THE MYTHS OF PLATO 5•1#•1 THE MYTHS OF PLATO TRANSLATED WITH INTRODUCTORY AND OTHER OBSERVATIONS BY J. A. STEWART, M.A. STUDENT AND TUTOR 0Γ CHRIST CHURCH AND WHITE'S PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD ; HON. LL.D., EDINBURGH iLottUon MACMILLAI^ AND CO., Limited NEW YORK : THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 1905 All rights reserved β35Έ PEEFACE The object of this volume is to furnish the reader with material for estimating the characteristics and influence of Plato the Mythologist, or Prophet, as distinguished from Plato the Dialectician, or Eeasoner. In order to effect this special object within a reasonable space, it was necessary to extract the Myths from the Dialogues in which they occur, with only the shortest possible indication of the Context in each case, and to confine the Observations to the Myths as individual pieces and as a series. The reader, therefore, must not expect to find in the Observations on, say, the Phaedo Myth or the Phaedrus Myth a Study of the Phaedo or the Phaedrus. The Greek text printed opposite the Translations and followed by them throughout, except in a few places where preferred readings are given in footnotes, is that of Stallbaum's Platonis Opera Omnia Uno Volumine Comprehensa (1867). I owe a large debt of gratitude to two friends for help received. Professor J. S. Phillimore read all the Translations through in proof with the most friendly care ; and errors which may be detected in these Translations will, I feel sure, turn out to be in places where, from some cause or other, I may have failed to make proper use of his suggestions. The other friend who• helped me, Frederick York Powell, is gone. A few weeks before his last illness began to cause serious anxiety to his friends, he read through all the 948 νί THE MYTHS OF PLATO Translations in manuscript up to the Phaedrus Myth, inclusive, and I read to him nearly the whole of the Introduction, and also other parts, especially those relating to the Theory of Poetry. The help he then gave me by his suggestive and sympathetic discussion of various points closed a long series of acts of friendship on which I shall always look back with a feeling of deep gratitude. J. A. STEWART, Oxford, December 1904. CONTENTS INTEODUCTION 1. The Platonic Drama — Two elements to be distinguished in it: Argumentative Conversation and Myth ..... Pages 1-4 2. General remarks on μυθολογία, or Stpry-tellino^ — Primitive Story-telling described as άρθρωττολοΎία καΐ ^'ipoXoyia — Stories, or Myths, are (1) Simply Anthropological and Zoological ; (2) Aetiological ; (3) Eschatological — A Myth, as distinguished from an Allegory, has no Moral or Other- meaning ........ 4-20 3. Plato's Myths distinguished from Allegories — To what experience, to what " Part of the Soul," does the Platonic Myth appeal ? To that part which expresses itself, not in "theoretic judgments," but in "value-judgments," or rather "value-feelings" — The effect produced in us by the Platonic Myth is essentially that produced by Poetry ; "Transcendental Feeling," the sense of the overshadowing presence of "That which was, and is, and ever shall be," is awakened in us — Passages from the Poets, quoted to exemplify the production of this effect .... 20-39 4. ' ' Transcendental Feeling " explained genetically as the reflection in Conscious- ness of the Life of the "Vegetative Part of the Soul," the fundamental principle in us, and in all living creatures, which silently, in timeless sleep, makes the assumption on which the whole rational life of Conduct and Science rests, the assumption that "Life is worth living," that there is a Cosmos, in which, and of which, it is good to be — "Transcendental Feeling " is thus Solemn Sense of Timeless Being, and Conviction that Life is good, and is the beginning and end of Metaphysics — It is Avith the production of the first of these two phases of "Transcendental Feeling" that the Platonic Myth, and Poetry generally, are chiefly concerned — The Platonic Myth rouses and regulates this mode of "Transcendental Feeling " for the use of Conduct and Science . . . 39-42 5. The Platonic Myth rouses and regulates "Transcendental Feeling" by (1) Imaginative Representation of Ideas of Reason," and (2) Imaginative Deduction of "Categories of the Understanding" and "Moral Virtues" — Distinction between "Ideas" and "Categories" implicit in Plato — Kant's distinction explained — Why does Plato employ Myth when he "represents" Ideas of Reason, Soul, Cosmos, God, and when he " deduces " Categories of the Understanding and Moral Virtues ? 42-51 6. Plato's treatment of the " Idea of God " .... 51-60 viii THE MYTHS OF PLATO 7. Plato's treatment of the ''Idea of Soul" — Agnosticism of Plato's day with regard to the Immortality of the Soul — Influence of Orphic Belief as felt by Pindar and Plato — Plato's Eschatological Myths plainly reproduce the matter of Orphic teaching .... Pages 60-71 8. Summary of Introductory Observations in the form of a defence of Plato against a charge brought against him by Kant, Kritik d. reinen Vernunft, Einleitung, § 3 — Plato's Myths (roughly distinguished as (1) representing Ideas of Reason, or Ideals, and (2) deducing Categories, Faculties, Virtues, i.e. tracing them back to their origins) will be taken in the following order : (a) as representing Ideas of Reason, the Phaedo Myth, the Gorgias Myth, the Myth of Er (the three Eschatological Myths par excellence), the Foliticus Myth together with the Myth of the Golden Age, the Protagoras Myth (Aetiological Myths), and the Discourse of Timaeus ; (b) as chiefly concerned with the deduction of Categories or Virtues, the Phaedrus Myth, the Meno Myth, and the Myth told by Aristophanes and Discourse of Diotima in the Symposium ; (c) the Atlantis Myth and the Myth of the Earth-born, which respectively represent the Ideals and deduce the Categories of the Nation, as distinguished from the Individual ....... 72-76 THE PHAEDO MYTH Context of the Myth ....... 77 Translation ........ 79-93 Observations on the Phaedo Myth 1. Plato's method of "giving verisimilitude to Myth, by bringing it into conform- ity with the " Modern Science " of his day, illustrated from the Phaedo, and paralleled from Henry More .... 94-101 2. The subject of the last section further illustrated by reference to the parallel between Plato's Geography of Tartarus and the "True Surface of the Earth" and Dante's Geography of Hell, Purgatory, and the Earthly Paradise — The parallelism between Plato and Dante dwelt on chiefly with the view of suggesting the method by which we may best under- stand the function of Myth in the Platonic Philosophy, the method of sealing the impression made on us by the Myth of one great master by the study of the Myth of another with whom we may happen to be in closer sympathy ...... 101-113 3. The distinction between Dogma and Myth insisted upon by Socrates, Phaedo, 114 d — "Moral Responsibility" the motif of the Phaedo Myth ........ 113-114 THE GORGIAS MYTH Context . . . . , . 115 Traiislation ........ 117-125 CONTENTS ix Observations on the Gorgias Myth 1. " Moral Responsibility " is the motif of the Gorgias Myth, as it is of the Phaedo Myth — The Gorgias Myth sets forth, in a Vision of Judgment, Penance, and Purification, the continuity and sameness of the Active, as distinguished from the Passive, Self, the Self as actively developing its native power under the discipline of correction, κ6λασί$, not as being the mere victim of vengeance, τιμωρία — Death as Philosopher Pages 126-128 2. The mystery of the infinite difference between Vice with Large Opportunity and Vice with Narrow Opportunity .... 129-130 3. Observations on Tablets affixed to the Judged Souls, on the Meadow of Judgment, and on the Three Ways .... 130-132 THE MYTH OF ER Context . . . . . . . . 133 Translation ........ 135-151 Observations on the Myth op Er 1. Cosmography and Geography of the Myth .... 152-154 2. Dante's Lethe and Eunoe taken in connection with the Orphic Ritual and Mythology, to which Plato is largely indebted for his account of the Soul's καθάρσια as a Process of Forgetting and Remembering . 154-161 3. More about the Cosmography and Geography of the Myth — The Pillar of Light, the Spindle of Necessity, the Model of the Cosmos in the lap of Necessity ....... 162-169 4. The great philosophical question raised and solved in the Myth, How to reconcile " Free Will " with the " Reign of Law " . . 169-172 THE POLITICUS MYTH Introductory Remarks ....... 173-174 Context ......... 175 Translation ........ 177-191 Translation of the Myth of the Golden Age .... 193-195 Observations on the Politicus Myth 1. Relation of the Politicus Myth to the " Science " of Plato's day . 196-197 2. Is Plato "in earnest" in supposing that God, from time to time, withdraws from the government of the World ? . . . . 197-198 3. Resurrection and Metempsychosis .... 198-200 4. "The Problem of Evil" raised in the Politicus Myth — How does Plato suppose the solution of tlis problem to be furthered by an Aetiological Myth like that of the Politicus ? — The value of Aetiological Myth as helping us to " solve " a " universal difficulty " as distinguished from a "particular difficulty" — It helps us to "put by" the former kind of THE MYTHS OF PLATO difficulty— The Kalewala quoted to illustrate the function of Aetiological Myth— The Story of the Birth of Iron— Transition from the Politkus Myth to the "Creation Myths" strictly so called, the Protagoras Myth., and the Discourse of Timaeus .... Pages 200-211 THE PROTAGORAS MYTH CotUextof the Myth > ....... 212-213 Translation ........ 215-219 Observations on the Protagoras Myth 1. Is it a ** Platonic Myth," or only a " Sophistic Apologue " ? — It is a true Myth, as setting forth a priori elements in man's experience . . 220-222 2. It sets forth the distinction between the "mechanical" and the " teleo- logical " explanation of the World and its parts — It raises the question discussed in Kant's Critique of Judgment . . . 222-226 3. Account given in the Myth of the Origin of Virtue as distinguished from Art ....... . 226-228 4. A Sculptured Myth, the Prometheus Sarcophagus in the Capitoline Museum ........ 228-229 5. The difference between Myth and Allegory — Sketch of the History of Alle- gorical Interpretation — The interpreters of Homer and of Greek Mythology — Philo— The Christian Fathers— The Neo - Platonists— Dante— Plato's Allegory of the Cave (which is a Myth as well as an Allegory) — His Alle- gory of the Disorderly Crew — Allegory and Myth compared with Ritual ........ 230-258 THE TIMAEUS Context ......... 259 Translation ........ 261-297 Observations on the Timaeus 1. General observations on its scope ..... 298-302 2. Purification and Metempsychosis ..... 302-304 3. On the Creation of Souls ...... 304-305 THE PHAEDRUS MYTH Context of the Myth ....... 306-307 Translation ........ 309-335 Observations on the Phaedrus Myth 1. Preliminary ........ 335 2. The Phaedrus Myth as giving a " Deduction " of the Categories of the Under- standing—But it also sets forth the Ideas of Reason . . 337-339 CONTENTS xi 3. The doctrines of Άνάμνησι^, 'Έρω$, Immortality— The Meno Myth translated, and compared with the Fhaedrus Myth — In what sense is the "Doctrine of Ideas" ''mythical"?. .... Pages 339-349 4. The Number 729 ...... . 349-350 5. The celestial, or astronomical, mise en βοέηβ of the "History of the Soul" in the Fhaedrus Myth, and the importance of that mise en sc^ne for sub- sequent philosophical and religious thought down to Dante . 350-381 6. Poetic Inspiration ....... 382-395 THE TWO SYMPOSIUM MYTHS Context of the Myths ....... 397 I.— THE MYTH TOLD BY ARISTOPHANES Translation ........ 399-407 General Observations on the Myth and comparison with the Zagreus Myth and with Rabelais . . 408-413i IL— THE DISCOURSE OF DIOTIMA Translation ........ 415-427 Observations on the Discourse of Diotima 1. The Discourse at once an Allegory and a Myth — May be taken as a study of the Prophetic Temperament — The nature of Prophecy . . 428-434 2. The History of the Doctrine of Daemons . . . . 434-450 GENERAL OBSERVATIONS ON MYTHS which set forth the Nation's, as distinguished from THE Individual's, Ideals and Categories Myths in which we have the spectacle of a Nation's life, (a) led on by a Vision of its Future, (&) conditioned by its Past. These are (a) the Atlantis Myth in the Timaeus and Critias, which, taken in connection with the account of the Ideal State in the Jiepublic, sets forth the Vision of an Hellenic Empire ; {b) the Myth of the Earth-born in the Republic 451-456 THE ATLANTIS MYTH Υ Abbreviated translation, or rendering ..... 457-464 Observations on the Atlantis Myth The Geology and Geography of*the Myth . , . . 465-469 xii THE MYTHS OF PLATO THE MYTH OF THE EARTH-BORN Translation ....... Pages 471-473 Note on the Myth of the Earth-born ..... 474 CONCLUSION— THE MYTHOLOGY AND METAPHYSICS OF THE CAMBRIDGE PLATONISTS The "Cambridge Platonists" represent Plato the Mythologist, or Prophet, rather than Plato the Dialectician, or Reasoner, and in this respect are important for the understanding of our modern English '* Idealists," who, it is contended, are " Platonists" of the same kind as Cudworth and his associates ....... 475-519 INTKODUCTION 1. The Platonic Dkama The Platonic Dialogue may be broadly described as a Drama in which speech is the action/ and Socrates and his companions are the actors. The speech in which the action consists is mainly that of argumentative conversation in which, although Socrates or. another may take a leading part, yet everybody has his say. The conversation or argument is always about matters which can be profitably discussed — that is, matters on which men form workaday opinions which discussion may show to be right or wrong, wholly or in part. But it is only mainly that the Platonic Drama consists in argumentative conversation. It contains another element, the Mythj which, though not ostensibly present in some Dialogues, is so striking in others, some of them the greatest, that we « are compelled to regard it, equally with the argumentative conversation, as essential to Plato's philosophical style. The Myth is a fanciful tale, sometimes traditional, some- times newly invented, with which Socrates or some other interlocutor interrupts or concludes the argumentative conv ersa- 1 tion in which the movement of the Drama mainly consists. ' The object of this work is to examine the examples of the Platonic Myth in order to discover its function in the organism of the Platonic Drama. That Myth is an organic part of the Platonic Drama, not an added ornament, is a point about which the experienced reader of Plato can have no doubt. The Sophists probably ornamented their discourses and made ^ Cf. Cratylics, 387 B. to Xiyetv μία tLs έστι των τράζεων. • Β THE MYTHS OF PLATO f ^^ them more interesting by the insertion of illustrative fables or allegories like the Choice of Hercules ; ^ but the Platonic Myth is not illustrative — it is not Allegory rendering pictorially results already obtained by argument. Of this the experienced reader of Plato is well aware. He feels when the brisk debate is silenced for a while, and Socrates or another great interlocutor opens his mouth in Myth, that the movement of the Philosophic Drama is not arrested, but is being sustained, at a crisis, on another plane. The Myth bursts in upon the Dialogue with a revelation of something new and strange i the narrow, matter- of-fact, workaday experience, which the argumentative con- versation puts in evidence, is suddenly flooded, as it were, and transfused by the inrush of a vast experience, as from another world—*' Put off thy shoes from off thy feet, for the place whereon thou standest is holy ground." It is in the mouth of the dramatic Socrates that Plato puts those Myths best fitted to fill us with wondering surmise and make us think — the so-called Eschatological Myths. It may be that here Plato represents a trait of the real Socrates. Socrates* method of argumentative conversation, it is fully recognised, determined the dialogue-form of the Platonic writings. It may be that also the introduction of Myths, at least of the Eschatological Myths — Myths distinguished by great impressiveness of matter and style — was suggested to Plato by something in the real Socrates. The personal influence of Socrates worked as a vital principle in Plato's mind, and bodied itself forth in Socratic dramas — plays in which, as I have said, Socrates and his companions are the actors, and philosophical discourse is the action. Any element, then, in the Platonic writings which the experienced reader finds of great dramatic moment — and the Myth is such — is likely to represent some striking trait in the person and influence of the real Socrates. In the Myths put into his mouth Socrates prophesies — sets forth, by the aid of imaginative language, the fundamental conditions of conduct and knowledge. He " prophesies," and his hearers listen spellbound. That Socrates possessed what is now called mesmeric influence is very likely. The comparison of his influence (in ordinary debate) with that Ϊ See Grote's Plato, ii. 38, note e. INTEODUCTION 3 ί •>.>,.., •. '. • •■ of the electric fish, η θαΧαττία νάρκη} may be thought to imply as much ; while his familiar spirit, or Βαιμόνιον, must be taken as evidence of "abnormality."^ I venture to offer the suggestion, for what it may be worth, that the Platonic Myths, in manner if not always in matter, represent (directly as spoken by " Socrates " himself, indirectly as spoken by "Timaeus," " Critias," "Protagoras," "the Eleatic Stranger") certain impressive passages in the conversation of the real Socrates, when he held his hearers spellbound by the magnetism of his face and speech. Be this as it may. Myth distinguished once for all by weight and ring from Allegory ^ is an essential element of Plato's philosophical style; and his philosophy cannot be understood apart from it.* The main plan of this work is to append to the English translation of each of the Platonic Myths observations and notes relating specially to that Myth itself. Each Myth is a unique work of art, and must be dealt with individually in its own context. But I hope that the general effect of these special observations will be to leave the reader, at the end, with an adequate impression of the significance of Myth, first in Plato's philosophy, and then in present-day thought. Before beginning, however, to carry out the main plan of 1 Meno, 80 A. ^ Hegel {Gesch. d. Philos. ii. 94-101) regards the δαιμόνων as a "magnetic" plienomenon, physiologically explicable. C. R. Volquardsen {Das Odmonium des Socrates und seine Interpreten, Kiel, 1862) holds (pp. 58 and 71) that it cannot be explained by any law of anthropology or physiology, but is a "singular" phenomenon. Zeller {Socrates and the Socratic Schools, pp. 72-79, Eng. Transl.) concludes that it is "a vague apprehension of some good or ill result following on certain actions." F. W. H. Myers {Human Personality, ii. 95 AT. ) cites the δαιμόνων of Socrates "as an example of wise automatism ; of the possibility that the messages which are conveyed to the supraliminal mind from subliminal strata of the personality — whether as sounds, as sights, or as movements — may sometimes come from far beneath the realm of dream and confusion, — from some self whose monitions convey to us a wisdom profounder than we know" (p. 100). Against L. F. Lelut {Du Demon de Socrate, 1856), who argues from the records of the δαιμόνων in Xenophon and Plato that Socrates was insane, Myers contends (p. 95) that "it is now possible to give a truer explanation ; to place these old records in juxta- position with more instructive parallels ; and to show that the messages which Socrates received were only advanced examples of a process which, if supernormal, is not abnormal, and which characterises that form of intelligence which we describe as genius." Dr. H. Jackson's article on "the δαιμόνων σημβΐον of Socrates" in the Journal of Philology (vol. x. pp. 232 if.) may also be referred to, and Kiihner's Prolegomena (v. de Socratis δαιμονίφ) to his edition of Xen. Mem. ^ See infra, p. 15 and pp. 230 if. * Zeller's Plato, pp. 159-163 (Eng. Transl.), may be read in connection with this and preceding paragraph!! 4 THE MYTHS OF PLATO this work, I will offer some preliminary remarks on μύθοΧο^^ία, or story- telling in general, in the course of which I hope to indicate what I conceive to be the ground of Plato's methodical employment of it in philosophy. 2. General Remarks on μ,υθοΧοψα^ or Story-telling. Myth distinguished from Allegory \— It is a profound remark that Imagination rather than Keason makes the primary difference between man and brute.^i ^The brute lives mainly among the immediate impressions of sense. The after-images of these impressions are evidently of \ . little account in his life, being feeble and evanescent.^ ©Tit man lives a double life — not only, with the brute, in Γ" the narrow world of present sensations, but also in a wide world of his own, where his mind is continually visited and re- visited by crowds of vivid, though often grotesque and grotesquely combined, images of past sense-impressions. It is in this wide wonder-world of waking dream, which encompasses the narrow familiar world of his present sense-impressions, that man begins his human career. It is here that the savage and the child begin to acquire what the brute has no such opportunity of beginning to acquire, and never does acquire, — a sense of vast I environment and of the long course of time. rPhis waking dream, which constitutes so great a part of man's childish experience, probably owes much of its content to the dreams of sleep. Some of the lower animals, as well as man, seem to have dreams in sleep. But man, we may suppose, differs from ^ "In the lower stages of civilisation Imagination, more than Reason, dis- tinguishes men Irom the animals ; and to banish art would be to banish thought, to banish language, tobanislithe expression of all truth." — Jowett, Dialogices of Plato, Introduction to the Republic, p. clxiv. r^ 2 "At the proper season these birds (swallows) seem all day long to be im- pressed with the desire to migrate ; their habits change ; they become restless, are noisy, and congregate in flocks. Whilst the mother -bird is feeding, or brooding over her nestlings, the maternal instinct is probably stronger than the migratory ; but the instinct which is the more persistent gains the victory, and at last, at a moment when her young ones are not in sight, she takes flight and deserts them. When arrived at the end of her long journey, and the migratory instinct has ceased to act, what an agony of remorse the bird would feel if, from being endowed with great mental activity, she could not prevent the image constantly passing through her mind of her young ones perishing in the bleak north from cohl and hunger " (Darwin, The Descent of Man, part i. chap. iv. . p. 173, ed. 1901). INTEODUCTION 5 the lower animals in remembering his dreams. And he can tell them, and improve upon them in the telling, whether they be dreams of sleep or waking dreams — indeed, he must tell them. They are so vivid that they will out ; he cannot keep them to himself; and, besides, the telling of them gives what may be called secondary expression and relief to certain emotions and feelings, which in the case of the brute find only primary expression in acts within the world of sense-impres- sions. In the case of man, fear, confidence, anger, love, hate, curiosity, wonder, find not only primary expression in acts within the world of sense-experience, but also secondary and, as it were, dramatic expression in the adventures and doings of the dream-world, all circumstantially told. It is impossible to over-estimate the early debt which man owes to his love of story-telling thus inspired and supplied with material. In telling and listening to stories about the dream-world, man, in J short, learns to think. The dream-world of the primitive *n story-teller and his audience is a large, easy world, in which they can move about freely as they like — in which they are rid of the hard facts of the world of sense-experience, and can practise their powers without hindrance on tractable material, calling up images and combining them at will, as the story goes on, and thus educating, in play, the capacity which, afterwards applied to the explanation of the world of sense-experience, appears as the faculty of constructive thought. The first essays of this faculty are the so-called Aetiological Myths, which attempt to construct a connection between the world of sense-experience and the dream-world — which take the dream- world as the context which explains the world of sense- experience. Judged by the standard of positive science the matter of the context supplied from the dream-world by the mythopoeic fancy is in itself, of course, worthless ; but the mind is enlarged by the mere contemplation of it; the habit of looking for a context in which to read the sense-given is acquired, and matter satisfactory to science is easily received when it afterwards presents itself. The conceptual context of science thus gradually comes to occupy the place once filled by the fantastical context of the dream-world. But this is not the only respect in which the mythopoeic fancy serves the development of man. 1[f_it pr epares the way for the exercise 6 THE MYTHS OF PLATO of the scientific understanding, it also indicates limits within which that exercise must be confined. This it does by- supplying an emotional context, if the phrase may be used, along with the fantastical context. The visions of the mythopoeic fancy are received by the Self of ordinary consciousness with a strange surmise of the existence, in another world, of another Self which, while it reveals itself in these visions, has a deep secret which it will not disclose. It is good that a man should thus be made to feel in his heart how small a part of him his head is — that the Scientific Understanding should be reminded that it is not the Eeason — the Part, that it is not the Whole Man. Herein chiefly Llies the present value of Myth (or of its equivalent, Poetry, Music, or whatever else) for civilised man. ^ The stories which the primitive inhabitants of the dream- world love to tell one another are always about the wonderful adventures and doings of people and animals. '' ΚνθρωιτοΚοηία tcuiX ΊκοόΚοηία^ may be• -taken as'^a-^ftlH description of these atories. The adventures and doings happened " Once upon a time " — " Long ago " — " Somewhere, not here " — that is preface enough for the most improbable story, — it receives belief or make- believe simply because it is very interesting — becau^ the animals speak and behave like people, and everything else happens topsy-turvy in a wonderful manner, and there is no lack of bloodshed and indecency. If the story is not " very interesting," i.e. not marvellous, gruesome, indecent, it does not carry belief Ijor make-believe, and is not interesting at all. The attitude of make-believe, which I have mentionecl, is worth the careful attention of the psychologist. This is not the place to analyse it.^ I will only say that it seems to me likely that it is very often the attitude of the primitive story-teller and his audience. The story may be very interesting to its teller and audience without being believed. This is as true, I take it, of a grotesque Zulu tale as of a modern novel written with due regard to probability or a jeu d' esprit like Alice in Wonderland. But if the story is very interesting, there will always be make-believe * I hope that I may be pardoned for introducing two words which are not in Liddell and Scott, but seem to be justified, in the sense in which I use them, by Aristotle's άνθρωπολόΎο^ {Ε. Ν. iv. 3. 31)= "fond of personal talk." 2 Coleridge, referring to Lyrical Ballads, speaks of "that willing suspension of disbelief for the moment, which constitutes poetic faith." INTEODUCTION 7 at least, and often serious, deliberate make-believe. It is in "Ή the spirit of this serious make-believe that not only the little girl talks about her dolls, but we ourselves read our Dante, or make pilgrimages to places associated v^ith the events of great fiction. The adventures of Kobinson Crusoe and the journey of Dr. Johnson are followed with little difference in our sense of actuality. The topography of the Inferno and that of the Koman Forum are approached in much the same spirit by the interested student in each case. These instances from civilised experience may serve to show how vague the line must be dividing belief from make-believe in the mind of primitive man with his turbulent feelings and vivid imagination controlled by no uniform standard of ascertained fact.^ His tendency is to believe whatever he tells and is told. That he sometimes stops short of belief at make-believe is, after all, a small matter. At any rate, we may be sure that Nature in this case, as in all other cases, does nothing that is superfluous — ovhev ττοιεΐ irepuepyov ovBe μάτην ή φύσις. If make-believe serve Nature's "purpose" as well as belief, which is more difficult, she will take care that her protego stops at make-believe. Certain stories, we assume, have to be wonderful or horrid up to a certain pitch, in order to give full expression and relief to feeling and imagination at a certain stage of development ; and the belief without which these necessary stories could not maintain themselves at all, we further assume, will be that which comes easiest, i.e. make-believe. It is plain that in proportion as stories are more extravagantly wonderful or horrid, the more likely is make- believe to be the attitude of tellers and hearers ; and that, where this is the attitude, stories are likely to go on becoming more and more extravagantly wonderful or horrid. / This is one tendency which, however, is met by another." When a wonderful story is often told and becomes very / familiar, it comes to be believed more seriously ; and, in proper- j tion as it is believed more seriously, it tends to disembarrass itself more and more of the wilder improbabilities which pleased when the attitude towards it was still that of make-believe. An im- ^ Professor Tyler {Primitive Culture, i. 284) describes **u usual state of the imagination among ancient and savage peoples" as "intermediate between the conditions of a healthy prosaic modern citizen and a raving fanatic or a patient in a fever-ward." * 8 THE MYTHS OF PLATO promptu 8tx)ry full of extravagant improbability and, it may be, of revolting indecency is told about some one. When and if that some one afterwards comes to be regarded, it may be on the sole authority of this story itself, as a hero or god of the race, those who revere him become ashamed of the old story about him. They rationalise and moralise it, either leaving out the improb- abilities and indecencies, and retaining the parts that are probable and proper; or allegorising it,i.e. showing that the improbabilities and indecencies are not to be regarded as historical facts, but to be interpreted as figures of some philosophic or scientific or religious doctrine favoured by the interpreters. Thus make- believe accumulates material for the " higher criticism." ^ΚνθρωττοΧο'^ία καν ZwoXoyia — " about people and animals " — is a sufficient account of what story-telling always is and why it is interesting. 1. Sometimes the story is about adventures and doings which happened once upon a time, and left no results to en- hance the interest which belongs to it intrinsically as a story about people and animals. Such a story may be called " Simply Anthropological and Zoological." A very large elephant came and said, "Whose are those re- markably beautiful children 1 " The child replied, " Unanana- bosele's." The elephant asked a second time, " Whose are those remarkably beautiful children ? " The child replied, " Unanana- bosele's." The elephant said, " She built in the road on purpose, trusting to self-confidence and superior power." He swallowed them both, and left the little child. The elephant then went away. In the afternoon the mother came and said, " Where are the children 1 " The little girl said, " They have been taken away by an elephant with one tusk." Unanana-bosele said, "Where did he put them ? " The little girl replied, " He ate them." Unanana- bosele said, " Are they dead ? " The little girl replied, " No, I do not know." They retired to rest. In the morning she ground much maize, and put it into a large pot with amasi, and set out, carrying a knife in her hand. She came to the place where there was an antelope ; she said, " Mother, mother, point out for me the elephant which has eaten my children ; she has one tusk." The antelope said, " You will go till you come to a place where the trees are very high and where the stones are white." She went on. She came to the place where was the leopard; she said INTRODUCTION 9 *' Mother, mother, point out for me the elephant which has eaten my children." The leopard replied, "You will go on and on, and come to the place where the trees are high and where the stones are white." She went on, passing all animals, all saying the same. When she was still at a great distance she saw some very high trees, and white stones below them. She saw the elephant lying under the trees. She went on ; when she came to the elephant she stood still and said, "Mother, mother, point out for me the elephant which has eaten my children." The elephant replied, " You will go on and on, and come to where the trees are high and where the stones are white." The woman merely stood still, and asked again saying, "Mother, mother, point out for me the elephant which has eaten my children." The elephant again told her just to pass onward. But the woman, seeing that it was the very elephant she was seeking, and that she was deceiving her by telling her to go forward, said a third time, " Mother, mother, point out for me the elephant which has eaten my children." The elephant seized her and swallowed her too. When she reached the elephant's stomach, she saw large forests, and great rivers, and many high lands ; on one side there were many rocks ; and there were many people who had built their villages there ; and many dogs and many cattle ; all was there inside the elephant ; she saw, too, her own children sitting there. She gave them amasi, and asked them what they ate before she came. They said, " We have eaten nothing, we merely lay down." She said, " Why did you not roast this flesh ? " They said, " If we eat this beast, will it not kill us 1 " She said, " No ; it will itself die ; you will not die." She kindled a great fire. She cut the liver, and roasted it and ate with her children. They cut also the flesh and roasted and ate. All the people which were there wondered, saying, "Oh, forsooth, are they eating, whilst we have remained without eating any- thing 1 " The woman said, " Yes, yes. The elephant can be eaten." All the people cut and ate. And the elephant told the other beasts, saying, " From the time I swallowed the woman I have been ill ; there has been a pain in my stomach." The other animals said, "It may be, chief, it arises because there are now so many people in your stomach." And it came to pass after a long time that the elephant died. The woman divided the elephant with a knife, cutting through a rib with an axe. A cow came out and said, " Moo, moo, we at length see the country." A goat came out and said, "Mey, mey, at length we see the country." A dog came out and said, " At length we see the country." And the people came out laughing and saying, " At length we tee the country." They made the woman 10 THE MYTHS OF PLATO presents; some gave her cattle, some goats, and some sheep. She set out with her children, being very rich. She went home rejoicing because she had come back with her children. On her arrival her little girl was there ; she rejoiced, because she Λvas thinking that her mother was dead.^ 2. Sometimes the story is about doings and adventures which produced interesting results which remain, and are explained by means of these doings and adventures — as when the shape of a hill is explained by the action of some giant or wizard — " He cleft the Eildon Hills in three." This is the Aetiological Story. It is not only interesting as a piece of simple anthropology, — every story must have that intrinsic interest, — but it satisfies what may be called the " scientific curiosity " — the desire to know the causes of things. It sets forth the cause. To the class of Aetiological Stories belong those myths in I which the creation of the heavens and earth as one whole is set forth — the so-called Cosmological Myths ; also myths which set forth the creation "of man, and the origin of his faculties and virtues ; also Foundation Myths describing the origin of society and of particular nations and cities, as well as myths describing the invention of the arts and their instruments ; and myths — a large and important section — explaining the origin of ritual practices — the so-called Cultus Myths ; and lastly, myths explaining topographical features and the peculiarities of animals and plants. The " scientific " curiosity which inspires these Aetio- logical Stories is not idle. Curiosity, indeed, is never idle. " To know the cause " is matter of much practical concern to the savage as well as to the civilised man. If one knows the cause one can control the effect. For example, to heal a wound made by iron one must know the story of the origin of iron. That story duly recited becomes the charm which will heal the wound.^ Many Aetiological Myths doubtless have their rise in the practice of magijc. Let me illustrate the Aetiological Myth by giving examples of its principal varieties, beginning with a Cosmological Myth 1 Nursei-y Tales, Traditions, and Histories of the Zulus, Callaway, 1868, vol. i. pp. 332 ff. 2 See infra, pp. 204 flF., where the Finnish Story of the Origin of Iron is given. INTEODUCTION 11 — the " Story of the Children of Heaven and Earth," written down by Sir George Grey among the Maoris.^ From Rangi, the Heaven, and Papa, the Earth, it is said, sprang all men and things; but sky and earth clave together, and darkness rested upon them and the beings they had begotten, till at last their children took counsel whether they should rend apart their parents or slay them. Then Tane-mahuta, father of forests, said to his five great brethren, " It is better to rend them apart, and let the heaven stand far above us, and the earth lie under our feet. Let the sky become as a stranger to us, but the earth remain close to us as our nursing mother." So Kongo -ma-tane, god and father of the cultivated food of man, rose and strove to separate the heaven and the earth ; he struggled, but in vain ; and vain, too, were the efforts of Tangaroa, father of fish and reptiles, and of Haumia-tikitiki, father of wild-growing food, and of Tu- matauenga, god and father of fierce men. Then slow uprises Tane-mahuta, god and father of forests, and wrestles with his parents, striving to part them with his hands and arms. " Lo, he pauses ; his head is now firmly planted on his mother the earth, his feet he raises up and rests against his father the skies, he strains his back and limbs with mighty efiOrt. Now are rent apart Rangi and Papa, and with cries and groans of woe they shriek aloud. . . . But Tane-mahuta pauses not ; far, far beneath him he presses down the earth ; far, far above him he thrusts up the sky." But Tawhiri-ma-tea, father of winds and storms, had never consented that his mother should be torn from her lord, and now there arose in his breast a fierce desire to war against his brethren. So the Storm-god rose and followed his father to the realms above, hurrying to the sheltered hollows of the boundless skies, to hide and cling and nestle there. Then came forth his progeny, the mighty winds, the fierce squalls, the clouds dense, dark, fiery, wildly drifting, wildly bursting ; and in the midst their father rushed upon his foe. Tane-mahuta and his giant forests stood unconscious and unsuspecting when the raging hurricane burst on them, snapping the mighty trees across, leaving trunks and branches rent and torn upon the ground for the insect and the grub to prey on. Then the father of storms swooped down to lash the waters into billows Λvhose summits rose hke clifi's, till Tangaroa, god of ocean and father of all that dwell therein, fled afi'righted through his seas. His children, Ika-tere, the father of fish, and Tu-te-wehiwehi, the father of reptiles, ^ I give this myth as it is quoted from Grey's Polynesian Mythology (p. 1, ff.) by'Prof. Tylor {Prim. Cult. i. 290 fF.). Mr A. Lang compares this myth, and others like it found in Ii^jiia and China, with the Greek myth of the mutila- tion of Uranus by Cronus {Custom and Myth, " The Myth of Cronus "). 12 THE MYTHS OF PLATO sought where they might escape for safety; the father of fish cried, "Ho, ho, let us all escape to the sea;" but the father of reptiles shouted in answer, " Nay, nay, let us rather fly inland," and so these creatures separated, for while the fish fled into the sea, the reptiles sought safety in the forests and scrubs. But the sea-god Tangaroa, furious that his children the reptiles should have deserted him, has ever since waged war on his brother Tane, who gave them shelter in his woods. Tane attacks him in return, supplying the off'spring of his brother Tu-matauenga, father of fierce men, with canoes and spears and fish-hooks made from his trees, and with nets woven from his fibrous plants, that they may destroy withal the fish, the Sea-god's children ; and the Sea-god turns in wrath upon the Forest-god, overwhelms his canoes with the surges of the sea, sweeps with floods his trees and houses into the boundless ocean. Next the god of storms pushed on to attack his brothers, the gods and progenitors of the tilled field and the wild; but Papa, the Earth, caught them up and hid them, and so safely were these her children concealed by their mother that the Storm-god sought for them in vain. So he fell upon the last of his brothers, the father of fierce men, but him he could not even shake, though he put forth all his strength. What cared Tu-matauenga for his brother's wrath ? He it was who had planned the destruction of their parents, and had shown himself brave and fierce in war; his brethren had yielded before the tremendous onset of the Storm-god and his progeny ; the Forest- god and his off'spring had been broken and torn in pieces ; the Sea-god and his children had fled to the depths of the ocean or the recesses of the shore ; the gods of food had been in safe hiding ; but man still stood erect and unshaken upon the bosom of his mother Earth, and at last the hearts of the Heaven and the Storm became tranquil, and their passion was assuaged. But now Tu-matauenga, father of fierce men, took thought how he might be avenged upon his brethren who had left him unaided to stand against the god of storms. He twisted nooses of the leaves of the whanake tree, and the birds and beasts, children of Tane the Forest-god, fell before him ; he netted nets from the flax-plant, and dragged ashore the fish, the children of Tangaroa the Sea -god ; he found in their hiding-place underground the children of Rongo-ma-tane, the sweet potato and all cultivated food, and the children of Haumia-tikitiki, the fern-root and all wild- growing food ; he dug them up and let them wither in the sun. Yet, though he overcame his four brothers, and they became his food, over the fifth he could not prevail, and Tawhiri-ma-tea, the Storm-god, still ever attacks him in tempest and hurricane, striving to destroy him both by sea and land. It was the bursting forth INTEODUCTIOISr 13 of the Storm -god's wrath against his brethren that caused the dry land to disappear beneath the waters : the beings of ancient days who thus submerged the land were Terrible-rain, Long-continued- rain, Fierce -hailstorms, and their progeny were Mist, and Heavy- dew, and Light-dew ; and thus but little of the dry land was left standing above the sea. Then clear light increased in the world, and the beings who had been hidden between Eangi and Papa before they were parted now multiplied upon the earth. " Up to this time the vast Heaven has still ever remained separated from his spouse the Earth. Yet their mutual love still continues : the soft warm sighs of her loving bosom still ever rise up to him ascending from the woody mountains and valleys, and men call these mists ; and the vast Heaven, as he mourns through the long nights his separation from his beloved, drops frequent tears upon her bosom, and men seeing these term them dewdrops." Another important variety of the Aetiological Myth — the Cultus Myth — is well illustrated by Grote in the follow- ing passage : ^ — It was the practice to offer to the gods in sacrifice the bones of the victim only, enclosed in fat ; how did this practice arise 1 The author of the Hesiodic Theogony has a story which explains it.2 Prometheus tricked Zeus into an imprudent choice, at the period when the gods and mortal men first came to an arrangement about privileges and duties (in Mekong). Prometheus, the tutelary representative of man, divided a large steer into two portions ; on the one side he placed the flesh and guts, folded up in the omentum and covered over with the skin ; on the other he put the bones enveloped in fat. He then invited Zeus to determine which of the two portions the gods would prefer to receive from mankind. Zeus " with both hands " decided for and took the white fat, but was highly incensed on finding that he had got nothing at the bottom except the bones. Nevertheless the choice of the gods was now irrevocably made ; they were not entitled to any portion of the sacrificed animal beyond the bones and the white fat; and the standing practice is thus plausibly explained. I select this as one amongst a thousand instances to illustrate the genesis of legend out of religious practices. In the belief of the people, the event narrated in the legend was the real producing cause of the practice ; but when we come to apply a sound criticism, we are compelled to treat the event as existing only in its narrative legend, and the legend itself as having been» in the greater number ^ Grote's History of Greece, part i. chap. i. 2^esiod, Theog. 550-557. U THE MYTHS OF PLATO of cases, engendered by the practice,— thus reversing the supposed order of production.^ Let me complete my illustration of the Aetiological Myth by giving the pretty Japanese story which accounts for the physiological effect produced by tea : — It is Daruna whom legend credits with the origin of tea. Before he went off into his present trance he made another effort at permanent contemplation, and had failed through falling asleep at the end of the ninth year. When he awoke he was so vexed at his eyelids for their drooping that he cut them off. No sooner had they fallen to the ground than, lo ! they took root, sprouted, and sent forth leaves. As the old monk looked in wonder, a disciple of Buddha appeared and told him to breAv the leaves of the new shrub and then drink thereof. Daruna plucked the leaves, which now all the world knows as tea, did as the vision commanded him to do, and has not slept a minute since.^ 3. From the Simply Anthropological Story and from the Aetiological Story it is convenient to distinguish a third kind of story, the Eschatological Story. Here the teller and his audience are not concerned with the adventures and doings of people once upon a time, long ago, but with adventures and doings which they themselves must take part in aft er death, like all who have gone before them. It is not to mere love of " personal talk " or to mere " scientific curiosity " that the Eschatological Story appeals, but to man's wonder, and fear, and hope with regard to death. This seems to make a great difference, and to justify us in putting the Eschatological Myths in a class by themselves. Where men fear and hope, they tend to believe strongly ; and if ritual practice is associ- ated with their fear and hope^ more strongly. Hence we find that Eschatological Myths as a class have more actuality, more consistency and sobriety, and more dignity, than other 1 The reader who wishes to pursue the subject of the Cultus Myth maj' consult Miss Harrison's Mythology and Monwnunts of Ancient Athens, pp. xxvi. tf., where he will find a very interesting treatment of the story of the birth of Erichthonios "as an instance of aetiological myth-making of a special kind, of a legend that has arisen out of a ritual practice, the original meaning of which had become obscured"; also Robertson Smith's Religion of the Semites, pp. 20 ff"., where the rule is laid down that "in the study of ancient religions we must begin, not with Myth but with ritual and traditional usage" ; cf. p. ]6 — "The antique religions had for the most part no creed ; they consisted entirely of institutions and practices." 2 The Heart of Japan, by C. L. Brownell (1902), p. 197. INTKODUCTION 15 myths, in proportion as the belief given is, for these reasons, stronger. If make-believe is enough for other myths, Eschato- logical Myths demand genuine belief, and easily get it from primitive man. It is in no spirit of make-believe that he performs the rites for the departed, which he knows will be performed one day for himself, when he shall have gone to the other world of which the stories tell. It is not always easy to assign a story to its class. The cause of something that attracts notice may be found in some- thing done by somebody in the course of adventures which have already been recounted as being in themselves interest- ing. A story which started as " Simply Anthropological," being told from pure love of άνθρωττοΚοψα, may be annexed by the scientific imagination and become Aetiological. And, again, a story which started as Aetiological may easily forget its original scientific inspiration and become a piece of simple ανθρωπολογία. Lastly, the interest of Eschatology — of talk about man's latter end — is so peculiar and engrossing that it tends to compel into its service Simply Anthropological and Aetiological Stories already in existence. The Fhaedrus Myth may be mentioned as showing this tendency at work. We have seen that in form every story of the dream- world, to whichever of the three classes it belongs, is anthropo- logical and zoological ; that it is about the adventures and doings of people and animals — men and men-like beasts and V "^^ gods; and that it is intrinsically interesting as a story, and ^<^<^^ ^ receives belief, or, at any rate, make-believe. "We must now _ V"^^' ^ add" thatit has no moral — i.e. the teller and his hearers do no t } t hink of anything but the story itse lf. This is the criterion ^ - ^yth as distinguished from Allegory or Parable : Myth h as no moral or other meaning in the minds of those who make it, and of those for whom it is made. It is a later ag e w hich reads other meaning into it, when the improbability and indecency of stories told by savage men provoke the rationalising work of those who are unwilling to give up the stories entirely, but cannot receiΛ^e them as they stand. The stories which seem to need this work most, and on which it is most effectually done, are apt to perish under the treatment which they receive. Becoming transparent allegories or ful- filled prophecies, they «cease to be interesting, and are soon r 16 THE MYTHS OF PLATO r \ forgotten. But there stand out among the myths of the world some which rationalism has not been able to destroy or even impair. These, we may be sure, were the creations, not of ordinary story-tellers, but of "'divine poets" and "inspired prophets" — of genius, using, indeed, material supplied by ordinary story-tellers, but transforming it in the use.^ Such myths — chiefly Eschatological Myths, created and originally received in the spirit of genuine belief, not of make-believe — yield precious fruit to interpretation. But the interpretation of a masterpiece of imagination, to be fruitful, must be " psychological." The revival, in aify shape, must be eschewed of that now formally discredited method which treated a masterpiece of creative imagination as an allegory by which the accepted dogma of the day might be supported, or as a prediction to be fulfilled, if not already fulfilled, in some particular event of history. Fruitful interpretation of a masterpiece of creative imagination will consist in showing the mind of its maker, and in so placing his creation before our own minds by means of some accompaniment or rendering — some parallel corroborative appeal to imagination and feeling — that it does for us in our age what it did for him in his age, making us pause in the midst of our workaday life, as he paused in the midst of his, filled With admiration and deep muse, to hear Of things so high and strange. Th e allegorical interpretation of old myth s (which were made, it is hardly necessary to say, without thought of the doctrine got out of them by the interpretation) dou btless sug- gest ed the deliberate making of allegorical tale s and parables. When their makers are men of genius, these tales are often myths as well as allegories and parables. Such are Plato's 'ave and Bunyan's Pilgrim's Progress, which I shall consider later with reference to this point.'^ Aesop's Fables, again, though retaining much of the * •' ΛΥβ must not be astonished if we come across myths which surprise us by their ingenious direction, or even by their profound philosophy. This is often the character of spontaneous products of the human mind. . . . The human mind, when it works thus spontaneously, is a philosopher just as the bee is a iraathematician." — Reville, Prolegomenes de VUistoire des Heligi&ns, Eng. Transl »y Squire, p. 112. f > ε> ^ See infra, "Excursus on Allegory," pp. 230 flF. ys' INTEODUCTION 17 "anthropological and zoological" interest which belongs to the African Beast-tale on which they were modelled, were doubtless, for the most part, deliberately composed for the sake of their morals or applications. As the Beast-tale is rewritten " with a purpose " in Aesop's Fables, so in the moral zoology of Physiologus even "The Natural History of Animals" is rewritten and turned into allegory.-^ The following, about the Lion, based on Physiologus, occurs in a British Museum Bestiary (Codd. Eeg. 2 C. xii.) quoted by Mann in his instructive work, der Bestiaire Divin des Guillaume le Clerc (p. 37): — " De natura leonis, hestiarum seu animalium regis. Etenim Jacob benedicens filium suum Judam ait (Gen. 49. 9) : ' Catulus leonis Judas filius mens, quis suscitabit eum ? ' Fisiologus dicit tres naturales habere leonem. " Prima : ambulat in montibus, et si contigerit, ut queratur a venatoribus, venit odor venatoris et de cauda sua post tergum cooperit vestigia sua quocumque ierit, ut secutus venator per vestigia eius non inveniat cubile ejus, et capiat eum. Sic et Salvator Noster 'spiritualis leo de tribu Juda, radix Jesse, filius David' (Apoc. δ. 5), missus a superno patre, cooperuit intelligentibus vestigia deitatis sue. Et hoc est : factus est cum angelis angelus, cum archangelis archangelus, cum thronis thronus, cum potestatibus potestas, donee descendit in uterum virginis, ut salvaret hoc quod erraverat humanum genus. Ex hoc ignorantes eum ascendentem ad patrem hi qui sursum erant angeli, dicebant ad eos qui cum Domino ascendebant (Ps. 24. 8 f.): 'Quis est iste rex glorie ? ' Kesponderunt illi : ' Dominus virtutum ipse est rex glorie.' ^ Physiologus, 6 φνσιο\^ο$, is a work, in its original Greek form, compiled at Alexandria towards the end of the second century, consisting of chapters, in each of which an animal, real or fabulous, (or a precious stone) is first described in the manner of natural history (or rather, as if in that manner), and then pre- sented as a type of Christian doctrine and life. After being translated into Latin, Physiologus spread over the whole West, and versions of it were made everywhere in the vulgar tongues — in Anglo-Saxon, Old English, Old High German, Flemish, Icelandic, Proven9al, Old French, and Italian. In the East, too, it appeared in Syrian, Armenian, Arabic, Ethiopic, and Slavonic versions. After the Bible it was probably the most popular book throughout the Middle Age. Examples of it — the so-called Bestiaries — are to be found in all the libraries of Europe. See der Bestiaire Divin des Guillaume le Clerc {Franzosische Studieuy 1888), by Max Friedr. Mann, pp. 17 ff.; Pitra, Spicilegium Solesmense, 1855, t. iii. pp. xlvii. if. ; Carus^ Gesch. d. Zoologie, pp. 108 fi". ; and article, Physiologus, by Prof. J. P. N. Land, in Encycl. Brit. C 18 THE MYTHS OF PLATO "(Secunda natura.) Cum dormierit, oculi eius vigilant, aperti enim sunt, sicut in Canticis Canticorum testatur spon- SU8 dicens (5. 2) : ' Ego dormio et cor meum vigilat.' Etenim corporaliter Dominus meus obdormiens in cruce et sepultus, deitas eius vigilabat. 'Ecce non dormiet qui custodit Israel' (Ps. 121. 4). " (Tercia natura.) Cum leena parit catulum, generat eum mortuum et custodit eum mortuum tribus diebus, donee veniens pater eius die tercio insufflet in faciem ejus et vivi- ficet eum. Sic omnipotens pater Dominum Nostrum Jesum Christum filium suum tercia die suscitavit a mortuis, dicente Jacob (4 Mos. 24. 9): 'Dormitabit tanquam leo, et sicut catulus leonis. Quis suscitabit eum ? ' " In Physiologus " The Natural History of Animals " has a double character : it is not only a narrative of " facts/' but, at the same time, a divinely appointed, as it were dramatic, representation of doctrine for the benefit of man. S imilarly, " Old Testament History " is regarded by Ph ilo a nd his school as at once a chronicle of actual events, an d a g reat allegorical representation of doctrine in which ev ents ar e figures or symbols of philosophic tr uths — and that, in the intention of God, not merely in the mind of the interpreter. I shall have occasion to return to this strange school of allegory ; meanwhile the purpose of this introductory refer- ence to the subject will be sufficiently served if I quote in passing, without comment, a classical passage in which one of the great masters of Myth distinguishes between the literal and the allegorical or mystical truth of events recorded in history. In the letter to Kan Grande,^ which is really a preface to the Coriimedia, Dante writes as follows, §§ 7, 8 : — "Ad evidentiam itaque dicendorum, sciendum est quod istius operis [the Commedia] non est simplex sensus, immo dici potest polysemum, hoc est plurium sensuum ; nam alius sensus est qui habetur per literam, alius est qui habetur per significata per literam. j^Et primus dicitur liter alis, secundus vero allegoricus, sive mysticusA Qui modus tractandi, ut 1 Dean Church {Davie and other Essays, p. 103, ed. 1897) refers to this letter as one "which, if in its present form of doubtful authenticity, without any question represents Dante's sentiments, and the substance of which is incor- porated in one of the earliest writings on the poem, Boccaccio's commentary. " INTEODUCTION 19 melius pateat, potest considerari in his versibus : * In exitu Israel de Aegypto, domus Jacob de populo barbaro, facta est Judaea sanctificatio eius, Israel potestas eius.' Nam uliteram solam inspiciamus, significatur nobis exitus filiorum Israel de Aegjpto, tempore Moysis ; si aUegoriam, nobis significatur nostra redemptio facta per Christum ; si moralem sensum, significatur nobis conversio animae de luctu et miseria peccati ad statum gratiae ; si anagogicum, significatur exitus animae sanctae ab huius corruptionis servitute ad aeternae Gloriae libertatem. Et quamquam isti sensus mystici varus appel- lentur nominibus, generaliter omnes dici possunt allegorici, quum sint a literali sive historiali diversi. . . . His visis, manifestum est quod duplex oportet esse subjectum, circa quod currant alterni sensus. Et ideo videndum est de subjecto huius operis, prout ad literam accipitur ; deinde de subjecto, prout allegorice sententiatur. Est ergo subjectum totius operis, literaliter tantum accepti, ' status animarum post mortem simpliciter sumptus.' Nam de illo et circa ilium totius operis versatur processus. Si vero accipiatur opus allegorice, subjectum est ' homo, prout merendo et demerendo per arbitrii ' libertatem Justitiae praemianti aut punienti obnoxius est." ■" In the Gonvivio (ii. 1 and 13) the four "senses" are dis tinguished exactly as in the Letter. Of the moral and anagogic senses he says (ii. 1, p. 252, 1. 42, Ox£ ed.) : "The third sense is called moral ; it is that which readers ought attentively to note, as they go through writings, for their own profit and that of their disciples ; as it may be noted in the Gospel, when Christ went up into the Mount to be 1 Gebhart {Vltalie Mystique, pp. 318 if.), referring to this Letter, remarks that the literal interpretation of the Divina Commedia represents the traditional belief of the mediaeval church, the other interpretations represent Dante's own personal religion. M. Gebhart's analysis of Dante's "personal religion " is very instructive : " Le dernier mot de sa croyance, cette 'religion du oceur' qu'il a nommee dans le Convito, est au vingt-quatrieme chant du Paradis, et c'est k Saint- Pierre lui-meme qu'il en fait la confession. II est revenu au symbole tros simple de Saint -Paul, la foi, I'espdrance et I'amour ; pour lui comme pour I'apotre, la foi elle-meme n'est, au fond, que I'esp^rance, fides sperandarum substantia rerum. . . . Pour lui, le peche supreme, celui qu'il punit d'un mepris ecrasant, ce n'est ni I'h^resie, ni I'incredulite, qu'il a raontrees, par le dedain meme et la jfigure altiέre des damnes, superieures h, I'enfer ; c'est la vilta, le renoncement timide au devoir actif, au dovouement, h. la vie, la lacheto du pape Celestin, Che fece per viltate il gran rifiuto." 2Q THE MYTHS OF PLATO transfigured, that of the twelve apostles he took with him the three ; wherein morally we may understand, that in matters of the greatest secrecy we ought to have few companions. " The fourth sense is called anagogic, that is, above sense ; and this is when a writing is expounded spiritually which, even in its literal sense, by the matters signified, sets forth the high things of glory everlasting : as may be seen in that Song of the Prophet which says that in the coming out of the people of Israel from Egypt, Judah was made holy and free. Which, although it is plainly true according to the letter, is ■ not less true as understood spiritually : that is, the Soul, in coming out from sin, is made holy and free." The rest of the chapter {Conv. ii. 1) dwells on the point, which Dante evidently considers of great importance, that the ^^literal sense must always be understood before we go on to jseek out the other senses. The reversal of this order is, indeed, impossible, for the other senses are contained in the literal sense, which is their envelope ; and besides, the literal sense is " better known to us," as the Philosopher says in the First Book of the Physics ; and not to begin with it would be irrational — contrary to the natural order. 3. Plato's Myths distinguished from Allegories. To WHAT Experience, or " Part of the Soul," does the Platonic Myth appeal ? Plato, 'We know from the BeyuUic'^ and Phaedr us?' de precated the allegorical interpretation of Myths, and his own Myths, we assume, are not to be taken as allegories ; \ but rather as representing, in the action of the Platonic Drama, J natural products of that dream-world consciousness which \ encompasses the field of ordinary wide-awake consciousness in •. educated minds as well as in the minds of children and ' primitive men. In appealing to the dream-world consciousness of his r eaders by a brilliant literary representation of its na tural p roducts — those stories which primitive men cannot lea ve un- ^ Rep. 378 D. ^ Phaedrus, 229 b-e, and see infra, pp. 231 if. INTEODUCTION ^^ 21 t old, and philosophers love to hear well tolcy — Plato appeal s t o an experience which is more solid than ^e might in fer f rom the mere content of the μυθοΚο^'ια in which it finds expre s- sion. He appeals to that major part of man's nature which is not articulate and logical, but feels, and wills, and acts — to that part which cannot explain what a thing is, or how it happens, but feels that the thing is good or bad, and expresses itself, not scientifically in " existential " or " theoretic judgments," but practically in "value-judgments" — or rather" value-feelings." Man was, with the brute, practical, and had struck the roots of his being deep into the world of reality, ages before he began to be scientific, and to think about the " values " which he felt. And long before he began to think about the "values" which he felt, feeling had taken into its service his imagination with its whole apparatus of phantasms — waking dreams and sleep-dreams — and made them its exponents. In appealing , thro ugh the recital of dreams, to that major part of us which fe els " values," which wills and ^cts, Plato indeed goes down to the bedrock of human nature , ^^t that depth man is more at one with Universal Nature- — more in her secret, as it were — than he is at the level of his " higher " faculties, where he lives in a conceptual world of his own making which he is always endeavouring to " think." And after all, however high he may rise as "thinker," it is only of "values" that he genuinely thinks ; and the ground of all " values " — the Value of Life itself — was apprehended before the dawn of thinking, and is still apprehended independently of thinking. It is good, Plato will have us believe, to appeal sometimes from the world of the senses and scientific understanding, which is " too much with us," to this deep-lying part of human nature, as to an oracle. The responses of the oracle are not given in articulate language which the scientific understanding can interpret; they come as dreams, and must be received as dreams, without thought of doctrinal interpretation.; Their ultimate meaning is the " feeling " which fills us in beholding them ; and when we wake from them, we see our daily concerns and all things temporal with purged eyes. [T'his effect which Plato produces by the Myth in the Dialogue is, it is hardly necessary to say, produced, in various 1 ό φι\6μυθθ5 φίλόσοφόί ttos έστιν. — Arist. Met. Λ 2, 982 b 18. 22 THE MYTHS OF PLATO degrees, by Nature herself, without the aid of literary or other artj The sense of " might, majesty and dominion " which comes over us as we look into the depths of the starry sky,^ the sense of our own short time passing, passing, with which we see the lilacs bloom again — these, and many like them, are I natural experiences which closely resemble the effect produced 1 in the reader's mind by Plato's art. When these natural moods are experienced, we feel " That which was, and is, and ever shall be " overshadowing us ; and famjKar things — the stars, and the lilac bloom — become suddenly strange and wonderful, for our eyes are opened to see that they declare its presence. It is such moods of feeling in his cultivated reader that Plato induces, satisfies, and regulates, by Myths which set forth God, Soul, and Cosmos, in vision. I The essential charm of these Myths is that of Poetry I generally, whether the theme of a poem be expressly eschato- logical and religious, like that of the Divina Commedia, or of some other kind, for example, like that of the Fairy Queene, or like that of a love song. The essential charm of all /Poetry, for the sake of which in the last resort it exists, lies ^ in its power of inducing, satisfying, and regulating what may I l^be called Transcendental Feeling, especially that form of ^ 1^ /Transcendental Feeling which manifests itself as solemn sense / I of Timeless Being — of " That which was, and is, and ever shall rbe," overshadowing us with its presence. Where this power is absent from a piece — be it an epic, or a lyric, or a play, or a poem of observation and reflection — there is no Poetry ; only, at best, readable verse, — an exhibition of wit and worldly wisdom, of interesting " anthropology," of pleasing sound, — all either helpful or necessary, in their several places, for the . production of the milieu in which poetic effect is felt, but ^jione of them forming part of that effect itself. Sometimes the power of calling up Transcendental Feeling seems to be exercised at no point or points which can be definitely indicated in the course of a poem ; this is notably the case where the form of the poem is dramatic, i.e. where all turns on our grasping " one complete action." Sometimes " a lonely word " ^ Coleridge says {Anima Poetae, from unpublished note-books of S. T. Coleridge, edited by E. H. Coleridge, 1895 ; p. 125), " Deep sky is, of all visual impressions, the nearest akin to a feeling. It is more a feeling than a sight, or rather, it is the melting away and entire union of feeling and sight ! " INTKODUCTION 2$ makes the great difference. At any rate, elaborate dream-f consciousness apparatus, such as we find employed in the Platonic Myths, in the Divina Commedia, and in poems like Endymion and Hyperion, is not essential to the full exercise of the power of Poetry. Some common scene is simply pictured for the mind's eye ; some place haunted by memories and emotions is pictured for the heart ; a face declaring some mood is framed in circumstances which match it and its mood ; some fantasia of sound or colour fills eye or ear ; some sudden stroke of personification amazes us ; there is perhaps nothing more than the turn of a phrase or the use of a word or the falling of a cadence — and straightway all is done that the most elaborate and sustained employment of mythological apparatus could do — we are away in the dream-world; and when we presently return, we are haunted by the feeling that I we have "seen the mysteries " — by that Transcendental Feeling which Dante finds language to express in the twenty-fifth sonnet of the Vita Nuova} and in the last canto of the Paradiso : — abbondante grazia, ond' io presunsi Ficcar lo viso per la luce eterna Tanto, che la veduta vi consunsi ! Nel siio profondo vidi che s' interna, Legato con amore in un volume, Cio che per V universo si squaderna ; ^ Sustanzia ed accidenti e lor costume, Quasi conflati insieme per tal modo, Che cio ch' io dico e un semplice lume. La forma universal di questo nodo Credo ch' io vidi, perche piu di largo^> Dicendo questo, mi sento ch' io godo. Un punto solo m' e maggior letargo, Clie venticinque secoli alia impresa, Che fe' Nettuno ammirar Γ ombra d' Argo.^ Let me give some examples from the Poets of their | employment of the means which I have just now mentioned. Λ common scene is simply pictured for the mind's eye : — Sole listener, Duddon ! to the breeze that played ΛVith thy clear voice, I caught the fitful sound 1 See infra^. 38, where this sonnet is quoted. * Paradiso, xxxiii. 82-9. 24 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Wafted o'er sullen moss and craggy mound — Unfruitful solitudes, that seem'd to upbraid The sun in heaven ! — but now, to form a shade For thee, green alders have together wound Their foliage ; ashes flung their arms around ; And birch-trees risen in silver colonnade. And thou hast also tempted here to rise. Mid sheltering pines, this cottage rude and grey ; Whose ruddy children, by the mother's eyes Carelessly watched, sport through the summer day, Thy pleased associates : — light as endless May On infant bosoms lonely Nature lies. Sometimes, again, the scene is fiduredfor the heart rather than for the eye — we look upon a place haunted, for the Poet, and after him for ourselves, by memories and emotions : — Row us out from Desenzano, to your Sirmione row ! So they row'd, and'there we landed — " venusta Sirmio ! " There to me thro' all the groves of olive in the summer glow. There beneath the Roman ruin where the purple flowers grow, Came that " Ave atque Vale " of the Poet's hopeless woe, Tenderest of Roman poets nineteen hundred years ago, " Frater Ave atque Vale " — as we wander'd to and fro Gazing at the Lydian laughter of the Garda Lake below Sweet Catullus's all-but-island, olive -silvery Sirmio ! Again, it is a face that we see declaring some mood, and framed in circumstan^ces which match it and its mood : — At eve a dry cicala sung. There came a sound as of the sea ; Backward the lattice-blind she flung. And lean'd upon the balcony. There all in spaces rosy-bright Large Hesper glitter'd on her tears. And deepening thro' the silent spheres Heaven over Heaven rose the night. Again, some fantasia of sound or light fills ear or eye, — of sound, like this : — Sometimes a-dropping from the sky I heard the skylark sing ; Sometimes all little birds that are. How they seemed to fill the sea and air With their sweet jargoning ! INTEODUCTION 25 And now 'twas like all instruments, Now like a lonely flute ; And now it is an angel's song, That makes the heavens be mute. Or like this :■ The silver sounding instruments did meet With the base murmur of the Water's fall : The Water's fall with difference discrete. Now soft, now loud, unto the Wind did call : The gentle warbling Wind low answered to all. Of sound and light together, like this : — A sunny shaft did I behold. From sky to earth it slanted : And poised therein a bird so bold — Sweet bird, thou wert enchanted ! He sank, he rose, he twinkled, he trolled Within that shaft of sunny mist ; His eyes of fire, his beak of gold, All else of amethyst ! And thus he sang: " Adieu ! adieu ! Love's dreams prove seldom true. The blossoms, they make no delay : The sparkling dewdrops will not stay. Sweet month of May, We must away ; Far, far away ! To-day! to-day!" Again, it is some stroke of personification that fills us with amazement — where we thought that Nature was most solitary, see I some one is present ! The nightingale, up-perched high. And cloister'd among cool and bunched leaves — She sings but to her love, nor e'er conceives How tiptoe Night holds back her dark-grey hood. Or, it may be, the presence is that of Great Nature herself — and she feels what we feel, and knows what we know : — fair is Love's first hope to gentle mind ! As Eve's first star thro' fleecy cloudlet peeping ; And sweeter than the gentle south-west wind. O'er willowy meads and shadowed waters creeping, And Ceres' golden fields ; — the sultry hind Meets it with bft)w uplift, and stays his reaping. L 26 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Lastly, it is perhaps hut the turn of a phrase or the fall of a cadence that touches the heart : — I heard a linnet courting His lady in the spring ; His mates were idly sporting, Nor stayed to hear him sing His song of love : — I fear my speech distorting His tender love. So much by way of illustrating poetic effect produced, as only the inspired poet knows how to produce it, by very simple means. I venture to ask the student of Plato to believe with me that the effect produced, in the passages just quoted, by these simple means, does not differ in kind from that produced by the use of elaborate apparatus in the Myths*^ / with which this work is concerned. The effect is always the induction of the dream-consciousness, with its atmosphere of solemn feeling spreading out into the waking consciousness Ljvhich follows. It will be well, however, not to confine ourselves to the examples given, but to quote some other examples from Poetry, in which this effect is produced in a way more closely parallel to that in which it is produced in the Platonic Myths. I will therefore ask the reader to submit himself to an experi- ment : first, to take the three following passages — all I relating to Death — and carefully reading and re-reading them, allow the effect of them to grow upon him ; and then, turning to Plato's Eschatological Myths in the Fhaedo, Gorgias, and Republic, and reading them in the same way, to ask himself whether or no he has had a foretaste of their effect in the effect produced by these other pieces. I venture to think that the more we habituate ourselves to the influence of the Poets the better are we likely to receive the message of the Prophets. Deh peregriniji che pensosi andate Forse di cosa che non V e presente, Venite voi di si lontana gente, Come alia vista voi ne dimostrate ? Che non piangete, quando voi passate ^ La Vita Nuova, § 41, Sonetto 24. INTEODUCTION 27 Per lo siio mezzo la citt4 dolente, Come quelle persone, che neente Par che intendesser la sua gravitate. Se voi restate, per volerla udire, Certo lo core ne' sospir mi dice, Che lagrimando n' uscirete pui. EDa ha perduta la sua Beatrice ; Ε le parole, ch' uom di lei puo dire, Hanno virtu di far piangere altrui. To that high Capital,^ where Kingly Death Keeps his pale court in beauty and decay, He came : and bought, with price of purest breath, A grave among the eternal. — Come away ! Haste, while the vault of blue Italian day Is yet his fitting charnel-roof ! Avhile still He lies, as if in dewy sleep he lay ; Awake him not ! surely he takes his fill Of deep and liquid rest, forgetful of all ill. He will awake no more — oh, never more ! Within the twilight chamber spreads apace The shadow of white Death, and at the door Invisible Corruption waits to trace His extreme way to her dim dwelling-place ; The eternal Hunger sits, but pity and awe Soothe her pale rage, nor dares she to deface So fair a prey, till darkness and the law Of change shall o'er his sleep the mortal curtain draw. Oh, weep for Adonais I — The quick Dreams, The passion-winged Ministers of thought. Who were his flocks, whom near the living streams Of his young spirit he fed, and whom he taught The love which was its music, wander not, — Wander no more from kindling brain to brain. But droop there, whence they sprung ; and mourn their lot Eound the cold heart, where, after their sweet pain, They ne'er will gather strength, nor find a home again. And one with trembling hand clasps his cold head. And fans him with her moonlight wings, and cries : " Our love, our hope, our sorrow, is not dead ; See, on the silken fringe of his faint eyes, Like dew upon a sleeping flower, there lies A tear some Dream has loosened from his brain." * Shelley, Adonais. 28 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Lost Angel of a ruined Paradise ! She knew not 'twas her own ; as with no stain She faded, like a cloud which had outwept its rain. One from a lucid urn of starry dew Washed his light limbs, as if embalming them ; Another clipt her profuse locks, and threw The wreath upon him, like an anadem. Which frozen tears instead of pearls begem ; Another in her wilful grief would break Her bow and winged reeds, as if to stem A greater loss with one which was more weak ; And dull the barbed fire against his frozen cheek. Another Splendour on his mouth alit. That mouth whence it was wont to draw the breath Which gave it strength to pierce the guarded wit, And pass into the panting heart beneath With lightning and with music : the damp death Quenched its caress upon his icy lips ; And, as a dying meteor stains a Avreath Of moonlight vapour, which the cold night clips, It flushed through his pale limbs, and passed to its eclipse. And others came, — Desires and Adorations, Winged Persuasions, and veiled Destinies, Splendours, and Glooms, and glimmering Incarnations Of hopes and fears, and twilight Phantasies ; And Sorrow, with her family of Sighs, And Pleasure, blind with tears, led by the gleam Of her own dying smile instead of eyes, Came in slow pomp ; — the moving pomp might seem Like pageantry of mist on an autumnal stream. All he had loved and moulded into thought From shape, and hue, and odour, and sweet sound, Lamented Adonais. Morning sought Her eastern watch-tower, and her hair unbound. Wet with the tears which should adorn the ground, Dimmed the aerial eyes that kindle day ; Afar the melancholy thunder moaned, Pale Ocean in unquiet slumber lay. And the wild winds flew around, sobbing in their dismay. Lost Echo sits amid the voiceless mountains. And feeds her grief with his remembered lay, And will no more reply to winds or fountains. Or amorous birds perched on the young green spray, Or herdsman's horn, or bell at closing day ; Since she can mimic not his lips, more dear INTRODUCTION 29 Than those for whose disdain she pined away Into a shadow of all sounds : — a drear Murmur, between their songs, is all the woodmen hear. Alas ! that all we loved of him should be, But for our grief, as if it had not been, And grief itself be mortal ! Woe is me ! Whence are we, and why are we ? of what scene The actors or spectators ? Great and mean Meet massed in death, who lends what life must borrow. As long as skies are blue, and fields are green, Evening must usher night, night urge the morrow. Month follow month with woe, and year wake year to sorrow. Peace, peace ! he is not dead, he doth not sleep — He hath awakened from the dream of life — 'Tis we, who, lost in stormy visions, keep With phantoms an unprofitable strife, And in mad trance strike with our spirit's knife Invulnerable nothings — We decay Like corpses in a charnel ; fear and grief Convulse us and consume us day by day, And cold hopes swarm like worms within our living clay. He has outsoared the shadow of our night ; Envy and calumny, and hate and pain. And that unrest which men miscall delight, Can touch him not and torture not again ; From the contagion of the world's slow stain He is secure, and now can never mourn A heart grown cold, a head grown grey in vain ; Nor, when the spirit's self has ceased to burn, With sparkless ashes load an unlamented urn. He is made one with Nature : there is heard His voice in all her music, from the moan Of thunder to the song of night's sweet bird ; He is a presence to be felt and known In darkness and in light, from herb and stone. Spreading itself where'er that Power may move Which has withdrawn his being to its own ; Which wields the world with never-wearied love, Sustains it from beiffeath, and kindles it above. 30 THE MYTHS OF PLATO He is a portion of the loveliness AVhich once he made more lovely : he doth bear His part, while the one Spirit's plastic stress Sweeps through the dull dense world, compelling there All new successions to the forms they wear ; Torturing the unwilling dross that checks its flight To its own likeness, as each mass may bear ; And bursting in its beauty and its might From trees and beasts and men into the Heaven's light. The splendours of the firmament of time May be eclipsed, but are extinguished not ; Like stars to their appointed height they climb. And death is a low mist which cannot blot The brightness it may veil. When lofty thought Lifts a young heart above its mortal lair. And love and life contend in it, for what Shall be its earthly doom, the dead live there, And move like winds of light on dark and stormy air. The inheritors of unfulfilled renown Rose from their thrones, built beyond mortal thought, Far in the Unapparent. Chatterton Rose pale, his solemn agony had not Yet faded from him ; Sidney, as he fought. And as he fell, and as he lived and loved. Sublimely mild, a Spirit without spot, Arose ; and Lucan, by his death approved : Oblivion, as they rose, shrank like a thing reproved. And many more, whose names on Earth are dark. But whose transmitted efiluence cannot die So long as fire outlives the parent spark. Rose, robed in dazzling immortality. " Thou art become as one of us," they cry ; "It was for thee yon kingless sphere has long Swung blind in unascended majesty, Silent alone amid a Heaven of Song. Assume thy winged throne, thou Vesper of our throng ! " When lilacs last in the dooryard bloom'd,^ And the great star early droop'd in the western sky in the night, I moum'd, and yet shall mourn with ever-returning spring. Ever-returning spring, trinity sure to me you bring, Lilac blooming perennial, and drooping star in the west. And thought of him I love. Walt Whitman, Leaves of Grass {Memories of President Lincoln). INTEODUCTION 31 From this bush in the dooryard, With delicate-colour'd blossoms and heart-shaped leaves of rich green, A sprig with its flower I break. In the swamp in secluded recesses, A shy and hidden bird is warbling a song — Song of the bleeding throat. Death's outlet song of life. Over the breast of the spring, the land, amid cities. Amid lanes and through old woods, where lately the violets peep'd from the ground, spotting the grey debris, Amid the grass in the fields each side of the lanes, passing the endless Passing the yellow-spear'd wheat, every grain from its shroud in the dark-brown fields uprisen. Passing the apple-tree blows of white and pink in the orchards. Carrying a corpse to where it shall rest in the grave, Night and day journeys a coffin. Coffin that passes through lanes and streets, Through day and night with the great cloud darkening the land, With the pomp of the inloop'd flags, with the cities drap'd in black, With the show of the States themselves as of crape-veil'd women standing. With the countless torches lit, with the silent sea of faces and the bared heads. With the tolling tolling bells' perpetual clang, Here, coffin that slowly passes, I give you my sprig of lilac. Sing on there in the swamj), Ο singer bashful and tender, I hear your notes, I hear your call, I hear, I come presently, I understand you. But a moment I linger, for the lustrous star has detain'd me. The star, my departing comrade, holds and detains me. how shall I warble myself for the dead one there I loVd ? And how shall I deck my song for the large sweet soul that has gone ? And what shall my perfumg be for the grave of him I love ? 32 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Sea-winds blown from East and West, Blown from the Eastern sea and blown from the Western sea, . on the prairies meeting . . . — With these and the breath of my chant, I'll perfume the grave of him I love. ******* ******* Sing on, sing on, you grey-brown bird, Sing from the swamps, the recesses, pour your chant from the bushes, Limitless out of the dusk, out of the cedars and pines. Sing on, dearest brother, warble your reedy song. Loud human song, with voice of uttermost woe. liquid and free and tender ! wild and loose to my soul — wondrous singer ! You only I hear — yet the star holds me (but will soon depart), Yet the lilac with the mastering odour holds me. With the knowledge of death as walking one side of me, And the thought of death close- walking the other side of me. And I in the middle as with companions, and as holding the hands of companions, I fled forth to the hiding receiving night that talks not, Down to the shores of the water, the path by the swamp in the dimness. To the solemn shadowy cedars and ghostly pines so still. And the singer so shy to the rest received me, The grey-brown bird I know receiv'd us comrades three. And he sang the carol of death, and a verse for him I love. And the charm of the carol rapt me, As I held as if by their hands my comrades in the night, And the voice of my spirit tallied the song of the bird. Come^ lovely and soothing death, Undulate round the world, serenely arriving, arriving, In the day, in the night, to all, to each, Sooner or later delicate death Dark mother always gliding near with soft feet. Have none chanted for thee a chant of fullest welcome ? Then I chant it for thee, I glorify thee above all, I bring thee a song that when thou must indeed come, come unfalteringly. From me to thee glad serenades. Dances for thee I propose saluting thee, adornments and f eastings for thee, And the sights of the open landscape and the high-spread sky are fitting, And life and the fields, and the huge and thoughtful night — INTKODUCTION 33 The night in silence under many a star, The ocean shore and the husky whispering wave whose voice I know, And the soul turning to thee, vast and well-veiVd death. And the body gratefully nestling close to thee. Over the tree-tops I float thee a song. Over the rising and sinking waves, over the myriad fields and the prairies wide. Over the dense-packed cities all and the teeming wharves and ways, I float this carol toith joy, with joy to thee, death. The conclusion which follows, as it seems to me, from examination of what one experiences in perusing great Poetry — of which the three widely dissimilar pieces which I have quoted at length are eminent examples — is that the essentiaT) charm of Poetry — that for the sake of which, in the last» resort^ it exists — lies in its ^wer of inducing, in certain care- fully chosen circumstances, that mode of Transcendental '^^^ 6^%\y^ Feeling which is experienced as solemn sense of the over- shadmaiiHg presence of " That which was, and is, and ever shall be." \The Poet, always by means of Kepresentations — images, μψημοΗ-α — products of the dream-consciousness in himself, and often with the aid of Ehythm and Melody which call up certain shadowy Feelings, strange, in their shadowy form, to ordinary consciousness, induces in his patient the dream-con- sciousness in which such Eepresentations and Feelings are at home.\ But the dream-consciousness induced in the patient by the imagery and melody of the Poet lasts only for a moment. The effect of even the most sustained Poetry is a succession of occasional lapses into the state of dream-con- sciousness, each one of which occurs suddenly and lasts but for a moment, in the midst of an otherwise continuous waking consciousness which is concerned, in a matter-of-fact way, with "what the poem is about," and "how the poet manages his theme," and a hundred other things. It is at the moment of waking from one of these lapses into the dream-world that the solemn sense of the immediate presence of " That which was, and is, and ever shall be " is experienced — at the moment when one sees, in the world of wide-awake consciousness, the image, or hears the melody, which one saw or heard only a moment ago — or, was it not ages ago ? — in the dream-world : — • D / 34 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Un punto solo m' e maggior letargo, Che venticinque secoli alia impresa, Che fe' Nettuno ammirar Γ ombra d' Argo. It is thus, as these sudden lapses, each followed immediately by waking and amazement, succeed one another, it may be, at long intervals, in a poem, that the power of its Poetry grows upon us. It is essential to our experiencing the power of Poetry that there should be intervals, and intervals of con- siderable length, between the lapses. 0?he sense of having seen or heard things belonging to a world in which " Time is not " needs for its immediate realisation the presence, in the world of waking consciousness, of things which shall " remind " us of the things of that other world in which " Time is not " — without such things to "remind" us, there would be no " recollection " of our visit to the world in which " Time is not.'^ ^he poet's image, therefore, which began by throwing us into the dream-state, must persist in the state of waking consciousness to which we are now returned, and there, as we look at it in the light of common day, amaze us by its " resem- blance " to an archetype seen in the world in which " Time is not." And its persistence in the world of waking con- sciousness can be guaranteed only by a more or less wide context addressed to our ordinary faculties — to the senses and understanding — and to our ordinary sentiments. Over this matter-of-fact context, however, the amazement produced in us when we perceive that the image, or other product of the Poet's dream-consciousness, which just now set us, too, a-dreaming, is double — is something both in the world without Time, and in this temporal world — casts a glamour for a while. Then the glamour fades away, and we find ourselves accompanying the Poet through the every-day world ; and it may be in accordance with the secret scheme which he is carrying out that we are kept in this every-day world for a long while, in order that we may be taken the more by surprise when suddenly, as we journey, the light from heaven shines round about us. "Whatever specific import," says Coleridge,^ " we attach to the word poetry, there will be found involved in it, as a necessary consequence, that a poem of any length neither can be, nor ought to be, all poetry." ^ Biog. Lit. ch. xiv. INTEODUCTION 35 The chief end of Poetry, then, is to induce Transcendental \ Feeling — experienced as solemn sense of the immediate pre- sence of " That which was, and is, and ever shall be " — in the Poet's patient, by throwing him suddenly, for a moment, into the state of dream-consciousness, out of a waking conscious- ness which the Poet supplies with objects of interest; the sudden lapse being effected in the patient by the communica- tion to him of images and other products of the Poet's dream- consciousness, through the medium of language generally, but not always, distinguished from that of ordinary communication ;. by rhythm and melody. *m^ But the same result — the induction of the same form of Transcendental Feeling — is produced, not only by the means which the Poet employs, — dream-imagery communicated by language generally, but not necessarily, rhythmic and melodious, — but also by different artistic means — by the means which the Painter and the Musician respectively employ ; indeed — and this seems to me to be a matter of first- rate importance for the Theory of Poetry — it is sometimes « produced by mere Nature herself without the aid of any art, and by events as they happen in one's life, and, above all, by scenes and situations and persons remembered out of the days of childhood and youth. " "We are always dreaming," Kenan (I think) says somewhere, " of faces we knew when we were eighteen." In this connection let me ask the reader to consider Wordsworth's lines beginning — ^ There was a Boy ; ye knew him weU, ye cliifs And islands of Winander — It seems to me that the mere scene described in these lines — a scene to which it would not be difficult to find parallels in any one's experience — is, entirely apart from the language in which it is described, and simply as a picture in the mind of the person who remembers it, and in the minds of those to whom he describes it, the milieu in which true poetic effect is experienced. As I write this, I can hardly recall a line of Wordsworth's description ; but the picture which the read- ing of his description has left in my mind is distinct ; and it is in dwelling on the picture that I feel the poetic effect — as it was, I am convinced, in dwelling on the picture, before 36 THE MYTHS OF PLATO he composed a line of the poem, that the poet himself ex- perienced the feeling which he has communicated to me. And the re-reading of such a poem is more likely to impair than to enhance the feeling experienced by one who has once Lfor all pictured the scene. The more I read and re-read the works of the great poets, and the more I study the writings of those who have some Theory of Poetry to set forth, the more am I convinced that the question WTiat is Poetry ? can be properly answered only I if we make WTiat it does take precedence of ITow it does it. The result produced by Poetry — identical, I hold, with that produced by the other fine arts, and even sometimes by the mere contemplation of Nature and Human Life — is the one thing of prime importance to be kept always in view, but is too often lost sight of in the examination of the means by which Poetry produces it, as distinguished from those by which, say. Painting produces it. Much that is now being written on the Theory of Poetry leaves one with the impres- sion that the writers regard the end of Poetry as something sui generis — in fact, something not to be distinguished from the employment of technique peculiar to Poetry among the fine arts.^ I shall return to this point afterwards. } In making the essential charm of Poetry — that for the sake of which, in the last resort, it exists — lie in its power of inducing, in certain carefully chosen circumstances, and so of regulating, Transcendental Feeling experienced as solemn sense of " That which was, and is, andj ever shall be " over- shadowing us with its presence, I must Vot be taken to mean that there is no Poetry where this seritee is not induced as a distinct ecstatic experience. Great i^oetry, just in those places where it is at its very greatest, indeed shows its peculiar power not otherwise than by inducing such distinct ecstatic experience ; but generally, poetic effect — not the very greatest, but yet indisputably poetic effect — is produced by something less — by the presence of this form of Tran- \ scendental Feeling in a merely nascent state, — ^just a little more, and it would be there distinctly ; as it is, there is a 1 Mr. Courthope {Life in Poetry, p. 78) says : "Poetry lies in the invention of the right metrical form — be it epic, dramatic, lyric, or satiric — for the expres- sion of some idea universally interesting to the imagination." And cf. p. 63. INTKODUCTION 37 " magic/' as we say, in the picture called up, or the natural sentiment aroused, which fills us with wondering surmise — of what, we know not. This "magic" may be illustrated perhaps most instructively from lyric poetry, and there, from the lightest variety of the kind, from the simple love song^ The pictures and sentiments suggested in the love song, regarded in themselves, belong to an experience which seems to be, more than any other, realised fully in the present, without intrusion of past or future to overcast its blue day with shadow. But look at these natural pictures and senti- ments not directly, but as reflected in the magic mirror of Poetry ! They are still radiant in the light of their Present —for let us think now only of the happy love song, not of the love song which is an elegy — they are still in their happy Present ; but they are not of it — they have become something " rich and strange." No words can describe the change which they have suffered ; it is only to be felt — as in such lines as these : — Das Mddchen. Ich hab' ilin geselien ! Wie ist mir geschehen ? Ο himmlisclier Blick ! Er kommt mir entgegen : Ich weiche verlegen, Ich schwanke zuriick. Ich irre, ich traume ! Ihr Felsen, ihr Baume, Verbergt meine Freude, Verberget mein Gluck ! ^ Der Jiingling. Hier muss ich sie finden ! Ich sah sie verschwinden, Ihr folgte mein BHck. Sie kam mir entgegen ; Dann trat sie verlegen Und schamroth zuriick. Ist 's Hoifnung, sind 's Traume ? Ihr Felsen, ihr Baume, Entdeckt mir die Liebste, Entdeckt mir mein Gluck ! The magic of such lines as these is due, I cannot doubt, to the immediate presence of some great mass of feeling which 38 THE MYTHS OF PLATO they rouse, and, at the same time, hold in check, behind our mere understanding of their literal meaning. The pictures and sentiments conjured up, simple and familiar though they are, have yet that about them which I can only compare with the mysterious quality of those indifferent things which are so carefully noticed, and those trifling thoughts which are so seriously dwelt upon, in an hour of great trouble. T^ But the Transcendental Feeling which, being pent up behind our understanding of their literal meaning, makes the magic of such lines, may burst through the iridescent film which contains it. We have an example of this in the trans- figuration of the Earthly into the Heavenly Beatrice. The Transcendental Feeling latent behind our understanding of the praise of Beatrice in the earlier sonnets and canzoni of Lthe Vita Nuova emerges as a distinct experience when we assist at her praise in the Paradiso. Contrast the eleventh sonnet of the Vita Nuova with the twenty-fifth, which, with its commentary, is a prelude to the Paradiso. The eleventh sonnet of the Vita Nuova ends : — Aiutatemi, donne, a farle onore. Ogni dolcezza, ogni pensiero umile Nasce nel core a clii parlar la sente ; Ond' e beato chi prima la vide. Quel ch.' ella par quand' un poco sorride, Non si puo dicer, ne tener a mente, Si h nuovo miracolo gentile. Here it is the magic of the lines which is all in all. Now let us turn to the twenty-fifth, the last, sonnet of the Vita Nuova, and to the words after it ending the book with the promise of more worthy praise — more worthy, because offered with a deeper sense of the encompassing presence of " That which was, and is, and ever shall be " : — Oltre la spera, che piu larga gira, Passa il sospiro ch' esce del mio core : Intelligenza nuova, che Γ Amore Piangendo mette in lui, pur su lo tira. Quand' egli h giunto Ik, doV el desira, Vede una donna, che riceve onore, Ε luce si, che per lo suo splendore Lo peregrino spirito la mira. Vedela tal, che, quand ο il mi ridice, INTRODUCTION 39 Ιο non Ιο intendo, si parla sottile Al cor dolente, che lo far parlare. So io ch' el parla di quella gentile, Perocche spesso ricorda Beatrice, Sicch' io lo intendo ben, donne mie care. " Straightway after this sonnet was writ, there appeared unto me a marvellous vision, wherein I beheld things which made me determine not to say more concerning this Blessed One until I should be able to speak of her more worthily. To this end I studied with all diligence, as she knoweth well. Wherefore, if it shall be the pleasure of Him through Whom all things live that my life endure for some years, I hope to say of her that which never before hath been said of woman. And then may it please Him Who is Lord of Courtesy that my Soul may go to behold the glory of her Lady, to wit, of that Blessed Beatrice, who in glory doth gaze upon the face of Him Who is blessed for evermore." 4. Transcendental "Feeling, the Experience to which the Platonic Myth and all other Forms of Poetry APPEAL, explained GENETICALLY. . Transcendental Feeling I would explain genetically (as f every mood, whatever its present value may be, — that is another matter, — ought to be explained) as an effect produced within consciousness (and, in the form in which Poetry is chiefly concerned with Transcendental Feeling, within the dream-consciousness) by the persistence in us of that primeval ι condition from which we are sprung, when Life was still as I sound asleep as Death, and there was no Time yet. That we \ should fall for a while, now and then, from our waking, time- marking life, into the timeless slumber of this primeval life is easy to understand ; for the principle solely operative in that primeval life is indeed the fundamental principle of our nature, being that " Vegetative Part of the Soul " which made from the first, and still silently makes, the assumption on which our whole rational life of conduct and science rests — the assumption that Life is worth living. No arguments which Keason can brftig for, or against, this ultimate truth 40 THE MYTHS OF PLATO are relevant; for Eeason cannot stir without assuming the very thing which these arguments seek to prove or to disprove. " Live thy life " is the Categorical Imperative addressed by f Nature to each one of her creatures according to its kind. ^^^^ At the bottom of the scale of Life the Imperative is r*^ obeyed silently, in timeless sleep, as by the trees of the tropical forest : — The fair and stately things. Impassive as departed kings, All still in the wood's stillness stood, And dumb. The rooted multitude Nodded and brooded, bloomed and dreamed, Unmeaning, undivined. It seemed No other art, no hope, they knew. Than clutch the earth and seek the blue. My eyes were touched with sight. I saw the wood for what it was : The lost and the victorious cause. The deadly battle pitched in line, Saw weapons cross and shine : Silent defeat, silent assault, A battle and a burial vault. Green conquerors from overhead Bestrode the bodies of their dead : The Caesars of the sylvan field. Unused to fail, foredoomed to yield : For in the groins of branches, lo ! The cancers of the orchid grow.^ When to the " Vegetative " the " Sensitive " Soul is first added, the Imperative is obeyed by creatures which, experi- encing only isolated feelings, and retaining no traces of them in memory, stiU live a timeless life, without sense of past or future, and consequently without sense of selfhood. Then, with Memory, there comes, in the higher animals, some dim sense of a Self dating back and prospecting for- ward. Time begins to be. But the sense of its passage brings no melancholy ; for its end in death is not yet anticipated by reflective thought. Man's anticipation of death would oppress his life with ^ Songs of Travel, R. L. Stevenson : "The Woodman." INTEODUCTION 41 insupportable melancholy, were it not that current employ- ments, especially those which are spoken of as duties, are so engrossing — that is, I would explain, were it not that his conscious life feels down with its roots into that " Part of the Soul " which, without sense of past or future or self, silently holds on to Life, in the implicit faith that it is worth living — that there is a Cosmos in which it is good to be. As it is, there is still room enough for melancholy in his hours of ease and leisure. If comfort comes to him in such hours, it is not from his thinking out some solution of his melancholy, but from his putting by thought, and sinking, alone, or led by some μυστa'γωybς του βίου, for a while into the sleep of that fundamental " Part of the Soul." When^he wakes into daily life again, it is with the elementary faith of this ParFof his Soul newly confirmed in his heart ; and he is ready, in the strength of it, to defy all that seems to give it the lie in the world of the senses and scientific understanding. Sometimes the very melancholy, which overclouds him at the thought of death, is transfigured, in the glow of this faith, into an exultant resignation — " I shall pass, but He abideth for ever." Sometimes, and more often, the faith does not merely trans- figure, but dispels, the melancholy, and fills his heart with sweet hope, which fancy renders into dreams of personalj immortality. To sum up in effect what I have said about Transcendental Peeling : it is feeling which i ndeed appears in our ordinary object -distinguishing, time -marking consciousness, but does not originate in it^ ϊ^ is to be traced to the influence on consciousness of the presence in us of that " Part of the Soul" which holds on, in timeless sleep, to Life as worth) living. Hence Transcendental Feeling is at once the solemn sense of Timeless Being — of " That which was, and is, and ever shall be " overshadowing us — and the conviction that Life is good. In the first-mentioned phase Transcendental Feeling appears as an abnormal experience of our conscious life, as a well-marked ecstatic state ;•^ in its other phase — as con- viction that Life is good — Transcendental Feeling may be said to be a normal experience of our conscious life : it is not 1 See Paradiso, xxxiii. 82βθ6, quoted svpra, p. 23, and Vita Nuova, Sonnet XXV., quoted supra, p. 38. 42 THE MYTHS OF PLATO an experience occasionally cropping up alongside of other experiences, but a feeling which accompanies all the experi- ences of our conscious life — that " sweet hope," ^Χυκβΐα ελτΓΐ?,^ in the strength of which we take the trouble to seek after the particular achievements which make up the waking life of conduct and science. Such feeling, though normal, is rightly called Transcendental," because it is not one of the effects, but the condition, of our entering upon and persever- ing in that course of endeavour which makes experience. 5. The Platonic Myth rouses and regulates Tran- scendental Feeling by (1) Imaginative Kepresen- TATiON OF Ideas of Eeason, and (2) Imaginative Deduction of Categories of the Understanding AND Moral Virtues. I have offered these remarks about Transcendental Feeling in order to preface a general statement which I now venture to make about the Platonic Myths — that they are Dreams expressive of Transcendental Feeling, told in such a manner and such a context that the telling of them regulates, for the service of conduct and science, the feeling expressed. How then are conduct and science served by such regulation of Transcendental Feeling ? In the wide-awake life of conduct and science. Under- standing, left to itself, claims to be the measure of truth ; Sense, to be the criterion of good and bad. Transcendental Feeling, welling up from another " Part of the Soul," whispers to Understanding and Sense that they are leaving out some- thing. What ? Nothing less than the secret plan of the Universe. And what is that secret plan ? The other " Part of the Soul " indeed comprehends it in silence as it is,^ but can explain it to the Understanding only in the symbolical language of the interpreter, Imagination — in Vision.* In the Platonic Myth we assist at a Vision in which the ^ y\vKe?a ol καρδίαν άτάΧλοισα Ύηροτρόφοί σνναορύ έ\ττί$, Λ μάΧίστα θνατων ΊΓολύστροψον Ύνώμαν κνβερνφ. — Pindar, quoted Eep. 331 Α. ^ As distinguished from "Empirical Feeling" ; see infra, p. 389. ' Plotinus, Enn. iii. 8. 4, and see infra, p. 45. * Tim. 71 D, E. The liver, the organ of Imagination, is a μαντεΐορ. INTEODUCTION 43 wide-awake life of our ordinary experiences and doings is seen as an act in a vast drama of the creation and con- summation of all things. The habitudes and faculties of our moral and intellectual constitution, which determine a priori our experiences and doings in this wide-awake life, are them- selves clearly seen to be determined by causes which, in turn, are clearly seen to be determined by the Plan of the Universe which the Vision reveals. And more than this, — the Universe, planned as the Vision shows, is the work — albeit accomplished under difficulties — of a wise and good God ; for see how mindful He is of the welfare of man's soul throughout all its wanderings from creation to final purification, as the Vision unfolds them ! We ought, then, to be of good hope, and to use strenuously, in this present life, habitudes and faculties which are so manifestly in accordance with a universal plan so manifestly beneficent. It is as producing this mood in us that the Platonic Myth, Aetiological and Eschatological, regulates Transcendental Feel- ing for the service of conduct and science. In Aetiological | Myth the Categories of the Understanding and the Moral Virtues are deduced from a PlmW^^^ they are represented as parts seen, together with the whole, in a former life, and " remembered " piecemeal in this ; in Aetiological and Eschatological (but chiefly in Eschatological) Μ rth the " Ideas of Eeason," Soul, Cosmos, as completed sy tem of the Good, and God, are set forth for the justification of bhat "sweet hope which guides the wayward thought of mortal mj ,n " — the hope without which we should not take the trouble to enter upon, and persevere in, that struggle after ever fuller comprehension of conditions,-^ ever wider " correspondence with environment," which the habits and faculties of our moral and intellectual structure — the Categories of the Understand- ing and the Moral Virtues — enable us to carry on in detail. At this point, before I go on further to explain Plato's hand- ling of Transcendental Feeling, I will make bold to explain my own metaphysical position. A very few words will suffice. I hold that it is in Transcendental Feeling, manifested * Kant makes " Reason " (i.e. the whole man in opposition to this or that part, e.g. "understanding") the source of "Transcendental Ideas," described as "conceptions of the unconditioned," "conceptions of the totality of the con- ditions of any thing that is given as conditioned." \ 44 THE MYTHS OF PLATO normally as Faith in the Value of Life, and ecstatically as sense of Timeless Being, and not in Thought proceeding by way of speculative construction, that Consciousness comes nearest to the object of Metaphysics, Ultimate Eeality. It is in Transcendental Feeling, not in Thought, that Consciousness comes nearest to Ultimate Eeality, because without that Faith in the Value of Life, which is the normal manifestation of Transcendental Feeling, Thought could not stir. It is Transcendental Feeling that Consciousness is aware of " The Good " — of the Universe as a place in which it is good to be. Transcendental Feeling is thus the heginning of Metaphysics, for Metaphysics cannot make a start without assuming " The Good, or the Universe as a place in which it is good to be " ; but it is also the end of Metaphysics, for Speculative Thought does not really carry us further than the Feeling, which inspired it from the first, has already brought us : we end, as we began, with the Feeling that it is good to be here. To the question, " Why is it good to be here ? " the answers elaborated by Thought are no more really answers than those supplied by the Mythopoeic Fancy inter- preting Transcendental Feeling. When the former have value (and they are sometimes not only without value, but mischievous) they are, like those supplied by the Mythopoeic Fancy, valuable as impressive afi&rmations of the Faith in us, not at all as explanations of its ground. Conceptual solutions of the " problem of the Universe " carry us no further along the pathway to reality than imaginative solutions do. The reason why they are thought to carry us further is that they mimic those conceptual solutions of departmental problems which we are accustomed to accept, and do well to accept, from the positive sciences. Imaginative solutions of the " problem of the Universe " are thought to be as inferior to conceptual solutions as imaginative solutions of departmental problems are to conceptual. The fallacy involved in this analogy is that of supposing that there is a " problem of the Universe" — a difficulty presented which Thought may " solve." The " problem of the Universe " was first pro- pounded, and straightway solved, at the moment when Life began on the earth, — when a living being — as such, from the very first, lacking nothing which is essential to " selfhood " or INTKODUCTION 45 " personality " — first appeared as Mode of the Universe. The " problem of the Universe " is not propounded to Consciousness, and Consciousness cannot solve it. Consciousness can feel that it has been propounded and solved elsewhere, but cannot genuinely think it. It is "propounded" to that on which Consciousness supervenes (and supervenes only because the problem has been already " solved ") — it is propounded to what I would call "selfhood," or "personality," and is ever silently being "understood" and "solved" by that principle, in the continued " vegetative life " of individual and race. And the most trustworthy, or least misleading, report of what the " problem " is, and what its " solution " is, reaches Consciousness through Feeling. Feeling stands nearer than Thought does to that basal self or personality which is, 1 indeed, at once the living " problem of the Universe " and its living " solution." The whole matter is summed up for me in the words of Plotinus, with which I will conclude this statement which I have ventured to make of my metaphysical position : " If a man were to inquire of Nature — ' Wherefore dost thou bring forth creatures ? ' and she were willing to give ear and to answer, she would say — ' Ask me not, but under- stand in silence, even as I am silent.' " ^ In suggesting that the Platonic Myth awakens and regulates Transcendental Feeling (1) by imaginative representa- / tion of Ideas of Eeason, and (2) by imaginative deduction/ of Categories of the Understanding and Moral Virtues, I doj not wish to maintain that the Kantian distinction between Categories of the Understanding and Ideas of Eeason was explicit in Plato's mind. There is plenty of evidence in his writings to show that it was not explicit ; but it is a distinction of vital importance for philosophical thought, and it need not surprise us to find it sometimes implicitly recognised by a thinker of Plato's calibre. At any rate, it is a distinction which the student of Plato's Myths will do well to have explicit in his own mind. Let us remind ourselves, then, of what Kant 1 means by Categories of the Understanding and Ideas of \ Eeason respectively. ^ Plot. Enn. iii. 8. 4, κοΧ cf rt j hh 'αύττ^ρ (ttjv φύσιν) έροιτο rivos ^Ρ€κα irotct, ei του έρωτωντοί έθέΧοι iiraaeiv καΐ \uyuv, etiroi &v' "^χρί}»' μέι/ μη έρωταν, άλλα συνιέναί και αυτόν σιωπτί, uxTTrfp ^7'^ σιωτώ καΐ ούκ ^ΐθίσμαι \ayeiv" 46 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Kant's Categories of the Understanding are certain a ^priori Conceptions, certain Characters of the Mental Structure, without which there could be no " experience " — no " know- ledge " of that which alone is " known," the world of sensible phenomena. These Categories, however, if they are not to remain mere logical abstractions, must be regarded as functions of the Understanding — as active manifestations of the unifying principle of mind or consciousness. As func- tions, the Categories need for their actual manifestation the presence of " sensations." In the absence of sensations they are " empty." They are functions of the mental organism or structure which are called into operation by stimulation from " environment," and that only in schemata or " figurations " involving the " garment " or " vehicle " of Time.^ Thus, the Category of Substance is realised in " the schema of the per- sistent in time " — Something present to sense is perceived as " Substance " persisting in change of " attributes " ; the Category of Cause is realised in " the schema of succession in time," — two sensible phenomena, one of which is antecedent and the other consequent, are conceived as cause and effect — the latter is conceived as following necessarily from the former. " The schemata, then, are the true scientific cate- gories."^ This amounts to saying that the Understanding, if rightly conducted, will never make a transcendental use, but only an empirical use, of any of its a priori principles. These principles can apply only to objects of sense, as con- forming to the universal conditions of a possible experience (phenomena), and never to things as such (noumena), or apart from the manner in which we are capable of perceiving them.^ In contrast to the Categories of the Understanding which are immanent — adequately realised in sense experience; we say, for instance, that this thing present to sense is cause of that other thing — the Ideas of Keason are transcendent: they overleap the limits of all experience — in experience no objects can be presented that are adequate to them. They 1 See Wallace's Kant, p. 172. 2 Wallace's Kant, p. 173. ^ See Kritik d. reinen Vern? pp. 297, 298, 303. A conception is employed transcendentally when it occurs in a proposition regarding things as such or in themselves ; empirically, when the proposition relates merely to phenomena, or objects of a possible experience. INTEODUCTION 47 are defined, generally, as "problematic conceptions of the totality of conditions of anything that is given as con- ditioned " ; or, since the unconditioned alone makes a totality of conditions possible, as " conceptions of the unconditioned, in so far as it contains a ground for the synthesis of the conditioned." ^ There are three Ideas of Keason, products of its activity in " carrying the fragmentary and detailed results of human experience to their rational issues in a postulated totality. . . . These three ideas are the Soul, as the super- sensible substance from which the phenomena of Consciousness are derivative manifestations ; the World [Cosmos, Universe], as ultimate totality of external phenomena; and God, as unity and final spring of all the diversities of existence. The ideas, strictly as ideal, have a legitimate and a necessary place in human thought. They express the unlimited obliga- tion which thought feels laid upon itself to unify the details of observation ; they indicate an anticipated and postulated convergence between the various lines indicated by observation, even though observation may show that the convergence will never visibly be reached; or they are standards and model types towards which experience may, and indeed must, if she is true to the cause of truth, conceive herself boimd to approxi- mate. Such is the function of ideas, as regulative ; they govern and direct the action of intellect in the effort to systematise and centralise knowledge. . . . But the ideas naturally sink into another place in human knowledge. Instead of stimulating research, they become, as Kant once puts it, a cushion for the lazy intellect. Instead of being the ever-unattainable goals of investigation, they play a part in founding the edifice of science. Ceasing to be regulative of research, they come to be constitutive of a pretended know- ledge." 2 The Ideas of Keason, then, are aims, aspirations, ideals ; ι but they have no adequate objects in a possible experi- ence. The three " Sciences " which venture to define objects for them — Eational Psychology, Kational Cosmology, and Theology — are, according to Kant, sham sciences. The Idea of Soul, the absolute or unconditioned unity of the thinking 1 Zriii;5;,2pp.J79, 384 (Prof. Watson's Transl. ). 2 Wafface's Kant, pp. 182, 183. 48 THE MYTHS OF PLATO subject, has no object in possible experience answering to it. "We are making an illegitimate transcendental use of a Category when we conceive the subject of all knowledge as an object under the Category of Substance. Similarly, the ultimate totality of external phenomena — the Cosmos as absolute whole — is not an object of possible experience ; it is not something given in sense, to be brought under Categories or scientific conceptions. Finally, the Idea of God is perverted from its regulative use, when it is made the foundation of a science — Dogmatic Theology — wlfich applies the Categories of Substance, Cause, and the rest, to a Supreme Being, as if He were an object presented in sense experience. To sum up : — The Categories of the Understanding are so many conditions of thought which Human Understanding, constituted as it is, expects to find, and does find, fully satisfied in the details of sensible experience. The Ideas of Reason indicate the presence of a condition of thought which is not satisfied in any particular item of experi- ence. They are aspirations or ideals expressing that nisus after fuller and fuller comprehension of conditions, wider and wider correspondence with environment — in short, that nisus after Life, and faith in it as good, without which man would not will to pursue the experience rendered possible in detail by the Categories. But although there can be no speculative science of objects answering to the Ideas of Eeason, we should come to naught if we did not act as if there were such objects ; and any representation of objects answering to these Ideas which does not invite exposure by pretending to scientific rank is valuable as helping us to " act as if" The objects of these Ideas are objects, not for science, but for faith. When the scientific understanding " proves " that God exists, or that the Soul is immortal, refutation lies near at hand ; but the " as if " of the moral agent rests on a sure foundation.•^ ^ "We have three postulates of practical reason which are closely related to the three Ideas of theoretical reason. These Ideas reason in its theoretical use set before itself as problems to be solved ; but it was unable to supply the solution. Thus, the attempt to prove theoretically the permanence of the thinking subject led only to paralogism ; for it involved a confusion of the subject presupposed in all knowledge of objects, and only in that point of view permanent, with an object known under the Category of Substance. But now we find that a faith of reason in the endless existence of the self-conscious subject is bound up with the possibility of his fulfilling the moral law. Again, the attempt speculatively to determine the world as a system complete in itself landed us in an antinomy INTKODUCTION 49 To return now from Kant to Plato : — Plato's Myths induce and regulate Transcendental Feeling for the service of conducti -s/ and knowledge by setting forth the a yriori conditions of con-i duct and knowledge — that is, (1) by representing certain ideals or presuppositions, in concrete form — the presuppositions of an immortal Soiil, of an intelligible Cosmos, and of a wise and good God — all three being natural expressions of the sweet hope in the faith of which man lives and struggles on and on ; and (2) byjracing to their origin in the wisdom and goodness of God, and the constitution of the Cosmos, certain habitudes or faculties (categories and virtues), belonging to the make of man's intellectual and moral nature, which prescribe the various modes in which he must order in detail the life which his faith or sweet hope impels him to maintain. Myth , not argumentative conversation, is rightly chosen by Plato as the, yehicle_o£.^j!cposition when he deals with a priori conditions of conduct and knowledge, whether they be ideals or faculties. When a man asks himself, as he must, for the reason of the hope in which he struggles on in the ways prescribed by his faculties, he is fain to answer — " Because I am an immortal Soul, created with these faculties by a wise and good God, under whose government I live in a Universe which is His finished work." This answer, according to Plato, as I read him, is the natural and legitimate expression of the " sweet hope . which guides the wayward thought of mortal man " ; and the I expression reacts on — gives strength and steadiness to — that ' which it expresses. It is a " true answer " in the sense that man's life would come to naught if he did not act and think as if it were true. But Soul, Cosmos as completed system of the Good, and God are not particular objects presented, along which we were able to escape only by the distinction of the phenomenal from the intelligible world — a distinction which theoretic reason suggested, but which it could not verify. But now, the moral law forces us to think ourselves as free, and therefore as belonging to an intelligible world which we are further obliged to treat as the reality of which the phenomenal world is the appearance. Lastly, the Absolute Being was to theoretic reason a mere ideal which knowledge could not realise ; but now His existence is certified to us as the necessary condition of the possibility of the object of a Will determined by the moral law. Thus, through practical reason we gain a conviction of the reality of objects corresponding to the three Ideas of Pure Reason. We do not, indeed, acquire what is properly to be called knowledge of these objects. We only change the problematic conception of them into an assertion of their real existence ; but, as we are not able to bring any perception under such Ideas, so we are unable to make any synthetic judgment regarding the objects the existence of which we assert." — Caird's Critical Philosophy of Kant, iif 297. Ε 50 THE MYTHS OF PLATO with other particular objects, in sensible experience. This the Scientific Understanding fails to grasp. When it tries to deal with them — and it is ready enough to make the venture ^ — it must needs envisage them, more suo, as though they were particular objects which could be brought under its Categories in sensible experience. Then the question arises, "Where are they ? " And the answer comes sooner or later, " They are I nowhere to be found." Thus " science " chills the " sweet hope " \ in which man lives, by bringing the natural expression of it vinto discredit. This, I take it, is Plato's reason for employing Myth, rather than the language and method of " science," when he wishes to set forth the a ^m^L ^s it expresses itself in Ideals. In the mise en scdne of the Timaeus or Myth of Er, Soul, Cosmos, and God are presented concretely indeed, but in such visionary form that there is little danger of mistaking them for particulars of sense requiring " scientific explanation." Again, as for the a priori Habitudes or Faculties of man's moral and intellectual structure, whereby he corresponds with his environment in detail — these, too, Plato holds, are to be set forth in Myth ; for they are properly set forth when they are " deduced " — traced to their origin, which is that of the Cosmos — a matter beyond the reach of the Scientific Under- standing. It is in a Myth of Reminiscence, therefore, such as that in the Fhaedrus, that we must take account of the question of " the origin of knowledge " ; in a Myth such as that of the Golden Age in the Laws, of the question of " the origin of society."•^ These and other ultimate "questions of origin," carrying us back as they do to the nature of God and the constitution of the Cosmos, are not for "science." Plato found Myth invested in the minds of his contemporaries with the authority of old tradition and the new charm which Pindar and the tragedians had bestowed upon it ; perhaps, too, if my sugges- tion 2 has any value, he found it associated, in his own mind and the minds of other Socratici viri, with the personal influence of the Master where that influence was most im- ^ The spirit, and much in the detail, of the Cratylus justify the view that Plato approached the question of the "origin of language" too δια μvθo\oyίas. ^ Supra, p. 3. INTRODUCTION 51 pressive and mysterious — he found Myth thus ready to his hand, and he took it up, and used it in an original way for a philosophical purj)ose, and transformed it as the Genius of Sculpture transformed the ξόανα of Daedalus. Further remarks on the a priori in conduct and knowledge as set forth by means of the mythological deduction of Faculties will be best deferred till we come to the Fhaedrus Myth ; but some general observations on the a priori as set forth by means of the mythological representation of Ideals — " forms of hope," ^ " objects of faith " — may be helpful at this introductory stage. Let us then consider broadly, first, Plato's handling of the " Idea of God," and then his handling of the " Idea.. oL-Soul." Consideration of his handling of the " Idea of Cosmos" may well be deferred till we come to the 2\7riaeus. 6. Plato's Treatment of the Idea of God To the religious consciousness, whether showing itself in the faith which " non-religious people " sometimes find privately and cling to in time of trouble, or expressed to the world in the creeds and mythologies of the various religions, the Idea of God is the idea of a Personal God, or, it may be, of personal Gods. The God of the religious consciousness, whatever else he may be, is first of all a separate individual — one among other individuals, human and, it may be, superhuman, to whom he stands in relations by which he is determined or limited. He is Maker, King, Judge, Father, Friend. It may be true that attributes logically inconsistent with his being a finite individual person are ascribed to him in some of the creeds ; but the inconsistency, when perceived, is always so dealt with that the all - important idea of his personality is left with undiminished power. The idea of the separate individuality or personality of the Self is not more essential to the moral consciousness than the idea of the separate individuality or personality of God is to the religious conscious- ness ; and in the religious consciousness, at any rate, both of 1 It never yet did hurt. To lay down Mkelihoods and forms of hope, Henry IV. (Part ii.), i. 3. 52 THE MYTHS OF PLATO these ideas are involved — an individual Self stands in a personal relation to another individual, God.^ But logical thinking — whether in natural science or in metaphysics — when it busies itself, as it is too fond of doing, with the " Idea of God," arrives at a conclusion — this cannot be too plainly stated — flatly opposed to the conviction of the religious consciousness. Aristotle's ivepyeta dvev Βυνάμ€ω<; is not a Person ; nor is Spinoza's Substantia Infinita ; nor is the Absolute of later systems, although its true logical character has sometimes been disguised ; nor is the " Nature " of modern science. Logical or scientific thinking presupposes and makes explicit the idea of an orderly Universe, of an organic whole determining necessarily the behaviour of its parts, of a single system realising itself fully, at every moment and at every place, in events which, for the most part, recur, and recurring retain a uniform character, or only change their character gradually. We should not be here, science assures us — living beings, acting and thinking — if the changes in our environment were catastrophic, not orderly and gradual. But although the Universe must be orderly if we are to live, it does not follow that it is orderly that we may live. Logical or scientific thinking, as such, scouts teleology in that form in which it is cherished by the religious conscious- ness, belief in a Particular Providence, — logical or scientific thinking, as such, that is, when it is not deflected from its path, as it sometimes is, by the attraction of religious conviction, just as the religious consciousness, on the other hand, is sometimes disturbed by science. Teleology, when taken up seriously, not merely played with, is a method which assumes the intentions of a Personal Euler of the Universe, and explains the means which he employs in order to carry out his intentions.^ Logical or scientific thinking, as such, finds it ^ Cf. Hegelianism arui Personality, A. S. Pringle-Pattison, pp. 217-218. 2 In saying that "science" scouts the teleology which recommends itself to the "religious consciousness" I do not think that I contradict the view, so ably enforced by Prof. W. James, that " teleology is the essence of intelligence " — that the translation, in which "science" consists, of the perceptual into the con- ceptual order "always takes place for the sake of some subjective interest, . . . and. the conception with which we handle a bit of sensible experience is really nothing but a teleological instrument. This whole function of coiiceiving, of fixing, and holding-fast to meanings, has no significance apart from the fact that the conceiver is a creature with partial purposes and private ends." — Princ. of Ρη /ch. i. 482. INTKODUCTION 53 inconceivable that the Part — and a Personal God, an individual distinguished from other individuals, is a Part — should thus rule the Whole. If science and the religious consciousness try, as they sometimes do, to come to an understanding with each other on the basis of such a phrase as " Infinite Person " or " Universal Consciousness," the result is only to bring out more clearly, in the self-contradictory phrase, the incompati- bility of their two points of view, and to make the breach, which it is attempted thus to heal, still wider. It is wise to recognise, once for all, that the scientific understanding, work-, ing within its own region, finds no place for a Personal God,( and that the religious consciousness demands a Personal God' — a Part^which rules the Whole. The scientific conception of Whole ruling Parts is, indeed, so distasteful to the religious consciousness that it always leans to Polytheism rather than to Monotheism. That the incompatibility of the scientific conception withy the conviction of the religious consciousness was present to Plato's mind is proved, as it seems to me, by the circumstance| that it is in Myth that he presents the idea of a Personal-' God and the correlate idea of a Personal Immortality of the' Soul. Lest it should be objected that it is " unhistorical " to ascribe to Plato any perception of the issue on which religion and " modern science " are at variance, it may be well to point out that Plato's pupil, Aristotle, was aware of the issue, and faced it with characteristic directness. Any one who reads the Metaphysics, Be Anima, and Ethics in connection will be struck by the way in which the logician gives up, apparently without scruple, the idea of a Personal God, and the correlate idea of the Personal Immortality of the Soul. It may help us to make out what Plato hopes for from presenting these correlate ideas, in Myth, to the adult readers of his Dialogues, if we recall what he lays down in the second book of the BepuUic about the religious instruction of young children, on which all mental and moral education, according to him, is to be founded. The education of children, he tells us, is not to begin with instruction in " facts " or " truths." It is not to begin, as we might say, with the " elementary truths of science " and " facts 54 THE MYTHS OF PLATO r^ca; common life," as learned in the primer. Young children cannot yet understand what is true in fact. We must begin, then, with what is false in fact — with fictions, with stories. Their only faculty is that of being interested in stories. Hence it is all important to have good stories to tell them — to invent Myths with a good tendency. They are to be told what is literally false, in order that they may get hold of what is spiritually true — the great fundamental truth that God is " beneficent " and " truthful " — both adjectives applicable to a person ; and a finite person, for they are to believe that he is the author only of what is good. That God is such a finite person, then, is true, Plato would tell us ; not, indeed, true in the sense in which the description of phenomena or data of experience may be true, but true, as being the only or best possible expression, at least for children, of the maxim or principle of guidance without which human life must come to naught. If children believe that God is the author, not of good only, but of evil also, they will grow up to be discontented and without hope — without faith in the good providence which helps those who help themselves — ready always to blame God or bad luck, rather than themselves, for their troubles and failures. If they do not believe that he is truthful, they will grow up to be careless observers and abstract reasoners, neglecting, as insignificant and " due to accident," those so-called little things which the careful interpreter of nature recognises as important signs and symptoms. They will grow up without the principles on which Conduct and Science respectively depend. On the one hand, they will be without that " hope which guides the wayward thoughts of men" — the faith (which indeed all struggle for existence implies) that honest effort will, on the whole, succeed in attain- ing good; they will believe instead — so far as it is possible for a living being to believe this — that "life is not worth living " ; and so far as they are not, and cannot be, consistent pessimists, they will be selfish, individualistic citizens. On the other hand, if they have not been taught in their childhood to believe that " God is truthful," they will grow up without the first postulate of science — faith in the order and interpretability of the world. In one sentence, — "The Lie in the Soul" — the spirit of pessimism in conduct and INTEODUCTION 55 scepticism in science — will bring to naught all those who have not believed, in their childhood, that God is a Person, good and true. In their childhood : May they, will they, give up afterwards the belief in his Personality when it has done its work? Most of them, continuing to live in " sense and imagina- tion," — albeit, under good guidance, useful lives, — will have no difficulty in retaining the belief of their childhood ; but a few will become so "logical" that they will hardly be able to retain it. It is in relation to the needs of these latter that we ought to consider the Myths setting forth the idea of a Personal God and the correlate idea of Personal Immortality of the Soul, which Plato has put into his Dialogues. In these Myths they have representations of what they once believed as fact without questioning. They see the world of childhood/ — that dream-world which was once so real — put on the stage! for them by a great Maker of Mysteries and Miracles. But why represent it ? That the continuity of their lives may be brought home to them — that they may be led to sympathise with what they were, and, sympathising, to realise that what they now are — is due to what they were. It is because the continuity of life is lost sight of, that religious conviction and scientific thought are brought into opposition. The scientific thinker, looking back over his life, is apt to divide it sharply into the time during which he believed what is not true, and the time during which he has known the truth. Thus to fail in sympathy with his own childhood, and with the happy condition of the majority of men and women, and with the feelings which may yet return to comfort him fwhen the hour of his death draws near, betokens, Plato would isay, a serious flaw in a man's " philosophy of life." The man /abstracts " the p resent time'' from its setting in his whole life. I He plucks from its stem the " knowledge of truth," and thinks lahat it still lives. The "knowledge of truth," Plato would tell us, does not come except to the man whose character has been formed and understanding guided, in childhood and youth, by unquestioning faith in the goodness and truthfulness of a Personal God. And this faith he must reverence all his life 56 THE MYTHS OF PLATO through, looking back to his childhood and forward to his death. To speak of this faith as false, and a thing of the past, is what no Thinker will care to do. The Thinker— "the spectator of all time and all existence "^^does not cut up the organic unity of his life into the abstractions of Past, and Present, and Future — Past which is non-existent. Present which is > mere imaginary point. Future which is non- existent. /His life is all one Present, concrete, continuous, indivisible.^ The man who cuts up life into Past, Present, and Future, does so with the intent of appropriating something for his own private use. The Thinker, who sees Life clearly and sees it whole, will regard religious belief and scientific knowledge as both means for the sake of conduct, or corporate action. He will show his devotion to this end by setting his face steadily against individualism in the pursuit of knowledge and the holding of belief — against the scientific specialist's ideal of the indefinite accumulation of knowledge — against the priest's doctrine of the opus operatum, effectual in securing the only true good, as it is thought, the private profit of the individual — hardest of all, against the refined form of indi- vidualism by which he is himself tempted, the individualism of the schoolman, or doctrinaire, who withdraws himself within his logical faculty, and pleases himself there with the con- struction of " a System " — ρήματα ε^εττιττ/δβ? άΧλήΧοίς ώμοίωμβνα. In the Allegory^ of the Cave, Plato sho'^g^us the victory of the Thinker over individualism. The Thinker has come out at last into the daylight, and, when he might s'iay in it always and enjoy it, he will not stay, but returns into the Cave to pay his τροφβΐα — the debt which he owes for the education which he has received — by carrying on, in the 'training of a new generation, the regime to which he owes it that he has seen the light. " We shall compel him to return," Plato says, and he adds, " We do him no injustice." The compulsion is moral, not external.^ It is the obligation which the perfectly ^ He realises in an eminent degree what seems to be the experience of us all ; for "our 'present* is always an extended time," not an indivisible point: see Bosanquet's Logic, i. 351. '^ — and Myth ; see ivfra, p. 252. 3 Eep. 520. INTEODUCTION 57 educated man feels laid upon him by. his consciousness of his inherence in the continuous life of his city — the obligation of seeing to it that his own generation shall have worthy successors. ,, How important, then, to keep alive in the elders sympathy with the faith in which it is necessary they should bring up the young generation ! Consciousness of what they owe as τροφβΐα, and earnest desire to pass the State on to worthy successors, will do most to keep alive this sympathy ; but, on the other hand, the logical understanding will always be reminding them that "in truth" (though perhaps not "in practice") the doctrines of science and the convictions of the religious consciousness are " incompatible " ; and it is here, I take it, with regard to this άτΓορία started by abstract thought, that Plato hopes for good from Myth, as from some great Eitual at which thinkers may assist and feel that there are mysteries which the scientific understanding cannot fathom. That the scientific understanding, then, working within its own region, must reject the idea of a Personal God, was, I take it, as clear to Plato as it was to Aristotle. Would Plato, then, say that the proposition " There is a Personal God " is not true ? He would say that what children are to be taught to believe — " that once upon a time God or the Gods did this thing or that" — is not true as historical fact. Where historical or scientific fact is concerned, the scientific understanding is within its own region, and is com- petent to say "it is true" or "it is not true" But the scientific understanding cannot be allowed to criticise its own foundation — that which all the faculties of the living man, the scientific understanding itself included, take for granted — " that it is good to go on living the human life into which I have been born ; and that it is worth while employing my faculties carefully in the conduct of my life, for they do not deceive me." This fundamental assumption of Life, " It is good to live, and my faculties are trustworthy," Plato throws into the proposi- tion, " There is a Personal God, good and true, who keeps me in all my ways." He wishes children to take this proposition literally. He knows that abstract thinkers will say that " it is not true " ; but he is satisfied if the men, whose parts and training have made theii influential in their generation, read 58 THE MYTHS OF PLATO it to mean — things happen as if they were ordered by a Personal God, good and true. To this as if — this recognition of "Personal God" as "Eegulative Principle" — they are helped — so I take Plato to think — by two agencies, of which Myth, breaking in upon the logic of the Dialogue with the representation of the religious experience of childhood, and of venerable old age like that of Cephalus, is one. The other agency is Kitual.^ This is recognised by Plato as very im- portant ; and Myth may be taken to be its literary counterpart. One of the most significant things in the Republic is the de- ference paid to Delphi. Philosophy — that is, the Constitution of the Platonic State — indeed lays down " canons of orthodoxy," the TVTTOL Trepl deoXoyia^ ^ — determines the religious dogma ; but the ritual is to be determined from without, by Delphi.* Keligion is to be at once rational and traditional — at once reformed, and conservative of catholic use. Plato was not in a position to realise the difficulty involved in this arrangement.• It is a modern discovery, that ritual reacts on dogma, and in some cases even creates it. Plato seems to take for granted that the pure religious dogma of his State will not in time be affected by the priestly ritual. At any rate, he assumes that his State, as the civil head of a united Hellas,^ and Delphi, as the ecclesiastical head, will, like Empire and Church in Dante's De Monarchia, be in sympathy with each other. It is plain, then, from the place — if I have rightly indicated the place — which Plato assigns to Eitual in daily life, and to * "A rite is an assemblage of symbols, grouped round a religious idea or a religious act, intended to enhance its solemn character or develop its meaning — just as a myth is the grouping of mythic elements associated under a dramatic form. . . . Thus we have the rite of baptism, funeral rites, sacrificial rites." R^ville, ProUgom^ies de VHistaire des Religions (Eng. Transl. by Squire), p. 110. 2 7?• 379 a. ^ Rep. 427 B, Ύί o^v, ^φη, in hv ήμΖν Xonrhv τη^ νομοθ€σία$ €Ϊη ; καΐ έ-γώ elirov δτι Ήμΐν μέν ουδέν, τφ μέντοι Άττόλλωνι τφ ev Αελφοΐ^ τά re μέ'/ίστα και κάλλιστα καΐ πρώτα των νομοθετημάτων. Τά ποια ; f} δ' 6s. Ιερών τβ Ιδρύσεις καΐ θνσίαι καΐ άλλαι Θεών τε και δαφόνωμ και ηρώων θεραττεΐαι, τελεντησάντων τε αΰ θηκαι καΐ 6σα tois έκεΐ δει υπηρετούνται ϊλεωί ai)roi>s έχειν. τα yap δη τοιαύτα οϋτ έπιστάμεθα ημεΐ$ οικίξοντέ$ τε πόλιν ούδενΐ άλ\φ πεισόμεθα, εάν νουν ίχωμεν, ουδέ χρησόμεθα εξηγητή, αλλ' ^ τφ πατρίφ• oDtos yap δηπου ό θεο$ περί τά τοιαύτα πάσιν άνθρωποι^ πάτριοι έξηyητ'r]ί εν μέσφ τηί yrjs έπΙ του ομφαλού καθήμενοι έξηyεΐτaι. "* See infra, pp. 454-5, where it is argued that;Plato's καλλίπολίί is misunder- stood (as in part by Aristotle) if its constitution is taken to be drawn for an isolated municipality, and not for an Empire-city (like the antediluvian Athens of the Atlantis Myth), under which, as civil head (Delphi being the ecclesiastical head), Hellas should be united against barbarians for the propagation of liberty and culture in the world. INTRODUCTION 59 Myth in philosophical literature/ what place he assigns to ' the scientific understanding. The scientific understanding, which is only a small part, and a late developed part, of the whole man, as related to his whole environment, is apt, chiefly because it has the gift of speech and can explain itself, while our deeper laid faculties are dumb, to flatter itself with the conceit that it is the measure of all things — that what is to it inconceivable is impossible. It cannot conceive the Part ruling the Whole : therefore it says that the proposition " the World is ruled by a Personal God " is not true. Plato has, so far as I can gather, two answers to this pronouncement of the scientific understanding. The first is, " Life would come to naught if we acted as if the scientific understanding were right in denying the existence of a Personal God " ; and he trusts to Ritual and Myth (among other agencies) to help men to feel this. His attitude here is very like Spinoza's : — Deum nullam aliam sui cognitionem ab hominibus per prophetas petere, quam cognitionem divinae suae justitiae et caritatis, hoc est, talia Dei attributa, quae homines certa vivendi ratione imitari possunt; quod quidem Jeremias expressissimis verbis docet (22. 15, 16). . . . Evangelica doctrina nihil praeter simplicem fidem continet ; nempe Deo credere eumque revereri, sive, quod idem est, Deo obedire. . . . Sequitur denique fidem non tarn requirere vera, quam pia dogmata, hoc est, talia, quae animum ad obedientiam movent. . . . Fidem non tarn veritatem, quam pietatem exigere.''^ Plato's other answer goes deeper. It consists in showing that the "Whole," or all-embracing Good, cannot be grasped I scientifically, but must be seen imperfectly in a similitude.^! The logical understanding, as represented by Glaucon, not satisfied with knowing what the all-embracing Good is like, wishes to know what it is — as if it were an object presented to knowledge. But the Good is not an object presented to. knowledge. It is the condition of knowledge. It is likel 1 Or rather, in philosopliical conversation ; for the Platonic Dialogues, after all, with their written discussions and myths, are only offered as models to be followed in actual conversation — actual conversation being essential to the continued life of Philosophy. '•^ Spinoza, Tractatus Tlieokgico-politiciiS, chapters 13 and 14. 3 Bep. 506. 60 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Light which is not one of the things seen, but the condition of seeing. To suppose that the Whole, or Good, is an object, among objects, of knowledge, is the fault which Plato, as I read him, finds with the logical understanding ; and a Platonist might, I think, be allowed to develop the Master's criticism as follows : — The conception of " Whole " or " Universe " which the logical understanding professes to have, and manipulates in its proof of the non-existence of a Personal God, is not a " conception " at all. The understanding cannot conceive the Universe as finished Whole. Its " whole " is always also a " part " of something indefinitely greater. The argument that " the Euler of the Universe is not a Personal God, because the Part cannot rule the Whole," juggling, as it does, with this sham conception — that of " Whole which is not also Part " — is inconclusive. 7. Plato's Treatment of the Idea of Soul Let us now turn to the " Idea of Soul." The Soul is represented in the three strictly Eschatological Myths of the Fhaedo, Gorgias, and BepuUic, and in other Myths not strictly Eschatological, as a Person created by God, and responsible to him for acts in which it is a free agent within limits set by ανάγκη — responsible to God throughout an existence which began before its incarnation in this body, and will continue for ever after the death of this body — an existence in which it is subject to periodical re-incarnations, alternating with terms of disembodiment, during which it receives recompense for the deeds done in the flesh ; till at last — if it is not incorrigible — it is thoroughly purified by penance, and enters into the peace of a never-ending disembodied state, like that which it enjoyed in its own peculiar star, before it began the cycle of incarnations. Zeller,^ while admitting that many details in Plato's doctrine of the pre-existence and future destiny of the immortal Soul are mythic, maintains that the doctrine itself, in its broad outlines, is held by him dogmatically, and propounded as scientific truth. Pre-existence, recollection, 1 Zeller, Plato, Eng. TraDsl. pp. 397-413. Thiemann {Die PlcUonische Eschatologu in ihrer geneiischen Entvnckelung, 1892, p. 27) agrees with Zeller. INTEODUCTION 61 retribution, re-incaruation, final purification, and never-ending disembodied existence of the purified soul — these, Zeller thinks, are set forth by Plato as facts which are literally true. Hegel,^ \ on the other hand, holds that the Platonic doctrine of the | Soul is wholly mythic. I take it from a passage in the Introduction to the Critique of Pure Reason ^ that Kant would think with Zeller against Hegel. Where such authorities differ one might well remain neutral; but I cannot help saying that I incline to the view that the bare doctrine of immortality (not to mention the details of its setting) is conceived by Plato in Myth, and not dogmatically — or perhaps 7 I ought to say, conceived eminently in Myth ; for the dogmatic' way of conceiving immortality is not formally excluded on Platonic, as it is on Kantian, principles ; although the mere circumstance that Plato has an alternative way of conceiving it — the mythological way, not to mention the great attraction which the mythological way plainly has for him — shows that he was dissatisfied with the scientific proof of immortality — entertained a doubt, to say the least, whether " the Soul is immortal " ought to be regarded as a scientific truth. Nor need Plato's doubt surprise us, when we consider the state of opinion in the Athens of his day. Belief in personal immortality had become very feeble among a large number of educated and even half-educated people in Athens.^ For the belief of the ordinary half-educated man, the Attic Orators, in their frequent references to the cult of the dead, are our best ^ Hegel, WerJce, vol. xiv. pp. 207 if. Coiitiirat {de Platmiis Mythis, Paris, 1896, pp. 84-88) agrees with Hegel. Grote {Plato, ii. 190, n. q.) expresses qualified agreement: "There is ingenuity," he says, "in this view of Hegel, and many separate expressions of Plato receive light from it ; but it appears to me to refine away too much. Plato had in his own mind and belief both the Soul as a particular thing, and the Soul as an universal. His language implies sometimes the one, sometimes the other." That Coleridge would have endorsed Hegel's view is clear from the following passage in Biogr. Lit. ch. 22. Speaking of Wordsworth's Ode on the Intimations of Immortality from Recollections of Early Childhood, he says : "The Ode Avas intended for such readers only as had been accustomed to watch the flux and reflux of their inmost nature, to venture at times into the twilight realms of consciousness, and to feel a deep interest in modes of inmost being, to which they know that the attributes of time and space are inapplicable and alien, but which yet cannot be conveyed, save in symbols of time and space. For such readers the sense is sufficiently plain, and they will be as little disposed to charge Mr. Wordsworth with believing the platonio pre-existence in the ordinary interpretation of the words, as I am to believe that Plato himself ever meant or taught it." - See infra, p. 72, where the passage is quoted. 2 See Jowett, The Oialogv£s of Plato, vol. i. 419 (Introduction to the Phaedo, § 12). 62 THE MYTHS OF PLATO authorities. They seem to take for granted a belief very much like that which Aristotle makes the basis of his remarks in Eth. Nic. i. 10 and 11 ; and, like him, are concerned chiefly to avoid TO Χίαν άφιλον, statements likely to wound tender feeling. " The continued existence of the Soul after death," says Eohde,^ " is not questioned by the orators ; but its con- sciousness of what happens in this world is only affirmed with deliberate uncertainty. Such qualifications as et τίνες των τ€Τ€\€ντηκ6των \άβοΐ€ν τρόττω τινϊ του νυν ^^ι^^νομ,ενου 'πράγματος αϊσθησιν are frequent. Apart from the offerings of his relatives there is little more to bind the deceased to this world than his fame among survivors. Even in the exalted language of solemn funeral orations we miss, among the con- solations offered to the mourners, any reference to a higher condition — to an eternal life of conscious blessedness attained to by the famous dead." Here the Orators are in agreement with that great master of the art of epitaph- writing, as Kohde'^ well describes Simonides, " who has never a word assigning the departed to a land of eternal blessedness," but places their immortality entirely in the memory of their deeds, which lasts, and will last, in this world : — οΰδ€ τίθναχτί θανόντ€ζ, ίτηί σφ' άρζτη καθνττίρθίν κνΒαίνονσ' avayec Βώμ,ατοζ e^ Άιδίω.^ Similarly Tyrtaeus^ had identified αθανασία expressly with κλέος : — ovBe 7Γ0Τ€ kAcos ίσθλον άττόλλυται οΰδ' ονο/α' αΰτου, αλλ' ντΓο -γης τηρ ίων ytyvcrat αθάνατο? — His body is buried in peace, but his name liveth for evermore. The Dramatists, too, did much to induce their public to look at the dead in the same way; for the dramatic interest required that prominence should be given to the pos- thumous influence of the dead here rather than to their personal ^ Psyche, vol. ii. pp. 202, 203 ; and see his important footnotes to these pages, in which he gives references to H. Meuss {Uber die Vorstellungen von Dasein nach deni Tode bei den attischen Rednern, Jahrb. f. Philol., 1889, pp. 801 if.), Wester- mann (on Demosth. Lept. 87), and Lehrs {Popid. Aufs. 329 if.), for the views expi-essed by the Attic Orators concerning the state of the departed. ' Psyche, ii. 204. '^ Simon. Epigr. 99, 3, 4, quoted by Rohde, Psyche, ii. 204, n. 1. ^ Tyrtaeus, 12, 31 f., quoted by Rohde, Psyche, ii. 201, n. 3. INTKODUCTION 63 condition in another world. When the Dramatists put the old national legends on the stage, attention was turned, as Eohde^ points out, from the mere events of the story to the characters and motives of the hitherto shadowy legendary personages now presented, for the first time, clearly to sense. The plots were well known, and not so curiously attended to by the audience as the characters of the personages now mov- ing before their eyes. Motives became more important than events. The Dramatist had to combine the traditional story of the legend with the motives of agents who must have the hearts of modern men, or else not be understood by the audi- ence. Hence the tragic conflict between events and motives. It is fated that a good man shall do an evil deed. How can he be responsible for such a deed, and merit the retribution which the moral sense of the audience would resent if he did not merit it ? This is the tragic άττορία which the Dramatists solved, I would suggest, by taking the Family, rather than the Individual, as the moral unit.^ The descendant is free because he is conscious of doing the ancestral, the fated, thing — a doctrine which Eohde,^ in ascribing especially to Aeschylus, compares with the Stoic doctrine of σν^κατάθεσυ^,^ The human interest of tragedy requires that the penalty for sin shall be paid here on earth rather than in Hades. This is why there is so little in the Greek Dramatists about the punish- ment of the wicked in the other world for their own sins. It is in this laorld that sin must be punished if the drama is to have any human interest. Since the Family, not the Indi- vidual, is the moral unit, it matters not that the sin punished here is ancestral. Nay, the tragic effect is heightened when the children suffer for the sins of their fathers. The dead fathers live in their children : that is, for aught we can ever know, the only life they have : — rovs yap θανόντας el ^eActs evcpyeruv etV ovv κακονργ€Ϊν, άμφιδίξίω'ζ €χ€ί τφ μήτ€ χαίραν μήτ€ λνπ^Ισθαυ veKpovs.^ 1 Psijche, ii. 225. 2 See Plutarch, i^e sera numinis vindicia, 16, on the continuity of tlie Family, and the justice of punishing children for the sins of fathers. 3 Psyche, ii. 229. ^ Cic. defato, 18, where avyKaraeeais is rendered by adsensio. ^ Aeschylus, /mgr. 266, quoted by Rohde, Psyche, ii. 232. "Under all circum- stances," says Dr. Westcott {Eetigious Thought in the West, edit. 1891, pp. 91, 92), 64 THE MYTHS OF PLATO If the dead, then, are unconscious or barely conscious, the living must be punished for the sins of the dead, that the justice of the Gods may be satisfied.^ Aristotle did little more than formulate the widely-prevalent opinion supported by Orators and Dramatists, when he defined the Soul as " the function of the body " — and Plato himself bears witness to the prevalence of the opinion when he makes Glaucon express surprise on hearing it suggested by Socrates that the Soul is immortal.^ It had never occurred to Glaucon that the doctrine of the Soul's immortality could be taken seriously. Socrates then offers a " scientific " proof of its immortality — a proof which he offers, I would sug gest, only or chiefly t hat he may supersede it by the Myth of Er.2 So much for considerations which make it reasonable to suppose that Plato, like many oth^s in_the Athens of his day, felt at least serious doubt as to whether anything could be known scientifically about the conscious life of the Soul after death, if he did not actually go the length of holding, as his disciple Aristotle did, that, as conscious individual, it perishes with the body whose function it is. That, while entertaining this serious doubt, Plato did not go so far as Aristotle, seems to me to be shown by the manner in which he allows himself to be affected by another class of opinions " the view of the condition of the Dead, which Aeschylus brings out into the clearest light in describing the condition of the Guilty, is consistent. The ful- ness of human life is on earth. The part of man, in all his energy and capacity for passion and action, is played out here ; and when the curtain falls there remains unbroken rest, or a faint reflection of the past, or suffering wrought by the ministers of inexorable justice. The beauty and the power of life, the mani- fold ministers of sense, are gone. They can be regretted, but they cannot be replaced. SorroΛV is possible, but not joy. " However different this teaching may be from that of the Myths of Plato, and the vague popular belief which they Λvitnessed to and fostered ; however different, again, even from that of Pindar, with which Aeschylus cannot have been unacquainted , it is pre-eminently Greek. Plato clothed in a Greek dress the common instincts of humanity ; Aeschylus works out a characteristically Greek view of life. Thus it is that his doctrine is most clearly Homeric. As a Greek he feels, like Homer, the nobility of our present powers, the grandeur of strength and wealth, the manifold delights of our complex being ; and what was ' the close-packed urn of ashes which survived the funeral pyre ' compared with the heroes whom it represented ? That * tear-stained dust ' was the witness that man — the whole man — could not live again. The poet, then, was constrained to work out a scheme of divine justice upon earth, and this Aeschylus did, though its record is a strain of sorrow." 1 On the necessity of satisfying the justice of the Gods, see Rohde, Psyche, ii. 232. 2 Rep. 608 D, on which see Rohde, Psyche, ii. 264, 265, and Adam, ad loc. ^ See infra, p. 73. INTKODUCTION 65 opposed to the agnosticism of his time. I refer to the opinions associated with the Mysteries and the Orphic revival throughout Greece, and especially in Athens. The Eleusinian Mysteries were the great stronghold in Greece of the doctrine of a future life ; ^ and the same doctrine was taught, in definite form, by the Orphic societies which appeared in Italy and Sicily (in some cases in close connection with the spread of Pythagoreanism) before the close of the latter half of the sixth century. As Athens became more and more the centre of Greek life, the Orphic cult gravitated thither. We find it represented by Onomacritus at the Court of the Pisistratids ; and, meeting the need of " personal religion," felt especially during the tribulation caused by the Peloponnesian War and the Great Plague,^ it had, in Plato's day, become firmly rooted in the city. The sure hope of salvation, for themselves and those dear to them, in a future life, the details of which were minutely described, was held before the anxious and afflicted who duly observed the pre- scribed Orphic rites. The hope was all the surer because it was made to rest on the consciousness of having one's self done something ; it was all the surer, too, because the comfort which it brought was offered, not to selfish, but to sympathetic feeling — for even ancestors long dead could be aided in their purgatorial state by the prayers and observances of their pious descendants.^ 1 See Gardner's New Chapters in Greek History, p. 397, and Gardner and Jevons' Manual of Greek Antiquities, p. 275. '^ See Rohde, Psyche, ii. 105, 106. ^ See important note (5), Rohde, Psyche, ii. 128, in which Rep. 364 b, c, e- 365 A is cited — especially 365 a, π€ίθοντ€$ . . . ws dpa λύσεΐί re καΐ καθαρμοί αδικημάτων διί θυσιών καΐ TratSiSs ηδονών eial μέν ^τί ξώσιν, etVi δέ καΐ reXeim;- σασίν, ά? δή reXeras καλουσίν, ά τών έκΐί κακών άττολύονσίν ημα$, μτ) θύσαντα$ δέ δ€ΐνά π€ριμέν€ΐ — as showing that deceased ancestors could be aided by the prayers and observances of descendants. Although the Orphic Fragm. 208 (cf. Mullach, Fr. Ph. Gr.i. 188) Opyia τ' έκτίλέσουσι, λύσιν νροΎόνων άθβμίστων \ μαώμενοί, σύ δέ τοΐσιν ίχων κράτος οϋί κ έθέλησθα | λύσβίί ίκ re ττόνων χαλ€ΐΓών καΐ aireipovos οίστρου, quoted by Rohde in the same note, seems to make it quite clear that dead ancestors could be aided by their descendants, I think that the passage quoted from Hep. 365 a leaves the matter in doubt ; see Paul Tannery in Eev. de Philol. October 1901, on reXerai {Orphica, Fr. 221, 227, 228, 254), who explains the etVi μέν ^n ξ'ώσιν, βίσΐ 5e και τεΧευτησασι of Rep. 365 A to mean that the expiatory rites clear the initiated person, some of them for the time of his earthly life, some of them for his life after death. These latter are As δη τ€\€τά$ καλονσί. TeXerat cannot affect any one except the initiated person himself (to whom they supply directions as to his journey in the other world) : they cannot clear an ancestor. According to this explanation, the reference in Rep. 364 c, ehe τι αδίκημα του ^4yovev αύτοΰ ή προ-γόνων, is not to ancestors as affected by the observances of their descendants, but to sin inherited from an F 66 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Now, what is Plato's attitude to this Orphic cult ? This question can be answered, in part at least, without difficulty : He derived the main doctrine, together with most of the details, of his Eschatological Myths — the doctrine of the pre- existence, penance, re-incarnation, and final purification of the Soul — directly, and through Pindar, from Orphic sources, the chief of which, if we accept the carefully formed view of Dieterich, was a popular Orphic Manual, the κατάβασης el<: AlBov, in which the vicissitudes endured by the immortal Soul, till it frees itself, by penance, from the Cycle of Births, were described — a work which lay at the foundation of Pindar's theology, was ridiculed by Aristophanes in the Frogs, was the ultimate source of the ^έκυιαι, of Plutarch and Virgil, and greatly influenced Neo-Platonic doctrine.^ Pindar, a poet and theologian after Plato's heart, whom he always quotes with deep respect, was, we may suppose, brought into contact with the Orphic cult in Sicily, where, along with the Pythagorean discipline, it had found a con- genial home.^ The difference between Pindar's outlook, and that of the Athenian Orators and Dramatists and their agnostic public, is very striking. In certain places he indeed speaks of the dead as gone, their earthly fame alone surviving. But this is not his dominant tone. Not only have a favoured few — heroes like Amphiaraus — been trans- lated, by a miracle, " body and soul," to immortal homes, but, ancestor, which a man may cleanse himself of. I do not think, liowever, that the reference in the λύσίν ιτρο-γόνων άθβμίστων of the Orphic fragment quoted by MuUach (i. 188) and Rohde can be to this. 1 See Dieterich, Nekyia, 116-158 ; and cf. Jevons, Introduction to the History of Religion, pp. 353, 354 : Orpheus had descended into Hades ; hence came to be regarded as the author of verses descriptive of Hades, which were current in thiasi, or disseminated by itinerant agyrtae. In Re^J. 364 e, βίβλων δέ δμαδον παρέχονται Μνσαίου και 'Ορφ4ω$, the reference is, doubtless, to this and other Orphic guide-books for the use of the dead. These Orphic books may be compared with the Egyptian Book of the Dead, a guide for the use of the Ka, or "double " (on which see Budge's Egyptian Ideas of the Future Life, p. 163), which Avanders from the body, and may lose its Λvay ; cf. Petrie's Egyptian Tales, second series, ρ 124 ; see also Eleusinia, by le Comte Goblet d'Alviella (1903), pp. 73 if., on the connection between Greek and Egyjitian guide-books for the use of the dead. To Dieterich's list of eschatological pieces in literature inspired by the Orphic teaching we ought perhaps to add the Voyage of Odysseus to Hades {Od. xi.) ; see v. AV'^ilamowitz-Mbllendortf, Horn. Untersuch. p. 199, who supposes that the passage was put in by Onomacritus, when Homer Λvas being edited at Athens in the time of the Tyrants. 2 See Rohde, Psyche, ii. 216, 217 ; and, for the spread of the Orphic Religion, Bury, Hist, of Greece^ chap, vii, sec. 13. INTKODUCTION 67 when any ordinary man dies, his Soul survives his body, and that, not as a poor vanishing shade, but as a responsible person destined for immortal life. The ψυχή, as Pindar conceives it, is not the " totality of the bodily functions," as the philosophers and the agnostic Athenian public conceived it, but the Double which has its home in the body. This Double comes from the Gods and is immortal : — και ατωμα μ\ν ττάντων έ'ττεται ό^ανάτω TrepLordevci, ζωόν ο €Tt λ€ΐ7Γ€ται αίωνο<ζ ειδωλον το yap ccTTL μόνον €κ θ€ωνΛ Being of God, the Soul is necessarily immortal, but is immersed in the body because of ancient sin — τταΧαών ττύνθος. At the death of its first body, the Soul goes to Hades, where it is judged and recompensed for the deeds, good or ill, done in the flesh. But its sin is not wholly purged. It reappears on earth in a second body, at the death of which it goes a second time to Hades, where its sin is further purged. Then it returns to animate a third body on earth (see Pindar, 01. ii. 68 it). Then, if these three lives on earth, as well as the two periods of sojourn in Hades, have been spent without fault, and if, when it returns for the third time to Hades, it lives there without fault, Persephone, in the ninth year of this third sojourn in Hades, receives the full tale of satisfaction due for τταλαών ττένθος, and sends it back to earth, to be born in the person of a Philosopher or King (see Pindar, quoted Meno, 81 b), who, at his death, becomes a holy Hero, or Daemon — a finally disembodied spirit : the Soul has at last got out of the κύκλος γβζ/εσβωζ/.^ This is ^ Pindar, fr. apud Plut. Consol. ad Apoll. 35. 2 I am indebted to Rolide {Psyche, ii. 207-217) for the substance of this sketch of Pindar's Eschatology. In the last paragraph I have tried to combine the doctrine of 01. ii. 68 ff. and the fragment, Men. 81 b. The life of Philosopher or King is indeed a bodily life on earth, but it is not one of the three bodily lives necessary (together with the three sojourns in Hades) to the final purifica- tion of the Soul. The Soul has been finally purified before it returns to this fourth and last bodily life which immediately precedes its final disembodiment. In the case of Souls which do not pass three faultless lives here and in Hades, the number of re-incarnations would be greater. Pindar's estimate seems to be that of the time required in the most favourable circumstances. We may take it that it is the time promised by the Orphic priests to those whose ritual observances were most regulfif. According to Phaedrus, 249 a, however, it would appear that a Soul must have been incarnate as a Philosopher in three 68 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Pindar's doctrine — plainly Orphic doctrine, with beauty and distinction added to it by the genius of the great poet. Plato's Eschatological Myths also, like Pindar's poems, plainly reproduce the matter of Orphic teaching. Is it going too far, when we consider Plato's reverence for the genius of Pindar, to suggest that it was Pindar's form which helped to recommend to Plato the matter which he reproduces in his Eschatological Myths — that the poet's refined treatment of the Orphic μυθο^ helped the philosopher, himself a poet, to see how that μυθο^ might be used to express imaginatively what indeed demands expression of some kind, — man's hope of personal immortality, — but cannot, without risk of fatal injury, be expressed in the language of science ? It is Pindar, as chief among divine seers who is quoted, in the Meno (81), for the pre-existence, transmigrations, responsibility, and immortality of the Soul ; but the Platonic " Socrates " is care- ful to say that he does not contend for the literal truth of the doctrine embodied in Pindar's myth, but insists on its practical value in giving us hope and courage as seekers after knowledge {Meno, 86 b). It is Pindar, again, who is quoted at the beginning of the BepuMic (331 b) for that yXvKeia cXtt/?, which is visualised in Orphic outlines and colours at the close of the Dialogue, in the greatest of Plato's Eschato- logical Myths. Orphic doctrine, refined by poetic genius for philosophic use, is the material of which Plato weaves his Eschatological Myths. And he seems almost to go out of his way to tell us this. Not only is the Meno Myth introduced with special mention of the priestly source from which it is derived (Meno, 8 1 b), but even brief allusions made elsewhere to the doctrine contained in it are similarly introduced — as in the Fhaedo, 70 c, where the doctrine of the transmigrations of the Soul is said to be derived from a τταΧαώς λόγο? ; in the Fhaedo, 81a, where it is connected with what is said κατά των μεμνημένων ; and in the Laws, 872 E, where the successive lives before entering on the disembodied state : see Zeller, Plato, Eng. Tr, p. 393 ; and cf. Phaedo, 113 d fi"., where live classes of men are distinguished with respect to their condition after death — on which see Rohde, Psyche, ii. 275, n. 1. "Έστρ-Λ έκατέρωθι," says Prof. Gildersleeve in his note on Find. 01. ii. 75, "would naturally mean six times, έστρί^ may mean three times in all. The Soul descends to Hades, then returns to earth, then descends again for a final probation." I do not think that this last interpreta- tion can be accepted. INTEODUCTION 69 τΓαΧαωϊ UpeU are referred to for the doctrine that, if a man kills his mother, he must be born again as a woman who is killed by her son. But, after all, the most convincing evidence for the great influence exercised by Orphic doctrine over Plato is to be found in the way in which he loves to describe Philosophy itself in terms borrowed from the Orphic cult and the Mysteries.^ Thus in the Phaedo, 69 c, Kol KLvSvvevovai καϊ ο I τας τβλβτας ημΐν ovtol κατα- στησαντ€ς ου φαΰΧοο elvai, άλλα τώ ovtl ττάλαι, αΐνίτ- τβσθαί 6τ(, 09 αν αμύητος καϊ άτέΧεστος βίς '^Αώον άφίκηταί, iv βορβόρω KeLaerac, 6 δε κβκαθαρμενος re καϊ rereke- σμένος έκβΐσε άφίκόμβνος μβτα θέων οίκησβί, βίσΐ yap 8ή, ψασϊν οι ΊΓβρΙ τας τέλβτάς, ναρθηκοφόροί μβν ττοΧΚοί, βάκ'χρυ δε τε ττανροί,. ούτοι δ' βίσΐν κατά την βμην Βόξαν ουκ aWoL η οί ττβφιΧοσοφηκότβς ορθώς. Again, in the Gorgias, 493 A, borrowing an Orphic phrase, he likens the body, with its lusts, to a tomb — το μβν σώμα βστιν ήμΐν σήμα — from which Wisdom alone can liberate the Soul (cf. also Cratylus, 400 b); and in the Phaedrus, 250 B, c, he describes Philosophy — the Soul's vision of the Eternal Forms — as a kind of Initiation : καλΧος δε τότ ην iSeiv Χαμττρόν, 6τ6 συν €ύΒαίμονί χορω μακαρίαν όψιν τε και θεαν, εττό- μβνοι μβτα μεν Αώς ήμεΐς, dWoL δε μβτ αλΧου θβών, elSov τε καϊ ετβΧοΰντο *Γών τεΧετών, ην θέμις Χε^ευν μακαριωτά- την, ήν ώρΎΐάζομεν όΧόκΧηροί μεν αύτοΙ οντες καϊ απαθείς κακών οσα ημάς εν υστερώ χρόνω ύττέμενεν, οΧόκΧηρα δε και άττΧά καϊ άτρεμή καϊ εύΒαίμονα φάσματα μυούμενοί τε καϊ ετΓοτΓτεύοντες εν αύγρ καθαρά, καθαροί οντες καϊ ασήμαντοι τούτου ο νυν σώμα ττεριφεροντες ονομάζομεν, οστρεου τρόττον ΒεΒεσμευμενοι. Again, in the Timaeus, 44 C,^ he speaks of the Soul which has neglected the ορθή τροφή τταιΒεύσεως as returning, " uninitiated " and " without know- ledge of truth," into Hades — άτεΧης καϊ ανόητος εΙς 'ΆιΒου ττάΧιν έρχεται; and in the Symposiumy 209 Ε, in Diotima's Discourse on έρως, the highest Philosophy is described as τα τεΧεα καϊ εττοτττικά, for the sake of which we seek initiation in τα ερωτικά.^ 1 See Rohde, Psyche, ii. 279. 2 See Arch^-Hind's note on Fhaedo, 69 c. ^ See Couturat, de Plat. Mythis, p. 55. 70 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Let us not think that this is " mysticism " — " the scholas- ticism of the heart " ^ — such as we find afterwards in the Neo- Platonic teaching. On the contrary, it is to be regarded as evidence of the non-scholastic, concrete view which Plato takes of Philosophy. Philosophy to Plato is not σοφία— a. mere system of ascertained truth — but strictly ψοΧο σοφίοτ—- βρως, child of ττόρος and άττορία, as the parentage is set forth in Diotima's Myth in the Symposutm : Philosophy is not what finally satisfies — or surfeits — the intellect : it is the organic play of all the human powers and functions — it is Human Life, equipped for its continual struggle, eager and hopeful, and successful in proportion to its hope — its hope being naturally visualised in dreams of a future state. These dreams the human race will never outgrow, — so the Platonist holds, — will never ultimately cast aside as untrue ; for the young will believe in them in every generation, and the weary and bereaved will cherish them, and men of genius — poets, philosophers, saints — will always rise up to represent them anew. The Philosophy of an epoch must be largely judged by the way in which it "represents" them. How much virtue Plato finds in " representation " — philosophical and poetical — may be gathered from the fact that, while he attaches the highest value to the Orphic doctrine which he himself borrows for philosophical use, he ascribes the worst moral influence to the actual teaching of the Orphic priests.^ I said that it is reasonable to suppose that Plato was affected by the agnosticism which prevailed in Athens, and felt, notwithstanding some "proofs" which he ventured to offer, serious doubt as to whether even the bare fact of con- scious immortality is matter of scientific knowledge.^ It may 1 "Der Mysticismus ist die Scholastik des Herzens, die Dialektik des Gefiihls," Goethe, Spriiche in Prosa: Maximen und Befieximen: dritte Abtheilung. 2 Republic, 364 e. In Aristoph. Ranae, 159, and Demosth. de Cormia, 259 ff., the practices of the agyrtae, or itinerant celebrants of initiatory rites, are held up to ridicule. 3 But see Zeller's Tlato, p. 408 (Eng. Transl.). Zeller holds that the fact of immortality and future retribution was regarded by Plato as established beyond doubt ; only details were uncertain. Couturat {de PL Myth. p. 112) thinks that the whole doctrine of immortality in Plato is "mythic." Jowett (Introduction to Phaedo) remarks that in proportion as Plato succeeds in substituting a philo- sophical^ for α mythological treatment of the immortality of the Soul, "the con- templation of ideas * under the form of eternity ' takes the place of past and INTEODUCTION 71 now be added, however, that his sympathy with the personal religion, in which many took refuge from agnosticism, was profound, and moved him to deal, in Myth openly borrowed from the religious teachers, with subjects which Aristotle left alone. Official (as distinct from personal) religion offers no safe refuge from agnosticism. Eecognising this, Plato took the matter of his strictly Eschatological Myths almost entirely from the Orphic teaching, which presented religion as a way of salvation which all, without distinction of sex or civil status, simply as human beings, of their own free choice, can enter upon and pursue.^ future states of existence." Mr. Adam {Bep. vol. ii. p. 456) says, " that soul is iminortal, Plato is firmly convinced : transmigration he regards as probable, to say the least." ^ See Gardner and Jevons' Manual of Greek Antiquities, Book iii. ch. iv. " Orgiastic Cults," and Jevons' Introduction to the History of Religion, pp. 327- 374. "The leading characteristic," says Dr. Jevons {o.c. p. 339), "of the re- vival in the sixth century B.C., both in the Semitic area, and as transplanted into Greece, is a reaction against the gift theory of sacrifice, and a reversion to the older sacramental conception of the ottering and the sacrificial meal as affording actual communion with the God whose flesh and blood were consumed by his worshippers. . . . The unifying efficacy (p. 331) of the sacrificial meal made it possible to form a circle of worshippers. . . . We have the principle of voluntary religious associations which were open to all. Membership did not depend on birth, but was constituted by partaking in the divine life and blood of the sacred animal." These voluntary associations formed for religious purposes — thiasi or erani—'^ differed (p. 335) from the cult of the national gods in that all — women, foreigners, slaves — Avere admitted, not merely members of the State." In short, initiatio (μύησίί) took the place of civitas as the title of admission to religious privileges. Prof. Gardner closes the chapter on "Orgiastic Cults," referred to above, with the following words: — "In several respects the thiasi were precursors of Christianity, and opened the door by which it entered. If they belonged to a lower intellectual level than the best religion of Greece, and were full of vulgarity and imposture, they yet had in them certain elements of progress, and had some- thing in common with the future as well as the past history of mankind. All properly Hellenic religion was a tribal thing, belonged to the state and the race, did not proselytise, nor even admit foreign converts ; and so when the barriers which divided cities were pulled down it sank and decayed. The cultus of Sabazius or of Cybele was, at least, not tribal : it sought converts among all ranks, and having found them, placed them on a level before the God. Slaves and women were admitted to membership and to office. The idea of a common humanity, scarcely admitted by Greek philosophers before the age of the Stoics, found a hold among these despised sectaries, who learned to believe that men of low birth and foreign extraction might be in divine matters superior to the Avealthy and the educated. In return for this great lesson we may pardon them much folly and much superstition." Prof. Gardner pursues this subject further in his Exploratio Evangelica, pp. 325 if., chapter on "Christianity and the thiasi"; see also Grot'e's History of Greece, part i. ch. i. (vol. i. 19, 20, ed. 1862). 72 THE MYTHS OF PLATO 8. Summary of Introductory Observations in the form OF A Defence of Plato against a Charge brought AGAINST HIM BY KaNT. Let me close this Introduction with a summing up of its meaning, in the form of a defence of Plato against a charge brought by Kant in a well-known passage.^ The light dove, in free flight cleaving the air and feeling its resistance, might imagine that in airless space she would fare better. Even so Plato left the world of sense, because it sets so narrow limits to the understanding, and ventured beyond, on the wings of the Ideas, into the empty space of the pure understanding. He did not see that, with all his effort, he made no way. Here Kant brings against Plato the charge of " transcen- dental use, or rather, misuse, of the Categories of the Under- standing"^ — of supposing super-sensible objects. Soul, Cosmos, God, answering to " Ideas " which have no adequate objects in a possible experience, and then determining these sup- posed objects by means of conceptions — the Categories — the application of which ought to be restricted to sensible objects. In bringing this charge, Kant seems to me to ignore the function which Myth performs in the Platonic philosophy. I submit that the objects which Plato supposes for the "Transcendental Ideas''^ are imaginatively constructed by him, not presented as objects capable of determination by scientific categories — that Plato, by means of the plainly non- scientific language of Myth, guards against the illusions which Kant, guards against by means of " criticism " ; or, to put it otherwise, that Plato's employment of Myth, when he deals with the ideals of Soul, Cosmos, and God — Kant's three Ideas of Keaion — shows that his attitude is " critical," not dog- matic. >l The part which the Myth of Er plays in the philo- sophic action of the Republic may be taken as a specimen of the evidence for this view of Plato's attitude. There is nothing in the Bepuhlic, to my mind, so significant as the ^ Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Einleitung, § 3. * See Krit. d. rein. Fern. : die transc. Dialectik, Einleitung, 1. 3 "Ideas" in Kant's sense, not the Platonic ίδ^αι. INTKODUCTION 73 deep sympathy of its ending with the mood of its beginning. It begins with the Hope of the aged Cephalus — " The sweet hope which guides the wayward thought of mortal man ; " it \ ends with the great Myth in which this Hope is visualised. | As his Hope is sufficient for Cephalus, who retires to his devotions from the company of the debaters, so is the Repre- sentation of it — the Vision of Er — given as sufficient, in the end, for the debaters themselves. To attempt to rationalise here — to give speculative reasons for such a Hope, or against it, would be to forget that it is the foundation of all our special faculties, including the faculty of scientific explanation ; and that science can neither explain away, nor corroborate, its own foundation. The attempt which is made in the latter half of the Tenth Book of the Republic to place the natural expression of this Hope — man's belief in the immortality of the Soul — on a " scientific basis," — to determine " Soul " by j means of " Categories of the Understanding," — I_jregardjas ' intended by the great philosopher-artist to lead up to the Myth of Er, and heighten its eftect by contrast — to give the reader of the Hepuhlic a vivid sense of the fu tility of I rationalism in a regi on wher e Hope confirms itself by " vis ion • splendid."^ ~™^ Of course, I do not deny that passages may be found in which the Ideas of Soul, Cosmos, and God are treated by Plato, without Mythology, as having objects to be determined under the scientific categories of Cause and Substance — e.g. in Phaedrus, 245 E, and Phaedo, 105 c,^ we seem to have 1 "The argument about immortality {Rep. 608c to 612a)," says R. L. Nettleship {Philosophical Lectures and Remains, ii. 355), " does not seem to be in any organic connection either with what actually precedes or with what actually foilows it. It would seem that Plato had two plans in his mind as to how to finish the Republic" I cannot think that Plato had two plans in his mind. The argument for the immortality of the Soul in Rep. 608c-612a is formally so inconclusive that it is impossible to suppose Plato to be serious with it. The equivocal use of the term Death {θάνατοι) in the argument could not have escaped a logician so acute as Plato. The argument is, that, as Injustice (aSt/cia), the proper vice {κακία) of the Soul, does not cause '= Death" {θάνατο$\ in the sense of the separation of Soul from body, nothing else can ever cause " Death " {θάνατοι), now, however, to be understood in the sense of the annihilation of the disembodied Soul itself. 2 Grote {Plato, ii. 190) has an interesting note on PAoecio, 105 c,— "Nemesius, the Christian bishop of Emesa, declares that the proofs given by Plato of the immortality of the Soul are knotty and difficult to understand, such as even adepts in philosophical study can hardly follow. His own belief in it rests upon the inspiration of the Christiai^criptures (Nemesius, de Nat. Homin. c. 2, p. 55, ed. 1565)." 74 THE MYTHS OF PLATO serious scientific argument for the immortality of the Soul — indeed, it would be astonishing if there were no such passages, for the distinction between Category and Idea, as understood by Kant, is not explicit in Plato's mind ; but I submit that I such passages fade into insignificance by the side of the great ' Myths. We are safe in saying at least that, if sometimes Plato lapses into a logical treatment of these ideals, or " Ideas of Eeason," he is well aware that there is another way of treating them, — in Myth, — and that he shows a marked pre- ference for this latter way. The Platonic Myth, then, effects its purpose — the regula- tion of Transcendental Feeling for the service of conduct and science — in two ways which we may profitably distinguish, while admitting that the distinction between them was not explicit in Plato's mind : (1) by representing ideals, and (2) j by tracing faculties hack to their origins. In following either of these two ways the Platonic Myth carries us away to " Places " and " Times " which are, indeed, beyond the ken of sense or science, but yet are felt to be involved in the concrete " Here " and " Now " of ordinary experience. The order in which I propose to take the Myths scarcely amounts to an arrangement of them in two classes according as the object is, either to represent ideals, or trace faculties to their origins, for most of them do both. I shall begin, how- ever, with the Myths which are mainly concerned with ideals, and shall end with those which are mainly concerned with origins. The former, it may be remarked, answer roughly to the so-called Eschatological Myths — but only roughly, for some of them are more properly described as Aetiological ; the latter answer to the Aetiological Myths. I shall take first the Myths in the Pliaedo and Gorgias, and the Myth of Er in the BepuUic, — strictly "Eschato- l ogical " Myths . — which present the Soul as immortal, free within limits set by ανάηκ'η, and responsible, under God's government, throughout all its transmigrations. N ext I shall take the Myth s — mainly " Aetiologica l " — in the Politicus, Fourth Book of the Laws, and Protagoras, where God's creative agency, and government of the Cosmos and Man, are broadly treated, and presented as consistent with the existence of evil. INTEODUCTION 75 Then I shall go on to the Timaeus } in which the three I / i deals, or " Ideas of Eeas on " — Soul, Cosmos, and God — are ' represented in one vast composition. Having examined these Myths — all chiefly interesting as \ representations of ideals, or "Ideas of Eeason" — I shall e xamine three Myths which are chiefly concerned with the deduction of Catecrories or Virtues . These are the Myths in the Fhaedrus, Meno, and Symposium. They are mainly con- cerned with showing how man, as knowing subject and moral agent, is conditioned by his past. Although the "Eschato- logical " outlook, with its hope of future salvation, is by no means absent from these three Myths, their chief interest lies in the way in which, as " Aetiological " Myths, they exhibit the functions of the understanding and moral faculty as cases of άνάμνησίς which, quickened by βρως, interprets the par- ticular impressions, and recognises the particular duties, of the present life, in the light of the remembered vision of the Eternal Forms once seen in the Supercelestial Place. Having examined the Myths which set forth the Ideals and Categories of the Individual, I shall end my review with an examination of tw^o Myths which set forth respectively the I deals and the Categories of a Nation — one of which gives us the spectacle of a Nation led on by a vision of its future, while the other shows us how the life of the "social organism " is conditioned by its past. These are the Atlantis Myth , introduced in the Timaeus and continued in the fragmentary ^ Critias, and the Myth of the Earth-Born in the BepuUi c. The V Atlantis Myth (intended to complete the account of the Ideal \^ State given in the Republic) is to be regarded as an Eschato- logical Myth ; but it differs from the Eschatological Myths of the other class which have been examined in representing, not the future lot of the Individual Soul, but the ideal which a Nation has before it in this world — the ideal of a united Hellas, under a New Athens, maintaining civilisation against the assaults of outer barbarism. After the Atlantis Myth I shall take the Myth of the Earth-Born in the Republic ^ which is an Aetiological Myth, 1 Couturat, de Platonis Mythis (Paris, 1896), p. 32, Tmuieus ipse totus mythicus est ; and Zeller, Plato, p. 160 (Eng. Transl), "The whole investiture of the Timaeus is mythic — the Dtmiurgus, together with the subordinate gods, and all the history of the creation of the Avorld." 76 THE MYTHS OF PLATO differing from the Aetiological Myths of the other class which have been examined, in deducing, not the Categories — faculties and virtues — of the Individual, but the deep-cut characteristics of the "social organism." And yet, here again, while Categories are deduced, an Ideal — that of the orderly life of the καΧλίττοΧις — is represented. Indeed, this is more or less true of all the Platonic Myths. They all view man's present life sub specie aeternitatis — in God; exhibit it as part of the great plan of Providence — as one \ term of a continuous progress to be reviewed at once a parte ante and a parte post. Especially in the Timaeus do we see the " Genesis " and the " Apocalypse " of the Platonic Mythology blended in one Vision. THE ΡΗΛΕΏΟ MYTH Context of the Myth In the Phaedo, the disciple from whom the Dialogue takes its name tells some Friends what was said and done in the Prison on the day of the Master's death. Tlie conversation was concerning the Immortality of the Soul, and was continued wp to the last hour. Cehes and Simmias, the chief speakers, brought forward arguments tending to show that, even granted that the identity of Learning with Reminiscence is in favour of the Orphic doctrine of the pre-existence of the Soul, yet its after-existence, not to mention its immortality, is not proved. Thereupon Socrates brought in the Doctrine of Eternal Ideas — a doctrine which the company were already prepared to accept — and showed, in accordance with it, that Life — and the Soul is Life — excludes Death. Thus was the Immortality of the Soul proved. Next came the practical question : How must a man live that it may he well with him both in this World and in the World Eternal ? It was then that Socrates, standing in the very presence of death, loas filled with the spirit of prophecy, and made able to help his friends before he left them : — If, he said, they took to heart the Myth which he told them, they should know how to live, and it woidd be well with them both now and hereafter for ever. Wlien he had finished the telling of the Myth, and had warned his friends against a too literal interpretation of it, he gave directions about his family and some other private matters ; then the Officef came in with the Cup. 77 78 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Phaedo 107c-114c 107 C Άλλα τόδε γ', βφη, ω άνΒρ€<ζ, Βίκαιον Ζίανοηθηναι οτι, elirep η ψνχ^η αθάνατος, βττιμβλβίας Βη Ββΐται ούχ virep του γρόρου τούτον μόνον, iv φ καΧουμβν το ζην, αλλ virep του τταντός, καϊ ό κίνδυνος νυν Βη καΐ Βοξαβν αν Βεινος elvat, €Ϊ τις αυτής άμεΧησει. el μεν yap ην 6 θάνατος του τταντος ατταλλαγ?;, βρμαιον αν ην τοις κακοίς άττοθανουσι του Τ€ σώματος άμα άττηΧλά'χ^θαι καϊ της αυτών κακίας μ€τά της ψυχής' νυν Be eTretBrj αθάνατος φαίνεται ούσα, D ουΒεμία αν εϊη αυτή άΧλη άττοφυ^ή κακών ούΒε σωτηρία ττλην του ώς βεΧτίστην τε καϊ φρονιμωτάτην γενέσθαι. ούΒεν yap άλΧο έχουσα εις '^ΑιΒου ή ψυχή έρχεται ττλήν τής τταιΒείας τε καϊ τροφής, α Βή καϊ μεyιστa \εyετaι ώφεΧεΐν ή βΧάτττειν τον τεΧευτήσαντα ευθύς εν αρχή τής εκεΐσε ττορείας. Xεyετaι Βε ούτως, ώς άρα τεΧευτήσαντα εκαστον 6 εκάστου Βαίμων, οσττερ ζώντα εΙΧήχει, ούτος άyειv εττιχειρεΐ εις Βή τίνα τοιτον, οΐ ΒεΙ τους ξυXXεyεvτaς Ε Β ιαΒ ι κάσα μεν ους εις ^ Α,ιΒου ττορεύεσθαι μετά ήyεμ6voς εκείνου, ω Βή ττροστετακται τους ενθενΒε εκεΐσε ττορεύσαι. τυχόντας δ* εκεΐ ών Βεΐ τυχεΐν καϊ μείναντας ον χρή χρόνον άΧΧος Βεύρο ττάΧιν ήyεμώv κομίζει εν ττοΧΧαΐς χρόνου καϊ μακραΐς ττεριοΒοις. εστί Βε άρα ή ττορεία ούχ 108 ώς ο ΑΙσχύΧου ΎήΧεφος Xεyει• εκείνος μεν yap άττΧήν οϊμόν φησιν εις '^ΑιΒου φερειν, ή Β' ούτε άττΧή ούτε μία φαίνεται μοι είναι, ούΒε yap αν ήyεμovωv εΒεΐ' ου yap ττού τις αν Βιαμάρτοι ούΒαμόσε μιας οΒού ούσης. νυν Βε εοικε σχίσεις τε καϊ ττεριόΒους ττοΧΧάς εχειν άττο τών οσίων τε καϊ νομίμων τών ενθάΒε τεκμαιρόμενος Xεyω. ή μεν ούν κοσμία τε καϊ φρόνιμος ψυχή εττεταί τε καϊ ουκ ayvoel τα Ίταρόντα' ή Βε εττιθυμητικώς του σώματος έχουσα, Β οΊτερ εν τω εμττροσθεν ειττον, ττερϊ εκείνο ττοΧύν χρόνον ετΓΤοημενη καϊ ττερϊ τον όρατον τόττον, ττοΧΧά άντιτείνασα καϊ ΤΓοΧΧά τταθοΰσα, βία καϊ μόyις ύττο του τΓpoστετay μενού Βαίμονος οϊχεται άyoμεvη. άφικομενην Βε οθιττερ αϊ άΧΧαι, τήν μεν άκάθαρτον και τι ττεττοιηκυΐαν τοιούτον, ή φόνων THE PHAEDO MYTH 79 Tkanslation " It is meet, my friends, that we should take thought of this : — that the Soul, being immortal, standeth in need of care, not only in regard of the time of this present life, but in regard of the time without end, and that 'tis now, even to-day, that the jeopardy is great, if a man will still be careless of his Soul. Were death riddance of all, 'twould be good luck for the wicked man to die and be rid of body and soul and his wickedness ; but inasmuch as the Soul is manifestly immortal, no other escape from evil hath she nor salvation save this — that she be p erfected in righteousness and wisdom. For she taketh hence nothing with her to the House of Hades, save only her instruction and nurture — that, to wit, where- from they say the greatest profit cometh to the dead or greatest damage straightway at the beginning of their journey thither ; for when a man dieth, his own Familiar Spirit, which had gotten him to keep whilst he lived, taketh and leadeth him to a certain place whither the dead must be gathered together; whence, after they have received their sentences, they must journey to the House of Hades with him who hath been appointed to guide thither those that are here; and when they have received there the things which are meet for them, and have sojourned the time determined, another Guide bringeth them again hither, after many long courses of time. The way, belike, is not as Aeschylus his Telephus telleth ; for he saith that a single path leadeth to the House of Hades. But, methinks, if it were single and one, there would be no need of guides, for no man would go astray. Nay, that it hath many partings and windings I conclude from the offerings which men use to make unto the dead. " The Soul which ordereth herself aright and hath wisdom, understandeth well her present case, and goeth with her Familiar. But the Soul which lusteth after the body, having fluttered about it and the Visible Place for a long while, and having withstood her appointed Familiar with great strife and pain, is by him at the last mastered and carried away ; and when she is come to the place where the other Souls are assembled together, inasmuch as ^e is impure and hath wrought that 80 THE MYTHS OF PLATO αδίκων ημμβρην rj αλλ αττα τοίαντα €ίρ<γασμ6νην, α τούτων άΒβΧφά τ€ καΐ άΒέλφων ψνχ^ων epya τνγχάνει, οντά, ταύτην μβν άττας (j>evyev re και νττβκτρβττβταί καί ούτε ξυνέμτΓορος οντ€ τρέμων iOeXei, yiyveaOaLy αύτη he ττλανάταί C iv ττάστ) β'χρμίνη άττορία, βω? άν 8ή τίνες 'χρόνοι, Ύβνωνται, ων ξξεΧθόντων ύττ ανάγκης φέρεται εις την αύτη ττρετΓουσαν οϊκησιν' ή Βε καθαρώς τε καΐ μετρίως τον βίον ΒίεξεΧθονσα, κα\ ξννεμττόρων καΐ ηγεμόνων θεών τυχούσα, ωκησε τον αύτη εκάστη τόττον ττροσηκοντα, ΈίΙσΙ Βε ττολλοί καΐ θαυμαστοί της ^ης τόττοι, και αύτη ούτε οΧα ούτε οση Βοξάζεταο ύττο τών ττερί γής εΐωθότων Χε^ειν, ώς iyo) υπό τίνος ττεττεισμαι, ΚαΙ 6 Χίμμίας, ΤΙώς D ταύτα, εφη, Χέζεις, ώ Χώκρατες ; ττερΙ yap tol της γης καϊ αύτος ττοΧΧα Βη άκηκοα, ού μεντοί ταύτα, α σε ττείθεί. ήΒεως αν ονν άκούσαιμι. Αλλά μεντοι, ώ %ιμμία, ούχ ή ΤΧαύκου yk μοί τέχνη Βοκεΐ είναι Βιηγησασθαι α y εστίν ώς μεντοί άΧηθή, χαΧεττώτερόν μοι φαίνεται ή κατά την ΤΧαύκου τέχνην, καϊ άμα μεν iyoo ϊσως ούΒ^ άν οΙός τε εϊην, άμα Βε, εΐ καϊ ήττίστάμην, 6 βίος μου Βοκεΐ ο εμός, ώ Ζ,ιμμία, τω μηκει του Χόγου ούκ εξαρκεϊν. την μεντοο Ε ΙΒεαν της yής, οίαν ττεττεισμαι είναι, καϊ τους τόττους αύτης ούΒεν με κωΧύει Χεγειν. 'Αλλ', εφη 6 '^ι,μμίας, καϊ ταύτα άρκεΐ, ΐΐέττείσμαι τοίνυν, η δ' 6ς, εγώ, ώς ττρώτον μεν, εΐ εστίν εν μέσω τω ούρανω ττεριφερης ούσα, μηΒεν αύτη Βεΐν 109 μητε άερος ττρος το μη ττεσεΐν μήτε άΧΧης ανάγκης μηΒεμιάς τοιαύτης, άΧΧά Ικανην είναι αύτην ϊσχειν την ομοιότητα του ουρανού αυτού εαυτω ττάντη καϊ της γης αυτής την ΙσορροΊΓίαν' ίσορροττον γαρ ττράγμα ομοίου τινός εν μέσω τεθεν ούχ εξει μάΧΧον ούΒ' ήττον ούΒαμόσε κΧιθήναι, ομοίως δ' έχον άκΧινες μενεΐ. ττρώτον μεν τοίνυν, ή δ' 6ς, τούτο ττεττεισμαι. Καϊ ορθώς γε, εφη ό %ιμμίας. 'Έτλ τοίνυν, εφη, ττάμμε^ά τι είναι αυτό, καϊ ημάς οίκεΐν τους Β μέχρι 'ϊΙρακΧείων στηΧών άττό ΦάσιΒος εν σμικρω τινι μορίω, ώσττερ ττερΙ τεΧμα μύρμηκας ή βατράχους, ττερΙ την THE PHAEDO MYTH 81 which is impure, having shed innocent blood, or done like deeds which Souls that are her like use to do, her all flee and eschew, and none will be her companion or guide ; wherefore she wandereth alone in great stress, until certain times have been accomplished; then is she constrained to go unto the habitation fit for her. But the Soul which hath lived all her days in purity and sobriety hath given unto her Gods to be her companions and guides, and she maketh her habitation in the place meet for her. " The Earth hath many and wondrous places, and it is of a fashion and greatness whereof those who use to tell concerning the Earth have no true opinion. There is one who hath persuaded me of this." " Socrates," quoth Simmias, " how sayest thou this ? for I also have heard many things concerning the Earth, but not this of which thou art persuaded. Wherefore I would gladly hear it." " Well, Simmias," quoth he, " methinks it needeth not the skill of Glaucus to set forth that which I have heard; but the truth thereof, which I wot it surpasseth the skill of Glaucus to find out, haply I should not be able to attain unto : nay, if I knew it, my life is too far spent, methinks, for the length of the discourse which should declare it : but my persuasion as touching the Earth and the places it hath nothing hindereth me from declaring unto thee." " That is enough," said Simmias. " I am persuaded, then," said he, " of this first — that if the Earth, being a globe, is in the middle of the Heaven, it hath no need of air or any other like constraint to keep it from falling, but 'tis sufficient to hold it that the Heaven is of one substance throughout, and that itself is equally balanced : for that which is itself equally balanced and set in the midst of that which hath one substance, will have no cause at all of inclining towards any side, but will continue the same and remain without inclination. Of this first I am persuaded." " And rightly," said Simmias. " Moreover, I am persuaded that the Earth is very great, and that we who inhabit unto the Pillars of Hercules from the river Phasis dwell in a small part thereof, like unto ants or frogs round about a ^ool, dwelling round this Sea ; and G 82 THE MYTHS OF PLATO ΘαΚατταν οίκοννταζ, καϊ αΧ\ον<ί aWoOc ττολλου? iv ττοΧΧοΐς τοίούτοις τότΓΟίς οίκεΐν. elvai yap ττανταχτ) ττβρί την yrjv ΤΓολλα κοίλα καϊ τταντοΒαττα καϊ τας ΙΒβας καϊ τα με^εθη^ €19 α ξυνβρρυηκεναι τ6 τ€ ν8ωρ καϊ την ομίχΧην καϊ τον aepa' αντην δε την yrjv καθαραν iv καθαρω κβΐσθαι τω ου ράνω, iv ωττβρ βστί τα άστρα, ον Srj αΙθέρα ονομάζειν C τού? ΤΓοΧΚονς των irepl τα τοιαύτα βίωθότων Xiyeiv ου Βη ύτΓοστάθμην ταΰτα elvai καϊ ξνρρείν aei el<; τα κοΊΧα τη<; y7jηVy €φη 6 ^ι,μμίας, ω ^ώκρατ€<ζ, ήμ€Ϊς ye τούτου τον μύθου ήΒέωζ αν άκούσαιμ^ν. AeycTac τοίνυν, βφη, ω βταΐρβ, ττρωτον μβν elvai τοιαύτη η yrj αΰτη Ihelv, €Ϊ τι<ζ άνωθεν θβωτο, ώσττβρ αΐ ΒωΒβκάσκυτοι σφαΐραι, ττοικίΧη, 'χρώμασι 8ΐ€ίλημμ€νη, ων καΐ τα ένθάΒε C elvai, 'χ^ρώματα ώσττερ 8eίyμaτa, οίς Βη οι ypaφ6L<ζ κατα- ^ρώνταί, €Κ€Ϊ δε ττασαν την yrjv εκ τοιούτων elvat, καΐ ΊΓοΧύ €Tt εκ Χαμττροτερων καΐ καθαρωτερων η τούτων την μεν yap aλoυpyή είναι, καΐ θαυμαστην το κάλλος, την Βε χ^ρυσοειΒή, την Βε οση Χευκη yύψoυ η γ^ιόνος Χευκοτεραν, καΐ εκ των άλΧων 'χρωμάτων ξυyκειμεvηv ωσαύτως, και ετι ττΧειόνων και καΧΧιόνων ή οσα ημείς εωράκαμεν. και yap αύτα ταύτα τα κοΐΧα αυτής, ΰΒατός τε και άερος εμττΧεα Ό όντα, χρώματος τι εΙΒος τταρεχεσθαι στίΧβοντα εν Tjj των άΧΧων χρωμάτων ιτοικιΧία, ώστε εν τι αυτής εϊΒος ξυνεχες ΤΓΟίκίΧον φαντάζεσθαι. εν Βε ταύττ} οΰση τοιαύτη ανά Xoyov τα φυόμενα φύεσθαι, ΒενΒρα τε καΐ άνθη και τους καρττούς- και αΰ τά ορη ωσαύτως και τους Χίθους εχειν ανά τον αυτόν Xoyov την τε Χειοτητα καΐ την Βιαφάνειαν και τά χρώματα καΧΧίω' ων καΐ τά ενθάΒε ΧιθίΒια είναι ταύτα τά άya^Γώμεva μόρια, σάρΒιά τε και ίάσττιΒας και σμapάy- Ε Βους και ττάντα τά τοιαύτα' εκεΐ Βε ούΒεν 6 τι ου τοιούτον είναι και ετι τούτων καΧΧίω, το δ* αίτιον τούτου είναι, ΟΤΙ εκείνοι οι Χίθοι είσΐ καθαροί και ου κατεΒηΒεσμενοι ούΒε Βιεφθαρμενοι ώσττερ οι ενθάΒε ύττο σηττεΒόνος και άλμης ύττο των Βεΰρο ξυνερρυηκότων, ά καΐ Χίθοις και yjj και τοις άΧΧοις ζώοις τε και φυτοΐς αΐσχη τε καΐ νόσους τταρεχει. την Βε yήv αύτην κεκοσμήσθαι τούτοις τε άττασι 111 και ετι χρυσω τε και άpyύpω και τοις άΧΧοις αΰ τοΐ^ τοιούτοις. εκφανή yap αυτά ττεφυκεναι, οντά ΤΓοΧΧά ττΧηθει και μεyaXa και ττολΧαχου της yής, ώστε αύτην ΙΒεΐν είναι θέαμα εύΒαιμονων θεατών, ζώα δ' eV* αυτής είναι άΧΧα τε τΓοΧΧα και άνθρώττους, τους μεν εν μεσoyaίa οίκούντας, τους Βε ττερι τον άερα ώσττερ ημείς ττερι την θάλατταν^ τους Βε εν νήσοις, άς ττεριρρεΐν τον άερα, ττρος τη ηττείρω ούσας' και ενϊ λόγω, οττερ ήμΐν το ΰΒωρ καΐ ή θάΧαττά Β εστί ττρος την ημετεραν χρείαν, τούτο εκεΐ τον άερα, ο Βε ήμΐν 6 αήρ, εκείνοις τον αιθέρα, τάς Βε ώρας αύτοΐς κράσιν THE ΡΗΛΕΌΟ MYTH 85 " Indeed, Socrates," quoth he, " we would gladly hear this Tale." " The beginning of the Tale, then, is this, my friend, that the Earth itself, if any one look down on it from the Heaven, is like unto a ball which is fashioned with twelve leathern stripes, whereof each hath his own colour. These be the colours whereof the colours here which limners use are as samples ; but there the whole Earth is of such, yea of far brighter than these and purer ; for one part is purple and of marvellous beauty, and another part is like gold, and all that part which is white is whiter than chalk or snow, and in like manner unto other parts are portioned the other colours — yea, and colours besides more than all those which we have seen here and fairer; for even these hollows of the Earth, being full to the brim of water and air, display a specific colour wherewith they glisten in the midst of the variety of the other colours, so that the face of the Earth seemeth, as it were, one picture of many colours contiguous, without blot. "According as the Earth is, so also are the things which grow therein — her trees and flowers and fruits ; and so also are her mountains, and her stones, which are polished and transparent and of exceeding fair colours ; whereof the precious stones here are fragments — sardian, jasper, smaragdus, and all such : but in that place there is no stone which is not as these are and fairer. The reason whereof is this, that the stones there are pure, and are not eaten away or corrupted as are the stones here by the rot and salt of that sediment which is gathered together here, whereof come, unto stones, and earth, and likewise unto beasts and herbs, deformities and diseases. Now, the True Earth hath these things, and also gold and silver and other things like unto them for her ornaments ; for there they are not hidden but manifest, and are in abundance, and of exceeding greatness, and in many places of that Earth ; so that to behold it is a sight meet for the eyes of the blessed. And on that Earth there are beasts of many kinds, and men, whereof some dwell in the inland parts, and some round about the Air, as we about the Sea, and some in islands encompassed by the Air, hard by the mainland ; for that which Water is and the Sea with us for our use, the Air is in that region, and that which the Air is* with us, the Aether is with them. 86 THE MYTHS OF PLATO €'χ^ζΐν τοίαντψ', ώστ€ εκείνους άνοσους elvai καΧ 'χρόνον re ζην ΤΓολυ Ίτλειω των ενθάΒε καΐ όψει καΐ άκοτ) και οσφρησει ^ και ττάσι τοις τοιούτοις ημών άφεστάναι τη αύτη άτΓοστάσει, ηττερ άηρ τε ΰΒατος άψεστηκε καΐ αίθηρ άερος Ίτρος καθαρότητα, και Βη και θέων εΒη ^ τε και Ιερα αύτοΐς είναι, εν οίς τω οντι οίκητας θεούς εϊναι, και φημας τε και μαντείας και αισθήσεις των θεών καΐ τοιαύτας C ξυνουσίας ηίηνεσθαι αύτοΐς ιτρος αυτούς' και τον <γε ηλιον και σεληνην καΐ άστρα οράσθαι ύττ αυτών οϊα τυγχ^άνει οντά, καΐ την άΧλην εύΒαιμονίαν τούτων άκόΧουθον εϊναι. ΚαΙ ολην μεν Βη την yrjv ούτω ττεφυκεναι και τα ττερϊ την yrjv τότΓους Β εν αύτη είναι κατά τα 'iy κοίλα αυτής κύκΧω ΊτερΙ οΧην ττοΧΚούς, τους μεν βαθύτερους καΐ άναττε- ΤΓταμενους μαΧΚον ή εν ω ημείς οίκουμεν, τους Βε βαθύ- τερους οντάς το γάσμα αυτούς εΚαττον εγειν του τταρ D ημίν τοτΓου, εστί Β ους καΐ βραγυτερους τω βάθει του ενθάΒε εϊναι και ττΧατυτέρους. τούτους Βε ττάντας ύττο yrjv εις άΧληΧους συντετρήσθαί τε ττοΧλαχτ), και κατά στενότερα και ευρύτερα, και ΒιεξοΒους ε'χειν, η ττοΧύ μεν ΰΒωρ ρεΐν εξ όΧΚηΧων εΙς αΧΧηΧους ώσιτερ εΙς κρατήρας, και άενάων ΤΓΟταμών άμη'χανα μεγέθη ύττο την ^ήν και θερμών ύΒάτων και ψυχ^ρών, ττοΧύ Βε ττϋρ καϊ ττυρος με^άΧους ττοταμούς, ΤΓοΧΧους Βε ύ^ρου ττηΧού και καθαρωτερου καϊ βορβορωΒε- Ε στερου, ωσττερ εν ΧικεΧία οι ττρο του ρύακος ττηΧοϋ ρέοντες ΤΓΟταμοι και αύτος ο ρύαξ* ων Βη καϊ εκάστους τους τόττους ττΧηροϋσθαι, ων αν εκάστοις τύγτ) εκάστοτε ή ττεριρροη ηιηνομενη. ταύτα Βε ττάντα κινεΐν άνω και κάτω ώσττερ αιωραν τίνα ενουσαν εν τη yrj. εστί Βε άρα αύτη ή αιώρα οια φυσιν τοιανΒε τινά. εν τι τών γασμάτων τής ^ής αΧΧως τε με^ιστον τυγχάνει ον και Βιαμττερες τετρημενον 112 Βι οΧης τής ^ής, τούτο οττερ 'Όμηρος Διτε, Χε^ων αυτό τήλ€ μάΧ^ yxi βάθιχττον ύττο χθονο^ 1(ττι βψζθρον^ ο και αΧΧοθι καϊ εκείνος και άΧΧοι ττοΧΧοϊ τών ττοιητών Ύάρταρον κεκΧήκασιν. εις yap τούτο το χάσμα συρρεουσί τε ττάντες οι ιτοταμοϊ και εκ τούτου ττάΧιν εκρεουσι- yiyvovTai Βε έκαστοι τοιούτοι, Βι* οίας αν καΐ τής yής ρεωσιν • ή δ' αιτία εστί του εκρεΐν τε εντεύθεν καϊ είσρειν Β ττάντα τα ρεύματα, οτι ττυθμενα ούκ έχει ούΒε βάσιν το 1 φρονήα-ει. 2 ^χ^^^ THE PHAEDO MYTH 87 Moreover, their seasons are so tempered that disease smiteth them not at all, and they live far beyond the measure of our days, and as touching eyesight, and hearing, and wisdom, and all such parts, are distant from us even as Air is distant from Water, and Aether is distant from Air in purity. Also they have groves of the Gods and temples wherein Gods verily are dwellers ; into whose very presence men come, hearing their voices and their prophecies and seeing them face to face. Moreover, the sun and moon and stars are seen there as they are truly ; and likewise in all things else the state of these men is blessed. " The Earth itself, then, and the parts that encompass the Earth are thus fashioned. But the Tale also telleth that in the Earth are many hollow places round about her whole girth, whereof some are deeper and more open than this place we dwell in, and some are deeper with a narrower mouth, and some are shallower and broader : all these are joined together, having channels bored under the Earth from one to another in many places, some narrow and some wide, whereby passage is given so that much water floweth from one into another, as into bowls, and measureless floods of perennial rivers run under the Earth, and streams hot and cold ; also much fire floweth, and there are great rivers of fire, and many rivers of running mud, some clearer, some thicker, even as in Sicily there run before the fiery flood rivers of mud, and then cometh the fiery flood. With these floods, therefore, each place is filled according as at each time the stream floweth round unto each. Now, all these waters are moved upward and downward by that in the Earth which swayeth like a swing. And it swayeth after this wise. There is a cavern in the Earth, which is the greatest of them all, and, moreover, pierceth right through the whole Earth, whereof Homer maketh mention, saying, 'Afar off, where deepest underground the Pit is digged,' which he in other places, and many of the other poets, call Tartarus. Now, into this cavern all the rivers flow, and from it flow out again, and each one becometh such as is that part of the Earth it floweth through. The cause of all streams flowing out and flowing in is that this flood hath no bottom or foundation. Wherefore it 88 THE MYTHS OF PLATO vypov TovTO, αΙωρ^Ιταν Βη καί κνμαίνβι, ανω καΐ κάτω, καυ ο άηρ καϊ το ττνβνμα το rrepl αυτό ταυτον ττοιβΐ' ξυνίιτβταυ yap αντω καϊ όταν βίς το έττέκβινα της >γής ορμήστ) καϊ όταν €t9 το €7γΙ τάΒβ, καϊ ωσττβρ των άναπνβόντων act eKirvel re καϊ avairvel peov το ττνβνμα, οντω καϊ €Κ€Ϊ ξυναιωρούμβνον τω ύ^γρω το ττνζνμα Βεινούς τινας άνεμους καϊ άμηγάνους τταρέχεται καϊ eiaiov καϊ έξών. όταν Τ€ οΰν C όρμησαν υττο'χωρηστι το ΰΒωρ eh τον τοττον τον Βη κάτω καΧούμενον, τοις κατ εκείνα τα ρεύματα Βια της γης είσρεί τε καϊ ττΧηροΙ αύτα ωσττερ οί ετταντΧοΰντες' όταν τε αυ εκείθεν μεν άτΓοΧίτττ), Βεΰρο Βε ορμηση, τα ενθάΒε ττΧηροΐ αύθις, τα Βε ΤΓΧηρωθεντα ρεΐ Βία των ογετων καϊ Βία της 7^9, καϊ εΙς τους τόπους έκαστα άφίκνούμενα, εις ους εκάστους οΒοττοίεΐταο, θαΧάττας τε καϊ Χίμνας καϊ ττοταμους καϊ κρηνας ττοιεί. εντεύθεν Βε ττάΧιν Βυόμενα κατά της ^ης, D τα μεν μακροτέρους τόττους ττεροεΧθόντα καϊ ττΧείους, τα Βε εΧάττους καϊ βραδύτερους, ττάΧίν εις τον Ύάρταρον εμβάΧΧεί, τα μεν ττοΧύ κατωτέρω η εττηντΧεΐτο, τα Βε oXiyov' Ίτάντα Βε ύττοκάτω εΙσρεΐ της εκροής, καϊ ενια μεν καταντικρύ rj εΙσρεΐ εξεττεσεν, ενια Βε κατά το αύτο μέρος' εστί Βε καϊ ά τταντάττασι κύκΧω ττεριεΧθόντα, η άτταξ η καϊ ΊτΧεονάκίς πτεριεΧί'χθέντα πτερϊ την yrjv ώσττερ οί οφεις, εΙς το Βυνατον κάτω καθεντα ττάΧιν εμβάΧΧεν. Βυνατον δ' Ε εστίν εκατερωσε μέ'χρο του μέσου καθιεναι, ττέρα δ' οι;. άναντες yap άμφοτεροις τοις ρεύμασι το εκατέρωθεν yίyvετaι μέρος. Τα μεν ούν Βη άΧΧα ττοΧΧά τε καϊ μεyάXa καϊ τταντοΒαττά ρεύματα εστί' τυy'χάvεί δ* άρα οντά εν τούτοις τοις τΓοΧΧοΐς τέτταρ άττα ρεύματα, ων το μεν μέyίστov και εξωτάτω ρέον ττερϊ κύκΧω 6 καΧούμενος 'Ω,κεανός εστί, τούτου Βέ καταντικρύ καϊ εναντίως ρέων ^Κγέρων, ος Βι 113 έρημων τε τοττων ρεΐ άΧΧων καϊ Βη καϊ ύττο yrjv ρέων εις την Χιμνην άφικνεΐται την ^ Α.'χερουσιάΒα, ου αί των τετεΧευτη κοτών ψυχαϊ των ττοΧΧών άφικνούνται καί τινας ειμαρμενους χ^ρονους μείνασαι, αι μεν μακροτέρους, αί Βε βραγυτέρους, ττάΧιν εκΊτέμίΓονται εις τάς των ζώων yεvέσεις. τρίτος Βέ ΤΓΟταμος τούτων κατά μέσον εκβάΧΧει, καϊ εγγύ? της εκβοΧής εκττίτττεί εις τόττον μέyav ττυρϊ ττοΧΧω καόμενον. THE ΡΗΛΕΌΟ MYTH 89 swingeth and surgeth up and down, and the air and wind surge with it ; for the wind goeth with it when it rusheth to the further side of the Earth, and with it returneth hitherward ; and even as the breath of living creatures is driven forth and drawn in as a stream continually, so there also the wind, swinging with the flood, cometh in and goeth out, and causeth terrible, mighty tempests. Now, when the water rusheth back into the place "beneath," as men speak, coming unto the region of the streams which run through that part of the Earth, it floweth into them and filleth them, as men fill reservoirs with pumps ; but when it ebbs again from thence and rusheth hither, it filleth again the streams here, which, being full, run through their conduits and through the Earth, coming severally to those places whither they are bound, and make seas and lakes and rivers and fountains. Thence they sink under the Earth again, and some, having fetched a longer compass and some a shorter, fall again into Tartarus, some far beneath the channel into which they were pumped up, and some a little way beneath ; but all flow into Tartarus again beneath the places of their outflowing. Some waters there be that, coming forth out of the Earth at one side thereof, flow in at the contrary side ; and some that go in and come out on the same side ; and some there be that go round the whole Earth and are wound about it once — yea, perchance, many times, like serpents. These rivers pour their waters back into Tartarus as low down as water can fall. Now, it can fall as far as the centre in each way, but no further : each half of the Earth is a hill against the stream that floweth from the side of the other half. " Now there are many great rivers of divers sorts, but amongst these there are four chiefest : whereof that one which is greatest, and floweth round the outermost, is that which is called Ocean, and over against him is Acheron, which floweth the contrary way, and flowing through desert places and also under the Earth, cometh to the Acherusian Lake, whither the Souls of the most part of the dead do come, and having sojourned there certain appointed times, some longer, some shorter, are again led forth to be born in the flesh. The third river issues forth betwixt these, and, near unto the part whence it issues forth, falleth into a great place burning 90 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Koi Χίμνην 7Γ016Ϊ μβίζω της irap* ήμΐν θαλάττης, ζεουσαν υδατο? καΧ ττηΧοϋ' evrevOev δε χωρ€Ϊ κύκλω θοΧβρος καΐ Β ττηλώΒης, ττεριεΧίττόμβνος δε [rrj yrj] άΧλοσβ Τ6 άφίκνεΐται καΐ Ίταρ^ βσγατα της ^Α'χερουσνάΒος Χίμνης, ου ξνμμι- ^νύμενος τω vBaTL• ττεριέΧί'χ^θεΙς δε ττοΧΧάκις νττο ^ής εμβάΧΧβυ κατωτέρω του Ύαρτάρου. ούτος δ* εστίν ον Ιττονομάζουσι ΤΙυρίφΧε'γεθοντα, ου καΙ ο Ι ρύακες άττο- σιτάσματα άναφυσώσιν, οτττ) αν τύγωσι της yής. τούτου δε αΰ καταντικρύ 6 τέταρτος εκττίτττεί εΙς τόττον ττρώτον Βεινον τε καΐ aypiov, ώς Χε^εται^ 'χ^ρωμα δε β'χρντα οΧον οίον 6 C κυανός, ον 8η εττονομάζουσι %τύ<γίον, καΐ την Χίμνην, ην ΤΓΟίεΐ 6 τΓοταμος εμβάΧΧων, Στυγα. ο δ' εμττεσων ενταύθα καΐ Βει,νας δυνάμεις Χαβων εν τω ϋ8ατί, Βύς κατά της γης, ττεριεΧίττόμενος χορεΐ ενάντιος τω ΥίυρίφΧεγεθοντι καΐ άτταντα εν ttj ^ΑχερουσιάΒί Χίμνχι εξ εναντίας' καϊ ούΒε το τούτου ΰΒωρ ούΒενΙ μίγνυται, άΧΧα καϊ ούτος κύκΧω ττεριεΧθων εμβάΧΧεί εΙς τον Ύάρταρον εναντίως τω ΤΙυρίφΧεγεθοντί' όνομα δε τούτω εστίν, ως οΐ ττοιηταΐ Χε^ουσί, Κωκυτός. D Τούτων δε οΰτω ττεφυκότων, εττειΒαν άφίκωνταο οΐ τετεΧευτη κότες εΙς τον τόττον, οΐ ο ΒαΙμων εκαστον κομίζει, ττρώτον μεν ΒιεΒίκάσαντο οι τε καΧώς καϊ όσίως βιώσαντες καϊ οι μη. καϊ οΐ μεν αν Βόξωσί μέσως βεβιωκεναι, ττορευθεντες εττΐ τον ^Αχέροντα, άναβάντες α Βη αύτοίς οχήματα εστίν, εττΐ τούτων άφίκνοΰνταί εΙς την Χίμνην, καϊ εκεί οίκούσί τε και καθαφόμενοί των τε άΒικημάτων ΒιΒοντες Βίκας άττοΧύονται, εϊ τις τυ ηΒίκηκε, των τε Ε ευεργεσιών τιμάς φέρονται κατά την άξίαν έκαστος* οι δ' αν Βοξωσιν άνιάτως εχειν Βια τα μεγέθη των αμαρτημάτων, η ιεροσυΧίας ττοΧΧας καϊ μεγάΧας ή φόνους άΒίκους καϊ τταρανομους ττοΧΧούς εξειργασμενοι, η αΧΧα οσα τοιαύτα τυγχάνει οντά, τούτους δε η ττροσηκουσα μοίρα ρίτττει εις τον Ύάρταρον, όθεν οΰττοτε εκβαίνουσιν, οι δ' αν ιάσιμα μεν, μεγάΧα δε Βοξωσιν ήμαρτηκεναι αμαρτήματα, οίον ττρος ττατερα η μητέρα ύττ οργής βίαιόν τι ττράξαντες, και, 114 μεταμεΧον αύτοΐς, τον ςίΧΧον βίον βιώσιν, ή άνΒροφόνοι τοιουτω τινι άΧΧω τρόττω γενωνται, τούτους δε εμττεσεΐν μεν εις τον Ύάρταρον ανάγκη, εμττεσόντας δε αυτούς καϊ ενιαυτον εκεί γενομένους εκβάΧΧει το κύμα, τους μεν THE ΡΗΛΕΌΟ MYTH 91 with much fire, and maketh a lake greater than our Sea, seething with water and mud : thence it fetch eth a compass, and going thick and muddy, and winding round the Earth, cometh at last unto the coasts of the Acherusian Lake, mixing not with the water thereof. Then after many windings under the Earth it poureth itself into a lower part of Tartarus. This is the river which they name Pyriphlegethon, whereof also the fiery floods which boil up in divers places of the Earth are derivations. Over against him the fourth river issues forth, first into a fearful savage place, they tell, which hath wholly the colour of blue steel ; and they call it the Stygian place, and the Lake which the river maketh with his flood they call Styx ; wherein to this river falling conceiveth mighty virtues in his water, and afterward sinketh under the Earth, and windeth round, going contrary to Pyriphlegethon, and cometh to the Acherusian Lake from the contrary side : neither doth his water mix with any; but he also goeth round about, and falleth into Tartarus over against Pyri- phlegethon. The name of this river, the poets tell, is Cocytus. " When the dead are come unto the place whither his Familiar bringeth each, first are they judged, and according as they have lived righteous and godly lives, or lived un- righteously, are they divided. Thereafter all those who are deemed to have lived indifferently well journey unto Acheron, and go on board the vessels which are prepared for them, and so come to the Lake ; and abiding there, get themselves cleansed, and paying the price of their evil deeds, are acquitted from the guilt thereof; and for their good deeds receive each the reward that is meet. But whoso are deemed incurable by reason of the greatness of their sins, robbers of temples, and those who have oftentimes shed blood unlaw- fully, or wrought other iniquities that are great, them the appointed Angel doth cast into Tartarus, and thence they come not out at all : and whoso are deemed to have com- mitted sins great but curable, who in wrath have violently entreated father or mother and have repented them thereof all the days of their lives thereafter, or who in like manner are manslayers, they must needs fall into Tartarus, but when they have been there one year, the surge casts them forth, the 92 THE MYTHS OF PLATO άνΒροφόνονς κατά τον Κωκντόρ, τους Be ττατραΧοίας καΙ μητράλοίας κατά τον VLvpL(\>\eyeeovTa' eireihav 8k φβρόμβ- VOL ^ένωνται κατά την Χίμνην την Αχερουσ^αδα, έντανθα βοωσί τ€ καΐ καΧοΰσιν, οί μεν ους άττβκτβιναν, οί Se ους Β ύβρισαν, καΧεσαντες δ' Ικετβύονσι καΐ Βεονταυ idaac σφάς €κβήναι eh την Χίμνην καΐ Βέξασθαί, καΐ eav μεν ττείσωσιν, Ικβαίνουσί τ€ κα\ Χη^ουσι των κακών, el Be μη, φέρονται αύθις eh τον Ύάρταρον KaKeWev ττάΧιν eh τους ττοταμονς, και ταύτα ιτάσγοντες ου ττροτερον τταύονται, ττρίν αν ττείσωσιν ους ηΒίκησαν αΰτη yap η Βίκη ύττο των Βικαστών αύτοΐς ετά'χθη. οι Be Βη αν Βόξωσι Βιαφεροντως ττρος το οσίως βιωναι, ουτοί eiaiv οί τώνΒε μεν των τόττων των ev τη yfj εΧευθερούμενοί τε και άτταΧΧαττόμενοι ωσπτερ C Βεσμωτηρίων, άνω Βε εh την καθαραν οίκησιν άφικνούμενοι και €7Γΐ της γης οίκιζομενοι. τούτων Βε. αυτών οι φιΧοσοφία ίκανώς καθηράμενοι άνευ τε σωμάτων ζώσι το τταράτταν eh τον εττεντα 'χ^ρόνον, και eh οικήσεις ετι τούτων καΧΧίους άφικνουνται, ας ούτε ραΒιον ΒηΧώσαι οΰτε 6 'χ^ρόνος ικανός εν τω τταρόντι. Αλλά τούτων Βή ένεκα 'χρή ών ΒιεΧηΧύθαμεν, ώ Έ^ιμμία, τταν ττοιεΐν, ώστε αρετής και φρονήσεως εν τω βίω μετασ'χεΐν καΧον yap το άθΧον καΐ ή βλττΐ? μεyάXη, THE ΡΗΛΕΌΟ MYTH 93 manslayers by Cocytus, and the slayers of father or mother by Pyriphlegethon ; and when they are carried down and are come to the Acherusian Lake, there they cry out aloud unto those whom they slew or used despitefuUy, and call upon them and beseech them with prayers that they will suffer them to come out into the Lake and will receive them ; and if they prevail, they come out and cease from their torments ; but if they prevail not, they are carried back into Tartarus, and thence again into the rivers, and they cease not from this torment till they have prevailed with those whom they have wronged ; for this was the doom that was appointed of the Judges unto them. But whosoever are deemed to have been godly above others in their lives, they are released from these places in the Earth, and depart from them as from a prison- house, and come unto the Pure Mansions which are above, and dwell upon the Earth. And of these whoso have cleansed themselves throughly by Wisdom live without fleshly bodies for evermore, and come to yet fairer Mansions, whereof it is not easy to tell, nor doth the time now suffice for the telling. Nevertheless, by that which hath been told are we admonished to do all so that we may lay hold of Kighteousness and Wisdom in this life ; for the prize is fair and the hope is great." 94 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Observations on the Phaedo Myth I We may begin by noting that Plato here, as elsewhere, gives verisimilitude to Myth by making it explain facts, or what he accepts as facts, and bringing it, as far as possible, into conformity with the " modern science " of his day. The fact of the Earth's rotundity had already been ascertained — or guessed — in Plato's day ; ^ and the geography of the Myth is made consistent with this fact, as well as with the supposed " fact " of the Earth's central position in the Cosmos — a position which it retains for a sufficient reason, which Plato sets forth " scientifically." The Phaedo Myth, starting with the " scientific truths " of the Earth's rotundity and central position, gives a consistent geography, which makes it easy for the reader to localise the " Earthly Paradise " and Tartarus, as real places continuous with the part of the world which men inhabit. Geo graphy is treated in this Myth, as ancient h istor y may, or must, be treated according to Plato — romanti- call y : the general scheme is, as far as possible, true to facts ; but blanks are filled in by μ.υθοΚ.οψα? The line between uncritical " science " and μ,υθόΚο^ία is difficult to draw, and Plato knows how to turn the difficulty to artistic, and more than that — to philosophic use. A sophistic use of the difficulty he happily has no temptation to make, because he holds no brief obliging him to contend for a large amount of literal truth in the traditional myths which he borrows. Again, the Phaedo Myth recommends itself to the " scien- tific mind " by explaining the origin of hot and cold springs, volcanic action, winds, and, I think, the tides of the Atlantic Ocean. The suggestion, too, that gems — objects which have 1 See ZqWqvs Plato, Engl. Transl. pp. 379, 380. ^ See E^puhlic, 382 d, koI iu als νυν δή έλέΎομβν rats μυθολοΎίαΐί, δίά τό μη (ίδέναι ό'τΓτ? τάληθβί ^χβι wepl των τταλαιών, άφομοωΰντεί τφ άληθεΐ τό ψευδοί Οτι μάλιστα οϋτω χρήσιμον ποιοΰμεν ; καΐ μάλα, ^ δ' 8s. Cf. Legg. 682 ff., where the early ^history of mankind appears as a my th, ' founded on fact, but embellished— τΓολλών των κατ^ άΧήθβιαν "γι-^νομένων ξύν τισι χάρισι καΐ Μουσαίε έφάττεται εκάστοτε ; and cf. Campbell's Politicus, Introd. p. xxxi. THE PHAEDO MYTH 95 always been regarded with wonder, as possessing mysterious virtues — are fragments which have found their way down to this part of the world from the rocks of the " Earthly Para- dise," is a touch of fine imagination which helps to bring the two regions — our part of the world and the " Earthly Para- dise " — into physical connection.^ Tartarus and the True Surface of the Earth, or Earthly Paradise, are indeed real places to which there are real approaches for the ghostly travellers from this οίκου μένη. The care, half playful, half earnest, which Plato takes to prove this scientifically from observed effects — volcanoes, tides, precious stones — has its parallel in the method of Dante and other great masters of Myth. Skilful use of " modern science " is indeed one of the marks of the great master. Before referring to Dante for this, let me first compare Plato's delicate handling of " science " in the Phaedo Myth with the work of one who is cer- tainly not a great master of Myth — the Cambridge Platonist, Dr. Henry More ; but let me preface his " Myth " with a few words explanatory of the " science " which serves as foundation to his " mythology." The Spirit of Nature, according to More and his school, is an incorporeal substance, without sense, diffused through the whole universe, exercising 'plastic power, producing those phenomena which cannot be explained mechanically.^ This plastic principle in nature explains " sympathetic cures," the " astral bodies " (the phrase More borrows from the Paracelsians) of witches, in which they appear as hares, cats, weasels (so that if the hare or other animal is wounded, the witch is found to be similarly wounded — More was a firm believer in all that, and could give " scientific " reasons for his belief), the growth of plants and embryos, and the instincts of animals, such as the nest- building instinct of birds, the cocoon-spinning instinct of silk-worms.^ The Soul of man partakes in this plastic principle, and by means of it constructs for herself a body terrestrial, aerial, or aethereal {i.e. celestial), according as the stage of her development has ^ Cf. Conv. iv. 20, p. 323, Oxf. Dante : "Ecosi e difinita questa nostra Bonta, la quale in noi similmente discende da sorama e spirituale Virtu, come virtute in pietra da corpo nobilissimo celestiale. 2 More's Immortality of the Soul, book iii. ch. 12. ^ More, o.c. iii. 13. 96 THE MYTHS OF PLATO brought her into vital relation with the vehicle of earth, air, or aether. " As we see," he says,^ " that the 'perceptive part of the Soul is vitally affected with that which has no life in it, so it is reasonable that the plastich part thereof may be so too ; that there may be an Harmony betwixt matter thus and thus modified, and that Power that we call plastick that is utterly devoid of all perception. And in this alone consists that which we call Vital Congruity in the prepared matter either to be organised or already shaped into the perfect form of an Ani- mal." He then lays it down as an " axiome " ^ that " there is a Triple Vital Congruity in the Soul, namely, Aethereal, Aerial, and Terrestrial " ; and proceeds : " That this is the common opinion of the Flatonists, I have above intimated {Immortality of the Soul, ii. 14). That this opinion is also true in itself, appears from the foregoing axiome. Of the Terrestrial Congruity there can be no doubt ; and as little can there be but that at least one of the other two is to be granted, else the Soul would be released from all vital union with matter after Death. Wherefore she has a vital aptitude, at least, to unite with Aire. But Aire is a common receptacle of bad and good spirits (as the Earth is of all sorts of men and beasts), nay, indeed, rather of those that are in some sort or other bad, than of good, as it is upon Earth. But the Soul of man is capable of very high refinements, even to a condition purely angelical, whence Eeason will judge it fit, and all Anti- quity has voted it, that the souls of men arrived to such a due pitch of purification must at last obtain Celestial vehicles." The Soul, by means of her plastic power, moulds the vehicle — earth, air, or aether — to any form she pleases; but having been first habituated to the human shape in the terres- trial body, she naturally moulds the aerial and celestial vehicles to the same shape. This is why ghosts (in whom More is a firm believer),^ being the Souls of the departed in their aerial bodies, are easily recognised by their features, when 1 More, o.c. ii. 14. 2 ^q^q^ qx. iii. 28. 3 See ImmoHality of the Soul, ii. 16, for the wonderfully well-told story of Marsilius Ficinus appearing (by arrangement) on the day of his death to his friend Michael Mercatiis. He rides up to Micliael's window on a white horse, saying, "Michael, Michael, vera sunt ilia." Michael sends to Florence, and finds that Marsilius died the same hour his ghost appeared at the window. THE PHAEDO MYTH 97 they return to the scenes of their terrestrial life.^ Now, it may be asked what the effect of the Final Destruction of the World by Fire at the Last Day will be on the human souls which then have still only terrestrial bodies, and on the human souls and souls of Daemons (or Angels) which have still only aerial bodies. These bodies, unless saved by a miracle, will be burnt up, and their souls, having no vehicles, will cease to live the life of active consciousness.^ Therefore, More argues,^ using Stoical terms, an άττοκατάστασις and TraXLyyeveaia after the άνάστασις and βκττύρωσίς would not meet their case ; for a soul whose body had been burnt would have ceased to be con- scious, and irdXiyyeveaia would only bring it back to con- sciousness a different being. It will require supernatural means to rescue the souls of good men and Daemons (or Angels) at the time of the Final Conflagration, or even 1 Cf. More's Philosophical Poems, p. 260 (ed. 1647) :— In shape they walk much like to what they bore Upon the Earth : for that light Orb of Air Which they inact must yielden evermore To Phansie's beck, so when the Souls appear To their own selves alive as once they were, So cloath'd and conversant in such a place, The inward eyes of Phansie thither stear Their gliding vehicle, that bears the face Of him that liv'd, that men may reade what Wight it was. Similarly Dante (Purg. xxv. 91-99) explains the aerial bodies of the souls in Purgatory : — Ε come Γ aer, quand' e ben piorno. Per Γ altrui raggio che in se si riflette, Di diversi color diventa adorno, Cosi Γ aer vicin quivi si mette In quella forma che in lui suggella Virtualmente Γ alma che ristette : Ε simigliante poi alia fiammella Che segue il foco la 'vunque si muta, Segue alio spirto sua forma novella. See also More's ImTnortality of the Soul, iii. 1, § 8, p. 149, where it is stated that the Soul, although she has a marvellous power, by the i'mjpmMm of her will, of changing the temper and shape of her aerial vehicle, and of solidifying it so that it reflects light and becomes visible, she has a much greater power over her aethereal vehicle. The aethereally embodied soul can temper the solidity of her vehicle (see Immortality of the Soul, p. 233), so as to ascend or descend, and pass from one "vortex " to another. More looks forward (Defence of the Moral Cabbala, eh. ii. p. 165) to the Millennium as the time when, instead of occasional communications between souls terrestrially and aethereally embodied, there will be close and constant intercourse. 2 **The very nature of the Soul, as it is a Soul, is an aptitude of informing or actuating Body." — More's Defence of the Moral Cabbala, ch. ii. p. 167, ed. 1662. • ^ More, Immortality of the Soul, iii. 18. Η 98 THE MYTHS OF PLATO before that time, when the extinction of the sun — presaged by his spots recently discovered by one Shiner ^ — takes place. Neither terrestrial nor aerial bodies could, without the interven- tion of a miracle, survive such heat or such cold. But it is only in this lower part of the universe that such destructive agencies can operate. The aethereal region will not be affected by them ; and souls which have reached the stage of aethereal or celestial embodiment will remain unharmed. So much for the " science " which serves to give plausibility to the following Myth, as we may well call it : — The greatest difficulty is to give a rational account whence the Bad Genii have their food, in their execrable Feasts, so formally made up into dishes. That the materials of it is a vaporous Aire, appears as well from the faintness and emptiness of them that have been entertained at those Feasts, as from their forbidding the use of Salt at them, it having a virtue of dissolving of all aqueous substances, as well as hindering their congelation. But how Aire is moulded up into that form and consistency, it is very hard to conceive : whether it be done by the mere power of Imagination upon their own Vehicles, first dabled in some humidities that are the fittest for their design, which they change into these forms of Viands, and then withdraw, when they have given them such a figure, colour, and consistency, with some small touch of such a sapour or tincture; or whether it be the priviledge of these Aereal Creatures, by a sharp Desire and keen Imagination, to pierce the Spirit of Nature, so as to awaken her activity, and engage her to the compleating in a moment, as it were, the full design of their own wishes, but in such matter as the Element they are in is capable of, which is this crude and vaporous Aire ; whence their food must be very dilute and flashie, and rather a mockery than any solid satisfaction and pleasure. But those Superiour Daemons, which inhabit that part of the Aire that no storm nor tempest can reach, need be put to no such shifts, though they may be as able in them as the other. For in the tranquillity of those upper Eegions, that Promus-Gondus of the Universe, the Spirit of Nature, may silently send forth whole Gardens and Orchards of most delectable fruits and flowers of an equilibri- ous ponderosity to the parts of the Aire they grow in, to whose shape and colours the transparency of these Plants may adde a particular lustre, as we see it is in precious stones. And the Ghymists are never quiet till the heat of their Fancy have calcined and vitrified the Earth into a crystalline pellucidity, conceiting that it will then be a very fine thing indeed, and all that then^ ^ More, Immortality of the Soul, iii. 19. THE PHAEDO MYTH 99 grows out of it : which desirable spectacle they may haply enjoy in a more perfect manner whenever they are admitted into those higher Regions of the Aire. For the very Soile then under them shall be transparent, in which they may trace the very Roots of the Trees of this Superiour Paradise with their eyes, and if it may not offend them, see this opake Earth through it, bounding their sight with such a white faint splendour as is discovered in the Moon, with that difference of brightness that will arise from the distinction of Land and Water; and if they will recreate their palats, may taste of such Fruits as whose natural juice will vie with their noblest Extractions and Quintessences. For such cer- tainly will they there find the blood of the Grape, the rubie- coloured Cherries, and Nectarines. And if, for the compleating of the pleasantness of these habi- tations, that they may look less like a silent and dead solitude, they meet with Birds and Beasts of curious shapes and colours, the single accents of whose voices are very grateful to the Ear, and the vary- ing of their notes perfect musical harmony ; they would doe very kindly to bring us word back of the certainty of these things, and make this more than a Philosophical Conjecture. But that there may be Pood and Feasting in those higher Aereal Regions, is less doubted by the Platonists; which makes Maximus Tyrius call the Soul, when she has left the body, θρψμα αίθψίον ; and the above-cited Oracle of Apollo describes the Felicity of that Chorus of immortal Lovers he mentions there, from feasting together with the blessed Genii — o(rots Keap iv θαΧί7](Τίν alkv ίνφροσνν^αην tatVerat. So that the Nectar and Ambrosia of the Poets may not be a mere fable. For the Spirit of Nature^ which is the immediate Instru- ment of God, may enrich the fruits of these Aereal Paradises with such liquors, as being received into the bodies of these purer Daemons, and diffusing it self through their Vehicles, may cause such grateful motions analogical to our last, and excite such a more than ordinary quickness in their minds, and benign chearful- ness, that it may far transcend the most delicate Refection that the greatest Epicures could ever invent upon Earth ; and that without all satiety, burdensomeness, it filling them with nothing but Divine Love, Joy, and Devotion.^ It is very difficult to ί disentangle the motives which go to the production of a passage like this. We should say 1 More's Immortality of the Soul, iii. 9, pp. 183, 184, ed. 1662. The indebtedness of More's "Myth" to the Platonic, and Stoic mythology of τά irepl γην inhabited by δαίμφν€% and human souls, is obvious. For further reference to that mythology see infra, pp. 437 ff. 100 THE MYTHS OF PLATO without hesitation that the writer wished to adorn his discourse with a myth, if we did not know how uncritical his " science " was, and how credulous he was in accepting, as literally true, things quite as visionary as those here described. In his Antidote against Atheism he shows how thoroughly he believes current stories about the doings of witches and ghosts (see especially Book iii. chap. vii. of that work, for the story of Anne Bodenham, a witch, who suffered at Salisbury in 1653), and how valuable he holds these stories to be as evidence for the immortality of the Soul; indeed, in the Preface to his Fhilosophickal Foems he goes the length of expressing the wish that stories of witchcraft and apparitions " were publicly recorded in every parish," for " that course continued would prove one of the best antidotes against that earthly and cold disease of Sadducisme and Atheisme which may easily grow upon us, if not prevented, to the hazard of all Eeligion and the best kinds of Philosophy." It is to be noted, however, that Cudworth and Smith are not so credulous as More. Cud worth may be said to be a cautious believer in apparitions, and dwells on the Scripture evidence for demoniacal possession, and not, like More, on that afforded by modern stories ; ^ while Smith, in a sermon preached on an occasion when credulity seemed to be required,^ expresses himself in a manner which makes one feel that he was in advance of his age. There is just one general remark I should like to make in taking leave of More for the present: — That facility of scientific explanation is apt to make men indifferent about the substantiation of the facts, as facts. The facility of scientific explanation afforded by the hypothesis of " plastick power" doubtless made it more easy for More and other Cambridge Platonists to accept as sufficient the evidence forthcoming for the actual appearance of ghosts and Daemons. Facility of scientific explanation is a danger which we have to be on our guard against at the present day too. [The true object of the Phaedo Myth is, indeed, moral and^ ^ Intellectual System, vol. ii. p. 640 (ed. Mosheim). 2 Discourse 10, 0/ a Christian's Conflicts with and Conquests over Satan, "delivered in publick at Huntingdon, where one of Queen's College, in e very- year on March 25, preached a Sermon against Witchcraft, Diabolical Contracts, etc." ; see Worthington's Preface to Smith's Select Discourses. THE PHAEDO MYTH 101 religious, not in any way scientific — its true object is to give expression to man's sense of responsibility, which it does in^v ^ the form of a vivid history, or spectacle, of the connected life- A\v)> stages of an immortal personality^ This moral and religious ^ ^O object, however, is served best, if the history or spectacle, v"^ ^\i though carefully presented as a creation of fancy, is not made C^ .»i too fantastical, but is kept at least consistent with " modern science." -^ It is of the greatest importance that the student of the philosophy of Plato's Myths should learn to appreciate the terms of this alliance between Myth and Science ; ^ and I do not know how the lesson can be better learnt than from parallel study of Dante's Divina Commedia, in which all the science — moral and physical — of the age is used to give verisimilitude to the great μνθος of medieval Christianity. Fortunately, no better instances of the art with which Dante presses Science into the service of Myth could be found than in his treatment of a subject which has special interest for us here, in connection with the geography and geology of the Fhaedo Myth. This brings me to the second head of obser- vations which I have to offer on the Fhaedo Myth. II In this section I wish to draw attention to the parallel between Plato's geography of Tartarus and the True Surface of the Earth, and Dante's geography of Hell and the Mount of Purgatory with the Earthly Paradise on its summit. The parallel is close. On the one hand, the Fhaedo Myth and the Divina Commedia stand entirely alone, so far as I know, among Eschatological Myths in making Tartarus or Hell a chasm bored right through the globe of the Earth (ΒίαμτΓβρβς τβτρημβνον Bl ο\ης τή<ί γ^9, Fhaedo, 1 11 Ε ; Inferno y xxxiv. sub fin.), with two antipodally placed openings. On the other hand, while the Fhaedo Myth stands alone among Plato's Eschatological Myths in describing a lofty terrestrial region raised, above the elements of water and air, up into the ^ Aristotle's canon applies — ττροαφεΐσθαί re Set αδύνατα elK&ra μάλλον ή δυνατά, απίθανα. — Poet. 1460 a 30. 2 In this connection the reader should turn to Prof. Dill's illuminating remarks on the mixture of science with devotional allegory and myth in the Commentary of Macrobius or» Cicero's Dream of Scipio : Roman Society in the Last Century of the Western Empire, Book i. ch. iv. pp. 88-90, ed. 1. 102 THE MYTHS OF PLATO element of fire or aether, Dante also, in agreement with a common medieval belief, places the Earthly Paradise on the top of a mountain — his own Mount of Purgatory — which rises up into the element of fire. The "Earthly Paradise" of the Phaedo Myth probably owes a good deal to the Homeric Olympus ; and the Earthly Paradise of medieval belief and of the JDivina Commedia may have derived at least its altitude from the same source. But the description of Tartarus as bored right through the Earth, unique in Greek mythology, in no way countenanced by Virgil, and yet reappearing in the Inferno, which is so largely modelled on the Sixth Book of the Aeneid — this is surely a strange coincidence. The Timaeus (in the version of Chalcidius) was, it would appear, the only work of Plato which Dante knew directly.^ There is no evidence whatever — unless this coin- cidence be regarded as evidence — that he was acquainted with the Latin version of the Fhaedo which was made in the twelfth century.^ It is possible, however, but I hardly think likely, that the passage in the Meteor ologica (ii. 2, 355 b, 32 ff.), in which the Phaedo description of Tartarus is referred to, may have given Dante the idea of an antipodal exit from Hell ; although it is to be noted that Aristotle, in criticising the hydrostatics of the Phaedo Myth, curiously enough omits to quote, or paraphrase, Plato's emphatic Βίαμττβρβς τβτρημενον ; and S. Thomas does not make good the omission in his com- mentary on the Aristotelian passage. I do not think that any one reading the Aristotelian passage, without having read the Phaedo, would easily gather that the Tartarus of tho Phaedo is bored right through the Earth. Aristotle is concerned to show that the theory of a central αΙώρα, or oscillation, gives a wrong explanation of the origin of seas and rivers ; and, more suo, he is careless in his description of the theory to which he objects. Although the hydrostatics of the Quaestio de Aqua et Terra^ agree in the main with ^ See Moore's Studies in Dante, first series, p. 156, and Tojnbee's^J^iwie Dictionary, s.v. "Platone." ^ '^ See Rashdall's Universities of Europe in the Middle Ages, i. 37, ii. 744, and Immisch, Philoloyische Studien zu Plato, pp. 33, 34. Henrieus Aristippus (Archdeacon of Catania) translated the Phaedo and Meno in 1156. There is a MS. of his translation in Corpus Christi College, Oxford (243), written in 1423 ; see Coxe, ii. 100. ' With regard to the authenticity of this treatise see Moore's Studies in Dante, second series, pp. 303 if. THE PHAEDO MYTH 103 those of the Meteor ologica, the Inferno is not influenced by the Meteor ologica. The Inferno follows the traditional mythology in supposing subterranean rivers, and, indeed, agrees with the account of these rivers given in the Fhaedo, to the extent, at least, of regarding them as forming a single system of waters connected somehow with waters on the surface of the Earth. Dante may have been helped to this view by Brunetto Latini, who speaks, very much in the same way as Plato does, of waters circulating in channels through the Earth, like blood through the veins of the body, and coming out in springs.^ But mark how the Poet uses these mere hydrostatics — how his genius transforms the physical relation between the living world and Tartarus into a moral relation ! It is the tears of this world that flow in the rivers of Dante's Hell.^ Let me close this passage on Plato's Tartarus and Dante's Hell with the remark that an antipodal exit from Hell, near the Mount of Purgatory, is almost necessary to the movement of the Commedia. If such an exit — whether derived directly or indirectly from the Fhaedo, or obtained from some other source — did not already exist among Dante's mythological data, he would practically have been obliged to invent it, and offer some explanation of it, such as that which he actually offers — the Fall of Lucifer (Inf. xxxiv.). Now to pass on to the parallel between Plato's " True Surface of the Earth " and Dante's Earthly Paradise on the top of the Mount of Purgatory : — Dante's Mount of Purga- tory is definitely a part of this Earth. It is an island, antipodal to Jerusalem, in the middle of the ocean which covers the southern hemisphere. This island rises up, in a series of circular terraces, into one lofty height on which is situated the Earthly Paradise, — where our first parents were created, — where the souls which have been purified by 1 See Schmidt, iiber Dantes Stellung in der GescMchte der Kosmographie, I. Teil, de Aqua et Terra (1876), p. 7. 2 Inferno, xiv. Dante probably profited by the crude fancy of predecessors in the matter of the contents of the infernal rivers ; see Gary on Inf. xii. It is perhaps worth noticing here that Dante's River of Blood {Inf. xii.) has its parallel in the Scottish ballad of Thomas the Rhymer :— It was mirk mirk night and there was nae stem-light, And tbey waded through red bluid to the knee ; For a' the bluid that's shed on earth Rins through the springs o' that countrie (i.e. Elf-land). 104 THE MYTHS OF PLATO penance during their ascent of the Mount are gathered together, before they drink the waters of Lethe and Εηηοέ, the twin streams of this Paradise, and are translated into the Heavenly Paradise. That Purgatory is a real place, on the surface of this globe, which an adventurous voyager from our hemisphere might possibly reach νηί μβΧαίντ), is suggested with consummate art in the hiferno, Canto xxvi., where Ulysses describes his last voyage — how, with Ceuta on his left and Seville on his right, he sailed out through the Straits, and south over the ocean for five months, till the stars of the northern hemisphere sank beneath the horizon, and new stars appeared in the sky, and he sighted A Mountain dim, loftiest, methouglit, Of all I e'er beheld i— and then the storm burst which overwhelmed him. Dante's Mount of Purgatory — for that was the land which Ulysses sighted — is identical with the lofty mountain on the top of which medieval belief placed the Earthly Para- dise ; but Dante apparently drew entirely on his own im- agination when he localised Purgatory on its slopes.^ This Mountain of the Earthly Paradise rises, according to the medieval belief, as high as the Lunar Sphere ^ — i.e. its upper parts are above the air, in the aether or fire, like Plato's True Surface of the Earth. Hence, as S. Thomas explains, the Earthly Paradise was not reached by the flood.* S. Thomas further remarks that Enoch and Elias are said to be now in it ; also, that it is said to be sub aequinoctiali circulo ; but he will not vouch for its exact position, only expressing his belief that it must be in a " temperate clime." ^ The Arabians, whose geographical treatises, and epitomes of the Greek geographers, Dante knew in Latin versions,^ spoke of a great ^ Gary's translation. 2 See Scartazzini {Companion to Dante, Butler's Transl. p. 419). "Purga- tory, so far as form and position go, is a creation quite of the poet's own." It may, I think, have relationship to the " steep hill of virtue " whicOhe Stoics climbed ; see Lucian, Vera Hist. ii. 18 — no Stoics were to be seen in the For- tunate Island, because they were climbing this liill : των δέ Στωικών ovSds ναρην ^L yap iX^yovTO ανάβαιναν τί>ν r^s dper^s &ρΘων λόφον. 2 See S. Thom. A qui. Sumina, i. 102, 2. ** Of. Schmidt, Cosrnographie des Dante, p. 23. ^ Sumina, i. 102, 2. β See Lelewel, Histoire de la Goographie, i. Ixxxv., and Toynbee's Dante Dictionary, arts. " Alfergano" and " Tolommeo^" THE ΡΗΛΕΌΟ MYTH 106 mountain in the far south. It is called Mons Caldicus by Albertus/ and Mons Malcus by Eoger Bacon, who places it in India.^ The view that this mountain, identified by the Christian Schoolmen with the seat of the Earthly Paradise, is an island antipodal to Jerusalem in the middle of the Southern Ocean (Furg. iv. 70), was due entirely, it would seem,^ to Dante's own " scientific imagination " or " mythopoeic faculty." According to the doctrine of Orosius, generally accepted in Dante's time, there is no land at all in the southern hemisphere. If there were land, its inhabitants would be cut off from those of the orhis notus — the unity and continuity of the human race, postulated by the command, " Go ye into all the world and preach the gospel to every creature," would not exist. The ideal of one Church and one Empire (and one Aristotelian Philosophy, as Dante adds in the Convivio, iv. 6) requires the geographical condition of one continuous οίκονμίνη} Dante's antipodal island, however, being peopled only by the souls of the departed, is in no way inconsistent with the teleological geography of Orosius — indeed, is made, with consummate art, to corroborate it ; for the cause which produced the solitary island of Purgatory in 1 Meteor, ii. 2. 7. Cf. Schmidt, Cosm. d. Dante, p. 23. 2 Op. Maj. pp. 192, 195, ed. princ. Jebb, London. ^ See Scartazzini's Companion to Dante, p. 419, Butler's Eng. Transl. It is, however, an island in the Exeter Book (an Anthology of Anglo-Saxon Poetry given to the Library of Exeter Cathedral by Leofric, first Bishop of Exeter, 1050-1071): see Exeter Book, edited by Israel Gollancz for the Early English Text Society, 1895, poem on the "Phoenix," pp. 200 ff.: "The Earthly Paradise is in eastern parts ... it is all plain ... is an island. . . . There the door of Heaven's Realm is oft-times opened. . . . It is green and flowery. There is no rain there, nor snow nor frost nor fire. It is neither too hot nor too cold. The plain (which is quite smooth) is higher than any mountain by 12 fathom measures. It escaped the flood. ... It shall abide perennially blooming till the Day of Judgment. Water falls not there, but rises from the turf in the midst of the forest each month of the year, and irrigates the grove [we are reminded of Dante's Lethe and Eunoe]. The beautiful grove is inhabited by the Phoenix " — which the Poet then goes on to describe. It ought to be mentioned that Claudian {Idyll, i. \. Phoenix) makes "the Earthly Paradise " an island : — Oceani summo circumfluus aequore lucus Trans Indos Eur um que viret. . . . Mr. Toynbee, however, thinks it doubtful whether Dante had any acquaintance with Claudian (see Dante Diet. art. " Claudianus "). Benvenuto da Imola, in his Commentary on the Divina Commedia, quotes Claudian several times, describing him, erroneously, as a Florentine ; see Mr. Toynbee's Index of Authors quoted by Beiw. da Imola in his Commentary on the D. C. (Annual Report of the Dante Society, Cambridge, Mass., 1901). 4 Orosius, Hist. adv. paganos^i. 2, §§ 87-89 ^ vi. 22, § 1 ; vii. 1 ; vii. 3, 4 ; and cf. Moore's Studies in Dante, first series, pp. 279 if. 106 THE MYTHS OF PLATO the southern hemisphere, simultaneously produced the one οικουμένη of the northern hemisphere. Lucifer fell on the southern hemisphere {Inf. xxxiv.), and the shock of his fall submerged the land which originally existed there, and caused an equivalent amount of land in the northern hemisphere to bulge up above the sea ; the Mount of Purgatory, the only land now in the southern hemisphere, having been formed by the material extruded, as Lucifer, with the force of his fall, bored a passage down to the centre of the Earth. Thus does Dante give verisimilitude to his mythology of " the abhorred worm that boreth through the world" {Inf. xxxiv. 108), by making it explain a physical fact, or what the science of his day accepted as a fact ; and, at the same time, by means of the explanation, he brings the fact — so important for the doctrine of one Church and one Empire — into clear con- nection with a vast system of belief already accepted. When the rebel angels — about a tenth part of the original number created — were lost to Heaven, the human race was created to make good the loss.^ The descent of the Prince of these rebel angels produced, at one blow, Hell, and Purgatory, and the One Continent which is the condition of the ecclesiastical and civil unity of the human race. All hangs together clearly. " Science " recommends Myth, and Myth " Science," in one consistent whole. Again, in Purg. xxviii., the distribution of plants in our hemisphere, from a common centre of creation, is explained in such a way as to make the existence of an Earthly Para- dise appear the only hypothesis consistent with " science." The wind which Dante notices with wonder among the trees of the Earthly Paradise is caused, he is told, by the rotation, from east to west, of the primum mobile, or crystalline sphere ^ See Convivio, ii. 6 : "Dico che di tutti questi Ordini si perderono alquanti tosto che furono creati, forse in numero della decima parte ; alia quale restaurare fu Γ umana natura poi creata. So also Spenser {An Hymn of Heavenly Love) : — But that eternal Fount of Love and Grace, Still showing forth his goodness unto all. Now seeing left a waste and empty place In his wide Palace, through those Angels' Fall, Cast to supply the same, and to enstall A new unknowen Colonic therein. Whose Root from Earth's base Ground-work should begin. In this Hymn the whole drama worked out by Milton in Paradise Lost and Paradise Regained is indicated in outline. THE PHAEDO MYTH 107 — the ninth sphere counted from that of the moon. The rotation of the primum mobile carries round with it the pure air or aether in which the Earthly Paradise is bathed ; and this aether is impregnated with the seeds of the trees of the Earthly Paradise, and carries them round to our hemisphere, where they germinate according as they find soils and climates suitable to their various virtues. Here we have a " Myth," in which Faith, Fancy, and Science are blended in the true Platonic manner. The close parallel between Plato's " True Surface of the Earth " and Dante's Earthly Paradise has been made evident, I trust, by what I have said about the latter. Plato's " True Surface of the Earth " is a real place in this world, physically connected with the region which we inhabit. It is distin- guished from our region essentially by its altitude. With its foundation, like that of Dante's Island of Purgatory, bathed in the crass elements of water and air, it rises up into the region occupied by the element of fire or aether — a region which, we must remember, belonged as definitely to the domain of " science " for Plato and Dante as the regions of water and air, of which men have direct experience. Given a sufficient altitude, aether will take the place of air, and beneath aether, air will be as water. This is " scientifically " true. It is also in accordance with " science " to believe that the inhabitants of the aethereal altitudes live longer, more vigorously, and more happily, than we, poor frogs, do, down in the mists beside the waters of our hollow. A place has been found — or as good as found — by "science," where the souls of the virtuous may live in the enjoyment of the rewards of their virtue, and in preparation for an even more blessed existence elsewhere. There can be no doubt, I think, that the lofty terrestrial Paradise of the Fhaedo Myth answers to the " Islands of the Blessed " in the Gorgias Myth, to the τα irepl yrjv of the Phaedrus Myth,^ and to the "heaven" or ουρανός of the Myth of Er, from which the souls of the virtuous, who have not yet completed their purgatorial course, return, after a thousand years' sojourn, to the " meadow," in order to journey thence to the plain of Lethe, and drink the ^ Phaedrus, 257 A ; and cfm 248 b-249 a, where τούραροΰ rtj tottoj seems to answer to τα rrepl γην, as contrasted with τά ύττό 7^s in 257 A. 108 THE MYTHS OF PLATO [water of the river, and be born again in terrestrial bodies. The " Islands of the Blessed " were doubtless pictured by Hesiod and Pindar as islands in the ordinary sense, sur- rounded by water, somewhere out in the Western Ocean ; ^ Plato, in the Phaedo, is singular in making them aerial, not oceanic. With an art that is charming, he not only gives direct " scientific " reasons for believing in the existence of his aethereal altitudes of the Earth's surface (the configuration of the Earth in its envelopes of air and aether — deep hollows of its surface being compensated for by lofty heights — naturally produces such blessed altitudes), but he also knows how to add the authority of the poets to the reasons of " science," by making his description of these altitudes recall, not only the Homeric Olympus,^ but the Islands of the Blessed as described by Hesiod and Pindar. The original conception, in Greek as in Celtic ^ mythology, of Islands of the Blessed was that of an Elysium or Paradise, somewhere on the surface of the Earth, inhabited by gods, in which also certain elect heroes, who have been translated thither, enjoy in the flesh eternal felicity. This is the con- ception which meets us in Homer,^ Hesiod, Pindar, and the ^Hymn to Harmodius and Aristogeiton. But in course of [time this original conception was modified in the interest of morality and religion, especially the religion of the Orphic cult, and the Islands of the Blessed came to be regarded as the abode of the souls of the virtuous generally. This view is acquiesced in in the Gorgias, where Tartarus indeed appears as a Purgatory or place of temporary sojourn for the majority of the souls which go thither after judgment ; but we are left to suppose that virtuous souls which go at once after judgment to the Islands of the Blessed remain there thenceforth for 1 Hesiod, 0. et D. 167 :— rots bk δίχ ανθρώπων βίοτον καΐ ijde' όττάσσαζ Ζβύί Κρονίδψ κατένασσ€ ιτατηρ ^s ιτείρατα Ύαίηί. καΐ τοί μέν ναίονσιν άκήδεα θνμόν ^χοντ€$ iv μακάρων νησοισι τταρ' 'ί}κ€ανόν βαθυδίνην, δλβίΟί TJpwes, τοΐσιν μελκηδέα καρπόν rpU έτεοί θάΧλοντα φέρει ζείδωροι άρονρα. ^ See Thiemann, die Platonische Eschatologie in ihrer genetischen Entwickeluna (1892), p. 20. 3 See Myer and Nutt's Voyage of Bran, i. 329. ^ See Rohde, Psyche, i. 69. THE ΡΗΛΕΌΟ MYTH 109 ever. In the Fhaedo, however, the notion of progressive purification dominates the view taken of the Islands or " aethereal altitudes," as well as of Tartarus. For " Philo- sophers " mansions even fairer than the aethereal altitudes are indicated as the final abode. We are to think, perhaps, of the natal stars of the Timaeus. Finally, in the Bepublic, where^ the notion of re-incarnation, kept in the background in the Gorgias and the Fhaedo} is so prominent, the region to which virtuous souls go after judgment is, at any rate for many of them, only a place of temporary sojourn. They return from it, as other souls return from Tartarus, to be born again in the flesh. This view of Elysium as a place of pleasant sojourn from which souls, virtuous on the whole, but not yet completely purified, pass to the river of Lethe, and thence, after drinking of its water, proceed to enter into new terrestrial bodies, is that which we find in the Sixth Book of the Aeneid. The view of Elysium represented in the Frogs and the Axiochus, on the other hand, is rather that of a final abode of bliss, into which ceremonial observances secure a speedy entrance, immediately after death, to the soul of the μύστης. With this substitution of the 02)us ojperatum for the personal struggle after purification, prolonged through this life and perhaps many other lives, Plato has no sympathy. The view of Elysium or ουρανός as still a place of probation he would have us accept as that which, on the whole, will guide us best in the conduct of our earthly life. Taking, then, the '' Islands of the Blessed " in the Gorgias Myth, the ουρανός in the Myth of Er, and the " True Surface of the Earth " in the Fhaedo Myth, as names for the same region, we may perhaps venture to harmonise the accounts given of it in the three Myths, by saying that the souls of the virtuous, after judgment, go thither — some of them to sojourn for ever {Gorgias), some of them for a thousand years, till they return again to enter into the flesh {Bep.), and a few of them — Philosophers {Fhaedo), till such time as they have been thoroughly purified, and are translated to still fairer mansions {οίκησβις ere τούτων καΧλίους, Fhaedo, 114 c) in the true Heaven, as the purified are taken up from Dante's Earthly Paradise into the Heavenly Paradise. 1 In the Fhaedo Myth; it appears in the Dialogue, 81 E-82 b. 110 THE MYTHS OF PLATO It is certainly important to note that the place to which the souls of the virtuous go in the three Platonic Myths — variously called " Islands of the Blessed," " True Surface of the Earth," and ουρανός, " Heaven " — is, for some of these souls at least, a temporary abode, a stage in their purgatorial course, just as Tartarus is a Purgatory for all except the utterly incorrigible. In what part of the world are the Platonic " Islands of the Blessed " or " Altitudes of the True Surface of the Earth " ? The Phaedo Myth does not say ; but we are allowed to sup- pose that they are far away from our οικουμένη, in another part of the world. Perhaps Plato, in writing the Phaedo Myth, did not even imagine a definite locality for them. We are bound to allow for this possibility, but, in doing so, we need not scruple to consider some evidence which may be thought to point to the conclusion that he did localise them — and that, in the antipodes, where Dante's Mount of Purgatory stands. The Axiochus, a pseudo-Platonic Dialogue,-^ identifies the world of the departed definitely with the antipodal hemi- sphere. The author of the Axiochus probably thought that the identification was in accordance with the geography and cosmography of Plato ; at any rate, those who accepted the piece as written by Plato must have thought so. We may safely go the length of saying that the identification would not be impossible for Plato, so far as his view of the position and shape of the Earth is concerned. He holds, with the writer of the Axiochus, that the Earth is a sphere in the centre of the Cosmos. The passage in the Axiochus is as follows (371a ff.) : την υττό^^ευον οίκησιν, iv fj βασίλεια ΐΙΧούτωνος, ουχ ηττω τήζ του Αώς αΰΧης, ατ€ της μεν ^ής Ιγούσης τα μέσα του κόσμου, του he ΊτοΧου οντος σφαιρΟΈΐΒοΰς ' ου το μεν έτερον ήμισφαίριον θεοί ελα'χρν ουράνιοι, το δε έτερον οι * See Thiemann, Plat. Eschat. p. 26, and Rohde, Psyche, i. 314 ; ii. 247, n. 1, and 422. Rohde says that it can hardly be earlier than the third century B.C. It is a παραμνθητίκό$ Xoyos containing expressions which point to the direct in- fluence of Orphic teaching and practice. Axiochus is described (371 d) as Ύβννητψ των θβών — i.e. as μ€μνημένο5, and therefore συγγεί/η? των θεών κατά, ttjv ΊΓοίησιν — by adoption, with which μύησις was commonly identified. For 'γ€νούστηί in Philebus, 30 d (a passage on which, I think, Plut. de gen. Soc. 22 — where μονά^ is said to be prior to voOs— throws light), Ύβννήτηί, I think, ought to be read ; but see R. G. Bury's note ad loc. Apelt {zu Platons Philebus in Rhein. Mus. vol. 55, 1. p. 13, 1900) suggests that ^ζνούστψ means "parent of vovs" by a punning derivation ! THE PHAEDO MYTH 111 vTrivepOev — i.e. the " Palace of Pluto," in addition to its sub- terranean, or properly " infernal " parts, includes the whole antipodal hemisphere of the Earth, with its sky lighted by the sun, when it is night in our hemisphere, — τοΐσο 'λάμττβι μεν μ€νο<ζ άβΧίου ταν evOdBe νύκτα κάτω (Pindar, /ra^m. 129), — Αητο^γενάζ, συ δε τταΐΒας iv ηρώβσσί φυΧάσσονς, βνσββέων alel χωρον βττερχόμβνος (Kaibel, ep. lap. 228 b 7, 8).•^ To this " under world " the dead go to be judged. Some are sent into the subterranean parts, while others enjoy the light of day, in a land of flowers and streams, apparently still in the hemisphere of ol vTrevepOev θεοί — of the antipodal gods, as we may call them. Among these blessed ones it is dis- tinctly stated that the " initiated " take precedence — ενταύθα τοις μεμνημενοίς εστί τίς ττροεΒρία, 371 D. Now, we may safely say that there is nothing in the Platonic doctrine of the shape and position of the Earth inconsistent with this " under world " of the Axiochus. But can we say more ? I venture to mention two points : — First, Plato's judgment-seat in the Myth of Er, between the open- ings of " Heaven " and Tartarus, is above ground, and so is the region across which the pilgrims travel towards the pillar of light ; and so (as I believe in all Greek accounts) is the river of Lethe.^ It is from the plain of Lethe, on the surface of the Earth, that the souls shoot up (άνω, Rep. 621 b) to be born again in terrestrial bodies — that is, I venture to χ suggest, up from the lower, antipodal hemisphere to our hemi- sphere. Secondly, the hollow or cave of Tartarus extends right through the globe of the Earth, as we have seen — Βίαμττερες τετρημενον δί,' οΧης της γης {Fhaedo, 111 ε) — i.e. has an opening in the lower hemisphere as well as in this. Without going the length of supposing that Plato's unseen world is mapped out with the definiteness of Dante's, we may take it that Plato, with his poet's faculty of visualisation, must have formed a clear mental picture of the opening of Tartarus in the " lower " or antipodal hemisphere, and of the country into which one comes on issuing from it. The anti- ^ Quoted by Rohde, Psyche, ii. 210, n. 1. 2 See Thiemann, Plat. Esch. p. 18. I shall return to this subject in my observations on the Myth of Er. Virgil's Lethe is of uncertain position ; but Dante follows the universal Qfeek tradition in making Lethe a river of the surface of the Earth. 112 THE MYTHS OF PLATO podal opening was not, we may assume, imagined by Plato in vain. Those souls which, after being judged (whether above or under ground does not appear in the Phaedo — but probably underground), go, not to the Islands of the Blessed, but down the river Acheron to the Acherusian Lake (which is certainly subterranean), have entered the infernal regions, we may fairly suppose, by the opening in our hemisphere, and will come out, after their penance, by the other — the antipodal — I opening, and will start thence on their journey — always above ground — to the river of Lethe. That Plato actually thought of the souls as going into Tartarus, and coming out of it, by distinct openings, we know from the Myth of Er. But while the entrance and exit are antipodally placed in the Phaedo Myth, which takes careful account of cosmographical and geological conditions, in the Myth of Er the purpose of pictorial composition is served by placing them side by side, \ opposite the entrance and exit of " Heaven " ; the " Meadow," / at once the place of judgment and the starting-place for the plain of Lethe, lying between Tartarus and "Heaven." It would be easy to give examples, from Greek vase-painting, of similar compression in pictorial composition. I call attention to this discrepancy between the Phaedo Myth and the Myth of Er, to show how absurd it would be to attempt to con- struct one topographical scheme for Plato's Eschatological Myths, as rigid as the one scheme to which Dante is so faith- ful in the Divina Commedia. What I venture to suggest, however, is that, in the Phaedo Myth, Plato is possibly — or shall I say " probably " ? — thinking of the world of the de- parted, so far as it is not subterranean, or celestial, as some- where in the other hemisphere of the terrestrial globe, — somewhere, but as in a dream, in which inconsistencies are accepted a§ natural; for the "True Surface of the Earth," though somewhere in the antipodal hemisphere, beneath us, is yet a region above us, whence gems have found their way down to our hollow ! I have dwelt on the parallel between the geography of the Phaedo Myth and that of the Divina Commedia with the view, not of clearing up particular difficulties in mythological geography, but of suggesting a method by which the function of Myth in the Platonic philosophy may be better understood THE FHAEBO MYTH 113 the method of sealing the impression made on us by the Myth of one great master by study of the Myth of another great master with whom we may happen to be in closer sympathy. The service which Myth, and poetical treatment generally, can render to the faith on which conduct and science ultimately rest is, I think, more easily and finely appreciated by us in Dante than in Plato ; for we live, though in late days, in the same Christian epoch with the medieval poet. Ill Let me close these observations on the Phaedo Myth by calling attention to what Socrates says at the end of the narrative (114 d), — that, while it would not be sensible to maintain that all about the Soul and the next world contained in the Myth is absolutely true, yet, since the Soul is plainly immortal, one ought to hazard the pious belief that, if not absolutely true, this Myth, or some other like it, is not far from being true, and " sing it over oneself " as if it were an enchanter's song : — το μεν ουν ταύτα ^ασγ^υρίσασθαί όντως €'χ^6ΐ,ν, ως iyo) ΒίβΧηΧυθα, ου TTpeiret, νουν β'χοντυ άνΒρί' οτι μεντοο ή ταϋτ εστίν ή τοιαυτ άττα ττερί τας ^^νχας ημών καϊ τας οίκησευς, εττείττερ άθάνατόν 'γε ή "^υχτ] φαίνεται οΰσα, τούτο καΐ Ίτρέττειν μου Βοκεΐ καϊ άξίον κινδύνευσαν οίομενω οΰτως ε'χειν καΧος yap 6 κίνΒυνος' καϊ 'χ^ρη τα τοιαύτα ώσττερ εττάΒειν εαυτω, Βώ Βη εγωγβ καϊ ττάλαι μηκύνω τον μύθον. The distinction between Dogma and Myth is carefully insisted on here, and also the practical value of Myth as an expression of moral and religious feeling. Myth, it is suggested, may be put into such form that it will react favourably on the feeling expressed, and make it a surer guide to what is good. The reaction of expression on that which it expresses — of style on the man — is a matter about which Plato had reflected deeplyL as is apparent from his whole scheme of education, mentall moral, and physical, in the Eepuhlic. If, then, the sense of responsibility, and the attendant sense of being a continuously existent Self, naturally express themselves, as Plato holds, Bia μυθοΧο'γίας, pictorially, in visions of an immortal life, it follows from the general law of the reaction of expression on feeling, that, by refining and ennobling μυθολογία, we shall be able to I 114 THE MYTHS OF PLATO refine and ennoble morals and faith. This is the " use " to which μνθο^ is put by Plato, not only in the education of young children, but in dialogues offered to mature readers as models on which they may mould their own conversations about the highest things. This is the "use" of great poetry, like Dante's Commedia, or of great painting, like the fresco on the left-hand wall of the Spanish Chapel — " the most noble piece of pictorial philosophy and divinity in Italy." ^ As philosophy and pictorial composition are blended together in that fresco — the philosophy is seen as a whole, in all the beauty of its μ€y€θo<ζ καΐ τάξις — so are philosophy and poetry blended together where Plato is at his highest — in his Myths. In the Fhaedo Myth the poet -philosopher has taken moral responsibility as the motif of his piece. Moral responsibility cannot, he knows, be explained in scientific terms, as a phenomenon is explained by being put into its proper place among other phenomena ; for moral responsibility attaches immediately to the subject of all phenomena — the continuously existing Self. But if it cannot be explained, moral responsi- bility may be pictured — pictured in a Myth representing the continuity of the responsible Self in terms of Pre-existence, Eeminiscence, Judgment, Penance, Free Choice, Ee-incarnation — a Myth not to be taken literally, but to be dwelt on (χρη τα τοιαύτα ωσιτερ eTraheiv βαυτω), till the charm of it touches one deeply — so deeply that, when the " uninitiated " say " it is not true," one is able to answer by acting as if it were true. ^ Ruskin's Mornings in Florence, chap, iv., " The Vaulted Book "; cf. Eenan, Averroes et V Averro'isme, pp. 245, 246. THE GORGIAS MYTH Context GORGIAS, the famous teacher of Rhetoric, and his young disciple Polus, meet Socrates at the house of Callicles, an Athenian gentleman ; and the conversation turns on the differ- ence between Rhetoric and the Way of true Knowledge and the true Conduct of Life. What is Rhetoric ? Socrates asks. Neither Gorgias nor Polus can give an intelligible answer ; ccnd Socrates answers for them by describing it as the Simutatton^' of Justice, the Jht of getting people to believe what the Professor of the Art wishes them to believe, and they themselves wish, to believe, without regard to t^ruth or justice. It is the Λχί of Mattery. It ignores the distinction between Pleasure and the 'Good — a dis- tinction to the reality of which human nature itself testifies-j-for all men, bad as well as good, wish the Good, and bad men, in doing what they think best for themselves, do what they do not wish to do. To seek after the Good is of the very essence of Life — it is better to suffer evil than to do evil ; and if a man has done evil, it is better for him to be chastised than to escape chastisement. Here Ccdlicles, speaking as a man of the world, takes up the argument, and maintains that Siiatesmanship does not recognise this distinction drawn by Socrates between pleasure and the dSfo od. Pleasure is the %)od. Might is Right. ^ After muAih talk Cauicles is silenced, and Socrates points out that there are two kinds of Statesmanship — that which uses Rhetoric as its instrument, and flatters people, and deceives them, holding up Pleasure before them; and that which, keeping the gopi? always in view, makes them better. 4 «^^«^^JweJtAj W ^(^^ 4j \J At the Day of Judgment, which tk^- Myth now told by Sem^^aUs. declares, there will be no place for the Art of Flatlery. Pretence will not avail. There will be no side issues then. The . only issue will be : Is this man righteous or is he wicked ? With the Myth of the Day of Judgment the Gorgias ends. 115 Ο 116 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Gorgias 523 A-527c 623 "Ajcove Βή, φασί, μαΚα καΧοΰ Xoyov, ον συ μβν η^ησβί μνθον, ώ<ζ εγώ οΐμαί, εγώ Be Xoyov ώς άΧηθή yap οντά σοι, Χέξω α μεΧΧω Xeyetv. ' Ω^σττβρ yap 'Όμηρος Xeyei, Βί€ν€ίμαντο την αρ'χην 6 Ζβύς καϊ 6 ΐΙΧούτων, βττβιΒη τταρα του ττατρος τταράΧαβον. ην οΰν νόμος oBe irepl άνθρώττων €7γΙ Ίίρόνου, καϊ ael καϊ νυν ert βστνν ev θεοΐς, των άνθρώττων τον μεν Βίκαίως τον βίον ΒίβΧθόντα καϊ οσίως, Β έτΓβιΒάν τεΧευτήστ), ες μακάρων νήσους άττιοντα οίκείν ev Ίτάση εύΒαιμονία έκτος κακών, τον Be άΒίκως καϊ άθεως εΙς το της τίσεώς re καΧ Βίκης Βεσμωτήριον, ο Βη τάρταρον καΧοΰσιν, Ιεναί. τούτων Βε Βίκασταϊ εττΐ Κ,ρόνου καϊ ετι νεωστί του Αιος την άρ'χτ)ν β'χοντος ζώντες ήσαν ζώντων, εκείντ) τη ημ^ρα Βικάζοντες, fj μεΧΧοίεν τεΧευταν. κακώς οΰν αϊ Βίκαι εκρίνοντο. 6 τε οΰν ΤίΧούτων καϊ οΐ εττιμε- Χηταϊ οί εκ μακάρων νήσων Ιόντες eXεyov ττρος τον Αία, C οτί φοίτωεν σφιν άνθρωττοί εκατερωσε ανάξιου, είττεν οΰν 6 Ίίεύς, 'Αλλ* εyώ, εφη, τταύσω τοΰτο yίyvόμevov. νυν μεν yap κακώς αΐ Βίκαι Βικάζονται, άμττε'χόμενοι yap, 'ύφη, οί κρινόμενοι κρίνονται* ζώντες yap κρίνονται. ττοΧΧοϊ οΰν, η δ* 6ς, ψύχρας ττονηράς εγοντες ήμφιεσμενοι είσΐ σώματα τε καΧά καϊ yεvη καϊ ττΧούτους, και, εττειΒάν ή κρίσις η, έρχονται αύτοΐς ιτοΧΧοΙ μάρτυρες μαρτυρήσοντες, ώς Βικαίως Ό βεβιωκασιν, οί οΰν ΒικασταΙ ύττό τε τούτων εκττΧήττονται, και αμα και αύτοΙ άμττεχόμενοι Βικάζουσι, ττρο της 'ψυχής της αυτών οφθαλμούς και ώτα καϊ οΧον το σώμα ττροκεκα- Χυμμενοι. ταΰτα Βή αύτοΐς ττάντα εττίττροσθεν yίyvετaι, και τα αυτών αμφιεσματα καϊ τα τών κρινόμενων, ττρώτον μεν ουν, εφη, τταυστεον εστί ιτροειΒότας αυτούς τον θάνατον νυν μεν yap ττροισασι. τοΰτο μεν οΰν και Βή εϊρηται τω £ ΤΙρομηθεΐ οττως αν τταύση αυτών, εττειτα yυμvoύς κριτεον άττάντων τούτων τεθνεώτας yap Βεΐ κρίνεσθαι. καϊ τον THE GORGIAS MYTH 11' Translation Hearken now to an excellent True Story : a Fable, me- thinks, thou wilt deem it ; but I deem it no Fable, for that the things are true, whereof I will now tell, I am fully per- suaded. What Homer telleth, that will I now tell : That Zeus and Poseidon and Pluto divided amongst them the kingdom, when they had received it from their father Cronus. Now, in his time there was this law among the gods concerning men, which standeth fast unto this day as of old, that the man who hath gone through his life righteously in the fear of the Gods, after death goeth to the Isles of the Blessed, and dwelleth there in all felicity beyond the touch of ill ; but the man who hath lived unrighteously without the fear of the Gods before his eyes, he goeth to the prison-house of just retribution, which men call Tartarus. They who were Judges in the time of Cronus, and when Zeus was newly come to his kingdom, were living men ; and they also were living men who were judged, each on that day on the which he should die. !N"ow, judgments given thus were ill-given, and Pluto and the Overseers from the Isles of the Blessed came and spake unto Zeus, making complaint that many came unworthily unto either place. Wherefore Zeus said : Verily I will end this ; for now are the judgments given ill, because they who are judged are judged with their raiment on, being judged alive. Many there be, he said, that have evil souls, and, for raiment, have fair bodies and noble birth and riches : when these are judged, many witnesses come to bear witness for them, that they have lived righteously. By these are the Judges confounded ; and, moreover, they themselves sit in judgment with raiment on, having eyes and ears, yea, and the whole Body, as clothing wherewith their Soul is covered. All these things hinder them, to wit, their own raiment, and the raiment of those that are judged. First, then, he said, must they be stopped of their foreknowing the day of their death : for now have they foreknowledge. Wherefore Prometheus hath been charged to stop them of this. Then naked, stripped of all, ^ust they be judged ; for they must be 118 THE MYTHS OF PLATO κρίτην hel >γυμνον elvai, τβθνβώτα, avrfj rrj ψυχτ) αυτήν την ylrvyrjv θεωρουντα εξαίφνης άττοθανοντος βκαστου, βρημον Ίτάντων των avyyevSiv καΐ καταΚιττόντα iirl της yrj^i ττάντα €Κ€Ϊνον τον κόσμον, ϊνα δικαία η κρίσιν rj. €<γω μεν ουν ταύτα βγζ/ω^ώ? πρότερο^; ή νμβΐς βττοιησάμην Βίκαστας νί€Ϊς €μαυτοΰ, Βύο μεν €Κ της ^ Ασίας, Μ^ίνω Τ6 καΐ ΎαΒάμανθνν, 524 €va Be i/c της Έ/ύρώττης, ΑΙακόν. ούτοι ουν, εττειΒαν τελβυτησωσι, Βυκάσουσιν iv τω Χευμωνι, ev Tjj τριοΒω, εξ ης φερετον τω οΒώ, ή μεν εΙς μακάρων νήσους, η δ* εΙς τάρταρον. και τους μεν εκ της ^Ασίας ΎαΒάμανθυς κρίνει, τους Βε εκ της Έιύρώττης ΑΙακός- Μίνω Βε ττρεσβεΐα Βώσω ετΓίΒιακρίνείν, εαν άττορήτόν tl τω ετέρω, ΐνα ως Βίκαωτάτη ή κρίσις 7] ΊτερΙ της ττορείας τοις άνθρώττοις. Ύαΰτ εστίν, ω Κ,αΧΚίκΧεις, α εγώ άκηκοως τηστεύω Β αληθή εΙναί' καΐ εκ τούτων των λογωζ/ τοιόνΒε τι \ο>γίζομαο συμβαίνειν. Ό θάνατος τυ<γχ^ανεί ων, ως εμοί Βοκεΐ, ούΒεν άΧΚο ή Βυοΐν 7Γpayμάτoίv ΒίόΧυσυς, της Λίτυχης καϊ του σώματος, άττ άΧΧήΧοιν. εττειΒαν Βε ΒίαΧυθήτον άρα άττ άΧΧήΧοι,ν, ου ττόΧύ ήττον εκάτερον αύτοΐν έχει την εξιν την αυτού ήνττερ καϊ οτε εζη 6 άνθρωττος, τ6 τε σώμα την φύσιν την αυτού καϊ τα θεραττεύματα καϊ τα τταθηματα, C ενΒηΧα ττάντα. οίον εϊ τόνος με^α ήν το σώμα φύσει η τροφβ ή αμφότερα ζώντος, τούτου καϊ εττειΒαν αττοθάντ} 6 νεκρός με'γας* καϊ εΐ τταγύς, τταγυς και άττοθανόντος, καϊ ταΧΧα οΰτως. καϊ ει αΰ εττετηΒευε κομαν, κομήτης τούτου καϊ 6 νεκρός, μαστί'γίας αυ εϊ τις ην καϊ ϊχνη εΐ'χε τών ττΧη'γών ούΧας εν τω σώματι η ύττο μαστιγών ή άΧΧων τραυμάτων ζών, καϊ τεθνεώτος το σώμα εστίν ιΒεΐν ταύτα ε'χον. κατεαηοτα τε εϊ του ήν μεΧη ή Βιεστραμμενα ζώντος, D καϊ τεθνεώτος ταύτα ταύτα ενΒηΧα. ενϊ Βε λόγω, οίος είναι τταρεσκευαστο το σώμα ζών, ενΒηΧα ταύτα καϊ τεΧευτή- σαντος η ττάντα ή τα ττοΧΧα εττί τίνα 'χ^ρόνον. ταύτον Βή μοι Βοκεΐ τούτ άρα καϊ ττερϊ την ψνγ^ην είναι, ώ ΚαΧΧικΧεις' ενΒηΧα ττάντα εστϊν εν τη ψυχβ, εττειΒάν ιγυμνωθ'ρ τού σώματος, τά τε τής φύσεως καϊ τα τταθηματα α Βια την εττιτήΒευσιν εκάστου ττpάyμaτoς εσγεν εν ττ} THE GORGIAS MYTH 119 judged dead. The Judge also must be naked, dead, with very Soul beholding the very Soul of each, as soon as he is dead, bereft of all his kindred, having left upon the earth all the adornment he had there. So shall the judgment be just. I therefore, having considered all these things before that ye came unto me, have made my sons Judges — two from Asia, Minos and Ehadamanthys, and one from Europe, Aeacus. These, when they are dead, shall sit in judgment in the Meadow at the Parting of the Ways, whence the two Ways lead — the one unto the Isles of the Blessed, and the other unto Tartarus. And those of Asia shall Ehadamanthys judge, and those of Europe, Aeacus. But unto Minos will I appoint the chief place, that he may give judgment at the last, if the other two be in doubt as touching any matter. Thus shall the judgments concerning the Passage of Men be most just. These are the things, Ο Callicles, which I have heard ; and I believe that they are true ; moreover, therefrom I con- clude this, to wit : — Death is only the separation of two things, Soul and Body, from each other. When they have been separated from each other, the state of each of them is well nigh the same it was while the man lived. The Body keepeth the natural fashion it had, and the marks plain of all the care that was taken for it and of all that happened unto it. For if any man while he lived was great of body, by nature, or nurture, or both, his corpse also is great when he is dead ; and if he was fat, his corpse also is fat when he is dead ; also, if any man wore long hair, his corpse also hath long hair ; and if any man was a whipped cur, and bore on his body the prints of his beatings — scars made by the whip, or scars of other wounds — while he lived, when he is dead thou mayest see his corpse with the same ; and if any man had his limbs broken and disjoint while he lived, when he is dead also the same is plain. The sum of the whole matter is, that what- soever conditions of Body a man hath while he liveth, these are plain when he is dead, all or most, for some while. Now, Callicles, that which happeneth unto the Body, happeneth, methinks, unto the Soul likewise, to wit, there are plain in the Soul, after she hath been stripped of the Body, her natural conditions and those affections which, through use in any matter, a man hath gotten in his Soul. 120 THE MYTHS OF PLATO ylrvyrj 6 άνθρωττο^;, Έττε^δάι^ οΐιν άφίκωνταί τταρα τον Ε Βίκαστήν, οΐ μεν έκ της ^ Ασίας τταρα τον 'ΡαΒάμανθυν, 6 ΎαΒάμανθνς εκείνους ετηστησας θβαταί εκάστου την 'ψυ'χ^ην, ουκ εΙΒως ότου εστίν, άΧλα ττοΧλάκίς του με<γάΧου βασίΧέως εττιλαβόμενος η άΧΧου οτουουν βασιλέως ή Βυνάστου κατεΐΒεν ούΒεν ύγίέ? 6ν της ψυχής, αλλά Βίαμεμαστί'γωμενην καϊ ούΧών μεστην ύττο εττίορκιών καΐ 525 άΒίκίας, α εκάστω ή ττραξις αυτού εξωμορξατο εις την ψυχην, καϊ ττάντα σκοΧια ύττο ψεύΒους καϊ αλαζονείας καϊ ούΒεν ευθύ Βία το άνευ αληθείας τεθράφθαί• καϊ ύττο εξουσίας καϊ τρυφης καϊ ύβρεως καϊ άκρατίας των ττράξεων ασυμμετρίας τε καϊ αίσχρότητος ^εμούσαν την ψυχην εΙΒεν. ίΒων Βε άτίμως ταύτην άττεττεμψεν ευθύ της φρουράς, οΙ μέλλει, ελθουσα άνατΧηναι τα ττροσηκοντα ττάθη. Β ΥΙροσηκευ Βε τταντί τω εν τιμωρία ovtl ύττ* αΧλου ορθώς τίμωρουμενω η βεΧτίονι ^ί^νεσθαί καϊ ονίνασθαί ή ΊταραΒεί^^ματυ τοΐς αλΧοις 'γί'γνεσθαι, ϊν άΧΧοι όρώντες ττάσγοντα α αν ιτάσγτι φοβούμενου βεΧτίους ηίηνωνται, είσΐ Βε οΐ μεν ωφελούμενοι τε καϊ Βίκην ΒιΒόντες ύττο θεών τε καϊ άνθρώττων ούτοι, οΐ αν ιάσιμα αμαρτήματα άμάρτωσιν όμως Βε Βι άΧ<γηΒ6νων καϊ οΒυνών ^ίηνεται αύτοίς η ωφέλεια κα\ ενθάΒε καϊ εν "ΑιΒου* ού yap οϊόν C τ€ αλλω? άΒικίας άτταΧΧάττεσθαΐ' οΐ Β αν τα έσχατα άΒικήσωσι και Βια τα τοιαύτα οΒικηματα ανίατοι ηενωνται, εκ τούτων τα τταραΒείηματα ηίηνεται, καϊ ούτοι αύτοι μεν ούκετι ονίνανται ούΒεν, άτε ανίατοι οντες, άΧΧοι Βε ονίναν- ται οι τούτους ορώντες Βια τας αμαρτίας τα μέγιστα καϊ οΒυνηροτατα καϊ φοβερωτατα ττάθη ττάσχοντας τον άει χρονον, άτεγνώς τταραΒεί^ματα ανηρτημένους εκεί εν '^ΑιΒου εν τω Βεσμωτηρίω, τοΐς άεΐ των άΒίκων άφικνουμενοις D θεάματα καϊ νουθετηματα. ων iyclo φημι ενα καϊ ΑρχεΧαον εσεσθαι, ει άΧηθη Χε<γει Πώλο?, και άλλον όστις αν τοιούτος τύραννος y. οΐμαι Βε καϊ τους ττοΧλούς είναι τους τούτων των τταραΒει^ μάτων εκ τυράννων καϊ βασιλέων καϊ Βυναστών καϊ τα των ττολεων ττραξάντων ^ε^ονότας' ούτοι yap Βια την εξουσίαν μεyιστa καϊ άνοσιώτατα άμαρτηαατα άμαρτάνουσι. μαρτυρεί Βε τούτοις καϊ ^^Ο μηρός' βασιλέας yap καϊ Βυνάστας εκείνος ττεττοίηκε τους εν THE GOBGIAS MYTH 121 Wherefore, when they from Asia are come before the presence of Khadamanthys their Judge, he causeth them to stand, and looketh at the Soul of each, not knowing whose Soul it is ; but perchance having gotten hold of the Soul of the Great King, or of some other King or Euler, perceiveth that it hath no soundness, but is seamed with the marks of many stripes, and full of the scars of perjuries and unrighteous- ness, according as the doings of each have stamped on his Soul their signs ; and all therein is crooked by reason of false- hood and boasting, and nothing straight, because he hath been bred up without truth ; and by reason of pride and luxury and wantonness and incontinency in his life, his Soul is altogether deformed and foul. This Soul then the Judge seeth, and having seen, sendeth with dishonour straightway unto the prison, whither it must go and endure the tor- ments appointed for it. Now, it is appointed for every one who is punished, if he be punished righteously by another, either to become better and himself receive benefit, or to be set forth for an example unto others, that they, seeing his torments, may fear and become better. ISTow, they who are profited the while they pay unto Gods and Men the penalty of their sins, are they whose sins may be cured. Through afflictions and pains there cometh unto them profit both here and in the House of Hades ; for otherwise can no man be rid of un- righteousness. But they who have sinned to the utmost, and by reason of their great sins are beyond cure, they are the examples whereof I spake ; for now they cannot themselves be benefited, inasmuch as they are beyond cure, but other men are benefited, when they see them by reason of their sins suffering torments exceeding great and terrible for evermore, being verily examples hung up in the House of Hades, in the prison-house, for a spectacle and admonition unto every sinner which cometh. Of these that be set forth for examples I say that Archelaus will be, if Polus speaketh truly ; and any other Prince that is like unto him. Most, methinks, were Princes and Kings and Eulers and Chief Men in their cities ; for they, by reason of the power they have, do sin more heinously than other men. Whereof Homer is witness, in that he telleth that they which are torment^ in the House of Hades for evermore 122 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Β'ΆιΒον τον ael γ^ρόνον τιμωρούμενους, ΎάνταΧον /cat Χίσυφον καΐ Ύιτυόν. θβρσίτην Be, καΐ ei rt? αλΧος ττονηρος ην ίΒιώτης, ονΒβΙς ττεττοίηκβ β€<γά\αί<; τίμωρίαος συνεγ^ομβνον ώς άνίατον ου yap, οΐμαι, βζήν αύτω- 8ώ καΙ βύΒαιμονί- στβρος ην η οίς έξην. άλλα yap, ω Καλλ/^λε^?, ifc των 626 Βυναμένων βίσϊ καΐ οι σφοΒρα ττονηροι ^ι^νομενοι άνθρωποι• ούΒβν μην κωΧύει και iv τούτοις άβαθους άνΒρας iyyi- yveaOai, και σφοΒρα ye άξιον ayaaOai των yιyvoμevωv' ^aXeirov yap, ω li^aXkiKXei^, και ττοΧλοΰ έτταίνου άξιον iv μeyά\rj εξουσία του aBiKeiv yev6μevov Βικαίως Βιαβιώναι. oXlyoi Be yiy νονται οι τοιούτοι' eVel καΐ ivdaBe καΐ άΧ- Χοθι yeybvaaiv, οίμαι Be κα\ €σονται καΧοι KayaOol ταύτην Β την apeTrjv, την του Βικαίως Bιa'χeιpίζeιv α άν τις eiriTpeirr)' ζΐς Be καΐ πάνυ eXX6yιμoς yeyove καΐ eις τους άΧΧους '^ΕΧΧηνας, ^ApιστeίBης 6 Αυσιμάχ^ου. οι Be ττοΧΧοί, ω άριστ€, κακοί yiyvovTai των Βυναστων. ^'Oirep ουν eXeyov, eireiBav 6 '^αΒάμανθυς €Κ€Ϊνος τοιούτον τίνα Χάβη, άΧΧο μίν irepi αυτού ουκ olBev ούΒέν, οΰθ* όστις οΰθ^ ώντινων, οτι Be ττονηρός τις* και τούτο κατιΒων ά7Γe7Γeμ^fr€v eις τάρταρον e'πισημηvάμevoς, eav re C Ιάσιμος eav re ανίατος Βοκη elvai' 6 Be eκeΐσe άφικoμevoς τά προσήκοντα ττάσχε^. evίoτe δ' άΧΧην €ίσιΒων οσίως β€βιωκυΐαν και μ€τ άXηθeίaς, άνΒρος ΙΒιωτου η άΧΧου τίνος, μάΧιστα μέν, έγωγε φημι, ω ΊίaXXίκXeις, φιΧοσόφου τά αυτού ττράξαντος καΐ ου 7ΓoXυlτpayμovήσavτoς iv τω βίω, ήyάσθη re καΐ e? μακάρων νήσους άττεττε/χλ/τε. ταύτα ταύτα και 6 Αιακός. ίκάτ€ρος Be τούτων ράβΒον 'βγων Βικάζ€ΐ. 6 Be Μ,ίνως i'πισκo^Γωv κάθηται, μόνος €χ^ων Ό χ^ρυσούν σκητττρον, ως φησιν ^OBυσσeύς 6 'Ομήρου IBeiv αύτον χρν(Γ€θν σκηπτρον έχοντα, θζμισηνοντα νίκνσσιν. Εγώ μ€ν ουν, ω K.aXXίκXeις, ύττο τούτων των Xόyωv ΊΓe7Γeισμaι, καΐ σκοττώ, όπως άποφανούμαι τω κριτή ώς ύyιeστάτηv την ψυχήν. ^^alpeiv ουν iάσaς τάς τιμάς τάς THE GORGIAS MYTH 123 are Kings and Kulers, to wit, Tantalus, and Sisyphus, and Tityus. But of Thersites, or any other Commoner which was an evil- doer, no poet hath told that he is held in great torments as being beyond cure : nay, methinks, such an one had not the opportunity to sin greatly. Wherefore also he was happier than those who had opportunity. Verily, Callicles, 'tis from among those who have power that the greatest sinners come, notwithstanding even among these may good men arise ; whom, when they are found, it is most meet to reverence, for 'tis a hard thing, Callicles, and worthy of all praise, for a man, who hath great opportunity to do injustice, to live justly all his days. Few such are found ; yet are some found ; for both here and elsewhere have there arisen, and, methinks, will arise again, men of a noble virtue and just conduct in those matters whereof charge at any time is given unto them : of whom was Aristides, the son of Lysimachus, a man famous throughout all Greece: but I tell thee. Sir, of them that have power in cities the most part are alway evil. When one of these evil men, therefore, standeth, as I told, before Ehadamanthys the Judge, he knoweth nought else concerning him, neither who he is nor whose son, but only this, that he is one of the wicked ; and perceiving this, sendeth him away unto Tartarus, having put a mark upon him to signify whether he can be cured or no : and he, coming to that place, there suffereth that which is due. But perchance the Judge seeth a Soul that hath lived in holiness and truth ; it may be, the Soul of a Common Man or of some other ; but in most likelihood, say I, of a Philosopher, Callicles, who hath minded his own matters and been no busybody in his life. That Soul pleaseth the eye of Ehada- manthys, and he sendeth it away to the Islands of the Blessed. In like manner Aeacus also judgeth. And each of these sitteth in judgment holding a rod in his hand. But Minos is seated as president over them ; and he alone hath a golden sceptre, as Homer his Odysseus telleth, that he saw him " with a golden sceptre in his hand giving laws unto the Dead." I am persuaded, Callicles, that these things that are told are true. Wherefore I consider how I shall show my Soul most faultless befoi^ the Judge. I will take my farewell 124 THE MYTHS OF PLATO των ΤΓοΧΧών άνθρώττων, την άΧήθβιαν σκοττών ιτζίράσομαι τώ οντι ώς αν Βννωμαι βύΧτίστος ων καΐ ζην καί, iirethav Ε αττοθνησκω^ αττοθνησκβι,ν. τταρακαΧώ Be καϊ τους άΧΧονς ττάντας άνθρώτΓονς, καθ* όσον Βύναμαι, καϊ 8η καϊ σβ άντίτταρακαΧώ βττϊ τούτον τον βίον καϊ τον aycova τούτον, ον €<γώ φημι άντϊ ττάντων των ένθάΒβ αγώνων elvac, καϊ ονβιΒίζω σοί, otl ουχ οΐός τ eaei σαυτω βοηθήσαο, όταν η Βίκη σοι η καϊ η κρίσίς ην νυν Βη εγώ eXeyov, άλλα εΧθων τταρα τον Βικαστην τον της ΑΙ^ίνης υΐόν, βττβιΒάν 627 σου €7ΓίΧαβ6μ6νος οίγτ;, 'χασμησβι καϊ ίΧυ^^ιάσζΐς ούΒβν ήττον ή €γώ βνθάΒβ συ €Κ€Ϊ, καϊ σε ϊσως τυτττησβι τις καϊ 67γΪ κόρρης άτίμως καϊ ττάντως ττροττηΧακιβΐ. Τάχα Β οΰν ταύτα μύθος σοι Βοκ€Ϊ Χε^εσθαι, ωσττερ ^ραος, καϊ κατα- φρονείς αυτών, καϊ ούΒεν γ αν ην θαυμαστον καταφρονβΐν τούτων, €Ϊ ΊΓΎ] ζητουντες εΧγομεν αυτών βεΧτίω καϊ άΧηθέστερα εύρεΐν νυν Βε οράς, οτι τρεις οντες ύμεΐς, οΐΊτερ σοφώτατοί εστε τών νυν 'ΈιΧΧηνων, συ τε καϊ Πώλο? Β καϊ Τορ^ίας, ουκ έχετε άττοΒεΐξαι, ώς Βεΐ άΧΧον τίνα βίον ζην η τούτον, οσττερ καϊ εκεΐσε φαίνεται συμφέρων, άλλ* εν τοσούτοις Xoyoις τών άΧΧων εXεyχ^oμεvωv μόνος οΰτος ηρεμεί 6 Xoyoς, ώς εύΧαβητεον εστϊ το άΒικεΙν μάΧΧον η το άΒικεΐσθαι, καϊ τταντος μαΧΧον άνΒρϊ μεΧετητεον ου το Βοκεΐν είναι ayaOov, άλλα το είναι καϊ ΙΒία καϊ Βημοσία' εαν Βε τις κατά τι κακός yίyvητaι, κοΧαστεος εστί, καϊ τούτο Βεύτερον ayaOov μετά το είναι Βίκαιον, το yίyvεσθaι καϊ κοΧαζομενον ΒιΒόναι Βίκην καϊ ττάσαν κοΧακείαν καϊ την ττερϊ εαυτόν καϊ την ττερϊ τους αΧΧους, καϊ ττερϊ 6Xίyoυς καϊ ττερϊ ττοΧΧούς, φευκτεον καϊ τη ρητορική οΰτω γ^ρηστεον, εττϊ το Βίκαιον αεί, καϊ τη αΧΧη ττάση ττράξει. THE GOBGIAS MYTH 125 of the honours that are among men ; and, considering Truth, will strive earnestly after Kighteousness, both to live therein so far as I am able, and when I die, therein also to die. And I exhort all men, so far as I am able, and thee more especially do I exhort and entreat, to enter into this life and run this race, which, I say unto thee, is above all the races wherein men strive ; and I tell thee, to thy shame, that thou shalt not be able to help thyself, when the Day of Judgment whereof I spake cometh unto thee, but when thou dost appear before the Judge, the son of Aegina, and he hath gotten hold of thee to take thee, thou shalt gape and become dizzy there, even as I do here ; yea and perchance some one will smite thee on the cheek to dishonour thee, and will utterly put thee to despite. Perchance this shall seem to thee as an old wife's fable, and thou wilt despise it : well mightest thou despise it, if by searching we could find out aught better and truer. But as the matter standeth, thou seest that ye are three, the wisest men of Greece living at this day, thou and Polus and Gorgias, and ye cannot show any other life that a man must live save this whereof I have spoken, which is plainly expedient also for that other life ; nay, of all sayings this saying alone is not confuted, but abideth sure: — That a man must shun the doing of wrong more than the receiving, and study above all things not to seem, but to be, righteous in the doing of his own business and the business of the city ; and that if any man be found evil in anything, he is to be corrected ; and that the next good thing after being righteous is to become righteous through correction and just retribution ; and that all flattery of himself and of other men, be they few or many, he must eschew ; and that he must use Oratory and all other Instru- ments of Doing, for the sake of Justice alway. 126 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Observations on the Gorgias Myth I Here, again, as in the Phaedo Myth, it is Besponsihility which Plato represents in a picture — a picture portraying the continuity of the Self through the series of its life-stages. It is in the consciousness of Responsibility — of being the cause of actions for which he takes praise and blame — that man first becomes conscious of Self as a constant in experience. Consciousness of an active — a responsible, or moral Self, is formally prior to consciousness of a passive, sensitive. Self realised as the one mirror in which sense- impressions are successively reflected. Thus, the Gorgias Myth gives a strictly natural representation of the Idea of Soul, when it sets forth, in a vision of Judgment, Penance, and Purification, the continuity and sameness of the active, as distinguished from the passive — of the responsible or moral, as distinguished from the sensitive Self. It is only in vision — in Myth — and not scientifically, that the Idea of Soul, or Subject, can be represented, or held up to contemplation as an Object at all ; and it is best represented, that is, in the manner most suitable, not only to our consciousness of respon- sibility, but to our hope and fear, if it is represented in a vision of Judgment and Penance and Purification, where the departed are not the passive victims of vengeance, τίμωρία, but actively develop their native powers under the discipline of correction, κόΧασις} In such a vision it is consciousness of wrong done and fear (that fear mentioned by Cephalus in the Republic) ^ which conjure up the spectacle of punishment ; but hope, springing from the sense of personal endeavour after the good, speaks comfortably to the heart, and says, "If .only 1 What we call sin I could believe a painful opening out Of paths for ampler virtue. Clough, Dipsychus. felix culpa, quae talem ac tantum Meruit habere Eedemptorem ! Easter hymn quoted by Leibniz, Thhdicee, p. 507, ed. Erdmann. 2 380 ε. THE GOBGIAS MYTH 127 a man will strive steadfastly to overcome evil passions in this life, and in future lives, all will be well with him in the end. The very punishment which he fears will be for his ultimate good, for punishment regards the future which can still be modified, not the past which cannot be undone." Pardon — for so we may bring home to ourselves the deeper meaning of Plato's κάθαρσίς — Pardon is thus involved in Punishment. This is a thought which cannot be set forth by the way of Science. Pardon is not found in the realm of Nature which Sciejice describes. It "comes of the Grace of God." It is t^ceived under another dispensation than that of Nature — a dispensation under which a man comes by " Faith " — Faith which Science can only chill, but Myth may confirm. Χρη τα τοιαύτα ώσττβρ eiraheiv βαντω. Besides containing this notable theory of Punishment and Pardon, the Gorgias Myth is remarkable for its power- ful imaginative rendering of the wonder with which man regards death — a rendering which is best taken side by side with another given in the Cratylus, 403, 4. Hades, Αί'δτ;?, the God of Death, Socrates says in the Cratylus, is not called, as most people in their fear suppose, άττο του άειΒοΰς — he is not the terrible Unseen One, who keeps the Dead in Hell, against their will, bound in the fetters of necessity. He is rather called άττο τον ττάντα τα καΧα elhevai — he is the All-wise, the Philosopher, who, indeed, holds the Dead in fetters, but not against their will ; for his fetters are those of that desire which, in disembodied souls, is stronger than necessity — the desire of knowledge. The Dead cleave to Hades as disciples cleave to a great master of wisdom. The wisest of men go to learn of him, and will not return from his companionship. He charms the charmers themselves — the Sirens -^ — so that they will not leave him. He is rightly 1 The Sirens, although they became eventually simply iluses, were originally Chthonian deities, and as such are sculptured on tombs and painted on lekythi : see Miss Harrison's Myths of the Odyssey, pp. 156-166 ; her Mythology and Monuments of Ancient Athens, pp. 582 if. ; and her article in J.H.S. vol. vi. pp. 19 IF. ("Odysseus and the Sirens — Dionysiac Boat-races — Cylix of Nicosthenes "), 1885. "As monuments on tombs, the Sirens," writes Miss Harrison {Myth, and Mon. p. 584), "seem to have filled a double function; they were sweet singers, fit to be set on the grave of poet or orator, and tliey Avere mourners to lament for the beauty of youtli and maiden. It is somewhat curious that they are never sculptured on Attic tombs in the one function that makes their relation to death clearly intelligible— i.e. that of death-angels. The 128 THE MYTHS OF PLATO called Pluto, because he has the true riches — wisdom. Here we have what is really a Myth offered in satisfaction of the deep wonder with which man regards that undiscovered country from whose bourn no traveller returns. Plato appeals openly to the " science of etymology " in support of his " myth," and, I would suggest, also appeals tacitly to traditional cultus : — Hades communicates true oracles to those who go down into his cave to sleep the sleep of death — truer oracles than those dreams which Trophonius sends to the living who sleep in his cave at Lebadia.^ It is only with the disembodied soul that Hades will hold his dialectic, for only the disembodied soul, freed from the distractions of the bodily passions, can experience that invincible desire of knowledge, that €ρω<; without which ΒιαΧβκτίκή is vain, which makes the learner leave all and cleave to his Teacher. In this, that he will hold converse only with the disembodied soul. Hades declares himself the true Philosopher. It is at this point that the connection appears between the Cratylus Myth — for we may call it a Myth — and the Gorgias Myth. The judges in the Gorgias Myth are naked souls (the phrase 7) ψνχτ) ^γυμνη του σώματος occurs also in Cratylus, 403 b) — naked souls, without blindness or bias of the flesh, which see naked souls through and through, and pass true judgment upon them — There must be wisdom with Great Death : The dead shall look me thro' and thro'. The wondering thought, that death may perhaps solve the enigma of life, has never been more impressively rendered than in these twin Myths of the Philosopher Death and the Dead Judges of the Dead. Siren of the Attic graves must surely be somehow connected with the bird death- angels that appear on the Harpy tomb, but her function as such seems to have been usurped for Attica by the male angels Death and Sleep." Eriuna's epitaph — {Γταλαί, καΐ Σ€φην€$ έμαί, καί πένθιμε κρωσσέ, δστίί ^xeis Άΐδα ταν dXLyav σποδίάν — brings the Sirens and Hades into connection just as Crat. 403 d does — 5ta ταΰτα άρα φώμερ, ώ Έρμ6'γ€ΐ^€$, ούδένα δεΰρο έθϊΚησαί άττέλθεΐν των iKeWev, ουδέ auras τά$ Σειρψαί, αλλά κατακβκλησθαι iiceivas re καΐ τού$ aWovs ττάντας' οϋτω καλούί TLvaSy ώί ioiKev, ένίσταται Xoyovs λέ-γειν 6 "Αιδη$. According to Mr. J. P. Post- gate {Journal of Philology, ix. pp. 109 if., "A Philological Examination of the Myth of the Sirens"), thev are singing birds = souls winged for flight hence. 1 Cf. Rohde, Psyche, i. 115 ff. THE GOEGIAS MYTH 129 II Another point, and I have done with the " Philosophy " of the Gorgias Myth. I am anxious to have done with it, because I know that the " Philosophy of a Myth " too easily becomes " the dogmatic teaching which it covertly conveys " ; but I trust that in the foregoing remarks I have avoided, and in the following remarks shall continue to avoid, the error of treating a Myth as if it were an Allegory. The point is this. The incurably wicked who suffer eternal punishment are mostly tyrants — men like Archelaus and Tantalus, who had the opportunity of committing the greatest crimes, and used it. All praise to the few who had the opportunity and did not use it. But Thersites, a mere private offender, no poet has ever condemned to eternal punishment. He had not the opportunity of committing the greatest crimes, and in this is happier than those offenders who had. Here a mystery is set forth. The man who has the opportunity of committing the greatest crimes, and yields to the special temptation to which he is exposed, is held worthy of eternal damnation, which is escaped by the offender who has it not in his power, and has never been effectively tempted, to commit such crimes. First, the greatness of the crime is estimated as if it were a mere quantity standing in no relation to the quality of the agent ; and then the quality of the agent is determined by the quantity of the crime ; so that vice with large opportunity comes out as infinitely worse than vice with narrow Oppor- tunity, the former receiving eternal punishment, the latter suffering correction only for a limited time. This mystery of the infinite difference between vice with large opportunity and vice with narrow opportunity — the mystery which is set forth in " lead us not into temptation " — this mystery is set forth by Plato in the Gorgias Myth as a mystery, without any attempt at explanation : " Men born to great power do not start with the same chance of ultimate salvation as men born to private stations." "With that the Gorgias Myth leaves us. In the Vision of Er, however, an explanation is offered — but still the explanation, no less than the mystery to be explained, is mythically set forth— ^not to satisfy the understanding, but Κ 130 THE MYTHS OF PLATO to give relief to feeling in imaginative expression. The explanation offered in the Vision of Er is that the Soul, before each incarnation, is free, within certain limits, to choose, and as a matter of fact does choose, its station in life — whether it be the station of a tyrant with large opportunity of doing evil, or that of a private person with narrow opportunity. In this way the mystery of the Gorgias Myth is " explained " — explained by another Myth. So much for the " Philosophy " of the Gorgias Myth — so much for the great problems raised in it. Now let me add a few notes on some other points, for the better appreciation of the Myth itself as concrete product of creative imagination. Ill The judged are marked (Gorg. 526 b) as "corrigible" or "incorrigible." So, too, in the Myth of Er {Bep. 614 c) those sent to Heaven have tablets fixed in front, those sent to Tartarus tablets fixed behind, on which their deeds and sentences are recorded. The idea of tablets may have been derived from the Orphic custom of placing in the graves of the dead tablets describing the way to be taken and the things to be done on the journey through the other world.-^ Before Dante enters Purgatory the Angel at the Gate marks him with " seven P's, to denote the seven sins {peccata) of which he was to be cleansed in his passage through Purgatory " — Seven times The letter that denotes the inward stain He on my forehead, with the blunted point Of his drawn sword, inscribed. And " Look," he cried, " When entered, that thou wash these scars away." ^ The judgment-seat of Minos, Ehadamanthys, and Aeacus is iv τω Χβίμώνί, iv rrj τρίόΒω, έξ ης φβρβτον τω όδώ, ή 1 See Comparetti, J. Η. S. iii. Ill, and Dieterich, Nekyia, 85, on the gold tablets of Thurii and Petelia ; and cf. p. 156 ff. infra. The Orphic custom itself may have come from Egypt, where texts from the Book of the Dead were buried with the corpse. The Book of the Dead was a guide-book for the Ka, or Double, which is apt to wander from the body and lose its way. See Jevons' Introduction to the History of Religion, p. 323, and Flinders Petrie's Egyptian Tales, second series, p. 124. 2 Purg. ix. 101, and see Gary's note ad loc. THE GORGIAS MYTH 131 μ€ν eh μακάρων νήσους, ή Β βίς Ύάρταρον {Gorg. 524 α). The topography of this passage corresponds with that of Rep. 614 c if., where, however, it is added that the Χειμών of the judgment-seat is also the spot in which the souls, returned from their thousand years' sojourn in Tartarus and Heaven (i.e. the Islands of the Blessed), meet, and rest, before going on to the place where they choose their new lives before drinking of the water of Lethe. In the Gorgias the two ways mentioned are (1) that to Tartarus, and (2) that to the Islands of the Blessed ; and the Χβίμών of judgment is " at the parting of the ways " — iv rfi τριόΒω, — no reference being made to a third way leading to the throne of Necessity, and thence to the Plain of Lethe. In the parallel passage in Hep. 614 c £f. the ways are not mentioned as three; but they are three — (1) the way to Tartarus, (2) the way to Heaven, and (3) the way to the Plain of Lethe — all three diverging from the Χβιμών. The " Three Ways," as indicated in the Myth of Er, — one to Tartarus, one to Heaven, and the third to Lethe (a river of the surface of the Earth), — constantly occur in the literature which reflects Orphic influence.^ They even appear in the folk-lore represented by the story of Thomas the Khymer : — Light down, light down now, true Thomas, And lean your head upon my knee : Abide, and rest a little space, And I will show you ferlies three. Oh see ye not yon narrow road, So thick beset wi' thorns and briars 1 That is the path of righteousness, Though after it but few inquires. And see not ye that braid braid road. That lies across the lily leven ? That is the path of wickedness. Though some call it the road to Heaven. And see not ye that bonny road. That winds about the fernie brae ? That is the road to fair Elf-land, Where thou and I this night maun gae. _ . ___ ^ See Dieterich, Nekyia, 89, 90, and especially Rohde, Psy. ii. 221, note. 132 THE MYTHS OF PLATO The three parts of the Divina Commedia correspond, in the main, to the " Three Ways." The theological doctrine of Purgatory, to which Dante gives such noble imaginative expression, is alien to the Hebrew spirit, and came to the Church mainly from the Platonic doctrine of κάθαρσις — especially as the doctrine found expression in Eschatological Myths reflecting Orphic teaching.^ We come now to the Myth of Er (Hep. 614 A if.), the greatest of Plato's Eschatological Myths, whether the fulness of its matter or the splendour of its form be considered. ^ See Thompson's note on Gorg. 525 b. THE MYTH OF EK IN THE REPUBLIC Context The subject of the Eepublic is Justice — that character in the individual which manifests itself in the steady ^performance of Duty — Duty being what a man does for the maintenance of a certain Type of Social Life, the good of which he has been educated to identify with his own good. What, then, is this Type of Social Life, in living for which a man does his Duty and finds his true Happiness t The Eepublic is mainly concerned with the description of it, and of the Education which fits men for it; and as the Dialogue proceeds, the reader, who enters into the feelings of the dramatis personae, becomes, with them, more and more con- vinced that true Happiness, in this world, is to be found only in the steady performance of Duty in and for a State ordered according to the spirit, if not according to the letter, of the Constitution described by Socrates. In this world, certainly, the man who does his Duty, as Socrates defines it, ha>s his great reward. He -is 729 times happier than the man who, despising the law of Duty, has fallen under the tyranny of Pleasure. But a greater reward awaits the Bighteous man, and greater torments are prepared for the Unrighteous man, in the world to come. For the Soul is immortal ; and an ontological proof of its immortality is given. Then, as though this proof were insufficient, the Eepublic ends with the Myth of Er {told by Socrates), which proves, indeed, nothing for the Understanding, but visualises, for the Imagination, the hope of the Heart. 133 134 THE MYTHS OF PLATO BepuUic 613e-621d ■^^A μεν τοίνυν, ην δ* εγώ, ζώνη τώ Βικαίφ ιταρα θεών 614 τ€ καΐ άνθρώττων αθΧά Τ6 καΐ μισθοί καΐ Βώρα fyiyverai, ττρος εκβίνοις τοις ά^γαθοΐς οίς αύτη παρβί'χετο η Βικαω- σύνη, TOtavT αν €Ϊη. Κ.αϊ μαλ\ εφη, καΧα Τ€ καϊ βέβαια. Ύαΰτα τοίννν, ην δ εγώ, ovBev έστί ττΧηθβί ovBe με^εθβι ττρος €Κ€Ϊνα, α τβλευτησαντα βκάτβρον ττεριμβνβί, 'χρη δ* αντα άκονσαί, ϊνα τελέως ίκάτβρος αυτών άττειΧηφτι τα ύττο τον \6yov οφειλόμενα άκοΰσαι. Λεγο^? αν, εφη, ώ? ου ττολλ,ά Β αλλ' rjBtov άκούοντυ, Άλλ' ου μεντοι σοι, ην δ* εγώ, ^Α\κί- νου γε airoXoyov ερώ, αλλ' όΧκίμου μεν ανΒρός, Ήρο? του ^Αρμενίου, το γεϊ/ο? ΤΙαμφυΚον 6ς ττοτε εν ττοΧεμω τεΧευ- τησας, άναιρεθεντων Βεκαταίων τών νεκρών ηΒη Βοεφθαρ- μενων, υ^ιης μεν άνρρεθη, κομισθείς δ' οϊκαΒε μελΧων θάτΓτεσθαί, ΒωΒεκαταΐος εττΐ ttj ττυρα κείμενος άνεβίω, άναβίονς Β εXεyεv α εκεί ϊΒοι» εφη δε, εττειΒη ου εκβηναι C την ψυχιίν, ττορεύεσθαί μετά ττοΧΧών, καϊ άφικνεΐσθαι σφας εΙς τοΊΓον τίνα Βαιμόνιον, εν ω της τε yής Βύ είναι 'χ^άσματε εγρμενω αΧΧηΧοιν καϊ του ουρανού αΰ εν τω άνω άΧΧα καταντικρύ. Βικαστας δε μεταξύ τούτων καθήσθαι, ους, εττειΒη ΒιαΒικάσειαν, τους μεν Βικαίους κεΧεύειν ττορεύεσθαί την εΙς Βεξιάν τε καϊ άνω Βια του ουρανού, σημεία ττεριά- ψαντας τών ΒεΒικασμενων εν τω ττρόσθεν, τους δε άΒίκους την εΙς άριστεράν τε καϊ κάτω, εγρντας καϊ τούτους εν τω D ΟΊΓίσθεν σημεία ττάντων ων εττραξαν. εαυτού Βε ιτροσεΧ- θοντος είττεΐν, οτι Βεοι αύτον άyyεXov άνθρώττοις yεvεσθaι THE MYTH OF EE 135 Translation " Of such sort, then, are the prizes and the wages and the gifts which the just man receiveth, while he is yet alive, from Gods and Men, over and above those good things whereof I spake which Justice herself provideth." " Yea, in truth goodly gifts," quoth he, " and exceeding sure." " Well," I said, " they are even as nothing, for number and greatness, in comparison with those things which await each of the two, to wit, the just man and the unjust man, when he is dead. Of these thou must hear, that each of them may have full payment of that which this Discourse oweth him to be said concerning him." " Say on," quoth he, " there is little else I would hear more gladly." " Nay," said I, " but it is not a Tale of Alcinous I will tell thee, but the story of a mighty man, Er, the son of Armenius, of the nation of the Pamphylians. " It came to pass that he fell in battle ; and when the corpses were taken up on the tenth day already stinking, he was taken up sound ; and when they had carried him home and were about to bury him, on the twelfth day, being laid on the pyre, he came to life again ; and began to tell of the things which he saw there. " He said that when his Soul went out, it journeyed together with a great company, and they came unto a certain ghostly place wherein were two open Mouths of the Earth hard by each other, and also above, two Mouths of the Heaven, over against them : and Judges were seated between these, who, when they had given their judgments, bade the righteous take the road which leadeth to the right hand and up through Heaven ; and they fastened tablets on them in front, signify- ing the judgments ; but the unjust they sent by the road which leadeth to the left hand and down, and they also had tablets fastened on them behind, signifying all that they had done. But when he himself came before the Judges they said unto him that he must be for a messenger unto men con- cerning the things thdl*e, and they charged him straitly that 136 THE MYTHS OF PLATO των €Κ€Ϊ καΐ Βιακβλξύοίντό οι άκονβιν re καΙ θεασθαι, Ίτάντα τα iv τω τόττω. οράν Βη ravrrj μ€ν καθ βκάτερον το χάσμα του ουρανού re καΐ τήζ 'γή<; άιηούσα^ τας 'ψ>υγα9, €7Γ€ίΒη αύταΐς Βικασθβίη, κατά Be τω ίτερω €Κ μβν του avievai €Κ της yrj^ μβστας αύγ^μου re καΐ κονεως, έκ Be του έτερου κaτaβaίveLv ετέρας €Κ του ουρανού καθαράς. Ε καΐ τα<ζ ael άφίκνουμάνας coairep έκ ττοΧΧήζ 7Γορ€ίας ^aiveaOaL ηκ€ίν, καΐ άσμίνας eh τον \eLμωva άτηουσας οϊον iv '7Γavηyύpeί κατασκηνάσθαι, καϊ άσ'πάζeσΘaί re άΧΚη- λα? οσαί ηνώριμαι^ και ΊΓυvθάveσθa^, τάς Τ€ €Κ της Ύης ηκούσας τταρα των ίτέρων τα eKel καϊ τας €κ του ουρανού τα Trap* eκeίvaίς. BLηyeΐσθac Be άΧληΧαις τας μ€ν 615 οΒυρομίνας Te καϊ κΧαούσας, άναμιμνησκο μίνας, οσα τ€ και οΙα TraOoLev καϊ IBoLev iv Tjj ύττο ^ής iropeia — elvau Be την TTopeiav 'χ^ιXίeτή — τάς δ* αΰ iK του ουρανού eύ'πaΘeίaς Βιη'γεΐσθαί καϊ θέας άμη'χάνους το κάΧΧος» τα μέν ουν ΤΓολλα, ω ΤΧαύκων, ττοΧΧοΰ 'χρόνου Βίηγήσασθαί' το Β οΰν κ€φάΧαίον €φη ToBe elvai, οσα ττώττοτέ τίνα ηΒίκησαν καϊ όσους €καστοι,, υττέρ άττάντων Βίκην BeBωκevaι. iv μepeL•, υπέρ έκαστου BeκάκLς — τούτο δ' elvai κατά έκaτovτaeτη- Β ρίΒα έκάστην, ως βίου οντος τοσούτου τού άνθρωττίνου — , ϊνα Beκa^ΓXάσLov το €κτισμα τού άΒικηματος iKTivoiev καϊ οϊτίν€ς ΤΓοΧΧών θανάτων ήσαν αϊτιοί, η ττόλει? 7ΓροΒ6ντ€ς η aTpaToireBa καϊ eh BoυXeLaς iμβeβXηκότeς, η τίνος αΧΧης κακουχίας μ€ταίτίοι, ττάντων τούτων Beκa^ΓXaσίaς άΧ^ηΒόνας ύττέρ έκαστου κομίσαιντο, καϊ αύ el τινας eύepηeσίaς eυepηeτηκoτeς καϊ Βίκαιοι καϊ όσιοι fγeς ξνμτταντας σφονΒνΧονς, εν αΧΧηΧοις ε^γκειμενονς, κνκΧονς Ε άνωθεν τα χείΧη φαίνοντας, νωτον σννεγες ενός σφονΒνΧον άττερ^αζομενονς ττερι την ηΧακάτην εκείνην Βε Βιά μέσον τον oyBoov Βιαμττερες εΧηΧάσθαι. τον μεν ονν ττρώτόν τε καϊ εξωτάτω σφονΒνΧον ττΧατντατον τον τον χείΧους κύκΧον εχειν, τον Βε τον έκτον Βεντερον, τρίτον Βε τον τον τέταρτον, τέταρτον Βε τον τον oyBoov, ττεμτττον Βε τον τον εβΒομον, έκτον Βε τον τον ττεμιττον, εβΒομον Βε τον τον τρίτον, oyBoov Βε τον τον Βεντερον καϊ τον μεν τον μεyίστov πτοικίΧον, τον Βε τον εβΒομον Χαμττρότατον, τον 617 δε τον oyBoov το χρώμα άττο τον εβΒομον εχειν ττροσ- ΧάμτΓοντος, τον Βε τον Βεντερον καϊ ττεμιττον τταραττΧησια άΧΧήΧοις, ξανθότερα εκείνων, τρίτον Βε Χενκότατον χρώμα εχειν, τέταρτον Βε νττερνθρον, Βεντερον Βε Χενκότητι τον έκτον ύττερβάΧΧειν. κνκΧεΐσθαι Βε Βη στρεφόμενον τον άτρακτον οΧον μεν την αντην φοράν, εν Βε τω οΧω ττεριφερομενω τονς μεν εντός ετττά κνκΧονς την εναντίαν τω οΧω ήρεμα ττεριφερεσθαι, αντών Βε τούτων τάχιστα μεν Β ιεναι τον oyBoov, Βεντερονς Βε καϊ άμα άΧΧήΧοις τον τε εβΒομον καϊ έκτον καϊ ττεμτττον ' τον τρίτον Βε φορά ιεναι, ως σφίσι φαίνεσθαι, εττανακυκΧούμενον τον τέταρτον τέταρτον Βε τον τρίτον καϊ ττεμτττον τον Βεύτερον στρεφεσθαι Βε αύτον εν τοις της ^Avάyκης y6vaσιv. εττϊ Βε τών κύκΧων αύτον άνωθεν εφ' εκάστον βεβηκέναι ζ,ειρήνα σνμττεριφερομενην, φωνην μίαν ίεΐσαν, ενα τόνον εκ ττασών Βε οκτώ ονσών μίαν άρμονίαν ξνμφωνεΐν. άΧΧας THE MYTH OF EE 141 bonds thereof: for this Light is that which bindeth the Heavens together; as the under-girths hold together ships so doth it hold together the whole round of Heaven ; and from the ends extendeth the Spindle of Necessity, which causeth all the heavenly revolutions, whereof the shaft and hook are of adamant, and the whorl is of adamant and of other substances therewith. " Now, the whorl is after this fashion. In shape it is as one of our whorls, but from what he said we must conceive of it as a great whorl, carved hollow through and through, where- in is set, fitting it, a smaller whorl of like kind, as caskets are set fitting into one another ; and then in this a third whorl is set, and then a fourth, and then four others ; for the whorls are together eight, set one within another, showing their lips as circles above, and making thus the even continued outside of one whorl round about the shaft ; and the shaft is driven right through the middle of the eighth whorl. " The first and outermost whorl hath the circle of its lip the broadest ; the circle of the sixth is second for breadth ; the circle of the fourth is third; the circle of the eighth is fourth ; the circle of the seventh is fifth ; the circle of the fifth is sixth ; the circle of the third is seventh ; the circle of the second is eighth. And the circle of the greatest is of many colours ; the circle of the seventh is brightest ; the circle of the eighth hath its colour from the seventh which shineth upon it ; the circles of the second and fifth are like unto each other, being ruddier than the rest ; the third hath the whitest colour ; the fourth is pale red ; and the sixth is second for whiteness. " The spindle turneth round wholly with one motion ; but of the whole that turneth round the seven circles within turn slowly contrary to the whole : and of these the eighth goeth swiftest ; next, and together, go the seventh and the sixth and the fifth ; third in swiftness goeth the fourth ; fourth, the third ; and fifth, the second. " And the whole spindle goeth round in the lap of Necessity. " Aloft upon each of the circles of the spindle is mounted a Siren ; which goeth round with her circle, uttering one note at one pitch ; and the notes of all the eight together do make one melody. 142 THE MYTHS OF PLATO C δέ καθημίνας ττέριξ Bo' ίσου τρβΐς, ev θρόνω βκάστην, dvyarepa^ τής ^ΑναΎκης, Μοίρας, Χβυχ^είμονονσας, στέμματα iirl των κβφαΧών έχ^ούσας, Κά'χβσίν Τ€ καϊ Κλω^ώ κα\ "ΑτροΊΓον, νμνβΐν ττρος την των Χβίρηνων άρμονίαν, Αάγβσυν μεν τα ηεηονότα, Κλω^ώ δε τα οντά, ^Άτροττον δε τα μάΧλοντα. καϊ την μβν ΚΧωθω τη Ββξια χ<£ΐρΙ βφατττομενην συνετηστρεφειν του ατράκτου την βξω ττεριφοράν, ΒιάΧεί- τΓουσαν γ^ρόνον, την δε "Ατροττον τη αριστερά τας εντο<; D αΰ ωσαύτως' την δε Αάγεσίν εν μέρει εκατερας εκατερα τη χ€ίρΙ εφάΐΓτεσθαί. σφάς ουν, εττειΒη άφικεσθαι, ευθύς Βεΐν Ιεναι ττρος την Αάγεσιν. ττροφήτην ουν τίνα σφάς ττρώτον μεν εν τάξει Βιαστήσαι, εττειτα Χαβόντα εκ των της Ααγεσεως ηονάτων κΧηρους τε καϊ βίων ιταραΒεί^γματα, άναβάντα εττί τι βήμα ύψηΧον είττεΐν ^Ανά<γκης θυ^ατρος κόρης Ααχεσεως Χό'^ος. "^υχαΐ εφήμεροι, άρχτ) άΧΧης ττεριοΒου θνητού yεvoυς Ε θανατηφόρου. ούχ υμάς Βαίμων Χηξεται, αλλ' ύμεΐς Βαίμονα αίρησεσθε. ττρώτος δ' ο Χαγων ττρώτος αίρείσθω βίον, ω συνεσται εξ ανάγκης. άρετη δε άΒεσττοτον, ην τιμών καϊ άτιμάζων ττΧεον καϊ εΧαττον αυτής έκαστος εξει. αίτια εΧομενου' θεός αναίτιος. Ταύτα είττόντα ρΐψαι εττϊ ττάντας τους κΧηρους, τον δε τταρ* αύτον ττεσόντα εκαστον άναιρεΐσθαι, ττΧην ου' ε δε ούκ εάν τω δε άνεΧομενω 618 δήλοι/ είναι, όττόστος είΧήγειν μετά Βε τούτο αύθις τα των βίων τταραΒεί^ματα εις το ττροσθεν σφών θεΐναι εττϊ την ^ήν, τΓοΧύ ττΧείω των τταρόντων. είναι δε τταντοΒαττά' ζώων τε yap ττάντων βίους καϊ Βη και τους άνθρωττίνους άτταντας. τυραννίΒας τε yap εν αύτοΐς είναι, τ ας μεν ΒιατεΧεΐς, τας δε καϊ μεταξύ Βιαφθειρομενας και εις ττενίας τε καϊ φυyaς καϊ εις τττωχείας τεΧευτώσας' είναι Βε καϊ Βοκίμων άνΒρών βίους, τους μεν εττϊ εϊΒεσι καϊ κατά κάΧΧη *? THE MYTH OF EK 143 " Eound about are three others seated at equal distances apart, each upon a throne : these be the Daughters of I^ecessity, the Fates, Lachesis, and Clotho, and Atropos. They are clothed in white raiment and have garlands on their heads ; and they chant to the melody of the Sirens ; Lachesis chanteth of the things that have been, and Clotho of the things that are, and Atropos of the things that shall be : and Clotho with her right hand ever and anon taketh hold of the outer round of the spindle, and helpeth to turn it ; and Atropos with her left hand doeth the same with the inner rounds ; and Lachesis with either hand taketh hold of outer and inner alternately.^ " Now he said that when they were come, it behoved them straightway to go unto Lachesis. Wherefore a Prophet did first marshal them in order ; and then having taken lots out of the lap of Lachesis and Ensamples of Lives, went up into a high pulpit and said : Thus saith Necessity's Daughter, Maid Lachesis — Souls of a day, now beginneth another course of earthly life which bringeth death. For you your Angels will not cast lots, to get you, but each one of you shall choose his Angel. Let him to whom falleth the first turn, first choose the Life unto which he shall be bound of necessity. But Virtue hath no master. As a man honoureth her and dis- honoureth her, so shall he have more of her and less. He who hath chosen shall answer for it. God is not answerable. " Er said that when the Prophet had spoken these words, he threw the lots unto all, and each took up the lot which fell beside him, save only himself; for the Prophet suffered him not. " Now when each had taken up his lot, it was plain what number he had gotten. Thereafter the Prophet laid on the ground before them the Ensamples of Lives, far more than for the persons there. Now these Ensamples were of all sorts: there were Lives of all kinds of creatures, and moreover of all conditions of men ; for there were kingships among them, some that lasted for a whole lifetime, and some on the way to downfall, and ending with poverty and flight and beggary. Also there were Lives of men renowned, some of them for ^ I.e., as Mr. Adam explains (note on 617 c, d), she lays hold of outer (the circle of the Same) and inner (1j;ie circle of the Other) in turn, using her right hand for the former, and her left for the latter. * 144 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Β καΧ την άΧλην Ισγνν re καϊ αηωνίαν^ τους δ' €7γΙ ηενβσυ καΐ Ίτροηόνων άρεταΐς, καϊ αδόκιμων κατά ταύτα, ωσαύτως δε καΐ yvvaiKcov ψυχής δε τάξί,ν ουκ iveivaL Bca το άνα^καίως εχε^ι/ αΚΚον ίλομύνην βίον άΧΚοίαν ηίην^σθαΐ' τα δ' άλλα αΚΚ'ηΚοις τε και ττΧούτοις καϊ ττενίαι,ς, τα Sk νόσοις, τα δε ύ^γίβίαις μβμΐχθαι,, τα Be καϊ μεσούν τούτων. €νθα Βή, ώς eoLK€Vy ω φίΧε ΤΧαύκων, 6 ττάς κίνΒυνος άνθρώττω, καϊ Bta ταύτα μάλιστα ίτΓΐμβΚητίον, οττως έκαστος C ημών των αΧλων μαθημάτων άμελησας τούτου του μαθή- ματος καϊ ζητητης καϊ μαθητής εσται, εάν ττοθεν οίος τ τ) μαθεΐν καϊ εξευρεΐν, τις αύτον ττοιήσει Βυνατον καϊ ετηστήμονα, βίον καϊ χρηστον καϊ ττονηρον Βια'^ΐ'^νώσκοντα τον βεΧτίω εκ των Βυνατών άεϊ ττανταχρύ αιρείσθαι, άνάλο<γιζ6μενον ττάντα τα νυν Βη ρηθεντα καϊ ξυντιθεμενα άΧλήΧοις καϊ Βιαιρούμενα ττρος άρετην βίου ττώς έχει, καϊ D εΙΒεναι, τί κάΧλος ττενία ή ττΧούτω κραθεν καϊ μετά ττοίας τίνος ψυχής εξεως κακόν ή ά^αθον εpyάζετaι, καϊ τί εύ^ενειαι καϊ Βυσ<γενειαι καϊ ΙΒιωτεΐαι καϊ άρχαϊ καϊ Ισχυες καϊ άσθενειαι καϊ εύμαθίαι καϊ Βυσμαθίαι καϊ ττάντα τα τοιαύτα των φύσει ττερϊ ψυχην όντων καϊ των επίκτητων τί ξυ^κεραννύμενα ττρος άΧληΧα εργάζεται, ώστε εξ άττάντων αυτών Βυνατον είναι συΧΧο^ισάμενον αίρεΐσθαι, ττρος την της ψυχής φύσιν άτΓοβΧεττοντα, τον τε χείρω καϊ τον Ε άμείνω βίον, χείρω μεν καΧούντα, ος αύτην εκεΐσε άξει, εις το άΒικωτεραν ^Ιτ^νεσθαι, άμείνω δε όστις εις το Βικαιοτεραν, τά δε άΧΧα ττάντα χαίρειν εάν εωράκαμεν yap, οτι ζώντί τε καϊ τεΧευτήσαντι αύτη κρατίστη αίρεσις, άΒαμαντίνως 619 δ^ Βεΐ ταύτην την Βόξαν έχοντα εις ^ΆιΒου Ιεναι, οττως αν η καϊ εκεί άνεκττΧηκτος ύττο ττΧούτων τε καϊ των τοιούτων κακών, καϊ μη εμττεσων εις τυραννίΒας καϊ άΧΧας τοιαύτας ττράξεις ττοΧΧά μεν εpyάσητaι καϊ ανήκεστα κακά, ετι δε αύτος μείζω ττάθη, αλλά yvo) τον μέσον άεϊ τών τοιούτων βίον αίρεΐσθαι καϊ φεύyειv τά ύττερβάΧΧοντα εκατερωσε κσ,ϊ THE MYTH OF ER U5 comeliness and beauty, or for strength and prowess, some for birth and the virtues of their forefathers ; likewise also there were Lives of men of no such renown. There were also Lives of women. But conditions of the Soul were not amongst the Ensamples ; the reason whereof is this, that a Soul which hath chosen a certain Life is of necessity changed accordingly ; but all other things both good and evil were there mixed together — riches and poverty, and health and disease, and also states between these. " There, methinks, dear Glaucon, is man's great peril Wherefore let each one of us give heed to this chiefly, how that, taking no thought for the knowledge of other things, he shall seek after the knowledge of one thing, if peradventure he may learn and find out who it is that shall make him able and wise, so that he may discern the good Life from the evil, and, according to his ability, alway and everywhere choose the better Life, and reckoning how all the things that have been now said, both taken together and severally, concern the Virtuous Life, may understand what good or evil, for what state of the Soul, beauty joined with poverty or riches worketh, and what good or evil noble birth, and base birth, and private station, and rule in the city, and strength, and weakness, and quickness of wit, and slowness, and the other native qualities of the Soul like unto these, and the qualities which the Soul acquireth, do work, according as they are mixed variously with one another ; to the end that, having taken count of all these, he may be able to choose, having regard to the nature of his Soul, between the worse and the better Life, calling that the worse which will lead his Soul to become more unrighteous, and calling that the better which will lead it to become more righteous. All else will he let go by ; for we have seen and know that this is the best choice for a man, both whilst he liveth and when he is dead. With this doctrine, then, as hard as adamant within him, must he go unto Hades, so that there also he may not be amazed at riches and such like trumpery, and may not fall into the Life of a tyrant or of some other such evil-doer, and work iniquities many and without all remedy, and himself suffer still worse things ; but rather may discern to choose alway the Life between such states, and eschew the extremes on eil;her hand, both in this Life, as far L 146 THE MYTHS OF PLATO €v τώδε τω βίω κατά το Βυνατον καΐ iv τταντϊ τω eiretTa' Β οντω yap εύΒαιμονύστατος yLyveTai άνθρω7Γ0<ζ, καϊ Βη ονν κα\ τότε 6 εκβΐθβν άγγελος rjyyeWe τον μεν ττροφήτην οΰτως είττεΐν, καϊ τεΚευταίω εττωντί, ξύν νω εΧομενω, συντόνων ζώντί κείται, βίος άγατττ/το?, ου κακός, μήτε ό αρ'χων αίρεσεως άμεΧεΙτω μήτε 6 τεΧευτών αθυμείτω. είττόντος Βε ταύτα τον πρώτον Χαγόντα εφη ενθνς ετΓίόντα την με^ίστην τνραννίΒα εΧεσθαί, καϊ υττο αφροσύνης τε καϊ Χαιμαρ^ίας ου ττάντα Ικανως άνασκεψά- C μενον εΧεσθαι, αλλ* αύτον ΧαθεΙν ενοΰσαν είμαρμενην, τταίΒων αύτον βρώσεις καϊ άΧΧα κακά* εττειΒη Βε κατά σ'χοΧην σκεψασθαί, κότττεσθαί τε καϊ οΒύρεσθαι την αΐρεσίν, ουκ εμμένοντα τοις ττρορρηθεΐσίν νττο τον προ- φήτου* ου yap εαυτόν αΐτίάσθαι, των κακών, -άΧΧα τύ'χτ^ν τε καϊ Βαίμονας καϊ ττάντα μάΧΧον άνθ^ εαυτού. είναι Βε αύτον των εκ του ουρανού ηκόντων, εν τετayμεvr} ττοΧίτεία εν τω ττροτερω βίω βεβιωκότα, εθεί άνευ φίΧοσοφίας αρετής D μετείΧηφοτα. ως Βε καϊ είττείν, ούκ εΧάττους είναι εν τοΐς τοιούτους άΧυσκομενους τους εκ του ουρανού ήκοντας, άτε ττόνων άyυμvάστoυς• των δ' εκ της γης τους ττοΧΧούς, άτε αυτούς τε ττεττονηκότας άΧΧους τε εωρακότας, ούκ εξ εΐΓίΒρομής τάς αΙρεσεις ττοίεΐσθαι. Βώ Βη καϊ μεταβοΧην των κακών καϊ τών άyaθώv ταΐς ττοΧΧαϊς τών ψυχρών yίyvεσθaL καϊ Βοά την του κΧηρου τύγτ^ν εττεϊ εϊ τις αεί, Ε ΟΊΓΟτε εις τον ενθάΒε βίον άφικνοΐτο, ύyίώς φιΧοσοφοΙ καϊ ο κΧήρος αύτω της αίρεσεως μη εν τεΧευταίοις Ίτίτττοι, κίνΒυνεύει εκ τών εκείθεν ά7ΓayyεXXoμεvωv ού μόνον ενθάΒε εύΒαίμονεΐν άν, άΧΧά καϊ την ενθενΒε εκεΐσε καϊ Βεύρο ΊτάΧιν τΓορειαν ούκ άν γθονίαν καϊ τραγεΐαν ττορεύεσθαι, άλλα λεί.αΐ' τε καϊ ούρανίαν. ταύτην yap Βη, εφη, την θεαν άξιαν είναι ΙΒεΙν, ως εκασται αϊ ψυ^αϊ τιρονντο τους 620 βίους • εΧεεινήν τε yap ιΒεΐν είναι καϊ yεXoίav καϊ θαυμα- σίαν. κατά συνηθειαν yap του ττροτερου βίου τά ττοΧΧά αίρεΐσθαι. ιΒεΐν μεν yap Λ^υχ^ζ/ εφη την ττοτε ^Ορφεως THE MYTH OF EK U7 as he is able, and in all the Life hereafter : for in this lieth man's chief happiness. " Now the Messenger who brought this Tale from that place went on and said that the Prophet then spake thus : — Even for him whose turn cometh last, if he hath chosen with under- standing, there is prepared a Life, which, if only a man bear himself manfully, is tolerable, not wretched. Neither let him who cometh first be careless of his choice ; nor let him who cometh at the end be downcast. " He said that when the Prophet had spoken these words, the one that had gotten the first place, as soon as he came forward, chose the greatest kingship there ; and by reason of folly and greediness looked not well enough into all before he chose it, and marked not that therein it was appointed of Fate that he should eat his own children, and that other evils should befall him. When therefore he had looked at it at leisure, he began to beat his breast and bewail his choice, not abiding by the commandment of the Prophet ; for he did not blame him- self for these evils, but Ill-Luck, and Gods, and any thing rather than himself. Now, he was of them that were come from Heaven, having spent his former life in a well-ordered city, and become virtuous through Custom without True Knowledge : they that were come from Heaven were not the least part, belike, of them that were caught thus ; for they had not been exercised with labours ; but most part of those from under the Earth, inasmuch as they themselves had endured labours, and had seen others enduring, made not their choice hastily. For this cause, as well as through the luck of the lot, a change of good and of evil befalleth most part of the Souls ; for if any man, whenever he cometh into this life, seek alway with his whole heart after wisdom, and if the lot so fall that he is not of the last to choose, there is good hope, from what the Messenger said, not only that he will have happiness here, but also that the journey hence to that place and back again hither will not be under the ground and rough, but smooth and heavenly. " Truly it was a sight worth looking at, he said, to see how the Souls severally chose their lives — yea, a pitiful sight, and a laughable, and a wonderful ; inasmuch as they chose mostly after the custom of their former life ; for he told how he saw 148 THE MYTHS OF PLATO ^€νομ€νην κύκνου βίον αίρουμβνην, μίσβί του ^γυναικείου γένους Βια τον υττ εκείνων θάνατον ουκ εθεΧουσαν iv yvvaiKl ^γεννηθείσαν γενέσθαι* ΙΒεΐν 8ε την %αμύρου άηΒόνος εΧομενην ί8εΐν Βε καϊ κύκνον μεταβάλΧοντα εΙς άνθρωττίνου Β βίου αϊρεσίν, καΧ άΧΧα ζώα μουσικά ωσαύτως. είκοστην Βε Χα'χρυσαν ψυγην εΧεσθαι Χεοντος βίον είναι Βε την Αϊαντο<; του ΎεΧαμωνίου, φεύ^ουσαν άνθρωττον ηενεσθαι^ μεμνημενην της των οττΧων κρίσεως. την δ' εττΐ τούτω Ay αμεμνονος* ε'χθρα Βε καϊ ταύτην του άνθρωττίνου γένους Βιά τα ττάθη άετου ΒιαΧΧάξαι βίον. εν μεσοις Βε Χαγουσαν την ^ΑταΧάντης ψυχ^ην, κατιΒουσαν με^άΧας τιμάς άθΧητοΰ άνΒρος, ου Βύνασθαι τταρεΧθεΐν^ άΧΧά Χαβεΐν. μετά Βε C ταύτην ΙΒεΐν την Έττε^οΟ του ΤΙανοττεως εις τε'χνικης γυναικός Ιουσαν φύσιν ττόρρω Β* εν ύστάτοις ιΒεΐν την του ^γεΧωτοτΓΟίοΰ ©ερσίτου ττίθηκον ενΒυομενην κατά τύγτ)ν Βε την ^ΟΒυσσεως, Χα'χρυσαν ττασών ύστάτην, αίρησομενην ιεναί' μνημτ) Βε των προτέρων ττόνων φιΧοτιμίας ΧεΧωφη- κυΐαν ξητεΐν ττεριϊοΰσαν χρόνον ττοΧύν βίον άνΒρος ΙΒιώτου άτΓ pay μονός, καϊ μο^ις εύρεΐν κείμενόν ττου καϊ τταρημεΧημενον D ύτΓΟ των άΧΧων, καϊ είττεΐν ΙΒουσαν, οτι τά αυτά αν ειτραξε καϊ πρώτη Χαχοΰσα, καϊ άσμενην εΧεσθαι, καϊ εκ των άΧΧων Βη θηρίων ωσαύτως εις ανθρώπους Ιεναι καϊ εις άΧΧηΧα, τά μεν άΒικα εΙς τά aypia, τά Βε Βίκαια εις τά ήμερα μεταβάΧΧοντα, καϊ πάσας μίξεις μί^γνυσθαι. επειΒη δ* οΰν πάσας τάς 'ψυγάς τους βίους ηρήσθαι, ώσπερ εΧαγον, εν τάξει προσ ιεναι προς την Αάγεσιν εκείνην δ' εκάστω ον Ε ε'ιΧετο Βαίμονα, τούτον φύΧακα ξυμπεμπειν του βίου καϊ άποπΧηρωτην των αίρεθεντων. ον πρώτον μεν άηειν αύτην προς την Κλω^ώ υπο την εκείνης χεΙρά τε καϊ επιστροφην της του ατράκτου Βίνης, κυροϋντα ην Χαγων εΐΧετο μοΐραν* ταύτης δ* εφαψάμενον αύθις επϊ την της ^Ατρόπου ά^ειν νήσιν, άμετάστροφα τά επικΧωσθεντα ποιουντα• εντεύθεν THE MYTH OF EK 149 the Soul that had been Orpheus's choosing a swan's Life, for that, hating womankind because women murdered him, it would not be born of a woman. Also he said that he saw the Soul of Thamyras when it had chosen the life of a nightingale ; and that he saw also a swan changing, and choosing the life of a man, and other musical creatures doing likewise. And the Soul which got the twentieth place chose the life of a lion : this was the Soul of Ajax, the son of Telamon, which eschewed becoming a man because it remembered the Judgment concern- ing the Arms. Next came the Soul of Agamemnon ; which also, out of enmity towards mankind because that it went evil with him, took in exchange the life of an eagle. The Soul of Atalanta, which had gotten her place between the first and the last, perceiving the great honour which belongeth to the life of a man who contendeth at the Games, was not able to pass by but took it. After her he saw the Soul of Epeius, the son of Panopeus, passing into the nature of a spinster ; and amongst the last he saw the Soul of Thersites the jester putting on an ape. Also it chanced that the Soul of Odysseus, which had gotten the last place of all, came forward to choose, and having abated all her ambition because she remembered her former labours, went about seeking for a long while, and after much ado, found the life of a quiet private man lying somewhere despised of the others, and when she saw it said — ' Had I come first I would have done the same ; ' and took it with great joy. " Beasts likewise were changed into men and into one another, the unjust into those that were savage, and the just into those that were tame : yea in everywise were they mixed together. " Now when all the Souls had chosen their lives according to the place allotted unto each, they went forward, in order, unto Lachesis; and she sent the Angel, which each one had chosen, with him, to be the guardian of his life and to fulfil the things that he had chosen; and the Angel, bringing him first unto Clotho, taketh him beneath her hand and the revolution of the whirling spindle, and ratifieth the Portion which the man had chosen in his turn ; then, from her presence, the Angel brought him unto Atropos where she span ; so did he make th5 threads of the man's life unalterable. 150 THE MYTHS OF PLATO 621 δε Βη άμ€ταστρ€7Γτϊ iiiro τον τή<ζ ^Ανά^γκης ievai θρόνον, καΐ Be εκείνου Βιβξβλθόντα, εττειΒη καϊ οι άΧλοι ΒιήΧθον, ΤΓορεύβσθαί άτταντας βίς το τή<ζ Αηθης ττβΒίον Βία καύματος Τ6 καϊ TTvlyovi Beivov* καϊ yap elvai αυτό Kevov ΒβνΒρων τ€ καϊ οσα yrj φύει. σκηνασθαι ουν σφάς ήΒη εσττίρα^ζ yiyvoμkv'η<ζ τταρα τον ^Αμελητα ττοταμον, ου το νΒωρ άyyεΐov ούΒεν στεyεcv. μετρον μεν ουν tl του ΰΒατος Ίτασι,ν avayKalov είναι ττιεΐν^ τους Βε φρονήσει, μη σωζομε- Β νους ΊτΚεον ττίνείν του μετρον τον Βε άεΐ ττιόντα ττάντων ετΓίΚανθάνεσθαί. εττειΒη Βε κοίμηθηναι καϊ μεσας νύκτας yεvεσθaLy βροντην τε καϊ σεισμον yεvεσθaly καϊ εντεύθεν εξαττίνης αλΧον αλλτ; φέρεσθαι άνω εΙς την yεvεσLv, άτ- τοντας ωσττερ αστέρας, αύτος Βε του μεν ΰΒατος κωΧυθήναι ΤΓίεΐν οΐΓΎ} μεντοι καϊ οττως εΙς το σώμα άφίκοίτο, ουκ εΙΒεναι, άλ\' εξαίφνης άναβΧεψας ΙΒεΐν εωθεν αυτόν κείμενον εττΐ ττ} ττυρα. ΚαΙ οΰτως, ω ΤΧαύκων, μύθος C εσώθη καϊ ουκ άττώΧετο, καϊ ημάς αν σώσειεν, αν ττειθώ- μεθα αύτω, καϊ τον της Αήθης ττοταμον ευ Βιαβησόμεθα καϊ την ψυχ^ην ου μιανθησόμεθα' αλλ* αν εμοϊ ττειθώμεθα, νομίζοντες άθάνατον ψυχ^ην καϊ Βυνατην πτάντα μεν κακά άνεγεσθαι, ττάντα Βε aya0a, της άνω οΒού άεϊ εξόμεθα καϊ Βίκαιοσύνην μετά φρονησεως τταντϊ τρόττω εττιτηΒεύσομεν, ίνα καϊ ήμΐν αύτοΐς φίλοι ωμεν καϊ τοΙς θεοίς, αυτού τε D μένοντες ενθάΒε, καϊ εττειΒάν τα άθλα αυτής κομιζώμεθα, ωσττερ οΐ νικηφόροι 7Γεpιayειp6μεvoι, καϊ ενθάΒε καϊ εν Τ'β γ^ΐΚιετεΐ ΊΓορεία, ην ΒιεΧηΧνθαμεν, εν ττράττωμεν. THE MYTH OF ER 151 " Thence, Er said, each man, without turning back, went straight on under the throne of Necessity, and when each, even unto the last, was come out through it, they all together journeyed to the Plain of Lethe, through terrible burning heat and frost; and this Plain is without trees or any herb that the earth bringeth forth. " He said that they encamped, when it was already evening, beside the River of Forge tfulness, the water whereof no pitcher holdeth. Now, it was necessary that all should drink a certain measure of the water ; but they that were not preserved by wisdom drank more than the measure ; and as each man drank, he forgot all. Then he said that when they had fallen asleep and midnight was come, there was thunder and an earthquake, and of a sudden they flew up thence unto divers parts to be born in the flesh, shooting like meteors. But he himself was not suffered to drink of the water: yet by what means and how he came unto his body he knew not; but suddenly he opened his eyes, and lo ! it was morning, and he was lying on the pyre. " Thus, Glaucon, was the Tale preserved from perishing, and it will preserve us if we believe in it ; so shall we pass over the River of Lethe safely, and keep our Souls undefiled. " This is my counsel : let us believe that the Soul is immortal, and able to bear all ill and all good, and let us always keep to the upward way, and practise justice in all things with understanding, that we may be friends both with ourselves and with the Gods, both whilst we sojourn here, and when we receive the prizes of our justice, like unto Conquerors at the Games which go about gathering their wages ; and that both here, and in the journey of a thousand years of which I told, we may fare welL" 152 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Observations on the Myth of Er Let us begin with the geography and cosmography of the Myth. The Meadow of the Judgment-seat, between the two open- ings of Tartarus (in and out) on the one side, and the two corresponding openings of Heaven on the other side, is also the meeting-place of the Souls which return from their thousand years' sojourn in Tartarus and Heaven. From the Meadow they journey, always above ground, till they come to a " rainbow-coloured light, straight like a pillar, extended from on high throughout the Heaven and the Earth." This Light is the axis, I take it, on which the whole heavenly system revolves, the Earth fixed in the centre of the system being a globe on the line of the axis. The destination of the Pilgrim Souls is that part of the surface of the globe at which, in the hemisphere where they are, the axis enters on its imaginary course through the centre of the Earth, in order to come out again at the antipodal point in the other hemi- sphere. The Souls, arrived at the very point where, in the hemisphere where they are, the axis of the Cosmos enters the Earth, are in the place of all places where the Law which controls all things is intuitively plain — they see the Pillar of Light as the Spindle of Necessity. Then, suddenly, the outlook presented to us in the Myth changes like the scene in a dream. It is no longer such a view of the Cosmos from within as we had, a moment ago, while we stood with the Pilgrims on the surface of the Earth, looking up at the Pillar of Light in the sky : we are now looking at the Cosmos from the outside, as if it were an orrery — a model of concentric cups or rings ; and Necessity herself is holding the model in her lap, and the three Fates are seated round, and keep turn- ing the eight cups, on each of which, on its edge, a Siren is mounted who sings in tune with her sisters. But the Pilgrim Souls are standing near, looking on at this spectacle. They are on their way, we know, from the Meadow to the Plain of Lethe, both places on the surface of the Earth : it is on the THE MYTH OF ER 153 Earth then, after all, that the throne is placed on which Necessity sits holding in her lap the model, which, like a true dream-thing, is both a little model and the great Cosmos itself.^ In this place, in the presence of Necessity on her throne, the Pilgrim Souls are addressed by the Prophet from his pulpit ; then choose, in the turns which the lots determine, lives of men or beasts scattered, it would seem, as little images at their feet ; ^ then go before the three Fates, who ^ Let me illustrate this characteristic of the "dream-thing" from the Dream in the Fifth Book of Wordsworth's Prelude : — On poetry and geometric truth, And their high privilege of lasting life, From all internal injury exempt, I mused ; upon these chiefly : and at length, My senses yielding to the sultry air, Sleep seized me, and I passed into a dream. I saw before me stretched a boundless plain Of sandy wilderness, all black and void. And as I looked around, distress and fear Came creeping over me, when at my side, Close at my side, an uncouth shape appeared Upon a dromedary, mounted high. He seemed an Arab of the Bedouin tribes : A lance he bore, and underneath one arm A stone, and in the opposite hand a shell Of a surpassing brightness. . . . ****** . . . The Arab told me that the stone Was "Euclid's Elements " ; and "This," said he, *' Is something of more worth " ; and at the word Stretched forth the shell, so beautiful in shape, In colour so resplendent, with command That I should hold it to my ear. I did so, And heard that instant in an unknown tongue, Which yet I understood, articulate sounds, A loud prophetic blast of harmony ; An Ode, in passion uttered. . . . ****** While this was uttering, strange as it may seem, I wondered not, although I plainly saw The one to be a stone, the other a shell ; Nor doubted once but that they both were books, Having a perfect faith in all that passed. 2 I think that Plato may have borrowed his τα των βίων τταραδεί-γματα here from votive images of trades and callings, and of animals : "The Argive Heraeum," says Mr. Rouse {Greek Votive Offeriiigs, p. 298), "yielded hundreds of animals in bronze and clay : bulls, cows, oxen and oxherds, goats, sheep, cocks, ducks, and other birds, including perhaps a swan." These animals (to which may be added horses, pigs, doves), were, Mr. Rouse supposes, either sacrificial victims or first-fruits of hunting. Referring to human figures he says, p. 79, " It is at least probable that a successful huntsman, artist, craftsman, trader, would dedicate a figure, in character, as a thank-offering for success in his calling." If I remember rightly, a little fignfe, recognised as that of a " Philosopher," was discovered in the tomb of " Aristotle " found near Chalcis some years ago. 154 THE MYTHS OF PLATO ratify the chosen doom of each; then pass severally under the throne of Necessity ; and thence travel together, through a hot dusty region, till they come to the Plain of Lethe, where no green thing grows, and to the Eiver the water of which no pitcher can hold. When the Souls have drunk of this water — the foolish, too much — they fall asleep ; but at midnight there is an earthquake and thunder, and suddenly, like meteors, they shoot up to be born again, in terrestrial bodies, in our part of the Earth. The account given by Plato here is strictly in accordance with the popular belief, which makes Lethe a river entirely above ground, never counts it among the rivers of Tartarus.^ Virgil, in Aen. vi. 705, 714, may be thought to place it under ground ; but his description suffers in clearness from com- pression ; and it is not likely that he willingly deserts traditional authority in a matter of such importance as the position of Lethe. His veKma, as a whole, is derived from a source (considered by Eohde and Dieterich to be the κατάβασις eh AKBov) common to himself with Pindar, Plato, Plutarch, Lucian, and (according to Dieterich, though here Eohde does not agree with him) ^ the writers of certain sepulchral inscrip- tions which I shall describe in the next section ; and where Lethe appears in any of these authors, it never, I believe, appears as one of the infernal, or subterranean, rivers. Indeed, all reasonable doubt as to Virgil's orthodoxy seems to be barred by his statement that the plain in which Souls about to be born again are gathered together near the banks of Lethe has its own sun (Ae7i. vi. 641). It is evidently above ground somewhere — the writer of the Axiochus would perhaps say in the antipodal hemisphere of the Earth. IP The object of this section is to point to a detail — the twin-streams, Εηηοέ and Lethe, of the Earthly Paradise {Purg. xxviii.) — in which Dante's vision of Purgatory reproduces — I ^ See Thiemann, Platonische Eschatologie, p. 18. 2 Dieterich, Nek. 128 f., 135, and Rohde, Psy. ii. 217. ^ It ought to be mentioned that this section was written, and the substance of it read in the course of a public lecture, and also to a private society, before the appearance of Miss Harrison's Prolegomena to the Study of Greek Religion, and her " Query " in The Classical Review, Feb. 1903, p. 58. THE MYTH OF EE 155 think, independently — a distinctive feature of that Orphic ritual and mythology to which Plato is largely indebted for his account of the Soul's κάθαρσις as a process of forgetting and remembering — as a series of transmigrations through which the particulars of sense, the evils and sins of the flesh, are forgotten or left behind, and the universal Ideas, long ob- scured, are, at last, so clearly remembered that they can never be forgotten any more, but become the everlasting possession of the Soul, finally disembodied and returned to its own star. It is easy to account, from the literary sources open to Dante, for the presence of rivers, and more particularly of Lethe, in his Earthly Paradise. On the one hand, the descrip- tion of Eden in Genesis would suggest the general idea of rivers girding the Earthly Paradise ; ^ while, on the other hand, the proximity of Purgatory to the Earthly Paradise makes it natural that Lethe should be one of these rivers — that first reached by one coming up from Purgatory. The drinking of Lethe, according to Aen. vi. and the current mythology, is the act with which a period of purgatorial discipline is closed by those Souls which are about to pass again into the flesh. In placing the Earthly Paradise on the top of a lofty mountain Dante followed a prevalent medieval beHef; and, although he seems to have drawn on his own imagination in placing Purgatory on the slopes of this mountain, it was natural, and in accordance with the current mythology, that he should place it there, close to the Earthly Paradise or Elysium ; for the Lethe of Aen. vi. is evidently in the same region as Elysium, — Interea videt Aeneas in valle reducta Secliisum nemus et virgulta sonantia sylvis, Lethaeumque domos placidas qui praenatat amnem.2 The presence, then, of Lethe, the purgatorial stream, in Dante's Earthly Paradise is easily accounted for by reference to the mythological authorities open to him. But for the association of Εηηοέ, the stream of Memory, with Lethe, the stream of Eorgetfulness, it does not seem possible to account in this way. The common mythology gives Lethe alone. It 1 See Vernon's Headings on the Purgatorio, ii. 285-293. Lethe girds the Earthly Paradise on the side o| Earth, Eunoe on the side of Heaven. 2 Virg. Aen. vi. 703. 166 THE MYTHS OF PLATO is not likely that Dante had heard of the twin streams — Lethe and Mnemosyne — of the Orphic cult ; at any rate, in the absence of evidence that he had heard of them, it seems better to suppose that the very natural picture of a stream of Memory beside the stream of Forgetfulness occurred to him spon- taneously, as it had occurred to others, who, like himself, were deeply concerned to find expression for their hope of κάθαρσης. For the twin streams of the Orphic cult which resemble Dante's Lethe and Eunoe so closely, we must turn to the sepulchral inscriptions mentioned at the end of the last section. These are certain directions for the ghostly journey to be made by initiated persons, written in hexameter verse on gold tablets found in graves at Thurii and Petelia in South Italy, and now preserved in the British Museum. These tablets were described by Comparetti in the Journal of Hellenic Studies, iii. p. Ill if., and are printed by Kaibel in his Insc. Gr. Sic. et It p. 157. Kaibel assigns them to the third or fourth century B.C. I shall quote the one that was found at Petelia.^ It gives directions to an initiated person who hopes to get out of the Cycle of Incarnations — κύκΚου τ αν Χήξαί, καϊ άναττνενσαί κακότητοζ^ — having been completely purified. Such a person, the verses say, must avoid the fountain on the left hand with a white cypress growing near it, evidently the water of Lethe, although the tablet does not name it. It is to the right that the purified Soul of the μύστης must turn, to the cool water of Mnemosyne. The guardians of the well he must address in set form of words, thus — " I am the child of Earth and Heaven : I am parched with thirst ; I perish ; give me cool water to drink from the well of Memory." And the guardians will give him water to drink from the holy well, and he will be translated to dwell for ever with the Heroes : — €νρήσ•€ί<ζ δ' Άΐ8αο δόμων ίττ' aplcrrepa κρήνην, τταρ* δ' avTy λ^νκην €σ-τηκνΐαν κνττάρισσ-ον. ταντη^ rrjs κρήνης μηδί σ•)(€δον Ι/χττελάσεια?• 1 For further description of the Petelia Tablet (in the Brit. Museum, Gold Ornament Room, Table-case H) and other Orphic golden tablets {e.g. the Eleuthernae Tablet from Crete, in the National Museum, Athens), the reader may consult Miss Harrison's Prolegomena to the Study of Greek Religion, pp. 573 if., with Appendix by Mr. G. G. A. Murray, pp. 660 ff. ^ See Lobeck, Aglaoph. p. 800. THE MYTH OF EE 157 €νρήσ€ί<ζ δ* €Τ€/3αν τψ μνημοσύνης άπο λίμνης xj/v^^pov ν8ωρ προρίον φνλακ€ς 8' ζττίττροσθζν eacriv. ctTTCtv yrjs παΐς ζ'ίμΙ καΐ ονρανον άστ€/οο€ντο?, ανταρ €μοΙ yivos ονράνιον τοδ€ δ' Γστ€ και αντοί' SiypYj δ' €ΐμΙ ανη καΐ άττόλλνμαι, άλλα δότ* α?^α \}/νχρον ν8ωρ Trpopkov της μνημοσύνης άττο λίμνης' καν[τοί (ro]t δώσουσι Trtetv θζίης άπ[ο κρήν'Ιης, καΐ τότ €7Γ€ΐτ* ά[λλοισι μ^Θ'^ ηρώ^σσιν ava^€t[s]. The Myth of Er indeed differs from the Petelia Tablet in being concerned with those who must still drink of Lethe, and be bom again in the flesh, not with those who have been thoroughly purified and drink of Mnemosyne, and so enter into the eternal peace of the disembodied state; yet there is a touch in the Platonic Myth which reminds us that the journey taken is the same as that which the Orphic μύστης; had to take with the golden tablet in his hand. The journey to the plain of Lethe, according to the Platonic. Myth, is through a dry, torrid region, and the temptation to drink too deeply of the water of Lethe is strong, and wisdom, in the imperfectly purified Soul, is needed in order to resist it. Similarly, the purified μύστης is warned by his tablet not to quench his burning thirst in Lethe, for the cool water of Mnemosyne is at hand. The drinking of Lethe is the act with which each successive period of the purgatorial discipline ends ; the drinking of Mnemosyne is the act which completes the whole series of periods in the discipline. Both streams, or fountains, are in the place — above ground, not subterranean — to which Souls journey in order that from it they may be either translated to the True Heaven, or sent back to be born again in this world. Similarly Dante places these two streams side by side on the top of the Mount of Purgatory, Lethe running west and north on the left hand of one standing on the south side of their common source and looking north ; Eunoe running east and north on his right hand. Dante, not having to set forth his doctrine of κάθαρσις in the form of a myth of metempsychosis, makes the purified Soul, before it passes from the Mount of Purgatory up into Heaven, drink only once of Lethe, at the completion of all its purgatorial stages, in order that it may forget its sins ; and then of Eunoe, that it may retain the memory of its meritorious deeds (Fur ρ. xxviii. 130). 158 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Sins are wiped out after penance, and so fully pardoned, that the sinner does not even remember that he has sinned ; but, on the other hand, he does not begin his heavenly existence as a tabula rasa — the continuity of his conscious life is pre- served by the memory he retains of his good actions. Here Dante sets forth the thought on which the Platonic doctrine of άνάμνησίς rests. It is the flesh, with its sins, that the Philosopher in the Fhaedrus forgets; but of the things of , the mind — of truth and virtue — he gains always clearer and clearer memory, working out his purification as a devotee of the true " mysteries " — μόνη τττβροϋταί ή του φιΚοσόφου Sidvota' ττρος yap βκβίνοις αεί βστι μνημΎ) κατά Βυναμ^ν, Ίτρος οΙστΓβρ θεοζ ων θβΐός έστί• τοΐς 8e 8η τοίοντοί<ζ άνηρ υττομνημασιν ορθώς 'χρώμβνος, reXeou? ael τελβτας τεΧούμβνος, τύΧβος όντως μόνος yljveTaL• (Phaedrus, 249 c). The parallel between the philosopher who "always, as far as he can, cleaves in memory to those things by cleaving to which the Deity is divine," ^ and the purified μύστης who finally drinks of the well of μνημοσύνη, is plainly in Plato's mind here, as Dieterich {Nekyia, pp. 113, 122) and others have noticed.^ Similarly, in the Phaedo, 114 c, he says ol φιλοσοφία ικανώς καθηράμβνοί avev σωμάτων ζώσο, speaking of those who are translated from the Earthly to the Celestial Paradise, i.e. from the True Surface of the Earth, or the Islands of the Blessed, to οΙκησεις eTi τούτων καΧλίονς. ^ See Thompson's note on the construction irpos έκάνοί$. 2 Dieterich {Nek. p. 122) says: " Platons Mythen stiminen in allem, was die erhaltenen Reste zu kontroliren uns gestatten, zu den Tafelchen von Thurioi und Petelia : in diesen und in jenen der himmlisohe Ursprung der Seeleu, der schmerzen voile Kreislauf, das Abbtissen der Schuld wegen alter Siinden, das Eingehen in die Gefilde der Seligkeit (Persephone tritt allerdings bei Platon ganzlich zariick) ; zur Rechten gehen wie in Platons Republik so nach deu Inschriften die zu Belohnenden und zur Linke die Strafenden, links ist die Lethe in beiden Uberlieferungen. Sollten wir nun nicht die Anspielungen bei Platon verstehen von der μνήμη der seligen Philosophen-seelen, irpbs yap iKeivois aei έστι μνημι^ {Phaid. 249 c), und unmittelbar daneben die Bezeichnung der Lehre als rAeot reXerat ? Es ist dasselbe, wenn von Pythagoras gesagt wird, er sei immer in Besitz der μνήμη gewesen (s. bes. Laert. Diog. viii. 4). Dort ist nur abstrakt gesagt, was der Quell der Mneme konkret, mythisch, und syrabolisch sein soil. Die Wiedererinnerung an das, was die Seele einst sah in ihrer gottlichen Heiniat, hilft sie erlosen ; wer sie euipfangt, ist erlost. Sollte es noch zu kiihn sein, in jeuer ofFenbar viel iilteren Vorstellung der unteritalischen Mysterien, die nun fur uns erst uni Platons Zeit oder etwas spater durch diese Tafelchen ans Licht treten, eine Quelle der platonischen Lehre von der άνάμνησίί zu finden ? Das kann hier nur angedeutet werden, sonst wiirde sich herausstellen, dass diese Mysterienlehre iiberhaupt von viel grbsserem Einflusse auf die ganze Psychologie, ja die ganze Ideenlehre gewesen sind, als man hatte annehmen konnen." THE MYTH OF EK 159 I may perhaps be allowed to notice here, in passing, a curious point of contact between Plato's representation of κάθαρσις as effected through a series of metempsychoses, and Dante's representation of it as an ascent from terrace to terrace of the Mount of Purgatory. In the Myth of Er Plato says that the Souls come to Lethe in the evening, and drink of the water, and fall asleep ; and at midnight there is thunder and an earthquake, and they shoot up like meteors to be born again in the flesh. Similarly, Dante tells us {Furg. XX. and xxi.) that when a Soul passes to a higher terrace in the course of its purification, the Mount of Purgatory is shaken, and there is a great shout of the spirits praising God. The Soul of the poet Statins, which had just passed to a higher terrace, thus explains the matter to Dante (Purg. xxi. 58 £f.) : — The Mountain, it says, Trembles when any spirit feels itself So purified, that it may rise, or move For rising ; and such loud acclaim ensues. ***** And I, who in this punishment had lain Five hundred years and more, but now have felt Free wish for happier clime. Therefore thou felt'st The mountain tremble ; and the spirits devout Heard'st, over all its limits, utter praise To the Liege Lord, whom I entreat their joy To hasten.^ The earthquake and sound of shouting which attended the passage of the Soul of Statins to a higher terrace are com- pared with the shaking of Delos when Latona "couched to bring forth the twin-born Eyes of Heaven," and with " the song first heard in Bethlehem's field." An earthquake and a great sound — of thunder or shouting — are thus associated both by Plato and by Dante with the new birth. The ascent of Souls from terrace to terrace of the Mount of Purgatory is a series of spiritual new births, and answers in Dante to the series of re-incarnations in Plato's mythological representa- tion of the doctrine of κάθαρσις. That the Orphic mythology of the two fountains of Lethe and Mnemosyne in the world of the departed — vouched for ^ Purg. xxi. 58 fF., Gary's Translation. 160 THE MYTHS OF PLATO by the gold tablet — originated in ritual practised by those who consulted oracles of the dead, is rendered probable by a passage in Pausanias ix. 39 (which Dante cannot be supposed to have known), in which the method of consulting Tro- phonius at Lebadeia is described. The priests of Trophonius, before they take the applicant to the μαντβΐον, lead him to certain fountains, Lethe and Mnemosyne, which are very close to each other — at Be Ιηηύτατά eiaiv άΧΚηλων. First, he must drink of Lethe that he may forget all that he thought of before; then he must drink of Mnemosyne that he may have power given him to remember what he sees when he goes down into the Cave of Trophonius. There is evidently a connection between the mythology of the Descent into Hades and the practice of consulting oracles of the dead like that of Trophonius. It is to consult his father Anchises that Aeneas goes down into Avernus ; and even the inmates of Dante's Inferno (for instance, Farinata, Inf. x.) have prophetic power. To summarise the results so far reached : — Dante was true to mythological data at his disposal in placing Lethe in, or near, Elysium or the Earthly Paradise, and making it a stream, not subterranean, but on the surface of the Earth ; but there is no evidence to show that he had any knowledge of the Orphic mythology of the twin-streams as we have it in the Petelia inscription. ISior can we suppose that he knew of Pausanias' (ix. 39) mention of the streams of Lethe and Mnemosyne at the entrance of the Cave of Trophonius.^ The safest course is to allow that Dante, taking the general idea of streams encircling the Earthly Paradise from Genesis, and the idea of Lethe as one of these streams from Aen. vi., may have hit, quite independently of mythological tradition, on the very natural idea of a stream of Memory to contrast with the stream of Oblivion, although his description of the attributes of Eunoe as stream of Memory certainly resembles Platonic and Neo-Platonic passages in which the process of κάθαρσις is identified with that of άνάμνησις, 1 It is possible that he may have seen Pliny, JT. N". xxxi. 15. For Dante's acquaintance with Pliny, see Toynbee's Dante Dictionary, art. " Plinius," and his Index of Authors quoted by Benvenuto da Imola in his Commentary on the D. C, published as Annual Report of the Dante Society (Cambridge, Mass.), 1900, art. "Plinius." THE MYTH OF EK 161 With regard to the name Ευηοέ (not a name obviously appropriate to the stream of Memory) I have a suggestion to make, which, if it goes in the right direction at all, perhaps does not go very far. I offer it, however, for what it may be worth, as a contribution to a difi&cult subject. My suggestion is that Dante's use of the name Εηηοέ may have some connection with the idea of refrigerium, which apparently found its way into Christian literature ^ from the early Chris- tian epitaphs which reproduce the ψνχρον νΒωρ of the pagan epitaphs. Thus, we have such pagan epitaphs as the follow- ing published by Kaibel, and referred to by Dieterich in his Nekyia and Eohde in his Psyche : ψυχρον νΒωρ 8οίη σοι άναξ βνβρων Άέδωι/εύ? (Kaibel, /. G., 1842) — βνψνχ^εί καΐ Βοίη σοι 6 "Οσιρις το ψνχ^ρον νΒωρ (Kaibel, /. G., 1488) — D.M. IVLIA POLITICE DOESE OSIRIS TO PSYCRON HYDOR (inscription found in Via Nomentana, Rome ; Kaibel, /. G., 1705; cf. Dieterich, JVek p. 95); and such Christian epitaphs (quoted by Dieterich, JVek. p. 95, and Rohde, Psyche, ii. 391) as i7i refrigerio et pace anima tua — Deus te refrigeret — spiritum tuum Dominus refrigeret. I suggest, then, that the name Eunoe — evvota, henevolentia — was chosen by Dante, or rather by an unknown authority from whom he borrowed it, to indicate that a boon was graciously bestowed by God through the water of this stream — the boon of refrigerium — ψνχρον νΒωρ Βοίη σοι άναξ βνέρων ΆϊΒωνενς — Dominus te refrigeret. Dante's Εηηοέ would thus mean the Stream of the Loving-kindness and Grace of God. Considering the probable descent of the Christian re- frigerium (the idea of which makes itself felt in the lines with which the Purgatorio ends), through epitaphs, from the Orphic ψνχρον νΒωρ, I am inclined to think that it is to Christian epitaphs that we ought to go for the more immediate source of Dante's Eunoe. If the word were found there in connection with refrigerium, we might infer with some confidence that it had occurred in Orphic epitaphs.^ 1 Tertullian, Apologeticus, xxxix., speaking of the Lord's Supper, says, "inopes- quosque refrigerio isto juvamus" ; and Dante, Par. xiv. 27, has **Lo refrigerio deir eterna ploia." In the "Query" in the Classical Review, Feb. 1903, p. 58, referred to on p. 154 supra, Miss Harrison coi^'ectured Έ{ύν]οία$ in Kaibel, I. G.S.I. 642. In a note on "The Source of Dante's Εηηοέ" in the Classical Review, March 1903, Μ 162 THE MYTHS OF PLATO III Dante's Mount of Purgatory has characteristics belonging to the Islands of the Blessed, or mansions eVl 7779, to the Plain of Lethe, and to Tartarus, as these places are described in Plato's Myths. The Earthly Paradise on the aethereal top of the Mount of Purgatory answers to the mansions eVl γης — " on the True Surface of the Earth." Lethe, as well as Eunoe, is on the top of the Mount of Purgatory; and the disciplinary punishment undergone by those not incorrigibly wicked, in Plato's Tartarus, answers in part to the penance undergone on the various cornices or terraces of Dante's Purgatory. Looking at the composition of the Myth of Er as a whole, we may say that in this Myth we have the sketch of a Divina Commedia, complete with its three parts — Inferno, Purgatorio, and Paradiso. The Inferno is painted with a few touches, where the torments of Ardiaeus are described. The Purgatorio is given in more detail, not only in the reference to what those who come out of Tartarus have suffered during their imprisonment, but also in the account of the march of these Souls to the throne of Necessity, and their choosing of new Lives, and further journey on to the water of Lethe : pp. 117, 118, in reply to Miss Harrison's "Query," I wrote: — "Until Miss Harrison's E[w]otas has been proved to belong to the original text of Kaibel, I.G.S.I. 642, and the reference in that inscription has been shown to belong certainly, to the Orphic Κρήνη Μνημοσύνης, it will be enough to admit that an Orphic writer in the third century B.C. might very naturally speak of the φύλακ€ί of the ΛΥβΙΙ of Memory as edvoL towards those μύσται on whom they bestowed rb ψνχρον ϋδωρ, or refrigerium, and that he might very naturally describe that well itself as Evvoias κρήνη — the Fountain of Loving-kindness." Since writing the above I have been reminded by a reference in Dieterich's Mne Mithrasliturgie (1903), p. 74, n. 1, that Plutarch, in his Is. et Osir. eh. 47, says that the Persian god Ormuzd made six gods, the first of whom is the God of eCvoLa — ό μ€ν Ώρομά^η$ έκ του καθαρωτάτου φάους ό δ' Άρειμάνως έκ του ζόφου Ύ^-γονώς τΓολεμοΰσίν άλλήλοις• καΐ ό μέν €ξ θεούς έττοίησβ, τόν μέν πρώτον ζύνοία$ τόν δέ δεύτερον αληθείας, τόν δέ τρίτον ευνομίας, των δέ λοίττών τόν μέν σοφίας, τόν δέ πλούτου, τόν δέ των έπΙ τοις καλοΐς ηδέων δημωυρΎόν ό δέ τούτους ώσπερ άντι,τέχνους 'ίσους τόν αριθμόν. Here, Ι take it, τόν μέν πρώτον is the first counted from Ormuzd himself ; so that the God of εϋνοια would be the last reached by the ascending Soul of the initiated person on its way up the Mithraic κλΐμαξ έπτάπυλος. It is a strange coincidence that the last stage in Dante's κλΐμαξ of purification — the Mount of Purgatory — should also be Εϋνοια, having passed which his μύστης is Puro e disposto a salire alle stelle. Miss Harrison {Prolegomena, p. 584) refers to tomb-inscriptions with εύνοιας καΐ μνήμης χάριν. This only means, I take it, "in affectionate remembrance," and can hardly give the clue to the problem of Dante's Eunoe = Mnemosyne. THE MYTH OF EK 163 these experiences, leading up, as they do, to yeveai^ in the flesh, are all parts of a purgatorial discipline. Lastly, we have the Paradiso of the Myth of Er in the vision of the orrery — the little model of the great Universe, by means of which the astronomical theory of Plato's age — essentially the same as that of Dante's age — is illustrated and presented in a form which appeals to poetical fancy, and yet — so Plato thought — is scientifically correct. This ancient astronomy, first poetised by Plato, has indeed played a notable part in the history of poetry. Dante's Paradiso is dominated by it — renders it into poetry, and yet leaves it "scientific"; and Milton, although he was acquainted with the Copernican system, adheres, in Paradise Lost, to the old astronomy with its concentric spheres revolving round the Earth.^ But when we say that Dante's Paradiso — the noblest of all Eschatological Myths — is dominated by the ancient astronomy, — renders its theory of the heavens into poetry and still leaves it " scientific," — we must not forget that the theory came down to Dante already touched into poetry by an influence not commonly considered poetical, to which, however, Dante's rendering owes much of its poetical effect. I refer to the influence of Aristotle. He put poetry into astronomy when he explained the revolutions of the spheres as actuated by the attraction of God — the Best Beloved, Who draws all things unto Himself with strong desire (see Met. A 7 ; de Coelo, ii. 2 ; and Mr. A. J. Butler's note, The Paradise of Dante, p. 8). It is Aristotle who dictates the first line of the Paradiso — La gloria di Colui che tutto muove ; ^ and it is with Aristotle's doctrine — or poetry — that the Paradiso ends — Air alta fantasia qui manco possa : Ma gia volgeva il mio disiro e Ί velle, Si come ruota che igualmente e mossa, L' Amor clae muove il Sole e Γ altre stelle.^ 1 See Masson's Milton's Poetical Works, vol. i. pp. 89 flf. 2 His glory by whose might all things are moved. Caby. ^ Here vigour failed the towering fantasy ; But yet the will rolled onward, like a wheel In even motion, by the Love impelled That moves tlfc Sun in Heaven and all the Stars. Cary. 164 THE MYTHS OF PLATO The Aristotelian doctrine — or poetry ^ — of these lines is set forth fully in the Convivio, ii. 44 : There are nine moving heavens, and the order of their position is as follows : The first that is reckoned is that of the Moon ; the second, that in which Mercury is; the third, Venus ; the fourth, the Sun ; the fifth. Mars ; the sixth, Jupiter ; the seventh, Saturn ; the eighth is that of the Stars ; the ninth is that which can only be perceived by the movement above mentioned, which is called the crystalline or diaphanous, or wholly transparent. But outside of these. Catholics suppose the Empyrean Heaven, which is as much as to say the Heaven of Flame, or the luminous ; and they suppose this to be immovable, since it has, in itself, in respect of every part, that which its matter requires. And this is the reason why the primum mobile has most rapid movement : because by reason of the fervent longing which every part of it has to be joined to every part of that most divine motionless Heaven, it revolves within that with so great desire that its velocity is, as it were, incomprehensible. And this motionless and peaceful Heaven is the place of that Supreme Deity which alone fully beholds itself. This is the place of the blessed spirits, according as Holy Church, which cannot lie, will have it ; and this Aristotle, to whoso under- stands him aright, seems to mean, in the first book de Coelo} This is μνθος — as truly μύθος as the Spindle of Necessity in the Vision of Er ; which Dante sufficiently recognises in Conv. ii. 3, where he says that although, as regards the truth of these things, little can be known, yet that little which human reason can know has more delectation than all the certainties of sense. To pass now to another point : — The νώτον, or continuous surface formed by the edges or lips of the concentric whorls of the orrery (Bep. 616 e), has been identified by some with the νωτον του ουρανοί) of Fhaedrus, 247 C — the outside of the outermost sphere of the sensible Cosmos, on which the Chariot-Souls emerge in sight of the Super-sensible Forms. Hence, it is inferred, the place where the Souls of the Myth of Er are assembled before the throne of Necessity, and where they choose new Lives before they journey on to the Plain of 1 Against the view here advanced — that Aristotle's doctrine of God is " poetry " — the reader may consult an interesting article on "The Conception oi ένέρτ^ΐΐα ακινησία^," \)j Mr. F. C. S. Schiller, in Mivd, Oct. 1900, republished in revised and expanded form, under the title of Activity and Substance, as Essay xii. in Mr. Schiller's Humanism (1903). 2 A. J. Butler's Translation of Scartazzini's Companion to Dante, p. 420. THE MYTH OF ER 165 Lethe, is outside the sensible Cosmos.^ I do not think that this inference is certain, or even probable. It is a model of the Cosmos, I think — and an old-fashioned model, with rings instead of spheres ^ — not the outside of the actual Cosmos, that the Pilgrim Souls of the Bepuhlic see. In the vision of this model, or orrery, we have what is really a vision within the larger vision of the whole Myth of Er. The Pilgrim Souls are still somewhere in the sensible Cosmos — indeed, they are on the surface of the Earth somewhere. In this place, on the surface of the Earth, Necessity and the three Fates, and the rest of the pageant, appear to them, iv βΙΒωλον ecBeo, as the Saints appear to Dante in the lower Spheres where they really are not.^ Standing in this place, on the surface of the Earth — it may be on» the antipodal surface of the Earth — the Pilgrim Souls see on the knees of Necessity the model of the Cosmos, with the lips of its rings making a continuous surface. It is true that in the Phaedrus Souls about to be born actually visit the νωτον ουρανού, and see thence the νττερονράνιος τότΓος, but in the Phaedrus these Souls have wings and can fly to the flammantia moenia mundi, whereas, in the Myth of Er the Souls plod on foot. This seems to me to make a great difference. In interpreting the details of a Platonic Myth we do well always to take account of the poet-philosopher's power of exact visualisation, in respect of which he can be compared only with Dante. I think, therefore, that in the Myth of ^ See R. L. Nettleship's Philosophical Lectures and Remains, ii. 361, n. 3. 2 Rep. 616 D : see Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, p. 202, and §78 generally. Σφόνδυλοι, Prof. Burnet points out, are not spheres, but rings, what Parmenides (adopting a Pythagorean idea) calls στέψαναι. According to the a0oi'5uXoi-scheme, the Earth and the Heavens are not spherical, but annular. As the astronomy accepted by Plato undoubtedly made the Earth spherical, in a spherical Cosmos (see ZeWer's Plato, Eng. Transl. p. 379), we must conclude that the system of rings or σφόνδύλοι, in Rep. 616, is that of a model only — either an old-fashioned Pythagorean one, or an up-to-date one, in which, however, only the half of each sphere was represented, so that the internal "works " might be seen. That astronomical models were in use we know from Timaeus, 40 d, where the speaker says that without the aid of a model of the Heavens it would be useless to attempt to describe certain motions ; and cf. Fabricii Bihl. Or. Liber iv. pp. 457 ff., on astronomical models in antiquity. With regard to the breadth of the rims of the σφόνδνλοι, see Mr. Adam's note on 616 E, and Appendix vi. Although the view supported by the πρότερα καΐ αρχαιότερα 'γραφ-ή mentioned by Proclus — that the breadth of the rims of the σφόνδνλοι is proportionate, but not equal, to the diameters of the planets — is plausible, it seems better to take it that the supposed distances of the orbits from each other are signified by the breadth of the rims. 3 Par. iv. 34 ff. Cf. 0dijs9 xi. 600, τόν δέ μ€τ είσενόησα βίην Έρακληείην Ι €Ϊδώ\ον, αύτό$ δέ μ€τ άθανάτοισι θ^οΐσι. i66 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Er the Souls about to be born again do not actually visit the νωτον ουρανού. Be this as it may, the region of the νωτον ουρανού, as described in the Fhaedrus, is either the actual abode, or in close touch with the stars (Tim. 42 b), which are the actual abodes, of the purified ones who have drunk of Mnemosyne, and "always remember" — "philosophers," who have been trans- lated from the " True Surface of the Earth," as we read in the Pliaedo (114 c): ol φιλοσοφία ίκανως καθηράμενοο ανβυ re σωμάτων ζώσι το τταράτταν eh τον eireiTa 'χ^ρονον και eZ? οίκησβί^ €Τί τούτων καΧλίους άφικνουνται «9 οΰτβ ράΒίον 8ηλωσαί οΰτβ 6 'χρόνος Ικανός iv τω τταρόντί. The abode of these purified ones, in or within sight of the super-sensible region, corresponds to the Empyrean or motionless Heaven of Dante, the tenth and outermost Heaven, in which the blessed really dwell, although they appear, iv βΙΒώλου eiBei,, in all the nine moving Spheres to the poet as he ascends.^ I wish to conclude this section of my observations on the Myth of Er with a few words about the view maintained by Mr. Adam in his note on Hep. 617 b, 11 : — *Ανάγκηζ γόνασιν. — Plato means us to imagine Necessity as seated in the centre of the Universe. The notion is probably Pythagorean ; for Parmenides, who attaches himself to the Pytha- goreans in this part of his system (Zeller,•^ i. p. 572), speaks of a central 'Ανάγκη as the cause of all movement and birth; see Diels, ΌΟΧ. Gr. 335. 12 if. — των δέ σνμμι-γων (sc. στ€φανων) την μζααιτατην άττασαι^ τοκ€α ττάσ-ης κινήσεως καΐ γενεσεω? νττάργΐΐν^ rjvTLva καΙ Βαίμονα κνβερνηην καί KXrj8ov)(^ov επονόμαζα 8ίκην καΙ ανάγκην; and Zeller, I.e. p. 577, η. 3 (Zeller identifies this 'Ανάγκη with the central fire of the Pythagoreans). The same school seem also to have held that 'Ανάγκη surrounds and holds the world together (Diels, I.e. 321), and Zeller thinks it is this external 'Ανάγκη of which Plato here avails himself (I.e. p. 434, n. 3). But it is quite clear that Plato's 'Ανάγκη is in the middle. I agree with Mr. Adam in rejecting Zeller's view that it is the external Άι/αγΛ:?; of which Plato here avails himself, and in thinking that Plato's ^AvajKy is in the middle. But in ^ Par. iv. 28-39. The appearance of a certain Saint in a certain moving Sphere is a sign of his or her position in the graded hierarchy of the Empyrean, or Unmoved Heaven, in which all the Saints have their real abode. A Saint who appears to Dante in the Lunar Sphere, for example, has a lower position in the Empyrean than one who appears in the Sphere of Jupiter. THE MYTH OF EK 167 what middle ? Not in the Pythagorean middle of the Universe, which is not the Earth, but the Central Fire. The throne of "Ανάγκη is certainly placed by Plato either on or within the Earth, which is in the middle of his Universe. Mr. Adam, with, I venture to think, too much regard for ακριβολογία, maintains that it is within, not on the surface of, the Earth. " If the light is ' straight like a pillar,' " he writes (note on 616b, 13), "and stretches 'through all the Heaven and the Earth,* it follows that as the Earth is in the middle of the Universe, the ' middle of the light ' will be at the centre of the Earth. No other interpretation of κατά μέσον το φως is either natural or easy. It would seem, therefore, that at the end of the fourth day after leaving the Meadow the Souls are at the central point both of the Universe and of the Earth, as is maintained by, among others, Schneider and Donaldson ; and this view is also in harmony with some of the most important features of the remaining part of the narrative." My view is that the throne of Necessity is on the surface of the Earth, at that spot where the pillar of light — the axis on which the Cosmos revolves — was seen, by the Pilgrim Souls as they approached, to touch the ground, — seen, with the dccompanying knowledge (so characteristic of dream-experience) that it goes through the Earth and comes out at the antipodal spot. I do not think that we ought to press the phrase κατά μέσον το φώ<ζ, as Mr. Adam does. Apart from the fact that the Pythagorean or Parmenidean central ^Avάyκη was not in the centre of the Earth, the whole scenery of the Myth and its general fidelity to mythological tradition seem to me to be against putting Plato's throne of Necessity, as Mr. Adam does, in the centre of the Earth. The Myth begins by telling us that the Souls came, some of them out of the Earth, some of them down from " Heaven," to the Meadow. The Meadow is certainly on the surface of the Earth. Their journey thence to the throne of Necessity is evidently on the surface of the Earth, — they have the sky above them ; they see the pillar of light in the sky before them for a whole day, the fourth day of their march, as they approach it. There is no suggestion of their going down on that day into Tartarus in order to reach the " middle of the light " at the centre of the Earth. Those of them who came out 5f Tartarus are still out of it, and are 168 THE MYTHS OF PLATO not going back into it. And those who came out of the region described as ουρανός, " Heaven," are still out of that region. Hence, if I am right in identifying the ουρανός of the Hep. with the " True Surface of the Earth " of the Fhaedo Myth, Mr. Adam cannot be right when he says, 616 B, 11 (cf. 614 c, n.), that " Plato in all probability thinks of the Χβψών as somewhere on the True Surface of the Earth described by him in the Myth in the Fhaedo, and it is apparently along this surface that the Souls progress until they come in view of the light." The True Surface of the Earth and Tartarus, accord- ing to my view, were both equally left when the Χβιμών was reached. The Souls are now journeying along the " Third Way," which leads, under the open sky, by the throne of Necessity, and then by the Kiver of Lethe, eh yiveacv. The Kiver of Lethe does not appear in the list of the subterranean or infernal rivers given in the Fhaedo ; ^ the mythological tradition (observed even by Dante, as we have seen) places it under the open sky — probably the sky of the under-world — the antipodal hemisphere of the Earth. And the φερεσθαυ άνω eh την yeveatv άττοντας tuairep αστέρας (621 b), from which Mr. Adam (citing Aen. vi. 748 fP.) infers " that the Souls, just before their re-incarnation, are underground," seems to me, on the contrary, entirely in accordance with the view that, encamped near the Eiver of Lethe, they are on the sur- face of the Earth, under the open sky, up into which they shoot in various directions like meteors, — surely an inappro- priate picture if they were down in a cavern somewhere at the centre of the Earth. The whole movement, in short, of the Myth of Er, from the meeting of the two companies of Souls at the Meadow onwards, is above ground, under the open sky. From afar they see a pillar of light reaching down through the sky to ^ Olympiodorus, Schol. in Phaedonem, connects the list of infernal rivers with Orphic tradition — ol τταραδώόμβνοί τέσσαρβί ποταμοί κατά. την Όρψέως τταράδοσιν rots VTToyeLoii avaXoyovcri δ' στοιχείοΐζ re καΐ κέντροι$ κατά δύο άντίθέσει^. 6 μέν yap JIvpίφ\cyέθωι' τφ irvpl καΐ τ^ άνατόΚχι, ό δέ Κωκντόί τ•η yrj καΐ τί? δύσα, ό δ^ Άχέρων αέρι re καΐ μεσημβρίφ. τούτου$ μ^ν O/)0e()s οντω διέταξαν, avTOs δέ τδν 'UKeavbv τφ ί/δαη καΐ Trj άρκτφ ττροσοικβωΐ. Here the River of Lethe does not appear. Roscher (art. " Lethe ") gives the following mentions of Lethe: Simonides, Upig. 184 (Bergk) — this is the first mention, but the authorship is doubtful ; Aristoph. Banae, 186 ; Plato, Hep. 621 ; Plutarch, Cons, ad Apoll. ch. 15, in quotation from a dramatic writer ; Virg. Aen. vi. 705, 715 ; Lucian, de luctu, §§ 2-9 ; MorL Dial. 13. 6, 23. 2 ; Ovid, Bp. ex Pont. 2, 4, 23. THE MYTH OF EE 169 the Earth ; and, because Plato, the Dreamer of the Myth, recognises this pillar as the axis of the Cosmos — the cause of its necessary revolutions— ^Id Γ when the Souls are come to the foot of the pillar, it is no longer a pillar reaching down through the sky that they see, but Necessity herself sitting on Earth, on her throne, with a model of the Cosmos revolving in her lap. There is another point on which I feel obliged to differ from Mr. Adam. " It is clear," he says (note on Bejp. 616 c), " that the light not only passes through the centre of the Universe, but also, since it holds the heavens together like the undergirders of men-of-war, round the outer surface of the heavenly sphere " — i.e. the ends of the light which passes round the outer surface are brought inside the sphere, and, being joined in the middle, form the pillar. This seems to me to make too much of the man-of-war, or trireme. It is enough to take Plato to say that the, .pillar (which alone is mentioned) holds the Universe together in its particular way, as the ντΓοζώματα, in their particular way, hold the trireme together. And if there is a light passed round the outer surface of the Heaven, as well as one forming its axis, why do the Pilgrim Souls see only the latter ? The Heavens are diaphanous. The Pilgrims ought, if Mr. Adam's view is correct, to see not only the pillar of light rising vertically from the horizon at a certain fixed point towards which they journey, but also another band of light — that which surrounds the outside of the Universe — travelling round with the motion of the sphere of the fixed stars from East to West. IV I shall now conclude what I have to say about the Myth of Er with a few words on the great philosophical question raised in it. I mean the question of How to reconcile Eree Will with the Eeign of Law. Both are affirmed in the Myth. The Pilgrim Souls are conducted to a spot at which they see, with their own eyes, the working of the Universal Law — they stand beside the axis on which the Cosmos revolves, and see clearly that the revolutions " cannot be otherwise." They see that the axis of the Cosmos is the spindle of Άνάτγκη : — and, 170 THE MYTHS OF PLATO behold ! there sits ^Κνώ^κη herself on her throne, and there are the three Fates, with solemn ritual, ordering the succession of events in time according to the law of ^λνάηκτ). Yet, within the very precincts of the court of ''λνάηκτ] in which they stand, the Pilgrim Souls hear the Prophet telling them in the words of Lachesis, that " they are ijm to choose, and will be held responsible for their choice>^ Plato here presents the Idea of Freedom mythically under the form of a prenatal act of choice — the choice, it is to be carefully noted, not of par- ticular things, but of a Whole Life — the prenatal " choice " of that whole complex of circumstances in which particular things are chosen in this earthly life. Each Soul, according to its nature, clothes itself in certain circumstances — comes into, and goes through, this earthly life in circumstances which it has itself chosen — that is, in circumstances which are to be regarded not as forcing it, or dominating it mechanically from without, but as being the environment in which it exhibits its freedom or natural character as a living creatur^/ Among the circumstances of a Life " chosen," a fixed character of the Soul itself, we are told, is not included — ψυγΎ]ς Be τάξιν ουκ ivetvaL {Rep. 618 b), — because the Soul is modified by the Life which it chooses. This means that the Soul, choosing the circumstances, or Life, chooses, or makes itself responsible for, its own character, as afterwards modified, and necessarily modified, by the circumstances, or Life. In other words, a man is responsible here on Earth for actions pro- ceeding from a connate character which is modified here in accordance with the circumstances of a general scheme of life made unalterable by Necessity and the Fates before he was born — αίρβίσθω βίον ω σύνεσται ef ανάγκης {Hep. 617 ε). In presenting Moral Freedom under the Eeign of Natural Law mythically, as Prenatal Choice made irrevocable by ^Avάyκη, Plato lays stress, as he does elsewhere, on the unbroken continuity of the responsible Self evolving its character in a series of life-changes. It is the choice made before the throne of ^Ανά^γκη which dominates the behaviour ^ It was chiefly in order to express this relation between living creature and environment that Leibniz formulated his theory of Pre-established Harmony. We may say of Leibniz's theory what he says himself of Plato's doctrine of άνάμνησις — that it is "myth" — "toute fabuleuse " {Nouveaux Essais, Avant- propos, p. 190 b, ed. Erdmann). THE MYTH OF EE 171 of the Soul in the bodily life on which it is about to enter ; but the choice made before the throne of Ανάγκη depended itself on a disposition formed in a previous life ; the man who chooses the life of a tyrant, and rues his choice as soon as he has made it, but too late, had been virtuous in a previous life, WeL avev φιλοσοφίας — his virtue had been merely " customary," without foundation upon consciously realised principle (Bep. 619 c}^^HPlato thus makes Freedom reside in esse, not in operari.K To be free is to be a continuously existing, self - affirming^ environment -choosing personality, manifesting itself in actions which proceed, according to necessary law, irom itself as placed once for all in the environment which it has chosen — its own natural environ- ment — the environment which is the counterpart of its own character. It is vain to look for freedom of the will in some power of the personality whereby it may interfere with the necessary law according to which charaMer, as modified up to date, manifests itself in certain actionjg; Such a power, such a liberum arhitrium indifferentiae, would be inconsistent with the continuity, and therefore with the freedom and respon- sibility, of the Self. It is, in other words, the freedom of the " noumenal," as distinguished from the " phenomenal " Self, which Plato presents as the " prenatal choice of a Life " — mythically ; which is, indeed, the only way in which such a transcendental idea can be legitimately presented, αίρβίσθω βίον φ σνν^σται εξ ανάγκης* ή δ' άρετη άΒέσττοτον. Α certain Life, with all its fortunes and all its influences on character, when once chosen, is chosen irrevocably.^ But, none the less, it is a life of freedom, for " Virtue is her own mistress." In being conscious of Virtue — that is, of Self as ^ For tlie distinction, see Schopenhauer, Parerga UTid Paralipoinena, ii. § 117 ; Die Welt als Wille u. Vorstellung, vol. ii. pp. 364, 365 ; and Die Grundlage der Moral, § 10. In the last of these passages Schopenhauer (explaining the dis- tinction between the "intelligible" and the "empirical" character, the latter of which is related to the former as operari is to esse — operari sequitur esse) quotes Porphyry (in Stobaeus, Eel. 8. §§ 37-40) : τό ykp 6\ov βούλημα τοωΰτ' eoiKev elvaL του HXarwyos ^χβιν μέν τό αύτεξούσιον ras ψνχά,ζ irplv ets σώματα καΐ βίον$ διαφόρους έμιτΐσβΐν, ets τό ^ τούτον τόν βίον έΧέσθαί fj άλλον. 2 Hobbes' " Sovereign, once chosen, ever afterwards irremovable," is a " founda- tion-myth " ; the social order which constrains individuals to conformity is accounted for "mythically" by a prehistoric act of choice exercised by indi- viduals. They willed themselves into the social order, and may not will them- selves out of it. A " categoricai imperative " is laid upon them to act as social 172 THE MYTHS OF PLATO striving after the good or self-realisation — the Soul is conscious of its own freedom. This consciousness of " freedom," involved in the consciousness of " Virtue," is better evidence for the reality of freedom than the inability of the logical faculty to understand freedom is against its reality. As Butler says, " The notion of necessity is not applicable to practical subjects, i.e. with respect to them is as if it were not true. . . . Though it were admitted that this opinion of necessity were speculatively true, yet with regard to practice it is as if it were false." '^ One other point and I have done with the Myth of Er : The momentary prenatal act of choice which Plato describes in this Myth is the pattern of like acts which have to be performed in a man's natural life. Great decisions have to be made in life, which, once made, are irrevocable, and dominate the man's whole career and conduct afterwards. The chief use of education is to prepare a man for these crises in his life, so that he may decide rightly. The preparation does not consist in a rehearsal, as it were, of the very thing to be done when the crisis comes, — for the nature of the crisis cannot be anticipated, — but in a training of the will and judgment by which they become trustworthy in any difficulty which may be presented to them. The education given to the φύλακβς of Plato's Καλλ/ττολύ? is a training of this kind. Its aim is to cultivate faculties rather than to impart special knowledge. It is a " liberal education " suitable to free men of the governing class, as distinguished from technical instruc- tion by which workmen are fitted for the routine of which they are, so to speak, the slaves. ^ Analogy, i. 6. THE POLITIGUS MYTH Introductory Eemarks We have now done with the three purely Eschatological Myths, and enter on a series of Myths which are mainly Aetiological. We begin with the Myth of the Alternating World-periods in the Politicus. The Cosmos has alternating periods, according as God either goes round with and controls its revolution, or lets go the helm and retires to his watch-tower. When God lets go the helm, the Cosmos, being a ζωον with its own σύμφυτος βτΓίθυμία, and subject, like all creatures, to ^Ιμαρμίνη, begins to revolve in its own direction, which is opposite to God's direction. The change of direction — the least possible change if there is to be change at all — we must ascribe to the change- able nature of the material Cosmos, and not either to God, who is unchangeable, imparting now one motion and then its contrary, or to the agency of another God. When God, then, lets go the helm, the Cosmos begins of itself to revolve back- wards ; and since all events on Earth are produced by the revolution of the Cosmos, the events which happened in one cosmic period are reproduced backwards in the next. Thus the dead of one period rise from their graves in the next as grey -haired men, who gradually become black -haired and beardless, till at last, as infants, they vanish away. This is the account of the fabled <γη^γ€ν€Ϊς. They were men who died and were buried in the cosmic period immediately preceding that of Cronus — the Golden Age of Cronus, when the Earth brought forth food plenteously for all her children, and men and beasts, her common children, talked together, and Βαίμονβς, not mortal men, were kings (cf. Laws, 713). But at last the stock of earthen men ra!i out — το γηϊνον ήΒη τταν άνηΚωτο 173 174 THE MYTHS OF PLATO 761/09 {Pol. 272 d) — and the age of Cronus came to an end: God let go the helm, and the Cosmos changed the direction of its revolution, the change being accompanied by great earthquakes which destroyed all but a few men and animals. Then the Cosmos calmed down, and for a while, though re- volving in its own direction, not in God's, yet remembered God, and fared well ; but afterwards forgot him, and went from bad to worse ; till God, of his goodness, saved struggling men, now no longer earth-born, from destruction by means of the fire of Prometheus and the arts of Athena and Hephaestus. In due time he will close the present period — that of Zeus — by again taking the helm of the Cosmos. Then will be the Kesurrection of the Dead. Such, in brief, is the Myth of the Changing World-periods in the Politicus. Like the Myths already examined, this one deals with God's government of man as a creature at once free to do good and evil, and determined by cosmic iniiuences over which he — and even God the Creator himself, whether from lack or non-use of power hardly matters — have no control. The Myth differs from those which we have examined in not being told by Socrates himself. It is told by an Eleatic Stranger, who says that the younger Socrates, who is present with the elder, will appreciate a μΰθοζ, or story. Similarly, Protagoras prefaces the Myth which he tells (Frot. 320 c) by saying that it will suit Socrates and the others — younger men than himself. The Eleatic Stranger in the Politicus tells his Myth ostensibly in order to bring it home to the company that they have defined " kingship " too absolutely — as if the king were a god, and not a human being. Gods directly appointed by the great God were kings on this Earth in a former period; but in the period in which we now live men are the only kings. Kingship must now be conceived " naturalistically " as a product of human society ; and human society itself, like the whole Cosmos of which it is a part, must be conceived " naturalistically " as following its own intrinsic law without divine guidance ah extra. To enforce a " naturalistic " estimate of kingship is the ostensible object of the Myth ; but it soars high, as we shall see, above the argument which it is ostensibly introduced to serve. THE FOLITICUS MYTH 175 Context The subject of the Politicus is the True Statesman. The hest form of government, if we could get it, would he the rule of one eminently good and wise man, who knew and desired the Chief Good of his People, and possessed the art of securing it for them. His unlimited personal initiative would he far better than the best administration of " laws " made only because he could not be found, and because such rulers as were cbctually available could not be trusted with unlimited initiative. But before we try to determine exactly the nature of the True Statesman — the man whom we should like to make King, if we could find him ; and before we try to define his Art, and distinguish it from all other arts — and we must try to do this, in order that we may get a standard by which to judge the work-a-day rulers, good and bad, vjhose administration of the " laws " we are obliged to accept as substitute for the personal initiative of the True Statesman, — before we try to formulate this standard, let us raise our eyes to an even higher standard : God is the True Ruler of men; and in the Golden Age he ruled men, not through the instrumentality of human rulers, but Gods were his lieutenants on Earth, and lived among men, and were their Kings. It is with this Golden Age, and the great difference between it and the present age, and the cause of the difference, that the Myth told to the elder and the younger Socrates, and to Theodorus the mathematician, by the Stranger from Elea, is concerned. 176 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Politicus, 268E-274E 268 Ε HE. *Αλλά Βη τω μύθω μον ιτάνυ ιτροσβγβ τον νουν, καθάτΓβρ οΐ τταΐΒβς' ττάντως ου ττοΧλα ε/^φευγεί? τταίΒιάς €τη. ΝΕ. 2ί1. Αε70^9 αν. BE. Ήι/ τοίνυν καΧ en βσται των τταΚαι Χβ'χθβντων ΤΓοΧλά Τ6 αΧλα και Βη καΐ το ττβρί την ^Ατρέως Τ6 καΧ ©υβστου ΧβγθβΙσαν epiv φάσμα. άκήκοας <γάρ ττου καϊ άίΓομνημονβνβί^; 6 φασί γενέσθαι τ6τ€. ΝΕ. %Ω>. Ύο ΤΓβρΙ της 'χ^ρυσης άρνος ϊσως σημβΐον φράζεις, 269 BE. ΟύΒαμώς, άλλα το irepl της μβταβοΧης Βνσβώς τε καϊ άνατοΧής ηΧίου καϊ των αλΧων άστρων, ώς άρα odev μεν άνατεΧλεί νυν, εις τούτον τότε τον τόττον εΒύετο, άνετεΧΧε δ' εκ του εναντίου, τότε Βε Βη μαρτυρήσας άρα 6 θεός ^Ατρεΐ μετεβαΧεν αυτό εττϊ το νυν σ'χημα. ΝΕ. 2ί2. Αεγετα^ yap ουν Βη καϊ τούτο. BE. ΚαΙ μην αυ καϊ την ^ε βασιΧείαν, ην ηρζε Ιίρόνος, ΤΓοΧΧών άκηκόαμεν. Β ΝΕ. 2ί2. Πλειστωΐ' μεν ουν. Be. Ύί Βε ; το τους εμττροσθεν φύεσθαυ 'γη^γενεΐς καϊ μη εξ άΧΧηΧων ^εννάσθαι ; ΝΕ. Sil. ΚαΙ τούτο εν των ττάΧαι Χεγθεντων. ΒΕ. Ύαυτα τοίνυν εστί μεν ξύμτταντα εκ ταύτοΰ Ίτάθους, καϊ ττρος τούτοις έτερα μυρία καϊ τούτων ετι θαυμαστότερα, Bta Βε γ^ρόνου ΊτΧήθος τα μεν αυτών άττεσβηκε, τα Βε Βιεστταρμενα εϊρηται χοορϊς έκαστα άιτ C αΚΚηΚων, ο Β εστϊ ττάσι τούτοις αϊτιον το ιτάθος, ούΒεϊς εϊρηκε, νυν Βε Βη Χεκτεον εΙς yap την του βασιΧεως άττόΒειξιν ττρεψει ρηθέν. ΝΕ. ΧΩ. Κ,άΧΧιστ είττες, καϊ λέγε μηΒεν εΧΧείττων. THE POLITICUS MYTH 177 Translation Stranger. Here beginneth my wonderful Tale ! Be as a child, and listen ! for indeed not far art thou gotten from the years of childish things. Socrates} Let us hear it. Stranger. Well, of those things which have been told from old time, there be many which came to pass, and shall yet again come to pass : whereof I count the Sign which appeared when that Strife the Old Story telleth of was between Atreus and Thyestes ; for, methinks, thou hast heard what they say came then to pass, and rememberest it well. Socrates. Is it of the marvel of the Golden Lamb that thou speakest ? Stranger. Not of that, but of the change in the setting and rising of the sun and stars ; for the story goes that in the quarter whence they now rise in that did they then set, rising from the opposite quarter ; but that God, bearing witness for Atreus, changed them into the way which they now keep. Socrates. That story also I know. Stranger. And of the kingship of Cronus, too, have we heard many tell. Socrates. Yea, very many. Stranger. And, moreover, do they not tell of how men at first grew out of the earth, and were not begotten of their kind? Socrates. That also is one of the old stories. Stranger. Well, of all these things one thing is cause ; yea, of innumerable other things also which are more wonder- ful than these things ; but by reason of length of time most are vanished, and of the rest mention is made separately of each, as of that which hath no fellowship with the other things. But of that which is the cause of all these things no man hath spoken. Let it therefore now be told ; for when it hath been set forth, it will help to our proof concerning the King. Socrates. Good ! Go on, and leave out nothing. 1 Socrates the Younger is Ihe interlocutor throughout the whole passage translated. 178 THE MYTHS OF PLATO BE. ^Ακούοί^ αν. το yap ττάν τόδε τοτβ μεν αύτο^ 6 ^€09 ξυμ7ΓoBηyeΐ ττορβυόμβνον καϊ σιτγκυκΧβΐ, τοτβ δ' άνήκεν, όταν αΐ 7Γ6ρίο8ον του ττροσηκοντο^ αυτω μετρον βΙΧηφωσυν ηΒη "χ^ρόνου, το δε ττάΧιν αντόματον eh τάναντια ττβριά- D ^€ται, ζωον ον καϊ φρόνησιν 6ΐληχο<ζ έκ τον συναρμοσαντος αυτό κατ άρχά?. τούτο δε αυτω το άνάτταΧίν levat Bta τόδ* έξ ανά^κη^ βμψυτον yiyovev. ΝΕ. ΣΩ. Δίά το τΓοΐον Βή ; 3Ε. Το κατά ταύτα καϊ ωσαύτως βγειν άεΐ καϊ ταύτον elvaL τοις ττάντων Θειοτάτοις ττροσηκβί μονοις, σώματος δε φύσις ου ταύτης της τάξεως, ον δε ούρανον καϊ κοσμον εττωνομάκαμεν, ττοΧΧών μεν καϊ μακαρίων τταρα του ηεννησαντος μετείΧηψεν, άταρ ουν Βη κεκοινώνηκε ^ε καϊ σώματος. όθεν αυτω μεταβοΧης άμοίρω ηίηνεσθαι Βία Ε τταντος άΒύνατον, κατά Βύναμίν γε μην 6 τι μαΧιστα εν τω αυτω κατά ταύτα μίαν φοράν κινείται' Βώ την άνα- κύκΧησιν εϊΧηχεν, ο τι σμικροτάτην της αυτού κινήσεως τταραΧΧαξιν. αύτο δε εαυτό στρεφειν άεΐ σγεΒον ούΒενΙ Βυνατον ττΧήν τω των κινουμένων αύ ττάντων ή^ουμενω. κινεΐν δε τούτω τοτέ μεν αΧΧως, αύθις δε εναντίως ού θέμις. εκ ττάντων Βη τούτων τον κόσμον μήτε αύτον 'χρη φάναι στρεφειν εαυτόν αεί, μήτ αύ οΧον άεΐ ύττο θεού στρεφεσθαι Βιττας καϊ εναντίας ττεριαηω^άς^ μήτ αύ Βύο 270 τινε θεώ φρονούντε εαυτοΐς εναντία στρεφειν αυτόν, αλλ' οττερ άρτι ερρήθη καϊ μόνον Χοιττόν, τότε μεν ύττ άΧΧης συμττοΒη^εΐσθαι θείας αιτίας, το ζην ττάΧιν εττικτώμενον καϊ Χαμβάνοντα άθανασίαν εττισκευαστήν τταρα του Βημιονρ^ού, τότε δ' όταν άνεθ?/, Βι* εαυτού αύτον ιεναι, κατά καιρόν άφεθεντα τοιούτον, ώστε άνάτταΧιν ττορεύ- εσθαι ττόΧΧάς ττεριοΒων μυριάΒας Βιά το μεηιστον ον καϊ ισορροττώτατον εττΐ σμικροτάτου βαΐνον ττοΒος Ιεναι. THE POLITICUS MYTH 179 Stranger. Hearken ! This Universe, for a certain space of time, God himself doth help to guide and propel in the circular motion thereof; and then, when the cycles of the time appointed unto it have accomplished their measure, he letteth it go. Then doth it begin to go round in the contrary direc- tion, of itself, being a living creature which hath gotten understanding from him who fashioned it in the beginning. This circuit in the contrary direction belongeth of necessity to the nature of the Universe because of this — Socrates. Because of what ? Stranger. Because that to be constant in the same state alway, and to be the same, belongeth only to those things which are the most divine of all ; but the nature of Body is not of this order. Now, that which we call Heaven and Universe hath been made, through him who begat it, partaker of many blessed possessions ; but, mark this well. Body also is of the portion thereof. Wherefore it is not possible that it should be wholly set free from change, albeit, as far as is possible, it revolveth in the same place, with one uniform motion : for this reason, when it changed, it took unto itself circular motion in the contrary direction, which is the smallest possible alteration of the motion which belongeth unto it. Now, to be constant alway in self-motion is, methinks, im- possible save only with him who ruleth all the things which are moved ; and move them now in this direction and again in that he may not. From all this it followeth that we must not say that the Universe either of itself moveth itself alway, or again is alway wholly moved by God to revolve now in one direction and then in the contrary direction ; nor must we say that there be two Gods which, being contrariously minded, do cause it so to revolve ; but we must hold by that which was just now said and alone remaineth, to wit, that at one time it is holpen and guided by the power of God supervening, and hath more life added unto it, and receiveth immortality from the Creator afresh ; and then, at another time, when it is let go, it moveth of it- self, having been so opportunely released that thereafter it journeyeth in the contrary direction throughout ages innumer- able, being so great of bulk, and so evenly balanced, and turn- ing on so fine a point. 180 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Β NE. Xil. Φαίνβταί yovv Brj καΐ μαλα €ΐκ6τω<; €ΐρήσθαι ττάνθ^ οσα ^ί€\ηΧυθα<;. ΞΕ. Χο^ισάμ^νοί Βη ξνννοήσωμβν το ττάθος €κ των νυν \e^eevTWVi ο ττάντων βφαμβν eivai, των θαυμαστών αϊτίον, €στι yap ονν Βη τουτ αυτό. ΝΕ. %η. Το ΐΓοΐον ; HE. Το την τον τταντος φοράν τοτβ μβν εφ' α νυν κυκΚβΐται φύρβσθαί, τοτβ δ* eVt τάναντία. ΝΕ. ta. ηώς Βη ; BE. Ύαύτην την μβταβοΧην ηηζΐσθαι Bel των irepl τον C ούρανον ^ί^νομενων τροττών ττασών elvao μ€^ίστην καΐ τεΧβωτάτην τροττην, ΝΕ. Sn. "Εοικ€ yodv, 3Ε. Μέγιστα? τοίννν καΐ μ€ταβο\ά<; 'χ^ρη νομίζειν yLyveadav τοτ€ τοΐς εντός ήμΐν οίκοϋσι,ν αυτού* ΝΕ. Sil. ΚαΙ τουτ εΙκός. BE. Μ€ταβο\άς Be με^αΚας καΐ ττοΧΚάς καΐ τταντοίας συμφ€ρομ€νας αρ* ουκ ϊσμεν την των ζώων φύσιν οτί χαλε- τώς ανί'χεται ; ΝΕ. til. Πώς Β" ου ; BE. ΦθοραΙ τοίνυν έξ ανάγκης τ6τ€ μβ^ισται ξυμβαί- D νονσι των τε αΧλων ζώων, καΐ Βη καΐ το των άνθρώττων γεϊ/09 oXijov τι ττεριλειττεται. ττερί Be τούτους αΧλα τε Ίταθήματα ττοΧΚά καΐ θαυμαστά καϊ καινά ξυμττίτΓτευ, μΑ^ιστον Be ToBe καϊ ξυνεττομενον Trj τον τταντος aveiXi^ei, τότε όταν ή της νυν καθεστηκυίας εναντία ^ί^νηται τροττή. ΝΕ. tn. Ίο τΓοΐον ; BE. 'Ήζ/ ήΧικίαν €καστον είχε των ζώων, αΰτη ττρώτον μεν εστη ττάντων, καϊ ετταύσατο ττάν όσον ην θνητον εττΐ το ^εραίτερον ΙΒεΙν ττορευόμενον, μεταβαΧΧον δε ττάΧυν εττΐ Ε τουναντίον οίον νεώτερον καϊ άτταΧώτερον εφύετο. καϊ των μεν Ίτρεσβυτερων αί Τ^υκαΙ τριχίες εμεΧαίνοντο, των δ' αΰ ^ενειώντων αΐ τταρειαΐ Χεαινόμεναι ττάΧιν εττΐ την τταρεΧ- θουσαν ώραν εκαστον καθίστασαν, των δε ήβώντων τά σώματα Χεαινόμενα καϊ σμικρότερα καθ^ ήμεραν καϊ νύκτα εκάστην ^ι^νόμενα ττάΧιν εις την του νεο^ενους τταιΒος φύσιν άττηεί, κατά τε την ψυχην καϊ κατά το σώμα άφομοίουμενα' το δ* εντεύθεν ηΒη μαραινόμενα κομιΒτ} το ^άμτταν εξηφανίζετο. τών δ* αυ βιαίως τεΧευτώντων εν THE POLITICUS MYTH 181 Socrates. All this, methinks, hath great likelihood. Stranger. Let us then reason with ourselves, and compre- hend from this that which, coming to pass, is, as we said, the cause of all these wonders. Well, it is this. Socrates. What ? Stranger. The circular motion of the Universe going as it now goeth, and then at another time going in the contrary direction. Socrates. How ? Stranger. This alteration we must needs deem to be of all the changes which are accomplished in the Heaven the change which is greatest and most complete. Socrates. So it would seem. Stranger. And we must conclude that by reason of it the greatest changes are then accomplished for us who dwell within this Universe. Socrates. That also is likely. Stranger. Now, when changes many and great and of all sorts come to pass, is it not true that the nature of living creatures hardly endureth them ? Socrates. Yea, 'tis true. Stranger. So it is then, of necessity, that beasts do perish most, and of mankind only a little remnant is left ; and unto these men do many things strange and new happen, but the strangest is that which attendeth the rolling back of the Universe when the motion contrary to this which is now established cometh to be. Socrates. What is that ? Stranger. Then cometh it to pass that the age of every creature, according as his time of life is, first standeth still, and mortals are all stayed in that course which maketh them look older and older : but presently they begin to go in the contrary direction — that is to say, they grow younger and more tender ; and the hoary locks of the old man become black, and the cheeks of the bearded man become smooth, and he is restored to the bygone springtime of his life ; and the lad becometh smooth again, and smaller day after day and night after night, till he cometh back, soul and body, unto the nature and likeness of^ a new-born child ; and thereafter he ever dwindleth away, and at the last utterly vanisheth. Like- 182 THE MYTHS OF PLATO τω Tore 'χρόνω το τον νεκρού σώμα ταύτα ταύτα ττάσ'χον 271 τταθηματα Βια τάχ^ονς άΒηΧον iv oXtyaLf; ήμύραις Βιεφθβί- ρ€ΤΟ. ΝΕ. Χω. Τέν€σις Be Βη τίς τοτ ήν, ώ ξένε, ζώων ; κα\ τίνα τρότΓον ef άΧληΧων iyevvcovTO ; HE. ΑήΧον, ώ Χώκρατ€<;, οτι το μβν εξ άΧΚηΧων ουκ ην iv TTJ τοτ€ φύσει 'γεννώμενον, το Βε ^η'γενες εΙναί ττοτε yivo^ Χεγθεν^ τοΰτ ην το κατ εκείνον τον γ^ρόνον εκ yrj<; ττάΧιν άναστρεφομενον, άττεμνημονεύετο Βε νττο των ημέτερων Ίτρο^όνων των ττρώτων, οΐ τεΧεντώστ) μεν Trj ττροτερα Β ττερίφορα τον εξής 'χ^ρονον ε^ειτόνουν^ τήσΒε Βε κατ αρ'χα<ζ εφύοντο' τούτων yap ούτοι κηρυκε<; lykvovd^ ημίν των Xoyωv, ΟΪ νυν ύττο ττοΧΧών ούκ ορθώς άτηστούνται. το yap εντεύθεν, οΐμαι, 'χ^ρη ξνννοεΐν, εγόμενον ^ yap εστί τω τους ττρεσβντας εττΐ την τον τταιΒος Ιεναι φύσιν, εκ τών τετεΧεντη κοτών αν, κειμένων δ' εν yrj, ττάΧιν εκεί ξννιστα- μενονς και άναβιωσκομενονς εττεσθαι τη τροττη σννανακν- κΧονμένονς ^ εις τάναντία της yεvεσεως, και yηyεvεlς Βη C κατά τούτον τον Xoyov εξ άvάyκης φνομενονς όντως ε'χειν τοννομα και τον Xoyov, οσονς μη θεός αυτών εις άΧΧην μοΐραν εκόμισεν. ΝΕ. Χίΐ. }ζ.ομιΒη μεν ονν τοντό yε εττεται τοις εμττροσθεν. άλλα Βη τον βίον ον εττι της Υ,ρόνον φης είναι Βννάμεως, ττότερον εν εκείναις ήν ταΐς τροτταΐς ή εν ταΐσΒε ; την μεν yap τών άστρων τε και ήΧίον μεταβοΧην ΒήΧον ώς εν εκατεραις ξνμττίτττει ταΐς τροτταΐς yίyvεσθaι, βΕ. Καλώ? τω λόγω ξνμτταρηκοΧούθηκας, ο δ' ήρον D Ίτερι τον τταντα αυτόματα yίyvεσθaι τοις άνθρώττοις, ήκιστα τής ννν εστί καθεστηκνίας φοράς, αλλ' ήν καΐ τοντο της εμττροσθεν, τότε yap αυτής ττρώτον τής κνκΧήσεως ήρχεν ετΓΐμεΧονμενος οΧης 6 θεός* ώς ννν κατά τόττονς, ταύτον τοντο ντΓΟ θεών άρ'χόντων ττάντη τα τον κόσμον μέρη ΒιειΧημμένα. και Βη και τα ζώα κατά yέvη και ατ^έΧας οιον νομής θείοι ΒιειΧήφεσαν Βαίμονες, αυτάρκης εΙς τταντα Ε έκαστος έκάστοις ων οις αύτος ενεμεν, ώστε οντ aypiov ήν ούΒεν ούτε άΧΧήΧων εΒωΒαί, ττόΧεμός τε ούκ ενήν ονΒε στασις το τταράτταν αΧΧα θ\ οσα τής τοιαύτης εστί κατακοσμησεως έττομενα, μνρι αν εϊη Xέyειv^ το δ' ονν τών ^ €ν6μ€νον. 2 συνανακνκ\ονμένη$. THE POLITICUS MYTH 183 wise the corpses of them that have died by violence at this time go through the same changes quickly, and in a few days are dissolved and gone clean out of sight. Socrates. But how were creatures then brought forth, and after what manner were they begotten of their kind ? Stranger. It is manifest, Socrates, that none was then naturally begotten of his kind, but that the earth-born kind they tell of was that which came up again from the earth in those days, whereof our first forefathers had remembrance who lived in the time next after the end of the former Period, being born at the beginning of this present one. From their mouth hath word concerning these things come down unto us : which of many is not believed ; but herein they err ; for consider what foUoweth next : — After the old men who go back to childhood, there follow in their turn the men who are already dead and lying in their graves ; these begin therein to be compacted anew out of their elements, and when his time cometh unto each of them in the cycle of generation whose motion is contrary to the former motion, he riseth from the dead. Thus were men, of necessity, earth-born in those days, and this name of earth-born which we have received is the true name of them all, save of those whom God translated to some other portion. Socrates. Yea, indeed, this foUoweth from that which went before. But tell me — the life thou sayest men led when Cronus reigned, was it in that Period or in this ? For 'tis plain that the change whereof thou speakest in the course of the stars and the sun falleth to happen in each. Stranger. Well hast thou followed the argument ; and thy question is to be answered thus: — That the age when all things came forth spontaneous for the use of man con- grueth not with this present motion, but with that which was before ; for then did God control with his providence the whole revolution, and all the parts of the Universe every- where were divided amongst gods appointed to rule over them, as now gods rule over certain places ; and, moreover, living creatures, according to their kinds, were assigned unto angels, as flocks unto divine shepherds, each angel being wholly sufii- cient in all things for his own flock, so that there was then no savagery, no devouring of one another, no war or sedition 184 THE MYTHS OF PLATO ανθρώπων Xe-^Oev αυτομάτου irepL βίου hia το τοωνΒβ €Ϊρηταί. Θ€ο<ζ eve^ev αύτού'ξ αύτ6<ζ βτηστατών, καθάττερ νυν άνθρωτΓοι, ζωον ον βτερον θεωτερον, άΧλα <γ€νη φαυΧότβρα αυτών νομεύουσι,. νβμοντος Se εκείνου ττολιτεΐαί τε ουκ ήσαν 272 ού8ε κτήσεις γυναικών καϊ τταίΒων εκ 'γης yap άνεβιώσκοντο ττάντες, ούΒεν μεμνημενοί των ττρόσθεν άλλα τα μεν τοιαύτα άττην ττάντα, καρττούς Βε άφθονους ^Ιχ^ον άττο τε ΒενΒρων καϊ ττοΧΚής ΰΧης άΧΧης, ούχ ύττο ^εωρ^ίας φυομενους, αλλ' αυτόματης άναΒιΒούσης της ^ης* γυμνοί Βε καϊ άστρωτοι θυραυΧοΰντες τα ττοΧΧά ενεμοντο' το yap των ωρών αύτοΐς άΧυττον εκεκρατο, μαΧακάς Βε εύνάς εΐ'χον αναφυόμενης εκ yης ττόας άφθονου. τον Βη βίον, ώ Β Χώκρατες, άκούεις μεν τον τών εττϊ Κρόνου' τόνΒε Β\ ον X6yoς εττϊ Αιος είναι, τον νυνί, τταρών αύτος ησθησαι. κρΐναι Β αύτοΐν τον εύΒαιμονέστερον άρ* αν Βύναιό τε καϊ εθεΧησειας ; ΝΕ. 2Ω. ΟύΒαμώς. 3Ε. ΈούΧει Βήτα εyώ σοι τρόττον τινά Βιακρίνω ; ΝΕ. Χω. Τίάνυ μεν ουν, οΈα. Et μεν τοίνυν οι τρόφιμοι του Κρόνου, τταρούσης αύτοΐς ούτω ττοΧΧής σχ^οΧής καϊ Βυνάμεως ττρός το μη μόνον άνθρώτΓοις άΧΧά καϊ θηρίοις Βιά Xόyωv Βύνασθαι C ξυyyίyvεσθaι, κατεγ^ρώντο τούτοις ξύμιτασιν εττϊ φιΧοσοφίαν, μετά τε θηρίων καϊ μετ αΚΧηΧων όμιΧοΰντες, καϊ ττυνθα- νομενοι τταρά ττάσης φύσεως εϊ τινά τις ιΒίαν Βύναμιν εγουσα γσθετό τι Βιάφορον τών άΧΧων εις συvayυpμbv φρονησεως, εΰκριτον, οτι τών νυν οι τότε μυρίω ττρος εύΒαιμονίαν Βιεφερον. εΐ Βε εμττιττΧάμενοι σίτων άΒην καϊ στοτών BιεXεyovτo ττρος άΧΧηΧους καϊ τα θηρία μύθους, οϊα D δ^ καϊ τα νυν ττερϊ αυτών Xεyovτaι, καϊ τούτο, ώς y€ κατά την εμην Βόξαν άττοφηνασθαι, καϊ μάΧ' εΰκριτον, όμως δ' ούν ταύτα μεν άφώμεν, εως αν ήμΐν μηνυτής τις THE POLITICUS MYTH 185 at all : nay, time would fail to tell of all the consequences of that dispensation. Now, therefore, hearken, and I will declare the truth that is in the old Tale of the time when all things came forth spontaneous. God himself was then the Overseer and Shep- herd of men, even as now man, being as a god amongst the creatures which are beneath him, is the shepherd of their tribes. When God was our Shepherd there was no civil government, and men had not wives and children, but all came up into life again from the Earth, without remembrance of aught before. Instead of these things they had in abundance, from trees and other plants, fruits which the Earth without husbandry brought forth spontaneous. For the most part they lived without raiment and without couches, in the open air ; for the seasons were tempered to do them no hurt ; and soft beds had they in the grass which sprang abundantly from the Earth. Now have I told thee, Socrates, of the life which was when Cronus reigned ; as for the life which now is, which they say is under the rule of Zeus, thou art here thyself and knowest what it is. Canst thou, and wilt thou, determine which of these two lives is the happier ? Socrates, I cannot. Stranger. Shall I then determine this for thee after some sort? Socrates. Prithee do. Stranger. Well then, if the nurslings of Cronus, having so great leisure and faculty of joining in discourse not only with men but with beasts, made use of their opportunity all for the getting of wisdom, conversing with beasts and one with another, and inquiring everywhere of Nature if haply any part thereof had some peculiar faculty, and perceived, better than another part, aught which might be of advantage for the ingathering of true knowledge, — if this, I say, was their manner of life, 'twould be no hard matter to determine our question : they were a thousand times happier than we are. And even if, after they had eaten and drunken their fill, they passed the time telling tales one to another and to the beasts — such tales as even to this day are told of them, — 'twould still, I declare, be easy to determine our question ; nevertheless, let us put 186 THE MYTHS OF PLATO ικανός φαντ}, ττοτβρως ol τότβ τας €7ηθνμία<ί βΐχ^ον irepL re €'7ηστημων καί της των \6ηων γ^ρείας' ου Β βνβκα τον μνθον rjyeipa^ev, τούτο \6κτ€ον, Χνα το μβτά τούτο eh το ττρόσθβν ΤΓβραίνωμβν. Έττε^δ^ yap ττάντων τούτων χ^ρόνος €Τ€\€ώθη καϊ μ€ταβο\ην eBev yiyveadat καΐ Βη καϊ το Ε ηήϊνον ήΒη ττάν άνηΚωτο 'γένος, ττάσας εκάστης της "^νχ^ης τας γ€ν€σ€ί9 άττοΒεΒωκυίας, οσα ην εκάστη ττροστα'χθεν, τοσαΰτα βίς yrjv σττίρματα ττεσούσης, τ6τ€ Βη τον τταντος 6 μεν κυβερνήτης, οίον ττηΒαΧίων οϊακος άφεμενος, εΙς την αυτόν ττερίωττην άττεστη, τον Βε Βη κόσμον ττάΧιν άνε- στρεφεν ειμαρμένη τε καϊ ξνμφντος εττιθυμία» ττάντες ουν οι κατά τους τόττους συνάρ'χοντες τω μεριστώ Βαίμονι θεοί, ^νόντες ήΒη το ^ιηνόμενον, άφίεσαν αυ τα μέρη του κόσμου 273 της αύτων ετημεΧείας. 6 Βε μεταστρεφό μένος καϊ ζυμ- βάΧλων, άργτις τε καϊ τεΧευτής εναντίαν ορμήν ορμηθείς, σεισμον ττοΧύν εν εαυτω ττοοών, άΧΧην αυ φθοραν ζώων παντοίων άττειρ^άσατο. μετά Βε ταύτα ττροεΧθόντος ικανού γ^ρονου, θορύβων τε καϊ ταρα'χης ήΒη τταυόμενος καϊ των σεισμών, ^αΧήνης εττίΧαβόμενος εϊς τε τον εΐωθοτα Βρόμον τον εαυτού κατακοσμού μένος ηει, εττιμεΧειαν καϊ κράτος Β έχων αύτος των εν αντω τε καϊ εαντού, την τού Βημίονρ'γού καϊ Ίτατρος άττομνημονεύων ΒίΒαγτιν εΙς Βύναμιν. κατ άρχας μεν ονν άκριβεστερον άττετεΧει, τεΧεντών Βε άμβΧύ- τερον. τούτων Βε αντω το σωματοειΒες της συ^κράσεως αϊτιον, το της ττάΧαι ττοτε φύσεως ξύντροφον, οτι ττοΧΧής ην μετεχον αταξίας ττρϊν εις τον νύν κόσμον άφικεσθαι. τάρα μεν yap τού σννθεντος ττάντα καΧα κέκτηται' ηταρα C Βε της εμττροσθεν εξεως, οσα χαΧεττα καϊ άΒι,κα εν ονρανω yίyvετaL, ταύτα εξ εκείνης αντός τε εγει καϊ τοις ζώοις εva7Γερyάζετaι, μετά μεν ονν τού κνβερνήτον τα ζώα τρεφων εν αντω σμικρά μεν φΧαύρα, μεyάXa Βε ενετικτεν άyaθά' χωριζόμενος Βε εκείνον τον εyyύτaτa χρόνον άεϊ THE POLITIC US MYTH 187 it away, until some one shall appear who is able to show us credibly which way these ancients were inclined in regard of knowledge and discourse: meanwhile let us speak of that for the sake whereof this Tale was started, that the next part of our argument may go forward. When the time of all these men was fulfilled, and the change must needs come, and of the generation of them that arose out of the Earth there was none left, and every Soul had rendered her tale of births, according to the number of times appointed for her to fall and be sown upon the Earth, then did the Governor of the Universe let go, as it were, the tiller, and depart into his own" watch-tower, and Fate and inborn Impulse began to cause the Universe to revolve backwards again. Straightway all the gods which, in their several places, bore rule together with the Great God, when they knew what was done, likewise left their provinces without oversight. Then was the Universe shaken as with a great earthquake through his depths by reason of the concussion of the reversed revolution and the strife betwixt the two con- trary motions whereof the one was ending and the other beginning; whereby was wrought a fresh destruction of living creatures of every kind. Thereafter, when the due time was accomplished, the Universe at last ceased from tumults and confusion and earthquakes, and coming into a calm, and being set in order for the course wherein it useth to go, therein went, itself having superintendency and dominion over itself and all that in it is, calling to mind alway, as it was able, the teaching of the Maker and Father of all. At first the things which it brought forth were more perfectly wrought, but at last more roughly : the cause whereof was the corporeal part which was mixed in the original nature of things, the which was full of confusion before that it came unto the present order. From Him who composed it the Universe hath all things fair and good ; but from the former state thereof come all the things difiBicult and unrighteous which in itself it hath, and bringeth to pass in the creatures which it fashioneth. Therefore when it was with the Governor, the evil cj^eatures it brought forth were few, and the good were in abundance ; but when it was separated 188 THE MiTHS OF PLATO της άφεσβως κάΧΚιστα ττάντα δίογβί, ττροΐόντος Be τον γρόνου καί Χηθης ε^^^ί'^νομ.ίνης iv αύτω μαΧΚον καϊ Βυνα- D aT€V6i το τη<ζ τταΧαιας άναρμοστίας ττάθος, τέλευτώντος δε εξανθζΐ του χρόνου καϊ σμικρά μβν τά^αθά, ττοΧΧην Be την των εναντίων κρασιν iire^Kepavvv μένος iirl Βιαφθοράς κίνΒννον αύτοΰ τε άφίκνεΐται καϊ των iv αντω. Βιο Βη καϊ τότ ήΒη θεός 6 κοσμησας αυτόν, καθορων εν άττορίαις οντά, κηΒομενος Ινα μη 'χειμασθεϊς υττο ταραγΎΐς ΒιαΧυθεΙς εΙς τον της άνομοωτητος αττειρον οντά τόττον Βύτ), τταΚιν εφεΒρος αυτού των ττηΒαΧίων yLyv6μεvoς, τα νοσησαντα καϊ ε Χυθεντα εν ττ) καθ^ εαυτόν ττροτέρα ττερωΒω στρεψας κοσμεί τε καϊ εττανορθών άθάνατον αυτόν καϊ ά^ηρων άττερ^άζεταν. τούτο μεν ουν τεΚος άττάντων εϊρηταΐ' το δ* εττΐ την του βασιλέως άττόΒειξιν Ικανον εκ του ττρόσθεν άτΓΤομενοις του λόγου. στρεφθεντος yap αύ του κόσμου την εττΐ την νυν yεvεσίv οΒόν το της ηΧικίας αΰ ττάΧιν ΐστατο καϊ καινά τάναντία άττεΒίΒου τοις τότε. τα μεν yap υττο σμικρότητος όXLyoυ Βεοντα ηφανίσθαι των ζώων ηύξάνετο, τα δ* εκ yής vεoyεvή σώματα ττοΧια φύντα ττάΧιν άτΓοθνησ κοντά εΙς yrjv κάτσει, και ταΧΧά τε ττάντα μετε- 274 βαΧΧεν, άτΓομιμούμενα καϊ ξυνακοΧουθουντα τω του τταντος τταθηματι, καϊ Βη καϊ το της κυήσεως καϊ yεvvησεως καϊ τροφής μίμημα συνείττετο τοις ττάσιν υττ άvάyκης. ου yap εξήν ετ εν yrj Βι έτερων συνιστάντων φύεσθαι ζώον, άΧΧα καθάττερ τω κόσμω ττροσετετακτο αυτοκράτορα είναι της αύτοΰ ΊΓορείας, οΰτω Βη κατά ταύτα καϊ τοις μέρεσιν αύτοΐς Βι^ αυτών, καθ' όσον οιόν τ ην, φύειν τε καϊ yεvvάv καϊ τρεφειν ττροσετάττετο υττο της όμοιας άγωγ^9. ου Βε ένεκα Β ο Xoyoς ώρμηκε ττάς, εττ αύτω νυν εσμεν ηΒη. ττερϊ μεν THE POLITICUS MYTH 189 from him, at first for a while after the separation it performed all things exceeding well ; and then, as time went on, and forgetfulness grew more and more within it, discord, inherent from of old, gained ever greater mastery and at last burst forth ; and things good that were produced being few, and the admixture of the opposite sort being great, the Universe came into danger of being destroyed together with all that was in it. Wherefore, when things were come to this pass, God, who fashioned this Order, perceiving that it was in distress, and careful lest, being tossed in the storm of so great a tumult, it should be loosed asunder and founder down into the measure- less deep of Confusion, again took up His post at the helm ; and having turned round that which was gone the way of disease and dissolution in the former Period when the Universe was left to itself, put all in order, and restored the Universe to the right way, and made it exempt from death and old age. Here endeth the Tale : now let us return, and take up the beginning thereof, which will suffice for our setting forth of " The King." When the Universe was turned back, and went the way of this present sort of generation, then again did man's age first stand still, and thereafter straightway began to bring forth things new, in the order contrary to that of the former period ; for those creatures which, by reason of their small- ness, were all but vanished away, began to grow bigger, and the bodies of men newly come forth from the Earth, which were born grey-headed, died again, and went down into the Earth; and all other things were likewise changed, according to the changed condition of the Universe, their Example and Controller ; and among these things which were of necessity so changed were the Conception and Birth and Nourishment of living creatures; for no longer could a living creature grow in the Earth, compacted together out of his elements by others, but even as it was ordained unto the Universe to be master of his own path, so also was it ordained, by the like law, that the parts of the Whole, of themselves, as far as might be, should bring forth, and beget, and provide nourishment. Now, therefore, are we come whither our Whole Discourse was bound. 190 THE MYTHS OF PLATO yap των αΧΚων θηρίων ττολλά αν κα\ μακρά ΒίεξβΧθβΐν yiyvoLTO, ef ών βκαστα καΐ δ^' α9 αίτιας μεταβάβΧηκβ' 7Γ€ρΙ δε ανθρώπων βρα'χυτβρα καϊ μαΧΧον ττροσήκοντα. της yap τον κεκτημένου καϊ νβμοντος ημάς Βαίμονος άττερη- μωθεντβς έττίμέΧβίας, των ττοΧΧων αν θηρίων, οσα χαλεττά τας φύσεις ην, ά'πaypLωθevτωv, αύτοΙ δε άσθβνβΐς άνθρωττοι C καϊ άφύΧακτοί yeyov6τeς, Βιηρττάζοντο νττ αυτών, καϊ 6Τ άμή'χανοί καϊ άτεγνοί κατά τους ττρώτονς ήσαν 'χρονονς, άτ€ της μεν αυτόματης τροφής έτη,ΧεΧοιττνίας, ττορίζεσθαι δε ονκ βτΓίστάμβνοί ττω Βια το μηΒεμίαν αντονς γ^ρβίαν Ίτρότβρον άvayκάζ€ιv. εκ τούτων ττάντων iv μeyάXaLς ήσαν άττορίαις. όθεν Βή τα ττάΧαι, Χεγθεντα τταρα θεών Βώρα ήμΐν ΒεΒώρη- ταί μετ άvayκaίaς δ^δαχτ}? καϊ τταίΒεύσεως, ττυρ μεν παρά ΤΙρομηθεως, τεγναν Βε παρ 'Ή.φαίστου καϊ τής συντεγνου, D σπέρματα δε αν καϊ φυτά παρ* άΧΧων καϊ πάνθ\ οπόσα τον ανθρώπινον βίον συyκaτεσκεύaκεv, εκ τούτων yεyovεv, επειΒή το μεν εκ θεών, όπερ ερρήθη νυν Βή, τής επιμεΧείας επεΧιπεν ανθρώπους, Βι εαυτών δε εΒει την τε Bι,ayωyήv καϊ την επιμεΧειαν αυτούς αυτών εγειν, καθάπερ οΧος 6 κόσμος, ω ξυμμιμούμενοί καϊ ξυνεπόμενοί τον άεϊ 'χρόνον νυν μεν ούτως, τότε Βε εκείνως ζώμεν τε καϊ φυόμεθα. καϊ το μεν Ε δ^ του μύθου τεΧος εγετω, 'χρήσιμον δε αύτον ποιησόμεθα προς το κατιΒεΐν, όσον ήμάρτομεν άποφηνάμενοι τον βασιΧικόν τε καϊ ποΧιτικον εν τω πρόσθεν Xoyo). THE POLITICUS MYTH 191 As for the beasts of the field, to tell how and by what causes they were changed would be a long story ; but our proper concern is man, and a shorter story will suffice. When we were bereft of the care of the god which had gotten us to keep and tend, then came it to pass, because the multitude of wild beasts, being fierce by nature, were become more savage, and we ourselves were become weak and defenceless, that we were harried by them ; and, more- over, at first, we were helpless, and without the aid of the arts ; for the food which grew spontaneous was now lacking, and we knew not yet how to provide food, because that aforetime need had not constrained us to make provision. By reason of all these things were men in sore straits : where- fore it came to pass that those Gifts from the Gods whereof the old stories tell were bestowed upon us, together with the teaching and training which were needful ; to wit, fire from Prometheus, and the arts from Hephaestos and his mate ; and seeds and herbs from others : yea, all things which have furnished man's life were thus brought forth, ever since the time when the watch kept over us by the Gods, as I said just now, failed us, and it behoved us to spend our lives by ourselves, caring for ourselves ; even as the whole Universe must care for itself; the which we imitating and following alway throughout all ages do live and grow up, now after this manner, and then again after that manner. Here endeth our Tale ; the use whereof will be to make us see how wrongly we set forth the nature of the King and Statesman in our former Discourse. Before I go on to offer observations on the Politicus Myth, I will supplement the foregoing translation of it by giving a translation of the Myth of the Golden Age of Cronus as it appears also in the Lavjs. 192 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Laws 712e-714a 712 Ε ΑΘ. "Οζ/τως γα/?, ώ άριστοι, ττόλιτβιων μβτέχ^ετβ' ας Be ώνομάκαμεν ννν, ουκ elal ττολιτβΐαι, ττοΧεων δε οικήσεις 713 ΒεστΓοζομένων re καϊ ΒουΧβνουσών μερβσιν εαυτών τισί, το του Βεσιτότου Be εκάστη ττροσα^ορεύεται κράτος, χρήν Β , εϊττερ του τοιούτου την ττοΧιν εΒει εττονομάζεσθαι, το του άΧηθώς των τον νουν ε-χόντων Βεσττόζοντος θεού όνομα Χέ'γεσθαι. ΚΛ. Τ/9 δ' ό θεός; ΑΘ. *Αρ* οΰν μύθω σμικρά γ* ^"^^ ττροσγ^ρηστεον, ει μεΧΧομεν εμμεΧώς ττως ΒηΧώσαι το νυν ερωτώμενον ; ούκουν 'χ^ρη ταύττ) Βράν ; ΚΑ. ΤΙάνυ μεν ουν. ΑΘ. Ύών yap Βη ττόΧεων, ων έμπροσθεν τάς ξυνοικη- Β σεις ΒιηΧθομεν, ετι πρότερα τούτων ττάμττοΧυ Χε^^εταί τις ^ΡΧν "^^ '^^^ οϊκησις ^^ε^ονεναι εττΐ Έίρόνου μάΧ^ εύΒαίμων, ης μίμημα εχρυσά εστίν, ήτις των νυν άριστα οικείται» * * * * ^( % 713 C φημην τοίνυν τταραΒεΒε'γμεθα της των τότε μακάριας ζωής, ώς άφθονα τε και αυτόματα πάντ ^Ιχεν, ή Βε τούτων αιτία Χέζεται τοιάΒε τις' ^ι^νωσκων ό Κ,ρόνος άρα, καθάττερ ήμεΐς ΒιεΧηΧύθαμεν, ώς ανθρωπεία φύσις ούΒε μία ικανή τα ανθρώπινα Βιοικουσα αυτοκράτωρ πάντα μή ούγ ΰβρεώς τε καϊ άΒικίας μεστοΰσθαι, ταΰτ οΰν Βιανοούμενος D εφίστη βασιΧεας τε και άρχοντας ταΐς πόΧεσιν ημών ουκ ανθρώπους, άΧΧά 'γένους θειοτερου τε και άμείνονος, Βαίμονας' οϊον νυν ήμεΐς Βρώμεν τοις ποιμνίοισι καϊ όσων THE MYTH OF THE GOLDEN AGE Athenian Stranger. The cities whereof we just now spake are not polities, or true cities, but mere dwelling-places, the inhabitants whereof are slaves in subjection unto certain ones among themselves ; and each one of these dwelling-places is called " the government of such and such," after them that be masters therein : but, if it is meet that a city should be called after her masters, the True City will be called after God, who verily ruleth over men of understanding. Cleinias. And who is this God ? Ath. I must still, for a little while, use Fable for the more convenient answering of thy inquiry — what thinkest thou? Cleinias. Yea — Fable. Ath. Before that those cities were, the inhabitation whereof we have set forth in the former part of this Dis- course — yea, very long time before these — it is told that there was a Government and Settlement when Cronus was King ; whereof the blessedness was great, and whichsoever city is now ordered best is an image of that exemplar. ^ * ^ ^ * * This, then, is the Tale which we have received concerning the blessed life of the men who lived in those days : It telleth that they had all things, without stint, spontaneous, and that the cause thereof was this : Cronus, saith the Tale, knowing that Human Nature could in no wise be left with sole authority in the administration of all things human and yet not become a vessel filled with insolency and injustice, took thought of the matter, and set over our cities, to be kings and rulers thereof, not n^en, but those of a more divine and excellent sort, to wit. Daemons ; just as we ourselves do with 193 194 THE MYTHS OF PLATO ημβροί elaiv ayeXac• ου βονς βοών ovBe αί^ας alycov άρ'χρντα'ζ ττοιοΰμβν αυτοΐσί τινας, άλλα ήμ€Ϊς y αυτών Ββσττόζομβν, άμβίνον βκβίνων yevo^. ταυτον Βη καΐ 6 θβος άρα [καϊ] φιΧάνθρωττος ών το yevo<; άμεινον ημών βφίστη το τών Βαομόνων, ο Βία ττοΧλης μεν αύτοΐς ραστώνης, Ε ΤΓοΧλής Β ήμΐν βΤΓίμεΧούμβνον ημών, βίρήνην Τ6 και αΙΒώ καΧ Βυνομίαν καΐ άφθονίαν Βίκης Ίταρβ'χρμβνον, αστασίαστα κσΧ ευΒαίμονα τα τών άνθρώττων άιτβίρ^άζετο ^ίνη. Xeyet Βη καΐ νυν ούτος 6 Χο^ος αλήθεια 'χ^ρώμενος, ώ? όσων αν τΓοΧεων μη θεός άλλα τις άργΎ) θνητός, ουκ εστί κακών αύτοΐς ούΒε ττονων άνάφυξις* άλλα μιμεΐσθαυ ΒεΙν ημάς οίεται ττάση μηχανή τον εττΐ του Κρόνου Χε^όμενον βίον, καϊ όσον εν ήμΐν αθανασίας ενεστι, τούτω ττειθ ο μένους 714 Βημοσία καϊ ΙΒία τάς τ οΙκήσεις καΐ τας ττόΧεις Βίοοκεΐν, την του νου Βιανομήν επονομάζοντας νόμον. THE POLITICUS MYTH 195 our cattle and flocks — for we set not oxen over oxen, or goats over goats, but we ourselves rule over them, being of a race more excellent than theirs. In like manner God, they say, of his loving-kindness toward men, set over us the race of Daemons, which is more excellent than ours ; and they, to their own great content and to ours, caring for us, and providing for us peace, and modesty, and good government, and justice without stint, made the nations of mankind peaceable and happy. This Tale, then, hath in it truth, inasmuch as it signifieth that whichsoever city hath not God, but a mortal man, for ruler, hath no way of escape from evils and troubles : where- fore, according to the admonition of the Tale, must we by all means make our life like unto the life which was when Cronus was King ; and in so far as that which is Immortal dwelleth in us, must we be obedient unto the voice thereof in all our doings private and public, and govern our households and cities according to Law, which, being interpreted, is the Award of Reason} ^ This Myth ought to be taken in close connection not only with the Politicus Myth, but with the Discourse of Diotima, in the Symposium, and the doctrine of Daemons set forth in that Discourse ; for which see pp. 434 fF. infra. 196 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Observations on the Politicus Myth I cannot do better at the outset than refer the reader for the general characteristics of the Politicus Myth to Jowett's Introduction to the Statesman {Dialogues of Plato), where his admirable remarks, indeed, leave little to be added. The philosophical import of the Myth, it will be gathered from Jowett's remarks, consists in its presentation of the " distinc- tions between God causing and permitting evil, and between his more or less immediate government of the world." Interesting observations will also be found on the art with which Plato gives verisimilitude to his own Myth " by adopt- ing received traditions (as the tradition about the sun having originally risen in the West and that about the γτ/γεζ^ε??) — traditions of which he pretends to find an explanation in his own larger conceptions." We have had instances of this art in the Platonic Myths already examined, which we have found securing credit to themselves by explaining not only old traditional Myths, but the facts and doctrines of " modern science " ; and we have found the same art employed by Dante. Having referred to Jowett's Introduction ^ for a general view of this Myth, I will now add some observations on special points. The doctrine of periodical terrestrial ''catastrophes," uni- versal or local, leaving on each occasion a few scattered survivors to build up society afresh, mythologically explained in the Politicus, was part of the " science " of Plato's day,^ and was afterwards a prominent tenet of the Peripatetics.^ It was also " scientific " in Plato's day to explain at least the general course of terrestrial phenomena as caused by the motion of the Hea\^ns. It is thus that the phenomena of ^ I would also refer to Grote's Plato, ii. 480, note s — a long and instructive note ; and to Stallbaum's Prolegomena to the Politicus. 2 Laws, iii. 676 ff. ' See Newman's notes on Arist. Pol. ii. 5. 1269 a 5 and 6. THE POLITICUS MYTH 197 yeveaL<; και φθορά in this sublunary region are accounted for by Aristotle.^ Putting together the occurrence of terrestrial catastrophes (cf. Tim. 22 £f.) and the influence of the motion of the Heavens, both vouched for by " science," Plato imagines the catastrophes as shocks produced by sudden changes in the direction of the motion. The western rising of the sun in the Atreus Myth may have suggested this explanation to him ; or he may have known the Egyptian tradition recorded by Herodotus (ii. 142), that during eleven thousand three hundred and forty years of Egyptian history the sun on four occasions altered his course, " twice rising where he now sets and twice setting where he now rises." Although another rationale of the Egyptian tradition (or of Herodotus's version of it) has been given,^ I venture to suggest that whereas East is left and West is right as one faces the mid-day sun in the northern hemisphere, while East is right and West is left to the spectator in the southern hemisphere, the "Egyptian tradition " was awkwardly built upon the tale of some traveller coming from south of the equator, who said truly that he had seen the sun rise on his right hand and set on his left. II Zeller {Plato, Eng. Transl. p. 383, n. 44) says, " Of course (cf. Tim. 36 E, and elsewhere) Plato is not in earnest in supposing that God from time to time withdraws from the governnient of the world." Since the supposition of God's intermittent agency is made in a Myth, Plato is certainly not " in earnest " with it, in the sense of laying it down dogmatically as a scientific axiom. But is he more " in earnest " with the supposition of the continuous agency of God in the Timaeus ? That supposition is equally part of a Myth ; Timaeus ipse totus mythicus est.^ The truth is that, however Plato represents God — and he Ϊ Be Gen. et Corr. ii. 10, 336 a 26, and cf. Zeller's Aristotle, Eng. Transl. i. 580 ff. 2 See Rawlinson's note ad Im. ^ Couturat, de Platonis Mythis, p. 32. / 198 THE MYTHS OF PLATO sometimes represents him in immense cosmic outlines, some- times on a smaller scale and more anthropomorphically — the representation is always for the imagination, mythical. And it ought not to be forgotten that the supposition of God's intermittent agency is advanced in the Politicus in order to explain (mythologically, of course) the fact which Plato does not shut his eyes to even in the Timaeus, where he supposes (still in Myth) the continuity of God's government — the fact of the existence of evil, both physical and moral, in a world supposed to be governed by God. In maintaining the exist- ence of evil Plato is certainly " in earnest." It is worth noting that the representation given by the Politicus Myth of the opposition between God and Matter — good and evil — as an opposition of motions is common to the Myth with the astronomy of Plato's day ; but whereas the Politicus Myth makes motion in God's direction alternate with motion in the world's direction, astronomical theory makes the two motions go on for ever simultaneously, i.e. the eternal motion of the whole Cosmos from East to West carries round the inner spheres, whose own motions take place from West to East. For a full discussion of the astronomy of the Politicus Myth I would refer the reader to Mr. Adam's RepuUic, vol. ii. 295 if. Mr. Adam's view is that the two cycles (the motion in God's direction, and that in the opposite direction) are of equal length, and that each of them represents a Great Year — the Great Year being 36,000 years. Ill To ηηίνον ηΒη ττάν άνηΚωτο yevo^ (Politicus, 272 d). The " Kesurrection " of the Politicus Myth and " Metempsy- chosis " may be regarded as parallel products of imagination. Metempsychosis assumes a fixed number of souls created once for all and continuing always in existence. New souls are not created ; the souls which animate the bodies of men in each successive generation are always souls which had been in- carnate in former generations. In Pep. 611a, Plato ex- THE POLITIGUS MYTH 199 pressly lays it down that the number of souls in existence is always the same without augmentation or diminution.^ This tenet involved in Metempsychosis Plato shares with the aborigines of Australia. Messrs. Spencer and Gillen say : ^ The idea is firmly held that the child is not the direct result of intercourse^ — that it may come without this, which merely, as it were, prepares the mother for the reception and birth of an already formed spirit child who inhabits one of the local totem centres. . . . In the native mind the value of the Churinga (stone or wooden objects lodged in a cave or other storehouse, near which women do not pass) lies in the fact that each one of them is intimately associated with, and is indeed the representative of, one of the Alcheringa ancestors, with the attributes of which it is endowed. AVhen the spirit part has gone into a woman, and a child has, as a result, been born, then that living child is the re-incarnation of that particular spirit individual.^ As Metempsychosis makes the same soul, so Eesurrection makes the same body, serve more than one life. There is a store of old bodies, as there is of souls, upon which a new generation draws. The store of souls assumed by Metempsy- chosis is never exhausted, being recruited as fast as it is drawn upon ; but the store of adult bodies in the " Eesurrection " of the Politicus Myth is at last exhausted, for each adult body, when in its turn it rises from the dead, grows smaller and smaller till it becomes the body of an infant and vanishes away. One might develop Plato's myth, and say that it is these vanished infants which reappear after the manner of ordinary 1 Cf. Rohde, Fs^Jche, ii. 279. ^ The Native Tribes of Central Australia, p. 265. ^ Cf. Myer and Nutt's Voyage of Bran, ii. 82, on the widespread idea of con- ception, without male intervention, through swallowing a worm in a drink, or through some other means. ^ Spencer and Gillen's Native Tribes of Central Australia, p. 138. Before going to press I have not had an opportunity of seeing Messrs. Spencer and Gillen's new book, The Northern Tribes of Central Australia, but 1 transcribe the following sentences from a notice of it in the Athenaeum (July 9, 1904) : — "These tribes believe that in every child the soul of a mythical Alcheringa ancestor of a given totem is re-incarnated. These totem souls haunt the places, marked by a tree or rock, where the ancestors 'went into the ground.' There the dying ancestors left stone amulets of a type familiar in Europe and America, styled churinga. ΛVhen a child is born his ancestral churinga is sought, and often is found near the place where the totem spirit entered his mother." Are the "articles belonging to th• deceased," referred to p. 450 infra, parallel to these Australian amulets ? 200 THE MYTHS OF PLATO birth, and grow back into adult size, when the revolution of the Cosmos is reversed. This would be in accordance with the belief, by no means confined to such primitive minds as those of the Australian aborigines, observed by Messrs. Spencer and Gillen, that intercourse is after all not the real cause of the birth of a child : that the child — hardly dis- tinguished as " soul " and " body " — is one who returns from the world of the departed and enters into the mother. The relationship between such a view of the nature of procreation and the custom of counting kinship through the mother, not through the father, is of course obvious. That the notion of Eesurrection, then, recommends itself to the imagination in much the same way as the notion of Metempsychosis is what I wish to suggest to the student of the Politicus Myth. The two notions are closely allied and, indeed, tend to coalesce. The distinction between soul and body is a hard one for the imagination to maintain ; thus it is very imperfectly maintained in the following instance: " The Jesuits relate that among the Hurons there were special ceremonies for little children who died at less than two months old; their bodies were not put in coffins in the cemeteries, but buried upon the pathway in order that they might enter into the body of some passing woman and so be born again ; " ^ and it is practically given up in the Christian Eschatology which insists on the ultimate union of the soul with its risen body. lY My remarks in this section will serve as introduction to the " Creation Myths," which we shall examine next. The Politicus Myth may be distinguished as Aetiological from the Eschatological Myths which we have examined in the Phaedo, Gorgias, and RepuUic. The Eschatological Myths are concerned immediately with the Ideas of Eeason. They set forth the Idea of Soul as subject of God's govern- 1 J. E. King on "Infant Burial," in Classical Review, Feb. 1903, p. 83. The souls of infants seem always to have caused difficulty ; see Rohde, PsycJie, ii. 411-413, on Άωροι, and Adam's note on Rep. 615 c, των 5k evdos Ύβνομένων καΐ OXiyov xpbvov βιούντων ττέρι άλλα ^Xeyev ουκ άξια μνήμην. THE POLITICUS MYTH 201 ment in the Cosmos, by depicting the future vicissitudes of the ψνχη, not, of course, without reference to its past out of which its future grows. The Aetiological Myth, on the other hand, may set forth either Ideas of Eeason or Categories of the Understanding. Thus the Timaeus (which is one great Aetiological Myth) sets forth the Ideas of Soul and Cosmos, by tracing their imaginatively constructed objects back to causes which are unfolded in an account of the Creation of the ψνχη and of the material world. The Phaedrus Myth, again, sets forth the Categories of the Understanding aetiologicaUy, by showing that the a priori conditions of our knowledge of sensible phenomena are abiding mental impressions caused by a prenatal vision of the Eternal Forms in the ύττβρονράνως τότΓος. There are other myths which cannot be called either Aetiological or Eschatological, but are merely Expository either of Ideas of Eeason or of Categories of the Understanding — thus Diotima's Myth is an imaginative exposition of the Idea of Soul as Love of Truth and Immortality, while the functions of the Understanding are described imagi- natively in the Timaeus as revolutions like those of the Cosmos. The Politicus Myth, setting forth as it does the Idea of Soul as subject of God's government in the Cosmos, is Aetio- logical in supplying a cause for the Evil which exists in the world and man's life under God's government. How does Plato think that we are helped out of the profound difficulty about the existence of Evil by an Aetio- logical Myth of Changing World -periods ? The answer, if we could give it, would be a complete theory of the influence which Aetiological Myths exercise over the mind of man. Here is the greatest difficulty of morals ; and it is easily solved by a fantastic story of the origin of the thing which makes the difficulty ! Let me try to explain how Plato comes to attach such value to this Aetiological Myth. First, Plato thinks that the immensity of the difficulty is best illustrated in this way — as the tragic import of a great crisis on the stage or in real life is sometimes illustrated by the trifling comment or behaviour of some one present — it may be of a child. Plato thinks that his Myth, with its childish unconsciousness of difficulty, is 202 THE MYTHS OF PLATO valuable as enhancing our sense of the immensity of the diffi- culty, and so helping us to remove the difficulty — the very difficulty which it makes appear more immense. When we know the real cause of any particular difficulty of detail we have got a grip of it, as it were, and can generally overcome it. We can never get this sort of grip of the difficulty about the existence of Evil ; for it is not a particular difficulty with a particular discoverable solution, but a universal difficulty — a contradiction inherent in the very nature of the system under which we live — it puzzles us, and paralyses us the more we try to remove it αιτίας Χο^ισμω — by particular explana- tions, more nostro. But Plato's Myth puts the difficulty once for all in its true place — exhibits it, in its immensity, as uni- versal ; and the moral is — You cannot solve it as you solve a particular difficulty. Do not try to do so. See how immense it is ! " Put it by " — The cloud of mortal destiny, Others will front it fearlessly — But who, like him, will put it by ? This is the first part of the answer which I venture to ofter to the question, How does Plato think that we are helped out of a profound difficulty by a childish Myth? The second part of the answer I venture to state as follows : It is very hard to " put it by " — impossible unless one fancies — it is enough merely to fancy — that one has somehow, at least partly, solved the difficulty which one is asked to " put by." An attempt to solve a fundamental or universal difficulty logically, by a thin process of reasoning, can only end in a sense of failure ; but a childish Myth, touch- ing, as it is apt to do, a vast complex of latent sensibilities, may awaken a feeling of vague satisfaction. A childish Myth may thus, after all, seem to solve a fundamental difficulty, so far as to warrant one in " putting it by " — the one important thing being that we should " put it by," and act, not think about it and hesitate. I suggest, then, that Plato's love of the Aetiological Myth is due to the instinctive sympathy of his many-sided genius with this — shall I call it weakness ? — of human nature, which finds, amid doubts and difficulties. THE POL IT reus MYTH 203 some satisfaction in fantastic explanation. Let me illustrate this weakness, with which I suggest that Plato is in artistic sympathy, by an instance of the use of the Aetiological Myth in Finnish mythology — by the Story of the Birth of Iron in the Kalewala. But first let me say a few words about the Kalewala by way of introduction to this story. The great Finnish Epic, the Kalewala, was pieced together about seventy years ago by Lonnrot out of Eunes or Cantos which had been, as they still are, sung separately by the popular Laujola, or Minstrels. The Eune, or Canto, is the unit of Finnish poetry, and may be fairly described as an Aetiological Myth growing out of the magician's charm- formula. The chief personages in the Kalewala are not national kings and warriors, as in other epics, but great magicians ; and the interest of the poem, or poems, is connected mainly with the manner in which these great magicians show their power over Nature, and Spirits, and Men. According to the Finnish belief, everything done in life, even the simplest thing done by the most ordinary person, has its appropriate charm- formula — is successfully done in virtue of the accompaniment of the suitable word or words — e.g. there is a word for success- fully laying the keel of a boat, and another for fixing the ribs, and so on. If ordinary acts depend on the utterance of the proper words, much more do the extraordinary acts of great magicians. Wainamoinen, the chief magician-hero of the Kalewala Eunes, when he was building his magic boat forgot three necessary words, and wandered over the whole Earth, and at last found his way into the World of the Dead, in his search for these lost words. Now these mighty words, which are the arms wielded by the magician-hero, are mighty in that they contain the cause of the thing on which he exercises his power. He is confronted with difficulties and dangers in his adventur- ous career, and it is by telling a difficult or dangerous thing its origin that he conquers it. If it is a wound to be cured it is the Birth of Iron that the magician must know and relate {Kal. ix. 29 ff.). If it is a monstrous bear that he has to overcome he must first tell the story of the Origin of the Bear {Kal. xlvi. 355). If it is a disease that he has to exorcise, he can only do tnat by telling the disease its hidden 204 THE MYTHS OF PLATO name, and the place from which it came, and the way by which it came {Kal. xlv. 23). If it is a snake-bite to be healed, he must know the Ancestry of Snakes {Kal. xxvi. 695). Thus, out of the charm-formula of the magician-hero the Aetio- logical Myth arises — especially when the singer of the Kune, identifying himself, as he often does, with his magician-hero, uses the first person. The Kalewala is a loosely connected collection of Cantos, in which magicians are the heroes, and charms the weapons, the charms being words which reveal the nature and origin of the things or persons overcome — magic words which the Finnish Kune -singers expanded into elaborate Aetiological Myths. Among other races it is the prayer at the sacrifice or offering, as Comparetti ^ observes, which is developed into the Hymn, and then into the Myth ; it is only among the Finns that the charm-formula is so developed. Sorcery, not as elsewhere ritual and custom, is here the germ of the Aetiological Myth. The Story of the Birth of Iron^ Wainamoinen, with blood streaming from a wound in his knee made by his axe when he was building a boat, hurries from place to place in his sledge, asking if any one knows the mighty words which will heal the " lion's outrage." No one knows them. At last he comes to a house in which there is a little grey-bearded old man by the fireside, who, in answer to Wainamoinen's ques- tion, calls out to him as he sits in his sledge at the door : "Wilder streams, greater rivers than this have ere now been tamed by three words of the High Creator." Wainamoinen rose out of his sledge and crossed the courtyard and entered the house. A silver cup and a golden tankard were brought and soon were full of blood, and overflowing. The little old man cried out from the fireside : " Speak, who art thou amongst men, of what people and nation, that already seven great basins and eight tubs are filled with thy blood ? All magic words I know, ^ Der Kalewala, oder die traditionelle Poesie der Finnen, p. 169 (German edition, 1892). 2 I have translated this story (with considerable compression and omission) from the German version of the Kaleioala by Hermann Paul, published at Helsinglors in 1885 to commemorate the fiftieth anniversary of the first publi- cation of the Finnish Epic. THE POLITICUS MYTH 205 save only that one word, which declareth how Iron was fashioned how the rusty metal arose." Then Wainamoinen answered and said : "I myself know the source of Iron, and the first beginning of Steel. " Heaven is the primaeval mother. Water is the eldest child, Iron is the youngest of the brethren. Fire is the middle son. "Ukko, the Almighty Creator, the Ruler of the wide world, separated Heaven from Water, separated dry Land from Water, before that Iron grew up, before that the rusty metal arose. "The Creator of Heaven, Ukko, rubbed together his right hand and his left, and pressed his two hands together, and laid them both upon his knee ; and straightway there came into being three fair women, lovely daughters of Nature, who caused Iron to come into being and the blue flashing Steel. "Lightly the fair women floated away by the edge of the clouds, and their swelling breasts were full of milk. The milk ran down over the earth continually, over the fields, over the fens, over the still waters and lakes. Black it flowed from the breasts of the eldest, white in bright drops it fell from the breasts of the second, red from the breasts of the youngest. She from whom the black drops fell caused the soft Iron to come forth, she from whom the white drops fell produced the glancing Steel, she from whom the red drops fell brought forth the brittle Iron. " After a while Iron would a- wandering go, to visit his elder brother Fire. But Fire was evilly minded towards him, and blazed up, and would have consumed him ; but Iron escaped out of the hands of his fierce brother, out of the mouth of the devouring Fire, and hid himself under the earth, in the bog, in the deep-hidden spring, on the wide expanse of the fen where the swans build their nests, on the ridge of the mighty cliff where the eagle watches over his brood. "So Iron lay deep in the moist fen, kept himself there for two years hidden ; yea, even in the third year lay quiet between the crooked trunks, under the rotten birch-leaves. " Yet could he not escape out of his brother's hands ; again must he return into the power of wicked Fire, and be forged into tools and weapons. " One day the Wolf ran over the fen, one day the Bear trotted growling over the moor. The footprints of the Wolf were plain, the Bear left his track behind ; and lo ! there the rusty Iron appeared, there the glancing Steel, in the broad footprints of the Wolf, in the Bear's great track. " Ilmarinen, the cunning Smith, came into the world, was born on a coal-heap, grew up on the murky hill, with a hammer in his hand, and little tongs undSr his arm. In the night was he born. 206 THE MYTHS OF PLATO and on the morrow went forth to seek a smithy and a place for his bellows. He saw a piece of fenland, a wet morass ; he went near to look at it ; and there he built him his smithy and put up his bellows. " Soon he marked the footprints of the Wolf and the track of the Bear on the fen, and saw the rusty Iron, found the Steel, discovered in the Wolf's broad footprints, in the Bear's great track. " Then spake the Smith : ' unhappy Iron ! What is happened unto thee ! What unworthy place is this that thou hast, under the Wolfs heavy feet, in the track of the clumsy Bear 1 ' "Thereafter he bethought him, and whispered to himself; ' What would come of it, if I cast the Iron into the Fire, into the sparkling glow ? ' " Then did the anguish of the fear of death take hold of the Iron, Avhen it heard the terrible name of Fire. " But the Smith lifted up his voice, and said : ' Fear not, poor Iron ; Fire hurteth not his brother. If thou enterest into the smithy, and layest thyself down in the furnace, thou shalt rise up again more beautiful, thou shalt become a sharp sword for men, a useful instrument for women.' " The Smith took the Iron, and cast it on the glowing hearth, and on the first day stirred up the flame, and yet again on the second day, and the third. Slowly the glowing Iron was melted, and boiled up in bubbles, and spread itself, like leavened dough, within the flames of the mighty Fire. " Then cried the Iron in anguish : ' Smith, have com- passion upon me ; take me out of the burning Fire, out of the hot flaming glow ! ' " Then answered the Smith : 'If I take thee now out of the Fire, thou mightest grow up to be evil, and all too dangerous ; thou mightest murder thy nearest-of-kin, regarding not thine own brother.' " Then Iron lifted up his voice, and swore a great oath, and said : ' There are still trees enough to fell, and stones enough to break : never will I hurt my brother, or do harm unto my nearest- of-kin. Better and fairer and more honourable 'tis to live as companion and servant of man, to be his friend, the weapon of his hand, than to be the enemy of one's kinsman, the destroyer of one's brother.' " Then took Ilmarinen the Smith, the famous Smith, the poor Iron out of the Fire, and laid it on the anvil, and hammered it till it was bent to use ; and therefrom he made sharp tools, axes and swords, and implements of every sort. " Yet something was still lacking to the Iron, the Steel still THE POLITICUS MYTH 207 needed something. The Iron's tongue lacked hardness, his mouth lacked the due sharpness. The Iron could not be forged hard, unless Water wetted it. " The renowned Smith bethought him what he should do ; and then he sprinkled a little ash upon Water, and dissolved it therein, and made a pungent bath, for to give hardness to the Iron and strength to the Steel. " Carefully did he prove the Water with his tongue, and then said : ' The Water is not yet made lit to harden the rusty metal and the blue glancing Steel.' " Behold a Bee came flying over the grass, sporting high and low on bright wings, flitting and humming round him. " Then spake the renowned Smith : ' Here I Busy Bee ! Bring me honey on thy wing, bring hither the noble juice, suck it from the cups of the flowers, to give the right hardness to the Iron, to give strength to the Steel.' " Hiisi's evil bird, the Wasp, overheard the talk, as she peeped down from the roof. She gave heed secretly to all, she saw the rusty metal prepared, she saw the glancing Steel brought forth. "In haste away flew the Wasp from thence, and gathered together Hiisi's horrors ; she brought the black venom of the serpent, and the deadly poison of the adder, and the bitter froth of worms, and the corroding liquor of the toad, to give hardness to the Iron and strength to the Steel. " Ilmarinen, the cunning workman, the renowned Smith, thought that the Busy Bee had brought him honey, had given him the noble juice ; and he said : ' Now is the bath right to harden the rusty metal, to give strength to the blue Steel.' " In the bath he dipped the Iron, without heed he cast the metal therein, when he had drawn it out of the Fire, out of the glowing forge. " Then came it to pass that Iron was made hurtful, and did rend Honour even as a dog rendeth flesh, and broke the sacred oath which he sware, and murdered his own brother, and bit wounds into him with sharp mouth, and opened paths for the blood, and poured it out in foaming stream." The little old man at the fireside cried aloud, and rocked his head to and fro, and sang : " Oh, now I know the Beginning of Iron, now I know who drave it to evil. Woe unto thee, thou luckless Iron ! woe unto thee, thou deceitful Steel ! Poor metal, taken captive by witchcraft ! Is it thence that thou art sprung ? Is it for this reason that thou art become a terror and hast too great mastery ? " Who moved thee to wickedness, who drave thee to treason 1 Was it thy Father or thy^other % Was thy eldest Brother guilty 208 THE MYTHS OF PLATO of this ? Was it thy youngest Sister, or some Friend, who coun- selled thee and turned thee to the evil deed ? "Neither Father nor Mother nor eldest Brother nor youngest Sister nor any Friend gave thee this counsel. Thyself hast thou done this wickedness, thyself hast thou accomplished the bloody deed. " Iron ! Look at this wound ! Heal the evil thou hast done ere I go in anger with complaint against thee to thy Mother. The sorrow of the old woman thy Mother is increased if her child turneth himself to evil and doeth wickedness. " Leave off, and run no more, thou foaming blood ! hold in thy course, spout forth no more in long-curved bow, bespattering my head and breast ! Stand like a wall immovable, like a fence, like the sedge by the water's side, like the grass in the slimy fen ! Stand like the rocks upon the firm earth, like the cliff in the raging storm ! " If thou heedest not these words, I will devise other means : hither do I call Hiisi's Kettle to seethe the foaming blood therein, to make hot the red juice, so that not a drop shall flow away, so that the purple gore shall run down thereinto, and wet not the earth nor stream foaming over the ground. " And if power be withheld from me myself to stay the endless flood, to become master of the wild stream, know that in Heaven there liveth a Father, a God dwelling above the clouds, who is the mightiest leech for the closing-up of bleeding wounds. " Ukko, High Creator, Everlasting God of Heaven, hear me when I call unto thee in time of need ! Lay thy soothing hand, thy finger which bringeth healing, on the w^ound, and be as a sure lock to close it. " Take, Lord, a healing leaf, spread a water-lily leaf to cover the opening, stay the strong current of the blood, so that it stain not my cheeks nor stream over my garments." Therewith the old man shut the mouth of the wound, stayed the swift course of the blood; then sent he his son into the smithy to prepare a salve of the finest threads of the grass, of a thousand herbs of the field, of the flowers whence honey, -healing balm, droppeth. The boy brought the salve to his Father, saying : " Here is strong healing salve, able to cement stones together into one rock." The Father proved it with his tongue, and found it good ; and therewith he anointed the wounded man, saying : " Not by my own power do I this, but only through the power of the Highest." Then he bound up the wound with silken bands, saying : " May the silk of the Eternal Father, the bands of the Almighty THE POLITICUS MYTH 209 Creator, bind up this wound. Be gracious, Ο Heavenly Father, look down and help, put an end unto the bitter anguish, heal this wound without the sharpness of pain." Then did Wainamoinen, on a sudden, feel that he was healed ; and soon thereafter the wound grew together, and was closed.^ A Myth like this of the Birth of Iron, amplified, indeed, and embellished by poetical art, but originally inspired by the childish belief in the value of words which set forth the cause, helps us, I think, to understand Plato's employment of the Aetiological Myth. Confronted by some profound difficulty, he lays it, or " puts it by," by means of a fanciful account of the origin of the state of things which presents the difficulty. He seems to feel that an Aetiological Myth is " a comfortable thing," ^ and a charm to conjure with when one is hard pressed. The transition is easy from the point which we have now reached to Plato's Creation Myths — his Aetiological Myths par excellence. These are the Timaeus (which is one great Myth) and the Myth of Prometheus and Epimetheus in the Protagoras (320 C fp.). In distinguishing these Myths as Aetiological fropi the strictly Eschatological Myths of the Phaedo, Gorgias, and the Republic, I do not ignore the eschatological prospect which is presented in them, especially in the Timaeus ; but aetiological retrospect is what is really characteristic of them. It is the origin of the Universe, and of Man, Soul and Body, not the future life of Man's Soul, that these Myths are properly concerned with. They set forth the Ideas of Keason, Soul, Cosmos, and God, aetiologically in a Vision of Creation ; and supply, moreover, a mythological deduction of Categories of the Understanding and Moral Virtues, which lies outside the scope of the strictly Eschatological Myths ; i.e. they deduce Categories and Virtues from their causes in the nature of God and the make of the Cosmos — they picture for the imagination the orderly constitution of nature as expressing the wisdom and goodness of God, and explain — always for the iinagination — the harmony subsisting between that constitution and the faculties of the Soul. Thus in Timaeus 40 E— 42 Ε the a 1 Kalewala, Runes 8 and 9, vol. i. pp. 95-124, German version by Hermann Paul (Helsingfors, 1885). • * " Prisms are also comfortable things " (Bacon, Nat. Hist. cent. x. 960). Ρ 210 THE MYTHS OF PLATO priori conditions of thought, the modes in which the Under- standing brings order into the manifold of sense-experience, are set forth as due to impressions received by the Soul in its speculative journey round the Heavens, when it rode on its star-chariot, and saw the eternal laws of the Universe, and learned to move in orbits of rational thought, similar to those which rule the stars. It will be convenient to begin our study of the Creation Myths with the Protagoras Myth. It is on a small scale, and by looking at it first the eye of imagination may perhaps be prepared for the contemplation of the vast Timaeus. Although it is only a small part of the Timaeus that the limits of this work allow me to translate and comment on, I would ask the reader to regard the whole book as one great Myth in which the Ideas of Soul, Cosmos, and God are set forth in great shapes for our wonder — in which the relation of the Created Soul — "World Soul and Human Soul — to the Creator, the relation of the Human Soul to the Human Body, the Origin of Evil, the Hope of Salvation, and other things which con- cern our peace, are made visible. The Timaeus is a Myth, not a scientific treatise, although it was its fortune from the very first to be treated as if it were the latter. No other work of Plato's was so much read and commented on in antiquity, and throughout the Middle Age, as the Timaeus ; and that chiefly because it was regarded as a compendium of natural science, all the more valuable because its " natural science " was not presented as something apart by itself, but " framed in a theo- logical setting." Aristotle, of course, treats it au pied de la lettre} With the Christian Platonists it took rank as a scientific and theological authority along with the Book of Genesis.^ Dante's references to Plato's actual text are, I believe, all to passages contained in the Timaeus^ ^ The reader may test the justice of this statement by referring to the passages quoted in the Index Arist. s.v. "Tiywatos Platonis dialogue"; and see Zeller, Plato, p. 344, Eng. Transl. 2 "Numenius the Platonist speaks out plainly concerning his master : What is Plato but Moses Atticus ? " (Henry More's Conjectura Cabbalistica, Preface, p. 3 ; ed. 1662.) It was practically as author of the Timaeus that Plato was ''Moses Atticus" Jowett {Dialogues of Plato, Introd, to Timaeus) has some interesting remarks on the text — ** The influence which the Timaeus has exercised upon posterity is partly due to a misunderstanding." ' See Moore's Studies in Dante, first series, pp. 156 if., and Toynbee's Dante Dictionary, arts. *' Platone " and " Timeo'^." THE POLITICUS MYTH 211 Like the Politicus Myth, the Protagoras Myth is not spoken by Socrates, and Protagoras, the speaker, like the Eleatic Stranger in the Politicus, says that a Fable will come well from himself, an older man addressing younger men — Socrates and the others present. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH Context The scene of the Protagoras is the house of Callias, a wealthy Athenian gentleman, to which Socrates takes his friend Hippocrates, that he may introduce him to the celebrated teacher of Rhetoric — or the Art of getting on in Life — Protagoras, who happens to he staying with Callias. Besides Protagoras they find two other Sophists of repute there, Hippias and Prodicus, also Critias and Alcihiades. Hippocrates wishes to hecome a pupil of Protagoras; and Socrates, after communicating his friend's wish to the great man, asks him, " What he will make of Hippocrates ? " and Protagoras answers, " A better and wiser man " — that is, he will teach him how to do the right ^thing always in private_and public life. Socrates expresses \doubt as to whethe r_Jthe science of right conduct, or virtue yprivate and political— for that is whaTProtagoras professes to be able to teach — can really be taught. The Athenians, as a body, apparently do not think that it can be taught, for they do not demand it of their politicians; nor do the wisest and best citizens think that it can be taught, for they never attempt to impart it to their sons. The Myth (together with the Lecture of which it is a part) is the answer which Protagoras now gives to the difficulties raised by Socrates. The object of the Myth and Lecture is to show, that virtue — or rather, the virtues, for Protagoras enumerates five : wisdom, temperance, justice, holiness, courage — can be taught. When Protagoras has finished his Myth and Lecture, con- versation is resumed between him. and Socrates, and results in making it plain that the five virtues must be reduced to one — 212 THE PBOTAGOBAS MYTH 213 viz., to knowledge, which is represented as the art of measuring values — the values of the various objects which conduct sets before itself. Thus it has been brought about that Protagoras must admit the conclusion that virtue is knowledge, unless he would con- tradict his own thesis that it can be taught; while Socrates, in showing that it is knowledge, confirms that thesis, which he began by disputing. 214 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Protagoras 320 c-323 A 320 C *Hi/ γαρ 7Γ0Τ€ χ^ρόνος, ore θβοί μβν ήσαν, θνητά Sk D yevη ουκ ην, βττβιΒη δε καΐ τούτοις γ^ρόνος ηΧθβν €ίμαρμ€νο<ζ '^^νεσβως^ τνττοΰσίν αυτά θβοί 'γης evhov €Κ 'γής καΐ ττυρος μίξαντβς καΐ των οσα ττυρί καΐ yrj κβραννυται. iTreihrj δ* ayeiv αυτά, προς φως βμεΧΧον, ττροσέταξαν Τίρομηθβΐ καΐ ^ΈίΤΓΐμηθεΐ κόσμησαν Τ€ κα\ νβΐμαί 8υνάμ€ΐ>ς €κάστοι,ς ώς ττρεττβι. ΐΐρομηθέα δε παραιτείται ^Έίττιμηθευς αύτος νβΐμαί* ^είμαντος δ' €μου, βφη, ίττίσκβ'ψαν. καϊ οΰτω Ε ΊΓβίσας ν€μ€ΐ, νέμων δε τοΐς μεν Ισγυν άνευ τάγρυς ττροσήτΓΤβ, τα δ' ασθενέστερα τάγει εκόσμεί' τα Βε ώττλίξε, τοις δ' άοττλον ΒίΒούς ψύσιν αΧλην τιν αύτοΐς εμηγανατο Βύναμίν εΙς σωτηρίαν. α μεν ycup αυτών σμικρότητα ημτη- σχε, τΓτηνον φυ^γην ή κατά^γειον οϊκησιν ενεμεν α Βε ηΰξε 321 με^εθει, τωΒε αύτω αύτα έσωζε* καϊ ταΧΚα οΰτως εττανισών ένεμε, ταύτα Βε εμη'χανατο ευΚάβειαν εγων, μη τι ^ενος άΐστωθείη. εττειΒη Βε αύτοΐς άΧΧηΧοφθοριών Βίαφυ'γας εττηρκεσε, προς τας εκ Δ,ώς ώρας εύμάρειαν εμη'χανατο άμφίεννύς αύτα πυκναΐς τε θριξϊ καϊ στερεοΐς Βερμασιν, Ικανοΐς μεν άμυναι χειμώνα, Βυνατοΐς Βε και καύματα, και εις εύνας ίοΰσιν όπως ύπαρχοι τα αύτα ταύτα στρωμνη οικεία τε καϊ αυτοφυής εκάστω* καϊ ύπο ποΒών τα μεν Β οπΧαΐς, τα Βε θριξι και Βερμασι στερεοΐς και άναίμοις. τούντεΰθεν τροφάς άΧλοις άΧλας εξεπόριζε, τοΐς μεν εκ ^γής βοτάνην, αΧΧοις Βε ΒενΒρων καρπούς, τοΐς Βε ρίζας* εστί δ* οϊς εΒωκεν είναι τροφην ζώων αΧΧων βοράν. καϊ τοΐς μεν oXiyoyoviav προσήψε, τοΐς δ* άναΧισκομενοις ύπο τούτων πoXυyovίav, σωτηρίαν τω yεvει πορίζων, ατε Βη THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 215 Translation Time^was when^there were Gods/but mo rtal c reatures / after their kind Avere_ not^ Now^^when the appointed time came unto these also tfiat they should be born, the gods fashioned them under ^i^e JEarth, compound^^ earth/ and of fire,] and of whatsoever is made by the mingling of fire and earth. Now when they were ready to bring them to light, they gave commandment unto Prometheus and Epi- metheus to adorn them, and distribute unto each the powers that were meet. But Epimetheus entreated of Prometheus to let him distribute. " When I have distributed," quoth he, " do thou see whether it is done well." So he prevailed with him, and distributed : and unto some he gave strength without swiftness, but the weaker he adorned with swiftness ; unto others he gave weapons ; and for those unto whom he gave not weapons he contrived other means of safety ; to wit, unto those of them which he clothed with smallness he appointed winged escape, or habitation under ground ; and unto those which he increased with bigness, the safety which cometh therefrom. After this fashion, then, did he distribute, ever making one gift equal unto another. These things he contrived, lest perchance any race should be cut off. But when he had furnished them with means for escaping destruction from one another, he contrived for them con- venient defence against the seasons of the year, clothing them with thick hairs and stout hides sufficient to keep off the cold of winter and the burning heat ; the which might also be for couches proper and native unto each one of them, when they went to their lairs. Moreover, he shod some of them with hoofs, and others with hairs and thick skin without blood. After that he appointed unto them different kinds of food: unto some the herbs of the earth, unto others the fruits of the trees, unto others roots ; and some there were unto which he appointed for food the flesh of other beasts. And he ordained that they should bring forth young, some few, and others, which were devoured of these, many, that their race might be preserved. 216 THE MYTHS OF PLATO ovp ου ττάνν τι σοφ6<ζ ων ο ^ΈίΤΤίμηθβνς eXaOev αυτόν C καταναΧώσας τά? Βυνάμ€ί<ζ eh τα aXoya. Χοιττον Βη άκοσμητον €τι αύτω ην το άνθρώττων yevo<;, καΐ ηττόρβι 6 τι γ^ρησαίτο. άττοροΰντί δε αύτω βργβται ΤΙρομηθβύς €7Γΐσκ€ψομ€νος την νομην, καϊ ορα τα μβν αΧλα ζώα εμμβΧώς ττάντων εγοντα, τον he άνθρωττον ηυμνόν Te καϊ άνυτΓοΒητον καϊ άστρωτον καϊ άοττΧον. ή8η Be καϊ η eίμapμevη ημέρα τταρήν, ev fj eBei καϊ άνθρωττον έξιάναι €Κ γ?}9 eh φως. άττορία ουν eχ^6μevoς 6 Ή.ρομηθ€ύ<;, ήντινα σωτηρίαν τω άνθρώττω €ΰροί, KXeiTTei Ηφαίστου καϊ Ό * Αθήνας την evTe^vov σοφίαν συν ττυρί — άμη'χανον yap ην άveυ ττυρος αύτην κτητην τω η 'χ^ρησίμην yev€σθac — , καϊ οΰτω Βη BωpeLτaι άνθρώττω. την μ€ν ουν TTepl τον βίον σοφίαν άνθρωττος ταύτη έ'σχβ, την Be ττοΧίτικην ούκ εΖχεζ^• ην yap τταρα τω Ad' τω Be Tipoμηθeΐ eh μίν την άκρό- TToXiv την του Αίος οϊκησυν ούκέτί eve'χώpeL elσeXθeΐv^ ττρος Be καϊ αΐ Αώς φυΧακαΙ φoβepal ήσαν eh Be το της Ε Αθηνάς καϊ 'Ή,φαίστου οϊκημα το κοίνόν, ev ω έφίΧο- Τ€χν€ίτην, Χαθών elσep'χeτaι, καϊ κΧέψας την Te €μττυρον τάχνην την του Ηφαίστου καϊ την άΧΧην την της 'Αθηνάς ΒίΒωσιν άνθρώττω καϊ έκ τούτου eύττopίa μβν άνθρώττω του 322 βίου yίyveτaι, ΙΙρομηθέα Be Βί 'Έ^ττίμηθέα ύστepov, ηττ€ρ XeyeTao, κΧοττής Βίκη μeτηXθev. ΈτΓβίδ^ Be ο άνθρωττος θeίaς μeτeσ'χe μοίρας, ττρώτον μ€ν Βία την του θeoϋ συyyeveLav ζώων μόνον θeoυς evόμισey καϊ eττe'χeίpeL βωμούς Te ίBpύeσθaί καϊ άyάXμaτa θeώv' eTrecTa φωνην καϊ ονόματα ταγυ Βιηρθρώσατο τη τέ'χνη, καϊ olκησeiς καϊ €σθήτας καϊ ύττoBeσeίς καϊ στρωμνας καϊ τας €Κ yής τροφας eupeTO. οΰτω Βη ττapeσκeυaσμevoL• κατ Β άρ'χας άνθρωττου ωκουν σττοράΒην, ττόXeLς Be ούκ ήσαν. άττώΧΧυντο ουν ύττο των θηρίων Βίά το ττανταγτΙ αυτών άσθeveστepoL elvai, καϊ η BημLoυpy^,κη τέγνη aύτoh ττρος μ€ν τροφην Ικανη βοηθός ην, ττρος Be τον των θηρίων ττoXeμov €vBeής• ττοΧιτικην yap τέγνην οΰττω el^pv, ης μέρος TToXetiLKTi. ίζητουν Βη άθpoίζeσθaί καϊ σώζeσθat THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 217 Now, inasmuch as Epimetheus was not very wise, he un- wittingly spent all the qualities he had upon the brutes ; and lo I mankind was still left unto him unadorned, and he knew not what he should do concerning them. While he yet doubteth, Prometheus cometh unto him to look into his distribution ; and perceiveth that all other creatures are duly furnished in all things, but that man is naked and without shoes or bed or weapons : and now was come the appointed day on the which man also should go forth from the earth into the light. ^ Wherefore PrometheusflSeing Brought tohis^lial.fiSi devise any means of safety for man/'stea leth the cun n in j workman's wisdom of Hephaestus and ABHena, togetheir with fire — for witho ut (fir e none can get this wisdom or Ise it ; and this he giveth as a gift unto man. J Thus did man get the mechanic wisdom needful for his bare life ; but the wisdom which is needful for the life poli- tical he had not, for it was with Zeus ; and unto Prometheus it was no longer permitted to enter into the citadel, the dwelling-place of Zeus ; moreover, the guards of Zeus were terrible ; but into the common dwelling of Athena and Hephaestus, wherein they plied their craft, he secretly entered, and stole the fiery art of Hephaestus, and also Athena's art, and gave them unto man. Whence came convenient living unto man ; but as for Prometheus, he was afterwards arraigned for theft because of Epimetheus, as the story telleth. Now man, having been made a partaker of the divine lot, by reason of his kinship with the Godhead, alone among living creatures believed in Gods, and began to take it in hand to set up altars unto them and make graven images of them. Then soon with cunning device did he frame articulate speech and names, and invented houses to dwell in, and raiment and shoes to put on, and beds for rest, and food from the fruits of the earth. Thus furnished, men at first dwelt scattered abroad, and there were no cities. Wherefore men were continually devoured by wild beasts, for they were altogether weaker than the beasts, and their craftsman's art could help them to get food enough, but was not sufficient for their war with the wild beasts ; for they had not yet the art political, whereof the art of warfare is a part. 218 THE MYTHS OF PLATO /€τΙζοντ€ς 7ro\et9. 6t ovv άθροισθεΐεν, ηΒίκουν ά\\ή\ου<ζ, are ουκ εγοντε^ την ττοΧιτίκην τεγνην, ωστ€ irakiv σκε^αν- C νύμβνοί Βίβφθβίροντο. Ζ6ύ<ζ ουν δεισα? ττερί τω ^evei ημών, μη άττόΧοιτο τταν, ^Έιρμήν ττβμττβί ayovra eh άνθρώπτου^ αΙΒώ τ€ καΐ Βίκην, ϊν elev ττοΚβων κόσμοι τε καΧ ΒεσμοΙ φιλίας avvaywyoL' έρωτα ουν Έρμης Αία, τίνα ουν τρόττον Βοίη Βίκην καΐ αΙΒω άνθρώττοις. ττότβρον ως αΐ τέγναι νενίμηνται, οΰτω καϊ ταύτας νβίμω; νενέμηνται Be ώδε• €Ϊς e -χ^ων ίατρικην ττοΧΧοΐς Ικανός ΙΒιώταις, καϊ οΐ aWol• Bημtovpyoί. καϊ Βίκην Βη καϊ αΙΒώ οΰτω θώ iv τοις D άνθρώττοος, ή eVl ττάντας ν€ίμω ; ΈττΙ ττάντας, εφτ; ο Zeύς, καϊ 'πάvτeς μετ€'χ6ντων ' ου yap αν yevoiVTO ^Γo\eLς, el oXiyoL αυτών μ€Τ€'χοί€ν ώσττερ αΧΚων τ€γνών. καϊ νόμον ye θ€ς τταρ Ιμου τον μη Bυvάμevov αΙΒοΰς καϊ Βίκης μeτeχeίv KTeiveiv ως νόσον πτο\,€ως. Οΰτω Βη, ω %ώκρατ€ς, καϊ Βία ταΰτα οΧ τε αΧΧοι, καϊ οΐ ^Αθηναΐοί, όταν μίν irepX άpeτης τeκτovcκης η Xoyoς η άΧΧης τίνος Bημιoυpyίκης, 6Xίyoις οϊονταί μeτeΐvaL συμβουΧης, καϊ eav τίς €Κτος ων Ε των 6Xίyωv συμβουΧ€ύΎ], ουκ άνέ'χ^ονται, ως συ φ^ς' eiKO- τως, ως iycio φημί' όταν δε €ίς συμβουΧην ττοΧιτικής 323 άpeτής ϊωσιν, ην Bel Βία Βίκαίοσύνης ττάσαν Ιύναί καϊ σωφροσύνης, €ΐκοτως άτταντος άνΒρος άνέ'χ^ονταί, ως τταντί ττροσήκον ταύτης ye /-ί,ετεχείΐ/ της άpeτής, η μη elvai 7Γ6Xeις. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 219 Wherefore they sought to assemble themselves together, and save themselves by building cities. Now when they were assembled together, they wronged one another, because they had not the art political ; so they were again scattered abroad, and were like to be destroyed. But Zeus, fearing lest our race should perish utterly, com- mandeth Hermes to go unto men bearing modesty and justice, for the ordering of cities, and to be bonds joining men to- gether in friendship. Hermes inquireth of Zeus how he shall give justice and modesty unto men. "Are these," quoth he, " to be distributed as the arts are distributed, the which are distributed after this wise — one man hath the art of physic, or some other art, and is sufficient unto many who have it not ? Shall I distribute justice and modesty among men thus, or give them unto all ? " " Unto all," said Zeus, " and let all be partakers of them. For if few were partakers as of the arts, cities would not arise. Also make it a law from me, that he who cannot partake of modesty and justice shall be put to death, for he bringeth plague into the city. For this reason, Socrates, the Athenians and others, when they consult about things which need the skill of the carpenter or other handicraftsman, think that few advisers are enough, and if any one who is not of those thrust himself forward to advise, they will have none of him. Thus do they, thou sayest. And I say 'tis but reasonable they should do this. But when they enter into counsel concerning those things that pertain unto virtue political, which must needs walk alway in the path of righteousness and temperance, then with reason do they bear with any man as a counsellor, considering that all men must partake of this virtue, else there could be no city. 220 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Observations on the Protagoras Myth I Before calling attention to some important points in this Myth, I must allude to a view maintained by some critics — that it is not a Platonic Myth at all, but only a Sophistic Apologue, or Illustrative Story, like Prodicus's Choice of Hercules. This view is stated, and objected to, by Grote in the following passage : ^ — The speech is censured by some critics as prolix. But to me it seems full of matter and argument, exceedingly free from super- fluous rhetoric. The fable with which it opens presents, of course, the poetical ornament which belongs to that manner of handling. It is, however, fully equal, in point of perspicuity as well as charm, — in my judgment, it is even superior, — to any fable in Plato. When the harangue, lecture, or sermon of Protagoras is con- cluded, Sokrates both expresses his profound admiration of it, and admits the conclusion — that virtue is teachable — to be made out, as well as it can be made out by any continuous exposition. Very different, indeed, is the sentiment of the principal Platonic commentators. Schleiermacher will not allow the mythus of Protagoras to be counted among the Platonic myths. He says that it is composed in the style of Protagoras, and perhaps copied from some real composition of that Sophist. He finds in it nothing but a " grobmaterialistiche Denkungsart, die iiber die sinnliche Erfahrung nicht hinaus philosophirt " {Einleitung zum Protagoras, vol. i. pp. 233, 234). To the like purpose Ast {Plat. Leh. p. 71), who tells us that what is expressed in the mythus is, " The vulgar and mean senti- ment and manner of thought of the Sophist ; for it deduces every- thing, both arts and the social union itself, from human wants and necessity." Apparently these critics, when they treat this as a proof of meanness and vulgarity, have forgotten that the Platonic Sokrates himself does exactly the same thing in the Republic — deriving the entire social union from human necessities (Eepubl. ii. 369 c). K. F. Hermann is hardly less severe upon the Protagorean discourse (Gesch. und Syst. der Plat. Phil. p. 460). For my part, I take a view altogether opposed to these learned persons. I think the discourse one of the most striking and 1 Plat. ii. pp. 46, 47. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 221 instructive portions of the Platonic writings ; and if I could believe that it was the composition of Protagoras himself, my estimation of him would be considerably raised. Steinhart pronounces a much more rational and equitable judgment than Ast and Schleiermacher upon the discourse of Protagoras (Einleitung zum Protagoras^ pp. 422, 423).^ I entirely agree with Grote ; and hope that I shall be able in the following observations to show reason for the opinion that this is not a mere illustrative story, designed to put popularly in a picture what might be put abstrusely, but a genuine Myth containing suggestions of the kind which must be put Sia μυθόλο'γίας or not at all. (ffhe mark of a true Myth, it I must be remembered, is that it sets fortj^ the a prior i elem ents I in man's exper ience. An illustrative Story or Allegory, as such, merely makes easier and more pleasant the task of receiving and recalling a posteriori data. This is the broad distinction between Myth and Allegory — a distinction which we must not lose sight of, although we observe that Allegory in the hands of a man of genius, like Plato, or Dante, or Bunyan, always tends to become Myth ; and that there are few Myths, as distinguished from Allegories, which are not built up of parts, some of which are Allegories. While contending strongly for the view that the discourse delivered by Protagoras is a true Myth, not an Allegory, I do not forget that it is delivered by Protagoras. But even this, I submit, is quite consistent with its being a Myth, and that, even if Stallbaum (Note on Protag. 320 c) is right in thinking that Plato is parodying Protagoras's style and borrow- ing from his book irepl της iv αρ'χτ} καταστάσεως. The Timaeus, at any rate, is a Myth, although it is not spoken by Socrates and imitates a style very different from that of the Myths spoken by Socrates. If we are to take the concrete view necessary to the proper understanding of Plato's Myths as they come up individually for critical judgment, we must allow for the dramatic circumstances of each case. The Myth told in the Symposium by Aristophanes, being told by Aristophanes, has ^ Professor Campbell [Politicus, Introd. p. xxxii.) is apparently with the critics from whom Grote differs : — " The myth in the Protagoras ... is meant to convey an idea which Socrates combats, and which Plato evidently does not fully accept. So also the elaborate myth of Aristophanes in the Symposium contains a phase of thought about tli• Origin of Love which is afterwards glanced at as an hypothesis of little value [Sympos. 205 e)." 222 THE MYTHS OF PLATO a comic vein ; similarly, the Myth put into the mouth of Pro- tagoras is somewhat pompous and confused. None the less, these, I would contend, and the other non-Socratic Myths are true Platonic Myths. It is always Plato the Dramatist who, through the mouth of Aristophanes, or Protagoras, or the Eleatic Stranger, sets forth for the Imagination the Universal of which the Scientific Understanding can give no account. II The second observation I have to make on the Protagoras Myth is that it sets forth the distinction between the Mechanical and the Teleological explanations of the world and its parts — the distinction with which Kant is occupied in his Kritik der Urtheilskraft. According to Kant, the antinomy between these two explanations exists for the Deter- minant Judgment (the Judgment which, given the Universal, brings the Particular under it) but not for the Eeflective Judgment (the Judgment which, given the Particular, finds a Universal by which to explain it). The Universal of Teleology — a σκοιτός, or Purpose, to serve which all things in the world are designed by a Personal God — is a Principle, or Universal, which may be posited by the Eeflective Judgment, without contradiction, by the side of the mechanical principle of explanation — indeed, must be posited, for without the guid- ance it affords we could not understand the world at all ; but, for all that, we are not warranted in assuming that it is a prin- ciple objectively existing and operative in the world. Natural objects which we can understand only as results of purpose may very well be due to mere mechanism. " Purposiveness is a concept which has its origin solely in the Eeflective Judgment " ; ^ i.e. it is a Universal which we think of, which we find useful ; but it does not, therefore, exist independently of our thought, as a real cause. What 2 in the end does the most complete teleology prove? Does it prove that there is such an Intelligent Being ? No. It only proves that according to the constitution of our cognitive ^ Bernard's Transl. of the Kritik der Urtheilskraft (Critique of Judgment), p. 18. 2 Bernard's Transl. of the Critique of Judgment, pp. 311, 312, and 260, 261. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 223 faculties ... we can form absolutely no concept of the possibility of such a world as this save by thinking a designedly working Supreme Cause thereof. ... If we expressed ourselves dogmati- cally, we should say, "There is a God." But all we are justified in saying is, " Things are so internally constituted as if there were a God"; i.e. we cannot otherwise think that purposiveness which must lie at the bottom of our cognition of the internal possibility of many natural things, than by representing it, and the world in general, as a product of an Intelligent Cause — a God. Now, if this proposition, based on an inevitably necessary maxim of our Judgment, is completely satisfactory, from every human point of view, for both the speculative and practical use of our Reason, I should like to know what we lose by not being able to prove it as also valid for higher beings, from objective grounds (which are unfortunately beyond our faculties). It is, indeed, quite certain that we cannot adequately cognise, much less explain, organised beings and their internal possibility, according to mere mechanical principles of nature ; and, we can say boldly, it is alike certain that it is absurd for men to make any such attempt, or to hope that another Newton will arise in the future, who shall make comprehensible by us the production of a blade of grass according to natural laws which no design has ordered. We must absolutely deny this insight to men.^ But then, how do we know that in nature, if we could penetrate to the principle by which it specifies the universal laws known to us, there cannot lie hidden (in its mere mechanism) a suflScient ground of the pos- sibility of organised beings, without supposing any design in their production 1 Would it not be judged by us presumptuous to say this? Probabilities here are of no account, when we have to do with judgments of the Pure Reason ; we cannot, therefore, judge objectively, either affirmatively or negatively, concerning the pro- position : Does a Being, acting according to design, lie at the basis of what we rightly call natural purposes, as the cause of the world, and consequently as its author 1 . . . The teleological act of judgment is rightly brought to bear, at least problematically, upon the investigation of nature, but only in order to bring it under principles of observation and inquiry according to the analogy with the causality of purpose, without any pretence to explain it thereby. It belongs, therefore, to the Reflective and not to the Determinant Judgment. The concept of combinations and forms of nature in accordance with purposes is then at least one principle more for bringing its phenomena under rules where the laws of simply mechanical causality do not suffice. For we bring in a teleological ground, when we attribute causality in respect of • ^ Is Kant right here ? This is the great Question of Pliilosophy. 224 THE MYTHS OF PLATO an Object to the concept of an Object, as if it were to be found in nature (not in ourselves),^ or rather when we represent to our- selves the possibility of the Object after the analogy of that causality which we experience in ourselves, and consequently think nature technically as through a special faculty. If, on the other hand, we did not ascribe to it such a method of action, its causality would have to be represented as blind mechanism. If, on the contrary, we supply to nature causes acting designedly^ and consequently place at its basis teleology, not merely as a regulative principle for the mere judging of phenomena, to which nature can be thought as subject in its particular laws, but as a constitutive principle of the derivation of its products from their causes, then would the concept of a natural purpose no longer belong to the Reflective but to the Determinant Judgment. Then, in fact, it would not belong specially to the Judgment (like the concept of beauty regarded as formal subjective purposiveness), but as a rational concept it would introduce into a natural science a new causality, which we only borrow from ourselves and ascribe to other beings, without meaning to assume them to be of the same kind with ourselves. Now let us return to the Protagoras Myth, which I have said sets forth the distinction between the teleological and the mechanical methods of explaining the world and its parts. In the animals as equipped by Epimetheus, Afterthought, "who was not very wise," the world and its parts are pre- sented as products of mere mechanism which are regarded by foolish Afterthought as due to his own design. The qualities with which Epimetheus equips the animals are only those by which they barely survive in their struggle for existence. An animal that is small and weak burrows in the earth, and survives. But to suppose that its power of burrowing was designed with a view to its survival is to forget that it was only Afterthought who conferred the power, not Forethought. To suppose design here is as unnecessary surely as it would be to suppose that gold ore was hidden in the quartz in order that men might have difficulty in finding it. As a matter of fact, small weak animals that burrow are not generally found by their enemies ; as a matter of fact, animals with thick fur do not generally perish in a cold climate ; as a matter of fact, swift animals are not generally caught ; as a matter of fact, ^ The proper understanding of the Doctrine of ίδέαί seems to me to depend on the proper appreciation of the point here put by Kant. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 225 prolific animals generally do not die off fast enough to become extinct. And yet Afterthought takes credit to himself for all this! In such cases there is really no design — no Forethought, — merely the inevitable consequence of blind natural law ; and it is only foolish Afterthought who pretends that there is design — Afterthought who always begins to reflect after the fait accompli, Afterthought the Father, as Pindar says, of Pretence — ταν ^Έττίμαθβος . . . οΛίηνόον Ovyaripa ΤΙρόφασίν} But the pretence of Epimetheus is found out. He has nothing left wherewith to equip Man. He can seem to " design " only where mechanism really does the work — really produces the results which he pretends to produce by his " design." The various modes of structure and habit by which the lower animals correspond with their various environments (and the summary list of these modes given in the Myth shows that Plato has the eye of the true naturalist) — the various modes of animal correspondence — are indeed best accounted for mechanically, without any Epime- thean pretence of teleology. But when we pass from the άνα^καΐον of mere animal survival to the κα\6ν of human civilisation, we pass, Plato in this Myth seems to tell us, into another order of things. The mere survival of animals is not such a great thing that we must think of it as caused by Prometheus — as designed in the true sense ; but the civilised life of Man is too beautiful and good a thing not to be designed in the true sense — not to be an end consciously aimed at by the Creator, who uses as his means the Art which Prometheus gave to a few, and the Virtue which Hermes placed within the reach of all. In short, Plato seems to say in this Myth that a teleological explanation of Man's Place in the Cosmos is indispensable. But let us note that the teleological explanation which he offers is conveyed in Myth. Plato's attitude here towards teleology is not different from Kant's, if allowance be made for the difference between the mythical and the critical ways of expression. " Though not for the Determinant, yet for the Keflective Judgment," says Kant,^ " we have sufficient ground 1 Findar, Pyth. v. 34. 2 Bernard's Transl. of the Grit, of Judgment p. 35. 226 THE MYTHS OF PLATO for judging man to be, not merely, like all organised beings, a natural purpose} but also the ultimate purpose of nature here on earth." It need hardly be said that the assumption or working hypothesis which Kant here makes on behalf of Man does not stand alone. If oaks could speak, they would say that the Oak is "the ultimate purpose of nature here on earth." Ill My next observation is on the account given of the origin of Virtue — άρβτη — in the Protagoras Myth. The gift of Epimetheus is φύσί<; — bodily structure and function, with the instincts and habits thereon dependent, whereby the lower animals correspond accurately, but blindly, with a narrow immediate environment ; the gift of Pro- metheus to Man, whose mere φύσις is not adequate to the wider environment into which his destiny advances him, is Al-t, τέχνη, which, though imparted to few, benefits the whole race by completing φύσις, to borrow the phrase in which Aristotle^ expresses the close relation existing between Nature and Art, φύσις and τέχνη, Plato, too, wishes us to look at the relation as a close one ; for in the Myth Pro- metheus takes up his brother's unfinished work. But άρβτη — morality (as distinguished, on the one hand, from φύσις — natural constitution — the gift of Epimetheus to animals, and, on the other hand, from τέχνη — aquired skill in some depart- ment — the gift of Prometheus to a few men) — άρβτη, as dis- tinguished from φύσις and τέχνη, is distributed by Hermes to all men. All men have implanted in them what may be called " an original moral sense," which education appeals to and awakens. All men are capable of morality as they are capable of speech. Virtue is " learnt " as one's mother tongue is learnt, without any special instruction like that through which some particular art or craft is acquired by a person specially capable of acquiring it. Here the resemblance and difference between Virtue and Art — a subject approached by ^ "An organised product of nature (a natural purpose) is one in which, every part is reciprocally purpose (end) and means." Bernard's Transl. of Crit. of Judgment, p. 280 ; cf. Watson's Selections from Kant, p. 345. '^ Phys. ii. 8, 199 a 15 : δλω? 5k η τέχνη τά μέν ivLTeXei ά η φύσι$ άδυνατ€Ϊ airepyaaaadaL, τά δέ μιμείται. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH /Q^ Plato from many sides — is viewed from yet another side, in Myth, and, therefore, we may take it. /wi th deep insigh t- int^ i its metap h^siral Ίτη] ;>οτΐΓ Art, though it is^the gilt*Oi Pro- metheus, and~-distinguishes Man, as working for consciously realised future ends, from the brutes, which, at most, live in a dream of the present, is still only " a completion of nature," and Man does not yet live the true life of Man under the regime of Prometheus. The gift of Prometheus, indeed, came from Heaven, but it was stolen. The Godlike intelligence of Man employs itself in the pursuit of objects which, though really means under the providence of the Creator to the ultimate realisation of the true human life, are not yet regarded by Man himself as more than means to the convenient life of the dominant animal on earth. Man, having received the stolen gift, conquers the lower animals ; yet still homo homini lupus. But the gift which makes him see, with the eye of justice and respect, his fellow-man as an End along with himself in a Kingdom of Ends — this gift was not stolen, but is of the Grace of God. It is given to all men, or at least is a it/i?^ βρμαων which all may hope in the course of life to find ; and it is given in greater measure to some men than to others. Great teachers of the moral ideal arise, like great poets, specially inspired ; and their power, whether manifested in the silent example of their lives, or in the prophetic utterance of Myth, is felt in its effects by all ; but the secret of it is incommunicable.^ The gift of άρβτη in greater measure is not, indeed, alluded to in the Protagoras Myth, but it is, after all, merely an eminent instance of the gift as described in that Myth. The gift of άρβτή, whether in less or greater measure, is of the Grace of God. Such a doctrine is properly conveyed in Myth ; and the discourse of Protagoras in which it is conveyed is, I submit, a true Myth, because it sets forth the a priori, not, as Schleiermacher and some other critics maintain, a mere Sophistic Apologue or Allegory illustrating and popularising a posteriori data. "As to the myth brought forward by Protagoras," says Schleiermacher,^ " there is no need to number it as some have *See Meno, 99, 100. 2 Introduction to the Protagoras, p. 96, Dobson's Transl. «ce^t THE MYTHS OF PLATO , good-naturedly raising it to an exalted rank, among those of Plato's own ; on the contrary, if not the property of Prota- goras himself, as seems likely, though there is no evidence to confirm the supposition, yet the manner in which Plato applies it makes it much more probable that it is, at all events, com- posed in his spirit. For precisely as is natural to one of a coarsely materialistic mode of thinking, whose philosophy does not extend beyond immediate sensuous experience, the reason- ing principle in men is only viewed as a recompense for their deficient corporeal conformation, and the idea of right with the feeling of shame, as requisite for a sensuous existence, and as something not introduced into the minds of men until a later period." " Not introduced into the minds of men until a later period I" This objection appears to me to be founded on a misunderstanding of what a Myth is and does. It is of the very essence of a Myth to represent as having a history in time what in itself is out of time. The Soul, which is the Subject of all experience in time, is mythologically set forth as an Object or Thing whose creation, incarnation and earthly life, disembodied state and penance, re-incarnation and final purification or damnation, can be traced as events in time. How absurd to draw inferences from the chronology of such a history! Fit is not the historical question. When the mind received the idea of Virtue, whether later or sooner, that Plato is really concerned with ; but the philosophical question, What is the true nature qfVirtue — of the Virtuous Soul — of the Soul itseLf.-et-4ts bestp " ^fce^ouj^j^ato," as Hege l ^ | says, " is nojfl a Thing l(he permanence^ Qrnoiy^^^^^^e^ofJ ' ^ ' " ^^ e}! in^y th this ' ImSperm^gj^ntM έ Tcis indeed no ' which uss, cessarily succession oiy^ ^me^B IS m er that a as a TJiim timSr Myth is a Myth.^ A Myth may be told in painting, or embroidery, or sculp- ,^^ ture, as well as in words ; and I am going to conclude these remarks on the Protagoras Myth by asking the reader to look THE PBOTAGOBAS MYTH 229 at a sarcophagus in the Capitoline Museum on which the mystery of Man's birth and li fe and death is rendered for the eye in a relief rep resenting,^^Svelv enough , the history of the (Butterfly -Sou l and bts Clay Bodyj the handiwork of Prometheus.•^ There sits Prometheus with a basket of clay beside him ; on his knees a little human figure standing, which he supports with his left hand ; while his right hand, holding the model- ling stick, is drawn back, its work finished. On the head of the little human figure Athena lightly sets a butterfly. Behind and above, Clotho spins the thread of life, and Lachesis draws the horoscope on a globe of the Heavens. It is morning, for Helios with his chariot and horses is rising on the left hand. Beneath him is seated Gaia with her horn of plenty; near him lies Oceanus with his rudder in his hand; while the "Wind-God blows through his shell ; and^ihalf hide rougJ among these elemental powers/Eros kiss es Psyche. ^ Now let us turn from the Morning and Day of the sculp- tured Myth, and look at its Evening and Night. On the right of the two central figures, Prometheus and Athena, close by Athena with Chgr butterfly, stands Nigh t, a tall draped woma n, aboyfiL^whom i s^^SuteSe'ln" her^r, witd her veir^ akin^(^ fjiresce niO behinc i her in th e wind^s she ridesl At the feet of Nightlies a Youth, dead, with his butterfly-soul fluttering near. Death, with down-turned torch, is bending over the corpse, and Fate sits at its head frmrolling^ a scroll J on her knee; while the Soul of the Youth, — now a little -winged human form, — led by Hermes, is already on its westward way to Hades. This is the front of the sarcophagus ; and the two ends include the mystery of the front in a larger mystery. On the one end is Hephaestus at his forge, and the fire is burning which Prometheus stole. On the other end the sin is punished — Prometheus lies bound upon Caucasus, and the vulture sits over him; but Heracles, with his bow bent, is coming to deliver him. ^ The versioji of the Myth presupposed by the Capitoline artist is plainly Neo-Platonic. Πη the Myth as Plato has it in the Protagoras, Pr ometheu s does not m ake Man . On the Capitoline sa rcophagus (No.* 446 [13], described by Ή.Q\h\g^;^J^^utιrer durch die qfentl. Sammlungen Tclass. Alterth. in Rom., vol. i. p. 341 ; and cf. Mitche l l, History of Anc. Scidpturc, p. 6&3X he does ; just as, in Plotinus, Enn. iv. ^ΓΤ3 (quoted p. 238 ir^ra), he — not, as in Hesiod, 0. et D. 49 fF., Hephaeatus— fnakes Pandor^ i^ 230 THE MYTHS OF PLATO {Excursus on Allegory) The story of Prometheus, wliether as told in the Prota- goraSy or as represented on the Capitoline sarcophagus, is, I am prepared to maintain, a genuine Myth — sets forth a ^mystery which the scientifi c understanding cannot fath'oS At the same time, it is a Myth which evidently lends itself more easily than those which we have hitherto examined to allegorical interpretation, and, indeed, in Keo-Plato ni c han ds beca me the subject o f very beautiful allegorical interpretation. It would seem, then, that at the Frotagords Myth we have reached the stage in our review of the Platonic Myths at which some connected remarks may be offered on a point which has been already alluded to — the Difference between Myth and Allegory ; and along with Allegory we may con- sider Parable. I remarked a little while ago that a composition which, as a whole, is a Myth, and not an Allegory, is often found to be built up of parts, some of which are Allegories. The Pliaedrus Mvth and the Divina Commedia are compositions of this build. /This partly explains the circumstance that even I the nob lest Myths have so often fallen ^^ easy prey to alle- go rical inter pretation./ Because the parts are plainly Alle- gories, it IS supposed that the whole is an Allegory. And there are no limits to allegorical interpretation, ^^y Myth — nay, any true account of historical events or of natural I phenomena — can be interpreted a s an Alleg ory, setting forth any do^na, religious, philosophical, or scientific.^ The importance of the part played by the allegorical interpretation of Homer in the Greek philosophical schools, of the Old Testament History among the Alexandrine Jews and Christian Fathers, and of the Platonic Myths among the JSTeo- Platonists,^ cannot easily be over-estimated by the historian of ^ * ' The Myths were accepted by common consent as the text for the deepest speculations of the later Platonic schools, and so have contributed, through them, more largely than any other part of Plato's writings to the sum of common thoughts." — Westcott's assays in the History of Religious Thought in the West ("The Myths of Plato "), p. 46. ( THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 231 philosophical and religious thought. As early as the time of Xenophanes^ it was felt that the tendency of the popular mythology was immoml. " Homer and Hesiod/' he says, " have as cribed to the Gods fall things that are a shame and a disgrace among men — thefts 8iii4 adulteries, and deception of one another." • With t his verdict(Plato is in entire agreement / (i? gy>. 378 d) ; but not with the method of allegorical interpre&Si^n (see Phaedrus, 229), which attempted to save both Homer and morality.^ Plato, objecting to the allegorical interpretation of Myth on literary and philosophical grounds, as well as on the practical ground alleged in Rejp. 378 D — that ^hildrenli cannot distinguish between a llegori cal and l iteral me aning, — *i banishes Homer from the educational curriculum, and in lieu of his stories, since children must begin with stories, sub- stitutes newly invented stories — moral^ tales, we may suppose^ for he gives no specimens — in whicl/Gods and human beingsY behave in a manner which can, ami ought to, be imitated,! just as the good people behave in some modern story-books for the young. But in his objection tofthe allegorisation of Homer jpiato stands almost alone. The line generally t aken by th e Greeks after, as well as before, Plato's time was that Homer is an inspired teacher, and must not be banished from the curri- culum. If we get beneath the literal meaning, we find him teaching the highest truth. The allegorical interpretation of Homer began doubtless in the spirit of apology for revered scriptures found to conflict with modern notions ; but it soon became an instrument of historical research and metaphysical speculation.^ Few were content to confine themselves with Plutarch to the plain ethical lessons to be drawn from Homer and the poets as picturing human life and nature — to read, for example, the story of The Intrigue of Aphrodite and Ares, if not simply for the story, at any rate for nothing more ^ He was alive in 479 B.C. ; see Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, p. 111. 2 On the allegorisation of Homer, beginning with Theagenes, see Lobeck, Aglaoph. pp. 155 if. ; the feeling which prompted it is expressed in the aphorism, "Ομηροι ykp -ησέβησβν, ei μτ] ήλληΎόρησβν. ^ — and perhaps also of literary embellishment. "Ion's allusion to his embel- lishments of Homer, in which he declares himself to have surpassed Metrodorus of Lampsacus and Stesimbrotus of Thasos, seems to show that, like them, he belonged to the allegorical school of interpreters" (Jowett's Introduction to the Ion). J 232 THE MYTHS OF PLATO abstruse than the lesson that luxury leads to such intrigue.-^ Such simple teaching did not satisfy either the historians or the philosophers. The Centaurs (Palaephatus tells us) were a body of young men from the village of Nephele in Thessaly, who first trained and mounted horses for the purpose of repelling a herd of bulls belonging to Ixion, King of the Lapithae, which had run wild and done great damage ; they pursued these wild bulls on horse- back, and pierced them with their spears, thus acquiring both the name of Prickers (Kevropes) and the imputed attribute of joint body with the horse. Aktaeon was an Arcadian, who neglected the cultivation of his land for the pleasures of hunting, and was thus eaten up by the expense of his hounds. The dragon whom Kadmus killed at Thebes was in reality Drake, King of Thebes ; and the dragon's teeth which he was said to have sown, and from whence sprung a crop of armed men, were in point of fact elephants' teeth, which Kadmus as a rich Phoenician had brought over with him : the sons of Drake sold these elephants' teeth and employed the proceeds to levy troops against Kadmus. Daedalus, instead of flying across the sea on wings, had escaped from Krete in a swift sailing-boat under a violent storm; Kottus, Briareus, and Gyg^s were not persons with one hundred hands, but inhabit- ants of the village of Hekatoncheiria in Upper Macedonia, who warred with the inhabitants of Mount Olympus against the Titans ; Scylla, whom Odysseus so narrowly escaped, was a fast- sailing piratical vessel, as was also Pegasus, the alleged winged horse of Bellerophon.^ ^ Plutarch, de Audiendis Poetis, c. 4. The de Aud. Poet, is worth careful study in connection with the allegorisation of Homer, against which it is a protest. On the one hand. Poetry is to be read for the entertainment which may be derived from a "good story" simply as a "good story" ; thus Homer bids Odysseus look carefully at the things in Hades, in order that he may go and tell his wife about them — αλλά φόωσδβ τάχιστα XCXaieo, ταύτα 5k ττάντα ϊσθ\ 'ίνα καΐ μετόπισθε Tcy (ϊττησθα ^υναίκί. καΐ yap τούτο χαρίέντω$ "Ομηροι els ττ]ν νεκνίαν eiirev, ώ? yvvaLKo^ άκρόασιν οΰσαν δια δ-ή τό μvθώδ€s (c. 2). On the other hand. Poetry is to be read for the lessons in morality and worldly wisdom which may be learnt from the characters and conduct of the personages portrayed ; but let not the young think that these personages are abstract types — all-good or all-bad ; the poets draw for us real men, mixed of good and bad qualities. Poetry is μίμησι$ ηθών καΐ βίων καΐ ανθρώπων ού τελείων ούδ^ καθαρών . . . άλλα μεμι^μένων ττάθεσι και δόξαίί ψενδέσι, διά δέ εύφϋί'αν αυτούς ττοΧλάκΐί μετατιθέντων πρόί τό κρεΐττον (c. 8). These are the advantages to be derived from Poetry. We must partake of it with caution, however, for it is like the polypus — pleasant to eat, but often gives bad dreams (c. 1). It ought to be noted that, where Egyptian Myths are concerned, Plutarch does not eschew the method of allegorical interpretation ; but see remarks on de Is. et Osir. § 78, in Prof. Dill's Roman Society in the Last Century of the Western Empire, pp. 76, 77. 2 Grote's Hist, of Greece, part i. ch. 16, vol. i. pp. 342, 343, edit. 1862. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 233 While those interested in history adopted this method of " natural explanation " ^ in dealing with Myths, the philo- sophers adopted the method to which it is best to confine the description " allegorical interpretation." Homer's whole story, and the proper names which occur in it, have a hidden religious, philosophical, scientific meaning which it is the work of the method to unfold, by discovering analogies and etymologies. So far as etymologies were concerned, this method probably owed something to the lead given by Plato himself in the Cratylus ; but while Plato's etymologies are put forward playfully, and as it were δ^ά μ.νθο\ο^ία<ζ, the etymologies of the Stoics and other allegorisers of Myth seem to be seriously offered as the meanings which Homer really had in his mind when he used the names. " Magnam suscepit molestiam," says Cicero,^ " et minime necessariam Zeno primus, post Cleanthes, deinde Chrysippus, commenticiarum fabularum reddere rationem, et vocabulorum cur quidque ita appellatum sit causas explicare." Two examples of the Stoic method will be sufficient, with a general reference to Zeller's Stoics, Epicureans, and Sceptics, pp. 334 ff. (Eng. TransL). The One God, of Many J^ames, ττόλυώνυμος, is called Zeus άτΓο του ζην : as manifested in air, is called Hera, from άηρ: as manifested in water, is called Poseidon, from ττόσίς: as manifested in aether, is called Athena, from αίθηρ : and so on.^ " If Hephaestus," says Heraclitus the Stoic, " intended the shield of Achilles to be a representation of this world, what else is thereby meant but that, by the influence of primary fire, matter has been shaped into a world ? " ^ ^ See Zeller's Stoics, EpicureaTis, arid Sceptics, p. 335, n. 1, Engl. Trausl. 2 Cic. de Nat. Deor. iii. 24, 63. ^ Diog. Laert. vii. 147. 4 See Zeller's Stoics, etc., p. 340, Eng. TransL "The Stoics," says Dr. Bigg (The Christian Flatonists of Alexandria, p. 146), "assur'e us that the heathen deities are but symbols of the forces of nature, and turn the hideous myths of Zeus or Dionysus into a manual of physical science." On the general subject of the allegorisation of Homer, both before and after Plato's time, the reader may consult, in addition to Lobeck, referred to above, Mr. Adam's note on Eep. 378 d, 24, with authorities cited there ; Zeller's Stoics, Epicureans, and Sceptics, pp. 334 if. , Eng. Transl. ; Jowett's Dialogues of Plato, Introd. to Rep. p. xxxviii. ; and Grote's History of Greece, part i. ch. 16, from which I extract the following passage (vol. i. p. 344, edit. 1862) : — "It remains that we should notice the manner in which the ancient myths were received and dealt with by the philosophers. The earliest expression which we hear, on the part of philosophy, is the severe censure bestowed upon them on ethical grounds by Ainophanes of Kolophon, and seemingly by some others of his contemporaries. It was apparently in reply to such charges, which /f 234 THE MYTHS OF PLATO The Jews, Palestinian and Alexandrine, before and after Philo's time,^ following the lead given by the Greek inter- preters of Homer, applied the allegorical method to the Old Testament scriptures. One may estimate the length to which allegorical interpretation of the Old Testament was carried by θβρατΓβυταί ^ and others before Philo's time from the circum- stance that even Philo himself was alarmed. The allegorising of the Law, he thought, makes for laxity in the observance of it.^ The wise man will loth seek out the hidden meaning, and observe the letter of the Law. He will allegorise without breaking with old custom.'^ But where the allegorisation, not of the Law, but of the History of the Old Testament scrip- tures, is concerned, Philo proceeds without fear. At once an ardent Platonist and a Hebrew of the Hebrews, he assumed the substantial accuracy of the narrative of events given in the Old Testament from the creation of the world downwards throughout the whole history of his Eace ; and, at the same time, he believed that the history of his Eace was not mere history — it was philosophy, or rather theology, as well as did not admit of being directly rebutted, that Theagenes of Rbegium (about δ20 Β. c. ) first started the idea of a double meaning in the Homeric and Hesiodic narratives — an interior sense, different from that which the words in their obvious meaning bore, yet to a certain extent analogous, and discoverable by sagacious divination. Upon this principle he allegorised especially the battle of the Gods in the Iliad. In the succeeding century, Anaxagoras and Metro- dorus carried out the allegorical explanation more comprehensivelv^^nd systematically ; tho-, ibrmw j:er)j:esenting t |ie mythical Ti^ jflftnag-es lasfmerj mental com^tionsfi nvested wjth^ η and gen dq^ and illustrative" ot"' erhical pr^^^^ts^^^nnHLatter coTTnecting ibhem witA'ViySifeal'^principles and p haenomen a. Metrodorus resolved not only the persons oTZeus, HefoT and Ath^fe^,**!!! also those of Agamemnon, Achilles, and Hector, into various elemental combinations and physical afTronn.jp^^^Qn^^j-^y^|^jjori -n^o ori-.rQr>fnT-oo as cribcd to them as naturai facts.concg^ edj^ der t Ke^ veil ol aTTegory^ Empedocjis, rrodicus', Antisthenes,! Parmemaes" €lSracTel()tB ot Jfontus, and, in a later age, Chrysippus and tha Stoic philosophersgeiisEally, followed nj ^re or less the same principle o f treating! thepopularGods^ a^ allegorical persona ges ; while the expositors ot Homer (such as ■STei3lIffbiOtus3'»Gl§;ucdn, and others, even down to the Alexandrine age), though none of them proceeded to the same extreme length as Metrodorus, employed allegory amongst other media of explanation for the purpose of solving difficulties, or eluding reproaches against the poet." Grote, in a footnote (p. 345, n. 1) to the foregoing passage, calls attention to the ethical turn given to the stories of Circe, the Sirens, and Scylla, by Xenophon, Mem. i. 3, 7, and ii. 6, 11-31. 1 The allegorising Jewish school began two hundred years before Philo (fl. A.D. 39) ; see Gfrorer, Urchristenthum, i. 83. 2 See Conybeare's Fhilo, de Vita Contemplativa, p. 293 : the θεραττβνταί (also called Ικέται, cultores deum — ascetic Jewish congregations or guilds) allegorised the Pentateuch. This was necessary in order to make Gentile converts, who looked for Plato in Moses. 2 See Conybeare's Philo, de Vita Cont. pp. 300, 301. ^ See Gfrorer, Urchristenthum, i. 104. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 235 history. The events recorded were not only true in fact ; they constituted also a continuous revelation of hidden meaning. He looked at the history of his Eace both as a chronicle of actual events, and as a great miracle-play in which dogma was put on the stage of this visible world. This double point of view is very difficult to enter into ; but we must enter into it, so far, at least, as to treat it very seriously, if we are to understand the " tendency " of certain currents of religious and philosophical thought which have prevailed since his day, even down to the present time. Here is a passage from his book de Sacrificiis Ahelis et Caini} in which the allegorical interpretation of " sacred history " reminds us of the method by which not only " sacred history " but tradi- tional dogma is, in our own day, being rewritten as " philosophy " : — For Abraham, coming with great haste and alacrity, com- mands Virtue, Sarah, to hasten and ferment three measures of meal, and to make cakes under the ashes, when God, attended by two Supreme Powers (ήνίκα 6 Qehs 8ορνφορονμ€νο? virh Sveiv των άνωτάτω 8υνάμ€ων), Dominion and Goodness, Himself one in the middle, produced three images in the visual soul {οραηκ-^ Ψ'^Χό\ e^^h of which it is impossible to measure (for His Powers also are not to be circumscribed), but Ithey measure all things. His Goodness is the measure of the good. His Dominion the measure of things sub- ject ; and the Ruler Himself the measure of every thing corporeal and incorporeal. ... It is good for these three measures to be fermented, as it were, and commingled in the soul, that being persuaded of the existence of a supreme God, who surpasses His Powers, and is either seen without them, or appears with them, it may receive impressions of His might and beneficence, and be initiated in the most perfect mysteries (των τελιών μνστι? γβνομΑνη). In the Old Testament history, then, Philo recognises at once a higher, or mystic, and a historical, or literal, sense — ή Βί υτΓονοία^ άττοΒοσις — ή άΧλη'γορία, and ή ρητή Βιη^ησι^''^ The personages in the book of Genesis are at once historical, and τρόττοο ψνχής. Adam is άνθρωττος 'γη'γβνης ; the fact of his existence is historical, but the details of his history are mythical, and must be interpreted allegorically : 1 De Sacrif. Ah. et (Mini, (15), 59, ed. Cohn, p. 173, Mangey. 2 Gfrorer, o.c. i. 84. 236 THE MYTHS OF PLATO thus his rib is μυθώΒβς — nobody can take it literally.^ Noah is justice, Enoch hope, Moses λόγο? ττροφήτης. Similarly, Egypt is the body, Canaan piety.^ Again — and here Philo's Platonism prevails — it was not God, but the λόγο?, who appeared in the burning bush.^ Spiritual men are satisfied, he says, with the truth that God exists ; but the ττοΧλοί need /' an anthropomorphic God. Moses gives God feet and hands, on account of the weak understanding of his readers. This is as it ought to be. Moses is like the physician who must keep his patient in ignorance of the truth. But for the f educated reader such representations of God are dangerous. ' They lead to Atheism, and the only true method of dealing .with them is that of Allegory.^ The allegorical wisdom, the possession of the few wise, is compared by Philo to the Hellenic Mysteries : ταύτα ω μ,ύσταυ κβκαθαρμίνού τα ωτα, ώς lepa όντως μυστήρια τταρα^ί'χβσθβ. Here, of course, Philo borrows directly from Plato,^ who often compares Philosophy, especially when Myth is its vehicle, to initiation, as in Sympos. 209 E, 210 a, and in Phaedrus, 249 c, 250 3."^ But it is only a phrase that Philo borrows from Plato. What a Myth is Philo does not understand. A Myth is indeed a mystery and remains a mystery. Philo and his following are only concerned to make it something under- stood. For the employment of the method of allegorical interpre- tation by the Christian Fathers I cannot do better than refer the reader generally to Dr. Bigg's Christian Platonists of Alexandria, especially to Lecture iv., and to Hatch's HMert Lectures, 1888, Lecture iii., on Greek and Christian Exegesis. To these references I would add a quotation from Professor G. Adam Smith's Modern Criticism and the Preaching of the Old Testament, pp. 226-228 : — The early fathers were interested in the Old Testament mainly for its types and predictions of Christ. The allegorical became the orthodox exegesis, and was at last reduced to a theory 1 Gfrorer, ox. i. 98, 99. 2 Gfrorer, o.c. i. 88. ^ Gfrorer, o.c. i. 87. •* Gfrorer, o.c. i. 97. ^ Philo, de cherubim, Mang. i. 147 ; Gfrorer, Urchristenthum, i. 100. ^ As he does also at the end of the passage quoted above from the de Sacrif. Ah. et Cain. ^ See Couturat, de Platonis Mythis, p. 55. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 237 by Origen, and elaborated into a system by the school which he founded. . . . When the heretics began to outdo the orthodox in allegorical exposition, the latter awoke to the dangers of the habit they had fostered, and loudly proclaimed the need of sobriety and reason in the pursuit of it. But the historical sense of the age was small, and till the close of the 4th century no exegete suc- ceeded in finding his feet on a sound historical basis. [Theodore of Mopsuestia (350-429) was the father of historical exegesis.] To Theodore the types and prophecies of the Old Testament had, besides their references to the future, a prior value in themselves and for the age in which they were delivered.^ It is perhaps worth reminding the reader that the Christian Fathers had high authority for their allegorical interpretation of the Holy Scriptures. St. Paul {Gal, iv. 22-26) had author- ised such interpretation : — It is written that Abraham had two sons, the one by a bond- maid, the other by a freewoman. But he who was of the bondwoman was born after the flesh ; but he of the freewoman was by promise. Which things are an allegory (arti/do ko-nv άλλη-γ ο ρουμάνα) : for these are the two covenants ; the one from the Mount Sinai, which gendereth to bondage, which is Agar. For this Agar is Mount Sinai in Arabia, and answereth to Jerusalem which now is, and is in bondage with her children. But Jerusalem which is above is free, which is the mother of us all.^ In the Philosophy of Plotinus and the !N'eo- Platonic School the allegorical interpretation of Myths— especially of those which describe and account for the Fall and Ascension of Souls after the manner of the Phaedrus Myth and the Discourse of Diotima — holds a position the import- ance of which it -would be difficult for the student of the development of religious thought to exaggerate. Έο more can be attempted here than to give a general idea of the ^ Chrysostom, in his ερμηνεία of Isaiah (vol. vi. p. 17, ed. Montfaucon), took the same line : — ^γώ δ^, he says, ovre ταύτψ ατιμάζω την έξή^ησιν (the alle- gorical), καΐ την έτέραν (the historical) άληθινεστέραν €Ϊναί φημι. Commenting on the new line of exegesis taken by Theodore and Chrysostom, Professor G. Adam Smith brings out its significance in one admirable sentence (p. 231) : " Recognise that the fundamental meaning of the prophecies must be that which they bore to the living generation to whom they were first addressed, and you are at once inspired by their message to the men of your own time." 2 Similarly in 1 Peter iii. Noah's ark, wherein "eight souls were saved by water," is allegorically interpreted as Baptism. In the Old Testament, Hosea (xii. 1-5) allegorises, according^© the writer of art. "Allegorical Interpretation" in the Jewish Eiieycl. f 238 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Neo- Platonic method of dealing with these Myths ; and perhaps the following specimens may be sufficient for this purpose. Plotinus {Enn. iv. 3. 13), adhering to the Orphic doctrine which Plato sets forth in the Phaedrus Myth, speaks of the Descent of Souls into the bodies prepared for them as taking place, for each Soul, at an appointed time : — καΙ άΧΚος dWy 'χρόνος, ου Trapa^yevo μενού οίον κηρνκος καΧοϋντος κατίασι καΙ elaeBv eh το ττρόσφορον σώμα. Their descent, he says, is fated or determined by universal law ; and yet it is free, for, in embodying themselves. Souls obey a universal law which is realised in themselves. They are free, as νους, Intelligence, is free, for they obey the necessity which is that of their own nature : — καΐ 6 μεν ττρο κόσμου νους είμαρ- μενην ε'χευ την του μενειν εκεί όττόσον καΐ ττεμττειν, καΐ το καθέκαστον τω καθόΧου υτΓΟΤΓίτΓΤον νόμω ττεμττεταί• ey/ceiTat yap εκάστω το καθοΧου καΐ 6 νόμος ουκ έξωθεν την Ισ'χυν εΙς το τεΧεσθήναι ϊσ^χ^ει, αΧΧα ΒεΒοταί εν αύτοΐς γ^ρησομενοις είναι καΐ ττερίφερουσιν αυτόν. " This Cosmos, then," he continues, " having many Lights, and being illumined by Souls, receiveth beauty added unto beauty from the great Gods and from the Intelligences which bestow Souls. And this, methinks, is the meaning of that Myth which telleth how that, when Prometheus — that is Forethought — had fashioned a woman,i the other gods did thereafter adorn her : one gave unto this creature of earth and water human speech, and beauty as of a goddess ; and Aphrodite gave unto her one gift, nd the Graces another, and all the other gods added their several gifts ; and she was called Pandora, because that all gave unto her who was fashioned by the Forethought of Prometheus. But Avhereas Epimetheus, who is Afterthought, rejected this gift of Prometheus, the Myth thereby signifieth that the choice of that which partaketh more of the nature of the Intelligible is the better choice. Yea, the Maker is himself bound, for he hath contact of some sort with that which hath proceeded from him, and is there- fore constrained by bonds which are without. But whereas Heracles releaseth him from his bonds, the Myth signifieth that he hath in him a Power whereby he is yet able to attain unto deliverance from these bonds." ^ 1 In Hesiod, 0. et D. 49 ff. Hephaestus, not Prometheus, makes Pandora ; and Prometheus warns his brother not to accept her, but he pays no heed to the warning. 2 Plot. Enn. iv. 3. 14 ; and see A. Ritter, die Psychologie des Plotin (1867), p. 42. Pandora is the World endowed by the Soul with ideal gifts. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 239 Another Myth from which the Neo-Platonists drew largely was that of Narcissus.^ Their interpretation of this Myth hinges on the identification of the " Mirror of Dionysus " with the " Bowl of Dionysus." ^ The Soul remains at peace in its heavenly home, till it sees its own image in the water of this mirror. It plunges into the water to embrace the image, and drinks forgetfulness of its heavenly estate : — ihovra yap, says Plotinus {Enn. i. 6. 8), het τα iv σώμασι, κάλα μητου ττροσ- Tpe^eiv, aWa jvSvTa, ως eiaiv είκονβς καΐ ϊχνη καΐ σκίαί, φβύ^βιν ττρος ifceivo ου ταύτα βίκονβς. el yap τις έττιΒράμοί \αβ€Ϊν βουΧόμβνος ως αληθινον, οία βΙΒώΧου κάλου €ή> νΒατος ο'χρυμίνου, ου Χαββΐν βουΧηθβίς, ως ιτού τυς μύθος, Βοκώ μοι, αΐνίττβται, Βύς βίς το κάτω του ρεύματος αφανής iyeveTO, τον αύτον Βη τρόττον 6 εγρμενος των καλών σωμάτων καΐ μη άφίβίς, ου τω σώματι, Trj Be ψνχβ κατα- Βύσεταυ εις σκοτεινά καΐ άτβρττη τω νω βάθη, ένθα τυφλός iv αΒου μίνων καΐ ενταύθα κάκεΐ σκιαΐς σύνεσται, φευ- ηωμεν Βη φίλην ες ττατρίΒα, άΧηθεστερον αν τις τταρα- κεΧεύοιτο. τις οΰν ή φυγή ; κ.τ.Χ. : and again, in Έηη. iv. 3. 12, he says — άνθρώττων Βε '^^υ'χαί εϊΒωΧα αυτών ΙΒοΰσαι οίον Διονύσου εν κατότττρω εκεί iyevovTO άνωθεν ορμηθεΐσαι ουκ άτΓοτμηθεΐσαι ούΒ* αύται της εαυτών άρ'χ^ης τε και νου. ου yap μετά νου ηλθον, αλλ' έφθασαν μεν μέχρι γης, κάρα Βε αύταΐς εστηρικται ύττεράνω του ουρανού. ττΧεον Βε αύταΐς κατεΧθεΐν συμβεβηκεν, οτι το μέσον αύταΐς ην- ayκάσθη φροντίΒος Βεομενου του εις ο έφθασαν φροντίσαι, Ζευς Βε ττατηρ ελεησας ττονουμένας θνητά αυτών τά Βεσμά 'ποιών Ίτερί α ττονοΰνται ΒίΒωσιν άναιταύΧας εν χρόνοις ΊΓΟίών σωμάτων ελευθέρας, ϊν εχοιεν εκεί καΐ αύται yLvεσθaι, ούττερ ή του τταντος "ψυχή άεΐ ούΒεν τά τ7]Βε ετΓίστρεφομενη.^ Souls, then, descending, at their appointed ^ See Ovid, Met. iii., and Pausanias, ix. 31, for this Myth. 2 See Macrobius, in Somn. i. 12. Q6: " Hoc est quod Plato notavit in Phaedone animum in corpus trahi nova ebrietate trepidantem, volens novum potum materialis alluvionis intelligi, quo gravata deducitur. Arcaui hujus indicium est Liberi Patris crater ille sidereus, et hoc est, quod veteres Lethaeum fluvium vocaveruut,< ipsum autem Liberum Patrem Orphai'ci νουν ύλικόν suspicantur intelligi." Lobeck,' who quotes this passage from Macrobius {Aglaoph. p. 736), criticises it as departing ^ from the original conception of the κρατήρ, which is that of the bowl in which Plato's Demiurgus mixes the ingredients, first of the World-Soul, and then of human souls. ^ See Lobeck {Aglaoph. p. 555, for the place of the κάτοτττρον in the Zagreus Myth ; and Rohde (Psyche, ii. 117) for Zagreus as a type, along with Narcissus,^ of the passage of the Unity o& the World -Principle into the multiplicity of sensible phenomena. 240 THE MYTHS OF PLATO times, come to the water which is the κάτοτττρον Δ^ίονύσον, and enamoured of their own images reflected therein — that is, of their mortal bodies — plunge into the water. This water is the water of oblivion, of Χηθη, and they that drink of it go down into the σττηΧαων — the cave of this world.^ The wise soul drinks moderately ; for to drink deeply is to lose all άνάμνησι,ς of the intelligible world. T he wise soul is t hus the "dry" soul — ξηρή ψυχή, as the phrase of Heraclitus^ seems to be understood by the Neo-Platonists who quote it.^ The dry soul hearkens, in this life, to the genius who accom- panies her in her κάθοδος : but, over all the genii of particular souls, Eros rules as summus genius. Creuzer* mentions a picture in which Narcissus is represented as gazing at his own image in the water, and the Heavenly Eros as standing with a sad countenance behind him. " I^arcissus adolescens," says Ficino,^ "id est, temerarii et imperiti hominis animus, sui vultum non aspicit ; propriam sui substantiam et virtutem nequaquam animadvertit ; sed ejus umbram in aqua pro- sequitur et amplecti conatur : id est, pulchritudinem in fragili corpore, et instar aquae fluentis, quae ipsius animi umbra est, admiratur." The moral ofjtiie Narcissus Myth is : Free thyself by " ecstasy " from lihelife of flux and sensible appearance — escape from the'^Stre^'orPleasure and the Flesh- — ή ρευστή του βνύΧου σώματος φύσις ^ — the Stream of Generation, which is the " Mirror of Dionysus." ^ With the Myth of Narcissus thus allegorised, the Neo- Platonists brought the story of Odysseus into very close relation. Thus the passage quoted above from JEnn. i. 6. 8, in which the immersion of the Soul in the Stream of Sense is described, is immediately followed by a passage in which the deliverance from that stream is compared to the flight of ^ ψ^Χν 'f'*^ δεσ/χόί ro σώμα και τάφοί και 6 κόσμο$ αύτχί σιτηΚαιον καΐ &Ρτρορ, Plot. Εηη. iv. 8. 3 ; and cf. iv. 8. 1, where the doctrine of the Fall or Incarna- tion of Souls, as set forth by Plato in the Phaedrus and TiTnaeus and by Em- pedocles, is reviewed. 2 See Bywater's HeracUti Eph. Reliquiae, Ixxiv. Ixxv. •^ See Creuzer, Plotinus de Pulch. p. xxxvi. ^ Plot, de Pulch. p. Ixiii. ^ Ficinus, in Plat. Sympos. cap. 17, quoted by Creuzer, Plot, de Pulch. p. Ixviii. δ See Creuzer, Plot, de Pulch. pp. Ivi. Ivii. ' I take it that the κάτοτττρον Αιονύσον of the Neo-Platonists is due to a ** conflation " of the Narcissus Myth and the Zagreus-Dionysus Myth. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 241 Odysseus from the enchantments of Circe and Calypso : — Tt? ουν ή φνγη ; καΧ ττώ? άναξόμβθα ; οίον άττο μά'γον }ζ.ίρκη<ί φησίν η }ζ.αΧυψον<; Όδυσσει;? αΐνυττόμενος, Βοκ€Ϊ μοι, μβΐναι ουκ άρεσθεί^;, καίτοι €'χων ήΒονας Bl ομμάτων και κάλΧβι τΓολλώ αίσθητφ σννών. ττατρίς 8τ) ημίν, όθεν ΊταρηΚθομβν, καΐ ττατηρ €Κ€Ϊ. τΐ9 ουν 6 στόΧος καϊ rf ψυ^γη ; ου ττοσΐ Sec Βιανύσαΐ' τταντα^ου yap φίρουσι ΤΓοδε? 67γΙ yrjv άΧΧην α/π αΧΧης' ούΒέ σε Bel ϊττττων ο^ημα η τι θαΧάττιον τταρασκβυάσαι, άλλα ταύτα ττάντα άφεΐναι Ββΐ καϊ μη βΧβιτΕίν, άΧΧ οίον μύσαντα όψιν άΧΧην άΧΧάξασθαι καϊ aveyeipai, ην €'χ€ΐ μεν ττά?, 'χρώνται Be oXiyoi. Similarly, Numenius (quoted by Porphyry, de Ant Nymph. cap. 34) ^ makes Odysseus the image of νους gradually, through various incarnations, freeing itself from the flesh — εικόνα του Bia της εφεξής yεvεσεως ερχ^ομενου, καϊ οΰτως άττοκαθ- ιστάμενου εΙς τους εξω τταντος κΧύΒωνος και θαΧάσσης άττείρους. Again, a Pythagorean quoted by Stobaeus, JEc. Phys. i. 52, p. 1044, ssijs /Ομηρος Βε την εν κύκΧω ττερίοΒον καϊ ττεριφοραν 7raXιyyεvεσiaς Κίρκην 7Γpoσηy6pευκεv, ΉΧιου ιταΐΒα : and Eustathius, on Od. i. 51, says, 6τι την ΚαΧυψώ, ει μεν βασίΧισσα καϊ ην οι yεωypaφoΰvτες τταραΒιΒόασι, μικρά 7Γεpιεpyάζovτaι οι τταΧαιοί. μεταττΧάττονται Βε αυτήν τη aXXηyopιa εις το καθ* ημάς σώμα, ώς συyκaXύ7ΓToυσav εντός Βίκην εΧύτρου τον ψυχ^ικον μάpyapov^ ήτις καϊ αυτή κατεΐ'χε τον φιΧοσοφον 'Οδυσσέα, ώς άνθρωττον ενΒεΒεμενον σαρκι. καϊ μυθικώς ειττεΐν, εν άμφιρύτη νήσω οντά ΒενΒρηεσση, ήτις ομφαΧός εστί ΘαΧάσσης, τουτέστιν εν \jyp(u σώματι οντι, καϊ ώς αν 6 ΤΐΧάτων εϊττη, εττιρρύτω καϊ άτΓορρύτω (Timaeus, 43 α). . . . Έρμου μεντοι, ώς εν τοις μετά ταύτα αΐνίξεται 6 ττοιητής, μεσιτεύοντος, 6 εστί Xoyoυ, yεyovε τής κατά την φιΧοσοφίαν ττοθουμενης ττατρίΒος, ήyoυv του νοητού κόσμου, 6ς εστί κατά τους ΤΐΧατωνικούς ψυχρών ττατρϊς άΧηθής' ομοίως yεyovε καϊ τής ΤΙηνεΧοττης, φιΧοσοφίας, Χυθεϊς καϊ ά'7ΓaXXayεϊς τής τοιαύτης ΚαΧυψοΰς. With words to the same effect Apuleius closes his treatise de Deo Socratis : — " Ήβο aliud te in eodem Ulixe Homerus docet, qui semper ei comitem voluit esse prudentiam: 1 See Creuzer, Plot, de Pulch. p. Ixxii. Κ 242 THE MYTHS OF PLATO quam poetico ritu Minervam nuncupavit. Igitur, hac eadem comitante, omnia horrenda subiit, omnia adversa superavit. Quippe, ea adjutrice, Cyclopis specus introivit, sed egressus est : Solis boves vidit, sed abstinuit : ad Inferos demeavit, sed adscendit. Eadem sapientia comitante, Scyllam praeter navigavit, nee ereptus est : Charybdi conseptus est, nee retentus est : Circae poculum bibit, nee mutatus est : ad Loto- phagos accessit, nee remansit : Sirenas audiit, nee accessit." ^ Beautiful as the Neo-Platonic allegorisation often is, I venture to think that the less we associate it with our reading of Plato's Myths the better. The Neo-Platonists did not understand the difference between Myth and Allegory. Alle- gory is Dogma in picture-writing ; but Myth is not Dogma, and does not convey Dogma. Dogma is gained and main- tained by Dialectic, which, as Stallbaum says (note on Rep. 614 b), " cannot be applied to the elucidation of the subjects with which Myth deals, any more than it can, at the other end of the series, be applied to the elucidation of the particulars of sense, as such." For light in understanding Plato's Myths, it is to the independent creations of other great μυθοΊτοιοί, such as Dante, that we must go, not to the allegorical interpretations of the Neo-Platonists and their like.^ What Plato himself thinks of allegorical interpretation we know from a passage near the beginning of the Fhaedrus (229): — In reply to the question of Phaedrus, whether he thinks that the story about Orithyia being snatched away by Boreas from the height overlooking the Ilissus is a true story, Socrates says, that if he took the learned line, he might answer, " Yes, it may be true that once upon a time a girl called Orithyia was blown by the wind over the cliff and killed." But such rationalism, imposing and ponderous, is I surely not very happy as a method, for if you begin to employ it, where are you to stop ? You will have to rationalise all the stories in Greek mythology, expending a great deal of matter-of-fact cleverness on an interminable task, and leaving 1 Bacon's allegorical interpretation of three myths — that of Pan, that of Perseus, and that of Dionysus — in his de Augmentis Sdentiarum, ii. cap. 13, is worth comparing with the Neo-Platonic examples given above. 2 For Zeller's opinion of the Neo-Platonic interpretation of Diotima's Myth in the Sympos. see his Plato, p. 194, n. 66 (Engl. Transl.). THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 243 no time for anything worth doing. As for himself, he declares that, not yet having satisfied the Delphic injunction, " Know thyself," he should be acting ridiculously if he spent his precious time over the interpretation of these stories : he is willing to receive them as they are told, and believe them just as other people believe them.^ Dr. Westcott, in his charming and suggestive essay on " The Myths of Plato " (the first of his Essays in the History of Religious Thought in the West), to which every student of the subject must feel himself under great obligation, contrasts Myth and Allegory in the following words : — In the allegory the thought is grasped first and by itself, and is then arranged in a particular dress. In the myth, thought and form come into being together : the thought is the vital principle which shapes the form ; the form is the sensible image which displays the thought. The allegory is the conscious work of an individual fashioning the image of a truth which he has seized. The myth is the unconscious growth of a common mind, which witnesses to the fundamental laws by which its development is ruled. The meaning of an allegory is prior to the construction of the story : the meaning of a myth is first capable of being separated from the expression in an age long after that in which it had its origin. It will be understood that I do not agree with the sugges- , tion contained in the last sentence. I do not recognise the competence of interpretation to separate the " meaning " from 1 Grote, Hist, of Greece, part i. ch. xvi. vol. i. pp. 362 ff. (ed. 1862), has re- marks of exceptional value on this passage, and generally on Plato's attitude to the old mythology. "Plato," he says, "discountenances all attempts to transform the myths by interpretation into history or philosophy, indirectly recognising the generic diflference between them. ... He shares the current faith, without any suspicion or criticism, as to Orpheus, Palamedes, Daedalus, Amphion, Theseus, Achilles, Chiron, and other mythical personages ; but what chiefly fills his mind is the inherited sentiment of deep reverence for these superhuman characters and for the age to which they belonged. . . . The more we examine this sentiment, both in the mind of Plato, as well as in that of the Greeks generally, the more shall we be convinced that it formed essentially and insepar- ably a portion of Hellenic religious faith. The myth both presupposes, and springs out of, a settled basis and a strong expansive force of religious, social, and patriotic feeling, operating upon a past which is little better than a blank as to positive knowledge. It resembles history, in so far as its form is narrative ; it resembles philosophy, in so far as it is occasionally illustrative ; but in its essence and substance, in the mental tendencies by which it is created, as well as in those by which it is judged and upheld, it is the popularised expression of the divine and heroic faith of the people." See further, vol. i. pp. 370 if., for a summary of Grote's whole discussion of Greek Myths in part i. of his Hist, of Greece. I am acquainted wifh no discussion of them which appears to me so informing and suggestive as Grote's. 244 THE MYTHS OF PLATO the " expression " of a Myth. I hold that Myth has no dogmatic meaning behind its literal sense. Its " meaning " is, first, its literal sense — the story which is told; and then, beyond this, the feeling which it calls up and regulates. The further one is removed from the age in which a Myth had its origin, the more difficult it must be to recover its " meaning " of this second sort — that is, the feeling which it called up and regulated in its maker and his immediate audience. Our task is not the facile one of reading our own doctrines into a Myth which has come down to us, but the vastly difficult one of entering sympathetically into the life of a prophet in a bygone world. While the conversion of old narratives, mythical or historical, into Allegories has most often been the congenial work of prosaic persons, ά<γροίκω tcvI σοφία χρώμενοι, it has sometimes been taken up by the great poets themselves with happy effect. Let me conclude this part of the subject with one instance of this — Dante's beautiful allegorisation of the story of the three Marys at the Sepulchre : — Mark saith that Mary Magdalene, and Mary the mother of James, and Mary Salome went to find the Saviour at the Sepulchre and found Him not, but found a young man clothed in a white garment, who said unto them : "Ye seek the Saviour ; I say unto you that He is not here ; but be not affrighted ; go and tell His disciples and Peter, that He will go before them into Galilee ; and there shall ye see Him, as He said unto you." By these three women are signified the three sects of the active life, the Epicureans, the Stoics, and the Peripatetics, which go unto the Sepulchre, to wit, this present World, which is the receptacle of corruptible things, and seek for the Saviour, to wit, beatitude, and find it not ; but they find a young man clothed in a white garment, who, according to the testimony of Matthew and also of the others, was the Angel of God ; thus, Matthew saith^ " The Angel of God descended from heaven, and came and rolled back the stone and sat upon it, and his countenance was like lightning, and his raiment like snow." This Angel is the Nobility of our Human Nature which cometh, as it is said, from God, and speaketh in our Eeason, and saith unto each of these sects — that is, unto every man who seeketh beatitude in the active life — "It is not here; but go and tell the disciples and Peter" — that is, those who go about seeking it, and those who have erred from the right way, like Peter who had denied Him — " that He will go before them into Galilee " — that THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 245 is, that beatitude will go before them into Galilee — that is, into the life of Contemplation. Galilee signifieth whiteness] and as whiteness is more full of corporeal light than any other colour, so is Contemplation more full of spiritual light than any other thing here below. And he saith, " will go before " : he saith not, "shall be with you"; thus giving us to understand that God alway goeth before our Contemplation ; here can we never over- take Him who is our highest beatitude. And he saith, "There shall ye see Him, as He said " — that is, there ye shall have of His joy, to wit, felicity, as it is promised unto you here — that is, as it is surely ordained that ye may possess it. Thus it appeareth that we can find our beatitude (which is this felicity of which we speak), first imperfect in the active life, that is, in the conduct of the moral virtues, and then perfect — after a certain fashion — in the conduct of the intellectual virtues.^ Hitherto we have considered the allegorical interpretation of narratives, mythical or historical, which the interpreters found ready to hand. Let us now pass to narratives deliberately constructed for the illustration of doctrine or the inculcation of moral conduct. When doctrine is illus-•*»^ trated with more or less detail, such narratives are best/ called Allegories ; when moral conduct is inculcated, Parables — that term being retained for little vignette -like stories which present some bit of conduct to be carefully noticed, imitated, or avoided. In Plato himself we have examples of deliberate allegorical composition in the Allegory of the "Cave" {Rey. 514 ff.), in that of the "Disorderly Crew" {Rep. 488 A ff.), and in that of the " Birdcage " {Theaet 197 c). The " Choice of Hercules," composed by Prodicus (Xen. Mem. ii. 1. 21 ff.), is another example ; the piece known as "Cebetis Tabula" is another; and the beautiful story of " Cupid and Psyche," told by Apuleius {Met. iv. V. vi.),^ is another. The story of Pandora also, as 1 Conv. iv. 22. "^ Mr. A. Lang, in his Introduction to William Adlington's Translation of the Cupid and Psyche of Apuleius (1566), shows how dependent the maker of an allegorical story often is on Myth, The Allegory of "Cupid and Psyche" is composed on the framework of a Myth which explains a custom— the widely distributed custom according to which the bridegroom must, for some time after marriage, seek the bride secretly in the dark. See also Custom and Myth, pp. 64 ff. Dr. Bigg {Neoplatonism, pp. 128-133) gives a charming epitome of the story, with its interpretation. Referring to Mr. Lang's folk-lore, he says (p. 129), "This artistic composition has very little indeed to do with Hottentots or Zulus. It is really a very elaborate piece of allegory, metaphysics without tears. " I agree with both Mr. Lang and Dr. Bigg. 246 THE MYTHS OF PLATO given by Hesiod {O.D. 49 if.), has much in it which must be ascribed to deliberate intention. The class of Parables, strictly so called, is represented by many of the Parables of the Old Testament and of the Gospels — by stories like "The Prodigal Son," as distinguished from stories like " The Sower," which are really Allegories. There are also narratives with a purpose, which, like The Pilgrim's Progress, are at once Allegories and Parables as dis- tinguished from Allegories. What strikes one most in these narratives originally written to be Allegories or Parables is : How much more eftective they are than old Myths tampered with by rationalism and converted into Allegories. These Allegories originally written to be Allegories, indeed, present doctrine often thinly disguised, but their makers have to exercise creative imagination, not merely scholastic ingenuity. The best of them are true Myths as well as Allegories, and appeal to us, at any rate, by their άνθρω7Γο\ο<γία, if not always by power of calling up Transcendental Feeling — a power which properly belongs to less consciously planned products of genius. Why is The Pilgrim's Progress a Possession for Ever ? Not because it is an ingenious Allegory setting forth doctrine rigorously held by its author; not because it has a good moral tendency, like Plato's tales for children ; but because it is a Myth — an interesting, touching, humorous, mysterious story about people — because its persons, albeit "allegorical," are living men and women, sometimes, like Moliere's or Shakespeare's, active in the dramatic movement of the story, sometimes sketched as they stand, like the people in the Characters of Theophrastus. And I slept, and dreamed again, and saw the same two Pilgrims going down the Mountains along the High-way towards the City. Now a little below these Mountains, on the left hand, lieth the Country of Conceit ; from which Country there comes into the way in which the Pilgrims walked, a little crooked Lane. Here, therefore, they met with a very brisk Lad, that came out of that Country. So Christian asked him From what parts he came, and whither he was going ? Ignor. Sir, I was born in the Country that lieth off there a little on the left hand, and I am going to the Celestial City. Chr. But how do you think to get in at the Gate, for you may find some difficulty there ? THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 247 Ignor. As other good people do, said he. Chr^ But what have you to shew at that Gate, that may iuse that the Gate should be opened to you ? Ignor. I know my Lord's will, and I have been a good liver ; I pay every man his own ; I pray, fast, pay tithes, and give alms, and have left my Country for whither I am going. Chr. But thou camest not in at the Wicket-Gate that is at the head of this way ; thou camest in hither through that same crooked Lane, and therefore I fear, however thou mayest think of thyself, when the reckoning day shall come, thou wilt hear laid to thy charge that thou art a Thief and a Eobber, instead of getting admittance into the City. Ignor. Gentlemen, ye be utter strangers to me, I know you not ; be content to follow the Keligion of your Country, and I will follow the Eeligion of mine. I hope all will be well. And as for the Gate that you talk of, all the world knows that that is a great way off of our Country. I cannot think that any man in all our parts doth so much as know the way to it, nor need they matter whether they do or no, since we have, as you see, a fine pleasant Green Lane, that comes down from our Country the next way into the way. When Christian saw that the man was wise in his own Conceit, he said to Hopeful whisperingly, There is more hopes of a fool than of him. And said, moreover, WTien he that is a fool walketh by the way, his wisdom faileth him, and he saith to everyone that he is a fool. What, shall we talk further with him, or outgo him at present and so leave him to think of what he hath heard already, and then stop again for him afterwards, and see if by degrees we can do any good of him ? So they both went on, and Ignorance he came after. I saw then in my Dream that Hopeful looked back and saw Ignorance, whom they had left behind, coming after. Look, said he to Christian, how far yonder youngster loitereth behind. Chr. Ay, ay, I see him ; he careth not for our company. Hope. But I tro it would not have hurt him, had he kept pace with us hitherto. Chr. That's true, but I warrant you he thinketh otherwise. Hope. That I think he doth, but, however, let us tarry for him. So they did. Then Christian said to him, Come away man, why do you stay so behind 1 Ignor. I take my pleasure in walking alone, even more a great deal than in Company, unless I like it the better. 248 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Then said Christian to Hopeful (but softly), Did I not tell you he cared not for our company ? But, however, said he, come up, and let us talk away the time in this solitary place. Then directing his speech to Ignorance, he said, Come, how do you? How stands it between God and your Soul now ? Ignor. I hope well ; for I am always full of good motions, that come into my mind to comfort me as I walk. Chr. What good motions ? pray tell us. Ignor. Why, I think of God and Heaven. Chr. So do the Devils and damned Souls. Ignor. But I think of them and desire them. Chr. So do many that are never like to come there. The Soul of the Sluggard desires, and hath nothing. Ignor. But I think of them, and leave all for them. Chr. That I doubt, for leaving all is an hard matter — yea, a harder matter than many are aware of. But why, or by what, art thou persuaded that thou hast left all for God and Heaven. Ignor. My heart tells me so. Chr. The wise man says. He that trusts his own heart is a fool. Ignor. This is spoken of an evil heart, but mine is a good one. Chr. But how dost thou prove that ? Ignor. It comforts me in hopes of Heaven. Chr. That may be through its deceitfulness, for a man's heart may minister comfort to him in the hopes of that thing for which he yet has no ground to hope. Ignor. But my heart and life agree together, and therefore my hope is well grounded. Chr. AVho told thee that thy heart and life agree together ? Ignor. My heart tells me so. * "k ^ ^ ^ ^ Now while I was gazing upon all these things, I turned my head to look back, and saw Ignorance come up to the Eiver-side ; but he soon got over, and that without half that difficulty which the other two men met with. For it happened that there was then in that place one Fainhope, a Ferry-man, that with his Boat helped him over ; so he, as the other I saw, did ascend the Hill to come up to the Gate, only he came alone ; neither did any man meet him with the least encouragement. AVhen he was come up to the Gate, he looked up to the writing that was above, and then began to knock, supposing that entrance should have been quickly administered to him ; but he was asked by the men that looked over the top of the Gate, Whence came you ? and what would you have ? He answered, I have eat and drank in the presence of the King, and he has taught in our Streets. Then they asked him for his Certificate, that they might go and shew it to the THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 249 King^ So he fumbled in his bosom for one, and found none. Then said they, Have you none ? But the man answered never a word. So they told the King, but he would not come down to see him, but commanded the two Shining Ones that conducted Christian and Hopeful to the City, to go out and take Ignorance^ and bind him hand and foot, and have him away. Then they took him up, and carried him through the air to the door that I saw in the side of the Hill, and put him in there. Then I saw that there was a way to Hell even from the Gates of Heaven, as well as from the City of Destruction. So I awoke, and behold it was a Dream. Now the day drew on that Christiana must be gone. So the Koad was full of People to see her take her Journey. But behold all the Banks beyond the Eiver were full of Horses and Chariots, which were come down from aboA^e to accompany her to the City Gate. So she came forth and entered the Eiver, with a beckon of Farewell to those that followed her to the River-side. The last word she was heard to say here was, / come^ Lord, to he with thee and bless thee. So her Children and Friends returned to their place, for that those that waited for Christiana had carried her out of their sight. So she went and called, and entered in at the Gate with all the Ceremonies of Joy that her Husband Christian had done before her. In process of time there came a Post to the Town again, and his business was with Mr. Ready-to-halt. So he enquired him out, and said to him, I am come to thee in the name of him whom thou hast loved and followed, tho' upon Crutches; and my message is to tell thee that he expects thee at his Table to sup with him in his Kingdom the next day after Easter, wherefore prepare thyself for this Journey. Then he also gave him a Token that he was a true Messenger, saying, / have broken thy golden bowl, and loosed thy silver cord. After this Mr. Ready-to-halt called for his fellow Pilgrims, and told them, saying, I am sent for, and God shall surely visit you also. So he desired Mr. Valiant to make his Will. And because he had nothing to bequeath to them that should survive him but his Crutches and his good Wishes, therefore thus he said, TL•se Crutches I bequeath to my Son that shall tread in my steps, with a hundred warm wishes that he may prove better than I have done. Then he thanked Mr. Great-heart for his Conduct and Kind- ness, and so addressed himself to his Journey. When he came at the Brink of the River.he said. Now I shall have no more need of these Crutches, since yonder are Chariots and Horses for me to ride 250 THE MYTHS OF PLATO on. The last words he was heard to say was, Welcome Life. So he went his way. The test, indeed, of a good Allegory is that it is also a good Myth, or story, for those who do not understand, or care for it, as a vehicle of doctrine. To this test the Parables spoken by Jesus appear to have been consciously accom- modated. He often spoke to the common people in Parables without interpreting them. These Parables were received by the common people as Myths ; afterwards He interpreted them as Allegories to His disciples. Many of His Parables, indeed, as was suggested above, have no interpretation. Stories like the Parables of the Prodigal Son, of the Eich Man who proposed to build barns, of Dives and Lazarus, of the Good Samaritan, are not Allegories to be interpreted — for they have no "other meaning," — but rather little dramas " which reduce to a single incident what is continually occurring in man's experience." ^ And even those Parables which are Allegories and admit of detailed doctrinal interpretation, such as the Parable of the Sower, have an intrinsic value apart from the doctrine which they convey — the value of pictures in which common things stand reflected — stand as images, or doubles, for our wonder, in another world, under another sky.^ When one looks at Millet's " Sower," ^ it is easy to put oneself in the place of those who heard Parables gladly without asking for the interpretation of them. Let us now look at Plato's two most elaborate " Allegories " - — the " Cave," and the " Disorderly Crew " ; and let us remind ourselves of the features of the former^ by first referring to BepuUic, 532 B, c, where a summary of the whole is given in one sentence : — η he ye, ην δ' εγώ, \ύσι<; re airo των Β€σμών καΙ μeτaστpoή>η άττο των σκιών eirl τα eϊSω\a καϊ το φως καΐ etc του κατα^είου eh τον rfKiov eiravoho^;, καϊ eKel ττρος μεν τα ζωά τ€ καϊ φντα καϊ το του ηΚίου ^ Reville, ProUgom^nes de VHist. des Religions (Engl. Transl. by Squire), p. 110. 2 See Shelley's poem, The Recollection, quoted infra, p. 395, where I attempt to show that a charm like that belonging to leflected images, or doubles, of natural objects — as of trees (or of Narcissus himself) in a pool — enters into the effect produced by the word-pictures of Poetry. ^ In the gallery of the Metropolitan Museum of Art, New York. * Republic. 514 A if. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 251 ψώ? ert αδυναμία βΧέττβίν, ττρο^ Be τα ev vBaat φαντάσματα e^ta καΐ σκοας των όντων, αλλ* ουκ βίΒώΧων σκίας Bl €T6pov τοιούτου φωτός ως ττρος ηΧίον κρίνβον άττοσκιαζο- μύνας, ττάσα αύτη ή Trpay^aTeia των τβγνών, ας ΒιηΧθομβν, ταύτην e^et την Βύναμιν καϊ Ιττανα^ω^ην του βέλτιστου iv '^^Χν '^ρος την του αρίστου iv τοις ουσι θέαν, ωσττερ τοτ€ του σαφέστατου iv σώματι ττρος την του φανο' τάτου iv τω σωματοβι,Ββΐ τ€ καϊ όρατω τόττω. — There is a Cave in form of a long tunnel which, retaining throughout the dimensions of its entrance, runs down, with a steep decline, into the earth. Some way down, where the daylight at last fails, a great Fire is burning, and beyond the Fire there is a low wall built across the Cave at right angles to its direction. Over the top of this wall showmen hold up and move about little images of men and animals. The shadows of these images are thrown on the rock with which the Cave ends some way beyond.^ Facing this end-rock of the Cave and the shadows thus thrown on it are Prisoners bound so that they cannot turn round. These Prisoners, whose knowledge is confined to shadows of images, represent people who have nothing better than second-hand, hearsay knowledge of " particular facts." But the " Philosopher " comes down from the daylight into the Cave, and unbinds some of them, and " converts " them — turns them round, so that they see the showmen's little images, the " realities " of these shadows. These converted ones represent people who have direct, first-hand knowledge of " facts." Some of these the Philosopher is able to lead up the steep floor of the Cave, past the Fire, which is the Visible Sun, and out into the daylight, which is the light of the Intelligible Sun, the Good, the source of existence and true knowledge. At first the released prisoners are so dazzled by the daylight that they cannot bear to look at the things illuminated by it — men, animals, trees — much less at the Sun itself, but can look only at shadows of men and animals and trees on the ground, or reflections of them in water. These shadows and reflections, ^ In the Pitt-Rivers Museum at Oxford there is a Javanese Wayang Kulit, used, in the Historical and Mythological Drama, for the production of shadow- representations. The shadows of puppets (made of leather) are thrown on a screen, the performer manipulatftg the puppets from behind, and working their arms by means of sticks. 252 THE MYTHS OF PLATO however, differ from the shadows seen on the end-rock of the Cave, in being shadows, not of images of real things, but of real things themselves — they represent the diagrams of geometry, and, generally, the symbols and concepts employed in the deductive sciences to express the principles or laws with which the inquiry is really concerned. In time, the eyes of the released prisoners become accustomed to the daylight, and men, animals, trees, the moon and stars, and, last of all, the Sun, can be looked at. We have now reached the end of all education — the direct apprehension of the IBeac, or Principles, which severally, and as connected system, explain particulars, just as the living man once seen " explains " the showman's image of him. I have called the " Cave " an Allegory. It certainly is an Allegory, and is offered as such together with its inter- pretation.^ But when a great poetic genius like Plato builds an Allegory, the edifice, while serving its immediate purpose as an Allegory, transcends that purpose. Plato sees the Cave and makes us see it, and there is much more to be seen there than the mere purpose of the Allegory requires. Perhaps Plato, when he was at Syracuse, saw such a gallery in the stone quarries (there are such galleries still to be seen in the Latomie at Syracuse) lighted up with a fire, and the miners — it may be slaves or convicts in chains — working at the far end with their backs to the fire, while their shadows and the shadows of people and things behind them flitted on the walls. Be this as it may, Plato's Cave is a mysterious place. We enter it wondering, and soon forget, in our wonder, that there is " another meaning." We acquiesce in what we see — the prisoners among the shadows, and the Eedeemer coming down through the dimly-lighted gloom, like Orpheus,^ to lead them up into the daylight. The vision which Plato's ^ See Couturat, de Plat. Myth. p. 51, who regards the "Cave" as an Allegory. Schwanitz, die MytJien des Plato, p. 9, on the other hand, calls the "Cave" a myth, and brings it into close comparison with the Prometheus-and- Epimetheus Myth in the Protagoras : — " Wenn in dem vorigen Bilde (the Cave) auf die verschiedene Erkenntniss der Menschen hingewiesen wurde, je nach dem sie der beschrankenden Fesseln mehr oder weniger entledigt waren, so leitet der Mythus von Prometheus und Pandora die Wahrheit ein, dass von Gott Eins in aller Gemiither eingepriigt ist, an Einem alle Theil nehmen, an der sittlichen Scheu und dem Sinn fiir Gerechtigkeit, den gemeinsamen Banden wodurch Staaten zusammengehalten werden." 2 The book κατάβαση e/s "Αιδου (see Lobeck, Aglaoph. p. 373) may have been in Plato's mind. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 253 " Allegory " calls up is such as his great Myths call up ; it is a vision which fills us with amazement, not a pictorial illus- tration which helps us to understand something.^ Its nearest parallel in literature is that vision which Dante on a sudden calls up before our eyes in Inferno, iv. 46-63 : — Dimmi, Maestro mio, dimmi, Signore, Commincia' io, per voler esser certo Di quella fede che vince ogni errore : Uscicci mai alcuno, ο per suo merto, per altrui, che poi fosse beato ? Ε quei, che intese 11 mio parlar coperto, Kispose : Io era nuovo in questo stato, Quando ci vidi venire un possente Con segno di vittoria coronato. Trasseci Γ ombra del primo parente, D' Abel sno figlio, e quella di Noe, Di Moise legista e ubbidiente ; Abraam patriarcba, e David re, Israel con Io padre, e co' suoi nati, Ε con Rachele, per cui tanto fe', Ed altri molti ; e fecegli beati : Ε vo' che sappi che, dinanzi ad essi, Spirit! umani non eran salvati. The " Disorderly Crew " is also an Allegory and offered as such ; but, like the " Cave," it has an interest independent of its " other meaning." Without being, like the " Cave," an impressive Myth as well as an Allegory, it is still, apart from its interpretation, a bit of highly interesting ανθρωττοΧοηία. Plato makes the crew of a Greek trading vessel live and move before our eyes. And how like the ancient crew is to the modern one ! Let me place Plato's sketch of the Disorderly Crew and the brilliant description in Eothen of the " politics " of the Greek brigantine caught by a sudden squall side by side : — "Imagine," says Socrates, "a shipowner bigger and stronger than all the other men in the ship, but rather deaf, and rather short-sighted, and with a corresponding knowledge of seamanship ; and imagine a crew of sailors all at variance with one another about the steering of the ship, each thinking that he himself ought to steer, although not a man among them has ever learnt the art of steering a ship, or can point to anybody who ever ^ This notwithstanding its tlose connection with the "Divided Line," Rep^ 609 D if. 254 THE MYTHS OF PLATO taught him, or can mention a time during which he used to receive instruction : imagine them even asserting that the art cannot be taught at all, and ready to cut down anybody who says that it can, and themselves always mobbing the shipowner, their master, and entreating him, with every argument they can lay hold of, to let them have the tiller; sometimes, if one faction fails to move him, and another is more successful, the unsuccessful killing the successful or casting them out of the ship, and taking the fine old owner, and drugging him, or making him drunk, or perhaps putting him in irons, and then taking themselves the command of the ship, and using the stores, and drinking and feasting, and sailing the ship as such revellers are likely to sail her ; and, to put the finishing touch to our picture, imagine them praising — describing as a 'true seaman,' a 'true pilot,' a 'man thoroughly qualified in navigation' — any one who is great in the art of capturing the owner by argument or force, and securing the command of the ship to themselves ; and imagine these men finding fault with one who cannot do this, and saying that he is 'of no use' — men who have no conception at all of what the true pilot must be — that one must make a study of the seasons, and the sky and the stars, and the winds and all things that belong to navigation, if one is to be really fit to take com- mand of a ship — men, I say, who have no conception whatever of this — men who think that there is no art of how a pilot shall steer whether some people wish him to steer or not — no art of steering as such — to be studied and learnt. With such a state of things as this on board, don't you think that the truly qualified pilot is sure to be called a ' star-gazer,' a ' mere theorist,' and ' of no use to us,' by sailors in a ship so appointed ? " "Yes, indeed," said Adeimantus. " Then," said I, " I don't think you want to have the simile analysed, in order to understand that it figures a city in its attitude to true Philosophers. You understand that ? " " Yes," said he.i I sailed (writes Kinglake) ^ from Smyrna in the Amphitrite, a Greek brigantine which was confidently said to be bound for the coast of Syria ; but I knew that this announcement was not to be relied upon with positive certainty, for the Greek mariners are practically free from the stringency of ship's papers, and Avhere they will, there they go. * "^ * ^ * * ^ ^ * * ^k ^ The crew receive no wages, but have all a share in the venture, and in general, I believe, they are the owners of the 1 Hep. 488 A ff. 2 ^jothen, ch. vi. THE PROTAGORAS MYTH 255 whole^fmght ; they choose a captain to whom they entrust just po#er enough to keep the vessel on her course in fine weather, but not quite enough for a gale of wind ; they also elect a cook and a mate. We were nearing the isle of Cyprus, when there arose half a gale of wind, with a heavy, chopping sea. My Greek seamen considered that the weather amounted, not to a half, but to an integral gale of wind at the very least ; so they put up the helm, and scudded for twenty hours. \Vhen we neared the mainland of Anadoli, the gale ceased, and a favourable breeze springing up, soon brought us off Cyprus once more. Afterwards the wind changed again, but we were still able to lay our course by sailing close-hauled. We were at length in such a position, that by holding on our course for about half an hour, we should get under the lee of the island, and find ourselves in smooth water, but the wind had been gradually freshening ; it now blew hard, and there was a heavy sea running. As the grounds for alarm arose, the crew gathered together in one close group; they stood pale and grim under their hooded capotes like monks awaiting a massacre, anxiously looking by turns along the pathway of the storm, and then upon each other, and then upon the eye of the Captain, who stood by the helms- man. Presently the Hydriot came aft, more moody than ever, the bearer of fierce remonstrance against the continuing of the struggle; he received a resolute answer, and still we held our course. Soon there came a heavy sea that caught the bow of the brigantine as she lay jammed in betwixt the waves ; she bowed her head low under the waters, and shuddered through all her timbers, then gallantly stood up again over the striving sea with bowsprit entire. But where were the crew ? It was a crew no longer, but rather a gathering of Greek citizens, — the shout of the seamen was changed for the murmuring of the people — the spirit of the old Demos was alive. The men came aft in a body, and loudly asked that the vessel should be put about, and that the storm be no longer tempted. Now, then, for speeches : — the Captain, his eyes flashing fire, his frame all quivering with emotion, — wielding his every limb, like another and a louder voice, — pours forth the eloquent torrent of his threats, and his reasons, his commands, and his prayers ; he promises — he vows — he swears that there is safety in holding on — safety, if Greeks will he brave I The men hear and are moved, but the gale rouses itself once more, and again the raging sea «omes trampling over the timbers that are the life of all. The fierce Hydriot advances one step nearer 256 THE MYTHS OF PLATO to the Captain, and the angry growl of the people goes floating down the wind ; but they listen, they waver once more, and once more resolve, then waver again, thus doubtfully hanging between the terrors of the storm and the persuasion of glorious speech, as though it were the Athenian that talked, and Philip of Macedon that thundered on the weather bow. Brave thoughts winged on Grecian words gained their natural mastery over terror; the brigantine held on her course, and smooth water was reached at last. Let me close these remarks on the relationship between " Myth " and " Allegory " with a reference to " Eitual," in which the characteristics of both seem to be united. A " ritual performance " or " rite " is made up of " symbols." ^ A symbol is a thing, or an act, taken to represent something else. That something else — generally something of great importance — may be a transaction (such as a sale of land, symbolised in the Koman law by the act of transferring a clod of earth), or a belief (such as the doctrine of baptismal regeneration, symbolised by sprinkling with water), or a concept (such as that of justice, symbolised by a figure holding an even balance), or a nation (symbolised by its flag). In most cases the symbol has some analogical resemblance, close or remote, to that which it represents ; in some cases it is a badge which has for some other reason become attached. The habit of symbolic representation is one of the most primitive and persistent tendencies of human nature. It was present in the first efforts of language, and the highest flights of science are still entirely dependent on the development of it ; while without the development of it in another direc- tion there could have been no poetry — the primrose would always have been but the yellow primrose; and even no courtesy of manners — everybody would always have called a spade a spade. Now, a ritual performance, or rite, is a composition made up of symbols so put together as to produce solemn feeling in those who celebrate and assist. This effect produced is a massive experience of the whole, and may be, indeed ordi- narily is, received without conscious attention to the signifi- cance of the separate parts — the symbols which together 1 See Reville, ProUgomhics de VHist. des Religions, p. 125 (Eng. Translation by Squire). ΎΈΕ PROTAGORAS MYTH 257 BM-k^^^i^wvhole rite. The rite, if effectually received, is received devoutly as a Myth, not critically apprehended as an Allegory. In its origin and composition it is an Allegory — a mosaic of symbols ; but as time goes on this is largely lost sight of ; the corporate genius of the religious society to which it belongs transforms it for the devout into a Myth. Plato compares that enthusiastic Philosophy, of which Myth is the vehicle, to the Mysteries.^ The devout went to Eleusis, not to get doctrine out of allegorical representations, but to have their souls purified by the awe of the " Blessed Sights " presented in the acted Myth. The procession in Furgatorio, xxix., like Ezekiel's visions, to which it is indebted, is an elaborately ordered series of symbolical creatures and objects ; in the fresco on the left wall of the Spanish Chapel of S. Maria Novella in Florence, every figure, either in itself, or in the position which it occupies in the group, is a symbol. It is true, of course, that to appreciate the beauty of either composition fully one must have at least a general acquaintance with the meaning of the symbols employed ; yet finally it is as a great spectacle that the procession of the twenty-ninth Canto of the Pur gator io or the fresco in the Spanish Chapel appeals to one. Indeed, it is because it so appeals that one is anxious to spell out the symbolical meaning of its separate parts, so that, having spelt this patiently out, one may find one's self all the more under the enchantment of the whole which transcends the sum of its parts so wondrously.^ Similarly, to take a third instance, it is because the Story, in the Second Book of the Fairy Queen, of the Adventures at the Castle of Medina, is very readable as a story, and contains beautiful passages of poetry, that we ^re pleasurably interested in following its elaborate translation of the dry Aristotelian doctrine of " Mean and Extremes " into pictures. I would add that the effect produced by a great professedly allegorical composition like the procession in Furgatorio, xxix., or the Spanish Chapel fresco, is sometimes produced by a poem — sometimes even by a single line or stanza of poetry — in which the poet's art, instead of definitely ^ See supra, p. 236. 2 The symbolism of the fres«o alluded to above is dealt with by Ruskin in his Mornings in Floreiue, iv. and v. υ 258 THE MYTHS OF PLATO presenting, distantly suggests a system of symbols. A symbol or system of symbols definitely presented is often enough a mysterious thing ; but a symbol or system of symbols distantly suggested " teases us out of thought," and arouses in no ordi- nary degree that wonder, at we know not what, which enters into the effect produced by Poetry as such. I do not think that a better example of what may be called suppressed symbolism, and of its wonderful poetical effect, could be found than that afforded by Dante's canzone beginning — Tre donne intorno al cor mi son venute ^ — a poem on which Coleridge's record of its effect upon himself is the best commentary. He begins ^ by describing it as " a poem of wild and interesting images, intended as an enigma, and to me an enigma it remains, spite of all my efforts." Then, in an entry dated Eamsgate, Sept. 2, 1819, he writes: " I hegin to understand the above poem (Tre donne intorno al cuor mi son venute, etc.), after an interval from 1805, during which no year passed in which I did not re-peruse, I might say, construe, parse, and spell it, twelve times at least — such a fascination had it, spite of its obscurity ! It affords a good instance, by the bye, of that soul of universal significance in a true poet's composition, in addition to the specific meaning." * Canzone xx. p. 170, Oxford Dante. '^ Anima Poetae, from the unpublished notebooks of S. T. Coleridge, edited by E. H. Coleridge, 1895, p. 293. THE TIMAEUS Context The subject of the Timaeus is the Creation of the Universe {soul and hody) and of Man (soul and body). The speaker in whose mouth the whole Discourse, or Myth, treating of this subject is put is Timaeus, the great Pythagorean Philosopher of Locri in Italy. The Discourse, or Myth, is part of the general scheme which is worked out in the Trilogy consisting of the Eepublic, Timaeus, and Critias. The assumed chronological order of the pieces is Kepublic, Timaeus, Critias : i.e. the Conversation at the house of Cephalus is repeated next day by Socrates to Timaeus, Critias, Hermocrates, and another — this is the Eepublic; the day after that again, Socrates, Timaeus, Critias, and Hermocrates meet, and the Con- versation and Discourse which constitute the Timaeus are held, followed by the Myth related by Critias in the unfinished piece which bears his name. Thus we have first an account of Mans education ; then an account of his creation ; and lastly the story of the Great War for which his education fits him. But, of course, the logical order is Timaeus, Eepublic, Critias : — God, because he is good, makes, in his own image, the Universe of which Man is part — not, however, a mere part, but a part which, after a fashion, is equivalent to the whole, in so far as it adequately represents the vjhole — a microcosm in the macrocosm. Man, as microcosm, is an image of God as adequate as the great Cosmos itself is; and, like God whose image he is, is a creator — makes in turn a Cosmos, the State. We have thus the analogy : — God : Cosmos : : Man : State. Upon God's creation of the Cosmos, in the Timaeus, there follows, in order, Man's creation of the State, in the Eepublic ; while the Critias comes last ivith the representation of the State performing the work for which it was created. 259 260 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Timaeus 29 D-92 c 29 D Αά'γωμεν Βή, Βί rjvrcva αΐτίαν ^eveaiv καΐ το τταν roBe Ε ό ξννιστας ξννβστησβν. ά'γαθος ην, αηαθω δέ ούδεί? ττβρί ονΒβνος ovBeTTore iyylyveraL φθόνος' τούτου δ' €λ:το9 ων ττάντα 6 τι μάΧίστα η^ν€.σθαί ββουΚηθη τταραττΧησια ίαυτω. 30 βουΧηθβΙς yap 6 θβος ayaOa μβν ττάντα, ψλανρον Be μηΒβν elvai κατά Βνναμιν, ούτω Βη τταν, όσον ην όρατόν, τταραΧαβων ουχ ησυγίαν ayov, άλλα κίνονμβνον '7ΓΧημμ€Χως καΐ ατάκτως, βίς τάξιν αντο rjyayev €Κ της αταξίας, ηyησάμevoς €Κ€Ϊνο τούτον ττάντως άμβινον, θέμις Be οΰτ ην οΰτ €στί τω άρίστω Βραν αΧΧο ττΧην το κάΧΧιστον. Β XoyL•σάμ€voς ουν βνρισκβν €Κ των κατά φύσιν ορατών ovBev άνόητον τον νονν 6'χοντος οΧον οΧου κάΧΧιον βσβσθαί ττοτβ epyov, νουν Β αν χωρίς ψν^ής άΒύνατον 7Γapay€veσθaι τω. Βίά Βη τον Xoyiapx>v TovBe νονν μ€ν iv ψν'χτ}, •ψνχην Be ev σώματι ξννιστάς το τταν ξvveτeκτaίveτo, οττως ο τι κάΧΧιστον €Ϊη κατά φύσιν άριστον τ€ epyov ά7Γeιpyaσμevoς. όντως ονν Βη κατά Xoyov τον €ΐκ6τα Bei Xeyeiv TOvBe τον κόσμον ζώον βμψνχον evvovv τ€ τη άΧηθ€ία Βιά την τον θeov C yeveσθaι ττρόνοιαν. Τούτου δ* ύττάρχοντος αν τά τούτοις €φ€ξής ήμϊν XeKTeov, τίνι των ζώων αντον eh ομοιότητα 6 ξννιστάς ξvveστησe, των μίν ονν ev μέρονς etBei ^Γeφvκό- των μηΒ€νι κaτaξιώσωμev ' aTeXei yap €θΐκος ovBev ττοτ αν yevoiTo καΧον ον Β €στι τάΧΧα ζώα καθ^ ev καΧ κατά yevη μόρια, τούτω -πάντων όμοιότατον αντον elvai τιθώμev. τά yap Βη νοητά ζώα ττάντα eKelvo ev €αντώ ττepΐXaβov e^ei, Kaeairep oBe 6 κόσμος ημάς οσα Τ6 αΧΧα θρέμματα D ξvveστηκev ορατά. τω yap τών νοονμένων καΧΧίστω και THE TIMAEUS 261 Translation Let the cause of the creation of this Universe be declared, to wit, that the Maker thereof was Good ; with the Good there is no grudging of aught at any time : wherefore, being altogether without grudging, God wished all things to be made as like unto Himself as might be. Now God, wishing that all things should be good so far as might be, and nothing evil, having received all that was Visible into His hands, and perceiving that it was not at rest but moved without measure and without order, took and brought it out of that disorder into order, thinking that this state was altogether better than that. For He Who is Best might not then — nor may He now — do aught save that which is most excellent. Wherefore He took thought and found out that, amongst those things which are by nature Visible, no work which is without Keason would ever, in the comparison, be fairer than that which hath Keason ; and again, that Keason could not, without Soul, come and abide with any- thing. For this cause He put Keason in the Soul, and Soul in Body, when he fashioned the Universe ; to the end that the creature of his workmanship might be the fairest by nature and the most excellent. Our discourse, then, following alway the way of likelihood, hath brought us thus far — that this Universe is a Living Creature, which hath in truth gotten Soul and Keason through the Providence of God. Next must we tell in the likeness of what Living Creature the Maker made it. Unto none of those creatures which are by nature Parts of the Whole let us compare it ; for naught fair could ever come forth in the likeness of that which is imperfect ; but unto That whereof the living creatures, severally and according to their kinds, are parts must we deem it most like. Now That containeth in itself all Intelligible Creatures, even as this Universe cointaineth us and all his other nurslings which were created to be Visible : for unto That which is the 262 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Kara iravra τβλβω μάλιστα αυτόν 6 θβος ομοίωσαν βουλή- θβΐς ζώον €V ορατόν, ττάνθ^ οσα αυτοΰ κατά φύσιν ξυ'^^^νη 31 ζωα €ντος e^ov ίαυτοΰ, ξυνέστησβ. Πότβρον ουν ορθώς eva ούρανον 7Γροσ€ΐρήκαμ€ν, ή ττολλούς καΐ απείρους λβ^ζΐν ην 6ρθ6τ€ρον ; €va, elirep κατά το τταρά^α^μα ΒεΒημιουρ^ημάνος €σται. το yap ττερύχ^ον ττάντα οττόσα νοητά ζωα, μεθ^ €Τ6ρου δεύτερον ουκ αν ττοτ €Ϊη* τταλι,ν yap αν βτερον elvai το 7Γ€ρ\ έκείνω Beoi ζώον, ου μέρος αν εϊτην έκείνω, καΐ ουκ αν €τι εκείνοιν, αλλ' εκείνω τω ττερίβγοντι, τοΚ αν άφωμοιωμβνον λeyo^,τo ορθοτβρον. ϊνα ουν τόΒβ κατά την Β μόνωσίν ομοιον η τω τταντελεΐ ζωω, Βιά ταύτα οΰτε Βυο οΰτ άττείρους εττοίησεν 6 ττοιών κόσμους, αλλ' εις οΒε μovoyεvης ουρανός yεyovώς εστί τε καΐ ετ εσται. ****** 82 Β fcal Βιά ταύτα εκ τε Βη τούτων καΐ τοιούτων και τον C αριθμόν τεττάρων το του κόσμου σώμα εyεvvηθη Βι άvdλoyiaς όμoλoyησav, φιλίαν τε εσχ^εν εκ τούτων, ώστ εις ταύτον αύτω ξυνελθον αλυτον ύττό του άλλου πλην ύττο του ξυνΒησαντος yεvεσθaι, Ύών Βε Βη τεττάρων εν όλον εκαστον εϊληφεν ή του κόσμου ξύστασις' εκ yap ττυρος τταντος ΰΒατός τε και άερος και yής ξυνεστησεν αύτον ό ξυνιστάς, μέρος ούΒεν ούΒενος ούΒε Βύναμιν έξωθεν ύττολι- D ττών, τάΒε Βιανοηθείς, ττρώτον μεν ϊνα όλον 6 τι μάλιστα 33 ζώον τελεον εκ τελεων τών μερών εϊη, ττρος Βε τούτοις εν, άτε ουχ υττόλελειμμενων εξ ων άλλο τοιούτο yivoir αν, ετι Βε ινα ώγήρων καΐ άνοσον η, κατανοών, ώς ξυνιστάμενά τω ^ σώματι θερμά και ψυχ^ρά και ττάνθ , οσα Βυνάμεις ^ For ξυνιστάμΐνά τφ read ξυστατφ. THE TIMAEUS 263 fairest of Things Intelligible and altogether perfect did God wish to liken it ; wherefore made He it a Living Creature, One, Visible, having in itself all the Living Creatures which are by nature kin unto it. Have we rightly called the Heaven One ? Or were it more right to say that there are Heavens many — nay, infinite in number ? One Visible Heaven there must be, if it is to be fashioned according to the pattern of That which, inasmuch as it con- taineth all Intelligible Creatures which are, could never be a second with another ; for if it were a second with another, then must there be another Creature including these two, whereof they would be parts ; and it would no longer be right to say that this Visible Universe was made after their likeness, but rather after the likeness of That which included them. Wherefore that this Universe might be One only, like unto the One only, All-perfect, Living Creature, the Maker made neither two Universes nor Universes infinite in number, but this One Only Begotten Heaven which was made, and is, and ever shall be. For this cause, and out of these elements, being of such sort and four in number, was the Body of the Universe brought forth at one with itself through the proportional dis- position of elements. Whence also it got Love, so that it was knit together with bonds which cannot be loosed, save by Him Who did bind. Now, the making of the Universe took up the whole of each of the four elements: for the Maker of the Universe made it of all the fire that was, and all the water, and all the air, and all the earth, and left not any part or virtue of any of these without ; to the end, first, that it might be a Living Creature, Whole, so far as might be, and Perfect, with the parts thereof perfect; and secondly, that it might be One Only, since naught was left over of which another like unto this could be made; and thirdly, that it might be without old age or disease; for He knew that if things hot and cold, and all such as have strong powers, encompass the composite 264 THE MYTHS OF PLATO υσγυρα<ζ €^et, ττβρΰστάμβνα βξωθβν, και ΤΓροσττίτΓΤοντα άκαίρω<;, Xvec καί νόσους yrjpaf; re eirayovra φθίνβιν ττοιβΐ. * * % * * * 33 Β Έ,χτιμα δε βΒωκβν αύτω το ττρβττον καί το ξυγγ€ν€<ζ. τω Se τα ττάντ iv αύτω ζώα Treptey^eiv μεΧΧοντι ζώω ττρβττον αν €Ϊη σχ^ημα το ττβρίβίΧηφος iv αντω ττάντα, οττοσα σχήματα. 8ώ καΐ σφαίρο€ΐΒ€<ζ, €κ μέσου ττάνττ] ττρος τας τβΧβυταζ ϊσον άττάχ^ον, κυκΧοτβρβς αύτο βτορνβύ- σατο, ττάντων τέλβώτατον όμοίότατόν Τ€ αύτο βαυτω σχ^ημάτων, νομίσα<ζ μνρίω κάΧΚιον ομοίον ανόμοιου. Αβΐον Be Βη κύκΧω τταν βξωθβν αύτο άττηκριβούτο, ττοΧλών χάριν. C ομμάτων Τ€ yap βττβΒβΐτο ούΒεν, ορατον yap ούΒβν ύττβλεί- ττ€Τ0 βξωθεν ούΒ' άκοή<ζ, ούΒβ yap άκουστόν ττνβύμά re ούκ ην ττβρίβστος Ββόμβνον άναττνοής. ούΒ^ αύ τίνος eVtSee? ην 6pyάvoυ σγβΐν, ω την μβν eZ? ίαυτο τροφην Βεξοίτο, την Be ττρότβρον βξίκμασμίνην άττοττεμψοί ττάΧιν aTTrjet re yap ovBev ούΒε ττροσ^ειν αύτω ττοθέν ούΒβ yap ην. αύτο yap βαυτω τροφην την βαυτού φθίσιν τταρέχον καϊ ττάντα iv D βαυτω και ύφ^ βαυτού ττάσγον καϊ Βρών iK τβχνης yeyovev ηyησaτo yap αύτο ό ξυνθβΙ<ζ ανταρκβς ον αμβινον βσβσθαι μαΧΚον η ττροσΒββς άΧλων. γειρών Be, ah οΰτβ Χαββΐν οΰτβ αύ TLva άμύνασθαι χρβία τις ην, μάτην ούκ ωβτο Ββΐν αύτω ττροσάτττβίν, ούΒ6 ττοΒών ούΒβ ολω? της ττβρί την 34 βάσιν ύττηρβσίας. κίνησιν yap άττβνβιμβν αύτω την του σώματος οίκβίαν, των βτττά την ττβρϊ νουν και φρόνησιν μάλιστα ούσαν. Βιο Βη κατά ταύτα iv τω αύτω καϊ iv βαυτω TTepiayayiov αύτο iττoίησe κύκΧω κινβΐσθαι στρβφο- μβνον, τας Ββ βξ άττάσας κινήσεις άφβΐΧε καϊ άττΧανβς άττ6ιpyάσaτo iκeίvωv. iTTi Be την ττβριοΒον ταύτην άτ ούΒβν ΤΓοΒών Beov άσκβΧβς καϊ άττουν αύτο iyevvησev. Οΰτος Βη ττας οντος άβϊ Xoyισμoς θεού ττβρϊ τον ττοτβ THE TIMAEUS 265 body from without, and strike against it unseasonably, they dissolve it and bring disease and old age upon it, and so cause it to decay. That shape likewise gave He unto it which is fit and proper. Inasmuch, then, as that shape which comprehendeth in itself all the shapes is fit for the Living Creature which should contain in itself all Living Creatures, for this cause did He turn it to be like a ball, round, with boundary at every point equally distant from centre. Thus gave He unto it that which of all shapes is the most perfect, and most like unto itself, deeming that which is like unto itself fairer by far than that which is unlike. Moreover, without He made it perfectly smooth all round, for reasons many : — eyes it needed not, because nothing visible was left remaining without ; nor ears, because there was nothing without audible ; nor was there air round about it that it should breathe ; nor did it need to have any organ for the taking in of food, or for the putting out of that wherefrom the juices were already expressed ; for nothing went forth, and nothing came unto it from anywhere ; for without there was nothing. Yea, it was fashioned cunningly that it should afford nourishment unto itself, through the wasting of itself, and should receive and do all within itself and through itself; for He Who made it thought that if it were sufficient unto itself, it would be better than if it had need of other things added unto it. Wherefore, inasmuch as it needeth not hands for taking hold of aught or withstanding any adversary. He deemed it not meet to give unto it hands to no purpose, nor feet, nor any instrument of walking ; for the motion that He allotted unto it was the motion proper unto such a body, to wit, that one of the Seven Motions which appertaineth most unto Eeason and Understanding. Where- fore He turned it round and round, with the same quickness, in the same place, about itself ; but the other motions, all save circular motion. He took away from it, and stablished it with- out their wanderings. Inasmuch, then, as for this revolution there was no need of feet. He created it without legs and feet. Thus did God, Who is alway, reason with Himself concern- 266 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Β €σομ€νον Oeov Xoyiadel'; Χβΐον καί ομαΧον ττανταγΎ) re €Κ μβσον ϊσον καΐ 6\ον καί reXeov €Κ τέλέων σωμάτων σώμα €7Γθίησ€. ψνχ^ην δε eh το μέσον αύτον θείς Sia 'ίταντος Τ€ €T€LV€ καΐ €Τί βξωθεν το σώμα αύττ) 7Γ€ρί€/€αΚνψ€ τανττ), καΐ κύκ\ω Βη κνκΚον στρεφόμβνον ονρανον €va μόνον ερημον κατέστησε, Βν άρετην Βε αύτον αύτω Βυνάμενον ζν^^ί- ^νεσθαι καΐ ούΒενο^ί έτερου ττροσΒεομενον, ^νώριμον Βε κα\ φίΧον Ικανώς αύτον αύτω. Bca ττάντα Βη ταύτα εύΒαίμονα θεον αύτον ε'γεννησατο, Ύην Βε Βη yjrv^rjv ουχ ώ? νυν C ύστέραν ετηγειρουμεν \ε<γει,ν, όντως εμη'χανησατο καΐ 6 θεός νεωτεραν ού yap αν άρ'χεσθαι ττρεσβντερον ύττο νεωτέρου ξυνερξας εϊασεν ****** ψυχ^ην σώματος, ώς Βεσττότιν καϊ άρξουσαν άρξομενον, 36 ξυνεστησατο εκ τώνΒε τε καϊ τοιωΒε τρόττω. της αμέριστου καϊ άεΐ κατά ταύτα ε-χούσης ουσίας καϊ της αΰ ττερί τα σώματα ^υ^νομενης μεριστης τρίτον εξ άμφοΐν εν μέσω ξυνεκεράσατο ουσίας εΙΒος, της τε ταύτού φύσεως αύ ττερο ^ καϊ της θατερου. ****** καϊ τρία Χαβών αύτα οντά συνεκεράσατο εΙς μίαν ττάντα ΙΒεαν, την θατερου φύσιν Βύσμικτον ονσαν εΙς ταύτον Β ξυναρμοττων βία. μι^νύς Βε μετά της ουσίας καϊ εκ τριών ΤΓΟίησάμενος εν ττάΧιν οΧον τούτο μοίρας όσας ττροσήκε Βιενει,μεν, εκάστην Βε εκ τε ταύτού καϊ θατερου καϊ της ουσίας μεμυ^μενην. * * * * * * ^ at ττέρι om. THE TIMAEUS 267 ing the god who should be, and made him to be smooth, and even, with boundary at every point at equal distance from the centre — a Body whole and perfect, composite of bodies perfect. And in the midst thereof He put Soul, and spread it throughout the whole, and also wrapped the Body round about on the outside therewith ; and made the Universe a revolving sphere, one only, and solitary, but, by reason of the virtue which belonged unto it, able to consort with itself, having need of no other, being itself acquaintance and friend unto itself in full measure. A god, then, in regard of all these things blessed, begat He it. But, albeit Soul cometh second in our discourse, yet was she not created by God younger than Body ; for of these twain which He joined together He would not have suffered the elder to be governed by the younger. The mistress and ruler of the Body did God fashion Soul, out of these elements, after this manner : betwixt that Sub- stance which is undivided and alway the same, and that which cometh into being and is divided in bodies. He made, by the mixing of them both, a third sort of Substance in the middle betwixt the Same and the Other. **•«-•«■* -/^ These Substances, being three, He took and mixed all together, so that they became one Form; and the Nature of the Other, which was hard to mix, He joined by force unto the Same, and these He mingled with the Third Substance ; and of the three made one : then again divided this whole mass into as many parts as was meet, whereof each one was compounded of the Same and the Other and the Third Substance.^ [35 B-36 D. — These parts, all standing in specified numerical ratios to one another, are cut off in specified order, until the whole soul-mass is used up. They are pieced together in the order in which they are cut off, and make a soul-strip, as it were, which is then divided lengthwise into two equal bands, which are laid across each other like the 1 "The Third Substance '* is "the Unity of Apperception "—"Self -Con- sciousneas." 268 THE MYTHS OF PLATO 36 D ΈτΓβΙ δε κατά νουν τω ξυνιστάνη ττασα η τη<; ψυχη'ζ Ε ξύστασυ^ 6γ6γ6ΐ/7;το, μ^τα τούτο ήταν το σωματο€ί8€<ζ ivTo ήΒονήν aXoyov, καθάττερ νυν, είναι Βοκεΐ 'χρήσιμος, αλλ εττΐ την yεyovυΐav εν ήμΐν άνάρμοστον Λΐ^υχής ττερίοΒον εις κατα- κόσμησιν καϊ συμφωνίαν εαυτή σύμμαχος ύττο Μουσών ΒέΒοταΐ' και ρυθμός αύ Βιά την άμετρον εν ήμΐν και Ε χαρίτων εττιΒεά yLyvoμεvηv εν τοις ττΚείστοις εξιν επίκουρος ετΓΐ ταύτα υττο των αυτών εοοση. Ύά μεν ούν τταρεΧηΧυθότα τών ειρημενων, ττΧήν βραχέων, εττιΒεΒεικται τά Βιά νου BεBημιoυpyημέva• Βεΐ Βε και τά Βι άνότ^κης yιyv6μεva τω λόγω τταραθεσθαι. 48 μεμιyμέvη yap ούν ή τούΒε του κόσμου yεvεσις εξ άvάyκης τε καϊ νου συστάσεως εyεvvήθη• νου Βε άvάyκης άρχοντος τω Ίτείθειν αυτήν τών yιyvoμεvωv τά ττΧεΐστα εττι το βεΧτιστον άyειv, ταύτη κατά ταύτα τε Βι άvάyκης ήττω- μενης ύττο ττειθούς εμφρονος ούτω κατ αρχάς ξυνίστατο τόΒε το Ίταν. εϊ τις ούν ή yεyovε, κατά ταύτα όντως ερεΐ, μικτεον καϊ το της πτΧανωμενης εΙΒος αίτιας, ή φερειν ττέφυκεν, ώΒε ούν ττάΧιν άναχωρητεον, καϊ Χαβούσιν Β αυτών τούτων Ίτροσήκουσαν ετεραν αρχήν αύθις αύ, καθάττερ ττερϊ τών τότε, νυν ούτω ττερϊ τούτων ττάΧιν άρκτέον άττ αρχής, τήν Βή ττρο τής ουρανού yεvεσεως ττυρος ύΒατός THE TIMAEUS 287 tions of Thought in ourselves, which are kin, albeit perturbed, unto those unperturbed celestial courses ; and having throughly learnt and become partakers in the truth of the reasonings which are according to nature, might, by means of our imita- tion of the Circuits of God which are without error altogether, compose into order the circuits in ourselves which have erred. Concerning Sound and Hearing let the same thing be said — that they also have been bestowed by the Gods to the same end as Sight. For to this end also hath Speech been ordained, and maketh thereto the largest contribution ; and, moreover, all that part of Music which is for the service of the Voice and Hearing hath been given unto us for the sake of Harmony ; and Harmony, having her courses kin unto the revolutions in our Soul, hath been given by the Muses to be a helper unto the man who, with understanding, shall use their art, not for the getting of imreasonable pleasure — which is commonly esteemed the use of Music — but for the ordering of the circuit of our Soul which hath fallen out of harmony, and the bringing thereof into concord with itself ; and Ehy thm also, because that the state of most men is without measure and lacketh grace, hath been given unto us for the same end, to aid us, by the same Benefactors. Hitherto hath this discourse been for the most part con- cerning those things which are of the workmanship of Eeason ; but now must it set by the side of these that which cometh to pass of Necessity ; for, in truth, the generation of this Universe was a mixed generation, sprung from the concurrence of Necessity and Eeason. Eeason exercised authority over Necessity by persuading her to bring the most part of the things which were made unto the Best Issue. According to this scheme, in the beginning, was the Universe established through the instrumentality of Necessity working in obedience unto the admonition of Wisdom. If any man, therefore, would tell truly how this Universe is come into being, he must include the natural operation of the Cause Errant.^ Let us then turn back, and, having taken up this other proper principle of things created, begin again from the beginning, even as we began the former inquiry. Wherefore let us search out the natures of Fire and ^ I have adopted this translatiou of η ττΚανωμένη αιτία from Mr. Archer-Hind. 288 THE MYTHS OF PLATO T6 καΧ άβρος καί <γης φύσιν θβατέον αντην καϊ τα ττρο τούτου ττάθη. 69 Β ωστΓβρ ουν καϊ κατ αργα<ζ βΧάχθη, ταύτα ατάκτως β'χοντα 6 θβος iv ίκάστω τβ αύτω ττρος αυτό καϊ ττρος αλΧηΧα συμμετρίας βνεττοίησεν, όσας τε καϊ oirrj Βυνατον ην avakoya καϊ σύμμετρα είναί. τότε yap οΰτε τούτων όσον μη τύ'χτ] tl μετεΐ'χεν, οΰτε το τταράτταν ονομάσαι των νυν ονομαζόμενων άξίολο^ον ην ούΒέν, οίον ττΰρ καϊ ΰΒωρ καϊ C εϊ τι των αΧλων, άΧλα ττάντα ταύτα ττρωτον Βιεκόσμησεν, εττειτ εκ τούτων ττάν τόΒε ξυνεστήσατο, ζώον εν ζώα ε'χον τα ττάντα εν αύτω θνητά αθάνατα τε, καϊ των μεν θείων αύτος ^ί^νεται Βημιουρ^ός, των Βε θνητών την ηενεσιν τοις εαυτού ^γεννημασί Βημιουριγεΐν ττροσεταξεν. οί Βε μιμούμενοι, τταραΧαβόντες ap^rjv "ψνχής άθάνατον, το μετά τούτο θνητον σώμα αύττ} ττεριετόρνευσαν οχ^ημά τε ττάν το σώμα εΒοσαν αΧλο τε εΙΒος εν αύτω '^υ'χης ττροσωκοΒομουν το θνητον, Βεινα καϊ ava^yKata εν εαυτω τταθηματα ε'χον, D Ίτρώτον μεν ήΒονην, μέ<γιστον κακού Βελεαρ, εττειτα Χύττας, άyaθώv φυ'γάς, ετι δ' αύ θάρρος καϊ φόβον, άφρονε ξυμβούΧω, θυμον Βε Βυστταραμύθητον, εΧττίΒα δ' εύ'πapάyω- yov αίσθησει τε άΧο^ω καϊ εττιχειρητ^ τταντος ερωτΐ' ξυ^κερασάμενοί τ αύτα άναηκαίως το θνητον >γενος ξυνεθεσαν. καϊ Βια ταύτα Βη σεβόμενοι μιαίνειν το θείον, 6 τι μη ττάσα ην άνά<γκη, χωρίς εκείνου κατοικίζουσιν εις Ε αΧΧην τού σώματος οϊκησιν το θνητον, ίσθμον καϊ ορον ΒιοικοΒομήσαντες της τε κεφαΧής καϊ τού στήθους, αυχένα μεταξύ τιθεντες, Ίνα εϊη χωρίς, εν Βη τοις στηθεσι καϊ τω καΧουμενω θώρακι το της Λίτυχής θνητον ^ενος ενεΒουν. καϊ εττειΒη το μεν αμεινον αυτής, το Βε χείρον εττεφύκει, 70 ΒιοικοΒομούσι τού θώρακος αύ το κύτος, Βιορίζοντες οίον 'γυναικών, την Βε άνΒρών χ(ορϊς οϊκησιν, τάς φρενας THE TIMAEUS 289 Water and Air and Earth, which were before the Heaven was brought forth ; and also the state which was before these natures themselves were. As was said at the beginning, these things, being without order, God took, and put into them all those measures of Proportion and Symmetry whereof they were capable, each one in respect of itself, and all in respect of one another. For before that there was nothing which partook of these measures save by chance ; nor was there any of the things which now have names which was then worthy at all of being named, neither Fire nor Water nor any of the other Elements; but all these did He first set in order, and then out of them instituted this Universe, One Living Creature, which hath in itself all living creatures mortal and immortal. Of those which are divine He himself is the Maker ; but the creation of those which are mortal He appointed unto His own offspring, to be their work ; and they following His example, when they had received of Him the immortal principle of the Soul, thereafter fashioned round about her this mortal Body, and gave it all unto her to be her vehicle ; and, moreover, they constructed another kind of Soul, and put it also into the Body, to wit the Mortal Soul which hath in itself passions terrible, of necessity inherent — first, Pleasure, evil's best bait, then Pains that banish good things, also Confidence and Fear, two heedless counsellors, and Wrath hard to entreat, and Hope easily led astray. These did they mix with Sense that lacketh Eeason, and Love that dareth all, and so builded the mortal kind of Soul. Wherefore, fearing to defile the divine more than was inevitable, they appoint a dwelling-place for the mortal apart therefrom, in another region of the body, having built an isthmus and boundary between the Head and the Breast, to wit, the Neck, set between them that they might be separate. In the Breast, then, or what is called the Chest, they enclosed the mortal kind of Soul ; and inasmuch as one part thereof was by nature better, and the other part worse, they also built a wall of partition to divide the vessel of the Chest, as a house is divided into the women's quarters and the men's υ 290 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Βίάφρα<γμα βίς το μέσον αυτών τιθέντβ^;. το μβτέ'χ^ον οΰν της "^^υγγις avhpeLa^ καί θνμον, φιΧόνβίκον 6ν, κατωκισαν Ιηηυτέρω της κεφαλής μεταξύ των φρενών τε καΐ αύγενος^ ϊνα του Χό^ου κατήκοον ον /coivfj μετ εκείνου βία το τών ετΓίθυμοών κατε'χοί ^ενος^ οττότ εκ της άκροττόΧεως τω τ ε7Γίτά<γματι καϊ Χό^^ω μηΒαμτ} ττείθεσθαι εκον εθεΧοι. Ύην Β δε Βη καρΒίαν αρχήν αμα τών φΧεβών καϊ ττη^γην του ττεριφερομενου κατά ττάντα τα μέΧη σφοΒρώς αίματος εΙς την Βορυφορικην οϊκησιν κατέστησαν. Ινα, οτε ξεσείε το του θυμού μένος, του Χ6<γου τταρα^γ^γείΧαντος, ως τις άΒίκος ττερί αυτά 'γί^νεται ττραξις έξωθεν ή καί τις άττό τών ενΒοθεν ετΓίθυμίών, οξέως Βιά πάντων στενωττών τταν, όσον αίσθητίκον εν τω σώματι, τών τε τταρακεΧεύσεων καϊ άττει- Χών αίσθανομενον ηίηνοιτο εττηκοον καϊ εττοιτο ττάντΎ} καϊ C το βεΧτυστον ούτως εν αύτοΐς ττάσιν ήyεμovεΐv εώ. D Το Βε Βη σίτων τε καϊ ττοτών εττιθυμητίκον της ψυχής καϊ όσων ενΒεοαν Βίά την του σώματος ϊσχεο φύσίν, τούτο Ε εΙς τα μεταξύ τών τε φρενών καϊ του ττρος τον ομφαΧον ορού κατωκισαν, οΐον φάτνην εν άτταντι τούτω τω τόττω Tjj του σώματος τροφτ} τεκτηνάμενοί' καϊ κατεΒησαν Βη το τοιούτον ενταύθα ως θρέμμα aypiov, τρεφειν Βε ξυνημμενον avajKaiov, εϊττερ τι μεΧΧοι το θνητον εσεσθαι ^ενος. Χν ουν άει νεμομενον ττρος φάτνη καϊ ο τι ττορρωτάτω τού βουΧευομενου κατοικούν, θόρυβον καϊ βοην ώς εΧαχίστην 71 τταρεχον, το κράτιστον καθ^ ήσυχίαν πτερϊ τού ττάσι κοινή ξυμφεροντος εω βουΧεύεσθαι, Βιά ταύτα ενταύθ' εΒοσαν αύτω την ταξιν. εΙΒοτες Βε αύτο ώς Χό<γου μεν οΰτε ξυνησειν εμεΧΧεν, εϊ τε ττη καϊ μεταΧαμβάνοι τίνος αυ τών αισθήσεων, ουκ εμφυτον αύτω το μεΧειν τινών εσοιτο Xoyωv, ύτΓΟ Βε ειΒώΧων καϊ φαντασμάτων νυκτός τε καϊ μεθ ήμεραν μαΧιστα 'ψυχα^ω^ήσοιτο, τούτω Βη θεός εττι- βουΧευσας αύτω την τού ήττατος ιΒεαν ξυνέστησε καϊ THE TIMAEUS 291 quarters ; so did they put the Midriff as a barrier betwixt these two parts. That part of the Soul, therefore, which partaketh of courage and spirit, loving strife, they established nearer unto the Head, betwixt the Midriff and the Neck, to the end that, being within hearing of the Eeasoning Part, it might, to- gether with it, keep down the brood of appetites by force, when they would not obey the word of command from the castle ; and the Heart, which is the knot of the veins and the fountain of the blood which floweth everywhere mightily through all the members, they set to be the guardhouse, so that when the fierceness of wrath boileth, what time Eeason doth pass the word that some wickedness is being done around them without, or haply by the Appetites within, then the whole sensitive system of the Body, keenly apprehending through all the narrow passages thereof the exhortations and threats uttered, should become obedient and tractable alto- gether, and so should let the Best Part be the leader of them all. * * -x- -x- -X- -it As for that part of the Soul which desireth meat and drink and the other things which it needeth by reason of the nature of the Body, this they established in the region which lieth between the Midriff and the borders of the ^iavel, having framed, as it were, a manger to extend throughout all this place for the nourishment of the Body. Here they bound this part of the Soul like a wild beast which nevertheless must be kept joined unto the rest and reared, if there was to be a mortal race at all. Accordingly, that, always feeding at the manger and dwelling as far as possible from the part which taketh counsel, it might raise as little tumult and uproar as possible, and let the Chief Part take counsel in peace concern- ing the common good, for this cause did they post it here. And knowing this concerning it that it would not be able to understand Eeason, and that even if it attained somehow unto some empiric knowledge of reasonable truths, it was not of such a nature as to give heed thereto, but for the most part would follow the ghostly conduct of Images and Phantasms by night and by day, God sought out a device against this, and put the Liver close by the dwelling-place of the Appetitive 292 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Β ϊθηκεν eU την βκείνον κατοίκησιν, ττυκνον καΐ Χβΐον καΐ Χαμττρον καΐ yXvKv καϊ ττικροτητα €^ον μη'χ^ανησάμενος, ϊνα iv αύτω των διανοημάτων ή €Κ τον νου φβρομβνη Βνναμις, οίον iv κατότττρω Ββχ^ομενω τνττους καϊ κατιΒεΐν εΐ'δωλα ιταρεγοντϋ, φοβοΐ μβν αυτό, οττότε μβρβί της τΓίκροτητος 'χ^ρωμένη ^v^yyevei γαΚεττη Ίτροσενβ'χθβΐσα aireLhrj κατά Ίταν ύττομί^νΰσα οξβως το ήτταρ χολώδτ; 'χ^ρωματα C έμψαίνοί, ξυνώ^ουσά τβ τταν ρυσον καϊ τραγυ ττοωΐ, Χοβον Be καϊ δοχά? ττνΧας Τ6 τα μβν έξ ορθόν κατακάμτττονσα καϊ ξνσιτώσα, τα Be ίμφράττονσα avyKXeiovaa re, Χνττας καϊ ασας τταρέ'χ^οί, καϊ 6τ αν τάναντία φάσματα άττο- ζω^ραφοί ττραότητος τις €Κ Βίανοίας έττίττνοια, της μ^ν ΊΓίκρότητος ήσνχ^ίαν τταρέ'χρνσα τω μητ€ KLvelv μητ€ ττροσ- ά7ΓΤ6σθαί της εναντίας eavTjj φνσ€ως eOeXeLV, ^Χνκντητϋ Be Tjj κατ €Κ€Ϊνο ζνμφντω ττρος αντο 'χρωμένη καϊ ττάντα D ορθά καϊ Xela αντον καϊ eXevθepa ά7Γ6νθύνονσα 'iXeojv re καϊ evήμepov ττοίοΐ την irepl το ητταρ '^^τνγτις μοΐραν κατωκισμένην, 'iv re τη ννκτϊ Βι,α^ω^γην 'έ'χρνσαν μeτpLav, μavτeίa 'χ^ρωμένην καθ^ νττνον, iTreiBr) Xoyov καϊ φpovησeως ον /Α€Τ€?χ€. μeμvημevo(, yap της τον ττατρος ilnστoXης οΐ ξννιστάντες ήμας, 6τ€ το θνητον εττβστελλε yevoς ώς άριστον eh Βνναμιν iroceiv, οντω Βη κaτopθovvτeς καϊ το Ε φανΧον ημών, Ίνα άXηθeίaς ττη ττροσάτττοιτο, κατέστησαν iv τούτω το μavτelov, * * Hi He % * 89 Ε κaθά'πep eϊlΓoμev ττοΧΧάκις, οτυ τρία τρί'χτ} '\^ν'χΎ)ς iv ήμΐν €ΪΒη κατωκίσται, Tvyj^avei Be εκαστον κινήσεις ε'χρν, οντω κατά ταντά καϊ ννν ώς Βιά βραγντάτων ρητέον, οτι το μ^ν αντών iv apyia Biayov και τών εαντον κινήσεων ησνχίαν ayov άσθενεστατον άvάyκη yίyvεσθaι, το δ' iv 90 yvμvaσίoις ippωμεvεστaτov' Βιο φνΧακτεον, οττως αν εγωσι τάς κινήσεις ιτρος άΧΧηΧα σνμμετρονς. το Βε ττερί τον κνριωτάτον ιταρ ήμΐν ψνχής εϊΒονς Βιανοεΐσθαι Βεΐ τηΒε, ώς άρα αντο Βαίμονα θεός εκάστω ΒάΒωκε, τοντο ο Βή φαμεν οικεΐν μεν ημών iir άκρω τω σώματι, ττρος Βε την iv ονρανω ξvyyεvειav άττο yης ημάς αϊρειν ώς οντάς φντον ονκ εyyειov, άλλα ονράνιον, ορθότατα Xεyovτες' iκεΐθεv Β yap, όθεν ή ττρώτη της ^^νχτις yεvεσις εφν, το θείον την κεφαΧήν καϊ ρίζαν ημών άνακρεμανννν ορθοί ττάν το σώμα. τω μεν ονν ττερΙ τάς i^Γlθvμίaς η ττερι φιΧονεικίας τετεν- THE TIMAEUS 293 Soul, having fashioned it close and smooth and shining and sweet and bitter too, so that the thoughts which come from the Intelligence, striking upon it as upon a mirror which receiveth impressions and causeth images to be seen, might fill the Appetitive Soul, at one time, with fear, ... at another time might make it mild and gentle, and give unto it a space of calm at night, wherein it should receive the Oracles of Dreams, meet for that which is without Eeason and Understanding ; for they who made us were mindful of that which their Father spake, commanding them to make the mortal race as perfect as possible ; therefore did they regulate even the base part of us after this wise, that it might lay hold of truth somehow, and therefore did they establish a Place of Oracles therein. Now, as touching the three sorts of Soul implanted in us, whereof we have• oft-times spoken, and the proper motions of each, let this be now said shortly, that any one of them which continueth in abeyance, having her motions stopped, must needs become weaker ; but any one which exerciseth herself becometh stronger. Wherefore we must take heed that they all, in regard to one another, have their motions accomplished in due measure. But as touching that kind of Soul in us which hath most authority, let this be understood, that God hath given it unto each man to be his Genius, to wit, that Soul which, we say, dwelleth in the topmost part of the Body, and lifteth us up from Earth towards our birthplace in the Heaven, forasmuch as we are not earthly creatures but heavenly : this we say, and most truly say ; for from that Place whence the Soul first sprang the Divine Principle suspendeth our head and root, and so causeth the whole Body to stand upright. Wherefore if any man have followed after the lusts of the 294 THE MYTHS OF PLATO τακοτι καΐ ταύτα Βίαττονουντι σφοΒρα ττάντα τα Βό^γματα ανάγκη θνητά iyyejovevaif καΐ τταντάττασί καθ* όσον μάΧιστα Βυνατον θνητω ηίην^σβαι^ τούτον μηΒβ σμικρόν βΧΧβίτΓβιν, ατ6 το τοιούτον ηύξηκότΐ' τω Be irepl φιλομαθίαν και ΊΓβρΙ τας αληθείς φρονησβις εσττουΒακοτί καϊ ταύτα C μάλιστα των αυτού ^β^υμνασμενω φρονεΐν μβν αθάνατα και θ€Ϊα, άντΓβρ άΧηθβίας βφάτττηται, ττασα ανάγκη ττου, καθ^ όσον δ' αΰ μβτασχ^εΐν άνθρωττίνη φύσις αθανασίας βνΒί'χεται, τούτου μηΒβν μέρος airoXeiireiVy ατ€ Be ael θεραττεύοντα το θείον εγοντά re αύτον ev κεκοσμημενον τον Βαίμονα ξυνοικον ev αύτω Βιαφεροντως εύΒαίμονα είναι. θεραττεία Βε Βη ΊταντΙ ττάντως μία, τάς οικείας εκάστω τροφας και D κινήσεις άττοΒιΒοναι, τω δ' εν ήμΐν θείω ξνγ^ενεΐς εισι κινήσεις αΐ τού τταντος Βιανοησεις και ττεριφοραί. ταύταις Βη ξυνετΓομενον εκαστον Βεΐ, τας ττερι την ^γενεσιν εν ττ} κεφαλή Βιεφθαρμενας ημών ττεριόΒονς εξορθούντα Βιά το καταμανθάνειν τας τού τταντος αρμονίας τε καϊ ιτεριφοράς, τω κατανοουμένω το κατανοούν εξομοιωσαι κατά την άρ'χαιαν φύσιν, ομοιώσαντα Βε τέλος ε'χειν τού ττροτεθεντος άνθρώτΓΟίς ύττο θεών αρίστου βίου ττρός τε τον τταρόντα και τον εττειτα γ^ρόνον. Ε ΚαΙ Βη καϊ τα νύν ήμΐν εξ αργ^ης τταραηηελθεντα Βιεξελθεΐν ττερϊ τού τταντος μέχρι γενέσεως άνθρωττίνης σ'χεΒον εοικε τέλος ε'χειν. τά yap άλλα ζώα y ^έηονεν αύ, Βιά βραχέων εττιμνηστέον, 6 τι μή τις ανάγκη μηκύνειν ούτω yap εμμετρότερος τις αν αύτω Βόξειε ττερϊ τους τούτων \oyoυς είναι. ttjL•^ ούν το τοιούτον έστω λey6μεvov, Ύών yεvo μένων άνΒρών όσοι Βειλοϊ καϊ τον βίον άΒίκως Βιηλθον, κατά \6yov τον εικότα yυvaΐκες μετεφύοντο εν rf Βευτέρα yεvέσει. ****** 91 D yυvaΐκες μεν ούν καϊ το θήλυ ττάν οΰτω yέyove. Το Βε THE TIMAEUS 295 flesh, or after contention, and busied himself wholly therewith, all his thoughts withior him muet ^ g^s be^prtal, and so farU t as it lie th_jn^(faim_to _ become mortal^ he cannot fail at all of \ this ; for this hath he fostered : but if any man have earnestly pursued learning and the knowledge of Truth, and have exercised most his faculty of thinking, he must needs have thoughts immortal and divine if he lay hold of Truth ; and so far as Human Nature may have part in Immortality, he cannot fall short thereof at all : and inasmuch as he serveth the Divine Part, and hath the Genius which dwelleth in him ordered aright, he must needs be blessed exceedingly : ^ and the service required of every man is the same alway — to wit, he must apportion unto each part the kind of nourishment and motion proper thereto. Now unto the Divine Part in us the motions which are kin are the Thoughts and Circuits of the All. These must every man follow, that he may regulate the Eevolutions in his Head which were disturbed when the Soul was born in the flesh ; and, by throughly learning the Harmonies and Circuits of the All, may make that which understandeth like unto that which is understood, even as it was in the beginning ; and having made it like, may attain unto the perfection of that Best Life which is offered unto men by the Gods, for this present time and for the time hereafter. Now is the commandment which came unto us in the beginning, that we should declare the nature of the All, even unto the generation of Man, well-nigh brought to fulfilment ; for the way of the generation of the other living creatures we may tell shortly, if it so be that it needeth no long history. Thus methinks shall a man set proper bounds unto his discourse concerning them. Let this, then, be said, that of those which were born Men, it is most likely that as many as were cowardly, and passed their life in unrighteousness, were changed into Women when they were born the second time. •K• * * * -x• -x- Thus were Women and the whole female sex brought forth. 1 Cf. Arist. E. N. x. 7. 8. 1177 b 26 ff., and E. E. θ 3. (Η 15) 1249 b 20, where t6v debv depaireveiv και ded^eiv seems to be an echo of the (ire δέ del Oepa- ττεύοντα τό Oeiov, Tim. 90 C. 296 THE MYTHS OF PLATO των ορνύων φϋΧον μβτβρρνθμίζβτο, άντΙ τρυ'χων ιττβρα ψνον, 6Κ των άκακων άνΒρών, κούφων Be, καΐ μβτβωρολο^γίκών Ε μβν, ηγουμένων δε hC οψβως τα<ζ ττβρί τούτων άτΓοΒβίξβί^; βββαίοτάτας elvau hC βύηθβίαν. Το δ' αν ττβζον καΐ θηρίώΒβς yeyovev 6Κ των μηΒεν ττροσγ^ρω μίνων φιλοσοφία μηΒβ άθρούντων τήζ πτβρί τον ούρανον φύσεως ττβρί μηΒέν, Βία το μηκίτι ταΐζ iv Tjj κεφαΧτ} γ^ρησθαί ττβρίόΒοις, αΧΧα τοις irepl τα στήθη της 'ψν'χτ}ς ή<γ€μ6σιν βττβσθαί μβρβσυν. 6Κ τούτων ονν των βτητηΒβνμάτων τά τβ βμττροσθια κωΚα καΐ* τας κβφαΧας βίς yrjv ίΧκόμβνα νττο ξν^^βνβίας ήρβι,σαν, ττρομήκβίς τ€ καΐ τταντοίας βσ^ον τας κορυφάς, otttj 92 συνβθΧίφθησαν νττο άρτιας εκάστων αί ττβριφοραί. τβτρά- ΤΓονν Τ6 το ^ενος αυτών €κ ταύτης βφύετο καΐ ττοΧύττουν της ττροφάσεως, θβοΰ βάσεις υττοτιθεντος ττΧείους τοις μαΧΚον άφροσιν, ώς μαΧΧον εττι yrjv εΧκοιντο. τοις δ* άφρονεστάτοις αυτών τούτων κα\ τταντάττασι ττρος yrjv Ίτάν το σώμα κατατεινομύνοις ώς ούΒεν €τι ττοΒών 'χηρείας ούσης, άττοΒα αυτά και ιΧυσττώμενα εττΐ γης εyεvvησav. το Βε τέταρτον γένος ενυΒρον γεγονεν εκ τών μάΧιστα άνοητο- τάτων καϊ αμαθέστατων, ους ούΒ^ άναττνοής καθαράς ετι ήξίωσαν οι μεταττΧάττοντες, ώς την '>^υγΎ)ν υττο ττΧημμε- Χειας ττάσης άκαθάρτως ε'χοντων, αΚΧ άντΙ Χετττης και καθαράς αναπνοής άερος εις νΒατος θοΧεράν καϊ βαθεΐαν Β εωσαν άνάττνευσιν όθεν Ι'χθύων έθνος καϊ το τών οστρεων ξυναττάντων τε οσα ενυΒρα γεγονε, Βίκην άμαθίας εσ'χάτης εσ'χάτας οικήσεις είΧη'χρτων. καϊ κατά ταύτα Βή ττάντα τότε καϊ νυν Βιαμείβεται τά ζώα εις άΧΧηΧα, νου και άνοιας άττοβοΧτ) καϊ κτήσει μεταβαΧΧόμενα. Kat δ^ και τεΧος ττερϊ του τταντος νυν ήΒη τον Xoyov ήμΐν φώμεν εγειν θνητά yap καϊ αθάνατα ζώα Χαβών καϊ ξυμτΓΧηρω- θεϊς οΒε ο κόσμος, οΰτω ζώον ορατον τά ορατά ττεριεγον, εΐκών του ττοιητοΰ, θεός αΙσθητός, μέγιστος καϊ άριστος κάΧΧιστός τε καϊ τεΧεώτατος γεγονεν, εις ουρανός οΒε μονογενής ών. THE TIMAEUS • 297 The tribe of Birds, putting forth feathers instead of hair, was the transformation of men that were guileless, but light- witted ; who were observers of the stars, but thought foolishly that the surest knowledge concerning them cometh through Sight. The tribe of Beasts which walk on the Earth sprang from those men who sought not "Wisdom at all for an help, nor considered the nature of the Heaven at all, because that they no longer used the Kevolutions in the Head, but followed the Parts of the Soul which are about the Breast, making them their guides. By reason of this manner of living their four limbs and their heads were drawn down unto kindred earth, and thereon did they rest them ; and they got head-pieces of all sorts, oblong, according as the circuits of each, not being kept in use, were crushed in. For this cause their kind grew four-footed and many-footed, for God put more props under those which were more senseless, that they might be drawn the more toward the earth. But the most senseless of them all, which do stretch their whole body altogether upon the earth, since they had no longer any need of feet, the Gods made without feet, to crawl on the earth. The fourth kind was born, to live in the water, from those men who were the most lacking in Understanding and Knowledge ; whom they who fashioned them afresh deemed not worthy any more even of pure air to breathe, because that they had made their Souls impure by all manner of wicked- ness: wherefore the Gods gave them not thin pure air to breathe, but thrust them down into the waters, to draw thick breath in the depths thereof. From these men is sprung the nation of Fishes, and of Oysters, and of all that live in the water, which have gotten for recompense of uttermost ignorance the uttermost habitations. "k ^ ^ ^ ^ * Now may we say that our discourse concerning the All is come to its ending. For this Universe, having taken unto itself Living Creatures mortal and immortal, and having been filled therewith, hath been brought forth a Creature Visible, containing the things which are visible ; the Image of his Maker, a God Sensible, Greatest, Best, Fairest, and Most Perfect — this One Heaven Only Begotten. 298 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Observations on the Timaeus Myth It lies outside the scope of this work to select for separate comment even a few of the most important questions and topics contained in the vast Timaeus, related as these are, not only to Plato's Philosophy itself as a whole, but to subsequent Philosophy and Theology and Natural Science as influenced by this Dialogue, perhaps the most influential of all Plato's Dialogues. I keep clear of the Timaeus as an Essay on Physics and Physiology profoundly interesting to the student of the history of these branches. I do not wish to ransack it for its anticipations of later metaphysical doctrine, such as that of the subjectivity of space, which may, or may not, be taught in the passages treating of χωρά and the ύττοΒοχη. I do not trouble myself or my readers with the lucubra- tions of Proclus and his like on it. I do not say a word about the theological doctrine which Christian exegesis has found in it in such abundant store. For these things the reader must turn to editions of the Timaeus, and Histories of Philosophy where the Timaeus is discussed. Here we are concerned with it merely as one in the series of Plato's Myths ; and as most of the observations which have been made in connection with the other Myths already examined apply equally to this Myth, special observations on it need not be numerous or long. Indeed, the transla- tion which I have made, if read in the light of these former observations, almost explains itself. More might have been translated, for the whole Discourse delivered by Timaeus is a Myth ; or other parts might have been substituted for some here translated. I had to use my judgment in choosing what to translate, as I could not trans- late the whole, and my judgment may have sometimes erred ; yet, after all, I venture to think that what I have translated presents the Timaeus in the aspect in which it is the object THE TIMAEUS 299 of this work to present it — as a great Myth in the series which we are reviewing. This Myth sets forth, in one vast composition, the three Ideas of Soul, Cosmos, and God : in one vast composition ; perhaps nowhere else in literature are they set forth so as to produce such a convincing sense of their organic inter- connection. And the impressiveness of this vast composition is wonderfully enhanced by the context in which it is framed. Indeed, what is new in the presentation of the Ideas of Soul, Cosmos, and God in the Timaeus, as compared with other Platonic Myths in which they are presented, is derived from the context in which this Myth frames them. The Timaeus, as we have seen, and shall see better when we reach the Critias, follows on after the BepuUic. It begins with a recapitulation of the first five books of the Republic, which Socrates offers in order that he may say : " Here you have the structure of theEfi£&i^ State set forth ; now let us s^ie^ that State exertin^^^ί?^cί^o^in accordance with its structur^ff^ Its structure is that or~anighly organised military system. Let us see it engaged in a great war." In answer to this demand Critias introduces and outlines the Atlantis Myth (afterwards resumed in the unfinished Dialogue which bears his name), the History of the Great Antediluvian War in which Athens — representing the καΧλίττοΧις of the Repuhlic — maintains the civilisation of Hellas against the outer barbarian. That is the immediate context of the Discourse, or Myth, delivered by Timaeus. But the Myth breaks away from the sequence of that context in the most startling manner, and soars, on a sudden, above the mundane outlook of the first five books of the EepuUic and the History of the Great War, with which the company were up to the moment engaged, and constrains them to give all their thoughts to the world eternal. Two things Timaeus seems to tell them in this Myth. First, the State must be framed in the Cosmos. You cannot ""Have any scientific knowledge of the Social Good till you understand it as part of the Absolute Good realised in the Cosmos which is the Image of God. The knowledge of the ihea τά^αθου which the EepuUic (in a passage subsequent to the books epitomisea by Socrates in the Timaeus) requires 300 THE MYTHS OF PLATO of the True Statesman is, indeed, nothing but the appre- hension of the Social Good as determined by the Cosmic Good. The method of the Eepublic was to write the goodness of the Individual large in the goodness of the State. But we must not stop here. The goodness of the State must be written large in that of the Universe : written, not, indeed, in characters which the scientific faculty can at last be sure that it has deciphered, but in the hieroglyphics, as it were, of a mysterious picture-writing which, although it does not further definite knowledge, inspires that Wonder which is the source of Philosophy, that Fear which is the beginning of Wisdom. But, secondly, Timaeus goes far beyond the mere recom- mendation of a study of Cosmology for the sake of the better realisation of the political end. He tells the company, in this \Myth, that the political end is not the only end which man I may propose to himself. The life of the State and of Man as member of the State, however it may be ennobled and made to seem more choice-worthy by being viewed as part of the blessed life of the One, Only Begotten, Living Creature which is the express image of God, is nevertheless an end in which it is impossible to acquiesce. The best-ordered State cannot escape the Decline and Fall which await all human institu- tions ; and the life of the citizen is incomparably shorter than that of his earthly city. If Man is to have any abiding end it must be in a life of_the Soul which lies beyond death, outside the κύκλος τή? yev^iretd^} ' To be remembered, anfl even tojbe worshipped, by future generations on Qarth is an " immortality " which can satisfy Ipo manji and fetjUless satis ^Ing~is the " imm ortality t of IbSsorption in the Spirit/oTthe Universe^ The~'inly im- i^^ .'St ^--r-"=^=Tw• '4^-x: i i. r • mortality wJ iicJi can sa tisfy a m an, ii 'he can only believe m it, is a personal life after bodily death, or, it may be, after many bodily deaths, ^^hen~he shall return to his " native star," 1 "In Plato the State, like everything else upon Earth, is essentially related to the other world, whence all truth and reality spring. This is the ultimate ource of his political idealism. . . . The State, therefore, serves not only for moral education, but also as a preparation for the higher life of the disembodied spirit into which a beautiful glimpse is opened to us at the end of the Republic " (Zeller, Aristotle, ii. 212, Engl. TransL; cf. Rohde, Psyche, ii. 293). The latter half of the Republic, as has been pointed out, is not before us in the TiTruuus. THE TIMAEUS 301 and be there for ever what the grace of God and his own efforts after κάθαρσί<; have made him. This third sort of immortality obviously holds the field against the two other sorts mentioned ; for, first, it is worth believing, which the second sort, however easy to believe, is not ; and, secondly, it is more worth believing than the first sort, because it is a true " immortality " — a personal life for ever and ever, — whereas the first sort, consisting in the lapsing memory of the short-lived individuals of a Kace itself destined in time to disappear from the earth, is not a true immortality, however comforting it may be to look forward to it as a brief period in the true immortality. Lastly, the third sort of immortality, being worth believing, is, in addition to that, easy to believe, because no evidence drawn from the Natural World can ever be conclusive against it. It is not like a miracle alleged to have occurred in the Natural World in opposition to the recognised Laws of that World. No objec-l tive Law of Nature is violated by the personal immortalityjl of the disembodied Soul. The evidence against it, as for it,i( is subjective only. Does belief in personal immortality com- fort men ? If it does, they will be found believing — a few, fervently, the majority, perhaps, in passive fashion. So far I have tried to express the thought and feeling which seem to be in unison with the note of the Timaeus Myth. But there is another type of thought and feeling, on this great subject, which we cannot ignore, although the Timaeus Myth ignores it entirely. We must rem ember that for the J^iBJEJ^ ^TEpnti pi ro M ia l immorta lity has li ttle or no attraction. Final sleep "^ems to be the ideal for a large portion of the human race. It would be foolish, then, to say that belief in personal immortality is at all a subjective necessity. All that we are entitled to say is that, as a matter of fact, this belief has prevailed among the races which hitherto have taken the lead in the world. Whether or no it is bound to remain prevalent it is impossible to say. The overworked and the indolent, in modern Europe, easily acquiesce in — nay, gladly embrace, the ideal of eternal sleep ; and even for some energetic constructive minds the time comes when they simply wish to rest from their labours, contented to think, 302 THE MYTHS OF PLATO or hope, that the mundane system, political, industrial, or scientific, for which they have worked hard, will continue to prosper when they are gone. The ideal of work or duty done is the ideal which, in the West, now competes most seriously with the ideal of personal immortality : — ώ ^€tv' άγγελλίΐν Αακ^Βαιμονίους otl TySe κί'ιμ^θα TOiS k€lv(uv ρήμαχτι π€ΐθ6μ,€νοι. II (Timaeus, 42, and 91 D ff.) The lower animals were created after (1) man, and (2) woman, to embody the Souls of human beings who had lived unrighteously. Here, as elsewhere in Plato, — in the Phaedrus Myth ; in. the Myth of Er ; in Fhaedo, 81, 82; in Laws, ix. 872 E, — the raison d'Stre of metempsychosis is κόΧασος and κάθαρσις, Correction and Punfijsation — its raison d*Stre also in the Orphic teaching and in Buddhism. But we must not suppose that belief in metempsychosis is necessarily associated with the notions of κόΧασις and κάθαρσος. Metempsychosis recommended itself to the imagination of man as Natural History long before it was used for an ethical purpose.^ The notion that there is a fixed number of souls always in exist- ence — perhaps a fixed number of bodies — and that all the people successively born on earth are dead people who return from the place of spirits or from their graves, by some law of nature in the presence of which sexual intercourse has quite a subordinate place, is a notion which prevails widely among primitive races, and is entertained merely as an item of Natural History — as a theory of generation, and has no ethical import. Now it seems to me that the difference between men and beasts which belief in metempsychosis as process of κοΧασι^ and καθάρσια makes little of, is one which belief in metem- psychosis as mode of generation is bound to regard as very ^ The ideas of retribution and purification seem to be entirely absent from Irish transmigration stories : see The Voyage of Bran, by Myer and Nutt, ii. 96. THE TIMAEUS 303 real. It may conduce to the κάθαρσις of a man's Soul that it should be incarnate afterwards in the body of a lion or a swan ; but if mere generation is all that is effected by metempsychosis it is natural to suppose that the Souls re-incarnated in one generation of men are those which appeared on earth in a former generation of men, and will reappear in some future generation of men. ^Where a beast becomes a man or a man a beast, and the change is not con- ceived as promoting κάθαρσί^, we have something exceptional — not a case of the normal metempsychosis by which the human race is propagated, but rather a case of metamorphosis due to some particular act of magic, like Circe's, or some other extraordinary cause like that which changed the daughters of Pandion, one into a nightingale, and the other into a swallow. The notion of a man's being able to transform himself or another man into a beast by magic is as primitive and as deeply rooted as that of metempsychosis, but in itself has nothing in common with the notion of metempsychosis. I would therefore distinguish sharply between belief in the reappearance, in human bodies, of departed human souls — or perhaps I ought to say the reappearance of departed human beings. Soul and Body not being regarded as separate entities — the normal generative process by which the human race is maintained on earth, and belief in the sudden bodily trans- formation, by magic or other cause, of men into beasts and beasts into men — an exceptional occurrence. Having distinguished two beliefs which I think ought to be distinguished, I am ready to admit considerable "con- tamination " of each by the other, even before the advent of the notion of κάθαρσις as an end served by re-incarnation of human Souls, not only in human bodies, but also in the bodies of beasts. "We see how natural it is that such " contamination " should take place, if we consider the mental condition which expresses itself in the Beast-Fable. It is a state of chronic dream-consciousness. The Beast-Fable is a dream in which men and beasts talk and act together ; in which the trans- formation of a man into a beast, or a beast into a man, is taken as a matter of course ; in which beasts, in short, are at once men and beasts. • 304 THE MYTHS OF PLATO The mental condition which expresses itself in the dream of the Beast-Fable easily lends itself to belief in bodily trans- formations of men into beasts, and beasts into men, effected supernaturally by magicians ; or sometimes taking place naturally, so that one who was a man in a former generation is born again in this generation as a beast, and may reappear in a future generation as a man. Here the originally in- dependent notions of metempsychosis and metamorphosis begin to " contaminate " each other. Metamorphosis, which is properly the supernatural bodily transformation of a man into a beast, or a beast into a man, appears as the re-birth, in due natural course, of a beast as a man, or a man as a beast : metamorphosis has insinuated itself into the place occupied by metempsychosis, and has become a sort of metem- psychosis ; while metempsychosis, originally a kind of re-birth of departed human beings as human beings, now includes the notion of departed human beings reappearing in new births as beasts, and of beasts as human beings.^ As soon as the notions of retribution and purification came to be connected with the notion of metempsychosis, the modification produced in that notion by the notion of magical metamorphosis would be greatly accentuated : to be born again as a beast would in many cases seem to be more appropriate, from the point of view of retribution and purifica- tion, than to be born again in the natural course as a human being. Ill Timaeus, 41 D, ξυστησας το ττάν Βίβΐλβ ψνγ^ας Ισαρίθ- μους τοις άστροίς, evetp^e θ^ ίκάστην ττρος βκαστον. Susemihl {Genet. Entw. ii. 369) and Archer-Hind {Tim. ad loc.) think that the Creator assigned to the fixed stars, not already differentiated individual Souls, but masses of the, as yet, undifferentiated Soul-stuff which he had compounded in the bowl. Only when the time came that Souls should be 1 The case of Tuan Mac Cairill, in Irish legend, may be quoted as illustrating the manner in which the ideas of metamorphosis, metempsychosis, and preg- nancy without male intervention, run into one another. Tuan became, in succession, a Stag, a Bear, an Eagle, and a Salmon. The Salmon was boiled and eaten by a woman, who thereupon conceived, and brought forth Tuan again in human form. See The Voyage of Bran, by Myer and Nutt, ii. 76. THE TIMAEUS 305 " sown " on the ορηανα γ^ρονου, the planets and earth, were these masses of Soul-stuif in the fixed stars taken and differen- tiated into individual Souls. I agree with Zeller {Plato, pp. 390, 391, Engl. Transl.) in holding that the Souls are differentiated as individuals when they are assigned each one to its fixed star ; and that it is these individual Souls which, on the completion of their speculative journey round the outer sphere of the Heaven, are transferred to the earth and planets in order to partake of their first birth, €'γ^/ος ούΒβν ev τοις TrjBe ομοιώμασιν, άΧΧα Βο* άμυΒρών οργάνων μό^ις αυτών καϊ oXiyoi, έττϊ τας €ΐκονας Ι6ντ€ς θeώvτaι το του €ΐκασθάντος yevoς. κάΧΧος Be τότ ην IBeiv Χαμττρόν, oTe συν eύBaίμovΰ χορω μακαρίαν όψιν τ€ καϊ deav, e7Γ6μevoι μeτa μ€ν Αώς ήμeΐς, άΧΧοι Be μeτ αΧΧου θeώv, elBov Te καϊ eTeXodvTO τών τeXeτώv ην θέμις Xeyeiv C μακαριωτάτην, ην ώpyιάζoμev οΧόκΧηροι μ€ν αύτοϊ 6vτeς καϊ ά'TΓaθelς κακών, οσα ημάς ev υστίρω χρόνω ύ7Γeμev€v, οΧόκΧηρα Be καϊ άττΧά καϊ άτpeμή καϊ eύBaίμova φάσματα μυoύμevoί Te καϊ e7Γ07Γτeύovτeς ev axjyy καθαρά, καθαροϊ THE PHAEDRUS MYTH wings and desire th with them to fly up, but is not able — looking up into the sky like a bird, and heeding not the things beneath — he is accounted as mad after the manner of the Fourth Sort of Madness ; because that the spirit of his Mad- ness wherewith he is possessed is the best, proceeding from the best for him who hath it, and for him who partaketh of it ; and because that he who loveth things beautiful with the spirit of this Madness upon him hath the name of Lover ; for, as hath been said, every Soul which is a Man's hath of necessity seen the Things which Verily Are — else would it not have entered into this creature ; but to call Those Things to mind, by means of these, is not easy for every Soul ; neither for those Souls which saw the Things There for a little space, nor for those unto which, when they were fallen down to the Earth, evil happened, so that they are turned to iniquity by evil communications, and forget holy things which they saw aforetime. Verily few are they which», are left having Memory present with them in sufficient | measure. These, when they see any likeness of the Things There, are amazed and cannot contain themselves any more ; but what it is that moveth them they know not, because that they perceive nothing clearly. Now of Justice and Temperance and all the other Precious Things of the Soul no glory at all shineth in the likenesses which are here ; but using dull instincts and going unto ngages, hardly do a few men attain unto the sight of that I (One Thing whereoJ^'tKeyare the i mag es. Beauty Itself, shining brightly, it was given unto them then to behold when they were of the blessed choir and went — we in the train of Zeus, and other Souls led by other Gods — and saw that great and holy sight, and were made partakers of those Mysteries which it is meet to call the most holy : the which they did then celebrate, being themselves altogether fair and clean, and with- out taste of the miseries prepared for them in the time there- after, and being chosen to be eyewitnesses of visions which are altogether fair, which are true with )^\\ ^ngleness/ which are without variablenessj which contain the fulness of jo y. Thes are the Things which our Souls did then see inroure ligh^, being themselves/pure and without the mark of this Vnich^ "^ve 320 THE MYTHS OF PLATO 6ντ€ζ καϊ ασήμαντοι τούτου, ο νυν σώμα ττερί,ψεροντε^ ονομάζομβν, οστρίου τρόττον ΒεΒβσμβυμένοι. Ύαΰτα μεν οΰν μνήμτ} κεγαρίσθω, Βι* ην ττόθω των τ6τ€ νυν μακροτερα βϊρηται, ττερί he κάΧΚου<ζ, ωσιτερ βϊττομβν, D μ€τ βκβίνων τ€ βΚαμττβν 6ν, Sedpo τ€ έΧθόντες κατζίΧήφαμβν αύτο Βία τήζ ζναρ^€στάτη<ζ αΙσθήσ€ω<ζ των ήμβτβρων στίΧβον εναργέστατα. οψις yap ήμίν οξυτάτη των Bici του σώματος έρχεται αισθήσεων fj φρόνησις ουχ οράται* Βεινούς yap αν τταρείγεν έρωτας, εϊ τι τοιούτον εαυτής εναργές εϊΒωΧον τταρείγετο εις oyfriv ιόν, και ταΧΧα οσα εραστά' νυν Βε κάΧΧος μόνον ταύτην εσγε μοΐραν, ώστ Ε εκφανεστατον είναι καϊ ερασμιώτατον. 6 μεν οΰν μη νεοτεΧής ή Βιεφθαρμενος ουκ οξέως ενθενΒε εκεΐσε φέρεται ττρος αύτο το κάΧΧος, θεώμενος αύτου την τ^Βε εττοίνυμίαν. ώστ ου σέβεται ττροσορών, αλλ* ή^ονη τταραΒούς τετράττοΒος νόμον βαίνειν εττιγειρεΐ καϊ τταιΒοστΓορεΐν, καϊ ΰβρει ττροσ- 251 ομιΧών ου ΒέΒοικεν ουδ* αισγυνεται τταρα φύσιν ήΒονήν Βιώκων. 6 Βε άργιτεΧής, 6 τών τότε πτοΧυθεάμων, όταν ΘεοειΒες ττρόσωττον ϊΒη καΧΧος ευ μεμιμημένον, ή τίνα σώματος ΙΒέαν, ττρώτον μεν έφριξε, και τι τών τότε ύττήΧθεν αύτον Βειμάτων, είτα ττροσορών ώς Θεον σέβεται, καϊ εΐ μη ΒεΒιείη την της σφόΒρα μανίας Βόξαν, θύοι αν ώς άηαΧματι καϊ θεώ τοις τταιΒικοΐς. ΙΒόντα Βε αυτόν, Β οίον εκ της φρίκης, μεταβοΧή τε καϊ ΙΒρώς καϊ θερμότης άήθης Χαμβάνει. Βεξάμενος yap του κάΧΧους την άττορροήν Βιά τών ομμάτων εθερμάνθη, η ή του τττεροΰ φύσις άρΒεται, θερμανθεντος Βε ετάκη τα ττερϊ την εκφυσιν, α ττάΧαι ύτΓΟ σκΧηρότητος συμμεμυκοτα εϊpyε μη βΧαστάνειν. rA^-^^ THE PHAEDRUS MYTH 1321 id now _ carrj;_about with usAs the fish carrieth >n-house of his shel D Let these words, then, be offered for a thanksgiving to Memory, for whose sake we, as remembering our joys that are past, have lengthened this Discourse. Now, as touching Beauty : — We beheld it shining, as hath "^ been said, amongst those other Visions ; and when we came hither, we apprehended it glittering most clearly, by means of that sense which in us is the most clear, to wit, eyesight, which is the keenest sense that the body conveyeth. But the — ► eye seeth not Wisdom. what marvellous love would Wisdom cause to spring up in the hearts of men, if she sent forth a clear likeness of herself also, even as Beauty doth, and it entered into our eyes together with the likenesses of all the other Things which be worthy of Love! But only unto Beauty hath this portion been given. Wherefore Beauty is the most evident of all, and the best beloved. Now, he who hath not lately partaken of the heavenly Mysteries, or hath been corrupted, is not quickly carried hence to that Other Place and to Beauty Itself, when he seeth the things which here are calledL after the name thereof. Where- fore, looking upon these, ^e giveth t hem/ n o t reverenc e, but, ΓλΙί delivering himself up to pleasure, after Cthe m an ner jiL-ar-beas t '^ίΤ he leapet h upon therii. desirin^/ io beget offsp ring '^ccordjagjbo 'πΓίί the flesh , and feareth not to have his conversationnn ims nesSjAnor is ashamed of following after pleasure contrar] nature. (But he who hath lately partaken, who hath beheld many of the Things There, when he seeth a face, or the figure of a person, made in the very likeness of Beauty, first his flesh trembleth, and awe of those things which he saw aforetime entereth into his heart ; then he looketh, and worshippeth the Beautiful One as a God, and, were he not afraid that men jJAt^ should account him a maniac, would offer sacrifice to his Beloved, as to a graven image and a God. Then while he looketh^ after the trft^ [^,bljn,g, ^,g jt nsp.th to happen, sweating and (unwonted heati take ^ hol d ol hiA, for he hath received the efiluxion of beauty througlTliis eyes, and is made hot, so that the wings in him are watered ; for when he is made hot, the parts where the wings sj)rout are melted, which before were closed by reason of their hardness and hindered the feathers γ 322 THE MYTHS OF PLATO εΐΓίρρυείσης Be της τροφής ωΒησε re καΐ ώρμησβ φύβσθαι άτΓΟ της ρίζης ο του τττβρου καυλός ύττο τταν το της 'ψ'νχή^ βΙΒος' ττασα yap ην το τταΚαν τττβρωτη. C Ζει ουν iv τούτω οΚη καϊ άνακηκί,εί, καϊ οττβρ το των οΒοντοφυούντων ττάθος ττβρί τους οΒόντας jlyveTat,, όταν άρτι φύωσο, κνήσίς re καΧ ά^ανάκτησις irepl τα ούλα, ταύτον Βη ΊΓβτΓονθβν η του ΤΓτβροφυεΐν άργομίνου 'ψυ'χΐ]' ζει Τ€ καϊ ατγανακτβΐ καϊ γαργαλίζεται φύουσα τα τττερά. όταν μβν οΰν βλέττουσα ττρος το του τταίΒος κάλλος, εκείθεν μέρη εττιόντα καϊ ρέοντα, α Βη Βια ταύτα Ίμερος καΧεΙταν, Βε'χρμενη τον ϊμερον άρΒηταί τε καϊ θερμαίνηται, λωφα τε D της οΒύνης καϊ ^ε^ηθεν όταν Βε χωρϊς ^ενηταν καϊ αύχμήσ^, τα των ΒίεξοΒων στόματα, rj το τττερον ορμά, συναυαίνόμενα μύσαντα άττοκλείει την βλάστην του τττεροΰ. ή δ' εντός μετά του Ιμερου άττο κεκλιμένη, ττηΒώσα οίον τα σφύζοντα, ttj ΒιεξόΒω εγχρίει εκάσττ) τη καθ^ αυτήν, ώστε ττασα κεντουμενη κύκλω η ψυχή οίστρα καϊ οΒυνάται, μνήμην Β αΰ έχουσα του κάλου ηεηηθεν, εκ δ* αμφοτέρων Ε μεμιημενων άΒημονεΐ τε τη άτοττία του ττάθους καϊ άτΓορουσα λυττα, καϊ εμμανης ούσα ούτε νυκτός Βύναται καθεύΒειν ούτε μεθ ήμεραν, ου αν η, μενειν, θεΐ Βε ττοθοϋσα οτΓου αν οϊηται, οψεσθαί τον έχοντα το κάλλος. ΙΒοΰσα Βε καϊ ετΓοχετευσαμενη ϊμερον έλυσε μεν τα τότε συμ- Ίτεφρα^μενα, άναττνοην Βε λαβοΰσα κέντρων τε καϊ ώΒίνων εληξεν, ήΒονήν δ' αΰ ταύτην ^λυκυτάτην εν τω τταρόντί 252 καρτΓουται. όθεν Βή εκουσα είναι ουκ άττολείττεται, ούΒε τίνα του καλοΰ ττερϊ ττλείονος ττοιεΐται, άλλα μητέρων Τ€ καϊ άΒελφών καϊ εταίρων ττάντων λελησται, καϊ ουσίας Be άμελειαν άττολλυμενης τταρ ούΒεν τίθεται, νομίμων Βε καϊ εύσχημονων, οίς ττρο του εκαλλωττίζετο, ττάντων κατα- φρονήσασα Βουλεύειν έτοιμη καϊ κοιμάσθαι οττου αν εα τις ε^^υτάτω του ττοθου• ττρος yap τω σεβεσθαι τον το THE PHAEDBUS MYTH ]^ 32 from growing. When, therefore, the nourishment floweth unto them, the stalks of the feathers swell, and are moved for to grow from their roots under the whole surface of \ the Soul; for aforetime the whole Soul was feathered. It ^ometh to pass then that the whole Soul doth boil and bubble ; and as it happeneth unto those who are teething, when thoir teeth are lately begun to grow, that there is an itching m their gums and distress, even so doth it happen unto the Soul of him who beginneth to put forth wings ; for his Soul boileth and is in distress and itcheth when she putteth forthXher feathers. When, therefore, she looketh upon the beauty of ner Beloved, parts (μβρη) come thence unto her in a stream (whioJi for this cause are called ΐμβροζ) ; and she, receiving them, iS watered and made hot, and cieaseth from her pain and rejoiceth., , . But ^heiLshQ is parted from her Beloved and wa xeth dry, the\ v^ (mouths ( Gf the passages ) whereb^he feathers shoot fort^ , being , ^ . parched and closed μρ . hinnjiF it Ki ri];youting of theT^ather^ \ V\ ( ( which is shut in t o getq pr^itfl^Desir^ and leapeth as a man's V ,V pulse, beating against eacti passage that withstandeth it, so \ Λ-\^^ that the whole Soul, being pricked on every side, is filled with ν ^ V frenzy and travaileth : but contrariwise, having memory of the Beautiful One, she rejoiceth ; so that this strange thing hap- fj (1 peneth unto her — her pain is mingled with joy, and she is bewildered, and striveth to find a way, but findeth none; and, AV being filled with madness, she cannot sleep by night nor stay Γ in one place by day, but runneth to and fro wistful, if per- ^^ ^ chance she may behold the One who possesseth that Beauty. And, beholding, she draweth Desire from the channel thereof unto her, and the entrances which were shut are opened, and she taketh breath and ceaseth from her prickings and travail, and instead thereof reapeth the sweetest pleasure for the present time. Wherefore willingly she departeth not, esteem- ing no one more highly than the Beloved ; but mother, and brethren, and all her friends, she forgetteth, and thinketh it of no account that her substance is wasted through neglectful- ness ; and the things which are approved of men and of good report, wherein she did aforetime take pride, all these she now doth despise, and is willing to be a slave, and make her lodging wheresoever shg may come nearest unto her Love ; for she cometh not to worship only, but because she hath 324 THE MYTHS OF PLATO κάΧΧοζ εγοντα Ιατρον €νρηκ6 μόνον των ^e^iaraiv ττονων» Β τοΰτο δε το ττάθος, ω τταΐ KoXe, 7Γ/309 ον Βή μοί ο Χο^ος, άνθρωτΓοι μεν ^Έ^ρωτα ονομάζονσι, θβοί Be ο καΧουσιν άκουσας €ΐκότω^ The Philosopher as conceived b ν Pl ato |is an ardent Lover, j^ He lives all his earthly life in a trembling hope, anH, out of his hope, sees vision s^ajidjproj^^iBsig^^ ^"^^IF Plato, keenly appreciating ffiep^^*with which expres-^^ sion of thought or feeling reacts onjbhoug ht gr feelings spares ^o^ins in showing how to give artistic form to^Myth, the natural expression (if only as by-product) of tlie^ enthusiastic philosophic ^isu^ after self-realisation or purifica tion. This is the justification of the artistic Myth, for the construction of which Plato supplies models — that it helps to moderate and refine and direct the aspirations, the hopes, the fears, the curiosity, of which Myth is the natural expression. It will be remembered what importance is attached, in the scheme of education sketched in the EepuUic, to " good form " in the mode of expressing not only literary meaning and musical eeling, but also athletic effort. The form of expression is, as t were, the vessel which contains and gives contour to the aracter which expresses itself. We must be careful to see tRat we have in our system of education good models of expression into which, as into moulds, young character may be poured. Apart from its bearing on education, the whole question of the reaction of expression on that which expresses itself is an interesting one, and may be studied in its biological rudiments in Darwin's work on the Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. 1 So Dante {Conv. iii. 12), says, "Filosofia e uno amoroso uso di Sapieiiza " : Amor is the Form, and Sapienza the Subject Matter of Filosofia {Conv. iii. 13, 14). So also Wordsworth, substituting "Poetry" for "Philosophy" (Pref. to Lyrical Ballads), " Poetry is the breath and finer spirit of all knowledge : it is the impassioned expression which is in the countenance of all Science." THE PEAEDEUS MYTH I said that we should do well, considering the complexity of the Phaedrus Myth, not to detach its Deduction of Cate- gories or doctrine of άνάμνησι,ς too much from the general context. The doctrine of ανάμνησι^; is treated by Plato, in the Phaedrus and Meno, as inseparable from the doctrine of the prenatal existence and immortality of the Soul, and is closely bound up with the Orphic doctrine of κάθαρσις and his own version of it— ^the_doctrine._of_phi^^ It is impossible, then, to pledge Plato to belief in the literal truth of the doctrine of άνάμνησι^, unless we are prepared to go with Zeller thelength of thiT^VirLg th^^t. ]y. ia in parnpst in believing that fi^ ^ g SouWa ctu a ll y exis^dT as a se paratej - porson before it w^:5" Tborn into this bodjs^and wriTpassThrough a serTes of incarnations ai'ter thedeath of this body. " If it be impossible," writes Zeller {Plato, pp. 404 ff., Eng. Tr.), "to imagine the soul as not living, this must equally hold good of the future and of the past ; its existence can as little begin with tliis-lu!s_as_end with it. S trictly speakingC it ca n/nev e^ havJv begun at_ all ; Jfor the soul being itself the source of all motion, from what c ould its m otion have proceeded ? Accord- 1 ingly Plato hardly ever mentions immortality without alluding i to pre-existence, and his expressions are as explicit and { decided about the one as the other. In his opinion they stand or fall together, and he^uses them alike to explain the facts of our spiritual life. /We therefore cannot doubt that he was thorowghly in earnest in his assumption of a pre- e ^istence . xAxia. that this pre-existence had no beginning is | so often asserted by him ^ that a mythical representation like I that of the Timaeus can hardly be allowed any weight to the contrary. We must, nevertheless, admit the possibility that in his later years he did not strictly abide by the consequences of his system, nor definitely propound to himself whether the soul had any historical beginning, or only sprang to its essential nature from some higher principle. / " If the two poles of this ideal circle, Pre-existence and Immortality, be once established, there is no evading the j doctrine of Eecollection which lies between them ; and the I notions of Transmigration and of future rewards and punish- ments appear, the moje we consider them, to be seriously 1 Phaedrus, 245 c, D ; Meno, 86 a. X '^0^'^ 344 THE MYTHS OF PLATO meant. With regard to EecoUection, Plato speaks in the above-cited passages so dogmatically and definitely, and the theory is so bound up with his whole system, that we must unconditionally reckon it among the doctrinal constituents of that system. The doctrine is an inference which could not well be escaped if once the pre-existence of the soul were admitted ; for an existence of infinite duration must have left in the soul some traces which, though temporarily obscured in our consciousness, could not be for ever obliterated. But it is also in Plato's opinion the only solution of a most important scientific question : the, question as to j^he,^pfίi=^p^'l•^^\^*y of i ndependent ^ inq uir y — of thought (transcending sensuous per- ception. Uur thought could not get beyond the Immediate and the Actual ; we could not seek for what is as yet unknown to us, nor recognise in what we find the thing that we sought for, if we had faotVnconsciously possessed jt jjglg ^w^ and were conscious of it.^ We could/ ^rm{n o conception) of Ideas , of tEe~~eternal ^ssenc^ (6ΐ things wHch is hid den /from our perception, if we had not attained to the intuition of tliese in aQormer existen^J^ The attempt of a modern work to e xclu de the theory of Eec oUec tion from the essential doctrines of the Platonic system ^ is therefore_entirely opposed to the teaching of Plato. The arguments for the truth and necessity of this doctrine are not indeed, f^com our point of view, difficult to refute ; but it is obvious that from Plato's they are seriously meant." I venture to think that the doctrine^ of άνάμνησίς, in itself, and in its Rp■tt^η σ^ is T|r>t intpnrlp.rl byPln.tn to be taken literally — that/lt is not Dogma but Myth?^ This view, for which I may appeal to the authority of Leibniz and Coleridge,* 1 Meno, 80 d if. 2 Phaedo, 73 c if. and 76 d. ^ Teichmiiller, Studien zur Gesch. d. Beqriffe, pp. 208 if. ^ Leibniz {Nouv. Ess. Avant-propos) describes the Platonic doctrine of Reminiscence as toute fahuleuse ; and Coleridge {Biog.J^L• ch. 22), speaking of "Vordsworth's Ode on the Intimations of Ιτ ϊιύιι orta liti/ from Recollections of Early 'hildhoodf^ys : ' * The od g ^was inteni Jan f o£sTTo1hjei^ prs as had been accustomed ivatchOfcLe flux and reflux of their inrnosTrnturtB, to venture at times into e twilighfT-ealms oX^onsciousne'sg;" and ^ i eeFa deep interest in modes of inmost being, to whicn they know that the attributes of time and space are inapplicable and alien, but which yet cannot be conveyed, save in symbols of time and space. For such readers the sense is sufficiently plain, and they will be as little disposed to charge Mr. Wordsworth with believing the Platonic pre- existence in the ordinary interpretation of Avords, as I am to believe that Plato " imself ever meant or taught it." THE PHAEDRUS MYTH/^ 345 ί seems to me to t)e borne out b y the passage in the Men^ dealing with άνάμνησι,ς : άνάμνησί<ζ is presented there, in accordance with Orphic belief, as becoming clearer and clearer at each incarnation, till the soul at last attains to the blessed life of a Βαί^ιων. Can it be maintained that Plato is in earnest with all the Orphic details of this passage ? — and, if not with all, with any ? It is to be noted, too, that Socrates ends by recommending his tale about άνάμνησίς entirely on practical grounds, as likely to make us more ready to take th e trouble of seeking after knowledge, /^ ere we ar e U n this il — ^ .J world) he says in effect, with Imen^lSgulties.j which perh aps f i^'t^ ive us. How are we to sa^^mirsel^s from scepticism . iiff^ decepe u s. How are we to save^^' TOfse T^s from scepticism . ^.^.^ and accidie ? ^^ } j ^7 .^, g^^^^^^ firm ly (that our mental I^Y-^ f acultie s /§o^ not/deceive usJ II^ience cannot establish in us \jp^ the beliet tKat our 6^ental^feculties) do not deceive us ; for our t ^ ^ ^ mental faculties are the conditions of science. The surest way of gettin g^ to belie v^r^^that our mental fa culti es do not / deceive us is, of course, to use them : but if the absence ov scientific proof~of their trustw"orbhiness should ever give us^^— anxiety, the persuasiveness of a Myth may comibrt us ; that is, a Myth may put us in the mood of ri^argui7ig\ about our mental faculties, but believing in themr~^~lVieno, i n argu- me ntative m ood, a sks h ow it is possible to i nvestigate fa thing 7 about which one knows a bsolute ly nothing — in tnis case. Virtue, about which Socrates professes tokaow nothing himself, and has shown that Men o kno^^ no thing. One's investigation, Meno argues, having no object whatever before it, might hit by accident on some truth — but how is one to know that it is thg^j truth one wants ? To this Socrates replies : I understand your meaning, Meno. But don't you see what a verba l sort of argument it is that youaj^ J^itro-v ducing ? You mean " that one can't investigat/eith erjwhatj o ne kno ws or what one_does noriknoy ; for (what one k nows one knows/and investigation is unnecessary ; and what one does not know one does not know, and how can one investi- gate one knows not what ? " Meno. Exactly ; and you think it is a good argument ? Socrates. No, I don't^ M. Why, pray ? 1 Meno, 81. 346 THE MYTHS OF PLATO S. I will tell you. I have heard from men and women who are wise_concerning divine things — M. What have you heard ? S. A Tale, true I believe, and great and glorious. if. What wasit ? WhoJipJ^ou? r^ Those ^pnes^ and^priestes^ whose continual study it able to give an account of (the thing s V hlch are th eir andlilso Pindar, and many other divin e poets. And ale is this — iFTs for you to consider whether you think ^jjt a true Tale: they say, "That the Soul of Man is immortal, Oaff^^BJid to-day she co meth to her End, which they call Death ; V^"^ and then afterwards is she born again, but perisheth never. yjyt ^ Wherefore it behoveth us to go through our lives observing ^jL^/-;^' religion alway: for the Souls of them from whom Persephone ^ hath received the price of ancient Sin, she sendeth hack to the ^&λΓ^ light of the Sun above in the ninth year. These he they who ' iJO become noUe 'Icings and men swift and strong and mighty in Q'^J wisdom, and are called Blesse d of them thatj come after unto all generations^ Since the Soul, then, Socrates continues, i s immort al, and N|\ has often been incarnate, and has seen both the things here i I > and the things in Hades, and all things, there is nothing which she has noTlearnt^ No wonder, thenTtHat she is able, of herself, to recall to memory whatshe f ormerlx k ne w ^ ibQutJ irt ue or anything else ; Tor, ag^'S ap^f^ is all of one_c ommon st ocj: and kind, and the Soul has^arnt all thing s, th ere is no reason why, tarting~firom Tier recollection of but one thing (this is what is lied "learning"), a man should .not,^ himself, discover „all ther t hings, i f only he hav^goodjcourage)an^^hij'k^ot inquiry for, according to this account, all inq uir/ and lea rning is " remembering." So, we must not be led away by your verbal argument. It would make us idle ; for it is an argument that slack people_Jike. But my account of the matter stirs people up to^ork and inquire. Believing~it to be the true account, I ajai willing, along with you, to inquire what Virtue is.^ The practical lesson to be drawn from the Myth contained ,^Λ^η this passage is indicated by Socrates a little further on : ^ — I There are things, he says, in the Doctrine, or Myth, of iscence on which it is hardly worth while to insist, if 1 Meno, 80 d-81 e. ^ j^^^^^ §6 a, b, c. V \r γ ^ THE PHAEDBUS MYTH 34Τ they are challenge d ; but there is one thing in its teaching which is worth maintaining against all comers — that, if we think that we ought t o investig ate wha^^ssie-danot know, we are better men, more courageou s aniViess slothfiji, than if we think that what we oonot know is something which it is neither possible to ascertain nor right to investigate. Zeller's reaso n for maintaining that the doctrine of άνάμνησις, set forth in this passage and in the Fhaedrus Myth, is to be taken literally seems to be that the doctrine is propounded by Plato | as the sole explanation of what he certainly accepted as a fact — the presence of a n a vrior i element in experience, and. moreover, is an explanation involv- ing the doctrine o f Ide aa which, it is urged, Plato wishes to be taken l iterall y. "^ I do not think that because introspection makes Plato accept as a fact the presence of an a vrio ri element in experi- ence, it follows that even the only "explanation" which occurs to him of the fact is regarded by him as " scientific." The "explanation" consists in thei assumption of Eternal Ideas which are "recollected" from a prenatal expe rience on fhe occasion of the pres entat ion, in this life, of sensible objects " resembling '^them. I go the length of th inkin g that the Eternal Ideas, as assumed in this " explanation," are, like their domicile, the Plain o f Truth, creations of^ mythology.^ It is^ . JJWn•- because Aristotle either ^ould not or would not see this, that. '\f his criticism of the do ctrine of Id eas ^ ^s a c oupmanqu4 . ' / j Milton's poem De Idea Platonica quemaamodum Aristoteles intellexit seems to me to express so happily the state of the case — that the doctrine of Eternal Ideas set forth by Plato in Myth is erroneously taken up by Aristotle as Dogma — that I venture to quote it here in full : ^ — ^ This view of the Ideas/ as we have them in the Phaedrus Mvt h is, of course, ajaije consistent with an o rthod ox view of their place in Logi c. I In Log ic the Qi5^) a.Te scientific p oints of vie-vy ^Sy means of whicITpI ienomena ^are br ought into natural ^groups a nd explained in their causal cont ext. USnswering το these scientific points of view are objectiveiy vali d Laws of .N aiure . Coutura t {de Pl at. Mythis, p. 81),'after pointing to certain ditieren ces in the accounts given m the Tim.^ Phae do, Hspilbl., 'dlld Ibuphistes, respectively^ of the Ιδέαι, ends with the remark t hat^we might complain o f ''inconsistency " Avere it'^oU tliat the whole doctrine of ίό'^αι is mythical." This,T think7 i s going too far. I t is interesting to UP t8' IlIar TjahTe f C?07M^ li. 5)"draws a close j5arallel between the Platonic ίδέαι and ' ' (Tody**T"so far as the parallel go , e s. the former will belong to "mythology" equally wit h the lat t er. • 2 Met. M. ^ * '^ Masson's Poetical Works of John Milton, vol. iii. p. 76. 348 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Dicite, sacrorum praesides nemorum deae, Tuque Ο noveni perbeata numinis Memoria mater, quaeque in immenso procul Antro recumbis otiosa Aeternitas, Monumenta servans, et ratas leges Jovis, Coelique fastos atque ephemeridas Deum, Quis ille primus cujus ex imagine Natura solers finxit humanum genus, Aeternus, incorruptus, aequaevus polo, Unusque et universus exemplar Dei ? Haud ille, Palladis gemellus innubae, Interna proles insidet menti Jovis ; Sed, quamlibet natura sit communior, Tamen seorsus extat ad morem unius, Et, mira ! certo stringitur spatio loci : Seu sempiternus ille siderum comes Caeli pererrat ordines decemplicis, Citimumve terris incolit Lunae globum ; Sive, inter animas corpus adituras sedens, Obliviosas torpet ad Lethes aquas ; Sive in remota forte terrarum plaga Incedit ingens bominis arcbetypus gigas, Et diis tremendus erigit celsum caput, Atlante major portitore siderum. Non, cui profundum caecitas lumen dedit, Dircaeus augur vidit bunc alto sinu ; Non bunc silenti nocte Pleiones nepos Vatum sagaci praepes ostendit cboro ; Non bunc sacerdos novit Assyrius, licet Longos vetusti commemoret atavos Nini, Priscumque Belon, inclytumque Osiridem ; Non ille trino gloriosus nomine Ter magnus Hermes (ut sit arcani sciens) Talem reliquit Isidis cultoribus. At tu,i perenne ruris Academi decus, (Haec monstra si tu primus induxti scbolis) Jam jam poetas, urbis exules tuae, Eevocabis, ipse fabulator maximus ; Aut institutor ipse migrabis foras. To put the matter briefly : I regard, the whole doctrine of άνάμνησις, and of jBea L• qua involved in that doctrine, as an A etiologica l l^th — plausible, comforting, and encouraging — 1 Prof. Masson (o.c. iii. 527) says: '* Tu is, of course, Plato; and bere, it seems to me, Milton intimates at the close" that he does not be lieve that the Aristotelian repr esentation of Plato's Idea, which be has been burTBsqu ing in the poem, is a true rendering'of ^Plato '^rear meaning. If it were" so —it Plato bad [really tau ght a ny s uch monstr osity ^ tBen7 "^c. I rather tT^ jnk non^ mentators on " the^poenj haVFmiS?df! its num^-ous character, and apposed Milton^mself to be ling fault with Plato." '""" THE PHAEDBUS MYTH 349 to explain the fact that Man_JftndsJhm]i^e]fo^A-^o^ iii which he can get on. The Myth is a protest against the Ignava Ratio of Menq and his like — the sophistry which excuses inacti vity b y proving,, to _the satisfaction of the inac- tive, that successful advance in knowledge and morality is impossible. IV Phaedrus, 248 D, Ε The fact that the Philosopher and the Tyrant are respect- ively first and last in a list of nine can be explained only by reference to the importance attached by Plato to 9x9x9 = 729, which, in RepuU. 587 D, Ε f see A dam's no^es), marks the superiority of the P hjlosop hep/oy^ the Tyrant in respect of Happiness. The number 72p^had a great vogue in la ter times. Plutarch, in his de animae procreatione e Timaeo, . ch. 31, makes it the number of the Sun, which we know from l the defac. in orhel unae, ch. 28, stands for νους : κατ αύτον Be τον ήΧίον θ' καϊ κ καΐ yjr^ όστις αμα τ€ τβτρά^ωνός τ€ καΐ κύβος εστί. It is also involved in the " mysterie of the I Septenary, or number seven," which is of tw o kind s — η ivjp^^^ ΒβκάΒος ββΒομάς, ί.β., ^β 7 which comes inKheseries 1, 2, J 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, l Oj and ή βκτος ΒβκάΒος εθ^/ζ,α^ "^ich is"^EEe sevenj^h t erm from unity in the series 1, 3, 9, 27, 81, 243, 729. This is both/a square^ ( = incor porea l substance) and a cube ( = corporeal ^^ubstance), ^.e.^7 X 27 and 9x9 X 9 both= 729. This is worked out by Philo in a passage ι of his Cosmopoeia Mosaica, quoted by Dr. Henry More in his I Defence of the Moral Cahhala, ch. ii. p. 164 (ed. 1662); and More's application is worth quoting : " Seven hundred and i twenty-nine is made either by squaring of twenty-seven, or | cuhicallg multiplying of nine, and so is both cuhe and square, f Corporeal, and Incorporeal. Whereby is intimated that the World shall not be reduced in the Seventh day to a mere spiritual ^ππβίβ^ατίρυ tn an ^^ςη'τ-' ρηγ^η? ^,η η(1ί|•|ίπτΊ h^t that there shall be ^ cohabitation of thd ^ Spirifr fwit h yJ Q in a mystical or moral sens^ and that~God wilfpitciynis Tent amongst us. Then shall be settled everlasting Eignteousnes 350 THE MYTHS OF PLATO 1 ^nd ( rooted in Jhg^-^Ei g^i, so long as mankind shall inhabit upon the face tnere of/'T^^ *^ Again, Dante makia 9 1 the number ofC feeatr ic^ She was ^- in her ninth jear when he first saw her (Vuirlmiova, 2); his , first greeting he recei Yed from her ni^e__jOar^/ afterwards at O^- ^'the ninth hour of ^e_da^ (F. iVi, 3); and she depa rte^^his σ^ life on the nintli day of the nintji month of the year, ^\λ] according to the Syrian style (F^ 2V! 30): — " Questo numero," /CA ' he concludes (V. Κ 30), "fu ella me desima ; per similitudine dico, e cio ihtendo cosi : Lo numero del tre e la radice del nove, peroccHe^~senza numero altro, per se medesimo moltipli- cato, fa nove, siccome vedemo manifestamente che tre via tre fa nove. Dunque se il tre e fattore per se medesimo del nove, e lo fattore dei miracoli per βέ medesimo έ tre, cio^ Padre, Figliuolo e Spirito Santo, li quali sono tre ed uno, questa donna fu accompagnata dal numero del nove a dare ad intendere, que ella era un nove, cioe un miracolo, la cui radice έ solamente la abile Trinitade^ With this may be compared a passage in Convivio, iv. 24, in which Dante, referring to Cicero, de Senectute {§ 5), as authority, says that Plato died aged eighty-one (cf. Toynbee, Oante Diet, art. "Platone," at the end, for a quotation from Seneca, Έρ. 58, to the same effect); and adds: "e io •credo che, se Cristo non fosse stato crucifisso, e fosse vivuto lo spazio che la sua vita potea secondo natura trapassare, egli sarebbe all' ottantuno anno di mortale corpo in eternale trasmutato." The contrast between ' the celestial mise en scdne of the History of the Sou l represented in the Fhaedrus Myth, and the terrestrial scenery of the great Eschatological Myths in the Phaedo, Gorgias, and BepuUic, is a pomt'on^" which some re- marks may be offered. In the Fhaedrus Myth we are mainly concerned with (the Fall and Ascension of human Soula through the HeavenlySpheres/ rintermediate between the Eartji and the ireBlov ^aXTjSela^. Reference to the^ublunary "Kegion which includes Tartarus, the !^iain of T^etS gland the Earthly Paradise (Islands of the Blesse^rTrue Sur^ce of the Earth, τα irepl ηην = ovpav6<;), is THE PHAEDEUS MYTH 351 slight and distant. In the Fhaedrus Myth we have light wings and "a TFcurad iso ; in the three other Myths mentioned, plodding feet and an Inferno and a Purgatorio. This distinction answers to a real difference in the sources on which Plat o drew for his History of the S oul. On the one hand, he was indebted to the P^1bhagorean^_Orphics, who put καθάρσια in the f orefront o f_their eschatology. On the other hand, he had at his disposal, for the selection of details, the less refinfid^I^γt hol•^ y• of the j caTa^a(7L^^,iels-lAi^ov, as taught Ι^^Νλ^ by t h^TPHft s ^^ ];ΐhftr^^_th ^ Cry stalline Sph ere, ' had been mt'erpolatedf as primum mohile] Let us turn again to the passage in the Convivio (ii. 4) in which Dante speaks of the Tenth Heaven, and read it afresh^ in the light of what has been said about the ireUov αληθβίας and the Aristotelian God :— " There are nine Moving Heavens ; and the order of ^ Phaedrus, 245 c, is the source of the thought and phraseology of Arist. Met. Λ, 1072 a 23 if. ^ '^ See Arist. Met. A, 1072 a 21-1072 b 30. 2 See p. 164 supra. y 356 THE MYTHS OF PLATO \ their position is as follows : The first that is reckoned is that -r^ of the Moon ; the second that in which Mercury is ; the ο third Venus ; the fourth the Sun ; the fifth Mars ; the sixth Jupi ter ; the sev enth Satu rn ; the eighth is that of the Stars ; ^he ninth J^^^tHaFwhicii can only be perceiv ed by the mm^r ment above mentioned, which is called Crystalli ne, oy^ia- phanou s. or wholly transparent . But outside of these Catholics suppose the Empyrean Heav en, ^hich is as much as to say the Heaven of Flam e, or the Lu mJTio us ; and they suppose this to be immovable, since it has in itself, in respect of every part, that which its m atter requ ires. And this is the reason why the primum mobile has most rapid movement : because by reason of the fervent longing which every part of it has to be joined to every part of that most divine Motion- less Heaven, it revolves within that with so grea t desire that i ts veloc ity is, as it were, in compre hensible. And this Motionless and Peaceful Heaven is the place of that Supreme Deity which alone fully j gholds i tself. This is_ the place of the blessed spirits, according as Holy Churc h, which cannot lie, will have~Tt; and this Aristo tle, to whoso understands him aright, seems to meafiTln the nrst hook jMihelo." In this doctrine of the Quiet Heaven, justly said to have the authority of Aristotle in its favour^^e have the motive of the whole ΜνϊΕ" of the Faradiso. [The ascent of Dante, ^tKrough the Mne M oving Sphere^ to the (mimoved Heaven, his~~wil lf and intellecj i moved at every stag e by "the Love M/which m avee tha-sun and ot her star s,'^ is a Myth — how y^ valuable in its regulative influence the world knows, and may yet know better — a Myth setting forth like the Myth of the S9u LCiiariots,^ .iHg^s personal effort to take his place in theH^osmos Jby "im itating " its eternal laws in his own thought andT will, not content to look always down, like the brutes, at the things beneath hiiiPoS:" the ground, but, first, lifting up his eyes to the Visible God s — the stars in their orderly courses — and^JJien thmEng out the law of_t heir ord er ; thus, as we read (in the Timaeus |47 a), rea lising the final cau se of eye s, wKic^^ s to^ ^a^en thought. The ultimate ideii\Mij Oi TliouglTT^nd ^^ilj<(as both drawn forth by the attraction of one Object— tKe Object, Plato would say, of " Philosophy," of " Theology " Aristotle and Dante would say ψ THE PHAEDBUS MYTH 357 — is thus contained in the Myth of the Farad iso, as in the Phaedrus Myth. The associations of Dante's Myth lie nearer to our modern life than those of Plato's Myth, and we may be helped to appreciate the latter through the former. In both we have models of ^ what a r efin ed(.My th ought tobe. It ought to be based on old tradition, and yet must not fetter, but rather give new freedom to, present-day thinking. It is impossible to define, or even describe, the aid which a refined mythology, such as that of Dante, brings to a man's life, for the aid which it brings is inseparable from the charm under which his personal study of it has at last brought him : -χρη τα τοιαύτα ωσιτερ iiraSeiv ίαντω} The τΓβΒίον οΧηθεία<ζ of the Phaedrus Myth, which thus answers to Aristotle's κινούν ου κινονμβνον, or God, and to Dante's Unmoved Heaven, or Empyrean, the dwelling-place of God, holds an important position in the Neo-Platonic philosophy. The passage in which Plotinus describes it is one of th/most highly-strung pieces of philosophical writings in the whole of his Enneads, and need not be entered upon here ; ^ but Plutarch's description of it may be given. It occurs in his de defectu oraculorum^ where he records the doctrine of a " Barbarian Stranger," who, rejecting alike the view of Plato, that there is onl y one Co sifljis, and the view of | others, that the numb er of Cosmi is infi nite J and that of I others still, that there are five of them, maintains that there J are exactly 183^ of them, arranged i n the figure of a triangle ; the sides of which they _jorm, touching on e an other — 60 to each side, and on e m each angle. These Cosmi move round along^e sides of the triangle in procession, άτρβμα ττβριϊόντας ωσττβρ iv χορβία ; and the area of the triangle which these moving Cosmi make is called the Plain of Truth, ττβΒίον αληθβίας. In thisPlain/abide unmoved the r ation es (\6yoi)\ formae (εϊΒη), exemplaria {ιταραΒεί^μ,ατα), of all things whichl ever have, and ever shall, come into being ; and round about! 1 Phaedo, 114 D.^^ "" 2 Enn. vi. 7. 13. Two sentences from it will show its character sufficiently : — iv αύτφ 6 αΚηθίν6$ vovs πέφνκ€ ττΧανα,σθαι• ττέφυκβ 5' έν ovaiais ιτΧανασθαι σννθίουσων των ούσιων rats αύτοϋ irXavats. ττανταχου δ' avrbs έστι• μένονσαν οΰν έ'χβι την ττλάνην. ή δέ ιτΧάνη avrq! iv τφ της αληθείας ΤΓβδίφ, οΰ ούκ iκβaίv€ι. 3 Ch. 22. ^ Half of the number of th^ days in the year, as a friend suggests to me. Cf. the number of the βασιλεύς (729), Eep. 587 E. MYTHS OF pl: Verities ip §J2Ig M Eternity (α Ιών), which flows φόνος) upon Tne moving Uosmi. jpiuman Souls, ive virtuously, have sight of these Eternal Verities once in ten thousand_years. _The holiest mysteries of this world are but aTHream of that Pex£a£it_^velation. " This Myth of the Barbaria^ Stranger," says the narrator of it in Plutarch's DialogueT^I listened to as though I were being initiated. The Stranger offered no demonstration or other evidence of the trutF"of it?^^ The Myth ^ is a good instance of the way in which the later Platonists used Plato's suggestions — and, it must be added, Aristotle's ; for in the de Coelo^ αΙών, outside the Ουρανός, where there is neither τόττος, nor κβνόν, nor 'χρόνος, nor μβταβοΧη, is identified with God, whose life is described as a7ra^27S*~ αρίστη, αύταρκβστάτη. Platonists had, indeed, almost as rich a mine to work in Aristotle as they had in Plato himself.^ ΒβίσΓδΊί leave the spji^eet-af-4he influence of the Fhaedrus Myth as tran smitted^^t o Dante yphrough the de Coelo and I ^ Metaphysics — it sho ws ^ ^ ^ί^Φ^ r.nomical framework of the Faradiso, and_jtlifi notion of L' Amor che move 11 Sole e Γ altre stelle — ^ v^may notice another notion ver^_pTominent in the Faradiso which seems to have taken forni in the course of an evolution > starting from the Fhaedrus My^, or the eschatology of which that Myth is the most eminent prod uct. Tl refer to the τκΓ — — notion that produced by This notion is various he actioi or characters, are of the stars) especially o f thejlaiiets. d eeply embe dggd^^ in [_ the structure The s pirits fwhom Dante Tsees in the ihree lower " ori^ exerted! Faradiso. >heres are seen by iumthere r * Referrea to by Dr. ^ i. 9. 279 a 16. ^ The Axiochus (371 b) is quite un-Platonic, and indeed singular, in its view of the ireUov άληθ€ία$. The place where Minos and the other Judges of the Dead sit is called the TreSfei' άληθβίαί, and is on the other side of Acheron and Cocytus, i.e. down mjiart^'us ; whereas the ^ιμών of the Judgment-Seat in the ide^{ t\ese rivers, va'ifil^iA the Republic is certainly outside Ά 4i> THE PHAEDRUS MYTH ambitious, unchastiJat In the Dante sees spirits 359 plane^ry spher es t^vHose c haract~erg< 6n_^Eai:th/^re su ch as t heir various planets determined ; thesa, Ipytfever, being^eyon4 ^^^ i^tf4f^ f 'S£,r^^ Eariji jland its inn uence, are no l pnp er | in ^ u man j^orirj fbu enclosed i n/an enveln-nft^ of h'^j-h^ — they sne araSntl^so le [spherical/fi ike the starj ; for the sphere! i s tf? y^€r!ec ( which ^the pureTaethereal vehicle na turally takes . Now, ifwe turn from the Paradiso\o (the Phaed rusJM.j W\ we find that opevral of, " ^^ W there Soul s are /V opeurat o f, follow fih the train oi7"va^pus Planet-GodsN Zeus, Ares, and others, m their ascenj/to the I Empy rean , or irehiov αλνθβί ας, and show /corresponding tem- ngj^^ents of charac ter when (they are afterwards bgriLan the Ihis mythological explanation of the varieties of tem- perament may be compared with that offered by Macrobius in his Commentary on Cicero's So mniu m Scijpionis, which 1 cannot do better than give in Professor DilFs words : ^ — The Commentary on the Dream of Scijpio enables one to understand how d evou t [minds^ could even to the last remain attached to pa ganis m. It presupposes rather than expounds the theology of Neoplatonism. Its chief motive is rather moral or devotional than s peculati ve. (The One, supreme, unapproachable» i neffab le, residing in the highe st heave n, is assume ^ as the source of mind and life , p enetratin g(all things, from ^ne star in the {highest ether^ to the lowest lorm of a mma l existence./^The Universe"is'G-od's temple, filled with His presenc fi. The unseen, inconceivable Author created ^ffom His es^gj^ce ipure min^ in the likenes sQf -Hj^m^ lf. I n contact with i^ ^e|TmJji m|ii€genefat ^βΚ and , ^co^&8 rt of intoxicatyipn and oblivion of the world from which it intoxi Roman Society Western Empire, pp. 90, 91. V THE MYTHS ^'■Y^-Xf OF PLATO comes, in some cases deeper than in others, of Soul among bodil^_fa r^}\. only a prison , or rathe a s Scond^dea th, the death to sin sath Thus s a kind of death ; th( in( tomb/ which cannot be iPftriKr ^mfa vi; lifFusion body i s ^y -^ .c^ V V p«irtici Here, in the Commentary . oC- Macrob ius, two things kept separate in the FhaedrusMjth — the Fall of Souls^ the Earth TO TTTepoppve cv, an . rticular gods- η/\/ W^co mes int o f^^c ( ^ J a complex te rnpe fament th^ir (Inembership of^ the reti nue of a re combineji^ . (Ι ϊΙβ in its FaUj that ρ Soul VQ^i i tlie"gocls iession/ ^ , and deriv es, i t would seem/ 3m touch with them ^11 in sue fr. ^ (^^ Ά jS^W' ^^^^ regard to the ca use of tli^Fal l of Sou ls — the Ήβο- ^N Platonic mythology, ^hile retajcing the i rrepoppv eiv explana- tion given ^^^ in th e ^lagc^r ^g/dwells more p articu larly on the ^3eas_ of ^Jllugg b) and intoxication. Soulsl remain at peace above till, like Narcissus, they see themsel vesTref iected) in the mirror of Dionysus : ^ this is (flge flowing stream of sense) and g eneratio n, into 3^]i jcli thp y p^^ng^e^ ^istaking t he ima ^ for' reautyT' With (S ief idea of[illusiSi n}lius_illustrated, theTHea of intoxication connecfeitselRSurally. ( The ^ream of sens e, the ^ y^ mirror of Dionysus, i s<^e bowl of Dio nysu^. Plunging into W^ /\ ijJ4)h eg gulj (jrinSs forget fuln^ of" Eternal Trut h, and the \ yy y/w^B ml; A which it is b orn thereatt^ t^'lis ^tlie ατ τη^αιον Χηθης. 1 ^/f T^^e are soulgT which haye^ ot ar unk so^ deeplv)as others of ^ )θηψ wnicr There are "retain some recoUec" ' /y^is l& up.) There are /the " dU:^ ^:aauls ^ ^ Jof Hera clitus.^ Thevy Jyp &fclll re toin_s ome recoUecEion oij^e ^embodied sta^ , and in ^Jl•^ ^ this^fearthly life hearken to th e ^:οο^όαίμων) wh^^omes with them m theiy^KaUooo^Y' The comparison ofyb he b ody to a ^ Macrobius, Somn. i. 12, 68. See Lobeck, Aglaoph. pp. 932 if., where other writers are quoted for this view of the formation of human temperament. The seven planets likewise connect themselves with the seven days of the week, and the seven metals {έκάστφ των αστέρων ϋλη rts auayerai, ηλίφ μέν ό xpvaos, aeXrjPTi δέ apyvpos, "Apec σίδηροί, Κρόνφ μόλιβδοί, Ad ήλ€κτρο$, Έρμτ} κασσίτ€ρο$, ΆφροδίτΎ} χαλκό?, Schol. on Pindar, Isthm. v. 2) ; consequently the Mithraic stair, κλΐμαξ έπτάττυλος, represented the seven planetary spheres, through which the Soul passes, by seven metals : the first step, that of Saturn, was of lead ; the second, that of Venus, of tin ; the third, that of Jupiter, of brass ; the fourth, that of Mercury, of iron, and so on, the days of the week being taken in backward order : see Lobeck, Aglaoph. p. 934. Further, there are seven colours, seven strings, seven vowels, seven ages of a man's life, as well as seven planets, seven days, and seven metals (cf. Dieterich, Mithrasliturgie, pp. 186 if.) ; also seven seals, some of them associated with differently coloured horses, and seven Is, in Eev. v.-viii. '2 Plotin. Ennead, iv. 3. 12, vol. i. p. 247, ed. Kirchhoff. ^ By water, Heracliti Mel, p. 30. THE PHAEDBUS MYTH 361 Heraclitean r iv er,Lwhich occurs in Timaeu s_(43 Λ, doubtless contributed to this Neo-Platonic mythol ogy of the Fall . J The second line of influence connecting fthe Faradiso with the Fhaedrus\Myth has, as I said, two strands, the first of which consiste of the Somnium Scipionis and its antecedents, chiefly Stoical. The links between the Phaedrus Myth and Somnium Scipionis (which Dante undoubtedly knew) ^ are in- dicated by Dieterich in passages referred to above,^ and need not be specified here ; but the second strand, consisting of the astronomical apocalypses, has scarcely received the attention which it deserves, and I venture to say something about it. It is remarkable how little Dante is indebted in the Paradiso to the Revelation of St. John. The seven references in the Paradiso to that Apocalypse noted by Dr. Moore {Studies in Dante, First Series, Index to Quotations, 1) concern details only. The Revelation of St. John has indeed nothing service- able for Dante's purpose except details, for its scheme is quite different from that of the Paradiso. It is very doubtful if the writer knows anything of the astronomy of the eight Moving Heavens and the Unmoved Heaven ; at any rate, if he does, he makes no use of it ; his scheme is not that of the Ascension of a Soul through Heaven after Heaven. The scene is always changing from Heaven to Earth, and to Hell ; and the New Jerusalem, in the description of which the Vision culminates, descends out of the New Heaven, and is established upon the New Earth. It is to apocalypses of an entirely different type that the Paradiso is related — to apocalypses in which the whole mise en scdne of the eschatological drama is astronomical, and the preoccupation of the writers is not, as that of the writer of the Revelation of St. John largely is, with the Keign of theM essiah j on E ar^jy^v^T• a / αυτούς ττοοησαι, και ηττορουν ούτε yap οττως αττοκτειναιεν εΐ'χρν καϊ ώσττερ τους Υι^αντας κεραυνώσαντες το ^ενος άφανίσαιεν — αΐ τιμαΧ yap αύτοΐς καϊ Ιερα τα τταρα των άνθρώττων ηφανίζετο — ούθ^ οττως εωεν άσεΤ^αίνειν, μoyις Βη 6 Ζευς εννοησας \εyει, οτι Αοκώ μοι, εφη, βχ^εον μη'χανην, ως αν εϊεν τε άνθρωποι καϊ τταύσαιντο της D άκοΧασίας ασθενέστεροι yεv6μεvoι. νυν μεν yap αυτούς, εφη, Βιατεμώ Βίχα εκαστον, καϊ αμα μεν ασθενέστεροι έσονται, αμα Βε γ^ρησιμώτεροι ήμΐν Βια το ττλείους τον αριθμόν yεy ονεναί' καϊ βαΒιουνται ορθοϊ εττϊ Βυοΐν σκεΧοΐν. εαν δ' ετι Βοκωσιν ασέΚηαίνειν καϊ μη εθεΧωσιν ησυγίαν άyειv, ττάΧιν αΰ, εφη, τεμώ Βίγα, ωστ εφ* ενός ττορεύσονται σκεΧους άσκωΧίζοντες. Ύαΰτα είττων έτεμνε τους άνθρώττους Ε Βίχ^α, ωσττερ οι τα 6α τέμνοντες καϊ μέΧΧοντες ταριγεύειν, ή ωσττερ οι τα ώα ταΐς θριξίν. οντινα Βε τεμοι, τον ΆττόΧΧω εκεΧευε τ6 τε ττρόσωττον μεταστρεφειν καϊ το τον αυγενος ήμισυ ττρος την τομην, ΐνα θεώμενος την αυτοΰ r/A?}atv κοσμιώτερος εϊη 6 άνθρωττος, καϊ ταΧΧα ιάσθαι εκεΧευεν. 6 Βε το τε ιτρόσωττον μετέστρεφε, καϊ συνέΧκων τταντα'χόθεν το Βερμα εττϊ την yaστεpa νυν καΧουμενην, ωσττερ τα σύστταστα βαΧάντια, εν στόμα ττοιών άττεΒει κατά μεσην την yaστεpa, ο Βη τον ομφαΧον καΧοΰσι. καϊ 191 τας μεν άΧΧας ρυτίΒας τας ττοΧΧας εξεΧεαινε καϊ τα στήθη Βιηρθρου, ε'χων τι τοιούτον opyavov, οίον οΐ σκυτοτόμοι, ττερϊ τον καΧόττοΒα Χεαίνοντες τας των σ κυτών ρυτίΒας' 6Xίyaς Βε κατέΧιττε, τας ττερϊ αυτήν την yaστεpa καϊ τον ομφαΧόν, μνημεΐον είναι του τταΧαιοΰ ττάθους. εττειΒη ουν THE TWO SYMPOSIUM MYTHS 401 their parents : and they were terrible by reason of their strength and valour ; and their hearts were proud, and they made assault upon the Gods ; for that which Homer telleth concerning-Ephialtes and Otus is told concerning them — that they essayed to go up into Heaven for to lay hands on the Gods. Wherefore Zeus and the other Gods took counsel what they should do, and were in doubt ; for they were not minded to slay them, as they slew the giants, with thunder- bolts, and to make men to cease utterly from the Earth, for then would the worship and the sacrifices which men render unto the Gods also cease ; nor were they minded to let them go on in their iniquities. At last after a long while Zeus bethought him of this that followeth, and said : " I have found out a way, methinks, of keeping men alive, and yet making them weaker, so that they shall cease from their wickedness : I will cut each one of them in twain ; and so shall they be made weaker, and also more serviceable for us, having been increased in number; and they shall walk upright on two legs ; and if I see them again behaving themselves frowardly and not willing to live peaceably, I will cut them yet again in twain," he said, " so that they shall go hopping on one leg." Having spoken thus, he straightway began to cut men in twain, as one cutteth apples for pickling, or eggs with hairs ; and each one whom he cut in twain he delivered unto Apollo, and commanded him to turn round the face and half of the neck towards the cut, so that the fellow, beholding it, might behave himself more seemly ; likewise the other parts did he command Apollo to dress : and Apollo turned the face round, and pulled the skin together from all parts over that which is now called the belly, even as one draweth together a purse, and the one opening which was left he closed and made fast in the middle of the belly — this is that which they now call the navel ; and smoothing out all the other wrinkles every- where, he fashioned the breasts with an instrument like unto• that wherewith cobblers smooth out the wrinkles of the leather round the last ; but he left a few wrinkles about the belly itself and the navel,eto be for a memorial of that which had been done of old. 2d 402 THE MYTHS OF PLATO η φύσις Βίχα έτμηθη, ττοΘουν βκαστον το ήμισυ το αυτού ξυνηβί, καΧ ΤΓβριβάΧλοντες τας 'χβ.ϊρας και συμττΧβκόμβνοι άΧΚηΚοις^ ΙτΓΐΘυ μουντές συμφϋναι, άττβθνησκον ύττο του Β Χιμοΰ και της αΧλης άρτιας Βια το μηΒβν eOeXeiv χωρίς άλΧηΧων Ίτοιβίν. καΐ οττότε τι άττοθάνοι των ημίσεων, το Be Χειφθβίη, το Χειφθεν αΧλο ίζητβι καΐ συνεττΧεκετο, εϊτε γυναικός της οΧης εντύχοι ημίσει, ο Βη νυν ηυναΐκα καΧου- μεν, εϊτ άνΒρός' κα\ ούτως άττώΧΧυντο, εΧεησας Be 6 Ζευς άΧΧην μηχανην ττορίζεται, και μετατίθησιν αυτών τα αΙΒοΐα εις το ττρόσθεν τέως yap καΐ ταύτα έκτος είχον, C καΐ εηεννων και ετικτον ουκ εις άΧΧηΧους, αλλ' εις <γήν, ωσττερ οι τεττι^ες. μετέθηκε τε ούν ούτως αυτών εις το ττρόσθεν και Βια τούτων την ηενεσιν εν άΧΧηΧοις εττοίησε, Βια τού άρρενος εν τω θηΧει, τώνΒε ένεκα, ϊνα εν ττ) συμττΧοκη άμα μεν εΐ άνηρ 'γυναικί εντύχοι, ^εννωεν καΐ yiyvoiTO το ^ενος, άμα δ* εΐ καΐ άρρεν άρρεν ι, ττΧησμονη ηούν y'lyvoiTO της συνουσίας καΐ Βιατταύοιντο καΐ εττΐ τα 'ipya τρετΓοιντο καΐ τού άΧΧου βίου εττιμεΧοΐντο. "Εστί δ^ D ούν εκ τόσου ό έρως έμφυτος άΧΧηΧων τοις άνθρώττοις και της αρχαίας φύσεως συνα^ω^εύς και εττιχειρών ττοιησαι εν εκ Βυοΐν και ιάσασθαι την φύσιν την άνθρωττίνην. "Έίκαστος ούν ημών εστίν άνθρωττου ξύμβοΧον, άτε τετμημενος ωσττερ αί '>^ητται, εξ ενός Βύο. ζητεί Βη άει το αυτού έκαστος ξύμβοΧον. όσοι μεν ούν τών άνΒρών τού κοινού τμήμα εισιν, ο Βη τότε άνΒρό^υνον εκαΧεΐτο, φιΧο^ύναικες τ είσι καΐ οι ττοΧΧοΙ τών μοιχών εκ τούτου τού Ε γένους ηεηόνασι, και οσαι αύ γυναίκες φίΧανΒροί τε και μοιχεύτριαι, εκ τούτου τού γένους yiyvovTai. οσαι Βε τών yυvaικώv yυvaικoς τμήμα εισιν, ου ττάνυ αύται τοις άνΒράσι τον νουν ττροσεχουσιν, άΧΧά μάΧΧον ττρος τάς yυvaΐκaς τετραμμεναι είσί, και αι εταιρίστριαι εκ τούτου τού yεvoυς yiyvovTai. όσοι Βε άρρενος τμήμα εισι, τα άρρενα Βιώκουσι, καΐ τέως μεν αν τταΐΒες ώσιν, άτε τεμάχια οντά τού άρρενος, φιΧούσι τους άνΒρας καΐ χαίρουσι συy κατ α κείμενο ι 192 καϊ συμττετΓXεyμεvoι τοις άνΒράσι, και εισιν ούτοι βέΧτιστοι τών τταίΒων καϊ μειρακίων, άτε άνΒρειότατοι οντες φύσει, φασί Βε Βη τίνες αυτούς αναίσχυντους είναι, ψευΒόμενοί' THE TWO SYMPOSIUM MYTHS 403 Now when the original creature was cut in twain, the one half, longing for the other half, went to meet it, and they cast their arms around one another, and clung unto one another, eagerly desiring to be made one creature ; and they began to die for lack of food and of all other things that a man must provide for himself; for neither would eat aught save together with the other : and when one of the halves died, and the other was left, that which was left went about seeking for another half, and when it happened upon the half of that which aforetime was a woman — this half we now call woman — or upon the half of that which was a man, joined itself unto it : and thus did they perish. Then Zeus had compas- sion upon them, and brought forth a new device : — He brought their privy parts round to the front — for before that time their privy parts were set in the outerpart of their bodies, and they had not intercourse one with another, but with the earth, as grasshoppers. So he changed them and caused them to have intercourse one with another, to the end that, if a man happened upon a woman, there might be propagation, and if male happened upon male, there might be satisfaction, and then an end made of it, both turning to other things and minding them. Of such oldness is the love of one another implanted in us, which bringeth us again into the primitive state, and endeavoureth of two to make one and to heal the division of Human Nature. Every human creature, then, is a counterpart, being a half cut flat like unto a flounder, and alway seeketh his own counterpart. They who are the halves of that composite nature which was then called Man-Woman are the kind whereof the most part of adulterers are ; and of this sort likewise are women which lust for men and are adulteresses. But those women who are halves of the whole which was Woman take little heed of men, but rather turn them to companionship with women ; and those males which are halves of the whole which was male, go after the male : while they are boys, inasmuch as they are slices of the male, they love men and take pleasure in companionship with men ; these be of all boys and youths the best, inasmuch as they are by nature the most manly : some, indeed, say that they are without shame ; but herein they speak falsely; for it is not by reason of 404 THE MYTHS OF PLATO ου yap vir άναισγυντία^; τούτο Βρώσι,ν, αλλ' ύττο θάρρου^ζ καΧ άνΒρβίας καΐ άρρβνωττίας, το ομοίον αύτοΐ^; άσιταζόμβνοι, /ιεγα he τβκμήρίον καϊ yap τεΧεωθβντες μόνοι άιτοβαίνουσιν eU τα τΓοΧιτικα άνΒρβς οΐ τοιοΰτοί. Ιττβώαν δε άνΒρωθώσι, Β τΓαώβραστονσί καϊ ττροζ ^άμου^ καϊ τταίΒοττοίίας ου ττροσ- βγουσι τον νουν φύσβί, αλλά ύττο του νομού αναγκάζονται* αλλ* βξαρκβΐ αύτοΐ<ζ μ€τ άΧλήΧων καταζην ά^άμοι^. πτάν- Tft)9 μ€ν ουν 6 τοιούτος ΊταιΒβραστής Τ6 καϊ φιλβραστης yijveTai, ael το ξυyyeve<ζ άστταζόμενος. όταν μβν ουν καϊ αύτω βκβίνω βντύ'χτ) τω αυτού ήμίσβι καϊ 6 τταιΒβραστης καϊ C αλλθ9 Ίτάς, τ6τ€ καϊ θαυμαστά βκττλήττονται φιλία re καϊ οίκ€ΐ6τητι καϊ βρωτι, ουκ βθβλοντβς, ώς βττος elweiv, γωρίζβ- σθαι άΧΚηΚων ούΒβ σμικρόν 'χρόνον. καϊ οι ΒιατεΧούντβς μ€Τ αλληΧων Βια βίου ουτοί βίσιν, οι ούΒ* αν βγοιεν elirelv, 6 τι βούλονται σφίσι τταρ αΧΚήΧων yίyveσθaι, ούΒβ yap αν Βόξβιβ τούτ elvai ή των άφροΒισίων συνουσία, ώ? άρα τούτου βνεκα βτβρος ίτέρω 'χαίρει ξυνων οΰτως έττϊ μeyά\η<ί D σίΓουΒης* αλλ' ahXo τι βουΧομενη ίκατβρου ή ψυχή Βή\ΐ} εστίν, ο ου Βύναται eliretv, αλλά μαντβύβται ο βούΧβται καϊ αΐνίττβται. καϊ el αύτοΐς iv τω αύτω κατακειμίνοις €ΊΓΐστας 6 "Έίφαιστος, έχων τα opyava, epoiTo• " Tt €σθ' ο βούΧεσθε, ω ανθρωττοι, ύμΐν τταρ άΧΧηΧων yeveσθaι ; " καϊ el άτΓορούντας αυτούς ττάΧιν epoiTO' "''Αρά ye τούΒε €πιθυμεΐτ€, ev τω αύτω yeveσθaι ο τι μάΧιστ άΧΧηΧοις, ώστε καϊ νύκτα καϊ ήμέραν μη άττοΧείττεσθαι άΧΧηΧων ; el Ε yap τούτου εττιθυμεΐτε, έθέΧω υμάς συντήξαι καϊ συμφύσαι εΙς το αυτό, ώστε Βύ^ οντάς eva yeyovevai καϊ €ως τ αν ζήτ€, ως eva οντά, KOivfj αμφότερους ζην, καϊ εττειΒαν άτΓοθάνητε, εκεί αύ εν " ΚιΒου άντϊ Βυεΐν eva είναι κοινή τεθνεωτε* αλλ' οράτε, εΐ τούτου εράτε καϊ εξαρκεΐ ύμΐν, αν τούτου τύχητε•^^ ταύτα άκουσας ϊσμεν οτι ούΒ' αν εις εξαρνηθείη ούΒ* άλλο τι αν φανείη βουΧομενος, αλλ' άτεχνώς οϊοιτ αν άκηκοεναι τούτο, ο ττάΧαι άρα εττεθύμει, συν€Χθων καϊ συντακεϊς τω ερωμενω εκ Βυεΐν εΙς yεvεσθaι. τούτο THE TWO SYMPOSIUM MYTHS 405 shamelessness that they do this, but by reason of the courage and manliness in them, which their countenance declareth. Wherefore do they greet joyfully that which is like unto themselves : and that this I say concerning them is true, what foUoweth after showeth ; for afterward when these are grown up, they alone of all men advance to the conduct of politiques. Now when these are grown up to be men, they make youths their companions, and their nature inclineth them not to wedlock and the begetting of children ; only the law con- straineth them thereto : for they are content to pass their lives with one another unwedded, being lovers one of another, and always greeting that nature which hath kinship with their own. When, therefore, one of these happeneth upon the very one who is his own other half, then are the two con- founded with a mighty great amazement of friendship and kin- ship and love, and will not — nay, not for a moment — be parted from each other. These be they who all their life through are alway together, nor yet could tell what it is they wish to obtain of each other — for surely it is not satisfaction of sensual appetite that all this great endeavour is after : nay, plainly, it is something other that the Soul of each wisheth — something which she cannot tell, but, darkly divining, maketh her end. And if Hephaestus came and stood by the two with his tools in his hand, and asked of them saying, " What is it, men, that ye wish to obtain of each other ? " and when they could not answer, asked of them again saying, " Is it this that ye desire — to be so united unto each other that neither by night nor by day shall ye be parted from each other ? If it is this that ye desire, I will melt and fuse you together so that, although ye are two, ye shall become one, and, as long as ye live, shall both live one common life, and when ye die, shall be one dead man yonder in Hades, instead of two dead men: see now, if it be for this ye are lovers, and if the getting of this is all your desire." We know well that there is none who would say nay unto this, or show a wish for aught else; yea, rather, each one would think that this which was now promised was the very thing which he had alway, albeit unwittingly, desired — to be joined unto the beloved, and• to be melted together with him, so that the twain should become one: the cause whereof 406 THE MYTHS OF PLATO . 97 if. • 2 0. et D. 126. 3 Psyche, i. 99-102. * 0. et D. 137 ff. δ 0. et D. 150 if. β 0. et D. 157 if. 436 THE MYTHS OF PLATO etymology of Βαίμονβς is discussed and Hesiod's verses about the Βαίμονβς βτηγβόνίου are quoted, and the Laws, iv. 713, and Politicus, 272, where the Myth of the Golden Age of Cronus, when Βαίμονβ^ζ ruled over men," is told, can fail to see that the Hesiodic account of Βαίμονες has a great hold on Plato's imagination ; and it may be that even the φύΧακες of the Republic — men with gold in their nature (as the βττίκονροί have silver, and the artisans and husbandmen have copper and iron) — are somehow, in Plato's imagination, parallel to Hesiod's φύλακες θνητών ανθρωττων, the spirits of the men of the Golden Age} But we must not forget that there is a difference between Plato's Βαίμονες of the Laws and Politicus and of Diotima's Discourse, and Hesiod's Βαίμονες, which is greater than the obvious resemblance. Hesiod's Βαίμονες ετΓίγθόνίοί are the spirits of deceased men — as are Pindar's ήρωες ayvoL (Meno, 81 c) ; but the Βαίμονες of the Laws and Politicus, who rule over men in the Golden Age, are not spirits of deceased men, but beings of an entirely different order — Gods, who were created Gods, to whom provinces on Earth were assigned by the Supreme God — ol κατά τους τοτΓονς συνάργοντες τω μεηίστω Βαίμονι θεοί, as they are described in Po^^^zczis, 272 Ε ; and in Diotima's Discourse το Βαιμόνων, headed by Eros, is clearly set forth as an order of divine beings essentially superhuman, not spirits of deceased men. They are, I take it, of the same rank as, indeed prob- ably identical with, the ^εννητοί θεοί of the Timaeus — created before men, to be managers of human affairs on behalf of the Supreme God.^ In Eep. v. 468 E, on the other hand, ^ This parallel is suggested by Mr. Adam in a note on Republic, 468 e, and worked out by Mr. F. M. Cornford in an interesting article on "Plato and Orpheus" in The Classical Review, December 1903. 2 Chalcidius, in his Commentary on the Timaeus, is at pains to show (cap. cxxxv.) that the Platonic δαίμονες and the Souls of deceased men are two dis- tinct orders : — "Plerique tamen ex Platonis magisterio, daemorias putant aiiimas corporeo munere liberatas : laudabilium quoque virorum aethcreos daemonas, improborum vero nocentes, easdemque animas anno demum millesimo terrenum corpus resumere. Empedoclesque non aliter longaevos daemonas fieri has animas putat. Pythagoras etiam in suis aureis versibus : Corpore deposito cum liber aethera perges, Evades hominem factus deus aetheris almi. Quibus Plato consentire rainime videtur, cum in Politia tyranni animam facit excruciari post mortem ab ultoribus, ex quo apparet aliam esse animaru, alium daemonem : siquidem quod cruciatur et item quod cruciat diversa necesse sit. Quodque opifex Deus ante daemonas instituit quam nostras animas creavit ; THE TWO SYMPOSIUM MYTHS 437 Plato's use of the term Βαίμονβς is strictly Hesiodic — he is speaking not of such Gods at all, but of the spirits of deceased men of the Golden Class. As Mr. Adam, in his note on the passage, says, " Plato compares his ' golden citizens ' with the heroes of the Hesiodic golden age. He would fain surround them with some of the romantic and religious sentiment that clung around the golden age of Greek poetry and legend." The two doctrines of Βαίμονβς which we find in Plato — that enunciated in the Golden Age Myth and Diotima's Discourse, and that adopted from Hesiod in Hep. v. 468 Ε — were both taken over by the Stoics, and accommodated to the tenets of their " physical science." According to the Stoics, the Soul, ψυχή, is material, σωματική, but its matter is rarer and finer (άραιότβρορ and \€7Γτομ€ρ6στ€ρον — Chrysippus apud Plutarch de Stoic. Repugn. 41) than that of the body. The Soul is, in fact, ττνβυμα βνθβρμον, " hot air, or breath." ^ When Souls leave their earthly bodies they do not immedi- ately perish. According to Cleanthes, they all retain their individuality until the Conflagration, μ^γ^ρι της έκττνρώσβως : according to Chrysippus, only the Souls of Wise Men.^ At the Conflagration, however, all Souls perish as individuals — are dissolved back into the one substance, the elemental fire, God, whose άττοσιτάσματα, or sundered parts, they were during the term of their individual existence. When Souls leave their earthly bodies, they rise into the Air which occupies the space between the Earth and the Moon, τον ντΓο σεΚήνην τόττον.^ That the dissolution of, at any rate, the majority of Souls inhabiting this aerial space takes place before the Conflagration is clearly the view of Marcus Aurelius in a curious passage (Comment, iv. 21), in which he meets the difficulty of the Air having room for so many separate beings. Eoom, he says, is always being made in the quodque has indigere auxilio daemonum, his voluerit illos praebere tutelam. Quasdam tamen animas, quae vitara eximie per trinam incorporationem egerint, virtutis m<'rito aereis, vel etiam aethereis, plagis consecrari putat, a necessitate incorporationis immunes." The whole passage relating to Daemons in the Com- mentary of Clialcidius (cxxvi. -cxxxv.) is interesting. He compares the Daemons of Plato with the angels of the ifebrews. ^ Diog. Laert. vii. 157. ^ o.c. vii. 157. ' Posidonius, in Sext. Phys. i. 73. 438 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Air for new-comers by the progressive dissolution of their predecessors, just as room in the Earth is always made for new bodies by the progressive dissolution of those earlier buried : — ei Βίαμβνουσιν al ψυχαί, ττώς αντας βξ ά'ώίου γωρβΐ 6 άηρ ; 7Γω9 δε η yij 'χωρεί τα των €κ τοσούτου αΙώνος θατττομβνων σώματα; ώσττβρ yap ivOdSe ή τούτων 7Γ/?09 ηντινα βΤΓίΒίαμονην μβταβοΧη καϊ ΒίάΧυσίς χωράν άΧλοις νεκροΐς ττοίβΐ, όντως αϊ et? τον akpa μβθιστάμεναυ 'sjrvyai, €7γΙ ττοσον συμμβίνασαι, μβταβάΧΧουσι καν χεονται καϊ βξάΐΓτονταί, eU τον των οΧων σττβρματίκον \oyov άναΧαμβανόμβναί, καϊ τούτον τον τρόττον χώραν ταΐ<; ττροσσννοίκίζομεναίς τΓαρίχουσιν. It is probably to the Stoic Posidonius, whose astronomy has been mentioned as influential in the development of the theory and practice of Mithras-worship and similar sacra- mental cults,^ that the idea of the Air as the habitat of the Souls of the deceased and also of Βαίμονβ^; — an order of beings distinct from that of human Souls — is chiefly indebted for its vogue. Posidonius wrote a treatise ττβρί ηρώων καϊ Βαψόνων, quoted by Macrobius (Sat i. 23),^ and Cicero (de Div. i. 64) quotes him as saying that the Air is full of Souls and Daemons.^ That belief in Daemons — spirits which have never been incarnate in human bodies — is as consistent with the " materialism " of the Stoics as belief in the continued existence of human Souls in the Air, is insisted upon by Zeller,^ and, indeed, is obvious. So much for Stoical belief. But it was exactly the astronomy — Pythagorean and Platonic in its origin — popularised by the Stoic Posidonius, which seems to have suggested a mode of escape from the Stoical doctrine that the Soul, though subsisting for a longer or shorter time after the death of the body, yet is ultimately dissolved. Above the Air — the Stoical habitat of Βαίμονες and Souls of deceased men, equally doomed to dissolution, according to the orthodox doctrine of the school — there is the Aether.* Into this region Souls purified by Philosophy — 1 See supra, pp. 352 if, 2 See Rohde, Ps7jche, ii. 320. 2 Stoics, Epicureans, and Sceptics, p. 333, Engl. Transl. * I use the term "aether" here in its proper sense, as the name of the element which contains the ' ' visible gods," the stars. This element is sometimes, as in the Epinomis, 984 (cf. Zeller, Plato, p. 615), called irvp, fire, while "aether" THE TWO SYMPOSIUM MYTHS 439 or, it may be, by sacramental observances — rise, and there, though united to God, retain their individuality for ever. This is the doctrine of the Somnium Scipionis — which probably owes its astronomy to Posidonius ^ — and of the Tusc. Lisp. (i. 17, 18, 19); it is the doctrine to which even the Stoic Seneca {ad Marc. 25. 1) seems to incline, and it inspired those sacramental cults, Orphic, Mithraic, and Egyptian, which became so important in the religious life of the first two centuries of the Christian era.^ In this doctrine of Aether, the region of the heavenly spheres, as everlasting home of purified Souls, we have, of course, merely the mythology of the Timaeus and Phaedrus framed in an astronomical setting somewhat more definite than that furnished by Plato himself. What it is important, however, to recognise is that this mythology, so framed, takes the place of what is properly called irvp, fire, in the list "fire, air, water, earth." Bywater \journ. of Phil. vol. i. pp. 37-39, on the Fragm. of Philolaus) quotes the de Coelo, i. 270 b, and the i)ieteor. 339 b, for "aether" above the four elements, and remarks that "the occurrence of this quinta essentia in the Platonic Epinomis is one of the many indications of the late origin of that Dialogue." ^ See Rohde, Psyche, ii. 320, and Dieterich, Eine Mithrasliturgie, quoted supra, p. 352. ^ The following references to the Commentary of Hierocles (President of the School of Alexandria) on the Golden Hymn of the Pythagoreans may be taken to show how the astronomy of the Timaeus and Pha&dms influenced eschatology even in the fifth century of the Christian era. Hierocles (see Mullach's Fragm. Phil. Graec. i. 478 fi'. ) is commenting on the lines — αλλ' etpyov βρωτων, ών εΐττομβν, ^v re καθαρμοΐί, ^v T€ λιάσει ψνχψ κρίνων, καΐ φράζεν 'έκαστα, ■ηνίοχον "γνώμην arrjaas καθύττερθεν άρίστην, and, after referring for ηνίοχον to the Phaedrus Myth, and remarking that it embodies Pythagorean doctrine, says that, for the purification of the aethereal body — Trpos την κάθαρσιν του at>yoei5oi/s ήμων σώματος — we must put away the filth of the terrestrial body, and submit ourselves to purificatory observances, καθαρμοί, which he describes — by means of which we shall rise from the Place of Generation and Corruption, and be translat^-d to τό -ηΚύσων ττεδίον καΐ Αιθέρα τόν έλβύθερον. But as the terrestrial body must be shed on Earth, the συμφυές, i.e. the aerial body, must be shed in the aerial region immediately under the Moon (cf. Plut. de fac. in orbe lunae, 28, quoted p. 440 infra). Then the aethereal or astral body (τό άστρο€ΐδέ$, αύΎ0€ΐδέ$, φωτανόν σώμα or ^χημα) which is the immortal vehicle of the Soul, is free to ascend, with the Soul, into the Aether : — τούτο δέ 'γ€ν6μ6νο3 ώ$ οΐόν τβ μ€τά. τ^ν κάθαρσιν, δ άεί βίσιν οΐ μ^ els Ύένβσιν ττίπτειν τΓ€φνκύτ€$, rots μέν Ύνώσεσιν ένουται τφ τταντί, καΐ trpbs αυτόν avayeraL τόν θ€Ον • σώμα δέ συμφυέ$ ^χων, τόττον δβιται els κατάταξιν άστροειδη, οίον θέσιν ξητΟιν. ττρέτΓΟί δ' άν τφ τοωύτφ σώματι tottos 6 υπό σ€λΎ]νην '7Γpoσeχωs, ώϊ υπερέχων μέν των φθαρτών σωμάτων, ύπoβeβηκώs δέ των ουρανίων, iv αΙθέρα ελεύθερον οί αυθα-γ^ρειοι καλοΰσιν αιθέρα μέν, ώs άϋΧον καΐ άΐδιον σώμα- ελεύθερον δέ, ώ5 υλικών παθημάτων καθαρόν. τι οΰν 6 έκεΐσε έλθών ^σται, ^ τούτο 6 φησιν, #σσεαι a0avaTos θeόs, ώμoιωμέvos rois iv άρχ^ των έπων λεχθεΐσιν Mavarois 0eo2s, ού φύσει aOavaros θεbs. 440 THE MYTHS OF PLATO appeared to Platonists to be a sufficiently " up-to-date " refutation of the " materialism " of the Stoics. The Soul, when perfectly purified, rises out of the Air into the Aether, returning to its original home, and there lives for ever and ever. Its perfect purification — effected by Philosophy, or ritual performances, or both — guarantees its immortality ; for its eternal intelligible essence — vov^ — stripped of perishing sensible vehicles, terrestrial — σώμα — and aerial — "^υχη — is alone left. Of this intelligible essence Aether is the vehicle. The aethereal region is full of f vigor mvi e vincenti "^ — immortal spirits made pure by Philosophy, and suffering, and holy rites. This Platonist doctrine is set forth by Plutarch in his de genio Socratis, and in his de facie in orhe lunae. In a curious passage in the latter work (ch. 28) he tells us that reason — νους — has its home in the Sun. Thither the purified spirit returns, having shed its corporeal vehicle — σώμα — on Earth, and its aerial — ψυχή — on the Moon. This is the order of purification. And the order of generation, he explains, is the contrary of that of purification : — Of the three parts which make up man, the Sun supplies νους, the Moon ψυχή, the Earth σώμα.^ Death on Earth makes the three two ; death on the Moon makes the two one. Every Soul, whether rational or irrational,^ must wander for a time in the region between the Earth and the Moon. In the lower parts of this region the unrighteous are punished and corrected, while the righteous tarry for an appointed time in its highest parts — in the region of the softest air, which is called the Meadow of Death — iv τω Ίτραοτάτω του άβρος ον Χειμώνας αΒου καΧουσι ; * then, being filled, like those initiated, with a strange joy, half amazement half hope, they aspire to the Moon. There, now styled Βαίμονβζ by Plutarch,^ they have their abode, descending sometimes to Earth to help men — to assist at mysteries, to watch and punish crimes, to save in battle and at sea. The good among them (for some of them are wicked and become incarnate again in human bodies) are the Souls of those who lived on Earth in the reign of Cronus, and they are still worshipped in many places. When one 1 Par. X. 64. 2 pj^t. de/ac. in orb. lun. 28. 3 o.c. 28. 4 o.c. 28. 5 o.c. 30. THE TWO SYMPOSIUM MYTHS 441 of these good Daemons at last loses his power on Earth and fails his worshippers, it is because his lunar death has taken place — his true Self, i/ou?, has at last been separated from the ψνχη, which remains, like a corpse, on the Moon. The separation of νους from ψυχή is effected by the operation in him of Love of the Solar Image — άττοκρίνβταν δ' βρωτν της 7Γ€ρΙ τον ηΚίον βίκονος, Βί" ης έττίΚάμττβί το βφβτον καΐ καΧον καΐ θβίον καΐ μακάριον, ου ττασα φύσνς, άΧΚη δ* αΧΧως, opeyeTai , . . Χβίττβταί δε ή 'ψ•ν'χΎ}ς φύσις εττΐ Trj aeKrjvrj, οίον ϊ'χνη Τίνα βίου και ονβίρατα Βιαφϋλάττονσα . . αύτος βκαστος ημών ου θυμός έστιν, ούΒβ φόβος, ουδ' βίΓίθυμία, καθάττβρ ούΒε σάρκες, ούΒβ ύypότητ€ς, αλλ,' ω Βιανοούμβθα καΐ φρονοΰμβν . . . τούτων δε ή σεΚηνη στοΐ'χείόν εστίν, αναλύονται yap εΙς ταύτην, ωσττερ εις την yrjv τα σώματα των νεκρών, Plutarch's other work, mentioned above, the de genio Socratis, is so important for the doctrine of Daemons, that it cannot be dismissed in a paragraph like that just devoted to the de facie in orhe lunae. On the whole, I think the best way of laying its contents before the reader is to let it speak for itself in the Myth of Timarchus, which indeed presents all that is essential to Plutarch's daemonology. As in the case of the Aridaeus-Thespesius Myth, I avail myself here again of Philemon Holland's version. There was one Timarchus of Chaeronea, who died very young, and requested earnestly of Socrates to be buried near unto Lamprocles, Socrates his son, who departed this life but few days before, being a dear friend of his, and of the same age. Now this young gentleman, being very desirous (as he was of a generous disposition, and had newly tasted the sweetness of Philosophy) to know what was the nature and power of Socrates' familiar spirit, when he had imparted his mind and purpose unto me only and Cebes, went down into the cave or vault of Trophonius, after the usual sacrifices and accustomed compli- ments due to that oracle performed : where, having remained two nights and one day, inasmuch as many men were out of all hope that he ever would come forth again — yea, and his kinsfolk and friends bewailed the loss of him — one morning betimes issued forth very glad and jocund. ... He recounted unto us many wonders strange to be hgard and seen : for he said that being descended into the place of the oracle, he first met with much darkness, and afterwards, when he had made his prayers, he lay 442 THE MYTHS OF PLATO a long time upon the ground, not knowing whether he was awake or dreamed. Howbeit, he thought that he heard a noise which lit upon his head and smote it, whereby the sutures or seams thereof were disjoined and opened, by which he yielded forth his soul ; which, being thus separate, was very joyous, seeing itself mingled with a transparent and pure air. . . When he looked behind him he could see the Earth no more, but the Isles all bright and illuminate with a mild and delicate fire, and those exchanged their places one with another, and withal, received sundry colours, as it were diverse tinctures, according as in that variety of change the light did alter ; and they all seemed unto him in number infinite and in quantity excessive : and albeit they were not of equal pourprise and extent, yet round they were all alike : also, by their motion, which was circular, the sky resounded. . . Amid these Islands there seemed a sea or great lake diffused and spread, shining with diverse mixed colours upon a ground of grey or light blue. Moreover, of these Isles some few sailed, as one would say, and were carried a direct course down the water beyond the current; but others, and those in number many, went aside out of the channel, and were Avith such a violence drawn back that they seemed to be swallowed under the waves. . . . And the same sea hath two mouths or entrances, whereby it recciveth two rivers of fire breaking into it, opposite one to the other, in such sort as the blueness thereof became whitish by reason that the greatest part was repelled and driven back. And these things he said he beheld with great delight. But when he came to look downward, he- perceived a mighty huge hole or gulf all round, in manner of a hollow globe cut through the midst, exceeding deep and horrible to see to, full of much darkness, and the same not quiet and still, but turbulent and oftentimes boiling and walming upward, out of which there might be heard innumerable roarings and groanings of beasts, cries and wrawlings of an infinite number of children, with sundry plaints and lamentations of men and women together, besides many noises, tumults, clamours, and outcries of all sorts, and those not clear, but dull and dead, as being sent up from a great depth underneath. . . . One whom he saw not, said unto him : The division of Proserpina, you may see if you will, how it is bounded with Styx. Styx (quoth he) is the way which leadeth unto hell and the kingdom of Pluto, dividing two contrary natures of light and darkness with the head and top thereof ; for, as you see, it beginneth from the bottom of hell beneath, which it touches with the one extremity, and reacheth with the other to the light all about, and so limiteth the utmost part of the whole world, divided into four regiments. The first is that of life ; the second of moving ; the third of generation ; THE TWO SYMPOSIUM MYTHS 443 and the fourth of corruption. The first is coupled to the second by unity, in that which is not visible ; the second to the third, by the mind or intelligence, in the sun ; the third to the fourth, by nature, in the moon. And of every one of these copulations there is a Friend, or Destiny, the Daughter of Necessity, that keepeth the key. Of the first, she that is named Atropos, as one would say Inflexible ; of the second, Clotho — that is to say, the Spinster ; of the third in the moon, Lachesis — that is to say. Lot, about which is the bending of geniture or nativity. As for all the other Isles, they have gods within them ; but the Moon, appertaining to the terrestrial Daemons, avoideth the confines of Styx, as being somewhat higher exalted, approaching once only in an hundred seventy seven second measures : and upon the approach of this precinct of Styx, the souls cry out for fear. And why ? Hell catcheth and swalloweth many of them, as they glide and slip about it : and others the Moon receiveth and taketh up, swimming from beneath unto her; such, I mean, as upon whom the end of generation fell in good and opportune time, all save those which are impure and polluted : for them, with her fearful flashing and hideous roaring, she sufi'ereth not to come near unto her ; who, seeing that they have missed of their intent, bewail their woeful state, and be carried down again, as you see, to another generation and nativity. Why, quoth Timarchus, I see nothing but a number of stars leaping up and down about this huge and deep gulf, some drowned and swallowed up in it, others appearing again from below. These be (quoth he) the daemons that you see, though you know them not. And mark, withal, how this comes about. Every soul is endued with a portion of mind or understanding : but look how much thereof is mingled with flesh and with passions ; being altered with pleasures and dolors, it becometh unreasonable. But every soul is not mixed after one sort ... for some are wholly plunged within the body . . . others partly are mingled with the flesh, and in part leave out that which is most pure, and not drawn downward by the contagion of the gross part, but remaineth swimming and floating as it were aloft, touching the top or crown only of a man's head, and is in manner of a cord hanging up aloft, just over the soul which is directly and plumb under, to uphold and raise it up, so far forth as it is obeisant thereto, and not over-ruled and swayed with passions and perturbations : for that which is plunged down within the body is called the soul ; but that which is entire and uncorrupt the vulgar sort calleth the understanding, supposing it to be within them as in mirrors that which appeareth by way of reflection : but those that judge aright and according to the trtlth name it Daemon, as being clean without them. These stars, then, which you see as if they were 444 THE MYTHS OF PLATO extinct and put out, imagine and take them to be the souls which are totally drowned within bodies ; and such as seem to shine out again and to return lightsome from beneath, shaking from them a certain dark and foggy mist, esteem the same to be such souls as after death are retired and escaped out of the bodies ; but those which are mounted on high and move to and fro in one uniform course throughout are the Daemons or spirits of men who are said to have intelligence and understanding. Endeavour now therefore and strain yourself to see the connection of each one, whereby it is linked and united to the soul. When I heard this I began to take more heed, and might see stars leaping and floating upon the water, some more, some less, like as we observe pieces of cork shewing in the sea where the fishers' nets have been cast ; and some of them turned in manner of spindles or bobbins, as folk spin or twist therewith, yet drawing a troubled and unequal course and not able to direct and compose the motion straight. And the voice said that those which held on a right course and orderly motion were they whose souls were obeisant to the reins of reason . . . but they that eftsoons rise and fall up and down unequally and disorderly are those which strive against the yoke. ... Of such as are obedient at the first, and presently from their very nativity hearken unto their proper Daemon, are all of the kind of prophets and diviners who have the gift to foretell things to come, likewise holy and devout men : of which number you have heard how the soul of Hermodorus the Clazo- menian was wont to abandon his body quite, and both by day and night to wander into many places ; and afterwards to return into it again . . . which it used so long, until his enemies, by the treachery of his wife, surprised his body one time, when the soul was gone out of it, and burnt it in his house. Howbeit, this was not true ; for his soul never departed out of his body ; but the same being always obedient unto his Daemon, and slacking the bond unto it, gave it means and liberty to run up and down, and to walk to and fro in many places, in such sort, as having seen and heard many things abroad, it would come and report the same unto him. But those that consumed his body as he lay asleep are tormented in Tartarus even at this day for it ; which you shall know yourself, good young man, more certainly within these three months (quoth that voice) : and for this time see you depart. When this voice had made an end of speaking, Timarchus, as he told the tale himself, turned about to see who it was that spake; but feeling a great pain again in his head, as if it had been violently pressed and crushed, he was deprived of all sense and understanding, and neither knew himself nor anything about him. But within a while after when he was come unto himself, he might see how he lay along at the entry of the foresaid cave THE TWO SYMPOSIUM MYTHS 445 of Trophonius, like as he had himself at the beginning. And thus much concerning the fable of Timarchus ; who being returned to Athens, in the third month after, just as the voice foretold him, he departed this life. The Aether, then, according to the Platonist belief which we are examining, is the birthplace of human Souls, and their final abode when they have completed the purification which guarantees immortality to them as Pure Intelligences. But the Air is, none the less, the habitat, and, it would appear, the permanent habitat, of another class of immortal spirits, Βαίμονβς, who never were incarnate in terrestrial bodies. These immortal Βαίμονβ^ occupy the Air, that they may be near to help men on Earth, and mediate between them and God, whose dwelling is in the aethereal region. It is in this interspace between the "visible Gods," the Stars, and the Earth that the author of the Epinomis^ places the Βαίμονες, whom he describes as interpreters between men and the Gods. He distinguishes three classes of such Βαίμονες: first, those who live in the so-called Aether under the Fire or true Aether, i.e. in the higher part of the space between the Earth and the Moon ; secondly, those who inhabit the Air round the Earth — these two kinds of Daemons are invisible ; thirdly. Daemons whose vehicle is watery mist — these are sometimes visible.^ It is in the same space between the Earth and the Moon that the Platonist Apuleius, writing in the second century after Christ, places the Βαίμονβς of Diotima's Discourse, an order of divine mediators between God and men to which he conceives the Βαιμόνιον of Socrates and the Guardian Angels of all other men as belonging. Atque (he says)^ si Platonis vera sententia est, nunquam se Deum cum homine communicare, facilius me audierit lapis, quam Jupiter. Non usque adeo (responderit enim Plato pro sententia sua, mea vice), non usque adeo, inquit, sejunctos et alienatos a nobis deos praedico, ut ne vota quidem nostra ad illos arbitrer pervenire. Neque enim ipsos cura rerum humanarum, sed contrectatione sola removi. Caeterum sunt quaedam divinae * AccordiniT to Zeller {Plato, p. 561, Engl. Transl.), probably Philippus of Opus, one of Plato's pupils. • 2 Epinomis, 984, 985 ; cf. Zeller, Plato (Engl. Transl.), p. 615. ' Apuleius de Deo SocrcUis, vol. ii. p. 116, ed. Botolaud. 446 THE MYTHS OF PLATO mediae potestates, inter summum aethera et infimas terras, in isto intersitae aeris spatio, per quas et desideria nostra et merita ad deos commeant; hos Graeci nomine δαίμονας nuncupaut. Inter terricolas caelicolasque vectores, hinc precum, inde donorum ; qui ultro citro portant, hinc petitionee, inde suppetias, ceu qoidam utriusque interpret es et salutigerL Per hos eosdem, ut Plato in Symposio autumat, cuncta deniinciata, et magorum varia miracula, omnesque praesagiorum species reguntur. Eorum quippe de numero praediti curant singula, proinde ut est eorum cuique tributa provincia : vel somniis confirmandis, vel extis fissiculandis, vel praepetibus gubemandis, vel oscinibus erudiendis, vel vatibus inspirandis, vel fulminibus jaculandis, vel nubibus coruscandis, caeterisque adeo, per quae futura dinoscimus. Quae cuncta caelestium voluntate et numine et auctoritate, sed daemonum obsequio et opera et ministerio fieri arbitrandum eat . . . Quid igitur^ tanta vis aeris, quae ab humillimia lunae anfractibus, usque ad summum Olympi verticem interjacet t Quid tandem 1 Yacabitne animalibus suis, atque erit ista naturae pars mortua ac debilis t . . . Flagitat ratio * debere propria enim animalia in aere intelligi ; superest ut quae tandem et cujusmodi ea sint, disseramus. Igitur terrena nequaquam, devergant enim pondere; sed ne flammida, ne sursum versus calore rapiantur. Temperanda ergo nobis pro loci medietate media natura. . . . mente formemus et gignamus animo id genus corporum texta, quae neque tarn bruta quam terrea, neque tam levia quam aetherea, sed quodammodo utrimque sejugata. . . . Quod si nubes' sublime volitant, quibus omnia et exortus est terrenus, et retro defluxus in terras est ; quid tandem censes daemonum corpora, quae sunt concretu multo tan to subtiliori 1 Non enim sunt ex hac faeculenta nubecula, tumida caligine conglobata, sicuti nubium genus est; sed ex illo purissimo aeris liquido et sereno elemento coalita, eoque nemini hominum temere visibilia, nisi divinitus speciem sui offerant, quod nulla in illis terrena soliditas locum luminis occuparit, quae nostris oculis possit obsistere, qua soliditate necessario offensa acies immoretur; sed fila corporum possident rara, et splendida, et tenuia, usque adeo ut radios omnis nostri tuoris et raritate transmittant, et splendore reverberent, et subtilitate frustrentur. . . . Debet deus * nuUam perpeti vel odii, vel amoris temporalem perfunctionem : et idcirco nee indignatione nee misericordia contingi, nullo angore contrahi, nulla alacritate gestire ; sed ab omnibus animi passionibus liber, nee dolere unquam, nee aliquando laetari, nee aliquid repentinum velle vel nolle. Sed et haec cuncta, et id genus caetera, daemonum mediocritati rit« congruunt. Sunt enim inter nos ac deos, ut loco regionis, ita ingenio mentis intersiti, habentes communem cum 1 o.e. p. 119. * o.e. p. 119. » o.e. p. 121. * o.e, p. 124. THE TWO SYMPOSIUM MYTHS 447 superis immortalitatem, cum inferis passioDem. Nam, proinde ut nos, pati possunt omnia animorum placamenta vel incitamenta : ut et ira incitentur, et misericordia flectantur, et donis invitentur, et precibus leniantur, et contumeliis exasperentur, et honoribus mulceantur, aliisque omnibus ad similem nobis modum varientur. Quippe, ut finem comprehendam, dς εοικας, εφη, οκνουντι λεγβίζ/. Δο^ω δε σοι, ην δ' εγώ, καϊ μάλ* είκοτως οκνεΐν, D εττειΒαν είττω. Λεγ', εφη, και μη φόβου. Λέγω δ?; • καίτοι ουκ οϊΒα, οτΓοία τόλμη ή ττοίοις \6<γοις γ^ρώμενος ερώ' καϊ ετΓΐ'χειρησω ττρώτον μεν αυτούς τους άργοντας ττείθειν και τους στρατίώτας, εττειτα δε και την αΧλην ττολιν, ώς άρ^ α ημείς αυτούς ετρεφομεν τε καϊ ετταιΒεύομεν, ώσττερ ονείρατα εΒόκουν ταύτα ττάντα ττάσγειν τε καϊ η'ιηνεσθαι ττερϊ αυτούς, ήσαν δε τότε ttj αλήθεια ύττο ^ής εντός ττλαττόμενοι καϊ τρεφόμενοι καϊ αύτοϊ καϊ τα οττλα αυτών καϊ ή άλλη £ σκευή Βημιουρ'γουμενη, εττειΒη δε τταντέλώς εξειρ^ασμενοι ήσαν, [/cat] ή γτ} αυτούς μητηρ ούσα άνηκε, καϊ νυν Βεΐ ώς ττερϊ μητρός καϊ τροφού της γωρας, εν η είσί, βούλεύε- σθαί τε καϊ άμύνειν αυτούς, εάν τις εττ αύτην ϊη, καϊ ύττερ τών άλλων ττόλιτών ώς άΒεΧφών όντων καϊ ηη^ενών Βιανοεΐ- σθαι. Ουκ ετο9, εφη, ττάλαι ησ'χυνου το ΛίτευΒος λέγειν. 415 ΤΙάνυ, ην δ* εγώ, εΐκότως' αλλ* όμως άκουε καϊ το λοιττον του μύθου, εστε μεν yap Βη ττάντες οι εν τη ττολει αδελ- φοί, ώς φήσομεν ττρος αυτούς μυθολο^οΰντες, αλλ' ό θεός Ίτλάττων, όσοι μεν υμών ικανοϊ άρ'χειν, -χ^ρυσον εν τη γενέσει ξυνεμιξεν αύτοΐς, Βιο τιμιώτατοί εισιν • όσοι δ' εττίκουροι, 470 THE MYTH OF THE EAKTH-BOKN We must try, says Socrates, to invent a Noble Fiction for the good of the People which we have distributed into the three classes of Kulers, Soldiers, and Workmen — a Fiction which, if possible, we must get the Kulers themselves to believe, but, failing that, the other citizens. And let our Fiction eschew novelty : let it be framed after the pattern of those Founda- tion-Myths which the Poets have made familiar. I hardly know how to recommend my story to the belief, first of the Kulers, then of the Soldiers, and then of the other citizens — it will be difi&cult, indeed, to get them to believe it ; yet, let me make the venture — and tell them that "All the things which they deemed were done unto them and came to pass in their life, when we were bringing them up and instructing them, were dreams, so to speak : all the while, in truth, 'twas under the Earth, in her womb, that they were being fashioned and nourished, and their arms and all their accoutrement wrought. Then, when the making of them was fully accom- plished, the Earth, which is their Mother, sent them forth ; and now must they take good counsel concerning the Land wherein they are as concerning a Mother and Nurse, and must themselves defend her, if any come against her, and also have regard unto all their fellow-citizens, as unto brethren — children, along with themselves, of one Mother, even of Earth." We shall further say to them in pursuance of our Myth : — " All ye of this City are brethren : but God, when He fashioned you, mingled gold in the nature of those of you who were Able to Kule ; wheiefore are they the most precious : and silver in the nature of the Soldiers : and iron and copper in 471 472 THE MYTHS OF PLATO apyvpov σίΒηρον Be καΐ 'χαΚκον τοΐζ τ€ γβωργοΓ? fcal τοις άΧλοίς Βημιουρ^οΙς. are ουν ξνγγβνβΐς οντβς ττάντβς το μεν Β ΤΓοΧύ ομοίους αν νμΐν αντοΐς yewtpTe, βστί δ' οτβ €κ γ^ρυσου ^εννηθβίη αν apyvpovv καΐ έξ apyvpov 'χ^ρυσοϋν eKyovov καΐ ταΧλα ττάντα οΰτως εξ όΧΚηΚων. τοις ουν άρ'χουσι, καΐ ττρώτον καϊ μάλιστα irapayyeWeu 6 θεός, οττως μηΒενος οΰτω φύλακες ayaQol έσονται μηΒ"* οΰτω σφοΒρα φυΧάξονσι μηΒεν ώς τους εκy6voυς, 6 τί αύτοΐς τούτων εν ταΐς ψυχ^αΐς τταραμεμικται, καϊ εάν τε σφετερος εκyovoς υττόγαλκος ή C ύτΓοσίΒηρος yεvητaL•, μηΒενΙ τρόττω κατεΧεήσουσιν, άΧλα την Tjj φύσει ττροσηκουσαν τιμήν άττοΒόντες ώσουσιν εις Bημιoυpyoυς η εΙς yεωpyoύς, καϊ αν αΰ εκ τούτων τις ύττόχ^ρυσος ή ϋlΓάpyυpoς φυτ], τιμησαντες άνάξουσι τους μεν εις φυΧακην, τους Βε εις εττικουρίαν, ώς 'χ^ρησμοϋ οντος τότε την ττόΧιν Βιαφθαρηναι, όταν αύτην ό σίΒηρος η ο 'χαΧκος φυΧάξη. τούτον ουν τον μυθον οττως αν ττεισθεΐεν, εγεις τίνα μη'χρινην ; ΟύΒαμώς, εφη, οττως y αν αύτοΙ D ούτοι* δττως μεντ αν οι τούτων υιεΐς καϊ οι εττειτα οί τ αΧΚοι άνθρωποι οί ύστερον. Άλλα καϊ τούτο, ην δ* εγώ, el• αν εγρι ττρος το μαΧλον αυτούς της ττόΧεώς τε καϊ άΧΧήΧων κηΒεσθαΐ" σγεΒόν yap τι μανθάνω ο Xέyεις, THE MYTH OF THE EAETH-BORN 473 the Husbandmen and Craftsmen. Now, albeit that, for the most part, ye will engender children like unto their parents, yet, inasmuch as ye are all of one kindred, it will sometimes come to pass that from gold silver will be brought forth, and from silver, golden offspring — yea, from any sort, any other. And this is the first and chief est commandment which God giveth unto the Rulers, that they be Watchmen indeed, and watch naught else so diligently as the issue of children, to see which of these metals is mingled in their Souls : and if a child of theirs have aught of copper or iron in him, they shall in no wise have pity upon him, but shall award unto him the place meet for his nature, and thrust him forth unto the Craftsmen or Husbandmen ; whereas, if there be any one born among these with gold or silver in him, they shall take account of this, and lead him up unto the place of the Watchmen, or unto the place of the Soldiers; for hath not the Oracle declared that the City will be destroyed in the day that Iron or Copper shall keep watch ? " This is the Myth. How are we to get them to believe it ? The generation to whom it is first told cannot possibly believe it; but the next may, and the generations after. Thus the Public Good may be served, after all, by our Noble Fiction. 474 THE MYTHS OF PLATO KoTE ON THE Myth of the Earth-born The three metals of this Myth must be taken in connection with the doctrine of Hesiod {O.D. 9 7 ff.) ; for which the reader is referred to the section on Daemones among the Observations on the Discourse of Diotima.^ With regard to the fancy which inspires the Myth — the fancy that " our youth was a dream " — I would only remark that Plato seems to me here to appeal to an experience which is by no means uncommon in childhood — to the feeling that the things here are doubles of things elsewhere. The produc- tion of this feeling in his adult patient has been dwelt on ^ as one of the chief means by which the Poet effects the purpose of his art. ^ Pages 434 if. supra. ^ Pages 34, 384 fF. sicpra. THE MYTHOLOGY AND METAPHYSICS OF THE CAMBEIDGE PLATONISTS The purpose of this Concluding Part is to show that Alexandrine Platonism, indebted for its chief tenets to the mythology of the Timaeus, Fhaedrus Myth, and Discourse of Diotima, has been, and still is, an important influence in Modern Philosophy. Our chief concern will be with the " Cambridge Platonists " of the seventeenth century ; but we shall keep a watchful eye throughout upon their successors, the English Idealists of the present day. Before we consider the central doctrine of the Cambridge Platonists and compare it with that of the English Idealists of the present day, we must try to realise the environment of the former. It was, in one word, " academic." That, in the seventeenth century, meant "theological." Their paramount interest was in Theology. They brought to the cultivation of Theology, first, classical, patristic, and rabbinical learning, and secondly, physical science, Cartesian — and Newtonian, if I may be allowed so to call the reformed science which was already all but ripe for Newton's great discovery. With regard to their Learning: — It was that of the Kenaissance, i.e. Platonic, not Aristotelian. The learning of the medieval Church had been Aristotelian; and the great Myth of that Church, the Divina Commedia, sprang into life out of the ashes of Aristotelianism. Antagonism to the Koman Church had, doubtless, much to do with the Platonic revival, which spread from Italy. Ficino, the great Florentine Platonist, took the place of Thomas Aquinas, and is the authority the Cambridge Matonists are always found appeal- ing to. Their Platonism, moreover, was that of Plato the 475 476 THE MYTHS OF PLATO mythologist, not that of Plato the dialectician ; that is, it was Alexandrine Platonism which attracted them, especially as its doctrine had been used by Philo to interpret the Old Testament, and by Origen and other Fathers to set forth the philosophy of the Christian mysteries, on lines common to them with Plotinus. Philo, whose method of exegesis has been referred to in the section on Allegory,^ never thought of doubting that Platonism and the Jewish Scriptures had real afi&nity to each other, and hardly perhaps asked himself how the affinity was to be accounted for ; but the English Platonists, imitators of his exegetical method, felt themselves obliged to satisfy doubts and answer questions. To make good the applicability of the Platonic philosophy to the exegesis of the Holy Scriptures, they felt, with Aristobulus and Numenius,^ that it was important to be able to show that Plato was Moses Atticus. In the Preface to his Conjectwra Cabhalistica^ or a Conjectural Essay of interpreting the mind of Moses in the three first Chapters of Genesis, according to a threefold Cahhala, viz., literal, philosophical, mystical, or divinely moral (1662), Dr. Henry More writes (p. 3) : — Moses seems to have been aforehand, and prevented the subtilest and abstrusest inventions of the choicest philosophers that ever appeared after him to this very day. And further presumption of the truth of this Philosophical Cabbala is that the grand mysteries therein contained are most- what the same that those two eximious philosophers, Pythagoras and Plato, brought out of Egypt, and the parts of Asia, into Europe, and it is generally acknowledged by Christians that they both had their philosophy from Moses. And Numenius the Platonist speaks out plainly concerning his master : What is Plato but Moses Atticus? And for Pythagoras, it is a thing incredible that he and his followers should make such a deal of doe with the mystery of Numbers, had he not been favoured with a sight of Moses his creation of the world in six days, and had the Philosophick Cabbala thereof communicated to him, which mainly consists in Numbers. Again in the same work (ch. iii. § 3, p. 100) he writes : — ^ Papjes 234 if. supra. 2 Aristobulus asserted the existence of a much older translation of the Law from which Plato and the Greeks stole their philosophy. Numenius is the author of the phrase Μωϋσης άττικίξ'ων : see Dr. Bigg's Christian Platonists of Alexandria, p. 6. THE CAMBRIDGE PLATONISTS 477 That Pythagoras was acquainted with the Mosaical or Jewish Philosophy, there is ample testimony of it in writers ; as of Aristobulus an Egyptian Jew in Clemens Alexandrinus, and Josephus against Appion. S. Ambrose adds that he was a Jew himself. Clemens calls him τον ίξ ^Εβραίων φιλόσοφον, the Hebrew Philosopher. I might cast hither the suffrages of Justin Martyr, Johannes Philoponus, Theodoret, Hermippus in Origen against Celsus, Porphyrins, and Clemens again, who writes that it was a common fame that Pythagoras was a disciple of the Prophet Ezekiel. And though he gives no belief to the report, yet that learned antiquary Mr. Selden seems inclinable enough to think it true. . . . Besides all these, lamblichus also affirms that he lived at Sidon his native country, where he fell acquainted with the Prophets and Successors of one Mochus the Physiologer or Natural Philosopher — σνν^βαλζ tols Μώ^ου του φνσωλόγον 7Γροφηταί<^ άπoγόvoLs' which, as Mr Selden judiciously conjectures, is to be read rots Μωσ^ω? κ.τ.λ. . . . wherefore it is very plain that Pythagoras had his Philosophy from Moses . . . and now I have said this much of Pythagoras, there will be less need to insist upon Plato and Plotinus, their Philosophy being the same that Pythagoras's was, and so alike applicable to Moses his text. So much, by way of specimen, to indicate the kind of evidence by which Plato is proved to be Moses Atticus. The proof, as managed by both More and Cudworth, calls into requisition a vast amount of uncritical learning. One has ta read these learned lucubrations to estimate the revolution wrought by Bentley. One of the oddest results of the desire of the Cambridge Platonists to show the derivation of Pythagoreanism and Platonism from the Mosaic philosophy was the thesis main- tained by them that the Mosaic philosophy was an atomistic system — a system which Pythagoras and Plato borrowed and kept in comparative purity, but which Democritus (the Hobbes of antiquity — see Cudworth, Intellectual System, vol. i. p. 276, ed. Mosheim and Harrison) corrupted into atheism. The true Mosaic atomism, or physical science, was of such a nature as to make it necessary to postulate God as source of motion ; whereas Democritus and modern materialists explain everything by blind mechanical principles. But why this desire to make out the true philosophy — that of Moses and the Greeks who retainect the Mosaic tradition — atomistic ? Because the Cartesian natural philosophy was " atomistic," i.e^ 478 THE MYTHS OF PLATO mathematical and mechanical. This was the natural philo- sophy in vogue — the natural philosophy which was reforming Physics and Astronomy, and was about to bring forth Newton. It need not surprise us, then, if we look at the matter atten- tively, that these alumni of Cambridge wished to show that Moses taught — allegorically, it is true — the Cartesian or mechanical philosophy. It was as if theologians of our own day were anxious to show that the account of the Creation in Genesis, or, if that would be too paradoxical, belief in a Special Providence, is compatible with Darwinism. It is true that More and Cudworth, especially the latter, are not entirely satisfied with the Cartesian theology, although they accept the Cartesian mathematical physics as giving a correct explanation of natural phenomena. It was indeed " atomism " in its genuine Mosaic form which Descartes revived, not the atheistic Democritean atomism ; for he posits an " Immaterial Substance " ; but he leaves this Substance, as First Principle, too little to do. While recognising immaterial cogitative substance as distinct from extended material substance, he falls into the error of identifying cogitative substance entirely with consciousness, and for the " plastic soul " — a spiritual or immaterial, though non-conscious, principle in Nature — he substitutes blind " mechanism," thus depriving theology of the argument from design. This is the gist of a remarkable criticism of Descartes which occurs in Cudworth's Intellectual System, vol. i. pp. 275, 276. It is well worth reading in connection with criticism of the same tendency to be met with in such modern books as Professor Ward's Naturalism and Agnosticism. More, in a notable passage in the Preface General to his Collected Works (1662), speaks of Platonism as the soul, and Cartesianism as the body, of the philosophy which he applies to the interpretation of the Text of Moses. This philosophy is the old Jewish-Pythagorean Cabbala, which teaches the motion of the Earth and the Pre-existence of the Soul. The motion of the Earth as Mosaic doctrine he discusses in the sixth chapter of his Appendix to the Defence of the Philo- sophick Cahbala (p. 126), and the passage in which he deals with an objection against ascribing the doctrine to Moses may be noted as an instructive specimen of the method of these THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 479 Cambridge Platonists. The objection — a suJBftciently formid- able one on the face of it — is that the doctrine does not appear in the Mosaic writings. More takes up the bold position that, although the doctrine of " the motion of the Earth has been lost and appears not in the remains of the Jewish Cabbala, this can be no argument against its once having been a part thereof." Though the fame of this part of the Cabbala (he says) be in a manner extinct among the Jews, yet that it was once the hidden doctrine of the learned of that nation seems to me sufficiently credible from what Plutarch writes of Numa Pompilius. For his so strictly prohibiting the use of images in divine worship is very apparently Mosaical . . . and Numa's instructor is said to be not a Grecian but βάρβαρος tls βζλτίων ΐίνθαγόρον, some Barbarian greater and better than Pythagoras himself; and where, I pray you, was such an one to be found, unless descended from the Jews ? ... It seems exceedingly probable from all these circumstances that Numa was both descended from the Jews and imbued with the Jewish religion and learning. What's this to the purpose ? or how does it prove the motion of the Earth once to have been part of the Judaical Tradition or Cabbala ? Only thus much : that Numa . . . knowing there was no such august temple of God as the Universe itself, and that to all the inhabitants thereof it cannot but appear round from every prospect, and that in the midst there must be an ever-shining Fire, I mean the Sun ; in imitation hereof he built a round temple, which was called the temple of Yesta, concerning which Plutarch speaks plainly and apertly, " That Numa is reported to have built a round temple of Vesta for the custody of a fire in the midst thereof that was never to go out : not imitating herein the figure of the Earth, as if she was the Yesta, but of the Universe; in the midst whereof the Pythagoreans placed the Fire, and called it Yesta or Monas, and reckoned the Earth neither immovable, nor in the midst of the Mundane Compasse, but that it is carried about the Fire or Sun, and is none of the first and chief elements of the World." What can be more plain than these testimonies 1 The learning of the Cambridge Platonists, of which the above passage enables us to take the measure, is expended in two main directions, pointed out by Philo and by Plotinus respectively. Philo was their master in Scriptural exegesis — the exegesis by which dogma was established (although Plotinus, too, helped thenf here, especially with regard to the doctrine of the Trinity) ; but Plotinus was especially their 480 THE MYTHS OF PLATO master in what concerned devotional religion. It would be tedious to quote passages in which they employ Philo's exegetical method (already illustrated in another part of this work) in order to establish dogma : it will be sufficient merely to mention More's Philosophick Cdbhala, ch. 1, his Defence of the Philosophick Cabhala, ch. 1, Cudworth's Intellectual System of the Universe, vol. ii. p. 366 and p. 406 (ed. Mosheim and Harrison), and Norris's Reason and Religion (1689), pp. 133, 134; but a few words respecting the aids to devotion which they derived from their Cablala may not be out of place here. First, it is to be observed that ecstasy was the general form in which they tended to envisage religious devotion ; and here, doubtless, Plotinus was their model. The ecstasy of Plotinus is an obscure phenomenon, probably deserving the attention of the physiologist as well as of the theologian ; ^ it will be enough, by way of indicating its nature, to refer to Cudworth, who quotes ^ a well-known passage in Porphyry's Life of his friend and master Plotinus : — And that we may here give a taste of the mystical theology and enthusiasm of these Platonists too, Porphyrius in his Life of Plotinus affirmeth, that both Plotinus and himself had sometimes experience of a kind of ecstatic union with the first of these three gods [Cudworth here refers to the Platonic Trinity], that which is above mind and understanding : " Plotinus often endeavouring to raise up his mind to the first and highest God, that God some- times appeared to him, who hath neither form nor idea, but is placed above intellect, and all that is intelligible; to whom Γ Porphyrius affirm myself to have been once united in the sixty- eighth year of my age." And again afterwards : " Plotinus' chief aim and scope was to be united to and conjoined with the Supreme God, who is above all ; which scope he attained unto four several times, whilst myself was with him, by a certain ineffable energy." That is, Plotinus aimed at such a kind of rapturous and ecstatic union with the rh L•, and τάγα(9οι/, " the first of the three highest gods " (called the One and the Good), as by himself is described towards the latter end of this last book (Enn. vi. 9), where he calls it €7Γαφήν, and τταρονσίαν ίπιχττημης κρείττονα, and το εαυτών KCVTpov τω οίον πάντων κίντρψ συνάτΓτειν, "a kind of tactual ^ For modern cases I would refer to Professor James's Varieties of Religious Experience (1902). 2 Intell. System, ii. 315, 316. THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 481 union," and " a certain presence better than knowledge," and " the joining of our own centre, as it were, with the centre of the universe." This doctrine, or rather practice, of ecstasy, especially identified with the name of Plotinus, appeals strongly to the English Platonists, who understand it, however, not as a mysterious trance, but as a " Holy Life," ecstatic in the sense of being dead to the flesh and the vanities of the world. Death to the flesh and the world is secured by — nay consists in,^ Contemplation of the glorious and lovable nature of God. " The highest and last term of Contemplation," says Norris,^ " is the Divine Essence. Whence it follows necessarily that the mind which sees the Divine Essence must be totally and thoroughly absolved from all commerce with the corporeal senses, either by Death or some ecstatical and rapturous Abstraction. So true is that which God said to Moses, Thou canst not see my face, for there shall no man see me, and live." Similarly, John Smith, in his Discourse on " The true way or method of attaining Divine knowledge," speaks of a good Life as the ττρόΧηψι^; or Fundamental Principle of Divine Science : " If any man will do his will, he shall know the doctrine, whether it be of God." "Were I indeed to define Divinity, I should rather call it a Divine Life, than a Divine Science \ it being something rather to be understood by a Spiritual Sensation, than by any verbal descrip- tion."^ . . . "Divinity is not so well perceived by a subtile wit, ώσ7Γ€/ο αίσθήσ-ζί KeKadap^kvy, as by a purified sense, as Plotinus phraseth it." * . . . " The Platonists . . . thought the minds of men could never be purged enough from those earthly dregs of Sense and Passion, in which they were so much steeped, before they could be capable of their divine metaphysics-, and therefore they so much solicit a γωρΐ(τμο<ζ άττο τον σώ/Αατο?, a separation from the Body, in all those who would καθαρώς φιλοσοφύν, sincerely understand Divine Truth ; for that was the scope of their Philosophy. This was also intimated by them in defining Philosophy to be ρ^λ^τη θάνατον, a meditation of Death; aiming herein at only a moral way of dying, by loosening the Soul from 1 Cf. Aristotle, E. N. x. 8. 8. 1178 b 32, είη &v η ευδαιμονία Θεωρία rts. 2 Reason and Religion (1689), p. 3. It is a book "of a devotional nature written for the use and benefit of the Learned Reader," "whose Heart may want as much to be inflamed as the Qi;her's Head [i.e. the head of the unlearned person for whose use devotional books are mostly written] does to be instructed." 3 Smith's Select Discourses (1660), p. 2. * o.c. p. 10. 2i 482 THE MYTHS OF PLATO the Body and this Sensitive life . . . and therefore, besides those aperat καθαρτικαί by which the Souls of men were to be separated from Sensuality . . . they devised a further way of separation . . . which was their Mathemata, or mathematical contemplations . . . besides many other ways they had, whereby to rise out of this dark body ; άναβάσ-βις ίκ τον σπηλαίου, several steps and ascents out of this miry cave of mortality, before they could set any sure footing with their intellectual part in the Land of Light and Immortal Being." ^ "The Priests of Mercury, as Plutarch tells us, in the eating of their holy things, were wont to cry out γλυκύ ή άλήθαα, Sweet is Truth. But how sweet and delicious that Truth is which holy and heaven-born Souls feed upon in their mysterious converses with the Deity, who can tell but they that taste it ? When Reason once is raised by the mighty force of the Divine Spirit into a converse with God, it is turned into Sense : that which before was only Faith well built upon sure principles (for such our Science may be) now becomes Vision. AVe shall then converse with God τω νω, whereas before we conversed with him only rrj διάνοια, with our Discursive faculty, as the Platonists were wont to distinguish. Before we laid hold on him only λόγφ ατΓοδεικτικω, with a struggling, agonistical, and contentious Eeason, hotly combating with difficulties and sharp contests of diverse opinions, and labouring in it self in its deductions of one thing from another; we shall then fasten our minds upon him λογ(^ άτΓοφαντίκω, with such a serene understanding, yaXrivy voepa, such an intellectual calmness and serenity as will present us with a blissful, steady, and invariable sight of him." 2 It may perhaps be thought that in the foregoing passage Smith oversteps a little the line which divides " ecstasy " as " Holy Life " from " ecstasy " as temporary state of exalted religious feeling ; and perhaps in the following passage too, from his Discourse of the Immortality of the Soul, he may be thought to commit the same fault; yet the passage seems to me to contain what is so valuable for our understanding of the influence of Platonism — as mythological, rather than logical system — on present-day religious thought, that I venture to transcribe it, together with the notable quotation from Plotinus included in it : — Though in our contentious pursuits after science, we cast Wisdom, Power, Eternity, Goodness, and the like into several 1 o.c. pp. 10, 11. '^ o.c. pp. 16, 17. This and the foregoing quotations are all from the Discourse concerning the True Way or Method of attaining to Divine Knowledge. THE CAMBEIDGE PLATONISTS 483 formalities, so that we may trace down Science in a constant chain of Deductions ; yet in our naked Intuitions and Visions of them, we clearly discern that Goodness and Wisdom lodge together. Justice and Mercy kiss each other : and all these and whatsoever pieces else the cracked glasses of our Reasons may sometime break Divine and Intelligible Being into, are fast knit up together in the invincible bonds of Eternity. And in this sense is that notion of Proclus descanting upon Plato's riddle of the Soul ώ§ -γζννητη καΧ άγίννητος, as if it were generated and yet not generated, to be understood ; ^/aovos ά/χα και αιών irepl την ψνχήν, the Soul partaking of Time in its broken and particular conceptions and apprehensions, and of Eternity in its Comprehensive and Stable Contemplations. I need not say that when the Soul is once got up to the top of this bright Olympus, it will then no more doubt of its own Immortality, or fear any Dissipation, or doubt whether any drowsy sleep shall hereafter seize upon it : no, it will then feel itself grasping fast and safely its own Immortality, and view itself in the Horizon of Eternity. In such sober kind of ecstasies did Plotinus find his own Soul separated from his body ..." I being often awakened into a sense of my self, and being sequestered from my body, and betaking myself from all things else into my self ; what admirable beauty did I then behold." . . . But here we must use some caution, lest we should arrogate too much to the power of our own Souls, which indeed cannot raise up themselves into that pure and steady contemplation of true Being ; but will rather act with some multiplicity or €Τ€ρότψ (as they speak) attending it. But thus much of its high original may appear to us, that it can correct itself for dividing and disjoin- ing therein, as knowing all to be every way one most entire and simple. . . . We shall add but this one thing further to clear the Soul's Immortality, and it is indeed that which breeds a true sense of it — viz.. True and real goodness. Our highest speculations of the Soul may beget a sufficient conviction thereof within us, but yet it is only True Goodness and Virtue in the Souls of men that can make them both kn^w and love, believe and delight themselves in their own Immortality. Though every good man is not so logically subtile as to be able by fit mediums to demonstrate his own Immortality, yet he sees it in a higher light : his Soul being purged and enlightened by true Sanctity is more capable of those divine irradiations, whereby it feels itself in conjunction with God, and by a σ-ννανγαα (as the Greeks speak), the Light of divine goodness mixing itself with the light of its own Reason, sees more clearly not only that it may, if it please the Supreme Deity, of its own nature exist eternally, but also that it shall do so. . . . It is indeed nothing else tlat makes men question the Immor- tality of their Souls, so much as their own base and earthly loves, 484 THE MYTHS OF PLATO which first makes them wish their Souls were not immortal, and then think they are not ; which Plotinus hath well observed and accordingly hath soberly pursued this argument : . . . " Let us now (saith he, Έηη. iv. 7. 10) consider a Soul, not such a one as is immersed into the Body . . . but such a one as hath cast away Concupiscence and Anger and other Passions. . . . Such a one as this will sufficiently manifest that all Vice is un- natural to the Soul, and something acquired only from abroad, and that the best Wisdom and all other Virtues lodge in a purged Soul, as being allied to it. If, therefore, such a Soul shall reflect upon itself, how shall it not appear to itself to be of such a kind of nature as Divine and Eternal Essences are ? For Wisdom and true Virtue being Divine Effluxes can never enter into any unhallowed and mortal thing : it must, therefore, needs be Divine, seeing it is filled with a Divine nature Sia crvyyeveLav καΐ rh ομοονσ-ίον, by its kindred and consanguinity therewith. . . . Con- template, therefore, the Soul of man, denuding it of all that which itself is not, or let him that does this, view his own Soul ; then he will believe it to be immortal, when he shall behold it €v τφ νοητά καΐ iv T(f καθαρψ, fixed in an Intelligible and pure nature ; he shall then behold his own intellect contemplating not any sensible thing, but eternal things, with that which is eternal, that is, with itself, looking into the intellectual world, being itself made all lucid, intellectual, and shining with Sun-beams of eternal Truth, borrowed from the First Good, which perpetually rayeth forth his Truth upon all intellectual beings. One thus qualified may seem without any arrogance to take up that saying of Empedocles, χαίρετ, Ιγώ δ' νμΐν θίος άμβροτοζ — Farewell all earthly allies, I am henceforth no mortal wight, but an immortal angel, ascending up into Divinity, and reflecting upon that likeness of it which I find in myself. When true Sanctity and Purity shall ground him in the knowledge of divine things, then shall the inward sciences that arise from the bottom of his own Soul display themselves ; which, indeed, are the only true sciences ; for the Soul runs not out of itself to behold Temperance and Justice abroad, but its own light sees them in the contemplation of its own being and that divine essence which was before enshrined within itself." ^ So much for Smith's presentation of the " Idea of Soul " ; it owes its main features to the doctrine of βρως and άνάμνησις set forth in the Phaedrus Myth ; and the " regulative " value of the " Idea " is finely appreciated. The regulative value of the " Idea of God " is as finely appreciated in the Discourse of ^ ox. pp. 99-105. THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 486 the Existence and Nature of God, where he says/ " God is not better defined to us by our understandings than by our wills and affections" and notes ^ the pre-eminence, in Platonism, of TO αηαθόν, which begets in us το ερωτίκον ττάθος. Similarly, in his Discourse of the Jewish Notion of a Legal Righteousness, he contrasts the doctrine of "Works set forth by the rabbinical writers with the Christian doctrine of Faith, and shows that the latter amounts to a doctrine of " divine grace and bounty as the only source of righteousness and happiness." St. Paul's doctrine of " Justification by Faith " is to be explained pla- tonically as ομοίωσις τω θεω. It is the justification of a sancti- fied nature — a nature which, by the grace of God, has been made a partaker of His life and strength. In Faith there is a true conjunction and union of the Souls of men with God, whereby they are made capable of true blessedness. " The Law is merely an external thing consisting in precepts which have only an outward administration" — it is the Βίακονία αγράμματος καΐ θανάτου : but " the administration of the Gospel is intrin- sical and vital in living impressions upon the Souls of men " — it is the BcaKovia ττνεύματος.^ " By which," he argues in a significant passage,* " the Apostle (2 Cor. iii. 6, 7) cannot mean the History of the Gospel, or those credenda propounded to us to believe ; for this would make the Gospel itself as much an external thing as the Law was, and according to the external administration as much a killing or dead letter as the Law was. . . . But, indeed, he means a vital efflux from God upon the Souls of men, whereby they are made partakers of Life and Strength from Him." I doubt we are too nice Logicians sometimes in distinguishing between the Glory of God and our own Salvation. We cannot in a true sense seek our own Salvation more than the Glory of God, which triumphs most and discovers itself most effectually in the salvation of Souls ; for indeed this salvation is nothing else but a true participation of the Divine Nature. Heaven is not a thing without us, nor is Happiness anything distinct from a true con- junction of the mind with God in a secret feeling of his goodness and reciprocation of affection to him, wherein the Divine Glory most unfolds itself. ... To love God above ourselves is not indeed so properly to love him ahov^ the salvation of our Souls, as if these 1 o.c. p. 137. 2 o.c. p. 139. » ^c. p. 311. * o.c. p. 312. 486 THE MYTHS OF PLATO were distinct things ; but it is to love him above all our own sinful affections, and above our particular Beings. . . . We cannot be com- pletely blessed till the Idea boni, or the Ipsum Bonum, which is God, exercise its sovereignty over all the faculties of our Souls, rendering them as like to itself as may consist with their proper capacity.^ I have quoted Smith at considerable length, that the reader may appreciate the place of the Platonist . doctrine, or rather άσκησις, of " ecstasy " in the Life and Philosophy of the Cambridge school. It would be easy to quote similar passages from Cudworth, More, and Norris ; but Smith seems to me to " keep his head " better than the others in the intoxicating Neo-Platonic atmosphere, and, moreover, to present " ecstasy " in a form which can be more easily recognised as connecting link between the doctrine of βρως and άνάμνησις set forth in the Phaedrus Myth and the doctrine of the " Presence of the Eternal Consciousness in my Consciousness," which meets us in the Epistemology and Ethics of T. H, Green and his school. Leaving the learning of the Cambridge Platonists, let us now look at their science. Their science was Cartesian — that is, it was physics and astronomy treated mathematically, according to mechanical principles, the application of which by Copernicus and Galileo, in the latter branch, had already overthrown the Aristotelian tradition, and produced an intellec- tual revolution, which can be compared only with that which Darwinism has produced in our own day. Natural science has always been influential in England in giving impulse to Philosophy, and even to Theology. Locke's Essay was occa- sioned and inspired by the activity of the Eoyal Society ; Berkeley's Idealism found expression in a monograph on the physiology of vision ; and it was not by mere accident that the University of Newton was the alma mater of the English Platonists. They received the new astronomy with enthusiasm. They were inspired by it. Like Xenophanes, they looked up at the Heavens and said, " The One is God." ^ " One great Order " and " Infinite Space " are the scientific ideas which dominate ^ o.c. pp. 410, 411, from "Discourse of the Excellency and Nobleness of True Religion." 2 Arist. Met. A 5. 986 b 24, e^s rbv oKov ovpavbv άττοβλέψαζ το ^v elvai φ-ησι. τόν θών. THE CAMBEIDGE PLATONISTS 487 Cudworth and his friends, and bring conviction to their belief — otherwise established by the authority of revelation and Platonic philosophy — in a " Governor of the Universe," a " Perfect and Infinite Being," a God who, in Plato's moral phrase, is " The Good," and yet, in scientific sense, may not unfitly be conceived spatially — as by Cudworth, in a strange passage : ^ — It is certain that there can be no mode, accident, or affection of Nothing; and consequently, that nothing cannot be extended nor measurable. But if space be neither the extension of body, nor yet of substance incorporeal, then must it of necessity be the extension of nothing, and the afi'ection of nothing; and nothing must be measurable by yards and poles. We conclude, therefore, that from this very hypothesis of the Democritic and Epicurean Atheists, that space is a nature distinct from body, and positively infinite, it follows undeniably that there must be some incorporeal substance whose aff'ection its extension is, and because there can be nothing infinite but only the Deity, that it is the infinite exten- sion of an incorporeal Deity. To this strange passage let me append some stanzas from More's FhilosophicJcall Poems, which show how the Copernican astronomy impressed his imagination — how the centrality of the Platonic αηαθόν in the intelligible world seemed to him to be imaged by the centrality of the Sun in the visible world. He has been speaking of the " stiff standers for ag'd Ptolemee," and proceeds : ^ — But let them bark like band-dogs at the moon That mindless passeth on in silencie : I'll take my flight above this outward Sunne, Regardless of such fond malignitie. Lift my self up in the Theologie Of heavenly Plato. There I'll contemplate The Arch type of this Sunne, that bright Idee Of steddie Good, that doth his beams dilate Through all the worlds, all lives and beings propagate. One steddy Good, centre of Essences, Unmoved Monad, that Apollo hight, The Intellectual Sunne whose energies Are all things that appear in vital hght, — * ' ^ Intellectual System, vol. iii. p. 232 (ed. Mosheim and Harrison). 2 Psychozoia, or Life of the Soul, pp. 157 flf. 488 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Whose brightness passeth every creature's sight. Yet round about him, stird with gentle fire, All things do dance ; their being, action, might, They thither do direct with strong desire. To embosom him with close embracements they aspire. Unseen, incomprehensible, He moves About himself each seeking entity That never yet shall find that which it loves. No finite thing shall reach infinity. No thing dispers'd comprehend that Unity ; Yet in their ranks they seemly foot it round. Trip it with joy at the world's harmony. Struck with the pleasure of an amorous stound. So dance they with fair floΛvers from unknown root y-crowned. Still falling short they never fail to seek. Nor find they nothing by their diligence ; They find repast, their lively longings eek Rekindled still, by timely influence. Thus all things in distinct circumference Move about Him that satisfies them all ; Nor be they thus stird up by wary sense Or foresight, or election rational 1, But blindly reel about the Heart of Lives centrall. So doth the Earth, one of the erring seven. Wheel round the fixed Sunne, that is the shade Of steddy Good, shining in this Out-heaven With the rest of those starres that God hath made Of baser matter, all which he array'd With his far-shining light. They sing for joy. They frisque about in circulings unstay'd. Dance through the liquid air, and nimbly toy, While Sol keeps clear the sprite, consumes what may accloy. The centre of each severall World's a Sunne With shining beams and kindly warming heat. About whose radiant crown the Planets runne, Like reeling moths around a candle light. These all together one World I conceit. And that even infinite such worlds there be, That unexhausted Good that God is hight A full sufficient reason is to me. Who simple Goodnesse make the highest Deity. The mathematical physics of Descartes and the Copernican astronomy were welcomed with joy by the Cambridge Platonists, as afifording a far better "Argument from Design" for the THE CAMBEIDGE PLATONISTS 489 existence of God than had been afforded by the Ptolemaic System, which, with its cumbrous commentary of Epicycles, called the mind away from the wisdom of the Creator to the ingenuity of man. The Copernican astronomy, by taking the fixed stars out of the solid sphere in which the Ptolemaic astronomy held them fast, and showing them to be central suns round which, as round the sun of our system, planets revolve in liquid aether, forces on us the thought that there is an infinity of such solar systems, or worlds, not a rounded-off universe, beyond whose flammantia moenia there is mere nothingness. " The infinity of worlds " was accepted as proof of the existence of an infinite, omnipresent Deity, an Incor- poreal Principle — a circle " whose centre is everywhere, and circumference nowhere." ^ A " finite universe " would be an argument for a " Corporeal Deity." This is why the Cam- bridge Platonists are so anxious to show that the Pytha- goreans and Platonists held, with Moses, the doctrine of the motion of the Earth. " Modern Science " had convinced them that this was the only doctrine consistent with a spiritual philosophy. The profound theological influence which the vast prospect opened up by the reformed astronomy exercised over the minds of men in the seventeenth century cannot be better brought home to us than by a passage in which Newton himself puts his own theological belief on record : ^ — The six Primary Planets revolve round the Sun in circles concentrical to the Sun, with the same direction of their motion, and very nearly in the same Plane. The moons (or secondary planets) revolve round the Earth, Jupiter, and Saturn, with the same direction of their motion, and very nearly in the plane of the orbs of the planets. And all these regular motions have not their rise from mechanical causes, seeing the comets are carried in orbs very eccentrical, and that very freely through all parts of the Heavens. . . . This most elegant system of planets and comets could not be produced but by and under the Contrivance and Dominion of an Intelligent and powerful Being. And, if the fixed stars are the centres of such other systems, all these, being framed by the like counsel, will be subject to the dominion of One ; especially seeing the Light of the fixed stars is of the same ^ More's Philosophickall PoemJf notes, p. 409. ^ Scholium generate at the end of the Friiicipia. I avail myself of Maxwell's translation in his edition of Cumberland's Laws of Nature. 490 THE MYTHS OF PLATO nature with that of the Sun, and the Light of all these systems passes mutually from one to another. And He has placed the systems of the fixed stars at immense distances from one another, lest they should mutually rush upon one another by their gravity. He governs all things, not as the Soul of the World, but as the Lord of the Universe ; and because of His dominion. He is wont to be called παντοκράτωρ, Universal Emperor. For God is a relative word, and hath a relation to servants ; and the Deity is the Empire of God, not over His own Body, as is the opinion of those who make Him the Soul of the World, but over His servants. The Supreme God is a Being, Eternal, Infinite, Absolutely Perfect ; but a Being, however Perfect, without Dominion, is not Lord God. . . . He governs all things, and knows all things which are done, or which can be done. He is not Eternity and Infinity, but He is Eternal and Infinite ; He is not Duration and Space, but He endures and is present. He endures always, and is present every- where ; and by existing always and everywhere. He constitutes Duration and Space, Eternity and Infinity. Whereas every particle of Space is always, and every indivisible moment of Duration is everywhere, certainly the Framer and Lord of the Universe shall not be never, nowhere. . . . We have not any notion of the Substance of God. We know Him only by His properties and attributes, and by the most wise and excellent structure of Things, and by Final Causes ; but we adore and worship Him on account of His Dominion. For we worship Him as His servants ; and God without Dominion, Providence, and Final Causes, is nothing else but Fate and Xature. There arises no Variety in Things from blind metaphysical necessity, which is always and everywhere the same. All diversity in the Creatures could arise only from the Ideas and Will of a necessarily-existent Being. We speak, however, allegorically when we say that God sees, hears, speaks, laughs, loves, hates, despises, gives, receives, rejoices, is angry, fights, fabricates, builds, composes. For all speech con- cerning God is borrowed, by Analogy or some Eesemblance, from human affairs. ... So much concerning God, of Whom the Dis- course from Phenomena belongs to Experimental Philosophy. . . . The main business of Natural Philosophy is to argue from Phenomena without feigning Hypotheses, and to deduce Causes from Effects, till we come to the very First Cause, which certainly is not mechanical. Besides the better Argument from Design which the reformed astronomy seemed to offer, there was also the famous Cartesian argument from our Idea of a Perfect Being to his Existence. Cudworth^ seems to feel the difficulties ^ Intellectual System, vol. iii. pp. 38 if. THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 491 connected with this argument, but is unwilling to declare himself against it. More/ however, who is less critical, accepts it thankfully. I have already alluded to one serious objection which Cudworth has to offer to the Cartesian system — viz., that by substituting " mechanism " for the " plastick soul," it leaves the immaterial substance, theoretically retained, little, if anything, to do, and weakens immensely the value of the argument from Design in Nature.^ However, the general tendency of Cartesianism being favourable to religion, and opposed to Hobbes, Cudworth is satisfied with merely warning his readers against this particular flaw in the system. Holding as he does a brief for Descartes, he argues that " mechanism," in the Cartesian system, is so conceived as to necessitate the assumption of the existence of an immaterial substance as άρχη κίνησβως. He evidently attaches more value to this merit in Cartesianism than to its proof of the Existence of Grod from our Idea of him ; and yet it is plainly not a very great merit after all, if we are left with data from which we are, indeed, compelled to infer an Immaterial Power or Force beyond dead matter, but cannot infer Wisdom controlling that Power or Force. We are not surprised, then, to find that Cudworth and his school, Cartesians though they profess to be, are very strenuous in maintaining the contrary of the Cartesian doctrine which makes True and False, Eight and Wrong, depend entirely on the Will of God, and not rather on an " Eternal ii'ature of Things," or " Law of the Ideal World," logically distinct from, and prior to, the Will of God, in accordance with which, however, the Will of God is always exercised. Smith, indeed, the clearest head, I think, among the English Platonists, is so well aware of the difficulty of combining Cartesianism with Platonism that he touches but lightly on the arguments for the existence of God supplied by the former system, and dwells mainly on the evidence fur- nished by man's moral nature and sanctified heart. " A Holy Life" he says,^ is the best and most compendious way to Bight Belief." Of the two witnesses spoken of by Kant — " The starry Heaven above, and the Moral Law within" — Smith 1 An Antidote against AtMism, Book i. chaps. 7 and 8, pp. 20 if. 2 See p. 478 supra. 2 The True Way or Method of attaining to Divine Knowledge, p. 9. 492 THE MYTHS OF PLATO chose the latter to found his theological belief upon — in this perhaps, more philosophical than Cudworth and More, thi greater lights of the school, who, without ignoring the " argu- ment from the heart," are inclined rather to look to " science ' — to " design in nature," and to " epistemology " — for proof o: the existence of God. For the Immortality of the Soul, the other cardina' doctrine of Theology and Morals, Cudworth and More are ver) busy in producing " scientific " evidence, and, on the whole find it easy to press the science of their day into the servici of the doctrine. The starting-point of their scientific argument is, that thi Soul is an "incorporeal substance." Systems of Philosophy both ancient and modern, are distinguished as " theistic " anc " atheistic," according as they profess or deny the doctrine o; " incorporeal substance." The saving merit of Descartes, as w( have seen, is that, after all, he recognises " incorporeal sub• stance." On the other hand, Hobbes denies it. In the nintl chapter of the First Book of The Immortality of the Soul More examines Hobbes' disproof of Spirit or incorporeal substance. Hobbes' argument is, " Every substance hai dimensions ; but a Spirit has no dimensions ; therefore then is no spiritual substance." " Here," writes More,^ " I con fidently deny the assumption. For it is not the character• istikall of a Body to have dimensions, but to be impenetrable All Substance has dimensions — that is. Length, Breadth, anc Depth ; but all has not impenetrahility. See my letters tc Monsieur Des Cartes." This refutation of Hobbes falls bacl• on the definitions of Spirit and of Body which More has giver in an earlier part of the same treatise ^ — Spirit is defined ai " a Substance penetrable and indiscerpible " ; Body, as " a Sub• stance impenetrable and discerpible." This definition he amends in the chapter against Hobbes, putting it thus : — Spirit or Incorporeal is " Extended Substance, with activity and indiscerpibility , leaving out impenetrability " More thui plainly ranges himself with those who assumed an extended incorporeal substance ; but, of course, there were many incor- porealists, among whom was Plotinus,^ who regarded Spirit as 1 Page 41. 2 p^ge 21. ^ See Cudworth, Intell. System, vol. iii. p. 386. THE CAMBEIDGE PLATONISTS 493 unextended. Cudworth compares the opposite views of these two classes of incorporealists at great length, and ends ^ by leaving the question open, although one might gather that he inclines to the view favoured by More from his speaking of Space as incorporeal substance, with the attribute of exten- sion, and infinite ; and therefore as equivalent to God, who is the only infinite substance.^ But the " incorporeal substance " of Descartes, though a good enough " scientific" beginning for a doctrine of the Immortality of the Soul, is only a beginning ; just as it is only a beginning for a " scientific " proof of the existence of God. Cartesianism falls short, according to the Cambridge School, as we have seen, in ignoring the " plastic principle," or "soul of nature." It leaves us between the horns of a dilemma : either mere mechanism, once started by God, pro- duces effects blindly ; or God interferes personally in the smallest details. The plastic principle releases us from this dilemma. It may be described as an incorporeal substance, or principle, which, like Aristotle's φύσις, works evexa τον without consciousness. To it God, who is Self-conscious Good- ness and Wisdom, delegates, as it were, the task of carrying on the operations of nature : these operations are therefore God's operations, and His goodness and wisdom may be inferred from them ; but we are not obliged to hold the ridiculous opinion that He produces them by immediate intervention. It is the plastic principle which, in the inorganic world, immediately determines, e.g., the distances of the fixed stars from one another and the paths of their planets, and, in the organic world, appears as that " vegetative part of the Soul " which builds up the body terrestrial, aerial or aethereal, without which, as " vehicle," consciousness would be impossible in the case of finite spirits : ^ without this plastic, vehicle-building, principle there could be no " reproduction," to use T. H. Green's terms, of the "Eternal Consciousness." I have already, in an early part of this work,* had occasion to describe the use which More makes of the plastic principle in his account of the future existence of the Soul, and would 1 o.c. iii. 398. ' o.c. iii. 232. ' Cudworth thinks it **j)robable" that no spirit except God can exist without a body of some kind {InteU. System, vol. iii. p. 368). 4 Pages 95 flF. 494 THE MYTHS OF PLATO only add here that Cudworth treats of the principle in his Intellectual System, vol. i. pp. 235-252 (ed. Mosheim and Harrison) — in a passage well worth the attention of any one interested in the point at issue between the " teleological " and the " mechanical " explanation of the world. The English Platonist of the seventeenth century, with his " plastic soul," makes out, I venture to think, as plausible a case for " teleology " as his successor, the English Idealist of the nineteenth or twentieth century, manages to do with his " spiritual principle." The chief difference between the two advocates is that the former tells us frankly that his plastic soul is "unconscious," while the latter leaves us in doubt whether his " spiritual principle " is " conscious " or " unconscious." Having attempted to describe — in mere outline — the learning and the science of the Cambridge Platonists, I now go on to compare their central doctrine with that of the English Idealists of the present day — the school of which T. H. Green may be taken as representative. The comparison will show, I think, that the central doctrine of these English Idealists, equally with that of the Cambridge Platonists, is to be traced to Plato — and to Plato the mythologist, rather than to Plato the dialectician. The central doctrine of the Cambridge Platonists is the Doctrine of Ideas as presented in the Phaedrus Myth — that is, presented to religious feeling as theory of the union of man with God in knowledge and conduct. In the Doctrine of Ideas, as it is presented to the scientific understanding in such contributions to Logic as Republic, 509 D fP., the Cambridge Platonists, like their Alexandrine predecessors, seem to take little interest. The Doctrine of Ideas as adopted by the Cambridge Platonists may be stated as follows : — Sensible things, which come into existence and perish, are but reflections, images, ectypes, of Eternal Essences, Archetypal Forms, or Ideas. These Ideas are the νοήματα, the " Thoughts," of Gou — the elements which constitute his Eternal Wisdom, σοφία, or X6yo<;. The Wisdom of God is that World of Ideas, that mundus arche- typus, according to the conception of which he created this visible world. Man attains to knowledge, ετηστημη, only in THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 495 so far as he apprehends these Eternal Thoughts of the Divine Wisdom — only in so far as, spurred to reflection by the stimuli of sense, he enters into communion with the Mind of God, " sees things in God." This communion is possible only be- cause man's spirit is of one kind with the spirit of God — τον yap 761/09 εσμεν. " All minds partake of one original mind," ^ are "reproductions of the Eternal Consciousness"^ — find that its eternal Ideas are theirs too. Thus epistemology involves theology. The theory of knowledge involves the supposition of a " universal consciousness," or " Wisdom of God," as Eternal Subject of those €ΪΒη or "forms," without the constructive activity of which in the mind of man his sensations would be " blind." From this sketch it may be seen that the doctrine of archetypal Ideas amounts, in the English Intellectualists, to a Theory of Knowledge, in which the a priori element is recog- nised, as in the Kantian philosophy. Let me fill in my sketch by quoting some passages from More, Cudworth, Smith, Norris, and Berkeley. In his antidote against Atheism,^ More speaks of " relative notions or ideas " — Cause and Effect, Whole and Part, Like and Unlike — in much the same way as Kant speaks of his "Categories of the Understanding." These "relative ideas," he says, " are no external Impresses upon the senses, but the Soul's own active manner of conceiving those things which are discovered by the outward senses." Again, in the Cahhala,^ in a passage which carries us out of the " Critique of Pure Eeason " into the " Metaphysic of Morals," he says : " The Soul of man is not merely passive as a piece of wood or stone, but is forth- with made active by being acted upon ; and therefore if God in us rules, we rule with him ; if he contend against sin in us, we also contend together with him against the same ; if he see in us what is good or evil, we, ipso facto, see by him — In his light we see light ; and so in the rest." Again, in his Philosophickall Poems^ the following curious passage occurs — a passage, I venture to think, of considerable philosophic import, on account of the wide view taken of innate ideas, or a priori forms : bodies, it is suggested, are shaped, as well as 1 Cudworth, Int. System, iii. 62. ^ Green, Prolegomena to Ethics. 8 Page 18, bk. i. ch. 6. ^ p^ge 154. β Page 238. 496 THE MYTHS OF PLATO conscious experience organised, according to a 'priori, constitu- tional forms : — If plantall souls in their own selves contain That vital formative fecundity, That they a tree with different colours stain, And diverse shapes, smoothnesse, asperity, Straightnesse, acutenesse, and rotoundity, A golden yellow, or a crimson red, A varnish'd green with such like gallantry ; How dull then is the sensitive ? how dead. If forms from its own centre it can never spread ? Again, an universal notion, What object ever did that form impresse Upon the soul ? What makes us venture on So rash a matter, as e'er to confesse Ought generally true ? when neverthelesse AVe cannot e'er runne through all singulars. Wherefore in our own souls we do possesse Free forms and immateriall characters, Hence 'tis the soul so boldly generall truth declares. ****** What body ever yet could figure show Perfectly, perfect, as rotundity. Exactly round, or blamelesse angularity ? Yet doth the soul of such like forms discourse, And finden fault at this deficiency, And rightly term this better and that worse ; Wherefore the measure is our own Idee^ Which th' humane Soul in her own self doth see. And sooth to sayen whenever she doth strive To find pure truth, her own profundity She enters, in her self doth deeply dive ; From thence attempts each essence rightly to descrive. The lines with which the last stanza ends find their com- mentary in a passage in Smith's Discourse of the Immortality/ of the Soul} in which the κίνησις ττροβαηκη and the κίνησι,ς κυκΚίκη of the Soul are distinguished. By the former she goes forth and deals with material things ; by the latter she reflects upon herself. What she finds by " refiection " he sets forth in his Discourse concerning the Existence and Nature of God} Plotinus hath well taught us, eU eavrov ίττιστρίψων, €Ls οίρχην ίτΓίστρβφζΐ, He which reflects upon himself reflects npon his own Origi- nally and finds the clearest Impression of some Eternall Nature and 1 Pages 65, 66. 2 p^geg 123, 124. THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 497 Perfect Being stamp'd upon his own Soul. And therefore Plato seems sometimes to reprove the ruder sort of men in his times for their contrivance of Pictures and Images to put themselves in mind of the Seoi or Angelicall Beings, and exhorts them to look into their own Souls, which are the fairest Images, not onely of the lower Divine Natures, but of the Deity itself; God having so copied forth himself into the whole life and energy of man's Soul, as that the lovely Characters of Divinity may be most easily seen and read of all men within themselves ; as they say Phidias the famous statuary, after he made the statue of Minerva with the greatest exquisiteness of art to be set up in the Acropolis at Athens, afterwards impressed his own Image so deeply in her buckler, uf nemo delere possit aut divellere, qui Mam statuam non imminueret. And if we would know what the Impresse of Souls is, it is nothing but God himself, who could not write his own name so as that it might be read but onely in Rationall Natures. Neither could he make such without imparting such an Imitation of his own Eternall Understanding to them as might be a per- petual Memorial of himself within them. And whenever we look upon our own Soul in a right manner, we shall find an Urim and Thummim there, by which we may ask counsel of God himself, who will have this alway born upon its breastplate. The passage which I shall quote from Cudworth is a criticism of Hobbes' " atheistical " doctrine that " knowledge and understanding being in us nothing else but a tumult in the mind raised by external things that press the organical parts of a man's body, there is no such thing in God, nor can they be attributed to him, they being things which depend upon natural causes." ^ To this Cudworth replies : — There comes nothing to us from bodies without us but only local motion and pressure. Neither is sense itself the mere passion of those motions, but the perception of their passions in a way of fancy. But sensible things themselves (as, for example, light and colours) are not known or understood either by the passion or the fancy of sense, nor by anything merely foreign and adventitious, but by intelligible ideas exerted from the mind itself — that is, by something native and domestic to it. . . . Wherefore, besides the phantasms of singular bodies, or of sensible things existing without us (which are not mere passions neither), it is plain that our human mind hath other cogitations or conceptions in it — namely, the ideas of the intelligible natures and essences of things, which are universal, and by and lender which it understands singulars ^ Inlell. System, Hi. p. 60. 2k 498 THE MYTHS OF PLATO . . . which universal objects of our mind, though they exist not as such anywhere without it, yet are they not therefore nothing, but have an intelligible entity for this very reason, because they are conceivable. ... If, therefore, there be eternal intelligibles or ideas, and eternal truths and necessary existence do belong to them, then must there be an eternal mind necessarily existing, since these truths and intelligible essences of things cannot possibly be anywhere but in a mind. . . . There must be a mind senior to the world, and all sensible things, and such as at once compre- hends in it the ideas of all intelligibles, their necessary scheses and relations to one another, and all their immutable truths; a mind which doth not ore μ^ν voet, ore δε ov voel (as Aristotle writeth it), sometimes understand, and sometimes not understand . . . but ova-La €V€/3y€ta, such a mind as is essentially act and energy, and hath no defect in it. . . . Hence it is evident that there can be but one only original mind ... all other minds whatsoever par- taking of one original mind, and being, as it were, stamped with the impression or signature of one and the same seal. From whence it cometh to pass that all minds, in the several places and ages of the world, have ideas or notions of things exactly alike, and truths indivisibly the same. Truths are not multiplied by the diversity of minds that apprehend them, because they are all but ectypal participations of one and the same original or archetypal mind and truth. As the same face may be reflected in several glasses, and the image of the same sun may be in a thousand eyes at once beholding it, and one and the same voice may be in a thousand ears listening to it, so when innumerable created minds have the same ideas of things, and understand the same truths, it is but one and the same eternal light that is reflected in them all (that light which enlighteneth every man that cometh into the world), or the same voice of that one everlasting Word, that is never silent, re-echoed by them. . . . We conclude, therefore, that from the nature of mind and knowledge it is demonstrable that there can be but one original and self- existent Mind, or understanding Being, from which all other minds were derived.^ This is a passage, I venture to think, of first-rate histori- cal importance. It furnishes the link which connects the Epistemological Theism which we find in the writings of T. H. Green with the Mythology of the Timaeus and Phaedrus. Norris's discussion of the a 'priori in knowledge has some points of special interest. Having shown, in the ordinary way, that there are eternal and necessary Truths, i.e. eternal and necessary Propositions, he dwells on the point that the ^ Intell. System^ iii. pp. 62-72. THE CAMBRIDGE PLATONISTS 499 simple essences, the mutual relations or habitudes of which are set forth in these propositions, must be themselves eternal and necessary. " There can be no mutual habitudes or relations of things as to affirmation or negation," he says,^ " without the reality of the things themselves," The point here insisted on by Norris is one which the modern dictum^ '' Things are nothing except as determined by Relations," is apt to make us lose sight of; and his remarks following seem to me to be worth attention : — Two circles touching one another inwardly cannot have the same common centre. This is a true Proposition. But I here demand, How can it possibly have this certain habitude of division or negation unless there be two such distinct simple Essences as Circle and Centre. Certainly there can be no reference or relation where there is nothing to support it. . . . If there can be no connexion or relation between things that are not, then also there can be no eternal connexion or relation between things that have not an eternal existence. . . . But there are such eternal habitudes and relations, therefore the simple Essences of things are also eternal. ... I know very well this is not according to the Decrees of the Peripatetic School, which has long since con- demned it as Heretical Doctrine, to say that the Essences of things do exist from eternity. . . . They tell us that the habitudes are not attributed absolutely to the simple Essences as in actual being, but only hypothetically — that whensoever they shall exist, they shall also carry such relations to one another. There is, says the Peripatetic, only a conditional connexion between the subject and the predicate, not an absolute position of either. This goes smoothly down with the young scholar at his Logic Lecture, and the Tutor applauds his distinction, and thinks he has thereby -quitted his hands of a very dangerous heresie. But now to this I return answer . . . that these habitudes are not (as is supposed) only by way of hypothesis, but absolutely attributed to the simple Essences, as actually existing. For when I say, for instance, that every part of a circle is equally distant from the centre, this proposition does not hang in suspense, then to be actually verified when the things shall exist in Nature^ but is at present actually true, as actually true as ever it will or can be ; and consequently I may thence infer that the things themselves already are. There is no necessity, I confess, they should exist in Nature, which is all that the objection proves, but exist they must. For of nothing there can be no affection. . . . Having cleared our way by making it evident that the simple Essences of things are ^ Reason and Religion, p. 73. 500 THE MYTHS OF PLATO eternal, the next thing that I consider is, that since they are not eternal in their natural subsistencieSj they must be eternal in some other way of subsisting. And that must be in some understand- ing, or by way of ideal subsistence.^ For there are but two con- ceivable ways how anything may exist, either out of all under- standing, or within some understanding. If, therefore, the simple Essences of things are eternal, but not out of all understanding, it remains they must have an eternal existence in some understand- ing. Which is what I call an ideal subsistence. There is, therefore, another way of existing besides that in Rerum Natura, namely, in the Mundus Archetypus, or the Ideal World, where all the Rationes rerum, or simple Essences of things, have an eternal and immutable existence, before ever they enter upon the Stage of Nature. I further consider, that this understanding wherein the simple Essences of things have an eternal existence must be an eternal understanding. For an Essence can no more eternally exist in a temporary understanding than a body can be infinitely extended in a finite space. Now, this Eternal Understanding can be no other than the Understanding of God. The simple Essences of things, therefore, do eternally exist in the Understanding of God.2 God, Norris goes on to argue, is a simple and uncom- pounded Being, and there is nothing in Him which is not Himself ; accordingly, these Eternal Ideas, or Simple Essences of Things, are but the Divine Essence itself, considered " as variously exhibitive of things, and as variously imitable or participate by them." ^ " This Ideal World, this Essence of God considered as variously exhibitive and representative of things, is no other than the Divine Χό^γος, the Second Person of the ever Blessed Trinity." * Descartes, it is argued/ makes God, as concepti'oe, the cause of Truth — i.e. as pleased to conceive — e.g. a Triangle so and so — not as exhibitive of the Eternal Ideas. Here Descartes " blunders horribly." " I am for the dependence of Truth upon the Divine Intellect as well as he, but not so as to make it arbitrary and contingent, and consequently not upon the Divine Intellect as conceptive, but only as exhibitive. That is, that things are therefore true inasmuch as they are conformable to those standing and ^ Norris here {Reason and Religion, p. 80) draws the distinction of which Lotze makes so much in his Logic (Book iii. ch. 2, The World of Ideas, pp. 433 ff., English Transl.), between the Reality of Existence and the Reality of Validity. ^ Jieason and Religion, pp. 74-81. 3 o.c. pp. 81, 82. 4 ^ g ρ 35 5 ^ ^^ pp_ g2, 93. THE CAMBEIDGE PLATONISTS 501 immutable Ideas which are in the mind of God as Exhibitive and representative of the whole Possibility of Being." God is omniscient, as " comprehending within himself all the Ideas and Essences of things with all their possible references and respects, that is, all Truth " ^ — a doctrine which seems to me to be exactly equivalent to T. H. Green's doctrine of " the Eternal Consciousness as subject of all Kelations." " We see and know all things in God." ^ This doctrine, Norris tells us, he thought out for himself, and afterwards found in Plotinus, Proclus, St. Augustine, Marsilius Ficinus, and especially in Malebranche, whose doctrine he then proceeds to state : ^ — We know objects by the mediation of " Ideas." The " Ideas " of things are in God. " God by his presence is intimately united to our minds, so that God may be said to be the Pla/ie of Spirits, as Space is the Plax^e of Bodies" Thus " we see all things in God."* This is the doctrine of Malebranche, accepted by Norris — a doctrine which labours under the ambiguity attaching to its use of the term " Idea," which means both a mental image derived from a sensible object, and an eternal ihea in the Platonic acceptation. But we need not go into this difiiculty in Malebranche's doctrine ; it is enough here to notice that Norris understands the doctrine as genuinely Platonic. Plato's definition of knowledge as a " Participation of Ideas " amounts, he says,^ to " seeing all things in God." "If we did not some way or other see God, we should see nothing at all ; even as if we did not love God, that is, if God did not con- tinually impress upon us the love of good in general, we should love nothing at all : for since this Love is the same with our Will, we cannot love or will anything without him, since we cannot love particular goods but by determining towards those goods that motion of Love which God gives us towards himself." ^ " All our Illumination proceeds from the Divine λόγο?, the substantial Wisdom of God. But St. John speaks more plainly : This is the true light which enlightens every man that comes into the world. Now, true Light is here the same as only Light, and implies that all other pretended lights are false ones. Again, says our Lord, / am the Light of the World. And, I am the way, the truth, and the life. And again says our Lord in his Prayer, Sanctifie them through m 1 o.e. p. 101. 2 Q^c. p. 18δ. ^ ^.c. pp. 187-194. 4 o.c. p. 202. « O.C. p. 207. ' o,c. p. 200. 502 THE MYTHS OF PLATO thy truth; thy word is truth : which is not meant of the written word, but of the Substantial and Eternal Word, as appears from the context. Lastly, the Apostle says expressly of this Divine Word, that L• is made unto us Wisdom. Which is exactly accord- ing to our hypothesis that we see all things in the Ideal World, or Divine λόγο?. . . . All our Light and Illumination proceeds wholly from him who at first said let there he light. We see so much of Truth as we see of God. The Ideas which are in God are the very Ideas which we see. The Divine Aoyos is our Wisdom, as well as the Wisdom of his Father. So absolutely necessary is the Doctrine of Ideas, when rightly stated, to the explaining the Mode both of Divine and Human knowledge; without which I shall venture to affirm that they can neither of them be explained or understood." ^ Dominus Illuminatio Mea\ "The Platonic Philosophers do wonderfully refine upon Light, and soar very high," as Berkeley writes in Siris^ — himself, at last, a professed ad- herent of the school of Cudworth : — As understanding perceiveth not, that is, doth not hear, or see, or feel, so sense knoweth not; and although the mind may use both sense and fancy as means whereby to arrive at know- ledge, yet sense or soul, so far forth as sensitive, knoweth nothing. For as it is rightly observed in the Theaetetus of Plato, science consists not in the passive perceptions, but in the reasoning upon them, τω π€ρΙ εκείνων σνλλογίσ-μω.^ So much for the epistemology, strictly so called, of the Cambridge Platonists. It is a theory of the communion of man with God, derived from the doctrine of IBeai as set forth " mythologically " in the Timaeus, Fhaedrus, and Symposium. It is easy to see how this epistemology explains the function ascribed by the school to Keason, as Moral Faculty — as recognising and imposing Obligation. Morality is the Kational Life — the Life regulated by the consciousness of Self, not as passive in the midst of the flux of vanishing sensibles, but as actively displaying its own spiritual nature and kinship with God by communicating in His eternal and immutable nature. Its rational communion in his nature is not an outward act, like looking at a picture which one may turn away from when one pleases: it is an inward act "i o.c. pp. 222-224. ] 2 § 2IO. » Siris, § 305. THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 603 of reflection — κίνησις κυκλική — revealing one's own per- manent nature — permanent, in that it " mirrors " or " repro- duces " God's nature ; it is an inward act revealing one's own permanent nature, which one cannot — even when it would please one to do so — turn one's back upon. The object of Keason, with which Eeason is itself identical, is the whole man, regarded sub specie aeternitatis, seen in God, seen in his own proper place in the Cosmos. This object cannot be set aside, as the object of a passing inclination may be set aside. This is how "Eeason imposes Obligation." Nor does the physical organism of plant or animal differ in this respect from the moral nature, if we consider the matter philosophi- cally. It obliges those functions and acts which are in accord- ance with its particular Type, its particular Type being a " mode " of the Universe. " Keason," then, as it is understood by the Platonists, being the consciousness of Self as creature made after the image of God — as mirror of the aeternae rationes rerum which constitute the Divine Sapientia, — " Eeason," being this, needs not to have its dictates enforced by any alien power : in being promulgated they are carried out. The moral life is, on its plane, as inevitable as the physical life. All living creatures strive after that good which is competent to their several types in the places which they hold in the great system of the Universe. " There is nothing," says Norris,^ " in nature more necessary — no, nor so necessary and invincible, as that motion whereby we are carried forth to good in general. Here the Soul must not pretend to the least shadow of Liberty, having no more command over this motion than she has over the motion of the Sun." " God is that which we directly and properly love (or desire), and created goods, or particular goods, are only so far loved as they resemble and participate of the nature of that universal good." " If we did not love God ... we should love nothing at all. . . . This Love is the same with our Will." ^ We are reminded of Aristotle's το iv ημΐν Oeiov, that answering nisus or love in us, and in all living creatures, which is awakened by God, who, himself unmoved, moves all things by the attraction of loveliness — a doctrine glossed by Plottnus, where he says that the Principle 1 Reason and Eeligimi, pp. 237, 238. - ox. p. 200. 504 THE MYTHS OF PLATO of Organic Life is Love contemplating the Ideal Forms, and, by its mere act of silent contemplation, producing embodi- ments of them — καΐ oi βρωτβς ΙΒόντων καΐ iirl το etSo? στΓβυΒόντων} That " Keason," in the epistemology and moral theology of our Platonists, is consciousness of the Whole — of God-in- Man and Man-in-God — is a point which it is important to keep steadily in view, not only if we would understand what is meant by " obligation," but also if we would get behind phrases to real meaning, when we are told that the " Truths apprehended by Eeason " are " eternal and immutable," that is, " necessary," being at once the contents of the Divine Wisdom and the conditions of human knowledge. No " Truth," taken by itself, can be apprehended as " necessary " ; it can only be accepted as a νττόθβσι,ς. The " necessity " of a " Truth " is apparent only to a synoptic gaze, which takes in the whole order of which the " Truth " is a part. The whole is first acquiesced in as άρχη άννττόθβτος, and then we see that its parts severally " cannot be otherwise." This is the gist of the passage at the end of the Sixth Book of the Republic, where the function of Eeason in Dialectic is set forth. A " Truth " is seen to be " necessary " when it is seen to be involved in the " whole " ; and the progress of knowledge is a process of integration by which disjecta membra of experience are pieced together into a con- sistent whole, and their natures seen to be such as " cannot be otherwise." But this process would be impossible unless the Eational Soul came to her task of integration with a native idea of the " whole." This native idea is not something which is a mere part of her. It is herself — the unity of her self- hood of which she is conscious. As her knowledge advances — that is, as she brings more and more data into clearly-seen relation with her own " self-centrality," as More phrases it, she herself spreads from her centre, becoming more and more " adequate " to the objective world, more and more assimilated to God. This growth of the Eational Soul in " Likeness to God " — in " correspondence with environment " — expresses the law of her inmost being, commanding categorically : Live thy Life, ^ Enn. iii. 8. 7, THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 505 " Reason," then, according to the Platonic school, is " organism." How shallow the criticism which finds fault with them for giving us, in Eeason, a principle which is not a principle of action, and carries with it no consciousness of obligation ! As if organism, with its invincible Wille zum Leben, did not move, and oblige, to action ! The central doctrine of the English Platonists, which I am trying to set forth, gives an important place to the discussion of the relation of God's " Will " to his " Wisdom and Good- ness." By the " Wisdom and Goodness " of God they under- stand the perfect order of that mundus archetyjpus, or system of iheat, or νοήματα, dwelling from all eternity in the Divine Intellect; by the "Will" of God, the going forth of his Power in the production and preservation of this visible world and all that is in it. They maintain, against Descartes and others,^ that God's " Will " did not make, and cannot alter, the contents of the intelligible world, which have natures "essential," not "arbitrary." God's "Will" is ruled by his " Wisdom and Goodness " — that is, his " Will " expresses his essential nature. He cannot make right wrong, or true false, by arbitrary act of Will. If God do all things simply at his pleasure ^ Because lie will, and not because it's good, So that his actions will have no set measure ; Is 't possible it should be understood What he intends ? I feel that he is loved Of my dear soul, and know that I have borne Much for his sake ; yet is it not hence proved That I shall live, though I do sigh and mourn To find his face ; his creature's wish he'll shght and scorn. Nor of well-being, nor subsistency Of our poor souls, when they do hence depart, Can any be assured, if liberty We give to such odde thoughts, that thus pervert The laws of God, and rashly do assert That Will rules God, but Good rules not God's Will. What e'er from right, love, equity, doth start. For ought we know then God may act'that ill. Only to shoΛV his might, and his free mind fulfill. 1 E.g. Occam (as quoted by Maxwell in his edition of Cumberland's Laws of Nature, p. 80) — " nullus est actuf mains, nisi quatenus a Deo prohibitus est, et qui non potest fieri bonus, si a Deo praecipiatur, et e converse." 2 More, Phil. Poems, p. 179. 506 THE MYTHS OF PLATO To the same effect, Cudworth : ^ — Plotinus writeth, Trotet to θ€Ϊον as ττ^φνκζ, 7Γ€φνκ€ Se κατά την αντου ονσίαν, η το καλ6ν kv ταΐζ ivepyeiais αντον καΐ Th δίκαιον (τννεκφίρζί, €t γαρ μη €κά ταύτα, ττον αν €Ϊη ; " The Deity acteth according to its own nature and essence ; and its nature and essence display eth goodness and justice : for if these things be not there, where should they else be found?" And again, elsewhere : θ^ος S-n-cp ^χρην cTvai, ov toIwv οΰτω σννίβη, αλλ* eSet οΰτω' το δ* €^€i τοντο αρχή των δσα Ιδβι : " God is essentially that which ought to be : and therefore he did not happen to be such as he is : and this first ought to be is the principle of all things whatsoever that ought to be." Wherefore the Deity is not to be conceived as mere arbitrariness, humour, or irrational will and appetite omnipotent (which would, indeed, be but omnipotent chance), but as an overflowing fountain of love and goodness, justly and wisely dispensing itself, and omnipotently reaching all things. The Avill of God is goodness, justice, and wisdom; or decorousness, and ought itself, willing; so that the TO βζλτίστον, that which is absolutely the best, is v6μos άττα/οά/^ατο?, "an indispensable law to it, because its very essence." God is μίτρον πάντων, an "impartial balance" lying even, equal, and indifferent, to all things, and weighing out heaven and earth, and all the things therein, in the most just and exact proportions, and not a grain too much or too little of anything. Nor is the Deity therefore bound or obliged to do the best, in any way of servility (as men fondly imagine this to be contrary to his liberty), much less by the law and command of any superior (which is a contra- diction), but only by the perfection of its own nature, which it cannot possibly deviate from, no more than ungod itself. Now, we must not regard this question of the relation of the " Will " to the " Wisdom and Goodness " of God as one of those bygone questions of scholasticism with which we need no longer, in our day, trouble ourselves. It is a present-day question — indeed, a perennial question. It raises the whole issue of Pessimism against Optimism. Pessimism will never infect the bulk of mankind — those who do not reflect, but push their way on, and lead ambitious, industrious lives ; but reflective idle people — a growing number in the modern world — it is likely to infect more and more. It is likely to get hold of literature, and even of philosophy, to a greater extent. The number is steadily growing of those who are educated in book-learning, and can make a living by 1 Intell System, iii. 463, 464. THE CAMBEIDGE PLATONISTS 507 supplying idle readers with reflections on life embodied in the novel and other forms of "light reading." Pessimism suits well with the mood which such writers have to cater for — the mood of habitual lookers-on at life ; but those whose energetic temperament moves them to put their hand to things and try to get them done are not troubled with the suspicion that all their work is vanity. It was a profound insight which caused Plato to debar from philosophy all those who were not likely to have an opportunity of taking an active part in affairs.^ It is Plato, of all the Greeks the most enthusiastically possessed by the idea of Greek civilisation as an influence to be propagated in the world, — it is Plato, with his firm practical hold of the belief that Life is worth living, — who stands out, in the His- tory of Philosophy, as the opponent of individualism, whether hedonistic or pessimistic. The individualists of his day, the Sophists, whom he opposes expressly or by implication through- out the whole range of his writings, were men for the most part without close political ties, aliens in the cities where they taught, who cultivated philosophy without patriotism and religion. It was from them that the doctrine ού φύσβι τα Βίκαία, άλλα νόμω μόνον came — a doctrine which answers to the view combated by the Cambridge Platonists, that Eight and Wrong, True and False, are creatures of God's arbitrary Will. If this is true, the " virtuously happy, or holy, life " is not worth pursuing ; chance is lord of all, and strenuous effort on our part is labour lost. This was how the Cambridge Platonists argued. In our own day. Pessimism is most often disappointed Hedonism. But it may well come from any cause which damps the energies of men : thus, the doctrine of Determinism may produce it by persuading us that our actions are all determined beforehand by the ειμαρμένη of the Uni- verse, and that we are but the passive spectators even of our own actions. Without denying that ειμαρμένη, in the sense of law universal, determines our actions, I would submit that the doctrine is too abstract to be of practical consequence. It takes us back to the axioma maxime generale — the Universe — ^and omits the immediate antecedent — the concrete character of the individual who performs the actions. It is this im- * Republic, 473 d. 508 THE MYTHS OF PLATO mediate antecedent, however, which one who wishes to take a scientific view of the actions must chiefly consider — the Uni- verse, or chain of remote antecedents, may "go without saying " ; and, above all, it is this immediate antecedent on which the agent himself must fix his attention ; he must " look to himself" as the phrase is, not to " the Universe," if he is to do anything worth doing. The abstract doctrine of Deter- minism, by calling attention away too much from the im- mediate antecedent of actions — the concrete agent himself — is at once unscientific and practically harmful, tending to paralyse the energy of the agent whose actions it seeks to account for. The agent must " believe in himself " if actions are to be done ; and he cannot believe in himself unless he believes in a system of things which is suitable to him, in which he can get on — a friendly, not an alien world. These two beliefs go together — belief in Self, and belief in a Friendly World. They are the two faces of the same coin. And this is the great truth signified by the doctrine of Reflection — κίνησις κνκλίκη — set forth by the Cambridge Platonists — their doc- trine that the Soul's reflection upon herself reveals to her that system of Eternal Truths which are at once the principles of human knowledge and conduct, and the Thoughts of God in accordance with which his Will is determined to do every- thing for the Best. The only sovereign antidote against Pessimism is a belief (tacit, or expressed — better, perhaps, tacit) of this sort. But such belief, it must be remembered, rests not on speculative grounds, but is the birth of conduct. It is the possession of those only who are airovhatoL — in earnest about the practical life. The issue between " Mechanism " and " Teleology " — for that, again, is the issue involved in the ques- tion about the relation of God's " Will " to his " Wisdom and Goodness " — is not one to be settled by logical thinkers, but by moral agents. Logical thinkers, it seems to me, must decide in favour of " Mechanism " ; moral agents will always decide in favour of "Teleology." And they are right, because " Teleology " is the working hypothesis of Life, whereas the doctrine of " Mechanism " damps the vis viva on which Life, including the logical understanding itself, depends for its con- tinuance. The central doctrine of the Cambridge Platonists receives THE CAMBEIDGE PLATONISTS 509 considerable illumination from their treatment of the famous maxim, identified chiefly with the name of Descartes, " Clear and distinct ideas must be true." The maxim, of course, can be traced back to Plato himself, who, at the end of the Sixth Book of the Eepublic, makes σαφήνεια the test of άΧήθεία. It is a maxim which undoubtedly lends itself to abuse, if not limited, as it is carefully limited by Plato in the passage just mentioned, as referring only to "ideas" in the sense of "categories" or "notions" — organic conditions of experience — and not also to " ideas " in the more ordinary sense — of "impressions," or data of experience. Kant's final proof of the apriority of his Categories of the Understanding is that " we cannot think them away " — their opposites are inconceiv- able — they belong to the structure of the mind — are not data received by it. Similarly, the Cambridge Platonists accept as principles of knowledge and conduct those Ideas which the κίνη- σις κυκλική, or Eeflection of the Soul upon herself as mirror of the Divine Wisdom, sees clearly and distinctly. Such are the " relative ideas " (as More calls them), Cause and Effect, Whole and Part, etc., and the Ideas of God and of Immor- tality. The truth of such " Ideas " is simply " their clear in- telligibility." Their truth needs no other witness. It is in order to maintain this view of the self-evident truth of these " Ideas " or " Categories " that Cudworth submits to a search- ing criticism Descartes' doctrine, that we fall back upon the supposition of the " Veracity of God " as ground of our belief that our clear and distinct ideas do not deceive us. Against this doctrine he argues that not even God could make clear and distinct " Ideas," in the sense of νοήματα, Categories, or principles of knowledge, false : they are essentially true ; and their clear intelligibility is alone sufficient warrant of their truth, or objective validity. Our very " Idea " of a Perfect, and therefore Veracious, God is itself one of these νοήματα, the truth of which is warranted by their " clear intelligibility." The passage ^ in which Cudworth makes this point against Descartes is, indeed, a notable passage in the History of the " Theory of Knowledge," and merits close comparison with Kant's Transcendental Analytic : — 1 IrUell, System, iii. 31-35. 510 THE MYTHS OF PLATO It hath been asserted by a late eminent philosopher that there is no possible certainty to be had of anything, before we be certain of the existence of a God essentially good ; because we can never otherwise free our minds from the importunity of that suspicion which with irresistible force may assault them ; that ourselves might possibly be so made, either by chance or fate, or by the pleasure of some evil demon, or at least of an arbitrary omnipo- tent Deity, as that Λve should be deceived in all our most clear and evident perceptions, and, therefore, in geometrical theorems themselves, and even in our common notions. But when we are once assured of the existence of such a God as is essentially good, — who, therefore, neither will nor can deceive, — then, and not before, will this suspicion utterly vanish, and ourselves become certain that our faculties of reason and understanding are not false and imposturous, but rightly made. . . . Now, though there be a plausibility of piety in this doctrine . . . yet does that very supposition that our understanding faculties might possibly be so made as to deceive us in all our clearest perceptions, render it utterly impossible ever to arrive to any certainty concerning the existence of a God essentially good ; forasmuch as this cannot be any otherwise proved than by the use of our faculties of under- standing, reason, and discourse. For to say that the truth of our understanding faculties is put out of all doubt and question as soon as ever we are assured of the existence of a God essentially good, who therefore cannot deceive ; whilst the existence of a God is in the meantime itself no otherwise proved than by our under- standing faculties ; that is at once to prove the truth of God's existence from our faculties of reason and understanding, and again to prove the truth of those faculties from the existence of a God essentially good : this, I say, is plainly to move round in a circle, and to prove nothing at all . . . so that if we will pretend to any certainty at all concerning the existence of a God, we must of necessity explode this new-supplied hypothesis of the possibility of our understandings being so made as to deceive us in all our clearest perceptions. ... In the first place, therefore, we affirm that no power, how great soever, and therefore not omnipotence itself, can make anything to be indifferently either true or false. . . . Truth is not factitious ; it is a thing which cannot be arbi- trarily made^ but is. The divine will and omnipotence itself hath no imperium upon the divine understanding ; for if God under- stood only by will, he could not understand at all. In the next place, we add that, though the truth of singular contingent pro- positions depends upon the things themselves existing without, as the measure and archetype thereof, yet as to the universal and abstract theorems of science, the terms whereof are those reasons of things which exist nowhere but only in the mind itself (whose THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 611 noemata and ideas they are), the measure and rule of truth con- cerning them can be no foreign or extraneous thing without the mind, but must be native and domestic to it, or contained within the mind itself, and therefore can be nothing but its clear and dis- tinct perception. In these intelligible ideas of the mind whatsoever is clearly perceived to be is ; or, which is all one, is true. . . . The very essence of truth here is this clear perceptibility, or in- telligibility. . . . The upshot of all this is, that since no power, how great soever, can make anything indifferently to be true, and since the essence of truth in universal abstract things is nothing but clear perceptibility, it follows that omnipotence cannot make anything that is false to be clearly perceived to be, or create such minds and understanding faculties as shall have as clear concep- tion of falsehoods — that is, of nonentities — as they have of truths or entities. For example, no rational understanding being that knows what a part is, and what a whole, what a cause, and what an effect, could possibly be so made as clearly to conceive the part to be greater than the whole, or the effect to be before the cause, or the like. . . . Conception and knowledge are hereby made to be the measure of all power, even omnipotence or infinite power being determined thereby ; from whence it follows that power hath no dominion over understanding, truth, and knowledge.^ We see, then, that the Epistemology of the Cambridge Platonists involves a Theory of God, according to which the Divine Will is subordinate to the Divine Wisdom and Goodness. A God merely all-powerful would be one of whom, and of whose world, knowledge would be impossible. We have a " clear and distinct idea " of a wise and good God, and in the light of this " idea " see the truth and do the right. This Platonic doctrine seems to me to contain all that is important in Kant's doctrine of the regulative value of the Idea of God. The Idea of God, Kant tells us, has no object in a possible experience. It lies deeper in human nature than the scientific understanding. Together with the Idea of Soul and the Idea of Cosmos, it has its seat in Keason ; which ^ Compare Spinoza, Eth. ii. 43. schol. : "Veram habere ideam nihil aliud significat quam perfecte sive optime rem cognoscere ; nee sane aliquis de hac re dubitare potest, nisi putet, ideam quid mutum instar picturae in tabula, et iion modum cogitandi esse, nempe ipsum intelligere . . . quid idea vera clarius et certius dari potest quod norma sit veritatis. Sane sicut lux se ipsam et teuebras manifestat, sic Veritas norma sui et falsi est." And again {de Intellectus Emen• datione, vi. § 33) : '* Modus quo sentimus essentiam formalem est ipsa certitudo. Unde patet quod ad certitudinem veritatis nullo alio signo sit opus quam verani habere ideam." And {o.c. ix. §#1): "Forma verae cogitationis in eadem ipsa cogitatione sine relatione ad alias debet esse sita ; nee obj actum tanquam causam agnoscit, sed ab ipsa intellectus potentia et natura pendere debet." 512 THE MYTHS OF PLATO must not be regarded as a " faculty " co-ordinate with other " faculties," but as the whole man — the indivisible organism in which " faculties " inhere. The Idea of God, then, having its seat in Keason, is an attitude of the whole man. An " Idea " which has no object in a possible experience, if expressed in language at all, must be expressed in figurative language ; so, I need not apologise for using a figure here to help me, and least of all for using the figure of Light, on which " the Platonists do wonderfully refine, and soar very high." The " Idea of God " is like the influence of Light, which draws living creatures out of the prison of darkness into the freedom of its borders. It is not a particular impression, nor yet one of the Categories in which impressions are received, but the Good Hope which urges on the living creature to go forth and meet the impressions of experience and organise his life in the world which they constitute. It is in feeling the stimulus of this Good Hope that man feels the obligation of the " Categorical Imperative." When I say that the doctrine of the " Categorical Imperative" is deeply embedded in the philosophy of the Cambridge Platonists, I am not trying to get them credit for great originality in their anticipation of a doctrine which has been too much identified with the name of Kant. Every system of Ethics, worthy to be called a system at all, takes us down to the bed-rock of the " Categorical Imperative." But what I do wish to claim for the Cambridge Platonists is that they lay the bed-rock very bare. The first original obHgation (says Cudworth) ^ is not from will, but nature. Did obHgation to the things of natural justice, as many suppose, arise from the will and positive command of God, only by reason of punishments threatened and rewards promised, the consequence of this would be that no man was good and just but only by accident, and for the sake of something else ; whereas the goodness of justice or righteousness is intrinsical to the thing itself, and this is that which obligeth (and not any- thing foreign to it), it being a different species of good from that of appetite or private utility, which every man may dispense withal. Again, in Smith's Discourse of Legal Righteousness and of the Righteousness of Faith, the Gospel, as distinguished from ^ Intell. System, iii. 512. THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 513 the Law, is presented as involving the obligation of a " Cate- gorical Imperative " : — The Righteousness of the Gospel transcends that of the Law in that it hath indeed a true command over the inward man, which it acts and informs ; whereas the Law by its menaces and punish- ments could only compel men to an external observance of it in tL• outward man ; as the Schoolmen have well observed, Lex joetus ligat manum. Lex nova ligat animum. Again, Maxwell,^ criticising the view which he ascribes (erroneously) to Cumberland, that the obligation of the Law of Nature is not in itself, but' in its external sanction, says : — Although Sin and Punishment are closely connected, yet the obligation of it may not he done (non licet) is distinct from the obligation of not with impunity {non impune), as Sin and Punishment are of distinct consideration. But a man is bound, both when he cannot do a thing without sin, and when he cannot do a thing without punishment. But because the obligation of non licet is ante- cedent to the obligation of non impune, the Precept to the Sanction, and the Sin is made by the Law, the Law hath so much obligation as to make the Sin, before the Penalty is enacted ; therefore the Law has an obligation antecedently to the Sanction of it. Maxwell's view of Cumberland — that he leaves the Law of Nature with no obligation save that derived from self- interest — I consider entirely mistaken ; Cumberland is really at one with Maxwell and the whole Platonist school in holding that the moral agent, the subject of obligation, is conscious of obligation in being conscious of the identity of the Law of Righteousness in himself with the Law which rules the Divine Nature. The moral agent is obliged, not because God arbi- trarily commands him, and will punish disobedience, but because he is conscious of a Law so august that even God is ruled by it. In Kant this consciousness which the moral agent has of God ruled by the Law of Righteousness is attenuated down to a consciousness of the " universality " of the Law. Thus the English statement of the doctrine of " obliga- tion " enables us to see the theological basis concealed under Kant's superstructure ; but, at the same time, shows us how ^ In his edition of Cumberland's Laws of Nature, Appendix, p. 56 (1727). 2l 614 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Kant may be successfully defended against the criticism of which Schopenhauer's attack, in the Grundlage der Moral} may be taken as a specimen — the criticism which urges that the Imperative is, after all, not " categorical," but " hypothetical " — has an external sanction, the penalty which attaches to disobeying God's command. The Platonic doctrine of the relation between the Divine Will and the Divine Wisdom and Goodness, and of man's participation in the mundus archetyjpus constituted by that Wisdom and Goodness — the doctrine of the "presence of the Eternal Consciousness in man's consciousness " — explains and justifies Kant's use of the epithet " categorical," and turns the edge of Schopenhauer's criticism, which proceeds on the assumption that the Deity, who undoubtedly stands behind the Kantian moral Imperative, is effective as mere Power threatening punishment, not rather as Wisdom-and-Goodness drawing the minds and hearts of all men unto it. In an amusing passage,^ Schopenhauer compares Kant to a man who dances the whole evening, at a ball, with a masked lady, who turns out, in the end, to be his own wife. That lady is Theology. But Schopenhauer takes for granted that she is the juridical theology modelled after the Koman Civil Law ; whereas, if we compare Kant with his next of kin, the English Platonists, we see that his masked theology is the theology of Platonism — a theology as different from the other as the Hellenic genius is different from the Eoman. I submit that the " Categorical Imperative " is best understood in close connection with the Greek moral notions of the ayaOov and the κ,άΧόν. Moral obligation is not essentially pressure brought to bear on the unwilling, but is rather the nisus of a nature eagerly seeking its appointed place In the Cosmos, and, in its efforts, experiencing, by anti- cipation, the joy of success. Virtue grows up like a flower to the light, joyfully realising its own nature as part of universal nature. This is, indeed, the way in which Maxwell wishes us to understand " obligation " — not juridically, but, if I may foist the term on him, liologically. Having quoted Shaftesbury at length, as holding the doctrine of the intrinsic obligation of the Law of Virtue — " That the excellence of the Object, not the Keward or Punishment, should be our motive," — he states his 1 Pages 120 if. ^ o.c. p. 169. THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 615 own view thus : ^ " The Good in Morality, the Good of Virtue, is the καλόν καΐ αηαθον, the Beauteous-Beneficial Life and Practice." This Greek standard he afterwards explains, in a way which reminds one of Kant, as " impartiality between man and man." " We should do all things," he says,^ " no otherwise than as if Justice itself did them." Maxwell's criticism of Cumberland — that he makes the ultimate motive the self-interest secured by obedience to the Law of Nature — is, as I have said, mistaken ; but it is interesting on account of its similarity to the criticism which Schopenhauer brings against Kant. Both critics are, I think, misled by the sup- position that their respective authors are juridical and not Platonist theologians. That juridical theology inliuenced both Cumberland and Kant is, of course, indisputable ; but it is a grave error, on the part of the critics, to mistake an influence, which made itself felt in the details of the superstructure, for the theological foundation of the building. We may grant to Schopenhauer that theology stands masked behind Kant's doctrine of the Categorical Imperative. But our study of the English Intellectualists — Kant's next of kin — enables us to recognise that theology as the Platonist theology of the com- munion of man's mind with God's mind rather than that of obedience to God as a superior who issues commands armed with sanctions — the theology of the Freedom of the Gospel, as Smith puts it, rather than that of the Bondage of the Law. I think I have now said enough to explain the central doctrine of Cudworth and his school in its relationship to the " mythology " of Plato on the one side and to the " formalism " of Kant and of T. H. Green on the other side. Let me add the observation that Cudworth and his school can hai'dly be said to make the Theory of Morals an independent subject. They make it merely an illustration of their Theory of Know- ledge. Moral good is simply an intelligihile, on the same footing as the other Iheai, or Eternal Keasons, required by the epistemology of the school. Cudworth's Eternal and Immutable Morality has much more to say about mathematical Truth than about Eight and Wrong. " Obligation " is treated merely as a • 1 Maxwell's Obligation of the Law of Nature, p. 68 (Appendix to his edition of Cumberland). ^ o.c. p. 85. 516 THE MYTHS OF PLATO case of " clear intelligibility," and the perception of it assimi- lated to the self-evidence of mathematical principles. Duty is clearly perceived by Keflection, just as Triangularity is. This characteristic of the System of Cudworth and his associates — that their Theory of Morals is but a corollary — and is carefully kept in the subordinate position of a mere corollary — of the Theory of Knowledge, is also a characteristic of the English System which, in our own day, represents that of the Cam- bridge Platonists. T. H. Green's Moral Theory is closely bound up with, and indeed, except so far as " contaminated " by utilitarianism, identical with, his epistemology — an epistem- ology which, as I have tried to indicate, has close affinity with that of Cudworth and his associates, inasmuch as it includes, as theirs does, a proof of the existence of God — is theology, or epistemology, indifferently. Green's Prolegomena and Cud- worth's Eternal and Imniutable Morality are books which should be read in connection ; and, in reading them together, let the reader take as his guide the thought that the theology of Green, as well as that of Cudworth, is ecstatic, not juridical. The critic's problem in interpreting the Philosophy of Green is that of interpreting a product of the Eenaissance — of the revival of Christian Platonism — I had almost said a late-born product of the Eenaissance ; but the Eenaissance, after all, is not circumscribed by dates — it is always with us as a reno- vating principle, as a vivid spirit craving for the freedom of personal experience. Platonism is a temper as well as a doctrine ; and in Cudworth and his associates, as in their Alexandrine pre- decessors, it is even more a temper than a doctrine — an enthusiastic mystical temper, always longing passionately for intuition, always ready to accept the clearness of passionate intuition as Standard of Truth in Divine Things: "Nature itself plainly intimates to us," says Cudworth,^ that there is some such absolutely perfect Being, which, though not incon- ceivable, yet is incomprehensible to our finite understandings, by certain passions which it hath implanted in us, that otherwise would want an object to display themselves upon ; namely, those of devout veneration, adoration, and admiration, together with a kind of ecstasy and pleasing horror ; which, ^ Intell. System, ii. p. 519. THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 517 in the silent language of nature, seem to speak thus much to us that there is some object in the world, so much bigger and vaster than our mind and thoughts, that it is the very same to them that the ocean is to narrow vessels ; so that when they have taken into themselves as much as they can by con- templation, and filled up all their capacity^ there is still an immensity of it left without which cannot enter in for want of room to receive it, and therefore must be apprehended after some other strange and more mysterious manner, namely, by their being, as it were, plunged into it, and swallowed up or lost in it." Similarly, More appeals ^ to the natural remorse of conscience, to good hope, and to reverence and worship, as proofs of the existence of God ; presenting the faculty of " Divine Sagacity " — the birth of a " Holy Life " — as " ante- cedaneous to Eeason " — άττλωσον σβαντόν, simplify thyself, he says,^ and walk by the " easie Sagacity," " the simple light of the Divine Love " ; while Norris lays it down ^ that " the mind which sees the Divine Essence must be totally and thoroughly absolved from all commerce with the corporeal senses, either by Death, or some ecstatical and rapturous abstraction " ; and Smith rests his belief in God and Immor- tality far more on the certitude of the Heart than of the Head. To these devout Platonists God and Immortality are simply ivants — wants of the practical volitional part of us, for the sake of which, after all, the thinking part thinks. A God fashioned logically, in such a way as to satisfy the think- ing part alone — that is, fashioned by the thinking part making its own satisfaction its end — will be a God who does not satisfy the volitional part, and consequently cannot, in the long run, be maintained. We have much to learn from the Platonists who, by laying stress on the mere want of a God, suggest that the logical faculty ought not to be allowed to have the last word in theology.^ That Platonism is a temper is brought home to us by nothing in the History of Philosophy more clearly than by the development of Berkeley's mind. His early thought ^ Antidote against Atheism, book i. ch. 10. p. 29. 2 Defence of the Moral Cabbala^ ch. 1, p. 3 55. ^ Reason and Religion, p. 3. * '^ I would refer, in this connection, to a remarkable Essay on "Reflex Action and Theism," by Professor W. James, in his volume, The Will to Believe. 518 THE MYTHS OF PLATO moved on lines laid down by Locke. In the New Theory of Vision (1709) and Principles of Human Knowledge (1710), works of his early manhood, he appears as the mid-link between Locke and Hume in the sensationalistic succession. His interest, at this period, is mainly scientific, although there is a theological reference even in this early work which distinguishes it from the work of either Locke or Hume. Experience, though interpreted according to the principles of the Lockian Critique, is yet " the Language of God " — Male- branche's doctrine of " seeing all things in God " doubtless influences him. In The New Theory and The Principles Berkeley may be said to adopt sensationalistic doctrine en Platonicien. But see how this Platonist temper, showing itself even in works written chiefly under the influence of Locke, hurries the man away from science into action, rouses him into sympathy — always, be it noted, practical and statesmanlike — with the miseries of the Irish people, carries him across the Atlantic on his enthusiastic mission to found a college which should be the centre of evangelical work among the American aborigines. The scheme failed ; he returned, disappointed, but not disillusioned, to devote the remainder of his life to the advocacy of philanthropic schemes — and to write that wonderful Siris, a Chain of Philosophical Reflections and Inquiries concerning the Virtues of Tar-water, in which the practical Platonism of his nature, pent up, as age and a fatal disorder condemned him to greater retirement, found natural relief in dogmatic expression. It is in Siris that Berkeley appears as the latest adherent of the school of Cud- worth and More But what, it may be well asked, is the connection between Tar-water (which Berkeley recommends as a panacea) and Platonism ? The answer is, that tar, the exuda- tion of the pine, is the purest vehicle of that " invisible fire or Spirit of the universe " by the agency of which all things live : the introduction of an additional amount of this vital cosmic principle into the human system by means of a decoction of tar has the effect of heightening the bodily powers and expelling all diseases. That there is such a vital principle of the Universe is shown to be the only hypothesis consistent with that Platonism which — to adopt More's phrase with a slight alteration — is " the soul of the Philosophy of which * modern science ' is the body." THE CAMBKIDGE PLATONISTS 519 Let me close this work with two quotations from Siris — eloquent utterances of the Platonist temper : — It might very well be thought serious trifling to tell my readers, that the greatest men had ever a high esteem for Plato ; whose writings are the touchstone of a hasty and shallow mind ; whose philosophy has been the admiration of ages ; which supplied patriots, magistrates, and law-givers, to the most flourish- ing states, as well as fathers to the Church, and doctors to the schools. Albeit in these days, the depths of that old learning are rarely fathomed, and yet it were happy for these lands, if our young nobility and gentry, instead of modern maxims, would imbibe the notions of the great men of antiquity. ... It may be modestly presumed there are not many among us, even of those who are called the better sort, who have more sense, virtue, and love of their country than Cicero, who, in a letter to Atticus, could not forbear exclaiming, Socrates et Socratici viri I nunquam vobis gratiam referam. Would to God many of our countrymen had the same obligations to those Socratic writers ! Certainly where the people are well educated, the art of piloting a state is best learnt from the writings of Plato. . . . Proclus, in the first book of his commentary on the Theology of Plato, observes that, as in the mysteries, those who are initiated, at first meet with manifold and multiform gods, but being entered and thoroughly initiated, they receive the divine illumination, and participate in the very Deity ; in like manner, if the Soul looks abroad, she beholds the shadows and images of things ; but returning into herself she unravels and beholds her own essence : at first she seemeth only to behold herself, but having penetrated further she discovers the mind. And again, still further advancing into the innermost Sanctuary of the Soul she contemplates the O^dv ykvos. And this, he saith, is the most excellent of all human acts, in the silence and repose of the faculties of the Soul to tend upwards to the very Divinity ; to approach and be clearly joined with that which is ineff'able and superior to all beings. When come so high as the first principle she ends her journey and rests.^ * •5ί• -X- -Jt -X- * Whatever the world thinks, he who hath not much meditated upon God, the Human Mind, and the Summum Bonum, may possibly make a thriving earthworm, but will most indubitably make a sorry patriot and a sorry statesman.^ 1 Siris, §§ 332, 333. « o.c. § 350. INDEX Adam, Mr., on Plato's attitude to doctrine of Immortality of the Soul, 71 on circle of the Same and the Other, 143 on the position of the Throne of Άvάyκη in the Myth of Er, 166, 167 on the Pillar of Light in the Myth of Er, 169 on the astronomy of the Politicus Myth, and the Great Year, 198 on άωροι, 200 on allegorisation of Homer, 233 on the φύλακ€$ of the Republic and the Hesiodic Daemons, 436 Adam Smith, Dr. G,, on allegorical inter- pretation, 236, 237 Aeschylus, attitude of, to doctrine of Immortality of the Soul, 63, 64 Aesop's Fables, at once African Beast- tales and Parables, 16 Agyrtae, 70 Αίθ-ήρ, in Epinomis, de Oodo, Meteorol., 438, 439 Albertus, on the Earthly Paradise, 105 Alfraganus, Dante's use of, 365 Allegorical interpretation. Dr. G. Adam Smith on, 236, 237 Dr. Bigg on, 236 Hatch on, 236 of Myths, by Plotinus and Neo-Plato- nists, 237 if. St. Paul authorises, 237 Chrysostom's opinion of, 237 of Myths, Plato's judgment on, 20, 242 of Myths, Grote on, 232, 234, 243 Neo-Platonic, Zeller's opinion of, 242 Dante's, 244 Allegorical tales deliberately made, 16 -...—Allegorisation of Homer, 231 ff. by the Stoics, 233, 234 Plutarch on, 231, 232 by Stoics, Cicero on, 233 Mr. Adam on, 233 • Allegorisation of Old Testament, Philo's, 234 flf. by Christian Fathers, 236, 237 Allegory of Castle of Medina, Spenser's, 257 in Purgaiorio, xxix., 257 of the Cave, Plato's, 250 ff. of the Disorderly Crew, Plato's, 253 ff. ^Ανάβασις, takes the place of κατάβασι$ in eschatology, 352, 353, 367 Stoical doctrine of the levity of the Soul contributed to, 380 Άνάμνησι$, doctrine of, 343 ff. Άνάμνησκ, ^ρω$, φιλοσοφία, 341 ff. Ανάμνηση, Platonic, Dieterich on, 158 compared with Dante's mythology of Lethe and Eunoe, 158 Angels, Jewish doctrine of, and Greek doctrine of Daemons, 450 Apocalypse of Paul, Dr. M. E. James on, 364 Apocalypse, the astronomical, 361 ff. relation of, to Sacramental Cults, 365-8 Apuleius^ his interpretation of the Ulysses Myth, 241, 242 demonology of, 445 ff. Aquinas, St. Thomas, on the Earthly Paradise, 104 Archer-Hind, Mr., his Timaeus quoted, 269 Aristippus, Henricus, translated Phaedo and Meno in 1156, 102 Aristotle and Eudemus echo Timaeus, 90 c, 295 Aristotle, misapprehends the Timaeus, 269 his God, 355 poetised astronomy, 163, 164 his poetised astronomy, influence of, on Dante, 163, 164 his supposed tomb near Chalcis, 153 Plato's καλλίτΓολα misunderstood by, 58 gives up ideas of a Personal God and of Personal Immortality of the Soul, 53 Aristotelian astronomy, 354 Astronomy, part played by, in Poetry, 163 521 2 L 2 622 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Atlantis Myth and maritime discovery, 468 Axiochus, the, date and characteristics of, 110 places the world of the departed in the southern hemisphere of the earth, 110 singular in its localisation of the ireUov αληθείας, 358 Bacon, his allegorical interpretation of Myths, 242 his definition of Poetry, 387 Bacon, Koger, on the Earthly Paradise, 105 Berkeley, his Siris characterised and quoted, 518, 519 as Platonist, 517 S. Bernard, his translation of Kant's Kritik d. Urtheilskraft quoted, 222 flP. Bigg, Dr., on allegorisation of Homer by the Stoics, 233 on allegorical interpretation, 236 on Myth of Cupid and Psyche, 245 Boeckh, referred to for Plato's astronomy, 354 Book of the Dead, 130 Bosanquet, Prof. B., on " present " as " ex- tended time," 56 Bran, The Voyage of, referred to for connection between notions of metem- psychosis, metamorphosis, and preg- nancy without male intervention, 304 Brownell, C. L., quoted for Japanese story of origin of tea, 14 Brimetto Latini, on the infernal rivers, 103 Buddhism, attitude of, to belief in Im- mortality, 301 Budge, Dr. , on Book of the Dead, &Q on a prehistoric form of burial in Egypt, 378 Bunbury, on the geography of the Atlantis Myth, 466 fiF. Bunyan's Pilgrim's Progress, an allegory and also a myth, 16, 246 Burnet, Prof., on the σφόνδυλοί of the orrery in Myth of Er, 165 referred to on Plato's astronomy, 354 on the Poem of Parmenides, 351 on the monsters and " organic com- binations " of Empedocles, 409 Bury, Prof., on spread of Orphic cult, 66 Butcher, Prof., his Aristotle's Theory of Poetry and Fine Art referred to, 391 Butler, on Necessity and Freedom, 172 Bywater, Prof. , on the Epinomis, 439 Caird, Dr. E., on Kant's Ideas of Keason, quoted, 48 Callaway, Nursery Tales of the Zulus, quoted, 8-10 Callaway, on one-legged people ; cf. Myth told by Aristophanes in Symposium, 408 -- 475 flf. influenced in two directions, by Philo and by Plotinus respectively, 479 ff. maintain that Moses taught the motion of the Earth, 478, 489 their enthusiasm for the new astronomy, 486 fiF. their science, 486 ff. their central doctrine, the Doctrine of Ideas as theory of union of man with God in knowledge and conduct, 494, 495 go back to Plato the mythologist rather than to Plato the dialectician, 494 their epistemology, 502 their epistemology, derived from the doctrine οϋδέαι "mythologically" set forth, explains their theory of Reason as Moral Faculty, 503 ff. their discussion of the relation of God's " Will" to his "Wisdom and Good- ness," 505 ff. their doctrine of Categorical Imperative, 512 ff. enable us to connect the " formalism " of Kant and Green with the " myth- ology" of the Phaedrus and Sym- posium, 515 Campbell, Prof., on Protagoras Myth, 221 Cams, his Gesch. d. Zoologie referred to, 17 Catastrophes, doctrine of, in Plato and the Peripatetics, 196 Categorical Imperative, doctrine of, in ■ Cambridge Platonists, 512 ff. Kant's doctrine of, criticised by Schopenhauer, 514 Categories of the Understanding and Moral Virtues, Plato's mythological "deduction" of, 50 Categories of the Understanding, mytho- logical deduction of, 337 ff. the Forms seen in the Super-celestial Place explained as, 339 ff. Cave, Plato's Allegory of, 250 ff. an allegory and also a myth, 16 its meaning, 56 Schwanitz on, 252 Couturat on, 252 Cebetis Tabula, 245 Chalcidius, translated the Timaeus, 102 quoted on Daemons, 436 his version of the Timaeus, how far used by Dante, 468 Charles, Prof. R. H., his editions of Secrets of Enoch and Ascension of Isaiah, referred to, 361, 362 Choice of Hercules, 2, 245 INDEX 523 Church, Dean, on The Letter to Kan Grande, 18 Cicero, eschatology of his Somnium Scipionis and Tusc. Disp., 353 Circe and Calypso Myths, Neo-Platonic interpretation of, 240 if. Claudian, on the Earthly Paradise, 105 "Clear and Distinct Ideas," 509 Clough, quoted to illustrate doctrine of κόλασι$ and κάθαρσί$ in Gorgias, 126 Coelo, de, influence of, in the Paradiso, 353 Coleridge, on " poetic faith, " 6 on deep sky akin to feeling, 22 quoted for the statement that a poem ought not to be all poetry, 34 on Plato's doctrine of the pre-existence of the Soul, 61 on Wordsworth's Ode on Intimations of Immortality, 61 his Anima Poetae quoted, 258 on Dante's Canzone xx., 258 regards the Platonic doctrine of Pre- existence as mythical, 344 holds that Poetry may exist without metre, 389, 390 Comparetti, on gold tablets of Thurii and Petelia, 130, 156 on the KaZeicala, 204 Conscience, Cardinal Newman on, as con- necting principle between creature and Creator, 447 Guardian Daemon as, 447, 448 Conybeare, Mr., his PMlo, de Vita Con- templativa, referred to, 234 Cook, Mr. A. B., on the Sicilian triskeles, and the Myth told by Aristophanes in Symposium, 408 Cornford, Mr. F. M., on the φΰΚακΐ^ of the Republic and the Hesiodic Daemons, 436 Courthope, Mr., his definition of Poetry quoted, 36 Couturat, on doctrine of Immortality of the Soul as held by Plato, 61, 70 Timaeus totus mythicus est, 197 on the Cave, 252 holds that the whole doctrine of lUat is mythical, 348 Cratylus, the, on the Philosopher Death, 127, 128 on the Sirens, 128 CTQVLZQT,Plotinus de Pulchritudine, quoted, 240, 241 Cud worth, his criticism of Descartes com- pared with criticism of the same tendency in Prof. Ward's Naturalism and Agnosticism, 477, 478 • conceives God spatially, 487 supplies the link between the epistemo- logical theism of Green and the mythology of the Timaexts and Phaedrus, 498 Cudworth, his criticism of the sensational- ism of Hobbes, 497, 498 his criticism of Descartes, 509 fl". Cultus Myth, a variety of the Aetiological Story, illustrated, 13 Cumberland, criticised by Maxwell, 513 ff. Cumont, his Mysteres de Mithra, 365 his criticism of Dieterich's Mithras- liturgie, 365 Cupid and Psyche, Myth of, Mr. A. Lang on, 245 Dr. Bigg on, 245 Daemon, Guardian, doctrine of, connected with belief in re-incarnation of Souls of ancestors, 449, 450 as Conscience, 447, 448 Daemon, the, of Socrates, 445, 448 ; cf. 2, 3 Daemons, doctrine of, 434 ff. two kinds of, recognised by Plato, 436 ff. Dante, Letter to Kan Grande, quoted for distinction between literal and alle- gorical truth, 18-19 Convivio, quoted for literal, allegoric, moral, and anagogic interpretation, 19-20 his *' personal religion," 19 expresses Transcendental Feeling in last canto of Par. and 25th sonnet of V. N., 23 F. N. sonnet 24, quoted for effect produced similar to that produced by Plato's Eschatological Myths, 26 F. iV. sonnet 11, quoted to illustrate the "magic" of certain kinds of Poetry, 38 Hell, Mount of Purgatory, and Earthly Paradise, compared with the Tartarus and True Surface of the Earth in the Phaedo, 101 ff. Quaestio de Aqua et Terra, 102 the tears of this world flow in the rivers of his Hell, 103 singular in locating Purgatory on the slopes of the Mountain of the Earthly Paradise, 104 Mount of Purgatory sighted by Ulysses, 104 his use of the teleological geography of Orosius, 105, 106 his mythological explanation of the distribution of plants, 106, 107 the human race created to make good the loss of the fallen angels, 106 "the seven P's," 130 the three parts ot his Ό. G. correspond to the "Three Ways," 132 Lethe and Eunoe, 154 ff. Earthly Paradise, 154 ff. 524 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Dante, his mythology of Lethe and Eunoe compared with the Platonic ανά- μνηση, 158 KadapaLS by gradual ascent of Mount of Purgatory takes the place of καθ- άρσια by metempsychosis, 159 appearance of Saints in the moving Spheres, 165 and the Timaeus, 210 his allegorisation of the story of the three Marys, 244 Inferno, iv. 46-43, and Plato's Cave, 253 Coleridge on, 258 "suppressed" symbolism in, 258 Procession in Purg. xxix. ff., 339 on relation of Philosophy to Science, 342 compares the Platonic ί5έαι to " Gods," 347 on the number of Beatrice, 350 Paradiso, latest example of the astro- nomical apocalypse, 353 Convivio, quoted for his astronomical system, 164, 355 if. on influence of Planets in producing temperaments, 358, 359 regards his vision of Paradiso as having sacramental value, 367 theory in the de MonarcMa compared with that of the Republic and Atlantis Myth, 454 his knowledge of the Timaeus through the version and commentary of Chalcidius, 468 Darwin, on the feebleness of imagination in the lower animals, 4 his Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals referred to, 342 Dead, Book of the, Egyptian, 66 Delphi, place assigned to, by the side of the Platonic State, 58 Descartes, criticised by Cambridge Pla- tonists, as ignoring the ' ' plastic principle," 478, 493 criticised by Cudworth, 478, 491, 493, 509 ff. Dialogue, the Platonic, two elements in — Argumentative Conversation and Myth, 1 Dieterich, on Orphic κατάβασίί eb Αΐδον, 66, 154 on refrigerium, 161 on Mithraic κλΐμαξ έπτάττυΧος, 162 his Mithrasliturgie referred to for influence of Posidonius, 352 his Mithrasliturgie, 365 ff. Dill, Professor, referred to for mixture of Science and Myth in Macrobius, 101 on Plutarch's allegorisation of Egyptian Myths, 232 Dill, Professor, quoted on Macrobius' Com- mentary on the Somnium Scipionis,Zl• 9 Disorderly Crew, Plato's Allegory of, 253 ff. Dramatists, the Athenian, their attitude to the doctrine of the Immortality of the Soul, 62 ff. take the Family, rather than the In- dividual, as the moral unit, 63 Dream-consciousness, induced by Poetry, - 382 ff. "Dream-thing," the, illustrated from Wordsworth's Prelude, 153 Dream-world, the, of the primitive story- teller characterised, 5 During, holds that the Phaedrus Myth is a " Programme," 338 Earth, rotundity of, recognised by Plato in Phaedo, 94 central position of, in Phaedo, 94 Earthly Paradise, the, 103 ff. of Dante and medieval belief, 104 ff. Dante's, 154 ff. Earthquake and thunder accompany new birth in Myth of Er and Dante, Purgatorio, xxi., 159 Ecstasy, Plotinus quoted on, 385 as understood by Cambridge Platonists, 480 ff. "Empirical" distinguished from "Tran- scendental" Feeling, 389 Enoch, Secrets of, referred to, 361 ff. Eothen, Kinglake's, quoted to illustrate allegory of Disorderly Crew, 254 tf. Epictetus on Guardian Daemon as Con- science, 448, 449 Epiraetheus, contrasted with Prometheus, 225 ff. Epinomis, demonology of, 445 Er, Myth of, place of, in the Republic, 64, 72, 73 great philosophical question raised in, 169 ff. Έύνοία% θβόί in Mithraic doctrine, 162 Evil, origin of, mythically explained in Politicus Myth, 197, 198 presence of, in Heaven, 367 Exeter Book, the, on the Earthly Paradise, 105 Expression, importance attached by Plato to, as reacting on that which is ex- pressed, 113 reaction of, on that which is expressed, 342 Eyes, the final cause of, 356 Fairbanks, Mr. Α., on cremation and άνάβασις, 379 Fall, the, of Souls as conceived by the Neo- Platonists, 360 Ficino, on the Narcissus Myth, 240 INDEX 525 Flinders Petrie, Prof., on Book of the Dead, 66 referred to for Book of the Bead, 130 Galton, Mr. F., on power of visualisation, 381 Gardner, Prof. P., on thiasi, 71 on the story of Zagreus, 409 on Prophecy, 431 on new epoch opened for Hellas by Alexander, 454 on Apocalypses, 455 Gebhart {Vltalie ^nystique), on Dante's "personal religion," 19 Gems, mythological theory of origin of, in Phaedo, 94, 95 Dante on origin of virtues of, 95 Geology of Attica in Atlantis Myth, 465 flf. Gfrorer {Urchristenthum), on Philo's al- legorical method, 234 if. Ghosts, H. More on, 96 Gildersleeve, Prof., on Pindar, 01. ii. 75, 68 Glaucon in Rep. 608 D, attitude of, to doctrine of Immortality of the Soul, 64 Goblet d'Alviella, on connection between Egyptian and Greek guide-books for the use of the dead, 66 on Initiation as Death and Ke- birth, 377 ff. God, a Personal, is a Part, not the Whole, 53 Goethe, quoted to illustrate the " magic " of certain kinds of Poetry, 37 Gollancz, his edition of the Exeter Book, 105 Good, the, not one of the objects of Knowledge, but its condition, 59, cf. 44 Gray, Sir George, his version of Maori story of Children of Heaven and Earth, quoted, 11-13 Green, T. H., his doctrine of "the Presence of the Eternal Consciousness in my Consciousness," its Platonic proven- ance, 486, 493 if. his Eternal Consciousness compared with the Ideal World of Cambridge Platonists, 501 his Philosophy a revival of Christian Platonism, 516 Grote, on the Cultus Myth, 13 on doctrine of Immortality of the Soul as held by Plato, 61 on thiasi, 71 on the general characteristics of the Politicus Myth, 196 • on the Protagoras Myth, 220 on allegorical interpretation, 243 on story of Zagreus, 409 Gummere, Prof., makes metrical form essential to Poetry, 391 Hades, Voyage of Odysseus to, of Orphic origin, 66 Harrison, Miss, on the Cultus Myth, 14 on the Sirens, 127 her Prolegomena to Study of Greek Religion referred to, 154 on Dante's Eunoe, 161 on story of Zagreus, 409 Hatch, on allegorical interpretation, 236 on Angels and Daemons, 450 Heavens, motion of, determines sublun- ary events, 196 motion of, in the Politicus Myth, and in the accepted astronomy, 198 Hegel, his view of the δαιμόνων of Socrates, 3 on doctrine of Immortality of the Soul as held by Plato, 61 on the Soul as Universal, 228 Helbig, on Prometheus sarcophagus in Capitol, 229 Heraclitus, his ξηρή ψυχή as understood by Neo-Platonists, 240, 360 Hesiod on the Five Ages, 434, 435 his Daemons, 434, 435 Hierocles, on bodies terrestrial, aerial, and astral, 439 History, relation of mythology to, accord- ing to Plato, 94 Hobbes, his Social Covenant a " founda- tion-myth," 171 his disproof of Spirit or Incorporeal Substance criticised by More, 492 his sensationalism criticised by Cud- worth, 497, 498 Holland, Philemon, his version of Plut- arch's Moralia, 369, 441 Ύπβρονράνως τόττο? of Phaedrus and the Aristotelian God compared, 355 Idealists, modern English, go back to Plato the mythologist rather than to Plato the dialectician, 494 their central doctrine that of the Cambridge Platonists — the Doctrine of Ideas as theory of union of Man with God in knowledge and conduct, 495 Ideas, Doctrine of, how far mythical? 347 fif. as adopted by Cambridge Platonists and modern English Idealists, 494 " Ideas of Reason," Soul, Cosmos, and God, set forth by Plato in Myth, not scientifically, 49 mythological representation of, 337 ff. Imagination, rather than Reason, dis- tinguishes man from brute, 4 part played by, in the development of human thought, 4-6 526 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Immisch referred to for medieval transla- tion of the Phaedo, 102 .Immortality of the Soul, attitude of Simonides, Tyrtaeus, Attic Orators, Dramatists, Aristotle, the Athenian Public, to doctrine of, 61 ff. Plato's doctrine of, according to Hegel, Zeller, Grote, Coleridge, Thiemann, Couturat, Jowett, Adam, 61, 62, 70, 71 personal, presented by Plato in Myth, 53 agnosticism regarding, in the Athens of Plato's day, 61 if. conceived by Plato eminently in Myth, 61, 73, 74 Plato's doctrine of, according to Jowett, 70 three sorts of, distinguished, 300 if. attitude of Buddhism to belief in, 301 "Imperial Hellas," ideal of, in Plato, 454 if. ideal of, how far it competes with that of Personal Salvation in Plato, 455, 456 Initiation, as ceremonial Death and Ee- birth, 368, 377, 378 Ion, Plato's, a study of " Poetic Inspira- tion," 382 Isaiah, Ascension of, referred to, 362 Islands of the Blessed, 107 if. in the Platonic Myths, 108, 109 in Greek and Celtic mythology, 108 in Oorgias, identical with "True Surface of the Earth" in Phaedo, and ''Heaven" in Myth of Er, 107-110 Jackson, Dr. H., on the δαιμόνων of Socrates, 3 James, Dr. M. R., on Apocalypse of Paul, 364 James, Prof. W., on teleology, 52 his Varieties of Religious Experience referred to, 480 his essay on "Reflex Action and Theism " referred to, 517 Jevons, Dr., on thiasi, 71 on the story of Zagreus, 409 Johnstone, Mr. P. de L., his Muliammad and his Power quoted, 363 Jowett, on Imagination and Reason, 4 on Plato's attitude to doctrine of Im- ^ mortality of the Soul, 70 on the general characteristics of the Politicus Myth, 196 Kaibel, on gold tablets found at Thurii and Petelia, 156 Kalewala, the, described, 203, 204 story of the Birth of Iron, in the, 204 flf. German version of, by H. Paul, 204 ΚαλλίτΓολυ, Plato's, not an isolated munici- pality, but an Empire-city, 58 Kant, his distinction between Categories of the Understanding and Ideas of Reason not explicit in Plato's mind, but sometimes implicitly recognised by him, 45 his distinction between Categories of the Understanding and Ideas of Reason explained, 45 if. in charging Plato with "transcendental use, or rather misuse, of the Categories of the Understanding," ignores the function of Myth in the Platonic philosophy, 72. his Critique of Judgment quoted, 222 ff. on distinction between the Teleological and the Mechanical explanations of the world, 222 flf. his theology that of the Platonist, 514 Kara^aais eh "Αώου, Dieterich on, 154 Rohde on, 154 Lobeck on, 252 the, eschatology of, 351 if. Καθάρσια, poetic, 393 King, Mr. J. E., on infant burial, 200, 450 Kingsley, Miss, on re-incarnation of souls of deceased relatives, 450 Knowledge, Theory of, common to Cam- bridge Platonists and modern English Idealists, 495 Ktihner, on the δαιμόνων of Socrates, 3 Land, Prof. J. P. N., on Physiologus, 17 Lang, Mr. Α., on Myth of Uranus and Cronus, 11 on Myth of Cupid and Psyche, 245 on savage analogies for Greek mysteries, 378 Leibniz, his "Pre-established Harmony" and " Prenatal Choice " in Myth of Er compared, 170 describes the doctrine of άνάμνησίί as mythical, 344 Lelewel, referred to for position of Earthly Paradise, 104 Lelut, on the δαιμόνων of Socrates, 3 Lethe, the River of, its locality discussed, 154 Thiemann on locality of, 154 not one of the infernal rivers, 154, 168 its locality in the Aeneid, 154, 155 and Mnemosyne in the Orphic cult, 156 if. topography of, in Myth of Er, and Petelia Tablet compared, 157 drinking of, precedes re - incarnation, 157 and Mnemosyne at Oracle of Trophonius, 160 Roscher on references to, 168 Liddell, Professor Mark H., makes metrical form essential to Poetry, 391, 392 INDEX 527 Lie, the, in the Soul, what ? 54 Lobeck, Aglaophamus on the ** Cycle of Incarnations," 156 on the allegorisation of Homer, 231 on story of Zagreus, 409 on re -incarnation of souls of deceased relatives, 450 Lotze, his distinction between the Reality of Existence and the Reality of Validity, appears in Norris, 500 Love song, the " magic "of, 37 Lucian on the Stoic "Steep Hill of Virtue," 104 Lucifer, the Fall of, how made use of by Dante, 106 Mackinder, Mr. H. J., on "Atlantis," 466 Macrobius, on the Bowl of Dionysus, 239 his Commentary on the Somnmm Scipionis compared with the Pliae- drus Myth, 360 on influence of Planets in producing temperaments, 359, 360 Madness, four kinds of, distiguished in Phaedrus, 306, 339 "Magic" of certain kinds of Poetry dis- cussed and illustrated, 36, 38 Mahomet, Vision of, quoted, 363 Malebranche, his doctrine of " seeing all all things in God " adopted by Norris, 501 Make-believe and Belief, 6, 7 Mann, Max Friedr., his Bestiaire Divin referred to, 17 Maoris, their Story of the Children of Heaven and Earth quoted, 11-13 Marcus Aurelius on the aerial habitat of souls, 437, 438 on Guardian Daemon as Conscience, 449 Masson, Professor, on Milton's De Idea Flatonicd, 348 Maximus Tyrius, demonology of, 447, 448 Maxwell, his criticism of Cumberland, 513 if. his theory of obligation, 514, 515 Meadow (λβιμών), the, of the Judgment- Seat, position of, 152 Mechanism and Teleology, 508 Metempsychosis, and Resurrection, 198 flF. not necessarily connected with notions of Retribution and Purification, 302 if. relation of, to metamorphosis, and to conception without male intervention, 302 if. MeteoTologica, geography of, 467 • Metre and Representation, the place of each in Poetry, 388 fF. Millennium, the, H. More on, 97 Millet's "Sower," 250 Milton, adheres to old astronomy in Paradise Lost, 163 his Poem De Idea, PlatonicA quemad- modum Aristoteles intellexit, quoted, 347 f. Mirror and Bowl of Dionysus, Neo-Platonic interpretation of, 239-40 Mitchell, Mrs., on Prometheus sarcopha- gus in Capitol, 229 Mithras cult, the κλΐμαξ έπτάτΓυ\ο$ of, 162 Mithrasliturgie, Dieterich's, 365 if. Mnemosyne, drinking of, precedes final disembodiment of purified soul, 157 Models, astronomical, in antiquity, 165 Moore, Dr. E., on authenticity of the Quaestio de Aqua et Terra, 102 on the geography of Orosius, 105 on references in Paradiso to Revelation of St. John, 361 More, H., on the Plastic Principle in Nature, 95 fiF. on vehicles, terrestrial, aerial, and aethereal, 96 on the Millennium, 97 a soul must have a vehicle of some kind, 97 on the efiect upon terrestrial and aerial bodies of the Fire of the Last Day, 97, 98 on sunspots, 98 one of his "Myths" quoted, 98 fF. indebtedness of his mythology of aerial daemons to that of the Platonists and Stoics, 99 his belief in witchcraft, 100 on the number 729, 349 his view of the end of the Scripture, 432 his Ρ hilosophickal Poems quoted, 487 AE"., 496, 505 criticises Hobbes's disproof of Incor- poreal Substance, 492 Morfill, Professor, his translation of Secrets of Enoch referred to, 361 Moses Atticus, Plato as, 476 Mundo, de, astronomy of, 353 geography of, 467 Murray, Mr. G. G. Α., on Brit. Mus. Gold Tablets, 156 Myer and Nutt's Voyage of Bran, on conception without male intervention, 199 Myers, F. W. H., on the δαιμόνων of Socrates, 3 makes changes in tension of muscles of the throat essential part of poetic excitation, 393 Mysteries, stronghold in Greece of doctrine of Immortality, 65 Mysticism, Goethe's definition of, 70 528 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Myth, the eschatological, characterised, 14 interpretation of, must be psychological, 16 the vehicle of exposition chosen by Plato, when he deals with the a priori conditions of conduct and science, 49 education of children to begin with, according to Plato, 53 fif. Plato brings, into conformity with science as far as possible, 94 not to be taken literally, according to Plato, but to be "sung over oneself" till the charm of it touches the heart, 113 aetiological, value attached to, by Plato, 201 if. aetiological, in the Kdlewala, 203, 204 its two "meanings," 244 the Phaedo, motif of, Moral Responsi- bility, 114 the Gorgias, Moral Responsibility the motif of, 126 the Gorgias, its theory of AcoXaais and κάθαρσίί — of Punishment and Pardon, 126, 127 the Gorgias, its rendering of the wonder and reverence with which man re- gards Death, 127, 128 the Gorgias, on the infinite difference between vice with large and vice with small opportunity, 129 if. distinguished from Allegory and Parable, 15 Myth and Allegory, Westcott on, 243 difference between illustrated from Spanish chapel fresco, 429 Myth and Ritual compared, 58 Myths, introduction of, perhaps suggested to Plato by certain passages in the conversation of Socrates, 2 Plato's, appeal to that part of the soul which expresses itself, not in theoretic, but in value-judgments, or rather, value-feelings, 21 Plato's, effect produced by, compared with that produced by contemplation of Nature, 22 Plato's, effect produced by, compared with that produced hj Poetry generally, 22 ff. Plato's, described as Dreams expressive of Transcendental Feeling, 42 allegorical interpretation of, Plato's judgment on, 242 allegorical interpretation of, Bacon's, 242 Narcissus Myth, Neo-Platonic allegorisa- tion of, 239, 240 " Necessary " Truth, what ? 504 Necessity, the throne of, in the Myth of Er, where ? 153, 165 ff. Nettleship, R. L., on the lack of organic connection in latter half of Rep. x., 73 on the νωτον ουρανού, 165 Newman, Cardinal, on Conscience as connecting principle between creature and Creator, 447 Newton, his Principia quoted for his theological belief, 489 ff. Norris, his Reason and Religion referred to, 480, 481, 498 ff on ecstasy and the holy life, 481 on the a priori in knowledge, 499 distinguishes, as Lotze does, between Reality of Existence and of Validity, 500 his Ideal World compared with T. H. Green's Eternal Consciousness, 501 adopts Malebranche's doctrine of " See- ing all things in God," 501 on moral obligation, 503 Number 729, 349, 350 7, instances given of its importance, 360 Obligation, how Reason imposes, accord- ing to Platonism, 503 Old Testament, Philo's allegorisation of, 234 ff. Olympiodorus on the infernal rivers, 168 Optimism and Pessimism, 506 ff. Orators, Attic, their attitude to the doctrine of the Immortality of the Soul, 61 ff. Orosius and the doctrine of one continu- ous οίκονμυένη, 105 Orphic cult, spread of, 65 ff. Plato's attitude to, QQ ff. Philosophy described by Plato in terms of, 69 Lethe and Mnemosyne in, 156 ff. Orphic κατάβασίί eis "Αίδου, 66 Orphic priests, as distinguished from Orphic doctrine, Plato's attitude to, 70 Orrery, the, in the Myth of Er, 1 65 Pandora Myth, in Hesiod, 238 Parable, Reville on, 250 Parables, the, of the New Testament, 250 Paradiso, the, latest example of the "Astronomical Apocalypse," 364 Parmenides, the celestial eschatology of the opening lines of his Poem, 351 Paul, H., his version of the Kalewala, 204 Pausanias on Lethe and Mnemosyne at oracle of Trophonius, 160 YieUov aX77^eias, the, 355 ff. Plotinus on, 357 Plutarch on, 357, 358 the Axiochus on, 358 INDEX 529 Personal God, idea of, presented by Plato in Myth, 53 Pessimism and Optimism, 506 ΰ. Phaedo, hydrostatics of, criticised by Aristotle, 102 medieval translation of, 102 PMedrus Myth, the, celestial or astro- nomical mise en seine of its eschat- ology, 350 ff. Philo, his allegorical interpretation of the Old Testament, 18, 234 flF. on the number 729, 349 on Jewish Angels and Greek Daemons, 450 influence of, on Cambridge Platonists, 480 Philosophy as Life and Immortality, 428, 429 Physiologus described and quoted, 17 Pilgrim's Progress, at once an Allegory and a Myth, 246 quoted, 246 ff. -Pillar of Light, the, in the Myth of Er, discussed, 152, 167 ff. Pindar, his eschatology, QQ S. Plato's debt to, 68 Pitra, on Physiologus, refeiTed to, 17 Planets, influence of, in producing tem- peraments, 358 ff. Rastic Principle, the, ignored by Des- cartes, 478, 493 explains, for Cambridge Platonists, the existence of " vehicles " without which the "Eternal Consciousness" could not "reproduce" itself, 493 of Cambridge Platonists compared with the " Spiritual Principle " of modern English Idealists, 494 Plato, as Moses Atticus, 210 his attitude to Teleology, 224 ff. his attitude to the allegorisation of Myths, 231 his astronomy, 354 Platonism, as temper, illustrated by Berkeley's life, 517 ff. Piatt, Mr. Α., on Plato and Geology, 465 ff. Pliny, on Lethe and Mnemosyne at oracle of Trophonius, 160 Plotinus, attitude of to the " Problem of the Universe," 45 his allegorisation of the Myth of Pro- metheus and Pandora, 238 his allegorisation of Narcissus Myth, 239 quoted on mirror and bowl of Dionysus, 360 his interpretation of Diotima's allegory, 428 • influence of, on Cambridge Platonists, 480 ff. on θεωρία and ^pωs (directed to Ιδέαι) as constituting the Principle of Life, 503, 504 Plutarch, on the justice of punishing children for sins of fathers, 63 on allegorisation of Homer, 231, 232 his Aridaeus - Thespesius Myth, given, and commented on, 369 ff. his power of colour-visualisation, 381 on vovs,. ψυχή, and σώμα supplied by Sun, Moon, and Earth respectively, 440, 441 his daemonology, 441 ff. his Timarchus Myth given, 441 ff. " Poetic Truth,' what ? 384 ff. Poetry, chief end of, production and regulation of Transcendental Feeling, 33 ff. its effect identical with that produced by other Fine Arts, and sometimes even with that produced by con- templation of Nature and Human Life, and by the memories of Child- hood and Youth, 35 a Theory of, 382 ff. Posidonius, influence of, on development of astronomical eschatology, 352 on aerial daemons, 438 Postgate, Mr. J. P., on the Sirens, 128 Pre-existence and άνάμνησι$, Zeller on, 343 ff. Pringle-Pattison, Professor A. S., referred to, 52 on "Categories in Things," 340 "Problem of the Universe," relation of Thought and Transcendental Feeling respectively to, 44, 45 attitude of Plotinus to, 45 Prometheus, contrasted with Epimetheus, 225 ff. Prometheus Myth, on Capitoline Sar- cophagus, 228 ff. various versions of, 229 lends itself easily to allegorisation, 230 allegorised by Plotinus, 238 Prophecy, Professor P. Gardner on, 431, 433 Prophetic Temperament, the, Diotima a study of, 430 ff. Spinoza on, 430, 431 Purgatory, Dante's Mount of, and the Stoic "Steep hill of Virtue" com- pared, 104 Rabelais, quoted in comparison with the Myth told by Aristophanes in Sym- posium, 410 ff. Rashdall, Dr., referred to for medieval translation of the Phaedo, 102 Refrigerium, doctrine of, taken in con- nection with Dante's Eunoe, 161 530 THE MYTHS OF PLATO Religious Consciousness, the, demands a Personal God, 51 how opposed to the Scientific Under- standing, 52 if. Renan, on Spanish Chapel fresco, 114 Representation and Metre, the place of each in Poetry, 388 ff. ^ Resurrection, doctrine of, 198 ff Revelation of St. John, not an " Astro- nomical Apocalypse," 361 Dante little indebted to, 361 Reville, on the profound philosophy of Myths, 16 on Rite and Myth, 58 on Ritual, 256 Ritschl, his view of Inspiration, 433 . Ritual, compared with Myth, 58 with Myth and Allegory, 256 ff. Robertson-Smith, on relation of Myth to Ritual, 14 Rohde, on Greek agnosticism regarding Immortality of the Soul, 62 on Orphic rites, 65 on Pindar's eschatology, 67 on κατάβασί$ eis "AtSov, 154 on refrigerium, 161 on άωροι, 200 Roscher, on Lethe, 168 .'Round People, the, of Aristophanes, com- pared with the Sicilian triskdes, 408 compared with Zulu and Arabian one- legged people, 408 compared with the monsters of Em- pedocles, 408, 409 Rouse, Mr., on votive figures, 153 Ruskin, on Spanish Chapel fresco, 114, 257 Sander, on Geography of Atlantis Myth, 466 Scartazzini, on Dante's Purgatory and Earthly Paradise, 104 Schiller, Mr. F. C. S., on ivipyia ακινησίας, 164 Schleiermacher, on the Protagoras Myth, 220, 227 ff. Schmidt, on Dante's Quaestio de Aqua et Terra, 103 referred to for position of the Earthly Paradise, 104 Schopenhauer, his Freedom in esse com- pared with Prenatal Choice in Myth of Er, 171 his definition of Poetry, 387 his criticism of Kant's Categorical Im- perative, 514 Schwanitz, on Allegory of the Cave, 252 Scylax, his irepiirXovs referred to, 467 Seneca's Letter to Marcia, eschatology of, 353 Sensitive Soul, supervenes upon the Vegetative, 40 Shelley, Adonais quoted for effect pro- duced similar to that produced by Plato's Eschatological Myths, 27 ff. on distinction between poetry and prose, 390 his Poem, The Recollection, quoted, 395 Simonides, his attitiide to doctrine of Immortality of the Soul, 62 Sirens, the, associated with Death, 127 Miss Harrison on, 127 Mr. J. P. Postgate on, 128 Smith, John, his view of the relation between a Holy Life and a Right Belief, 432 on ecstasy and the Holy Life, 481 differs from Cudworth and More in relying less on "Science" than on "moral feeling" for proof of the existence of God, 491, 492 distinguishes κίρησις ττροβατική and KLvi]ats κυκλική, 496 Socrates, his " mesmeric " influence, 2 his Daemon, 2, 3 Somnium Scipionis probably owes its astronomy to Posidonius, 439 astronomical eschatology of, 353 Sophists, the — their use of Allegories or Illustrative Fables, 1 Soul, the Idea of, as represented in Plato's Eschatological Myths, 60 ft". Soul-stuff, in Timaeus, 304 f. Souls, number of, fixed, 198, 199 Spanish Chapel, fresco referred to, 114 referred to to illustrate difference between Myth and Allegory, 429 Spencer and Gillen on Souls of ancestors entering into women, 199 Spenser, the human race created to make good the loss of the fallen angels, 106 his allegory of Castle of Medina, 257 Spinoza, his view that religion is a matter of piety rather than of dogmatic truth, 59 on the Prophetic Temperament, 430, 431 Springs, hot and cold, origin of, in Plmedo, 94 Stall baum, on the general characteristics of the Politicus Myth, 196 on Protagoras Myth, 221 on Myth and Dialectic, 242 Stevenson, R. L., his Woodman quoted, 40 Stoics, the, their doctrine of σνγκατά• θ€σι$, 63 their allegorisation of Homer, 233, 234 their doctrine of aerial habitat of daemons and souls of the dead, 437 ff. Story-telling, love of, importance of for the development of man, 5 INDEX 531 Story-telling, always "about people and animals," 6 if. Stories, distiuguislied as Simply Anthropo- logical and Zoological, Aetiological, and Eschatological, 8 flf. Simply Anthropological and Zoological, illustrated, 8 ff. Aetiological, illustrated, 10-14 and magic, 10 various classes of, 10 Cosmological, a variety of the aetio- logical story, 10-13 Sun, western rising of, in Atreus Myth, 197 rising where he now sets, and setting where he now rises, in Egyptian story, 197 Symbolism, "suppressed," illustrated from Dante, 258 Tablets, attached to Souls by Judges of the Dead, 130 gold, of Thurii and Petelia, 130, 156 ff. Tablet, Petelia, quoted, 156 Tannery, on Orphic rites, 65 Tartarus, has entrance and exit separate in Phaedo and Myth of Er, 112 Teleology, attitude of the religious con- sciousness and the scientific under- standing respectively to, 52 Plato's attitude to, 224 ff. and Mechanism, 508 Teleological and mechanical explanations of the World, distinction between, set forth in Protagoras Myth, 222 fiF. Theodore of Mopsuestia, his exegesis, 237 Thiasi, and personal, as distinguished from official, religion, 71 Thiemann, on doctrine of Immorality of the Soul as held by Plato, 60 on locality of Lethe, 154 Thomas the Rhymer, Ballad of, quoted for rivers of blood in Elf-land, 103 referred to for the "Three Ways," 131 Thompson, regards the Phaedrits Myth as a Rhetorical Paradigm, 336 regards the Phaedrus Myth as an allegory, 336, 339 Three Ways, the, Ballad of Thomas the Rhymer referred to for, 131 the three parts of Dante's D. C. corre- spond to, 132 Tides of Atlantic Ocean, origin of, in Phaedo, 94 Timaeus, the only work of Plato which Dante knew directly, 102 reputation of, in antiquity and the middle age, 210 ^ one of a Trilogy, 259, 299 Toynbee, Dr., on Dante's acquaintance with Claudian, 105 Toynbee, Dr., on Dante's acquaintance with Pliny, 160 referred to for Dante's knowledge of Macrobius, 361 on Dante's knowledge of the version of the Timaeus made by Chalcidius, 468 Tozer, Mr., quoted for Dante's know- ledge of Somnium Scipionis, 361 on Par. xxxi., 79 ff., 367 Transcendental Feeling, production and regulation of, the end of Poetry, 22, 33 expressed by Dante, last Canto of Par., and V. JSi., Sonnet xxv., 23, 38 Poets quoted to illustrate means em- ployed for production of, 23-33 means employed by Poetry to produce the dream-consciousness in which it arises, 33 ff. in a nascent form accounts for the " magic " of certain kinds of Poetry, 36 explained genetically, 39 ff. two phases of, 41 Imagination the Interpreter of, 42 its relation to Sense and Understanding, 42 Consciousness aware of " the Good " in, 44 ; cf. 59 the beginning and end of Metaphysics, 44 Consciousness comes nearest to the object of Metaphysics, Ultimate Reality, in, 44 "Transcendental," as distinguished from *' Empirical " Feeling, 389 Tylor, Prof., on the state of the imagina- tion among ancient and savage peoples, 7 Universal, the, of Poetry, 384 ff. "Vegetative Part of the Soul," funda- mental, and source of that implicit Faith in the Value of Life on which Conduct and Science rest, 39 and " Universal of Poetry," 386 Vehicles, terrestrial, aerial, and aethereal, H. More on, 96 aerial, of Souls in Purgatory, Dante on, 97 Vernon, on Lethe aud Eunoe, 155 Virgil, where does he localise the River of Lethe ? 155 Visualisation, colour- and form-, power of, possessed by Plato, Plutarch, and Dante, 380, 381 Volcanic action, explained in Phuedo, 94 Volquardsen, his view of the δαιμόνων of Socrates, 3 Votive figures and the βίων trapaSeiy' ματα of the Myth of Er, 153 532 THE I4YTHS OF PLATO Wallace, W., on Kant's Ideas of Reason, quoted, 46-7 Walt Whitman's Memories of President Lincoln^ quoted for effect produced similar to that produced by Plato's Eschatological Myths, 31 if. War, Plato's view of, 452, 453 Ward, Prof., his Naturalism and Agnos- ticism referred to, 478 Weismann, Prof., referred to, 434 Westcott, Bishop, on Aeschylus' view of the Condition of the Dead, 63 on influence of Plato's Myths through later Platonic schools, 230 on Myth and Allegory, 243 Wilamowitz - Mollendorff, on Voyage of Odysseus to Hades, as Orphic epi- sode in Odyssey, QQ Witchcraft. Cudworth's belief in, 100 Smith's belief in, 100 H. More's belief in, 100 Wordsworth, his lines beginning " There was a boy " quoted to illustrate nature of " poetic effect, " 35 Wordsworth, on relation of Poetry Science, 342 on place of metre in Poetry, 390 Xenophanes, on the immorality of Hon and Hesiod, 231 Yeats, Mr. W. B., referred to for the ic of "poems spoken to a harp," 393 Zagreus Myth, 239 compared with that told by Aris• phanes in Symposium, 409 ff. Zeller, on the δαιμόρων of Socrates, 3 on doctrine of Immortality of the SO' as held by Plato, 60, 70 on allegorisation of Homer by ti Stoics, 233 on Neo-Platonic allegorisation, 242 on Pre-existence and άνάμνησίί, 343 ■. Λ Λ THE END Printed by R. & R. Clark, Limited, Edinburgh. 15δ U.C. BERKELEY LIBRARIES COafl^DTDSfi