GIFT OF Elisabeth Whitney Putn ^ at nan . ^p (Eleanor Kotnlanli THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART. THE RIGHT TO BELIEVE. HOUGHTON MIFFLIN COMPANY Boston and New York THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART Studies in Analytical Esthetics BY ELEANOR ROWLAND, Ph.D. Professor of Psychology and Dean of Women in Reed College BOSTON AND NEW YORK HOUGHTON MIFFLIN COMPANY ^z Ulitoecjiitie '^xzH Cambcibge COPYRIGHT, 1913, BY ELEANOR ROWLAND ALL RIGHTS RESERVED Published September iqi^ TO PROFESSOR HUGO MUNSTERBERG THE HONORED TEACHER WITH WHOM I FIRST BEGAN THE STUDY OF ^ESTHETICS 412480 PREFACE To a thoughtful person who spends any portion of his life in the contemplation of beautiful things, it must occur at one time or another that there is a certain strangeness in grouping under one head such an enormous variety of objects as we find in our world of Art, and labeling them with one term. What common factor unites such diverse creations as a poem and a cathedral, a song and a statue, and makes it possible and intelligible to call them all art products ? The answers to this question have been many. The problem has been attacked from standpoints that diverge so widely that the discussions have easily failed to meet on any issue. From the sociologist, the scientist, and the philosopher, to the practical artist, repre- vii PREFACE senting every type of training and habit of mind, have come more or less comprehen- sive surveys of the various arts, and at- tempts to define the meaning of Art as a whole. The historian is preeminently interested in what Art has been, and the reformer in what it should be. But to the philosopher or psychologist, the essential enigma is — what is it? That objects presenting diversity of material as wide as the world affords, and reflecting activities coextensive with man's whole life, can with any accuracy be brought into one group, and can produce certain characteristic states of mind, is indeed ex- traordinary. More than this, that certain materials should have been selected as most appropriate for clothing certain ideas, so that one idea flies to a garment of stone and an- other to one of words, yet both finished products remain art, is a puzzle that cannot viii PREFACE fail to tease the mind of one equally alive to the facts and to their apparent inconsist- ency. That many roads to the problem suggest themselves is evident enough from the num- ber that have been chosen. There is, how- ever, a directness in the method of a certain great writer on aesthetics which commends itself by its simplicity, and in his case at least, by the results. Aristotle set out for an explanation of tragedy as a form of art. What common factor makes a complete tragedy of this or that impersonation of character? To answer this question he lis- tened to the best tragedies. He spent time in their presence, observing what com- posed them, and exactly what made up his own state of mind as a spectator. He was then able to formulate an exposition of tragedy which has never been surpassed. If he had left us a similar analysis of the other ix PREFACE arts, such as that of sculpture with a dissect- ing of the "sculpturesque" emotions, the essentials of music and the common factor in all musical appreciation, much later work, and above all the present one, would not have been necessary. Some of the arts have developed since his day, so that any ancient formula must have been in any case outgrown, but it is as a humble disciple of Aristotle's method that the writer has conceived the following stud- ies. They represent an attempt to limit the provinces of certain arts, the ideas which these arts, better than any other of man's creation, can express, and the characteristic mental states that are aroused in appreciat- ing them — states which, like the pity and fear of tragedy, must be aroused if an object is to fulfill the demands of its own particular art. What one art may do and what it can never do remain still as obscure in many X PREFACE cases as if Lessing had never set the ex- ample of a masterly setting of limits. This group of studies makes no pretense to cover the field of the fine arts. It repre- sents merely the crystallization of some of the results of four years* teaching of aesthet- ics, and the arts which find no place in this analysis have been omitted because their treatment did not fall into a length and char- acter coordinate with the other essays. Portland, Oregon, May I, 1913. CONTENTS I. Sculpture I II. The Minor Arts 47 III. Painting . 83 IV. Music III V. Art and Nature . • 153 I SCULPTURE THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART SCULPTURE That our acquaintance with the world often dulls our appreciation of its real meaning has been a commonplace since the begin- ning of speculative thought. It was the task of Socrates, in Athens, to demand of his countrymen, somewhat too little aware of the mystery of things, that they define the nature of the simplest objects and give rea- sons for the most everyday pursuits. By exposing their ignorance in the matters of which they were most certain, he thus roused them to a more vigorous philosophy. It is profitable now and then, for us, as well, to 3 . THE/SIGNIFICANCE OF ART make a restatement of our old ideas, to "break through the crust of familiarity which tends to be deposited around well-known things," and to be as it were our own Socratic teachers. Let us suppose ourselves, then, deprived of all acquaintance with sculpture as a fine art, and for the sake of an unprejudiced point of view let us imagine ourselves as entering a gallery of statues for the first time. It is all to be a surprise to us. Everything will seem astonishing. There is to be an impartiality of emphasis as if we had succeeded in com- bining the sensitiveness of a mature appre- ciation with the candid curiosity of a child. Our questions when we are to be intro- duced to any new experience naturally fall into certain types. We ask, "What kind of thing is it to be? " "Are we to see, hear, or feel it?" "What is it made of?" "Why was it made?" "What are we to do with 4 SCULPTURE it ? ** " How must we act when brought into its presence ? " — and with such questions on our lips we are ushered into a gallery of sculpture, and told to find our answers as best we may. We are on the threshold of a long room, around the edges of which are arranged images of men and animals. Some are cut from marble, granite, or softer stone, and others are molten out of bronze. They all stand raised from the floor on pedestals, or hang as reliefs upon the wall, but this arti- ficial isolation only serves to emphasize a detachment which is already a conspicuous feature of their whole attitude. Here stands a youth in marble, well developed, nude, graceful, and with no apparent excuse for being, except that he exhibits a fine ideal of what a youth should be. There stands/ another boy, similarly well developed, al- though his build is somewhat diflferent, and 5 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART the poise of his limbs and the direction of his glance are slightly varied. We pass from one room to another, and lining every wall are quiet figures: some draped, some nude, some whole, some frag- mentary, some of marble, some of metal, some alone, and some in groups. But despite their proximity, no statue looks at us or at its neighbor. The room is full of them, but they are solitary ! Even when the figures make up one relief, and where they are engaged in actions which bind them seemingly together, they are curiously alone. A lady takes jewels from her handmaiden's box. In a gentle, idle fashion, as if despite her level glance she saw neither box nor maiden. An old man stands beside his son — a glorious youth, who (since this IS a grave relief) presumably has died, although there is no suggestion of death in his perfect form. He gazes away from his father, just as his father looks past him, 6 SCULPTURE while the dog at his feet snufFs for a foot- print that he cannot find. We recall other groups, where despite the fact that centaurs and Lapiths struggle for the possession of the women, the contest is an impersonal one. Each Lapith, each woman, is in a world of its own, and carries with it an air of unique self-sufficiency, which in a figure like that of the Olympian Apollo is almost overpower- ing. His proud arm is extended over a struggle which he does not deign to watch, and his eyes are turned to a horizon in- finitely remote. All this is not without its effect upon an observer. The atmosphere does not invite words. Apparently the question as to what is to be done is not in order. There is nothing to be done but to look, perhaps to feel the smooth surface here and there, and to pre- serve a silence as of listening to a voice where no voice speaks. ^ 7 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART In other rooms are more standing and sitting forms. One leans against a pillar, another holds her drapery, one glances here, another there. Their lines are subtly varied, and the figures diflPer in being more or less free-standing from their background. But all of them are quite simple, and wholly un- concerned with us or with each other. The titles on their marble bases read something like this : " Youth carrying calf," " Statue of a woman," " Athena," " Priestess," " Youth leading sacrificial cows," "Man with musical instrument," " Nike binding her sandal," " Seated goddess." There are warriors, too, and men on horseback. There are combats with animals and with gods. But most of the figures are doing nothing, or, when an action is introduced, it is of a nature whose triviality one would seemingly ^ resent. We do not consider it the most sig- nificant act in the world to ride on a horse. 8 SCULPTURE Why make a stone image eternally exploit- ing that act? It has never seemed momen- tous to handle a necklace, to lean on a spear, to hold drapery, to watch a lizard, to finger a reed ; but as if even these vague pursuits were too arduous, the actors perform them ^ with serene indifference, and by far the greater number make no pretence to occu- pation, but stand without apology and with- out concern. y Even the animals have caught this disre- gard of busy-ness. Many of them are repre- sented in motion as the human athletes had been, but, as with them, the motion is suc- cessful, the muscular adaptation is secure. There is in every case an easy certainty as to the outcome, which makes the movement, however transitory, as stable as the pedestal beneath it. The questions arise. Why these acres of stone ? Why this monotony of sub- ject, gods, men, and animals at rest or in 9 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART /" ever-repeated action ? Where is the dramatic interest to be found in such successful move- ment, such calm joy and such stable grief? Is not the only excuse for these stones' ex- istence, that they represent life, and yet could we tolerate such passionless society or such meaningless pursuits ? We are asking these questions because we are here to question and not at all be- cause we have felt incongruities in what we have seen. The trivial, the unimportant has affected us like grandeur. The lack of occu- pation in these figures abashes us as no re- proof for inaction has ever done, and our separate restless efforts to understand, to in- vestigate, to be well informed — all these praiseworthy anxieties lose their customary respectable footing, and take on a reversed color of contempt. Our activity becomes shamefaced before an idle boy in stone who N^vplays with an apple ! 10 SCULPTURE Our point of view must not be confused with that of the historian of art, who informs us that all these actions were significant when the statues were chiseled. It, of course, is/ true that these seemingly unoccupied maid- ens held a votive offering in their hands, and by their presence before the temple reminded every beholder of the donor's piety. The athletic figures commemorated the Olympic triumphs, than which nothing could have a more serious meaning to a Greek mind. The pediment groups represented the most stir- ring combats in the Greek mythology, and those dignified figures on the Parthenon frieze were in the Pan-Athenaic procession which of all things stood for the glory and the culture of a city dedicated to Athena. The historian would then say, " If these actions seem trivial to a modern spectator, he has simply failed to understand them." It is undoubtedly true that the Greek II THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART sculptor expressed in his art the most im- portant and profound ideas of his national genius. But all our observations neverthe- less remain as true as before. Even the most tragic, the gayest, the most significant thoughts and acts of life were to the Greek artist tempered and made subject to the re- straint of things as they are. He did not strive beyond bounds, but, as has so often been said, he chose rather to glorify his lim- its ; and because this is also the spirit of sculpture, and because thereby this universal Greek spirit and this particular art have the same essential ideal, the sculpture of the y Greeks was their especial glory. All that Greek artists did was good in this respect because, to a certain degree, this doctrine of restraint is the law of all art and of all life. It is not, however, with the other arts the absolute requirement that it is with sculp- . ture. Therefore, although Greek architecture 12 SCULPTURE is great, we can hardly say that it is un- equaled. Greek painting — what we know of it — is superb, but we can hardly say that later men have not done as much. Though Greek literature is unique in its beauty, there have been literary Titans who broke its rules and followed other models. But Greek sculpr ^ ture is not only unsurpassed : it is unequaled. For the world of art, sculpture is synonymous with Greek sculpture — and why ? Because the simple dignity, the detachment, the es- sential preeminence of mere living lines and movements, whereas it may not be all of other arts, is the very kernel of sculpture. To the modern art-lover, therefore, it is^^ absolutely non-essential whether these fig- ures were at one time religious, political, or commemorative — or, indeed, whether they signified anything whatever. We have lost, nothing from the sculpture of the Greeks by embracing a different creed. Far from 13 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART enjoying their sculpture less than they, per- haps we enjoy it more ! If our admiration of their work is so robust, with no admixture of solemnity from the religious motives of the sculptors, we must lay aside their mo- tives as non-essential to the spirit of the work. In the same way that a statement of the evolutionary importance of the scents of flowers does not explain their appeal, so an historic account of the social and religious importance of Greek sculpture is not in the least an analysis of its essence. We shall agree, I think, that it is not in point to call a uniform experience accidental. That which is inevitably present, as well as the inevitably absent in all good examples of a given art, must be regarded as the ex- pression of some law, some deep demand, however unconscious were the artists of their obedience to it. We must begin, then, with the most incontestable uniformity we have 14 SCULPTURE noted in the sculpture gallery, and that will be the actual material from which the statues have been fashioned. We find in any artistic expression that \ some idea must be presented in material form -i« to the senses. Both are essential, the idea and the substance in which it lives. There must be a harmony of the two, and in no art is it so easy to separate them — to comprehend our material, to name our idea — as it is in sculpture. We have found that sculpture expresses itself in ston e and bronze. These ^ two materials have been selected from all the possible substances which would have been much easier to work, and while exceptions in the way of wood, terra-cotta, and faience '^ come at once to mind, they are in a certain sense a class by themselves, which indicates that they have never been quite admitted into the family of sculpture in the fullest sense of the term. We have records also of 15 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART statues in gold and ivory, though none re- main to testify of their excellence. Never- theless as we examine one famous gallery after another, or study sculpture in the orig- inal setting where that is possible, it is plain that porous stone, marble, granite, basalt, and bronze, either plain or gilded, are the materials to which sculpture has consecrated itself, more than to any others. We can- not call this accident, nor yet convention, since it has survived art periods of the great- est originality. Nor can we call it wholly a practical matter. Statues that must endure the assaults of wind and rain required un- doubtedly a durable material. But art forms as well as other matters adapt themselves to a situation, and why should a statue erected to stand within a temple or protected shrine be made as stoutly as if it were exposed to the winds of heaven ? Many statues of an- tiquity, and perhaps the greater number of i6 SCULPTURE sculptures to-day, face the necessity of with- standing the weather as little as do pictures or books. We demand a certain amount of durability in anything, but our pictures are not painted to defy the rain ; why should we ask of the sculptor that his material be hard and difficult to cut, for the sake of a dura- bility that will never be put to the test ? It must be borne in mind that we are not presuming to say what were the conscious motives of different sculptors in using stone for their material. Artists, as a rule, are un- conscious in proportion as they are success- ful, and their motives may have been, even to themselves, apparently guided by conven- tion and practical considerations of all kinds. We often think that we are doing a thing for one reason, when to a dispassionate ob- server it is quite evident that we are doing it for another. So it is not the artist's task to formulate why he does this or that. His 17 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART results may often be happy accidents. But it is not as presumptuous as it may seem at first, for one interested in the philosophy of art to point out what were the real under- lying reasons for an aesthetic choice, inde- pendently of the artist's careless account of himself We are not, therefore, in the least assuming that we know the reason which Phidias, Praxiteles, and Michael Angelo gave to themselves for using the sculptural material that they did. If they say, or if any one says, that they did it merely from acci- dent or convention or what you will, we can only say, as we do to any other incor- rect introspection from one unused to psy- chological analysis, " We know better ! To dissect mental states is our business, not yours, and the account of an artist's mind as it reveals itself in his work, which is his life, is far more accurate than an introspection, in which he is not trained and but scantily i8 SCULPTURE interested." Towering geniuses in sculpture would not have followed a convention in ma- terial, when its reason for being was gone. That is not their way. If with other wide variations in style, great sculptors have kept to a constant uniformity in material, even though they have protested that it was quite accidental, it is obvious that there is an in- herent harmony between their ideas and that material. If they cannot detect such a con- scious demand, they are simply poor psy- chologists. No doubt much of the poverty of aesthetic research arises from the fact that psychol- ogists and philosophers attempt to theorize in an art field where they have no appreci- ation. But that is only half the story. The other difficulty is that artists and art-lovers, who have the appreciation, attempt introspec- tion when they are not trained. How natural, then, that misapprehension should arise I 19 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART Our demand for stone or metal, aside from their inherent beauty, is not therefore merely because of a practical advantage, however conspicuous that advantage may be in out- door sculpture. We must make, nevertheless, a very careful distinction between being dur- / able, and looking durable. Undoubtedly the suggestion of permanence which stone car- ries with it is a very important part of the sculptural idea. This would be as potent a V factor in indoor as in outdoor sculpture. Is it not true that the idea of ageless perma- nence still breathes from a battered Victory in stone, even when practical durability has obviously been found wanting ? Furthermore, some critics have suggested that just the difficulty in cutting gives the abiding charm to sculpture. We scorn the easy victory over wax or clay, and only honor a work, the enormous difficulty of which has been overcome in conflict with a resisting 20 SCULPTURE medium. This supposition stands the test of reason even less than the other. A diffi- cult technic is noble just so long as it is nec- essary for a result, but exploited for its own sake, it is trivial. A painter who uses incon- venient brushes from choice ; a piano player who exhibits extraordinary muscular control in playing all his music with crossed hands, excites our laughter. A sculptor who chose a difficult material to show off his chiseling powers, when a softer or lighter one would serve his purpose as well, would merit the astonished interest which we give to a trick- ster, but not to an artist. Even the sugges- tion that the cost of rare stones excites our admiration falls to the ground when we re- member that the rarer colored marbles have not been chosen for the finest sculpture. The more beautiful the stone in itself, the greater delight it affords us as stone, but even a duller stone is no less sculpture, 21 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART I am Inclined to think that the quality of stone which we are all the time unconsciously demanding is not so much its durability, cer- tainly not its difficulty in manipulation or its cost, but above all things its weight, and connected with this — its size. If the statue has too fragile a surface, it is inconvenient ; if it cannot stand the weather, it must be brought indoors ; if the stone is dull granite, instead of translucent marble, it is not so beautiful ; if it is of a softer sandstone, the chiseler cannot be so subtle ; if it is of bronze, the technic of construction is a different one. But if it dwindles in size sufficiently, and thereby in weight, it may still be beautiful, but it is not sculpture. It is a cameo, a coin, a gem, a carving, a lovely object still ; but it is sculpture, strictly speaking, no longer. ^Size and weight are so bound up in each other that it is difficult to determine which is the more fundamental of the two. If the 22 SCULPTURE statue were of required size, but of some material so light that no feeling of solidity accompanied it, we should call it a poor se- lection of material, and hence poor sculpture. Even though wooden statues show a high degree of beauty, and certainly have a greater ease of manipulation, they have never ex- pressed the sculptural ideal par excellence. Is not this the reason ? However permanent they may be from their sheltered location, they never look entirely so ; and however great their subject-matter, the pressure of their lesser weight does not carry so profound a message. On the other hand, as a marble or a bronze dwindles in size, it does not lose its beauty, but its classification. It may be beautiful still, but in the fullest sense of the term it is not a statue. Thus we do not call coins and cameos, statuettes and figurines, sculpture, without some modification in the term. By the very diminutive endings of 23 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART the words, we imply a variation from a larger standard. How large or how small is a different question. Just as Aristotle said of tragedy, that it must be an action "of a certain magnitude," so we may say of sculp- ture, that other things being equal, a certain size limit is implied. Life-size is not required, for the figures of the Parthenon frieze, the Orpheus relief, and the Mourning Athena are far smaller than that. It seems, however, as if reliefs could be smaller than free-stand- ing statues, and still remain sculpturesque. The stone or metal background of a relief gives the figures their own scale, and lessens the likelihood of comparing their size with that of neighboring objects. In addition to that, the background brings with it its weight ; and I believe that we have not an- alyzed the experience correctly if we leave out the appeal of that quiet, heavy slab of substance, apparently so ignored. Hangings 24 SCULPTURE of silk or velvet behind a free-standing statue also serve to throw the figures into relief, but they do not tell the same story. Figures of the same size as those in the Parthenon frieze, against any but their own background, would be a different matter. Thus even the tiny reliefs of coins gain size from their metal grounds, and do not so speak of smallness as do free-standing figures which are even larger. We cannot definitely set a limit for size ; and, moreover, at this point we may again come into difliculties with the archaeologist. Sculpture is always governed by the same laws, no matter what its size. That which the Greeks expressed in colossal statues, they carved upon their gems. Their athletes were of the same type in marble larger than life, and in bronze three inches high. Here again our critic is perfectly right. The point of difference lies only in what we are to 25 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART call sculpture. We are analyzing what we consider to be the quintessence of the art, not what was intended to be such. In the same fashion, when we use the term " art " in general, we mean the best, the most widely accepted forms of every type, not those forms which in one way or another have failed to be the best. Now that the Greeks did not always adapt their ideas to the absolute size of the object is true, but it is their weakness and not their strength. The little gold Nik^ driving a chariot, which is in the Boston Art Museum, happens to be an ear-ring. Multiply it a thousand times, and modify it in no other fashion, and it would decorate appropriately a monumental arch. In fact it would decorate an arch much more satisfactorily than it would an ear ; and because its idea is not suited to its size, it is not the best. The tiny reliefs, the gems, the coins that are most successful, are not 26 SCULPTURE those where the same idea is expressed in the same fashion as in the larger type. That any form can be forced into any size is true ; but it were better not. Our point is, \ then, simply that the sculptural size, the size that can express anything that any sculpture can, must be at least approxi- mately twelve or fourteen inches high. Be- low this, if the subject is modified, the beauty and excellence may be as overwhelming, but it is not in its strictest sense a piece of sculpture. Or if the same idea is forced intoy^ the size, it is not so good, and hence, from our definition, not sculpture as the finest art. All sizes may have developed together. Our interest is not, however, in what they were, or might have been, but in what they are. The tiny in sculpture strikes no sculp- tural note impossible to larger work. Its message is as clear, but it is diflPerent. We ordinarily take this so much for granted 27 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART that perhaps it has never occurred to us that it is simply the change in size which makes us call a relief a cameo ; or a statue, a carv- ing ; and which makes our ideal demand so different. All are strictly carvings, and while a change of size is likely to mean a change to a more delicate material as well, it is the difference in size which really makes the difference in classification, and the differ- ence in weight which changes our attitude from the more sculptural to that befitting the so-called minor arts. If a decrease in size so changes the sculptor's appeal, what about increase? Could a statue become so large that it would be a statue no longer? If not a statue, what would it be ? Here we can only theorize, since even the colossal statues known to art are not so large that they have lost their sculpturesque quality. One can always reduce size by distance, so that a smaller image may be cast upon the 28 SCULPTURE retina; and whereas an architectural char- acter would presumably be present in a monumental statue, the presence of weight is so essential to the material expression of sculpture that additions do not trifle with its effect as does decrease. A certain size and solidity, then, must be immediately and ob- viously presented to us in the material of the essentially sculpturesque; and the two abstract terms recall to us certain definitions of substance itself. Philosophers and scien- tists have always been trying to define what we mean by " substance." What, if any- thing, is the outer world finally composed of in itself, aside from the modifications which it appears to undergo in relation to our sense organs ? The ancient and mediaeval thinkers made a distinction between the qualities which inhere in substance, as op- posed to the qualities which it seems to have by virtue of its action on our sense organs. 29 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART Thus color, taste, smell, sound, and tempera- ture all depend on the state of our own nerv- ous system. To the color-blind, the grass is gray ; to the fever patient, the air is hot ; to the dry tongue, there is no taste — and so these sensations are illusory, and represent only the secondary qualities of substance. ^ ^ But the primary qualities — shape, size, and solidity — were distinguished from these as being more intimately bound up in the nature of substance itself. It was argued that, however relative a matter taste and color, for instance, might be, size and weight were so a part of matter itself that they be- longed in a peculiar fashion to the structure of substance as such. Thus from the Greek Democritus, who deprived atoms of any qualities but size and weight, to the later scientific theorizers, who associated atoms with no characteristic but that of weight, there has been a greater intimacy of connec- 30 SCULPTURE tion in thought between the idea of matter and the primary qualities than between it and those termed secondary, and size and weight have been regarded as the essentials to any concepts of matter. Modern scien- tific theory goes beyond this, and reduces atoms to something more elemental, and modern psychology will not admit that per- ceptions of weight and size are different in any peculiar sense from the other sense perceptions. But be that as it may, the only point in which we are interested now is that in the imagination, the customary concepts of things as they occur in any mind, these so- called primary qualities have a different men- tal coloring to us than do other perceptions. So an art, which shows its material aspect so obviously, the material substance of which we can recognize so easily, we should expect to awaken in us a greater sensitiveness to just those characteristics of substance, which 31 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART for whatever reason have been most inti- mately bound up with our very conception of it. It will be no surprise to find that wide variations in volume, and hence in weight, make more difference to us in our strictly (kl sculpturesque feeling than the presence or b ) absence of color, smooth or unfinished sur- C face, greater or less detachment from the background, or even more or less fidelity to /^realism in the form represented. Of course, marble sculpture, even when supposedly \ white, appeals to us more or less by color. It is a cream white, or a veined white, or a translucent white; or, in the case of other stones and metals, it may be gray, green, brown, red, or almost any shade in plain colors or varied tints intermixed. There is evidence that the Greek sculptors of the early and even the classic period went be- yond this in often painting their marble in broad saturated colors. Whatever the color 32 SCULPTURE variation, nevertheless, however we like or dislike these changes, sculpture stays sculp- ture for us, in a way it does not when wide variations are made in size. Green bronze and gold trimmings make a statue no more and no less than the whitest or blackest of marble. But how great a difference in our\ point of view toward a colossal Apollo and a figure two inches high, however similar the color may be, and however the outline and beauty of both may approach each other ! As we have already said in this connection, it is not a question of difference in beauty, , but in classification. So much, then, for the material in which our sculptural idea must find expression. Is there also a limitation in the sculptural ideas that can be expressed, or can any idea find appropriate exploitation in the materials we have discovered to be the essential medium ? The statues we have studied in our tour of 33 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART the gallery have been almost exclusively representations of human and animal forms. Conspicuously infrequent have been figures of the dead, and nowhere have we found, as we find, for instance, in painting, isolated subjects from still life. In reliefs, especially low reliefs which approach drawing, we have seen representation of inanimate things in the background. But as the relief becomes higher, they disappear, and in free-standing statues they have practically ceased to exist in any other capacity than as ornament or support for the living figures. Inanimate things as statues by themselves we have not found at all. Thus we have no free-standing statue of a tree or of a flower by itself, of a hillside or of a seashore. There are no interi- ors in the round, with rich furniture or house- hold objects, which make such charming sub- jects for painting or poetry. And yet, why could not sculpture, which has of all the arts 34 SCULPTURE a tangible medium in which to work, express material things more suitably than other arts, where the translation must be more complete ? Here, of course, we observe that a stone chair is a chair and not the statue of a chair, no matter how much the grain of another sub- stance, like wood, be imitated. A statue of a \ table is a table ; a statue of a vase is a vase — and, therefore, so far as this kind of work is concerned, we have no representation of another idea, but another construction of the subject itself. Its art value must then depend on the beauty of its decoration and its pro- portion — not at all on the faithfulness with which it has caught the spirit of its model. This, however, does not dispose of flowers, fruit, and vegetables as sculptural subjects. A » statue of a palm tree is no more a tree than is a painting of one, and yet we have never seen such a thing. In sculptural relief we see the loveliest fruit and flower decoration possible. 35 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART The relief may even be very high, in the decoration of capitals of columns and other architectural work. But where a painter goes beyond this, and devotes a complete art work to a vase of flowers, or to a table covered with still-life objects, we feel that such a sculp- tural free-standing group would be a mon- strosity — so much so in fact that it has never crossed a sculptor's mind to try it ! It cannot be all a matter of absence of color in sculpture which makes this difference, for nothing need have prevented artists from coloring such still-life studies. But appar- ently the subject-matter of any piece of in- dependent sculpture must be a living form, or one strongly suggesting the life that has just left it ; and/ar from being more adapted to express the material side of nature because of its heavy material, it more than any art must express life^ or the idea as far as possi- ble removed from stone. 36 SCULPTURE Let a poet or a musician, who deals in a more spiritual medium, takefor his subject, if he will, a tree, a mountain, or a crumbling wall. But the sculptor who is handling a block of stone must fashion from it a living and breathing form. Art is a translation of an idea into a substance, and just in so far as the substance is a heavy one, the idea must be vital enough to vivify it throughout its mass. But here one more restriction is necessary>s^ Shall we argue from this that if living forms must animate our stone, they must be as liv- ing as possible ? Shall they always dance and sing, shall their expression be of the liveliest, and their draperies of the lightest, to counter- act the material out of which they are strug- gling ? Here our taste and our observation rebel. The greatest statues are quiet. The drapery, if there is such, falls as a rule in dignified folds. No attempt is made to force 37 \ THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART the stone to be anything but stone — or, in other words, the heavy substance, although it is vivified, is not contradicted. The idea, when well chosen, exhibits just enough of liveliness to spiritualize its mass, without quarreling with it. We are impressed with the fact that Sculp- ture is more than any other art the expres- sion of restraint. It must avoid this and that material, and be strict as to the size which it chooses for its idea. It cannot represent this inanimate subject nor that too brisk idea — but above all, as it is the most classic art, it must look carefully to the most perfect harmony of idea with subject, and show ex- traordinary strictness in the things it does not do. What, then, are the ideas which are suit- able for Sculpture, after finding so many that are not? Are we not forced to an un- bearable monotony, if our subjects must be 38 SCULPTURE chosen from the ranks of living forms, at ease with themselves ? In a picture gallery, were subject after subject to show as little variation as is indicated in a sculpture cata- logue, we should rebel. But here, strangely enough, we do not rebel in the least, and since the ordinary monotonies do not ob- tain, we shall be forced to investigate the meaning of the word. We call any group of people monotonous when each member of the company talks, dresses, and acts like every other. We are fatigued in any circle where the opinions, the habits, and the standards of all its members are a foregone conclusion, and we sigh for a difference, — for a shock if necessary, — to reinforce our- selves with the variety of living. With all this, there exist certain constant similari- ties, any trifling with which gives an abnor- mality and not a gratifying change. We do not complain, as did Humpty Dumpty in 39 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART "Through the Looking Glass," that more people have not been made distinctive by having two eyes on the same side of their nose! We do not ask that social monotony be varied by walking on hands instead of feet, or painting our faces the color of jade. We demand individual variation within a constancy of type. Therefore it is tiresome to reiterate the same remarks, but not to consort always with vertebrates; because conversation is an individual matter and should be varied, and backbones are typical matters and should be as uniformly regular as possible. Now, it is wholly a matter of the point of view whether you fasten your attention on the individual or on the typical aspect of any matter. Both sides of the ques- tion must be always present to a certain ex- tent, but the emphasis is different. That is, every art object is an individual existence, no matter how typical in conception ; and 40 SCULPTURE just as truly all art which is truly great points beyond the fleeting individual emotion to the type of which it is a part. Nevertheless the emphasis varies greatly, and sculpture, in its essence, is the art expressive of typi- cal values. After all that we have said that it does not do, at last we affirm positively that which it does. The figures of sculpture are not engaged in so-called significant ac- tions, because those are individual matters. Your traveling, or singing, or banking, or teaching are the pursuits which represent the more important aspects of life to you as individuals. But the statues, as we noticed at the beginning, are standing, sitting, leaning, watching, holding, playing, living, or per- haps dying, in a fashion as far as possible removed from individual application, but which expresses, if we catch its message, the absolute dignity of life as such. Man him- self is more than anything he does. Our 41 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART separate actions are, after all, two thirds fussiness, and the superb dignity of these sculptured maidens who clasp a belt or bind a sandal, the repose of those serene athletes who stand or bend so easily, and who refuse to commit themselves to more, is an eternal proud assertion that life itself, not its pur- suits, is the greatest reality. There is a mag- nificence in this high simplicity which is in some respects more touching than the most individually impassioned lyric. If we apolo- gize for anything, let it be for our lacks or abnormalities, not for the splendid vital postures and movements which unite us with the race. We are both individuals and mem- bers of a type — the emphasis is ours to make, and thus has sculpture chosen. Could any material so express our bond with nature and with each other as blocks of the earth from which we sprung? All that we have said does not in the least 42 SCULPTURE prevent sculpture from being an art in which portraiture is possible, and portraiture of the highest order. But just as any great portrait, in whatever material, gives through the individual features the universal type of which it is the expression, so sculpture does it even more. There is, in the very weight of its stone, a suggestion of the pressure of that human family for which one man has been chosen to be the symbol. One must\ come away from any sculptural display with a sense of the magnificence of the human heritage strong upon him, and it is the nicely adjusted harmony of the idea with the substance which brings this result to pass. / We cannot have failed to notice in our tour through the gallery of sculpture that a head, a torso, a bit of decoration even, is treated with a curious respect. In fact, sculp- ture, in spite of the apparent durability of material, is likely to be, more than any other 43 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART art, in a fragmentary condition. We are little disturbed, or at least not too much shocked, by the battered condition of a large part of classic sculpture, to find in it a splendid beauty notwithstanding. Is there no limit to the ex- pressiveness of a stone ? A man's head, his foot, his trunk are but mutilated parts of his whole body ; but a head in sculpture is not a mutilation, but a complete thing. In coins, a head more often than not is chosen as com- plete design, and evokes no impression of fragmentariness. Moreover, although other isolated parts of the body are seldom chosen for separate treatment, if time and hard us- age have unhappily destroyed the rest of the figure, we can treat such a fragment as if it were a whole. We forget the absence of the legs of the Hermes, and of the heads of the figures on the Parthenon pediment. We re- gret their loss, as we should regret the loss of any great art work, but their absence does 44 SCULPTURE not vitiate the appeal of what remains. Any part of the body which can enough express the meaning of the whole to give a fair idea of what the rest would be, can be called a sufficiently complete expression of a living value to stand as an art work on its own merits. Thus the face without the nose, or without the cranium ; the torso without the limbs, or the head without the torso, can all express a complete living value, which a nose without a face or an arm without a hand can- not do. Without a sufficient admixture of life, and living lines in the material, the stone has turned to stone again. Is there any possibility of summarizing this discussion? We have tried to under- stand a little of the sculptural demand which underlies the matter and the idea of this art, which represents as perhaps no other does an age-long human experience. No defini- tion can expound its essence, and no for- 45 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART mula can bind it. Yet for the sake of a clear, even if imperfect parting concept, let us try- to gather up the loose ends and epitomize our results. We have limited the substance in which sculpture may fittingly be ex- pressed; we have limited the ideas, the action, the emotion which is fitting to the substance, and we have pointed out the bond, and the gulf, by which sculpture is respectively united with and separated from the nature which is her model. Let us conclude then by a formulation of our results : — Sculpture is the representation of a certain magnitude, in stone or other heavy material, of a complete expression of a living form ; where the idea harmonizes with the material, by expressing no action or passion that is uncontrolled, but where, through a simple and universal bodily attitude, the grandeur of the life of the type is represented. II ' THE MINOR ARTS II THE MINOR ARTS Perhaps there is no more paradoxical situ- ation in the vocabulary of art than this : that a public which can passionately admire the minor arts cannot give them a better name ! To label them as " minor " calls forth a pro- test from those who find in this field of art a nearer approach to perfection than in any other. " Industrial " art is surely a misno- mer, for many objects which fall within this classification are no more industrially useful than others which enjoy unquestioned rank among the fine arts. " Decorative " art is hardly more satisfactory, since so much painting and sculpture of the best periods is decorative. The nomenclature is certainly faulty, and 49 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART yet there is, I believe, a certain justification for the name we have chosen as our title, against which we cannot rebel if we under- stand It fully. What are the minor arts ? We find under this heading such diverse products as wood- carving and terra-cottas, coins and mosaics, glass- and metal-work, carved ivory and jewelry, bookbinding, pottery and textiles, and the question naturally arises, " What is there in common among such a variety of materials and forms ? " Surely a coin bears no more resemblance to an embroidered scarf or a carved desk than does a picture to a statue — not so much, in fact; and yet, ac- cording to some broad distinction, they are all grouped together. To limit the field of sculpture is comparatively easy, since there is an almost complete uniformity in the ma- terials of stone and metal. But in the minor arts obviously no one substance can be the 50 THE MINOR ARTS binding tie between products of brass and of leather, clay and silk ; so" we must look for some kinship in the ideas represented. Here again our search is unrewarded, for now it is a Christ in ivory, and now a lily- like bowl in glass ; here a bull delicately chased on a gold cup, and there a palmette on a shawl. We find an impartial interest in natural and geometric forms, which is no more exclusively common to this group of arts than it is to painting or sculpture. In fact the satisfaction of the minor artist (since we must use the term) in his work is appar- ently shared by the painter, for the latter delights in painting the rich objects which the former has already fashioned. Is it not a paradox to label as " lesser " the artist who produces the brocades and gold ornament, the furniture and gems, with which the painter decks his model, and which he is at so much pains to reproduce ? 51 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART However this may be, we must apparently look beyond conformity in material, or in the objects chosen for representation, for a satisfactory reason why all these diverse beautiful objects should be thought of as re- lated. We can detect no common demand of color, size, or weight, for these arts range from the tiny to the massive, with every conceivable variety of surface, solidity, form, and finish, according to the material of which they are made and the place they are / to fill. The reason sometimes given for their common grouping is that they are, despite their wide difference, alike in the respect that they serve a practical purpose. They are subservient to use, and because of this harnessing to the ordinary pursuits of life, they cannot be placed in the proud circle of the arts which exist for their own sake, aside from practical issues. While there is undoubtedly a large measure of 52 THE MINOR ARTS truth in this distinction, it would seem as if we were not wholly conscious of a tendency to unfairness in our comparisons. We are likely to put side by side in our imaginations the finest of painting or sculpture with the mediocre in the industrial arts, where the subserviency of beauty to use, in the latter, is unduly obvious. Let us rather compare the best of Greek sculpture with the best Greek coins and vases; the best Italian painting with finest jewelry and tapestries of the period, and at once the distinction loses its obvious character. It is true that the vases were made for wine, and the coins for currency, but so, on the other hand, were the paintings made to decorate walls, and many of the statues were for votive offer- ings. Now, neither statues, vases, nor coins perform their function, but they all retain their importance. When they stand in the/ trying isolation of an art gallery, the minor 53 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART arts tell their story articulately with no help from a former industrial value. It is un- ' doubtedly true that the frescoes upon the wall are every bit as useful to their owner as are the crown jewels to the king, when at long intervals he places them upon his head. One art product decorates one thing, and one another; why then charge the second with an industrial purpose, when we do not so charge the first ? Here it is possible to make a distinction. Granted that any art ob- ject may be used for some practical purpose if it is forced to be so used ; the minor arts are deliberately fashioned with such a purpose in view, and any divorcement from their in- tended function is wholly artificial. The re- moval of the industrial art object to an art gallery amounts only, we might say, to an admission that we are too busy or too poor to afford such things for daily handling. On the other hand, there is no such artificiality 54 THE MINOR ARTS in the painting wrenched from the wall it was made to decorate. A wall is a wall, no matter where. To decorate it is but a shadow of usefulness in any case. Therefore, the sacrifice in a changed setting in the latter case is a negligible quantity. But the place for coins is in a wallet, or slipping through one's fingers ; the place for glass and pottery is on a well-decked table, with milk and honey glimmering within. If not where they were meant to be, we lose the piquancy of their workmanship, whereas a painting or a statue need be only where it has a good light and a fair approach. It will be admitted, however, that there is a very wide variation in such practical util- ity. Some industrial arts are undoubtedly very useful in gaining a livelihood for others besides the artist who makes them, while others are as vaguely usable as the most disinterested major arts could be. 55 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART Why is the richly ornamented frame of an altar-piece any more ■practical than the painting within ? The frame is needed for the picture, but so is the picture for the frame. Both are lovely objects. Both serve the purpose of decorating a shrine. Both are sufficiently good to retain their merit if transferred to another setting ; and whereas, for other reasons, we are justified in calling the painting as much more important as we like, it would hardly seem that the basis of distinction were practical, industrial useful- ness. Another thing has been very evident in a mere naming of the industrial arts. There is no abstraction in their titles as there has come to be in the so-called fine arts. Instead of " sculpture " and " painting " of somethings with a vagueness as to what, and the still further indefinite character of the terms "literature" and " music,** we have a brisk 56 THE MINOR ARTS concreteness in the material of the art — wood, metal, glass, clay — which indicates at once that here is the centre of our inter- est. The other arts must have material ex- pression no less than these, but they have not considered the material of such para- mount importance that it must be named as the essence of their whole work. Thus a minor artist may be frankly a gem-cutter ; while a sculptor does not perhaps recognize himself at once as a stone-cutter. At any rate, whatever his own fondness for his material, the rest of the world does not call him such, and here we have struck one important note of difference. Vocabulary is after all a sensitive indica- tor of thought — or at least of the absence of it. If minor artists have never separated their work from their material enough even to name the art which they pursue, the chances are that the substance which they 57 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART handle remains a factor in their imagination of supreme importance. A name may be given to their products in terms of the use to which they will be subjected : as, furni- ture or bookbinding; or in terms of the material of which they are made : as, gems, brasses, blown glass, or terra-cotta. But there is apparently no way to indicate such an ab- straction as that of painting and sculpture, where the process and the material have grown together in the connotation of the term; as that of literature, with its reference to deal- ing in " letters "; architecture to building; and music, denoting by its name only an art watched over and inspired by the muses. If the industrial artists had so looked upon their art that the idea or activity which it embodied took rank above the particular material of which it was fashioned, such a point of view would have become crystal- lized in language. 58 THE MINOR ARTS To admit, then, an especial emphasis in"^ thought upon the material which passes through the workman's hands is the first step toward penetrating to the principle in- volved. This in no way indicates inferiority, but simply a diflFerence in the manner of approach. All artists must feel the utmost sensitiveness to the subtle appeal of the substance which they handle, and to feel it more acutely is of itself no indication of a materialistic mind, but rather of more delicate susceptibility. It seems as if the nations that took sub- stance more seriously were rewarded by a skill in its invention and manipulation, that we of the Occident, who feel more sharply the cleavage between mind and matter, spirit and body, could never have. A philosophy, for instance, with a settled conviction that God is in everything, for " when me they fly, I am the wings," does not share in our dis- 59 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART tinction between creator and created things. Whether causally connected with this or not, the inventions of the East display a genius for detecting the possibiHties of mere matter which we do not share. Take, for instance, textiles, where the idea represented is per- haps as difficult to separate from the material as in any of the industrial arts. There may be pictorial representation in the weaving, or there may be simply the dumb beauty of texture and surface and color, but by their very names our more beautiful textiles are branded with their Eastern origin : Pongee and rajah, crepes and cashmeres, Persian carpets, India mulls, scarfs from Egypt, and chuddahs from India. What invention in textiles has the Western world, with its greater development in literature and music, to offer in comparison ? It cannot invent a beautiful substance because it does not understand it, and in its heart despises even 60 THE MINOR ARTS while it admires. A man's or a nation's phi- losophy is the most important thing about them, and until both honor substance, and see the idea of material power behind its actuality, neither man nor nation will ever become preeminent in the minor arts. ^^ So much, then, for the materials of these arts — as wide a range as there are beautiful substances to be found or fashioned. What is the artist to do with his material when he finds it? He must not only exploit its own beauties, but, as in the other arts, he must there embody some idea which by its harmony with the substance lives in it in a way that makes all observers feel that here is its inevitable setting. If we look through the industrial arts, we find the range of ideas expressed in them as wide almost as the materials. Moreover, as the list of subjects indicates, there is a strong suggestion with each of 6i THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART these art objects that something is to be done with it. It may be as distinctly useful an action as clothing the person, or as re- motely practical as slipping a ring on the finger, or hanging a rug on the wall. But its position is always relative. To be seen to the best advantage, there is an appropriate- ness about its being seen in one place rather than another ; on a table or in a window, around the neck or on the floor ; and despite the fact that good industrial art can stand alone, only in the place for which it was designed can we get its full charm. Perhaps nothing will illustrate so clearly this range of subject-matter as to contrast it with the subjects common to sculpture. There we find man in his essential aspects, not man in his diverse activities ; man in his universal nature which we all share, not in his occupations in which no two of us are alike. 62 THE MINOR ARTS Here seemingly we have just the reverse. We are not now interested in what man is, so much as in the innumerable things which he does ; the things he handles, and reads, and eats from, and sits upon, and looks out of, and kneels upon, and laughs at, and hunts with, and in which he arrays himself, his family and his house. Just what sculpture never does, the minor arts do. They embody the ideas of man's infinite activities. They illustrate for us the habits of a people as nothing else could / possibly do. But are we not here involved in a contra- diction ? We decided earlier in our discussion that it was not in point to give as the distin- guishing mark of the minor arts that they were practically useful, for many of them are not so. Here, on the other hand, we seem to be saying that it is their embodiment of the idea of man's activities that gives them 63 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART / their distinctive classification. Is it not the same thing? If these arts mirror an artist's attention as centred upon human activities, and if he suggests them in art forms which may enable a man to live them out, is not that the same thing as to call them practically \^ useful? Here, however, an important distinction must be made. We have granted already that the minor arts bear a special relation to the place they were intended to occupy. They demand, by their very form, that the activity which they suggest be carried out. But that is very dif- ferent from practical usefulness. That a stained-glass window cries out to have the light shine through its vivid panes ; that a heavy ring implores to be handled ; and that a rich shawl sighs for its breadth to be gath- ered into folds and its colors reflected on Itself, seems as far removed from bread-and- 64 THE MINOR ARTS butter pursuits as for a poem to prefer articu- lation by a good voice to distortion by a cracked one. What do we mean by usefulness when we^ watch the color of tea in a porcelain cup or fondle a leathern volume with illuminated pages? If all we cared to do was to drink the tea or look out of the window or read the book, then why go to the trouble of making the porcelain, the glass, and the leather beautiful? To accomplish an action and get through with it is all that most of us care for, and the arts of our country show it. In reality the lovely binding embodies the idea of reading, the cup is the quintessence of tea- drinking, the window stands for the spirit of " windowness " — aside from the fact of whether we wish to use it to Improve the ventilation or not. Paradoxical as it may sound, these arts, 6s THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART instead of standing for practical issues, stand for exactly the reverse 1 This beautification of the daily tools of living is not a practical matter, practical in the sense of ministering thereby to our bodily life, but it is a purely ideal one. In so far as the ordinary tools are lovely, we for ever so slight an instant forget to use them, and look at them instead. We are not content that a really beautiful neck- lace be always unseen by ourselves upon our own necks, but we let it slip through our fingers endlessly to watch the lights therein V — and then omit to wear it. Instead of thumping impatiently on the wrought bronze knocker for an answer, we are beguiled by its beauty into forgetting our errand. A carven chair demands at least another chair for one to sit in while he gazes at the rich- ness of the first, and who does not pause before stepping upon a beautiful rug and hesitate to subject it to so mean a purpose? 66 THE MINOR ARTS For practical drinking, give us a stout mug that will not break, and that will keep its heat or cold, not a delicate shell that brooks no rough treatment and whose transparency- distracts our thirst. For practical currency- give us mediocre bits of metal, where our satisfaction in the handling is wholly relative to the mint value, and whose beauty of de- sign will never tempt us to expose it when it is not in use. Surely to keep out the light, there are many materials more substantial than lace or embroidery, and who can look in or out of a stained-glass window ? It is obvious that these objects are far from practical in the sense of making more successful the pursuits to which they are dedicated. Human attention is a rigorously limited affair, and when it is directed to the graving on a knife or fork, it cannot so de- vote itself to wielding them. When it is lost in the contemplation of the enamel on a 67 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART buckle, the clasp remains unfastened, and wheels of industry go round again only when the representative idea of buckling and eat- ing and sitting at a table has been forgotten, and the actual operation has begun. ^/ Thus it is that the minor arts make for a slower, less practical life. They put the brakes on restless transactions which are concerned only with ends to be gained for the advantage of the doer, and by giving him pause as he fingers each tool in the proc- ess, the idealism of the manifold interests ^ of life comes home to him. He forgets the bargain and the hunt, which are after all relative matters and must soon be done again, and instead he loses himself, for ever so short a time, in the idea of the pursuit, its infinite human interest, and therewith the activity becomes not relative but eternal. The materialism of any age begins, not when men are held periodically in the spell of the 68 THE MINOR ARTS grandeur which is typified by their tools, but when they are deluded' into thinking that the tools are nothing, and that some material result of the process is the reason for it all. ^' To regard a dinner as solely a matter of food and the disposing of it is the practical point of view. To look upon the shapes of the dishes and their texture as symbols of the kinds of substance that are placed within, and as indicating the physical laws which govern the way they must be served and eaten, puts an idealistic touch on a necessary occupation and makes acceptable a less redundant repast. With such a range of exquisite materials, and such an abundance of ideas to express, how could it ever happen that these arts were labeled minor ? There is no less skill in making, and no less time required to bring such art objects to perfection. It may take 69 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART longer to build a cathedral or paint a fresco than to fashion a goblet ; but, on the other hand, the goblet may be longer in the mak- ing than a poem or a melody. Art is long in any case, and any attempt to measure the preeminence of an art by such a time-scale would be certain to end in ineffectual dis- tinctions. We cannot say there is less beauty in the minor arts ; indeed, there is often a perfection about a coin or a bit of embroidery that more imposing work, by the very am- bition of its attempt, finds impossible to reveal. f Yet, despite all this, I believe that the distinction between the major and the minor arts is based upon a vital and universal dif- ference in emotional approach, and that it is of this difference that we are inarticulately aware when we pass from one type of art to the other, and vaguely feel that the atmos- phere has changed. I believe that this differ- 70 THE MINOR ARTS ence of attitude is indicated very clearly in the facial expression of a company which passes from the contemplation of painting and sculpture to a collection of gems, tex- tiles, or porcelains. They come from the one elated but serious, chastened somewhat by its grandeur and quiet. To use Aristotle's term there has been a katharsis of the mind through the weight of sublime things, but A as soon as the scene has changed and they are faced with the products of the industrial artist, they shift from an attitude of awe to one of unmixed delight. There is no less respect for the skill of the artist or for the value of his work ; but his message is always joyous, full of abundant life. Such pleasure is contagious. The spec- y; tator literally smiles as he fingers the smooth carving or the sinuous links of a gold chain. Moreover, he longs to handle them, almost^ to play with them — faintly echoing by this 71 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART very desire that pleasure with which the craftsman gave the burnished surface in the beginning, and toyed with his work before \ it left his hands. This pleasure in physical contact with the minor arts is the natural impulse to handle any delightful form, an impulse which in the major arts is only coun- teracted by our reverence for the dignity of the idea conveyed. With the minor arts, on the contrary, our delight is without admixture of awe. Our respect is no less. It may in certain cases be more. But just as the most devoted subject in the realm might feel an impulse to pat the cheek of the royal baby whom he adored, whereas he would only bow before the king, so we may love the minor arts as much as we will and marvel at their perfection, but however we love them, we are not afraid of them ! They speak to us only of joy, and joy unmixed with other emotions cannot 72 THE MINOR ARTS stay our hand. Just here, I believe, is the province of the minor artist and his limita- tion. No art sings so exclusively of happi- / ness and delight in living as does this which deals in the fashioning from exquisite mate- rials the typical tools of the life of humanity. Living, as we do, in a country where the craftsman is never seen at work, we lose sight of this prime factor of his creative impulse. But what could be more cheerful than the shop of an Italian gold or silversmith, a gem- cutter, a wood-carver, or (the economic con- ditions being satisfactory) of a lace-maker? If they in ever so slight a degree have caught the spirit of the real artist, it is their joy which they put into their work. No heavy / brows, such as we have by common consent relegated to the dramatic author, no brim- ming eyes, such as the lyric poet describes so feelingly ; no grasping for intangible visions, none of the melancholy of the Medici 73 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART tombs. But everywhere is a delight in things as they are, an infectious gayety which does not moralize, but catches the light in a thou- sand colors and shapes, and brings a smile to any face which does not hide a soul too abstracted to note its compelling joy. Just here is the abiding charm of the minor arts. ^They ask no questions of fate, and we are asked to face nothing but beauty and vibrant life. And yet, because these arts not only do not express sorrow and struggle, disappoint- ment and agony, but because they cannot ^ we turn from them as from fairies or archangels and say that they are less than men. If the criterion of any art is its perfection in attaining that which it set out to do, these minor arts would not be less, but perhaps would take a higher place than those where the struggle to express the mixed glooms and triumphs of life has left a less finished whole. 74 THE MINOR ARTS But If breadth of possible subject Is our standard, the Industrial arts have chosen the sunny side of existence, and have thereby forfeited their share In the representation of life as a complex of light and shadow. I can-;^ not think of any circumstance which so epit- omizes this spirit of the minor arts as the placing of the bust of Benvenuto Cellini, like a tutelar deity, to crown the arches of the Ponte Vecchio In Florence. Across that bridge stretches on cither hand the line of cheerful little shops filled with gems of vary- ing values, but of uniform brilliancy — from the most sumptuous pearls to the humblest turquoise — and brisk gold- and silversmiths are fashioning jewelry from them with untir- ing joy. Over the bridge, with its constant stream of jewel-seekers, presides the rollick- ing, the sanguine, the truculent, the self- satisfied but beauty-loving Benvenuto, who turned with equal readiness and enthusiasm 75 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART to knifing an adversary or graving the Lord Almighty on a button ! Possibly Benvenuto was not as perfect in his art as he confidently supposed, but at any rate a great eminence was possible for him, and a man of his tem- per was thought worthy of mention as a master craftsman, without that admixture of solemnity which appears in the finer exam- ples of the more serious arts. Could such a man dominate music or poetry or sculpture, even for a period of time, as Cellini has dominated the Italian jewelers and craftsmen for centuries ? As is the master so is the dis- ciple. Contrast Benvenuto's attitude toward life with the bearing of passion tempered with melancholy which devotees of certain fine arts adopt ! However conventional this manner may have become, even a convention springs from some root, and has a certain meaning. If we grant the truth of this observation, 76 THE MINOR ARTS the questions still remain, Why is it true ? What is there in the nature of the industrial arts with their beauty of material, their mani- fold expression of man's interests and their feeling for perfection, which prevents them from being the avenues for the most som- bre, sublime, or prophetic ideas that might inhabit an artist's mind? Perhaps it is not too much to say that the two characteristics of the minor arts which have been emphasized, the unlimited interest in substances and the presentation through these substances of the ideas of man's infinite activities — just those characteristics which are the rich field of the arts in question — are, by the very structure of human nature, their limits. It is the material world which brings sorrow ; it does not alleviate it. What- ever may be the cause of gloom — death, the fear of it, obstructed plans, disease, poverty, solitude, renunciation — all these experiences 11 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART come from the clash of material mechanical laws with spiritual demands. Every one of them means a tyrannical check imposed on a too desirous soul, and why should such a soul fly to more matter, even though it be lovely, when the inner brutality of things is tormenting the artist? The major arts depend also upon mate- rial. They show no less sensitiveness to its beauty or brutality, but they limit their range of material. Moreover, they may oppose to it their idea, so that the whole story — the opposition, the struggle, and the victory of one or the other — may be expressed, and the substance does not remain supreme. Again we ask the same question : " Why cannot the industrial arts do the same?*' Because, as we have found, the ideas rele- gated to these arts are all strongly suggestive of man's activity, and men in grief are not interested in action. 78 THE MINOR ARTS The attitudes of a sorrowful man are not drawing soft garments through his fingers, toying with gems, eating and drinking from gold and crystal, hunting with inlaid mus- kets, or handling rich volumes. Since these activities are absent, his thoughts and the thoughts of the fashioners of these objects are absent too, and in such an atmosphere of sadness, I venture to say that the minor arts would neither be made nor noticed. It is a fact of elementary psychology that joy or agreeable mental states of any kind have a tendency to send the blood to the surface, to quicken the breath, and to in- crease the muscular energy. All these bod- ily changes can be observed in even the slight changes of agreeable stimuli possible in a psychological laboratory. How much more are they marked in the real satisfac- tions of life outside a laboratory ! On the contrary, the disagreeable mental 79 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART states tend to deepen the breath and to de- crease the muscular strength and the dis- position toward expansive movement. Grant- ing this lowering of bodily activity and tone under the influence of unpleasant stimuli, what would be the natural result? Inaction, quiet, contemplation, repression, but never the varied movements which every one of the minor arts suggests. A man in sorrow can sit motionless and get the full force of the greatest of the fine arts without adopting an attitude in oppo- sition to his mood. His sorrow may be alleviated without being contradicted. The same man, on the other hand, can- not sympathize with the industrial arts with- out facing the constant suggestion of human action represented as the supreme interest of life. But material at ease with itself and buoyant activity are antagonistic to his mood, and he turns from them and calls the arts 80 THE MINOR ARTS devoted to them " minor," because in his greatest distress they do not and cannot sympathize. Thus we can fancy the joyful human be- ing as equally delighting in his pictures, his statues, and his jewels, his dance music, his lyric poetry, and his rugs. But his mood changes to despair, and the major arts in- stantly change with him. His sculpture and architecture remind him of the abiding ele- ments of humanity which survive all shocks./ He sees the ravages of similar distress in portraits and crucifixions. His poetry re- sponds to a melancholy note even more quickly than to joy. Not only a poem of sadness, but the same blithe lyric that he read before can change its emphasis by a slower cadence or a different tone, and his dance music can become a dirge if he chooses and be all the more sombre by its contrast with a dead gayety. 8i THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART But how about his jewels, his burnished metals, and his rugs ? They do not lose one brilliant color or reveal one hint of under- / standing of any mood but their own. One cannot dampen their suggested activity. There they are, with no dark past, and ab- solutely contradictory in every suggestion to any mood but joy. If the contemplator feels no obligation to his grief, nothing could divert him so quickly. But if he nurses his sombre view of life, and believes his grief too sacred to relinquish, he ignores these unsympathetic arts until his mood has changed, and calls them " minor " only because they are less in range than his whole self. Ill PAINTING Ill PAINTING If we are to analyze the art of painting by the same methods that we employed in the arts of sculpture and the minor arts, we are embarrassed at the start by an apparent change in the constitution of our subject- matter. We find the measuring-rod which has served us easily is now attempting a task which it cannot so well perform. Our first question is to be as before, " Of what material is. our art constructed?" and we are placed at the threshold of a picture gallery and told to wander through it and to answer the question for ourselves. There are on the walls many canvases and panels in wooden and gilded frames, with paint applied in various manners. Some- 85 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART times we see pictures in colored chalks and again the wall itself is decorated, the plaster itself serving as a ground, or in some cases the canvas is laid upon the plaster. Turning from the material used to the forms which are represented, we can detect no uniformity in subject-matter, for every possible object seems to be represented, from the simplest portrait to the most complex grouping in landscape or interior. The inevitable answer to our first question, *' What is the material medium of the art? " must be, "canvas, paper, paint, oil, chalk." But this answer has a strange sound, as if it were a summary of the materials of the art in only the most formal sense. To say that stone and bronze are the materials of sculp- ture, that gold and jewels are the substances of the jeweler's art comes as no shock to the dignity of these arts. But when we do the analogous thing in the art of painting, the 86 PAINTING tendency is to protest at once, " Not oils or pigments on paper or plaster,' but the forms and colors of these pigments. The material itself, save in its technical side, is of no im- portance." What right have we, however, to make any such distinction in painting? Of course it is the color of these materials in which we are interested, but so it is the color and the outline of the gold and gems that delight us in jewel-work, and the color, outline, and surface of the marble which satisfy us in sculpture. Why should we, then, be forced to give the abstraction of color as painting's material expression, when we do not say of sculpture, architecture, or the minor arts, as we well might, that their mate- rials are colors, lights, shadows, or surfaces ? Why cannot we state frankly that, as the ma- terial of cathedral architecture is stone, metal, and glass, so a fresco is built of plaster and pigment; and why is notour statement as 87 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART satisfactory ? That it is not as satisfactory I believe we shall agree, but we must in- quire more closely to find what change has /taken place. Why must we become less ob- jective in a discussion of painting, and sub- stitute for the term substance^ the sensations of color and light to which that substance . gives rise ? We cannot for an instant believe that cer- tain arts have a material element and that others present an idea with no dependence on a material medium. But it is obvious that the arts of sculpture and architecture represent not only an idea which in some way peculiarly harmonizes with the medium in which it lives, but they also exhibit the spirit of the substance itself; whereas in the arts of painting, literature, and music, this is far less true. ^ Thus a statue of a nude boy in marble or bronze represents not only the possibilities 88 PAINTING of vigorous boyhood, but the poetry of stone and metal. Even though the stone is pri- marily for the purpose of exhibiting the enduring spirit of eternal youth, the figure is also to some extent a vehicle for exploit- > ing the vitality of stone and metal. The ^ human figure is thus not the only speaker, but there is a duet of organic with the in- organic, in which the less articulate stone is^ by no means unheard. The same is true in architecture, where the ponderous battlement tells a story even in ruins ; where size, and weight, and thrusts — even lacking in structural plan — can make an architectural appeal. Surely the material of the minor arts can make this harmonious but independent impression. Their materials are often beautiful without formal arrange- ment. But when we approach painting as a fine art, it may be questioned whether paint as 89 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART paint, canvas as canvas, plaster as plaster, makes any appeal whatever. The canvas and the paint must be present to support the picture, as the bolts may re- inforce masonry, but the effect of the paint- ing has been independent of its material medium in this sense. It does not combine within itself a double message. An altar piece does not interpret the spirit of the saints and the spirit of paint. We do not face the unhewn block and tubes of pig- ment with the same emotion. With the block of stone and the sculptor*s model we have two spirits to harmonize, two voices each chanting of its own essence. With the pal- ette and the painter's model, be he the same model in the two cases, a change has taken place in our attitude toward the situation. We have not two spirits, but only one. The paint and canvas are wholly servants to the model. The canvas is too humble to sing 90 PAINTING of canvas, and the paint has no message to impart of its own inner self. Therefore,^ we can see that, while painting is no less dependent on her material than the arts of sculpture and architecture, she is less dependent on the spirit of her material or upon the message of her substance. She loses and gains by this difference in appeal. She loses that grandeur in which a material force, met face to face, will always clothe itself, but curiously enough she gains a para- doxical advantage by this change from a sub- stance-idea duet to a purely ideal solo ! Since/ she does not and cannot give us a mes- sage from matter itself, she can represent it. Since paint and chalk and paper and plaster have so modestly withdrawn their own indi- vidualities from the art product that as sub- stance they can be ignored, at once by a strange shift it becomes possible for paint to paint itself; that is, to paint, if it will, a table 91 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART covered with paints, or to paint a repre- sentative of any material substance which it chooses, while sculpture, being the art of inorganic substance, can never represent in- organic things independently, but only that which is the furthest removed from the inorganic that is, the living form. It is a curious compensation of the arts. Express the spirit of material substance by presenting it, and you sacrifice the possibility of expressing it by representation. Or, on the other hand, suppress the presentation of material in the raw, and you may represent it as much as you please. It is not a piece of landscape from which a landscape may be hewn ; not a boulder in which the spirit of rocks may be expressed. But colored sub- stances, made from one cares not what, can represent the landscape and the cliff, and ma- terial form without life becomes subject for art only in a material which has ceased, so 92 PAINTING far as in It lies, to have a life of its own at all. For this reason we slip unconsciously into^ the convention of calling color, and not the colored substance, the material of painting. We schematize our visual sensations accord- ing to their hue, their value, and their satu- ration, just as we formalize color schemes in a laboratory. We abstract their color quality^ from all their other sensory characteristics, and have thereby, as it were, already idealized our material before we have begun to use it. Our material medium is thus becoming, not less important in technic, but more subordi- nate in significance. Our paintings may shift from wood or plaster to canvas, without seri- ous change, in a manner quite impossible to imagine in sculpture. Moreover, the absolute size, which makes such a difference in sculp- ture and architecture, does not figure as sig- nificantly in painting. Size again, as well as 93 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART weight, are distinctly substantial concerns. Matter is expressing its own essence when it impresses us by its rigidity, its size, its weight, and pressure, and the fact that we classify statues quite defensibly as figurines, at an ab- solute size where a painting has by no means become a miniature, shows that we are not as sensitive to this factor in the art of painting. Of course, in a general sense, there must be a relation in the size of any art objects to the size of human beings, or to the size, more especially, of the picture which any object at a visible distance throws upon the human /retina. But in painting, the figures may be large, as in a Michael Angelo fresco, or small, as in a Mantegna easel picture; heavy, as in painted plaster, or light, as in painted wood ; huge in immediate foreground, or tiny on the horizon ; and we think little of it. We begin to note a change of size only when the whole work approaches the cameo size of minia- 94 PAINTING tures. Because we do not concern ourselves with size until so great a divergence from life has taken place, we have proved ourselves relatively indifferent to the spatial demands of substance. Apparently, then, it is not so pertinent to inquire how large, how heavy, how small, or how light our painted art objects must, or may, be made. By passing beyond these de-/ mands, we have gained a freedom of repre- sentation so great that at first it may seem unlimited. We have found that we may not carve landscapes, but we may paint them ; we cannot make statues of interiors, but we may make pictures of them ; we do not (save in decoration) carve groups of still-life objects, but we may paint them ; we cannot to advan- tage perpetuate in stone the individual tricks of costume and activity, which we have a right to represent in painting as much as we like. Moreover, the living forms to which 95 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF ART sculpture devotes herself may also become models for painting, with the nudity of a sculptural background or the richness of the minor artist's craft, according to the painter's fancy. Is there anything, then, that painting may not do ? Have we here an art with no ideal limits ? // To state a universal fact is to state an obvious one, and in so doing, one ventures perilously near to platitudes. We are, how- ever, concerned throughout our aesthetics with truths so obvious that they are ordinar- ily overlooked, and the reasons for the limits of painting and sculpture fall into such a class of axioms. That they have » 21-100m-8.'34 LIBRARY USE RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED LOAN DEPT. THIS BOOK IS DUE BEFORE CLOSING TIME ON LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW ■|BR*.RYUSE AUG 7 '67. . RFCFIVED AUG 7 '67 -8 PM kOAN DFPTi '^F.^lt^^t^iil uow?^|]^;&u