MASTER NEGA TIVE NO. 92-80720 MICROFILMED 1 993 COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES/NEW YORK as part of the "Foundations of Western Civilization Preservation Project" Funded by the NATIONAL ENDOWMENT FOR THE HUMANITIES Reproductions may not be made without permission from Columbia University Library .*■ COPYRIGHT STATEMENT The copyright law of the United States - Title 17, United States Code - concerns the making of photocopies or other reproductions of copyrighted material. Under certain conditions specified in the law, libraries and archives are authorized to furnish a photocopy or other reproduction. One of these specified conditions is that the photocopy or other reproduction is not to be "used for any purpose other than private study, scholarship, or research.*' If a user makes a request for, or later uses, a photocopy or reproduction for purposes in excess of "fair use," that user may be liable for copyright infringement. This institution reserves the right to refuse to accept a copy order if, in its judgement, fulfillment of the order would involve violation of the copyright law. AUTHOR: ARISTOTLE TITLE: RHETORIC OF ARISTOTLE ... PLACE: LONDON, NEW YORK DA TE : 1886 Restrictions on Use: COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES PRESERVATION DEPARTMENT BIBLIOGRAPHIC MICROFORM TARGET Original Material as Fiin\ed - Existing Bibliograpliic Record ^ ■<■ ri n ir •mmm^^f^f^m^^^m^ 88Ar51 IVXI4 Rhetorica. English •'^^ /•«'%*« . » 9 Aristoteles . The Rhetoric of Aristotle; translated with an analysis and critical notes, by J. E. C. Welldon • .. London and New York/ Hdacmillsui and oo., 1886 xlvii, 306 p. 19i«n^ YTvn Gepy-i»-Sutler-f— 1886-t- . -D88Ar5t Another-copy- in-Carpenter-. D€ > QA r 61^ -^l ■VXIStt f.::^ Q r^ ^. >Xtr-w ricar; — iSS6; o Master Negative # TECHNICAL MICROFORM DATA ___J}1.T™ «^_ REDUCTION RATIO: ^LLilL IMAGE PLACEMENT: lA QlA^ IB IID DATE FILMED: __J>-Ji:^ INITIALS J^^__ HLMEDBY: RESEARCH PUBLICATIONS. INC WOODDRIDGE. CT 7 FILM SIZE: BIBLIOGRAPHIC IKRHG U LAKlTlliS ■^h^MkH^Hi^R^HMd ^ • ■ fcii A W , 1 11 I M tw tJttti^mttimlm tmmt it-^ I MAIN EN mY:_Qyu^i'ntf ^ ,. -3 WA(if(ytA(? en ffui^tcjijji . Bibliographic Itregula rities in the Orig inal Dncumpnt List volumes and pages affected; include name of institution if fihning borrowed text. « PageCs) missing/not available: yolumes(s) missing/not available:. L/_lllegible and/ or damaged page(s):. t^3^ /^^ Page(s) or volumes(s) misnumbered:. Bound out of sequence: .Page(s) or illustration(s) f ihned from copy borrowed from:_; Other: FILMED IN WHOLE OR PART FROM A COPY BORROWED FROM STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK, STONY BROOK Association for information and Image Management 1 1 00 Wayne Avenue. Suite 1 1 00 Silver Spring, Maryland 20910 301/587-8202 Centimeter 12 3 4 5 iiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiilii 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 mm iiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiiiliiii^^ m m Inches 1 1 1 I 1 I 1.0 I.I I I I I I 2.5 ■ 63 IS 14.0 2.2 2.0 1.8 I I I 1.25 1.4 1.6 MFINUFfiCTURED TO fillM STRNDfiRDS BY RPPLIED IMOGE, INC. ) .J '" _.t ^. lEj|l rinjffuilfrugfrui][ruilf^ THE LIBRARIES COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 1 1 1 i General Library k I i f^ 111 |gi pjiJ f rirD f rmllpJiV rinJffiJilfrijg n i if; Given by _. oiven by iJonald L. Clark -^^^^^.j^^ Ri^^tX^^^c^xX. a/v;c^Xo--U-c- ^ O^ Z^^uiX-^ oA*^ THE KHETOKIC OF AEISTOTLE THE EHETOKIC OF AEISTOTLE TKANSLATED WITH AN ANALYSIS AND CRITICAL NOTES BY J. K C. WELLDON, M.A. FELLOW OF king's COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE, AND HEAD-MASTEB OP HABEOW SCHOOL. Hon&on MACMILLAN AND AND NEW YOBK 1886 CO. \Th£ Right of Translation is reserved.} 1 GIFT OF 'CLh,M^ :\ V XX4 ©ambritJge : PRINTED BY C. J. CLAY, M.A. AND SONS, AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. , \ PEEFACE. This Translation of the Rhetoric of Aristotle is a companion volume to my Translation of the Politics. But it differs from it in the greater fulness of the notes ; for, as I have no thought of publishing an edition of the Rhetomc, it seems to me necessary to explain as well as I can my interpretations of some difficult pas- 8a{;es and my reasons for them. It is well known that Mr Cope published in his lifetime an Introduction to Aristotle s Rhetoric and at his death left an elaborate commentary, which has since been edited with scrupulous care by Dr Sandys. Nobody, who has not been led to a close study of the Rhetoric, can appreciate the extent and exactness of Mr Cope's labours. Next to his works, but below them in judg- ment, stands the critical commentary of Spen- gel. There are many other books bearing upon the Rhetoric, which a Translator is bound to consult, as the British Museum Catalogue (s. v. \ I tm VI PREFACE. Aristotle) so fully shews ; but it is not worth while to enumerate them. Among personal helps it is a pleasure to remember that I owe an especial debt of gratitude to my friend, Mr W. T. Lendrum, who was one of my col- leagues at Dulwich, for his kindness in reading my proof-sheets and in giving me the benefit of his opinion, to which his accurate scholar- ship lends pecuhar value, upon several points in the Translation. The science or, as Aristotle would call it, the art of Rhetoric has had a curious history. It was his creation ; and what- ever has been best in it from this time to the present is due to him. The definition of Rhetoric, its relation to Psychology, the distinction of its three kinds, the nature of its proofs, the use of enthymeme and example, the special and common topics, the style and arrangement of a speech, all are his. Where the Latin writers, such as Cicero and Quintilian, ampUfied the field of Rhetoric, it is not unfair to say that they amplified it in a direction which he had delibe- rately lefb alone. Nor is there any rhetorical work of a later age which can be placed in comparison with his. Even so late a book as Archbishop Whately's Elements of Rhetoric is in its method essentially Aristotelian and hardly goes beyond his statement of principles. \ PREFACE. Vll The study of Rhetoric as an educational instrument, although it formed a part of Roman as well as of later Greek culture, although in the middle ages it was one of the subjects of the Trivium, although from the era of the Revival of Learning it entered into the curriculum of the Universities, has at least in England been practically neglected since the beginning of the eighteenth century. There are several reasons for this neglect, and they are valid; but it is not a gain without a loss. It is possible that the time will come again when the world will recognize that "it is not enough to know what to say, but it is necessary also to know how to say it " (ov yap anoxpr) to cxeti/ a Set XeyetVy dkX' avdyio) kol Tavra a5s Set elneiv). Then the RhetoHc of Aris- totle will, I think, be widely read, as being perhaps a solitary instance of a book which not only begins a science but completes it. It is one of my hopes in publishing this Translation that I may bring the Rhetoric within the reach, if I may so express it, of the modern world. The office of a translator, even if he is also in some sense an interpreter, may not unfairly be regarded as a humble one. But as knowledge broadens, and the mass of men have less leisure for studying Greek f ^ VUl PREFACE. thought in the language of the Greeks, it would seem to become more and more desir- able that the links which unite the new civi- lization with the old should be strengthened and multiplied ; and of these links translation is the chief. For, as Goethe says in one of his letters to Carlyle, So ist jeder Uebersetzer anzusehen, dass er sich als Vermittler dieses allgemein geistigen Handels bemiiht, und den Wechseltausch zu befordern sich zum Geschaft macht. Denn was man auch von der Unzu- langlichkeit des Uebersetzens sagen mag, so ist und bleibt es doch eines der wichtigsten und wurdigsten Geschafte in dem allgemeinen Weltwesen. Harrow School, October 13, 1886. KB. The text adopted is that of Bekker's octavo edi- tion. The marginal references are to the pages of the Translation, the references in the foot-notes to the pa<»es and lines of Bekker's text. As in the Politics, the words italicized, except in a few self-evident instances, are inserted in order to make the original fully intelligible. 1 ANALYSIS. BOOK I. CHAPTER I. Rhetoric is a counterpart {dvTiaTpocjyos) of Dialectic. Both are general in their application ; neither is limited to any definite science. At present Rhetoric, like Dialectic, is unmethodical; or its method is purely empirical. Still it is possible to treat Rhetoric systematically. The artistic part of Rhetoric consists in the proofs (TrtWfiff) — although this is a part of it which is neglected in rhetorical hand- books {rixvai) — to excite the emotions of the audience i s to war p i.,- their judgment. (There are three reasons for preferring the authority of the laws to the decisions of particular judges : (1) It is easier to find a few competent legislators or judges than a large number. (2) Laws are the results of mature deliberation ; judicial decisions are given on the spur of the moment. (3) The legislator's decisions are general and prospective ; the judge's decisions relate to the issues of the moment in which his personal feelings may be and often are involved. Still there are certain questions, such as questions of fact, which are necessarily left to the decision of the judges.) The reason why writers upon Rhetoric have generally confined themselves to forensic Rhetoric is that it affords the most op- portunity of "wa^elling out of the record," i.e. of introducing other topics than strict proof The only proper subjects then of artistic treatment are the proofs. i / : * |i 1 -^ ANALYSIS. But proof (TTiWtff) is a species of demonstration (dnodfiiU rtr), and the rhetorical form of demonstration is the enthymeme- ^' Also the enthymeme is a species of syUogism ((rv\koyi among the arts. , ^^ (4) It is a means of self-defence. J> ' r ^^ 'T If it is urged that Rhetoric, when used unjustly, may do great harm, the answer is that this objection holds good equally of all good things, except virtue itself. The functi on (€pyov)^f Rhetoric is not to persuade but t o dis- cover the available niSns ot p e rsuasion in anv subieot (t,\ ;;t.7u TO virapxovra iriBava ncpl fKaarop). N.B. There are apparent or fallacious, as well as real, means of persuasion ; but the discovery of both belongs to the same art. CHAPTER II. Rhetoric may be defined as a " faculty of discovering all the possible means of persuasion on any subject" (dvvafus ntpl tKatnov Tov Beapfja-ai ro ivbfx6p,fvov nidavop). Rhetorical proofs are of two kinds : (1) inartistic (arfx^ot), which the rhetorician finds ready to his hand, e.g. witnesses, tortures, contracts. (2) artistic (evrf^vot), which he invents. ^ ANALYSIS. XI \ The artistic proofs are threefold, consisting in (1) the manifestation of moral character {^6os) in the saker, (2) the production of a certain disposition in the audience, (3) the argument of the speech itself. Accordingly the complete rhetorician should possess (1) the power of argumentative reasoning, (2) a knowledge of character, (3) a knowledge of the nature and quality of the emotions (TrdBtf). Hence it follows that Rhetoric is an offshoot of Dialectic on the one hand and of Ethics on the other. The proofs conveyed by the argument are (1 ) the example {napdbfi.yyM^ corresponding to the induction (cTraywyif) in Dialectic, (2) the enthymeme, corresponding to the syllogism, (3) the apparent enthymeme ((jyaivopevov ivBvfiTjfia) corre- sponding to the apparent syllogism {.Ma .tltj. xu ANALYSIS. I vi^ iV The example is an induction, where the example itself and the thing exemplified both fall under the same general law, but the example is the better known instance of it. The materials of enthymemes are {a) such as are common to many various arts and faculties ; these are the "common topics" or "topics," as they are sometimes called par excellence (koivoI tottoi or roVoi) ; (&) such as are special to one art or faculty (rata, l8ioi rwrot, €i8t)\ e.g. physical propositions to Physics, ethical to Ethics, and so on. • ^ An over-skilful i i sfl of t hej^special topics" is not appropriate _rhetorician; it leads him into the province of the special art or faculty to which they belong. Vv> yi \ 4 J CHAPTER III. There are three kinds of audience, and corresponding to them three kinds of Rhetoric, viz. deliberative ((n;/i/3ovXfVTt#coi'), forensic (^iKaviK6v\ epideictic (eViSeixTticdi/), i.e. the Rhetoric of display. They admit of the following classification : Kind of Rhetoric. Deliberative Forensic \ Epideictic V Divisions. Exhortation Dissuasion Accusation Defence Eulogy Censure } } } Time. Future Past Present / Ena (r€Xoff). Expediency and Inexpediency. Justice and Injustice. Honour and Disgrace, or Nobleness and Shamefulness {jo Kokov Kai TO aicr- Xpov). \ ANALYSIS. xiii Hence the deliberative orator employs propositions (7rporaa««) relating to expediency and inexpediency, the forensic orator propositions relating to justice and injustice, the epideictic orator propositions relating to honour and disgrace; and these are the "special topics" of each kind of Rhetoric. But they all employ propositions relating to possibility and / impossibility, the occurrence or non-occurrence of events in the I past and in the future, and magnitude both absolute and com- I parative ; /^these are the "common topics." CHAPTERS IV— VIIL Deliberative or political Rhetoric (r^ (rvfx^ovXtvTiKov fj drjfiTjyopiKov y(Pos). CHAPTER IV. As the end (reXos) which deliberative Rhetoric regards is expediency, its subjects are things good or bad^ i.e. expedient or injurious, but not all such things, not such as do not admit of two possibilities, nor such as depend on Nature {(fyvais) or chance (rvxrj). The subjects of Rhetoric are all such things, being expedient or injurious, as are possible matters of deliberation, i.e. such as naturally depend upon our own action. The most important of these are :— (1) Finance. (2) War and peace. * M ./ X Vr J \ XIV ANALYSIS. (3) Defence of the country. (4) Imports and exports. (5) Legislation. Under (1) Finance, comes a knowledge of the resources of the State and their possible development and its channels of expenditure. Under (2) War and Peace, a knowledge of the actual and possible military force of the State and of other States with which it has been or may be at war and of their military history. Under (3) Defence of the country, a knowledge of its defensive force and the sites of its fortresses. Under (4) Imports and exports, a knowledge of the relation of the State to other States in respect of its necessary supplies. Under (5) Legislation, a knowledge of the different kinds of polities and their sources of strength or weakness. CHAPTER V. ^ As all men, both individually and collectively, aim at happiness (€vSaifiovia\ it is upon happiness or the constituents of happiness that exhortation and dissuasion turn. Various definitions of happiness : (a) prosperity conjoined with virtue. (b) an independent state of existence. (c) the pleasantest life conjoined with safety. {d) an abundance of goods and slaves with the ability to preserve them and to make a practical use of them. ^^ K I I i i\ ANALYSIS. XV Happiness implies the possession of (1) personal goods (ri cV avVw dya0d), whether of the soul or of the body ; (2) external goods (rA €'kt6s dyadd), such as nobility, riches, honour. The constituent parts of happiness are (1) Nobility, which implies in a State, that its citizens are indigenous or of high antiquity or have won themselves fame. in a family, the legitimacy of its members and their good name or celebrity. (2) The blessing of offspring, whether of a numerous, stalwart and moral youth in a State, or of numerous and goodly children, both male and female, in a family. N.B. It is important to provide for the moral culture of the women as well as of the men. (3) Wealth, in money, lands, live stock and slaves ; not only the productive kinds of wealth, but luxuries. The possession of wealth should be both absolute and secure. (4) Reputation, whether for personal character or for some prized possession. (6) Honour, which may assume a number of different forms (6) Health. (7) Beauty, which is different at different periods of life. (8) Strength. (9) Size, which should exceed the average size, i.e. height stoutness and breadth, of men. ' (10) Athletic excellence. (11) A happy old age. (12) The possession of many good friends. (13) Good Fortune. (14) Virtue. XVI i \ ANALYSIS. CHAPTER VI. As the end of deliberative Rhetoric is expediency and what- ever is expedient (a-vficpepov) is good {aya66v\ it is necessary to apprehend the nature of Good. Good may be defined as that which is desirable for its own sake and for the sake of which we desire or choose something else, and which is sought by all things or by all sentient or intelligent things or would be sought by them, if they should acquire intelligence. The following then are goods : (1) happiness. (2) justice, courage, temperance {a-a(f)poavtn]\ magnanimity (fi€yaXo'sln)xta), magnificence (jieydkoTrpineia) and other virtues of the soul. (3) health, beauty etc., as being physical virtues or graces. (4) wealth. (5) friendship. (6) honour and reputation. (7) rhetorical and practical ability. (8) natural gifts, such as memory, sharpness of wit, etc. (9) all sciences and arts. (10) life itself, apart from the goods of life. (11) justice. These are admitted to be goods; but there are other goods of a disputable kind, and in respect of them Aristotle suggests some twenty topics which may be used in syllogisms to show that a thing is a good. CHAPTER VII. Comparison of goods. It often happens that two things are admitted to be expedient, but the question arises, Which is the more expedient of the two ? ■ r 1 ANALYSIS. XVll Hence it is necessary to consider the question of degree (rb fiSKXov KOI ^TTOP). — ^_ , Aristotle suggests a number of topics bearing upon the com- parative greatness or goodness of things. v.' \ CHAPTER VIIL The principal means of persuasiveness in deliberative Rhetoric is an acquaintance with the various forms of polity. The character of a polity is determined by the character of its supreme authority {t6 Kvpiov). There are four pohties, viz. Democracy, Oligarchy, Aristocracy Monarchy. ' A Democracy is a poUty in which the ofllces of State are distributed among the citizens by lot. An Oligarchy, one in which they are distributed among persons possessing a certain property qualification. An Aristocracy, one in which they are distributed among the educated class. Monarchy, or the polity in which an individual is supreme, may be (1) constitutional Monarchy or Kingship (/Sao-tXfta), (2) absolute Monarchy or Tyranny. Of these polities each has its end {rikos). The end of Democracy is liberty. The end of Oligarchy is wealth. The end of Aristocracy is education and legality. I The end of Tyranny is self-preservation. I The customs or institutions of a polity are relative to its end, -Also polities have their characters; aristocratical sentiments are suited to the character of an Aristocracy, democratical to that of a Democracy, and so on. Hence it is necessary that the deliberative orator should apprehend the characters of the several polities. W. R. yj j f/iO J \) \^ XVUl ANALYSIS. CHAPTER IX. Epideictic Rhetoric {r6 iiribtixTiKov yeVoc ). Its subjects are virtue and vice, or nobleness and shameful- ness. Definition of moral nobleness— A thing is noble if, while it is desirable for its own sake, it is laudable, or if, while it is good, it is pleasant in virtue of its goodness. It follows that virtue is noble ; and the elements of virtue are justice, valour, temperance, magnificence, magnanimity, hberality, gentleness, sagacity {4>p6- vrja-is) and speculative wisdom {ia). The greatest virtues are those which are in the highest degree serviceable to others. Taking this conception of virtue, Aristotle proceeds (1) to analyse moral actions, (2) to compare them in respect of their virtuousness. N.B. Rhetorical artifices : (1) To represent certain quaUties as identical with other qualities which are closely allied to them, e.g. caution as subUety foohshness as simplicity, extravagance as liberality. * (2) To consider the qualities held in esteem by the audi- ence. (3) To display the moral purpose {npoaiptais) of the person who IS the subject of the speech. (Digression upon eulogy (cVatvoy), panegyric (e'yccoVtoi/), feUcita- tion (jiaKapiafios), congratulation {(vdaifioviafMos) : The subjects of eulogy are actions (Trpa^t j), those of panegyric are accomplished results (^pya). Felicitation and congratulation are synonymous terms, em- bracmg eulogy and panegyric. . The same topics, differently expressed, are suitable to euloirv and deliberative Rhetoric.) (4) To employ the means of exaggeration (aCir, XXll ANALYSIS. I I i i \ (h) contrary to his intention, if it touches upon a point which has escaped his notice. Aristotle illustrates the province and nature of equity. CHAPTER XIV. The magnitude of a crime is proportionate to the magnitude of the injustice which prompts it. Hence it is sometimes necessary to estimate the comparative magnitude of crimes. Application of the topic of degree to criminal actions. CHAPTER XV. ^ The inartistic proofs {artx^oi Triorcts), which are properly limited to forensic Rhetoric. They are five, viz. (1) laws, (2) witnesses, (3) contracts, (4) tortures, t (6) the oath. (1) Laws. Topics suitable for upsetting the authority of a law, if it tells against us, and for confirming it, if it makes in our favour. (2) Witnesses may be (a) ancient, (&) contemporary; and, if the latter, either involved in the risk of the action at law or independent of it (a) Ancient witnesses are : poets, who testify to facts of the past, interpreters of oracles, who testify to facts of the future, proverbs. ANALYSIS. XXlll V (6) Contemporary witnesses are : living authorities, if they have pronounced judgment on a particular point, witnesses who appear in Court and give their evidence. Ancient witnesses are more credible than contemporary. Topics for confirming or invalidating the weight of testimony. Testimony may have reference either to oneself or to one*8 adversary and either to fact or to character. (3) Contracts. Topics of exaggeration or depreciation in regard to con- tracts. (4) Torture. / J '^ Topics in support or depreciation of torture, as a means of arriving at the truth. (5) Oaths. Four possible cases : (a) when a person both tenders and accepts the oath, (b) when he does neither, (c) when he tenders the oath without accepting it, (d) when he accepts it without tendering it. Also there may be combinations of two such cases. Or there may be a further complication, if a person his adversary has already taken the oath. Aristotle suggests topics suitable to all these cases and combinations of cases. BOOK 11. CHAPTER L As Rhetoric is intended to be judged, there are two things— apart from direct proof— which should be the objects of the rhetorician's endeavour : /0/4 '■ - * . , II I 1 ¥ XXIV ANALYSIS. m 0v) : A declaration relating not to particulars but to universals, and not to all universals but to such as are the objects of human action and are to be chosen or eschewed in that regard. The enthymeme being the form of syllogism which is ap- I)ropriate to these matters, if the syllogistic form is done away the conclusion of an enthymeme or its major premiss is a maxim' There are four kinds of maxims ; for maxims may either have or not have a logical supplement (eV/Xoyor). Maxims have no such supplement (a) when the maxim is a generally axicepted opinion, (b) when it is intelligible at a glance; maxims which have it are (a) parts of an enthymeme, W.B. ^ (•' III f xxxiv ANALYSIS. (ft) not parts of an enthymeme, but enthymematic in their character, where the reason of the maxim is contained in the words of the maxim itself. Where the maxim is disputable, obscure or paradoxical, the addition of the supplement is indispensable. Maxims are appropriate (1) upon the lips of persons of years and experience, (2} in contradiction of popular or proverbial sayings. There are two important uses of maxims : (1) That, as being general statements, they are pleasing to a vulgar audience who find in them the generalization, or, as it were, the consummation of their partial experience. (2) That, as expressing moral predilections, they invest the speech with an ethical character. CHAPTER XXII. Enthymemes. • • , In the consideration of enthymemes it is necessary to consider (1) the true method of looking for them, (2) their topics. The proper materials of enthymemes are not aU opinions in- discriminately, but such opinions as commeiui themselves to the .^audience. " ' -- But it is necessary that the rhetorician should know all or some at least of the special facts of the subject with which ho deals, e.g. of military matters, if it is war, of justice, if it is a judicial case, and so on. There are two species of enthymemes, viz.: (1) demonstrative (5ftn-«ci), which consist in drawing con- elusions from admitted propositions, (2) refutative (eXfym^a), which consist in drawing con- clusions which are inconsistent with the conclusions of one'd adversary. v^ •N -^ J* \i 1 ANALYSIS. XXXV The special topics of enthymemes will be derived from the special facts of each particular subject. But there are common topics belonging to all subjects. CHAPTER XXin. Aristotle gives a list of 28 topics of demonstrative and refuta- tive enthymemes. N.B. Refutative enthymemes are more popular than de- monstrative, as they are conclusions of opposites in a small space. But of all enthymemes none are so much applauded as those which, although not being superficial, are immediately intelligible. CHAPTER XXIV. As there are not only true syllogisms but syllogisms which are apparent but not true, it follows that there are apparent as well as true enthymemes. Aristotle gives ten topics of apparent enthymemes. CHAPTER XXV. Refutation (XvVtr). There are two methods of refutation, viz. : (1) by countersyllogism, (2) by objection {eparaa-is). The topics of countersyllogisms are clearly identical with those of syllogisms. Objections are of four kinds, being derivable (a) from the enthymeme of one's adversary, (b) from antithesis, (c) from analogy, (d) from a previous decision. L ■- i -1 \:y •^■■■Hki 'f ^ y \ XXXVl ANALYSIS. Aristotle iUustrates these four kinds of objection. The materials of enthymemes being fourfold viz. probabilities, examples, demonstrations (re/e/iifpia), and signs (oTy/icIa), enthymemes constructed from probabilities may invariably be refuted by an objection ; but the objection must be more geuerallv true than the fact objected to. enthymemes constructed from signs or examples are liable to refutation, although they may be probable. It is enthymemes constructed from demonstrations which are irrefutable, unless indeed the fact alleged as a demonstration can 1)0 disproved. CHAPTER XXVI. Correction of two possible errors : (1) Exaggeration and depreciation (rh a^uv Ka\ finovv) are not elements (crroc^ela) or topics of enthymemes but actual enthymemes tending to show the greatness or smallness of things. (2) Refutative enthymemes do not form a species distinct from constructive. For refutation must consist either in urging positive proof or m adducing an objection ; and in the former case it is proving the opposite of an ad- versary's conclusion, and in the latter it is bringing forward an opinion to show tliat the adversary's reasoning is inconclusive or that there is something false in his assumptions. The inventive part of Rhetoric may be now said to have received adequate consideration. It remains to consider style (Ac|*y) and arrangement (rdf«) k. ANALYSIS. XXXVII BOOK III CHAPTER L Style. It is not enough to know what to say ; it is necessary also to know how to say it. The subject admits of three divisions : {a) the sources of persuasiveness in facts, {h) the disposition of the facts, {c) declamation (uTro/cpto-t?) ; and declamation includes (1) the use of the voice, (2) the use of the accents or tones {t6vol) (3) the use of rhythms. Upon declamation no scientific treatise exists. The consideration of it is necessary, if only because of the de- praved character of the audience. The capacity for declamation is a natural gift, and on its histrionic side is hardly susceptible of artistic treatment. But on its rhetorical side it may be reduced to an art. Declamation originated among the poets, who were generally the declaimers of their own tragedies. The consequence wa^ that a poetical style was originally adopted and admired in prose. But the styles of prose and poetry are distinct. We confine ourselves therefore to rhetorical style. CHAPTER IL The principal virtues or graces {dp^Tat) of style are (1) perspicuity, (2) propriety. KB. A certain dignity is imparted to style by the use of words which are a Uttle out of the common. Yet upon the whole m/.^) i.e. a style in which the con- necting particles (aMeafioi) form the only links of the sentence; Such is the style of Herodotus ; (2) or " compact" (Karea-Tpafifi^vr)) i.e. periodic. A period (TTfpiodos) is a sentence which has a beginning and an end m itself and such a magnitude as can be easily comprehended at a glance. A periodic style has two advantages, as being (1) agreeable, (2) easily learnt. ' But the period should be marked by the completion of the sense as well as of the rh)i;hm. Periods may be (1) divided into members or clauses (fV /coJXotr), (2) simple (a^eXelj), i.e. consisting of a single member or clause. The periods and the members of which they are composed, should be neither too short nor too lono' A further division of the periodic style may be made according as Its clauses are (1) simply separate, (2) antithetical Aristotle gives several instances of antithetical clauses The agreeableness of an antithetical style lies in its emphatic and syllogistic character. li. xlii ANALYSIS. ANALYSIS. xliii I!/ h Parisosis is equality of members or clauses. Paromoiosis is similarity of extremities, whether the beginnings or the ends of sentences. The same sentence may combine Tarious points, e.g. antithesis, parisosis, etc. CHAPTER X. Clever sayings (ra darfla). Learning without trouble is agreeable to everybody. Metaphors and similes, but especially metaphors, are instruc- tive. The test of a cleverly constructed enthymeme is its power of conveying rapid instruction. Enthymemes are popular (1) if their structure is antithetical, (2) if their words contain a metaphor which is neither superficial nor far-fetched, (3) if they vividly represent the subject to the eye. In a word there are three objects to be kept in view, viz. metaphor, antithesis and vividness of representation. Metaphors are of four kinds, proportional metaphors being the most popular. Aristotle gives various instances of metaphor. CHAPTER XL Vividness of representation shows a thing in a state of activity. It may be illustrated by Homer's treatment of inanimate objects as animate. Metaphors should be derived from objects which are closely related to the thing itself, but which are not immediately obvious. Another instrument of clever sayings is surprise or deception {irapa Trpoa-BoKiau), as it gives people the sense of having learnt something. Hence too the pleasure of good apophthegms, riddles, and puns. A proper enunciation is requisite in all such sayings. But their chief merit is their appropriateness to the things described. I I I Metaphor, especially proportional metaphor, antithesis, pari- sosis and vividness are all means of giving point to a sentence ; and the larger the number of these means, the more cleverly pointed the sentence appears. Similes, as has been said, are always in a sense popular meta- phors. Proverbs are metaphors from one species to another. Hyperboles of an approved kind are also metaphors.— There is however a character of juvenility in hyperboles. CHAPTER XIL Every kind of Rhetoric has its own appropriate style. There is a difference between the literary {ypacfiiKij) and contro- versial (ayayviariKij) styles and in the controversial style between the political {drffirjyopiKij) and forensic {8iKaviKrj). But the rhetorician should be familiar with both. It is the literary style which is the most finished and the con- troversial which is the best suited to declamation. Controversial oratory is (1) ethical, (2) emotional. Hence such artifices as the use of asyndeton and the repetition of the same word, although alien from the literary style, are favourites among controversial orators. The style of political oratory resembles scene-painting, for as the view is more distant, where the crowd is greater, a finished style becomes inappropriate. The style of forensic oratory, especially when addressed to a single judge, is most finished. The epideictic style is best suited to literary purposes. CHAPTER XIIL A speech has two parts. It is necessary first to state the case and then to prove it. The exposition of the case and the proof— these are the only indispensable parts of a speech. But if more parts are added, they must not exceed four, viz. exordium, exposition, proof and peroration. xliv ANALYSIS. CHAPTER XIV. The exordium {npooiynov). The exordium of a speech corresponds to a prologue in poetry and to a prelude m a musical performance. The sources of exordia in epideictie speeches are eulo-y censure, exhortation, dissuasion and appeals to the au.lience ^ihe exordia of forensic speeches resemble the proems of epic The exordia of epideictie speeches resemble the proems of dithyrambic poetry. The essential function of the exordium is to explain the end or object of tlie speech itself. ' Exordia of other kinds, whether derived from the speaker hunself or from the audience or from the subject or from Urn adversary, are merely the means of remedying certain defecU in !orrui.f "''' ' ""'^'^ ""' ^ "^''' '^ "'^ '">'1'«'«='= »'=™ not nf Jl'Tf "^ T'""^ ''"''''"°" '^''"'8« «^"»"y t» a" tho parts of a speech, perhaps to other parts rather than to the exordium. m^!.» f *"•!' "PP^-'P™'" t» «'e exordium may all bo used as means^of oxcfng attention. Ko means however is so effective as In the exordia of epideictie speeches the audience should bo led to fancy themselves participators. CHAPTER XV. Calumny or prejudice (8ia/3oX,{). create.'!,!.' 1*°""'^*"' '^^ "'^'' "''•* '^« "^'f"' as means of creatmg or dissipating prejudice. CHAPTER XVI. Narrative (S.ijy^ff.t). (1) In epideictie speeches the narrative should bo not con- tinuous but fnigmentary. But if the facU are notorio; U U ANALYSIS. xl proper merely to recall them to the memory of the audience ; there is no need to dwell upon them. (2) In regard to forensic speeches it is absurd to lay down the rule that the narratire should always be rapid. Here too it is proper to observe the rule of the mean. The orator may slip into his narrative anything which tends either to prove his own virtue or to gratify the jury. On the side of the defence the narrative part of the speech may be abbreviated, as the facts upon which it turns are already known. But the narrative should be ethical ; and it will be ethical (a) if it indicates a moral purpose, {b) if it contains such characteristic marks as accompany particular characters, (c) if it seems to proceed not from policy but from the heart It is possible to derive topics from emotional signs by de- scribing the familiar features of emotion. N.B. The narrative should be distributed over the speech. (3) In political speeches, as referring to the future, there is the least room for narration. It can be introduced only because a knowledge of the paat facilitates a judgment of the future. CHAPTER XVIL Proofs (Tr/oTf if). The proofs should be demonstrative {anoheiKriKai). In forensic speeches, as there are four points on which the issue may turn, viz. the fact, the injury, the magnitude of the injury or the criminality the proof should be directed to the particular point at issue. In epideictie speeches the facts must be generally taken on trust, and amplification {av^rja-is) used to emphasize their moral or utilitarian character. In political speeches it must be urged that the policy of one's adversary is impossible or unjust or inexpedient or that it will not have the important results which he anticipates. xlvi ANALYSIS. * Examples are especially appropriate to political Rhetoric. Enthy memos are especially appropriate to forensic Rhetoric. The enthymemes, which should be chosen with discrimination, should not be put forward in a continuous series, but intermingled with various other topics. Enthymemes are out of place in the pathetic or ethical passages of a speech. Maxims, as possessing an ethical character, should be used both in narrative and in proof. Pohtical Rhetoric is more diflBcult than forensic, as it relates to the future, and the future cannot be known; nor does it equally allow of digressions or appeals to the emotions. In epideictic speeches eulogies should be introduced by way of episodes. In default of proofs the speech should be both ethical and demonstrative ; in default of enthymemes it should be exclusively ethical. Refutative enthymemes are more popular than demonstrative. The reply to the adversary is not a separate branch of the speech. The arrangement of the speech will vary according to circum- stances. In deliberative and forensic Rhetoric, if you speak first, you should begin with a statement of your own proofs and then meet the arguments on the other side. (But if the case on the other side is of a varied character, you should begin by meeting the opposing arguments and then make your own statement.) If you speak last, you should begin with the answer to the argu- ments on the other side. As to character, things which would be invidious or tedious, if you said them of yourself, or which would be calunmious or coarse, if you said them of others, may be conveniently put into the mouth of a third person. Enthymemes should sometimes, by a change of form, be expressed as maxims. ANALYSIS. xlvii CHAPTER XVIIL (1) Interrogation (epaJnyo-ty). The interrogation of one's adversary is a device which may be opportunely used as a means of landing him in an absurdity or contradiction. (2) Reply {djroKpia-is). In replying to ambiguous questions it is proper to proceed by distinction or definition, and not to use too concise a mode of expression. Where the adversary's conclusion is put in the form of a question, the reply to the question should be made at once. (3) Jokes {to yeXoia). It is necessary that they should be such as are suited to gentlemen. N.B. Irony (elpapfla) is more gentlemanly (iXevdepKorepov) than buffoonery (/Sw/ioXox/a), as the former is used simply for its \)\m sake and the latter for some ulterior object. CHAPTER XIX. The peroration (cViXoyoy). There are four elements of the peroration, viz. (1) to inspire the audience with a favourable opinion of oneself and an unfavourable opinion of one's adversary, (2) to amplify or depreciate the subject, (3) to excite the emotions of the audience, (4) to recall the facts to their memory. In the recapitulation it is a good rule to repeat the points several times for the sake of intelligibility. Comparison, irony, interrogation are all suitable elements of recapitulation. An asyndeton forms an appropriate conclusion. ■\ i^a-sUju ^y C^jyv-w^ . 336 -330 r? c . THE EHETOEIC OF ARISTOTLE. Dialectic. I BOOK I. dL"\/ Tiir Tp o^ OS Rhetoric is a counterpart of Dialectic. For both ch.p i wkhrtT™ ''"'' ^"""^ '''''•'""*' ^ ''^» '» ^ sense lES^' within the cognizance of all men, and neither is "'"'""- limited to any definite science. Accordingly we are g;iH±J§S§&^lialectimaaaudaiMoS body essays up to a certain point the criticism and 1 support of a thesis, defence and accusation. It is ) ITk ^^\ T* f ''P'^ ^"^ *•»>« ^'*her without any ^^itt^ f *''■ ^y ^ familiarity which is the result these wavstf/,f ^"''''f'' "' ''''^''''^^ '» ^^^h ''--'^ systematized ./'^ '. """"^^ *^"* ^'^^ ^'"^"^ ^^ ^ ^^^ «^use8 of such success as is attained by familiarity or at random, and such an investigation will be uni- versally admitted to be essentiaUy rfonction of an 3«rt« 'Aristotle's conception of a W^,^ or art is clearly expressed ij 7 W. R. 1 9Sl^- I X A-*-w C^^^yy\^ - / C^ LA <-ptv^t-^' / r Criticism of existing rhetorical handbooks. V >v 1/ ^ 2 THE RHETORIC [}' As it is, the coaipilers of our "'arts" or rhetorical handbooks have supplied but a fragment of an art. For while it is the proofs alone which form the proper subjects of artistic treatment, and everything except the proofs is a mere accessory, they omit all mention of enthymemes^which are the soul of proof, and occupy themselves almost exclusively with such things as lie outside the actual issue. For 'prejudice, compassion, anger and such emotions of the soul have no bearing upon the point at issue; they merely affect the minds of the jury. Our rhetoricians then would not have a word to say, if the practice in all trials were the same as at this moment exists in some few States, especially States which are well ordered ; for it is universally allowed that there ought to be, even if there is not actually, a provision in the laws by which a veto is set upon " travelling out of the record," as e.g. in the Court of Areopagus. There is reason in this practice ; for it is improper to waq> the judg- 1 The connexion between rex^v and al Hx^ai' rau Xoyav can hardly be preserved in translation. It is well known that tc'xvi; in the language of the rhetoricians came to mean (1) Rhetoric, as the supreme art, (2) a rhetorical treatise or handbook. (Dr Thompson's Gorgias of Plato, Introduction, p. v.) The Latin writers ITse ars in much the same sense, e.g. Juvenal Sat. vii. 177, artem scindes Theodori, where see Prof. Mayor's note. 2 Nothing can be clearer than that dia^okjj is here in Aristotle's view a irdeos rrjs ylrvxvs. When Spengel says dia^oKri " non est quidem nddos sed efficit ndBos" he separates it generically from TKfos (compassion) and ofyyij (anger) with which it is joined. Perhaps it has the sense not of 8ia^ak\(iv but of dia^oXXecr^at, and means a " prejudice" or " preconceived hostility." Cp. p. 64, L 6, where opyiy, cTn^pcac/ioff, dia^Xij are described as iroirjfTiKl txBpO'i* *• -»-.-, ~'f- I.] OF ARISTOTLE. 3 ment of a juror by exciting him to anger or jealousy or compassion, as this is like making the rule, which one is going to use, crooked. It is evident too that one who is a party to a l^gal suit has nothing to do except to show that the feet alleged is or is not so, or hW or has not occurred, and that its magnitude or triviality, its justice or injustice, except in cases where the legislator has determined this, is a point which the juror should presumably decide for himself and not learn from the statements of the parties. It is best, we may observe, where the laws Reasons for , , preferring are enacted upon right principles, that everything the autho- should, as far as possible, be determined absolutely laws to the by the laws, and as little as possible left to the dis- particular cretion of the judges. For in the first place it is easier to find an individual or a few than a number of people who are sensible and capable of exercising legislative and judicial functions ; and secondly, while • legislative enactments are the results of mature de- liberation, judicial decisions are given on the spur of the moment, so that it is difficult for the judges in particular cases duly to deliver such a sentence as is just and expedient. But the point of principal im- portance is this ; that, while the legislator's decision is not particular but prospective and universal, the members of the Public Assembly or the Court of Law from the nature of the case decide upon actual definite issues, in which feelings of afiection or ill- will and private interests are necessarily often 4n- ^ Reading a-vvrjpTrfTcu,^ which has the support of the Vetusta Translatio (ad quos...annexa sunt) and agrees better than avvrjpi]- 1—2 7 f THE RHETORIC [t yolved, so that they lose the power of adequately studying the truth, and their judgment is clouded by a consideration of their personal pleasure or pain. It is then, as we say, a general rule that we should limit as far as possible the authority of the judge. But such questions as whether a feet has~or /has not occurred in the past, or will or will not be so / m the future or is or is not so at present, are neces- sarily left to the decision of the judges, as they lie y beyond the prescience of the legislator. This Tieing -the case, it is clear that to lay down definite rules, a» IS sometimes done, upon a number of other points, e.g. upon the proper contents of the exordium, tiie narrative or any other part of a speech, is to make an art of things which are foreign to the issue ; for the authors of such rules have no other object than to produce a certain disposition in the judge, while they give no explanation of the 'artistic proofs, which are the materials of all enthymematic reasoning. . Ae Hence it is that, although the same mode of treat- Jubler" ment is applicable to the oratory of public life and to p^ that of the Law Courts, and the study of political i«u.db«oks. oratory is more elevated and statesmanlike than a study which limits itself to the ordinary dealings of man with man, they disregard political oratory alto- gether and set themselves with one consent to make ra. with Aristotle's usage. (See the Indeu; Arutotelicm of Bonite 8. V. (rvvaprav,) ^ ' Aristotle is scarcely justified in using the expressions at ^PTfXPoi TTtcTTf iff and €uev^ir)t,aTiK6s, as if they would be intelligible at this point of his treatise. It is not until the second chapter that he defines them. p. 11. p. 13. Forensic rhetoric the »._ I.] OF ARISTOTLE. an art of pleading in Court, because it does not pay so well to " travel out of the record " in political questions, and political oratory, as 'involving wider interests, offers fewer opportunities of chicanery. For while in politics, where the judges are personally in- t^reste d in the questio ns whiclTcoinenSeforelhem, all "njaTtlglMlQcaje^ j ^cer^^ do h t o d emonstrate that the^cts are as heane^s Tlg^fer^ ensic cases such a procedurels insufficient,"anariri8 worth while to conciliate the audience. For as they have no personal interest in the decision, they con- sider their own gratification and, as they do not listen to the case impartially, are carried away by the parties instead of judging between them. The result is that there are many places, as we said before, where the p. 2. law forbids all "travelling out of the record." In political matters however the judges themselves look to this sharply enough. Itjs^clearjhe n that iho only pro per subjects of Riet* artistic, treatment are proofs. But proof is a species oFdemonstration ' (for we regard a demonstration as the highest form of proof), and a rhetorical demon- * It seems clear from the following words {ivravBa fiev yap o KpiTTii 7r€p\ olKfloiv Kpivfi) that KoivoTepov Tefcrs to the personal interest of the audience collectively in the subjects of political debate. The jury, who would be the audience in a legal case, would not be personally interested in its result. But it is to be noticed that the iKKXrja-uKrrai as well as the biKaaral are called Kpirai or judges of the arguments addressed to them. 2 The alleged reason is in fact little more than another way of saying ij maris dnodei^is ris ; but it would be more natural to argue that demonsti-ation is a species of proof than that proof is a species of demonstration. ^ma* mAm I'l "il^ ; , .V THE RHETORIC [I. ^ m^i stration takes the form of an enthymeme, which may be^broadlyjleg cribed as the most powerfiiT form of The^enthy. rhetorical^proSr-A^nvffirenlfiynreTiie-ts a species j of syllogism, and it falls within the province of Dia- lectic, either as a whole or in some one of its branches, to make a complete examination of the syllogism in all Its forms. 'From all this it appears that the most competent judge of the materials and con- structive principles of a syllogism will also be the most complete master of enthymemes, if only he is further acquainted with the proper subjects of enthy- II no n 1^1 '"T.f ^^^ '''^^ ^^^ differences between enthymemes " \t^,J^'^'<'%^nd logical syllogisms. For as it is the same faculty which discerns what is true and what resembles truth and as men have a sufficient natural aptitude for truth and m a majority of instances attain it, it tollows that the most sagacious judge of truth will be at the same time the most sagacious judge of .probabilities. Although it is clear then that the matters, which all other writers upon Rhetoric reduce to an art, are irrelevant to the issue, and it is clear why they have inchned by preference to forensic oratory, still Rhe- toric IS not without its value. It is vcdiuible,JirsUy because truth and justice possess a natural superiority ' The Msa reading ^\ou &' Sn may be retained, if the »i .8 regarded as apodotic. It is in Aristotle's manner to build up ^Kfon * '"""'^'' "^ "''"^'' ""' "" ^'*"*''^ "'fl"enciDg the ' The Xoy«ir »gjHml toas high ^ jpoiiiTonh ealth as possible] for even people who can never possibly recover their health may still be scientifically treated. Further, it is evident that it falls within the scope of the same art to di8cenLihe_j:eaLand^^ means of persuasion, as in Dialectic the real and the apparent syllogism. For it is not the faculty but the moral purpose which constitutes the sophistical character. But there is this 'difference between Rhe- torw and Dialectk, that, while in the former the name "rhetorician" is descriptive either of the science or of the moral purpose, there is in the latter the name "sophist" to describe the moral purpose, and '* dialectician" to describe not the purpose but the faculty. But it is now time to endeavour to state the actual system, or in other words the means and materials which will enable us to attain the objects aiy/xioi;py(59 eWti/ ij piyroptK,,', Ka\ ^ Trpayfiareia airfjs ^rraaa Ka\ t6 K€dKaiop «V roCro r«Xfura, p. 453 A. But the definition of Rhetonc as ncidovs 8rjfiiovpy6s is said not to have been Plato's own, but to have descended from Corax and Tisias or Isocrates (Dr Thompson's note ad loc.). 1 The point, which is somewhat obscurely put, seems to be this: There are sophistical rhetoricians as well as sophistical dialecticians ; but while the latter are called by the special name of " sophists," the former, having no special name, are simply called ** rhetoricians." The fallacious branch of Rhetoric. 10 THE RHETORIC [I- illi , I proposed. Let us start afresh then, as it were, and before we proceed, define the actual nature of Rhe- toric itself. iS^r.io" rC^-^*''"*' "^y ^ ^®*"«<* ^ a faculty of discovering ,«{ Ehetori^l the possible means of persuasion in any subje^. >«f this IS exclusively the function of Rhetoric iii p r. every other art, 'whether instructive or persuasive deals with a subject-matter peculiar to itself, Medi- cine e.g. with the conditions of health and disease, Geometry with the properties of magnitudes, Arith- metic with number, and so on through the list of arts and sciences. Rhetoric on the other hand may ^ be said to possess the faculty of discovering the means of persuasion in any given subject ; and ac- cordingly we hold that the rules of the rhetorical art arc not limited in their application to a certain jspecial definite class of subjects. Rhetorical proofs are either artistic or inartistic By "inartistic proofs" I mean all such as are SoT provided by our own skill but existed before and independently, e.g. witnesses, tortures, contracts and the like; by "artistic," such as admit of being con- structed systematically and by our own skill- in fine the former we have^only to apply and the latter we have to invent "The proofs provided through the instrumentality ' The distinction between arts as "instructive" or "persuasive " i.e. in other words as exact or inexact, depends upon the special sense in which Aristotle uses " instruction." See note on ch i Cp. Plato Gorgim, p. 455 a, o^' Spa &«a«aX«« 6 p^T,op .Vri a«<.. Kal dSU,ou, aXXA n€l Suction of a certain disposition in the audience or J- / •^ i n the speecli itseit by mea ns of real or apparen t demonstration. The instrument of proof is the moral character, when the delivery of the speech is such \i^ as to produce an impression of the speaker's credi- bility; for we yield a more complete and ready credence to persons of high character not only ordi- narily and in a genei*al way, but in such matters as do not admit of absolute certainty but necessarily leave room for difference of opinion, without any qualification whatever. (It Js_i2quisitehoweyer_^^ this result should itself be attalnednBy^neans of the speecITand not of any antecedent conception of the speaker's character.) For so far from following the example of some authors of rhetorical handbooks, who in their "art" of Rhetoric regard the high character of the speaker as not being itself in any sense contributory to his persuasiveness, we may practically lay it down as a geneml rule that-there is no proof so effectiveasjthat of the ch aract^er. Secondty, proof may be conveyed through the au- dience, when it is worked up by the speech to an emotional state. For there is a wide difference in our manner of pronouncing decisions, according as we feel pleasure or pain, affection or hatred ; and indeed thev^3j:^ii^--4^f.JiSm]^^!}^ W^*^ ^^^ ^'motiom is, as we p 2 assert, the one end oF object to which our present professors of the rhetorical art endeavour to direct their studies. This is a part of the subject which will be elucidated in detail, when we come to discuss // f> \ 12 THE RHETORIC [l. y the emotions. Lastly, Hhe instrument of proof is /I the speech itself, when we have proved a truth or M an * apparent truth from such means of persuasion 1 as are appropriate to a particular subject quaiifica- Such being then the channels of rhetorical proofs, rhetorician, it is evident that no one can make himself master of airtliree, unless he is competent to reason logically, to^^flJlEuman^characters and virtues, and thirdly to study the natureancTquality of the several emotions, the sourcesTrom which th^~8pring and the metliods Relation of of cxcitiug them. It follows that Rhetoric is, so to Rhetonc to ^ o -r^* ^ * i » SidE^iT say, an oiishoot of Dialectic on the otie hand and ^ ' on the other of the study of Ethics ^ which may fairly be described as political. Hence it is that Rhetoric and its professors assume the mask of Politics, whether from ignorance or imposture or any other human infirmity. For it is really a branch or copy of Dialectic, as we said at the outset, neither being a science which deals with the constitution of any definite subject-matter, but both being mere faculties of supplying arguments. Enough has perhaps been said as to the faculty and mutual relations of Rhetoric and Dialectic. But taking the proofs conveyed by real or ap- parent demonstration, we find that^ as in Dia- * Omitting marfvovaiv. ^ There is no need to insert dXrjdfi after (f>aiv6n€voif as in Bekker's text ; see e.g. p. 25, 1. 22 dyae6v ^ fniCovy p. 37, 1. 13 rau Xxmrjpav r) (f)aivo^€P(ov. 3 The view of Politics as the architectonic science, embracing Ethics as a subordinate or ancillary science, is expomided in Nicom. Eth. i. ch. 1. p. 1. ) I-J OF ARISTOTLE. 13 lectics there are three modes of proof, viz. induction, syllogism and apparent syllogism, so in Rhetoric there is the example corresponding to induction, the Example enthymeme to syllogism and the apparent enthymeme meme. to apparent syllogism. I call an enthymeme a rhe- torical syllogism and an example a rhetorical in- duction. Thejiniv£i:sal4tteaQa..o£^iemon strative proof in Rliet oric are examples or enthymem es, and there is no other; hence if it is assumed tolBe absolutely necessary that ^ whatever is proved should be proved either by syllogism or by induction — and this we see clearly from the * Analytics — it is a necessary con- clusion that the enthymeme and example are respec- tively identical with the syllogism and induction. The difference between example and enthymeme on tJie one hand and induction and syllogism on the other is clear from the ^Topics, For as syllogism and induction have been already discussed, it is clear ^ The words fj otn-ivovv are rightly omitted in Bekker after oTiovv ; they are at best, I think, nothing more than a marginal note, showing that either onovv or ovrivovv would make good sense. 2 There are several passages of the Analyticft which may have been in Aristotle's mind, as Mr Cope says (Introduction, p. 153) ; perhaps the clearest is Analyt. Pri. ii. ch. 23, p. 68 Bg_i4. 3 The meaning, as Mr Cope saw, should be not so much that tlie difference is stated in the ToniKo. as that it may be inferred from the definitions of syllogism and induction given in the Toitlko. A syllogism is there defined as Xoyo? h a r^divrav nvav erepov Ti rav K€ifX€va}if €^ avayKTjs (rvfi^aivfi 8ia rav K(tn€va>v, Bk i. ch. 1, p. 100 A25; an induction as »; dn6 tu)V Kaff eKaarov eVi ra KadoKov €oiosy Bk i. ch. 12, p. 105 a^^. But the passage remains obscure, unless €Kfi is altered to (ntl, and avfp6v supplied before ort to fA€v eVt iroWav koi ofioitov deiKwadai on ovras tx€i. -«M* - ^ — i, . 14 THE RHETORIC [I. that the proving of a rule in a number of similar instances is an induction in Dialectic and an example m Rhetoric, while the conclusion from certain pre- misses that something else which is different from them results as a consequence of them by reason of their being what they are, whether universally or generally, is caUed a syllogism in Dialectic and an enthymeme in Rhetoric. It is clear that there IS an advantage in either kind of Rhetoria For the remark which has been made in the 'Methodics is not less applicable here ; there are some rhetorical efforts in which the example and others in which the enthymeme predominates, and rhetoricians are similarly distinguishable by a predilection for the one or the other. It may be added that speeches which make use of examples are fully as persuasive as the others, but enthymematic speeches are more applauded. The sources of examples and enthy- memes and the proper uses of them both w^T^^" stateniereafter. Let us now however define more explicitly these logical processes themselves. 'Persuasiveness then is a relative conception, and a fact 18 persuasive and credible either immediately and in its own strength or as seeming to be proved Theiimita- by facts which are persuasive and credible. But no • Rhetoric, art takcs particular cases into consideration. Thus ' A logical treatise of Aristotle, now lost. M have broken up the long protasis of the sentence : for the conck8.on oiiij fi^op^ rt, .aff «a<^„. |.8„|,, e..f,^.,. follows not from all the three preceding clauses, but, as Mr Cope says, from the third only, or perhaps more accurately from the first and third. D- I.] OF ARISTOTLE. 15 Medicine does not consider what is wholesome to Socrates or Callias as individuals but what is whole- some to a person or persons of a certain constitution ; for it is this generalization which is characteristic of an art, whereas particulars are infinite in number and cannot be known. Similarly Rhetoric will not in- vestigate what is probable to each individual, as e.g. to Socrates or Hippias, but what is probable to persons of a certain character ; and the same is true of Dialectic. Both are pra^ticcdly limited in respect of tJie subjects with ivhich they deal. For Dialectic no less than Rhetoric does not employ any and all opinions indiscriminately as materials of syllogisms (for even people who are out of their minds have certain fancies) ; but the materials of Dialectic are such sub- jects as need discussion, and those of Rhe toric are the ordinary and recognized subjects of deliberation. The function of Rhetoric is limited to matters about which we deliberate *and do not possess artistic rules for our guidance in determining them, and the audience to which it addresses itself consists of per- 1' sons wlio are nnaVJp fn pnmpvAhArifi a uumbcr or arguments in asin gle view or to follow ou t a long] ^ain of reaioningr Now the proper subjects of de- liberation are such as appear to admit of two possi- bilities; for if things cannot possibly either have happened or happen or be otherwise than in one par- ticidar way, nobody deliberates about them, at least upon that supposition, i,e, so long as he regards them as absolutely certain; for what would be the advan- ^ The rules of medicine, e.g., would not be the proper subjects ^ of rhetorical argument. - — — . ' ^ i» *1L — — ^ / - % *- V v_^ 'C- VJS. ._ V-A^'V,^^ ' V—- •~" ■" ^~>* — 0^ cy-iA - '^«-trl '*~.#.~^' I. 16 THE RHETORIC [l. tage of deliberation ? (But the materials of syllogistic and inferential reasoning may be either the actual conclusions of previous syllogisms or propositions which have not been syllogistically proved and at the same time need such proof, as lacking probability. \o ^ Syllogisms of the first class will be necessarily diflScult to follow from their length, as the judge is assumed to be a simple sort of person ; and those of the second class will fail to carry conviction, as the premisses on which they rest are neither practically admitted Inor intrinsically probable.) *We conclude then that the enthymeme and example are necessarily applied to such things as are in general indeterminate; the T^eenthy- example being an induction and the enthymeme a syllogism, with its constituent parts only few and generally fewer than those of the * primary or normal syllogism ; for if one of them is well known, it need not be stated, as the audience supplies it of its own accord. If we wish e.g. to prove that Dorieus has been victorious in a contest in which the prize of victory is a crown, it is enough to say that he has won an Olympic victory ; there is no need to add that the prize of an Olympic contest is a crown, as the fact is universally known. * The conclusion is not justified by the sentences which im- mediately precede it, but follows as a natural consequence from 11« 4 — 6, ^vXevofifOa de ntpi rav aivofi€vv a-vWoyiafiav. 2 Omitting tovs uKpoaras. r i OF ARISTOTLE. 21 Thus there are propositions in physics from which it is impossible to form an enthymeme or syllogism upon ethics, ethical propositions again from which it is impossible to form an enthymeme or syllogism upon physics, and so on through the whole range of subjects. The general topics, as having no special subject-matter, will not convey a practical knowledge of any class of subjects. But in regard to the special topics it may be remarked tJud, in proportion as a rhetorician is specially skilful in the choice of his propositions, he will imperceptibly construct a science different from Dialectic and Rhetoric ; for if he lights upon first principles, i,e, the principles or axioms of the special seienceSy it will cease to be Dialectic or Rhetoric and will be the science to which the prin- ciples in question belong. The materials of enthy- memes however are in the great majority of cases the particular and private topics, comparatively seldom the common ones. Accordingly here as well as in the Topics it is necessary to draw a distinction be- tween the special and general topics from which enthymemes may be derived. I mean by special topics such propositions as are proper to a particular class of subjects, and by general topics such as are common to all alike. We will begin then with a discussion of the special topics. But let us first ascertain the different kinds of Rhetoric, that after determining their number we may ascertain the * elements and propositions of each separately. * What is meant by an "element" {(rroixfiov) of Rhetoric is clear from il ch. 22, where Aristotle says (rroixelov Se Xcyw koi ^■* 1/ \ Chap. III. The three kinds of Rhetoric. The subdi- visions of each. 22 THE RHETORIC [l. There are three kinds of Rhetoric, corresponding to the three kinds of audience to which speeches are naturally addressed. For a speech is composed of three ele ments, viz. tlTe^ speaker ^ic a ub iect of the sp PecIPa n d the persons ad 4feaaed^_aB d the end or hject oL lhe speech is det ermined by the last, viz. the audience. Audiences"^afe~Tiecessarily either [cities or judges ; and if the latter, they may be judges ^f things lying either in the past or in the future, member of the Public Assembly may be taken LS an instance of a judge of the future, a member of the Courts of Law as an instance of a judge of the )ast; while one who judges merely of the ability lisplayed in a speech is the critic. It follows that there must necessarily be three kinds of rhetorical speeches, the deliberative, the forensic and the *epi- deictic. Deliberative Rhetoric is partly hortatory and partly dissuasive ; for people who counsel their friends delibe- ratively on private affairs and people who address popular meetings on matters of State are alike in this, that they always exhort or dissuade. Forensic Rhetoric may be divided into accusation and defence ; for the parties to any legal action necessarily adopt either one or other of these lines. To the epideictic Torrou €vBvfjii^^jLaTos rb avro, p. 95, 1. 26. The term itself is discussed by Mr Cope, Introd. pp. 127, 128. ^ The difference, as appears in the next sentence, is that the "critic" regards a speech merely as an intellectual effort, the " j^&® " *^ ^" argument in which he is personally interested. / 2 As (TTidfi^is is a set rhetorical display, so epideictic oratory ( is the oratory of display. I.] OF ARISTOTLE. 23 orator belong eulogy and censure. Again, there are Their times. times belonging to the several kinds of Rhetoric ; to deliberative Rhetoric the future, as deliberative counsel, whether hortatory or dissuasive, has reference to things which lie in the future; to forensic Rhetoric the past, as the subject of accusation or defence is always something which has been already done ; and to epideictic Rhetoric most properly the present, as it is always existing facts which form the grounds of eulogy or censure, although epideictic orators often amplj^L-lheir Resources , by appe aling to the past in the way of reminiscence and to the future in the wsL^ of anticipation. There are three ends too appro- Their ends. priate respectively to the three kinds of Rhetoric. The end which the deliberative orator has in view is expediency or injury ; for iTTie exhorts to a parti - ^cular line of action, he recommends it as being better, i.e, more advantageous, iFhe dissuades from it, he does^soonlihe ground that it is worse, and every other consideratipu^-whetlier justice or injustice, honour or disgrace, he embraces merely as something secondary and subservient to this. The end of the parties to a legal action or in otlier words of forensic oro^org is justice and injustice ; an djf they too intro- duce other considerations, it is always as subordinate to these. Orators of the panegyrical and depreciatory style take honour andT^disgraceas their end and again refer all other considerations to these. As a sign that the end of Rh c torio is ig each case such as we have stated, it may be noticed that an orator will sometimes forbear to argue any point in the case except this one. Thus a person who is a party to MiXHU II [ I r 24 THE RHETORIC [l. a legal suit will sometimes not care to contend that the action with which he is charged has not occurred or that it did no damage ; but the injustice or criminality of the action he will never for a moment allow, as, if he did, there would be no need of a suit at all. Similarly deliberative speakers, while they frequently abandon every other point, will never admit that the course which they recommend is inexpedient or that the course from which they dis- suade is advantageous ; but the injustice of reducing their neighbours, even if absolutely unoifending, to slavery is often a point about which they do not trouble themselves in the least. So too in eulogy or depreciation the speakers, instead of considering the expediency or hurtfulness of a person's actions, often go so far as to reckon it meritorious that he did some noble deed at the sacrifice of his own interest, as when they eulogize Achilles for having avenged his friend Patroclus, although he knew he must perish and he might have saved his life, if he had chosen. But in this case, although it was more honourable so to die, yet his personal interest was to live. The propo- The remarks we have made clearly show that these, sitions in- . j • • • » dispensable VIZ, expediency, justice, honour and their opjwsites, to a rhe- . , i • i i 1.1 torician. are the subjects about which propositions are primarily indispensable to the rhetorician. By rh etorical pro- positions I ^ nean demonstra tio ns^ p rogggTTfjpfl^^^l ^^signs. For a syllogism consists of proposition^TanJ the"^nthymeme is a syllogism composed of the pro- positions described, viz. demonstrations, prohahiUties and signs. Again, as things which are impossible f . 4 I.] OF ARISTOTLE. 25 cannot have been done in the past or be done in the future, and tilings which have not occurred or will not occur cannot have been done or be done hereafter, it is indispensable that the rhetorician, whether deliberative, forensic or epideictic, should be master of certain propositions as to possibility and impossibility and as to the occurrence or non- occuiTcnce of events in the past or in the future. And further, as all speakers, whether in eulogy or depre- ciation, exhortation or dissuasion, accusation or de- fence, are not contented with trying to prove the points I have mentioned, but try also to prove the greatness or smallness of the good or evil, the honour or disgrace, the justice or injustice which is the sid)ject of their speech, either absolutely or in com- parison with something else, it will clearly be necessary to be supplied with propositions respecting greatness and smallness both absolute and comparative, whether universally or in reference to particular cases, as e.g. to the greater or less of two good things or of two actions either just or unjust ; and the same is tine of every other subject. So much then for the subjects in regard to which it is right that the rhetorician should acquire his propositions. We must now proceed to distinguish them individually, ije. to distinguish the proper sub- jects of deliberative, of epideictic, and in the third place of legal oratory. The first step is to ascertain the character of the f chap, rv!" good or bad things in regard to which the delibe- t??e^5i rative orator gives his counsel. For he does not xltuVe of concern himself with all things which are good qj. ^^^ ^^^^J®*'*^ ( 1/ 26 THE RHETORIC I, " ■«•' p. 12. [I- bad, but only with such as either may or may not come to pass; whereas, if a thing either is or will be necessarily or cannot possibly be or come to pass, it is not a proper subject of deliberative counsel. Nor again does he concern himself with all things which either may or may not come to pass ; for there are some good things of the kind which are the gifts of Nature or the results of chance, and about these it is entirely useless to offer counsel. It is clear that his subjects are all such things as are possible matters of deliberation, i.e. all things which are naturally referred to our own agency and * whose production depends in the fii-st instance on our own will. For we always carry back our investigations to the point of discovering whether the act in question is or is not within our power. Now any attempt at an exact and particular enu- meration and classification of the ordinary subjects of public business and at an accurate definition of them, so far as such is possible, would be inappropriate on the present occasion ; for such a task belongs not so much to the rhetorical art as to an art of a more intellectual and authentic character, and a gi-eat deal more has already 'been assigned to Rhetoric than its own proper subjects of investigation. For 1 For the meaning of the phrase ^ dpx^ r^s ycveVf wf c'<^* ^f^lp eWtV, see Metaphysics vi. ch. 8, p. 1033 A24 eVfi bt <>n6 rti^dy tc yiyvtrai, to yiyv6fi€i;ov (roOro Sf Xtyta odtv )) dpxri rrjs y€V€a((ag eVrt) K,r.\. 2 Aristotle is alluding to the practice of preceding writers on Rhetoric. See marginal reference. As Rhetoric is there said to be an oflfshoot of Dialectic and Ethics, it is clear that " the analy- tical science " must be Dialectic. See Mr Cope's note ad loc. ► ♦ I.] OF ARISTOTLE. 27 the truth is, as indeed we have already remarked, that Rlu^tauc-is_compQsed_of the analytical science and of the ethical brancholTolitics and bears a certain resemblance to Dialectic on the one hand an'd'to'the sophistical arguments on the other. But the— more one attenapt* to set either Dialectic or Rhetoric on the footing of sciences rather than of simple faculties, the more will one imperceptibly ob- literate their nature Jjy tmnsgressing their jyroper limits in the reconstructive process and passing from a science of mere words to sciences of certain definite subject-matters. Still so far as an analysis of tJie subjects of public business has a practical value mid is 2)ossihle without encroachment upon the studies proper to political science, it is one upon which we may now proceed to enter. The most important subjects of general delibe- The five ration and deliberative oi*atory are practically five, subjects of . _ _ 1 , o « , deiiberar VIZ. finance, war and peace, the defence of the country, tion. imports and exports, and legislation. Thus to speak (i) Finance. in the first instance of finance: one who aspires to be a deliberative or political speaker will need to be acquainted with the nature and number of the resources of the State, so that anv resource which is neglected may be added to them and any which is defective may be increased, as well as with all the items of the public expenditure, so that what- ever is superfluous may be abolished and whatever is excessive may be cut down ; for it is possible to en- rich a State not only by adding to its resources but also by curtailing its expenses. But it is not only from experience at home that a comprehensive view -J-* (2) War and peace. '*] li / I I li 28 THE KHETORIC [l. of these questions maybe derived; it is indispensable, if one is to deliberate and advise respecting them, that he should be equally familiar with the discoveries made in other lands. Under the head of war and peace he must know the strength and character of the existing military force in the State and of the force which can be called into existence, also the wars in which the State has been engaged and its success or failure in them. Nor must his knowledge of these points be limited to his own State ; it must extend to neighbouring countries ^ or even to all covntrles with which there is a prospect of war, his object being to conclude a peace with the superior powers and to have the option of fighting or not with the inferior. He must know too whether the forces of the States are similar or dissimilar, as this is a point in which one may have an advantage or disadvantage as compared with the other. With the same view it is necessary that he should have studied the issues of the wars not only of his own State but of other States as well; for similar causes naturally (8) Means producc similar results. Nor again should he be ^^nce. jg^Qj^^^^ ^f ^Y^Q means of defence possessed by his country ; he should know the strength and character of its defensive force and the sites of its fortresses (which is impossible without a practical knowledge of the country) in order to strengthen the force, if it is inadequate, or to abolish any part of it, if superfluous, and to concentrate the attention of the ^ It seems best to place only a comma after ftSfvai, so that the sentence, if fully expressed, would run r«i/ o/xopcav ravra dvayKoiov flbevaij fj koi itavnov npbs ovs eirido^ov nokffulv. I.] OF ARISTOTLE. 29 citizens upon the most favourable localities. In re- gard to the question of supplies, the deliberative (*) sup- orator ought to understand the total expenditure which is adequate for the State, the nature of the supplies produced at home and imported from abroad and the requisite exports and imports, with the view of making conventions and commercial treaties with the exporting and importing countries. For there are two classes of persons in regard to whom it is neces- sary that the citizens should always be kept clear of offence, viz. those who are superior in military strength and those who control the supplies. But while it is necessary, as a means of safety, that our orator should be a competent observer of all the points we have described, it is especially necessary that he should understand legislation. For as the safety of (s) Legisia- the State depends upon its laws, he must know all the different kinds of polities, the nature of the measures beneficial to each and the natural causes of its destruction whether inherent in the polity itself or antagonistic to it *When I speak of the destruction of a polity by causes which are inherent in itself I mean that all polities, except the ideally best polity, are liable to destruction either by relaxation or by intensi- fication ; a democracy e.g. is not only enfeebled by relaxation so as to issue actually in an oligarchy but may he destroyed also by a marked intensification, ^ There is a passage of the Politics so closely resembling this, even in the illustration drawn from the characteristics of the nose, that the two should be read side by side. It is viii(v) ch. 9, and will be found on pp. 377 — 379 of my Translation. } b \ Chap. V. The object of human actions. 1! 30 THE RHETORIC [l. in the same way as not only does the aquiline or snub character of a nose become regular by relaxation, but, if the nose becomes excessively aquiline or snub, it acquires such a shape that it ceases to look like a nose at all. It is useful too for legislative purposes not only to understand the nature of the proper polity by a study of the past but to be familiar with the polities of other countries and to know the particular polities suitable to particular peoples. It is clear then that fi'om a legislative point of view there is a value in the accounts of travels round the world, as from them we may learn the laws and customs of foreign nations, and from the point of view of political counsel there is a value in historical compositions, although all this is the province of Politics rather than of Rhetoric. These then are all the principal topics which the deliberative or political orator should ' understand. But the proper materials of exhortation or dissuasion upon these or upon any other topics remain to be discussed ; and the discussion of them will be a fresh branch of our inquiry ^ It may be said that all men both individually and collectively have a certain object at which they 1 I can hardly believe in the absolute use of exciy, without an object or with ras TrpoTao-ets to be mentally supplied. Nor does Spengel's Xiyav commend itself as an emendation. Is it possible that the true reading is Trcpi Stv \i.kv ow vovv tx^'-^ ^*^ "^^^ y.fK\ovTa poin](riv avhpLav SiKaioavvrjv v(Tiv, rare ovk dnb Tvxrjs dWa fiaWov diro TavTOfidrov yeyov€vai (t)afjL(Vy {\im\^v faculties are productive of good. Natural gifts again, * memory, aptness to learn, sharpness of wit and the like, all these faculties being productive of what is good. Similarly, all sciences and arts and life itself; for life if unattended by any other good is yet intrin- sically desirable. And lastly, justice as tending to promote the interest of the community at large. This is a fairly exhaustive catalogue of such things as are generally admitted to be good. There are other goods of a disputable kind, and in regard to these the materials of syllogism will be as fol- lows. A thing is good if its opposite is evil. Or if its opposite is advantageous to our enemies ; as if it is of high advantage to our enemies that we should be cowards, it is clear that valour is highly beneficial to our country. It is in fact a general rule that, whatever our enemies desire or rejoice at, tlie opposite of this is clearly beneficial to ourselves. Hence the point of the lines "Sure ''Priam would rejoice," &c. But this is only a general and not an invariable rule ; for there is no absolute reason why our own interest should not in some instances coincide with ^ Reading fiw;'^?;, with Spengel. 2 The passage referred to is the beginning of the speech in which Nestor tries to reconcile Achilles and Agamemnon. Iliad, i. 255 sqq. T) K€v yrjdfjo'ai npta/ioy, Upiafxoio re Trat^fff, aXXoi re TpcScf fJieya k€v Kf)(apoiaTo Bvyiuty (I (T(oiv rabf irdvra nvdoiaro ytapvayitvouv. OF ARISTOTLE. 43 that of our enemies. Hence the saying "Misery acquaints a man with strange bedfellows," when the same danger threatens two people. Again, 'if a thing is not in excess, it is a good ; but if there is more than tlie proper amount of it, it is an evil. It is a good too, if it is a thing for which a great deal of trouble or expense has been incurred ; for it is proved thereby to be an apparent good, and an apparent good is assumed to be an end and not only so but an end of various actions, and an end is ex hyx)othesi a good. Hence ^ the lines heginning "Yea, after Priam's heart" and "'Twere shame to tarry long" and Hhe proverb "to break the pitcher at the door." ^ It seems from the coiTespondence of the clauses ov prj itrriv virfp^oXij and o 8* av ^ fi^iC^v ff dtl that the former means not "that which does not admit of excess" but rather "that which is not in excess," 2 Both quotations are from the Second Book of the Iliady w. 176 and 298. The point lies not in the mere words quoted but in the context. In the first passage Athene is speaking of the noble lives sacrificed for Helen's sake. Ka8 Se K€V cv)^a)\rjp Tlpiafico Kai Tpoxri XiTroire ^Apyeirjv 'EXfvrjVj ijs (IvtKa ttoXXoi *A;^aio3i/ fv Tpoirj airokovTOy (fyiXrjs dno TrarpiBos atijs. In the second it is Odysseus who speaks Tjfiiv d eivaros eari nepiTporrdoyp iviavroi (vOdbf p.ip.v6vT€(r itself It fo lows then that the lai^er number of things is a greater good than a single thing or than the smaller mimber be reckoned as part of the larger ; for then tAe larger number is in excess of tfJsrrUlerXd that which IS included in the larger is exceeded by exc^J'J'h'Jf''^ 'T'* T"^^' ''^''''' ^^'^ «/«*%« exceeds the largest member of another, then the firet :^"::o:,"" rr = ^"^^ '^'^^^-'^^' '^ --^ exceeds another, the largest member of the fii-st ex- ceeds the largest member of the second. Thus if the tallest man is taller than the tallest woman so are men generally taller than women, and if me^ 're taller than the tallest woman ; for the excess of one dass over another is proportional to the excess of the greatest member of the one over the greatest member B isTJ "• ^f "' '' ^ '^ ^«"«^"-t -Po» B bu tluL A T~t consequent upon A, B is greater tlmn A, whether the consequence is simultaneous or subsequent or potential'; for then the use of the consequent A is involved in the use of B. (Life tione,r;. 2«Tr'" " * "''^' "'^ "' ^""^^ \ it would never have been executed, if he had not de- vised it, whereas in his accusation of Chabrias he argued that he who executed it was a greater crimi- nal than he who advised it, on the ground that it would never have taken eflFect without somebody to execute it, as it is the execution which is the object of any conspiracy. Again, that which is rarer is greater or more valuable than that which is plen- teous, e.g. gold than iron, although it is not so use- ful ; for the acquisition of it, as being more difficidt is something greater. But there is another sense in which what is plenteous is greater than what is rare as being more abundantly useful ; for frequency of use is superior to rarity, whence the saying '"The best of things is water." It is in fact a general rule that the more difficult of two things, as being the rarer, is gi-eater than the easier, although in another sense the easier, as gratifying our Avishes, may be said to be greater than the more difficult. Again, a thing is greater, if its opposite is greater, or if the depriva- tion of it is greater. ^ virtue is greater than non- virtue, vice than non-vice; for virtue and vice are, and the others are not, ends or complete states. Again if the functions of things are nobler or baser, they are themselves greater. Or if the >ices and virtues of things are greater, so are their functions, as results 1 Pindar, Olympians, i. 1. '^Rhetoric, as Aristotle says, p. 4, 1. 13, r^vavria avW^i^rai, and the supcnonty of virtue to non-virtue or of vice to non-vice i.e. of the positive or complete state to the negative or incomplete IS only, as it were, a rhetorical thesis in which the moral point of view IS disregarded. OF ARISTOTLE. 51 f ■■] correspond with their causes or originating principles and vixie versa. Things are greater too, if superiority in them is more desirable or nobler ; and 'conversely, if tilings are themselves better and nobler, the ex- cesses of them are also better and nobler. Thus keen- ness of sight is more desirable than keenness of smell, as sight itself is more desirable than smell ; and as it is nobler to be excessively fond of friends than to be ex- cessively fond of money, the love of friends is itself nobler than that of money. Again, the objects of the nobler or better desires are nobler or better ; for the greater impulses are directed to greater ends. So too the desires of nobler and better objects are for the same reason themselves nobler and better. Or if the science which deals with particular subjects is nobler and more moral, so are the subjects ; for as is the sci- ence, so is the truth at tvhlch it airas, and every science is supreme in its own province. Similarly the higher and more moral the subjects, the sciences which deal with them are proportionately more moral and nobler for the same reason. Again, that which would be decided or has been decided by sagacious people, whether by all or almost all or the majority or the ablest of them, to be a good or tlie greater of two goods, must necessarily be such, either absolutely or in so far as their decision was the result of their sagacity. This is a rule which is applicable to every- thing else as well as to goods ; for the nature, quantity and quality of things are always such as science and sagacity would pronounce. But it is only in respect * I cannot doubt that the words Koi aim.K€iixiv(os hi...pea\v olp.ai iravToias cVe^vo-fi/' eoi/ca Be roi Trapafideiv woTf ^fw" Tw fxi; /i€ XiXaifo bfiporofifjaai. 3 It is well known that this famous simile, which is quoted again p. 127, 1. 22, is not found in the funeral oration which Thucydides (Bk. ii. ch. 35-46) has put into the mouth of Pericles. Some commentators, e.g. Gottling and Westermann, think that it is taken from the funeral oration delivered by Pericles after the Samian War, b.c. 440. There are other references, which cannot now be verified, to passages in the speeches of Pericles, p. 118, 11. 15 sqq., p. 128,1. 1, p. 146, L 2. I I 56 THE RHETORIC [l. The same is true of such things as are useful when the necessity is greater, e.g. such things as are useful in old age or in times of sickness. Again, of two things that which is nearer to the end is the greater. That which is good * relatively to the individual as well as absolutely is greaUr than that which is good only in one of these senses. Possibilities are greater goods than impossibilities, as the possible is good relatively to the individual, and the impossible is not. Such things as are inherent or implied in the end of life are greater goods; for all that approxi- mates to the end is in a liigher degree participant in the character of the end. Genuineness of any kind is a greater good than pretence, the test of pretence being that a person would not choose the thing, if there were no chance of his being known to have it. And from this it would seem that it is more desirable to receive benefits than to confer them, as one would choose to receive benefits, even if they were quite unknown, but would probably not choose to confer benefits without getting credit for them. Again, anything of which the reality is preferable to the appearance is a greater good, as being more genuine. This is the reason why justice itself in the eyes of some people is a poor thing, because it is ^ Spengel's interpretation, which I have accepted, lays the stress upon the Kai in the phrase r6 avTav^ [1. / eulogy and censure. For the discussion of them will ' incidentally serve to indicate the means by which 1 we shall ourselves be regarded as persons of a certain p. 11. ^ moral character, (which, as we saw, is a second species of proof), since the same means will enable us to represent both ourselves and others as de- serving of confidence in respect of virtue. And further, as eulogy is often jocular as well as serious, its subjects being not only men or gods but even inanimate things or any animals however insignifi- cant, it is right to provide ourselves in the sanae manner with other propositions respecting these. Let us then treat of them too sufficiently for the purpose of illustration. A thing is noble if, while it is desirable for its 1 sake, it is laudable, or if, whi is pleasant in virtue of its goodness. Virtue. This being the definition of nobleness, it follows that virtue is noble ; for, while it is good, it is also laudable \ By virtue is meant according to the popular idea a faculty of providing and preserving good things and a faculty of conferring many great benefits and indeed benefits of all kinds on all occasions. The elements of virtue are justice, valour, temperance, magnificence, magnanimity, liberality, gentleness, sagacity and speculative wisdom. Assuming then that virtue is a faculty of bene- Definitioii nobielSss. owu sakc, it is laudable, or if, while it is good, it The several virtues. ^ It is only necessary to compare this off-hand definition of virtue with the definition given in Nicom. Eth. vi. ch. 10 and the discussion of particular virtues which follows it, to see how unphilosophical is Aristotle's treatment of ethical questions in a popular work like the RJietoric. OF ARISTOTLE. 61 I.] ficence, we conclude at once that the greatest virtues are those which are in the highest degree serviceable to others. Accordingly none are so highly esteemed as valour and justice, the former being serviceable to others in war, and the latter both in war and in peace. Libemlity comes next, as libeml people are always lavish and never contend with their neighbours in the race for wealth, which is the prin- cipal object of other men's desire. Justice is the virtue to which it is due that individuals possess their own property and possess it in accordance with the law, whereas to injustice it is due that they possess the property of others illegally. Valour is the virtue which inspires people to perfonn noble deeds and such as the law enjoins in the face of perils ; its opposite is cowardice. Temperance or continence is the virtue which leads them to regard all bodily pleasures in the spirit enjoined by the law ; and its opposite is licentiousness or intemperance. Libe- rality is the virtue of the beneficent use of money and is opposed to illiberality. Magnanimity is the virtue which inspires beneficent actions on a large scale', magnificence the virtue which produces grandeur in matters of expenditure, their opposites being pusillanimity and meanness. Lastly, sagacity is an intellectual virtue, rendering people capable judges of the things good and evil which I have described in their relation to happiness. Virtue and vice in their general character and Elements of their constituents have now been discussed suf- nobleness ficiently for our present purpose. Nor is it difficult ^ Omitting fiiKpoyfrvx^o. 8e rovvavriov. 62 THE RHETORIC in the remaining cases to see the truth. It is clear that whatever is productive of virtue, as tending in a virtuous direction, and whatever results from virtue must itself be noble ; and by these I mean the signs of virtue and its effects. And as the signs and all such things as are the effects of good, ' whether active or passive, are noble, it follows that any effect or sign of valour or any deed valiantly done must be noble, and that just deeds and active effects of justice must be noble too, not its passive effects however : for justice is unlike all other virtues in this, that the adverb "justly" has not always a noble sense, but in the case of punishment inflicted it is more disgraceful to be punished justly than unjustly. It follows also that the same is true of the other virtues. Again, a thing is noble, if its prize is honour ; or if its prize is honour rather than money ; or if it is a desirable thing and yet is not done from selfish motives ; or if it is good absolutely, like 'a deed done for one's country without regard to one- self It Is noble too, if it is in its nature good, or 1 Aristotle illustrates his owii meaning by the examples which follow. To inflict punishment justly would be an tpyov dp€T9js or "active effect of virtue"; to suffer it justly would be a TrdBos dpcTfjs or "passive effect of virtue." * Reading virep rrji narpidos. The passage, as it stands, can only be regarded as a striking example of the Greek way of looking upon the individual as properly and absolutely a part of his State. But it mav be doubted whether services rendered to the State should not constitute a special class of moral actions. The true text ought then to be kqI ov(T€L dyadd, k.t.X. I.] OF ARISTOTLE. 63 if it is not good only in relation to the individual, as individual interests are always selfish. Or again if it is soniething capable of enjoyment after death rather than in life ; for there is more of selfishness in the enjoyments of life. Or if it is any work un- dertaken for the sake of others, as being less selfish. Or any service rendered to one's neighbours and not to oneself Or a service rendered to one's bene- factors, as being a just return. Or any beneficent action, as being unselfish in its object. Or the op- posite of anything of which one is ashamed ; for we are ashamed of saying or doing or intending to say or do anything shameful, as may be illustrated by the lines of Sappho in reply to the confession of Alcaeus that he would " fiiin speak, but shame forbade." " ^ If thou would'st say aught good or wise Nor meditate to speak some ill, Shame should not sit upon thine eyes But thou should'st rightly say thy will." Or again anything about which we distress our- selves although without a sense of fear ; for this is our natural attitude in regard to all such good things as conduce to reputation. The virtues and fc^^P^J^f " functions of the class which is naturally higher in the moral scale are themselves nobler, those of a| man e.g. than those of a woman. The virtues whicl ^ The reading of this Fragment, as given by Bergk, seems to be best. at 5' ^X*^ ea-Xcdv Tp.€pov fj KaXtov, Koi p.rj Tt Feirrrjv yXa>(r(r €KVKa kukov, ai86iv t ovaa Tvpdwav 7raiba>p r ovk rjpO^ ^'ovv €S draaOaXiriv. •^.^sy^^^jL^ \^^tXju<^Jt^ ojl \J^-^ t^ V rfX.>>-'^ I.] OF ARISTOTLE. ^7 Again, as the subjects of eulogy are actions and it is characteristic of a virtuous person that he acts in accordance with a moral purpose, we must make it our endeavour to prove that the hero of our speech has a moral purpose in his actions. To this end it is useful that he should be shewn to have j frequently acted in the same way. Accordingly mere / coincidences and happy accidents should be repre-J sented as actions of deliberate purpose ; for if a large number of similar actions are alleged, there will seem to be here a sign of virtue and moral purpose. , Eulogy is speech setting forth magnitude of Definition ^virtue. It is the business then of an orator in etdogy pistinction to demonstrate that the actions of his hero are eulogy and panegyric. virtuous. But a paneg}Tic has reference to accom- plished results, and the attendant circumstances, , such as rank and education, are merely confirmatory from the natural presumption that the children of virtuous parents will be virtuous, and that the re- cipient of a good education will be good. * Hence when we pronounce a panegyric upon anyone, we pronounce it for something that he has already done. But the accom]>lished results are praised as being indications of the moral state ; for we should eulo- gize a person even without his actual performance of the deeds, if we believed him to be capable of performing them. Felicitation and congratulation, Felicitation it may be observed, although themselves identical, gratuiation. are not identical with eulogy and panegyric ; still, ^ The hio follows from the words to S* iyKutpnov tu>v tpya>v eariv, the intervening words being unnecessary to the conclusion. 5—2 i I Means of exaggera- tion. 68 THE RHETORIC [I- as virtue is included in happiness, so are these in- eluded in congratulation. There is a community in kind however between eu- .ogy and counsel, inasmuch as the suggestions which you would make in giving counsel may by a change of expression be rendered panegyrical. Thus as we have ascertained the points of good conduct and character, it is only necessary to change and shift the form of expression in order to put them forward as suggestions. Let us take as an 'example the sentiment that we ought not to be proud of what Fortune has done for us but only of what we have done for ourselves. Put it so, and it is virtually a suggestion. But put it in this way, "Proud not of what Fortune has done for him but of what he has done for himself," and the sentence becomes eulo- gistic. We arrive then at the following rule, that, if eulogy is your object, you should consider what you would suggest, if suggestion, you should con- sider what you would eulogize. But the expression will be contradictory in the ttvo cases, 'when the prohibitive and the non-prohibitive elements are interchanged. cx•^^-^ JU^^^^-Ci Again, there are various means of exaggeration to be employed. It may be said e.g. that our hero is the only person or the first to have done a particular deed or has been almost single-handed or the chief agent in doing it, all these being points which enhance 1 The example is taken from two passages of Isocrates, Panath. § 35 and Emg. § 52. 2 In the "suggestive" form of expression pride is prohibited, in the "eulogistic" it is not prohibited but rather enjoined. I.] OF ARISTOTLE. 69 the nobleness of the deed. Then there are the cir- cumstances of time and opportunity, if they exceed reasonable expectation. There may be the fact that he has been often successful in the same under- taking ; a fact which not only increases its im- portance but is calculated to convey the impression that the success has not been an accidental result but has been due to his own exertions. Or it may be the case that especial incentives and distinctions have been devised or were instituted in his honour. Or that he is the first person who was the subject of a panegyric, like * Hippolochus, or i\\e first for whmn some special compliment was devised^ like the erec- tion of a statue in the market-place for Harmodius and Aristogiton. And what is true of signal dis- tinctions is not less true of their opposites. Further, if you cannot find much to say about compari- your hero himself, it is proper to contrast him with other people, after the manner which ^Isocrates adopted owing to his inexperience in forensic ora- tory. But the persons with whom you compare him must be persons of reputation, as superiority to persons who are confessedly virtuous lends new ilignity and nobleness to the character. Exaggera- tion naturally finds a place in eulogies ; for it is a means of establishing superiority, and superiority is one kind of nobleness. It follows that, even if you cannot compare your hero with persons of 1 Nothing is known, except from this passage, of Hippolochus. '^ It seems most probable that Aristotle regarded Isocrates as having introduced into his forensic speeches the habit of com- parison which was better adapted to panegyrical orations. 70 THE RHETORIC \% Hi f The charac- teristics of the three kinds of Rhetoric. / Chap. X. Forensic Rhetoric. Accusation and defence, The three points. Definition of crime. reputation, yet it is best to compare him with some other persons, as superiority is taken to indicate virtue. It may be laid down as a general rule that, of the characteristics which are common to the three styles of Rhetoric, exaggeration is most appropriate to the epideictical style— for as the facts are taken for granted hi this style, it only remains to invest them with grandeur and dignity— examples to tlie" deliberative style, as in this we divine and infer the future from the past ; and enthymemes to the fo- rensic style, as in this the obscurity of the facts leaves the largest room for deduction and demon- stration. So much then for the general materials of eulog}' and censure, the proper objects to be observed in both and the sources of panegyric or abuse. For having ascertained the one we can at once see their opposites, as the materials of censure are exactly opposed to those of eulogy. Coming now to accusation and defence, we liave next to describe the number and nature of the materials proper for the construction of the syllo- gisms. There are three points whicli we have to ascertain, viz. (1) the nature and number of the objects of crime, (2) the dispositions of the criminals, and (3) the character and condition of the victims. But in the first instance it is necessary to define crime. Crime may be said to be injury voluntarily in- flicted in defiance of the law. But law may be either particular or universal. I mean by "particular" the OF ARISTOTLE. 71 I.] written law which regulates the life of the citizens Particular in any polity and by "universar' the unwritten prin- versaiiaw. ciples which may be said to be universally recognized. Voluntary action is all such action as is performed vo^^^t^ry with knowledge and not under compulsion. Now an action may be voluntarily performed without being deliberately purposed ; but if it is done of deliberate puriM)se, it is always done knowingly, as nobody is ignorant of his own purposes. The causes of a deliberate purpose to conmiit causes o^^^ injury and to do evil in defiance of the law are vice ^^.^^mit and incontinence. For if there are certain people wlio have vicious habits, whether one or several, it is in the particular respect in which they are vicious that they are apt to commit crimes,— an illiberal pei-son e.g. in respect of money, a licentious person in his sensual pleasures, an effeminate person in his luxuries, a coward in dangers, by leaving his com- rades in the lurch from personal fear, an ambitious person from the love of honour, a passionate person from anger, an emulous person from the love of victory, a vindictive person to gratify his revenge, a foolish person from his mistaken notion of justice and injustice, a shameless person from disregard of public opinion, 'and so each individual in respect of his own particular subject Tliis is a matter however which will be sufficiently clear partly from the description already given of the p. eo. several virtues and partly from the remarks which we shall have occasion to make when we come to discuss pp.nssqq. the emotions. It remains for us now to describe the * Putting only a comma after b6$rjs. / 72 THE RHETORIC i til (I) The objects of cnine. i Causes of human action. f [I. objects of crime, the conditions under which people commit it and its victims. Let us begin with a classification of the objects, the attainment or avoidance of which is the motive inciting to crime. For it is cleariy the duty of the prosecutor to consider the nature and number of such of these objects as are present to his * adversary and that of the defendant to consider the nature and number of such as are not present to him. All our actions are either due to ourselves or not. If they are not, they are either due to chance or else arise from necessity, and, if necessary, are done either under compulsion or by nature. The result is that all such actions as are not due to ourselves are done either by chance or by nature or under compulsion. Actions on the other hand which are due to ourselves and of which we ourselves are the authors may be due either to habit or to impulse and, if to the latter, either to rational or irrational impulse. ^The one of these is the wish, which is an impulse towards good ; for nobody wishes a thing, unless he conceives it to be good ; the irrational impulses are e.g. anger and desire. ^ To sum up then ; all our actions are necessarily due to seven causes, viz. chance, nature, compulsion, ^ Omitting tis unnecessary the words c5v €(f)i€^€voi rrdims rovt 7r\r)(riov adiKOvat. - There is no need to insert /SovXi/o-tj d' as in Bekker's text, although it makes t]ie meaning a little plainer. 3 It would be better to put a full stop after eVt^/iia, as the sentence beginning aare iravra oa-a nparrova-iv sums up the results of the two preceding sections. I.] OF ARISTOTLE. 73 habit, * reasoning, passion and desire. It is super- fluous to make a further classification of actions according to periods of life or moral states or any other occurrences ; for if it happens as a matter of fact that the young have quick tempers and strong desires, yet it is not their youth but anger or desire which is the cause of their passionate and sensual actions. Nor again can wealth and poverty be de- scribed as causes of action ; it happens as a matter of fact that the poor from their indigence are desirous of money and that the rich from their abundance desire the pleasures of luxury, but in these cases as before the cause of the actions will be not wealth and poverty but their desire. The same is true of persons who are just or unjust and of others whose actions are said to be regulated by their moral states; it will be either reason or emotion which is the cause of their actions, although in some cases good characters and emotions, and in others the reverse. Still it is the fact that particular qualities are the accompaniments of particular moml states. No sooner, it may be said, is a person temperate than in virtue of his temperance good opinions and desires in regard to pleasures wait upon him, while contrary opinions and desires in regard to pleasures wait upon one who is destitute of self-restraint. It is right there- fore, while we abandon such classifications as have been mentioned, to consider the connexion of par- ticular qualities with particular classes ; for although a person may be fair or dark, tall or short without any of the qualities in question regularly following, ^ Xoytc/xoff is equivalent to XoyiariKr) 6p€^is of 1. 20. Ill jl 74 THE RHETORIC y II » I f (2) nature, ( [I- yet it does necessarily make a difference whether he is young or old or just or unjust. And it is right to consider generally all such accidental circumstances as produce differences of moral character. It will make a difference e.g. to a person whether he believes himself to be rich or poor, fortunate or unfortunate. Postponing then this question for the present, let us first proceed to the points which still remain. The causes 'A thing is the result of chance, if its cause is SJn'jSd: indeteiminate and if it is not directed to any object (1) chance, ^^ ^^^g ^^^^ occur invariably or usually or by any regular law, as indeed is evident from the definition of chance. It may be said to occur by nature, if its cause is self-contained and regular; for then it happens invariably or usually in the same way. For we need not endeavour to determine accurately whether vio- lations of the law of Nature happen in accordance with some natural law or with another cause, although the more probable view is that such occurrences are also caused by chance. Again, a thing is said to be done under compul- sion, if it is done against the desire or mtional facul- ties of the agents themselves. It is done by habit, if the reason for doing it is that it has been often done by the same person before. ^ The early chapters of the Second Book of the v(nKri aKpoa- aii should be studied in connexion with this passage. The distinction between ij t^x*; and to avVofiaroi/, which is there em- phasized, would be out of place in a popular treatise like the Rhetoric. (3) com pulsion. (4) habit, 1."] OF ARISTOTLE. 75 To the influence of reason may be ascribed all (s) reason, such actions as have an air of expediency in ac- cordance with the catalogue of goods already given, pp.39 8qq. whether as ends or as means to ends, when it is the expediency which is the cause of the action — a limi- tation which Is necessary, inasmuch as it sometimes happens that the actions of persons who have no self-restraint are expedient, although the cause of them is not their expediency, but pleasure. Passion and anger are the causes of revengeful (6) anger, acts. There is a distinction, it may he observed, between revenge and punishment ; for the object of punishment is the reformation of the sufferer, and that of revenge the gratification of the agent The nature of anger will be seen in our treatment p. iis. of the emotions. Desire is the cause of all such actions as appear (7):de8ire. pleasant, and among them of actions with which we are familiar or to which we are habituated ; for there are many things, even such as are not naturally pleasant, which we do with pleasure after habitua- tion. In a word then all such actions as are due to ourselves are either good or apparently good or pleasant or apparently i^leasant. And further, as actions which are due to ourselves are done volun- tarily and actions which are not due to ourselves are done involuntarily, it follows that all voluntary actions must be either good or apparently good or pleasant or apparently pleasant ; for I reckon as a good the deliverance from evils either real or apparent or the exchange of a greater evil for a I I 76 THE RHETORIC [l. smaller one, as being events which are in a certain sense desirable, and on the same principle I reckon as a pleasure the deliverance from painful things whether real or apparent, or the exchange of a greater pain for a smaller one. It is necessary then to ascertain the number and character of such things as are expedient or pleasant. It follows that, as expediency has been already discussed under the head of deliberative oratory, we have now to discuss pleasure. But we must regard our definitions as satisfactory, if upon any point they are neither ob- scure nor yet exact. CHAP. XL Let us assume that pleasure is a certain motion KeSSre. of the soul and a sudden and sensible settling of the soul into its normal and natural state ; and that pain is the opposite. Such being the nature of pleasure, it is evident that everything which tends to produce the con- dition described is itself pleasant, and everything which tends to destroy it or produce a settling of an opposite kind is painful. It follows at once then that the return to the natural condition is generally pleasant, * and never so pleasant as when the pro- cesses of nature have attained their full natural de- velopment. It follows also that habits are pleasant ; for that to which we are habituated becomes, as being so, virtually natural, as habit is in a certain sense a second nature, owing to the close connexion between the usual, which is the sphere of habit, and 1 The meaning is apparently that the pleasure is keenest when not only the general laws of Nature but the bye-laws of one's own individual nature have been satisfied. Pleasures and pains. I.] OF ARISTOTLE. 77 the invariable, which is the sphere of Nature. Again, anything that is not done under compulsion is pleasant, as compulsion is a violation of Nature. Accordingly all necessity is painful, as has been truly said* " Need-be is evermore a thing of pain." Acts of attention too or serious effort or strong ex- ertion must be painful, as they involve necessity and compulsion, unless one is habituated to them, in which case habit renders them pleasant. The op- posites of these are pleasant. Accordingly all con- ditions of ease, comfort or inattention, amusements, recreations and sleep may be reckoned as pleasures, none of these having a character of necessity. Any- thing of which we have a natural desire is pleasant ; for desire itself is an impulse to pleasure. But Rational desires may be either rational or irrational. I de- tionai scribe as irrational desires all such as do not spring from any definite theory, meaning all natural desires, as they are called, such as those of which the body is the necessary instrument, e.g. the desire of food, viz. himger and thirst ^and so on, or desires of the taste, of sexual love and of the touch in all its forms or of the smell, the hearing and the sight Rational desires on the other hand are all such as originate in conviction, as there are many things which we are desirous of seeing and acquiring from the report of them and from a conviction of tlieir excellence. desires. ^ The saying is attributed to Evenus of Paros. * Omitting Tporji and in 1. 14 ^vMas, n I1< I* P 78 THE RHETORIC [}» As pleasure then consists in the sensation of some emotion, and impression is a kind of feeble sensation, Pleasures of ^memory or anticipation must be attended by a cer- o?mi^r tain impression of the object remembered or antici- pated. If this is so, it is clear that, as there is sen- sation, there are accompanying pleasures also in memory and anticipation. Consequently, all pleasant things must consist either in the sensation, if they are present, or in the memory, if they are past, or in the anticipation, if they are fixture ; for the present is the object of sensation, the past of memory and the future of anticipation. Now the objects of recollection are pleasant not only if they were pleasant at the actual time at which they happened but in some cases even if they were not pleasant, provided that the consequence of them has been noble and good. Hence the lines and 2'*Ti8 pleasant to remember ills survived" ^'*For there is after-pleasure e'en in woes For one remembering toils and troubles past,** 1 Upon the whole there seems to be no sufficient reason for changing the reading or punctuation of the passage. It is true that the apodosis, Kau r^ fx(tivr}fi4u 1' I I 80 THE RHETORIC [l. fill to US, there is still a kind of pleasure arising in our very regrets and lamentations; for although there is pain in the loss of him, yet is there a pleasure in recollecting him and almost seeing him and his very actions and the manner of man that he was. Hence the appropriateness of the words 1" He spake and in them stirred the love of tears." Again, there is a pleasure in revenge. For where failure is painful, success is pleasant ; and as angry men are pained beyond all measure by the failure to gnitify their revenge, they are equally delighted by the anticipation of it. Victory too is pleasant, pleasant to us all, not only to those who always hate to be beaten. The reason is that we experience an impression of supe- riority, and superiority is an object of desire to all in a less or a greater degree. And from the pleasure of victory follows the pleasure of all amusements which are contests of strength or wit, as they atford many opportunities of victory, games of knuckle- bones or tennis or dice or draughts. The same re- mark applies to serious amusements ; they either become pleasant by habit or are pleasant from the first, as e.g. the chase and every variety of field- sports ; for wherever there is competition, there is victory. This too is the explanation of the pleasure which the Bar and the Debating Society aflbrd to all experienced and able speakers. 1 A line which occurs more than once in the Homeric poems, e.g. Iliady xxiii. 108, when Achilles has seen and sought to hold the shade of Patroclus, Odyssey ^ iv. 113 when Menelaus has told to Telemachus the tale of his sorrow for Odysseus. I.] OF ARISTOTLE. 81 Again, there are few things so pleasant as honour and a good reputation ; for the consequence of pos- sessing them is an impression that one is a virtuous sort of person, especially if this is the opinion of those in whose judgment one has confidence, i.e. of neighbours rather than of those wiio live at a distance, of friends and fellow-citizens rather than of strangers, of contemporaries rather than of posterity, of sensible people rather than of fools, of a number of people rather than of a few, as these classes of people are more likely to form a true judgment than their opposites. It is necessary however that the classes should he capable of judging; for if they are such as one regards with a strong contempt, e.g. as children or animals, there is no regard paid to their respect or opinion, at least for its own sake or unless for some independent reason. There is pleasure too in a friend ; for love Ms pleasant — nobody e.g. can be said to be a lover of wine who does not find pleasure in it — and it is pleasant to be the object of another's love, as here again one has an impression of possessing a good character, which is the desire of every sentient being. But to be loved is to be esteemed for one's own sake. Again, it is pleasant to be an object of admiration, if only for the esteem which it implies. Again, there is a pleasure in flattery and in a flatterer, as a flatterer is ostensibly an admirer and friend. Or in frequent repetition of the same actions ; for habit, as has been already said, is pleasant. Or p. 76. ^ There is a diflficulty here, as elsewhere, in translating <^iXeti/, where it varies between "loving" and ''liking." W. R. 6 82 THE RHETORIC l> [I- again in change, as being a return to Nature ; for perpetual uniformity produces an excess of the normal state. Hence the saying \ "Change ever is delight." This is the reason why occasional visitors or occasional events are always pleasant, as not only do they imply a change from the existing condition, but the occasional is necessarily rare and therefore pleasant. Wonder and learning too are generally pleasant ; wonder, because it necessarily involves the desire of learning, and therefore the wonderful is an object of desire, and learning, because it involves a settling' into a person's proper natural condition. Again, it is pleasant to receive benefits or to confer them ; for the former implies the satisfaction of our desires, and the latter implies possession and su- periority, which are both natural objects of ambition. And as the poAver of conferring benefits is pleasant, it follows that there is a pleasure in setting up our neighbours again after a failure and in^ supplying such deficiencies as are seen in them. From the pleasure of learning and Avonder it results that there is a pleasure in such things as the imitative* arts, e.g. * Euripides, Orestes, 228. 2 The reason assigned here for the pleasure found in learning accords with the definition of pleasure at the beginning of the chapter. But it strikingly shews the Aristotelian sense of <^v