:<■>'. ffl&tswm fw.''.'- ■ - '''.
THE LIBRARY
OF
THE UNIVERSITY
OF CALIFORNIA
LOS ANGELES
THE INTRODUCTION TO
HEGEL'S PHILOSOPHY OF FINE ART
THE INTRODUCTION TO
HEGEL'S
PHILOSOPHY OF FINE ART
TRANSLATED FROM THE GERMAN
WITH NOTES AND PREFATORY ESSAY
BY
BERNARD BOSANOUET, M.A.
LATE FELLOW AND TUTOR OF UNIVERSITY COLLEGE, OXFORD
i
• • * * ' "»
, ' * '
a 3 ■ « ' ■ , «• -, » *
... • .
> > '>
3 3
■
- .
> - O
I
6 ) « • 3 * »4
■
^3
LONDON
KEGAN PAUL, TRENCH & CO., i PATERNOSTER SQUARE
1SS6
• t » . « « e*
{The rights of translation and of reproduction are reser-jed.)
AH1 9
'(/
6f
TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE.
Hegel's " ^Esthetik? or "Philosophy of Fine Art,"
is a work which should no longer be inaccessible to
the English reading public, but the reproduction
of which, in its complete form of 1600 pages, is a
task not to be lightly undertaken. I know of three
partial reproductions of the "sEsthetik" in English,
viz. Mr. Bryant's translation of Part II.,* Mr.
Kedney's short analysis of the entire work,f and
Mr. Hastie's translation of Michelet's short "Philo-
sophy of Art," J prefaced by Hegel's Introduction,
partly translated and partly analysed.
I wholly disapprove of analyses (among which
may be reckoned Michelet's summary above men-
tioned) as representations of Hegel's writing, which
* New York, Appleton and Co.
t Chicago, Griggs and Co., 1885.
% Edinburgh, Oliver and Boyd, 1886.
b 2
230428
vj TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE.
is attractive chiefly by the force and freshness of
its detail. I am convinced that Hegel should be
allowed to speak for himself, and that failing the
translation of the whole "sEsthetik" or of very
copious selections, the best course is that which
I have adopted in the present volume, viz. to trans-
late the entire Introduction, including the chapter
entitled, " Division of the Subject." This Introduc-
tion is in Hegel's best manner — so far as he can
be said to have literary manner at all, especially
in a work which has been produced by editors from
lecture-notes, — and is tolerably complete in itself.
It is not contained as a whole in any of the above-
mentioned works. I ought to say, however, that
Mr. Hastie's translation is excellent in style ; but
after the first thirty-four pages it also becomes an
analysis. Nor is it wholly free from serious mistakes.
I have hoped that the present volume may be of
interest to many who, without being students of philo-
sophy, are intelligent lovers of art. I have therefore
done my best to interpret philosophical expressions,
instead of merely furnishing their technical equiva-
lents. I have also added a few short notes, either
to explain literary allusions, or to complete the in-
TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE. vii
terpretation of technical terms. The prefatory essay
was written with a similar intention, not as original
speculation, but as an assistance to general readers
in apprehending the point of view from which Fine
Art is regarded by Hegel and kindred writers.
I have broken up the " Einleitung" or Introduc-
tion proper, which is continuous in the original, into
four chapters,* hoping that the arrangement of the
discussion may be thus rendered easier to follow.
The " Eintheilung" which forms my Chapter V., is
a separate chapter in the original. The table of
contents is translated from the original, excepting
those portions of it which are enclosed in square
brackets, [ ].
My literary notes are entirely borrowed from the
late Mrs. F. C. Conybeare's translation of Scherer's
" History of German Literature ; " a work invaluable
to the English student, whose gratitude must for
long be saddened by the untimely death of the
translator.
* Of these, Chapter III. is subdivided into two Parts, because
of the disproportionate length of the division in the original to
which it corresponds.
CONTENTS
FACE
Prefatory Essay f.y the Translator ... ... vii
CHAPTER I.
The Range of ^Esthetic defined, and some Objections
against the philosophy of art refuted (i-25).
[a. ^Esthetic confined to Beauty of Art ... ... ... 2
jS. Does Art merit Scientific Treatment ? ... ... 5
7. Is Scientific Treatment appropriate to Art ? ... ... 8
5. Answer to £. ... ... ... ... ... 13
€. Answer to 7.] ... ... ... ... ... ... 20
CHAPTER II.
Methods of Science Applicable to Beauty and Art (26-42).
[l. Empirical Method — Art-scholarship ... ... ... 27
(a) Its Range ... ... ... ... ... 27
(b) It generates Rules and Theories ... ... ... 28
(c) The Rights of Genius ... ... ... ... 38
2. Abstract Reflection ... ... ... ... ... 40
3. The Philosophical Conception of Artistic Beauty, general
notion of] ... ... ... ... ... 4 1
CONTENTS.
CHAPTER III.
The Philosophical Conception of Artistic Beauty,
beginning with current ideas of art (43-io5).
PAGE
Part I. — The Work of Art as Made and as Sensuous ...43-78
1. Work of Art as Product of Human Activity ... ... 48
[() Hnmani nihil — ? ... ... ... ... 87
(c) Mitigation of the Passions ? ... ... ... 90
(a) How Art mitigates the Passions ... 91
(£) How Art purifies the Passions ... ... 94
(aa) It must have a Worthy Content ... 95
(£j8) But ought not to be Didactic ... ... 95
(77) Nor explicitly addressed to a Moral
Purpose ... ... ... 98
(it) Art has its own Purpose as Revelation of Truth ... 105
CONTENTS.
XI
CHAPTER IV.
Historical Deduction of the True Idea of Art in
2.
Modern Philosophy (107-132).
Kant
[(a) Pleasure in Beauty not Appetitive
(b) Pleasure in Beauty Universal
(c) The Beautiful in its Teleological Aspect ...
{d) Delight in the Beautiful necessary though feli\
Schiller, Winckelmann, Schelling
The Irony
PAGE
I07
no
III
112
"3
116
120
CHAPTER V.
Division of the Subject (133—175).
[I
The Condition of Artistic Presentation is the Correspondence
of Matter and Plastic Form
J 33
2.
Part I. — The Ideal
141
3-
Part II.— The Types of Art . . .
144
(a) Symbolic Art
145
(j3) Classical Art
148
(7) Romantic Art
151
4-
Part III.— The Several Arts
157
(a) Architecture
160
(/3) Sculpture
162
(7) Romantic Art, comprising
164
(i.) Painting
167
(ii.) Music
169
(iii.) Poetry
171
5-
Conclusion]
173
PREFATORY ESSAY BY THE TRANSLATOR.
ON THE TRUE CONCEPTION OF ANOTHER WORLD.
" With such barren forms of thought, that are always in a
world beyond, Philosophy has nothing to do. Its object is
always something concrete, and in the highest sense present."
— Hegel's Logic, Wallace's translation, p. 150.
It will surprise many readers to be told that the
words which I have quoted above embody the very
essence of Hegelian thought. The Infinite, the supra-
sensuous, the divine, are so connected in our minds
with futile rackings of the imagination about remote
matters which only distract us from our duties, that
a philosophy which designates its problems by such
terms as these seems self-condemned as cloudy and
inane. But, all appearances to the contrary notwith-
standing, Hegel is faithful to the present and the
concrete. In the study of his philosophy we are
always dealing with human experience. " My stress
lay," says Mr. Browning,* " on the incidents in the
* Preface to " Sordello."
xiv PREFATORY ESSAY.
development of a soul ; little else is worth study."
For " a soul " read " the mind," and you have the
subject-matter to which Hegel's eighteen close-
printed volumes are devoted. The present intro-
ductory remarks are meant to insist on this neglected
point of view. I wish to point out, in two or three
salient instances, the transformation undergone by
speculative notions when sedulously applied to life,
and restrained from generating an empty " beyond."
By so doing I hope to pave the way for a due
appreciation of Hegel's philosophy of fine art. That
the world of mind, or the world above sense, exists
as an actual and organized whole, is a truth most
easily realized in the study of the beautiful. And to
grasp this principle as Hegel applies it is nothing
less than to acquire a new contact with spiritual
life. The spiritual world, which is present, actual,
and concrete, contains much besides beauty. But
to apprehend one element of such a whole constitutes
and presupposes a long step towards apprehending
the rest. It is for this reason that I propose, in the
first place, to explain, by prominent examples, the
conception of a spiritual world which is present and
actual, and then to let Hegel speak for himself on
the particular sphere of art. So closely connected
indeed are all the embodiments of mind, that the
, Introduction to the " Philosophy of Fine Art " is
\almost a microcosm of his entire system.
THE OTHER WORLD. xv
We know, to our cost, the popular conception of
the supra-sensuous world. Whatever that world is,
it is, as commonly thought of, not here and not now.
That is to say, if here and now, it is so by a sort of
miracle, at which we are called upon to wonder, as
when angels are said to be near us, or the dead to
know what we do. Again, it is a counterpart of our
present world, and rather imperceptible to our
senses, than in its nature beyond contact with sense
as such. It is peopled by persons, who live eternally,
which means through endless ages, and to whose
actual communion with us, as also to our own with
God, we look forward in the future. It even perhaps
contains a supra-sensuous original corresponding to
every thing and movement in this 'world of ours.
And it does not necessarily deepen our conception
of life, but only reduplicates it.
Such a world, whatever we may think about its
actual existence, is not the " other world " of philo-
sophy. The " things not seen " of Plato or of Hegel
are not a double or a projection of the existing
world. Plato, indeed, wavered between the two
conceptions in a way that should have warned his
interpreters of the divergence in his track of thought.
But in Hegel, at least, there is no ambiguity. The
world of spirits with him is no world of ghosts.
When we study the embodiments of mind or spirit
in his pages, and read of law, prop erty, and na tional
xvi PREFATORY ESSAY.
unity ; of fine art, the religious community, and the
intellect that has attained scientific self-conscious-
ness, we may miss our other world with its obscure
" beyond," but we at any rate feel ourselves to be
dealing with something real, and with the deepest
concerns of life. We may deny to such matters the
titles which philosophy bestows upon them ; we
may say that this is no " other world," no realm of
spirits, nothing infinite or divine : but this matters
little so long as we know what we are talking about,
and are talking about the best we know. And what
we discuss when Hegel is our guide, will ahvays
be some great achievement or essential attribute of
the human mind. He never asks, "Is it?" but always
" What is it ? " and therefore has instruction, drawn
from experience, even for those to whom the titles of
his inquiries seem fraudulent or bombastic.
These few remarks are not directed to maintain-
ing any thesis about the reality of nature and of
sense. Their object is to enforce a distinction which
falls within the world which we know, and not
between the world we know and another which we
do not know. This distinction is real, and governs
life. I am not denying any other distinction, but
I am insisting on this. No really great philosopher,
nor religious teacher, — neither Plato, nor Kant, nor
St. Paul — can be understood unless we grasp this
antithesis in the right way. All of these teachers
THE OTHER WORLD. xvii
have pointed men to another world. All of them,
perhaps, were led at times by the very force and
reality of their own thought into the fatal separa-
tion that cancels its meaning. So strong was their
sense of the gulf between the trifles and the realities
of life, that they gave occasion to the indolent
imagination — in themselves and in others — to
transmute this gulf from a measure of moral effort
into an inaccessibility that defies apprehension.
But their purpose was to overcome this inaccessi-
bility, not to heighten it.
The hardest of all lessons in interpretation is to
believe that great men mean what they say. We
are below their level, and what they actually say
seems impossible to us, till we have adulterated it
to suit our own imbecility. Especially when they
speak of the highest realities, we attach our notion
of reality to what they pronounce to be real. And
thus we baffle every attempt to deepen our ideas of
the world in which we live. The work of intelligence
is hard ; that of the sensuous fancy is easy ; and so
we substitute the latter for the former. We are told,
for instance, by Plato, that goodness, beauty, and
truth are realities, but not visible or tangible.
Instead of responding to the call so made on our
intelligence by scrutinizing the nature and conditions
of these intellectual facts — though we know well how
tardily they are produced by the culture of ages — we
xviii PREFATORY ESSAY.
apply forthwith our idea of reality as something
separate in space and time, and so " refute " Plato
with ease, and remain as wise as we were before.
And it is true that Plato, handling ideas of vast
import with the mind and language of his day,
sometimes by a similar error refutes himself* He
makes, for instance, the disembodied soul see the
invisible ideas. Thus he travesties his things of the
mind as though they were things of sense, only not of
our sense — thereby destroying the deeper difference
of kind that alone enables them to find a place in
our world. That his doctrine of ideas was really
rooted, not in mysticism, but in scientific enthusiasm,
is a truth that is veiled from us partly by his
inconsistencies, but far more by our own erroneous
preconceptions.!
There is, however, a genuine distinction between
" this " world and the " other " world, which is merely
parodied by the vulgar antitheses between natural
and supernatural, finite and infinite, phenomenal
and noumenal. We sometimes hear it said, " The
* " Endless duration makes good no better, nor white any
whiter," is one of Aristotle's comments on Plato's " eternal "
ideas, and is just, unless " eternal " conveys a difference of
kind.
t Whewell, I think, misinterprets Plato's language about
astronomy in this sense. Plato is not decrying observation, but
demanding a theoretical treatment of the laws of motion,— a
remarkable anticipation of modern ideas.
THE OTHER WORLD. xix
/ *»
world is quite changed to me since I knew such a
person," or " studied such a subject," or " had suggested
to me such an idea." The expression may be
literally true ; and we do not commonly exaggerate,
but vastly underrate its import. We read, for
instance, in a good authority, "These twenty kinds
of birds (which Virgil mentions) do not correspond
so much to our species as to our genera ; for the
Greeks and Romans, I need hardly say, had only
very rough-and-ready methods of classification, just
as is the case with uneducated people at the present
day."* Any one may verify the same fact as regards
the observation of flowers. Every yellow ranunculus
is called a "butter-cup," every large white umbel-
lifer a " hemlock." These, with hundreds of other
differences of perception, affect the surroundings in
which men consciously live, at least as much as a
considerable degree of deafness or blindness. It is
no metaphor, but literal fact, to say that man's whole
environment is transformed by the training even of
his mere apprehension of natural objects. But there
is more in the matter than this. Without going into
metaphysics, which I wish to avoid, I cannot, indeed,
maintain that mind "makes" natural objects, although
by enabling us to perceive them it unquestionably
makes our immediate conscious world. My individual
consciousness does not make or create the differences
* " A Year with the Birds," by an Oxford Tutor.
c
xx PREFATORY ESSAY.
between the species of ranunculus, although it does
create my knowledge of them. But when we come
to speak of the world of morals or art or politics,
we may venture much further in our assertions. The
actual facts of this world do directly arise out of and
are causally sustained by conscious intelligence ; and
these facts form the world above sense. The unity
of a Christian church or congregation is a governing
fact of life ; so is that of a family or a nation ; so, we
may hope, will that of humanity come to be. What
is this unity ? Is it visible and tangible, like the
unity of a human body? No, the unity is "ideal;"
that is, it exists in the medium of thought only ; it
is made up of certain sentiments, purposes, and ideas.
What even of an army ? Here, too, an ideal
unity is the mainspring of action. Without mutual
intelligence and reciprocal reliance you may have
a mob, but you cannot have an army. But all these
conditions exist and can exist in the mind only. An
army, qua army, is not a mere fact of sense ; for not
only does it need mind to perceive it — a heap of sand
does that — but it also needs mind to make it.
The world of these governing facts of life is the
world of the things not seen, the object of reason,
the world of the truly infinite and divine. It is, of
course, a false antithesis to contrast seeing with the
bodily eye and seeing with the mind's eye. The
seeing eye is always the mind's eye. The distinction
THE OTHER WORLD. xxi
between sense and spirit or intellect is a distinction
within the mind, just as is St. Paul's opposition
between the spirit and the flesh. Nevertheless, the
mind that only sees colour — sense or sense-perception
— is different from the mind that sees beauty, the
self-conscious spirit. The latter includes the former,
but the former does not include the latter. To the
one the colour is the ultimate fact ; to the other it
is an element in a thing of beauty. This relation
prevails throughout between the world of sense and
the world above sense. The " things not seen,"
philosophically speaking, are no world of existences
or of intelligences co-ordinate with and severed from
this present world. They are a value, an import,
a significance, superadded to the phenomenal world,
which may thus be said, though with some risk of
misunderstanding, to be degraded into a symbol.
The house, the cathedral, the judge's robe, the
general's uniform, are ultimate facts for the child or
the savage ; but for the civilized man they are
symbols of domestic life, of the Church, and of the
State. Even where the supra-sensuous world has
its purest expression, in the knowledge and will of
intelligent beings, it presupposes a sensuous world
as the material of ideas and of actions. " This " world
and the "other" world are continuous and inseparable,
and all men must live in some degree for both. But
the completion of the Noumenal world, and the
xxii PREFATORY ESSAY.
apprehension of its reality and completeness, is the
task by fulfilling which humanity advances.
I pass to the interpretation, neither technical nor
controversial, of one or two of Hegel's most alarming
phrases.
The " infinite " seems to practical minds the very
opposite of anything real, present, or valuable. As
the description of life, it is the mere negation of the
life we know ; as the description of a purpose, it is
the very antithesis of any purpose that we can con-
ceive to be attainable ; as the description of a being,
it appears to be formed by denying every predicate
which we attach to personality. And I could wish
that Hegel had not selected this much-abused term
as the distinctive predicate of what is most real and
most precious in life. He adhered to it, no doubt,
because his infinity, though different in nature to that
of common logic, yet rightly fills the place and meets
the problem of that conception. I will attempt to
explain how this can be, and what we are discussing
when we read about infinity in the Hegelian philo-
sophy.
It is an obvious remark, that infinity was a symbol
of evil in Hellenic speculation, whereas to Christian
and modern thought it is identified with good. Much
idle talk has arisen on this account, as to the limita-
tion of the Hellenic mind. For in fact, the Finite
ascribed to Pythagoras, and the idea of limit and pro-
THE OTHER WORLD. xxiii
portion in Plato or in Aristotle, are far more nearly
akin to true infinity than is the Infinite of modern
popular philosophy. Infinite means the negation of
limit. Now, common infinity, which may be identified
in general with enumeration ad infinitum, — the false
infinity of Hegel — is the attempt to negate or transcend
a limit which inevitably recurs. It arises from attempt-
ing a task or problem in the wrong way, so that we
may go on for ever without making any advance
towards its achievement. All quantitative infinity —
which of course has its definite uses, subject to proper
reservations — is of this nature. A process does not
change its character by mere continuance, and the
aggregate of a million units is no .more free from
limitation than the aggregate of ten. A defect in
kind cannot be compensated by mere quantity. We
see the fallacious attempt in savage, barbaric, or
vulgar art. Meaningless iteration, objectless labour,
enormous size, extravagant costliness, indicate the
effort to satisfy man's need of expression by the mere
accumulation of work without adequate idea or pur-
pose. But such efforts, however stupendous, never
attain their goal. They constitute a recurrent failure
to transcend a recurrent limit, precisely analogous
to enumeration ad infinitum. A hundred thousand
pounds' worth of bricks and mortar comes no nearer
to the embodiment of mind than a thousand pounds'
worth. To attempt adequate expression by mere
xxiv PREFATORY ESSAY.
aggregation of cost or size is therefore to fall into the
infinite process or the false infinity.
Another well-known instance is the pursuit of
happiness in the form of " pleasure for pleasure's
sake." The recurrence of unchanging units leaves us
where we were. A process which does not change
remains the same, and if it did not bring satisfaction
at first, will not do so at last.* We might as well go
on producing parallels to infinity, in the hope that
somehow or somewhere they may meet. An infinite
straight line may serve as a type of the kind of
infinity we are considering.
Infinity in the Hegelian sense does not partake
in any way of this endlessness, or of the unreality which
attaches to it. Its root-idea is self-completeness or satis-
faction. That which is " infinite " is without boundary,
because it does not refer beyond itself for explanation,
or for justification ; and therefore, in all human existence
or production infinity can only be an aspect or element.
A picture, for instance, regarded as a work of fine
art, justifies itself, gives satisfaction directly and with-
out raising questions of cause or of comparison, and
is in this sense — i.e. in respect of its beauty — regarded
as " infinite." When, on the other hand, we consider
this same work of art as an historical phenomenon, as
a link in a chain of causation — e.g. as elucidating the
development of a school, or proving the existence of
* See note above, p. xii.
THE OTHER WORLD. xxv
a certain technical process at a certain date — then we
go beyond itself for its interest and explanation, and
depress it at once into a finite object. The finite is
that which presents itself as incomplete ; the infinite
that which presents itself as complete, and which,
therefore, does not force upon us the fact of its limita-
tation. This character belongs in the highest degree
to self-conscious mind, as realized in the world above
sense ; and in some degree to all elements of that
world — for instance, to the State — in as far as they
represent man's realized self-consciousness. It is the
nature of self-consciousness to be infinite, because it
is its nature to take into itself what was opposed to
it, and thus to make itself into an organized sphere
that has value and reality within, and not beyond
itself. If false infinity was represented by an infinite
straight line, true infinity may be compared to a
circle or a sphere.
The distinction between true and false infinity is
of the profoundest moral import. The sickly yearn-
ing that longs only to escape from the real, rooted
in the antithesis between the infinite and the actual
or concrete, or in the idea of the monotonous " infini "
which is one with the " abime" or the " gonffre" is
appraised by this test at its true value. It is seen
to rest on a mere pathetic fallacy of thought and
sentiment. So far from the infinite being remote,
abstract, unreal, nothing but the infinite can be truly
xxvi PREFATORY ESSAY.
present, concrete, and real. The finite always refers
us away and away through an endless series of causes,
of effects, or of relations. The infinite is individual,
and bears the character of knowledge, achievement,
attainment. In short, the actual realities which we
have in mind when, in philosophy, we speak of the
infinite, are such as a nation that is conscious of its
unity and general will, or the realm of fine art as
the recognition of man's higher nature, or the religious
community with its conviction of an indwelling Deity.
Now, whether we like the term Infinite or not,
whether or no we think that man's life can be ex-
plained and justified within the limits of these aims
and these phenomena, there is no doubt that these
matters are real, and are the most momentous of
realities. In acquainting ourselves with their struc-
ture, evolution, and relation to individual life, we are
at least not wasting time, nor treating of matters
beyond human intelligence.
There is a very similar contrast in the conception
of human Freedom. " Free will " is so old a vexed
question, that though the conflict still rages fitfully
round it, the world hardly conceives that much can
turn upon its decision. But when in place of the
abstract, " Is man free ? " we are confronted with the
concrete inquiry, " When, in what, and as what, does
man carry out his will with least hindrance and with
fullest satisfaction ? " then we have before us the
THE OTHER WORLD. xxvii
actual phenomena of civilization, instead of an idle
and abstract Yes or No.
Man's Freedom, in the sense thus contemplated,
lies in the spiritual or supra-sensuous world by which
his humanity is realized, and in which his will finds
fulfilment. The family, for example, property, and
law are the first steps of man's freedom. In them
the individual's will obtains and bestows recognition
as an agent in a society whose bond of union is ideal
— i.e. existing only in consciousness ; and this recog-
nition develops into duties and rights. It is in these
that man finds something to live for, something in
which and for the sake of which to assert himself.
As society develops he lives on the whole more in
the civilized or spiritual world, and less in the savage
or purely natural world. His will, which is himself,
expands with the institutions and ideas that form
its purpose, and the history of this expansion is the
history of human freedom. Nothing is more shallow,
more barbarously irrational, than to regard the pro-
gress of civilization as the accumulation of restric-
tions. Laws and rules are a necessary aspect of
extended capacities. Every power that we gain has
a positive nature, and therefore involves positive
conditions, and every positive condition has negative
relations. To accomplish a particular purpose you
must go to work in a particular way, and in no other
way. To complain of this is like complaining of a
xxviii PREFATORY ESSAY.
house because it has a definite shape. If freedom
means absence of attributes, empty space is " freer "
than any edifice. Of course a house may be so ugly
that we may say we would rather have none at all.
Civilization may bring such horrors that we may
say " rather savagery than this ; " but in neither case
are we serious. Great as are the vices of civilization,
it is only in civilization that man becomes human,
spiritual, and free.
The effort to grasp and apply such an idea as
this can hardly be barren. It brings us face to face
with concrete facts of history, and of man's actual
motives and purposes. True philosophy here, as
everywhere, plunges into the concrete and the real ;
it is the indolent abstract fancy that thrusts problems
away into the remote "beyond" or into futile abstrac-
tion. Plato, the philosopher, knows well that the
mind is free when it achieves what as a whole it truly
wills. But Plato, the allegorist and imaginative
preacher, refers the soul's freedom to a fleeting
moment of ante-natal choice, which he vainly strives
to exempt from causal influence. Pictorial imagina-
tion, with its ready reference to occurrences in past
and future, is the great foe to philosophic intelligence.
Finally, it is impossible to omit all reference to
the notion of an immanent Deity, which forms the
very centre of Hegel's thought. When an unspecula-
tive English reader first meets with Hegel's passionate
THE OTHER WORLD. xxix
insistence that God is not unknowable, that He
necessarily reveals himself as a Trinity of persons,
and that to deny this is to represent men as " the
heathen who know not God," he feels as if he had
taken sand into his mouth. He is inclined to ask
what these Neo-Platonic or mediaeval doctrines are
doing in the nineteenth century, and why we should
resuscitate dead logomachies that can have no
possible value for life or conduct. Now, I must
not attempt here to discuss the difficult question of
Hegel's ultimate conception of the being of God,
and I am bound to warn any one who may read
these pages that I only profess to reproduce one
— though by far the most prominent — side of that
conception. But, subject to this reservation, I have
no hesitation in saying, that our own prejudices form
the only hindrance to our seeing that Hegel's subject-
matter is here, as elsewhere, human life. He gives
us what he takes to be the literal truth, and we will
have it to be metaphor. Verbally contradicting
Kant, he accepts, completes, and enforces Kant's
thought. " Revelation can never be the true ground
of religion," said Kant ; " for revelation is an historical
accident, and religion is a rational necessity of man's
intelligent nature." " Revelation is the only true know-
ledge of God and ground of religion," says Hegel,
" because revelation consists in the realization of God in
mans intelligent nature." We are, however, not unac-
xxx PREFATORY ESSAY.
customed to such phrases, and our imagination is
equal to its habitual task of evading their meaning.
We take them to be a strong metaphor, meaning
that God, who is a sort of ghostly being a long way
off, is, notwithstanding, more or less within the know-
ledge of our minds, and so is " in " them, as a book
which is actually in London may be in my memory
when I am in Scotland. Now, right or wrong, this
is not what Hegel means. He means what he says ;
that God is spirit or mind,* and exists in the medium
of mind, which is actual as intelligence,* for us at a7iy
rate, only in the human self-consciousness. The
thought is hard from its very simplicity, and we
struggle, as always, to avoid grasping it. We imagine
spirits as made of a sort of thin matter, and so as
existing just like bodies, although we call them dis-
embodied. And then we think of this disembodied
form as an alternative to human form, and suppose
spirit to have somehow a purer existence apart from
human body. This error really springs from ima-
gining the two as existences of the same kind, and
so conflicting, and from not realizing the notion of
spirit as mind or self-consciousness, which is the only
way of conceiving its actual presence in our world.
* The fusion of these meanings in the German " Geist "
gives a force to his pleading which English cannot render.
He appeals, e.g., triumphantly to " God is a Spirit," i.e. not " a
ghost " but " mind."
THE OTHER WORLD. xxxi
Mind uses sensuous existence as its symbol ; perhaps
even needs it. The poet who has hit Hegel's thought
so nearly,* fails here : —
• " This weight of body and limb,
Are they not sign and symbol of thy division from Him?"
Here we leave the track of the higher Pantheism
for that of vulgar mysticism. Spiritual being is
conceived as somehow incompatible with bodily
shape, either because incapable of any concrete
embodiment, or because it has a quasi-material shape
of its own. Now, this is just the reverse of the
Hegelian idea. According to Hegel, it is only in the
human form that intelligence can for us find its full
expression. The notion of a spiritual body other
than and incompatible with the natural body does
not arise. Spirit exists in the medium of conscious-
ness, not in a peculiar kind of matter. The spirituali-
zation of the natural body is not to be looked for in
an astral or angel body, but in the gait and gesture,
the significance and dignity, that make the body of
the civilized man the outward image of his soul, and
distinguish him from the savage as from the animal.
The human soul becomes actual itself, and visible to
* See Tennyson's " Higher Pantheism," especially the fine
lines —
" Speak to Him thou, for He hears, and Spirit with Spirit can
meet,
Closer is He than breathing, and nearer than hands and feet."
xxxii PREFATORY ESSAY.
others, only by moulding the body into its symbol
and instrument. It ought to have been an axiom of
physiology, Hegel says, that the series of animated
forms must necessarily lead up to that of man. For
this is the only sensuous form in which mind could
attain adequate manifestation. Thus anthropomor-
phism in fine art is no accident, nor an unworthy
portrayal of divinity. If the Deity is to be symbolized
to sense, it must be in the image of man. The
symbol is not indeed the reality, as the sensuous
image is not conscious thought ; but this is a defect
inherent in artistic presentation, and not attributable
to anthropomorphism in particular.
It is obvious that in the light of such a conception,
a speculative import can be attached to the doctrine
of the Incarnation, and Hegel's reading of Christian
ideas is, in fact, to be interpreted entirely in this
sense. This is not the place to go deeper into such
views, which, however profound, may perhaps continue
to seem non-natural expositions of Christian dogma.
I am only concerned to show how here, also, the
speculative idea, operating upon the concrete and
actual, generates a fresh and inspiring insight into
life and conduct. Few chapters of anthropology are
more thorough, profound, and suggestive than Hegel's
account of the " actual soul ; " i.e. of the habits and
attributes which make the body distinctively human
by stamping it with the impress of mind. Nor has
THE OTHER WORLD. xxxiii
philosophic insight ever done better service to the
history of religion than in grasping the essence of
Christianity as the unity, (not merely the union) of the
divine and human nature.
Among the things which are spiritually discerned,
an important place belongs to beauty. As a boun-
dary and transition between sense and thought, it
is peculiarly fitted to illustrate the reality which we
claim, in contradistinction to mere sensuous appear-
ance, for what is best in life. Many who distrust
Hegelian formulae are convinced that beauty at least
is real. They will admit that fine art and the recog-
nition of beauty are not trifles, not amusements, but
rank high among the interests that give life its value.
All such will find themselves in sympathy with the
purpose of a great philosopher who has bent all the
power of his genius and his industry to vindicating
a place for art as an embodiment of the divine nature.
The Introduction to Hegel's "^Esthetic," which is all
that it was possible to reproduce in the present volume,
lacks, of course, the solidity and detailed elaboration
of the treatise. Yet to all who care for thorough and
noble thought on a great subject, and for a defence
of their faith in the true spiritual realities, I have
hope that the ensuing pages, however marred by
imperfect translation, will be welcome.
HEGEL'S .ESTHETIC.
INTRODUCTION.
CHAPTER I.
THE RANGE OF .ESTHETIC DEFINED, AND SOME
OBJECTIONS REFUTED.
The present course of lectures deals with " ^Esthetic."
Their subject is the wide realm of the beautiful, and,
more particularly, their province is Art — we may
restrict it, indeed, to Fine Art.
The name " ^Esthetic " in its natural sense is
not quite appropriate to this subject. "^Esthetic"
means more precisely the science of sensation or
feeling. Thus understood, it arose as a new science,
or rather as something that was to become a branch
of philosophy for the first time,* in the school of
* In Baumgarten's "^Esthetica," 1750. See LotzeV/Esthetik
in Deutschland," p. 4, and Scherer's " Hist, of German Litera-
ture," Engl. Transl., ii. 25.
E
2 THE RANGE OF AESTHETIC. [Chap. I.
Wolff, at the epoch when works of art were being
considered in Germany in the light of the feelings
which they were supposed to evoke — feelings of
pleasure, admiration, fear, pity, etc. The name was
so inappropriate, or, strictly speaking, so superficial,
that for this reason it was attempted to form other
names, e.g. " Kallistic." But this name, again, is
unsatisfactory, for the science to be designated does
not treat of beauty in general, but merely of artistic
beauty. We shall, therefore, permit the name
./Esthetic to stand, because it is nothing but a name,
and so is indifferent to us, and, moreover, has up to
a certain point passed into common language. As
a name, therefore, it may be retained. The proper
expression, however, for our science is the " Philosophy of
Art," or, more definitely, the " Philosophy of Fine Art."
a. By the above expression we at once exclude
the beauty of Nature. Such a limitation of our
subject may appear to be an arbitrary demarcation,
resting on the principle that every science has the
prerogative of marking out its boundaries at pleasure.
But this is not the sense in which we are to under-
stand the limitation of ^Esthetic to the beauty of art.
It is true that in common life we are in the habit of
speaking of beautiful colour, a beautiful sky, a beautiful
river, and, moreover, of beautiful flowers, beautiful
animals, and, above all, of beautiful human beings.
We will not just now enter into the controversy how
Chap. I.] ART HIGHER THAN NATURE. 3
far such objects can justly have the attribute of
beauty ascribed to them, or how far, speaking
generally, natural beauty ought to be recognized as
existing besides artistic beauty. We may, however,
begin at once by asserting that artistic beauty stands &
Jiiglier than nature. For the beauty of art is the
beauty that is born — born again, that is — of the
mind;* and by as much as the mind and its products
are higher than nature and its appearances, by so
much the beauty of art is higher than the beauty of
nature. Indeed, if we look at it formally — -i.e. only
considering in what way it exists, not what there is
in it, — even a silly fancy such as may pass through
a man's head is higher than any product of nature ;
for such a fancy must at least be characterized by
intellectual being and by freedom.f In respect of
its content, on the other hand, the sun, for instance,
appears to us to be an absolutely necessary factor in
the universe, while a blundering notion passes away
as accidental and transient ; but yet, in its own being,
a natural existence such as the sun is indifferent,^ is
not free or self-conscious, while if we consider it in
* Aus dem Geiste — allusion to "born of water and of the
Spirit."
f Not in the sense of fancying what you please, but in the
technical sense of having separate existence ; detached, so to
speak, from the general background of things, not a mere
concurrence of other elements.
% Has no power of distinguishing itself from other things.
4 THE RANGE OF ^ESTHETIC. [Chap. I.
its necessary connection with other things we are not
regarding it by itself or for its own sake, and, there-
fore, not as beautiful.
To say, as we have said, in general terms, that
mind and its artistic beauty stand higher than natural
beauty, is no doubt to determine almost nothing. For
"higher" is an utterly indefinite expression, which
designates the beauty of nature and that of art as
if merely standing side by side in the space of the
imagination, and states the difference between them
as purely quantitative, and, therefore, purely external.
But the mind and its artistic beauty, in being "higher"
as compared with nature, have a distinction which is
not simply relative. Mind, and mind only, is capable
of truth, and comprehends in itself all that is, so that
whatever is beautiful can only be really and truly
beautiful as partaking in this higher element and as
created thereby. In this sense the beauty of nature
reveals itself as but a reflection of the beauty which
belongs to the mind, as an imperfect, incomplete
mode of being, as a mode whose really substantial
element is contained in the mind itself.
Moreover, we shall find the restriction to fine art
very natural, for however much has been and is said
— though less by the ancients than by ourselves —
of the beauties of nature, yet no one has taken it
into his head to emphasize the point of view of the
beauty of natural objects, and to attempt to make a
Chap. I.] BEAUTY OF NATURE EXCLUDED. 5
science, a systematic account of these beauties. The
aspect of Utility, indeed, has been accentuated, and
a science, e.g. of natural things useful against diseases
a materia medica, has been compiled, consisting in a
description of minerals, chemical products, plants, and
animals that are of use for curative purposes. But
the realm of nature has not been arrayed and
estimated under the aspect of beauty. In dealing
with natural beauty we find ourselves too open to
vagueness, and too destitute of a criterion ; for which
reason such a review would have little interest.
The above prefatory remarks upon beauty in
nature and in art, upon the relation between the
two, and the exclusion of the former from the region
of the subject proper, are meant to remove any idea
that the limitation of our science is owing merely to
choice and to caprice. But this is not the place to
demonstrate the above relation, for the consideration
of it falls within our science itself, and therefore it
cannot be discussed and demonstrated till later.
Supposing that for the present we have limited
ourselves to the beauty of art, this first step brings
us at once into contact with fresh difficulties.
/3. The first thing that may suggest itself to
us is the difficulty whether fine art shows itself to
deserve a scientific treatment. Beauty and art, no
doubt, pervade all the business of life like a kindly
genius, and form the bright adornment of all our
6 OBJECTIONS REFUTED. [Chap. I.
surroundings, both mental and material, soothing the
sadness of our condition and the embarrassments
of real life, killing time in entertaining fashion, and
where there is nothing good to be achieved, occupying
the place of what is vicious, better, at any rate, than
vice. Yet although art presses in with its pleasing
shapes on every possible occasion, from the rude-
adornments of the savage to the splendour of the
temple with its untold wealth of decoration, still
these shapes themselves appear to fall outside the
real purposes of life. And even if the creations of
art do not prove detrimental to our graver purposes,
if they appear at times actually to further them by
keeping evil at a distance, still it is so far true
that art belongs rather to the relaxation and leisure
of the mind, while the substantive interests of life
demand its exertion. Hence it may seem unsuitable
and pedantic to treat with scientific seriousness what
is not in itself of a serious nature. In any case, upon
such a view art appears as a superfluity, even if the
softening of the mental temper which pre-occupation
with beauty has power to produce, does not turn out
a detrimental, because effeminating influence. In
this aspect of the matter, the fine arts being granted
to be a luxury, it has been thought necessary in
various ways to take up their defence with reference
to their relation towards practical necessities, and
more especially towards morality and piety ; and, as
Chap. I.] IS ART UNWORTHY OF STUDY? 7
it is impossible to demonstrate their harmlessness,
at least to make it credible that the mental luxury in
question afforded a larger sum of advantages than of
disadvantages. With this view very serious aims have
been ascribed to art, and it has been recommended in
various ways as a mediator between reason and
sensuousness, between inclination and duty, as the
reconciler of these elements in the obstinate conflict
and repulsion which their collision generates. But
the opinion may be maintained that, assuming such
aims of art, more serious though they are, nothing
is gained for reason and duty by the attempt
at mediation, because these principles, as essentially
incapable of intermixture, can be parties to no such
compromise, but demand in their manifestation the
same purity which they have in themselves. And it
might be said that art itself is not made any more
worthy of scientific discussion by such treatment,
seeing that it is still doubly a servant — to higher
aims, no doubt, on the one hand, but none the less
to vacuity and frivolity on the other; and in such
service can at best only display itself as a means,
instead of being an end pursued for its own sake.
Finally, art, considered as a means, seems to labour
under this defect of form, that, supposing it to be
subordinated to serious ends, and to produce results
of importance, still the means employed by art for
such purposes is deception. For beauty has its being
8 OBJECTIONS REFUTED. [Chap. I.
in appearance.* Now, it will readily be admitted that
an aim which is real and true in itself ought not to
be attained by deception, and if it does here and
there achieve some success in this way, that can
only be the case to a limited extent, and even then
deception cannot approve itself as the right means.
For the means should correspond to the dignity of
the end, and only what is real and true, not semblance
or deception, has power to create what is real and
true ; just as science, for instance, has to consider
he true interests of the mind in accordance with
the truth of reality and the true way of conceiving it.
In all these respects it may appear as if fine art
were unworthy of scientific consideration ; because,
as is alleged, it is at best a pleasing amusement, and
even if it pursues more serious aims is in contradiction
with their nature, but is at best the mere servant
alike of amusement and of serious aims, and yet has
at command, whether as the element of its being or
as the vehicle of its action, nothing beyond deception
and semblance.
y. But, in the second place, it is a still more prob-
able aspect of the question that, even if fine art were
to form a subject of philosophical reflections in a general
way, it would be no appropriate matter for strictly
scientific treatment. The beauty of art presents itself
to sense, to feeling, to perception, to imagination ; its
* " Das Schbne — in dem Scheine"
Chap. I.] IS ART UNSUITABLE FOR STUDY? 9
sphere is not that of thought, and the apprehension
of its activity and its productions demand another
organ than that of the scientific intelligence. More-
over, what we enjoy in the beauty of art is precisely
the freedom of its productive and plastic energy. In
the origination, as in the contemplation, of its crea-
tions we appear to escape wholly from the fetters of
rule and regularity. In the forms of art we seek for
repose and animation in place of the austerity of the
reign of law and the sombre self-concentration of
thought ; we would exchange the shadowland of the
idea for cheerful vigorous reality. And lastly, the
source of artistic creations is the free activity of fancy,
which in her imagination is more free than nature's
self. Not only has art at command the Avhole wealth
of natural forms in the brilliant variety of their ap-
pearance, but also the creative imagination has power
to expatiate inexhaustibly beyond their limit in pro-
ducts of its own. It may be supposed that, in presence
of this immeasurable abundance of inspiration and
its free creations, thought will necessarily lose the
courage to bring them completely before it, to criticize
them, and to array them under its universal formulas.
Science, on the contrary, every one admits, is com-
pelled by its form to busy itself with thought which
abstracts from the mass of particulars. For this reason,
on the one hand, imagination with its contingency
and caprice — that is, the organ of artistic activity and
io OBJECTIONS REFUTED. [Chap. I.
enjoyment — is of necessity excluded from science.
And on the other hand, seeing that art is what cheers
and animates the dull and withered dryness of the
idea, reconciles with reality its abstraction and its dis-
sociation therefrom, and supplies out of the real world
what is lacking to the notion, it follows, we may think,
that a purely intellectual treatment of art destroys
this very means of supplementation, annihilates it,
and reduces the idea once more to its simplicity
devoid of reality, and to its shadowy abstractness.
And further, it is objected that science, as a matter
of content, occupies itself with what is necessary. Now,
if ^Esthetic puts aside the beauty of nature, we not
only gain nothing in respect of necessity, but to all
appearance have got further away from it. For the
expression Nature at once gives us the idea of Neces-
sity and Uniformity,* that is to say, of a behaviour
which may be hoped to be akin to science, and
capable of submitting thereto. But in the mind, i
generally, and more particularly in the imagination, |
compared with nature, caprice and lawlessness are
supposed to be peculiarly at home ; and these with-
draw themselves as a matter of course from all scien-
tific explanation.
Thus in all these aspects — in origin, in effect, and
in range — fine art, instead of showing itself fitted for
scientific study, seems rather in its own right to resist
* " Gcsetzmassigkeit."
Chap. I.] BASIS OF THE OBJECTIONS. n
the regulating activity of thought, and to be un-
suitable for strict scientific discussion.
These and similar objections against a genuinely
scientific treatment of fine art are drawn from com-
mon ideas, points of view, and considerations, which
may be read ad nauseam in full elaboration in the
older writers upon beauty and the fine arts, especially
in the works of French authors. And in part they
contain facts which have a certain truth ; in part, too,
the argumentation * based upon these facts appears
plausible at first sight. Thus, e.g., there is the fact
that the forms of beauty are as manifold as the phe-
nomenon of beauty is omnipresent ; and from this, if
we choose, we may proceed to conclude to a universal
impulse of Beauty in human nature, and then go on
to the further inference : that because ideas of beauty
are so endlessly various, and therefore, as seems
obvious, are something particular,] it follows that
there can be no universal laws of beauty and of taste.
Before it is possible for us to turn from such
considerations to our subject proper, it is our busi-
ness to devote a brief introductory discussion to the
objections and doubts which have been raised. In
the first place, as regards the worthiness of art to be
* u Raisonnement" — a disparaging term in Hegel.
t " Particular " — different unconnected matters, considered as
merely thrown together in an aggregate, or occurring in a series ;
opposed to parts or cases united by an essential principle.
12 OBJECTIONS REFUTED. [Chap. I.
scientifically considered, it is no doubt the case that
art can be employed as a fleeting pastime, to serve
the ends of pleasure and entertainment, to decorate
our surroundings, to impart pleasantness to the ex-
ternal conditions of our life, and to emphasize other
objects by means of ornament. In this mode of
employment art is indeed not independent, not free,
but servile. But what we mean to consider, is the
art which is free in its end as in its means.
That art is in the abstract capable of serving other
aims, and of being a mere pastime, is moreover a
relation which it shares with thought. For, on the
one hand, science, in the shape of the subservient
understanding, submits to be used for finite purposes,
and as an accidental means, and in that case is not
self-determined, but determined by alien objects and
relations ; but, on the other hand, science liberates
itself from this service to rise in free independence
to the attainment of truth, in which medium, free from
all interference, it fulfils itself in conformity with its
proper aims.
Fine art is not real art till it is in this sense free,
and only achieves its highest task when it has taken
its place in the same sphere with religion and philo-
sophy, and has become simply a mode of revealing to
consciousness and bringing to utterance the Divine
Nature,* the deepest interests of humanity, and the
* "Das G'ottliche?
Chap. I.] ART NOT UNWORTHY.
most comprehensive truths of the mind. It is in
works of art that nations have deposited the pro-
foundest intuitions and ideas of their hearts ; and
fine art is frequently the key — with many nations
there is no other — to the understanding of their
wisdom and of their religion.
This is an attribute which art shares with religion
and philosophy, only in this peculiar mode, that it
represents even the highest ideas in sensuous forms,
thereby bringing them nearer to the character of
natural phenomena, to the senses, and to feeling.
The world, into whose depths thought penetrates, is a
supra-sensuous world, which is thus, to begin with,
erected as a beyond over against immediate con-
sciousness and present sensation ; the power which
thus rescues itself from the here, that consists in the
actuality and finiteness of sense, is the freedom of
thought in cognition. But the mind is able to
heal this schism which its advance creates ; it gene-
rates out of itself the works of fine art as the first
middle term of reconciliation between pure thought
and what is external, sensuous, and transitory, be-
tween nature with its finite actuality and the infinite
freedom of the reason that comprehends.
& The element of art was said to be in its general
nature an unworthy element, as consisting in appear-
ance and deception. The censure would be not
devoid of justice, if it were possible to class appear-
14 OBJECTIONS REFUTED. [Chap. I.
ance as something that ought not to exist. An
appearance o r show , hmvevpr, is pqse n fhl to e> dsfence.
Truth could not be, did it not appear and reveal
itself,* were it not truth for some one or something,
V for itself as also for Mind. Therefore there can be no
objection against appearance in general, but, if at all,
against the particular mode of appearance in which
art gives actuality to what is in itself real and true.
If, in this aspect, the appearance with which art gives
its conceptions life as determinate existences is to be
termed a deception, this is a criticism which primarily
receives its meaning by comparison with the external
world of phenomena and its immediate contact with
us as matter, and in like manner by the standard of
our own world of feeling, that is, the inner world of
sense. These are the two worlds to whiciv^ii the life
of daily experience, in our own -prreliomenal | We, we
are accustomed to attribute the value and -the title
of actuality, reality, and truth, in contrast to art,
which we set down as lacking such reality and truth.
Now, this whole sphere of the empirical inner and
outer world is just what is not the world of genuine
reality, but is to be entitled a mere appearance more
strictly than is true of art, and a crueller deception.
Genuine reality is only to be found beyond the
* u Schiene und erschiene."
t The life in which we treat common circumstances and
sensations as, in their degree, realities.
Chap. I.] ART NOT UNTRUE. 15
immediacy of feeling and o f external objects.
Nothing is genuinely real but that which is actual in
its own right,* that which is the substance of nature
and of mind, fixing itself indeed in present and
definite existence, but in this existence still retaining
its essential and self-centred being, and thus and no
otherwise attaining genuine reality. The dominion
of these universal powers is exactly what art ac-
centuates and reveals. The common outer and
inner world also no doubt present to us this essence
of reality, but in the shape of a chaos of accidental
matters, encumbered by the immediateness of sen-
suous presentation, and by arbitrary states, events,
characters, etc. Art liberates the . real import of
appearances from the semblance and deception of this
bad and fleeting world, and imparts to phenomenal
semblances a higher reality, born of mind. The
appearances of art, therefore, far from being mere
semblances, h ave th e_higher reality and the more
genuine existence in comparison with the realities of
common life.
Just as little can the representations of art be
called a deceptive semblance in comparison with the
representations of historical narrative, as if that had
the more genuine truth. For history has not even
immediate existence, but only the intellectual pre-
sentation of it, for the element of its portrayals, and
* " Das An — und Fiirsichseyende."
1 6 OBJECTIONS REFUTED. [Chap. I.
its content remains burdened with the whole mass of
contingent matter formed by common reality with its
occurrences, complications, and individualities. But
the work of art brings before us the eternal powers
that hold dominion in history, without any such super-
fluity in the way of immediate sensuous presentation
and its unstable semblances.
Again, the mode of appearance of the shapes pro-
duced by art may be called a deception in comparison
with philosophic thought, with religious or moral
principles. Beyond a doubt the mode of revelation
which a content attains in the realm of thought is the
truest reality ; but in comparison with the show or
semblance of immediate sensuous existence or of
historical narrative, the artistic semblance has the
advantage that in itself it points beyond itself, and
refers us away from itself to something spiritual
which it is meant to bring before the mind's eye.
Whereas immediate appearance does not give itself
out to be deceptive, but rather to be real and true,
though all the time its truth is contaminated and
infected by the immediate sensuous element. The
hard rind of nature and the common world give the
mind more trouble in breaking through to the idea
than do the products of art.
But if, on the one side, we assign this high position
to art, we must no less bear in mind, on the other
hand, that art is not, either in content or in form,
Chap. I.] ART NOT ULTIMATE TRUTH. 17
the supreme and absolute mode of bringing the
mind's genuine interests into consciousness. The
form of art is enough to limit it to a restricted con-
tent. Only a certain circle and grade of truth is
capable of being represented in the medium of art.
Such truth must have in its own nature the capacity
to go forth into sensuous form and be adequate to
itself therein, if it is to be a genuinely artistic content,
as is the case with the gods of Greece. There is,
however, a deeper form of truth, in which it is no
longer so closely akin and so friendly to sense as
to be adequately embraced and expressed by that
medium. Of such a kind is the Christian conception
of truth ; and more especially the spirit of our modern
world, or, to come closer, of our religion and our
intellectual culture, reveals itself as beyond the stage
at which art is the highest mode assumed by man's
consciousness of the absolute. The peculiar mode
to which artistic production and works of art belong
no longer satisfies our supreme [need. We are above
the level at which works of art can be venerated
as divine, and actually worshipped ; the impression
which they make is of a more considerate kind, and
the feelings which they stir within us require a
higher test and a further confirmation. Thought
and reflection have taken their flight above fine art.
Those who delight in grumbling and censure may
set' down this phenomenon for a corruption, and
C
1 8 OBJECTIONS REFUTED. [Chap. I.
ascribe it to the predominance of passion and selfish
interests, which scare away at once the seriousness
and the cheerfulness of art. Or we may accuse the
troubles of the present time and the complicated
condition of civil and political life as hindering the
feelings, entangled in minute preoccupations, from
freeing themselves, and rising to the higher aims of
art, the intelligence itself being subordinate to petty
needs and interests, in sciences which only subserve
such purposes and are seduced into making this
barren region their home.
However all this may be, it certainly is the case,
that art no longer affords that satisfaction of spiritual
wants which earlier epochs and peoples have sought
therein, and have found therein only ; a satisfaction
which, at all events on the religious side, was most
intimately and profoundly connected with art. The
beautiful days of Greek art, and the golden time
of the later middle ages are gone by. The reflective
culture of our life of to-day, makes it a necessity
for us, in respect of our will no less than of our
judgment, to adhere to general points of view, and
to regulate particular matters according to them, so
that general forms, laws, duties, rights, maxims arc
what have validity as grounds of determination and
are the chief regulative force. But what is required
for artistic interest as for artistic production is,
speaking generally, a living creation, in which the
Chap. I.] MODERN REFLECTIVENESS. 19
universal is not present as law and maxim, but acts
as if one with the mood and the feelings, just as,
in the imagination, the universal and rational is con-
tained only as brought into unity with a concrete
sensuous phenomenon. Therefore, our present in its
universal condition is not favourable to art. As
regards the artist himself, it is not merely that the
reflection which finds utterance all round him, and
the universal habit of having an opinion and passing
judgment about art infect him, and mislead him into
putting more abstract thought into his works them-
selves ; but also the whole spiritual culture of the
age is of such a kind that he himself stands within
this reflective world and its conditions, and it is
impossible for him to abstract from it by will and
resolve, or to contrive for himself and bring to pass,
by means of peculiar education or removal from the
relations of life, a peculiar solitude that would replace
all that is lost.
In all these respects art is, and remains for us,
on the side of its highest destiny, a thing of the past.
Herein it has further lost for us its genuine truth
and life, and rather is transferred into our ideas
than asserts its former necessity, or assumes its
former place, in reality. What is now aroused in
us by works of art is over and above our immediate
enjoyment, and together with it, our judgment;
inasmuch as we subject the content and the means
20 OBJECTIONS REFUTED. [Chap. I.
of representation of the work of art and the suita-
bility or unsuitability of the two to our intellectual
consideration. Therefore, the science of art is a much
more pressing need in our day, than in times in
which art, simply as art, was enough to furnish a full
satisfaction. Art invites us to consideration of it
by means of thought, not to the end of stimulating
art production, but in order to ascertain scientifically
what art is.
£. As soon as we propose to accept this invitation
we are met by the difficulty which has already been
touched upon in the suggestion that, though art is
a suitable subject for philosophical reflection in the
general sense, yet it is not so for systematic and
scientific discussion. In this objection there lies the
false idea that a philosophical consideration may,
nevertheless, be unscientific. On this point it can
only be remarked here with brevity, that, whatever
ideas others may have of philosophy and philoso-
phizing, I regard the pursuit of philosophy as utterly
incapable of existing apart from a scientific procedure.
Philosophy has to consider its object in its necessity,
not, indeed, in its subjective necessity or external
arrangement, classification, etc., but it has to unfold
and demonstrate the object out of the necessity of its
own inner nature. Until this evolution * is brought
to pass the scientific element is lacking to the treat-
* "Explication:"
Chap. I.] ART NOT UNSUITABLE. 21
ment In as far, however, as the objective necessity
of an object lies essentially in its logical and meta-
physical nature, the isolated treatment of art must
be conducted with a certain relaxation of scientific
stringency. For art involves the most complex pre-
suppositions, partly in reference to its content, partly
in respect of its medium * and element,! in which art
is constantly on the borders of the arbitrary or acci-
dental. Thus it is only as regards the essential
innermost progress of its content and of its media of
expression that we must call to mind the outline
prescribed by its necessity.
The objection that works of fine art elude the
treatment of scientific thought because they originate
out of the unregulated fancy and out of the feelings,
are of a number and variety that defy the attempt to
gain a conspectus, and therefore take effect only on
feeling and imagination, raises a problem which
appears still to have importance. For the beauty of
art does in fact appear in a form which is expressly
contrasted with abstract thought, and which the latter
is forced to destroy in exerting the activity which is f
its nature. This idea coheres with the opinion that,
reality as such, the life of nature and of mind, is
disfigured and slain by comprehension ; that, so far
* " Material" e.g. colour, sound, heavy matter, etc.
t " Element : " perhaps more especially any mental function
entering into art — sense, imagination, understanding, etc.
22 OBJECTIONS REFUTED. [Chap. I.
from being brought close to us by the thought which
comprehends, it is by it that such life is absolutely
dissociated from us, so that, by the use of thought as
the means of grasping what has life, man rather cuts
himself off from this his purpose. We cannot speak
fully on this subject in the present passage, but only
indicate the point of view from which the removal of
this difficulty, or impossibility depending on mal-
adaptation, might be effected.
It will be admitted, to begin with, that the mind is
capable of contemplating itself, and of possessing a
consciousness, and that a thinking consciousness, of
itself and all that is generated by itself. Thought —
to think — is precisely that in which the mind has its
innermost and essential nature. In gaining this
thinking consciousness concerning itself and its pro-
ducts, the mind is behaving according to its essential
nature, however much freedom and caprice those
products may display, supposing only that in real
truth they have mind in them. Now art and its
works as generated and created by the mind (spirit),
are themselves of a spiritual nature, even if their
mode of representation admits into itself the sem-
blance of sensuous being, and pervades what is
sensuous with mind. In this respect art is, to begin
with, nearer to mind and its thinking activity than is
mere external unintelligent nature ; in works of art,
mind has to do but with its own. And even if artistic
Chap. I.] THE MIND KNO WS ITS CREA TIONS. 23
works are not abstract thought and notion, but are an
evolution of the notion out of itself, an alienation from
itself towards the sensuous, still the power of the
thinking spirit (mind) lies^lierein, not merely to grasp
itself only in its peculiar form of the self-conscious
spirit (mind), but just as much to recognize itself in
its alienation in the shape of feeling and the sensuous,
in its other form, by transmuting the metamorphosed
thought back into definite thoughts, and so restoring
it to itself. And in this preoccupation with the other
of itself the thinking spirit i s not to be held un true to
itself as if forgetting or surrendering itself therein,
nor is it so weak as to lack strength to comprehend
what is different from itself, but it comprehends both
itself and its opposite. For the notion is the uni-
versal, which preserves itself in its particularizations,
dominates alike itself and its " other," and so becomes
the power and activity that consists in undoing the
alienation which it had evolved. And thus the work
of art in which thought alienates itself belongs, like
thought itself, to the realm of comprehending thought,
and the mind, in subjecting it to scientific considera-
tion, is thereby but satisfying the want of its own
inmost nature. Fo£_be£ajise_jthougJnMs_h^s_essence
and notion, it can in the last resort only be satisfied
when it ha^~slicceeoyed~lnimb uing a ll_t he produ cts of
its activity with thought, and has thus for the first
time - mlide~thehr~ gehuihely its own. But, as we
24 OBJECTIONS REFUTED. [Chap. I.
shall see more definitely below, art is far from being
the highest form of mind, and receives its true rati-
fication only from science.*
Just as little does art elude philosophical con-
sideration by unbridled caprice. As has already been
indicated, it is its true task to bring to consciousness
the highest interests of the mind. Hence it follows
at once with respect to the content that fine art cannot
rove in the wildness of unfettered fancy, for these
spiritual interests determine definite basest for its
content, how manifold and inexhaustible soever its
forms and shapes may be. The same holds true for
the forms themselves. They, again, are not at the
mercy of mere chance. Not every plastic shape % is
capable of being the expression and representation
of those spiritual interests, of absorbing and of repro-
ducing them ; e^ejx_d£fimte__c^ntent determines a
form suitable to jt
IrPErus - aspect too, then, we are in a position to
find our bearings according to the needs of thought
in the apparently unmanageable mass of works and
types of art.
Thus, I hope, we have begun by defining the
* " Philosophy," " WissenschaftP
t " Haltpunkte:" ultimate points that the matter of art
must not leave hold of, leading ideas that must somehow
dominate it.
% " Gcstaltiwg : " shaping, as if arrangement of shapes.
Chap. I.] ART NOT CAPRICIOUS. 25
content of our science, to which we propose to
confine ourselves, and have seen that neither is fine
art unworthy of a philosophical consideration, nor is
a philosophical consideration incompetent to arrive
at a knowledge of the essence of fine art.
CHAPTER II.
METHODS OF SCIENCE APPLICABLE TO BEAUTY
AND ART.
If we now investigate the required mode of scientific
consideration, we here again meet with two opposite
ways of treating the subject, each of which appears
to exclude the other, and so to hinder us from
arriving at any true result.
On one side we see the science of art merely, so to
speak, busying itself about the actual productions of
art from the outside, arranging them in series as a
history of art, initiating discussions about extant
works, or sketching out theories intended to provide
the general points of view that are to govern both
criticism and artistic production.
On the other side we see science abandoning
itself independently to reflection upon the beautiful,
and producing mere generalities which do not touch
the work of art in its peculiarity, creating, in short,
an abstract philosophy of the beautiful.
Chap. II.] ART-SCHOLARSHIP. 27
I. As regards the former mode of treatment, which
starts from the empirical side, it is the indispensable
road for any one who means to become a student of art.
And just as in the present day every one, even though
he is not busied with natural science, yet pretends to
be equipped with the essentials of physical know-
ledge, so it has become more or less obligatory for
a cultivated man to possess some acquaintance with
art,* and the pretension to display one's-self as a
dilettante and connoisseur is pretty universal.
(a) If such information is really to be recognized
as art-scholarship,f it must be of various kinds and
of wide range. The first necessity is an exact
acquaintance with the immeasurable region of
individual works of art of ancient and modern times,
works which in part have actually perished, in part
belong to distant countries or portions of the world,
or which adverse fortune has withdrawn from one's
own observation. Moreover, every work belongs to
its age, to its nation, and to its environment, and
depends upon particular historical and other ideas
and aims. For this reason art-scholarship further
requires a vast wealth of historical information of a
very special kind, seeing that the individualized
nature of the work of art is related to individual
detail and demands special matter to aid in its com-
prehension and elucidation. And lastly, this kind
* " Kunstkenntm'ss." t " Gelehrsamkeit?
2