B 945,849 808.1 C866 ope 808.1 C862 in... Jaite. T · ARTES 183 18371 SCIENTIA LIBRARY VERITAS OF THE UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN E-PLURIBUS-UNUM TUEBOR SIQUAERIS PENINSULAM AMOENAM CIRCUMSPICE ぷり​入り​。 808.1 86€ Liberty & Authority in Matters of Taste AN INAUGURAL LECTURE DELIVERED IN THE SHELDONIAN THEATRE, OXFORD, ON THE 15th OF FEBRUARY, 1896 BY WILLIAM JOHN COURTHOPE C.B., M.A., HON. D.LITT. (DURHAM) PROFESSOR OF POETRY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD + London MACMILLAN AND CO., LTD. NEW YORK: MACMILLAN & CO. 1896 One Shilling Net Liberty and Authority in Matters of Taste : : Liberty & Authority in Matters of Taste AN INAUGURAL LECTURE DELIVERED IN THE SHELDONIAN THEATRE, OXFORD, ON THE 15th OF FEBRUARY, 1896 BY WILLIAM JOHN COURTHOPE C.B., M.A., HON. D.LITT. (DURHAM) PROFESSOR OF POETRY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD London MACMILLAN AND CO., LTD. NEW YORK: MACMILLAN & CO. 1896 The Rights of Translation and Reproduction are Reserved • 13.6 pam R рат RICHARD CLAY AND SONS, LIMITED, LONDON AND BUNGAY." LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY IN MATTERS OF TASTE EVEN those of my predecessors who have been called with higher qualifications than myself to dis- course on Poetry before the University of Oxford must, on contemplating their duties, have felt that they had to face a problem of peculiar difficulty. The Professor of Poetry enjoys what I believe is the unique honour of being raised to his Chair by the vote of Convocation. Yet though he may thus be said to represent the oldest seat of learning in the British Empire on a subject of the deepest interest to the human imagination, he finds himself launched on this wide sea of thought without chart or compass or any kind of external instruction to guide him in the course which he is expected to steer. He is, indeed, bound to deliver three lectures yearly during his tenure of the Chair. But as to the subject-matter of these lectures he is under no obligation. Whether he should examine and discuss the general principles of poetry; whether he should rather dwell on the 6 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY practice of individual poets; whether he should draw his illustrations exclusively from the acknowledged classics of literature, or should also handle the debate- able questions of modern art; in all these points he is left entirely to his own discretion. If he seeks for a solution of his difficulty in the definitions of language, he is at once met by an ambi- guity of terms. We can have no doubt as to the meaning of the words Logic and Natural Science, nor as to the limitations imposed on those who give in- struction in these subjects. But the word Poetry may be used to signify either the outward form in which imaginative thought is expressed by means of metrical language, or that inward conception of the mind preliminary to creation which is shared by the poets with the professors of the other fine arts. Thus we may without impropriety speak of the Poetry of Painting and even of the Poetry of Architecture. : Perhaps with natural piety the newly elected Professor of Poetry looks for guidance to the inten-. tions or the character of the Founder of his Chair. But here too search is in vain of him little is known that is definite, nothing that is remarkable. Henry Birkhead must have been born in the first quarter of the seventeenth century, for he took his degree of M.A. in 1639. He appears to have been affected by the religious difficulties of his time, for shortly after taking his degree he became a Jesuit, but, soon returning to the Church of England and to Oxford, he was elected a Fellow of All Souls. IN MATTERS OF TASTE He was known as a skilful philologist. He was also a writer of Latin verse, but there is no particular merit in the compositions of this kind which he has left behind him. When the Civil War broke out he was prominent among the little group of Oxford scholars and poets who attached themselves to the cause of the king, and the most distinguished of whom were John Cleveland and William Cartwright. The characteristic features in the poetry of these men are well known. They helped to develop what Addison calls the style of False Wit, and Johnson the school of Metaphysical Poetry. Their object was to give distinction to any theme, however trivial, by adorning it with a multitude of far-fetched metaphors, similes, and allusions. A specimen of their art survives in a small volume of poems, written by them in co-operation to celebrate the memory of Sir Bevill Grenvill, who was killed in a skirmish with the Parliamentary forces at Lansdown Hill. Birkhead's contribution to this poetical garland was not abso- lutely the worst; but he was the champion of a losing cause, alike in politics and in poetry. He saw the execution of the king for whom he had fought and written; the establishment of the Commonwealth ; the Restoration of the Monarchy; the Revolution of 1688. Living till 1695, he witnessed the influence of the school of Cowley decline before the rising school of Dryden; and a Chair, which owed its existence to the liberality of one so deeply imbued with the spirit of the Middle Ages, was filled by its first Professor almost at the same time as English .8 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY society began to listen to the criticism of the Tatler and Spectator. The history of the Founder, then, throws no light on the duties attaching to this Chair. Nor can any clear notion of rule or system be gathered from the practice The list of the Professors of those who have held it. of Poetry indeed furnishes us with name after name intimately associated with great changes in the poetical taste of this country. Prominent in the early history of the Chair we observe the figure of Joseph Spence, author of the Polymetis, and of the better known Anecdotes, which so vividly illustrate the literary character of an age that found its standard in the poetry of Pope. Spence is followed after a short interval by Lowth, who enlarged the range of taste by his lectures on Hebrew Poetry, and attracted the attention of the world of letters by his dispute with Warburton, Pope's commentator and biographer. Later in the century appears Thomas Warton, the historian of English Poetry, and perhaps the earliest pioneer of the Romantic Revival, which refreshed with a new stream of thought and sentiment the exhausted classicism of those times. Coming to the present century, we admire the fine and balanced taste of Milman, the writer of the polished Newdigate prize poem on "The Belvedere Apollo," beginning: Heard ye the arrow hurtle through the sky? Heard ye the dragon monster's dying cry? and containing the truly beautiful lines descriptive of the statue : IN MATTERS OF TASTE 9 For mild he seemed as in Elysian bowers, Wasting in careless ease the joyous hours, Haughty as bards have sung, with princely sway Curbing the fierce, flame-breathing steeds of day, Beauteous as vision seen in dreamy sleep By holy maid on Delphi's haunted steep, Mid the dim twilight of the laurel grove, Too fair to worship, too divine to love. Next to Milman in point of succession, and equal to him in scholarship and refinement, the author of the Christian Year lent indirectly the aid of his criti- cism to the Lake School, then still struggling against the current of contemporary taste. Keble's Prælec- tiones, delivered as they were in Latin, appealed to a necessarily limited audience, but a new note was struck when Matthew Arnold, a name always cherished with affectionate admiration in Oxford, began to lecture in English. With him the classical genius of poetry revived under new auspices. The attention of the public at large was directed to the form of the Greek drama as a vehicle for the expres- sion of modern thought. Attic wit amused itself with applying the standards of Hellenic culture to every department of English life. It seems to me but yesterday that I listened in statu pupillari to the famous dictum pronounced from this Chair, that "there were no Wraggs by the Ilissus." Neverthe- less the stream of taste, diverted for the moment, has in our own generation shown a tendency to flow back into national channels, nor do I know of any book which has done more to accomplish this change than The Golden Treasury of English Song, a work of Uorm 10 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY Greek beauty, which will always remain as a monu- ment of the critical refinement and the large sym- pathy of my predecessor, Francis Palgrave. When I consider all this ambiguity in the meaning of terms, this silence as to the intentions of the Founder of the Chair, this diversity of taste and practice among those who have held it, it appears to me that the first question to be decided is, how far it is possible to speak on Poetry with the con- fidence which is expected from one who discharges Professorial duties. I accordingly propose in this my Inaugural Lecture to ask my audience to consider with me the question of Liberty and Authority in Matters of Taste, so that we may determine from this point of view what limits Reason imposes on the Art of Poetry, and to what extent we can apply in the domain of Imagination those scientific methods which are properly applied to the objects of Sense. But I can imagine that an objection may be made on the very threshold of such an inquiry. It may be said The question you raise is one that contains its own answer. There can be no established law in the sphere of Art and Taste. The Mind is its own place, and in itself Can make a Heaven of Hell, a Hell of Heaven. In everything relating to aloenois, taste, perception, the individual is free. Genius is the sole lawgiver in Art; and though the critic may serve the artist by sharpening the faculty of perception, yet if he attempts to measure works of art by any external IN MATTERS OF TASTE 11 standard, he ignores the proverbial and accepted wisdom of all ages: πάντων μέτρον ἄνθρωπος: De gustibus non est disputandum. This is a formidable objection; the more so because it is an echo of the prevailing philosophy of the day which we recognise by the name of Culture. The philosophy of Culture is based on self-consciousness ; that is to say, in this philosophy, the consciousness of freedom in the individual mind is made the standard and starting-point for all speculation about Religion and Art. Let me cite, as an example of what I mean by self-consciousness, a striking passage from the chapter in Sartor Resartus, called "The Everlasting No " : "The Everlasting No has said: Behold thou art fatherless, outcast, and the Universe is mine; to which my whole Me now makes answer, I am not thine, but free and for ever hate thee.' In the same spirit, though in a less obscure and poetical style, Matthew Arnold defines Criticism to be the free faculty that advances in the mind the growth of an inward Perfection; and, quite logically from his own premises, he identifies Poetry with the Idea as it exists in the individual mind and contrasts "" 72 it with dogmatic Religion. The future of poetry, he says, "is immense, because in poetry, where it is worthy of its high destinies, our race as time goes on will find an ever surer and surer stay. Our religion has materialised itself in the fact, in the supposed fact, and now the fact is failing it. But for poetry the idea is everything, the rest is a world of il- lusion, of divine illusion. Poetry attaches its emotions 12 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY AN E to the idea; the idea is the fact. The strongest part of our religion to-day is its unconscious poetry." But the opinion of those who hold with the maxim De gustibus non est disputandum is supported by a yet stronger ally in the prevailing taste of the age. It seems to be a necessary characteristic of a highly civilised society, that in proportion as it grows im- patient of Authority in Belief it insists upon Novelty in Imagination. Everywhere we hear the question asked: May we know what this new doctrine whereof thou speakest is? And from all quarters, in satisfaction of the demand, comes the answer, in the revelations of the new Humourist, the new Dramatist, the new Woman. The same feeling is paramount even in those whose imagination is accustomed to dwell in the higher regions of art and taste, and I know not where it is more eloquently expressed than in the words of an Oxford scholar whose works live in the minds of many of us as his memory is fresh in our affections. "For us," says Walter Pater, "the Renaissance is the name of a many-sided but yet united movement in which the love of the things of the intellect and the imagination for their own sake, the desire of a more liberal and comely way of con- ceiving life, make themselves felt, urging those who experience this desire to search out first one and then another means of intellectual or imaginative enjoy- ment, and directing them not merely to the discovery of old and forgotten sources of this enjoyment, but to divine new sources of it, new experiences, new sub- jects of poetry, new sources of art.” IN MATTERS OF TASTE 13 What, then, is to be said in regard to this maxim, De gustibus non est disputandum, supported as it is by the philosophy of those who preach the gospel of self-culture, and impelled by the powerful current of the public taste? I do not think that there can be the slightest doubt as to the answer. To any one who raises such a preliminary objection as I have supposed, I would reply: You have stated strongly one side of the truth, but you have ignored, com- pletely ignored, the other. You have asserted the claims of individual liberty, and up to a certain point I agree with you. I do not deny that spiritual liberty is founded on consciousness, and hence the self-consciousness of the age is part of the problem we are considering. I do not deny that the prevail- ing rage for novelty must also be taken into account. Liberty, variety, novelty, are all necessary to the development of Art. Without novelty there can be no invention, without variety there can be no charac- ter, without liberty there can be no life. Life, character, invention, these are of the essence of Poetry. But while you have defended with energy the freedom of the Individual, you have said nothing of the authority of Society. And yet the conviction of the existence of this authority is a belief perhaps even more firmly founded in the human mind than the sentiment as to the rights of individual liberty. If Henry Birkhead had not believed that the prin- ciples of poetry were, like those of all other arts or sciences, capable, up to a certain point at all events, of definition and demonstration, would he, being in 14 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY .. possession of all his senses, have bequeathed his property for the endowment of this Chair? If the University of Oxford, as a corporate body, had not shared his opinion, would it have accepted his bene- faction? Could the long succession of those who have filled this Chair have been maintained, if the great majority of the Professors of Poetry, however various their opinions, however opposite their tastes, had not felt sure that there was in taste, as in science, a theory of false and true, in art, as in conduct, a rule of right and wrong? And even among those who have asserted most strongly the inward and relative nature of poetry, do you think there was one so completely a sceptic as to imagine that he was the sole proprietor of the perception he sought to embody in words; one who doubted his power, by means of these accepted symbols, to communicate to his audience his own ideas and feelings about ex- ternal things? Yet until some man shall have been found bold enough to defend a thesis so preposterous, we must continue to believe that there is a positive standard, by which those at least who speak a common language may reason about questions of taste. There is no doubt a point at which the principle De gustibus non est disputandum must be strictly applied. Our English law recognises this. We know that when a man pursues his own taste so far as to publish in writing that which is decided to be con- trary to the law of the land, the plea of the offender that he only wrote what seemed beautiful to him, or IN MATTERS OF TASTE 15 what he believed to be true, will not avail for his protection. Tastes of that kind we do not dispute about; we punish them. It is seldom indeed in England that any individual so far oversteps the large liberties allowed him by the law as to translate into action opinions which are recognised as dan- gerous to the community. But beyond those appet- ites which are proscribed as illegal there are secret proceedings of thought and perception which, while they elude the clumsy vigilance of the law, may poison the atmosphere about us-tastes that corrupt, sentiments that emasculate, affectations that debase, the whole spirit and character of society. To treat these with easy tolerance is only a sign of social cowardice. A nation which has a just sense of its own greatness and liberty must also have a sense of what is ideally noble and beautiful, and must not be afraid to condemn any departure from this standard. And indeed all experience shows that the instinct of every society impels it to assert its authority in questions relating to imagination and art. Nature bids us judge in matters of taste: the difficulty is how to judge rightly. Since, then, this is the object of our inquiry, I will ask you in the first place very briefly to glance at the different kinds of external tribunal by which Society has endeavoured to decide questions of taste, in order that we may see how far we can accept their authority. Perhaps the form of external authority which most readily occurs to each of us is the Academy after the French model. No one will deny a grandeur 16 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY { to the constitution and history of this great body. You will remember what was the object of its crea- tion as described by Richelieu, its founder: "The main function of the Academy shall be to work with all possible care and diligence at giving sure rules to our language, and rendering it pure, eloquent, and capable of treating the arts and sciences." And Renan, giving a slight emphasis to the idea of Richelieu, says: The duty of the Academy is to preserve the delicacy of the French language." As far as regards the intellectual history of France, these strictly conservative duties have been performed with splendid fidelity and success. The Academy has admitted within its walls almost every great French writer since the day of its foundation, so that on literary grounds it may justly claim to speak with the representative authority of France. In the stan- dard of taste which it has consistently upheld the French nation has seen the image of its own genius. One doubts whether to admire the Academy most for the thoroughness with which it has realised the idea of Richelieu, by carrying the rules of the French language through the anarchy of the Revolution, or for the courage with which it has maintained the standard of Renan, by preserving the delicacy of French thought in the days of M. Zola. I do not wonder that so great a triumph should have profoundly impressed the imagination of English critics, or that we should frequently hear the opinion expressed, that it would be an excellent thing if we could have an institution of the same kind in Eng- IN MATTERS OF TASTE 17 (6 land. Those who speak in this way usually support themselves by the authority of Matthew Arnold, and refer to a lecture delivered, I believe, from this Chair, on the Literary Influence of Academies. But they seem to me to misunderstand the mind of that eminent critic, because though all his arguments point to the foundation of an Academy in England, he concludes as follows: An Academy quite like the French Academy, a sovereign organ of the highest literary opinion, a recognised authority in matters of intellectual tone and taste, we shall hardly have, and perhaps we ought not to wish to have it." That is the conclusion of common sense, and the most elementary considerations show why it must be so. The French Academy is an effect, not a cause; it is the product mainly of certain intellectual qualities of the French people. It was founded as an institution because, at a certain point of their history, the French people became conscious that they possessed these qualities, and a number of representative men began to form themselves into a society for the purpose of discussing questions of taste and expression. They had no intention of initiating or legislating: they came together to discuss and to judge. The English people do not possess that analytical and logical genius which would enable them to constitute a representative assembly for the same purpose. But if the French Academy derives its representa- tive character from the nature of the French intellect, the official prestige and authority it possesses come 18 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY to it solely from a political source. It was in fact, the offspring of the French Monarchy. It was established by the king; for a long time the king retained and exercised the power of veto in its elections: it would have been impossible to make it a really comprehensive and representative as- sembly if all the best minds of France had not first found a natural centre of attraction in the Court. Even therefore if the qualities of the English genius facilitated, instead of hindering, the constitution of an Academy like the French, the decentralisation of English institutions and our habits of individual liberty would necessarily prevent such a body from exercising any authority. I might dwell on other Courts, of the nature of Academies, by means of which Society at different times has attempted to pronounce judgment in matters of taste. Such, for example, is the Coterie, which may be defined as a miniature Academy without official status, and which under various conditions has exercised great influence in Italy, France, and Eng- land. But as the Coterie represents no body of opinion beyond itself, and as it flourishes most in an aristocratic form of society, it is unnecessary to speak of it in detail, and I pass on to consider a tribunal with whose decrees we are all familiar, the Court of Public Opinion. Public opinion delivers judgment either collectively, or representatively by means of an anonymous press. When it acts collectively it is certainly one of the most remarkable of human phenomena, and I think IN MATTERS OF TASTE 19 1 that the spectacle of vast bodies of men giving simultaneous expression to their consciousness of what is right furnishes the strongest refutation that could be desired of the fallacy in the maxim, De gustibus non est disputandum. Such are the judgments pronounced by the spectators in a theatre, or by the audience at a public meeting when they express their approval of or dissent from the opinions of an orator. On these occasions the verdict of public opinion is, for the moment at least, irresistible. The dramatist is not obliged to regard it as final: he may reason with his judges, as Aristophanes did in the Clouds; he may even pro- claim his contempt for their taste, as Ben Jonson did in his Ode to Himself after the failure of his New Inn; but he knows that there is no higher court to which he can appeal. It must be allowed that, as a tribunal of taste, public opinion, or perhaps I should rather say popu- lar opinion, possesses certain great virtues. For one thing, the taste of the people is almost always natural, and natural taste is the foundation of good taste. When a whole society-at least a society which is both historic and free-judges collectively, its instincts will not allow it to go very far astray. It will reject what is nasty and unwholesome; it will favour such tastes as are on the whole manly, and healthy, and vigorous. The judges in the gallery of a theatre, who hiss the villain of a play for his evil sentiments, are representatives of the authority of popular opinion. Critics of this stamp will also show themselves intolerant of such fundamental faults of 20 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY taste as affectation and conceit, which pass unscathed the judgment, for example, of the Coterie. When a dramatist or any other kind of artist shows that he is thinking more of his own nature than of human nature, any large audience will be quick to find him out. Nor is the collective verdict of the public ever consciously unjust, because, as it judges in the mass, it is not affected by those petty personal motives of envy, jealousy, and resentment which so often disturb the reason of private critics. But public opinion as a court of justice has certain obvious limitations and weaknesses. Like the old Teutonic assemblies of freemen which announced their decisions by the shouts of the multitude and the clashing of shields, its powers are restricted to simple approval or rejection. Moreover its judgments are always arbitrary, being founded on emotion, not on reason. The standard by which it judges may be constituted out of the merest prejudice and ignor- ance, yet as it knows of no other, it will regard its own canon as conclusive. In no other tribunal is the last word of the despot so decisively uttered: "Sic volo, sic jubeo, stat pro ratione voluntas. Again, even when it decides more deliberately through the anonymous criticism of the press, public opinion is subject to weaknesses, arising from hurry and superficiality, which lower its authority as a tri- bunal of taste. To judge rightly in matters of taste we must have time. An enduring work of art is the product of meditation and labour, and by the nature of things it cannot be measured by a mere ephemeral standard. The press can and does judge with admir- Y IN MATTERS OF TASTE 21 able accuracy of the mass of novels, poems, plays, and pictures, which men read, glance at, talk about, and forget its methods of swift intuition and general- isation are inadequate to estimate the work of a Raphael or a Milton. : I think that from the facts I have attempted to put before you two conclusions may safely be drawn. One is, that society in all ages has been constantly attempting to assert its authority in matters of taste; the other is, that no form of social organisation of which the world has had experience is likely to be accepted as a tribunal of taste in such a country as England. The Academy of the French pattern is de- fective because it is the offspring of centralisation ; the Coterie is defective because it is not representative; Public Opinion is defective because it has no recognised standard of judgment, and also because its judgments are too rough and ready to be applicable to the higher creations of Art. It may indeed be doubted whether for such a society as ours, so full of self- consciousness and the spirit of individual liberty, so charged with party feeling, divided between so many sections and interests, any representative body could ever be formed which would be recognised as giving expression to the deliberate sense of the community on purely aesthetic questions. Yet one thing we may surely hope for the growth of an educated Public Conscience in matters of taste which shall exercise a general influence on private judgment. Perhaps the most signal of the services performed by Matthew Arnold was the constancy with which he insisted on the 22 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY This necessity of exercising right reason within the sphere of criticism. This is no mere rhetorical phrase. For not only is it possible to apply right methods of reason- ing in art and taste, but certain evil consequences inevitably ensue when these methods are neglected. Every critic who attempts to decide a disputed point of taste must satisfy two conditions; in the first place he must judge judicially, that is to say, he must strive to regard the object of his criticism scientifically and apart from prejudice; in the second place he must verify his own conclusions by reference to some recognised standard of authority. seems almost like the statement of a truism, and yet how rare it is to find these two requirements both fulfilled! How often, on the one hand, does private dislike and prejudice intervene to cut off the critic from the sight of his object; how often, on the other, is he satisfied with the unassisted decision of his own consciousness ! And what are the consequences? Let me illustrate by two notable examples what happens when critics content themselves with satisfy- ing one of the essential conditions of good criticism without attending to the other. Probably no literary judgment ever produced more disastrous results in the interests of good taste than the article in the Quarterly Review on Keats' Endy- mion. Here the issue as between Liberty and Autho- rity was raised in a very trenchant manner. Keats was an innovator. Both in his treatment of his sub- ject, in his diction, and in his versification, he came into violent collision with the canons of composition IN MATTERS OF TASTE 23 accepted in his day. Yet in the points of taste which called for a decision there was really nothing new. The question, for example, as to the right of coining new words or reviving disused words in poetry was as old as Horace; it had been debated in Italy by Castiglione in his Courtier; it had been raised in France by the Pleiad, and afterwards discussed by almost every French critic; it was familiar in England since the publication of Lyly's Euphues. The ruling on the point is given with admirable clearness in Horace's Ars Poetica— Multa renascentur quæ jam cecidere, cadentque Quæ nunc sunt in honore vocabula, si volet usus, Quem penes arbitrium est et jus et norma loquendi. • Usus; usage; the genius of the language; there was the law. The sole question was whether Keats had violated the law, and if so, with what amount of justification. Nothing could have been simpler than to apply the test of right reason. But how did Croker deliver judgment? In the first place he announced that he had only read one book of Endy- mion, which was quite enough for him. In the next place, as to the particular point at issue, he decided as follows:- "By this time our readers must be pretty well satisfied as to the meaning of Mr. Keats's sentences and the structure of his lines. We now present them with some of the new words with which, in imitation of Mr. Leigh Hunt, he adorns our lan- guage. We are told that turtles passion their 6 24 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY voices;' that an arbour was nested; and a lady's locks gordianed up; and to supply the names of the nouns thus verbalised, Mr. Keats with great fecundity spawns new ones: such as 'men-slugs and human serpentry'; the honey-feel of bliss; wives prepare needments; and so forth." Now as to the substance of this judgment we can- not doubt that Croker was right. He had satisfied one of the conditions of sound criticism in referring to a positive standard of authority, and, like all sane critics before him, he had taken usage as the standard of measurement. Keats had offended against the genius of the English language with crudeness, violence, and affectation. But could anything be more unjudicial than the manner in which Croker told him so, without making any allowance for the fact that he was a young man, and evidently a young man of genius? More unfortunate still in the in- terests of criticism was the fact that Croker's judg- ment, besides being offensive and contemptuous in tone, was in certain points incorrect. The standard of usage by which he measured was simply the standard recognised in his own day without reference to the historic growth of the language, and he showed ignorance in supposing Keats to have been merely coining new words. Hence the "cockney school” as he called the innovators, while they justly complained of his manners, could also point to his mistakes. They hardened themselves in impenitence, and began to criticise by rules of their own the practice of the prevailing school, whom, with a ludicrous self-import- IN MATTERS OF TASTE 25 ance, they called the disciples of "one Boileau." The general reader was puzzled with the dispute, but when he turned to Endymion, and found there such an exquisite passage as Whence come ye, jolly Satyrs, whence come ye, So many, and so many, and such glee? he was amazed at the blindness of the Quarterly Reviewer, and concluding that he must be entirely wrong, rejected his whole standard of measurement —though it was really a just one-to the irreparable damage of good taste and common sense. This is an example of the consequences of not judging judicially. As an illustration of the results of judging by a merely private standard, I think I shall not be mistaken in citing Matthew Arnold's lecture on the Literary Influence of Academies. You will remember that he there criticises a great number of English authors, amongst others Addison, Jeremy Taylor, Burke, and Mr. Ruskin, from whose works he quotes passages as samples of bad taste in writing. Now it is plain that Matthew Arnold is here judging judicially. All the examples he pro- duces are really examples of bad taste. All of them are selected with great fineness of perception and great accuracy of instinct. But whereas the kind of taste they exhibit is extremely diverse, specific, and characteristic of the individual, Matthew Arnold chooses for his own purposes to ascribe their defects to one single source, and that a national one. He says: Adopting Dr. Newman's expressive word, 66 菁 ​26 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY ' I say that in the bulk of the intellectual work of a nation which has no centre, no intellectual metropolis like an Academy-like M. Sainte-Beuve's sovereign organ of opinion,' like M. Renan's recognised au- thority in matters of tone and taste '-there is ob- servable a note of provinciality. Now to get rid of provinciality is a certain stage of culture, a stage the positive results of which we must not make of too much importance, but which is nevertheless indis- pensable; for it brings us on to the platform, where alone the best and highest intellectual work can be said to begin." There have been some who shrank from bringing an indictment against a whole nation. Matthew Arnold had no such diffidence. But what is the supposed standard by which he judges? The note of provinciality? How can the genius of a great nation be called provincial? Of what central society is a nation a province? Is it not plain that when Matthew Arnold produces a rhetorical effect by a phrase like this, he is judging by a measure recog- nised only by himself? The world would not have accepted Quintilian's judgment on Seneca's style as conclusive, if he had not criticised it by canons which the world could understand. Thus then we are brought to the practical question -What is the final authority to which right reason should refer in judging of matters of taste? I do not think that we can be in doubt about the answer. In every art the standard is the example of the great artist, the practice of those who are acknowledged to be masters in the art. Not, however, because they IN MATTERS OF TASTE 27 are arbitrary dictators. There are, I think, two para- mount reasons why the standard must be settled by them. One is that argument from antiquity which is so admirably stated by Sir Joshua Reynolds in his Dis- courses on Painting. He says: "The modern who recommends himself as a standard may justly be sus- pected as ignorant of the true end, and unacquainted with the proper object, of the art which he professes. To follow such a guide will not only retard the student but mislead him. On whom then can he rely, or who will show him the path that leads to excellence? The answer is obvious: those great masters who have travelled the same road with suc- cess are the most likely to conduct others. The works of those who have stood the test of ages have a claim to that respect and veneration to which no modern can pretend. The duration and stability of their fame is sufficient to evince that it has not been suspended upon the slender thread of fashion and caprice, but bound to the human heart by every tie of sympathetic approbation." But there is, it seems to me, another reason even more powerful than the argument from antiquity, though it merely presents a different side of the same truth: great artists are the standards of art because they are old no doubt, but also because they are representative. I take all great poetry to be not so much what Plato thought it, the utterance of indi- vidual genius, half inspired, half insane, as the enduring voice of the soul and conscience of man living in society. The great poets and orators of 28 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY ነ Greece and Rome are justly accepted as our masters in eloquence, because their works present in an ideal form lasting records of the thoughts and emotions which the human heart experiences in the various vicissitudes of active life. For example, Milton says, in words which are a living part of our language, Fame is the spur that the clear spirit doth raise (That last infirmity of noble minds) To scorn delights and live laborious days. But is it not a striking thought that, between two and three thousand years before, the same sublime logic should be found in the words with which Homer makes Sarpedon animate the courage of Glaucus, and which have scarcely lost anything of their original nobility, in the version of Homer's English translator ? Could all our care elude the gloomy grave Which claims alike the fearful and the brave, For lust of fame I would not vainly dare In fighting fields to urge the soul to war. But since, alas! ignoble age must come, Disease, and death's inexorable doom, The life that others pay let us bestow, And give to Fame what we to Nature owe. Brave though we fall, and honoured if we live, Or let us glory gain, or glory give. We watch the conflict between divine and human law in the Antigone of Sophocles, and we realise the eternal truth of the dramatic situation when we pass to the history of England and see it repeated in the tragedy of Alice Lisle. How intelligible seems the dispute between the Just and Unjust Argument in IN MATTERS OF TASTE 29 the Clouds of Aristophanes to the old English Tory! Why do we feel a peculiar sublimity in the famous oath of Demosthenes on the souls of those who fought at Marathon and Salamis? Is it not because we too cherish the memories of the men who perished under Nelson and Wellington in a later defence of European liberty? And when we read the ever memorable lines of Virgil, Tu regere imperio populos, Romane, memento; Hæ tibi erunt artes, pacisque imponere morem, what Englishman is not proud to feel how justly they may be applied to those who administer the government of India? I conceive that it is this political spirit—I use the word political in its wide Greek sense-which has given a special character to the study of the classics in the English Universities since the days of Erasmus and Colet, of Cheke and Ascham. Our ideal of classical education differs alike from the æsthetic ideal of the Italian Humanists, who deified the ancients as absolute lawgivers in the sphere of abstract form, and from the scientific ideal of the German Universities, which regard the dead languages as one of the many departments of abstract knowledge. We in England, on the contrary, look on the classics as a great school of taste, and we consider the educa- tion of taste itself as a means to a practical, a political end. We have not allowed the necessarily Pagan genius of the Greek and Roman writers to undermine the foundations of the Christian faith. 30 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY but treating their works as living creations of humanity, interpreting their spirit and character with the kindred sympathy of freemen, we have familiarised ourselves for centuries with the principles that governed their imagination. We appreciate their singular felicity in the choice of subject, the chastened elegance of their composition, the har- monious purity of their style. Testimony is borne to the efficacy of this system of University education by the most illustrious of those who have pursued a different object. "The office of the English Universities," says Döllinger, "is by means of the study of classics and mathematics, com- bined with logic and moral philosophy and a college education to turn out for the benefit of the State and Society the cultivated and independent gentleman. I will not conceal the fact that these renovated and improved editions of the old and unfortunately ex- tinct German bursaries, the colleges of Oxford and Cambridge, have many a time as I observed their working on the spot awakened in me feelings of envy, and led me to long for the time when we might again have something of the kind; for I could plainly perceive that their effect was to make in- struction take root in the mind, and become a part of it, and that their influence extended beyond the mere communication of knowledge, to the ennobling elevation of the life and character." What member of the English Universities, above all what member of the University of Oxford, would wish to see an education which has borne such fruit as IN MATTERS OF TASTE 31 this displaced in favour of a system calculated to promote mere self-culture? Year by year the Univer- sities send to the Bar, to the Public Services, to the great army of Journalism, bands of recruits who diffuse the influence of their own tastes, and help to direct the movements of popular opinion. Were there to be any breach between the educated taste of the Universities, and the natural taste of the public at large, the whole system of irrigation in English æsthetic culture would be tainted at its source. The taste of the Uni- versities would become more monastic, more epi- curean; the taste of the public would grow more rude, more barbarous. It should surely therefore be the object of all patriotic endeavour to strengthen the established principle of authority in matters of taste, and to widen its base so as to meet the necessities of our imperial society. A great opportunity of advancing in this direc- tion seems to be offered by the foundation of the new Oxford School of English Language and Litera- ture. For while the ancient classics must always remain our primal authority in determining what are the principles of good taste, it is in the classics of our own country that we can best study the manner in which these principles have been and should be applied. The tablets of the English School are still almost a blank : it will depend upon the first teachers and examiners what shall be written in them. You may make it a genuine school of taste, which shall show the student what is the true standard of excel- lence in English writing, and how he may measure 32 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY for himself the aberrations of eccentric genius. In that case the School will follow the lines of Literæ Humaniores. You will cause the greatest English writers to be studied mainly for the purpose of understanding their spirit and character; you will show each of them in his just propor- tions, and the place which he occupies in our literature as a whole; how he was affected by, how he represented, and how he himself influenced, the movement of his own age. In such a school the exact study of language will be, as it is in Litera Humaniores, of the highest value in helping to un- lock the secrets of thought, and in exhibiting the orderly development of the laws of taste and harmony. Language is the instrument of thought, and, like the winged sandals of Mercury, it may aid the mind to mount into the higher regions of thought and imagina- tion. But it would be an error to take Mercury's sandals as the source of his divinity, and some- thing of the kind would happen, if, as might be done in the English School, the study of language were allowed to predominate over the study of literature. The study of language in itself is, like every branch of science, of the highest intellectual interest. But were it to be raised above literature, or even studied apart from literature, I venture to say that you would be wasting an unequalled opportunity; for you would be introducing a foreign educational principle which can never acclimatise itself in the genius of England and Oxford. You might under such conditions get a school of archæological research, which would doubt- IN MATTERS OF TASTE 33 less be of use and interest to the special student; but you would not get, what you may still get, a school capable of exercising a national influence in the discipline of English taste. I have now arrived at something like a practical conclusion to the inquiry with which I started. A question is naturally raised by the scepticism of an old society, whether any law or authority can be recognised as binding in matters of taste. The universal instinct, which in every society prompts. men to insist on their right of judging in such matters, seems to point to the existence of some principle of authority in the constitution of human nature. But in what way can this authority be enforced? I have shown that it is idle to expect Englishmen to submit their private liberty of judg- ment to any external tribunal of taste. It would appear, however, to be a less hopeless task, by close attention to great works of art, to create a conscious- ness of what is truly beautiful, and so to form a canon of taste which shall impose itself on the indi- vidual judgment. A public conscience of this kind must be the product of education, and the education which is required is precisely that which has been long established in the English Universities. As for the particular functions of this Chair in promoting, the education of taste, several conditions have to be regarded. I do not think that the duties of a Professor of Poetry lie mainly in the illustra- tion of technical principles; for in poetry, even less than in the other arts, is great work the 1 34 LIBERTY AND AUTHORITY མ result of mere attention to rules; it is the result of the inspiration, corrected by the severe self- discipline, of genius. Moreover, the rare occasions on which the Professor of Poetry makes his appearance in the lecture-room must preclude him from giving that minute and systematic teaching in the subject which is rather the function of a resident Professor of Literature. On the other hand, there are questions of taste constantly and naturally rising out of the doubts of a self-conscious society-conflicts between Liberty and Authority, between Novelty and Tradition- which suggest subjects that may be profitably con- sidered from this Chair. I shall therefore hold myself at liberty to treat Poetry in that wide and general sense of the word which makes it co-extensive with the creative power of the Imagination, and I shall devote my lectures mainly to examining the laws and conditions on which the life of Poetry depends. This may be done in a variety of ways: by dwelling on the principles of great poetry; by observing the manner in which these have been applied by great poets; by analysing the causes of national movements of imagination; and by tracing the development of individual genius. Much also may be learned from the fate of poets, who in all ages have fallen victims to Affectation, Exaggeration, Conceit, False Wit, False Sentiment, in a word to all the im- mortal fallacies by which the fascination of novelty bewitches the weakness and inexperience of taste. I am aware that the task I propose to myself is one of great difficulty. To define the laws of Good Taste IN MATTERS OF TASTE 35 becomes always harder as civilised society moves farther away from the primal sources of poetical inspiration. But at least we shall be looking in the right direction if we take for our standard the prin- ciple which Pericles recommended to the Athenians —φιλοσοφοῦμεν ἄνευ μαλακίας: We pursue culture in a manly spirit. 1 To renew the charge, book must be brought to the desk. TWO WEEK BOOK DO NOT RETURN BOOKS ON SUNDAY DATE DUE AUG 1 6 2002 MAY 23.2002 MAY 2 4 2002 Form 7079 5-53 30M S . UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN 3 9015 03104 0465