not, in this celebrated dialogue, make any mention of the argument from the um- 'Dcrsal belief o{ a future state, as handed do\\n by tradition in all nations ; \vhich, though far short of a proper proof of the docUinc, is more pluusiblc tlian any of the three arguments above mentioned. For it might be presumed tliat the ancestors of the human race, from whom the tradition descended to their posterity, had some proper evidence of T-liat they delivered, though that had not been pre- served, the doctrine itself only being retained. This, indeed, seems to have been the case with re- spect to the Jews. Though tliey \\ere in the time of our Saviour firm believers in the doctrin of a resurrection, tlx: record of the revelation (for it could not have come from any other source) had been long lost. How far short is every thing that Socrates is re- presented as saying of the perfect assurance with vliich JESUS COMI^AE^ED 77 Ivhich Jesiis always spoke of his resmrection to an immortal life, and of the glory that was prepared for him in the councils of God from tlie foundation of the world; when, as the writer of the epistle to the Hebrews says (-c. xii. 20.) foj- the joy. that was set before him, lie endured the cross, despising the shame, and is set down at the right hartd of the throne of God. Ho\y short it (Idls of the confidence which the apostle Paul, in the near view of deatli, expresses with ^-espect to his future prospects, (2. Tim . iv. 7. ) / haije fought the good fight, I have finished my course, I ha'oe kept the faith. Hence- forth; there is laid up for me a crown of righteous- 7iess, which the Lord, the righteous judge, "(Jbill give me at that day ; and not to me only, hut to all them that love fiis appearing. With ■\\'hat satisfac- tion and joy have thousands of christian martyrs relinquished this life in the assurance of a better. Besides, after all that Socrates advances in proof of a future state, he seems to make it the peculiar privilege of those who apply to philosophy, who havein some degree abstraic ted the purer mind from the gross body by intense meditation, (p. 83.) " This," he saysy (p. 94.) " was intended by the " authors of the mysteries when they said that non^ *^ besides the initiated wqmW live with the gods af- ^*te» to S-0 C il A T E S A X D '* tcr dcaili ; for that by tlie initiated were meant •' those >\1k) philosophized in a riBus) *' and that whether he had succeeded or not, it had *' been his endeavour through life to do so." According to tliis, the gnat mass of mankind have no more interest in a future state dian brute animals. But the gospel makes no diiference in favour of philosophers, or any odier class of men. According to this, all that are in the grai^es slicdl Jiear the 'voice of the son of man, (John. v. 28.) am. shall come forth. ; they t/iat ha'dc done good to the resurrection of life ^ and they that have done evil to the resurrection of condemnation. Then too (Rev. XX. \S.) the sea shall give up t/ie dead that is in />, and every man shall be judged according to hi.? ivorks. Sectiox VI. Of the D^mon of Socrates. Much has been advanced on the subject of the damon, as it is commonly called, of Socrates, or that divine voice , as he termed it, which gave him ^vamings about what he was about to do, if it Mas impro- JE:^ir3 COMPARED. 79 improper for him, and which was e\ IJently some- thh^ different from dmnatlan., to which he often liad recourse, or from any casual cfnien that might occur to him. This he said had accompanied him from his youth ; but though it forbad him to do certain tilings that he was deliberating about, it had never prompted him to any particular action, fib. J This divine voice did not respect his own conduct only, but sometimes that of others ; and he declar- ed that whenever he had, from this ^^'arning, signi- fied tire will of the gods to any of his friends, he had never been deceived by it. (p. 370.) Speaking of his general manner of life, and plaii of conduct, in devoting his time and talents to the instruction of others, he said, (p. ^2.) it had been enjoined him " by the gods, by oracles, by the <■<■ god" (probably meaning that paiticuUir deity from whom he had the hints alcove mentioned) " by *' dreams, and every other node in whicJi, by dl- " vination, they order things to be done." This was said by him in his address to his judges ; and he added that, though the deity had checked him in the smallest things tliat he was about to do, if they were improper (p. 44.) yet that when he was thinking of his defence, the deity had thus forbidden him. 80 SOCRATES A.VD him to make aiiy, and this not only once, but twice, (p. 365.) nor, while he was then speaking did he perceive any check with respect to any part of his conduct, (p. 44.) He therefore concluded that, since this divine voice liad not interfered on this occasion, it was best for him to await the sen- tence of his judges, though they should condemn him to death. " The situation I am now in," he said, "did not come to me by chance; for no- " thing can happen amiss to a good man \\ith rc- *' spect to life or deatli; since the gods never ne- *' gleet him. It is, therefore, better for me to die *' now, and to be exempt from all fartlier labours," (p. 47.) These intimations, in whatever manner tliey were communicated, are now, I believe, generally thought to haxebeen a mere illusion y when notliing really supernatural took place. Had these sugges- tions occurred only once or twice in the cour^ of his Hfe, the hypothesis of their being an illusion, or jnere imagination, might have been admitted. But they had attended him, he said, from liis youth, an,d had given him hints not only respecting liis own conduch (whicJi by his account had been yer}' fre- quent) but sometimes that of his frieixds; «fnd be- cause he had received no check from thi^ quarter with JESUS COMPARED. 81 ^vith respect to his conduct at his trial, heconclud" ed with certainty that it was right, and would have the best issue. Besides the admonitions of this kind which were communicated while he was awake, he had others he says, given him in dreams. One of these he mentioned just before his death ; which was that he should apply to music. On this he had put va- rious constructions ; and lest he should not have hit upon the true meaning of it, he com.posed w hile he was in prison, a hymn in praise of Apollo, and turned some of the fables of ^Esop into verse, which were always recited in a musical recitative. (P- 77.) This might have been nothing more tlian a com- mon dream, on w^hich he put an uncommon con- struction, in consequence of imagining tliat there was something supernatural in it. B.ut tliis could not have been the case with respect to the hints that he received when he was a\vake, whether by the fnedium of area! voice, or in any other way. In no other respect does Socrates appear to have httn an enthusiast. On the contrary, he was a man of a calm and even temper, not distinguished by any peculiarity of behaviour, or extravagance of any kind. And though he seems to have addres- F. sed 82 5/)CRAT£S AyiD bed lilinsclf to every person to whom he imagincci that hiii a(l\ ice would he useful, he was never eharg- cd with iKing impertinent, so as to give oft'ence to any. On the contrary, his address was insinuating ynd pleasing; so that his heiu^ers in general were delighted wih his conversation, and this through the course of a long life. Since, then, he persisted in his account of these admonitions to the last, and in the most serious sit- I'.ation that a man could l^e in, and his veracity was never qiiv.'st)oned, though I am far fromfoimijng any fixed opinion on a subject of so p^'C'\t obscuri- ty, I thi.'ikit may admit of 3 doubr, whctJicr ^lty r.:a net be supposed to have L.ome, in whatever manner diey were given, from God. I do not see any thing unworthy of the Divine Being in his dis- tinguishing this extraordinary man in diis way. Being no judge of the propriety of the divine con- duct, we must be determined in every case of this kind by die cuidcncc of facts, according to the esta- blished rules of estimating the value of testimony in general. These admonitions are said to ha\e been proper to the occasions on which they A\'erc delivered ; so that leading iogood, if they came from any superi- [ or being, it must have been a m ise and benevolent one. Jesus compared 83 one. They, would, therefore, tend to impress the mind of Socrates, and those of his numerous disci- ples and admirers, with an idea of the existence of a power su|5erior to man, though not in a manner so decisive and convincing as the express re\^elations that w^ere made to the Hebrew prophets* But v/hy it should please God to distinguish any on^ man, or any particular nation, with his peculiar gifts, and in what degree he should do this, is not for us to say. If we see good to result from it, we ought not to cavil or complain, but be satisfied, and thank- ful. That in an)' manner whatever, and in what degree soever, it shall appear that the maker of the world gives attention to it, it is a proof of the realit}'^ of a proindence in general, and of the divine interference out of the usual course of the laws of nature. It is therefoi'e a decisive proof of a great and important truth. And if he be not such a god as Epicurus and other philosophers supposed, one who, (whe- ther he had created the world or not) sat a perfectly unconcerned spectator of all that passed in it, but really interested himself in thfe affairs of men by oc- casional kiterpositions, it cannot be doubted but that, from the same principle, he does it at all F 2. ' times,. S4 SOCRAlta AS» times, though in a manner less apparent ; and that his final trcatnKnt of men will be accoicimg to his proper clwraeter, \vhatc\cr that be, if he be a right- eous and good be'mg, he will, no doubt, most ap- prove of virtue and goodness in men, and show it by rcM-aiding the r*fgl>teous and punishing tlic wicked. The reason why tie does not do this completely at present, though we are not without some intima- tions of his disposition to do so, it is not dlilicalt to ac e-junt for. The. e must be time and opportunity to Lrm ch:irac*ers. The existence of vice, as well as of virtue, in the \vorld is necessary for tliis pu r- pose ; and it is not till a cliaracter be properly form- ed that a suitable trc^ment can be adjusted to it. li our maker think of us at all, it must be for our good. Thus do such siipcmatiiral suggestions as Soc- rates asserts that he had aftbrd some obscure and indistinct e\'idence of a moral government of tlte vyorid^ and consequently of a future state of righte- ous retribution. Why such intimations were not more frequent, more distinct, or more general, is beyond our compiehension. If we be asked why the ^^ise and beiKvolent auUior of nature painitted the ribc and long continuance of the most absurd and JEStTS COMPAREB. 85 jand abominable systems of polytheism and idolatry to prevail so long in the world, or why he should suffer so much vice and misery to exist in it at pre- sent; why mankind should be afflicted with war, pestilence, and famine, and be subject to such dis- tressful accidents as lightning, hurricanes, and earthquakes, we can only say with Abraham of old, (Gen. xviii. 25.) that the maker and judge of the earth will do "what is right ; and therefore that all these evils, repugnant as tliey seem to our ideas of benevolence, may hereafter appear to have been the best methods of promoting general and lasting hap- piness, u ne- ed by the son of a caipcnter, of only about Uiirty years of age, and publicly in the temple, where he was alwa} s attended by great multitudes of per- sons of all ranks, and tliat no reply w as ever made to him on these oceasions. He by this conduct made liinistL'as many enemies as Socrates, but it was In a manner that sho\\'ed more courage. Both Jesus and Socrates took advantage of pre- sent incidents, as hints for their instructive dis- courses; but diose of Socmtes have the appearance of having been contri\cd before hand, -while those to which Jesus alluded were such as naturally pre- sented themselves at the time. What was peculiar to Socrates was his propos- ing to his hearers a series of questions, by means of which he made the conclusions he wished to have drawn seem to be their own ; so tliat all objections were precluded. A great peculiarity in the dis- courses of Jesus, though his manner was ve^^'^'ari- ous, and often authoritatively didactic, which that of Socrates never was, consisted in his numerous /^at- ables^ die meaning of which, when he intended it to be so, was sufficiently obvious, and peculiarly striking ; as in diose of the rich man and Lazarus, of the man who was robbed, and nearly murdered, on \ JESUS COMPARED 69 oii^his way to Jericho, and the peculiarly fine one of the prodigal son, and therefore more easily re- tained in memory, as well as adapted to make a stronger impression on the mind, than a moral les- son not so introduced and accompanied. At other times there was an intended obscurity in the parables and sayings of Jesus. He did not always wish to be understood at the time, but to have what he said to be remembered, and reflected upon afterwards. Such sayings were calculated to engage more attention from their being expres- sed in a concise, figuraj:ive and enigmatical man- ner; as when he said, (John ii. 19.) Destroy this temple and in three days I will raise it up. Such a saying as this would not be forgotten. His ene- mies, we find, remembered it, and his fiiends would understand his meaning in due time ; as they would his saying, (John xii. 31.) If I be lift. ed up from the ^arth I ivill draiv all men unto me ; in which he alluded both to his crucifixion, his re- surrection, and the universal spread of his gospel. It is very remarkable that there are not in the most elaborate compositions of the antients or mo- dems any parables so excellent for pertinency to the occasion on which they were delivered, for pro- priety and consistency in their paits, and for inv F 5. portant 90 SOCRATES AND portant meaning, as tliose of Jesus. Numerous as they are, they all appear to have l)Len unpamedi-' latcd, as therhaps with mocker}^ as they had treated him before. And yet it is probable that at the very time when they were putting him to the greatest pain. JESUS COMPARED. 99 pain, he pronounced that admirable prayer in their fevour, (Luke xxiii. 24.) Father forgive them, for they knoiv not what they do, there being no par- ticular guilt in their doing tliat oflice. Rousseau, though an unbeliever, was struck with the great difference between the cases of Jesus and Socrates in their last moments, and describes them in the following energetic manner. •' The *' death of Socrates, who breathed his last m philo- •* sophical conversation with his friends, is the *' mildest death that nature could desire ; while *' the death of Jesus, expiring in torment, injured, *' inhumanly treated, mocked, and cursed by an *' assembly of people, is the most horrible one that " a mortal could apprehend. Socrates while he *' tak-es the poisoned cup gives his blessing to the *' person who presents it to him v^ith the tenderest " marks of sorrow, Jesus in the midst of his ago- " nies prays — for whom? for his executioners. *' Ah! if the life and death of Socrates carry the *' marks of a sage, the life and death of Jesus pro- *^ claim a God." SfiCTIftN C2. 100 , SOCRATES AND Section V'III. OftJic a'ljfcrcnt Objects of tin- Inztruct'ions of Socrates and of Jesus. There is a remarkable difference Ijetueen thef»e- neral conduct of Jesus nnd liis apostles, and that of Socrates and the Grecian philosophers in gene- ral, with respect to tlie persons to tvhom they usu- ally addressed tJicir instructions. All the teaching of the latter Mas confined to persons of good condi- tion, such as were likely to have influence in the important offices and concerns of the stats ; but this was 110 particular object with Jesus. Though So- crates, unlike other philosophers, took no money for his instructions, his admonitions appear to have been confined to persons of tlie same class with the pupils of the others. There is not one of the dia- logues in which he is the speaker, eiUier in Xeno- phon or Plato, in aa hich the common people are an}' part of the audience ; so that the great mass of citizens could not receive any benefit from his teaching. On the other hand, the discourses of Jesus were addressed to persons of all ranks promiscuoasly, aiid JE6U3 COMPARED. 101 and generally to crowds of the common people, though without excluding any, and rather selecting those of the lower classes, who were held in con- tempt by the learned scribes and pharisees, for his audience. He was commonly attended by great multitudes, of whom very few can be thought to have been what we c^W persons of condition, or who were likely to have any influence in public affairs, to which indeed his instructions had no relation whatever. On two occasions, when crowds of this kind at- tended him, he fed them by a benevolent miracle ; ivhereas had they been opulent, they would, no doubt, ;have come sufficiently provided with every thJJig. We read (Mark vi. 34.) that ke was mov- ed with compassiwx towards tfie miihitude^ because iheywere as sheep not having a shepherd. And a^in, (Matt. xv. 32.) he says, I have compassion m the multitude., because they have continued with me mow three days, ojid have nothing to eat ; and I am unwilling to send them away fasting, lest they fjmit m the luay. Sometimes pes'sons of better condition, and of •a 'higl>er rank, such as Nicodemus, applied to Je- ««-6 ; sbut we i-kever find that he sought their socie- ty, or first, in:any -manner, applied to them, or to G 3. any 102 SOCRATES AND any of the scribes and phari^sces, who were the lead- ing men in tlie coruntr}-. Whereas, Socratei) \\ith the l)est views, no doubt, appears to have applied to no other. In this circiimstajice, ho\v'ever, we see a sti ikin,^ dlflerencc bcl^veen these two teach- ers of virtue. The object of Socrates was the in- struction of a Jlii\ but that of Jesus of the rnany^ and es})eeiuli those of the middle and lower clas- ses, as standing in most need of instruction, ^d most likely to rccci\e it wiih gratitude and without pi'ejudice. The apostles, in this and in every thing else, fol- lowed the example ot their master, and addressed themselves to all classes of men without distincti- on, and \\ithout ever selecting the powerful, the rich, or the learned. To tliem men of all descrip- tions were equal, as standing in the same relation to the common parent of all mankind ; equally train- ing up by him in the same great school of moral discipline here, and alike heirs of immortality here- after. Thus the apostle Paul says, (1 Cor. xii. 13.) We are all baptized into one body^ ivhether ive be Jews or Gentiles^ whether ive be bond or free. (Gal. xiii. 27.) As many of you as hai^e been baptized into Christ /Miic put on Christ. There is iwiiher Jew JESUS COMPARED. 103 Jew nor Greek, there is neither bond 7ior free, there is neither male nor female, for ye are all one in Christ Jesus. (Col. iii. 11.) There is neitlier Greek nor JeWf circumcision nor iincircumcision, barbarian, Scythian, bond nor fr/ee ; but Christ is all arid in all. This is language suited to the equal nature, and e- qual rights of all men ; but it \v'as never held by the Grecian philosophers, nor did their conduct at all correspond to it. With them barbarians, and espe- cially slaves, were of little account, any farther than they were qualified to serve them. Accordingly, we find that the scliools of the Grecian philosophers were attended by none but persons of considerable rank and v^'calth. The lower order of the citizens took no interest in any thing that they taught, so that their morals could not be at all improved by them. But by the preach- ing of the apostles a great and visible reformation was made among all ranks of men, and especially the lower, and of those some of the most depraved. Thus the apostle Paul, after observing M'hat was quoted from him before, concerning those who should ;zo/ inherit the kingdom of God, as idolaters, adulterers, thieves, &c. adds, but such were some of you, But ye are ixiashed, but ye are sanctifed, but ye are justi^ed, in the name of the Lord Jesus, and by G 4. tlie lOi &OC*ATT.8 AND r^}ePprrxt aftnir 'Qvrl, Many jxissik^s ra the epis- tles of the apostles shew the Mretohed state with re^ ■sjicd to iTKJTifcls in which the ^-os])ol fbundfnen,imd ho^- much, t'hey weie improved \Ty k. In none of the dialogues of Socrates do we iind any ivoman to be present, except Thcodota, tlie courtezan above mentioned , ancl though the do- mestic manners of the Grecian 'women of virtue, and of condition, \\ere such as that they could not with decency attend public discourses, the middle and lower classes of women in Greece, as in all o- ther countries, went abroad as openly as men ; and therefore might have been in the way of instructi- on, had the common people in general been addres- sed by the philosophers. But christian teachers ne\ er made any account of diiference of sex. When Jesus fed tlic five tliou- -sand, and also the four tliousand, dicre were "coo- men and children among them, as veil as men. The same was the case with tlK- chiistian churclics in Conndi, and otlicT cities of Greeoe. Even at Athens, ^\■hel•e Paul did not jnakc many con- verts, there was one woman ctf the name of J>ama- ris, (Acts xvii. 34.) Wliat her coiniit-ion was is not said. But as she is menliomid by name, it ib pr()h;ihlf* J'EStrS COMPARED. 105 probable ifeit, likeLydia, she was of some consi- derable rank, -at least her own mistress, not subject to (tlie controul of another. Section IX. InfersTwes tohe drawn from the Comparison of So- crates and Jesus, 1. In comparing the characters, the moral in- structions, and the whole of tlie history, of Socrates and Jesus, it is, I think, impossible not to be sen- sibly struck with the great advantage of revealed religion, such as that of the Jews and the christians, as enlightening and enlarging the minds of men, and imparting a superior excellence of character. This alone can account for tlie difference between Socrates and Jesus, and the disciples of each of them ; but this one circumstance is abundantly- sufficient for the purpose. I1ie inanner in \^^ich -5ie «iind of Jesus must iiave been impressed by the persuasion that he had of his peculiar relation to God on the one part, and to all mankind on the other, could not fail to make him superior to "Socrates, or any other man, in ele- va:tion of mind, what ever might be their superiori- G 5. \y 106 SOCRATES AND ty With respect to intellect, general knov. ledge, or natural ad\antagcs of any other kind. The far greater extent of the views of Jesus, as bearing an important relation to all mankind, and the most distant generations of them ; being their prophet and k'lng^ and also his own peculiar relati- on to God, the common parent of them all, being, as it were, his 'uicegeretit itpon earth, necessarily gave him an elevation of character that neither Socrates nor any other man could have. Interested as he was for all that should ever bear the christian name (which in due time he did not doubt would be the case with all men) \\ ith \\liat fer\'our did he pray, (John xvii. 21.) that they might be one with him and his Father, as they two were one, and that they might shcire in the glo-ry that was destined for himself from the foundation of theworhl- What dignity, as Avell aspiet)-, do we see here ? What other man could have used such language as this? The habitual piety of Jesus was such as could not have been expected in Socrates, or the most virtuous of tlie heathens. He appears to have spo- ken, and acted, as at all times not only in the im- mediate presence, but as by tlie immediate directi- on of God. The words that he spakcy he said, (John xiv. 10.) JESUS COMPARED ' 107 xiv. 10.) were not his owti, but those 0/ the Father ivho sent him ; and who, being always with him, and ahvays hearing him, performed the miraculous works by which his divine mission was evidenced. So assiduous was he in the discharare of his hiQ:h commission, that, as he said, (John iv. 34.) it was his meat and drink to do the ivill of his Iieavcnly fa^ ther, and Jinish the -work t/mt he gai^e him to do. Raised as he was to a preeminence above all other men, he seems to have been even more than any other man sensible of his dependence upon God, and he had recourse to him on all occasions. We even read (Luke vi. 12.) of his spending^ whole night in prayer to God ; and it was in obedi- ence to his will that, notwithstanding the dread tliat he naturally felt for the painful death to which he was destined, and the horror that he expressed on the near view of it, he voluntarily and patiently submitted to it. He prayed, and with peculiar earnestness, that the bitter cup might pass from him, but iramediately added, (Matt. xxvi. 39.) Not my will but thine be done. Nothing like this could be expected from Socrates, or any heathen. Their knowledge of God, his providence, and his will, were too obscure and uncertain for the pur- pose, though they had been ever so well disposed. As l08 SOCRATES AVD As the- w orship of Socrates was, nominally at Jeast, directed only to Jupiter, Juno, and the otl^r gods that were acknowledged by his counti}-, it was hai'dly possible for him not to retain such ideas as were generally entertained of tliem ; and not- withsUmding his endca\'oui-s to divest his mind of every tiling in their character that must have ap- peai'ed un\\orthy of divinity, such is the power of association, that it was impossible he should ever do it completely ; and if not, his reverence for the objects of his worship must have fallen infinitely short of that which Jesus, and the Jews in general, had for their God; and every sentiment of -devoti- on must have partaken of tliat imperfection. Tl^eir love, or attachment to them, their dread of their power, their dcvotedness to their will in doing, and dieir resignation to their will in suftering, the sense they had of their constant dependence upoaathem, and of their presence with them, must have -beau very little compared \\'Tth the same sentiments in the mind of a pious Jew, with respect to the one great object of his worship. This must be apparent to any person wIiq wrH read the book oi" Psiilms, Hnd cxji^ipai'e those devo- tional compositions '\vithTniy(H'tlierebe any such) of asimilarnaturc composed -by hcaflsens. But tiicre JESUS COMPARED. 109 there was nothing in the religions of the lieathens, at least among the Greeks and Romans, that could inspire any sentiments that deserve to be called de- votional. This striking difference no person will say was owmg to any superiority of genius in the Hebrew poets, and therefore it must have been owing to superior knowledge; and this superior knowledge could not have had any source but from divine revelation. Witliout this tlie Hebrews would, no doubt, have been as absurdly supersti- tions as any of the neighbouring nations ; and con- sequently their ideas of the power and providence of God as little proper to inspire sentiments of true devotion. To persons of reflection, and acquainted with the state of the heathen world, gind especially their turn of thinking and acting with respect to religion, there needs no other evidence of the truth of revela- tion than a compai'ison of the hymns in honour of the heathen gods by Callimachus, and other Gre- cian poets, or the carmen secular e of Horace, with the psalms of David, and other devotional parts of the books of scripture, with respect to justness and elevation of sentiment, and correspondent sublimi-. ty of language. 2. In 110 SOCRATES A!>rD 2. In the account that we have of the daemon of Socrates, what he says of it himself, and what ap- pears to have been gcnerall}' thought of it by others> we clearly perceive that there is nothing so natural- ly incredible as modem unbelievers represent with respect to di^ ine intcipositions, either in the case of the vulgar, or the philosophers of ancient times. The universal practice of having recourse to oracles anddiviniition, is alone an abundant proof of this y,\th respect to mankind in general ; and tlie idea of a mystical wiion with God, and a consequent inti- mate communication with him, came into Christia- nity from the later Platonists. In every thing of this kind the emperors Marcus Aurelius and Ju- lian, the great boasts of modem unbelievers, were as credulous as the lowest of the vulgar. Where, indeed, can be the impropriety, or im- probability, oftlie Being that made the world, giv- ing attention to it, and giving suitable intimations of that attention ; and this no uniform appeai-ances will do. It is not men's seeing the sun rise and set, or their observing the regular changes oftlie seasons, that impresses them with the idea of any tiling supernatural ; but unusual appearances, though equally natural, arising from the same ])rin- dples and laws of nature, such as thunder, light- ning, JESUS COMPARED. IH fiing, eclipses, and earthquakes, &c. Both history and daily observation is a proof of this. And, sure- ly miracles, performed by duly authorized pro- phets, do this infinitely better than any merely un- usual natural phenomena. This opinion of the natural incredibility of ac- counts of miracles, on which Mr. Hume, and af- tcr him other unbelievers lay so much stress, as what no positive testimony can shake, is quite a modem thing. But had tiiis incredibility had any foundation in nature, it must have been the same at all times, and in all countries ; and it must have affected all classes of men, princes and peasants, the learned and the unlearned ; whereas all history shews that a propensity to believe accounts of di- vine interpositions has been universal. It entered into all systems of religion whatever, and no nation was ever without some religion. It is impossible, therefore, not to conclude that a system wliich sup- poses miracles is naturally adapted to gain belief, and therefore that a pretension to miracles is far from being a circumstance unfavourable to its re- ception. It is rather a presumption in its favour. If it be any object with the Divine Being to giA-e mankind intimations of his attention to them, and govern- \.13 SOCRATES AND- government over them, which no person can say is impossible, or improUibie, he con Id not take any otlier mc^iod tiian that of niiiacles to gain his encL Much has been said about Socrates referring Alcibiadcs to a future instructor^ as if he had been sensible of the want of supcmatttral communicati- on, and tliat he hoped for, and cx^x^ctcd it. But supposin,£^ Plato's account of tlie conversation, (p. 295.) to be depended upon, which it certainly caimot, I can by no means infer so much from it. After expressing the uncertainty men arc under with respect to proper requests to the gods, he tells Alcibiadcs that '* he must wait till some person in- ** form him (r/j y.uB-/\) how he sliould conduct " himself both M'ith respect to the gods ai^ to. *• men." When, in reply to this, Alcibiadcs expresses much importunity to be informed who this teach- er was, taking for granted that it was some man (for he says ** I would gladly know who diis man. "is,") Socrates only says, that *' it was one who " cared much for him," meaning probably that he was much his friend ; "but that at present a degire " of darkness hung over his mind, which must " first be dispersed." I therefore diink it most probable JESUS C^OMPARED 113 probable that he meant hhnsdf^ but that he thought his pupil not then sufficiently prepared to receive fiirther instruction on the subject. 3. We see in the case of Socrates himsehS as well as in that of the people of Athens in general, the strong attachment \vhich the heathens had to the rites of their ancient religions. To disregard them, and to adopt other rites, was punishable with death. The Athenians, as well as other nations, occasion- ally adopted the worship of other gods, and other gods, and other modes of worship, out individuals were not allowed to do it. It must be done by the authority of the state, and at Athens it was by the court of Areopagus. On this account the apostle Paul, who was said to endeavour to introduce the worship of strange gods, and anew religion, vv'as brought before this court. But though heathen nations sometimes adopted other rites, they never abandoned then- ancient ones. There does not appear to have been any ex- cimple of this in all antiqi'.ity. Nor can we wonder at this, when it is considered, that in all heathen countries, the prosperity of the state was thought to depend upon the observance of the religious ritts of their ancestors, the founders of the respectixe states. No principle appears to have been more H. fixed 114 SOCRATES AND fiiiccl in the mmds-of-?H-mcn than this. Wcsee it in the extreme reluctance with ^hich some of the most absurd and indecent rites, as the Lupercaha at Rome, \\ere given up. .-Vnd to the \cry last, the more learned, and therefore, it may be presumed, tlie least superstitious of die Romans, constantly upbraided the christians with being the cause of the decline of the empire, by the introduction of their new religion. This attachment of the heatlicns to their religion was necessarily increased by its entering into all the customs, and confirmed habits, of common life ; .some rite of a religious nature being observed from the time of their birth to that of their death, and in fact from tlie moniing to the evening of eve- ry day. Every entertainment, public or private, was tinctured \vith it. No act of magistracy could be pciformed \\ iihout it ; and in countries the most advanced in civilization the public festivals, in ho- nour of their gods, were ver)' numerous. It will be seen in Potter's Antiquities of Greece^ that not less than sixty-six of them v;ere observed by the Athenians, and several of them were of some days continuance. And in general there was so much in them of festivity and amusement, bordering, to say the least, on licentiousness, tliat they \vere very fascinating to die common people. \\''hca JESUS COMPARED. 115 • When it is considered how discordant and incon- sistent all this was with the principles of Christiani- ty, so that when any heathen became a christian lie must change every habit of his life, as well as his opinions; that let him live ever so privately, he .could hardly pass a single day wrtlwut the change being observed, and that at the birth of a child, a marriage, or a funeral, it must have been conspi- cuous to all his neighbours, and the whole city, though he might have found some excuse for not attending the public sacrifices, and other rites of a visible nature, and though he should not have thought himself obhged (which ajl christians arc) to make an open ^irofession of his fairfi, confessing Christ before men^ we shall not wonder at the dif- ^ulty with which this great change must have been made, any more than at the alarm that was ta- ken when many converts were made to christianitr, and the consequent persecution of christians, as se- ditious persons, men ^vho turned the ivorld upside down, (Acts xvii. 6.) their principles tending to the ♦uin of all states. While the christians were few, and generally con- sidered as converts to Judaism, which Avas univer- sally tolerated, and while they behaved in a very H 2. peaceable 116 SOCRATES AVd ]>caccabic inoffensive munner, ihey might not give much alarm, noLuitlrfsUincIing their singularities; but when the}' were observed to be numerous, they ^\oulcl not fail to give alarm to nil heathen go- vernors. They were tllen exposed to tl^ ii'Ost unrelenting persecution, except where the acting magistrates w ere secretly disposed in their favour* Tlie r?pid j-^rogress of Christianity in these cir- cuip.stances will ever appear the most extraoidina- ry thing in t^ie history of the v oi Id. It afipeitrs from the epistle of Paul, th.at in his time there were christian churches in all the more considerable ci- ties in *he eastern part of the Roman empire. In the time of die emperor Trajan, the younger Pliny, then governor of Bithynia, complained that the rites ofthc ancient religions were generally dicontinued in his province ; and in the space of about three hun- dred years so numerous and respectable ^vcre the christians become, in the whole extent of that \-ast empire, that the emperors thems-elvcs found they miglit sjifel) declare themselves christians. To account for the rise and progress of Christia- nity, and the overtlirow of heathenism, and this without A iolence, in the whole extent of die Ro- man empire, in so short a space of time, is a pro- blem that no unbeliever has seriously attempted to solve. JE«tJS COMPARED. 117 solve, except Mr. Gibbon may be said to htive en- deavoured to do it. But his observations on the subject are so exceedingly futile, that they discover equal prejudice and ignorance, ignorance of the common principles of human nature, of the nature of heathenism, and of the state of the heathen Avorld. I proposed to enter into the discussion of this im- portant subject with him, but he petulantly declin- -ed it, as may be seen in the letters that passed be- tween us relating to it, published in the Appc?idix to tlye first 'volume of my Discourses en- tJie ei^'utcncc \ill honour the one " God in a better manner than the Barbai'ians, e- '* specially as instructed, and warned, by die Del- " phic oracle" (lb.) so that, in his opinion, the Greeks had divine instrucdon as well as human. He fardier acknowledges that, in die early ages, " the Greeks enterti\ined ver\' imperfect ideas of *' die gods and their w orship, having low ideas of " their characters, which they did well to correct. *' Because in time past, he says (lb.) our ancestors " formed WTong opinions of the gods, and dicir ** proge- OF PLATO. 123 '• progenies, as if they had been aniruals , we •' should now treat the subject differently." In this he alludes to the marriages of the gods and god- desses, and their reputed offspring, in odier gods, and also in their acceding to the iwpular notions, adopted and embellished by the poets, which gave him such offence diat we shall find he proscribed their writings, and excluded them from his com- monwealtii. Indeed, these notions of the vulgar were rejected by all who pretended to philosophy, or s-iperior knowledge, in Greece, from long be- fore the time of Socrates, as we have seen already and to the latest period of it. Section I. Of God and his Promdence, iTie being of a god, or of gods, for Plato uses both the phrases promiscuously, he generally takes for granted. Occasional!}-, however he introduces arguments for his opinion, especially (De Legib. lib. 10.) from the consideration of the structure of the earth, the sun, the stars, and the whole universe; *' How couid bodies of such magnitude," he says. (Epin.) " perform tlieir circuits without god. I tlierefore Ii24 OF THE PHILOSOPHT " therefore assert that t^od is the cause of this, ".nd " that there cannot be any other." Tic also ar- gues " from tlie varietv of seaso'-is, dividing time *' into years and months, and also from die con- ^' sent of all nations, Greeks and Barbarians.'* (De Ia:^. lib. 10.) But according to him, and in- deed ail die headien philosopliers without excc]:>ti- on, die matter out of ^hich the world was made, was not created by god, but found by him ; having existed from eternity as well as himself, but in a confused disorderly state, such as was generally termed chaos. The being of a God, or gods, Pla- to thought to be so evident, that he says (lb.) " No person persists in his disbelief of the gods " from youdi to old age." There is a great air of piety in the writings of Plato ; and this, no doubt, contributed to make his philosophy so -well received by the early chris- tians. In a letter to Dion (Epist. 4.) he says, " by *' the favour of die gods diings go well-" The same pious language occurs again in the same let- ter. That he pj cferred the term god to that of gods js evident from his letter to Dionysius, of Syra- cuse (Epist. 13.) in which he informs him diat^ in his serious letters lie begins with the tcrm^o^, but OF PLATO 125 bat thiitin those in which he was not serioushe u* ses the term gods. This, however, is no guide to us witli request to his dialogues, so that we iire left to distinguish his real sentiments from those sjDcak- crs to whom he gives the advantage in tlie argu- ment, whichj however, is sufiicicntly apparent. Notwithstanding Plato's great admimtioa of So> crates, he did not confine hiinself, as Socrates did,, to that philosophy which is of practical use in life, tending to rectify the dispositions of men, and incit- ing them to such virtues as would make them use- iul members of society, but indulged in various speculations concerning- tlie nature of God and the universe, and in a manner that liis master would not have approved. Indeed, on these great but ob- scure subjects he is in inany respects perfectly un- intelligible- According to Plato, the universe was constructed by the supreme being, whom he frequently dis- tinguishes by the title of ( ayoBog ) without the instrumentality of any subordinate being, ac- cording to a pattern of it previously fi>rnied in his Own mind. But there is great confusion in his ac- count of these ideas in the di'oine rhind^ (which he, no doubt, borrowed from the Pythagoreans as was observed before) so that he sorfietimes makes them a se-f |gi5 or THE PHILOSOPHY a second principle of things, and distinguishinsj be- tween what is sensible from w liat is ititellectual in man ; and considtring all that wc see here as the object of the senses ^ he supposes these ideas to be invisible to the senses, but comprehended by the intellect; and though they exist in the divine mind, the intellect of man has free access to them. He therefore calls them t/iings inte/IigibL', and says that what we see here are only the shadows of them, and changeable, whereas those intelligible ideas are the only things that are unchangeable, and perma- nent. The great object of philosophy, according to him, is to raise the mind to the contemplation of these higher, intelligible, ami permanent, objects. Aristotle ascribes this view of thinge to Hera- clitus. " The doctrine oHdeas, he says, is advanc- " ed by those who were con\inced by Heraclitus, " that sensible things are always flowing, and "changeable; so that if there be any such thing ** as real knoivledge^ wliich M'as supposed to re- " quire 2l fixed object, there must be things ofadif- " ferent nature from those that are the object of our *' senses- They must be fixed, there being no *• proper ^Knowledge of things that arc flowing.'' (Metaph, Lib. 12. Cap. 4.) T<^ OF PLATO. '127 To this doctrine Plato seems to allude when he says (De. Leg. Lib. 10.) " All see the body of ** the sun, but not the soul tliat animates it ; Not ** being the object of any of our senses, it is seen *' by the mind.'' All the meaning that I can make of this doctrines of ideas, perceived by the intellect, and not by the senses, things not fluctuating and variable, as the objects that we converse with are, is that they mean what we call abstract ideas, as those of horses, men, trees, &c. divested of the cir- cumstances of colour, size, place, 8?:c. which 31! . ways attend individual objects ; and in this there is no great mystery, but still every actual idea has^ some peculiarity or other, as well as real objt:/;. On this mysterious doctrine of ideas, which ^^ere personified by the later Platonists, and made a kind of second god, the immediate author of the creation, was founded the doctrine of the christian trifiity, as I have she^\'n at large in my History of Early Opinion concerning Jesus Christ. I'he mis- chief that has arisen from false metophysical prin- ciples has been most extensive, affecting every ar- ticle of christian faith and practice, as may be seen in several of my writings. Indeed, no branch of science has wholly escaped this subtle and baleful influence. Happily, however, good sense is at length 128 OF THE ^Hitosoriir length prevailing over every thing tliat is not found- ed on reason and truth; and with this, though seemingly foreign to the subject of religion, we are deriving that light which exhibits Christianity in its best and purest state, as it came from Christ and the apostles, who knowing nothing of heathen phi- losophy, or metaphysics, delivered the- plainest truths in the plainest language, though the)' have since their times been most strangely penerted by an unnatural mixture of heatlK'n principles, and heathen superstition. Notwithstanding the absurdity of Plato's meta- physical notions concerning tlie nature of God, and his itlation to the universe, his ideas of his attri- butes , and of his proiiidencc^ were in g-encral just and excellent, agreeing with those of ihc scrip- tures. Having frequently represented the Supreme Be- ing as the friend of virtue, and the enemy of vice, he says, (De. Leg. Lib. 10.) " God cannot have *' the disposition that he hates. God apj)rovcs of *' those who resemble himself, and is angry (vcjUfcra) " with those who are unlike to him. But iwthing " is so like God as a good man He is the most " sacred of all things," (Alcib. 2.) meaning diat he has tlie nearest relation to divinity. The OF PLATO. 129 The term by which he generally characterizes the Supreme Being is in the singular number, viz. the Good, {ayuB^') vindicating his most essential attribute. *' Evil," he says (Rep. 3.) "cannot " come from God," and in (Rep. xi.) " we must *' look to some other than God for the cause of e- " vil." This principle, however, he did not cairy so far as the Stoics, who maintained that God was incapable of anger, so that he would not punish even the wicked. On the contrary, Plato repre- sents the Supreme Being, though termed t/ie Good, as no less jusi than merciful. " That there are *' gods," he says (De. Leg. Lib. 10.) " and that " they are good, and respect justice more than- *' men, is tlie best introduction to a body of laws." After denominating him, " the beginning, the mid- *' die, and the end, and tlie supporter of all things," he says (De. Leg. Lib. 4.) " he is always accompa- " nied by justice, and punishes diose who depart ** from the divine law. The humble follow him " quiet and composed, but he that is ekvated by *' his riches, his beauty, or any other advantage, as " if he stood in no need of a guide, is deserted by ** lum ; and though such a person may appear en- ** viable to man, in the end he destroys himself, his ?* family, and the state." Agreeably to this, he I. Sraycj, 130 OK TlfE niiLosopiiv says, (Dc. Lev;. Lib. 10.) " Let not tlic sue- " cess of wicked and unjust men, who, though not '* truly happy, ai-e generally reputed to be so, and " who are extolled in poems and discourses, drive " thee rashly into impiety ; nor be disturbed tho' " diey should continue so to old age, and this pros- *' perity should extend to their children. Nor be " thou angn' w ith the gods w ho permit tliis, or *' think that diey neglect the affairs of men ; for " they will not be exempt from punishment after " death." Veracit}- is another moral attribute that Plato as- cribes to God. " The nature of God, and of " demons," he says, (De. Rep. Lib. 2.) '*ad- *' mits not of falsehood ; for God is altogether *' simple, and tnie in his words and actions. He " neither changes himself, nor can he deceive o- " thers, by vicious speeches, or omens, to men *' sleeping or awake." This he says by way of censure on Homer, who represents Jupiter as act- ing in this deceitful and unworthy manner, dis- gi'acefiil to a man, ajid much more so to a God. To the divine character in this respect he seems to al- lude, though w ith much obscurity, wlien he says, (De. Rep. Lib. 6.) *' As light and our view of it, ** are not the sun, but the resemblance of the sun, " so OF PLATO. 131 " SO knowledge and trudiarc die image oUhe Goody *' but not die Good," meaning God. The majes- ty of the Good itself is greater. Agreeably to this honourable idea of the divine character, he says that " the offerings to God," meaning those diat are most acceptable to him, " arc honour, vencra- ''* tion, and gratitude," (Eutliyphro.) But notwithstanding this, we shall see that, like all the other Jieathen philosophers, Plato strongly recommends a conformity to the idolatrous rites of religious worship established in his countr}% and even the rigorous punishment of all that did not conform to them ; so far were they from following the light they really had, and so little prospect wa.s there of the world in general being enlightened, and and reformed, by their instructions. The writings of Plato contain several just ami beautiful illustrations of the providence and moral government of God. " God,'* he says, (Politicus) *' is the shepherd of mankind, taking the same care ** of us that a shepherd does of his sheep and oxen. *' He takes care (Dc. Leg. Lib. 10.) of the smallest " things as well as of the greatest. None ofihe *' causes of neglect in men can take place with rt-- ** spect to God. We all acknoM ledge," he says, 1 2. ' (lb.) r 132 or THE PHILOSOrH'?' (lb.) " that the Gods set every thing, tliat lliey art *' all powerful imd good, jeathc best possible, nof *' can ihey be affected Ijy idleness or fear. The}', *' therefore, cannot des])ise or neglect aiiy thing be- ** cause it is small. Besides, there is more difli- " culty in seeing, and disposing of, small things ** thiui of great ones." " The universe," he adds, " belongs to God, " and he ^^ ill not neglect what is his own. He *' cannot be called a \\ ise physician who only at- *' tends to the body in general, and not to the par- *' ticular parts. Nor do governors of cities, or "masters of families, neglect small -dungs. Ar- " chitects also make use of small stones in laying *' the lai-rcr ones. And let us not think that God, " who is the w isest of all, is less w ise than man. *' Besides man is a worshipper of die gods," and tlierefore more deseiTing of his attention and care. To shew that the Supreme Being is incapable of I fcing diverted from the just administration of af- fairs by any imworthy motive, he saf^s (De. Leg. Lib. 10.) " To say that the gods aixr easily appcas- *' ed, is to compare them to dogs or wolves, which " are pacified by giving tliem part of the plunder, ** and tlitn sufici- them to worry the slicep. Cha- ** riotecps JDF PLATO. 133 ^ rioteersarenotto be bribed, nor arc commanders *' of armies, or physicians, nor arc husbandmer^ " or shepherds to l)e deceiA ed in this manner, nor *' even can crafty aaoIvcs thus decei\'e dogs. And ^' are the gods the greatest guardians of the great- *' est things, and are the keepers of the greatest '' things worse tlian dogs, or rhen of moderate ca* *' pacit}'-, who never act unjustly deceived by the ^* bribes of unjust men ?" There is haidly any advantage that men ar^ possessed of that Plato does not ascribe to the gods, and to their good Avili to men. " It appeal's to me," he says fPhilebus,) '• that God sent gifts to men by *' Prometheus, together with fire. It is not by " art," he says, (Epin.) *' but by nature, and the *' favour of the gods, that we cultivate the earth." He makes God the author of friendsliip, by dispos- ing dispositions that are similar, and formed for friendship, to unite. (Lysis,) " In the forming of " states," he says, (De. Leg. Lib. 4.) " we must *' begin with invoking the gods, that they may be propitious to us, and assist us in making laws." And after representing the advantage of the right worship of the gods, as the most important of all things to be attended to, he says, j( Epin.) *'No man " can rightly teach this without the assistance of 1 3, *'God." lo4' CF THE lI'lLOSOrilV He even asciibcs to d'niiic ins])iration tlie great thini^sthut eminent statesmen do for their eouutry, ■witliout understanding the nature, or foreseeing the consequences of them, adding, that " all good mcQ *' arc in some sense divine." (Meno.) i. It must have been among the Pythagoreans that Pli.to learned ^vhat he writes, but in a manner that is very unintelligible, conci:ming mmiberSy of \\ hich their philosophy made great use. It seems most probable that by metaphysical reasoning they made tlie Supreme Being to be represented by imity ; and as all numbers consist of unity repeated, and after thus proceeding from it are resolvable into it a- gain; so all things, after proceeding from their Jirst cause, will be resolved into it. But this is not the oni}' use that Plato, no doubt after the Pytha- goreans, made of this comparison. But t\ hate\er be the knowledge tliat we derive from this source, Plato ascribes it to God. " We affirm," he says, (Epin.) " that numbers are the gift of God, and *' on them all the arts of life depend, but this no " prophet ( ixavjis ) can comprehend. "W'hate- *' vcr is \\ ickcd and irregular is deficient ^idi rc- *' spect to number. Many animals cannot learn *' from their parents the use of numbers. It is *' God tliat gives us tliis power. The excellent " ancient, or PLATO 135 " ancients," he says, (Philebus) " who were near- " cr to the gods than we are, taught us that the uni- " verse consists of one and many^ which ahvays has " been, and ever will be. The resemblance of *' numbers dissimilar in their nature, when reduced " to a plane, is e\'ident ; and this to a person of *' understanding must appear not to be a human, *' but a divine wonder" (Epin.) We do not, however, find, that this mysterious doctrine of numbers was taken up by any of the succeeding sects of philosophy, so that it probably died with Plato. Section II. Of the Polytheism of Plato, With all Plato's knowledge of the divinity, of his attributes, and his universal providence, and of his preference of the term god to that of gods^ \\ hen he is treating of the divine nature, he was, like all hea- thens, a polytheist, and like them an advocate for the strict observance of the idolatrous rites of his country. He seems to have learned the doctrine of two principles in the East, %m his sayings (De. Leg. I 4. Lib. 10.) 136 OF THE rillLOSOPHY Lib. 10.) " Are there one or more souls? Not less " than two, tlie one beneficent, and the other ma- ,, leficent* ;" and also from his saying, as was quoted before, that " we must look to something "else than god for the source of evil." But this was never a doctrine that prevailed in the West. But that Plato considered more being-s than one to be entitled to the rank of gods, is evident from his saying (Epin.) " why should we not take the part *' of god who is the author of all good. But which *' of gods, perhaps the hea'ucns, which we consider *' as the most righteous, as all the demons and the " other gods agree to honour him ; and pray to *• him above all." What he meant by the divini- ty of the heavens ^ w hetlier the Supreme Being, or the sun, is not clear. He evidently considered all the celestial bodies as animated, ajid intitled to the rank of gods. " The ** divine race of stars," he says, (Epin.) must be *' considered as celestial animals, with most beau- *' tiful bodic-s, and happy blessed souls ; and tliat " diey * By this he might 7nean matter, which rvas by seme considered as refractory., and the only source of evil. But by saying it was maleficent, /ic seem- ed to consider it as a principle that had intelligence, end activity. OF PLATO. 137 ** they have souls is evident from the regularity of ** their motions." In a manner that to me is per- fectly unintelligible, he derives the different orders of gods from the diiferent elements in nature, plac- ing them, after mentioning by name Jupiter, Juno, and the demons, according to their dlflercnt ranks, and provinces (Epin.) He seems, too, to have con. sidcred the earth as a proper deity, and the parent of the animals that exist upon it./ " For the same *' reason" he says, (Menexenus.) " that a inoaier " bears her children, the eai'th has produced men. *' For it is the earth, and nothing else, that supplies *' them with food, as having itself produced them." Plato's dread of innovations in matters of religi- on, appeal's from the following passage in his Epi- nomis. " A legislator of the least understanding " will make no innovations, and take care not to *' turn his state to any othei' mode of worship, or " dare to move what his country has established by " law or custom concerning sacrifices; for hd " knows that no mortal can come at any certainty *' with respect to these matters." And yet he ap- proved of such additions to the public rites as would be an improvement upon any of them. ^' A " legislator," he says (lb.) *' will be free from I 5. " blame 138 OF THE PHILOSOrHY " blame if he thinks better of the gods tlian his *' prcdecebsors, aiid by excellent discipline honour " them with hymns and praises, and live according- " ly." This, however, Avas not introducing the worship of new gods. Having distinguished the crime oVtmpicty into three kinds, viz. the maint:iining that there are no gods, that tliey take no caie of human affairs, or that they are easily appeased by sacrifices, (De. Leg. Lib. 10.) he prescribes the following punish- jnent for the different degrees of guilt in this re- spect. *' If a man neglect the gods by omitting sacrifi- '• ces and despising oatiis, he must be punished, ** lest he make others like himself. There are ma- *' ny who deceive others in this manner, deserving ' ' to die more than one or two deatlis. Others de- '' serve only castigation or imprisonment. They " who tliink that the gods neglect human affairs, " and they who think them easily appeased, are not *' to be confounded. They who think so not from " any bad principle, but a kind of madness, should *' be imprisoned not less than fn e years, widiout " any citizen being allowed to go near diem, except '* those who will admonish them of tlieir eiTors. If " after OF PLATO. 139 "after this they contmue m their impiety, they " must be punished with death." *' Some who are obstinate in these opinions, and "■ draw many after them, especially the common *' people, whole families, and tlie state," meaning no doubt, the danger of influencing die whole state, *' should be confined in prisons surrounded by the ** sea, where no free person should have access to *' them, and when they die, they should be buried " without the bounds of the state ; and if any per- " son should bury them, he should be accounted *' guilty of impiety. If he had children, they should *' be taken care of by the state from the time that " the father was condemned." " There should also be a general law to prevent " any person from making what gods, or what sa- *' cred rites, he pleases ; and for this reason no per- *' sons should have chapels for Avorship in their o\mi *' houses, but perform their worship in public, and " be punished like they do so. If any person, not •' from childishness, but from depraved impiety, *' act in this manner, by sacrificing either in private " or in the public worship of the gods, let him be " condemned to death as impure ; and let the re- *' gulators of the laws judge concerning the mo- *' lives of liis conduct." (De. Leg. Lib. 10.) So I'lO OF THE rillLOSOPHy So intolerant were the \\iscst and best disposed of all tlic heathens widi respect torclij^ion, that \vc cannot wonder at the dread diey entertained of chi-istianity, u hen it began to spread, as it was ac- cording to their ideas, the hciglit odmpicfy ; aim- ing at nothing less than the overthrow of every thing that was deemed the most sacred, and ^^•hat had been established from time immemorial, and on V hich it was universally tiiken for granted Uiat the well being of ever}- state depended. But Christ was fully aware of this difficulty, and he apprized his followers of it. He enabled them, however, to overcome it, though they were for- waiTiedduit they should be hated of a// men for the sake of his name, that is, merelj- for being christi- ans, and that they who killed them would think t/iey didGod sennce ; which was actually the case, both with respect to Jews and heathens. And great as this obstacle was, which made all that was powerful in the world the enemy, of Christianity it finally triumphed ; and it is now the prevailing religion in all those countries in which Jupiter, Juno, and numberless odier objects of heathen worship, Mere most revered, but whose names are now to be learned from history only. This is an argument of peculiar importance with respect to the e\ idence of OF PLATO. 141 of Christianity, but can only be felt and undci-stocd by those who are acquainted with the opinions and prejudices of the heathens at the time of iis promulgation. And these opinions and prcju- dices appear now to be so unreasonable, and extraordinary, that a faithful account of them is barely credible- That Plato was both sensible of the great ignorance of the common people on the subject of religion, and of the Iiazard that might be the consequence of informing them better, appears from his saying (Timseus.) " It is a difficult thing " to discover the nature of the creator of the uni- *' verse, and being discovered, it is impossible, to " expose the discovery to vulgar understandings. This intolerance in matters of religion is the more extraordinary in the case of Plato, as he acknow- ledges the imperfection of the popular religion when it was first instituted in Greece, and com- mends those statemen who improved it, in order tQ do more honour to their gods ; and as he con- demns such poems as these of Homer and Hesiod, because they led persons, and especially young persons, to entertain unworthy notions of their gods ; when it must have been evident to himself, and every one else, that the popular religion, which he wished to perpetuate, was founded altogether on those rerj^ notions. Hesiod and Homer did not Ht 142 OF THE PHILOSOPHV make a religion for the Greeks, but onl}- made uge of what they found uni\ersally received to embel- lish their poems, and to please those before whom they were to be recited. So much was Plato offended at these poems, and all others of the same nature and tendency, that he excluded them all, without exception, from his commonwealth, though he A\ould retain such hymns as were composed in honour of the gods* But even the hymns, if they resembled those ascril^- ed to Homer, or those of Callimachus, are similar to the poems of Hcsiod and Homer, repeating the same popular and absurd stories. " We reject," he says (De. Rep. Lib. 2.) " poems from this " commonwealth, because they deceive men, as *' Hesiod by his accounts of Coelum and Satuni ; *' which, if they were true, ought to be concealed *' rather than divulged. For it must not be told a " young man, that the greatest ciimes may be " committed without any thing extraordinar}-hap- " pening, or that a man who punishes an offending " parent docs no wrong, but what the greatest and " best of the gods have done. The imitation of " the poets," he says, (Dc. Rep. Lib. 3.) *' at- " tended to in early years affects the morals and " nature itself, with respect to the body, the *' speech, and the \'Xiry thought." This OF PLATO. 143 This is the more extraordinan^ in Plato, as he a- sci ibes to tlie poets a real ins-^piration, the same that was generally ascribed to the priestesses of Apol- lo at Delphi (Meno.) " Poets who" he says, " re- *' scmble the Coi-}bantes, \\ ho are seized with a di- " vine afflatus, and knoAV not w hat they do. They " are the' intei-preters of the gods." (lo.) Section III. Of the Human Soul. The sentiments of Plato concerning the human soul are by no means clear and distinct, nor are they pursued by him to their natural consequences, as they uerc by the stoics afterwards. Matter was always acknowledged to be incapa- ble of any kind o{ action, and was always thought to be acted upon ; whereas the igneous nature of the soul was supposed to give it natural activity. A- greeable to this, Plato says (De. Leg. Lib. 10.) " The soul has the power of moving itself." He is not uniform in denying what was called passion to the mjnd. He must, therefore, mean it in a gross sense when he says (De. Leg. Lib. 10.) *' Where there is passion, there must be gcnerati- " on ; 144 or THE PHILOSOPHY " on ; and this applies to the body ," meaning, no doubt that where ^hcrc is generation, there must be a succession of beings produced from one another, that the death of some may make room for others ; whereas mind is incapable of any such thing, and consequently of that kind of passion which leads to it. It must, therefore, be immortal, and in this doctrine Plato is perfectly uniform and consist- ent. " Every soul," he says (Phcednis.) " is im- " mortal. That \\ hich is always in motion is from •' eternity, but that v^ hich is mo^•ed by another " must have an end." Accordingly he mention- ed the pvc-exhtcnce^ as well as the iTmnonality^ of tlie soul ; and in the East these two doctrines al- ways went together, and are al\\ays ascribed to Py- thagoras ; the soul and the body being supjTOsed to have only a temporary connection, to ans\ver a par- ticular puq:!0£e. " The soul existed," he says (De. Leg. Lib. 10.) " before bodies were produc- *' ed, and It Is tlie chief agent in the changes and " the ornament of the body." Agreeably to this doctrine of pre-existence, Pla- to maintained that all the knowledge we seem to acquire here is only the recollection of what ^\e knew or rLATo. 145 knew in a former state. '* It belioves man," he says (Phoedrus.) " to understand how many sensati- ** ons are united in one, and tliis is the recollection *' of what the soul, when in a state of perfection " with God, saw before." So greatly superior, in the idea of all the heathen philosophers, was the soul to the body, the latter being intirely subservient to tlie former, that we can- not wonder that they consider the soul as the \\hole se/fof a man, and the body as a thing foreign to him. "The mind," Plato says, (De. Leg. Lib. 12.) '* is all that we call oursehcs, and the bodv ■*• attends it: meaning as a servant. It is only af- " ter death," he says (De. Rep. Lib. 10.) " when it " has got rid of the clog of the body, that we can "see what the soul really is; whetlxi?r cbm- *' pound or simple, and the whole of its condition." It is on this supposition of the independence of tlit? Jriind on the body, that he advances one of his ar- guments for the immortality of the soul. " The *' soul," he says, (lb.) " cannot die b}^ any affecti- **■ of the body, but only by some disorder peculiar *' to itself. The soul by the death of the body ** does not become more unjust, and the death of *' the body is not the punishment of its injustice, *J but other punishments. For death is to it a free- K, " dom 14G OF THE PHILOSOPHY " dom from every evil. Since, then, neither the " death of the body, nor its own depravity, can *' destroy the soul, it must be immortah" That the souls of men arc emanations from the Su])reme Being, the fountain of all intelligence, seems to ha^•cbeen taken for granted by Plato, but I do not find it distinctly expressed in any part of his writings. He seems, hov.ever, to allude to it in a passage that I quoted before. But he general- ly cop.siders it as retaining its individuality after death; as when he says (De. Leg. Lib. 12.) " In *' ti'uth the soul of each of us is immortal, and *' goes to the other gods, to give an account of its " actions." Thio agrees with his uniform lan- guage about the rewai"ds of virtue, and the punish- ments of vice, after dcadi. Whether souls are to be reunited to their source afterwards, which he probably supposed, as being held to be die necessary consequence of their being originally derived from it, this retribution he must huAC thought \\ ould previously take place. \Vith respect to the threefold dhision of man ^ a doctrine held by later philosophers, I do not find any Uiing clear, or consistent, in Plato. And the term (ijyux'?) which in other writers signifies die mere animal principle in man of which they partake in or PLATO. 147 common with the brutes, he appHcG to the highest principle, that oi intdUge?ice in him, when he says (Alcib. 1.) " The body is not the man, but the soul {ijvxn) which makes use of, and commands, the body." Section IV. Of Plrtiies and Vices On the subject of mrtuc and "oice it may be tak- ken for granted that the sentiments of Plato were not, in general, different from those of Socrates ; so that it is unnecessary to make quotations from his writings recommending the practice of virtue, and dissuading from that of vice. His" belief in the being and providence of God, and in a future state of retribution, must have laid a foundation for pie- ty, and the practice of virtue in general, if what he advances on those subjects were his real senti- ments ; and the frequency with v.hich he uro-es them, and the stress that he lays upon them, makes it difficult to believe that diey wqvq not. In these respects he comes nearer to the doctrines of revelation tlian any other of the heathen philoso- phers that came after him, even than Socrates him- self. But his arguments in proof of the immortai- K 2. itv i4S Of THE PHILOSOPHY itv of the soul, and also those for a future state, ar« so weak, and tliey made so little impression on those diat eup.ie alter him, ihiit it is barely possible that he could have been influenced by them him- self; and his writings in general have much die air of being calculated to plciise the generality of his countnmcn, with whom those opinions wer? in some sense popular, and to ^hom they would, of course, tend to recommend him. And it is evi- dent f)om his histor}- that he was much more desir- ous of general applause than his master. On this accoui^.t there will ah\a}s remain some doubt with respect to the real sentiments of Plato on these im- portant subjects. Judging of him by his WTitings, we Ctinnot wonder that his philosophy was held in such high estimation b}' many of the more learn- ed of the eaily christians, and that they embraced it in preference to any other. With respect to the proper objects of men's pursuits in life, Plato says (Philebus) Uiat " nei- " thcr pleasure, nor wisdom, ai'C to be ranked with " thiiigs diat are absolutely good^ because ^\hat is *' good is perfect, and sufiicient of itself,'* A\hieh, he observes Mill not apply to ehher ofthem. But he M as far from entertaining the exu-avagant opinion of the Stoics, in classing bodi pleasure and pain a- mong OF fLATO. 149 mon^the things that are absokitely indifferent, un- worthy of the attention of a wise man, and incapa- ble of affecting him. , -.^ There are three remai'kable exceptions to the moral maxims of Plato, in which he would not have had the concun'ence of Socrates, viz. his re- commending a community of women in his com- monwealth, his approbation of perjuiy m matters of love, and in the licentiousness which he would allow soldiers on a militaiy expedition. How little must Plato have known of human ^lature, and human life, when he recommended a community of women in his republic (De. Rep. Lib. 5.) and an education of them the same with men and together with them, even so far as to ex- ercise in the gymnasia naked ; saying that nothing that was useful ouglit to be deemed shameful, that in former times it w^as thought shameful for men to exercise naked, but that now it was no longer so. Being naturally capable of doing many of the du- ties of men, such as serving their country both in the army and in civil offices, they ought, he says to receive an education proper to qualify them for those, though they should be exempted from what .w^s most laborious in any of those offices. By K 3. -thi? 150 or THE PHILOSOPHV this means, and sexual commerce being confmcd to a proper age, wliich he makes to be thirl)- for for men, and twenty for v\omen, a more hardy race of men he says, would be produced. These health}- women being accessible to more men, he says, would have more children, though this now appears to be, by a \vise providence, con- tiv.ry to fact, as prostitutes have seldom any chil- dien at all. The ehildien thus promiscuously produced he would have nursed and educated to- getlier, the stronger, howe\'er, in one place, and the weaker in anoUiCr by women cngi\ged by the state for that pui^pose, w ithout gi^'ing them any in- timation concerning their parents. He would not, howe'.cr, allow of any sexual intercourse between men and their own mothers or daughters, &:c. But it is not necessary to follow him through all the details of so visionary and absurd a scheme. Indeed, the objections to this scheme are so ob- vious, and so numerous, that it is not wortli while to enter into any serious discussion of it. I would only obscne that if frequent divorces have been found, as is universally acknowledged, to be attend- ed with much evil, a community of women, which it has always been the \ ery first step of civilization to prevent, must be attendul with infinitely more, and greater. With OF PLATO. 151 With how much more wisdom did our Saviour forbid even divorces except on account of adultery. When the change of a partner for life is considered as imposiihle^ the most discordant minds>reconciIe themselves to it, and live together more happily than if they had the liberty to separate, ^\'hich, in that case, they would >ipon every trifling disgust be thinking of, and contriving ; and this being the case of a whole society, jealousy, and violence in every- form, would be unavoidable. Besides, no mode of education is equal to that which arises from tlie affection of parents to their own childi*en, and the attachment of childien to their parents. This is a source of the purest satis- faction to both, and to the ver}^ close of life. And what has any parent to lock to in the infirmities of old age compai-able to the affection and attention that he may reasona]:)ly expect from his own chil- dren ? What a miserable legislator must that be, who would deprive mankind of the purest source of domestic happiness for any advantage of a politi- cal nature? Besides, ^vhat is the great object of all true policy ; but to give men the secure posses- sion of their private rights, and individual enjoy- ments ? K4. The 152 »F THE PHILOSOPHY The second great objection to the moral maxims of Plato is his allowing of perjury in mattera of love. " The laws of God," he says, (Convivium.) " allow of oaths," meaning a breach of oadis,^" in " affairs of.love. God," he says, (Hippias Major.) " pardons diosc \\ho perjure diemselves with re- " spect to love, as if they were childi-en, and did " not know what they did." It appears too that the laus of Athens took no cognizance of these oaths. But the Uw of God, in our scriptures, makes no such distinction. It requires the strict- est performance of eveiy oatli. Plato in his books on the Republic, censures with much severity the vice of Sodomy, which was too generally practiced in Greece. *' We must ab- " stain," he says, (Dc. Leg. Lib. 8.) " from all *' commerce with males. For this is being worse " than birds and beasts, among which the males *' have no commerce with otlier males, but with "females only; and if it be not concealed from "■ both men and women, the criminal may bepu- " nished by deprivation of all ci\il offices, and be '* treated like a foreigner." This, however, is prescribing a very mild and inadequate punishment for the most abominable of crimes- Notwithstanding, this he says, (De. Rep. Lib. 5.) or PLATO 153 5.) that "on an expedition soldiers should be al- *' lowed unbounded licence both witli respect to *' women and boys, as by this means they will be *' more inflamed to gain the victory," meaning that with the expectation of this indulgence they will be more ready to enlist, and to engage in any hazardous enterprize. The laws of Moses and of God relating to war are very different from this. According to them, wherever men are, in peace or in war, the same rules of morality are binding upon them, and the same punishment awaits the infringmentof them. Section V, Of Deaths and the Consequence of it. \\\ what Plato says on the subject of death, and the consequence of it, we see the stress that he laid on the practice of Virtue in general, though with- out distinguishing particular virtues or vices ; and if he may be understood litenally, his sentiments are decidedly in favour of a future state of retribu- tion, in which individuals will retain their separate consciousness, at least till their proper rewards or punishments are coijipleted. But much of what K5. hfi 154 OF THE PHILOSOPHY he advances on this subject has such a mixture of imagination, and of popular notions, that many I^ersons enteitain doubts of his writing what he re- ally thought. *' It is impossible," he says, (Epin.) " that there *' should be much happiness in this life ; but there * is great hope that after death e\'er}' person may " obtain the things that he most wishes for. Nor " is this new, but known bodi to the Greeks and " Barbarians." This is the only passage that I liave found in the WTitings of Plato in w hich he lays any stress on the argument from general con- sent, or Uadition, in favour of the reality of a fu- ture state ; and here he intimates some degree of doubt, by only saying that there is great hope with, respect to it. In other places he expresses more. *' In truth," he says, (De. Leg. Lib. 12.) " the " soul of each of us is immortal, and goes to other *' gods, to give an account of its actions, as die laws " of our countr}' express , w'hich giAes the greatest " confidence to good men, and terror to die wick- " ed, lest they should suffer the greatest punish- *' ments after death for the crimes committed in " this life. A happy man," he says, (Epin.) " will '^ learn all that he can from nature, j^i-suaded that " thus he \\\\\ live most happily, and when he dies "he OF PLATO. 155 ** he will go to a place suited to his \'irtuc ; and be- ** ing thus truly initiated, and having acquired " true wisdom, will pass the rest of his life in the *' contemplation of die most beautiful objects. " Justice is the best reward of the soul, and we " should not envy it those rewards of justice and *' universal virtue, which God has prepared for it " in this life, or the next." " The gods," he adds, " must know who are just, and who are unjust, *' and must love the one and hate the other, and they " wdll give to their friends every good that is in their " power." (De. Rep. Lib. 10.) Plato introduces one of his speakers in (De. Leg. Lib. 10.)addi"essing a young man licentious- ly disposed in the following manner. " O young *' man, who think that you are o^•erlookcd by the *' gods, consider that there is a seat of justice with " the gods who dwell in heaven, thatthc}- ^\hoare *' wicked may join the wicked, and they avIio are " good may join the good, in life and in death, and '' do and suifer what others like them do and suf- " fer. Neither, therefore, do you , or any other '' person, presume that you will be happy, so as to *' escape, or brave the justice, of God. You are " not overlooked by him, though you should go to *' the bottom of the cartli, or ascend into the hea- " vens, 156 or THE PKILOSOTHY '* vens, but shall suffer according to your deserts, " whether here, in the infernal regions, or in some *' distant place." This, however, being the ad- dress of an old citizen to a young one, may be no- thing more than popular language, calculated to reclaim him from his \ices, which would be inju- rious to die stite ; using such arguments, as whe- tlitr tliought to have any A\eight b}' the speaker or not, might make some impression on tlie hearer. The state of diose who die in battle, in die ser- vice of their country, Plato gives on the audiority of Hesiod; saying, (De. Rep. Lib. 5.) " If Hesi- ** od may be believed, they become terrestrial de- *' mons, expellers of evil, and the guardians of *' mankind." For this, therefore, he does not make himself responsible. In his Phoedrus Plato gives such an account of the state of souls after death, widi the various peri- ods of their purifications and transmigrations, as it is possible he might have heard in Uic East, but such as it was impossible he could be in earnest ia professing his belief of. *' Souls do not," he says, " return to the source "from which they came in less than ten thousand «' years. For they do not recover their wings till *' that ot pr.ATO. 157 *' that time, except the souls of those- who truly •< philosophize, and who love boys," (meaning probably sensual pleasure in general) " and wis- *' dom at tlie same time. These perform it in the *' third circuit of a thousand yeai's ; if after this *' they three times chuse this life, thus recovering " their wings after three tliou sand years. But other " souls are judged after the first term of life, some " of them going to a place of judgment under the " earth, to suffer according to their deserts, others *' ascending to a place in the heavens suited to their " merit when tliey were in the form of men. lliese, *' after a thousand years take their choice again^ " some the life of a brute, and again that of man, " provided it had formerly been the soul of a man. " For souls that have not seen truth cannot assume <' that form." This particular period of three thousand years Herodotus had from the priests of Egypt, who said that " when the soul had gone " through bodies of eveiy kind, terrestial, ma- *' rine, and also those of birds, it entered again into *' that of a man, and that this was accomplished in *' the space of three thousand years. This ac- " count," he adds, " some Greeks, whose name^ " he forebore to mention, clftim as their ov/n.J* (Lib.2.ch. 123. Euterpe.) Still 158 or THE PHILOSOrHY Still less can we think Plato to have given any credit to the following vcn- al)surd relation, which, however, he recites at full length (De. Rep. Lib. 10.) and without intimating any doubt of its truth. It is the story of one r>is, of Armenia, Avho after having lain dead on the field of battle twelve days, came to life, and then related what he said he had seen in the infernal regions, the whole agreeable to the fables of the poets, with many absurd additi- ons ; as that of the soulsof particular persons chus- ing to pass into the bodies of different animals, that of Ajax into a lion, that of Orpheus into a swan, from his hatred of women, that of Thamyris into a nightingale, and that of Agammemnon into an ea- gle, &:c. &;c. As Plato's account of a future state has such a mixture of fancy and fable, and so little support from argument, his declaration of his belief of it will admit of much doubt, as well as what he says of the immortality of the soul in general. They were Eastern doctrines, to this day firmly believed by the Hindoos and others, though Plato gives no intimation whence he had them. But excepting this doubtful case of Plato himself, they never gain- ed any degree of credit in the West. How happy, then, should we think ourselves, and OF PLATO. 159 and how thankful to God, for the glorious light erf the gospel, which leaves us under no doubt or un- certainty with respect to a future life in general, or the different conditions of the righteous and tlie wicked in it ; and especially for that most satisfac- tory'^ evidence of it in the death and resurrection of Jesus, as furnishing at the same time 2l proofs and also a pattern of a future universal resurrection ; ■\^hen all that are in the granges shall hear the voice of the son of man and comeforth^ some to the resur- rection of life^ and others to that of condemnation ; and when all men shall receiiie according to their works. "What Aveight has the mere opinion of Plato, or that of any heathen philosophers, admit- ting them to have been ever so much in earnest, compared to this ? We find nothing in our scriptures concerning the fanciful doctrine o^ pre-existence^ or of the state of souls separate from the body ; but are assured that as the man dies, the whole man shall rise again, with a perfect recollection of all that he had done, and therefore satisfied Avith respect to the state to which he will be sentenced corresponding to it. And this is all that w^e are at present concerned to know. It follows from this that we shall know our fi'iends as well as ourselves. Jesus assured ICO OF THE PHILOSOPHY, ScC. his apostles, that then t/iey should be nmth him ivherccer he should be, and see and partake of his glory y and tJiat this \^ ill also be shared by all ivho believe on him through their wordy that is all sin- cere christians to the end of the world. We are al- so assured that all those who shall suffer with him shall also reign ivith him for ccer. What ample encouragement is this to a life of virtue, and how will it enable us to bear all the troubles of this life, and the pains of death, be they what they may, with such an expectation. This is such hope and joy set before us, as was set before Jesus himself, and by w hich he was enabled to bear liis cross, and to make no account of the shame of that ignominious^ as well as painful, deatli. OF 161 b I THE PHILOSOPHY of A R I S T O T L E. INTRODUCriON. Ai .RISTOTLE wa- the disciple of Plato, but \± appears to have been greatly superior to hira, and indeed to all the other Grecian philosophers, in ge- nius and good sense. He had also considerable advantage from having been tutor to Alexander the Great, and from being assisted by him in the study of nature, which was wholly neglected by all the other phiiosopliers ; as they confined them- selves to subjects of mere speculation, which re- quires little or no knowledge of external things. Aristotle, however, himself followed them too closely in their own track ; and he seems to have taken great pleasure in collecting, and confuting, all tlieir sentiments ; in so much that, if he could be depended upon, it would be easy to ascertain the L. opinioni> ir)2 OF IHE rHILOSOfHV opinions ol'ull the pliilo.soj)hcrs wlio had preceded him. But he is said to have gixatly misrepresent- ed tliem, in order to make it the more eas\- for him to expose and confute them, which it is evident he took much pleasure in doing, that his own opinions might appear the more original iuid respectable. Ne\ er perhaps, was so much genius employed on more useless subjects tlian in all tliat we see in the greater part of the writings of Aristotle. The works of Thomas Aquinas, aiid the christian schoolmen, are, in this respect, far inferior to his ; but the subjects aie much more important, and the trifling, as well as the subdety, less. Though the reading of the disquisitions of Aris- totle on theological and metaphysical subjects be un- speakably tiresome, so that, probably, no person in this age, who has any proper idea of the value of his time, will ever read a tenth part of them , many of his conclusions, and summaries, are clear and striking ; far more so dian those of Plato, without affecting his sublimity, the art of his dialogues, or the eleg-ance of his style ; his aim seaming to have been nothing more than to express his own ideas, such as they were, in the most intelligible lan- guage. At least, so it appears to me, notwith- standing his acknowledging to Alexander, that though or ARISTOTLE. 163 though he had published his opinions, they were in fact not published, as only those ^vho had been par- ticulai'ly instructed by him could understand them. This may be true with respect to some of his writings, but it certainly is not so with respect to the generality of them ; and of this the extracts that I shall make from many of them will enable the reader to judge for himself, in what he writes con- cerning the Supreme Being, the human soul, and the nature of virtue and vice ; which are all that, in this work, I propose to consider ; as nothing else in the writings of the heathen philosophers is of such a nature as that it can be brought into compa- . rison with the doctrine of our scriptures ; since the bulk of their wTitings relate to subjects wh?ch probably never entered the thoughts of luiy of the sacred WTiters, and indeed were the least important in themselves, being frivolous in the extreme. It has been usual to class Aristotle amotig Ai//^- is!s, and his writings, as translated and commented upon by Averroes, in a later period, were the great source of modern atheism and infidelity ; but I dp not see any pretence for this charge in the writinf^ of Aristotle himself. For in tliem the Being and L 2. g-eneral 164 or TIIE fHILOSOPHY genei-al providence of God arc more distinct!}* as- serted than In the vTitinp^s of Plato ; and ^hat is pailic:;!arlr remarkable is, that, whereas Plato uses the term God and gods promiscuously, the latter never, I believe, occurs in any of the works of A- ristotle, except once in his trc.-'.tLc on ricl.es :^nd vice:,, in which be tvidcntly alludes to the popular feligion. In all his serious m riiings he U::Cs the t.c\n\ god[Bc^-) and never any otlier that implies plurality. And } c t ip. tliis he w^s, not followed by the stoic?, or any oth'-r philosophers. II he was an athcibt, he muL>t r.ct only have concealed, but have denied, and confated, his own opinions in ma- nv parts of lus writings, when he had not the least occasion to do it, as they ai'e not calculated, as t}io:jc of Plato evidently were, for the generality of readers. They ai'e also written in such a manner as not to be at all inviting to readers in general, in- dependently of the extreme abstniseness of tlie sub- ject ; so dial they could only ha\ e been read by persons well versed in the philosophy of tlie times. Besides, it is of more importance to my object to ascerUiin what were the opinions of tlie readers, than those of the writers; and those are most likc- 1}' to be found in such of their w orks as were c-al- culatcd for geneial use. To my object die private senti- OI- ARISTOTLE. 165 sentiments of an}'- particular man, and such as he did not think proper to divulge, or explain, arc of no consequence whatever. I want to ascertain the opinions of the disciples, and of tlie sect in general. Section I. Of the Being, the Attributes^ and the Providence, of God. The reader, I am coniident, will be surprised, as well as pleased, with many passages in the various writings of Aristotle, expressing his opinions con- cerning the nature, the attributes, and the provi- dence of God. " God," he says, (De Mundo. cap. 6.) " is the most powerful Being, immortal, *' and of perfect virtue, and though by nature in- *' visible to all perishable things, he is seen in his " works, as in the air, in the earth, and in the wa- " ter , for whatever is done in them is the work of " God." He expresses his approbation (Met. Lib. xii. cap. 7.) of those who say, that " God is from eterni. " ty, and die best of Beings, and tliat life, and a "continuance of existence, is in him." So fai* was Aristode from representing God as of the same L 3. rank 1G6 «F THE PIIILOSOrHi' rank and nature whh the hcavcnlv bodies, or from piving any portion of divinity to them, that he says, (De. Miindo. cap. 6.) *' Ciod conducts the stais •' according to number,-' tliat is, with regu larit}--, " and that on this account he may be called their " Coryplioeus." Aristotle -was even a professed advocate for the unity oiGod, and as I have observed before, he ne- ver, in expressing his own sentiments, uses the term gods, but always that o[ God. " There is," he says, (De Mundo. cap. 7.) " but one God, " though he has obtained ma.. • -^ames, according " to his different attributes. By the appellations of " ( Z;;y ) and ( Aio: ) united is signified that in him we live. He is Saturn, and Chronos, as hav- ing existed from eternity. " He is iilso called the *' thunderer, the gi\er of rain, {kc. It can only be *' God that is to be understood in the Orphic *' hymns. He is also called Fate, from thing-s pro- *' ceeding in a connected series ; and Nemesis, as " possessed of a divine power, which he exercises *' as he pleases; Adrastias, as the cause of every " thing ill nature, which no person can deceive or "avoid; and iiisas, because he exists always. " What is said of the P;ucoc must be explained " in the same manner. Finally, God, holding the " begin- OF ARISTOTLE. 167 ** beginning, the middle, and the end of all things, *' operates according to nature, accompanied by *' justice, called ( Anir,)t\\e vindicator of the di- " vine law when it is violated. And lie who would " obtain a happy life must be a partaker of divinity "from the beginning;" meaning, that he must derive it from God. The pcjpular opinion of a multiplicity of gods, Aristotle explains in the following manner, (Met. Lib. xii. cap. 8.) " The heavens (ovpxv.'^) are one, *' but it has been handed down to us by our ances- " tors, and the antients, and left in the form of fi- " gure to posterity, that these ^.r^gods, and that e- ** very part of nature has divinity in it. Other " things too of a fabulous nature are told to the *' multitude, to induce them to obey the laws. For " they say that the gods are in the form of men, ** and of other animals," &.c. Aristotle's doctrine concerning the providence of God he introduces by an account of an old traditi- on, which he says prevailed among their ancestors and all men, that " CA^ery thing was made by God " and out of God." He adds, as from the same tradition, which is better founded, that " nothing " can be well or safely conducted, without his care ^' and providence," (De Mundo. cap. 6.) L 4. His 1G*8 OF THE PHILOSOPHY 1 1 is account of the relation tliat God bears to the ■world, as its supreme j^o\'enior, is peculiarly strik- ing ; considering the little light "the heathens had on this most important subject. " WTiat the pilot is *' hi a ship," he says, (De. Mundo. cap. 6.) " What " tlie charioteer is in his chariot, w hat the prccen- *' tor is in a chorus, what the laAv is in a sUite, or a " general in his army, God is in the world, ^^'hat '• manifold labour, motion, and care, would diere " be without this." '' Whereas widi him every '' thing succeeds without laboui-, ^vidiout ti-ouble, " or infirmity of body. For, being situated in a "steady and immoveable situation, every thing is " moved at his pleasure, according to the different " forms and natures of things. In this he resem- " bles the law in a state, which, being immoveable, " go^ems eveiy diing in the state, all the magis- ^' trates having their ^oper place and province un- " der it. But he is gi^eatly superior to, and more " stable dian, our l^^^•s. For l>y him die whole "world of heaven is administered and governed. " All animals obey his laws, and even reptiles that " feed upon the earth." It w ill be seen in di<; following passiige diat Aris- totle hv;d not the same, or equally just, ideas of the opeiiiLtions and pro^•idencc of God that \\c are tiught * in V: OF ARISTOTLE. 169 ill our scriptures. " God," he says, (De. Mundo. cap. 6.) *' is the preserver of every thing tliat is " done in the world, and also the author of it, with. <* out being affected by \\eariness, as a human " workman, or an animal, and of things at a dis- *' tance, as well as near. For ha^ing his scat in " the highest region, from which he is called the " supreme (TTra]^) those bodies which are nearest " to him feel the most of his power ; but I cannot '' tlijnk him concenied in things that arc low and " mean ; but that rather, like the king of Persia, *' he knows and acts by his agents. Tims he moves " the sun, and moon, and the whole heavens, and " is the author of every thing that is safe and sakita- *' ry in the world. Not that he stands in need of " tlie assistance of others, as he does every thing " without difficulty, with a simple motion." (Dt Mundo. cap. 6.) I would observe on this, that philosophy, as woll as true piety, considers every tiling in the universe as, in a proper ser^, equal in the eye of God, who made the smallest things as wc^l as the greatest, as equally subservient to his puq^ose. Moses repre- sents him as having' made by tlie cxi:rtion of the same power, reptiles as \\ell as men, the grass of the fields as v.'cll as die largest tt:ccs, and iill these L 5. as 170 OF THE PHILOSOPHY as well as the sun, moon, and stars. " He said, let *' them be, and they rose into existence-" David represents all animals, as well as men, as equally dependent upon God, even for their daily food ; when he says the lions roar cuer their prey^ and seek their meat from God ; t/iat fie feedeth the r aliens , ^hcn they cry^ and that all creatures haiic their lJcs tip unto him, and lie satisfies the desire of CDery liv- ing thing. Agreeably to this, Jesus says a spar- row) falls not to the ground without hiin, and it is he that so beautifully clothes the lillies of the field. So incomprehensible has the doctrine of the uni- versal presence, and constant agency, of one jnind been thought by the generality of mankind, who are apt to judge of all intellects by tlieir own, that many of the most intelligent and speculative of men have thought it necessary to provide him Mith some assistant, or assistants, in his extensive and VcU^ious operations. Hence the origin of idolatry in genenil, from its being thought absolutely impos- sible that one mind should comprehend, and at- tend to, e\'ery thing. Hence the ideas of Plato were improved into the notion of <7 second God, the (A',;^/ci',:y3>^) or immediate agent in die work of cre- ation ; iind hence also die christian logos^ as a Bc- ^ng separate from the deity, and the still pre\ ailing opinion, OF ARISTO fs^ 17o opinion, that it was not God tl who made the world, and th^ Aristotle, therefore, must be j this idea, as he was not singuj peared to many others, as well more honourable to the Supreii ^ ^. ^_^ him not to be immediately concerned in an}' tWng, that is low or mean. EA-en some christian philosophers seem still to be intangledin this idea, when they speak oftlie opera- tion o^ general lanvs^ as if they could relieve the de- ity from any part of his immediate agency. For what are laws, or general rules, in the hands of those who have no power to execute them ? Why should a stone, for example, move towards the earth? It is said, by the law of gravity. But Vv^hat is that law, or any other law of nature, without a power of agency? There must, therefore, be an universal agency of the author of nature through the whole extent of his wj^rks, the meanest, as they appear to us, as well as the greatest. And what we call ge- neral laws cannot be any thing else than his general mode of acting, or exerting his power and influ- ence. Incomprehensible as this must ever appear to us, it is not the only circumstance relating to tho Supreme Being that is so. In fact, all his attii- butse, OF THE J'HILOSoi'HY 1 tO outes, aiid especially his eternal and necessary ex- istence must ever be so to firjtc minds, Que is, to all Beings except to liimself. There is another work ascribed to Aristotle, not now extcmt in Greek, Iwt said to ha\ e been trans- lated from the Greek Into .Vrabic, and then fi"om ll:c Arabic into the Latin, in which \vc now have it; puq:orting to contain the doctrine of the Egjpti- ans concerning God and nature, 'w hich I have not yet quoted ; De secretiore parte dlvinre sapenti» scrundnm .-^Qiyptios. (Lib. 11.) Indeed, it ap- pears iiii^hly improbable that .Vristolle should have written the whole of it, though the minuteness and subtlety of the discussions contained in it \ery much resemble his usual m/) ** the principle of all vegetative, sensation intellect *' and motion." What Aristotle is represented as savino- in the doubtful treatise mentioned before, fa\'ours the idea which prevailed at the revival of his philosophy, of a common princ'ipk 0/ life and motion^ tho' not di- rectly, of intelligence^ pervading all nature, and re- solvable into its source at the death of each indivi- dual. "Plants and animals," he says (/Egypt. Lib. viii. cap. 2.) *' besides that soul which is pe- " culiar to each, enjoy the life of the common soul ; *' because they cannot gi\e aliment to others witli- ** out paiting with their own lives. The first au- " thor of form," he says (lb.) " gave reason to the " common soul." He even says that this is the principle of life ^ though he does not call it a soul. It is in all the elements, " in fire, air, and water." Here however he allow s a separate individual soul M 2. to 178 or THE piiii.osopiir to each, bcbldcs a piirticipalion in the common soul. The docti-'rnc of tlic fnc- existence of souls and of their descent into mortal bodies, I do not find men- tioned in any of the genuine writings of Aristotle ; but it is mentioned in the doubtful treatise quoted above, in the exordium to which he says (/Eg}pt. Lib. i. cap. 1.) *' Wc shall then describe the de- " scent of souls into bodies, and their ascent." But I do not fuid that he does this in any part of this treatise. Concerning the state of the soul, or of die man, after death, Aristotle is nearly silent ; and what he docs say, or rather hint, is expressive of much doubt. " If any thing," he says (De Moribus. Lib. i. cap. IL) " be enjoyed by the dead, AvheUicr *' srood or ca il, it must be very little, either in it- ■^^ self, or to them; not suflicicntto make them " happy or unhappy, who were not so before." This w ith respect to the souls, or the shades, of the virtuous, is pretty nearly the sentiment which Homer puts into the mouth of Achilles in the Ely- sian fields ; ^^ ho says, he had rather be a slave to the meanest person upon earth, than king of all in the regions below. Section" OF ARISTOTLE. 173 Section III. Of Happiness^ and of Virtue and Vice. Aristotle's ideas of happiness, and of things that should be classed among goods or ciiih^ are very different from those of the Stoics who came after him, and, as may be inferred from what he says, those of many who preceded him; but they are far more agreeable to reason and die common sense of mankind- In consequence of his making more account of the body dian other philosopers of his time did, lie justly observes (De Moribus. Lib. i. cap 4.) that '^' if good be one^ which he sa}*s is the common opi- " nion, or a thing separate from c\Try other, and in- " dependent of every other, it cannot be procured '■'■ by man, or depend upon any actions of his. *' Some kinds of good," he says, (Mag. Mor. Lib. i. cap. 3.) *' relate to the soul, and the \irtues, and *' some to the body, as health, beautv, and other ex- " ternal things, opulence, &c. It is agreed by *' all," he says, (Eudem. Lib. vi. cap. 13.) " that " grief (Autt;?) is an evil, and to be avoided. For " whatever is to be a\'oided is an evil, and ^vhate\'cr M3. "is 180 OF THE I'HILOSOPHY " is to be pursued is a good. It is not easy" he fiirtlier says, " for him to be completely happy, who *' is either remarkably deformed, or of mean condi- " tion, or \'. ho lives a solitary life, or is without " children ; and much less if he have clUldren that " are very profligate. Some, therefore, place hap- *' piness in outward prosperity, and some in virtue. " He, therefore, must be pronounced happy, who *' is both virtuous, and possessed of external " goods." (De Moribus. Lib. i. cap. 9 and cap. il.) In this opinion he would now, I believe, have the general concurrence of mankind. On the subject o^ virtues and vices, the ideas of Aristotle are peculiar to himself, but he was cer- tainly at liberty to make his o^^Tl definitions, tliough this may lead to mistake when they are different from those that are commonly received. NoAv virtue is, I believe, universally considered .ns the property of the soul, independent of any thing relating to the body, and only on the will and inten- tion, arising from the inward disposition of tiic mind. But it is not so \; ith Aristotle. He consi- ders every circumstance that is reputable, and that makes a man appear to ad\antage in the eyes of others, as a virtue, (api/j;) and e\ery thing that is disreputable, as a vice. His general definition (Dc \'irlutibus.) OF ARISTOTLE. 181 Vlrtutibas.) is that whatever is commendable is virtuous, and vice tl\e contrar3\ Thus, under the head of liberality, besides what we call generosity, he includes " neatness in dress, " elegance in a house,'"' and this, he says, " with- *' out any regard to utility. He also is to be classed " amongthe liberal who keeps animals forpleasurCj " or for the sake of being admired." After mentioning Plato's division of the soul in- to three parts, he assigns the virtues peculiar to each of them. *' Of the ?'atwnal part of man," he says, " the virtue is prudence, of the animal ** {Bvfx.osi'^cva-} the virtues are gentleness, and forti- " tude ; of the concupiscible part, {sTn^^y^.y.ov) *' the virtues of temperance and continence ; and " those of the whole soul are justice, liberalitv,and '^ magnanimity." (De Virtu tibus et Vitiis.) I do not, however, find the abo^ e mentioned division of the faculties of the soul in the works of Plato. Aristotle's ideas of justice were much more ex- tensive than those of most other philosophers, or perhaps those of statesmen. " The first justice," he says) (De Virtu tibus) respects the gods ; the *^ next the demons ; then those relating to our coun- " try and our parents, and the last the dead, in M 4. " which 182 OF THE PHILOSOPHY " V. lilch is included piety, ^\hich is either a part of "justice or Ibllows it." This is the only passage in the works of Aristotle in \\l,l(h mention is made of gods^ and here he evidently means such gods as were ackno\\Iedg- ed L) his countiy. However, the neglect or con- tempt of these rites of worship, whatever they were, he Mould hiue punished. "It is injustice," he adds, (lb.) "to violate the custom and institution " vA our eountiy, and not to obey the laws and the " magistrates." 'J'his includes the principle of persecution for religious opinions and practices, which Aristotle, no doubt, held, in common with all the pliilosophers and magistrates of his time, so that notiiing better cotild reasonably be expected of him. Thus we have seen the result of the speculation, and laborious researches, of the most acute and sa- gacious of all die Grecian philosophers, of a man who, with respect both to genius and industr}-, may be classed among the first of mankind, on these most important subjects. Rut notw iihstanding maiks of superior good sense, and discernment, in the writ- ings of Aristotle, we do not find in them any real advance in theological or moral science. And as to any /;/Y7C/ic<;///^^ of his doctrines, it appears to be something OF ARISTOTLE. 183 something less than the world was in possession of before. As to the great object of heathen philosophy in o-eneral, which was to enable men to bear tiie e\ils of life, and the fear or the pains of death, he never, tliat I recollect, so much as mentions the subject; but treats of generation and dissolution merely as natural phenomena, to be explained upon physical principles, but he never regards them in a moral light. On tlie consequence of death, and a state of retribution after it, he is likewise \\ holly silent ; probably from not believing any thing either of the notions of the vulgar, or the refined speculations of Plato. Had the subjects been much upon his mind, he must have treated of them, and \^iih seri- ousness, as in themselves highly interesting to him- self; as well as to the rest of mankind. What is peculiarly remarkable in Aristotle, is tliat though he reasons much, and disputes with wonderful subtlety, he seems to have fch nothing. He never expresses himself with any warmth, or any degree of sensibility, when he is treating of th.c most important subjects ; but writes concerning God, and the soul, and of ^'irtue and vice, with as much coolness as he describes his plants and ani- mals. How different, in this respect, as well as m M 5. rnunv 184 OF THE riiii.O'^orn V many otliers, arc the vritin!:^ of Aristotle from the Psahns of David, the writings of the prophets, and other devotional and moral aiticlc^ in the books of scripture, penned by men of no uncommon ability of any kir.d, but deeply impressed with the impor- tance of the subjects on which they write, and hav- ing more knowledge of them. They know infi- nite! v more of God, and of his constimt attention to the affairs of men, individuals as well as nations, and therefore they write as if they were really sensible ofhis presence with them, and his unremitted at- tention to them, as the proper author of all the good and evil that fell to their lot. They regarded him not only as their moral governor, and final judg(\ but as their father, and their friend; and thence were led to address themselves to him on all interesting occasions. What is there, in this respect, in all the heathen Amtings to compare with tlie language of the Psalnis ? To quote a few vei'scs out of thousands, I shall just transcribe the beginning of the 116th. Psalm. / loi:e the Lord because he /tos lieavd my Toice, and tny suppl'i cations. Because he has inclin- ed his ear unto fiie, therefore will I call upon him as long as I five. 7 he sorrows of death compassed nu\ and the pains of hell got /i/)ld upon mc. I found troubk and or ARISTOTLE. 185 and sorroiVj then called I upon the name of the Lord, Lord I he seech thee, dclhcr my soul. fcrV. I am tempted to add the begimiing of the 139th Psalm. Lord thou hast searched me and hiovjn Trie. Thou knoivest my down sitting and my upris- ing. Thou iinderstandest my thoughts afar off. Thou compassest my path, and my lying doivn, and art acquainted with all my ways. 'For there is not a word in my tongue, but lo, Lord, thou know est it altogether. Thou hast beset me behind and be- fore, and laid thine hand upon me. Such knowledge is too wonderful for me. It is high, I cawiot at- tain unto it. This is language that comes from the lie art ^ im- plying a feeling sense of the intimate ];)resence, and constant inspection, of God, naturally producing a direct address to him, which does not ajjpcar ever to hvive been made by any of the philosophers. Their feelings, therefore, must have been vcr}'^ diftcrent.* Supposing them to ha\e been the same in kind, diey must have been unspeakably different in de- gree. Their acknowledgment of the universal presence of God must have been mere speculation, and rested, as we say, in head, but ne\er reached the hearf. But this strikes us in every psahn of David. O F 186 OF THE STOICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MARCUS ANTONINUS AND E P I C T E T U S. i PIE Stoic philosophy the founder of which was Zcno, \\ ho flourished about three hundred ycai-s be- fore Christ, and a litdc after Arisrotle, ai-ose a con- sidcrahle time after Socrates, and it is on se^ eral accounts the most respectable of all the heathen systems, especially as it regai ds the being and pro- vidence of God, and the submission we owe to it, patience in adversity, and resignation to death. It was soon opposed by the doctrine of Epicurus, vhich m^dc pkasurc, though not sensual pleasure, but rather the enjoyment of life in general, the great ebject and end of human life, whereas, according to the Stoics, pleasure of e\ cry kind, as well as pain, is to be ranked among Uiings 'mdiffercnt, and not to be attended to in the great rule of life. AVhen the Grecian philosophy was introduced into Rome, some of tlie most virtuous and respec- table characters embraced that of the Stoic?, in pre- ference OF THE rHILOSOPHY, &c. 187 ference to any other ; especially Cato, and in a later period the emperor Marcus Antoninus, who vnade \\ hat he deemed to be virtue, and ^^•hatevcr he thought to be subservient to the good of his coun- try, more an object than any other of the emperors, or almost any other heathen that we read of. It will, tlierefore, be well worth while to examine the fundamental principles of this philosophy ; as this alone can come in any competition \\\\\\ the christi- an. And as the fairest specimen of it may be seen in the writings of Marcus Antoninus, and Epicte- tus, I shall, in this place, confine myself to the exa- mination of their works, in which we may be sure to find the genuine principles of it without any dan- ger of mistake. Seneca indeed, and Arrian came before Marcus Antoninus, and their principles were those of the Stoics. But there is too much of rhetoric in their compositions, especially those of Seneca, whereas the writings of the emperor came, no doubt, from the heart, and express nei- ther more nor less than he reallv thoup'ht. How- o ever, I shall subjoin to this section an account of the sentiments of Seneca and Arrian. Section 183 ar tjie rHiLosoPKy Section I. Of God mid Providence. It was a fixed maxim w ith the Stoics, as it wvca w itli Socrates, from \\hom none of the founders of sects that came after him pretended to differ, tliat there is a principle of intelligence, wisdom and also of benevolence, directing all the affairs of the world and of men, though they do not ascribe proper cre- ation to it. Sometimes they even speak of it in the singular number, though more generally in the plural; believing that, though the principle of in- telligence was one, it w as distributed to several in- dniduals, and indeed to men, and all other intelli- gent agents. But none of the philosophers adopted the popu- lar ideas of the gods of their countr}-. 7'hough thev sometimes make use of the same navies, (and this is not frequent) they had a very different idea of their characters. In their writings we find no- thing of the lewdness, the cruelty, and caprice of the gods of Homer and Virgil ; nor do they e^•cr make any apology for rejecting die notions of tlic common people. This OF THE STOICS. 189 This unity of principle in all the orders of intel- ligent beings would, in the opinion of the philoso- phers, secure the unity of design in the whole sys- tem that was subordinate to them, and governed by them. " There is," says Marcus Antoninus (Lib. vii. sect. 9.) " one world, one god in ail *' things, one matter, and one law. Consequently, " reason in all intelligent beings is the same \\\ " all, and truth also is one." He makes use, though only once, of the name of Jupiter as that of the Supreme Being, when he Tspeaks of the principle of intelligence in all men as derived from one source. " We should live," he says, (Lib. v. sect. 7.) " v/ith the gods; and this *' any person \\\\\ do who preserves his mind in a " disposition to acquiesce in what is appointed " him, and who acts according to that genius, *' which Jupiter, having detached it from himself, ** gives to every person to be his future guide and " commander, which is every person's mind, or " reason." He evidently considered the sun as a portion of the universal deity, when he says, (Lib. viii. sect. 19.) " the sun, and the other gods, exist " for some purpose or other." That this universal mind has a perfect know- ledge of all things, even of what passes in the minds of 190 OP THE fHlLOSOPHY men, was the belief of the Stoics, as well as of So- crates. " God," says Marcus Antoninus, (Lib. xii. sect. 2.) " sees all minds divested of their co- '* vcrings and flesh. By his own mind alone he " sees them as derived from him. If you will do " the same, you will be freed from much trouble.'* For believing that all minds are only parts of one whole, he ascribes to diem all much of the same power, as we shall see more particularly hereaf- ter. He, howc\cr, takes it for granted that all good and evil is the dispensation of the gods, and there- fore he holds it as a fixed maxim to be th:mkful for the former, and patiently to bear the latter. " I ''thank God," he says, (Lib. i. sect. 17.j "for ** good grandfathers, good parents, good precep- " tors, good acquaintimce, domestics, and friends, •* and for good of every other kind. If," siiys he (Lib. vi. sect. 44.) " the gods take no care of the ** world, which it is impiety to believe, why do we •* sacrifice, pray, take oaths, and do other things *' which suppose the gods to be present witJi us. ** and attentive to us?" The heathens in g-encral, without excepting any of the philosoj^hcrs, except Epicurus, were dis- posed OF THE STOICS. 191 posed to believe that the gods interposed in tlic af- fairs of man, giving him admonitions, and sugges- tions by drearrrs, omens, oracles, and various other ways. " With respect to the gods," say Marcus Antoninus (Lib. i. sect. 17.) " their suggestions, *' and the aids, and inspirations that come from " them, nothing hinders my living according to the ** rule of nature, unless it be my fault, in not ob- " serving those hints from the gods, which are *' sometimes obscure." He seems sometimes, however, to consider such an order of tilings established from all eternity as would render ail prayer, sacrifices, 8;c. useless. ^' Whatever happens to you," he sa}'s, (Lib. x. sect. 5.) " was destined for you from all eternity. *' This" he says, '' v.as done, (Lib. iv. sect. 26.) ** by a certain fate." And again, " the series of " causes combined with one another, connects ** your existence with that c^ent from all eternity." This, however, is the belief of Jews and Christians, and according to their ideas is not incompaiib-le with prayer. But it is doubtful whether Marcus Antoninus entered into the proper principle of this, so as to make prayer perfectly compatible v\ ith his idea of fate. It does not appear that tlie Stoics in general, any more than other heathen philosophers, 1^j2 of the phii.osophv liud their minds exercised in prayer, habitiiul and occasional, in die manner of|)ious Jews aiid Chris- tians. Wc shonlel oUieruisc have had more of iheir devotional compositions, similar to those ot tlie psalms of David, and other forms of prayer that occur in the hooks of scripture. The difl'ere^ce between die heatliens and the believers in revelati- on in this respect is so striking as I observed before, as proves a veay different state of mind with respect to a God and provielencc, whatever may be inferred to the contrary from occasionid expressions in their writings. That every thing diat was appointed and direct- ed by the Supreme Being is right, Marcus Antoni- nus never doubted. *' If there be a God," he says, (Lib. ix. sect. 29.) ** every thing is right." Ac- cording to him, diis made the existence of any thing properly evi/ absolutely impossible. *' No- " thing,'" he savs, (Lib x. sect. 6.) " can be hurt- *' ful diat is good for the \\hole; and eveiT thing^ '' in the universe nuist be good for //. This is ** common to the nature of every thing, and the "world must have it in the greatest degree, be- " cause tliere is nothing external to itself to force " any thing noxious upon it." This considerati- on is with us also an argument for the unchangea- ble OF t:!e stoics. 193 ble goodness, and other attributes, of God, tliv. evi- dence of which we see in the works of nature. We say that, since there are evident marks of bcncvo- Icnce ill what wc experience and see around us, a principle of nialeiiolence ^ which is opposite to it, cannot be admitted. E>'ery thing, therefore, must have been designed for the best, A\hether at present we can see it to be so or not. And as there is no- thing in nature superior to this bcncvolcnit su- preme intelHgence, this system, tendin.g iu all re- spects to good, must be perpetual. That this system is in a progressive state of con- tinual improvement was not the doctrine of the Stoics. It was rather their opinion that, after a certain period, every tiling would return to the state in which it had been before ; so that nothing would be gained by their perpetual revolu lions. In this their system coincided with that of the Hindoos, and tlie oriental philosophers. This seems to be intimated by Marcus Antoninus. " We should bear in mind," he says, (Lib. ii. sect. 14.) " two things, one that all things have " been from eternity in a perpetual round. There *' is in it no difference between seeing the sioic " things a hundred years, two hundred 5ear.s, or in " a longer duration," How dull and unpleasant is N 2. > . thlr, 1^4 OF THE PHILOSOPHY this prospect cgjpparcd to thiit wiiich is suggested ill our scriptures ; according to which nothing will ( vcr r( turn to the state in \\ hich it has been before, but every thing will continually advance in ini- pro\ement, without, however, ever reaching pcr- fcct'ion^ which must e\er be tlie exclusive preroga- ti\e of the Supreme Being. I^he duty of absolute submission to the divine \^il!, and the order of nature, as coincident widi it, cannot be inculcated more forcibly tlian it is by the Stoics. " Man," says Marcus Antoninus, (Lib. xii. sect. 12.) " should donodiingbut what God " himself would approve, and he should receive " \\illingly \\hatever he assigns him. \Vith re- *' sptet to every thing that is agreeable to nature, " the i^ods are not to be blamed, for they do nothing " \\rong v.ith design." " The principal article of *' piety towards the gods," says Epietetus, (sect. .'>1.)'" is to have just opinions coneeniing them, " as diat they exist, and administer every thing *' u ell and rightly, and tliat it is our business to " obey them, and acquiesce Aoluntarily in every " thing that takes place, as being disposed for the "best." Treating of death, Marcus Antoninus says, (Lib. \\. sect. 10.) " If every thing be order- •' ed by providence, I venerate the supreme niler, " and OF THE STOICS. 195 " iind, depending upon him, am iinnyoved." From '^Tiis opinion of the duty of submission to the di\ine will, he excellently obsen^es, (Lib. ix. sect. 40.) *' the gods either have power, or no power. If " they iiave no power, why do you pray? If they *■'■ have power, why do you not rather pray that you " may be without anxiety about an event, than that *' the event may not take place ?" This may in- struct even a christian. It was the opinion of all the heathens, from the earliest to tlie latest times, that it ^vas right, and even necessar\', to adhere to the religious rites o^ their ancestors ; since die prosperity of the state they thought depended upon it. On this princi- ple, absurd and groundless as it apparently is, it was that the wisest and best of the heathens acted. It was on this principle that Marcus Antoninus, Trajan, and some others, die best disposed of the Roman emperors, wished to exterminate the chris- tians, in order diat the rites of the antient religion might not grow into disuse, to the endangering of the state. " It is every person's duty," says E- pictetus, (sect. 31.) "to ma\e libations, offer sa- " orifices, and first fruits, according to the custom " of his country, not sordidl}^ or negligently, nor " above our means." N3. The 196 OF THE rniLOSOPHV Tlie good sense, houcvcr, of Marcus Antoninus taught him th;it thci'C might be an excess, and su- perstition, in this external vvorsl.ip. For he com- mends aperson (Lib. vi. sect. 30.; for l>cing " rcli- *' gious without superstition." He ali>o i;ays (Lib. vi. sect. 23.) " In all things pray for the divine *' aid, and consider that there is no difference how " long \\c are doing this. Three hours thus pas- *' sed may suffice." He docs not, however, say for vvliat space of time thcbc three hours would suffice. Lilic Socrates, the emperor connected the practice of morality whh religion ; though widi this, the re- ligious rites of states, those on which their prospe- rity M as thought to depend, had no connection w hatever. " It is of much consequence," he says, (Lib. X. sect. 8.) "to remember diat there are •' gods, and that they do not wish men to deceive "them, or to flatter them, but to imitate them. *' He that fears pain, (Lib. ix sect. 1.) fears what " must be in the world, and this is impious; ajid " he who follows pleasure will not refrain from in^ "justice, which is certainly impious." Section OF THE STOICS. 197 Section II. Of the Human Soul. Hitherto we have found the principles of the Stoics what may be called sublime^ and in a great degree rational, as there is but little to correct in their ideas of the supreme intelligence, of his uni- versal providence, or the obligation they maintain that all men are under to conform to its will, and acquiesce in its decisions, as necessarily right and good. But we shall now find them deviating \'e- r\^ far from truth and common sense, and leading tliemselves and others into errors of a practical na- ture, as we proceed to consider their ideas concern- ing the mind of ?nan, the disposition to be cultivat- ed in it, and the essentials of moral virtue. The Stoics held the doctrine of t/ircc principle': in man, viz. his body, consisting of gross matter, the principle of mere animal life, called by them ( TTvsvua ) or ( ijyuxr?, ) and the proper intellectual principle, called {vov$.) The difference between men and other animals appeared to them to be so great, that they could not believe the latter to be possessed of the highest principle of human nature. N 4. But 198 OF I HE PHILOSOrilY But as nun have every thing that belongs to brutes, in uliiclithey acknowledge some thing su- perior to mere matter, they uere under a necessity of making the component p:uts of man to be three. IMoreover, as they considered all matter as fun- damentally the same, though forming different sub- stances, they conceived die animal principle to be the same in all, flowing from a common source, to anim.ate particular bodies for a time, and then, like the breath to whicli it A\as generallv compared, mixed with the origin from which it \\as derived. In like manner, having no idea of a proper cre- ation^ i. e. out of nc! /ling, the}' considered the high- est principle in man, aIz. that of intelligence, as the same in all, dcri\'ed from tlic same source ; and this they conceived to be tlie supreme intelligence, which disposed and directs tlie affairs of the whole universe, and like tlic principle of animal life, they held that, being detached from Uiis source at tlie bi.ili of every man, it was absorbed into it again ftfter his death, as a drop of \\ater (to use a com- parison that is frequent with them) is absorbed and lost in die ocean. Consequendy, its separate ex- istence, and separate consciousness, Uien \'anishcd. Accord- OF THE STOICS. 199 According to this philosophy, therefore, the soiib of men are so many portions of the diA'inity ; and tliis led the professors of it to ascribe to them the properties and powers of divinity, making them sufficient for tiieir oavii happiness, independently of ever}^ thing external to them. And, as the su- preme intelligence is incapable of suffering from evil of any kind, tiiey transferred this extraordina- ry power to the soul ; maintaining that notl ing foreign to itself could affect it without its own con- sent, so that it is in every man's power to be com- pletely htippv, whatever his outward circumstances may be. This sentiment, which has an air of great subli- inity, tended to inspire the Stoics with a sense of native dignity, rendering them superior to every tiling mean and base; but it excluded humilit}^ and many amiable and useful virtues, peculiarly adapted to the state of society with beings equally imperfect with themselves. Their sentiments how- ever, on this subject so nearly connected with mo- rals, led them to express themsehes with respect to the common accidents of life in a manner that, with a little qualification, is truly admirable and edify- ing. But when taken literally their language just- ly shocks a christian, who feels his own weakness, N 5. and 200 OF THE IMIILOSOrUY and is thereby disposed to compassionate tlie weak- ness luul infirmitLes of others ; the most amiable, and in the present state of tlnnj^, one of the most useful of all virtues. On the subject of the different component parts of man Marcus Antoninus expresses himself as follows: "Man, (Lib. xii. sect. 2.) consists of flesh, " the animal piinciple, {TrvsviJLuJiov ) and the go- *' vernin}^ principle ( ■/j'/.-^vikov. ) The ( Trviv^oc ) '* is breath, or air, {uvty.^) nor is it always the " same, but is drawn in and emitted. You con- " sist, (Lib. xii. sect. 3.) of three parts, the body, *' the {-KVivy^ujiov,) and tlic mind, ( y:vi )• Thr *' two former arc so far yours, iis that the}- are ♦* committed to your care, but the third only is *' properly yours." For the intellectual part of man was considered as so much superior to the other two, as to deserve to be alone called a nicui's sc'lf. And on se\eral occasions we shall find that the two other parts v\ere thought to be as much fo- ixign to a man as if they did not belong to him at all, an}- more than other parts of the external world. The unity of these three elements of which every man consists, is thus described by Marcus Antoni- nus, "One living principle (ylivyj) (Lib. ix. sect. 8.) *' is distributed to all irrational animals, and one in- " telligcnt «r THE STOICS. 201 *' telligent living principle ( vcs^^a 4/u%i? ) to all ra- " tional ones, just as to the several elements there ** is one and the same earth. We all see and live *• with one light, and breathe one air. There is " (Lib. xii. sect. 30.) one light of the sun, though *' it be distributed upon different things, one com- *' mon nature, though distributed into various dif- " ferent bodies, one (ipi'X'?) ) though distributed to ** innumerable peculiar natures, and one intelli- " gent principle ( voc-[)Cc il^wx'J ) though it seems to *' be divided." The idea which the Stoics entertained of the na- tive dignity, and superior powers, of the human mind flowed necessarily from their opinion of its origin and final destination; but it coiresponds very little with experience, and is wholly discordant with the principles of revelation. " You forget," says Marcus Antoninus, (Lib. xii. sect. 26.) " that " the mind of every man is God, and flowed from " the divinity." And again, (Lib. iv. sect. 14.) " Thou art part of the universe, and will vanish " into that which produced thee, or rather by some *' intervening change, thou wilt be received into *' die seminal reason ( Xoyov a-Tr-pfji^ocjiKc:' ) i. e. die *' the source of all reason. '^ These 202 OF THE niiLOcopny . These ideas of the great power, and natuixd in- dependence, of the mind were suiuibleto the opini- on of iU high ori^^in and final destination, as having been original!}- part of the supreme iini\'erK^ intel- ligence, and destir.ed to be alisorl^'d into it, and to beeomc part of it again. " It belongs," says Mai-- ciis Antoninus, (Lib. vii. sect. 55.) " to the mind "to be free from error and defect. Neither fire, '* nor e::tezTial violence, nor calumny, nor any " thing else can reach the mind when, like a sphere, " it is compact within itself (J/ib. ^iii. sect. 41.) " The soul endued ^\ith reason has t!:c following " powers, (Lib. xi. sect. L) it sees itself, it forms " and limits itself, it makes itself whatever it pleas- *' es. Whatever fruit it produces it reaps itself; " whereas other persons gather the fruits of tj-ees, ** and also whate\er is produced froin animals. " It always gains its purpose, at \\ hatever time its " life terminates ; so that it is not, as in a dance, *' or a play, in which the action is sometimes intcr- " nipted by incidents, and is therefore imperfect. *' But wherever it is taken, wh?ct precedes is com- " plete and perfect ; so that I may say, I have eve- *' ry thing that belongs to me within me. Add to *' diis, the mind traverses the whole world, and *' what suiTounds it. It contemplates its form, " and 0¥ THE STOICS. 203 *' and lookiiii^ forward into eternity, it considers *' the reno^'ation of the universe at certain inter- " vals." An essential prerogative of the mind of man, and of tlie most use in the conduct of life, the Stoics considered to be its coimnand of thought^ and hy this means its total independence on every thing fo- reign to itself; since it is under no necessit}^ of giving any attention To them. " How can opini- /' ons," says Marcus Antoninus (Lil). vii. sect. 2.) *' be abolished, unless thoughts suitable to them be *' extinguislied, which you may for tiiat purpose " call up whenever you please. I can think of " any thing that I have occasion for ; and if I can, *' why should my mind be disturbed ?" Thus these philosophers flattered themselves with the idea of tlieir happiness being wholly indepen- dent on any thing foreign to the mind, and that it became them to maintain a perfect indifference to- wards every thing that is die object of affection, or respe.*'', to other men. " If you behave" says E- pictetus (sect. 15.) *' with becoming indifference " towards children, wife, the magistrate, riches, ** &c. &:c. you will be worthy of being a guest of " the gods; but if you can despise all these things ** that are foreign to yourself, you will not only be " a com- 204 OF THE PHILOSOPHY " a companion with them, but a god \ourbclf. " Thus Diogenes, Hcraclitus, and others Hke *■ them, deserve to be called, and really ncre, di- ** vine.''^ It is surely hardly possible to carry ex- travagance and absurdity farther than this ; so far, however, we see that a false philosophy, pursued to its natural consequences, can cany men from every thing that we aie taught by daily experience aixl observation of common life. And yet these vere men of deep thought and reflection, and both Kpictetus and Marcus Antoninus lived in the world, and had to do \\\\h men and their affairs Section III. Of rirtue and Ficc. The great use of religion, and of moral philoso- phy, is to furnish thg mind >\ ith proper rules of life, by the observance of which we shall best se- cure our own happiness, and be the most ('' nosed to promote that of others, to enable us to bear the evils of life with the least pain, and the prospect of death without terror. On all these three heads, therefore, I shall examine the merit of the Stoical philosophy, and compare it with the christian. The OF THE STOICS. 205 y The dli^nified sentiments maintained by the Stoics concerning the human soul lead us to ex- pect great elevation of mind with respect to virtue; and in this we shall no tbe disappointed, as far as vir- tue in their ideas of it extended ; and it compre- hended every thing that relates to the due govern- ment of the passions, all the relative duties, and those that affect the intercourse between man and man. They also made happiness to depend entire- ly on the practice of viitue, independent on any fo- reign consideration, such as the fear of punish- ment, the hope of reward, or the opinion of otheis, expressed in praise or censure. Marcus Antoninus, having observed tliat it is in the power of man to be happy in any situation, and especially in one that suits him, says (Lib. v. sect, 36.) " If you ask what this proper situation is, lan- ** swer, that it consists in good morals, a good dis- " position, and good actions. It is a pleasure to a " man (Lib. viii. sect. 26.) to do what suits his na- " ture, and it suits the nature of man to be kind to *' his countrymen, to command die emotions of *' his senses, to distinguish what is probable in " what is before him, to contemplate the nature of " the universe, and the things that are agreeable to ** it. Do nothing" he says, (Lib. xi. sect. 18.) " for 1 OF THE PHILOSOPHY - tlK'sakc of admiration, but be the same ^^ lieu *' alone as if your were before others." For he justly obscTA-es (Lib. xii. sect. 4.) " Wc fear more *' what others think of us, than what we think of " ourselves." Agreeable to this, Epictetus says (sect. 23.) " If your thoughts be employed in ex- *' temal things, and you wish to please any person, '* you err from the path of life ; whereas in all ea- " ses remember that you are a philosopher, and " that you appear so to yourself, tliough not to "others." The Stoics carried the principle of disinterested- ness to the highest pitch, beyond the bounds of rea- son ornature, expecting no reward for their virtues eitl!cr in this life, or any other, except the satisflicti- on of their own minds ; and this was short of any proper pleasurable sensation. For, according to their general system, nothing of this kind ought to be indulged. " When you confer a favour" says Marcus Antoninus (Lib. ix. sect. 42.) *' is not this "sufficient, without any i"e\vard ? Docs the eye " require a reward for seeing, or the feet for walk- ** ing? So man, who is made to do good, should *' be satisfied w ith tlie good that he does." These extremely rigid maxims, so much above the comprehension of the vulgar, led tliein to cou^ sider OF THE STOICS. 207 ^idcr the practice of A'irtue as the peculiar privi- lege of philosophers, and real happiness asnir.ch more so. For who besides philosophers could be expected to despise e^■ery thing thut '^^■as foreign to themselves, and to consider f^xcry thing on \\iiich the comfort of life depends asinckided in tliis class; and \vithoiit this there is, according to them, nei- ther real ^'irtue or true happiness, as \\ ill l>e more evident in the farther dcvelopement of their prin- ciples. Some philosophers vrcre poor, as Epictetus him- self, who ^vas even some time in servitude ; and in an age in wliich books were scarce and dear, and learnini^ not easily attained, some of them m!;.^ht not be able to read. In this case Marcus Antoni- lius says, (Lib. viii. cap. 8.) " If you cannot read, *' you can abstain from abuse, even of the ungrate- *' ful, and also be kind to them. You need not be *' heard to complahi of your situation, or envy *' that of others." Happily, hov.cver, these vir- tues and every other may be attained without phi- losoph}-. Unhappily, the Stoics considered every thing that is foreign to the calm dictates of reason, ail e- motions and passions, a:i belonging to mere animal nature ; seeing that men have them in .common O. with 208 OF THE piiii.osonrr •\\ilh brutes. They, therefore, thought it a pohit of niai^.ianinilty and duty in man to suppress every thing ofthis kind w lti» respect to others, as well as themselves. Do not," says Marcus Antoninus, (Lib. vii. sect. 43.) '' join others in their lamentati- "ons, or l:e moved by them." Epictetus, howe- ver, makes some little allowance for the weakness ofhuman nature when he says (sect. 16.) " If you " see a friend in distress, accommodate yourself to *' him so far as to lament and gioan dong with him, *' but take care that you groan not inwardly." These maxims, I need not sa}-, are as remote from the dictates of nature, as they are from die precepts of scripture, which bids us to be kindly af- fcctioucd one to anotJicr^ ijoith brot/icrly love, and from this principle to rejoice wit/i them that rejoice^ and to Tocep "cnth them that ivecp. How can men be supposed to act., but as prompted by Xhtiv feel- ings ? Though Mai'cus Antoninus advises to do good to a man's fellow citizens, and even to the ungrate- fiil, it was not, according to his principles, to be dictated by any affection, as that of Iwuc, but only because it was the part of man, and became him to act in this manner ; as it A\as for the eye to see, or the feet to walk. Butchristiajiity knows notliing of the OF THE STOICS. 209 the distinction of the different eomponent parts of man, and the natural superiority of one of tliem to the rest. Paul, though he expresses a wish that his brethren might \)(t sanctified in body^ soul and spi- rit^ it v/as only in allusion to the three fold division of man above mentioned, which was familiiu' to the Greeks, to whom he \\'as writing, desiring that, ^\•hatever they considered as belonging to man, or part of him, it might be sanctified, as a suitable temple for the spirit of God. He was not declar- ing his own principles, as a Jew, or a Christ! n. The opinion which the Stoics maintained of the superior excellence of the intellectual pn:iciple in all men was such, that they considered e^•ery emo- tion or passion that led to vice as foreigr. to it, as arising only from the principle that is common to men and brutes ; and therefore not horn anv tiling that was properly a man's self. In consequence of this, they professed to have no iiidignLition ag.iinst tlie vices of men, but considered them like evils, and inconveniences of an} other kind, at \vhlch it does not become any man to be disturbed, being acrreeable to the order of the nature. . Accordingly, Marcus Antoninus having observed that wc have no reastni to complain of the gods w ith Q 2. respect V 210- or THE niiLOzoi'iiY icspcct to any thlnp' that befalls us, adds(Lil). xif. sect. 12.) '*' Neither arc men to Ijc complained of. *' Tor nLiihcr do they ofiRnd williniijly. It is the part *' of man (Lib. vii. sect. 22.) to love those who of- " fend tl^.cm ; and this he will do if he recollect *' that all men arc related, and that when they of- " fend, it is whtn they do not know it, or do it a- ** gainst their w ills. When I consider that the *' person who injures m.e (Lilx ii. sect. 1.) is a par- *' taker cf the same intellect, and portion of the *' divinity, that I cannot be injured In' him, that he *' has no pow cr to di'aw me into any thing disho- *' nest, I cannot be angry with him, or hate him." The Stoics were led into these sentiments, and tiiis conduct, by considering every man as wholly independent on e\'ery other, each being separately suflicient for his own happiness, and incapable of interfering with th.at of any otlier. " Does anv *' person ofiend uic," says Marcus Antoninus (Lib. V. sect. 25.) " let him look to it. He has his own *' dispositions and actions, and I have what nature " w ills me to have, and I do w hat is agreeaiile to *' nature." Again he says, (Lib. iv. cap. 26.) " Does any person injure me. No, he hijures " himself. If you suffer (Lib. ix. sect. 42.) " through fiaudu lent, faithless, injurious, persons, " consi- OF TKE STOICS. 211 " consider that tliere must be such men in thr " VTOrld, and vou will bear with them. ..v^-.v^, ^^,.^ J'"-^ iwii i^v^tll Willi lilL-ill. VV you take any thing ill (Lib. xii. sect. 25.) you forget that every thing takes place according to *' tlie nature of the universe. If vre consider these " things only as evils Vvhich depend upon our ou n *' wills, we shall see no reason for blameinc!:, or bear- " ingill will to, an}'^ man." Besides diis great indiSerence to the vices of other persons, as injuring only themselves, that of fornication was never considered by any heathen;* philosopliers, or odicrs, as one, an}- farther tlian it was found to be hijurious. This is evident from the advice that E.pictetus gives (sect. 33.) *' Ab- " stain as much as }'ou can from veiiery bclbre " marriage. If not, do it as the lav/s permit, but ^' do not find fault with others Vvho are nut eon ti- *' nent, or boast that you ai'e so." How short is this of the purity required of chris- tians, vvho are taught to consider fornicators, as well as adulterers, diicves, See. excluded from the king- dom of heaven, and how little attention must these philosophers have given to the natural consequence of venereal indulgence vvithout the bounds of mar- riage ; how ill it qualifies men to be affectio nate O 3. husbands 212 oj THE nriLCcopiiY husbnrids, and fallicrs, ai:d that in many cases it n\iist indispose nu'i to marriage in general. There was also this inconsistence in tlKJr maxims in this respect, that fornication \vas always reckoned infa- mous in the female sex ; so that women of charac- ter never associated with known prostitutes. The christian catalogue of both virtues and vices is far more copious than that of tlie heathens, which was defective \\ iih respect to duties of ever}- kind, those thiit are commonly said men ov, e to dicmselves, and to society, as well as those that \\e owe to God, not- withstanding tlwt of submission to his will, which is one of the great excellencies of the maxims of the Stoics ; as this was founded chiefly on its being merely taken for granted, without considering any particular evidence of it, that evciy Uiing in the universe, and the goveinmtnt of ii, must be right. For the wisdom of j)r()\idence in the permission or appointment of evil is never mentioned by Marcus Antoninus. That such things as evils of every kind must bc^ is the amount of all diat he says on the subject ; and Uiat they do not aftect anv person \\ho considers these as foreign to himself. He says nothing of the beneficial tendency of the tilings that we call evil, and complain of in the system, obvious as diis tendency is now seen to be. Mar- cus OF THE STOICS. 213 cus Antoninus would bear tribulation, but tlie apostle Paul rejoices in it. The maxims of the heathens "vvcre still more de- fective v;ith respect to sufficient niothesio the prac- tice of virtue, in the fear of future punishment, and the prospect of future reward ; and all other mo- tives will have but little hold on the bulk of man- kind, especially if they be already engaged in bad habits. On such persons, a disinterested respect to virtue, so much insisted upon by Pvlarcus Antoni- nus, cannot be expected to ha\'c any influence. Section IV. OftJie 'various Ei^'ils of Life. Another great use of religion and philosophy is to enable men to bear the various evils incident to them in life with as little inconvenience as possible ; and accordingl}^ this was a princi]:)al object of die philosophy of the Stoics, far more than it was with any of the other sects. In this inspect their preten- sions went very high indeed, far, as we shall see, beyond the bounds of reason and nature; so that daily experience, one would have thouglit, must O 4. have 2 1 '1 Of r II £ r II 1 1. s o r H y have cor.vinced ihcm (jf llicir mistake. Xotnitli- star.diR[^ tliis, they resolutely niaiiitaincd their fa- vourite, anJ indeed fundamental maxims, of indif- fercncc to every thing foreign to themselves, (mean- ing the intellectual principle in them onl} ) which enjoined palicnee under, and even insensibility to, all that mankind in general complain of, and call ceils I On this principle they held that, w ithout its own consent, the mind could not be affected by any thing. " I learned," says Marcus Antoninus (Lib. 1. sect. 8.) *' of Apollonius to regard nothing be- " sides mere reason, to be the same in the most " acute pain, in the loss of children, and in diseas- *' es of long continuance." So also Epictetus says, (sect. 1.) " If the things that disturb you be " not in your pow er, have it ready to say. This is ** notI";ing to me. And if you consider that only '* as yours ^hich is yours, and what is foreign to " you as foreign to you, no person will constrain ** or hinder you. You will complain of no man. *' You will do nothing against your w ill. You " will have no enemv, nor suffer anv dunsr disa- "gieeabletoyou." This OF THE STOICS. 215 This opinion of tliLMiatiirc and povvxrs of the mind, and of things that were, or were not, fo- reign to themselves, an opinion on u hieh so much depended, they contrived to be easily formed by those who had been tauglit to ji'iilosophize, so as to be readily applied on all occasions. It was only the office of thoiiQ-hl, than v> hich nothini:* is more easy to mind^ the property of which is to think. In this respect thev made no difference between the most painful sensations and impressions, cor- poreal or mental, though in these we find that the mind is absolutely passive ; tliey supposing all sensations and emotions were to be refeiTcd to the merely animal part of man, on vihich they maiii tained that the mind was A\holly independent ; so that whatever impression might be made from without, it was in its power to rclic\'e itself. Consequently, they held that pieasu re and pain of every kind are not to be classed among things diat are either good or evil. Marcus Antoninus says (Lib. ii. cap. 11.) " Life and death, honour " and ignominy, pain and pleasure, wealth and po- " verty, may be equally considered as good or evil ; " since they are neither honourable nor dislio- " nourable, and are therefore neither s:ood no- 5. "evil*." -10 or 1 HE J'HILOSOniY " evil-:; ." ijij, ii;^. aifliculty consists in being ful. ly coininced of this, and regarding that as indiffer- ent in contradiction to the actual llxlings of them- selves, as well as of the rest of mankind. Of diis, ho^vc^'er, they made very light. *' Reject opinion," says Marcus Antoninus, (Lib. xii. sect. 25.) " and you lue safe ; and v. hat " hinders your doing this, \vhen any thing happens *' tliat is disagreeable to you ? }ou forget that this " happens * There is a passage in t/ie TliNl' of Cebes^ ivho ivas a disciple of Socrates^ in iv/iic/i this sentiment of life and deaths health and sickness ^ being to be classed among things indifferent to Jiappiness occurs. But it must hai}e been added by some person %vho, if not a Stoic, must ha've lived long after the time of this Ccbcs. " /-{/t'," he says, is not to be classed " arnong the goods or the e^ ils ; because it is enjoy - *' ed alike by those 'ivho live well, and those ivho live *' ill. The same vmy be said of cutting and burn- " i//^; for these operations are usefully employed by " those vjho are sick and those nuho are voell. Net- *' ther is death an absolute evil ; because it is some- *' ti77ies preferred to life by the brave ; nor health, *' or sickness, riches, or any other seeming advan- *' tage; because they are often of no real use. ''^ OF THE STOICS. 217 ** liappens according to the nature of Uic universe. *' Take away opinion," he says (Lib. iv. sect. 7.) ' and complaint is removed. Whatever docs not " make a man worse, or his conduct worse, cannot *' injure him internally or externally." And a- gain, (Lib. vii. cap. 14.) " If I do not consider a- *' ny thing that befalls me as an evil, I am not in- " jured, and it depends upon myself ^^lled^er I think *' so or not. How easy," says he, (Lib. v. sect. 2.) " to remove every imagination that is troublesome *' or inconvenient, so as to preserve the mind in " perfect tranquility. In pain (Lib. viii. cap. 28.) " the soul may preserve its tranquility, and not *• think it to be an evil. Every thing of the nature '' of opinion, inclination, and appetite, is within us, •' where nothing that is evil can come. Remove '* imagination," he says, addressing himself", and " it is in my power that no vice, no irregular de- *^ sire, no perturbation, exist in my mind ; but, re- *• garding every thing as it really is, to make use of *' it according to its value. Remember that this * power is given to you by nature. So Epictetus says (sect. 30.) " No person can hurt you unless *' you will. Then only are you injured, when you *' think you are so." In a more particular manner they made light of everv" 218 OF THE nilLOSOPHY even^ tiling tliat afllctcd the body only, for which, as consisting of brute niatt-.r, ihcv professed the great- est contempt, as if it had borne no relation w hatc- vcr to the mind, w hich they considered as the only proper seat of good or evil, true pleasure or pain. ** Nothing," says Marcus Antoninus, (Lib. iv. sect. 39.) "that is an evil to you, deper.ds upon " any change that takes place in that in Avhicli vou *' are inclosed. If ihc body be cut, burned, or " putrefy, only let that j)ari: of a man v/hich forms " its opinion concerning it be at rest, that is, ••' not consider diat as good or e\il, uhieh may hap- *' pen either to good or bad men. For whatever " happens aUke to him that lives agreeably to na- " ture, or contrary to it, is a matter of incliflference. *' Vou may pass your life (Lib. vii. sect, (i^,) willi- " out injury, and with the greatest cheerfulness, *' though \\ ild beasts tear the limbs of the body ** that surrounds you , and adheres to yor." The language in which diey sometimes express this indifference to the body is amusing, and might have been said by way of ridicule of their system. " Pain," says Marcus Antoninus, (Lib. viii. sect. 28.) " is an evil to the body. li it is so, let die bo- *' d}- look to it. As to tlie limbs of die body, (Lib. •' vii. sect. 33.) ifdiey be in pain, let them take " ciu-c Of THE STOICS. 219 •' care of it, if they ean do any thing." Again (Lib. Kii. sect. 1.) " Let the f^esh v>ith which yon " are surrounded mind its own sufferings." ** U " the reason," sfiys Epictetus (sect. 18.) " forebode ** any ill, immediately reply, it may be to your bo- *' dy, your reputation, your children, or your wife. " Every thing fortunate is intended forme, if I '' please. For ^\hatever happens to me, is in my " power, and I may deri^'e advantage from it." However, besides this great sheet anchor, as it may be called, of the Stoics, by ^vhich they procured their tranquility in all the storms of life, viz. their idea of the absolute independence of the mmd upon eve- ry thing external to it, and its sufficiency for its own happiness, they occasionally mention other consi- derations not peculiar to themselves, some ofm.ore, and some of less, weiglit. Among others, Marcus Antoninus says, (Lib. vii. sect. 33.) " If pain con- " not be borne, it will cease, and if it be of long *' continuance, it may be borne ; and in the mean " time the mind, by means of its opinion, may *' preserve its tranquility." Another of his resources is not so reasonable. " Think with yourself," he says (Lib. viii. sect. 36.) " that nothing past or future, but only that " which 220 OF THE PHILOSOPHY " vvhicli is present can be the cause of uneasiness " to you." This is by no means true with respect to beings capable of reflection, %vhose happiness or misery nccessuiily depends much more on the past and the future than on die present moment. It is only a brute, or a child, to w Inch this observation is applicable, nor even to them completely, or long. One rule of Epictetus, however, istmly valua- ble, if it could be applied. But the Stoics always imagined that much more was in their pow cr than really was so. " Do not (sect. 8.) seek to find things " as you w ish them to be, but wish for that w hich " actually is, and you will pass your life in tranqui- " lity." The great difficulty in this case (but to this the Stoics gave no attention) is in the appKcati- on of such a rule ; and other principles, out of the sphere of their philosophy, but comprehended in those of Christianity, are necessar}' to assist us in this. This great excellence of character, which raises some men so much above the lc\el of their species, and w hich rendered them superior to all the e\ ils of life, and also to the fear of death, the Stoics a- scribcd wholly to philosophy ; so that it required much study and reflection to attain it, though af- terwards the exercise of it was easy. " The time *' of OF THE STOICS. 221 " of liurnan life," says Marcus Antoninus (Lib. ii. sect. 17.) " is a point; nature is in a continual " flux, the senses are obscure, the body liable to " corruption, &.c. &c. the only thing" (that is of value) " is philosophy, which consists in preserv- " ing the mind intire, superior to pleasure or pain, *' self-sufiicicnt, having nothing to do with what *' others do or do not do, and receiving the things " that befall them as coming from tlie same source " with themselves.'" " It is a mai'k," says Epic- tetus (sect. 48.) " of the common people to look *' for loss or gain from what is external to them, *' but the philosopher expects nothing but from " himself. The proof that he is a philosopher, is, " that he censures no person, commands no per- *' son, complains of no man, never boasts of him- " self, as a person of any consequence. If he meets " with obstacles from his acquaintance he blames " only himself If any person praise him he laughs " at him, and if he be censured he does not excuse *' himself." &c. If only such persons as these be philosophers, they will never be very numerous. Indeed, we must not look for them among men^ not even those who make the greatest profession and boast of this very philosophy ; because it could not be in their power 222 OF THE piiiLosoniY power to divest themselves of tlie common princi- ples of human nature. A\'c sec, however, in these extremely absurd maxims, liow fiy metaphysical or {general pi ineiples can carry men, at least in spe- culation ; and therefore of what impoi-timce it is to form just ones, agreeable to the real principles of human nature ; for such only can lead to the pro- per duty and happiness of man. That die Stoics, however, found more difficulty than they were w illing in general to allow, in re- ducing dieir maxims to practice, appears from dieir frequently inculcating die neccssit}- of having pro- per rules, or remedies, at hand for every ease that might occur. " As surgeons," says Marcus An- toninus(Lib. iii. sect. 13.)" have their instruments ** ready for c\ery operation, so have you your niax- " ims ready, by the help of which you may distin- " guish divine and human things," meaning pro- bably things within our power, and those that were out of it. " There is no retirement (Lib. iv. sect. " 3.} so complete as that into one's own mind,espe- " cially if it be -^W stored w idi maxims, by the con- " sideration of which it may attain perfect tranquili- " ty. And by diis means it is in a mim's power to *' remove e\ery cause of uneasiness." " WMiate- " ver occurs to you," says Epictetus (sect. 10.) " have OF THE STOICS. 223 *' have some principle ready to oppose to it. If *' you see a beautiful boj'' or girl, have recoui'se to ** coiitiiieiice, if labour the enduring of it, if re- *' proach patience. By this means appearances *' will not mislead you." " In pain let. this consi- " deration be at hand," says Marcus Antoninus, (Lib. vii. sect. 64.) " tliat it is not disgraceiiil, or " makes the governing power" (the mind) " atalithe *' \."orse, and that nothing that is either material, or *' that relates to other persons, ean injure it." Hov»- gi-eatly superior, and how much better a- dapted to the real principles of human nature, and the common feelings of men, are the consolations of our religion, to those of this philosophy ! In the scriptures the idea of the Di\ ine Being is that of the universal parent, our father in heaven, who never afflicts his children but for their benefit. He docs not-t we read, afflict will'mgly^ nor grie'ses the di'ildren of men. Tea as a father pitieth his children^ the Lord pitieth them that fear him. He knoweth their frame and remembers that they are dust. \Vith re- spect to the wicked, he is represented as forbearing to punish with severit}', waiting for their repentance and reformation, which is the sole object of the dis- cipline to which they are exposed ; not being wil- ling that any slioidd perish^ but that all should come to repentance, P. These 224 OF THK PHILOSOPHY These sentiments are such as all men may feel the force of, and are therefore adapted to common lii>e. Chris'.ianity also holds out a sufficient re- ward for all our sufferings, \vhcn they are borne with a p roper • tc mper ; and of this the Stoics t^ULjht no- thing. Afji'ic lions y as the apostle siij's, arc not joyous but griewus^ v.o'ccrtheless they work out for us a far fnorc exceeding, even an eternal weJg/it of glory ; luhlle they make us to look not at :Jk things that are seen^ \\:h'ich are temporary^ but at the things that are unseen, "[^liich arc eternal. It is not among the Stoic?, or any heathens, that \\e must look for such truly consoling sentiments as these. With these helps, christians are enabled to endure affliction not only with patience, which was all that the Stoics pretended to, but with joy: and accordingly the apostles exhort their fellow christians to rejoice in tribulation ; in every thing to give thanks. Count it ell joy says the apostle James^ (Chap. i. V. 2.) when ye fall into divers trials; knowing that the trial of your faith worketh pati- ence. But let patience hai}C her per fi. ct work, that you may be perfect and inti e, wanting nothing — (\'. 12.) Blessed is the man tiiat endureth tempt a- lion : for when lie is tried he shall receive tlie crown of life f which the Lord has promised to them that lo'-ce him. Section' OF THE STOICS. 225 Section V. Of Death. Of all the evils of life death is the natural termi- nation ; but it, is likewise the same with respect to all the enjoyments of it, and what is more, of all our future hopeSy^ if we have nothing to look to be- yond it. On this account it has always been clas- sed in the catalogue of the c'Gih to which men are subject, and one from which no man, whatever may have been his rank or situation in life, can be ex- empt. The apprehension of this universal catastrophe would oppress the mind much more than it gene- rally does, if the t'lme^ and other circumstances^ at- tending it were known to us. But these being un- known, and uncertain, and all men having their thoughts engaged iathe pursuit of their several ob- jects, and also naturally disposed to flatter them- selves, they seldom think of death till the very near approach of it ; and then they are often wholly in- sensible of it ; so that their suffering from it at the time is generally inconsiderable. P 2. Still, 226 or THE PHILOSOPHT Still, however, the consideration ol" death must often tlirow a cloud o\er tlie brii^htest prospects of many men who reflect en their situation, and espe- cially those \\ hose lot in Hie is tlie most pleasing to tliem ; and, in general, tend to abate the san- guine views and expectations wi.n wliich per- sons generally enter upon lil'e. On tliese accounts a remedy for the fear of death has always been con. bidered as a most desireable thing, and an impor- tant article in religion and philosophy. It v.as so more particularly with the Stoics, as is evident from their frequent mention of it, and the \arious arguments tlicy urge to reconcile the mindb of men to it. Some of tlieni are valuable, and as far as they go, satisfactory ; especially that to which they have con;>t.;nt recourse, as flo^^'ing directly from the fandamental principle of tlieir system, viz. the submission that we owe to the established order of nature and providence, \\hich we cannot alter, and which we must take for granted is right. " To die," says Miu'cus Antoninus (Lib. ii. sect. 11.) 'Ms not grievous, since tlicre are gods, *' M ho will not involve thee in any thirg that is evil. " If there were no eods, or if thev &x\e no attenti. " on to tlic affairs of men, it would not be A\orth ** while to li\e iji such a \\orld. But thei-e are gods. OF THE STOICS. 227 ** god.^. ?.nd they do take care of human affairs, and ^' they have put it into every man's power not to *' fall into any evil. We should meet death," he says (Lib. ii. sect. 17.) " with a benevolent and *' placid mind, as a dissolution of those elements of *' v\hich ever}^ animal consists. And if nothing " extraordinar}' happens to tliese elements, which *' are continually changing into one anodier, it is " no subject of dread, because it is according to *' nature, and nothing is an evil that is agreeable ** to nature." One use of the expectation ofdcath is well j^oint- ed out by Epictetus, " I^et death," says he (sect. 21.) " exile, and every thing that is trouble- " some, be always present, to your thoughts, and *' especially deadi, and you will have no mean "*' thoughts, nor desire any thing inordinately." Some of the Stoical ai'gu ments against the fear of death are not equally satisflictory with that abo^'C mentioned, especially that which Marcus Antoni- nus alleges with respect to evils in genera , hough he apphes it more particularly to the consideration of death, viz. that nothing really interests us besides- v'hat is actually present. " In dea:ii," he says (Lib. ii. sect. 14.) " we only lose tlie present^ P 3. " whicb 223 OF THE PHILOSOPHY *' uhicli is the same to all persons ; for vhat is past *' or future cannot be the subject of life. This "makes tlie longest life equal to the shortest." Oil this idea he enlarges in a manner that is tiuly cxtiaordinar}', in a man of genenil good sen^e, and disposed to reflection. *' Though you should ** live," he says, " three thousand yeai-s, or more ** thiui ten times as long, you sliould remember *' that no person can have more of this life, or of " any other life, than he really has. It is the same <' thing, therefore, whether you have the longest or " the shortest life, since the present is the same to all ; *' so tliat what is lost is only momentary." " If any oftliegods," he says (Lib. iv. sect. 47.) *' should tell you that you must die eitlier this day " or the next, you Avould think it a matter of indif- " ference \\ hich to chuse, unless you were tlie most *' abject of men. In hke manner, neither \\oald ** you think it of consequence whether you lived *' a thousand years, or died to-morrow. He who *' thinks (Lib. xii. sect. 35.) that whatever is season- " able is good, will think there is no difference whe- *' ther he perform more or fewer actions agreeable " to reason, and whether he contemplate tlie uni- *' verse a longer or a shorter sj)uce of lime. To " him deatli cannot be formidable." In OP THE STOICS. 229 In this sentiment, however, the emperor would rot have the concunence of mankind in general. They consider Ufe as vakiable, and would, therefore, prefer a longer to a shorter one ; and no doubt he himseli" notwithstanding this reasoning, would have done so too, provided (as we may presume in his case) his prospects, in the continuance of life and of pO'A'er, had been promising. What makss the apprehension of death distres- sing to some persons of a melancholy turn of mind, is their connecting with it diings that do not proper- perly belong to it ; being things that at the time they camiot have any know ledge or feeling of. as the circumstances attending a funeral, being inclos- ed in a coffin, being put under ground, and there putrifying, and perhaps devoured by v/orms, Sec. &.C. Oil this subject the emperor veiy properly eays (Lib. ii, sect. 12.) "If we separate from *' death every thing that does not necessarily belong *' to it, and which usually m:ike it an object of ter- *' ror, there is nothing in it bat the work of na- *'ture; and whoever dreads any thing in nature " is a child. But death is not only the work of na- *' ture, but a thing that is of use in the system of *' nature, and it is in a man's power to consider P 4. *' tlic 230 OF THE PHILOSOPHY *' the relation that the principal part of him bears to *' God, and what is to he tlic condition of that " part when it shall be released from the body." In this he alludes to the jjliilosophical principle ofthe absoq^tion of all hiferior intelligences into tlie great uni^'ersal intelligence. But neither he, or any other heathen philosopher, had, or could have, an unshaken belief in that doctrine, little con- solation as it can afford. For \\ hat is a drop of u a- ter (which is their usual comparison) when absorb, ed in the ocean ! Besides, tlie Stoics as well as all tlie other philo- sophers often express doubts on the subject ; like Socrates, putting the supposition, that death is ei- tlier an entire dispersion of all the elements of which man consists, which puts a period to all con- sciousness, or that absorption of the soul into the soul of the uni^•crse which puts an end to all sepa- rate individual consciousness, and which caimot be vers' different from it. " If," says Marcus An- toninus (Lib. vi. sect. 10.) " every thing is to be ^* dissipated, why should I diink of any thing but *' being, some way or other, reduced to earth ; and ** why should I be disturbed at this ? Do wliat I *' will, tliis dispersion will come some time or *' otlier or THE STOICS. 231 ** other. If after death (Lib. iii. sect. 3.) you be " deprived of all sense, j-^oii w'lW likewise lose all *' sense of pleasure and pain. You will then cease *' to be a slave to the worst part of yourself. But " is not that which was enslaved the better part of " you, when the one is intellectual and a genius, *' and the other mild and corruption? Wait your *< death (Lib. v. sect. 33.) with ti-anquility, whe- *' ther it be an extinction of being, or a removal. *' Till that time come, be content to worship die *' gods, to do good to men, to bear with them, and *' keep at a distance from them, remembering tliat *' every thing foreign to yourself is neither yours, *' nor in your poWer." This supposition of the two possible consequen- ces of death, so frequent with the heathen philoso- phers, and with the Stoics as mu<:h as any other, certainly shews an unsteadiness of opinion on the subject, and that little consolation was in fact d^ rived from it. No such uncertainty is expressed by Jesus, the apostles, or any christian. With them the belief of a resurrection was as unshaken as that of death, and it operated accordingl}', re- lieving them from all anxiety on the subject, and enabling them e\erto rejoice in the prospect of ex- ehanging this life for a better. P5. On 2C2 OF THE PHILOSOPHY On the subject o[ sd/jnunkr, the Stoics seem to have had no settled opinion, some times main*.c'.in- ing, as the emperor seems to do, tiiat it is the duty of every man to remain in tlic station in ^' hich pro- vidence hr.s placed him, till he receives an order from tlie same power to quit it, by ^\hich must be meant, something foreign to a man's own a\ ill, or inclination, as by disease, or violence. But if ve judge by the practice of scm:: ufthe most dis- tinguished ofthe sect, as that of Zer.o himself, Pla- to, and others, they considered it as an act of great heroism, especially becoming a man who must o- tlierwise live in ignominy ; notwithstanding their maintaining at other times, that neither praise nor blame, servitude or exile, being things foreign to a man's self, ought to give him any uneasiness. Marcus Antoninus himself expresses, though somewhat obscurely, his approbation of self mur- der. "If you must die (Lib. v. sret. 29.) let it "be as those who have suffered nothing. If the " smoke be troublesome, I leave it. Why should " this appear of consequence to any person ? But " nothing compels me to depart. I rcn^ove irce- " l}-^, since no person can hinder me from doing " what I please. It is my \\\s\\ to do what belongs ** to a m.ui enddcd willi reason, and born lor socie- OF THE STOICS. 233 <* ty.'* This allusion to his quitting a smoky- house, looks like a voluntary act ; the compulsion being very inconsiderable, since a smoky house is tolerable though not pleasant. The amount of all these philosophical remedies against the fear of death, is nothing more than a pati- ent acquiescence in what is unavoidable, and what must be taken for granted is right, with respect to the \\hole system of ^^•hich we are a part : deadi, as well as birth, being included in it. The same ar- gument applies to the deprivation of any thing that men \'alue, as health, riches, pleasure, pov.er, Sec. &c. but wliat can prevent our regret at the loss of them, if we really value them ? and is not life a thing that all men value, and consequently must they not naturally part with it, as -well as other things, with regret, when they can retain it no long- er, and have no prospect of any equivalent for the loss, which must have been the case with the hea- then world ? This is certainly the language of na- ture ; and if philosophers say any thing to the con- traiy , as the Stoics do, it is a proof diat their prin- ciples are not agreeable to nature, and therefore false, and their topics of consolation under afHicti- on, and in the prospect of death, are not adapted to the nature and condition of man. How 234 OF THE PIIILOSOniY' How unspeakably more natural, and therefor© more cITicacious, and valuable, is the consolation that Christianity holds out to a dying man, who is conscious that he has lived a virtuous life ! It is not the gloomy consolation of the dispersion of the elements of w hich his body consists, and never to be collected again, or the rc-union of his soul to tliat of the whole universe, from m Iiieh he cannot conceive any source of joy to himself individually, and of w hich, indeed, he cannot form an.y distinct idea ; but the exchaiige of this ll^j for a better, a state in which he will not be subject to sickness or pain, and in vhich he will not die any more, but continue in existence without end ; and this not mere existence, but a life of the truest enjoyment, the enjoyment of things which the apostle says, eye hath iiGt seen, nor ear heard ^ and such as it has not entered into the mind of man to conceive. AV'idi this prospect, certain and glorious, tliough not distinct and particular, mcII may the christiim siiy in dying, death where is thy sting, grave ivliere is tliy victory / That christians cf eveiy^ denomination actually believe this, and that this is the most es- sential and uniuestionuble article of tl.cir faith, cannot be denied ; and this firm fiith accounts. in the most suti.,factory mimner, not only for the calm OF THE STOICS. 235 calm -resignation, which is all that the Stoics pre- tend to, but the joy with which thousands of chris- tians have met death, and even endured the ^eatcst tortures that could be inflicted upon them, rather than renounce their faith. Had Marcus Antoninus been acquainted with tlic sentiments of christians on this subject, he couIl. not have called their refusal to In'e on the terms that he proposed to them obstinacy^ because it had a natural and real foundation, the bearing of an evil of short continuance, however severe, for a degree of happiness that would be an abundant re compence for it. The Stoics, indeed, held out as v/e have seen a kind of immortality to man, in those great revoluti- ons, to which tliey supposed that, at certain periods, every thing in nature would be subject, so that as cverv thing had once been in the very state in which it now is, it will sometime hence revert to the very same, and so \\ithout end, and without a- ny improvement. But besides that this notion, which is also entertained by the Hindoos, and pro- bably came into Greece from the East, is destitute of all foundation, and could hiudly be seriously^ believed by any man, how inferior is it to that 'kind of immortality tliat chiistians are taught to expect. 236 OF THE fHILOSOPHY expect ! A state of existence that w ill not only have no end, but that w ill be continually improv- ing; an idea most sublime and transporting, and vdhichib countenanced even by present appearances, as we actually obscne the state of mankind, and of every thing wc see, to be in a st;ite of improvement. Compared \\ ith the cold indifilrence, (and this no doubt in a gi'eat measure affected) ^\'ith which Marcus Antoninus speaks of meeting death, how short does i: fall of the joy, and even rapture, with ■which the apostle Paul speaks of his approaching end! (2. Tim. c. iv. v. 6.) / am no\v rcfat/y to be offered, and the time of my departure is at hand, I have fought the good fight. I ha'ce finished my course. I have kept the faith. Henceforth there is laid up fior me a cro\vn ofi righteousness, ivhich the Lord, the righteous judge, shall give me at that day ; arid not to me only, hut unto all them also that love his appearing. What an idea does tliis gi\e us of the infinite superiority of the principles of Christianity to those of heathen philosophy of every kind ! The probability is, that Marcus Antoninus held the christians (few of whom pretended to any know- ledge of philosophy) in too great contempt to make any proper inquiry uito their sentiments, or to read or THE STOICS. 237 l^ad their writings. He had learned, he saj-s, (Lib. i. sect. 6.) '* of Diognctus not to spend his ^' time about trifles, nor to give credit to those who ** dealt in inchantments and exorcisms, and other ** impostures of that nature." And being under the influence, as he evidently was, of the Greek phi- losophers, cad taking all his lessons from them, he was no doubt, targht to believe that all die miracles the clu-Jstians nretendcd to, as the foundation of theii- religion, were no better founded than such inchantineiits and exorcisms as many of the hca- diens also pretended to. So educated and instructed, he could not have any proper idea of the firm faith and hope of chris- tians, which, without any aid of speculative philo- sophy, enabled them to bear, v.ith what he calls ob- st'mdcy^ all the tortures that he, in so unrelenting a manner, ordered to be inflicted upon them. What could his boasted philosophy do in comparison with tliis ? Thus was the wisdom of this worlds with every advantage that time and reflection could give it, mere fooUjhness, as the apostle called it, compared with the simple doctrines of Christianity, which were intelligible andefl&cacious with the lo\\'- cst, and least exercised understanding, as well as the highest. Indeed, the admirable plainness, and as 238 OF THE PHILOSOPHY as well as superior excellence of its principles, le- vels all distinctions of this and of every other kind. To the poor the gospel is preached, as well as to the rich ; and it is e^qually intelligible to them. Ac- cording to the gospel, as in die eye of God, all men are equal. It is conferred as a conimon blessing on all his ofispring of manliind. But ^\ ith this excellent religion Marcus Antoni- niiswas unacquainted, and from his pride as a philosopher, \\\\\d\ is sufficiently conspicuous in his w 1 itings, his contempt of the «tTu doctrine of christians, who made no account of his philoso- phy, or any other, his zeal for the welfare of die em- pire, at the head of which he was placed, and on which his glory depended, which, Avidi iill odier heathens, he imagined to have some unknown con- nection \vith the observance of those antient rites, in which the christiiuis refused to join, he might, without any particular cruelty in his disposition, direct the persecution ^\'hich continued during the whole of his reign. It is farther probable diat he only hcaixl of the sufferings of the christians through die unllivourable accounts of his officers, who would naturally be disposed to ridicule, and make light of them, and to flatter him with respect to the success of his measures. And Uius, w iUi- out QF THE STOICS. 23b out hearkening to any remonstrance or intreat}^ m\d resisting, as his philosophy t lught him to do, every motion of compassion, which he might think was farther unbecoming him as an emperor, he might persist as he did without remorse, in those rigorous proceedings as long as he lived. He had less knowledge of Christianity than Julian, and therefore less guilt; as in all respects he was a fRUch superior character. Q. TH5 2tG T Vt E flllLOSOPIIY ARHIAN AND SENECA. INTRODUCTION. jjfEXiXA and An-ian were both men of the world, and statesmen; the former tutor to Nero, and the latter diatliiq-uibhed by the most honoura- blc employments under Adrian, and the succeed- \\v^ emperors. But both of thcni were great wri- ters, and both made profession of the Stoic philo- sophy. Arriln was a disciple of Epictctus, and the Enchiridion was com.posed by him from the sayinp;sof his master. Seneca appears to have been well acquainted with all the sects of tlie Greek phi- losophy, and he particularly quotes a great num- ber of the sayin.i^s of Epicurus, but he preferred the philosophy of the Stoics to any otlier. " Otl^ers," he says (De Const. Sap. c. 1.) " pro- " eecd in a gentle maimer, but the Stoics endea- " your OF THE ::toics. ^41 *' voiir to raise men at on-^e to the hij^hcst pitch " of excellence." This philosophy, indeed, may be said to have been the greatest effort of human ge- nius on the important suhjcct o[ rel'g ion and mo- rals^ in \\hich the proper conduct of life, under all the evils of it, and the prospect of death, subjects so highly interesting to all men, ai-c particularlv in- sisted upon. I have, however, chosen to give the details of it from Marcus Antoninus and Epicte- tus, rather than from ScMicca or Arrian, because the former, not being writers by profession, as we may consider the others to have been, mav be sup- posed to have expressed their sentiments without exaggeration ; so that v,'G are in less danger of being misled by any thing like oratory in their ^vorks. Some valuable illustrations, howe\cr, of the Stoi- cal principles will be found in the Vvritlngs of Sene- ca and Arrian, and expressed with more empha- sis, for which we may m.ahc what allowance we think proper. Section I. 0/ God and Pro^oidence* The Stoics strictly followed Socrates in the be- lief of the being, and of the v.ise and benevolent Q 2. provi- 24i^ OF THE PHIIOSOPHV providci.cc, of a sij'>rcmt' intelligence, whether it resided in one suLject or many. Indeed, on thi«r ail their di'jtinguihhing maxima, Cbpeeially that of the soul of man being a portion of this intelligence, njid retaining- its pov. ers, depended. Other philo- sophers held viirious opinions on this subject. .'Vr- rian gives the following account of them. *' Concerning the gods," he siiys, (Lib. i. cap. 12.) "some say there arc no gods ; others that they " exist, but take no care of any thing ; others that *' they exist, but take no care of any besides ce- " ICvStial tilings ; others thut ihey attend both to *' celestial and tenestriiil things, but only in a gcnc- *' ral V. ay ; others, like Uljsses and Socrates, siiy *' that we cannot even move v» itliout God." Ar- rian himself proves the being of a god from the wonderful frame of tlie world (Lib. i. cap. C.) He even supposes tliat God made the sini, \\ hieh Mar- cus Antoninus, and the heathens hi general, sup- posed to be itself a deity. " Can that God who " made the sun, and guides it," he says (Lib. i. cap. 14.) " a small part of lus works compared to *' the universe, not sec all things." Seneca also feavs (Ep. 41.) " such a system as this could not " stand without the support of the deity. AV'hen *' } ou are most alone," sa}s» Arriaii (Lib. i. cap. 'or THE STOICS. 243 cap. 14.) " God is within you ; your gv-^ni- " us is within you. Do they require light to *' see what you do ?" See also Seneca, (Ep. 41.) Like Socniiles, the Stoics connected good mo- lals with their regard to Gvjd. Arrian having mentioned the deity says (Lib. ii. cap. 14.) " such *' as the deity is, such will be those who endea- *' vour to please Iiim. If he be faithful, they will *' be so. If he be beneficent, the}' will be so. If he *' be magnanimous, they will be so." He shews ^t large the great danger that would not fail to re- sult to society from a general neglect of religion. *' Then," says he (Lib. ii. cap. 20.) "justice is *' nothing, modesty is folly, and the relation of (U- *' ther and son is as nothing." The constant presence, and assistance, of God was thought by some of the Stoics to be necessary to all good men. *' There is no good man," says Seneca (Ep. 41.) '* without God. No person can *^ rise above fortune, but as assisted by him. It is " he that gives great and exalted councils. God," he says, *' removes from good men every evil, all **■ wickedness , evil thoughts, blind lust, avarice," ?vC. (De Provid* chap. 6.) He did not, however, suppose that the divine guide of each parti cular person was a deity of the highest rank. For he Q 3. sa) »- 244 or THE PHILOSOPHY says (Ep. 110.) " Every person has a god for his "■ ^uicle, but one of an inferior kind."* 'I'hc union of tiiis intelligent principle, which occasionally descended to the earth to the aid of men, is thus expressed by Seneca (Ep. 41.) " As *• the rays of the sun reach to the earth, but arc '' still united to their source; so a great and sa- ** crcd mind, being sent dow n hither that \\c may " have d nearer ^'ie\v of divine things, converses •* with us, but adheres to its original." It is not easy to say what the heathen philoso- phers and others thought oi/aic, and the relation that the gods bore to it. Sometimes tlicy seem to have thought that they directed fate, at other times that fate v.as a power independent of them, and that controlled them. Seneca seems to have thought that late was nothing more than the will of tlic gods themselves. "Tiieuuthoraiid governor of all things'' he says (Prov. v. cap. 1.) "wrote the fates, but " he Ibllows them. He orders, but always obeys. *' Some things must always please God (Quaest. " Nat. Lib. i. pri\;f. ) bcaiuse the best things '' on)}- please liim. Nor is he on this account less "free, * T//OSC of this class of deities that atlcrnkd luo- saen "wcrc by the heathens called Juno's. OF THE STOICS. 245- *' free, or powerful ; for he is his own necessity. " If this be not the cr^se, it would not be worth " while to be bom." It was taken for granted by all tl\e later phllo.io- pliers, that the gods were incapiU^le of angcry iis well as all good men ; and the natural consecjucncc of this opinion was that there could be no fulure punishment for the wicked , which took awa;- a great motive against the commission of vice. " The immortal gods," says Seneca (Dc Ira. Lib. ii. c. 27.) " neither will any anger, nor can indulge *' in any. Their nature is mild, and placid^ as re- *' mote from injuring others as themselves. No *' man in his senses" he says (De Bencf. Lilj. iv. cap. 19.) " fears God, for it is madness to feai *' what is salutary ; nor can any person lo\ c uliat " he fears. No person is so much a child as to be *' afraid of Cerberus." And he joins the Epicu- reans in their contempt of every thing in the hifer- nal regions. (Ep. 24.) It appears from the v»'ritings of Arrian, that tlie common people among the heathens were ^^ery re- ligious in their way. " No person," he says (Lib. iii. cap. 21.) " leaves a port without sacrificing to *' the gods ; nor do husbandmen sow without in- Q 4. " yoking £4 ^^ TIIF. fHILO SOPHY " yoking Ceres. W'ould any person who should *' neglect such duties be safe ?" lie must liavc thought, however, that such rites as these took thcplace of duties of more importance, when he said (Lib. ii. cap. 7.) ''Bv means of un- *' seasonable divination many duties aie neglqcW. ♦' ed." Sectiox II. Of the Soul of Man, avd its Power. We have seen enough, it miglit be tliought, of the consequences which the Stoics chew from their opinion of the derivation of the souls of men from the supreme intelligence, in ascribing to tliem si- milar powers, especially that of absolute self-suffi- ciency, and a total independence on even' thing fo- reign to itself, even, on the body, to ^hieh it is, hovv'e\er, necessarily connected at present. But arrogant as is the language of Marcus Antoninus and Ej)ictctus on the subject, it falls short of tliat of Seneca, One ob-sious similarity between God and man is their relation to matter. *' The place," says Seneca (Ep. 65.) " that God has in the world, the " mind OF THE STOICS. 247 ** mind has in man. He works upon matter, and *' tl^e mind upon the body." But he surely eould pot tliink that the supreme mind was as necessari^ Jy attached to the material system as to be aiFected by every thing that passes in it, as the mind is by the affections of the body ; which, though it may make light of it, has no power to free itself. The union of the soul with the supreme ii^telligence, notwithstanding its present separation from it, is thus maintained by Seneca. " There is nothing," he says, (Ep. 92.) <* improper in endeavouring to " ascend from whence we came. Why should ** we not think there is something divine in a good *' man, since he is part of God. The whole sys, " tern is one, and is God. We are his compani- ^* ons, and members of him." To christians, who believe that there is an infi- nite difference between God and man ; and his in- finite superiority to us, notwithstanding our being said to be made in his image ^ and to resemble iiim in some respects, the language of Seneca respect- ing their equality is truly shocking. " A good " man," he says, (De Provid. chap. 1. & 2.) '^ dif- *' fers froni God only with respect to time. He is; hior *' disciple, his emulator, and true offspring, whom *' he educates ^\ith severity, to prepare him for Q 5. '' him 248 OF THE PHILOSOPHY ** himself; but no real evil can bcfal a good man. *' God," he farther says (Ep. 73.) " is not superi- ** or to man in liappincss, but only in time ";' and *' virtue is not greater for being of longer continu- " ance." What he says above of God training up good men to .prepare them for himself is a truly fine sentiment, though connected with so much extravagance. Seneca g()es be3'ond Marcus Antoninus in his boasting of the all sufficiency of the mind of man with respect to happiness, and its independence on every thing foreign to itself. "It is,"hcsiiys, (De Consol. ad. Hclv. c. 5.) " in the power of eve- • ' vy man to make himself happy . With respect to him.self," he says, " I assure you I am not unhap- *' py, (miserum)," and, m.oreover, that I cannot be " so (lb. c. 4.) If small things cannot affect a wise *' man, (De Constant. Sap. c. 15.) neither can *' greater things ; if not a few, neither many. I *' would persuade you neA'er to pity a good man, *' De Prov. c. 3.) for though he may seem to be *' miserable, he cannot be so." To manv this would seem a difficult attainment, but not so to our author. " What does reason *' require of man, but the easiest things, (Ep. 41.) <' viz. to live according to nature. A wise man is " no Of THE STOICS. 249 ** no creature of imagination. There arc many " examples of it, and Cato seems to have exceed- " ed what v/as required of him." (Dc Const. Sap. c 7. This extraordinary power, it is evident, howe- ver, that Arrian restricts to philosophers. '* Philoso- " phy," says he, (Lib. ii. cap. I.) '' allows none to " be free, but those who have been instructed (TriTra/- " Sfi/ufvc/) that is, God does not permit it." Again he says, (Lib. ii. cap. 19.) " She v/ me a person *' who is sick and happy, in danger and iiappy, " dj'ing and happy, banished and happy, disgraced ** and happy, such a one is a Stoic." Bat, sure- ly, such a one is rather a christian, hh source oi consolation under the evils mentioned alone, be- ing infinitely superior to any that the Stoics could have recourse to, and accessible to persor^s of the meanest capacity, such as they could ae\ cr have adopted, or indeed have understood, viz. the distinction of things within the power of the mind, and things foreign to it, in the sense of tlic Stoics, As to dying circumstances, there caimot, surely, be a question of the superior happiness of the eliris- tian, for reasons obvious enough, and enlarged up- on in the preceding scclion. *' The ^50 OF TJIE rUILO'SOPJlT The po^\cr of llie mind o\ct tlic bocly is ralh(^ -Inorc strongly expressed b}' Arrian than by any other Stoic writer. *' My IkicK," he sa^ys, (Lib. iii. cap.) 22. " is not me, its parts arc nothing to •' mc. Death is nothing to me, let it come when " it will." He supposes a dialogue between a t}'- rantanda philosopher that is truly curious for tl>e extravagance of it. The tyrant says (Lib. i. cap. L) ** You shall die."" The philosopher replies, "but ** not lamenting. T. You shall be in chains. P. ♦' But not whining. T. You shall be banished. *' P. But what hinders my going laughing. T. •* Tell me your secrets. P. No, that is in my '^ power. T. But I will tlirow }ou into chains. " P, What say you, man? You may bind my -•' feet, but Jupiter himself c^^nnot change my reso- " lution. T. I will throw you into prison, and ** strike oif your head. P. And did I ever say *' that you could not strike it off? T. I will kill " you. P. When did I say that I \\as immortal ? *^ These things," he says, *' must be thought of, " and meditated upon." In one place, however, Arrian seems willing to make some allowance for the A\takness of human nature, and especially on account of the necessary influence of die body over the mind. " If the " rods/' OF THE STOICS/ 251 ** gods," he says, (Lib. i. cap. 1.) ''were willing *' to gnint us the command of the thing;s that are '' out of our power^tliey could not do it. Fof ** while wc itfc upon tlis earth, and are tied to snch *' bodies, imd sucti compaiilofis, ho\v is it possi!)!? " but that things foreign ta us must be an impedi- *' meiit to Ub." Seueca, whose luxurious and splendid mode of living did but ill con-espond with the maxims of his philosophy, and wliose flattery of the em])croi-y whom he must Jiave despised, was fulsome in ilie extreme, seems disposed to make still more allow- ance for the weakness of human nature than any other of the Stoics. " I v/ou Id prefer pleasure,'' he says, (Ep. 66.) " to pain if the choice was " proposed to me, because the former is more a- " greeable to nature, and the latter contrary to it.'^ But for the very same reason, is not every thing tliat men call good more agreeable to nature, than those that we agree to call emils ; and ho\v, on this concession, could pleasure and pain be classed a- mong the things that are perfectly indilFerent to a philosopher ? When his luxurious life was objected to him, he said, after reciting the particulars of it. " These *^ things are apud ?7i^, (in my pos5Cssion) but at " tlie 252 OF THE I'HILOCOPnv ** the f:ame time they nrc extra me^ (foreign to me, " i. c. to my mind") (Dc Vita, beata. cap. 23.} a ** pretty nice, but convenient distinction." Ac- cording to him, a more ingenious acknowledg- mcnt was made by Plato and l^picurus, when the same objection ^vas made to them. For tliey said, *' that men should hve accordinsr to what thev " thought, not as they themselves lived." (lb 18.) It Is not probable, however, that either of these men v.ould have said this in earnest. Others mnv have said it for diem, as Jesus did of die Scribes and Pharisees. Section III. Of Moral Precepts. Arrian has many excellent moral precepts ; but as they are similar to those of IVIarcus Antoninus abo\'e recited, they need not be repeated here. A- mong other things he says, (Lib. ii. cap. 6.) " Life *' is a thing indifferent, but not so die use of it. *' Difficulties shew who arc men. When you '* meet with them (Lib. i. cap. 24.) remember " that God is making you engage with a rough and " expert antagonist.'* As or THE STOICS. 253 As the Stoics made no allowance for the ialiil- gence of any passion^ or emotion^ which tliey refer- red to mere animal nature, tlie}- equally condemn- ed anger and compassion. *' Anger," says Seneca (Deira ii. cap. 14.) " is never to be indulged, but " only the appeai^ance of it to excite othcES as a " spur to a horse. A good man (lb. C.) is inca- *' pable of inflicting punishment ; but anger is a " punishment, and thererorc anger it not natural." On this subject, as well as on eve:y other hov/ much more natural is the doctrine of the scrip- tures, which alms not at the extirpations of any of our passions, but only at the due regulation of them. Be ye angry ^ but sin not. Let not the sun go down upon your ivrat/i. " Compassion," he says (Clem. ii. cap. 4.) *' is a vice of tlie mind, " in the view of the miseries of others. A v> ise " man will relieve a person that weeps, but he will •' not weep with him (cap. 6.) He will relieve the *' distressed, but without feeling compassion." On the subject of self murder AiTian seems ta be inconsistent. " God," he says (Lib. i. cap. 29.) *' requires such a world as this, and those tliat are " in it. If he order a retreat, as in the case of So- ** crates, we should yield obedience, as to a com- " mandep ^54 OF THE PHILOSOPHY " mander in chief." But on another occasion ho supposes that men ha\'e a right to judge for them- selves in this case, without waiting for the orders of any su perior. Addressing a discontented per- son he says, (Lib.i. cap. .9) " You slave, if you be " not satisfied, go out of life. The gate is open.'* Seneca is (juite decided in favour of the latter opi- nion. *' If you dislike life," he says (De Prov. c. 6.) the door is open. If you will not fight, you " may fly." He frequently commends Cato for putting im end to his own life : He even says (Ep. 13.) " Take away the sword from Cato, and you " take from him a great part of his gloiy " The indifference that he expressed to life or death would appear affected, as his Umguage certainly is on other occasions, but that he actually did meet death with sufficient fortitude, at the command of a cruel and capricious tyrant. " Death," he says (Ep. 21.) " is so far from being to be feared, that *' nothing is to be preferred to tlie benefit to be de^ ** rived from it." Lipsius, however, proposes a- nother reading) which softens this. He also says (Ep. 54.) " We know what death is. It is to be *' \vhat we were before we ^ve^e bom, when we *' had no sense of t"u?7." But it follows ft-om this that neither shall we have after death a sense of any OF THE STOICS. 255 good. And this seems to have been the real opi- nion of all the later heathen philosophers, not- withstiuiding what they sometimes say of the im- mortality oi'' die souh When, in his eloquent manner, he describes the destriietion and renovati- on of the world hes:iys (De Cortjolatione adMarci- am. cap. 26.) "We also, happy souls, when it *' shall please God to renew all things, shall only *' be a small addition to the immense ruin, and *' shall be changed into theaniient elements." What he says to Marcia, (cap. 25.) of her son being received by the Scipio's and Cato's ; See. af- ter his death, could only be said by way of accom- modation to heropinioni, and as a topic of consola- tion, and not his own real belief. R. THE 25« THE PlilLOSOPHY of EPICURUS. INTRODUCTION. JL he only sect of Grecian philosophy tliat re- mains to be considered, as coming within my ob- ject, of a comparison of them with tlic system of revelation, is that oi Epicurus which arose present- ly after that of the Stoics, to which it was, in many respects, opposite and hostile ; the one being re- markable for its austerity, and the other for its ease in the conduct of life ; the one for a belief in a di- vine pro\idcnce, as superintending eveiy thing in the world, and the other for the utter neglect and contempt of religion in every form. There was also another source of opposition and hostility be- tu-een the two. All the philosophers w ho had pre- cecded Epicurus, the Stoics among the rest, had deserted the plain maxims of Socrates, and spent the bF THE PHILOSOPHY, 8cC. 257 the greatest part of their time on Logic and Meta- phvsicks, of no use whatever in the conduct of life; whereas Epicurus, following the steps of their common master, held all their subtle disputa- tions on these subjects in the greatest contempt, and made the true enjoyment of life the great ob- ject of his philosophy. And considering that the great doctrine of a future state was in fact exclud- ed from all their systems, there was more of reason and good sense indie maxims of Epicurus than in theirs; especially as, though he maintained diat pleasure was the great end of life, he did not, as wc shall see, mean sensual pleasure, but the happmess of man upon the whole, in which temperance, and every virtue, was an essential ingredient. Epicurus also differed from other philosophers in the circumstances of his leaching, more resem- bling a society of friends, than that of master and scholars. Their meetings were held in a private garden of his own ; and the friendship of this fra- ternity Cicero spake of in the highest temis. (A- cad. Lib. 20.) though they had not every thing in common, like the disciples of Pythagoras. Though we have no proper treatise oi^ Epicu- rus, we have several of his letters preserved by Di- ogenes Laertius, especially one to Herodotus, in R 2. which^ Cj8 OV the PHILOiOrHY which he profcbscs to give aii outline of his princi- ples. And the poem of Lucretius contains a dc- velopcnient oi' the w 'nole of iiis pliilosophy. From these it is ea^y to form a very complete idea oi his tenets; and from these, and seme of his sayingy tjuotedby Seneea, the following account is given. Section I* >0f God and of tlic Structure of the Unhcrsd. Fpicurus's triumph over religion in all its forms, and thereby delivering men from the fear of death, Ava.s the great boast of all his followers, this victor}- (Lucretius says Lib. i. V. 78.) has raised men from earth to heaAcn, and by this means he has conferred greater benefit on mankind than Ce- res in giving diem bread, or Bacchus in giving them wine (lb. Lib. v. V. 15.) Religion he consi- dered as having done unspeakable mischief to man- kind, and in jxirticulMr instances the sacrifice of Iphigenia, the daughter of Agamemnon to Dia- na, of w hich he gives a verj- afiecting description* (Lucret. Lib. i. V. 85.) Kpicunis did not, ho\ve\er deny the existence of gods, imd though this is commonly thought to have OF TilE STOICS. 259 hn\^ been only ^^'ith a view to his safety ; since by an open profession of atheism he would ha\'e been exposed ^o the rigour of the Athenian laws, I think he iniglit have been -/ery sincere in that opinion ; tH'n];ina^, with all other philosophers, that every pir» of the univci'se was replete v»'ith inhabitants, ctiited to their natures, the gods occupying the higher regions, demons the middle, and men the earth. Wliat lie openly maintained v/as that, tho' there ere go^k t\\cy take no thought about thj affairs of thh vrorld. " The god*," he says (Diog. Laert. pag. 785.) " are immortal ** and happy beings *^-*' but not such as tlie *' vulgar opinion makes them to be;" and hav- ing said that happiness is two fold, he adds tliat '*' supreme hapj^iness is that of the gods A\'hlch ad- " mits of no addition." (lb 783-4.) The reason that he gives for this opinion is, that happiness could not consist vidth the ti'ouble and "care which he thought must attend the go^'cm- ment of the world, though he seems to ha\c thought that they had something to do in the up- per regions, which are nearest to them. Speaking of the motions, and other properties of meteors, lie says (lb. 755.) " They are not directed by any *' thing besides tlie ord;:r and appointment of him '' who 062 or THF. rniT.osopHT *' ^vho has all happiness and immortality. For it ' is inconsistent with haj)piuciis to ha\e business, *' and cares, or to be affected by anger, or favour, •' These l^elongto beings subject to infirmity, and " fear, who stand in need of others." Again he says, (lb. 735.) " Whoever is happy, and immor- ** lal, neither has any troublesome business him- " self, nor gives trouble to others ; and in conse- " quencc of this he is neidier moved by anger " or favour." As to the charge of impiety he says, (lb. 786.) " he is not guilty of impiety who Uikes from the *' muliiplicity of Gods, but he who adopts the opi- *' nion of the multitude concerning them," Lu- cretius ascribes the origin, and the frightful effects cf religion upon the human mind, in part to what people' see, or imagine they sec, in dreams, as well as to the regular course of the heavenly bodies, and to die terror excited by storms, thunder, light- ening, earthquakes, &c. For seeing no cause of these things, men ascribe them to some un- known invisible beings, whose po\ver was great, and tremendous. (Lucret. Lib. v. V. 1165. &.c. Considering the vulgar superstition, ajid the serious eli'ccts of it in human sacrifices, prostituti- on? OF THE STOICS. 261 ons in religious rites, divination, and its distruct- ing influence in the common business of life, it may well be questioned whetlier it was not wiser, with Epicurus, to reject it altogether, than to re- tain it in any form or degree. Nay I doubt not but the system of Pol}-theism and Idolatry took more from the happiness of mankind than either Epicurus or Lucretius suspected. Epicurus, however, well knew that none of the philosophers maintained the vulgar opinions, but much more honourable ideas of tlie divinity and the govern- ment (y. the worlds opinions highly pleasing to good men, and perhaps some restraint upon the wicked ; and we shall see that his ideas of the govenuuent of tlie world, and the direction of it, \vhich diffeied exceedingly from those of other philosophers, \verc absurd in the extreme, in supposing that there A\as no wisdom, design, or a regard to final causes, in tilings that most of all required tliem. The Atomical system, which ^^ as oi7j:)osed to that of Plato, and most other philosophers, who held that the world was formed by an intelligent principle, out of pre-existent matter, and that it was finite, was first suggested by Democritus, but adopted by Epicurus. He maintained that there was no wisdom employed in the arrangement of R 4. any 262 or THE riiiLosofHY any part of the system, !)ut that it arose from the foiiuitous concourse of atoms, moving at random in all directions. " Tliesc atoms" he says, (Dioc^. Lacrt. p. 74 1.) " have no properties besides those "of figure, gravity and magnitude; but being *' perfectly hard, though of difttrcnt forms, they " are incapable of destruction, or change." The construction of the world, according to Lucretius, is too faulty to have aiisen fiom a principle of in- telligence anddcsign^ (Lucret. Lib. ii. V. 180.) The universe having come into existence from these materials, "it must." Epicurus s;,; s (lb. 733.) " be infinite. For had there been any bounds *' to it, the parts of which it consists would have "been dispersed into infinite space; having no; " place to fix in, and nothirig to stop their motion,'*^ n^oreo^•er, since the giving these floating atoms, every chance for. their fortunate meeting, so as to. form such a compieie system as this, must have re- quirLti ahnobt infinite time hcibre it could have taken place, he maintained, contrary to die opinion of many other philosophers that " the world had a "beginning, and will have an end. (Lib. v. V. 245.) Since the continual contention, and dispo- sition to motion, in the elements of \\ Inch it con- sists will in course of time efl'cct its compleat dis- solution OF THE STOICS. 263 solution. He even thought there were already evident signs of a tendency to decay and disso- lution in the earth, and that there has been a great degeneracy in all its productions, animals being now of less size and strength than they were for- merly, and all the products of the earth requiring the labour of man which they did not originally, when every thing for the use of man was produced by it spontaneously (Lucret. Lib. ii. V. 1150. and 1170.) so that in time every thing will probably decline more and more, and the a\ hole go to decay and ruin. But since nothing could be formed out of nothing, the atoms of which it consists can only be dispersed to form other systems, and can ne- ver be annihilated (Lucret. Lib. i. V. 150. 8c21G.} But before this event takes place Epicurus main- •tained that, with the exception of the gradual de- cay mentioned above, " every thing is now as it *' ever has been, and will continue to be ; since there is nothing into which it can be changed, and no superior power to make a change in it. (Diog. Laert. p. 732.) In the same manner as this world was formed, viz. by the random concourse of atoms, since the universe has no bounds, " other worlds," Epicu- rus says (Diog. Laert. p. 735. and 73G.) ''have, 115. "no 264 OF THE PHILOSOPHY *' no doubt been formed in the same manner; and " there is no reason w hy there may not be an in- *' finity of them, similar or dissimilar to this. *' For the atoms of which they are eomposed are " infinite, and earried to the greatest chstances." Such wild and absurd schemes, altogether un- worthy of examination or refutation, may the most ingenious of men be led to form for want of at- tention to a few fundamental principles, and those of the most obvious nature. For what can be more evident than that there are infinite marks of design, and what we call contrivance, in the sti'uc- ture of the world, and of ever)- j>lant and animal in it. Epicurus must have maintained that tlie eye was not formed for seeing, nor the ear for hear, ing; but that being so formed, by this fortuitous concourse of atoms, they were found to be capa- ble of these particular uses. Other philosophers, however, were not backward to acknowledge the reality of final causes, and consequently of design in the structure of the world, and of every part of it, and it is certainly unspeakably more satisfactory- to acknowlede, than to deny, this. W^e have then some superior intelligence to look to, as a be- ing to whom this world, and ourselves as a part of it, belong ; and who ^^ ill take some care of \\\mi witli OF THE STOICS. 265 With such exqaisite skill, he has planned and exe- cuted. Section II. Of the Human Soul. Since, according to Epicurus, every thing is in U perpetual flux, through the constant tendency to motion in its primary atoms, it could not be sup- posed that he would, with many other philoso- phers, maintain cither the pre-existence, or tiie im- mortality of the soul. Accordingly he denies, and even ridicules, diem both ; using however one just argument, though he was little aware of the real nature or extent of it, viz. "All thought arises from the impression made on the bodily senses,'* (Diog. Laert. p. 727.) thinking it to follow from this, that the soul, on which the impressions wcvo. made, was equally corporeal with the objects from which they came. His principal argument, however, is that there is nothing in nature besides body and space ^ m which bodies can be placed, and mo^•ed. " There " is nothing," he says (lb. 732) *' but what can *' be handled," or become the object of our sen- ses. ilGG or THE PHILOSOPHT ibcs.*' " Wc cannot even form an idea of any thinir ** cli;e. Nothing," he says, (lb. 749.) " is incor- ** poreal,*' (which all other piniosophers held the soul to be) " besides a -cacuulii^ whidi only affords " room for bodies to move in." He adds '* they " who siy that the soul is incorporeal tilk fool- y ishh". (at7a/a{c;\ill *' have no concern in public affairs." lliis wa* probably to avoid ever)- jealousy and opposition, ^\idi 1^11 the unpleasant consequences of them, un- avoidable to men in public life. For it could not be from idleness, in a man "s\ho MTote so many books, and who employed so much of his time in the instruction of others. From a similar motive he might say, (lb. 784.) " A wise man will make •' use of poems, but will not compose any him- ♦' self." Agreeably to diis he says, (lb. 761.) " the. K or THE STOICS, 271 " the happiness of life does not require viuity, or ** vain glory," which he might think to be particu- larly conspicuous in poets, " but in tranquility " and security." In order to secure his favourite tranquility, he recommended the practice of universal virtue ; and according to all accounts, his own life was v.ithout reproach in this respect. " The virtues," he says, (lb. 795.) " are chosen for the sake of pleasure, *' and not on their own account;" which is true when properly explained. For when the two are compared, happiness appears to be the end^ and virtue the means, though the necessary means, to attain it. He justly represents the chief cause of perturba- tion, and consequently of unhappiness in general, to be wrong dispositions of mind, which he says it is the business of philosophy to correct. '' What " men suffer," he says, (lb. 781.) "from hatred, " envy or contempt, a man may overcome by rea- ** son ; and he who has once been m ise will not *' acquire different habits, or yield to any cause of ** perturbation, or to any thing else that may retard " his progress in knowledge. A wise man," he says, (lb. 784.) " will not be affected if iuiother be S. " said 172 OF lllE IMIILOSOPHY ** said to l»e ^^ i>xr tb.an he." On tliis account he rc- comnjcnds an application to philosophy at all times of life. " If any jirson say it is too soon or too " late to apply to philosophy, it is, he says, tliesame " th/ing as if he said it is too late or too soon to be "happy." (lb. 785.) The life of Epicurus Mas according to all ac- counts con.formable to his precepts ; and so far was he or his disciples from habits of self-indul- gence, that no persons lived more abstemiously, on the plainest food, and drinking little besides a\ ater. (lb. 713.) V\'liat he himself says on this subject, (lb. 790.) is particularly deserving of attention. V/e consider frugality," he says, "as a great " good, not that we should always live spaiinglv, " but that when we cannot do otherwise, we may " be satisfied with a little, and ha^•e a greater en- " joyment of abundcUice when we have it. Plain *' bread i:nd watci- give the greatest pleasure when "they iU"C wanted; and to accustom oncs'selfto " plain food, not exquisitely prepared, contii- " butes both to health and activity for all the pur- " poses of life, and makes us not to ditad bad for- " tune. When, therefore, we say that pleasure is " the end of life, it is not the pleasure of the luxu- <" rious and the spendthrift, w hich consists in cat- "ing i OF THE STOICS. 273 " ing and drinking to excess, wliichcome, through ** ignorance or perverseness, say that we maintain, " but to be free from pain of body and to enjoy " tranquility of mind, free from all perturbation. *' There is no living pleasantly but by living pru- *' dently, honorably, and justly. For the virtues " are connected with a delightful and pleasant life, *' and cannot be seperated from ihcm." Epicu- rus must have been of a pleasant, social, and bene- volent turn of mind, to have attached so many per- sons to him as is universally acknov. ledged that he did. He says, (lb. 801.) *' the most valuable ** thing in life is the acquisition of friendship. " I shall conclude this article with some valuable sayings of Epicurus, quoted by Seneca. " If you '' live according to nature, you will never be poor, '* but if you live according to the opinion of others, "you will never be rich (Ep. 10.) The man *' who lives upon bread and water can never be " poor ; and he who can confine his desires to ** this, may vie with Jupiter for happiness (Ep. 25.) *' First consider with whom you eat and drink ; " and then what you eat and drink (Ep. 19.) They ** live ill who are always beginning to live." (Ep. 23.) Thus wc have seen that, at the commencement S 2. of £74 OF THE PHILOSOPHY cFour cnqiiin-, all the more intelligent Gixeks re- tiiined the belief of the exist/^ncc of one Supreme B;ing, the mnkcrofthe world, and of all Lliinj^s in it, though aided by a muliiplicii}'^ of inferior ones in the g;overnmcnt of it : of the constant attention ofthii great Beinr^ to uU Iranian affairs, of his love ofAartue, and abhorrence of vice, and of such an administration of the- world, as that the wicked \\ill generally meet with tlieir due punishment, and the virtuous \a 1th dieir jMoper reward ; that the souls of all men arc immortal, and v, ill be more fully rewarded or punished, according to their de- fcrts, in a future state. But as v^e have advanced, we have found these principles and motives of moral CfMxUict grow^ more obscure, till at last they en- tire ly vanished; other principles, utterly inconsist- ent with them, being generally received ; as that of the derivation of all human souls from the sub- tance of the Supreme Being, and their final ab- sorption into tliC same source again, all individual consciousness being thereby lost. The last of these sects, viz. tliat of die Epicureans, who disco- ver more good sense, and consister.cy in other re- spects, disclaimed all belief of wisdom and design indie construction of the universe, and of the pro- \idcnce of God in any of the aiFuii-s of men at this time OF THE STOICS. 2/5 tisTie, too, the last period of heathen philosophy, all the sects, without exception, had abandoned the belief of a future state of any kind. And yet, with respect to mental ability, the founders of these sects may be classed amon.g the first of the hu- man race, sagacious, thoughtful, and laborious, in the extreme. What prospect was there, then, of the world ever becoming more enliglitened by human wisdom, and the experiment was continued a sufficient length of time, from Pythagoras to Marcus Antoninus, a space of about seven hun- dred years. But what men could not do for themselves, it pleased God to do for them ; and after giving much light to one particular nation, hi the fulness of time he sent Jesus Clirist, with aijundant evi- dence of a divine mission to be the light of the whole world. His doctrine, in a reasonable time, through die instrumentality of men, to appearance tlie least qualified for the undertaking, arid in spite of all opposition from power, from prejudice, and from heathen philosophy, establised itseli^, to the utter overtlirow of all jDreceeding religions, which having been maintained from time immemorial, and thought to be connected with the well being of t\zry state, had ever been held the most sa- cred. 27G or THE THILOSOPHY, ScC. rrccl. At present no doubt is enteiHiincd l^y any chrijitian of llic Li inc^ or providence of God in this state, or of a ri;:^htcous retnl)ution in anotlier ; so thiit nothi?ig is v.antinr, no principle or mothc^ v.hateve*', to the virtue and happiness of man, hut his receiving this divine light, andilvir.g acccrdinj^ to it. THE END. CONTENTS. Dedication page I. Preface v. On the STATE of RELIGIOUS and MORAL PRINCIPLES in GREECE before the time of PYTHAGORAS. Introduction Page 1 Section I. Of the obligation to the Worship of the Gods i?i general 5 II. Of the Superiority of Jupiter^ the principal God of the Greeks 8 III. Of Promdence 10 IV. Of Jupiter'' s regard to Virtue 1 6 V. Of the Influence of the Fates 20 VI. Of Moral Duties, and also of Death and the Consequences of it 25 Of the PHILOSOPHY of PYTHAGORAS. Introduction 28 Section I. Concerning God 31 II. Of the Structure of the World 3^ III. Of the Human Soul 37 CONTENTS. I\^ Of Good and E'oUy Firtuc and yice 43 SOCRATES and JESUS COMPxVRED. Introduction 47 S E c T 1 N I . Of the Polytheism and Idolatry of Socrates 50 n. The Sentiments of Socrates con- cerning the Cods and their Providciice SZ III. Of the Excellent Moral Charac- ter of Socrates 58 IV. Ofthelmperjectionof Socrates's idea concerning Piety and Fir. tue in general 63 V^. Of Socrates'' s belief in a future State 70 VI. Of the Djemon of Socrates 78 \\\. Of the Character and Teaching of Socrates covipared 'iuith those of Jesus 86 ATII, Of the different Objects of the Instructions of Socrates and of Jesus 100 IX. Inferences to be draivnfrom the comparison of Socrates and J<'siis . 105 CONTENTS. On PLATONISM. Introduction 121 Section I. Of God and of his Providence 123 IL Of the Polytheism of Plato 135 III. Of the Human Soul 143 IV. Of Firiues and Vices 147 V. Of Deaths and the Consequences of it 153 Of the PHILOSOPHY of ARISTOTLE. Introduction IGl Sjectign I. Of the Beings the Attributes, and the Promdence, of God 165 II. Of the Human Soul 17G III, Of HappinesSy and of Virtue and Vice 179 Of the STOICAL PHILOSOPHY of MAR^ CUS ANTONINUS and EPIC- TETUS. Introduction 186 Section I. Of God and Providence 183 II. Of the Human Soul 197 III. Of Virtue and Vice 204 IV. Of the various Evils of Life 213 V. Of Death CONTENTS. Of the nilLOSOPHY gf ARjRIAN and SENECA. Introduction 240 Section I. Of God and Fro'oidaicc 211 II. Of the Soul of Man and /Vj Powers 2-16 III. Of Moral precepts 252 Of the PlilEOSOPHY of EPICURUS. Introduction 25G Section I. Of God and the Structure of the Unherse 258 II. Of the Human Soul 265 III. Of Human Life and Happiness 269 DEDICATION. To JOSHUA TOULMLN, D. D. Dear Sir, MY having- had for man}- years tlic hiippiness of your acquaintance and friendship, and particular- ly my ha\ing lately turned my thoughts to the sub- ject of one of your valuable dissertations y have led me to take the liberty to address to 3 ou tlie follow- ing ^.?6V7)', cliicfly as a testimonial, and one of the Inst that I shall be able to gi\e, of my esteem for your general principles and character. Having here much leisure, iuid ha\ing been led to look bi'ck to some writings of the anticnts with which I was formerly much better accjuainted than I am now , and among others the Mcmorabilid of Xniop/iofij and Plato'' s account of Socrates^ it oc- curred to me to draw out on exhibition of his prin- ciples DEDICATION. ciplesand conduct from die words of those two ori- ginal writers ; and this suggested the idea of draw- ing a comparison between him and Jesus. Knowing that you had published an excellent dissertation on the same subject, I forbore to look into it till mine was transcribed for the press. By this means I was not biassed, as I naturally should have been, in favour oi^yju:- opinion ; and I ha^'c seldom more than a \'ery indistinct recollection of any ^^•ork that I have not very recently read. On this second pe- rusal of your Dissertation I was as much pleased with it as I remember I was at the first, tliough I found that in some particulai's I diiTer from you. I hope that neither of us, inattentive as most persons now are to subjects of this kind, will have wholly written in vain. I take this opportunity of publicly thanking you for your many excellent publications in defence of rational Christianity. Having given so many specimens of your ability and zeal in the cause, it is to you, and your excellent coadjutors, Mr. Beisham, Mr. Kentish, and a few others, that the friends to the same cause ^vili naturally look, whenever particular occasions, occurring on your side of the water, will appear to call for a cham- pion. My labours in this or any other field of exertion DEDICATION. cx'jrtif;!! iv-c ncarl}' o\cr ; hut it gives mc much S'.ilinfitction to reflect on what I have done in defence Oi' wh.it appeared to me important christian truth. As v.v liinc laboured, I hope M'e sliall hereafter re- joice, tcgetlier. But v.e must hold out to the end, v. ithout heing iveary of well doing, indult^ing no remission of labour while we are capable of any. Even a d\inrr hand has sometimes done execution. AecordiuL;' to Uie apostle Paul, the whole life of evcrv eluistiim is a %varfare. Our enemies are "Cice and error, aiid ^\ilh them we must make neiUier peace nor truce. Their advocates will not make cither peace or truce with us. I know I shall not offend you by acknowledg- ing'', as I now do, that I had a pailiculai* view io you ill my late tract in favour of infant baptism. Whatever you may think of the performance itself, you will not, I am confident, think uncandidly of tlic intention \\\\\\ which it was written. While we really think for ourselves, it is impossible, in this state at least, but that we must often see things in difilivnt lights, and consequently form different opinions concerning them. But w ith the ingenuous minds which become ehristiiuis this will onlv be an occasion of exercisinir thiit candour which DEDICATION. which is one of the most prominent christian vir- tues, in which I am persuaded }ou will never be defective. With a very high degree of esteem, lam, Dear Sir, yours sincerely. J. PRIESTLEY. Northumberland Jan. 1803. Though the Dedication to Dr. Toulmin of tliat article in the work which relates to Socrates has no relation whatever to the subject of it, and is there- fore not inserted at the head of that article in tliis publication, my father wishing to preserve it as a monument of their friendship, directed me to have it printed at the end of the whole work. J. P. .A