PT |X)RNELL ^y>3 UNIVERSm /9s LBRAKY /Sr-?S OLIN LIBRARY ~ CIRCULATION DATE DUE ''i*Ml aig^sfipf**-^ iBS jyi j U » 'i9tg ^4^ juuu-im: iSmm m ,^#iR & ei^g9s JU M I nyg& S*!**?*.. PRINTCOINU.S.A. f^- PT 2473.A5"'l895™""' """^ ***;ii?n,!ii!iif',LS';;.l£'!,i!9.soph|c^^ essavs. 3 1924 026 198 683 Cornell University Library The original of tliis bool< is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924026198683 IvXPECTATION. THE WORKS FREDERICK SCHILLER. ^STHETICAL AND PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS. TRAnSLATRD FROM THE GERMAN, ILLUSg-RATED. HARVARD PUBLISHING COMPANY" 189s NEW YORK This edition is limited to one thousand copies, of which this is no.\:.^.,.. . W. W. PRO UT, Printer. CONTENTS. PAGE iNTKODtrCTION 5 -Letters on the ^sthetioal Eddcation of Man ... 33 jEsthetical Essays : — The Moral Utility of Esthetic Manners . . .126 On the Sublime 135 The Pathetic 149 On Guace and Dignity 175 On Dignity . . . . .... 211 On the necessary Limitations in the Use of Beauty AND Form 230 Reflections on the Use of the Vulgar and Low Elements in Works op Art 254 _- Detached Reflections on Different Questions of .(Esthetics . 261 - On Simple and SentimeiAal Poetry .... 269 ^ The Stage as a Moral Institution 339 ■^ On the Tragic Art 346 ^^ Of the Cause of the Pleasure we derive from Tragic Objects . 367 Schiller's Philosophical Letters: — Prefatory Remarks 379 Theosophy of Julius 387 On the Connection between the Animal and the Spiritual Nature in Man 406 Physical Connection 408 Philosophical Connection . 41i> INTEODUCTIOK. The special subject of the greater part of the letterr tMid essays of Schiller contained in this volume is iEsthe'^ics ; and before passing to any remarks on his treatment of the subject it will be useful to offer a few observations on the nature of this topic, and on its treatment hy the philo- sophical spirit of different ages. First, then, aesthetics has for its object the vast realm of the beautiful, and it may be most adequately defined as the philosophy of art or of the fine arts. To some the definition may seem arbitrary, as excluding the beautiful in nature ; but it will cease to appear so if it is I'emarked that the beauty which is the work of art is higher than natural beauty, because it is the offspring of the mind. Moreover, if, in conformity with a certain school of modem philosophy, the mind be viewed as the true being, including all in itself, it must he admitted that beauty is only truly beautiful when i|^ shares in the nature of mind, and is mind's offspring. Viewed in this light, the beauty of nature is only a reflection of the beauty of the mind, onl3- an imperfect beauty, which as to its essence is included in that of the mind. Nor has it ever entered into the mind of any thinker to develop the beautiful in natural objects, so as to convert it into a science and a system. The field of natural beaut}' is too uncertain and too fluctuating for this pur- pose. Moreover, the relation of beauty in nature and beautj' in art forms a part of the science of aesthetics, and finds again its proper place. But it maj- be urged that art is not worthy of a scientific treatment. Art is no doubt an ornament of our life and a charm to the fancy ; but has it a more serious side ? 5 6 ^STHETICAL I.ETTEES AND ESSAYS. "When compared with the absorbing necessities of human existence, it might seem a luxurj', a superfluity, cal- culated to enfeeble the heart by the assiduous worship of beauty, and thus to be actually prejudicial to the true interest of practical life. This view seems to be largely countenanced by a dominant part}- in modern times, and practical men, as they are styled, are only too ready to take this superficial view of the office of art. Many have indeed undertaken to defend art on this score, and to show that, far from being a mere luxury, it has serious and solid advantages. It has been even apparently exaggerated in this respect, and represented as a kind of mediator between reason and sense, between inclination and dutj', having as its mission the work of reconciling the conflicting elements in the human heart. A strong trace of this view will be found in Schiller, especiallv in all that he says about the play-instinct in his " iEsthetical Letters." Nevertheless, art is worthy' of science ; aesthetics is a true science, and the office of art is as high as that assigned to it in the pages of Schiller. We admit that art viewed onh' as an ornament and a charm is no longer free, bat a slave. But this is a perversion of its proper end. Science has to be considered as free in its aim and in its means, and it is only free when liberated from all other considerations; it rises up to truth, which is its only real object, and can alone fuUj* satisfy it'. Art in like manner is alone truly art when it is free and inde- |)endent, when it solves the problem of its high destina- tion — that problem whether it has to be placed beside religion and philosophy' as being nothing else than a particular mode or a special form of revealing God to con- sciousness, and of expressing the deepest interests of lunnan nature and the widest truths of the human mind. For it is in their works of art that the nations have iini)rinted their favorite thoughts and their richest intui- tions, and not unfrequentl}' the fine arts are the only means by which we can penetrate into the secrets of their wisdom and the mysteries of their religion. It is made a reproach to art that it produces its effects by appearance and illusion; but can it be established that INTRODUCTION. 7 appearance is objectionable? The phenomena of nature and the acts of human life are nothing more than appear- ances, and are yet looked upon as constituting a true reality ; for this reality must be sought for beyond the objects perceived immediately by the sense, the substance and speech and principle underlying all things manifesting itself in time and space through these real existences, but preserving its absolute existence in itself. Now, the very special object and aim of art is to represent the action and development of this universal force. In nature this force or principle appears confounded with particular interests and transitory' circumstances, mixed up with what is arbitrary in the passions and in individual wills. Art sets the truth free from the illusory and mendacious forms of this coarse, imperfect world, and clothes it in a nobler, purer form created bj' the mind itself. Thus the forms of art, far from being mere appearances, per- fectly illusory, contain more realitj' and truth than the phenomenal existences of the real world. The world of art is truer than that of histor}' or nature. Nor is this all : the representations of art are more ex- pressive and transparent than the phenomena of the real world or the events of historj-. The mind finds it harder to pierce through the hard envelop of nature and common life than to penetrate into works of art. Two more reflections appear completel}' to meet the objection that art or aesthetics is not entitled to the name of science. It will be generally admitted that the mind of man has the power of considering itself, of making itself its own object and all that issues from its activitj' ; for thought constitutes the essence of the mind. Now art and its work, as creations of the mind, are themselves of a spiritual nature. In this respect art is much nearer to the mind than nature. In studj'ing the works of art the mind has to do with itself, with what proceeds from itself, and is itself. Thus art finds its highest confirmation in science. Nor does art refuse a philosophical treatment because it is dependent on caprice, and subject to no law. If its highest aim be to reveal to the human consciousness the 8 iESTHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. highest interest of the mind, it is evident that the sub- stance or contents of the representations are not given up to tlie control of a wild &nd irregular imagination. It is strictly- determined by the ideas that concern our intelli- gence and by the laws of their development, whatever may be the inexhaustible variety of forms in which they are produced. Nor are these forms arbitrary, for every form is not iitted to express everj' idea. The form is deter- mined by the substance which it has to suit. A farther consideration of the true nature of beauty, and therefore of tlie vocation of the artist, will aid us still more in our endeavor to show the high dignity of art and of aesthetics. The history of philosophy presents us with many theories on the natiire of the beautiful ; but as it would lead us too far to examine them all, we shall only consider the most important among them. The coarsest of these theories defines tlie beautiful as that which pleases the senses. This theory, issuing from the philosophj- of sensation of the school of Locke and Condillac, only explains the idea and the feeling of the beautiful by dis- figuring it. It is entirely contradicted b}- facts. For it converts it into desire, but desire is egotistical and insati- able, while admiration is I'espectful, and is its own satisfaction without seeldng possession. Others liave thought the beautiful consists in proportion, and no doubt this is one of the conditions of beauty, but only one. An ill-proportioned object cannot be beautiful, but the exact correspondence of parts, as in geometrical figures, does not constitute beauty. A noted ancient theory makes beautj- consist in the per- fect suitableness of means to their end. In this case the l)eautiful is not the useful, it is the suitable ; &nd the latter idea is more akin to that of beaut3-. But it has not the true character of the beautiful. Again, order is a less mathematical idea than proportion, but it does not explain what is free and flowing in certain beanties. The most plausible theory' of beauty is that which makes It consist in two contrary a.'id eqna]]\- necessary elements — unity and variety. A beautiful flower has all the elements we have named ; it has unity, symmetry, and variety of shades of color. There is no beauty without INTRODUCTION. H life, and life is movement, diversit3-. These elements are found in beautiful and also in sublime objects. A beautiful object is complete, finished, limited with symmet- rical parts. A sublime object whose forms, though not out of proportion, are less determined, ever awakens in us the feeling of the infinite. In objects of sense all qualities that can produce the feeling of the beautiful come under one class called physical beaut}-. But above and beyond this in the region of mind we have first intellectual beautj', including the laws that govern intelligence and the creative genius of the artist, the poet, and the philosopher. Again, the moral world has beautj' in its ideas of libert}-, of virtue, of devotion, the justice of Aristides, the heroism of Leonidas. We have now ascertained that there is beaut^' and sublimity in nature, in ideas, in feelings, and in actions. After ail this it might be supposed that a unity could be found amidst these different kinds of beauty. The sight of a statue, as the Apollo of Belvedere, of a man, of Socrates expiring, are adduced as producing impressions of tlie beautiful ; but the form cannot be a form l)y itself, it must be the form of something. Physical be.Tiity is the sign of an interior beauty, a spiritual and moral beauty which is the basis, the principle, and the unity of the beautiful. Physical beauty is an envelop to intellectual and to moral beautj-. • Intellectual beautj', the splendor of the true, can only have for principle that of all truth. Moral beauty comprehends two distinct elements, equallj- beautiful, justice and charity. Thus God is the principle of the three orders of beauty, physical, intellectual, and moral. He also construes the two great powers distrib- uted over the three orders, the beautiful and the sublime. God is beaut}' par excellence ; He is therefore perfectly beautiful ; He is equally sublime. He is to us the type and sense of the two great forms of beauty. In short, the Absolute Being as absolute unit}- and absolute variety is necessarily the ultimate principle, the extreme basis, the finished ideal of all beautj-. This was the marvellous beauty which Diotimus had seen, and which is described in the Banquet of Socrates. so jJESTPE'nCAI. LETTKK.s A.Vi) KSSAVS. It i'l our purpose after the prcvio-.is discussion to aUempt to elucidate still furthsr the 'deft o*' art b^' follow- ing its historic development. Manj- questions bearing on prt and relating to the beautiful had been propounded hsfore, even as far back as Plotinus, Plato, and Socrates^ but recent times have been the real cradle of aesthetics as a science. Modern philosophy was the first to recognise that beautj- in art is one of the means by vrhich the contradictions can be removed between mind considered in its abstract and absolute existence and nature constituting the world of sense, bringing back these two factors to unity. Kant was the first, who felt the want of this union and expressed it, but without determining its conditions or "expressing it scientifically. He was impeded in his efl'orts to eflfect this union by the opposition between the subjec- tive and the objective, by his placing practical reason ^bove theoretical reason, and he set up the opposition found in the moral sphere as the highest principle of morality. Reduced to this difficulty, all that Kant could ilo was to express the union under the form of the sub- jective ideas of reason, or as postulates to be deduced from the practical reason, without their essential character being known, and representing their realization as nothing more than a simple i/ou ought, or imperative " Du soUst." In his teleological judgment applied to living beings, Kant comes, on the contrary; to consider the living organ- ism in such wise that, the general including the particular, and determining it as an end, consequently the idea also determines the external, the compound of the organs, not by an act springing from without but issuing from within. In this way the end and th6 means, the interior and ex- terior, the general and particular, are confounded in unity. But this judgment onlj' expresses a subjective act of reflection, and does not throw any light on the object in itself. Kant has the same view of the aesthetic judgment. According to him the judgment does not pro- ceed either from reason, as the faculty of general ideas, or from sensuous perception, but from the free pla}- of the reason and of the imagination. In this analysis of the INTRODUCTION. 11 cognitive facultj', the oliject only exists relatively to the subject and to the feeling of pleasure or the enjoy- ment that it experiences. The characteristics of the beautiful are, according to Kant : — 1. The pleasure it procures is free from interest. 2'. Beauty appears to us as an object of general enjoy- ment, without awaliening in us the consciousness of an abstract idea and of a category of reason to which we might refer our judgment. 3. Beautj' ought to embrace in itself the relation of conformit}' to its end, but in such a way that this conform- ity may be grasped without the idea of the end being offered to our mind. 4. Though it be not accompanied by an abstract idea, beauty ought be to aclinowledged as the object of a neces- sar3' enjoyment. _ A^ged£U_XeiUJli^Li^f^aU this systemJs thejndissgluble J;li3it31_of_vi^at^su|jpo8ed_tojte^ in consciousness. This distinction disappears in the beautifijl, because inlt the general and tlie particular, the end and the means, the idea and the object, mentally penetrate each other com- pletely. The particular in itself, whether it be opposed to itself or to what is general, is something accidental. But here what may be considered as an accidental form is so intimateh' connected with the general that it is con- founded and identified with-it. By this means the beauti- ful in art presents thought to us as incarnate. On the other hand, matter, nature, the sensuous as themselves possessing measure, end, and harmony, are raised to the dignity of spirit and share in its general character. Thought not only abandons its hostility against nature, but smiles in her. Sensation and enjoyment are justified and sanctified, so that nature and liberty, sense and ideas, find their justification and their sanctiflcation in this union. Nevertheless this reconciliation, though seem- ingly perfect, is stricken with the character of subjective- ness. It cannot constitute the absolutely true and real. Such is an outline of the principal results of Kant's criticism, .ind Hegel passes high praise on the profoundly philosophic mind of Schiller, who demanded the union 12 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. and reconciliation of tlie two principles, and who tried to give a scientific explanation of it before the problem had been solved by philosophy. In his " Letters on Esthetic Education," Schiller admits that man carries in himself the germ of the ideal man which is realized and repre- sented by the state. There are two ways for the individual man to approach the ideal man ; first, when the state, considered as morality, justice, and general reason, absorbs the individualities in its unity ; secondly, when the indi- vidual rises to the ideal of his species by the perfecting of himself Reason demands unity, conformity to the species ; nature, on the other hand, demands plurality and individuality ; and man is at once solicited by two contrary laws. In this conflict, aesthetic education must come in to effect the reconciliation of the two principles ; for, according to Schiller, it has as its end to fashion and polish the inclinations and passions so that thej- may become reasonable, and that, on the other hand, reason and freedom may issue from their abstract character, may unite with nature, may spiritualize it, become incarnate, and take a body in it. Beauty is thus given as the simul- taneous development of the rational and of the sensuous, fused together, and interpenetrated one hy the other, an union that constitutes in fact true reality. This unitj' of the general and of the particular, of liberty' and necessity of the spiritual and material, which Schiller understood scientiflcallj' as the spirit of art, and which he tried to make appear in real life by aesthetic art and edu- cation, was afterwards put forward under the name of idea as the principle of all knowledge and existence. In this way, through the agency of Schelling, science raised itself to an absolute point of view. It was thus that art began to claim its proper nature and dignity. From that time its proper place was finally marked out for it in science, though the mode of A'iewing it still labored under certain defects. Its high and true distinction were at length understood. In viewing the higher position to which recent philo- sophical systems have raised the theory of art in Germany, we must not overlook the ndvantnges contributed by the study of the ideal of the ancients by such men as Winckel- INTRODUCTION. 13 mann, who, by a kind of inspiration, raised art criticism from a carping about petty details to seelc the true spirit of great works of art, and their true ideas, by a study of the spirit of the originals. It has appeared expedient to conclude this introduction with a summary of the latest and highest theory of art and aesthetics issuing from Kant and Schiller, and devel- oped in the later philosophy of Hegel. Our space only allows us to give a glance, first, at the metaphysics of the beautiful as developed by Hegel in the, first part of his ' Aesthetik,' and then at the later development of the same system in recent writers issuing from his school. Hegel considers, first, the abstract idea of the beautiful ; secoudlj', beauty in nature ; thirdl}', beauty in art or the ideal ; and he winds up with an examination of the qualities of the artist. His preliminary remarks are directed to show the rela- tions of art to religion and pliilosoph}-, and he shows that man's destination is an infinite development. In real life he only satisfies his longing partially and imperfectly by limited enjoyments. In science he finds a nobler pleasure, and civil life opens a career for his acti^■itJ■ ; but he only finds an imperfect pleasure in these pursuits. He cannot then find the ideal after which he sighs. Tlien lie rises to a higher sphere, where all contradictions are effaced and the ideas of good and happiness are realized in perfect accord and in constant harmonj-. This deep want of the soul is satisfied in three ways : in art, in religion, and in philosophj^ Art is intended to make us contemplate the true and the infinite in forms of sense. Yet even art does not fully satisfy the deepest need of the soul. The soul wants to contemplate truth in its inmost consciousness. Religion is placed above the dominion of art. First, as to idea of the beautiful, Hegel begins by giving its characteristics. It is infinite, and it is free ; the contemplation of the beautiful suffices to itself, it awakens no desire. The soul experiences something like a godlike felicity and is transported into a sphere remote from the miseries of life. This theory of the beautiful comes verj' near that of Plato, 14 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. Secondly, as to beauty in nature. Physical beauty, considered externallj^ presents itself successivel}' under the aspects of regularity and of symmetry, of conformity with a law, and of harmony, also of purity and simplicity of matter. Thirdly, beauty in art or the ideal is beauty in a higher degree of perfection than real beauty. The ideal in art is not contrary to the real, but the real idealized, purified, and perfectly expressed. The ideal is also the soul arrived at the consciousness of itself, free and fully enjoying its faculties ; it is life, but spiritual life and spirit. Nor is the ideal a cold abstraction, it is the spiritual principle under the form of a living individuality freed from the laws of the finite. The ideal in its highest form is the divine, as expressed in the Greek divinities ; the Christian ideal, as expressed in all its highest purity in God the Father, the Christ, the Virgin. Its essential features are calm, majesty, serenity. At a lower degree the ideal is in man the victory of the eternal principles that fill the human heart, the triumph of the nobler part of the soul, the moral and divine principle. But the ideal manifested in the world becomes action, and action implies a form of society, a determinate situa- tion with collision, and an action properly so called. The heroic age is the best society for the ideal in action ; in Its determinate situation the ideal in action must appear as the manifestation of moral power, and in action, properly so called, it must contain three points in the ideal: first, general principles ; secondly, personages ; thirdly, their character and their passions. Hegel winds up 'by con- sidering the quahties necessary in an artist : imagination, genius, inspiration, originality, etc. A recent exponent of Hegel's sesthetical ideas further developed expresses himself thus on the nature of beauty : — " After the bitterness of the world, the sweetness of art soothes and refreshes us. This is the high value of the beautiful — that it solves the contradiction of mind and matter of the moral and sensuous world, in harmony. Ihus the beautiful and its representation in art procures for intuition what philosophy gives to the cognitive insight INTEODUOTION. 15 and religLon to the believing frame of mind. Hence tlie deliglit with which Schiller's wonderful poem on the Bell celebrates the accord of the inner and outer life, the fulfil- ment of the longing and demands of the soul by the events in nature. The externality- of phenomena is removed in the beautiful ; it is raised into the circle of ideal existence ; for it is recognized as the revelation of the ideal, and thus transfigured it gives to the latter additional splendor. " Thus the beautiful is active, living unity, full existence without defect, as Plato and Schelling have said, or as recent writers describe it ; the idea that is quite present in the appearance, the appearance which is quite formed and penetrated bj' the idea." " Beauty is the world secret that invites us in image and word," is the poetical expression of Plato ; and we may add, beca;use it is revealed in both. We feel in it the harmony of the world ; it breaks forth in a beautj', in a lo\ely accord, in a radiant point, and starting thence we penetrate further and yet further, and find as the ground of all existence the same charm which had refreshed us in individual forms. Thus Christ pointed to the lilies of the field to knit His followers' reliance on Providence with the phenomena of nature : and could they jet forth in royal beauty, exceeding that of Solomon, if the inner ground of nature were not beauty? We may also name beauty in a certain sense a mys- terj-, as it mediates to us is a sensuous sign a heavenly gift of grace, that it opens to us a view into the Eternal Being, teaching us to know nature in God and God in nature, that it brings the divine even to the perception of sense, and establishes the energy of love and free- dom as the ground, the bond, and the end of the world. In the midst of the temporal the eternal is made pal- pable and j)resent to us in the beautiful, and offers itself to our enjoyment. The separation is suppressed, and the original unity, as it is in God, appears as the first, as what holds together even the past in the uni- verse, and what constitutes the aim of the development in a finite accord. The beautiful not only presents itself to us as mediator of a foreign excellence or of a remote divinity, but the 16 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. ideal and the godlike are present in it. Hence aesthetics requires as its basis the sj'stem in which God is known as indwelling in the world, that He is not far distant from any one of us, but that He animates us, and that we live in Him. ^Esthetics requires the knowledge that mind is the creative force and unitj' of all that is extended and developed in time and space. The beautiful is thus, according to these later thinkers, the revelation of God to the mind through the senses ; it is the appearance of the idea. Tn f.he beautiful spirit reveals itself to spirit through matter and^the senses ; thus the._entire inanT feels hini^_elf.i'aised and... satisfied „bj: it. By the unitj- of the beautiful with us we experience with delight that thought and the material world are present for our individualitj', that the_v utter tones and fehine forth in it, that both penetrate each other and blend in it and thus become one with it. We feel one with them and one in them. This later -view was to a great extent expressed b}- Schiller in his "^sthetical Letters." But art and aesthetics, in the sense in which these terms are used and understood by German philosoi^hical writers, such as Schiller, embrace a wider field than the fine arts. Lessing, in his " Laocoon," had already shown the point of contrast between painting and poetry ; and aesthetics, being defined as the science of the beautiful, must of necessity embrace poetrj-. Accordingly Schiller's essays on tragic art, pathos, and sentimental poetry, contained in this volume, are justly classed under his aesthetical writings. This being so, it is important to estimate briefly the transitions of German poetry before Schiller, and the position that he occupied in its historic development. The first classical period of German poetry and litera- ture was contained between A.D 1190 and 1300. It extiibits the intimate blending of the German and Chris- tian elements, and their full development in splendid productions, for this was the period of the German na- tional epos, the " Nibelungenlied," and of the " Minne- gesang." ' This was a period which has nothing to compare with INTRODUCTION. 17 it in point of art and poetiy, save perhaps, and that im- perfectlj', the heroic and post-Homeric age of earlj- Greece. The poetical efforts of that early age may be grouped under — (1) national epos : the ■■ Nibelungenlied ; " (2) art epos: the " Rolandslied," " Percival," etc. ; (3) the introduction of antique legends: Veldeck's "JSneide," and Konrad's " War of Tro}- ; " (4) Christian legends: '' Barlaam," " S3'lvester," " Pilatus,"&c. ; (5)poetical nar- ratives : " Crescentia," " Graf Rudolf," etc. ; (6) animal legends; " Reinecke Vos ; " (7) didactic poems: " Der Renner ; " (8) the Miune-poetrj', and prose. The fourth group, ttiough introduced from a foreign source, gives the special character and uiueh of tlie charm of the period we consider. This is the sphere of legends derived from ecclesiastical ground. One of the best German writers on the history of German literature remarks: "If the aim and nature of all poetry is to let yourself be filled bj' a subject and to become penetrated with it ; if the simple representation of unartificial, true, and glowing feelings belongs to its most beautiful adornments ; if the faithful direction of the heart to the invisible and eternal is the ground on which at all times the most lovely flowers of poetry have sprouted forth, these legendarj' poems of early Germany, in their lovel}' heartiness, in their unambitious limitation, and their pious sense, deserve a friendl}- acknowledg- ment. What man has confidered the pious images in the praj'er-books of the Middle Ages, the unadorned inno- cence, the piet}' and purit3', the patience of the martyrs, the calm, heavenly transparency of the figures of the holy angels, without being attracted by the simple innocence and hurailitj' of these forms, the creation of pious artists' hands? Who has beheld them without tranquil joy at the soft splendor poured over them, without deep sym- pathy, nay, without a certain emotion and tenderness? And the same spirit that created these images also pro- duced those poetical effusions, the same spirit of pious belief, of deep devotion, of heavenly longing. If we make a present realitj- of the heroic songs of the early German popular poetry, and the chivalrous epics of the 18 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. art poetiy, the military expeditions and dress of the Crusades, this legendary poetry appears as the invention of humble pilgrims, who wander slowly on the weary way to Jerusalem, with scollop and pilgrim's staff', engaged in quiet prayer, till they are all to kneel at the Saviour's sepulchre '; and thus contented, after touching the holy earth with their lips, they return, poor as they were, but full of holy comfort, to their distant home. ' ' While the knightly poetry is the poetry of the splen- did secular life, full of cheerful joy, full of harp-tones and song, full of tournaments and joyous festivals, the poetry of the earthly love for the earthly bride, the poetry of the legends is that of the spontaneous life of poverty, the poetry of the solitary cloister cell, of the quiet, well-walled convent garden, the poetry of heavenly brides, who without lamenting the jo3-s of the world, which they need not, have their joy in their Saviour in tranquil piety and devout resignation — who attend at the espousals of Anna and Joachim, sing the Magnificat with the Holy Mother of God, stand weeping beneath the cross, to be pierced also bj' the sword, who hear the angel harp with St. Cecilia, and walk with St. Theresa in the glades of Paradise. While the Miune-poetr}' was the tender homage offered to the beauty, the gentleness, the grace, and charm of noble women of this world, legendary poetry. was the homage given to the Virgin Mother, the Queen of Hea^•en, transfiguring earthly love into a heavenly and eternal love. " P'or the twelfth and thirteenth centuries were the time of woman cidtus, such as has never been before or since seen ; it is also the time of the deepest and simplest and truest, most enthusiastic and faithful veneration of theVirgin Mary. If we, by a certain eff'ort, manage to place ourselves back on the standpoint of childlike poetic faith of that time, and set aside in thought the materializing and exaggera- tion of the hagiology and Mariolatrj' produced b3' later centuries, rendering the reaction of the Reformation unavoidable — if now in our age, turned exclusively to logical ideas and a negative dialectic, we live again b)- thought in those ages of feeling and poetrj- — if we acknowledge all these things to be something more than INTRODUCTION. 19 harmless play of words and faucj-, and as the true lifelike contents of the period, then we can properly appreciate this legendary poetry as a necessary link in the crown of pearls of our ancient poetrj-." In short, the first classical period of German literature vvas a time of youthful freshness, of pure harmonj-, plunged in verse and song, full of the richest tones and the noblest rhythm, so thai rhyme and song alone must be looked for as the form of poetic creations. Accordingl}- it had no proper prose. Like our own youth, it was a happj-, free, and true j-outh, it knew no prose ; like us it dreamed to speechless songs ; and as we expressed our jouthfnl language and hopes, woes and joj'S, in rhyme and song, thus a whole people and age had its beautiful youth full of song and verse tones. The life was poetrj- and poetr}- was the life. Then came degeneracy and artifice ; after that the great shock of the Reformation ; subsequentlj' a servile and pedantic studj' of classical forms without imbibing their spirit, but preparing the way for a truer art spirit, ex- tracted from their study bj' the masterly criticism of Winckelmann and Lessing, till the second classical period of German literature and poetry bloomed forth in full beauty, blending the national and legendary elements so well expressed bj- Herder with the highest eff"usions of dramatic poetry, partly creative and partlj- imitative of the Greek models, in Schiller a^d Goethe. Modern German literature presents a ^•ely remarkable spectacle, though far from unique in historj-, for there we see criticism begetting genius. Lessing, the founder of the modern German drama, sought to banish all pomp from the theatre, and in doing so some critics have thought that he banished the ideal and fell nito aflfectation. At any rate, his " Dramaturgy " is full of original ideas, and when he drew out the sphere of poetry contrasted with that of painting in his " Laocoon," all Germany resounded with his praise. " AVith that delight," says Goethe, " we saluted this luminous ray which a thinker of the first order caused to break forth from its clouds. It is necessary to have all the fire of youth to conceive the effect produced on us bj" the ' Lao- 20 iESTHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. coon' of Lessing." Another great contemporary, whose name is imperishable as that of art, struck a mortal blow at a false taste in the study of the antique. Winckelmann questioned the works of the Greek chisel with an intelli- gence full of love, and initiated his countrymen into poetry by a feeling for sculpture ! What an enthusiasm he displayed ff)r classical beauty ! what a worship of the form ! what a fervor of paganism is found in its eloquent pages when he also comments on the admirable group of "the Laoooon, or the still purer masterpiece of the Apollo of Belvedere. These men were the vanguard of the great Germanic army ; Schiller and Goethe alone formed its main column. In t'hem German poetry shows itself in its perfection, and completely realizes the ideal designed for it by the critic. Kvery factitious precept and conventional law was now overthrown ; these poetical Protestants broke away en- tirely from the yoke of tradition. Yet their genius was not without a rule. Every work bears in itself the organic laws of its development. Thus, although they laugh at the famous precept of the three unities, it is because they dig still deeper down to the root of things, to grasp the true principle from which the precept issued. "Men have not understood," said Goethe, " the basis of this law. The law of the comprehensive — • das Fassliche ' — is the principle ; an I the three unities have only value as far as they attain it. When they become an obstacle to the comprehension it is madness to wish to observe thom. The Greeks themselves, from whom the rule is derived, did not alwaj's follow it. In the 'Phaeton' of Euri- pides, and in other pieces, there was change, place ; ac- cordingly they prefer to give a perfect exposition of their subject, rather than blindlj- respect a law never very essential in itself. The pieces of Shakspeare violate in the highest degree the unity of time and of place ; but they are full of comprehensiveness ; nothing is easier to grasp, and for that reason they would have found favor. with the Greeks. The French poets tried to obey exactly the law of the three unities ; but they violate the law of comprehensiveness, as they do not expound dramatic sub- jects by dramas but by recitals." INTRODUCTION. 21 Poetical creation was therefore viewed as free, but at tlie same time responsible. Immediatel}', as if fecundity were the reward of correctness, the German tiieatre be- came filled with true and li\'ing characters The stage widens under their steps that they maj- have room to mo\-e. Histoiy with its great proportions and its terrible lessons, is now able to take place on the stage. The whole Thirtj- Years' War passes before us in " Wallenstein." We hear the tumult of camps, the disorder of a fanatical and un- disciplined army, peasants, recruits, sutlers, soldiers. The • iUusion is complete, and enthusiasm breaks out among the spectators. Similar merits attach to many other of Schil- ler's plays. This new drama, which seemed to give all to the natural sphere, concedes still more to the ideal. An able critic has said the details which are the truth of history are also its poetry. Here the German school professes a principle of the highest learning, and one that seems to be borrowed from its profoundest philosophers ; it is that of the uni- versal beautj' of life, of the identity- of beauty and exist- ence. "Our aesthetics," says Goethe, "speak a great deal of poetical or antipeetical subjects ; fundamentally there is no subject that has not its poetry ; it is for the poet to find it there." Schiller and Goethe divide the empire over modern Ger- man poetry, and represent its two principal powers ; the one, Schiller, impassioned^nd lyrical, pours his soul over all the subjects he touches ; in him every composition, ode, or drama is always one of his noble ideas, borrowing its di'ess and ornament from the external world. He is a poet especially through the heart, by the force with which he rushes in and carries you with hira. Goethe is espe- cially an epic ; no doubt he paints the passions with admir- able truth, but he commands them ; like the god of the seas in Virgil, he raises above the angry waves his calm and sublime forehead. After this glance at the position and chief characteristics of Schiller, it may be useful to ofl'er a few remarks on those of the principal works in this volume, his ^sthetical Letters and Essays. Schiller, in his iEsthetical Essays, did not choose the pure abstract method of deduction and 22 .ESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. conception like Kant, nor the historical lilje Herder, who strove thns to account for tlie genesis of our ideas of beauty and art. lie struck out a middle path, which pre- sents certain deficiencies to the advocates of either of these two systems. Me leans upon Kantian ideas, but without scholastic constraint. Pure speculation, which seeks to set free the form from all contents and matter, was remote from his creative genius, to which the world of matter and sense was no hinderance, but a necessarj- envelop for his forms. His removal to Jena in 1791, and acquaintance with- Reinhold, familiarized him with the Kantian philosophy, but he only appreciated it by halves. The bare and bald dealing with fundamental principles was at this time equally repulsive to Goethe and Schiller, the man of the world and the man of life. But Schiller did not find any- where at that time justice done to the dignit}' of art, or honor to the substantial value of beauty. The iEsthetical Essays in this volume appeared for the most part since 1792, in the "Thalia" and the "Hours" pei'iodicals. The first, " On the Ground of our Pleasure in Tragic Subjects" (1792), applies Kantian princii)les of the sublime to traged}', and shows Schiller's I<;fty estimate of this class of poetry-. With Kant he pjiows that the source of aW pleasure is suitableness; the touching and sublime elicit this feeling, implj-ing the existence of un- suitableness. In this article he makes the aim and source of art to consist in giving enjoyment, in pleasing. To na- ture pleasure is a mediate object, to art its main object. The same proposition appears in Schiller's paper on Tragic Art (1792), closely connected with the former. This article contains views of the affection of pity that seem to approximate the Aristotelian propositions about tragedy. His views on the sublime are expressed in two papei's. " The Sublime" and " The Pathetic," in which we trace con- siderable influence of Lessing and Winckelmann. He is led especially to strong antagonism against the French fragedj-, and he indulges in a lengthy consideration of the passage of Virgil on Laocoon, showing the necessity of suffering and the pathetic in connection with moral adapt- ations to interest us deeply. INTRO DUCTIOX. 23 All these essays bespeak the poet who has tiiod his hand at tragi'cly, Viiit in liis next |)!iper, " On Ora'je and Dignity," we trace more of the moralist. Those passages where he takes up a medium position between sen;e and re,ason, between Goethe and Kant, are specially attractive. The therae of this paper is the conception of grace, or the ex- pression of a beautiful soul and dignity, or that of a lofty mind. The idea of grace has been developed more deeply and truly by Schiller than by Wieland or Winckelmann, but the special value of the paper is its constantly point- ing to the ideal of a higher humanity'. In it he does full justice to the sensuous and to the moral, and commencing with the beautiful nature of the Greeks, to whom sense was never mere sense, nor reason mere reason, he con- cludes with an image of perfected humanity in which grace and dignitj- are united, the former by architectonic beauty (structure), the last supported by power. Tlie following year, 1795, appeared his most important contribution to sesthetics, in his ^sthetical Letters. In these letters he remarks that beauty is the work of free contemplation, and we enter with it into the world of ideas, but without leaving the world of sense. Beauty is to us an object, and yet at the same time a state of oui subjectivity, because the feeling of the conditional is under that which we have of it. Beauty is a form because we consider it, and life because we feel it ; in a word, it is at once our state and our ajjt. And exactly because it is both it serves us as a triumphant proof that suffering does not exclude activity, nor matter form, nor limitation the infinite, for in the enjoj'ment of beauty both natures are united, and by this is proved, the capacity of the infinite to be developed in the finite, and according!}- the possi- bility of the sublimest humanity. The free play of the facultj- of cognition which had been determined bj- Kant is also developed by Schiller. His representation of this matter is this : Man, as a spirit, is reason and will, self-active, determining, form-giving ; this is described by Schiller as the forui-instinct ; man, as a sensuous being, is determinable, receptive, termed to matter ; Schiller describes this as the material instinct, ■' Stofftrieb." In the midst between these two is situated 24 7ESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAVS. the beautiful, in wliicb ix'ason and the sensuous ijenetrate each other, and theii- enjoval)le product is designated b}- Schiller the play instinct. This expression is not happily chosen. Schiller means to descrilic by it the free play of the forces, activity according to nature, which is at once a joy and a happiness ; he reminds us of the life of Olympus, arid adds: "Man is only quite a man when he plays." Personality is that which fasts, the state of feeling is the changeable in man; he, is the fixed unity remaining eternally himself in the floods of change. Man in con- tact with the world is to take it up in himself, but to unite with it the highest freedom and independence, and, instead of being lost in the world, to subject it to his reason. It is only b3- his being independent that there is reality out of him ; onl^- by being susceptible of feeling that there is reality in him. The olyect of sensuous instinct is life; that of the purer instinct figure ; living figure or beauty is the object of tiie play instinct. Only inasmuch as life is formed in the understanding and form in feeling does life win a form and form win life, and only thus does beauty arise. By beauty the sensuous man is led up to reason, the one-sided tension of special force is strung to harmon}-", and man made a complete whole. Schiller adds that beauty knits together thought and feeling ; the fullest unity of spirit and matter. Its free- dom is not lack, but harmony, of laws ; its conditions are not exclusions, inclusion of all infinity determined in itself. A true work of art generates lofty serenitj" and' freedom of mind. Thus the aesthetic disposition bestows on us the highest of all gifts, that of a disposition to humanity, and we may call beauty our second creator. In tliese letters Schiller spoke out the mildest and high- est sentiments on art, and in his paper on Simple and Sentimental Poetry (171)5) he constructs the ideal of the perfect poet. This is by far the most fruitful of Schiller's essays in its results. It has much that is practically applicable, and contains a veiy able estimate of German poetry. The writing is also \-ery pointed and telling, because it is based upon actual perceptions, and it is interesting because tlie contrast drawn out throughout it INTRODICTIOX. 25 between tlie simple and tlie sentimental lias been I'ofeneil to his own contrast with Goethe. He also wislied to vin- dicate modern poetry, which Goethe seemed to wish to sacrifice to the antique. The sentimental poefcrj- is tiie fruit of qniet and retire- ment ; simple poetry the child of life. One is a favor of nature ; the sentimental depends on itself, the simple on the world of experience. The sentimental is in danger of extending the limits of human nature too far, of being too ideal, too mj-stical. Neither character exhausts the ideal of humanitj-, but the intimate union of both. Both are founded in human nature ; the contradictions hing at their basis, when cleared in thought from the poetical faculty, are realism and idealism. These also are sides of human nature, which, when unconnected, bring forth disastrous results. Their opposition is as old as the^ beginning of culture, and till its end can hardly be set aside, save in the individual. The idealist is a nobler but a far less perfect being ; the realist appears far less noble, but is more perfect, for the noble lies in the proof of a great capacity, but the perfect in the general attitude of the whole and in the real facts. On the whole it may be said, taking a survey of these labors, that if Schiller had developed his ideas system- atically and the unity of his intuition of the world, which were present in his feelings, and if he had based them scientiflcallj-, a new epoch in philosophy might have been anticipated. For he had obtained a view of such a future field of thought with the deep clairvoyance of his genius. A few words may be desirable on Schiller's religious standpoint, especially in connection with his philosophical letters Schiller came up ten j-ears later than Goethe, and con- cluded the cyclus of genius that Goethe had inaugurated. But as he was the last arrival of that productive period of tempestuous agitation, he retained more of its ele- ments in his later life and poetry than any others who had passed through earlier agitations, such as Goethe. For Goethe cast himself free in a great measure from the earl}- intoxication of his youthful imagination, de- 26 ^STHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. voting himself partly to iioblci' matter and partly to purer forms. Schiller derived from the stormy times of his youth his direction to the ideal, to the hostility against the narrow spirit of civil relations, and to all given conditions of society in general. He derived from it his disposition, not to let himself be moulded by matter, but to place his own creative and determining impress on matter, not so much to grasp reality poetically and represent it poetically as to cast ideas into reality, a disposition for lively represent- ation and strong oratorical coloring. All this he derived from the genial period, though later on somewhat modi- fied, and carried it over into his whole life and poetry; and for this very reason he is not only together with Goethe, but before Goethe, the favorite poet of the nation, and especially with that part of the nation which sympa- thizes with him in the choice of poetic material and in his mode of feeling. Gerviniis remarks that Schiller had at Weimar long fallen off from Christianity, and occupied his mind tran- quilly for a time with the views of Spinoza (realistic panthe- ism). Like Herder and Goethe, lie viewed life in its great entirety, and sacrificed the individual to the species. Aecoidingly, through the gods of Greece, he fell out with strict, orthodox Christians. But Schiller had deeply religious and even Christian elements, as became a German and a Kantian. He re- ceives the Godhead in His will, and He descends from His throne. He dwells in his soul ; the poet sees divine reve- lations, and as a seer announces them to man. He is a moral educator of his people, who utters the tones of life in his poetry from youth upwards. Philosophy was not disclosed to Plato in the highest and purest thought, nor is poetry to Schiller merely an artificial edifice in the har- mony of speech ; philosophj- and poetry are to both a vibration of love in the soul upwards to God, a liberation from the bonds of sense, a purification of man, a moral art. On this reposes the religious consecration of the Platonic spirit and of that of Schiller. Issuing from the philosophical school of Kant, and .'mbued with the antagonism of the aiie against constituted INTRODCOTION. 27 authorities, it is natural tliat .Scliilier siiould be a rational- ist in his religious views. It has been justl}' said of him that while Goethe's system was an apotheosis of nature Schiller's was an apotheosis of man. Historically he was not pi-epared enough to test and search the question of evidence as applied to divine things handed down b^' testimony, and his Kantian coloring naturallj' disposed him to include all religions within the limits of pure reason, and to seek it rather in the subject than in an3-thing objective. In conclusion, we may attempt to classify and give Schiller his place in the progress of the world's literarj- history. Progress is no doubt a law of the individual, of nations, and of the whole race. To grow in perfection, to exist in some sort at a higher degree, is the task im- posed b}' God on man, the continuation of the very work of God, the complement of creation. But this moral growth, this need of increase, may, like all the forces of nature, yield to a greater force ; it is an impulsion rather than a necessity ; it solicits and does not constrain. A thousand obstacles stay its development in individuals and in societies ; moral liberty ma^- retard or accelerate its effects. Progress is therefore a lavv which cannot be abro- gated, but which is not invariabl}' obeyed. Nevertheless, in proportion to the increase of the mass of individuals, the caprices of chance and of liberty' neu- tralize each other to allow tke providential action that presides over our destinies to prevail. Looking at the same total of the life of the world, humanity undoubtedly advances : there are in our time fewer moral miseries, fewer ph^-sical miseries, than were known in the past. Consequently art and literature, which express the dif- ferent states of society, must share in some degree in this progressive march. But there are two things in literary work : on the one hand the ideas and social manners which it expresses, on tlie other the intelligence, the feehng, the imagination of the writer who becomes its interpreter. While the former of these elements tends incessantly to a greater perfection, the latter is subject to all the hazards of individual genius. Accordingly the progressive litera- ture is only in the inspiration, and so to speak in the 28 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. matter; it may and must therefore not lie eontinnous in form. Bnt more than (his : in very ad\anced societies tiie very grandenr of ideas, the al)undanee of models, the satiety of the public render the task of the artist more and more difficult. The aitist himself lias no longer the enthusiasm of the first ages, the youth of imagination and of the heart ; he is an old man whose riches have increased, but who enjoys his wealtli less. If all the epochs of literature- are considered as a whole it will be seen that they succeed each other in a constant order. After the period when the idea and the form com- bined in a harmonious manner comes another where the social idea is superabundant, and destrojs the literar3- form of the preceding epoch. The middle ages introduced spiritualism in art; before this new idea the smiling untruths of Greek [loetry fled away frightened. The classical form so beautiful, so pure, cannot contain high Catholic thought. A new art is formed ; on this side the Alps it does not reach the ma- turity that produces masterpieces. But at that time all Europe was one fatherland ; Ital3- completes what is lack- ing in France and elsewhere. The renaissance introduces new ideas intt) civilization; it resuscitates the traditions of antique science and seeks to unite them to the truths of Christianity. The art of the middle ages, as a vessel of too limited capacity, is broken bj- the n-ew flood poured into it. These different ideas are stirred up and in conflict in the sixteenth cen- tury ; the^' became co-ordinate and attain to an admirable expression in the following a'ge. In the eighteenth century there is a new invasion of ideas; all is examined and questioned ; religion, govern- ment, society, all becomes a matter of discussion foi' tlie school called [ihilosophical. Poetry appeared dying out. history drying up, till a truer spirit was breathed into the literarj' atmosphere by the criticism of Lessing, the phi- losophy of Kant, and the poetry of Klopstock. It was at this transition period that Schiller appeared, retaining throughout his literary career nuich of the revolutionary and convulsive spirit of his eai-ly days, and faithfuUV INTRODUCTION. 29 reflecting much of the dominant German philosophj' of his time. Part of the nineteenth century seems to take in hand the task of reconstructing the moral edifice and of giving back to tliought a larger form Tlie literary result of its effects is the renaissance of Ijrical poetry- with an admira- ble development in history, Schiller's most brilliant works were in the former walk, his histories have inferior merit, and his philosophical writings bespeak a deep thinking nature with great origi- nality of conception, such as naturally results from a combination of high poetic inspiration with much intellect- ual power. Schiller, Hke all great men of genius, was a representa- tive man of his country and of his age. A German, a Protestant free-thinker, a woi'shipper of the classical, he was the expression of these aspects of national and gen- eral thought. The religious reformation was the work of tht North. The instinct of races came iu it to complicate the questions of dogmas. The awakening of individual nationalities was one of the characters of the epoch. The nations compressed in the severe unity of the Mid- dle Ages escaped in the Reformation from the uniform mould that had long enveloped them, and tended to that other unity, still very distant, which must spring from the spontaneous view of the same truth by all men, result from the free and original development of each nation, and, as in a vast concert, unite harmonious disonances. Europe, without being conscious of its aim, seized greed- ily at the means — insurrection ; the only thought was to overthrow, without yet thinking of a reconstruction. The sixteenth century was the vanguard of the eighteenth. At all times the North had fretted under the antipathetic yoke of the South. Under the Romans, Germany, though frequently conquered, had never been subdued. She had invaded the Empire and determined its fall. In the Mid- dle Ages the struggle had continued ; not only instincts, but ideas, were in conflict ; force and spirit, violence and polity, feudalism and the Catholic hierarchy, hereditary and elective forms, represeuted the opposition of two 30 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. races. In the sixteenth century the schism long antici- pated toolv place. The Catholic dogma had hitherto triumphed over all outbreaks — over Arnaldo of Brescia, the Waldenses, and Wickhffe. But Luther appeared, and the work was accomplished : Catholic unit}- was broken. _ And this bivaking with authority went on fernientin-; in the nations till its last great outburst at the French Revo- lution ; and Schiller was born at this convulsive period, and bears strong traces of his parentage in his anti-dog- matic spirit. Yet there is another side to Germanism which is prone to the ideal and the mystical, and bears still the trace of those lovely legends of mediaeval growth to which we have adverted. For Christianity was not a foreign and antag- onistic importation in Germany ; rather, the German char- acter obtained its completeness through Christianity. The German found himself again in the Church of Christ, only raised, transfigured, and sanctified. The apostolic repre- sentation of the Church as the bride of Christ has found its fullest and truest correspondence in that of Germany. Hence when the German spirit was thoroughly espoused to the Ciiristian spirit, we find that character of love, tenderness, and depth so characteristic of the early class- sics of German poetry, and reappearing in glorious after- glow in the second classics, in Klopstock, Herder, and, above all, Schiller. It is this special instinct for the ideal and mystical in German nature that has enabled spirits born of negation and revolution, like Schiller, to unite with those elements the most genial and creative inspirations of poetrj'. VOCABULARY OF TERMINOLOGY. Absolute, The. A conception, or, more strictly, in Kantian lan- guage, an idea of the pure reason, embracing the fundamental and necessary yet free ground of all things. Antinomy. The conflict of the laws of pure reason ; as in the question of free will and necessity. Autonomy (autonomous). Governing itself by the spontaneous action of free will. Esthetics. The science of beauty; as ethics of duty. Cofjnition (knowledge; Germanicfe, " Erketnntniss " ) is either an intuition or a conception. The former has an immediate relation to the object, and is singular and individual; the latter has but a mediate relation, by means of a characteristic mark, which may be common to several things. Cognition is an objective perception. Conception. A conception is either empirical or pure. A pure conception, in so far as it has its origin in the understanding alone, and is not the conception of a pure sensuous image, is called notio. Conceptions are distinguished on the one hand from sensation and perception, and on the other hand from the intuitions of pure reason or ideas. They are distinctly the product of thought and of the understanding, except vphen quite free from empirical ele- ments. Feeling (Gefiihl). That part'fcf our nature which relates to pas- sion and instinct. Feelings are connected both witli our sensuous nature, our imagination, and the pure reason. Form. See Matter. Ideas. The product of the pure reason (Vernunft) or intuitive faculty. Wherever the absolute is introduced in thought we have ideas. Perfection in all its aspects is an idea, virtue and wisdom in their perfect purity and ideas. Kant remai'ks (" Critique of Pure Reason," Meiklejohn's translation, p. 2.56): "It is from the under- standing alone that pure and transcendental conceptions take their origin ; the reason does not properly give birth to any conception, but only frees the conception of the understanding from the un- avoidable limitation of possible experience. A conception formed from notions which transcend the possibility of experience is an idea or a conception of reason."' Intuition (Anschauung) as used by Kant, is external or internal. Externa], sensuous intuition is identical with perception; internaV Intuition gives birth to ideas. 31 32 JiSTIIETICAL LETTERS AXD ESSAYS. UTatter and Form. " These two conceptions are at the foundation of 3ll other reflection, being inseparably connected with every iiiode of exercising the understanding. By the former is imphed that wliicli can be determined in general; the second implies us deter- raiiiatioii, both in a transcenilental sense, abstraction being made of T,ny diffei'ence in tliat wliich is given, and of the mode in which it is determinerl. That which in the phenomenon corresponds to the sensation, I term its matter; but that which effects that the content of tlie phenomenon can be arranged under certain re- lations, I call its form." — Kant, " Critique," op. cit. Objective. What is inherent or relative to aii object, or not Myself, except in the case when I reflect on myself, in which case my states of mind are objective to my thoughts. In a popular sense objective means external, as contrasted with the subjective or inlernal. Perceidion, if it relates only to the subject as a modification of \u state, is a sensation. An objective perception is a cognition (Krlcenntiiiss). Phenomena (Erscheinungen). The undetermined object of an empirical intuition is called phenomenon. Ueason (pure; Germanicfe, " Vernunft"). The source of ideas of moral feelings and of conceptions free from all elements taken up from experience. Representation ( Vorstellung). All the products of the mind are styled representations (except emotions and mere sensations) and tiie terra is applied to the whole genus. Representation with consciousness is perceptlo. Sensation. The capacity of receiving representations through the mode in wliich we are affectei by objects is called sensibility. By means of sensibility objects are given to us, and it alone fur- nishes witli intentions meaning sensuous intuitions. By the understanding tliey are thought, and from it arise conceptions. Subjective. What has its source in and relation to the person- ality, to Myself, I, or the Ego; opposed to tlie objective, or what is inlierent in and relative to tlie object. Not myself, except in the case when my states of mind are the object of my own reflection. Sujiersennuous. Contrasted with and opposed to the sensuous. What is exclusively related to sense or imparted through the sen- suous ideas is supersensuous. See Tranf:cenclental. Transcendental. What exceeds the limits of sense and empirical observation. " 1 apply the term transcendental to all knowl- edge which is not so much occupied with objects as with the mode of our cognition of these objects, so far as this mode of cognition is possible H priori." Kant's "Critique," op. cit. p. 16. Unilerstandin^j (Verstand). Tlie thought of faculty, the source of conceptions and notions (Begriffe) of the laws of logic, the c.itegories, and judgment. LETTEES ^STHETICAL EDUCATIOl^ OF MAN. Letter I. By your permission I lay before you, in a series of letters, the results of my researches upon beai/ii/ and art. I am keenly sensible of the importance as well as of the charm and dignity of this undertakmg. I shall treat a subject which is closely connected with the better portion of our happiness and not far removed from the moral nobility of human nature. I shall plead this cause of the beautiful be- fore a heart by which her whole power is felt arid exer- cised, and which will take upon itself the most difficult part of my task in an investigation where one is compelled to appeal as frequently to feelings as to principles. That which I would beg of you as a favor, you gener- ously impose upon me as a duty ; and, when I solely con- sult m}' inclination, you impute to me a service. The libertj'' of action you prescribe is rather a necessity for me than a constraint. Little exercised in formal rules, I shall scarcely incur the risk of sinning against good taste by any undue use of them ; my ideas, drawn rather from within than from reading or from an intimate experience with the world, will not disown their origin ; they would rather incur any reproach than that of a sectarian bias, and would prefer to succumb bj- their innate feebleness than sustain themselves bj' borrowed authority and foreign support. In truth, I will not keep back from you that the asser- tions which follow rest chiefly upon Kantian principles ; 34 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. but if in the course. of these researches jou should be re- minded of any special school of philosophj-, ascribe it to my incapacity, not to those principles. No ; your liberty of mind shall be sacred to me ; and the facts upon which I build will be furnished bj- your own sentiments ; your own unfettered thought will dictate the laws according to which we have to proceed. With regard to the ideas which predominate in the practical part of Kant's system, philosophers only disagree, whilst mankind, I am confident of proving, ha\'e never done so. If stripped of their technical shape, they will appear as the A'erdiet of reason pronounced from time immemorial bj' common consent, and as facts of the moral instinct which nature, in her wisdom, has given to man in order to serve as guide and teacher until his enlightened intelligence gi^■es him maturity. But this very technical shape which renders truth visible to the understanding conceals it from the feelings ; for, unhappily, understand- ing begins by destroying the object of the inner sense before it can appropriate the object. Like the chemist, the philosopher finds synthesis only by analysis, or the spontaneous work of nature only through the torture of art. Thus, in order to detain the fleeting apparition, he must enchain it in the fetters of rule, dissect its fair proportions into abstract notions, and preser^'e its living spirit in a fleshless skeleton of words. Is it surprising that natural feeling should not recognize itself in such a copy, and if in the report of the analyst the truth appears as paradox ? Permit me therefore to crave j'our indulgence if the following researches should remove their object from the sphere of sense while endea^-oring to draw it towards the understanding. That which I before said of moral experience can be applied with greater truth to the mani- festation of "the beautiful." It is the mystery which enchants, and its being is extinguished with the extinction of the necessary combination of its elements. ^STHETICAIi LKTTEES AND ESSAYS. 35 Letter II. But T might perhaps make a better use of the opening j'Ou afford me if I were to direct your mind to a loftier theme than that of art. It would appear to be unseason- able to go in search of a code for the sesthetic world, when the moral world offers matter of so much higher interest, and when the spirit of philosophical inquiry- is so stringently challenged by the circumstances of our times to occupy itself with the most perfect of all works of art — the establishment and structure of a true political freedom. It is unsatisfactory to live out of your own age and to work for other times. It is equally incumbent on us to be good members of our own age as of our own state or country. If it is conceived to be unseemly and even unlawful for a man to segregate himself from the customs and manners of the circle in which he lives, it would be inconsistent not to see that it is equally his dutj' to grant a proper share of influence to the voice of his own epoch, to its taste and its requirements, in the operations in which he engages. But the voice of our age seems by no means favorable to art, p< ail events to that kind of art to which my in- quiry IS directed. The course of events has given a direction to the genius of the time that threatens to re- move it continually furthSr from the ideal of art. For art has to leave reality, it has to raise itself boldlj^ above necessity and neediness ; for art is the daughter of freedom, and it requires its prescriptions and r ules to be fumish ed liy^he'hecessityT3f%piittS"Hndm)tTJ5That of inattei\ KuT ^■iioiir~Tte}-" ifr^isTiecessity, neecTiness, that^rBrailsriind Jends a degraded humanity under its iron yoke. Utiliti/ is the great idol of the AijHf'i„to_v»^clLJiiL4iOwer8_do libmage and jflEIauhjects _are_snb^er\-ient. In this g reat balance on utility, the spiritual service of art has no weight, and, depiT\fed "of all] encdufagemeTit^ Tt^linishes from the noisy Vanity Fair of "oiirtime. — -Tlie very spirit of philosophical inquiry itself robs the imagination of one promise after another, and the frontiers of art are nar- 36 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. rowed in proportion as the limits of science are en- larged. The eyes of the philosopher as well as of the man of the world are anxiouslj- turned to the theatre of political events, where it is presumed the great destinj- of man is to be plaj-ed out. It would almost seem to betray a culpa- ble indifference to the welfare of society if we did not share this general interest. For this great commerce in social and moral principles is of necessity a matter of the greatest concern to every human being, on the ground both of its subject and of its results. It must accord- ingly be of deepest moment to everj- man to think for himself. It would seem that now at length a question that formerly was onlj' settled by the law of the stronger is to be determined by the calm judgment of the reason, and every man who is capable of placing himself in a cen- tral position, and raising his individuality into that of his species, can look upon himself as in possession of this judicial faculty of reason ; being moreover, as man and member of the human family, a party in the case under trial and involved more or less in its decisions. It would thus appear that this great political process is not only engaged with his individual case, it has also to pronounce enactments, which he as a rational spirit is capable of enunciating and entitled to pronounce. It is evident that it would have been most attractive to me to inquire into an object such as this, to decide such a question in conjunction with a thinker of powerful mind, a man of liberal sympathies, and a heart imbued with a noble enthusiasm for the weal of humanity. Though so widely separated by worldly position, it would have been a delightful surprise to have found your unprejudiced mind arriving at the same result as my own in the field of ideas. Nevertheless, I think I can not only excuse, but even justify by solid grounds, my step in resisting this attractive purpose and in preferring beautj' to freedom. [ hope that I shall succeed in convincing you that this matter of art is less foreign to the needs than to the tastes of our age ; nay, that, to arrive at a solution even in the political problem, the road of assthetics must be pursued, because it is through beauty that we arrive at freedom. JESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 37 But I cannot carry out this proof without my bringing to your remembrance the principles by which the reason ib guided in political legislation. Letter III. Man is not better treated bj- nature in his first start than her other works are ; so long as he is unable to act for himself as an independent intelligence she acts for him. But the very fact that constitutes him a man is that he does not remain stationarj% where^ nature has placed him. that he can pass with his reason, retracing the steps na- ture had made him anticipate, that he can convert the work of necessity into one of free solution, and elevate ph3-sical necessity into a moral law. When man is raised from his slumber in the senses he feels that he is a man ; he surveys his surroundings and finds that he is in a state. He was introduced into this state by the power of circumstances, before he could freely select his own position. But as a moral being he cannot possibly rest satisfied with a political condition forced upon him by necessity, and onlj' calculated for that condi- tion ; and it would be unfortunate if this did satisfj' him. In many cases man shakes off this blind law of necessit}-, by his free spontaneous action, of which among many others we have an instance, in his ennobling by beauty and suppressing b}- moraf infiuence the powerful nnpulse implanted in him by nature in the passion of lo^■e. Thus, when arrived at maturity', he recovers his childhood by an artificial process, he founds a state of nature in his ideas, not gi\-en him by any experience, but established by the necessary laws and conditions of his reason, and he attrib- utes to this ideal condition an object, an aim, of which he was not cognizant in the actual realitj' of nature. He gives himself a choice of which he was not capable before, and sets to work just as if he were beginning anew, and were exchanging his original state of bondage for one of complete independence, doing this with complete insight and of his free decision. He is justified in regarding this work of political thraldom as non-existing though a wild 38 ^STHETICAL LETTEKW AND ESSAYS. and arbitraiy caprice may have founded its worlf veiy art- fully ; though it may strive to maintain it with great arro- gance and encompass it with a halo of veneration. For the work of blind powers possesses no authority before which freedom need bow, and all must be made to adapt itself to the highest end which reason has set up in his personahty. It is in this wise that a people in a state of manhood is justified in exchanging a condition of thraldom for one of moral freedom. Now the term natural condition can be applied to every political body which owes its establishment originally to forces and not to laws, and such a state contradicts the moral nature of man, because lawfulness can alone have authority' over this. At the same time this natural condi- tion is quite sufficient for the phj'sical man, who onlj- gives himself laws in order to get rid of brute force. More- over, the physical man is a reality, and the moral man prohlematical. Therefore when the reason suppresses the natural condition, as she must if she wishes to substitute her own, she weighs the real physical man against the prob- lematical moral man, she weighs the existence of societ}' against a possible, though morally necessary, ideal of societ\'. She takes from man something which he really possesses, and without which he possesses nothing, and refers him as a substitute to something that he ought to possess and might possess ; and if reason had relied too exclusively on him she might, in order to secure him a state of humanit3- in which he is wanting and can want without injury to his life, have robbed him even of the means of animal existence, which is the first necessar3- condition of his being a man. Before he had opportunity to hold firm to the law with his will, reason would iiave withdrawn from his feet the ladder of nature. The great point is, therefore, to reconcile these two con- siderations, to prevent physical societj- from ceasing for a moment in time, while the moral society is being formed in the idea ; in other words, to prevent its existence from being placed in jeopardy for the sake of the moral dig- nity of man. When the mechanic has to mend a watch he lets the wheels run out ; but the living watchworks of the state have to be repaired while they act, and a wheel JESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 39 has to be exchanged for another during its revolutions. Accordingly props must be sought for to support society and keep it going while it is made independent of the natural condition from which it is sought to emancipate it. This prop is not found in the natural character of man, who, being selfish and violent, directs his energies rather to the destruction than to the preservation of society. Nor is it found in his moral character, which has to be formed, which can never be worked upon or calculated on by the lawgiver, because it is free and never appears. It would seem, therefore, that another measure must be adopted. It would seem that the physical character of the arbitrary must be separated from moral freedom ; that it is incumbent to make the former harmonize with the laws and the latter dependent on impressions ; it would be expedient to remove the' former still farther from matter and to bring the latter somewhat more near to it ; in short, to pro- duce a third character related to both the others — the physical and the moral — paving the way to a transition from the sway of mere force to that of law, without pre- venting the proper development of the moral character, but serving rather as a pledge in the sensuous sphere of a morality in the unseen. Letter IV, Thus much is certain. 'It is only when a third character, as previously suggested, has preponderance that a revolu- tion in a state according to moral principles can be free from injurious consequences ; nor can anything else secure its endurance. In proposing or setting up a moral state, the moral law is relied upon as a real power, and free-will is drawn into the realm of causes, where all hangs together mutually with stringent necessity and rigidity. But we know that the condition of the human will always remains contingent, and that only in the Absolute Being physical coexists with moral necessity. Accordingly, if it is wished to depend on the moral conduct of man as on natural re- sults, this conduct must become nature, and he must be led by natural impulse to such a course of action as can 40 ^STHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. only and invariably have moral results. But the will of man is perfectly free between inclination and duty, and no physical necessity ought to enter as a sharer in this mag- isterial personality. If, therefore, he is to retain this power of solution, and yet become a reliable link in the causal concatenation of forces, this can only be effected when the operations of both these impulses are presented quite equally in the world of appearances. It is only possible when, with every difference of form, the matter of man's volition remains the same, when all his impulses agreeing with his reason are sufficient to have the value of a universal legislation. It may be urged that every individual man carries within himself, at least in his adaptation and destination, a purely ideal man. The great problem of his existence is to bring all the incessant changes of his outer life into conformity with the unchanging unitj- of this ideal. This pure ideal man, which makes itself known more or less clearlj' in every subject, is represented by the state, which is the objective, and, so to speak, canonical form in which the manifold differences of the subjects strive to unite. Now two ways present themselves to the thought in which the man of time can agree with the man of idea, and there are also two ways in which the state can maintain itself in individuals. One of these ways is when the pure ideal man subdues the empirical man, and the state suppresses the individual, or again when the individual becomes the state, and the man of time is ennobled to the man of idea. I admit that in a one-sided estimate from the point of view of morality' this difference vanishes, for the reason is satisfied if her law prevails uuconditionallj-. But when the surve\- taken is complete and embraces the whole man (anthropology), where the form is considered together with the substance, and a living feeling has a voice, the differ- ence will become far more evident. No doubt the reason demands unitj', and nature variety, and both legislations take man in hand. The law of the former is stamped upon him by an incorruptible consciousness, that of the lat- ter by an ineradicable feeling. Consequently education will always appear deficient when the moral feeling can only be iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 41 maintained with the sacrifice of what is natural ; and a political administration will alwa3S be very imperfect when it is only able to bring about unity by suppressing variety. The state ought not onh- to respect the objective and generic, but also the subjective and specific in individuals ; and while diffusing the unseen world of morals, it must not depopulate the kingdom of appearance, the external world of matter. When the mechanical artist places his hand on the form- less block, to give it a form according to his intention, he has not any scruples in doing violence to it. For the nature on which he works does not deserve any respect in itself, and he does not value the whole for its parts, but the parts on account of the whole. When the child of the fine arts sets his hand to the same block, he has no scruples either in doing violence to it, he onl^' avoids show- ing this violence. He does not respect the matter in which he works any more than the mechanical artist ; but he seeks by an apparent consideration for it to deceive the eye which takes this matter under its protection. The political and educating artist follows a very different course, while making man at once his material and his end. In j this case the aim or end meets in the material, and it is only because the whole serves the parts that the parts adapt themselves to the end. The political artist has to treat his material — man — with a very different kind of re- spect than that shown by the artist of fine art to his work. He must spare man's peculiarity and personality, not to I produce a defective effect on the senses, but objectively and out of consideration for his inner being. i But the state is an organization which fashions itself"! through itself and for itself, and for this reason it can only be realized when the parts have been accorded to the idea of the whole. The state serves the purpose of a repre- sentative, both to pure ideal and to objective humanity, in the breast of its citizens, accordingly it will have to ob- serve the same relation to its citizens in which they are placed to it ; and it will only respect their subjective , humanity in the same degree that it is ennobled to an ob- I jective existence. If the internal man is one with himself"^ he will be able to rescue his peculiarity, even in the greatest 42 ^STHKTICAL LETTKRS AND ESSAYS. generalization of his conduct, and the state will only become the exponent of his fine instinct, tlie clearer formula of his internal legislation. But if the subjective man is in ; conflict with the objective, and contradicts him in the character of a people, so that only the oppression of the former can give victor3' to the latter, then the state will take up the severe aspect of the law against the citizen, and in order not to fall a sacrifice, it will have to crush under foot such a hostile individuality without any com- promise. '' Now man can be opposed to himself in a twofold manner ; either as a savage, when his feelings rule over his principles ; or as a barbarian, when his principles destroy his feelings. The savage despises art, and acknowl- edges nature as his despotic ruler ; the barbarian laughs at nature, and dishonors it, but he often proceeds in a more contemptible way than the savage to be the slave ; of his senses. The cultivated man makes of nature his friend, and honors its friendship, while only bridling its caprice. Consequently, when reason brings her moral unity into physical society, she must not injure the manifold in na- ture. When nature strives to maintain her manifold character in the moral structure of society, this must not create any breach in moral unit}' ; the victorious form is equally remote from uniformity and confusion. There- in fore, totality of character must be found in the people i which is capable and worthy to exchange the state of ' necessity for that of freedom. Letter V. Does the present age, do passing events, present this character? I direct my attention at once to the most prominent object in this vast structure. It is true that the consideration of opinion is fallen ; caprice is unnerved, and, although still armed with power, receives no longer any respect. Man has awakened from his long lethargy and self-deception, and he demands with impressive unanimity to be restored to his imperishable ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 43 rights. But he does not only demand them ; he rises on all sides to seize by force what, in his opinion, has been unjustly svrested from him. The edifice of the natural state is tottering, its foundations shake, and a physical possibility seems at length granted to place law on the throne, to honor man at length as an end, and to make true freedom the basis of political union. Vain hope ! The moral possibility is wanting, and the generous occa- sion finds an unsusceptible rule. Man paints himself in his actions, and what is the form depicted in the drama of the present time ? On the one hand, he is seen running wild, on the other, in a state of letharg\- ; the two extremest stages of human degeneracy, and both seen in one and the same period. In the lower larger masses, coarse, lawless impulses come to view, breaking loose when the bonds of civil order are burst asunder, and ha.stening with unbridled fury to satisfy their savage instinct. Objective humanity may have had cause to complain of the state ; jet subject- ive man must honor its institutions. Ought he to be blamed because he lost sight of the dignity of human nature, so long as he was concerned in preserving his existence ? Can we blame him that he proceeded to sepa- rate bj- the force of gravity, to fasten by the force of cohesion, at a time when there could be no thought of building or raising up? The extinction of the state con- tains its justification. Society set free, instead of hasten- ing upward into organic iffe, collapses into its elements. On the other hand, the civilized classes give us the still more repulsive sight of lethargy, and of a depravity of character which is the more revolting because it roots in culture. I forget who of the older or more recent philoso- phers makes the remark, that what is more noble is the more revolting in its destruction. The remark applies with truth to the world of morals. The child of nature, when he breaks loose, becomes a madman ; but the art scholar, when he breaks loose, becomes a debased char- acter. The enlightenment of the understanding, on which the more refined classes pride themselves with some ground, shows on the whole so little of an ennobling influence on the mind that it seems rather to confirm cor- 44 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. ruption by its maxims. We deny nature on her legitimate Held and feel her tyranny in the moral sphere, and while resisting her impressions, we receive our principles from her. While the affected decency of our manners does not even grant to nature a pardonable influence in the initial stage, our materialistic system of morals allows her the casting vote in tlie last and essential stage. Egotism has founded its system in the very bosom of a refined society, and witlioutdevelo|)ing even a sociable character, we feel all the contagions and miseries of society. We subject our free judgment to its despotic opinions, our feelings to its bizarre customs, and our will to its seductions. We only maintain our caprice against her holy rights. The man of the world has his heart contracted bj- a proud self- complacency, while that of the man of nature often beats in sympathy ; and every man seeks for nothing more than to save his wretched property irom the general destruction, as it were from some great conflagration. It is conceived that the only way to find a shelter against the aberrations of sentiment is by completely foregoing its indulgence, and mockery, which is often a useful chastener of mysticism, slanders in the same breath the noblest aspirations. Cul- ture, far from giving us freedom, onty develops, as it advances, new necessities ; the fetters of the physical close more tightly around us, so that the fear of loss quenches even the ardent impulse toward improvement, and the inaxims of passive obedience are held to be the highest wisdom of life. Thus the spirit of the time is seen to waver between perversion and savagism, between what is unnatural and mere nature, between superstition and moral unbelief, audit is often nothing but the equilibrium of evils that sets bounds to it. Letter VI. Have I gone too far in this portraiture of our times ? I do not anticipate this stricture, but rather another — that I have proved too much by it. You will tell me that the picture I have presented resembles the humanitj' of our day, but it also bodies forth all nations engaged in the ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 45 same degree of culture, because all, without exception, have fallen off from nature b^- the abuse of reason, before they can return to it through reason. But if we bestow some serious attention to the character of our times, we shall be astonished at the contrast between the present and the previous form of humanity, especially that of Greece. We are justified in claiming the reputa- tion of culture and refinement, when contrasted with a purely natural state of society, but not so comparing our- selves with the Grecian nature. For the latter was com- bined with all the charms of art and with all the dignity of wisdom, without, however, as with us, becoming a vic- tim tottiese influences. The Greeks have put us to shame not only by their simplicity, which is foreign to our age ; ! they are at. the same time our rivals, nay, frequentlj- our ! models, in those very points of superiority from which we seek comfort when regretting the unnatural character of our manners. We see that remarkable people uniting at once fulness of form and fulness of substance, both philosophizing and creating, both tender and energetic, uniting a youthful fancy to the virility of reason in a glorious humanity. At the period of Greek culture, which was an awakening of the powers of the mind, the senses and the spirit had no distinctly separated property ; no division had yet torn them asunder, leading them to partition in a hostile atti- tude, and to mark off their limits with precision. Poetry had not as yet become the^dversary of wit, nor had spec- ulation abused itself bj' passing into quibbling. In cases of iiecessitj- both poetry and wit could exchange parts, because they both honored truth onlj' in their special way. However high might he the flight of reason, it drew matter in a loving spirit after it, and while sharply and stiflfly defining it, never mutilated what it touched. It is true the Greek mind displaced humanity, and recast it on a magnified scale in the glorious circle of its gods ; but it did this not by dissecting human nature, but by giving it fresh combinations, for the whole of human nature was represented in each of the gods. How different is the course followed by us moderns ! We also displace and magnify individuals to form the image of the species, but 46 ^STHETICAI- LKTTERS AND ESSAYS we do this in a fragmentary way, not by altered combina- tions, so that it is necessary to gather up from diflFerent individuals the elements that form the species in its totality. It would almost appear as if the powers of mind express themselves with us in real life or empirically as separately as the psychologist distinguishes them in the representation. For we see not only individual subjects, but whole classes of men, uphold their capacities only in part, while the rest of their faculties scarcely show a germ of activity, as in the case of the stunted growth of plants. I do not overlook the advantages to which the present race, regarded as a unity and in the balance of the under- standing, may lay c' ..im over what is best in the ancient world ; but it is obliged to engage in the contest as a com- pact mass, and measure itself as a whole against a whole. Who among the moderns could step forth, man against man, and strive with an Athenian for the prize of higher humanitj'. Whence comes this disadvantageous relation of individ- uals coupled with great advantages of the race? Why could the individual Greek be qualified as the type of his time ; and why can no modern dare to offer himself as such? Because all-uniting nature imparted its forms to the Greek, and an all-dividing understanding gives our forms to us. It was culture itself that gave these wounds to modem humanity. The inner union of human nature was broken, and a destructive contest divided its harmonious forces directl}' ; on the one hand, an enlarged experience and a more distinct thinking necessitated a sharper separation of the sciences, while, on the other hand, the more complicat- ed machinery of states necessitated a stricter sundering of ranks and occupations. Intuitive and speculative under- standing took up a hostile attitude in opposite fields, whose borders were guarded with jealousy and distrust ; and by limiting its operation to a narrow sphere, men have made unto themselves a master who is wont not unfrequentlj' to end by subduing and oppressing all the other faculties. Whilst on the one hand a luxuriant imagination creates ravages in the plantations that have cost the intelligence so much labor ; on the other band, a spirit of abstiaction ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 47 suffocates the fire that might have warmed the heart and inflamed the imagination. This subversion, commenced by art and learning in the inner man, was carried out to fulness and finished by the spirit of innovation in government. It was, no doubt, reasonable to expect that the simple organization of the primitive republics should survive the quaintness of primi- tive manners and of the relations of antiquit}-. But, in- stead of rising to a higher and nobler degree of animal | life, this organization degenerated into a common and j coarse mechanism. The zoophyte condition of the Grecian ' states, where each individual enjoj^ed an independent life, and could, in cases of necessity, become a separate whole and unit in himself, gave way to an ingenious mechanism, when, from the splitting up into numberless parts, there results a mechanical life in the combination. Then there'll was a rupture between the state and the church, between ' laws and customs ; enjoyment was separated from labor, the means from the end, the effort from the reward. Man himself, eternally chained down to a little fragment of the whole, only forms a kind of fragment ; having nothing in his ears but the monotonous sound of the perpetually re- volving wheel, he never develops the harmony of his being, and instead of imprinting the seal of humanitj- on his being, he ends by being nothing more than the living impress of , the craft to which he devotes himself, of the science thatj he cultivates. This very partial and paltr\- relation, link- ing the isolated members to*the whole, does not depend on forms that are given spontaneously ; for how could a com- 1 plicated machine, which shuns the light, confide itself to the free will of man? This relation is rather dictated,^ with a rigorous strictness, by a formulary in which the free intelligence of man is chained down. The dead letteri takes the place of a living meaning, and a practised mem- ory becomes a safer guide than genius and feeling. If the community or state measures man by his function,- only asking of its citizens memory, or the intelligence of a craftsman, or mechanical skill, we cannot be surprised that the other faculties of the mind are neglected for the exclusive culture of the one that brings in honor and profit. ! Such is the necessary result of an organization that is 48 ^STHETIOAL LETTERS ANP ESS ATS. indifferent about character, only looking to acquirements, wiiilst in other cases it tolerates the thickest darkness, to favor a spirit of law and order ; it must result if it wishes that individuals in the exercise of special aptitudes should gain in depth what they are permitted to lose in extension. We are aware, no doubt, that a powerful genius does not shut up its activity within the limits of its functions ; but mediocre talents consume in the craft fallen to their lot the whole of their feeble energy ; and if some of their energy is reserved for matters of preference, without prejudice to its functions, such a state of things at once bespeaks a spirit soaring above the vulgar. Mora- • over, it is rarely a recommendation in the ej'e of a state to have a capacity superior to your employment, or one of those noble intellectual cravings of a man of talent which contend in rivalry with the duties of office. The state is so jealous of the exclusive possession of its ser- vants that it would prefer — nor can it be blamed in this — for functionaries to show their powers with the Venus of Cytherea rather than the Uranian Venus. - It is thus that concrete individual life is extinguished, in order that the abstract whole may continue its miserable life, and the state remains forever a stranger to its citizens, because feeling does not discover it anywhere. The gov- erning authorities find themselves compelled to classify, and thereby simplify the multiplicity of citizens, and only to know humanity in a representative form and at second-hand. Accordingly they end by entirely losing sight of humanity, and by confounding it with a simple artificial creation of the understanding, whilst on their part the subject-classes cannot help receiving coldly laws that address themselves so little to their personality. At length, society, weary of having a burden that the state takes so little trouble to lighten, falls to pieces and is broken up — a destiny that has long since attended most European states. They are dissolved in what may be called a state of moral nature, in which public authority is only one function more, hated and deceived by those who think it necessary, respected only by those who can do without it. Thus compressed between two forces, within and with- ^STHETICAIi LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 49 out, could humanity follow any other course than that which it has taken? The speculative mind, pursuing imprescriptible goods and rights in the sphere of id-eas, must needs have become a stranger to the world of sense, and lose sight of matter for the sake of form. On its part, the world of public affairs, shut up in a monotonous circle of objects, and even there restricted bj* formulas, was led to lose sight of the life and liberty of the whole, while becoming impoverished at the same time in its own sphere. Just as the speculative mind was tempted to model the real after the intelligible, and to raise the sub- jective laws of its imagination into laws constituting the existence of things, so the state spirit rushed into the opposite extreme, wished to make a particular and frag- mentary experience the measure of all observation, and to apply without exception to all affairs the rules of its own particular craft. The speculative mind had nece?sarily to become the prey of a vain subtlety, the state spirit of a narrow pedantry ; for the former was placed too high to see the individual, and tlie latter too low to survey the whole. But the disadvantage of this direction of mind was not confined to knowledge and mental production ; it extended to action and feeling. We know that the sensibility of the mind depends, as to degree, on the liveliness, and for extent on the richness of the imagination. Now the pre- dominance of the faculty of analysis must necessaril}' deprive the imagination of Its warmth and energj-, and a restricted sphere of objects must diminish its wealth. It is for this reason that the abstract thinker has very often a cold heart, because he analyzes impressions, which only move the mind by their combination or totality ; on the other hand, the man of business, the statesman, has very i often a narrow heart, because, shut up in the narrow circle i of his employment, liis iiiuigination can neither expand nor adapt itself to another manner of viewing things. My subject has led me naturally to place in relief the distressing tendency of the character of oiu' own times and to show the sources of the evil, without its being my province to point out the compensations offered by nature. I will readily admit to 3-ou that, although this splitting up of their being was unfavorable for individuals, it was the 50 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. only open road for the progress of the race. The point at which we see humanitj' arrived among the Greeks was undoubtedly a maximum; it could neither stop there nor rise higher. It could not stop there, for the sum of notions acquired forced infallibly the intelligence to break with feeling and intuition, and to lead to clearness of know- ledge. Nor could it rise any higher ; for it is only in a determinate measure that clearness can be reconciled with a certain degree of abundance and of warmth. The Greeks had attained this measure, and to continue their progress in culture, they, as we, were obliged to renounce the totality of their being, and to follow different and sep- arate roads in order to seek after truth. There was no other way to develop the manifold apti- tudes of man than to bring them in opposition with one another. This antagonism of forces is the great instru- ment of culture, but it is only an instrument : for as long as this antagonism lasts man is only on the road to cul- ture. It is onl}" because these special forces are isolated in man, and because they take on themselves to impose an exclusive legislation, that they enter into strife with the truth of things, and oblige common sense, which generally adheres imperturbably to external phenomena, to dive into the essence of things. While pure understanding usurps authority in the world of sense, and empiricism attempts to subject this intellect to the conditions of experience, these two rival directions arrive at the highest possible development, and exhaust the whole extent of their sphere. While, on the one hand, imagination, bj' its t^yranny, ven- tures to destroy the order of the world, it forces reason, on the other side, to rise up to the supreme sources of knowledge, and to invoke against this predominance of fancy the help of the. law of neeessitj*. By an exclusive spirit in the case of Ms faculties, the individual is fatally led to error ; but the species is led to truth. It is only by gathering up all the energj'^ of oui mind in a single focus, and concentrating a single force in our being, that we give in some sort wings to this isolated force, and that we draw it on artificially far beyond the limits that nature seems to have imposed upon it. If it be certain that all human individuals taken togethei ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSATS. 51 would never have arrived, with the visual power given them by nature, to see a satellite of Jupiter, discovered by the telescope of the astronomer, it is just as well established that never would the human understanding have produced the anah'sis of the iniinite, or the critique of pure reason, if in particular branches, destined for this mission, reason had not applied itself to special researches, and it, after having, as it were, freed itself from all mat- ter, it had not, bj^ the most powerful abstraction given to the spiritual ej^e of man the force necessary, in order to look into the absolute. But the question is, if a spirit thus absorbed in pure reason and intuition will be able to emancipate itself from the rigorous fetters of logic, to take the free action of poetrj', and seize the individ- uality of things with a faithful and chaste sense ? Here nature imposes even on the most universal genius a limit it cannot pass, and truth will make martyrs as long as philosophj' will be reduced to make its principal occupa- tion the search for arms against errors. But whatever may be the final profit for the totality of the world, of this distinct and special perfecting of the human faculties, it cannot be denied that this final aim of the universe, which devotes them to this liind of culture, is a cause of suflfering, and a kind of malediction for in- dividuals. I admit that the exercises of the gymnasium form athletic bodies ; but beauty is only developed by the free and equal play of th^ limbs. In the same way the tension of the isolated spiritual forces ma}' make extraor- dinary men ; but it is only the well-tempered equilibrium of these forces that can produce happy and accomplished men. And in what relation should we be placed with past and future ages if the perfecting of human nature made such a sa.crifice indispensable? In that case we should have been the slaves of humanity, we should have consumed our forces in servile work for it during some thousands of years, and we sliould have stamped on our humiliated, mutilated nature the shameful brand of this slavery — all this in order that future generations, in a happy leisure, might consecrate themselves to the cure of their moral health, and develop the whole of human na- ture by their free culture. 52 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. But can it be true that man has to neglect himself fo: any end whatever ? Can nature snatch from us, for ani end whatever, the perfection which is prescribed to us bj the aim of reason ? It must be false that the perfecting of particular faculties renders the sacrifice of their totaliti necessary ; and even if the law of nature had imperiouslj this tendency, we must have the power to reform by t superior art this totality of our being, which art hai destroyed. Lettee VII. Can this effect of harmony be attained by the state That is not possible, for the state, as at present consti tuted, has given occasion to evil, and the state as con ceived in the idea, instead of being able to establish thii more perfect humanity, ought to be based upon it. Thui the researches in which I have indulged would hav( brought me back to the same point from which thej' hat called me off for a time. The present age, far fron offering us this form of humanity', which we haAC acknowl edged as a necessary condition of an improvement of th( state, shows us rather the diametrically opposite form. If therefore, the principles I have laid down are correct, anc if experience confirms the picture I have traced of thi present time, it would be necessary to qualifj- as unsea sonable everj^ attempt to effect a similar change in th( state, and all hope as chimerical that would be based oi such an attempt, until the division of the inner man ceases and nature has been sufficiently developed to become her self the instrument of this great change and secure th< reality of the political creation of reason. In the physical creation, nature shows, us the road thai we have to follow in the moral creation. Only when the struggle of elementary forces has ceased in inferior organ- izations, nature rises to the noble form of the physica man. In like manner, the conflict of the elements of the moral man and that of blind instincts must have ceased, and a coarse antagonism in himself, before the attempt car be hazarded. On the other hand, the independence of man's character must be secured, and his submission tc >3ESTHETICAL LETTEKS AND ESSAYS. 53 despotic forms must have given place to a suitable libertj-, before the variety in his constitution can be made subordi- nate to the unity of the ideal. When the man of nature still makes such an anarchial abuse of his will, his liberty ought hardly to be disclosed to him. And when the man fashioned by culture makes so little use of his freedom, Ills free will ought not to be taken from him. The conces- sion of liberal principles becomes a treason to social order when it is associated with a force still in fermentation, and increases the already exuberant energy of its nature. Again, the law of conformity under one level becomes t3Tanny to the individual when it is allied to a weakness alreadj' holding sway and to natural obstacles, and when it comes to extinguish the last spark of spontaneity^ and of originality. The tone of the age must therefore rise from its pro- found moral degradation ; on the one hand it must eman- cipate itself from the blind service of nature, and on the other it must re^•ert to its simplicity, its truth, and its fruit- ful sap ; a sufficient task for more than a centur}-. How- ever, I admit readily', more than one special effort may meet with success, but no improvement of the whole will result from it, and contradictions in action will be a con- tinual protest against the unity of maxims. It will be quite possible, then, that in remote corners of the world humanity may be honored in the person of the negro, while in Europe it may be^legraded in the person of the thinker. The old principles will remain, but they will adopt the dress of the age, and philosophy will lend its name to an oppression that was formerly authorized by the church. In one place, alarmed at the libert3- which in its opening efforts alwa3's shows itself an enemy, it will cast itself into the arms of a convenient servitude. In another place, reduced to despair by a pedantic tutelage, it will be driven into the savage license of the state of nature. Usurpation will invoke the weakness of human nature, and insurrection will invoke its dignity, till at length the great sovereign of all human things, blind force, shall come in and decide, like a vulgar pugilist, this pretended contest of principles. 54 iESTHETICAL LETTEES AND ESSAYS. Letter VIII. Must philosophy therefore retire from this field, disap- pointed in its hopes ? Whilst in all other directions _ the dominion of forms is extended, must this the most precious of all gifts be abandoned to a formless chance ? Must the contest of blind forces last eternally in the political world, and is social law never to triumph over a hating egotism ? Not in the least. It is true that reason herself will never attempt directly a struggle with this brutal force which resists her arms, and she will be as far as the son of Saturn in the "Iliad" from descending into the dismal field of battle, to fight them in person. But she chooses the most deserving among the combatants, clothes him with divine arms as Jupiter gave them to his son-in-law, and by her triumphing force she finally decides the victory. Reason has done all that she could in finding the law and promulgating it ; it is for the energy of the will and the ardor of feeling to carry it out. To issue victoriously from her contest with force, truth herself must first be- come a, force, and turn one of the instincts of man into her champion in the empire of phenomena. For instincts are the onlj' motive forces in the material world. If liith- erto truth has so little manifested her victorious power, this has not depended on the understanding, which could not have unveiled it, but on the heart which re- mained closed to it and on instinct which did not act with it. Whence, in fact, proceeds this general sway of pi'eju- dices, this might of the understanding in the midst of the light disseminated by philosophy and experience? The age is enlightened, that is to say, that knowledge, obtain- ed and vulgarized, suffices to set right at least our practi- cal principles. The spirit of free inquiry has dissipated the erroneous opinions which long barred the access to truth, and has undermined the ground on which fanaticism and deception had erected their throne. Reason has pur- ified itself from the illusions of the senses and from a mendacious sophistry, and philosophy herself raises her ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 55 voice and exhorts us to return to the bosom of nature, to which she had first made us unfaithful. Whence then is it that we remain still barbarians ? There must be something in the spirit of man — as it is not in the objects themselves — which prevents us from receiving the truth, notwithstanding the brilliant light she diffuses, and from accepting her, whatever may be her strength for producing conviction. This something was perceived and expressed by an ancient sage in this very significant maxim : sapere aude.* Dare to be wise ! A spirited courage is required to triumph over the impediments that the indolence of nature as well as the cowardice of the heart oppose to our in- struction. It was not without reason that the ancient Mythos made Minerva issue fully armed from the head of Jupiter, for it is with warfare that this instruction com- mences. From its very outset it has to sustain a hard fight against the senses, which do not like to be roused from their easy slumber. The greater part of men are much too exhausted and enervated by their struggle with want to be able to engage in a new and severe contest with error. Satisfied if they themselves can escape from the hard labor of thought, they willingly abandon to others the guardianship of their thoughts. And if it happens that nobler necessities agitate their soul, they cling with a greedy faith to the formula that the state and the church hold in reserve for such cases. If these unhappy men deserve our compassion, those others deserve our just contempt, who, though set free from those necessities by more fortunate circumstances, yet willingly bend to their yoke. These latter persons prefer this twilight of obscure ideas, where the feelings have more intensity, and the imagination can at will create convenient chimeras, to the rays of truth which put to flight the pleasant illusions of their dreams. They have founded the wnole structure of their happiness on these very illusions, which ought to be combated and dissipated by the light of knowledge, and they would think they were paying too dearly for a truth which begins by robbing them of all that has value in their sight. It would be necessary that they should • Dare to be wise. 56 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. be already sages to love wisdom : a truth that was felt at once by him to whom philosopliy owes its name.* It is' therefore not going far enough to say that the light of the understanding only deserves respect when it reacts on the character ; to a certain extent it is from the charac- ter that this light proceeds ; for the road that terminates in the head must pass through the heart. Accordingly, the most pressing need of the present time is to educate {the sensibility, because it is the means, not only to render lefflcacious in practice the improvement of ideas, but to call this improvement into existence. Letter IX. But perhaps there is a vicious circle in our previous rea- soning ! Theoretical culture must it seems bring along with it practical culture, and yet the latter must be the condition of the former. All improvement in the political sphere must proceed from the ennobling of the character. But, subject to the influence of a social constitution still barbarous, how can character become ennobled ? It would then be necessary to seek for this end an instrument that the state does not furnish, and to open sources that would have preserved themselves pure in the midst of political corruption. I have now reached the point to which all the consider- ations tended that have engaged me up to the present time. This instrument is the art of the beautiful; these sources are open to us in its immortal models. Art, like science, is emancipated from all that is posi- tive, and all that is humanly conventional ; both are com- pletely independent of the arbitrarj' will of man. The political legislator ma}- place their empire under an inter- dict, but he cannot reign there. He can proscribe the friend of truth, but truth subsists ; he can degrade the artist, but he cannot change art. Xd doubt, nothing is more common than to see science and art bend before the spirit of the age, and cicaliNe taste receive its law from critical taste. When the character becomes stiff and * Tlie Greek Avord iiiuans, ^s is known, love of wisdom. ^STHETICAL LETTJERS AND ESSAYS. 57 hardens itself, we see science severely keeping iier limits, and art subject to the harsh restraint of rules ; when the character is relaxed and softened, science endeavors to please and art to rejoice. For whole ages philosophers as well as artists show themselves occupied in letting down truth and beauty to the depths of vulgar humanitj'. The}' themselves are swallowed up in it ; but, thanks to their essential vigor and indestructible life, the true and the beautiful make a victorious fight, and issue triumphant from the abyss. No doubt the artist is the child of his time, but un- happy for him if he is its disciple or even its favorite ! Let a beneficent deitj' carry off in good time the suckling from the breast of its mother, let it nourish him on the milk of a better age, and suffer him to grow up and arrive at virility under the distant sky of Greece. When he has attained manhood, let him come back, presenting a face strange to his own age ; let him come, not to delight it witli his apparition, but rather to purify it, terrible as the son of Agamemnon. He will, indeed, receive his matter from the present time, but he will borrow the form from a nobler time and even beyond all time, from the essential, absolute, immutable unitj'. There, issuing from the pure ether of its heavenlj' nature, flows the source of all beau- ty, which was never tainted by the corruptions of genera- tions or of ages, which roll along far beneath it in dark eddies. Its matter may be dishonored as well as ennobled by fancy, but the ever-chasfe form escapes from the caprices of imagination. The Roman had already bent his knee for long years to the divinity of the emperors, and yet the statues of the gods stood erect ; the temples retained their sanctity for the eye long after the gods had become a theme for mockery, and the noble architecture of the palaces that shielded the infamies of Nero and of Commodus were a protest against them. Humanity has lost its dignity, but art has saved it, and preserves it in marbles full of meaning ; truth continues to live in illusion, and the copy will serve to re-establish the model. If the nobility of art has survived the nobility of nature, it also goes before it like an inspiring genius, forming and awakening minds. Before truth causes her triumphant light to penetrate into 58 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. the depths of the heart, poetry intercepts her rays, and the summits of humanity shine in a bright light, while a dark and humid night still hangs over the valleys. But how will the artist avoid the corruption of his time which encloses him on all hands? Let him raise his eyes to his own dignity, and to law ; let him not lower them to necessity and fortune. Equally exempt from a vain activ- ity which would imprint its trace on the fugitive moment, and from the dreams of an impatient enthusiasm which applies the measure of the absolute to the paltry produc- tions of time, let the artist abandon the real to the under- standing, for that is its proper field. But let the artist endeavor to give birth to the ideal by the union of the possible and of the necessarj'. Let him stamp illusion and truth with the efflg3' of this ideal ; let him apply it to the play of his imagination and his most serious actions, in short, to all sensuous and spiritual forms ; then let him quietlj- launch his work into infinite time. But the minds set on fire by this ideal have not all received an equal share of calm from the creative genius — that great and patient temper which is required to impress the ideal on the dumb marble, or to spread it over a page of cold, sober letters, and then intrust it to the faithful hands of time. This divine instinct, and creative force, much too ardent to follow this peaceful walk, often throws itself immediately- on the present, on active life, and strives to transform the shapeless matter of the moral world. The misfortune ( f his brothers, of the whole spe- cies, appeals loudly to the h( art of the man of feeling ; their abasement appeals still louder : enthusiasm is in- flamed, and in souls -dowed with energy the burning desire aspires impatiently to action and facts. But has this innovator examined himself to see if these disorders of the moral world wound his reason, or if tliey do not rather wound his self-love ? If he does not determine this point at once, he will find it from the impulsiveness with which he pursues a prompt and definite end. A pure, moral motive has for its end the absolute ; time does not exist for it, and the future becomes the present to it directly ; by a necessary development, it has to issue from the present. To a reason having no limits the direction to- ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 59 wards an end becomes confounded with the accomplish ment of this end, and to enter on a course is to have fin- ished it. If, then, a young friend of the true and of the beautiful were to ask me how, notwithstanding the resistance of the times, he can satisfy the noble longing of his heart, I should reply : Direct the world on which you act towards that which is good, and the measured and peaceful course of time will bring about the results. You have given it this direction if bj' j'our teaching you raise its thoughts towards the necessary and the eternal ; if, bj- jour acts or your creations, you make the necessarj- and the eternal the object of your leanings. The structure of error and of all that is arbitrarj' must fall, and it has already fallen, as soon as you are sure that it is tottering. But it is impor- tant that it should not onlj' totter in the external but also in the internal man. Cherish triumphant truth in the modest sanctuary of your heart ; give it an incarnate form through beautj', that it maj- not only be in the understand- ing that does homage to it, but that feeling may lovingly grasp its appearance. And that you may not bj' any chance take from external reality the model which j'ou yourself ought to furnish, do not venture into its danger- ous society before you are assured in j'Our own heart that you have a good escort furnished by ideal nature. Live with your age, but be not its creation ; labor for your contemporaries, but do for^them what they need, and not what they praise. Without having shared their faults, share their punishment with a noble resignation, and bend under the joke which thej' find it as painful to dispense with as to bear. Bj^ the constancy with which j'ou will despite their good fortune, j'Ou will prove to them that it is not through cowardice that j'ou submit to their sufl'er- ings. See them in thought such as they ought to be when you must act upon them ; but see them as they are when you are tempted to act for them. Seek to owe their suf- frage to their dignitj' ; but to make them happy keep an account of their unworthiness : thus, on the one hand, the nobleness of your heart will kindle theirs, and, on the other, your end will not be reduced to nothingness by their unworthiness. The gravity of your principles will keep 60 ^STHETICAL LETTEES AND ESSAYS. them off from you, but in play they will still endure them. Their taste is purer than their heart, and it is by their taste you must lay hold of this suspicious fugitive. In vain will you combat their maxims, in vain will you con- demn their actions ; but you can try your moulding hand on their leisure. Drive away caprice, frivolity, and coarse- ness from their pleasures, and you will banish them imper- ceptibly from their acts, and at length from their feelings. Everywhere that you meet them, surround them with great, noble, and ingenious forms ; multiply around them the symbols of perfection, till appearance triumphs over real- ity, and art over nature. Letter X. Convinced by my preceding letters, you agree with me on this point, that man can depart from his destination by two opposite roads, that our epoch is actually moving on these two false roads, and that it has become the prey, in one case, of coarseness, and elsewhere of exhaustion and depravity. It is the beautiful that must bring it back from this twofold departure. But how can the cultivation of the fine arts remedy, at the same time, these opposite de- fects, and unite in itself two contradictory qualities? Can it bind nature in the savage, and set it free in the barba- rian ? Can it at once tighten a spring and loose it ; and if it cannot produce this double effect, how will it be rea- sonable to expect from it so important a result as the edu- cation of man? It may be urged that it is almost a proverbial adage that the feeling developed bj^ the beautiful refines manners, and any new proof offered on the subject would appear superfluous. Men base this maxim on daily experience, which shows us almost always clearness of intellect, delicacj' of feeling, liberality and even dignity of conduct, asso- ciated with a cultivated taste, while an uncultivated taste is almost always accompanied by the opposite qualities. With consideralDle assurance, the most civilized nation of antiquity is cited as an evidence of this, the Greeks, among whom the perception of the beautiful attained its highest ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 61 development, and, as a contrast, it is usual to point tfi nations in a partial savage state, and partly barbarous, who expiate their insensibility to the beautiful by a coarse, or, at all events, a hard, austere character. Nevertheless, some thinkers are tempted occasionallj' to denj- either the fact itself or to dispute the legitimacy of the consequences that are derived from it. They do not entertain so unfa- vorable an opinion of that savage coarseness which is made a reproach in the case of certain nations ; nor do they form so advantageous an opinion of the refinement so highly lauded in the case of cultivated nations. Even as far back as in antiquity there were men who by no means regarded the culture of the liberal arts as a benefit, and who were consequentlj' led to forbid the entrance of their republic to imagination. I do not speak of those who calumniate art because they have never been favored by it. These persons only appreciate a possession by the trouble it takes to acquire it, and by the profit it brings : and how could the}' prop- erly appreciate the silent labor of taste in the exterior and interior man? How evident it is that the accidental dis- advantages attending liberal culture would make them lose sight of its essential advantages? The man deficient in form despises the grace of diction as a means of corrup- tion, courtes}' in the social relations as dissimulation, deli- cacy and generosity in conduct as an afl'ected exaggeration. He cannot forgive the favorite of the Graces for having enlivened all assemblies as a man of the world, of having directed all men to his views like a statesman, and of giv- ing his impress to the whole century as a writer: while he, the victim of labor, can only obtain with all his learning, the least attention or overcome the least difficulty. As he cannot learn from his fortunate rival the secret of pleasing, the onlj- course open to him is to deplore the corruption of human nature, which adores rather the appearance than the reality. But there are also opinions deserving respect, that pro- nounce themselves adverse to the effects of the beautiful, and find formidable arms in experience, with which to wage war against it. " We are free to admit " — such is their lan- guage — " that the charms of the beautiful can further hon- 62 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. orable ends in pure hands ; but it is not repugnant to its nature to produce, in impure hands, a directly contrary effect, and to employ in the service of injustice and error the power that throws the soul of man into chains. It is exactly because taste only attends to the form and never to the substance ; it ends by placing the soul on the dangerous incline, leading it to neglect all realitj' and to sacrifice truth and morality to an attractive envelope. All the real difference of things vanishes, and it is only the appearance that determines the value ! How manj' men of talent" — thus these arguers proceed — "have been turned aside from all effort bj^ the seductive power of the beautiful, or have been led awaj' from all serious exercise of their activitj^, or have been induced to use it verj' fee- bly ? How many weak minds have been impelled to quar- rel with the orgaaizations of societj', simplj- because it has pleased the imagination of poets to present the image of a world constituted differenth", where no proprietj' chains down opinion and no artifice holds nature in thral- dom ? What a dangerous logic of the passions they have learned since the poets have painted them in their pictures in the most brilliant colors, and since, in the contest with law and duty, they have commonly remained masters of the battle-flcld. What has society gained by the relations of society, formerly under the swa^^ of truth, being now subject to the laws of the beautiful, or by the external impression deciding the estimation in which merit is to be held? We admit that all virtues whose appearance produces an agreeable eff"ect are now seen to flourish, and those which, in society, give a value to the man who possesses them. But, as a compensation, all kinds of excesses are seen to prevail, and all vices are in vogue that can be reconciled with a graceful exterior." It is certainly a matter entitled to reflection that, at almost all the periods of history when art flourished and taste held sway, humanity is found in a state of decline ; nor can a sin- gle instance be cited of the union of a large difl'usion of aesthetic culture with political liberty and social virtue, of fine m-anners associated with good morals, and of politeness fraternizing with truth and loyalty of character and life. ^STHETICAL LETTEKS AND ESSAYS. 63 As long as Athens and Sparta preserved their inde- pendence, and as long as their institutions were based on respect for the laws, taste did not reach its maturity, art remained in its infancy, and beauty was far from exercis- ing her empire over minds. No doubt, poetry had already taken a sublime flight, but it was on the wings of genius, and we know that genius borders very closely on savage coarseness, that it is a light which shines readily in the midst of darkness, and which therefore often argues against rather than in favor of the taste of time. When the golden age of art appears under Pericles and Alexan- der, and the sway of taste becomes more general, strength and liberty have abandoned Greece ; eloquence corrupts the truth, wisdom offends it on the lips of Socrates, and virtue in the life of Phocion. It is well known that the Romans had to exhaust their energies in civil wars, and, corrupted by Oriental luxury, to bow their heads under the yoke of a fortunate despot, before Grecian art triumphed over the stiffness of their character. The same was the case with the Arabs : civilization only dawned upon them when the vigor of their military spirit became soft- ened under the sceptre of the Abbassides. Art did not appear in modern Italy till the glorious Lombard League was dissolved, Florence submitting to the Medici ; and all those brave cities gave up the spirit of independence for an inglorious resignation. It is almost superfluous to call to mind the example of modern nations, with whom refine- ment has increased in direct proportion to the decline of their liberties. Wherever we direct our eyes in past times, , we see taste and freedom mutually avoiding each other. I Everywhere we see that the beautiful onl}' founds its sway I on the ruins of heroic virtues. ' And j'et this strength of character, which is commonly sacrificed to establish sesthetic culture, is the most power- ful spring of all that is great and excellent in man, and no other advantage, however great, can make up for it. Accordingly, if we only keep to the experiments hitherto made, as to the influence of the beautiful, we cannot cer- tainly be much encouraged in developing feelings so dan- gerous to the real culture of man. At the risk of being hard and coarse, it will seem preferable to dispense with 64 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. this dissolving force of the beautiful rather than see human nature a pre}- to its enervating influence, notwithstanding all its refining advantages. However, experience is per- haps not the proper tribunal at which to decide such a question ; before giving so much weight to its testimonj', it would be well to inquire if the beauty we have been discussing is the power that is condemned bj' the previous examples. And the beauty we are discussing seems to assume an idea of the beautiful derived from a source diflferent from experience, for it is this higher notion of the beautiful which has to decide if what is called beautj- by experience is entitled to the name. This pure and rational idea of the beautiful — supposing it can be placed in evidence — cannot be taken from any real and special case, and must, on the contrary, direct and give sanction to our judgment in each special case. It must therefore be sought for by a process of abstraction, and it ought to be deduced from the simple possibility of a nature both sensuous and rational ; in short, beauty ought to present itself as a necessary condition of human- ity. It is therefore essential that we should rise to the pure idea of humanit}', and as experience shows us nothing but individuals, in particular cases, and never humanity at large, we must endeavor to find in their individual and variable mode of being the absolute and the permanent, and to grasp the necessary conditions of their existence, suppressing all accidental limits. No doubt this transcen- dental procedure will remove us for some time from the familiar .circle of phenomena, and the living presence of objects, to keep us on the unproductive ground of abstract idea ; but we are engaged in the search after a principle of knowledge solid enough not to be shaken bj- an^^thing, and the man who does not dare to rise above reality will never conquer this truth. Letter XI. If abstraction rises to as great an elevation as possible, it arrives at two primary ideas, before which it is obliged to stop and to recognize its limits. It distinguishes in man ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 65 something that continues, and something that changes incessantly. That which continues it names his person ; that which changes his position, his condition. The person and the condition, I and my determinations, which we represent as one and the same thing in the necesr sary being, are eternally distinct in the finite being. Not- withstanding all continuance in the person, the condition changes ; in spite of all change of condition the person remains. We pass from rest to activity, from emotion to indifference, from assent to contradiction, but we are always we ourselves, and what immediately springs from ourseloes remains. It is onl3' in the absolute subject that all his determinations continue with his personality. All that Divinity is, it is because it is so ; consequently it is eternally what it is, because it is eternal. As the person and the condition are distinct in man, be- cause he is a finite being, the condition cannot be founded on the person, nor the person on the condition. Admit- ting the second case, the person would have to change ; and in the former case, the condition would have to con- tinue. Thus in either supposition, either the personalit}' or the quality of a finite being would necessarilj- cease. It is not because we think, feel, and will that we are ; it is not because we are that we think, feel, and will. ^Ve are because we are. We feel, think, and will because there is out of us something that is not ourselves. Consequently the person must have its principle of existence in itself, becaui^ the permanent cannot be de- rived from the changeable, and thus we should be at once in possession of the idea of the absolute being, founded on itself; that is to saj-, of the iihi't of freedom. The condition must have a foundation, and as it is not through the person, and is not therefore absolute, it must be & sequence and a result; and thus, in the second place, wt should have arrived at the condition of every independent being, of everj'thing in the process of becoming something else : that is, of the idea of time. " Time is the necessary condition of all processes, of becoming (Werden) ; " this is an identical proposition, for it says nothing but this : " That something may follow, there must be a succes- sion. " 66 iBSTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. The person which manifested itself in the eternally con- tinuing Ego, or I mj'self, and only in him, cannot become something or begin in time, because it is much rather time that must begin with him, because the permanent must serve as basis to the changeable. That change may take place, something must change ; this something cannot therefore be the change itself. When we say the flower opens and fades, we make of this flower a permanent being in the midst of this transformation ; we lend it, in some sort, a personality, in which these two conditions are manifested. It cannot be objected that man is born, and becomes something ; for man is not only a person simply, but he is a person finding himself in a deter- minate condition. Now our determinate state of con- dition springs up in time, and it is thus that man, as a phenomenon or appearance, must have a beginning, though in him pure intelligence is eternal. Without time, that is, without a becoming, he would not be a determinate being ; his personalit3' would exist virtually no doubt, but not in action. It is not by the succession of its percep- tions that the immutable Ego or person manifests himself to himself. Thus, therefore, the matter of activity, or realit}-, that the supreme intelligence draws from its own being, must be received b}- man ; and he does, in fact, receive it, through the medium of perception, as something which is outside him in space, and which changes in him in time. This matter which changes in him is alwaj'S accompanied bjr the Ego, the personalilj', that never changes ; and the rule prescribed for man by his rational nature is to remain immutably himself in the midst of change, to refer all perceptions to experience, that is, to the unity of knowl- edge, and to make of each of its manifestations of its modes in time the law of all time. The matter only exists in as far as it changes : he, his personality, only exists in as far as he does not change. Consequently, represented in his perfection, man would be the permanent unity, which remains alwaj'S the same, among the waves of change. Now, although an infinite being, a divinity could not become (or be subject to time), still a tendency ought to JESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 67 he named divine which has for its infinite end the most characteristic attribute of the divinity ; the absolute mani- festation of power — the reality of all. the possible — and the absolute unity of the manifestation (the necessity of all reality) . It cannot be disputed that man bears within himself, in his personality, a predisposition for'divinitJ^ The way to divinitj'— if the word " way" can be applied to what never leads to its end — is open to him in everj' direction. Considered in itself, and independently of all sensuous matter, his personality is nothing but the pure virtuality of a possible infinite manifestation ; and so long as there is neither intuition nor feeling, it is nothing more than a form, an empty power. Considered in itself, and inde- pendently of all spontaneous activitj' of the mind, sensu- ousness can only make a material man ; without it, it is a pure form ; but it cannot in any wa}' establish a union between matter and it. So long as he only feels, wishes, and acts under the influence of desire, he is nothing more than the world, if by this word we point out onlj- the formless contents of time. Without doubt, it is onl}' his sensuousness that makes his strength pass into efficacious acts, but it is his personality alone that makes this activ- itj" his own. Thus, that he may not onl}- be a world, he must give form to matter, and in order not to be a mere form, he must give reality to the virtuality that he bears in him. He gives matter to form by creating time, and by opposing the immutable to change, the diAcrsitj' of the world to the eternal unitj' of the Ego. He gives a form to matter by again suppressing time, bj- maintaining per- manence in change, and b}- placing the diversity of the world under the unity of the Ego. Now from this source issue for man two opposite exigencies, the two fundamental laws of sensuous-rational nature. The first has for its object absolute realitij: it must make a world of what is only form, manifest all that in it is only a force. The second law has for its object absolute /br^'iaZiYy/ it must destroy in him all that is only world, and carr}' out liarmony in all changes. In other terms, he must manifest all that is internal, and give fori'i to all that is external. Considered in its most lort\- 68 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. accomplishment, this twofold labor brings back to the idea of humanitj^, which was my starting-point. Letter XII. This twofold labor or task, which consists in making the necessary pass into reality in us and in making out of us reality subject to the law of necessity, is urged upon us as a duty by two opposing forces, which are justly styled impulsions or instincts, because they impel us to realize - their object. The first of these impulsions, which I shall call the sensuous instinct, issues from the physical exist- ence of man, or from sensuous nature ; and it is this instinct which tends to enclose him in the limits of time, and to make of him a material being ; I do not say to give him matter, for to do that a certain free activity of the person- ality would be necessary, which, receiving matter, distin- guishes it from the Ego, or what is permanent. By matter I only understand in this place the change or realit}- that fills time. Consequently the instinct requires that there should be change, and that time should contain something. This simply filled state of time is named sensation, and it is only in this state that physical existence manifests itself. As all that is in time is successive, it follows bj' that fact alone that something is : all the remainder is excluded. When one note on an instrument is touched, among all those that it virtually oflTers, this note alone is real. When man is actually modified, the infinite possibilitj' of all his modifications is limited to this single mode of existence. Thus, then, the exclusive action of sensuous impulsion has for its necessary' consequence the narrowest limitation. In this state man is onl3' a unit}' of magnitude, a complete moment in time ; or, to speak more correctly-, he is not, for his personality is suppressed as long as sensation holds sway over him and carries time along with it. This instinct extends its domains over the entire sphere of the finite in man, and as form is only revealed in matter, and the absolute by means of its limits, the total mani- festation of human nature is connected on a close analysis iESTUEXIOAL LETTKK8 AND ESSAYS. 69 with the sensuous instinct. But though it is only this instinct that awakens and develops what exists virtualh* in man, it is nevertheless this ver\' instinct which renders his perfection impossible. It binds down to the world of sense bj- indestructible ties the spirit that tends higher, and it calls back to the limits of the present, abstraction which had its free development in the sphere of the infinite. No doubt, thought can escape it for a moment, and a firm will vlctoriouslj- resist its exigencies : but soon compressed nature resumes her rights to give an imperious realitj- to our existence, to give it contents, substance, knowledge, and an aim for our activity. . The second impulsion, which may be named the formal | ■iaatinct, issues from the absolute existence of man, or from his rational nature, and tends to set free, and bring har- mony into the diversity of its manifestations, and to main- tain personalitj' notwithstanding all the changes of state. As this personalitj-, being an absolute and indivisible unit}', can never be in contradiction with itself, as we are ourselves forever, this impulsion, which tends to maintain personalit}-, can never exact in one time anything but what it exacts and requires forever. It therefore decides for alwaj's what it decides now, and orders now what it orders forever. Hence it embraces the whole series of times, or what comes to the same thing, it suppresses time and change. It wishes the i«al to be necessary and eternal, and it wishes the etgrnal and the necessary to be real ; in other terms, it tends to truth and justice. If the sensuous instinct onl}' produces accidents, the i formal instinct gives laws, laws for ever}' judgment when it is a question of knowledge, laws for every will when it ■ is a question of action. Whether, therefore, we recognize J an object or conceive an objective value to a state of the subject, whether we act in virtue of knowledge or make of the objective the determining principle of our state ; in both cases we withdraw this state from the jurisdiction of time, and we attribute to it reality for all men and for all time, that is, universality and necessity. Feeling can only say : " That is true for this subject and at this moment" and there may come another moment, another subject, which withdraws the affirmation from the actual feeling. 70 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. But when once thought pronounces and says : " That is" it decides forever and e\'er, and the validitj- of its decision is guaranteed by the personality itself, which defies all change. Inclination can only say : " That is good ./or yowr indwidualitii and jore«e;4i necessity '' ; but the changing current of affairs will sweep them awaj', and what j'ou ardently desire to-day will form the object of 3'our aversion _ to-morrow. But when the moral feeling saj's : "That ought to be," it decides forever. If you confess the truth because it is the truth, and if you practise justice because it is justice, you have made of a particular case the law of all possible cases, and treated one moment of your life as eternit}-. Accordingly, when the formal impulse holds sway and the pure object acts in us, the being attains its highest expansion, all barriers disappear^ and from the unity of magnitude in which man was enclosed by a narrow sehsuousness, he rises to the wniiy of idea, which embraces and keeps subject the entire sphere of phenX)mena. Dur- ing this operation we are no longer in time, but time is in us with its infinite succession. We are no longer individ- uals but a species ; the judgment of all spirits is expressed by our own, and the choice of all hearts is represented by our own act. Letter XIII. On a first survey, nothing appears more opposed than these two impulsions ; one having for its object change, the other immutabilitj', and yet it is these two notions that exhaust the notion of humanity, and a ihvcA fundamental iiiipidsion, holding a medium between them, is quite inconceivable. How then shall we re-establish the unity of human nature, a unit}' that appears completely destroyed by this primitive and radical opposition ? I admit these two tendencies are contradictor}-, but it should be noticed that they are not so in the same objects. But things that do not meet cannot come into collision. No doubt the sensuous impulsion desires change ; but it does not wish that it should extend to personality and its ^STHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 71 field, nor that there should be a change of principles. The formal impulsion seeks unitj' and permanence, but it does not wish the condition to remain fixed with the person, that there should be identitj- of feeling. There- fore these two impulsions are not divided bj' nature, and if, nevertheless, thej- appear so, it is because they have become divided by transgressing nature freely, by ignoring themselves, and bj- confounding their spheres. The office of culture is to watch over them and to secure to each one its proper limits ; therefore culture has to give equal justice to both, and to defend not onlj' the rational impulsion against the sensuous, but also the latter against the former. Hence she has to act a twofold part : first, to protect sense against tlie attacks of freedom ; secondly, to secure per- sonality against the power of sensations. One of these ends is attained by the cultivation of the sensuous, the other by that of reason. Since the world is developed in time, or change, the perfection of the facultj- that places men in relation with the world will necessarily be the greatest possible muta- bility and extensiveness. Since personality is permanence in change, the perfection of this faculty, which must be opposed to change, will be the greatest possible freedom of action (autonomy) and intensity. The more the recep- tivity is developed under manifold aspects, the more it is movable and offers surfaces to phenomena, the larger is the part of the world seized upon by man, and the more virtualities he develops in himself. Again, in pro- portion as man gains strength and depth, and depth and reason gain in freedom, in that proportion man takes in a larger share of the world, and throws out forms outside himself. Therefore his culture will consist, first, in placing his receptivity in contact with the world in the greatest number of points possible, and in raising passivity, to the highest exponent on the side of feeling ; secondly, in procuring for the determining faculty the greatest possible amount of independence, in relation to the receptive power, and in raising activity to the highest degree on the side of reason. By the union of these two qualities man will associate the highest degree of self-spontaneity (autonomy) and of 72 AESTHETIC AL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. freedom with the fullest plenitude of existence, and instead of abandoning himself to the world so as to get lost in it, he will rather absorb it in himself, with all the infinitude of its phenomena, and subject it to the unity of his reason. But man can invert this relation, and thus fail in attaining his destination in two ways. He can hand over to the passive force the intensity demanded by the active force ; he can encroach b}' material impulsion on the formal impulsion, and convert the recei:)tive into the deter- mining power. He can attribute to the active force the extensiveness belonging to the passive force, he can en- croach by the formal impulsion on the material impulsion, and substitute the determining for the receptive power. In the former case, he will never be an Ego, a personality ; in the second case, he will never be a Non-Ego, and hence in both cases he will be neither the one nor the other, consequently he will be nothing. In fact, if the sensuous impulsion becomes determining, if the senses become lawgivers, and if the world stifles personality', he loses as object what he gains in force. It may be said of man that when he is only the contents of time, he is not and consequently he has no other contents. His condition is destroj'ed at the same time as his personality, because these are two correlative ideas, because change presupposes permanence, and a limited realit3- implies an infinite reality. If the formal impulsion becomes receptive, that is, if thought anticipates sensation, and the person substitutes itself in the place of the world, it loses as a subject and autonomous force what it gains as object, because immutability implies change, and that to manifest itself also absolute reality requires limits. As soon as man is only form, he has no form, and the person- ality vanishes with the condition. In a word, it is onl3' inasmuch as he is spontaneous, autonomous, that there is realit}' out of him, that he is also receptive ; and it is only inasmuch as he is receptive that there is reality in him, that he is a thinking force. Consequently these two impulsions require limits, and looked upon as forces, they need tempering ; the former that it maj' not encroach on the field of legislation, the ^<:STHETIOAL LETTERS ANU E8BAVS. lO latter that it may not invade tlie ground of feeling. But this tempering and moderating the ponsuous impulsion ought not to be the effect of physical iiiipotence or of a blunting of sensations, which is always a matter for contempt. It must be a free act, an activity of the person, which by its moral intensity moderates the sensuous intensitj-, and bj' the sway of impressions takes from them in depth what it gives them in surface or breadth. The character must place limits to temperament, for the senses have only the right to lose elements if it be to the advan- tage of the mind. In its turn, the tempering of the formal impulsion must not result from moral impotence, from a relaxation of thought and will, which would de- grade humanity. It is necessary that the glorious source of this second tempering should be the fulness of sensa- tions ; it is necessarj- that sensuousness itself should defend its field with a victorious arm and resist the violence that the invading activity of the mind would do to it. In a word, it is necessary that the material impul- sion should be contained in the limits of propriety b}- personality, and the formal impulsion by receptivity or natul'e. Lettee XIV. We have been brought ta the idea of such a correlation between the two impulsions that the action of the one establishes and limits at the same time the action of the other, and that each of them, taken in isolation, does arrive at its highest manifestation just because the other is active. No doubt this correlation of the two impulsions is simply a problem advanced bj' reason, and which man will only be able to solve in the perfection of his being. It is in the strictest signification of the term : the idea of his humanity; accordingl}', it is an infinite to which he can approach nearer and nearer in the course of time, but without ever reaching it. " He ought not to aim at form to the injur}- of realitj, nor to reality to the detriment of the form. He must rather seek the absolute Jbcing bv 74 ^STHBTICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. means of a determinate being, and the determinate being by means of an infinite being. He must set the world before him because he is a person, and he must be a person because he has the world before him. He must feel be- cause he has a consciousness of himself, and he must have a consciousness of himself because he feels." It is only in conformity with this idea that he is a man in the full sense of the word ; but he cannot be convinced of this so long as he gives himself up exclusively to one of these two impulsions, or only satisfies them one after the other. For as long as he only feels, his absolute personality and existence remain a mystery to him, and as long as he only thinks, his condition or existence in time escapes him. But if there were cases in which he could have at once this twofold experience in which he would have the conscious- ness of his freedom- and the feeling of his existence to- gether, in which he would simultaneously feel as matter and know himself as si)irit, in such cases, and in such only, would he have a complete intuition of his humanity, and the object that would procure him this intuition would be a symbol of his accomplished destiny' and consequently serve to express the infinite to him — -since this destination can only be fulfilled in the fulness of time. Presuming that cases of this kind could present thera- seh'es in experience, they would awake in him a new impulsion, which, precisely because the other two impul- sions would co-operate in it, would be opposed to each of them taken in isolation, and might, with good grounds, be taken for a new impulsion. The sensuous impulsion I requires that there shoukl be change, that time should '• have contents ; the formal impulsion requires that time should be suppressed, that there shoLild be no change. Consequently, the impulsion in which both of the others act in concert — allow me to call \t Vae. instinct o/" jofoy, till I explain the term — the instinct of play would have as its object to suppress time in time, to conciliate the state of ' transition or becoming with the absolute being, change L with identity. The sensuous instinct wishes to be determined, it wishes to receive an object ; the formal instinct wishes to deter- mine Itself, it wishes to produce an object. Therefore the ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 75 instinct of pla}- will endeaxor to receive as it would itself have produced, and to produce as it aspires to receive. The sensuous impulsion excludes from its subject all 1 autonomy and freedom ; the formal impulsion excludes all dependence and passivit}-. But the exclusion of free- dom is phj'sical necessitj- ; the exclusion of passi^it}- is moral necessit}'. Thus the two impulsions subdue the mind : the former to the laws of nature, the latter to the laws of reason. It results from this that the instinct of pla}-, which unites the double action of the two other instincts, will content the mind at once morall}- and phy- sicall3^ Hence, as it suppresses all that is contingent, it will also sujjpress all coercion, and will set man free ph3-si-j cally and morally. When we welcome with effusion some one who deserves our contempt, we feel painfully that nature is constrainejj . When we have a hostile feeling I'.gainst a person who commands our esteem, we feel pain- full}' the constraint of reaso)i. But if this person inspires us with interest, and also wins our esteem, the constraint of feeling vanishes together with the constramt of reason, ' and we begin to love him, that is to say, to play, to take ; recreation, at once with our inclination and our esteem. Moreover, as the sensuous impulsion controls us phy- sically, and the formal impulsion morally, the former makes our formal constitution contingent, and the latter makes our material constitution contingent, that is to saj', there is contingence in tHe agreement of our happiness with our perfection, and reciprocall}-. The instinct of play, in which both act in concert, will render both our formal and our material constitution contingent ; accord- ingly, our perfection and our happiness in like manner. And on the other hand, exactlj- because it makes both of them contingent, and because the contingent disappears with necessity, it will suppress this contingence in both, and will thus give form to matter and reality to form. In i proportion that it will lessen the dynamic influence of feeling and passion, it will place them in harmonj- with rational ideas, and by taking from the laws of reason their moral constraint, it will reconcile them with the interest of the senses. 76 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. Letter XV. I APPROACH continually nearer to the end to which I lead jou, by a path offering few attractions. Be pleased to follow me a few steps further, and a lai'ge horizon will open up to j'ou, and a delightful prospect will reward you for the labor of the waj-. ,- The object of the sensuous instinct, expressed in a L universal conception, is named Life in the widest accepta- tion ; a conception that expresses all material existence and all that is immediately present in the senses. The r object of the formal instinct, expressed in a universal con- i ception, is called shape or form, as well in an exact as in an inexact acceptation ; a conception that embraces all formal qualities of things and all relations of tiie same to the thinking powers. The object of the pla}' instinct,^ represented in a general statement, ma,y therefore bear the name of living form; a term that serves to describe all sestiietic qualities of phenomena, and what people stj'le, in the widest sense, beauty. , Beautj- is neither extended to the whole field of all ( living things nor merelj' enclosed in this field. A marble block, though it is and remains lifeless., can nevertheless become a living form bj' the ai'chitect and sculptor ; a man, though he lives and has a form, is far from being a living form on that account. For this to be the case, it is necessary that his form should be life, and that his life should be a form. As long as we onh' think of his form, it is lifeless, a mere abstraction ; as long as we onlj' feel his life, it is without form, a mere impression. It is only when his form lives in our feeling, and his 'life in our understanding, he is the living form, and this will evervwhere be the case where we judge him to be beau- tiful" But the genesis of beautj- is by no means declared because we know how to point out the component parts, which in their combination produce beaut3-. For to this end it would be necessary to comprehend that combination itself, which continues to defy our exploration, as well as JESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 77 all mutual operation between the finite and tiie infinite. The reason, on transcendental grounds, makes the fol- lowing demand : There shall be a communion between the formal impulse and the material impulse — that is, there shall be a pla}' instinct — because it is onlj^ the unity of reality with the form, of the accidental with the necessary, of the passive state with freedom, that the conception of humanity is completed. Reason is obliged to make this demand, because her nature impels her to completeness and to the removal of all bounds ; while every exclusive activity of one or the other impulse leaves human nature incomplete and places a limit in it. Accordingl}', as soon as reason issues the mandate, " a humanity shall exist, " it proclaims at the same time the law, '■ there shall be a beautj'." Kxperionce can answer us if there is a beauty, and we shall know it as soon as she has taught us if a humanity can exist. But neither reason nor experience can tell us how beauty can be and how a humanity is possible. We know that man is neither exclusively matter nor exclusively spirit. Accordingly, beauty as the consum- mation of humanity, can neither be exclusivel3' mere life, as has been asserted by sharp-sighted observers, who kept too close to the testimony of experience, and to which the taste of the time would gladly degrade it ; Xor can beauty be merely form, as has been judged b}' speculative sophists, who departed too far from experience, and by philosophic arti!^ts, who were led too much by the necessity of art in explaining beauty ; it is rather the coumion object of both impulses, that is of the plaj- instinct. The use of language completely justifies this name, as it it wont to qualify with the word play what is neither subjectively nor objectively accidental, and j^et does not impose necessity either externally or internally. As the mind in the intuition of the beautiful finds itself in a happy medium between law and necessity, it is, be- cause it divides itself between both, emancipated from the pressure of both. The formal impulse and the ma- terial impulse are equally earnest in their demands, because one relates in its cognition to things in their •■eality and the other to their necessity ; because in action 78 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. the first is directed to the preservation of life, the second to the preservation of dignitj', and therefore both to truth and perfection. But life becomes more indifferent when dignity is mixed up with it, and dutj' no longer coerces when inclination attracts. In like manner the mind takes in the reality of things, material truth, more freely and tranquilly as soon as it encounters formal truth, the law of necessity ; nor does the mind find itself strung by abstraction as soon as immediate intuition can accompany it. In one word, when the mind comes into communion with ideas, all reality loses its serious value because it becomes small; and as it comes in contact with feel- ing, necessity parts also with its serious value because it is easy. But perhaps the objection has for some time occurred to you. Is not the beautiful degraded by this, that it is made a mere play .? and is it not reduced to the level of frivolous objects which have for ages passed under that name? Does it not contradict the conception of the reason and the dignity of beauty, which is nevertheless regarded as an instrument of culture, to confine it to the work of being a mere plaj'? and does it not contradict the empirical conception of play, which can coexist with the exclusion of all taste, to confine it merely to beauty? But what is meant bj- a tnere play, when we know that in all conditions of humanity that very thing is plaj^, and only that is play which makes man complete and develops simultaueousl.y his twofold nature? What j'ou stj'le limitation, according to your representation of the matter, according to my views, which I have justified by proofs, I name enlargement. Consequenth' I should have said exactly the reverse : man is serious only with the agreeable, with the good, and with the perfect, but he ^j/ays with beauty. In sajing this we must not indeed think of the plays that are in vogue in real life, and which commonly refer onl}' to his material state. But in real life we should also seek in vain for the beaut}' of which we are here speaking. The actually- present beauty- is worthy of the really, of the actually- present play -impulse ; hut hy the ideal of beauty, \vhich is set up by the reason, an ideal of the play-instinctjis also presented, which man ought to have before his eyes in all his plays. JESTHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 79 Therefore, no error will ever be incurred if we seek the Ideal of beauty on the same road ou which we satirfj' our play-impulse. We can immediately understand why the ideal form of a Venus, of a Juno, and of an Apollo, is to be souglit not at Rome, but in Greece, if we contrast the Greek population, delighting in the bloodless athletic contests of boxing, racing, and intellectual rivalry at Olympia, with the Roman people gloating over the agony of a gladiator. Now the reason pronounces that the beau- tiful must not only be life and form, but a living form, that is, beaut}', inasmuch as it dictates to man the twofold law of absolute formality and absolute reality. Reason also utters the decision that man shall onl}' play with beauty, and he shall onlij flay with heanty. For, to speak out once for all, man only plaj-s when in the full meaning of the word he is a man, and he is only completely a maniohhi he plays. This proposition, which at this moment perliaps appears paradoxical, will receive a great and deep meaning if we have advanced far enough to apply it to the twofold seriousness of dutj- and of destiny. I promise j-ou that the whole edifice of aesthetic art and the still more difficult art of life will be supported by this principle. But this proposition is only unexpected in science ; long ago it lived and worked in art and in the feeling of the Greeks, her most accomplished masters ; only they removed to Olj-mpus what ought to have been preserved on earth. Influenced b}' the truth of this prin- ciple, they effaced fromk;hebrow of their gods the earnest- ness and labor which furrow the cheeks of mortals, and also the hollow lust that smoothes the emptj' face. They set free the ever serene from the chains of every purpose, of every duty, of every care, and they made indolence and indifference the envied condition of the godlike race ; merely human appellations for the freest and highest mind. As well the material pressure of natural laws as the spiritual pressure of moral laws lost itself in its higher idea of necessity, which embraced at the same time both worlds, and out of the union of these two necessities issued true freedom. Inspired b}' this spirit the Greeks also effaced from the features of their ideal, together with desire or inclination., all traces of volition, or, better still, 80 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. they made both unrecognizable, because they knew how to *ed them both in the closest alliance. It is neither charm, nor is it dignity, which speaks from the glorious face of Juno Ludovici ; it is neither of these, for it is both at once. While the female god challenges our veneration, tlie godlike woman at the same time kindles our love. But while in ecstacy we give ourselves up to the heavenly beauty, the heavenly self-repose awes us back. The whole form rests and dwells in itself — a fully complete creation in itself — and as if she were out of space, without advance or resistance ; it shows no force contending with force, no opening through whicli time could break in. Irresistibly carried away and attracted by her womanlj^ charm, kept off at a distance by her godly dignity, we also lind ourselves at length in the state of the greatest repose, and the result is a wonderful impression for which the under- standing has no idea and language no name. Letter XVT. From the antagonism of the two impulsions, and from the association of two opposite principles, we have seen beauty to result, of which the highest ideal must therefore be sought in the most perfect union and equilibrium possi- rble of the reality and of the form. But this equilibrium I remains always an idea that reality can never completelj' ( reach. In reality, there will alwaj's remain a preponder- ance of one of these elements over the other, and the highest point to which experience can reach will consist in an oscillation between two principles, when sometimes reality and at others form will have the advantage. Ideal beauty is therefore eternally one and indivisible, because there can only be one single equilibrium ; on the contrary, e'xperimeutal beauty will be eternally double, because in the oscillation tlie equilibrium maj^ be destroj'ed in two waj's — this side 'and that. I have called attention in the foregoing letters to a fact that can also be rigorouslj^ deduced from the considera- tions that have engaged our attention to the present point; this fact is that an es-citing and also a moderating action iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 81 may be expected from the beautiful. The tempering action is directed to keep within proper limits the sensuous and the formal impulsions ; the exciting, to maintain both of them in their full force. But these two modes of action of beauty ought to be complete!}" identified in the idea. The beautiful ought to temper while uniformly exciting the two natures, and it ought also to excite while uni- formly moderating them. This result flows at once from the idea of a correlation, in virtue of which the two terms mutually imply each other, and are the reciprocal condition one of the other, a correlation of which the purest pro- duct is beauty. But experience does not offer an example of so perfect a correlation. In the field of experience it will always happen more or less that excess on the one side will give rise to deficiency on the other, and deficiency will give birth to excess. It results from this that what in the beau-ideal is only distinct in the idea is different in reality in empirical beauty. The beau-ideal, though sim- ple and indivisible, discloses, when viewed in two different aspects, on the one hand, a property of gentleness and grace, and on the other, an energetic property ; in expe- rience there is a gentle and graceful beauty and there is an energetic beauty. It is so, and it will be always so, so long as the absolute is enclosed in the limits of time, and the ideas of reason have to be realized in humanity. For example, the intellectual man has the ideal of virtue, of truth, and of happiness ; but the active man will onl^- practise virtues, will only §rasp truths, and enjoj' happy days. The business of physical and moral education is to bring back this multiplicitj- to unitj', to put morality in \ the place of manners, science in the place of knowledge ; i the business of aesthetic education is to make out of j beauties the beautiful. Energetic beaut}' can no more preserve a man from a certain residue of sa^'age violence and harshness than graceful beauty can secure him against a certain degree of efreminacj' and weakness. As it is the effect of the energetic beautj' to ele^•ate the mind in a physical and moral point of view and to augment its momentum, it onlj' too often happens that the resistance of the temperamsnt and of the character diminishes the aptitude to receive 82 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. impressions, that the delicate part of humanity suffers as oppression which ought onlj- to affect its grosser part, and that this coarse nature participates in an increase of force that ought only to turn to the account of free per- sonality. It is for this reason that, at the periods when we find much strength and abundant sap in humanitj-, true greatness of thought is seen associated with what is gigantic and extravagant, and the subli.mest feeling is found coupled with the most horrible excess of passion. It is also the reason why, in the periods distinguished for regularity and form, nature is as often oppressed as it is governed, as often outraged as it is surpassed. And as the action of gentle and graceful beauty is to relax the mind in the moral sphere as well as the physical, it hap- pens quite as easily that the energy of feelings is extin- guished with the violence of desires, and that character shares in the loss of strength which ought only to affect the passions. This is the reason •" hy, in ages assumed to be refined, it is not a rare thing to see gentleness degen- erate into effeminac3', politeness into platitude, correctness into empty sterilitj', liberal ways into arbitrarj" -caprice, ease into frivolity, calm into apathy, and, lastly, a most miserable caricature treads on the heels of the noblest, the most beautiful tj-pe of humanit3'. Gentle and graceful beauty is therefore a want to the man who suffers the constraint of manner and of forms, for he is moved hj grandeur and strength long before he becomes sensible to harmony and grace. Energetic beauty is a necessity to the man who is under the indulgent swaj- of taste, for in his state of refinement he is only too much disposed to make light of the strength that he retained in his state of rude savagism. I think I have now answered and also cleared up the contradiction commonly met in the judgments of men respecting the influence of the beautiful, and the appre- ciation of aesthetic culture. This contradiction is ex- plained directly we remember that there are two sorts of experimental beauty, and that on both hands an affir- mation is extended to the entire race, when it can only be*pro^-ed of one of the species. This contradiction dis- appears the moment we distinguish a, twofold want in ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 83 humanity to which two kinds of beauty corresponfl. It is therefore probable that both sides would make good their claims if they come to an understanding respecting the kind of beauty and the form of humanity that thej have in view. Consequently in the sequel of my researches I shall adopt the course that nature lierself follows with man considered from the point of view of aesthetics, and setting out from the two kinds of beauty, I shall rise to the idea of the genus. I shall examine the effects produced on man by the gentle and graceful beauty when its springs of action are in full play, and also those produced by energetic beauty when they are relaxed. I shall do this to confound these two sorts of beauty in the unity of the beau-ideal, in the same way that the two opposite forms and modes of being of humanity are absorbed in the unity of the ideal man. Letter XVII. While we were only engaged in deducing the universal idea of beauty from the conception of human nature in general, we had only to consider in the latter the limits established essentially in itself, and inseparable from the notion of the finite. Without attending to the contingent restrictions that human ^ature may undergo in the real world of phenomena, we have drawn the conception of this nature directly from reason, as a source of every necessity, and the ideal of beauty has been given us at the same time with the ideal of humanitJ^ But now we are coming down from the region of ideas to the scene of reality, to find man in a determinate state, and consequently in limits which are not derived from the pure conception of humanity, but from external circum- stances and from an accidental use of his freedom. But, although the limitation of the idea of humanity may be very manifold in the individual, the contents of this 'idea suflSce to teach us that we can only depart from it by two opposite roads. For if the perfection of man consist in the harmonious energy of his sensuous and spiritual forces. 84 JESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. he can only lack this perfection through the want of har- mony and 'the want of energy. Thus, then, before having received on this point the testimony of experience, reason suffices to assure us that we shall find the real and conse- quently limited man in a state of tension or relaxation, according as the exclusive activity of isolated forces troubles the harmony of his being, or as the unity of his nature is based on the uniform relaxation of his physical and spiritual forces. These opposite limits are, as we have now to prove, suppressed by the beautiful, which re-establishes harmony in man when excited, and energy in man when relaxed ; and which, in this waj', in con- formitj- with the nature of the beautiful, restores the state of limitation to an absolute state, and makes of man a whole, complete in himself. Thus the beautiful bj' no means belies in reality the idea which we have made of it in speculation ; only its action is much less free in it than in the field of theory, where we were able to apply it to the jjure conception of humanity. In man. as experience shows him to us, the beautiful finds a matter, already damaged and resisting, which robs him in ideal perfection of what it communicates to him of its individual mode of being. Accordingh- in realitj' the beautiful will alwaj's appear a peculiar and limited species, and not as the pure genus ; in excited minds in a state of tension it will lose its freedom and varietj- ; in relaxed minds, it will lose its vivifying force ; but we, who have become familiar with the true character of this contradictory phenomenon, cannot be led astray by it. We shall not follow the great crowd of critics, in determining their conception by separate experiences, and to make them answerable for the deficiencies which man shows under their influence. We know rather that it is man who transfers the imperfections of his individualit3' over to them, who stands perpetually in the wa}' of their perfection by his subjective limitation, and lowers their absolute ideal to two limited forms of phenomena. It was advanced that soft beauty is for an unstrung mind, and the energetic beauty for the tightly strung mind. But I apply the term unstrung to a man when he is rather under the pressure of feelings than under the pressure of ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 85 donceptious. Eveiy exclusive sy^&y of one of his two fundamental impulses is for man a state of compulsion and violence, and freedom only exists in the co-operation of his two natures. Accordingl}-, the man governed preponderately by feelings, or sensuously unstrung, is emancipated and set free by matter. The soft and grace- ful beauty, to satisfy this twofold problem, must therefore show herself under two aspects — in two distinct forms. First, as a form in repose, she will tone down savage life, and pave the way from feeling to thought. She will, secondl3', as a living image, equip the abstract form with sensuous power, and lead back the conception to intuition and law to feeling. The former service she does to the man of natui'e, the second to the man of art, But be- cause she does not in both cases hold complete swaj- o^er her matter, but depends on that which is furnished either b}' formless nature or unnatural art, she will in both cases bear traces of her origin, and lose herself in one place in material life and in another in mere abstract form. To be able to arrive at a conception how beautj- can become a means to remove this twofold relaxation, we must explore its source in the human mind. Accordingly, make up 30ur mind to dwell a little longer in the region of speculation, in order then to leave it forever, and to advance with securer footing on the ground of experience. LEftER XVIII. By beauty the sensuous man is led to form and to thought ; b}- beauty the spiritual man is brought back to matter and restored to the world of sense. From this statement it would appear to follow that between matter and form, between passivity and activity, there must be a middle state, and that beautj- plants us in this state. It actuall3- happens that the greater part of mankind reallv form this conception of beauty as soon as they begin to reflect on its operations, and all experience seems to point to this conclusion. But, on the other hand, nothing is more unwarrantable and contradictory than such a conception, because the aversion of matter and form, 86 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. the passive and the active, feeling and thought, is eternal, and cannot be mediated in anj- wa}'. How can we re- move this contradiction? Beauty weds the two opposed conditions of feeling and thinking, and yet there is ab- solutely no medium between them. The former is imme- diately certain through experience, the other through the reason. This is the point to which the whole question of beauty leads, and if we succeed in settling this point in a satisfactor}' wa}', we have at length found the clue that will conduct us through the whole labyrinth of ses- theties. But this requires two ver}' different operations, which must necessarily support each other in this inquirj'. Beautj', it is said, weds two conditions with one another which are opposite to each other, and can never be one. We must start from this opposition ; we must grasp and recognize them in their entire purity and strictness, so that both conditions are separated in the most definite manner ; otherwise we mix, but we do not unite them. Secondlj-, it is usual to say, beauty unites those two opposed condi- tions, and therefore removes the opposition. But because l)oth conditions remain eternally opposed to one another, thej- cannot be united in any other way than by being suppressed. Our second business is therefore to make this connection perfect, tocarrj'' them out with such purity and perfection that both conditions disappear entirely in a third one, and no trace of separation remains in the whole ; otherwise we segregate, but do not unite. All the disputes that have ever prevailed and still prevail in the philosoph- ical world respecting the conception of beauty have no other origin than their commencing without a sufficiently strict distinction, or that it is not carried out fully to a pure union. Those philosophers who blindly follow their feeling in reflecting on this topic can obtain no other conception of beauty, because they distinguish nothing separate in the totality of the sensuous impression. Other philosophers, who take the understanding as their ex- clusive guide, can never obtain a conception of beauty, because they never see .anything else in the whole than the parts : and spirit and matter remain eternally separate, ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 87 even in their most perfect unity. The first fear to sup- press beauty dynamically, that is, as a working power, if the}' must separate what is united in the feeling. The others fear to suppress beauty logically, that is, as a con- ception, when they have to hold together vrhat in the understanding is separate. The former wish to think of beaut}- as it works ; the latter wish it to work as it is thought. Both therefore must miss the truth ; the former, because they try to follow infinite nature with their limited thinking power ; the others, because they wish to limit unlimited nature according to their laws of thought. The first fear to rob beauty of its freedom by a too strict dis- section, the others fear to destroy the distinctness of the conception by a too violent union. But the former do not reflect that the freedom in which the}' very properly place the essence of beauty is not lawlessness, but harmony of laws ; not caprice, but the highest internal necessity. The others do not remember that distinctness, which they with equal right demand from beauty, does not consist in the exclvsion of certain realities, but the absolute includ- ing of all ; that is not therefore limitation but infinitude. We shall avoid the quicksands on which both have made shipwreck if we begin from the two elements in which beau- ty divides itself before the understanding, but then after- wards rise to a pure aesthetic unity by which it works on feeling, and in which both those conditions completely dis- appear. Lettek XIX. Two principal and different states of passive and active capacity of being determined* can be distinguished in man ; in like manner two states of passive and active determi nation . f The explanation of this proposition leads us most readily to our end. The condition of the state of man before destination or direction is given him by the impression of the senses is an unlimited capacity of being determined. The infinite of time and space is given to his imagination for its free use ; and, because nothing is settled in this kingdom of * Bestimmbarkeit. t Bestimmung. 88 ^sthetical letters and essays. the possible, and therefore nothing is excluded from it) this state of absence of determination can be named an empty infiniteness, which must not by anj' means be con- founded with an infinite void. Now it is necessarj' that his sensuous nature should be modified, and that in the indefinite series of possible de- terminations one alone should become real. One percep- tion must spring up in it. That which, in the previous state of determinableness, was onlj- an empty potency be- comes now an active force, and receives contents ; but, at the same time, as an active force it receives a limit, after having been, as a simple power, unlimited. Reality exists now, but the infinite has disappeared. To describe a figure in space, we are obliged to limit infinite space ; to represent to ourselves a change in time, we are obliged to divide the totality of time. Thus we onlj- arrive at reality by limitation, at the positive, at a real position, by negation or exclusion ; to determination, by the suppres- sion of our free determinableness. But mere exclusion would never beget a reality, nor would a mere sensuous impression ever give birth to a perception, if there were not something fi'om which it was excluded, if by an absolute act of the mind the negation were not referred to something positive, and if opposition did not issue out of non-position. This act of the mind is styled judging or thinking, and the result is named thought. Before we determine a place in space, there is no space for us ; but without alisolute space we could never deter- mine a place. The same is the case with time. Before we have an instant, there is no time to us : but without infinite time — eternity — we should never have a repre- sentation of the instant. Thus, therefore, we can only arrive at the whole by the part, to the unlimited through limitation ; but i-eciprocallj' we only arrive at the part through the whole, at limitation through the unlimited. It follows from this, that when it is affirmed of beauty that it mediates for man, the transition from feeling to thought, this must not be understood to mean that beauty can fill up the gap that separates feeling from thought, the passive from the active. This gap is infinite ; and, without JESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 8C the interposition of a new and independent faculty, it is impossible for the general to issue from the individual, the necessary from the contingent. Thought is the immediate act of this absolute power, which, I admit, can only be manifested in connection with sensuous impressions, but which in this manifestation depends so little on the sen- suous that it reveals itself specially in an opposition to it. The spontaneity or autonomy with which it acts excludes every foreign influence ; and it is not in as far as it /te^:>s thought — which comprehends a manifest contradiction — but only in as far as it procures for the intellectual faculties the freedom to manifest themselves in conformity witli their proper laws. It does it only because the beautiful can become a, means of leading man from matter to form, from feeling to laws, from a limited existence to an absolute existence. But this assumes that the freedom of the intellectual faculties can be balked, which appears contradictory to the conception of an autonomous power. For a power which only receives the matter of its activitj' from without can only be hindered in its action by the privation of this matter, and consequently by way of negation ; it is there- fore a misconception of the nature of the mind to attri- bute to the sensuous passions the power of oppressing positively the freedom of the mind. Experience does indeed present numerous examples where the rational forces appear compressed in proportion to the violence of the sensuous forces. But %istead of deducing this spiritual weakness from the energy of passion, this passionate energy must rather be explained by the weakness of the human mind. For the sense can onlv have a sway such as this over man when the mind has spontaneously' neglected to assert its power. Yet in trying by these explanations to move one objec- tion, I appear to have exposed myself to another, and I have only saved the autonomy of the mind at the cost of its unity. For how can the mind derive at the same time from itself the principles of inactivity and of activity, if it is not itself divided, and if it is not in opposition with itself ? Here we must remember that we have before us, not the 90 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. infinite mind, but the finite. Tte finite mind is that which only becomes active through the passi\'e, only arrives at the absolute through limitation, and only acts and fashions in as far as it receives matter. Accordinglj', a mind of this nature must associate with the impulse towards form or the absolute, an impulse towards matter or limitation, conditions without which it could not have the former impulse nor satisfy it. How can two such opposite tendencies exist together in the same being? This is a problem that can no doubt embarrass the meta- physician, but not the transcendental philosopher. The latter does not presume to explain the possibility of things, but he is satisfied with giving a solid basis to the knowl- edge that makes us understand the possibility of expe- rience. And as experience would be equally impossible without this autonomy in the mind, and without the absolute unity of the mind, it lays ^down these two con- ceptions as two conditions of experience equally necessary without troubling itself any moi'e to reconcile them. Moreover, this immanence of two fundamental impulses does not in any degree contradict the absolute unitj' of the mind, as soon as the mind itself, its selfhood, is dis- tinguished from those two motors. No doubt, these two impulses exist and act in it, but itself is neither matter nor form, nor the sensuous nor reason, and this is a point that does not seem alwajs to have occurred to those who only look upon the mind as itself acting when its acts are in harmonj' with reason, and who declare it passive when its acts contradict reason. Arrived at its development, each of these two funda- mental impulsions tends of necessitj- and bj' its nature to satisfy itself; but precisely because each of them has a necessary tendenc}-, and both nevertheless have an oppo- site tendency, this twofold constraint mutually destroys itself, and tlie will preserves an entire freedom between them both. It is therefore the will that conducts itself like a power — as the basis of realitj' — with respect to both these impulses ; but neither of them can by itself act as a power with respect to the other. A violent man, bj' his positive tendency to justice, which never fails in him, -s turned away from injustice ; nor can a temptation of ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 91 pleasure, however strong, make a Sjtrong character violate its principles. There is in man no other power than his will ; and death alone, which destro.ys man, or some priva- tion of self-consciousness, is the onlj- thing that can rob man of his internal freedom. An external necessity determines our condition, our existence in time, by means of the sensuous. The latter is quite involuntary, and directl}- it is produced in us we are necessarily passive. In the same manner an internal necessitj- awakens our personality in connection with sen- sations, and bj- its antagonism with them ; for conscious- ness cannot depend on the will, which presupposes it. This primitive manifestation of personality' is no more a merit to us than its privation is a defect in us. Reason can only be required in a being who is self-conscious, for reason is an absolute consecutiveness and universalitj- of consciousness ; before this is the case he is not a man, nor can any act of humanity- be expected from hini. The metaphysician can no more explain the limitation imposed by sensation on a free and autonomous mind than the natural philosopher can understand the infinite, which is revealed in consciousness in connection with these limits. Neither abstraction nor experience can bring us back to the source whence issue our ideas of necessity and of universality : this source is concealed in its origin in time from the observer, and its super-sensuous origin from the researches of the metaphysician. But, to sum up in a few words, consciousness is there, and, together with its im- mutable unity, the law of all that is for man is established, as well as of all that is to be by man, for his understand- ing and his activity. The ideas of truth and of right present themselves inevitable, incorruptible, immeasurable, even in the age of sensuousness ; and without our being able to saj- wh}- or how, we see eternity in time, the neces- sary following the contingent. It is thus that, without any shai-e on the part of the subject, the sensation and self-consciousness arise, and the origin of both is be- yond our volition, as it is out of the sphere of our knowl- edge. But as soon as these two faculties have passed into action, and man has verified by his experience, through the 92 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. mediumof sensation, a determinate existence, and through the medium of consciousness its absolute existence, the two fundamental impulses exert their influence directly their object is given. The sensuous impulse is awakened ■with the experience of life — with the beginning of the individual ; the rational impulsion with the experience of law — with the beginning of his personalit3- ; and it is only when these two inclinations have come into existence that the human type is realized. Up to that time, ex-erything takes place in man according to the law of necessity ; but now the hand of 7ic(ture lets him go, and it is for Mm to keep upright humanity, which nature places as a germ in l)is heart. And thus we see that directly the two opposite and fundamental impulses exercise their influence in him, both lose their constraint, and the autonomy of two necessities gives birth to free- dom. Letter XX. That freedom is an active and not a passive principle results from its very conception ; but that liberty itself should be an effect of nature (taking this word in its widest sense), and not the work of man, and therefore that it can be favored or thwarted bj' natural means, is the necessary consequence of that which precedes. It begins only when man is complete, and when these two fundamental impulsions have been developed. It will then be wanting whilst he is incomplete, and while one of these impulsions is excluded, and it will be re-established by all that gives back to man his integrity. Thus it is possible, both with regard to the entire species as to the individual, to remark the moment when man is yet incomplete, and when one of the two exclusions acts solely in him. We know that man commences by life simply, to end by form ; that he is more of an indi- vidual than a person, and that he starts from the limited or finite to approach the infinite. The sensuous impulsion comes into play therefore before the rational impulsion, because sensation jirecedes consciousness ; and in this iESTHETICAL T.ETTERS AND ESSAYS. 93 priority of sensuous iiupulsiou we find tlie key of the historj^ of tiie whole of human liberty'. There is a moment, in fact, when the instinct of life, not yet opposed to the instinct of form, acts as nature and as necessity ; when the sensuous is a power because man has not begun ; for even in man there can be no other power than his will. But when man shall have attained to the power of thought, reason, on the contrarj', will be a power, and moral or logical necessitj' will take the place of phj'sical necessity. Sensuous power must then be annihilated before the law which must govern it can be established. It is not enough that something shall begin which as yet was not ; previously- something must end which had begun. Man cannot pass immediately from sensnousness to thought. He must step backwards, for it is only when one determination is suppressed that the con- trary determination can take place. Consequentl}', in order to exchange passive against active libertj', a passive de- termination against an active, he must be momentarily free from all determination, and must traverse a state of pure determinability. He has then to return in some degree to that state of pure negative indetermination in which he was before his senses were affected by anything. But this state was absolutely empt}' of all contents, and now the question is to reconcile an equal determination and a determinability equallj- without limit, wiih the greatest possible fulness, because from this situation some- thing positive must immediately follow. The determi- nation which man received b^' sensation must be preserved, because he should not lose the realit}' ; but at the same time, in so far as finite, it should be suppressed, because a determinabilit}- without limit would take place. The problem consists then in annihilating the determination of the mode of existence, and yet at the same time in pre- serving it, which is onl^' possible in one way • hi opposim/ to it another. The two sides of a balance are in equi- librium when empt}' ; they are also in equilibrium when their contents are of equal weight. Thus, to pass from sensation to thought, the soul tra- verses a medium position, in which sensibility and reason are at the same time active, and thus they mutually- destroy 94 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. their determinant power, and by their antagonism produce a negation. Ttiis medium situation in wtiicli the soul is neither phj'sicall^- nor morally constrained, and yet is in both ways active, merits esserjtiall3- the name of a free situation ; and if we call the state of sensuous determina- tion physical, and the state of rational determination logical or moral, that state of real and active determination should be called the aesthetic. Letter XXI. I HAVE remarked in the beginning of the foregoing letter that there, is a twofold condition of determinableness and a twofold condition of determination. And now I can clear up tliis proposition. The mind can be determined — is determinable — only in as far as it is not determined ; it is, however, deter- minable also, in as far as it is not exclusivelj^ determined ; that is, if it is not confined in its determination. The former is only a want of determination — it is without limits, because it is without reality' ; but the latter, the aesthetic determinableness, has no limits, because it unites all realit}'. The mind is determined, inasmuch as it is only limited ; but it is also determined because it limits itself of its own absolute capacity. It is situated in the former position when it feels, in the second when it thinks. Accordingly the sesthetic constitution is in relation to determinableness what thought is in relation to determin- ation. The latter is a negative from internal and infinite completeness, the former a limitation from internal infinite power. Feeling and thought come into contact in one single point, the mind is determined in both conditions, the man becomes something and exists — either as indi- vidual or person — b^- exclusion ; in other cases these two faculties stand infinitely apart. Just in the same manner the aesthetic determinableness comes in contact with the mere want of determination in a single point, by both excluding every distinct determined existence, b}- thus being in all other points nothing and all, and hence by being ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 95 infinitely different. Therefore if the latter, in the absence of determination from deficiency, is represented as an empty infiniteness, the aesthetic freedom of determination, which forms the proper counterpart to the former, can be considered as a completed infiniteness; a representation which exactly agrees with the teachings of the previous investigations. Man is therefore nothing in the aesthetic state, if atten- ] tion is given to the single result, and not to the whole J faculty, and if we regard only the absence or want of every special determination. We must therefore do justice to those who pronounce the beautiful, and the disposition in which it places the mind, as entirely indifferent and unprofitable, in relation to knowledge and feeling. They are perfectly right ; for it is certain that beautj- gives no separate, single result, either for the understanding or for the will ; it does not carry out a single Intellectual or moral object ; it discovers no truth, does not help us to fulfil a single dutj-, and, in one word, is equally unfit to found the character or to clear the head. Accordingly, the personal worth of a man, or his dignitj', as far as this can only depend on himself, remains entirely undetermined by aesthetic culture, and nothing further is attained than that, on the part of nature., it is made profitable for him to make of himself what he will ; that the freedom to be what he ought to be is restored perfectly to Him. But by this something infinite is attained. But as , soon as we remember *hat freedom is taken from man ' by the one-sided compulsion of nature in feeling, and by \ the exclusive legislation of the reason in thinking, we ! must consider the capacity restored to him by the aesthet- ical disposition, as the highest of all gifts, as the gift of humanit}'. I admit that he possesses this capacity for humanity, before every definite determination in which he ma}- be placed. But, as a matter of fact, he loses it with every determined condition into which he ma,y come ; and if he is to pass over to an opposite condition, humanity must be in every case restored to him by the aesthetic life. It is therefore not only a poetical license, but also philosophically correct, when beauty is named our second 96 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. creator. Nor is this inconsistent with the fact that she only makes it possible for us to attain and realize humanity, leaving this to our free will. For in this she acts in common with our original creator, nature, which has imparted to us nothing further than this capacity for humanity, but leaves the use of it to our own determina- tion of will. Letter XXII. Accordingly, if the aesthetic disposition of the mind must be looked upon in one respect as nothing — that is, when we confine our view to separate and determined operations — it must be looked upon in another respect as a state of the highest reality, in as far as we attend to the absence of all limits and the sum of powers which are commonly active in it. Accordingly we cannot pronounce them, again, to be wrong who describe the aesthetic state to be the most productive in relation to knowledge and morality. They are perfectly right, for a state of mind which comprises the whole of humanit}' in itself must of necessity include in itself also — necessarily and poten- tially — every separate expression of it. Again, a dis- position of mind tliat removes all limitation from the totalitj' of human nature must also remove it from everj' special expression of the same. Exactly because its "aesthetic disposition " does not exclusively shelter any separate function of liumanitj^, it is favorable to all with- out distinction ; nor does it favor any particular functions, precisely because it is the foundation of the possibilitj' of all. All other exercises give to the mind some special aptitude, but for that ver}' reason give it some definite limits ; onlj- the sesthetical leads him to the unlimited. Ever^- other condition in which we can li\'e refers us to a previous condition, and requires for its solution a following condition ; onlj' the aesthetic is a complete whole in itself, for it unites in itself all conditions of its source and of its duration. Here alone we feel ourselves swept out of time, and our humanity expresses itself with puritj' and integrity as if it had not j-et received any im- >E8THETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 97 pretss'ob or interruption from the operation of external powers. That wXiich flatters our senses in immediate sensation opens our weak and volatile spirit to everj- impression, but makes us in the same degree less apt for exertion. That which s';retches our thinking power and invites to abstract conceptions strengthens our mind for every kind of resistance, but hardens it also in the same proportion, and deprives us of susceptibility in the same ratio that it helps us to greater mental activity. For this very reason, one as well as the other brings us at length to exhaustion, because matter cannot long do without the shaping, constructive force, and the force cannot do without the con- structible material. But on the other hand, if we have resigned ourselves to the enjoyment of genuine beauty, we are at such a moment of our passive and active powers in the same degree master, and we shall turn with ease from grave to gay, from rest to movement, from submission to resistance, to abstract thinking and intuition. This high indifference and freedom of mind, united with power and elasticitj-, is the disposition in which a true work of art ought to dismiss us, and there is no better test of true aesthetic excellence. If after an enjoyment i of this kind we find ourselves specially impelled to a ; particular mode of feeling or action, and unfit for other j modes, this serves as an infallible proof that we have not experienced cm y pure msthetic effect, whether this is owing I to the object, to our ow« mode of feeling — as generally I happens — or to both together. As in reality no purely sesthetical effect can be met with — for man can never leave his dependence on material forces — the excellence of a work of art can only consist^ in its greater approximation to its ideal of aesthetic purity, \ and however high we may raise the freedom of this effect, we shall always leave it with a particular disposition and a particular bias. Any class of productions or separate work in the world of art is noble and excellent in pro-' portion to the universality of the disposition and the unlimited character of the bias thereby presented to our mind. This truth can be applied to works in various branches of art, and also to different works in the same 98 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. branch. We leave a grand musical performance with our feelings excited, the reading of a noble poem with a quickened Imagination, a beautiful statue or building with an awakened understanding ; but a man would not choose an opportune moment who attempted to invite us to abstract thinking after a high musical enjoyment, or to attend to a prosaic affair of common life after a high poetical enjoy- ment, or to kindle our imagination and astonish our feel- ings directly after inspecting a fine statue or edifice. The reason of this is, that music, hy its riiatter, even when most spiritual, presents a greater aflflnity with the senses than is permitted by aesthetic liberty ; it is because even the most happy poetry, having /br its medium the arbitrary and contingent plaj' of the imagination, alwaj's shares in it more than the intimate necessity of the reallj- beautiful allows ; it is because the best sculpture touches on severe science by what is determinate in its conception. However, these particular aflSnities are lost in proportion as the works of these three kinds of art rise to a greater eleva- tion, and it is a natural aaid necessary consequence of their perfection, that, without confounding their objective limits, the different arts come to resemble each other more and more, in the action which they exercise on the mind. At its highest degree of ennobling, music ought to become a form, and act on us with the calm power of an antique statue ; in its most elevated perfection, the plastic art ought to become music and move us by the immediate action exercised on the mind bj' the senses ; in its most complete development, poetry ought both to stir us pow- erfully like music and like plastic art to surround us with a peaceful light. In each art, the perfect style consists exactlj' in knowing how to remove specific limits, while sacrificing at the same time the particular advantages of the art, and to give it by a wise use of what belongs to it specially a more general character. Nor is it only the limits inherent in the specific charac- ter of each kind of art that the artist ought to over step in putting his hand to the work ; he must also triumph over those which are inherent in the particular subject of which he treats. In a really beautiful work of art, the substance ought to be inoperative, the form should ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 99 do everything ; for by the form the whole man is acted on ; the substance acts on nothing but isolated forces. Thus, however vast and sublime it may be, the substance always exercises a restrictive action on the mind, and true festhetic liberty can only be expected from the form. Consequently the true search of the matter consists in destroying matter by the form ; and the triumph of art is great in proportion as it overcomes matter and maintains Its sway over those who enjoy its work. It is great par- ticularly in destroying matter when most imposing, ambi- tious, and attractive, when therefore matter has most power to produce the effect proper to it, or, again, when it leads those wlio consider it more closelj' to enter directly into relation with it. The mind of the spectator and of the hearer must remain perfecth' free and intact ; it must issue pure and entire from the magic circle of the artist, as from the hands of the Creator. The most frivolous subject ought to be treated in such a way that we preserve the faculty to exchange it immediately for the most serious work. The arts which have passion for their object, as a tragedy for example, do not present a difficult}' here ; for, in the first place, these arts are not entirel}' free, because they are in the service of a particular end (the pathetic), and then no connoisseur will deny that even in this class a work is perfect in proportion as amidst the most violent storms of passion it respects the liberty of the soul. There is a fine art of passion, but an impassioned fine art is a contradiction ii:^ terms, for the infallible effect of the beautiful is emancipation from the passions. The idea of an instructive fine art (didactic art) or improving (moral) art is no less contradictor}', for nothing agrees less with the idea of the beautiful than to give a determinate tend- ency to the mind. However, from the fact that a work produces effects only by its substance, it must not always be inferred that there is a want of form in this work ; this conclusion may quite as well testify to a want of form in the observer. If his mind is too stretched or too relaxed, if it is only accustomed to receive things either by the senses or the inteUigence, even in the most perfect combination, it will only stop to look at the parts, and it will only see 100 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. matter in the most beautiful form. Only sensible of the i;oarse elements^ he must first destro.y the sesthetic organi- zation of a work to find enjoyment in it, and carefuUj- disinter the details which genius has «aused to vanish, with infinite art, in the harmony- of tlie wliole. The interest he takes in the work is either solelj' moral or exclusivelj' physical ; the onl^* tiling wanting to it is to be exactly what it ought to be — ggsthetical. The readers of tlus class enjoj- a serious and pathetic poem as thej- do a sermon : a simple and playful work, as an inebriating draught; and if on the one hand they have so little taste as to demand edification from a traged}' or from an epos, even such as the " Messias, " on the otiicr hand they will be infallibly scandalized by a piece after the fashion of Anac- reon and Catullus. Letter XXIII. I TAKE up the thread of my researches, which I broke off' only to apply the principles I laid down to practical art and the appreciation of its works. The transition from the passivity of sensuousness to the activity of thought and of will can be effected only by the intermediary state of aesthetic liberty ; and though in itself this state decides nothing respecting our opinions and our sentiments, and therefore it leaves our intellectual and moral value entirely problematical, it is, however, the necessary condition without which we should never attain to an opinion or a sentiment. In a word, there is no other wa}' to make a reasonable being out of a sensuous man than bj- making him first sesthetic. But, you might object : Is this mediation absolutely indis- pensable? Could not truth and duty, one or the other, in themselves and b^' themselves, find access to the sen- suous man ? To this I reply : Not only is it possible but it is absolutely necessarj' that they owe solel}' to themselves their determining force, and nothing would be more contradictory to our preceding affirmations than to appear to defend the contrary opinion. It has been expressly proved that the beautiful furnishes no result, either for the ^STHETICAL LETTERS ANP EPSAYS. 101 comprehension or for the will ; that it mingles with no operations, either of thought or of resolution ; and that it confers this double power without determining anything with regard to the real exercise of this power. Here all ' foreign help disappears, and the pure logical form, the idea, would speak immediately to the intelligence, as the pure moral form, the law, immediately to the will. But that the pure form should be capable of it, and that there is in general a pure form for sensuous man, is that, I maintain, which should be rendered possible by the aesthetic disposition of the soul. Truth is not a thing which can be received from without like reality or the visible existence of objects. It is the thinking force, in his own liberty and activity, which produces it, and it is just this liberty proper to it, this lihertj- which we seek in vain in sensuous man. The sensuous man is alreadj- ] determined physically, and thenceforth he has uo longer I his free determinability ; he must necessarily first enter j into possession of this lost determinability before he can j exchange the passive against an active determination. J Therefore, in order to recover it, he must either lose the passive determination that he had, or he should enclose alreadj' in himself the active determination to which he should pass. If he confined himself to lose passive deter- mination, he would at the same time lose with it the possi- bility of an active determination, because thought needs a body, and form can only be realized through matter. He must therefore contain already in himself the active de-, termination, that he may be at once both activelj' and passively determined, that is to saj-, he becomes necessarily .esthetic. Consequent!}', b}- the aesthetic disposition of the soul the proper activity of reason is already revealed in the sphere of sensuousness, the power of sense is already broken within its own boundaries, and the ennobling of physical man carried far enough, for spiritual man has onlj- to develop himself according to the laws of liberty. The • transition from an esthetic state to a logical and moral state (from the beautiful to truth and dutj) is then infl- nitelj-more easj- than the transition from the physical state 102 ^STHETIOAIi LETTERS AND ESSAYS. to the Eesthetic state (from life pure and blind to form). This transition man can effectuate alone by his liberty, whilst he has only to enter into possession of himself not to give it himself; but to separate the elements of his nature, and not to enlarge it. Having attained to the aesthetic disposition, man will give to his judgments and to his actions a universal value as soon as he desires it. This passage from brute nature to beauty, in which an entirely new faculty would awalien in him, nature would render easier, and his will has no power over a disposition which, we know, itself gives birth to the will. To bring the aesthetic man to profound views, to elevated sentiments, he requires nothing more than important occasions : to obtain the same thing from the sensuous man, his nature must at first be changed. To make of the former a hero, a sage, it is often only necessary to meet with a sublime situation, which exercises upon the faculty of the will the more immediate action ; for the second, it must first be transplanted under another sky. One of the most important tasks of culture, then, is to submit man to form, even in a purely physical life, and to lender it aesthetic as far as the domain of the beautiful can be extended, for it is alone in the aesthetic state, arid not in the physical state, that the moral state can be developed. If in each particular case man ought to pos- sess the power to make his judgment and his will the judgment of the entire species ; if he ought to find in each limited existence the transition to an infinite existence ; if, lastlj-, he ought from everj' dependent situation to take his night to rise to autonomy and to libertj', it must be ob- served that at no moment he is only individual and solely obe3's the laws of nature. To be apt and read^' to raise ' himself from the narrow circle of the ends of nature, to rational ends, in the sphere of the former he must already have exercised himself in the second ; he must already have realized his physical destinj' with a certain liberty that belongs onl}' to spiritual nature, that is to say accord- ing to the laws of the beautiful. And that he can effect without thwarting in the least degree his physical aim. The exigencies of nature with regard to Mm turn only upon what he does — upon the ^STHETICAIi LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 103 substance of his acts ; but the ends of nature in no degree determine the way in which he acts, the form of his actions. On the contrar}', the exigencies of reason have rigorously the form of his activity for its object. Thus, so much as it is neeessarj' for tiie moral destination of man, that he be purely moral, that he shows an absolute personal activity, so much is he indiflferent that his physical destination be entirely physical, that he acts in a manner entirely passive. Henceforth with regard to this last destination, it entirely depends on him to fulfil it solely as a sensuous being and natural force (as a force which acts onlj- as it diminishes) or, at the same time, as absolute force, as a rational being. To which of these does his dignit_y best respond? Of this there can be no question. It is as disgraceful and contemptible for him to do under sensuous impulsion that which he ought to have determined merely by the motive of duty, as it is noble and honorable for him to incline towards conformity with laws, harmony, independence ; there even where the vulgar man only satisfies a legitimate want. In a word, in the domain of truth and morality, sensuousness must have nothing to determine ; but in the sphere of happi- ness, form maj' find a place, and the instinct of pla3' prevail. Thus then, in the indifferent sphere of physical life, man ought to already commence his moral life ; his own proper activity ought already to make way in passivity, and his rational libeiity beyond the limits of sense ; he ought already to impose the law of his will upon his inclinations; he ought — if j'ou will permit me the ex- pression — to carry into the domain of matter the war against matter, in order to be dispensed from combatting this redoubtable enemy upon the sacred field of liberty ; he ought to learn to have nobler desires, not to be forced to have sublime volitions. This is the fruit of sesthetic i culture, which submits to the laws of the beautiful, in ' which neither the laws of nature nor those of reason suffer, which does not force the will of man, and which by the form it gives to exterior life already opens internal life. 104 iESTHKTICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. Letter XXIV. Accordingly three different moments or stages of devel- opment can be distinguished, which the individual man, as well as the whole race, must of necessity traverse in a determinate order if thej- are to fulfil the circle of their determination. No doubt, the separate periods can be lengthened or shortened, through accidental causes which are inherent either in the influence of external things or under the free caprice of men : but neither of them can be overstepped, and the order of their sequence cannot be inverted either b}- nature or by the will. Man, in his [physical condition, suffers only the power of nature ; he gets rid of this power in the sesthetical condition, and he Irules them in the moral state. What is man before beauty liberates him from free r pleasure, and the serenitj' of form tames down the savage- , ness of life? Eternallj- uniform in his aims, eternally changing in his judgments, self-seeking without being ' ! himself, unfettered without being free, a slave without serving any rule. At this period, the world is to him only l^destinjr, not yet an object ; all has existence for him only in as far as it procures existence to him ; a thing that 1 neither seeks from nor gives to him is non-existent. \ Everj' phenomenon stands out before iiim separate and cut off, as he finds himself in the series of beings. All that is, is to him through the bias of the moment ; every change is to him au entirely' fresh creation, because with the necessarj- iM, him, the necessary out of him is wanting, which binds together all the changing forms in the universe, and wliich holds fast the law on the theatre of his action, wliile the individual departs. It is in vain that nature lets the rich variety of her forms pass before him ; he sees in her glorious fulness nothing but his 'prey, in her power and greatness nothing but his enem}'. Pvitber he encounters objects, and wishes to draw them to himself in desire, or the objects press in a destructive manner upon him, and he thrusts them away in dismay and terror. In both cases his relation to the world of ^.STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 105 senseis immediate contact; and perpeluallj- anxious through its pressure, restless and plagued bj- imperious wants, he nowhere finds rest except in enervation, and nowhere limits save in exhausted desire. "True, his is the powerful breast, and the mighty hand «f the Titans. . . . A certain inheritance ; yet the god welded Round his forehead a brazen band ; Advice, moderation, wisdom, and patience,— Hid it from his shy, sinister look. Every desire is with him a rag-e. And his rage prowls around limitless." — Iphigenia in Tauris. Ignorant of his own human dignitj', he is far removed from honoring it in others, and conscious of his own savage greed, he fears it in eveiy creature that he sees like himself. He never sees others in himself, onlj' himself in others, and human societ}', instead of enlarging him to the race, only shuts him up continually closer in his indi- viduality. Thus limited, he wanders through liis sunless life, till favoring nature rolls away the load of Katter from his darliened senses, reflection separates him from things, and objects show themselves at length in the afterglow of the consciousness. It is true we cannot point out this state__of rude iiature as we have here portrayed it in any definite people and age. It is only an idea, but an idea with which experience agrees most closely in special features. It maj- be said that man was never injhis animal condition, but he has not, on the other hand, ever entirely escaped from it. Even in the rudest subjects, unmistakable traces of ra- tional freedom can be found, and even in the most culti- vated, features are not wanting that remind us of that dismal natural condition. It is possible for man, at one and the same time, to unite the highest and the lowest in his nature ; and if his dignity depends on a strict separa- tion of one from the other, his happiness depends on a skilful removal of this separation. The culture which is to bring his dignity into agreement with his happiness will therefore have to provide for the greatest purltj- of these two principles in their most intimate combi- nation. 106 JESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. Consequently the first appearance of reason in man is not the beginning of humanity. This is first decided by his freedom, and reason begins first by making his sen- suous dependence boundless ; a phenomenon that does not appear to me to have been sufficiently elucidated, consid- ering its importance and universality. We know that the reason makes itself known to man by the demand for the absolute — the self-dependent and necessary. But as this want of the reason cannot be satisfied in any separate or single state of his physical life, he is obliged to leave the physical entirely and to rise from a limited reality to ideas. But although the true meaning of that demand of the reason is to withdraw him from the limits of time and to lead him from the world of sense to an ideal world, yet this same demand of reason, b\- misapplication — scarcely to be avoided in this life, prone to sensuousness — can direct him to physical life, and, instead of making man free, plunge him in the most terrible slavery. Facts verify this supposition. Man raised on the wings of imagination leaves the narrow limits of the present, in which mere animality is enclosed, in order to strive on to an unlimited future. But while the limitless is unfolded to his dazed imagination, his heart has not ceased to live in the separate, and to serve the moment. The impulse towards the absolute seizes him suddenly in the midst of his animalit}', and as in this cloddish condition all his ef- forts aim only at the material and temporal, and are lim- ited by his individuality, he is only led by that demand of the reason to extend his individualitj- into the infinite, in- stead of to abstract from it. He will be led to seek in- stead of form an inexhaustible matter, instead of the un- changeable an everlasting change and an absolute securing of his temporal existence. The same impulse which, di- rected to his thought and action, ought to lead to truth and morality, now directed to his passion and emotional state, produces nothing but an unlimited desire and an ab- solute want. The first fruits, therefore, ^that he reaps in the world of spirits are cares and fear — both operations of the reason ; not of sensuousness, but of a reason that mistakes its object and applies its categorical imperative to matter. All unconditional systems of happiness ai'e iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 107 fruits of this tree, whether they have for their object the present daj' or the whole of life, or what does not make them any more respectable, the whole of eternitj-, for their object. An unlimited duration of existence and of well- being is only an ideal of the desires ; hence a demand which can only be put forth b}' an animality striving up to the absolute. Man, therefore, without gaining anything for his humanity by a rational expression of this sort, loses the happy limitation of the animal, over which he now only possesses the unenviable superiority of losing the present for an endeavor after what is remote, yet without seeking in the limitless future anything but the present. But even if the reason does not go astray in its object, or err in the question, sensuousness will continue to falsify tlie answer for a long time. As soon as man has begun to use his understanding and to knit together phenomena in cause and effect, the reason, according to its conception, presses on to an absolute knitting together and to an un- conditional basis. In order, vaerely, to be able to put for- ward this demand, man must already have stepped be3-ond the sensuous, but the sensuous uses this very demand to bring back the fugitive. In fact, it is now that he ought to abandon entirely the world of sense in order to take his flight into the realm of ideas ; for the intelligence remains eternallj- shut up in the finite and in the contingent, and does not cease putting questions witliout reachWig the last link of the chain. But as the man with whom we are engaged is not yet capable of such an abstraction, and does not find it in the sphere of sensuous knowledge, and because he does not look for it in pure reason, he will seek for it below in the region of sentiment, and will appear to And it. No doubt the sen- suous shows him nothing that has its foundation in itself, and that legislates for itself, but it shows him something that does not care for foundation or law ; therefore, thus not being able to quiet the intelligence by showing it a final cause, he reduces it to silence by the conception which de- sires no cause ; and being incapable of understanding the sublime necessity of reason, he keeps to the blind con- straint of matter. As sensuousness knows no other end 108 ^STHKTICAL LKTTEHS ANO ESSAYS. than its interest, and is determined by nothing except blind chance, it maltes the former the motive of its actions, and the latter the master of the world. Even the divine part in man, the moral law, in its first manifestation in the sensuous cannot avoid this perversion. As this moral law is only prohibited, and combats in- man the interest of sensuous egotism, it must appear to him as something strange until he has come to consider this self- love as the stranger, and the voice of reason as his true self. Therefore he confines himself to feeling the fetters which the latter imposes on him, without having the con- sciousness of the infinite emancipation which it procures for him. Without suspecting in himself the dignitj- of lawgiver, he onlj' experiences the constraint and the im- potent revolt of a subject fretting under the yoke, because in this experience the sensuous impulsion precedes the moral impulsion, he gives to the law of necessity a begin- ning in him, a positive origin, and b}' the most unfortunate of all mistakes he converts the immutable and the eternal in himself into a transitorj- accident. He makes up his mind to consider the notions of the just and the unjust as statutes which have been introduced by a will, and not as having in themselves an eternal value. Just as in the explanation of certain natural phenomena he goes bej"ond nature and seeks out of her what can only be found in her, in her own laws ; so also in the explanation of moral phenomena he goes beyond reason and makes light of his humanity, seeking a god in tiiis wny. It is not wonderful that a religion which he has purchased at the cost of his humanit}- shows itself worth}* of this origin, and that he only considers as absolute and eternally binding laws that have never been binding from all eternity. He has placed himself in relation with, not a holy being, but a powerful. Therefore the spirit of his religion, of the liomage that he gives to God, is a fear that abases him, and not a veneration that elevates him in his own esteem. Though these different aberrations hj which man de- parts from the ideal of his destination cannot all take place at the same time, because several degrees have to be passed over in the transition from the obscure of thought to error, and from the obscure of will to the corruption of ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 109 the will ; these degrees are all, without exception, the consequence of his physical state, because in all the vital impulsion sways the formal impulsion. Now, two cases maj- happen : either reason may not yet have spoken in man, and the physical maj^ reign over him with a blind necessity, or reason may not be sufficiently purified from sensuous impressions, and the moral ma}- still be subject to the plysical ; in both cases the onlj* principle that has a real power over him is a material principle, and man, at least as regards his ultimate tendency, is a sensuous being. The only difference is, that in tlie former ease he is an animal without reason, and in the second case a rational animal. But he ought to be neither one nor the other : he ought to be a man. Nature ought not to rule him exclu- sively ; nor reason conditionally. The two legislations ought to be completelj' independent, aud yet mutually complementary. Letter XXV. Whilst man, in his first phj-sical condition, is only pas- sively affected b}- the world of sense, he is still entirely identified with it ; and for this reason the external world, as yet, has no objective existence for him. When he begins in liis aesthetic state of mind to regard the irorld object- ively, then onl}' is his personalitj' severed from it, and the world appears to him aif objective reality, for the simple reason that he has ceased to form an identical portion of it. That which first connects man with the surrounding universe is the power of reflective contemplation. "Whereas desire seizes at once its object, reflection removes it to a distance and renders it inalienably her own by saving it from the greed of passion. The necessity of sense which he obeyed during the period of mere sensations, lessens during the period of reflection ; the senses are for the time in abeyance ; even ever-fleeting time stands still whilst the scattered raj's of consciousness are gathering and shape themselves ; an image of the infinite is reflected upon the perishable ground. As soon as light dawns in man, there is no longer night outside of hiin ; as soon as there is 110 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. peace within him the storm lulls throughout the universe, and the contending forces of nature find rest within pre- scribed limits. Hence we cannot wonder if ancient tradi- tions allude to these great changes in the inner man as to a revolution in surrounding nature, and symbolize thought triumphing over the laws of time, by the figure of Zeus, which terminates the reign of Saturn. As long as man derives sensations from a contact with nature, he is her slave ; but as soon as he begins to reflect upon her objects and laws he becomes her lawgiver. Nature, which previously ruled him as a power, now ex- pands before him as an object. What is objective to him can have no power over him, for in order to become ob- jective it has to experience his own power. As far and as long as he impresses a form upon matter, he cannot be injured by its effect ; for a spirit can only be in- jured by that which deprives it of its freedom. Whereas he proves his own freedom bj- giving a form to the form- less ; where the mass rules heavily and without shape, and its undefined outlines are for ever fluctuating between uncertain boundaries, fear takes up its abode ; but man rises above any natural terror as soon as he knows how to mould it, and transform it into an object of his art. As soon as he upholds his independence towards phenomenal natures he maintains his dignity toward her as a thing of power, and with a noble freedom he rises against his gods. They throw aside the mask with which they had kept him in awe during his infancy, and to his surprise his mind perceives the reflection of his own image. The divine monster of the Oriental, which roams about chan -,ing the world with the blind force of a beast of prey, dwindles to the charming outline of humanitj' in Greek fable ; the empire of the Titans is crushed, and boundless force is tamed by infinite form. But whilst I have been merely searching for an issue from the material world, and a passage into the world of mind, the bold flight of my imagination has already taken me into the very midst of the latter world. The beauty of which we are in search we have left behind by passing from tlie life of mere sensations to the pure form and to the pure object. Such a leap exceeds the condition of ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. Ill human nature ; in order to keep pace with the latter we must return to the world of sense. Beauty is indeed the sphere of unfettered contemplation and reflection ; beauty conducts us into the world of ideas, without however taking us from the world of sense, as occurs when a truth is perceived and acknowleged. This is the pure product of a process of abstraction from everything material and accidental, a pure object free from every subjective barrier, a pure state of self-activitj- without any admixture of passive sensations. There is indeed a way back to sensation from the highest abstrac- tion ; for thought teaches the inner sensation, and the idea of logical or moral unity passes into a sensation of sensual accord. But if we delight in knowledge we sepa- rate very accuratelj' our own conceptions from our sensa- tions ; we look upon the latter as something accidental, which might have been omitted without the knowledge being impaired thereby, without truth being less true. It would, however, be a vain attempt to suppress this con- nection of the facultj- of feeling with the idea of beauty, consequently, we shall not succeed in representing to our- selves one as the effect of the other, but we must look upon them both together and reciprocal!}^ as cause and effect. In the pleasure which we derive from knowledge we readilj' distinguish the passage from the active to the passive state, and we clearly perceive that the first ends when the second begins. On the contrar}-, from the pleasure which we take in beaut^, this transition from the active to the passive is not perceivable, and reflection is so intimately blended with feeling that we believe we feel the form immediatelj'. Beautj' is tlien an object to us, it is true, because reflection is the condition of the feeling which we have of it ; but it is also a state of our person- ahty (our Ego) because the feeling is the condition of the idea we conceive of it : beauty is therefore doubtless form, because we contemplate it, but it is equally life because we feel it. In a word, it is at once our state and our act. And precisely because it is at the same time both a state and an act, it triumphantlj' proves to us that the passive does not exclude the active, neither matter nor form, neither the finite nor the infinite ; and that consequently the 112 jESthetioal letters and essays. phj-sclcal dependence to which man is necessarilj' devoted does not in an}' waj' destroj' his moral liberty. This is the proof of beauty, and I ought to add that this alone can prove it. In fact, as in the possession of truth or of logical unity, feeling is not necessarily one with the thought, but follows it accidentally ; it is a fact which only proves that a sensitive nature can succeed a rational nature, and vice versa; not that thoj- co-exist, that they exercise a reciprocal action one over the other ; and, lastly, that the}' ought to be united in an absolute and necessary manner. From this exclusion of feeling as long as there is thought, and of thought so long as there is feeling, we should on the contrary conclude that the two natures are incom- patible, so that in order to demonstrate that pure reason is to be realized in humanitj-, the best proof given hy the analysis is that this realization is demanded. But, as in the realization of beautj' or of a'sthetic unit}-, there is a real union, mutual substitution of matter and of form, of passive and of active, b}^ this alone is proved the com- patibilitj^ of the two natures, the possible realization of the infinite in the finite, and consequently also the possi- bility of the most sublime humanity. Henceforth we need no longer be embarrassed to find a transition from dependent feeling to moral libertj', because beauty reveals to us the fact that they can perfeotl}- co- exist, and that to show himself a spirit, man need not escape from matter. But if on one side he is free, even in his relation witli a visible world, as the fact of beauty teaches, and if on the other side freedom is something absolute and supersensuous, as its idea necessarily implies, the question is no longer how man succeeds in raising himself from the finite to the absolute, and opposing him- self in his thought and will to sensualit}', as this has alread}' been produced in the fact of beautj'. In a word, we have no longer to ask how he passes from virtue to truth wliich is already included in the former, but how he opens a way for himself from vulgar realitj- to aesthetic reality, and from the ordinary feelings of. life to the per- ception of the beautiful. ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 113 Letter XXVI. I HAVE shown in the previous letters that it is only the r aesthetic disposition of the soul that gives birth to libert}-, |j it cannot therefore be derived from liberty nor have a " moral origin. It must be a gift of nature ; the favor of chance alone can break the bonds of the physical state and bring the savage to dutj'. The germ of the beautiful will find an equal difficulty in developing itself in countries where a severe nature forbids man to enjoy himself, and in those where a prodigal nature dispenses him from all effort ; where the blunted senses experience no want, and where violent desire can never be satisfied. The delight- ful flower of the beautiful will never unfold itself in the case of the Troglodj'te hid in his cavern always alone, and never finding humanity outside himself; nor among nomads, who, travelling in great troops, onlj' consist of a multitude, and have no individual humanity. It will i only flourish in places where man converses peacefully : with himself in his cottage, and with the whole race when ; he issues from it. In those climates where a limpid ether opens the senses to the lightest impression, whilst a life- giving warmth develops a luxuriant nature, where even in the inanimate creation the sway of inert matter is over- thrown, and the victorious form ennobles even the most abject natures ; in this»joyful state and fortunate zone, where activity alone leads to enjoj^ment, and enjo3'ment to activitj', from life itself issues a holy harmony, and the laws of order develop life, a different result takes place. When imagination incessantlj- escapes from reality, and does not abandon the simplicitj' of nature in its wander- ings : then and there only the mind and the senses, the receptive force and the plastic force, are developed in that happy equilibrium which is the soul of the beautiful and the condition of humanity. What phenomenon accompanies the initiation of the savage into humanity ? However far we look back into history the phenomenon is identical among all people who have shaken off the slaverj'' of the animal state : the love of appearance, the inclination for dress and for games. 114 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. Extreme stupidity and extreme intelligence have a certain affinit}- in only seeking the real and being com- pletely insensible to mere appearance. The former is onl}- drawn forth by the immediate presence of an object in the senses, and the second is reduced to a quiescent state only by referring conceptions to the facts of experience. In short, stupidity cannot rise above realit}-, nor the intelli- gence descend below truth. Thus, in as far as the want of reality and attachment to the real are only the conse- quence of a want and a defect, indifterence to the real and an interest talien in appearances are a real enlargement of humanity and a decisive step towards culture. In the first place it is the proof of an exterior liberty, for as long as necessity commands and want solicits, the fancy is strictly chained down to the real : it is onlj' when want is satisfied that it develops without hinderance. But it is also the proof of an internal liberty, because it reveals to us a force which, independent of an external substratum, sets itself in motion, and has sufficient energy to remove from itself the solicitations of nature. The realit}' of , things is effected by things, the appearance of things is { I the work of man, and a soul that takes pleasure in ap- ' ' pearance does not take pleasure in what it receives but in what it makes. It is self-evident that I am speaking of aesthetical evi- dence different from reality and truth, and not of logical appearance identical with them. Therefore if it is liked it is because it is an appearance, and not because it is held to be something better than it is : the first principle alone is a play, whilst the second is a deception. To give a value to the appearance of the first kind can never injure truth, because it is never to be feared that it will supplant it — the only wa}^ in which truth can be injured. To despise this appearance is to despise in general all the fine arts of which it is the essence. Nevertheless, it happens sometimes that the understanding carries its zeal for reality as far as this intolerance, and strikes with a sentence of ostracism all the arts relating to beautj- in appearance, because it is only an appearance. However, the intelli- gence only sliows this vigorous spirit when it calls to mind the atflnity pointed out further back. I shall find some iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 115 day the occasion to treat specially of the limits of beautj- in its appearance. It is nature herself which raises man from reality to appearance by endowing him with two senses which only lead him to the knowledge of the real through appearance. In the eye and the ear the organs of the senses are alreadj^ freed from the persecutions of nature, and the object with which we are immediately in contact through the animal senses is remoter from us. What we see b3- the eye differs from what we feel ; for the understanding to reach objects overleaps the light which separates us from them. In truth, we are passive to an object : in sight and hearing the object is a form we create. While still a savage, man onl}' enjoys through touch merely aided by sight and sound. He eitlier does not rise to perception through sight, or does not rest there As soon as he begins to enjoj' through^ sight, vision has an independent value, he is aesthetically , free, and the instinct of play is developed. i Tlie instinct of plaj- lil?es appearance, and directly it is j awakened it is followed b^- the formal imitative instinct which treats appearance as an independent thing. Directly ' man has come to distinguish the appearance from the reality, the form from the body, he can separate, in fact he lias ah-eady done so. Thus the faculty of the art of imi- tation is given with the faculty of form in general. The inclination that draws us to it reposes on another tendency I have not to notice%ere. The exact period when the aesthetic instinct, or that of art, develops, depends entirely on the attraction that mere appearance has for men. As every real existence proceeds from nature as a foreign power, whilst every appearance comes in the first place from man as a percipient subject, he only uses his absolute sight in separating semblance from essence, and arranging according to subjective law. With an unbridled liberty he can unite what nature has severed, provided he can imagine his union, and he can separate what nature has united, provided this separation can take place in his intelligence. Here nothing can be sacred to him but his own law : the only condition imposed upon him is to respect the border which separates his own sphere from the existence of things or from the realm of nature. 116 ESTHETIC AL LETTERS AND ESSAYS, This human right of ruling is exercised by man -in the art of appearance ; and his success in extending the em- pire of the beautiful, and guarding the frontiers of truth, will be in proportion with the strictness with which he sep- arates form from substance : for if he frees appearance from reality-, he must also do the converse. But man possesses sovereign power only in the world of appearance, in the unsubstantial realm of imagination, only by abstaining from giving being to appearance in theory, and by giving it being in practice. It follows that the poet transgresses his proper limits when he attributes being to his ideal, and when he gives this ideal aim as a determined existence. For he can only reach this result by exceeding his right as a poet, that of encroaching by the ideal on the field of experience, and by pretending to determine real existence in virtue of a simple possibility, or else he renounces his right as. a poet b}' letting experi- ence encroach on the sphere of the ideal, and by restrict- ing possibility to the conditions of realit}'. It is only b3' being frank or disclaiming all reality, and by being independent or doing without reality, that the appearance is sesthetical. Directlj' it apes reality or needs reality for eflfect, it is nothing more than a vile instrument for material ends, and can prove nothing for the freedom of the mind. Moreover, the object in which we find beauty need not be unreal if our judgment disregards this reality' ; for if it regards this the judgment is no longer sesthetical. A beautiful woman, if living, would no doubt please us as much and rather more than an equallj^ beauti- ful woman seen in painting ; but what makes the former please men is not her being an independent appearance ; she no longer pleases the pure aesthetic feeling. In the painting, life must only attract as an appearance, and reality as an idea. But it is certain that to feel in a living object only the pure appearance requires a greatly highei aesthetic culture than to do without life in the appearance. When the frank and independent appearance is found in man separately, or in a whole people, it may be inferred they have mind, taste, and all prerogatives connected with them. In this case the ideal will be seen to govern real life, honor triumphing over fortune, thought over enjoy- ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 117 ment, the dream of immortality over a transitory exist- ence. In this case public opinion will no longer be feared, and an olive crown will be more valued than a purple mantle. Impotence and perversity alone have recourse to false and paltry semblance, and individuals as well as I nations who lend to reality the support of appearance, or to the sestlietic appearance the support of reality, show I their moral unworthiness and their sesthetical impotence.! Therefore, a short and conclusive answer can be given to this question — how far will appearance be permitted in the moral world ? It will run thus in proportion as this appearance will be aesthetical, that is, an appearance that does not try to make up for reality, nor requires to be made up for by it. The sesthetical appearance can never en- , danger the truth of morals : wherever it seems to do so the appearance is not sesthetical. Only a stranger to the j fashionable world can take the polite assurances, which are only a form, for proofs of affection, and say he has been deceived ; but only a clumsy fellow in good society calls ill the aid of duplicity and flatters to become amiable. The former lacks the pure sense for independent appear- ance ; therefore he can only give a value to iip[)earance bj' truth. The second lacks reality, and wishes to replace it by appearance. Nothing is more common than to hear depredators of the times utter these paltry complaints — that all solidity has disappeared from the world, and that essence is neglected Tor semblance. Tiiough I feel by no means called upon to defend this age against these re- proaches, I must say that the wide application of these criticisms shows that the}' attach blame to the age, not only on the score of the false, but also of the frank ap- pearance. And even the exceptions thej- admit in favor of the beautiful have for their object less the independent appearance than the need}' appearance. Not onl}' do they attack the artificial coloring that hides truth and replaces reality, but also the beneficent appearance that fills a vacuum and clothes poverty ; and they even attack the ideal appearance that ennobles a vulgar reality. Their strict sense of truth is rightly offended by the falsity of manners ; unfortunately, they class politeness in this cate- 118 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. gory. It displeases them that the noisy and showy so often eclipse true merit, but they are no less shocked, that appearance is also demanded from merit, and that ii real substance does not dispense with an agreeable form. They regret the cordiality, the energy, and soliditj' of ancient times ; they would restore with them ancient coarseness, heaviness, and the old Gothic profusion. By judgments of this kind they show an esteem fo]' the matter itself un- worthy of humanitj-, which ought only to value the matter inasmuch as it can receive a form and enlarge the empire of ideas. Accordingly, the taste of the age need not much fear these criticisms if it can clear itself before better judges. Our defect is not to grant a value to aes- thetic appeaiance (we do not do this enough): a .severe judge of the beautiful might rather reproach us with not iiaving arrived at pure appearance, with not having sepa- rated clearly enovigh existence from the phenomenon, and thus established their limits. W-e shall deserve this re- proach so long as we cannot enjoy the beautiful in living nature witliout desiring it ; as long as we cannot admire the beautiful in the imitative arts without having an end in view ; as long as we do not grant to imagination an abso- lute legislation of its own ; and as long as we do not in- spire it with care for its dignitj- by the esteem we testify for its works. Letter XXVII. Do not fear for reality and truth. Even if the elevated idea of aesthetic appearance become general, it would not become so, as long as man remains so little cultivated as to abuse it ; and if it became general, this would result from a culture that would prevent all abuse of it. The pursuit of independent appearance, requires more power of abstraction, freedom of heart, and energy of will than man requires to shut himself up in realitj- ; and he must have left the latter behind him if he wishes to attain to aesthetic appearance. Therefore, a man would calculate very badly who took the road of the ideal to save himself that of reality. Thus realitj' would not have much to fear ^STHETICAL LETTERS AXD ESSAYS. 119 I'loni appearance, as we understand it ; but, on the other hand,, appearance would have more to fear from reality. Chained to matter, man uses appearance for his purposes before he allows it a proper personalitj' in the art of the ideal : to come to that point a complete revolution must take place in his mode of feeling, otherwise he would not be even on the way to the ideal. Consequentl}', when we find in man the signs of a pure and disinterested esteem, we can infer that this revolution has taken place in his nature, and that huraanitj' has realk begun in him. Signs of this kind are found even in the first and rude attempts that he makes to embellish his existence, even at the risk of making it worse in its material conditions. As soon as he begins to prefer form to substance and to risk realitj' for appeai'ance (known by him to be such) , the barriers of animal life fall, and he finds himself on a track that has no end. Not satisfied with the -needs of nature, he demands the superfluous. First, only the superfluous of matter, to se- cure bis enjoyment beyond the present necessity ; but af- terwards he wishes a superabundance in matter, an ajsthet- ical supplement to satisfy the impulse for the formal, to extend enjo^-ment bej'ond necessity. By piling up provis- ions simply for a future use, and anticipating their enjoy- ment in the imagination, he outsteps the limits of the present moment, but not those of time in general. He en- joj's more ; he does not enjoy differently. But as soon as he makes form enter fhto his enjoyment, and he keeps in view the forms of the objects which satisfj^ his desires, he has not only increased his pleasure in extent and intensitj-, but he has also ennobled it in mode and species. No doubt nature has given more than is necessarj- to unreasoning beings ; she has caused_^a gleam of freedom to shine even in the darkness of animal life. When the lion is not tormented by hunger, and when no wild beast challenges him to fight, his unemployed energy creates an object for himself; full of ardor, he fills the re-echoing desert with his terrible roars, and his exuberant force rejoices in itself, showing itself without an object. The insect flits about rejoicing in life in the sunlight, and it is certainly not the cry of want that makes itself heard in the 120 .KSTIIETICAL LKTTKRS AND ESSAYS. melodious song of the bird ; there is undeniabl.y freedom \n these movements, though it is not emancipation from want in general, but from a determinate external necessitj-. The animal works, when a privation is the motor of its activity , and it plays when the plenitude of force is this motor, when an exuberant life is excited to action. Even in inanimate nature a luxury of strength and a latitude of determination are shown, which in this material sense might be styled plaj'. ' The tree produces numberless germs that are abortive without developing, and it sends forth more roots, branches, and leaves, organs of nutrition, than are used 'for the preservation of the species. Whatever this tree restores to the elements of its exuberant life, without using it or enjoying it, maj' be expended by life in free and joyful movements. It is thus that nature ofl'ers in her material sphere a sort of prelude to the limitless, and that even there she suppresses partiallj' the chains from which she will be completely emancipated in the realm of form. The constraint of superabundance or physical play answers as a transition from the constraint of necessity, or oi physical seriousness, to sesthetical plaj' ; and before shaking off, in the supreme freedom of the beautiful, the j'oke of any special aim, nature alreadj' ap- proaches, at least remotely, this independence, by the/ree movement which is itself its own end and means. The imagination, like the bodilj' organs, has in man its free movement and its material play, a play in which, without any reference to form, it simply takes pleasure in its arbitrary power and in the absence of all hinderance. These plays of fancy, inasmuch as form is not mixed up with them, and because a free succession of images makes all their charm, though confined to man, belong exclu- sively to animal life, and only prove one thing — that he is delivered from all external sensuous constraint — without our being entitled to infer that there is in it an independent plastic force. From this play of free associiifion of ideas, which is still quite material in nature and is explained hj simple natural laws, the imagination, by making the attempt of creating a free form, passes at length at a jump to the {esthetic plaj' ■ I say at one leap, for quite a new force ^;is;iHKTICAI. LKTTEKS AND ESSAYS. 121 enters into action liere ; for here, for the first time, the legislative mind is mixed with the acts of a blind instinct, subjects the arbitrary march of the imagination to its eternal and immutable unitj-, causes its independent permanence to enter in that which is transitory, and its infinity in the sensuous. Nevertheless, as long as rude nature, which knows of no other law than running inces- santlj' from change to change, will yet retain too much strength, it will oppose itself bj' its difl'erent caprices to this necessity ; by its agitation to this permanence ; by its manifold needs to this independence, and hj its insatia- bility to this sublime simplicity. It will be also trouble- some to recognize the instinct of play in its first trials, seeing that the sensuous impulsion, with its capricious humor and its violent appetites, constantly crosses. It is on that account that we see the taste, still coarse, seize that which is new and startling, the disordered, the adventurous and the strange, the violent and the savage, and fly from nothing so much as from calm and simplicity. It invents grotesque figures, it likes rapid transitions, luxurious forms, sharplj'-marked changes, acute tones, a pathetic song. That which man calls beautiful at this time is that which excites him, that which gives him matter ; but that which excites him to give his personality to the object, that which gives matter to a. possible plastic operation, for otherwise it would not be the beautiful for him. A remarkable change has there- fore taken place in the form of his judgments ; he searches for these objects, not because they affect him, but because they furnish him with the occasion of acting ; they please hira, not because they answer to a want, but because they satisfy a law which speaks in his breast, although quite low as yet. Soon it will not be sufficient for things to please him ; he will wish to please : in the first place, it is true, onl}' by that which belongs to him ; afterwards bj* that which he is. That which he possesses, that which he produces, ought not merely to bear any more the traces of servitude, nor to mark out the end, simply and scrupulously, by the form. Independently of the use to which it is destined, the object ought also to reflect the enlightened intelligence 122 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAY*!. which imagines it, the hand which shaped it with affection, the mind free and serene which chose it and exposed it to view. Now, the ancient German searches for more ma^w- ficent furs, for more splendid antlers of the stag, for more elegant drinking-horns ; and the Caledonian chooses the prettiest shells for his festivals. The arms themselves ought to be no longer only objects of terror, but also of pleasure ; and the skilfull3'- worked scabbard will not attract less attention than the homicidal edge of the sword. The instinct of play, not satisfied with bringing into the sphere of the necessary an aesthetic superabundance for the future more free, is at last completely emancipated from the bonds of duty, and the beautiful becomes of itself an object of man's exertions. He adorns himself. The free pleasure comes to take a place among his wants, and the useless soon becomes the best part of his joys. Form, which from the outside gradually approaches him, in hisdwelhng, his furniture, his clothing, begins at last to take possession of the man himself, to transform him, at first exteriorly and afterwards in the interior. The disordered leaps of joy become the dance, the formless gesture is changed into an amiable and harmonious pantomime, the confused accents of feeling are developed, and • begin to obey measures and adapt themselves to song. When, like the flight of cranes, the Trojan army rushes on to the field of battle with thrilling cries, the Greek army approaches in silence and with a noble and measured step. On the one side we see but the exubei-ance of a blind force, on the other the triumph of form, and the simple majesty of law. Now, a nobler necessity binds the two sexes mutually, : and the interests of the heart contribute in rendering dur- able an alliance which was at first capricious and changing like the desire that knits it. Delivered from the heavy fetters of desire, the eye, now calmer, attends to the form", the soul contemplates the soul, and the interested exchange of pleasure becomes a generous exchange of mutual incli- ^ nation. Desire enlarges and rises to love, in proportion as it sees humanity dawn in its object ; and, despising the vile triumphs gained by the senses, man tries to win a nobler victory over the will. The necessity of pleasing subjects the powerful nature to the gentle laws of taste; iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 123 pleasure may be stolen, but love must be a gift. To obtain tiiis higher recompense, it is only through the form and not through matter that it can carry on the contest. It must cease to act on feeling as a force, to appear in the intelligence as a simple phenomenon ; it must respect liberty, as it is liberty it wishes to please. The beautiful reconciles the contrast of different natures in its simplest and purest expression. It also reconciles the eternal con- trast of the two sexes in the whole complex framework of society, or at all events it seeks to do so ; and, taking" as its model the free alliance it has knit between manly strength and womanly gentleness, it strives to place in harmonj', in the moral world, all the elements of gentleness and of violence. Now, at length, weakness becomes sa- cred, and an unbridled strength disgraces ; the injustice of nature is corrected b3' the generosity of chivalrous manners. The being whom no power can make tremble, is disarmed b^- the amiable blush of modest}-, and tears extinguish a vengeance thatblood could not have quenched. Hatred itself hears the delicate voice of honor, the con- queror's sword spares the disarmed enemy, and a hospitable hearth smokes for the stranger on the dreaded hillside where murder alone awaited him before. In the midst of the formidable realm of forces, and of the sacred empire of laws, the aesthetic impulse of form creates by degrees a third and a joyous realm, that of play and of the appearance, v^iere she emancipates man from fetters, in all his relations, and from all that is named constraint, whether phj-sical or moral. If in the dynamic state of rights men mutually move and come into collision as forces, in the moral (ethical) state of duties, man opposes to man the majesty of the laws, and chains down his will. In this realm of the beautiful or the aesthetic state, man ought to appear to man only as a form, and an object of free play. To give free- dom through freedom is the fundamental law of this realm. The dynamic state can only make society simple pos- sibly by subduing nature through nature'; the moral (ethical) state can only make it morally necessary by sub- mitting the will of the individual to the general will. The .-Esthetic state alone can make it real, because it 124 yesthetical letters and essays. carries out the will of all through the nature of the indi- vidual. If necessity alone forces man to enter into society, and if his reason engraves on his soul social prin- ciples, it is beauty only that can give him a social char- acter; taste alone brings harmony into society, because it creates harmony in the individual. AH other forms of perception divide the man, because they are based exclu- sively either in the sensuous or in the spiritual part of his being. ■ It is only the perception of beauty that makes of him an entirety, because it demands the co-operation of his two natures. All other forms of communication divide society, because they apply exclusivel3' either to the receptivity or to the private activitj' of its members, and therefore to what distinguishes men one from the other. The sesthetic communication alone unites societj' because it applies to what is common to all its members. We only enjoy the pleasures of sense as individuals, without the nature of the race in us sharing in it ; accordingly, we cannot generalize our individual pleasures, because we cannot generalize our individuality. We enjoy the pleas- ures of knowledge as a race, dropping the individual in our judgment ; but we cannot generalize the pleasures of the understanding, because we cannot eliminate individu- alit}^ from the judgments of others as we do from our own. -Beaut}' alone can we enjoy both as individuals and as a race, that is, as representing a race. Good appertaining to sense can only make one person happy, because it is founded on inclination, which is always exclusive ; and it can only make a man partially happj-, because his real personality does not share in it. Absolute good can only render a man happy conditionally, for truth is only the reward of abnegation, and a pure heart alone has faith in a pure will. Beauty alone confers happiness on all, and under its influence every being forgets that he is limited. Taste does not suffer anj^ superior or absolute authority, and the sway of beauty is extended over appearance. It extends up to the seat of reason's supremacy, suppressing all that is material. It extends down to where sensuous impulse rules with blind compulsion, and form is undevel- oped. Taste ever maintains its power on these remote iESTHETICAL I^ETTEItS AND ESSAY'S. 125 borders, where legislation is taken from it. Particular desires must renounce their egotism, and the agreeable, otherwise tempting the senses, must in matters of taste adorn the mind with the attractions of grace. Duty and stern necessity must change their forbidding tone, only excused by resistance, and do homage to nature by a nobler trust in her. Taste leads our knowledge from the mysteries of science into the open expanse of common sense, and changes a narrow scholasticism into the common propertj- of the human race. Here the highest genius must leave its particular elevation, and make itself familiar to the comprehension even of a child. Strength must let the Graces bind it, and the arbitrary lion must yield to the reins of love. For this purpose taste throws a veil over physical necessity, ofiending a free mind bj' its coarse nudit3^ and dissimulating our degrading parentage with matter by a delightful illusion of freedom. Mer- cenar}- art itself rises from the dust ; and the bondage of the bodily-, at its magic touch, falls off from the inanimate and animate. In the sesthetic state the most slavish tool is a free citizen, having the same rights as the noblest ; and the intellect which shapes the mass to its intent must consult it concerning its destination. Consequently, in the realm of aesthetic appearance, the idea of equality is real- ized, which the political zealot would gladly see carried out socially. It has often been said that perfect politeness is only found near a Jjirone. If thus restricted in the material, man has, as elsewhere appears, to find compen- sation in the ideal world. _ Does such a state of beauty in appearance exist, and where? It must be in every finely-harmonized soul ; bnt as a fact, only in select circles, like the pure ideal of tlie chu rch an d state — in circles where manners are not formed byThe emptj' imitations of the foreign, but by the \cry beauty of nature ; where man passes through all sorts of complications in all simplicity and innocence, neither forced to trench on {mother's freedom to preserve his own, nor to show grace at the cost of dignity. ^STHETICAL ESSAYS. THE MORAL UTILITY OF ESTHETIC MANNERS. The author of the article which appeared in the eleventh number of " The Hours," of 1795, upon " The Danger of iEsthetic Manners," was right to hold as doubtful a moralitj- founded onty on a feeling for the beautiful, and which has no other warrant than taste; but it is evident that a strong and pure feeling for the beautiful ought to exercise a salutary influence upon the moral life ; and this is the question of which I am about to treat. When I attribute to taste the merit of contributing to moral progress, it is not in the least mj' intention to pre- tend that the interest that good taste takes in an action suffices to make an action moral ; moralit}' could never have any other foundation than her own. Taste can be favor- able to moralit3' in the conduct, as I hope to point out in the present essay ; but alone, and by its unaided infjuonce, it could never produce anything moral. It is absolutel3' the same with respect to internal liberty as with external physical libertj". I act freely in a physical sense only when, independently of all external influence, I simplj- obey my wilL But for the possibility of thus obeying without hinderance my own will, it is probable, ultimately, that I am indebted to a principle beyond or dis- tinct from myself immediately it is admitted that this principle would hamper my will. The same also with regard to the possibility of accomplishing such action in conformity with duty — it maj'be that I owe it, ultimately, to a principle distinct from mj* reason ; that is possible, the moment the idea of this principle is recognized as a force 126 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 127 which could have constrained my independence. Thus the same as we can say of a man, that he holds his liberty from another man, although libert}' in its proper sense consists in not being forced to be regulated by another — in like manner we can also saj- that taste here obeys virtue, although virtue herself expressly' carries this idea, that in the practice of virtue she makes use of no other foreign help. An action does not in anj- degree cease to be free, because he who could hamper its accomplishment should fortunatel}' abstain from putting any obstacle in the way ; it suffices to know that this agent has been moved by his own will without anj- consideration of another will. In the same way, an action of the moral order does not lose its right to be qualified as a moral action, because the temptations which might hs.\e turned it in another direction did not present themselves ; it suffices to admit that the agent obe3'ed solely the decree of his reason to the exclusion of all foreign springs of action. The liberty of an external act is established as soon as it directly proceeds from the will of a person ; the moraliti" of an interior action is established from the moment that the will of the agent is at once determined to it b)' the laws of reason. It may be rendered easier or more difficult to act as free men according as we meet or not in our path forces adverse to our will that must be overcome. In this sense liberty is more or less susceptibj^. It is greater, or at least more visible, when we enable it to prevail over the opposing forces, however energetic their opposition ; but it is not suspended because our will should have met with no resistance, or that a foreign succor coming to our aid sliould have destroj-ed this resistance, without any help from ourselves. The same with respect to moralitj' ; we might have more or less resistance to offer in order on the instant to obe}^ our reason, according as it awakens or not in us those instincts which struggle against its precepts, and which must be put aside. In this sense morality is sus- ceptible of more or of less. Our morality is greater, or at least more in relief, when we immediately obey reason, however powerful the instincts are which push us in a 128 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. contrary direction ; but it is not suspended because we have liad no temptation to disobey, or tliat tliis force had been paralyzed by some other force other than our will. We are incited to an action solelj- because it is moral, without previously asking ourselves if it is the most agreeable. It is enough that such an action is morally good, and it would preserve this character even if there were cause to believe that we should have acted differentlj' if the action had cost us any trouble, or had deprived us of a pleasure. It can be admitted, for the honor of humanity, that no man could fall so low as to prefer evil solely because it is evil, but rather that every man, without exception, would prefer the good because it is the good, if by some acci- dental circumstance the good did not exclude the agree- able, or did not entail trouble. Thus in reality all moral action seems to have no other principle than a conflict between the good and the agreeable ; or, that which comes to the same thing, between desire and reason ; the force of our sensuous instincts on one side, and, on the other side, the feebleness of will, the moral facultj' : such \ apparently is the source of all our faults. There may be, therefore, two different ways of favoring morality, the same as there are two kinds of obstacles which thwart it : either we must strengthen the side of reason, and the power of the good will, so that no temp- , tation can overcome it ; or we must break the force of : temptation, in order that the reason and the will, although ■ feebler, should yet be in a state to surmount it It might be said, without doubt, that true morality gains little b}' this second proceeding, because it happens with- out any modiflcation of the will, and yet that it is the nature of the will that alone give to actions their moral character. But I say also, in the case in question, a change of will is not at all necessary ; because we do not suppose a bad will which should require to be changed, but only a will turned to good, but which is feeble. Therefore, this will, inclined to good, but too feeble, does not fail to attain by this route to good actions, which might not have happened if a stronger impulsion had drawn it in a contrary sense. But every time that a strong will towards good becomes the principle of an action, we are really in ESTHETIC AL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 129 presence of a moral action. I have therefore no scruple in 'advancing this proposition — that all which neutralizes the resistance offered to the law of duty really favors morality. Morality has within us a natural enemy, the sensuous instinct ; this, as soon as some object solicits its desires, aspires at once to gratify it, and, as soon as reason requires from it anything repugnant, it does not fail to rebel against its precepts. This sensuous instinct is constantly occu- pied in gaining the will on its side. The will is never- theless under the jurisdiction of the moral law, and it is under an obligation never to be in contradiction with that which reason demands. But the sensuous instinct does not recognize the moral law , it wishes to enjo^- its object and to induce the will to rea'ize it also, nothwithstaudiug what the reason may advant^. This tendency of the faculty of our appetites, of immedi!<*^elj' directing the will without troubling itself about superior laws, is perpetually in conilict with our moral destination, and it is the most powerful adversary that man has to combat in his moral conduct. The coai'se soul, without either moral or aesthetic education, receives directly the law of appetite, and acts only according to the good pleasure of the senses. The moral soul, but which wants ffisthetic culture, receives in a direct manner the law of reason, and it is only out of respect for duty that it triumphs over temptation. In the purified aesthetic soul, there is moreover another motive, another force, which frequentlj^ takes the place of virtue when virtue is absent, and which renders it easier when it is present — that is, taste. Taste demands of us moderation and dignity ; it has a horror of everything sharp, hard and violent; it likes all that shapes itself with ease and harmony. To listen to the voice of reason amidst the tempest of the senses, and to know where to place a limit to nature in its most brutified explosions, is, as we are aware, required bj' good breeding, which is no other than an aesthetic law ; this is required of every civilized man. Well, then, this constraint im- posed upon civilized man in the expression of his feelings, confers upon him already a certain degree of authority 130 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. over them, or at least develops in him a certain aptitude to rise above the purelj- passive state of the soul, to inter- rupt this state by an initiative act, and to stop by reflection the petulance of the feelings, ever ready to pass from affec- tions to acts. Therefore everything that interrupts _ the blind impetiiositj' of these movements of the affections does not as yet, however, produce, I own, a virtue (for virtue ought never to have any other acti\e principle than itself) , but that at least opens the road to the will, in order to turn it on the side of virtue. Still, this victory of taste over brutish affections is by no means a moral action, and the freedom which the will acquires by the intervention of taste is as j^et in no wa3' a moral lihertj'. Taste delivers the soul from the yoke of instinct, only to impose upon it chains of its own ; and in discerning the first enemy, the declared enem3- of moral liberty, it remains itself, too often, as a second enemj-, perhaps even the more dangerous as it assumes the aspect of a fi-iend. Taste effectivelj' governs the soul itself oii\y bj' the attraction of pleasure ; it is true of a nobler type, because its principle is reason, but still as long as the will is determined bj- pleasure there is not yet morality. Notwithstanduig this, a great point is gained already bj- the intervention of taste in the operations of the will. All those material inclinations and brutal appetites, which oppose with so much obstinacy and -vehemence the prac- tice of good, the soul is freed from through the sesthetic taste ; and in their place, it implants in us nobler and gentler inclinations, which draw nearer to order, to har- mon}-, and to perfection ; and although these inclinations are not bj' themselves virtues, they have at least some- thing in common with virtue ; it is their object. Thence- forth, if it is the appetite that speaks, it will have to undergo a rigorous control before the sense of the beau- tiful ; if it is the reason which speaks, and which commands in its acts conformitj' with order, harmonj-, and perfection, not only will it no longer meet with an adversary on the side of inclination, but it will find the most active com- petition. If we survey all the forms under which morality can be produced, we shall see that all these forms can be reduced to two ; either it is sensuous nature which moves ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 131 ilie soul either to do this thing or not to do the other, and ido will finally decides after the law of the reason ; or it is the reason itself which impels the motion, and the will obeys it without seeking counsel of the senses. The Greek i)riLicess, Anna Comnena, speaks of a rebel prisoner, whojn her father Alexis, then a simple general of his predecessor, had been charged to conduct to Con- stantinople. Dtu'ing the journe}-, as thej' were riding side by side, Alexis desired to halt under the shade of a tree to refresh himself during the great heat of the day. It was not long before he fell asleep, whilst his companion, who felt no inclination to repose with the fear of death awaiting him before his eyes, remained awake. Alexis slumbered profoundly', with his sword hanging upon a branch above- his head ; the prisoner perceived the sword, and immediately conceived the idea of killing his guardian and thus of regaining his freedom. Anna Comnena gives us to understand that she knows not what might have been the rssult had not Alexis fortunately awoke at that instant. In this there is a moral of the highest kind, in which the sensuous instinct first raised its voice, and of which the reason had onl^^ afterwards taken cognizance in qualitj- of judge. But suppose that the prisoner had triumphed over the temptation only out of respect for justice, there could be no doubt the action would have been a moral action. When the late Duke Leopold of Brunswick, standing upon the banks of the raging waters of the Oder, asked himself if at the peril o^ his life he ought to venture into the impetuous flood in order to save some unfortunates who without his aid were sure to perish; and when — I suppose a case — simply under the influence of duty, he throws himself into the boat into which none other dares to enter, no one will contest doubtless that he acted mor- ally. Tiie duke was here in a contrary position to that of ' the preceding one. The idea of dut}-, in this circumstance, was the first which presented itself, and afterwards only the instinct of self-preservation was roused to oppose itself to that prescribed by reason. But in both cases the will acted in the same way ; it obeyed unhesitatingly the reason, yet both of them are moral actions. 132 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. But would the action have continued moral in both cases, if we suppose the aesthetic taste to have taken part in it? For example, suppose that the first, who was tempted to commit a bad action, and who gave it up from respect for justice, had the taste sufficiently cultivated to feel an invincible horror aroused in him against all dis- graceful or violent action, the aesthetic sense alone will suffice to turn him from it ; there is no longer any deliber- ation before the moral tribunal, before the conscience ; another motive, another jurisdiction has already pro- nounced. But the aesthetic sense governs the will by the feeling and not by laws. Thus this man refuses to enjoy the agreeable sensation of a life saved, because he cannot support his odious feelings of having committed a base- ness. Therefore all, in this, took place before the feelings alone, and the conduct of this man, although in conformity with the law, is morally indifferent ; it is simply a fine effect of nature. Now let us suppose that the second, he to whom his reason prescribed to do a thing against which natural instinct protested ; suppose that this man had to the same extent a susceptibilitj- for the beautiful, so that all which is great and perfect enraptured him ; at the same moment, when reason gave the order, the feelings would place themselves on the same side, and he would do willinglj'' that which without the inclination for the beautiful he would have had to do contrary to inclination. But would this be a reason for us to find it less perfect? Assuredl3' not, because in principle it acts out of pure respect for the prescriptions of reason ; and if it follows these injunc- tions with joy, that can take nothing away from the moral purity of the act. Thus, this man will be quite as perfect in. the moral sense; and, on the contrary-, he will be incomparably more perfect in the phj'sical sense, be- cause he is inflnitelj' more capable of making a virtuous subject. Thus, taste gives a direction to the soul which disposes it to virtue, in keeping away such inclinations as are con- trary to it, and in rousing those which are favorable. Taste could not injure true virtue, although in every case where natural instinct speaks first, taste commences by ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 133 deciding for its chief that which conscience otherwise ought to have known ; in consequence it is the eanse that, amongst the actions of those whom it governs, there are many more actions morallj* indifferent than actions truly moral. It thus happens that the excellencj- of the man does not consist in the least degree in producing a larger sum of vigorously moral particular actions, but bj' evincing as a whole a greater conformit}- of all his natural disposi- tions with the moral law ; and it is not a thing to give people a verj' high idea' of their country or of their age to hear morality so often spoken of and particular acts boasted of as traits of virtue. Let us hope that the day when civilization shall have consummated its work (if we can realize this term in the mind) there will no longer be any question of this. But, on the other side, taste can become of possible utility to true virtue, in all cases when, the first instigations Issuing from reason, its Aoice incurs the risk of being stifled by the more powerful solicitations of natural instinct. Thus, taste determines our feehngs to take the part of duty, and in this manner renders a mediocre moral force of will sufi3cient for the practice of virtue. In this light, if the taste never injures true moralitj', and if in many cases it is of evident use — and this cir- cumstance is ver}' important — then it is supremely favor- able to the legality of our conduct. Suppose that sesthetic education contributes in no degree to the improvement of our feelings, at least it renders us better able to act, although without true moral disposition, as we should ha\e acted if our soul had been truly moral. Therefore, it is quite true that, before the tribunal of the conscience, our acts have absolutely no importance but as the expres- sion of our feelings : but it is precisely the contrarj' in the physical order and in the plan of nature : there it is no longer our sentiments that are of importance ; the}* are only important so far as they give occasion to acts which . conduce to the aims of nature. But the phjsical order which is governed by forces, and the moral order which governs itself by laws, are so exactly made one for the other, and are so intimately blended, that the actions which are by their form morally suitable, necessarily con- 134 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. tain also a physical suitability ; and as the entire edifice of nature seems to exist only to render possible the highest of all aims, which is the good, in tiie same manner the good can in its turn be employed as the means of preserv- ing the edifice. Thus, the natural order has been rendered dependent upon the morality of our souls, and we cannot go against the moral laws ' of the world without at the same time provoking a perturbation in the physical world. If, then, it is impossible to expect that human nature, as long as it is only human nature, should act without interruption or feebleness, uniformly and constantly as pure reason, and that it never offend the laws of moral order ; if fully persuaded, as we arc, both of the neces- sity and the possibility of pure virtue, we are forced to avow how subject to accident is the exercise of it, and how little we ought to reckon upon the steadfastness of our best principles ; if with tliis conviction of human fragility we bear in mind that each of the infractions of the moral law attacks the edifice of nature, if we recall all these considerations to our memorv, it would be assuredl}' the most criminal boldness to place the interests of the entire world at the mercy of the uncertainty of our virtue. Let us rather draw from it the following conclu- sion, that it is for us an obligation to satisfj' at the very least the physical order by the object of our acts, even when we do not satisfy the exigencies of the moi'al order by the form of these acts ; to paj', at least, as perfect instruments the aims of nature, that which we owe as im- perfect persons to reason, in order not to appear shame- faced before both tribunals. For if we refused to make any effort to conform our acts to it because simple legality is without moral merit, the order of the world might in the meanwhile be dissolved, and before we had succeeded in establishing our principles all the links of society might be broken No, the more our morality is subjected to chance, the more' is it necessary to take measures in order to assure its legality ; to neglect, either from levity or pride, this legality is a fault for which we shall have to answer before morality. When a maniac believes himself threatened with a fit of madness, he leaves no knife JSSTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS 135 within reach of his hands, and he puts himself under con- straint, in order to avoid responsibility in a state of sanity for the crimes which his troubled brain might lead him to commit. In a similar manner it is an obligation for us to seek the salutary' bonds which religion and the eesthetic laws present to us, in order that during the crisis when our passion is dominant it shall not injure the physical order. It is not unintentionally that I have placed religion and taste in one and the same class ; the reason is that both one and the other have the merit, similar in effect, although dissimilar in principle and in value, to take the place of virtue properlj' so called, and to assure legality where there is no possibility to hope for morality. Doubtless that would hold an incontestably higher rank in the order of pure spirits, as they would need neitlier the attraction of the beautiful nor the perspective of eternal life, to conform on ever}- occasion to the demands of reason ; but we know man is short-sighted, and his feebleness forces the most rigid moralist to temper in some degree the rigidity of his S3'stem in practice, although he will j'ield nothing in theory ; it obliges him, in order to insure the welfare of the human race, which would be ill protected by a virtue subjected to chance, to have further recourse to two strong anchors — those of religion and taste. ON THE SUBLIME. " Mak is never obliged to say, I must — must" says the Jew Nathan * to the dervish ; and this expression is true in a wider sense than man might be tempted to suppose. The will is tlie specific character of man, and reason itself is only the eternal rule of his will. All nature acts rea- sonablj- ; all our prerogative is to act reasonablj-, with consciousness and with will. All other objects obey neces- sity ; man is the being who wills. * Lessing's play, " Naihan the Wise," act 1. scene 3. 136 ^.STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSATS. It is exactly for this reason that there is nothing more inconsistent with the dignity of man than to suffer vio- lence, for violence effaces him. He who does violence to us disputes nothing less than our humanity ; he who sub- mits in a cowardly spirit to the violence abdicates his quality of man. But this pretension to remain absolutely free from all that is violence seems to imply a being in possession of a force sufficiently great to keep ofi' all other forces. But if this pretension is found in a being who, in the order of forces, cannot claim the first rank, the result is an unfortunate contradiction between his instinct and his power. Man is precisely in this case. Surrounded bj' number- less forces, which are all superior to him and hold sway over him, he aspires by his nature not to have to suffer anjr injury' at their hands. It is true that bj- his intelli- gence he adds artificially to his natural forces, and that up to a certain point he actually succeeds in reigning physi- cally over everything that is physical. The proverb says, " there is a remedy for everything except death ;" but this exception, if it is one in the strictest acceptation of the term, would suffice to entirely' ruin the very idea of our nature. Never will man be the cause that wills, if there is a case, a single case, in which, with or without his consent, he is forced to what he does not wish. This single terrible exception, to be or to do what is necessary and not what he wishes, this idea will pursue him as a phantom ; and as we see in fact among the greater part of men, it will give him up a prej* to the blind terrors of imagination. His boasted liberty is nothing, if there is a single point where he is under constraint and bound. It is education that must give back liberty to man, and help him to complete the whole idea of his nature. It ought, therefore, to make him capable of making his will prevail, for, I repeat it, man is the being who wills. It is possible to reach this end in two ways : either really, hy opposing force to force, by commanding nature, as nature yourself; or by the idea, issuing from nature, and bj' thus destroying in relation to self the very idea of violence. All that helps man really to hold sway over nature is what is styled physical education. Man culti- JESTHETIOAL LETTERS AND E9SATS. 137 vates his understanding and develops his physical loicBi either to convert the forces of nature, according to their proper laws, into the instruments of his will, or to secure himself against their etfects when he cannot direct them. But the forces of nature can onlj- be directed or turned aside up to a certain point ; beyond that point the}' with- draw from the influence of man and place him under theirs. Thus beyond the point in question his freedom would be lost, were he only susceptible of physical education. But he must be man in the full sense of the term, and consequently he must have nothing to endure, in any case, contrary to his will. Accordingly, when he can no longer oppose to the physical forces anj' proportional phj-sical force, onl}- one resource remains to him to avoid suffering an}' violence : that is, to cause to cease entirely that rela- tion which is so fatal to him. It is, in short, to annihilate as an idea the violence he is obliged to suffer in fact. The education that fits man for this is called moral edu- cation. The man fashioned by moral education, and he only, is entirely free. He is either superior to nature as a power, or he is in harmony with her. None of the actions that she brings to bear upon him is violence, for before reach- ing him it has become an act of his ovm will, and dj'namic nature could never touch him, because he spontaneous!}' Iteeps away from all to.which she can reach. But to at- tain to this state of muid, which morality designates as resignation to necessary things, and religion styles abso- lute submission to the counsels of Providence!^ to reach this by an effort of his free will and with reflection, a cer- tain clearness is required in thought, and a certain energy in the will, superior to what man commonly possesses in active life. Happily for him, man finds here not only in his rational nature a moral aptitude that can be developed by the understanding, but also in his reasonable and sen- sible nature — that is, in his human nature — an msthetie tendency which seems to have been placed there expressly : a faculty awakens of itself in the presence of certain sen- suous objects, and which, after our feelings are purified, can be cultivated to such a point as to become a powerful 138 iESTHKTICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. ideal development. This aptitude, I grant, is idealistic in its principle and in its essence, but one which even the realist allows to be seen clearl3' enough in his conduct, though he does not acknowledge this in theorj^ I am now about to discuss this facult}-. I admit that the sense of the beautiful, when it is developed hy culture, suffices of itself even to make us, in a certain sense, independent of nature as far as it is a force. A mind that has ennobled itself sufficiently to be more sensible of the form than of the matter of things, contains in itself a plenitude of existence that nothing could make it lose, especiallj- as it does not trouble itself about the possession of the things in question, and finds a very liberal pleasure in the mere contemplation of the phenomenon. As this mind has no want to appropriate the objects in the midst of which it lives, it has no fear of being deprived of them. But it is nevertheless necessary that these phenomena should have a body, through which they manifest themselves ; and, consequently, as long as we feel the want even only of finding a beautiful appear- ance or a beautiful phenomenon," this want implies that of the existence of certain objects ; and it follows that our satisfaction still depends on nature, considered as a force, because it is nature who disposes of all existence in a sovereign manner. It is a different thing, in fact, to feel in j^ourself the want of objects endowed with beaut}' and goodness, or simply to require that the objects which surround us are good and beautiful. This last desire is compatible with the most perfect freedom of the soul ; but it is not so with the other. We are entitled to require that the object before us should be beautiful and good, but we can only wish that the beautiful and the good should be realized objectively before us. Novr the disposition of mind is, par excellence, called grand and sublime, in which no attention is given to the question of knowing if the beautiful, the good, and the perfect exist ; but when it is rigorously required that that which exists should be good, beautiful and perfect, this character of mind is called sub- lime, because it contains in it positively all the character- istics of a fine mind without sharing its negative features. A sign by which beautiful and good minds, but having JE8THETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 139 weaknesses, are recognized, is the aspiring alwaj's to find their moral ideal realized in the world of facts, and their being painfully affected hy all that places an obstacle to it. A mind thus constituted is reduced to a sad state of dependence in relation to chance, and it may always be predicted of it, without fear of deception, that it will give too large a share to the matter in moral and sesthetical things, and that it will not sustain the more critical trials of character and taste. Moral imperfections ought not to be to us a cause oisufferiny and of pain : suffering and pain bespeak rather an ungratified wish than an unsatisfied moral want. An unsatisfied moral want ought to be accompanied by a more manly feeling, and fortifj- our mind and confirm it in its energy rather than make us unhappj^ and pusillanimous. Nature has given to us two genii as companions in our life in this lower world. The one, amiable and of good companionship, shortens the troubles of the journey by the gayety of its plays. It makes the chains of necessity light to us, and leads us amidst joy and laughter, to the most perilous spots, where we must act as pure spirits and strip ourselves of all that is bodj-, on the knowl- edge of the true and the practice of duty. Once when we are there, it abandons us, for its realm is limited to the world of sense ; its earthly wings could not carry it beyond. But at this moment the other companion steps upon the stage, silent aad grave, and with his powerful arm carries us beyond the precipice that made us giddj'. In the former of these genii we recognize the feeling of the beautiful, in the other the feeling of the sublime. No doubt the beautiful itself is already an expression of liberty. This liberty is not the kind that raises us above the power of nature, and that sets us free from all bodily influence, but it is only the liberty which we enjoy as men, without issuing from the limits of nature. In the presence of beauty we feel ourselves free, because the sensuous instincts are in harmonj' with the laws of reason. In presence of the sublime we feel ourselves sublime, be- cause the sensuous instincts have no influence over the jurisdiction of reason, because it is then the pure spirit that acts in us as if it were not absolutely subject to any other laws than its own. 140 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. The feeling of the sublime is a mixed feeling. It is at once a paiaful state^ which in its parox3-sm is manifested by a kind of stiudder, and a joyous state, that may rise to rapture, and which, without being properly a pleasure, is greatly preferred to every kind of pleasure by delicate souls. This union of two contrary' sensations in one and the same feeling proves in a peremptory manner our moral independence. For as it is absolutelj' impossible that the same object should be with us in two opposite relations, it follows that it is we ourselves who sustain two different relations with the object. It follows that these two opposed natures should be united in us, which, on the idea of this object, are brought into play in two perfectly opposite wajs. Thus we experience bj' the feeling of the beautiful that the state of our spiritual nature is not necessarilj' determined by the state of our sensuous nature ; that the laws of nature are not necessarilj' our laws ; and that there is in us an autonomous principle independent of all sensuous impressions. The sublime object may be considered in two lights. We either represent it to our comprehension, and we tr3' in vain to make an image or idea of it, or we refer it to our vital force, and we consider it as a power before which ours is nothing. But though in both cases we experience in connection with this object the painful feeling of our limits, yet we do not seek to a\'oid it ; on the contrary we are attracted to it hj an irresistible force. Could this be the case if the limits of our imagination were at the same time those of our comprehension ? Should we be willingly called back to the feeling of the omnipotence of the forces of nature if we had not in us something that cannot be a prey of these forces. We are pleased with the spectacle of the sensuous infinite, because we are able to attain by thought what the senses can no longer embrace and what the understanding cannot grasp. The sight of a terrible object transports us with enthu- siasm, because we are capable of willing what the in- stincts reject with horror, and of rejecting what they desire. We willingl}' allow our imagination to find some- thing in the world of phenomena that passes bej-ond it ; because, after all, it is only one sensuous force that ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 141 triumphs over another sensuous force, but nature, not- withstanding all her infinit}-, cannot attain to the absolute grandeur which is in ourselves. We submit willingly to phj-sical necessity- both our well-being and our existence. This is because the verj- power reminds us that there are in us principles that escape its empire. Man is in the hands of nature, but the will of man is in his own hands. Nature herself has actually used a sensuous means to teach us that we ai'e something more than mere sensuous natures. She has even known how to make use of our sensations to put us on the track of this discovery — that we are bj' no means subject as slaves to the violence of the sensations. And this is quite a different effect from that which can be produced bj^ the beautiful ; I mean the beautiful of the real world, for the sublime itself is surpassed b\- the ideal. In the presence of beautj^, reason and sense are in harmony, and it is onlj^ on account of this harmony that the beautiful has attraction for us. Consequently', beauty alone could never teach us that our destination is to act as pure intelligences, and that we are capable of showing ourselves such. In the presence of the sublime, on the contrary, reason and the sensuous are not in harmonjr, and it is pi'ecisely this contradiction between the two which makes the charm of the sublime. — its irresistible action on our minds. Here the pln'sical man and the moral man separate in the most marked manner ; for it is exactl5' in the presence of objects that make us feel at once how limited the former is that the other makes the experience of its force. The ver3' thing that lowers one to the earth is precisely that which raises the other to the infinite. Let us imagine a luan endowed with all the virtues of which the union constitutes a fine character. Let us suppose a man who finds his delight in practising justice, beneficence, moderation, constancy, and good faith. All the duties whose accomplishment is prescribed to him by cir- cumstances are onlj' a play to him, and I admit that for- tune favors him in such wise that none of the actions which his good heart may demand of him will be hard to him. Who would not be charmed with such a dehghtful har- 142 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. mony between the instincts of nature and tlie prescrip- tions of reason ? and wlio could help admiring such a man ? Nevertheless, though he maj' inspire us with affection, are we quite sure that he is reallj' virtuous ? or in general that he has anjtliing that corresponds to the idea of virtue ? If this man had onlj' in view to obtain agreeable sensations, unless he were mad he could not act in anj- other possible way ; and he would have to be his own enemy to wish to be vicious. Perhaps the principle of his actions is pure, but this is a question to be discussed between himself and his conscience. For our part, we see nothing of it ; we do not see him do anything more than a simply clever man would do who had no other god than pleasure. Thus all his virtue is a phenomenon that is ex- plained by reasons derived from the sensuous order, and we are bj' no means driven to seek for reasons beyond the world of sense. Let us suppose that this same man falls suddenly under misfortune. He is deprived of his possessions : his repu- tation is destroyed ; he is chained to his bed by sickness and suffering ; he is robbed by death of all those he loves ; he is forsaken in his distress by all in whom he had trusted. Let us under these circumstances again seek him, and demand the practice of the same virtues under trial as he formerly had practised during the period of his prosperity'. If he is found to be absolutely the same as before, if his poverty- has not deteriorated his benevolence, or ingratitude his kindlj- offices of good-will, or bodily suffering his equanimity, or adversitj- his joy in the happiness of others ; if his change of fortune is perceptible in externals, but not in his habits, in the matter, but not in the form of his conduct ; then, doubt- less, his virtue could not be explained by any reason drawn from the phj'sical order; the idea of nature — which always necessarilj^ supposes that actual phenomena rest upon some anterior phenomenon, as effects upon cause — this idea no longer suffices to enable us to comprehend this man ; because there is nothing more contradictory than to admit that effect can remain the same when the cause has changed to its contrary. ^Ve must then gi\e up all natu- ral explanation or thought of finding the reason of his acts ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 143 in his condition ; we must of necessitj- go beyond the physical order, and seek the principle of his conduct in quite another world, to which the reason can indeed raise itself with its ideas, but which the understanding cannot grasp by its conceptions. It is this revelation of the absolute moral power which is subjected to no condition of nature, it is this which gives to the melancholj' feeling that seizes our heart at the sight of such a man that peculiar, inexpressible charm, which no delight of the senses, however refined, could arouse in us to the same extent as the sublime. Thus the sublime opens to us a road to overstep the limits of the world of sense, in which the feeling of the beautiful .would forever imprison us. It is not little by little (forbetween absolute dependence and absolute liberty there is no possible transition), it is suddenly and by a shock that the sublime wrenches our spiritual and inde- pendent nature away from the net which feehng has spun round us, and which enchains the soul the more tightly because of its subtle texture. Whatever may be the extent to which feeling has gained a mastery over men by the latent influence of a softening taste, when even it should have succeeded in penetrating into the most secret recesses of moral jurisdiction urider the deceptive envelope of spiritual beauty, and there poisoning the holiness of principle at its source — one single sublime emotion often suffices to break all this tissue of imposture, at one blow to give freedom to the fettered elasticity of spiritual nature, to reveal its true destination, and to oblige it to conceive, for one instant at least, the feeling of its liberty. Beauty, under the shape of the divine Calypso, bewitched the virtuous son of Ulysses, and the power of her charms held him long a prisoner in her island. For long he believed he was obeying an immortal divinity, whilst he was onlj' the slave of sense ; but suddenly an impression of the sublime in the form of Mentor seizes him ; he remembers that he is called to a higher destiny — he throws himself into the waves, and is free. The sublime, like the beautiful, is spread profusely throughout nature, and the faculty to feel both one and the other has been given to all men ; but the germ does 144 ESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. not develop equally ; it is necessary that art should lend its aid. The aim of nature supposes already that we ought spontaneously to advance towards the beautiful, although we still avoid the sublime : for the beautiful is like the nurse of our childhood, and it is for her to refine our soul in withdrawing it from the rude state of nature. But though she is our first affection, and our faculty of feeling is first developed for her, nature has so provided, nevertheless, that this faculty ripens slowly and awaits its full develop- ment until the understanding and the heart are formed. If taste attains its full maturity before truth and morality have been established in our heart by u better road than that which taste would take, tlie sensuous world would remain the limit of our aspirations. We should not know, either in our ideas or in our feelings, how to pass bej'ond the world of sense, and all that imagination failed to rep- resent would be without reality to us. But happily it enters into the plan of nature, that taste, although it first comes into bloom, is the last to ripen of all the faculties of the mind. During this interval, man has time to store up in his mind a provision of ideas, a treasure of princi- ples in his heart, and then to develop especiallj^,. in drawing from reason, his feeling for the great and the sublime. As long as man was only the slave of physical necessitj', while he had found no issue to escape from the narrow circle of his appetites, and while he as yet felt none of that superior libertj' which connects him with the angels, nature, so far as she is incomprehensible, could not fail to impress him with the insufficiency of his imagination, and again, as far as slie is a destructive force, to recall his physical powerlessness. He is forced then to pass timidly towards one, and to turn away with affright from the other. But scarceljr has free contemplation assured him against the blind oppression of the forces of nature — scarcely has he recognized amidst the tide of phenomena somethin > permanent in his own being — than at once the coarse agglomeration of nature that surrounds him begins to speak in another language to his heart, and the relative grandeur which is without becomes for him a mirror in which he contemplates the absolute greatness which is ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 145 within himself. He approaches without fear, and with a thrill of pleasure, those pictures which terrified his imagi- nation, and intentionally makes an appeal to the whole strength of that facultj' by which we represent the infinite perceived bj^ the senses, in order if she fails in this attempt, to feel all the more vividly how much these ideas are superior to all that the highest sensuous faculty can give. The sight of a distant infinity — of heights bejond vision, this vast ocean which is at his feet, that other ocean still more vast which stretches above his head, transport and ravish his mind beyond the narrow circle of the real, beyond this narrow and oppressive prison of physical life. The simple majesty of nature offers him a less circumscribed measure for estimating its grandeur, and, surrounded by the grand outlines which it presents to him, he can no longer bear anything mean in his waj' of thinking. Who can tell how many luminous ideas, how many heroic resolutions, which would never ha^e been conceived in the dark study of the imprisoned man of science, nor in the saloons where the people of society elbow each other, have been inspired on a sudden during a walk, onlj' by the contact and the generous stiuggle of the soul with the great spirit of nature ? Who knows if it is not owing to a less frequent intercourse with this sublime spirit that we must partiallj- attribute the narrowness of mind so common to the dwellers in towns, always bent under the minutite which dwarf and wither their soul, whilst the soul of the nomad remains open and free as the firmament beneath which he pitches his tent? But it is not only the unimaginable or the sublime in quantity, it is also the incomprehensible, that which escapes the understanding and that which troubles it, which can serve to give ns an idea of the super-sensuous infinity. As soon as tliis element nttains the grandiose and announces itself to us as the work of nature (for otherwise it is only despicable) . it then aids the soul to represent to itself the ideal, and imprints upon it a noble development. Who does not love the eloquent disorder of natural scenery to the insipid regularity of a French garden? Who does not admire in the plains of Sicilj' the 146 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. marvellous combat of nature with herself — of her oreathe force and her destructive power ? Who does not prefer to feast his eyes upon the wild streams and waterfalls of Scotland, upon its misty mountains, upon that romantic nature from which Ossian drew his inspiration — rather than to grow enthusiastic in this stiff Holland, before the laborious triumph of patience over the most stubborn of elements ? No one will deny that in the rich grazing- grounds of Holland, things are not better ordered for the wants of physical man than upon the perfid crater of Ve- suvius, and that the understanding which likes to compre- hend and arrange all things, does not find its requirements rather in the regularly planted farm-garden than in the uncultivated beauty of natural scenery. But ™^i ^^^ requirements which go beyond those of natural life and comfort or well-being ; he has another destiny than merely to comprehend the phenomena which surround him. In the same manner as for the observant traveller, the strange wildness of nature is so attractive in physical nature — thus, and for the same reason, everj' soul capable of enthusiasm finds even in the regretable anarchy found in the moral world a source of singular pleasure. Without doubt he who sees the grand econom}' of nature only from the impoverished light of the understanding ; he who has never any other thought than to reform its defiant disorder and to substitute harmony, such a one could not find pleasure in a world which seems given up to the caprice of chance rather than governed according to a wise ordination, and where merit and fortune are for the most part in opposition. He desires that the whole world throughout its vast space should be ruled like a house well regulated ; and when this much-desired regularity is not found, he has no other resource than to defer to a future life, and to another and better nature, the satisfactio^i which is his due, but which neither the present nor the past afford him. On the contrary, he renounces willingly the pretension of restoring this chaos of phenomena to one single notion ; he regains on another side, and with interest, what he loses on this side. Just this want of connection, this anarchy, in the phenomena, making them ^STHETICAL LETTERS A?Vt) ESSAYS. 147 useless to the understanding, is what makea them valuable to reason. The more thej- are disorderly the more they represent the freedom of nature. In a sense, if 30U sup- press all connection, jou have independence. Thus, under the idea of liberty, reason brings back to unity of thought that which the understanding couJd not bring to unity of notion. It thus shows its superiority over the understanding, as a faculty subject to the conditions of a sensuous order. When we consider of what value it is to a rational being to be independent of natural )?.ws, we see how much man finds in the libert}- of sublime objeots as a set-off against the checks of his cognitive faculty. Liberty, with all its drawbacks, is everywhere vastly more attract- ive to a noble soul than good social order without it — than society like a flock of sheep, or a machine working like 1 watch. This mechanism makes of man onty a pro- duct ; liberty' makes him the citizen of a better world. It is only thus viewed that history- is sublime to me The world, as a historic object, is only the strife of natiira' forces ; with one another and with man's freedom. His tory registers more actions referable to nature than to fre*' will ; it is only in a few cases, like Catoand Phocion, tha' reason has made its power felt. If we expect a treasure of knowledge in history- how we are deceived ! AU attempts of philosophy to reconcile what the moral worW demands with what the real world gives is belied by ex- perience, and nature seepis as illogical in historj- as she ij logical in the organic kingdoms. But if we give up explanation it is different. Nature, in being capricious and defying logic, in pulling down great and little, in crushing the nobleSt works of man, taking centuries to form — nature, by deviating from in- tellectual laws, proves that j'ou cannot explain nature bj* nature's laws themselves, and this sight drives the mind to the world of ideas, to the absolute. But though nature as a sensuous activit3' drives us to the ideal, it throws us still more into the world of ideas by the terrible. Our highest aspiration is to be in good relations with phj'sical nature, without violating morality. But it is not always convenient to serve two masters ; and though duty and the appetites should never 148 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. be at strife, phj-sical necessity is ptreiiiptory, and nothing can save men from evil destinj'. Happj' is he who learns to bear what he cannot change ! There are cases where fate overpowers all ramparts, anil where the only resist- ance is, like a pure spirit, to throw freely off all interest of sense, and strip jourself of jour bodj% Now this force comes from sublime emotions, and a frequent commerce with destructive nature. Pathos is a sort of artificial mis- fortune, and brings us to the spiritual law that commands our soul. Eeal misfortune does not always choose its time opportunely, while pathos finds us armed at all points. By frequently renewing this exercise of its own activity the mind controls the sensuous, so that when real misfortune comes, it can treat it as an artificial suffer- ing, and make it a sublime emotion. Thus pathos takes away some of the malignity of destinj', and wards off its blows. Away then with that false theory which supposes falselj' a harmony binding well being and well doing. Let evil destinj' show its face. Our safety is not in blindness, but in facing our dangers. What can do so better than familiaritj- with the splendid and terrible evolution of events, or than pictures showing man in conflict with chance ; evil triumphant, securitj' deceived — pictures shown us throughout history, and placed before us bj' tragedy? Whoever passes in review the terrible fate of Mithridates, of Sj'racuse, and Carthage, cannot help keeping his appetite in check, at least for a time, and, seeing the vanity of things, strive after that which is per- manent. The capacity of the sublime is one of the noblest aptitudes of man. Beauty is useful, but does not go beyond man. The. sublime applies to the pure spirit. The sublime must be joined to the beautiful to complete the (esthetic education, and to enlarge man's heart beyond the sensuous world. Without the beautiful there would be an eternal strife between our natural and rational destiny. If we only thought of our vocation as spirits we should be strangers to this sphere of life. Without the sublime, beauty would make us forget our dignity. Enervated — wedded to this transient state, we should lose sight of our true country. ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 14^ We are only perfect citizens of nature when the sublime is wedded to the beautiful. Manj- things in nature offer man the beautiful and sub- lime. But here again he is better served at second-hand. He prefers to have them ready-made in art ratlier than seek them painfully in nature. This instinct for imi- tation in art has the advantage of being able to make those points essential that nature has made secondar3-. While nature suffers violence in the organic world, or exercises violence, working with power upon man, though she can onlj' be eesthetical as an object of pure contem- plation, art, plastic art, is fully free, because it throws off all accidental restrictions and leaves the mind free, be- cause it imitates the appearance, not the realit3' of objects. As all sublimity and beauty consists in the appearance, and not in the value of the object, it follows that art has all the advantages of nature without her shackles. THE PATHETIC. The depicting of suffering, in the shape of simple suffer- ing, is never the end of art, but it is of the greatest im- portance as a means ^f attaining its end. The highest aim of art is to represent the super-sensuous, and this is effected in particular by tragic art, because it represents by sensible marks the moral man, maintaining himself in a state of passion, independentlj" of the laws of nature. The principle of freedom in man becomes conscious of itself onl}' by the resistance it offers to the violence of the feelings. Now the resistance can only be measured bj' the strength of the attack. In order, therefore, that the intelligence may re\eal itself in man as a force independ- ent of nature, it is necessary' that nature should have first displayed all her power before our eyes. The sensuous being must be profoundly and strongh'- affected, passion must be in play, that the reasonable being may be able to testifj- his independence and manifest himself in action. 150 ^STHETICAL utntKXiS AND ESSAYS. It is impossible to k^jOw :f tht empire which man has over his affections is the effect .<;f a moral force, till we have acquired the certainty that it vs not an effect of in- sensibility. There is no merit in msistering the feelings which only lightly and transitorih' skim over the surface of the soul. But to resist a tempest which stirs up the whole of sensuous nature, and to preserve in it the free- dom of the soul, a facultj- of resistance is required infi- nitely superior to the act of natural force. Accordingly it will not be possible to represent moral fivedom, except by expressing passion, or suffering nature, with the great- est vividness ; and the hero of tragedy must first have jus- tified his claim to be a sensuous being before aspiring to our homage as a reasonable being, and making us believe in his strength of mind. Therefore the pathetic is the first condition required most strictly in a tragic author, and he is allowed to carry his description of suffering as far as possible, without prejudice -to the highest end of his ((rt, that is, without moral freedom being oppressed by it. He must give in some sort to his hero, as to his reader, their full load of suffering, without which the question will always be put whether the resistance opposed to suffering is an act of the soul, something positive, or whether it is not rather a purely- )ief/ative thing, a simple deflcienc}-. The latter case is offered in the purer French traged}', where it is veiy rare, or perhaps unexampled, for the author to place before the reader suffering nature, and where generall}-, on the contrarj', it is onlj- the poet who warms up and declaims, or the comedian who struts abouv on stilts. The icy tone of declamation extinguishes all nature here, and the French tragedians, with their super- stitious worship of decorum, make it quite impossible for them to paint human nature truly. Decorum, wherever it is, even in its proper place, alwaj's falsifies the expression of nature, and yet this expression is rigorousl}* required by art. In a French tragedy, it is difficult for us to be- lieve that the hero ever suffers, for he explains the state of his soul, as the coolest man would do, and always; thinking of the effect he is making on others, he never lets nature pour forth freely. The kings, the princesses, and ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 151 the heroes of Corneille or Voltaire never forget their ranh even in the most violent excess of passion ; and they part with their hwmanity much sooner than with their dignity. Thej- are like those kings and emperors of our old picture- books, who go to bed with their crowns on. What a difference from the Greeks and those of the moderns who have been inspired with their spirit in poetry ! Never does the Greek poet blush at nature ; he [eaves to the sensuous all its rights, and j-et he is quite certain never to be subdued by it. He has too much depth and too much rectitude in his mind not to distin- guish the accidental, which is the principal point with false taste, from the reallj' necessary ; but all that is not humanity itself is accidental in man. The Greek artist who has to represent a Laocoon, a Niobe, and a Philoc- tetes, does not care for the king, the princess, or the king's son ; he keeps to the man. Accordinglj- the skil- ful statuary sets aside the drapery, and shows us nude figures, though he knows quite well it is not so in real life. This is because drapery is to him an accidental thing, and because the necessary ought never to be sacrificed to the accidental. It is also because, if decencj' and phj'sical necessities have their laws, these laws are not those of art. The statuary ought to show us, and wishes to show us, the man himself ; drapery conceals him, therefore he sets that aside, and with reason. The Greek sculptor rejects draperj' as a useless and embarrassing load, to make way for human nature; and in like manner the Greek poet emancipates the human per- sonages he brings forward from the equallj' useless con- straint of decorum, and all those icy laws of propriety, which put nothing but what is artificial in man, and con- ceal nature in it. Take Homer and the tragedians ; suffer- ing nature speaks the language of truth and ingenuous- ness in their pages, and in a way to penetrate to the depths of our hearts. All the passions play their part freely, nor do the rules of propriety compress any feeling with the Greeks. The heroes are just as much under the influence of suffering as other men, and what makes them heroes is the verj' fact that they feel suffering strongly and deeply, without suffering overcoming them. They 152 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. love life as ardently as others ; but they are not so ruled by this feeling as to be unable to give up life when the duties of honor or humanity call on them to do so. Philoctetes filled the Greek stage with his lamentations ; Hercules himself, when in fury, does not keep under his grief. Iphigenia, on the point of being sacrificed, con- fesses with a touching ingenuousness that she grieves to part with the light of the sun. Never does the Greek place his glory in being insensible or indifferent to suffer- ing, but rather in sxqijyorting it, though feeling it in its fulness. The very gods of the Greeks must pay their tribute to nature, when the poet wishes to make them approximate to humanitj-. Mars, when wounded, roars like ten thousand men together, and Venus, scratched by an iron lance, mounts again to Olympus, weeping, and cursing all battles. This lively susceptibility on the score of suffering, this warm, ingenuous nature, showing itself uncovered and in all truth in the monuments of Greek art, and filling us with such deep and livel}' emotions — this is a model pre- sented for the imitation of all artists ; it is a law which Greek genius has laid down for the fine arts. It is alwaj's and eternallj' nature which has the first rights over man ; she ought never to be fettered, because man, before being anything else, is a sensuous creature. After the rights of nature come those of reaso7i, because man is a rational, sensuous being, a moral person, and because it is a dutj' for this person not to let hmiself be ruled by nature, but to rule her. It is only after satisfaction has been given in the first place to nature, and after reason in the second ■ place has made its rights acknowledged, that it is per- mitted for decorum in the third place to make good its claims, to impose on man, in the expression of his moral feelings and of his sensations, considerations towards society', and to show in it the social being, the civilized man. The first law of the tragic art was to represent suf- fering nature. The second law is to represent the resist- ance of morality opposed to sufl'ering. AflFection, as affection, is an unimportant thing; and the portraiture of affection, considered in itself, would be without anj' lesthetic value ; for, I repeat it, nothing that jEsthetical letters and essays. 153 only interests sensuous nature is worthy of being repre- sented by art. Thus not only the affections that do nothing but enervate and soften man, but in general all affections, even those that are exalted, ecstatic, whatever may be their nature, are beneath the dignity of tragic art. The soft emotions, only producing tenderness, are of the nature of the agreeMe, with which the fine arts are not concerned. They only caress the senses, while relaxing and creating languidness, and only relate to external nature, not at all to the inner nature of man. A good number of our romances and of our tragedies, particularl}- those that bear the name of dramas — a sort of com- promise between tragedy and comedy — -a good number also of those highly-appreciated family portraits, belong to this class. The only effect of these works is to empty the lachrymal duct, and soothe the overflowing feelings ; but the mind comes back from them empty, and the moral being, the noblest part of our nature, gathers no new strength whatever from them, " It is thus," says Kant, "that many persons feel themselves ec?{/fe(/ bj' a sermon that has nothing edifying in it." It seems also that mod- ern music onlj' aims at interesting the sensuous, and in this it flatters the taste of the day, which seeks to be agreeably tickled, but not to be startled, nor strongly moved and elevated. Accordinglj- we see music prefer all that is tender; and whatever be the noise in a concert- room, silence is immediately restored, and every one is all ears directly a sentimental passage is performed. Then an expression of sensibility common to animalism shows itself commonly on all faces ; the eyes are swimming with intoxication, the open mouth is all desire, a voluptuous trembling takes hold of the entire bod3% the breath is quick and full, in short, all the sj'mptoms of intoxication appear. This is an evident proof that the senses swim in delight, but that the mind or the principle of freedom in man has become a prey to the violence of the sensuous impression. Eeal taste, that of noble and manly minds, rejects all these emotions as unworthy of art, because they only please the senses, with which art has nothing in common. But, on the other hand, real taste excludes all extreme l54 JiSTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. affections, which only put sensuousness to the torture^ without giving the mind any compensation. These affee tions oppress moral libertj- hy pain, as the others by volup- tuousness ; consequently they can excite aversion, and not the emotion that would alone be worthj' of art. Art ought to charm the mind and give satisfaction to the feeling of moral freedom. This man who is a prey to his pain is to me simply a tortured animate being, and not a man tried hy suffering. For a moral resistance to pain- ful affections is already required of man — a resistance which can alone allow the principle of moral freedom, the intelligence, to make itself known in it. If it is so, the poets and the artists are poor adepts in their art when they seek to reach the pathetic only bj' the sensuous force of affection and by representing suffering in the most vivid manner. They forget that suffering in itself can never be the last end of imitation, nor the immediate source of the pleasure we experience in traged}'. The pathetic only has sesthetic Aalue in as far as it is subhme. Now, effects that only allow us to infer apurely sensuous cause, and that are founded only on the affection experienced by the faculty' of sense, are never sublime, whatever energy they may display, for everytliing sublime proceeds exclusively from the reason. I imply by passion the affections of pleasure as well as the painful affections, and to represent passion onlj-, with- out coupling with it the expression of the super-sensuous faculty which resists it, is to fall into W'hat is properly called vulgarity; and the opposite is called nobility. Vulgarity a,nd nobility are two ideas which, wherever thej' are applied, have more or less relation with the super- sensuous share a man takes in a work. There is noth- ing noble but what has its source in the reason ; all that issues from sensuousness alone is mdgar or common. We saj- of a man that he acts in a vulgar manner when he is satisfied with obej'ing the suggestions of his sensuous instinct ; that he acts suitably when he onlj' obeys his instinct in conformity with the laws ; that he acts nobly when he obeys reason onlj^ without ha\'ing regard to his instincts. We say of a physiognomy that it is commoji when it does not show anj' trace of the spiritual man, ^STIIETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 155 the intelligence ; we say it has expression when it is the mind which has determined its features : and that it is noble when a pure spirit has determined them. If an architectural work is in question we qualify it as common if it aims at nothing but a ph3-siealend ; we name it noble if, independently of all physical aim, we find in it at the same time the expression of a conception. Accordingly, I repeat -it, correct taste disallows all painting of the affections, however energetic, which rests satisfied with expressing physical suffering and the physi- cal resistance opposed to it hj the subject, without making visible at the same time the superior principle of the nature of man, the presence of a super-sensuous faculty. It does this in virtue of the principle developed farther back, namel}', that it is not suffering in itself, but only the resistance opposed to suffering, that is pathetic and de- serving of being represented. It is for this reason that all the absolutely extreme degrees of the affections are forbidden to the artist as well as to the poet. All of these, in fact, oppress the force that resists from within : or rather, all betray of themselves, and without any neces- sit}' of other symptoms, the oppression of this force, because no affection can reach this last degree of intensity as long as the intelligence in man makes any resist- ance. Then another question presents itself. How is this principle of resistance, tMs super-sensuous force, mani- fested in the phenomenon of the affections? Only in one way, by mastering or, more commonly, by combating affec- tion. I saj' affection, for sensuousness can also fight, but this combat of sensuousness is not carried on with 'the affection, but with the cause that produces it ; a contest which has no moral character, but is all phj'sical, the same combat that the earthworm, trodden under foot, and the wounded bull engage in, without thereby exciting the pa- thetic. When suffering man seeks to give an expression to his feelings, to remove his enemy, to shelter the suffer- ing limb, he does all this in common with the animals, and instinct alone takes the initiative here, without the will being applied to. Therefore, this is not an act that ema- nates from the man himself, nor does it show him as an 156 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. intelligence. Sensuous nature will always fight the enemy that makes it suffer, but it will never fight against itself. On the other hand, the contest with affection is a con- test with sensuousness, and consequently presupposes something that is distinct from sensuous nature. Man can defend himself with the help of common sense and his muscular strength against the object that makes him suffer ; against suffering itself he has no other arms than those of reason. These ideas must present themselves to the eye in the portraiture of the affections, or be awakened by this por- traiture in order that the pathetic may exist. But it is impossible to represent ideas, in the proper sense of the word, and positively, as nothing corresponds to pure ideas in the world of sense. But thej- can be alwaj's represented negatively and in an indirect way if the sensuous phenom- enon by which they are manifested has some character of which you would seek in vain the conditions in physical nature. All phenomena of which the ultimate principle cannot be derived from the world of sense are an indirect representation of the upper-sensuous element. And how does one succeed in representing something that is above nature without having recourse to super- natural means ? What can this phenomenon be which is accomplished by natural forces — otherwise it would not be a phenomenon — and j^et which cannot be derived from physical causes without a contradiction? This is the problem ; how can the artist solve it ? It must be remembered that the phenomena observable in a man in a state of passion are of two kinds. They are either phenomena connected simply with animal nature, and which, therefore, only obey the physical law, without the will being able to master them, or the independent force in him being able to exercise an immediate influence over them. It is the instinct which immediately produces these phenomena, and they obey blindly the laws of in- stinct. To this kind belong, for example, the organs of the circulation of the blood, of respiration, and all the sur- face of the skin. But, moreover, the other organs, and those subject to the will, do not always await the decision ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 157 of the will ; and often instinct itself sets them immediate!}- in play, especiallj- when the physical state is threatened with pain or with danger Thus, the movements of m\- arm depend, it is true, on my will ; but if I place my hand, without knowing it, on a burning bodj', the movement by which I draw it back is certainly not a voluntarj- act, but a purely instinctive phenomenon. Nay more, speech is assuredly subject to the empire of tlie will, and yet instinct can also dispose of this organ according to its whim, and even of this and of the mind, without cunsulting before- hand the will, directly a sharp pain, or even an energetic affection, takes us bj- surprise. Take the most impassil le stoic and make him see suddenly' something ver^- wonder- ful, or a terrible and unexpected object. Fanc}- him, for example, present when a man .slips and falls to the bottom of an abyss. A shout, a resounding crj-, and not only inarticulate, but a distinct word will escape his lips, and nature will have acted in him before the will : a certain proof that there arc in man phenomena which cannot be referred to his person as an intelligence, but only to his instinct as a natural force. But there is also in man a second order of phenomena, which are subject to the influence and empire of the will, or which may be considered at all events as being of such a kind that will might always have prevented tbem, conse- quentl}' phenomena for which the person, and not instinct is responsible. It is the office of instinct to watch with a blind zeal over the interests of the senses ; but it is the office of the person to hold instinct in proper bounds, out of respect for the moral law. Instinct in itself does not hold account of any law ; but the person ought to watch that instinct may not infringe in an}' way on the decrees of reason. It is therefore evident that it is not for instinct alone to determine unconditionall}- all the phenomena that take place in man in the state of affection, and that on the contrary the will of man can place limits to instinct. When instinct onlj' determines all phenomena in man, there is nothing more that can recall the person; there is onh' a phj'sical creature before you, and consequentlj' an animal ; for every physical creature subject to the sway of instinct is nothing else. Therefore, if you wish to repre- 158 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. sent the person itself, you must propose to yourself in man certain phenomena that have been determined in oppo- sition to instinct, or at least that have not been determined by instinct. That they have not been determined by in- stinct is sufficient to refer them to a higher source, the moment we see that instinct would no doubt have deter- mined them in another way if its force had not been broken by some obstacle. We are now in a position to point out in what way the super-sensuous element, the moral and independent force of man, his Ego in short, can be represented in the phe- nomena of the affections. I understand that this is possible if the parts which only obey physical nature, tliose where will either disposes nothing at all, or only under certain circumstances, betray the presence of suffer- ing ; and if those, on the contrary, that escape the blind swiiy of instinct, that only obey physical nature, show no trace, or only a very feeble trace, of suffering, and con- sequenth' appear to have a certain degree of freedom. Now this want of harmony between the features imprinted on animal nature in virtue of the laws of phj-sical necessity, and those determined with the spiritual and independent faculty of man, is precisely tlae point bv which that super- sensuous principle is discovered in man capable of placing limits to the effects produced by physical nature, and therefore distinct from the latter. The purelj- animal part of man obeys the physical law, and consequent!}' ma}' show itself oppressed by the affection. It is, therefore, in this part that all the strength of passion shows itself, and it answers in some degree as a measure to estimate the resistance — that is to sa}^ of the energ}- of the moral faculty in man — which can only be judged according to the force of the attack. Thus in proportion as the affec- tion manifests itself with decision and violence in the field of animal iMtare, without being able to exercise the same power in the field of human nature, so in proportion tlie latter makes itself manifestly known — in the same proportion the moral independence of man shows itself gloi-iously : the portraiture becomes pathetic tind the pa- thetic sublime. The statues of the ancients miike this principle of ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 159 sesyietics sensible to us ; but it is difficult to reduce to conceptions and express in words what the ver\- inspection of ancient statues makes the senses feel in so lively a manner. The group of Laocoon and his children can give • to a great extent the measure of what the plastic art of the ancients was capable of producing in the matter of pa- thos. Winckelmann, in his "History of Art," saj-s : " Laocoon is nature seized in the highest degree of suffer- ing, under the features of a man who seeks to gather up against pain all the strength of which the mind is con- scious. Hence while his suffering swells his muscles and stretches his nerves, the mind, armed with an interior force shows itself on his contracted brow, and the breast rises, because the breathing is broken, and because there is an internal struggle to keep in the expression of pain, and press it back into his heart. The sigh of anguish he wishes to keep in, his very breath which he smothers, ex- haust the lower ^ part of his trunk, and works into his flanks, which make us judge in some degree of the palpi- tations of his visceral organs. But his own suffering appears to occasion less anguish than the pain of his children, who turn their faces toward their father, and implore him, crying for help. His father's heart shows itself in his e3'es, full of sadness, and where pitj' seems to swim in a troubled cloud. His face expresses lament, but he does not cry ; his e3'es are turned to heaven, and implore help from on high. Hi^mouth also marks a supreme sad- ness, which depresses the lower lip and seems to weigh upon it, while the upper lip, contracted from the top to the bottom, expresses at once both physical suffering and that of the soul. Under the mouth there is an expression of indignation that seems to protest against an undeserved suffering, and is revealed in the nostrils, which swell out and enlarge and draw upwards. Under the forehead, the struggle between pain and moral strength, united as it were in a single point, is represented with great truth, for, while pain contracts and raises the eyebrows, the effort op- posed to it by the will draws down towards the upper eye- lid all the nu5scles above it, so that the eyelid is almo=<- covered by them. The artist, not being able to embellisli nature, has sought at least to develop its means, to increase 160 JESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. its effect and power. Where is the greatest amount of pain is also the highest beauty. The left side, which the serpent besets with liis furious bites, and where he in- stils his poison, is that which appears to suffer the most intensel}-, because sensation is there nearest to the heart. The legs strive to raise themselves as if to shun the evil ; the whole bod3- is nothing but movement, and even the traces of the chisel contribute to the illusion ; we seem to see the shuddering and icj'-cold skin." How great is the truth and acuteness of this analysis ! In what a superior stj'le is this struggle between spirit and the suffering of nature developed ! How correctly the author has seized each of the phenomena in which the animal element and the human element manifest them- selves, the constraint of nature and the independence of reason ! It is well known that Virgil has described this same scene in his "^neid," but it did not enter into the plan of the epic poet to pause as the sculptor did, and describe the moral nature of Laocoon ; for this recital is in Virgil onl}' an episode ; and the object he proposes is sufflcientlj' attained bj' the simple description of the phy- sical phenomenon, without the necessity on his part of looking into the soul of the unhappj- sufferer, as his aim is less to inspire us with pity than to fill us with terror. The dutj- of the poet from this point of view was purelj- negative ; I mean he had only to avoid carrying the pic- ture of phj-sical suffering to such a degree that all expres- sion of human dignitj' or of moral resistance would cease, for if he had done this indignation and disgust would certainly be felt. He, therefore, preferred to confine him- self to the representation of the least of the suffering, and he found it advisable to dwell at length on the formida- ble nature of the two serpents, and on the rage with which thej- attack their victims, rather than on the feelings of Laocoon. He only skims over those feelings, because his first object was to represent a chastise- ment sent by the gods, and to produce an impres- sion of terror that nothing could diminish. If he had, on the contrary, detained our looks on the person of Laocoon himself with as much perseverance as the statu- ary-, instead of on the chastizing deity, the suffering man ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 161 would have become the hero of the scene, and the episode would have lost its propriety in connection with the whole piece. The narrative of Virgil is well known through the ex- cellent commentarj' of Lessing. But Lessing only pro- posed to make evident by this example the limits that separate partial description from painting, and not to make the notion of the pathetic issue from it. Yet the passage of Virgil does not appear to me less valuable for this latter object, and I crave permission to bring it for- ward again under this point of view : — Ecce autem "femini Tenedo tranquilla per alta (Hoi'i'esco referens) immensis orbibus angues Incumbunt pelago, pariterque ad litora tendunt; Pectora quoi'um inter tiuctus arrecta juba^que Sanjruinse exsuperaiit undas ; pars esetera pontum Pone legit, sinuatque immensa volumine terga. Fit sonitus spumaute salo, jamque arva tenebant, Ardentes oculos suffecti sanguine et i^ni, Sibila lambebant Unguis vibrantibus ora ! ^neid, ii. 203-211. We find here realized the fi.rstof the three conditions of the sublime that have been mentioned further back, — a very powerful natural force, armed for destruction, and ridiculing all resistance. But that this strong element may at the same time be terrible, and thereby sahlime, two distinct operations of the miud are wanted ; I mean two representations that we produce in ourselves by our own activitj'. First, we recognize this irresistible natural force as terrible by comparing it with the weakness of the faculty of resistance that the physical man can oppose to it; and, secondly, it is by referring it to our will, and recalHng to our consciousness that the will is abso- lutely independent of all influence of physical nature, that this force iDCComes to us a sublime object. But it is we ourselves who represent these two relations ; the poet has onlj' given us an object armed with a great force seeking to manifest itself. If this object makes us tremble, it is onl}- because we in thought suppose ourselves, or some one Mke us, engaged with this force. And if trembling in this way, we experience the feeling of the sublime, it is because our consciousness tells us that, if we are the vie- 162 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. tims of this force, we should have nothing to fear, from the freedom of our Ego, .for the autonomy of the deter- minations of our will. In short the description up to here is subhme, but quite a contemplative, intuitive sublimity : — Diffugimus visu exsangues, illi agmine certo Laocoonta petunt ... — ^neid, ii. 212-213. Here the force is presented to us as terrible also ; and contemplative sublimity passes into the pathetic. We see that force enter really into strife with man's impotence. Whether it concerns Laocooh or ourselves is only a ques- tion of degree. The instinct of sympatliy excites and frightens in us the instinct of preservation : there are the monsters, they are darting — on ourselves ; there is no more safety, flight is vain. It is no more in our power to measure this force with ours, and to refer it or not to our own existence. This happens without our co-operation, and is given us by the object itself. Accordingly our fear has not, as in the preceding moment, a purely subjective ground, residing in our soul ; it has an objective ground, residing in the object. For, even if we recognize in this entire scene a simple Action of the imagination, we nevertheless distin- guish in this fiction a conception communicated to us from without, from another conception that we produce spon- taneously in ourselves. Thus the mind loses a part of her freedom, inasmuch as she receives now from without that which she produced before her own activitj'. The idea of danger puts on an appearance of objective reality, and affection becomes now a serious affair. If we were only sensuous creatures, obeying no other instinct than that of self-preservation, we should stop here, and we should remain in a state of mere and pure affec- tion. But there is something in us which takes no part in the affections of sensuous nature, and whose activity is not directed according to physical conditions. According, then, as this independently acting principle (the disposi- tion, the moral faculty) has become to a degree developed in the soul, there is left more or less space for passive ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 163 nature, and there remains more or less of the independent principle in the affection. In the truly moral soul the terrible trial (of the imagination) passes quickly and readily into the sub- lime. In proportion as imagination loses its liberty, rea- son makes its own prevail, and the soul ceases not to enlarge within when it thus finds outward limits. Driven from all tlie intrenchments which would give phjsical pro- tection to sensuous creatures, we seek refuge in the stronghold of our moral liberty, and we arrive b}- that means at an absolute and unlimited safety-, at the very moment when we seem to be deprived in the world of phenomena of 'a relative and precarious rampart. But precisely because it was necessarj' to ha\e arrived at tlie physical oppression before having recourse to the assist- ance of our moral nature, we can only buj' this high senti- ment of our liberty through suffering. An ordinary soul confines itself entirely to this suffering, and never com- prehends in the sublime or the pathetic anything beyond the terrible. An independent soul, on the contrar}-, pre- cisely- seizes this occasion to rise to the feeling of his moral force, in all that is most magnificent in this force, and from everj- terrible object knows how to draw out the sublime. The moral man (the father*) is here attacked before the physical man, and that has a grand effect. All the affec- tions become more aesthetic when we receive them second- hand ; there is no stronger sj-mpath^' than that we feel for sympathy-. t The moment had arrived when the hero himself had to be recommended to our respect as a moral personage, and the poet seized upon that moment. We alread3- know- by his description all the force, all the rsge of the two monsters'who menace Laocoon, and we know how all re- sistance would be in vain. If Laocoon were oiily a com- mon man he would better understand his own interests, and, like the rest of the Trojans, he would find safet}' in rapid flight. But there is a heart in that breast ; the danger to his children holds him back, and decides him to meet his fate. This trait alone renders him worthj' of our * See ".^Eneid, ' ii. 213-215. t Ibid, 216-217. 164 ^.STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. pity. A.t whatever moment the serpents had assailed him, we should have always been touched and troubled. But because it happens just at the moment when as father he shows himself so worthj' of respect, his fate appears to us as the result of having fulfilled his duty as parent, of his tender disquietude for his children. It is ths which calls forth our sympathj' in the highest degree. It appears, in fact, as if he deliberatel}- devoted himself to destruction, and his death becomes an act of the will. Thus there are two conditions in everj' kind of the pathetic : 1st. Suffering, to interest our sensuous nature ; 2d. Moral liberty, to interest our spiritual nature. All l)(>rtr:iitMre in which the expression of suffering nature is wanting remains without aesthetic action, and our heart is untouclied. AIJ. portraiture in which the expression of moral aptitude is wanting, even did it possess all the sen- suoui force possible, could not attain to the pathetic, and would infallibly revolt our feelings. Throughout moral liberty we require the human being who suffers ; through- out all tlie sufferings of human nature we alwaj'S desire to perceive the independent spirit, or the capacity for inde- pendence. But the independence of the spiritual being in the state of suffering can manifest itself in two ways. JCither neg- atively, when the moral man does not receive the law from the phj'sical man, and his state exercises no influence over l>is manner of feeling ; or positivelj", when the moral man is a ruler over the physical being, and his manner of feel- ing exercises an influence upon his state. In the first case, it is the sublime of disposition ; in the second, it is the sublime of action. The sublime of disposition is seen in all character inde- pendent of the accidents of fate. " A noble heart strug- gling against adversity," says Seneca, " is a spectacle full of attraction even for the gods." Such for example is that which the Roman Senate ofi'ered after the disaster of Cannas. Lucifer even, in Milton, when for the first time he contemplates hell — which is to be his future abode — penetrates us with a sentiment of admiration by the force of soul he displays : — JESTHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 165 " Hail, horrors, hail . Infernal world, and thou, profoundest Hell; Eeceive thy new possessor! — one who brings A mind not to be clianged by place or time; The mind is its own place, and in itself Can make a Heaven of Plell Here at least We shall be free,'' &c. The repl}' of Medea in the tragedy belongs also to this order of the sublime. The sublime of disposition makes itself seen, it is visible to the spectator, because it rests upon co-existence, the. simultaneous ; the sublime action, on the contrary, is conceived only bij the thought, because the impression and the act are successive, and the intervention of the mind is necessary to. infer from a free determination the idea of previous suffering. It follows that the first alone can be expressed by the plastic arts, because these arts give but that which is simultaneous ; but the poet can extend his domain over one and the other. Even more ; when the plastic art has to represent a sublime action, it must necessaril}' bring it bade to sublimitj'. In order that the sublimity of action should take place, not only must the suffering of man have no influence upon the moral constitution, but rather the opposite must be the case. The affection is the work of his moral character. This can happen in two wajs : either mediatelj', or ac- cording to the law of nbertj-, when out of respect for such and such a duty it decides from free choice to suffer — in this case, the idea of duty determines as a motive, and its suffering is a voluntarj^ act — or immediately', and accord- ing to the necessity of nature, when he expiates by a moral suffering the violation of dutj- ; in this second case, the idea of duty determines him as a force, and his suffer- ing is no longer an effect. Regiilus offers us an example of the first kind, when, to keep his word, he gives himself up to the vengeance of the Carthaginians ; and he would serve as an example of the second class, if, having betrayed his trust, the consciousness of this crime would have made him miserable. In both cases suffering has amoral course, but with this difference, that on the one part Eegulus shows 166 JESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. US its moral cluxracter, and that, on the other, he onl}', shows us that he was made to have such a character. In the first case he is in our eyes a morall\- great person ; in the second he is onlj- ajstlietically great. Tliis last distinction is important for the tragic art ; it consequently deserves to be examined uiore closely. Man is alread}- a sublime object, but onlj- in the aes- thetic sense, when the utate in which he is gives us an idea of his human destination, even though we might not find this destination realized in his person. He onl}' becomes sublime to us in a moral point of view, when he -acts, moreover, as a person, in a manner conformable with this destination ; if our respect bears not onl}- on his moral faculty, but on the use he makes of this faculty ; if dig- nity, in his case, is due, not onlj' to his moral aptitude, but to the real morality of his conduct. It is quite a dif- ferent thing to direct our judgment and attention to the moral faculty generally, and to the possibilitj' of a will absolutely free, and to be directing it to the use of this facultv, and to the realit}' of this absolute freedom of willing. It is, I repeat, quite a difl!erent thing ; and this difl'er- ence is connected not onh- with the olijects to which we maj' have to direct our judgment, but to the very criterion of our judgment. The same object can displease us if we appreciate it in a moral point of view, and be very attract- ive to us in the sesthetical point of view. But even if the moral judgment and the sesthetical judgment were both satisfied, this object would produce this effect on one and the other in quite a different way. It is not morallj- satis- factory because it has an sesthetical value, nor has it an cesthetical value because it satisfies us morally. Let us take, as example, Leonidas and his devotion at Therm.op- j'lse. Judged from the moral point of view, this action represents to me the moral law carried out notwithstanding all the repugnance of instinct. Judged from the testhetic point of view, it gives me the idea of the moral facultv, independent of every constraint of instinct. The act of Leonidas satinfen the moral sense, the reason ; it enrap' tures the sesthetical sense, the imagination. iESTHETICAL I-ETTEItS AND ESSAYS. 167 Whence comes this difference in tlie feelings in connec- tion witli the same object? I account for it thus : — In tlie sjime way that our being consists of two princi- ples and natures, so also and consequently our feelings are divided into two kinds, entirely different. As reason- able beings we experience a feeling of approbation or of disapprobation ; as sensuous creatures we experience pleasure or displeasure. The two feelings, approbation and pleasure, repose on satisfaction : one on a satisfaction given to a requirement of reason — reason has onlj' re- quirements, and not wants. The other depends on a sat- isfaction given to a sensuous want — sense only knows of wants, and cannot prescribe anjthing Tliese two terms — requirements of reason, wants of the senses — are mutually related, as absolute necessity and the necessity of nature. Accordingly', both are included in the idea of necessity, but with this difference, that the necessity of reason is unconditional, and the necessity of sense only takes place under conditions. But, for both, satisfaction is a purely contingent thing. Accordingl}- every feeling, whether of pleasure or approbation, rests definitivel3' on an agreement between the contingent and the necessary. If the necessary has thus an imperative character, the feeling experienced will be that of approbation. If necessity has the character of a want, the feeling experienced will be that of pleasure, and both will be strong in proportion as the satisfaction will be cjpntingent. Now, underlying every moral judgment there is a requirement of reason which requires us to act conforma"bly with the moral law, and it is an absolute necessity that we should wish what is good. But as the will is free, it is physical!}' an accidental thing that we should do in fact what is g'ood. If we actually do it, this agreement between the contingent in tlie use of free will and the imperative demand of reason gives rise to our assent or approbation, which will be greater in pro- portion as the resistance of the inclinations made this use that we make of our free will more accidental and more doubtful. Every gesthetic judgment, on the contrary, refers the object to the necessit}' which cannot help will- ing imperatively, but only desires that there should be an agreement between the accidental and its own interest. 168 jESThexioal letters and essays. Now what is the interest of imagination? It is to emancipate itself (Voui all laws, and to play its part freely. The obligation imposed on the will by the moral law, which prescribes it.s object in the strictest manner, is by no means favorable to this need of independence. And as the moral obligation of the will is the object of the moral judgment, it is clear that in this mode of judging, the imagination could not find its interest. But a moral obligation imposed on the will cannot be conceived, ex- cept by supposing this same will absolutely independent of the moral instincts and from their constraint. Accord- ingly the possihilitij of the moral act requires liberty, and therefore agrees here in the most perfect manner with the interest of imagination. But as invagination, through the medium of its wants, cannot give orders to the will of the individual, as reason does by its imperative character, it follows that the faculty of freedom, in relation to imagi- nation, is something accidental, and consequently that the agreement between the accidental and the necessary (con- ditionally necessary) must excite pleasure. Therefore, if we bring to bear a moral judgment on this act of Leoni- das, we shall consider it from a point of view where its accidental character strikes the eye less than its necessary side. If, on the other hand, we apply the cesthetical judg- ment to it, this is another point of view, where its charac- ter of necessity strikes us less forcibly than its accidental character. It is a duty for every will to act thus, directly it is a free will ; but the fact that there is a free will that makes this act possible is a favor of nature in regard to this faculty, to which freedom is a necessity. Thus an act of virtue judged by the moral sense — by reason — will give us as its onlj- satisfaction the feeling of approbation, because reason can never find iixjre, and seldom finds as much as it requires. This same act, judged, on the con- trary, by the »sthetic sense — by imagination — will give us a positive pleasure, because the imagination, never re- quiring the end to agree with the demand, must be sur- prised, enraptured, at the real satisfaction of this demand as at a happj' chance. Our reason will merely approve, and only approve, of Leonidas actually taking this heroic resolution; but that he cr^^A? take this resolution is what delights and enraptures iis. iKSTHETIOAL LETXEKB AND ESSAYS, 169 This distinction between the two sorts of jurlgments becomes more evident still, if we take an example where the moral sense and the aesthetic sense pronounce a differ- ent verdict. Suppose we take the act of Perigrinus Pro- teus burning himself at Olympia. Judging this act morally, I cannot give it mj- approbation, inasmuch as I see it determined by impure motives, to which Proteus sacrifices the duty of respecting his own existence. But in the aesthetic judgment this same act delights me ; it delights me precisely because it testifies to a power of will capable of resisting even the most potent of instincts, that of self-preservation. "Was it a moral feeling, or only a more powerful sensuous attraction, that silenced the instinct of self-preservation in this enthusiast. It matters little, when I appreciate the act from an aesthetic point of view. I then drop the individual, I take awa}- the relation of his will to the law that ought to govern him ; I think of human will in general, considered as a common faculty of the race, and I regard it in connection with all the forces of nature. We have seen that in a moral point of view, the preservation of our being seemed to us a duty, and therefore we were ofl'ended at seeing Proteus violate this duty. In an aesthetic point of view the self-preservation only appears as an interest, and therefore the sacrifice of this interest pleases us. Thus the operation that we perform in the judgments of the second kind is precisel3' the inverse of that whicU we perform in those of the first. In the former we oppose the individual, a sensuous and limited being, and his personal will, which can be effected pathologicall}', to the absolute law of the will in general, and of unconditional dut}- which binds every spiritual being ; in the second case, on the contrary, we oppose the faculty of willing, absolute volition, and the spiritual force as an infinite thing, to the solicitations of nature and the impediments of sense. This is the reason why the aes- thetical judgment leaves us free, and delights and enrap- tures us. It is because the mere conception of this faculty of willing in an absolute manner, the mere idea of this moral aptitude, gives us in itself a consciousness of a manifest advantage over the sensuous. It is because the mere possibility of emancipating ourselves from the imped- 170 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. iments of nature is in itself a satisfaction tliat flatters our thirst for freedom. Tliis is tiie reason wiiy moral judgment, on the contrary, makes us experience a feeling of constraint that humbles ns. It is because in connection with each voluntarj' act we appreciate in this manner, we feel, as regards the absolute law that ought to rule the will in gen- eral, in a position of inferiority more or less decided, and because the constraint of the will thus limited to a single determination, which duty requires of it at all costs, con- tradicts the instinct of freedom which is the property of imagination. In the former case we soared from the real to the possible, and from the individual to the species ; in the latter, on the contrary, we descend from the possible to the real, and we shut up the species in the narrow limits of the individual. We cannot therefore be surprised if the sesthetical judgment enlarges the heart, while the moral judgment constrains and straitens it. It results, therefore, from all that which precedes, that the moral judgment and the aesthetic, far from mutlially corroborating each other, impede and hinder each other, because they impress on the soul two directions entirely opposite. In fact, this observance of rule which reason requires of us as moral judge is incompatible with the independence which the imagination calls for as aesthetic judge. It follows that an object will have so much the less aesthetic value the more it has the character of a moral object, and if the poet were obliged notwithstanding that to choose it, he would do well in treating of it, not to call the attention of our reason to the rule of the will, but that of our imagination to the power of the will. In his own interest it is necessar3' for the poet to enter on this path, for with our liberty- his empire finishes. We belong to him only inasmuch as we look beyond ourselves ; we escape from him the moment we re-enter into our inner- most selves, and that is what infallibly takes place the moment an object ceases to be a phenomenon in our consideration, and takes the character of a law which judges us. • Even in the manifestation of the most sublime virtue, the poet can onl}^ emploj' for his own views that which in those acts belongs to force. As to the direction of the JESTHKTICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 171 force, he has no reason to be anxious. The poet, even when he places before our e3'es the most perfect models of morality, has not, and ought not to have, any other end than that of rejoicing our soul bj' the contemplation of this spectacle. • Moreover, nothing can rejoice our soul except that which improves our personality, and nothing can give us a spiritual joy except that which elevates the spiritual faculty. But in what way can the morality of another improve our own personality-, and raise our spir- itual force? That this other one accomplishes really his duty results from an accidental use which he makes of his liberty, and which for that ver}' reason can prove nothing to us. We onlj' have in common with him the facult}' to conform ourselves equally to duty ; the moral power which he exhibits reminds us also of our own, and that is why we then feel something which upraises our spiritual force. Thus it is onl}' the idea of the possibility of an absolutely free will which makes the real exercise of this will in us charming to the aesthetic feeling. We shall be still more convinced when we think how little the poetic force of impression which is awakened in us by an act or a moral character is dependent on their historic realitj'. The pleasure which we take in consid- ering an ideal character will in no way be lessened when we come to think that this character is nothing more than a poetic fiction ; for it is on the poetic truth, and not on historic truth, that everj- Aesthetic impression of the feel- ings rest. Moreover, poetic truth does not consist in that this or that thing has effectuallj' taken place, but in that it may have happened, that is to say, that the thing is in itself possible. Thus the aesthetic force is necessarily obliged to rest in the first place in the idea of possibilit3-. Even in real subjects, for which the actors are borrowed from hlstorj-, it is not the realitj- of the simple possibility of the fact, but that which is guaranteed to us by its very reality which constitutes the poetic element. That these personages have indeed existed, and that these events have in truth taken place, is a circumstance which can, it is true, in many cases add to our pleasure, but that which it adds to it is like a foreign addition, much rather unfavorable than advantageous to the poetical impression. 172 ^STHETIOAL LETTEBS AND ESSAYS. It was long thought that a great service was rendered to German poetry by recommending German poets to treat of national themes. Why, it was asked, did Greek poetry have so much power over the mind ? Because it brought forward national events and immortalized domestic ex- ploits. No doubt the poetry of the ancients may have been inj grace. But a great difficulty now presents itself from the idea alone of the expressive movements which bear witness to the morality of the subject : it appears that the cause of anO ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. these uiovemetits is necessarih' a moral cause, a principle which resides bej'oiid the world of sense ; and from the sole idea of beauty it is not less c\ident that its principle is piirel}' sensuous, and that it ought to be a simple effect of natui-e, or at the least appear to be such. But if the ultimate reason of the movements which offer a moral ex- pression is necessarily without, and the ultimate reason of the beautiful necessarily witldii, the sensuous world, it ap- pears that f/race, which ought to unite both of them, con- tains a manifest contradiction. To avoid this contradiction we must admit that the moral cause, which in our soul is the foundation of grace, brings, in a necessarj- manner, in the sensibilit}' which de- pends on that cause, preciselj' that state which contains in itself the natural conditions of beaut}'. I will explain. The beautiful, as each sensuous phenomenon, supposes certain conditions, and, in as far as it is beautiful, these are purely- conditions of the senses ; well, then, in that the mind (in virtue of a law that we cannot fathom) , from the state in which it is, itself prescribes to physical nature which accompanies it, its own state, and in that the state of moral perfection is precisely in it the most favorable for the accomplishment of the physical conditions of beautj', it follows that it is the mind which renders beauty possible ; and there its action ends. But whether real beauty comes forth from it, that depends upon the phj'sical conditions alluded to, and is consequently a free effect of nature. Therefore, as it cannot be said that nature is properly free in the voluntary movements, in which it is emploj-ed but as a means to attain an end, and as, on the other side, it cannot be said that it is free in its involun- tary movements, which express the moral, the liberty with which it manifests itself, dependent as it is on the will of the subject, must be a concession that the mind makes to nature ; and, consequently, it can be said that grace is a favor in which the moral has desired to gratify the sen- suous element ; the same as the architectonic beautj' maj' be considered as nature acquiescing to the technical form. Maj' I be permitted a comparison to clear up this point? Let us suppose a monarchical state administered in such a way that, although all goes on according to the will of one iESTHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAY8. 201 person, each citizen could persuade himself that he governs and obe3S onlj- his own inclination, we should call that government a liberal government. But we should look twice before we should thus qualify a government in which the cliief makes his will outweigh the wishes of the citizens, or a government in which the will of the citizens outweighs that of the chief. In the first case, the government would be no more liberal ; in the second, it would not be a government at all. It is not difficult to make application of these examples to what the human face could be under the government of the mind. If the mind is manifested in such a way through the sensuous nature subject to its empire that it executes its behests with the most faithful exactitude, or expresses its sentiments in the most perfectly speaking manner, without going in the least against that which the aesthetic sense demands from it as a phenomenon, then we shall see produced that which we call grace. But this is far from being grace, if mind is manifested in a con- strained manner hy the sensuous nature, or if sensuous nature acting alone in all liberty the expression of moral nature was absent. In the first case there would not be beauty ; in the second the beautj' would be devoid oiplatj. The super-sensuous cause, therefore, the cause of which the principle is in the soul, can alone render grace speak- ing, and it is the purely sensuous cause having its princi- ple in nature which along can render it beautiful. We are not more authorized in asserting that mind engenders beauty than we should be, in the foi-mer example, in main- taining that the chief of the state produces liberty ; be- cause we can indeed leave a man in his libertj-, but not give it to him. But just as when a people feels itself free under the constraint of a foreign will. It is in a great degree due to the sentiments animating the prince ; and as this liberty would run great risks if the prince took opposite senti- ments, so also it is in the moral dispositions of the mind which suggests them that we must seek the beaut}- of free movements. And now the question which is presented is this one : What then are the conditions of personal morality which assure the utmost amount of liberty to the sensuous 202 jESthetical letters and essays. instruments of the will? and what are the moral senti- ments which agree the best in their expression with the beautiful? That which is evident is that neither the will, in the intentional movement, nor the passion, in the sympathetic movement, ought to act as a force with regard to the physical nature which is subject to it, in order that this, in obeying it, may have beautj'. In truth, without going further, common seuse considers ease to be the first requisite of grace. It is not less evident that, on another side, nature ought not to act as a force with regard to mind, m order to give occasion for a fine moral expression ; for there, where physical nature commands alone, it is absolutely necessar}- that the character of the man should vanish. We can conceive three sorts of relation of man with himself: I mean the sensuous part of man with the rea- sonable part. From these three relations we have to seek which is that one which best suits him in the sensuous world, and the expression of which constitutes the beau- tiful. Either man enforces silence upon the exigencies of his sensuous nature, to govern himself conformably with the superior exigencies of his reasonable nature ; or else, on the contrary, he subjects the reasonable portion of his being to the sensuous part, reducing himself thus to obey only the impulses which the necessity of nature imprints upon him, as well as upon the other phenomena ; or lastly, harmony is established between the impulsions of the one and the laws of the other, and man is in perfect accord with himself. If he has the consciousness of his spiritual person, of his pure autonony, man rejects all that is sensuous, and it is only when thus isolated from matter that he feels to the full his moral libert}-. But for that, as his sensuous nature opposes an obstinate and vigorous resistance to him, he must, on his side, exercise upon it a notable pressure and a strong effort, without which he could neither put aside the appetites nor reduce to silence the enegetic voice of instinct. A mind of this quality makes the phj-sical nature which depends on him feel that it has a master in him, whether it fulfils the orders of the will or endeavors to anticipate them. Under its stern dis- ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 20& cipline sensuousness appears then repressed, and interior resistance will betra}' itself exteriorly by the constraint. This moral state cannot, then, be favorable to beauty', because nature cannot produce the beautiful but as far as it is free, and cousequentlj' that which betrays to us the struggles of moral liberty against matter cannot either be grace. If, on the contrary, subdued bj' its wants, man allows himself to be governed without reserve by the instinct of nature, it is his interior autonomy that vanishes, and with it all trace of this autonomy is exteriorl}- effaced. The animal nature is alone visible upon his visage ; the e^'e is watery and languishing, the mouth rapaciously open, the voice trembling and muffled, the breathing short and rapid, the limbs trembling with nervous agitation : the whole bodj' b^- its languor betra3-s its moral degradation. Moral force has renounced all resistance, and physical nature, with such a man, is placed in full liberty. But precisely this complete abandonment of moral independ- ence, which occurs ordinaril3' at the moment of sensuous desiie, and more still at the moment of enjoyment, sets sud- denly brute matter at liberty which until then had been kept in equilibrium b}' the active and passive forces. The inert forces of nature commence from thence to gain the upper hand over the living forces of the organism ; the form is oppressed by matter, humanity by common nature. The e^-e, in whi\ obtain- ing the closest connection between the conceptions forming 236 ^SXHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. the spiritual part of the discourse, while the perceptions, corresponding to them and forming the sensuous part of the discourse, appear to cohere merely through an arbitrary play of the fancy. If an inquiry be instituted into the magic influence of a beautiful diction, it will always be found that it consists in this happy relation between external freedom and internal uecessit3'. The principal features that contribute to this freedom of the imagination are the individualizing of ob- jects and the figurative or inexact expression of a thing; the former employed to give force to its sensuousness, the latter to produce it where it does not exist. When we ex- press a species or kind by an individual, and portray a conception in a single case, we remove from fancy the chains which the understanding has placed upon her and give her the power to act as a creator. Always grasping at completely' determinate images, the imagination obtains and exercises the right to complete according to her wish the image afforded to her, to animate it, to fashion it, to follow it in all the associations and transformations of which it is capable. She may forget for a moment her subordinate position, and act as an independent power, only self-directing, because the strictness of the inner concatenation has sufficiently guarded against her breaking loose from the control of the understanding. An inexact or figurative expression adds to the libertj', hy associating ideas which in their nature differ essentially from one another, but which unite in subordination to the higher idea. The imagination adheres to the concrete object, the understanding to this higher idea, and thus the former finds movement and variety even where the other verifies a most perfect continuity. The conceptions are developed according to the law of necessity, but they pass before the imagination according to the law of liberty. Thought remains the same ; the medium that represents it is the only thing that changes. It is thus that an elo- quent writer knows how to extract the most splendid order from the verj' centre of anarch3', and that he succeeds in erecting a solid structure on a constantly moving ground, on the verj' torrent of imagination. If we compare together scientific statement or address, ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 237 popular address, and fine language, it is seen directly that all three express the idea with an equal faithfulness as re- gards the matter, and consequently that all three help us to acquire knowledge, but that as regards the mode and degree of this knowledge a ver3- marked difference exists between them. The writer who uses the language of the beautiful rather represents the matter of which he treats as possible and desirable than indulges in attempts to con- vince us of its reality, and still less of its necessity. His thought does in fact onl}- present itself as an arbitrary creation of the imagination, which is never qualified, in it- self, to guarantee the reality of what it represents. No doubt the popular writer leads us to believe that the matter realli/ is as he describes it, but does not require anything more firm ; for, thougli. he may make the truth of a propo- sition credible to our feelings, he does not make it abso- lutely certain. Now, feeling may always teach us what is, but not what must be. The philosophical writer raises this belief to a conviction, for he proves b}' undeniable reasons that the matter is necessdrily so. Starting from the principle that we have just established, it will not be difficult to assign its proper part and sphere to each of the three forms of diction. Generally it ma}' be laid down as a rule that preference ought to be given to the scientific stjle whenever the chief consideration is not only the result, but also the proofs. But when the re- sult merely is of the most essential importance the advan- tage must be given to popular elocution and fine language. But it may be aslied in ^chat cases ought popular elocution to rise to a fine, a noble style ? This depends on the de- gree of interest in the reader, or which j^ou wish to excite in his mind. The purely scientific statement may incline either to popular discourse or to philosophic language, and accord- ing to this bias it places us more or less in possession of some branch of knowledge. All that popular elocution does is to lend us this knowledge for a momentary pleasure or enjoyment. The first, if I may be allowed the com- parison, gives us a tree with its roots, though with the condition that we wait patiently for it to blossom and bear fruit- The other, or fine diction, is satisfied with gather- 238 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. ing its flowers and fruits, but the tree that bore them does not become our propertj-, and when once the flowers are faded and the fruit is consumed our riches depart. It would therefore be equally unreasonable to give onlj- the flower and fruit to a man who wishes the whole tree to be transplanted into his garden, and to offer the whole tree with its fruit in the germ to a man who onlj' looks for the ripe fruit. The application of the comparison is self- evident, and I now only remark that a fine ornate style is as little suited to the professor's chair as the scholastic style to a drawing-room, the pulpit, or the bar. The student accumulates in view of an ulterior end and for a future use ; accordingly the professor ought to endeavor to transmit the/wW and entire propert'^ of the knowledge that he communicates to him. Now, nothing belongs to us as our own but what has been communicated to the understanding. The orator, on the other hand, has in view an immediate end, and his voice must correspond with an immediate want of the public. His interest is to make his knowledge practically available as soon as possible ; and the surest way is to hand it over to the senses, and to prepare it for the use of sensation. The professor, who only admits hearers on certain conditions, and who is entitled to suppose in his hearers the dis- positions of mind in which a man ought to be to receive the truth, has only in view in his lecture the object of which he is treating ; while the orator, who cannot make anj' conditions with his audience, and who needs above everything sympathy, to secure it on his side, must regulate his action and treatment according to the sitbjects on which he turns his discourse. The hearers of the professor have already attended his lectures, and will attend them again ; thej' only want fragments that will form a whole after having been linked to the preceding lectures. The audience of the orator is continually renewed ; it comes unprepared, and perhaps will not return ; accordingly in everj- address the orator must finish what he wishes to do ; each of his harangues must form a whole and contain expressly and entirelj' his conclusion. It is not therefore surprising that a dogmatic compo- sition or address, however solid, should not have any ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 239 success either in conversation or in the pulpit, nor that a fine diction, whatever wit it ma^- contain, should not bear fruit in a professor's chair. It is not surprising that the fashionable world should not read writings that stand out in relief in the scientific world, and that the scholar and the man of science are ignorant of works belonging to the school of worldly people that are devoured greedily by all lovers of the beautiful. Each of these works ma}' be entitled to admiration in the circle to which it be- longs ; and more than this, both, fundamentally, may be quite of equal value ; but it would be requiring an im- possibility to expect that the work which demands all the application of the thinker should at the same time ofllfer an easy recreation to the man who is only a fine wit. For the same reason I consider that it is hurtful to choose for the instruction of youth books in which scien- tific matters are clothed in an attractive stj'le. I do not speak here of those in which the substance is sacrificed to the form, but of certain writings realh' excellent, which are sufficiently well digested to- stand the strictest examina- tion, but which do not offer their proofs by their ver^^ form. No doubt books of this kind attain their end, thej' are read ; but this is alwa3's at the cost of a more impor- tant end, the end for which they ought to be read. In this sort of reading the understanding is never exercised save in as far as it agref s with the fancj' ; it does not learn to distinguish the form from the substance, nor to act alone as pure understanding. And yet the exercise of the pure understanding is in itself an essential and capital point in the instruction of jouth ; and verj' often the ex- ercise itself of thought is much more important than the object on which it is exercised. If j'ou wish for a matter to be done seriously, be very careful not to an- nounce it as a diversion. It is preferable, on the contrary, to secure attention and eflfort bj' the very form that is em- ployed, and to use a kind of violence to draw minds over from the passive to an active state. The professor ought never to hide from his pupil the exact regularity of the method ; he ought rather to fix his attention on it, and if possible to make him desire this strictness. The student 240 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. ought to learn to pursue an end, and in the interest of that end to put up with a difficult process. He ought early to aspire to that loftier satisfaction which is the reward of exertion. In a scientific lecture the senses are altogether set aside ; in an aesthetic address it is wished to interest them. What is the result? A writing or conversation of the aesthetic class is devoured with interest ; but ques- tions are put as to its conclusions ; the hearer is scarcely able to give an answer. And this is quite natural, as here the conceptions reach the mind only in entire masses, and the understanding only knows what it analyzes. The mind during a lecture of this kind is more passive than active, and the intellect only possesses what it has produced by its own activity. However, all this applies only to the vulgarly beautiful, and to a vulgar fashion of perceiving beauty. True beautj' reposes on the strictest limitation, on the most exact defini- tion, on the highest and most intimate necessitJ^ Only this limitation ought rather to let itself be sought for than be imposed violently. It requires the most perfect conformity to law, but tiiis must appear quite natural. A product that unites these conditions will fully satisf}' the understanding as soon as study is made of it. But exactly because this result is really beautiful, its con- formity is not expressed ; it does not take the understand- ing apart to address it exclusiveh' ; it is a harmonious unitj- which addresses the entire man — all his faculties together ; it is nature speaking to nature. A vulgar criticism may perhaps find it empty, paltry, and too little determined. He who has no other knowl- edge than that of distinguishing, and no other sense than that for the particular, is actually pained by what is precisely the triumph of art, this harmonious unit}' where the parts are blended in a pure entirety'. No doubt it is necessary, in a philosophical discourse, that the under- standing, as a faculty of analysis, find what will satisfy' it ; it must obtain single concrete results ; this is the essential that must not bj- anj- means be lost sight of. But if the writer, while giving all possible precision to the substance of his conceptions, has taken the necessarj^ measures to suable the understanding, as soon as it will take the ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 241 trouble, to find of necessity these truths, I do not see that he is a less good writer because he has approached more to the highest perfection. Nature always acts as a har- monious unitj', and when she loses this in her efforts after abstraction, nothing appears more urgent to her than to re-establisli it, and tlie writer we are speaking of is not less commendable if he obeys nature bj' attaching to the understanding what had been separated by abstraction, and when, bj' appealing at the same time to the sensuous and to the spiritual faculties, he addresses altogether the entire man. No doubt the vulgar critic will give very scant thanks to tliis writer for having given him a double task. For vulgar criticism has not the feeling for this harmonj', it only runs after details, and even in the Ba- silica of St. Peter would exclusively attend to the pillars on which the ethereal edifice reposes. The fact is that this critic must begin by translating it to understand it — in the same waj- that the pure understanding, left to itself, if it meets beauty and harmonj', either in nature or in art, must begin bj' transferring them into its own language — and b3- decomposing it, by doing in fact what the pupil does who spells before reading. But it is not from the narrow mind of his readers that the writer who express his conceptions in the language of the beautiful receives his laws. The ideal which he carries in himself is the goal at which he aims without troubling himself as to who follows and who remains behind. Manj- will staj- behind ; for if it be a rare thing to find readers simple- capable of thinking, it is inflnitel}' more rare to meet anj- who can think with imagination. Thus our writer, by the force of circumstances, will fall out, on the one hand, with those who have only intuitive ideas and feelings, for he imposes on them a painful task by forcing them to think ; and, on the other hand, he aggravates those who only know how to think, for lie asks of them what is absolutely impossible — to give a living, aniniateil form to conception. But as both only represent true humanity very imper- fectly — that normal humanit3' which requires the absolute harmony of these two operations — their contradictorj- objections have no weight, and if their judgments prove anything, it is rather that the author has succeeded in 242 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. attaining his end. The abstract thinker finds that the substance of the worlf is solidly thought ; the reader of intuitive ideas finds his style lively- and animated ; both consequently find and approve in him what they are able to understand, and that alone is wanting which exceeds their capacity. But precisely for this very reason a writer of this class is not adapted to make known to an ignorant reader the object of what he treats, or, in the most proper sense of the word, to teach. Happil}' also, be is not required for that, for means will not be wanting for the teaching of scholars. The professor in the strictest acceptation is obliged to bind himself to the needs of his scholars ; the first thing he has to presuppose is the ignorance of those who listen to him ; the other, on the other hand, demands a certain maturity and culture in his reader or audience. Nor is his oflSce confined to impart to them dead ideas ; he grasps the living object with a living energy, and seizes at once on the entire man — his understanding, his heart, ana his will. "We have found that it is dangerous for the soundness- of knowledge to give free scope to the exigencies of taste in teaching, properly so called. But this does not mean by any means that the culture of this facultj^ in the student is a premature thing. He must, on the contrary, be encour- aged to apply the knowledge that he has appropriated in the school to the field of living development. When once the first point has been observed, and the knowledge ac- quired, the other point, the exercise of taste, can only have useful results. It is certain that it is necessary to be quite the master of a truth to abandon without danger the form in which it has been found ; a great strength of un- derstanding is required not to lose sight of your object while giving free play to the imagination. He who trans- mits his knowledge under a scholastic form persuades me, I admit, that he has grasped these truths properly and that he knows how to support them. But he who besides this is in a condition to communicate them to me in a beautiful form not only proves that he is adapted to promulgate them, he shows moreover that he has assimilated them and that he is able to make their image pass into his produc- ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 243 tions and into his acts. There is for the results of thought only one waj' by which they can penetrate into the will and pass into life ; that is, by spontaneous imagination, only what in ourselves was already a livin^ act can become so out of us ; and the same thing happens with the creations of the mind as with those of organic nature, that the fruit issues only from the flower. If we consider how many truths were living and active as interior intuitions before philosophy showed their existence, and hOw many truths most firmly secured by proofs often remain inactive on the will and the feelings, it will be seen how important it is for practical life to follow in this the indications of nature, and when we have acquired a knowledge scientifically to bring it back again to the state of a living intuition. It is the only way to enable those whose nature has forbidden tliem to follow the artificial path of science to share in the treasures of wisdom. The beautiful renders us here in relation with knowledge what, in morals, it does in rela- tion with conduct ; it places men in harmony on results, and on the substance of things, who would never have agreed on the form and principles. The other sex, by its very nature and fair destin}', can- not and ought not to rival ours in scientific knowledge ; but it can share truth with us bj- the reproduction of tilings. Man agrees to have his taste ofiended, provided compensation be given to his understanding b}- the in- creased value of its possessions. But women do not for- give negligence in form, whatever be the nature of the con- ception ; and the inner structure of all their being gives them the right to show a strict severity on this point. The fair sex, even if it did not rule bj- beautv, would still be entitled to its name because it is ruled bj- beauty, and makes all objects presented to it appear before the tribunal of feeling, and all that does not speak to feeling or belies it is lost in the opinion of women. No doubt through this medium nothing can be made to reach the mind of woman save the matter of truth, and not truth itself, which is in- separable from its proofs. But happily woman only needs the matter of truth to reach her highest perfection, and the few exceptions hitherto seen are not of a nature to make us wish that the exception should become the rule. 244 ^STIIETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. As, therefore, nature has not ouh* dispensed but cut off the other sex from this task, man must give a double at- tention to it if he wishes to vie with woman and be equal to her in what is of great interest in human life. Conse- quently- he will tr\' to transfer all that he can from the field of abstraction, where he is master, to that of imagination, of feeling, where woman is at once a model and a judge. The mind of woman being a ground that does not admit of durable cultivation, he will tr}' to make his own ground yield as manj' flowers and as much fruit as possible, so as to renew as often as possible the quickly-fading produce on the other ground, and to keep up a sort of artificial harvest where natural harvests could not ripen. Taste corrects or hides the natural differences of the two sexes. It nourishes and adorns the mind of woman with the pro- ductions of that of man, and allows the fair sex to feel without being previousl3' fatigued by thought, and to enjoy pleasures without having bought them with labors. Thus, save the restrictions I have named, it is to the taste that is intrusted the care of form in every statement by which knowledge is communicated, but under the express condi- tion that it will not encroach on the substance of things. Taste must never forget that it carries out an order ema- nating elsewhere, and that it is not its own affairs it is treating of All its parts must be limited to place our minds in a condition favorable to knowledge; over all that concerns knowledge itself it has no right to anj" autliority. For it exceeds its mission, it betrays it, it disfigures the object that it ought faithfully' to transmit, it laj's claim .to authority out of its proper province ; if it tries to carry out there, too, its own law, which is nothing but that of pleasing the imagination and making itself agreeable to the Intuitive faculties ; if it applies this law not only to the operation^ but also to the matter itself; if it follows this rule not only to arrange the materials, but also to choose them. When this is the case the first consideration is not the things themselves, but the best mode of presenting them so as to recommend them to the senses. The logical se- quence of conceptions of whicli only the strictness should have been hidden from us is rejected as a disagreeable im- pediment. Perfection is sacrificed to ornament, the truth iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 245 of the parts to the beauty of the whole, the Inmost nature of things to the exterior impression. Now, directly the substance is subordinated to form, properly speaking it ceases to exist ; the statement is empty, and instead of having extended our knowledge we have onlj' indulged in an amusing game. The writers who have more wit than understanding and more taste than science, are too often guilty of this decep- tion-; and readers more accustomed to feel than to think are only too inclined to forgive them. In general it is un- safe to give to the sesthetical sense all its culture before having exercised the understanding as the pure thinking faculty, and before having enriched the head with concep- tions ; for as taste always looks at the carr3'ing out and not at the basis of things, wherever it becomes the onl3' arbiter, there is an end of the essential difference between things. Men become indifferent to reality, and thej' finish b^' givmg value to form and appearance only. Hence arises tliat superficial and frivolous bel-esprit that we often see hold swa}' in social conditions and in circles where men pride themselves, and not unreasonabl3-, on the finest culture. It is a fatal thing to introduce a .young man into assemblies where the Graces hold sway before the Muses have dismissed him and owned his m."ijority. Moreover, it can hardly be prevented that what completes the external education of a young man whose mind is ripe turns liim who is not ripened by study into a fool. I ad- mit that to have a fund of conceptions, and not form, is only a half possession. For the most splendid knowledge in a head incapable of giving them form is like a treasure buried in the earth. But form without substance is a shadow of riches, and all possible cleverness m expression is of no use to him who has nothing to express. Thus, to avoid the graces of education leading us in a wrong road, taste must be confined to regulating the external form, while reason and experience determine the substance and the essence of conceptions. If the impres- sion made on the senses is converted into a supreme criterion, and if things are exclusively referred to sensa- tion, man will never cease to be in the service of matter; he will never clear a way for his intelligerce ; in short, 246 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. reason will lose in freedom in proportion as it allows imagination to usurp undue influence. Tlie beautiful produces its effect by mere intuition ; the truth demands study. Accordingly, the man who among all his faculties has only exercised the sense of the beauti- ful is satisfied even when study is absolutely required, with a superficial view of things ; and he fancies he can make a mere play of wit of that which demands a serious effort. But mere intuition cannot give any result. To produce something great it is necessary to enter into the fundamental nature of things, to distinguish them strictly, to associate them in different manners, and study them with a steady attention. Even the artist and the poet, though both of them labor to procure us only the pleasure of intuition, can only by most laborious and engrossing study succeed in giving us a delightful recreation by their works. I believe this to be the test to distinguish the mere dilettante from the artist of real genius. The seductive cliarm exercised by the sublime and the beautiful, the fire which they kindle in the young imagination, the apparent ease with which they place the senses under an illusion, have often persuaded inexperienced minds to take ni hand the palette or the harp, and to transform into figures or to pour out in melody what they felt living in their heart. Misty ideas circulate in their heads, like a world in forma- tion, and make them believe that they are inspired. They take obscurit}' for depth, savage vehemence for strength, the undetermined for the infinite, what has not senses for the super-sensuous. And how they revel in these creations of their brain ! But the judgment of the connoisseur does not confirm this testimony of an excited self-love. With his pitiless criticism he dissipates all the prestige of the imagination and of its dreams, and carrying the torch before these novices he leads them into the mysterious depths of science and life, where, far from profane eyes, the source of all true beautj' flows ever towards him who is initiated. If now a true genius slumbers in the j'oung aspirant, no doubt his modesty will at first receive a shock ; iiut soon the consciousness of real talent will embolden Jiim for the trial. If nature has endowed him with gifts ESTHETIC AL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 247 for plastic art, he will study the structure of man with the scalpel of the anatomist ; he will descend into the lowest depths to be true in representing surfaces, and he will question the whole race in order to be just to the indi- vidual. If he is born to be a poet, he examines humanity in his own heart to understand the infinite variety of scenes in which it acts on the vast theatre of the world. He subjects imagination and its exuberant fruitfulness to the discipline of taste, and charges the understanding to mark out in its cool wisdom the banks that should confine the raging waters of inspiration. He knows full well that the great is onlj' formed of the little — from the imperceptible. He piles up, grain by grain, the materials of the wonder- ful structure, which, suddenly disclosed to our eyes, pro- duces a startling effect and turns our head. But if nature has only intended him for a dilettante, difficulties damp his impotent zeal, and one of two things happens : either he abandons, if he is modest, that to which he was diverted by a mistaken notion of his vocation ; or, if he has no modesty, he brings back the ideal to the narrow limits of his faculties, for want of being able to enlarge his faculties to the vast proportions of the ideal. Thus the true genius of the artist will be always recognized by this sign — that when most enthusiastic for the whole, he preserves a cool- ness, a patience defying all obstacles, as regards details. Moreover, in order not to do any injury to perfection, he would rather renounce the enjoyment given bj'the comple- tion. For the simple amateur, it is the difficult}' of means that disgusts him and turns him from his aim ; his dreams would be to have no more trouble in producing than he had in conception and intuition. I have spoken hitherto of the dangers to which we are exposed by an exaggerated sensuousness and susceptibility to the beautiful in the form, and from too extensive ses- thetical requirements ; and I have considered these dangers in relation to the faculty of thinking and knowing. What, then, will be the result when these pretensions of the ses- thetical taste bear on the loill? It is one thing to be stopped in your scientific progress by too great a love of the beautiful, another to see this inclination become a cause of degeneracy in character itself, and make us violate the 248 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. law of duty. In matters of thought the caprices of " taste" are no doubt an evil, and they must of necessity darken the intelligence ; but these same caprices applied to the maxims of the will become really pernicious and infal- libly deprave the heart. Yet this is the dangerous extreme to which too refined an aesthetic culture brings us directly we abandon oursehes exclusively to the feelings for the beautiful, and directly we raise taste to the part of abso- lute lawgiver over our will. The moral destination of man requires that the will should be completely independent of all influence of sen- suous instincts, and we know that taste labors incessantly at making the link between reason and the senses contin- ually closer. Now this effort has certainly as its result the ennobling of the appetites, and to make them more conformable with the requirements of reason ; but this very point ma}- be a serious danger for moralit}*. I proceed to explain m^- meaning. A verj- refined ees- thetical education accustoms the imagination to direct itself according to laws, even in its free exercise, and leads the sensuous not to have any enjoyments without the concurrence of reason ; but it soon follows that reason, in its turn, is required to be directed, even in the most seri- ous operations of its legislative poioer, according to the interests of imagination, and to give no more orders to the will without the consent of the sensuous instincts. The moral obligation of the will, which is, however, an absolute and unconditional law, takes unperceived the character of a simple contract, which onlj- binds each of the contracting parties when the other fulfils its engage- ment. The purely' accidental agreement of duty with inclination ends b}' being considered a ??ece«sar(/ condition, and thus the principle of all morality is quenched in its source. How does the character become thus gradually depraved? The process ma}' be explained thus : So long as man is only a savage, and his insiincts cily bear on material things and a coarse egotism (u'termincs his actions, sensu- ousness can only become a There is not in the Greek mythology a more terrible, and at the same time more hideous, picture than the Furies, or Erinj'es, quitting the infernal regions to throw them- selves in the pursuit of a criminal. Their faces frightfully contracted and grimacing, their fleshless bodies, their heads covered with serpents in the place of hair — revolt our senses as much as the}' offend our taste. However, when these monsters are represented to us in the pursuit ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 267 of Orestes, the murderer of his mother, when tliey are shown to us brandishing the torches in their hands, and chasing their pre}', witliout peace or truce, from country to country', until at last, the anger of justice being appeased, they engulf themselves in the abj-ss of the infernal regions ; then we pause before the picture with a horror mixed with pleasure. But not only the remorse of a criminal which is personified bj' the Furies, even his unrighteous acts : nay, the real perpetration of a crime, are able to please us in a work of art. Medea, in the Greek traged}' ; Clytem- nestra, who takes the life of her husband ; Orestes, who kills his mother, fill our soul with horror and with pleasure. Even ifl real life, indifferent and even repulsive or fright- ful objects begin to interest us the moment that they approach the monstrous or the terrible. An altogether vulgar and insignificant man will begin to please us the moment that a violent passion, which indeed in no way upraises his personal value, makes him an object of fear a.id terror, in the same way that a vulgar, meaningless object becomes to us the source of aesthetic pleasure the instant we have enlarged it to the point where it threat- ens to overstep our comprehension. An ugly man is made still more ugly by passion, and nevertheless it is in bursts of this passion, provided that it turns to the terrible and not to the ridiculous, that this man will be to us of the most interest. This remark extends even to animals. An ox at the plow, a h(*se before a carriage, a dog, are common objects ; but excite this bull to the combat, enrage this horse who is so peaceable, or represent to yourself this dog a prey to madness ; instantly these animals are raised to the rank of sesthetic objects, and we begin to regard them with a feeling which borders on pleasure and esteem. The inclination to the pathetic^ an inclination common to all men — the strength of the sympathetic sen- timent — this force which in nature makes us wish to see suffering, terror, dismay, which has so many attractions for us in art, which makes us hurry to the theatre, which makes us take so much pleasure in the picturing of great misfortune, — all this bears testimony to a fourth source of £esthetic pleasure, which neither the agreeable, nor the good, nor the beautiful are in a state to produce. 268 jESTHETICAt, LETTERS AND ESSAYS. All the examples that I have alleged up to the present have this in common — that the feeling thej- excite in us rests on something objective. In all these phenomena we receive the idea of something " which oversteps, or which threatens to overstep, the power of comprehension of our senses, or their power of resistance " ; but not, however, going so far as to paralyze these two powers, or so far as to render us incapable of striving, either to know the object, or to resist the impression it makes on us. There is in the phenomena a complexity which we cannot retrace to unitj' without driving the intuitive faculty to its furthest limits. We have the idea of a force in comparison witlj which our own vanishes, and which we are nevertheless compelled to compare with our own. Either it is an object which at the same time presents and hides itself from our facultj- of intuition, and which urges us to strive to represent it to ourselves, without leaving room to hope that this aspir- ation will be satisfied ; or else it is an object wliich appears to upraise itself as an enemy, even against our existence — which provokes us, so to say, to combat, and makes us anxious as to the issue. In all the alleged examples there is visible in the same way the same action on the faculty of feeling. All throw our souls into an anxious agitation and strain its springs. A certain gravity which can even raise itself to a solemn rejoicing takes possession of our soul, and whilst our organs betray evident signs of internal anxiety, our mind falls back on itself by reflection, and appears to find a support in a higher consciousness of its independent strength and dignity. This consciousness of ourselves must always dominate in order that the great and the horrible may have for us an aesthetic value. It is because the soul before such sights as these feels itself inspired and lifted above itself that they are designated under the name of sublime, although the things themselves are objectively in no way sublime ; and consequently it would be more just to say that they are elevating than to call them in themselves elevated or sublime. For an object to be called sublime it must be in oppo- sition with our sensuousness. In general it is possible to conceive but two different relations between the objects .BSTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 269 and our sensuousness, and consequently there ought to be two kinds of resistance. They ought either to be consid- ered as objects from which we wish to draw a knowledge, or else thej' should he regarded as a force with which we compare our own. According to this division there are two kinds of the sublime, the sublime of knowledge and the sublime of force. Moreover, the sensuous faculties contribute to knowledge only in grasping a given matter, and putting one by the other its complexity in time and in space. As to dissecting this complex property and assorting it, it is the business of the understanding and not of tlie imagination. It is for the understanding alone that the diversity exists : for the imagination (considered simply as a sensuous facult}') there is but an uniformity, and conse- quently it is but the number of the uniform things (tiie quantit3- and not the quality) which can give origin to any difference between the sensuous perception of plienomena. Thus, in order that the faculty of picturing things sensu- ouslj' maybe reduced to impotence before an object, nec- essarily it is imperative that this object exceeds in its quantity the capacity of our imagination. ON SIMPLE AND •SENTIMENTAL POETEY. There are moments in life when nature inspires us with a sort of love and respectful emotion, not because she is pleasing to our senses, or because she satisfies our mind or our taste (it is often the very opposite that happens), but merelj' because she is natui'e. This feeling is often elicited when nature is considered in her plants, in her minerab kingdom, in rural districts ; also in the case of human nature, in the case of children, and in the manners of country people and of the primitive races. Every man of refiued feeling, provided he has a soul, experiences this feeling when he walks out under the open sky, when he lives in the country, or wlien he stops to contemplate the monuments of early ages ; in short, when escaping from \ 270 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. factitious situations and relations, he finds himself sud- denly face to face with nature. This interest, vvliich is often exalted in us so as to become a want, is the expla- nation of many of our fancies for flowers and for animals, our preference for gardens laid out in the natural style, our love of walks, of the country and those who live there, of a great number of objects proceeding from a remote an- tiquity, etc. It is taken for granted that no affectation exists in the matter, and moreover that no ' accidental i interest comes into play. But this sort of interest which we take in nature is onlj- possible under two conditions. First the object that inspires us with this feehng must be really nature, or something we take for nature ; secondlj^ this object must be in the full sense of the word simple, that is, presenting the entire contrast of nature with art, all the advantage remaining on the side of nature. Directly this second condition is united to the first, but no sooner, nature assumes the character of simplicity. Considered thus, nature is for us nothing but existence in all its freedom ; it is the constitution of things taken in themselves ; it is existence itself according to its proper and immutable laws. It is strictly necessarj' that we should have this idea of nature to take an interest in phenomena of this kind. If , we conceive an artificial flower so perfectly imitated that it has all the appearance of nature and would produce the most complete illusion, or if we imagine the imitation of simplicity carried out to the extremest degree, the instant we discover it is only an imitation, the feeling of which I — -have been speaking is completely destroyed. It is, there- fore, quite evident that this kind of satisfaction which nature causes us to feel is not a satisfaction of the aesthet- ical taste, but a satisfaction of the moral sense ; for it is produced by means of a conception and not immediately by the single fact of intuition : accordingly it is by no means determined by the different degrees of beauty in forms. For, after all, is there anything so specially charming in a flower of common appearance, in a spring, a moss-covered stone, the warbling of birds, or the buzzing of bees, etc. ? What is that can give these objects a claim i '; to our love ? It is not these objects in themselves ; it is iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 27J an idea represented bj- them that we love in them. W« love in them life and its latent action, the effects peaeefnllj / produced b}' beings of themselves, existence under its ( proper laws, the inmost necessity of things, the eternal unity of their nature. These objects which captivate us are what we were, \, what we must be again some daj'. We were nature as they ! are ; and culture, following the way of reason and of libertj-, must bring us back to nature. Accordingly, these objects are an image of our infancj' irrevocably past — of our infancy which (Vill remain eternallj- very dear to us, and thus they infuse a certain melancholj- into us ; they are also the image of our highest perfection in the ideal world, whence thej' excite a sublime emotion in us. But the perfection of these objects is not a merit that belongs to them, because it is not the effect of their free choice. Accordingly they procure quite a peculiar pleasure for us, by being our models without having anything humiliating for us. It is like a constant manifestation of the divinity surroujiding us, which refreshes without dazzling us. The very feature that constitutes their character is precisely' what is lacking in ours to make it complete ; and what distinguishes us from them is precise!}' I what they lack to be divine. "We are free and they are ' necessar}- ; we change and thej' remain identical. Now it . IS only when these two conditions are united, when the will submits freelj- to the^aws of necessitj', and when, in the midst of all the changes of which the imagination is susceptible, reason maintains its rule- — it is onlj- then that the divine or the ideal is manifested. Thus we perceive eternall}' in them that which we have not, but which we are continually forced to strive after ; that which we can never reach, but which we can hope to approach hj continual progress. And we perceive in ourselves an advantage which thejr lack, but in which some of them — the beings deprived of reason — cannot absolutely share, and in which the others, such as children, can only one day have a share by following our way. According!}^, they procure us the most delicious feeling of our human nature, as an idea, though in relation to each determinate state of our nature they cannot fail to humble us. 272 JSSTHETICAIi LETTERS AND ESSAYS. As this interest in nature is based on an idea, it can only manifest itself in a soul capable of ideas, that is, in a moral soul For the immense majority it is nothing more than pure affectation ; and this taste of sentimentality so widely diffused in our day, manifesting itself, especially since the appearance of certain books, by sentimental excursions and journej'S, hy sentimental gardens, and other fancies akin to these — this taste by no means proves that true refinement of sense has become general . Nevertheless, it is certain that nature will always produce something of this impression, even on the most insensible hearts, be- cause all that is required for this is the moral disposition or aptitude, which is common to all men. For all men, liowever contrary' their acts maj- be to simplicity and to the truth of nature, are brought back to it in their ideas. This sensibilitj' in connection with nature is specially and most strongly manifested, in the greater part of persons, in connection with those sorts of objects which are closely related to us, and which, causing us to look closer into ourselves, show us more clearlj- what in us departs from nature ; for example, in connection with children, or with nations in a state of infancj. It is an error to suppose that it is only the idea of their weakness that, in certain moments, makes us dwell with our eyes on children with so much emotion. This maj' be true with those who, in the presence of a feeble being, are used to feel nothing but their own superioritj'. But the feeling of which I speak is only experienced in a veiy peculiar moral disposition, nor must it be confounded with the feeling awakened in us 1)}- the joyous activity of children. The feeling of which I speak is calculated rather to humble than to flatter our self-love ; and if it gives us the idea of some advantage, this advantage is at all events not on our side. We are moved in the presence of childhood, but it is not because from the height of our -strength and of our perfection we drop a look of pity on it ; it is, on the con- trary, because from the depths of our impotence, of which the feeling is inseparable from that of the real and deter- minate state to which we have arrived, we raise our eyes to the child's determinableness and pure innocence. The feeling we then experience is too evidently mingled with ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 273 sadness for us to mistake its source. In the child, all is / disposition and destination ; in us, all is in the state of a completed, ^finished thing, and the completion always re- mains infinitely below the destina'tion. It follows that the child is to us like the representation of the ideal ; not, ) indeed, of the ideal as we have realized it, but such as our ' destination admitted; and, consequently, it is not at all the idea of its indigence, of its hinderances, that makes us experience emotion in the child's presence ; it is, on the / contrarj-, the idea of its pure and free force, of the integ- rity, the infinity of its being. This is the reason why, in j the sight of every moral and sensible man, the child will always be a sacred thing ; I mean an object which, by the grandeur of an idea, reduces to nothingness all grandeur realized by experience ; an object which, in spite of all it ; may lose in the judgment of the understanding, re- gains largely the advantage before the judgment of reason. Now it is precisely this contradiction between the judg- ment of reason and that of the understanding which pro- duces in us this quite special phenomenon, this mixed feeling, called forth in us by the sight of the simple — I mean the simple in the manner of thinking. It is at once the idea of a childlike simplicit}' and of a childish simplic- ity. By what it has of childish simplicity it exposes a weak side to the understanding, and provokes in us that , smile by which we testify ©ur superiority (an entirely spec- ulative superiorit}') . But directly' we have reason to think that childish simplicity is at the same time a childlike simplicity — that it is not consequently a want of intelli- gence, an infirmity- in a theoretical point of view, but a superior force (practically), a heart-full of truth and inno- cence, which is its source, a lieart that has despised the help of art because it was conscious of its real and inter- nal greatness — directly this is understood, the under- standing no longer seeks to triumph. Then raillery, which was directed against sinipleness, makes way for the admiration inspired by noble simplicity. We feel ourselves obliged to esteem this object, which at first made us smile, and directing our eyes to ourselves, to feel ourselves ■ unhappy in EOt resembling it. Thus is produced that very 274 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. special phenomenon of a feeling in whicli good-natured raillery, respect, and sadness are confounded. It is the condition of the simple that nature should triumph over art, either unconsciously to the individual and against his inclination, or with his full and entire cognizance. In the former case it is simplicity as a surprise^ and the impres- sion resulting from it is one of gayety ; in the second casC;. it is simplicity oi feeling, and we are moved. With regard to simplicit}' as a surprise, the person must be morally capable of denying nature. In simplicity of feeling the person ma^' be morally incapable of this, but we must not think him physically incapable,, in order that it may make upon us the impression of the simple. This is the reason whj' the acts and words of children only produce the impression of simplicity upon us when we for- get that they are physicallj' incapable of artifice, and in general only when we are exclusively impressed by the contrast between their natural c haracter and what is arti- ficial in us. Simplicity is a childlike ingemiousness which is encountered when it is not expected; and it is for this very reason that, taking the word in its strictest sense, simplicity could not be attributed to childhood properly speaking. But in both cases, in simplicity as a surprise and sim- plicity as a feeling, nature must always have the upper hand, and art succumb to her. Until we have established this distinction we can only form an incomplete idea of simplicity. The affections are also something natural, and the rules of decencj' are artificial ; yet the triumph of the affections over decencj- is anything but simple. But when affection triumphs over artifice, over false decencj', over dissimulation, we shall have no diflSculty in applying the word simple to this. Nature must therefore triumph over art, not by its blind and bru^ tal force as a dynamical power, but in virtue of its form as a moral m,agnitude; in a word, not as a want, but as an internal necessity. It must not be insufficiency, but the inopportune character of the latter that gives nature her victory ; for insufficiency is only a want and a defect, and nothing that results from a want or defect could pro- duce esteem. No doubt in the simplicity resulting from ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 275 surprise, it is always the predominance of affection and a\ want of reflection that causes us to appear natural. But this want and this predominance do not by any means sufHoe to constitute simplicity ; thej' merely give occasion to nature to obey without let or hinderance her moral con- stitution, that is, the law of harmony. __,y The simplicity resulting from surprise can onlj' be en- countered in man and that onlj- in as far as at the moment he ceases to be a pure and innocent nature. This sort of simplicity implies a will that is not in harmony with that which nature does of her own accord. A person simple after this fashion, when recalled to himself, will be the first to be alarmed at what he is ; on the other hand, a person in whom simplicity is found as a, feeling, will only wonder at one thing, that is, at the way in which men feel aston- ishment. As it is not the moral subject as a person, but only his natural character set free by affection, that con- fesses the truth, it follows from this that we shall not attribute this sincerity to man as a merit, and that we shall be entitled to laugh at it, our raillery not being held in check by any personal esteem for his character. Never- theless, as it is still the sincerity of nature which, even in the simplicity caused by surprise, pierces suddenly through the veil of dissimulation, a satisfaction of a superior order is mixed with the mischievous jo3' we feel in having caught any one in the act. This is because nature, opposed to affectation, and truth, opoosed to deception, mustineveiy case inspire us with esteem. Thus we experience, even in the presence of simplicity originating in surprise, a really moral pleasure, though it be not in connection with a moral object. ^~- I admit that in simplicity proceeding from surprise we always experience a feeling of esteem for nature, because we must esteem truth ; whereas in the simplicity of feeling we esteem the person himself, enjoying in this way not only a moral satisfaction, but also a satisfaction of which the object is moral. In both cases nature is right, since she speaks the truth ; but in the second case not only is nature right, but there is also an act that does honor to the person. In the first case the sinceritj' of^ nature always puts the person to the blush, because it is 276 .ESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. involuntary; in the second it is alwaj's a merit which must be placed to the credit of the person, even when what he confesses is of a nature to cause a blush. We attribute simplicity of feeling to a man, when, in the judgments he pronounces on things, he passes, without seeing them, over all the factitious and artificial sides of an object, to keep exclusively to simple nature. We require of him all the judgments that can be formed of things without departing from a sound nature ; and we only hold him entirely free in what presupposes a departure from nature in his mode of thinking or feeling. If a father relates to his son that such and such a person is djing of hunger, and if the child goes and carries the purse of his father to this unfortunate being, this is a simple action. It is in fact a health^" nature that acts in the child ; and in a world where healthy nature would be the law, he would be perfectly right to act so. He only sees the misery of his neighbor and the speediest mean's of relieving bim. The extension given to the right of property, in consequence of which part of the human race might perish, is not based on mere nature. Thus the act of this child puts to shame real society, and this is ac- knowledged by our heart m the pleasure it experiences from this action. If a good-hearted man, inexperienced in the ways of the world, confides his secrets to another, who deceives him, but who is skilful in disguising his perfidy, and if by his very sincerity he furnishes him with the means of doing him injury, we find his conduct simple. We laugh at him, j'et we cannot avoid esteeming him, precisely on account of his simplicity. This is because his trust in others proceeds from the rectitude of his ow^n heart ; at all events, there is simplicity here only as far as this is the case. Simplicit}' in the mode of thinking cannot then ever be the act of a depraved man ; this quality only belongs to children, and to men who are children in heart. It often happens to these in the midst of the artificial relations of the great world to act or to think in a simple manner. Being themselves of a truly good and humane nature, they forget that they have to do with a depraved world ; iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 277' and tUey act, even in the courts of kings, with an ingenu- ousness and an innocence that are onlj' found in the world of pastoral idyls. , Nor is it alwaj'S such an easy matter to distingiiisli exactly childish candor from childlike candor, for tlierc are actions that are on the skirts of both. Is a certain act foohshly simple, and must we laugh at it? or is it nobl^- simple, and must we esteem the actors the higher on that account? It is difficult to know which side to take in some cases. A ver}- remarkable example of this is found in the histor3' of the government of Pope Adrian VI., related by Mr. Schrockh with all the soliditj- and the spirit of practical truth which distinguish him. Adrian, a Netherlander by birth, exerted the pontifical swaj' at one of the most critical moments for the hierarchj' — at a time when an exasperated party laid bare without anj- scruple all the weak sides of the Roman Church, while the opposite party was interested in the highest degree in covering them over. I do not entertain the question how a man of a trulj' simple character ought to act in such a case, if such a character were placed in the papal chair, But, we ask, how could this simplicity of feehng be compatible with tlie part of a pope? This question gave indeed very little embarrassment to the predecessors and successors of Adrian. Thej- followed uniformly the system adopted once for all by the court of Eome, not to make any concessions afij-where. But Adrian had pre- served the upright charater of his nation and the inno- cence of his previous condition. Issuing from the humble sphere of literary men to rise to this eminent position, he did not belie at that elevation the primitive simplicity of his character. He was moved by the abuses of the Roman Church, and he was much too sincere to dissimulate pub- licly what he confessed privatel3r. It was in consequence of this manner of thinking that, in his instruction to his legate in Germany, he allowed himself to be drawn into avowals hitherto unheard of- in a sovereign pontiff, and diametricallj' contrary to the principles of that court : "We know well," he said, among other things, " that for many years many abominable things have taken place in this hoi}' chair ; it is not therefore astonishing that the 278 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. evil has been propagated from the head to the members, from the pope to the prelates. We have all gone astray from the good road, and for a long time there is none of us, not one, who has done anything good." Elsewhere he orders his legate to declare in his name " that he, Adrian, cannot be blamed for what other popes have done before him ; that he himself, when he occupied a comparatively mediocre position, had alwaj's condemned these excesses." It may easily be conceived how such simplicity in a pope must have been received by the Roman clergy. The smallest crime of which he was accused was that of be- traying the church and delivering it over to heretics. Now this proceeding, supremely imprudent in a pope, would j'et deserve our esteem and admiration if we could believe it was real simplicity ; that is, that Adrian, without fear of consequences, had made such an avowal, moved by his natural sincerity, and that he would have persisted in acting thus, though he had understood all the drift of his clumsiness. Unhappily we have some reason to beheve that he did not consider his conduct as altogether im- politic, and that in his candor he went so far as to flatter - himself that he had served verj' usefully the interests of his cliurch by his indulgence to his adversaries. He did not even imagine that he' ought to act thus in his quality as an honest man ; he thought also as a pope to be able to justify himself, and forgetting that the most artificial of structures could only be supported by continuing to deny the truth, he committed the unpardonable fault of having recourse to means of safetj-, excellent perhaps, in a natural situation, but here applied to entirely contrary circum- stances. This necessarily modifies our judgment very much, and although we cannot refuse our esteem for the honesty of heart in which the act originates, this esteem is greatly lessened when we reflect that nature on this occasion was too easily mistress of art, and that the heart too easil}' overruled the head. True genius is of necessity simple, or it is not genius. Simplicity alone gives it this character, and it cannot behe in the moral order what it is in the intellectual and fflsthetical order. It does not know those rules, the crutches of feebleness, those pedagogues which prop up ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 279 slippery spirits ; it is only guided b^' nature and instinct, its guardian angel ; it walks with a Arm, calm step across all the snares of false taste, snares in which the man without genius, if he have not the prudence to avoid them the moment he detects them, remains infallibly imbedded. It is therefore the part onlj' of genius to issue from the^ known without ceasing to be at home, or to enlarge the ; circle of nature without overstepping it. It does indeed I sometimes happen that a great genius oversteps it ; but only because geniuses have their moments of frenzy, when nature, their protector, abandons them, because the force of example impels them, or because the corrupt taste of their age leads them astraj*. The most intricate problems must be solved by genius with simplicitj', without pretension, with ease ; the egg of Christopher Columbus is the emblem of all the discoveries - of genius. It only justifies its character as genius by triumphing through simphcity over all the complications of art. It does not proceed according to known principles, but b^' feelings and inspiration ; the sallies of genius are the inspirations of a God (all that health^' nature pro- duces is divine) ; its feelings are laws for all time, for all human generations. Tins childlike character imprinted by genius on its works is also shown by it in its private life and manners. It is modest, because nature is always so ;, but it is not decent, because corruption alone is decent. It is intelligent^ because nature cannot lack intelligence ; but it is not cunning, because art only can be cunning. It is faithful to its character and inclinations, but this is not so much because it has principles as because nature, notwith- standing all its oscillations, alwaj's returns to its equili- brium, and brings back the same wants. It is modest and even timid, because genius remains always a secret to itself; but it is not anxious, because it does not know the dangers of the road in which it walks. We know little of the private life of the greatest geniuses ; but the little that we know of it — what tradition has pre- served, for example, of Sophocles, of Archimedes, of Hippocrates, and in modern times of Ariosto, of Dante, of Tasso, of Raphael, of Albert Dilrer, of Cervantes, of 280 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. Shakespeare, of Fielding, of Sterne, etc. — confirms this assertion. Nay, more ; though this admission seems more difficult to support, even the greatest pliilosophers and great com- manders, if great by their genius, have simplicity in their character. Among the ancients I need onl}^ name Julius Caesar and Epaminondas ; among the moderns Henry IV. in France, Gustavus Adolphus in Sweden, and the Czar Peter the Great. The Duke of Marlborough, Turenne, /'and Vendome all present this character. With regard to the other sex, nature proposes to it simplicity of character ' as the supreme perfection to which it should reach. Ac- cordingly, the love of pleasing in women strives after nothing so much as the appearance of simplicity ; a suf- ficient proof, if it were the only one, that the greatest power of the sex reposes in this qualit^^ But, as the principles that prevail in the education of women are perpetually struggling with this charactei*, it is as diffi- cult for them in the moral order to reconcile this mag- nificent gift of nature with the ad\'antages of a good education as it is difficult for men to preserve them unchanged in the intellectual order : and the woman who knows how to join a knowledge of the world to this sort of simplicity in manners is as deserving of respect as a scholar who joins to the strictness of scholastic rules the freedom and originalitj' of thought. Simplicity in our mode of thinking brings with it of necessit}' simplicity in our mode of expression, simplicity in terms as well as movement ; and it is in this that grace especially consists. Genius expresses its most sublime and its deepest thoughts with this simple grace ; the}' are the divine oracles that issue from the lips of a child ; while the scholastic spirit, always anxious to avoid error, tor- tures all its words, all its ideas, and makes them pass through the crucible of grammar and logic, hard and rigid, in order to keep from vagueness, and uses few words in order not to say too much, enervates and blunts thought in order not to wound the reader who is not on his guard — ^ genius gives to its expression, with a single and happj"^ stroke of the brush, a piecisc, firm, and yet perfectly free form. In the case of grammar and logic, the sign and the ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 281 thing signified are always heterogenous and strangers to each other : with genius, on the contrary, the expression gushes forth spontaneously from the idea, the language and the thought are one and the same ; so that even though the expresssion thus gives it a body the spirit appears as if disclosed in a nude state. This fashion of expression, when the sign disappears entirely in the thing signified, when the tongue, so to speak, leaves the thought it translates naked, whilst the other mode of expression cannot represent thought without veiling it at the same time : this is what is called originality and inspiration in style. This freedom, this natural mode by which genius ex- presses itself in works of intellect, is also the expression of the innocence of heart in the intercourse of life. Every one knows that in the world men have departed from simplicity, from the rigorous veracity of language, in the same proportion as they have lost the simplicity of feelings. The guilty conscience easily wounded, the imagination easily* seduced, made an anxious decency necessary. Without telling what is false, people often speak differentlj' from what they think ; we are obliged to make circumlocutions to say certain things, which however, can never aflSict any but a sickly self-love, and that have no danger except for a depraved imagination. The ignorance of these laws of propriety (conventional" laws), coupled with a natural sincerity which despises all kinds of bias and all appearance of falsitj' (sincerity I mean, not coarseness, for coarseness dispenses with forms because it is hampered), gives rise in the intercourse of life to a simplicity of expression that consists in naming things by their proper name without circumlocution. This is done because we do not venture to designate them as thej' are, or only to do so by artificial means. The ordinary expressions of children are of this kind. They make us smile because they are in opposition to received manners ; but men would always agree in the bottom of their hearts that the child is right. It is true that simplicity of feeling cannot properly be attributed to the child any more than to the man, — that is, to a being not absolutely subject to nature, though there 282 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. is still no simplicity, except on the condition that it is pure nature that acts through him. But b^- an effort of the imagination, which likes to poetise things, we often carry over these attributes of a rational being to beings destitute of reason. It is thus that, on seeing an animal, a land- scape, a building, and nature in general, from opposition to what is arbitrarj' and fantastic in the conceptions of man, we often attribute to them a simple character. But that implies always that in our thought we attribute a will to these things that have none, and that we are struck to see it directed rigorously accordmg to the laws of necessity. Discontented as we are that we have ill em- ployed our own moral freedom, and that we no longer And moral harmony in our conduct, we are e&sily led to a certain disposition of mind, in which we willingly address ourselves to a being destitute of reason, as if it were a person. And we readil}' view it as if it had reallj- had to struggle against the temptation of acting otherwise, and proceed to make a merit of its eternal uniformity, and to env3' its peaceable constancy. We are quite disposed tc consider in those moments reason, this prerogative of the human race, as a pernicious gift and as an evil ; we feel so vividly all that is imperfect in our conduct that we forget tg^be just to our destinj' and to our aptitudes. We see, then, in nature, destitute of reason, only a sister who, more fortunate than ourselves, has remained under the maternal roof, while in the intoxication of our free- dom we have fled from it to throw ourselves into a stranger world. We regret this place of safetj', we earnestlj' long to come back to it as soon as we have begun to feel the bitter side of civilization, and in the totally artificial life in which we are exiled we hear in deep emotion the voice of our mother. While we were still only children of nature we were happj', we were perfect : we ha\'e become free, and we have lost both advantages. Hence a twofold and verj' unequal longing for nature : the longing for happiness and the longing for the perfection that prevails there. Man, as a sensuous being, deplores sensibly the loss of the former of these goods ; it is onl}- the moral man who can be afflicted at the loss of the other. Therefore, let the man with a sensible heart and a loving ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 283 nature question himself closely. Is it your indolence that longs for its repose, or your wounded moral sense that longs for its harmonj'? Ask yourself well, when, disgusted with the artifices, offended by the abuses that j'ou discover in social life, you feel yourself attracted towards inanimate nature, in the midst of solitude ask 3'ourself what impels you to fly the world. Is it tlie privation from which you suffer, its loads, its troubles 'i or is it the moral anarchy, the caprice, the disorder that prevail there? Your heart ought to plunge into these troubles with joj-, and to find in them the compensation in the liberty of which thej' are the consequence. You can, I admit, propose as j'our aim, in a distant future, the calm and the happiness of nature ; but only that sort of happiness which is the reward of your dignitj-. Thus, then, let there be no more complaint about the loads of life, the inequalit}' of conditions, or the hampering of social relations, or the uncertainty of possession, ingratitude, oppression, and persecution. You must submit to all these evils of civilization with a free resignation ; it is the natural condition of good, jo«r excel- lence, of the only good, and you ought to respect it under this head. In all these evils j-ou ought onl}' to deplore what is morally evil in them, and you must do so not with cowardl}' tears onlj-. Eather watch to remain pure j-ourself in the midst of these impurities, free amidst this slavery, constant with yqjirself in the midst of these capri- cious changes, a faithful observer of the law amidst this_ anarchy. Be not frightened at the disorder that is with- out jou, but at the disorder which is within ; aspire after unity, but seek it not in uniformity ; aspire after repose, but through equilibrium, and not by suspending the action of your faculties. This nature which you envj- in the being destitute of reason deserves no esteem : it is not worth a wish. You have passed beyond it ; it ought to ••smain for ever behind you. The ladder that carried you having given wa}- under your foot, the only thing for you to do is to seize again on the moral law freelj', with a free consciousness, a free will, or else to roll down, hopeless of safety, into a bottomless abyss. _^ But when you have consoled 50urself for having lostThe "^ happiness of nature, let its perfection be a model to your ! 284 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. heart. If 3- ou can issue from the circle in which art keeps you enclosed and find nature again, if it shows itself to you in its greatness and in its calm, in its simple beauty, in its childlike innocence and simplicity, oh ! then pause before its image, cultivate this feeling lovingly. It is worthy of you, and of what is noblest in man. Let it no more come into 3'our mind to change with it ; rather embrace it, absorb it into your being, and tr}' to associate the infinite advantage it has over you with that infinite prerogati^-e that is peculiar to you, and let the divine issue from this sublime union. Let nature breathe around j'ou like a lovel}' idyl, where far from artifice and its wanderings you may alwaj'S find j'ourself again, where j'ou maj- go to draw fresh courage, a new confidence, to resume j-our course, and kindle again in j^our heart the flame of the ideal, so readil}^ extinguished amidst the tempests of life. If we think of that beautiful nature which surrounded the ancient Greeks, if we remember hoTV intimately that jieople, under its blessed skj-, could live with that free nature ; how their mode of imagining, and of feeling, and their manners, approached far nearer than ours to the sim- plicity of nature, how faithfully the works of their poets express this ; we must necessarily remark, as a strange fact, that so few traces are met among them of that senti- mental interest that we moderns ever take in the scenes of jaature and in natural characters. I admit that the Greeks are superiorly exact and faithful in their descriptions of nature. They reproduce then- details with care, but we see that they take no more interest in them and more heart in them than in describing a vestment, a shield, armor, & piece of furniture, or any production of the mechanical arts. In their love for the object it seems that thej' make no diflference between what exists in itself and what owes its existence to art, to the human will. It seems that nature interests their minds and their curiosity more than moral feeling. They do not attach themselves to it with "that depth of feeling, with that gentle melancholj', that characterize the moderns. Naj-, more, hy personifying nature in its particular phenomena, b}- deifying it, by representing its effects as the acts of free being, they take from it that character of calm necessity which is pre- ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 285 cisely what makes it so attractive to us. Their impatient imagination only traverses nature to pass beyond it to the drama of human life. It only takes pleasure in the spectacle of what is living and free ; it requires characters, acts, the accidents of fortune and of manners ; and whilst it happens with us, at least in certain moral dispositions, to curse our prerogative, this free will, which exposes us to so many combats with ourselves, to so manj- anxieties and errors, and to wish to exchange it for the condition of beings destitute of reason, for that fatal existence that no longer admits of anj- choice, but which is so calm in its uniformity ; — while we do this, the Greeks, on the con- trarj', onlj' have their imagination occupied in retracing human nature in the inanimate world, and in giving to the will an influence where blind necessity rnles. Whence can arise this diflJ'erence between the spirit of the ancients and the modern spirit? How comes it that, being, for all that relates to nature, incomparably below the ancients, we are superior to them preciselj- on this point, that we render a more complete homage to nature ; that we have a closer attachment to it ; and that we are capable of embracing even the inanimate world with the most ardent sensibilit}'. It is because nature, in our time, is no longer in man, and that we no longer en- counter it in its primitive truth, except out of humanity, in the inanimate world. It is not because we are more con- formable to nature — qui^ the contrarj- ; it is because in our social relations, in our mode of existence, in our manners, we are in opposition with nativre. This is what leads us, when the instinct of truth and of simplicity is awakened — this instinct which, like the moral aptitude from which it proceeds, lives incorruptible and indelible in everj' human heart — to procure for it in the physical world the satis- faction which there is no hope of finding in the moral order. This is the reason why the feeling that attaches us "to nature is connected so closely with that which makes us regret our infancy, forever flown, and our primitive innocence. Our childhood is all that remains of nature in humanity, such as civilization has made it, of untouched, unmutilated nature. It is, therefore, not wonderful, when we meet out of us the impress of nature, that we are always brought back to- the idea of our childhood. 286 ^STHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. It was quite different with the Greeks in antiquity. Civilization with them did not degenerate, nor was it carried to such an excess that it was necessary to break with nature. The entire structure of their social life re- posed on feelings, and not on a factitious conception, on a work of art. Their very theology was the inspiration of a simple spirit, the fruit of a joyous imagination, and not, like the ecclesiastical dogmas of modern nations, subtle combinations of the understanding. Since, therefore, the ^Greeks had not lost sight of nature in humanity, they had no reason, when meeting it out of man, to be surprised at their discovery, and they would not feel verj' imperiously the need of objects in which nature could be retraced. In accord with themselves, happy in feeling themselves men, they would of necessity keep to humanity as to what Tvas greatest to them, and they must needs tay to make all the rest approach it ; while we, who are not in accord with ourselves — we who are discon tented with the experience we have made of our humanitj' - — have no more pressing interest than to fly out of it and to remove from our sight a so ill-fashioned form. The feeling of which we are treating here is, therefore, not that which was known by the ancients ; it approaches far more nearlj- that which we ourselves experience for the ancients. The ancients felt naturally ; we, on our part, feel what is natural. It was certainly a verj- different inspiration that filled the soul of Homer, when he depicted his divine cowherd * giving hospitality to Ulysses, from that which agitated the soul of the young Werther at the moment when he read the " Odyssey " f on issuing from an assembly in which he had only found tedium. The feeling we experience for nature resembles that of a sick man for health. ~~ As soon as nature gradually vanishes from human life — that is, in proportion as it ceases to be experienced as a subject (active and passive) — we see it dawn and increase in the poetical world in the guise of an idea and as an object. The people who have carried farthest the want 'of nature, and at the same time the reflections on that matter, must needs have been the people who at the * ATof h((iopPdi, "Odj^ssey," xiv. 413, etc. t Werther, May 26, June 21, August 28, May 9, etc. ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 287 same time were most struck with this phenomenon of the simple^ and gave it a name. If I am not mistaken, this people was the French. But the feeling of the simple, and the interest we take in it, must naturally go much farther back, and it dates from the time when the moral sense and the sesthetical sense began to be corrupt. This modification in the manner of feeling is exceedingly^ striking in Euripides, for example, if compared with his predecessors, especiallj' ^schj'lus ; and yet Euripides was the favorite poet of his time. The same revolution is perceptible in the ancient historians. Horace, the poet of a cultivated and corrupt epoch, praises, under the shady- groves of Tibur, the calm and happiness of the countr^^, and he might be termed the true founder of this senti- mental poetry, of which he has remained the unsurpassed model. In Propertius, Virgil, and others, we find also traces of this mode of feeling ; less of it is found in Ovid, who would have required for that more abundance of heart, and who in his exile at Tomes sorrowfully regrets the happiness that Horace so readily dispensed with in his villa at Tibur. It is in the fundamental idea of poetry that the poet is everywhere the guardian of nature. When he can no longer entirely fill this part, and has alread3- in himself suffered the deleterious influence of arbitrary and facti- tious forms, or has had to struggle against this influence, he presents himself as the witness of nature and as its avenger. The poet will, therefore, be the expression of nature itself, or his part will be to seek it, if men have lost sight of it. Hence arise two kinds of poetry, which embrace and exhaust the entire field of poetry. All poets — I mean those who are really so — will belong, according to the time when they flourish, according to the accidental circumstances that have influenced their education gene- rall}', and the different dispositions of mind through which they pass, will belong, I say, to the order of the sentimental poetry or to simple poetrj-. The poet of a 3'oung world, simple and inspired, as also the poet who at an epoch of artificial civilization approaches nearest to the primitive bards, is austere and prudish, like the virginal Diana in her forests. Wholly unconfiding, he 288 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS hides himself from the heart that seeks him, from the desire that wishes to embrace him. It is not rare for the dry truth with which he treats his subject to resemble insensibilitjr. The whole object possesses him, and to reach his heart it does not suffice, as with metals of little value, to stir up the surface ; as with pure gold, you must go down to the lowest depths. Like the Deit3' behind this Universe, the simple poet hides himself behind his work ; he is himself his work, and his work is himself. A man must be no longer worthy of the work, nor understand it, or be tired of it, to be even anxious to learn who is its author. Such appears to us, for instance. Homer in antiquity, and Shakespeare among moderns : two natures infinitely different and separated in time by an abyss, but perfectly identical as to this trait of character. When, at a very youthful age, I became first acquainted with Shakespeare, I was displeased with his coldness, with his insensibilitj-, which allows him to jest even in the most pathetic mo- ments, to disturb the impression of the most harrowing scenes in " Hamlet," in " King Lear," and in '' Macbeth," etc., by mixing with them the buffooneries of a madman. I was revolted by his insensibility, which allowed him to pause sometimes at places where my sensibility would bid me hasten and bear me along, and which sometimes carried him away with indifference when my heart would be so happy to pause. Though I was accustomed, by the prac- tice of modern poets, to seek at once the poet in his works, to meet his heart, to reflect with him in his theme — in a word, to see the object in the subject — I could not bear that the poet could in Shakespeare never be seized, that he would never give me an account of himself. For some years Shakespeare had been the object of my studj' and of all my respect before I had learned to love his personality'. I was not yet able to comprehend nature at first hand. All that my ej'es could bear was its image only, reflected bj' the understanding and arranged bj' rules : and on this score the sentimental poetry of the French, or that of the Germans of 1750 to 1780, was what suited me best. For the rest, I do not blush at this childish judgment : adult critics pronounced in that day in the same way, and car- ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 289 ried their simplicity so far as to publish their decisions to the world. The same thing happened to me in the ease of Homer, with whom I made acquaintance at a later date. I re- member now that remarkable passage of the sixth book of the " Iliad," where Glaucus and Diomed meet each other in the strife, and then, recognizing each other as host and guest, exchange presents. With this touching picture of the piety with which the laws of hospituUiy were ob- served even in war, maj"^ be compared a picture of chival- rous generosity in Ariosto. The knights, rivals in love, Ferragus and Einaldo — the former a Saracen, the latter a Christian — after having fought to extremity, all covered with wounds, make peace together, and mount the same horse to go and seek the fugitive Angelica. These two examples, however different in other respects, are very similar with regard to the impression produced on our heart : both represent the noble victory of moral feeling over passion, and touch us bj' the simphcity of feeling dis- plajed in them. But what a difference in the wa}- in which the two poets go to work to describe two such analogous scenes ! Ariosto, who belongs to an advanced epoch, to a world where simplicitj' of manners no longer existed, in relating this trait, cannot conceal the astonishment, the admiration, he feels at it. He measures the distance from those manners to the manners of his own age, and this feeling of astonishment is too strong for him . He abandons suddenly the painting of the object, and comes himself on the scene in person. ' This beautiful stanza is well known, and has been always speciallj- admired at all times : — "Oh nobleness, oh generosity- of the ancient manners of chivalry ! These were rivals, separated b}- their faith, suffering bitter pain throughout their fi-ames in consequence of a desperate combat ; and, without any suspicion, behold them riding in company along dark and winding paths. Stimulated by four spurs, the horse hastens his pace till they arrive at the place where the road divides." * Now let us turn to old Homer. Scarcely has Diomed learned b}' the story of Glaucus, his adversary, that the latter has been, from the time of their fathers, the host and friend of his family, when he drives his lance-,into the * " Orlando Furioso," canto i., stanza 32. 290 ^STHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. and friend of his familj^ when he drives his lance into the ground, converses familiarly with him, and both agree henceforth to avoid each other in the strife. But let us hear Homer himself : — " Thus, then, I am for thee a faithful host in Argos, and thou to me in Lycia, when I shall visit that country'. "We shall, therefore, avoid our lances meeting in the strife. Are there not for me other Trojans or brave allies to kill when a god shall offer them to me and my steps shall reach them ? And for thee, Glaucus, are there not enough Achseans, that thou ma3'est immolate whom thou wishest? But let us exchange our arms, in order that others may also see that we boast of having been hosts and guests at the time of our fathers." Thus they spoke, and, rushing from their chariots, they seized each other's hands, and swore friendship the one to the other." * It would have been difficult for a modern poet (at least to one who would be modern in the moral sense of the term) even to wait as long as this before expressing his joy in the presence of such an action. We should pardon this in him the more easily, because we also, in reading it, feel that our heart makes a pause here, and readily turns aside from the object to bring back its thoughts on itself. But there is not the least trace of this in Homer. As if he had been relating something that is seen everj' day — nay, more, as if he had no heart beating in bis breast — he continues, with his dry truthfulness : — • " Then the son of Satu'rn blinded Glaucus, who, ex- changing his armor with Diomed, gave him golden arms of the value of one hecatomb, for brass arms only worth nine beeves." f The poets of this order, — the genuinely simple poets, are scarcely any longer in their place in this artificial age. Accordingly they are scarcely possible in it, or at least they are only possible on the condition of traversing their age, like scared per sojis, at a running pace, and of being preserved by a happy star from the influence of their age, which would mutilate their genius. Never, for a,j and forever, will society produce these poets ; but out of society they still appear sometimes at intervals, rather, I * Pope's " Iliad," vi. 264-287. t " Iliad," vi. 234-236. ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 291 admit, as strangers, who excite wonder, or as ill-trained children of nature, who give offence. These apparitions, so very comforting for the artist who studies them, and for the real connoisseur, who knows how to appreciate them, are, as a general conclusion, in the age when they are begotten, to a very small degree preposterous. The seal of empire is stamped on their brow, and we, — we ask the Muses to cradle us, to carry us in their arms. The critics, as regular constables of art, detest these poets as disturbers of rules or of limits. Homer himself maj' have been onlj' indebted to the testimony of ten centuries - for the reward these arista rchs are kindlj' willing to concede him. Moreover, they find it a hard matter to maintain their rules against his example, or his authority against their rules. Sentimental Poetry. I have previously remarked that the poet is nature, or he seeks nature. In the former case, he is a simple poet, in the second case, a sentimental poet. The poetic spirit is immortal, nor can it disappear from humanity ; it can only disappear with humanity itself, or with the aptitude to be a man, a human being. And actually, though man by the freedom of his imagination and of his understanding departs from simplicitj', from truth, from the necessitj' of*nature, not only a road always remains open to him to return to it, but, moreover, a powerful and indestructible instinct, the moral instinct, brings him incessantly back to nature ; and it is precisel}- the poetical faculty that is united to this instinct by the ties of the closest relationship. Thus man does not lose the poetic faculty- directl.y he parts with the simplicity of nature ; only this faculty acts out of him in another direction. Even at present nature is the only flame that kindles and warms the poetic soul. From nature alone it obtains all its force ; to nature alone it speaks in the artificial cul- ture-seeking man. Any other form of displaying its activ- ity is remote from the poetic spirit. Accordingly it may be remarked that it is incorrect to apply the expression 292 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. poetic to any of the so-styled productions of wit, thougli the hiigh credit given to French literature ' has led people for a long period to class them in that categor3-. I repeat that at present, even in the existing phase of culture, it is still nature that powerfully stirs up the poetic spirit, only its present relation to nature is of a diflferent order from formerly'. ~ As long as man dwells in a state of pure nature (I mean pure and not coarse nature), all his being acts at once like a simple sensuous unit}-, hke a harmonious whole. The senses and reason, the receptive faculty and the spontan- eously active faculty, have not been as yet separated in their respective functions : a fortiori they are not yet in 'contradiction with each other. Then the feelings of man are not the formless plaj- of chance ; nor are his thoughts an empt}' play of the imagination, without any value. His feelings proceed from the law of necessity ; his thoughts from reality. But when man enters the state of civiliza- tion, and art has fashioned him, this sensuous harmony which was in him disappears, and henceforth he can only manifest himself as a ii.ond unity., that is, as aspiring to unity. The harmony tiiat existed as a fact in the former state, the harmony of feeling and thought, onl^- exists now in an ideal state. It is no longer in him, but out of him ; it is a conception of thought which he must begin hj real- izing in himself ; it is no longer a fact, a reality of his life. Well, now let us take the idea of poetry, which is nothmg else than expressing humanity as completely us possible, and let us applj- this idea to these two states. We shall be brought to infer that, on the one hand, in the state of natural simplicity, when all the faculties of man are exert- ed together, his being still manifests itself in a harmonious unity, where, consequently, the totality of his nature ex- presses itself in reality itself, the part of the fioet is neces- sarily to imitate the real as completely as is possible. In the state of civilization, on the contrarj-, when this harmo- nious competition of the whole of human nature is no longer anything but an idea, the part of the poet is necessarily to raise reality to the ideal, or, what amounts to the same thing, to represent the ideal. And, actually, these are the only two ways in which, in general, the iESTHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 203 poetic genius can manifest itself. Their great fiifference is quite evident, but though there be great opposition be- tween tliem, a higher idea exists that embraces both, and there is no cause to be astonished if this idea coincides with tlie very idea of humanity. This is not the place to pursue this thought anj^ further, as it would require a separate discussion to place it in its full light. But if we only compare the modern and ancient ^Joets together, not according to the accidental forms which they maj- have emploj'ed, but according to their spirit, we shall be easily convinced of the truth of this thought. The thing that touches us in the ancient poets is nature ; it is the truth of sense, it is a present and a living reality : modern poets touch us through the medium of ideas. The path followed b}- modern poets is moreover that necessarily followed by man generall}-, individuals as well as the species. Nature reconciles man with himself; art divides and disunites him ; the ideal brings him back to unit}-. Now, the ideal bemg an infinite that he never succeeds in reaching, it follows that civilized man can never become perfect in his kind, while the man of nature can become so in his. Accordinglj' in relation to perfec- tion one would be infinitely below the other, if we onl}' considered the relation in which the}' are both to their own kind and to their maximum. If, on the other hand, it is the kinds that are compared together, it is ascertamed that the end to which man tends b}- civilization is infiniteh" superior to that which h? reaches through nature. Thus one has his reward, because having forobject a finite mag- nitude, he completel}' reaches this object ; the merit of the other is to approach an object that is of infinite magni- tude. Now, as there are only degrees, and as there is only progress in the second of these evolutions, it follows that the relative merit of the man engaged in the w&js of civilization is never determinable in general, though this man, taking the individuals separateh', is necessarily at a disadvantage, compared with the man in whom nature acts in all its perfection. But we know also that humanitj* can- not reach its final end except by j^roffress, and that the man of nature cannot make progress save through culture, and consequently bj- passing himself through the way of 294 iESTHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. ci^■ilization. Accordingly there is no occasion to ask with whicli of the two the advantage must remain, considering this last end. All that we say here of the different forms of humanitj- ma^' be applied equally to the two orders of poets who correspond to them. Accordingly it would have been desirable not to com- pare at all the ancient and the modern poets, the simple and the sentimental poets, or onl}' to compare them by re- ferring them to a higher idea y_ since there is reallj- onh' one) which embraces both. For, sooth to say, if we begin b}' forming a specific idea of poetr}-, merelj' from the ancient poets, nothing is easier, but also nothing is more vulgar, than to depreciate the moderns b^' this comparison. If persons wish to confine the name of poetry to that which has in all times produced the same impression in simple nature, this places them in the necessitj- of con- testing the title of poet in the moderns precise!}' in that which constitutes their highest beauties, their greatest originality and sublimit}' ; for precisel}' in the points where they excel the most, it is the child of civilization whom they address, and thej have nothing to say to the simple child of nature. To the man who is not disposed beforehand to issue from reality in order to enter the field of the ideal, the richest and most substantial poetry is an empty appear- ance, and the sublimest flights of poetic inspiration are an exaggeration. Never will a reasonable man think of placing alongside Homer, in his grandest episodes, anj' of our modern poets ; and it has a discordant and ridiculous effect to hear Milton or Klopstock honored with the name of a "new Homer." But take in modern poets what characterizes them, what makes their special merit, and try to compare any ancient poet with them iu-this point, the}' will not be able to support the comparison any bet- ter, and Homer less than any other. I should express it thus : the power of the ancients consists in compressing objects into the finite, and the moderns excel in the art of the infinite. What we have said here may be extended to the fine arts in general, except certain restrictions that are self- ^STHETXOAL LETTEliS AND ESSAYS. 295 evident. If, then, the strength of the artists of antiquity' consists in determining and limiting objects, we must no longer wonder that in the iield of the plastic arts the ancients remain so far superior to the moderns, nor espe- cially that poetry and the plastic arts with the moderns, compared respectively with what they were among the ancients, do not offer the same relative value. This is be- cause an object that addresses itself to the ej-es is only perfect in proportion as the object is clearly limited in it ; whilst a work that is addressed to the imagination can also reach the perfection which is proper to it by means of the ideal and the infinite. This is whj- the superiority of the moderns in what relates to ideas is not of great aid to them in the plastic arts, where it is necessarj- for them to determine in space^ with the greatest precision, the image which their imagination has conceived, and where they must therefore measure themselves with the ancient artist just on a point where his superiority cannot be contested. In the matter of poetry it is another affair, and if the ad- vantage is still with the ancients on that ground, as re- spects the simplicit}' of forms — all that can be represented by sensuous features, all that is something bodily — yet, on the other hand, the moderns have the advantage over the ancients as regards fundamental wealth, and all that can neither be represented nor translated by sensuous signs, in short, for all that is called mind and idea in the works of art. - From the moment that the simple poet is content to fol- low simple nature and feeling, that he is contented with the imitation of the real world, he can only be placed, with regard to his subject, in a single relation. And in this respect he has no choice as to the manner of treating it. If simple poetry produces different impressions — I do not, of course, speak of the impressions that are con- nected with the nature of the subject, but only of those that are dependent on poetic execution — the whole differ- ence is in the degree ; there is onlj' one waj' of feeling, which varies from more to less ; even the diversity of ex- ternal forms changes nothing in the qualitj* of esthetic impressions. Whether the form be Ij-ric or epic, dramatic or descriptive, we can receive an impression either stronger 296 iESTHETIOAt, LETTERS AND ESSAYS. or weaker, but if we remove what is connected with the ■nature of the subject, we shall always be affected in the same way. The feeling we experience is absolutely iden- tical ; it proceeds entirely' from one single and the same element to such a degree that we are unable to make any distinction. The very difference of tongues and that of times does not here occasion anj- diversity, for their strict unity of origin and of effect is precisely a characteristic of simple poetry. It is quite different with sentimental poetry. The sen- timental poet reflects on the impression produced on him by objects ; and it is only on this reflection that his poetic force is based. It follows that the sentimental poet is always concerned with two opposite forces, has two modes of representing objects to himself, and of feeling them ; these are, the real or limited, and the ideal or infinite ; and the mixed feeling that he will awaken will alwa3's testify' to this dualit}- of origin. Sentimental poetry thus admit- ting more than one principle, it remains to know which of the two will be predominant in the poet, both in his fash- ion of feeling and in that of representing the object ; and consequently a difference in the mode of treating it is pos- sible. Here, then, a new subject is presented : shall thO' poet attach himself to the real or the ideal? to the real as an object of aversion and of disgust, or to the ideal as an object of inclination? The poet will therefore be able to treat the same subject either in its satirical aspect or in its elegiac aspect, — taking these words in a larger sense, which will be explained in the sequel : everj- sentimental poet will of necessity become attached to one or the other of these two modes of feeling. Satirical Poetet. The poet is a satirist when he takes as subject the dis- tance at which things are from nature, and the contrast between realitj^ and the ideal : as regards the impression received bj' the soul, these two subjects blend into the same. In the execution, he may place earnestness and passion, or jests and levity, according as he takes pleasure ^STHBTIOAL LETTEKa AND ESSAYS, 291 in the domain of the will or in that of the understanding. In the former case it is avenging and pathetic satire ; in the second case it is sportive, humorous, and mirthful satire. Properly speaking, the object of poetry is not compat- ible either with the tone of punishment or that of amuse- ment. The former is too grave for play, which should be the main feature of poetry ; the latter is too trifling for seriousness, which should form the basis of all poetic play. Our mind is necessarily interested in moral con- tradictions, and these deprive the mind of its liberty. Nevertheless, all personal interest, and reference to a per- sonal necessity, should be banished from poetic feeling. But mental contradictions do not touch the heart, never- theless the poet deals with the highest interests of the heart — nature and the ideal. Accordingly it is a hard matter for him not to violate the poetic form in pathetic satire, because this form consists in the liberty of move- ment ; and in sportive satire he is ver}- apt to miss the true spirit of poetry, which ought to be the infinite. The problem can only be solved in one way : by the pathetic ; satire assuming the character of the sublime, and the playful satire acquiring poetic substance by enveloping the i theme in beaut3^ — In satire, the real as imperfection is opposed to the ideal, considered as the highest reality. In other respects it is by no means esseiftial that the ideal should be ex- pressly represented, provided the poet knows how to awaken it in our souls, but he must in all cases awaken it, otherwise he will exert absolutely no poetic action. Thus reality is here a necessary object of aversion ; but it is also necessary, for the whole question centres here, that this aversion should come necessarily from the ideal, which is opposed to reality. To make this clear — this aversion might proceed from a purely sensuous source, and repose onl3' on a want of which the satisfaction finds obstacles in the real. How often, in fact, we think we feel against society a moral discontent, while we are simply soured by the obstacles that it opposes to our inclination. It is this entirely material interest that the vulgar satirist brings into play ; and as by this road he never fails to call forth 298 jJiSTHETICAL LETTERS AKC ESSAYS. in US movements connected with tlie affections, he fancies that he holds our heart in his hand, and thinks he has graduated in the pathetic. But all pathos derived from this source is unworthy of poetry, which ought only to move us through the medium of ideas, and reach our heart onlj' bj- passing through the reason. Moreover, this im- pure and material pathos will never have its effect on minds, except by over-exciting the affective faculties and „ by occupying our hearts with painful feelings ; in this it / differs entirely from the trulj' poetic pathos, which raises I in us the feeling of moral independence, and which is rec- ' ognized by the freedom of our mind persisting in it even while it is in the state of affection. And, in fact, when the emotion emanates from the ideal opposed to the real, the sublime beauty of the ideal corrects all impression of restraint ; and the grandeur of the idea with which we are imbued raises us above all the limits of experience. Thus in the representation of some revolting realitj, the essen- tial thing is that the necessary be the foundation on which the poet or the narrator places the real : that he know how to dispose our mind for ideas. Provided the point from which we see and judge be elevated, it matters little if the object be low and far beneath us. When the historian Tacitus depicts the profound decadence of the Romans of the first century, it is a great soul which from a loftier po- sition lets his looks drop down on a low object ; and the disposition in which he places us is truly poetic, because it is the height where he is himself placed, and where he has succeeded in raising us, which alone renders so per- ceptible the baseness of the object. Accordingly the satire of pathos must always issue from a mind deeply imbued with the ideal. It is nothing but an impulsion towards harmonj' that can give rise to that deep feeling of moral opposition and that ardent indignation against moral obliquitj^ which amounted to the fulness of enthusiasm in Juvenal, Swift, Eousseau, Haller, and others. These same poets would have suc- ceeded equally well in forms of poetry relating to all that is tender and touching in feeling, and it was only the accidents of life in their early days that diverted their minds into other walks. Nay, some amongst them actually ^STHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 299 tried their hand successfully in these other branches of poetry. The poets whose names have been just mentioned lived either at a period of degeneracy, and had scenes of painful moral obliquity presented to their view, or personal troubles had combined to fill their souls with bitter feelings. The strictly austere spirit in which Rousseau, Haller, and others paint reality is a natural result, moreover, of the philosophical mind, when with rigid adherence to laws of thought it separates the mere phenomenon from the sub- stance of things. Yet these outer and contingent influences, which alwa3's put restraint on the mind, should never be allowed to do more than decide the direction taken by enthusiasm, nor should they ever give the material for it. The substance ought always to remain unchanged, emancipated from all external motion or stimulus, and it ought to issue from an ardent impulsion towards the ideal, which forms the only true motive that can be put forth for satirical poetry, and indeed for all sentimental poetry. While the satire of pathos is only adapted to elevated minds, playful satire can only be adequately represented b}' a heart imbued with beauty. The former is preserved from triviality by the serious nature of the theme ; but the latter, whose proper sphere is confined to the treatment of subjects of morally unimportant nature, would infallibly adopt the form of frivolitj^ and be deprived of all poetic dignity, were it not th»t the substance is ennobled by the form, and did not the personal dignity of the poet com- pensate for the insignificance of the subject. Now, it is only given to mind imbued with beauty to impress its character, its entire image, on each of its manifestations, independently of the object of its manifestations. A sub- lime soul can onlj- make itself known as such by single victories over the rebellion of the senses, only in certain moments of exaltation, and by efforts of short duration. In a mind imbued with beauty., on the contrary, the ideal acts in the same manner as nature, and therefore contin- uously ; accordingly it can manifest itself in it in a state of repose. The deep sea never appears more sublime than when it is agitated ; the true beauty of a clear stream is in its peaceful course. 300 iESTHETICAL LETTER8 AND ESSAYS. The question has often been raised as to the comparative preference to be awarded to tragedy or comedy. If the question is confined merely to their respective themes, it is certain tiiat tragedy has the advantage. But if our inquiry be directed to ascertain which has the more important ^ - personality-, it is probable that a decision may be given in ' favor of corned}'. In tragedy the theme in itself does ; great things ; in comedy the object does nothing and 1 the poet all. Now, as in the judgments of taste no \ account must be kept of the matter treated of, it follows naturally that the aesthetic value of these two kinds will be in an inverse ratio to the proper importance of their themes. The tragic poet is supported by the theme, while the comic poet, on the contrary, has to keep up the aesthetic character of his theme by his own individual influence. The former may soar, which is not a very difficult matter, but the latter has to remain one and the same in tone ; he has to be in the elevated region of art, where he must be at home, but where the tragic poet has to be projected and elevated by a bound. And this is precisel}' what distin- guishes a soul of beauty from a sublime soul. A soul of beauty bears in itself by anticipation all great ideas ; they flow without constraint and without difficulty from its very nature — an infinite nature, at least in potency, at \ whatever point of its career you seize it. A sublime soul ', can rise to all kinds of greatness, but by an effort ; it can I tear itself from all bondage, to all that limits and constrains ; it, but only by strength of will. Consequently the sublime ! soul is only free by broken efforts ; the other with ease and always. The noble task of comedy is to produce and keep up in us this freedom of mind, just as the end of tragedj^ is to re-establish in us this freedom of mind by aesthetic ways, when it has been violently suspended bj- passion. Consequently it is necessary that in tragedy the poet, as if he made an experiment, should artificially suspend our freedom of mind, since tragedy shows its poetic virtue by re-establishing it ; in comedj-, on the other hand, care must be taken that things never reach this suspension of freedom. ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 301 It is for this reason that the tragic poet invariablj' treats his theme in a practical manner, and the comic poet in a theoretic manner, even when the former, as happened with Lessing in his "Nathan," should have the curious fancy to select a tlieoretical, and the latter should have that of choosing a practical subject. A piece is constituted a tragedy or a comedy not by the sphere from which the theme is taken, but by the tribunal before which it is judged. A tragic poet ought never to indulge in tranquil reasoning, and ought always to gain the interest of the heart ; but the comic poet ought to shun the pathetic and bring into plaj' the understanding. The former displays his art bj" creating continual excitement, the latter by perpetually subduing his passion ; and it is natural that the art in both cases should acquire magnitude and strength in proportion as the theme of one poet is abstract and that of the other pathetic in character. Accordingly, if tragedy sets out from a more exalted place, it must be allowed, on the other hand, that comedy aims at a more important end ; and if this end could be actually attained it would make all tragedy not only nnnecessary, but impossible. The aim that comedy has in view is the same as that of the highest destiny of man, and this consists in liberating himself from the influence of violent passions, and taking a calm and lucid survey of all that surrounds him, and also of his own being, and of seeing everywhere occurrence rather than fate or hsfzard, and ultimately rather smiling at the absurdities than shedding tears and feeling anger at sight of the wickedness of man. It frequently happens in human life that facility of imagination, agreeable talents, a good-natured mirthful- ness are taken for ornaments of the mind. The same fact is discerned in the case of poetical displays. Now, public taste scarcely if ever soars above the sphere of the agreeable, and authors gifted with this sort of ele- gance of mind and style do not find it a difficult matter to usurp a glorj- which is or ought to be the reward of so much real labor. Nevertheless, an infallible text exists to enable us to discriminate a natural facihty of manner from ideal gentleness, and qualities that consist in notlung more than natural virtue from genuine moral worth of 302 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. character. This test is presented by trials such as those presented by difficulty and events offering great oppor- tunities. Placed in positions of this liind, the genius whose essence is elegance is sure infallibly to fall into platitudes, and that virtue which only results from natural causes drops down to a material sphere. But a mind imbued with true and spiritual beautj' is in cases of the kind we have supposed sure to be elevated to the highest sphere of character and of feeling. So long as Lucian merely furnishes absurdity, as in his "Wishes," in the "Lapithas," in "Jupiter Tragoedus," etc., he is onlj' a humorist, and gratifies us by his sportive humor ; but he changes character in many passages in his "Nigrinus," his " Timon," and his " Alexander," when his satire directs its shafts against moral depravity. Thus he begins in his " Nigrinus" his picture of the degraded corruption of Rome at that time in this way : " Wretch, why didst thou quit Greece, the sunlight, and that free and happy life? Why didst thou come here into this turmoil of splendid slavery, of service and festivals, of sycophants, flatterers, poisoners, orphan-robbers, and false friends?" It is on such occasions that the poet ought to show the lofty earnestness of soul which has to form the basis of all plays, if a poetical character is to be obtained by them. A serious intention may even be detected under the malic- ious jests with which Lucian and Aristophanes pursue Soc- rates. Their purpose is to avenge truth against sophistry, and to do combat for an ideal which is not always promi- nently put forward. There can be no doubt that Lucian has justified this character in his Diogenes and Demonax. Again, among modern writers, how gra,ve and beautiful is the character depicted on all occasions by Cervantes in his Eton Quixote ! How splendid must have been the ideal tiiat filled the mind of a. poet who created a Tom .Tones and a Sophonisba 1 How deeply and strongly our hearts are moved by the jests of Yorick when he pleases ! I detect this seriousness also in our own Wieland : even the wanton sportiveness of his humor is elevated and impeded by the goodness of his heart; it has an influence even on his rhythm ; nor does he ever lack elastic power, when it is his wish, to raise us up to the most elevated planes of beauty and of thought. ^STHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 303 The same judgment cannot be pronounced on the satire of Voltaire. No doubt, also, in his case, it is the truth and simplicity of nature which here and there makes us experience poetic emotions, whether he really encounters nature and depicts it in a simple character, as manj' times in his " Ingenu ; " or whether he seeks it and avenges it as in his " Candide" and elsewhere. But when neither one nor the other takes place, he can doubtless amuse us with his fine wit, but he assuredly never touches us as a poet. There is always rather too little of the serious under his raillerj-, and this is what makes his vocation as poet justly suspicious. You alwa3'S meet his intelligence only ; never his feelings. No ideal can be detected under this light gauze envelope ; scarcely can anj'thing absolutely fixed be found under this perpetual movement. His prodigious diversit3' of externals and forms, far from proving anj'thing in favor of the inner fulness of his inspiration, rather testifies to the contrarj' ; for he has exhausted all forms without finding a single one on which he has succeeded in impressing his heart. We are almost driven to fear that in the case of his rich talent the povertj' of lieart alone determined his choice of satire. And how could we other- wise explain the fact that he could pursue so long a road without ever issuing from its narrow rut ? Whatever maj' be the variety of matter and of external forms, we see the inner form return everjwhere with its sterile and eter- nal uniformity, and in Sipite of his so productive career, he never accomplished in himself the circle of humanity, that circle which we see joyfully traversed throughout by the satirists previously named. Elegiac Poetry. When the poet opposes nature to art , and the ideal to the real, so that nature and the ideal form the principal object of his pictures, and that the pleasure we take in them is the dominant impression, I call him an elegiac poet. In this kind, as well as in satire, I distinguish two classes. Either nature and the ideal are objects of sadness, when one is represented as lost to man and the other as 304 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. unattalned ; or both are objects of joj', being represented to us as reality. In the first case it is elegy in the narrow- er sense of the term ; in the second case it is the idj'l in its most extended acceptation. Indignation in the pathetic and ridicule in mirthful satire are occasioned by an enthusiasm which the ideal has excited ; and thus also sadness should issue from the same source in elegy. It is this, and this only, that gives poetic value to elegy, and any other origin for this description of poetical effusion is entirely beneath the dignity of poetry. The elegiac poet seeks after nature, but he strives to find her in her beauty, and not only in her mirth ; in her agreement with conception, and not merely in her facile disposition towards the requirements and demands of sense. Melancholy at the privation of joys, complaints at the disappearance of the world's golden age, or at the vanished happiness of youth, affection, etc., can only become the proper themes for elegiac poetry if those con- ditions implying peace and calm in the sphere of the senses can moreover be portrayed as states of moral harmony, ~0n this account I cannot bring myself to regard as poetry the complaints of Ovid, which he transmitted from his place of exile by the Black Sea ; nor would they appear so tome however touching and however full of passages of the highest poetry they might be. His sufi'ering is too devoid of spirit, and nobleness. His lamentations display a want of strength and enthusiasm ; though they may not reflect the traces of a vulgar soul, they display a low and sensu- ous condition of a noble spirit that has been trampled into the dust by its hard destiny. If, indeed, we call to mind that his regrets are directed to Rome, in the Augustan age, we forgive him the pain he sufi'ers ; but even Borne in all its splendor, except it be transfigured by the imagination, is a limited greatness, and therefore a subject unworthy of poetry, which, raised above every trace of the actual, ought only to mourn over what is infinite. Thus the object of poetic complaint ought never to be an external object, but only an internal and ideal object ; even when it deplores a real loss, it must begin by making it an ideal loss. The proper work of the poet consists in bringing back the finite object to the proportions of the iESTHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 305 (nflnite. Consequently the external matter of elegj-, con- sidered in itself, is always indifferent, since poetry can never employ it as it finds it, and because it is onlj- by what it makes of it that it confers on it a poetic dignity, i The elegiac poet seeks nature, but nature as an idea, and; in a degree of perfection that it has never reached in real-j ity, although he weeps over this perfection as something! that has existed and is now lost. When Ossian speaks to us of the days that are no more, and of the heroes that have disappeared, his imagination has long since trans- formed these pictures represented to him by his memory into a pure ideal, and changed these heroes into gods. The different experiences of such or such a life in particu- lar have become extended and confounded in the universal idea of transitoriness, and the bard, deeply moved, pursued by the increase of ruin everywhere present, takes his flight towards heaven, to find there in the course of the sun an emblem of what does not pass away. I turn now to the elegiac poets of modern times. Rousseau, whether considered as a poet or a philosopher, always obeys the same tendency ; to seek nature or to avenge it by art. According to the state of his heart, whether he prefers to seek nature or to avenge it, we see him at one time roused by elegiac feelings, at others show- ing the tone of the satire of Juneval ; and again, as in his Julia, delighting in the sphere of the idyl. His composi- tions have undoubtedly • poetic value, since their object is ideal ; onl^' he does not know liow to treat it in a poetic fashion. No doubt his serious character prevents him from falling into frivolity ; but this seriousness also does not allow him to rise to poetic plaj'. Sometimes absorbed by passion, at others by abstractions, he seldom if ever reaches sesthetic freedom, which the poet ought to maintain ' in spite of his material before his object, and in which he / ought to make tlie reader share. Either he is governed by ' his sickly sensibility and liis impressions become a torture, '■ or the force of thought ciiaiiis down his imagination and I destroys by its strictness of reasoning all the grace of his • pictures. These two faculties, whose reciprocal influence ; and intimate union are what properly make the poet, are j found in this writer in an uncommon degree, and he only 306 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. lacks one thing — it is that the two qualities should mani- ifest themselves actually united ; it is that the proper activ- ity of thought should show itself mixed more vsrith feeling, and the sensuous more with thought. Accordingly, even in the ideal which he has made of human nature, he is too much taken up with the limits of this nature, and not enough with its capabilities ; he always betraj^s a want of phj'sical repose rather than want of moral harmony. His passionate sensuousness must be blamed when, to finish as quickly as possible that struggle in humanity' which offends him, he prefers to carry man back to the unintelligent uni- formity of his primitive condition, rather than see that struggle carried out in the intellectual harmony of perfect cultivation, when, rather than await the fulfilment of art he prefers not to let it begin ; in short, when he prefers to place the aim nearer the earth, and to lower the ideal in order to reach it the sooner and the safer. Among the poets of Germany who belong to this class, I shall only mention here Haller, Kleist, and Klopstock. The character of their poetrj' is sentimental ; it is by the ideal that they touch us, not bj' sensuous reality ; and that not so much because they are themselves nature, as because the}' know how to fill us with enthusiasm for nature. However, what is true in general., as well of these three poets as of every sentimental poet, does not evidently ex- clude the facultj!^ of moving us, in particular y by beauties of the simple genus ; without this they would not be poets. I only mean that it is not their proper and dominant char- acteristic to receive the impression of objects with a calm feeling, simple, easy, and to give forth in like manner the impression received. Involuntarily the imagination in them anticipates intuition, and reflection is in play before the sensuous nature has done its function ; they shut their eyes and stop their ears to plunge into internal meditations. Their souls could not be touched by any impression with- out observing immediately their own movements, without placing before their eyes and outside themselves what takes place in them. It follows from this that we never see the object itself, but what the intelligence and reflection of the poet have made of the object ; and even if this object be the person itself of the poet, even when he wishes ESTHETIC AL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 307 to represent to us his own feelings, we are not informed of his state immediately' or at first hand ; we onlj- see how this state is reflected in his mind and what he has thought of it in the capacity of spectator of himself. When Haller deplores the death of his wife — every one knows this beautiful elegy — and begins in the following manner : — ** If I must needs sing of thy death, O Marian, what a song it would be ! When sighs strive against words, And idea follows fast on idea, " etc., we feel that this description is strictly true, but we feel also that the poet does not communicate to us, properly- speaking, his feelings, but the thoughts that they suggest to him. Accordingly, the emotion we feel on hearing liim is much less vivid ! people remark that the poet's mind must have been singularlj- cooled down to become thus a spectator of his own emotion. Haller scarcely treated any subjects but the super- sensuous, and part of the poems of Klopstock are also of this nature : this choice itself excludes them from the simple kind. Accordingly, in order to treat these super- sensuous themes in a poetic fashion, as no body could be given to tliem, and thej- could not be made the objects of sensuous intuition, it was necessarj- to make them pass from the finite to the infinite, and raise them to the state of objects of spiritual intuition. In general, it may be said, that it is only in thig sense that a didactic poetrj^ can be conceived without involving contradiction ; for, repeat-^ ing again what has been so often said, poetrj' has only two fields, the world of sense and the ideal world, since in the sphere of conceptions, in the world of the understandings it cannot absolutel}' thrive. I confess that I do not know as j-et anj- didactic poem, either among the ancients or "^ among the moderns, where the subject is completel3' brought down to the individual, or purely and completelj- raised to — , the ideal. The most common case, in tlie most happy essays, is where the two principles are used together ; the abstract idea predominates, and the imagination, which ought to reign over the whole domain of poetry, has merely the permission to serve the understanding. A didactic poem in which thought itself would be poetic,' ' 308 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. and would remain so, is a thing whicli we must still wait to see. What we say here of didactic poems in general is true in particular of the poems of Haller. The thought itself of these poems is not poetical, but the execution becomes so sometimes, occasionally by the use of images, at other times by a flight towards the ideal. It is from this last quality only that the poems of Haller belong to this class. Energ3S depth, a pathetic earnestness — these are the traits that distinguish this poet. He has in his soul an ideal that enkindles it, and his ardent love of truth seeks in the peaceful valle3's of the Alps that innocence of the first ages that the world no longer knows. His complaint is deepljf touching ; he retraces in an energetic and almost bitter satire the wanderings of the mind and of the heart, and he loviuglj' portrays the beautiful simplicity of na- ture. Only, in his pictures as well as in his soul, ab- straction prevails too much, and the sensuous is over- weighted 1)3' the intellectual. He constantl3' teaches rather than paints ; and even in his paintings his brush is more energetic than lovable. He is great, bold, full of Are, sublime ; but he rarely and perhaps never attains to beauty-. For the solidit3' and depth of ideas, Kleist is far inferior to Haller ; in point of grace, perhaps, he would have the advantage — if, as happens occasionall3', we did not im- pute to him as a merit, on the one side, that which really is a want on the other. The sensuous soul of Kleist takes especial delight at the sight of country scenes and man- ners ; he withdraws gladly from the vain jingle and rattle of society, and finds in the heart of inanimate nature the harmony and peace that are not offered to him by the moral world. How touching is his " Aspiration after Repose " ! how much truth and feeling there is in these verses I — " O world, thou art the tomb of true life ! Often a generous instinct attracts me to vii-tue; My heart is siid, a torrent of tears bathes my cheeks But example conquers, and thou, fire of youth! Soon you dry these noble tears. A time man must live far from men ! " ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 309 But if the poetic instinct of Kleist leads him thus far away from the narrow circle of social relations, in solitude and among the fruitful inspirations of nature, the image of social life and of its anguish pursues him, and also, alas ! its chains. What he flees from he carries in him- self, and what he seeks remains entirely outside him : never can he triumph over the fatal influence of his time. In vain does he find suflScient flame in his heart and enough energy in his imagination to animate by painting the cold conceptions of the understanding ; cold thought each time kills the living creations of fancj-, and reflection destroj-s the secret work of the sensuous nature. His poetry, it must be admitted, is of as brilliant color and as variegated as the spring he celebrated in verse ; his imagination is vivid and active ; but it might be said that it is more variable than rich, that it sports rather than creates, that it always goes forward with a changeful gait, rather than stops to accumulate and mould things into shape. Traits succeed each other rapidly, with exuberance, but without concentrating to form an individual, without completing each other to make a living whole, without rounding to a form, a figure. Whilst he remains in purely- lyrical poetry, and pauses amidst his landscapes of country life, on the one hand the greater freedom of the Ij'rical form, and on the other the more arbitrary' nature of the subject, prevent us from being struck with this defect ; in these sorts of works it is in general rather the feelings of the poet, than the object in itself, of which we expect the portraiture. But this defect becomes too apparent when he undertakes, as in Cisseis and Paches, or in his Seneca, to represent men and human actions ; because liere the imagination sees itself kept in within certain fixed and necessary Hmits, and because here the efl'ect can only be dei-ived from the object itself. Kleist becomes poor, tire- some, jejune, and insupportably frigid ; an example ful'.. of lessons for those who, without having an inner vocation, aspire to issue from musical poetry, to rise to the regions of plastic poetry. A spirit of this family, Thomson, has paid the same penalty to human infirmity. In the sentimental kind, and especially in that part of the sentimental kind which we name elegiac, there are but 310 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. few modern poets, and still fewer ancient ones, who can be compared to our Klopstock. Musical poetry has pro- duced in this poet all that can be attained out of the limits of the living form, and out of the sphere of individualitj', in the region of ideas. It would, no doubt, be doing him a great injustice to dispute entirelj' in his case that indi- vidual truth and that feeling of life with which the simple poet describes his pictures. Many of his odes, manj- sep- arate traits in his dramas, and in his " Messiah," repre- sent the object with a striking truth, and mark the outhne admirably ; especially, when the object is his own heart, he has given evidence on manj' occasions of a great natural disposition and of a charming simplicity. I mean only that it is not in this that the proper force of Klop- stock consists, and that it would not perhaps be right to seek for this throughout his work. Viewed as a produc- tion of musical poetry, the "Messiah" is a magnificent work ; but in the light of plastic poetrj-, where we look for determined forms and forms determined for the intui- tion, the "Messiah" leaves much to be desired. Perhaps in this poem the figures are sufficiently determined, but the}' are not so with intuition in view. It is abstraction alone that created them,' and abstraction alone can discern them. The}' are excellent types to express ideas, but they are not individuals nor living figures. With regard to the imagination, which the poet ought to address, and which lie ought to command by putting before it alwajs perfectly' determinate forms, it is left here much too free to repre- sent as it wishes these men and these angels, these divini- ties and demons, this paradise and this hell. We see quite well the vague outlines in which the understanding must be kept to conceive these personages ; but we do not find the limit clearly traced in which the imagination must be enclosed to represent them. And what I saj- here of characters must applj- to all that in this poem is, or ought to be, action and life, and not onl^'' in this epopceia, but also in the dramatic poetrj' of Klopstock. For the under- standing all is perfectly determined and bounded in them — I need only here recall his Judas, his Pilate, his Philo, his Solomon in the tragedy that bears that name — but for the imagination all this wants form too much, and I must ^STHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 311 readily confess I do not find that our poet is at all in his sphere here. His sphere is alwa3's the realm of ideas ; and he knows how to raise all he touches to the infinite. It might be said that he strips away their bodilj' envelope, to spiritualize them from all the objects with which he is occupied, in the same way that other poets clothe all that is spiritual with a body. The pleasure occasioned by his poems must almost always be obtained by an exercise of the faculty of reflection ; the feelings he awakens in us, and that so deeply and energetically, flow always from super-sen- suous sources. Hence the earnestness, the strength, the elasticity, the depth, that characterize all that comes from him ; but from that also issues that perpetual tension of mind in which we are kept when reading him. No poet — except perhaps Young, who in this respect exacts even more than Klopstock, without giving us so much compen- sation — no poet could be less adapted than Klopstock to play the part of favorite author and guide in life, because he never does anything else than lead us out of life, because he never calls to arms anything save spirit, without giving recreation and refreshment to sensuous nature by the calm presence of an^^ object. His muse is chaste, it has nothing of the earthl}', it is immaterial and holy as his religion ; and we are forced to admit with admiration that if he wanders sometimes on these high places, it never hap- pened to him to fall from them. But precisety for this reason, I confess in alWngenuousness, that I am not free from anxiety' for the common sense of those who quite seriously and unaflTectedly make Klopstock the favorite book, the book in which we find sentiments fitting all situ- ations, or to which we may revert at all times : perhaps even — and I suspect it — Germany has seen enough results of his dangerous influence. It is only in certain dispositions of the mind, and in hours of exaltation, that recourse can be had to Klopstock, and that he can be felt. It is for this reason that he is the idol of youth, without, however, being by any means the happiest choice that they could make. Youth, which always aspires to something beyond real life, which avoids all stiffness of form, and finds all limits too narrow, lets itself be carried away with love, with delight, into the infinite spaces opened up to them by 312 jestHetical letters and essays. this poet. But wait till the youth has become a man, and till, from the domain of ideas, he comes back to the world of experience, then you will see this enthusiastic love of Klopstock decrease greatly, without, however, a riper age changing at all the esteem due to this unique phenomenon, to this so extraordinary genius, to these noble sentiments — ^^the esteem that Germany in particular owes to Ms high merit. I have said that this poet was great specialty in the elegiac style, and it is scarcely necessary to confirm this judgment by entering into particulars. Capable of exercising all kinds of action on the heart, and having graduated as master in all that relates to sentimental poetr}', he can sometimes shake the soul by the most sub- lime pathos, at others cradle it with sweet and heavenlj' sensations. Yet his heart prefers to follow the direction of a lofty spiritual melancholy ; and, however sublime be the tones of his harp and of his lyre, they are always the tender notes of his lute that resound with most truth and the deepest emotion. I take as witnesses all those whose nature is pure and sensuous : would they not be ready to give all the passages where Klopstock is strong, and bold ; all those fictions, all the magnificent descrip- tions, all the models of eloquence which abound in the "Messiah," all those dazzling comparisons in which our poet excels, — would they not exchange them for the pages breathing tenderness, the "Elegy to Ebert" for example, or that admirable poem entitled"" Bardalus, " or again, the "Tombs Opened before the Hour, " the " Sum- mer's Night," the "Lake of Zurich," and many other pieces of this kind? In the same way the " Messiah" is dear to me as a treasure of elegiac feelings and of ideal paintings, though I am not much satisfied with it as the recital of an action and as an epic. I ought, perhaps, before quitting this department, to recall the merits in this style of Uz, Denis, Gessner — in the " Death of Abel " — jacobi. Gerstenberg, Holty, De Gockingk, and several others, who M knew how to touch by ideas, and whose poems Ix'long to the sentimental kind in the sense in which we liave agreed to understand the word. But my object is not he^-e to write a history of ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 313 G-erman poetry ; I onty wished to clear up what I said further back bj' some examples from our literature. I wished to show that the ancient and the modern poets, the authors of simple poetrj- aud of sentimental poetry, follow essentially different paths to arrive at the same end : that the former move by nature, individuality, a very vivid sensuous element ; while the latter do it by means of ideas and a high spirituality, exercising over our minds an equally powerful though less extensive influence. It has been seen, by the examples which precede, how sentimental poetry conceives and treats subjects taken from nature ; perhaps the reader ma}' be curious to know how also simple poetry treats a subject of the sentimental order. This is, as it seems, an entirely new question, and one of special difficulty ; for, in the first place, has a subject of the sentimental order ever been presented in primitive and simple periods? And in modern times, where is the simple poet with whom we could make this experiment? This has not, however, prevented genius from setting this problem, and solving it in a wonderfijlly happy way. A poet in whose mind nature works with a purer and more faithful activity than in any other, and who is perhaps of all modern poets the one who departs the least from the sensuous truth of things, has proposed this problem to himself in his conception of a mind, and of the dangerous extreme of the sentimental character. This mind and this character have been porttayed by the modern poet we speak of, a character which with a burning sensuousness embraces the ideal and flies the real, to soar up to an infinite devoid of being, alwaj's occupied in seeking out of himself what he incessantly destroys in himself ; a mind that only finds reality in his dreams, and to whom the realities of life are only limits and obstacles ; in short, a mind that sees only in its own existence a barrier, and goes on, as it were, logically to break down this barrier in order to penetrate to true reality. It is interesting to see with what a happy instinct all that is of a nature to feed the sentimental mind is gathered together in Werther : a dream}' and unhappy love, a verj' vivid feeling for nature, the religious sense coupled with the spirit of philosophic contemplation, and lastly, to omit 314 JESTHETICAL LETTEliS AND ESSAYS. nothing, the world of Ossian, dark, formless, melancholy. Add to this the aspect under which reality is presented,- all is depicted which is least adapted to make it lovable, or rather all that is most fit to make it hated ; see how all external circumstances unite to drive back the unhappy man into his ideal world ; and now we understand that it was quite impossible for a character thus constituted to save itself, and issue from the circle in which it was enclosed. The same contrast reappears in the " Torquato Tasso " of the same poet, though the characters are very- different. Even his last romance presents, like his first, this opposition between the poetic mind and the common sense of practical men, between the ideal and the real, between the subjective mode and the objective mode of seeing and representing things ; it is the same opposition, I say, but with what a diversity ! Even in "Faust" we still find this contrast, rendered, I admit — as the subject required — much more coarsely on both hands, and mate- rialized. It would be quite worthwhile if a psychological explanation were attempted of this character, personified and specified in four such diflferent ways. It has been observed further back that a mere dispo- sition to frivolity of mind, to a merr}' humor, if a certain fund of the ideal is not joined to it, does not suffice to constitute the vocation of a satirical poet, though this mistake is frequently made. In the same way a mere disposition for tender sentiments, softness of heart, and melancholy do not suffice to constitute a vocation for elegy. I cannot detect the true poetical talent, either on one side or the other ; it wants the essential, I mean the energetic and fruitful principle that ought to enliven the subject, and produce true beauty. Accordinglj- the productions of this latter nature, of the tender nature, do nothing but ener-sate us ; and without refreshing the heart, without occupying the mind, they are only able to flatter in us the sensuous nature. A constant dispo- sition to this mode (3f feeling ends necessarily, in the long run, by weakening the character, and makes it fall into a state of passivit3' from which nothing real can issue, either for external or for internal life. People have, therefore, ■been quite right to persecute by pitiless raillerj' this fatal iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 315 mania of sentimentality and of tearful melancholy which possessed Germany eighteen years since, in consequence of certain excellent worlis that were ill understood and indiscreetly imitated. People have been right, I say, to combat this perversitj', though the indulgence with which men are disposed to receive the parodies of these elegiac caricatures — that are very little better themselves — the complaisance shown to bad wit, to heartless satire and spiritless mirth, show clearly enough that this zeal against false sentimentalism does not issue from quite a pure source. In the balance of true taste one cannot weigh more than the other, considering' that both here and there is wanting that which forms the aesthetic value of a work of art, the intimate union of spirit with matter, and the twofold relation of the work with the faculty of perception as well as with the faculty of the ideal. People have turned Siegwart * and his convent story into ridicule, and yet the "Travels into the South of France " are admired ; yet both works have an equal claim to be esteemed in certain respects, and as little to be unreservedly praised in others. A true, though excessive, sensuousness gives value to the former of these two romances ; a livel}' and sportive humor, a fine wit, recom- mends the other : but one totally lacks all sobriety of mind that would befit it, the other lacks all sesthetic dignit}'. If you consult experience, one Is rather ridiculous ; if you think of the ideal, the other is almost contemptible. Now, as true beauty must of necessity accord both with nature and with the ideal, it is clear that neither the one nor the other of these two romances could pretend to pass for a fine work. And notwithstanding all this, it is natural, as I know it bj' mj' own experience, that the romance of Thummel should be read with much pleasure. As a fact it onlj- wounds those requirements which have their principle in the ideal, and which consequently do not exist for the greater part of readers ; requirements that, even in persons of most delicate feeling, do not make themselves felt at the moments when we read romances. With regard to the other needs of the mind, and especially to those of the senses, this book, on the other hand, affords * " Siegwart, " a novel by J. MuUer, published at Ulm, 1776. 31G ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. unusual satisfaction. Accordingly, it must be, and will be so, that this book will remain justly one of the favor ite works of our age, and of all epochs when men only write aesthetic works to please, and people only read to get pleasure. But does not poetical literature also offer, even in its classical monuments, some analogous examples of injuries inflicted or attempted against the ideal and its superior purity? Are there not some who, by the gross, sensuous nature of their subject, seem to depart strangely from the spiritualism I here demand of all works of art? If this is permitted to the poet, the chaste nurseling of the muses, ought it not to be conceded to the novelist, who is only the half-brother of the poet, and who still touches by so many points ? I can the less avoid this question because tliere are masterpieces, both in the elegiac and in the satirical kind, where the authors seek and preach up a nature quite different from that I am discussing in this essay, and where they seem to defend it, not so much against bad as against good morals. The natural conclu- sion would be either that this sort of poem ought to be rejected, or that, in tracing here the idea of elegiac poetry, we have granted far too much to what is arbitrary. The question I asked was, whether what was permitted bj- the poet might not be tolerated in a prose narrator too? The answer is contained in the question. What is allowed in the poet proves nothing about what must be allowed in one who is not a poet. This tolerancy in fact reposes on the very idea which we ought to make to ourselves of the poet, and only on this idea ; what in his case is legitimate freedom, is only a license worthy of contempt as soon as it no longer takes its source in the ideal, in those high and noble inspirations which make the poet. The laws of decencj' are strangers to innocenl nature ; the experience of corruption alone has given birth to them. But when once this experience has been made, and natural innocence has disappeared from manners, these laws are henceforth sacred laws that man, who has a moral sense, ought not to infringe upon. The^- reign in an artificial world with the same right that the laws of ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 317 nature reign in the innocence of primitive ages. But b3' wiiat characteristic is the poet recognized ? Precisely b}- his silencing in his soul all that recalls an artificial world, and by causing nature herself to revive in him with her primitive simplicity. The moment he has done this he is emancipated by this alone from all the laws by which a depraved heart secures itself against itself. He is pure, he is innocent, and all that is permitted to innocent nature is equally permitted to him. But you vrho read him or listen to him, if you have lost j'our innocence, and if you are incapable of finding it again, even for a moment, in a purifying contact with the poet, it is your oion fault, and not his : why do not you leave him alone ? it is not for you that he has sung ! Here follows, therefore, in what relates to these kinds of freedoms, the rules that we can lay down. Let us remark in the first place that natui'e only can justify these licenses ; whence it follows that you could not legitimately take them up of your own choice, nor with a determination of imitating them ; the will, in fact, ought always to be directed according to the laws of morahty, and on its part all condescending to the sensuous is absolutely unpardonable. These licenses must, there- fore, above all, be simplicity. But how can we be con vinced that the}' are actually simple? We shall hold their- 1 to be so if we see them accompanied and supported by all i the otlier circumstances^hich also have their spring of | action in nature ; for nature can only be recognized In' the close and strict consistency, by the unit}' and uniformit}' | of its effects. It is only a soul that has on all occasions I a horror of all kinds of artifice, and which consequently / rejects them even where they would be useful — it is only that soul which we permit to be emancipated from ihem when the artificial conventionalities hamper and hinder it. A heart that submits to all the obligations of nature has \ alone the right to profit also by the liberties which it au- thorizes. Alt the other feelings of that heart ought con- sequently to bear the stamp of nature : it will be true, simple, free, frank, sensible, and straightforward ; all dis- guise, all cunning, all arbitrar}' fancj-, all egotistical petti- ness, will be banished from his character, and 30U will see no trace of them in his writings. 318 iESTHBTIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. Second rule : beautiful nature alone can justify freedoms of this kind ; whence it follows that they ought not to be a mere outbreak of the appetites ; for all that proceeds exclusively from the wants of sensuous nature is con- temptible. It is, therefore, from the totality and the full- ness of human nature that these vivid manifestations must also issue. We must find humanity in them. But how can we judge that thej"^ proceed in fact from our whole nature, and not only from an exclusive and vulgar want of the sensuous nature ? For this purpose it is necessary that we should see — that they should represent to us — this whole of which they form a particular feature. This disposition of the mind to experience the impressions of the sensuous is in itself an innocent and an indifferent thing. It does not sit well on a man onlj' because of its being common to animals with him ; it augurs in him the lack of true and perfect humanitj'. It only shocks us m the poem because sucli a work having the pretension to please us, the author consequent!}- seems to think us capa- ble, ns also, of this moral infirmitj'. But when we see in the man who has let himself be drawn into it by surprise all the other characteristics that human nature in general embraces ; when we find in the work where these liberties have been taken the expression of all the realities of human nature, this motive of discontent disappears, and we can enjoj', without anj'thing changing our joy, this simple ex- pression of a true and beautiful nature. Consequently this same poet who ventures to allow himself to associate us with feelings so basely human, ought to know, on the other hand, how to raise us to all that is grand, beautiful, and sublime in our nature. We should, therefore, have found there a measure to which we could subject the poet with confidence, when he trespasses on the ground of decenc}', and when he does not fear to penetrate as far as that in order freely to paint nature. His work is common, base, absolutely inex- cusable, from the moment it is frigid, and from the moment it is empty, because that shows a prejudice, a vulgar necessity, an unhealth}' appeal to our appetites. His work, on the other hand, is beautiful and noble, and we ought to applaud it without any consideration for all ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 319 the objections of frigid decencj', as soon as we recognize in it simplicity, the alliance of spiritual nature and of the heart. Perhaps I shall be told that if we adopt this criterion, most of the recitals of this kind composed b^' the French, and the best imitations made of them in German}', would not perhaps find their interest in it ; and that it might be the same, at least in part, with many of the productions of our most intellectual and amiable poets, without even excepting his masterpieces. I should have nothing to reply to this. The sentence after all is anj'thing but new, and I am only justifj-ing the judgment pronounced long since on this matter by all men of delicate perceptions. But these same principles which, applied to the works of which I have just spoken, seem perhaps in too strict a spirit, might also be found too indulgent when applied to some other works. I do not deny, in fact, that the same reasons which make me hold to be quite inexcusable the dangerous pictures drawn by the Roman Ovid and the German Ovid, those of Crebillon, of Voltaire, of Mar- montel, who pretends to write moral tales ! — of Lacroix, and of many others — that these same reasons, I say, rec- oncile me with the elegies of the Roman Propertius and of the German Propertius, and even with some of the decried productions of Diderot. This is because the for- mer of those works are only witty, prosaic, and volup- tuous, while the others arg poetic, human, and simple. Idyl. It remains for me to say a few words about this third kind of sentimental poetry — some few words and no more, for I propose to speak of it at another time with the developments particularly' demanded by the theme. This kind of poetrj- general^ presents the idea and ^^ description of an innocent and happj- humanity. This innocence and bliss seeming remote from the artificial i refinements of fashionable society, poets have removed the scene of the idjl from crowds of worldly life to the simple shepherd's cot, and have given it a place in the 320 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. infancy of humanity before the beginning of culture. These limitations are evidently accidental ; they do not form the object of the idyl, but are only to be regarded as the most natural means to attain this end. The end is everjwhere to portray man in a state of innocence : which means a state of harmony and peace with himself and the external world. But a state such as this is not merelj' met with before the dawn of civilization ; it is also the state to which civili- zation aspires, as to its last end, if only it obeys a deter- mined tendencj' in its progress. The idea of a similar state, and the belief of the possible reality of this state, is the onlj' thing that can reconcile man with all the evils to which he is exposed in the path of civilization ; and if this — idea were only a chimera, the complaints of those who accuse civil life and the culture of the intelligence as an evil for which there is no compensation, and who represent this primitive state of nature that we have renounced as the real end of humanity — their complaints, I say, would have a perfectly' jiist foundation. It is, therefore, of in- : finite importance for the man engaged in the path of I civilization to see confirmed in a sensuous manner the ! l>elief that this idea can be accomplished in the world of I sense, that this state of innocence can be realized in it ; and as real experience, far from keeping up this belief, is rather made incessantly to contradict it, poetrj- comes here, as in manj' other cases, in aid of reason, to cause this idea to pass into the condition of an intuitive idea, and to realize it in a particular fact. No doubt this innocence of pastoral life is also a poetic idea, and the imagination must already have shown its creative power in that. But the problem, with this datum, becomes infinitely simpler and easier to solve ; and we must not forget that the elements of these pictures already existed in real life, jind that it was only requisite to gather up the separate traits to form a whole. Under a fine sky, in a primitive society, when all the relations are still simple, when science is limited to so little, nature is easily satisfied, and man only turns to savagery when he is tortured by want. All nations that have a history have a paradise, an age of innocence, a golden age. Nay, more than this, every man iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 321 has his paradise, his golden age, which he remembers with more or less enthusiasm, according as he is more or less poetical. Thus experience itself furnishes sufficient traits/ to this picture which the pastoral id^yl executes. But tliis does not prevent the pastoral idyl from remaining alwaj's a beautiful and an encouraging fiction ; and poetic genius, in retracing these pictures, has really worked in favor of the ideal. For, to the man who has once de- parted from simple nature, and who has been abandoned to the dangerous guidance of his reason, it is of the greatest importance to find the laws of nature expressed in a faith- ful copj% to see their image in a clear mirror, and to reject all the stains of artificial life. There is, however, a cir- cumstance which remarkablj' lessens the aesthetic value of these sorts of poetry-. By the very fact that the idyl is / transported to the time that precedes civilization, it also loses the advantages thereof ; and bj' its nature finds itself in opposition to itself. Thus, in a theoretical sense, it takes ^ us back at the same time that in a practical sense it leads us / on and ennobles us. Unhappil}' it places behind us the end / towards which it ought to lead us, and consequently it can \ only inspire us with the sad feeling of a loss, and not the j joyous feeling of a hope. As these poems can only attain ; their end bj' dispensing with all art, and by simplifying human nature, they have the highest value for the heart, r but they are also far too poor for what concerns the mind, and their uniform circle is too quickly traversed. Accord- ingly we can only seek them and love them in moments in which we need calm, and not when our faculties aspire after movement and exercise. A morbid mind will find its cure in them, asound soul will not find its foodra them. They cannot vivif^', they can only soften. This defect, i grounded in the essence of the pastoral id^'ll, has not been remedied by the whole art of poets. I know that ^ this kind of poem is not without admirers, and that there are readers enough who prefer an Amyntus and a Daphnis to the most splendid masterpieces of the epic or the dramatic muse ; but in them it is less the sesthetical taste than the feeling of an individual want that pronounces on works of art ; and their judgment, by that verj^ fact, could not be taken into consideration here. The I'eader 822 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. who judges with his mind, and whose heart is sensuous, without being blind to the merit of these poems, will confess that he is rarely affected bj- them, and that thej* tire him most quickly. But they act with so much the more effect in the exact moment of need. But must the truly beautiful be reduced to await our hours of need ? and is it not rather its office to awaken in our soul the want that it is going to satisfy' ? The reproaches I here level against the bucolic idjl cannot be understood of the sentimental. The simple pastoral, in fact, cannot be deprived pf aesthetic value, since this value is already found in the mere form. To explain myself: every kind of poetry is bound to possess an infinite ideal value, which alone constitutes it a true poetry ; but it can satisfj" this condition in two dif- ferent ways. It can give us the feeling of the infinite as to form, by representing the object altogether limited and individualizing it ; it can awaken in us the feeling of the infinite as to matter, in freeing its object from all limits in which it is enclosed, by idealizing this object ; therefore it can have an ideal value either by an absolute repre- sentation or by the representation of an absolute. Simple poetry takes the former road, the other is that of senti- mental poetrj'. Accordingly the simple poet is not ex- posed to failure in value so long as he keeps faithfully to nature, which is always completely circumscribed, that is, is infinite as regards form. The sentimental poet, on the contrarj', b}' that ver^- fact, that nature only offers him completely circumscribed objects, finds in it an obstruction when he wishes to give an absolute value to a particular object. Thus the sentimental poet understands his in- terests badly when he goes along the trail of the simple poet, and borrows his objects from him — objects which by themselves are perfectly indifferent, and which onl^' be- come poetical by the way in which they are treated. By this he imposes on himself without any necessit}- the same limits that confine the field of the simple poet, without, however, being able to carry out the limitation properly, or to vie with his rival in absolute definiteness of rep- resentation. He ought rather, therefore, to depart from the simple poet, just in the choice of object ; because, ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 323 the latter having the advantage of him on the score of form, it is only by the nature of the objects that he can resume the upper hand. Applying this to the pastoral id3'ls of the sentimental poet, we see wly these poems, whatever amount of art and genius be displayed in them, do not fully satisfy- the heart or the mind. An ideal is proposed in it, and, at the same time, the writer keeps to this narrow and poor medium of pastoral life. Would it not have been better, on the contrary, to choose for the ideal another frame, or for the pastoral world another kind of picture? These pictures are just ideal enough for painting to lose its individual truth in them, and, again, just individual enough for the ideal in them to suffer therefrom. For example, a shepherd of Gessner can neither charm by the illusion of nature nor by the beauty of imitation ; he is too ideal a being for that, but he does not satisf}^ us any more as an ideal by the infinity of the thought : he is a far too limited creature to give us this satisfaction. He will, therefore, please up to a certain point all classes of readers, without exception, because he seeks to unite the simple with the sentimental, and he thus gives a commencement of satis- faction to the two opposite exigencies that raay be brought to bear on anj' particular part of a poem ; but the author, in tr^-ing to unite the two points, does not fully satisfy either one or the other exigency, as you do not find in him either pure nature or She pure ideal ; he cannot rank himself as entirelj' up to the mark of a stringent critical taste, for taste does not accept anytliing equivocal or incomplete in sesthetical matters. It is a strange thing that, in the poet whom I have named, this equivocal character extends to the language, which floats undecided between poetry and prose, as if he feared either to depart too far from nature, by speaking rh^'thmical language, or if he completelj' freed himself from rhythm, to lose all poetic fligiit. Milton gives a higher satisfaction to the mind, in the magnificent picture of the first human pair, and of the state of innocence in paradise ; — -the most beautiful idyl I know of the sentimental kind. Here nature is noble, inspired, simple, full of breadth, and, at the same time, of depth ; it is humanity in its highest moral value, clothed in the most graceful form. 324 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. Thus, even in respect to the idyl, as well as to all kinds of poetrj^ we must once for all declare either for individuality or ideality ; for to aspire to give satisfaction to both exigencies is the surest means, unless j'ou have reached the terminus of perfection, to miss both ends. If the modern poet thinks he feels enougli of the Greeks' mind to vie with them, notwithstanding all. the indocility of his matter, on their own ground, namel}- that of simple poetry', let him do it exclusivel}', and place himself apart from all the requirements of the sentimental taste of his age. No doubt it is ver^' doubtful if he come up to his models ; between the original and the happiest imitation there will always remain a notable distance ; but, by taking this road, he is at all events secure of producing a reallj' poetic work. If, on the other hand, he feels him- self carried to the ideal b3' the instinct of sentimental poetry, let him decide to pursue this end fully ; let him seek the ideal in its puritj-, and let him not pause till lie has readied the highest regions without looking behind him to know if the real follows him, and does not leave him by the wa^-. Let him not lower himself to tiiis wretcljed expedient of spoihng the ideal to accommodate himself to the wants of human weakness, and to turn out mind in order to play more easily' with the heart. Let him not take us back to our infancy', to make us buj', at the cost of the most precious acquisitions of the under- standing, a repose that can only last as long as the slum- ber of our spiritual faculties ; but let him lead us on to emancipation, and give us this feeling of higher harmony which compensates for all his troubles and secures the hap- piness of the victor ! Let him jirepare as his task an idyl that realizes the pastoral innocence, even in the children of civihzation, and in all the conditions of the most mili- tant and excited life ; of thought enlarged by culture ; of the most refined art ; of the most delicate social conven- tionahties — an idyl, in short, that is made, not to bring back man to Arcadia^ but to lead liim to Elysium. This idyl, as I conceive it, is the idea of humanity definitely reconciled with itself, in the individual as well as in the whole of society ; it is union freely re-established between inclination and duty ; it is nature purified, raised ^STHETIOAL LETTBKS AND ESSAYS . 825 to its highest moral dignit}' ; in short, it is no less than the ideal of beautj' applied to real life. Thus, the char- acter of this idyl is to reconcile perfectly all the contradic- tions between the real and the ideal, which formed the matter of satirical and elegiac poetry, and, setting aside their contradictions, to put an end to all conflict between the feelings of the soul. Thus, the dominant expression of this kind of poetry would be calm ; but the calm that follows the accomplishment, and not that of indolence — the calm that comes from the equilibrium re-established between the faculties, and not from the suspending of their exercise ; from the fulness of our strength, and not from our infirmity ; the calm, in short, which is accompanied in the soul by the feeling of an infinite power. But precisely because idyl thus conceived removes all idea of struggle, it will be infinitely more difficult than it was in two previously -named kinds of poetry to express movement ; yet this is an indispensable condition, without which poetry can never act on men's souls. The most perfect unity is required, but unit}' ought not to wrong variet}' ; the heart must be satisfied, but without the inspiration ceasing on that account. The solution of this problem is properly what ought to be given us by the theory of the idyl. Now, what are the relations of the two poetries to one another, and their relations to the poetic ideal? Here are the principles we have established. Nature has granted this favor to the simple poet, to act always as an indivisible unity, to be at all times identical and perfect, and to represent, in the real world, humanitj' / at its highest value. In opposition, it has given a power- ( ful facultj' to the sentimental poet, or, rather, it has im- piinted an ardent feeling on him ; this is to replace out of himself this first unity that abstraction has destroj'ed in him, to complete humanity in his person, and to pass from a limited state to an infinite state. They both propose to represent human nature full}-, or they would not be poets ; but the simple poet has always the advantage of sensuous reality over the sentimental poet, by setting forth as a real fact what the other aspires only to reach. Every one experiences this in tlie pleasure he takes in simple poetry. 326 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. We there feel that the human faculties are brought into play ; no vacuum is felt ; we have the feeling of unity, without distinguishing anything of what we experience ; we enjoy both our spiritual activity and also the fulness of physical life. Ver^' different is the disposition of mind elicited by the sentimental poet. Here we feel only a vivid aspiration to produce in us this harmonj' of which we had in the other case the consciousness and reality ; to make of ourselves a single and same totality ; to realize in ourselves the idea of humanity as a complete expression. Hence it comes that the mind is here all in movement, stretched, hesitating between contrar}- feelings ; whereas it was before calm and at rest, in harmonj' with itself, and fully satisfied. But if the simple poet has the advantage over the senti- mental poet on the score of realitj- ; if he causes reall^' to live that of which the other can only elicit a vivid instinct, the sentimental poet, in compensation, has this great ad- vantage over the simple poet : to be in a position to offer to this instinct a greater object than that given bj- his ri\'al, and the onl3' one he could give. All reality, we know, is below the ideal ; all that exists has limits, but thought is infinite. This limitation, to which everything is subject in sensuous reality, is, therefore, a disadvantage for the simple poet, while the absolute, unconditional free- dom of the ideal profits the sentimental poet. No doubt the former accomplishes his object, but this object is lim- ited ; the second, I admit, does not entirely accomplish his, but his object is infinite. Here I appeal to experi- _eiice. We pass pleasantl}' to real life and things from the frame of mind in which the simple poet, has placed iis. On the other hand, the sentimental poet will always dis- gust us, for a time, w^ith real life. This is because the in- finite character has, in a manner, enlarged our mind be- yond its natural measure, so that nothing it finds in the world of sense can fill its capacit}-. We prefer to fall back in contemplation on ourselves, where we find food for this awakened impulse towards the ideal world ; while, in the simple poet, we only strive to issue out of our- selves, in search of sensuous objects. Sentimental poetry is the ofljspring of retirement and science, and invites to ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 327 It ; simple poetry is inspired by the spectacle of life, and brings back life. I have styled simple poetry a gift of nature to show that thought has no share in it. It is a first jet, a happy inspiration, that needs no correction, when it turns out well, and which cannot be rectified if ill turned out. The entire work of the simple genius is accomplished by feel- ing ; in that is its strength, and in it are its limits. If, I then, he has not felt at once in a poetic manner — that is, in a perfectly human manner — no art in the world can remed}' this defect. Criticism may help him him to see the defect, but can place no beauty in its stead. Simple genius must draw all from nature ; it can do nothing, or almost nothing, b}' its will ; and it will fulfil the idea of this kind of poetry provided nature acts in it bj' an inner necessity. Now, it is true that all which happens by na- ture is necessarj', and all the productions, happ^' or not, ' of the simple genius, which is disassociated from nothing 80 much as from arbitrary will, are also imprinted with this character of necessity- ; momentary constraint is one thing, and the internal necessity dependent on the totality of things another. Considered as a whole, nature is in- dependent and infinite ; in isolated operations it is poor and limited. The same distinction holds good in respect to the nature of the poet. The very moment when he is most happil3' inspired depends on a preceding instant, and consequenth' only a conditional necessity can be attributed to him. But now the problem that the poet ought to solve is to make an individual state similar to the human whole, and consequently to base it in an absolute and necessary manner on itself. It is therefore necessar}' that at the moment of inspiration every trace of a temporal I need should be banished, and that the object itself, how-- \ ever limited, should not limit the fiight of the poet. But i ■it may be conceived that this is only possible in so far as ■ the poet brings to the object an absolute freedom, an ab- * solute fulness of faculties, and in so far as he is prepared \ by an anterior exercise to embrace all things with all his' humanity. Now he cannot acquire this exercise except by the world in which he lives, and of which he receives the impressions immediately. Thus simple genius is, in a fi28 iESTHETIOAL LETTBliS AND ESSAYS. state of dependence with regard to experience, while the sentimental genius is forced from it. We know that the sentimental genius begins its operation at the place where the other finishes its own : its virtue is to complete by the elements which it derives from itself a defective object, and to transport itself by its own strength from a limited state to one of absolute freedom Thus the simple poet needs a help from without, while the sentimental poet feeds his genius from his own fund, and purifies himself by himself. The former requirc^s a picturesque nature, a poetical world, a simple humauitj- which casts its eyes around ; for he ought to do his work without issuing from the sensuous sphere. If external aid fails him, if he be surrounded by matter not speaking to mind, one of two things will happen : either, if the general character of the poet-race is what prevails in him, he issues from the particular class to which he belongs as a poet, and be- comes sentimental to be at any rate poetic ; or, if his par- ticular character as simple poet has the upper hand, he leaves his species and becomes a common nature, in order to remain at any rate natural. The former of these two alternatives might represent the case of the principal poets of the sentimental kind in Roman antiquitj' and in modern times. Born at another period of the world, transplanted under another skj-, these poets who stir us now by ideas, would have charmed us bj- individual truth and simple beautj'. The other alternative is the almost un- avoidable quicksand for a poet who, thrown into a vulgar world, cannot resolve to lose sight of nature. I mean, to lose sight of actual nature ; but the greatest care must be given to distinguish actual nature from true nature, which is the subject of simple poetry. Actual nature exists ever^'where ; but ti'ue nature is so much the more rare because it requires an internal necessity that determines its existence. Ever}- eruption of passion, how- ever vulgar, is real — it maj' be even true nature ; but it is not true himrcai nature, for true human nature requires that the self-directing faculty in us should have a share in the manifestation, and the expression of this faculty is always dignified. All moral baseness is an actual human phenomenon, but I hope not real human nature, which iESTHETIOAL LETTBIiS AND ESSAYS. 329 is always noble. All the faults of taste cannot be surveyed that have begn occasioned in criticism or the practice of art by this confusion between actual human nature and true human nature. The greatest trivialities are tolerated and applauded under the pretext that the}- are real nature. Caricatures not to be tolerated in the real world are care- fully preserved in the poetic world and .reproduced accord- ing to nature ! The poet can certainly imitate a lower nature, and it enters into the verj- definition of a satirical poet : but then a beautj' by its own nature must sustain and raise the object, and the vulgaritj' of the subject must not lower the imitator too much. If at the moment he paints he is true human nature himself, the object of bis paintings is indifferent ; but it is only on this condition we can tolerate a faithful reproduction of reality. Unhappj' for us readers when the rod of satire falls into hands that nature meant to handle another instrument, and when, devoid of all poetic talent, with nothing but the ape's mimicry, they exercise it brutallj' at the expense of our taste ! But vulgar nature has even its dangers for the simple poet ; for the simple poet is formed by this fine harmon}^ of the feeling and thinking faculty, which ^et is only an idea, never actually realized. Even in the happiest geni-/ uses of this class, receptivitj- will alwaj's more or less carry the day over spontaneous activity. But receptivltj' is always more or less sujjordinate to external ilnpressions, and nothing but a perpetual activitj' of the creative fac- ulty could prevent matter from exercising a blind violence over this qualitj-. Now, every time this happens the feel- ing becomes \ulgar instead of poetical. ---' No genius of the simple class, from Homer down to Bod- mer, has entirely steered clear of this quicksand. It is evident that it is most perilous to those who have to strug- gle against external vulgaritj', or who have parted with their refinement owing to a want of proper restraint. The first-named difHcultj'^ is the reason why even authors of high cultivation are not always emancipated from plati- tudes — a fact which has prevented many splendid talents from occupying the place to which they were summoned by nature. For this reason, a comic poet whose genius 330 JESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. has chiefly to deal with scenes of real life, is more liable to the danger of acquiring vulgar habits of stj-le and ex- pression — a fact evidenced in the case of Aristophanes, Plautus, and all the poets who have followed in their track. Even Shakspeare, with all his sublimit}', suffers us to fall very low now and then. Again, Lope De Vega, Moli^re, Regnard, Goldoni worry us with frequent trifling. Hol- berg drags us down into the mire. Schlegel, a German poet, among the most remarkable for intellectual talent, ' with genius to raise him to a place among poets of the first order ; Gellert, a truly simple poet, Rabener, and Lessing himself, if I am warranted to introduce his name in this categor}- — this highly-cultivated scholar of criti- cism and vigilant examiner of his own genius — all these suffer in different degrees from the platitudes and unin- spired movements of the natures they chose as the tlieme of tiieir satire. With regard to more recent authors of this class, I avoid naming any of them, as I can make no exceptions in their case. But not onlj' is simple genius exposed to the danger of coming too near to vulgar reality ; the ease of expression, even this too close approximation to reality, encourages vulgar imitators to trj^ their hand in poetry. Sentimental poetr}-, though offering danger enough, has this advantage, to keep this crowd at a distance, for it is not for the first comer to rise to the ideal ; but simple poetrj- makes them believe that, with feeling and humor, you need only imi- tate real nature to claim the title of poet. Now nothing is more revolting than platitude when it tries to be simple and amiable, instead of hiding its repulsive nature under the veil of art. This occasions the incredible trivialities loved by the Germans under the name of simple and face- tious songs, and which give them endless amusement round a well-garnished table. Under the pretext of good humor and of sentiment people tolerate these poverties : but this good humor and this sentiment ought to be carefull}' pro- scribed. The Muses of the Pleisse, in particular, are singularl}- pitiful ; and other Muses respond to them, from the banks of the Seine, and the Elbe. If these pleasant- ries are flat, the passion heard on our tragic stage is equallj' pitiful, for, instead of imitating true nature, it is only an ^STHBTICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 831 insipid and ignoble expression of the actual. Thus, after shedding torrents of tears, you feel as you would after visiting a hospital or reading the "Human Misery" of Saltzmann. But the evil is worse in satirical poetry and comic romance, kinds which touch closely on evei'y-day life, and which consequentlj', as all frontier posts, ought to be in safer hands. In truth, he less than any other is called on to become the painter, of his century, who is himself the child and caricature of his centur}-. But as, after all, nothing is easier than to take in liand, among our acquaintances, a comic character — a big, fat man — and draw a coarse likeness of him on paper, the sworn enemies of poetic inspiration are often led to blot some paper in this way to amuse a circle of friends. It is true that a pure heart, a well-made mind, will never confound these vulgar productions with the inspirations of simple genius. But purity of feeling is the very thing that is wanting, and m most cases nothing is thought of but satisfying a want of sense, without spiritual nature having any share. A fundamentally- just idea, ill understood, that works of hel esprit serve to recreate the mind, contributes to keep up this indulgence, if indulgence it may be called, when noth- ing higher occupies the mind, and reader as well as writer find their chief interest therein. This is because vulgar natures, if overstrained, can only be refreshed bj- vacuity ; and even a higher intelligence, when not sustained by a proportional culture, can «nly rest from its work amidst sensuous enjojmeijts, from which spiritual nature is ab- sent. ■^- Poetic genius ought to have strength enough to rise with a free and innate activity above all the accidental hin- derances which are inseparable from every confined condi- tion, to arrive at a representation of humanity in the absolute plenitude of its powers ; it is not, however, per- mitted, on the other hand, to emancipate itself from the necessar}- limits implied bj' the very idea of human nature ; for the absolute only in the circle of humanity is its true problem. Simple genius is not exposed to overstep this sphere, but rather not to Jill it entirely., giving too much scope to external necessity, to accidental wants, at the expense of the inner necessitj-. The danger for thesenti- 332 iESTHEXrCAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. mental genius is, on tlie otlier liand, by trj-ing to remove all limits, of nullifj'ing human nature absolutel}-, and not onlj' rising, as is its right and dut}-, beyond finite and determinate reality, as far as absolute possibility, or in other terms to idealize ; but of passing even beyond possi- bilit}', or, in other words, dreaming. This fault — over- straining — is precisely dependent on the specific property of the sentimental process, as the opposite defect, inertia, depends on the peculiar operation of the simple genius. The simple genius lets nature dominate, without restrict- ing it ; and as nature in her particular phenomena is alwaj's subject to some want, it follows that the simple sentiment will not be always exalted enough to resist the accidental limitations of the present hour. The sentimental genius, on the contrarj-, leaves aside the real world, to rise to the ideal and to command its matter with free spontaneity. But while reason, according to law, aspires always to the unconditional, so the sentimental genius will not alwavs remain calm enough to restrain itself uniformly and without interruption within the conditions implied by the idea of human nature, and to which reason must always, even in its freest acts, remain attached. He could only confine himself in these conditions by help of a receptivity pro- portioned to his free activity ; but most commonly the activ- ity predominates over receptivity in the sentimental poet, as much as receptivity over activit}- in the simple poet. Hence, in the productions of simple genius, if sometimes inspiration is wanting, so also in works of sentimental poetry the object is often missed. Thus, though they pro- ceed in opposite ways, they will both fall into a vacuum, for before the aesthetic judgment an object without inspir- ation, and inspiration without an object, are both nega- tions. The poets who borrow their matter too much from thought, and rather conceive poetic pictures by the internal abundance of ideas than bj- the suggestions of feeling, are more or less likelj- to be addicted to go thus astra3\ In their creations reason makes too little of the limits of the sensuous world, and thought is always carried too far for experience to follow it. Now, when the idea is carried so far that not only no experience corresponds to it — as is ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 333 the case in the heau ideal — but also that it is repugnant to the conditions of all possible experience, so that, in order to realize it, one must leave human nature altogether, it is no longer a poetic but an exaggerated thought ; that is, supposing it claims to be representable and poetical, for otherwise it is enough if it is not self-contradictor3-. If thought is contradictory it is not exaggeration, but nonsense ; for what does not exist cannot exceed. But when the thought is not an object proposed to the fancj', we are just as little justified in calling it exaggerated. For simple thought is infinite, and what is limitless also cannot exceed. Exaggeration, therefore, is onlj' that which wounds, not logical truth, but sensuous truth, and what pretends to be sensuous truth. Consequent!}-, if a poet has the unhappy chance to choose for his picture cer- tain natures that are merely superhuman and cannot pos- sibly be represented, he can onl}' avoid exaggeration by ceasing to be a poet, and not trusting the theme to his imagination. Otherwise one of two things would happen : either imagination, applying its limits to the object, would make a limited and merely human object of an absolute object — which happened with the gods of Greece — or the object would take away limits from fancy, that is, would render it null and void, and this is precisely exaggera- tion. Extravagance of feeling should be distinguished from extravagance of portraiture ; we are speaking of the former. The object of the feeling maj- be unnatural, but the feeling itself is natural, and ought accordingly to be shadowed forth in the language of nature. While extrav- agant feelings maj' issue from a warm heart and a really poetic nature, extravagance of portraiture alwaj's displays a cold heart, and very often a want of poetic capacity. Therefore this is not a danger for the sentimental poet, but onl}- for the imitator, who has no vocation ; it is there- fore often found with platitude, insipidity, and even base- ness. Exaggeration of sentiment is not without truth, and must have a real object ; as nature inspires it, it admits of simplicity of expression and coming from the heart it goes to the heart. As its object, however, is not in nature, but artificially produced by the understanding, it 334 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. has only a logical reality-, and the feeling is not purely human. It was not an illusion that Heloise had for Abelard, Petrarch for Laura, Saint Preux for his .Tulia, Werther for his Charlotte ; Agathon, Phanias, and Pere- grinus — in Wieland — for the object of their dreams : the feeling is true, only the object is factitious and outside nature. If their thought had kept to simple sensuous tTuth, it could not have taken this flight ; but on the other hand a mere play of fancy, without inner value, could not have stirred the heart: this is only stirred by reason. Thus this sort of exaggeration must be called to order, but it is not contemptible : and those who ridicule it would do well to find out if the wisdom on which they pride them- selves is not want of heart, and if it is not through want of reason that they are so acute. The exaggerated deli- cacy in gallantry and honor which cliai'acterizes the chival- rous romances, especiall}- bf Spain, is of this kind; also the refined and even ridiculous tenderness of French and English sentimental romances of the best kind. These sentiments are not only subjectively true, but also object- ivel}' thej' are not without value ; thej- are sound senti- ments issuing from a moral source, only reprehensible as overstepping the limits of human truth. Without this moral realitj- how could they stir and touch so powerfully ? The same remark applies to moral and religious fanaticism, patriotism, and the love of freedom when carried up to exaltation. As the object of these sentiments is alway; a pure idea, and not an external experience, imagination with its proper activity has here a dangerous libertj', and -Xjannot, as elsewhere, be called back to bounds by the presence of a visible object. But neither the man nor the poet can withdraw from the law of nature, except to sud- mit to that of reason. He can onlj^ abandon reality for the ideal ; for liberty must hold to one or the other of these anchors. But it is far from the real to the ideal ; and be- tween the two is found fanc^', with its arbitrary conceits and its unbridled freedom. It must needs be, therefore, that man in general, and the poet in particular, when he withdraws bj- liberty of his understanding from the domin- ion of feeling, without being moved to it bj- the larws of reason — that is, when he abandons nature through pure ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 335 libertj- — he finds himself freed Jrom all law, and therefore a prey to the illusions of phantasy. ' It is testified by experience that entire nations, as well as individual men, who ha^e parted with the safe direction of nature, are aotuallj' in this condition ; and poets have^ gone astray in the same manner. The true genius of sen- timental poetrj', if its aim is to raise itself to the rank of the ideal, must overstep the limits of the existing nature ; but false genius oversteps all boundaries without any dis- \ crimination, flattering itself with the belief that the wikl i sport of the imagination is poetic inspiration. A true j poetical genius can never fall into this error, bccr.use it only abandons the real for the sake of the ideal, or, at all events, it can onl}' do so at certain moments when the poet forgets himself; but his main tendencies may dispose him to extravagance within the sphere of the senses. His example maj- also drive others into a chase of wild con- ceptions, because readers of livel}' fanc^' and weak under- standing onl}' remark the freedom which he takes with existing nature, and are unable to follow him in copying the elevated necessities of his inner being. The same difficulties beset the path of the sentimental genius in this respect, as tiiose which afflict the career of a genius of the simple order. If a genius of this class carries out everj- work, obedient to the free and spontaneous impulses of his nature, the man devoid of genius who seeks to imitate him is not willing to cansider his own nature a worse guide than that of the great poet. This accounts for the fact that masterpieces of simple poetry are commonly followed by a host of stale and nnprofitable woi'ks in print, and masterpieces of the sentimental class by wild and fanciful effusions, — a fact that may be easily- verified on questioning the history of literature. Two maxims are pre\alent in relation to poetrj-, both of them quite correct in themselves, but mutually destructive in the way in which thej- are generally conceived. The first is, that " poetry serves as a means of amusement and recreation," and we have [)re\iously observed that this maxim is highly favorable to aridity and platitudes in poetical fictions. The other maxim, that " poetry is con- ducive to the moral progress of humanity," takes under 836 ^STHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSATS. its shelter theories and views of the most wild and extrav- agant character. It may be profitable to examine more attentively these two maxims, of which so much is heard, and which are so often imperfectly understood and falsely applied. We say that a thing amuses us when it makes us pass from a forced state to the state that is natural to us. The whole question here is to know in what our natural state ought to consist, and what a forced state means. If our natural state is made to consist merely in the free develop- ment of all our physical powers, in emancipation from all constraint, it follows that every act of reason by resisting what is sensuous, is a violence we undergo, and rest of mind combined with physical movement will be a recreation par excellence. But if we make our natural state consist in a limitless power of human expression and of freely dis- posing of all our strength, all that divides these forces will be a forced state, and recreation will be what brings all our nature to harmony. Thus, the first of these ideal recrea- tions is simply determined by the wants of our sensuous nature; the second, by the autonomous activity of human nature. Which of these two kinds of recreation can be demanded of the poet? Theoretical^, the question is inadmissible, as no one would put the human ideal beneath the brutal. But in practice the requirements of a poet have been especially directed to the sensuous ideal, and for the most part favor, though not the esteem, for these sorts of works is regulated thereby. Men's ipinds are mostly engaged in a labor that exhausts them, or an enjoyment that sets them asleep. Now labor makes rest a sensible want, much more imperious than that of the moral nature ; for physical nature must be satisfied before the mind can show its requirements. On the other hand, enjoyment paralyzes the moral instinct. Hence these two dispositions common in men are very injurious to the -^feeling for true beauty, and thus very few even of the best judge soundlj' in aesthetics. Beauty results from the harmon}^ between spirit and sense ; it addresses all the faculties of man, and can onlj' be appreciated if a man employs fully all his strength. He must bring to it an open sense, a broad heart, a spirit full of freshness. All ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 337 a man's nature must be on the alert, and this is not the case with those divided by abstraction, narrowed by for- mulas, enervated by application, Thej* demand, no doubt, a material for the senses ; but not to quicken, only to suspend, thought. Thej' ask to be freed from what? From a load that oppressed their indolence, and not a rein that curbed their activitj-. After this can one wonder at the success of mediocre talents in esthetics ? or at the bitter anger of small minds against true energetic beautj- ? Thej- reckon on finding therein a congenial recreation, and regret to discover that a display of strength is required to which thej'are unequal. With mediocrity' thej' are alwajs welcome ; however little mind thej' bring, they want still less to exhaust the author's inspiration. They are relieved of the load of thought; and their nature can lull itself in beatific nothings on the soft pillow of platitude. In the temple of Thalia and Melpomene — at least, so it is with us — the stupid savant and the exhausted man of business are received on the broad bosom of the goddess, where their intelligence is wrapped in a magnetic sleep, while their sluggish senses are warmed, and their imagination with gentle motions rocked. Vulgar people ma3- be excused what happens to the best capacities. Those moments of repose demanded hj nature after lengthy labor are not favorable to aesthetic judg- ment, and hence in the Jpusy classes few can pronounce safely on matters of taste. Nothing is more common than for scholars to make a ridiculous figure, in regard to a question of beauty, besides cultured men of the world ; and technical critics are especially the laughing-stock of connoisseurs. Their opinion, from exaggeration, crude- ness, or carelessness guides them generally quite awrj', and they can only devise a technical judgment, and not an (esthetical one, embracing tlie whole work, in which feeling should decide. If they would kindly keep to techni- calities the}' might still be useful, for the poet in moments of inspiration and readers under his si)ell are little inclined to consider details. But the spectacle which they afford us is only the more ridiculous inasmuch as we see these crude natures — with whom all labor and trouble only 338 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. develop at the most a particular aptitude, — when we see tUem set up their paltry individualities as the representation of universal and complete feeling, and in the sweat of their brow pronounce judgment on beauty. We have just seen that the kind of recreation poetr}' ought to afford is generally conceived in too restricted a manner, and only referred to a simple sensuous want. Too much scope, however, is also given to the other idea, the moral ennobling the poet should have in view, inas- much as too purely an ideal aim is assigned. In fact, according to the pure ideal, the ennobling goes on to infinity, because reason is not restricted to anj- sensuous limits, and only finds rest in absolute perfection. Nothing can satisfy whilst a superior thing can be con- ceived ; it judges strictly and admits no excuses of infirmity and finite nature. It only admits for limits those of thought, which transcends time and space. Hence the poet could no more propose to himself such an ideal of ennobling (traced for him by pure (didactic) reason) any more than the coarse ideal of recreation of sensuous nature. The aim is to free human nature from accidental hinderances, without destroying the essential ideal of ciur humanity, or displacing its limits. All bej^ond this is exaggeration, and a quicksand in which the poet too easily suffers shipwreck if he mistakes the idea of nobleness. But, unfortunately, he cannot rise to the true ideal of ennobled human nature without going some steps bej'ond it. To rise so high he must abandon the world of reality, for, like every ideal, it is onlj- to be drawn from its inner moral source. He does not find it in the turmoil of worldly life, but only in his heart, and that onh' in calm meditation. But in this separation from real life he is likely' to lose sight of all the limits of human nature, and seeking pure form he may easily- lose himself in arbitrary and baseless conceptions. Reason will abstract itself too much from experience, and the practical man will not be able to carry out, in the crush of real life, what the con- templative mind has discovered on the peaceful path of thought. Thus, what makes a dreamy man is the verj' thing that alone could have made him a sage ; and the advantage for the latter is not that he has never been a dreamer, but rather that he has not remained one. ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 339 We must not, then, allow the workers to determine recreation according to their wants, nor thinkers that of nobleness according to their speculations, for fear of either a too low phj-sical poetry, or a poetry too given to hj-perphj'sical exaggeration. And as these two ideas direct most men's judgments on poetrj', we must seek a class of mind at once active, but not slavishly so, and idealizing, but not dreamy ; uniting the realit}' of life within as few limits as possible, obe3ing the current of human affairs, but not enslaved by them. Such a class of men can alone preserve the beautiful unit}' of human nature, that harmonj' which all work for a moment disturbs, and a life of work destroys ; such alone can, in all that is purely human, give hy its feelings universal rules of judgment. Whether such a class exists, or whether the class now existing in like conditions answers to this ideal conception, I am not concerned to inquire. If it does not respond to the ideal it has only itself to blame. In such a class — here regarded as a mere ideal — the simple and sentimental would keep each other from extremes of extravagance and relaxation. For the idea of a beautiful humanity is not exhausted by either, but can only be presented in the union of both. THE STAGE AS A MORAL INSTITUTION. SuLZER has remarked that the stage has arisen from an irresistible longing for the new and extraordinary. Man, oppressed by divided cares, and satiated with sensual pleasure, felt an emptiness or want. Man, neither alto- gether satisfied with tlie_senses,_ nor forever capable of thought, wanted a middTeTtatfi^_a bridge between the two states, bringing them into harmony. Beauty and aesthet- ics supplied that for him. But a good law^giver is not sat- isfied with discovering the bent of his people — he turns it to account as an instrument for higher use ; and hence he chose the stage, as giving nourishment to the soul, without straining it, and uniting the noblest education of the head and heart. 340 JESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. The man who first pronounced religion to be the strong- est pillar of the state, unconsciouslj- defended the stage, when he said so, in its noblest aspect. The uncertain nature of political events, rendering religion a necessitj-, also demands the stage as a moral force. Laws only jpre- vent disturbances of social life ; religion prescribes posi- five orders sustaining social order. Law only governs ac- tions ; religion controls the heart and follows thought to the source. Laws are flexible and capricious ; religion binds for- ever. If religion has this great swaj' over man's heart, can it also complete his culture ? Separating the political from tlie divine element in it, religion acts mostly on the senses ; she loses her sway if the senses are gone. By what channel does the stage operate? To most men re- ligion vanishes with the loss of her symbols, images, and problems ; and yet the}' are oulj' pictures of the imagina- tion, and insolvable problems. Both laws and religion are strengthened by a union with the stage, where virtue and vice, joy and sorrow, are thoroughly displayed in a truthful and popular way ; where a variet}- of providential problems are solved ; where all secrets are unmasked, all artifice ends, and truth alone is the judge, as incorruptible as Khadamanthus. Where the influence of civil laws ends that of the stage begins. Where ^•enality and corruption blind and bias justice and judgment, and intimidation perverts its ends, the stage seizes the sword and scales and pronounces a terrible verdict on vice. The fields of fancy and of his- tory are open to the stage ; great criminals of the past live over again in the drama, and thus benefit an indig- nant posterit3^ They pass before us as empty shadows of their age, and we heap curses on their memory while we enjo}- on the stage the very horror of their crimes. When moralitj' is no more taught, religion no longer re- ceived, or laws exist, Medea would still terrify us with her infanticide. The sight of Lady Macbeth, while it makes us shudder, will also make us rejoice in a good con- science, when we see her, the sleep-walker, washing her hands and seeking to destroy the awful smell of murder. Sight is always more powerful to man than description ; ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 341 hence the stage acts more powerfully than morahty or law. But in this the stage onlj' aids justice. A far wider field is really open to it. There are a thousand vices un- noticed by human justice, but condemned 53- the stage ; so, also, a thousand virtues overlooked b}- man's laws are honored on the stage. It is thus the handmaid of reli- gion and philosophy. From these pure sources it draws its high principles and the exalted teachings, and presents them in a lovelj' form. The soul swells with noblest emo- tions when a divine ideal is placed before it. When Augustus offers his forgiving hand to Cinna, the conspira- tor, and sa3'^s to him : '• Let us be friends, Cinna ! " what man at the moment does not feel that he could do the same. Again, when Francis von Sickingen, proceeding to punish a prince and redress a stranger, on turning sees the house, where his wife and children are, in flames, and 3-et goes on for the sake of his word — how great humanity' appears, how small the stern povver of fate ! Vice is portrayed on the stage in an equall}^ telling manner. Thus, when old Lear, blind, helpless, childless, is seen knocking in vain at his daughters' doors, and in tempest and night he recounts by telling his woes to the elements, and ends bj- sa3'ing : "I have given you all," — how strongly impressed we feel at the value of filial piety, and how hateful ingratitude seems to us ! The stage does even more than this. It cultivates the ground where religion and law do not think it dignified to stop. Folly often troubles the world as much as crime ; and it has been justly said that the heaviest loads often hang suspended by the slightest threads. Tracing actions to their sources, the list of criminals diminish, and we laugh at the long catalogue of fools. In our sex all forms of evil emanate almost entirel3'' from one source, and all our excesses are only varied and higher forms of one qualit3', and that a quality which in the end we smile at and love ; and whj' should not nature have followed this course in the opposite sex too ? In man there is only one secret to guard against depravity ; that is, to protect his heart against wickedness. Much of all this is shown up on the stage. It is a 342 jESThetical letters and essays. mirror to reflect fools and their thousand forms of folly, which are there turned to ridicule. It curbs vice by ter- ror, and folly still more effectually by satire and jest. If a comparison be made between tragedy and comedy, guided by experience, we should probably give the palm to the latter as to efl"ects produced. Hatred does not wound the conscience so much as mockery does the pride of man. We are exposed specially to the sting of satire by the very cowardice that shuns terrors. P'rom sins we are guarded by law and conscience, but the ludicrous is specially punished on the stage. Where we allow a friend to correct our morals, we rarely forgive a laugh. We may bear heavy judgment on our transgressions, but our weaknesses and vulgarities must not be criticised by a witness. The stage alone can do this with impunity, chastising us as the anonymous fool. We can bear this rebuke with- out a blush, and even gratcfull3'. But the stage does even more than this. It is a great school of practical wisdom, a guide for civil life, and a key to the mind in all its sinuosities. It does not, of course, remove egoism and stubbornness in evil waj's ; for a thousand vices hold up their heads in spite of the stage, and a tliousand virtues make no impression on cold- hearted spectators. Thus, probably, Moliere's Harpagon never altered a usurer's heart, nor did the suicide in Bev- i erley save any one from the gaming-table. Nor, again, is ! it likely that the high roads will be safer through Karl I Moor's untimely end. But, admitting this, and more than this, still how great is the influence of the stage! It has shown us the vices and virtues of men with whom we have to live. We are not surprised at their weaknesses, we are prepared for them. The stage points them out to us, and their remedy. It drags off" the mask from the hypocrite, and betrays the meshes of intrigue. Duplicity and cun- ning have been forced by it to show their hideous features in the light of day. Perhaps the dying Sarah may not deter a single debauchee, nor all the pictures of avenged seduction stop the evil ; yet unguarded innocence has-been shown the snares of the corrupter, and taught to distrust his oaths. ^STHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 343 The stage also teaches men to bear the strokes of for- tune. Chance and design have equal swaj- over life. We have to bow to the former, but we control the latter. It is a great advantage if inexorable facts do not find us un- prepared and unexercised, and if our breast has been steeled to bear adversity. Much human woe is placed be- fore us on the stage. It gives us momentarj' pain in the tears we shed for strangers' troubles, but as a compensa- tion it fills us with a grand new stock of courage and en- durance. We are led by it, with the abandoned Ariadne, ttirough the Isle of Naxos, and we descend the Tower of Starvation in Ugolino ; we ascend the terrible scaffold, and we are present at the awful moment of execution. Things remotely present in thought become palpable real- ' ities now. We see the deceived favorite abandoned by the queen. When about to die, the perfidious Moor is abandoned by his own sophistry. Eternity reveals the secrets of the unknown through the dead, and the hateftd wretch loses all screen of guilt when the tomb opens to condemn him. Then the stage teaches us to be more considerate to the unfortunate, and to judge gently. We can only pro- nounce on a man when we know his whole being and cir- cumstances. Theft is a base crime, but tears mingle with our condemnation, when we read what obliged Edward Ruhberg to do the horrid deed. Suicide is shocking ; but the condemnation of an»enraged father, her love, and the fear of a convent, lead Marianne to drink the cup, and few would dare to condemn the victim of a dreadful tyranny. Humanitj' and tolerance have begun to prevail in our time at courts of princes and in courts of law. A large share of this maj- be due to the influence of the stage in showing man and his secret motives. The great of the world ought to "be especially grate- ful to the stage, for it is here alone that they hear the truth. Not only man's mind, but also his intellectual culture, has been promoted by the higher drama. The lofty mind and the ardent patriot have often used the stage to spread enlightenment. Considering nations and ages, the thinker sees the masses enchamed by opinion and cut off by adver- 344 ^STHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. sity from happiness ; truth onlj' lighis up a few minds, who perhaps have to acquire it b}- the trials of a lifetime. How can the wise ruler put these within the reach of his nation. The thoughtful and the worthier section of the people diffuse the light of wisdom over the masses through the stage. Purer and better principles and motives issue from the stage and circulate through society ; the night of bar- barism and superstition vanishes. T would mention two glorious fruits of the higher class of dramas. Religious toleration has latterly become universal. Before Nathan the Jew and Saladin the Saracen put us to shame, and showed that resignation to God's will did not depend on a fancied belief of His nature — even before Joseph II. contended with the hatred of a narrow piety — the stage had sown seeds of humanity and gentleness : pictures of fanaticism had taught a hatred of intolerance, and Chris- tianitj-, seeing itself in this awful mirror, washed off its stains. It is to be hoped that the stage will equally com- bat mistaken systems of educa tion. This is a subject of the first political importance, and yet none is so left to private whims and caprice. The stage might give stirring examples of mistaken education, and lead parents to juster, better views of the subject. Many teachers are led astray b}- false views, and methods are often artificial and fatal. Opinions about governments and classes might be re- formed by the stage. Legislation could thus justifj^ itself by foreign symbols, and silence doubtful aspersions without offence. Now, if poets would be patriotic the}- could do much on the stage to forward invention and industry. A standing theatre would be a material advantage to a nation. It would have a great influence on the national temper and mind by helping the nation to agree in opinions and incli- nations. The stage alone can do (his, because it commands all human knowledge, exhausts all positions, illumines all hearts, unites all classes, and nmkes its way to the heart and understanding by the most |)opular channels. If one feature characterized all dramas ; if the poets were allied in aim — that is, if they selected well and from ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 845 national topics — there would be a national stage, and we should become a nation. It was this that knit the Greeks so strongly together, and this gave to them the all-absorbing interest in the republic and the advancement of humanity. Another advantage belongs to the stage ; one which seems to have become acknowledged even by its censurers. Its influence on intellectual and moral culture, which we have till now been advocating, may be doubted ; but its very enemies have admitted that it has gained the palm over all other means of amusement. It has been of much higher service here than people are often readj- to allow. Human nature cannot bear to be always on the rack of business, and the charms of sense die out with their grat- ification. Man, oppressed by appetites, wearj' of long exertion, thirsts for r efined pleasur e, or rushes into dissi- pations that hasten his fall and ruin, and disturb social order. Bacchanal J03S, gambling, follies of all sorts to disturb ennui, are unavoidable if the lawgiver produces nothing better. A man of public business, who has made noble sacrifices to the state, is apt to pay for them with melancholy, the scholar to become a pedant, and the peo- ple brutish, without the stage. The stage is an institution . combining amusement with instruction, rest with exertion, where no faculty of the mind is overstrained, no pleasure enjoyed at the cost of the whole. When melancholy gnaws the heart, when trouble prisons our solitude, when we are disgusted with the world, and a thousand worries oppress us, or when our energies are destroj'ed by over-exercise, the stage revives us, we dream of another sphere, we re- cover ourselves, our torpid nature is roused % noble pas- sions, our blood circulates more healthil}-. The unhappj^ man forgets his tears in weeping for another. The happy^ man is calmed, the secure made provident. Effeminate natures are steeled, savages made man, and, as the supreme triumph of nature, men of all ranks, zones, and conditions, emancipated from the chains of conventionality and fash- ion, fraternize here in a universal sympathy, forget the world, and come nearer to their heavenly destination. The individual shares in the general ecstacy, and his breast has now only space for an emotion : he is a vfian. 346 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. ON THE TRAGIC AET. The state of passion in itself, independenth' of the good or bad influence of its object on oui' moralitj-, has some- thing in it that charms us. We aspire to transport our- selves into that state, even if it costs ns some sacrifices. You will find this instinct at the bottom of all our most habitual pleasures. As to the nature itself of the affection, whether it be one of aversion or desire, agreeable or pain- ful, this is what we take little into consideration. Expe- rience teaches us that painful affections are those which have the most attraction for us, and thus that the pleasure we take in an affection is preciselj- in an inverse ratio to its nature. It is a phenomenon common to all men, that sad, frightful things, even the horrible, exercise over us an irrisistible seduction, and that in presence of a scene of desolation and of terror we feel at once repelled and attracted b}' two equal forces. Suppose the case be an assassination. Then eveiy one crowds round the narrator and shows a marked attention. Anj' ghost story, however embellished by romantic circumstances, is greedil}' de- ^•oured by us, and the more readilj- in proportion as the story is calculated to make our hair stand on end. This disposition is developed in a more livel3' manner when the objects themselves are placed before our eyes. A tempest that would swallow up an entire fleet would be, seen from shore, a spectacle as attractive to our imagina- tion as it would be shocking to our heart. It would be difficult to believe with Lucretius that this natural pleasure results from a comparison between our own safet}- and the danger of which we are witnesses. See what a crowd accompanies a criminal to the scene of his punishment ! This phenomenon cannot be explained either by the pleas- ure of satisfj'ing our love of justice, nor the ignoble joy of vengeance. Perhaps the unhappy man may find excuses in the hearts of those present ; perhaps the sincerest pity takes an interest in his reprieve : this does not prevent a ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 347 lively curiosity in tbe spectators to watch his expressions of pain with eye and ear. If an exception seems to exist here in the case of a well-bred man, endowed with a delicate sense, this does not imply that he is a complete stranger to this instinct ; but in his case the painful strength of compassion carries the day over this instinct, or it is kept under bj' the laws of decenej'. The man of nature, who is not chained down by any feeling of human delicacj', abandons himself without anj' sense of shame to this powerful instinct. This attraction must, therefore, have its spring of action in an original disposition, and it must be explained by a psychological law common to the whole species. But if it seems to us that these brutal instincts of nature are incompatible with the dignitj' of man, and if we hesi- tate, for this reason, to establish on this fact a law common to the whole species, yet no experiences are required to prove, with the comjjletest evidence, that the pleasure we take in painful emotions is real, and that it is general. The painful struggle of a lieart drawn asunder between its inclinations or contrary' duties, a struggle which is a cause of misery to him who experiences it, delights the person wiio is a mere spectator. We follow with always height- ening pleasure the progress of a passion to the abj-ss into which it hurries its unhappy victim. The same delicate feeling that makes us turn our ej'es aside from the sight of physical suffering, or e^»sn from the physical expression of a purely moral pain, makes us experience a pleasure heightened in sweetness, in the sympathy- for a purely moral pain. The interest with which we stop to look at the painting of these kinds of objects is a general phenome- non. Of course this can onl}- be understood of sympathetic affections, or those felt as a secondary effect after their first impression; for commonlj- direct and personal affec- tions immediately call into life in us the instinct of our own happiness, they take up all our thoughts, and seize hold of us too powerfully to allow any room for the feeling of pleasure that accompanies them, when the affection is freed from all personal relation. Thus, in the mind that is really' a prey to painful passion, the feeling of pain 348 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. commands all others notwithstanding all the charm that the painting of its moral state may offer to the hearers and the spectators. And yet the painful affection is not deprived of all pleasure, even for him who experiences it directly ; only this pleasure differs in degree according to the nature of each person's mind. The sports of chance would not have half so much attraction for us were tliere not a kind of enjoyment in anxiety, m doubt, and in fear; danger would not be encountered from mere foolhardiness ; and the very sj-mpathy which interests us in the trouble of another would not be to us that pleasure which is never more lively than at the verj- moment when the illusion is strongest, and when we substitute ourselves most entirely in the place of the person who suffers. But this does not imply that disagreeable affections cause pleasure of them- selves, nor do I think an3' one will uphold this view ; it suffices that these states of the mind are the conditions that alone make possible for us certain kinds of pleasure. Thus the hearts particularly sensitive to this kind of pleasure, and most greedy of them, will be more easily led to share these disagreeable affections, which are the con- dition of the former ; and even in the most violent storms of passion they will always preserve some remains of their freedom. The displeasure we feel in disagreeable affections comes from the relation of our sensuous faculty or of our moral faculty with their object. In like manner, the pleasure we experience in agreeable affections proceeds from the very same source. The degree of libertj- that may prevail in the affections depends on the proportion between the moral nature and the sensuous nature of a man. Now it is well known that in the moral order there is nothing arbitrary for us, that, on the contrarj^ the sensuous instinct is subject to the laws of reason and consequentlj- depends more or less on our will. Hence it is evident that we can keep our liberty full and entire in all those affections that are concerned with the instinct of self-love, and that we are the masters to determine the degree which the}'' ought to attain. This degree will be less in proportion as the moral sense in a man will prevail over the instinct of happiness, and as by obeying the universal laws of reason ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 349 he will have freed himself from the selfish requirements of his individualit}', his Ego. A man of this kind must tlierefore, in a state of passion, feel much less vividh' the relation of an object with his own instinct of happiness, and consequently he will be much less sensible of the displeasure that arises from this relation. On the other hand, he will be perpetually more attentive to the relation of this same object with his moral nature, and for this very reason he will be more sensible to the pleasure which the relation of the object with moralitj- often mingles with the most painful affections A mind thus constituted is better fitted than all others to enjoy the pleasure attaching to compassion, and even to regard a personal affection as an object of simple compassion. Hence the inestimable value of amoral philosophy, which, bj' raising our e3'es constantly towards general laws, weakens in us the feeling of our individuality, teaches us to plunge our paltr^' personalitj- in something great, and enables us thus to act to ourselves as to strangers. This sublime state of the mind is the lot of strong philosophic minds, which by working assiduously on themselves ha^e learned to bridle the egotistical instinct. E\ en the most cruel loss does not drive them beyond a certain degree of sadness, with which an appreciable sum of pleasure can alwa3-s be reconciled. These souls, which are alone capable of separating themselves from themselves, alone eujo3- the privilege of sj^ipathizing with themselves and of receiving of their own sufferings onlv a reflex, softened by sympathy. The indications contained in what precedes will suffice to direct our attention to the sources of the pleasure that the affection in itself causes, more particularly the sad affection. We have seen that this pleasure is more ener- getic in moral souls, and it acts with greater freedom in proportion as the soul is more independent of the ego- tistical instinct. This pleasure is, moreover, more vivid and stronger in sad affections, when self-love is painfull3' disquieted, than in ga3' affections, wliich impl3' a satisfac- tion of self-love. Accordingly this pleasure increases when the egotistical instinct is wounded, and diminishes M'hen that instinct is flattered. Now we onl3' know of 350 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. two sources of pleasure — the satisfaction of the instinct of happiness, and the accomplishment of the moral laws. Therefore, when it is shown that a particular pleasure does not emanate from the former source, it must of necessity issue from the second. It is therefore from our moral nature that issues the charm of the painful affec- tions shared by sympathj', and the pleasure that we some- times feel even where the painful affection directly affects ourselves. Many attempts have been made to account for the pleasure of pity, but most of these solutions had little chance of meeting the problem, because the principle of this phenomenon was sought for rather in the accompany- ing circumstances than in the nature of the affection itself. To many persons the pleasure of pity is simpl}- the pleasure taken by the mind in exercising its own sensibility. To others it is the pleasure of occupj-ing their forces energetically, of exercising the social faculty vividly — in short, of satisfying the instinct of restlessness. Others again make it derived from the discovery of morally fine features of character, placed in a clear light by the struggle against adversity or against the passions. But there is still the difficulty to explain why it should be exactly the very feeling of pain, — suffering properly so called, — that in objects of pity attracts us with the greatest force, while, according to those elucidations, a less degree of suffering ought evidently to be more favoi-- able to those causes to which the source of the emotion is traced. Various matters maj-, no doubt, increase the pleasure of the emotion without occasioning it. Of this nature are : the vividness and force of the ideas awakened in our imagination, the moral excellence of the suffering persons, the reference to himself of the person feeling pity. I admit that the suffering of a weak soul, and the pain of a wicked character, do not procure us this enjoy- ment. But this is because they do not excite our pity to the same degree as the hero who suffers, or the virtuous man who struggles. Thus we are constantly brought back to the first question : why is it precisely- tlie degree- of suffering that determines the degree of sympathetic pleasure which we take in an emotion? and one answer ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 351 only is possible ; it is because the attack made on our sensibility is precisely the condition necessary to set in motion that quality of mind of which the activity produces the pleasure we feel in sympathetic affections. Now this faculty is no other than the reason ; and because the free exercise of reason, as an absolutely inde- pendent activitj', deserves par excellence the name of activity ; as, moreover, the heart of man only feels itself perfectly free and independent in its moral acts, it follows that the charm of tragic emotions is reall3- dependent on the fact that this instinct of actixitj- finds its gratification in them. But, even admitting this, it is neither the great number nor the vivacity of the ideas that are awakened then in our imagination, nor in general the exercise of the social faculty, but a certain kind of ideas and a certain activity of the social faculty brought into play bj- reason, which is the foundation of this pleasure. Thus the sj'mpathetic affections in general are for us a source of pleasure because the}' give satisfaction to our instinct of activity, and the sad affections produce this effect with more vividness because the}' give more satis- faction to this instinct. The mind only reveals all its activity when it is in full possession of its liberty, when it has a perfect consciousness of its rational nature, because it is only then that it displays a force superior to all resistance. Hence the state of mind which allows most eflfectuallj- the manifestation of this force, and awakens most success- fully its activity, is that state which is most suitable to a rational being, and which best satisfies our instincts of activity : whence it follows that a greater amount of pleasure must be attached necessarily to this state. Now it is the tragic states that place our soul in this state, and the pleasure found in them is necessarily higher than the charm produced bj' gay affections, in thQ same degree that moral power in us is superior to the power of the senses. Points that are only subordinate and partial in a S3Stem of final causes maj' be considered by art independently of that relation with the rest, and may be converted into principal objects. It is right that in the designs of nature pleasure should only be a mediate end, or a 352 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. means ; but for art it is the highest end. It is therefore essentiall}- important for art not to neglect this high enjoy- ment attaching to the tragic emotion. Now, tragic art, taking this term in its widest acceptation, is that among tlie fine arts which proposes as its principal object the pleasure of pitj'. Art attains its end bj- the imitation of nature^ by satis- fj'ing the conditions which make pleasure possible in reality, and hy combining, according to a plan traced b3' the intelligence, the scattered elements furnished b}' na- ture, so as to attain as a principal end to that which, for nature, was only an accessor}- end. Thus tragic art ought to imitate nature in those kinds of actions that are spe- cially adapted to awaken [jit}-. It follows that, in order to determine generall}- the S3S- tem to be followed by tragic art, it is necessary bef(;re all things to know on what conditions in real life the pleasure of the emotion is commonl}- produced in the surest and the strongest manner ; but it is necessary at the same time to pay attention to the circumstances that restrict or abso- lutely extinguish this pleasure. After what we have established in our essaj' "On the Cause of the Pleasure we derive from Tragic Objects," it IS known that in e\'ery tragic emotion there is an idea of incongruity, which, though the emotion may be attended with charm, must alwaj-s lead on to the conception of a higher consistency. Now it is the relation that these two opposite conceptions mutuall}' bear which determines in an emotion if the prevaiUng impression shall be pleas- urable or the reverse If the conception of incongruity be more vivid than that of the contrary', or if tlie end sac- rificed is more important than the end gained, the prevail- ing impression will alwaj-s be displeasure, whether this be understood objectiveU/ of the human race in general, or only subjectively of certian individuals. If the cause that has produced a misfortune gives us too much displeasure, our compassion for the victim is dimin- ished thereby. The heart cannot feel simultaneously', in a high degree, two absolutely contrary atfections. Indigna- tion against the person who is the primary cause of the suffering becomes the prevailing affection, and all other ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 353 feeling has to yield to it. Thus our interest is always en- feebled when the unhappy man whom it would be desirable to pity had cast himself into ruin by a personal and an inexcusable fault ; or if, being able to save himself, he did not do so, either through feebleness of mind or pusillan- imity The interest we take in unhappj' King Lear, ill- treated by two ungrateful daughters, is sensibly lessened by the circumstance that this aged man, in his second childhood, so weakly gave up his crown, and divided his love among his daughters with so little discernment. In the tragedy of Kronegk, " Olinda and Sophronia," the most terrible suffering to which we see these martyrs to their faith exposed onl^' excites our pit}' feebly, and all their heroism only stirs our admiration moderately, be- cause madness alone can suggest the act b}- which Olinda has placed himself and all his people on the brink of the . precipice. Our pity is equally lessened when the primary' cause of a misfortune, whose innocent victim ought to inspire us with compassion, fills our mind with horror. When the tragic poet cannot clear himself of his plot without intro- ducing a wretch, and when he is reduced to derive the greatness of suffermg from the greatness of wickedness, the supreme beauty of his work must always be seriously injured. lago and Lady Macbeth in Shakspeare, Cleo- patra in the tragedy of " Rodogune," or Franz Moor in " The Robbers," are so manj- proofs in support of this as- sertion. A poet who understands his real interest will not bring about the catastrophe through a malicious will which proposes misfortune as its end ; nor, and still less, bj' want of understanding : but rather through the imperious force of circumstances. If this catastrophe does not come from moral sources, but from outward things, which have no volition and are not subject to any will, the pity we experience is more pure, or at all events it is not weak- ened by any idea of moral incongruity. But then the spectator cannot be spared the disagreeable feeling of an incongruit}' in the order of nature, which can alone save in such a case moral propriety. Pity is far more excited when it has for its object both him who suffers and him who is the primary cause of the suffering. This can only 354 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. happen when the latter has neither elicited our contempt nor our hatred, but when he has been brought against his inclination to become the cause of this misfortune. It is a singular beauty of the German play of "Iphigenia" that the King of Tauris, .the only obstacle who thwarts the wishes of Orestes and of his sister, never loses our esteem, and that we love him to the end. There is something superior even to this kind of emo- tion ; this is the case when the cause of the misfortune not only is in no wa^' repugnant to moralit3', but only be- comes possible through moralitj', and when the reciprocal suffering comes simply from the idea that a fellow-creature has been made to suffer. This is the situation of Chimene and Rodrigue in " The Cid " of Pierre Corneille, which is undeniabl}' in point of intrigue the masterpiece of the tragic stage. Honor and filial love arm the hand of Eod- rigue against the father of her whom he loves, and his valor gives him the victory. Honor and filial love rouse up against him, in the person of Chimene, the daughter of his victim, an accuser and a formidable persecutor. Both act in opposition to their inclination, and they trem- ble with anguish at the thought of the misfortune of the object against which they arm themselves, in proportion as zeal inspires them foi- their duty to inflict this misfor- time. Accordingly both conciliate our esteem in the high- est sense, as they accomplish a moral duty at the cost of inclination ; both inflame our pity in the highest degree, because they suffer spontaneously for a motive that ren- ders them in the highest degree to be respected. It re- sults from this that our pity is in this case so little modi- fied by any opposite feeling that it burns rather with a double flame ; only the impossibility of reconciling the idea of misfortune with the idea of a morality so deserving of happiness might still disturb our sympathetic pleasure, and spread a shade of sadness over it. It is besides a great point, no doubt, that the discontent given us by this contradiction does not bear upon our moral being, but is turned aside to a harmless place, to necessity only ; but this blind subjection to destiny is always afflicting and humiliating for free beings, who determine themselves. This is the cause that always leaves something to be jESthetical letters and essays. 355 wished for even in the best Greek pieces. In all these pieces, at the bottom of the plot it is always fatality that is appealed to, and in this there is a knot that cannot be unravelled by our reason, which wishes to solve everj- thing. But even this knot is untied, and with it vanishes ever}' shade of displeasure, at the highest and last step to which man perfected by moralit}' rises, and at the highest point which is attained by the art which moves the feelings. This happens when the very discontent with destiny be- comes effaced, and is resolved in a presentiment or rather a clear consciousness of a teleological concatenation of things, of a sublime order, of a beneficent will. Then, to the pleasure occasioned in us bj- moral consistenc}' is joined the invigorating idea of the most perfect .suitability in the great whole of nature. In this case the thing that seemed to militate against this order, and that caused us pain, in a particular case, is only a spur that stimulates our reason to seek in general laws for the justification of this particular case, and to solve the problem of this sepa- rate discord in the centre of the general harmony. Greek art never rose to this supreme -serenity of tragic emotion, because neither the national religion, nor even the philos- ophy of the Greeks, lighted their step on this advanced I'oad. It was reserved for modern art, which enjojs the pri\ilege of finding a purer matter in a purer philosophj', to satisf}' also this exalted want, apd thus to display all the moral dignity of art. If we moderns must resign ourselves never to re- produce Greek art because the philosophic genms of our age, and modern civilization ni general are not favorable to poetry, these influences are at all events less hurtful to tragic art, which is based rather on the moral element. Perhaps it is in the ease of this art only that our civiliza- tion repairs the injury that it has caused to art in general. Ill the same manner as the tragic emotion is weakened by the admixture of conflicting ideas and feelings, and the charm attaching to it is thus diminished, so this emotion can also, on the contrary, by approaching the excess of direct and personal affection, become exaggerated to the point where pain carries the daj- over pleasure. It has 356 JESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS, been remarked that displeasure, in the affections, comes from the relation of their object with our senses, in the same wa\- as the pleasui'e felt in them comes from the rela- tion of the affection itself to our moral facultj-. This implies, then, between our senses and our moral faculty a determined relation, which decides as regards the relation bcitween pleasure and displeasure in tragic emotions. Nor could this relation be modified or overthrown without overthrowing at the same time the feelings of pleasure and displeasure which we find in the emotions, or even without changing them into their opposites. In the same ratio that the senses are vividly roused in us, the influence of inoralit}- will be proportionately diminished ; and recipro- cnllj, as the sensuous loses, morality gains ground. There- fore that which in our hearts gives a preponderance to the sensuous faculty, must of necessity, by placing restrictions on the moral faculty', diminish the pleasure that we take in tragic emotions, a pleasure which emanates exclusively from this moral faculty*. In like manner, all that in our heart impresses an impetus on this latter faculty, must blunt the stimulus of pain even in direct and personal affections. Now our sensuous nature actually acquires this preponderance, when the ideas of suffering rise to a degree of vividness that no longer allows us to distinguish a sympathetic affection from a personal affection, or our (jwn proper Ego from the subject that suffers, — reality, in short, from poetry. The sensuous also gains the upper liand when it finds an aliment in the great number of its objects, and in that dazzling light which an over-excited imagination diffuses over it. On the contrary, nothing is more fit to reduce the sensuous to its proper bounds than to place alongside it super-sensuoiis ideas, moral ideas, to which reason, oppressed just before, clings as to a kind of spiritual props, to right and raise itself above the fogs of the sensuous to a serener atmosphere. Hence the great charm which general truths or moral sentences, scattered opportunely over dramatic dialogue, have for all cultivated jiations, and the almost excessive use that the Greeks made of them. Nothing is more agreeable to a moral soul than to have the power, after a purely passive state that has lasted too long, of escaping from the subjection of the -fflSTHETIOAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 357 senses, and of being recalled to its spontaneous activity, and restored to the possession of its liberty. These are the remarks I had to make respecting the causes that restrict our pity and place an obstacle to our pleasure in tragic emotions. I have next to show on what conditions pity is solicited and the pleasure of the emotion excited in the most infallible and energetic manner. Every feeling of pity implies the idea of suffering, and the degree of pity is regulated according to the degree more or less of vividness, of truth, of intensitj', and of duration of this idea. 1st. The moral faculty' is provoked to reaction in pro- portion to the vividness of ideas in the soul, which incites it to activity and solicits its sensuous faculty. Now the ideas of suffering are conceived in two different manners, which are not equallj^ favorable to the vividness of the impression. The sufferings that we witness affect us nicomparably more than those that we have through a description or a narrative. The former suspend in us the free plaj- of the fancy, and striking our senses immediately penetrate b^- the shortest road to our heart. In the nar- rative, on the contrary, the particular is first raised to the general, and it is from this that the knowledge of the special case is afterwards deri-\'ed ; accordingl}', merely- bj' this necessary operation of the understanding, the impres- sion already loses greatly in strength. Now a weak im- pression cannot take complete possession of our mind, and it will allow other iffeas to disturb its action and to dissipate the attention. Verj' frequently, moreover, the narrative account transports us from the moral disposition, in wiiich the acting person is placed, to the state of mind of the narrator himself, which breaks up tlie illusion so necessary for pity. Iif ever}- case, when the narrator in person puts himself forward, a certain stoppage takes place in the action, and, as an unavoidable result, in our sympathetic affection. This is what happens even when the dramatic poet forgets himself in tlie dialogue, and puts in the mouth of his dramatic persons reflections that could only enter the mind of a disinterested spectator. It would be difficult to mention a single one of our modern tragedies quite free from this defect ; but the French alone S58 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. have made a rule of it. Let us infer, then, that the imme- diate vivid and sensuous presence of the object is necessary to give to the ideas impressed on us by suffering that strength without which the emotion could not rise to a high degree. 2d. But we can receive the most vivid impressions of the idea of suffering without, however, being led to a remarkable degree of pity, if these impressions lack truth. It is necessary that we should form of suffering an idea of such a nature that we are obliged to share and take part in it. To this end there must be a certain agreement between this suffering and something that we have alreadj' in us. In other words, pity is only possible inasmuch as we can prove or suppose a resemblance between ourselves and the subject that suffers. Everywhere where this resemblance makes itself known, pity is necessar}- ; where this resemblance is lacking, pitj' is impossible. The more visible and the greater is the resemblance, the more vivid is our pity ; and they mutually slacken in dependence on each other. In order that we maj' feel the affections of another after him, all the internal conditions demandedby this affection must be found beforehand in us, in order that the external cause which, bj' meeting with the inter- nal conditions, has given birth to the afiection, may ajso produce on us a like effect. It is necessary that, without doing violence to ourselves, we should be able to exchange persons with another, and transport our Ego by an instan- taneous substitution in the state of the subject. Now, how is it possible to feel in us the state of another, if we have not beforehand recognized ourselves in this other. This resemblance bears on the totalitj' of the constitu- tion of the mind, in as far as that is necessar3- and uni- versal. Now, this character of necessity' and of univer- sality belongs especially to our moral nature. The faculty of feeling can be determined differentl}' by accidental causes : our cognitive faculties themselves depend on va- riable conditions : the moral facultj- only has its principle in itself, and by that ver^-fact it can best give us a general measure and a certain criterion of this resemblance. Thus an idea which we find in accord with our mode of thinking and of feeling, which offers at once a certain rela- tionship with the train of our own ideas, which is easily ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 359 grasped by our heart and our mind, we call a true idea. If this relationship bears on what is peculiar to our heart, on the private determinations that modify in us the common fundamentals of humanity, and which maj' be withdrawn without altering this general character, this idea is then simply true/ci;- us. If it bears on the general and neces- sary form that we suppose in the whole species, the truth of this idea ought to be held to be equal to objective truth. For the Roman, the sentence of the first Brutus and the suicide of Cato are of subjective truth. The ideas and the feelings that ha^-e inspired the actions of these two men are not an immediate consequence of human nature in general, but the mediate consequence of a human nature determined by particular modifications. To share with them these feelings we must have a Roman soul, or at least be capable of assuming for a moment a Roman soul. It suffices, on the other hand, to be a num in general, to be viviiU}' touched by the heroic sacrifice of Leonidas, bj- the quiet resignation of Aristides, "by the voluntar3' death of Socrates, and to be moved to tears b3' the terrible changes in the fortunes of Darius. We attribute to tliese kind's of ideas, in opposition to the preceding ones, an objective truth because they agree with the nature of all human subjects, which gives them a character of univer- salitj' and of necessity as strict as if they were independ- ent of every subjective condition. Moreover, although^he subjectively true description is based on accidental determinations, this is no reason for confounding it with an arbitrarj' description. After all, the subjectivel}- true emanates also from the general consti- tution of the human soul, modified only in particular directions by special circumstances ; and the two kinds of truth are equally necessary conditions of the human mind. If the resolution of Cato were in contradiction with the general laws of human nature, it could not be true, even subjectively. The only difference is that the ideas of the second kind are enclosed in a narrower sphere of action ; because the}^ implVj besides the general modes of the human mind, other special determinations. Tragedy can make use of it with a very Intense effect, if it will renounce the extensive effect ; still the unconditionally true, what 360 it;STHETICAL LETTEKS AND ESSAYS. is purely human in human relations, will be always the richest matter for the tragic poet, because this ground is the onlj' one on which tragedy, without ceasing to aspire to strength of expression can be certain of the generality of this impressioii. 3d. Besides the vividness and the truth of tragic pictures, there must also be completeness. None of the external data that are necessary to give to the soul the desired movement ought to be omitted in the representation. In order that the spectator, liowe\'er Roman his sentiments may be, may understand the moral state of Cato — that he may make his own the high resolution of the republican, this resolution must have its' principle, not onlj' in the mind of the Roman, but also in the circumstances of the action. His external situation as well as his internal situation must be before our cj-es in all their consequences and extent : and we must, lastlj', have unrolled before us, without omitting a single link, the whole chain of deter- minations to which are attached the high resolution of the Roman as a necessary consequence. It maj- be said in general that without this third condition, even the truth of a painting cannot be recognized ; for the similarity of circumstances, which ought to be fully evident, can alone justify our judgment on the similarity of the feelings, since it is only from the competition of external conditions and of internal conditions that the aflfectiA-e phenomenon results. To decide if we should have acted like Cato, we must before all tilings transport ourselves in thought to the external situation in which Cato was placed, and then onlj' we are entitled to place our feelings alongside his, to pronounce if there is or is not likeness, and to give a verdict on the truth of these feelings. A complete picture, as I understand it, is onlj' possible by the concatenation of several separate ideas, and of several separate feelings, which are connected together as cause and effect, and which, in their sum total, form one single whole for our cognitive faculty. All these ideas, in order to affect us closely, must make an immediate impres- sion on our senses ; and, as the narrative form alwaj'S weakens this impression, thej' must be produced hy a present action. Thus, lu t)rder that a tragic picture maj' ;ejsthetical letxehw and essays. 361 be complete, a whole series is required of particular actions, rendered sensuous and connected with the tragic action as to one whole. 4th. it is necessary-, lastl}-, that the ideas we receive of suffering should act on us in a durable manner, to excite in us a high degree of emotion. The affection created in us b}' the suffering of another is to us a constrained state, from whicli we hasten to get free ; and the illusion so neces- saiy for pit}- easily disappears in this case. It is, therefore, a necessity to fasten the mind closely to these ideas, and not to leave it the freedom to get rid too soon of the illusion. The vividness of sudden ideas and the energy of sudden impressions, which in rapid succession affect our senses, would not suffice for this end. For the power of reaction in the mind is manifested in direct proportion to tlie force with which the receptive facultj* is solicited, and it is manifested to triumph over this impression. Now, the poet who wishes to move us ought not to weaken this independent power in us, for it is exactly in the struggle between it and the suffering of our sensuous nature that the higher charm of tragic emotions lies. In order that the heart, in spite of that spontaneous force which reacts against sensuous affections, may remain attached to the impressions of sufferings, it is, therefore, necessary that these impressions should be cleverlj' suspended at intervals, or even interrupted and intercepted by contrary im- pressions, to return a^in with twofold energy and renew more frequently the vividness of the first impression. Against the exhaustion and languor that result from habit, the most effectual remedj' is to propose new objects to the senses ; this varietj' retempers them, and the gradation of impressions calls forth the innate facultj', and makes it employ a proportionatelj- stronger resistance. This facultj- ought to be incessantlj' occupied in maintaining its inde- pendence against the attacks of the senses, but it must not triumph before the end, still less must it succumb in the struggle. Otherwise, in the former case, suffering, and, in the latter, moral activity is set aside ; while it is the union of these two that can alone elicit emotion. The great secret of the tragic art consists preciselj' in manag- ing this struggle well ; it is in this that it shows itself iu the most brilliant light. 362 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. For this, a succession of alternate ideas is required ; therefore a suitable combination is wanted of several par- ticular actions corresponding with these different ideas ; actions round which th« principal action and the tragic impression which it is wished to produce through it unroll themselves like the yarn from the distaff', and end by enlacing our souls in nets, through which they cannot break. Let me be permitted to make use of a simile, by saying that the artist ought to begin b3' gathering up with parsimonious care all the separate rays that issue from the object by aid of which he seeks to produce the tragic effect that he has in view, and these raj-s, in his hands, become a lightning flash, setting the hearts of all on fire. The tyro casts suddenl3- and vainly all the thunderbolts of horror and fear into the soul ; the artist, on the contrary, advances step bj' step to his end ; he onh* strikes with measured strokes, but he penetrates to the depth of our soul, precisely- because he has only stirred it bj' degrees. If we now form the proper deductions from the previous investigation, the following will be the conditions that form bases of the tragic art. It is necessary, in the first place, that the object of our pit}' should belong to our own species — I mean belong in the full sense of the term — and that the action in which it.is sought to interest us be a moral action ; that is, an action comprehended in the field of free-will. It is necessar}-, in the second place, that suffering, its sources, its degrees, should be completely communicated by a series of events chained together. It is necessary-, in the third place, that the object of the passion be rendered present to our senses, not in a mediate wa}' and by description, but immediatelj' and inaction. In tragedy art unites all these conditions and satisfies them. According to these principles tragedy might be defined as the poetic imitation of a coherent series of particular events (forming a complete action) : an imitation which shows us man in a state of sutfering, and which has for its end to excite our pity. I say first that it is the imitation of an action ; and this idea of imitation already distinguishes tragedj- from the other kinds of poetry-, which only narrate or describe. In ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 363 tragedy particular events are presented to our imagination or to our senses at the verj- time of ttieir accomplishment ; they are present, we see them immediately-, without the intervention of a third person. The epos, the romance, simple narrative, even in their form, withdraw action to a distance, causing the narrator to come between the acting person and the reader. Now what is distant and past always weakens, as we know, the impressions and the sj'mpathetic affection ; what is present makes them stronger. All narrative forms make of the present some- thing past ; all dramatic form makes of the past a present. Secondly, I say that tragedy is the imitation of a suc- cession of events, of an action. Tragedj- has not onl^' to represent bj- imitation the feelings and the affections of tragic persons, but also the events that have produced these feelings, and the occasion on which these affections are manifested. This distinguishes it from lyric poetry, and from its different forms, which no doubt offer, like tragedy, the poetic imitation of certain states of the mind, but not the poetic imitation of certain actions. An elegy, a song, an ode, can place before our eyes, by imitation, the moral state in which the poet actuall3' is — whether he speaks in his own name. Or in that of an ideal person — a state determined bj' particular circumstances ; and up to this point these lyric forms seem certainly to be incorpo- rated in the idea of tragedy ; but they do not complete that idea, because they are confined to representing our feelings. There are still more essential differences, if the end of these lyrical forms and that of tragedy are kept in view. I say, in the third place, that tragedy is the imitation of a complete action. A separate event, though it be ever so tragic, does not in itself constitute a tragedi'. To do this, several events are required, based one on the other, like cause and effect, and suitabl}' connected so as to form a whole ; without which the truth of the feeling represented, of the character, etc. -j- that is, their conformit}' with the nature of our mind, a conformity which alone determines our sj-mpathy — will not be recognized. If we do not feel that we ourselves in similar circumstances should have experienced the same feelings and acted in the same 364 jTISTHETrCAIi LETTERS AND ESSAYS. waj', our pit}- would not be awakened. It is, therefore, important that we should he able to follow in all its concatenation the action that is represented to us, that we should see it issue from the mind of the agent by a natural gradation, under the influence and with the concurrence of external circumstances. It is thus that we see spring up, grow, and come to maturity under our 63-68, the curiosity of OEdipus and the jealous^' of lago. It is also the onlj' way to fill up the great gap that exists between the joy of an innoceijt soul and the torments of a guilty conscience, between the proud serenitj- of the happy man and his terrible catastrophe ; in sliort, between the state of calm, in which the reader is at the beginning, and the violent agitation he ought to experience at the end. A series of several connected incidents is required to produce in our souls a succession of different movements which arrest the attention, which, appealing to all the faculties of our minds, enliven our instinct of activity when it is exhausted, and which, by delaying the satis- faction of this instinct, do not kindle it the less. Against the suflfering of sensuous nature the human heart has onl}' recourse to its moral nature as counterpoise. It is, therefore, necessary, in order to stimulate this in a more pressing manner, for the tragic poet to prolong the torments of sense, but he must also give a glimpse to the latter of the satisfaction of its wants, so as to render the victory of the moral sense so much the more difficult and glorious. This twofold end can onlj- be attained by a succession of actions judiciousl}' chosen and combined to this end. In the fourth place, I say that tragedy is the poetic imitation of an action deserving of pit}', and, therefore, tragic imitation is opposed to historic imitation. It would only be a historic imitation if it proposed a historic end, if its principal object were to teach us that a thing has taken place, and how it took place. On this hypothesis it ought to keep rigorously to historic accuracy, for it "would only attain its end by representii;g faithfully that which really took place. But tragedy has a. poetic end, that is to say, it represents an action to move us, and to charm our souls by the medium of this emotion. If, therefore, a matter being given, tragedy treats it conformably with ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 365 this poetic end, which is proper to it. it becomes, by that ver^- thing, free in its imitation. It is a right — naj-, more, it is an obligation — for tragedy to subject historic truth to the laws of poetry ; and to treat its matter in conformity with requirements of this art. But as it cannot attain its end, which is emotion, except on the condition of a perfect conformity with the laws of nature, tragedy is, notwithstanding its freedom in regard to history, strictly- subject to the laws of natural truth, which, in opposition to the truth of histor}-, takes the name of poetic truth. It may thus be understood how much poetic truth maj' lose, in many cases by a strict observance of historic truth, and, reciprocallj', how much it maj"^ gain by even a very serious alteration of truth according to historj-. As the tragic poet, like poets in general, is only subject to the laws of poetic truth, the most conscientious observance of historic truth could never dispense him from his duties as poet, and could never excuse in him any infraction of poetic truth or lack of interest. It is, therefore, betraying verj- narrow ideas on tragic art, or rather on poetry in general, to drag the tragic poet before the tribunal of history, and to require instruction of the man who by his ver}' title is onl}' bound to move and charm you. Even supposing the poet, bj^ a scrupulous submission to historic truth, had stripped himself of his privilege of artist, and that he had tacitlj' acknowledged in histwry a jurisdiction o^'er his work, art retains all her rights to summon him before its bar ; and pieces such as "The Death of Hermann," " Minona," " Fust of Stromberg," if they could not stand the test on this side, would only be tragedies of mediocre value, notwithstanding all the minuteness of costume — of na- tional costume — - and of the manners of the lime. Fifthly, tragedy is the imitation of an action that lets us see man suffering. The word tnan is essential to mark the limits of tragedy. Only the suffering of a being like ourselves can move out pit}'. Thus, evil genii, demons — - or even men like them, without morals — and again pure spirits, without our weaknesses, are unfit for tragedy. The very idea of suffering implies a man in the full sense of the term. A pure spirit cannot suffer, and a man 366 ESTHETIC AL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. approaching one will never awaken a high degree oi sj-mpathy. A purely sensuous being can indeed have terrible suffering ; but without moral sense it is a prey to it, and a suffering with reason inactive is a disgusting spectacle. The tragedian is right to prefer mixed charac- ters, and to place the ideal of his hero half way between utter perversity and entire perfection. Lastly, tragedy unites all these requisites to excite pity. Many means the tragic poet takes might serve another object ; but he frees himself from all requirements not relating to this end, and is thereby obliged to direct himself with a view to this supreme object. The final aim to which all the laws tend is called the end of any style of poetry. The means by which it attains this are its form. The end and form are, therefore, closely related. The form is determined by the end, and when the form is well observed the end is generally attained. Each kind of poetry having a special end must have a distinguishing form. What it exclusivel3' produces it does in virtue of this special nature it possesses. The end of tragedj' is emotion ; its form is the imitation of an action that leads to suffering. Many kinds may have the same object as tragedy, oi emotion, though it be not their principal end. Therefore, what distinguishes tragedj' is the relation of its form to its end, the way in which it attains its end by means of its subject. If the end of tragedj' is to awaken sympathy^, and its form is the means of attaining it, the imitation of an action fit to move must have all that favors syuipathy. Such is the form of tragedy. The production of a kind of poetry is perfect when the form peculiar to its kind has been used in the best waj'. Tlius, a perfect tragedy is that where the form is best used to awaken sympathj\ Thus, the best tragedy is that where the pity excited results more from the treatment of the poet than the theme. ■ Such is the ideal of a tragedj'. A good number of tragedies, though fine as poems, are bad as dramas, because thej' do not seek their end by the best use of tragic form. Others, because they use the form to attain an end different from traged}-. Some very popular ones only touch us on account of the subject, -ffiSTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 367 and we are blind enough to make this a merit in the poet. There are others in which we seem to have quite forgotten the object of the poet, and, contented withprettj- pla3s of fancy and wit, we issue with our hearts cold from the theatre. Must art, so holy and venerable, defend its cause by such champions before such judges ? The indulgence of the public only emboldens mediocrity : it causes genius to blush, and discourac^es it. OF THE CAUSE OF THE PLEASURE WE DERIVE FROM TRAGIC OBJECTS. Whatever pains some modern aesthetics give themselves to establish, contrary to general belief, that the arts of imagination and of feeling have not pleasui'e for their object, and to defend them against this degrading accu- sation, this belief will not cease : it reposes upon a solid foundation, and the fine arts would renounce with a bad grace the beneficent mission which has in all times been assigned to them, to accept the new employment to which it is generoTJslj'' proposed to raise them. Without troubling themselves whether they lower themselves in proposing our pleasure as object, they become rather proud of the advantages^ of reaching immediately as aim never attained except mediately in other routes followed by the activity of the human mind. That the aim of nature, with relation to man, is the happiness of man, — although he ought of himself, in his moral conduct, to take no notice of this aim, ■ — is what, I think, cannot be doubted in general by any one who admits that nature has an aim. Thus the fine arts have the same aim as nature, or rather as the Author of nature, namely, to spread pleasure and render people happy. It procures for us in play what at other more austere sources of good to man we extract onlj^ with difficulty. It lavishes as a pure gift that which elsewhere is the price of many hard efforts. With what labo'-, what application, do we not pay for the pleasures ot the understanding; with what 368 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. painful sacrifices tlie approbation of reason ; with what hard privations the jo}-s of sense ! And if we abuse these pleasures, with what a succession of evils do we expiate excess ! Art alone supplies an enjoj-ment which requires no appreciable effort, which costs no sacrifice, and which we need not repay with repentance. But who could class the merit of charming in this manner with the poor merit of amusing? who would venture to denj- the former of these two aims of the fine arts solely because they have a tendency higher than the latter. The praiseworthy object of pursuing everywhere moral good as the supreme aim, which has already brought forth in art so much mediocrity', has caused also in theory a similar prejudice. To assign to tlie fine arts a really ele- vated position, to conciliate for them the favor of the State, the veneration of all men, thej' are pushed be^'ond their true domain, and a vocation is imposed upon them contrary to their nature. It is supposed that a great ser- vice is awarded them by substituting for a frivolous aim — that of charming — a moral aim; and their influence upon morality, which is so apparent, necessarily mditates in favor of this pretension. It is found illogical that the art which contributes in so great a measure to the devel- opment of all that is most elevated in man, should pro- duce but aceessorily this effect, and make its chief object an aim so vulgar as we imagine pleasure to be. But this apparent contradiction it would be verj' easj' to conciliate if we had a good theorj^ of pleasure, and a complete sys- tem of ffisthetic philosoph}'. It would result from this theor}- that a free pleasure, as that which the fine arts procure for us, rests whoUj' upon moral conditions, and all the moral faculties of man are exercised in it. It would further result that this pleasure is an aim which can never be attained but by moral means, and consequently that art, to tend and perfectly attain to pleasure, as to a real aim, must follow the road of healtliy morals. Thus it is perfectly indifferent for the dignity of art whether its aim should be a moral aim, or whether it .should reach only through moral means ; for in both eases it has always to do with the morality, and must be rigor- ously in unison with the sentiment of duty ; but for the ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 369 perfection of art, it is by no means indiiferent which of the two should be the aim and which the means. If it is the aim that is moral, art loses all that by which it is pow- erful, — I mean its freedom, and that which gives it so much influence over us — the charm of pleasure. The plaj' which recreates is changed into serious occupation, and yet it is precisely in recreating us that art can the better complete the great affair — the moral work. It cannot have a salutary influence upon the morals but in exercising its highest aesthetic action, and it can only pro- duce the aesthetic eflfect in its highest degree in fully exer- cising its liberty. It is certain, besides, that all pleasure, the moment it flows from a moral source, renders man morally better, and then the effect in its turn becomes cause. The pleas- ure we find in what is beautiful, or touching, or sublime, strengthens our moral sentiments, as the pleasure we find m kindness, in love, etc., strengthens these inclinations. And just as contentment of mind is the sure lot of the morally excellent man, so moral excellence willingly ac- companies satisfaction of heart. Thus the moral efficacy of art is, not only because it employs moral means in order to charm us, but also because even the pleasure which it procures us is a means of moralitj'. There are as many means by which art can attain its aim as there are in general sources from which a free pleasure for the mind ca^ flow. I call a free pleasure that which brings into play the spiritual forces — reason and imagination — and which awakens in us a sentiment by the representation of an idea, in contradistinction to phy- sical or sensuous-pleasure, which places our soul under the dependence of the blind forces of nature, and where sensation is immediately awakened in us by a physical cause. Sensual pleasure is the only one excluded from the domain of the fine arts ; and the talent of exciting this kind of pleasure could never raise itself to the dig- nitj' of an art, except in the case where the sensual im- pressions are ordered, reinforced or moderated, after a plan which is the production of art, and which is recog- nized bj- representation. But, in this case even, that alone here can merit the name of art which is the object 370 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. of a free pleasure — I mean good taste in the regulation, which pleases our understanding, and not phjsical ehanas themselves, which alone flatter our sensibilit}'. The general source of all pleasure, even of sensual pleasure, is proprietj", the conformit}' with the aim. Pleasure is sensual when this propriet3' is manifested by means of some necessar}- law of nature which has for physical result the sensation of pleasure. Thus the move- ment of the blood, and of the animal life, when in coo- formity with the aim of nature, produces in certain organs, or in the entire organism, corporeal pleasure with all its varieties and all its modes. We feel this conformitj' by the means of agreeable sensation, but we arrive at no representation of it, either clear or confused. Pleasure is free when we represent to ourselves the con- formabilitj', and when the sensation that accompanies this representation is agreeable. Thus all the representations bj' which we have notice that there is propriety and har- mony between the end and the means, are for us the sources of free pleasure, and consequent^ can be em- ployed to this end by the fine arts. Thus, all the repre- sentations can be placed under one of these heads : the good, the true, the perfect, the beautiful, the touching, the sublime. The good especially occupies our reason ; the true and perfect, our intelligence ; the beautiful interests both the intelligence and the imagination ; the touching and the sublime, the reason and the imagination. It is true that we also take pleasure in the charm (Heiz) or the power called out by action from play, but art uses charm only to accompany the higher enjoyments which the idea of propriety gives to us. Considered in itself the charm or attraction is lost amid the sensations of life, and art disdains it together with all mereh' sensual pleasures. We could not establish a classification of the fine arts only upon the difference of the sources from which each of them draws the pleasure which it affords us ; for in the same class of the fine arts many sorts of pleasures may enter, and often all together. But in as far as a certain sort of pleasure is pursued as a principal aim, we can make of it, if not a specific character of a class properly 60 called, at least the principle and the tendency of a class ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 37] in the works of art. Thus, for example, we could take the arts which, above all, satisfy the intelligence and im- agination — consequently those which have as chief object the true, the perfect, and the beautiful — and unite them under the name of fine arts (arts of taste, arts of intelli- gence) ; those, on the other hand, which especially occupy the imagination and the reason, and which, in conse- quence, have for principal object the good, the sublime, and the touching, could be limited in a particular class under the denomination of touching arts (arts of senti- ment, arts of the heart). Without doubt it is impossible to separate absolutely the toucliing from the beautiful, but the beautiful can perfectly subsist without the touching. Thus, although we are not authorized to base upon this difference of principle a rigorous classification of the lib- eral arts, it can at least serve to determine with more of precision the criterion, and prevent the confusion in which we are inevitablj- involved, when, drawing up laws of aesthetic things, we confound two absolutely different domains, as that of the touching and that of the beautiful. The touching and the sublime resemble in this point, that both one and the other produce a pleasure b\- a feeling at first of displeasure, and that consequently' (pleasure proceeding from suitability, and displeasure from the contrary) they give us a feeling of suitabilitj' which pre- supposes an unsuitabilitpr. The feeling of the sublime is composed in part of the feeling of our feebleness, of our impotence to embrace an object ; and, on the other side, of the feeling of our moral power — of this superior facultj' which fears no ob- stacle, no limit, and which subdues spiritually that even to which our ph^'sical forces give way. The object of the sublime thvrarts, then, our phj-sical power ; and this contrariety (impropriety) must necessarily excite a dis- pleasure in us. But it is, at the same time, an occasion to recall to our conscience another faculty which is in us — a faculty which is even superior to the objects before which our imagination yields. In consequence, a sublime object, precisely because it thwarts the senses, is suitable with relation to reason, and it gives to us a joy by means of a 372 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. higher faculty, at the same time that it wounds us in an inferior one. The touching, in its proper sense, designates this mixed sensation, into which enters at the same time suffering and the pleasure that we find in suffering. Thus we can only feel this kind of emotion in the case of a persona! misfortune, onl^' when the grief that we feel is suffi- ciently tempered to leave some place for that impression of pleasure that would be felt by a compassionate spectator. The loss of a great good prostrates for the time, and the remembrance itself of the grief will make us experience emotion after a year. The feeble man is always the prey of his grief; the hero and the sage, whatever the misfortune that strikes them, never experience more than emotion. Emotion, like the sentiment of the sublime, is composed of two affections — grief and pleasure. There is. then, at the bottom a propriet}*, here as well as there, and under this proprietj' a contradiction. Thus it seems that it is a contradiction in nature that man, who is not born to suffer, is nevertheless a prey to suffering, and this contradiction hurts us. But the evil which this contradiction does us is a propriety with regard to our reasonable nature in general, insomuch as this evil solicits us to act : it is a propriety also with regard to human societj' ; consequentlj-, even displeasure, which excites in us this contradiction, ought necessarily to make us experience a sentiment of pleasure, because this displeasure is a proprietj-. To determine in an emotion if it is pleasure or diaj^leasure which triumphs, we must ask ourselves if it is the idea of impropriety or that of propriety which affects us the more deeply. That can depend either on the number of the aims reached or abortive, or on their connection with the final aim of all. The suffering of the virtuous man moves us more pain- fully than that of the i)erverse man, because in the first case there is contradiction not only to the general destinj' of man, which is happiness, but also to this other particular principle, viz., that virtue renders happy; whilst in the second case there is contradiction onlj' with regard to the end of man in general. Reciprocally-, the happiness of the wicked also offends uf much more than the misfortune of the good man, because we find in it a double contradic- ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 373 tion : in the first place vice itself, and, intlie second place, tlie recompense of vice. Thiere is also this other consideration, that virtue is much more able to recompense itself than vice, when it triumphs, is to punish itself; and it is preciselj' for this that the virtuous man in misfortune would much more remain faithful to the cultus of virtue than the perverse man would dream of converting himself in prosperitj-. But what is above all important in determining in the emotions the relation of pleasure and displeasure, is to compare the two ends — that which has been fulfilled and that which has been ignored — and to see which is the most considerable. There is no proprietj- which touches us so nearly as moral proprietj-, and no superior pleasure to that which we feel from it. Physical proprietj- could well be a problem, and a problem forever unsolvable. Moral propriety is already demonstrated. It alone is founded upon our reasonable nature and upon internal necessity. It is our. nearest interest, the most consider- able, and, at the same time, the most easilj- recognized, because it is not determined bj' anj' external element but by an internal principle of our reason : it is the palladium of our liberty. This moral propriety is never more vividly recognized than when it is found in conflict with another propriety, and still keeps the upper hand ; then only the moral law awakens in full power, ^hen we find it struggling against all the other forces of nature, and when all those forces lose in its presence their empire over a human soul. By these words, "the other forces of nature," we must understand all that is not moral force, all that is not subject to the supreme legislation of reason : that is to say, feelings, aflTections, instincts, passions, as well as physical necessity and destiny. The more redoubtable the adver- sary, the more glorious the victoiy ; resistance alone brings out the strength of the force and renders it visible. It follows that the highest degree of moral consciousness can only exist in strife, and the highest moral pleasure is always accompanied bj- pain. Consequently', the kind of poetry which secures us a high degree of moral pleasure, must emploj' mixed feelings, 374 ^STI-IF/nOAL LKTTERS AND ESSAYS. and please us through pain or distress, — this is what tragedy does specially ; and her realm embraces all that sacrifices a physical propriety to a moral one ; or one moral propriety to a higher one. It might be possible, perhaps, to form a measure of moral pleasure, from the lowest to the highest degree, and to determine by this principle of propriety the degree of pain or pleasure ex- perienced. Different orders of tragedy might be classified on the same principle, so as to form a complete exhaustive tabulation of them. Thus, a tragedy being given, its place could be fixed, and its genus determined. Of this subject more will be said separately in its proper place. A few examples will show how far moral propriety com- mands physical propriety ni our souls. Theron and Amanda are both tied to the stake as martyrs, and free to choose life or death by the terrible ordeal of fire — the3' select, the latter. What is it which gives such pleasure to us in this scene? Their position so conflicting with the smiling destiny they reject, the reward of misery given to virtue — all here awakens in us the feeling of impropriety : it ought to fill us with great distress. What is nature, and what are her ends and laws, if all this impropriety shows us moral propriety in its full light. We here see the triumph of the moral law, so sublime an experience for us that we might even hail the calamity which elicits it. For harmony in the world of moral freeilom gives us infinitely more pleasure than all the discords in nature give us pain. WheuCoriolanus, obedient to duty as husband, son, and citizen, raises the siege of Rome, them almost conquered, withdrawing his army, and silencing his vengeance, he commits a very contradictory act evidentlj'. He loses all tiie fruit of previous victories, he runs spontaneously to his ruin : yet what moral excellence and grandeur he offers ! How noble to prefer any impropriety rather than wound moral sense ; to violate natural interests and prudence in order to be in harmony with the higher moral law ! Every sacrifice of a life is a contradiction, for life is the condition of all good ; but in the light of morality the sacrifice of life is in a high degree proper, because life is not great m itself, but only as a means of accomplishing the moral ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. 375 law. If then the sacrifice of life be the way to do this, life must go. "It is not necessaiy for me to live, but it is necessary for Eome to be saved from famine," said Pompej', when the Romans embarked for Africa, and his friends begged him to defer his departure till the gale was over. But the sufferings of a criminal are as charming to us tragically as those of a virtuous man ; yet here is the idea of moral improprietj'. The antagonism of his conduct to moral law, and the moral imperfection which such conduct presupposes, ought to fill us with pain. Here there is no satisfaction in the morality of his person, nothing to com- pensate for his misconduct. Yet both supply a valuable object for art ; this phenomenon can easily be made to agree with what has been said. We find pleasure not only in obedience to morality, but m the punishment given to its infraction. The pain resulting from moral imperfection agrees with its opposite, the satisfaction at conformitj' with the law. Repentance, even despair, have nobleness morally, and can onl}' exist if an incorruptible sense of justice exists at the bottom of the criminal heart, and if conscience maintains its ground against self-love. Repentance comes bj- comparing our acts with the moral law, hence in the moment of repenting the moral law speaks loudly in man. Its power must be greater than the gain resulting from the crime as the infraction poisons the gnjo3'ment. Now, a state of mind where duty is sovereign is morallj' proper, and therefore a source of moral pleasure. What, then, sublimer than the heroic despair that tramples even life underfoot, because it cannot bear the judgment within ? A good man sacrificing his life to conform to the moral law, or a criminal taking his own life because of the morality he has violated : in both cases our respect for the moral law is raised to the highest power. If there be any advantage it is in the case of the latter ; for the good man may have been encouraged in his sacrifice by an approving conscience, thus detracting from his merit. Repentance and regret at past crimes show us some of the sublimest pictures of morality in active condition. A man who violates morality comes back to the moral law by repentance. 376 iESTHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. But moral pleasure is sometimes obtained only at the cost of moral pain. Thus one dutj- may clash with another. Let us suppose Coriolanus encamped with a Koman armj- before Antium or Corioli, and his mother a Volscian ; if her prayers move him to desist, we now no longer admire him. His obedience to his mother would be at strife with a higher duty, that of a citizen. The governor to whom the alternative is proposed , either of giving up the town or of seeing his son stabbed, decides at once on the latter, his duty as father being beneath that of citizen. At first our heart revolts at this conduct in a father, but we soon pass to admiration that moral instinct, even combined with inclination, could not lead reason astraj- in the empire where it commands. When Timoleon of Corinth puts to death his beloved but ambitious brother, Timophanes, he does it because his idea of duty to his country bids him to do so. The act here inspires horror and repulsion as against nature and the moral sense, but this feeling is soon succeeded by the highest admiration for his heroic virtue, pronouncing, in a tumultuous conflict of emotions, freely and calmly, with perfect rectitude. If we differ with Timoleon about his duty as a republican, this does not change our view. Nay, in those cases, where our understanding judges differently, we see all the more clearly how high we put moral proprietj' above all other. But the judgments of men on this moral phenomenon are exceedingly various, and the reason of it is clear. Moral sense is common to all men, but differs in strength. To most men it suffices that an act be partially conformable with the moral law to make them obey it ; and to make them condemn an action it must glaringlj' violate the law. But to determine the relation of moral duties with the highest principle of morals requires an enlightened in- telligence and an emancipated reason. Thus an action which to a few will be a supreme propriety, will seem to the crowd a revolting improprietj-, though both judge morallj' ; an hence the emotion felt at such actions is by no means uniform. To the mass the sublimest and highest is only exaggeration, because sublimity is perceived by reason, and all men have not the same share of it. A vulgar soul is oppressed or overstretched by those sublimo ^STHKTICAli LETTERS AND E.S.SAVS. 377 ideas, and the crowd sees dreadful disorder where a thinking mind sees the highest order. This is enough about moral proprietj' as a principle of tragic emotion, and the pleasure it elicits. It must be added that there are cases where natural propriety also seems to charm our mind even at the cost of moralitj'. Thus we are alwa3-s pleased by the sequence of machina- tions of a perverse man, though his means and end are immoral. Such a man deeply interests us, and we tremble lest his plan fail, though we ought to wish it to do so. But this fact does not contradict what has been advanced about moral propriety, and the pleasure resulting from it. Propriety, the reference of means to an end, is to us, in all cases, a source of pleasure ; even disconnected with morality. We experience this pleasure unmixed, so long as we do not think of any moral end which disallows action before us. Animal instincts give us pleasure — as the industry of bees — without reference to morals ; and in like manner human actions are a pleasure to us when we consider in them onlj'' the relation of means to ends. But if a moral principle be added to these, and impropriety be discovered, if the idea of moral agent comes in, a deep indignation succeeds our pleasure, which no intellectual propriety can remedy. We mujt not call to mind too vividlj"^ that Richard III., lago, and Lovelace are men / otherwise our sympatly' for them infallibly turns into an opposite feeling. But^^as daily experience teaches, we have the power to direct our attention to different sides of things ; and pleasure, only possible through this abstrac- tion, invites us to exercise it, and to prolong its exercise. Yet it is not rare for intelligent perversity to secure our favor by being the means of procuring us the pleasure of moral propriety. The triumph of moral propriety will be great in proportion as the snares set by Lovelace for the virtue of Clarissa are formidable, and as the trials of an innocent victim by a cruel tyrant are severe. It is a pleasure to see the craft of a seducer foiled b}- the omni- potence of the moral sense. On the other hand, we reckon as a sort of merit the victory of a malefactor over his moral sense, because it is the proof of a certain strength of mistd and intellectual propriety. 378 ^STHETICAL LETTERS AND ESSAYS. Yet this propriety in vice can never be tiie source of a perfect pleasure, except when it is humiliated bj' morality. In that case it is an essential part of our pleasure, because it brings moral sense into stronger relief. The last impression left on us bj' the author of Clarissa is a proof of this. The intellectual propriety in the plan of Lovelace is greatly surpassed bj- the rational propriety of Clarissa. This allows us to feel in full the satisfaction caused by both. "When the tragic poet has for object to awaken in us the feeling of moral propriety, and chooses his means skilfully for that end, he is sure to charm doubly the connoisseur, by moral and by natural propriety. The first satisfies the heart, the second the mind. The crowd is impressed through the heart without knowing the cause of the magic impression. But, on the other hand, there is a class of connoisseurs on whom that which affects the heart is entirely lost, and who can only be gained by the appro- priateness of the means ; a strange contradiction resulting from over-refined taste, especially when moral culture remains behind intellectual. This class of connoisseurs seek only the intellectual side in touching and sublime themes. The}' appreciate this in the justest manner, but you must beware how j'ou appeal to their heart ! The over-culture of the age leads to this shoal, and nothing becomes the cultivated man so much as to escape b}- a happy victory this twofold and pernicious influence. Of all other European nations, our neighbors, the French, lean most to this extreme, and we, as in all things, strain every nerve to imitate this model. SCHILLEll^: iHILOSOPHICAL LETTERS. PREFATORY REMARKS. The reason passes, like the heart, through certain epochs and transitions, but its development is not so often por- traj'ed. Men seem to have been satisfied with unfolding the passions in their extremes, their aberration, and their results, without considering how closelj' they are bound up with the intelleetual constitution of the individual. Degeneracy in morals roots in a one-sided and wavering philosophy, doul)ly dangerous, because it blinds the be- clouded intellect with an appearance of correctness, truth, and conviction, which places it less under the restraining influence of man's instinctive moral sense. On the other hand, an enlightened understanding ennobles the feelings, — the heart must be formed by the head. The present age has witnessed an extraordinary increase of a thinking public, by the facilities afforded to the dif- fusion of reading ; the former happy resignation to ignor- ance begins to make waj^ for a state of half-enlightenment, and few persons are willing to remain in the condition in which their birth has placed them. Under these circum- stan(;es it may not be unprofitable to call attention to cer- tain periods of the awakening and progress of the reason, to place in their proper light certain truths and errors, closely connected with morals, and calculated to be a source of happiness or misery, and, at all events, to point out the hidden shoals on which the reason of man has so often suffered shipwreck. Earely do we arrive at the summit of truth without running into extremes ; we have frequently to exhaust the part of error, and even of folly, before we work our waj^ up to the noble goal of tranquil wisdom. Some friends, inspired by an equal love of truth and 379 380 Schiller's philosophical letters. moral beantj', who have arrived at tlie same conviction by different roads, and who view with serener eye the ground over which thej- have travelled, have thought that it might be profitable to present a few of these resolutions and epochs of thought. They propose to represent these and certain excesses of the inquiring reason in the form of two 3'Oinig men, of unequal character, engaged in epistolary correspondence. The following letters are the beginning of this essaj-. The opinions that are offered in these letters can only be true and false relativelj^ and in the form in which the world is mirrored in the soul of the correspondent, and of him only. But the course of the correspondence will show that the one-sided, often exaggerated and contradic- tory opinions at length issue in a general, purified, and well-established truth. Scepticism and free-thinking are the feverish paroxj'sms of the human mind, and must needs at length confirm the health of well-organized souls by the unnatural convul- sion which they occasion. In proportion to the dazzling and seducing nature of eri-or will be the greatness of the triumphs of truth : the demand for conviction and firm belief will be strong and pressing in proportion to the torment occasioned by the pangs of doubt. But doubt was necessary to elicit these errors ; the knowledge of the disease had to precede its cure. Truth suffers no loss if a vehement youth fails in finding it, in the same way that virtue and religion suffer no detriment if a criminal denies them. It was necessary to offer these prefatory remarks to throw a proper light on the point of view from which the following correspondence has to be read and judged. Letter 1. Julius to Raphael. October. You are gone, Raphael, — and the beauty of nature de- parts : the sere and yellow leaves fall from the trees, while a thick autumn fog hangs suspended like a bier over the Schiller's philosophical letters. 381 lifeless fields. Solitary-, I wander through the melancholy- country. I call aloud jour name, and am irritated that ray Raphael does not answer me. I had received your last embrace. The mournful sound of the carriage wheels that bore you away had at length died upon my ear. In happier moments I had just suc- ceeded in raising a tumulus over the joys of the past, but now again j'ou stand up before me, as j'our departed spirit, in these regions, and yon accompanj' me to each favorite haunt and pleasant walk. These rocks I have climbed by your side : bj- your side have my ej'es wan- dered over this immense landscape. In the dark sanctuarj' of this beeeh-gro\e we first conceived the bold ideal of our friendship. It was here that we unfolded the genealogical tree of the soul, and that we found that Julius was so closel3' related to Raphael. Not a spring, not a thicket, or a hill exists in this region where some memory of de- parted happiness does not come to destro}- my repose. All things combine to prevent my recovery. Wherever I go, I repeat the painful scene of our separation. What have j'ou done to me, Rapliael ? What am I be- come ? Man of dangerous power ! would that I had never known or never lost you ! Hasten back ; come on the wings of friendship, or the tender plant, 50ur nursling, shall have perished. How could you, endowed with such tender feelings, venture to leave the work you had begun, but still so incomplete* The foundations that your proud wisdom tried to establish in my brain and heart are totter- ing ; all the splendid palaces which 30U erected are crum- bling, and the worm crushed to earth is writhing under the ruins. Happy, heavenly time, when I groped through life, with bandaged eyes, like a drunken man, — when all my knowl- edge and my wishes were confined to the narrow horizon of my childhood's teachings ! Blessed time, when a cheer- ful sunset raised no higher aspiration in my soul than the wish of a fine day on the morrow ; when nothing reminded me of the world save the newspaper ; nothing spoke of eternit)' save the passing bell ; onh* ghost-stories brought to mind the thought of death and judgment ; when I trembled at the thought of the devil, and was proportion- 382 Schiller's philosophical letters. ately drawn to the Godhead! I felt and was happy. Raphael has taught me to think I am on the way to regret that I was ever created. Creation ? No, that is only a sound lacking all mean- ing, which my reason cannot receive. There was a time when I knew nothing, when no one knew me : accordingl}', it is usual to sa3', I was not. That time is past : there- fore it is usual to say that I was created. But also of the millions who existed centuries ago nothing more is now known, and yet men are wont to say, they are. On what do we found the right to grant the beginning and to deny the end? It is assumed that the cessation of thinking beings contradicts Infinite Goodness. Did, then, Infinite Goodness come first into being at the creation of the world? If there was a period when there were no spirits. Infinite Goodness must have been imperative for a whole eternity. If the fabric of tlie universe is a perfection of the Creator, He, therefore, lacked a perfection before the creation of the world. But an assumption like this con- tradicts the idea of perfect goodness, therefore there is no creation. To what have I arrived, Eaphael? Terrible fallacj' of my conclusions ! I give up the Creator as soon as I believe in a God. Wherefore do I require a God, if I suffice without the Creator? You have robbed me of the thought that gave me peace. You have taught me to despise where I praj-ed before. A tlioiisand things were venerable in my sight till 30ur dis- mal wisdom stripped off the veil from them. I saw a crowd of people streaming to church, I heard their enthu- siastic devotion poured forth in a common act of prayer and praise ; twice did I stand beside a deathbed, and saw — wonderful power of religion ! — the hope of heaven triumphant over the terror of annihilation, and the serene light of joy beaming from the ej-es of those departing. "Surely that doctrine must be divine," I exclaimed, " which is acknowledged bj' the best among men, which triumphs and comforts so wondrously ! " Your cold- blooded wisdom extinguished my enthusiasm. You affirmed that an equal number of devotees streamed for- merly round the IrmensUule and to Jupiter's temple ; an equal number of votaries, with like exultation, ascended Schiller's philosophical letters. 38S the stake kindled in honor of Brahma. "Can the very feeling," you added, "which you found so detestable in heathenism prove the truth of your doctrine ? " You proceeded to say: " Trust nothing bat j'our own reason. There is nothing holy, save truth." I have obeyed you : I have sacrificed all my opinions, 1 have set Are to all my ships when I landed on this island, and I have destroyed all my hopes of return. Never can 1 become reconciled to a doctrine which I joyfully' wel- comed once. My reason is now all to me — my only warrant for God, virtue, and immortality. Woe to me if I catch this, my only witness, in a contradiction ! if my esteem for its conclusions diminishes ! if a broken vessel in my brain diverts its action ! My happiness is henceforth intrusted to the harmonious action of my sensorium : woe to me if the strings of this instrument give a false note in the critical moments of my life — if my convictions vary with my pulsations ! Letter II. Julius to Raphael. Your doctrine has flattered my pride. I was a prisoner : you have led me out into the daylight ; the golden shimmer and the measureless vault have enraptured my eye. Formerl^^ I was#atisfied with the modest reputation of being a good son of my father's house, a friend of my friends, a useful member of societj'. You have changed me into a citizen of the universe. At that time my wishes had not aspired to infringe on the rights of the great : I tolerated these fortunate people because beggars tolerated me. I did not blush to envj- a part of the human race, because there was a still larger part of humanity that I was obliged to pity. Meeting j'ou, I learned for the first time that mj' claims on enjoj'ment were as well founded as those of my brethren. Now, for the first time, I learned that, raised one stratum above this atmosphere, I weighed just as much and as little as the rulers of this world. Raphael severed all bonds of agreement and of opinion. I felt myself quite free ; for reason, as Raphael declared. 384 Schiller's philosophical letters. is the only monarchy in the world of spirits, and I carried mj' imperial throne in my brain. All things in heaven and earth have no value, no estimation, except that which my reason grants them. The whole creation is mine, for I possess an irresistible omnipotence, and am empowered to enjoy it fully. All spirits — one degree below the most perfect Spirit — are my brethren, because we all obey one rule, and do homage to one supremacy. How magnificent and sublime this announcement sounds ! What a field for my thirst of iinowledge ! But — unlucky contradiction of nature — this free and soaring spirit is woven together with the rigid, immovable clockwork of a mortal body, mixed up with its little necessities, and yoked to its fate — this god is banished into a world of worms. The immense space of nature is opened to his research, but he cannot think two ideas at the same time. With his eyes he reaches up to the sunnj' focus of the Godhead, but he himself is obliged to creep after Him slowly and wearily through the elements of time. To absorb one enjoyment he must give up all others : two unlimited desires are too great for his little heart. Ever^"^ fresh joj' costs him the sum of all previous joys. The present moment is the sepulchre of all that went before it. An idyllic hour of love is an intermittent pulsation of friendship. Wherever I look, Raphael, how limited man appears ! How great the distance between his aims and their fulfil- ment ! — yet do not begrudge him his soothing slumber. Wake him not ! He was so happj' before he began to inquire whither he was to go and whence he came ! Reason is a torch in a prison. The prisoner knew nothing of the light, but a dream of freedom appeared over him like a flash in the night which leaves the darkness deeper than before. Our philosophy is the unhappy curiosity of CEdipus, who did not cease to inquire till the dreadful oracle was unravelled. Mayest thou never learn who thou art! Does your wisdom replace what it has set aside ? If ji^ou had no ke}^ to open heaven, why did you lead me away from earth ? If you knew beforehand that the way to wisdom leads through the frightful abj'ss of doubt, why Schiller's philosophical letters. 385 did you venture the innocence of j-our friend Julius on this desperate throw ? — If to the good, which I propose to do, Something very bad borders far too near, I prefer not to do this good. You have pulled down a shelter that was inhabited, and founded a splendid but lifeless palace on the spot. Raphael, I claim my soul from you ! I am unhappy. My courage is gone. I despair of my own strength. Write to me soon! — your healing hand alone can pour balm on my burning wounds. Letter III. Raphael to Julius. Julius, happiness such as ours, if unbroken, would be too much for human lot. This thought often haunted me even in the full enjoyment of our friendship. This thought, then darkening our happiness, was a salutary foretaste, intended to mitigate the pain of mj- present position. Hardened in the stern school of resignation, I am still more susceptible of the comfort of seeing in our separation a slight sacrifice whose merit ma}- win from fate the reward of our future reunion. You did not yet know what privation was. You suffer for the first time. And yet it is perhaps ^n advantage for you that I have been torn from you exactly at this tim.e. You have to endure a malady, from which you can only perfectly recover by your own energy, so as not to suffer a relapse. Tlie more deserted you feel, the more jou will stir up all healing power in yourself, and in proportion as jou deri\'e little or no benefit from temporary and deceptive pallia- tives, the more certainly will you succeed in eradicating the evil fundamentally. I do not repent that I roused j'ou from your dream, though your present position is painful. I have done nothing more than hasten a crisis, which every soul like yours has sooner or later to pass through, and where the essential thing is, at what time of life it is endured. 38 G Schiller's philosophical letters. There are times and seasons when it is terrible to doubt truth and virtue. Woe to the man who has to flglit through the quibbles of a self-sufficient reason while he is immersed in the storms of the passions. I have felt in its fulness all that is expressed by this, and, to preserve you from similar troubles I could devise no means but to ward off the pestilence by timelj' inoculation. Nor could I, mj' dear Julius, choose a more propitious time? I met you in the full and glorious bloom of youthful intelligence and bodily vigor, before you had been oppressed by care or enchained by passion ; full}' prepared, in j-our freedom and strength, to stand the greait fight, of whicli a sublime tranquillity, proHuced b}- convic- tion, is the prize. Truth and error had not j-et been interwoven with your interests. Your enjoyments and virtues were independent of both. You required no images of terror to tear j-ou from low dissipation. The feeling for nobler joys had made these odious to 30U. You were good from instinct and from unconsecrated moral grace. I had nothiiig to fear for j'our moralitj', if a building crumbled down on which it was not founded. Nor do your anxieties alarm me, though you ma}' conjure up manj- dark anticipations in your melancholy mood. I know you better, Julius I You are ungrateful, too ! You despise the reason, and forget what joys it has procured ^'ou. Though you might have escaped the dangers of doubt all j'our life, still it was my duty not to deprive you of the pleasures which you were capable of enjoj'ing. The height at which 3-ou were was not worthy of jou. The way up which you climbed gave you compensation for all of which I deprived you. I still recall the deliglit — with what delight j-ou blessed the moment when the bandage dropped from j'our eyes ! The warmth with which j-ou grasped the truth possibly may have led your all-devouring imagination to an abj'ss at sight of which you draw back shuddering. I must follow the course of j'our inquiries to discover the sources of your complaints. You have written down the results of 3-our thoughts : send me these papers and then I will answer you. Schiller's philosophical letters. 387 Letter IV. Julius to Raphael. I HAVE been looking over vsrj papers this morning. Among them I have found a lost memorandum written down in those happj' hours when I was inspired with a proud enthusiasm. But on looking over it how different seem all the things treated of ! My former views look like the gloomy boarding of a plajhouse vvlien the lights have been removed. My heart sought a philosophy, and ima- gination substituted her dreams. I took the warmest for the truest coloring. I seek for the laws of spirits — I soar up to the inQnite, but I forget to pro^'C that they really exist. A bold attack of materialism overthrows my creation. You will read through this fragment, my dear Raphael. Would that you could succeed in kindling once again the extinct flames of my enthusiasm, to reconcile me again to my genius ! but my pride has sunk so low that even Raphael's friendly hand can hardly raise me up again. THEOSOPHY OF JULIUS. The 'VYorld 4ND the Thinking Being. The universe is a thought of God. After this ideal thought-fabric passed out into reality, and the new-born world fulfilled the plan of its Creator — permit me to use this human simile — the first duty of all thinking beings has been to retrace the orighial design in this great reality ; to find the principle in the mechanism, tlie unity in the compound, the law in the phenomenon, and to pass back from tlie structure to its primitive foundation. Accordinglj- to me there is only one appearance in nature — the thinking being. The great compound called the world is only remarkable to me because it is present to shadow forth symbolically the manifold expressions of that being. All in me and out of me is only the hieroglj'ph of 388 Schiller's philosophtcal letters. a power which is like to me. The laws of nature are the cyphers which the thinking mind adds on to make itself understandable to intelligence — the alphabet by means of which all spirits communicate with the most perfect Spirit and with one another. Harmon}-, truth, order, beauty, excellence, give me joj-, because they transport me into the active state of their author, of their possessor, because- the}' betra}' the presence of a rational and feeling Being, and let me perceive my relationship with that Being. A new experience in this kingdom of truth : gravitation, the circulation of the blood, the natural s^'stem of Linnaeus, correspond essentially in my mind to the discovery of an antique dug up at Herculaneum — they are both only the leflections of one spirit, a renewed acquaintance with a being like myself. I speak with the Eternal through the instrument of nature, — through the world's historj- : I read the soul of the artist in his Apollo. If you wish to be convinced, mv dear Raphael, look back. Each state of the human mind has sorne parable in the phj'sical creation bj- which it is shadowed forth; nor is it only artists and poets, but even the most abstract thinkers that have drawn from this source. Lively activity we name fire ; time is a stream that rolls on, sweeping all before it ; eternitj' is a circle ; a myster\- is hid in midnight gloom, and truth dwells in the sun. Naj-, I begin to believe that even the future destiny of the human race is prefigured in the dark oracular utterances of bodily creation. Each coming spring, forcing the sprouts of plants out of the earth, gives me explanations of the awful riddle of death, and contradicts m}- anxious fears about an ever- lasting sleep. The swallow that we find stiffened in winter, and see waking up to life after ; the dead grub coming to life again as the I)utterfly and rising into the air, — all these give excellent pictures of our immortality. How strange all seems to me now, Eaphael ! Now all seems peopled round about me. To me there is no solitude in nature. Wherever I see a body I anticipate a spirit. Wherever I trace movement I infer thought. Where no dead lie buried, where no resurrection will be. Omnipotence speaks to me this through His works, and thus I understand the doctrine of the omnipresence of God. schillee's philosophical letters 389 Idea. All spirit^ are attracted by perfection. There may be deviations, but there is no exception to this, for all strive after the condition of tlie highest and freest exercise of their powers ; all possess the common instinct of extending ^ their sphere of action ; of drawing all, and centring all in themselves ; of appropriating all that is good, all that is acknowledged as charming and excellent. When the beautiful, the true, and the excellent are once seen, they are immediately grasped at. A condition once perceived by us, we enter into it immediately. At the moment when we think of them, we become possessors of a virtue, authors of an action, discoverers of a truth, possessors of a happiness. We ourselves become the object perceived. Let.no ambiguous smile from you, dear Raphael, discon- cert me here, — this assumption is the basis on which I found all that follovrs, and we must be agreed before I take courage to complete the structure. His inner feeling or innate consciousness tells every man almost the same thing. For example, when we admire an act of magnanimitj', of bravery and wisdom, does not a secret feeling spring up in our heart that we are capable of doing tlie same ? Does not the rush of blood coloring our cheeks on hearing narratives of this kind proclaim that our modesty tremfeles at the admiration called forth by such acts ? that we are confused at the praise which this ennobling of our nature must call down upon us? Even our body at such moments agrees with the attitude of the man, and shows clearlj' that our soul has passed into tlie state we admire. If j'ou were ever present, Raphael, when a great event was related to a large assembly, did 3'ou not see how the relater waited for the incense of praise, how he devoured it, though it was given to the hero of his storj', — and if j^ou were ever a relater did 3'ou not trace how 3"our heart was subject to this pleasing deception? You have had examples, my dear Raphae.\ of how easily I can wrangle with my best friend respecting the reading aloud of a pleasing anecdote or of a beautiful poem, and my heart told me truly on these occasions that I was only 390 Schiller's PHrLosoriiirAL Mrrn-.i;>>. (lispliwscil III voiir I'jirniiii;- oil' llio Isimvls ln'i'Miiso tliosp IKisscil rroui (ho lii-ail «{' aiiUior to that of the reader. A quick anil dcoi) artistie apiHvi'iatioii of virtue is justly held to lie a ^ real aptiliule lor virtue, iu the saiiu' way as it. is usual to have no seruplo in distrustiuu' the iieart. of a man whose intelliiience is slow to take iu moral beauty. You need n