=5= DEPARTMENT OF ESIA LIBRARY OF o mm 'sMfci < ^nduiiiiai e ^nivw6ity, CHAMPAIQN, ILLINOIS. Books are Not to be Taken From the Library Room. The person charging this material is re- sponsible for its return on or before the Latest Date stamped below. Theft, mutilation, and underlining of books are reasons for disciplinary action and may result in dismissal from the University. University of Illinois Librai§lAS$lv APR 4 m BtC - 9 12 ^ NOV 4 9 wo SEC 4 1980 L161— 0-1096 t Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2016 with funding from University of Illinois Urbana-Champaign Alternates ■) t https://archive.org/details/platoagainstathe00plat_0 PLATO CONTRA ATHEOS. PLATO AGAINST THE ATHEISTS; OR, THE TENTH HOOK OP THE DIALOGUE ON LAWS, ACCOMPANIED WITH CRITICAL NOTES, AND FOLLOWED BY EXTENDED DISSERTATIONS ON SOME OF THE MAIN POINTS OF THE PLATONIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE- OLOGY, ESPECIALLY AS COMPARED WITH THE HOLY SCRIPTURES. BY TAYLER LEWIS, LL.D., PROFESSOR OF THE GREEK LANGUAGE AND LITERATURE IN THE UNIVERSITY IN THE CITY OF NEW-YORK. rnrv-'n As the Lord livetli, and as thy soul liveth. Hebrew Oath. NEW YORK: HARPER & BROTHERS, PUBLISHERS, FRANKLIN SQUARE. 1870 . Entered, according to Act of Congress, in the year 1845, by Harper & Brothers, afi the Clerk’s Office of the Southern District of New-Yor&. TO l lfB UEV. ELIPHALET NOTT, D.D„ THE VENERABLE -VTVci \ PRESIDENT OF UNION COLLEGE * *' . f,»£RED alma mater, THIS WORK s most respectfully XnscrtfieT), IN REMEMBRANCE OF THOSE LESSONS, BOTH OF THEORET ICAL AND PRACTICAL WISDOM, WHICH HAVE AIDED IN FORMING THE MINDS AND CHARACTERS OF SO LARGE ^A PORTION OF THE EDUCATED MEN OF OUR LA^ t* o'ri^x rx isSs ^33 nox • v: I •* • : t t - r Psalm x iv., 1. 'lirr 0 X 3 xbo ’ 3 x ynxrrnxi o’nssrrnx xVi Jeremiah , xxiii., 24 *Ei> avrCp yap £ ti/uev, Kal KivovpeOa, nai kofiev. Acts , xvii., 28. HiGTEVGac yap del rov TrpoGepxopevov rfi Qe

S JJ2TI, Kal Tolg EK£nraii?Lv avTov pcGdanodoTTjg ytv* rat. • Hebrews , XI., 6 K\ INTRODUCTION. It is generally agreed among those who hold The Laws of Plato to be a genuine production, that it was a treatise written in his old age. If so, it may be re- garded as containing his most matured and best-set- tled opinions on many of the great subjects discussed in his other dialogues. Some have thought that they discovered many contradictions between this work and the Republic. One has even gone so far as to say that they are opposed in every page. In this opinion, how- ever, we cannot concur ; although it must be admitted that they differ in respect to style, and, notwithstand- ing the near relationship which would seem to be in- dicated by their titles, are very dissimilar in design. In the one, the State is the main subject of discussion ; in the other it is a secondary part, subordinate to what the writer evidently regards as a higher and more philosophical investigation into the nature of right or righteousness. The practice of contrasting these two works has arisen from a wrong view of the true title of the one generally styled the Republic. Its most appropriate designation is nep£ A maiov, or, An Inquiry into the Nature of Right . The imaginary State is ev- idently made subservient to this, or, as he expressly tells us in the second book, intended only as a model of the human soul, so magnified that we might read therein, in large letters, what would not be distinct enough for the mental vision when examined in the smaller characters of the individual spirit. Vide lib. ii., 369, A. This comparison of the soul to a com- monwealth has been a favourite, not only with Plato, A 2 VI INTRODUCTION. but with the most philosophical minds in all ages. We find it on a much smaller scale in the eleventh book of •The Laws, where the Nightly Conference, or the most solemn legislative and judicial body in the state, is com- pared to the head in thQ human system. In the Re- public it is the great idea, to which the construction of the fancied State is altogether secondary. Sometimes, however, it must be admitted, the author seems so taken up with this imaginary commonwealth, that he unconsciously, perhaps, brings it into the primary place, and thus distorts his plan. It is this occasional forgetfulness of his main design that has introduced into Plato’s Republic those incongruities which, in all ages, have been so much complained of. Sometimes the con- sistency of the under or fictitious part is overlooked, or, in other words, the State is utterly forgotten, while we are carried away to some of the most abstruse of all metaphysical discussions, such as may be found in the sixth and seventh books. Again, his attention seems to be so occupied with the outward drapery that he loses sight of his main theme, and, pleased with the efforts of his own fancy, dwells at great length on what, in reality, is merely externa] to the higher and inner sense. In the third, fourth, and last three books, the harmony of primary and secondary is well pre- served. In the sixth and seventh he seems to lose sight of the commonwealth almost wholly, while in some parts of the second he appears to have nothing else before him. The fifth may be regarded as a sort of hybrid production, arising from a confusion of both views. Some of its arrangements are altogether too unnatural to allow the supposition that they were ever intended for a real State ; and yet it is very diffi- cult to discover what bearing they can have upon the INTRODUCTION. Vli higher philosophy to which the whole scheme was in- tended to be subservient. The least we can say is, that Plato here lost himself, and produced something which was neither allegory nor reality, neither philos- ophy nor legislation. It is on the subject of the domestic relations, which are supposed to be assailed in this fifth book, that there exists the greatest contrariety between the Republic and The Laws. Plato seems, even in his own day, to have been so reproached with this apparent blot in his philosophy, that he was led to take special pains to do it away in this work of his old age ; and hence the great desire he shows in The Laws to set in their high- est light the sanctity of the family, or parental and fil- ial relations. We have adverted to this at some length in the first of the dissertations appended to the text. In other respects, the discrepancies between the Republic and The Laws have been greatly exaggera- ted. Differing, however, as they may in some of their minor details, no one can attentively study both with- out discovering evidences that they are productions of the same mind, and that, in the main elements of that higher philosophy on which all legislation and morals depend, they are substantially the same. The Treatise on Laws is undoubtedly intended for a really practicable , if not a really existing State. In discussing, however, the primary principles of legisla- tion, the author takes a very wide range, occupying far more time in what he styles the preambles, or rec- ommendatory reasonings about the laws, than in the laws themselves. Hence there are but few points in the Platonic philosophy and ethics, as exhibited in the other dialogues, but what have some representative here. We find the same questions started respecting via INTRODUCTION. the nature and origin of virtue — whether it is didafcrrj , or capable of being taught as a science or not ; wheth- er it is one or many — that is, whether the virtues are ah so essentially connected that one cannot exist without the others. We find the same views in regard to the end and origin of law — the importance in all things oi looking to the idea, the ev ev 7 rohXoig, or one in many. There is the same reverence for antiquity and ancient myths, the same disposition to regard religion as the beginning and foundation of every system of civil pol- ity, and the same method of representing the ideas of a God, of his goodness, his providence, of a present and future retribution, as lying at the foundation of all morals and all religion. Even in the departments of psychology and ontology we find many things in The Laws which remind us of the author of the Phaedon, the Parmenides, and the These tetus. The favourite doctrines and methods of reasoning contained in the Gorgias are exhibited everywhere ; and perhaps there is no other part of Plato’s works more in the style and spirit of the Timseus than this very tenth book of The Laws, which we have selected as the ground of our comments in the present work. It was on this account chosen as forming, in our judgment, one of the best central positions from whence to make excursions over a large part of the Platonic philosophy. We may perhaps be charged with hav- ing sometimes used the text as a mere thread on which to hang our own discussions ; but even should it be admitted that there is some truth in this, still might it be maintained that those discussions are all closely connected with the Platonic philosophy and theology, and that from this field we never depart, unless, per- haps, to dwell on kindred subjects suggested by the INTRODUCTION. IX Holy Scriptures. Our object has not been merely to make a classical text-book, but to recommend Plato to the student or reader by every means through which attention could be drawn to our favourite author ; be- lieving that in no other way could we render a better service to the cause of true philosophy and religion. Some may say that, in our great partiality, Plato is made to talk too much like a Christian. It may be that we have found senses higher and more Scriptural than are contained in the letter of the passages to which reference is made ; yet even if this is, to some extent, the case, it only shows the suggestive nature of his philosophy ; how it is capable of carrying the earnest reader to more spiritual views than the author himself, perhaps, ever entertained, and how he differs, in this respect, from all other profane writers of an- cient or modern times. We think it will be found that the views in which we have indulged are thus naturally suggested ; that they are not hunted for, or brought from afar, but are such as, if not always con- tained in the precise letter of our text, do most easily present themselves in connexion with it, especially to one who reads Plato by the light of the Christian Rev- elation. On this subject, of what may be called the Platonic Spiritual Sense , or capability of accommoda- tion to higher views, the reader is referred to Disserta- tion LX., where it is treated of at some length. In pursuance of this favourite plan of recommending Plato and the Platonic philosophy, the method follow- ed in the present work was adopted. The text and critical notes form by much the smallest part, and even these accompanying annotations frequently ex- hibit as much of a philosophical and theological as of a critical character. The longer dissertations an INTRODUCTION. nexed, and which, for the reader’s convenience, we have divided into numbered sections, with general and running titles, are devoted almost entirely to the eluci- dation of some of the main points of the Platonic phi- losophy, in their connexion with other systems of an- tiquity, to a comparison, whenever there was occasion for it, with the sentiments of Aristotle, illustrations drawn from the Grecian poets, together with a con- tinual reference to the Holy Scriptures, by way of resemblance, contrast, agreement, or condemnation. For these purposes, there have been introduced, from almost all the other Platonic dialogues, very frequent and extended quotations of the most striking passages ; h ing such as, besides having a natural connexion with the subject discussed, would promote our main design, by producing in the reader a desire to have a deeper knowledge of Plato than is generally possessed by the greater part of our philosophical and theological wri- ters. To these quotations, in almost every case, full translations have been given, sometimes literal, and sometimes paraphrastic. The exceptions to this course are, when the nature and substance of the quotation were sufficiently indicated by the manner of its intro- duction. The main references are to the Timaeus, the Republic, the Phaedon, Gorgias, Theaetetus, Par- menides, Philebus, Protagoras, Symposion, Politicus, Cratylus, Sophista, and the other books of The Laws, with occasional citations from most of the minor dia- logues having any claims to be regarded as genuine. The work has been the result of a careful examin- ation of the Platonic writings ; in which we have sought to interpret Plato mainly by himself, and by the aid, on the one hand, of his jealous rival, Aris- totle, and on the other, of his enthusiastic admirer INTRODUCTION. XI Cicero. Of modern critical and philosophical helps, whether English or German, we make little display, because, in fact, we have made but little or no use of them. In regard to the text, we have followed that of Bekker and Ast, who hardly differ at all, either in words or punctuation. Wherever there has been a departure from them, the reasons are assigned, mainly in the shorter notes. The critical means within our power have been very limited, and we therefore, in this department, ask indulgence for any errors which may have been committed. For the philosophical opin- ions advanced no such plea is interposed. By their own merit, and their accordance with the true inter- pretation of the Platonic system, they stand or fall. One design of the work is to serve as a text-book for senior classes in college, not so much by way of furnishing an exercise in the study of the Greek lan- guage, as for the higher object of exhibiting, in connex- ion with the Platonic, the other systems of Greek phi- losophy, and their bearing upon the Christian theology. On the same grounds, it is supposed that it may be found useful to students in our theological seminaries, and form no unprofitable addition to the libraries of cler- gymen, besides commending itself generally to the at- tention of our scholars and literary men. We believe that in this age there is a peculiar call for a deeper knowledge of Plato. Some acquaintance with his doctrine of ideas seems needed as a correct- ive to the tendency, so widely prevalent, to resolve all knowledge into an experimental induction of facts, not only in physical, but also in ethical and political science. If the Good, to adopt our author’s own style,* is something more than pleasure or happiness * See The Cratylus. 440, B. ; also Dissertation XX., p 163. Xll INTRODUCTION. either present or anticipated — if the True is something higher than past, present, or future facts — if the Beau- tiful is something more than a generalization from pleasing individual sensations — if the Just and the Right involve inquiries far above those endless logoma- chies, and questions of casuistry, which form the main features of modern ethics — if the State is a reality transcending a present aggregation of flowing and perishing individuals — if Law is a spiritual power dis- tinct from the muscular force of a majority of present wills — if God is something more than gravitation, or the eternal development of a physical fate, which is only another name for an eternal succession of inex- plicable phenomena — if there is a real foundation for the moral and religious, as distinct from, and not em- braced in, the natural , or, in other words, if penalty and retribution are terms of far more solemn import than the modern jargon about physical consequences — then surely is it high time that there should be some disturbance of this placid taking for granted of the opposing views ; then surely should Plato be stud- ied, if for no other purpose, as a matter of curiosity, to see if there may not possibly be some other philoso- phy than this noisy Baconianism, about which there is kept up such an everlasting din, or that still more noisy, because more empty, transcendentalism, which some would present as its only antidote. In place of all this, we want the clear, simple, common sense philosophy of Plato, commending itself, when rightly understood, to all the aoival evvoiat , or universal ideas of the race, in distinction from that miscalled common sense which is only the manufactured public opinion of the moment — a philosophy most religious — most speculative, and yet most practical — most childlike in its primeval simpli- INTRODUCTION. xia city, and yet most profound. We speak with confi- dence on this point. The young man who is an en- thusiastic student of Plato can never be a sciolist in regard to education, a quack in literature, a dema- gogue in politics, or an infidel in religion. Our main object, then, is to recommend this noble phi- losopher to the present generation of educated young men, especially to our theologians. The present work by no means professes to set forth his system as a whole, but merely to present some of its attractive points, to allure other minds among us to a more thor- ough examination. The main doctrine of ideas, al- though alluded to in almost every dissertation, is not discussed under its own title, because we had formed the design, if permitted to accomplish it, and if the present work should be acceptable to the public, of treating it by itself in ah*examination of another of the most interesting of the Platonic dialogues. We conclude with the remark that, in a moral and practical, as well as in a speculative point of view, the particular subject of the dialogue selected has some claim to attention. He who thinks most deeply, and has the most intimate acquaintance with human na- ture, as exhibited in his own heart, will be the most apt to resolve all unbelief into Atheism. Especially will this be the case at a time when physical science, in league with a subtle pantheism, is everywhere sub- stituting its jargon of laws, and elements, and nebular star-dust, and vital forces, and magnetic fluids, for the recognition of a personal God, and an ever wakeful, ever energizing special providence. Theism, we ad- mit, is everywhere the avowed creed, but it wants life. It is too much of a mere philosophy. There B XIV INTRODUCTION. are times when the bare thought tnat God is, comes home to the soul with a power and a flash of light which gives a new illumination, and a more vivid in- terest to every other moral truth. It is on such occa- sions the conviction is felt that all unbelief is Atheism, or an acknowledgment of a mere natural power cloth- ed with no moral attributes, and giving rise to no moral sanctions. We want vividness given to the great idea of God as a judge, a moral governor, a special superintendent of the world and all its move- ments, the head of a moral system, to which the ma- chinery of natural laws serves but as the temporary scaffolding, to be continued, changed, replaced, or finally removed, when the great ends for which alone it was designed shall have been accomplished. Just as such an idea of God is strong and clear, so will be a conviction of sin, so will be a sense of the need of expiation, so will be a belief in a personal Redeemer, and so will follow in its train an assurance of all the solemn verities of the Christian faith, so strong and deep, that no boastful pretension of that science which makes the natural the foundation of the moral, and no stumbling-blocks in the letter of the Bible will for a moment yield it any disquietude. There is a want of such a faith, as is shown bv the feverish anxiety in re- spect to the discoveries of science, and the results of the agitations of the social and political world. This timid unbelief, when called by its true name, is Athe- ism. The next great battle-ground of infidelity will not be the Scriptures. What faith there may remain will be summoned to defend the very being of a God, the great truth involving every other moral and reli- gious truth — the primal truth, that HE IS, and that he is the rewarder of all who diligently seek him . CONTENTS. Png « Introduction .......... v Statement of the Argument ....... Greek Text and Critical Notes . . . . 1 to 84 EXCURSUS I. The Platonic View of the Parental and Filial Relations, and the Ancient Doctrine generally on this Subject . . .87 II. The Words npooifuov and Uapa/j,v6tov . — The Preamble, the Ad- visory or Argumentative Part of the Law . . . .95 III. Subjective Sense of the Word ’A ?i7j6ev(j 97 IV. The Orphic Poetry 99 y. Plato’s Regard for Antiquity and the Ancient Mythology. — His Use of the Word QeoI 102 VI. Philosophy and Character of Anaxagoras .... 105 VII. The Divine Justice the Ground of Human Law . . .110 VIII. Universality of the Belief in a God Ill IX. Antiquity of Atheism 114 X. Principle of Authority 116 XI. Degrees of Atheism. — Peculiarity of Plato’s Style . . .117 XII. Ancient Doctrine of the Four Elements 119 XIII. Atheistical Doctrine of $v(ng, Tvxv, and T exvrj . . .130 XVi CONTENTS. XIV. Mfi Atheistical Doctrine that Law and Religion were not by Na- ture, but by Art . XV . 135 The Figure Aposiopesis . XVI. 139 Argument for the Existence of a God from Motion . XVII. . 141 Soul Older than Body XVIII. . 144 Remarkable Comparison of the Dangerous Flood . . 146 XIX. Invocation of the Divine Aid in the Argument. — Striking Ex- amples of this from other Dialogues 148 XX. The Great Question of the Ancient Schools, Do all Things flow 1 &c. ; with a Sketch of some of the principal Mate- rializing or Atheistical Philosophers who belonged to the Ion- ic, and to the Physical School of Elea .... 152 XXI. Mathematical Use of the Word A oyog 164 XXII. Paradox of Circular Motion -166 XXIII. The words QOLo ig, Teveatg, UaOog, and $6opd . . . .167 XXIV. Philosophy of the Verb TO BE. — Platonic use of E Ifii and Ytyvopac .......... 170 XXV. Ancient Divisions of Motion. — According to Plato. — According to Aristotle. — Distinction between Teveaig and ’A/iXolucig. ^-The Atomic Theory more favourable to Theism than the Doctrine of Occult Qualities 184 XXVI. A vroKLvijGig, or Self-motion of Soul. — Energy or Action be longs to the Essence of the Deity. — Whether on this View God must have created Worlds from Eternity. — Aristotle’s Misrepresentations of Plato on this Point. — His own Doc- trine. — Aristotle’s Immoveable Essence. — Moral Reasons the first of Moving Causes 190 XXVII. The Words A oyog, EMo$-, and ’Idea . . . . . .195 CONTENTS. XVII XXVIII. Distinction between A oyog and v O voua XXIX. Infinite Distance between Self-motion and Motion by Impulse. —Impassable Chasm between' Spirit and Matter. — Ideas of Change, Cause, and Spirit inseparable. — The Word IIoA- loarfj . — Principle of Euphonic Attraction . XXX. Argument of Ancient Atheists that Apparent Evidences of Design were only Evidences of subsequent Accommodation. — Things (they said) older than Knowledge of Things, and therefore older than Soul XXXI. Platonic Doctrine of the Evil Principle. — Of ’Av&yKq, or Ne- cessity XXXII. Platonic Analogy between the Motion of N ovg and and that of a Sphere, or of the Heavens XXXIII. The Motions of the Evil Soul Irregular and Disorderly. — The nearer an Approach to the Pure Reason, the more of Fixed- ness and Uniformity. — Heaven a State of Eternal Rest. — Atheistic Objection from the unvarying Regularity of the Heavens, from whence was inferred the Absence of Will and Reason XXXIV. Platonic Doctrine of the Animation of the Heavenly Bodies. — Ancient Belief that each Nation had its own peculiar Guardian Daemon or Genius XXXV. Three Hypotheses in respect to the Animation of the Heav- enly Bodies XXXVI. Ff)g v O xw a -> or Vehiculum Mundi. — Examination of a Remark able Passage from Euripides XXXVII. Second Grand Division of the Argument. — Doctrine of a Special Providence. — Mistake of Cudworth .... XXXVIII. The Greek Words for Blessedness, Happiness, Fortune, &c. . XXXIX. Atheistic Argument against Providence drawn from the Pros- perity of the Wicked. — Plato’s Language compared with that of the Scriptures . B 2 Page 196 201 204 207 219 224 229 233 235 237 239 243 XV111 CONTENTS. XL. Pug 9 The Singular Word ’ AnodLOTro/LiTreoftcu, and the Remarkable Use made of it by Plato 245 XLI. 'Defect of Plato’s Theology in regard to the Doctrine of Atone- ment and the Necessity of Expiation 249 l XLII. # Highest Proof of the Divine Goodness, the a priori Convic- tion of the Moral Sense 253 XLIII. Sublime Mode in which the Bible represents the Divine Provi- dence and Omniscience as contrasted with all mere Philos- ophizing on these Attributes. — Analysis of the Greek Word ’A vSpeia, as denoting one of the Cardinal Virtues of Soul. — Piety of Epicureanism 255 XLIV. The true Dignity of Man his Religious Nature. — Analysis of the Greeek Words Sefiaf, E vaebtLa, &c. .... 259 XLV. Men Compared to Sheep of the Divine Pasture. — Language of Plato on this Subject in Harmony with that of the Scriptures 261 XLVI. Peculiarity of certain Negative Forms of Greek Verbs . . 262 XLVII. Great Things cannot Exist without Small. — Application of the Maxim to the Doctrine of a Special* Providence, to Educa- tion, and to Politics 264 XLVIII. Gentleness of Plato’s Mode of Argument, and its peculiar Adaptation to the Minds of the Young .... 267 XLIX. The Machinery of Physical Events controlled by Invisible Spir- itual Agencies. — The Doctrine of Plato and of the Bible. . 268 L. The Ancient Maxim De Nihilo Nihil. — Greek Ideas in Respect to Creation. — Language of the Fathers. — Plato defended against the Charge of teaching the Eternity of the World and of Matter. — Platonic Sense of the Maxim. — Comparison of Hebrews, xi., 3, with the Language of Plato. — Difficulties of Reason when the Doctrine of Cieation is examined apart from Revelation 272 CONTENTS. XIX LI. Page Doctrine that the Parts are made for the Whole as set forth by Plato, and as viewed by Modern Rationalists and Semi- Infidels. — The Converse Doctrine, that the Whole is also for the Parts, examined with Reference to the Mutual Harmony of both 286 LII. Atheistic Objection drawn from the Extent of the Universe . 292 LIII. Explanation of a Difficult Passage. — Remarks on those Views that resolve Morality into an Obedience to Physical Laws, and regard all Punishment as Consequential instead of Penal 294 LIV. The Word ’Av^eOpog as distinguished from A luvioc. — Remark- able Passage in the Timaeus 300 LV. The Greek Words for Eternity, A I6v and A lovloq . . . 302 LVI. Plato’s Doctrine of the Freedom of the Will, viewea in Con- nexion with the Law of Cause and Effect in Nature . . 307 LVII. Explanation of a Difficult Passage 312 LVIII. The Greek Word "kidrjg and the Hebrew and 1 — iSvp jy 3 316 LIX. Similar Views of a Future State, and Similar Fears of Hell in all Ages 318 LX. The Word "kytog . — Exceeding Spirituality of some of Plato’s Views. — Many of his Thoughts capable of being fairly ac- commodated to p Spiritual Sense higher than the Author him- self had ever intended to convey. — Difference in this Re- spect between his Writings and those of all other Philoso- phers, Ancient and Modern 322 LXI. Mythical Sense of the Word Quvarog 331 LXII. Omnipresence of the Divine Justice. —Remarkable Resem- blance of Plato’s Language to some Passages from the Bible 333 LXIII. Doctrine of a Final Judgment.— Use of the Word Iwreketa 334 XX CONTENTS. LXIV. Pag* Platonic Use of the Word Tvnog ..... 338 LXV. Explanation of a Difficult Passage, in which Plato seems to assert that our Evils in the Present State exceed our Good 339 LXVI. M.axv ’AOavarog, or Battle of the Universe, between the Pow- ers of Good and Evil. — Sin, therefore, no Light Matter, be- cause it is Treason against the Cause of Good, for which God is contending with the Evil Soul 342 LXVII. Plato’s Doctrine of the A atiioveg, or Genii .... 347 LXYIII. Beauty and Accuracy of the Ancient and Platonic Division of the Four Cardinal Virtues. — Deep Moral Significance of the Four Greek Words, ’ knokaaia , ’A Kpareia, ’Ey/cpdma, and 'Zutypoavvri, as indicating the Four Moral Degrees . . 35 LXIX. Peculiar Use of the Indicative Mode in certain Cases. — Com- parison of Passages from the New Testament . . . 355 LXX. Use of the Word YUeovE^ia. — Aristotle’s Distinction between Arithmetical and Geometrical Equality .... 356 LXXI. Impiety and Folly of attempting to bribe Heaven . . . 357 LXXII. Different Species of Atheists. — Morality of Atheists not found- ed on Principle. — First Species styled A inaiog by Plato, and invested by him with too Good a Character. — Second Species, the Magician or Juggler. — The Atheist often in Secret the Victim of Superstition. — Hobbes. — The Ironical Species of Atheist, a Character peculiar to the Ancient World. — Ely- mas the Sorcerer. — Apollonius of Tyanea .... 359 LXXIII. The Nightly Conference, or Areopagus of Plato’s State. — The Athenian Areopagus 363 LXXIV. Common Law against all Private Religions. — Examination of Plato’s Doctrine in respect to Changes in the Public Wor- ship and Religion of the State 364 LXXV. Belief in Apparitions, Ghosts, Spectres, Dreams, &c., the same in all Ages 369 STATEMENT OF THE ARGUMENT. As a dramatic work, The Laws is far inferior to the Republic. The speakers are three : namely, Clinias, a Cretan, Megillus, a Lacedaemonian, and a stranger, who passes by no other name than the Athenian. The latter is the Socrates of the dialogue. The first two are either mere listeners, or only brought in as suggestive helps in the various transitions of the discourse. After nine books occu- pied with varied and extended schemes of legislation, and wffiere laws are mingled with reasonings and introductory preambles, which need not here be specified, the author comes, in the tenth book, to treat of offences against the public worship and religion, which it is supposed, of course, the State must possess, if it would be a state indeed, and not a mere herding together of men and women in a political congregation, having no other bond of union than the tem- porary consent of individual wills. Previously, however, to the en- actment of laws for the punishment of sacrilege and other offences against religion, the chief speaker proposes that there should be laid down, by way of foundation, a preamble or hortatory statement, containing the reasons of the laws ; which preamble, although con- cisely expressed at first (page 3), is subsequently expanded into an argument which occupies nearly the whole book, the few last pages only being taken up with the laws and the penalties annexed. The argument is divided into three parts ; 1. Against those who denied the Divine existence ; 2. Against those who, while they ad- mitted the existence of a God, denied a providence ; and, 3. Against those who, while they admitted both a God and a providence, main- tained that the Deity was easily propitiated, or would not punish sin severely. The first part is introduced by a declaration of Clini- as, that it must be easy to prove the existence of the Deity. He appeals at once to the most obvious phenomena of nature, the sun, the earth, and stars, &c., as conclusive evidence, especially if taken in connexion with the universal sentiments of mankind. This gives occasion to the chief speaker to suggest that the subject is involved in greater difficulties than the other, in his simplicity, had imagined ; difficulties, however, not intrinsic, but arising from the perverseness of those who imposed upon themselves by the words chance , nature , art , &c., referring to the old Atheists of the Ionic or Materializing school ( page 4 to page 15). After a short digression, in which it is XXII STATEMENT OF THE ARGUMENT. debated whether it is best at once to apply the law to such men, without argument (15 to 19), the Athenian devotes himself to the work of refutation, and commences a most subtle disquisition re- specting the nature of soul as implying self-motion involved in its very essence. Hence he proves that matter cannot possess this power, and, therefore, soul being more ancient than body, the prop- erties of soul must also be older than the properties of body. From this it is inferred that nature is the child, and not the mother of Art, as the Atheists said, and that, therefore, law , and will, and design , and thought , must have been before hard , and soft , and heavy , and light , and all the adaptations of the natural world. The Atheists had held that religion, and the belief in the existence of Gods, being the production of human law, which was a production of art, and art itself being the offspring of Nature, therefore religion and all ideas of the just and right were conventional among men, and had no other foundation. This argument is refuted by the Athenian by showing the superior antiquity of soul, and, therefore, of these ideas as essential parts of its constitution (25). In proving the self- energy of soul, he goes into a very minute examination of the differ- ent kinds of motion, summing them all up, however, under two gen- eral heads ; namely, motion by impulse , and that which moves some- thing else by commencing motion in itself. This latter he identifies with psyche, or soul , by a species of logical necessity, or an argu- ment drawn from the force of terms and the innate ideas involved in them. The next step is to determine whether it is one or more souls which are engaged in the affairs of the universe ; the result of which inquiry is, that there are two, the one good and the other bad ; the one constant, uniform, and ever exhibiting the highest reason in all its motions, which he compares to those of a sphere, the other irregular, disorderly, without reason, and full of madness (36). After this, there are stated three methods by which soul may guide the motions of the heavenly bodies ; namely, by an indwell- ing spirit, or by a soul with an aethereal body, or entirely destitute of body, and external to the object of its guidance (42). This brings the Athenian to the second grand division of the sub- ject, namely, the arguments of those who deny a Providence. Af- ter premising that men are led to this opinion by seeing the appa- rent impunity and prosperity of the wicked (45), he shows that it is utterly derogatory to any right views of the Divine Nature. For if we admit that God is possessed of every virtue, indolence and indif- ference can form no part of his character. Neither can it be tliat there is in him any want of power. Therefore we cannot suppose STATEMENT OF THE ARGUMENT. XX11I that he will neglect anything, either great or small. Next is shown the importance of small things as parts of a whole , absolutely essen- tial to its totality, and that, without small things, the great could not exist. Hence the doctrine of a minute special providence, un- less the Deity is to be regarded as inferior in wisdom to human art- ists (56). The method of this special providence is shown to be by such arrangements in the sovereignty of God (but not by any inhe- rent necessity of things), that every agent finds its fitting place namely, virtue rises and wickedness descends, until the one reaches The Most Holy Place, and the other sinks down to the most painful retributions of Hades (61). This Eternal Justice, or fixed law of God’s government, no one can escape, and, unless it is kept in view, t will be impossible to form any right opinion respecting a blessed or miserable life (64). The third grand division of the argument respects those who view sin as a trifle, and who confide in the general mercy of God as capable of being easily moved by prayers and sacrifices. He contrasts their views of the Deity with such as are entertained of the lowest class of human guardians, as though God could be bribed by the wages of iniquity, when dogs could not be prevailed upon by similar motives to admit the wolf into the flock. Arguments against those views which would regard sin as a small matter, and God as easily appeased, are drawn from the [idxrj dddvarog , the battle of the universe, or everlasting conflict between good and evil, in which God and all good influences are contending for the victory, and where, of consequence, the least taking part with the enemy, or the least neutrality is treason against the cause of good throughout the universe (69, 74). There are then enumerated six classes of offenders ; namely, two to each of the three divisions of Atheists or semi- Atheists, differing in their degrees of guilt, and therefore requiring different gradations of punishment. The book closes with a specification of the various penalties, and a law against private chapels and private religious rites ; in the course of which a very striking description is given of that class of Atheists who, while they had no religious belief them- selves, made it their business to excite the superstitious fears of mankind for their own unnatural pleasure or profit. N.B. — All references to any of the dialogues of Plato, except the text of the present work, are made according to the pages and let- ters of the alphabet, as given in the standard edition of Stephanus, * and as they may be found in the margin of the Leipsic. i'LlNO^ PLATO CONTRA ATHEOS. DE LEGIBUS LIBER X. META tie rag altitag , irepl navrdg 1 ev elprjoOo) roiovde tl vdfJLCfjiov fliaiojv irept • tgjv aXhorpLUv pijdsva prjdev (pepeiv pL7]ds ayecv - 2 prjd’ av %pri ( idat prjdevl rcov rov ite- 1. He pi navrdg. In reference to the whole subject discussed in the preceding book (ix.), namely, vdpeig, or wrongs committed wil- fully and with some degree of violence, of which ahcia , treated of at the close of the ninth book, is one species, and sacrilege another. 2. epxi rj XP1 T ai r ivi 9 rdjv eneivcov , prj ireioag avrovg. rrepn rov de, rd no- Xinnov av eirj enaorov rtiv TtoXir&v vbpioOev, dinrjv em- naXovpevov. olg d?) doreov 10 11 elg noivov vopov enaoroig. iepoovXCa pev yap eiprjrai £ vXXrjddrjv , (dialog re nal XaOpa eav yiyvr\rai, ri xprj rraoxsiv. oaa de Xoycp nal ooa epyep uepi tieovg vdpi^ei ng Xeycjv rj Trparrojv , u to napapvdiov vnoOepevcp 12 prjreov a del naox^iv. eoro) dij rode • deovg 3. ’E av prj neioy, “unless he get the consent.” 4. "Y Speig, “violent wrongs committed wilfully and with malice prepense, whether by act or speech.” The writer now proceeds to specify five different grades into which offences of this kind might be divided : 1st, against sacred things public ; 2d, against sacred things private ; 3d, against parents ; 4th, against magistrates ; 5th, against private political rights of individual citizens. 5. A evrepog has respect to diaQepovrug above, referring not, like devrepa, to numerical rank, but to the grade of enormity. 6. Eif de yoveag. See Note I., App. 7. Xoplg tuv epnpooOev elpypevuv, namely, those mentioned in the ninth book. 8. "Orav u$povtlotC)v Tig, “ when any one who is reckless of the authority or respect due to magistrates.” 9. The case of tlvI is determined here grammatically by the iast verb, xp^rcu, although in sense it is the common object of them all. 10. T 0 Xg drj doreov, “ for all which cases there must be a common law,” or “a law in common containing provisions applicable to each respectively.” 11. Tieyov i) nparrov, “by speech or action.” 12 See Note II., App. CONTRA ATHEOS. 3 rjyovpevog elvai nard vopovg ovdelg ncbnore ovre epyov aoedeg elpyacaro encbv ovre Xbyov af)r\nev avopov. aXXa ev 13 6rj ri rd)v rpicov naox^v, rj rovro onep elrcov ov% ijyovpevog, rj to devrepov , ovrag , ov (ppovri^eiv dvGpc ottcjv , rj rpirov , eimapapvGrjrovg elvai , 'Gvoiaig re nal evxalg na- oayopevovg. KA. Tl ovv drj dplppev av rj nal Xeyoipev rrpog avrovg ; A0. T £2 ’ yaOe , enanovocopev avrebv Trpcbrov a rep naraeppo- veiv rjptiv 1 * npoanal^ovrag avrovg Xeyeiv pavrevopai. KA. TLola drj ; A0. Tavra rdpf civ epeox^Xovvreg ehroiev. T £2 i-ev e ’A Gr\- vale nal Aanedaipovie nal K.vdj oie, dXrjGrj Xeyere. rjpcbv yap ol pev ronapdnav Geovg ovdapcog vopi^ovoiv • ol de , prjdev rjpojv (ppovri^eiv * ol de, evxalg napayeaGai, oiovg vpeig Xeyere . a^iovpev drj, naQdnep vpeig rj^icbnare nepl vopojv, rrplv aneiXelv rjpiv onXrjpdjg, rjpdg nporepov eni- X^ipelv 7 relOeiv nal didaoneiv (bg elol deol, 15 renprjpia Xe- yovreg inavd, nal on j QeXriovg rj rrapd ro dinaiov vno rivijjv dbopcov iraparpeireoGai nrjXovpevoi. vvv pev yap rav- ra dnovovreg re nal roiavG ’ erepa rcbv Xeyopevcov apioruv elvai 7TOi7]rcbv re nal prjropcov nal pavreejv nal lepecov , nal 13. akla ev. Supply as follows: “but when he has done thus, he has done it — ev drj tl t&v rpibv ndex^v — being in one or the other of these three states.” 14. rb eara^poveiv ypbv, “in their contempt for us.” npocrTrai- fyvrag is best rendered adverbially, “ sportively .” 15. bg elol &eoi. This example furnishes an excellent illustration of the general difference between the particles bg and on. Both follow nearly the same class of verbs, and are frequently regarded and rendered as though they were nearly, if not quite, synonymous. The difference, however, in this and similar cases, is obvious. "On would simply refer to the fact ; bg, to the manner or reason of it. As, for example, didaoneiv on, “ to teach us the fact , that there are Gods didaoneiv bg, “to teach us how that is, “ in what manner, and for what necessary reasons, there are Gods.” And so in the follow- ing sentence : nal on (SeXrlovg rj, n. t. h., “ and also the fact that they are better than,” &c., or “ that they are too good.” 4 CONTRa atheos. aXXcov TroXXatetg pvpicjv, ovte enl to pi) dpav rd ddttea 1 rps- rzopeQa ol TiXelorot, dpdoavreg 6’ e^ateelodai irecpdopeda. napa di dr/ vopoOerCov (^aoteovrcjjv eivai pi) aypicov, aXXd r/pspcov, a^iovpev ttelOoi npdjrov xpr/oOac i rpdg r/pdg, el pi) 7roA/L %eve, doteel padiov eivai dXr/devovrag 3 , Xeyeiv d)£ elol d eoi ; A0. ITw^ ; KA. IT pedrov pev yi) teal r/Xiog, aorpa re rd gypnavra, teal rd rcov djpcdv diateeteoopr/peva teaXddg oyrcog, eveavroeg re teal pr/ol dieiXr/ppeva * teal ore ndvreg f 'E XXr/veg re tea ) Pdpdapoi vopi^ovoiv eivai deovg. A0. Qodbvpai ye, d) patedpie, rovg poxOr/povg, ( ov yap drj 7 Tore elnoip f av &oye aldovpai) pr/Te^g yptiv tearaeppovrj- c(j)olv . vpelg pev yap ovte lore avrebv irepi ri/v rr/g diacpOo- pdg 4 alriav , a/ IA’ r/yeloOe dtepareia povov i/dovedv re teal 1 . ovk km to [ir/ dp$v tcl adLKa. This may be freely rendered thus : “ Instead of being turned away from the commission of sin, the most of us are wholly occupied in attempts to avert its consequences .” In this there is most concisely, yet most forcibly expressed, the essen- tial difference between two things that are often mistaken the one for the other, namely, between true religion , consisting in right views of the Divine Nature, or that true “ fear of the Lord which is to de- part from evil ” (Tpeneadai km to pr/ 6pq,v Ta adma), and superstition , which is wholly occupied, not in the avoidance of sin, but in vain attempts to cure the evils and terrors which it brings upon the soul, (dpaoavTeq 6’ kZaneZodai ireip&peOa). This superstition, or false reli- gion, as Plato elsewhere shows, is nearly allied to Atheism. See Note LXXX. and LXXXI., App. 2. TcoTihti peTiTiu. The antithesis here is between noMu (3e?LTitj and peTiTLo ye , “ better, indeed, in respect to truth, if not far better.” 3. dTir/devovrag. See Note III., App. 4. diacpdopag. We have adopted this instead of the common read- ing, diatyopuq. It is supported by the authority of Cornarius and Stephanus, although Ficinus seems to have read diaQopag, and is in CONTRA ATHEOS, 5 imOvpitbv sm rov dosbr] f3tov oppaoOat 5 rag 'ijjvxag av - ru)V. KA. To 6s Tt npog rovrotg alrtov av , gj gsvs, sir] ; A0. 'Zxsdov 6 navraTraoLV vpslg s%G) ^tivrsg ovk av st- dsirjrs, dXXa vpag d,v XavOavot. KA. T i 6i) tovto (ppd^stg ravvv ; A0. ’Aji tadta rig 6 paXa x a ^ 87T ^ 6otcovoa slvat psytorrj (ppovrjotg. KA. lUbg Xsyetg ; A0. E lolv rjptv sv ypappaot Xoyot Kstpsvot , ol reap* vplv ovk, slot 6t 9 apsrijv noXtrstag , wg sytb pavOavco • ol I usv, sv not psrpotg , 7 ol 6s, nai dvsv psrpcov, Xsyovrsg nspt fistiv, ol psv TraXatorarot , ysyovsv rj irpcbr r\ cpvotg ovpavov, row rs dXXcjv • tt potovrsg 9 6s rijg apx^]g ov ttoXv bbsoyovtav bts^spxovrat, ysvopsvot rs (bg repdg aXXrjXovg (bptXrjoav. a rolg anovovotv si psv slg aXXo rt reaXebg r] pi) far better accordance with all the words of the context — morum cor - ruptio atque depravalio — rottenness of soul. In the same way are the same class of persons characterized by the Psalmist : “ The foot hath said in his heart , there is no God;" nS’ , S# corrupt are they , and abominable in their deeds. Psalm xiv., 1 . :)p; l 7 v 9 vr;( corrupti , perditis moribus sunt. They are altogether become futhy. 5. oppaoOai, “ to rush impetuously or violently.” Admirably de scriptive of the headlong course of those to whom it is here appiieo 6 . ’ApaOla tlq. A more perfect description of this disease of Athe ism (SiafOopag) could not be given. It sets forth the malady with it , cause, and is equally applicable to ancient and to modern times : “ an invincible ignorance , fancying itself the highest vnsdom .” ’A paOia here has no reference to speculative or scientific knowledge, but is used in the usual Platonic sense for “ ignorance of one’s self.” 7. ol pev hv perpoig. See Note IV., App. 8 . liyovreg . . . 6g . See remarks on ug and on, page 3, 15. 9. TTpolovreg dr, “ Advancing, or going on from the discussion of the origin {rrjg upxrjg) of the first nature ( 17 )g tt purrjg (jivaeog), which was the subject of the most ancient (or Orphic) writings (rtiv nahae- otutuv), they treated next of the theogony, that is, the individual births and generations of the Gods, with their actions and mutual intercourse,” as set forth by Homer and Hesiod. A 2 6 CONTRA ATHEOS. naXCog e^oi , ov padiov kiunpav naXatolg ovoiv. 10 elg pevroi yovicov re dspanelag nal npag 11 ovn av eyo)ye ttote enai- vd)v ehrotpi, ovte (hg g deiva epya^dfxeda vopoderovyreg dog ovtcov $ecov ; r/ XacpELV eaoavTEg , ettl rovg vopovg rpEntipEda ndXiv, urj teal to npooiptov * 2 rjplv panpOTEpov yiyvr]Tat rcov vopa>v; ov yap fipaxvg o Xoyog kuraOElg av ytyvotro , eI toZoiv ETiiOvpOVOtV aOEdELV, T& f. LEV dlTodElljaipEV, 3 4 pETptCOg TOlg Xoyotg , cbv E(j)patjov 6eIv TTEpi XiyEiv • rd 6s, Elg cj)66ov t ps- xpaipsv * ra 6s, dvoftEpaLVELV nocrjoavrEg, oaa irpETtsi^ psra ravra rj6r] vopodsTolpsv . KA. ’AA/l’, d) tjsvs, TzoXXdtag psv coays 5 £t> bXiy cp %po- T’G) rovr’ a^TO siprjfcapsv, d)g ovdsv ev rep rrapovre 6sl TtpoTipav ppaxvXoytav pdXXov ff prjteog. ovdslg yap rjpdg, to Xsyopsvov, ETcstycov didwEL. ysXolov dr} teal (jyavXov to TTpo tg)v I3eXtlgto)v Ta Ppa^vTSpa alpovpsvovg (patVEoOat. 6iacj)EpEi 6 ’ ov epuepov apejaysneog 6 * * mOavoTrjTa Tiva Tovg Xoyovg rjpCbv exslv, cog foot t 9 slot teal dyadot, d'uirjv Tip de- fendant in such a cause, and of being required to give reasons for the belief in the existence of the Deity, especially before profane and ungodly men. 2. Trpooipiov. See Note II., App. 3. rd pev drzobei^aipev , k. t. 7i., “ Should in some things demonstrate by arguments , &c. — rd 6e, elg epobov rpeipaipev, should in others excite their fears — rd be, five x e P 0iveiv i k. t, A., and in others making them dislike , or appealing to their prejudices ,” Ac. Or it may be para- phrased still more generally : If we should address ourselves to their reason, their fears, or their tastes , namely, their moral sentiments, of which they cannot wholly divest themselves, or their wholesome prejudices. 4. oaa npetret. In most editions there is a comma after npenei. It is clear, however, that these words are connected with vopoOerol- pev which follows, and that the comma should be after Troiijoavreg. 5. haye ev oliyu, “ for so short a time as we have been together.” 6. apocryenug. A difficult particle to analyze, so as to show the force of each part. It may be rendered “ in some one way or other, at least;” apug, in some way, expressing the certainty that there is such a way ; 7 vug (indefiniteness), whatever that way may be ; ye, that there is one such way at least, if no more, ye always, whether alone or in composition, implies that the writer chooses to limit the mean- ing of a word, although intimating that he could say more if it pleas* ed him. CONTRA ATHEOS. y reg dta^ epovrcog avOpcorrov. c%edbv yap tovto 7 8 fjp.lv vrrep andvTG)v tgjv vopo)v tcdXXcoTov te teal apiorov i rpoolptov dv elrj. prjdev ovv dvox^pdvavTeg prjde eTTeixOcvreg, rjvrt- vd 7 Tore exopev dvvaptv elg ttelOco tgjv tolovtgjv Xoycjv, urjdev arcoOepevot , dte^eXOG)pev elg to dvvarbv hcav&g. AO. E vxfj v pot, doted napatcaXelv* 6 Xeyopevog vtto gov vvv Xoyog , ETtEidfj npodvpG)g ovvTEiveig * peXXetv de ovketl eyx^pd Xeyetv. (f)epe dfj, 7 rcbg dv Tig pfj 'dvpcp Xeyoc nepl $eCdV , dog eioev ; dvdyurj yap dfj x^XenGog rjoepetv teal ptoelv etceivovg ol tovtgov fjplv alrioi tgov Xoytov yeyevrjvTai teal ytyvovrat vvv , dv rteidopevot 9 rolg pvdoig, ovg etc vegjv nal- 7. oxeSov yap tovto. See Note VII., App ? 8. YiVxv v TrapaKaheiv, “ to invite the wish,” that is, to second one’s wishes — to invite one to do what he already desires to do. 9. yiyvovTai vvv , ov rrstdojuevoi. In the common text this stands thus : ylyvovrac. Nvv ovv TceiOopevoi : the great objection to which is, that it is impossible to make any suitable sense out of it. Fici- nus felt the difficulty, and therefore made a paraphrase rather than a translation. The correction was made by Stephanus, partim (as he says) veteris exemplar is ope , partim conjectura mea. In fact, the exigenlia loci absolutely requires the reading of Stephanus, which we have given, although not altogether free from objections. It is fol- lowed by editors generally in their notes and translations, although the other reading is retained in their text. The words ov neidopevoi may therefore be regarded, not as a commencement of the follow- ing, but as the conclusion of the preceding sentence, which runs on, without coming to a close, until it terminates in ovk hoi iSteol, some distance below. The whole passage being the language of justly- indignant feeling against those who would ruthlessly destroy all the religious reminiscences of youth, and all the hallowed associations of domestic instruction, is, on this account, rather involved and pa- renthetical. The thoughts and emotions outrun the expressions, leaving much to be supplied to bring out the meaning in all its ful- ness. This we attempt in the following free paraphrastic transla- tion : “ For we must feel indignant, and dislike those who have ever been and are now the causes of such discussions ; who believe not the myths, which, when yet children, they heard of nurses and mothers in soothing strains of sportive or serious song, as they lis- tened to the prayers and gazed upon those attending spectacles (of 10 CONTRA ATHEOS. do)v art ev yaXa^t rpecpopevot, rpocpcov re rjfcovov nai prjre- pcjv , olov ev empdalg pera re rtaididg nal pera onovdrp ; Xeyopevovg , teat pera 'dvotebv, ev ev^atg avrovg ateovovreg re y teat oipetg optivreg enopevag avrotg , ag Tjdtora o ye veog opa re teat ateovet rrparropevag , bhjovrGJV ev onovdjj r r q pe- yiGTTj rcbv avrebv yovecjv , vnep avrtbv re teat eteetv g)v eo - rcovdateorcov , cbg on paXtora ovot tieolg evffiug npoodtaXe- yopevcov teat iteeretatg * avareXXovrog re rjXtov teal oeXrj- vrjg nai irpog dvopdg iovrcov, repotevXtoetg apa teat rrpootev- vrjpetg ateovovreg re teal optivreg 'EXXrjvcov re teal j3apda- pG)v 10 ndvrcov ev ovpcpopatg iravrotatg e^opevcov teal ev ev- repaytatg , oi>x &g ovte ovruv, aXX ’ o)g on paXtora ovrcjv, teal ovdaprj vno'iptav evdidovrcov djg ovte elol 'Seat, rov - rcov dfj rravruv boot tearaeppovrjoavreg ovde ei; evog Iteavov Xoyov , wc (patev av boot nai optKpov vov teeterrjvrat , vvv avayted^ovotv rjpag Xeyetv a, Xeyopev , nebg rovrovg av rtg ev rrpaeot Xoyotg dvvatro vovdercov apa dtdaoteetv nepl 'detiv TTpojrov d>g eiot ; roXprjreov de. ov yap apa ye del pavrjvat , n rovg pev y vtto Xaipapytag rjdovrjg, rjptiv, rovg d’ religious worship) which the young soul hears and sees so joyfully — their parents sacrificing with solemn earnestness for themselves and their families, and by their vows and supplications conversing with the Gods as the most real of existences — who too, at the ri- sings and settings of the sun and moon, have often seen and heard the prostrations and adorations both of Greeks and Barbarians, in every diversified situation of prosperity and adversity appealing to the Gods, not as unreal fancies, but as existing in the highest sense, and without any suspicion to the contrary.” It is a strain of elo- quence fervid and indignant, yet not unkind or harsh, against those who, trampling under foot the most sacred associations, demand proof for that which never should have been doubted, and which seldom again finds a secure resting-place in that soul in which false reasoning, the result of licentious passions, has taken the place of wholesome religious authority. 10. '’EiXXrjvidv re nai j3ap6dpuv. See Note VIII., App. 11. Ov yap apa ye Sec pavf/vai , rove pev . . . rjpuv, rove de, &c. Ste- phanus, Cornarius, Ast, and most of the commentators, would here reieet qpfiv, although without the authority of any manuscripts. We CONTRA ATHEOS. 11 vito rov 'dviiovoQai Tolg roiovroig , ltg) d?j TTpopprjGLg tol - tide ng advpog rolg ovto) tt)v diavoiav dLELpOdppsvoLg • tcdi XeyupEV npdcjg, 12 odeaavreg rov ftvpov, cog evl dcaXeyope- VOL T( OV TOLOVTG)V, T £2 TTdl, VEOg EL * TTpolCdV ds GE 6 XP° V0( > TTOLTjGEL TToXXd d)V VVV do^d^ELg pLETdddXoVTd , ETTL TdVdVTLd TlOegOcU . T TEpipELVOV OVV Elg TOTE fCpLTljg TTEpl TG)V pLEytG- tg)v yiyvEoOai . piyiGTOv de, o vvv ovdkv r] y ov , to, TTEpl Toi)g tiEOvg opOtdg diavor^EVTa , $ 7 v tcaXtig rj prj. Trpdj- TOV ds TTEpl CLVTLdV EV TL pLEya GOl p7]VVG)V OVfC dV TTOTE (f)d- VEL7]V XpEvdpg, TO TOLOvds • OV OV povog ovds ol Gol (j)iXoi TTpd)TOL Kal TTpCOTOV TGVT7JV d6%dV TTEpl $ E(OV EG^ETE * JLJ- VOVTCLL d£ GEL 13 TT^ELOVg 7] kX&TTOVg TGVTTjV T7]V VOGOV e%ov~ T£g. Tods tolvvv gol TTdpdyEyovog gvt&v TToXXolg (j)pd- £ OLfl * dV , TO prjdEVd TT(x)TTOTE XddoVTd EH VEOV TGVT7JV TT\V do^dv TTEpl 'decdv pa£’ ETt oacpEOTEpov. ism does not often continue in old age, but that, although a specu- lative theism may take its place, the other accompaniments, name- ly, unbelief in a special Providence, or an indifferent trust in the Divine placability, may continue to the latest period. We think that this remark of Plato would be abundantly confirmed by an actual observation of life. It is seldom that we find an old man a specu- lative Atheist, whatever he may have been in his youth. It is, however, much more common to meet with those whose insensi- bility in respect to the reality of the Divine anger against sin is in direct proportion to the years in which they have experienced the special care and sparing mercy of Heaven. 15. /cal 61} nai paktara ical. The combination of particles here is worthy of notice. K at drj generally denotes an application of a pre- vious assertion, and is commonly used a fortiori , “learning from others, and, therefore, If from others {a- fortiori), from the lawgiver also, and in the highest degree.” The second kcll is to be taken with pak/cra, and the third with vopoOerov. See Note X., App. 1. pexpi ye tov vvv , “ so far at least.” 2. navTaTccKn pev ovv. See Note XI., App. CONTRA ATHEOS. 13 A0. A eyovot nov rev eg cjg ndvra earl rd 7 jpdypara yiy- vopeva, nal yevopeva , nal yevrjoopeva, rd pev, (pvoet, rd fie, re%vy, rd de did rvxd v - KA. Ovnovv naXcdg ; A0. E Inog ye rot nov 3 4 oocpovg avdpag opQtig Xeyetv. enopevoi ye urjv> avrolg , oneipcjpeda rovg enelOev f ri nore nal Tvy%avovoL diavoovpevoi. KA. Udvrcjg. A0. "E ouce, c pact , rd pev peytora avrcdv teal naXXcora anepyd&oOai (pvoev nal rvxd v i rd de aptnpdrepa, rexvrjv • rjv dfj napd (pvaecjg Xapdavovaav rr\v rtiv j ueyaXcov teal npd)ro)v yeveenv epycov , nXarretv nal renratveoOai ndvra rd opinporepa, a drj rexvtnd navreg npooayopevopev . KA. IIw^ Xeyeig ; A0. T £2d’ eri oaepearepov epoj . nvp real vdo)p nal yrjv nal depa , 5 (pvoet ndvra elvac teal rvxd * Text'd de ovdev rovreov. 6 nal rd perd ravra av ocapara , yrjg re nal rjXlov nal oeXrjvrjg , aorpejv re nepi , did rovrtov yeyovevai nav- reX&g ovrcov aipvxMV. Tvxd de (pepopeva rjj rr]g dvvdpecjg enaqra enaorcov, rj £ vpnenreonev appdrrovra olneicog ncog , 3. ’Eikoc ye rot nov. This is the usual Socratic or Platonic irony. “ It may be likely, at least, that these wise people talk correctly.” E Uog ye, “ likely, plausible, probable, at least, if not certain .” Te rot nov is a combination of particles deserving special notice. Te has its usual limiting sense as given above ; rot, like $7, confirms and strengthens the limitation, while nov seems in the usual manner to diminish the positiveness of the expression by way of appeal to the party addressed. “ Surely (rot) may we say, may we not (nov), that these wise men talk plausibly at least (ye), to use no stronger term.” 4. rovg eKeldev. Haud dubie (says Ast) scribendnm est, to eKeldev, quod ex illo consequitur. We have but little doubt, on the other hand, that Ast is wrong. The old and established reading, rove, eKeldev, may be rendered “ those from, or of that school,” namely, their fol- lowers, those who expand and explain the doctrine more fully, as in the next answer. 5. nvp Kcii vdcjp Kal yrjv. See Note XII., App. 6. (j>v yeyev- vrjKEvai rov re ovpavov oXov nai iravra breboa nar ’ ovpa - vov • teal oa av teat (pvrd %vpiT avra, dptiv iraotiv Etc rov - rojv yevopevcov , ov did vovv, (paoiv , ovde did rtva tieov ovde did rex'V'rjVi aXXd, o Xeyopev, cpvoei teal rvxxi • T ^X m vrjv ds vorepov Etc rovrcov vorepav yevopev'qv , avrrjv fivT]- rr\v he '&V7]rdjv, vorepa yeyevvrjKevai iraididg nvag , dXrj- Oeiag ov oepodpa perexovoag , dXXd Eldar) 1’ drra £ vyyEvrj eavrdrv, oV fj ypacpiterj yevva teal povoiK? ), teal boat ravraig slot ovvepiQoi rbxvai • aZ (5’ em /ecu oreovdalov apa yevvdj- oi rdv rExvcbv, eivai ravrag onboai ryj (pvoEi E/coivcooav rrjv avrdrv dvvapiv • olov av larpiKrj teal yeorpyiKij teal yvpvaoriKi j. teal drj teal rrjv noXiriKrjv opiKpov ri pbpog eh vat (paoi tcoivcovovv (pvoei, rex^Xl to ttoXv. ovrar ds teat rrjv vopodeoiav irdoav , 7 8 ov (pvoei , rexv^j de * rjg ovtc aXip Oelg Eivai rag 'deoeig. KA. II tig Xeyeig ; A0. Oeovg , 0 ) paKapie, Etvai irpdrrov (paoiv ovroi rexvrj, ov (pvoEi , dXXd, not vopoig • teal rovrovg aXXovg aXXoig, otttj Etcaoroi eavroioi ovvcrpoXbyrjoav vopoOsrovpevoi • teal drj teal rd teaXa, (pvoei pev dXXa eivai, vopep ds erepa • rd de drj dtteata ovd 5 Eivai ronapanav (pvoei , d/L/l’ ap(pto6rjrovv- rag diareXeiv aXXrjXoig teal peraridepevovg del ravra • a <3’ dv psraOcovrai teal orav, rors tevpia Eteaora Eivai, yiy - vbpEva rEXvy teat rotg vopoig , a/M/ ov drj nvi cpvoEi . Tadr' EorLv, d) c p'iXoi , are avra dvdpcbv oocpcbv napa vioig avOpd)- Txoig, idt(x)rd)v re teal iroirjrddv , (paoteovrcov Eivai rd dueaio- rarov o, rl rig dv vitea (dia^opEVog. oOev aoibEial re av- 0pd)TTOig epniiTrovoi veoig, d)g ovtc ovrcov $ed)V oiovg o vo - pog npoorarrei diavoeioOai delv * oraoeig re did ravra, eXteovrG)v s repog rov Kara (pvoiv opdov (3iov, og eon ry 7. voftodeolav naoav. See Note NIV., App. 8. kTiKovTov. The article rtiv would seem to be required here be- CONTRA ATHEOS. 15 dXrjdEta uparovvrd £ rjv r&v aX/ io)v, nal pbrj SovXevovra eTEpoiOi Kara vopcov . KA. 0 iov disXrjXvOag, gj %eve , Xoyov , 60772 ; Xibbrjv avOpdoncov veo)v drjpoGta ttoXegl te teal idioig olnoig. A 0 . 'AXrjOrj piivTOL Xsystg, o) K Xsivla. tl ovv oIel XPV~ vac dpav rov vopoOsrrjv , ovtg) tovtg)v tt&Xcu napEGnsvaG - p,ev G)v ; rj piovov dixsiXslv ordvra ev t'q t:6Xei gvpinaGi rolg av0pd)7TOLg , (bg, el per/ (frrjGovoLV 9 stvai tisovg acil diavorjOrj- Govrai , do^d^ovrsg roiovrovg olovg cfirjGlv 6 vopiog ; /cat TTEpi naXCbv teal ducaitev, nal nspl andvrcov rtiv psyLGTGJv , 6 avrog Xoyog , oaa re 7 rpd$* dpsrrjv telvel nal nantav , deZ ravra ovtg) nparrsiv, dtavoovpsvovg burjirsp dv 6 vopo- 0sT7]g v(p7]y'rjGrjrac ypd(j)cov • <5’ av ptfj rrapEx^rai savrov rolg vopoig evttelO? 7 , rov psv dslv rsOvavcu, rov 6s nva nXrjyalg nai bsGpolg , rov 6e , dripiicug, dXXovg 6s 'nsviaig noXa^EGOcu real (bvyalg * ttelOg) 6e rolg dvQpbbnoig, 10 apa fore eA/cwrcjv, although there is no authority of manuscripts for it, It seems to refer to (pacKovruv above. “ Hence factions or quarrels arise by reason of these things, while they violently drag (the young) to that mode of life which is right by nature (that is, in their opin- ion), which consists, in reality, in so living as to have power over others, and to be in subjection to none by virtue of law.” In this metaphorical expression, ehwvruv, Plato seems to have had an eye to some of those violent contests which Homer so vividly describes as taking place over a dead body, in which both sides are pulling with all their might, the one to carry off, the other to rescue ; as in the battle over the body of Patroclus, in the sixteenth book of the Iliad. He rises, however, infinitely above Homer in his subject. It is not the dead body of the slain hero which is here the object of contention, but the living soul of the young man that the atheistic crew are seeking to drag down to their own kingdom of darkness ; or, to accommodate the language of the Grecian poet to a sense far beyond his highest conceptions, we may say, with a slight change of the verse, Iliad, xxii., 161 : ’A/UA 7 repi X V XVC pdpvavrai dSavaroio. 9. See Note NV., App. 10. t teiOcj de rolg uvftpi'oTcoig. Connect this with rj piovov dnei7^eh\ about ten lines back ; and then, by leaving out all that is explanatory 16 CONTRA ATHEOS. riQevru avrolg rovg vopovg, prjdeplav ex^iv TOi C hoyoig irpooamovra eig dvvapiv ?fpepovv ; KA. Mrjdapcbg, oj %eve • dAA’ einsp rvyxdvei ye ovoa nal opinpd ttslOg) rig rrepl ra roiavra , del prjdaprj napveiv rov ye d^iov nal opinpov vopoOerrjv, dAAa naoav , to Ae- yopevov, (jrcjvrjv ievra , * 11 rep rcaXaicp vopep enucovpov yiy- veodai Aoyo), d)£ eiol deot, nal boa vvv dr) dirjXOeg ov , nal d?) nal vopep avrep fiorjOrjoai nal rexv^l ' eorov (ftvoei rj (pvoecog ovx rjrrov, ehrep vov ye eon yevvr\para , nard Ao- y ov opOov ov ov re Xeyeiv poi (paivy nal eycb ooi morevet ravvv. A0. T £2 7 jpoQvporare KXeivla, ri d 9 ; ov ^aAerrd re eon %vvanoXovQelv A byoig eig TrXrjOr) A eyopeva, prjnrj re av 12 nenrrjrai duoXvyia ; Dr parenthetical, the contrast may be exhibited thus : “ Or ought he to threaten them only, that unless they shall say, &c. ; but not, by attaching it to his arguments, exercise persuasion towards men at the same time that he lays down the laws, so that (by such persua- sive arguments) he may render them as mild, or as well-disposed to- wards the laws as possible.” As here may be rendered “ and,” which, in a similar connexion in English, is sometimes a disjunctive particle : “ Shall he threaten, &c., and shall he not persuade!” Or the disjunctive force of 6e may be better brought out, and the con- nexion with the first part of the sentence at the same time preserv- ed, by rendering it “ instead of,” thus : “ Ought he only to threaten instead of using persuasion!” &c. In this construction, exeiv, as well as aTZELlelv, will depend on olei xpyvat, about twelve lines back. 11. Tzuaav (povTjv levra, “ letting out all his voice,” that is, omitting nothing which may tend to produce conviction. A proverbial ex- pression, for which see Erasmus, Adag., p. 788. It seems some- what to resemble a nautical metaphor, of which the Greek poets were very fond, and of which we have a striking example, Eurip., Medea, 280 : ’Ex^poc yap k^lacn izdvra 6rj k&Xov. “ For my enemies let out all their rope,” that is, “ are attacking me under full sail, and straining every nerve.” 12. firjKrj re av. There is a harshness here in consequence of the sudden change from the participle to the indicative mode KEicrTjrai. CONTRA ATIIEOS. 17 KA. T l 6s, co t-eve ; nspl psOrjg 13 psv nal povoncfjg ovrco imnpd Xeyovrag rjpdg avrovg irsptspLStvdpLSv , 14 nepl tisoov 6s feat rcbv rotovrov ovx VTcopLSVoiyisv ; nal pfjv real vopoOs - old ys sort irov r q psrd (ppovrjosog ptsyLorr} porjOstd, 6 lotl rd nspl vopovg npooraypara sv ypdppdoc rsOsvra , cog 6co- aovra slg iravra xpovou sXeyxov , rtdvrcog fjpspsl * 15 coots ovt 1 si x a ^ £1T d tear 7 dpxdg dnovstv sort (jyobrjTsov , a y ’ so • Tdi Kdi TCO 6vOpddsl TroXXdfCLg STTdVLOVTL 1 OfCOTTSLV * OVTS si pd/cpd, cocbsXipd 6s, 6id Tdvrd Xoyov ov6dpr] sx £ ^ ov6e ooiov spotys slvdt cpdivsTdi to prj ov (3or)0slv rovroig rdig Xoyotg ndvTd dv6pd tedTd 6vvdptv. MEr. v kpiOTd, co gsvs, 6onsl Xsystv K Xsiviag. A0. Kdl j udXd ye, co MsytXXs * ttoltjtsov re d)g Xsyei. This, however, must be rendered as though it were KEKTypeva, if, indeed, this is not the true reading. 13. 7 TF.pl peOyg. This refers to discussions in the first and third books of this treatise, which had been continued at great length. 14. Trepipevo, “ to linger around a subject — to wait one’s own lei- sure.” vnopevG), “ to endure, to wait with patience.” After vnope- vovpev supply TZEpipevEiv, thus : ov% vnopEvovpev TZEpipevEiv, “ shall we not endure to wait]” or, taken adverbially, “ shall we not wait patiently]” There is evidently a case of paronomasia, or play upon words here. 15. ypepel. “ Are altogether silent .” Compare this with the myth respecting the God Theuth in th.e Phaedrus, 275, D., where oral in- struction is commended, as better than that of books, and doubts are suggested, whether, after all, the art of writing has been of real service to mankind : ug dhyOtig bpocov (ypaQy) faypatyia • Kai yap ra tKeivyg EarrjKEv uev ug gCivra, edv 6’ dvepy tl, aepvcjg navv ciyp. ravrov 6e nai 7] ypaavelev Tioycov anropevoi daeOoVf “ for it would make no small difference if they should appear,” &c This sense of Ki.vdvvevo is quite a favourite with Plato. 3. e^dpxovreQ — auspicantes — qui aliis auctores sunt. 4. dr)6earepa)v. See Note XVI., App. CONTRA ATHEOS. 19 KA. Ovn 6kv7]teov , (b %eve. pavdavo) yap (bg vopoOsctag EKTog oh'jorj patvstv, sav rcbv tolovtcjv dnrcbpEda Xoycov. eI ds egtl prjdapr) STEporg GvpcfroJvrjGat 5 rolg vvv Kara vopov % XsyopsvoLg ■dsolg (bg opOtig exovglv i) ravrrj , a eicteov, cb •dav pacts, teat ravrrj . A0. A syotp? dv, (bg sotnev , rjdrj cx^ddv ova slorOoTa Xo- yov Ttvd rovds. o TTpcbrov ysvEGEorg teal (pOopag alrtov dr:dvro)v, rovro ov uptirov aXXa vorspov anE(f>r)vavTO sl- vat ysyovog oi tt)v rtbv aosdcbv 'ijrvx'rjv dnEpyaodpsvot Ao- yot * 6 o ds vorspov , TTpoTspov. 7 8 oOsv rjpaprrjtcaGt irspl dstbv TTjg bvTG)g ovotag. KA. Ovtcg) pavdavo). A0. 'kvx'rjv, c b sratps, rjyvorjnsvat ntvdvvEvovot psv oXt- yov i-vpnavTEg olov te ov rvyxdvst /cat dvvaptv fjv sxet * r(bv te aXXorv avrrjg irspi, nat dr) real ysvEGsarg, (bg sv nptb- roig egtl Gorparcov EpnpooOev 9 irdvrorv yEvopsvrj , nat psra - doXrjg te avTtbv nat p£Tanocpr)GEG)g aTTdcrjg apx m rtavTog paXXov . si ds egtl TavTa oviorg, apa ovtc eg avdyurjg rd GvyyEvrj TrpOTEpa dv sir) ysyovoTa T(bv GtbpaTt 7i pog7]k6vtg)v, ovG7]g TavTrjg rcpEGdvTEpag rj G(bpaTog ; KA. ’A vaynr). A0. A 6%a dr) 9 teal EntpsXEta nat vovg nat texvt) nat vo- pog , G/tXrjpcbv nat paXanebv nat ftapEorv nat noveporv npoTE- pa dv sir) * nat dr) nat Ta psyaXa nat irpcbTa spy a nat irpai f- 5. ovptyMvrjoat. Plato was very fond of metaphorical expressions derived from the science of music. Similar terms in similar con- nexions are found throughout all the dialogues, such as gwclSelv, ovvudy, kizqidEiv, kneidy, &c. 6. ol rrjv rtiv dosbivv Tpvxyv uTVEpyaadpEvot hoyoi, “ which render the soul of the impious what it is.” Equivalent to this other ex- pression, UTTEpyaGapEvot rrjv rrjg avrCrv Tpvxvc uGE&stav. 7. o de vorspov ( arr Efo'jvavro ) 7r porspov. They are guilty of the fault which logicians style hysteron proteron , that is, putting the ef- fect for the cause, and the cause for the effect ; which they did, in making rexvrj posterior to dvotg and rvx rj. 8. 9. Guudrtov epTrpooOEv. See Note XVII., App. 20 CONTRA ATHEOS. eig , 7 sx vr J^ ^v ytyvoLTo, ovra ev Trpcoroig • ra de cf)vasi nal cj)vcng (jjv ovtc opQtig ei rovopa^ovaiv avrb' 0 tovto) vg- * rspa real apxopeva av etc Texvrjg eh] nal vov, KA. ITwf ; A0. Ov/c opOtig (f>voiv povXovraL Xeyeiv yevsoiv rfjv rrepl rd npdjra. el 6s (fravrjoerai 'ipvx'rj nptirov, ov ttv p ovde drjp, 'ipvx'rj < 5 ’ ev npuroig yeyevrjpevrj , oxedov * 11 opdorara Xeyoir’ av elvai dLacpepovTCog, ore (pvoei 12 ravr ’ eoO ’ ovTCog exovra, av 'ijjvx'fjv reg emdei^ irpeodvrepav ovoav o bbpa- rog , aXXcog de ovdap&g. * KA. ’A XrjOeoTara Xeyeig. A0. Ovtcovv rd perd ravra en' f avro 6rj tovto otsXXo)* ueOa ; KA. T t prjv ; A0. QvXaTTCjpev drj navTanaoLV dnaTr]Xbv Xbyov , prj 10. avro tovto, “ which they incorrectly call this very thing,” namely, “ this first thing, which we call iftvxTr, they call $vgls” vg- Tepa nal, &c., “Nature and its works would be posterior to and ruled by art and reason, or mind.” 11. ox^bbv, here, does not qualify opdorara , but \eyoiTo , — “ it might almost be said with the highest degree of correctness.” It, in fact, renders the whole declaration stronger instead of weakening it. It seems to be often used as a sort of apology for a bold expression, and thus, instead of diminishing or impairing its force, as the com- mon rendering ( almost ) would imply, it has directly the contrary effect. 12. pvGEi. “ It might then be said with the highest degree of cor- rectness, that these things are thus by nature , if any one should show that soul is older than body, but otherwise not.” Plato seems some- how to have changed the sense of the word upon the atheist. He evidently here makes tyvGig the same with the truth of things , what- ever that may be, and, therefore, if soul is o.der than body, then in the highest sense may this be said to be the order of nature. If any should regard it as a mere play upon words, it certainly should be deemed pardonable in a contest with those whose whole strength consists in the dexterous use of such words as tvxv, voi(;, chance , nature , &c. CONTRA ATHEOS. 21 itt] npeadvrag rjpag ovrag veonpenrjg cov uapa7T£LO / q y /cal di- a(j)vycbv naTaysXaOTOvg Trotrjo'd * teal dd^cjpev, pet^ova em- baXkdpevoi™ /cat rtiv cpuip&v anorvxeZv. u icon sire ovv , Kadanep ei 1 * irorapov rjpag edec rpelg ovrag biabaivEiv ps- ovra o(j)6<5pa , vetbrarog 6’ eyob rvy^avoov vptbv aai ttoXXcov epiretpog pevpdro)v , elnov on irplorov epe xprjvat ixeipaQi]- vac 15 icar^ epavrov , KaraXcnovra vpag ev aoeptiXel, OKS'ipao- Ocu el diabarog eon TtpeobvTEpoig ovot real vplv , rj irtig £%££, teal (j)avevTog pev ravr y, ttaXelv vpag tots aal ovv- dtabtba^Etv epnEipia , el be abarog fjv (bg vplv , ev epoi rov Kivdvvov yeyovivai • perplcjg av eddfcovv Xeyeiv. nai Srj real vvv 6 peXXw eon Xoyog ccfrodpoTEpog, nai oxedov loug 13. emSaXXopevoi. “Lest, aiming at things too great, we should fail even of the small.” 14. Kadanep el. The common reading is el Kadanep. We have ventured to make the change from the exigency of the place, and on the authority of Stephanus ; “ as if we three had to cross a violent- ly-flowing river.” — See Note XVIII., App. 15. neipadijvai. Whenever a verb is used only in the middle voice to the entire exclusion of the active, or when the middle is the predominant form — or when the active has a causal signification, thus giving rise to what in the middle is seemingly an independent sense — in all such cases, the passive aorists and passive perfect do not denote the receiving of an action, or, in other words, are not the passive of the active, even when it is in use, but are strictly middle tenses. Thus, neipdu , “ to tempt another ;” neipdopai , “ to tempt one’s self, or to attempt, to try ;” neipadrjvai , not to be tempted , but “ to attempt, or try ;” same as the middle. So, also, 7rAa£b, “ to cause to wander ;” nhdfypai, “to wander;” nXayxdrjvai, not “ to be made to wander,” but to wander ; same as the middle. Such cases are very frequent in Greek. Nothing seems to us to be gained by calling them deponent, a term which would seem to belong peculiarly to the Latin where there is no middle form, except as it is supplied by the passive. In Greek no good reason can be assigned why such verbs should be regarded as essentially different from others of the middle voice. This peculiarity does certainly exist in cases where there is an actual middle beyond all doubt, as shown in the use both of the middle and passive aorists with the same sense. 22 CONTRA ATHEOS. a6arog l 2 (bg 737 ocp&v p(bpq • pi] 6i) onorodivlav iXiyyov* rs vplv epiroirjorj, napacpepopevog 3 4 re nai epcjrdjv arjOecg ovrag airoKpLoeuv , elr' dox'rjpoovvrjv airperxeidv re evreay] arjdr], done! 6rj pot xp^l vai 17 oielv ovro)al ravvv epe * avepurav TTpGjrov epavrov cuiovovTGdv vpibv ev docpaXel, ical pera ravra dirouptvaodai TrdXtv epe • teal rov Xoyov duavra ovto) diegeXOelv, axpcnep dv 'ipvxijs ^cept dianepavij-cu, nal deify 71 porepov ov 'ijwxijv O(bparog. KA. V A pior\ (b fyve, frorcelg rjplv elprjicevat • ixolet re (bg Xeyetg. A0. "Aye fy* dedv elnore uapanXrjreov rjplv, vvv eo~G) tovto ovtg) yevopevov * enl ye anodeii-tv (bg elol rijv av- 1 . (jxedov u jug a6arog. See page 20 , 11 . Here also, Gxebov, instead of impairing, increases the force of the expression, and may be re- garded as an apology for not using a stronger term. “ We might almost say aSarog” &c. 2 . oxoTobcvlav ITuyyov re vplv spnoLr/Gri. These are favourite terms with Plato to express that state of intellectual dizziness with which the soul approaches the contemplation of those great truths, which may he regarded as the apxal or foundations of all others. Compare the language used in the beginning of the seventh book of the Repub- lic, as applied to those who are supposed suddenly to emerge from the dark cave of error and phenomena into the upper world of light and truth. Compare, also, the Gorgias, 527, A. ; Theaetetus, 155, D. That this language was common with Socrates himself, and that Plato in this, as well as in almost everything else, truly represents his peculiarities, not only of reasoning, but of style, may be inferred from the manner in which Aristophanes joins together these two terms in evident allusion to Socrates, whose philosophy and favourite modes of speech he omits no opportunity to ridicule, not only in the Clouds, but also in many places of his other comedies. Vide the Acharnenses, 1218. ITuyyuo Kapa Xldtp 7rEn?i7jyphogy Kal GKOTodiviib. 3. 'KctpatyepopEvog. In this word the metaphor of the rushing stream is still sustained, although, in a critical point of view, it is rather awkwardly dropped in tporuv. T^oyog is to be supplied for both. See Note XVIII., App. 4. See Note XIX., App. CONTRA ATHEOS. 23 rwr, onovd'Q iraorf napaKeuXrjoOuv . exoperoi de 6 tig nvog aGcfraXovg netGparog, Emdacvoopev elg rov vvv Xoyov. icaZ poi eX eyxopbvcp 1 nepl rd rocavra , epojrrjOEGL roialode da- (paXeorara dnonpivEoda c 8 (paLverai. Kara ds, d) Z-eve , ono - rav (pr\ rtg, dpa EorrjKE pev navra , 9 KiveZrai de ovdev ; rj rovrcp 7T av rovvavrtov ; ?] rd pev avrtiv tuveZrat , rd de pevEL ; Ta pev ntveZrai nov , 10 (prjGU ), rd ds psvei. Mwv otw Tm to re eortira egttjue , /ecu to Kivovpeva tuveZrat j 11 IIw^ ydp ov ; Ka£ to ye ev edpa nov av 5. See Note XIX., App. 6. kxopevoL 6e &g tivoq do^akovg neerparog. “ Holding fast as by some sure cable.” There is still preserved here the metaphor of the dangerous flood, and there can be no doubt, that by this sure cable is meant that Divine strength and guidance for which he had just prayed. See Notes XVIII. and XIX., App. 7. ElEyxopeva). This word is generally rendered “ refuted,” or “convicted of error.” It here, however, means simply “engaged in an argument.” It is thus frequently used in the Gorgias and elsewhere. 8. dnoKpLVEGdcLL, “ to take the part of respondent” as well as that of interrogator. Kara ds . — See Note XX., App. 9. egttjke psv navra. See Note XX., App. 10. nov. This particle, of so frequent use in the Platonic dia- logues, in its primary sense implies doubt or hesitation, and is, there- fore, generally said to take away from the positiveness of a declara- tion, in a manner directly the opposite of drj. It is, however, often employed, when nothing of this kind is really intended, but only an appearance of it, in those familiarities of the colloquial style, to which this particle is so admirably adapted. It is a term of courtesy, by which the speaker, to avoid being thought dogmatic or positive, ap- peals to the other party for his assent, without, however, intending any doubt of the proposition advanced. If connected here with g onoTav ap%r) Xadovoa av^rjv, 5 elg ttjv dev- TEpav eXOrj peTadaoiv, nal and TavTrjg , elg ttjv nXrjoiov, nal pEXpt Tpitiv eXOovoa , aloOrjfUv oxzi r olg aioOavopEVotg. pETadaXXov pev ovv ovtoj nal peTamvovpevov ytyvETac nav. eotl 6e ovTug ov, s onoTav pevrj • peTabaXbv de elg dXXrjv egiv, diecpOapTai 1 * 8 navTeXtig. dp ’ ovv nivrjGEig naoag elprjnapEV (bg ev e16egi Xadelv j uet’ aptOpov, nXrjv ye, cb (pt- Xol , dvolv ; KA. II oiaiv drj ; A0. X^edov, cb 9 yaOe , eneivatv , cov evena naoa rjpZv eg- rlv t] Gne'iptg Tavvv, KA. Aeye GacpeOTEpov . A0. vxTjg fjv evena nov ; KA. Jlavv j uev ovv . A0. "E (7T6) TOtVVV 7] j UEV ETEpa dwapEVrf niVElv niV7]Gl EavT7)v de adwaTOvoa alel pea Tig • d’ eavTrjv r’ aZet Am erepa dvvapevr] naTa te GvynpiGEtg 9 ev re dianptGEGcv , av^acg te nal Tcb evavTicp, nal yeveoeot nal cpOopatg , a X Xr\ ata Ttg av tg5v nao&v ntvrjGEtiv . KA. ’Kcrrct) yap ovv. opposing objects, by those that stand they are divided, while with others that meet them (being borne from opposite directions) they unite, so that the centres and intervening parts come together into one.” 3, 4, 5. See Note XXIII., App. 6. See Note XXIV., App. 7. dieQOaprac. “ It is utterly destroyed,” that is, “ the thing which before was, no longer is” See Notes XXIII. and XXIV., App., on the words tyOioLg, avt-rjOLQ, (fiQopa , eipi, and yiyvopai . 8. 9. See Note XXV., App. O 26 CONTRA ATHEOS. A0. Ovkovv rrjv pev erepov dec mvovoav , teal peradaX- Xopevrjv v(p 9 erepov , 'drjoopev evarrjv av , 10 rrjv re eavrrjv mvovoav teal erepa , evapporrovoav Trace pev rrocrjpaoc, rraoc de iraOrjpaoc , tcaXovpevrjv de ovrcog rcov ovrcov n av. rcov peradoXrjv teal mvrjocv, ravrrjv de detcarrjv o%eddv epovpev. KA. UavraTraoi pev ovv. A0. Tcov dr) dena pdXcora rjplv mvrjoecov reva rrpoKpc- vaepev * 11 opOorara rraccdv eppcopeveordrrjv 12 re elvac nat Trpatcrcicrjv deaepepovreog ; KA. M vpccp 13 avdyterj i rov (jravac dcacjrepecv rrjv avrrjv dvvapevrjv mvelv , rag de aXXag 7rdoag, vorepag. A0. Ev Xeyecg. dp’ ovv rjplv rcov vvv ova dpQcdg prjdev- rcov peraOereov 14 ev fj teal dvo ; KA. Hoc a cpxig ; A0. To rrjg detearrjg prjQev oftedov ova dpOcdg elprjrac . KA. Urj; A0. Upcdrov 15 yeveoec re eon teal pcdpyp teard Xoyov to de pera rovro e%opev rovrov devrepov , apre prjQev aro- rrcog evarov. KA. nc5$* Xeyecg ; A0, T £2de. orav erepov aXXo rjplv peraddXyj , nal rovro aXXo erepov dec , rcov rocovrcov apa eorac rrore rc irpcdrov peradaXXov ; teal rrcdg, orav vn’ aXXov mvrjrac , rovr ’ eoTat 10. See Note XXV., App. 11. riva TTpoKpivaifiEV. This is the common reading. It is evi- dent, however, that dv should be supplied. 12. See Note XXVI., App. 13. pvpiG). Hyperbolical measure of excess. “ By ten thousand times.” 14. /LcsTaderiov. “ Must we change the order in one or two par- ticulars V } 15. npcorov. The meaning of this is, that what was last or tenth in the order of the previous investigation, becomes first in the order of nature and in the degree of importance ; and that which we be fore wrongly called the ninth, becomes now the second. See Notes XXV. and XXVI., App. CONTRA ATHEOS. 27 irore rtiv aXXoiovvTO)v rrpCdTov ; advvarov yap, dAA’ orav apa avro avrd tuvrjcrav erepov dXXoitior], to d ’ erepov aX- Xo , nat ovtg) dfj x^ ia pvpioig ytyvrjrai rd /avrjOevra , I ucbv apx'f] rcg avrtiv ear at rrjg mvrjoeojg dndorjg aXXr], 7 tXt)v i] Ti]g avTrjg avTrjv mvr\odG7\g peTadoXrj ; KA. K aXXiOTa elnsg • Gvyx^p'ijrea te TOVTOig. A0. ,7 E tl dr) real Tode ehrcjpev, nai dnofcptvcjpeOa irdXiv rjplv avToloiv. el GTairj ncjg rd rravTa opov yevopeva , na- Oanep oi nXeloTOt t&v tolovtgjv toX pd)Gi Xeyeiv , tlv ’ apa ev avTOtg avay/crj 7rpd)Trjv Ktvrjoiv yevsoOai tcov eiprjpsvG)v $ KA. T rjv avT7]v dr] rrov mvovaav . in’ aXXov yap ov prj~ 7 tots spnpoaOev psTanso'y , prjdepidg ye ev avTOtg ovorjg epirpoaOev psTanTuaecog. A0. ’A pxv v apa 1 Kivrjosojv naotiv teal Trpd)T7]v ev ts eg- tgjgl yevopevrjv teal ev tuvovpevoig ovGav tt)v avTrjv mvov~ Gav , tyrjGopev dvaynaiatg elvai TTpeGdvTaTrjv ical KpaTiGTTjv peTaboXfjV naGtiv • tt)v de dXXoiovpevrjv veff ETepov , klvov- GaiPds eTspa , devTepav. KA. ’A Xr}OeGTaTa Xeyetg. A0. ' Ottote d 7} TOivvv evTavda EGpev tov Xoyov , 2 Tode dnorcpivtipeOa. KA. To 7 Tolov ; A0. 5 E av ldo)pev 7 tov TavTTjv 3 yevopevrjv ev tgj yrjivcp , rj evvdpG), rj Trvpoeidei, nexupiopevcp rj teal ^vppiyel , tl ttotg (frrjGopev ev tgj tolovtg) tt aOog elvai ; KA. Mtiv apa pe epo)Tag el £?/ v 4 avro npoGepovpev OTav avTO avTO mvf \ ; 1. apxvv apa klvt/ceov. “ Seeing, then, that it is the principle of all motions, the first among things that stand, and being self-mo- ving among things that move, we will say that it is *he oldest and strongest,” &c. 2. hravda Xoyov. “In this part of our argument.” Compare such expressions as 7 tov yr/c — 7r oi yijc — ek rod’ anoplag — Iv* el naKov — we opyrjg 3. TttVTIJV. Supply KLVTJOLV. 4. Cyv npooEpovfjiEV orav avro avro tavrj ; “ Shall we call it life (of CONTRA ATHEOS. A0. N at, tfjv. KA. Hug yap ov ; A0. T L de ; onorav 'i/jvxrjv ev tloiv optipev, ptiv aXko f t ravrov TOVTCp $q v opoAoyrjreov ; KA. 0 vtc aXXo. A0. "E %e dr\ 5 irpog ktog * ap ’ oi>/£ av eOeXoig nepl enao- tov rpia voelv ; KA. Hug Xeyetg ; AO. *'Ev pev, rrjv ovolav * 6 ev de , rrjg ovoiag rov Xoyov • ev de, ovopa. t cal dr) Kal 7 epcorrjoetg eivai nepl to ov anav dvo. KA. IIw^ dvo ; A0. Tore pev 8 rjpojv enaorov rovvopa nporecvopevov avro , rov Aoyov airairelv • tots de rov Xoyov Tcporeivope- vov, epcorav av rovvopa. apa ye to rotovde av fiovXopeda vvv Xeyeiv ; KA. To 7 toIov ; ♦ — to Live) when a thing itself moves itself'?” £««, to live , and to boil , to bubble , to bubble up , are unquestionably of the same radical idea. Effervescence or fermentation from the action of heat, taking place in matter otherwise apparently motionless, would be the phe- nomenon which of all others would most readily suggest to the primitive mind the idea of self-motion , and would thus be taken as a symbol of life. 5. v E^£ drj tt poc A Log. “ Hold there by Jove.” An important posi- tion is gained. Let us secure it, and then advance to another view of the subject. Compare Gorgias, 490, A. The usual rendering ot this phrase, age dum , does not seem to us to give its peculiar sig- nificance. 6. ev pev , ttjv ovolav, k. t. X. “ One thing the essence, one the Xoyog or reason of the essence, and one the name.” See Note XXVII., App. 7. Kal dq Kal l This phrase generally denotes an application of a preceding proposition. “And accordingly, respecting every such essence, there must be always two questions.” 8. tote pev tote de. “ At one time, the name being present • ed, we demand the loyoq, reason or definition ; at another time, the Tibyog or reason being given, we ask the name.” CONTRA ATHEOS. 29 A0. V E otl 7 tov dix a dtaipovpevov 9 ev aXkotg re nai h aped pep, Tovrcp drj rep nar ’ dptdpov , ovopa pev, apnov • Ad yo^ de, aptOpog dtatpovpevog elg loa dvo peprj. KA. N al. A0. To tolovtov (ppa^G). pdrv ovv ov ravrov enarepodg Trpooayopevopev, 10 av re tov Xoyov epo)T(x)pevot, Tovvopa anodtdcbpev, av re Tovvopa, tov Xoyov * apTiov dvopaTij nai \oyavai ; KA. T l prjv ; ly required, we have with Ast substituted elpev, which is used for elrjpev, the rj in this form being often dropped in the dual and plural. K vpicog is a stronger word than bpQtig. It means “ by au- thority^as an established truth — or as something which we may now assert with confidence.’’ 2. See Note XXX., App. 3. tu)v re dyaQ&v airiav eivai ipvxyv Kai rtiv nahuv. “ Soul is the cause of the good, and fair, and right.” It is not, however, simply the efficient cause regarded objectively, but the very subjective ground of their existence, without which they could have no being, whether there was a universe of matter or not. Where soul is not, there can be no harmony, no beauty, no right, no good. And so, also, it not only makes its own paradise, but its own earth, and its own hell. Without it there is no discord, no deformity, no evil. 4. diouiovcav — evoinovoav , “pervading — inhabiting — indwell- ing.” 32 CONTRA ATHEOS. A0. Miav.rj nXecovg ; 5 HXetovg • £yfi) vt rep o (f) 0 )lv arro - Kptvovpcu. Avolv 6 i lev ye irov eXarrov prjdev rtOtipev, rrjg t£ evepyendog , /cat ravavria Svvapevrjg ei-epya^eodcu. KA. X if judged according to the English idiom, would be redundant as a connective. It may, however, retain its place as an intensive particle. Ka/' tcugiv olg is to be rendered as olg Kal tzclglv. So Cornarius regards it — quibus omnibus si anima, quee Dea est , utitur , &c. Or it may be taken in the order of the words, only regarding Kal as intensive instead of connective, so that rraGcv is not additional, but only a collective term for all the things mentioned before — “ And all which,” or “ even all (those second working motions) which the soul using — itself being Divine, and taking along with it that Divine thing vovg — rightly and happily guides all things ; but when conversant with folly, it ever doeth the contrary,” &c. Qeog here, according to a common Pla- tonic usage, is equivalent to tielog. 11. rrorepov ovv dq Tpvxrjg yevog , “which of the two souls (lately mentioned), do we say, has the control of the heavens, &c. — the one wise and full of virtue, or the one that hath neither of these qualities'!” 34 CONTRA ATHEOS. i cal yrjg nai irdarjg rrjg nepiodov yeyovsvcu (pdpEV ; to 0po* vcpov , teal apsrrjg nXrjpEg ; ?j to prjdETEpd Kenrrjpsvov ; QovXegOe ovv npog ravra (1 j6e GTTOfcpivGjpedG ; KA. IIg5$* ; A0. E l pkv, gj ftavpaoLe, (pcbpEv, rj £ vpndoa ovpavov odog dpa nal (popd nal tgjv ev dvreb ovtgjv anavruv, vov fuvrj- o el nal 7 T£pL ovg neptayetv ojvra. A0. K aXXtora, ch KA eivta, vmpiovoag rolg Aoyoig • rode de npoovnanovoov ert. KA. To uolov ; A0. "HA lov /cal oeX'fjvrjvf nal rd dXXa dor pa , elnep ipvXV neptayet navra , dp' ov nal ev eKaorov ; KA. T t prjv ; A0. Uepl evog 8 drj noirjocbpeOa A oy ovg, ol nal enl navra rjplv dor pa dpporrovreg (pavovvrai. KA. T ivog; A0. f HAA>v nag avOpunog otipa 9 pev opa, tyvxrp* de ovdeig • ovde yap aXXov odoparog ovdevog ovre %£)V- rog ovre anodvrjofcovrog rcbv £g)G)v • dAAd eXnlg 10 7 roAAf/ ronapanav to yevog rjplv rovro avaioOrjrov ndoaig ralg rov cojparog aloOrjoeoi, nepinetyvnevai, 1 ' vorjrov d’ elvat. 7. "H 7uov nal cE’krjvrjv. See Note XXXIV., App. 8. IIep4 hog. Supply d GTpov, which, in Greek, is often used for the sun and planets, as well as the fixed stars. 9. "H/l lov 7r dg dvOpuTcog cdpa pev opp, &c. Compare the well- known passage Xen., Memorabilia, iv., c. 3, 14. 10. hlnlg. This word in Greek has a much larger signification than hope in English. It means here, and in many other places, expectation , or, rather, ground of expectation , or belief. So, also, the verb ropai. 11. dvalodrjrov — TrspiTceQvKEvai. This should be rendered not simply, “ is not by nature an object of perception,” but rather, that “it is so in consequence of being above the nature of the sense,” being of a higher order of essence. Such is the force of nepl. Ast would amend as usual, and read TzepnretyvKhcu votjtov povov. vti 6%, &c., placing a comma after aioOrjGEOL , rejecting elvat , and connect- ing TTEpuz£(j)VKEvaL with votjtov, There is, however, no need of this. UcptnetyvKhai bears more naturally upon dvatGdijTov aiGdrjGEGt,, or, rather, upon aiGdrjGEov understood. y Eivat, which Ast wholly re- jects, is far better adapted to the word votjtov. See Note XXIV., App., on the difference between hpl and the other substantive verbs, such as ylyvopai and (j)vco , when used with philosophical correctness. Such an expression as TrepLTrecpvKevai votjtov would be at war with CONTRA ATHEOS. 39 v

66pa ye, “ earnestly to say no more, or to use no stronger expression, did I give heed to it.” In this w*ay, although a limiting particle, it does, in an indirect manner, in- crease the force of the term to which it is attached. 13. ovvef-eT&gupev. The common reading here is cwe^era^ovrov, which neither suits the vulgar text preceding it, nor any of the vari- ous readings proposed. The change is made on the authority of the best commentators, and the Latin versification of Ficinus — commu • niter inves tig emus. 14. Kai tcov pev irpootiKeiv rjplv. Twv and ijplv are neither of them CONTRA ATIIEOS. 47 KA. Ka£ ravQ ’ ovrcog bfioXoyoi nag av. A0. T C 6s, apsXeiav re /cal apyiav /cal rpv(f)7]v elg ape - rrjv 'ipvxrjg ^rjc/opev ; rj nojg ’ksyeig ; KA. K at ntig ; 15 A0. ’A/l/l’ Tovvavriov. KA. Nat. governed by n pocrjueiv, but by psrbv below, which may have a dative of the person and a genitive of the thing. Ast regards tCjv as gov- erned by npoarjKeiv , but he is clearly wrong, psrbv is used for ps- TEivai ; and thus taken for the infinitive, there is no anomaly in the neuter plural ottogu. In this use of the participle for the infinitive, the Greek resembles the English more than the Latin. Compare the Philebus, 22, E. : ovd’ av rfiv devrepecuv j/dovrj lletov aTir/Q&g av tcote T^eyoLTo. There should be a comma after eItzep, which is not to be connected with orbaa dfkavpa, but is to be taken elliptically, or with the ellipsis supplied, thus : shrEp ( nvlg eIglv olg petegtl). orbaa (p?iavpa is to be referred to t&v pbv. The order of the whole, with the ellipsis supplied, would be as follows : Kal rjplv.plv kpovpEv tt poGrj- kelv pETElvai tuv bizbaa (J>?iavpa — Ecnsp (rivsg eIgIv olg petegtl). “ And we will say, that to us (if to any beings) it pertains to have a share in those things that are bad, but to the Gods there is not the least participation,” &c. For this use of sinsp, compare Aristotle’s Politi ca, ii., 6 : xpr/Gipov bs ovcr/g ^pacvTi/Tog Trpbgovbsv rtiv eyKVKTiicjv, aKX EiTcsp — npog tov no^Epov. Aristot., Ethic. Nicomach., v., 9, 9 : ov blv yap tt apd tt/v avTov n ugxco ^ov^tjglv, cjgte ovk aduiElrat, bid y tovto, a?i/ 1’ ELTcsp — fi'X.d'KTETai povov. Aristophanes, Nubes, 227 : ETZEif dro Tafijbov Tovg fisovg VTTEpcppovEtg, aTCK ovk dno Tijg yfjg ; Elrsp. 15. KA. Kat nug ; “And how should we I” A0. ’A XX slg tov- vavTiov. ’A/Md, like yap , frequently refers to something understood, supposed to pass rapidly through the mind of the speaker. It also always implies a negative, if not expressed. This use of these lit- tle particles gives singular beauty as well as force to the Greek language. They thus carry along with them variety and fulness of meaning, at the same time without encumbering or weakening the sentence with too many words. By silent implication they keep us from losing sight of previous propositions. Thus, bXkd here carries along with it, or keeps in mind, the whole of the precedi-ng sentence, being pregnant with a denial of the question. “ No, we cannot assign dpe^Eiav apyiav , &c., to the virtue of soul, but (aTM) to the contrary.” 48 CONTRA ATHEOS. A0. T avavrta apa tovtolc; 1 eig rovvavrlov . KA. T ovvavTiov. A0. T i ovv 6rj ; Tpv(ptiv 2 teal apehrjg dpyog te ( ov 6 ixoi^ 7]T7]g KT](j)rjGL KoOoVpOLGL paXiOTCL ELUeXoV E(paOKEV Aval) yiyvoir ’ dv 6 rotovrog rcaoiv rjplv. 1. Tavavna apa tovtolc, that is, “ the opposites of TpvaGKEV elkeTlov elvaL , Ac. “ Such a Deity would be to us all Tpvtytiv, dpEhrjc, Ac. ; in short, one whom (ov), or just such a one as the poet said was like,” Ac. The only real difficulty in the passage is in ov, which, as it stands, is somewhat harsh. The relative we should expect would be olov, corresponding to tolovtoc. From its position, how- ever, in the order of the words before its correlative, it may be re- garded as affected, through a species of attraction, .by the words im- mediately preceding. Had it followed tolovtoc, it would probably have been olov, in which case the sentence would have presented no difficulty. The form of words in Greek is frequently affected by distance or contiguity, so as to be different from what would be re- quired by strict grammatical depend ance. See remarks on the w ? ord 7 toXXogttjv, Note XXIX., App. The view taken in respect to dv is confirmed by similar examples which occur a few lines below : ov pTjTsov tyeLv rjdoc tolovtov 6 ys, instead of tolovtov olov ys. So, also, page 49 ( 5 ), in the words d 6rj ttoogtjkel , Ac. The poet here refer red to is Hesiod : 76 J Se &EOL VEpEGCOGL KCU CLVEpEC, OC KEV CLEpyOC gdy, K7](j)fjVEGGL Kodovpoic elkeIoc bpyrjv. Works and Days, 278 . It may be that we have dv, instead of olov, to accommodate it to the language of the verse quoted ; a circumstance which often in- terferes with the strict grammatical dependence of a sentence CONTRA ATHEOS. 49 KA. ’0 pOorard ye elntiv. 3 A0. 0 vkovv tov. ye tieov* ov prjreov e%etv rjOog tolovtov o ye roi avTog pLoel • rep re n tolovtov (pOeyyeoOat, neipG)- pevcp ovfi emTpenTeov. KA. Ov pev 6rj. ntig yap av ; A0. T £h 6rj npoorjneL 5 pev rcpaTTecv nai empefelodaL dca- (pepovTCjg Ttvog , 6 6e tovtov ye vovg tgjv pev peyaXuv em- peXelTaL, t&v opwptiv 6e apeXel , tcaTa Tiva eixaivovvTeg tov tolovtov Xoyov , ovfc av navTanaoL nXrjppeXolpev ; Guo- 'S. bpOoTard ye elrrdv. Ast would subjoin these words to e(paonev, and make them a part of what was said by the Athenian. They un- doubtedly refer to e^aanev, yet it is perfectly agreeable to the Greek idiom to regard them as the answer of Clinias. There is a great deal of vivacity in such an elliptical reply. It is equivalent to tyaa- tcev, opdorard ye elndv. Our own language admits of it ; as, e. g ., when it is asserted that one said so and so, the reply may be, and most correctly too. 4. ovkovv tov ye fieon. A most important truth. God hates that , and that only , which is unlike himself. The Divine character is the ground and sanction of the Divine Law. It must never be called in question : r

av?iog dv. So, also, opiKpdv fj pe- yaTiav may be viewed as equivalent to dre apiKptiv dre psyahov, “whether small or great.” Or, it may be regarded as understood, as in the Republic, vi., 486, B. : ov pyv ovds rode TTapaTisiibEig. to ttolov ; Evpo.0r)g fj dvopaOrjg. “ Surely you will not omit this (circum- stance). What circumstance! Whether docile or dull.” 9. dv’ ovtec. The two supposed objectors. 10. oi dsovg psv uptyorspoc. “ Who admit, both of them, that the Gods exist, while the one says that they are easily propitiated, and the other, that they are regardless of small things.” 11. TTapaiTijTovg. See Note XLI., App. 12. Tdv onooov eiaiv ai aiaOrjceu ; rs Kai ETnoTrjpaL. “ All such things as are capable of being perceived by the sense and by the un- derstanding.” 13. tl dal\ A ai has the same analogy to 6rj that vai has to vrj. It differs from 6r] only in a prolongation and sharpening of the voice to express surprise or wonder, which is its usual office. “ But real* ly!” 14. dyaOovg te Kai dptarovg. See Note XLII., App. 52 CONTRA ATHEOS. rovg opoXoyeiv Tcparrecv otlovv ronapanav, bvrag ye otovg opoX&yovpev ; decXcag yap 15 e/cyovog ev ye 7]plv dpyca • pa- Ov/iia de , apycag /cat rpvcprjg. KA. ’ A^rjOearara Xeyetg. A0. ’A py 'ta pev drj /cat paOvpca ovdetg dpeXel fietiv. ov yap pereonv avrcp rcov detXiag. KA. ’O pOorara Xeyetg. A0. Ovkovv to Xotnov, * 1 elrcep apeXovct t&v optrcptiv /cat oXtycov rtiv nept to nav , rj ytyvdxj/covTeg d)g Toirapa - nav ovdevog tg)V tocovtgjv empeXetodat del, dpcpev dv rov- to * rj Tt to Xotnov nXfjv to ytyvcbo/cetv TOvvavTtov ; KA. Ovdev. A0. TLorepov ovv , d) aptOTe /cat (3eXTtOTe , 'dtipev ce Ae- yorra, 2 ayvoovvTag re, fmt deov empeXetodat, dt’ ay- voiav apeXovvTag , 7/ ytyvdo/covTag otl del, icaOanep oi (pav- XoTaTOi tg)v avOpuncov XeyovTat notetv , etdores* aAAa £?- vai /3eXTLG) npaTTetv 3 gjv drj npaTTOvai dm rjTTag rjdovtiv ij Xvi rcov, ov notetv ; 15. 6 tag yap. Connect this with what is said page 46, 10 : aperfjg pev avdpeiav elvai, deikiav be, Katdag. See Note XLIII., App. 1. to Xoitcov. “ For the rest of our argument.” tuv Tcepl to nav. “ Which have a relation to the whole.” 2. dtipev ce leyovTa. “ Shall we put you down as saying that the Gods are ignorant, and that even when they ought to exercise a care, they through ignorance neglect it ; or, that knowing that they ought, yet still, as the meanest of men are said to do, who know better, &c. ; so they (the Gods), through the overpowering influence of pleasures and griefs, do not do what they ought 1” A eov etz ipe- Tieiadai. A mode of expression very common with the nominative neuter participle of del and of the compounds of the substantive verbs. It is nearly equivalent to the genitive absolute, being, however, more closely connected with the reasoning of the sentence in which it stands, instead of denoting, like the latter, a mere accessory cir- cumstance of time or place. “ It being necessary,” or “ when they ought,” &c. 3. peTiTiu 7rpa,TT£Lv. Stephanus, -on the authority of Eusebius, would here read \3e7iTLov npaTTecv, melius esse alia facere. /3e7iTiG) npaTTEiv , however, is more strictly in accordance with the purest CONTRA ATHEOS. 53 KA. Utig yap av ; A0. Ov/covv 6rj rays dvOpcbmva rr pay par a* rrjg re kp- ipvxov perexEL (pvo£G)g apa , teal 'dEOGedecrarov 5 avro eotl navjcjv %G)G)v dvOpomog. KA. f, E owe yovv. A0. Qegjv ys pr\v nr^para 6 (frapEV uvai iravra onooa $vr]Ta £oja, uvnEp /cat rov ovpavov oXov 7 KA. II tig yap ov ; A0. "H 6rj Totvvv oputpa fj pEyaXa rig tyarG) ravra elvai rolg dEolg. ovdETEpug 8 yap rolg HE/crripEVotg rjpag dpsXElv av EL 7 ] TTpoorpiov , empEXEGTaroig ye ovoi /cal dpiarotg. o/co- 7 rtipEV yap dfj /cat to6e eti rrpog rovroig. KA. To 7 rolov ; A0. To 7 TEpt te aloOrjGEGjg nal dvvapEug, dp ’ ovtc kvav- tlCi )g 9 dXXrjXoLV irpog paordbvrjv /cal %aAe7rdT?yTa egtov 7re- ( pV/COTE ; Greek idiom. Compare the examples, ^a/leTrd or x^sir urepa opav ; also such phrases as padta paOelv , uaha ideiv, Aoyof dwarog KCiravorj- cat , T/diorr/ niveiv , at-ia ftavpaocu, and others, which are generally ex- pressed in Latin by the supine, difficile visu, mirabile dictu, &c. In such cases, of an infinitive dependent on an adjective, the Greek usage of the active, instead of the passive, corresponds to the Eng- lish idiom. As we say, hard to learn , cruel to behold, better to do, in- stead of better to be done, although some might regard this last ex- ample as hardly admissible. 4, 5. dv6pd)mva Tzpaypara deoGeSeoTarov. See Note XLIV., App. 6. fietiv KTr/para. See Note XLV., App. 7. ovpavov olov. This is here evidently put for the whole ani- mated universe, like Paul’s naoa tj ktlgiq, Rom., viii., 22, “ the whole creation, the whole creature world." GpuKpa 7 } peyaXa, “be they great or small.” See page 50, (8.) 8. ovderepug. “ In neither respect,” that is, whether you take the ground that we are small or great. empeleardTotg ye ovgi. The participle, in such connexions as this, often has the force of a con- ditional clause, “ if they are most provident," &c. 9. dp’ ova evavTiog. “ Have they not (that is, have not sense and power) reciprocally an opposite nature in respect to ease and diffi- E 2 54 CONTRA ATHEOS. KA. XIoj^* Xeyeig ; A0. 'Opav pev nov Kal aKoveiv ra opiKpd 10 ftaXeirurepov fj ra peyaXa • aotv oi XiOoXoyoi XiOovg ev kelgOgl. KA. Hug yap dv ; A0. M?) roLvvv tov ye fteov ai;id)OG)p,£v 14: nore 'Svtjtgjv dripLLOvpy&v (pavXorepov, oi tg npoorjtcovTa avrolg epya, docpnep dv dpeivovg gjgl, roocp dupideGTepa tc ai TeXeojTEpa pud TEXvrj Gpjh'pa nai p,eydXa dnepya^ovrat • tov 6e 'deov ovTa 15 te GocpdjraTOV, ftovXopievov t* empLeXelodaL teal dvva- bmpe^ovpevcp as a conditional clause, like empeTieGTaTOig ye ovoi , on which we remarked a short distance back. In this way deparzeveiv is governed by npooTeTaypevov. and avrip comes in easily in the order of the sense. 12. h Ttpekovpevid . . . upehovvTi. See Note XLVI., App. 13. dvev (j/u/eptiv. See Note XLVII., App. 14. 7 A ZiuGcopev. Some would here prefer the reading uZi&pev on account of the particle pfi], which, it is contended, cannot be joined with the 1st aorist subjunctive active. To this rule of the gramma- rians there are, however, so many cases in direct opposition, that it may well be doubted whether the common reading should be chan- ged on account of it. See many of these cases, Matthiae, Gr. Gram., 728, and the emendations by which he proposes to make them con- form to this rule. 15. tov 6e deov ovtcl. This is to be connected with drjpuovpyCiv (pavlorepov above. Had it immediately followed, it would have re- quired only the connective re in prjre, and would probably have read thus : prjre to'lvw tov ye d-eov d^ioiGupev tzote -d-VTjTCjv 6r)fuovpyC)v av?ioTepov elvat, prjTe -deov ovtcl (a ^LGiGopev), &c. “ Let us not deign to think that the Deity, of all others, is inferior to mortal workmen, nor that, being a God most wise, with the will and the power, &c\, he should take no charge of those small things, the care of which is sc 56 CONTRA ATHEOS. .jiEvov, gjv pev paov rjv empsXrjdrjvat opiKptiv ovrcSv , prjda- arj empeXelcdat, aaOdnep apybv rj detXov riva did irovovi * padvpovvra , tg)V 6e peyaXw 1 — KA. Mrjdapcog dogav rotavrrjv irepi detiv, G) %eve, ano * dexrifieOa • ovdaprj yap ovre ooiov ovr 9 aXrjOeg dtavorjpa dtavooiped ’ av. A0. A onovpev 6e pot vvv 7]6rj paXtora perp'uog 2 dieiXex- 6 at rep (j)iXatTt(p rfjg dpeXetag nept tietiv. easy,” &c. The 6s in this case is occasioned by the parenthetical or explanatory clause, ol tu npocyKovTa, &c. There is an opposition, or, rather, contrast between this clause and what follows, and this contrast is denoted by de, which, in consequence of its position and relation to a subordinate part, appears harsh and difficult to be rendered. It is a rule in English composition, that there should be no grammatical dependence between a parenthesis and the other members of a period ; or that it should be so introduced, that it may be taken out without altering the grammatical relation of the other parts. The propriety of such a rule may be doubted. At all events, the Greek writers allowed themselves much more freedom in the construction of their periods ; and hence the frequent occurrence of what grammarians style anakoloutha , and suspended sentences. Per- haps, on the whole, it would be better thus to regard the passage be- fore us as suspended, for the sake of the stronger impression. After speaking parenthetically of the exact care exercised by human artists, the writer breaks out in the following unfinished contrast: “But that God, being most wise, possessed of power and will, &c-., should neglect small things like some idle and cowardly being, while he concerns himself about the great” — The impatient and characteris- tic interruption of Clinias then comes in with admirable effect — No, we can hold no such opiniem ; we can entertain no such false and unholy sentiment. In this way far more power is given to the sentence than could be imparted by the most perfect regularity. 1. Ttbv <5£ ysfalov. “While he does concern himself about the greater.” See the remarks on the best mode of rendering^ in cer- tain cases, page 49, 5 and 50, 7. 2. psrplog. “ Properly, both in manner and degree.” r<5 (j>i?icuTup rye apsldag irepL ftstiv. “ The one who loves to impute neglect to the Gods — who querulously arraigns the Divine Providence.” Ordo — < i>ihaLTL(p ds&v nspl ryg aps^slag. CONTRA ATHEOS. 57 KA. N at. A0. Tg5 ye pid&oOai 3 rolg Xbyoig opoXoyelv avrov pi) Xeyecv . KA. ’OpOtig. 4 A0. ’Encpddjv ye prjv rcpoodelodai pot done l pvOcov en TLVU)V. KA. II 0 L 6 )v, d) ’y aOe ; A0. Ueldojpev rov veavi'av rolg Xoyoig, dig rep rov tt av- rog empeXovpevcp rrpog rrjv ocjTTjpiav nal dperrjv rov oXov f ndvr > earl ovvreraypeva , 5 d)v nai to pepog elg dvvaptv enaorov to npoorjfcov nao^ei Kal noiel. rovroig d’ eiolv dpxovreg TTpooreraypevoi 6 endorotg ent to opL/cporarov del ndOrjg real rcpa^ecog, elg pepiopov rov eoxarov reXog direipyaopevoi - 7 d)v ev teal to gov, d) o^erAte, popiov elg 3. rtj ye pidgeadat. See Note XLVIII., App. 4. bpOtiq. Stephanus, whom Ast follows, and whom Eusebius and Ficinus seem to countenance, would connect opOibq with the pre- ceding leyeiv , making the whole, from rw ye to en tivuv, the lan- guage of the Athenian. Alioque Xeyeiv, sine hoc adverbio quern usum hie haberet ? STEPH. Xeyeiv itself, however, in the sense of “ speaking improperly,” or of “ saying nothing to the purpose,” is so common in Greek, that we much prefer the vulgar text, which gives opd&q to Clinias, making it very similar to the reply of the same speaker, page 49 (3), bpOoTara ye elndv, on which we have remark- ed. There is great vivacity, and much that is characteristic of the simple-hearted Clinias in this interrupting assent. It is principally directed to the word Pia&oOai, and intimates that, in his view, the argument had been perfectly irresistible, so that nothing more need be added. As much as to say — you are most correct in declaring that you have forced him ; your argument is, indeed, most triumphant. And then this brings on very naturally the subsequent reply of the chief speaker : “ And yet there seems to me to be need in addition of something of a more persuasive kind.” tlv&v errudfiv. 5. owreraypeva. Not simply “appointed by” (although this sense is included), but “ so arranged as to co-operate (gw) with the uni- versal guardian.” 6. upxovreq. See Note XLIX., App. 7. uTetpyaGpevoi. This word must have here the sense of consh • 58 CONTRA ATHEOS. to nav gvvTELvei /3Xenov* aei, na'tnsp navoptnpov ov. os fie X sXrjOs nspi rovro avro cog yevsotg 9 svsna snstvov yiyvs- tcu 10 naoa , oncjg fj rj rep rov navTbg [ 3io ) vnapxovoa svfiat- pux)v ovoid , ovx evsna oov 11 y tyvopsvrj, ov fie svsna snsi- vov. nag yap iarpog nai nag svrsxvog firjptovpyog navrog pev svsna navra spya^erai, npog to noivrj £ vvrelvov 12 [3eX- tlotov • pspog prjv svsna oXov nai ovx o^ ov pepovg svsna dnspya^srai. ov fie dyavanrslg , dyvoebv on?]' 3 to nspi os apiorov rip navTL ^vpbaivst nai ooi naTa fivvaptv 14 ttjv Trjg noivrjg yevsoscog . snsi fie del ^vx?) ovvTSTaypsv'rf 5 oco- paTL tots psv aXXcp, tots fie dXXcp, psTabdXXsi navTotag psTadoXag fit’ eavTTjv * 1 rj fid erspav 'ipvx'fjv, ovfisv aXXo sp - tuted, appointed, or organized, although such an application is some- what unusual. Efc pepiapov rov £o x arov , “ to the most minute di- vision.” TeAof must be taken abverbially, as equivalent to teIeoq. *£lv must be referred to rovroig and Gwreraypeva. 8. t-wreivei pTLeirov. “ Looking tends.” The participle, being a favourite part of speech with the Greeks, is often thus used in con- nexion with a verb ; in this manner becoming equivalent to two verbs in English, as though it were (3X£n ei nai reivei. 9. Yeveaig. See Note L., App. 10. 11, 12, 13. See Note LI., App. 14. Kara dvvapiv, &c. “According to the power of the common generation,” that is, as far as it is possible for both these ends to be jointly accomplished, viz., the good of the individual and the good of the universe at the same time. 15. GvvTeraypsvrj. The common reading here is Emreraypevip We have, however, followed Eusebius and Stephanus, who refers to several old manuscripts as authority. 'Lwreraypevr) makes a much better sense, and is much better adapted to the context. It may be rendered here, “ soul appointed to act in co-operation with body.” 1. 6i’ kavrrjv. “By its own internal action.” bi’ erepciv \pvxyv “ Through the influence of another soul.” This is one of those cases in which bid with the accusative would be said to signify the instrumental cause, a sense which it generally has with the genitive. Even here, however, we may perceive a difference. It denotes a spiritual instrumentality, either of soul upon itself, or of one soul upon another, and may, perhaps, be more appropriately rendered by reason CONTRA ATHEOS. 59 yov Tx£Lv ts nai notslv a npoorjnov dpav eon rolg npoocpe- pECL rovg npooepspslg . 5 ravrrjg rrjg dtnrjg ovre ov prjnore ovre el aXXog arvxrjg 6 yevopevog in ev^rjrac nepiyeveodai 'ftecov. fjv nacrtiv dtnCav diatyepovrcog eraijav re oi rai-avreg, of the Platonic views in regard to the future blessedness of the soul , and the capability , which many parts of the Platonic writings possess , of be- ing accommodated to a higher system of truth. 3. kvrr} tol diKrj earl detiv ol v OAiyz7 tov cxovgl. This is an un- doubted hexameter line, evidently intended as a quotation. What immediately follows, although the language of the writer, and de- signed only for prose, is yet capable of being reduced to the same measure by a slight transposition, and by pronouncing tietiv in one syllable, as must frequently be done in the Greek poetry, 7 £2 nai nai veavioKE, Sokcjv vtco -&eC)v apeTiEioOaL. The Platonic writings furnish many examples of a similar kind, which by slight changes, and sometimes with no change at all, may be reduced to a pleasing rhythm. They were, in all probability, not designed, but flowed spontaneously from the well-tuned ear and har- monized spirit of this poetical philosopher. Nothing could more perfectly describe the exquisite softness and polish of his own Greek, than what he says of Theaetetus, in the dialogue of that name, page 144, B. : olov eXaiov fisvpa aipoc^yri fisovTog. 4. h TcdGL tiavaroLg. See Note LXI., App., on the mystical senses of this word. 5. npoGcpepcGL rovg npootyspeig. “ Like to like.” 6. urvxyg. Ficinus here evidently read evrvxyg without ri, for he renders the passage thus : Quare nec tu neque ullus alius optet confidatquc se adeo felieem fore ut judicium hoc Decorum effugiat atque exuperet. It is capable, however, of a very good sense according to the common reading. “Neither do you expect, nor if any other is in like unfortunate condition (that is, exposed to the Divine jus- tice), let him ever boast he shall escape (or survive) the justice of Heaven.” TlepLyeveodaL — superesse. The same lemarks apply to el here, as to ehrep, page 46 (14). It is equivalent to ovre dXXog arvx^g yevopevog , elnep egtl roiovrog, knev^yraL, &c. CONTRA ATHEOS. 63 Xp£& v e^evXa6elodai rortapdirav. ov yap dpeXrjOrjGrf irore vtt’ avrrjg. ovx ovtcj op,ucpog cov dvoq /card to rljg yrjg (3a0og , ovd’ viprjkog yevopsvog, elg rov ovpavov avan - rr/Gy ' riGEig ds avrtdv rrjv TrpoGrjtcovGav npcopiav, eit’ ev * Odds* i uevojv, site /cal ev "Albov dianopEvOsig , eite real tovtgjv Elg aypiG)TEpov eti dia/copiGdEig 7 8 9 totcov. o avrog ds Xoyog GOl fiat TTEpl EKEIVG)V aV Ell], TG)V, OVg GV KaTldojV E/C Gpi- uptiv psyaXovg ysyovorag , dvoGiovpyrjGavrag, f\ ri toiov- rov npd^avrag, (brjdTjg aOXitov svdaipovag ysyovevai , Kara, w$* ev /caronTpoig, 10 avrtiv raig npd&Giv, rjyrjGG) aa - 7. ov yap dpeTiijdfjGri ttote vn' avTjjg. ’Avryg refers here to AUcrj, or the Divine Justice or Law personified. See Note LXII., App., on the Divine Omniscience , and the remarkable resemblance between this passage and certain declarations of the Scriptures. 8. hOade. “In this world , or in Hades after having passed through ( bia — tt opevdelg) this world.” In the same way, ekei is often used for the other world. There is a power in these brief adverbs, when thus employed, that no descriptive terms could equal. They are several times used in this manner in the Gorgias, especially in the passage where Socrates is pointing Callicles to that final and Divine tribunal, where he will stand so much more in need of a de- fence and of an advocate, than in the Athenian courts — x aa M G V Kat i'kiyyiaoeiq ovdev yrrov rj hyd ’EN0AAE, ov ’EKEI — No less than 1 would HERE ( that is, before a human bar), will you be speechless and dizzy THERE. Gorgias, 527, A. With how much effect are they employed by Euripides, when Medea, in making her last address to her children, says so concisely, yet with such fulness of meaning : E vdaipovolrov • ’EKEI • rd S’ EN0AAE. Uaryp a^eOier’ : Would that ye might be blessed, but THERE ; all HERE Your father’s hand hath ruined. Medea , 1069. 9. dianofucdeig. The intensive sense of bid comes directly from its primitive local sense : through, thorough, significant of complete- ness. Here both offices unite : “ carried through all intervening states to the remotest bounds .” 10. 6g ev KaronTpoir, &c. “ In the events of their lives, as in mirrors, you think you have seen (reflected) the neglect of all things by the Gods.” This fine simile is exceedingly descriptive of these 64 CONTRA ATHEOS. OeGjpcucevai rr\v ndvrcov apeXetav tiecov • ova elddog avrcov rr\v GwreXetav, 11 orcrj rcore rep rravrl tjvpddXXercu. Tcy - vd)Gnetv de avrrjv , d) navrcov dvdpeiorare, ndog ov delv do- tcelg 5 r\v rig pi] ytyvd)GHG)v ovd' dv rvnov 12 idol nore , ovde Xoyov ijvpdaXXeoOat, nepl j3cov dvvarog dv yevoiro eig ev- daipovtav 13 re nal dvGdatpova rvx^v. ravra el pev gs m'l- who look only upon the surfaces of things, superficial men , dvdpeg imnd’kaioi. It suggests the similar comparison, by the Apostle James, of those “ who behold their natural faces in a glass hv kGOTTTpG), James i., 23. Upa^eciv avr&v. Not “their deeds,” but rather, “ the events of their lives,” namely, “ their seeming or super- ficial prosperity in the midst of all their crimes.” II paijig sometimes has almost the sense of nddog, and may mean a condition or state, thus differing from the derivatives of tzoleio, and even from most verbals of a similar form terminating in ig. As in the Trachiniae of Sopho- cles, 151 : Tor’ dv rig daidoiTO, tt\v avrov cnconfiv IIPAaIN, naKolaiv olg kyw f3apvvopai. Tlpu^ig is also a technical term, used in reference to the stage or tragedy. It is so applied by Aristotle, in his Art of Poetry, to that event which constitutes the leading action of the drama. There may be some such allusion here to human life, and especially the life of such as are here referred to, in the light of a drama, a tragic Trpc^cg, which has not yet been wound up, or come to its catastrophe, and the issue of which has not yet been seen. T rjv navrov dpeXeiav tiEtiv. The genitive, having a much more extensive significance in Greek than the corresponding possessive case in English, and em- bracing many more relations, frequently gives rise to constructions which appear to us very harsh. Thus here, ti-Efiv bears to dpekuav the relation of agent, while ndvruv has to it the relation of ob- ject. Instead, however, of governing them both by dpekeiav, it would, perhaps, be better to regard dew as an ellipsis for the more usual expression of the cause or agent, vtco tuv dew. 11. Ovk eidcog avrejv ttjv awTeheiav. See Note LXIII., App., on the doctrine of a final judgment. 12 . tvtzov. On the use of this word, see Note LXIV., App. 13. evdaipoviav . . . dvedatpova. The location and context of these words in this passage, and a few lines above (e£ adXiov evdaipoveg yeyovevai), furnish an admirable illustration of the remarks made Note XXXVIII., App., on the difference between happiness , in the usual CONTRA ATHEOS. 65 Oei K Xeivlag ode real ^vfinaoa rjfxtiv rjde r\ yepovoia , nepl ftetiv (bg ovtc oloOa o, ri keyeig, naXfbg dv ooi 6 tieog av- rog l4= ^vXXapdavoi • el d’ emderjg Xoyov rivog eri dv eirjg , Xeyovrcov v\\L(bv tt pog rov rpirov eiranove , 15 el vovv nal ottojgovv e^eig . on p,ev yap deoi re eloi nal avOpoyruv empieXovrai, eycoye ov rcavranaoi (pavXug 1 dv (pairjv rjpZv worldly sense of the term, and blessedness. The passage may be paraphrased : “ Without giving heed to this type of life, that is, with- out keeping in mind this general notion (see Note LXIV., App., on the word rvnov) of their contribution (ovvr&eiav) to the good of the whole, you will be able to form no right judgment respecting blessed- ness or its opposite.” Or, if we take the other view of Gwreksba, adopted in Note LXIII., App., and regard it as including the idea of end, consummation , final reckoning , &c., we then have a sentiment almost the same with the famous declaration of Solon to Croesus, related by Herodotus, lib. i., 32, and which sometimes appears in the tragic poets as an ancient saying ; as in the beginning of the Trachiniae of Sophocles : A oyog fiev egt ’ ’APXAIOS avOptinov (pavelg tig ovk dv aitiv * EK/idOoig fiportiv, npiv dv d-dvoi rig .... 14. 'O dsog avrog. There cannot be a doubt but that this is to be taken here in its purest and highest sense, as referring to the One Ineffable Supreme — the One True God of Socrates and Plato. “ The Deity himself, the very being whose existence and Providence we have been proving — may he assist you.” Had he referred in any way to the local Divinity of Athens or Pallas, he would have used the feminine avr 15. Tzpog rov rpirov enuKove. “ Keep listening (as the present im- perative here most impressively signifies) while we address our- selves to the third head of our argument.” This is evidently spoken not to the two companions who, with the speaker, formed the yepovoia mentioned above, but to the imaginary young disputant so frequently referred to. It has been shown, 1st, that GOD IS ; 2d, that he exercises a special Providence ; which two propositions are almost equivalent to what the apostle assigns as the objects of faith, Heb., xi., 6. It now remains to be shown that he is not easily propitiated, or turned away from the right, by the offerings and sacrifices of the wicked. 1. ov ravrdnaoi QavTiog. Tne speaker evidently looks back witb F 2 66 CONTRA ATHEOS. anodedelxOai, * rd 6e napaLrrjrovg av rovg Beovg elvcu rol - glv adiKOVGi de^opevovg dCopa, ovre tlvI ovy^coprjrsov ttclvtl * 2 r 9 av Kara dvvapuv rponcp eXey/creov. KA. KaXXtoF elneg • TroiCbpiv re chg Xeyeig. A0. $eps 6rj 3 4 * * * * npog tietiv avrtiv, riva rponov TrapaLTrjrol ylyvoiVT 9 av 4 fjplv, el yiyvoiv-o av ; teal riveg f( ttoIol ti- a good deal of satisfaction, to what he regards as his master-piece in this argument : the subtle disquisition about self-motion. On the word TrapaiTrjTovg , see Note XLI., App. 2. tzclvtI rpoTru. He seems to regard this as the most important position of the three, as being, in fact, more vital to the soul’s highest interests than any speculative belief in the Divine existence, or in a Providence without it. Hence, he says, “ there must be no yield- ing here, and no pains must be spared in the refutation of this per- nicious error,” namely, that the wicked can easily propitiate the Deity by gifts. 3. $epe by. Ay never wholly loses its force as an inferential par- ticle. It has, however, much less strength as an illative than ovv or apa. It imports in such a connexion as this, a going on of the argument, a transition to another head, with an implication that something previous had been proved in a solid and satisfactory man- ner. It implies, therefore, when thus employed in argument, a con- sciousness of strength, and an anticipation of victory. Hence, when joined with aye, epe, 7 l eye, or with imperatives generally, it has been most appropriately styled 6y hortativa. 4. ylyvoivr’ av. “Would they become propitiated or placable!” The use of yiyvoivTo instead of elev implies that they are to be re- garded as previously angry. There is in the Protagoras, 340, c., a still more striking example, in which the true sense wholly depends on the distinction between these two substantive verbs. It is there shown that the two propositions yevbodat, ayaOov, and ttov elvcu ayadov, instead of being the same, as Protagoras rashly sup* posed, are, in fact, so widely distinguished, that one is true and the other false. For a bad man to become good in his own strength is not, only difficult , but impossible. For one who has become, or who has been made good, or who is so by nature, TO BE good, is not only not diffi- cult, but delightful. Ov yap tovto 6 I IcrraKog b?ieye to TF.- NE20AI ecd'hov, cboTrep 6 2 ipuovtbyg, uTiXu, to 'EMMENAI. CONTRA ATHEOS„ 67 veg* ovreg ; dp^ovrag pev avaynalov nov yiyveoOai rovg ye diOLfirjGovrag 6 rov drcavra evreXeyfag 1 ovpavov. KA. OvTcog. 5. rives fj noZoi rives. “Who being, or of what kind being'!” In these two questions rives refers to the offices the Gods are supposed to hold to men, and noZoi rives to the nature of those offices, or the manner in which they are discharged. The answer to rives is con- tained in the word apxovras below. The answer to rcoZoi rives is suggested in the specification of the several kinds of rulers set forth. 6. diOLKrjGovras. “ Who are going to administer.” The future here is used, not in reference to the actual state of things, but sub- jectively, to the state of the argument. “ Who on our scheme are going, &c., or whom we are going to represent as actually adminis- tering.” So, also, the mathematician employs eo rat and eaovrai in the statement of his demonstration, although there is no sequence or futurity, except in the mode in which the mind conceives of the relations of truths, which in themselves are older than time or space. Subjectively, to the demonstrator, they may appear, and be stated as consequences yet future. 7. evrehextis- “ Actually , as opposed to potentially .” Correspond- ing to ev evepyeia , as opposed to ev Svvagei. Hence the noun ev - relexeia, so much used by Aristotle, as contrasted with <5 vvagis- Philologists have differed much about the etymology of this word. The derivation, however, from evrelys, perfect , complete , and fyw, seems satisfactory, both as respects form and meaning. That which exists only ev Svvdpe i is inchoate and imperfect : activity , energy ( avro - KivrjGLs) is its completion and perfection. The word actually , in Eng- lish, has come to signify not much more than truly , as matter of fact, and is therefore not a good representative of evrehex&s, although it is difficult to find any other substitute for it. There is another word, evSeTiex^ia, continuance , duration , which some confound with this, as is done by Cicero, Tusc. Disp., i., 22 : Quintum genus adhibet, vacans nomine ; et sic ipsum animum evrelex^tav (evdel exetav) ap- pellat, quasi quamdam continuatam motionem. The etymology of ev - Selexeia is very uncertain. Tov arcavra ovpavov i*s here put for the whole universe — the Heavens and all things they contain. It is very much like the Hebrew expression Sd nnrb as xxviii., 24: He looketh under the whole Heaven , or — CD'S# the Heaven of Heavens, that is, all space — the universe. 68 CONTRA ATHEOS. AO. ’AA/l’ apa rtot npoaepepelg tg>v apxbvrcov • }} rivtg rovrotg^ cjv 8 dvvarbv rjplv arteuia^ovoi rvyxaveiv psi^oatv eXarrovag ; norepov rjvcoxoi nveg av elev tolqvtol ^evycov apiXk copevcov, 7 / nXoicdv Kvdepvrjrat ; raxa de Kav aitemaa Oelev Grparonedcov dpxovot tlglv . elrj < 5 ’ dv teal vogojv no - Xepov 9 evXadovpevoig larpolg eoucevat nepl Gcopara, rj ye - (opyotg nepl (pvrdjv yeveoiv elojOvtag c opag x a ^ £7T dg did i bo6(j)v X0 npoodexopevoig • rj tzal noipvicov eniGTaraig. h tel- drj yap Gvytcex^prjtcapev * 11 rjplv avrolg elvai pev rov ovpa - vov noXXtiv peorov ayaOtiv, elvai de teal rtiv evavricov , n Xeiovoov 12 de rcbv prj , pax?} 13 dfp (j)apev, adavarog egtiv rj 8. gjv is genitive by reason of rvyxaveiv — quos assequi possimus, or, quorum compotes esse possimus. 9. vogov 7 Tolepov. The language employed above respecting con- tending chariots and commanders of camps, suggested the repre- sentation of the physician in the same style, as carrying on a war with diseases. In all this, however, he has in mind the allusion which soon follows to what he styles pdxv dOuvaroq , the grand and universal conflict between the powers of good and evil, on which we have dwelt at length, Note LXVI., App. E vlabeopae. “ To be careful , circumspect , cautious .” Hence to be timid, fearful , especial- ly to be occupied with religious dread, to be devout towards God; al- though in this last sense, as Prof. Hacket, in his Notes to Plutarch, De Sera Numinis V indicta, has well observed (page 92), it is seldom, if ever, found in classic usage. The primary conception of the w r ord, from ev and TirjSu, A apdavo, is to handle carefully, to touch with caution. 10. did 66ov. The common reading is did 66ov, which is certainly incor- rect. Compare the phrase <5t’ dnexOsiag, ASsch., Prom. Vine., 121. 11. kneidy ydp GvyKcxopyKapev. This admission could only have referred to the fact of the mixture of good and evil in the world, and which may be regarded as expressed in what is said page 32, line 3. Plato has in no other part of this book, except in the present passage, told us which he thought had the preponderance. 12. 7 tIelovwv de t&v prj. For an extended examination of this passage and the doctrine contained, see Note LXV , App. 13. pdxv adavarog. On this remarkable expression, see Note LXVI., App. CONTRA ATHEOS. 69 roiavTT] , nal cpvXanrjg a ^avpaarrig x4= deofievrj • f vppaxoi 6e rjplv ftsoL re a\ia nal 6aipovsg^ rjpslg 6’ av nrrjpara dstiv nal 6atpovo)v • (pQeipec 6s rjpdg a6inla nal v&ptq psrd deppo- ovvrjg • (jd)£ei 6s dtnatoavvif nal OGXppoavvr] psra (ppovrj- osevq, sv ralg rtiv tistiv sp'ipvxotg olnovoat 6vvapsoi. * 1 2 /3pa - %v 6s n nal rdyds av rtg tgjv rotovrcov svotnovv r\\uv cra- (psg l6ot, ipv%al 6rj rtvsg 3 4 sm yr]q oinovoat , nal a6tnov A rj* pa nsnrrjpsvat , drjXovorf ^pidjdstg, 5 npog rag r&v (pvX a< 14. See Note LXYI., App. 15. 'deol nal dalpoveg . . . icrypara ■deuv. See Note LX VII., App. 1. g ufri dLKcuoGvvri. See Note LXVIII., App., on the ancient division of the four cardinal virtues. 2. efj.ipvx°tg dwapecL. “Animated, spiritual, or moral powers and faculties,” in distinction from physical agencies, or what he else- where styles second working motions, or second causes. 3. xfjvxal dy nveg km yrjg. Ay, as an inferential particle, relates back to what precedes sir eidy yap, &c. What followed came in by way of parenthetical ejaculation, suggested by the previous meta- phorical allusions and mention of nohe/xog calling up to mind the great conflict of the universe, as presenting a bold and striking con- trast with the petty conceptions of the men whose doctrine he is disproving. He now returns to them, and resumes the more natural order of the argument, which had been interrupted. “ There are , then, (it seems), certain souls dwelling upon the earth,” &c., name- ly, such as would measure the Gods by themselves, and attribute to them all those imperfections and weaknesses which pertain to such earthly guardians and rulers as we have mentioned by way of com- parison. 4. dyTiovon. This is generally given as two words, dylov on. The construction, however, seems to require that it be taken and written as one : drj?i ovotl — as is clear, evidently, &c. 5. dypiudeig. There should, we think, be a comma after this word. The usual rendering, ferocious, would not here be in har- mony with such expressions as we have below — netdovGc dun date Tioyuv, nal kv evKTaiaig knudalg. It might much better be translated brutal, or, rather, brutish , referring not so much to the wildness and fierceness of their dispositions, as to the stupidity and beastly gross- ness of their conceptions. It is meant by these terms to indicate men who have no right notions, any more than the beasts, of theii 70 CONTRA ATHEOS. K(*)v 'iftvx&g apa kvvgjv , ?) ra^ rCbv vopicov, rj npdg rag rcov iravranaocv anporaroov deonorow npoGntirrovaat , ttelQov- true relations to God and the universe. Aristotle, in his Ethic. Nicomach., vii., 1 , seems to use the term in this sense, to denote a state as much below what is properly human as the Divine is above it ; although he applies the epithet to a class of men : wore rj ti-ela E^ig av eItj 6it}\ov6ti Trj 'ftypiufiELa uvtlOe[aevt). It would seem here to correspond well to the Hebrew ^ 3 , as used Psalm xlix., 11 ; lxxiii., 22 ; xcii., 7. Proverbs, xii., 1 ; xxx., 2 . The sentiment, Psalm xcii., 7, is strikingly in harmony with the whole train of thought in which Plato here indulges respecting the views such men entertain of the Divine justice. The brutish man (-^ 3 , ■&r}pi66rjg) knoweth not , and the gross man ( l 7 ' , D 3 fr° m carnosus pin guis fuit) understandeth not this , that when the wicked flourish , it is that they may be destroyed forever. To make 'ftypiudEig agree with Tpvxuc would be exceedingly harsh, not only in respect to the construction, but also as regard the sense. apa icwtiv. There is a peculiar force and elegance in this particle apa, when thus employed. The rj, which follows twice, justifies, as in similar cases, the supplying of another rj, or, rather, an eIte, be- fore it, and then it will be in all respects parallel to the Iliad, i., 65 : "Ejt’ ap' by EvxcoXfjc ETUfiEfityErai, eW’ EKaropbrjc- Hogeveen styles it, in such cases, apa conjecturalis. This, how- ever, is but little, if any, significant of its real force. Even in such an example it does not wholly lose its power of concluding. Neither, as he supposes, does it denote the reason why Apollo was angry. That he had reason for anger was taken for granted from the fact. Since he was angry, therefore the prophet was to tell the cause, wT.ether it was on account of a vow or a hecatomb. So, in this passage, we may render : “ Being evidently brutish, and approaching (or falling upon) their keepers, be they dogs or shepherds, or rulers of the highest grade, they would persuade them by flatteries, n &c. That is, since they are brutish ( therefore apa), it matters not to them whether they be dogs or shepherds, &c. : because they are of this gross and animal nature, they make no distinction between the highest and the lowest class of guardians, but'Stupidly imagine that they all may be influenced alike. Thus the inferential force of apa is felt in giving vividness and a great addition of meaning to the sentence, while yet it is free from the encumbrance and clogging ef- CONTRA ATIIEOS. 73 cl * * * * * 6 reiaig Xoycov, xal ev evxTaiaig tigIv enipdaig (chg at (jyrjpat (j)aocv al tu>v xaxtiv) e^eivai TrXeovexTovoi oepioiv ev dvOpdonoig rraoxeiv prjdev ^aAenw. (f)apev d’ elvai ttov to vvv ovopa^opevov apdpTrjpa rrjv nXeove^iav 7 ev pev oaprdvoig GivpaGi voarjpa xaXovpevov , ev de c5 paig erCov xai eviavT&>v Xoipov , ev de uoXeoi xal uoXiTeiaig , tovto av to prjpa peTea^paTLopevov , adixiav. KA. HavT&TtaoL pev ovv. A0. Tovto v dr} tov Xoyov avayxalov Xeyeiv , tov Xeyov - Ta 7/pec. A strong and earnest word of caution. “Be care- ful how you speak — speak words of good omen.” It was employed in the sacrifices to caution the people against the utterance of any inauspicious words during the religious rites. There is a very fine and impressive example of its use in the Republic, lib. vi., 509, B., where, at the suggestion of Glaucon, that 'H dovij, or Pleasure, might be The Good, Socrates cries out, EvtyTjpei,, “ utter words of good omen, or be cautious in your language intimating that there might be blasphemy in the very conception. The same feeling is excited here by the bare thought, that the course of the argument had re- quired him, however necessarily, to connect the mention of the Deity with such comparisons as had been used CONTRA ATHEOS. 73 A0. T ovg dr) ndXXiord re repay par a (j) vXdrrovrag , <5ia- v ye , and connect this (to ovrov ) with the preceding sentence. In accordance with which view he renders : Neque tolerabilis est haec oratio liomi - num in quovis impietatis genere versantium. There is no difficulty, however, in connecting rov (as in the common reading) with doebov following, if we may regard the repetition as arising from the length of the intervening clause, and also as intended to add force and . vehemence to the whole sentence. “ Of all those who are con- versant with every species of impiety, this man who so tenaciously holds to this opinion would, of all wicked men , most justly seem to be esteemed the worst and most impious.” ’ Avrexopevog , “ holding firmly to,” like one who braces himself against something for the purpose of giving tenacity to his grasp. The word implies that men cling much more obstinately to this doctrine than to Atheism, or even the denial of a Providence. By connecting rov re , or rov ye, with the preceding, we should also destroy the fine effect of the pas- sionate burst of indignation which is so characteristic of Clinias, and which is so forcibly expressed by the words ovdapoq, &c., when standing by themselves. K ivdvvevei, in this passage, may be regard- ed in the same light as at page 18 (2). See remarks on the word in that place. So, also, here the primary sense appears through the secondary. ‘‘ He is in danger of being judged, he runs a risk of be- ing thought, or he is liable to the imputation,” Ac. G 74 CONTRA ATHEOS. oav aoebetav oi tgjv ntvbvvevet Trojg o ravrrjg rr\g bofrjg av- rexopevog navrcov av rcov aoedcbv nefcpioOat butaiorara Hantorog re elvat nai aoebeorarog. AO. Td pev 6?) nporeOevra rpta , deot re cog slot, nai pEv hcavtig dnodE^elxOai nov. This is something like the • mathematician’s onsp eSel deigai, quod erat demonstrandum. It is the formal conclusion of the long argument or preamble to the law which is now to follow against those impious men, who have given the lawgiver so much trouble. 1. cQodporepov. This is said in reference to the apparently harsh epithets which have been used in this third branch of the discus- sion against those who abused the doctrine of the Divine placability, and especially to the strong language a few lines above. The other parts of the argument, instead of needing apology in this respect, were marked by a peculiar mildness towards his supposed perverse opponents. 2. a drj teal oca teal ola. “ Whatever things, and however enor- mous, and however bad.” 'Oca often, when the context requires it, is to be taken in a bad sense, implying not simply the number or quantity, but the enormity of the things referred to. So, also, ola not only imports quality, but sometimes a bad quality, of whatevci kind , that is however wicked. CONTRA ATHEOS. 75 AO. Merd to irpooipiov rocvvv Xoyoqf olog av two vo - poov epprjvevg, opOtiq yiyvoiTo fjpZv, npoayopevcjv e%Lorao- Oai iraoi rolg aoebeoi rponcdv tCov avrojv eig rovg eva edeZg. roZg de pi) rceidopevoig. doedeiag ode eoro) nepi vopog * ’E av rig aoeby Xoyoig sir ’ epyoig , 6 TraparvyxdvGJv apvveTG), orj- paZvcov 7 rpdg ap^ovrag • rtiv de dpxbvTO)v oi f npCi)TQi ttvOo - (. levoi , TTpog to nepi 4, tovtgjv anodedeiypevov npiveiv ditiaa- Trjpiov elaayaydvTCOv KaTa Tovg vopovg . eav de Tig anov- oaaa ap^rj pi] dpa TavTa , avTrj doede'iaq viroduwg yiyvecr- 6o) Tip edeXovTi TipoopeZv 3 4 5 vnep tcov vopcjv, eav de Tig cxpXq, TipaTG) to dmaoTrjpiov ev enaoTip 6 tcov naO’ ev aGedovvTCjv Tiprjpa. deapog pev ovv virapx^ro) navi, dec po)T7]piG)v de 7 3. pera to npootpiov ’koyog. The whole law is regarded as con- sisting of three parts : the preamble or argument, the declaration or exhortation, and the penalty. The first has occupied nearly the whole of the book, the second is despatched in a single sentence, and then all that remains is to specify briefly the several punish- ments for the several grades of impiety. 4. Tcpog to nepi. Ordo — etoayayovTov npog to dmacTripiov dnode- deiypevov Kpiveiv nepi tovtov. The tribunal here referred to may be found described in the ninth book of the Laws, 855, D. 5. Tipopelv vnep. “ To avenge the law.” It sometimes has this same sense with the dative : Tipupelv tivi , “ to avenge any one.” In the middle voice, “to take revenge, or to avenge one’s self.” The noun npopia, as well as Ttotg , generally has reference to vin- dictive, in distinction from preventive or remedial punishment. 6. ev enaaTip. Ast would read here ev e/caorov. The construc- tion, in the common reading, is somewhat unusual, but not suffi- ciently so to justify the correction proposed. Tiprjpa would mean, originally, an estimate , a fine ; but it is applied to any species of pun- ishment, and may be rendered here, generally, pocnam or pcenas. Ordo — TipuTG) to dmaGTrjpiov Tiprjpa ev eKaoTcp tuv /cad’ ev acjedovvTav , equivalent to saying — in each individual case of each, or according to each particular offence. 7. deopoTrjpiov de. This is the common reading. Stephanus and Ast would put a comma after navi, read ye for de, and thus connect the whole of this, down to tyrjprjv tivu, as an appendage to the pre- ceding short sentence. Without this, it is said, the sense must re* main suspended. It may be a question, however, whether this con 76 CONTRA ATHEOS. OVTGJV EV TXf noXet TpitiV, kvog fJLSV, ttotvov 9 rocg nXsiOTOig Tcepl ayopav , ourrjpLag evekcl rotg rtoXXolg rcov dcopdrojv, kv'og 6e , nepl rov rco v vvtcroop ovXXeyop,evG)v %vXXoyov, oco- c ppoviorrjpiov 9 ETrovopa^opEvov , kvog 6s av Kara pkorjv tt)v %o )pav, omjTTEp av sprjpog te teat oyg on paAtora aypccjjra- rog q Tonog , rtpcoptag e^^v kncovvptav cjirjprjv * 11 rtva. nspl sideration alone is sufficient to justify the change, although so slight. Such cases of suspension do occur in the Platonic writings, in places where all efforts at correction fail ; and in the present case some might suppose even the irregularity to be more tolerable than the attaching so long an appendix to so short a clause, and by so feeble a connective. We would suggest, moreover, whether it would not be better to connect this with 7r ept aoebetav ds dvrov be- low. There is, it is true, something awkward in making the enu- meration of offenders an apparent inference from the number of prisons, yet still there is something of a natural connexion between the two ideas, so that the one might easily suggest the other, al though in an inverted order. 8. koivov rots 'kAelotols. “ Common to the people at large,” that is, to the ordinary class of offenders. 'ZcoTr/ptag h>Ena rcov ooparov. This is precisely the phrase of the English common law — -for the safe keeping of the body- — in corporis custodiam. 9. GutypovioTripLov. The police prison , or, more properly, the house of correction, the place where lawless people are sobered. 10. oTzrf'KEp. “ In the very spot in which.” (!>? on paAtora ayptd- rarog. These particles, thus combined, form the strongest superla- tive in the power of the Greek language. The three are seldom found in this manner in one expression. It may be styled a double super-superlative. 11. ETzovvyiav Qrjpyv. ^ypijv here may be regarded as having the force of an adjective— famosam. Or it may be rendered, “ having in common fame (Kara tyrjpriv), or by common report, the appellation,” &e. The first prison was for safe custody ; the second for correc- tion, discipline, or reformation ; the third, the prison of vengeance (npwpiac), of strictly penal restraint, intended for examples, and not for the good of the offender. Plato seems to have in mind the de- partments in Hades, which he specifies in the Gorgias, and to rep- resent human laws as proceeding by the same grades with their brethren of the other world : oi yperepot adeAQoi, oi hv Atdov NOMOI, as he styles them in the Crito, 54, C. This prison would be analo- gous to that division in Hell to which the avia-rot, or incurable , are CONTRA. ATHEOS. 77 aoedeiav 6e ovtuv , 12 alriaig psv rpioiv, alonep real dirjXOo- pev, dvo d’ eg kndarr\g rr]£ roiavrrig alrtag y evopsvcov, Sl- av yiyvoivro , a real dianpioecog a$ia yevrj rcbv irepl rd dela dpapravovrcov , ovtc torjg oi>d’ opo'iag dittrjg deopeva. olg yap dv prj vopi^ovoi deovg elvai ronapanav , fjdog cpvoei rrpocr- yevrjrai duiaiov , piGovvreg re y'lyvovrai rovg nanovg , nal to dvo^epaiveiv 13 rrjv aditdav , ovre rag roiavrag npa^eig npoatevrat nparreiv , tov^* ts prj dinacovg tgjv avOpcbnoiv < pevyovot , /eat TOt>£ duiaiovg crepyovoiv • olg 6 ’ av 7rpd^ tt/ <56^ r?/ $£65^ eprjpa 1 * elvai irdvra, anpdreiai 15 re rjdovcov consigned as everlasting admonitions, and spectacles of the Divine vengeance : drexvug napaSetypara dvyprypevovg ticet tv A ISov tv ru AE2M12THPK2I, dsapara teal vovderrjpara. Gorgias, 525, C. 12. nepl dasSetav St ovreov. An elliptical mode of expression, which may be thus rendered : “ Those who are conversant with impiety, be- ing so from three causes which we have described, and there being two classes from each such cause, there would be, of those who of- fend against Divine things, six kinds worthy of discrimination, and requiring neither an equal nor a similar sentence.” 13. r<5 Svg xepaivstv. “ By having a disrelish for wrong doing,” that is, a dislike arising from habit, prejudice, or an early bias of the mind remaining in spite of their Atheism. 14. $efiv epypa. Nothing could convey a more vivid idea of the horrors of Atheism than this expression. Every meaning of the word Iprjpa crowds at once into the serious mind ; a universe de- serted , lonely , solitary , waste, forsaken — a wilderness full of horror and desolation in proportion to its boundless extent. Probably the best antidote to Atheism, when it happens to invade the mind, and more effective than any speculative argument, would be to yield up the soul for a season to the deep gloom of so insupportable a thought. Of course we mean not the hardened and scoffing Atheist, but one to whom the most transient shade of skepticism on this point is a source of pain. To quote again the line of Empedocles, we may well say, in reference to such a one, detkog d’ c5 oKOTosccra tiefiv nipi dofa peprjlev. The expression $e£)v eprjpa seems used here by Plato as an an- tithesis to that of Thales, referred to page 41, tietiv elvai nTiypy navra. 15. i iKpuretat . See remarks on this word in connexion with au* typoGvvy cacohaGLa, &c., Note LXVIII., App. G 2 78 CONTRA ATHEOS. teal Xvtx£)v irpoGnsGcoGi, pvrjfiat ts la^vpal teal paOrjastg o^slai napcoGL, to psv pi) vopi^siv tisovg apepolv 1 dv sv vnap^OL teoivov naOog * Tyj 6 s to )v akXcov av 0 pd) 7 TG)v Xd) 6 xj, to psv eXaTTG), to 6 s tcXslg) teatea spya^oiT 1 av. 6 psv yap Aoycp* ts av nspl tisovg napprjoiag sir] psGTog teal nspl tiv- otag ts teal opteovg , teal c bg tcov a/ iXcjv teaTaysXcbv tci %* dv sTspovg TOiovTOvg anspya^oLTO, dltcrjg pi) Tvyxdveov • 6 6 s 6 r) 6 o%d£(i)v 2 psv teaOansp aTspog , sv(j)vi)g 6 s snueaXovps- vog , 60 H 0 V 6 s teal svs 6 pag nX rjprjg, s% &v pavTstg ts teaTaa- Ksva^ovTat noXXol teal nspl ndoav tt)v payyavsiav testeevr)- psvoc . 3 yiyvovTai 6 s s£ avTtov sgtlv ots teal Tvpavvot teal 6 rjprjy 6 poi teal OTpaTrjyoL, teal TsXsTalg 6 s I 6 iaig smbsbov- XsvteoTsg , 4 GoepiGTcbv ts snueaXovpsvGiv prjxavae . 5 6 7 tovtcjv 6 i) noXXd i usv sl 6 r] ysvoiT 9 dv • rd 6 s vopcjv a^ta tisosug 6 vo , &v to psv sipG)viteov 6 to ovx evog ov 6 s 6 volv a^ta 'davcLTOiv 1 dpapTavov , to 6s vovOsx'rjGscog dpa teal 6 sGpcbv 1. ujLLcpolv. This word relates back to the preceding sentence, not- withstanding it had been apparently fully closed and takes in both classes, as far as they hold the atheistic sentiment in common al- though with different practical results. 2. 6 pev yap loyu. See Note LXXII., App., on the different spe- cies of Atheists, according to the Platonic division. A o£d&v .... EV(j)vr/g. See Note LXXII., App. 3. KEKivripivoL. “ Who are most strenuously and violently en- gaged in every species of juggling or legerdemain.” 4. ettlSeSovTievkote^. Not simply “ those who attempt private mysteries,” mysteria privata molientes , as some render it, but, rather, “those who, by means of such mysteries, plot to deceive other men.” We would, therefore, regard TsXEraig as the dative of the instrument. 5. p7ix avai cotyLGT&v. The abstract is used here for the concrete. It is an expression equivalent to ol ralg pr)x ava go^lgtcjv xpdpEvoi, “ those who use sophistical arts.” 6. to psv EipidviKov . See Note LXXII., App. 7. ovx &OQ ovd e dvolv tiavaToiv. That is, either one or two deaths would be too small a punishment for him. No one will think this sentence too severe, who has carefully studied those specimens of CONTRA ATHE08. 7'J ( hopEVov. coodVTug 6 e* /cal to dsovg vopi&iv a^eXelv 6v ’ erepa yevva , nai to TTdpdLTTjTOvg dXXd dvo. tovtcov 6t) tclvtxi 6l£Ott]ic6tg)v, Toi)g p£V vn ’ avotag , avev ndurjg dpyrjg te ^ yeyevrjpevovg, eig to ococppoviOTrjpiov 6 diK.ao- Ti)g TiOepevog vdj pep, tlOeoOco prjdev eXclttov etlov ttevte. ev tovtg) d's tgj XP° VC P p^Elg tcov ttoXltc)v dVTolg dXXog ovyyiyvEodo), TrXfjv oi tov vvKTEpivov %vXXoyov 9 kolvgj- VOVVTEg , E7TL VOvPeTT[GEI TE KCLL T%f TTjg 'IpVX^ 0(0T7]ptd Opi- XovvTEg . 10 otclv (T 6 XP° V0 S a vToZg e^eXO^ tCov dEoptiv, kciv piv 60 KXI ri S OG)(j)pOV£CV dVTGJV , olfCELTG) p£Td T(x)V OGXj)pO - this abominable character to which we have referred, Note LXXII., App. 8. tJGavTuc tie. The doctrines, that there was no special Provi- dence, and that the Gods were easily propitiated, gave rise also, each respectively, to two species of offenders, distinguished by characters analogous to those above presented, and. requiring each a different mode and gradation of punishment ; the mildest form of which was to be imprisonment in the GoQpovLGTrjpLov, or house of correction, for a term not less than five years. Such a law, among us at the present day, would be thought greatly to infringe on men’s religious liberties — on the precious right to be an Atheist or blas- phemer. 9. wfcrepivov guXXoyov. See Note LXXIII., App. 10. ki n vovOerriGec re Kal ry ryg 'ipvxyg Gurypta ofuhovvreg. “ Con- versing with them for admonition, and for the salvation of the soul.” It is interesting to meet thus in a heathen writer with that very expression with which from infancy we have been accustomed to as- sociate the most sacred ideas of Christianity. We may, perhaps, have given it too much of a Scriptural aspect in our rendering of Gorypia , — the term, as thus presented by Plato, being undoubtedly to be taken in a somewhat lower sense — yet still, with all qualifications, what an immense difference does such language, employed in such connex- ions, make between him and all other philosophers and legislators either of ancient or modern times. The phrase Gurypca Tpvxyc seems also to have been intended by way of antithesis to the expression GtdTrjpLCLQ cuparog, some distance back, page 76 (8). In this view, the aucfipoviGTTjpiov was not only intended, in corporis custodio.m lor the safe keeping of the body , but also for the well-beings health , m salva- tion of the soul. 80 CONTRA ATHEOS. vg)v • eav 6s firj , depstXxi & avQig rrjv rotavr7]v dlfcrjv , tiavd- rep £ rjfuovoQu ). ogol d’ av '&7]pLd)6sig 11 ysvcjvrat npog rep &£oi)g i ill) vopi^stv rj apEXslg rj 7TapatT7]rovg elvai , nara- (ppovovvreg 6s tgov avQp g)tto)v 'ipvxayuytiGt, 10 psv noXXovg tQ)v (juvrcjv rovg 6s rsdvscdrag aanovreg 'ipyx^yo^yslv^ nal tieovg vmGxvovpsvoi Ttsidsiv , r) viag ev novrep Kpovidr/g anoTtvvrai avr&v. .^AA EXTENDED NOTES AND DISSERTATIONS, SUGGESTED BY PASSAGES IN THE TEXT, ON SOME OP THE PRINCIPAL POINTS OF THE PLATONIC PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY, ESPECIALLY AS COMPARED WITH THE HOLY SCRIPTURES ; TOGETHER WITH SOME EXPLANATIONS OP DIFFICULT PASSAGES AT GREATER LENGTH THAN WOULD BE CONVENIENT IN MARGINAL OBSERVATIONS. vwnaa vwvyv . \ EXTENDED NOTES AND DISSERTATIONS. r. The Platonic View of the Parental and Filial Relations , and the Ancient D.octrine generally on this Subject. Page 2, Line 8. ’E^ 6e yoveag. A misconception of the end and scope of the Republic, or, as it should be more properly styled, The Dialogue on the Nature of Right or Righteousness (rtepl dutaiov ), has subjected the name of Plato to great reproach. He has been charged with main- taining, in the fifth book of that dialogue, sentiments which, if carried out, would result in the utter overthrow of all the domestic relations. A defence, had we space for it here, might be derived from the peculiar parabolical or allegorical nature of that work, and from the evident absence of any design that it should serve as the model of any actual ex- isting polity. Whether, however, this be regarded as a right view of the Republic or not, and whatever we may think of the justice of the charge to which he may there be thought to have exposed himself, there can be no doubt that in this treatise (nepl vopwv), in which he means to ap- pear in the character of a serious legislator for a really practicable , if not existing state, he takes special pains to remove the reproach to which, even in his own day, he had been subjected on account of the passages referred to This long dialogue on legislation was the work of his old age, and in it he strives to set in the highest light the sanctity of the domestic, and especially the filial and pa- 88 PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE rental relations. For the strongest proof of this, we might refer, among many other passages, to what is said in the ninth book, 881 , A., and especially to that most striking and beautiful passage, lib. xi., 931 , A., in which he speaks of the veneration of children towards their parents as a re- ligious. rather than a merely moral or political duty, and not only this, but also as involving acts partaking of the na- ture of religious worship. We would recommend to the student the close study of the whole argument, not only for its exceeding moral beauty, but also as a most triumphant refutation of the charge that Plato, like some modern re. formers, would have destroyed the family state. Tovscjv 6s dfisXelv, ovrs $£ o g ovrs avOpconog vovv e%G)v ^vpibovXog 7TOTG ysvoir ’ dv ov6sig ovdev'i. (j)povr]aai 6s xprj rrepi tietiv, tc. r. X. In this passage he not only sets in the highest light the sanctity of the relation, and of the duties resulting, but would deduce from it a method of indirectly reforming the grossness of some parts of religious worship, by sub- stituting the holy feeling of filial veneration for the idola- trous adoration household images of the Gods. He would have their place occupied by the venerable living form of the aged sire or grandsire, as the household ayaX- pa, or image of the Eternal Father. UarTjp ovv orcp real fXTjTTjp rj tovtcov narspeg rj [irjrspsg sv oIklcl uslvrai fcstfirj- Xlol CLTTSCpTjKOTsg yijpa, prjbslg 6iavo7]drjTG) n otg ayaXpa aVTCO, TOLOVTOV S(j)SGTLOV l6pV\LCL SV olu'iCb pLCbXXoV Kvpcov sgsgOcu, sdv 6ij Kara rponov ye opOcbg avro depa- 7 tsvxi b Keurriiievog . “ If any one hath a father, or mother, or grandparents worn out with age, and laid up as sacred relics in his house, let him never suppose, as long as he possesses this altar of the domestic hearth, that any other dyaXpa or sacred image is more worthy of his adoration, provided he knows how to worship it aright.” And again, 931, D., ’0 vkovv biavorjOtifiev d>g ov6sv TTpog 'Sscov repov ayaXfjia dv KTrjGaifJLsda rrarpog real rrpondropog n a- FILIAL RELATION. 89 peifievcov yrjpa na) prjrepcov rrjv avrrjv dvvaiuv ex ov(7( ^ v — ov( ; ogov ayaXX't] rig npalg yeyrjQev o $ eog. “Let us, then, believe that we can have no religions image more pre- cious in the sight of Heaven than a father, or grandfather, or mother worn out with age, and that in proportion as we honour or delight in them with a religious joy (so ayaX- Xq, whence ayaXfia, may be rendered here , as in Pindar , Olymp ., i., 139), in the same proportion does God himself rejoice.” If this is idolatry, it is certainly far more inno- cent than that which is practised by the professedly Christian Church of Rome. What a beautiful and affect- ing picture is here presented ! The aged and infirm parent not only revered in the secret sanctuary of the heart, but actually regarded, if not as the very household deity of the secluded domestic temple, yet, in truth, as the best visible representation or eltccov , through whom homage was to be rendered to the Invisible God. Sophocles seems to have had in mind something of this same beautiful conception in the Antigone, 703 : T t yap narpog '&aXXovrog, svtcXeiag tskvolq ’'ATAAMA j uel^ov ; There is not the same high meaning to dyaXpa here as in Plato, although in other respects the language is striking- ly similar. It more strongly resembles Proverbs, xvii., 6 : □nnx lZPJS mXDn> where the Hebrew word mxsn has r — ; • r V V : • t t • # a striking affinity to the Greek ayaXpa, being like it, too, used in a religious sense, as in Psalm lxxviii., 61, where it is applied to the ark of the covenant. As a consequence of this religious relation, Plato attaches great importance to the blessing and curse of a parent, and in this he is in accordance with one of the most ancient and universal doctrines that have ever prevailed among mankind. After reciting the examples of Theseus, CEdipus, and Amyntor, he thus proceeds : apalog yap yovevg knyovoig H 2 90 PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF TIIE dig ovdeig erepog aXkoig dLnaiorara, 931, C. “For the curse of a parent (to give a free rendering) comes loaded with calamity to children in a way that is true of no other relations.” Wherefore, as he says in another passage, nag drj vovv (frodelrai teal npa yoveuv ei>xdg, eldcbg noXAoig nai noXXdmg emreXelg yevopevag , 931 , A. “ Every one that hath reason both fears and honours the prayers of parents, knowing well that often, and to many, have they been fulfilled.” How deeply this sentiment was impressed upon the minds of the Grecian poets, and how important an element it forms of their most tragic representations, we may learn from the dismal effects and long train of calam- itous consequences which they set forth as following the imprecations of CEdipus upon his unnatural sons. The sad story of Hippolytus, who, although innocent, is repre- sented by Euripides as perishing under a father’s impreca- tion, exhibits the same doctrine, although in a most pervert- ed and distorted form. The dying cry which the poet puts into the mouth of the wretched young man, d) narpog epov dvarrjvog dpa , shows how awful was the calamity which the ancient world universally regarded as involved in a parent’s curse. The converse doctrine, namely, the importance of the parental blessing, is certainly one of the most clearly taught truths of the Old Testament. How consonant it is, both with the language and spirit of Scripture, no one need be told who recollects the value attached to the blessing of the Patriach Isaac, and the declarations of the dying Jacob to the twelve heads of Israel, besides many other passages which are founded upon the same idea. It was a prominent principle in all the ancient systems of law and religion that the relation of parent and child gave rise to religious , rather than merely civil obligations. Hence Aristotle says, eotc d’ rj pev npog yovelg (\uXia tek- voig tig avOpunoig npog fieovg * rov yap elvat nal Tpacprjvai FILIAL RELATION. 91 cm.ot, teal yevofievotg rov tt cudsvOrjvcu. Ethic , Nicomach . , viii., 12, 5. They belonged to the class of duties styled '6(ua, in distinction from those that were only diicaia , and their violation was regarded among offences committed directly against Heaven. Something of this feeling has come down and affected even modern languages. Hence we speak of filial piety or impiety. On this account the Bible makes this relation the subject of the first command- ment immediately following the direct duties we owe to God, and hence, too, the Jewish law punished the crime with such unrelenting severity, as though, if permitted to pass with impunity, it would be the fruitful source of every viola- tion, both of the laws of Heaven and Earth. The filial and parental tie seems to have been regarded as a continuation of that which bound us to God, and hence, in strictest har- mony with this view, Plato regards the man who had sun- dered the latter as having utterly annihilated the duties and obligations of the former. On this account, as we have seen in a passage on which we have already commented, page 8 1 , the children of the Atheist were to be regarded as orphans, and placed under the care of the state. The importance of this relation in a political point of view, may be inferred from the fifth commandment itself. The promise annexed has generally been referred to indi- viduals. It appears to us, however, to have more of a po- litical aspect, and to be addressed to the nation collective- ly. The language certainly seems to favour this idea : “ that thy days may be long in the land which the Lord thy God giveth thee intimating that the long continuance of their national polity in the land of Canaan would depend, more than on anything else, on the preservation of this fund- amental conservative article ; on the reverence with which this duty should be regarded, as forming the connecting link between the civil and the more purely religious, and as being the source and guarantee of every inferior domestic 92 PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF TIIE and political obligation. For undoubted examples of the same and similar language, used in the national instead of the individual sense, see Deuteronomy, iv., 2G, 40 ; v., 30 ; vi., 2. In accordance with this universal sentiment of antiquity, Plato, in the passage at the beginning of these remarks, and in other places in the Laws, enumerates duties to parents as immediately succeeding those which are owed to God, and ranks their violation as next in enormity to public and private sacrilege. Compare the fourth book of the Laws, 717, B., and especially a most remarkable pas- sage in the ninth book, 881, A. : Ilarpc^ yap rj prjrpbg i) rovrcov ere 7 Tpoyovcov bang roXprjoet a\pao0ai u ore /3ca%o- pevog alicta tlvc, prjre tgjv avo) deioag 'deebv prjviv, prjre tCjv vtto yrjg npopiCdv Xeyopevuv, dXXd tearaeppovtiv rcbv 7 raXatcov nai vno irdvrov elprjpevov rrapavopel , rovrep del TLVog anoTponrjg eoxdrrjg. $ avarog pev ovv ovk eonv eax^TOV, oi de ev f/ A idov tovtolol Xeyopevoi ttovol , &c. ‘‘If any one shall dare to treat with violence father or mother, or any one of his or their progenitors, having before his eyes neither the fear of the powers above, nor of the vengeance of the world beneath, but, despising the ancient and universal traditions of mankind, shall break through all law, for such a one there is need of some most extreme remedy. Death, then, is not this greatest or most extreme remedy, but something still beyond this, even those pains of Hell which are said to await these enormous offenders.” The whole passage is full of dreadful meaning, which can with difficulty be transferred to the English. We have no word which comes up to the Greek dnorponf. It is ap- plied to the most solemn religious act by which we may avert the wrath of Heaven for some enormous wickedness, and hence the terms anorponaiog , drcorpomaGpog , inauspi- cious , that which is to he averted hy sacrifice , an expiation or turning aivay of the Divine wrath , and, in a secondary FILIAL RELATION. 93 sense, whatever is most odious or an utter abomination. In all lists of great crimes, as presented to us by the poets, one of the worst abodes in Tartarus is ever assigned to of- fenders of this description, and thus Paul classes those who are guilty of violence towards their parents among the un- holy and 'profane : dvoaioig nai fiebrjXoig TrarpaXtiaig nal pyrpaAcpaig. 1 Timothy, i., 9. The holiness of the family relation is intimated, in the ancient mythology, by the worship of Vesta; and the per- petual cherishing of the domestic affections, as affording the vivifying and fructifying warmth by which all social and political institutions must be preserved, is represented in the Eternal Fire. Well did Cicero say, in aris et focis est Respublica. This intimate connexion is set forth by the Greek and Latin poets in almost every form of expression. Virgil presents the holy alliance in one line : Sacra Deum sanctique patres. Georg., ii., 473. And this seems but a reiteration of the precept, Leviticus, xix., 2, and of the order in which the religious and family duties are there given. Speak unto all the congregation of Israel , and say unto them , Ye shall be holy , for I the Lord your God am holy. Fear ye every man his father and his mother . I am the Lord your God. The obligation of filial obedience, as the fountain of all moral and political virtues, is thus beautifully set forth in a fragment of Euripides from Stobaeus : *'E yco o pev MEIT2TON ap^opai Xeyeiv etc rovde upCorov • narpl TteWeoOai XP £ ^ V naldag, vopi&LV r’ avro rovF dvai diicrjv. Eurip. Alopa. So, also, in a still more striking fragment of the same poet, in which duties to parents are ranked next after those due the Gods, and before mere political obligations: 94 PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE FILIAL RELATION. rpslg holv aperal ag XPV clokeIv go teuvov, 0EOY2 re rtpav, rovg re dpsipavrag T0NEI2, • N0M0T2 re Kotvovg f E XXadog - teal ravra dptiv k&XXlotov e^eig ore(j)avov evtcXeiag aei. Eurip. Antiope. W e have dwelt the longer on this, because we think that Plato’s views here, and in many other places in the Laws and other dialogues, furnish a complete refutation of the charge, which might otherwise be drawn from the fifth book of the Republic ; and because, at the present day, even with all the declarations of the Bible, the relation seems to be becoming divested of that sanctity which it anciently possessed. In the theories of some, it is placed even below civil duties. So far from being thought to pos- sess any religious character, it is denied that it forms a sub- ject even for political legislation. It is ranked among im- perfect obligations , and is never with us, except in some few cases of pauperism, enforced by law. Why, when so many inferior subjects are made matters of legislation, this fundamental and all-conservative relation should have so little space assigned to it in our jurisprudence, it would be difficult to say. The effects, however, which will inevita- bly result, in loosening the whole political structure, can be far more easily and with more certainty predicted. The relation and the duties resulting are also attacked by spuri- ous reformers, who, under the name of a cold and heart- hardening universal benevolence, or love to being in general, would utterly break up all the family ties, and destroy all the associations connected with that holy word, Our Home. These men sometimes, in their ignorance, make stale second- hand quotations from Plato, and we would wish to rescue him from their profane’ grasp. PREAMBLE, OR ADVISORY PART OF THE LAW. 95 II. The Words Trpootptov and i rapapvOcov. The Preamble , the Advisory or Argumentative Part of the Law . Page 2, Line 16. To tt apapvOiov vnodepevcp prjreov a dec Ttaoxti'V- “ The lawgiver (vopoOerq, understood ) must declare what each one must suffer, after having put under, by way of hypothesis or foundation, an exhortation or pre- amble.” Another reading has tt pooiptov, which is followed by Ficinus. They both, however, would possess nearly the same significance. II poolfuov would literally mean 44 a preface or preamble tt apapvOiov, 44 an exhortatory ex- ordium,” containing the ground or reason of the law. This the philosopher deemed essentially and peculiarly neces- sary in those institutions that related to religion. Such an exhortation or argument, by way of preamble, nearly the whole of this tenth book may be considered, as only the last few pages are devoted to the preceptive declaration, and the penal statute founded upon it. In a more limited sense, however, the TrapapvQiov here intended is contained in what immediately follows. In like manner, Cicero, in evident imitation of Plato, introduces in his treatise De Legibus a similar Tcpooipcov , in which he makes religious belief and reverence the only true foundation of law and of every form of civil polity. It may be found in that noble passage, lib. ii., sec. vii. : Sit igitur hoc a principio per- suasion civibus, dominos esse omnium rerum ac moderatores Deos, eaque quae gerantur, eorum geri judicio ac numine, eosdemque optime de genere hominum mereri, et, qualis quisque sit, quid agat, quid in se admittat, qua mente, qua pietate colat religiones, intueri, piorumque et impiorum habere rationem. His enim rebus imbutae mentes, haud sane abhorrebunt ab utili ac vera sententia. Quid est enim verius, quam nemincm esse oportere tarn stulte arrogantem, ut in se rationem et mentem putet inesse, in coelo m undo quo 96 PREAMBLE, OR ADVISORY PART OF THE LAW. non putet ? aut ut ea, quae vix sumraa ingenii ratione compre- hendat, nulla ratione moveri putet ? Utiles esse autem opiniones has, quis neget, quum intelligat, quam multa fir- mentur jurejurando, quantae salutis sit foederum religiones, quam multos Divini supplicii metus a scelere revocarit, quamque SANCTA SIT SOCIETAS civium inter ipsos, Diis immortalibus interpositis turn judicibus , turn testibus. Habes legis PROCEMIUM : sic enim hoc appellat Plato. What a striking contrast between the sentiments of these noble heathen, and those of many modern political theories, constitutions, and boasting bills of rights, from which the very names of God, religion, Christianity, or the least allu- sion to any bond ( religio ) by which the visible state is connected with the invisible world, are as carefully ex- cluded, as though they were the deadliest foes to the po- litical happiness of mankind. On this subject we may compare also the sublime npool * jjuov in the Timasus, or the Dialogue in which Plato at- tempts to set forth the universal code of laws which govern both the physical and intelligible universe. The preamble or TTpoolfUov there, is found in that remarkable passage, in which he divides all things into what he styles, to 5/ ON /l lev del yevecnv de ovk s%ov * ual to riTNOMENON per, ov de ovdenoTE. to pev di) vorjoec pETa Xoyov nepiXprcTov, del Kara Tavra ov • to de do^rj peT ’ aloOrjoecog aXoyov , do^aorov, yiyvopevov, real dnoXXvpevov. ovTog de ovdenoTE ov. That which eternally IS and hath never generation , and that which is ever BECOMING or being generated , and never truly IS ; the one received by the intelligence with reason, always BEING in the same relations, the other re- ceived by opinion with irrational sense, ever becoming, perish - ing, and never truly , and in the highest sense, having a sub - stantive being. — Timwus, 27, P. This he evidently intends as a preamble to the system of physical and psychological legislation contained in that wonderful dialogue; for after SUBJECTIVE SENSE OF THE WORD aXrjOeVG). 97 dwelling upon the above distinction at some length, pre- paratory to the statement of the universal laws of mind and matter, Timaeus is thus addressed by Socrates : to pev ovv IIPOOIMION davpaoicog arced e^apeOd gov , rov de 6?) NO- MON rjplv ecpe^g rcepatve, “ Since in such a wonderful way we have received from you the 'preamble , next in order propound to us the law” Timaeus, 29, C. III. Subjective Sense of the Word aXrjOevG). Page 4, Line 9. 0 v/covv, cj %eve, do/cel padcov eivai dXrfevovrag Xeyetv cog eioi tieoi ; “ Does it not, then, seem to be an easy matter to affirm, in all truthfulness, that there are Gods, or that the Gods exist ?” ’A XrjOevo), although it includes in its signification the utterance of truth, and there are many passages in which it must be so rendered, has yet reference rather to truth of feeling than to truth of ex- pression, to that which belongs to the subjective state of the soul or the moral diathesis, rather than to that which is the result of scientific, or speculative, or casuistical argu- ment — what the Psalmist styles, “ truth in the in ward parts ” Paul seems to include much of this sense as he uses the term, Ephesians, iv., 15 — aXrjOevovreg ev ayarcr) : not so much “ speaking the truth,” as our translation has it, but rather, as is shown by the context, and especially by the word ayarcr], “ being truthful, or of a true heart in love” So, also, Galatians, iv., 16 — chare exOpog vpdjv yeyova aXrj- Oevcov vflv ; “ Have I become subject to your hatred while I am true (in heart) to you It may refer, in this last ex ample, to the declaration of truth, but even if that is sup- posed to be included, the subjective sense of the word is still predominant. Hence we may best render aXrjdevov- rag , in the passage at the head of these remarks, adverbial- I 98 SUBJECTIVE SENSE OF THE WORD dXrjOeVG). ly, thus : “ In all sincerity, in all truthfulness, in consistency with the truest and purest sentiments of our nature.” The other rendering, which would refer it merely to the declara- tion of truth, would be comparatively tame, besides pro- ducing a pleonasm in A eyeiv. Our translation is also in perfect keeping with the character of the honest and truth- ful Clinias, as he is, with great dramatic skill, represented to us throughout this whole argument. He uses the lan- guage of a man who never had felt a doubt on the subject. This is a favourite word with Plato, and frequently to be found in his writings in this subjective sense. For a very excellent example, see the Theaetetus, 202, B. : orav pev ovv dvev Xoyov rr]v dXr\d7j do^av rivog ng Xa6rj, ’AAH- 0ETEIN pev avrov tt\v 'i/jvx'rjv rrepl avro , yiyv&otteiv 6’ ov. The sentiment is, that the soul may be subjectively in harmony with the truth, so as cordially to embrace it in its creed before scientific knowledge, or an objective presenta- tion of it to the speculative reason. It may have the life before it possesses a clear apprehension of the doctrine . This may be, and often undoubtedly is, the case in religion ; but those who would, on this account, undervalue logical and doctrinal statements, or what they rather disdainfully style systematic theology, are in danger either of a mysti- cism, in which all clear perceptions of truth are utterly lost, or of taking opinions upon the mere testimony of others, or on the credit of a blind tradition, without either light in the reason, or any true warmth in the affections We have an illustration of this truthful state of mind in the course which Clinias pursues in the next reply — npiorov pev yr\ nal rjXiog, &c. He enters upon the argument with all the confidence of an easy victory. He appeals at once to the most obvious phenomena, not so much as scientific proofs of the Divine existence, but rather as visible repre- sentations of a manifest Divine power. “ The Heavens de- clare (to all whose souls are prepared for it) the glory of THE ORPHIC POETRY. 99 God.” But as though this had too much the appearance of speculative reasoning, he retreats again to his strong- hold, the feelings of his own nature, and appeals to the common and universal sentiments of mankind. This, with the bare aspect of the heavens, he deems enough for those who were true-hearted (akrjdevovreg) concerning the Gods. We are taught in the Holy Scriptures, that not only a true belief, but also unbelief in respect to the Divine existence, has its seat primarily in the affections rather than in the intellect. “ The fool hath said in his heart , there is no God.” The Hebrew word here is sometimes used for the understanding ; still, like the Greek (ppeveg, with all its cognates, such as (frpoveo), (frpovrjocg, typovrjpa, &c., it gen- erally refers to the intellect, not so much in a speculative or scientific aspect, but rather as modified by the state ol the affections or moral powers. IV. The Orphic Poetry. Page 5, Line 12. 0/ pev ev not perpoig, ol ds nal avev I usrpcov. “ Some in poetry and some in prose.” It is very uncertain what prose writings are here referred to. Those in poetry must have been the works of Homer, Hesiod, and perhaps of Orpheus. The term n aXaioraroi ( most ancient) would seem to refer to some productions older than the Iliad and the Theogonia. These might be styled n aXaia, in comparison with the period of Grecian literature in which Plato lived, which, although many centuries posterior in time, was not separated from them by any distinct literary epoch prior to the Persian wars. They could not, how- ever, be well entitled to the epithet iraXaiorara , which, as it is introduced, and as the context shows, is meant to des- ignate the most remote of two distinct periods, in reference 100 THE ORPHIC POETRY. to which it is intimated, there was a progression, if we may so style it, from the cosmological to the theogonic or my* thological. The first, or most ancient class, were of the former description. They were more philosophical than the latter, more taken up with the origin of things, that all- absorbing question which so engrossed the early mind : yeyovev rj IlPftTH <1>Y2I2 ovpavov rcov re aXXcdv. They were pantheistic rather than polytheistic, manifesting a de- parture, but still a less departure from the primitive reli- gion than is denoted by the latter stage. (See Note 9, page 5.) All these marks correspond well with the nature of some of the hymns styled Orphic, under which name a few fragments, whether spurious or not, have survived to our own day. Although these are generally regarded as productions of a much later age, yet, from the frequent refer- ence made to Orpheus by the Greek poets, it would seem almost certain that a collection of hymns under this name existed in the most ancient times, forming that copious fund or storehouse of rich poetical appellations, from which Homer, and subsequently Aeschylus, were supplied, besides being the source of whatever is pantheistical or mystical in the Grecian tragedies. The existence of forgeries is evidence that there must have been originals in imitation of which they were composed, and an ancient philosophy and theology, which had once exerted great influence on the human mind, to serve as their plausible and probable foundation. In connexion with the passage before us, compare lib. iv., 716, A.: f O pev dr) deog , tjonep nal 6 nahaiog Xoyog, dpx'fjv re teal reXevrrjv nal p,eoa rtiv ovtgtv andvrejv ex^v. This is almost the very language of one of the so-styled Orphic fragments now extant, and is directly referred to Orpheus by the scholiast on the place : — 0 eov pev rov dr}- puovpyov ocKptig, naXcuov de Xoyov Xeyei rov OPIKON, bg eanv ovroq, THE ORPHIC POETRY. 101 Z evg apxrj, Z evg peaoa, A tog d’ en iravra rervurar Z evg 7tv0[jLtjv yairjg re aal ovpavov aarepoevrog . Should any one say that this resembles very much the language of Thales, or some of the philosophers of that period, and that, therefore, the ignorant old scholiast had been imposed upon by one who had affixed a fabulous name and given a poetical dress to some of their dogmas, — why, we would reply, may not Thales and others have derived this peculiar mode of expression from a still earlier source, and why this disposition to charge the scholiasts and Christian fathers with combining to produce such useless and yet elaborate forgeries as some critics are constantly connecting with their names ? We say useless, because a philosophy and theology, such as appears in these hymns, did, beyond all question, exist at a very early period, and the poetical dress, had it not been real, would have added nothing to the argument they sought to derive from them. For places in the ancient writings, in which reference is made to Orpheus and his poems, the reader is referred to Plato, Ion, vol. iii., p. 134, Leip. ; Convivium, vii., 219 ; De Legibus, vi., 230 ; Cratylus, ii., 263 ; Aristotle, De Anim., i, 8 ; Euripides, Rhesus, 947 ; Hippolytus, 967 ; Cicero, De Nat. Deor., i., 38 ; Diod. Sic., iv., 25 ; Just. Mart., Co- hortat. ad Graecos, p. 17 ; Athenagoras, Legat. pro Christ., xv., 64, 65. 12 102 plato’s regard for the ancient myths. V. Plato's Regard for Antiquity and the Ancient Mythology . — His Use of the Word Qeoi. Page G, Line 1. Ov padcov emrtpav n aXaiolg ovclv, “ It is hard to find fault with them, seeing they are ancient things.” We discover, in this and similar expressions, Plato’s conservative spirit and reverence for antiquity, struggling with his conviction of the importance of having the minds of the young imbued with higher notions of the Divine Nature than could be obtained from the ancient poets. The same feelings are manifested in that passage in the Republic, in which he dismisses Homer, with the rest of the poets, from his imaginary City of the Soul, al- though, at the same time, he sends him away with a garland of honour on his head. “ Should such a one (he says) come to our city, wishing to exhibit his poems, we would, indeed, reverence him as something sacred, and wonderful, and delightfully pleasant, yet still would we say that no such man could abide with us : aTTonepnoLfiev re av elg dXXrjv ttoXlv , pvpov Kara rr\g /csdtaXijg Karajfavreg real eptCi) ore^avreg, and we would send him away to another state, having poured myrrh upon his head and crowned him with a wreath.” Republic, 398, A. We find, however, everywhere, in his works, a strong attachment to the an- cient myths, wherever they contained nothing gross or of- fensive to his views of morality ; a number of which, and those, too, distinguished for the feeling of awe and sublimity with which they inspire the reader, he has himself present* ed in some of the most important and philosophical of his dialogues. It is exceedingly interesting to contemplate the peculiar condition of this philosopher, endeavouring to reform what he felt he had no power or commission to abolish. Having no Divine warrant, like the Hebrew prophets or the apostles plato’s regard for the ancient mytiis. 103 ot Christ, he did not dare to enter upon an exterminating crusade against ail the rites, opinions, and traditions held sacred in the Athenian worship. The Grecian reformer was too well acquainted with human nature not to fear lest, in destroying the monster Superstition, he should call up another of a still more horrid aspect — Atheism. He did not wish utterly to pull down existing institutions, while he had no new revelation, whose authority might replace, with increased vigour, the departed reverence for those ancient myths, the probable remains of truths once communicated from Heaven, yet mysteriously abandoned to all the cor- ruptions and distortions of the human mind. He probably thought that out of some of the better parts of the Grecian mythology there might be constructed a system, which, while it recognised the One Eternal Supreme, placed at an immense distance from all things created by him or ema- nating from him, might, at the same time, admit of inferior powers, retaining the individual names at least, (if not the characters), which had been consecrated by the popular superstition. That he did believe in such an Eternal and Ineffable Supreme (6 yevvrjoag a'idioq rcarrjp , Timseus, 38, A., — 6 KoXkioroq teal dptoroq pevcjv del dnXtig ev ry avrov pop(j)rj , Rep., 381, C., — 6 Trdvrcjv rjiaora rrjq eavrov Ideaq ka&aivwv, 380, D.), every reader of his works must admit. He undoubtedly erred in supposing that the pure worship of such a glorious Being could be consistent with any kind of religious homage paid to inferior powers ; yet we should remember that the same error has been com- mitted by the largest portion of the professedly Christian Church, and that we are to judge Plato, not as a Christian under the light of revelation, but as a heathen philosopher struggling with difficulties, of the magnitude of which we have no just conception. These remarks are deemed ne- cessary in reply to the charge often made against Plato, of countenancing the polytheism of his countrymen, and which 104 plato’s use of the word $eol. w may be found set forth in its strongest light in a tract by Jacob Zimmerman, contained in the ninth volume of the Amcenitates Literaria. A misconception in regard to the Platonic theology has arisen from his use of the word deoi. The Greek writers, whether poets or orators, generally meant by it nothing more than supernatural beings of a higher order than men. The word, in itself, had attached to it none of those more metaphysical conceptions which belong to our term Divine, as significant of the uncreated and eternal. There was, therefore, no philological inconsistency in its being applied to those beings whom Plato elsewhere calls datfioveg, and who, in his scheme, may be regarded in the same light with the angels or sons of God, mentioned in the Holy Scriptures. In respect to the objection which might be made to his use of the plural, it may be remarked, that throughout this whole argument with the atheist, tiedg may be substituted for tieoi, without at all affecting its validity, and we should by so doing come nearer to the philosopher’s true meaning, than by retaining the common term, with the misconception arising from our modern notions ; that is, we should better translate his spirit by adopting a slight mistranslation of the letter. Qeoi is often to be taken collectively for the whole of the superhuman Genus, however inferior and de- pendent some parts of it may be in respect to another, and is equivalent, in the discussions which follow, to to tielov or to d(U[i6mov. Another suggestion, which it may be proper to make here, is, that by the phrase tieot Kara voiiovg, the writer means not directly the Theogony and worship established by law at Athens (although even this he would touch with the hand of a wise reformer, and not of a reck- less destructionist), but rather the cultus of the Supreme and inferior Divinities, as it should be set forth by the law- giver in that pure system of polity which he contemplates in the present treatise. PHILOSOPHY OF ANAXAGORAS. 105 VI. Philosophy and Character of Anaxagoras. Page 6, Line 6. veoov oo(p(hv. “ Of our modern wits, or wise men that is, comparatively modern, although all to whom he refers did not live in Plato’s own time. He seems chiefly to have had in mind Anaxagoras, who, not- withstanding his speculative theism and his boasted doc- trine of the N ovg, was yet regarded by Plato as giving an atheistical tendency to the age in which he lived. In re- gard to his theology, Anaxagoras is best known by the po- sition, in which he so much gloried, “ that mind was the cause of all things,” and in physics, by the unpopular dogma, “ that the sun was nothing but a mass of ignited stone, instead of an animated being,” as was commonly be- lieved, and as Plato seems to teach in this book. The character of this philosopher may be understood from the boasting he himself made, and which his friends made for him, in regard to the first of these doctrines ; as though, in this respect, he had in any way advanced beyond the more modest Thales, or had discovered a truth which had been concealed from the beginning of the world to his own day. Socrates seems to have had a right view of him in the Phsedon, where he charges him with setting out with the doctrine that N ovg was the cause of all things, as a mere speculative tenet, and then making no use of it in subse- quent parts of his philosophy ; that is, never ascending above second causes, or rising from the physical to the moral (to f3eXri(JTOV ), but ever assigning, as the chief mo- tive powers, aepag ts ual alOepag nai v6ara y gases , and fires , and fluids, as the words may be rendered in accom- modation to the same spirit in modern physical philosophy. “ Having once (says he) heard one reading a book of Anax- agoras, and saying, that Nous was the disposer and the effi- cient cause of all things, I was highly delighted with the 106 PHILOSOPHY OF ANAXAGORAS. declaration, and it seemed to rne to be admirably said ; and I thought* that if Novg (or Mind) thus arranged all things, everything must be placed in that position in which it was best for it to be ; so that no other study remained for man, in regard to both himself and other things , but the investigation of that which was (morally) most excellent and best (or. in other words, moral causes), and that this was the only true science of things. But in this wonderful hope (of discover- ing the universal science, or science of sciences) I was greatly disappointed ; for as I read on I find the man making no farther use of his boasted N ovg, nor assigning any other cause in the disposal and arrangement of the world, than airs, and aethers, and waters, and other similar things many and strange. And he seemed to me to act precisely as if any one saying, that Socrates doeth whatso- ever he doeth by mind’or reason , should then, in attempt- ing to assign the causes of my actions, assert that I now sit here for these reasons , namely, that my body is com- posed of bones and nerves, that my bones are solid and have joints, and that my nerves contract and relax ; where- fore that the bones being raised up in their joinings, the nerves, by reason of tension and relaxation, make me to bend my limbs, and that for this reason I now sit here : and so, also, in respect to our conversing, should assign other similar causes of the phenomena of speech, such as voices, and aerial vibrations, and sounds (( pcovag re nal aepag nal anoag ), and ten thousand other such agencies, all the while neglect- ing to assign the true reason (of reasons), that because it seemed good (j3 eXriov) to the Athenians to condemn me, therefore it seemed better to me to sit here, and more just to submit to the sentence they had imposed. Since, as I verily believe, had it not been for the last-mentioned reasons, these nerves and bones would long before this have had me away to Megara or among the Boeotians, being set in mo- tion by an opinion of the best ( rov PeXriarov), if I had not PHILOSOPHY OF ANAXAGORAS. 107 thought it more just and better to remain than to fly.” Phaedon, 97, 98. We recommend the close study of this whole passage, and the admirable sketch it presents of such theists as Anaxagoras, to every student who wishes to know the essential difference, on this most vital point, be- tween the Socratic and other ancient systems of philosophy. How strongly does it remind us of many modern books of physical science, in which the name of God may, perhaps, appear in a preface or some introductory note, while all the rest is not merely silent, but directly adapted to produce an atheistic turn of thought, by suffering the mind to dwell on nothing else than aepag re ual alQepag nal vdara , gases, and fluids, and fires, or imponderable agents. The opinion which Plato entertained of this philosopher is also signifi- cantly expressed, although he does not mention his name, in the eleventh book of the Laws, 967, A. B. C., a passage which is more freely examined in Note XIII., on the athe- istic doctrine of (pvoig, rvx 7 ]* and x vr ] • The Noi)^ of Anaxagoras can hardly be regarded as a personal being, or as a 'ipvx^j vnepnoagitiy distinct from the world, of which it might be considered the informing law. The atheist may admit the dogma without changing his creed. La Grange undoubtedly believed that there was N ovg, or reason, in the Heavens, even a science so profound, that all the powers of his highest mathematical analysis could barely follow the laws of motion in which it was dis- played ; and yet La Grange was an atheist. The Heavens had no interest for him except as they formed a splendid diagram for the illustration of his calculus, and as long as the moral element was wanting it made no difference what name was inscribed upon it, whether Noi;^ or (ftvoig, or a God possessed of mere intelligence, to whom we were no- thing, and who was nothing to us, except as affording subjects for the exercise of the speculative intellect. This Noi)c of Anaxagoras had no respect to moral as final causes, which 108 PHILOSOPHY OF ANAXAGORAS. as Socrates shows, were studiously excluded from his philos- ophy. It was only another name for the physical truth of things, in which the atheist contends there may be science on his hypothesis, as well as on any other. It was an abstract intelligence, displayed wholly in physical adaptations, with- out either a general or special providence. It might be regarded as the instinct of the universe , working in the great whole, as some of its emanations in minute portions, blindly, unconsciously, without personality, and knowing everything but itself. However incomprehensible this may be, it is still the highest reach of that philosophy which makes no account of any moral attributes in the Deity, but regards him as a mere impassible intelligence. We have no hesitation in preferring pantheism if it embrace, although inconsistently, that moral element, without which there can be no true personality, either to Novg or 'ibvxf Plato evidently regarded this philosophy as no better than practical atheism, notwithstanding it sets out so pom- pously, and apparently so religiously, with the dogma afore- said. He seems here to condemn its modern advocates, the veot cofiol, as he styles them, equally with that ancient superstition which they so much derided. Anaxagoras was of a spirit the very opposite of that which pervades all the teachings of Socrates. He was inclined rather to insult and shock the popular superstitions than gently to remove them, or turn to good account whatever of truth they might possess, and that, too, not in the spirit of enthusiastic reli- gious zeal, which we cannot help respecting even when we are compelled to condemn, but in the mere conceit of a little fancied progress in physical science. Like the modern Galileo, whose name is so frequently in the mouths of the scientific enemies of religion, he evidently rejoiced more in the thought, that this very small advance raised him somewhat above the religious notions of his country- men, than in any honest wish or desire to elevate those PHILOSOPHY OF ANAXAGORAS. 109 popular views which placed him, as he supposed, in such egotistical contrast. He seems to have been a regular priest and poet hater, and there is, therefore, no cause for surprise that he should have called forth the enmity and prejudices of those whom he had, from no higher motive than vanity, attacked. This spirit was manifested in the declaration, a few lines below referred to, that the heavenly bodies were only masses of earth and stones, and that the sun was a ball of melted ore. For this he was charged by the Athenians with atheism, and justly too ; for he who assails the com- mon belief of any people, without putting anything better in its place, or who attempts to destroy false notions of the Deity, without teaching, as Socrates and Plato did, the doc- trine of the one eternal and ineffable, yet personal Supreme, the head of a moral government, and directing all things with final reference to moral ends, is in heart no better than an atheist, whatever refined speculative notions he may have in the abstract about N ovg or intelligence being the cause of all things. It is probable that the condemna- tion of Socrates was mainly effected in consequence of his views having been misunderstood by the unthinking Athenian mob, and confounded with those of Anaxagoras. Plato did undoubtedly hold that the Heavenly bodies were animated personal beings ; but when here and in sub- sequent passages he styles them deoi, it is only in the sense of beings superior to men. The simple doctrine, there- fore, for it goes no farther, that the Heavenly bodies were animated beings, was no greut heresy either in philosophy or religion. (See Note XXXIV., where this subject is more fully discussed.) It was far better than the specula- tive semi-atheism of Anaxagoras, or even of some modern naturalists, who have only substituted for the abstract Novg of the Grecian philosopher the symbols and equations of the differential and integral calculus. One religious com K 110 DIVINE JUSTICE GROUND OF HUMAN LAW. ception of God as a moral governor, the light in which Plato and Socrates chiefly regarded him, and which may exist in connexion with the most absurd notions of the physical universe, does yet belong to a philosophy almost infinitely removed above the mere scientific theism of such men as Anaxagoras, Galileo or La Place. VII. The Divine Justice , the Ground of Human Law . Page 9, Line 1. Ex^ddv yap tovto rjpiv virep anavrcov TO)V VOflOJV K&XhiOTOV TE Kal dpLOTOV TipOOLpLOV CiV £L7)« “ For this is just the fairest and most excellent 'preamble to all laws, or to every system of law,” namely, fteoi r’ eld nal dyaOot , dhcrjv rtpcovreg diacpepovrcog dvdp&irov. “ That the Gods not only are , but that they are also good, and that, moreover, they have an esteem for justice beyond anything that is felt among men.” deol here, as we have remarked before, is used as a collective term for the whole of the Divine Nature, being equivalent to to 'Selov , or to daipoviov, and should be rendered in the singular, if we would do full justice to the thought. See Note V. The sentiment is this : It is not enough simply to believe in the Divine existence. God is something more than the dynamic principle of the universe. Neither is it enough to connect with this the notion of infinite knowledge. God is some- thing more than the N ovg of Anaxagoras, something more than mere intelligence. The law should present him to us in the far sublimer idea of a Being clothed with the moral attributes of justice, and of a special, or, rather, moral providence. It is this, and not a merely speculative or scientific theism, which must lie at the foundation of every true system of legislation. We may talk as loftily as we please of The Supreme Intelligence, or The First Cause, or UNIVERSALITY OF THE BELIEF IN A GOD. Ill The Great Idea, it is still practical atheism, until along with this there is recognised The Lawgiver, The Judge, and The Moral Governor, the constant and interested Witness of our every act, the ground and sanction of the solemn appeal of the oath. “ That such views (says Cicero) are useful and necessary, who will deny, when he reflects how many things must be confirmed by an oath, how much safety there is in those religious rites that pertain to the solemnization of con- tracts, how many the fear of the Divine punishment keeps back from crime ; in short, how sacred and holy a thing So- ciety becomes when the Immortal Gods are constantly pre- sented (in the Law) both as judges and witnesses.” Cic., De Leg., ii., vii. We would even venture to assert, that a gross anthropopathy or anthropomorphism, if it retain such views of the moral attributes of the Deity as a God of Law, is every way to be preferred to the most metaphysical or philosophical notions of the Divine Nature and its im- passibility, which reject them, or do not even assign to them the most prominent place. Mill Universality of the Belief in a God. Page 10, Line 10. f E/l Xrjvcov re teal (3ap6dpo)v ndvrcov ev ovpzpopalg Tzavroiatg. Compare with this what Clinias says, page 4*, line 14 : nal oti irdvreg f/ E XXrjver re izal f3ap6apot vopi^ovoiv elvcu deovg. By Greeks and Bar- barians, the former always meant all mankind, and, there- fore, the belief in a God is here declared to be coextensive with the race. If any man might rely on his own unaided reason, who will venture to say that Plato would not have been justified in thus trusting himself to it ? And yet, pro- found as he was in the investigation of truth beyond the most, if not all, of his fellow-men, he never hesitates to ap- 112 UNIVERSALITY OF THE BELIEF IN A GOb. peal to the common sentiments, the noival Ivvoiai of man- kind, and to throw himself upon them often with a confidence which he yielded to no speculative argument. Hence his fondness for those ancient myths, under which were con- cealed, in various forms, the opinions universally held re- specting the moral government of God and the doctrine of future retribution. This was not, as Warburton supposed, a mere accommodation of himself to those vulgar dogmas, which he did not wish to destroy, because he deemed them useful. All that has been said by writers of that school, and by the ancient authorities on whom they pretend to rely, respecting the exoteric and esoteric teaching, we be- lieve to be wholly unsupported by any parts of the genuine dialogues of Plato. No man was farther from his true spirit than Warburton, and, without an appreciation of this, his learning only led him to misunderstand the philosopher in some of his most serious discussions. If ever Plato is deeply earnest, it is when he gets engaged in the discus- sion of a traditionary myth, which he can regard in some measure as standing in the place of primitive revelation, or can find relief from the uncertainties of his own specula- tions, in what he could trace as the universal voice of hu- manity. We need no stronger proof of this, than is found in the manner in which he closes the long discussion in the Gorgias (in some respects the most perfect and rigidly con- ducted argument to be found in his works), with the mythi- cal representation of the final judgment ; as though, without this appeal to the authority of ancient and universal tradi- tion, human reason could never freely and satisfactorily prove that a life of sensual pleasure, or of worldly ambition, was not better than one spent in acts of virtue and the culti- vation of philosophy. He was the last man to spurn such aid, in order to gratify that pride of intellect, that would adopt no conclusions to which it had not arrived through the independent exercise of private judgment. He knew UNIVERSALITY OF THE BEFIEF IN A GOD. 113 too well the direct tendency of such a spirit to darken the understanding, and to lead to error instead of truth. We would not, however, confound this with a modern affectation which has sought to support itself by the au- thority of our philosopher. Plato, it should be ever borne in mind, had no Bible, and he did well, therefore, and ex- ercised his highest reason in seeking for a Divine revelation in those universal sentiments of all people and nations, which were as ancient in time as they were extended in space, and which could most truly be said to be, semper, ubique, et ah omnibus. This object of his reverence was something far different from the vox populi of the dema- gogue, who is often most successful when he can array the artificial and transient feeling of one generation, or one na- tion, against what he would style the antiquated prejudices of mankind. It was rather that vox humanitatis, which, by its universality at all times and in all regions, gave evi- dence of having been once the voice of God , remains of a primitive inspiration, however darkened it may have been by human depravity — opinions which had not been the prod- uct of the speculative reason, but which, under the con- serving influence of a higher principle, had maintained their ground in spite of the opposition of human depravity, and the consequently superinduced darkness of the human un- derstanding. It was this vox humanitatis to which Hesiod seems to allude : < prjyr] d ’ ov rig 7rd[j,nav diroXXvrai, rjv nva iroXXol Xaol (prjfi^ovoL * fteog vv rtg eg tl teal avrrj. Works and Days , 709. Compare, also, Cicero, De Nat. Deorum, i., 43 : Solus enim videt, primum esse Deos, quod in omnium animis eorum notionem impressisset ipsa natura. Quae est enim gens, aut quod genus hominum, quod non habeat sine doc - trina anticipationem quamdam Deorum? quae rpohppig K 2 114 ANTIQUITY OF ATHEISM.. appellatur, &c. Quum enim non instituto aliquo aut more aut lege sit opinio constituta, rnaneatque ad unum omnium firma consensio, intelligi necesse est esse Deos, quoniam insitas eorum vel potius innatas cogitationes habemus. De quo autem omnium riatura consentit, id verum esse necesse est. And again, lib. ii., 12: Itaque inter omnes omnium gentium sententia constat. Omnibus enim innatum est et in animo quasi insculptum esse Deos. Still more to the same effect, Tusc. Disp., i., 30, where we find the best definition of the Law of Nature that has ever been given. Ut porro firmissimum hoc afferri videtur, cur Deos esse credamus, quod nulla gens tarn fera, nemo omnium tarn sit immanis, cujus mentem non imbuerit De- orum opinio. Multi de Diis prava sentiunt (id enim vitioso more effici solet), omnes tamen esse vim et nature m Di- vinam arbitrantur. Nec vero id collocutio hominmn aut consensus efficit : non institutis opinio est confirmata, non legibus. Omnis autem in re consensio omnium gentium LEX NATURiE putanda est. IX. Antiquity of Atheism. Page 11, Line 12. Tiyvovrai 6s del nXecovg rj eXarrovg ravT7]v rrjv vooov exovreq. “ There have always been more or less who have had this disease of atheism.” It has been maintained that there were no philosophical atheists, professedly so, before Democritus and Leucippus. Plato, however, asserts that some such have existed from a very early period, and in this he is borne out by Aristotle, who tells us that most of the earliest philosophers, especially those of the Ionic school, assigned only material causes of the universe : rdv irpcorcov (piXoaocftrjadvTOJv oi uXeloroi rag ev vXpg eldei j uovov (brjOpoav apxdg elvac iravrov. ANTIQUITY OF ATHEISM 115 Aristotle, Metaph., i., 3. A distinction, however, should be made between those who were professed atheists, such as Democritus and Diagoras, and those who were inclined to an atheistical mode of philosophizing, while they yet pro- fessed to be theists, although of an impure and inconsistent species. In this latter class the world has always abound- ed. On the other hand, it is most conclusively shown by Cudworth, that, although this materializing school was an- cient, the first philosophy was spiritual , and that the sub- sequent atheism arose from a perversion of the atomical theory, which, when truly held, and according to the views of those who originated it before Democritus, was not only favourable to, but one of the firmest supports of a pure theism. Plato, in this passage, styles atheism a disease , as though it were something unnatural, a corruption, diacpOopa (see page 4, line 18), a departure from those innate sentiments orirpo- Arjxpetg, of the race of which he and Cicero speak so em- phatically. So, also, the apostle treats it as a degeneracy from a primitive better state, Rom., i., 28. He speaks of this tendency as a darkness of the spirit , nai eonorioOrj rj dovverog napdia avr&v, Rom., i., 21 : as a reprobate mind or reason , adoiapov vovv , 28, to which men “ had been given up, because they did not like to retain God in their knowledge.” We cannot read these Scriptures without calling to mind a similar sentiment expressed in a fragment of the old poet Empedocles : A eiXog d’ gj GKoroeooa tt epi 6o^a peprjAev. Ah wretch ! whose soul dark thoughts of God invade. If the light that is in thee be darkness , how great is that darkness ! 116 PRINCIPLE OF AUTHORITY. X. Principle of Authority, Page 12, Line 6. civ epoi n elOtj, nepipEVElg avao/tonQv elre ovrog Eire aXXcog e^el, nwOavopEVog napa te rtiv aX Xcjv, teal 6rj icai pdXiora nai napa tov vopoOerov. “ If you will take my advice, you will patiently wait, repeated ly examining whether it is thus or otherwise, learning from others, and therefore, and in a most especial manner, from the Lawgiver.” Notwithstanding the earnest recommenda- tion to most diligent study and inquiry, and in perfect con. sistency with it, Plato holds that the acceptance of establish- ed opinions must go before and guide the exercise of pri- vate judgment ; not to supersede or dispense with the ne- cessity of the latter in its proper time and place, but be- cause the state of mind which submits to lawful authority affords the surest guarantee of subsequent mental independ- ence, instead of that counterfeit which is often nothing more than a slavish fear of a creed, and which loses all true independence, in its premature efforts to avoid what the best and wisest of mankind have long regarded as established. The next sentence contains a thought of the highest practical importance : iv de di) rovrcp rep XP° V( ? M ToXpr}- cyjg nepl 'deovg p7]dev aaEdrjoai, “ but during this, period see to it that you venture upon nothing impious or unholy.” That is, religious obligation must be revered, and pious emotions cherished, before the young soul can reason about them, and there is no period, however short, that we have a right to remain atheists until we are able to prove by in- duction the existence of a God. He who thus honours reason , by following its first dictate, submission to authority which God himself has established, will doubtless leave those who have been taught to pursue a different course, far behind him in all the severer and more abstruse depart. DEGREES OF ATHEISM. 117 ments of philosophy and theology. Throughout this whole treatise, it should be borne in mind that vofXQOsrrjg means rather the ancient founder of a state or of a religion, than a temporary or subordinate magistrate ; so that “ to learn of the Lawgiver,’’ is to consult with deference and respect, as one great means of forming right opinions, the civil and religious constitution of the state in which we may be born. XI. Degrees of Atheism . — Peculiarity of Plato's Style. Page 12, Line 13. Tlavranaoi j uiv ovv , &c. The author now proceeds to the discussion of speculative and practical atheism in its three degrees, which may be thus stated : 1st. An absolute denial of the existence of a Deity. 2d. The opinion that, if a Deity exists, he does not con- cern himself about us, or in other words, the denial of a Providence. 3d. A sentiment clearly allied to the second ; that if a Deity exists, and if he even exercises a physical care or providence over the world regarded as a physical produc- tion, still he is in a great measure, if not wholly, indifferent to moral conduct, and that, therefore, his displeasure, should it be ever excited, is easily appeased, not by repentance, nor by an atonement that God himself has provided, but by self-imposed votive offerings and superstitious services We expect a direct argument on the first head, conduct- ed in the usual manner by an appeal to evidences of design in the phenomena around us. This mode of proceeding is adopted in the discourses recorded in the Memorabilia, and there is, also, an admirable specimen of it in Cicero’s treatise De Natura Deorum. Such a line of argument, however, although quite a favourite with modern theolo- 118 DEGREES OF ATHEISM. gians, was not that which would first suggest itself to the ancient mind, but a more abstruse speculation, and one which had a more intimate relation to the great question about the first origin of things, the first life and motion in matter, whether to be regarded as eternal, or as having had a dis- tinct origination from some older essence. This, also, we fully believe, is the way in which the subject would present itself to such a mind as Socrates, notwithstanding it is gen- erally considered that the plain and practical mode of reasoning ascribed to him by Xenophon is more in accord- ance with the truth, than the metaphysical character in which he appears in the Dialogues of Plato. At all events, this is the mode adopted here by the Athenian, who un- doubtedly represents Socrates, and he also takes a very peculiar method of introducing it. In the commencement of his reasoning on the first head, he takes his hearers by surprise, by suddenly suggesting that they had unawares fallen upon the discussion of a most important principle, which deserved to be disposed of before going on with those more popular views which had just been mentioned. It has, at first, the appearance of being accidental, but one familiarly acquainted with the Platonic method will rec- ognise here the usual ironical resource the author employs when he wishes to enter upon a discussion more than usually subtle — namely, the apparently undesigned eliciting of a question in relation to it from the one with whom the dialogue is maintained. The chief speaker seems, or af- fects, suddenly to remember something essential to the argu- ment, and which they were in danger of having entirely forgotten, although it is evident that it is the main thing which has been kept in view from the beginning, notwith- standing its seeming incidental introduction. Frequent ex- amples of this may be found in the Protagoras, Republic, and Theaetetus, especially the last. It is, in fact, so purely Platonic, that it may be regarded as one of the best signs, ANCIENT DOCTRINE OF THE FOUR ELEMENTS. 119 as far, at least, as the style is concerned, by which we may distinguish a genuine from a spurious dialogue. XII. Ancient Doctrine of the Four Elements . Page 13, Line 15. Hvp feed v6cop uai yr\v teal aspa . It is generally assumed that in the use of these terms all the ancient philosophers meant four simple, indestructible, and incomposite elements ; being the primordia , or apyal , by the union or composition of which all other things were con- stituted. Hence many a superficial sneer by popular lec- turers at the ignorance of the ancients in respect to chem- istry and the number of simple substances. This view of the matter, however, is far from being correct. Some, it is true, maintained the above doctrine nearly in the terms which we have employed, and as it would be stated by a modern chemist. Among these, if we understand Aristotle aright, was Empedocles. ’EpnsdorcXrjg psv yap ra psv gco- parircd rsooapa , rd 6s ndvra perd tw v klvovvtcov , ef tov aptdpov . Aristotle, De Gen. et Corrup., i., 1. By the two moving powers here are intended his poetical personifica- tions of Love and Discord, ’'Epog and *E peg, or, as they would be styled in the language of modern science, Attrac- tion and Repulsion, which, together with the four elements, made the number of original principles or primordia to be six. Anaxagoras, Leucippus, and Democritus maintained that the elements were infinite, not only in number, but in form. ’A va^ayopag 6s dnsipa, nal Asyrannog, ual Arjpo- Kptrog * ravra 6s arcstpa uai to tt X rjOog sivat ual rag pop - < pag . The doctrine which the first of these held respect- ing the homoeomerice, or similar parts, is well known. Aris- totle represents him, on this subject, as in every respect the direct opposite of Empedocles. ’E vavrloyg 6s fyaivoviai 120 ANCIENT DOCTRINE OF THE FOUR ELEMENTS. XeyovTeg ol nepl ' kva^ayopav rolg nepl ^pnedonXea. 'O pev yap §t\gl nvp nal vdcjp teal aepa teal yr\v OTOi%eia teg- Gapa , nal dnXd elvat paXXov fj oapna teal ogtovv nal ra roiavra tcjv opotopepebv • 6 de ravra pev anXa nal Groix^la, yrjv de teal nvp nal aepa Gvvdera . De Gen., &c., i., 1. “ For the latter says that fire, and water, and air, and earth are four elements, and more simple than flesh and bone, and others of the liomceomerice , while the former contends that these are simple elements, but that earth, and air, and fire are compounds.’’ See Aristotle, De Generatione et Cor- ruption, lib. i., where there is a long, but not very clear account of some of the ancient opinions on this subject. Compare, also, lib. iii., 3. In general, however, we are quite satisfied that, even when they used the term <7TO£%ehz, most of the ancient writers on physics had in view elemental states of bodies, without reference to their composition, rather than simple substances or elements in the sense in which modern chemis- try would define the term — that is, as substances incapable of being changed, or of passing one into the other from a change of state. It was in this sense of elemental states that Parmenides held to two, nvp and yrjv, or the solid and the cetliereal , regarding the fluid and the aerial as only mix- ed modifications : ol de evdvg dvo noiovvTeg, tjoirep Jlap- pevidrjg nvp nal yrjv , ra pera^v plypara tcolovgl tovtcjv , olov aepa nal vdcop. Arist., De Gen., &c., ii., 3. In like manner, Aristotle himself declares that they are not simple substances as actually found in nature, but ever compound- ed of one another, although in their ultimate state he seems to regard them as pure : ovn egti de to rrvp, nal 6 afjp, nal enaoTOV tcov elprjpevcov, anXovv, dXXa pucTOV, n. r. X Lib. ii., 3. At all events, we have no doubt, from several very de cided passages, as to the manner in which these terms are employed by Plato, whatever meaning may be attached to ANCIENT DOCTRINE OF THE FOUR ELEMENTS. 121 them in the sentence at the head of these remarks, as the supposed language of the atheistical philosophers. He was so far from regarding them as strictly elements {aroix^Za) in the modern chemical, or even ancient Greek sense of the word, that he would not even rank them in that second stage of combination which he styles ovXXadrj. See the Timaeus, 48, B. : T i)v 6e rrpd rrjg ovpavov yeveceog irvpog vdarog re nai y r\g (pvacv $ eareov , nal ra irpo rovrcdv n ad?]. Nvv yap cjg eldooi nvp 6 n ixore eon, real enaorov avrtiv, Xeyopev apx&g, avra TtOepevoi croixela rov navrog • Trpoo- rjrcov avrolg ovd ’ (hg sv 2TAAABH2 elded aTTetfcaadrjvac. “We must contemplate the nature of fire, water, air, and earth, before the generation of the Heavens ; for now, as though we spoke to those who well knew what fire is, and each one of the rest, we talk of principles, and regard them as the elements ( aroix £ Za , also used for the letters of the alphabet) of the universe, when they ought not to be liken- ed even to the species of the syllable.” It is very clear likewise, from other passages, that Plato views them not as elements, but as elementary states ( Karaordoeig ), in which all bodies must exist, however varied in other respects their compositions ; namely, as solid, fluid, gas , or that fourth condition which the ancients generally denoted by the term fire (nvp), but which modern chemistry would style the class of imponderable agents. These are heat , light, the electric, the galvanic, and the magnetic influence, which, al- though having five different names, are coming to be more and more regarded by our most scientific men as only modi- fications of one and the same principle. In other words, earth (y^), as used by Plato and many others of the Greek philosophers, was simply their scientific term for solid (to arepeov, to which it is sometimes equivalent), whether the substance was earth, or wood, or precious stones, — v6o)p for liquid or fluid , &c., and nvp for all that modification more subtle than air, of which they had some tolerably clear L 122 ANCIENT DOCTRINE OF THE FOUR ELEMENTS. views, as the seat of higher agencies than were usually cognizable by the senses, and of which they regarded the visible lire as the lowest representative form. Whoever wishes to see the views of Plato on these sub- jects more fully stated may consult that portion of the Timaeus, where he treats at great length of the primary constitution of bodies, and which, although erroneous in the details of its numerical ratios (as every a priori or theo- retical attempt of the kind must be), contains evidently the germ of the modern chemical theory of definite 'proportions . These four states , or naraoraGSig , with all other interve- ning compound modifications, were, in fact, regarded but as varied manifestations of one simple essence (vXrj), which receives all forms, itself having no form, and is therefore ( ayvodorov ) unknown and incapable of being known : since all physical knowledge is possible only in respect to those things which have number and Xoyog, ratio or reason ; and therefore elements, which are strictly such, are in their very nature ak oya, or incapable of being objects of scien- tific contemplation, except in their binary or trinary com- binations. As he says in the Thesetetus, 202, B., ovro.) dr) rd psv GTOix^ia aXoya teal ayvcoora elvai , oXadryrd ds , rag 6s GvXXabag yvoGrag rs nal prjrag nal dXrjOsl do^rj do%- aGrdg. All modifications of this simple essence were ( (paivopsva ) phenomena or appearances, having nothing absolute except in the idea manifested by them, no indestructible material nature of their own, but continually passing into and out of each other, or, in other words, ever becoming (yiyvopeva not yev7]Gopeva), instead of absolutely being ( ovra ) in them- selves distinct and imperishable substances. Thus, in the Timaeus, 49, C. : Uptirov psv o dr) vvv vdoop (bvopdnapsv , Tcrjyvvpevov, &g donovpsv, Xtdovg nal yrjv TirNOMENON optipsv • rrjnopsvov d’ av teal dtanpivopsvov ravrov rovro , rcvevpa nal aspa • (ovynavOevra ds tov aspa , nal tt vp) ava - ANCIENT DOCTRINE OF THE FOUR ELEMENTS. 123 iraXcv de avynpiOev nal naraadeadev, eig ’IAEAN re amov avOig depog nvp * nal naXiv aepa % vviovra nal nvnvovpevov, vefpog nal opi'xXrjv • in 6i tovtov etl paXXov gvpmXovpe- vcov, peov vdojp * i^vdarog de, yr\v nal XWovg avOig * nvnXov re ovtg) diadidovra eig dXXrjXa, cog tpaiverat , tt)v yeveaiv. “ For, in the first place, what we call water ( fluid ), when condensed, we behold becoming earth (or solid). Again, dissolved and separated, we behold this same thing becoming air [or gas). The air (gas), heated or being burned together (if ovynavOevra be a right reading ), becomes nvp, and nvp again having its particles more closely united and condensed by cold (naraadeadev), departs back again into the idea of air. Again, we see the air, when condensed, becoming cloud or vapour, and from them, when still more compressed, converted into flowing water. Finally, from water we be- hold again earth or solids, thus in a circle appearing suc- cessively to give birth or generation to each other.” Of the unknown elementary vXr] he thus speaks : did rr\v rov yeyovorog bparov nal navrog aiaOrjrov MHTEPA nal vnodo%f)v, prjre yrjv, prjre aepa, prjre nvp, prjre vdcop Xeycopev, prjre baa in rovrcov , j urjre it; cbv ravra yeyovev • aXX* aoparov eldog n nal ap,opcpov, navde^ig . p^eraXapda^ vov de anopebrara nr] rov vorjrov nal dvaaXcororarov avro Xeyovreg, ov 'ipevaopeOa. “ But as for the mother and re- cipient of everything which becomes an object ©f sight and sensation, let us call it neither solid, nor air, nor fire, nor fluid, nor anything which springs from these, nor anything from which these are (directly or immediately) generated, but the invisible species, having no form of itself, yet capa- ble of receiving all. Should we say that it is something which partakes in some most obscure way of the intelligi- ble, and that it is most difficult to be apprehended, we should not mistake.” Timgeus, 51, A. The term aoparog is not confined to the sense of sight, but is employed gen- erally for all that region which is beyond the sphere of 124 ANCIENT DOCTRINE OF THE FOUR ELEMENTS. sensation, or does not come under the cognizance of any of the senses. Sometimes, in its Platonic import, it is used for the intelligible , and is equivalent to vorjrov , but that does not seem to be the case here. There is, no doubt, an allu- sion in the above to Thales and Anaximenes, the former of whom held that water, and the latter that air, was this ele- mental principle, or mother of all things. The Greek philosophers and poets generally regarded nvp as a modification of matter more subtle than air, and nearer to that simple elementary substance or vXr] which was the basis of them all. Modern chemistry has experi- mentally developed this a priori idea of the ancient mind, in the discovery of that class of agents styled impondera- ble. Most abundant proof could be given, that by this term 7n)p was not meant merely the element, as commonly un- derstood, which goes by that name (although this was in- cluded), any more than by the term y?/, when thus philosoph- ically used, was intended only the earthy matter beneath our feet. Another name for this fourth modification was aWrjp. Some, indeed, made this a higher form than tti ;p, as the author of the treatise De Mundo once ascribed to Aristotle : Xeyoj de yr\g pev ev vdan , vdarog ev aepi , aepog ev TTVpl , 7 rvpdg de ev aiOepc , k. t. A. Ch. iii., p. 143. In general, however, all who held to but four modifications regarded the two last mentioned as one and the same. The peculiar region of the aether or fourth state was supposed to be all of space above the atmosphere, although at the same time interpenetrating and diffused through all below it. There seems to be an allusion to this in iEsch., Prom. Vine., 1090 : d) ndvrcov aWrjp kolvov (j)dog elXicocjv, where the poet clearly regards it as the source of vision, and seems to have held respecting it something like the modern undulating theory of light. At least, we can make ANCIENT DOCTRINE OF THE FOUR ELEMENTS. 125 no other sense of elXcaaov, which, in connexion with alOfjp and (j)dog , suggests at once to the mind that waving or en- larging spiral motion that the air undergoes in the propaga- tion of sound, and which, in the theory referred to, is sup- posed to take place in that universal fluid whose vibrations or undulations give rise to the phenomena of vision. In respect to the antiquity of this opinion, there is a remarka- ble passage in Aristotle’s Meteorologica, lib. i., c. 3. On account of its length, we give only a very concise version. “We have already (he says) spoken respecting the first element, what power it hath, and how that the whole uni- verse above us is full of that substance ( euecvov rov ocbpa- rog). And this opinion is not only entertained by us, but seems to have been a very ancient supposition, and to have been held by the primitive men ; for that which is called aether received of old the appellation which Anaxagoras seems to me to have regarded as the same with the fire. For he says that all the upper regions are filled with fire (rd avo nXrjprj irvpog elvai ), and yet he calls the same power, or the influence which pervaded that portion of space, the aether. And in this he was right ; for that sub- stance which remains forever unchanged men very natural- ly suppose to be a God, and Divine in its nature (to yap ’AEI c&pa 0EON dpa re 0EION, ac. t. A.), and they ac- cordingly defined such a substance by the name alOfjp (equivalent to del deog, or del decor), as though it had no identity with anything that pertains to us. Thus must we say , that not once, or twice, or a few times, hut with almost infinite repetitions, the same opinions come round in a circle (( dvativnXelv ) among men .” We think little of Aristotle’ etymology of alOfjp in this passage, but if this doctrine of the universal aether was, as he says, so ancient, and if it was held to be the cause of light and vision, it is certainly a remarkable confirmation of the closing sentiment, that ♦his same opinion should now be becoming everywhere a L 2 126 ANCIENT DOCTRINE OF THE FOUR ELEMENTS. favourite with our most scientific men, especially when modem wits had for so long a time made themselves merry with what they styled the ancient absurdities respecting a plenum and a vacuum. There is no doubt that Aristotle himself held light to be an undulating motion in a fluid affecting the sensorium of vision, as the undulations of the air affect that of the ear. This fluid he styles to diacjjaveg, and says that colour af- fects it, olov rov aepa , as the air ; vno tovtov tie ovvexovg bvrog, mvelrai to aloOrjrrjpiov • ov yap icaXtig tovto /ley ei ArjpdfcpiTog, oiopevog , el yevoiTO nevov to peTa^v, opaodac av aKptdu )g, teal el pvpprji; ev tgj ovpav (p eh j, tovto yap eoTiv advvaTOv. “ But by this fluid being continuous the sensorium is affected ; for Democritus is not right in the supposition, that if all the intervening space were a vacuum, we might see so sharply as to discover an ant in the sky. This, however, is impossible without an intervening me- dium,” &c. Aristot., De Anima, ii., 7. In the Pantheistic Orphic hymn, quoted by the author of the treatise De Mundo, and by the scholiast on Plato, De Leg., iv., 716, A., to which we have already referred, the sether is represented as the seat of the Divine intellect, or, rather, as the Divine or universal sensorium : vovg de oi d^evdrjg paoiXrjiog atyOiTog ’AIOHP gj drj navTa nXvec aai (ppa^eTat. Whether this fragment be spurious or not, it is unques- tionably of a very respectable antiquity. We have a simi- lar sentiment, although, in a style less pantheistic, in that common Homeric line, Zev , avdiOTe, peyiOTe KeXaivecfreg ’AI0EPI NAIS2N, and which, although immeasurably inferior, can hardly fail to call to mind the Scriptural declarations, Who alone dwell - eth in light inaccessible — Thou coverest thyself with light as with a garment. The sublimity of this is heightened ANCIENT DOCTRINE OF THE FOUR ELEMENTS. 127 by the thought that light, or, rather, the universal undu- latory aether which causes the sensation, is itself invisible. The Greek conception has a tinge of pantheism, and of the doctrine of the anima mundi . The Hebrew, besides its inexpressible sublimity, represents God as separated from the universe and veiled in thick darkness by the interven- tion of that very substance, which is the cause of light and knowledge to every portion of the worlds he has created. The Orphic and Homeric expressions, it is not absurd to suppose, arose from perversions of that purer idea which we find in the Bible. Similar language is frequently .to be met with in the tragic poets, and sometimes a knowledge of its Orphic application and origin is absolutely necessary in illustrating passages which would be otherwise most obscure. As when Sophocles, in one of the sublimest choral odes in the (Edipus Tyrannus, speaking of the an- tiquity of Law, represents it as born of the heavenly tether, ovpaviav aldepa renvoodevreg, or, in other words, the offspring of that universal sensorium or Divine Noi;^, which, according to the Orphic hymn, hath its peculiar dwelling-place in the aether. From this manner of employing the term, it became one of the names of Jove himself, being regarded as his peculiar province in the division of Saturn’s kingdom, as to Juno was allotted the air or lower atmosphere, and to Neptune the water. ’A rjp and aiOrjp are sometimes confounded by the poets, although the distinction between them is, on the whole, tol- erably well observed. ’A rjp is regarded as the source of respiratory , and of the lowest animal life ; aldrjp of -the higher life of sensation, and even of the intellect — the life of the spirit. Hence, as the one is from aco, arjpi, to breathe, the other is from atOco (old root ato)), to burn , to be hot ; in the same manner as the first expression of the idea 128 ANCIENT DOCTRINE OF THE FOUR ELEMENTS. of life (£aco, t$v) was most naturally associated with the appearance of self-motion in fermentation or ebullition. (See page 27, note 4, on the words and ^eco.) Hence we cannot help thinking that there is some connexion be- tween aWfjp, aiQo), and the verb atoOopcu , aloOdvopai. On this matter, some of the old poets and materializing philoso- phers may have indulged in views similar to what are now held by not a few modem savans, respecting the influence of an aethereal magnetic or galvanic fluid in the production of motion, sensation, and even thought. Hence Aristoph- anes, in the Clouds, 570, styles the aether fiioOpetipova : 5 Aidspa ospvoraTov flioOpsppova ndvrcjv. The scholiast thinks that it is here used for arjp. The higher sense, however, best accords with the term oepvo- rarov and other expressions of this writer, who, when he chooses to lay aside his buffoonery, is the most philosophical of all the Grecian poets, although much inclined to a ma- terializing pantheism. In another place, in the style of the Orphic hymn and Homer, he calls it the dwelling-place of Jove, "Oj uvvpi TOtvvv aWep’ olnrjcnv Aiog. Thesmoph ., 279. A Wrjp or nvp, on the one hand, and yrj on the other, be- ing the two extremes, are frequently spoken of together as the cogenerating causes, or male and female parents of all material existences. As in .ZEsch., Prom. Vinct., 88 : T £2 dlog cdOrjp — TTapprjTop re yrj. v j? \fj- pjy *■>:'*>* T) ft, A \ p -4 * * \ ? ' [ ' v fTOr ; > O i f * ’ \ */• v* So, also, in a fragment of Euripides, from the drama of Chrysippus, yala peyiorrj nal A Log alfffjp. On like grounds, in the dissolution and death of animate objects, this semi-materializing philosophy and poetry taught that the more refined or spiritual parts returned to ANCIENT DOCTRINE OF THE FOUR ELEMENTS. 129 the higher element from which they derived their origin, while the denser returned to the earth The Trvsvpa (spiritus) ascended to its kindred aidrjp. the fluids and grosser matter sank into the bosom of their mother yala, as in the line of Euripides which so strongly calls to mind Ecclesiastes, xii., 7 : ’E dear’ rjdrj y%j naXvcjiOrjvai VEKpovg, oOev 6’ ercaorov slg to dcbinsro kvravO* aTTEXOelv • TINETMA pev Trpog ’AI0EPA to otipa 6 ’ slg THN. Supplices , 533. Compare Orestes, 1085, and Helena, 1023: 6 vovg TG)V KdTOaVOVTCJV pEV OV , yVGjpTJV d’ E%El aOdvcLTOV Eig aOavaTOV AI0EP’ EpnEouv. Compare, also, the line of the fragment of the Hypsipyle from Stobseus, 108, in which we have the very language of the English Church burial service ; earth to earth — dust to dust : axOovTai (3pOToi elg yrjv (j)ipovTEg yv\v. In the case of the more gross and animal, it was supposed that the nvsvpa , being borne down by the attraction and weight of the earthy and sensual, and being unable to ex- tricate itself from it, sank into still lower forms, until puri- fied and set free by the penetrating and cleansing fires of Hades. See the Phsedon, 81, D. We cannot conclude this long and yet, as we trust, not altogether irrelevant excursus, without giving an extract from a fragment of Euripides, in which there is most beau- tifully expressed this departure of the elements to their native homes, and which we cannot help thinking to be genuine, notwithstanding it is strongly controverted by Valckenaer : 130 ATHEISTICAL DOCTRINE OF (pVGig^ ~VXV> AND T ^X V7 \' Xciipei 6 ’ 0776(76), rd /i£T eu yatag ( pvvr 5 £$• yalav , Ta d’ a7r’ aiOepiov fiXaoTOvra yovrjg elg ovpaviov iroXov fjXOe iraXiv • i9 vtjgicec d’ ovdev tgjv ycyvopevcov • diaKpcvopevov d ’ dAAo irpog aXkov j uopfpfjv Idlav airsdsi^ev. Valckenaer , Dlairib. in Eurip Frag. XIII. Atheistical Doctrine of (f>vGLg,rv^ 9 and re^v?]. Page 13, Line 16. i;(7£6 navra elvat teal rvxv (paGt* rex v XI de ovdev tovtcjv. 44 They say that all these things are by nature and chance , none of them by art ” That is, these first four states, namely, 7ri;p, a??p, &c., were the production of rvx 7 ] and votg , compare Aristotle, Physic. Ausc., lib. ii. , ch. 4. RELIGION AND LAW, NOT BY NATURE, BUT BY ART. 135 XIV. Atheistical Doctrine that Law and Religion were not by Na- ture, but by Art. Page 14, Line 10. Ovtu 6s teal rrjv vopodsotav ndoav , ov (pvoei, tsxvxi 6s. This is simply mentioned as one of the inferences from their doctrine, namely, “ that legislation or law was not by nature, but by art.” It was, however, just the inference that Plato deemed of the most dangerous con- sequence, and against which he directs all the strength of his reasoning, both here and in many other parts of his dia- logues. Compare the Gorgias, and especially that long argument of Callicles (482, C.), in which he advances this same doctrine, namely, that law, and right (to 6Uaiov ), and religion are not by nature, but by human appointment, which is equivalent to what the atheist here is supposed to mean by ts^vt]^ as something junior and posterior to nature : d)£ rd noXXa de ravra svavrla dXXfXoig sgtlv , tj ts (f>vcug teal 6 vdfiog, k. t. X. Gorgias, 483, A. It is a doctrine which in all ages has had its advocates, and in modern times has been specially revived by Hobbes and his followers. It is this inference that gives atheism all its interest. As a speculative tenet for the intellect merely, it would have no charms even for the darkest mind. If this creed be true, then not only religion, but also all morality, and all right views of law, are without any founda- tion either in God, or in any nature of things proceeding from him, or in any nature at all implying a moral sanction and which necessarily suggests the idea of something older, and higher, and stronger than itself. They are all, in that case, the offspring of T s^vt], or Art. That is, they have only a human origin ; since, in this creed, Art is the result of the junior production, Mind ; or, in the language which Plato ascribes to the atheist, vorspav etc tovtwv yevofisvrjv 0NHTHN sk ONHTS2N. They can, therefore, have only 136 RELIGION AND LAW, NOT BY NATURE, BUT BY ART. human sanctions, and it is this conclusion which, to the depraved soul, gives atheism all its value, while, if the in- tellect alone were concerned, it would shrink from it as from the very “ blackness of darkness” itself. The ancient atheists saw that there could be no true nat- ural morality without the belief in a God, and they did not pretend it. As in the moral and political philosophy of Plato, the Deity was the beginning, middle, and end : 6 pev 6?) deog (cjonep 6 iraXaiog Xoyog) apx'fjv re real te\ev- rr)v Kal peoa ru)v ovrtov andvruv £%6)T, lib. iv., 715, or, as he says in another place, 6 dr) -dedg rjplv ndvruv perpov av Etrj paXiara, 717 ; so, on the other hand, he justly rep- resents those against whom he is here contending, as hold- ing to no conscience, no law, no right and wrong, as well as no religion and no God. They reasoned, however,- like their modern followers of the school of Hobbes, in a vicious circle. From an atheistic assumption, they proved that law was not by nature, but by art, and then from this latter posi- tion, taken as established, they argued that Divine worship, being enjoined by law, was also by art, and*not by nature : fieovg eivai irpCdrov (paoiv ovtoi rex^V °v (pvoet, aXXa tlol vopoig. Page 14, line 20. We see the absurdity of the thing in the way Plato states their positions and their irpcbrov 'ipevdog ; yet, by conceal- ing this vicious and circular mode of reasoning, such writers as Hobbes have seemed to make out a most formidable argument. This atheistical dogma, that religion is the creation of law and the civil magistrate, is most strikingly set forth in the following fragment attributed by Sextus Empiricus (Advers. Matliem., lib. ix., sec. 54) to Critias, one of the thirty tyrants of Athens, and by Plutarch (De Placit. Philosoph., i., 6 and 7) to Euripides, who, he says, utters these sentiments in the character of Sisyphus instead of his own, through fear of the Areopagus. We give these verses in full, because of their intrinsic interest as one of RELIGION AND LAW, NOT BY NATURE, BUT BY ART. 137 the most remarkable remains of antiquity, because they set forth in all its strength the substance of all that has ever been said on this head from that time down to the present, and because they furnish a specimen of most finished poetry, of a higher stamp than atheism could have been supposed to employ in the utterance of its dark oracles : ’TL> xpovoc OT* 7]V LLTCLKTOQ avdptOTCCOV /3£og YLal ftypLudyg, ioxvog vnypETyg, "Or’ ovdev aeQlov ovre ToZg egOTioZglv yv , O vf av noTiaapa ToZg kclkolq kylvero. KanELTa poL doKovaiv dvdpcjnoL vopovg Qeodcu KohaoTag, Iva diny Tvpavvog y Tsvovg Pporelov , Tyv vfipiv 6ov\yv EXVi ’E £rj[LLOVTO 6\ EL TLQ E^apapTUVOL. *E KELT ETCELdrj Tup^aVT] [1EV 0L VOpOL ’AnsZpyov avTovg epya py npdoGELv (3ia, AaOpa 6’ snpaGGOV, rrjvLKavrd pot 6 okel $ vv r’ UKOVCOV KCLt (37 lE 7CG)V (j)povtiv t’ del, m IT pooExuv ts ravra t cal (pvGiv tislav povovv " Ev egtl '&e'lg)v. tovgSs TLg oyovg Pisyov A LdaypaTuv ytiiGTOv eloyyyGaTo , 'Tevcki Kakvtyag Tyv dlyOsLav Xoyc j. N ateiv 6’ E(j)aoK£ Tovg i Jsovg svTavO’, Iva M dTiLGTu y y EKnTiy^sLsv dvOpunovg, ayuv "OOev n Ep Eyvcj Tovg (j>66ovg elvaL ppoToZg K.al Tag ovyoEig tc 5 TaTiaLnupu (3Z(p , ’E/c Tyg vnspde nspityopag, Iv * aoTpanyg KaTsZd’ kvavGEig , Selvcl 6’ av nTvnypaTa B povTyg, to t’ uoTspunov ovpavov denag r Xpovov Kahbv noiniTipa, TEKTOvog GO(j>ov. M 2 138 RELIGION AND LAW, NOT BY NATURE, BUT BY ART. * OQev re Xa/urpog darepag onepx^i pvdpog, O #’ vypog tig yrjv opdpog EttTtopL&Tai. Toiovode 7r epLEGrrjGEv avdpcoTroig tyodov 'Zrotxovg, tcaTi&g re tcj Xoycp kcltguclgc T ov Aalpov’ oyn&v, kv 7rpenovTL x^pi V- A most masterly refutation of this atheistic dogma, espe- cially as it was, in more modern times, advanced by Hobbes, , may be found in Cudworth’s Intellectual System of the Universe, in which there is a most thorough and conclusive examination of the general doctrine, that morality and reli- gion are not by nature, or from the Divine mind, but are strictly conventional, that is, by human law. Plato also touches upon this subject in the Theaetetus, 172, B., where he sets forth the unavoidable conclusions of that flowing philosophy, which, rejecting ideas , and making man, or, in other words, sensations the measure of all things ( perpov rravrojv), utterly sweeps away all morality, all religion, all law, in short, all foundations whether of a civil or religious kind : Ovnovv nal nepl TzoXinnCbv (cpaa), naXd pev nal alo%pa, Sinaia nal dSina , nal baa nal p?], ola av enaorr] rcoXzg ozrjOezoa (t-vp^epovra elvai) # r\rai vopipa eavrirj, ravra real elvai rfi akrfleia enaarxj * nal ev rovrozg pev ovSev ooepebrepov ovre ISabrrjv ISubrov, ovre rroXtv noXecog elvai . nal ev rolg Scnaiozg nal dSznozg, nal ooiozg nal avo- GiOig , edeXovozv loxvpi^eoOai, d>g ovn eon (pvoez avrebv ovSev ’0Y2IAN eavrov aXXd to nozvyj So^av, rovro yiveraz aXrjdeg rore, orav So^. Theaetetus, 172, B., C. They assigned a rather higher rank to the idea of the beautiful (to naXov) than to that of the right . Ka£ 6?) nal rd naXa, (pvoei pev aXXa elvai , vopep de erepa * ra Se Srj dinaza odd’ elvai rorrapdirav (pvoez. Page 14, line 23. “ The beautiful , they said, was partly by nature and partly by law (that is, conventional agreement or custom), but the Just (or Right) had no foundation at all in nature,” or, in other words, was the creation alone of arbitrary enactment. THE FIGURE APOSIOPESIS. 139 The doctrines of an immutable standard of morals and of an immutable standard of taste must go together. Both are necessarily and consistently rejected by the atheist, and both should be strenuously maintained by all consistent theists. Physical, moral, intellectual, and religious beauty, although not the same, can all be traced to one common foundation. All are harmonies ; all spring from one root, and all are alike unmeaning notions, unless connected with that idea of God in which the Beautiful, the Righteous, and the Good (to fcaXdv , to ayadov , to diuacov) are all embraced and regarded, not only as older than human art ( $vr)T7 ) tex - vrj), but also than (pvvig, or Nature itself. Compare the argument of the atheist Callicles, in the Gorgias, 485 : a (pvOEL [lev ova eotl naXa vdfuo ds, k. t. X. XV. The Figure Aposiopesis. Page 15, Line 8. E i prj (frrjoovoiv. The apodosis here # is wanting, or, rather, interrupted in a manner, which, al- though frequent in Greek, would not be admissible in the English. This silent omission has sometimes a much more powerful effect than any expression of the apodosis, especially in the case of threatening and admonitions. The answer, in such examples, seems to be left entirely to con- science, as though it could not possibly mistake the proper response. There are very powerful and numerous in- stances of this in the Hebrew of the Old Testament, and from thence in the Hebraistic Greek of the New. One of the most striking may be found, Luke, xiii., 9 : nav pev TTOLrjorj rcapnov — eI 6e prjye. Compare, also, Luke, xix., 42 ; xxi /., 42 ; Acts, xxiii., 9; Romans, ix., 22 ; John, vi., 62. There is a very fine example, Iliad, i., 135 : 140 THE FIGURE APOSIOPESIS. akA? el [j,ev d&oovoi yepag f. leyaOvuoc ’AxaioX— el 6e tie pi) 6 g)g)olv . . . See, also, the ninth book of the Laws, 854, C., aal eav j uev ooi dptivTL ravra Acoa n to vooppa • — el 6e pr), &c. We have also an example very similar to the present in the Protagoras, 325, D., teal eav pev e^ioy Tcetdrjrai — el 6e I ui), &c., where, in the same manner, the answer is left to the inward voice, and the writer hurries on to the second condition as the principal clause. See, also, the Republic, ix., 575, I)., ovuovv eav pev enovreg vneirccjOLV — eav 6e pi), &c. ; Thucydides, iii., 3, teal fjv pev £ vpdirj , rj rceipa • — el 6e pi], &c. ; Plato, Symposion, 220, D., el 6e fiovXeode, n. 7. A. This has been most appropriately and beautifully styled by grammarians aposiopesis, or an omission arising from an excitement of the feelings, in which a gesture or a look is supposed to supply the place of the voice. Al- though these and similar cases- may by some be regarded as defects or irregularities in the Greek language, every scholar who has any claim to taste or philosophy must re- gard them as its highest beauties. It is a great pity that our own tongue had not more of this flexibility, and did not admit more licenses of a similar kind, instead of being so stiffly confined in that strait jacket which has been put upon it in the rules imposed, for the most part, by pedantic, unphilosophical, and unclassical writers on English Gram- mar ; for such, with some few exceptions, have been the great mass of those who have taken upon themselves to lay down the laws of this science, and to sit in judgment on Lowth and Murray. To return, however, to the sentence before us : if it is desired to avoid the aposiopesis, this may be done by taking all from nal nepl to ypacjxov inclusive, as a parenthesis, and then bringing in what follows as a repetition with an apodosis to el pi) (prjoovoiv. The only thing in the way of this is the particle de, the insertion of which, however, may be regarded as occasioned by the ARGUMENT FROM MOTION. 141 prodosis having been, in a measure, lost sight of in conse- quence of the length of the intervening parenthesis. XVI. Argument for the Existence of a God from Motion . Page 18, Line 22. ’A rjdsGrepcov Xoyuv. “ Unusual , or out of the common track” Reference is had to those subtle disquisitions respecting motion which are soon to follow. They are so called, because differing from the common and more obvious arguments generally made use of, such as those arising from evidence of design, and the more striking phenomena of the visible world, to which Clinias had so readily alluded in the commencement of the discus- sion. Plato thinks it best to begin at the beginning, or, as he elsewhere styles it, the fountain-head of the error : rr\v 7ir\yr\v avoiyrov dogrjg. If the least power or property of motion is conceded to matter, or to the least particle of matter per se, all is given up to the atheist, at least as far as the physical world is concerned. The whole cause is surrendered to the enemy. If this is granted, or not de- nied, then it would not be hard to admit that matter may also have an adaptive as well as a moving property, a tendency to an accommodation of itself to the circumstances in which it is placed, or, according to the doctrine just taught, a disposition to fit itself to those conditions in the universe into which it may be thrown by its own self- moving power, acting only under the direction of rv^r], or chance : £ vpnenrojfcev navra apfiorrovra olue'nog rrcog, paXaua npog GfcXrjpa, u. r. X. Here we are in the dark ‘region of occult qualities, and we can as well conceive of the one property as of the other. In fact, it is easier for the mind to admit this doctrine of an adaptive power, after conceding that of motion, than to receive the latter first as 142 ARGUMENT FROM MOTION. an independent starting-point. In this view, then, all ar- guments from fitness fall to the ground, unless the first mo- tion is shown to be the offspring of rexvr], and not of tvx^i or even of (pvcug. If we only give the atheist time enough — and eternity is very long — he may fancy that, on his theory, everything will at last fall into its proper place ^vpirlnreL oineiog ncog), and commence the natural dis- charge of its only and long-sought appropriate office Plato, therefore, takes his stand on the first position, namely, that the mere motion of matter implies the existence of Spirit as an older and higher essence, or, in other words, that Spirit alone is self-moving, because it alone possesses that duality which resolves itself at the same time into sub- ject and object . The term avroidvrjGLg is not to be con- fined to local motion, but may refer to any change in the state or condition of a thing. It may, therefore, be pred- icated of mind, or pure spirit, independent of space. In this sense volition is avTontv7]Gtg , or self-motion, even al- though it may never be exhibited outwardly. That matter cannot possess this, in either acceptation of the term, is an affirmation rendered necessary by the very laws of mind. It is involved in the term itself, or rather in the idea of which the term is the real, and not merely arbitrary rep- resentative, and may therefore be called a logical necessity. Although the argument may have something of the a pos- teriori form, it is nevertheless strictly a priori. It is a con- clusion not derived from experience ; for in truth, aside from the essential idea which the laws of our minds compel us to create, all our mere experience of matter is directly op- posed to it. As presented to our senses, it seems to be evei in motion, and this phenomenon exhibits itself more con stantly the more closely and minutely it is examined ; so' that if experience alone were to be consulted, or, to use the language of some of our Baconians, if nature alone were to be interrogated, motion would appear to be the law, and rest ARGUMENT FROM MOTION. 143 ' v if absolute rest were ever to be discovered) the exception. Notwithstanding all this, the mind cannot divest itself of that idea (whether innate, or acquired, or suggested) which it hath of body, as distinguished from space ; and whenever this idea is clearly called out, the soul doth affirm of neces- sity, and in spite of all the phenomena of experience to the contrary, that matter cannot move itself. The same ne- cessity compels it, also, to declare that matter cannot con- tinue motion by virtue of any inherent power, any more than it can commence it, and this, too, notwithstanding the opposing dogma so confidently laid down in all our books of natural philosophy. We have the constant observation of ten thousand motions, commenced and continued with- out the visible intervention of any spiritual agent, and ap- parently the result of innate properties, and yet, when the mind remains sound and true to itself, all this does not at all weaken the innate conviction, that every KLvrjOLg implies the existence of an originating will or spirit somewhere, however many the impulsive forces that may seem to have intervened between that will and its ultimate object. When the mind >3 in a healthy state, we say it is compelled to affirm, and does affirm this, with the same confidence as the proposition that the three angles of every triangle are equal to two right angles, or that two bodies cannot occupy the same space. Even this, notwithstanding it lies at the foundation of mechanical and dynamical physics, is ulti- mately to be resolved into a logical necessity , that is, a ne- cessary affirmation into which the mind is driven by those laws of its own, that form not only our highest, but our only idea of truth. Hence, having the idea, or that notion un- der which it is forced to think of matter, the soul affirms that two bodies occupying the same space are one bod)r because the last differentia , or erepotOTriq, is destroyed. (44 SOUL OLDER THAN BODY. XVII. Soul Older than Body. Page 19, Line 16. 2 a) par cov epnpooOsv Tcavrcjv yevo - fievrj. Compare with this Timaeus, 34, B. : T rjv 6s 6?) ibvx?] v ov% 6)g vvv vorspav smx^povpsv Xsysiv , ovrcog eprjxdvrjaaro uai o dsog vscorspav. ov yap av apx^Oai rcpsadvrspov vi to vecorspov ovvsp^ag etaosv. b 6s real ys- vsesi uai apery nporspav uai npeodvrepav 'ipvx'rjv ocoparog, fog 6sgtt6tlv teal dp^ovoav ap^opsvov ovveoryoaro. “ God did not create soul, as we now speak of it (in the order of our argument), posterior and junior ; for he would not have suffered an elder thing to be ruled by a younger. Where- fore he constituted soul, both by virtue and by birth, to be prior to and older than body, as the mistress and ruler thereof.” The term ijn’XV is used here in a less sense than in the tenth of the Laws, where it includes all that is immaterial, and is employed in a peculiar manner for God as distinguished from (pvoig . It, however, means much more, in this passage of the Timaeus, than the soul of man. The philosopher is speaking of soul collectively, the animus mundi , or Soul of the Universe, as distinct from, inferior to, and dependent upon, the Deity who had constituted it (ovv- eoTrjGaro , ep7]x av V aaT0 )’ and yet as the source, and fountain from which all other souls emanate or are generated, whether of men or of the inferior Divinities, according to that verse of Pindar, Nem., Carm. vi., 2., a., 1, 2 : n Ev ay6pfov, sv ftefov ysvog • eu ptdg 6s rcvsopsv parpog apfporepoL. If soul is older than body or matter, then the properties or innate powers (cvyyevr]) of the former must be also be- fore those of the latter. Wherefore, as he says below, 661-a 6rj real smpsXeia ual vovg ual rsxv?] ual vopog ( rd SOUL OLDER THAN BODY. 145 ovyyevrj ipvxVG)* TTporspa av etrj anXrjpcbv nal j uaXantiv nal /3ap£G)v nal novcpcov (rtiv TTpoarjnovTUv Gupan). “ Thought, and providence, and reason, and art , and law , must have been before hard, and soft, and heavy, and light.” It is evident that the term otipa here is not taken for organized substances, but is in all respects equivalent to our word matter ; for he mentions only those elementary properties which belong to it, or were supposed to belong to it as matter, such as hardness or resistance, weight, &c. So that there is nothing in this word against the inference we have drawn respecting Plato’s opinion on the eternity of the material world, whether regarded as organized or unor- ganized. It seems to us perfectly clear that in every sense of the word, as used by the modern philosophy, he held matter to be junior to soul. The order of the argument, it should be observed here, is the direct opposite of what is commonly styled the a posteriori. In the latter, we proceed from evidences of fit- ness in matter to a soul or art , which, for all that this method can oppose to the contrary, may have been the offspring of an older tyvoig, of whose adaptations its designs may be only an imperfect imitation, whether regarded as proceed- ing from the soul of man, or of some superhuman being. In the other, the older existence of spirit is first establish- ed, and then it is inferred, even before experimental induc- tion, that there must be such evidences of design, because art and law, which are properties of soul, must be older than the material structures in which they are exhibited. On the scheme of the atheist, or the naturalist (the worship- per of (pvotg ), only some of the smaller and latest produc- tions were the work of tex vt ] making its appearance in the latter cycles of the universe. In the other view, which the author here presents, ra peyaXa nal npebra epya nal npa %- eig rexvrjg av yiyvoiro, ovra ev irptiroLr, ra 6e (\>vaei nal iiVGiq varepa nal apxopsva av en rexvrjg ecrj nal vov N 146 COMPARISON OF THE DANGEROUS FLOOD. “ The great and first works would be the works of arl t while the things of nature, and even nature herself, would be posterior to, and ruled by art and mind.” There is likewise another view which is essential to the full interpretation of the passage, namely, that not only was it impossible that these phenomena of matter should exist objectively , without the previous existence of soul as an effi- cient cause of that substance of which they are phenomena, but also that they could not exist subjectively without a soul of which they constitute the sensations. In this sense, also, is it true that spirit must be older than hard , and soft , and visible , &c. Compare the passage in the Phsedon, in which he refutes the doctrine that the soul is only a har- mony, by showing that its pre-existence is essential to har- mony itself, and that, where the former is not present, the latter is nothing more than dead strings, and chords, and tensions, and relaxations, and vibrations of the air, but has as harmony no real or true being. It is clear that the same reasoning may be carried down through all the elementary properties of matter. XVIII. Remarkable Comparison of the Dangerous Flood. Page 21, Line 3. hrconelre ovv , uaddnep el norayov rjyag edei rpelg Hvrag diabatveiv peovra otyodpa , k. t. A. The common reading is el tcaddnep. We have ventured to make the change from the exigency of the place, and on the authority of Stephanus. “ Consider, then, as if we three had to cross a violently flowing river,” &c. The Athenian here most graphically compares himself and his two com- panions, just entering upon this most profound and difficult argument respecting motion, to men who are about to plunge into a deep and rapid torrent, and who, therefore, need the COMPARISON OF THE DANGEROUS FLOOD. 147 utmost caution in the examination of every step, lest, if at any point they should lose a firm foothold, they might be overwhelmed in floods of darkness, and carried down the stream of doubt, without any chance of recovery. The comparison is admirably sustained, and even when it seems to be dropped, does nevertheless continue to affect the dis- course, and tinge the style with a metaphorical hue for many sentences ; as in the expressions, A oyog otpodporepog teal abarog — napacpepopevog, page 22, and exopevoc cog n - vog aocpaXovg neioparog , page 23. Cicero was very fond of imitating Plato, and we cannot help thinking that he had this passage in his eye, and meant to institute a similar comparison in respect to himself, when placed in like cir- cumstances in reference to another great truth. Itaque du - bitans , hcesitans , circumspectans , multa adversa reverens, tamquam in rate in mari immenso , nostra vehitur oratio. Cicero, Tusc. Disp., i., 30. So, also, in the Phaedon, after exhausting the direct ar- guments for the immortality of the soul, Socrates “ trusts himself to the best of human reasons (that is, to the old and unbroken tradition respecting the doctrine) as the safest vessel to which the soul could be committed, and on which alone, although in continual danger of shipwreck, it could be expected to outride the storms of doubt ; unless , perhaps , it might hereafter find a surer vehicle in some Divine reve- lation , or Xoyog tielog, which Heaven might yet condescend to make known to men We do not know which to admire most, the sound philosophy, the unaffected humility, or the striking imagery, with which the whole passage abounds. A elv yap nepl avra ev ye n tovtcjv bcanpa^aodcu, iq pa- Oelv onrj iq evpelv , fj, el ravra advvarov rbv yovv QeXriOTOV rtiv avOpconivcov Xoyo)v Xadovra enl tovtov dxovpevov, toonep enl ox^dcag, luvdvvevovra dianhevoai rbv j3iov • el prj rig dvvatro aacpaXearepov ttal cuavdvvore pov, £nl fiedaiorepov bxppcLrog rj AOrOT 0EIOT rtvog 148 INVOCATION OF DIVINE AID. dtanopevOrivat,. Phaedon, 85, E. We take avOpumvo $ X oyog, in this passage, not in the sense of reason or argu- ment, but rather as it is used in the Gorgias, 523, A., at the introduction of the mythical representation of the judgment after death : atcove paXa uaXov Xoyov, ov av pev fjyrjO'Q pv- Oov , 6e Xoyov. In the word ox^biag above, Plato seems to have had an eye to Homer’s account of the ship- wreck of Ulysses, in his voyage on such a vessel from the island of Calypso, and thus to intimate that this /3eX rtorog tcjv avOpG)nivG)v Xoyov could be regarded as at best only a temporary support, until the coming of that more sure ( 'fiebaLorspog ) word of Revelation. Can we doubt that the soul of our philosopher would have rejoiced in the an- nouncement that there was even then in the world a “ sure word of prophecy, like a light shining in a dark place” and that he would have surrendered all his speculative reason- ing for the security and comfort of such an assurance ? XIX. Invocation of the Divine Aid in the Argument. Striking Examples of this from other Dialogues . Page 22, Line 11. *Aye 6rj, Oeov elnoTe rcapauXriTeov rjplv, vvv sotg) tovto ovrco yevopsvov. “ If ever we ought to call upon God , let it he done now” Many professed Christian writers, both metaphysicians and theologians, might here take a lesson from the heathen philosopher. What more sublimely appropriate than this petition for Di- vine aid in an argument against those who denied the Divine existence ? The dark, violent, and almost impassable tor- rent upon which they are about to embark is yet kept in mind, and in view of this the soul is led to seek for some aid out of itself. There is, we think, an allusion to some of those prayers which Homer puts into the mouths of his INVOCATION OF DIVINE AID. 149 heroes, as they are about to engage in some arduous and perilous contest ; it may be to the prayer of Ajax for light in that desperate battle (lib. xvii., 645) in which Jove covers the whole held of conflict with thick darkness ; or, perhaps, in still greater consistency with the metaphorical imagery here employed, to the prayer of Achilles, in the twenty-flrst book of the Iliad (273), when in danger of being over- whelmed by the rising floods of the angry and turbulent Scamander : Zev rrdrep , dog ovrtg pe ftecov eXeecvov vneor? ], etc TTorapolo oaoooai. Whether this be so or not, it is in this case a prayer which the purest Christianity need not blush to acknowl- edge and admire. There are several interesting examples of similar invocations in others of the Platonic dialogues, either put into the mouth of Socrates or of some speaker by whom he is evidently represented. We have but little doubt, too, that in these remarkable peculiarities of charac- ter, Plato accurately represents the model he so closely ob- served, and with whom his own intellectual existence may almost be regarded as identified. We may note, among others, the invocation in the fourth book of the Laws, at the commencement of his system of positive legislation for the state ; a work which certainly, of all others, should never be attempted without a deep feeling of the necessity of Divine assistance. Qedv 6rj 7Tpdg rr\v rr}g noXecog uarao- tcevrjv emuaXcopeOa * 6 de auovaeie re, ttai vnatcovcrag IXe- cog evpevrjg re rjplv eXOol, ovvduncooprjGcov rrjv re ttoXlv teal rovg vopovg , 712, B. “ Let us invoke the aid of God in the construction of our state. May he hear us, and when he has listened to our requests , may he kindly and propitiously come to our assistance, that he may jointly with us arrange in order the state and the laws” How much higher a light than this is boasted of by those modern law-makers who N 2 150 INVOCATION OF DIVINE AID. have endeavoured, as far as they could, to banish the voice of prayer from our legislative halls ! Compare, also, the Philebus, 25, B : Beog j uev ovv (rjplv cppacrei) av 7r ep ye epalg ev%aig knrjfcoog ycyv^rai. Here, too, the subject, in the discussion of which the Divine aid is invoked, is of the very highest importance, being no less than a most profound analysis of the radical difference between physical or sen- sual, and spiritual pleasure ; a theme, in his estimation, so holy, that, when again alluding to it in the sixth book of the Republic, he utters the same word (evcprjpei,) which was employed in driving all profanation, whether of speech or action, from the sacrificial altar, Rep., vi., 509, B. Perhaps, however, the most striking example of an invo- cation of this kind may be found in connexion with that sublime prooemium of the Timseus, to which we have al- ready alluded. That too, it should be borne in mind, is a. treatise on law, or, in other words, the legislation of the physical and intellectual universe, embracing equally the laws of mind and matter : 'AXXa, rovro ye dij navreg oool nal nara Ppaxv OGXppoovvrjg psrexovoiv, eirl ndo^ dppfj nal opuepov nal peyaXov irpayparog tieov del irov naXovav • rjpdg 6e rovg irepl navrog Xoyovg TcoieloOaC mj peXXovrag, el yeyovev , rj nal dyeveg ectlv , avaynr} fteovg emnaXovpe- vovg evxeoOai ndvrag Kara vovv enelvotg pev paXiora , eiropevcjg 6e rjplv elnelv, 27, C. “ Even those who have but little of sobriety, in the undertaking of any affair, wheth- er of small or great consequence, always call upon God. Much more, then, when about to engage in a discussion re- specting the universe, whether it is generated or eternal , ought we to invoke God by prayer, that what we say may be, first of all, according to his mind, and then consistent with ourselves.” • # Page 23, Line 1 . Irrovd^j irdaq TTapanenXrjoOGiv. The prayer on the present occasion has all the conciseness and simplicity that characterize all the recorded petitions of INVOCATION OF DIVINE AID. 151 Socrates. Compare the last he ever uttered, for an easy death, just before taking the cup of poison in the prison, Phaedon, 117, B : ’AA/C evx^Oal ye ttov rolg tieolg eijeorL re nal xpf rrjv pETo'utr\oiv rrjv evOevSe eicelge evtvx ?} ye - vegQcll • a dr) teal eyd> evxopai re, nal jevolto ravr^j. The longest specimen is that remarkable prayer at the end of the Phaedrus, or the dialogue on Spiritual Beauty, which we cannot resist the temptation of quoting in full : T £2 $IAE IIAN re nal aXkoi deoL, doirjrs pot naXip yEVEoOat rdvdo- 6ev , ra^coOev 6e ooa rolg Evrog elva'i pot, (ptXia * ttXov- giov 6e vop'foipi rov coepov * to 6e xP V(J ov nXfjOog elrj (lot ogov fjirjTE (pEpEcv prjre dyeiv dvvairo aXXog rj 6 erw- < ppo)v , 279, B. “ Oh thou beloved Universal Numen , and ye other Divinities , grant that I may become beautiful within , and that whatever of externals I may possess may be all in har- mony icith my inward ( spiritual ) being. May I regard the wise alone as rich ; and may I have just so much of gold as no other would, take from me but the virtuous man” The last sentence is somewhat obscure, but the whole petition ap- proaches the spirit of the Gospel, although lacking some of the essential requisites of a Christian supplication. It may justify us in hoping that its author, had he received the rev- elation for which he longed, would not have remained “ far from the kingdom of Heaven but it furnishes no grounds for the extravagant language of one who said, in his enthu- siastic admiration of the heathen sage, sancte Socrates ora pro nobis. He is represented here, however, as receiving a strengthening of his confidence, and some degree of as- surance from his supplication ; for he says immediately, u holding fast to this ( that is, the hope of Divine aid) as by some sure cable , let us embark ,” %eve, onorav (pq rig, apa eorrjfce pev navra, fctvelrat, 6e ovdev ; fj tovtg) nav tov- vavrlov ; For the common reading nara 6e, established by the concurrence of all the manuscripts, Ast would substitute Kara rads, connecting it with (paiverai in the preceding sentence ; and in this he follows Eusebius and the version of Ficinus. We think the common reading is correct, and that Ast and Ficinus have mistaken the spirit of the passage. The Athenian, entering alone in this dan- gerous flood, to try, as he says, its depth and strength, be- fore calling upon his companions to follow, assumes for a time the parts both of interrogator and respondent. He con- sequently supposes an objector from the atheistic or Ionic school, adopting some of the peculiar phraseology or cant terms of that sect, and taking him up in the midst of his positions in some such way as this, “ And so , then (teal elra de), answer me, if you please, one of these three questions : Do all things stand, and does nothing move ? or is the op- posite of this the case, namely, that all things move and nothing stands ? or do some things move and some things stand ? Give me, I say, an answer to these old queries, which have so long perplexed our schools of philosophy.” To which supposed objector the Athenian replies by taking the third hypothesis as his starting position in this argu- ment. There is much vivacity in this mode of introducing ‘he discussion about motion, and Kara ( nal elra) is the very particle by which it is best effected ; it being used to introduce a sudden inference, and implying a previous ar- THE ANCIENT dUESTION, DO ALL THINGS FLOW? 153 gument, in the midst of which the objection is supposed to be made. If any alteration of the established text is to be allowed, we think it should consist in changing de into 6t]. On the particle elra , see note, page 40. Whatever else may be intended, there can be no doubt that there is here an allusion, at least, to the same ques- tions which are so fully discussed in the Thesetetus, and stated there several times in nearly this same language. See, especially, Theaetetus, 180, D. These were the fa- mous problems which so divided, first the Ionic and Italian schools, and afterward the physical and metaphysical schools of Elea ; embracing, however, a much wider range than the merely dynamical points to which Plato, in the present argument, confines himself. There is an allu- sion to them in the Memorabilia, lib. i., c. i., 14 : teal rolg l iev del fuveloOat, navra , rolg 6e ovdev av rrore mvrjOfjvai . In this language was stated the great debate between those who referred all things to sensation, making it the measure of all reality, or what Plato styles tt)v (pepofievrjv ovoiav (Theaetetus, 179, C.), and those who held to a higher and immutable world of ideas ( tt)v ditlvrjrov ovoiav , the immove- able essence ), the real and only dXrjOtig ovrcjg ovra , while they regarded the objects of sense as continually moving, changing, never for a moment remaining the same, and having nothing about them (aside from the idea, or Xoyog , which, by its connexion alone, imparted to them a temporal reality) that could constitute real being ( ovoiav ) in the highest and truest senses of the word. They formed, as we have elsewhere observed,* the grand line of separation between two ever opposing systems of philosophy, and right *views, in almost every department of knowledge, are more or less connected with these subtle inquiries when viewed in their widest relations. Their odd phraseology may be more fully interpreted thus : What constitutes real * Discourse on the True Idea of The State, Andover, 1843. 154 THE ANCIENT GlUESTION, DO ALL THINGS FLOW ? ity ? Are all things in a perpetual flux ? Is there nothing in the universe but phenomenal facts and sensations, or is there a world of truth and being separate from, and inde- pendent of, the perceived and apparent — not merely as gen- eralizations of the mind, but as realities, more stable than the earth, more permanent than the old rolling heavens — ideas fixed, immoveable ( dtdvrjra ), eternal, which were nev- er born, and which can never die — the del Kara ravrd nai daavrcog e^ovra, the dig aXpOdg ovrcog ovra, from which all individual things derive reality, and by partaking alone of which they become the true objects of science, or emor- ijgai instead of do^ai. There is quite a full account of the systems of philosophy, of which these questions were the symbols, to be found in the dialogue Theaetetus. Plato there makes Homer (wheth er sportively or not, it is difficult to determine) the head and founder of that Ionic school which held that all tilings flowed ; and this because the poet represents Oceanus and Tethys as the original and mother of Gods and men. We greatly doubt whether in this Homer had any philosophical or mythical sense at all. If, however, anything of the kind was intended, there would seem to be nothing more than an allusion to the doctrine afterward advanced by Thales, that water was the apx^Jy or originating element of the uni- verse, and so the matter is viewed by Aristotle, Metaph ., i., 3. This doctrine of Thales was, in all probability, deri- ved from a corrupt and perverted tradition of the Mosaic account of the creation, where it is said that “ The Spirit of God ivas brooding over the waters ,” and the succeeding hypotheses of Anaximander and Anaximenes, one of whom held that air , and the other that infinite space was the first principle of the universe, were only attempts to refine upon what seemed to them the grosser element of Thales. In the later writers, however, who may be regarded as being in the line of this school, these speculations, and the THE ANCIENT QUESTION, DO ALE THINGS FLOW? 155 phraseology employed in reference to them, assumed a dif- ferent aspect, and were applied to the moral and mental, as well as the physical world. In the Thesetetus, Socrates is represented as thus setting forth their doctrine : (hg apa ev pev avro tcaO’ avro ovdev eortv • etc be Srj (popag re teal tei- v 7 ]OEG)q teal tepdoeevg irpoq aXXrjXa y iyverai navra a bfj (pa- pev EINAI ovte opOcbg Trpooayopevovreg * ’E2TI pev yap ovbenor ’ ovdev , del de riPNETAI • teal rcepl rovrov ixav- reg e%rjq ol oo(pol, rcXrjv Uappevidov , %vp(pepeodov, IT pora- yopag re teal f llpdieXetrog teal ’ EpnedotcXrjg ■ teal rtiv TTOtrj- Tcbv ol atepot rrjg Ttoir\oe acverai , to tov 'O firjpov* aioolog re poi apa dtivog re. Gvpnpoasp^a yap 6rj to avdpi navv veog 7:dvv 'npeodvr'q, teat poi e UvOayopSLOv nva nal II appevideiov efyXoyittig (3lov. From this passage in the Thesetetus some have inferred that Plato was guilty of an anachronism in the circumstances mentioned in the be- ginning of the dialogue Parmenides. A careful examina- * Iliad, iii., 172 : Mdolog t£ pot kooi, LXe knvpe, deivog re. THE ANCIENT aUESTION, DO ALL THINGS FLOW? 159 lion, however, will show, as we think, that such an infer- ence is without any real foundation. We would remark generally respecting some of the phi- losophers of the Ionic school, that we cannot accurately sit in judgment on their doctrines, or decide whether they were really, and in the grossest sense, atheistic materialists or not, unless we can determine what they included in their term iravra, when they said that all things flowed. If they merely meant thereby that the material world was ever flowing, this might have been consistent with a pure the- ism, and they might have even drawn arguments from this view of things in favour of a higher attention to the spirit- ual and supernatural. Such may possibly have been the case with Heraclitus. The sophist Protagoras, we have reason to believe on other grounds, was an unqualified athe- ist. Of Empedocles, who is also in Plato’s list, we hope better things, judging from many of the fragments of his po- etry that have been preserved, and especially that line which we have already referred to, pages 77, 115. They have doubtless suffered in the extravagances of their followers, some of whom carried their doctrines to a most ridiculous extent. One of them, as we are told by Aristotle ( Metaph ., iii., 5), heraclitized ( 'jipafcXeiTi&Lv ) to such an extent, that he denied that any one could leap twice, or even once, over the same stream, or that it was possible to speak the truth in any case whatever, because the terms of every proposition were changing and becoming false in the very process of articulation. Hence he finally conclu- ded not to open his lips, but, to every question, made no other reply than simply to move his finger : og to reXevralov ovdev g ')£to 6etv Xeyetv, aXXd rov daurvXov e/rivet govov. Some, on the other hand, carried the propositions that sense was knowledge, and that man was the measure of all things, to such an extreme, as to affirm that everything was true, and that there could be nothing false ; the seeming oppo- 160 THE ANCIENT QUESTION, DO ALL THINGS FLOW? site of the former, but, in reality, only the same absurdity in another shape. This last extravagance, however, brought its own antidote along with it ; for, if all things were true, the proposition which denied this dogma was equally true with all the rest, and so, like the famous syllogism respect- ing Epimenides the Cretan, the result was an everlasting circle of alternate contradictions. See Aristot., Metaph ., iii. (iv.), 5. Cicero , Academ . Posieriorum , i., 12. This school of sophists, as Socrates tells us in the Theae- tetus, were likewise famous for a quibbling and eristic logic, yet had a great aversion to that sober and truth-evincing system of dialectics which was carried on by question and answer. A somewhat ludicrous account of this may be found page 180, A., B., &c. Their logic was like their philosophy, ever flowing, and incapable of being reduced to any firm and fixed conclusions. “ You can do nothing with them (says Socrates), nor can they among themselves ar- rive at anything certain and satisfactory, but take special care that, neither in their language nor in their philosophy, shall there be anything which has firmness or stability ( oraoifiov ) ; but against this they are continually warring, and, as far as they can, would banish all rest from the uni- verse. This, although not the same, has some resem- blance to the modern doctrine of eternal progress, which, of course, is eternal imperfection, and which allows of no- thing fixed or established, any more than the ancient tenet that all things flowed , and that nothing stood. This phi- losophy, too, like some of the sophisms of our own day, had “ a wonderful alacrity at sinking” down into the vulgar mind, and of inspiring the masses with the most exalted opinion of the doctrine and its teachers ; “ so that the very coblers (ot ouvrordfioi), when they had imbibed or become inspired with this profound system of fluxions, abandoned at once that foolish old notion, that some things stand (enav- oavro 7]Xidi(oq olopsvoL ra pev karavai ra 6s mvsloOai THE ANCIENT QUESTION, DO ALL THINGS FLOW? 161 tg)V ovtgjv), and when they were told that all things were moving , they greatly honoured those who taught them this,” as being a most comforting and democratic doctrine. See Thesetetus, 180, A., B., &c. In the Cratylus, which, although, in the main, a sportive jeu d'esprit, does yet abound in very many most important and serious views, Plato dwells at some length on two the- ories of language which may be derived from these two systems of philosophy, in one of which the idea of motion, and in the other that of rest, are made respectively the ba- sis of an inquiry into the primitive etymological structure of words. After most ridiculously deriving ovolav (< tboiav ), or essence, from to (bOovv ( pushing or impulse ), because, on this hypothesis of Heraclitus, rd ovra ievai re rcavra nal pevetv ovdev, “ all real existences were ever moving- on, or pushing ahead, and nothing stood still” (401, C.), he comes to speak of Kronus and Rhea (pea), when Socrates, in his old ironical method, suddenly affects that in this name there is suggested to him this whole flowing philos- ophy. “ Oh, my good sir (he exclaims), I have just dis- covered a whole hive of curious lore, oprjvog tl oocpiag — A eyei yap nov f H panXeirog on rravra %u>pel aal ovdev pe- vet, nal norapov porf dnetfca^cov ra ovra Xeyec, (bg dig eg rov avrov irorapov ovtc av epdalrjg, k. r. A.” “ Heraclitus somehow says that all things are moving, &c,, and, in his comparison of existences to the course of a stream, he even says that one could not twice enter into the same river.* Do you suppose, then, that he who originally gave names to Rhea and Kronus, the progenitors of the other Gods, had any other philosophy than this of Heraclitus ? or do you * He would seem to mean something more here than a mere illus- tration. Since all being is compared to one ever-moving stream, the expression, that we cannot twice enter the same river, would signify, that neither our own personal identity, nor the identity of the universe, can remain for two consecutive moments. O 2 162 THE ANCIENT aUESTION, DO ALL THINGS FLOW? think that through mere accident he gave these flowing names to both? Just as Homer makes Oceanus and Te- thys the original and mother of the Gods, and I think He- siod also. But Orpheus surely says, ’12 Keavdg np&TLora tcaXippoog fjpge ya\ioio • og pa fca(uyvr}T7)v dfiopirjTopa T rjOvv onviev. See how all these things accord with one another, and how they tend to these doctrines of Heraclitus.” Cratylus , 402, A., B. At the conclusion of the first part of this etymological excursus, in which he sportively finds the origin of so many words in this ancient flowing theory, he assigns as the cause of it all the want of stability in their own brains (to adopt a modern phrase), which they mistook for the ever- lasting change of things and truths themselves. “ I think (says Socrates, with grave irony) that I indulged in no bad surmise, when I just now supposed that the very ancient men ( ol navv naXaiot), who gave names to everything, just like many of our modern wits (rtiv vvv ootfitiv), in consequence of their getting frequently turned round in their search into the real nature of things, became dizzy, and then things themselves appeared to be whirling around, and to be borne in every direction. Wherefore they blame not the internal state of their own souls as the real cause, but say that this is the very nature of things , that there should be nothing firm or stable, but that all things flow (n avra pelv), and are full of motion, change, and generation.” Cratylus, 411, C., D. And again, 439, C., he thus char- acterizes the whole school under an ironical allusion to the old authors of language : “ They seem to me to have thus thought (namely, that all things are in motion), but, in real- ity, it is not so. For the fact is, that they themselves are utterly confounded, like men who have fallen into a whirl pool, and would wish to drag us in after them. For con THE ANCIENT QUESTION, DO ALL THINGS FLOW? 163 sider this, O most excellent Cratylus, of which I am often dreaming,* can we in truth affirm that there are such real- ities as the Beautiful, the Good,” &c. ? 3 eyd) noAhaiug ovecpojTTG), norepov (jiojpev tc elvat avro TO KAAON uat ’AFAOON ual ev ercaorov tcjv ovtgjv ovrcog In this philosophy, too, he shows that there could be no true moral or political science, no law, no real State, no so- cial or civil rights, with their corresponding obligations. See the Theaetetus, 172, B., and the remarks thereupon, page 138. There could be no science, he affirms, of any kind, for it must necessarily be grounded on the eternal and im- mutable. A coOrjocg would take the place of emoTrjprj, and nothing could be really known : ’A/lAd prjv ovd’ civ yvoo- 0si7] ye vtt ’ ovdevdg ovdev • apa yap av emovrog rov yvco- oouevov aXXo teal aXXolov ycyvocro • nai etc rovrov rov Xoyov ovre to yvooopevov ovre to yv(oo0r]o6pevov av eerj. Hence he draws the sublime conclusion, that, since the very laws of our being compel us to affirm the real, and not mere- ly relative existence of these ideas, therefore there is some- thing which is eternal and immutable, or, in the language of the ancient schools, all things do not flow, but some things stand. EZ de eon pev dec to ytyvCbouov, eon 6e to del ycyvcoouopevov, eon de to KAAON, eon de to ATAOON, eon de TO AIKAION, ov poc (pacverac ravra op.ota ovra po^\ ovdev ovde cj)opa. “ But if there is something which eternally knows , and something which is eternally known — if there is THE BEAUTIFUL, and THE GOOD, and THE JUST, then things do not all seem to me to be similar to mo- tion or a flowing stream .” Cratylus , 440, B. * bveipuTTo. No word could better express that peculiar state of mind in which Socrates (or Plato) often contemplated his favourite doctrine of ideas. Sometimes he seems to be perfectly assured of the real existence of the nakov, &c., the Fair, the Just, and the Good. Again, he appears perplexed with doubt, and, at other times, seems to have but a glimpse, as in a dream, of some such bright rem- iniscences of a better state. 164 MATHEMATICAL USE OF THE WORD Xoyog XXI. Mathematical Use of the Word Xoyog. Page 24, Line 6. ava Xoyov . The common reading is avdXoyov ; the other, however, is unquestionably to be preferred. It would signify here 'proportionally , certa qua - dam ralione. This is called in Latin ratio , and in Greek Xoyog (especially in all mathematical writings), because a simple quantity or magnitude, irrespective of the relation it bears to another as a multiple or a divisor, cannot be an ob- ject of science, or be contemplated by the mind. It remains only an object of sense, aloOrj-rov , being, to the intellect, dXoyov , and therefore ayvcoorov. See the Theaetetus, 202, B. It is this relation or ratio which becomes the true votjtov , or real object of the mind, while the sensible figure serves only as the diagram by which it is exhibited. Hence it is styled the Xoyog, ratio, or reason . It is that which is predicated of its subject, and hence is its Xoyog, or word , as well as reason ; because, when viewed as sim- ple quantity or magnitude, nothing can be said about it, no truth affirmed respecting it. This Xoyog, or reason , ever implies a third thing or mid- dle term, namely, the common measure or divisor to which both quantities must be referred, and by which we are ena- bled to predicate the one as a part, or multiple, or any cer- tain ratio of the other. The Xoyot or ratios are absolute and immutable verities of science, as all voTjra must be, while the alaOrjrd by which they are suggested are muta- ble, flowing, and without anything which can be styled ab- solute. They likewise are capable of being compared among themselves, and thus give rise to others — ratios of ratios, ad infinitum. In modern works the simple radical meaning of the term is lost sight of, because we use the Latin ratio without any reference to its primary sense, as MATHEMATICAL USE OF THE WORD Xoyog. 165 the same with the Greek koyog, and hence the great vague- ness which prevails in most minds respecting this plain mathematical idea. In some of our older mathematical works, such as the English editions of Euclid’s Elements by Dee and Barrow respectively, our own word reason is everywhere properly employed instead of ratio. By this means the metaphysical notion of ratio is kept before the mind as the intelligible, by which what would otherwise be merely, as magnitude, an object of sense, becomes known to the intellect as an object of science. See Proclus, Com- mentary on Euclid’s Elements, lib. i. All mathematical truths, and especially the geometrical, are ultimately to be resolved into a comparison of ratios. For even parallelism, and other properties which would seem to have no connexion with it, do, after all, depend upon certain equalities or correspondences, from which they derive their Xoyoq, notion, or definition. So that all mathematical science is finally brought down to those in- nate ideas of the to loov , &c., which are discussed in the Phsedon, and of which visible magnitude is only suggestive. Even a straight line involves this idea of the to loov, or simplest ratio. It is that which lies evenly, equally, or, as it is expressed by Euclid, e^toov, between its extreme points ; that is, having nothing capable of being predicated of the one side and not of the other. Playfair and others seem to have entirely misunderstood the expression, and to have greatly bungled in their efforts to amend, by substitu- ting a far more complex idea for this old and perfect defini- tion of Euclid. Any one who is capable of consulting his own consciousness, must acknowledge that the language of Euclid best expresses that innate idea of straightness, which we ever apply, as the perfect ideal exemplar, to the deter- mination of visible figure. From this use of the word Xoyog it is, that those magni- tudes and numbers whose ratio cannot be expressed by 166 PARADOX OF CIRCULAR MOTION. other numbers — that is, which have no common divisor by which one may be predicated as any arithmetical part or multiple of another — are called aXoya, and in modern works, irrational. Two magnitudes, however, may be arithmetically incommensurable or irrational, like the side and diagonal of the square, the circumference and diameter of the circle, or what are styled surds among numbers ; and yet, in all these cases, there may be, and often is, a geomet- rical representation which renders them rational, and may be styled the expression of the ratio, Xoyog, or reason, just as well as though they were embraced by some common numerical divisor. Much on this subject of quantities, styled dXoya , or irra- tional, may be found in Euclid’s Laws of the Musical Can- on, as contained in Meibomius. All concords, let it be re- marked, are founded on rational numbers, while the irra- tional ever produce discords under all circumstances. The first have a Xoyog or reason, and the soul, when the sounds suggest it, perceives this reason in its supersensual being, although unconscious of the intellectual process on which it depends ; and hence a delight which mere sense could never furnish. Where this process is made objective, and thus presented to the mind, it is called science. It would net be difficult to refer to the same ideas of equality and ratio all the fundamental elements of the beauty of figure and motion. XXII. Paradox of Circular Motion. Page 24, Line 8 . A/A 6i) rcov 'davfiaoTGjv andvrcov Trrjyrj yeyovev. This is stated as a sort of strange paradox, that one motion should be at the same time greater and less, or should give rise to different velocities, according as the rev- the words (pOloig, yevEOig^ naOog , and (pOopa . 167 elution was nearer to, or more remote from, the centre, while there was but one impulse distributing itself propor- tionally, ava Xoyov, to every part. The paradox, however, arises from confounding circular, or angular, with rectilineal motion. The idea of the latter arises from a compound comparison of two elements, namely, the space passed over, and the time employed in the passage. Hence, there being no absolute measure of space, there can be nothing absolute about rectilineal motion. The other must be always refer- red to the centre of motion, and the time occupied in one revolution ; or, in other words, one must be referred to space and time, the other to time only. The latter may also be said to have something absolute about it, since there is an absolute standard of angular space. Hence the mo- tions of the inner concentric circles of the same great cir- cle, moving on one centre, identical with the centre of the circle, are all the same when thus measured, although va- rying infinitely when referred to other points. The veloci- ty of the hour hand of a watch, that revolves once in twen- ty-four hours, is the same with that of the earth on its axis. If the same hour hand could be conceived of as extending to the moon, the tangential velocity of its extremity would be greater than the orbit motion of that body — exceeding many thousand miles a minute — and yet its absolute velo- city, taken as a whole, would be that same slow and almost imperceptible motion which apoears in our timepieces. XXIII. The Words cpdtmg, yeveoig , tt ddog, and (pOopa. Page 25, Line 5. cpOivei . . apicpoTepa diroXXvrai. This word (pOivei (0opd . the opposite of avt-dvercu, av^rjocg. ’AnohXvraL is used where the very law, nature, or idea of a thing (that which makes it what it is) is taken away. It is the opposite of ytyverat. The one would express the difference between a fat man and a lean one, the other between a living man and a dead body. 0mo is generally intransitive, but is sometimes used in a transitive sense, as in the Iliad, vi., 407 : A aijjiovie (pdioeL a e to gov pevog. $6lvg) and (f>0tpevog are applied by the poets to the dead, but more in a metaphorical than a strictly philosophical sense. When thus poetically used, they still retain some- thing of their primary meaning, and suggest the conception of the wasted , the emaciated , the weak ( apevrjvd tcap7]va), as though the ghostly state were but a diminution of their for- mer life. In the same manner the poets use /tapovTeg , the wearied , the deceased. The Hebrews seem to have had something of the same metaphorical conception in their word CD'KSn • T l Mere increment or diminution is said to take place as long as the naOeGTrjKvla ei-tg , the constituting state , remains (diapevy, continues through , or survives the change ). But it may be destroyed both ways ( 'dp&orepa ), that is, by (pOiotg , or av^rjotg, when carried so far that the law of the body becomes affected. No increment or decrement which does not take away that £§tg^ or state, which makes a thing what it is, can ever amount to that great change denoted by cj)6opd, and the verb dnoXXvpt. Until this takes place, the real or essential identity remains, although that phenomenal iden- tity may have been affected, which depends on the numer- ical sum or aggregate. So that we may say, that, if every particle of matter has been removed and replaced by others, still, if during the process the KaOeoTTjuvla e^tg is preserv- ed, it is the same body, although not the same matter ; and if, on the other hand, no single material particle be lost, yet the words (pdioig , yeveoig, naOog , and (pOopa. 169 if, in any way, tliis e%ig has been destroyed, it is no longer tKe same, but there has taken place the yeveoig of some- thing else, having a different name, a different law, and a different identity, or, as is said a few lines below, perada- Xdv elg dXXrjv e%iv diecpOaprai navreXkg, “ passing into another state, it is utterly destroyed the thing which be- fore was, no longer is, whatever may have taken its place. See Note XXV., on the difference between yeveoig and aXXoiuoig. The next question is, What is yeveoig, or generation ? It is rather abruptly put by the supposed interlocutor, yet still is naturally enough suggested by what precedes : Tiyverai 6rj navriov yeveoig tjvik 1 dv r'l naOog ; to which the suc- ceeding answer is given : A fXov kg onorav ap%r\ XaOovoa av^rjv, k. t. A., “ It is evident (that generation takes place , or that the peculiar naOog under which it takes place is) when- ever a principle here put for the originating idea , the principium, or law of life to anything ) receiving growth, (that is, being developed in the outward or material ) passes into the second change, and from this into the next, and so on, until, coming as far as to three, it arrives at such a state as to become an object of sensation.” This is certainly rather obscure, but perhaps as well expressed as was pos- sible, in the attempt to set forth the transition from the law of life to its material organic development. Tpikv would seem to refer to the three mathematical dimensions, length, breadth, and thickness, which every object of sense must possess in some degree ; or it may be intended as an in- definite number, representing the stages, be they more or less, through which the thing generated must pass, until it become an object of sensation, visible, tangible, &c. P 170 PHILOSOPHY OF THE VERB to be. XXIV. Philosophy of the Verb TO BE. Platonic Use of dpi and ylyvopai. Page 25, Line 11 . MeradaXXov pev ovv ovro aai pera- uvovpevov ylyverai ndv. eon de bvrcog ov onorav pev^j * perabaXov de elq aXXrjv egtv dtecpdaprai navreXtiq. The tenses here are emphatic, and must have their precise meaning. “ While thus changing and moving, it is in the act of being generated. It really is, when it becomes fixed and stands ; but after it has passed into another state, it (that is, the former thing) is utterly destroyed.” M evyf is to be taken here in its philosophical sense, as opposed to perabdXXei, and for eorr}iie, in the language of the schools, as opposed to tavelrai , or to that which is in a constant flux or motion. This, however, can only strictly be applied to the law or idea, and in this sense it includes what Plato so often expresses by the phrase del tiara ravra, &c., as that which remains unaffected amid the material mutations to which it is constantly subject. It may be, however, that ovrcoq ov is not to be taken here in the highest philosophical sense, as opposed to yiyvope- vov , but more according to the vulgar usage of the substan- tive verb, as signifying the real being, not simply of the law or idea, but of the generated material object itself, du- ring that period in which it suffers no n dOog, or change of state. It is because they are always suffering change or flux, like a river ever passing away, and never for two suc- cessive moments preserving the same numerical or aggre* gate identity, that even some of the ancient philosophers who were theists denied that generated material things were at all entitled to the epithet ovrcoq ovra. Plato, how- ever, clearly regards their identity as not depending upon number and the aggregate mass ; but as long as they suffer 171 TLATONIC USE OF elflL AND J lyVOgai. no naOog by which rj fcaOeoTrjitvia e%ig is taken away, he does not hesitate to apply to them this higher substantive verb, although entitled to it only by partaking for a time of that idea, to which it truly and in itself belongs. Modern scientfic men seem to be making rapid advance to this position of some of the ancients, that, in the material world, all things are ever flowing, and nothing stands. Would that we could say, that they all held as firmly as Pythago- ras, Plato, and Parmenides, to a higher and far more real universe of truth, in which all was stable, immutable, and eternal as the throne of God. There is a most important distinction between the verbs h[ii and ylyvopai , on which we would here dwell at some length, although almost every page in Plato’s dialogues might have given occasion for such an excursus. In fact, many portions of this writer are not fully comprehensible, in their highest intended meaning, unless the philosophical distinctions between these words are kept constantly in mind. They are often emphatic, and used antithetically, when the careless reader little suspects it ; and thus sen- tences most pregnant in meaning seem frequently to con- tain mere truisms, or propositions of a most unmeaning character. In defining the Platonic sense of these words, we rely directly on the authority of the philosopher him- self, in the Timaeus, 27, P., 28, A. From this passage alone, had there been no other, we are justified in saying, that elpi, in its highest sense, expresses essential , eternaJ- necessary, self-existent, independent, uncaused being or es- sence, having no dependence on time and space. The other, ytyvofiai, expresses phenomenal, temporal , contingent , de- pendent being, generated in time and space. This philosophical distinction is more clear in Plato than in any other Greek writer, because the subjects he discuss- ed led him to be more precise in the application of those primary meanings of the terms in question, which grew not 172 PHILOSOPHY OF THE VERB to be . out of philosophy, but must have been coeval with the first roots of this most spiritual language. Whatever his nom- inal themes may be, whether ethical, sesthetical, physical, or metaphysical, they are, in his treatment, almost always made ultimately to turn, in a greater or less degree, on the distinctions in the modes of being expressed by these two verbs. However he may commence, the argument seldom proceeds far before we are engaged in the consideration of the eternal, the immutable, the one in the many (to ev ev noXXolg), the del ovra , in contrast with the temporal, the changeable, the individual, and the generated. The differ- ence between the classes of ideas expressed by these two verbs must be kept in mind everywhere in reading his more serious dialogues ; and in many parts it may be said to form the key to some of his most valuable thoughts. The key passage, in which they are placed in most remarkable contrast, is one which we have already partly quoted for another purpose (page 96), but whose importance will jus- tify its being presented again. In the Timaeus he defines the two grand departments into which all being or substance is divided, namely, on the one hand, the sensible world , with its phenomena , and, on the other, the intellectual world , in- cluding soul as the oldest essence, and also those eternal truths, ideas, or principles, which Plato seems to have re- garded as entitled to the name of entities — as existences, in fact, even more real than matter itself, although their dwell- ing was not in the world of time and space : "E otlv ovv drj npCdrov dtaipereov Tade- tl to ’'ON pev del, TENE2IN de ovk exov , ml tl to TITNOMENON per, v ON de ovdeno- Te * to pev drj vorjaeL peTd Xoyov nepL^rjnTbv, del mra TavTa v ON. nav de av to yvyvopevov vtt > clItlov Tivoq e% dvdynpg y lyveodat. navTl yap ddvvaTOV x^pl? clItlov ye- veav oxelv. And again, in continuation of the same dis- tinction : haenTeov ovv drj uepl rravTog, re OTepov T HN del yevecrecjg dpx^ v ex^v ovdeplav fj PETONEN an’ apx^g platonic use of elfiL and yiyvopai, 173 tlvoc ap^dfievog. Timceus, 28, A., C. In another part of this same passage he contrasts ovoid (or essence) with ye- veotg, as knowledge with opinion, 29, C. It must not be expected always to find these two verbs used with this phil- osophical precision even in Plato. In mere narration, con- fined simply to the assertion of facts, without reference to the nature of the objects, fjv and eyevero are often con- founded, and used one for the other. In such cases the substantive verbs simply perform the office of an asserting copula, without any respect to the mode of being. Even here, however, we often find in careful writers a marked difference in their application. The plain historian He- rodotus, whenever his subject requires it, presents the con- trast strongly, as in lib. iii., 53 : evOev 6e eyevero etcaorog rcbv decor, errs tie del rjoav. In the dialogues of Plato, however, the distinction, whenever important, is ever care- fully preserved ; and we may say, generally, from a review of the Platonic writings, that in all cases which require care in the use of terms, eori is the appropriate word to ex- press that which IS necessarily, such as the existence and attributes of the Deity, the independent existence of incor- poreal substance, the eternal truth of a moral distinctions. Thus, for example, the sentence eon ro ayaOov, would imply far more than simply the assertion of a fact. In this expression, when used with philosophical strictness, eori performs the office of a predicate as well as of a copula, and that predicate, moreover, includes the mode as well as the fact of being. There is expressed by it, without the aid of any other words, a general and most important proposi- tion, namely, that the idea of goodness is not merely rela- tive or accidental, or the result of the mind’s generalization from outward acts, but an absolute, eternal verity; that it has an absolute existence in the Divine mind, and that there is a fixed foundation for the absolute, and not merely relative nature of moral distinctions. In the sciences, this P 2 174 PHILOSOPHY OF THE VERB to be. term would be peculiarly appropriate to the enunciation of the truths of geometry and numbers. In mathematical prop- ositions the ideas of cause and effect have no place. There is no ysvEOiq. One truth is essentially connected with an- other, or, rather, seen in it as eternally abiding. The ap- pearance of sequence arises from the necessities and im- perfections of our own minds, compelling us to state them in time ; and yet it is strictly true, that every property of every mathematical figure, and every corresponding mode of generating, contains in itself every other property, and that, as far as theory, irrespective of convenience, is con- cerned, any one of them might, with equal truth, be made the fundamental Xoyog, or definition from which all the rest should be evolved. Mathematical propositions, strictly speaking, have no relation to time, being eternally true, without past, succession, or future. We may, without con- tradiction or absurdity, conceive of a period when it may cease to be true, that bodies attract in the inverse ratio of the squares of their distances, but never when it shall be no longer a truth, that the square of the hypotenuse is equal to the* sum of the squares of the two sides. To make use of the verb ylyvojicu, therefore, in the enunciation of a mathematical theorem, would be introducing a foreign and altogether heterogeneous idea. This latter substantive verb would be most appropriate to physics or natural philosophy, to the ever- moving phenomena of nature regarded as under the law of cause and effect, as having a beginning and an end, as yiyvofieva nal dno^v^eva ; although even these may be stated as absolute truths, and, generally, are thus stated when the mind conceives of them as involving ulti- mately something that is necessary and eternal. It is by reason of some such d 'priori conception, whether it be cor- rect or not, that the primary laws of physics come to be ex- pressed in the same language with the axioms of the pure mathematics. 175 platonic use of elpl and yiyvopai. Even the etymological origin of these two verbs may, without any extravagance of fancy, be supposed to betoken the vast difference between them. The primary elements of the one (ew e el) are found in the most aethereal of the vowels. The other (yaw y) has for its ultimate radical the hardest, and, we might almost say, the most earthly of the guttural mutes ; for it is the origin of the term for earth (y//), and, of all letters, is most easily associated with the conceptions of the sensible or tactual. Plato, although a very poor philologist, seems to recognise the connexion : y r\ yap yevvrjTEipa av eirj opOtig KEuXrjpEvrj, tog (prjOLv "O \ir\- pog * to yap yeydaoc yeyevvTjoOai Xeysi. Cralylus , 410, D. Trjg yXo)TT7jg 6e dXioOavovorjg avriXapbaverat rj rov r dvvapcg. Ib., 427, B. These distinctions clearly exist, and are probably coeval with the first elements of the language. They do not, how- ever, as we have remarked, appear so obvious in ordinary use ; their full power being evinced only in the discussion of those truths, in which are involved the very ideas that are radical in the words themselves. On this account they are so distinctly marked in many passages in Plato. The spirit of the difference, however, is diffused throughout the Greek literature, and is probably to be found, to some ex- tent, and under various forms of expression, in almost every known language. May we not believe that, in this way, God, who may be regarded as the author of language as well as of everything else, has provided an antidote against that materialism to which our depraved nature is so contin- ually tending. It is surely no small protection against this, that there are to be found (and perhaps in every tongue) terms which, whatever may have been their origin, must ever be irreconcilably at w T ar with the sensual or atheistic hypothesis. The great truth of the real existence of incorporeal sub - stance , as something independent of, and not posterior to, or 176 PHILOSOPHY OP THE VERB to be. a result of matter, lies at the foundation of all faith and all religion. We verily believe, too, that whosoever will care- fully examine his own consciousness must admit, that a latent doubt of this lies at the bottom of all skepticism, in all its various forms. It is all to be resolved into material- ism, a system into which such a verb as eotl, in its purest philosophical sense, could not consistently enter. The ex- istence of an Eternal Spirit, independent of the organization of the world by which he manifests himself — the real ex- istence of our own souls as something in the order of na- ture, if not of time, prior to, and independent of, the organi- zation of our bodies ; the consequent immateriality and im- mortality of the soul ; the eternal existence of all which are styled necessary truths ; the eternity of moral distinctions ; the existence of moral attributes as the highest part of the Divine character, and the solemn verities of the Christian faith and the Christian redemption, as flowing necessarily from the above truths in their relation to man — all these are, in every thinking and well-balanced mind that has receiv- ed a religious or Christian education, parts of one system ; all are inseparably connected together, so that a doubt of one is a doubt of all, and a firm conviction of one brings with it a satisfactory belief in all the rest. The prime ele- ment which runs throughout, is a firm faith in the reality of incorporeal substance , or that there is something in the uni- verse besides the sensible world and its phenomena, some other God or soul than that pantheistic power which is only another name for their combined manifestation — in short, some vnepKoofila, as the origin and cause of the ipvxi] eyrcoofiia , as well as of the material world in which its en- ergies are displayed. Yet it must be confessed, that there is a downward tendency in our fallen race to atheism. We do not like to retain God in our knowledge. We find this tendency (unless checked, as it ever has been, by Divine interpositions at special times of grace) gradually infecting 177 PLATONIC USE OF Elfll AND ylyVOgai. individuals and nations, giving an atheistic tinge to Ian- guage, and corrupting and finally destroying religious belief. There is, at the beginning of this, the opposite of the con- viction before mentioned — a secret and almost unconscious skepticism, a suspicion, a fear, and in some, perhaps, a hope, that all is nature , that all is generation (yeveaig), or the mere succession of phenomena ; that there is nothing naO' eavTijv, absolute, necessary, eternal, self-existent, or, in other words, d)$* ovdsv earrjiie , that nothing stands . Now we cannot help indulging the thought, however ex- travagant it may appear to some, that the Divine Author of our race, “ who careth for us,” and who arranges all things to bring about his own eternal decrees, does exert a provi- dential control over so important an instrument as speech, and that in these two substantive verbs, so distinctly mark- ed in their primary sense, their philosophical applications, and their numerous derivative and kindred terms, he has stamped upon the noblest language of earth, an indelible im- pression of the eternal distinction between the classes of substances denoted by them, and of the real existence of those great truths so fundamental to all others, the chief of which is, u that HE IS , and that he is the rewarder of those who diligently seek him” Especially would this seem to be a sober conclusion, when we consider how, in the provi- dence of God, this same language was intended to be the medium of a Divine revelation, and the teaching of a wide- spread Christian theology. The modern tongue which comes the nearest to it in this respect is the German. And may we not regard this, too, as intended, by its high spirit- ual character, to resist effectually the neology and natural- ism which have been attempted to be conveyed through it ? May we not hope, that, after all the extravagances of the German mind, the conservative, religious, and spiritual in- fluences which in this and other respects exist in their na- tive Teutonic, will yet hold them firm to those great truths 178 f HILOSOPHY OF THE VERB to be. which are the foundation of all faith. Materialism can a best only babble in other languages : it cannot speak at all in Greek or German, without the use of words which must continually remind it of its absurdities and contradictions. The English, and most of the modern languages of Eu- ope, are very deficient in the expression of the distinction conveyed by these verbs. Words, it is true, may be found, which may be forced into a sort of awkward correspond- ence ; but they want that unction, that naturalness, that di- rect and easy contrast with the opposing terms, which would show that they are in harmony with the genius and spirit of the language. Hence the almost impossibility of a faithful and yet lively translation of Plato into the French and English. If we needed proof how poorly the Latin is aapted to this purpose, it may be found in the version of the Timeeus by Ficinus, and even in the translation of the same dialogue by Cicero, of which a large fragment yet remains.* We may trace the distinction between elfit and ytyvofjtat, even where we may not suppose it to have been directly in * Among all modern authors, there is no one in whose writings these Greek words seem more wanted than in those of the English Plato, Ralph Cudworth. He often seems to labour with the stiff Latin, and the still more clumsy English, when the Greek sljui and ytyvoyai would have helped him at once out of all difficulty. As, for example, when speaking of the eternity of truth, and of its inde- pendence even of the creating or generating power of the Divine will, he says, that “it cannot be made, but is he means just what Flato'would have expressed by the words, ovderzors kyevero i] dM/deca, alX dec eon. Intellectual System of the Universe , vol. iii., p. 376, Eng. ed. And again, vol. iii., p. 405, where he wishes to tell us in English, that “ the perfect triangle, &c., really is, although it never yet existed, and never may exist in rerum natural As we feel for our imperfect language, and for the difficulties of our most admira- ble author, we cannot help thinking how easily the Greek enables Aristotle to express the same thought by the same words, del kart, ovd^Trore kyevero. 179 PLATONIC USE OF elflL AND J lyvopai. the mind of the writer, but to have arisen (perhaps uncon- sciously) from its adaptedness to the truth intended to be conveyed. Thus, for example, in the first verses of the Gospel of John, the one is applied to the Eternal A oyog, the other to the sensible world, which derived its yeveoig from him. We might, in defence of this position, say at once, that the terms were specially suggested by the Holy Spirit, the *eal author of the passage, without supposing John him- self to have had any acquaintance with the Platonic wri- tings, or to have intended any philosophical contrast. But without this, we can recognise the distinction as growing directly out of the genius of the language, although, in the expression of truths in which it did not enter, either verb, or both, might have been used, without anything special to attract observation. But John was treating of a subject which, of all others, called for the contrast ; and that, too, whether Xoyog is used here for a personification of the Su- preme Reason, or for the Eternal Son of God, the second Person in the Trinity. There is, then, no absurdity and no extravagance in* supposing that the words are here used, not in their ordinary narrative sense, but with special re- gard to their primary differences, when employed in phil- osophical strictness. This may be more clear of one of them- than of the other. r Hv or kart may be applied to the lower class of existences — and it is this that has rendered necessary the qualifying adverb, ovrojg, which we find so frequently in the Platonic phrase, ovrcog ov — but eyevero cannot well be used for the higher. One the least familiar with the genius of the Greek language must feel the impro- priety of the expression, ev apxy eyevero 6 Qeog ; unless it had been actually intended to teach the fabulous generations of such gods as Hesiod treats of in his Theogonia, who all came from an older <\>voig , and were generated out of Chaos and the broad-bosomed Earth : 180 PHILOSOPHY OF THE VERB to be. ’TI tol [lev Tcpcortara Xaog TENET’, avrap eneira YaV evpvorepvog , Travroiv edog aocbaXeg alec. Hesiod, Theog ., 117. A much more clear and striking example from the Scrip- tures may be found John, viii., 58. Here we have the most remarkable antithesis, and here we feel confident in saying, not only that the philosophical distinction was in- tended, but that, without it, the designed idea could not Jiave been expressed : ’Aprjv dprjv Aeyw vplv rrplv ’A dpaap TE- NE20AI eyed EIMI . — Before Abraham came into being , or received his yeveotg , I AM, eternally and essentially AM, WAS, and ever SHALL BE : for dpi, here, like the He- brew rynx, Exodus, iii., 14, seems to include all tenses. To be convinced that this juxtaposition of words was not accidental, or used merely for the sake of variety, let us compare the other modes that might seem to be equivalent, namely, irplv 9 A 6paap dvai eyco d\u, or n piv ’Abpaap ye- veoOat eyd) eyevoprjv ; and the difference is not only to be perceived, but felt. In consequence of our using the soli- tary verb to be for both modes of existence expressed by elpt and y iyvopai, the English fails, and ever must fail, in setting forth the truth in all its fulness. It is not extrava- gant to suppose that our Saviour here intended, and the Jews understood, a direct reference to Exodus, iii., 14 — I AM that I AM — where the Septuagint employs the partici- ple of elpi as a name or personal appellation of the Deity, corresponding to the Hebrew rrnx, or DUV, namely, f O "I2N hath sent me unto you. There seems, also, good rea- son for the opinion that this term, f O "QN, may, in some other passages, have the force of a descriptive appellation (as one of the Divine names), instead of being a mere par- ticipial copula. As in the noted passage, Rom., ix., 5 — f O T2N, ent ndvrcov tiedg, evXoyyrog elg roi)g aitivag. — Of whom, according to the flesh ( Kara oaptca), was Christ, The Tehovah , God over all, blessed forever . The Hebraism, 181 PLATONIC USE OF ELflL AND ylyVOgUi. Kara capita (wsn 'D 1 ?), is the only form of expression in that language, which at all corresponds to the Greek Kara ysveciv ; and, by keeping this in mind, we find that there is the same contrast, Rom., ix., 5, as in John, i., 1, 2, 14 : Kal o Xoyog cap% eyevero . Transfer the Hebraistic idiom to more philosophical Greek, and this contrast would be thus set forth : Kar ’ ovciav , ev apxxj fjv 6 Xoyog — Kara ye - veav , cap £ Eyevero. Compare, also, Rev.,i., 8, ’E ytb Eipu o cbv Kal o i]v. We are aware of the objections to all this, and have no expectation that it will have much force with those who entertain different views in theology ; but some such impression of a reference to Exodus, iii., 14, is very naturally left on the mind of one who believes, on other grounds, in the Divinity and eternal self-existence of the being here styled The Logos. This impression receives strength, also, from the supposition that the language of the Septuagint version of Exodus, iii., 14 (6 cbv ), had already passed into a descriptive appellation, and been ranked among the Old Testament names of the Deity. Should it be thought that we are too much inclined to represent Paul and John as Platonizing, or as indulging in the use of philosophical language, we would simply refer, in the case of the former, to Acts, xvii., 28 : ’Ev avrcp yap £ g ) gev, Kal KivovgeOa itat eogev. — “ In him we live , and move, and are The allusion here, as well as in other parts of that chapter, to the language of the Greek schools is too plain to be mistaken ; and it does not seem extrava- gant to suppose, that the Apostle had in mind the Greek and Hebrew names respectively of their Supreme Deity The etymology of Jehovah is suggested at once by Exodus, iii., 14. It may be called the proper name of God, or, as he styles it himself, his memorial to all generations — The Essentially Existent one (6 ojv) ; the Being who has life in himself, and who is the source of existence to el^rything else. In spiritual substances, life and being are the same. Q 182 PHILOSOPHY OF THE VERB to be. The two roots in Hebrew expressive of these two ideas, namely, rrn and rrn, are so nearly alike, that they may be regarded as from one source, and, in some cases, as nearly synonymous. Hence the appellation so common in the Old Testament, The Living God . To say that this is in- ended merely to distinguish the God of the Jews from the dead idols of the Heathen, or from their deified dead men, is not to give it half its meaning. None of the Heathen nations, any more than the Romanists of modern times, were ever so besotted as to worship their idols without re- garding them, in some measure, as the representatives of living and immortal beings. The epithet, therefore, must have had a higher significance, and seems to refer to this name Jehovah — The Being that not only exists, but exists necessarily — who has life in himself, unoriginated and un- caused — that Divine existence which the mind is compelled to admit a priori, as the ground of the belief in all other ex- istences, or as a necessary truth, the contrary of which, when fairly presented, cannot be admitted without bringing darkness over every other truth. Hence the appeal so oft- en found in the Old Testament, 61 As I live , saith the Lord,” is used to denote the highest ground of certainty. Gese- nius and other German critics, indulging their propensity ever to undervalue the testimony of the Scriptures, and to lessen our reverence for their antiquity and sacred author- ity, assign an Egyptian origin to this name, and deduce it from an inscription upon the temple at Sais, as given by Plutarch : ’Eyc5 el[U to yeyovbg teal ov teal eodyevov . — “ 1 am that which has been, is, and shall be.” This inscrip- tion, although, perhaps, itself comparatively modern, may have contained an old Egyptian sentiment; and yet such an admission would not militate at all against the pure He- brew origin of the name, and its derivation from ideas ex- isting in the patriarchal ages, or in that common early the- ology which was transmitted pure to the Jew, while it w^as 183 PLATONIC USE OF EL[H - AND yiyV0\iai. corrupted by every other nation. To the same early source must we look for the notion on which was grounded the etymology of the Greek Z evg, and which presents so strong a contrast with the corruptions of the subsequent mythology. Although it may not be precisely the same with the prim- itive idea of the Hebrew term, there certainly seems some approach to it. There is no need of travelling, as some have done, to the Sanscrit for the origin of this term. It seems as purely Greek as Qeog and A aipojv, and nothing can be more simple, or less liable to the charge of being forced, than the etymology which Plato gives us in the Cra- tylus. He derives Zevg , Zrjva, from t'q v , to live : Ov yap lonv rjplv teal rolg aXXoig Traotv bong eorlv alnog paXXov tov rj 0 apx^ v ts fiaoiXevg tCjv navreov . — “ For to us, and to all other beings, there is no one who is more prop- erly the cause of life than the ruler and king of all things.” At all events, it is sufficient for our present argument, that this was the received and probably well-known philosoph- ical etymology in Paul’s time, and we have every reason, therefore, to suppose that he alludes to it in this famous passage of his sermon at Athens. In the words ^bjpev and eopev, we have the radical Greek and Hebrew ideas com- bined in one description, composed of terms severally sig- nificant of motion , life , and essence ; as though Paul had said, he is our Zevg and our Jehovah: “For in him we live and are , as some of your own poets have said,” g vnonetpevov rov avrov , vXP olov e% vdarog aijp, rj el; aspog vdcjp, rov pev 7]Sr) ye - VEGig to toiovtov , rov 6e cpdopa , paXtara 6e dv rj peradoXrj yivErai e% dvatoQrjrov elg aloOrjrov. “ Alloiosis takes place when the subject (some object of sense) remains the same, while there is a change in its passions. As, for ex- ample, the body is healthy, and again is sick, yet remains the same body ; or the brass is at one time round, and at another angular, yet still the same. But when there is an entire change, the subject no longer remaining the same, but it being as though from water air, or from air water snould arise, such a change is, in respect to the one thing, a generation, and, in respect to the other, a (pdopa , or cor- ruption,” &c. In applying this, however, it will be found to be only a matter of degrees, unless it is determined what constitutes totality, or an entire change, as also what is meant by not- DISTINCTION BETWEEN yeVEGig AND dXXoLUGLg. 187 orrfg, properly, or quality. This must be viewed in refer- ence to two theories, one of which, or the atomic, considers all iroiOTTjT ag, or qualities of bodies, as arising from the site, figure, motion, and order of the atoms of which they are composed (d)g AryxoupiTog real Aevtannog aot KtvrjGiv • dAAd Sea tl, teat riva , ov Ae- yovoev. “ Some make it an everlasting activity, as Leucip- pus and Plato. For they say that there is an eternal mo- tion, but by reason of what, and what, they do not tell us.” Aristot ., Metaph., xi. (xii.), c. 6. This disparagement of Plato, by associating him with the atheists, Leucippus and Democritus, is merely done to set off his own dogma, that “ the first essence was immoveable on dvdyftrj elvai at- diov nvd ova lav, dfdv7]rov ; in which proposition, taken in its true sense, we shall see that Plato most fully agreed with him. In another part of this same chapter, he infers, that if there be an eternal rdv?]Oig , its very essence must be activity (evepyeia), in distinction from power ( dvvapig ) : E£ yap pij evepyrjoei , ovre eorai tdvrjoig • ert ovd ’ el evepyrjoei, i] 6' ovGta avrrjg dvvapig • ov yap eorai nivrjoig atdiog • ev - Several yap to dvvapei ov, prj dvai. A el apa elvai dpxrjv roiavrrjv, fjg ij ovoia evepyeia— u For if it should not ener- gize, there will be no motion ; neither if it should energize, t ARISTOTLE MISREPRESENTS TLATO. 19l while yet its essence was only (dvvapcg) power or poten- tiality. Even in that case, there will be no eternal motion ; for that which exists, tv dvvapec, in potentiality, admits of not-being. Therefore there must he some such principle, whose very essence is energy .” In stating the objections to the doctrine, he misrepresents Plato in his usual manner, by drawing the unsound infer- ence, that the Phrst Cause must have been ever engaged, from its very nature, in the work of creation, and that, there- fore, the universe must have been eternal : (hare ova av fjv dnecpov xpovov %ao£ i) vv%, dXXa ra avra dec, rj rrepcodcp, ?] dXXcvg, ehrep nporepov tvepyeca dvvapecog, el de to avro del Trepcodcp, dec re dec peveev tvepyovv — “ So that there could have been no chaos or night for an infinite (or indef- inite) time ; but the same things must have been ever taking place, either in a circuit or in some other manner, if activ- ity ( tvepyeca ) is older than dvvapcg. But if the same eter- nally took place in a circuit, then there must have ever been something continually energizing, or putting forth active power.” Metaph., xi. (xii.), c. 6. Aristotle was never careful to do Plato justice ; although it would be easy to show — the modern declamation to the contrary notwithstanding — that their philosophy was sub- stantially the same ; the main difference arising from the Stagyrite’s studious care to adopt, in many cases, a different phraseology, for the purpose of creating the appearance of a wider disagreement than really existed, and from his con- tinual disposition to pervert and misstate Plato's real mean- ing. His misrepresentation here, whether wilful or not, arises from his utterly confounding the two aspects under which our philosopher defines his tenth species of teevrjoeg, as eavrrjv re teevovoa — teal erepa dvvapevrj. In the first only did he hold it to be eternal and essential. In this respect, too, however much it may be above our comprehension, he regards it as purely spiritual, or, as the scholiast defines it f 192 IN GOD, THE VERY ESSENCE IS ENERGY. psychical, in distinction from topical motion ; as something ever energizing within itself, and only presenting the sec- ond aspect when exercised, tiara ronov, in the generation, creation, and changes of the topical universe. What Plato meant was this, that the First Cause was something more than dvvapig ; an eternal activity constituting its very es- sence, yet by no means necessitating it to act out of itself, until, by an exercise of will, it should give rise to an out- ward universe, which, although actuated by, remains clear- ly distinct from, this everlasting energy. We have likewise an example of the gross manner in which Aristotle misstates Plato, in another assertion of this same chapter, wherein he charges him with inconsistency in respect to his first Mover or Eternal Soul : ’AAAd firjv ovde UX arcovi ye olov re Xeyeiv fjv olerai apxrjv elvat evi- ote to avro kavro ntvovv. vorepov yap teal apa rep ovpavcp 7) ipvrxrj, cog (j>rj(u — “ But, surely, neither is Plato able to tell us what he means by that which he sometimes thinks to be the first principle, namely, his self- moving power ; for soul, he says (in a certain place), is cotemporary with the heavens, or the material universe.” Aristotle undoubtedly would convey the inference, that this is inconsistent with the doctrine of the Eternal Spiritual Mover as laid down in the tenth book of The Laws. The position which he cites is from the Timaeus, but the careful reader can hardly fail to see that there, by ^vx^j, Plato means the anima mundi , which he expressly represents as the direct production of the Eternal Father, who formed it together with the body of which it was to be the plastic power ; whereas through- out this book, and especially the present argument respect- ing motion, he employs the term soul for the immaterial principle which was prior to all creation and generation of matter — in fact, as another name for the Eternal Deity him- self — and this wide difference could hardly have been un- known to one. who must have been familiar with the dia- Aristotle’s immoveable essence. 193 logues of Plato, especially such important portions of them as the Timseus and this argument* against the atheists. One cause of Aristotle’s misconception may have been his own unsound definition of motion, which necessarily excluded this tenth species, which Plato makes the ground of all the rest : ixaaa yap ntvrjatg £% akXov slg aWo sorl peradoXrj. Metaph., x. (xi.), c. 12. In other places, how- ever, he seems to mean the same with our author, and even to go beyond him in the sublimity of some of his ideas re- specting the first Mover. Compare, for this purpose, the last chapter of the last book of Physics, and the seventh chapter of the eleventh book of the Metaphysics. The First Cause he styles a/cLvrjrov, not, as we think, in the sense of inactivity or quiescence, but as incapable of being moved, or of deriving its motion from anything external or antecedent. This, instead of being 6vvapig alone, he him- self describes as essentially an Eternal Energy : errel 6s eon to Ktvovpsvov teal tavovv , peoov eotl n , o ov Kivovpe- vov Kivsly aidiov , nal ovoia nai sv spy eta ovoa . Metaph ., xi. (xii.), c. 7. He sometimes even transcends Plato, and seems to intend the energy of vovg as something higher than a merely psychicalf first mover, if he does not rather mean an apx'fj, or principle of a still higher nature even than this, namely, the moral and final cause of the heaven- ly motions. We allude especially to that most remark- * There cannot be a doubt, that, in the passages we have quoted, Aristotle has reference to this tenth book of The Laws ; for nowhere else does Plato talk in the same style about motion and the first mo- ver, unless it be in some of the subsequent books of this very trea- tise. In the Timaeus, the argument is conducted in a manner alto- gether different. This, then, together with other references which Aristotle makes to the Laws, as a production of Plato well known in his day, ought to be conclusive evidence of their genuineness. t Plato, however, in this argument, evidently uses 'tpvxv for all that is incorporeal, including intellect (vov-c) as well as life and motive power. R 194 MORAL REASONS, THE FIRST OF MOVING CAUSES. able passage, where he says “ that this dpx% or First Cause, moves the heavens, as being loved — tuvel 6e epd>- pievoi’ ,” c. 7. By this, Cudworth supposes that he meant to represent a second moving power, or soul of the world, which, “ enamoured with this supreme, immoveable Mind, did, as it were, in imitation of it, continually turn round the heavens.” Intellectual System , vol. ii., p. 313, Eng. ed. We cannot, however, discover any solid grounds for this opinion, and would rather regard this as a mode of expres- sion, by which the Stagyrite would give the first place in the series of moving causes to moral reasons — what he himself so tersely styles, to ev nal tzaX&g, or the well and fit , and what Socrates was fond of denominating to PeXtio- tov , the best. It was this principle which produced that motion of the Highest Heavens or sphere, on which all in- ferior motions depend : etc Toiavrr\g apa apx^g TjpTTjrat, 6 ovpavog nal rj (pvoig. In this language we think there can be discovered some allusion to Homer’s golden chain ; and, indeed, the whole style and sentiment of the passage seems far more in accordance with the semi-poetical philosophy of Plato than with that of the dry and rigid Aristotle. No- thing could be more Platonic than this conception of the universe eternally moving on through love of/rhe First Fair and The First Good, attracted rather than impelled, and ever tending to the object of its admiration, as though it were striving to develop, in the harmony of its varied physical influences, that all-perfect idea with which it was enraptured. We may compare with all this a splendid passage from the Phaedrus, of which Cicero has given a version in the first book of the Tusculan Disputations, sect, xxiii. : “All soul is immortal, for that which ever moves must be eter- nal ; while that which moves another, and yet is moved by something else, since it hath cessation of motion, may have cessation of life. But that alone which moves itself, seeing 195 the words hoyog, eldog, and Idea. that it never leaves itself, not only never ceases energizing, but is also the fountain and beginning of motion to all other things. This can never either be bom or perish, or all the heaven and earth collapsing must stand still, and never again find a renewed source and origin of motion. For, since it is evident that that which is self-moving is eternal, we need not fear to say that this is the very essence and reason (Xoyog) of soul, or, in other words, its very nature,” cjg ravrrjg ovor]g (pvoeog i pvxVS* Phcedrus , 245, D. We need not remind the reader that in this passage, as well as in the tenth of The Laws, the term sow/ is taken collective- ly for the oldest soul, as the source of all animation, and in- cluding all other souls as in some way proceeding from it. XXVII. The Words Xoyog, eldog, and idea. Page 28, Line 9. j uev, rrjv ovaiav ev 6e, rrjg ovoiag rov Xoyov • ev 6e ovoya. “ One thing the essence, one the X oyog, reason, definition, or notion of the essence, and one the name.” A oyog, when rendered reason , is not to be taken for the faculty of the mind to which we give that ap- pellation. It more properly signifies the reason of a thing ; the reason as existing in a thing, perceived, or, rather, un- derstood by the mind, or the rationale. It is not the reason why the thing exists, or the final cause, as we often use the term, but, rather, the constituting cause , what Aristotle calls to tl fjv elvat , that which makes anything what it is ; a, particular modification of the general idea of existence. The X oyog is that which is the object of the mind’s intellection ( notio ) ; that which binds together (primary sense of Xeyco) or gathers into a unity for the soul’s contemplation — that to which alone the ovoga , or name, belongs, and without which the thing itself is only an object of sensation. 196 DISTINCTION BETWEEN Xoyog AND OVOpa. In reading Plato, it is sometimes difficult to distinguish between X oyog, eldog, and I6e a. The conclusion to which we have arrived, but which we would state with some de- gree of hesitation, is as follows : A oyog is the notion or reason of a thing viewed in relation to the mind contem- plating it, yet having an existence separate from such a mind ; eldog , the notion in reference to the thing itself — as the ev ev noXXolg, or one in many, residing in it ; Msa, the same, regarded as self-subsisting, apart from mind, and also from the individual things through which it is manifested. The absolute existence of the last is the great question in philosophy. In respect to the second term, which is the one Aristotle is most fond of using, there is no real dis- agreement between him and Plato. If we reject the third hypothesis, there is still a wide difference between that, philosophy which was common to Aristotle, Plato, and Ba- con, and that which is now styled the system of Locke. XXVIII. Distinction between Xoyog and ovopa. Page 30, Line 3. To eavro Kivelv cpqg Xoyov exeiv'rrjv *lvtt)v ovoiav , rjVTcep rovvopa, o 6?] iravreg , ipvxrjv irpooa - yopevopev. The order of this rather complicated sentence would seem to be this : rrjv avrrjv ovoiav (/caff) rjvnep rd ovopa TTpooayopevopev , o drj iravreg (jrpooayopevovoi) xpvx'rj'Vy Xoyov exew — to eavro Kivelv. “ You say, then, that that very essence, of which we predicate that name which all men predicate, namely, vxrj , or soul , hath for its Xoyog self-motion, or avroKivrjoig .” See the notes and explanations accompanying the text. It may, perhaps, be objected, that Plato is resting these important positions on mere words, to which he assigns his own arbitrary definitions or notions. But what is meant by distinction between Xoyog AND ovoya 197 the sneering expression, mere words , which is such a fa- vourite with a certain class of modern declaimers ? What are words — we speak not now of sounds or articulate enun- ciations, dvopara or pryiara, but of the higher term Xoyoi - — what are words, in this sense, but outward expressions of the inward logical necessities of our own minds ? And what can be higher proof for us than those affirmations, which the immutable laws of our own souls compel us to make, in respect to what is included or not included in a certain idea ? Whatever belongs to the idea is necessary ; so, on the other hand, whatever is necessary pertains to an idea, and the exclusion of any part involves, for our minds, a logical contradiction. The naming of them, therefore, cannot be arbitrary, ex- cept so far as the mere outward sound is concerned. There are certain ideas which are not dependent on language, as some of the nominalists of the school of Locke would hold, but language on them. So far, human speech may be re- garded as something supernatural, although its outward dress or vocal forms may have been the result of conven- tional or accidental usage, instead of any natural adapted- ness of sound to sense. We may give to the A oyog, or no- tion, any ovopa we please. We may call it 'ipvxrj , nvevfia, nn» animus , anima , ©etj!, or soul ; we may etymolo- gically associate this ovopa with any such sensible phe- nomenon as we may fancy comes the nearest to the con- ception, such as air, breaLli, fire, (Ether, &c. ; and in this way the ovopa may continually change ; but the Xoyog is not conventional. In all languages, even from the earliest periods, it has had a distinct vocal sign — as much so as that of body — and we expect, as a matter of course, to find it in every tongue we may investigate. The idea which calls for the name is implanted by God as one of the fixed parts of our being. The metaphysical notion of soul is self-motion, self-energy , avrordvyaiq. Of this notion we R 2 108 DISTINCTION BETWEEN Xoyog AND QVOfld. cannot divest ourselves. Hence, after proving, even from physical premises, that there must be somewhere self-mo - tion , the mind attaches this Xoyog to its ovo[ia, and affirms that this self-motion is soul, 'ipvx'rji ©etjl:, &c. — being the same unchanging notion, whatever be the name — and that this name, although affixed to the flowing and varying sen- sible phenomenon from which it may have been etymologi- cally derived, ultimately represents the immutable Xbyog of which that sensible* phenomenon is the symbol. * To dwell on this distinction between ovopa (or pfjpa) and loyog at greater length, we may say, that the former simply represents a sensible perception or action ( aloOrjTov ), or what Plato sometimes calls eldolov ; the latter, a thought, an idea (idea), the intelligibile, in- tellcctum, or votjtov , being no part of the sensible image or action, but suggested or symbolized by it. All words, being a communica- tion from mind to mind, through matter , must array the thought, du- ring its passage, in the garments of the flesh, or, in other words, must originally represent something sensible. The ovopa, then, in reality, goes no farther than this sensible image or action, which it primarily presents. There are but two stages in the process. The Xoyoc, on the other hand, goes beyond this, and represents the intel- ligibile, or votjtov, of which that image, action, or aiodrjTov, is but the symbol. Here, then, are, in fact, three stages, and the eiduXov, or action, which the word, as ovopa , presents, does itself re-present something still behind it. The life of language is gone, when, with respect to abstract terms, the primary sensible images have faded away and become unknown, or, in other words, when this second stage in the process has been left out, and the word stands for the thought, in the same way that x and y represent quantities in algebra. The same term may be regarded both as ovopa and Aoyof. For example, the word circle, as a name, merely presents that round, sensible image, which, as far as the elduhov is concerned, is the same to the vision of an animal as of a Newton ; as Tioyog, it suggests that cardinal idea, involving all the properties of the figure, which is pres- ent to the mind of the mathematician, and of which this eldulov is itself the word or representative. This cannot be better expressed than in the language of Plato himself, if the Epistles can in any way be regarded as genuine : kv/c^oc, to km to pkoov ek tuv eox^tov lgov arrexov 7r avTrj, AOrOS av elrj ekelvov tyrrep GTpoyyvhov Kal tt Ept^epki DISTINCTION BETWEEN Xoyoq AND OVOJia. 199 It is not a vain support to rely upon language. We may say, in the words which Plato puts into the mouth of Cra- tylus, OlfJLCU fiev tlvcl dvvapiv elvat r\ dvOpomeiav , rrjv 'depevrjv rd npdjra dvopara rolg irpaypaoiv. Cratylus, 438, C. As is shown in this last-cited dialogue, it follows, in its origin and progress, an inward necessity, and must, therefore, possess inward truth and necessary correctness.* * It is a striking proof of its Divine origin (we mean in the bounding, defining, classifying, and combining of ideas, and not in the outward vocal sounds affixed to them), that the atheist or materialist cannot use it as it is, but must change the meaning of its terms to suit non-existent notions, to which it never has been and never can be adapted, without introducing confusion extending far beyond the particular cases of amendment. He must have an entire new dialect, and that, too, one which will ever destroy itself by the con- tradictions, discords, and jarring inconsistencies which must* exist between its parts, in every attempt to express the doc- trine of death in words necessitated to glow with a life which no efforts can wholly quench. It has been well observed, that there is no language un- der heaven in which the atheist, the pantheist, or the man who denies the reality of moral distinctions, can talk five minutes without a logical contradiction, or, in other words, a war of ideas. Should they form a new one, and take the utmost pains to adapt it to their philosophy of darkness, it will be found to be built on a disarrangement of the neces- sary and logical elements of speech, and must soon perish by reason of its own innate contradictions. No such Babel, formed in opposition to the high decree of Heaven, can ever ovoya kcll kvkTioq. “ The word circle, representing the idea of equal- ity in every direction, from extremities to a central point, is the lo- yog of that to which roundness, and periphery, and circle, are the names.” Plat., Epist ., vii., 342, B. Compare, also, the Theceteius , 201, 202; Sophista, 221, A. * See Schleiermacher’s Introduction to the Cratylus. 200 DISTINCTION BETWEEN Xoyog AND .OVOpa. stand. The ideas of incorporeal substance, of eternal ves ities, of moral distinctions, cannot be separated from lan guage. The proof of soul and of God is stamped upon it as indelibly as it is written on the firmament of heaven itself. Some of the views we have been endeavouring to set forth may be found admirably stated in Varro’s account of the Platonic or Socratic philosophy, especially in respect to the importance it attached to innate notions and words as representatives of them, in Cicero, Acad. Poster ., viii. : Tertia deinde philosophise pars, quse erat in ratione et in disserendo sic tractabatur ; quanquam oriretur a sensibus, tamen non esset judicium veritatis in sensibus. Mentem (vovg) volebant rerum esse judicem : solam censebant ido- neam cui crederetur, quia sola cerneret id, quod semper es- set, ( ra del ovra ), simplex et unius modi ( del Kara ravra Kal d)oavTG)g) et tale quale esset. Hanc illi ideam appella- bant, jam a Platone ita nominatam : nos recte speciem (el- dog) possumus dicere. Sensus autem omnes hebetes et tardos esse arbitrabantur, nec percipere ullo modo eas res quae subjectae sensibus viderentur, quse essent ita mobiles (psovTa) et concitatse, ut nihil unquam unum esse constans, ne idem quidem, quia continenter laberentur et Jluerent om- nia. Itaque hanc omnem partem rerum opinabilem (do^acr- tov) appellabant. Scientiam autem nusquam esse cense- bant nisi in animi notionibus atque rationibus (Aoyoi), qua de causa dejinitiones rerum probabant, et has ad omnia, de quibus disceptabatur, adhibebant. Yerborum explicatio pro- babatur, qua de causa quceque essent ita nominata , quam etymologiam appellabant. Arguments et quasi rerum notis ducibus utebantur ad probandum et ad concludendum id quod explanari volebant, in qua tradebatur omnis dialectics dis ciplina, id est, orationis ratione conclusae. IMPASSABLE CHASM BETWEEN SPIRIT AND MATTER 201 XXIX. Infinite Distance between Self-motion and Motion by Impulse. Impassable Chasm between Spirit and Matter. The Word ttoXXogttj. Principle of Euphonic Attraction. Page 30, Line 13. T Ap’ ovv oi>x erepov .... 7roA- Xogttjv, k. r. A. This is a very complicated and awkward sentence, with several anomalies, although the general meaning is quite clear. The following is a very free ren- dering : t£ Is not that motion, which takes place in one thing by reason of another, but which never effects that anything shall have motion in itself, by itself — is not such a principle of motion, we say, justly styled second , and even the most remote in degree of all such numbers, however great, as any one might choose to use in the computation ? being, in truth, that kind of motion or change which is pe- culiar to a soulless body.” The order of the latter part (in which, however, we are compelled to use ttoXXogtt] for TToXXoGrrjv, in consequence of the change of position) would be as follows : devrepa re nal noXXoGrrj togovtcov apiOytiv 6tt6gg)v rig dv fiovXoiro avr'fv dpiSpslv. The general sense is, that motion by impulse, or the motion of matter, although it may be next in order ( devrepa ), is yet almost infinitely removed from self-motion, or the motion of soul ; that is, by a distance greater than any limit assignable in numbers. It is another mode of saying that there is an impassable chasm between them, by which they are forever parted and assigned to two distinct worlds of being. Materializing naturalists have ever been striving to fill up or bridge this chasm, either by a direct connexion through some most sub- tle matter, or imponderable agent, or occult quality, or by some tertium quid which might identify in one common es- sence these two motions, or, rather — the great object £>f all 202 IDEAS OF CHANGE, CAUSE, AND SPIRIT, INSEPARABLE* their strivings — to make the higher a result of the lower These efforts, however, from the days of Plato to the pres- ent, have been all in vain. The distance between the nat- ural and the supernatural, or between the spiritual and ma- terial, must ever remain impassable by any uniting essence. The most aethereal motions of matter, even of that class of substances which the ancients included under the general names rrvp and alOrjp , and which the moderns have styled imponderable agents, make no approach to the self-motion or avroKLvrjOLg of Spirit. However subtile and attenuated they may be, yet, as matter, and falling under that one idea • of matter to which we have before alluded (page 142), the laws of our minds (from which we cannot escape, and aside from which there is, to us, no such thing as truth) compel us to regard them as destitute of all motion and all property of motion in themselves — in fact, as much so as the most ponderous mass of lead or iron. Plato was deeply sensible of the importance of this fundamental position, and there- fore he labours so earnestly, even at the hazard of being thought tedious and prolix, to maintain it. We have made the remark before, and yet its importance and its adapted- ness to our present subject will justly warrant its repetition. This point being conceded to the atheist, namely, that self- motion may in some way be an occult property of matter in itself, or that the least and most aethereal atom in the uni- verse could ever get in motion without the aid of that older and higher something to which he has here assigned the Xoyog and the ovopa ; or that there is the distance of a hair’s breadth between the ultimate ideas of change , cause , and the action of spirit — this, we say, being conceded to the atheist, all is lost. If this can be conceived of, or is not at war wkh the idea, or Adyo^, of matter, as given u§ by the laws of our own minds, then may it also be conceived of as having an occult adaptive property, and the conclusion can- not be resisted, which would alike establish materialism in EUPHONIC ATTRACTION. 203 respect to man, and pantheism (which is, in fact, the same doctrine) in respect to the universe. UoaXogttjv, as it appears in this sentence, is a very pe- culiar word. It signifies one of many, a fraction whose de- nominator is a very large number, and hence its name — an infinitesimal part. Compare the Philebus, 44, P. : ra 7ioA- Xogtcl mc?i7]p6rrjTL ; where it is put in direct contrast with otckrjpoTara, as an infinitesimal fraction opposed to a su- perlative. There is also a peculiar grammatical anomaly in this word. According to the order of its construction in the sentence, it should be tcoXXogt? /, since it regularly re- fers to devrepa , and must be taken in connexion with it. It is, however, made accusative, in consequence of its position after the infinitive, apcOpelv , and by the attraction of avrrjv. This differs from the ordinary case of attraction which ex- ists between the relative and antecedent. It may be styled euphonic, because it seems to affect words solely for the sake of euphony, or, rather, homceophony, and on the mere ground of contiguity in location, although very remotely re- lated in all other respects ; so much so, that, in this way, great violence is sometimes done to the true grammatical construction. There is no need of resorting to any various reading, or to any conjectural emendation. We have no doubt, from the location of the word, that Plato wrote ttoX- XoGrrjv, however harsh the construction may appear to us. The position of togovtov also seems very awkward, and yet (although we cannot well keep it in that place when we adopt the order for a literal translation) it is easy to see that, by standing where it does, it has a much stronger em- phasis than though it had occurred in the beginning of the clause ; as though we should thus paraphrase it in English : “ However great the number , carry it as high as you please , still by so much (togovtov) is it remote ,” &c. This princi- ple of local or euphonic attraction, although it sometimes interferes with grammatical smoothness, is undoubtedly in 204 ATHEISTIC ARGUMENT AGAINST DESIGN. accordance with the genius of the language ; and no true scholar can endure the attempts which are sometimes made to divest it of this peculiarity by means of pretended emen- dations. - XXX. Argument of Ancient Atheists , that Apparent Evidences of Design were only Evidences of Subsequent Accommodation. Things {they said) older than Knowledge of Things , and therefore older than Soul. Page 31, Line 8. Tporcot, 6rj nai ijOrj nai (3ovXrjaecg teal XoyLopoi Tcporepa aoparov, ti. r. X. The full force of this unnot be appreciated unless we keep in mind the objection against which it was directed. The ancient atheists said that soul was the offspring or result of matter, and conse- quently younger. Hence what theists would call evidences of design , or of mind’s preceding matter, they would regard as merely subsequent accommodations to an accidental ex- isting state of things, which, had it been any other, would, in like manner, have drawn after it the only uses and ac- commodations to which it could be adapted ; and which, in that case, would have carried w T ith them like appearances of previous design, or, as Lucretius has most concisely ex- pressed it, Nil adeo natum est in corpore, ut uti Possemus, sed quod natum est, id procreat usum. Lucretius , iv., 832. Thus, for example, they would say, in accordance with their theory, that teeth were not made of a certain shape with the previous design that the animal should eat herbs, but that, because they happened to be of a certain form (and there was no reason in themselves why they should be of one form rather than another), therefore nature applied them ATHEISTIC ARGUMENT AGAINST DESIGN. 205 9 to the use, and the only use, adapted to their accidental structure. Again, if certain bodies had, in the course of ages, received from tv%7] elongated projections from the main trunk, or an attenuated and flexible shape, or a round- ed form, in all these cases, they would have said, and did say, that that animation residing in them (which was itself but a junior art, the production of an older tyvocg ), when it found itself thus circumstanced , made the best of its condi- tion, by accommodating the one to a walking, the other to a crawling, and the other to a rolling locomotion. So, also, had they been acquainted with some of the arguments of our modern natural theology, they would have denied that the revolution of the earth on its axis was adjusted to twen- ty-four hours, with any design that such a period should correspond to designed circumstances in the alternating • changes which occur in the economy of the animal and vegetable tribes. On the contrary, they would have con- tended that, in the eternal and fortuitous dance of tv%7], the earth having received such an accidental impulse as just produced the aforesaid period, nature, in time, accommoda- ted to it the intervals for the exercise and relaxation of hu- man bodies, together with „all the periodical vicissitudes which seem to have relation to such a revolution ; and that, had this accidental period been of any other length, the same adapting (pvcug and rv^r] would, long before this, have brought all the earthly economy into perfect harmony with it. This argument, of which we have given an imperfect outline, they carried to great length, and it is easy to see that it is capable of a most extensive and subtle application. It is difficult, if not impossible, for any one who admits the doctrine of occult properties to any extent in matter, to give a direct answer to the objections drawn from it ; and yet we believe that not a vestige of any skeptical doubt which it may produce can remain upon the mind, after reading Pa- ley’s most valuable work on natural theology. As a specu- S 206 THINGS OLDER THAN KNOWLEDGE OF THINGS. lative argument, this doctrine of subsequent accommodation, as opposed to a previous designed use, may have a formi- dable appearance, but it vanishes on a close observation of nature, because the soul, in such observation, instead of re- ally relying on a 'posteriori facts, cannot divest itself of that a priori view which believes in design, and looks for de- sign, and carries along the preconception of design as in- volved in those ideas of God and truth with which it enters upon the investigation. Plato, as we have seen, overcomes the difficulty by be- ginning with motion instead of evidences of design ; thence, from this more remote point of view, proving the higher an- tiquity of soul, then of the acts or exercises of soul, one of which is /3ov?i7](7Lg , purpose , or design . Another subtle objection from this same school was, that knowledge, being the knowledge of things , must, therefore,, have been posterior to things ; hence that mind was young- er than matter. In this they, of course, rejected the doc- trine of any other knowledge than that of things, or that the mind or intellect contained, in any sense, its own ideas or intelligibles {yoryra) ; making it to be all from without by way of impression from the external world.* If this be * Should it be said that the objection may be stated in the same way in respect to ideal or eternal truth, and that there must have been vo7]T& before vovg , or truth before knowledge, the only reply is, that God is at the same time, and from eternity, both vovq and votjtov , intclligens and inlelligibile , or intellectual. It is the absolute neces- sity of some such view which suggested to the most profound minds of antiquity the idea of a plurality in the Divine nature, a dis- tinction of two hypostases, at least, with a third, ipvxv, to which they were related, and in which they were united. Instead of being contrary to reason, it was the highest result to which she arrived (if the truth w r as not rather obtained from some primitive revela- tion), as her only refuge against the cheerless and incomprehensible conception of an eternal, solitary monadity, or the equally difficult conception of a necessary, eternal, outward universe, towards which the Divine love and the Divine intelligence might be directed. PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE EVIL PRINCIPLE. 207 atheism, as it most assuredly is, when held in relation to the Divine Mind, what shall we think of the corresponding doctrine when applied to the human soul ? If we start from the conclusions to which such inquiries lead us, it should be borne in mind, that the only possible defence against them must be found in that ideal philosophy which supposes a knowledge belonging to mind, as mind , whether it be Di- vine or human, entirely independent of things , or of any out- ward world. The above atheistic objection is also express- ed by Lucretius, with far more of poetry than piety : Exemplum porro gignundis rebus, et ipsa Notities hominum Divis unde insita primum, Quid vellent facere, ut scirent, animoque viderent'? Quove modo est unquam vis cognita principiorum, Quidnam inter sese permutato ordine possent, Si non ipsa dedit specimen natura creandi 1 Lucretius, lib. v., 132. XXXI. Platonic Doctrine of the Evil Principle. Of ’ AvdjK ? /, or Necessity. Page 32, Line 2. A volv yev ye irov eXarrov yrjdev nOti- yev, Trjy re evepyendog real rrjg ravavrla dvvayevjjg e^ep. ya&oOai — “ Nothing less than two, at least, the one that does us good, and the one that is able to do the contrary.” We have here presented, in the most unequivocal terms, that grand defect in Plato’s theology, which occasionally mars, by its presence, almost every part of his otherwise noble system. It is most clear, from this and other passages in his dialogues, that he held the doctrine of two uncreated principles or souls, one good (or the benefactor, as he styles him), the other evil. Neither Plato, however, nor Zoroas- ter, can be charged with the absurdity of believing in two Supremes. They avoided this by running into the incon- 208 PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE EVIL PRINCIPLE. sistency of supposing that the evil principle, although un- created, was under the dominion of the good, constantly controlled, and ultimately to be completely conquered by it. This doctrine, likewise, made harsh discord with almost every other part of his philosophy, especially his views of the origin of the universe, as set forth in the Timaeus, where no mention is made of a distinct evil soul ; and yet, when we examine the matter closely, it is difficult to see how he could have come to any other conclusion. Plato had no other guide than reason, aided, perhaps, by a dim and cor- rupted tradition of primitive truth ; and reason can account in no other way for the existence of evil, without charging it upon God as its immediate author. It is evident, from the manner in which he ever speaks on this subject, that he had a deep conviction of the essential goodness of the Deity, and that he felt himself sorely pressed by the diffi- culty of reconciling with this goodness the evil which he saw everywhere existing in the world. On this point, compare what he says in the second book of the Republic , 379, B., C. : ovuovv ayaOog 6 ye tieog rep ovti re , teat Xek- tsov ovro) — “ Wherefore is not God really good, and must we not thus ever affirm?” "0 6e ye p?]dev nanov iroiel, ovd' av rivog eh] nanov ’AJTION. ovk apa uavrcov ye acri- ov to ayaOov, aXXa rcbv pev ev exovrcov alriov , tcov be nancov avatnov. ovd ’ apa 6 deog IIANTI2N av elrj ’AJTI02, cog oi noXXol Xeyovoiv • dAA’ oXiycov pev rolg avOpamocg alriog , iroXXcbv 6e avalnog • noXi) yap eXdrrco rayaQa tgjv uancov rjplv — “ But he doeth nothing evil (evidently taking nanbv here in the sense of physical evil), nor could he be the cause of anything evil. The Good cannot, then, be the author of all things, but only of those that are good, while he is never the author of the bad. God cannot, therefore, be the author of all things, as the many say, but only of few things is he the cause to men, &c .,for our good things are much fewer in number than our evil things .” He does PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE EVIL PRINCIPLE. 20G not, in this place of the Republic, directly speak of the evil principle, but leaves it to be plainly inferred : Tow 6e na- n6)V aXXa arra del tyrelv rd atria , dXX' ov rov 'deov — Of the evils, then, must we seek some other cause, and not the Deify.” After this, he proceeds to censure Homer for his myth of the two casks which lie in the court of Jove, one filled with good and the other with evil, from which he dispenses to mortals severally as he will.* When we read the impressive application of this great truth which Achilles makes to the case of Priam, we cannot help recognising the poet as far more orthodox than the philosopher, and as coming much nearer to the true teaching of revelation. He was so, however, because, instead of yielding his mind to the perplexing and insurmountable difficulties which attend every merely speculative view of the matter, he simply gives utterance to one of those universal and unvarying sen- timents of the human soul, which could have come from no other source than a tradition of the primeval fall and the woes consequent upon it. Revelation removes this difficulty respecting the origin of evil, not by solving the mystery, and bringing it down to the level of our understandings, but by imposing silence upon reason, in her attempt to investigate a subject alto- gether beyond her powers. The Bible does not shrink from the solemn declaration, I form the light and I create the darkness ; I make peace and I create evil ; I the Lord do ALL these things and yet, at the same time, it sternly A oiol yap re ttlOoi KaraKeiarai hv A log ovdei, dopov, ola dtdoGi, nantiv, erepog de, eucov. d [lev k ’ apfii^ag 6oltj Zevg, k. t. X. — Iliad , xxiv., 527. t Isaiah , xlv., 7. There can be no doubt, from the mention here of the light and the darkness , and from the connexion of this remark- able declaration with the prophecy respecting Cyrus, that there must have been intended a special reference to the Zoroastrian or Persian doctrine. S 2 210 PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE EVIL PRINCIPLE. forbids the impious thought, that the Divine Essence can hold any communication with sin. Thou art of purer eyes than to behold iniquity. Evil shall not dwell with thee. The caviller may say that this is cutting, instead of untying the Gordian knot ; and that, according to this, revelation teach- es the apparent contradiction, that God creates evil, and yet is not the author of sin, without which there could be no evil. It is even so. There is a contradiction to our un- derstandings, but it is a contradiction to which we must submit, or receive all the contradictions, mysteries, absurd ities, and total darkness of atheism. It has been well ob- served, that this great difficulty lies, in some form, at the very threshold of every system which has the least title to be styled religious, in order to teach us that, some things must be received as matters of faith. This, instead of be- ing at war with reason, is, in fact, its highest dictate. It presents an incipient faith as the only condition on which everything else is to be understood, and declares that we are shut up to it by something higher and stronger than reason itself, even the necessities of our moral being . Let those who, in such a case as this, will not take the Bible as their only guide, devise, if they can, a better sys- tem than the one which Plato and Zoroaster felt themselves compelled to adopt, although they must have been well aware of the difficulties, and war of ideas, or first princi- ples, in which it involved them. They could not believe in two Supremes on account of the logical contradiction, and yet, if they held that the evil soul was inferior to, and capable of being controlled by, the Good (as they unques- tionably did), the same old objection comes back with all its force. The position to which our philosopher manifests so strong a repugnance is only so changed as to make God the permissive , instead of the positive author of evil. Small consolation in this ; especially when taken in connexion with that melancholy declaration just quoted by us from the TLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE EVIL PRINCIPLE. 211 second book of the Republic, that “ our good things are much fewer in number than our evil things.” It should be remarked, however, that Plato’s evil princi- ple differed, in some most important respects, from the evil spirit made known to us in the Bible. The former, al- though recognised by him as a 'ipvxv, or soul, was not so much a moral or spiritual, as a physical power. It was the dark, foolish, disorderly, intractable, chaotic, evil spirit of matter (if we may use so paradoxical a term), on which the Good God was ever exerting an influence, in bringing it from chaos into harmony, although that influence was ever resisted, and sometimes exercised with great difficulty. It is to this he alludes in the Timaeus, although in this lat- ter work we find no trace of that animation and personality which is assigned to the evil principle in the tenth of The Laws. In the Timaeus, too, although possessed of motion and a sort of blind activity, it is a hinderance, or an obstacle, rather than an enemy : BovXrjOeig yap 6 $ ebg ayaOa psv navra , (f)Xavpov 6s pr]6sv elvat , ovro) 6f] rtdv ooov rjv opa- rov napaXadcov oi>x rfOvx^ v ciyov , aXXa tuvovpevov* rrXrjp- psXtig teal ardteredg, Kara 6vva\av slg rd^tv avro rjyaysv etc rrjg ara^iag. Qsjug yap our’ rjv ovr ’ son T12I ’APIU- T£2I 6pav aXXo TrXrjv to KAAAI2T0N — “For God, wish- ing that all things should be good, and that there should be * On this and some few similar expressions in the Timaeus has been grounded the argument for the common position, that Plato held to the eternity of matter, and that it possessed a principle cf its own, independent of the creating and constantly energizing pow- er of the Deity. Should it be admitted that our philosopher is justly chargeable with inconsistency, still we contend that the positions assumed in the Laws in respect to the inertness of matter, and the superior antiquity of soul, should have the greater weight, inasmuch as the extracts from the Timaeus are merely incidental declarations, whereas the latter form the very heart and substance of one of his most studied and elaborately-prepared arguments. See farther, on this subject, Note L., On the Ancient Doctrine , Dc Nihilo Nihil jit. 212 PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE EVIL PRINCIPLE. nothing bad, thus taking in hand the visible (or material), never at rest, but ever moving about in a strange and disor- derly manner, as far as he could reduced it from disorder to order. For it is not permitted (ov tiefug, it is morally impossible) for the Best Being to do anything else than the best” Timceus, 30, A. So, also, in that trinity about which so much has been said, and which but faintly appears in any parts of his authentic dialogues, the or third hy- postasis, seems to be rather a benign physical influence, than to make any approach to that renovating moral power which is revealed in the Scriptures. If we should dare to institute any comparison, we would say that it has more resemblance to the nn of Genesis, i., 2, and Psalms, civ., 30, than to the Ttvevfia of Paul and John. The truth is, that, on this great and difficult subject of the existence and origin of evil, the mind of Plato seems to have wavered, and to have had different opinions at differ- ent times. Here he very briefly, yet very distinctly, avows his belief in a 'personal evil soul . In the Republic he leaves it as a matter of inference, contenting himself with the dec- laration, that God is the author of good, and of good only, while, at the same time, he asserts that the evil predomi- nates, at least in the present state. In the Timaeus, it is a lower order of being, the dark and chaotic principle of mat- ter, possessing something of a positive character, yet still without anything psychical or animate in its nature. In the Politicus, or Statesman, there is a view, in some of its fea- tures, allied to this, yet capable of being resolved into what modern theologians would call a mere permission of evil, as a negative principle, deriving its power from occasional withdrawals of the Divine presence and superintendence. This we gather from that most singular myth, in which he represents the universe as subject to alternate revolutions of immense length, during one of which good and perfection predominate, while, in the other, although the good, for a PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE EVIL PRINCIPLE. 213 long time, exerts an influence, through habit, even after the withdrawal of the Divine Presence, yet evil and disorder, being introduced by degrees, increase more and more, until, finally, Old Chaos comes again, and total destruction would ensue, did not God once more resume the long-abandoned helm. It is a portion of Plato’s works on which but little attention has been bestowed, and yet, in consequence of its always having seemed to us to possess a deep theological interest, we give the passage to our readers at some length, and in a very free version : “ God himself, at one time, guides this universe (fvyi Todrjyel), and turns it round. Again, he abandons it to itself, when the periods of its des- tined times have received their full complement ; when, be- ing animate, and having had wisdom implanted in it from him who harmonized it at the beginning, it commences of its own accord to move in a contrary direction ; and this tendency to a retrograde motion arises from an innate ne- cessity of its nature. For to be ever in the same relations [nard ravra ), and uniform, and the same, pertains alone to those things which are most divine ; but the nature of mat- ter has no share in this dignity. What we name, therefore, the heavens or the universe ( ovpavov real nooyov), hath par- taken of many blessed things or qualities from him who generated it ; still, it has communion with matter, and, on this account, it is impossible that it should be altogether exempt from change, although, as far as it is capable, it moves on in one regular course, in the same and according to the same relations. It is in this way that it gets this property of unrolling, or rolling back, consisting, at first, in the slightest conceivable change or parallax of its previous motion. For anything always to turn itself is impossible, except for Him who is the supreme controller of all moving things ; but for this Being to act in a changeable manner, or to turn things, now in this direction, and now in the con- trary, is impossible ( ov fiefur, is morally impossible ). For 214 PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE EVIL PRINCIPLE. all these reasons must we say, that the world neither turns itself forever, nor that it is forever turned by God in con- trary circuits. N either must we suppose that two Gods * with opposing purposes conduct its revolutions {prjp avrov orpe- (j)£tv eavrov del, prjr' av oXov imo deov orpecpeodai del 6 lt- rd g real evavrtag TrepLaycoyag, j upp av 6vo rive tied) (f>po- vovvre eavrotg evavria Grpecpeiv avrov), but, as has been said (and which, in fact, is the only supposition left), that, at one time, it is guided by a Divine cause ; during which period it receives again the acquired power of life, and an immortality not innate, but imparted to it from the Demiur- gus ; and then, again, that it goes by itself, being abandon- ed so long, that even many ten thousand years may be oc- cupied in the revolution.” Politicus, 269, P. The myth then proceeds to describe the alternate pe- riods. The first, or that which is under the direct care of the Deity, is represented as the golden age, during which time the earth produces all things spontaneously, without cultivation, and, in general, the order of all things is from death to life.f This was the reign of Saturn. Good was * This is in direct opposition to the doctrine laid down in The Laws, where he maintains that there are at least two souls, one good and the other bad, occupied in the movements of the universe. Here, however, he seems to be very much averse to such an opin- ion, as inconsistent and unnatural. Some would say that this fur- nishes conclusive evidence that the one or the other, or both of these dialogues, are spurious. If such an argument could be held legitimate, the conclusion would certainly be against the Politicus, since the doctrine of The Laws was followed by all the subsequent Platonists, and regarded as an undoubted position of their master ; but, in truth, instead of invalidating either, it only show’s how a great mind wavered on the deepest question in philosophy and theology. f It might, however, seem, to some, to be rather a species of in- verted death, as during this period the order of all things is so chan- ged, that the old commence a process of return to the vigour of mid- dle age, manhood returns to youth, youth to boyhood, boyhood to infancy, infancy to entire disappearance from the stage of life. In PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE EVIL PRINCIPLE. 215 predominant, although there is no little confusion in the ac- count which this splendid myth, in other respects so clear, gives of this period. It at last, however, comes to an end, and when the complement of the times had been filled up, and the change must take place, then, it is said, the Divine Pilot , letting go the helm , retires to his secret place of obser- vation , and destiny and innate tendency are left to turn hack the revolutions of the world : tots 6i) tov rravTog 6 [isv nv- depvrjTpg , olov rrrjdakiGiv olanog acpepevog slg tt)v clvtov TT spLCJTTrjv aTTsoT?) • tov 6s dij uoopov rtdXtv dvsoTpscj)SV Kipappsv7] ts uai ^vpcpVTog smOvp'ia , 272, E. At the same , time, the other A aipovsg, to whom, as presiding divinities, or angels,* -the various parts of the universe had been al- lotted in subordination to the Supreme Ruler, hear the sig- nal, and retire from their respective provinces. Then com- mences the predominance of evil. Nature, through all her works, gives signs of wo. First, a strange tremour or com- motion ( osiopbg TTohvg) is felt in every part of the aban- doned world. After a while, however, to employ Plato’s imagery, the vessel ceases from the tumultuous surging which at first ensues, and enjoying a calm, gets at length into the new course in which it is destined to proceed. The world goes on for a season with some degree of regu- larity, in consequence of influences being yet exerted by those laws and principles to which it had been accustomed in that previous state when it was directly under the Divine continuation of the same wild and strange fancy, the dead are said to come out of their graves, and thus to be born again from the earth : ek, rtiv TETETievTrjtiOTov av, kel/j,£v(*)v 6e ev yy } tt a?uv ekel %vvig- rafjLEVovg Kal avafiiooicopEVOvg, ETTEodaL ry rpoTrrj — ovvavanvK?iOVfj,Evrjg slg Tavavrca rf/g ysvicrEog. We can hardly help thinking that in this singular myth may be traced the rudiments of an ancient doctrine of a resurrection. The general idea intended by Plato is clear enough, and yet so much confusion rests upon the details, that it sometimes is difficult to decide to which period they in fact belong. * See Note XXXIV., on the Platonic Doctrine of the Animation of 216 PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE EVIL PRINCIPLE. care. # By slow degrees the former motion, with the order and harmony by which it was accompanied, is diminished, until, having passed the minimum point, it makes a transi- tion to the contrary direction with a constantly accelerated momentum. It is then that the greatest deteriorations and corruptions take place ; first, of the vegetable, next, of the animal world, and, finally, of the human race, until here and there a small and wretched remnant alone survive. The old har- mony, the remembrance of which had not before been en- tirely quenched, is now utterly extinct. The former laws of nature are all reversed, until, finally, when on the very verge of utter ruin — tot’ TjSrj o Beog, naOopCov avrov ev dno- otatg bvra, KTjdopevog Iva p?) ^Bipaodelg imo rapa)(f\g bta- XvOelg elg rov rrjg avopotorprog auetpov ovra rorrov dv'qj ttclXlv eepedpog avrov rcbv nrjdaXiojv ytyvopevog , ra voorj- oavra teal XvOevra orpBifjag , Koopel re teal enavopOtiv, aOa- varov avrov nal ayrjpG) anspya^eraL — “ God, beholding it in great extremity, and being concerned, lest, being over- whelmed in disorder and utterly dissolved, it should plunge again into the limitless, formless region of dissimilitude and chaos, once more seats himself at the helm ( from which he had before returned to his secret place of observation , elg ri)v avrov rrepiOJTcrjv), and having arrested its weak and dissolv- ed parts in their course to ruin, arranges it again in order, rectifies it, and thus renders it immortal,” 273, D. the Heavenly Bodies ; and Note LXVII., on the Platonic Doctrine of tlic Demons or Genii. * Or, in the expressive language of the original, ttjv tov narpog 61- daxrjv anopvrjfiovEvuv dg dvvapiv — “ Still, as well as it could, remem- bering the teaching of its father.” The allusion seems to be to the fable of Phaeton striving in vain to remembe^and follow the direc- tions given him by his father, when he so rashly undertook to drive the chariot of the Sun. t Lest it should plunge again into the limitless place of dissimilitude. That is, back again to old chaos. The language strongly ceJJ? fo mind the JiriDl n °f Genesis, i 2 . 217 of avdynTj , or necessity. We find occasionally in Plato, especially in the Timaeus, mention made of dvdynr] , or necessity , as some strong and apparently opposing power, on which the Divine energy was constantly exercised, not so much in directly overcom- ing, as in controlling and directing it to the accomplishment of the Divine purposes. Thus, in the Timaeus, 48, A., he speaks of the generation of the world having proceeded from the combined operation of vovg and avdynr] , mind and necessity. To the former, however, he ascribes a species of authority, yet of a persuasive rather than of a violent na- ture : Nov 6s avdyrcrjg dp^ovrog, rep rtdduv avrrjv rtiv yeyvopevov ra nXelora enl to /3sXtigtov ayetv , ravr'q 6i 9 avdyurjg rjTTCjpevrjg vi to iruOovg epeppovog, ovro) % vvioraro rode to nav — “ But, since Mind rules Necessity, by per- suading her to bring to the best results the most of things as they are generated ; thus, in this way, through necessity overcome by rational persuasion, this universe received its construction.” By dvdyfcrj, here, Plato does not mean his evil soul , nei- ther does he generally intend any physical necessity ari- sing from motion as a property of matter (although he and the Greek poets* do sometimes apply the term to what we style the laws of nature, and it has something of this aspect in the present passage from the Timaeus), but rather a met- aphysical or logical necessity, a necessity existing in the idea of a thing, in its constituting cause , or that which makes it what it is — in its Xoyog , or notion — in short, a necessity of the mind, by which it is compelled to include certain principia in the very definition of any existing or conceiv- able thing; and hence he employs in respect to it such terms as rcdOecv, and iretOovg epeppovog, words which would have little or no meaning as applied to a purely physical necessity. * As, for example, Euripides, Troades, 893 : Zfik, elr y avayurj tyvoeoQ , elre vovq pporuv. T 218 of avdyicrj, on necessity. For example, in the idea of matter, or rather body, im- penetrability necessarily enters. Hence, also, the impos- sibility that two bodies should ever occupy the same space ; which we have shown (page 143) to be more of a logical than a physical necessity. God cannot make matter with- out this. It is no more irreverent thus to speak, than to say that God cannot make matter or body, which is not body, or in any case go contrary to the idea of anything, and yet have it remain the same. Motion is not a necessary prop- erty of matter ; and when we say this, we mean that there is no law of our minds, as in the above cases, which com- pels us to predicate it of matter. Other species of logical necessity (that is, a necessity in the ideas of things ) are the mathematical avdyuai. Hence, the laws of motion, being partly mathematical and partly physical, are necessary, so far as they partake of the former character. It is not ne- cessary that bodies should attract each other in the inverse ratio of the squares of their distances : had it been the or- dinance of God, it would have been in the ratio of their cubes. When, however, the Deity establishes such a mo- tion as a fact, it must conform to all the necessities of num- bers involved in, and which grow out of, the first simple formula or statement of the law. So, also, in morals, the idea of good may, perhaps, necessarily include the contin- gency of evil ; sin may be necessarily associated, in idea, with misery. In all such cases, Plato would speak of the Deity not as violently overcoming necessity, but as ruling, directing, controlling it, to bring about the purposes of his moral government, or, in other words, using towards it “ a kind of rational persuasion.” MOTION OF VOVg COMPARED TO THAT OF A SPHERE. 219 XXXII. Platonic Analogy between the Motion ofNovg and ^v%7] ana that of a Sphere, or of the Heavens. Page 34, Line 5. E l pev rj t-vpnaoa ovpavov bdog apa nal (popa vov Kivrjoei real nepiepopa Kai Xoyiopolg opoiav (pvotv ex et Kai %vyyevtig epxsrai, k. t. A. — “ If the whole way and course of the heavens hath a nature similar to the course, and period, and reasonings of mind, and proceeds in a kindred manner, we must certainly affirm that the best soul ( [rrjv evepyenda) takes care of the universe.” We may compare with this the expressions, nepiodog vov — 7T£- piodog 'ipvx'ijg, which occur so frequently in the Timaeus : Tdf rr\g aOavdrov ipv%$jg nepiodovg evedovv elg emppvrov nal anoppyrov owpa. Timceus, 43, A. So, also, 39, where there is the same allusion in the expression, rj rijg ptag nal (ppompojrdrrjg KVK^rjoecog nepiodog. After the description of the visible animal (£g3op oparov), or material universe in which the new-created soul of the world was to reside, he thus says : KivrjOiv yap anevetpev avTtp rrjv rov odparog pa’kiora oiKeiav, rcov ejira rr\v nepi vovv nai (ppovrjoiv paXiora ovoav. did drj Kara ravra, ev rep avrep Kai ev avrep rtepiayayebv avro, enotrjoe kvkXco K ivelodai orpeepopevov — “ For he gave to it a peculiar mo- tion of its own, namely, that one of the seven which has the nearest relation (or analogy) to mind and wisdom. Wherefore, guiding it so as to move always in the same relations, in the same place, and within itself, he made it revolve in a circle.” Timceus , 33, P. We have the same idea a little farther on in this tenth book of The Laws, page 35, line 15 : To Kara ravra diyrtov Kai ehoavreog Kai ev tgj avrep, Kai nepi ra avrd, Kai npog ra avrd , Kai eva Xoyov Kai ra%iv piav apepeo Kivelodai Xeyovreg, vovv, rrjv re ev kvi (pepopev7]v KivrjOiv, oepatpag evropvov aneiKaopeva vGeojg nal rrjg rov erepov. The first he likens to spherical or circular motion (<£ epopevrjv ev evi), and finds its symbolical expression in the steady, unvarying, and eternal revolution of the sphere of the fixed stars or highest heavens (wheth- er regarded as phenomenal or not makes, in this respect, no difference). The other, which he elsewhere styles a bas- tard reason (vodog XoytGpog ), is conceived as represented by the irregular, variant, and sometimes retrograde motions of the lower bodies, and especially of the terrestrial phe- nomena. Matter and the external world being in a con- tinual flux, he regarded sensation, and that exercise of rea- son which takes sensation and phenomenal facts for its necessary hypotheses , as partaking of all the instability of its ever-flowing foundation. See the Tim77 naidevcrsog — it ac- quires calmness, abstraction, and stability ; and having thus escaped from this most fearful disorder, comes at length un- der the abiding influence of immutable truth as exhibited in the eternal ideas of which matter presents only the flowing and varying diagrams. The whole passage is too long for insertion continuously, and some parts are quite difficult. We would, however, earnestly recommend its perusal to the student, not only for its most sublime imagery, but also for the profound philosophy of human nature which is con- tained beneath it. See the Timceus, from page 42, P., to page 44, D. XXXIV. Platonic Doctrine of the Animation of the Heaveiily Bodies . Ancient Belief that each Nation had its own 'peculiar Guardian Daemon or Genius. Page 38, Line 6. r/ H/l tov real oeXrjvrjv teal ra aWa do- rpa. The next question, after deciding the nature of the governing soul, is, whether it is one supreme, or many sub- ordinate (plav rj tt X etovg), engaged in these offices. Here is another point in Plato’s theology which has given offence to some of his warmest admirers. It has also been the sub- ject of peculiar animadversion by Warburton and others, who have been as far as possible removed from the Platon- ic spirit. They would charge our philosopher here with an absurd polytheism, in making each one of the heavenly bodies either a divinity in itself, or, at least, under the con- trol of a separate divinity. If by this is meant that he did not t believe in one Supreme Ineffable Power, the generator and creator of all other existences, whether divine (in the U 230 ANIMATION OF THE HEAVENLY BODIES. Greek sense of deoi, as we have explained it, page 104) or human, the answer is found in places of his dialogues too numerous to mention ; and especially might we refer to the remarkable passage in the TimaBus (41, A.), in which the Eternal Parent thus addresses the inferior divinities to whom he had given being : Oeot fteCdv cjv eyd) drjptovpyog Trarrjp re epyo)v, k . t. X. His great object here is to show, in opposition to the atheist, that soul, or instead of tvxtj, guides the motions of the heavenly bodies. Indeed, throughout the whole argument, he evidently regards the being of a God, and of soul generally, distinct from, and not a result of, bodily organization, as facts which involve each other, and which are shown by similar and equivalent proofs. He appears to have considered even a belief in the real entity of the human soul as inseparable from an acknowledgment of the Divine existence ; so that the one was, as it were, the ground and guarantee of the other. In this respect, the language of the Hebrew oath, “ as the Lord liveth , and as thy soul liveth ,” expressed the true spirit of his philosophy. In consequence, therefore, of his constant- ly using these terms for each other, we cannot be certain, when he speaks of soul or souls as guiding the motions of the heavenly bodies, whether he means that this was done by the direct agency of the Supreme Soul, or whether it was delegated to inferior spirits ; and whether these dele- gated conducting powers resided severally in the bodies as an animating life, or were separate from them. All these are points which do not affect his main argument. With- out making a division into those distinct hypostases which appear in the Timaeus, he here uses ipvxrj as a general col- lective term for all that is immaterial, or, at least, as a name for the Deity, and all celestial or superhuman powers deri- ved from, and dependent upon, him. This was enough for his argument, without any farther precision or explanation, when dealing with the atheist, who denied all powers above man, be they one or many. ANIMATION OF THE HEAVENLY BODIES. 231 We may even go still farther in our apology, and main- tain, that if he did hold that the heavenly bodies were ani- mated, or that they were severally under the care of dis- trict spirits, there was, in the latter opinion at least, no se- rious error, even when viewed in the light of revelation it- self. The Bible not obscurely teaches that the personal destinies of individual men are, in a measure, under the di- rection and guardianship of supernatural beings. Churches are said to have their guardian angels, according to Reve- lations, ii., 1, which we prefer to take in this literal sense, rather than to adopt any other interpretation which has been forced upon it in the controversy respecting ecclesiastical government. The same doctrine is pretty clearly intimated in respect to nations, Daniel, x., 20, 21, where Greece and Persia are said each to have their invisible champion, whether of a good or of an evil nature. There is also a remarkable passage, Deuteronomy, xxxii., 8, which, if taken according to the Septuagint version, would directly estab- lish the same doctrine : When the Most High divided the nations , when he separated the sons of Adam, he appointed the hounds of the people according to the number of the chil- dren of Israel , nsprp 1 ?, as it is in the Hebrew, but, according to the number of the angels of God — uara aptOpov dyyeX G)v deov — as it stands in the Greek of the Septuagint. We cannot account for the difference, but it certainly seems as though the Greek version was more consonant with the context which follows, and which asserts that Israel is the Lord's peculiar inheritance , in distinction from the other na- tions, who seem to have been left to the subordinate care of other directing powers. This very passage, too, it should be remarked, is quoted by Eusebius, Frcep. Evang., xi., 26, to prove that Plato obtained his doctrine of the A acpoveg from Moses. That such an idea prevailed among the heathen nations, especially the Persians, is evident from Herodotus, vii., 53 : rot Hepolda ypv XeXoyxaoi. 232 ANIMATION OF THE HEAVENLY BODIES. The Bible teaches us also that even the ordinary courses of physical events are under the controlling agency of an- gelic beings. He maketh his angels winds , his ministers a flaming fire ; as the author of the Epistle to the Hebrews renders it. Science, with all its modern boasting, can af- firm nothing in opposition to this. It is a view which in- terferes not at all with the regularity and the apparent laws of physical phenomena, and, as we have seen, the Bible quite plainly reveals it. Nay, more, may there not be found some countenance there to this very doctrine of Pla- to ? If individuals, and churches, and nations, and every department in nature, have their presiding invisible powers, why not the heavenly bodies ? Why not an angel of the sun, of the moon, and of each planet ? Did the ancient Hebrew writers mean only physical instead of psychical powers, when they spoke of the hosts of heaven, and used that most sublime epithet, m'NDV Hi ri], Jehovah Tsehhaoth, or Lord of Hosts ? The Septuagint, by rendering it nvpioq 6vvd[ie(ov, have seemed to refer it to physical rather than to spiritual agencies ; but it is a serious question, whether much more than this is not contained in the Hebrew. Was it simply a sublime personification, when it was said, He bringetli out their host by number ; he calletli them all by name or when we are told that, at the creation of our earth, the stars of the morning sang together, and all the sons of God shouted for joy ?\ We have no hesitation in prefer- ring this, extravagant as it may appear, to that modern ex- treme, which would leave such an immense, unanimated solitude between man and the Deity, instead of filling it up, as the old Patristic theology did, with datgovec, angels, thrones, dominions, principalities, and powers : With helmed Cherubim, And sworded Seraphim, and all that array of invisible beings, whose existence the * Isaiah, xl., 26 . t dob, xxxviii., 7. ANIMATION OF THE HEAVENLY liODIES. 233 Bible does seem to take for granted, although some, in for- mer times, may have carried it to an extravagant extent. Surely we may still maintain the precious Protestant doctrine, that no one but the Supreme Lord of Hosts is en- titled to any the least species of religious adoration, and yet believe in many an order of being, which, although of far higher rank, yet constitute, with man, an immense brother- hood of created intelligences, all intended for the manifest- ation of the glory of Him, by whom, and for whom, all things were created, whether visible or invisible, whether in the earth or in the heavens. There is some reason to fear that Protestants, under the guise of a hyperspirituality, have gone too far in the opposite direction, to what is real- ly a materializing and physical hypothesis. When we dis- cover a disposition to banish in our minds all intermediate spiritual agencies, and, by magnifying natural causes, to place the Deity at the most remote distance possible, it does really seem as though, if we could or durst, we would dispense with his presence also in the regulation of the universe. In all ages, a tendency to that sadduceeism which barely saves the doctrine of the soul’s existence in anothe'r state, has been held, and justly held, to be near of kin to infidelity, if not to downright atheism. Far better to believe too much on this subject than too little, even if we cannot agree, with Plato, that there is a presiding spiritual superintendence assigned to each celestial body. XXXV. Three Hypotheses in respect to the Animation of the Heavenly Bodies. Page 39, Line 7. 'Qg rj kvovoa evrog tgj Tcepu^spel rov- r G), n. r. A. We have here three hypotheses. The first would make the sun itself an animated being ; the second U 2 234 ANIMATION OF THE HEAVENLY BODIES. would regard it as under the direction of an external angel, or A ai[iG)v, having a material yet highly arthereal body, and making use of a sort of impulsive motion ; the third would represent it as under the care of a pure, unimbodied spirit or intellect (' ipiXrj ocj^arog ovoa ), either the Universal Nu- men, or some delegated power specially assigned to that office. If by the last is meant only a particular exercise of the energy of the Universal Soul (which view is perfectly consistent with his present argument against the atheist, although it does not fully agree with some things he says elsewhere), there would be no need of any defence of Plato against the charges to which we have referred. The sec- ond, however, as we have seen, may be held by a firm be- liever in the Christian revelation. The first is only the doctrine of the anima mandi applied to particular parts of the universe. It may be maintained, as Plato did maintain it, in perfect consistency with a pure theism, or a recogni- tion of an Eternal Spirit, not only above the anima mandi , but regarded, also, as its creator and constant guide. There is most abundant proof of this in the Timaeus, and, indeed, we have every reason to believe that Plato meant no more by his soul of the world, whether in respect to the universe or to particular parts, than Cudworth intends by his famous Plastic Nature, to which, in some places, he seems inclined to ascribe a species of obscure animate existence.* In fact, some such hypothesis must be adopted by those who would make nature a distinct thing from the Deity, or a subordi- nate cause under the Divine reason and wisdom ; as all must do who are averse to the doctrine that God does all things by his own immediate agency, or the systematic in- tervention of angelic or spiritual beings. The only escape from one or the other of these is in that philosophy of oc- cult qualities, which is a mere play upon words, a mere apology for ignorance, and which, when carried to its le- Cudworth's Intellectual System , vol. i., page 346, Engl. ed. ypg &X r H JLa > or yehiculum mundi. 235 gitimate results, is, as vve have seen, the most favourable of all hypotheses to atheism. The independent, unoriginated essence ( avroOeog ), which is above nature and above the soul of the world , is called, in the Timaeus, ’AtStog Harrjp , and represented as the genera- tor of and even of No£f. Elsewhere, and especially in the Republic, Plato is fond of styling him To ’ AyaOov , The Good. XXXYI. 1% ”C )xrj[ia, or Vehiculum Mundi. Examination of a Re - markable Passage from Euripides. Page 39, Line 17. ev dppaocv e%ovoa rjplv r\kiov. This cannot be rendered, having the sun in a chariot or vehicle ; for the sense evidently requires that the sun itself be re- garded as the vehiculum of the indwelling spirit. ’Ev here is equivalent to in loco — ev appaoiv — cog dppara — in loco currus—for a vehicle* By a similar phraseology, the body is elsewhere styled o^/m, vehiculum ; as in the Timaeus, 41, C. : eptibaGag cog elg oxrjpa. In that place, however, Plato has reference, not to the animating souls of the heav- enly bodies, but to human souls, placed, or, as he says, sown there previous to their more intimate connexion with matter in their earthly existence, that they might learn those universal truths which were to be recalled to recollection in their subsequent stage of being. f In the Troades of Euripides the same term is applied, in a manner directly the opposite of this, to signify, not the corporeal vehiculum , but the animating, moving power. On account of its deep, intrinsic interest, we give the passage in full, and dwell upon it at some length : * So, also, Laws , xi., 913, C. : kv ovcrta nenTfjoOaL. t Compare Origen contra Celsum, ii., 60. From this came those doctrines which Origen held respecting the pre-existence of souls. 236 yrjg bx^j(ia, 0R vehiculum mundi. T £2 yrjg oxqiia, team yfjg ex^v edpav "OoTig nor’ el cv dvaroTraGTog eldevcu , Zn;f, elf avdynr) (pvaeog, tire vovg (Sportiv^ UpOG7]v^dp,7]v Ge • ndvra yap di tajjotyov B aevov tceTievdov , rcara Alktjv to, fivijr* uyeig. 0 Thou who guid’st the rolling of the earth, And o’er it hast thy throne, whoe’er thou art, Most difficult to know — the far-famed Jove, Or nature’s law, or reason, such as man’s — 1 thee adore, that, in a noiseless path, Thy steady hand with justice all things rules. Euripides , Troades, 890. We do not know which to admire most, the philosophy or the poetical beauty of these remarkable lines. The ex- pression, kccttl yr\g exuv edpav, relieves them, in our view, from all liability to the charge of pantheism. These words, in the connexion in which they appear, are only applicable to what Plato styles 'ipvx'^l vnspicoofifa ; a soul which, al- though pervading, is also, at the same time, above , and dis- tinct from , the world or universe which it moves ; for yrj here is evidently to be taken in this large sense. The last line, also, can only be referred to a moral power, not only far above pantheism, but also that view which delights in contemplating a God of mere intelligence. It indicates a special moral providence, looking to ends and varied by events, yet at the same time general, administered by un- broken and harmonious laws, pervading all nature, silent in their operation, traversing a noiseless path (dp d'lpocjyov (3al- vcov ueXevQov) ; the universal moving power of earth ( mun - di veliiculum ) ; influencing and controlling all things, and yet in its secret springs unsearchable ( dvaronaorog etde- vat) ; ruling in the earthquake, the fire, and the tempest, yet, in itself, not the earthquake, nor the storm, but the still small voice of mind, specially and for special ends control- ling matter. So Plutarch, writing of the Divine Logos, or Reason, in SECOND TART, DOCTRINE OF PROVIDENCE. 237 the government of the world, uses almost the very woids of Euripides, if he did not rather intend a quotation : (ptvvrjg yap f O 0EIO2 AOrOS dnpooderjg eon nal dd axjjo^ov f3al - vg)v keXevOov rd i9 vrprd dyEi rcara 61ktjv. Plutarch , De Iside et Osiri. We may compare with this a passage from Seneca, Nat. Q., lib. ii., 14 : Deum ilium maximum poten- tissimumque, qui ipse vehit omnia (rnundi vehiculum ), qui ubique et omnibus prsesto est. Compare, also, a passage of one of the lost tragedies of Euripides, as it is quoted by Eusebius, Proep. Evang ., xiii., page 681 : tov avro^vfj, tov kv aWeptcp P v/j,6(p ndvrcov Qvolv e/mheZavO’ . Thou self-sprung Being that dost all infold , And in thine arms heaven’s whirling fabric hold. The idea expressed by such phrases as those on which we have been just commenting, may have been more ancient than Plato or Euripides, and may have given rise to the mythological representation of the chariot and horses of the sun. It is more likely, however, that the poetical repre- sentation may have^suggested the language here employed. We have also in the Phsedrus (246, A.) this same compar- ison, by which man, in his compound being, is likened to a chariot and horses, with their charioteer, representing re- spectively his animal and his rational nature. XXXVII. Second Grand Division of the Argument. Doctrine of a Special Providence. Mistake of Cudworth. Page 42, Line 10. Tov 6e rjyovpEvov p.ev deovg Eivai , I ur) (ppovrl^Eiv tie, k. r. X. We come now to the second grand division of the subject, and one, the treatment of which will probably be more satisfactory to the reader, pre 238 SECOND PART, DOCTRINE OF PROVIDENCE. senting, as it does, less of subtle physico-metaphysical dis- cussion, and more that is in strictest harmony with the Holy Scriptures. The author is now to prove the doctrine of a special providence against those who speculatively admitted the existence of a Deity, and yet could not believe that he concerned himself with the ordinary afFairs of human life ; especially, what seemed to them of so little consequence — human sins. Cud worth asserts that “ Plato, in his tenth book of Laws, professedly opposing the atheists, and under- taking to prove the existence of a Deity, does, notwithstand- ing, ascend no higher than to the Psyche, or Universal Mundane Soul, as the self-moving principle, and the imme- diate or proper cause of all the motion which is in the world. And this (he says) is all the God he there under- takes to prove.” This very learned man must have strange- ly overlooked the latter part of this book, upon which we are now entering, or he could not have made so incorrect an assertion. It is true, that all which his previous argu- ment has required as yet has been the existence of such a Psyche ; but he now advances not only above self-motion, or psychical power, to the second hypostasis of intelligence, or Noi^ (as it may be regarded when viewed according to the statements and divisions of the Timaeus), but also to that still higher degree which is above mind or intelligence, and which he elsewhere styles To ’A yaOov ; including, in the idea, all moral attributes — justice and severity, as well as benevolence and compassion. It is of this higher degree, or hypostasis, as we think it may be styled, that Plato, or some later Platonist, thus speaks, in that remarkable passage, contained in what is styled the second epistle to Dionysius, 312, E. : Uept rov Trdvrcjv paoiXea ixdvr > sari, nai efcetvov evetca navra * /cai enelvo clltlov diravrcvv rcov KaX&v devrepov 6e nepl rd devrepa , nal rpirov Trepl ra rptra — “ All things relate to the King of all, and on his account are all things, and he is GREEK WORDS FOR BLESSEDNESS, HAPPINESS, ETC. 239 the cause of all things beautiful ; but the second honours pertain to the second, and the third to the third.” In othei words, He is the final , or moral , as w r ell as the designings and the efficient or psychical cause of all things ( evena ov iravra ) ; for the manifestation of whose moral glory all things are created, moved, and constantly governed. Every reader must admit that the admirable arguments which follow in the remainder of the book are generally in strict accordance with the Holy Scriptures, and that Plato even reasons on this part of his subject in a more religious manner than many nominally Christian writers ; much of whose theology and science might fairly be ranked with the very atheism with which he is here contending. XXXVIII. The Greek Words for Blessedness , Happiness , Fortune , fyc. Page 42, Line 14. akrfiua psv ovtz evdatpovegs do^atg de evdcupovi^opevcu, u. t. A. The words evdacpcov, evdcu- povca , do not refer simply to a state of present pleasure or enjoyment ; for, in that sense, the poets and others were right in asserting, and the philosopher could not deny, that wicked men are often happy. E vdacpcov, in its primitive, etymological import, has a much higher sense than this ; a sense derived to it at that time, when A aipcov remained un- impaired in its significance as one of the Divine names, and had not yet been corrupted into that atheistic sense of Fortune which it subsequently acquired in the natural de- generacy of man and of language. From ev and A aipo)v, it would etymologically signify one who had the favour of Heaven ; and its purest meaning would be best expressed by our good old Saxon word blessed. It refers not simply to a man’s present state of feeling or enjoyment, but to the whole of his being and his relation to the whole ; so that 240 GREEK WORDS FOR BLESSEDNESS, HAPPINESS, ETC. one in the midst of the most acute pain, like the martyrs in the flames, might be evdacficdv ; while another, in the pres- ent enjoyment of all the pleasures of sense, might be aQXc- og : as Socrates, in the Gorgias, describes the life of the sensualist as bsivog teal alaxpog feat aOXiog, and asks if any one would dare to call such Evdaiptovag, or blessed, eav d(pd6v cjg e%u(5LV cjv beovreu — “ even if they have in the greatest abundance all that their souls may desire.” Gor- gias, 494, E. This is also the meaning of Solon in that most celebrated account which Herodotus gives of his in- terview with Croesus ; although he sometimes uses oXdtog instead of Ev6atp,G)v, out of accommodation to the language of the sensual Phrygian. Plato himself clearly gives this as the radical idea of the word, and seems evidently to allude to its etymology when he says, ov yap "ANEY TE 0E£2N prjnore rig evdatpedv eotlv — “ Without the Gods no man can be called evdaifiuv, blessed , or happy” So, also, in the Timceus , 90, D. : AeZ 61 depanevovra ro 'delov , exovra rs T ET j uaXa KEKoaprjpi- vov rov AA1MONA %vvouzov ev avrep 6ia(j)Ep6vTG)g ’EYAAI- MONA Etvai — “ He must be blessed beyond all others who cultivates the divine, and who has ever in harmony within him the indwelling God.” The juxtaposition of terms here leaves no doubt that there was intended an allusion to the radical sense and etymology of the word. There is the same allusion in the Orestes of Euripides : "O rav 6’ 6 AAIMS2N T EY dtdti t'l del Q'iTujv ; dpnel yap avrog *0 GEOS, btyeXeZv ftelcdv. When God his blessing grants, what need of friends'? A friend above supplies the soul’s desire. Euripides , Orestes , 660. These lines are quoted by Aristotle in the discussion of the question, norEpov evdaipejv dErjaErat (j)tXo)v fj prj ; Ethic. Nicomaclu, ix., 9. Even this cold and passionless writer tells us that happiness ( Evdaipovia ) is a divine thing ( delov GREEK WORDS FOR BLESSEDNESS, HAPPINESS, BV<1, 241 t i), and without the favour of Heaven cannot grow on the soil of earth: E l pev ovv nai dXXo tl detiv eotl dupTjpa avOpdonoig, evXoyov nai T7\v evdacpoviav {tedodorov elvac — “ If, therefore, there is any other thing which is the gift of the Gods, it is reasonable to suppose that happiness is Heaven’s own peculiar boon.” Ethic. Nicomach ., lib. i., 9. For similar passages, the reader is referred to his Ethic. Eudern ., lib. i., 8 ; Ethic. Nicomach ., lib. i., 12 ; and espe- cially to lib. x., 8, where, treating of evdaipovia in its other aspect, as an active exercise of the soul, instead of simply a state of well-being, he defines it to be a contemplative energy — deop^nni) evepyeia — such as we have supposed (page 225) to form the chief element in the bliss of the heavenly world. It is this which, in his view, constitutes the happiness of the Deity, and of that human state which is nearest to the divine. In proof of it, he asserts that no one of the inferior animals can ever be styled evdaipojv, be- cause the term implies a state possible only in relation to a religious and rational being, or one who could be sensible of the blessedness of the Divine favour : T<5 pev yap 'deep 7 rag 6 /3log evdaipcov * rolg d’ dvOpunoig eft ooov opoccopa rt rrjg Totavrrjg evepyetag vTrapx^ * rwr <5’ aXkiov feuam ovdev evdaipovel , eireidi) ovdapov aocvcovel fteupLag * nai gj aaXkov VTxapXEL to 'deojpelv, nai evdatpovelv . Wherefore, as he says in what follows, every such a one is fteoftXeo- rarog, or most beloved of Heaven. It will be seen how visibly, in all these extracts, can be traced the radical, ety- mological idea of the term, as it was exhibited in the most primitive Greek, and how very similar it is to the corre- sponding one presented in the Bible, although the former may not be taken in so elevated a sense, and perhaps nev- er comes up to the full etymological import which may fairly be supposed to be contained in its component parts. The Scriptures speak of it as the blessedness of that rnan who enjoys the Divine favour : Blessed is the man (or peo - X 242 GREEK WORDS FOR BLESSEDNESS, HAPPINESS, ETC. pie) whose God is the Lord ; blessed are they who dwell in thy house ; who remain in the secret place of the Most High ; who abide under the shadow of the Almighty. Thy favour is life, and thy loving kindness is better than life . Ava6ai[io)v and dvodaifiovia as clearly express the oppo- site view, namely, not merely present misery, but the state of one visited by the displeasure of Heaven. It is thus re- peatedly used by CEdipus, in the Phcenissae of Euripides, when lamenting his wretched condition as one pursued from his earliest years by the wrath of the Gods, on account of his own sins and his father’s impious disobedience to the oracle : ’APA2 napaTiabkv Aatov nal natal dovg. ov yap , . . . uvev ftetiv rov, ravr’ kfiTJxavTjad/Ltrjv. etev • Tt dpdao) drjO ’ 6 AY2AAIMS2N ky6. Phoenissce , 1626 . In its later applications, evdaiiiovia loses much of its old religious sense, and degenerates into a synonyme of svrv- %ia, or good fortune, losing almost entirely its etymological reference to the favour of an overruling divinity. In this it shares the corruption of its principal component part, dal- For a most striking illustration, however, of the rad- ical primitive difference between evdalficov and evrvxrjg, Ave may refer to Euripides, Medea, 1225 : Qvijtu)V yap ovdelg karlv ’EYAAIM12N to plan , to invent , dprjxavEC °, to & e without plans , to be at a loss ; (dovXopat, to be willing , ddovXeo), to be unwilling , or refuse — although this word has oftener, perhaps, the sense of inconsiderateness , or want of refection , as though it were the privative of (3ovXevg) — rpopiopat, to tremble , arpopio), or drpepeG), to be undisturbed ; (pEtdopat, to spare , acpEidEG), to be lavish , or prodigal. Compare, also, x a pi^°l iai i piOTEG) — ipEvdopat, d'lpEvdEO, d'lpEvorec*) — dvvapai, ddvva teg) — oedopac, daedso), &c. It may be observed, that in most of these cases the form with a privative is not the direct negative either of the ac- tive or the middle ; that is, is not simply the denial of a re- flex action , but expresses rather a negative state of mind. As, for example, arcEiOEiv , besides being wholly different from pi] tteIOelv, is not even equivalent to prj nEiOeoOat , to 264 GREAT THINGS CANNOT EXIST WITHOUT SMALL, which it seems to have the nearest alliance, but expresses rather that positive condition of the soul from which all acts of disobedience do proceed. So, also, in the passage from the text, apEXelv is not the same as j urj emiieXelodat , but rather expresses that sluggish, indifferent, careless disposi- tion, which is so utterly opposed to all right views of the Divine nature. Mr) empeXeZoOaL may or may not involve criminality, as may be seen from the manner in which it is used page 50, lines 8, 10. It may result from want of pow- er, or a variety of other justifying reasons. ’ApeXeZv al- ways implies fault, and is always to be taken in an unfa- vourable sense. So, also, pi) ttzlOegOcu, or pi) tuotevelv , may be consistent with freedom from all blame, according to the presence or absence of other circumstances ; but. cliteiOeIv must always be associated with condemnation, as implying an unbelieving and guilty condition of the soul. This is the force of the word as used by our Saviour, John, iii., 36 : 6 6s clttelOCjv ovx oxpErat farjv — The unbelieving shall never see life , but the wrath of God abideth on him . For these reasons, perhaps, these verbs fell into an in- transitive sense, leaving the denial of the action of the pos- itive form to be expressed by the negative particles. And perhaps, «also, because they differ somewhat from the mere negation of the reflex action of the middle, they retain, for distinction’s sake, the active form ; although, at first view, such privative words would seem, of all others, the most foreign to the ordinary use of that voice. XL VII. Great Things cannot Exist without Small. Application of the Maxim to the Doctrine of a Special Providence , Edu- cation , and to Politics. Page 55, Line 5. Ov pi)v ovde Kvdepvrjratg, ovde orpa- rrjyolg ovd 9 av noXtritcoZg X^P 1 ^ optHptiv pevaXa. ov6e GREAT THINGS CANNOT EXIST WITHOUT SMALL. 265 yap avev ojurcptiv rovg p,eydXovg (paoiv ol XiOoXoyoi XiOovg ev fceloOac — “ Neither to pilots, nor to commanders, nor to political men, can great things exist without small things ; for, as the stone-masons say, neither do large stones lie well together in a structure without the small.” This max- im is capable of the widest range. It is not only applica- ble to stone-masons, and politicians, and to the sublime ar- gument of Plato here in favour of a special providence, but is also of the highest importance in respect to education, and well worthy the attention of all teachers of youth. For want of a patient and laborious care in respect to what may seem the more minute elements of science, a structure is often erected without cohesion or symmetry, and destined, through the looseness of its parts, to fall to pieces almost as soon as completed. As Plato applies the maxim here to politicians, so, also, Aristotle, in his Politico, lib. ii., 2, institutes a similar com- parison in respect to government, and shows that it is es- sential to the very constitution of a sound and healthy state that its individual elements should be small things mingled with great, in such a way as to give coherence and sym- pathy to the whole. In pursuance of this same idea, he condemns those theorists who, even in his day, advocated the impracticable doctrine of perfect equality, and charges them with being the greatest enemies to that very idea of unity which they would be thought so zealously to main- tain. The levelling dogma, he admits, is plausible, and ap- parently most philanthropic — evirpoaconog ical (pcXavOpcjirog av elvai So^etev — but, in the end, instead of being produc- tive of the greatest happiness of the greatest number, it is fraught with the seeds of all evil both to individuals and to the state. As unity implies plurality and variety, so, he de- clares, there can be no true unity in sameness. There can be no binding sympathy except in a community of higher and lower, lesser and greater interests. As well might one Z 266 GREAT THINGS CANNOT EXIST WITHOUT SMALL. attempt to construct a wall with round, smooth pebbles, all of the same size and fashion, or produce harmony from strings all of the same length and tension ; which, as he justly remarks, might furnish an insipid homophony, but never a true symphony : coanep nav el ng rrjv ovpupGiviav TroLrjoeiev dfjiO(po)vcav, rj rov pvOpov (3aoiv plav, Politica , ii., 2. There is a singular passage in the Ajax of Sophocles, in which we think there is had in view this same comparison of great and little stones, although the word is not expressly mentioned in the Greek. He also applies it, in the same manner, to those wild and disorganizing doctriftes of gov- ernment, which would destroy all confidence and all mutual support, by exciting an unholy jealousy between the rich and the poor. The passage is interesting, if for no other purpose, to show how precisely the same, in temper and in argument, have been the demagogues of all ages : IIpo^ yap rov exovO’ 6 (j)6ovoc £pnet. Kalroi cpuipoi peyahuv x^P^ C(j>a?iep6v nvpyov pvpa nehovTai. pera yap peyd^cjv /3aidg apicr 9 dv , nal psyag opOoW’ vtzo pLKporipov. ’A/U/ ov dvvarov rovg avorjTovg tovtcov yv6pag TTpodidaoKELv. — Ajax , 151. Which we would thus attempt to render, by way of improve- ment on Potter’s version, in which, we think, he has over- looked the implied simile, and thus failed to bring out its principal beauty : Thus envy secretly assails the rich. And yet small stones, unmingled with the great, Build up a dangerous tower — a frail defence* The high and low in mutual sympathy Sustain each other ; yet this truth is one Which fools can never learn. No one, we think, can fail to admire the still higher and yet most just application which Plato makes of this striking GENTLENESS OF PLATO S MODE OF ARGUMENT. 267 comparison to the government of the Divine Architect, and to the doctrine of a special providence. XL VIII. Gentleness of Plato's Mode of Argument , and its Peculiat Adaptation to the Minds of the Young. Page 57, Line 2. Tgj ye pca^eadat rolg Xoyoig, k. t. A. The propriety of this word will best appear in a paraphrase of the spirit of the whole passage. It suggests some such train of thought as this : “We have now addressed his rea- son, and by a summary yet conclusive syllogism, forcibly, as it were, compelled him to admit the incorrectness of his positions. Still, although his reason is silenced, his feel- ings or imagination may yet refuse to surrender, and may revolt at the idea that the Deity is concerned in all the ap- parently trivial and minute operations of the universe. There seems, therefore, in addition, to be need of some soothing charms (eTTudtiv), some gentle persuasions, to overcome those prejudices or distastes which will not yield to reason.” ’E nadetv (encod?]), with its derivatives, is a favourite word with Plato. What a sublime beauty does it possess in the Phsedon, where Socrates, after having gone through the strongest and most recondite arguments that reason could array for a future life, makes, as his ground of con- fidence, the cheering hope which the belief produces in the soul, and those sweet persuasions of a moral kind, which surpass in power all the deductions of the intellect ; “ for noble is the prize (he says), and great the hope” — rca- Adv yap to aOXov uai rj eXnlg peydkrj. And then, after having gone through the mythical representations of the unseen world, he tells us that the soul must ever chant these to itself as some soothing incantation ( roiavra %pr\ 268 PHYSICAL EVENTS CONTROLLED BY SPIRITUAL AGENTS. coonep enadeiv eavrd), Phced ., 114, D.), and like the dying swan, to which, in another part of this dialogue, he com- pares himself, sing this song of immortality more sweetly and more clearly the nearer it approaches that period which is to test the great question forever. Nothing can be more admirable than the tender care which, throughout this discussion, the Athenian is made to exercise towards his supposed youthful disputant. The philosopher knew that very often little direct influence of a moral kind was produced by means of dialectical argu- ment, however excellent it might be as preparatory to the application of other remedies. He knew that, even where it silenced, it not unfrequently hardened the vanquished disputant to a more tenacious hold upon former prejudices. He therefore, in what succeeds, endeavours to make him feel that this is no matter of mere speculation, like any mere scientific theorem, but that he has a deep personal interest in the great arrangements of Providence, and to impress him with the fact, that as a part (although a very small one) of an immense whole, the importance and dignity of his own position, instead of being diminished, is magnified by this very circumstance. See remarks, notes 1 1 and 12, page 1 1 ; also, explanation of the word dvoxepaiveiv, note 3, page 8. XLIX. The Machinery of Physical Events controlled by Invisible Spiritual Agencies . The Doctrine of Plato and of the Bible . Page 57, Line 12. V A pxovreg tt poorer ay pevoi. The form and gender of the word ap%ovreg will not permit us to regard it as referring to any inanimate influences. It can only mean beings of a higher order than man, to whom the lower parts of the universal administration were thought PHYSICAL EVENTS CONTROLLED BY SPIRITUAL AGENTS. 269 to be committed. This doctrine, somewhat modified, we believe to be taught in the Holy Scriptures, without suppo- sing that the Jewish writers, any more than Plato, did not hrmly hold to that regular and orderly succession of events and phenomena which we style the laws of nature. They manifestly believed in a connexion of cause and effect, ex- tending in a chain from the throne of God to the minutest operations of the visible world and yet all along down this golden chain of celestial influences, and in all its vibra- tions throughout its immense extent, they constantly recog- nised the control and guidance of supernatural or angelic beings. Besides revealing the doctrine, the Scriptures sometimes, as matters of historical fact, draw aside the veil from the invisible world, and lay open to us this constant supernatu- ral agency ; as in the account of the angel who descended * We find this idea in Hosea, ii., 23, which is commonly thus ren- dered : And it shall come to pass in that day , I will hear , saith the Lord , I will hear the heavens ; and the heavens shall hear the earth, and the earth shall hear the corn, and the wine, and the oil ; and they shall hear Jezreel. The word HJjP, here used, means, in its primary sense, to sing. Hence, secondly, to pronounce with a measured and solemn voice ; thirdly, to respond ; fourthly, to hear ; having, however, no ref- erence to the auricular sensation, which is expressed by another word. It resembles the Greek pehno, pehnopaL, or, rather, apetGo- pai, and conveys the idea of responsive or choral singing. Hence the passage would be more literally, and at the same time more ex- pressively, rendered thus : And it shall come to pass in that day, 1 will sing , saith the Lord, I will sing to the heavens ; and the heavens shall sing (or respond) to the earth ; and the earth shall respond to the corn, and the wine, and the oil ; and they shall respond to Jezreel. There seems here a reference to that doctrine of the choral harmony of nature, with which the ancient mind was so filled ; as though the touching a chord in heaven, when the great Coryphaeus or leader of the universal orchestra gives the starting tone, sounds and vibrates down through all the compass of the notes, until it makes its closing cadence in the end designed to be accomplished. Z 2 270 PHYSICAL EVENTS CONTROLLED BY SPIRITUAL AGENTS. into the pool of Bethesda, or of the destroying angel that appeared with a drawn sword standing over the devoted city of Jerusalem, 2d Samuel, xxiv., 16, 17. In this latter instance, there is no intimation that it differed in any way from the ordinary method by which God sends pestilence upon the earth, except that here the curtain is withdrawn and the supernatural machinery disclosed. No doubt, sec- ond causes were here also at work, and the philosopher of that day, had there been any such to investigate the ante- cedents and consequents connected with the event, might have bid the Jew Take heart and banish fear ; yet still, all this would not change the fact, so clearly re vealed, that behind them all, however far they may have extended beyond the utmost bounds of scientific research, there stood the spiritual power of God, and his delegated minister, directing them, without any violation of their vis- ible order, to the production of the decreed result. Let science cease her babble. We all know, the most igno- rant as well as the most learned, that second causes are employed in these visitations. The writers of the Bible were no more ignorant of this, as a general principle, than our most scientific savans, although they may have known less of the steps of the process in its minute details. Even here we surpass them only in having traced a few more links in a chain, in which what is yet unknown sinks all differences of the known into insignificance. These links, in the series of natural sequences, may reach back to any extent short of the infinite, and yet leave on the other shore room enough for the supernatural , in perfect consistency with them. We have, therefore, no reason at all for infer- ring that the Scriptures meant to represent this as a mirac- ulous intervention. In every case of pestilence, they would have us believe that the destroying angel is abroad in the air, but. in this one, for special reasons, the eye of man was PHYSICAL EVENTS CONTROLLED BY SPIRITUAL AGENTS. 271 permitted to behold him.* He maketh his angels winds , his ministers a fiery flame, as the inspired Apostle renders it, Heb., i., 17 ; all not, as it would be explained by the ra- tionalizing interpreter, he maketh the winds his messengers , and the flaming fire his servants. The angels of the Lord are ever encamped round about the righteous, although we have but one example in the Bible of the glorious vision being revealed to mortal eyes. See 2 Kings, vi., 17. The great objection to this view, as it would present itself to some minds, would spring from the prejudice to which Plato alludes in the Epinomis, 982, D., E., and on which we have remarked, pages 226, 227. Men are so much inclined to associate undeviating regularity and con- stancy in physical motions with a nature implying the ab- sence of a special will and reason ; as though an animated personal agency must necessarily be sometimes freaky and capricious in its operations as evidences of the exercise of a personal volition. One answer to such an objection is furnished at once by maintaining that all such intermediate spiritual powers are under the constant control of the Su- preme Will and Reason, producing the regularity of natural sequence, not as though it needed such sequences at all as indispensable helps to itself, but for our sakes , that by means of them, as signs, we might be able to exercise faith in the general constancy of the Divine operations, and regulate our own conduct in accordance with it. When, however, this feeling becomes practical atheism, prevailing to any great extent among mankind, we have reason to believe that God* will come forth, as Plato says in the Politicus, from his re- tired place of observation, break up the long repose of nal- * There are also in the Bible intimations that evil supernatural agents, under the dominion of the Prince of the Powers of the Air, are sometimes permitted to exercise a physical influence in the af- fairs of our globe, and thus to afflict men with disease both of mind and body. See Luke, xiii., 16 ; Job, i., 12 ; ii., 6, 7. 272 THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIH1L0 NIHIL. ural laws, and again astonish the world, as in the early times, by displays of super - natural power. Nemesius, in his treatise on the Nature of Man, alluding to Plato’s doctrine of providence, describes it as recogni- sing three divisions. The first province is assigned directly, or without media, to the Deity himself, or, as he styles him, the first God. This has respect to the world of ideas, and the general care of the universe as a whole — n porjyovpEVcog pev t(ov Idetiv eireira 6e % ypnavrog rov uaOoXov uoapov. The second department is given in charge of the second or inferior divinities, and has relation to those things which are said to be under the law of generation and corruption — 7rdvTG)v tgjv £V yEvioci ual (pOopa — or, in other words, or- dinary physical events. The third relates to the conduct of life, and to the distribution of what he styles organic good and evil. Nemesius , Be Nat. Horn ., p. 345. We know not in what part of Plato’s dialogues authority can be found for this precise division, as Nemesius states it, al- though for the second some warrant may be discovered in the passage which has furnished the ground of this excur- sus. For farther information on the ancient views in re- spect to a special providence, we may consult Cicero , Be Leg., ii., 7 ; Plutarch., Be Fato, 572, E. ; Eusebius, Prczp Evang ., 630. L. The Ancient Maxim, Be Nihilo Nihil. Page 58, Line 2. (bg ysveoig evena ekeivov ylyvErai rrdaa onog, k. r. X . — “ That all generation, or every gener- ation, takes place for this purpose, and in such a way,” &c. This argument would be better accommodated to mod- ern ideas, and, at the same time, lose none of its force or intended meaning in this place, by rendering y EVEOig ere THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIHILO NIHIL. 273 # ation. According to the view we have taken of this word, page 187, it would always signify the bringing into being of what did not exist before, so far as the law or idea was concerned ; as when from a different disposition of the same matter an entirely new substance is produced — nitric acid, for example, from what before was atmospheric air. Here there is the creation of a new being , although not of any new matter. It would not, however, be quite fair to regard it, in this way, as synonymous with our phrase, cre- ation out of nothing. The word yevsoig, it is true, does generally imply, in Greek writers, a production in some way out of something pre-existent ; and yet this something is not necessarily, or e vi terminorum , to be regarded as pre- existent matter. Many held to a metaphysical phantom which they styled hyle (yXrj), and which the more spiritual philosophers may have adopted to save their favourite max- im, de nihilo nihil. From some such idea as this the Sep- tuagint gave the name Teveoig to that book which treats of the generations of the heavens and the earth ; and in this they had some countenance from the Hebrew word m'lbin- Gen., ii. , 4. Thus, also, they render the Hebrew substan- tive verb VP, in the account of the origin of light (Gen., i., 3), not eoTG) (j)d)g, but yevrjOrjTG) tyug. In the same way, Psalm xc., 2 — npo rov oprj yev7\0r\vai — although, in this case, it is no more than a faithful rendering of the Hebrew nb\ a word of precisely similar import, implying successive generation from something pre-existent — nV tDVH bnni ^binm — before the mountains were generated , and the earth was born or brought forth. In this way do the Scriptures, both Greek and Hebrew, speak of the formation of the present earth , or of what may be styled the Mosaic creation. In regard, however, to that originating act which took place in the beginning, mentioned Gen., i., 1, a different language is employed in many parts of the Bible. It is 274 THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIIllLO NIHIL. + represented as proceeding from a word or fiat — a calling of something from a state of non-existence both in respect to matter and form — as Romans, iv., 17 : uaXovvrog ra pi) ovra cog ovra ; where there seems to be a reference to Isa- iah, xlviii., 14.— HIT npjP 'JK *np — My hand hath founded the earth , and my right hand hath spanned the heav- ens ; when I called to them they stood up. So, also, Isaiah, xli., 4 — nrnn *Op — who called the generations from the beginning . To such passages we may trace the similar language of Philo, De Create 728 : ra pi) ovra enaXeaev elg to elvai. Notwithstanding the clear declarations of the Bible, the Greek ideas of origination, connected with the words yeveoig and eyevero , maintained their ground for some time, and continued to affect the expressions, if not the intended meaning, of some of the earliest fathers. Even the Jewdsh Philo, at times, uses language which seems to imply the eternity of matter, if not of the organized world. As when he gives us this account of what he styles the philosophy of Moses, in his treatise De Mundi Opificio , page 2, B. : “Moses, who had attained the highest summit of philosophy, knew that it was most necessary {avaytzaibra- rov ) that in existing things ( [kv rotg ovoi) there should be, on the one hand, the efficient ( dpaorrjpiov ), namely, the universal mind, most pure and unmixed with anything else, and, on the other hand, something inert, passive, or passible, destitute of soul and motion (a'tpvxov real dnivrprov ), which when moved, endowed with form, and animated by the mind aforesaid, should be converted into this most perfect work, the world.” Although in this very argument he is dispu- ting against the eternity of the world, yet he seems to re- gard the ultimate element of matter as one of the two ne- cessary existences, almost as much so as mind itself ; and his language greatly resembles that in which Cicero de- scribes the doctrine of one of the ancient schools : De nat- ura autem ita dicebant, ut earn dividerent in res duas : ut THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIHILO NIHIL. 275 altera esset -effipiens, altera autem quasi huic se praebens, eaque efliceretur aliquid. In eo, quod efficeret, vim esse censebant : in eo autem, quod efliceretur, materiam quam- dam : in utroque tamen utrumque. Neque enim materiam ipsam cohaerere potuisse, si nulla vi contineretur, neque VIM SINE AL1QUA MATERIA. Cic., Acad. Post ., 6. In other places, however, he contends clearly and strongly that even the hyle , or unformed principle of matter itself, had been created in the beginning by the direct act of God. In general, the Christian fathers, with some wavering arising from the systems of philosophy in which they had been first instructed, assert pretty clearly an absolute cre- ation from a state in which there was no pre-existent mat- ter (which we prefer to the expression, out of nothing) ; al- though, in stating the Scriptural doctrine, they often use lan- guage which was more congenial with the opposite system. The words yeveaig and yevr]r6v were employed for cre- ation, and dyevTjrov was used as synonymous with anna- tov. In consequence, however, of discussions growing out of the Nicene controversy, and the doctrine of the eternal generation of The Son, they made a distinction between yevrjrog and yevvyrog, and dyevryTog and dyevvrjrog , which is far from being so evident in classical Greek as in the Pa- tristic writings. Christ, they said, was yevvrjrog , but not yevrjrog ; or, in other words, he was ayevrjrog and annorog , but not dyevvrjrog. So, also, the first progenitor of any or- ganized species was dyevvrjrog , although nothing was dye- vrjrog which was beneath the Divine hypostases. Vide Cyril. Alexand ., Be Sancta Trinit., 8, page 37. The Greek philosophers have been, almost all of them,- charged with teaching the eternity of matter, and of having been universally agreed in the tenet, that nothing could be created or generated out of nothing, or, as it is expressed by Lucretius, De nihilo nihil, in nihilum nil posse reverti. 276 THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIHILO NIHIL. No doubt this was the doctrine of many, if not%iost of them, even in the modern acceptation of the terms ; that is, they believed in no creation or generation except from pre-exist- ent matter with all the properties of matter as it now exists ; or, in other words, the visible material universe was eter- nal, whatever changes or modifications it might in the lapse of ages have undergone. It was thus held by the Ionic school in all its branches, by some of the Italian, and by all who were atheistically inclined. It was also maintain- ed, however inconsistently, by some who were undoubted theists, as by Plutarch, and a few others who have been styled Platonists. We cannot, however, charge any of them with these consequences simply from the language of the maxim, as it x.iay be taken in different senses; in some of which it is not only consistent with the purest theism, but absolutely essential to its proper explanation and defence. It is by no means clear that the eternity of matter was ever held by Plato ; and, although some things in the Timaeus may look that way when only partially considered, yet are they all capable of a consistent interpretation on a different hypoth- esis. His doctrine of the inherent evil of matter does not at all, by any necessity, involve its eternity. It was not connected with any necessary existence of matter, but with certain necessary properties which it must possess if cre- ated — without which it could not be matter, and without which God could not cause it to exist. Vide remarks on the Platonic doctrine of avdyrcrj, pages 217, 218. In The Laws, as w T e have seen, his evil principle is spiritual, and has, therefore, nothing to do with the dogma against which we are defending him. Even if he had held it, it would not have been a heresy fatal to his claim to be regarded as a pure theist, although an inconsistent one ; and the cir- cumstances in which he was placed would have presented the same palliation as we have offered for his doctrine of THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIHILO NIHIL. 277 evil. But, indeed, we know of no system of philosophy to which the tenet in question, in this gross form, would have been more foreign. To have allowed any necessary self- existence to matter would have been directly in the face of some of his most favourite notions, and especially opposed to that grand division in the Timreus, in which, under the general name to oparov, it is expressly excluded from the class of the tgjv ovrcog ovtgjv , and assigned to that of the yiyvoyevcov icat ovSettote ovrwg ovtcov. Vide page 172, and the remarks on the distinction between the verbs dpi and ytyvopac. Nothing can be more express than the dec- laration that matter — not as organized, but in the most ex- treme or lowest state in which it can be matter, or, as he defines it in the most general terms, the tangible, the visi- ble, the extended — belongs to the class of generated, in dis- tinction from eternal existences : oparog yap dirrog re teal otipa yiyvopevog teal ysvrjrog ecpdvrj. Tim., 28. And when we connect this with another proposition in the same passage — rrav 6e av to yiyvopevov in 9 alriov nvog el; avdyterjg yiyveoQai — “ that everything which is yiyvopevov must have been produced by some cause” — it seems impos- sible any longer to maintain that Plato regarded matter in any state as belonging to the world of necessary entities ; and if not necessary , then not eternal in its nature ; for he ever uses the two terms as mutually implying one another. It would also be in opposition to that high and even hyper- spirituality which runs through all his writings, and which would warrant us in giving to them collectively, as their compendious title, “ The SOUL , its eternal nature ; its infi- nite value ; its superior antiquity to matter ; the immense pre- eminence of incorporeal when compared with corporeal sub- stances, and the utter worthlessness of the whole material uni - verse in itself, or when not viewed as subservient to the higher wants of the spirit .” It is true that, in conformity with this ancient maxim, A A 278 THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIHILO NIHIL. De nihilo nihil — cue ov dvvarai ovdsv en rov pif ovrog ye - veodcu — which, as it stands in the Greek, unmarred by any attempt to transfer it to a more imperfect language, is one of the clearest axioms of reason — he held to an elementary principle, or apxv, more ancient than matter, even in its lowest organized state, and which he and others styled hyle (yXrj). Although he sometimes seems to use this term in the sense of material or source, yet he could not have mean* by it matter itself as something solid, extended, or resisting, since he expressly denies to it any of these properties, or, indeed, any connexion in itself with the sensible world ; regarding it, in fact, as belonging to the vorjrd , rather than, in any sense, to the aloOrjrd. No sublimation or refine- ment of the conception of resisting substance, even when carried to its most aethereal limits — not even the nebular star dust* or rudimentary fluid of the universe, which some modern writers find so convenient an aid in the construc- tion of planetary systems — made the least approach to it ; for it was not a mere difference of degree, but a metaphys- ical entity altogether distinct. It is very difficult to under- stand precisely what idea Plato and other Greek philoso- phers attached to this elementary hyle , without form, exten- * This is a favourite term with those scientific men who are ever talking about the progression of the universe from the lower to the higher, from the imperfect to the more perfect, from the unorgani- zed to the organized, and, as they ought to say if they would consist- ently follow out their theory, from matter to mind, and, finally, to a God. But, on another hypothesis of occasional retrogradations (which no one who considers the vast extent of the universe can deny to be possible, probable, and in perfect consistency with some unfathomable designs of its Eternal Author), the peculiar celestial appearances indicated by this phrase may be, in fact, the floating remains of worlds going out, and in the last stages of their approach to inanity. We are too much in the condition of the fly on the Pyr- amids, to determine with any satisfaction, unless we resort to rea- sons drawn from revelation, which theory is correct, or whether we are physically nearer our descending or ascending node. THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIHILO NIHIL. 279 sion, parts, or divisibility. Some ap%h or principle seems to have been in his mind as the origin of matter, which was not matter ; and yet something separate from the Deity, and existing with him before the formation of the outward material universe.* We are confident, for the reasons as- signed, that he did not hold to its necessary eternity, but it is not easy to determine whether he regarded it as an em- anation, a generation, or a creation, in the more modern sense of the word. Whether it was merely space regarded as an apx?h or first principle, like the aneipov , or infinite of Anaximander ; or something similar to the unextended points in the modern theory of Boscovitch ; whether it was the manifestation of the Divine power in space, so that vis- ible outward matter would be only those impressions upon soul, of resistance, figure, &c., which are the result of the action of the Divine immaterial principle — a theory which, although ridiculed as Berkleian and absurd, gives us all the results or properties of matter, which is matter enough for all substantial purposes, while yet it leaves spirit, in reality, the only ovoid , or essence in the universe — or whatever else we may suppose, it is certain that Plato did not teach the necessary self-existence of matter according to the common idea, that is, as a substance composed of solid, ex- tended parts or particles, whether regarded as existing in an organized or a chaotic state. The axiom De nihilo nihil , or others similar to it, may be found in his writings and those of Aristotle. They both regarded it as a self-evident truth ; and the latter, in the first book of his Physics, c. 4, asserts that it was the common * In the passage of the Timaeus which we have cited page 123, he uses language which seems to describe it as the matter or material from which matter was formed, yet still without any of its sensible properties. He also styles it there the mother of the sensible world, as though it were the passive or negative principle, while God was the father, or positive power, which produced its manifestations in time and space. 280 THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIHILO NIHIL. opinion of all the ancient naturalists, that nothing could come tnto being from that which was not — uolvt) 6o^a rchv cj)Vot- utiv, chq ov rirNOMENOY ovdevdq etc rov grj ,7 0NT02. This is capable, it is true, of being taken in the atheistic or materializing sense by those who lay no emphasis on the contrast between the two substantive verbs, or who re- gard the latter, in this expression, as significant of the ma- terial, or of the terminus a quo . If, however, we keep in mind the radical distinction between elgc and yly voficu, as explained page 171, and which is generally maintained by Plato in all important propositions, we shall find this sen- tence divested at once of all objectionable features, and presented, as it really is, as one of the clearest dictates of reason. This language may be, and has been, used by the atheist ; but it is capable of being employed with far more power against him. Aristotle gives us the key to this high er sense in another place, where he says, with his usual conciseness, chore eorai nplv yeveodcu — that essential or necessary being must be before generation ; or, in other words, that there must be a being before a becoming. Vide Arista Phys . Ausc ., i., 9. The position, thus understood, is that which forms the very sold of Plato’s philosophy, namely, the superior rank and antiquity of incorporeal sub- stance in respect to all derived or generated things. It is the very position which he so strongly maintains in this tenth book of The Laws, to wit, “ that soul (in its largest sense, and including the Divine Soul, as the source from whence all other spirits proceed, and in which they may be said to pre-exist) must, of necessity, have existed eter- nally, or that mind is necessarily older than matter.” In- stead of being favourable to atheism, it is, when thus held, the grand conservative principle which ever stands in di- rect opposition to it. The English fails properly to express the axiom, in this sense, from the want of two words ex- actly corresponding to elfii and yiyvopai ; and when care- THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIHILO NIHIL. 281 lessly rendered it seems to favour the eternal existence of matter. The Latin has the same defect ; and hence the atheistic perversion by Lucretius to a purpose so different from that intended by Plato and the Grecian theists. This aiises from referring the term ovrog , as well as yiyvopevov, to generated and phenomenal being, to which, when used in this higher sense, and especially when placed in such direct antithesis, it has no application ; and we are thus led into the mistake that all the ancient philosophers taught that matter could only proceed from pre-existent matter. The idea conveyed by the proposition, ovdev etc rov pr) ovrog yeveoOai , or, if the positive form is preferred, 7 ravra etc rov ovrog yeveoOac, may be shown to be very similar to that of the Apostle, Hebrews, xi., 3 : By faith we understand that the worlds were made by the Word of God , so that the things that are seen were not made ( yeyovevat ) from things ichich do appear , etc (paivopevov. There is another reading given by Griesbach, namely, etc prj < paivopevw ; on what authority, however, we know not. This would change the sentence to the positive form, and bring it nearer to the Greek maxim when taken in the higher sense to which we have alluded, but would not essentially vary its meaning. It would then be rendered, By faith we understand that the worlds were formed , so that the things which are seen were made from things which are not seen ; or, in other words, that the visible or phenomenal was made from the invisible . A slight attention will show a resemblance to the Greek maxim which does not at first, sight appear, and that the language of the Apostle is in several respects similar to the Platonic. Besides the distinctions so frequently conveyed by ovra and yiyvopeva , the same ideas are variously expressed in Plato by the terms opara or (patvopeva (the visible, or phe- nomenal), used in place of yiyvopeva ; and aopara, aetdrj, or pi) (patvopeva , used as synonymous with rd ovra. By these and kindred terms he ever opposes the visible to the A a 2 282 THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIHILO NIHIL. invisible, the phenomenal to the essential, the ever- chan- ging objects of sense (t« aloOrjra) to the vorjra, or those necessary, eternal things which are the objects of the in- tellect alone. It is not supposed that Paul had any direct reference to Plato or to Platonic language ; but we cannot doubt that he uses these words in a similar philosophical sense, especially when we compare the many coincidences of expression, and remember that, although originally deri- ved from Plato, these terms, in the Apostle’s time, had be- come a part of the current scholastic phraseology, with which he must have been familiar. So, also, the words rd pi) fiXsnopEva ( the unseen things ), which we find He- brews, xi., 1, and which are equivalent to pi) f^aivopEva in the third verse, are elsewhere used by the Apostle to ex- press the same class of substances which are so frequently styled by Plato, rd ovra , ra opara , ra aetdrj , rd del Kara ravrd nai cooavroyg Exovra. Compare 2d Coruithians , iv., 18 : i urj OKonovvrcov rjptiv rd pXEnopEva aXXa rd pi) /3Ae- t Togeva * rd yap fiXenopEva upoonaipa , rd ds j pi) PXetto- psva alcbvta — while ice aim not at the things which are seen , hut at the things which are unseen ; for the things which are seen are temporal (belong to time ) ; the things which are un- seen are eternal . The striking resemblance which this bears to some passages in the Phaedon cannot be mistaken : Q&pev ovv 6i) 6vo Eidrj, rd pen oparov , rb be aEideg * nai to pev deibeg del Kara rd avrd exov , rb 6e oparov u 7 ) 6 e - nors Kara ravrd — “ Let us lay down two classes of being, the seen and the unseen : the unseen, eternal in their rela- tions ; the seen, never the same, but ever changing.” Phw- don, 79, A. The terms are nearly, if not quite, synony. mous. IT pooKatpa is that which exists in time, temporal, or, rather, temporary — liable to change — the opposite of del Kara rd avrd exovra. On the other hand, alcjvia is that which is eternal, not simply in duration, but in its very na- ture, as not belonging to time — fixed, unchangeable, and ne- THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIHILO NIHIL. 283 cessary — del nard ravrd exovra. In these passages, nei- ther Paul nor Plato mean by the unseen things a mere ne- gation of sense, namely, that which is simply concealed from view as a present fact, or not seen because belonging to a future untried state of existence ; but rather those things that are in their very nature invisible , that is, which belong not to the sensible w r orld — either the present or any one to come — the vorjrd as distinguished from the aioQrjrd , or the objects of faith and reason as distinguished from the objects of sense. See, also, Rom., i., 20. We find the doctrine of the hyle in the apocryphal book entitled The Wisdom of Solomon, ch. xi., 18 : ual urtoaoa rov fcoofiov d[iop(j)OV vXrjg — “ having built the earth out of the unformed, or, rather, formless hyle.” Compare, also, the Septuagint. version of Genesis, i., 2 : rj 6e y r\ fjv aopa- rog nal duaraonevaorog. The word aoparog here could only have been used in reference to the Greek doctrine, which represented the hyle not only as invisible, but as incapable of being seen ; in fact, as not belonging at all to the sensible world, even if it could not be ranked among the vorjrd. It may be doubted whether we ever ought, in translating the more strict philosophers, to render vXrj by our term matter, unless we can conceive of it as an essence abstracted from qualities, figure, and extension. That God may have created such an essence we have no right to deny, merely because our minds can form no conception of it ; and if it may exist as the originally created ground of all subsequently generated or created material things when manifested in time and space and clothed with qualities by that Eternal Spirit, which, we are told in Genesis, hovered over the chaotic deep, then may the doctrine of Plato and of the more spiritual writers of the ancient world be in ac- cordance with the philosophy of Paul, Hebrews, xi., 3. Our only safety here is in clinging to the Bible, and to the fair interpretation of Genesis, i., 1. Human reason left 284 THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIHILO NIHIL. to itself, finds tremendous difficulties in both views ; and when she rejects the aid of revelation, must shrink from taking a decided position on either. The belief that mat- ter in any form, as an independent principle, is eternal, or that anything is such apart from God, carries us to atheism, although it may be maintained by an honest yet inconsist- ent theist. On the other hand, the doctrine that God once existed alone , or that there was a time when God was all , seems to draw after it the strange consequences that he never could have ceased to be all , or have become less than all , and that therefore creation is but an extension of his being ; or, in other words, we are in danger of a pantheism seemingly more philosophical, yet less favourable to piety than the inconsistent theism which we have condemned. Reason reels and staggers here like a drunken man, and if she will walk alone, finds a dark abyss on each side of her narrow path, into which she is perpetually in danger of stumbling. There may possibly be a way between these two conclusions, but her eyes are too dim to discover it. The Scriptures most solemnly declare that God did call into being things that were not , and yet denies the conse- quence which reason, if she will trust herself alone, can hardly avoid deducing from it. We must, therefore, on this subject, as on the doctrine of evil, keep close to reve- lation, ready at a moment’s warning, and without a mur- mur, to give up our most darling philosophy, if it comes at all in collision with any truth which a sound and unforced interpretation would elicit. Neither should we be afraid for our Protestantism, even if we are reluctant to adopt any interpretation which differs from that long received by the Church ; by which we ever mean that line of the good, and pious, and learned in the Scriptures, in all ages, which no spiritually-minded reader of ecclesiastical history can ever fail to trace. In such a case as this, too, we should feel that the most pious interpretation is most likely to be true. THE ANCIENT MAXIM, DE NIHILO NIHIL. 285 even if it should not seem to be the most philosophical. If we cannot comprehend a positive enunciation of the great truth, we must be content with a negative one, better adapt- ed, perhaps, to the present state of our faculties, and believe by faith that the worlds were not made of things which do appear. There is a passage in the Sophista in which Plato speaks plainly of a creation by the direct act of God, and that, too, from things which before were not. It is very much in the style of the Scriptures, and no better refutation of some of the charges against him could be given than this clear declaration from this undoubted dialogue : Zci oa dij Travra ' dvrjra nai IAEI ov% bpLoXoyrjoopLev ITAN TA ylyveoOai (bg olov re dpcora ; Qvrcog dpa vno^Tjnreov Kept tov dmaiov dvdpog edv re ev nevta yiyvrpTai lav rs ev voootg rj tlvl aAAo) rtiv donovvrcov natitiv • tovtgj ravra elg dyaOov n reXeyrrioei ££jvtl fj teal dnodavovrt. ovrcovv Tzepi rov adltcov ravavrla rovrcov del dtavoelodac. Republic , 613, A., B. Physically , he would teach us, man is but an atom, subserving the interests of the great whole ; morally , all things, even a universe of mind and matter, is working together for his individual exaltation or degrada- tion. Instead of dwindling into the insignificance of an in- finitesimal, he rises in proportion to the magnitude of that universe of which he is a member, or, in other words, be- comes of the greatest individual importance as a rational part of the greatest whole. These apparently opposite yet strictly consistent views are likewise equally true in science. The whole cannot be fully understood without the parts, and it is an axiom no less important, that some a priori knowledge of a whole as a whole, that is, as a unity, and not merely an arithmetical sum, is necessary to an understanding of the parts. It is by the mutual action, reaction, and introaction of such a mental synthesis and analysis, that any true progress is made in science. When either is neglected, or the balance destroyed, science becomes, on the one hand, an ep,nei- h aXoyog* an irrational empiricism , or evaporates, on the other, into empty a priori speculation. Page 58, Line 5, Ila^ yap larpog nal nag evre^vog drj- puovpyog. The comparison adopted shows that Plato views the doctrine which the present state of his argument re- quires him to advance, namely, that the parts are made for the whole, rather in its physical than its moral aspect. It * Gorgias, 464, D r DOCTRINE OF PARTS FOR THE WHOLE. 291 is not the KvdEpvrjTrjg , the orparrjyog , the commander, the governor, the pilot — comparisons so often employed by him in illustration of moral and political relations — but the phy- sician, the artist, all of whose efforts are directed to the physical perfection of the work in which they are engaged, or that physical harmony which consists in the subservien- cy of the parts to the whole irrespective of any moral con- siderations. 'This is the order of physical production, and of those arts and sciences that copy from it — pipog evena oXov. It forms the parts for the whole, and not the whole, in any sense , for the parts. Line 6. n pdg to fcoivq f vvrelvov (3 eXtlotov. Ast and Stephanus would both read ^vvte'lvcov in this place, and refer it to the artist. The common reading, however, al- though the literal version in English is very harsh, seems, on the whole, to be deserving of preference. It more prop- erly has for its subject the work than the workman ; as in the example a few lines back — popiov eig to rcdv %vvtelvei. It may here be taken with (3eXtlotov 9 and the sentence would be freely translated, doeth all things for the whole , in respect to that best end which aims at the common good ; that is, in this case, the physical good , the good of the machine or structure as a structure, moral reasons, strictly such, not being here brought into view. The argument, then, when carried no farther, would be this : God will not overlook you ; his special providence is ever directed towards you, because, however insignificant you may be, physically, in yourself, you are wanted to fill up some place or some va- cancy in the great structure, for which nothing else is so well adapted. You may therefore seem to be laid aside, but you are not forgotten — his eye is upon you. Line 8. dyvocov onrj to tt E pl oe aptOTOV tco ttovtI %vp- baivEi Kal oot. It is somewhat uncertain whether apLOTOV here is to be taken with to i zEpl oe , or with tco ttovtI , or i-vudaivei. ^vpbalvei 9 however, may be rendered, to con 292 OBJECTION FROM THE EXTENT OF THE UNIVERSE. tribute to the good of anything, or to the accomplishment of any purpose , without any such qualifying word as apiorov. It makes but little difference, in the general sense, what view we take of it, and, on the whole, we prefer the follow- ing version : You are vexed , not knowing how that , in relation to yourself which is best for the whole , contributes also to your own good ; or, if we connect dptorov with ^vpbalvec, it may be read, not knowing how that which relates to ’ thee best con- tributes to the good both of the whole and of thee. At the hazard, then, of a little repetition, we would give the fol- lowing free paraphrase of the substance of the whole pas- sage ; the latter part, however, or converse doctrine, being rather implied than expressed, although it may be clearly found ia other parts of the Platonic dialogues : Physically, thou art but an insignificant pebble in the great rcrlopa, or building of the universe (see the comparison of the XlOol and XtdoAoyoi , page 55), yet forming a necessary part in the joinings and compactness of the whole, even absolutely essential to the whole as a whole, and which the builder and keeper cannot neglect without risking the ruin of the whole : morally, the great universe is also all made for thee, and reciprocally for each of its rational parts ; it was intended, with all its other parts, to have a bearing upon thy blessedness or misery, according as thou violatest or re- mainest in concord with its moral harmony ; its physical harmony thou shalt ever subserve, whatever may be thy condition or thy course. LII. Atheistic Objection drawn from the Extent of the Universe. Page 59, Line 6 . r Hin£p av e^oi Xoyov paor&vr] deoTg . ^ )v ndvrcdv, TavTy) pot 6okg) (frpa&tv — “ I think that I am explaining in what way ease in the administration of tho OBJECTION FROM THE EXTENT OF THE UNIVERSE. 293 Divine providence may have reason, that is, may be shown to be in accordance with reason.” The Epicureans and semi-atheists, in all ages, have been much concerned les‘„ the physical and moral government of the universe should be burdensome to the Deity. Lucretius was unable to see how it could consist with the happiness of the Gods. He therefore most reverently relieves them of all share in so troublesome a business, and, with pious concern for their ease and quiet, commits the world into the hands of Nature : Quae bene cognita si teneas, Natura videtur Libera continuo, dominis privata superbis , Ipsa sua per se sponte omnia Diis agere expers. Nam, pro saneta Deum tranquilla pectora pace Quae placidum degunt aevom, multumque serenum ! Quis regere immensi summam, quis habere profundi Indu manu validas potis est moderanter habenas? Quis pariter ccelos omneis convortere, et omneis Ignibus aetheriis terras subfire feraceis ; Omnibus inve locis esse omni tempore praesto, Nubibus ut tenebras faciat, ccelique serena Concutiat sonitul turn fulmina mittat, et aedeis Ipse suas disturbet ; et in deserta recedens Saeviat, exercens telum ; quod saepe nocenteis Praeterit, exanimatque indignos, inque merenteis 1 Lucretius , lib. ii., 1089. Horace entertained the same very elevated notions in re- gard to -natural laws and the abstraction of the Deity from all the concerns of this world, until he was frightened into a little unphilosophical piety by happening to hear it thun- der on a clear day. See Ode xxxiv. of the first book, com- mencing Parcus Deorum cultor et infrequens, Insanientis dum sapientiae Consultus erro — He seems to have been brought by his fright into quite a religious fit, and the sentiment with which the ode con- clude? is not only a devout acknowledgment of a special B b 2 294 EXPLANATION OF A DIFFICULT PASSAGE. providence, but is expressed in language bearing a striking resemblance to some of those many passages in the Bible which speak of depressing the proud and elevating the lowly : Valet ima summis Mutare et insignem attenuat Deus, Obscura promens : bine apicem rapax Fortuna cum stridore acuto Sustulit ; hie posuisse gaudet. His use, however, of the word Fortuna shows that he could not altogether divest himself of his old atheistic habit, even when he attempts to talk religiously. Some of our modern scientifico-religious works occasionally exhibit a similar mixture of the Jew’s language with the dialect of Ashdod. LIII. Explanation of a Difficult Passage. Remarks on those Views which resolve Morality into an Obedience to Physical Laws, and regard all Punishment as Consequential instead of Penal . Page 59, Line 7. E i pev yap repoq to oXov , k. t. A. This obscure passage may be thus paraphrased : “ For if any Power, having constantly regard only to the whole, should ever fashion his work by suddenly transforming all things — as, for example, by forming at once frozen water from fire — and should not* proceed by (analyzing) many things out of one, or (compounding) one thing out of many, so that they might thus partake of a first, a second, and even a third generation — in that case, the transformations of each displaced arrangement would be infinite in number ; blit now (that is, in the actual established course of things) * Ast, by taking, in this place, tj for the common reading, yy, has completely changed and perverted the whole meaning of the passage* EXPLANATION OF A DIFFICULT PASSAGE. 295 there is a wonderful ease in the administration of the Uni- versal Guardian.” We will proceed to give what seems to us the general sense of the passage, and of what follows it for some dis- tance, before going into any particular comment on words and phrases. It seems to be this : the speaker is showing that the Divine administration, even when extended to the most minute particular, is conducted with ease, in conse- quence of being a special superintendence carried on by general laws or media, whatever they may be, or by the in- ternal operation of powers which he lias implanted in things themselves ; so that there is no necessity for supposing any great or general change, or sudden transformation in the state of things (what would be called, in modern phraseol- ogy, a miraculous interposition), for the rectification of nat- ural or the punishment of moral evil — a transposition which, if it took place in every case, would call for an infinite number of changes, differing in every instance, and as mi- raculous as the immediate production of cold water* or ice * In the text, we have given vdop e/i'ipvxov. The common read- ing is epipvxov, and those who maintain it would render vdop e/iipv- Xov, aquam animatam ; to make any sense of which they refer us to the doctrine of Thales and Heraclitus, that water was the first prin- ciple of all things, and who also said something about fire, changed into water, being the universal semen. What is told us here about the changes and transformations of matter has, it is true, some little resemblance to the flowing philosophy of Heraclitus. Still, this re- semblance is only verbal. The illustration would be too far-fetched and obscure to suit the present place, in which the Athenian is la- bouring to give his hearers as clear an idea as possible of this diffi- cult position. It would also be giving a sanction to Heraclitus which Plato could never have intended ; and besides all this, it is very dif- ficult to perceive how it would present any illustration at all of the subject he has in hand. We therefore altogether prefer the other reading, which only requires the change of an accent, and which has some authority of manuscripts in its favour. ’E ju’ipvxov would be a participle of the verb epijjvx «, to cool , to freeze, and may be taken as 296 PUNISHMENT OF SIN HOW FAR CONSEQUENTIAL. from fire, without any of the intervening generations ; thus giving to rational beings no grounds for physical science, or a knowledge of the Divine operations, and making every act of Providence, instead of moving in harmony with, tc jar and displace every preceding and temporary arrange- ment. Instead of this, as we are told in what follows, he has so constituted things, not by any innate necessities of physical laws, but by his own absolute fiat, that good and evil will find in themselves, both in this world and in the pre-arrangements of Hades, their appropriate reward, and will each seek and find its proper place and level ; namely, vice will diverge, at first slightly, from the level plane, and thence descending with constantly-accelerated velocity ( 'elg / 3dGog ), will find its ultimate place in the terrors of Hades ; while virtue, mingling with the Divine nature, will ascend to a purer region, and through different degrees of blessed- ness will at last arrive at a perfectly holy or separate state, totcov ayiov oXov. This doctrine of Plato, and the mode in which he states it, is indeed sublime. Still, it needs a qualification similar to the one we applied to a previous view — a qualification for which there may be found abundant support in other portions of his writings where he maintains the strictly penal nature of punishment, as in the close of the Gorgias and the Republic. The doctrine which seems to be here presented is the truth, but not the whole truth. Standing thus alone, and without the corrective influence of any high- er views, it is a favourite scheme with many of our modern semi-infidels, who would resolve all morality into an obe- equivalent to the adjective frigidus. We doubt if Plato meant any- thing more by it than a strong example derived from substances ap- parently so remote, although capable of passing into each othei through a succession of physical media and generations. The othei and more common reading probably arose from some ignorant tran- scriber, who did not understand the passage, and to whom £/u'ipvxov l animatam, appeared more philosophical. PUNISHMENT OF SIN HOW FAR CONSEQUENTIAL. 297 dience to, or a co-operation with, physical laws, and all punishment into natural consequence. We do not wonder at the partiality with which it is entertained by such. They feel that it has no terror for a sinning soul, and that it utterly takes away all the moral power which belongs to the ideas of penalty and retribution. At the same time, they are pleased with it as a wonderful discovery of the nine- teenth century, when, in fact, they have merely revived a doctrine of some of the old heathen philosophers, who held that it was the great duty and chief end of man to live ac- cording to nature — Vivere secundum naluram. Vide Cicero , De Finibus , v., 9. With writers of this stamp it is the whole. When em- ployed by Plato and Bishop Butler, it is only held in sub- serviency to higher qualifying views of the Divine govern- ment, with which it is entirely consistent. Those to whom we allude would confine the maxim, vivere secundum natu - ram , entirely to the nature without us ; whereas, in obedi- ence to the law of a higher nature, man is often called to contend with the external world. The perfection of his moral being requires that he should often contemn the law of gravitation, and sometimes even submit that most exqui- site handiwork, his body, with all its most wonderful nat- ural laws, to be disfigured, ruined, and utterly broken up in the flames of martyrdom. Still, there is a truth in this mo- rality of nature, and it is only by refusing to associate with it any higher principle that such writers convert it into a most pernicious falsehood. So, also, may we admit, that the doctrine, that the pun- ishment of sin is the physical consequence of sin itself, is found in the Bible. “ What a man soweth , that shall he also reap.” “ He that soweth to the flesh , shall of the flesh reap corruption : he that soweth to the Spirit , shall of the Spirit reap everlasting life.” Revelation declares all this, but it also teaches with much more frequency and with more sol- 298 PUNISHMENT OF SIN HOW FAR CONSEQUENTIAL. emn emphasis, that the punishment of sin is, in the strictest sense, a penalty pronounced by a sovereign judge. “ The wicked shall go away into everlasting fire, PREP ARED for the devil and his angels” Physical consequences, even when they are strictly such, may be regarded as but pre- appointed executioners, deriving their powers, and their connexion with the sin, from no inward necessities, but from the sovereign pre-arrangements of God ; while the law of which they may thus form the penalty is anterior, both in the order of nature and of time, to all the laws of the natural world. The great absurdity of this scheme, when it thus stands alone, consists in this, that it is the penalty which creates the sin. It is wrong to eat too much, because it will be followed by a pain in the stomach ; and men are punished with a pain in the stomach, because they have been guilty of a breach of its physical law. Remove the pain, and you remove the sin. Can any one bring him- self to feel that anything like this would be true in regard to a breach of the law of charity, or that malevolence would change its moral character, though it could be followed by an eternity of pleasure ? If the violation of a physical law proceeds from a disposition to contemn a known arrange- ment of God, whatever may have been the object of that arrangement, it belongs to another department, and must be transferred to a tribunal higher than the natural. It is by overlooking the nature of punishment as strictly retributive, notwithstanding the mode of its infliction, that this doctrine of consequential suffering strips the Divine law of all its majesty, and becomes such a favourite with infidels and neologists. There is no terror in it ; and when employed, as it sometimes is even in the pulpit, without the qualifications to which we have adverted, its immediate ef- fect is ease and stupefaction of the conscience, rather than any alarm or true conviction of sin. There is, however, no inconsistency in the belief of both views. The punishment PUNISHMENT OF SIN IIOW FAR CONSEQUENTIAL. 299 inflicted by human government would be no less the retrib- utive penalty of positive law, although its preordained ar- rangements were such, that the path of every transgressor was literally beset with snares, or that it finally brought him, without arrest or the aid of the executioner, directly to the prison or the gallows. Page 59, Line 7. npog to oXov del pXenuv — “ Looking continually to the whole.” There is implied here a nega- tive assertion. It is equivalent to saying, “ and having no- thing else in view.” The meaning seems to be, that the process here mentioned might perhaps be adopted, if no re- gard was had to the parts, as parts, or except in their rela- tion to the whole. In that case, the Divine administration might perhaps proceed by these sudden transformations. But as in each act of Providence avast number of purposes, direct and collateral, are to be kept in view, and no one to be effected by disturbing or displacing another, there is need of an arrangement that shall be carried on by media, so that one move on the great chess-board (see note 6, p. 59) may accomplish many ends, instead of requiring separ- ate transpositions in every case. The philosopher evidently perceives a great difficulty at- tending any explanation that can be given. We can never, perhaps, fully understand the harmonious connexion be- tween a providence carried on by general laws, operating, in the main, with uninterrupted regularity, and a minute at- tention to those individual cases which may be made the subjects of special prayer and special judgments. It be- longs to that same class of mysterious truths, and presents the same apparent contradictions, as the doctrine of the Di- vine foreknowledge or foreordination, when viewed in con- nexion with the freedom of the human will, or of the Divine goodness, when attempted to be reconciled with the exist- ence of evil. Why should men be so clamorous for the rights of reason in religion, when, in so many cases, she 300 DIFFERENCE BETWEEN dvd)Xe0pOg AND aubviog. herself declares her own insufficiency as the highest lesson she can teach us, and delivers us over, either to total skep- ticism, or to that faith by which we receive truths appa- rently opposed, or whose point of connexion is beyond our radius of mental vision ; because, without this, we must give up other truths which our moral nature can only yield at the price of total darkness on all that most concerns us to know. LIV. The Word ’A vtiXedpog as distinguished from Aluviog. Re- markable Passage in the Timceus. Page 60, Line 3. avddXeOpov de ov yevopevov aXX’ ovu aicjviov. There is intended here an important distinction between alibvtov and av&XeQpov. The former means that which is in its very nature eternal, not subject, in any sensfe, to generation or decay, and, in fact, having no reference to %povog, or time regarded as proceeding by succession. ( See the definition of time as given in the Timceus, 37, E., and remarks upon it, page 223.) ? A v&XeQpov, on the other hand, suggests, from its etymology, the idea of something composite, although, when used without precision, it may be applied to that which is possessed of a higher nature. It signifies indestructible, not in itself, but because the thing of which it is predicated is upheld and maintained in being by the Supreme Power, and thus rendered capable of en- during through an endless succession, although never strict- ly ald)VLov or eternal in its essence. Kara vopov $eoi, says Ast, has respect to aluviov alone, and not to av&XeOpov. He would read according to the following order and punc- tuation : i/jvftTjv teal ocbpa, avibXedpov yevopevov, ov, Kadtinep ol Kara vopov ovreg deoi, aiibvtov — indestructible , , yet not eternal as the Gods are. This contrast between REMARKABLE PASSAGE FROM THE TIM^IUS. 301 Gods and men seems plausible, and yet we are satisfied that Ast is wrong. Our opinion is founded upon that pas- sage of the Timaeus, in which the Eternal Father thus ad- dresses the inferior deities to whom he had given being : 0 eol tietiv, G)v eyd) drjpcovpyog, narrjp re epycov, a 6l ’ epov yevopeva , dXvra , epov ye deXovrog. to pev ovv dr) deOev uav , Xvtov. to ye prjv tcaXtig dppooOev aal e%ov ev Xvetv eOeXeiv, Hanoi). 6l 9 a teal eneiirep yeyevifoOe , ’A0ANATOI pev ovn £(7T£, ovd’ aXvroi to Tzapirav. ovrt pev dfj XvOrj - oeoOe ye, ovde rev^eode Zavarov poipag , TH2 ’EMHS BOYAHDE£22 pei^ovog en deopov teal tevpiorepov Xa^ov- reg, erceivov olg ore eyiyveode cvvedeloOe — “ Ye Gods of Gods, of whom I am the Maker and the Father, as of works which, deriving their existence from me, are indis- soluble as long as I will it. Everything bound (or compos- ite) is capable of dissolution : nevertheless, to choose to dissolve that which is well harmonized, and works well, is the part of an evil being. For which reasons, and since ye were made (or had a beginning of your existence), ye are not immortal (in yourselves), nor in every respect in- dissoluble. Still, ye shall not be dissolved, nor shall ye experience the doom of death, partaking, IN MY WILL, of a bond of life stronger and more powerful than those things by which ye were bound (or of which ye were com- posed) when ye received your being.” Timceus, 41, A. That is, the permanence of all created things, from the highest to the lowest, rests on the moral attributes of the Deity. In his goodness they have a stronger bond than in all the laws or necessities of nature and of things. On this depends the continued existence not only of man, but of Gods, or, in the more sublime language of Scripture, of Thrones, Dominions, Principalities, and Powers. Kara vopov ovreg Qeoc : According to the decree or fate ( fatum ) on which their existence depended. Compare, also ; the similar expression, page 61, line 7 : tiara ttjv rrjg eipap • C c 302 GREEK WORDS FOR ETERNITY, ai(OV AND ald)VLOg . pevyg t&I-lv nal vojjlov. This confirms the view we have taken above in respect to $eof. They were dependent on this iaw, and not on any innate immortality. No^o^* here has about the same meaning with [iolpa, which, according to the more ancient creed of the Greeks, meant simply the Divine decree. This, we are prepared to show, is its sig- nification in Homer, and not a physical fate, as many con- tend. The wor^s nal ocbpa are to be taken col- lectively for all animated beings thus constituted. The continued existence of soul and body, severally or united, whether in the present state or in any one to come, is de- pendent on the Eternal Father, who is thus represented as speaking in this sublime passage from the Timaeus — who alone is strictly aluviog in the highest sense of that epithet, or, as the Apostle declares, 1 Timothy , vi., 16, 6 pbovog aQavaotav — who alone hath immortality . LV. The Greek Words for Eternity , A ld)v and A Icbvcog. Ald)V is compounded of del cov (see Aristotle , De Coelo, lib. i., c. ix., 10). 9 A el, ever, is from aco, deco, or drjpt , sig- nifying, primarily, to blow, to breathe, secondly, to live, to pass or spend time. v A(o seems also related to dlo), to feel life, to be conscious ; from whence some would derive alcbv in the general sense of existence. Homer uses ao or aeo) in the second of the above meanings, as in the Odyssey, iii., 151, and 490: v EvOa 6s vvnr 9 aeoav. Because this verb is thus used, in several places in the Odyssey, in con- nexion with vv%, some lexicographers absurdly render it to sleep . It is, however, only thus employed, because by night the flow or succession of time becomes a matter of distinct observation and consciousness more than by day. Hence, as the context shows, it is generally used of wake- ful and anxious nights : GREEK WORDS FOR ETERNITY, aiuv AND al&VLOg. 303 N v/cra pev deaauev, xaherr a cppsalv oppatvovreg. Odyssey , iii., 151. ’Ael, from this derivation, would present the idea of contin- uous being, of a going on, or succession ; and as a particle of time, is ever used of that which is boundless or undefined ; not so much that which cannot be bounded as that which is not bounded — which is not attempted to be defined, but is always considered as going on, on, on. ’A et, therefore, alone, would not express the true idea of eternity , but only of endless or unbounded time. This flowing word must be connected with, and, as it were, anchored upon another of more stability ; since stability and fixedness enter into the essential idea of eternity. This other word is the partici- ple of that verb of existence which expresses, in its philo- sophical sense, the highest mode of being. One part of the compound, then, is boundless and unconfined ; the other chains it to an eternal present, or, rather, since dov is of all tenses, altogether excludes the idea of time. It is thus that the Greek term approaches as near the true notion of eter- nity as it is in the power of language to bring us. Although the human mind may fail to take in all that idea which alcdv aims to express, still an apprehension of it may exist, sufficient, at least, to convince us that it con- tains nothing unreal, but has a solid foundation in the truth of things. We may approach it by negatives. Aidov is not time long or short, bounded or endless. It is not the oppo- site of time, but that of which xpo vo Si or time, in our pres- ent state, is the moving image. ( See remarks , page 223, and the comparison there referred to.) It may more proper- ly be said to be the opposite of tcaipog, or upoonatpog ; be- ing thus used by the Apostle, 2 Corinthians , iv., 18, and in such a way as to exclude all cavil as to its extent, at least in that place. It is there the direct antithesis of temporal or temporary. However difficult it may be for beings who can only 304 GREEK WORDS FOR ETERNITY, aUx OV AND ClloVLOg. think in a series, to form a conception of that which neces- sarily excludes succession of thought, we are nevertheless driven, by the clearest decisions of that reason which often goes where the conceptive faculty cannot follow, to affirm that this is the state in which all things must be present to the Divine mind. If to this we apply the term alcov, we have its perfect definition. We may be certain of its real- ity, although utterly unable to comprehend it. The idea of time is connected with an imperfection necessarily be- longing to our present state, namely, an inability to enter- tain in the mind more than one thought at once. This gives rise to what is called the succession of ideas, consti- tuting the measure of time ; and this succession we apply even to those truths which, as reason plainly assures us, have no relation to time or the sequences of cause and ef- fect. Nothing, on these abstruse points, could be more sat- isfactory than Plato’s comparison and definition, to which we have before referred, and which may be found Timceus , 37, E. Almost all our difficulties on the subject of endless being, and especially endless future punishment, arise from con- sidering eternity, or alcov, as time infinitely prolonged, as end- less succession or duration. This addresses itself to the imagination or conceptive power rather than to the reason, and hence this weak faculty of the soul faints and staggers under the attempt to realize what, as a conception of the sense, never can be realized. But the whol-e subject pre- sents itself under quite a different aspect when we regard the future state not as the beginning of a prolonged period, having its own past and future, but as a transition into eter- nity — as a condition differing not merely in degree, but in its very nature, from the present world of time. When the revolving mirror of Chronos, which now represents all things in motion, has ceased its revolutions, either in re- spect to the whole or each man individually, the landscape GREEK WORDS FOR ETERNITY, ald)V AND ald)VLOg. 305 of eternity, with all its fearful states, becomes in experience, as it ever had been in reality, fixed and motionless — cuzlvt ]- ra , dperdozara, del Kara ravrd e^ovra. There will be no endless succession of years and periods, which, in ev- ery effort of the mind to grasp them, only present, over and over again, the same difficulties of comprehension, and, in- stead of a true idea , give rise only to a painful* and imper- fect conception of the sense. “ For days, and nights, and months, and years, and all other successions of time,” says Plato, “ were not before the heaven existed. The past, the present, and the future are but temporal forms, which we ignorantly and incorrectly attribute to the eternal ovaca , or essence. For we say was, and is, and will be, when IS ( eon ) alone pertains to aeonian being, while was and will be belong to that flowing yeveoig, or generation, which exists in time. For they are motions ( mvijaecg ), but the eternal is, in respect to these, immoveable ; never younger, never older, having no past and no future” — to 6 e del Kara ravra e\ov aiavrjrog, ovre npeodvrepov, ovre ve&repov irpoarjUSL ylyveodai ttote , ovds yeyovevat, ovd’ eloavdcg eoeoOai Timceus, 38, A. Change and succession may be said to form the predom- inating characteristics of the present flowing phenomenal world. In eternity, all is just the reverse. There, to use language derived from the old Ionic problem, all things will stand. The things which are seen are temporal, probation- ary, preparatory ( Ttpoonaipa ). The things which are un- seen are eternal (alwwa), fixed, immutable, without succes- sion. The word ah ov is undoubtedly used in the Greek * In nothing is this more fully realized than in the efforts some- times made by preachers and others to convey what they call an idea of eternity; as, for example, from an ocean of drops, or the space of the solar system filled with grains of sand, and those mul- tiplied by myriads and millions of centuries. By such immensities of numbers the mind is wearied and exhausted, but never brought a hair’s breadth nearer the object at which it aims. C c 2 306 GREEK WORDS FOR ETERNITY, ald)V ^ ND aid)ViOg. poetry in the indefinite sense of life, existence, or state of being ; and there are also some passages in the Scriptures where it is taken figuratively in a lower signification of age or dispensation, although even these are grounded on the higher and radical import ; but this we affirm with confi- dence, that the restorationist can derive no aid from these specimens of Platonic usage, and, in fact, nothing could be more utterly opposed to all his views of change, reforma- tion, or restoration in the eternal state. We conclude with a definition of alcov, derived from the high authority of Aris- totle. It contains more reference to succession than that of Plato, but yet is directly in the way of all attempts to limit the meaning of this illimitable word. He is speaking of the super-celestial, or extra-mundane state, and what- ever we may think of its reality, there can be no doubt about the force of the Greek terms by which he attempts to set it forth. “ Time,” he says, “ is the number of motion, but above the heaven it has been shown that time cannot exist. There, there is no growing old, neither is there any change, but all is immutable, all is impassible, and having the best and most satisfying life (fa )fjv apioTrjv nal tt)v av- TapKeGTdrrjv ), continues for all eternity (tov aixavra aiti- va ) ; and this its name is divinely declared to us from the an- cients ('detcog EtyOeynraL napa rtiv apxatcov). For that end which contains the period of each existence is called its alcjv ( cevum , age , or being). According to the same reason or definition — tcard tov avrov Xoyov , nal to tov navrog ovpavov reXog, nal to tov navTCOV aneipov xpovov nal tt)v ansiplav i repisxov TeXog, ’AIS2N egtiv, duo tov ’AEI ’EI- NAI eiXr)(j)d)g tt\v err covvpiav, aOavaTog nal delog — that which constitutes the enclosing limit of the whole heaven or universe, that which embraces the infinite period , and the infinity of all things — that is alcov , ETERNITY, taking its name from EVER BEING, immortal and divine.” Arist., De Coelo, lib. i., c. ix., 10. Compare, also, The Laics , iv., PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL. 307 715, P., where Plato speaks of the Eternal Justice, which always follows as an avenger of crimes committed against the Divine law ( rov &eiov vopov npopog), and in com- menting on which the scholiast thus defines the word n epi- 7TopEvop,evog , namely, to aiovlcog — to ’A el (boavrog ttai Kara ra avra * rj yap irepi(j)Opd rovro LYI. Plato’s Doctrine of the Freedom of the Willy viewed in Con- nexion with the Law of Cause and Effect in Nature . Page 60, Line 11 . M eprjxdvrjrat 6rj Trpog nav rovro , k. r. A. — “ He devises this in reference to the whole, namely, what kind of a situation everything which becomes of a cer- tain quality must receive and inhabit.” That is, the itoio- rr\g or quality which, in the course of generation, anything assumes, must determine the quality of its final habitation. The establishment and enforcement of this law God has reserved to himself as his peculiar prerogative, while, as we are told in the following sentence, he has left to our own wills, rag alriag rr\g yeveoeug rov ttolov rivog — the causes of becoming such or such. (See note 10 , page 60 .) In other words, he has so ordered the course of nature, by a sort of pre-established harmony, that it constantly enforces this law, while the power of becoming the subjects of its rewards or penalties is left to the freedom of our own wills. The sentiment is about the same with that of Pope : And binding nature fast in fate, Left free the human will. We cannot find much fault with this in the heathen Plato, and the doctrine is undoubtedly true of man viewed as un- fallen, and in that primitive state when his will was truly free, because it was one with the will of God. The Chris- tian theology, however, does require us to modify the prop- 308 PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL. osition as regards our present condition, and to believe that, in some way, man by the fall subjected his will to nature ; that, therefore, although it has a wide prison-house within which to rove, and where it may be said to be free in its choices of objects before it, still it can never, by any voli- tion, rise above this state of nature, or escape its adaman- tine chain of cause and effect, until a stronger than nature shall interpose for its deliverance and perfect freedom. The sick man may turn from side to side upon his weary couch, but he cannot rise, take up his bed, and walk. We may exercise all kinds of choices (a term which in the strife of words on this subject so many have confounded with will) within the limits of the sphere into which we have fallen, but we cannot will to be holy, to love God with all our souls, and to live to his glory. If the Scriptures were not clear on the subject, it is so plainly a matter of personal experi- ence that we may well wonder how, in the light of an awa- kened conscience or consciousness, there could be any room for cavil about it. There is no doubt, however, that Plato was rather Pe- lagian on this great question ; although places could be cited which show that his mind was unsettled, and that there were very great difficulties attending any view he could take of the matter. We may find this same doctrine that is here advanced more fully set forth in the Republic, x., 617, P., where, after a long argument, in which he in- troduces that wild mythical legend respecting the Destinies, Lachesis, Clotho, and Atrope, he concludes in the follow- ing most concise and remarkable manner : Ov% vpag dai- pcjv Xr\^erai dA/l’ vfieig daiptova atprjoeoOe • aperr) 6e ddecr- 7 totov • atria eAoptevov * deog avairtog — “ Virtue is free from control : the fault is in the chooser : God is blame- less,” or, rather (since avairtog and atria do not in them- selves imply blame), God is not concerned in the causation of sin or the production of virtue. Notwithstanding this. PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL. 309 there are several striking passages in which he asserts,, without qualification, that virtue is a Divine gift, and that, in the present state of man, its attainment is hopeless with- out the Divine aid. As, for example, in the Meno, 99, P. : ’A peri) ovv dv elrj ovre (pvoet ovre dcdatcrov , dXXd deia poipa Trapaycyvopevrj olg dv TrapayiyvrjTcu — “ Wherefore virtue would be neither by nature nor by science or teach- ing, but by a Divine gift, bestowed upon those by whom it is possessed.” So, also, a few sentences below, to the same effect. (Meno, 100, B.) Nothing can be clearer than this declaration, and yet, when we take into view other parts of that same dialogue, it is extremely difficult to determine what he really thought about the cause and source of true virtue. Whether it was by nature, by sci- ence, or directly from God, were questions to which his mind often reverts, and which he seems never to have sat- isfactorily solved. The student may find it discussed at great length in the Protagoras. In the Republic, again (lib. vi.), where he is led to draw as strong as possible a picture of human depravity, he declares most expressly that the acquisition of virtue is impossible without the Divine as- sistance. “ Do you think,” says Socrates, “ that any soph- ist” — by which he means one of the ancient lecturers on moral philosophy who undertook to teach virtue for pay — “ do you think that any sophist, or any instructions of private persons, can control or even withstand such an in- fluence for evil ? No one ; yea, even to attempt it would only be evidence of folly.” And then he concludes in this most solemn and impressive manner : Ovre yap yiyverat , ovre yeyovev ovre ovv prj yevrycai aXkolov rjOog npog ape- ttjv rrapa rijv tovtcov 'natdelav. avOpcbneiov , cb eralpe * del- ov e^aipcb Xoyov . ev yap XP?1 eldevai , o ri nep dv ooO^j re ual yevryrai olov del ev roiavr \ 7 naraoraoei , Qeov polpav avro oCdo at Xeycov ov aanCdg epelg — “ For it neither is the case, nor has been, nor ever can be, that any character (or 310 PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL state of soul) should undergo a change to virtue in opposi- tion to the corrupt training of these influences. At least nothing human, my friend ; the Divine I lay out of the ac- count. For we may be well assured that he speaks most truly who asserts that if anything, under such circumstan- ces, is saved, and becomes such as it ought to be, a Divine dispensation alone hath saved it.” Republic , vi., 493, A. In another part of this same passage he pronounces the case absolutety desperate — eav firj rig avry /3orjdrjoag detiv tvxV — “ unless some God should come to the aid of the soul.” Repub., vi., 492, A. Surely, if this be a true picture of human nature,* Plato may be justly charged with inconsistency, yet no greater than many have manifested on this subject who possessed the higher light of revelation. If these representations be correct, how can virtue be said to be without restraint ? How can that be free which has so many impediments, to say the least? If there is no accountability when these impediments are supposed utterly to surmount the strength of the will, why is not this same accountability diminished pro rata when they exist in a less degree, although falling short of an absolute inability ? and how, then, can we avoid the conclusion, that the more vicious the disposition, and, * There is a most remarkable declaration of Thucydides on the subject of human depravity, which is the more worthy of attention, because it comes from one who, without any philosophical or reli- gious theory, was as cool and keen an observer of human nature as ever lived. “ It is the nature of man to sin (says this sagacious his- torian) both in public and private. No law can restrain him from it. All modes of punishment have been exhausted in the attempt.” Lib. iil, 45. And again, in the same section : an k&g re, advvarov , Kal nokkfjg svijOetag, bang olerat , Trig avdpaneiag tyvaeog oppcdpivrjg npoOvpwg tl npa^ai, anoTponrjv riva e^etr, rj vopiov rj ok k(p T(p deivtp — “To speak plainly, it’is impossible ; and it is a proof of great simplicity for any one to suppose that, when human nature rushes eagerly to the attainment of any gratification, it can be turned aside either by force of law or any penalty, however fearful.” PLATONIC DOCTRINE OF THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL. 311 consequently, the more difficult the practice of virtue, the less the degree of guilt, and the nearer an approach to a state of perfect innocence. Jacob Zimmerman, in his tract Be Proestantia Religionis Christiana collata cum Philosophia Socratis, finds fault with this doctrine that virtue is a Bivine gift , and thinks that, in the contest of Socrates with the sophist Protagoras, on the question whether virtue could be taught, the latter has great- ly the advantage. He also charges the views of Socrates with leading to licentiousness, while he seems to regard his most corrupt antagonists as the friends of the public morals : Et hac ratione Socrates vel invitus efiecit, ut illi qui jam vitiis immersi sunt aliquod presidium inde caperent. Nihil enim libentius ejusmodi homines audiunt, quam ea, quae summam difficultatem in virtuti colenda probare pos- sunt ; ita enim necessario inferri posse putant in sua potes- tate situm haud esse virtutem sequi. Vide Amcenitates Lit - erarice , vol. xi., p. 187. That the doctrine of Bivine grace — for such is substantially the declaration that virtue is the gift of God — should be charged with licentiousness is not surprising, since it has thus been characterized in all ages, even by men themselves as utterly corrupt as those Gre- cian sophists with whom Socrates contended even unto death ; but it certainly is a matter of exceeding wonder, that a professed Christian writer should censure him for that very sentiment in which, of all others, he approaches the nearest to the Bible. See some of these questions most acutely argued in Cicero’s treatise De Fato, s. v., vi. It is worthy of an attentive perusal, if for no other reason, to see how very similar, in all ages, have been the discussions which have arisen on these most ancient queries respect- ing fatalism, causality, co-causes, conditions, moral agency, and the freedom of the will. Jonathan Edwards himself does not distinguish with more keenness than Cicero and the persons whose opinions he has introduced in the tract referred to. 312 EXPLANATION OF A DIFFICULT PASSAGE. Page 61, L. 6. ev eavrolg ne/crrjpeva tt)v rr\g per aboXrjg airiav — “Possessing in themselves the cause of change.” That is, without, or to the exclusion of external causes, yet still not, as those maintain who contend for the self-determi- ning power of the will, without being under the law of cause and effect existing within them ; the cause being the inter- nal result of their present state at any one time, or the com- bined sum and product of all the influences, from within and from without, then existing in their physical, intellect- ual, and moral constitution, and the effect being the one single following state which the laws of our minds compel us to affirm must result from it. So Cicero, De Fato, s. xi. : Sic quum sine causa animum moveri dicimus, sine ex- terna causa moveri, non omnino sine causa , dicimus. LVIT. Explanation of a Difficult Passage. Page 61, Line 8. opiKporepa, pev rtiv i]d gjv, k. t. a. There is a good deal of difficulty about this sentence, and yet we think a very good sense may be made of the com- mon reading, without resorting to those conjectural emenda- tions which some commentators would propose. The ver^ sions of Ficinus and Cornarius both proceed upon the idea that the main contrast is between opucporepa pev and nXeio de, which view, it must be confessed, seems to have ap- pearances strongly in its favour. Neither translator, how- ever, adheres to the Greek text as it now stands. Yiger proposes amendments grounded upon the same view of the passage. He would read eXarro) pev nai ducatorepa , that it might be more directly opposed to ttXelg) teal adiK&repa, just below. Ast thinks there is no need of any other change than to expunge eXarro, and would render as follows : Quae minus depravata sunt, ea per terrae planitiem ingredi- untur, quae vero in majorem depravationem inciderunt in EXPLANATION OF A DIFFICULT PASSAGE. 313 profundum, &c., detruduntur. It seems to us, however, that almost all difficulty is removed by regarding the main contrast as intended between opuiporepa pev and pel^oov 6 e five or six lines below, and a subordinate contrast between eXarro) and ttXsig) tie. We would place a comma after eXarr 6), and regard a.. pev as implied in connexion with it ; the omission being nothing strange, seeing that the particle had just been used to mark the main antithesis. In this view of the matter, pera6dXXovra is to be taken with eXar- to), and there will also be a contrast of degree between this participle and peraTreadvra ; the former, from its being in the present tense, implying a slight beginning of a change, either for good or evil ; the latter, a more sudden and rapid descent. ~Elg is to be taken with peranopeveraL understood as though repeated, and not with perarcEGovra . In this view, eXarrcOj instead of being required to be expunged, becomes an important word, and the only real defect in the sentence is a mere want of verbal symmetry in having no- thing to correspond to aduuhrepa, together with the harsh, ness which is felt in connecting this word with peraixeGov- tcl. On the other view, it is not easily explained how opc- uporepa tg)v i]Q(x)v can be made to mean those who are less depraved , as the phrase is regarded by Ficinus, Cornarius, and Ast. Another objection to their version is, that there is nothing with which we can contrast pel^cov 'ipvxv below, when the whole following context shows that a very strong antithesis was most certainly intended. This, we think, can only be effected by regarding it as in opposition to opi- Kporepa, tgjv rjOojv, a phrase equivalent to opiKporepa rfO?], or ol exovreg opiKpoTEpa, rfO?], and which we would consid- er as synonymous with what Plato elsewhere styles opwpa (pvoLg, the small nature , the less marked or inferior char- acter or habit of soul, in distinction from the psi^cov ipyx^i ; neither expression in itself implying depravity, but, on the other hand, each including the good as well as the bad. D D 314 EXPLANATION OF A DIFFICULT PASSAGE. With these preliminaries, we proceed to state the order of the whole passage, according to the view above taken, enclosing in brackets the implied words which are deemed essential to a full interpretation : opiKporepa pev tojv 7 ] 0 d)v, eXarrco \jpsv~\ psrabdXXovra^ peranopeverat Kara to rrjg X<- opag entnedov , ttXslo) 6 s perarcsGovra teal d6tKd)repa, sig paOog [peTaTTOpeveTCu] rd re itaro), n. r. X. — psc^cov 6s 6rj 'ipvX'h Kairiag rj dpsrr]g onorav psraXdb 37, k. t. X. Of which there may be given the following free translation : “ The smaller natures, to wit, those possessed of none of the greater traits of soul, whether for good or evil, undergoing less change, or as long as they undergo less change, pro- ceed with a slight deviation (change being implied in psra) along the apparently level plain of life ; but when they de- cline more rapidly, and with greater degrees of wickedness (the metaphor being carelessly lost sight of in aduuorepa), they change their course (slg fiaOog) into a steep descent, and to those regions commonly spoken of as being below, which, under the name of Hades, men fear and dream about, &c. ; but as for the greater soul, whenever it par- takes of vice or virtue, by the exercise of its own will or by association, &c. — such a soul, we say, whenever, by mingling with the Divine excellence, it becomes in a re- markable degree similar, makes a transition, also, into a surpassingly holy place, being continually carried into an- other still better region ; but when contrariwise, then trans- ferring the seat of its life in a contrary direction and to a contrary abode.” From ooa to ouparuv inclusive, may be regarded as a parenthetical clause, explanatory of ra narco tojv roucov. In the second member of the principal antith- esis, had there been preserved a perfect correspondence, we should have had psc^G) 6 s rtiv rjOtiv ; from some idea of wdiich in the mind of a transcriber probably arose the other reading preferred by Ast, namely, pst^co 6s 6rj i/> rj, &c. In this way, sXdrrco (/i£F) and tcXsig) 6s indicate two EXPLANATION OF A DIFFICULT PASSAGE. 315 different stages in the course of those denoted by opiKpo- repa 7 ] 0 r ] : the first, a gentle deviation, almost level, and therefore called ettctte6ov ; the second, a rapid descent. There is also a great propriety in the use of the present pera6d?i?iOVTa , which Ast would change into the second aorist — while , or as long as , they undergo less change. In the words entnedov and j3a6og there may be one of those geometrical allusions of which Plato was so very fond, and which he so frequently employs. An evil course may be compared to the three dimensions of magnitude. It is first a mere point, then extends itself into a line, then spreads out into superficial space ( Eninedov ), and, finally, grows into the solid dimensions of iniquity in all theii length, breadth, and depth ; that is, in the fixed and immu- table condition of the sinful nature — a state from which Plato would admit that it was not in the power of the will to return. There are, in a critical point of view, several defects about both members of this antithesis and the subordinate contrasts. It is, however, far better to admit that Plato sometimes writes carelessly than to hazard so many con- jectural emendations. The whole passage strongly sug- gests a similar thought from the Republic : e^el 6fj Xoyov , rrjv dpLOrrjv (pvav kv aXXorpLCOTEpa ovoav Tpocpy, Kamov diraXX&TTEiv r?jg (pavXyg — Kal rag 'ijjvxag rag EV(pvEOT&- rag , KaKijg Traidayoytag rvxoverag , diacpEpovroig KaKag yiy- vEoOat — “ It is reasonable to suppose that the best nature, being in a condition adverse to its proper development, turns out worse than the meaner ; and that the most high- ly-gifted souls, partaking of evil instruction, become surpass- ingly wicked.” Republic, vi., 491, D. ^avXrj 'ipvx'f] here is equivalent to opiKporepa rjdrj in the passage before us. Compare, also, the Republic, vi., 495, B., where the simi- larity of the expression tends greatly to confirm the view we have here taken : OfUKpa de (j>voig ovdsv psya ovdenors ovdeva ovte 16 l(x)tt]v ovte ttoXiv dpa. 316 GREEK WORD HADES, After all, however, it must be confessed that there is no little difficulty about the passage. Had the first member of the principal antithesis been double, like the second, or had it specified two distinct courses in opposite directions, we should have had no doubt about the correctness of the ver- sion we have given. Such a view, however, may be im- plied, and thus opacporepa rjdrj may be taken of virtue and vice both, as well as j in the second member ; the change either way, in respect to the meaner nature, be- ing at first so slight as not to call for the distinction ; and, in the second stage, the acceleration of velocity being more naturally associated with the ideas of descent and sin than with that of virtue ; so that it is the metaphor which seems to have led the writer astray from the symmetry and con- sistency of the thought he intended to express. Hence, too, we may perhaps account for the introduction of adt/cd)- repa , which seems otherwise to mar the harmony of the passage. Yiger proposes as an emendation eXarrco pev /cal di/caiorepa , as opposed to 7 rXeto) tie Kdl adirccbrepa. This would favour the idea contained in our version more than his own. A better course, however, would be to regard the words /ca/clag rj dperrjg, &c., as implied after opucporepa t(ov rjOcbv, in the first member, as they are expressed after pel^cov ds dr) 'ipvx'ij , in the second. The passage has given great difficulties to all commentators. LVIII. The Greek Word "A idrjg, and the Hebrew and rP3 oSty. Page 61, Line 11 . "Aidrjv enovopa^ovreg. This word is most clearly from deidrjg , invisible. Thus it is explained by Plato, although he is no great authority in etymological matters : ev adov — to aeideg dr) Xeycov, Gorgias , 493, B. It may therefore mean the invisible world , that is, unseen , in AND HEBREW SHEOL AND BETH OLAM. 31 ? the sense of concealed from present vision , or it may be con- nected with the more philosophical import of aeidijq, as used by Plato in the Phaedon, namely, the ideal , the intelli- gible world , in distinction from the visible world of sense and matter. The first, however, is doubtless the most common acceptation of the word — the unseen , the unknown region which the grave hides from our view, and whither we can- not follow the departed. It strongly suggests the old ety- mologies given for the Hebrew 'lisp (sheol), and to which we cannot help being partial, notwithstanding they are so contemptuously rejected by Gesenius. They make it from to ask , to demand , to inquire; as though intimating the deep anxiety of men in all ages to penetrate the dark mys- tery concealed by the veil of death, as in the wailing lan- guage of Job : “ Man dieth, and wasteth away ; he giveth up the ghost, and where is lie?” Job , xiv., 10. The common poetical expression, olnoq *. AiSov , corre- sponds, both in form and sense, to the Hebrew IV5> as used Ecclesiastes, xii., 5 : Man goeth to the house of his eternity , or to his eternal house , instead of our very de- fective translation, his long home , which suggests the grave for the body, rather than that abode of departed spirits which is undoubtedly meant by the Hebrew as well as the Greek phrase. Compare Xenophon’s Life of Agesilaus, near the close : “ And thus this man spent his life in the service of his country, and, having at length died, was transferred to his eternal home ” — elq tt)v ’AIAION "OIKH- 2IN uarrjydyeTO. So, also, Diodorus Siculus, in his ac- count of the Egyptians, says, “ They call the habitations of the living, lodging-places (fcaraXvoetq), or inns, because we dwell in them but for a short time ; but the abodes of the departed they style eternal houses , because they con- tinue in Hades during the boundless eternity ” — aldiovq ol- Kovq TzpoaayopevovGiv, ev f/ A idov diareXovvriov tov •AJIEIPON ’AIS2NA. Diod. Sic ., lib. i., 51. D d 2 318 SIMILAR FEARS OF HELL IN ALL AGES. The Hebrew oSty corresponds more closely to the Greek ''Aidrjg than SiKBh It signifies hidden, unknoivn , boundless in time, and undefined in space. The composition of the phrase is the same in both languages : rrs — oixog r/ Aidov- — the house of Olam—the house of Hades — the invisible state, the abode of unseen spirits. These terms suggest conceptions of vastness, of dread sublimity, while the inquiring word sheol calls up the unknown world, and presents it to the mind as That undiscovered country, from whose bourn No traveller returns. The expression olnog "Acdov must have been common in the most ancient Greek. Its antiquity is proved by the ellipsis, elg r 'A idov, which afterward came into such fre- quent use by the poets. Hence we conclude that it must have been an early Orientalism, derived from this very phrase with which we have compared it. Had it not been so very common in classical Greek, some critics would doubtless have pronounced it a Hebraism. LIX. Similar Views of a Future State, and Similar Fears of Hell in all Ages. Page 61, Line 11 . ooa r/ A tdrjv rs teal rd tovtojv e^dfieva twv ovoparcov enovofad^ovreg ofiodpa (bodovvrac ual ovet- pomXovoi ty7)vreg diaXvOevreg re twv owparwv — “ which, under the name of Hades and similar titles, men greatly fear ( valde horrent) and dream about, both when living and when separated from the body.” This may be compared with a similar passage from the Republic : Fv yap loOi, cb EuKpareg, otl eneidav rig eyyvg % rov oleoOai reXevTr}- oetv, elaep^eraL avrd 3 deog ual (f)povrlg. olre yap Xey opevoi uvOol TCEpt t(ov ev "A idov, &>g rov evOade dduerjoavra 6ei SIMILAR FEARS OF HELL IN ALL AGES, 319 ekeI didovcu dlfcrjv, orpetyovoc rrjv i/jv%7]v 6 pkv ovv evpLGico)v kavTOv kv rw (3ccp iroXXd aSL/crjpara, etc tg>v im- vo)v, cjouep oi tt aldeg, dapa eyeipopevog, deipaivei , ual £rj pera nanfjg eXiridog — “For be well assured, O Socrates, that when any one is near that time in which he thinks he is going to die, there enter into him fear and anxiety. For then the old stories about hell, how that the man who has here been guilty of wrong must there suffer punishment, torture his soul. Wherefore he who, in the retrospect of his life, finds many crimes, like frightened children starting from their sleep, is terrified, and lives in evil forebodings.” Republic , 330, E. Nothing could give us a surer glimpse into the ancient conscience than such a passage as this. We are very apt to think that the fears of the future world are almost wholly derived from the Bible, and that the an- cient mythology respecting Hades was the mere picture of the poet, without possessing any very strong hold upon the common mind. This declaration, however, of the aged Cephalus, is undoubtedly meant by the writer to be characteristic of the class and age to which the speaker belonged. In this most dramatic of all the dialogues of Plato, nothing of the kind would have been put in the / mouth of such a character, had it not truly expressed a sen- timent deeply grounded in the popular creed and feeling. It testifies more strongly to the ancient universal belief in a retributive hell and a coming judgment, than all the ab stract reasonings of our philosopher, and all the mytholo- gical allusions of the poets. The doctrine of a hell for the wicked, as we have else- where observed,* is one of the oldest articles in the reli- gious creed of all ages and nations. Such incidental pas- * See the Biblical Repository, No. xix., Art. 3d, where this and kindred topics are dwelt upon at some length ; also a discourse de- livered at Burlington, Vermont, 1839, entitled Natural Religion, the Remains of Primitive Revelation. 320 SIMILAR FEARS OF HELL IN ALL AGES. sages as these refute all the reasonings of Warburton, in his attempt to prove that the doctrine of future punishment exerted but little influence in the ancient systems of legis- lation and religion. The very efforts of the Epicureans to ridicule the vulgar fears, and to make light of the terrors of the unseen Hades, show how deeply these awful truths, whatever may have been their origin, had penetrated the human soul. Even the style in which Lucretius speaks of them betrays a secret trepidation, and instead of philosophic indifference, manifests that bitter hatred which, as in the case of most modern infidels, proceeds from a mind once deeply troubled, anxious, and yet unable to shake off those fears which its philosophy affects to despise. This exhi- bition of a soul ill at ease, and of an interested hostility to the very idea of future retribution, is apparent in those lines in which he thus sets forth that monster of horrid as- pect, with whose gloomy frown the timid Epicurean was ever haunted : Humana ante oculos quom vita jaceret In terris, obpressa gram sub Religione ; Quae caput a cceli regionibus obtendebat, Horribili super adspectu mortalibus instans. — Lib . i., 63. The same thing is manifested when (to use Plato’s com- parison), like a child who has awaked from some dream of terror, he seems to exult in the timid hope of deliverance from the fears of a future hell : Et metus ille foras praeceps Acheruntis agundus, Funditus humanam qui vitam turbat ab imo , Omnia subfuscans mortis nigrorc ; neque ullam Esse voluptatem liquidam, puramque, relinquit. Lib. iii., 37. Such strong language most clearly shows, that the doctrine and fears against which it was directed were no light or laughing matter, either to the poet or to those for whom he wrote We have every reason, therefore, for believing that much SIMILAR FEARS OF HELL IN ALL AGES. 321 the same views of death, and the same apprehensions of future retribution as now prevail, have ever existed among mankind ; coming not from reason or philosophy, but hand- ed down by tradition from some revelation made in the most ancient time. In all ages, too, and in all creeds, the rep- resentations of the nature of this future punishment have been of the most terrific kind, as though the imagination, for this purpose, had been taxed to its utmost powers. Fire, and chains, and utter darkness, and similitudes of ever-un- gratified desire and of ever-raging passion, have always formed a part of the dread machinery of Hades. The reli- gious poet Pindar describes it as that from which the eye of the soul turns away, as from scenes too full of horror to contemplate for a moment : rol d’ anpoGoparov oh^ovtl novov — * and, in reference to it, a still more religious poet, even the inspired prophet and leader of Israel, asks with dread so- lemnity,! “ Who knoweth the power of thine anger V * Or, as it has been most admirably paraphrased, Thy dreadful wrath exceeds our thought, And burns beyond our fear. Leaving out of the account the solemn confirmation of the doctrine which may be derived from the fearful imagery employed by our Saviour, and taking into view only the heathen world, we may well ask the question, Whence came all this ? The great problem is for them to solve who as- sert that the doctrine of future punishment is contrary to the Scriptures, the reason, and the feelings. Whence, then, came it, in the face of all these opposing influences ? Men are not fond of what is irrational for its own sake, and they certainly do not love their own misery. Whence, then, came this rptyepcov pvdog^ these fears of Hades, of * Find Olymp. Carm ii., J., d. f Psalm xc., 11. t JEschylus , Choeph 312. 322 the word ayioq. Tartarus, of Gehenna, and those other names which, as Plato says in the passage before us, men have applied to this state ? Why, if this be all false, and without founda- tion in any view of the moral government of God, have the human race thus ever .tortured themselves for naught ? Why have they indulged in these terrific inventions of fan- cy, handing down, from age to age, and from generation to generation, a useless, yet most tormenting anxiety ? And above all, how is it, if sin be such a trifle, that men, by these inventions, have ever persevered in passing a sen- tence so unjustly severe on their own depravity ? Compare the Gorgias , 525, C. ; Phcedon, 114, A. ; Republic , 616, A. LX. The Word "Ay tog. Exceeding Spirituality of some of Pla- to's Views. Many of his Thoughts capable of being fairly accommodated to a Spiritual Sense higher than the Author himself had intended to convey . Difference in this respect between his Writings and those of all other Philosophers , Ancient or Modern . Page 61, Line 17. uai perebaXe tottov ayiov oXov — “Is transferred, or passes into a place all holy.” Purity , or holiness , is generally given as the primary sense of the Greek aytog and of the Hebrew or tyYp. This, how- ever, besides being incapable of accounting for the other meanings, some of which are almost directly opposite, does of itself require some ultimate, and, at the same time, more simple conception into which it may be resolved. This more simple and primary idea is that of separation * or of * This will account for those other senses of the root which seem almost the opposite of holy , since it may also refer to that which is purely wicked , or separated from all good. Hence ayo<;, or ayof, may signify an abominable crime. So, also, uytog may sometimes denote the word ayiog . 323 leing set apart. In proof of this we may compare the use of the word throughout the Pentateuch, in its application to places, sacrifices, and to the whole nation of Israel, as sep- arated from the rest of mankind, to be a holy , that is, a sep- arate people. In the same manner are Christians charac- terized, in the New Testament, as ayioi , separate , peculiar ; although in the world, yet not of the world. Thus God is styled ayiog, in the highest sense, to distinguish him, on the one hand, from the earthly and impure conceptions of polytheistic idolatry, and, on the other, from the apparently more philosophical, but no less degrading views of the pan- theist. He is holy, separate from the universe he has call- ed into being, and, although filling all things , yet, in his es- sence, inhabiting the high and holy place. As here used by Plato, ayiog roirog means a place set apart from everything that is sinful and vile — the end of a course of purification, during which there has been a con- tinual ayiaopog , that is, a continual separation of the pure from the impure, leaving at last nothing that defileth or ren- ders unfit for this exceedingly separate region. Compare the description of this holy place in the Phsedon : “ When thus the soul is occupied, it goes away to the pure, to the that which is accursed , execrable. On the same principle, the Hebrew may mean one devoted to the most beastly wickedness, as in Deuteronomy, xxiii., 18. In a similar manner, the kindred Latin word sacer may signify blessed or cursed . The Hebrew ^3 has the same peculiarity, but derives it from a different source. Some would make ayiog, or dyvog, which occurs in the tragedians ( ayiog being found mostly in later Greek), from a£cj, ufoyai, to revere, to stand in awe of. Even here, however, the mind is led to the same original or ultimate sense of separation, as the ground of the feeling express- ed by it, whether that feeling be one of admiration and awo of the pure and holy, or of fearful astonishment at enormous crime. The same primary idea undoubtedly exists in the Latin purus, from the Greek nvp, fire, the penetrating and separating element which has, in all ages, been regarded as the means and emblem of purification. See the Timseus, 56, A. 324 PLATONIC SPIRITUAL SENSE. ever-being, to the immortal, the unchangeable, and, being of a kindred nature with it, always would abide there, and ceases from its restless wandering — ual uenavrai rov i:Xa- vov — and is ever engaged in the contemplation of the eter- nal. Phcedon, 79, D. Elsewhere he tells us, in almost Scriptural language, that holiness becomes those who would enter this holy place ; whether by the term he means a lo- cality in space, or an exceedingly separate state of the soul : E Ig 6e delov yevog \jlt\ tt avreXwg KaOapcp amovn ov tiefug acpuiveloOcu — “ To enter into the family of the Di- vine,’’ or, in other words, to become a partaker of the Di- vine nature, “ can only be for him who departs wholly pure.” Ibid ., 82, B. Without irreverence may we com- pare this with Hebrews, xii., 14 : dycaopov ov ov- Idg o'lpETcu rov K vpiov — Holiness , without which no one shall see the Lord. We are very far from saying, or even imagining, that Plato attached to these expressions the same high sense in which they are used by Paul, and yet there are many such passages which, without any violation of the spirit of his language, are capable of a comparison, to say the least, with some of the most precious truths of revealed religion. He was evidently directing his vision to a region of reality, far beyond the aim of any of the heathen philosophers who preceded, or were cotemporary with him. May he not have had some faint glimpses of those higher truths which his words, without any violence in their interpretation, fre- quently suggest to one who reads him by the light of the Christian revelation ? Almost everything depends upon the state of mind with which his writings are studied. To the materialist and the skeptic he will often appear visionary and unmeaning. Jefferson, in a manner most characteris- tic, pronounced him a foggy intellect. Many of the Chris- tian fathers, and a succession of the most learned and pious in the Church throughout its whole history, have ever re* PLATONIC SPIRITUAL SENSE. 325 garded him with enthusiastic fondness, and esteemed his dialogues as ranking next to the Scriptures, although at a distance which forbade any comparison with the latter as an inspired message from Heaven. We w^ould not be so extravagant as to assert that Plato has a spiritual or esoter- ic sense, as these terms are used by the allegorist or the mystic. No violence need be done to the letter, or to the ordinary laws of interpretation, and yet, by a species of ac- commodation most easy, and, at the same time, most natu- ral, a higher elevation, and a new and almost divine beauty, may be imparted to many passages, causing them to glow with a radiance that seems derived from the same source with the inspiration of the Sacred Volume. Whatever may be the cause, whether it be that lower truths are ever types of higher, which shine through them when examined by a peculiar light and in a peculiar state of the soul, so that there may be truly a lower and a higher sense equally well conveyed by the same letter (a principle which undoubted- ly prevails to some extent in what the soundest expositors regard as the double sense of Scripture) ; or whether there is a spiritual power in language considered in its essence, if not in its forms, as an emanation from the Universal Reason, so that at times, and when happily employed, it may so manifest its own inherent light as to transcend the mind and intended meaning of the writer himself, while the reader, under more favoured circumstances, is admitted to a higher region of thought, and to a deeper participation of that Spirit which dwelleth in the words — or whatever may be the explanation of the fact, most certain it is, that the language of Plato is often thus easily adapted to a spiritu- ality of meaning, in the Christian sense of the term, beyond that of any uninspired writings, ancient or modern, and to an extent which, we may suppose, would transcend anv con ception of the philosopher himself. Any one may understand what is meant by this, by keep E E 326 PLATONIC SPIRITUAL SENSE. ing these thoughts in mind while reading some of the more striking passages to which reference is made. In those parts of the Phaedon, for example, where the true philoso- pher is represented as daily dying to the world and sense (tuvdvvevovoL boot ivy^dvovoiv opOcbg anropEvot tyiXooo- (pcag keXrjOEvai rovg aXXovg, on ovdev avrol emrrjdevovoLv fj anoOvrjo/ceiv te /cal TEdvavai ), let the reader think of the Christian instead of the philosopher, and what a close af- finity does the style at once assume with some of the ex- pressions of the apostle. What language could more truly set forth that hidden aim in the life of the follower of Christ, in which he is so unknown to the great mass around him. The world knoweth him not. “ The rest of mankind/’ says Socrates, “ understand not that he lives to die a saying which Cicero, although he but imperfectly comprehended even its Platonic sense, has imitated in the declaration, Tota philosophorum vita commentatio mortis est. Tusc. Disp ., i., 74. Again, in the same dialogue, take the description of that wisdom for which everything else must be exchanged, and without which all other apparent virtues are but splendid cheats — o/uaypacptac — mere shadows of a shade, consisting only in a wretched barter of one passion for another (rjdovag npog rjdovag , /cat Xvnag npog Xvnag, /cal (j)66ov npog (j)66ov , /cal pEc^oj npog EXarrco, coonep vopiopara /caraWaTTEaQai), “ the exchanging of pleasure for pleasure , grief for grief fear for fear, and greater for less, like the coin of traffic let any one, we say, in reading this, and its most instructive context, think of the Scriptural Wisdom in place of the Platonic (ppovrjcng , and how vividly arise to mind our Saviour’s parable of the pearl of great price, and the sub- lime personifications of wisdom in the books of Job and Proverbs. Plato may not have exactly meant by (ppovrjoig that fear of the Lord which is the beginning of all right un- derstanding, but he was certainly aiming far above any philosopher of his day, or any modern moralist who docs PLATONIC SPIRITUAL SENSE. 327 not draw directly from the fountain of inspiration. Ex- amples of a similar kind may be taken from a great variety of passages everywhere meeting us in his most important dialogues. In the first half of the sixth book of the Re- public, for philosophy, and the philosopher, keep in mind Christianity and the Christian, and how sublimely does the sense, so sublime before, mount up to a new region of spiritual light ; and yet, in all this, no violence is done to the language ; every argument, every epithet, every metaphor retains its native force and its relative harmony, while the mind can hardly resist the impression, that this glowing description of the true philosophy and the true philosopher was intended for a higher meaning than, at first, appears upon its face. The incongeniality of this spirit, be it philosophy or be it religion, .with the selfish, debasing, and corrupting influences in the midst of which we live — its struggles with sense, the contempt poured upon' it by the world, its de- pendence upon that Divine aid which Plato, in this passage, so expressly acknowledges, its continual aspirations after the fixed and eternal, the rest which it bestows where all else is changing and flowing, the exceeding joy with which, at times, it inspires that small number who, in every age, have tasted and experienced how sweet and blessed is this gift of Heaven, while they contemplate the madness which rules the multitude — ol oXtyot yEvopEVoi nal yevodfievoi rjdv nal panaptov to nrrjpa , nal rcbv noXXtiv Idovreg rrjv (laviav* — the elevation of soul which is produced by a re- ligious contemplation of the whole of our being , leading, not to a contempt of our present human life, but to a just esti- mate of it as an exceeding small portion of our entire ex- istence, and of the boundless field of being which lies around us, as when he says, advvarov ry 6/avota , (] vtt&pxel avTTj i\ pEyaXonpETCEia nal 'dECopia iravrog j ilev * Republic, vi., 496, C. 328 PLATONIC SPIRITUAL SENSE. Xpovov , TraGrjg 6s ovotag , peya tl 6ouslv elvac rov avOptim* vov piov* all these, as they are presented in this warm and eloquent description of philosophy and the philosophic life, rise at once to a more elevated meaning, while, at the same time, how admirably does every sentence, thought, and word accommodate itself to this higher sense, as though it had formed the main and only design of the writer. When, with that mild pathos w T hich he sometimes uses with so much effect, he tells us what difficulties the 'philosophic nature has to encounter in maintaining its ground against the unfriendly influences of a foreign, uncongenial clime (cjoirsp %svikov onsppa sv yxf aXX'q onsLpopevov e^irrjXov (ptXel uparovpevov Isvai elg to smx&piov),] we can hard- ly help thinking that we hear the spiritual and plaintive Leighton declaring, that “ the grace of God in the heart of man is like a tender plant sown in a strange, unkindly soil,” where its fruit would inevitably wither and degenerate into affinity with some base native weed, unless he that planted it should exercise that constant care, without which it must perish. In the hands of no other writer, ancient or modern, does philosophy ever assume this heavenly aspect. Should it be supposed that this is all the effect of a partial imagina- tion, let the experiment be tried with others. Let any one, with a similar purpose, read Aristotle, or Bacon, or any of the moderns who treat of the philosophy of the soul, and ascertain if he can, without violence, extract from them any such higher sense, or any such easy accommodation to an elevated Christian spirituality. A faint resemblance of this peculiar Platonic unction may be traced in some of the philosophical tracts of Cicero, especially those that were written during the latter years of his life, and in the sub- dued spirit of his adverse fortunes ; but even with Cicero, * Republic, vi., 486, A. f Ibid., 497, B. PLATONIC SPIRITUAL SENSE. 329 they are mere imitations of the style and manner of one whom he professedly takes as his model, and whom he so affectionately styles “his master Plato.’’ Let these thoughts be carried with us in reading, in the seventh book of the Republic, the description of the dark cave, and of the poor prisoners who are there confined, with their backs to the light, and their intent gaze ever fix- ed upon those shadowy appearances which so strangely flit across the walls of their chamber of imagery. What thoughtful mind can fail to recur to the higher truths of the Christian revelation, or avoid being struck with the al- most perfect parallelism, as, in Plato’s most truthful picture, he contemplates the fondness of those miserable bonds- men for their gloomy abode, their first aversion to the daz- zling splendour of the world of reality, and the strong grasp with which they cling to their prison house, when some kind hand attempts to draw them forth, through the rough and steep ascent (rpaxeiag real avavrovg avadat Jscog), into the light of life. How graphic, too, the description of the science and philosophy of that narrow world (rrjg steel aoeplag). How admirably does he depict the interest with which these subterranean savans are occupied in the study of what they style nature, in tracing the law of cause and effect, antecedents and consequents, as the dim shadows pass across their contracted scene of observation — the petty pride with which they dignify this pursuit with the exclu- sive name of science, their stinging jealousy of others who are ambitiously aiming at the distinctions and honours of the same most intellectual life, the laborious earnestness with which they are engaged in thus building up from these inductions a science of shadows , which might astonish their more vulgar companions, by its seeming vaticinations of the periods and returns of those (jiaLvopeva, with which their minds are daily occupied, to the exclusion of any study of themselves or of their true position — while all this time the E e 2 330 PLATONIC SPIRITUAL SENSE. real world , in which shines the real sun , where may be seen the real heavens , and where alone exists the real science , are as much and as utterly unknown as are the high hopes of the Christian, and the sublime truths which occupy his soul, to the most grovelling and sensual world- ling. T cpal 6s teal snaivoi el Ttvsg avrolg rjoav tots reap’ dXkfkuv teal yspa tco ot-vTaTa tcaOapcbvTL Ta napiovra teal avrjpovevovTC paXiora oca ts nporspa avTcbv teal oca vcTspa siuOsi teal apa nopsvscOac , teal ste tovtojv 6?) 6vva- TGdTaTa anopavTevopsvG) to psXXov fj^stv, 6otcsig dv avTov (tov npog to cpcog sXOovTa ) smdvprjTiucbg avTibv s%siv teal f 7\kovv Tovg nap ’ steslvoig Ttpcjpsvovg ; Republic, vii., 516, D. The resemblance between this and the spirit and tenor of the Scriptural representations need not be pointed out. One might almost fancy it an expansion of the striking, yet concise description of the Psalmist : #'*r:]bniy 0^3“^, Man walketh in a shadow , a land of images, A VAIN SHOW. Wish this philosopher even politics assumes a divine and religicms aspect, and, in all his speculations, the political closely connects itself with the theological. How easy and natural would it be, in pursuance of the same method, to adapt what he says of the heavenly paradigm in the close of the ninth book of the Republic, and his seventh kingdom in the Politicus, to the Christian Church : sv r %f npd)TX) 6s noAv npcoTov ts teal apiCTOV /3lo)tsov , nXrjv Tr\g f EBA0MH2. naoojv yap skslvtjv ys snnpiTSOv, oiov 'Ssov s £ dvOpunoiv, sre t(a)v dXXcov noXuTSiCdV. Politicus , or Statesman, 303, A. From such an accommodation of Plato’s rich and won- drous fancy, how many most valuable thoughts, or rather illustrations, might be suggested, which would not be un- worthy even of the pulpit — thoughts which, while they claimed the closest affinity with the Scriptures, might be brought to bear upon the soul and conscience with all the power of illustration drawn from the language of the divin- MYTHICAL SENSE OF THE WORD 1 Mvarog. 331 est of philosophers. We know of no profane writer who, in this way, might be so useful to the preacher as Plato, and no one whom we would so earnestly recommend to all young men who are aiming at the Christian ministry. Let them not read Plato to understand the Bible — although, even with this in view, they would receive no small assist- ance — but let them read the Bible in close connexion with our philosopher, and they will understand Plato better than he ever understood himself. LXI. Mythical Sense of the Word Qavarog. Page 62, Line 4. ev re %G)yj nal kv naoc ftavaroig. This evidently refers to the deaths of one individual, and not of many. But why, then, the plural ? We think Plato keeps in mind here his doctrine of the transition of the soul, or its {jL£T£fj,\ljvx(oo£i,g, into various states, either in an ascend- ing or a descending series ; the passage from one to the other of which he styles a death and a birth. See the Phse- don, 114, B., also 70, C. : uaXaiog jt i£v ovv korl ng 6 Ao- yog, (hg elalv £v6iv6£ d(bino\i£vai Znti , nal tt&Xlv ye d£vpo acpuivovvTCU , nal ylyvovrac kn rCdv t£0v£O)tc»)v — u It is an ancient tradition that souls go there from hence, and again return hither and arise from the dead.” Compare, also, what is said respecting the purgations and metempsycho- ses of the soul, in the remarkable myth at the end of the Republic. Thus, also, in the Gorgias, 493, A., he speaks of the present life as though, when compared with some preceding state, it might in reality be a death, to which, for reasons arising out of some former relations, we may have been doomed. “ As you say,” continues Socrates, “ life is an awful thing (duvog 6 (3log ), and I should not wonder if Euripides spoke the truth when he said, 332 MYTHICAL SENSE OF THE WORD tiavaTOg. Tig 6' oldev , el to v pev eon rcarOavelv , to rcarOavelv 6e ^ v ; Who knows but life is death, and death is life ? And per- haps we are now dead, as I have heard of the wise, and that the body is our monument ( orjpa ) or sepulchre in which the soul is buried.” The context of this strange declaration in the Gorgias affords strong reasons for believing, that it may have been spoken mystically and mythically of that spiritual death which is so prominent a subject of the Scriptures. In this most exquisite analysis of the nature of physical pleasure, and its utter want of all claim to be considered The Good, the sensualist is regarded as “ dead while he lives.” His soul is said to be rotten and leaky, like a perforated cask (d)£ rdOog rerpr^evog). His pleasure is described as a continual inflowing to supply a constant outflowing ; a “ bro- ken cistern,” requiring a constant and laborious filling, in distinction from that spring which Socrates represents as ever full, and which so strongly suggests our Saviour’s “ well of living water, bubbling up to everlasting life.” In this description, physical pleasure is regarded as a pro- tracted dying, because it can only exist as the gratifying of an ever-craving want, the removal of an ever-tormenting pain, the vain attempt to quench an ever-burning thirst, or to fill an ever-empty void. In the language of the sensual- ist himself : ev rovrcp earl to rjdecog ev rep