'■•t ':■ " THE BRITISH ACADEMY Croce's Aesthetic By Bernard Bosanquet Fellow of the Academy I [I^rom the Proceedings of the British Academy; Vol. IX ^ London Published for the British Academy By Humphrey Milford, Oxford University Press Amen Corner, E.G. Price Tim Shillings net 3H CROCE'S AESTHETIC By BERNARD BOSANQUET FELLOW OF THE ACADEMY Communicated December 10, 1919 Art and Beauty are one and the same thing, and that thing is an experience of the human spirit. We might even say that it is the simplest of all such experiences, and the earliest. Whenever a human being concentrates his total feeling into an image which is at once its essence and its utterance, the spirit of art is awakened. Beauty, in other words, lives in the creative imagination, and there alone; and art is nothing more and nothing less than the experience which we call beauty. All else is irrelevant. True and false, real and unreal, good and bad, have no place in the aesthetic world. Here nothing counts but the perfection of the imaginative act in itself, and by its own standard. And this is in principle all that we need to know about the beautiful. It has no subdivisions within itself, and its manifestations array themselves in no kind of series. Aesthetic philosophy lies in explaining the rank of beauty among the experiences of the spirit, and in defending the simplicity of the principle against traditional but unjustified intrusions. This is the meaning of Croce's doctrine that beauty is expression. And that doctrine is sound. It does justice to the essential qualities of the beautiful ; to its spirituality and its simplicity. Wherever, it says, you find vision and utterance, there you have art and beauty. They may be on a great scale or a small, but they have one quality throughout. It is a real service for a man to have thrown the whole weight of his conviction into this principle, and through it to have asserted aesthetic theory as a plain and human thing, disembarrassed of traditional lumber, and addressed directly to the central interest of all who care for beauty. This service it appears to us that Croce has rendered, and it should not and will not be forgotten when the exaggerations by which he has endeavoured to emphasize it have gone the way they will go. For here, as elsewhere in his philosophy, it is impossibly not to ask IX H 2 IPtlOCP^i^iilis^^^.'OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY wiiy;t]Vef f,}iii/j)<,tr Hfha Has ^jven us so much has also taken so much away ; wh}', to set off his true and spirited outhne, he has thought it necessary to erase the whole supporting system. To understand this necessity, we must follow his argument step by step. The conceptions of Art and Beauty, which are for him coincident, are developed in his system by two constantly recurring terms, which are coincident both with the two former and with each other. These are Intuition and Expression. The term Intuition insists mainly on the simplicity of the artistic experience, and on its priority in the scheme of the spiritual forms, which two characteristics intimately involve one another. The term Expression insists on the distinctive quality of the^ constructive imagination by which ^-.rpressive activity is distinguished from the passivity which marks the impression. The two terms, being conjoined throughout as descriptive of the same experience, convev the conception that man's primary attitude to the world, before in the judgement of perception he discriminates the real from the unreal, is that of an intuition which is at once and inherently an imaginative expression.)^ He does not judge; he pictures, focuses, apprehends ideally in an image the matter pre- sented to his mind.7 Ideally, or imaginatively — for apprehension is ■ideal or imaginative when it portrays and does not affirm. Tliis intuition-expression, as he calls it, this primaiy self-conceiitration of the mind in something which without any intellectual character is none the less a determinate spiritual utterance — think, Croce would say, of the simplest imaginable phrase of love or song — this intuition-expression is the elementary type of art and beauty. Let it swell to a five-act tragedy, and include all the sayings of Hamlet and Polonius, yet the constituents take their characters from the whole, and the primary intuition is a primary intuition-expression still. The mind gathers up in it the state and the material which it feels driven to portray as a whole, but it makes no judgement of reality, and simply looks before it at the expression it has created. Here is a passage which emphasizes in connexion the simplicity and priority of the intuition. ' I observe in myself — that, in presence of any sensation whatever, if I do not abandon myself to the attractions and repulsions of instinct and feeling, if I do not permit myself to be distracted by reflections and reasonings, if I persist in the intuitive attitude, I am in that very disposition by means of which I enjoy what is commonly called a work of art. I live the sensation, but as a pure contemplative spirit. CROCKS AESTHETIC 3 In ordinary life, reflections and volitions follow like lightning on the sensations, and then follow other sensations and reflections and voli- tions. Bat however lightning quick that succession may be, it does not abolish the first instant, which must be one of pure intuition. That first instant, multiplying and expanding itself, forms the region of the life of art. Without that first instant, without the little spark, the great flame could not follow. Artists in the pre-eminent sense are those who have the power of persisting longer than others in the moment of pure sensation or intuition,^ and of inducing others to persist in it. Artists (as has been imaginatively observed) pre- serve the ingenuous and intent regard of the child ; remain remote and undistracted by practical preoccupations.' ^ This conception of the artistic intuition as something essentially primitive and prior in nature to intelligence and practice, while communicating a welcome emphasis to Croce's view of the simplicity and universality of art, is yet, in the systematic exaggeration which he imposes on it, the source of serious defects in his doctrine, which we must now consider. ( Intuition in Croce's theory is the primitive form of knowledge , he higher form of which is philosophy. To call it knowledge seems strange to us, as it is in its proper nature free from conceptual affirmation and so prior to the judgement of perception, and uncon- cerned with discrimination between real and unreal. On the other hand, it is inherent in Croce's whole theory that language, conceived as an expressive flux of tone and gesture, belongs to this primitive stage, and is in fact a thing identical with intuition. Its conceptual and conventional side belongs to logic and the judgement, and by dwelling on this we are led to misconceive the nature of speech, which is in truth far nearer akin to poetry than to logic. Art then, as prior and single, is independent. Art does not need the concept nor philosophy, but philosophy and the concept depend upon art, without which they would not possess the original flow of language — the poetry natural to man — on which their structure of universal meanings has to be erected. These, then, art and philosophy, are the two theoretical phases of the spirit. Above or beyond' these, in the sense of employing and depending upon them, are the two practical phases, the economic, that in which the particular person wills his particular end ; and the * As a rule Croce ranks pure sensation with impressions as a condition precedent of intuition or expression. 2 Prnhlptjti cli Kxfl^fira , p. 484. u2 4 PROCEEDINGS OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY ethical, in which the particular is expanded into the universal end of man and dominated by it. The practical forms depend on the theoretical, because will depends on knowledge ; the ethical on the economic, because you must have a will before you can have a good will. These four forms constitute the complete cycle of reality, of the spirit's phases, which are not united in any complete experience, but are traversed by the human mind in spirals,^ so to speak, in which every cycle recommences at the point of experience to which the race has been raised by that previously completed. Thus Croce by no means denies that art can absorb and include the products of conceptual thinking. It precedes all other experience, he would maintain, in a logical but not in a temporal sense. Never- theless, the idea of temporal precedence is influential in furnishing his theory with its primary type and ideal, as the passage which has been cited suffices to show. And from this idea there arises a series of conceptions, which, while they rhetorically reinforce his leading contention, really undermine and empty its substance. These con- ceptions draw out the consequences of reducing art and language to a common measure, the depth of which is prescribed by the conviction • which we have already observed in Croce, regarding the primitive intuition. The origin of this conviction, to which Croce continually recurs, and which he holds with extreme intensity, we find apparently in Vico's influence. In the spring of 1900 Croce communicated his htst paper on Aesthetic theory to the Academia Pontiana at Naples, and in April 1901 he published his first contribution to the history of the subject under the title ' Giambattista Vico primo scopritore della scienza estetica'', which twelve years later he developed into a complete study of Vico's philosophy. What concerns us here is Vlco's funda- mental attitude to poetry in its connexion with primitive language and primitive imagination. He adopts, or re-discovers, what our own Elackwell, an Aberdeen professor and late contemporary of Vico, speaks of as the ' Ancient Opinion that Poetry was before Prose '. But he intensifies it into a general theory of the origin of language in Song ^ and of the vast and profound imagination belong- ing to primitive men. ' The men of the world's childliood were by ^ This phrase is not to my knowledg'e used by Croce. ^ So Blackwell {Life of Homer , a. n. 1735), nvbav = (uiSew. Vico points out that men wlio stammer can often sing- witliout impediment^ which reminds us of an incident in one of Marryat's novels. CROCKS AESTHETIC 5 nature sublime poets.' ^ 'These two common errors of the gram- marians, that prose-writers'" language is proper, and tliat of Poets improper ; and that speech in prose came first, and verse afterwards.' ^ Croce is thoroughly permeated with the ideas here suggested, the former of which he insists on in his rejection of the rhetorical distinc- tion between bare and ornate language, and expands, as we shall see, into a general condemnation of doctrines which establish laws and classes in art and literature. Now we cannot venture to say that tliese suggestions of Vico determined the whole form of Croce's philosophy of the spirit, the theory, that is, of the successive grades of reality, related as we have described. But obviously this doctrine harmonizes with Vico's attitude, and is reinforced by it ; and we have now to consider the consequences which this fundamental orientation of his philosophy imposes upon Croce's aesthetic. It is a fundamental principle with him, embodied in the attitude which we have seen that he shares with Vico, that languao-e i^ identical with expression in the whole pregnancy of the term, that is, with intuition, art, and beauty. This reduction of art and language to a common measure depends on the idea of a phase of lin£2:uistic utterance in which logical meanina; and assertion have not yet appeared ; in which parts of speech are not distinguished, and words are not discriminated as signs for objects, each to each, but tlie dramatic flow of tone and gesture springs from the total state of mind like a song or an imaginative vision. That there is much truth in a view which insists upon such an aspect of language need not be questioned. It is 'familiar ground to us to-day that the sentence and not the w^ord is the linguistic unit. But to enable ourselves to say all that Croce says, not merely ' all language is expression ' but ' all expression is language ', it is obvious that we must not only insist upon this aspect of speech but must exclude every other. If language is to be intuition and expression in a sense level w^ith that in which these terms apply to all the utterances of art and embodiments of beauty, then logical affirmation and conceptual or conventional meaning must necessarily be banished from it. And this, we see at once, is the point in which Croce's scheme of degrees and Vico's equation of poetry and primitive speech converge and agree. We may put it thus. We are quite accustomed to say that all art and beauty are expression and ' speak a language '. We are then * VicOj Scien!::a Niiova : Degnitd (axiom); xxxvii, cf. Ixii. * Op. cit. ii. d\d9i^H 6 PROCEEDINGS OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY adopting a phraseology which has for us a strong and unmistakable significance derived from our familiarity with the definite and con- ventional usage by which the spoken or written sentence ' means "* to us something definite, other than itself. When we say that the music or the picture speaks a language to us we allude to this familiar quality with a modification distinctly understood. It speaks to us, we say, but we cannot put in words what it tells us. What it tells us cannot be told except by the music or the picture itself. It is not something outside them and separate. Even of a poem, which is in explicit words, we say the same. And we say it because tlie words of the poem have undergone a transformation, and no longer are mere words. They have been made part of a new whole, and have acquired a quality peculiar to them. But the general truth we are urging is this. When we say that the music or the picture speaks to us, but we cannot put in words what it says, we are referring to the significance of language, not in any partial value, but in its completeness. We employ the full conception of definite meaning, modified by a reservation which we believe ourselves clearly to understand, to help in explaining what it is that we experience in the intuition which we call art or beautv. Something, something of supreme value, we are sure, is communicated to us, though what it is w^e can only indicate by retraversing the actual communication, which differs in this respect from 'language"", that is, from the articulate discourse of ordinary life. Now when language is despoiled of its full capacity for significance, in order to equate it, to level it, with expression in general, the manoeuvre is self-destructive. Language has become a gesture or a tune, and to compare a tune or a gesture to language is now to compare a thing to itself. If expression, beauty, and language are taken in principle as prior to thought and explicit meaning, then the problem of beauty is treated as if it were solved, when in truth . it has not yet been raised. Beauty is not a datum but a transforma- tion ; not a gift at birth, but the achievement of an adult. We can see, however, the advantage which to Croce's masterful and, I had almost said, unscrupulous genius appeared to be off^ered by \'ico"'s attitude. Singleness was the gain ; the absolute annihilar tion of everything that could in the slightest degree appear to dictate from without to the self- creating expression which is beauty. To be rid of alien aims ; of instructiveness, moral or intellectual ; of pleasureableness ; of rank, dignity, and appropriateness in -the subjects selected for artistic expression ; to banish technical rules and the laws of stereotyped kinds ; to shake off even the dictatorship CROCKS AESTHETIC 7 of well-authenticated physical beauty considered as located in actual works of art or of nature — we can imagine the lelicf which came to so uncompromising a spirit from the idea that all this was to go, and that\nothing was to matter any more but the intuition of a mind that in a coherent imagination had found and satisfied itself,\ It is evident to an English reader that there must have been a struggle with traditions of rhetorical and literary criticism with which we are less familiar, and which imparted a zest and keenness to the work of repudiation. And this together with Croce's proneness to sweep- ing and unmodified conclusions goes far to account for the exaggera- tions and distortions, as they seem to us, into which his systematic doctrine impelled him. Singleness, we said, was the lure. Not even content, we add to our former statements, was to dictate to expression. You cannot lay it down that this theme must be treated thus, and that other in that other way. For apart from the expression the content does not exist. You cannot take the content as a burden or a trust, to which in some way justice has to be done or appropriate treatment meted out by a method and form to be contrived. Content and form are created pari passu ; the intuition or expression is the two in one. And this true doctrine I hope is not unfamiliar to us ; our great English students of fine art and poetry have shown I believe no disposition to ignore it. And yet, when we speak of expression, it is plain that sheer singleness, the singleness of priority and primitiveness, of the initial moment of sensation as it was portrayed for us above, cannot be the last word. Expression after ail is an empty name, unless there is a something to be expressed, in an utterance which bears a definite quality and character. We cannot here pursue at length a profound misinterpretation of which Croce has been guilty, because he will not admit that you may so much as say that art and beauty are the sensuous reflex of the spirit that lives in the world-life. If you have called it the reflex or semblance of anything, he seems to say, you have made it the vehicle of an idea, and then, because such a vehicle can be nothing but an inferior philosopliy, it must vanish and be absorbed when knowledge comes to its own.^ But this is the very madness of method. In all vision of beauty of course there is present and concentrated a shape and revelation of life, and though to dissolve it into sides of burden and utterance is to falsify it, yet to study its coherence as a whole and the mode and self-congruence of ' See Appendixj '^ Croce's view of •'the death of art" in Heg-el'. 8 PROCEEDINGS OF THE BRITISH ACADEJMY its harmony is both inevitable and desirable. Art is in truth the perpetual union of body and spirit, and to refuse to study the body in which it clothes itself betrays a bias which indicates a one-sided philosophy. Croce, in fact, denies the reality of the external world, and we shall see how this denial, advocated with vehement conviction, converges with the influences we have mentioned in his attitude to art. Now whether or no Croce's philosophical scheme was moulded initially by the impulse of Vico, there can be no doubt that, to go no further, the position which the latter assigns to art and intuition and with them to language in its simplest form is exaggerated by Croce into self-contradiction. The impulse to look to the primitive for the type of perfection is natural and recurrent, and is not without a certain rough justification. There are obvious obsessions of advancing civilization from which all that is nearer to the primitive seems relatively free, and it is a natural suggestion that by pursuing a regressive inquiry we shall come upon a phase of experience which shall be single, utterly expressive, and wholly free from alien pre- occupation and from analytic thought. Eut it cannot be so. The whole conception of antedating intuition and language by comparison with tlie logical affirmation and the concept or category is a nest of contradictions. Intuitions, we are told, are things, concepts are universals or relations.^ Things ! We can have intuitions of things, then, without concepts or categories, without the de facto woiking in our minds — questions of reflective recognition are here quite irrelevant — of the thoughts of identity, distinction, substance, whole and part. It is a complete absurdity. And so with language. We can have language, the poetry which is primitive speech, without the agreement upon the reference of signs — agreement with ourselves and with others — upon which the definite interpretation of language depends. Signs cannot be conventional in origin, because you nuist understand their reference, before you can agree upon their significance. And so we are told the belief in a conventional aspect of language drives you necessarily back to an original gift of God. The solution of this problem by the development of natural signs into conventional meanings, the inevitable result of co-operation in practice, seems not to have attracted Croce"'s attention. In fact, apart from an aspect of definite analysis by which meanings are broken up and re-constituted out of simpler meanings, the primary function of language, to communi- I ^ Estctica, p. 27. GROCERS AESTHETIC 9 cate to a mind what it does not know in terms of what it ah'eady knows, could not possibly be achieved,^ The primitive mind, so far from being purely contemplative and imaginative, is immersed in practice ; and at every moment it must demand communication through definite and separable elements of speech. ' Cross two rivers and turn upstream by the third.' How could primitive life be carried on without such communications as this ? And how could such a sentence convey useful advice if the points at which error is possible were not distinct and recognizable references ? The mood of art is a victory and an advance, a divergence which contemplates from a new and happier standpoint the determinate taskwork with which life begins. It is an extraordinary contradiction to appeal, as Croce does more than once, to the contrast, already remarked by Aristotle, between the logical assertion or proposition and the sentence which utters a wish or command. Croce takes this to mean that the former alone had a significance according to agreement, while the latter could be a type of the primitive poetry which he thinks of as free from such meaning and prior to it. But both kinds of sentence alike, though one of them is not assertory, have of course ' conventional ' or logical significance, and it was to clench this point that I used an imperative as my illustration. (^Language, in short, is not language without its conceptual side ; and to equate language with intuition, and treat intuition as prior to thinking, is to shatter and overthrow the whole conception of a unity of the human mind. ': The exaggeration which we have been criticizing is summed up in Croce's favourite identification of Aesthetic Philosophy with the general science of language. The problems of linguistic, so far as they are philosophical, are the same, he continually urges, with the problems of Aesthetic. Language is truncated by the rejection of its logical aspect, and its name is reduced to an indication that some- how, when the mind finds relief and completeness in an utterance, an intuition, or an expression — we may hardly say, a communication — is achieved. The problems of the acquisition of definite meaning, or of the degree in which aflfirmation asserts reality, are set aside. All problems, on the other hand, which concern the theory of art — for example, we must suppose the question whether the human imagina- tion reveals a progress in its creation of beauty — are swept into the province of 'general linguistic". Many matters which we should consider to be problems of aesthetic — the nature and relations, for instance, of comedy and tragedy — are indeed excluded from the ^ Stout J Manual of Psychology, pp. 595 fF. h3 10 TROCEEDINGS OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY philosophy of art by the limitations which Croce imposes on it. But enough remain, it would seem, to make it a serious paradox that they should be assigned to the philosophy of language. The moment we look at language in its full significance we see that to identify its problems with those of the theory of art is an absurdity. I Croce rejects, we said, the reality of the external \vorld.^J With this rejection, the singleness of the intuition-expression is forcibly intensified. In art, it is usually felt and held, there is in some sense an inner and outer. True, beauty lies in imagination and not in physical character, but yet the striving for expression seems to be a striving to give outward reality to something from within. To any such feeling of an inner and an outer in art or beauty Croce will not yield a hair's breadth. The. -external world is not real at all; art is the most real of things. How then can art become a part of the external world, or be in any way concerned with physical processes or media ? The ' work of art ' then, picture, statue, musical performance, printed or spoken poem, is called so only by a metaphor. It belongs to the practical (economic) and not to the aesthetic phase of the spirit, and consists merely in expedients adopted by the artist as a practical man, to ensure preservation and a permanent possibility of reproduction for his imaginative intuition. The art and beauty lie primarily in his imagination and secondarily in the imagination of those to whom his own may communicate its experience. The picture or the music are by themselves neither art nor beauty nor intuition- expression.^ Thus all embodiment in special kinds of physical objects by help of special media and special processes is wholly foreign to the nature of art and beauty. Every expression is single and individual. There is nothing to be learned from the practical means by help of which intuitions of beauty receive permanence and communicability. The whole of Lessing's line of inquiry is futile. Expression does not fall into classes and types ; neither according to the media employed in externalizing it, nor according to any other principle of division. There are no limits of the arts.^ There are indeed no arts dis- tinguishable in accordance with the philosophy of beauty. The distinction, for example, of sound and colour is purely empirical. The inner vision, the intuition which is expression, is the experience ' See account of stages of expression and externalization. Estetica, p. 113, ^ There is some laudatory criticism of writers \^■llose prose is like verse or like painting in Scritti di .storiu kttcniria, x. 342. CHOCKS AESTHETIC 11 of beauty. Or better, there is no question of inner or outer. The outer world is an abstract construction of physicists in order to explain and deal practically with our experiences. You cannot translate intuitions into tern)s of it. We see how this philosophy reinforces Croce's devotedness to the undivided expression. But the contention seems on the way to become ridiculous. It has destroyed our meeting point with ourselves and others in linguistic signiKcance, and now it offers to destroy our medium of intercourse thz'ough the body and through natural objects. True, an object not experienced cannot be the experience of beauty. True, we hope and believe that all, which we call body, is in some sense an incarnation of the spirit. Nevertheless, it is an incarnation, and is not a mere state of mind. We experience natural objects as full concrete existences, with real qualities of colour and sound and splendour. Externality is a character of the world and a sign and vehicle of spiritual achievement, and there can be no doubt tiiat the creative imagination yearns towards externality, and externality in some special medium. Indeed, as we have seen, Croce's whole heart is set on insisting that there is no jot or tittle of content in our imagination beyond what has passed into expressive form, and that it is self-deception to su{)pose that we possess a mental store of beauty which only a lack of physical skill prevents us from translating into outwardness. » * If you really had the thoughts, you would have coined them into as many beautiful ringing words.' ^ ' You are confronted with the reality of your imagination, when you are set to traverse the asses' bridge of expression — s};eak, or, here is a pencil, draw, we shall say to you." ^ Now on this side all is clear, and we claim no imagination Avhich is not fused with expressive form. But has not Croce here committed himself also on the other side ? Is not, in this latter sentence, externalization at least the test, if not the essence, of ex- pression ? Can the art-impulse, which is complete only in lines, colours, words, and tones,^ be content before it has realized them in determinate objects of sense .'* The external object, certainly, is not imagination ; but can imagination complete itself without the external object ? Croce tells us himself, ' When our music is really music, it quavers in the throat and thrills along the fingers, as they run over an ideal keyboard '."^ Is this yearning of soul and body for complete determinateness in the world of sense-perception nothing but the practical man's precaution that his expression may not be lost.-^ » Edetku, p. 12. ^ lb., p. 14. Mb., p. 11. * Brcviurio di E-bWlica, p. 5G. H 4 ^ 12 PROCEEDINGS OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY Surely the simple fact is that the external world of sense-perception, though we may call it a form of the spirit, is yet a peculiar and distinctive form, with a function wliich nothing can replace ; and the noblest part of this function is to be the medium to ourselves and to others of the special discipline and determination with and by which the artistic imagination is formed. We may consider the art of music. Apart from the special discipline and experience which the instrument aifords, the special world of purified sound in which the musical imagination is exercised and educated could hardly have existence for it at all. To reject the function of the body — our own and nature's — is not to honour but to bereave the spirit. The truth is, surely, that different inclinations of the spirit have affinities with different qualities and actions of body— meaning by body that which a sane philosophy accepts as concretely and com- pletely actual in the world of sense-perception. The imagination of the particular artist is , like the dyer's hand Subdued to what it works in, and its intuition and expression assume a special type in accordance with the medium it delights in, and necessarily develop certain capacities, and acknowledge, however tacitly, certain limitations- Croce has remarked indeed that painting, for example, is not solely concerned with visual expression, but can raise softness, coolness, or keenness to the level of beauty. But this is irrelevant. What has beauty may concentrate in itself all the qualities of life ; but it is not every quality of life that can form the vehicle of beauty ; nor can everything that is capable of beauty present the spirit of life in the same aspect and mood. After all, then, it is necessary for philosophy to study the specialities and limits of the arts ; for in considering them we are considering the qualities and aspects of the human spirit ; nay more, of the spirit which is in the world. If you know or can feel how the beauty of bronze — that is, its expressive capacity — di-ffers from the beauty of marble, you are on the way to understand the diverging beauties of the arts ; and if you insist on neglecting these affinities of the spirit, your theory remains abstract, and has no illuminating power. And one thing more you lose, almost the greatest thing of all. Vou lose all sympathy with the spirit which is in nature. For you have forbidden yourself to think of it as a real revelation of the heart of things, though needing to be apprehended by man's appre- ciative imagination. And you come to account for it as a reproduction, GROCERS AESTHETIC 13 by association with a physical stimulus, of some expression which you have experienced before. You impose yourself on nature, and do not submit your spirit to hers ; and so you condemn yourself to say that ' she is stupid in comparison with art, and is dumb if man does not make her speak \^ If indeed the properties of what is 'outer' were separable and distinct from what is ' inner ', the repudiation of the former would be plausible. But Croce's passionate insistence on the inner deter- minate expression recoils upon him, as we have amply seen, when he comes to reject the necessity of outer determinateness. For it is perfectly plain that the inner — the imaginative vision — depends upon the outer, and that the human spirit, as is just and right, attains its greatness and its clearness only by going to school to the spirit of the universe in all its manifestations. In music we saw a decisive example of this; and in visual art the 'innocence of the eye' may be indeed a second childhood, but probably there never was a first corresponding to it. Practical necessities have taught us to see things ' as they are ', before we have had leisure and interest to see them as they genuinely appear. Here again the ideal of singleness and priority leads us astray. To love and to see the semblance is a victory and not a beginning. The spirit of the universe may be revealed in the spirit of man, but certainly not apart from man's intercourse with his surroundings ; and his imagination, already fashioned by disci- pline under the spirit that is in the outer world, feels itself incomplete until in union with the most perfect bodily effort it has created an example of complete self-determination in one of the vehicles which that world supplies. We have merely to think of the effort of song or of passionate speech to realize this creative outward pressure of soul and body as a whole. We may set against each other no doubt the saying of Leonardo, ' The more of bodily labour any art demands, the less is it honourable ', and the words of Mr. Ruskin, ' All art is athletic'. It is not difficult to interpret the balance of body and mind — the fine adjustment and intense concentration — which taken together they suggest. The beauty of physical objects, we agree, is the experience which they suggest to a human imagination. But where Croce argues at length ^ that such beauty, because relative to variety of cases, is sub- jective and unreal, we are confronted with the hoariest of fallacies. If anything is certain in philosophy it is that an experience varying relatively with the variation of conditions is an experience that ^ Breviario, pp. GO-1. * Edetku, c. xiv. 14 PROCEEDINGS OF THE BKITISH ACADEMY indicates a reality. By such an argument, as we have seen, we shut our souls against the world spirit, and refuse to submit to his teaching. Thus the ideal of pure singleness in expression and intuition has- led us to the point that, because there is in beauty no content dis- tinct from the expression, there is therefore in the whole expressed, and in the total gamut of expressive forms, no life or spirit \vhose character concentrates itself in their quality and shaping. We have abandoned all regard for the respective affinities which fuse the spirifs utterance Avith the se\eral splendours of sense-perception. And we are now to see, further, how we lose all interest in the ordered variations of the expressive quality itself — the subdivisions of the beautiful and the transition which connects it with the ugly — and the shapes and patterns of poetry which the various visions of life have forged for themselves and are for ever forging anew. An over-strained emphasis on the distinction, in principle obsolete, between what is philosophical and what is empirical, will aways bring us into peril of nominalism and particularism. And so we find it here. 'Sublime' (and comic, tragie, humoristic, &c.) 'is all that which has been or shall be so named^ by those who have employed or who shall employ these words.' ^ These distinctions, that is to say, are not philosophical. They are only what we find essential to apprehending the special and characteristic values in which beautiful expression arrays itself. So again : ' He who speaks of tragedies, comedies, dramas, romances, genre paintings, battle pieces, landscapes, sea pieces, poems, idylls, lyrics, and so forth — certainly says nothing scientifically erroneous, because he is employing names and phrases, not establishing definitions.' (The 'laws' of kinds of literature, considered as rigid imperative rules, are his great hete noire, which shows, as I noted above, that he is partly incensed by the prevalence of traditions which have become unfamiliar to us.) These distinctions he goes on to compare with the arrangement of books in bookcases according to their format or publisher's series — a useful arrangement, but without literary significance ! We will say a word upon each of these classifications. First it is to be noted that the doctrine of sheer simplicity in expression destroys what a philosopher might call the dialectic of expressiveness ; that is to say, the tendency of distinctions of quality to arise through the presence of something which is felt as entering into, breaking through, or breaking down, the unity of the imagina- tive utterance. ^ Croce's italics. * Estetica, p. 106. CROCK'S AESTHETIC 15 Thus the difference between the merely beautiful and the sublime is for Croce no question of aesthetic, but a verbal and fallacious distinction, arising from what he classes under the heresy of aesthetic hedonism, namely the restriction of beauty as such to the sympathetic or what is immediately pleasing. The beautiful being for him coex- tensive with expression, and equated with the aesthetically excellent? admits of no subdivision into more facile and more difficult types, such as beauty par excellence, the sublime, the terrible^ and the grotesque. And this extension of the term beauty to the whole province of the aesthetically excellent is in harmony, I believe, with the best artistic feeling, and if this were all that he maintained, Croce's position, as is often the case with him in the advocacy of very general truths, would be exceedingly strong. But when he denies all aesthetic value to the distinction, within the general region of beauty, between the simply beautiful and the sublime, he is influenced by the ideal which destroys for him the dialectic of expression. There can be little question that in some intuitions of beauty there is a felt or threatened interruption to the perfectness of the harmony, such as itself to be expressive of a presence which no vehicle of manifestation can altogether contain.^ We cannot here go further into the theory of the sublime, but it is easy to see that it is a variation of the beautiful dependent on a negative^ factor in the. expression demanded in some experiences by the spirit of the whole. An analogous dialectic connects the beautiful with the ugly, and here it is interesting to note how an imperfect recognition of the particular mode in which the one is negative towards the other introduces confusion into Croce's account of both. The question about ugliness which stares a student of aesthetic in the face is whether or no it is an aesthetic quality — whether it is to beauty as evil to good, or merely a vacancy and an absence. /Croce 's primary position is laid down thus : ' It is idle to speak, as does the doctrine which confines beauty to the sympathetic, of ugliness in art. For us there is no ugliness but the anti-aesthetic or the inexpressive, which can never form part of the^aesthetic fact, being on the other hand its contrary and antithesis."' ^[ Now it is difficult for a contrary and antithesis not to be something of an invader ; it is not quite the same as a contradictory and privation.>> And so we are not surprised to find that where you have the spiritual fact of expression you have a bipartition between the poles of the beautiful and the ugly,^ which, thus, I take it, is after all held to be an aesthetic quality. And we ^ e.g. Bradley, Oxford Lectures on Poetry, p. 58. 2 Edetku, p. 104. ' lb., i)p. 112-13. lA 16 PROCEEDINGS OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY further find that ugliness implies the presence of some element of beauty ; for if no such element were present the ugly would lose the self-contradictory quality which is its essence, and falling outside the aesthetic frontier (so I understand the passage) would cease to be ugly.^ A clearer case of ugliness and one which seems to us best to elucidate its natui-e as an aggressive contrary within aesthetic terri- tory — ' aesthetic ugliness ' Croce himself calls it — is that in which the would-be artist has ' nothing of his own to express, but attempts to cover his inward emptiness with a flux of words, with sonorous verse, with deafening polyphony, with dazzling colour — all without meaning. The ugly is the arbitrary, the charlatanesque — it is due to the inter- vention of the practical will in the theoretic function, and without this you might have absence"^ of beauty, but you could never have anything effective which should merit the name of the ugly.' ^ You create, that is, a something which both is and is not aesthetic. One other case will complete the account. 'There are uglinesses and beastlinesses {tnrpitudini) in the world, and as long as this is so they will impose themselves on the artist and the correlative ex- pressions will arise. But these expressions a true critic, in opposition to the vulgar, will recognize as beautiful.' ^ It is clear that in these various cases of the ugly, as in the sublime, and, we shall further see, in comedy and tragedy, we are dealing with a connexion between expression and something to be expressed. The cases can only be brought into intelligible order if we recognize the conception of conflicts and collisions within the life which takes shape in art, giving rise, in the expressions which it creates, to intuitions in which conflict is explicit but wholly reconciled, or announces itself through a hinted restraint or check in the artistic structure, or dominates with its falsehood the entire utterance, fashioning it into an involuntary cari- cature — a tawdry imitation — of something which truly expressed would have been great or strong. Some such relations as these obviously subsist between the tragic along with other types of difficult beauty, the sublime, and the ugliness which disguised as an aesthetic quality, or entangled with one, invades the aesthetic province. And finally we may test the doctrine which expels from aesthetic * philosophy the consideration of literary genera, by some reference to the recent discussions of tragedy, comedy, and the distinction between poetry and prose. To begin with the latter. ' In fact,' Croce tells us, ' the two ex- 1 Estetieu, p. 93. * lb., p. 115. ' lb., p. 99. CROCKS AESTHETIC 17 pressions (poetry and prose) qua expressions, are of the same nature, and they both have the same aesthetic value ; because, if the poet is the lyrical singer (lirico) of his own feelings, the prose writer is no less the lyrical singer (lirico) of his own, that is to say, a poet, though it be with reference to feelings which arise in him from the research and in the research of the idea (as opposed to the intuition). There is no reason to concede the quality of poet to the composer of a sonnet and to deny it to the composer of the Mctaphysic, the Summa Theohgica, the Phenomenology of Mind,'' or to Thucydides and Tacitus,^ &c. All this springs from the doctrine we have noted throughout. Expression is individual and indivisible ; there is nothing to observe of its correlation or adapted variation in view of anything to be expressed. It would be an injustice to the subject if we were here to reproduce imperfectly the study which one of our finest critics devoted not long ago to the meaning of verse as returning or repeating language, as opposed to the language of prose which moves on Avithout any such return or repeat.^ ' The essence of poetry is that it is patterned language.' It is the repeating and yet continuous pattern in language which makes it technically poetry, and its substantial and vital function is to make patterns out of life. And with this mere reference we may leave the subject ; only pointing out that here as everywhere to the philosophical critic the study of expression in correlation with what is expressed is endlessly fruitful in the revelation of organic and inherent variations, and a doctrine which demands its rejection stands self-condemned. A word on the ideas which emerge from' the consideration of Tragedy and Comedy will lead us to a suggestive conclusion, bearing upon yet another aspect of Croce's aesthetic conceptions. Tragedy and comedy correspond to' a certain type of pattern which art in their case finds in or weaves out of life. They work in a certain medium, which is the stage, and their action is what can be acted. They have in common a certain tension and concentration ; ' a problem, we may say, is in each case set and solved.' These characters are inherent and essential ; they spring from the relation of the art- function to certain characters of life.^ Other modes of pattern-making are possible ad infinitum, who can doubt it ? It is in contrast with such another mode that in the study I am referring to these characters are emphasized. But we repeat — relative variation is no proof of arbitrariness ; to a philosophy that knows its business, it is the sure indication of reality. ^ Breviario, p. 93. * Mackail, Lectures on Poetry, pp. 12 ff. ^ Miickailj op. vAi., p. 211. 18 PROCEEDINGS OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY About tragedy, where it differs from comedy, there is also much to be said which has essential truth. \VJK're Aristotle and Hejjel have given us of their best, and recent criticism has pursued the study on the highest level, ^ it seems an impoverishment of life to argue that in principle the distinction of these forms is valueless. But there is an essential distinction between Comedy and Tragedy. 'When Dante (in speaking of the Divina Cornmed'ia) wrote Siihiectuvi operis est homo, one can hardly doubt that he had in his mind, consciously or sub-consciously, the famous line of the Terentian comedy, the Homo sum, hiimani nihil a me aliemon puto of Chremes, which is the complete and permanent motto of comedy itself.' *Comedia\ the same writer quotes from John of Salisbury, 'est vita hominis super terram,' and after further quotations he continues : 'The great truth upheld in, latent in, these fragmentary but illu- minating sentences is that in the evolution of poetry, comedy tends to displace tragedy, or tragedy to mei'ge in a higher and wider Tragi-comedy. Only in that larger and wider scope can the ex- pression of life be given, the pattern and interpretation of life be found. All the more tense and exclusive forms of poetry gradually translate themselves into a larger pattern and looser texture.''^ And finally, we are to feel that in the Aeneid itself 'there is a something which transcends art, properly so called,^ for the function of art is to create and embody some image of perfection ; and the image which Virgil finally sets before us is of imperfection ; the wist- fulness, the haunting trouble of its poetry, is of its inmost quality.'' ' That transcendence, that continued search further and further after what cannot be found, that stretching out of the hands (to use his own words rather than those of any later appreciation) in love of a further shore, is not consistent with the requirements of a complete and finished work of art.' The evolution from tragedy in the direction of the larger and looser texture which is characteristic of comedy in the widest sense, or of romance; the transcendence of the limits of art just when the summit appears to have been attained — who that is familiar with the theory of Hegel will feil to recognize, in the finer and subtler design of the critic of to-day, the impulse of transformation which the philosopher's insight detected ? Here is what Hegel intended when he portrayed the longdrawn dissolution or resolution of art, as it passed Irom the age and habit of classical tradition to the freedom ^ A. C. Bradley, Oxford Lectures on Poctri/; Shakesperiun T raged ij. CROCKS AESTHETIC 19 and fullness, or the constant verge of self-transcendence, which belongs to the modern artist. As Mr. Mackail applies to the Shakespeare of the romantic plays Virgil's crowning address to Dante, so we might apply it to the free and modern artist as Hegel portrays him.^ And in Croce's mis- conception which has fatally obscured for hiiYi Hegel's gi'eat work of insight, and has reiteratedly impeached the profoundest student of beauty with teaching as a truth and necessity that art's life has reached its term, and the hour of its dissolution, which is its death, has come,^ we see the reaction of the fatal pursuit of singleness, which insists that to assign a meaning to expression is to turn it into bare philosophy. The truth is surely other. Schiller was right, and to love and look at the appearance for its own sake, which is for the sake of its meaning, is not a primitive gift, but perhaps man's most typical self- conquest on the path to civilization. It is well to proclaim the unity of beauty and the autonomy of the shaping imagination ; but it is not well to disregard the fact which forms the glory of art, that in it alone the body of man and of nature rushes to meet the soul in a splendour which springs from both, and every pai*ticle of which is charged with siunificance. Bernard Bosanquet. ^ Aesthetik, ii. 232. "^ Croce, Scritti di storia letteraria, x. 306 and passim. The phrase ' death of art', which Croce constantly cites as if verbatim from Hegel, does not, so far as I know, occur iu his writings. It is, I presume, a mistranslation oi Avftosuug der Kuitst, APPENDIX ON CROCKS CONCEPTION OF THE 'DEATH OF ART^ IN HEGEL Considerable interest attaches to the problem raised by a hostile criticism of Hegel's aesthetic theory, which Croce repeats, so to speak, at the top of his voice, throughout the whole range of his writings. The statement has passed unchallenged in English critical literature, although it concerns no mere question of technical philosophy, but the appreciation of a whole aspect of beauty, in his vision of which Hegel was right, and profound, and in harmony with what our best recent critics have taught us. Here is the statement in its fullest form.^ ' (For Hegel) the artistic activity is distinguished from the philo- sophical solely by its imperfection, solely because it grasps the Absolute in sensible and immediate form, whereas philosophy grasps it in the pure element of thought. Which implies, logically, that it is not distinguished at all, and that art, for Hegel, reduces itself substantially, whether he will or no, to a philosophical error, an illusory philosophy. The true art, then, must be philosophy, which re-proposes to itself the same problem on which the other [art] labours in vain, and resolves it in a {)erl'ect manner. That such is Hegel's genuine thought is proved by the fact that he does not repudiate the extreme consequence of this theory ; when philosophy is completely developed, art must disappear, as a super- fluity ; art must die, and, moreover, is to-day stark dead {hella e viorta). If it is an error, it is not necessary and eternal. The history of art, as Hegel traces it, is directed to exhibit the progressive dissolution of artistic form, which, in modern times, no longer pertains to our true and profound interest ; it is a past, or a survival of the past. This immense paradox illuminates HegePs aesthetic error in all its detail ; and better perhaps than any other example, ekicidates the error of the logical presupposition itself. It has been said, in defence of Hegel, that the death of art, of which he speaks, is that eternal dying which is an eternal rebirth ; as it is observed in the spirit of man, when from poetry it makes a transition to philo- sophy, from intuition exalts itself to the universal, and thereupon the world of intuitions loses its visible hues. But contradicting this intei-pretation there is the fact that Hegel speaks of a death oi art, not perpetually renewing itself, but, strictly, as happening and ^ Croce^ Saggio suUo Hvgel, p. 89. CROCE'S AESTHETIC 21 having happened ; of a death of art in the world of history. And this is fully in agreement with his treatment of the grades of reality as if they were a series of opposites,* infelicitously abstracted and dissevered. Given this application which he made of the dialectic, Hegel was left no choice but either to suppress art by that immense paradox, or to preserve it by an inconsistency no less immense.'' ^ This and many similar passages raise two questions, one of logical necessity, one of historical judgement. I believe that it can be shown briefly and finally that the author is wrong in his answer to both. Hegel was under no logical necessity to infer the death of fine art ; and in his historical judgement he affirmed not that, but some- thing very different, which is still of interest. 1. Croce himself has formulated an unanswerable criticism on the inference which he here asserts that Hegel is logically compelled to draw. ' On the assumption that art is a necessary grade of the spirit, to question whether art is eliminable would be neither more nor less than like asking whether sensation or intelligence is eliminable.' Now why does he launch this as a criticism against Hegel, instead of advancing it as an interpretation of Hegel's view? The answer is indicated in my quotation. It is because, in theory, Hegel treats the phases of experience as degrees of completeness in the characterization of reality, and because, in fact, as we shall see directly, Croce mis- translates and misreads Hegel's historical judgement upon *the dissolution of art '. The former point could only be explained with completeness in a logical discussion.^ But the net result is this. Croce thinks that if you treat the forms of experience as terms in a logical progress towards perfection, you have committed yourself to regard them as no more than logical abstractions, of which every earlier is absorbed and included without remainder in every later term. He seems unable to employ the conception of a system whose members, just because each implies a logical progress to some other, are constituent factors of it, as well as degrees of its perfection. Croce's own * grades of the spirit' are not ' degrees of reality ', although ^ ' Opposite ' concepts are for Croce such as ' true ' and ' false ' ; ' distinct ' concepts are such as ' true ' and ' beautiful '. His technical criticism is that Hegel treats the latter just like the former, and therefore as inadequate on one side at least. Croce's own doctrine is difficult to reconcile with his account of the stimulus to progress from phase to phase of the spirit. Breviaiio di Estetica, p. 82. ^ Compare Estetica, p. 70. 3 Estetica, p. 76. The passage is directed, I take it, against Hegel's and kindred views, though his name is not tliere mentioned. * tSee Mind, Octol)er, 1'J18, review of C^roce's logic. 22 PROCEEDINGS OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY he makes use of this expression. They are successive and alternative phases of spiritual activitity, and each contains in itself no logical demand for advance or completion beyond itself and towards any other. Thus when Hegel exhibits fine art as continuous with religion, which is its complement, and both of them together as experiences which demand a fuller understanding in philosophy, and apart from which philosophy would itself be incomplete, Croce holds himself entitled to infer that when philosophy comes on the scene the other two are taken to be ipso facto swallowed up and annulled, as the Ptolemaic by the Newtonian astronomy. But this whole reading of HegePs logical method is erroneous. The phases of experience which reveal relative approximations to completeness are not successive in time nor vanishing in logic. Croce's own observation above cited shows the absurdity of trying to take them so. As factors implying the whole system and implied in it they are grades of the spirit in the fullest sense. The absolute is the whole which they constitute, and if any of them were eliminated would be the absolute no longer.^ If art finds its completion in philosophy, then a philosophy lacking the peculiar experience of art is an incomplete philosophy. One might as well argue that philosophy must be taken to supersede and become a substitute for life or being. Thus the defence of HegePs view, to Avhich Croce refers in the passage quoted above, has a sound logical basis, which in his version is insufficiently explained. The terms of a logical progression whose mainspring is the spirit of an immanent whole, must necessarily tend each to pass beyond itself, into the more complete terms which succeed it, while each nevertheless retains its being as in itself an irreplaceable experience. Croce knows no immanent whole, no systematic unity W'hich is the mainspring of a logical advance towards the definition of an inclusive perfection. And therefore he can understand no logical advance which does not supersede whatever came before it. 2. On the question of HegePs de facto historical judgement the evidence leaves no room for doubt. The points can be stated very shortly. (1) The phrase 'the death of art\ which Croce reiterates as if a verbal quotation, does not occur in the sixteen hundred pages of ' On tlie absolute as the inclusive whole of its stages, cf. Hegel, Encyclopaedia, sect. 237. CROCKS AESTHETIC 23 HegePs Lectures on Aesthetic and I do not believe that it occurs anywhere in his woi'ks. It probably represents a mistranslation of the term ' Auflosung' encouraged by the logical misunderstanding eluci- dated above. This word has a pregnant meaning of great interest, Avhich we will examine below, (2) The general relation of philosophy to life in Hegel's theory excludes the possibility of an historical judgement which involves a prediction, such as that of the non-persistence of art in human life. All students are aware that for Hegel philosophy explains but does not predict. It is needless to labour this point further. It is. however, interesting to note that as a mere illustration Hegel does at . one point permit himself to speak of the future of epic poetry, and expresses the opinion that the necessary national contrast for a great war epic of the future could only be found in the relations between America and Europe, and not within the European complex of peoples.^ It is plain that the disappearance of art from human experience has never occurred to his mind. The same ridiculous mistake is frequently made by neglect of the same principle, about his view of the historical succession of peoples in the leadership of the world. Philosophy for him deals with the past and present. He actually mentions America as the country of the future, and as, being so regarded, no subject for philosophy. ^ (3) The citation of texts almost weakens an argument which depends on the appreciation of a philosopher's entire attitude and systematic convictions ; but so far as any expression can be decisive, the following words, the authenticity of which there is no reason to doubt, forming the close of the Introduction prefixed to his posthu- mous Lectures on Aesthetic, appear to settle the question of his de facto belief and opinion. ' What, therefore, the particular arts bring into being in individual works of art are according to their notion only the universal forms of the self-developing idea of beauty, as whose external realization there is rising the immense Pantheon of art, whose architect and director is the self-recognizing spirit of the beautiful, but which to complete, the world-history will require its evolution of millennia."' ^ (4) And the question is set at rest finally and in detail, as it seems to me, by the elaborate and most interesting discussion devoted by Hegel to the function and position of ' the modern artist ', the artist * of our own day V considered with reference to the situation which existed after the period of ' romantic ' art had come to an end, and * Aesthetik, iii. 355. '^ Philosophie der Geschkhte, pp. 107-8. 3 Aesth. i. 114. * Jb. ii. 233-5. M PROCEEDINGS OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY therefore, after the final Auflosung of classical and romantic art, to which as a rule, and not to art in general, he attaches the term Auflosung.^ In a word, after all the AuHosung had taken place, art and the artist survived in a new attitude and a new world. On the main point at issue this is enough. But the interest of the question will justify a brief examination of what Hegel meant by the Auflosung or any similar term as applied to art or to any form of it ; and what was this function and position which he recognized as that of the 'modern artist \ the 'artist of our own day\ (5) The word ' Auflosung ■", like the English word ' dissolution \ may of course in certain contexts be equivalent to ' death '. But its natural usage rather follows the suggestion of loosening a knot, as in a tragic complication (denouement), resolving a contradiction or a dis- sonance, solving a problem or difficulty, elucidating by analysis. In Hegel we find it once at least in the Logic bearing such a meaning, where the contradiction embodied in an infinite series is said to be ' resolved ' into the end or terminus.^ Of course this does not imply that the contradiction so resolved ceases to be experienced. It is used in the extra-logical works in a sense akin to that of the familiar logical verb ' aufheben ' or ' sich aufheben \ which expressly involves the persistence ot the element so ' set aside \ And it is noticeable that in a crucial passage of the Aesthetic lectures^ Hegel applies the term 'sich aufhebt' (transcends itself) to the process which he mostly describes as the Auflosung of art in some special form. What Hegel means by the dissolution of art is the course of development which transformed the art of classical Greece into the art of "Christian Europe, and ultimately into the art of the world in the early nine- teenth century. It divides itself primarily in his rubrics into the dissolution of classical art and the classical ideal, and the dissolution and the close of romantic art. But this matters little for the general problem, since what he means by romantic art m* for him, in its several stages, one and the same thing with the dissolution of classical art, with its own dissolution, and with the dissolution of art as such, in so far as he intended to speak of any such thing. The meaning of the term is double, logical and aesthetic. Art is being dissolved or set aside, as any logical form is dissolved or set aside, which becomes by its inadequacy a source of contradiction demanding resolution and explanation by larger points of view. * On a rare example to the contrary see below. ^ EncycL, sect. 242. Cf. Wins. d. Logik, p. 7. ^ Aesth. ii. 138. * lb. ii. 217, where this is very definitely stated. CROCE'S AESTHETIC 25 Undoubtedly the whole world of art, as addressing itself to sensuous intuition, was in his eyes tending to become a spring of such contra- diction and transcendence when compared with the full resources of the human spirit in religion and philosophy. And art is within itself in a parallel way being dissolved, resolved, or disintegrated in abandoning the relative narrowness and fixity of early traditional vision, and expanding from the relatively rigid and inherited basis of Greek and of Christian art into nothing; less than the love and imairiua- tive penetration of any and every feature by which man or the world can touch in the region of sense man's own heart and mind. This is ' Dissolution ', if we will have it so ; after all, it is Browning's metaphor That one face, far from vanish, rather grows, Or decomposes but to recompose. Become my universe that feels and knows. Necessarily in this 'resolution' a cha'ige has come about not only within art, but in the relation of art to our whole experience. 'One may hope that art will continue to ascend and to perfect itself; but its form has ceased to be the highest demand of the spirit. How excellent soever we find the Greek statues, however nobly and perfectly we see portrayed God the Father, Christ, and Mary, it makes no difference, our knees no longer bend.' ^ The observation is surely a simple truism, and even of the most modern and most comprehensive art it holds good in spirit. There are more things in heaven and earth than are dreamed of even in beauty. The 'dis- solution ' of art is both into an altered art, and also into an altered status in life. It is an obvious case of such transcendence and displacement, both logical and aesthetic, when Hegel speaks definitely of comedy as ' leading to the dissolution of art in general '.^ It is a truth akin to that which recent criticism has recognized in agreement with Hegel to the effect that 'in the evolution of poetry, comedy tends to displace tragedy '.^ ' All the more tense and exclusive forms of poetry gradually translate themselves into a larger pattern and looser texture.' When ' Dante meant to include everything in his poem ', he called it a Comedy. And to include everything would be to transcend the limits of art. There is always a Avorld which art cannot include. So even with the Aeneid; there is in it, the same critic has pointed outs'* a transmutation and spiritualization of poetry 1 Aesth. i. 132. ^ lb. iii. 580. ' Mackail^ Lectures on roctry, pp. 176-7. * lb., p. 90. 26 PROCEEDINGS OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY which transcends art properly so called, 'a continued search further and further after what cannot be found \ But that art, like every experience, has in it the spirit which leads it at a certain point to pass beyond itself, tells no more, as we saw, against its persistent vitality than the same characteristic tells against the vitality of sensation or of science. The whole 143 pages ' of HegePs Aesthetic lectures which deal with the Auflosung of the special art-forms and of art bear out the above account, which is a very brief and unworthy summary of them. The Auflosung, the dissolution or resolution, goes hand in hand, for example, wqth the Versohnung^ — the reconciliation or union of inward feeling and the complex actual world, with the Aufschliessung ^ — the unfolding or self-manifestation of the divine, and the infinite Erweiterung^ — expansion of the range of art, obtained by a correlative concentration in the focus of the human soul. (6) Enough has really been said. But a word mav be added on the decisive climax, which comes in Hegel's explicit attitude to the modern artist, the artist of his own day, whom he regards as living and working after the Auflosung of art in general has fully come into play. Here one or two quotations will be in place and will suffice. 'In contrast with the time in which the artist, owing to his nationality and his age, stands essentially within a definite view of the world and type of artistic production, w^e now find an absolutely opposite standpoint, which in its complete development has become important only in the most recent period. In our day, among almost all nations, reflective culture and the critical spirit, and with us Germans freedom of thought, have extended their domination to the artists themselves, and have made them so to speak a tabula rasa with regard to the matter and form of their production, after ^ even the inevitable particular stages of the romantic form of art have been traversed. For the artist of to-day it is a feature of the past to be bound to a particular content and a mode of representation appropriate to it, and art has become a free instrument by the fact that it can operate in accordance with its subjective ability in relation to any content of whatsoever kind. Hence the artist stands above the determinate traditional forms and shapes, and moves freely in his own mind, independently of the content and mode of intuition in which consciousness in former ages envisaged the holy and the eternal.' ^ » Aesth. ii. 100-243. '^ lb , p. 118: 3 lb., p. 123. * Jb., p. 281. * My italics. ' lb. , p. 232. CROCKS AESTHETIC 27 * In this latter form of art (the romantic) as in those before it, the divine was essentially and definitely the object of art. But this divine element had to take objective shape, to particularize itself, and thereby to advance out of itself into the secular import of subjectivity. To begin with' (asHegel has described) 'the infinite value of personality lay in honour, love, and loyalty, then in the peculiar individuality, the determinate character, which fused itself with the special sub- stance of a man's existence. The amalgamation with such a specific limitation of content was finally set aside again by humour, which had the power of rendering unstable and resolving every specification, and thus caused art to transcend itself. Yet in this self-transcendence, it is none the less a withdrawal of man into himself, a descent into his own breast, whereby art strips off from itself every rigid limitation to a definite sphere of content and of apprehension, and adopts as its modern saint the human man,^ with the deeps and heights of the human heart as such, with universal humanity in its joys and griefs, its aspirations, acts, and destinies. Hereby the artist receives his content within himself, and is one with the human mind as it actually specifies itself, as it contemplates, creates, and expresses the infinity of its feelings and situations, the mind to which nothing now is alien, which can live in the human breast. This is a subject-matter which is no longer essentially and definitely determined as artistic,^ but surrenders the choice of content and of creative shaping to original invention, but yet excludes no particular source of interest. For art no longer needs only to represent that which is absolutely at home in some one of its particularized stages, but has everything open to it which man in general has capacity to make his own.' ^ ' ^ The artist need feel no special necessity, with a view to his work, of settling his own conviction and caring for his own salvation ; his great and free soul must, fundamentally, and before he enters upon production, know and possess the basis on which it is to stand, and be sure and confident within itself; and more particularly the great artist of to-day ^ is in need of the free development of mind, in which all superstition and belief such as is permanently limited by deter- * ' den humanus \ a reference probably to the famous line, ' Homo sum, humani nihil a me alieuum puto'. See five lines below. ''i.e. We do not now say ' these and these subjects are the subjects of art ; those and those are not '. ^ Aesth. ii. 204-5. This passage, besides indicating Hegel's view of modern art, is a brief epitome of the Auf losung and self-transcendence of art, setting in relation its positive and negative sides. ^ Aesth. ii. 'l'^^. ^ heutige : cf. p. 234, Der moderne Kunstler. 28 PROCEEDINGS OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY minate forms of intuition and representation, are set aside as mere parts and aspects, over which the free mind has made itself sovereign. For he sees in them no consecrated conditions of his exposition and imagina- tive shaping, but assigns value to them only in virtue of the higher import with which, in his re-creation of them, he endows them as their true belonging.' In a word, art, after passing through phases determined by the conditions of relatively early mind, has achieved its freedom, as thought after a similar apprenticeship has achieved its own.^ What the necessary evolution of the art-forms, in Hegel's view, here says to the modern artist, inasmuch as the dissolution of art was con- currently its liberation, is in the tone of what Virgil said to Dante : ^ Tratto t' ho qui con ingegno e con arte, I^o tuo piacere omai prendi per duce : F'uor sei delF erte vie, fuor sei delP arte. Non aspettar mio dir piu, ne mio cenno. Libero, dritto e sano e tuo arbitrio, E fallo fora non fare a suo senno : Perch' io te sopra te corono e mitrio. This I hold to be the truth about ' the death of art ' in Heirel. ^ See the Phenomenology of Mind. * Mackailj op. cit. , p. 218. This application of Dante's lines, analogous to that made hy Mr. Mackail in speaking of Shakespeare's romantic plays, suggested itself to the writer, he believes, independently. GENERAL LIBRARY ' TALTFORNIA 14 DAY USE RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED LOAN DEPT. RENEWALS ONLY— TEL. NO. 642-3405 This book is due on the last date stamped below, or on the date to which renewed. Renewed books are subject to immediate recall. fgPB 2^ 19^^ ^A CjB.ft»e 16 T7. F^ECEJVEO NOV 6 1984 m 1 h '69 Prin ^<^'-' DCP ^^^-H RECEIVFr> JUL 7 1971 7 AUG 14 1977 -N0V — ^^m^ ^ CIRCULATIQ N-D£^ h o LD 21A-38m-5,'6{ (.J401slO)476B tr o ^ General Library Jniversity of California Berkeley