• % = O v \ +~r '% V- ,^v ^ ^ \ 'j otf ,0 o £ r . " 1/ i - sS> "^'. ^ °*. V * * A '->, "O, V ^ % ^v x°°- '•■« ^ '"' ^ ' A)' .OKC ,'V' ^> '- ■0' * %>.# 0c> .A* ,\>' -p- -? oi/uLai, TrpoXovaiv ov% tjttov earai KctTCKpaves. (Polit. 287 b.) SOPHIST AND STATESMAN PLATO. GENERAL INTRODUCTION. -A.S the discovery of truth and the direction of life are the twofold function of philosophy, so Plato saw a twofold counter- feit of his ideal educator and governor in the professors of wisdom and the public men of his time. The one corrupted in- quiry with controversy, the other spoiled politics with faction. These Sophists and party leaders seemed to exhaust between them the serious interest of the Greek world. ; for the poets, sculptors, painters, and other " imitators with their child's play/' were by this time of less account. There might be jealousies between these two great powers, who formed the intellect and heart of every state, but they were usually in league, and together held the public ear. Rarely, either in the present or the past, might be traced the footprints of a more august presence; of a Divine spirit "coming down in the likeness" of sage or legislator. Such glimpses of the Phi- losopher and true potentate were few and far between, and he had always been either misunderstood or rejected by man- kind. The writer of these dialogues, whom for the present we assume to be Plato, seems to have viewed this spectacle with a feeling strangely mixed of curiosity, interest, and scorn. In approaching his subject by a circuitous track, he makes inquiry the vehicle of satire, and satire of inquiry. But it is not to be inferred from this that the inquiry or even the per- plexity which he exhibits here is merely ironical. On the b ii (iEXKRAL IXTKOD! (TION. contrary, Plato is nowhere more intensely speculative, nor is the aim of his discussion anywhere more real. This appears even from the form in which the questions are asked. In other dialogues the character of Gorgias or Protagoras, Thra- s\ machus or Polus, is dramatized, and certain hints thrown out as to the nature of their profession; casual remarks are made on the career of Pericles, Themistocles, and other servants of the state: but here not a single name is mentioned; the spirit of inquiry (as described in the Theaetetus) refuses to deseend to individuals or to things near at hand, and the ideal Sophist, the ideal Statesman, each character in the utmost generality, is at once represented and defined. Again, in other dialogues certain abstract questions are proposed, such as, What is cou- rage, prudence, justice? and in the Theaetetus, What is know- ledge '( But even " Sophistic" is not a purely abstract con- ception : the Sophists were a real class of persons, having, as Plato believed, certain common characteristics. The state also is an essentially complex thing, and the statesman can only be known in relation to the state. This union of the universal and the real, this personifying of a general notion, this attempt to descend into the complexity of life without losing hold of metaphysical conceptions, may be regarded, even on an external view, as a leading peculiarity of these two dialogues. And the form in this case truly indicates the substance; for these writings are, together with the Theaetetus, the most dis- tinct record which remains to us of a great effort, of which other traces are found in the Parmenides and Philebus, by which Plato endeavoured to bridge over the gulf which the first impulse of philosophy had made between the absoluteness of Knowledge and Being and the relativeness of Sensation and Appearance. In some dialogues the phenomenal side of this antithesis, while dramatically represented with great liveliness, is dialectically annihilated; opinion, custom, the conceit of knowledge, are brought on the stage with ironical circumstance for a prepared overthrow; and the difficulty is stated, but not fully met — How can virtue, not based on science, be virtue at all ? But here the same difficulty is presented in a more general aspect. The hollowness of pretended wisdom, and the futility of existing governments, are taken for granted or summarily proved. But the question is, How can the real and the apparent, the ideal GENERAL INTRODUCTION. iii and actual, coexist? And yet they must. For the non- existent cannot bo the object of attack ; and unless true ideas can be brought to bear on the actual circumstances of men, there is no hope of remedying the evils of which the world is full. This speculative doubt, while giving rise to certain changes in Plato's theory of Knowledge, forms the link be- tween these dialogues and the Thcastctus. That their con- nexion with that dialogue is not merely outward, is the more probable because the Theastetus, though ending, like the Philebus, with a promise of further talk, wears no appearance of being the first instalment of a larger design. But if, as would appear from this, the two dialogues were conceived and written at a later time, their author would not, without good reason, present them as a continuation of an earlier writing. And it may be regarded as a sufficient reason, that he was now engaged with the more objective phase of the same anti- thesis, of which the subjective aspect was developed in the Thesetetus ; for the opposition between the Absolute and Relative, which the mind experiences in contrasting Know- ledge with Sensation and Opinion, is also seen by her as the contrast between the Real and the Unreal, and between the Ideal and the Actual ; when, for instance, the pretended wise man is compared with the true lover of wisdom, and the great men of this world with the perfect King. The chief aim of each inquiry, however, is not so much to point the antithesis, as to draw together the opposite poles ; to find room for the relative beside the absolute ; to obtain a meeting-point between idea and fact. As in the Thesetetus the question, " How is false opinion possible?" was met by an unsuccessful effort to conceive the mode in which thought acts on sensation and memory, so in the " Sophist" there is raised the parallel question, How can that which is not, appear to be? And this doubt is, for the present at least, removed by raising Difference (i. e. Negation) to the rank of an idea or category, which has "communion" with, or participates in, Reality or Being, and may thus become the object of thought. The cor- responding difficulty in the Politicus has a double aspect. First, What place is there for an ideal of government at all ? This question is answered by the supposition of alternate cycles, in which the world is first guided and then left alone by God. b 2 i\ GENERAL ENTRODUCTION. Secondly; How is science to be applied to government during the inferior cycle in which we now livei* The latter question is only provisionally answered; but in a way which points to the conception of an accommodation or oevre/jos tt\ovs, which Plato afterwards embodied in the Laws. The main difficulty which assumes these different forms (that of the relation of ideas to phenomena) is clearly stated in the I'armenides (to which dialogue allusion is made in the Thea> letus, and again in the Sophist), and receives a passing notice at the opening of the Philebus. And the final elucidation of the whole subject, the delineation of the bright form of Being, the reconcilement of the speculative with the practical reason, and the attainment of a perfect method, were probably the destined task of the " Philosopher," a dialogue which was to have ended this series or tetralogy of dialogues, but which it does not appear that Plato ever composed. Whether he in- stinctively turned back from an impossible enterprize, or whe- ther, after he had once descended into the phenomenal world, ethical and cosmical intci'ests predominated over the merely speculative, it is clear that the aspiration after an ideal certainty which appears in these dialogues, and also in the Republic and elsewhere, but which is here combined with a promise that the very exactness of truth (clvto 7-d(cpt/3e5, Polit. 284 d) shall be hereafter displayed, is nowhere satisfied. Nor was the hope attainable in the infancy of science. But it is not unlikely that Plato intended to place this keystone of the dialectical fabric when he should take in hand to define the Philosopher. We have before us, therefore, the middle portion of an unfinished work, looking backwards on the Thesetetus, pro- bably across an interval (with a momentary glance at the Parmenides), and forwards to an unwritten dialogue. Having taken note of this, we may draw a little closer, — to a point, however, from which the two dialogues can still be taken in one view. There are marked and obvious differences be- tween them. But these will be better seen when they are examined separately : in a general survey it is more im- portant to notice, without exaggerating, the features which they have in common. § 1. The subjects of both dialogues arc nearly related to GENERAL INTRODUCTION. v each other. The Sophist and Statesman were, as already noticed, the main representatives of the world as it then was, of the leading thoughts and principles of Plato's contempo- raries. Could these typical men be reduced under definitions t Was a scientific knowledge of them possible ? Did the vague- ness of the science which they professed extend also to them- selves? In what relation did the Sophist stand to the Philo- sopher, or the members of existing governments to the true King? There is however this difference of treatment: that whereas the " Sophist" is from the beginning a search for the definition of pretended knowledge, the distinction between reality and pretence only appears in the Politicus towards the close. § 2. In both an extreme or premature ideal theory is modi- fied : in the Sophist the dictum of Parmenides annihilating " Not-Being ;" in the Politicus the Pythagorean notion of a theocracy under the Divine King. The mere abstract " num- bers" of the same school, are exchanged in the Politicus (in another connexion) for a relative standard determined by the idea of Good (to jue'rptov) ; and, in the Sophist, either the same Pythagoreans, or the Megarians, or some of Plato's own followers, are criticized as the " Friends of Ideas." § 3. In both there is a deep vein of irony, or rather of satire. The assertion of Socher, that in these dialogues the Socratic irony is silent, could only be justified if it had been meant that the irony is rather that of Plato. The humour with which the chase after the Sophist is maintained, the fear of his great cunning, the solemnity with which he is described as a soul-purifier; and in the Politicus, the notion of the crane exalting himself at man's expense, the quiet substitution of Lydians and Phrygians for Hellenes as distinguished from Barbarians, and the description of a state in which navigation and medicine should be administered according to legal pre- scription, are touches of an irony singularly Platonic. It is true that the wild playfulness of the Phsedrus and the dramatic liveliness of the Republic are absent, and that the humour is not unmixed with bitterness ; but the occasional shadow of misanthropy is not more unlike the caustic cheerfulness of the Gorgias and Meno, than is the sad smile and sober colouring of the Laws. Two points may be noticed in which vi OENERAL [NTRODUCTION. the dialectical method conveys the effect of irony. First, n is remarked thai science is a great leveller, she cares equally for Bmall and great; hence the physician and the bath- man are equally good examples of the purifier; the general is a species of huntsman, so is the vermin-killer; priest, pro- phet, archon-basileus, are servants equally with the shopkeeper and the household slave. Akin to this is the mode in which the Sophist is thrust down by the process of divisions, and is found in a low place amongst the class of imitators; just as Pleasure in the Philebus, after aiming at the highest rank, has assigned to her, by the same process, the fifth and lowest. § 4. Both dialogues are pervaded, or rather haunted, by the idea of scientific method. Every inquiry, even that con- cerning Government, is held to be important, chiefly as an exercise by which the dialectical faculty may be improved. The nature and function of this power are described in each dialogue in language which forcibly recals the well-known passages of the Phsedrus and Philebus, and which even the most doubtful critic must admit to have a Platonic flavour. " To distinguish things according to their kinds, and neither to account the same form to be another nor another to be the same, is surely the work of dialectic. And the dialectician is he who adequately perceives one idea pervading many separate things, and many distinct ideas embraced by one, and many such wholes pervaded and knit together in one crowning form, — many also completely isolated and sundered. And what is this but to know how to distinguish the respects in which each kind admits or rejects communion with other kinds V (Soph. 253 d, e.) " But because they have not been accustomed to distinguish the subject of an inquiry into its forms, they not only confound things so widely different as the More and the Too-much, the moment they see a similarity between them, but fall also into the converse error of dividing things not according to their parts ; whereas the right way is, when one first perceives com- munity in a multitude of things, not to desist till one have seen all the differences contained within that common nature, all, that is, which rest upon any logical distinction; and on the other hand when dissimilarities are seen in a mass of objects, the eye should be incapable of contentment or rest, GENERAL INTRODUCTION. vii until one have confined all that is kindred within the pule of one resemblance, and fenced them round with the new crea- tion of a single kind or category." (Polit. 285 a-c.) The notions of Sameness and Difference, and of the corre- sponding arts of collection or combination, and division or distinction (aw ay coy 1), bia[peais, avyKpuiK.r\, btaKptTLKij), are pro- minent in many places of these dialogues. The Elenchus is described as purifying, that is, dividing the good from the bad. The chief " kinds" next to Being, are Same and Other. Dialectic is the science of the communion and exclusion of kinds, and language itself would be impossible without a similar process of combination and distinction. And these logical forms have also a practical bearing ; for the art of the true statesman, like that of the weaver, consists in com- bining elements which have been first separated and purified. Thus it appears that the process of classification, involving generalization and division (avvaywyr] and biaipecnn), is only a particular application of a form of thought to which a meta- physical and a practical as well as a logical importance is attributed. But it has been felt that the " dichotomous " classifications of these dialogues are a caricature of method, and are unlike anything which is to be found elsewhere in Plato. "Are we to suppose," it has been asked % "that the Dichotomous Method of the Sojjhistes Dialogue (I may add of the Politicus, for the method is the same in this dialogue also) is the method of division of a subject according to its natural members, of which Plato speaks in the Phsedrus?" Is it the same, it may be further asked, which Plato has him- self used in the Phasdrus, Gorgias, Philebus, Republic, and elsewhere ? The likeness is unmistakeable, (compare espe- cially the close of the " Sophist'''' with that of the Philebus and of the sixth book of the Republic) ; but so also is the differ- ence, consisting partly in the extent to which the method is carried, and partly in the arbitrary and superficial character of some of the divisions, when compared with the dialectical analysis of madness in the Phasdrus, or with that of pleasure in the Philebus. And although there is no reason to suppose that the division of each kind into two parts only was a novelty (for this is required in the Philebus), there appears a further a By Dr. Whewell. Cambridge Phil, Soc, Tr. vol. ix. pt. 4. p. 594. viii GENERAL [NTRODUCTION. refinement on this notion, when, in the Politicus | 262 b), the pupil is advised to divide each as nearly as possible in half. It has liccii suggested, in order to explain this difference, that thf ThesBtetus and Sophista (with the Politicus) were meant respectively to serve as examples of the two parts of the Dialectic process; the Theffltetus of avvayuyrj, the Sophista and Politicus of Statpeaty. But although the Theaetetus affords many good specimens of Socratic induction, it is not less fertile in the negative instances by which that induction was tested. Generalization thus alternates with distinction or division 1 '. On the other hand, no more striking example of avvaycayr] could be given than the generalization of OrjpevTiKi] in the Sophist, or the seven categories of industry in the Politicus. And in the latter dialogue a separate discussion is devoted to the subject of example, that is, the act of bringing resemblances together (avvayeiv). The existence of such an intention, then, can hardly be established, and the comparison of the Theae- tetus only throws the characteristic peculiarity of these dia- logues into stronger relief. We learn from a comic fragment (quoted at length by Dr. Thompson of Cambridge, in his paper on the genuineness of the Sophista) that when Plato, Speusippus, and Menedemus were together in the Academy, they and their scholars were ridi- culed for their endless minute classification of natural objects; and Aristotle speaks more than once of " written divisions" (yeypaufxevai StatpeVets), which, as they seem in some points to have coincided with those advanced in these dialogues, may be conjectured to have been extant in the school of Plato. It seems not improbable that this new passion for classification as a me- thod of science, which had a germ in Socrates and the Eleatics, and ripened afterwards into the analytic of Aristotle, was in full bloom at the Academy when these dialogues were written, and that Plato, who entered into every phase of thought, but ffvvaywyri, Sialpecris, 67ritrT7]|U7) = aicrdrjens * 4iri(frr)fj.y] ovic alffdyais' w aladavnfxeOa = ^vxv- 86£a a\-r)Qr)S, \pevSfis' aAridJis aArjOijs fxcTa \6you KivrjfTis = aWoioiais, (popa. c A then. II. 59 ; Com Gr. Fr. VIII. p. 370, ed. Meineke. GENERAL INTRODUCTION. ix was entirely possessed by none, took up the method, as he takes up that of etymologies in the Cratylus, " for the day." This may account for the unusual number of the divisions. But how is the peculiar nature of many of them to be ex- plained : a. First, the lesson is meant to be progressive. Thus the external and superficial character of some distinctions is at once accounted for by the often-repeated Platonic maxim, that the elements of truth must be spelt out in easy syllables, before the meaning of truth can be read. The most obvious data of sense and experience are the primer of thought. The simplest examples are chosen to illustrate principles of reason, not as being adequate, but because they can be apprehended at once. But there may be also traced in the method of these dia- logues a progress of a deeper kind. The argument of the Theaetetus, though generally destructive, left two results : first, that the mind gathers from the impressions of different senses certain common perceptions ; and secondly, that know- ledge and right opinion imply distinction, i. e. definition by the characteristic difference. This definition by difference, we will suppose, was becoming recognised as an organ of know- ledge, and the youth of Plato's school were delighted with their new exercise. We can imagine them, according to their master's description, rejoicing as if they had found a treasure of inexhaustible wisdom, first rolling up the ball and then unrolling and dividing, and never content till they had made everybody else to share their wonder. The negative aspect of Socratic inquiry, the controversial dialectic of Zeno, the Pythagorean n the ground that Difference meant logical exclusion; that, for instance, because making is dif- ferent from acquiring, production and acquisition cannot be attributes of the same art : and we have been surprised to sec the Sophist starting up on the left side of the cordon which wo had drawn, when we thought to have secured him on the right. At last he seems to be convicted of pretence, that is of appearing to be what he is not. He retorts that " what- is-not" has no Being, and can neither be denned nor criti- cized : a position which is only met by reconsidering the whole question of negation and difference, and also of Being, in a discussion where the vaunted method of exclusions is laid aside. It is at last found that ideas which are distinguished from each other may still be mutually related. Whereon follows the remark that mere " oppositions of science" are not philosophy. (Soph. 259.) The effect of this discovery may be traced in the Politicus. Not only are the two elements of generalization and distinction much more nearly balanced (it was always im- possible for either of them to be entirely absent), but more care is taken to define the relation between the members of each division. The respondent is significantly warned that every logical segment must be a natural part, and have a form of its own, i. e. that the distinction must have a rational ground or principle : he is told that the external resemblances and differences of objects are easily mastered, but that there are qualities of another sort, which cannot be perceived with- out a " vision and a faculty divine/' A mistake arising from dividing without generalizing sufficiently is corrected ; side by side with the partition of science appears " the interrogation of every nature, in order to learn what special contribution each has to offer from the store of experience to the treasury of wisdom ; " and we are reminded that it is not enough to define a subject by a single characteristic difference, for that nothing is completely known, until all other species, at least those of the same genus, have been also distinguished and defined. (Pol. 362, 285 e, 275, 272 e, 281 c.) Thus mere logical division by means of negatives is criticized by Plato on nearly the same ground as by Aristotle, who ob- jects that a negative term as such is not divisible. "Aristotle," GENERAL INTRODUCTION. xi says Mr. G. II. Lowes, " has here pointed out the scientific error of all classification founded on negatives, and his criti- cism reaches even the familiar division founded by Lamarck between vertebrata and invertebrata. The vcrtebrata form a natural division, characterized by an obvious peculiarity, but to lump together all other animals, no matter how manifestly different, merely on the negative character of their having no vertebral column, is, except as a provisional expedient, eminently unphilosophic" But Plato employs division by exclusions precisely as a provisional expedient. His object is not the classification of many things but the definition of one d . He never attempts to divide a class which is only known by a negative characteristic 6 . And he has himself striven to remedy the defect in question ; for he has observed that things are not perfectly distinguished until the mutually exclusive positive qualities of both are known. fi. Further, the end of this progressive lesson in dialectic is not to exalt a formal method, but to quicken and regulate the free action of the inquiring mind. Plato never conceived, as some modern philosophers have done, that a new method could possibly level intellects, or become a substitute for inven- tion. He never imagines a form of thinking as separable from thought. His dialectic is not a dead organon, but an inspiration, a divine gift, which may be imperfectly described in words, and by oral teaching may be awakened and stimu- lated in the philosophic nature, but cannot be once for all embodied in a book of aphorisms or a Chrestomathy. Dialectic is the right application to the highest subjects of the twin operations of distinction and combination, which are present as elements in the simplest exercise of the reason : whether the difference and resemblance noted be that of two fingers or of two virtues, the process is essentially the same. But thought is liable to perversion, and Plato is never weary of distinguish- ing argument from controversy (Sia/Ve/cri/oj from avnXoyiKrj or d This remark also supplies an an- and to Mr. G-rote's observation that swer to the other objection of Ari- Plato would have objected to class stotle, that the species of a genus are the wolf with the dog. by this method sometimes unnaturally ° He always follows the " right separated (e. g. birds are divided be- hand" section: Kara tovtt\ 5e|ia aet tween the land and water animals), fxepos rov T/x-qOevros, Soph. 264 e. xii GENEH \L [NTRODUCTION. (pHTTiioj). Perhaps controversy is too respectable a name for that ape of the Elenchus, a barren hybrid between Zenonian and Socratic method, which seems to have been a favourite pastime in the schools of Athens as well as Megara. The faults which Plato assigns to the devotees of this " illogical logic" of disputation arc chiefly the following, (i) They con- fused verbal with real agreement and difference. (2) They assumed that agreement and difference must mutually exclude each other not only in idea but in fact f . (3) They argued about first principles when consequences were in question, and vice versa. (Phasd. ioi e.) (4) They generalized too hastily both in the way of induction and deduction. (Phileb. 17.) (5) They chose sensible in the place of ideal distinctions. (6) They substituted abstract reasoning from a single isolated notion for real inquiry into the nature of things. (7) They preferred the exercise of logical ingenuity to the common interests of mankind. (" Water, the cheapest of commodities, is the best, says Pindar," Euthyd, 304 b.) (8) From the want of any true command of ideas, they distinguished in the wrong place and failed to distinguish in the right. These errors arose in great measure from making victory and not truth the end of discussion, and the mental result of the pro- cess was a vain-glorious scepticism. Such at least is Plato's ver- dict on the character and tendency of much of the intellectual activity of his day. And he has occasionally, even in the person of Socrates, given not unconscious illustration of this Attic euphuism, just as our own master of thought and ex- pression sometimes condescended " to speak most infallibly" in the " conceited" vein of his contemporaries. Now it is a chief purpose of the present dialogues to coun- teract this vice of the reason, by conveying wholesome ideas about logical method. And one idea which they convey with tolerable clearness, by example if not by precept, is that the right course to be followed in an inquiry cannot be altogether prescribed by rules, but is in great measure the direct result of original thought and inventive power in the inquirer?. f Plato seizes upon this as the key- gested, in the infancy of logic, the stone of their method, a principle bor- notion that positive and negative attri- rowed from the Eleatics,who in saying, butes are absolutely incommunicable. " Being is," " Not-Being is not," sug- £ Cf. especially Phsedr. 269 e. GENERAL INTRODUCTION. xiii Whether the method of divisions or some other shall be em- ployed, what general form shall be selected for tho primary division, where to draw the line in each subdivision, when to introduce example and comparison, when to exchange logical for metaphysical reasoning, and when to seek the aid of imagination; all such points are entirely left to tho prescient insight and selective judgment of the leader of the discussion. y. Another lesson not doubtfully taught in these pages is, that the subtilty of nature is not exhausted by a single line of classification. The several paths by which the Sophist is approached, and the shorter and longer way to the definition of the genus Homo in the Politicus (not to dwell now on the ironical humour of this passage), shew that method has not yet stiffened into system. The division of the arts of life not into two but seven distinct "limbs," warrants the same inference, which is strengthened by the comparison of other dialogues (see next section), and by the playful and satirical uses of generalization and division noticed above. (§ 3.) In both dia- logues the "divisions" at the opening and the close belong rather to the framework than the substance of the thought, and the real movement of the argument is almost wholly in- dependent of this outward form ; though certainly not inde- pendent of the great laws of agreement and difference, of which Plato's crvi/aycoyq and biaipeats are the expression. Plato's views on method, when thus stated, may appear strangely simple, as the errors to which they are opposed were gross ; but the errors, however gross, were typical : and his thoughts, however simple, may find many an instruc- tive application in the later history of science. That all true method is an extension of the natural operation of the mind, and, instead of making inquiry an easy task for all men, is inseparable from that last and highest acquisition and gift, the philosophic spirit, are maxims of which the schoolmen and Bacon were equally in need. The " prudens qugestio" of the latter (the " mental initiative" of Coleridge) is a notion which, at the expense of consistency, redeems the misconception of a levelling method by approaching to the Platonic point of view. Nor is it fair to speak of the method which Plato approved as merely subjective (G. H. Lewes), in the face of his protest xiv (JKNERAL INTRODUCTION. against the arbitrary manipulation of logical forms. His metaphysical ardour docs not prevent him from blaming, but rather constrains him to chastise those who in their frigid ingenuity closed their eyes to the light of facts. His faith in dialectic was, in other words, a faith in an order of the Uni- verse which could be discovered by the patient use of genuine inquiry, and by this alone. Although verification, in the modern sense, was almost entirely absent from his method, and his idea of " nature" was of course different from that which later discoveries have made familiar ; yet the importance which he attaches to the duty of following the real lines and veins of things as they are, of " hitting the joint" in carving the body of truth, and, what amounts to the same thing, the stress which he lays on the distinction between an accidental and a natural part (juepos and ei§os, a mere • portion find a form h ), are indications of a general conception of Jhe-- task of philosophy, Avhich is not to be confounded with the- '.German notion of evolving thought from itself, or the Scotch method of introspection in psychology. How facts are to be ascertained, he has not determined ; but that the discoveries of the true phi- losopher are matters of fact, and not mere notions of his own mind, is an axiom without which much that he has written would be unintelligible. But it is no less an axiom with him that every true fact is also an idea, and were it not so would be incognizable ; and that the only real concatenation of things as they are, is that which dialectic gradually reveals to the inquiring reason. Would Bacon have said otherwise, if "form'" were substituted for "idea," and for "dialectic" the "interro- gation of nature," a phrase which occurs almost verbatim in Plato's Politicus ? Or will any modern reasoner dispute the assertion that the Laws of Nature are only discoverable by the right exercise of Mind ? Plato's contribution to the positive science of Method was indeed most simple, but, at that juncture in the history of philosophy, of extreme value. Not to anticipate further here, what must be described at length in examining the " Sophist," his position is briefly this, that to divorce analysis from syn- thesis, negation from affirmation, variety from unity, distinc- tion from mutual relation, is fatal to the interests of inquiry. h Compare Protag. 329 d. GENERAL INTRODUCTION. xv "Cupid comes forth from an egg whereon Night hath brooded, i.e. Knowledge is obtained by exclusions and nega- tives." Yes, but Knowledge is affirmative, and the negations arc seen in the result, only like the dark spaces on a polarized spectrum, caused, as natural philosophers tell us, by the mu- tual interferences of waves of light. A contrast and a parallel, both taken from within the limits of the Platonic dialogues, may fitly conclude this section. a. When the peculiar form of dialectical exercise which at first sight appears to reign in the Sophist and Statesman, 'is compared with that of the more purely Socratic dialogues, abstracting from the Pythagorean notion of bisection and the Eleatic absoluteness of distinction, this mode of handling a subject appears like an abridgment of Socratic procedure. From long familiarity with the successive steps, the disciple is ready for a more summary process, and a generalization and distinction to which Socrates would have led the way through a morning of ironical banter, is now disposed of by a few rapid strokes. The argument from pleasure being the good to science being virtue, which fills several pages of the Pro- tagoras, would not have occupied ten lines of the Sophist. And a further stage of this transition from conversational profuseness towards scientific exactness and compression may be observed in the latter of these two dialogues, where the dichotomies, by which the art of weaving is defined, are enu- merated in close succession in a single sentence ; a doubly condensed form of intellectual nutriment, which proves too strong for the respondent to assimilate at once. (Pol. 379 c — 380 b.) /3. The parallel of the Philebus will be frequently suggested as we proceed by many likenesses of style and structure. We now confine ourselves to one point, which bears immediately on the question of method. There is a passage near the opening of that dialogue (p. 16) which distinguishes the right from the wrong application of the eternal opposition and inter- change of the One and the Many to the analysis and synthesis of ideas. It is interesting to examine how far the directions there given correspond to the procedure here employed. " In every enquiry we should set before us one idea, which we shall find, if we look for it, in the subject of our investiga- xvi GENERAL [NTRODUCTION. tion." So in oacli of these inquiries the idea of Knowledge, or of a person who knows, is immediately recognised and .selected for analysis. "And in this one idea we must look for two, if we can find two, or if not two, then the smallest number pos- sible." This rule is also strictly followed, which is the more noticeable, because no such principle is laid down in the Ph©- drus. In the case of the seven "summa genera" of civil life (Polit. 287 c), we are expressly told that it is impossible to divide them into two parts; and it would be obviously difficult to reduce the number, except by an abscissio infiniti, which would be out of place, because some of the kinds which arc in direct competition with the kingly art would then be left undefined. " We must then proceed to subdivide these units, until we see, not only that the one idea is both one and many, but also how many are its real subdivisions." In the Sophist and Politicus, as well as in the Pha3drus, the notion of the aTfjiriTov eTSos, or species infima, has an important place (cf. Soph. 289 d), and the danger of passing at once from the highest generality to the lowest specialty is exemplified (e. g. Polit. 263). " In like manner, when one is compelled to start from the indefinite (in cases where there is not immediately apparent a single comprehensive idea), he ought not all at once to spring from infinity to unity, but should find a number in the undis- tinguished mass, and so proceed from number to number until he reaches unity." (Phil. 18 b.) It is more difficult to prove that this precept is exactly obeyed. But the cautious spirit thus enjoined may be illustrated from several instances of gradual generalization, as where the speakers cry a halt to count up the number of forms in Avhich the Sophist has appeared, previous to one of these being selected as the most universally applicable (Soph. 231 d) ; or where from the narrower generalization, " nurture of men," they pass on to the wider conception of "care or superintendence of men" (Polit. 275) ; or where from the comparison of the king and the weaver (implying a provisional generalization) is evolved the more general notion of an art of combination (auyKptn/o/) (lb. 282 b). § 5. The forms of Sameness and Difference appear in the Sophist amongst the five kinds or forms which are selected GENERAL INTRODUCTION. x\ii for examination as being the "greatest," or the most universal. " Being," the highest of all, was found to embrace the oppo- site principles of " motion/'' the essence of the materialist, and "rest," that of the idealist philosopher. On comparing these three " kinds," each is seen to have sameness and difference, — to be the same with itself, different from the other two. And these predicates of sameness and difference are found to be no less universally applicable than the form of Being. Thus Being, Sameness, and Difference, to use Aristotelian language, are universal predicaments, or categories. Everything, of which we can speak, exists, is the same in one relation, different in others, and is either at rest or in motion or both in different ways. " Number" is incidentally mentioned in the same dia- logue (238 b) as being also an inseparable attribute of every possible term. Again, in the latter part of the Politicus, there is an enume- ration of seven kinds, as an ultimate division of the industries which are the helpers of the ruling power in a state. These are — raw-material, instruments, reservoirs, vehicles, cover- ings, amusements, food. To these summa genera of human labour is added the work of servants of every sort. And it is not obscurely implied, that with the addition of the royal science as a moving and regulating cause, this enumeration affords an exhaustive analysis of human activity. Thus in both dialogues there is seen a tendency to select certain natures or ideas as being the highest and most comprehensive, either of all ideas, or of the ideas belonging to a particular subject. If we except the Tima^us, where something similar is observ- able in the constitution of the Psychical Substance (p. 35) and in the five elements, which however are not viewed as by any means ultimate 1 , the only other dialogue where there is a similar enumeration of categories is the Philebus, where Being is analyzed into Limit, the Unlimited, their union, and the cause of this ; and the end of Being, or the good, is embraced in five kinds, Measure, Symmetry, Reality, Mind, and Pleasure. An approach, however, to a similar notion may be traced in two places of the Thesetetus : first, where the ideas selected as the undoubted objects of pure mind are Being, Not-Being, 1 Tim. 48 b : ouS' iv a-uWaPrjs slSeai povov. A remarkable anticipation of modem chemistry. d xviii GENERAL INTRODUCTION. Sameness and Difference, Likeness and Unlikcness, and Num- ber J; and again, where in the "aviary" of tbe mind, wbile most of tbo " birds" or knowledges are collected in larger or smaller groups, a few arc seen careering through every part. (ThesBt. 197 c.) Tbis peculiarity of these three dialogues, Pbilebus, Sophista, PoliticuSj affords a point of comparison or rather of approxi- mation between Plato and Aristotle. The only previous attempt at ultimate classification had been the oworoixiai of tbe Pythagoreans, and in the greater number of Plato's dia- logues, even where ideas (or forms) are mentioned, there is no selection of a certain number as supreme and as embracing all others, except partially in the case of moral ideas. Even when the form of good is described in the Republic as surpass- ing in glory and dignity the idea of Being, this saying has rather a cosmological and ethical than a logical or metaphy- sical meaning. But here not only is the word yiios for the first time k employed in the technical sense, but each of the terms so described is viewed as a universal, containing a variety of species, and obtained by a process of induction (aw ay cay i]. See Phileb. p. 25) ; and each enumeration is, for the time being, and in relation to the particular question raised, regarded as ultimate. This is therefore a nearer approach to a doctrine of categories than the casual reference to quantity (Soph. 245 d, Phileb. 24 c), quality (Rep. 4, 438 b, Theset. 182 b), relation (Soph. 255 c, Phil. 51 c), action and passion (Theset. and Soph.), in scattered passages. But the categories of Plato are not connected with the theory of Predication, towards which, as appears even from Soph. 261 c, Plato had made but little progress. Even those of the " Sophist" are rather ontological than logical, and are more nearly analogous to the " four causes" of the Metaphysics : denoting, to use a convenient distinction of Plotinus, rather the elements than the kinds of Being. And he is less bound than Aristotle to his own forms of thought. The enumeration is in no two places the same. In the highest region of dia- lectic Plato still asserts the freedom of Mind. He "stands J Theset. 185 d. Compare Parrnenides, p. 129 e, where Eest and Motion are added to these. k The only exception is in Phasdrus, 271 b. GENERAL INTRODUCTION. my behind" the forms which ho has invented to express what cannot be fully expressed, the electric play of thought. Col- lection and distinction, union and division, finite and infinite, same and other, one and many, Being and Not-Being, are various names for the two poles on whose attraction and repul- sion depend the " high-strung harmonies'" of the ideal world. § 6. Not less peculiar than the method of these dialogues is their structure, style, and diction, which, however, receive considerable illustration from the Philebus, Timaeus, and Laws. To take first what is most obvious, Socrates is no longer the chief speaker. A stranger from Elea, with whom Theodoras, Theaetetus, and the younger Socrates have been conversing, accompanies them to the place of meeting, where they are expected by Socrates; who, with his accustomed pertinacious politeness, brings on a conversation, but with the exception of a few words when there is a change of subject, is silent for the remainder of the morning. In this respect this pair of dialogues is like the Parmenides, Timaeus, and Critias, and resembles the two last named also in another equally external point, namely, that each pair form the middle part of an unfinished tetralogy. Plato has only twice thus connected dialogues in a series. The Theaetetus, Sophist, Statesman, and Philosopher, are in this the counterpart of the Republic, Timaeus, Critias, and Hermocrates. The retirement of Socrates, however, though in keeping with, will not account for, the other peculiarities of which we are now to speak. For the few words assigned to him at the beginning partake of the general change of tone. Nor can this be ascribed to the subject ; for the subjects of either dialogue, though related to each other, are wholly distinct. Every reader of Plato must have felt a difference in passing from the Republic or Phaedrus to the Sophist and Politicus ; or, may it not be added? to the Philebus or the Laws. He is like one who, after walking with a gifted friend in town and country, and hearing him converse with all men, sits down to listen to a lecture from the same person. There is an air of self-imposed restraint, at the first glance distinguishable from the absolute conversational freedom of the Gorgias, a didactic tone, unlike the Socratic dissimulation of knowledge, a vein of refined and biting satire, which may be contrasted as well d2 xx (JKNERAL INTRODUCTION. as compared with the naive and playful humour of the Phsedrufl or Charmides. As the student proceeds, he is struck by the more elaborate, though not more regular conformation of the periods, by the more frequent, almost monotonous recurrence of a certain rhythmical cadence, which he may have noticed here and there in the Phaedrus, Republic, and Thcsetetus 1 , by the precision of manner into which the Socratic urbanity has been transformed. And if he examines more minutely into the diction, he will find that the natural order is more often inverted than in the dialogues with which he is familiar, and that a greater fondness is shewn for unusual words, both poetical and technical, than in any dialogue except the Phas- drus, Republic, Timaeus, and Laws. In some respects the language approaches to that of tragedy, in others to the formality of an Aristotelian treatise. (i) To dwell a little more at length on some of these points : and first, on the more didactic and systematic manner of the con- versation. Nothing can exceed the courtesy and modesty both of Socrates and the Stranger in the opening scene, but when the Eleatic guest and his respondent have once crossed blades, he deals with him, not without pleasantry, but with a becoming degree of gravity, and secundum artem. There are no sallies, like those of Glaucon in the Republic, no sudden bursts of eloquence, as in the Phaedrus. With a tone of mild authority the philosopher, for the edification of the bystanders, guides his pupil by a path familiar to himself to conclusions which he foreknows. He acknowledges from the first that he is thoroughly conversant with the whole subject (Sia/oj/coeVcu ye (f)r] ao e^pT/ro toi? 6vop,acnv etVe koX jxtj. Aeyco be, Ota to ev kvioLs tS)v ovop.drcav fiiaiorepov xPWdai. Pollux, Onomasticon, VIII. 33, p. 206, 7.) More palpable, though not more real, than these general nuances of style, are certain peculiarities of diction. Of these perhaps the most obvious to a cursory reader is the use of technical expressions. Mr. Cope has well observed, in the Preface to his translation of the Gorgias, that one of the most striking peculiarities of Plato's philosophical writings is the almost entire absence of any scientific terminology. He adds, that "with the exception of one or two peculiar terms, such as etSos or Ibea and SiaAe/cn/cr/, and the special appro- priation of btdvoia and dvpoeibes in the Republic, and possibly one or two others, Plato's philosophy is absolutely devoid of any technical phraseology." This remark applies with perfect truth to the Gorgias, Pro- tagoras, Phaedo, and most other dialogues. The technicalities which occur in the Phsedrus (except biaXeKriKos, awayeayi], bimpeais) are quoted with contempt. But the Thesetetus already bears the marks of an opposite tendency, which becomes more decided in the Philebus, Sophist, and Politicus. Each theory advanced in the Thegetetus is characterized by an incipient terminology, which, like the theories themselves, is not entirely set aside. Thus to express the doctrine of Sense we have klvtjctls, noiovv, rrda^ov, aloOrjcns, alaQrvrov, cpopa, 7ToV arret, aladavop.eva, alaOrjrris, Kptr-qpLov, rb alo-da.v6p.evov, ttoi- 6tt]s, each having a definite meaning required by the theory ; and two of them, alaOrjrrjs and ttchot^s, being evidently new- fangled words. Other terms of the same kind which are pro- duced in the later phases of the discussion are eKp.ayelov, p.vr]- p.e'iov, emcrr-tjprjv eyziv, KenrrjaOaL, ersioTy\rd, aroL^e'iov, crvXka^r}, hiacpoporrjs. There are words of a more general character, GENERAL INTRODUCTION. xxv such as araXaftelv, 'to resume,' hiopi(zcr6ai, 'to distinguish/ which receive a preciscness of meaning from familiar use which they could not have had in ordinary speaking or writing. It is true that even Plato's technicalities are fresh from the mint ; they retain the gloss of novelty, and the hues of life. But no student of these dialogues can doubt that there was floating before him the conception of a scientific language, based on dialectic, which should express more perfectly than they were known to the first name-giver the true sections and combina- tions of things. The Heracliteans were indeed ridiculed in the Thea3tetus (183 b), because their theory confounded the ordi- nary use of speech : but even this ridicule shews that the notion of a philosophic vocabulary was already there. (Cf. ib. 166 b.) And in defence of one of the strangest of his coinages (Sofo/u/xquKTj), towards the conclusion of the Sophist, the Stranger gravely says that for want of the power of dividing "kinds" into their "forms" the vocabulary of the ancients was most defective. (Compare Cratylus, 436-439.) Yet he is careful to vary his new-made words, so as to avoid the hearer's being enslaved to them, and commends the youth with whom he converses for not setting too high a value on the choice of a name. (KaA<3? ye,a> Sajjcpares, k&v bia4>v\a£ri$ to [xr) crnovbafav k-nl tols ovoixam, Trkovcnobi.(TTL- kos, t avOpisbTiiKos, * av6p(oiro6r)pla, f airaTrjTiKos (Xen.), * aenra- \l€vtlk6$, ^avToirtokiKos, avTovpyitcos (M. Anton.), * fiakavevTiKoSj * 8r;/xoAoytKOs, * ho£op.i[ir)Tr]s , * Sojfo/xi/u^u/cds, * So£o7rcu8et>n/cos, bcoprjTLKOS (Philo.), bcopo\lKUariKO$. The following are found in other dialogues : — * ayKLarpevTLKOs (Soph., * ayxiaTpda Legg.), aypapLparos (Po- lit. Tim. Critias), dyooznoriK?; (Soph. Legg.), apLvvrfpLos (Polit. Legg.), /3taov- 6zt7]tlk6s (Soph. Legg.), opvLdevTcnos (Soph., dpvidevTrjs Legg.), iraiyviov (Polit. Legg.), 7rAeKUKo? (Polit. Legg.), t^Ken-aa-fid (Po- lit. Legg.), oracriaoTUos (Polit., oracrtcoreta Legg.), CTtyacrpia (Polit. Tim. Critias), f avyKpurLs (Soph. Phil. Tim. Legg.), , 8ix«t w j f bixoTop,S>, inrpoTTrj (tov Xoyov), kvdpyeia (met. from painting), Ae7rrovpy<3, * p.eaoTop.S>, 6vop.aaCa, Tra\4(t)s, f irpoa-aTro^aiVco, av- vdpi(p(i). Soph. Polit. — ( = assist in dividing). And, recurring elsewhere in Plato, — d-nopLepLfa (Polit. Legg.), ano- (tx^(>> (Polit. Legg.), ta0-X taTO? (Soph. Tim.), aropo? (Soph., cf. arpjyros Pha3dr.), ye'i-os (as a metaphysical term, Parm. Soph. Polit. Phil. Tim. Legg., and once in Phaedr.), *yrw- piens (Polit. Legg.), beapios (a bond uniting ideas, Soph. Polit. Phil. Parm. Tim. Legg.), bidyvaxns (Soph. Legg.), 8ta- XoyiCppLcu (Soph. Phil. Tim.), 8iapepA>&> (Polit. Phil. Legg.), * biav6r](n (to raise a difficulty, Soph. Tim. Legg.), biaKpifioXoyovp\ai (Soph. Tim.), 8taxwpt'(a> (Polit. Phil. Tim.), | &">p«rpos (Polit. Tim.), eKKptva (Polit. Legg.), emvepLGd (Polit. Legg.), fpe'0e£ts (Soph. Parm.), pep^co (Soph. Polit. Parm. Tim.), pepfc (Soph. Legg.), -napoo vvpnov (Soph. Legg.), Ttpoop.oXoyovp.ai (Soph. Tim.), iipocrKoiva>v(a (Soph. Legg.), a-vyKe(pa\aiovp:aL (Soph. Phil.), f avvoXos (Soph. Polit. Legg.), * o~vvop.oXoy(.a (Soph. Legg.), o-xtfa (Soph. Polit. Phil. Tim.), Top.r\ (metaphorical, Soph. Polit. Tim. Legg.). /3. Words expressing physical and mathematical conceptions : Soph. — fipaTToo, biaKivG> (? 226 b), TropKos, f TrXaaTos. Polit. — * depatperos, yvd\j/is, evrJTptos, tyrjo-Ls, koXXt)t6$, * /cpoKcoS???, f pe- raXXevco, vico, vr\6(a, vr\p.a, * ^airrjs, 7rAef is, o-ndprov, * avyKep- K[((a. Recurring — dp,€rpo$ (Soph. Phil. Tim. Legg.), avanv- kXt](tls (Polit. dvaKVK.Xovp.ai Tim.), avaroXi] (Polit. Legg.), dveiXCTTu (Phileb., avetXigts Polit.), dirXavijs (Polit. Tim. Legg.), f a^ea-ts (Polit. Legg.), /3po'xos (Soph. Critias), fyivzem (of production in general, Soph. Polit. Phil. Tim. Legg.), yvp.va- 0-7779 (Polit. Legg., 7rai.boTpi[3r}s is the usual word in Plato), t§ia0eo-is (Soph. Phil. Tim. Legg.), biaOpavw (Soph. Tim.), bidden? (Soph. Phil. Tim. Legg.), ^buqOziv (Soph. Tim.), * bpvorop.iK'q (Polit., * bpvorop.(a Legg.), Z , nio-K6vd(op,ai (Polit. xxviii GENERAL INTRODUCTION. Legg.), tTTcairevOG) (Polit. Legg.), cvkvkXos (.Soph., quotation from Parm., Tim.), IcrorraX'ks (Soph, quotation from Parm., Tim.), KaraK(fo-jU?7 (Soph. Polit. Lcgg.), ixirprja- is (Polit. Legg.), ^erp?jr6s (Polit. Lcgg.), irapak\a£t$ (Polit. Tim.), Trapd(j)opos (Soph. Lcgg., irapacpopoTrjs Tim.), 7n/£is (Polit. Phil.), 7rAdros (the dimension of breadth, Soph. Polit. Critias, Lcgg.), 7r\eyp.a (Soph. Polit. Tim. Lcgg.), rrpofBoXi] (Polit. Tim. Lcgg.), * patyr] (Polit. Tim.), avyxpaaLs (Polit. Phil.), avyKpiais (Soph. Phil. Tim. Lcgg.), avp.pu£is (Soph. Polit. Phil. Tim. Legg.), o-vixtti\G> (Polit. Tim.), * 0-vpnrobrjyovp.ai (Polit., irobriye'iv Legg.), avp.(pvi]S (Soph. Tim. Legg.), ovvv(palva> (Polit. Tim.), aa>p.a, " body in gene- ral,'^ to crwjuaroetSes (Soph. Phil. Tim. Legg. 896), ttjktos (Soph. Critias), TpoiTij, as an astronomical term (Polit. Tim. Legg.), vkrjV (Polit. Phil. Tim. Critias, Legg.), vitepoyj\ (Polit. Legg.), vcprj (Polit. Legg.). y. As the terms just enumerated betray Plato's love for those physical pursuits which were rejected by Socrates, so the new word aOeorrjs, which occurs only in the Politicus and Laws in all Greek literature before the death of Plato (unless we must add the seventh Platonic Epistle), affords an indi- cation of his tendency to religious thought. And it is a fact worth noticing in this connexion that the word ayios is con- fined to the Sophist, Critias, and Laws, amongst the Platonic writings, and ol KpeCrroves as a euphemism for ol 6eoC to Soph. 216 b, Epist. 7, 326 e. Perhaps the notion of technical language (voces artis) may be thought to be unduly stretched in being extended to some of the words under the last two headings. But in whatever way they are described they are equally suitable to be adduced in the present section, whose object is to define and illus- trate peculiarities of diction. There remain to be noticed words borrowed from the poets, and especially from the trage- dians : respecting which it may be observed that the affecta- tion of unusual phrases, which appears in the Phaedrus as the result of a half playful dithyrambic and epic fervour, at which p The introduction of this word is TrpooToyevh elSos in the Politicus is interesting in connexion with Ari- one of the few anticipations in stotle's Material Cause, of which the Plato. GENERAL INTRODUCTION. xxix Socrates himself wonders, is here interwoven with grave and unimpassioncd talk, giving a tone of sustained dignity to the style. To this class (8) belong : — Soph. — avT(0ey- ktos, bvcreib/js, eia 8?/, davcFTepov, ^KaOibpvGO, piaXOaK&s, vcIkos (quoted from Emped.), 6Xkt6t]p6s, pvfxrj, v\}/66€v. Polit. — a\e£r]Ti]pios (Xen.), &Xis (Xen.), airaypm (Thcophr.), aTroAe/xa)? ^X ( - lv ) a^ 1 " 7 ?^ *apyvpap.oi[S6s (cf. xP urra M ol /3os), fior)- Xcltt]?, (3ov(pop(36s, yereiw, bioiypa, e^avOco, evyi'oocrros, evKpiro?, %(pebpo$, Otacros, K&Tayp,a, Kepaa ) oirXicrpLa, napeia, itepLamij, TToXvirXavijs, 7rpo, crvvayvpp.6s } crvvaTio- reAw, * irpoaipeiffBat, i[i, (pvAov, v eip.apju.eVa t&v 'Hpa/cAeiW kKTeXevraadai icovcav ( = tov 'HpanXrj reAeuray rovs ttovovs Toiavra, cogn. ace). In the So- phist, where much has to be said of various processes, this form of expression is often found convenient, e.g. 221 a. to ttjs — TrXrjyfis — avaair^ixevov, " the stroke effected by an upward jerk ;" cf. Polit. 271 a. to e£ aXXrjXav — yevva>p.€vov. By a fur- ther extension of the same usage, the verbal noun in fj.a often means not the result of an act, but the act or process itself: so 5?p\.top:a, Soph. 262 a ; yeWrjpa, ib. 266 e ; ptprjp:a Polit. 274 a ; and, as I venture to think, o-nipp.a, ib. 272 e. The case of 8pe[xp.a, ib. 289 b, is even more peculiar ; here a transition is made from the act to the means by which the act is performed, just as often happens with the English verbal noun in ing (e. g. furnishings, trappings, dressing, &c.) . v. One instance at least occurs of the infinitive used for the imperative : Soph. 262 e. av pot (ppafciv. vi. And one of the imperative put interrogatively : * Periphrases are altogether more frequent : e. g. t/Aos exew. GENERAL INTRODUCTION. xxxv Polit. 295 0. |u?) ^eoro) 8?/ — ; Cf. Aeschin. iii. %\ t 8n 1)^6.- \ir\v [Ai] a~nohr]\Ai}(T(ii ; vii. Partitive genitives arc frequent : c. g. Soph. 265 a. T1JS KTT]TlKrjS. Polit. 281 e. t&v ahi&v. Cf. Phileb. 56 a. teal £vp,Tiacra avrys avkrjTLK'q; viii. Attraction, of an adverb, Polit. 263. 66ev=evTev6ev, ov. of a verb, Soph. 263. ws eoue — yiyvevQai^yiyverai, ojs iotKev. Cf. Phileb. 61 c. ix. Apposition, a. Sing, and plur. kv rravra, frequent here and in Phileb. Polit. 306 d e. t&xos koI crcpobpoTTjTa kclI o^vrrjra — avro. b. Femin. and neut. Soph, to p.ev novrfpta Kakovp,evov. c. Masc. and fem. or neut. (concrete and abstract), Polit. 259 d. 7TokiTLK7]V nai ttoXltlkou KCU j3aaiklK.T)V KO.I fiacnktubv — ly rtavra ravra. d. Of clauses, (i.) To each other, Polit. 257 d. ravra — nonqreov ovk ciito- crrariov. (ii.) To a demonstrative : frequently to be or to be ye. Soph. 244 a. to be tovtov yfyvrjrai irav rovvavriov. Polit. 263 d. to be ye — to\\ hv — biovop.a(oi. lb. 308 e. ravrov br'] ju.01 rov(? rj (BacnkiK^ (patverai, K.r.k. (iii.) To a relative, Soph. 227 c. onep ijpov, K.r.k. lb. 236 d. o Se Kal tot rip,(peyv6ovv, K.r.k. x. The use of the neut. article with the genitive to express the abstract notion of a thing, is especially frequent in the Politicus and Laws. Polit. 263 c. to rqs airoirkav^aecos. lb. 274 d, to rod pjvOov. xi. Ellipse (more frequent in the Sophist), a. Soph. 225 &• t<3 8e koyovs irpbs koyovs (yiyvop.£vu>). lb. 233 b. ]u.?jr' efyaivovro (6p9a>s avrikeyecv). lb. 235 b. bebeiKrai tolvvv (belv). lb. 238 c. pj} ov be (erretbav keyap.ev). lb. 248 e. to be {av (palev). Polit. 276 c. rt \J\v (ebei); — ekeyofiev (belv). lb. 301 b. TTpocnrotTJTaL be m 6 emaT'qp.oiv (apxew). f 2 ■i GENERAL [NTRODUCTION. b. Of to jxtv with to be following, Sopll. 221 0. VeVCTTlKOV /xtpOVS, TO 0£ TI(.(qV. lb. 267 b. veve\i-\\, to oe p.eOeto-Oo). Polit. 291 c. n//oavz;/8i, to oe jdaepoWcos.' to-xet. Cf. Rep. 455 e ; Symp. 207 d ; Theaot. 191c; Apol. 18 d. Cf. Horn. II. 22. 157. i. Pleonasm, a. Simple, of betv, Soph. 221 a. orrep npov6ep.eda Seu> e£ei>- p&v. Repetition of avros, Polit. 268 a (cf. the frag- ment of iEsch. in Rep. 2, 383 c) etvat, lb. 300 c. els hvva\xtv elvai. Comparative, lb. 288 b c. [xakXov — dp0OT€pOV. b. Redundant or explicit use of the participle, Soph. 225 a. 8vo\xa \eyeiv — TiQep.evovs. lb. 229 e. w y^pStVTai, to. pCev yakenatvovTes, to, be ju.aA(9aK&>Te'pa)? "napay.vQovixevoi. lb. 234 c. dboiXa Xeyop,eva. lb. 240 a. evl -npouei-nelv ovo- fjLCLTt. qb8ey£6.p.evos. lb. 243 b. p.ev. lb. 248 c. Xeyovcrtv 8ri — p.iv — be — (pum axrirep bpapa K.T.X. Gen. with irepl, Soph. 258 e. Trepl kvavriov twos — yalpeiv Xeyopev. Dat., Polit. 295 e. rw be to. bUaia — k.t.X. Ace, Polit. 295 d. Trav to toiovtov ^vpfialvov — ye'Acos av 6 lieyicrTos yiyvoiTO t&v tolovtojv vopLoOeTtjixaTcov. lb. 282 e. to p,ev oLTpoiKT^ — oaa hi ye av — . lb. 283 a. to ye nj? vcpavTLKris p — ye. xvi. The subject of the inversion of words belongs rather to the structure of sentences than to grammar. But it may be well in this place to call attention to the frequency of hyper- baton, especially in the use of particles. E. g. Soph. 263 c. ecpapev — irov. lb. d. p.ivTOL. lb. 264 a. OTav — av. Several of these modes of expression, such as the redundant participle, the use of the auxiliary verb, and the extension of the cognate accusative, not to mention the Ionic dative plural, and the peculiar effects of attraction, are in the manner of tragedy; and we may therefore be the less surprised at such directly tragic forms of expression as Soph. 238 a. pL-q-noo p,ey eiTTrjs. lb. 235 a. vvv vp-irepov epyov i]br\ tqv 6rjpa p.r\KeT avelvai. lb. 229 e. apxcuoTTpeiris tl iraTpiov. lb. 235 d. ov p,rj Trore exepvybv errev^Tai, or such "pregnant" constructions as in Polit. 271 a. abrjXov — 8tec/)#eipero. Cf. Legg. II, 926 b. paivop,eva Krjbevpara. xxxviii GENERAL INTRODUCTION. (2) It may bo remarked generally with regard to the structure of tho sentences in these dialogues, that they are more elaborate and also more irregular than in the greater number of Plato's writings. They have less of the sponta- neous movement of conversation, and in the Politicus especially are often more redundant and complicated. While the reader's car is filled with a peculiar stately rhythm, his attention is quickened by artificial or poetical collocations of words. These traits are clearly marked in the dialogues before us ; they may be traced also in the Philebus and some parts of the Phsedrus, and they are eminently characteristic of the Laws. Note for example the elaborateness and balanced formality of the following replies : Soph. 217 a. ri 8e fxaXia-Ta Kal to txoiov nepl avr&v biaTro- prjdels epeuQai bievoijQrjs ; lb. 224 c. kcu tl tls av dXXo elirvv ovk c\v ttA 17/^X067 TtXi]V to vvv ^r\rovp.evov avTo elvaL to crocpLcrTLKov yevos ', lb. 226 b. to ttoHop nepl clvtQv (3ovXrjdels brjXaxiaL, ■napabeiy- [xcvra Trpodeh Tama KaTa ttcivtcov fjpov ; lb. 234 b. ovbap.G>s' irdp.TioXv yap elprjKas ethos els ev ■navra avXXa/3o)v Kal a^ebbv iroiKiXdiTaTOV. Polit. 262 c. ■ndiov ovv brj s apTi bpav ; lb. 270 b. (paiveTaL y ovv brj Kal jxdka et/co'reos dprjcrOai irdvTa ocra bieXijXvOas. lb. 277 a. Kal KLvbvvevei y\ & £eVe, TeXecos av ijjuv ovtohs e\eLV 1] 7T€pl TOV TToXiTLKOV CLTlobeL^lS. lb. 284 e. /cat jieya y eK&Tepov Tp.r)p,a cures, Kal tsoXv bta- tpepov aXXrjXoiv. Compare with these Phil. 29 d. tls yap a-noKpiv6\xevos dkkos vyiaivcdv av hots, (paveirj ; lb. 32 d. 'Op0orara keyeLs otl TavTrj 7777 Set biaitopzv&rjvai to vvv p.eTabL(aKop.evov. lb. 47 c. TldvTa, a> 2w- KpaTes, to. crvpLfiaivovTa npbs tQ>v irokk&v dv6pu>iru)V ds bogav bee- Ttipavas. Tim. 29 d. "Aptora, 00 Ttjuate, iravTa-nao-i re as KekeveLS cnrobeKTeov to jikv ovv Ttpooifiiov cov davpLaaMS direbe^dp-edd aov, tov be brj Xoyov r)\uv ev apxovra, dXXd tlvcov vtyobpa yvvaiK&v. GENERAL INTRODUCTION. xxxix In these and numberless other places thcru is easily recog- nised the presence of a common typo. The same careful precision is observable in the cxplicitncss with which a ques- tion is often stated. See Soph. 218 c; 230 b, c, d; 248 d, e; 265 c ; Folit. 262 c, d, e ; 293 a, b ; and compare Phil. 12 c, d ; 15 b, c ; 18 b, c, d, and Legg. 637. Instances of redundancy and complication, of a somewhat harsher kind than those of the Phsedrus, Gorgias, or Republic, arising more from lengthiness than fulness, will soon enough become familiar to the student of these dialogues. Meanwhile the following passages may be taken as samples : Soph. 230 c, d; Polit. 288 d, 293 b, 298 c, d, 309 b. Compare Phil. 17 d, e ; Legg. 716 b, 740 d, 779 d. Such irregularities are especially frequent in the Politicus and Laws. In point of rhythm and the collocation of words, these dialogues hold, with the Philebus, an intermediate place be- tween the Pheedrus (to which may here be added the Theae- tetus and Republic) and the Timaeus, Critias, and Laws. Every reader of Plato is acquainted with the poetic cadences, which in his more highly wrought passages he occasionally introduces, not without a smile at his own magnificence. In the myths especially (to use his own words), he speaks with a tragic air, as if telling a tale impressively to children. (Rep. 8, 545 e. eux.coiJ.e6a reus Movacus direlv fjjjuv cc "0 77(77) cos 8r) irpco- tov crracrts e/xrrfcre," kcu cpconev avras rpayiKCos, cos 7rpos iralbas rjfjias irai^ovaas /cat epecrxTjAoucras, cos St) enrovhrj Xeyovcras v^\rrjXo- Xoyovixivas Aeyeiv ;) Examples will readily occur from the Protagoras, Symposium, Theaetetus (172—177), and the con- clusion of the Republic (where note especially the speech of Lachesis). It appears from the Phsedrus that these harmonies were not unconscious. The Socrates of that dialogue is sur- prised to find himself discoursing in this unwonted strain. When the afflatus of the higher rhetoric first descends on him, he says, " I am speaking almost in dithyrambs/'' and afterwards, when he breaks out into a verse in the epic metre, he remarks on this as shewing a further access of enthusiasm. The ironical shyness with which he at first ex- ercises his suddenly acquired gift wears off as he proceeds, and in the second long speech, or " palinode," he evidently "forgets that they are at play." Both speeches, besides xl GENERAL INTRODUCTION. such mock-poetical turns as £vp.p.ot. XafteaOe tov pvOov, — r.a- piTe bij, Opeppara yevvaxa, KaXXi-naibd re <\>albpov -neLQeTe, aro full of a sententious solemnity and rich music, to which the choice and arrangement of the words contribute largely. The following single phrases will partly illustrate this : 246 d. 6 pXv bij p.eyas fjyep.ihv ev ovpavu Zeus, eXavvotv T7Ti]vbv apjxa, TtpSnos iropeveTai. 247 a. tG>v dXXojv ocrot ev rcj> tG>v bubeica api0p<2 TeraypLevoi Oeol ap^ovTes. lb. b. ditpai' vtto tt]v vttov- pdviov &\J/Z8a TTOpevuvrai, irpbs dvavTes 7/877. lb. fipiOei yap 6 T?pi KaK??? iTf-n-09 p-ere^v. lb. 248 b. iroXXal p.ev yjuXevovTai, ■noXXol be iroXXa TTTepa Opavovrai, iraaat be noXvv eypvcrai ttovov areXels rrjs tov ovtos 6eas a-nepyovTai — where the alliteration also adds to the effect. The music of language, thus half-humorously struck out, seems to have had an increasing fascination for Plato, and sounds on unreservedly in his latest works. In the Tirnaeus and Laws these tragic and " dithyrambic" cadences are no longer occasional, but perpetual, and the speaker does not now "veil his face" with Socratic irony while uttering them. There appears an increasing preference for balanced phrases and "good mouth-filling" words. The rhythm, however, while more laboured, is less varied and less instinct with movement and life. The following examples are taken almost at random. Tim. 41 e. Scot be arrapeicras clvtcls els ra irpoarjuovra eK&aTcus e'/cacrra opyava \povov (pvvai ^wcoi' to 6eocrefBev 6 pJr) cpiXocrocpos rut/JAco- dels obvpop-evos av Oprjvoi p.aT7Jv. Legg. ] , 644 b. bel bi] ti]v Traibeiav p.r]bap.ov aTip\a(eiv, m irp&Tov t&v KaXXtorcnv tols aptarois avbpacn Tiapayiyvop.evov. lb. 2, 6$$ d. 6eol be olKTeipavres to tw d>0pw-nw e-n'movov ire^VKOs yivoq. lb. 654 e. pL&raios 6 p,eTu Tao0' fjpuv i:ep\ iraibeias opdr\<$ elff 'EXX-qvLKrjs ehe (3apfiapt,Ki]s Xoyos av elrj. lb. 66 1 b. to brj TeXos airdarjs paKaptoTrjTOS elvai to TavTa neKT-qpLevov aOavaTov elvai yevop,evov 6 u Tax}.o-Ta. lb. 3, 677 e. pcvpiav piev riva (pofiepav epr\p.iav, yrjs be acpOovov TtXr\- 60s Trdp-TToXv, ((aw be t&v aXXvv eppovTcav /3ovkoXl ajra, Kal el t( hov aly&v irepiXeicpOev yevos. lb. 7, 824 a. 77 tS>v bia-navp-ara iroVwi' expvera. lb. 8. 831 e. tov ] (tv iroOev euireTeorepai' e^eis zIttuv aWrjv oSdc. 234 d. kcu ixavTa TtavTt] avaTtrpcufidai ra kv rots Ao'yots (})avTdv irapayevopLevav. 242 a. Tj to irapairav iariov, et touto tXs tlpyil bpdv oWos. 259 d. oin-e tls eXeyxos ovtos ak-qOivos, apri re t&v ovtmv tlvos ecpa-nro- fxivov brjkos veoyevrjs &v. Polit. 26 1 e. Tt\ovcria>T€po5 ei? to yrjpas avacpavrjcreL (ppovr\- aem. lb. tt]V oe aytkcuoTpotpLKrjv dp' ivvoch irf] rt? btbv[xov anocprivas r6 (r}ToviLevov kv biirkaaioLcn ravvv iv rots fjpuo-etriv els Tore 7rot?/(ret (flTtlcrdai. 268 b. ovk akkos Kpeirrcoy iiapapcvdeicrOat /cat Kr)\S>v Tipavve.iv juera re opyav&v k.cu \jnk<2 ro3 aro'/xart tt]V tt]s amov Tro[p.vi]s aptara //eraxeioi^Oju.ez'o? p.ovmKi]v. 269 d. rots TtuvTcav OetoTaTois 7Tjoocr?]/cet fjLoi/6i§. 270 a. tot€ b OTav avedfj, 8V kavTov amov Uvai, koto, Katpbv acpzQivTa tolovtov, wcrre ava- Tiakiv iropzveo-Oai irokkas irepiobav p,vpiabas but to p-iyicnov ov kcu laoppoTto>TaTov eiri //eyforou fidivov irobbs Uvai. 273 d. 8to g xlii GENERAL INTRODUCTION. dri tot ijbi] Oebs o Kovfxijvas avrov, KaOopdv ev airopLaLS ovra, KrjbS[i€VOS tva fxi'i xdixdrrOeU ei? rbv rfjs bp.o lot 7]TO 9 aireipov ovtcl tottoc bmj, -nahXv ec/>c%>o? avrov tG>v -nqhaXmv yiyv6p.cvo$, ro vo(Ti](ravTa Kal \v9evra kv rfj na& kavrbv Trporepq, we/Hooto orrpo//as, Koap.el re Kal k-navopQ&v uddvarov clvtov kcll ayijpoiv airepyaftTaL. (This is almost in the manner of the Timseus and Laws.) ]Ol ol. C7rei yevojitvov y av olov \4yop.ev dyaTracrOai re av Kal oIkclv hLaKvfiepvwvTa eiiSai/xoVco? 6p0i)v d/cpi/3co? p.6vov rroKLrdav. 309. BtLav kv haip.ovm y[yvea9aL yivei. The following are selected from many parallel examples in the Philebus. 18 d. tovtov rbv beapLov av KoyLadfxevos cos ovra era Kal TTCLvra ravra eV 7rco? noiovvra, \iiav eV avroLs cos ovaav ypapL/JLaTLKip riyvtiv €77€(p0iy£aTO irpoa-eLTtow. 45 d. to be rcor a(pp6v(0V re Kal vfipLaT&v pe'x/H p.av(as rj o-(pobpa rjbovi] Kareyovaa TTepLJBorjTovs 2)co- Kpares, eWe yiyveo-Qai tl ko.k6v. (Where there is *a manifest approach to the structure of an Iambic line : o~vp\p.LKrov ap eWe yLyveadai KaKov u .) 66 b. Trpwrov pikv irepl p.irpov Kal to p-irpLov Kal irdvra OTToo-a XPV roLavra vop,l(€LV tijv a'CbLov rjpfjo-dal abvo-lv. 67. Kal robs 6-qpicov epcoras olovTai Kvpiovs eirai p,dprvpas p.dKKov rj tovs kv Movo-jj (pLkoaocfxi) ^ep^avrevpevcav l/cacrrore Koyojv. Whatever may be thought of a matter which depends so much on individual impressions as this of rhythm, there can be no question that the transposition of words from their natural sequence, either for the sake of sound or emphasis, which was noticed occasionally in the Thesetetus, Appendix A. p. 218, becomes more frequent in these dialogues. See, for instance, the hyperbaton of vvv in p. 218 b, and two other places of the Sophist; and Polit. 268 e (rroAAd — hy\), 2j6 c (eTnpe'Aeia — Kal — riyv-q), 280 d (ocrat re irepl rds kXottcls Kal rds /3ia 7rpd£ets Sia/ccoAuriKa tpya irapexovraL re'x/'cu (ppaypdrcov x ) . In more than one passage this has been the chief source of difficulty to interpreters. Nor will it be denied that the same symptom of laborious and artificial arrangement reappears with increased frequency in the Laws. u Cf. Polit. 300 a. rod krkov rod wpSaOiv fj-el^ov en tovto yiyvoiro kixk6v : sug- gesting the line too irp6o-9e nti(ftv tovto ylyveTai ko.k6v. x Soph. 253 c. Sia TtdvTcnv el (for el 5ia ■kolvtwv). lb. e. lSe7v /j.ev xaAe7rbi> evapyoi? Kal tovtov. Polit. 260 c. Trjs £wiTa.KTLKrJ9 ws ovto. avTbv t£x v7 I s - lb. 27O C. T0ls iVTOS Tlu'lV OlKOVfftV O.VT0V. GENERAL INTRODUCTION. iliii § 9. The relation of our two dialogues to the Philebus on the one hand, and on the other to the Timacus and Laws, which is indicated by this general survey of their scope, method, style and diction, and may perhaps be confirmed when each is oxamined separately, contains the answer to the question raised by Socher, Are these dialogues Platonic or Antiplatonic 1 The single point of authorship is iudccd sufficiently decided by three references of Aristotle (Met. vi. 2, § 3, 1026 B, Ato Ylk&TWV TpoTTOV TiVa OV KaKtoS T7]V aO(f)L(TTLKr]l> TT€pl TO fJLT] ov fragev: ib. xi. 8, 1064 B; xii. 2, 1089 C), and in reference to the Sophist few Platonic scholars will not feel the force of Dr. Thompson's words (Genuineness of the Sophista, p. 5) : " So far as the mere style is concerned, there is no dialogue in the whole series more thoroughly Platonic. In their structure the periods are those of Plato, and they are unlike those of any other writer. Throughout, it seems to me, the author is writing his very best. His subject is a dry one ; and he strives to make it palatable by a more than ordinary neatness of phrase, and by a sustained tone of pleasantry. His style is terse or fluent, as terseness or fluency is re- quired : but the fluency never degenerates into laxity, nor the terseness into harshness. The most arid dialectical wastes are refreshed by his humour : and bloom in more places than one with images of rare brilliancy and felicity. Few besides Plato would have thought of describing the endless wrangling of two sects (?) who had no principle in common, under the image of a battle between gods and giants; and. fewer still, had they conceived the design, would have ex- ecuted it with a touch at once so firm and so fine. What inferior master could have kept up so well and with so little effort, the fiction of a hunt after a fierce and wily beast, by which the Eleatic stranger sustains the ardent Thesetetus amid the toil and weariness of a prolonged logical exercitation ? Or who could so skilfully have interwoven that exercitation itself with matter so grave and various as that of which the dialogue in its central portion is made up ? If vivacity in the conversations, easy and natural transitions from one subject to another, pungency of satire, delicate persiflage, and idiomatic raciness of phrase are elements of dramatic power, I know no dialogue more dramatic than the Sophistes/'' 2 2 mu GENERAL INTRODUCTION. But the objections of Soulier are not thus met, or rather the difficulties which he raised arc not explained. And yet the solution of them may contribute something towards a theory of these dialogues, and may even throw some light on the history of Plato's mind. i. Sochcr objects first that the dichotomies, unlike the divi- sions of the Gorgias and Philcbus, arc meaningless, arbitrary, accidental, and tastelessly prolonged. It has been shewn that division as a logical exercise was at one time rife in the school of Plato ; that the use of that exercise here is propaedeutic and provisional ; and that the method while used is also criticized, modified, and partly rejected : that its use here is not more singular than that of etymologies in the Cratylus : and that as the Cratylus vein recurs occasionally in. these dialogues, so traces of the method of dichotomies appear in the Laws. The use of the method is also seen to be an approach to Aristotle, who makes use of some of the divisions which are here in- vented. %. " The absence of humour, seen especially in the gravity with which trivial examples are worked out." Whatever may be thought of the humour of these dialogues, they are not less humorous than the Timseus and Laws. And whoever misses humour in them, will probably find the same want in the greater part of the Philebus. Soche^s objection is really based on the prominence which is given in these dialogues — and also in the Philebus and Parmenides, and in a different way in the Laws — to the idea of method. And it may be retorted that the " gravity" is often that of the accomplished humorist, who does not " himself laugh, to set on some quantity of barren spectators to laugh too/'' 3. "Plato identifies Being with the ideas; Not-Being with the objects of sense: the object of opinion being intermediate. (Rep. v. 477-480.) The Eleatie Stranger takes no account of this absolute antithesis of Being and Not-Being. Being, with him, is the sum of all positive notions. Plato, on the other hand, takes no account of the logical antithesis or correlation of Being and Not-Being." 4. " Further, the Sophist contains a criticism of the Platonic doctrine of Ideas." These cardinal objections can only be fully met in the sepa- rate Introduction to the Sophist, Meanwhile the reader GENERAL INTRODUCTION. xlv may be asked to bear in mind what has been already said of Plato's modification of his theory of Knowledge, and the un- doubted approximation to the Aristotelian point of view which appears in the Philebus, Timseus, and Laws. And we may notice, as a discrepancy of the same kind, the final rejection in the Thesetetus of a definition of Knowledge, which might well bo thought essentially Platonic, namely, " True opinion able to give a reason of itself" (S6£a aKiiQ)js juera Koyov). 5. To the Politicus, besides the general grounds (1 and 2), Socher objects that the political notions here advanced are not in harmony with the Republic, and still less with earlier dia- logues. The examination of this point must also be reserved : but we are in a position to remark that there is a third case not put by Socher, viz. Is the Politicus intermediate between the Republic and the Laws ? 6. Lastly, he observes that the idea of the Divine Govern- ment, implied in the mythical description of the Saturnia regna, is wholly unlike what appears in the Phsedo, Republic, Tima3us, and Laws : with which the notion of God ever leaving the helm of the universe is wholly irreconcilable. The signifi- cance of this remark will be developed, when the Politicus is considered separately. At present it may be enough to point to the well-known passage in the tenth book of the Laws (896 e), where an independent evil soul is postulated in order to account for evil ; with which compare Rep. 2, 379 c, "God, since he is good, cannot be the cause of all things, as most men say, but of what happens to mankind little is due to him, and there is much of which he is not the cause : for our good is much less than our evil." Each of Socher's objections, although inconclusive, arose from the perception of some real peculiarity, of which those who maintain the genuineness of these dialogues are bound to give account. It will appear in the sequel, whether any light is thrown upon this subject, when they are viewed, as by the indications of style and diction we have been led to view them, in especial connexion with the Thesetetus, Philebus, TimaBus, Critias, and Laws. INTRODUCTION TO THE SOPHIST. OF the title given to this dialogue by the early grammarians, 2,o(picrT7}9, rj Trepi rod ovtos, AoyiKo'?, the name Sophistes is so far acknowledged by Plato himself, as in an allusion to it which occurs in the succeeding dialogue, the form of referenco used is kv rc3 o-o<^6aTr) a : i.e. "in discussing or defining the Sophist." And nothing can be more explicit than the manner in which this subject is proposed for definition in the opening scene. Yet it may not unnaturally appear to many readers that the remaining words, although of less authority, describe more accurately the real subject of the dialogue, in which, it may be thought, either two distinct inquiries are sought to be combined by a tour de force, or the former of these is only the occasion, excuse, or starting-point for the latter. The questions which occupy the largest and certainly the most important place are concerned with the nature of nega- tion, the relativity of ideas, and the defects of early speculation on the idea of Being. It may not seem obvious why these metaphysical questions should be necessarily involved in the study of a class of per- sons whose procedure and influence was a matter of historical fact ; or, again, supposing it necessary to raise and discuss such difficulties, why they might not have been equally sug- gested by some other example. We should bear in mind, first, the extremely abstract and general manner in which Plato looks at every problem ; the rarity of the metaphysical atmosphere in which he lived. Rightly or wrongly, he passed at once from the simplest to the deepest matters of thought : a Such an aUusion to a previous dialogue is rare in Plato, and can hardly be paralleled except from the Timaeus and Laws. INTRODUCTION TO THE SOPHIST. xlvii like one possessed with a great passion, " examples, gross as earth/' suggested to him the same themes, always old and always new. Just as, in the Philebus, the distinction of pleasures into good and bad suggests the problem of the one and the many, the description of the Sophist as a " phantastic artist" raises the whole question of the existence of the appa- rent beside the real. But, secondly, the connexion of thought, though at first sight remote, is, in this case at least, far from being arbitrary or accidental. As the question is a cardinal one, so is the instance by which the question is introduced. Plato is not merely clothing an ontological discussion in the garb of flesh and blood : it is at least equally true that in the ontological problem he sums up the difficulties of life and experience in the most abstract form : difficulties and con- tradictions which he had elsewhere illustrated with dramatic power. And the name Sophistes itself expresses a provisional generalization, or vindemiatio prima. As in the Theaetetus, the theory " Each man the measure of truth to himself" is the most general expression for all opinion that is not founded in reason, so the Sophist, even before definition, is, as he is described in the Republic, only the conscious reflection and embodiment of ordinary thought. The fact remains, however, that the dialogue is naturally divided into two main portions, one of which is enclosed or embedded in the other. In the opening and concluding passages (I.) an attempt is made to form a definite conception of the genus Sophist by the method of dichotomies, i. e. through logical divisions to follow the ramifications of the tree of know^- ledge till the particular branch which supports him is dis- covered. But there is a point (p. 236 d) at which this series of divisions is interrupted by what is formally a long digres- sion, but really the most serious part of the whole (II.), where instead of dividing and subdividing, the mind is carried up to reconsider the first principles on which this method of distinc- tions, and all criticism and controversy, rest ; in other words, to examine the meaning of negation, which cannot be deter- mined without also examining the nature of positive concep- tions. When this question has been set at rest, the divisions are resumed (p. 264 b), and a definition is obtained, in which the interlocutors acquiesce with more satisfaction than is xlviii INTRODUCTION usually expressed at the conclusion of a Socratic dialogue. It will bo convenient to treat these portions separately. In I. the problem is presented in the concrete, but still in a very general aspect. According to the habit of Socratic induction it is assumed that the name Sophist, though applied to a great variety of persons, has one meaning, which may be ascertained by a process of definition : just as the word 'angler,' which is defined as a preliminary example, has one meaning which can be clearly conceived and expressed. A modern respondent might have questioned this assumption at the outset, and have challenged Socrates to prove that the word had the same meaning when applied to the poets by Pindar, to the geometers by Socrates himself, to Zeno who denied motion, to the Heracliteans who denied all else, to the philologer Frodicus, and the astronomer Hippias, to Gorgias who ignored speculative truth, and to Protagoras who held every proposition to be of equal value. The possibility of such a doubt does not occur to Plato. He has in his mind a very simple, but a very sweeping distinction, for which the names ovbev tovtcov, to. bi ovra nal yeyovora to. fx^v ytipovrai Ao'yots Kal TTpdigeat. ra 8e toIs x€ipovjj.ivoi.s ovk e77trp€7iet). He contends, then, not with bodily but mental force ; not with long arguments, as in court, but through brief questions and replies : not on the infinity of details about which men wrangle, but on the general nature of the Just and Unjust, and of all other things : not, like some wearisome talkers, to the injury of his property, but (to note this point once more) to the increase of his gains. The So- phist's procedure is here characterized as essentially abstract and negative : being distinguished by the former quality from ordinary converse, and by the latter from positive science and philosophy. (225 a — 226 a.) It is not immediately apparent, however, how, under this description, the work of the Sophist is to be distinguished from the work of Socrates, except by the outward symptom that the one becomes rich by his trade and the other poor. And accordingly the two are brought into close companionship in the remarkable passage which follows. (226 b- 23 1 a) . Controversy is, or should be, an art of separating the false from the true, of determining what propositions are not tenable. And this amounts to a most valuable purification of the mind. For of separation there are two kinds, the sepa- ration of like from like and the purgation of the good from the evil : and of mental evils there are two kinds, that civil war of reason and passion w r hich is the disease of the soul, and ignorance, or spiritual ugliness, which is either conscious or unconscious. Unconscious ignorance is the last stage of mental deformity. And it is from this that men are freed when they are asked questions about something which they think they know, and are thus purged from the obstructions of conceit, without which purgation no learning will do them any good. This process is no other than the Elenchus. Shall Ave attri- bute this to the Sophist ? Plato stands in doubt. I12 In LNTRODUCTION We are thus led from observing a feature of the Sophist which any one might verity, to a theory of his end or function which is only temporarily admitted, and from which some- thing is at once detracted. For the value of his office, as a purifier of the mind, clearly depends in some measure on the reality of the arguments by which he convinces men of error. And these are presently shewn to be unreal. Yet Plato had a meaning in assigning to him this function even provisionally : and we have here perhaps the most striking appreciation of a contemporary phase of thought which is to be found in ancient philosophy. For it is the simple truth that Protagoras and Gorgias did imperfectly and unconsciously a part of the same work Avhich Socrates did thoroughly and consciously : that their reasonings were to be valued chiefly for their negative results : that in breaking up the ground of old beliefs they did indispensable service as the pioneers of philosophy : and that this clearing of the way, by the application of a shrewd and fearless intellect to all matters sacred and profane, fami- liar and unfamiliar, and that chiefly in the way of question and denial, was a necessary step of progress, as it was cer- tainly the most widely-spread intellectual phenomenon of the generation which immediately preceded Socrates. The differ- ence between him and them, which is left unnoticed here though implied in what follows, — partly because the historical Socrates no longer exactly squared with Plato's ideal, — is that the Sophist disputes as if he knew; Socrates asks questions as one desiring to know : the Sophist is contented with de- molishing an opponent's theory, he is not conscious of any further aim ; with Socrates each negative result is valued at once as a liberation of the mind from error, and as a forward step towards the positive apprehension of truth. This union or balance of the positive with the negative "arm," it is Plato's aim in this dialogue to vindicate and preserve. Thus the History of Philosophy, although not endorsing the assump- tion with which Plato sets out, that the common name Sophist must be significant of a common nature, confirms his estimate of the general tendency and common function of those to whom he assigns the name. Up to this point all is tentative and uncertain : and the definitions hitherto obtained are phenomenal merely. This is TO THE SOPHIST. liii manifest from their number and variety. For of an object which is fully comprehended there is one adequate definition and only one. In order to come nearer to understanding the Sophist's nature, we take up again the definition which appeared most suggestive, that which described his procedure as contro- versial. This art of controversy or disputation embraces all topics in heaven and earth. And those who admire the Sophist believe him to know all the things about which he disputes. This pretension refutes itself, for omniscience is not given to man. The essence of the Sophist is that he pretends to a knowledge which is unreal. Thus the disguises of our Proteus are stripped off, and we see him in his true colours, neither as a huntsman, nor as a merchant, nor as an intellectual wrestler, nor as a physician of the soul, but as the master of an art of illusion : a juggler, who imposes with the appearance of knowledge on inexperienced minds : just as the painter can pass off his shows for realities on the more thoughtless amongst young children. Hence he belongs to the multifarious class of imitators, or likeness-makers, and, not to dwell at present on the cardinal difficulty which this new notion involves, he is brought once more under a different summum genus. Hitherto, his race has been derived, by different lines, from the art of "getting/'' his origin must now be referred to the art of "making/"' all art having been at first divided into these two branches. " Creation" is Divine and Human, and each of these again is divided according as the thing made is real or only a likeness of what is real. A dream, for instance, is a divinely- made likeness or illusion. A picture may be called a humanly- made dream. Of human likeness-making there are two kinds : one where the likeness is real, the other where the likeness is only apparent and relative to the individual who sees the like- ness. The Sophist's arguments belong to this more shadowy or " phantastic" kind. And here he works not with instruments, but with his own person ; not with knowledge of the things he imitates, namely, justice and virtue, but only having opinion respecting them : not innocently thinking that he knows them, but hiding a guilty consciousness of charlatanry. By pausing here we should include the public speaker, who is the counter- feit of the statesman as the Sophist is of -the philosopher. He, however, imposes on the public in lengthened addresses, liv INTRODUCTION whereas the Sophist's business, as we have already said, is, by brief arguments, to compel individuals to contradict themselves. (281 c — 236 a, 265 a — 268.) The name is thus restricted to the dialectical as distinguished from the rhetorical aspect of the false use of the intellect. This is a distinction which Plato had not always observed : and in treating individual Sophists it was not easy to do so, for the two characters were often com- bined in the same person. Protagoras, for instance, as we learn from Plato's dialogue of that name, professed himself to be equally a master of copiousness and brevity. And Socrates ob- serves in the Gorgias that Sophists and rhetoricians are mixed up together, and know not Avhat to make of one another, nor do other men know what to make of them d . But Plato is here describing the ideal Sophist : and the function of fallacious scientific argument is ideally distinguishable from that of speaking so as to influence the feelings. The word is, how- ever, allowed to regain the more extended application in Polit. 291b, 303 c. 2o0t(TriK?/ is here characterized as a method, and is to philo- sophy what avTiXoyiK-r] is to 8ia\eKTi/c7j, what disputation is to scientific inquiry. It is possible that while restricting the application of the term on one side, Plato here extends it on another beyond the limits of his own habitual use. so as to include some of his own brethren of the Socratic family. He perhaps indicates that the Eristic tendency, which was growing strong by this time amongst the pupils of Euclides of Megara, w r as defective in some of the elements of a true philosophy. The reason for thinking that he means this is not merely the emphatic mention of the art of controversy, which Plato is fond of distinguishing from real inquiry 6 , but the direction of the whole dialogue against the extreme of Eleatic doctrine, on which we know that the Megarian logic w^as based. This hypothesis also accounts for the Sophist being identified with a picture of the cross-examining spirit, which, as Mr. Grote a He tells Callicles afterwards (p. Rep. 5, 454 a — c; Phaed. 90 b, 101 e; 520 a) that the Sophist is superior to Theset. 164 c; Men. 80 e. In this enu- the Rhetor, as the lawgiver is to the meration the description of the young judge: i.e. the Sophist furnishes the dialecticians in Phileb. 15 d e, should Rhetor with ideas and arguments. not be omitted : with which compare e The chief passages in which Plato also Rep. 7, 539 b. censures a.vri\oyiK7\ are the following: TO THE SOPHIST. Iv observes, not only resembles Socrates, but resembles no one else. For the Megarians followed Socrates in refuting opinions : but departed from him by separating the negative process from the inductive aim, and, in directing their method to the resolution of phenomena, and the establishment by this means of an abstract being, or goodness, or thought, returned partially to the dogmatism of Zeno. There are a few detached points which it will bo well to notice before we turn from this frame-work of satirical defini- tion to the larger and more dialectical portion of the dialogue. 1 . Though the Sophist is of course an artist and a man of science (for the definition proceeds through a classification of the sciences), yet the science of learning and knowing (to IAadinxa.TiK.bv — elbos 6\ov tG>v tz\vG>v koX to tt\s yv(ap[a€u>s) is the only heading of those introduced at first, viz.; (rtoirjTLKr) — k 7-7777/07 r— ; -i -^ t n [xadrnxaTLKi] Kal )^pr]p.aT- aycov- 6r]pevT- yvcopiaTiKrj laTiKij kttlkti <- k v)') under which no attempt is made to bring him. This touch of satire can hardly be unintentional. 2. The variety of definitions to which we are led by the process of dichotomies when applied to the Sophist, not only shews that his nature is difficult to grasp, but also proves the method to be one-sided and inadequate. The angler, an artist, by the way, who is known to Homer (Od. 4, 369), has easily a place assigned him, because the conception of his art, when analysed, is not found to contain elements which are imper- fectly known. But the activity of the Sophist is complex and various ; and when the principle, on which his other traits depend, is at last found, this leads the way to difficulties, which the process of mere logical distinction is powerless to resolve. And this for two reasons : because the difficulty lies in that notion of absolute difference on which the method itself rests; and because for the solution of the difficulty there is required the complementary notion of combination, commu- nion, correlation : which division cannot dispense with indeed (since the members of each division are unities and general forms), but throws into the background. AtaKptriK?) needs to be supplemented by avyif sameness and difference, on which this double process depends, arc related to each other in their most abstract form f . 3. The idea of purification, connected here with the Elen- chus, or negative dialectic, and in the Politicus with the banish- ment of offending members from the state (this being a political as the former was a mental purgation), though in both places illustrated from the art of medicine, probably originated in the mysteries and was derived by Plato from a Pythagorean source. Compare the KaOapixoC of Empedocles, and see pp. 80-82 of the Phasdo. It may be noticed that, in the Phaedo, the notion of impurity is associated with all that is sensible and bodily, as contrasted with the ideal : in these dialogues the evils deprecated are falsehood in the mind and wickedness in the state, which are only mythically identified with the corporeal element, and purification is the separation of the evil from the good. 4. The comprehension under one heading of the processes of dialectic, pharmacy, ablution, scouring, sweeping, and even clothes-brushing, gives rise to the remark that scientific method ignores all those distinctions of worth, respectability, triviality, and baseness, which rest on feeling and habit, and looks only on those resemblances and differences which are acknowledged by Reason. This may be compared with the saying of Parme- nides to the youthful Socrates, that when philosophy has taken hold of him as it will one day take hold, he will no longer have regard to the opinions of men, but will view all things, however vulgar or base, in the light of Universal Forms. On this point enough has perhaps been said in the notes. But there is some- thing extremely characteristic of the spirit of these dialogues, in the mixture of scientific calmness and ironical satisfaction with which the high things of this world are thus brought to the level of the meanest s. f See the passage of the Politicus is only partially applicable. (285 d) where the argument from ex- S Compare the treatment of rhetoric ample is vindicated on the ground that in the Gorgias as coordinate with cook- the highest subjects have no analogies ing, and in the Euthydemus as a de- which are immediately palpable, to partment of magic (rrjs twv incpSiov sense. It is to such as these that T6X"??s). classification as a method of definition, TO THE SOPHIST. Ivii 5. The form of evil from which deliverance is effected by refutation deserves a passing notice, although the thought is one of the most familiar to readers of Plato : the greatest igno- rance, i. e. ignorance which the mind mistakes for knowledge. So the false statesmen are said to have the greatest ignorance of the greatest of all subjects, in that they are ignorant of statecraft, when they think they are most certainly informed of this h . And in the analysis of the ridiculous, in the Philebus, the same bad eminence is given to the conceit of knowledge 1 . (See also Legg. 9, 863 c.) Yet in the conclusion of this dialogue it would seem as though unconscious ignorance were the less culpable ; for the Sophist is denned as having a guilty suspicion that all is not right within. The inconsistency of these two views does not seem to be noticed by Plato, who would probably, however, have said, if he had been taxed with it, ' that he meant by conscious ignorance, the ignorance of one desirous to know/ Still, the notion of a state of ignorance acquiesced in, not- withstanding a suspicion that it exists, is hardly reconcileable with the Socratic principle, which is here made the ground of the Socratic cross-examination, that no soul is willingly ignorant of anything. The more practical view, which is'turned to the disadvantage of the Sophist as an " ironical mimic," belongs to the later phase of Platonism. See the passage in the ninth book of the Laws, already quoted, where an attempt is made to reconcile the theory that injustice is never voluntary, with legislation for the exemption from punishment of involuntary crime k . 6. Plato's later manner may also be detected in the grave digression, suggested by the logical distinction of the Art of Making into Divine and human, in Avhich it is solemnly asserted that the world was made by God in accordance with Reason, and not by the spontaneous working of Nature or Chance. The tone of this passage closely resembles that of the tenth book of the Laws : where the persuasive demon- stration, the koyos juera ttciOovs avaynaias here spoken of, is applied to an imaginary case. The strong reprobation in which the opposite view is held, and the moral and religious fervour with which the answer of Theastetus is received, are h Polit. 302 a. ! Plrileb. 48 e. 1: Laws, 861-S64. i lviii INTRODUCTION in keeping with the impressive solemnity and earnestness of Plato's latest writings. (Sec especially Legg. 10, 889.) II. In defining the Sophist as an illusory controversialist, we seem to have caught him in our net; hut we only seem to have caught him : for hy his controversial art he will prove that our net is non-existent, and as we are allowed no weapons hut arguments, to he refuted is to fail. However shameless it may appear for a controversialist, who is daily detecting falsehood, to say that falsehood is impossible, he will use this argument in self-defence, and we must meet his logic with a higher logic or give up the battle. Our object will not merely be to refute him, for that would be after all only a controver- sial victory like his, but to throw fresh light upon the whole question which his art confuses, — that of the nature and cor- relation of the affirmative and negative elements in thought, or, according to the more objective mode of conception which Plato still preserves, of Being and Not- Being. Thus we are led at once to the most abstract form of the inquiry, the nature of the negative idea ; even the relation of this idea to a subject being through the greater part of the discussion left out of view. The Sophist is accused of making a false impression. But to speak of false impressions is to assert an existence which is in the same breath denied — to predicate reality of the unreal. Is this possible ? That depends on the meaning of the word not, and of the word existence, and their relation to each other. This question has a double bearing on the Sophist, of whose definition we are in search. If it is proved that this combination of existence and non-existence is possible, he exists, but his foundation is insecure, for his con- troversial art is based on the absolute mutual exclusion of these alternatives. If on the other hand his art is sound, he escapes refutation, but only by proving his own non-existence. There is hardly to be mistaken in the dialogue this twofold refer- ence, which is not a little perplexing to the modern reader, a reference on the one hand to the problem of the existence of phenomena, one of the deepest of all to Plato, and, on the other, to the oppositions of false science, that " last decom- position of the reason, which consisted in separating everything from all things 1 ." Yet both this error and that difficulty 1 Soph. 259 e. TO THE SOPHIST. lix arc included in the sweeping generalization of the fxrj 6v, and both are met by the new formula of the Relativity of Negative Expressions. This has also a bearing, as Plato did not fail to discover, on the method of logical divisions. Duaresis cannot be safely used apart from Synagoge. Classes mutually exclusive are still to be viewed in their relations to each other. The mind must not be dazzled by difference, so as to overlook resemblance, nor by resemblance, so as to neglect true differ- ences. By a resuscitation of the Heraclitean principle in the world of mind, it is again found that the objects of thought are held asunder and together at once (pLacjjepojxevov ael avixcpe- perat). And thus the notion of Being is not less modified than the notions of Appearance and the Negation of Being. For Being can be no longer held as a mere Absolute, but stands related to Not-Being, which it differs from, and yet includes. Here also it appears to the modern reader as if conceptions, which are to him radically distinct, are blended, not to say confused. For Being seems to be conceived at once logically, as the positive in thought and speech, and metaphysically, as an " hypostatized" idea. But in order to enter into Plato's meaning, it is necessary to study his position in this dialogue, as he has in some measure enabled us to do, historically. The fallacies which we find satirized in the Euthydemus are chiefly of two kinds ; in one of which all resemblance or analogy is supposed to imply identity and to exclude the notion of difference, while in the other all difference is conceived as absolute difference, exclusive of all resemblance and relation : ' If I know one thing, I know all things, for I cannot know and not know ; ' ' If Zeus is my God, he is mine to do what I please with him ; ' ' That which is different from the idea of beauty cannot be beautiful,'' and so on. And thus all propo- sitions except identical propositions are declared impossible, a theory which Aristotle imputes to the followers of Antisthenes. Another paradox, which is likewise attributed to the Cynic, appears in the same dialogue, — the impossibility of negative argument {\xr] zlvai avTikeyziv). The above is a humorous picture of the same notions with which Plato deals seriously in the present dialogue. That the same cannot be different, nor the different the same; that predication is impossible, that is, i 2 Ix INTRODUCTION there can be no relation between different ideas; above all, that falsehood cannot bo disproved, for that to deny existence, while naming existence, involves a contradiction in terms, — these are in substance the very theories which Plato here undertakes to modify. Now in accounting for these aberra- tions of thought, to say that the Organon did not yet exist, is to state what, though true and important to remember, docs not afford a sufficient explanation — aArjOcs \iiv, ovQlv be aa^h. It is true that in the shape in which they then appeared, they could have no strength now. But their strength then lay in a mode of thought, which prevailed very extensively in that age, and which had exercised a more powerful influence over Plato himself than any other except that of Socrates ; a mode of thought derived in great part uncon- sciously from the philosophy of Parmcnides and the dialectic of Zeno : the same which appears in such assumptions (familiar to the student of the Thesetetus) as that Socrates ill is a different man from Socrates well (Theset. 159 b), and that everything must be either known or not known by the mind (lb. 188 a). This may be described as the tendency to view every subject in the light of abstract alternatives : to apply the language of logic immediately to the sensible world : to reject as matter of fact that which cannot at once be formu- lated as an idea. This " disease," as we can imagine him to have called it, Plato here traces to its origin in the teaching of Parmenides, and thus redeems the promise made by Socrates in the Theaetetus, there not fulfilled, to examine the deep wisdom of this man : the greatest of those who uphold the indissoluble unity of Being. (Theaet. 183 e.) In doing so, he not only confutes others who had pushed the tendency in question to an extreme, (he rather uses them as a beacon to indicate where the truth does not lie,) but, what is of more importance, develops further, or at least defines more clearly, his own central point of view. For he also had yielded to the charm of " the Eleatic Palamedes" and had held Parmenides " in reverence and awe:" nor had the dominance of this idea been merely logical, but had amounted to a speculative convic- tion, may we not even say, a theological belief? We cannot tell whether this impression had at all been derived from Socrates, whom he has represented as meeting TO THE SOPHIST. Ixi with the philosopher in early youth. Socrates may have spoken of Parmenides, as he did of Heraclitus, though his own work in philosophy was independent of all influence from without. At all events it is quite possible that even during the time of his converse with Socrates, Plato may have been attracted towards the Eleatic School. His master's influence was unobtrusive, not hindering the accretion of ideas from all sides, and only after his death would be found to "comprehend all other." It was probably at a still earlier time that Plato's interest and curiosity was excited by the fine discourses and immense popularity of Protagoras and Gorgias ; and it is certain, on the authority of Aristotle, that his first deep draught of philosophy had been received from Cratylus, who taught him the Heraclitean doctrine that " all was motion." This theory, as then held by the enthusiasts of Ephesus, whom Plato has satirized, was the secondary and less noble phase of a great thought — that all which abides eternally is a universal ever-active Law of Becoming. Heraclitus was no materialist. " Matter" had no existence for him, and he denied the separate existence of all " Form" except the Highest Law, whose Per- manence is Perpetual Energy. In the hands of his followers, however, the assertion of this universal law seems to have degenerated into a mere doctrine of the relativity of particular being. And here the Eastern theorists were met by Zeno, who in support of the Eleatic faith in One Sole Being, proved that all relative existence was self-contradictory and inconceiv- able by Reason. Time and Motion, into which the sensible universe had already been resolved, were themselves annihi- lated. The movement of the intellect, by which this defensive negative process was effected, was the first conscious dialectic, the germ of much in Plato and of more in Aristotle, and, in conjunction with the Socratic Elenchus, the direct parent of the method which in this dialogue, and somewhat differently in the Parmenides, is turned against the hypothesis of the simple absoluteness of Being™. But however important logi- cally, the philosophy of Zeno, like that of Cratylus, while more definite, was also narrower than that of his master. He had m The Zenonian method is " parri- iartv el Kal evriv, aKard\7]Trrov av- cidally" turned against the Eleatic Opdi-Ktf ei Kal KaraX^wrdv, avsp^uiVTov doctrine in the thesis of Gorgias : ovdev Kal aSie^riy^Tou reus WAas. Ixii INTRODUCTION descen led from metaphysics to logic, and in endeavouring to linkl the Absolute against all comers had assumed an atti- tude which was purely negative, and had adopted a method which, though of great significance, was merely abstract, and not directly applicable to the solution of any real problem. Plato, however, had " risen to the height of the great argu- ment/'' and had felt, not only the dialectical might of Zeno, but the transcendental sublimity of Parmenides. It is possible that he may have derived some of his own most famous imagery from the opening lines of the poem on the Nature of Things, where the philosophic impulse is represented as a car drawn by swift steeds, and the philosopher as the comrade of immortal charioteers. Be that as it may, a modern reader can hardly imagine the effect which the impressive lines of Parmenides must have produced on the mind of Plato, when already convinced by Cratylus of the utter changeableness of " all that seems/'' Something analagous may have been ex- perienced by individual students of Spinoza, Kant, or Hegel ; but philosophical belief in modern times presents for the most part but a faint image of the heaven of contemplation into which Plato must have been carried away on hearing reiterated with the eloquence of energetic faith, and proved as a neces- sary truth of Reason, the absolute Existence of One Being, inseparable from thought, equable, unchangeable, without beginning and without end, with no past or future, but an everlasting Now ; however apparently discrete, yet really con- tinuous or omnipresent, so that differences of space are done away as completely as differences of time ; whence phenomenal distinctions of all kinds, relation, change, beginning, ending, time, space, motion, are thrust out of sight or are seen to vanish away. This intellectual movement, by which we suppose Plato to have been affected, was confirmed, but also gradually modified, by his contemplation of the work of Socrates. In reflecting on the manner and substance of that wonderful endless talk, and on the ruling motive of that unswerving life, he saw the elements of all previous speculation brought into antagonism and yet into immediate relation with the common thoughts and common life of men, — to whose mental and political state the issue of that antagonism had given a deep and bitter interest. TO THE SOPHIST. Ixiii Before the cross-questioning of Socrates, which brought men to know the vanity of their own knowledge, the most fixed opinions were seen first to waver, and then to disappear. This Plato associated with the changeableness of phenomena ac- cording to Heraclitus; which viewed subjectively becomes the relativeness of sense, according to the doctrines of Protagoras and Aristippus : a relativeness which at the touch of negative dialectic, such as that of Zeno, is reduced to nothingness. But the result of the method of Socrates was not merely negative. His aim was to define, that is, to lay bare the one conception which belongs universally and unalterably to each subject of inquiry. Tn such a conception, if it were found, his mind would gladly rest. This is well expressed by Aristotle, who says that Socrates was the first who checked the aimless career of thought, and fixed the mind on Definition : irpdorov Trepl opcaixovs emoT^a-avTos tjjv hiavoiav. Now there is here implied a new and independent assertion of the Absolute ; for the endeavour of Socrates had no meaning, if the " Know- ledge" which he sought were less than the knowledge of that which is always and everywhere true ; if the ignorance of which he accused himself and convinced others, were ignorance only of the relative, the transient, or the phenomenal. But this Absolute of Socrates differs from that of Parmenides in two important respects. i. The Substance or Reality of which he speaks is not asserted as if known, but sought for as still unknown. The Existence of Being, which Parmenides asserted with so much vehemence, is taken for granted, and the mind is called away from the absorbing contemplation of this truth to the consi- deration of a new problem, which may be thus stated gene- rally : " What is Being ? or What is the form of Being ?" The change of mental attitude expressed in these few words, — from asserting "Being is" to asking "What is Being?" is of the highest importance ; for without the consciousness which is here evolved, that knowledge is a synthesis of a less general with a more general notion, the growth of science would have been arrested. Philosophers would have been contented with either assigning universality to some particular thing, or, like the Eleatics, excluding the particular from cognition. 2. Further, he did not ask the question in this merely Ixh INTRODUCTION abstract form: he implied an absolute standard of truth and good; but, as the word "good" reminds us. his inquiries had an immediate bearing on the life of men. Hence, instead of attempting at once to solve the problem, " What is Being V lie sought to determine " What is righteous, what is un- righteous, what is a state, what is the true statesman, what is government, what is it to be fit to govern?" The solution of these problems was approached by what Bacon would have called a process of exclusions, through a series of hypotheses, which were successively modified or relinquished when in some case not found to apply to the subject of definition. And while things commonly confused were thus distinguished, things commonly distinguished (e. g. folly and madness) were not less unexpectedly combined. 3. The personal attributes of Socrates enhanced this union of the universal with the particular, and of the abstract with the concrete, in his method of talk. The eye that was fixed on the unchangeableness of truth and right, was the same which pierced through and through the follies of his contemporaries ; the lofty soul had a cynical exterior, the widest generalizations were hidden beneath the meanest instances, the imperturbable, urbane, ironical demeanour, helped to bring the dry light of reason into continual, immediate contact with the infinite anomalies of opinion and action; the strange being, unlike all other men, had a direct, unmistakeable influence on almost all. By contrast with him the hollowness of all pretence, espe- cially in other teachers, was clearly seen, while his example gave the appearance of meanness to those who taught for pay. Yet he was the first to admit their individual excellences and accomplishments ; while in conversation with him their real characteristics, their strength as well as their weakness, were most truly manifested. Thus with Socrates began a philosophic movement which in some elements was kindred to the Eleatic, but radically different in others ; — kindred, because vindicating by the refu- tation of falsehood an ideal truth; different, because inductive in method, and practical as well as speculative in ultimate aim — identifying truth with good. But in continuing and interpreting this movement, Plato at first dwelt consciously rather on the former than the latter TO THE SO I'll 1ST. Kv aspect of Socratic thought; rather on the absolute contrasl between the actual state of human opinion and the ideal of Knowledge, than on the nature of Knowledge as implying a relation of the mind to " Being," or of the Universal to the Particular. This, as may be gathered indirectly from this dia- logue, was partly due to the prevalence of the Elcatic impulse ■ — the conviction, namely, of the incommunicable perfection of abstract Being, the sole object of Knowledge or true thought: but partly also to the general law by which belief always precedes criticism. The problem of the post-Socratic philo- sophy for those who did not hold with Antisthenes that Defi- nition was merely nominal, was, granting the possibility of Knowledge and the existence of general forms, i. What is Knowledge 1 2. What are the dbrj ? And, from the objective character of the Greek philosophy, the first of these two ques- tions was chiefly, although not wholly, studied in the light of the second. In other words, the effort of Socrates was to find the etSos of man, justice, temperance, &c; that of his followers was to find the nature of the etSo? generally. But, just as the Existence of Being was asserted, before any one thought of asking, What is Being ? so, in entering on this new stage of thought, Plato believes in Knowledge and the Ideas before he examines them, and his dialectic is for a time coloured with a haze of imagination. He is at first contented with declaring that Knowledge is the only real ground of virtue, and that accordingly all virtue is essentially one. Presently a question rises about the Origin of Knowledge — How can Knowledge have a beginning ? For how can a man inquire into what he does not know ? How are we to conceive the transition from ignorance to certainty ? This question is answered, as Plato elsewhere answers questions which are not ripe for solution, mythically. We learn by recollection, as appears from the lessons of geometry where the teacher leads the pupil to draw forth from his own mind what the moment previously he did not know. Thus the "Eristic" objection is removed, that a man cannot inquire about either what he knows or what he does not know: and the anticipation of poetry and prophecy, that we are immortal beings, is confirmed. To learn is to awaken slumbering knowledge. " The Soul has been every- where and has seen all things, and therefore must have known k Ixvi INTRODUCTION ail things before coming hither: and if she can recover one thing only, there is hope that she may by courageous efforts regain the rest." (Men. 81 c.) By this hypothesis the true objects of knowledge arc relegated to another world than this and to a previous life. The objects of sense remind us of them through a process of association. (Phaedo.) These Eternal Forms the Soul beheld in her first flight, ere she lost her wings, when the impulse of the higher love carried her amongst immortal chariots, beyond the visible sphere, into the plain of truth, where Beauty, Justice, Temperance, Wisdom, dwell eternally, not as they are imagined but as they are known. (Phaadr.) This is the poetical mode of conceiving of the ideas, in which Plato embodied the feelings of wonder and delight with which he contemplated the first real inquiry which the world had seen. The object and end of that inquiry appeared to him surrounded with a mystic halo, — like his own image of Beauty, lightening from a transcendent height, — annihilating and making worthless the shadows which surround us here. But Plato was far from resting in this as a final theory of Knowledge. His belief in immortality and pre-existence remained, it is true ; but did not supersede other inquiries con- cerning the ideas, which were wholly independent of such a theory, and proceeded simply by experience and reflection. Thus in the Republic, the vision of the ideas in their purity, without help from sense, is the goal towards which the mind is allowed to climb up the ladder of hypotheses, and although we hear of an intellectual region, the context shews this language to be metaphorical, rather than mythological as in the Phsedrus and Phsedon. The line is still drawn sharply and broadly be- tween Being as the object of knowledge and Not-Being as the object of ignorance ; but, first, an intermediate state, having for object the changeable, which is and is not, is crudely imagined, and, at a later period of the discussion (bk. vii.), the succes- sive steps by which the mind rises from the lowest ignorance to the highest knowledge are supplied. No mention is made of recollection, unless we count as such the mythical account of Lethe in bk. x. ; and immediately after the allegory of the cave, in which the sensible has been represented as the copy of the ideal world, we have a piece of psychological analysis, in which TO THE SOPHIST. lxvii tho idea is spoken of as the universal element evolved by Reason from the impressions of Sense. " Intelligence is called in to determine between the contrarieties of sense. I see two fingers, one large the other small. Sight gives me opposite im- pressions respecting objects which are alike. But sight cannot answer the questions which the mind cannot but ask hereupon. Is this puzzling impression one, or two ? If two, then each is one, and so on. Thus intelligence distinguishes between great and small, which in the sensation of vision were confused. And then only are we induced to ask the question which reason suggests,, ' What is the nature of greatness and small- ness?' The ideas thus distinguished are objects of Reason, the former confused impression was received through sight." (vii. 534.) Such a relation between intelligence and sensation is ac- knowledged even in the Phsedrus, in the midst of the mythical description of the Plain of Truth : Aei yap avOpuirov avviivai k -nXriffidaas /ecu /j-iyels he is perhaps covertly satirizing the t<3 ovti ovtqos, yevprjeras vovv koX aArj- thoroughness of the Megarian logic. deiav, yvoit) re km. a\r)6cos {wtj «ai rpe- See Rep. 6, 490 b. Xlplv ab-rov $> sgtiv (poiro, /cot ovtoo A.17701 coSlvos, irplv 8' ov. Ixx INTRODUCTION fruitless isolation in which it has been placed by the first efforts of purely abstract thought ; and the reflection rises that Perfect Being must include the attributes of consciousness and life, and therefore, in a certain sense, of motion. (Soph. 248.) The difficulties which attend the hypothesis of the ideas are at least as clearly stated by Plato as by Aristotle : and his statements have also the advantage of being directed against the phase of the doctrine which he knew and to which he had been himself inclined, and not to the confused Pythagorean fancies of his followers. The question is most clearly enun- ciated in the Theaetetus from the side of Knowledge, and in the Parmenides from the side of Being. But those who re- member the various fertility of Plato's mind will not expect the objections raised in different dialogues to be precisely the same. He never sought to bind the play of thought in a single formula. When it had once occurred to him to criticize the theory of ideas, the problem was sure to be seen by him in changing lights, although the elements of the question remain essentially unaltered. Is each idea one or many, at rest or in motion, isolated or related to others, limiting or limited; is Being inanimate or endowed with life, exclusive of particulars, or how related to them ? Is it possible wholly to separate Knowledge from sense and opinion ? These, if not the same question, form a class of questions, of the reality of which Plato is conscious in some dialogues, but appears wholly unconscious in others (for instance in the Phsedo and Cratylus). The dialogues, besides the Sophist and Politicus, in which the effect of this movement within Platonism in the mind of its founder are most evident, are the Philebus, Timaaus, and Laws. In the Philebus, not only is the difficulty stated at the outset, in the form of the problem how to reconcile the antithesis between the one and many, but the combination and resolu- tion of ideas is elaborately exemplified, and a Cause of their combination in reality is conceived. The earlier part of the Timaeus contains a similar passage, and in both the author has laboured to imagine the mode in which the ideal and corporeal are conjoined. Both anticipate Aristotle in speaking of matter (omeipov, Ti6r\vrj), and of a cause by which form is impressed on matter. The Philebus has also a graduated scale of Know- ledges, in which the knowledge of the particular and concrete, TO THE SOPHIST. lxxi although regarded as " impure/' is deliberately allowed to have a place. And in the Laws, while the dhti are not heard of except as logical forms, and a higher movement (namely that of mind) is imagined as the cause both of rest and motion (10, 895), Plato is vehement in asserting that mind in all its manifestations is prior to the elements and controls them. The object of the preceding remarks has been to shew (1) That side by side with the poetical or metaphysical there grew up in Plato's mind a logical mode of conceiving the ideas ; (2) That as he viewed them in this two-fold aspect, and saw the latter of the two more clearly, he became conscious of the difficulties which the theory involved ; and (3) That he was led, partly through the consideration of these difficulties, to alter considerably his theory of Knowledge and Being : pass- ing from the bare assertion of an absolute object of Mind, to which he had been led by interpreting Socrates through Parmenides, towards the Aristotelian conception of logical categories and of Being as composed of Matter and Form by an efficient Cause. Turning now to the Sophist, from which we have been too long detained, we find the elaborate treatment of a difficulty, which is allowed to have been occasioned by the exclusiveness of the Eleatic point of view. This difficulty is not, as in the Philebus, how to find a meeting-point between unity and in- finity, but one more abstract still, how to explain the possibility of combining the positive and negative in thought. Philosophy by aspiring to the pure form of Being had become "dark from excess of light ; " had soared beyond the ken of mortals into an unseen heaven; and in "turning away her mind" from that which is not — from the unreal, and therefore from nega- tion—had deprived herself of the only weapon which could be of any avail to her against the spurious counterfeits of herself. She must deny as well as affirm, and she cannot deny without giving a certain place to Not-Being. It has been already said, that the Negative is here viewed in its ultimate abstraction. The distinctions of Aristotle, between xlrevbos, o-repjjerts, and hvva\xi$ or Kara (TviAfiefirjKos, which he employed in criticizing Plato, are certainly not thought of, but neither were they required, at least in the statement of the question. For false- hood is the object or correlative of denial, and both are equally Ixxii INTRODUCTION expressed whenever (he word "not 11 is uttered: and negation " per accidens" must obviously be explained through the theory of simple negation. The question is, does this word " not" imply such absolute severance between the terms which it divides, as to exclude the possibility of any relation between them .' If A is exclusive of B, is B therefore incapable of all communion or combination with At If so, a counterfeit of reality is inconceivable, for it is not reality, and yet partakes of reality in so far as it is really a counterfeit. This question is raised not with respect to individuals, or infimaB species, in which the coexistence of sameness and difference was an ad- mitted fact (Phil. 15 d), but with respect to general ideas, and the most universal of these, beginning with the most compre- hensive of all ideas, viz. that of Being. The " absolute sever- ance/'' which the injunction of Parmenides requires, between that which Is, and that which Is Not, was the origin and type of the spirit " which would separate each thing from every other" (Soph. 259 e); and the correction of this deeply-rooted tendency was necessary in order to make inquiry possible. After a statement of the perplexities in which the notion of Not-Being is involved according to the ordinary conception of it as the opposite of Being, shewing that it is inconceivable either as a predicate or as a subject, or as the object of refuta- tion and denial ; the Stranger expresses his intention, in this desperate case, of attacking the revered authority of Par- menides. This opens the whole question of the Nature of Being, and the theories of previous and contemporary philoso- phers on the subject. And in the course of the inquiry it is found that the notion of Being, according to prevailing views, is no less full of contradictions than that of Not-Being. Amongst the earlier thinkers, those who hold a fixed plurality of Beings must admit that existence is common to all these, and hence whatever number they assert must either be in- creased, or reduced to one. Those who, with Parmenides, believe in the Unity of Being, will find it hard to keep this unity inviolate while they use the terms Being, One, Whole, each with a distinct meaning, and while they admit, as they needs must, that a whole has parts. These difficulties are only briefly indicated : the chief criti- cism of Parmenides, or rather the modification of his view, TO THE SOPHIST. Ixxiii which has been promised above, is made indirectly, and only emerges when the contemporary phase of Greek philosophy has been examined in its two chief aspects. Here no attempt is made to determine the exact number of Beings. The battle rages about a different point. Is lieing corporeal or ideal? Some hold that nothing exists but bodies, which they can touch and handle : their opponents break up these bodies by dialectic into a flux of change, and assert the sole existence of certain bodiless ideas. Now the former, if pressed, and if they were capable of argument, would admit the existence of a soul, and of virtue and vice as attributes of the soul; and, though they might contend that the soul is corporeal, they could hardly maintain this of justice or wisdom. Hence they may be willing to sub- stitute for body as the characteristic of Being, the power of acting or of being acted upon. Being is possibility of energy. But the idealists will refuse this definition. Acting and suffering they say are properties not of Being, but of Becom- ing : for Being is exempt from change. Whereupon we ask them whether to know is an active, and to be known a passive verb; and whether Being therefore, so far as known, is not acted upon 1 And here, apart from logic, the reflection rises, that Perfect Being cannot be devoid of life and movement, and the power of thought. That which has thought has life, that which has life has a soul, and that which has a soul cannot be motionless. And yet it is most true that reason could not exist nor come into being without uniformity and permanence, which imply a principle of rest in the object of reason. Being therefore has both Motion and Rest. But Being is neither Motion nor Rest. We are in the position of the dualists whom we compelled to admit a third principle. Motion and Rest are opposites, yet both exist. Being therefore comprehends both, and is different from both, and though essentially partaking both of motion and rest, in its own nature neither rests nor moves. In solving this apparent contradiction, we stumble on the solution of the original problem of the reconciliation of Being and Not-Being. As we endeavour to harmonize the dis- cords which have arisen within the sphere of Being, we are led to modify our notion of the mutual exclusiveness of Being and that which had been hitherto regarded as the opposite of Being. 1 Ixxiv INTRODUCTION Before proceeding with the argument, we may glance at one or two points in the interesting passage which has just been analyzed. (Soph. 246-250.) Under the titles of the Earth-born and the Friends of Ideas docs Plato allude to any particular schools, and, if so, to which of those existing round him ? It is difficult to bring either description into exact harmony with the tenets of any single school. The yrjyevels would at first sight appear to be the same who are mentioned in the Thesetetus as " stubborn and repellent" men, but are there emphatically, though somewhat ironically, distinguished from the " disciples of Protagoras :" whereas here the akr]deia of Protagoras appears to be brought under the general censure. It may be remarked, however, that there is a distinction amongst the yrjyeyets also, for some are viewed as more hope- lessly irreclaimable than the rest (01 glvt&v cnraproi re kch avro- Xdoves). According to this view, Antisthenes may possibly be included, but the whole description and the line of argument pursued point rather in the direction of a physical school. The moral maxims of Democritus, when taken in connexion with his general principle, might lay his followers open to the criticism here employed. But on the other hand, his analysis of the senses makes it improbable that he is alone intended. It remains, therefore, most probable that Plato has here idealized, if such a paradox may be allowed, the materialistic tendency in contemporary thought. In the other description, of the friends of motionless forms, there are some marks which answer to the Pythagoreans, and others which point rather in the direc- tion of Megara. That the Pythagoreans, whose djaznjroi ovaiat are very similarly criticized by Aristotle, are intended here, is an opinion which Proclus p takes for granted, and which has been recently advanced, quite independently as it would seem, by a French critic, M. Mallet. That the Megarians are meant, has been the common belief, since this was somewhat doubt- fully asserted by Schleiermacher. The Pythagoreans certainly p Comment, in Parmen. p. 149 ed. crofyovs. A comparison of Parmenides, Pont. : iiv fiXv yap Kal irapa rots Uv- Philolaus, and Empedocles shews that Bayopeiois r/ irepl rwv elda/v Oeoopia Kal the Eleatic and Pythagorean specula- 5?;Ao7 Kal avrbs ev 2ov. " Das Schwere unci Wahrhafte ist dieses, zu zeigen, dasz das, was das Andere ist, Dasselbe ist, und, was Dasselbe ist, ein Anderes ist : und zwar in derselben Riicksicht, und nach derselben Seite, dasz das Eine ihnen geschehen ist, wird auch die andere Bestimmung an xc INTllODUCTlOxN TO THE SOPHIST. ihncn aufgezeigt. Dagcgcn zu zeigen, das Dasselbe auf irgcnd cine AVeiso cin Andercs, und das Andcrc auch Dassclbe, dasz das Grosze auch kloin JJ (z. B. Protagoras 1 Wurfel), " und das Aenliche auch un'ahnlich scy, und scin Gefallen daran haben, so durch Griinde immer das Entgcgcngcsetzte vorzubringen, — dicsz ist keine wahrhafte Einsiclit (eAey^os), und offenbar das Erzcugniss eines Neulings," ira Denken, " welcher erst das Wcsen zu beriihrcn anfangt;" (Werke, vol. 14. p. 210. ed. 1840.) Both the ancient and the modern appreciation were in- fluenced by preconceptions ; and supposed a dogmatic and sys- tematic intention which is not to be found in Plato. Whether the movement of modern philosophy, from Spinoza through Kant to Hegel, is in any respects analogous to that which has now been traced from Parmenides through the Plato of the Phaedrus to the Plato of the Sophist, is a question which it belongs to the historian of philosophy to decide. 2 0*1 2TH2 20$I2TH2. T.I. jd.Steph. b. 2 1 6. ta tot AiAAoroT npomnA 6EOAOP05;, 2QKPATH2,£EN02 EAEATH2, 0EAITHTO2. J\ATA ttjv y6e$ ofioXoylap, co ^coKpares, rjKOfiev i. The word a-o^ia-r^s, like many others in Plato (e. g. Aoyos, 8idvoia, yevecris, crTOi^eioi/, o-co/xa), may be observed in the act of passing from the common or vernacular, to- wards a technical and philo- sophical use. When Aristo- tle defines the Sophist xPW a - tktttjs ano - 6ei. urn is in the background, the So- cratic spirit of inquiry still reigns in this ami the follow- ing dialogue. There arc at leasl four points in which this intellectual (as distinguished from the personal) influence of Socrates may still be traced. 1. The use of trivial and gro- tesque examples to illustrate general truths (see Xen. Memo- rabilia I. 2. § 23, and compare the words of Callicles in the Gorgias, 491 a : del enevrias re Kat Kvafaas Ka\ payelpovs Aeytof kol larpovs ovbev Travel), and the elevation of this practice into a principle of scientific method. The angler has a definition no less than the highest artist. Philosophical classification re- spects not persons, but views the military commander and the destroyer of vermin as ecmally deserving a place in the category of huntsmen. The Sophist is a salesman, a magi- cian, a sportsman, a scene- painter. The image of the " herdsman" (compare Xen. Mem. 1. a), used satirically in the Thesetetus (p. 174 d) and in Rep. 1, and with a more serious meaning in the Laws (4, 713 b, c), appears again in the Politicus, at first in the hu- morous but afterwards in the deeper signification. In the same dialogue an elaborate pa- rallel is drawn between the statesman and the weaver, and this leads to a vindication of the argument from Example. Here also the Socratic mode of teaching by instances (coin- ciding with the Pythagorean parable) is not only imitated 20I2TH2. 216. yeuos e£ 'EAear, eraipov 8e tu>v u/x(fA Ylapuzvi&riv but is made the object of re- flection and study. 2. The con- viction, which appears chiefly in the Politicus, that all prac- tical wisdom may be resolved into pure knowledge, aud that this master-science is one only, and stands in close relation to all others. 3. The destructive, cross-questioning method of Socrates is characterised as a purgation of the soul (iu. lb. p. 7 2 - naiyap entlvov ]i;,i;':;l 1:1. and bring with t!i(.'in an Eleatic friend, whom B 2, nAATQNOS Theodoras introduces us a true philoso- pher. Socrates is awe-struck. " What if h« I"' some God in dis- guise, who, as pouts KCU Z)/va>i>a •\'€Taipaii>'\', fxrxAa St uvdpa (f)iAo- p. 2lfl au(j)oi'. 20. ' Ap ovv, eo Qeodtope, ov ^evov uAAa tlvol 6ebv ayoiv Kara rov 'Q/jujpou Aoyov AeAr)$a? ; oy 5 (f»](Tii> aAAouy re Oeov? roh uudpcQirois, onocroL /xere- b ovroi npoaeiprjKfv, eratpov tuiv ap(jn II. kci\ Z. pdXa 8e uvdpa (pi\6cro(pov . II). p. 83 : iraipos Tovnov vrriipxuv, \iraipa>v\ is pro- bably a gloss 011 rav. (Bodl. tov.) The word is transposed in one MS. (A), which gives iralpav kui tfvava. It is doubtful whether t&v is a partitive genitive or governed by iraipov : — "A com- panion of the number of those" or " a companion of those." The former is more idiomatic, gives a better emphasis to irai- pov, and is on the whole more consistent with the quotations of Proclus. For the use of the word iraipos, cf. Theset. 180 c : ov yap o~oi eraipoi elaiv. " This stranger is of Eleatic race, an adherent of the school of Par- menides and Zeno, and he is a true philosopher." Avtlvo , ov p.ev koX e'jz I . p.dXa St avbpa (JjiX6(Torj>ov] ( T. Pann. 1 26 b : oldt — n-oXt- ral poi flat, pdXa (jjiKutroj.oi. For the conjunction of the adverb and noun, cf. Legg. 1, 639 b : aXXd tivoov o-(j)68pa yvvaiiccbv. 3. ov £tvov dXXd nva #eoi>] The ausvver of Theodorus, oi>x ovtos 6 rp. r. £., shews that these words of Socrates express an ironical fear lest the stranger should bring the Zenonian negative dialectic to bear on his own (i. e. Plato's) mode of reasoning. Compare Euthyd. 273 e : el 8e vvv dXrj- dcos ravTrjv ri]V e7VL0-Tt]p.rjv e'xe- tov, lXea> e'lrjTov. dre^i/cos yap eycoye a(f)a> u>o-nep 8eco irpoo-ayo- pevo). 4. XeX^oy] Sc. aavrov. Cf. Theaet. 180 e. 5. aXXovs re 6eovs~\ OdvSS. P. 483-7: aXes 8v(Trr}vov dXijrrjv, ovkofitv, el fir) ttoxj rts iirovpavioi deos eo-rtv. kcil re 6eo\ tjeivoiaiv e'oiKores dXXo8a7rolai.v, navroloL reXtBovres, e-n-io-Tpaxpoio-i noXrjas, dvdpwTTCov vftptv re Ka\ eiivop.irju e'cfropcovres. lb. I. 270, I : Zevs 5' eTTtTiprjTaip iKtrdaiv re £eiva>v re, ^eii/tos, 09 tjeivoio-iv a\C aiSoioio-ie oirrjSei. Both these passages are present Greek religion. Bodl. dXXrjXovs : to the speaker's mind, but the second less distinctly than the first : for geivoio-iv is dropped, and aldoioicriv taken actively, = respectful or merciful. The substitution of 6e6s for Zeus-, the general for the individual, belongs to the later phase of but the correction is not by the first hand. Cf. Legg. 5, 730 a: 6 §ivtos imarav §aip.u)v Kal 6eos ra> £evia> o-vvenop-evoi Au. lb. 12, 953 e: TificovTfs i^iviov Ala. (iXXovs n Beovs tu'is di>0pa>nois] The apodosis of these words is 20I2TH2. 3. 216. 'xpvcriv alSovs St-tcaia?, kou 8r/ koll top i^eviov ov)( rJKKTTa 6eov avvo7rabov yiyvoptvov v(3pei? re kul tvvo[±ias tcov dvOpcoircov KaOopav. rcl^ ovu dv koll aOl TIS OVTO? TCOV KptLTTOVCOV GwllTOLTO^ (pavXoVS 7][j.as ovtols eV Tois XoyoLs iiroip'op.ei'os re koll e\e'ytjtoi>, Oebs cov T19 f:\ey ktikos. GEO. Ov\ OVT09 6 Tpoiros, co *2coKpaTc-s, rov tje'vov, dAXa fxerpicoTepo? tcov 7repl ray eptdas 1 ecnrovSaKorcou. koll jjlol Sok€l Oeos pc-v 6\vrjp ovhapcos eivod, Ohos fXTjV c ttclvtcls yap eyco tovs (pi\ocr6(pov? toiovtovs irpocra- yopevco. absorbed in avvonadov yiyvd- fiepop. I. Snocroi — StKaias] Said in compliment to Theodoras, who, in reward for his modest and candid temper (see the Thesete- tus), may unawares be enter- taining a superior being. Com- pare the combination of aldcos with 81KJ7 in the Protagoras (322 c), and in Hesiod. 4. tu>v KpeiTTovcou] " Some higher power," i. e. a God or Hero, cf. Legg. 4,718 a : napa 6ea>v Kai ocroi Kpeirroves rjpcov. Euthyd. 291 a : prj ns tcov KpeiTTOPOov napcov avra icpdey^aro ' Ep. y, 326 e : tones pr)v nvt. t5>v xpeiTTOvcov apxyv (3a\e(r6ai twv vxiv yeyovoTcov irpaypaTcov. Compare Aesch. Prom. 905 : pr/8e Kpeia- aovcov [decov] epcos acpvKTOV oppa 7rpoa8pa.Koi pe. 5. e7To\j/6pevos] Referring to ecpopcovres in the line of Homer. 7. Ov% OVTOS 6 rpoiros — TOV ^»ou] Cf. Theast. 145 e : ovx ovtos 6 Tponos Beobcopov. 8. perpiarepos] " More rea- sonable." Cf. Thea?t. 161 b : dnoSf'i-acrOai perpias. tcov nepl rds epibas io-irovha- kotojv] Cf. Isocrates Soph. 20 : tcov TTtpl Tas ?pi8as KaKivbovpivcov. And for eo-novdciKOTcov inf. p. 259 b, C : etre — X at P ei — TOVS ^dyovs s\kcov, ovk aj-ia 7To\\r)s o-rrovdrjs icnrovDaKe. The Stranger is re- presented as not contentious, that the reader may be pre- pared for the modification of the Eleatic doctrine in what follows, and for the general scope of the dialogue, which tends to deprecate the arts of controversy. 9. dvrjp] In this and similar places the MSS. persistently give dvrjp. This is equally the case in tragedy (e. g. Soph. Aj. 9 : tvhov yap dvrjp), where the quantity proves the presence of the article. 6eios] Cf. Rep. 1, 331 e : aocpbs yap nal deios dvrjp (6 2t- pcovidr/s) . Phileb. 1 8 b : ehe tis 6eos eire kcu delos cwdpconos. In Legg. i, 626 c, the address d> dele occurs — characteristically — in the mouth of the Spartan. 10. toiovtovs] Sc. Be'iovs. Cf. Theeet. 154 e, Phsed. 67 a. have ■• ung, mpa- niea the good man's going, and comes to exjio.se the notbing- 5 oess of Athenian wisdom ?" Tmeo. "He is not con- tentious, as some are: and certainly 10 no God, though I must call him, as I do all phi- losophers, divine." nAAmNos SoOB."And the divine philoso- pher is also rarely dis- cerned, and often walks disguised through the igno- rance of other men, whose life he watches from above, appearing to them ^Q.. K«Ao3y ye, co r/j/'Ae. touto \uvtol kivSvvc-vu p. liQ to yevo? ov iroXv ri paav, oV eros c-l7tc-li>, eivou dia- Kpivetv ?/ to too Oeov' irdvv yap avSpes ovtol iravToloi (j)avTa^ofiepoi Sia rrjv tcov aXXcov ayvoiav ilivLo~Tpco(\mcTi noAija?, oi fxrj 7rXacrTLO? dXX % ovtco? (friXocrocpoi, KaOopwvTts v\\ro9c-v tov tcov koltco fiiov, Keel Tols fxev Sokovctlv elvat tov /j.rj8c-vo? Tipuoi, rols* I. roOro pevrot to yevos~\ The more remote purpose of the dia- logue appears in these words. The definition of the Sophist is preparatory to that of the philosopher. 3. to tov 6eov\ Note the sin- gular case with the article, ex- pi'essing a generalized concep- tion — as in tov avdpunrov : Thu- cyd. 1, 140. tow] "certainly;" almost = aTexvas, referring to the words of Homer. Compare the use of Tvavv ye, ndvu p.ev ovv in re- plies. 4. iravToloi (pavTa^opevoi] (pav- tci(. is Substituted for TeXeOovTes because the philosophers do not really change, but appear in various disguises through the ignorance of men. Compare Rep. 2, 381-2, where there is a reference to the same pas- sage of Homer. See also Timseus 41 a, where the tradi- tionary deities are spoken of in contradistinction to the hea- venly bodies as 00-01 cpaivovrai Ka0 y oaop av edeXtoai Qeo'i. 5. oi fir] 7r\ao-Tios clXX' ovtcos <£iAdVoo5oi] " The real, not the would-be philosophers." Cf. Thea?t. 173 c: Ae'ycopev — irep\ tcov Kopvs kciI ov tl 7rXacrra)« elo~\v ayaOol. lb. 6, 777 d. 6. KcidopowTts] Echoing nado- pav supr., but with the addi- tional meaning of " down- wards." For Kad. vy\fi'i6ev tov twv Kara jBlov, see the digression in the Theaetetus 173 b, 175 c, d. Also Rep. B. 7. 7. rot? pev boKovaiv — paviK&>s\ " The true philosopher appears to some men nothing worth : to others, worth all the world : now he presents the semblance of a statesman, now of a public teacher : and, again, he may give to some men the impres- sion that he is clean mad." The philosophic spirit is a treasure whose value is un- known : a pearl of great price, for which he who has found it will sell all that he has : appearing now in the practical, now in the specula- tive sphere : in both apt to be confounded with lower types of wisdom by ordinary men, who, when they begin to see the real issues towards which the spirit leads, will brand it with the name of foolishness or madness. For tov iravros, cf. Phsedr. 235 e. The article is SOM2TH2. <5' aijioi tov iravros' kgu tot€ p.ev ttoXltikoi (f)avTa- (ovtoli, tote 8e crcxpiaTai, Tore 8' ecrTtv oh 86£av TrapaaxpiVT av cos iravTairacriv t^ovTts paviKco?. tov yiivTOi ^evov i]plv r]8ea>? av irvvOavolp^v, el (j)iXov avrcp, tl ravff oi nrep\ tov e'/cet tottov rjyouvTO 5 Kal ojvo/JLa^ov. GEO. Ta irola 8rj ; 212. ^oc^LO-TrjV, 7ToXltik6v, (fiiAoaocpov. GEO. TV 8e fxaXiara kou to ttolov tl ire pi amwv 8iaiTopi]6eh epeaOai SievoyOrjs ; k here partly suggested by tov firjdevos, which hardly needs illustration. 1. tots pev — Tore Se] Bodl. p. m. Tore fiev — tote Se. ttoXitikol] E. g. Epiinenides, Solon, Pythagoras. 2. cro^ia-Tai] As Socrates in the 'Clouds,'or Plato at Syracuse. The word is used here with- out any invidious association, like ttoXitikol, merely denoting a recognized class. The variation of language in rifuoi — agtoi is in keeping with the studied refinement of this dialogue. 3. TravTCLTTacnv e\ovres [wviicas] Cf. Phsedr. 249 c, d : lb. e : al- Tiav e'xei a>s pavLKms bLaKeipevos : and the words of Alcibiades in the Symposium 218 b : navres yap KeKoivoivrjKaTe rrjs (pi- Xoaofpov pavlas re ko.1 ^aK^fias. Note the emphatic position of fiaviKws. 4. tov pevroi £evov~\ The double fitvTot marks a double transi- tion : from the person of the Stranger to the nature of philo- sophers, and from this to the Stranger again,who is addressed with an inquiry bearing on the subject which has been thus sug- gested. " The philosopher is apt tobe confounded with the States- man and Sophist, except when he is looked upon as mad. Will the Stranger clear the confusion by defining each of the terms in question ?" tj/jllv gives a courteous turn to *fche expression, like poi after a vocative. et (piXov avra] Cf. Theset. 162b: dXX' el ovrcos, a> Qe68cope, v6pa£ov~] "What his countrymen (in Magna Grascia) thought of these mat- ters, and how they used to apply the terms." The imper- fect implies the qualification "When he was amongst them." For the adverbial ti, cf. Phsedr. 234 C : tl vol (paiverai 6 \6yos " 9. Ti 8e pa\io~ra — Sieporjdrjs] The curious formality of this address belongs to Plato's later style. (See General Introd.) Cf. infr. 226 b : to tto'lov avTav nepL ISov^Tjdels Sf/Xcocrcu, irapa.8eiypa.Ta ■rrpodus TavTa Kara ttcivtcov ijpov ) 24O C : TTfj KOA TO 7TOtoV TL (fiofiov- niiw rv^ Statesman, now aa • Sophist,' despised, believed in, wondered at as mad. Sophist, Statesman, Philoso- pher : — What lias our Italian friend to tell us of these things ? 8 IIAATQN02 l>o his conntry- men ac- count them one, or two, or three '" Tlie Stran- ger had been al- ready asked this ques- tion on the way. He will shew that each of the three terms denotes a different nature, though to distinguish them is by no means a simple task. 213. T68e' TTOTtpQV €V iraVTOL TOLVTO. ev6pi(j)V l) \>-2\J. 860, i] KaOairep tu ouofiara rpla, rpla kou yevrj 8ua- povpevoi Kaff ev ovopta yevos eKaarco irpoo-rjTrTOV ; GEO. 'AAA' ov8el?, cos eyco/xai, ([jOovo? avrco 8teX- 5 0eiv aura. ' H 7TC09, co £eVe, Xeycopiev; SE. Our cos", co Qe68cope. (pOovos p.ev yap ov8el?, b ov8e )(aXe7rov elwelv on ye rp'C rjyovvTO' Kaff eKacrrov pcr/v SLopLcraaOai cra(J)co?, t'l ttot ecmv, ov ap.iK.pov ov8e pa8iov epyov. 'o 0EO. Kal p.ev 8rj Kara rvyj]v ye, co ^coKpares, Xoycov e7reXa(3ov 7rapairXr](Ticov cov Kal irp\v rjpa? 8evp eXOelv 8iepcoTcovre? avrov eTvyya.vop.ev. 6 8e ramd, airep 7rpo? ere vvv, koll tote iaKrj7rr€TO irpos rj peas' eire\ 8iaKr)Koevat, ye <§>r\cnv 'iKavcos Kal ovk isapLvqpovelv. 20. Mt) tolvvv, co tjeve, rjfxcov tt)v ye 7rpcorr)v c pevos ovra> XeyeLS ) Legg. 6,752b: Ttepi TL (SXiTTCdV Kai 7Toi paXlCTTa avrb e'lpr/Kas ra vvv; lb. 4, 705 cl : els 8r] tl TG>v elpr/pevcov jSke\jras, emes o Xe'yeis ; "In regard to what point, and with a view to what difficulty respecting these things, did the question occur to you?" 2. rpLa Kaiyevrj] The Bodleian MS., as well as Alii, has Ka\ yevrj, which is manifestly right, to yevrj does not suit with Siaipov- pevoi. They do not divide the classes, but distinguish three. " Did they, as the names are three, distinguish also three kinds, and assign one severally to each name 1 ?" 6. (pdovos — elnelp] (fidovos IS not to be joined with ehreiv. " You are right, Theodorus ; I have no wish to withhold any- thing." 7. rpi' r)yovvTO~\ So Bodl. 1 1 . \6yoav — hv $iepa>TU>vTes~] For the apposition of the clause to the relative, cf. Theaet. 158 b : to Toiovfte dp(pio-l3fjTJ]pa, — 6 ttoX- Aa/as v\ As Trapa- nXrjo-ms is rarely found with the genitive, there is probably here a double attraction : i. e. hv = ols = TOVTOtS ovs. 12. 6 8e TavTa] Heindorf's slight emendation (ravTa for TavTa) seems to be required by the antithesis npos ere vvv — totc npos rjpas. 16. Mr) — yevrj] " Be not so cruel as to refuse our first boon when we have asked it of you." 20w koll 8le^iovtl Xoyovs irayKaXovs 5 Trapeyevofxrjv eyco veos cov, €K€lvov paXa 8ij totc ovtos 7rp€a(3vTov ; HE. Tw pep, co "EcoKpare?, olXvttco? re koll evrjvlco? The use of the auxiliary verb (see Gen. In trod.) is a feature of Plato's later style : and is one of the points in which that style approximates to the lan- guage of tragedy. 2. (tcoBas rj§iov~\ " Do you commonly prefer 1 ?" 3. (laKpcp \6yco 8te{;iei>ai Xeywj/] There is a slight emphasis on Ae'ywj/. " Do you prefer to en- large in an extended speech on the subject which you desire to explain, or to discuss the matter (8u£ievai) by means of questions, a practice Avhich I remember that Parmenides used — ?" 4. oiov ^pco/ieVw] oiov is cognate or adverbial accus., like tl — rjyoiivTo above. Com- pare Theset. 170 b: 7-1 — XPV- aofieda tw Aoyw, and Lys. 213c: t'i ovv 8rj xpTjo-wfxeda, where there is an ellipse of the da- tive, 7U Xoyw or to"ls Xoyoiy, as here. It seems probable that the Parmenides had been com- posed, or at least planned, when this passage and Theret. 184 a were written. 8. To} — aXvnas re Kai evr)- viu>s 7rpo(r5iaXsyojiteVw] " With a respondent who gives no trou- ble and is guided easily." It must be acknowledged that most of the respondents in Plato's dialectical dialogues have this virtue. They an- swer in the spirit of the ques- tioner, and accept true reason- ing when it is placed before them. When a sally is per- mitted them, this is obviously done either for the sake of relieving the gravity of the argument, or in order that they may derive instruction from their own mistakes, or thirdly, in one or two rare cases, that they may shew that the highest truths are some- times the intuitions of the simple mind. Docility in the pupil as well as the mens divinior in the teacher is re- quired for the purposes of dia- lectic. This is less obviously the case in the Republic and Phsedo, where Glaucon and Adimautus, Simmias and Cebes, are allowed to propound their difficulties, thus exhibiting an- other aspect of the philosophic spirit. Yet Glaucon claims the merit of being a more facile respondent than some others would be. Rep. 5, 474 a : ta-cas av aWov rov f/x/ieXfcrrepni/ dno- Kpivotfxrjv. Cf. Legg. 7, 797 d. It 1 1 e choo < to pro© 1 d li_\ qui =- tions, a 1 Parmeni- des used, and accepts Theietetus for his re- spondent : who, when tired, will be relieved by Socra- tes the younger. 10 OAATONOS TrpouSiaAeyofitvcD pa.ov ovtu), to irpo? aAkov /,(?/, to Kaff amov. 2i7. ' EijeaTi Tolvvv twv TrapovTwv ov av fiovAijOrjv eKAetjao-@a.r TrdvTts yap viraKOvaovTai aoi 7rpaco<>. < crvpifiovAcp p.i)v ip.ol xpcopevo? tcov vecov tlvol aiprjo-ei, QeamjTov TOv8e, i] kol tcov aAAcov ei riy croi kutu vovv. SE. 'O Sco/cpares", aidco? t'ls p! e^ei to vvv npcoTov crvyyev6p.€vov v/uv prj Kara crpuKpov eiros irpos 67T09 d de p. 2 i (I is curious to observe that the Heracliteims of Ephesus (Theret. 1 80) aud the extreme mate- rialists (Soph. 246) are de- spaired of in this respect as being incapable of dialectic, rod dovvai kci\ de^ao-dai Xoyoj/. For the use of npos in irpooSiake- yopeva, compare Theaet. 162 b, irpoo-nakauiv; ib. 169 C, ivpoo-ava- Tpiy^dpevos ; and for inraKOvcrov- rai TTpdas, paullo infra, cf. Theset. 162 a ". pah' eppeXas o~oi i(paLv€TO vTraKoveiv. The community of spirit between those convers- ing is also dwelt on in Ph?ed. 58 d : Kai p,rjv, w ^aidcov, Ka\ rovs aKovaopevovs ye toiovtovs aWovs e'xeis. The adj. evrjvios occurs with the ethical meaning = obedient, tractable, Legg. 5, 730 b, 9, 880 a. I. to npos ciXXov — to Kad' qvtov] Sc. 8ie£ievai tovs Xoyovs. 4. TTpaas = ov 8vo~peva>s oi8e paxrjTiKu?, Theset. 168 b. 5. tu>v vecov tivo] As being free from prepossessions and more supple to follow the wind- ings of an argument, cf. Parm. 137 b : 6 vemTdTOs ; ^/ciara yap av TTchvirpaypovol, Ka\ a o'lerai fiaXiaT av aivoKpLvoiTo. Theait. 162 b : prj (\k(lv irpos to yvpvd- o-iov o-KXrjpov rjSrj ovra, rw 8e 8tj veoiTepai nal vyporepa ovti Trpoana- Xaieiv. Ib. 146 b. 8. atScbj tls p f'x et ] "•" s01 't °f modesty comes over me at the thought of continuing our in- terview not colloquially but by spinning a lengthened mono- logue by myself, or even ad- dressing myself to another at length, which would only be a kind of display. For the truth is, that the word you have now given us is not of such easy compass as one might ex- pect on hearing the question, but requires an immense amount of discussion." to vvv'] The Vatican MS. (A) and the Bodleian a and Venetian (n) first hand have preserved a reading tov vovv, which is partly due to the preceding vovv, and partly to the intelligibleness of the phrase al8d>s p exei tov vovv. But irpwTov could have no mean- ing without vvv, and the article is required to mark the limita- tion of the preceding clause. 9. ems ivpbs eTros] Cf. Ari- The Bodleian has tui with the omicron erased. p. 21 7. TTOiHaOou Tt]v avvovalav, dXX eKTelvavTa a.7rop(.i]KV- c veiv Xoyov o~v)(vov kclt e/xavTov, eire kou irpos tTepov, oiov tiridei^LV TTOiovfievov' tco yap ovtl to vvv pi-jOlv ov% oaov coSe tpcoTrjOev eXTrlaeiev av ai)TO eivai tls; aXXa Tvyyavei Xoyov TrapiprjKOvs ov. to 8e av aoi 5 per) ^apl^eaOai kou TolaSe, aXXco? re kou aov Xe'tjavTos coy elire?, a^evov tl KaTa^alveTai p.ot kou aypiov. eireX p. 218. QeaiTrjTov ye tov it poaScaXeyopievov eivai 8e\opat iravTonraaiv eij wv amos re rrpoTepov 8t.elXeypL.ai kou av to. vvv p.01 SiaKeXevei. 10 2CKM2TH2. 11 stopll. Nub. 1379 : ndvTevdev pev, olov eUos, eiros np6s enos rjpeido- peada. And for the construc- tion, see note on Thefet. 193 d: Se£ta els dpicrrepa perappeov- CTTjS. 1. eKTelvavra — ^coKparys, iraai KeyapiaLievos e av 8' apa tl tolovtov ylyvrjrai, /cat rov8e 7rapaAr)\\ro- o jieOa ^coKparrj, rbv "ScoKparov? ptev optcovvpLOV, efxbv Se i]Xlklcoti]v koll avyyvp.vaaTi]v, cp Gwoiairovelv iier epLOv ra iroWa ovk wqOes. HE. Ei) Ae'yei?, kol ram a p.ev 18 la ftovAevaei agreed as TTpOlOVTOS TOV AOyOV' KOLVYj Oe p.eT epLOV CTOL CTVCT- to the name 18. I. We are I. ? Apa rolvvv — etret ;] "Will you then in this (in select- ing me) be doing also what Socrates desired — ministering to the gratification of all pre- sent 1 " Ka\ is separated from Traa-L /ce^. ev x^P iv j m which words Socrates had included all present. 3. KivSvvevei — eraipovs] A murmur of assent from the by- standers must be supposed to follow Thesetetus' words. 5. rco prjKei TTovav] Stallbaum, in his note, has substituted ttovcov for 7rova>v, but the par- ticiple is obviously right. For the dative, cf. Soph. Track 681 : ttovcov TrXevpav iriKpa yha- 6. fit/ ifie curiao-dai] Bodl.Vat. Ven. n. p.e. The infinitive is a softened imperative, cf. Rep. 5, 473 a; infr. 262 e: av pot KpdTrf\ So Pro- tarchus relieves Philebus, when tired. Phileb. 1 1 c : dvdyKt) bix^o-dai, i'X?y/3oj yap r)p1v 6 KaXos aTreiprjKev. i 2. ra 7roXXa is better taken as cognate accusative after o-wbiaTToveiv than as adverbial to ovx. drjOes. " Who is well used in most thiugs to share labours with me." Young Socrates ap- pears in the Theagtetus as a mute personage, and shares the credit of the geometrico- arithmetical definition of the irrational roots. Theret. 147, 148. 2CXM2THZ. 18 21 8. K€7TT€0U ap^OfieVCO TTpCOTOl/, COS" €fJLOL (pCUl/€Tai, VVV OTTO ", (j-jTOVVTL KCU t\ltyavi(pVTl AoyO) TL 7TOT TOV CTOCpiCTTOV, ear 1. vvv yap 81] av [re] Kayco tovtov irepi Tovvo/xa /jlovov e'xp/jiev KOtvrj' to 8e epyov, i(f> co KaAodfiev, 1. vvv, which is opposed to Trpo'iovros r. X., and would be joined most naturally with arvo-nenTeov, appears to be dis- placed by a conversational hyperbaton, perhaps to avoid the hiatus cpalverai — ano, per- haps drawn by a sort of at- traction to the words which indicate the immediate subject of discourse, vvv is again dis- placed, apparently for euphony, infr. 221 c, 231 b; cf. also Legg. 1, 627 b : to d' ino o~ov Xeyopevov fj.avda.va> vvv. 2. efi is slightly emphatic, and is referred to in what immediately follows. ovo- pa = the name, is distinguished on the one hand from epyov or irpayiia, the thing, and on the other from \6yos, the de- finition or true conception of the thing. For the former, cf. Cratyl. 413 e : avTO prjvvei to epyov to ovopa fj avpela, and for the latter, Theset. 202, which is closely related to the pre- sent passage. The conception of \6yos is the same in this place as in the conclusion of the Thea?tetus, viz. definition through division or the ex- pression of the characteristic difference, epyov and Xdyo? are here correlative, and not op- posed, as in the common anti- thesis epya> ov Xo'yw. The union 01 both, to irpaypa avTo 81a \6ya>v, is opposed to the mere name, to b'popa povov X^P^ Xdyou. The variation of epyov and irpaypa is perhaps due to the same re- finement to which that of cpi,- \ov and yevos is owing. But epyov is rather the Sophist's function, irpaypa simply the thing meant by the word. Cf. also Legg. 9, 864 b : rjplv fie OVK eCTTl TO. vvv ovopuTcov nepi ovo-epis Xdyoy. lb. I o, 895 d : 9 > > * >/|/x \ t 1 ap ovk av eueAois rrepi eKao~Tov Tpia voelv, ev pev ttjv ovalav, ev fie ttjs cvaias tov \6yov, ev fie to ovopa k.t.X. lb. 12, 964 a: ovco- irapev tov eifidra iKavas irep\ usvtl- vcovovv, ois eo-TL pev ovopa, eari o' av Ka\ Xdyos, iroTepov povov eirlara- o-Qai Tovvopa xpeav *] tov ye ovTa tl Ka\ irep\ tcjv 8ia(pep6vTccv peyedei Ka\ KaXXei iravTa to. ToiavTa ayvo- elv alo~xpov. (pv~kov, tribe, is a more poetical, because a newer, metaphor, for the idea of Sort or Kind than yevos, race or family. The search for the Sophist is spoken of as a branch of natural history. For to ovopa — crvvcopoXoyrjaao-dai, cf. Theset. 164 c : Trpds Tas t£>v ovopaTcov SpoXoyias 6po\oyr]o~d- pevoi. 3. av [re] Kaya>] The Bodleian MS. gives o-v nay io with the rest, except Flor. i. 4. e(p' co KaXovpev] Sc. to ovopa. "Sophia*." our objeci ia bo defin< tin; thing, and so to bring to light the conception U 1IAATQNQ2 which, it may be, we llHVt: si'Vc- rally within our minds. Great sub- jects, it has long been felt,' should be ap- proached through easy exam- ples. And, as the So- phist is a creature difficult to eKUTepo? rax av iota Trap yptv avTOLg €\oip.eV fiei \>. z\H. Se del ttolvtos irept to irpdypa avTo ptaXXov did Xoycov rj tovvo/jlci povov crvvopoXoyrjo~ao~0ai \cop19 Xoyov. to 8e (pvXov, o vvv eirtvoovpev (jjTe'iv, ov 5 TTaVTCOV paCTTOP CTvXXafiuv Tl TTOT €0~TIV, 6 aOffjLO-TT}?. baa 8" av tcov peyaXcov Set hiairoveiaOat KaXtos, irept tcov tolovtcov Se'SoKTai irdat kcu irdXai to irpoTepov ep crpLiKpois Ka\ paoaiv am a 8etv p.e\eTav, irptv iv <\ avTois rots peyicrTois. vvv ovv, cb QeaLTrjTe, eycoye io/cat vcov ovtco avp(3ovXevco, ^aAe7ro^ kol SvaOrjpevTOV 4. to Be (pvXop — 6B6p] " Now the Sophist tribe, which we are at present minded to examine, is of a nature which is not the easiest in the world to comprehend. Again, when a great subject is to be adequately handled, it has long since been the ap- proved course in such a case to try one's hand upon the question in trivial and easy instances, before attempting it in the great matter which has been undertaken. On the present occasion there- fore, Theaetetus, I would re- commend that you and I, con- sidering the Sophist to be of a kind which is difficult to cap- ture and to chase, should try our prentice hand on some easier quarry, and make this a preparatory study of the way to find him, unless you have at your command some more feasible proposal." Perhaps in ttjp fxidoBop avrov there is an allusion to the literal mean- ing of fieTiepai, ' to pursue.' Cf. infr. 235 d. ov TraPTcup paorop] Cf. inf. 244 c. In Eep. 6, 497 d, ov iravras pqenop 8ie\8elp, ttuptodp should probably be read. 7. Kal 7rdXai] " Even from of old." Not only now but long ago. Cf. Thea?t. 202 d : kcu 7roXXot. to — Belp] The article marks the infinitive as the subject of the verb. 7repi tS>p tolovtcop may be construed with BsBoktuc, but belongs rather to the whole sentence. "In dealing with such subjects it has long been the general opinion that one should first exercise inquiry on lesser and easier topics." avTa is vague, resuming to>p toiovtwp, but in a more general sense = the inquiry or the method of procedure. I O. ^aXenop — npopikeTqp] These words are in apposition to ovtco after o~vp.[3ov\eva>. xakewop = "troublesome." As if he were some animal we were trying to lay hold of. Cf. Polit. 273b: 80-a XaXeTra tus €)(€L? €L7TeLV 6lXXt]V 6SoV- with him. 0EAI. 'AAA' ovk ex&). HE. BofAef Sijra ivepi tlvos tcov obavXwv pceriovTes 5 7reipa&cop.€V Trapadeiypa avro OeaOaL tov /W(Wo9 ; e 0EAI. Not. 3?E. Tfc ^ra 7rpoTatjaLpi€0' av evyvcoaTov pev Let the v / x / *v » v >. / ,/ „ angler be /cat apLKpov, Xoyov oe p-yoevo? eXarrova e^ov tcov our ex- yi t > / 9 ' ' " / / ample, in peiCpvcov ; Oio*/ acnraXievT-qs' ap ov iracn re yi/co- 10 which to v ^~j/ \ \ ~ \ j /s. practise the /)£/UOI> Kdl TToBev epol crvy- yevetav e'xeiv rivd. 5. /xeriwres] Used absolutely, as in Protag. 350 d : el ovra p,e- Tiav epoio p,e. It is natural that words like p-enevac and xpw® ai (supr. 217 c), which recur often with the same object (\6yos), should sometimes be used alone. 6. 7rapd8eiypa Oeivai] Cf. Polit. 277 c sqq., where the nature of such examples is explained. The "large letters" of the Ee- public afford an apparent in- stance of the converse method. But in each case the inquiry advances from the less known to the more known. 8. 7rpo7-a|ai/xe^' av] Sc. {JlTeiv or periivai. 10. oiov acmaXuvTris] The con- struction is absolute. Cf.Theset. 178 C : oiov 6epp.d ; dpa k.t.A. Euthyd. 302 a : olov @ovs nai Trpopara, dpa k.t.X. alib. 11. 011 irdvv tl 77oX\rjs rivos] " Worth no very great amount of interest." 15. KaXcos ni» e^oj] " That is well." The expression is slightly hypothetical. Thesetetus takes the Stranger's word for what he himself does not clearly see. Ui 1IAAT12N02; He is an artist, and there are two kinds of art : HE. cf. Theset. 168 a: ami — (piXoa-o- cpav pio-ovvras tovto to irpaypa. Legg. 7; 8 TO a: (pi\oo-os Trpbs akXrjkovs 6)pihrjo~av. 4. "Hklo-to. ye] ye, though omitted by the Bodleian MS., with All, is probably right, and expresses assent to the meaning of the question. 8. nav aapa] " All," col- lectively, as in Ar. Eth. Nic. I. 13. § 7 '• o(fi6a\p6v Kai ttclv (Tcbpa. For (TKiVOS = $-vv8(Tov Kai ivkao-Tov, cf. Hep. 2, 38 1 a : Kai pijv Kai to. ye i^vvdera ■navTa, aKevr] re Kai olKodoprjpara Kai dpcpieo-paTa. o-Kevos here de- notes what is manufactured, (compounded or moulded,) as distinguished from organized bodies; cf. Eep. 10, 596 d. a twice over, after 8iKai6rara and -npoa- ayopevoiro. 1 4. Uav oTrep] " In the case of everything, which — ." The ac- cusative is placed, as if abso- lutely, at the beginning of the sentence, and is rather governed by cpapev than by Syovra. Cf. Polit. 295 d : TTCLV TO TOIOVTOV £vp- Paivov, where the accusative is absolute. And infr. t6 — padrjpa- tik6v — et'Sos. For the meaning, cf. Theset. 155 b : o pi) npoTepov fy, SOM2TH2. 17 iy. ovaiav ayy, rov \xev ayovru iroLelv, to 8e ayo\xevov TTOieiaOai irov (j)afui>. 6EAI. 'OpOm. HE. Ta 8e ye vvv 8rj [a] 8ir']A0opev airavTa ei^ev els tovto tx]v olvtcdv 8vvat±iv. 5 0EAI. Ei'xe yap ovv. HE. Y]oli]tiki)v tolvvv aura avyKe(PaAaicoadfxevoL TrpoaeLTTCojiev. c 0EAI. "Eo-rco. SE. To 5?) pLaOrjfAaTiKov av fierce tovto elSo? oAov io /cat ro r?79 yvcopiaecos to re ^pi]/xaTiaTLKov koll ay to- ol uXXu varepov tovto elvai livev tov yevea6ai Kai yiyue(T0cu cibvvaTov ; Symp. 205 b : »/ yap rot eV tov firi ovtos els to bv Iovti 6t(oovv atria ndo-d iort Trolqais. Pro- duction is more fully desci'ibed in Legg. 10, 894 a: ylyverat 5/) ndvrcov yeveo-is, rjviK av ri nddos f] \ 8r]Kov cos oiiQTav dp^rj \a(3ovo~a av£r]v els ttjv 8evTepav e\8{] /xerd- (3ao-iv, koX dnb ravrr^s els ti)v ttAt/- o~lov, kcli pexP 1 T p l <<> v eXdovcra aladrjo-iv o~XJ] Tols alo-davofievots. 4. Ta Se ye vvv 8r) [a] 8ltj\6o- /xei'] " But those things which we just now enumerated." a is omitted in the Bodleian and seven other MSS. The reading a 8e ye vvv 8rj 8ir)\6ou.ev, which is adopted by the Zurich editors, is due to a corrector of the Coislinian MS. But the read- ing in the text is preferable as being less obvious ; and the inversion (vvv 81) d for a vvv S17) is in the manner of these dia- logues. (The old edd. had vvv a 8>} with B E F.) For Td — a, cf. Rep. 8, 585 b : to 0101/ a irov re (cat ttotov ku\ b\j/ov. 10. To 81] — Tvptnci yap «i>] " Well, if we take next to this the whole department of learn- ing and of acquiring know- ledge, with those of money- making, contention and pursuit, since none of these produces, but they are engaged either in conquering, or in preventing men from conquering, that which already exists and has been produced, — on account of all these sections, it will ap- pear most suitable to use the term ' acquisitive art.' " "It will indeed wear an appro- priate look." Observe that no attempt is made to look for the Sophist either in the padrjp.aTi- kov or yvcopio'TiKov el8os tu>v Te%- vav. The construction of the sentence is not determined from the beginning, but the accusa- tives (which are resumed in TavTa i-vvdiravTa to. p-eprj) simply follow the analogy of ttoitjtlktjv — axiTa. p.adr]u.aTiKbv] So the Bod- leian MS. Here, as in Ar. Met. I. 1, the MSS. vary between u-aBquaT. and p.a6rjT. IS FIAATQNOS Ami an art of getting. The an- gler's is an art of get- ting. vicniKov koli OijpevriKov, — iirevbrj Siyuovpyu. pclv uvoev p. 219. tovtcov, ra 8e ovra koll yeyovora r« fitv yeipovrou Aoyoi? koll Trpaijeai, tu 8e toi? yeipovixevois ovk t7riTp€7r€i, — \mkicrT av nov 81a. ravra ^vvairavra ra 5 fiepy rtyyr) ris KTr/riKi] XeyOeiaa av Stair ptyeiev. GEAI. Ngu' irpliroi yap av. £?E. KrrjriKrj? 81] Ka\ 7roirjTiKr]<; ^v/nraacov ovacov d rcov reyycov eV rrorepa rrjv aairaXievTiK-qv, co Qeal- rrjre, ridco/iev; ° GEAI. 'Ei> KTYjTLKfl 7T0V 8rjAoV. 2. ra pev xeipovrai Xoyots] Cf. Eutliyd. 290 b, where geometers &c.are classed amongst 8-qpevrai. 4. eTTiTpsTre 1] SC. X.eipoiHT0aiavrd. fiaKuTT av ttov — 8itt7rpe\|/-eiei>] So Bocll. a. n. i. : cett. 8iaypd- •fyeuv. If we compare the cor- responding clause in the pre- ceding context, supr. b, £vp- iravra ravra — ovopari, it ap- pears that no rendering of these words is satisfactory which separates ravra from ^vvdnavra ra pepr] ■ (e. g. Stallb. " maxime propterea has partes cunctas — dici decebit :" which is also objectionable because of the harshness of the at- traction, Aex<9etrra for Xf^eVra). The same objection holds (un- less but were omitted) against the reading hiaypd-fyeiev, which was justly suspected on other grounds by Heindorf. Hence the preceding accusatives, which are absolute, are re- sumed with a new construc- tion in ravra ^vvdnavra ra. pepr] '. and the words mean either, as above rendered, " an art of ac- quisition is the most suitable to be named on account of all these parts" (cf. Polit. 269 c : Trpe^et prjdev. lb. 288 C : rovro — rovroLS ev ovopa anaa-iv npeyj/ei irpouayopevdi'v), or, by a return to poetical usage, suggested by the rare verb, Sid may per- haps be construed "through- out," and Sianpeyf/etev may re- tain something of the original meaning of " looking brightly forth." " An art of acquisition will, when named, be seen clearly to peiwade all these sections." Cf. Emped. Fr. w. 5,6: rpls pev pvplas a>pas dno paKa- pa>v dXaXrjcrBai, yeivopevov irafTOia 8 id xp* a eiSea 6vr}ra>v. Horn. Hymn to Hermes, w. 350, 1 : ocppa pev ovv e'SiWe Sid i|/ap.a- 0w8ea \S>pov, pela pdX i^via ivavra Sie'irpeTrei' ev Kovirjaiv. The latter interpretation makes the anacoluthon easier, and gives a more appropriate meaning to the compound verb, but is too singular to be asserted with confidence. For pd\i. 6. npeivoL yap av] Sc. ovra Xe^delcra. IO. S^Xoi/] Sc. on. 20I2TH1\ 19 p. 219. aE. K.Tr)TiKr/s 8e dp ov 8vo e\8r) ; to pei> €k6i>tq)v Trpo? €kovtol9 p.eTafi\r)TiKOV ov 8td re 8cope(ov koll jXLaOcaireodv koll dyopdaeoov ; to 8e \ol7tov 77 /car Not by ,/ * v . / / j., y contractoi epya iq klxtcl Aoyovs yeipovpevov ^vpirav x €l P COTLKOi/ ,; ■■■ ' ,x „ but con- ay €LTJ ; 5 quest. GEAI. ^aiVerat yovv e/c twv elp^pevoav. (H*E. T/ 8e ; rr}f yeipadTiKTjV dp' ov 8l\t) TprjTeov ; GEAI. IIt?; e £JE. To /zej> dvaffiairSbir o\ov dycaviaTiKov -\6ev- An ' 1 tl,is T€?~f , TO de KpV(j)OLOV aVTYJS irdv 6r)peVTlKOV. 10 force but GEAI. Not. aE. Ti]v 8e ye p.1^1/ 6f)pevTiK^v dXoyov to prj ov Tep.veiv Sixfj- GEAI. Aeye 07177. mE. To pev axj/v^pv yevovs SieXop.€i>ovs, to b* 15 €fJL\jnJ)(OV. GEAI. Tt pr)v ; elirep eo~Tov ye ap(f)to. SE. IT coy 8e ovk eaTOv ; /cat <5e? ye rj/zay ro /ueV Now of catching by 2. iAeTa(3\r)TiKov ov — ^etpcort/coi/ £u/M7raf] I. e. while undi- au eirj] For the independent vided. So o\ov, nav, k.t.X., in verb in the second of two de- what follows. pendent clauses, see Theset. 9. forest] Sc. repvcopev. 149 e : bvvavrai. eyeipeiv re — /cat Bevras Heind. and Par. E. corr. — dfxj3\io-Kovo-iv, et passim. The MS. confirmation is too 3. f) kcit epya rj koto. Xoyovs] slight to justify the admission Like Xoyois kuI TTpa^eo-t above. of a conjecture, which must Science is here included under however be regarded as pro- xetpmriKi]. Knowledge is like bable. Cf. infr. dielopevovs. But the kingdom of heaven, which see Polit. 302 d : kcu ravrrjv the violent take by force. r^plv Beriov ecrrl 8ltt\?]v. JJas 6Y7 ; 4. xetpou/ueiw is possibly Kal rivi biaipovvres Tavrrjv. passive, like dvao-TTu u\j/v)((oi>, dvowvpov *oj/*' irXrjV kclt evict ttjs p. 22(1 KoAvpfitjTiKi}'? olttu pepr) KCii TOiavT u\\a (3pa^e'a, yalpeiv edaai, to 8e, rwv ep^rvytav (joocov ovaav 6i)pav, Trpoaenreiv faoOypiKrjv. 5 0EAI. "E*TCO. 3*E. Z(ji)oOi]ptKrjs Se up' ov SnrAovv eiSo? av Ae- yoiTO ev SiKr), to pev 7re(ou yei/ovs, TroAAot? eldeai KCU ouopaat Str)pr)p€i>ov, TretpBypiKov. to 8" eTepov vevaTiKov (a>ov rrav evvypo9r]piKQv ; 10 0EAI. Yldvv ye. HE. NevcrTLKOv prjv to p.ev TTTTjvbv (jwAov opoopev. b to Se evvdpov ; 0EAI. n»j 5' ov; SE. Kcd tov TTT-qvov p.r)P ye'vovs wdaa rjplv 1) ^bOi'-jpa XeyeTdi ttov tis bpviQevTiKr). I. dva>vvp.ov *oj/*J MSH. iav (sic Bodl.) ov is Heindorf's conjecture. Cf. Polit. 260 e : dvoovvp-ov ov Tvyxdvei to yevos. The difference of tense (eai/ — ecio-cu) forbids the notion of an epexegesis like that in Legg. 3, 697 a : to 8e Tpixjj SieXelv — TTeipadapev 8ta.Tcp.eiv. Cf., how- ever, Parm. Fr. 73 : t^v pev iav uvotjtov, dvcovvpov. Plat. Legg. 9, 878 b : dva>vvp.ov (av. ttjs Ko\vfi(3r)TiKris arret /xep'/] E. g. fj t£>v o~7royyoKo\vp.ftr}T(ov 6r)pa. V. Oppian Halieut. V. 612. II. Net/o-rtKoG] "of Avhat swims." The ai'ticle is some- times omitted before a generic or collective word. Cf. infr. 221 b : ^vfXTTao-r]s — Texv>]S. Mr. Grote remarks on this (Plato, (fee, vol. ii. p. 401): "Plato considers the air as a fluid in which birds swim." But the vevo-TLKti TTTrji'd are the water-foAvl. The expression irao-a — t) drjpa below probably implies that only a part of opvidevTiKr] has been previously mentioned. In Legg. 7, 824 c the evvypoOijpevTrjs is distin- guished from the 6pvi0evTrjs, and is forbidden to exercise his art in harbours, or in sacred rivers, marshes, or In the present passage is distinguished from "in wet" from "under the former term in- the latter. The Eleate shews his dialectical skill in proving that " aquatic sport" is not an adecpiate definition of the fisherman's craft. 14. Tvaaa — r) 6r)pa\ I.e. not only of the v(vo-tik6v -m-qvov but of all that flies. The objection pools. evvypos evvdpos, water," cludinQ SO*I2TH2. 21 p. 220. 0EAI. Aeyerai yap ovv. HE. ToV $€ €Vv8pGV 0~)(eSoV TU (TVV0A0V aAicvTiKr). 0EAI. Net/. HE. T/ oY; Tavrr)i> av tijv Orjpav ap ovk av koltol ixeyicrra pe'prj 8uo SieXolp.r]v ; GEAI. Kara. irdla ; HE. Ka0' a to pev epKecrtv uvtoOl ivoidraL ti)v 6-qpav, to Se irXrjyf}. GEAI. ITw? Ae'yei?, kol 7777 8'iatpovp.evos eKa.Tepov\ c HE. To /xeV, — otl irav ocrov av kveKa KoyAvaeoj? etpyy tl Trepieyov, epKO? eiKo? ovopdteiv. GEAI. Haw p.ev ovv. HE. Kvprovs $7] Ka\ diKTva ko! fipoy(pvs /cod TropKOVS Kal tol TOiavTa pccov aWo ti 7rXrjv IpKiq \prj 7rpoaayopev€iv; 5 Offiabing there are two chief parts, one working by enclosure, as with baskets, creels, and nets, the 10 other In- striking ; and this sometimes at night, l>y torch- light, some- times by day with barbed * points. of Aristot., de Part. Anim. I. 2, applies here : npoo-fjKfi pr) 81a- cnrav emo-Tov yevos, oiov rovs opvi- 6as rovs pev iv 7776V tovs 8° ev (iWrj diaipeau, Kado^'p e^ovatv al yeypappevai 8iaipeacrl yovv TLves. S?E. To de ye Xolttov Icttlv ev eTL p.6vov, a>$ threw, eldos. 8. [4]] 3.1 12. Trpos 77V pos s yiyv6fievov\ The nocturnal branch of the art of striking fish, as it is pur- sued by fire-light, has received from those who practise it the name of ' firing.' I 6. nav ayKurTpevTiKou] Sc. ep- prjOr) from prjOrjvai avpfteftrjKev. dyKto-rpevTiKov] This notion reappears in Legg. 7, 823 e (a curious passage) : h cpiXoi, eld' i>p.as pr]re t\s emdvp,ia pfjr epcos rrjs 7re/H dukarrav Stjpas Trore Xu/3oi, pr]8e aytuarpeias' prjS" oXeos tt)s rcbf evvdpcov £a>oov, prjre iypr)- yopocn pi']re ev8oV(Ti Kvprois (cf. SUpr. b.) apybv 8rjpav dicnrovovpe- vois. (Cf. Opp. Halieut. 3, et sqq. : Kvprois, 01 Kvao-aovras eovs r)v(ppr]vav avaKTas.} 2 0. oiirco] Qc.avcoOev els to kcltw. Xpr)0-6ai~\ Sc. tovs nepl ttjv re^- vr]v. Cf. Gorg. 457 C, hvvavrai. p. 220. GEAI. To irolov ; aE. To tt}s tvavTias TavTy 7rXr)yr]?, uyKicrTpcp re 521. yiyvopevov kcu tcov lyOvcav ov)( ?) tis av Tvyr) rou o~go- /xaros 1 , cocnrep tols Tpiodovaiv, aXXa irep\ Tiqv K((pdXrjV kou to o~TQ\±a rod OrjpevOevTOs eKaarore, koll KarcoOev eh TOwavTiov avco pa(38oL$ kcu kclXcc/jlois uvacrTrco- fxevov' ov 11 (frrjcrofiev, co Gecu'r^re, Sew Tovvopa Xeyeadai ; GEAI. Aokco fxev, oirep dpri 7rpov0€/xe0a Sew e^evpelv, tovt clvto vvv chroTereXeaOaL. aE. Nw apa Tr)? acnraXievTLKrjS iripi o~v re Kciyco b avvcop.oXoyr]Kapev ov fiovov tovvo/jlo,, dXXa koll top Xoyov Trep\ clvto Tovpyov elXrjtyapLtv 'iKavm. £vpma- o~r]9 yap T€)(i>r)? to fiev rjpicrv Liepos ktt]tlkov rjv, KT7JTLKOV Se ^ipcOTlKOV, )(eipCOTLKOV Se OrjpEVTLKOV, TOV 2GvypoO)]piKov Se tI) KarcoOeu rprjpa o\ov aXievTiKov, aAievriKrjs de ttXiiktikov, 7rAi]KTiKr]? 8e (tyKKTTptVTLKOV' TOVTOV $6 TO 7T€pl TY)V KOLTCx>6eV (ll>(jd 5 irXtiy^v uva(J7ru>p.evriv, air avrri? rrj<> TTpaijecos d(f)o- c pLotcoOeu rovvopa, i) vvv aaTruXtevTiK^ (jfTrjOeura Itt'l- k\i~\v yeyovev. 0EAI. Ylavrawacri pev ovv tovto ye lkolvco? 8e8r']- Xootcli. 2. to Ktircodev] Cf. infr. 266 a. 4. to 7rep\ tt)v] " The class which comprised." Cf. supr. tov \6yov nepl civto Tovpyov. 5. an ai/Trjs Trjs Ttpu^ecos d(po- poiuidev Tovvopa] I.e. it is pro- posed to derive danraXuvs from dvao-nda. See also Tim. Lex. 52 : do-7raXLevs, d\i(vs, dno tov dvucmqv tijv aypav. HesycllillS has preserved the real deriva- tion from ao-TTakos, an Athama- Tt X vr) {irOirjTlKl]) 1 KTTjTLKT] (p.eTalB\r]TLKr]) — L. — ^eipcoTiKT] (dyeovio-TiKr)) — I^OrjpevTiKi] {6i]pn tcov dyj/v)((bv) — ' — ^coodTjpLKrj (rre^odrjpiKT]) — ' — evvypodrjptKi) (opvidevTiicfi) — I — dXievTiKi] (epKodrjpiKrj'j — ' — tt\i]kti.ki] (jTVpeVTlKT]) 1 dyKtO~Tp€VTlKr) nian word for 'fish.' (Passow Lexic. s. v.) 6. 17 vvv do-TvuXitVTiKrj £r)TT)- 6e'io-a\ T. e. da7Ta\i(VTiKr], 77 vvv (i)T7]6eio-a. Cf. infr. 231 b : iv T(p vvv Xo'yw Trapa(pav€VTi. Note the apposition of neuter and fern. : to irepl — 17 k.t.A., and of the name with the thing : t<.v- vopa with 1) dcmaXievTLKi]. TliC following is a summary of the ahove divisions : 8. TiavTairao-i pev ovv tovto ye cKavcbs deSfoaiTai] The method of dichotomies has proved ade- quate for the definition of an art so simple and familiar as that of the angler. The notion of the Sophist, however, is more complex, and after several par- tial attempts, the definition of him is found to be impracti- cable, until we lay aside this (rpiodovria) — ' — do-Tra\.ievTiKi']. method for a time and review some of our fundamental ideas. It is difficult to say how far the first or tentative part of the inquiry is seriously intended by Plato as an illustration or application of method. There is a tinge of satirical humour obvious in almost every line. This was the motive for the choice of the angler as an ex- 20<1>I2TH2. 2.5 p. 221. SE. €p€ 8/], Kara tovto to Trapuhtiypa koll tov o-o(j)iarrji> iTriyeip&pev evpeiv, o tl ttot ecrTiv ; 0EAI. l^o/ntSfj fieu ovv. iftE. Kai /x?;^ €«€iv6 y rjv to (rjTrjpa TrpcoTOv, TTOTtpOV l8lC0T1fV 7] TLVOL Tt\Vr]V tyOVTOL 0€T€OV ell/at 5 tov acnraXievT-qv. 0EAI. Nat. HE. Kou zw <5r; tovtov ISicoTyv Orjaofitv, co Qeai- d r?;re, ?} 7ravTa.7ra.0-Lv cos aXrjdcos o~o(pio~Tr)V ; 0EAI. OvSapLCos IduorrjV pavOavco yap o Aey«9,co? 10 *7ra^roy* <5et toiovtos elvai to ye bvo/ia tovto e^oov. 2E. 'AAAa rti/a Te^vrjv amov rjpuv ZyovTa, cos eoiKe. OtTeov. Foil. this ( pie Li t as endeavour to find til*: nature of the Sophist also. Is he an artist, as the fisher- man was ? His name declares him to he, par excel- lence, an artist. ample, this prompts the in- clusion of war and tyranny, pleading and arguing, under SijpevTiKr], and that of poetry and learning amongst the mer- chant's wares, and the defini- tion of higgling in the market as au inartistic kind of con- troversy. A deeper irony un- derlies the admission of the Sophist's claim to be considered as a purifier of the soul. Yet inseparably bound up with this tone of sarcasm there is the scientific spirit, which seeks for general truths and disregards common opinion. The defini- tion of the tyrant or the war- rior as a hunter of men falls in with Plato's satiric fancy, but has also an element of scientific truth, and belongs to the effort to connect things apparently diverse under one idea. This mixture of satire and inquiry finds characteristic expression in infr. 227 b : tov KTTjo-aadai yap f-'vexa vovv irao-av Texvmv to £vyyeves Kai to flrj gvyyei'es KaTavoelv neipcopevr] (17 twv \6ya>v Texyrf) Tipa npos tovto e'£ to-ou Trao-as — aepivoTepov 8e n tov 81a o-TpaTTjyiKTJs *] epdeipiaTiKTjs drj'XovvTa 8r]pevTiKr)v ov8ev vevo- p.LKev, dXX as to rro\v yavvoTepov . 8. Kai vvv 8r/] "So now also." Ka\ to be taken closely with vvv. 9. as akrjQms o-o] the one turning to the sea- For the omission of to pev, which shore and to rivers and lakes, is present in some MSS., com- to angle for the creatures that pare Soph. Trach. 117 : rpeqba, are therein." HE. At^a 7rov vvv 8iel\op.ev tt]v dypav Trdcrav, V6V- CTTLKOV pt€pOV9, TO 8e 7T€(^OV T€pVOVT€9. 0EAI. Nat. HE. Kal to pev SirjXOopev, oaov irepl to. vevorTiKa tcov ivvSpcov to Se ire^ov eldaapev dcryio-TOv. elirov- 15 re? otl iToXvubes e'lrj. 0EAI. Haw ye. p. 222. HE. Me'x/)* ptev tolvvv IvTavQa 6 ao(picrTr)s re /cat o aaiTaXtevTrjs a/xa goto tt]? kt7]TIKt]? Teyyrj^ iropev- ecr&ov. -° 0EAI. 'FtOlKGLTOV yOVV. From this £?E. ^KTpeireaOov Se ye goto 7-77? ^tooOrjpLKrj^, 6 2. rdubpos tov avdpa] Cf. to S' ai/|ei. Eurip. Hippolyt. Kep. 5, 455 d: to yevos tov 233, 4. Theset. 181 d. 20M2TH2. 27 p. 222. p-tv eVrt OaXarrav irov koll 7rorap.ov? koll XipLvas, rav T0VT0L9 £coa OrjpevaopLtvos. GEAI. Tifirjv; SE. O <5e ye etn rrjv yrjv koll Trorapovs erepovs av tlvols, ttXovtov koll veoTrjTO? oiov Xei/mcovas a(j)66- 5 vovf, rav tovtols OpepLpcara xeLpwaopLevos. b 0EAI. Um Xeyeis ; HE. Tr/s ire^rjs &r)pa$ yiyveaOov Svo p-eylarco rive fJteprj. 0EAI. Yiolov eKccrepov ; ic path di 1 1 rge. The Ml"!' | i flu rivers, lakes, and teeming seas. The Sophist turns him to the land: or if to rivers they are the rivers of wealth, which nourish bounteous i. 7rov gives the touch of conscious iudefiniteness in which the preciseness of the Greek language delights. 4. 'O 8e ye errl ttjv yrjv — ] " To very different rivers of wealth, and rich meadow-lands of generous youth." Lit. " to rivers of wealth, a different sort of rivers." This punctu- ation avoids the confusion of the two metaphors (river and meadow) and preserves the appropriateness of each. For the former, cf. iEsch. Prom. 805 : 01 XP v(J °PP VTOV oIkovvas is naturally sug- gested by the notion of a fer- tilizing river with green banks, and perhaps partly by a false echo from Xip,vas preceding. 8. Tr)s Tre^s 6i)pas k.t.X.] The description of 8i)pevriK^ in Legg. 7, 823 b should be compared, line by line, with this passage : 6r\pa yap TtapnoXv tl irpdypa. eo-n, TrepieiXr]p.p,evov ovopari vvv o~xe86v ivi. 7rok\rj p.ev yap i) ra>v ivv8pa>v, tvoXXtj 8e rj rav Trrr]vu>v, irapnoXv 8e Kal to tvepX to. 7re£a drjpevpara, ov povov drjplcov, aXXa Ka\ ttju rav dvdpamcDV ai^iov ivvoelv 8i)pav, ttjv re Kara ir6Xepov : tyoXXtj 8e /cat 77 Kara (piXiav Orjpevovaa, rj p.eu enat- vov, T] 8e xj/oyov e\ei' Kal KXaTrelat,, Ka\ Xy]o~Ta>v /ecu o~TpaTOTre8av arpa- TOTre8ois Brjpai. yiyveo-6ov\ Bodl. Vat. Ven. n. yLyveo-Qa, which might be defended from emap.ev follow- ing. But the word is explana- tory of exxpeireo-Qov in what precedes, and the v is more likely to have been dropped than to have been inserted wrongly, especially considering the SpoioTfXevrov of peyiara). The 61'ipa tcov ijpepcov is termed peyLCTTOV as including o-Tpari]yui, XrjariKr), 8iKaviKrj, epcoTlKrj, koXu- KlKl], CTOCpllTTlKl]. E 2 IS IIAATI2N02. pastures i generous youth. Now land animals arc tame and wild ; and, if man is a tame crea- ture, tame creatures also ran be made a prey. HE. To pev riiiv rjptpoyv, to 8e tcov dypicov. BEAI. Etr €(.ttl tl? 6i)pa tcov ypc-'pcov ; HE. Ei' irlp ye iorTiv av6pa>iroov. 0e? 8e ottyj xalpcL?, e'/re p.r)8ev TiOeis ijpepov, e'/re aAAo 5 p.ev i]p.epov ti, tov he avOpcoirov aypiov, etre rjpepov pcev Aeyei? av tov avOpioirov, avOptoiTtov 8e prjdeplav rjyel 6r\pav. tovtcov '\ biroTep^ av r]yel (j)i\ov elprjoQai aoi, tovto iip.lv Stopiaov. p. 222. 2. eira expresses surprise. Cf. The^et. 207 d. 3. El' trip ye eariv dvd, rjp. £.] This is not always fully ad- mitted. See Theset. 174 d: Bvo-KoXwrepov 8e eKelvasv ££>ov Kai e-m^ovXoTepov noipaiveiv re Kai (38dXXeiv vupi^ei avrovs. Legg. 6, 766 a '. "AvBpumos 6Y, wt (papev, ijpepov, opcos prjv naiSelas pev opdrjs tv\ov Kai (pvaecos eirvxovs 6eioTdTOV rjpepaiTaTov re ££)ov yiy- vecrBat (piXel, pr) Ikciucos 8e r) pr) Ka\£>s rpacfrev aypiioTciTov onocra (pvei yr\. Cf. Xen. Cyr. I. 1, § 2 : Tracras roivvv tcis ayeXas ravras ebonovpev opav paXXov edeXovo-ai Tveldeadai rots vopevo~iv r) tovs avBpconovs rois apxovai. For Ti6e\s — Xeyeis, cf. Supr. 221 d, and note. 7. foTrorep'T av rjyel (piXov el- prja-Oal aoi] The plural onoTepa, with 4>iXov and tovto following, is difficult ; and the word im- plies two, whereas there are three if not four alternatives. Badham's conjecture, o ti irep &v (cf. infr. 255 a, Legg. 1, 645 c), is probably right, rjyel is the Bodleian reading ; av is to be taken with elpija-dai (ptXov o-ot : " Whichever of these alterna- tives you think will please you when spoken." Com- pare infr. 223 b: TO 7TpOO-?)KOV ovop av rjyovpat KaXelv avrov. There is no objection to the repetition of the same word r]yel in a somewhat different connexion ; cf. Theset. 148 b : ovk av Surcupyrji' — wa-rrep trepl — ttjs Wdjiews. alib. 8. tovto rjplv Siopiaov] The Bodleian and the cognate MSS. (including Flor. i.) have biopi- o-reov. This could only mean, " Whichever of these alterna- tives you think will please you, this we must decide upon." But this reading, though not altogether absurd (cf. Polit, 261 e *. KaOarvep bianeXevus iroirjreov), may probably be classed amongst those which, although occurring in the best MSS., are traceable to the wrong-headed ingenuity of the scribes, like etjaio-101 o-otpol for e|i}s ol crocpoi in Theset. 1 52 e (Bodl.), aKpiftccv for aKpcov, ib. 148 c. (Bodl. A. n.) The impe- rative is required by 6e$ pre- ceding. For tovto rjplv diopiaov , cf. Gorg. 488 d : tovto poi avTo o~a(pa>s biopiaov, tovtov tj eTepov eo~Ti to Kpelrrov Ka\ to fieXTLov Kai to lo-\vp6Tepov. Rep. IO, 598 a : 'A pa ola eariv r) oia (pai- verai ; tovto yap en 8iopiaov. 20, drjpav re avOpwiraiv tivai Xe'yco. 3*E. AlTT7jV TOLVVV KOLl TTJL* rjfJL€po9^piKl)V ei7T0)/JL€l>. 0EAI. Kara ti XeyovTt? ; AE. T?)^ /X6// Xr]0~TLK1]V KOLL aV^paTToBLCTTLKrjV K.OLI 5 This hap- \ \ 5- / \ . /,\/ P enB either TVpaVVlKTjV KOLl ^VpLTTaCTaV TY]V TToXepLLKyV, €V TTaVTa through n / n / i / force or piaiov Ur/pav opicra/jLevoi. through 0EAI. KaXm. pe,su " ion - SE. Tt)v <5e' ye 8iK.avLKi]v roll Srj/j.i]yopiKr]i> kou 7TpO, €V CLV TO ^VVoXoV IT iO av OV py LK1]V 10 d riva fiiav riyviqv irpoawirovTes. 6EAI. 'Op0m. HE. T^9 &) 7ndaV0VpyiKrj? SlTTOC XiycopLeV yevr). And per- suasion may be public o private. 0EAI. YiyvecrOov yap ovv tido? eKarepov. 3*E. OvKOVV ai) TT]? i8lO0r]p€VTlKrjs TO /ueV pucrOap- Persuasion / , v jv rs , , in private VtVTLKOV eO~Tl, TO be OCOpoCpopLKOV ; sometimes 0EAI. Ou piavOaVGi. wards, and H-cpi m ~ " > ' r\' '* * »/ sometimes A ti. 1 27 tcov ep&vTcov urjpa. TOV VOW, 0)? toiKas, 20 on the v / contrary oi>7rtt> 7rpoaeo-yes. brings /"vtt< at tt " suasion BEAI. Ilcua; ^TT' T^ * " '£•' v £ v £> ' ' public or A hi. 1 o ^.tej/ eTepou iota., to be or/pLoaia yiyvop.tvov. Tr gifts. 5. T?jv fih \j]o-TiKi'jv — ] Com- cler one heading, pare Ar. Pol. I. 3 : Oi 8' anb 17. pia6apvevTiKoi> — ptaGapvev- 6i]pas C&>o-ii>, tca\ 6t)pa<; (repot tikov] I prefer giving the form erepas, oluv oi pev airb A^oreta?, of the word which appears ill 01 $' acp' akielas — ol S' air opvl- all the MSS. (instead of pi- 6u>v r) Brjplaiv aypiav. Alb ko.\ r) crdapvrjTLK.), though suspected by Tro'XepiKr] cpvo~ei kttjtikt] ttws ea-rar Heinclorf, whose dictum (Quod rj yap 6-qpevTucr) pepos avTrjs, jj SeZ in Lexicis, auctore nullo, pro- XPi)o~6ai Ttpos re ra Brjpici Kai rav fei'tur verbum ptcrdapveveiv, val- dv6p6iTru)v 00-01 necpvKOTes apx^o-dai de vereor ne a sermonis ana- prj 6e\ov from invented in order to include Kanr/'Kos 1 Still it may be cor- love-making and sophistry un- rupted from ISiodijpeur. so riAATQNOS Lovers, for instance, lavish pre- sents "ii v. I mi they win. Of mercen- ary persua- sion, one 1. ranch allures through pleasure, and, as for hire, ex- pects no more than to be fed. This is called flattery. Another kind pro- fesses to impart virtue, and takes a money fee. What is 0EAI. Tovwepi; p. HE. ' Qti roi9 drjpevOdcrt Scopa 7rpocre7rt8i8oao~ii>. 0EAI. ' AXydearara Xe'yet?. e HE. Tovto pev tolvvv epcoTiKr/s T€)(W]9 earco elSos: . 5 0EAI. Udvv ye. HE. Tou Se ye pucrOapvevTiKov to pev irpoao- ptXovu Sid -)(apLTOs koll TravTanvaai Si rjSovrj? to Se'Xeap ireironip.evov kou tov piaOov irpaTTopevov Tpo(f)-qv eavTcp povov KoXa.KiKi]i>, coy eycopai, irdvTes p. iofyalpev av rj8vi>TiKr)V Tiva Te^vrjv elvai. 0EAI. YIcos yap ov ; HE. To Se eirayyeXXopevov pev coy apeTrjs eveim Tag bpiiXias iroiovpievov, pnaOov Se vo pier pa irpaTTo- pievov, dpa ov tovto to yevos eTepw Trpoo~emeiv d^iov Hoi/opart,; 0EAI. Umydp ov ; HE. Tivi 8r) tovtco ; rreipco Xeyeiv. 223. 2. 7rpo(T€7T-t^tSoao"ii'] The pre- positions imply " in addition to all the means employed to win them." (npocreTi 8a>pa yp. 2.B.) 4. ipu>riKT)s Tex v is — eiSos] Gen. of apposition. 6. Tou de ye piadapvevTiKOv elvai] " But that sort of hireling the object of whose commerce is to gratify, and whose lure is baited with any kind of plea- sure, while the only hire which lie exacts is sustenance for him- self, I presume we should all describe as the flatterer, who is one of the sweeteners of life." 8. ■neTroirip.ivov ] pf. passive with middle signification. IO. TjSvvTiKip Tiva Tex vr } v ~\ " al1 art of sweetening." These words express the function of koKcikikt] more precisely. There is no need of inserting fj before ^w. with Heindorf and some later editors. Cf. Theast. 175 e : p-q- 8e 6\f/6v rj8vvai t] 6a>na<; Xoyovs, where cookery and flattery seem to be included under rjSvvTiKT] ; and Gorg. 462-465, where however KuXaKela is the general word, including o^o- noua, prjTopLKTj, and the rest. Other instances occur (e. g. p.eTa$\r}TiKTi supr. compared with infr. 224 c) in which the same word has alternately a general and specific meaning. 12. To Se — ovopan] " But an- other sort, professing to make virtue the end of his inter- course, while exacting his hire in the shape of coin, — is it not worth while to address this kind by a different name?" 20M2TH2. 31 p. 223. 0EAI. ArjXov 8i]' tov yap ao({)io-T)jv poi Sokou- pcev avevprjKevou. tout ovv eycoye elircov to irpoo~i)K.ov ovopi av rjyovpcai KoKtlv avTOv. b HE. Kara Srj tov vvv, co Qec/.LTrjTe, Xoyov, cos* 4. Kara 8rj — 8r)pn] The obser- vation of Schleiermacher, that thei'e are several redundant words in this passage, was mis- applied by Heindorf and Stall- baumwhen they rejected picrdap- VLKrjs as Well as KrrjTiKrjs, ne(o8r]- pias, and r'lpepodrjpiKijs. For the science which takes rewards includes the flatterer with the Sophist, who stands alone how- ever in taking his reward in money. The word ireCodrjpLas can hardly be retaiued, x e P- aaias being evidently substi- tuted for this with reference to Slipr. 222 a: 6 be ye eir\ ri)v yrjv. The Case of r)pepo8rjpiKr)S is somewhat different. For there might be other tame creatures besides man which became the objects of the chase (e.g. pheas- ants and deer in modern times); compare Polit. 262 b. The MSS., however, vary as to the form of the word. xetpodTiKris, which the edi- tors retain after oliteiaiTiKrjv, has very slight authority (Ven. 2. Aid. Bas. 1, 2. St.) The word is not indispensable ; for oucetomfo/s might be fairly substituted (according to the spirit of the present passage) for xeipojrtK^s, as a softer word — " Convey the wise it call." We may therefore either read KTr}TiKi)s, OLKeia>TiKrjs, 01' omit XeipaTiKijs and KTTjTiKrj^, taking otKeLooTiKrjs as a substitute for both. The Stranger is not always quite exact in reca- pitulating. Thus, infr. 224 d, peTa(3\r]TiKri is substituted for aWciKTiKr], and the peTa(H\t]TtKr) of the previous argument is omit- ted. Hence it is unnecessary, with Heindorf and Stallbaum, to supply the missing link tti- davodiipiasinike present passage. Cf. Polit. 261 e, where such va- riation of terms is justified. nefodripias, if genuine, distin- guishes Tre£a from TTrrjva, x e P~ crains, 7re£a from evvbpd, but X- should then come first. The divisions have been as follows : Texvr) TTOir]TlKr]-^—KT^TLKr) peTaffk-qTlKTj 1 \eip(£>TlKT] dyaviCTTiKr] ' 8r]pevriKT} twv d^vx^v 1 £ao6r)piKr] ire£o8rjpiKi) ' ivvypoBrjpiKr) OpVldeVTLKT] ' aKieVTLKT] i8>]ptKrj--l 7r\rjKTiKr) (3iaios Br)pa *— — TridavovpyiKi] TrvpevriKi] — ' — dyKiarTpeVTiKrj i] bijpoala yiyvopevr] — >■ — IbiodrjpevriKii rpinbovria — ' — danciKievTiKr) tuv dypicov-i—f]pepo8r]pLKr] epi< called ' t<» have found the Sophist. 8a>po(popiKr r — I picrdapvevTiKi] KoXaKlKrj 1 acXpKTTlKrj. 32 IIAATUNOI' Still let us look at this many-sided creature in .another aspect. For the divisions we have made afford an opening for defining him in a different way. One eoiKev, ■>'] T€)(i/r)S oii<(ta)TiK))<>, -|/cr/;nK?;9 f", drjpevrucfjs, p (fix)0)]pia\ vopuapaTO- 7tco\ik)]9, 8o^o7rat8evriK7]9, vecov irXovcrLwv kou iv 5 Sofjcov yiyvoplvr) drjpa 7rpoapi]Teov, a)? 6 vvv Aoyoy i]puv avpfialvei, aofpiartKr). 0EAI. YlavTairacn pev ovv. HE. 'En oe /ecu Tjjde ?8(opev ov yap tl (f)av\r}? peToypv earn reyyrjs to vvv (rjTovpevov, aAA' ev p.aka c io7roiKi\r]?. Kal yap ovv ev toIs irpoaOev elprjpevois (j)avracrp.a irape^eTai, p.i] tovto o vvv avro rjp.ei9 (pape'v, aAA' erepov elval tl yevos. 0EAI. Uy 8y ; HE. To Trj? KTrjTLKrjs Te^v^s 8ltt\ovv rjv ei86s ' 5 ttov, to p.ev O-qpevTLKOV p.epos eypv, to 8e aXXaKTLKOV. 23. 4. §ogo7rai.§evTiKTjs] This refers to Slipr. a : inayyeKkopcvov — noiovpevov. kol ev86§av] Cf. Protag. 316 b, where Socrates recom- mends Hippocrates to the con- sideration of Protagoras : 'ln- TTOKpaTrjs o8e ecrrl pev ra>v eVi^co- pia>v, 'A7roXAoScopov vios, oiKias peydXrjs re Kai cv8a.ifj.ovos' avros be Trjv (pvaiv 8oKel evdpiXXos eivai to'is rjXiKiwrais. imdvpelv 8e poi 80- Kel eWoyipos yevecrdai iv rfj Trohei. The use of pe'roxdv io-n for fitrexei, like that of the par- ticiple and auxiliary verb noticed above, is in the style of these dialogues. Cf. also Phaedr. 262 d. 7. ovv] "In accoi'dance with this remark," i. e. consistently with the creature's manifold cunning. 8. Tfj8( 'tioopiv] Eodl. FA An eldcofiev. This might be de- fended from Theset. 202 e : 'la-riov 81). But the text pre- sents a more lively image, and is in better accoi'dance with Plato's usual manner. This corruption is frequent. 1 1 . qbdvT .TTapex-]" tie (aur6,the subject of our inquiry) holds forth the appearance ; leads us to imagine." No English word exactly corresponds to p.ev, to p.ev boop^TtKov, to Se tTipov dyopa- CTTLKOV J 0EAI. Eip7]O-0CO. HE. Kai iatjv av (fyyaopeu dyopaaTLKi]v Stxfl T€fi- veaOai. d GEAI. IL7; HE. Tr)v peu twv avTOvpycov avTOTrcoXiKrjv Siai- povpevr)v, tt)v be toc aWoTpia eypa pL€Tafia\Xopevr)v p.eTafi\r)TLKr)v. GEAI. Udvv ye. HE. Ti Se ; rrjs fjL€T, Ka.7n]- Xlktj Ti'poo-ayopeveTai ; GEAI. Nat. kind ol ac quisition we found bo be ex- change. Property ia exchanged l>y gift and 5 by sale. The seller is either a io manufac- turer or a merchant. The mer- chant either re- tails or 15 exports. quite exact : kttjtikt) was divided into perafShrjTiKov ( = dWaKTiKov) and x (l P COTlK ° 1 'i an d x fl P a>TlK0V into dycoviariKov and drjpevriKov. Supr. 219. 3. to pev baprjTiKov] These words are suggested by 8a>po- (poptKov in the previous argu- ment ; the new discussion, as so often in Plato, taking colour from that which precedes. But cf. also supr. 219 d : /j.eTo/3X^n- kov ou did re Scopecov kul dyopdo-ecov. 9. TrjV pev 8iaipavpevr}v\ " Those who make what they sell being distinguished as ' producers.' " tS>v avrovpySiv] Those who manufacture what they sell. The word is used etymologi- cally. The usual meaning is, ' one who farms his own land.' Cf. >\ Rep. 8, 565 a : tr/pos — ocroi avrovpyoi re kcii anpaypo- ves, ov ivdvv 7roAXa KeKTrjptvoi. 9. diaipnvpevrjv (passive) an- swers better to the question jt/J ((pr)0-0fj,ev TepveaBai) than b~iai- povpevoi, which is read only in two MSS. of inferior note, and appears in two others (n B) as a correction. 11. peT(i(3\r]TiKr)v] This name was previously given to the whole class which is now called dWaKTIKT]. 13. rfj? pfral3\T}TiKTJs K.r.A.] Cf. Ar. Pol. I. 4 : rr/s 8e pera- f3\T]TiK.rjs peyiarrov pev ip-rropia. 1 4. o-^eSov — fjpto-v] And there- fore fit to form our next divi- sion. Ka'mj'kiKTj] The notion of retail business in Rep. 37 ib,c, iv avr% rfj ttoKci k. t. X. is more exact than here. Bodl. p.m. : tcdi n^Xi^. 34 TIAATQN02 Now the export trader deals in food for the body or in food for the mind. HE. To 6V ye e£ aAA?;y eh akXi-jV irokiv 8iaA\ar- p. 229 Topcevov (bvf) kcil Trpdaei epLiropiKi] ; GEAI. Ti 8 ov; 2;E. Trj? 6° e/jLTTOpLKrj? up ovk fiaOijpeOa otl to '< fie'v, ocroi? to crtopa r pefeTai "j"j" Kexprjrat, to 8e, e ocroiy 77 'i'VXHi 7rcoAovv 8id vop.iorp.aTos aAAarrerai ; GEAI. rTcos* toDto Ae'yei? ; SE. To 7repi 7-7)1/ tyvxqv ureas dyvoovp.ev, «T€« to ye ercpov irov ^vviep.ev. » GEAI. No/. SE. Movo"i/O7i> re toLvvv ^vvdiraaav XeycopLeu, eVc I. SiaXXarrouei'Oi/] Prob. mid- dle voice, as p.eTafiaX\6p.€Vov supr., dWaTTerai infr. But per- haps passive, like dvatnrafievov and other words noticed above. dia signifies 'transmission,' as in Rep. i, 328 a : XapnaBia i'\ovTes 8ia8a)p.ev — ^vvUptuJ The first pei-s. plur. is used with a kind of playful condescension, as in Theset. 210 b : rj ovv en Kvovfiev Tt Kai o>8ivopev, w (£iXe, fj Tvdvra eKreroKapev ; II. Movr)v, Kai ypa(f)i- ktjv Kai 0au/j.aTO7rouKr}u kou 7roAAa erepa rrj? ^X^r, Ta fxev 7rapapvOla?, ra 8e Kai (T7rov8rjs X"-P ll> dyOtvra Kai 7rQ)Aovfiei>a, tov ayovra Ka\ ircaXovvTa pr)8ev 5 tjttov rrj? tqjv aiTiwv Ka\ ttotwv Trpdo-ews epiropov opdats dv Xeyopevov irapacr^lv . 0EAI. ' AXrjOeaTaTa Xeyeis. b SE. Ovkovv Ka\ tov fiaOyfiara £vv(ovovfj.€VOV irokiv re €K 7r6\€(09 vopla/JLaTOf dfulfiovTa ravrhv ic Trpoo-epei? ovofjta ; 0EAI. ^(poSpaye. SE. T^s* 8rj y\rv\epTropLKri9 ravrrjs dp ov to fiev Xeiv, cf.Phaedr. 238 a: kcutovtcdv t3>v l8eS)v ennpeTrrjs 17 av rvxfi yevo- pevr/ TTjv avrrjs enavvpiav ovopa- £6pevov tov e'xovTa Trapexerai. In the mention of painting and juggling there is probably a tacit anticipation of pp. 234, 5, where the art of the Sophist is compared to both. For the two genitives ifrvxns napa- fiv6ias x<*p tv > cf. Rep. 7 > 5 2 5 c : ovk 0)1/775 ov8e npacrecos X^P lv ™ s ipiropovs f) Kairrjkovs pehercovTas, d\\' avrrjs rrjs ^fvxrjs, pqo-Ta>vr]s re p.eTao~Tpov aWcov rexvaiv fpya 8iaKop.l£ovT(s or d\\rp\ovs F Kai avio-ovvres, 01 pep Kar ayopas ol 8e ttoKiv eK noKeas dWdrTovrts Kara 6d\ao-a>, it is observable that the middle voice is used ; cf., however, Legg. 760 c. The meaning is the same as supr. 223 e : e'£ aXXrjs els aX\t]v 7ro\iv BiaXXaTTO- pevov &vt] Ka\ Trpdaei. 224 a : eV noXetos — els tto)uv — iwtpao-KO- pivqv. For \eyu>pev, cf. Theset. 159 a: \eywpev df] epe re Kat tre Ka\ TaXX* fjHir) Kara tov avrov \6yov. 13. T77SS17 — dvdyKr}] "Well, of this mental mex*chandize one And the trade in mental 86 riAATQNOS conducted either through fliHjiit'nl display, or tlie com- munication of points of learning. Ami the learning thus bar- tered may concern the arts, or virtue. The pur- veyor of arts may be called an art- seller: but what name is appli- cable to the seller of virtue ? The name of Sophist alone. (7ri8€iKTtKri StKaioTOLTa AeyoiT av, to Se yeXolov p.(v p. 114. oi>x i)ttov tov 7rp6(T0€v, o/aco? Se ixaOrjfxdriov ovaav irpdaiv avrr/v dSeXcjjco tlvl ttj? 7rpdtjecos ovopcaTi irpoaenreiv dvdyKt] ; 5 0EAI. Yldvv pev ovv. HE. TavTr]9 tolvvv ttj9 p.a0r)fjLaTO7rcoXu9 to KTrjTiKrjs, pL€Tal3Ar)TiKrj9, dyopaaTiKrjs; kind might be most fairly term- ed the art of display : but there is another, which will sound no less oddly than the last, but yet, as dealing in learned ware, it must be called by some name which smacks of learn- ing." Heind. and Stallb. think that yeXoIoK applies to the name fiadrj^aToncoXtKrj as com- pared with -^vxefiTTopiKr], and suggest yeXoiw. The interpre- tation is probably right, but the emendation is unnecessary. (13.) \}fvx€finopiKris] The word calls up the same contemptible association which is contained in ^vxaycoyla. Compare also the expression of Soph. Antig. 1063 : as (ifj efi.TTo\r]p.evos, to. 8e KC115 TeKTaivopevos avTO? paOrjpara irep\ tol avra ravra KCU 7T&)AC0J>, €K TOVTOV TO tflV TTpOVTOL^aTO, KaXeiV ovSev dXXo ttXtjv hrrep vvv hr\. GEAI. Tt 8 ov fi€\\a> ; HE. Kai to KT7)TiKrj9 dpa p€Ta(3Ar)TiKOV, dyopa-10 e o~tikov, Kanrr]\iK.ov elre avT07rcoXiKov, dptpoTepcos, o tl 7T€p OLV fj 7T€pl TOL TOLCLVTO. pa07]/J.aTOTTCoXlKOV yeVO$, del av Trpoaepels, to? (fialvei, o~o, ei tivl Toiq>8e irpocreoiKev 15 p. 225. apa to vvv pteTaSicoKopevov yevos. GEAI. Uolco 8rj ; HE. Tr}9 KTTjTlKrjs dyCOVLGTLKr) TL pepOS Tjplv TjV. 4. Kav et tis avrov Ka6i8pv- (xevos iv TrdXet] The former de- finition included all the greater Sophists (including Zeno, see 1 Ale. 119 a), this applies to some lesser lights, such as Anti- phon, and Damon the musician, perhaps to Antisthenes, though it is not certain that he taught for pay. Cf. Men. 92 b (Any- tlis' speech) : e'tre tis gevos eVt- X*ipri tolovtov ti noielv e'ire dcrros. 5. ra 8e na\ reKTaivofievos] I.e. avrovpyos &>v rmv pad^pdrav. 6. 7Tep\ ra avra. ravTa] Sc. to ttjs dpeTrjs : so also tt. to. ToiaiJTa infr. II. Kcmr]\iK6v ei're auro7TC»Xi- kov] This alternative is justi- fied by the words to. ph — The same is found tu apply, thirdly, to I he Iiihik merchant or nianu- faeturer of learned stores. avTos in the preceding sen- tence. Cf. Protag. 313 c : 6 vo yap ovv. ]>. HE. OvK OL7TO TpOTTOV TOLVVV «OTi SlUipf'tV aVTTjV 6Y X a. GEAI. Ka&' OTToia Ae'ye. 5 HE. To p.lv a/AiAAr/TiKov avrr}? TiOevTav, to Se p.ayr]TiK.6v. GEAI. "Eo-tlv. SE. Tr]9 toivvv fia\r]TtKr)9 rw fiev acofiaTL irpos crcD/JuxTa yiyvopevco o~\(E^ov eiKos /ecu 7rpeirov bvopa io Xtyeiv tl tolovtov Tiflefievovs olov (3taaTLKov. GEAI. Noi. HE. Tc3 8e \6yoL9 TTpos \6yov? tl tls, d> Gecu- TrjTe, ctAAo thrr) irXrjv apL^ia^-qTrjTLKOV ; J> GEAI. Ovk'v. r? HE. To Se ye 7rep\ tols ap.(f)icr(3r)Tr]o-€i'? OeTe'ov Slttov. GEAI. Ufj; HE. Kac? ocrov fxev yap ylyveTat p.rjKeai re irpos IvavTia /xrjKr) Xoycov kou irep\ to. 8Uaia /ecu aSiKa 20 8r)pocria, StKaviKov. GEAI. Nat. 2. citto] So the Bodleian MS. here as in Theset. 143 c. 5. T6 (iev apikXrjTtKov — to 8e paxqTiKov] Perhaps there is here the germ of the fine thought which is more fully expressed in Legg. 5, 731 a: (piXoveiKelra Se rjp.1v 7ra? irpbs dperrjV ds. 6 pev yap toiovtos ras TToXeis av£ei, apiWtopevos fiev avTos, tuvs aWovs Be oi koXovoov BiaftoXals. Cf. Criti. 1 09 b : Oeoi — airaaav yr)v — BieXdy^avov, ov Kar epiv. 9. ytyvopevco] Cf. SUpr. 2 20 e. I O. Xeyciv Ti6epevovs] A periphrasis for rldco-dai. " To use some s\ich name, assign- ing it." For Tideo-dai in this sense, cf. Theset. 157 c : v eWur/xeOa kuXiiv dXXo 7rXrjv dvTtXoyiKov ; 6EAI. Ov&v. J5?E. ToO 8e dvriXoyiKov to fiev, oaov Trepi rot ^Vfi^oXaia a/JL(pLo-(3r]T€'LTai fxev, ukt} 8e kou ure^yois irep\ avTO wparreTai, raura Oereov p.tv eiSos, tirehrep avTO SieyvuiKev cos erepov ov 6 Xoyos, drap eiroovv- fxias ovff v7ro twv epnrpoaOev trvytv ovre vvv v(f) rjficou Tvyelv d^tov. 0EAI. ' hXrfOrj' Kara crp.iKpd yap Xiav kou irav- ToBonra. SirjprjTai. SE. To 5e ye evre^yov, kou nepl SiKatcov avrcoi/ kou dSiKcav kou irepi tcov dXXwv bXcos apLcpiaft-qTovi', dp ouk epicrTLKov av Xiyetv eWurfieOa ; Of disputa- tious con- troversy, one kind is nameless, and does not deserve a name, when men higgle over 1 contracts. Another and more systematic form of the 15 same thing is when I. KaraKeKt ppar lapevov — ano- Kpurets] The construction fol- lows fii]K«Ti -rrpos ivavria fir]Krj Xnycov, by a sort of zeugma, since the dative (of the man- ner) is more natural with 71- yvopevov than KaraKeKep/jiaTKr- ptvov. 5. Toy 8e dvTi\oyiKov — o\r/pJ7- tnevov, &c, supra. Compare Soph. Trach. 167 : TOiai>T e(pa(rKe npos 6cv 'Hpa- icKdcov (KTeXtVTciadai irovuv. 6. dre^vas] Bodl. arexfajy. 7. 7rparT6rai is impersonal. 8. encouvpias] Modern poli- tical economy has supplied the missing term, viz. " higgling in the market," except that the word gvpPoXaia extends to other contracts besides those of commerce, including every private matter of dispute, how- ever trifling. 13. Kai ntpl BiKaicov avronv Km dSiKwv Kal nepl tcov ciXXoov oAws] Compare Theset. 175b: orav — ideXrja-Tj — iKJUrjvai (K tou ti tyoj ae ddiKO) 7 rl ail ept (Is aKerf/iu avTrjs SiKaivavvrjs T( Kal ddiKias, 40 11AATQN02 men argue • aecundem artem" on general principles of right. This is Eristic, which may either waste the talker's substance and the hearers' patience, when it is mere loqua- city, or may make a gain of disputa- tion, in which case, what is its right name ? This won- derful So- phist has turned up a fourth time. GEAI. Yla>x eWepov d8oXeo~)^iKov . GEAI. AeyeTai yap ovv ovtco 7rcos. HE. Tovtov TOivvv TovvavTiov, diro tcov ISlcotlkcov c 15 epidcov xprjjAaTilppevov, ev tco p.epeu av ireipco vvv threw. GEAI. Kal tis dv av elircov e\epov ovk e^aptdpTOi 7rXrjv ye tov 6avp.ao~Tov irdXiv eKeivov rJKeiv av k.t.X. For oXcoy (referring to avT&v = in a universal manner, opposed to Kara apiKpa Kal nav- ToSana), cf. ib. 1 74 a: (pvo-iv e'pevvaipe'vrj t5>v ovtcov eKaarov ciXov. The Sophist's art is now described as bearing the semblance of philosophy, and as being engaged with the same class of questions. 8. to ye Si' rjdovrjs — d8oXeo~)(i- kov] It is possible that the work of Socrates is here ironi- cally described as ' chremato- phthoric,' whereas that of the Sophist is ' chrematistic' Com- pare Polit. 299 c, where in the state which is jealous of the laws the ture statesman or philosopher is said to be called by his fellow-citizens dSoAeo-^y TIS (TO(pLO-TT]S. 9. wept Se ttjv Xei-tv — aKovope- vov] These words are inserted in order to indicate the deri- vation of dSoXeo-x^y, quasi d^Sr/s ttj Xe£ei. 18. Trakiv — r\t<.eiv\ Cf. Theset. 196 bl els tovs avTOvs dvi)Kei Xoyovs. Cf. Legg. 3, 683 a : TeTl'ipTTj TIS 7]Kei 7ToXlS KdTOlKl^O- pevrj. Cf. 7*4 c • nd-Xiv rjplv dpcfua^TjTovpevov eXr]Xv6ev. Hip- parch. 232 a : irdXtv Tplrov rj TeTciprov i)Kei Tjpiv opoXoyovpevov. The conjecture of Heindorf, Km t'i tis av, although supported 1 >y the analogy of p. 224 c, km t[ tis av aXXo ovopa elncov ovk av TrXrjppeXotr), to which av clearly 20M2TH2. 41 226. VVV TCTCtpTOV TOV fXiTabnOKOjJieVOU V(Jj r)/J.(t)l> - . SE. OvSeu aAA' ?; to xP 1 ll JiaTL(JTLK0V 7 e ^°fj <*>>> €OLK€V, epL(TTLKr)S OV T€)^V1]?, TTjS GlVTiAoyiKr]?, T>/S" d/j,(pL(r(3r]Tr)TiKr}?, tt}? fiaymTtia}?, rrj? dyoovtaTiKr)?, 5 7-179 KTTjTiKrj? ecTTLV, go? 6 Xoyo? au jie/ir]i>vK€ vvv, 6 , ToiovSe tl pieTaOeovTas i^yo? avTov. /cat refers, is not absolutely ne- cessary or certain. i. t6v om. Bodl. An. The omission is probably due to the 6[ioioTe\evTov rather than, as Stallbaum imagined, to conjecture : although the in- telligibleness of the phrase rv oik^tlkow ovoparcov KaXovfMP arra \>- Z2M Also of combing, carding, warping, and the like. 7T0V ; 0EAI. Kal woXXa' drap irola 67; rol>i> ttoXXcov Trvv6av€L ; : 5 HE. Td roiaSe, olov SiyOeiv re Xeyopcev kol diar- rav kol ftpdrreiv Kou •fdtaKpli/ewf . 9EAI. Tlfirjv; SE. Kal irpos ye rouroi? en. j-aiveiv, Kardyeiu, KepKiteiv, kcu pivpia ev reus reyyaLS dXXa rotavra o evovra eiuardp.e6a. rj yap ; 0EAI. To iroLOv avrcov irepi (3ovXr/0ei9 SrjXwcrai, 7rapa8elyp.ara wpoOels 1 ravra Kara iravrov rjpov ; £?E. /\iaiperiKa wov to. Xe^Oevra e'lprjrai ^vp.- iravra. 5 0EAI. Nat. S*E. Kara rov ep.ov to'lvvv Xoyov coy irep\ ravra in other words, we must try another and independent track. This " new scent," how- ever, is not wholly uncon- nected with those previously followed. For the notion of the Elenchus, which is the characteristic now to be set up, has been suggested by the mention of avTikoyiKrj. I . Tmv oikctikcov oz/o/xaYcw] Throughout these dialogues, by an exaggeration of the cy- nical irony of Socrates, not without a true feeling of the universality of science, the highest thoughts are illustrated by the lowest images. Tav olKeriKcov — wov ;] " There are some words in use amongst our menials to which we give currency, I presume ?" 5. Xeyofitv] Note the intro- duction of a fresh verb, re- suming KaXovptv. 6. Kal iSiaKpiveivi] Unless Bia- Kpiveiv (or SiaKifeiw(l), to "shake up," cf. Ar. Nub. 477) was used in some special technical sense, the word occurs strangely here, and awkwardly antici- pates what follows. " Itaque ni, quod parum probabile, ab aliena manu asserta hsec Kal SiaKpiveiv putentur, in verbo SiaKplveiv aliud videtur delitu- isse, quod felicior aliquando conjector reperiet." Heind. 16. cos — Texvrjv] Cf. Phileb. 18 C : fiiav eV avroly cos ovcrav ypappariKTjv rtx vr ) v «re<£#e'y|aTO irpocrenrcbv. re^vr/v is resumed by avTTjv for the sake of clear- ness, as in Theset. 155 d : dvbpCav — nvTcbv. alib. KXM2TH2. 43 p. 226. jaIolv ovaav eV airaai re^yr]v, evbs ovofiaTos afjiw- aofiev avrrjv. 0EAI. Tiva irpocrenrovTes ; HE. AiaKpLTiKrjv. 0EAI. "Eoro). HE. 2/C07T6t 5?) TOLVT1]? OLV &VO OLV 7TT) 8vP(OfJ.€$a KOLTibelv e'ldrj. 0EAI. Tayeiav toy efiol (TKe^Lu eir it arrets. d SE. Kal firjv ev ye reus elpypcevais SiaKplaecn rh fiev yeipov a.7ro fieXrlovos airoywpl^eiv rjv, to $' Ofioiov a0' opolov. 0EAI. ^ye&ov ovto) vvv \ey6ev (palverai. HE. T^s* p.€v Toivvv 6vop.a ovk e^co Xeyop.evov' All Hi.- are in ol dividing; but while in tliosi- last men- tioned like is divided from like, iii the for- mer the good is separated from the 4. AiaKpiTLKTjv] Cf. Polit. 282 b : peyaka Tive Kara iravra fjpiv tj(TTr}V re^va, 17 crvyKpiTiKr] re Kal 8ia e cw Tray av \8oi ; 0EAI. N«/, Kara crypXiqv ye 'law ov p.i]v eycoye \oKaOopco vvv. aE. Kai ixrjv Ta Trepl Ta acofiaTa iroXXa e?8r] KO-Odpaecav evl irepiXafielv bvop.aTi irpocrrjKei. 0EAI. Yiola KOI tlvl ; £JE. Ta Te tcov (cocav, ocra £vtos acopLaTcov viro ir,yvfxuao~TiKi]^ larpiKYji- Te opOoos 8taKpivo\xeva KaOal- p. 227. peTai Ka\ irepi tolktos, threw p.ev tyavXa, ocra (3aXa- 4. as eyw £vvvoa>\ " As I perceive ou taking a general survey :" i. e. by a process of ovvayayr). 'O yap (twotttlkos StaXeKTiKos. (Rep. 7, 537 C.) 5. Ka.6apiJ.6s rts] The thought which is here introduced, that philosophy is a purification of the soul, has an affinity with Pythagorean doctrine, and is in harmony with the Phsedo. The same idea is applied to the science of government in the Politicus, 293 d. Cf. also Legg. 5,735. tis marks the introduc- tion of a fresh notion. Cf. Polit. 299 c: els 8rj ti hiKav £d>a>v — icadal- perai] " I mean both cleans- ings of living bodies, including such right separations and pur- gations as are effected within." 15. tiaKpivopeva] Compare Phileb. 46 e : tS> to. o-vyKeKpi- piva /3('a 8ia\fiv r\ to. bianeKpipeva trvyxelv. Ar. Eth. Nic. VII. 1 4, § 6 : 01 8e p(\ay)(okiKoi Trp> (pvcriu del biovrat larpeias Kal to crcopa 8aKvopevov SiareXeZrat 81a tt/v Kpao-iv, where similar physio- logical notions are implied. 16. 7repi tclkt6s\ Sc. KaBaipo- ptva. The notion of e'i8rj is not distinctly repeated with So-a, which is the cognate sub- ject (in apposition to the ac- tion) of 8iaKpivopeva Kadalperai. I. e. ocra 8. k. = oo~ai 8iaicpio-eis re Kal Kadappo\ yiyvovrai. elnew pev fpavka] Sc. ei8os 8e. e\ovTa 6pa>s. 20v d\j/v)(a)V acofiarcou, rj /caret afiiKpa 7roAAa kcil yeXoia Sokovptu 6v6f.1a.Ta eaytv. 0EAI. MaXaye. 5 £?E. YlavTa-naai jiev ovv, co QeaiTr)T6. aAAct yap 2. yvacpevriKr] Kai £vpircura ko- . Ibid. 176 d: Seu/oV^rts toKovam. And compare Legg. 7, 799 d • 7i"oXXa Kai apiKpa SoKovvTa thai vopipa. 4. ea-x ev ] Cf. Rep. 6, 502 d : tTTfitrj ravra poyis riXos tcr)(fV. 6. Havranao-i ptv ovv] "There can be no doubt of their being thought absurd. But then, Theretetus, the spirit of method cares neither more nor less for sponging than for physicking, if it be so that the one does us small service and the other great in the way of purifying. For her endeavour is to know what is and is not kindred in the whole range of the sciences and arts ; wherefore she pays equal ob- servance to them all, and where she finds resemblance between things, she counts the one no whit more ridiculous than the other ; nor does she esteem him who gives generalship as an instance of "pursuit" at all more decorous but as a rule rather more affected than one who prefers the example of vermin-killing." For the verb o-noyyifa, see Dem. de Cor. 313. 12 ; Aristoph. Thesm. 247. This clause refers to the many minute branches of KoaprjTiKr] of which (T7ToyyiaTiKTj is one, rather than to the cktos €i /xeAoi>, el to fj.€i> (TfjiiKpd, rh 8e p.eyd\a tj/jlos cof/jeAet KaOrxipov. tov KTycraaOai yap eveKa vovv iraawv Ttyywv to b 5 ijvyyeves kou to fir) ^vyyeves KOLTavoelv Treipajfuevrj ti/ulu Trpos tovto i£ 'ictov 7rdcra?, /cat Oarepa twv irepcov kclto, tyjv bp.oioTr\Ta ovhlv rjyeiTOU yeXoioTepa, aepLVOTepov Se tl tov Sid aTpaTTjyiK^y ?) (f)6eipicrTiKr}s 8r)\ovvTa 6-qpevTLK.rjV ov8ei> vevopaKev, aAA' a>? to 1 . o-noyyurrLKris] " The art of cleansing with the sponge." dX\a ydp implies, " But the apparent absurdity of the names is nothing to us, for," &c. 2. ov8e Tl paWov] Cf. Rep. I, 339 b : ovira 8rj~kov ovS" el peydXyj. From a humorous determination to be strictly impartial, it is purposely left doubtful which is to be con- sidered the more useful art. Plato seems to have changed his opinion on the subject of pharmacy. Compare Rep. 3, 407 with Tim. 89 c, d. 4. tov KTrjcracrdai evexa vovv] Compare Polit. 272 c : irvvda- vopevoi napa ndo~r]s tcov \6ya>v ovTe aepvoTepov pakXov epe^rjo-ev r) p^j. It is a true reflection, though here ironically applied, that science ignores the fasti- diousness of the senses and the prejudices of a refined taste, and, as Lord Bacon says, " iEque palatia et cloacas in- greditur nee tamen polluitur." Nov. Organ. 1, 120. Compare also the defiance of ridicule in Rep. 5, 452. And see the re- marks of Mr. Grote on the pas- sage of the Parmenides above cited, Plato &c, vol. ii. p. 268. tl — ov8ev] Cf. Pha?d. 74 a: oiS' oXXo Tl TQ)V TOIOVTCOV Ol)8£v. 9. BrjpevTiKTjv] Plato seems to have been fond of the no- tion of a science of 6rjpevTi tvirpeTrecrTaTov eluai So^eC fiovov i)(€Tco ^W/Ois" tcov Trjs ^vyr)? KaOdpaewu 5 ■ndvTO. £vv§r}(rav ocra aAAo tl Kadalpei rov yap 7rep\ tt]v hidvotav KtxOappov diro tcou dXKcov tiriKt- )(etpr)K€i> d(f)opicra(70ai ra vvv, ei ye oirep /3oi>Aerou pavOdvopev. GEAI. 'AAAa pepdOrjKa, kcu avyywpw Svo p.ev 10 eldr] KtxOdpcrem, ev Se to irep\ T-qv ^v)q~\v eldos elvau, tov irep\ to acopa x^pts ou. HE. YIdi>TGL>i> KaWiaTa. koii pot to peTtx Polit. 299 d, Rep. 2, 373 b, Legg. 7, 823 ; see also Epin. 975 c. 1. onep rjpov] Supr. 226 e: 7roia kcu tivi. "And so now, with respect to the question you have asked, What name is to be given to all faculties whose province is to cleanse animate or inanimate bodies, she will not care, what expres- sion will sound most seemly." t'i ivpoo-ep. is explanatory of onep, whose antecedent is in the ac- cusative of respect after cWo-«. ovBiv is adverbial, and the subj. of Siotaei is the clause TTOIOV Tl t)6£;€l. 3. felXrjCpaaif ] So all the MSS. except a corrector of Par. B.,who gives el\r)x a0 ~ L (thus, d\rj- cpacn). Although it is difficult to bring forward another in- stance of Xapl3dv(o used exactly in this sense, or followed by an infinitive, it is not quite certain that elXrjcpao-i here is wrong. Cf. Legg. 1, 624 a: t'i\7](pe ttjv alriav. lb. 6, 768 d : ttjv Tr\ei(TTr]P vopndeaiav elXrjcpaai. Hdt. IIL71. See also Phileb. 37 b, and the Zurich Editors' preface to the Philebus, p. xiv. There is, however, a much greater internal probability in favour of elXi^xao-i. Cf. Thea?t. I49 b : ttjv ~Xo%eiav e'lXrj^f. Tim. 5 2 a: tovto b 8tj vorjcris c'lXlJXfV eTTlCTKOTTflv. lb. 38 d: Tt]V ivavTiav elk-qxbs avr av TO \t\QfV Si)(rj p. T€fXV€lV. BE A I. KaO* oiroV av v(j)i]yr}, 7reipa.o-op.ai croi avvTepiveiv- 5 HE. Ylovtjplav krepov uperi]9 ev "^v)(rj Xeyo/iev ti ; 0EAI. ricos" yap ov ; SE. Kai fJLrjv KaOap/xo? rjv to XnreTv fiev #«Ye- pov, €K(3dAA€ii> 8e ocrov av r) irov ti (pXavpov. io 0EAI. 'Hv yap ovv. e iHE. Kai yj/vxr}? apa Kaff oo~ov av evplcrKcofjiev KaKias d(palp€o-iv Tiva, Kadapfxov avTOv XeyovTeg ip pLeAci ,/ ,, body: (3EA1. (Ju/c e\xadov. I. enaKove TTtipaipevos] Bad- ham elegantly conjectures eira- KoXouOei : and, less happily, Treipaptvco. Cf. Polit. 26 1 a : dW £naKo\ov6a>v avvrepve. See however Legg. 900 d : «ai o-$o- 8pa -ye eVijKoue. it). 905 d. 5. aper^s] Bodl. (ip rrjs. 8. X«reu/] So all the MSS. " To leave once for all what is not evil, but continually to throw out Avhatever evil is found anywhere." So the dif- ference of tense may be ex- pressed. The action of Xcrrdv is viewed as final, that of eK/3dX- Xeiv as continuous. Heind. conj. Xeineiv. 9. nov] " anywhei'e." I. e. (in the present instance) " in any region of the soul." II. ^v^y] Gen. after KaKi'ay d(paipeaiv and ica.9app.6v. Cf. supr. 224 a and note. I 2. avrbv refers to d(paip€(Tiv, but agrees in gender by at- traction with Kadappov. iv p,e\,i\ Cf. Phileb. 28 b : iva pr] — napa /xe'Xor (pdey^ai- ne6d ti. " In tune," i. e. con- sistently. 15. Auo jtev e'lSt] Kaicias] The implied apodosis, which is postponed by the explanation which follows, is 8vo 8e KaBappwv. 18. iyytyvoptvov] Sc. iv tyvxfj. 20M2TH2. 49 228. HE. Nocrov tcrays koll aracnv ov tolvtov vevo- fllKOLS. 0EAI. Ovdi av npos tovto eyco tl \pi'j p.e diro- KpivaaOai. HE. YloTepov aXXo tl ardaii/ yyovptevo? y ttjv 5 tov (frvaei Ijvyyevov? e/c tlvos 8ia(popa? 8iaopdt 8ia(p8apdv] This is the MS. reading: that of Cornarius, taken from a quotation of this passage by Galen, 8icxp8opds diacpopav, being supported only by a correction in Par. F. The object is to shew that sedition is a disease ; and it is more natural to speak of disease as a dissolution or decay of kindred elements in consequence of some dissen- sion amongst them, than as a dissension arising from some decay. 11. §o£u? emdvpiais k.t.X.] Cf. Rep. 4, 439, 440. 12. Xoyov Xv7raiy] Cf. Rep. 3, 387, 338. 1 3. Twvs €)(6vTav] These words are an afterthought, and are placed in immediate con- struction with Tavra (viz. So|. «V. 8vp. i]8. Xoy. Xv7T.). TTovTjpia appeared above as a general word, but is here used with a special meaning, as distin- guished from dpaOla. 50 nAATONOS [gnorance is n kind of deformity, and may be c l- pared t" tlie bodily state, i?i which the movements of different members are inhar- monious and fail of accom- plishing their end. irov Tiva de'fjLeva, 7reipa>/j.ei>a tovtuu Tvy^aveiv, KaO' p. €KacrTiiu 6pfM]i> 7rupafj)opa avTov ylyverai koll diro- rvyyavet, irorepov avra (j)rjaop.ei-> viro avppLerpla^ tyjs 7T/309 akXtjXa rj rovvavTiov viro d/jLerpla? avid 5 irdayetVj 0EAI. ArjAov coy viro d\xeipla aKOvaav irdaav irdv dyvoovaav. 6EAI. l(/)6Spa ye. io HE. To ye f±r}v ayvoelv eariv eV dkr)6eiav opfxco- p.evr)s \j/v)(r)?, 7rapa(p6pov ^vveaeoos yiyvop-evi-js, ovSev d aXXo irXr/v irapa(f>pocrvvr). 0EAI. Wdvv p.ev ovv. 228. i. 7mpa)/iei>a] The omission of this word in the Bodleian MS. is probably due to the 6po 107 eXeVTOV of 6£\i.tva.. 2. napdcpopa avrov] Sc. rov o-Konov, " swerving from the mark." In Tim. 87 e (where the word napacpopoTTjs is used) the same connexion is noticed be- tween irregularity of action and disproportion of parts. 4. avra wdcrxeiv] " Are thus affected." For the neut. plur., cf. Theset. 207 e, and note. Compare Ar. Eth. Nic. I. 13 : arenas yap Kaddnep ra rrapa'Xe- Xvpiva rov crcoparos peprf els to. he^ia npoaipovpevov Kivrjcrai rov- vavriov els ra apto~repa 7rapa(fie- perai, K.a\ en\ rrjs tjsvxrjs ovrcos' eiri ravavria yap al oppa\ rcov aKparcoW dXX' ev rols a-copaat pev opaipev to irapacpepopevov, enl 8e ttjs yj/vxrjs oi>x opcopev. But what Aristotle thus describes approaches more nearly to what Plato hei*e calls o-rdo-is rrji ^vxrjS. 7 . \jfvxr)v ye — dyvoovaav ] This is emphatically the na- ture of " soul" or " mind" — according to the well-known Socratic or Platonic principle, which remains unaltered in the Laws. See Legg. 9, 860 d : as oi KaKol txavres els ndvra elalv anovres kokoi. II. TTapacpopov £weVecor] An etymological analysis, in the Cratylus vein, of 7rapacppo- o-vvt]. Cf. Legg. 6, 775 d: Trapd(popos — 6 pedvwv. Trapas is governed by wapa^opov, which agrees with if/vx^s. For this interpretation Ave are in- debted to the acumen of Hein- dorf. 20I2TH2. 51 p. 228. aE. ^Vv^rjv apa avor^rov ala^pav kou ajJLirpov Oereov. GEAI. "Eolk€v. HE. "Ran 8)) 8uo ravra, a>9 tyaiveTcu., KdKOiv iv olvtyj yei/7], to /J.6V irovr)pia KaKovfievov vtto twv 5 7toAAgw, voaos avrrjs aafpearara ov. GEAI. Nat. S?E. To oY ye ayvoiav fxev kccAovcti, KaKiav 8e (xvto eV v/'fX^ f^ovov yiyvopcevov ovk tOekovaiv 6/jlo- Xoyeiv. IO e 0EAI. Y^ofxibf} avy^coprjreou, o i'W 5?) Xe'tjavTos y/J-fayvor/crd aov, to 8vo eivca yivr) /cowa'ay eV ^v\f}, kou 8ei\iav fiev kcu aKoXaaiav kou olSlklolv ^vfiiravTa r}yi]T€ov voaov Iv tj/mv, to 8e r^y TroXXr]^ kou ttolvto- 8aTrrj9 ayvoias iraQos oucryps Qztzov. 15 HE. Ovkovv Iv acofxaTi ye 7rep\ 8vo iraOr^fiaTe tovtco 8vo Ttyya Tive eyeveadrjv ; GEAI. Tive tovtco ; '< 2 9- HE. rieyot /xeV alayos yvpivaaTLKrj, vrepl 8e voaov As gyi larpiKq. 20 counter- acts defor- mity, and 1— *t-i /~\ > — \ \ \ r//-> \ ) o> / v medicine A Hi. UVKOVV KOU 7T€pi fX€V vppLV KOU CtOLKiaV KOU disease so 0EAI. v noXKcbv yveadm. For the omission of supra. (ivai, cf. infr. 246 e: touto 8e 9. eV tyvxfi y-ovov yiyvop.(vov\ ov aaifia i'n^/v^ov 6y.o\oyovo~iv. I. e. When mental is not com- 13. ^vfiTravra] Stallb. adds bined with bodily deformity: ravra from C. F. b, c, unnecessa- for the converse of which see rily. For nddos, infr., cf. Theajt. Rep. 3, 402 e: or iv \|/i%v 193d: to ttjs dogrjs Trdflos. fxovov, "only in the soul," as 16. nepl 8vo TradrjimTc] Cf. if that was a matter of less Phsedr. 261 c: nepl ndvra rd consequence. Stallb. 's inter- Xeyopeva pia tis rkyvr]. pretation, " earn esse eximie 22. Ovkovv kcu] "And in like (jxSvov) in animo pravitatem," manner.'' H 2 nAATQNOS there is chastise- niriit for the cure of vice, and instruction to remedy tlie more latent evil. SeiAiuv y KoAacrriKi] 7T€(f>VK€ rtyvtov paAiara Or) p. 229. 7ruau)V irpocn'/Kovaa '[ StKij-f ; 0EAI. To yovv eiKO?, a>s tLiriiv Kara rr)v avOpu>- irivr)v 8oijai>. 5 SE. T/ 6V; 7Tepl £yp.iraao.v ayvoiav fxcou aWrjv TLva ?) bibacTKaXiKyv opOorepov ehroi tis olv ; 0EAI. Ovdefilav. SE. <£>epe 8iy 8L8aai rj ttAcwb, Svo 8e rive avrrjs eivat b 10 /xeyicTTco, aKOirec. 0EAI. 2K07TCO. HE. Ka/ /uot SoKovpLtu rfjde av irr) rd^iara evpeiv. I. 19 KoKnariKT] — tSuo/t] The position of 81kt] in the sentence may be paralleled from many similar inversions in this and other dialogues. Many of Plato's rhythmical sentences end purposely with a dissyl- able, which is often sepa- rated from the natural con- nexion. And 8Ur) is similarly enumerated amongst other arts, including medicine, in Gorg. 478 b, C : XprjpaTiaTiKrj p.ev iTivias cmaKKarTei, larpiKJ) 8e voo~ov, 8ikt] 8e aKokaaias Kat d8iKias. ri ovv tovtcov Kcik- Xhttov e ' a * TpiKrjs, 8lkt)S ; ttoKv 8ia(pepei, a> 2a)KpaTe<>, rj 8iai. 204>I2TH2. 229. 9EAI. Tlf,; 3*E. Tyu ayvoiav Xhovjts ti ttyj Kara fxeaou avrr)? rofxrjv c')(ei riva. 8t7r\rj yap ai/Ti] ytyvop^vr) hifhov otl Kal t-i]v StSao-KaAiKyv 8vo avayKa<^u popia tytiv, cv e(f) iiA yevet twv avrrjs e/carepw. But ignor- ance, and therefore instruction also, is two- fold: the more uu- manage- 3. roprju e'xti riva] Cf. Legg. 12, 944 b: cr^efioi/ ovv ev rols oveibeaiv e\ei riva ropfjv t) rovrav twv 6vopdra>v eVi^opd. pfycurms pev yap ovk iv iraatv ovopd^oir av diKaicot, dnofiohevs 8e ott\(ov. 8ut\t} yap avTt) yiyvopevr) ] Cf. Gorg. 464 b : Avolv ovtolv toIv irpaypcLTotv 8vo \tya> re)(vas K.r.X. The meaning of pp. 226- 231 may be thus stated : The Sophist professes to be an edu- cator ; and the highest form of education is that which leads men to know them- selves, and liberates them from the conceit of knowledge : in other words, the elenchus, or cross-questioning method. This Separation 1 is distinguished from the an- tiquated mode of correction by direct reproof, and also from the positive instruction which is given to those who are consciously ignorant of any subject. There is grave doubt whether the Sophist deserves to be called an educator in this highest sense : but the honour is yielded to him for the pre- sent, with the feeling that he will not retain it long. The serious thought, that educa- tion is the purification of the mind through the separation of the false from the true, is approached ironically through the trivial example of house- hold processes, and also through the following distinctions : Of like from like Of srood from evil = Purification Corporeal Mental (and mental evils are) , /cTTacrts\ novnpia I , I \ voaos I \aptTpiai (iiKha pepr) dpa6ias") TO /JLTJ KaTdOOTa ,ti doKe'iv eldevai. Hence instruction is 8i]ptovpyiKa\ 8i8ao-Ka\laL 7ratSet'a vovdcnjriKrj eXey^c 54 I1AATI2N02 ablekind 0EAI. TV ovv ; Karacjjave^ nj] aoi to vvv (i]Tov- p. --•>• being stu- pidity, or fievov ; tliiit ignor- i— (T-i »a /?>»•? ' ' ^ ~ v \ ancewhich All.. Ayycuay o oiw /xeyce tl julol ooko) koll y^aXe- c tlie mind \ , , / * ~ 5<\ ~ v x > ~ mistakes 7TOV a(pCOpi(Tp.€VOV OpUV 6LOOS, TTOLCTL TOLS ClXXoL? CLVTt]? for know- > / /i / ledge. 5 aVTLOTaUfXOV fiepeCTlV. 0EIA. IIokw &J; HE. To /u?) KareiSoTa tl 8oKc-iv eldevai' oY ou KLvdvvevti TrdvTa oaa diavola a7/.u- 3. 'Ayvoias §' ow] Badham : norance, Phil. 48 cl, e ; Legg. 9, " 'Ayvolas y ovv legendum : est 86od; 863 c; 10,886 b; Symp. enim responsio aliqua ex parte I.e.; Phsedr. 275 b. Ale. 118 a: assentientis." So also the old avTr) ap f) ayvoia tcov kokcov ah [a editions. The words as they teal f] enoveidto-Tos dpadia. stand certainly take no account SV ov navra — iracriv] Because of the question, but continue men never act without think - the previous speech. ing they know. 5. dvTicrTadfxov] " Which may 8. ndvra oaa acpaXKopeda = be weighed against all the Trdvra ra yiyvopeva fjplv acpdX- other parts of ignorance put para. Cf. supr. 226 e: oaa — together." The word belongs Kadalperai, and note. to tragedy. Cf. Soph. El. 561 : 11. pova] Badham conjectures cos — avTiaradpov tov Brjpos eV poplco, but pova has more point. Bvo-eie ttjv avTov Koprjv. For " This alone earns the title of xaXenov = difficult to handle, stupidity." Cf. Symp. 222 a: cf. Symp. 204 a : avro yap vovv e^ovras — povovs tcov Xoycov. tovto \a\en6v itrnv rj dpadia. I 4. Ti — XeKTeov] Sc. ovopa. 7. To pfj KareiSora tl SoKeiv 16. to pev dXXo — 8i8aaKaXias] elftevai ] See, amongst other " The part which is separated places where the ignorant from this includes instruction conceit of knowledge is dis- in various handicrafts." A simi- tinguished from conscious ig- lar division is made in Phileb. 20I2TH2. 55 p. 229. ovpytna? 8i8aaKaAla9, tovto 8e tvOdde ye iraifciav 81 y/jLCOU K€K\rj;re, Iv TraaivKX- Arjiriv. aAAa ya^o iip.lv en kou tovto aKeirTeov, el aTopLOv rjbrj eort 7ray, rj two. tyov 8iaipecriv a£iav 5 hritivvixias. 0EAI. Oukow ^77 CTKOTreiv. HE. Ao/Cet TOiVVV p.01 KOU TOVTO 6TL 7TY) a")(i^€a'$(U. 0EAI. Karar/; HE. T779 eV rot? Aoyoiy 8i8ao-Ka\u ; HE. To pjev apxaioirpeires tl iraTpiov, a> npos 1 The ari which removes tliis has the peculiarly ( in* k name of IlatSfia — Education. 55 C : ovkovv rjfxiv to pev — * 8tj- piovpyiKov to~Ti ttJS nep\ to. padi]- pctTa eTno~Ti]nrjs, to 8e nepl nai- 8eiav m\ Tpo8 earai, e7rei vvv i'ariv opov nav, €i> £vve)(es. I. e. whether we have reached the liTprjTov ei'Soj. 8. KCli TOVTO €TL 771] (T\l^((T0ai] " This, like the rest, admits of being divided somewhere." The words kcu tovto '4tl are in exact keeping with fj8rj wdv supr. Cf. supr. 222c. Hermann's conjecture, koto, tovto, is un- necessaiy and awkward, be- cause anticipating the ques- tion, and because tovto has no antecedent. IO. Tijs — StSacr/caXtK^y] Traideia is assumed to be equivalent to rj ei> toIs \6yois 8t8a \ o>\ \ n ' n ' v the old- irouvovTes, ra oe pLaXdaKoiTepm 7ra.pafivUovpi.evoL' to fashioned £> 9 y ' » v > a ' ■>' * n admonitory ° ovu CVpCTTav aVTO OpOOTaTa €L7TOL TL9 av VOVOtTr)- system ' of moral $TIKI)V. 5R?' 9EAI. "Ee™ otrm. rectly included in the general name of admonition." " True." " Now for the other method. It would seem that some had reflected with themselves that stupidity is always involun- tary, and that no one who thinks himself wise will ever care to be a learner of those matters in which he fancies himself to be accomplished : moreover, that education in the form of admonition spends a world of labour with but small result." " And they were right." " Therefore they address themselves differently to the task of exorcising this con- ceit." The two modes of correc- tion may be compared with the two kinds of legislation (with and without explanation and persuasion) mentioned in the Laws, of which the former is there preferred : see esp. Legg. 4, 720 sqq. So far was Plato from reversing his judg- ment, as Mr. Grote (vol. iii. p. 355, note on p. 354) supposes, respecting the vovderr/Tiicov el8os rrjs iraiSeias, which Protagoras advocates, Prot. 3 2 5 d : nai eav fxev 4ko>v TreldrjTai, — el 8e p,rj, wo-nep £u\ov 8ieo-Tpapp.evov Kal xapTTTopevov evdvvovariv aTreiXais Ka\ TrXrjynls. (14.) ap^aion penes tl ndrptou] A tragic expression; cf. Aesch. Prom. 409 : peyako ttclvtcov dv8peLOTa.Te, Ta.% av, e'l ttov (ppovipov etrri tl £a>ov eTepov, oiov 8oKe7 to tcov ye- pdvcov, rj tl tolovtov ciWo, Kara TavTa iacos 8iovop.d£oi. If cos is retained, which is perhaps better on the whole, as e'L^ao-l Tives riyrjaao-daL k.t. A. IS equi- valent to rjyTjo-apevoi Tives, cos ei£ao~i — o~TeX\ovTCii. Xoyov eavTols 86vres] " On re- flection." Cf. Hdt. I.34: 'o 8' 5()I2TH2. p. 230. 86i>T€? I'lyrjaacrOoLL irairav ukovitlov up.a0lai> etVat, kcil fiaOeiv ouSeis ttot av iOeXeiu tov olofievov tlvai O~0(J)0V TOVTCOV Q)V OLOLTO TTtpl SetVO? elvai, /X€TCX 8t noXXov ttovou to vov0€ty)tikov ettW rrj? nut^eta? tr/jLiKpou avvreiv. \ 0EAI. 'QpOcos: ye vopl^ovTe?. HE. TS tol tolvti]? rr/s Soljrjs eiri ei<(3oXr)v aXXco b TpOTTCd (TTeXXouTat. 0EAI. T/w S77 ; SE. AiepcoTaHTiv <£>v av otrjTal rU tl irept XeyeLV Xeycov prjSev' dff are 7rXav(o/JLevcov tols Soija? paStco? €$J€Ta{pvo-i, kcu crvvdyovTes 8rj rois Xoyois els Tavrov TiOeaat Trap aAA^Aay, tl0€vt€? Se iTribeLKvvovaiv auras avTols afia wepl tcov avTcov npbs tol aura tlms de- scribed. that do man h i >hea pid, and that the source of error lies in the con- ceit of wivl'Mn : too, thai the old me- thod was lal.nr'i.H!,, and had small result, there are some who address themselves differently to the task (Trei8fj i^ytpBrj Kcii \6yov eavrco c8ookc, KaToppoo8r)(ras tov oveipov ayerat ra ttcu8\ yvvaiKa. Soph. OEd. Eex. 583 : Ovk, el 8i8oirjs y , cos cyoo, (ravrco \6yov. 2. oi8ev ttot av idckeiv] So Bodl. Alii., Stallbaum. Edd. Vet. oiSeVore. It desei'ves mention that Heindorf had at one time been led to con- jecture oiBev, because of tov- tcov following, but had after- wards contented himself with making tovtcov depend on nipt, 3. aov irepi avrovs fieyaXcov KOI aKkrjpcdv doijcov airaXXarTOVTai iracrwv re dwaXXa- c 5 ycou (xkov€lu [re] rjdlaTTju Kai rw iravyovri fiefiaioTara yLyvojievrju. vofii^ovTes yap, co iral c/u'Ae, oi Kadal- 1. 6pS>vTes~\ Sc. to (TriSeiKvvo- fxevov. eavrols /.lev xaXeTraivovai] Cf. Theffit. 168 a : eavrovs aiTid- (TOVTai K.T.X. 2. TTpos 8e tovs aXXovs rjp.] Cf, Thetet. 2IO: tjttov eaei ftapvs roiy (Tvvovo-i Kai fjpepaiTfpos, o~a>- (ppovcos ovk olopevos el8evai 6 prj olada. 3. tcdv irepl avrovs] " Which encompass them." The same expression might be used of a disease, or of unwholesome hu- mours. Perhaps avrovs should be read. The Bodl. (ut ssepe) has no breathing. 4. o-K\r]pS)v] " Stiff," " un- bending," " unyielding." Cf. Crat. 487 d : to (TKXrjpov re Kai dp€Tao-Tpo(j)ov, o 8r) appaTOV Ka- Xelrai. Charm. 175 d: ovrcas fjpcov fvrjdiKwv Tvxovaa rj £rjT7]0~is xai ov o-Kkrjpcbv. Theset. 155 e : o~K\r)povs ye Xeyeis Kai uvtitvttovs dudpcJonovs. 7rao~£)v re anaXXaycov ukovsiv [Te]r)o'lo-Tr)v] TheVat.alone rejects the second re. If this is fol- lowed, the displacement of re may be defended from Eep. 9, 572 a, Phsedr. 269 c. For the cogn. accus., cf. Eep. 6, 496 e. 5. /3e/3aioYara yiyvopevqv] Cf. Legg. 2, 663 e : KaXbv f) dXr)- 6(ia Kai p.6vtpov. 6. vop,l£ovT(s yap] The con- struction of this sentence is broken off by the introduction and application of the simile, as in Phileb. 58 c : 7/ 8' etnov — etircopev. Kep. 3, 402 b, C Theset. 197 c, alib. The idea of voplfrvTes is then resumed in the finite verb 8ievorj6r]o-av, and the apodosis is postponed, or rather is absorbed into the sub- ordinate clause rrplvav tis — nXeia 8e pi). By a kind of attraction the latter part of the sentence follows the analogy of the &o-nep clause. For clkovuv jjSiW^v, cf. Apol. 23 c: oi veoi — avToparoi Xa'ipovcnv aKovovres e^eTa^opevwv tcov avdpioTvav. The regularity of the sentence might be re- stored thus : TavTbv 8iavorj0evTes eKeivoi, — Karao~Tr]0~avTes, e^eXov- Tes, Kadapov dne(pr)vav k.t.X. " For such, dear youth, are the thoughts of their purifiers. Just as the physicians of the body think (vevopLiKaa-i, frequentative perfect) that a body cannot profit by the food received, until the obstructing matters are cast forth, in like manner these reason about the mind, that it will never obtain benefit from the learning which it receives, until, by cross-examination, the person cross-examined be put to shame ; and a riddance being made of the notions which obstruct learning, the man is purged, and thinks he knows no more than what he really knows." 20*I2TH2. 59 p. 230. povTes avTou?, cocrirep 01 irep\ ru aco/xara larpul VtVOpLLKOUTL fit) 7TpOT€pOV OLV TY}9 7TpOCT(f)€pop€U7]? Tpo- (prj? airoXaveiv SuvaaOat crcopa, irpiv av tcl ep.7ro8l- tbvTa ev avrco ris €/c/3aA?7, tovtov /cat 7rept ~^/v\i]9 $L€voi]6r)crai> e/cetVot, per) npoTepov avTiqv t^iv tcov d irpoaCiSepopevcov paQipxcvrcov ovrjatv, irp\v av eXeyyow Tis tov eXey^optevov el? a\(jyyvr\v Karaarrjaa?, ras" toI]i/r) /cat ravTa rjyovpLevov, airep oldev, eidevai ptova, 7rAe/a) 8e pr\. GEAI. BeAr/an? yovv kcu aco^povearaTq tcov e'tjecov avrrj. 3?E. Aid Tama Srj Tvavra rjpuv, co QeaLTme, /cat rov eheyxpv XeKTeov ebs apa peylaTrj kcu KvpLcoTa.Tr) tcov KaOapaecov ecrTL, kcu tov dveXeyKTOv av vopi- (TTeov, av /cat Tvyyavr) fiaaiXev? 6 p.kyas cov, to. e peyicrTa aKaOapTOV bvTa, airaibevTov re /cat alcr^pov yeyovevac Tama, a KaOapcoTaTov /cat kccXXicttov 67rpe7re tov ovtco? iaopevov ev8aip.ova elvat. 6. 7rpoa(pepojjL(vcov'\ The verb irpoartpipeiv is more often applied to physic than to diet (Thucyd. II. 51, Plato Charm. 157 c, Phsedr. 270 b), but is conve- nient here as equally applicable to food and instruction. Cf. Legg. 7, 809 e : trorepov fls dxpi- /3eiai' rov padi'iparos Ireov — 77 to wapdnav cwSe irpoo-oicrTeov. 13 — 15. Kal Kal] " Not only — but." 15. tov dveXeynTOv] Cf. Apol. 38 a: 6 dvegeracrTOS fiios ov /3tco- tos dvdpanrco. 1 6. av Kal (3ao-t\ei>s 6 peyas i]] Compare Theset. 175 c: v & a - o-i\evs evbaipav. Lys. 2 09 e : JJpos Ai'or, tjv 6° eya>, t'i cipa 6 p.iyas j3acn\evs; k.t.X. Euthyd. 274 a: MaKap('£o) ap vpds eycoye TOV KTTjpaTOS 7ro\l> pdXXov 77 /Xf- yav j3ao~i\ea ttjs ap^r;?. And for ra peyio-Ta, in which there is perhaps a slight allusion to the greater mysteries, cf. Rep. 6,504 a : TTola S>) Xeyeis pa6r]paTa peyictTa k.t.X. Polit. 301 a. 17. dnalbevTov re Kal alo~xpov] Since it was proved that dpa- 6ia, of which education is the remedy, is a kind of alaxos. Supr. 228 d. 1 9. eirpene} Sc. yeyovevai. per ceii ing « bieh, the angry with tin in and I' -- disposed to be con- tentious towards othi 1 , In this way tliey are most surely re- lieved by an opera- tion, which it is de- lightful to witness, of the stubborn tumors of self-con- ceit. For - mental, like bodily food, can do no good to the sick man, until the noxious obstruc- tions of vanity are ()•() IIAAT12N02 removed, and ;i w lii>U'snnie state of in- i llcctual humility has been restored. Thus refu- tation is the great- est of all purgations: and even the Great King, if he has not undergone this test, is uneducated and there- fore un- happy. 0EAI. l\avTa.Trao-L ptv ovv. p. 230 HE. T/ 84 ; tovs; TavTr) yjpcojiivovs rrj re^vrj rivets (f)/]ao/jL€i> ; iyco fxev yap (j)o(3ovpai cro(piai. 5 0EAI. T/AJ; HE. M?) fxutpv avrots TrpocraTTTwiiev ytpas. 0EAI. 'AAAa firju irpocreoLKe tolovtco tlvl tol vvv elprjfieva. HE. Kal yap Kvvl Xvko?, aypK^rarov rj/jLepcoraTU). orov 8e aa(J)a\rj Set ttclvtcdv pLaXiara irepl ras 6/jloio- Ti]Tas del TTOLeiaOat tttjv (j)vXaKiqv' 6\i(T0r)poTaTOi> 6. avrols] Sc. rois (rocpi- (TTClTs. 7. roiovra tiv\ to. vvv elprjpevaj " The modes of action which have been described (e. g. the art of controversy) bear some resemblance to this purifying method of education." 9. Kal yap kvv\ \vkos] Mr. Grote remarks on this, that Plato would have objected to the wolf being placed in the same genus with the dog. He would certainly have objected to class them together as 'tame' or ' wild.' But he here recog- nizes the likeness between them, on which, had it suited his purpose, he might have dwelt to the exclusion of the difference. This illustrates the unfixed and provisional nature of Plato's classification, but nothing more. Cf. Rep. 5, 454 b, where it is shewn that differences are no less treacher- ous than resemblances, except to those who are able ko.t ei'S?7 (Tvvdyeiv kcl\ Siaipelcrdai. io, t6v 8e dv rjroi if; opoloov av- tov fj e£ dvopoicov avvl(TTaa-6ai' Kai ei [lev e'£ Spolav, wepi avrd 8elv paXKov r) ols opold earcv dva- arpecpeadai, et 8e e£ dvopoioov, nap- ekneiv tt/v napddea-iv. Cf. Phsedr. 262 b, c, 273 d. Ar. Eth. Nic. VI. 3, 2 : et Set aKpifioXoyel- uQai Kal prj dicoXovdelv reus opoi- oTrjcnv. But Euclides dwelt merely on the logical weak- ness of comparisons: Plato here speaks practically of the danger which attends their use. Compare the consciousness of modern times on the same point, Avhich some one has ex- pressed by saying that Analogy is like a broken reed, good to point with but not to lean upon. 2C)€VTi p.r)8ev aXK rjpuv elvai Xeyea0a> TrXrjv rj ye'wi yevvaia ao(j)L- 1 OTlKq. 0EAI. AeyeaOco puiv' airopco 8e eycoye rj8r) 81a. e to 7roXXa 7T€(f)ai'dai i tl ^prj iroTe cos dXrjOrj Xeyovra Ka) 8uo-yypi(ppevov ear eat ovt&s elvai tov ao. HE. Elkotgos ye crv diropwv. dXXd tol KaKtivov rjyeicrOaL XPV vvv rj8rj a(j)68pa diropelv oirrj ttotc en But by shall the 111:1 rter "i" called ' The fun.- t ions as- signed bo the Sophial bear some relation to this. And yet he seems scarce worthy of so high a ' dignity. Analogies aresHppery ground. The savage wolf wears some re- semhlance to the gen- . tie dog. ' Let us, however, grant him I. Eoraow] Sc. aocpurrai ol Taxirrj -^pwfievot. rfj re^vrj. Cf. ovtoi fxev yap, el Men. 92 d Toi Trados ak\o TrapaCpaivecrdat, ptoi SoKet. Nvv is to be taken, i/7rfp/3aro)r, with the participle. IO. rj yevei yevvaia cro<£.] Cf. Soph. (Ed. Kex. 1469 : iff & yovfi yewah. Compare the tragic grandiloquence of Pep. 5, 454 a : f] yevvaia tj 8uvap.is /c.r.X. It is not meant to distinguish the So- phist " of a noble stamp" from the " degenerate variety." 13. its a\r]6fj Xeyovra] "What definition of the Sophist one may assert with entire confidence." 16. dnopelv] There is an allu- sion to the literal meaning = avev nopov, " having no passage for escape." 6 ( 2 nAATQNOS tliis pro- visionally, l'..ivsi'1'iny that he will have to fight hard here- after for his claim. We are em- barrassed with the number of our defini- tions ; the only com- fort is that the So- phist's merit must be still greater. We have surrounded him : let us now close in upon him. We have had glimpses of him as a 8iadvcr€Tai tov XoyoV opOij yap r/ irapoipla, to tois p. 231 airaaas p.i] padiov elvai hiafyevyeiv . vvv ovv koll pLaXiara ewiOeTeov avTcp. SEAL KaXcos Xeyeis. 5 AE. YlpcoTOv 67; (TTavrts oiov e^avairvevacopev, /cat irpos i)pas avrovs StaXoyicrcDpLeOa apa avairavo- pLevoi, — (f)€pe, oirocra ypuv 6 ao(piaT7]9 7reXV s F% flra ] A pleonastic expression, sug- gested by the analogy of r) tov aapaTos rpocprj. Vid. SUpr. 224 a. 17. rjp.lv] Heindorf added rjv 2CXM2TH2. 63 o. %$i. SE. 'Op0a>? e/JLvrj/jLovevaa?. Tre/mrou <5' eyo) 7T(l- o pa.o~op.aL pvrjpoveveiv rrj? yap ayoL>VL(JTiKi)S 7rep\ Aoyous tjv tis adXi-jTrj^, tijv epi]i> rlyvrjv dcjjcopt- apevos. 0EAI. H^ yap ovv. 5 HE. To ye fjLTjV Iktov apL^La^rrjaipov p.ev, o/xeo? 8* edeptev avrco avyxwp/jo-avTe? 8o^cov €/x7ro<5tW p.a- Orjfxacn TrepL y^rv\i]v KaOapTr/v avrov elvat. GEAI. WavTairaai p.ev o\)V. 2 3 2 " SE. 'Ap ovv evvoeis, orav hno'Trjp.wv tis ttoWcdv™ (f)aii>r/Tai, puas 8e T€)(yr)$ bvo\xari irpocrayopevrjTai, to I I -in. in. :i merchant - a :-ll"|' keeper, a manufac- turer, :i mental athl( fce, from conjecture. But rjy.lv may depend on the verbal meaning of avTOTva>\r)s nepl to. fiadijfiara. " One who sells us learned wares of his own manufac- ture." 2. rrjs dycoviOTLKris Trepl \6yovs dflXq-Tjy] rrjs dy. is partitive; and 7repi \6yovs is to be joined with ddXrjTTjs. " Under the head of contention he appeared as a champion in argument." 3. dr) OVTOV LLTjVVOV. 0EAI. To ttoIov ; HE. 'AvriXoyiKOV olvtov efyaiiev eivai ttov. 0EAI. No/. 15 HE. TV 6" ; ov kol tcov aXXcov avTOv tovtov bi^daKaXov ylyvecrOai ; 0EAI. Tlfirjv; HE. ^K07ra>pL€P Sr) 7rep\ t'lvo, ti Ka\ paBrj- aopeBa. 19. e£ dpxr/i — TfloV JT17] " In examining this let us take a comprehensive survey, and begin as follows." For ?'£ dp- xys, cf. Theset. 180 d. 2CXM2TH2. 65 p. 232. dpxv? to-TQ) rfjde -rrrj. (pe'pe, irepl rwv deicov, ev ye tolls i8lcu? crvi>ovorlais, bivoTav yeveaem re kcu ovala? irepi Kara irdvTwv Xeyrjral tl, i-vviapev a>? avrol re dvreLirelv 8eLi>oi 1° rovs re dWov? otl ttolov(Tlv direp avrol ftvvarovs ; GEAI. Ylavrdircuri ye. d HE. TV 5' au 7re/3t vopcav /ecu ^vprrravrcov rwv I. Trepi to>j> tfeiW] Cf. Rep. 10, 598 e, where the same thing is said of the poets : kcu rd ye 6ela. 4. yow] The MSS., with exception of Flor. i, have ovv. 5. otra Cpavepd] Ar. Eth. Nic. VII. 7 : dvOpamov aXXa rroXXd Beiorepa ttjv (pvaiv, oiov (pavepa- rard ye e£ iov 6 Kocrpos o~vvearr)Kev. The distinction between the visible and invisible in Divine things is perhaps the same as in Tim. 41a: ndvres oaoi re Trepu 7to\ovv nepl do-rpovopiav re nai dppovlas re Kai Xoyiapovs. 7. Tiydp ;] " What, indeed V ydp is the usual formula of assent, confirming the previous question : = " You may well ask." 8. tv ye rati Idiais avvovaiais] " In private conversations " — Which are the proper sphere of dvTiXoyiKi) as distinguished from SiKaviKTj, to which refer- ence is presently made ; cf. supr. 225 b. For the limitation with ye, cf. Theset. 204 d : rav- tov cipa, ev ye rols oaa e£ dpidpov eo~TL, to re ndv npoo~ayopevopev /cat Ta anavTa. 9. Trepl yeveaeios re Ka\ ovo-ias — XeyrjTai ti ] " When any general statement is made re- specting the woi-ld of tran- sitional or of absolute Being." K (>G nAATONOS Bedisputes and teaches others to dispute, about things divine, mundane, metaphy- sical, legal, political, and on the subject matter of every branch of art. The Sophist seems to have the power of disputing about all things. ttoXitlkwv, dp oi>)( viricryyovvTai TTOLtlv ufX(fjta(3r)Tr]- p. 232. TLKOVS ; 0EAI. OvSels yap av olvtoIs, coy eiros eiirelv, SieAe'yero p.r) tovto \mio-yyovp.evois. 5 HE. Ta ye prjv irep\ iracrcov re kou Kara p.lav eKaaTrjv Te\vrjv } a del irpbs enaaTOv avrov rbu drjpi- ovpyov dvTenrelv, SeSrjp.ocrMop.eva irov Kara/3e/3Ar^rat yeypafx/jieva tu> /3ouAo/xeW padelv. GEAI. Ta YlpcoTayopeid fxoi (fyaivei 7repl re 7rd\r)s 10 kcu tcou dWcov Teyywv e\pr\Kevai. e HE. Kc« iroXXwv ye, a> /xaKapie, erepcop. drdp 8r) to rr}9 dvTtXoyt,Kr)S Te^vrjs dp ovk ev Ke^aXalco irepl irdvToav 7rpb? dpjfyio-fiiynqcriv 'iKavr) tls Svvapus eoiK elvai ; 1. iroulv ajxcj).] In the sphere of law and justice the Sophist's business is rather to enable men to dispute than himself to hold controversy. dfMju(rfir)Tr}TiKovs ] So here also the Bodl. MS. 3. Oi8els yap av] Cf. Theset. I78e: tovto ye o-v\ With -repl iraacov must be sup- plied a Set Xeyeiv from the fol- lowing clause, in which the expression becomes more de- finite. 6. 7rp6s eK.ao~Tov\ Probably neut. : SC. dpCpia^TjTTjpa. avTov implies, They dictate even to the masters of each craft. 7. 8t8rjp.oo~uop.eva — r<5 ftovAo- pevw paOeh] " The mysteries of each profession are published in manuals for all to learn." Compare the imaginary case put in the Politicus, 299 c : ov8eva yap dyvoelv to re laTpiKov Kal to vyieivbv ox)8e to KvftepvijTiKov Koi vavTiKov' ei-elvai yap to> @ov- \opeva pavddveiv yeypap-peva Kal ■Jarpia edr) neipeva. And for KaTafie$kr)Tai, cf. Ar. Eth. Nic. I. 3 : Ka'iToi ttoXKoI Xdyoi -rpos at)Ta KaTa@e(S\r)VTai. 9. Ta— -rdXrjs] Diog. Laert. 9, 8, 55, mentions the treatise of Protagoras on wrestling. That on rhetoric is mentioned in the Phaedrus, 267 c : Upa- rayopfia 8e, a> Sco/cpares, ovk r\v ToiavTa pevroi aTTa ; 'Opdoeneid ye tis, u> 7tih, Kal ciXXa 7roXXa Kal Ka\d. 12. to tt)s dvTiKoyiKTJs rexPTjs] " As for the province of the controversial art, does it not seem," &c. Cf. Rep. 7, 519 b: to Tr)s ToiaxiTTjS (pvaecos. Legg. 3, 683 d : to toii pvdov. 2012TH2. 07 0EAI. 5?) 7T/0O9 6eu)v, co 7rai, SvvaTOv rjyel tovto ; toluol yap dv v/iew fiev o^vTepov 01 veoi irpbs avTo /3Xe7roiT€, rjpei? Se dpfiXvTepov. 0EAI. To 7TOLOV, kou 7rp6s tl paAiaTa Aeyeis ; ov yap nov Karavoco to vvv epcoTcopevov. S*E. Ei iravra tirLCTTacrOai riva dvOpcoircov earl 8vvaTov. 0EAI. MaKaptov pcevT dv tj/jlcov, co tjeve, i]v to yevo?. HE. TIcos ovv dv 7TOT€ tls irpos ye tov errLCTTa- fievov avTos dveTnaTrjpcov cov bwair dv vyies tl Aeycov avTenrelv ; 0EAT. Ovdafim. S*E. Ti 7T0T ovv dv eirj to Trjs ao(f)icTTLKrJ9 Svva- /x€(0? Oav/xa ; I H I 1 1 1 | . , Hil.l..' 3. ogvrepov oi veoi] Cf. Rep. 595 e : eVel 7roXXa tol of-vrepov fiXenovTcov dp(3\i>Tepov opavres wporepov el8ov. The young are here ironically challenged to use their keen eyesight to de- termine a difficult question. In Legg. 4,715 e, keen mental vi- sion is spoken of as the privi- lege of age. Nai p.a At", & give, naff fj^iKiap yap 6£v ftXeneis. A0. Ne'or p.ev yap &v nas avdpanos ra TOinvra dp-^Xiirara avTos avTOv opa, yepwv 8e o^vrara. For wpos avro, cf. Rep. 7, 515 d, e : npos to (pa>s — jSXenfiv. 5. To — daiifxa] " The secret," " mystery," as of a juggling trick. Cf. Legg. 1, 644 d, 645 b, d, where man is spoken of as a puppet, or magical contrivance, of the gods. This rendering- of the word in the present passage is con- firmed by reference to 235 b : OVKCT €K(j)ev£fTai TO p.Tj OV TOV yevovs eivat. tov tu>v 6avpaTonoia>v tis fir. 6. 011 yap ttov Karavoai] " For I do not think I comprehend (I suppose I do not compre- hend) the drift of your ques- tion." 7rco is read in a few MSS., and is more pointed, but does not seem to be certainly right. The vagueness of nov consorts well with the puzzled tone of Thefetetus. 7. iravTa eVi'crracr&u] Cf. Eu- thyd. 294 c, Ar. Met. 1, 2. 15. Tt' TTOTS 0-0(p(i)TaTOl] " What then can be the mys- tery of the Sophist's art?" "Why?" " I mean, how can they create an impression in the 2, In other words, [a universal knowledge possible for man ? J That were happy for mankind. But with- out know- ledge of a subject how can one dispute with those •' that know ? What then can be the mystery of the So- phist's art ? 6*8 nAATONOI How does lie raise the baseless fabric of a belief that he is all- wise; with- out which he could not hope for a disciple or a fee ? 0EAI. Tov 81) irepi ; p. 233. HE. Kac? ov TLva rpoirov rrore 8vvaro\ toIs veois h ootjav 7rapao~K€vd(JEiv, co? elcri iravra ttolvtcov avroi ao(f)o)Taroi. SrjXov yap ay? el porrre. dvreXeyov 6p0(o? 5 /jL1]T€ iieeivois efyaivovro, (fyaivopevoi re el p.rj8ev av p.aXXov e8oKOW 8id rrjv dp.(f)io-fir)Tr}o-iv elvai (fipovip.01, TO GOV 8rj TOVTO, CT^oAr) 7TOT OLV OLVTols TL9 \pT)p.aTa 8i8ovs rjOeXev av tovtcov avrcov pa6r)Tr\s ylyveaOai. 0EAI. *2,)(oAfj fievr av. lo HE. "Nvv 8e y eOeXovaiv ; GEAI. Kcu fmXa. HE. AoKovat yap, oifiat, irpos Tama e7naTi]p.6vo)s c e\eiv uvtoI Trpos direp dvriXeyovaiv. GEAI. Flcoy yap ov ; 15 HE. Apcoai 8e ye tovto wpoy arravTa, e- peiv avTos. " The only men." 5. pf)T€ eKeivois i(paivoPTo\ For the ellipse of the infinitive, avrCkeyeiv 6p6as, compare Rep. 4, 430 d : KpeiTToa 8fj avrov (pai- vovrai ovk oi8' ovriva rp&nov (sc. \eyovres) na\ aXXa arra rotavra &anep 'i\vr) avrov Xeyerat. Thuc. III. 16 : av€xa>pr}aav — eneibff Ka\ eKeivovt eidov. el fiT)8ev\ Bodl. €i pr/ prjbev, with A and pr. n. 7. to a6v 8rj tovto] u To quote your own observation." 8. TOVTiOV a\]TO>v\ SC. TOl> O.VTI- \eyeiv re o-i tovto] Sc. dvrCKe- yovaw. 20M2TH2. 69 3- 0EAI. Nat. HE. YlavTa apa cro(f)oi tol? paOrjrah (jmivovTai. GEAI. Tturjv; 3 apa tlvol irep\ iravruiv einaTr]- firjv 6 ao(piaTT)9 rjfjuu, aAA' ovk aXijdeiav eywv avair'e- v tov vovv ev pdXa] " Giving me your very closest attention." For the position of ev pdXa, cf. Phsed. 1 1 6 e : deinvrj- o-avrds re Kal iriovras ev pdXa. For Kai introducing an impera- tive, cf. Theret. 145 d, Kal fioi Xeye alib. ; and compare the use of Kai fjioi Xeye (or dvayv&dt) to ^(pio-pa &c. by the orators. 17. Xe'yew] Sllbaudi enio-Ta- o-6ai. The same illustration which is used here to depre- ciate the Sophist is applied to the poets in Rep. 10, 596 c : 'AXX' opa 8t) Ka\ rov8e riva KaXels tov 8i]piovpyov. Tov nolov ; *Oy irdvra iroie'i, oaanep eis emo-ros t5>v x fl P 0T( X v * >v *• T - ^- HdW 6avpaar6v — Xeyeis o-o(piOTr]V. 70 nAATftNOS Imagine a parallel case. Sup- pose IIIK' t>> profess, not that he knows, but that he can create all things : men, ani- mals, the sea, the heaven, the Gods. TroLelv koll 8pdu pid r^x v V ^vdiruvra ewtaraaOai p. 233 Trpayfiara. 0EAI. Ilwy iravra etVey ; e HE. Ttjv apxh v T °v pv]@zvT09 (TV y rjpiv ev6v? 5 dyvoeis' to. yap ^vpiravra, a>? eot/ca?, ov fiavOdvus. GEAI. Ov yap ovv. HE. Aeyco to'lvvv ere kcu e'/xe twv 7rdvrcou, Kal Trpoy rjfiLP rdXXa £coa Ka\ 8ev8pa. 0EAI. Um Aeyet? ; 10 (HE. Ei rt^ e'/ue /cat ere /cat raAAa 0ura irdvTa 7roirj(T€Li> (f)a[r). 0EAI. TtVa 5?) Xeycou ttju iroiiqcriv ; ou yap 8rj yewpyov ye epeh rivd' Kal yap (cocov ovtov emes P« 234 7TOLT]Tr)V. <5 3?E. ^tyfu, /cat 777)0? ye OaXdrrrj^ [/cat 777c-] /cat ovpavov Kal Oecoi/ Kal tcou a\\a>v ijv/JL7rduT(oi>* Kal Toivvv Kal ra)(y 7roir)cra$ avrwv eKaara irdvv a/iLKpov i/Ofx[(rfjLaro9 aVooYcWat. Compare Emped. Fr.13 4-141: a>s 8 oirorav ypafpees — Kai re 6e- ovs 8o\i)(aia>vas rififjai (pepicrrovs. I. fhjvarravra — ^v/xnavraj Note the variety. 4. Tr)v dpxhv] " The very key to ray meaning is unknown to you. You do not understand what I mean by All." 7. Aeyco — tS>v Tvdvrav\ Cf. Rep. 5, 398 C : eya — Kivhvvevat euros t£>v Trdvrav eivai. IO. Kal raXka (pvraj The no- tion of cpvra need not include efie Kai ve, according to a well- known Platonic use of o'XXos, e. g. Ale. II2b: rois re 'Axalois Kal rols aXXots Tpwcriv : with which compare Horn. Od. 2, 43. But the word is probably used here in the widest sense ( = creatures) ; cf. Tim. 90 a : v iyyeimv e'ire ra>v £w(ov. Theag. 121b. 12. \eyu>v\ Sc. (pair] civ. 15. <$>T]p.i] "Yes." Cf. Phsedr. 270 c. Kal yrjs] These words oc- cur only in two MSS., Ven. S. and Flor. i, which however belong to different families. They are not absolutely re- quired, for the earth as well as the sun may be included in the expression ko.1 8e5>v. But cf. Rep. 10, 596 d : Kal irpbs rovrois yrjv Ka) ovpavov Kal deovs. 20M2TH2. 71 >. 234« 0EAI. Wouhiav Aeyei? riva. HE. TV he ; •n)j> roO XeyovTOS otl ttolvtol olhe Kal raura erepou av hiha^eiev oAlyov kou ev oXiyw ^povco, fxiov ov iroubiav vop.Lo~Teov ; GEAI. ndl>TC09 7TOV. 5 b HE. YlcuSia? he e\eL$ rj n TeyyLKWTepov ?) kou XapieaTepov ethos y to /iLpiyTLKOi/ ; GEAI. Ovhapco?' irapnroXv yap elprjKas eiho? els ei> TravTa ^vkXaftcov kou ax^hou irotKiXoiTaTov. HE. Ovkovv rov y v7na\vovp.evov hvvaTov eivanc pua Teyyri iravTa iroielv yiyvcoo-Ko/nev tvov tovtoi/, otl fM/JLrj/JLaTCL kou 6p.coi>v/JLa tcov ovtcov airepyatppevos tyj 2. Ttjv tov \eyovros] Sc. Tex v 1 v - Compare Coleridge, Friend, vol. iii. p. 145 : "For the ancients, as well as the mod- erns, had their machinery for the extemporaneous mintage of intellects, by means of which, off-hand, as it were, the scholar was enabled to make a figure on any and all subjects, on any and all occasions." 4. p.wv ov 7rai8iav vop.io~reov\ Cf. Euthyd. 278 c: nai8iav 8e \eyco 81a. ravTa, on, el Kal 7roXXa tis rj Kal TravTa ra roiavra fiddoi, ra pev irpdypara oi8ev av paXXov el8elrj nfi e'xei, irpocrTrai^eLV 8e olds t av e'trj rols dvdpurtvcos. Legg. 2, 66*] e : Kal irai8idv ye ttjv ai)Ti)v ravrtjv Xeya Tore orav pyre Ti. (SkaTTTy prjre a>(pe\{j aTrov8rjs fj \6yov agiov. The contempt for the art of painting which is here expressed reappears in Legg. 6, 769 b : ivrpi^ — ov- 8ap.ws ye'yova rfj roiavrj] Te\vr] . — Kal ov8ev ye efikdftj}?. See also Polit. 277 C : ypacprjs 8e Ka\ (Tvpira(TT]s ^eiponpyi'as \e£ei Kal Xoyw 8t]\ovv nav £cbov pdWov Trpeivei rols 8vvapevoi<; e-rrea-Oai. 6. TexyiKtorepov xapieo-re- pov] " More artful," and there- fore more worthy of the So- phist ; " more amusing," and therefore more deserving of the name naiSid. Cf. Polit. 288 c, where piprjTiK-q is in- cluded under mdyviov. 8. 7rajnrroXv] " Most exten- sive." Lit. "abundant." Cf. infr. 236 b. 9. 7TOlKi\a)TaTOV ] " Most various." Cf. Theset. 146 d : TroiKiXa dv8' dnXov. 1 1 . yiyvaHTKopev irov tovtop] tovtov, although the reading of only two MSS. (Par. H. Flor. b), is certainly preferable to tovto, because adding point to the parallel : and has been introduced into the text by Stallbaum. The same reading had previously been conjec- tured by Van Heusde. 12. Spuvvpa] Cf. Parm. 133 d : ra — nap' i]piv ravra, opwvvpa ovra e\eivois. We should understand at once that he is a painter, and that 72 nAATQNOS his arc only mimic " crea- tions ;" by which, however, he can im- pose from a distance 5 on the less intelligent amongst young children. There is also a mimic art of reason- ing, by IO ypa(f)iKr) T€)(i>r) Swaros earaL tov? uvoi]tovs tcou viwv p. 234 iraiSoov, iroppmdev rd yeypappeva hriBeuaws^ XavOd- veiv, cu?, o ti 7rep av ftovXrjOfj Spav, tovto 'ikolvcotoltos cov diroTeXelv epycp. 0EAI. Ylco? yap ov ; SiE. TV 8e 8/] ; irepl tov? Xoyov? dp ov irpoaBo- Kwp.€v elvai twcl aXXr/v re^vrju ; j-rj °V"f Swarbv av Tvyyaveiv tov? vkov? /cat en Troppco tmv irpaypLaroav Trj? dXr/OeLa? d(peo~TU)Ta? 81a tQ>v cotwu toi? Xoyoi? yorjTevetv, SeiKvvvTa? etScoXa Xeyofieva wept 7rdvT(x>v 9 2. iroppa&ev — afacrrcoTas] Ct. *. I, 663 b : (TKOToSiviav 8e to noppooOev 6pa)p.evov iracri re a>s eirog elireiv nal 8tj kcu toIs natal napex". The spirit of Prot. 314b is the same : rj^ls yap en veoi, (bare toctovto irpaypa 8ie\eo~dai. Cf. also Kep. 1, 331 e : &o-nep fjdr) eyyvrepoy &>v rav ocei fidWov ti KaQopa avrd. 7. nva aXXrfv Texvrjv] roiavr-qv, which Heindorf proposed to insert before rexvrjv, is found in C. H. c, and has been added by a recent hand in two other MSS. But with roiavTT] following (infr. d), the common reading is more pro- bable. + »7 oi+] The reading of most MSS., 17 ov Swarov av rvyxdveiv, is awkward unless Toiavrijv is added above, ov may possibly have arisen from aZ following. The translation of Ficinus (qua seductores — adolescentulos decipere vale- ant) points to Schleiermacher's conjecture, T] bvvarbv av rvyxd- veiv, which is also supported by a correction of the Coisli- nian MS. (fj Bvvarov.) (fj ov n.) For rvyxdveiv with the ad- jective, cf. Tim. 61 d, rvyxdvet — raiira — Sward "hex^^vai, and seven other passages quoted by Ast, Lex. S. V. rvyxdvco. And for the infinitive after the relative #(subaud. ivpoo-boKa>pev), cf. Parm. 130 e : thai e'idr) cirra, S>v rate — ras inavvp-ias i'cr^ftv. 8. tovs veovs Ka\ en iroppco] A similar parallel is drawn between rhetoric and tragic poetry in Gorgias 502 d : Nw cipa 17/xety evprjKapev prjTopiKrjv nva Trpbs brjpov toiovtov oiov irai- 8cov re 6/j.ov Kal yvvaiKcov Kal dv8pa>v, Kal 8ov\a>v Kal i\ev6epa>v, rjv ov irdw dydpeda, koXokiktjv yap avrrjv (ttjv tt)s rpaycodias iroirjcnv) qbapav eivai. See also ib. 458 e, where the " omniscience" of the rhetor is noticed : wepl irdvTcov (prjTopiKOv) war iv o^Xw iridavbv ehai. Ib. 459 b: 6 ovk el8u>s tov etSdroy iv ovk el86ai TTidavcoTepos. Compare Legg. 2, 658 C : il p.ev tolvvu Ta ap,iKpa Kpivoi iraihia, Kpivovo~i tov rd dav- p.ara inideiKVvvTa. IO. ei'SaXa Xeyopeva] .■= rd iv 2()I2TH2. 73 p. 234. Q)0~T€ 7T0L€LV dX^Ovj 8oK€W Xey€(T0UL KCU TOV XtyOVTU Srj ao(j)(OTaToi> irdvToov uttolvt civcti ; d 0EAI. TV ydp ovk av eiq aXXrj tls roiavri] rexyrj ; S*E. Tov? ttoAAow ovu, J^coJ QtalrrjTe, rwv Tore olkovovtcov dp ovk dvdyKi^ XP^ V0V T€ zttcXOovtos avTois LKauov kou 7rpoiovcrr)s rjXiKias, tols re overt TrpocnriiTTOVTas eyyvOeu koll did iraO^jidroiv uvayKa- {ppevovs evapyws efydirTeaOai rcov optcov, perafidX- Xeiv tol9 rore yevopievas Soijas, cocrre apuKpd p}v v irapayzvopiviov ; rots Xoyois (pavraa-para, infr. e. " Exhibiting fictitious argu- ments, as the painter exhi- bited fictitious shapes." There is a stress on \eyopeva as op- posed to yeypappeva emdeiKPvs above. Compare Theset. 150 e : yJAevSrj Koi ei'ftcoXa ivepl irXeiovos iroirjcrapevoi rod akrjBovs. For the plural SeiKvvvTas, to which objection has been made, cf. Theast. 172 b: edeXovcrcv Icrxv- pi£ecrdat. lb. 1 67 b : 8oga£ovras avyyevrj eavTtjs, and notes. i. Trotelv — 8oi] emiTrjre] The Bodl. omits S> with An. 8. 81a 7m6T)pdr(ov] According to the " rpiyepcov pvdos," 7ra6i)- para padrjpara. 9. evapyas] " To come into unmistakeable contact with re- ality." 10. crpiKpa — ra peyaXa] E.g. wealth, distinction, &c. 11. xaAe7ra — ra pabut] E.g. the government of men. 13. vtto roiv iv rais irpa^cnv epycov Tvapayevopevcov] "The reali- ties which have encountered them in action." Compare the complaint of Adimantus in Rep. 6, 487 b, c. And cf. Legg. 6, 769 d : irpo'iovTos tov xp^vov, koi tcov 8o£('wtcov f'py

peyurTco Sul/jlovl Oeol, yi/ovre? rfdr) to yiyvo- p. 27.1:; ptevov, a(j)ieaav av to. p.epi] tov KocrpLov rr;? clvtgov eV^/xeAe/a?. 6 <5e ptTao-Tpecpopevo? /cat £vp(3a\Acov, p. 27 apXV? Te KaL TeXevrrjs ivavTiav opprjv op/irjOei^, crei- 5 a/JLov ttoXvv iv eavTW iroi&v, aKkqv av (frQopav ^cocov iravTOKov aTTtipya.cra.To- p.6Ta he Tama irpoeXOovTOs LKavov )(povov, 0opv(3a>v T€ Koi Tapa^rj^ rjSr] irav- op.evos Kal tcov o~eicrp.(DV, ya\y')vr]9 einkafiop.evos eh re tov elcoOora Spopov tov eavTOi) KaTaK0ap.0vp.ev09 l oj]6i, eTTLfieXetav /cat /cparos* e^oav avTos tcov iv avTa> b fMfVTj — raw S' aXXwv iaoi iv rw twv 8a>8eKa dpidpSt reraypieVoi 6eol apxovres, I'lyovvrai Kara ra£iv fjv eKaaros eraxdrj. £u/i/3aAAa)x> sc. iavT<0 : — " coming together with a, shock :" cf. Theophr. de SeilSU I : tovs tvttovs avdyKt) avpfidWeiv iavTols, Soph. CEd. Col. 901 : 'iv6a 8l(TTOfioi /jLaXiara o~vp[3dWovo-iv iprrdpcov 6801. Hom. II. n. 565. And compare the frequent use of avp^dXXco in Hdt. to express conflict in war. I. rep peyiarcp 8aipovi #eoi] Badham conjectures to jac- yiCTTW SaifJ.oi'es Qedj. Cf. supr. 271 d, infr. 274 b, Legg. 8, 848 C : 6ea>v re Kal tcov irropevcov Oeols 8uifx6vav. lb. *] , 82 1 a: tov /xeyio-rov 8ebv Kal 6'Xoi> tov koo-jxov. See however supr. 271 d, e, where 8aipa>v and Beds are interchanged. 4. dpxqs re Kal reA. — opprj- 6eis] " Having received an im- pulse opposite, both in respect of beginning and end," — the ■KoQev and the 71-ot. This of course happens when a circular motion is reversed : and aggra- vates the violence of the imme- diate shock. Had the world " gone off" at a tangent," the beginning would have been the former end, but the end not the former beginning. 5. aXkrjv av Cp6opdv\ Supr. 270 c. 8. els tov eladoTu 8popov\ The vibrations are supposed to cause a temporary perturba- tion or nutation of the cir- cular motion, as in a top that is not " asleep." The notion of vast cycles is assumed in the Laws. Cf. 3, 680 a, where the first survi- vors of the flood are called of iv TovTd roi pepei ttjs 7repid8ov yeyovdres. lb. 6, 782 a : TrdXeav o-vo-rdo-eis Kal (pdopds Kal iiriTr)8ev- para ivavTola ragecos re Kal dra^ias Kal fipaaeos Kal Trcopdrcov re apa Kal ftpcopdraiv iTTi6vp.iip.aTa 7ravTo8and ndvTos Kal rvepl Tvdcrav ttjv yrjv ap ovk oldpeda yeyovivai, Kal o-Tpopa>v 7ravTolas, ev als to. £a>a peTa(3dX\eLV avToiv irap- TrXrjdels /xeraj3oXas etKosj ei'sre — KaTaKoapovpevos] "Set- tling down into his accus- tomed course." Cf. Eep. 8, 560 a : al8ovs tlvos Zyyevopivqs iv tji tov ve'ov ^v^f) — KaTeKoo~pr)6r) rrdXiv. Supr. 271 e. Qu. an. omittend. re 1 nOAITIKOS. 65 p73* T€ KaL eCLVTOV, T1~)V TOV 8l]/lL0Vpy0V KCU 7T(XTpOS U7T0- /jLvrjfjLOvevcov SiSa^rju el? 8vvap.LV. kolt dpyas p.ev ovv aKpifiecrTepov direTeXei, TeXevTcov 8e d/xfiXvTepov. tovtcov 8e avrcp to acop.aToet8e? tyj? avyKpdaeco? OLITLOV, TO TY]? TTaXoU 7TOTC (j)VCr€C09 tjl)VTpO(j)OV, OTL iroXXrjs rjv jxtTeypv aTatjla? irp\v el? tov vvv Koap.ov dcpiKeaflcu. Trapa pcev yap rod avvOevTO? irdvTa rd KaXd KeKTTjrar irapd 8e tyj? ep.7rpoo~6ev e^eco?, ocra c \aXeird kcll d8iKa ev ovpavw ylyverai, ravra e'tj e'/ce/- vrj? avTO? re eyei koI to?? ftooi? evairepyaJ^erai. fiera fiev ovv rov KvftepvrjTOv to. (coa Tpe(pcov ev avTco cr/jLiKpd p.ev (pXavpa, fxeydXa 8e everiKTev dyadd' \copi^6p.evo? be eKeivov tov eyyvrara ypovov del tyj? brought by his Crea- tor : fY'iii whom he derives all that he has of good : and in con- 5 junction with whom, in that former cycle, the evil within him is re- duced to a minimum. But that guiding hand being withdrawn, as forget- fulness in- creases the ancient 10 I. Trarpos] Cf. Tim. 28 e, 37 d. The word is used here for the sake of the metaphor, " Calling to mind his father's instruction •" as in Tim. 42 e : vorfaavres 01 irai8es rr)v tov Tra- rpos bidra^iv, fxifj.ovfj.evoi tov (npeTepov 8rjfj.iovpyov. 3. dfiftXvrepov] " "With less sharpness and precision," as if making an inferior copy of some masterpiece of sculpture or painting, or, " with dimin- ished powers," " with less in- sight," " with less keenness of vision." The latter is more probable. 4. tovtcov 8e — dcpiKecrdai ] " Now this falling off comes to the world from the bodily- element of her composition, which was inherent in her pri- mal nature, since this partook of much disorder, before at- taining the present organised form." Cf. Tim. 30 a : ttov ocrov rjv oparbv TrapaXaficdv cv% fjO~v)(iav ayov dXka. Kivovfievov TT'\r]p.u.e\a)S Kal draKrcos, els Tafjiv avTO ijyayev in rr)s dratjias. on — d(piKeo-8ai is epexegetic of the previous clause. For the iden- tity of the oparbv and o-coparo- ei8es, cf. Phfedo 80 c: to opa- rbv avrov to o~a>p.a. Several MSS., including All, have fie- roxov. 8. Trapa. 8e rr)s eixTrpocrQev e|eo)r] Thus a time is ima- gined before the alternate cy- cles began. Compare the thought in Rep. 10, 613, of the just man : ova ye airb decov yiyverai, iravra yiyvedai cos oiov re apiara, el fir) tl dvayKalov avrco kokov e< Trporepas dpaprlas imijpxev. Trapa 8e — f£fW, e'£ eiceivrjs] The expression at first cor- responds to Trapa p.ev — tov avv- devros, but when resumed for the sake of emphasis in a pro- nominal form, is more strictly adapted to the immediate con- text. 13. tov eyyvrara xpoVoi/ dei K m nAATONOS aliaivliy gradually returns, until the world and all depend- ent organ- isms are in danger of ruin. "Wherefore then the first dis- poser of the world, lest he should founder in a0ecrea)? KaXXtara iravra Sidyet, ir poiovTOS <5e tov p. 2J' : I' Xpovov Kol XijOi]? eyyiyi>opL€i>r}9 ip avrco fxaWov kcll Swaarevei to Trj? 7raXcaas uvapfiocrTias wado?, re- d Xzvtcovtos Se l^avOa. tov \povov kol crpuKpd fxlv STayaOa, ttoXXi-jv 8e ri]v tcov ivavTtaiV Kpaaiv eVey/ce- pavvvpievos eVi diacjjOopas kivSvvov olvtov re a.(f)L- Kvfirat kol tcou ip amui. dio 8rj kcu tot rj8r] Beo? 6 Koaprjaa9 glvtop, KaOopcov iv ouKopious ovtol, ki]86- pL€VO?, M 7 \eip.acr6eL9 viro Tapa)09 SiaXvOeh els TTJs dcpeo-eas] Proximum quod- que ab remissione tempus. 2. pdWov Kol — 7rd#o?] " The influence of the old habit of disorder also gains a greater ascendancy." Plato's use of 7rd#oj, as of yevevis, is often difficult to render from its generality. Cf. Theast. 193 d. 4. egavdel] " Breaks out into full bloom." Sc. t6 t^s- dvappoarias nddos. Cf. infr. 310 d : TeXeuTcicra 8e i^avQelv iravTamacnv pavlais. Aesch. Pers. 821.: vj3pis yap ef-avdova itcap- 7ra>o~e o-raxvv arrjs. So Stallb. and Passow s. v. In what follows, the sentence returns to the ge- neral subject, 6 Koap.os. The other renclei'ing, however, de- serves notice ; in which 6 koV- fios is the subject of i£av8ei, which is explained to mean " leaves blossoming," " ceases to produce anything good." 5. 7toXKtjv eTveynepavvvpevos] "Administering evil to itself in large measure." ineyKepav- vvpevos, lit. " pouring into itself additionally." The world is a great vessel, in which differ- ent elements are mixed : and during this cycle is itself the author of the mixture. (Kpumv, abstract for concrete). Or per- haps the participle is passive, " Receiving large admixture of evil." (The passive of a verb which governs the dative in the active voice appears in Re P- 1 , 337 a, and Legg. 11, 925 e, 926 a, 937 b.) For the image, cf. Rep. 8, 562 c : 7rdXtf eXevdepias Si\j/r](ra(ra kokcov OiVO)(6cOV TTpOCTTaTOVVTCdV TVXV k.t.X. For the force of the prefix in eTreyKepavvvpevos, cf. eVeyxeoo, e. g. iEsch. Ag. 1 1 3 7 . 6. diacpdopds] This word, if alone, would have been passive, but by the addition of the genitives is turned to an active meaning. 8. KTjftopevos tva prj] " In care for the world that it may not" &c. A similar feeling appears in Legg. 2, 653 c : deol fie oiKTeipavTes to tcov dvdpai- ttu>v eirinovov 7rev. 9. Iva pt] 8vt] ] " Lest being tost with tempest it might be shaken in pieces and nOAITIKOS. 67 273. TOV TYJ9 aVO/JLOLOTr/TO? OLTTeipOV OVTOL TOTTOV 8vr}, irdXiV e(pe8po9 avrov twv 7n]8a\la>i> yiyvo\JLtvo aTpeyjfav, Koafiei re kcu iiravopOoiv aOavarov avrov koll ayrjpcov threpyatjETaL. tovto pev ovv reAos 5 airavTOdU elprjTOLL. to 8* eVi ri^v tov fiacriAecos airo- 8tL^LV 'lKCLVOV €K TOV TTpoaOtV 0L7TT0p.€U0L? TOV \6yOV. crTpecpOevTos yap av tov Koa/mov ttjv hri tx]v vvv yevecfLv o8ov to t^s* rjKiKtas av TraXLv \0~TaT0 K.a\ ■ of dissimili- tude, re- verses tlir process of decay, and restores him to im- mortal youth. The wheel i8 thus brought full circle : but for our present purpose founder in the abyss of dis- similitude." For a glimpse of the darkening path towards this limbo of " chaos come again," see Parrn. 165 ; Tim. 48 e-52 d. In the chaos of Anaxagoras, the 6p.otopepeiai were at least latent ; but to this new and worse chaos even this degree of consistency is denied. The words aneipov ovra recall Pythagorean asso- ciations. 1. Tonov has been objected to. Stallbaum would read ttovtov, and M. Wagner, in the Kheinische Museum, has sug- gested tvttov, which is too ab- stract for the context (x €i - pao-dels — 8vrj). Stallbaum's ob- jection (Displicet istud roVo*/, quo rnetaphoraa elegantia pes- sumdatur) forgets the differ- ence between metaphor and allegory. The vagueness of to- kos in Plato's use ( = "region") exactly suits the passage. Cf. Theset. 176 a ; Phsedr. 247 c, 274 d; Soph. 254 a; Rep. 6, 508 c, 7, 516 b, 532 d, 10, 614 c. Trakiv — yiyvopevos] " Again presiding at the helm." e'cpedpos not = " successor," (Ast. Lex. s. v.,) but according to the tragic use with the genitive, " seated on or at." 3. iv rfj — nepiuSa] " In the former circuit which the world made by himself." Ka6' iavrov depends on the verbal notion m 7repi6da>. 4. o-Tptyas] " Having re- versed." Not only arresting decay, but causing growth : rfj rpoirfi avvavaKVKKovpevrjs els Tavavria rrjs yeveaews, as before. 5. reXos dndvTcou etprjTai] Our account of each recurring cycle is complete. " The wheel is brought full circle." 7. iKavdv ] Subaud. rjp.lv \eyftv. €K tov fvpoo-dev divTopevois tov \6yov] " Taking hold of the story by the previous part." I. e. attaching what we have to say to an earlier point in the fable, viz. the (pdopd mentioned in 273 a, as ensuing on the change from the obedient to the self-di- rected movement of the world. 8. ttjv — 686v] "Towards the present operation of na- ture." Cf. note on yeveaeo)*, supr. 271 b. K 2 68 nAATONOS: we must revert to the in -in- ning of the period in w hirli WO live: when, the uni- verse being left to it- self, the bodies that were dwin- dlingbegan to grow, and those which had just sprung in full ma- turity from the Earth, put on grey- locks, and went be- neath the ground. Then, as Kaiva rdvavrla dTre8i8ov rdis rare, rd fiev yap vtto p. 273 (TfiLKpoTijTo^ oXiyov 8eovra T)(f)ai>t(T0aL TCOV (fiXtiV ■>lv£di>€TO, to. 5' e/c yr)$ veoytvrj acouara ttoXlci (j)vvra iraXiv cmodvr)(TKQVTa ds yr\v Karrjei. kcu rdXXa re 5 iravra LieTefiaXXev, caTOLLLfiovjieva kcu ^vvolkoXov- p. 27* dovvra tcd tov ttclvtos 7ra0r]paTi, kcu 8rj kcu to ttjs Kvqtreais kcu yevvifaeco^ kcll rpo(j)r]9 uljirjua avveLirero tols iracriv vtt dvdyKiqs. ov yap i$ji}p er iv yrj 81 erepcov avvicrravTcov (JjvecrOai tcoov, dXXd Kadairtp ioTco Kocrucp 7rpocreT6TaKTO avTOKparopa elvat 7-779 avrov Tropela?, ovtco 8rj Kara, ravrd koli tois uepecnv avrols 8l avrcov, Ka0 J ocrov oiov r rjv, (pveiv re Ka\ yevvav /cat rpecpeLU TrpoazraTTeTO virb tyjs opLOia? dycoyrjs. ov 8e ei>€Ka 6 Xoyos cop/mrjKt iras, eV avrco vvv iafxev b I . miva. — Tore] " Made an opposite inversion of the phe- nomena." to. pev yap — Karrjei] Those who according to the previous order had risen from earth in full maturity, and had passed through the stages of youth and childhood, and were on the point of disappearing from the earth, returned to child- hood, youth, and manhood ; while those who had been lately born, and were there- fore in full maturity, instead of becoming more youthful, passed into old age and died and went below the ground — so preparing the soil for the next crop of earth-born men. 3. veoyevrj] It is to be re- membered that they are al- ready full-grown. 7roXta (pvvra ] " Having grown grey." The aorist re- tains the temporal significa- tion. 6. to — piprjpa] I. e. to ttjs Tpocprjs pepiprjpevov crvveinfTO. 81 eTepoov o~vvio~Ta.vTa>v] DC. 6ca>v. Cf. Tim. 43 a; Protag. 320 d. 9. ov] Bodl. A LEY £acov. I 3. vnb Tr/s opoias dyeoyfjs] By a similar entrainement, by an eddy from the same current. Cf. Phsedr. 238 c : viKrjcracra ayayfj. Rep. 10,604 b: ivavrias 8e dycoyrjs yiyvopevr/s iv tu dv- 6p(OTvco. As the world is moved, so human beings are brought together, by destiny and innate desire (elpappevrj kcu crvpcpvTos eTTiBvpia) : ov yecoperpucals aX\' epaTiKals dvaynais. (Rep. 5> 458 d.) 14. eV avrcp — ecrpev] Cf. Rep. 5, 473 C : eV avTO (v. 1. avrco) 8tj eipi 6 tco peylcTTCo 7rpoo-eiKci£o- pev Kvpari. lb. 7? 53 2 c • e '' ^, nOAITIKOS. GO 274. rj8rj. irepl pev yap tcou aXXwv Orjplcou 7roXXa av kgu fiaKpa Si€^€\0€iv yiyvoiro, i£ (hv eKaara kou 8l as airlas p-erafiefiXyKe' irepl 8e dvOpcoTrcou fipayyrepa kcu fxaXXov TTpoarjKOVTa. ti)s yap tov KdKTr)fievov Kal vepLOvros rjpids 8alp.ovos aTrepr/puoOevTes eVt/ue- 5 Ae/ay, rcof iroXXcov av drjpicov, ocra ^aXeTra tols (f)v- a€L9 rjv, airaypL(£)6evT(£>v, avrol 8e acrOevels avOpaiiroi c Kal dcpvXaKTOL yeyovores, 8ii]p7rd{pi>To vir avroov, Kal er apxiyavoi Kal arzyyoi Kara, tov? 7rp(OTovs rjcrav Xpovovs, are rrjs p.ev avTopbaTij? rpcxfirj? eVnAeAot- 10 irvias, TropL^eaOat Se ovk eTTKJTapLevoi ttco Sia to p.r\8ep.iav avrov? ^peiav irporepov avayKa^iv. €K tovtcdv iravTcov ev peyaXats diro plats fjaav. 06 ev <5/? rd irdXai Xe\6evTa irapd decov 8a>pa rjplv 8e8ooprjTaL fier dvayKaias 8i8a\rjs Kal 7rai8evaeo39, irvp p.ev 15 irapa Hpop.r)6em', Teyyai 8e 7rap' 'HfpalaTOV Kal ttjs tlio world was self- impelled, bo tin.- races of animals were left to propagate themselves. And men, being de- serted by their Di- vine Shep- herd, were torn by the now savage beasts, while the earth no longergave them spon- taneous sustenance. Whence the gods, who still ho- vered near, gave them fire, mecha- nical arts, the vine, avrco yiyverai tco tov votjtov re- A«.' Soph. (Ed. Eex. 11 68 : Trpbs avroi y elpl ro> 8eiva> ~kiya.v. 6. av] Used here almost as a conjunction. xaKeTra ] The opposite of tractable : fierce and unman- ageable. Cf. Rep. 6, 493 b, 500 a; bis. Legg. 11, 922 b, 950 b.^ 7. doSevels — Kal d(pv\aKTOi] The myth at this point touches closely on that of Protagoras. Prot. 3 2 1 C : tov 8e avOpunrov yvpvov re Kal avvTrobrjrov Kal ao-rpcoTOv Kal cionXov. The whole passage, giving an account of the origin of the arts of life, should be carefully compared with this. II. 8ia to pr]8eplav — dvay- Ka^eiv\ " Because no previous necessity had driven them to invention." Cf. Theset. 149 c : 17 dvOpayrrLvrj (pvais do-QevecrTepa 77 \afielv Teyvr}v cov av g aneipos. 14. to. iraKai \e)(6£vTa\ Still more of the existing fragments of mythology are incorpoi'ated into the Great Myth. 15. peT dvayKaias SiSa^y] The Deity " left not himself without witness." The parts of the Universe were left to guide themselves as far as was possible (els hvvap.iv, supr. 273 a) ; but in their extreme need, such Divine instruction as they could not do without (dvayKaias) was still afforded them. 16. Kal ttjs o-vvrexvov] Cf. Prot. 321 e : t6 ttjs 'Adrjvds Kal H eCpiXoTexvelrrjv. Legg. II, 92 1 d : 'HcpaiaTOV Kal \6rjvds lepov to tcov 8r)p.iovpyav yevos, ol tov 70 IIAATQNOS the olive, the sustain- ing corn, accompa- nied with such in- struction as was indispen- sable : and thereafter left them to themselves. Such is the fable which we must now apply. The myth has brought to lisjht the avvTtyvov, cnrzpiiaTa hi av koll (jwra irap dXXwv' p. 27v — rrjs inipe- \das\ Double constr. with the article, ttjs imp. being added epexegetically. Cf. supr. 271 e : to Tu>v dvBpinrov \e\6ev av- TOfxaTov irepl /3iou. 7. co t-vp.pip.ovp.evoi koX £vv(- Tropevoi] Cf. supr. 2 7 3 e : dno- pipovpcva kcu £vva.Ko\ov8ovvTa — nip-qpa o-vveiTreTo. gvp. appears to be added by a sort of at- traction from §war., by which the dative is in the first in- stance governed. It may per- haps occur to the student to render tjvpp-ipovpevoi " helping the Universe to imitate (the movement of the Divine Hand):" comparing supr. 273 a : rrjv tov drjpiovpyov Kal ira- Tpos diropvrjpovevcov 8i8axr)v els dvvapiv, and infra 293 e, 297 c. And this sense would not be unsuitable to this expression taken singly, and to to tijs — rpocprjs plp.rjpa. But these words cannot be interpreted apart from the previous phrase, peTe- @a\\ev dnopipovpeva kcu £vvaKo- XovdovvTa tco tov navTos TraOi-jpaTi., which can only be rendered in one way. 9. reXos ex*'™] Cf. Phsedo 77 c; Legg. 4, 717 e. II. oaov fjpdpTopev] Cf. 268 b, C : 7rws av ovv rjplv 6 Xoyos 6p6bs (pavelTai Kal dv yeyovoaiv evofinderovv, dXX' dvdpamoi re Ka\ a\v6pccma>v o-irep- p.ao~i vopoderovpev Ta vvv, dvep.e- ar/Tov 8rj (poBe'iadai k.t.X. The same thought is present also in Legg. 10, 906 : tos twv (pvXaKcov \j/vxas kvvcov 77 Tas TOiv vop.ea>v rj — Tas rav TvavTcmao-iv aKpoTCLTav 8eanoTa>v. Compare also Parm. 134 d : Ovkovv el Ttapa rw 6eu> avTrj eo~Tiv rj aKpiffe- o-TaTr) 8ecnroTela Kai avrrj f/ aKpi- fieo-Ta.Tr) eTTio-TTjpr] k.t.X. Al'ist. Pol. III. 8 : aianrep deov ev av- Bptoirois eiKOS eivat tov toiovtov (t6v 8ia(pepovTa kut dperijs vnep- (3o\r]v). 6. ■napr\vex& r \P- fV ] " Went astray." Cf. Phileb. 60 d : el 8e ye TrapT]vex6r]p,ev tl Tore, vvv oariaovv eiravaKaj3cov opdoTepov elndra. real grava- lii'-n of ' error. Our defini- tion of tin.- ruler of bhe statu is not merely in- adequate, as we fear- ed, but, what is more se- rious, we 72 IIAATQNOS haw i-i ni- Rued bhe modern Statesman with the Divine Shepherd. The myth was intro- duced that we might see in a clearer light the image of the kin sr. ov 8i€i7ropev, TavTY] 8e av to pev Xe^Bev d.Xr)6e?, ov p. 27 p.i)v oXov ye ov8e aaqjes epprjdr/, 81b kou ftpayvTepov 7) kclt eKelvo rjpapTrjKapev. NE. 20. 'AXrjOij. 5 HE. Aei. to'lvvv tov Tpowov, 6)$ eotKe, 8ioplaavTa9 T V? ®-p\ri9 tt}9 TroXecos 1 ovtco TeXetos tov ttoXitlkov rjp.lv eiprjcrOou 7rpooSoKav. NE. 20. KaXw. HE. Aia Tama pr/v kou tov pvOov 7rapeOepe0a, b iotva evSelljaiTO 7repl ty)$ dyeXaiOTpoffilas pr) povov a>5 TfdvTes avTrj? dpi(pLO~(3r/T0vo~L tco fyrovpe'vcp tol vvv, dXXa KotKelvov clvtov ivapyeaTepov 'Idoipev, ov irpocr- rjKei, povov kolto. to 7rapd8eLypLa 7roip.evcov re kou fioVKoXcOV TTJS dv0pu>7TLVr/9 eTTipeXeiaV €)(OVTa TpoiAi7/3ov ye evena napedeprjv tov \6yov. Phsedo 65 e : prjTe tt)v oyj/iv napadepevos ev tco diavoelcrdai. 1 0. iva ev8ei£aiT0 — pr) povov dkX 'iSoipev] The structure of the sentence is slightly altered by the change of subject. II. tco (rjTOvpevco Tavvv\ I.e. tco ttoXitikco. For a similar formal allusion to the subject of inquiry, cf. Soph. 223 c : oi yap ti cpavXrjs peToypv ecTTt Te'x vr }'> to vvv £rjTovpevov, aXX' ev pa\a iroiKiXr]?. Phileb. 5 b : i-a vvv 7toXXcikis Xeyopeva. Cf. Gorg. 451 e : ovBev tvco aacpes. Tim. 49 a : e'iprjTai pev TciXrjdes, Set §' ivapyeaTepov elnelv ivep\avT0v. I 2. ov Tvpoo-rjiceL, povov — Trpocr- prjparos] " To whom it belongs, having, in accordance with our image, alone of shepherds and herdsmen the care of human nurture, alone to be thought worthy of this title." The order of the words is pecu- liar, as is the case frequently throughout these dialogues. nOMTIKOS. 73 175. fAeltpv 7) Kara fiacriXea dvat to ayj]p.a to tov Oeiov C l>O/UL€C0$, TOVS 5' iu6a8e VVV OVTCLS TToXlTLKOVS TOL9 dp)(Ofl€l>OL9 OflOlOV? T€ elvOLL fiaXKoV TToXv TCL9 (f)Va€L9 Kal 7rapa7r\r]oriaiTepoi> 7rai8eia? peTeiXrjtyevaL koll TpO(f)T)S. 5 NE. 20. I\a.VT(OS 7T0V. aE. Ztr)TT)T€OL ye pnqv ov8ev av elrjcrav ovO* fjTTOv ovt€ paXXov, et@' ovtco? eiT eKelvco? 7revitao-iv\ Ac- cording to the principle laid down in Soph. 227 b, and re- peated supr. 266 d, that de minimis ceque ac de maximis curat scientia. 1 1 . iiraveXdajfiev] " Let us re- trace our steps." 14. aye\aioTpo(fiiKr]V ] Supr. 262 e. 17. Tavrrjs — diTj/jLapravoiJiev] " Our error lay somewhere in this." The genitive is governed by Try, and not by the verb. 19. Kara rr]v ovonacr'iav~\ The verbal noun ovop.. occurs here for the first time in Greek literature. 74 nAATQNOS WY.sl.nl.ld have spo- ken more generally of an art of tending. And then by follow- ing the same series of divisions we before employed, ov fA6T0i> eirrjveyKCLfxev Tovvopa, 8eov tcov kolvcov e?r- p. 27 eveyKtiv tl ^vpnraaiv. e NE. 212. ' A\i]0rj Xeyet?, eiirep tTvyyave ye ov. HE. Y\m <5' ovk rjv to ye Bepcmeveiv ttov ttolctl skolvov, fir)$ev SioptaOelo-qs rpofprj? /J.r)8e twos aXhr)aiveTaC &tco 8e av rl to fieTa tovto ; aE. ArjXov otl XeyOevTos ovtco tov ttjs dyeXaio- b K0/JLIK7]? OVOfJLaTO? OVK OCV TCOT iyeveO' Tj/MV TO TWOS 5 dfMpiafirjTe'LV cos oi)8 eiTineXeia to irapdirav eaTiv, coawep tot€ Sikglicos 7]/JL(pLcr(3r}Tr)0r) /irjSe/iiav dvai Te^yrjv ev r]plv d^lav tovtov tov OpeirTiKOv rrpocr- prmoLTOs' el 5' ovv tls elr], rroXXols upoTepov a\)Tr}9 dTTOTereXeo'fievrjv irpocr- ayopeveLv. NE. SO. Tl mv ; SE. \\pu)Tov pjev, o ^Aeyo/jLev*, rovvop.a fxera- crKevcoprjaacrOai, 7rpb? rrju eirLp.eXeLav pLaXXov irpoa- d ayayovra? rj ttjv rpo(])rji>, eirecra ravTr/v refiveW ov yap cr/jLiKpas av eyoi Tfxrjcrei? en. NE. 20. IW; of division : that now to be named is an omission with which we were chargeable at the close. Supr. 267 c. (18.) crv^vov 8irjpaprdveT0 ] "We erred largely." Cf. Phsedr. 257 c : wxybv 8iapaprdvei?. 2. ToSe — 7rpocrayop€veiv ] " This was our mistake, that it might be said (apa) that how- ever clear we were as to the existence of a nurturing art, we were not therefore justified in at once calling this by the names of ' kingcraft' and 'state- craft,' as if perfectly defined." 7. Ti firjv ;] Sc. ?8« ; " Why, what ought we to have done 1" See note on « prjp ; supr. 258 b. 8. UpcoTOv pev o *Xeyopev*] Bodl. All. eXeyopev : cett. o eXey- opev. Cf. Rep. 3, 402 C : ap' ovv, o Xeyw, irpbs 8ea>v, ovtcos ov8e povcFLKoi rrpoTepov eo~6pe6a . lb. 5; 464 C : dp' ovv o&x, oirep \eyoa, rd re 7rp6o~8ev elprjpeva /cat rd vvv Xeyopeva en pdXXov dnep- yd^erai airovs akq6ivovs (pv- Xanas ; Legg. 3, 68 1 b : els rovs iraihas cmorvTvovpevovs Kal naidoov Traidas, b Xiyopev, tftcetv k.t.X. Compare Theset. 188 c : 6' fy- rovpev : where Bodl. An. give e{j)Todfiev. p.eTao~Kevcopr]0-ao-dai] Sc. e8ei. " We ought first, as we are now saying, to have remo- delled the name." The word is ana^ Xeyopevov, and it is a little difficult to catch the exact shade of association which sug- gested it. The literal meaniug is " to rearrange furniture :" and the word is perhaps chosen because this step is prepara- tory to the real business in hand, since names are the fur- niture or utensils (o-Kevrj) of thought. Cf. Rep. 7, 540 e : 81a- crKevcopr]o~ovTat. ttjv eavraiv itoXiv. 9. enipeXeiav] The word is used technically by Aristotle, Pol. VII. 14 '. o~xe86v 8r/ iravra ravra avpfiaivei Kara plav inipe- Xeiav. 10. TavTT)v] Sc. ttjv ovtco pera- vopao~pevr]v (^e7ripeXrjTi.Krjv) re^vrjv. nOAITIKOS. 77 jff6. HE. 'Hi re roy ^etof eu> 7rof 8ieiX6p.e6a vop.ea XCt>/3i? KOa TOi/ avOpWTTLVOV eiT ip.eXr\Tr\V . NE. SO. 'O/D&Sff. HE. Av0i 8e ye ttolXlv eTra.vop6ovp.evoi, KaOdirep ehrov, ttjv av0pa>7rlvr)v e7rip.eAr)TiKr)v 8t)(a Sicupcop-eOa, 1 TW fiialcp T€ /ecu eKOvaiw ; NE. 20. I1gu>i> /zeV ovv. HE. Kcu T?)y /xeV ye irov tcov fiialcov TvpavviKrjv, tyjv 8e eKovaiov kcu eKovaicov SlttoSoov dyeAcuoKopuKrjv We should have dis- tinguished; first, the Divine Shepherd from the human ruler, and then, the king of a willing people from the tyrant ofunwilling subjects, than which no differ- 1 ence can be greater. I. r Hi re— ASffa fie ye] The correspondence of clauses is not strictly preserved. 4. airove^r]6ii(Tav\ I. e. " As- signed to the human ruler." The word is partly suggested by a false echo from vopea. 6. Tivi eKova-iui] " By what mark of distinction 1 That be- tween the compulsory and the voluntary." Cf. 265 d : ra> o-ykttq) kcu — po>vv\i, alib. IO. evr)8inlvT]u fTTipeXrjTiKrjv] " The human art of superin- tendence" as distinguished from the Divine. 18. ttjv tcov fiiaicov] " The superintendence of the violent." The genitives fiiatcov and €kov- o-icov are different, the former pointing to the rulers, the latter to the persons ruled. 1 9. 7-171/ fie — £aa>v] "That tend- 78 nAATONOS But this is not all. Even with the cum- brous help of our " great fa- ble" we have only obtained a shadowy outline of our subject (johidp 7rpoa€i7rui>Te? noXiTiKrjv, tov eypvTa av Teyvi-jV p« i\ TavTrjv kou eiripeXetav ovtois ovtol fiacriXea kou ttoXl- TLKOV U7TO(f)aLl'(Of.l€0a \ NE. 20. Kai Kivdvvevei ye, do £eve, reAeW p. 2; sav rjixlv ovtco? e\eiv 1) irep\ tov ttoXltlkov oltto- Seitjis. HE. KaAeoy av, co ^coKpare?, rjpiv eyou. Set 8e firj ao\ fiovcp Tama, dXXa KapLoi fxera aov Koivfj ijvvooKelv. vvv 8e Kara ye ttjv e/JLi)v ovtto) (fyaiveraL lorekeov 6 fiaaiXevs r\plv a\y)pa eyeiv, aXXa KaOairep avSpiavTonoio), irapa KOLLpov ev'toTe CT7rev8ovTes TrXelco kou p.el£cQ rod SeovTOs eKacrTa twv epycov €7re/x/3aAAo- ixevoi fipadvvovcri, kou vvv rjfiei?, tva 8r) 7rpb? Top b Taxy kou fxeyaXoTrpeiru)? SrjXaHJoupev to ttjs 1 €/x- ibTrpoaOev ap.apTr\pa Sie^odov, tw fiaaiXel vofilcravTe? ance of animals in herds whose principle is voluntary and whose subjects are bipeds hav- ing free will." 8. Koivrf] Cf. supr. 260 b : tovtov toivvv (tov OfXOVOe'lv) p.1- Xpmep av avToi Koivcova>p.ev, eariov to. ye rav ciXXoov 8o{-dvpaTa ^m- peiv. 258 c : tovto fjht) aov, oifxai, to epyov, S £eve, «XX' ovk etiov yiyverai. 3. Aei ye iir)v — avTo eivai Kai aov. 9. Kara ye tt)v ep.r)v\ Cf. Phileb. 41 b. 1 1 . ir\eia> v epyoiv] Badh. conj. to epyep. But there is no need of change if the words are taken alternately, as often in these dialogues, and Bpadw. be transitive : — Bpahvvovo-iv e<- acrra twv epyonv entfiBaWofievoi pelfa Kai nXeco Toil deovros. If this is thought harsh, I should prefer to read eKao-rois. inepfiaWoixevoi ] " Throw- ing in additional material." Cf. Tim. 51 d : ovt eirl \6yov firjKet. irdpepyov aK\o fj.rJK.os enep.- f3\r]Teov. The middle voice sig- nifies " into their own work." 13. tva npos T(£ Ta^v Kai peya- XoTrpeTTcos] " That not only with speed but with magnificence." 7rpoy tco Ta%i) SC. SijAcoo-at. npos ra raxei would be a more usual expression, but the ad- verb is suggested by the suc- ceeding adverb. 14. to — Ste|oSov] Stallbaum well compares Tim. 39 d: -rrpbs Tr)v tt)<; hiaimvias piprfcrLV (fivo-eoos. lb. 506, Hipp. Maj. 300 c. 15. ftaaiXel] Governed partly by wpe'neiv, partly by noielo-dai. nOAITIKOS. 79 77- irpeirtiv peydXa irapafteiy para iroLeiaOaL, Oavpasnov oyKOV dpd/jL€i>oi tov pvOov, ptifyvL tov 8eouTOf rji>ay- KdcrOrjfjLtv avTOV pepu irpoa^prjaaaOaL. Sib paKpo- ripav tt]v diroSeL^Lv TreTTOLrjKapev kcu itolvtws to pvOco re'Aos- ovk iire^efxev, aAA' aTeyyws 6 Aoyos 5 c rjpuv wcnrep tjuoov rrjv e^codeu pev 7repiypa(f)7]v eoiKev iKavcios e'xew, tt\v 8e olov toi? (pappaKOis kcu rfj avyKpdau to>v xpuipaTcov Ivdpytiav ovk d.7reiXrj- 1. VaVfMHTTOV OJKOV TOV flV- 6ov\ " Taking up in the fable, as it were, a monstrous lump, we have been obliged to use more of it than was good for our purpose." The image of the statuary (or modeller) is continued. But there is also in oyKov dpdfievoi an association from the other meaning of oy- kov aipeiv, to assume a lofty vein. Cf. Soph. Aj. 129 : pijb' oyKov aprjs prjdev. 2. tov (xvdov is a genitive of apposition or of respect. Cf. Protag. 329 a: 8o\ixbv kcito.- Ttivas tov \6yov. 4. ndvTcos] " With all," like the Homeric ep,irr)s. 6. So-nep £a>ov] " Like a pic- ture" of some living thing. The illustration passes from statuary to painting. 7. rfj o~vyKpdo~ti tu>v xpa>pd- rav] " Harmony of colour." Cf. Legg. 6, 768 c: olov vepi- ypa(pr] tls e^coBev Trepiyeypappevr] to. pev e'lprjKe, to S' dnoXeiTrei o~x*86v. lb. d : to 8e 8\ov kcu duplies irepl evos re kcu irdvTcov TOOV KCITO. TT0\lU KCU IToXtTLKrjV •ndcrav 8ioiKr)aeo)v ovk eort yeve- o~dai aacpes, rrplv av t) 8ie't-o8os an clpx*j s T< * Te 8evrepa kcu to. p.eo~a kcu TvdvTa peprj tci eavrrjs dTro\aftovo-a irpbs tc\os cKpUrjTai. lb. 769 b : KaduTvep faypdcpoav ov8ev iripas e\eiv fj irpaypaTeia SoKCL 7tcpl eKCtCTTOV T(OV £&)&)!/, «XX' fj tov xp atvflp 1 dnoxpaiveiv, *j tl 8fj KoXovai to toiovtov ol £a>ypdv Trai8es } ovk civ ttotc pot 8okc'i Travirao-Bai Kocrpovaa, wot' enlboaiv prjKer e'xeiv els to ko\- Xico Te kcu (pavepiOTepa yiyveadai tu yeypappeva. The question, How far is the requirement of artistic proportion appli- cable to philosophical dis- course"? is partly suggested here, and is fully discussed in the sequel. Plato's contempt of the mere artist comes out in the same passage (769 c): evTpipfjs — oi8a- p£>s yeyova ttj Toiav-rp Te'xvrj. A0. Kcu ov8ev ye efiXdPrjs. Com- pare Soph. 234. 8. e'vdpyeiav] " Distinctness." Here, as in Theset. 203 b, the Bodl., with An., has ivepy. — the more familiar word. The word expresses the way in which the parts come out in relief (wore fao\ fipoToi) as the last touches are added to a painting. Aristotle uses the same combination of metaphors to describe the necessary imper- 80 nAATON02 No great tiling can be made clear with- out exam- ples. Even the nature (f)€vm 7rco. ypa(j)r)? 8e koll (rvfiirdcrr}? yeipovpyias p. 27 Ae'£et kcu Aoya) 8rj\ovv irav (wov iiaWov irpeireL tois 8vvapL€vois eweaOac tois <5' aXXois 81a )(€ipovp- yiwv. 5 NE. 2Q. ToVTO p}v OpOcoS' OTTT) 8e 7)pLU OVWU) (pys iKavcos €iprj(r0ai f 81-jXwaov. S*E. XaAe7ro//, co 8aip.6i>i€, fir) Trapa8eLypa.cn xpu>- d fievov iKavcos ev8eLKvvo~6ai tl tcov pLeitpvcov . klv8v- vtvei yap r)p,wi> e/caaros- olov ovap el8cos airavra 10 ttolvt av ttolXlv coaTrep virap dyvoeiv. fection of an Ethical discourse : duv8pcos kcu Timcp TcWrjOes e'vbe'i- Kvvcrdcu — to kci\£)s e\ovra rfj 7repiypaav~\ And therefore human society, which is a liv- ing organism. 3. roh hwapevois] Governed by brjkovv. tols S' aKkois 8ia %eipovp- yia>u] " To the other sort the creatures maybe shewn through works of art." This is a good illustration of Plato's manner of displaying both sides, even when a subject is mentioned by the way, and when one side only is required for his pur- pose. Cf. Rep. 7, 520 e, Legg. 1, 632 d : Tois S' aWois rjplv ov8aucbs Icttl KciTcXpavrj. 7. XaXe7roi/- — ti tcov uei^ovaiv] This remark is preparatory to the example of the art of weav- ing : which, however, is not introduced till p. 279, a di- gression on the nature of Ex- ample being put between. The thought is one of frequent occurrence. Phsedr. 262 c : coy vvv ye yjrikcos 7ra>s \eyouev, ov% e\ovTes lKa.vcnrapa8eiyua.Ta. Soph. 2l8 C— e : oo~a S' av tcov ueyd- Xcov Set Sianoveludai — irpoTepov ev cruiKpols — Sen/ ueXerdv. /3ov- Xet drjra irepl twos tcov cpavXcov ueTiovTfs ireipadcouev napddeiyua avTo 6io~6ai tov pei(ovos ; In the Laws the use of Example is recognized as a necessary preliminary to discourse. 1,632 e : ottcos S' av to 7rpS>Tov S(.e|eX- 8couev, ireipao~6ue6a avTO irapd- 8eiyua de'uevoi Ka\ roXXa ovtco 8iauv8o\oyovvTes irapauvdia ttoit]- aacrdai Trjs 68ov. 9. olov ovap el8cos dnavTa ] Compare Lys. 218 c : kiv8v- vevouev ovap ncnXovTTjKe'vai. Theset. 208 b : ovap S17 — eVXov- Tr)o-auev (" In sleep a king, in waking, no such matter"). A similar feeling appears in Phi- leb. 1 6 b : ov urjv eaTi KaXXicov 686s otiS' av yevoiTO, r/s eyco epa- o-Trjs uev elui del, TroXKaKis 8e ue tj8t] 8iacfivyovo~a eprjuov re Ka\ nOAITIKOS. 81 277. NE. 20. IleSc* tout eiVes* ; S*E. Kal yuaA' aroirods eoiKa ye ev rw irapovTt Kivrjaas to ire pi rrj9 €7naT)]/ir)9 iraOos ev rjp.lv. NE. 20. f / 8rj ; HE. HapaSelyiLiaTOs, a> fiaKapie, av p.01 Kal ro TrapdbeiypLO. avrb deoe'r/Kev. c NE. 20. T7 ovv ; Ae'ye pLrjftev e/xov ye eVe/ca oVo/c^coy. EE. AeRreop, hretdrj Kal av ye eroipLos aKoXovOeiv. tovs yap irov iralBas 'ia/xev, orav dpri ypap-parcov epLTreipoi ylyvcovrai — NE. 20. To iroiov ; aE. Otl tgov arot^eicov eKaarov ev rals fipayy- Tarais Kal paarat9 tcov avXXaftcav iKavcos StaiaOd- vovrai, Kal raXrjOr) (frpd^eiv irepl eKelva Svvarol ^78. yiyvovrai. NE. 20. Ilco? yap ov ; of example, it would seem, is no exception to this rule. We know, then, that 10 children learn to read by being re- ferred from syllables which they cannot spell to others hav- J 5 ing the same let- ters, which they al- ready know. airopov Karea-Trja-ev : with which compare Legg. 2, 654 e : el Se ravd' rjfias 8ia(pvyovTa ol^rjo-eTai. Phsedo 89 b, C : idv uep ye rjpuv 6 Xoyoy reXevTrjUT] kcu jjltj bvvcop.eda avrbv dvafiiaxracrdai. 3. to ivepl rfjj eTrio~Tr]p.r)s ird- 6os~\ Cf. to tjjs 86£t]s ndSos, Theset. 193 d. "After a strange fashion, it would seem, I have now touched upon the expe- l'ience of our minds in regard to knowledge." For the par- ticiple with eoiKa, cf. Xen. Hell. VI. 3, 10 (Passow, Lex. s. v. eoiKa), and for Kivrjaas, cf. infr. 297 C : KlVTjO-aS TIS TOVTOV TOP \6yov. Theset. 163 a : rd 7roAXa Kal aTOira TavTa eKivrjo-ap-ev. 5. IlaoaoVty/iaros] The illus- tration to be drawn presently from boys learning their let- ters is an example of what is meant by Example. 7. fj.rj8ev dwoKvaivJ I. e. Don't be afraid of seeming tedious to me. 9. o-v ye] So also the Bodl. MS., where the omission of ye, noted by Gaisford, is after e'p.ov in the previous line, perhaps caused by Aeye preceding. 13. ev rats fipaxyraTais Kal pdo-Tais tu>v o-v\\a@5iv ] See the same illustration more fully drawn out in Eep. 3, 402 c, where however the notion of syllables is not distinctly present ; Theset. 206 a, 207, 208 ; Phileb. 17. M 82 FIAAT0N02 HE. Tavrd de y€ ravra eu dAAai? diJL([)iyi>oovi>re9 p« 27 irakiv So^rj re \j/ev8ovrai koll Aoyco. NE. 212. Wdvv fJLtv ovv. EE. 'A/?' oi)f ot^ coSe pacrrov /cat KuAAtcrrov eVa- 5 ye^ avrov? hri ra fir)7rco yiyvojaKO/ieva ; NE. 20. ns eHd^afrv) have been shewn 8. nde'vai] Sc. to iv ols 6p- in comparison with all the 6a>s i86£a(ov. things which they do not IO. rrjv uvttjv Ofxoior-qra Ka\ know." There is a slight al- yrjs de\ e^ovaiv. Theset. 207 ', Soph. 259 d. I10AITIK02. 83 17%. S?E. Ovkovv tovto p.ev ikousco? avpetXy(papei>, otl 7rapa.8e1yiJ.aT0s y eo~Ti Tore yevecrts, birorav ov rav- top, ev eWepo) ^Leairaafievco Soljaijopevov 6p6u>s /ecu crvvayOev, irepl emaTepov coy avvdp.(j)w filav aXrjOrj 86ljai> drroTeXfj ; NE. SO. «fWat. 3?E. Qavp.dtpLp.ev di> ovv el tolvtov tovto rj/JLCov 77 ] [enoe it appears that Exam- ple comes into use, when the name element 5 rightly dis- cerned in sometliing else, and brought 2. onorav — aTrore'Kfj^ " When that which is the same in another separate thing, and which is rightly conceived, is brought into comparison, and so effects one true opinion about each of the two things which are thus regarded in one view." 3. biea-TTaa/JLevcp ] Cf. Soph. 2 53 d : fiiav I8eau 8 id noXXav, cvos CKacrrov Keipevov X w I'^ s j ■navTrj 8iarerape'vr]v. 4. avvaxOev] A technical word. Cf. Phaedr. 266 b : tS>v diaipcaecov Kcti <7vvaymya>v. ircp\ cadre pov a>s ? tyap+] Stallbaum is probably right in conj. nas ap—. 15. SXov] The "whole" is often put by Plato for the universal, to which Kara pepos is here opposed as the par- ticular. Cf. Rep. 6, 491 c: Aaftov Toivvv, rjv S' eyco; oXov avTov 6p6ws. Theset. 178 a: el 7rep\ iravros tls rov e'ldovs epcorar] k.t.X. lb. 1 82 b : Kara peprj ovv aKOve. 16. aXXa] Other, as the par- ticular is other than the ge- neral. per a 8e ravra peXXovres — ] " Intending, however, after- wards to bring the same na- nOAITIKOS. 85 279 278. ravra p.eXXovT€?, em to tov fiaaiXem peytaTov ov ravTov eldos air eXaTTOVcov (jjepovre? 7ro0ev, Sea rrapadeiypaTo? hrij(eLpeTv av ty)v tcov Kara ttoXlv Oepaireiav Tiyyr) yvcopl^eiv, tva virap avT bveiparos r)plv yiyvrjTai. ; NE. 20. YIdvv p}v ovv 6p6m. ftE. YlaXiv 8rj top tpirpocrOev Xoyov dvaXrjTTTeov, &)? lireiSr] tco (3ao-iXtKco yc.vet rrjs 7rep\ ra ^coKpares, el per) tl Trpoyeipov eTepov eyoptev, aXX' ovv tj]v ye v(pavTiKrjv irpoeXcopeOa ; Ka\ TavTrjv, el So/cel, per) Trdcrav ; airo^prjaet yap 'laca? r) 7rep\ to. e/c tcov epicov v(paap.aTa' ra^a yap av rjp.lv Ka\ tovto to pepos avTrj? p,apTvprjaei€ irpoaipeOev o fiovXopeOa. NE. 20. Tlyapov; illustrate for us tins poird of method, and pre- pare the way for a more en- 5 lightened view of the States- man's office. Reverting then to what has been pre- IO viously said, that we must try to clear away from the King the crowd of rival artists, we select as an j - example the art of weaving woollen cloth. ture from some lesser subject to bear on the most important nature of the king, and to endeavour — ." The construc- tion is determined by a sort of attraction from the previous participle. I . piyicrrov ov ravrbv ei'So?] Cf. Kep. 4, 435 a : o ye ravrov av tis Trpooenroi peiifiv re Kai eXarrov. 3. rav Kara. noXiv] MaSC. 4. vrrap avr oveiparos] Cf. supr. 277 d. 7. tov epTvpoo-Qtv Xoyov ava- XtjtttIov] P. 268 d : ew? av tovs TrepiKe^vpevovs avra ku\ rrjs avvvoprj? avra avTiTVOLOvptvovs irepuXovres Ka\ x a> pL°~ avTes " 7r ' eVeiVcov Kadapov p.6vov eKelvov a.T;op.ev. Also 275 — 2 7 7- IO. eKeivov] r'ov fiaaiXea im- plied in rw (3acriXiKcp yevei. 14. *TToXlTtKrj*] MSS. TToXlTl- k\]v. The correction occurred also to Ast and Stallbaum. 20. paprvprjaeie Ttpoaipe6ev ] The participle, as in npityei pr)6ev, supr. 269 c, and the like. 86 FIAATQNOS 3E. Tt 8i]Ta ov, KaOanep ev tow ep7rpoa0(v 76- p. pvovTts pe'py peptov eKaaTov 8ir)povp€0a, kou vvv nepl vcpavTLKifv tcwtov tovto eSpdcrapev, kou Kara c 8vvapiv o Tt pdXiara 8lu fipa^etov Ta\v ttolvt eVeA- 5 OovTts iraXiv ijXOopev eVt to vvv xPWipov ; NE. 212. Urn Xeyus ; SE. Avti)v ti]v 8ie£o8ov airoKpLCTLv aoL iroLrj- crofxat. NE. 20. KaXXiaT ehres. io ^E. "Eart to'lvvv iravTa rjpuv biroaa Srjpiovpyov- pcev kou KTCopeda, tol pev eW/ca tov iroielv tl, to. 8e tov pj] 7ida\eLv dpLWTrjpia' kou t&v dpvvTrjplcov rd pcev dXe^KpdppaKa kou Oeia kou dv0pd>7rtva, ra 8e cl TrpofiXrjpaTa' tcov 8e irpofiXrjpdTcnv Ta plv irpbs tov iSTroXepLOv birXicrpLaTa, Ta 8e (ppdypaTa' kou tgov (ppaypaTcov Ta pcev irapair^TacrpaTa, Ta 8e 7rpb? I . Ti ov — ihpdaap.ev ] Cf. Soph. 251 e. Phileb. 54 c. 3. Kara bvvap.LV — Sta /3pax«W] This is fulfilled in the follow- ing sentence, in which the method of dichotomies is ex- emplified as it were in short hand. Perhaps also there is here a sly anticipation of the length to which the illus- tration is allowed to run, which is made the occasion of comment afterwards. 7. AvTTJV TTOll)(TOjXai ] Cf. Soph. 250 a : Treipdaopai 8pav tovto epcoTcov ae KaBcnrep itceivovs tots, \va apa tl kol Trpoicopev. 10. hrjp.Lovpyovp.eu kci\ KT«>p.e6a\ 7T01TJTLK1] and KTTJTLKTj (Soph. 2 I 9) are thus combined. 1 3. d\e£i(pdpp.aKa kol 6ela Km dvdpamLva] Preventives divine and human — in the form of talismans or of drugs. 14. to>v 8e — o-vv8erd] "De- fences from the weather are housing and body-shelter : of the latter sort are mats and envelopments ; which are of one piece or of several. Those of several pieces are stitched or otherwise compacted, of vegetable fibre or of hair or wool : and of these some are felted together with the help of water and earth, while some are compacted of themselves." 16. Trapo.ireTdo-p.aTa] " Cui'- tains — to shut out the view." Hesycll. : TtapaTreTdo-paTa, irapa- K.a\vp.p,aTa. Cf. Prot. 316 e : tols Texvais TavTais 7rapa7T€TU- o-paaip ixprjo-avTO. The word is used also by Herodotus of the Persian hangings found in the tent of Mardonius at Platsea. nOAITIKOS. 87 279. )(€ificdva? kou Kavjiara d.Xe^i]Ti]pia' tcov Se ciXe^ifTrf- picov to. fiev areydafiara, tcl Se o-KeiroxrpoTa' kou tcov aKeiracrfiaTcov inroirtTacr flora fiev dXXa, irepi- KaXvpLfxara Se krepa' irepiK.aXvfifid.Tcov Se to fiev e bXoayio-Ta, avvOera Se erepa' tcov Se avvQercov to. fiev TprjTa, to Se avev Tprjcrecos crvvSeTa' kou tcov aTprjTcov to, fiev vevpiva (fivTcdv eK yr/?, to. Se Tply^iva' tcov Se Tpiyivcov to. fiev vSaai kcll yfj KoXXifTa, to Se avTa. avTois crvvSeTa. tovtolctI 8r) toI? e/c tcov eavTois avvSovfievcov epyaaOelatv dfivvTifpiois koI aKeiracr- fiacn to fiev ovofia \fio.Tia eKaXecra/iev ttjv Se tcov IjiaTLCov fiaXiCTTa eTrifieXovfievrjv Te^vrjv, cocnrep tot€ >• ttjv Trj? 7roXeco9 TroXiTiKrjv etrro/iev, OVTCO Kal VVV TO.V- tt\v irpoueiTTCOfiev air ai>Tov tov TrpdypaTos IfioTL- ovpyiKrjv' (pcdfiev Se kou vcpavTiKr/v, ocrov erri tyj tcov IfiaTLcov epyaala fieyiaTOv rjv fiopiov, /it]8ev Sicupepeiv Protectionw are prophy- lactii defences. Defences are armour and bar- riers. Bar- 5 riers are screens and weather- stops. Wea- ther- are shelter and clothes. Clothes are rugs and integu- ments. In- teguments are of one piece or composite. The compo- site are stitched or otherwise j r combined. Those un- stitched are of 7. The genitive (pvrcov de- pends on ear), which is to be supplied, but at the same time defines more particularly the idea of veipivov, " of fibres, from plants." 9. ro^Toto-t] Several MSS. have Tovroiai : but this is a case Avhere the chorior lectio is preferable. 10. dfivvrripiois ] Cf. Legg, 1 1, 920 e : 01 to. rav &T)p.iovpy£)v (rco^ovres rexvaicnv erepais dpvv- rrjpiois e'pya. 15. ocrov] This can hardly mean " Inasmuch as." In Rep. 1, 328 d, which Ast com- pares (Lex. s. v.), 00-ov is distinctly an accusative of measure, and is answered by TocrovTov, which could not be introduced here without de- stroying the sense. And if so rendered, the words must be understood to anticipate what is brought out afterwards, that weaving is only a part of the making of clothes. This should be kept in the back- ground here. The word al- ludes to what is said above and explained immediately be- low, that only a part of the art of weaving is concerned with making woollen gar- ments. 279 b: Kal ravTTjv, el 8oKel, pr) iracrav k.t.\. This is confirmed by rjv. " At least that very large portion of this art which we saw to be for the making of clothes." ocrov therefore limits the subject of 8t.a(pepeiv. eVi] As in Gorg. 463 c : TCTTapa ravra popia em rerrapaiv TTpdypao-iv, alib. 88 ITAATQNQ2 vegetable fibre or of hair. Those of hair are compacted with ear tli and water, or com- bined of their own substance without such help. These last are called clothing : and the art which tends on these may- be called cloth- making : which dif- fers from the weav- ing of wool, as the King and the Statesman ttX))v ovofiaTi ravT)]? r?/9 IpariovpyiK)]?, KaOanep p. 28 p: KOLKU TOT€ T)]V f3a(TlXlKy]V T?/9 TToXlTLKl^. NE. SO. 'OpOorard ye. 3E. To //era tovto 8rj avXXoyiaojp.eOa, otl ttjv 5 ipaTioov v(f)avTiKi)v ovTco piiOelcrdv tls rd)( dv 'lkolvcos etprjaOaL So^eie, p.rj 8vvdp.evo? ^vvvoelv otl twv pev b lyyvs ijvvepycov ovrrco dicopicrrai, rroXXcov 8e eTepcov ^vyyevcov direp.eplo-6y). NE. 20. YIolcov, eiwe, tjvyyevcov ; to 3?E. Ov\ eowov rots \e)(6a.criv, coy (palvec ttoX.lv ovv -ffeoiKev eiravureov dp^opevov thro TeXevTrjs. el ydp ^vvvoets ttjv olfceioTTjTa, ti)v fxev 8terep.op.ev drr avT-qs vvv Srj, ttjv tcov arpcoparcov avvflecnv, irepi- (3oXf) yropl^ovre^ kou v7ro(3oXfj. '5 NE. 20. Mav0dvco. SE. Kcd pj]V TT)V €K TOW XlVCOV KOU aTTapTCOV KOU C 2. KCLKil r6re\ 259 b, c. See also 274 e. 4. avWoyicraipeda] " Let US reflect." " Let us think, put- ting together what has been said." Or, perhaps, " Com- paring this argument with the preceding." As the definition of the king seemed to be com- plete, at the end of the first series of divisions, so might the definition of the weaver at this point. Yet neither has been distinguished from his greatest rivals. 10. ttoKiv cvv 1"T eoixev inavi- reovj Either cos eomev or inavL- reov elvai seems to be required. 11. dp^opevov drrd reXevTrjs] " Beginning from the end." As in resuming the " gene- alogy" of the Sophist, 226 a, ib. 268. This order is not strictly followed, however, un- less the " end " includes all from Kal tcov CTKeiracrpaTcov downwards. el fjvvvoels ttjv oiKeioTTjTa] Young Socrates' question, Uoicov — £vyyevS>p ; shewed that he had not observed the likeness or kindred, e. g. between eo-drjs and arpcopara. 12. ttjv pev 81eTep.op.ev] pev is answered by kol pr)v. ttjv pev vnoftdkr] ] " We just now cut off from the weaving of garments that of bed clothes, distinguishing them by the one being put under us and the other round. l^.-rrepiftohf) kul v7ro(3o\j}] Supr. vTronerdcrpaTa pev aXAa, nepiKa- \vppara 8e erepa. nOAITIKOS. 89 80. iravTcop, birocra ('pvrwv apri vevpa Kara Xoyov tiiro- \xev, Srjpuovpyiav iracrav a^e/Ao/xe^* ti~jv t av ttlXi-j- tlkyjv afpcopiaafieOa /cat Tr/v rfj rprjaei kou pa(Pfj ^pap.evr)v avvOeaiv, rjs rj irXeicrTr) aRVTOTO/JUKr). NE. 20. Yldvv p}v ovv. \ £jE. Kai Toivvv T7]v twv oAoo-^/crra)^ aK€7racr/id- T(dv Oepcnrelav, StpjuarovpyiKyis, /cat ray tw areyaa- /mx,tcoi>, oaai re kv OLKoSopuKfj kou oXy t6ktovikJj kou d lv a'XXai? reyvais peup.aT(Dv , oaai re 7repl ras KXoirds kou Tas /3/a irpd^eis SiaKcoXvriKa. epya irapeypvrai Teyyai (fipaypLOLTOJV, irepi re yeveaiv e7ri6rjp.aTovpyLas ovaai Rat ras twv dvpcofidroiv wrj^ei?, yo/jKpcoriKiis dirovejx- I. (pvrcov vevpa — e'lnopev\ Viz. in saying vevpiva (pvrav supr. Kara. Xoyou] Following ana- logy. 8. oaai re — yiyvovrai] I. e. oaai re ev oIko8. k. ok. rexrov. are- KTiKai (or o~Teyao~TLKat) yiyvovrai, Kai oo~ai ev aXkais Texv. pGVfi&Tesv crreKT. yiyv. 9. pevpdrav o-TeKTiml] "Hous- ing" is not an adequate trans- lation of o-Teyaa-TiKT), as this includes the damming of rivers and the like : " the art of making wind-and-water-tight." Many of the words in this passage are quoted, with others from the Politicus, by Pollux, Onomasticon 7, 208-10, who adds : etre o-irov8d((L>v e'xprjro rols ovopacrtv, ei're Ka\ prj — Xeyco Se, 81a to ev eviois ra>v ovopdrcov /3iai- orepov xpV°~@ M - IO. ocrai Te — re'xvrjs] "And all the arts which produce pre- ventive barriers, as against theft and violence, such as are the process of lid-making and the fixing of doors, being separate portions of the art of joining." The order is oaai re^vai nape- Xovrai — 8iaKcokvTiKa epya cppaypd- tuv. The genitive of apposi- tion again recals the language of tragedy. This class was not strictly included in the Trapane- rdapara of the previous enume- ration. 13. yopcpcoTiKrjs airovepr)6e1o-8ai popia Texvrjs] Either " set apart as portions of the joiner's art," or " having had assigned to them several portions of the joiner's art." For the latter, cf. infr. 281 c: /xeyuXa Se {^pn) Ka\ acpiaiv avrais cnrovepovcrai. The use of the passive would then be analogous to rriarev- opai ti, " I am entrusted with something" — a trace of which occurs as early as Plat. Ep. I. 309 a : biomcov ri)v vperepav ap- Xr)v iremarevpevos rravrccv pd- Xto-ra. Other instances in which a noun which would have followed the active verb" differed, in aame only. But though the di fini tion is spe- cious, we see "ii re- flection that the ari baa still to be dis- tinguished from those most akin to it. Se- veral kin- dred arts have in- ' deed been parted off, such as the making of bedclothes, of skins, of linen cloth, no riAATONOS and rush matting, of Fi It, of Bhoes, of houses and dams, of lids and doors, of armour, all of which are in- cluded in the cate- gory of defences. The art of magical charms was early re- jected, so that one only art, that of de- fying wea- ther by the production of a woollen ■>]$eurai fiopta T€)(yrj?' rrjv re oTrXoTrouKi-jV (hrtTepo- p. 2> fji€0a, fxeydXr]? kcu iravroias rrj? irpo^XrifxarovpyLKrj^ T/iTJ/ia ovcrav dvvdfitw' kou Sr) kol t?]v payevTiKrjv ttjv irepl to. dXe^KpdppaKa kolt dp^us evdvs enw- e 5 piadpeda ^vpTracrav, /cat XeXoiirapev, &>£ 86{jcufiev av, avri)i> ti-jv ^-jTi-jOeiaav cljxvvtlk^v yeifiwvwv, ipeov irpo- /3A?}/xoctos > epyao-TiKijv, ovop.a hi vtyavTLKrjv M^Ouaav. NE. 20. "Eot/ce yap ovv. SE. 'AAA' ovk earl tt(o reXcof, co ttou, tovto Xe- voXeypevov. 6 ydp ii> dpyjl T V? T ^ v ipaTtcDV ipyaaia? dirTOfxeuos tovvclvt'iov v(j)r) Bpav (patveTai. NE. 20. Um ; P- 2 SE, To plv tt)s v(prJ9 avfnrXoKi] tls earl wov. in the dative case is made the subject of the the passive verb, are Legg. n, 925 e: robs «rt- TdTTUpiVOVS. lb. 926 a: Tols VOflO- BeTovptvois (masc). lb. 937: eav c7nou twos, ovs ivrovovs re kol viro£d)pa.Ta Kcii vevpcov €7Tlt6vovs piav ovaav v BlolXvtlki). NE. 20. To irolov By ; HE. To r^s* rod ^aivovros Teyyys epyov. ?) tyjv ^avTLKi]v ToXjja]aofiev v(f)ai>TLKr)i> koll tov ^dvrrjv tv? bvTa v§avTr)v KaXeiv ; NE. 20. OvdcLfAW. HE. Kat /,i?)z/ r?/i> ye av aTy/iovo? epyaariK^v koll KpOK-qs ei TL9 v(j)avT lio)v 7rpocrayop€veL, irapdBo^ov re b koll \j/evSo? ovofia XeyeL. NE. 20. Has yap ov ; HE. Tt 5c'; Ki>a(j)€VTiKr)i> avparaaav koll tt)i> txKecTTLKiiv irorepa p.i]BejJLLav eiTLpeXeLau firjBe tlvol OepojKelav eaOrJTO? dtofxev, i] koll ravras irdcras d)S vcpavTLKCL? Xe^ojiev ; NE. 20. OvSa/im. HE. 'AAAa fXTju tt]9 ye Oeponrelas dp.(f)La(3y]Ti , j- (tovctlv avTOLL ^vparao~aL koll rr}? yeveaecDS TYjS TCDP ipLoiTLGiv rfj tyjs vTLKr}? SuvdfieL, [xeyLcrrop \xlv fiepos eKelvrj BLBovaaL, fieyaXa Be kou a(pl(TLi> clvtqus throvip-ovaaL. c NE. 20. TLdvv ye. nairn . would bi in to be left. The defini t inn, how - 5 ever, is not yet com- plete. Other pro- cesses be- sides weav- ing are engaged in the making of cloth. io Forcarding is not com- bination but^ divi- sion. Nor are spin- ning and weaving to be con- . founded. Once more, fullini'; and daruing are processes concerned with cloth, from which weaving must be 20 distin- guished. Here are several rival arts, whose land- marks must 2. To 8e ye — SiaAvTiK)';] Sc. to 8e ye ev apxfl rrjs to>v Ipdncov epyaaias bpaspevov earn irpa^is 8iaXvTLKr]. 1 3. Kvav Kai larpovs ovdev iravei. Soph. 227 a. 1 6. vfpavTLKas ] Cf. Gorg. 450 b : ti Sjj 7TOT6 Taj aXkas re^vas ov p)]TopiKcis KaXe'is, ovo~as rrep\ \6yovs, einep tuvttjv prjro- * piKijv KaXets, f] av 17 nep\ \6yovs ', 17. Ovdapobs] Sc. vCpavTiKas. Only the latter half of the question is answered : hence Socrates calls attention to the former part, with aX\a pljv — ye—. 18. rijs — depctnelas ] For the construction without nepi, cf. infr. 275 b, 279 a, Phileb. 2 2 C : tujv VLKr]TT]plcoj> ovk ap- v tpyaXeiaiv p. 28 28 ftilfxiovpyovs Ttxyas, 81 d>v diroTtkeiTai ra tt)$ vcjyrj? epya, SokcIu \pr) to ye crvvairlas elvai irpocrivoir)- oaaOai ttclvtos v(f)ao-paT09. 5 NE. SO. 'OpeSrara. SE. Ylorepov ovv i)puv b irep\ tyjs vfyavTiKrjs Ao- yos, ov irpoaXopiiOa fiepovs, 'iKavm earat Suopio-- /levo?, lav ap avrrju rwv i7rip.eXeta)V, biroaai irepi Ti)v epeav icrOrJTa, eh rrjv KaAAi(TTr)v kou fxeylaTrjv 2. 81 Z>v\ Sc. epya\elu>v. 3. to ye — TTpoo~noit]crao~6ai\ " Lay claim to be at least co- operative causes :" cf. dpcpicr- j3r]Tr]crovaiv supr. 7. ov 7rpoei\6pe&a pepovs] An explanatory limitation. " The art of weaving, that part of it which we selected:" supr. 279 b : tovto to pepos avTrjs irpoai- p(6eu. The second noun limits the first, with which it is in apposition : as in such expres- sions as ol 'Adrjualoi ol (TTpaTr]- yoi in Thucydides. 8. onoo-ai — Ti6£>pev~\ The reading of most MSS., els tt]v Ka\\io-Tr)v, is sufficiently de- fended by Soph. 235 a (where see note) ; Tim. 57 e : klvyjo-iv be els dvcopa\6TT]Ta del Ti6cbpev. Legg. 867 b : els e'lKova ttov 6a>p.ev. For the omission of the substantive verb after ottoVos, which frequently hap- pens, cf. infr. 285 a : ■ndvG' onoaa evrexva. The Zurich editors read elcri, which is found in Flor. i. The Bodl., with A, has els yrjv. 9. els Ttjv KaWicTTrjv kciI pey'ia- ttjv Traaa>v ] This recals the example by which the last hypothesis concerning know- ledge in the Thea±tetns is il- lustrated (p. 207 d): to exav n o~t]pelov elnelv a> tcov uttuvtcov 8ia(fiepei to epcoTapevov — oinv rjAiov irepi iKavov oipai o~oi etvat awohe^acrQai on to \apnpoTaT6v eo~Ti tuv Kara tov ovpavuv Iovtcov ■nep\ yrjv. Since that definition was given, the argument of the "Sophist" has intervened. We now see that it is not enough to describe the sun as diffident in brightness from other hea- venly bodies. These other bodies, which are not the sun, have a nature of their own, which is defined by and de- fines their difference from the sun. I do not know the sun, or any other thing, therefore, until I have determined the exact limit between each of these other natures and the one in question. Comp. Legg. 6, 768 d : to 8e oXoi> Ka\ d*pt/3es nepl evos re kol iravTav tcov Kara ttoXiv Kai 7roXiTiKTjv ovk etrri yi- yveo~6ai aacpes k. t. X. Parm. 136 b, C : nep\ otov av del imodfj cos bvros Ka) ovk 'ovtos Kai otlovv n'XXo nddos Tido-)(OVTOS, 8el (tko- •ne\v tu {-vpftaivovTa 7rpos civto Kai npos ev eKaaTov t5>v aXXcov, o ti av TtpofKji K.r.X. nOAITIKOS. 93 zSi. iraacov TiOcopev ; rj XeyoLjxev /lev av tl dXrjOe's, ov "• fxrjv aa(j)is ye ovBe TeXeov, irpiv av kol t auras avrr/? waaas TrepieXodfiev ; NE. 20. 'Opdm. HE. Ovkovv /xera. Tavra Troiryreov o Xeyo/xev, "iv ecpefjij? rj/jLii> 6 Xoyo? trj ; NE. SO. nwy 5' ov; HE. Tlpcorov p.ev to'lvvv Bvo Te^yas ovaas 7repi iravTa to. Bpwpteva Oeaacofieda. NE. SO. TLvas ; HE. Tt)j> /xeV r?;? ye^ecreco? ovaav ^vvatTLOv, rrjv B> avrrjv air lav. NE. 20. nw ; HE. ' Oaai pev to irpayp.a avrb ptrj BrjpiovpyovaL, e rah Be BrjiuovpyovaaLs opyava 7rapao-Kevd{pvcriv, cov pLrj irapayevopievwv ovk av wore epyaaOelrj to 7rpoaT€Tayi±evov eKaaTj] twv Teyycov, ravTa? fxev i^vvaiTLOvs, tcls Be avTO to wpaypta direpyafypLevas aiTias. NE. 20. "Ex« yovv Xbyov. HE. Mera tovto Brj Ta? p.ev irepl re arpaKTOvs Ka\ KepKtBas K.a\ birbaa aXXa opyava ttjs irepl tol a/KpieapLara yevearem KOivcovel, Tracras ^vvairlov? plete until all these have been parted off. "We must not be con- tented with saying that 5 it is the noblest of the indus- tries which have to do with wool- len cloth. First, then, we may draw a uui- versal dis- tinction between productive and admi- nicular arts ; and then apply this distinc- j j. tion to the case in point. Washing, mending, and other furbishing of clothes, carding, spinning, •20 and the other em- ployments operosce Minerva included underwool- 2. 7rph av] So all the MSS. except 2Y. aS is suffi- cientty in point : and for the omission of au (more common in tragedy), cf. Tim. 57 b : irp\v — iK(pvyfjs, where there is no good reason to suspect the text. 8. 8vo — Texyas] The dis- tinction between cause and condition, which is the essen- tial point in this part of the argument, is also stated in Phfedo 99 a, b ; Phileb. 27 a; Tim. 46 c, d. 2 2. rrjs nepl ra apcpucrpaTa yeueaecos] Cf. Soph. 25 1 c: rrjs nepl (ppovrjaiv KTrjaecos. " All the instruments that share in the operations for producing clothes." 94 IIAAT0NQ2 working, are pro- arts, €L7ro)/ji€i>, rets Se avra OepoLTrtvovaas kul Sijpiovpyou- p. »j era? ahta? ; NE. 20. 'OpOoTara. HE. T&>i> cuTicov drj ir\vvTLKr)v p,lv koll aK€(TTiKr)i> p. 282] 5 /cat iraaau ti)v irepl ravra 6epairevTiKr)v, iroXki]^ ovarj9 Trj? KoaprjTiKrj? rovvravOa avrf/s popiov, et/cos* pdXiara irepikapfidvtiv ovopdfyi'Tas irav rfj re^vy rfi KvacpevTiK?). NE. 20. KaAwy. [o ££E. Kai )U?)i> * fjavriKrj* ye koll * vrjcrTiKr)* Kal iravra av ra 7repi ttjv ironqaiv avrr/v rrjs i(j6r)T0v rjpepcov, supr. 265 b. 5. TroWr/s — jx6piov~\ Appo- sition. The genitive is not absolute, but is resumed in avTTjs because of the interven- tion of the participle. See Theagt. J55 e, and note. 7. irepihaixfiaveiv — KvcKpevTixfi] The dative is governed by 7repiXapj3dvet.v, which 6vopd£ovras explains. Cf. Soph. 225 a : ra> — a-wpart 7rpos crcopara yLy- vopeva — ovopa Xeyeiv ri toiov- tov riBepevovs olov (Hmutikov. Phsedr. 273 e ; Theset. 148 e ; Soph. 226 e. The accusative ttuv depends on the participle and the infinitive taken toge- ther. nap] Agreeing with popiov, and of course including nXwri- Krjv, aKea-TiKrjV k.t.X. 10.* gaVTLKl)* *VT](TTIK>]*~\ MSS. ^avTKrjv — vrjariKrjv. The correc- tion is due to Stephanus. II. rjs Xeyopev] Sc. rr/s {peas. I 2. pla tls eari re^i"]] " Form a single art which is one of those universally acknow- ledged, that of working in wool." Cf. Legg. 7, 805 e: KepKt'Scoi/ ap%eiv koX ivao-qs raXa- aias. iari follows the num- ber of the nearest word, and is also assisted by the neuter plural peprj. Cf. infr. b, irav tovto, and 284 e, 288 d: Xpv- o~6v re Kal apyvpov Ka\ rrdvB' oirocra peraXXeverai K.r.X. Kal en cpXoi(TTi.Krj — Kal ov nepl TTjV nOAITIKOS. 95 282. NE. 20. Ilwy ydp ov ; h S*E. T?)y 87) TaXaaiovpyiKrjS 8vo Tp^pard icrrov, kcu tqvtoiv tKarepov apa 8volv TrecfjvKarou riyvatv fiiprj. NE. 20. n«? ; S*E. To /X€f ^OLVTIKOV KCU TO Tl}9 K€pKL (ppd^etu Trjs re raXaaiovpyla^ avrrjs €(ttl 7T0V, kou peydXa rive Kara, irdvra i]plv rjar-qv T€)(ya, tj avyKpiTiKT] re kou dtaKpiTiKr] — NE. 20. Na/. Now of wool work- ing there are two chief kinds, each falling 5 under one of the two great cate- gories of division and compo- sition. Carding and one use of the 10 comb be- long to wool-work- Gr\pav 7TVpevTiKi)v prjdijvai crvp.- fJefirjitev. The Stranger loves to parade the commonness of his examples. For the genitive, cf. Rep. IO, 615 d : ideaaop-eda — Kal tovto tS)v 8eiva>v 6ea.pa.T00v. An art acknowledged by all men is distinguished from one for which a name has to be invented, such as 8o^op,iprjTiKr) in the Sophist. 3. toutoiv eKarepov — Tre(pvi ; X. KpaTijpes elo-iv, av8pos ev^eipos Tiyyr], hv KpaT epe^ov kcu Xafias up.cpio'To- p-ovs. Ejusd. Track 750-755 : od' elpne — uktt) tis — eaTiv, ev8a j3a>p.ovs opl^et. — ov viv — eo-el8ov. 9. rjo-Trjv] " There are two comprehensive arts of univer- sal application, with which we are familiar." Cf. Soph. 228 e : eyeveadrjv. lb. 258 C : r)v Te ical earn. Compare the frequent use of the perfect : e. g. vev6p.tKa Soph. 227 a, 228 a, 265 d, infr. 293 b. 96 nAATONOS tag and nev) all the parts of division which we found there (rjv avrodi, sc. iv avrfj), separating the art into two halves, distinguished by composition and division." MSS. pericopev. No attempt is made to " follow up " (p.e- rUvat) the divisions of Siaicpi- tlkt]. Probably therefore for fieriafiev we should read p.e6i- S>p.ev or fieda>p.ev, as Hermann has already seen. The present tense agrees better with rifivov- res, which is in immediate construction with it. The pres. subj. occurs Phileb. 62 d : p,edi£>. It is surprising that Dr. Badham should prefer p.€Trjpev to this. Cf. Soph. 267 b : to S' a\\o TTav d(pwp,ev p,a- XaKicrdevTes — p.ede[ada>. 13.T6 avyKpiriKov Siaiperiov] " You must again, Socrates, divide the part which belongs at once to combination and to wool-working." nOAITIKOS. 97 t83. ovpyiKov ajxa popiov, co ScoK/jares", SiaipeTe'ov, etirep " 'lko.vcos pteXXopev rrjv irpoppydelaav vtyavTiKrjv al- p-qaeiv. NE. 20. Ovkovv xpr). 3^E. Xpr) /xeV ovi>' kcu Xeywpev ye avTrjs to pev elvai arpeTTTiKov, to 8e o-vpirXeKTiKOV. NE. 20. 'A/)' ovv pavdavco ; SoKei? yap pot to 7repl tttjv tov o~Tr)p.ovos epyaalav Xeyeiv o-TpeirTiKov. HE. Ov jjlovov ye, dXXa kcu KpoKrjs. y yeveaiv ao~Tpo(f)ou Tiva avTrjs evprjaopev ; NE. 20. OvBafim. aE. Atopiaai 8r} kcu tovtolv eKctTepoW '/crco? yap e o 8iopio-pLo? eyKatpo? av ctol yevouro. NE. 20. Ufj; HE. Tfjde. twv 7rep\ ^avTiKrjV epycov pr\Kwdev re Kai cryov ttXcctos' Xeyopev elvai KccTaypcd tl ; NE. 20. No/. HE. Touroi; Srj to pev wrpaKTCp re crTpa(pei> kcu o-Tepeov vrjpa yevopevov OTr}p.ova pXv r)v ™Tivofr KpoKOvrjTiKrjV (f)a>[Aev. NE. 20. 'Opdorara. SE. Kcu f±r)V to ye ttjs vtyavTiKrjs fiepo? o Trpov- OefxeOa, hovt'i irov hr\\ov rj^ij. to yap crvyKpiTiKr}? p. 28 I. aira] Sc. ra tcivtijs Ttjs (TV<7Tpo(f)rjs (viz. rrjs vr) avTwv o Aoyos yfjuv, oi/jloli, yiyvopevos opOoos av yiyvotTo. NE. 20. TtW ; 5 SE. M^/couy re Trept /ecu (3paxvT7]TO? kcu 7rdar)9 v7r€po)(r)? re Ken tAAelxf/eois. rj yap irov perprjTLKT] d 7repl ttolvt iarl ravra. NE. 20. Nat. SE. AceAoopev tolvvv avri]v Svo pepr/' 8e7 yap 8r) io7Tp09 O VVV CnT€V(!)OfJL€l>. NE 20. Aeyois av rrjv diaipecriv 07rr). SE. Tjjde' to fiev Kara r-qv irpos aAArjAa p.tye- Tavrrj Set hit epov re /cai aov t6v \6yov inaivt6r]vai, cos to. heovra €ipr]KOT0i TOV TT01TJT0V, dXX' OVK ineivrj fxovov, ort o~a(pr) /cat arpoy- yv\a /c.r.A. 5- Mtjkovs re 7rept — e'XXet\^ecos] For an application of the fol- lowing idea, cf. Legg. 4, 719 d : ovaiqi yap rcKprjs Tr]s nev VTTepjSe- (3\r]ix€vr)s ttjs oe eWenrovarjs Tr)s Se p-erpLas. lb. 722 a : ret yap /3e'Xrtora, uAV ov ra (3paxvTciTa oboe ra prjKrj TLprjreuv. Tim. 82 a : to tu>v voaa>i> odev ^vviaTarai, 8r)\6i> 7rov /cat iravTi yrjs 7rvpos v8aT0S re /cat depos, tovtcov f] irapa (pvaiv 7rAeove£ta /cat eVSeta. Theaet. I 7 2 e : /cat 81a pav rj (3paxeoiv pe'Aet ouSev Xe'yeip, av p.6vov ru^cocrt row 6W0?. 6. 77 yiore 37E. 'Ap ov Kara (Pvcrii> SoKel croi to fxeitpv i£ Much. fjLr)8evbs eTepov $eiv fxeitpv Xeyetu 77 tov cXolttov oy, 5 c koll tovXclttov av tov fieitpvos eXuTTOv, aXXov <5e /jLi]8ei>6? ; NE. 20. ,r Epoty€. aE. TV fie ; ro Tr)i> rou fxeTplov (fyvcriv vnep- itself to a reader of the So- phist, where the Koivcovia chiefly spoken of is the mutual com- munion of ideas. Compai-e with this whole passage Phajdo 100, 10 1. Note that to pel&v = to peye'dovs kolvcovovv irpbs to e'XaTTOv. And to eXaTTOV = to aplKpOTTjTOS KOiVCOVOVV ITpOS TO p.a.£ov. 1. to 8i — oho-iav\ These words are meant to be enig- matical, like the definition of rhetoric as ttoXitikijs popLov ei'ScoXoi/ in Gorg. 463 d, or as ttjs tcov e7ra>8S)V Texvrjs popiov in Euthyd.289e. (dvaTravXaydpTrjs crnov8rjs yiyverai eviore f) Traibid, Phileb. 30 e.) But they are less clearly explained in what follows. They seem to be connected with the assertion that a standard is necessary to the existence of the pro- ductions of art (infr. 284 a, b), and may probably be ren- dered " according to the other- wise impossible existence of production." avayKaiav is then used in the same sense as in Rep. 2, 369 e : e'lr] §' av rj dvay- KaioTaTr] noXis in TeTTapav tj irevre dv8pa>v. " A city could not possibly consist of less than four or five men." And ye'veo-is is a general word for the ope- rations of all the arts. Cf. Soph. 235 e, Phileb. 27 a. Compare Legg. 10, 903 d : KaTu. bvvap.iv ttjv ttJs Koivrjs yeve- o-fws. I. e. " So far as it was possible that both should be combined." Translate, therefore — " I divide the art of measur- ing in the following way. One part is determined by the fact that things partake of great- ness and smallness relatively to each other : the other by this, that without it the exist- ence of production would be impossible." A similar verbal use of the word oio-la occurs immediately below (e, oio-las) and in p. 285 b : yevovs twos ovcriq. The meaning of this passage will appear more clearly on comparing Phileb. 25 d, 26 c. 9. Tt hi; — dya6o\ ;] " But, again, shall we not say that there is really found that which exceeds or is exceeded by the nature of the Meet, in words, or, if so be, in deeds, and that herein consists the 102 IIAATQN02 fiaXXov koll virepfiaXXopevov vtt avrys Iv XoyoLS eire p. 28 koll eV tpyois dp ovk av Xe^opev coy ovtw yiyvo- p.€i>oi>, Iv cp kcu Siacjje'povcTi paXLura i]p.cov ol re kukoi kcu ol ciyaOol ; 5 NE. 20. , aAA' ov\ cb? tyap.c-v apTL 7T/>09 aXXrjXa povov dew, aAA' cocnrep vvv elpr)- tcu paXXov rr\v p\v irpos clXXtjXol Ae/creW, rrjv 8 av loirpos to perpLOv. ov be eveKa, pLaOeiv dp av (3ov- Xolp.eda ; NE. 20. Tiiirjv; chief mark of difference be- tween bad men and good 1 " Compare Rep. 1, 349, where it is shewn that the good and wise man does not aim at " more" but at " what is meet." "When workmen strive to do better than well They do confound their skill in covetousness." (9.) tov fierpiov cpvo-iv] Com- pare the darepov (piais of the Sophist, the diSios cpvais of the Philebus, and the igaicpvrjs cpv- o~is of the Parmenides. The word cpvo-is expresses the more concrete or determinate con- ception of the Idea. 6. AiTTas apa — 6ereov\ "We must therefore assume that great and small exist and are discerned in these two ways, in- stead of following what we just now said, that one must only- judge or speak of them (Sew sc. Kpipeiv implied in Kplcreis, or perhaps Xeyeiv from supr. d) relatively to each other : instead of this we must speak rather in accordance with what has just fallen from us, of one mode of their existence which is mutually relative, and of an- other which is relative to an ideal standard." The minute- ness of the antithesis, d\\u — obx — dX\a, and the explicit re- sumption of the first clause with the second d\\d, make the sentence rather tortuous, but the meaning is clear. In the words aXXa — Setf the chief pre- dicate is absorbed, as frequently happens, in the relative clause. Cf. Phileb. 54 d : oVep — einou — Seiz/. 10. ov S' epeKa] Plato's dia- lectical subtleties have gene- rally an end beyond them- selves. Here the end is the vindication of the Arts, in order to establish an Art of Eule. Cf. Theset. 184 d : tov U tol eveKa avrd croi BiaKpificofiai. @ov\oip.fda.] The first per- son is used, as more gentle than the second. nOAITIKOS. 103 284. 3?E. Et irpos fiT/Sei* erepou tijv tov /JLeltjovos idcrei Tl? (j)VaiV TJ 77-/90? TOVACLTTOIS, OVK €TiKr]v a(paviovfiev ; awacrai yap al roiavral irov to tov pLCTplov TrXeov Kai eXaTTOv ovx coy ovk ov dXK coy bv \aXeKov irepl Tas irpa^us irapa^vXaT- b Tovari, Ka\ tovtod Srj tw Tpoirco to fitTpov crco^ovaai irdvTa dyaOd Ka\ KaXd aTrepyd^ovTat. NE. 20. T/ fxrjv ; ££E. Ovkovv av TTju TroXiTiKTJv d on the ground that this adj. placed absolutely can only mean " difficult to ob- tain :" and conjectures x a ^ e7r ^s napajcrei — earai Trore] It has been thought that this passage is seriously cor- rupt : but when 6 ti (or 6) is rendered as a pronoun, and either nai introduced before /j.el£uv, with six MSS., or re read for ti (or ri ti, with Hermann), the words as they stand give a better meaning, and one more suited to the context, than any which it has been proposed to substitute. " That some day there will be need of that which has now been mentioned" (the proof that "more" and "less" are relative to a standard of right measure as well as to each other, supr. b) "for the demonstration of the highest problem of all." (o.vto TCLKpifiis is that absolute prin- ciple which is essential to and identical with perfection of method. Cf. i Ale. 130 d: avro to avro). " But (to dwell only on) what is fairly and sufficiently shewn for our pre- sent purpose, this argument, I think, comes grandly to our aid, that we must alike believe in the existence of the arts, and at the same time (ap,a), in a greater and less being measured, not only in relation to each other, but with a view to the production of the mean. For if the latter is true the former is true (for eiceiva, cf. Theset. 207 d, avra, and note), and if the former exist, the latter is the case ; and if either is not, neither will ever be." This explanation is substan- tially the same as Stallbaum's. It appears from the Philebus that the absolute standard (jueVpoi/) was closely allied in Plato's mind with Reason and the Idea of Good. The de- monstration of the " very ex- actness of truth" is probably reserved for the " Philosophus." Even in the dialectical dia- logues Plato complains of an imperfect method. For n almost = o, = " a thing which," cf. Gorg. 508 d: 6 fi« Sij ep.bs, Bans TroXKaKis p.ev fj8r) e'lprjTai ovSev 8e KmXvei /cat en \eye- adai ov (jirjui K.r.X. The in- definite relative is used be- cause the antecedent is only determined as the sentence proceeds. " But as for that which," &c. And for the clause in apposition, cf. Theset. 158 b : 6 TroWdias. infr. 293 a. A similar looseness of con- struction occurs in Gorg. 454c: dXX' tva \xt] 6avfjLa.crr]s — onep yap \eya> k.t.X. For the notion of a.KpL$eia, cf. Rep. 4,435 c-e, 504. Comp. esp. with npos ra vvv, 435 d : tcov re irpoeiprjp,ev(i>v d£iws. 5°4 D : T ® v — efnrpocrdev eiYopevas dnodei^ets. For nep\ avro TaKpifih, cf. Rep. 7, 525 a: f] Tvep\ to ev p,d6r]o-ii. The Bod- leian has SeiKWTai, with most other MSS. The distinction here brought out obviously resembles and may have suggested that drawn by Aristotle in Eth. Nic. II. between the absolute and re- lative mean. But what is absolute in Aristotle is rela- tive in Plato. Aristotle's nXeov, eXctTTOv, kclt avrb to this in ;i harder piece of work than that. 106 IIAATON02 We may content ourselves for the pre- sent willi I lie indirect proof, that if inoiv and Less are not i lnis mea- sured with reference to what is meet and proper, no art can ever exist. Hence we may pro- ceed to di- vide the art of mea- surement, making one seg- ment to consist of 7T€pi avrb TUKpifie? uirbtieL^iv. o tl de irpos ru vvv kclAoos koll lkuvco? SeiKwrai, — Sokzl poL $or)6eiv /xe- ya\eiyei o \6yos, els to opolms eivai ttjv re ^v)(r}V rjpcov irp\v yevea6ai rjpas kuI ttjv ovaiuv r\v S17 av vvv Aeyets-. A direct proof of the existence of such a standard is still to seek. But it is enough for our purpose that no art can exist without it. pel£6v ti apa Kal eXaTT0v\ " There is a greater and less whose measure is not merely relative." I. e. This is one kind of "greater" and " less." But perhaps na\ should be re- jected and re read for ti. Cf. Theaet. 195 e : Xi6 , olopevoL 8rj tl 285. aotyov (ppcttJELv iroXXol tcov KopL\j/cou Xeyovaiv, coy apa peTprjTLKT] Trepl ttolvt ecrrt tcl yiyvop,ei>a, tovt clvto to vvv XtyOlv ov TvyyavtL. pLeTprjaecos pev yap Sr) TLva Tpoirov ttolvO* birocra evTtyya pteTelXr/cpe' Slol t. Taxvrr]Tas] The Bodleian, with A EII 2, has iraxvTrjTas, cf. infr. 299 e, where the intro- duction of Traxe(TLV would be more intelligible than of na- XvrrjTas here, but the MS. au- thority is slight. The tran- sition from solid quantity to speed is less obvious and more Platonic and philosophical than that from depth and breadth to thickness : and density (which Stallbaum speaks of) can hardly be in question. See the connexion between solid geometry and astronomy (o>s (popav ovcrav jiadovs) in Rep. 7, 528 foil. See esp. 529 d: t£>v S' aKrjdLvuiv iroXii c'vdeiv, as to bv rdxos kcu r) ovo~a (3pa8vTi)s iv tg> d\rjdt,va> dpiBpca Ka\ ttclo-l to'is akrjBivols cr^jj/iacri (popds re Trpos a'XA^Xa (peperai Kcii tci ivovra (pepei. Where the distinction of the two kinds of astronomy is essentially analogous to that suggested here. Also Legg. 7, 820 sqq., 10, 896 d : prjKovs o-a>pd~cov Ka) n\drovs kcu ftddovs kci\ pcSfJLYjs. 4. dnaiKicrdr]] " Have removed their abode" — as to a safe dis- tance from evil. The word seems to have been adopted by the Pythagoreans. See Mullach. Pyth. Fr. p. 537 : ov pav\ Evi- dently the Pythagoreans, who are spoken of in similar terms in Gorg. 493 c : Kop\j/os dvrjp, icrcos 2iKe\6s tls rj 'ItoKckos. Crat. 405 d : 6Vt TavTa ndvTa, as (paaiv 01 Kop^rol nep\ povcriKijv kcu daTpovopiav, appovlq rivt tto- Aei apa ttuvtu. 11. to vvv \ex6ev] That there could be no yevecns without the p(Tpiov, which is the first em- bodiment of to peTpov, cf. Phileb. sub. fin. and 55 e. 12. did 8e to pi] TrepiftdXrjTai] " But from never having been habituated to distinguish every subject of inquiry according to real forms, they not only jumble indiscriminately, from a notion that they resemble each other, these widely different things. which mea- sure the size and lllllllltlT of obj >■' 1 in relation to each other, and one of those which measure with refer- ence to a mean or standard. This is the truth which underlies the doc- trine that "all is measure- ment." r 2 108 FIAATQN02 But, for want of the power of distin- guishing kinds, the authors of this doc- trine con- fuse the More and the Too Much, and elsewhere distinguish inoppor- tunely. Whereas one ought not to rest short of any real dis- tinction, or oe to fir) kclt etSrj avveiOlaOai (TKOTreiv diaipovfievovs ravra re toctovtov Siafa'povra ^vpfidAAovaiv evOv? eh tolvtov ofioia vofiio-avres, kou rovvavTiov av tov- tov Spaxitv, erepa ov Kara, fitpr) Siaipovvre?, Se'ov, 5 qtclv /lev Ti]v tcov iroWcov tl? irportpov aurOrjTai Koivcovlav, /ir) 7rpoa(plaraa0aL irptv av Iv avrfj rd? Stafpopas' 'idy Trdcras, OTToaamep iv eldeai Kelvrai, ret? 8e av iravToSairas dvo/iOLorrjTa?, orav iv 7rXr)0ecnv o(f)0cocri, /irj Svvarov elvai dvcrcoTrovfievov iraveaOai, io7rp\v av tjv/nravTa rd oiKela kvros fiias 6fioiOTr)T09 cptja? yevovs rivos ovcrla. 7rept(3d\rjTaL. ravra yueV ovv wavco? irepi re tovtcov kcu 7rep\ tcov iXXelyj/ecov p. 28 but fall into the converse error of distinguishing other things not according to their real di- visions : whereas the right way is, when one has first perceived a common nature running through a great variety of things, not to desist till one has seen all the differences which subsist within that na- ture, and which constitute dis- tinct kinds, and on the other hand, not to be able to look contentedly upon the endless diversity which has been seen in a multitude of objects, until one has brought all kindred objects within the pale of a single resemblance, and invest- ed them with the real nature of a single kind." I . to [xr] Kar' e'lSrj] Cf. Rep. 5, 454 a, Phsedr. 265 e. 5. orav Tn tcov iroKkfov — Koivcaviav] This " divinatio " seems always to be assumed as the first step in a dialectical inquiry. Cf. Phileb. 16 d: piav ibiav nepl nnvTOs €KaTTOTe 6epe- povs Cyre'iV ivpr) 8rj ddpolapaTi avdpanrov re tl- devrat Ka\ \160v k.t.A., and the oyKoi of the Parmenides, 164, 5. This process corresponds to that described in Phileb. 18 a-d. 9. hvo-o)TTovpevov\ " Looking upon with discomfort or dis- like." Cf. infr. 291 b, c. 1 1, yevovs tivos ovcriq] " With the reality (dasein) of a genus." ovo-la is used in nearly the same sense as supra 284 bis. = tco yevos ti elvat. The latter half of this de- scription (from Tas 8i av) is the opposite of the second error mentioned above. nOAITIKOS. 109 185. kou i>7T€p(3oXcov elprjadco' (f)vXaTTO)p,eu 8e povov on omit any c 860 yevrj irepl olvtol e^evprjTai tyjs p€Tpr)TiKr}? kou ralization. a (papev avr eivou pepLUcopeda. observation , by tne way. NE. 20. MepvrjcropeOa. Gramma- Ahi. Mera tovtov or) tov Xoyov erepov irpoaoe- 5 tdonehave j. / /i v , „ -v ' v \ / an end be- ^copeua wept avrcov re rtov (r]Tovp.ei>a)V kou irtpi wot- yond them- S(*l Vt'S err;? 7-779 e^ TO?? roiolarSe Xoyoi? diarpifirj?. that of NE. 20. To 7roio^ ; making gramma rians. So Hp t"' » / e « \ v / nans, oo A£i. -ki rty avepotTO rjpas ttjv irept ypapp.ara the present nquiry hai m end be- yond itf that of d Tore 7rep\ airavra. 15 HE. TV K av vvv r)puv 7} wepl tov woXitikov <> — tlpi-jo-Bai ] 10 riAATUNOS still less is such an art as weaving to be fol- lowed fru- its own sake. But (though few are aw T are of this) the highest things have no sensible mean through which they can be ex- plained, but are shadow- ed forth by Xov ?) tov 7T€p\ irdvra 8iaX€KTiK(oT(pois ylyve- p- 2b aOai ; NE. 20. Kai T0VT0 SvjXoV OTl tov Trtpi iroLvra. aE. 'H ttov tov rr/s vTiKr}8ev tjttov ovbe ti paXXov Tvy\avei peXov. In both cases it is the method alone which gives importance to the particular subject. 6. dAA', olpai, — \eyopeva ] " But I think that it has es- caped most men, that, while some thiugs are endued with resemblances which are sensi- ble, and therefore easily known, which there is no difficulty in shewing, when one wishes to point out any of them (n un- derstood from nepl tov) to any one who asks about it, with no trouble, but easily, without argument, — there are also things, and those the greatest, and of priceless worth, which have no image wrought so as to strike human perceptions, by pointing to which he who would content the mind of an inquirer, shall fully satisfy him by imprinting this on some one of his senses. Wherefore one ought to study to be able to give and receive a rational account of every- thing, for things bodiless, which are the fairest and the greatest things, for the sake of which all that is now said is spoken, are made clearly manifest by reason alone." Cf. supr. 277 c. 7. MSS. aloSrjTiKai. 10. padicos KaTapa6a.v~\ Per- haps pqblois should be read, with Hermanu and Badham. Badham further conjectures ah ovbiv xakiTTov o tl av avTwv tis /3ov\rjdfj tco A. a. — evS(i£a(rdai. But the whole sentence is la- boured and pleonastic, so that there is little cause for omit- ting- an inconvenient word. nOAITIKOS. Ill 86. appoTTOov, LKavcos 1 7rXrjpco(rei- 810 8ei /leXtTous Xoyov €ko,TiKr)i> airebe^dpeOa ftvcryepm, fcai rr]v Trepl analogies which can only be ex- argument. Let us recal the io motive of this digres- sion. It was chiefly to calm the disquiet which we felt at the length to which our 5. pdcov pdXXov 77] Cf. Pl*0- tag. 317 c: nai evXaffeiav tcivttjv oipat j3(\ti(o eKelvrjs eivai, to 6/j.o- Xoyelv pdXXov rj etjapvov eivai. 12. Tavrr/s re — XeyotpevJ The construction is obscured by the attraction of the latter part of the sentence into the relative clause. Strict syntax would require TavTrjs re — kql 7-775 (Svo-^fpet'as) irepl ttjv (paKpo- Xoylav} nep\ ttjv tov tmvtos k.t.X.: instead of which the latter clause, with what follows, is made to depend on dnedegapeda 8vax e pus, with wdiich the re- mainder of the sentence, ewoovv- res — Kal eneTrX^apev k.t.X., is also connected. 13. rjv + irepl + ttjv paKpoXo- yiav] Hermann suggests rjvnep. Wagner, Rheinische Museum, vol. xii. (1857) p. 309, prefers finep. This avoids the, collo- cation of the two accusatives, which is the objection to fjvnep. But fjv is unobjectionable. Cf. Soph. 264 b : ttjp TrpoadoKiav rjv e(pol3i]8r)p.ev, and note. Gorg. 509 C : ravTTjv eivai ttjv ala- xLo~T-qv (Bofjdeiav pf] 8vvao-0ai j8o- r)6elv. Also Legj 666 b ttjv — naididv, *]v toIs dvdpdmois iirinovpov ttjs tov yr]pa>s avarrjpo- rrjTos e8a>pr)0-aTO tov oivov cpdp- pattov. And nepl also may be defended if we suppose a7re- 8ei-dpe8a 8vaxepa>s (sc. ttjv paK- poXoyiav) to be substituted for ibvo-xepdvapev. Such a change in the form of a sentence will not astonish the attentive stu- dent of these dialogues. Plato here seems determined to "bestow all his tediousness" on his critics, whoever they were. fiaKpoXoylav] " Lengthiness in argument," not in speech, as in Gorg. 461 d, alib. 14. dne8e£dpe8a Sucr^epwy (sc. 7-171/ pciKpoXoyiav) is unexpectedly 112 nAATONO^ remarks on weaving, as well as the m\ tliu hich preceded, and the discussion Oil tlie na- ture of the Sophist l had been Bpun : by shewing that length was not lengthinesa unless ex- ceeding what is meet. Tiju tov iravTos dveiXitjiv kcu tyjv tov ao(f)icrTOv p. 281 iripi rr/s tov urj ovto? ovcrias, ivvoovvTes co? ^X e /ii]ko? irXtov, kcu eiri tovtois Sr) iracnv eireirXrj^aptv fjfuv avTois, SeiaavTe? prj irepiepya dpa kcu fxaKpa c 5 Xeyotpev. iv ovv elaavOis prjdev Trct.o-yodp.tv tolov- tov, tovtcov eveKct ttolvtcov tol irpocrOev vcov eiprjaOcu NE. 20. Tolvt ecrTai. Ae'ye e£f}s uovov. HE. Aeyco tolvvv otl ypr) $V fJL€/xvrj/JL€vovs ifJL€ kcu 10 ere tcov vvv elprjuevcov tov re yj/oyov eKtxaTOTe kcu kircuvov TTOieicrOcu fipayyTYjTOS dpa kcu pr]KOvs d>v civ del irepi Xeycop.ev, p.rj 7rpb? aXXrjXa tol p.r\Kr\ Kpi- VOVT€S, dXXd KCLTCC TO Tr)$ peTprjTLKY}? ptpOS, T0T6 e(f>afi€U 8etv pLep.vrja6ai, irpos to irpeirov. d 15 NE. 212. 'OpOm. HE. 06 TOLVVV OvSe 7T/00? TOVTO TTCLVTO.. 0VT€ ydp Substituted for ebvaxepdvapev '. hence the introduction of Trept. 1. dvei\i£iv] Supr. 269 e. Ttjv (sc. fiaKpoXoyiav). tov ao(pi(TTOv 7rept] It is better to take Tre'pi thus with tov o-oqbio-Tov, in which case it can easily be resumed with the explanatory words tjjs tov prj ovtos ovaias. Otherwise the preceding dialogue would be referred to as 6 arocpurr^s, a form of reference which has no parallel in Plato. Cf. supr. 284 b : iv ra o-ocpiaTjj, and note. 6. tovt, kou 8r) Kai Xoyov, av re 7rapLp.r)Kr)9 Xe\6e\s And yet qo< "meet 1 for plea- sure, nor evi n Eor discovery, I. in Eor i be I ml ul dl relopiag tic.-il me- thod and of making is that which is becoming or suitable, not with a view to pleasure, or persuasion, or gracefulness, but to the awakening of reason and the furtherance of truth." Cf. Legg. 2, 655 C : \eyovcri ye ol jrXeio-rot povo-LKrjs opdoT-qra eivai rrju r]8ovi)v rals ^i^ais 7ropi£ovo~av SvvapiV dWa Toi/TO p.ev ovre av- €Ktov ovre oaiov to Tvapdnau (p6ey- yeo-dai. We might be disposed to conjecture navrrj, but wdvTa is used elsewhere adverbially. Soph. 233 a: cos elal Tvdvra ttuv- tTaroi. (16.) ovre yap — \6ya>v~\ "For first we shall have no need of a length that is suitable for pleasure, unless merely by the way : and our argument further enjoins that Ave esteem only as of secondary import- ance that which helps investi- gation and facilitates and hastens discovery, but that we should prize by far most highly, and in the first place, the method itself and the power of dividing according to the real species, and feel an interest in that discourse which makes the hearer more inventive, whether it be brief or interminable alike : more- over, that the man who blames lengthiness (d8o\eo-xiav) in this kind of intercourse, and is in- tolerant of circuitous digres- sions, ought not so cpiickly and all at once to have done when he has blamed the dis- course as long, but should con- sider that it is his duty to shew further that a shorter one woidd have made those conversing better reasoners, and would have improved their power of finding a mode of declaring realities by speech : all other blames aud praises, made with reference to any other stand- ard, our argument bids us dis- regard and to seem deaf to any such remarks." 1. prjKOVS Cipp-OTTOVTOs] Cf. Phileb. 36 d : xa'ipeiv Set \eyeiu Tois ciXhovs prjK((Tiv rj Kai otcoovv twu Ttapa to irpoo-rJKOV Xeyopevcov. lb. 28 d. Rep. 5, 450 b, Legg. 1, 640 a, b. 2. TrXrjv el firj] See Lobeck ad Phrynich. p. 459, who ad- duces Ar. de An. I. 3 : tt'Ktjv el pfj Kara arvpftefiriKus. The greater frequency of the expression in later Greek throws some doubt on the few instances of it in Attic Greek which, like the pre- sent, have full MS. authority. to Te\ Sc. prjuos dppoTTOv. 6. TT\v pedoBov — tov — BwaTov elvai] Cf. Ale. 115 b : Kara rfju eni\eipT]0'iv tov craxreu ovs eSet. 1 14 IIAATQNOS men inven Boners. To return, :,n,l apply our ex- ample. Kingcraft has been distin- guished from other artsof tend- ing ani- mals in herds. But there remain those arts, both opera- tive and assistant, which are found within the state. tov aKovauvra evpeTtKcoTepov aTrepyaip-jTut, tovtov p- airovbd^Lv kcu tu> /jli]K€l firjdev dyavaKTelv, av r av fipa)(VT€po?, axravTW eri 8 av wpo? tovtol? tov nepl ra? TOtdaBe orvvovcrlas \j/eyovTa Xoyoov pyKr) 5 kcu ray ev kvkXco rreptodovs ovk dirodexoLievov, otl )(py) TOV T0L0VT0V fXY] TTOLVV TU)(V pL1]8 6v6vS OVT00 peOievai xj/e^avra \xovov cos" fxaKpd to. XeyOevTa, aXXa p. kcu 7rpoo-a7ro(paLveiv oiecrOai Selv oos fipayyTepa av yevofxeva tov? avvovTas direipyd^eTO SiaXeKTiKcoTe- io povs Kal Trjs tcov ovtcov Xoyco Si^Xcocreaos evpeTiKcoTe- povs, tcov <5e aXXcov koll irpos aXK aTTa \j/6ycov Kal eiraivcov Lirjbev (ppovTiQiv Lir/8e to irapditav aKOveiv SokeIv tcov toiovtcov Xoycov. Kal tovtcov fxev aXts. el Ka\ cro\ TavTjj ijvvdoKel' Trpbs Se 8r) tov ttoXltlkov i$\cQLiev iraXiv, tt)s 7rpoppr)de[ar)9 ixpavTLKi]^ avTco ; Trpoaelnov cos iXecov ovoiidaas. 2. av t av ftpaxvTepos] Sc. "XexOeis. 3. tov — \j/eyovTa] We seem to detect in these words an apolo- getic tone. Comp. Gorg. 453 b. 5. oTi xph T0V toiovtov] These words depend immediately on 6 Aoyos rrapayyeXXa. 6. irdvv Taxv] Bodl. TTavTa\v. 7. peBUvai] Cf. Phileb. 16 e : els to aneipov peBevra x ai P el - v eav. IO. Trjs — 8r)Xcoarecos] This is probably a genitive of respect. Xoyco depends on the verbal meaning in SrjXcocrecos. 1 2. 6i 8iarpi]6evTus ivi anXdy- xvoio-i Xoyoto, with a further allusion to divination. 11. Set yap] Cf. once more Phileb. 16 d : 8vo, etnas elai, o-Koireh, el 8e prj, rpels fj tlv liXXov apidpov. 15. 8f)7rov] Bodl. 8e TTOV. 1 8. TCIVTOV peV TOVTO, STl 8£ paXkov] For the slight inex- actness of pev and 8e, cf. The«t. 150 b : to pev tvTai, KaOdirzp opyavov, aAA' eW/ca rod SypuovpyijOevros arcoTrjpias. NE. 20. To ttoZov ; SE. Tovro o Sr) ijypoi? kcu vypois [kol epirvpois kcu airvpoi$\ TravToSawov eiSo? epyaaOev, dyyeiov 5 "j~b Srff fiia KArjaei irpootpOeyyoiieOa, kol paXa ye avyyov ddos kol rfj ^rjTOup.evrj ye, coy olficu, rrpoa- $88. yjkov ovbev dre^vm eTnaT-qpy). NE. 20. ricoy ydp ov ; 37E. Tovtgw Srj rpirov erepov eiSos KTr/parcov 10 7rdfjL7ro\v koltotttIov ire^bv kol evvSpov kol ttoXv- Thinlly, platforms, or vehicles : I. e7Tt yevecrecos atrt'a] " Pro- ductionis causa." inl as in eVi rex v ll pavddvei. alria as 111 hv ot) av irepi air lav e^et? 8ia- ipepeiv. I. e. With the view of having production referred to them. 4. Tovto — 7rpoa(pdeyy6pedaj This place also appears easilyre- medi able by rejecting the second 6 8rj, which is either a gloss or a clerical error. Stallb. is wrong in saying that two arts must be developed here. (How would he distinguish ipyaXeiov from opyavov '?) The opyavov has been already distinguished, though with difficulty, as a separate kind, being lightly passed over because already spoken of under vcpavriKT), and that here named (dyyelov) has been previously spoken of as erepov, " a second." The next is therefore properly introduced as rpirov. [kgu epTrvpois Ka\ dn-upoic]] For things prepared by fire and not so prepared. Thus caldrons and pitchers are both included. In Legg. 3, 679 a, ctkcvcov epirvpcov re nai airvpcov, the distinction is made between pottery and wickerwork, the former of which is baked and will bear heat. 9. Tlcos yap ov;] Sc. e'mcopev cos ovk ion ravrrjv rr)v ovvap.iv '4x°v. This form of assent to a negative proposition has been questioned, and ttcos yap, itcos yap ovv, ncos yap civ, suggested. But for a similar inexactness in reply, if this be inexactness, cf. Gorg. 467 e : T Ap' ovv ecrn Tt, rcov ovrcov, o ou^i rjroi dyadov y eo~r\v i] Kaicov r) pera^v rovrcov, ovre ayaOov ovre kokov ; II. 7roAAi) avdyKTi, co 2. (sc. pr) elval Tt rcov ovrcov o etc.) 1 O. Tovrcov 81) — ycyvopevov ] " And there is a third kind of possessions, different from these and very extensive, which we must descry, on land and on water, perambulatory and stationary, honourable and dis- honoured, to which one name is given, because it is always intended to be sat upon, and is a seat for some one." sports 1 1 8 I1AATQN02 7rXave$ kou dirXaves koll ti/xlov koll utl/xov, ev oe p. ->!• wofj-a e'xov, 8lotl irdv Ivskol tlvos €(jje8pa? earl, Oolkos dei tlvl yiyvofxevov. NE. 20. To irolov ; 5 HE. ' O^ifpa avro ttov Xeyopev, ol> Tra^f ttoXltl- Kr/? epyov, dXXa pcaXXov ttoXv tcktovlkt]? koll Kepa- LiLKT]? KOLL Xa7\K0TV1TLKr)S. NE. 20. MavOavoo. Fourthly, ££E. T7 oe rerapTOV : dp' erepov elvou tovtidv }> defences; / , T x „/,■„/ , ioAeKreo^, eV co tol TrXeiara iari tcov iraXai prjdevTcov, eadrjs re ^vpiraaa koll tcov 07rXcov to 7roXv koll rel)(r] ttolvtol 0' oaa yr/iva 7repil3XrjLiaTa kou XiQiva, koll fxvpia erepa ; TrpofioX-qs 8e eW/ca {jvLnravTcov avTcov elpyaapievcov diKouorar dv oXov irpoaayopevoiTO irpo- i5/3A?7pa, kou 7roAAc5 piaXXov reyyiqs oiKoSopuKrjs epyov kou vTiKrj9 to ttXucttov volllC^olt dv bpOorepov r) TToXlTLKYj?. NE. 20. Yldw pL€V OVV. Fifthly, AE. YlefXTTTOV 8e dp OLV £6eXoiLl€V TO TTtpi TOV C ioKoap.ov kou ypa(f)iKT)v Oeivai kou oaa tclvty) irpoa^pco- fjLeva kou pLovatKrj LiiLirjLiaTa TeXeiTcu, irpo? to:? r)8ova? I. rifiiov Kai ciripov] Cf. rrpo- g. Tt 8e Teraprov;] Cf. Gorg. e8pia, Trpcorov £v\ov. Horn. II. 474 C: rl he 8r/ alo-\iov ; norepov M. 3II : TeTiprjpeada paXiara k.t.'X. eSpy re Kpiaalv re K.r.A. Dio IO. t£>v Trakai prjdevrav] Supr. Cass. 58, 18 : eopat. re anpoi Kai 279, 280. crraaeis iirovdbiaTOi. 1 1. tcov oirhav to 7roAii] I. e. 6. paWov 7roXu] Cf. supr. Defensive armour. 275 c, and note. 16. to w\f7o-Tov] " Most," K(papiKr]i\ The exact bear- not " all." Not 6-n\oirouKr], for ing of this would be more evi- example. dent if we knew more of the 6p66repov pleonastically re- details of Greek life. sumes ttoKv paXXov, as suiting 7. x a ^ K0TV7riK 'i s ] By which better with vopi^oir av. chariots, for example, are made. flOAITIKOS. 11!) 1I288. fxovov n)fjLcoi> aTreipyao-fitva, SiKaicos 0" av bvofxari TrepiXrjCJiOevTa kvi ; NE. 2Q. Uotcp ; SE. Yiaiyvibv 7rov tl Xeyerai. NE. 20. 17 ixr]v ; 5 SE. Touro Toivvv tovtoi9 ei> bvofia anraai 7rpe\j/€i irpoaayoptvOeV ov yap cnrovdrj? oiideu olvtwv xapiv, aXKa 7rai8La? evtKa iravra hparai. cl NE. 20. Kai tovto cr^eSo^ en p.av6dv(o. 3?E. To Se 77W4 tovtois aco/iara irape^ov, e£ &v 10 /cat eV o!y 8r)piovpyov(riv biroaai twv re^vcov vvv ei- prjvrat, 7ra.vT08a.7rbv elSo?, ttoWwv irepcov reyvcov tKyovov ov, ap oi>x Iktov 6y]aop.ev ; Sixthly, materials, (which should have been put first :) 4. HaLyviov tvov tl] "There is such a word in use as 'child's-play.'" Cf. Soph. 226 b : Xeyofiev. We have here the larger kind, of which p.i- fxrjrtKrj is part. Cf. Soph. 234 b : natdias he ex els tf Tl Te X vl ~ Kwrepov t) Kai xapu'&Tepov eihos 1) TO pipTJTLKOV j IO. To he nao-L tovtois awfiaTti napexov] This (if earlier than the Timseus) is probably a nearer approach than philo- sophy had hitherto made to the distinction of matter and form, of which the doctrine of elements in the earlier Greek philosophy was the anticipa- tion. The aneipov of the Phi- lebus (see esp. 25 c) is a more abstract mode of the same conception, taken from Pytha- gorean philosophy (cf. ib. 54 c: yeveo-ecos p.ev eveKa (pappaKa tc /cai wdvTa opyava Kai Trdo~av vkrjv TvapaTiOeadaL iracnv) : and the notion of formless matter oc- curs once again in the Timseus, in a passage of which the germ may be found in the text, 49 a: vvv 8' 6 Xoyoy eoiKev elaavay- Ka£eiv x a ^* 7 > ov Kai apvhpbv eihos emxeipe'iv Aoyoty ep.i> re kou e/x\|/u^a)^ Sep/iara awp.drow Trepioupovaa aKVTOTopuKT], kou octou 7rep\ ra tololvt elal riyyou, kou (f)e\\cov kou (3v(3Aooi> kou 8eap.wu epyacTTLKai, irapeayov 8-qpiovpyuv avvOtra e'/c p.rj crvvTiOefitvcDV €'i8r] yevwv. eV -5e avro irpoaayopevu>fxev \ottolv to TrpaiToyeves dvOpojirois Krrj/jLa, kou dtvvOtrov kou /3av d\l/i>xc0V aiopdraiv (icaOapiTcis) , hv yuacpev- tikt] kci\ £vpirao~a KocrprjTtKi) rrjv ini- jxiXaav TrapexopevT] Kara apiKpa, 7roAAa Ka\ yeXola 8okovvtci ovdpara ev 8<$8eKa opioiai pepav. 3. Kovpd] E. g. the cutting of osiers and brushwood, the mowing of grass and reaping of straw, the cropping of horses' and camels' hair, the shearing of sheep. 7. 8eo-pcbv] Such as glue and thread. IO. to npa>Toyev€S dvOpatnois KTTJpu] The first-born of hu- man possessions, because ne- cessary to the production of all else. The word is a rare one, and occurs in the Orphic verses, where also Nature ((£ucm) is called npcDToyeveia. It seems probable that Plato had this, in common with other terms employed in these dialogues, from a Pythagorean source. nOAITIKOS. 121 i88 NE. 2Q. KaXm. S'E. Trjv <5?) rrjs rpo(j)r)s KTrjaii 1 , kou oau ek to au>pa ^vyKarapLyvvpeva eavTwv pepeai peprj aoopa- T09 €L9 to OepaTrevaai. Tiva hvva\xiv e'/A^e, XtKTtov 89. efiSofXOV ovopaaavTas avTO ^vp-rvav i]p £(OCQl>, lv T0VT0L9 llTTOL ol/JLGU yeVtCTLV elprjcrOai. aKowei 8e' rjv yap SiKaioTaTa pli> av TeOlv b /car' apxas to TrpcoToyeves elSo?, /xercc Se tovto op- yavov, ayyeiov, oxypa, 7rp6(3Xr)p,a, iraiyviov, Opeppa. irapaXeLTTopev Se el tl prj peya XeXrjOev eh tl tov- Sevi ntlil;. . nourish- ments. Into these seven kin ds all posses- sions ex- cept living creatures can, by hook or 5 by crook, be distri- buted. 3. eavTav fxepeai] The po- sition of eavT&v pepecriv, which is for the sake of emphasis, determines the order of the following words. The whole is a periphrasis for (pdppaKa. peprj aaparos eh to 6epa- 7rev(rai hvvap.iv riva] Note the invei*sion : for 8w. r. eh to 6ep. 0-copa.TOs peprj. 7. yvp.va.aTiK.fi] Because the trainer prescribes a certain diet. II. ova e)(eTai /cr^o-ews] Cf. Thefet. 145 a : ova. re iraidelas e)(eTai, alib. 13. rjv yap] " For we had, what would rightly have been placed first, the primitialkind." 15. Gpeppa] "Nourishment." This meaning is not noticed in the Lexicons, but Stallbaum well compares the use of yev- vrjpa in Soph. 266 d. Both uses originate in the " cog- nate" object of the active becoming the subject of the passive voice. 6peppa retains a verbal signification also in Legg. 7, 789 b : Tpecpovaiv — dpviOcov 8pepp.aTa. 1 6. irapake'iiTopev — 0-vp.cpaiv^aei] " But we pass over whatever insignificant kind may have escaped us, which may pos- sibly be made to fit into one of these, for instance, -the na- ture of coins, seals, and stamps of all sorts." [peya], which Bocll. Vat. Ven. n omit, is re- tained, not as genuine, but as possibly preserving the trace of a lost reading, perhaps of P-6yis, suggested by Stallbaum. 1252 HAATONOS Animate *ii mis, with the excep- tion of sl:m s,\\i re previously i 1 1- ' 1 1 1< 1 ■ < I in the art of tending herds. There remains therefore the class of servants, amongst whom to look for the nearest rivals of the king. But slaves, who are servants in Tcov *|* [//eya] "|" Svvoltov dppoTTeiv, olov i) rov vofii- p. 28 (t/jlutos I8ea koll a([)payldoju koll ttolvtos x a P aKT VP ^- yivos Te yap Iv avrois ravra ovftev e^ei ptya qvv- vollov, aXXd tol piv els Koapov, tol 8e el? opyava 5 j3ia p.ev, opco? <5e irdvTtos eXKO/ieva avpojcouyaei. tol Se 7T€pl tfiiodv ktyjctlv tcov r)p.lpcov, ttXt]V SovXcov, ■>'] Trporepou uyeXaLorpo(j)LKr) Sia/jLepiaOe'io-a irdvTa c eiXrjcpvia avcKpaiverai. NE. 212. Yldvv p.lv ovv. o SE. To Se 8r) 8ovXow koll iravrcov inrypeTcdu Xonrov, Iv oh itov koll pavrevo/xaL rov? 7rep\ clvto to 7rXeyp.a dpcpcafirjTOvi'Tcxs tco fiacnXeL Karoxpaveis yevrjaeaOaL, KaOdirep toI$ vcpdvTOLLs tot€ tov? irep\ to vrjOew re 3. yevos — o-vp(paiVT)0~ei\ u For these, while they have not in them the nature of any exten- sive kind which can be classed along with them, yet can, by hook or by crook, be made to harmonize, though not without some violence, either with the ornaments or the instruments of life." re yap — aAXct] be and even pevToi and dXka may sometimes follow re, when the opposition between two paral- lel clauses is thought of as the sentence proceeds, Cf. Phasdo 63 C : irapa avbpas re — on pevroi irapa deovs, where however pev is interposed, and Theeet. I43 C : irepl ahrov re rj av Trepl rbv diroKpivopevov. The two clauses here answer to py peya and hvvarbv dpporreiv SUpr. 4. ds Kocrpov] Which is a de- partment of iraiyviov '. 288 C. 5. /3t'a pev — opms 8e] Cf. Eep. IO, 607 e: (3la pev, opws Be dnexovTat, and Soph. Ant. 1 1 16 : o'ipoi pohis pev, KapBlas B' eglaTapai to Bpav, re is used because their not being refer- rible to an important class is one of the two reasons for omitting them. 7. rj nporepov dyeXaiorpoCpiKr) biapepiaGelaa ] Note the in- verted order. 11. ev oh nov] " Somewhere amongst whom." rovs irepl avro to irXeypa] He refers to the difficulty about the king in the language of the example of weaving r i. e. those who dispute with the king about the fabric of the web itself and not only about the instruments of the manu- facture. Cf. 268, 281 ; and vid. infr. 305 e : iravra gwv- (paivovaav opdoraTa ttjv Br) (3ao~i\iKr)v avpirXoKrjV. 1 3. toIs v(pdvrais\ Sc. dptfiio-- ftrjTovvTas (paiveo-Qai. nOAITIKOS. 123 289. Kai ijalveiv kcll oaa aXXa eiTrop.zv. 01 <$' aXXoi ndv- res, c6? dvvaiTLOi XeyOtvTes, d/xa reus- epyoi? to 19 vvv d 8y prjOeicriv dvrjXcovTai Kai aTreywpLcrOi^aav diro /3a- aiXiKrj? T€ kou TroXiTiKrjs 7rpd^eco9. NE. 20. 'EoLKacn yovv. 5 SE. "Wl 8rj aKeyj/cofieOa tov? Xolttovs, irpoo-- eXOovTe? iyyvOev, tv clvtovs 1 dftcofiev fiefiatoTepov. NE. 20. Ovkovv xPV- S*E. Tov? fiev Srj fieyiaTOVs VTrrjptTas, coy IvOivBe iSeiv, TOvvavTLOV e)(0VTas evplaKO/jLev oh v7rco7TT€vaa- 10 fxev eTTLTrjbevfxa kou ttglOos. NE. 20. Ttvas ; SE. Tow wvttjtovs T€ Kai rco Tpo7ra> tovtco ktt]- tovs' ov? avafjLCpio-firjTrjTcos SovXov? eypp.ev direlv, e r\KiCFTa fiao-iXLKrjs pLCTairoLovpLevovs Teyvrjs. 15 NE. 20. ILSpc? otf; 37E. T/ 6Y; 7W iXevOepcov octol toIs vvv brj prj- tli«- highest degree, have do- thing in common with the king. Nor have thoBe freemen who en- gage as hirelings in the ser- vile opera- tions of trade. 9. fieyia-rovs — cos iv6kv8e tSeti/] " The greatest — as seen from where we now stand." I. e. the greatest servants, because most essentially such, this being the only measure which our method allows. Cf. infr. 303 c, for the same use of (xeyio-Tos. Also Phileb. 45 a : peyuTTai. tcov t)8ov£>v. Legg. I, 630 a : tov ? iv too fieyi(TTco 7To\epa> yiyvopevovs aplcrToxjs 8tc«pa.va>s. The contempt here implied for dianovia may be contrasted with a striking pas- sage of the Laws, where the power of ministering to them- selves and others is made es- sential to the officers of state, 6, 762 e : KaWa>Tri£ecr6ai XPV too KaKcos 8ov\ev(rcu paXKov fj too koXcos apgai. lb. 763 a : avrol 81 avriov 8iavorj8ijTcoarav cos j3tco- aopevoi 8caKovovvres re Kai 8ia- Kovovpevoi eavTols. 10. ok] = eKeivois a. Plural, because of the two antecedents, eTrLTT]8evpct icai iraOos. 1 1 . Ka\ TtaOos] " And feel- ing," viz. ambition. 17. vols viiv 8f] prj6ei. 2* yeoopyla? koll tu twv akkcov Teyvwv epya SiaKu/JLitpv- T€$ eir ah\i)\ovs koll avi(rovi>T€?, ol p.ev kolt uyopa?, ol Se ttoKlv 4k iroXeois aXXaTTOVTes Kara OaXarrav 5 koll Tre^rj, v6/ucrp.d re wpb? ruXXa koll olvto 7rpbs olvto SLapLelfiovTes, ow dpyvpap.oi(3ov9 re koll ep.7ropov9 koll p. 29 VOLVKAl'lpOVS KOLL KOLTTqkoVS €7rOWOp.OLKOLp.ei>, p.U>V T7]9 ttoXltlkyjs dp.(j)Laj3r]Tr)crovaL tl ; NE. 20. Tax' dv 'laws rr)s ye rcou epiropevTLKwv. [o 3?E. 'AAA' 01; pjjv, ovs ye opcopev p.Lcr0o)Tov? koll Orjras ttolo-lv eTOLpLOTOLTOL innqpeTOvvTOLS, prj TTore /3a- ctlAlktJs p.eTo.7TOLOvp.evovs evpoypiev. ally inferior to other forms of industry. Cf. Rep. 2,371b: Kai 8?) rail' ciXkav Siaxovuv 7rou Ta>i> re elo~a£6vra>v Kai i^n^ovrmv eKaara. ovtoi 8e elaiv 'dpnopoi. lb. C : elalp oi tovto opavres eavroiis iirl ttjv StaKOViai' rdr- Tovai TavTrjv, iv pew rats 6p6a>s otKovpevais noXecri a^ebov ti ol ao~6eveo~TaTOL to. aapara Kai uxpeloi Ti aXAo epyov irpdrTetv. — avTrj apa rj XP eia KanijXcov Tqplv yeve&iv e/x7roiet rfj noXet. rj ov KaiT7]Xovs KaXovpev tovs irpbs wvt]V re Kai irpao-iv diaKovovvras \ and for ttoXiv in TrdXeco? in tbis connexion, cf. Soph. 224 b, and note. The statesmen are viewed as duiKovoi in the Gorgias, p. 517. Cf. Theset. 175 e: Topa>$ re Kai b£ews oiaKoveiv. Legg. 8, 831 e (of the influ- ence of commerce) : ipnopovs re kuI vavKXrjpovs ko.1 diaKovovs irdv- T(os rovs (pvaei Koapiovs twv av- QpcoTTav tnrcpyafrpevr). I. to. re — diapeifiovres ] " Bringing over to each other and equalizing the work of the husbandman and of the other artificers (eV aXX^Xou?, sc. rovs yecopyovs, &c.) : some in the market-place and some trans- ferring them from city to city by sea and land, exchanging money for other commodities, and these for money." 3. dvio-odvres] This seems to point to a doctrine of ex- change approaching to that of Aristotle in Eth. Nic. V. 4. noXiv — dXXuTTOvTes] Cf. Soph. 224 b, and note. The words are usually taken to mean " going from city to city ; " for which cf. Theaet. 181 d : x^P av eK x®P as M era " PdXXy. 9. rrjs ye to>v epiropevriKcov (sc. iroXirtKTJs)] " The science of directing commercial inter- course." The merchant may profess political economy, but not statesmanship or political science. 10. Kai drjTas] Cf. Euthyphr. 4 c. I10AITIK02. 125 1290. NE. 20. Ylco9 yap ; aE. T7 <5e «jOa rotis* ra roiaSe SiaKovovvTas rjp.lv eKacTTore ; NE. 20. Ta 7rota eiVey /cat Ttvas ; b S*E. 'O//' to K^pvKLKOV eOvos, hcroi re irep\ ypap,- p.ara ao(j)di yiyvovTai ttoWvlkls vTryperyjaavTes; koll 7roAA' arra erepa irepl rots apyas SiaTroveiaOai tivzs erepoi 7rav8eivoi, t'l tovtovs av Aetjopcv ; NE. 20. c 'Oirep eiTres vvv, vTrrjpera?, aAA' ovk av- rov? iv tolls iroXecriv apypvTCLS. HE. 'AAA' ov pjjv, olpai ye, evimviov iScov ehrov TavTy Trrj (pavijcreaOai tovs 8ia(j)€p6vTa>? dp. fiefiacravio-pevovs. elcri Se di re 7rep\ piavTiKrjv e^ovTes twos e7ricTTr)pr/? SiaKovov popiov epp.7]vevTal yap 7T0V vopifyvTai irapa 6ecov avdpumois. Then th< ra arc j .i 1 1 1 1 i ■ • HCrV.'UltH, -h.-li .1 ; bi paid a ad '-ribes, who arc not to be 5 confound- ed with the rulers. Yet, however strange the thought that the claimants for the art of rule are 10 to be found amongst servants, it was no mere dream. There are other pub- lic minis- ters -whom ** we have not yet tried. The priest, who me- diates be- tween gods and men, and the 20 prophet, who inter- 2. rovs — SiciKavovvTas] Sc. ev- pcopev or Xe^opev. 5. irep\ ypappara ] E. g. the public ypapparels at Athens. 6. o-o(po\ — vivr]p(TrjO-avTei\ Of. Leg'g. 4, 720 b: e'dv re y eXev- 8epoi aaiv edv re 8ovXoi, kut eiri- raf-iv be tbc beuTTOTUtv K.a\ decopiav Ka\ VTai - 7 . Kal 7roAA' arra — ndvbeivoij " And certain others most accomplished in performing many other processes con- nected with government." 9. "Oirep elnes\ Supr. vnrjpe- Ti] yap eVi- uTarwv tj noXiTiKi) Koivavia Bel- rat' dioirep iravTas ovre tovs alperovs ovre tovs KXrjpaTovs apxovras OeTtov, olov tovs iepeis TrpwTov. VTTrjpfTas avTav] The Xo- yoypacpoi are perhaps included, who furnished public speakers with arguments. 9. Tivas — Kai] Cf. Thetet. 160 e : o ti BrjTTOTe Kai rvy- Xavei ov. Euthyd. 27 1 a: '07ro- Tepov Kai iparas, a> Kpircav ', I 3. 7roXXoi — ffrjplois ] I. e. " Some strong and fierce, some weak and cunning." Compare Bacon, Adv. of Learning, Ellis' ed., p. 394. "And although we have said that the use of this doctrine (of Elenches) is for redargution, yet it is mani- fest the degenerate and cor- rupt use is for caption and contradiction : which passeth for a great faculty, and no doubt is of very great advant- age : though the difference be o-ood which was made between 128 IIAATONOS dpcoi^ zi^aai kol Y^evTavpois kui TOiovroiaiv (T€poi?, p 7rap.7roXAoL 8e ^.arvpois koll tois dcrOevecri kol 7roXv- h Tpo7roi? Oif plots' rayv Se fieraXXuTTOvaL ra? re iSea? kcu ti)v Suva/iiv eh dXXrjXov?. kol fievroi fioi uvu, 5 co 2co/c/j«re?, apri Sokco KaTavevorjKtvai tov? av- Spas. NE. 213. Aeyoi? av* eoiKa? yap arowov tl kolQ- opav. £E. Nat" to yap aroirov i£ ayvolas Tvacri avfi- to (3aivei. K.a\ yap Srj Ka\ vuv avrbs tovto cnraOop' itjatyvr)? rj/uL(fieyi>6r]o-a Kanbcov top 7rep\ ra tcoi> 7ro- Xecov irpaypLara yppov. NE. 20. lioiov ; e SiE. TW iravTcov ra>i> o~o^>io~twv fieyiarov yoryra orators and sophisters, that the one is as the greyhound, which hath the advantage in the race, and the other as the hare, which hath her advantage in the turn, so as it is the advantage to the weaker crea- ture." And cf. Legg. 6, 781 a : to 8rj\v eTTU<\oira>Tepov 8id to daBeues. 4. kcu jievToi av8pas] " And come, I do think I now this moment have perceived the na- ture of the men." 7. eoiKcts — Kadopau] I. e. " Judging from your looks." Cf. Soph. Ant. 20 : S/7A01S ydp ti Ka\x a L V0V0 ~' enos. Legg. 7> 8lO C : TL ffOTe T0VT G> £«Vf, (paivet Trpbs aavTov ovtcos T]7T0pr]- kcos \eyeiv ' } The principle of election by lot, which Plato ridicules here, is admitted within very narrow limits in the Laws. Cf. Legg. 3, 690 d : Qeocpikr) 8e ye Kcil evcpikrj Tiva \eyovTes e/386pr]V cip- xw (compare the seven forms of government and seven ca- tegories of possession in the Politicus) els Kkrjpov Tiva irpo- dyopev k.t.\. 9. to yap (itottov ££■ dyvoias] Cf. Arist. Met. I. 2. 982 b: 6 8' dwopcov kcu 6avp.d£a>v ot'erat dy- voe'iv. 10. avros tovto enadov] " I myself fell into this snare," viz. of thinking sti-ange what was only strange to me. The Stranger is like the philoso- pher as described in the Theas- tetus, Avho knows nothing of public assemblies or the de- tails of civic life. For Trdo-xs. 11. e£al(pvr]s belongs by an hyperbaton to KaTi8a>v. 14. Tov — yorjTa] Cf. Soph. 235 a : els yorjTa p.ev 8i] kcu p.i- 00AITIK02. 129 91. KOLl TOLVTT}? Tt]S Te^UTJ^ epireipOTOLTOV OV U7T0 T03V bvrm ovtcov ttoXltikwv kou fiaaiXiKCDv Ka'nvep iray- yaXeTrov ovra a^atpeiv d(f)aipeT€OV } el p.eXXopev \8e1v evapym to (jfTovpevov- NE. 20. 'AAAa prjv tovto ye ovk avereov. HE. Ovkovv 8rj Kara ye tijv e/.u/u. kul p.ot (f)pa£e To8e. NE. 20. To TToigv; d HE. 'Ap ov povapyja twv ttoXltlkwv -qplv ap^cov earl pla ; NE. 20. Nat. HE. Kou pera povapylav e'hroL tis av>, olpat, ttjv virb tcov oXiycov dvvaareiau. NE. 20. n«?<5' ov; HE. Tplrov Se a)(rjpa 7roXiTeias ov\ rj rod nXr/- 6ovs apyr), SrjpoKpaTia rovvopa KXrjOelaa ; NE. 20. lidvv ye. HE. Tpel? 5' ovaai p.a>v ov irevre rpoirov tlvol yiyvovTOLi, 8vo e£ eavrcov aXXa 7T/oo? avrcus bvbpara tiktovo-cli ; impostor of impostors, who must be ■ pa- rato a, how- ever diffi- cult the task, from i tlie true Statesman and King. We com- monly speak of three forms of govern- ment, mon- archy, oli- [ °garchy,and democracy. And the distinctions of compul- sion and freedom, poverty and wealth, [£ . observance of the laws and law- give rise to the further division of mon- archy into royalty and 20 tyranny, fiTjTrjv apa dereov riva. The sin- gular after x°P ov is curious, but this is only one more instance of the transition from the class to the ideal individual, which we have had frequent occasion to notice. I. TavTrjs ttjs re)(yr)s epneipo- rarov] Sc. ttjs aocpiariKris. Cf. Gorg. 465 d : (pvpovrai iv rw avrcp kuI irep\ ravra aocpajrai Ka\ prjTopes, kol ovk e^ovcriv on XP1~ o~a>vTv oXiyoov] Depend- ing on the verbal notion in SwacrTeiav. Cf. Rep. 2, 359 a : to biro tov vopov iniTaypa. 19. 8vo — TiKTovcrai] So the three categories of the Sophist, Being, Eest, and Motion, be- came five through generating, " by their own dialectic," the categories of Sameness and Difference. 130 riAATONOS and of oli- garchy Into aristocracy and pluto- cracy. The Bame distine- tions do doubt arise in demo- cracy, I'Ut without changing the name. Thus the common way of thinking recogiiizes five forms. But is any one of these based on a real prin- ciple ? For we have as- sumed from the first that there is a science of govern- ment. NE. 20. Uola Srj ; p. SE. 11/90? TO filaiOV 7T0V K(JU eKOVGLOV aTTOCTKO- G TTOVVTtS VVV, Kol TieviaV KCli TrXoVTOV, KOL VOfJLOV KOLL avofxlav, Iv aureus yiyvofxeva, 8nrXr)v eKarepav rolv sSvolv diaipovvres p.ovapyiav fiev wpoaayopevovaiv a>? Svo irapeyo\ievr\v eldi] 8vo?v bvopacn, TvpavviBt, to 8e /3ao-i\iKj}. NE. 20. 17 wit ; S*E. Tr)v 8e virb oXlycov ye eKaaTOTe KparrjOelaav iottoXlv dpicrTOKpaTia. kou oXiyapyla. NE. 212. Kat irdvv ye. HE. Arj/xoKpaTias ye jxrjv, lav r ovv ftiaico? lav T6 eKovo-lco? tcov To.? ovcria? e\bvT(£>v to TrXrjQos p. apxf), Koi lav re tovs vo/jlov? aKpiftcos (f)vXa.TTOv 1 5 lav re fir}, iravTcas Tovvo/xa ovdels avTrj? etcoOe fieTaXXdrTeiv . NE. 20. 'AAt?^. HE. T/ ovv ; oiopLeOd Tiva tovtcov tcov TroXiTeicov ^ ■ 29 3. vvv\ " According to pre- sent notions." Cf. Soph. 236 a. In Rep. 8, 9, we have the picture of four imperfect states, Timocracy, Oligarchy, Demo- cracy, and Tyranny, nearly cor- responding to the four "which are distinguished from Kingly Monarchy here. But the esti- mate of each, and the mode in which their relation to the ideal government is conceived, are very different in the two passages. Plato is avowedly speaking here according tp the common opinion. The acknowledgment that, after all, democracy, under legal con- ditions, is the least bad, is a point of approximation to the Laws. See the Introduction to the Statesman. tve.vi.av Ka\ -rikovTov\ Wealth being the mark of the tyrant and oligarch, as distinguished from the king and the aristo- crat, as well as from the people. 6. Tvpavvidi, to 3e (Sacri\iKfj~\ Cf. Soph. 221 e : v(v(ttikov fie- povs, to Se Tre^ov TepvovTes (where see note). Phsedo 105 e : ' Apovaov, e yiyveaOcu ; • NE. 20. T7 yap 87) kou KcoXuei ; 5 b aE. ^k6tt€l 87) (jatyearepov, rfjde €7r6p.evos. NE. 20. By ; aE. T« prjdevTL Kara 7rpcoTas irorepov e/ifxevovpiei' ?; dLa(poji>7]0'OfJLeu ; NE. 20. Ta> 87) Tro'icp Xeyus ; 10 £7E. Trjv fioi(TL\LKr)v ap)(r)V tcdis liTLcnri\xoiv dva'i nva etyapev, oipou. NE. 20. No/. SE. Kat tovtcov ye ol>x airaawv, dXXoc KpiriKrjv 8r)7rov tlvol kou €7riaraTLKrjP e/c tw akXoov 7rpoeiX6- 15 2. Tffl ftiaia Kal eKOvaico] Cf. Arist. Pol. III. I : at eVi'as rS>v 7rd\iT€iS>v tco Kpareiv ovcras, aX\ ov 81a to Ko'ivrj vvpcpepeiv. 3. Kai — ylyveadatj Plato re- verts to the main construction (here participial) instead of add- ing another dependent clause. The Words perci — ypappdroov — ylyveo-Bai stand in apposition to tovtois — 6pio~de7o~av. pera ypappdrcov Kal avev vo- pav\ Note the variety of ex- pression. The laws are spoken of with some contempt as mere ypdppara, and are thus compared to written rules of art. Compare Phsedr. 258 a, Gorg. 451 b : ol iv to> 8rjpm avyypacpopevot. Legg. 9, 858 C : ypdppara pev ttov ko.1 iv ypdupacri \6yoi Kal aWcov dcrl noXXcov iv rals TroXecrt yeypappevoi, ypdppara de Kal to. tov vopadirov Kal Xdyot. lb. 957 c. The expression is often used also by Aristotle in the Politics. 8. Kara nparas] A parallel idiom to Kara povas. Kara as in Kar dpxds. Some such word as vnoOeo-iis may be here supplied. II. to>v im.o~Trjpa>v eivai Tiva~\ Supr. 258 b. I4. KpiTlKTjV Tiva Kal iirio-TaTi- ktjv] " One which is at once critical and commanding." This appears from 260 a, where, however, KpiriKf], or rather yvw- ariKrj, and ciutcuo-iky], are the terms opposed. Compare supr. 275 c, Soph. 223 b, 224 d, where there is a similar verbal inexactness of reference. S 2 i m nAATONOS But scien- tific go- vernment is not se- cured by the rulers being many, few or one, rich or poor, or by their rule being com- pulsory or voluntary. We have still, then, to discover under which of these forms there is contained NE. 20. Nai. p. SE. K(XK Tl]$ €7riCTTaTtKrj? T^f /J.€U eV d\j/vxoLS epyois, Ti]v 8e iirl £wois". kcu Kara tovtov 5tt tov c Tpoirov /lepl^ovre? 8evp del 7rpoeXi]Xv0a/iev, eirLaTrj- 5 /X77? ovk liTL\av6av6p.evoL, to $ rjri? ovx ikolvcos irco 8vvdpevoc SiaKpL^coaaaOaL. NE. 20. Aeyeis 6 P 0m. SE. Tout olvto tolvvv dp evvoovpev, oti tov opov ovk oXiyovs oi>8e 7roXXovs, ov8e to eKovcnov ov8e to 10 aKOvaiou, ov8e ireviav ov8e ttXovtov ylyvecrOai irepl amcov \pecov, dXXd Tiva e7Tio-Tr]prjv ; eiirep aKoXov- dr]aop.ev toIs irpoadev ; NE. 20. 'AAAce fJLTjv tovto ye d8vvctTOV /lit) d iroLelv. l 5 S?E. 'E£ dvdyKr)? 8rj vvv tovto ovtco aKeiTTeov, iv tlvl 7TOT6 tovtcov eir LCFTr) /XT? £vp(3alveL yiyvecrdai ire pi dvOptoirtov dpyrjs, crye8ov ttJ? x a ^ e7r&rrc "" 7 7 y KaL fieyiCTT-qs KTrjaaaOai. 8et yap tdeiv avTr/v, tva 6ea- crcop.e6a twos dcpaipeTeov diro tov (ppovl/xov fiacri- 2. ttjp pev ttjv Be] irpoetko- fieda cannot be repeated here, but some notion contained in this verb, such as iOepeda, must be supplied. 5. to s 6 Aoyoy c rjfxii; TrpoeiprjKev. HE. Mwf ow 5o/c€i TrXijOos ye ev iroXei ravTr/v < t^ €7rio-Tr)fJLi]v bvvoTov eivai KT-qaaaOai ; NE. 20. KcuTrcSy; HE. 'AAA a^oa eV ^iXiavSpcp iroXei bvvarov e'/coc- roz^ r^a? 7) /ecu TrevTrjKovTa avrr)v Ikclvws ktyj- aacrdai ; NE. 212. 'Paarr) pAvr av ovrco y elrj Traawv tcov Teyycav' tdfiev yap otl ^lXlcov dvdpcov aKpot ireTTev- ra\ roaovTOi irpbs rovs ev tols aXXois "YtXXrjaiv ovk av yevoivro 7rore, pur) ri Sr) (3a(riXei? ye. Set yap Si) tov ye rr)v fiacriXLKi]v eypvra eTTLarrjfxrjv, av r oipyrj .93. K.a\ eav pirj, Kara, tov eparpoaOe Xoyov ofioos (3aai- Xlkov TrpoaayopeveaQai. HE. KaAeos" aTTepivrjfxouevcrag. eiro/xevov 8e olficu tovtco rrjv fiev opOrjv dp\rjv irep\ eva tlvol Kal 8vo il, harde 1 of .-ill ac qui ition the art of governing men, be- fore we can clear awaj the rival impostors from the true king. The mul- titude cannot have this science. ( Nor can fifty in a thousand be found possessed of it. The true rulers, then, if more than 5. 7r\r)66s ye] " The people at least." I. e. " Whoever else has wisdom, do you think the masses have it V Cf. Rep. 6, 494 a : (piXoaotpov pev lipa — n^r/dos ahvvarov eivai. 13. too-ovtol] Sc. enaTov r) -nev- TrjKovra. irpos — •"EAAqo-ti'] " First-rate as compared with those in the rest of Greece." Even these few are still judged, therefore, by a relative stand- ard. 14. pi] ti §77 — ye] Cf. Dem. 01. 2, § 23 : ovk evi 8' avrov dpyovvra ovbe toIs (pi\ois irnraT- reiv virep avrov ti iroielv, prjn ye 8r) toIs 6eo7s (PaSSOW, S. V. [Mr]). Compare Rep. 2, 374 c : 7) ovroa pqbiov ware a|ta. And for the general tenour of this passage, Rep. 4, 428, Cratyl. 389 a : 6 vopo&errjs, off 8r) tcov Srjpiovp- ya>v cnravicoTaTOs ev avBpcoTTOLs yiyverai. 1 6. Kara tov eprrpocrde \6yov] Viz. 259 a. 18. eiropevov — tovtco] These words are in apposition. 19. ttjv pev opdrjV cipxrjv] The context shews that dpxn is used here generally of all authority. Cf. Rep. 1, 342 e : old' SWos ovdus iv ovdepiq clpxij- nepl eva tivci Ka\ Svo] Cf. 134 FIAATQN02 one, must verj few. And u In - thcr they be rich or I r, w ne- ther their subjects be willing or unwilling, whether they go- vern with or without law, we must es- teem them as such, so long as they rule according to the prin- ciples of their art, koll iravTaixacriv oXiyovs del (j]T€W, orav opOrj yi- p. 2< yvrjTai. NE. 20. T/ ix-qv ; 3*E. Tovtov? Se ye, lav re Ikovtcov lav re clkov- 5 tcov apyoxriv, lav re Kara ypappcara lav re avev ypappdrcov, kol lav 7tXovtovvt€? t) 7T€vop.evoi, vopu- cttIov, (ocnrep vvv r)yovp.e0a, Kara rlyvrjv tjvtlvovv dpXVv apyovras. tovs larpovs 5e ovy^ x]Kiaja vevopl- b Ka/utev, lav re eKOvra? lav re atcovras rj/idg icovTai, to Tepvovres rj Kaiovrts rj nva dXXrjv dXyrjdova 7rpocr- dirrovTeSi koll lav Kara ypappoja r) yapis ypo.pp.d- tcov, Kai lav 7revrjT€S k ovres r) ttXovctloi, iravTcas ovdev tJttov larpovs (j)ap.ev, eaxrirep dv iTricrTarovvTes re^vr), Phileb. 66 b : ire pi perpov Kai to perpcov kol OTVoaa \P1 Toiavra vopi^eiv rrjv atdiov rjpr]0-6ai (pvaLV. 6. TrXovTovvres f/ irevopevoi] Cf. I Ale. 107 C : av re Treves dv re irXovcrios rj 6 irapaivuiv ovhev bioicreC ABrjvaiOLS orav — fiovkevwv- rai irons dv vyiaivoiev, dWa forov- o~iv larpbv eivai rbv avpftovXov. vop-icrreov — cipxovras] dp^ovras is to be taken twice in con- struing. " They must be es- teemed as rulers, whatever rule it be which they conduct ac- cording to art." 8. vevopUapev] The verb is resumed in iral — irXeico 8e p.rj, and note. larpovs is to be repeated in thought after vevopUapev : or the verb is perhaps used absolutely, as in vopl^eiv 6eovs. Cf. Rep. 5, 476 c, Gorg. 466 b. '■ And physicians more especially we allow to rank as such, whether they heal us with or against our will, by incision or cautery, or by the application of any other pain," (these words re'pvov- res — irpoo-dirrovres are explana- tory of aKovras,) "with or with- out written precepts, in po- verty or wealth, — in every case we call them equally physi- cians, so long as those who minister preside according to art over that to which they minister, and preserve the same by purging and reducing, or by adding flesh, if only they do this for the good of the bodies which they make better from being worse." (Perhaps however the sentence was at first intended to run vevopUa- pev — cpdvai = " We are accus- tomed — to speak," &c.) The meaning is further perplexed by the redundancy of dv povov in the same construction as «oo-- irep dv with aafao-iv. Compare Kep. 7, 529 b : e'ym yap av — pavddvrj. nOAITIKOS. 1 35 93. KaOalpovres e'/re d'XXto? \7r ' dyaOco ap\eiv tS>v dpxofj-evcov. The doctrine of this passage coincides with Legg. 4 ; cf. esp. 712 e : as 5° covofxaKapev vvv, ovk elcrl 7roAireZa<, noXecov fie olKTjcreis hzo-iro(,op£vcov Te kcu 8ov\evovo~cov ptpecriv eavTcov tco-lv. lb. 713b: apxn re kcu o'ikt]0~is — en\ Kpovov pa\' evdal- pcov, tjs plprjpa e'xovad io~Tiv tJtis tcov vvv apio-ra oi/ceirai. lb. 7*5 b. Compare the rejection of the false pleasures in Phileb. 51 a, tovtov — apx^ s ] This clause is an explanatory resumption of TCll/Ty. 9. Kal poviiv 7roAfreiaz>] "And alone deserving of the name." 11. doKOvvras] I. e. eTncrTrj- povas SoKovvras, like SeivorrjTes 8oKovo-aL in Theset. 176 d. 1 2. ko). — kcu] "Whether — or." Note the variety of expres- sion. 13. vno\oyio-T€ov~\ Cf. Rep. I j 341 d : ovdev, olpai, tovto v7ro\oyio~Teov, on Tr\ei iv ttj vrp, oiK earl k\tjtcos vuvttjs' ov yap Kara to irXeiv KV^fpvrjTrjs Ka\elrai dXAa Kara, ttjv Te^vrjv Kal ttjv tcov vavTcov dpxr)v. 16. dnoKTivvvvTes — e'/c/3aXXoi/- Tis] Cf. Gorg. 468. 17. Kadalptoaiv] Cf. Legg. 5, 735, Rep. 7, 540 e. rae t banish- ment, 01 emigrati or U [36 riAATONOS have re- apiKpoTepau 7T0lu)(Tlv, rj Tivas eTreicrayopevoi TroOev p. aWovs eijooOev, ttoXitols TroiovvTes, amyv av^oicnv, ecocnrep av eino-Tiiprj koll tco Sikollco Trpocr^pcopevot, portation / > w v v \ r » \ % > by the pro- AeyopeV, OV yvyCTLa? OVO OVTCO? OVO~aS A€KT€Ol>, fJLAAa position / / ,\ \ « j / x / that there pLtpiprjpeva? TCLVTrjV, a?. peV 039 eVVOpOVS Aeyoptev, "^ g . eVt toc KaAAlco, tols 8e aAAay eiri ra altryiova pie- 3KS" »(wfa law. He is answered, that al- though le- gislation is certainly a function of the king, yet the best conceiv- able go- vernment would be the supre- n f?y> not ^ avev vopcov dpxpvTcov dpOorrjTO? SieAOeip r)pas. NE. 212. Ta pev aAAa, w iijeve, peTplco? eoiKev elprjcrOai' to 8e kou avev vopcov 8eiv apyeiv yaAe- 7T(DTepoi> ciKOveiv ipprjOrj. HE. 'Ep.iKpov ye e'(p07]s pe epoptevo?, d> ^EcaKpare?. i^epeAAov yap ere SiepcoTrjcreiv ravra irorepov airo8eyei P- 29 wavTa, rf tl /cat ^ucr^epaiVei? to>v AeyOevToov' vvv he rjSy (pavepbv otl tovto fiovArjaopeOa to irep\ ttj? tcov 1 . a-fiiKporepav Troiaxnv] This body politic, which is largely answers to la-^vaivovTes above. applied in the Republic. The 3. eTvuTT^LTj Ka\ ro> 8iKaia>] notion of " the physician in- Which in regard to politics creasing the body" is obviously are the same. Cf. Theret. 150 suggested by the parallel of the a : aXXct dia ttjv ciSikov re NE. 20. Ylm yap ov ; HE. Tf)07T01/ TLVOL fltVTOL ftr)\0V OTl TY)S (3a(TLAlKr)? icrrii/ i) vofxoOtTiKiy to S' apiarov ov tovs vopovs eariv io~)(V€ii>, aAA' avhpa rov pera (Ppoviyreois (3aai- Xlkov. olaff onr} ; 5 NE. 212. Uf) 8y) Xlyeis ; HE. 'On VOp.09 OVK OLU 7T0T€ hvVOLLTO TO T€ apiCTTOV b KOLL TO SlKOLlOTOLTOV CLKplfitOS TTaCftV OLpGL TT6pihaficOV TO fieXTLCTTOV iiriTaTTtiV ai yap avopoLOTiqTes twv re l.iii oi B will. The reason La fchat :i fi.\';v dvOpomivaiV ov8ev ewaiv airXovv eV ovdein nepl cnrdi'Tcou roll ewl iravra tov yjpovov airo^aiueaOaL Teyyrjv ov$ tjvtivovv. ravra 5 8r) crvy)(OL>pov/jL€v ttov ; NE. SO. TV wv ; SE. Tov 8e ye vop.ov bptofiev o~ye8hv eir avTO tovto ^vvTelvovTa, wcnrep tlvol avOpaarov av0d8r] /cat d/uLa0r) Kca paqhiva pcr]8ev eu>vTa iroLtiv napa tt)v io iavrov rd^ii>, parjo^ eirepcoTav fxr]8ei>a, 117)8' dv tl veov dpa tco ijvpLfiaivri fieXnov irapd tov Xoyov ov avros eireTa^ev. NE. 20. 'AXr)6rj' 7tol€l yap areyycos, KaOdirep elprjKas vvv, 6 vop.09 tj/jllv eKaaTOLs. J 5 SE. OvKOVV d8vVCLT0V €V €)(eiP TTpOS TO. flT]8€7rOT€ dirXd to 8ia ttolvtos yiyvofxevov airXovv ; NE. 20. KivSvvevei. HE. Aid tl 8r) 7tot ovv dvayKaiov vop.oOeTeLV, i7T€l8r)7T€p OVK OpOoTdTOV 6 VOpLOS J dvevpeTeOV T0VT0V 20 T7]V CLLTLOLV. NE. 20. Tiiirjv; SE. OvKOVV KOLL Trap V/JLLV 6tCTl TLVES, 0I0LI KOLL €V j». 2. (join prfikv tcov dvOpuTrlvoov,) suffer no art whatever to lay down in any matter any simple rule which shall be applicable to all cases for all time." Cf. Theset. 180 a. 7. in avrb tovto] Sc. to cnrkovv ti a.Tro(j)r]vao~8ai irepi dndv- twv Km eVt TtavTO. tov xpovov. eV ciiito tovto f-WTelvovTa\ " Bending all his energies to this." 8. wanep k.t.X.] E. g. the Creon of Sophocles. Cf. Antig. 705-7 «3- IO. firjKavTi — iirira^v] "Not even if some fresh thing, differ- ent from the terms of his en- actment, should happen to be better for some individual." For a-v^aivr] @e\Tiov, cf. infr. 295 C '. arvp(3aiv6vTcov ciXXcov j3eX- TIOVCOV TOIS KlijXVOVCTlV. 16. 8td ffavTos;] Sc. tov \p6vov. 2 2. Ovkovv Kai -trap vp.1v] This is one of the places where we nOAITIKOS. 139 94. dXXais TroXtaiv, dOpocdv dvOpMiroov daiojaei?, €M"€ 7rpos Spofxov etre TTpos dXXo tl, (jjiXoveiKias eueKa ; NE. 20. Kai irdvv ye ttoXXolL AE. <&€pe vvv dvaXd(3co/jL€i> irdXiv p.vqpir) rots tcov re X^t7 yvpLvafyvTCdv €7r travels eV rai? roiavrais dp- NE. 20. To Trow// ; S*E. 'Or* XeirTovpyeiv ouk ey^copelv rjyovvTou ko.0' e ej/ ;] " In what re- spect ?" 8. XeTTTovpyetv] "To work in minute detail." The word is used above, 262 b, of dividing too minutely at the beginning of an inquiry. The only other passage where the word oc- curs in classical Greek is Eur. Hippol. 923, where it is ap- plied to subtlety in discourse. Another coincidence between the language of these dia- logues and that of the trage- dians. 10. TTaxvrepov\ Opposed to \eiTTovpya.v. " In larger masses. More in the gross." Cf. supr. 277 a-c. Contrast Aristotle's view, that the work of the gymnast and physician regards the individual — fxdWov 8' "icrcos ttjv rovoe, Ka6' eKaarov yap la- Tpevei. Eth. Nic. I. 4. naxvTepov — cos eVt to 7roXu] We find an echo of these words in the language of Aristotle, Eth. Nic. I. I : dyanr^Tov ovv irepl toiovtcov Kai €K toiovtcov Xe- yovTas naxvXcos Kai tvtvco Ta\r]6es ivhe'iKWO-Qai, Ka\ nc-pl tcov cos eirl to no\v Kai 4k toiovtcov Xe- yovTas ToiaiiTa ml 0-vp.nc-paive- adai. 140 nAATQNOS So the law- giver,being unable to provide for ever}' case, enactswhat is generally for the best. He who could pro- vide for every case, could do so, while present, 7ToAv KflL CTTl 7T()AA0V<> Tl]l> TOV AvCTlTeAoVVTOS TOIS p. :< y crco/iaai iroielaOai ra^w. NE. 20. KaAm. SE. Aib Si] ye Kal laovs irovovs vvv fiiSovres 5 6.6 pool's dfia fiev etjopficoaiv, a/xa de Kal Karairavovai Spofxov leal 7raAr)? Kal iravTcov tcov Kara ra acopiaTa TTOVCOV. NE. 2Q. "Eari radra. HE. Kat tou vopoOeTrjv rolvvv rjyco/jieda, rov rai- \ocriv ayeAais erriaTaTrjaovTa rov SiKaiov irepi Kal tcov 7rpb? dAArjAovs ^vp,(3oAalcov, firj 7ro#' Ikclvov yevr\- p. 2<^ o~eo~6ai rrdaiv dOpoois TrpoararTovTa aKpificos evl eKacrrco to 7rpoarjKOv dirobiBovai. NE. 20. To yovv cikos. 15 aE. 'AAAa to tois 7roAAols ye, olfiai, Kal cos €7rl TO 7T0\v Kal 7TC0S OVTCOCTl ira^vTepcos eKacrTois top vbpov Orjaei, Kal iv ypdpp.acrtv onrodiSov? Kal ev dypa/j-paTois, iraTpiois Se eOecri vopcodeTcov. NE. 20. *Op6m. 20 HE. *Opdm fievToi. ttcos ydp av T19 'iKavbs ye- voit dv 7T0T€, co ^coKpaTes, coo~Te Sia (3iov del Trapa- KaOrjpcevo? eKacrTcp Si aKpifieias irpoaTaTTeiv to irpoa- b rJKOv ; eirel tovt av SvvaTO? cbv, cos oipiai, tcov ttjv 1. rrjv — ra|jz/] "To pre- scribe what is profitable for the body." 4. vvv] " As the matter stands." Cf. supr. 291 e. 9. Tais 86£eiev, ov- tcos aftapdvTivos. 13. e'8e\eiv~\ Governed by eiTmfiev, which must be repeated in thought. 15. Tide; ei] Bodl. ti 81j. 1 6. nap' eKelva — inro6eo-6ai] " To suggest other things not contemplated in his former prescriptions." 18. 81a. nvevpara yevopeva] " On account of winds or other heavenly influences which have come unexpectedly out of the usual course." Note the alter- nation of words. 142 IIAATQNOS different course ex- pedient for tients ? And were the law- giver, or another like him, to come again on earth, shall he not be 7Tu>9 Twv €iu)06tu)U ytvofieva, Kaprepcov 8' av r/yoho 8dv pu) €K(3aiveiv rd uphold 7TOT€ voptoOeryOevTa prjTe avrbv TrpoerTCLTTOvTa dXXa fxr/re rbv Kupvovra crept* roXficovTa irapd tcl ypa(f)evra 8pav, v tolov- TCOV VOpLO0€T7] flOLTOdV \ io NE. 20. YlavTairacri p.ev ovv. SE. Ta> 8e rd 8lkcllol 8r] koll dSiKa koll KaXd koll ai(T)(pd koll dyaOd koll KaKa ypdyjfavTi koll aypaipa vopLoOerr/o-CLVTi toll? rcov dv0pa>7rcov dyeXais, biroaaL Kara ttoXlv ev eKacrTais vopLevovrm Kara tovs tcov isypatyavTcov vopLovs, dv 6 /xerd Teyyqs ypdyjsa? rj 1. Kaprepmv — vop.o8eTt]p.aTa>v ;] " But would think it right, both for himself and the sick man, stubbornly to avoid trans- gressing the ancient laws once given, he giving no new com- mandment, and his patient not daring to do otherwise than was prescribed, accounting this the medicinal and wholesome course, any deviation from which is inartistic and un- wholesome : or would every such proceeding in the case of a science or genuine art, in any circumstances involve such lawgiving in the most utter ridicule V 2. rot dpxaia vopodeTrjdevra] I. e. tci air apxfjs vop.. The par- ticiple, as in Soph. Trach. i : apxaios (Pavels. 6. rj nav to toiovtov — T*X v Il\ What is at first expressed ge- nerally in the nominative is resumed in the genitive in a more particular form, by a change of construction like that in Horn. II. Z. 510 : 6 §' dy\a'irj(pi nenoidcos plp(pa e yovva ov rfj aXrjOda yeXolov (paivoiTO ; NE.20. Tlfl^l SE. OlaO' ovv im rw tolovtco Xoyov tov irapa rcoi> iroXXwv Xeyopevov ; NE. 20. Ovk ivvoco vvv y ovrco?. HE. Kat /u?)z/ ev7rp€7rrj9. (fiaal yap 8i) Self, el T19 yiyvooo-Kei irapd tovs twv epLirpocrOev (oeXriovs vopovs, vop.oOe.Teiv tt)v iavrov ttoXlv eKaaTOv TreicravTa, aAAcoy hep.1). NE. 20. T/ ow ; ou/c SpOco? ; SE. 'Io"ws'. a^ 5' ow /x?) 7T6i8g)v tis $La{r)Tai to fieXTLOV, aTTOKpLVOU, TL TOVVOpa TYjS (3la? carat ; Mr) pAvTOi ttco, irep\ 8e tcov epnrpocrOev irpoTepov. NE. 20. Yloiov 8r) Xeyeis ; permitted to change his "\\ 11 appoint- IllOIlt '. The cur- rent saying is specious enough : "Let a man win over his state to accept 10 new laws, and then let him im- pose them." But sup- pose lie force them on her ac- ceptance, what shall 1 5 be said ? 1. tis erepos opoios] I. e. A new lawgiver. Compare Legg. II, 926 C : r) prjv irupovra v Keipeveov vdpcov Kivtlv rj d"Wov elo~v 86^rj \eKvcr8at tov vopov r) imdp- X ei v tov elo~(pepopevov, /cat avTov d8a>ov elvai' edv 8e 5 TTpoxnrdpxcov pdXKov 8okj) KaXcos e\etv rj 6 elo~- (pepopevos, r) ci8ikos, redvdvai tov Kivovvra f) elacptpovTa vopov, em- o~nao~8evTos tov /3/jo^ov. 9. tcov epwpoo-8ev~\ Of the men of former time. 10. vopodeTelv — pr{\ "That he should legislate when he has persuaded his own state, but not otherwise." I 5- n"ep V ' 8e Tcov epirpoo-6ev irpo- Tepov\ " But answer me first with regard to our previous instances, i. e. the physician, &c." 144 nAATQNOS it' a |.ii\ i- oian forced a patient to '1" <'"ll- trary to lion, and the treat- ment so Forced were bi -i. would ii be called iinw bole- some treat- N ,, more should the proceeding of one who forces a state to do a great right con- trary to the laws be called un- righteous. Nor does it make any HE. "Aj> ti? apa fxr) TrtiOow tov laTpevo/ievois, p, iy t\tov Se 6p0a>? T))i> Te^pi^u, irapd to. yeypa/xpcei/a /3eA- TLOV avayKaijj 8pav irulba rj tlvu. avbpa ?; koll yvvaiKa, tl Tovvofia r>;? /3/a? karat tolvti]? ; dp ov lirdv p.dX\ov i) to irapd ti)i> rt\vr)v Xtyofievov dp.dp- Ti]p.u to vocrcodes ; kcu irdvra opOcos ehruv eari c TrpoTepov tw /3iaa0eWt irep\ to tolovtov ttXi^v otl foacoSi] kcu dreyva niirovOev viro twv fitacrapAvoiV IcLTpwv ; io NE. 20. ' ' AXrjOecrTOLTa Xeyeis. HE. T7 8e rifiiv 8r) to Trapa rr)v ttoXltlki-jv reyyr)v dpdpTrjjxa Xeyop.evov Igtlv ; dp ov to alcryjpov koll KaKOU koll clSlkov ; NE. 20. YlavraTTaai ye. iB HE. Tcov 8rj ^Laa6evTu>v irapd ra yeypafi/iei^a I. "Av tis tipa firj nci6a>v tov uiTpevofieuov] Cf. Legg. 3,684 c: Kal prjv rovro yt 01 7roXAot ivpoa- TaTTovcri rots vopoBerais, 07rws TOIOVTOVS 6l'](T0V0~L TOVS VOflOVS OVS enovres 01 dtjpoi koi ra nXr)6rj S«- £ovrai, KaBairep av e'i Tt? yvfxva- o-rals rj tarpols TvpoaraTTOt p,e8' r)8ovr)s Btpanevtiv re Kal Idadat ra 6epaTrev6p.€va aapara. apa] " According to the theory we are considering." 5. irav — voawSes] "Anything rather than the error which is spoken of as a violation of the art, namely unwholesome treat- ment." 6. Kal irdvra — larpmv] " And the man who has been com- pelled in such a case has a right to say anything sooner than that he has suffered un- wholesome and unscientific treatment from the physicians who compelled him." j 1 . Ti Se — eo-nv] " But what is the error which is named as a violation of the political art?" 15. Tffli/ 8rj j3ia(rap,eva>v~\ A redundant and irregular sen- tence. The first genitive is resumed in rwv toiovtoov go- verned by ■v/z-oyov, which is an accusative without an explicit construction, but governed by dire implied in resumes in a more definite construction. " Now in the case of those who are compelled to do contrary to written and hereditary laws, other things more just and better and no- bler than their former doings, say again of the exclaimcr of nOAITIKOS. 145 296. /cat irarpta Spdv erepa SiKaiorepa kol dfielvco kou d KaXXico twv efxTTpoadev, (f)€p€ 9 tov tu>v toioutqjv av \}/oyov irep\ rr}? TOiavrr)? /3/ay, dp', el peXXei fxrj KaTayeXaaTOTaTO? elvai iravTcov, wdvra avTw pdXAov XeKTtov €KdaroT€, 7tXt}v g>? alcr\pd kol aSiKa kou ; kolko: TrtTrovOacTLV 01 (3iaa0evT€? vtto tcov (3iao~a- fxevcov ; NE. SO. ' AXydearara Xeyeis. SE. 'AAA' dpa tdv p.ev ttXovctlos 6 fiiaadpLevos 77, Sifcaia, dv 5' apa wivqs, aSiKa ret fiiacrOe'vTa Icttiv ; 77 kolv 7T€icra? kolv prj ireicras tis, irXovaios rj 7revr)?, rj e Kara ypdpp.ara rj irapd ypdpp,ara, Spa *rd ijvp.(f)opo*, tovtov dec kou Trepi Tama tov opov eivai tov ye dXrj- difference whether he who does so l)e rich or poor. The light of reason and science determin ing what is expedient and just, is the only criterion of good go- vernment : and he who acts by ' this light, howsoever his actions may he de- scribed, is the true ruler. such men about such violence, must not this, to avoid being utterly absurd, say everything rather, on each occasion, than that those who are compelled have suffered what is dishon- ourable and unjust and evil at the hands of those who com- pelled them 1 ?" Cf. Legg. 9, 875 C : eWi ravra eiTrore tls avdpamos, (pvcrei iKavos, 6ela fioLpa yevvtjdels, tvapa\af$eiv bvvarbs e'irj, vopcov ov8ev av beovro tcov dp^ovrcov eavrov. imdTrjprjs yap ovre vopos ovre rdi-is ov8(pia Kpeirrav, ov8e Oepis earl vovv ov- 8ev6s vnrjKoov ovbe 8ov\ov dWa iravTotv apxpvra eivai, enrep a\rj- divbs eXevdepos re ovtcos fj Kara (pvcriv. vvv 8e, ov yap e&Tiv ov- bafjLOV ov8apa>s, dXX' fj Kara. j3pa%v. 816 8r) to 8evrepov alpereov, rdi-iv Kai vopov, a. St) to fiev ws eVt to noXv opa (col /3Ae7r«, to S' eVi ttuv d8vvare'i. lb. 3, 69 1 C. 2. (pepe] Cf. Aristoph. Ach. 541. Stallbaum makes -fyoyov dependent on Xeyav 8a. implied in XeKTeov. Perhaps rightly : but cf. infr. 306 c. 12. *ra %vp.]? to ttjs vea>v ovtcos dpyeiv 8vvxp.e'va>v opdi] ylyvoir dv 7ro\iTela, ttjv Trjs Teyvt]? pdopLl-jV TCOV VOpLCOV TTOLpeyOpLeVLOV Kpe'lTTCO J KOU 7TaVTCX ttoiovctl roh epLffipoaiv dpypvcriv ovk eo~Tiv a/idprr/pa, io pceyjUTrep av ev peya o~i. to pera vov — Biavepovres] Cf. Legg. 4, 714 a : ttjv tov vov biavoprjv enovopd£ovres vopov. 12. o~d>£eiv ts — Kal dpeivovs dnoTeXelv] For, as Aristotle afterwards said, the end of a city is not life merely, but a good life. Cf. supr. 293. ofot re wen] In apposition with (pv'XdTTcocri. 14. napd ye — e'lpr/raij " At least in contradiction to what has now been said." The re- spondent wishes to reserve his opinion on the main point, like Adeimantus in Piep. 6, 487 b: Trpos pev ravrd aoi oioels av 0109 T e'irj avrenrelv aXXct yap . Cf. Gorg. 475 e : ov pot. 8oice~i Kara ye tovtov tov Xoyov. 16. eKeiva] P. 292 e. nOAITIK02. 147 *y7 NE. 2fi. Ta 7roia etVey ; aE. 12? ou/c ai> 7rore 7rXr}$09 ovft cdvtlvoovovv tyjv roiavTiju Xafiov €7riaTr)/JLr]i> oiov r av yevovro fiera c vov BioiKtiv ttoAlv, dXXd irep\ afUKpov tl koll oXiyov /cat to ev €(ttl ^Tiyreov tyjv fiiav eKeivrjV irokLTeiav ty)V bpdrjv, ras 8' aAAay \iL\n~ipaTa Oereou, axrirep /cat oXiyov irpoTepov epprjOrj, ras jxev eVt tol kclXXlovcl, ray be eVt tol alayia) pLLp.ovp.evas TavTijv. NE. 212. 11 coy ; tl tout eiprjKas ; ovSe yap dpTL SrjOev KCLTepaOov to 7rep\ tcov pLLpypLaTcov. £?E. Kat pjrjv ov (j)avX6v ye, av Kivqaas tls tov- tov top Xoyov avTOv KaTafiaXr) /cat firj SieXOcov evdel- d ijrjTai to vvv yiyvopLevov dfxdpTrjfjia 7rep\ ovto. Still leBS can the former pro- position, that scien- tific go- 5 vernment must of necessity- be in the hands of very few : and that the other forms are imitations, IO more or less imper- fect, of this. This is a weighty truth, especially 2. ovK covtivcovovv] I. e. Whe- ther rich or poor. 7. ra? pev — pipovpevas rav- rr]v\ An epexegetic or redun- dant clause. 9. Has ti tovt c'ipr]Kas\ Cf. Leg'g. 12, 968 C : 7TCOS Tl TOVTO elprjadai pev av ; which the Zurich editors have pointed differently, putting a mark of interrogation after iras. If this is right, it should be ap- plied consistently to all such expressions, e. g. nag ; tI tovt ernes ; which is of frequent occurrence. apri] P. 293 e. 10. 8rj8ev~] "I suppose." He had accepted the former state- ment, but is now forced to confess that he had not under- stood it. That Srjdev is not always ironical appears from Herod. VI. 138 : rt 8rj dv8pa>- Bevres 8r)8ev iroir]o~ovo-i ; and similar uses of it are more frequent in later Greek. Schol. Apoll. Rh. (quoted in the Paris Stephanus) : to 8r)6ev nore pev n\rjpa>pa.TiK6v, 7TOTe 8e cLvt\ tov drj'Xabt) 77 as 8tj. Compare the use of SrjTTovdev, Phileb. 62 e, Ion 534 a. Badham, who objects to the word, very plausibly conjectures prjBev. 1 1. Kat prjv irepX ui/to] "And yet it were a remark of no little weight, even if one merely threw it out and left it, without discussing and making plain the error which men now com- mit in this matter." dv Kivrjcras avTov Kara- /3dX?;] " If, having started this question, one should leave it where he took it up." For avTov used metaphorically as here, cf. Gorg. 490 : "E^e S?) avTov. 13. to vvv — dpdprr]pa] I.e. The capricious defiance of law, which is worse even than the maintenance of imperfect laws. See infr. 300 a, b. U 2 148 I1AAT0NO2 when Fol- lowed into its applica- tions : u hen by in.i\ be revealed ill.' error into « bich politicians now-a-daya are fallen. Their best course is to follow tin- traces of the p.iTrct state which have been preserved in laws ; although the main- tenance of law is only a second- best course, and not ideally the best. This ap- pears, if we consider the origin of law, as we may do under a familiar image. NE. 20. Wolov 8/) ; p. HE. Totov8e tl Set ye tflTelv, ov irdvv £6vr)0e? ovSe padtov ISetV o/xco? pi]v netpcofxeOa Xaftetv avro. (j)e'pe yap' bpdrjs rjpuv llovy)? ovarjs TavTiy? rrj? ttoXl- 5 re/ay, i)v etpi]Kap.ev, oiaO* art ras a'AAa? Set rots- tolvti]? auyya.pp.aaL ^pwiievag ovtco acoteaOat, Spcoaa? to vvv e7ratvovp.evov, Kaiirep ovk opOo- Tarov bv ; NE. 20. To TToiov ; IO HE. To irapd tovs voptovs p.r]Sev p.r)8eva ToXptav irotelv tcov ev ry wbXet, tov ToXp.covTa Be OavaTco {ripuovaOai Kal iraai toIs eayarois. Kal tovt eartv e bpOoTora Kal KaXXiaT e\ov, u>s SevTepov, eiretSav to wpcoTOV TL5 p.€Ta0fj to vvv Srj prjOev. d> 8e Tpoiro) 15 yeyovos eaTt tovto b Srj SevTepov efprjaaLiev, Stairepa- v(op.€$a. T) yap ; NE. 20. Haw /xev ovv. HE. Ety Sr] Tas etKovas eiravtcopev uaXtv, ah dvayKalov diretKa^etv del tous fiaatXiKOvs ap- 2o\0VTa9. NE. 20. no/ay; *9 2. Set ye ^reiv] "We must certainly examine — with what success Ave may." 5. tjV elprjKapev] P. 293, viz. That which is guided by the consciousness of what is best, in which, according to the lan- guage of the Republic, philoso- phers are kings. 7. ovk 6p66raTov\ Cf. supr. 294 d : eneidrjTrep ovk opdorarov 6 vop,os. 13. as devrepov] Cf. Legg. 9> 875 c, quoted above. eneidav — pr\6kv\ " When one has withdrawn from the first and best principle, which we described just now." 15. &ianepava>pe6a. r) yap j] Cf. Theaet. 173 C : \eya>p.ev 8rj, cos eoiKev . 18. iivavicdp.ev irakiv ] The image of the physician was employed above, p. 293. But the yevvaios KV^epvr^rrjs seems to be an echo of Rep. 6, 488 a. Cf. also Legg. 12, 963 b, and Arist. Pol. III. 2, where the virtue of a citizen is infez-red from that of a sailor. nOAITIKOS. 14!) ,;97. J^E. TW yevvaiov KvfiepvrjTrjv koll tov irepcov iroWcov olvtol^lov larpov. KaTibtoptv yap 8r) tl o~yr)p.a ev tovtols olvtols TrXaaapevoi. NE. 20. Ylotiv tl ; 98. £?E. Toiovde, olov el TravTes nepl avTcov 8tavorj- 6elp.ev otl BavoTara vn clvtcdv irdcr^opev. ov pev yap av eOeXrjacoaLV rjpcov tovtcov eKtXTepoL (reopens, 6/XOLC09 8rj ct(o(ov(tii>, ov 8* av \cofiao-6ai fiovXrjOcocTL, XcofiwvTai TepvovTes Kal KaovTes Kal 7rpoo~TaTTOvT€? dvaXcoptaTa (pepetv Trap eavTovs olov (popovs, cbv ap.LKpd p}v els tov KoifivovTa Ka\ oi>8ev dvaAicrKovai, Suppose men, indig- nant at the harm done by the ca- price of physicians and pilots, devised a constraint for them by calling an oligarchi- cal or de- mocratic assembly, where all ( who chose might speak, and the advice 1. erepav ttoW&v dvTat-iov] Horn. II. A. 514 : 'Irjrpos yap avfjp 7roWa)V aurd^ios dWcov. 2. tl u kol ev ols. deferred by the explanation of this clause, and the sense is resumed and continued in el 8fj k.t.X., infra. 10. olov qbopovs] The physi- cian, as being an image of the king, is made to assume a kingly o- X npa. 1 1 . crpiKpd — Kal oiSer] " Little or nothing." Cf. Theset. 173 e. The influence of the following- argument appears in Ar. Pol. II. 5 '• e '*" yovv Tv dXXcov eTTL- o-Trjpmv tovto avvevrjvoxev olov laTpiKr) Kivrjdelo-a irapd to. Tzdrpia, v Texv&v, oi yap onoiov to KLve'iv Te^vrju Kal vopoV 6 yap vopos la\vv ov8epiav e\eL Trpos to ireiQeo-Qai ttXtjv Bid to edos k.t.X. lb. III. 1 1 : to 8e t£)v rexveov elvaL 8oKel irapdheLypa y\re\)8os, otl to Kara ypdppara larpeveadaL (pavXav .... enel Kal tovs laTpovs orav vnoiTTevcoo'L neLO-QevTas roty ex&pols 8ia(p6eipeiv 8ia Kep8os, TOTe Ttjv eK T&v ypaupaTcov depa- TTeiav £r)Tr]0-aiev av pdXXov. 5. olov el] The apodosis is 150 riAATONOS of unpro- fessional persons mighl often be pre- Eerredj and ii\ there making decrees for the re- gulation of the prac- tice of na- vigation and medi- cine, which should be binding on those pro- fessions for all time. rots $ aXXois avrol re kou o'l oiKtrai yjpuwTaV kgu p. 2t 8i] kou TeAevTGovTe? ?} irapac ^vyyevwv ?) irapa tlvu>v b e\6pwv tou KapLvovTO? xprjfiaTa puaOov XapifidvovTe? aTTOKTLvvvacnv. 61 r au Kv^pvryrai ptvpia ere pa roi- 5 avra epyd^ovrai, KaraXemovris re eK tivos tTrifiovXrjs ev tolls dvaycoycu? epyfiovs, kou ac^aXpara •Koiovvres Iv rots ireXdyeaLV €K(3dXXovaii> els rrjv OdXarrau, kou erepa KaKOvpyovaiv. el 8)] ravra SiavorjOevres (3ov- Xevcratp.eOa irepi avruiv (3ovXr)v tlvol, rovroav tcov lore^ycov pLi]K€Tt eTTirpeireiv ap)(€ii> avroKpdropi p.r)8e- c repq. ptrjT ovv SovXcov pafjT e'XevOepcov, ijvXXe'ijou 8e tKKXr)(riav r)p.a>i> avru>i>, r) ^vpLiravra rov Sr}p.oi> y rov? ttXovctlovs p.6voi>, e^eivai Be kou IBmatiov kou rtov aXXcou 8-qp.iovpywv irepl re nXov kou wept voaoov vbyvcajju-jv ijvpifiaXe'o-Oai, kv pi)T e\ev- de'pav] " No, not over slaves, still less freemen." See the picture of the slave physician of slaves in Legg. 4, 720. 13. e£elvai he — hrjpiovpycov] Sub. anviovv. Cf. Prot. 319 d, Gorg. 456. KOI l8l(OTO>V KCU T0)V ciXXav 8qpiovpyS>v] " Other," i. e. than physicians and pilots. Cf. Protag. 319 c, d. 15. Kad' o tl XPV erepa rot- avra] " What is to be the me- thod of using drugs and sur- gical instruments in our treat- ment of the sick, and vessels also, and the tackling of ves- sels in navigation, and in en- countering dangers, whether those incident to the voyage in the shape of winds and waves, or in encountering an affray with pirates, or perhaps the necessity of fighting at sea with old-fashioned galleys against an armada of the like build." The words 7rp6s rds — Toiavra, though in point of meaning explanatory of irepl tovs Kivbuvovs, return to the construction with naff on xpl — XP r ) (T ^ at — 1 "°' J ttXoiois. IIOAITIKOS. 151 298. rjfJ.a.9 kou toIs iarpiKois bpydvots 7rpbs tovs Kap.vovras d XPW@ a h KaL $t) KOLL TOLS TtXoLOIS T€ OLVTols KOU TOIS vavTiKois bpyavois els Tr\v tcoi> irXoloov yjpeiav koCl irepl tovs klv8vvovs tovs re irpos olvtov rov irXovv ape/mow kou 0aXaTTi]s irepi kou irpos tols toIs XrjcrTous ?, evTev^eis, kou eav vavpLayeiv apa Serj irov paKpois ttXolols wpbs erepa tolclvtoC tol 8e tu> irXi)6eL 86^avra irep\ tovtojv, ewe tivgjv larpwv kou KvfiepvrjTwv e\r aXXcov 18lootcov £vp.$ovXevbvToov, ypco\ravjas ev Kvp- fieal Tiai kou o-Tr)Xous, ra be kou dypa(pa irarpia 10 e 6ep.evovs eOr], Kara tglvt rf8i] navra tov eireiTa \pbvov vavTiXXecrdou kou tols tcov kcl/jlvovtoov depa- Treias iroieiaOou. NE. 20. KopuSfj ye e'lprjKas aroTra. 3?E. Kar' eviavrov 8e ye apyovTas KaOlaraaOai 15 Then sup- . / a ,1 ~ v / ,/> -o,/ pose them tov TrXrjUovs, eire e/c tcov irXovcrioiv eire €/c tov or/pov to elect iravTOS, bs av KXrjpovpLevos Xayyavr^ tovs 8e Kara- annually, either by The present is of course a and Persians, which alter not." wholly imaginary case. The In the same spirit he recals the larpav aipeats alluded to in the old word Kvp(3eo~i just below. Gorgias, 455 b, is not the de- 8. elV aXKav ldia>Tu>v] " Or cision of the question who are else private citizens." The to be physicians, but the selec- Platonic use of SXXos already tion of certain physicians for noticed. Cf. Gorg. 473 c : vno some public duty connected tS>v ttoAm-wi/ koI tS>v a\\a>v £evwv. with their profession. Cf. Ar. 11. 77877 tov hrara xpovov vav- Pol. III. 6 : So-irep ovv larpbv Set riXXea-dai] Cf. Soph. Antig". 8i86vai ras evdvvas iv larpols, ovrw 7 I *J '. vnriois Kara GTpe\j/as to tovs aWovs ev Tols 6p,olois. Xoinov o~e\p.acriv vavriXXfraL. 6. paKpoU 7r\olois] The most 15. Se ye] " Yes, and more- antiquated kind of fighting over." vessel, of which Plato speaks 17. 6s — \ayxdvrj] This seems as an English writer of the to refer only to « tov 8r]jiov present day might of the old -navros, see infr. e : 77 tS>v — Xn- three-decker. He imagines the x° VTas - effect of perpetuating such a The practical and speculative mode of warfare in written physician are again contrasted laws, like those of " the Medes in illustration of the lawgiver's 152 IIAATQNQ2 vote or lot, til. is,- to whom au- thority in each de- partment should l"' given. Who, when their term of office had expired, might be summoned before an unprofes- sional court, and perhaps condemned and pun- ished for breaking the written regulations in their art. Not con- tent with this, sup- pose them to enact, that who- ever is found in- quiring (iravras avTav rj pr) koXcos fX €l > H- l 9- $ € ^ av l] KQ i i£ evbs o-Toparos irdvTas irvp(pa>- velv wj Tvavra Kakws Keirac devTcov deav k.t.X. And for the ex- pression, Legg. 5, 741 e : 7rp6r tovtols 8' stl vopos eTTCTai nao-L TOVTOLS. nOAITIKOS. 153 599. TOVTOl?, OiU T19 KV(3€pV)]TlKr]V KOLL TO VOLVTIKOV 1] TO vyieivov koll larpiKrjs aXrjdeiav irepl irvevfiaTa re km 6epp.d koll yf/vxpci ^tjtcov (paii>r]Tai irapa tol ypdppaTa KOU aO(f)l,{pp€VOS QTIOVV 7T€pl TO. TOiaVTCl, TTpWTOV plv fxrjTe larpiKOV olvtov prjTe KvfiepvrjTiKov bvop.d^Lv dAAd pceTecupoAoyov, a8oAeo~)(r)v Ttvd ao(j)LcrTr]v, d6' toy BiatyOeipovTa aAAovs vewTtpovs koll avairdOovTa c hriTiOeo-Qai KvfiepvrjTiKrj koll laTpiKrj pLrj /cara i>6p.ov?, a A A' avTOKpoLTopa? ap\eiv tu>v ttAolwv koll t&v voa- ovvtcov, ypatydpevov eladyetu tov fiovAopevov, oh ti^ecrTiv, els Srj tl BiKacrT-qpLov. av 8e irapa tovs vopiovs Ka\ to. yeypap.peva So^t) ireiOeiv eire veov? e'/re 7rpecr(3vTa?, KoAatjtiv tois ia^aTOLS. oi)8ev ydp into the tlUtll Of medicine and n.'ivi- ion, and is therein " wise l><- yond what 5 is written," lie shall first be called no artist, but a dreamer or a prating sophister, and then be publicly indicted of corrupting the youth, and per- suading them to address themselves 2. Trvev/iaTa] " Winds," as affecting health. Cf. supra 295 d '. {-vpffaivovTcov aWav /3eX- tiovcov to"ls Kapvovcri did irvevpaTa rj ti Koi aXXo. Kai deppd koi yfrvxpd] I. e. the more general inquiry which in- cludes the subject of winds. 6. peTeiopoXoyov, ddoXicrxrjv riva !• tu)u v6fia>v dvai cro(f)U)T€pov ovde'isa yap ayvoeiv p- to re larpiKOv Kcii to vyieivov ov8e to KvfiepvmiKov Kai vavTLKov' t^eivai yap tw /3oL>Ao/xeW p.av6aveiv yeypap.fitva Kal iraTpia 607] Ktlfieva. Tama 8rj irep'i d 5 re Tamas tcls £irL0-T7)\xa9 Xeyo- jJLtv, (6 ^.ooKpaTe?, Kal GTpaT-qyiKrjs Kal tjvp.7racrr)? -qaTLVoaovv Q-qpevTLKrjs Kal ypa(f)iKrj$ rj ^vp.Trao~r)9 fxepo? otiovv fjLifxrjTiKrj? Kal TeKTOviKrj? Kal ^vvoXrjs biroiaarovv aKtvovpyias rj Kal yecopyla? Kal tyjs irepl lord (fivTct ijvvoAi]? re'^^y, 17 Kal Tiva i7r7rov ra pa- SrjfiaTa ov TrdpnoXv Kexooplcrdai. dpidprjTiKrjv, i\riXr)v iv ra^e- aiv] Supra 258 c, 284 e. 2. elr iv (UdOecnv eir iv rd^e- v dpidpcov 8iavopds kcu iroiKiXcreis, ocra re avrol iv eavTois ttoikiWovtcii kcu ocra iv prjKcai Kal iv fiadecri noiKiXpaTa, kcu 8r) Kal ev v vvv 8f8r]p(.ovpyT]pevav oi/'re rt KaXXiova ovt atc^ia), ttjv avrrjV 8e T€X vr l v dneipyacrpeva. KA.QavpaaTOV Xeyeis. AG.Noyno- deriKov pev ovv Kal ttoXitikov vrrep- (BaXXovTcoc. 6. AtjXov — to Trapdnav, infr. apa ov — KaKov, dpapTrjpaTOS jjvyypappaTcov] Note the tragic cadence of these clauses. X 2 [56 IIAATONOS Bui things would tall into -till greater confusion , if i he men appointed mart ments disregard- ed them, not in the interest of but of their owi private For the laws have at least some basis of experi- ence and of plausible counsel. Hence if laws are made, it is best, though only second best, that they should be en- forced. HE. TV <5e roSe ; a Kara avyypap.\xaTa fxev av- p. y- ayKatpi/iev Zkolcttov yiyveadai tqjv elpi]fjevo)v koll tois avyypa.jj.ij.aaiu rj/jaiv e7riaTaTelv tov yetpoTovrjOevTa 7) Xa^ovra e'/c Tvyr/s, ovtos 8e fn]8ev (fjpovTiQuv rwf sypafjfjaToov i] fcepSovs kveKev tlvos 77 yapLTOS i8ia? irapa ravra eircyeLpol 8pav erepa, /xrj8ev yiyvcoaKcov, dpa ov tov Kaicov tov irpoaOev fiei^ov av en tovto yiyvotTO KaKov ; NE. 2ft. 'AA^eo-rara. 10 3?E. Ylapa yap olfiat tov? vofxovs tov? e'/c Treipas b 7roAA^9 Keifievovs Kal tlvcov ^v/j(3ovXcov eKaaTa ya- pi6i>T(o? tjv/jfiovXevadvTcov koll 7reiadvTCov Oe'aOai to ttXtJOos, 6 irapd Tama ToXfidw 8pav, d/iapTrjfiaTOs dfidpT^fja 7To\\a7r\daiov direpyatpixevos, dvaTpeiroL \liraaav av wpaljiv en /jeitpvo? tqjv ijvyypa/jfxaTcov. NE. SO. Urn 8' ov pceXXtL ; SE. Aid TavTa 8rj toIs nepl otovovv vopiovs koll ^vyypdjjjiaTa TiOe/jevoi? 8evTepos 7rXov? to irapa c TavTa ixr/Te eva firjTe ttXyjOos pL7]8ev fxr)8eiroTe eav zo8pav por}8' otlovv. IO. Ilapa yap otpai ] The sentence begins with an under- stood subject, viz. ovtos supra, but as the irp6rao~is lengthens this is forgotten, and hence, in resuming, the article is intro- duced : 6 Tvapa ravra roXpiov bpav. ii. x a P l e VTa >s] I. e. by right opinion without science. Cf. Ar. Eth. Nlc. I. 3 : ol — X a P l - earepoi. Pseudo-Zaleuc. ap. Stob. (Mul- lach.p.543a): rebv §e Keipevav vo- pa>v iav ris 8oKrj prj Ka\a>s neio'dai, perariQevat, in\ to fiekriov. pev- nvrtov 8e, ndvras neidapxelv' as vn avdpimwv pev fjrrao-6ai rovs Keipevovs vopovs ov koXov ov8e avpepepov, virb be vopov (3e\rlovos Tjrraipevov KaraKpareladai na\ «a- \6v Ka\ avpv ivkovo-mv ■jiKrjBos. Note the emphatic accumulation of negatives. D0AITIK02. 157 }oo. NE. 20. 'Opdm. AE. Ovkovv pipy para pev av eKaarcov ravra eh] rrJ9 a\r}0eias, ra, irapa rcov eldorcov eh Svvapiv elvai yeypappeva ; NE. 20. n«? $ ov ; SE. Kal prjv rbv ye elSora ecpapev, rbv ovrws ttoXltlkov, el pepvrjpeOa, iroi)]aeiv rfj re\vy iroXXa eh rrjv avrov irpa^iv rcov ypapfxdrcov ovSev (j)pov- d rl^ovra, birbrav aXX avrco (3eXrlco So^rj irapa. ra ye- ypappeva v(j) avrov /cat eirearaXpeva airoval tlo-lv. NE. 20. 'E(papev yap. SE. Ovkovv dvr]p bartaovv eh y irXrjdos briovv, ols av vbpoi Kelpevoi rvyyavcoo~i, rrapd ravra 6 rt av emyeiprjcrcdO-L Troielv cos fie'Xriov erepov 6v, ravrbv dpcocri Kara, Svvapiv oirep 6 aXrjOivbs eKelvos ; NE. 20. Haw pev ovv. HE. 'Ap ovv el pev aveiriar^poves ovres rb roi- ovrov Bpcoev, pipeiaOai pev av eiriyeipolev rb dXi]6es, Such insti- tutions are at least an imitation of the truth. But IS whoever contra- venes them for the sake of the general good, as- sumes the 2. piprjpaTa — rrjs dXr/Oeias ] Compare the account iu Eep. 6, goo, 501, of the procedure of the TToXireicbv £mypa(poi. The word yeypappeva here contains associations both from writing (cf. ypdppara above and eVe- araXjiiva below) and painting, as appears from the word piprjpaTa. emo-Tcov — ttjs dXrjdeias] For the structure of this, cf. Phasdo 65 d : tS>v akXav . . . dnavrcov rrjs ovaias. 3. napa tusv elhoTv. Or, perhaps, because the injunctions continued in force during his absence. 13. irapa TavTa — ov] "When- ever they do contrary to what is written in their laws, in the belief that another course is better." other than the law- giver in person. Hence the nearest approach which can be made 158 IIAATON02 function of pipolvT av p.evTOi ixav /ca/cwy el 5' evTeyvoi, rovro p. 30 the law- > ,/ „ , , , , \ \ , ~ , river. ovk ecrTiv eTi pipy pa, aXX olvto to aX^OeaTaTOV e t Inly we , have seen exeivo ; mass of NE. 20. YlaVTGOS 7T0V. poor' or 5 EE. Kal pijv epirpooOe ye aypoXoyrjpevov rjpiv competent KtlTai p.7)8eV 7rXr)0O? fJ.rjS' TjVTlVOVV ftwOLTOV tLVOLl Xa- to do this. ~. „ / And if an (3eLV TeyVIJV. individual -vj-17, ^/-j u ~ \ -? do this, he WE. 212. Keirai yap ovv. can be no >—it? /■>»«» \ v n \ ' ' v Ah*. Uvkovv ei pev eari pacriXtKT] tls Teyyr), to iotqjv 7r\ovcri(x>v irXr/dos kou 6 £vprras drjpos ovk av 7T0T6 XafioL TTjV 7ToXlTLKr)l> TaVTTjV €7T LCTTr) fl7]l> '. NE. 20. Ha>? yap av ; SHE. Aet 8r) tol$ TOiavTas ye, d>9 eoiKe, iroXiTeias, ^rnmeift ' eL p.eXXovcrL KaXcos ty]v akr]6ivr]v eKelvrjv ttjv tov eVo? by states, 15 ytterct te)(vt]9 apypvTOs TroXiTelav eh 8vvap.iv pipL-qcra- p. 301 the strict aOat, p.r)8eiroTe Keipevav avTols tg>v vop.a>v p.rj8ev of the laws -jroieiv Trapa. To, yeypappeva /cat iraTpia edrj. etna, cus- tomsof NE. 20. KdXXlCTT e'lpTjKas. their fore- ' * fathers. 3*E. OrCCZ/ a/JOC Ot 7rX0VCTL0l TaVTTJV flL/JLCOVTai, rich do so, 20 rore apicrTOKpaTiav KaXovpLev ttjv TOiavTrjV ttoXl- itiSarl " ' . « ' *v «* / v , ;*. », stocracy; TeiaV OTTOTaV 0€ TCOV VO/100V /XT) (bpOVT^COCTLV, oAl- when they , neglect the yapyiav. oligarchy. NE. 20. K^oWeuet. When one _ Vf , 9 ^ „ x , rules ac- A Hi. i\.cu /x?;^ oiroTav av ^tis* eis apxy Kara vo- cording to , \ y / a « / » „ law, it is 25 p.ovs, pLip.0vp.ev09 tov eiricrTr]pova, paaiXea kclAov- royalty; > 5, ,y. , , x » > / * when in \**V, Of OLOpiCflVTeS OVOJJLaTl TOV p.€T eTTLaTyfXrjS Tj h spite of jv 1 >- \ / law, falsely 00^77$- /car a i/o/iow p.ovapxovvTa. 1. 7rai/] Cogn. or adv. ace. 24. av *ns* ] MSS. aWiy. as in irav Tovvavrlov. Cf. Legg. The correction is due to 4, 718 e : 7rac dyanrjTov. Badham. Cf., however, Soph. 2. ovk — ert fi'ifirjfia] Cf. Soph. Trach. 1 234: flJ]Tp\ fiep Baviiv 240 a : erepov 8e Xe'yets rotovroj/ — aot t avBis as e\fis e^etv. aKrjdivov ; Cratyl. 432 C 26. rj bogrjs Kara vopovs] The nOAITIKOS. 1 5<) 3° i. NE. 20. ¥>.Lv8vvevopLev. SE. O^/COW KOLV TLS apa €7rKTT7]/JL(Ol> 0UTC0S OiV CIS ct-PXy? iravTcos to ye bvopa tclvtov (3ao~iAevs kcll ov8ev eTepov 7rpoo-pi]@i]creTai' 81 a 8rj to. ixevTe bvopaTa rcov vvv Aeyop-e'vcov iroXtTemv ev pcovov yeyovev. 5 NE. 20. "Eot/ce yovv. SiE. Tt 8' otolv prjre Kara vop.ovs p.rfe Kara edrj c irpaTTrj tls els ap^cou, irpoairoLrjTaL 8e eocnrep 6 eiri- aTypLcov, w? apa it apa. to. yeypappeva to ye /3e'A- tlcttov 7roir)Teov, rj 8e tls eiriOvpua kol ayvoia toutovio affecting wisdom, tyranny. And when one rules by wisdom, and is su- perior to the laws, this too is royalty, but in a sense which an- nihilates the other so-called govern- ments. words koto, vopovs are a limita- tion of fiera 86£r]s — povapxovvTa, not of e7naTi]ij.T]s, and distin- guish the constitutional mo- narch from the tyrant. 4. 6Y a 8fj — yeyovev] "Where- fore we have found that the five names of the constitutions, of which men now speak, are resolved into one only." Badham corrects A (i.e.rerra/ja) bfj Ta 77evre ovo/xara to>v Xe- yopevcov trokireiaiv povov yeyovev. But how can the five have be- come four, when the fifth kind immediately reappears ; and all five are enumerated just below? It is true that the distinction of knowledge or ignorance (or of the better and worse imitation of know- ledge) is substituted for the distinction between persuasion and force. But this applies in a measure to apio-TonpaTia and oXiyapxla as well as to PaaiXeia and Tvpawis. The true fiao-ikevs is only introduced here in order to define the tyrant who affects to act the same part ; and the words Si' a — yeyovev recall the assertion of supr. 293 c, that the government of knowledge was the only go- vernment (8ta(pep6vTa>s 6p6i)v ml p,6vr]v iroXireiav), and the rest not governments but imita- tions of government, some better and some worse. Cf. also supr. 300 e : ttjv ahrjdtvriv eneivrjv, ttjv tov evos. pera rexm/s apxovros. infr. : tov eva iicelvov povap^ov. 302 e : ttjv opdrjV £77- Tovo~i tovto to rprjpa ovk r/v Xprjo-ipov. For vvv, cf. 291 e: irpbs to (Hiaiov ivov v apTi 8ieXr]\v8apev oaa Xeyov- o~iv ol noXXoi. 8 . wpoo-ivoirjTai — eTno-Trjpcov ] Sc. npaTTetv. Compare the el- lipse of the infinitive after '() rTAATONOS The reason of these forms i*, that the true mon- arch is no- where to he found : and men, despairing of his ad- vent, have had re- course to convention and law. tov pi.pyp.aTO? ijyovpevr/, p.cov ov tot* tov toiovtov p. 30 tKaorrov Tvpavvov k\i]T€Ov ; NE. 2Q. TV p.i]v ; 3E. Ovrco 8rj Tvpavvos re ye'yove, (frapev, /cat 5 fiacrikevs /cat oXiyapyjia /cat upiaTOKparia /cat 8r]po- Kparia, hvaytpavavTozv tcov dvOpcorrcov tov eva eKel- vov povap^ov, /cat aV laTrjaavTcov prjhiva rr)? TOiavrrj? dpXV? d'tjiov av yeveaOai irore, ware lOeXeiv /cat d SvvaTOV elvai fierd dperi}? /cat einaT-qprj? apyovTa rd 10 diKaca /cat oaia hio.vip.ziv opOco? 7racrt, Att>/3aa-#at <5e /cat cmoKTivvvvai /cat kolkovv ov av fiovArjOfj eKaarore rjp.cov' eVet yev6p.evov y d.v olov Aeyopcev, ay air da Boll re av /cat oIk€lv dLaKvfiepvcovTa evdaLpovcos opdrjv aKpificDS pLOVOV 7T0\lT€LaV. 15 NE. 20. llwy tfou; HE. Nw £e ye birore ovk eart yiyvopevos, a>? 8rj (fiapev, iv rai? iroXecn ^aaiXev? o!os iv o-pLrjveo-iv ipKpverai, to re acopia evOijs /cat ttjv ^vyr^v oia(pipcov e the individual in a state of " tyranny" in book 9, esp. 572 e, sqq. 4. K(ii Pacrikevs] In the former of the two senses mentioned above. 7. Ka\ CLTnarr-qaavrav] Com- pare the language of Aristotle and of Plato himself in the Laws, already quoted supr., notes on pp. 294, 296. 10. XeofiacrSai Se] Sc. fjyov- fievcov navTa riva av, supplied fl'Oni dm rS)V 7roWa>v Ka- rrjyopei, dXXolav rot 86t-av e£ovo~i.v k.t.X. 14. fiovov] Masculine. Note the inverted order and tragic rhythm. 1 6. onoTe ovk eari yt.yv6p.evos] " Since there does not arise a king in states as in hives (at least so we think), one un- mistakeably surpassing both in body and mind, it follows that we are obliged to meet and make enactments." For this meaning of Snore = quoniam, cf. Euthyd. 297 d, and com- pare Ar. Pol. III. 8. 18. to re oSijia evdvs] I. e. At the first glance, before his 110AITIK02. 161 {oi. eis, Set 8rj avveXOovras ^vyypdppara y parens, &>$■ eoiK€, pLtTadeovTCLS TO. 7-779 d\r)0€pevr) 502. iravri KarddrjXo? d>9 irdvr dv SioXe'aeie rd # eV carry* yiyvoptva. r\ Ikuvo i]piv Oavpaareov paXXov, d>9 iayypov ri ttoXis earl (Pvaei. ; irdaypvaai yap 8rj roiavra at 7roX€is vvv yjpovov airepavrov, opens euiat rives avrcov p6vtp.oi re elcrt K.a\ ovk avarpeirovrai' 5 And do we wondi 1 that ninny evils should arise in states thus based on ignorant custom ? Ought 10 we not rather to admire the strength of the social bond which can endure this strain ? For there are still mental qualities can be known. Cf. Ar. Pol. VII. 13 : El pev toL- vvv t'irjcrav toctovtov 8iav dpxdvTcov, 8r/Aov on j3e\riov alel tovs avrovs pev cipxciv tovs S' apxeo-6ai KaBaira^' inel 8e tovt 011 pa8iov kajSelv, oi8e eartp, ao-wep ev "lv8ois Cprjal 2kl»Aci£ eivai tovs (3acri\eas toctovtov 8iav dpxop.ei'a>v, qbavepov, k.t.A. 2. peTctdeovTas — "x vr l ] Cf. Soph. 226 a : Toiov8e ti peTade- ovTas 'lx vos 0-vtov. Perhaps there is a slight allusion to the Homeric per Ixvia ^alve Se'oio. Cf. Phffidr. 266 b. 7- TTJS KpT]7Tl80S TTjS 7TpOT- Toio-rjs ] Viz. a responsible executive. 9. irepa^ Sc. dpxrj, 01' re^i/r;, which is naturally suggested by the preceding argument. irpocrxpoypevj] ] Sc. toiovtt) Kpr)Tr"i8i. Stephanus conjectured 27 from the version of Ficinus : quo si alia qusedam gubernatio vel civitas utatur. But for the asyndeton, which is as- sisted by ttcivtX K.aTa8rfKos as a kind of particle, cf. the usage with 7rdvT(0s, e. g. supr. 268 e. Badll. COllj. 7rpaTT0vcrr]s, f) rrpdgis erepa. 10. *ra €7r' avTjj* ] MSS. tcl TavTT], Badh. corr. Tan avTJj. Qy. vtt' aiirf] 1 11. ens Icrxvpov ti ttoXis eori (pvaei] Compare Lcgg. 4, 708 e : efieXkov ~keyeiv cos ov8els Trore dvOpomcov ov8ev vop.o8eTei, Ti>xai 8e Ka\ £vp(popa). navTolai ninTov- crai TravTolcos vapodtTovcri tci Trdi'Ta rfplv. 14. p6vip,oi\ E.g. Sparta. Cf. Legg. 3, 686 a, b. 1 62 HAATONOS i-it 'us 01 men which have exist- ed from uiikiiou D time, though many from age to age are seen to founder, like ships at sea, through the preten- tious igno- rance of their pilots and mari- ners. Now let us ask which of these bad go- vernments noXXai jii]v evlore /cat Kaddirep irXola Karadvo/JLevai p. 31 SloXXvVTOU KOLL 8loX(o\rX(TL KCU €TL SloXoVVTCU Sid T1)U tcov Kv(3epvi-)TU)V /cat volvtwv fioyQ-qplav tcov irepi tol fJL€yi(TTa /jL€ylaTi]v ayvoiav elXifyoTcov, o'l wept ra no- b sXiriKa kolt ovoev ytyvcoaKOvres rjyovvTai Kara irdvTa aa(pearaTa iraacov liriaTr]p.Q>v ravrrji/ eiXrjcpevai. NE. 20. ' AXi-jOlaTara. AE. Tt9 OVV St] TCOV OVK 6p0COV TToXlTCLCOV TOVTCOV rJKiara )(aX€7rr) avtrjv, iraacov ^aXeircov ovacov, /cat 10 tls fiapvTdrr) ; del tl KaTide'iv 77/xaV, Ka'mep irpos ye to vvv irpoTeOlv rj/uv irdpepyov Xeyo/xevov ; ov firjv dXX! e'ls ye to oXov 'laces 7rdv@' eveica tov tolovtov irctvTes Spcojiev \apiv. 1. 7ro\\a\ p.rjv — elXr](pevai ] " Many however also from time to time are seen to founder like ships at sea, and thus are perishing, have perished, and shall hereafter perish, because of the vileness of their pilots and crews ; men guilty of the greatest ignorance on the greatest subject ; who, having absolutely no inkling of po- litical science, believe them- selves at all points above all other sciences to have master- ed this." Compare the de- scription of the " ship's crew" in Rep. 6, 488. KaOdnep irXola] Cf. Legg. 6, 758 a '• vavs re iv Bakatrar} TrXeowa — noXis Se axravrcos iv kXvScdvi todv aXXcuv noXecov. 2. 8i6X\vvraL — 8ioXovvTai ] Cf. supr. 268 e ; Tim. 22 c; Legg. 3, 676 b; 688 d. Hdt. 3. to. jueytcrro] Sc. to. 7to- \iTiKa. Cf. Legg. 3, 688 c : rfj XoiTTT) re 770077 KaKia 8ce e'trri tuvti]?' dXXa to re Kara vo/jlovs dp^eip kou Trapavo/ioos eaTi kul tcivty) koll tolls aXXat?. NE. 20. ' Ectti yap ovv. 5 SE. Tore p.\v To'ivvv T7)v 6p6i]v (iiTovai tovto to TfiijpLa ovk r)v xprjai/Aov, coy eV toIs irpoaOev dire- Sel^apev' €7T€i8r) 8e e^e'iXoptv eKeivrjv, tos 8' aXXas 6@ep.ev dvayKalas, Iv tolvtolis 8r) to irapa.vop.ov koll eVVOpLOV 6KaO~T1]V 8i)(0T0p.ei T0VT03V. io NE. 20. 'Koike tovtov vvv pr)6evT09 tov Xoyov. SE. Movapxia tolvvv ^ev^Oelaa p.ev ev ypdppacnv ayaOols, ov? vop.ov$ Xe'yop.ev, apio~Trj 7raaoou tuiv e£* avopios 8e ^aXeirii kou (3a.pvTa.TT] ^vvoiKijaai. NE. 20. Kiv8vvevei. 15 HE. Tr)v 8e ye tcov p.r) ttoXXcdv, wairep evos kou P- 3°3- the name of this constitution is already twofold," this seems inconsistent with 292 a. But Stallbaum ingeniously suggests that Plato here alludes to a distinction, which, though not in common use, had been invented by some philosopher. Still it is difficult to see the bearing of the clause when thus interpreted. Something is required in which democracy may be seen to differ from the other names. And this is supplied by the accidental dif- ference that democracy has a twofold meaning, is one word for two things, whereas in each of the former cases there was a name for either side of the division. " Even though, when we come to democracy (?j8r] ravT-qs), we find that the name has a twofold mean- ing." Cf. Pheedr. 244 a, twr- \ovv. 5. tovto to Tfirjpa ] This section, viz. the distinction between the use and neglect of law, which was shewn to make no essential difference in the conduct of the perfect ruler. Supr. 292, sqq. 6. a>s iv tols Trpoo~9ev dne- deiga/iev] It has been shewn that questions of law are in- different to the ruler who has perfect knowledge. Supr. 293- 8. dvayKaias] I. e. Such as we are compelled to put up with. Compare dvayKaias, e. g. Rep. 7, 527 a: \iyovo~i — •yeAcuW re Ka\ dvaynaioiS. 1 1 . ^evxdelo-a pev iv ypappacnv dyadols] " Subject to a yoke of good prescriptions." 15. a>ff7rep evos Kal tt\tj6ovs to nOMTlKOS. 1()5 •03. 7r\r)0ovs to 6"hiyov fxeaou, ovtws yyrjcrcofxeOa fxiarjv in ap(f)OTepa' ttjv 8' av rod ttXtjOovs Kara iravTa aaOevrj koll pifiev LirjTe ayaOov Lirjre kolkov fieya 8vvapevrjv d>? vrpos ras aXXa? 8lcl to tols ap)(a? Iv TavTY] ftiaveveprjadai kcltol a/j-iKpa eis 7roXXov?. 810 yeyove Tracrwv filv voplpcov tcov iroXLTtLwv ovawv tovtwv )(€ip[o~Trj, irapavop-wv 8* ovo~(iov ^vpiraawv b (3eATio~Tr)' koll aKoXaaTcov pev iraawv ovacov kv SrjfxoKpaTia vlko. (r)i>, KoafiiodV 8' ovawv tJklo-tcl Iv TaUTT] (3lQ)T€0l>, Iv Tjj irpCdTYf 8e TToXv TTpWTOV T€ KOLL apLo~Tov, irXr/v tyjs e(38oprj?' iraatoi' yap iKeivrjv ye cracy are interme- diate, and democracy in the least powerful for good or harm. 5 Whence a democracy is the worst of law- respecting communi- ties, but the least bad amongst those which despise the laws. Still, there oKlyov peo-ov ] There is a Pythagorean tone in these words, similar to that which is observable in the Politics of Aristotle. 4. 81a. to tcis dpxas — els ttoA- Xovs] The remarks of Aristotle, that much water is less easily fouled than little, and that bad influences in a democracy are neutralized by admixture with wholesome elements, as in the case of food, have an analogy with this observation of Plato. 8. Ka\ aKo\do~TG>i> pev — /3ico- reoi>] This opinion is quoted by Aristotle as that of one of those who had gone before him. Pol. IV. 2 : ttjv rvpawida Xeipio-Tr)v ovaav, nXelo-rov dnexeiv 7To\ireias. Aevrepov 8e ttjv oXt- yap\iaV t] yap dpiaroKpaTLa 6V to-TrjKiv dnb ravr-qs ttoKv tt)s noXirelas' perpiwTarTjv 8e ttjv drjpoKparlav. "H8tj pev ovv tis d7rt(pr]vaTO kcu rav irporepov ovto), ov prjv els tcivto fiXeyj/as i)pAV' enelvos pev yap eKpive, ira- (tcov pev ovacov eTnemav, oiov 6\iyap\las re XPW T *1 S Kal T ™ v nXXoov xeipio~Trjv bqpoKpariav, t£>v be (pavXwv dpl pev 0X1- yapxlav aXXqv aXXrjs ov KaXcos e^ei Xe'yeiv, tjttov 8e (pavXrjv, See also ib. c. 4. It will be observed that the last words exactly express the doctrine of the Politicus : so that if Aristotle is alluding to this dialogue he has misunder- stood the author's meaning. This does not prove that he does not refer to this passage, but it does tend to shew that he is quoting loosely without thinking of the context, and perhaps without distinctly re- membering the author from whom he quotes. tis t£>v Trporepov is certainly a cu- rious expression for him to use, if he remembered that he was quoting Plato. But the saying may perhaps be older than either of them. See Introduction to the States- man. For the infinitive, as subject of vim, cf. Soph. (Ed. Col. 1225 : pfj (pvvai tov anavra viKq \6yov. 166 11AAT0NQ2 18 do com- pari -on be- t « sen even c. institu- tional roy- ally ami the ideal state. None of these forms deserve the name of govern- ment : and their up- holders are not states- men, but factious partisans. AVe have done, then, with this " crew of Centaurs eKKpLT€oi>, olou 6ebi> e£ uvOpo'mcov, €K twu aAAcov p. 30 TToAlTtlOiV. NE. 20. <\>aiv£Tai tovO" outgo ^VjifiaLvtLV re kcu 7toli-jtwv ])7T€p Aeyei?. 5 SE. OvKOVV 8l) KOLi TOV? KOIVCOVOVS TOVTCOV 7U>V ttoAitzicov 7raaye alrias eivai (prjpt as TToWaKls e'lprjKa ev tols 77poa6ev Xoyois, 8r]poKpaTiav Ka\ 6\iyapx.iav Kal TvpavvL8a. tov- tcov yap 8rj iroXireia pev ov8epia, aratruoTeiai 8e 7rdcrai XeyoiVT civ opBorara. araaiaa-TiKovs] This is the salient point also in the al- legory of the ship : Rep. 6, 488. 8. eiSwXcoi'] Viz. t£>v ov no- XiTeiiov eiceiveav. 9. toiovtovs ] Sc. ei'SwXa. " The very substance of the ambitious is but the shadow of a dream." Cf. Phsedo 67 b: Kadapoi airaWaTTopevoi — peTCi tolovtcov — icropeda. I I . KtvSvvevei — opBorara] So above, 291 c, the same cha- racter is described as rbv ndv- tcov tcov crocpioTcov peyicrTov yorjTa Kal Tavrrjs tt]S rixyr)S epneipoTa- tov, in both places with direct reference to the argument of the Sophist, in which the false politician (not 7to\itikos but SrjpoXoyiKos) is distinguished from the Sophist last of all (Soph. sub. fin.). Cf. Gorg. 465 C : (pvpovrai ev tco avrco Kal ivepl Tavra ao(picTTa\ Kal prjTopes. lb. 5 21 - 5 a ■ Tavrov J) paKapie, earl ao b " fc dpyvpos, tan 6" ore /cat dSdpa?, # [a]^ /xera fiacravGov 15 y e * ellini - rat? i^rjaecTL pbyis dcpaipeOe'vra tov Xeyopevov precious aKrjpaTOv xpvabv elaaev rjpds' iSelv avrov povov i(j) w llich are iaVTOV. nation with ^ x that which NE. 20. Aeyerat ya/) ovv Srj ravra ovrco yuy- we seek to bring out veaOai. 20 clear - Arj. J\ara roy avrov roivvv Xoyov eot/ce /cat z/iw ciousand ,-%><-, v < / , . . / V > kindred rjpiv ra pev erepa /cat OTrocra aXXorpia /cat ra prj elements 0tAa iroXiriKrjs i7rio-rr]pT]? a7roK€)(copio~0ai, XelneaOaL ralsMp, the *\ \ 1 v s- - / w y / judicial 06 ra rtpia /cat fjvyyevi]. tovtojv o eari ttov err pa- function, Biaa-ov is suggested by the word move striking image. See this Bpapa. described in Faraday's Che- 6. ra i^vyyeves re opov elvai] mistry of a Candle, pp. 184- So Bodl. MS. Vulg. ra gvyyeves 204. 6' ofMovT. 15. * [a] * ] So Stephanus 12. ko.1 ene'ipoi] Here also the and Ficinus. MSS. om. text follows the Bodleian MS. 17. avrov povov e(j> eavrov] 13. ra arvyyevrj rod xp v0 ~°v Cf. Slipi*. 268 C : x (0 pi°~ avTes ° 7r ' Tt'/Ltm] The fusion of platinum eneivcov Kadapov povov avrov drro- would have afforded a still iprjvapev. J 68 flAATONOS and that nobler rhe- toric w hich is the ally of good govern- ment. \\ e must do our best to part these iitl' from the supreme science. Take music and the mechanical arts. There can be no doubt that they must yield prece- dence to the art which determines which of them is to be learnt. Trjyla koll SiKaariKy kcil oai] (3aai\LKfj koivcovovctoc p. 3c | pi-jTopeia ireiOovaa to Slkoliov £vv&La.Kvfi€pva ret? ev tous 7t6\€(tl irpa^eis' a 8i) * ' rivi* Tporrcp paara ti? diropLtpifav Seltjei yvfxvov kou /jlovov Ikiivov ko.0' 5 avrov tov ^qTovfxevov v(\j -t]pu>v ; NE. 20. Ar/Aov otl tovto tttj Spav TreLpareov. SE. Tlelpas pL€v Toivvv eve/to. (fjavepos earat' 81a $€ pLOVaiKtjs OLVTOV ey\€lpT]T€OV SfjXcQOrai. KOLl fJLOL Xeye. 10 NE. 20. To ttoIov ; SE. Mouv we pi xeipore^las €7rio-Tr)pLa>i> ; NE. 20. "Earn,. S*E. TV 6Y; to <5' av tovtcdv -qvTivovv e'/re del I . Ka\ oar) — 7rpdtjets] Such a higher rhetoric is hinted at in the Phsedrus and Gorgias, but more ironically than here. Cf. Gorg. 480 c, e ; Phsedr. 271 d, e. The word pijro- pela is peculiar to this place. Perhaps, as Stallbaum thinks, it conveys a nobler idea than prjTopiKTj. The admission of rhetoric into the state is a return to nature similar to the adoption of paid teachers which accompanies it in the Laws. Cf. Legg. 4, 7 1 1 d, e : r) ttjv Nearopos — (pvatv, ov rrj tov Xeyeiv pcoprj (petal it&vtcop htevey- Kovra dvdpaircav nXeov %ri t<5 acocppovelv hta(pe'petv k.t.A. The npootpta or vovdeTTjTiKcii Xoyot of that dialogue are an example of the kind of rhetoric here meant. Compare also the re- admission of the practical sci- ences in the Philebus. 3. *7"iVt* Tponcp paaraj I have ventured to accent r'm and to add the mark of interrogation, as the superlative seems to be otherwise without meaning ; and the answer of Young Socrates is at least equally apposite when the words are thus taken. Cf. Soph. 241 e ; Legg. 6, 779 e • h v $h Tiva T p6- ttqv \pr] £ijv vvp(ptov Kal vvp(prjv ; A similar change has still to be made in the text of Phileb. 26 e : TeTaprov ri Tore e(papev eivat yevos aKeTTTeov : ubi legend, re- Taprov t'i rare. See Mr. Poste's translation. 14. Tt he ; to h' av] Ast's conj., tL he Toh' av ; has been adopted by the Zurich editors. TOVTGtV TjVTIVOVV K.T.X.] This thought was afterwards deve- loped into the apx n " eKT0 " lK '? of Aristotle. See esp. Eth. Nic. I. 2. Pol. VII. 3. Compare Plat. Euthyd. 289, 290 ; Cra- tyl. 390 a. Gorg. 517 c Legg. nOAITIKOS. 169 I504. fiavOdveiv rj/j.a.9 elre 107, worepa (jjrjcro/jLev eirurrrjfjLrjv av kcu Tavrrjv elvai riva irep\ aura ravra, ?/ 7rco? ; NE. 20. Our coy, eJvai (j)i](JOfxev. SE. Ovkovv eWepav ofioXoyrjcrofiev eKelvcov eivai Tavrrjv ; NE.*2Q. Na/. HE. Ylorepa 8' avrcov ovSepclav ap^eiv Sew aXXr/v c aXXr)?, rj iiceivas ravrr)?, rj Tavrrjv 8elv eirirpoirevov- aav apyeiv ^vjiTraawv rcov aXXoov ; NE. 20. Tavrrjv eKelvcov. HE. [Tr)v\ el 8el jiavOdveiv rj /xt) rrj? fiavOavo- jievrjs kcu SidcKTKOvar)? apa av y dirofyaivei 8eiv rjjiiv apyeiv ; NE. SO. 20o6> ye. aE. Kca rr;t* el Set weldeiv apa rj fxrj rrjs 8vva- jievrjs ireldeiv ; NE. 20. Ilcor t? ov; HE. Etez/" rm ro ireiariKov ovv diro8coaojj.ev eiri- d arrjjxrj 7rXr)6ovs re Kal o^Xov 81a /ivOoXoyla? dXXa jxrj &a oi8a)(r}$ ; NE. 20. Oaz/e^ooi/, olfxai, Ka\ rovro prjropiKfj 80- reov ov. HE. To 5' are &a ireiOovs eire Kal 8lol tivos fiias So of the art of per- suasion. 'I'lii i urn t yield to the art which de- cides whe- 5 ther per- suasion or force is to lie used : i. e. the art of states- manship. Tli en gene- ralship du- I0 cides how war is to be conduct- ed : hut the prior ques- tion of war or peace must be decided by another j - and more authorita- tive art, which can be nothing less than royal. 12, 963 : vovv yap 8i) Kvfiepvrj- tikov pev Kcii larptKov e'liropev — top 8e ttoXitlkov iXeyxpvres h>- ravd' ea-fiev vvv. 1 1. [T^i/] et Set pavBavew r) prj\ The old editors, supported by few MSS., insert ttjv before el, which Stallbaum has retained. The Zurich editors read Tavrrjv eKelvcov, el del pavddveiv rj prj. 3. rrjs p. k.t.X. But the tenor of the argument makes the retention of ttjv almost impe- rative. Compare similar spe- cimens of analogical reasoning in the Gorgias. 18. TTeiaTiKov] This word is used again in Legg. 4, 723 a. 20. pi) 81a 8i8axrj<:] Cf. Gorg. 445 a ; Theset. 201 a, b. Com- pare the opposition of pvdos and Xo'yos in Gorg. 523 a. 170 I1AATON02 Set TTpa.TT€iv irpos Tiva? otlovv r) koli to irapuirav p. y j[€)(€wf, tovt av Troia 7rpoa0i]aofxev imcrTrjpir) ; NE. 20. Tfj r;;y 7T€i(JTiKr)9 dpyovorr) koli Xektikt}?. HE. En; 8e av ovk aXXrj r*?, coy oifiai, irX-qv rj 5 T0V 7ToXtTlKOV Svvafll?. NE. 20. KaAAicrr' e'lpr/Ka?. HE. Kat roi}7-o /xe> eWe ra^i; K^wpiaOai ttoXl- TLKYjS TO prjTOpiKOV, &>? €T€pOV el8o? 0V, V7TT]p€T0Vl> yu^ TavTy. io NE. 20. Na/. HE. T7 <5e 7re/0i r^? tolocctS' av Swa/ieco? 8iavo- ryriov ; NE. 20. Woias ; HE. T77? coy TroXepcqTeov i/cdo-Toi? oW av npo- 15 tXwfxeOa TroXejieiVy e'/re avTrjv areyyov eiTt evTeyvov epovfiev ; NE. 20. Kai 7rco? az> areyyov diavorjOelpLev, rjv ye rj cTTpaT-qyLKr) /cat iraaa rj 7roXepLLKr) irpa^is irpaTTti ; HE. T^f 5' e'/re 7roX€fir)Teov e'/re &a (piXias 20 ajraXXaKTeov otav re /cat hricrTriixova SiafiovXev- 1. ij «at to irapaTrav fe'xeivf] qualifying an assertion supr. Schleiermacher conjectured iav 263 e : ayikaiav prjv £acov. So (cf. Soph. 242 a: ro Trapanav ia- pevroi in Rep. 1,334 b: eV rkov. And e'av may perhaps have aXpeXelq p.evroi tcov (pikcov k.t.\. been mistaken for a contraction 1 4. a>s] How, in what way. of e'xeiv) ; Stallbaum an£x. elv = to 15. eiVe] Interrogative, de- refrain — supposing an to be pending on 8iavor]Teov. absorbed in Tvapairav. (d7re'x«i> 17. 17V -ye] " "Why it is the sc. tov TrpaTTtiv.') Herm. conj. function on which generalship y\o-y)\ia.v e%eiv. Badh. \eyew, and all warlike action is em- with a view to XeKTiKrjs infra. ployed." Cf. Protag. 322 b : But XeKTiKrjS is only an ex- ttoXitiktjv rjs pepos 7ro\epiKfj. pansion of ireio~TiKrjs. The 19. Tfjv 8 fire 7T.] Bodl. ttjv conjecture of Hermann is the Se w. with All. best. 20. o'Lav re koi eVto-rij/xoj'a] 9. p.r)v] (irjv is thus used in "Able through knowledge." nOAITIKOS. 171 1304. aaaOat, Tavrr)? erepav vnoAdficofiev 7) ti)v uvtijv ravrrj ; NE. 20. Tol? rrpoaOeu dvayKaiov eirofxevoLcriv erepav. 305. 3?E« Ovkovv apyovcrav tclvtt)? avrrjv dirotyavov- [ /jteOa, elirep tols epurpoaOev ye v7ro\rj\l/6/xe$a o/xojW ; NE. 20. 0»7/x/. £?E. TiV ow 7TOT6 /ecu iTTixeLprjaopLev ovtco Seivrj? kou fxeyaAr]? re\vr)9 ^vpcKacnyi r^y 7ro\ep.iK.r)s Se- cnroTiv dmo§aivecr6ai 7rXi]v ye 8rj rrjv ovtcos ovcrav (3acri\LKi]v ; NE. 20. Ovde/xlav dkX^v. HE. Ovk apa iroXiTiK-qv ye Orjaofiev, vTrrjpeTLKr^v ovcrav, rrjv tcov arpar-qycov hrio~Tr]p.r]v. NE. 20. Ovk gIkos. b S?E. "I#i £77, /cat r?)i> 70)2/ 8iKao-T(ov tcov opOcos 8iKa(pvTcov Oeacrco/ieda 8vvap.Lv. NE. 20. ria^i; /xeV ovv. HE. 5 A/)' o?jj> eVi irXeov ri hvvarai rod 7rep\ rd The gene- ral, then, is a servant, and not a 5 governor. Let us now examine the judicial faculty. What can this do be- yond the impartial 8. ovtco — -7ro\eij.tKr]s~\ " What science shall we go about to make supreme over the whole of strategy, a power so for- midable and so mighty?" IO. tt]v ovtcos ovcrav /3ao"tX»C7ji/] So the argument is strength- ened by an appeal to language in Soph. 2 2IC: f/ iravrdnaaiv cos dXrjdcbs cro(pto-TrjV. Supi*. 260 C : 8ecm6£ovTa ye. 13. VTrr)periKT)v ov. 3c administpa- Oerov fiaaiXea)? TrapaXafiovaa, Kpiveiv ei? eKelva tion of ex- m , 9 v v LBtinglawB? (JKGiTOvcra r« re olkoliol Taypevra eivai koli aoiKa, TT\v avTrjs iSiav dperi-jv 7ra.peypp.evr1 tov p.i]6 vtto hTLVO)V SwpWV pLl]0 y VTTO (f)6/3cDl> fJLTJT€ OLKTCOV pL7]6* vtto TLV09 aAXrj? e^6pa9 ptr]8e (f)iXlas -qTrrjOelaa uapa c tt)V tov vop.o6erov rd^iv edeXeiv av to. dXXrjXcov iy/cXr/pcara Siaipelv ; NE. 20. Ovk, dXXa crxeSou ocrov e'tprjKas, returns* ioeoTt 7-779 SvvdpLeco? epyov. Thisppwer, £E. }^ a \ T ^ v T £ v SlKa(TTG)l> apa pU>pLT/l> dvevp'i- only the aKopLev ov fiao-iXiKrjv ovcrav dXXa vop.coi> (hvXaKa koll guardian, f ' and not the VTTrjpeTLV eKeiVT]^. directress, of the laws. NE. 20. ' Eoi/C6 ye. The science f , , , f f , y of govern- 15 ^E. Tooe o?; KaravorjTeov loovtl avvairaaa? TOL? nient must , , ^ if rf , » ~ > ^ ^ he different eiTl(TTr)p.aS CLl eipqVTOLl, OTl TToXlTLKT) ye aVTCOV OVOepUd from all of , , , \ x v ■$ n , \ > » \ , these. Her avecpavq. tt)v yap ovTws ovaav pacrcXiKr]u OVK aVTTjV d business is^« / > . , » v ~ c» t ' notimme- oet Trparreiu, aXX apyeiv T(£>v ovvapLevcov irpaTTeiv, diate ac- / \ > r \ t \ ~ / tion, but yiyvuto-Kovo-av tyjv apyrjv re /cat op\xr\v tcdv pLeyLcrrcov the guid- > ~ / .. 1 / / v > / \ ance of 20 w T a ^ 7ToA€0~iv eynaipias re irepi Kai aKaipias, ras action w " \ \ % /\ ' s> " through ° aAAa? ra Trpoo~TayUevTa bpav. 'Zfr NE. 20. "OpM,. 5. p^d' u7ro' rtvos aXX^? ey#p.] " Understanding, as regards " No, nor yet hatred ;" accord- fitness and unfitness of times, ing to the well-known Platonic the beginning and first im- idiom. Cf. supr. 298 d : are pulse of what is most im- tlvcov larpcop Kai Kvf5epvr)Tv e'ir portant in states." Cf. Rep. aXXcov Idicorwv. 4, 424 a : jroXtreia iav airag 9. ' \ rt ' v ^ ' • " versa] : ;unl KArjo-eL irepiAapovTes rrju ovvap.Lv avTiqs, irpoaayo- hence thia pevoipev diKaioTCLT av, &>? eoiKe, ttoXltiktjv. 10 sc " NE. 20. YlavTouracri pev ovv. SE. OltcoOj> 5?) /cat /cara to rrjs ixfiavTiKrjs irapa- Secypa /3ouAo//xec9' av eire^eXOelv avTr)v vvv, ore koll bears the general name of govern- Having now distin- udvTCL rd yevt] rd Kara ttoXlv 8r)Xa rjplv yeyovev ; ft Ulshe ti ** forms of NE. 20. Kgu a(j)68pa ye. let us view StE. Trjv 8r) fiatriAiK-qv avpurXoK-qv, cos eoiKe, c in unison. We must now ex- amine whe- ther cou- NE. 20. IlaW ye. HE. Kal p.r)v (Tco(f)poavvrju ye dvSpelas p.ei> erepov, €P $ OVV KOI TOVTO pLOpiOV Tj? KOLKeivO. J3J? NE. 20. N«/. ance are >— IT7 , rr\ ' S> v/ /i ' % ' » not rather ro Ati. 1 OVTCOV 07] TTtpL VOLV{ia(TTOl> TIVOL KoyOV UTTO- opposed. I / /i % / (paiveaUai roXp.7]reov. NE. 20. notoi/ ; £7E. '12? i?' iravra yap way different from another 8. ^s Kd»«v ovtcov] Cf. tion between el8os and p-epos, illfr. C : e'lTe Kara (Toopara eire iv SUpr. 263 a. Cf. Legg. 7,791 ^t^ats eire Kara (pcovrjs (popav, C, where dvSpeia is called ^vx>js ew' avrwv tovtodv eiV iv elboAois popiov dpeTrjs. lb. 3, 689 d : OVTCOV. Charm. 1 60 a. The words from 1 7. iravra yap ovv — cpi\ia] The rj YaAe7rw to 86gas are given to present is certainly a modifi- the same speaker in the Bodl. cation of the view taken by MS. Socrates in the Protagoras, 4. 'AAA' o>Se ttoIlv] Cf.Theset. where he upholds the simple 191b: aX\' a>8e. Rep. i. 352 e. unity of virtue. Soph. 262 e : m^ 0-p.iKpbv rode. flOAITIKOS. 175 i |»o6. ovv <5?7 dXXr']Aoi? rd ye tyjs dperr/s fiopia Xeyerai c 7rov (filXia. NE. 2Q. Nat. 3?E. ^Koircopev 81) 7rpoaypvTe9 tov vovv ev pdXa, ivorepov ovtcos dirXovv earl tovto, ?) iravros pLuXXov ■ clvtcov e\ei Siacpopdv rols ijvyyeveaiv es ti ; NE. SO. Nat, Xeyots dv tttj aKeirreov. HE. 'E*> roi9 ^vpuraciL yjpr) (jjTeiv oaa KaXd ptev Xeyopev, els Svo 5' avrd riQep.ev evavria dXXijXcav e'lSr}. NE. 20. Ae'y en. cracpearepov. HE. 'OtjvTTjTa kcll rd)(OS, etre Kara acopara eire d ev >\/vyai$ evre Kara (pcovrjs (popdv, eire avnov tovtcov e\r ev eldcoXois ovtcdv, biroaa plovctlkt] pupovpevr) kcll en ypa(f)iKr) pipjjpLara wape^erat, tovtcov tlvos enrai- We mu t loot E01 tin amongst ad ions which we admire, and at the same time con- trast with each other. We praise quickness and bold- ness on many occa- sions, and always by , applying the same epithet of ' brave.' 5. ovtcos anXovp] Cf. Symp. 183 d : ovx an'hovv ecrrtv, — ovre aaXov eivai qvto — ovre alcrxpov, dWa Kcikcos fiev TrparTOfxevop KaXov, alcrxpu>s 8e alcrxpov. rj — ™] "Or whether there be of them which differ in some respect from their congeners." The old editions had e'xov — earl, which however is only found in the margin of Ven. H, and is probably due to iariv having been read for is t\. Heindorf COllj. e'xov er)fir]i> e^ty OVTiva Tpoirov avro 5 SpcoCTLJ/ Iv €K auro eV rot? virevavTLOLS yeveari. tcov yap 8i] irpd^eu>v iv woXXals /cat ttoXXclkis eKacrroTe ra^os Kal o-r]9, orav dyao-0a>p.ev, Xeyop.ev avro ibtiraivovvTts pud xpcop.evoi irpocrprjaeL rfj rrjs avBpeias. NE. 20. Urn ; 37E. 'Oijv /cat dv8pel6v ttov (f)ap.ev, Kal ra^v /cat di>8piKov, /cat a(po8pbv waavrcos' /cat iravrcos im(J)6- povres rovvopca b Xeya> koivov irdo-ais tols (pvaeat 20 ramais £iraivovp.€v avrds. 4. avro bpaxrC] Cf. Soph. ra>v yap 8tj — dvbpeias] "For 233 c: ApSo-t Se ye toOto npbs there are many actions in which, ajravrd, cpapfu. and that repeatedly, we praise 5. eV sicdo-Tois tovtcov] " In speed and vehemence and quick - the case of body, mind, voice, ness, mental and bodily; and or imitative art." on each occasion" (erao-Tore) 7. wcnrep — 8iavoovp.at] Cf. "express our praise of the qua- Crat. 435 b. lity which we admire by the 11. iv tols v-rrevavriois yeVecn] one appellation of ' bravery.' " " In the kinds where the oppo- 12. iv iroXXal? na\ ttoXXokis ] sition appears." Supr. c : ivavria Cf. Soph. 264 b: evia ko.\ more — — ei'877. Qy. Tais uTrerarriais with which should bave been yece'o-eo-i ? Cf. infr. : rjpepalas av compared Phileb. 32 d : ivlore yeviarecos. 3IO 0.'. TroWals yeve- Ka\ evia — eo~riv ore . o-eo-iv, where some MSS. have 14. avro] Sc. rdxos ko.\ o-cpo- noWols yeveatv. dpoTrjra Ka\ o^vTrjTa k.t.X. nOAITIKOS. 177 ,06. NE. 20. Nat. JE?E. Tt (V; 70 rrjs r)pep.alas av yeueaeoj? elftos dp [07. ov 7roAAa/cfy eirrjveKap.ev ev TroAAaty twv 7rpd$jecov ; NE. 20. Rat cr0do>a ye. HE. Mc3y oui/ ou rdvavTia Xeyovre? ?) 7re/9t €/ce/- yaw rouro (f)0eyyopLe6a ; NE. 20. ricSy ; HE. '0? rjavxaid ttov (fiapLev eKaarore kou ad? yiyvop.eva Aeta kou jQapea, kou irdaav pvOfiiKrjv Kivrjaiv kou oXyjv povaav ev Koupcp (3paSv- h rrJTi 7rpocr)(pa>p,ei>i]v i ov to ttjs dvftpeias aAAa to Trjs KOO-fJuoTijTo? ovopta eiTL^epopiev oivtoIs ^vpuraGLV. NE. 20. 'AAT/foarara. HE. Kat fir)i> birorav av ye dpttpoTepa ylyvrjTai ravTa i)puv aKaipa, peTafiaXXovTes eKarepa avrwv \j/e- yop.ev eVt TavavTia irdXiv dirovepiQVTes toIs bvopuacriv. Again, wc often praise x<-i\~ tlenesa and q detail of di mean our and movement , and here wc use the very dif- ferent epi- thet of ' modest.' On the other hand, both bold- nesa and gentleness are often blamed, as rash and cowardly. But rash- ness and . cowardice are not found toge- ther, and bravery and mo- desty have not a natu- 2. yevecreoos] The word is used in the same sense as supr. 283 d, 287 e, to express the operation of any art, or, more generally, the act of doing any- thing. 8. c Oy rjcrvxala — £vfjLTra eV rat? irepl ra TOiavra 7rpdtjecTiv, en re rov? iv rah y^/v^cus loavTas l(j)(0VTas dLCKpepouevovs aAA^Aot? 6\j/6u€0a, iau ueradicoKcouev. NE. 20. Uod St) Aeyw ; HE. 'Ey iracri re 8rj tovtois oh vvv ehrofiev, cos P-3 them to the opposite quarters again in our nomenclature." 3. [ko.\] vj3picTTiKa\ So all the MSS. except Ven. S. ml v(3p. kcu fiav. = " Not only violent, but mad." vfipio-TiKa] Cf. Pheedr. 252 b: vfBpKTTlKOV TTU.VV KOI OV 0~(ji68pa ti epperpov. Cratyl. 426 b. 4. paviKa] Cf. Soph. 242 a: pi] TTore aoL pai'iKus eivai 86£a> napci 7768a peTa(3aXo>v ipavrbv uva) Kal Kara). 5. (BXaKiKa] Cf. Eep. 4, 432 d : (BXcikikov ye fjpav to irdBos. Gorg. 488 a : irdvv pe rjyuv /3X5ko effect. Euthyd. 287 e : i^paprov 8u\ rr)v fikaneiav, kcu cr^eSof peTahi&>Ka>pev ] " And so it is for the most part that we find these (the harsh and effeminate), and also the temperance and manliness of the characters opposed to them, as ideas diametrically antago- nistic, not mingling with each other in the actions concerncd Avith such things ; and, more- over, we find, if Ave folloAv up the quest so far, that the men also of whose minds they are attributes are at variance Avith each other." dv8peiav is pro- bably a substantive. 7. olov — Ideas] The Avords as they stand must be construed " As hostile forms having taken different sides in a quarrel." (SmX. or.) But I Avould venture to read iroXeuacu', and translate " Forms Avhich as it were have severally been put in a hostile attitude." Compare o-rdaiv evavTiav eyoire SUpr. 306 b. Alberti's interpretation, Avho AVOllld join ttjv tu>v ivavriav 8iaX.axovo-as ardo-iv, oiov %o\e- pias I8eas, - " participating, as hostile forms, in the Avar of opposites," Avill hardly com- mend itself to scholars. He is right, however, in adducing Legg. 8, 836 d : to ttjs aaxppo- vos ISeas yivos. nOAITIKOS. 179 \oj. cIko? re, Iv €T6poL9 noXXois. Kara yap ol/j.ai Ti]V d avrcois eKarepois j-vyyivtiav rd /xeV tiraivovvrzs co? oiKeia a(j)€Tepa, rd Se twv $ia(f)6p(av xj/f-yovres coy dXXorpia, 7roX\rji> ei? tyOpav dXXr/Xois koll ttoXXwv 7T€pL KaO'tdTavTai. 5 NE. 20. Ku/Svvevovcriv. £?E. Ilac8ia Toivvv avrr) ye' tls rj 8ia(f)opa tovtcdv iarl twv eldcow 7rep\ de rd p,ey terra vocros ^vpifiaiveL Tracrwv kyOiaTr) yiyveaOai reus TroXeaiv. NE. 20. He pi Si) ttolol (j)rj$ ; i° e HE. rie/n oXi]P, cos ye ekoy, rr)V rov £r}v irapa- aKevrjv. ol p.lv yap di) $ia(f)€p6i>TQi? ovres Kocrp-ioi rov rj del fiiov eroipoi (r)v, avrol Ka0* avrov? povoi ra a(f)erep' avrcov 7rpa.TT0i>T€?, olkol re wpbs awavras ovtcos bpiXovvres, /ecu irpbs rd$ e'ijcoOev 7roX€is oocrav- 15 which this contrarii ty leads. For tho lovers of a quiet life, if they have their way, by enerva- ting them- selves and tlic youth, will often bring theii country into sla- very. 2. cos oiKe'ia atcu 7rpaTTco(Tii>, tXaOov clvtol re uiro- Xe/jLco? ta)(oi>T€9 koll tovs veovs oxravrcos 8iaTi0€VT€? 5 6We? re del twv €7rtTi.d€p.ei>coi>, tij d>v ovk Iv ttoXXols €T€criu avTol Kai Troupes koll tjv/JLTraaa r\ ttoXis avr eXevOepcov noXXaKis eXaQov civtovs yevop.evoL 8ovXol. p 30 NE. 20. XaXewov eiVe? koll 8eivhv iraOos. SE. Tt 8' ol 77-/30? tt)v dv8peiav llolXXov piirovTVi ; odp ovk hri iroXeLtov del Tiva ret? avrcov ^vvTeivovrts everstir- woXets 81a tt)V tov TOLOvTou (3lov o~(po8poTepav rov strffeand 8e0VT09 llTlQv\Xiav, €L9 6\dpav TToXXoh KCU 8vvCLT0LS quarrels 15 /coa-aorayre?, 7] irdpurav 8i(aXeaav ?) 8ovXa? av Kai MneSbT" VTToyeipiovs tols eyOpoh viriOeaav tols avrutu ira- %? m °P NE. 20. "Ear, «* rccvra. _ b opposite &E. riooy ouj> /x?) (pco/uLtv ev tovtol? d/xcfjorepa ravra ra yevrj iroXXr/v irpos aXXrjXa del kou ttjv fieylo-Trjv 'layetv eyOpav kou ordaiv ; 20 NE. 20. Ov8a/xco9 a>? ov (f)r)o-o/jL€i>. HE. OlfKOVV 07T€p i7reO-K07TOV/JL€V kglt ap^a?, dvevprjKafxev, on /xopia dperrjs ov apuKpd dXX-qXois 8ia(j)€pea6ov (pvaei Kai 8r) koll tow IcrypvTas 8pdjov to avTo tovto ; 1. TTavra] Adverbial. 19. i'xdpnv kci\ a-rdaiv] Supr. 7. noWaKis — 8av\oi] Note 306 b. The writer seems to the rhythm. The style of this pass almost unconsciously from passage is closely similar to the one meaning of o-rdo-is to that of the Laws. the other. IO. %vvteivovT£S ] Cf. Rep. 20. OvSap.£>s ws ov] The 9, 590 b : otuv to Xeovrcodes — adverbial form of oidels 00-- o-WTeivr)T(ii dvappdaTas. tis ov. 13. KaTaardvTes] Qy. KaraaTr)- 23. dparou to avro tovto] Sc vavTes 1 noiovaiv 8u«ptpeiv. nOAITIKC)2. 181 308. NE. 20. Kiv8vvev€Tov. 3?E. To5e tolvvv av Xd(3co/j.ev. NE. 20. To two* ; SE. El' r/ff 7rou ra>*> avvOeTiKcov ejriaTyjpcov irpdypa otlovv tcov avTTJs epycov, kolv el to c/>gcuAo-5 toltov, (Kovcra t/c poyOrjpcov /cat xprjo-Tcov tlvcov £vvl- arrjaLU, rj Trdaa emo-Tr)p.r] iravrayov tcl p.ev pLoyO^pd els dvvapiv a7ro(3aXXei, tcl 8 e7riTr)8eia /cat xprjorTa eXafiev, Ik tovtcov 8e /cat bpLOitov /cat dvopLoicov ovtcov, f » a > \ > / / v s> ' v cast the bad TtavTa eis ev avTa ^vvayovaa, puav Tiva 0vvap.1v /cat i° asvay .And '?>' S ~ will nut the ideav d^fiiovpyei. polilical science, then, com- bine good elements, whether like or un- Now let us ask whe- ther any .art 1 if com- bination will not first select good ele- ments to be com- bined, and NE. 20. Tifirjv; HE. OvS 1 dpa r) kclto. fyvcnv dXyOais ovcra r)plv d ttoXltlkt] pur) iroTe e/c xprjaTcov kou kolkcov dvOpcoircov eKodcra eivai avaTrjarjTaL ttoXlv Tiva, dXX' ev'8rjXovis llk otl 7rai8ia 7rpcoTov fiaaavie'i, peTtx 8e tx\v /3daavov av toIs 8vvapevois 7rai.8eveiv K.a\ virr/peTelv npos tovt avTO 7rapa8(oaei, 7rpoo~TaTTOvaa /cat hno~TaTovo~a avTrj, KaOdirep vcpavTiKr/ toIs re tjalvovcri /cat tols There can- not be a good com- bination of good and bad. And as the weaver pre- sides over 5. kclv ei] Cf. Soph. 247 d, 267 e ; Phileb. 58 c. 13. OuS' apa — eVto-rarft] "Nor is it possible then that our art of statesmanship, in the true and natural sense, will ever (if this can possibly be avoided) form a city by the combination of bad and good : but she will clearly first test her subjects by some child's- play, after which she will en- trust them to those who are able to educate youth and to be her ministers for this end: and over these she will maintain authority, just as the art of weaving continually presides over and directs the carders and the rest who prepare what is necessary for her use in the production of her fabric." 1 4. £k XPT] 413 ; Legg. 1, 648; supr. 307 & 17. Koi VTTrjpeTe'iv npos tovt avTo] Seeing that the art of education also is ministerial to the state. Cf. supr. 304. 19. Kadatrep vqbavTiKi]\ Supr. p. 282. 1 82 nAAT0N02 the prepa- ratory pro- cesses of cardingand Bpinning,80 this Bcience will deliver those whom she selects to educa- tors, over w hose work she will herself pre- side. Those incapable of moral training she will reject and suppress. Those of an ignorant and abject nature she will en- slave. The rest, who are capable of being moulded to a noble type and drawn into har- mony, she rdXXa 7rpcnrapa(TKtva.(<)V(Tiv ocra irpos tijv irXtfyv p. 30 >' avrrj?, ijv/x7rapaKuXov0uvcra irpoaTwrTti koll briara- re?, roiavra tKaarois ivBeiKvvaa tu epya dnore- e AetV, ola av eTrmjSeia rjyrjrai irpos rrjv avrrjs eivat 5 ^vpirXoK-qv. NE. 20. Ylavv p.lv ovi>. SE. Tolvtov 8r/ llol rovO' rj fiaaLXiKr] (fjalisercu iraai tols Kara vollov 7rou8evTca? koll Tpofevai, ttjv tyjs iTTicrTCLTLKr}? avrrj 8vi>cl/jllv e')(OV(Ta, ovk hriTp&fy&v lod(TK€?l> O TL LIT} TLS TTpOS T7]V OLVTYjS j~vyKpO.O~LV d.7T€p- ya{p/jL€vos rjOos tl irpiirov dwoTeXei, tolvtol 8e p.ova 7rapaKe\euea0a.L 7rai8eveii>. koll tovs pev per) 8vva- pLtvovs Koivcovelv rfOovs dvSpelov koll aaxfipovos oaa re aXXa earl reivovra irpos dper-qv, dXK els d6eo- l5Tr)T0L KOLL vfiplV KOLL d$LKLOLV VTTO KaKYjS (3la (f)Va€0)S p. 309 ^diroiOovptvovs*) Oolvcltols re ck^olXXel koll (fivyals KOLL TOLLS p.eyl(TTOLLS KoXatfiVCTOL aTLpLLaLS. NE. 20. Ae'yeroLL yovv itcds ovtcos. SE. Tovs 5' kv dpiaOla r av koll T VTTotj-vyvvai will weave , together in ytVQS. the follow- NE. 20. 'OpOoTOLTOL. taking the hti t* v -v > > <" ' j ' » n ^ brav< oa- AUt. LOV? A017TOV9 TOLVVV, OCTUiV OLL (pVO~€LS C7Ti TO turea for \ <> r ' n > -the warp yevvaiov iKavai iraiotias Tvyyavovaai Kauio-Taavai 5 and the gentle for «$■> the Boftei woof. As nature directs, she will bind b koll SeijaaOai peTtx T&vyrjs (-vfifiictv irpos a A At; A TOVTCOV TOL9 p€V €7TL TT]V OLvbpeLOLV paXXoV ^VVTtLVOV- crar, oiov crTi]noi>o\\/ // v the iminor- aTepeov rjuos, tols oe em to Kocrpiov iriovi re /cat t;ll t in paXaKw koll kcltol ti)v eiKova KpoKcodei * diainj/juzTi* i t( 7rpoaxpcopevas, kvavTia 5e Teivovaas aXXrjXcus, iru- parai TOiovde tlvol Tpoirov ^vvbtiv koll ^vpirXeKtLV. NE. 20. Uolov hi ; Rightopin- ' ' ion of what c 37E. Ylp(OT0v pev kcltol to ^vyyeves to aeLytvls bv Trj? "fyvyfjs avT(ov ptpos Oelco ^vvappoaapevrj bond, and the animal part by human ties. is noble, just, and good, when confirmed SeO-pW, peTCL <5e TO OflOV TO tjooytvh CLVTCOV avOtS by reason avOpcoirivoLs. ** a d . ivirie principle in NE. 20. 11(0? TOVT el7T€? OLV ; a godlike \ ~ t f v form. SE. Tyv tcov kolXcdv koll Slkolloiv irepL koll ay a- The good lawgiver I. v7ro£evyvv(ri\ Sc. rols ak- depart. Cf. 8t,av6i^a>. Corrected Xoir, " makes subject to the by Cornarius. rest." 14. Ilpcorov — dvdpcoTriuon ] 7. ray pev hri — ^vfinXe- " First harmonizing that part Kuv~\ " Some natures tending of their soul which is of eter- more to courage, whose hard nal origin with a kindred, quality she compares to that that is a divine bond; and, of the warp, while others are after that which is divine, the disposed to gentleness, as if animal nature again with hu- spun thick and soft and, ac- man bonds." For the fooyeves cording to the image, in the pepos ttjs ^vxns, cf. Tim. 69 c, manner of the woof, these op- sqq. posite tendencies she tries to 15. 6eia — dvdpconlvois] Cf. bind aud weave together in Legg. 1,631b: SinXd 8e dyaffd the following way." icrri, rd pev dvdpcaniva, rd be gvvreivovcras] Neut. Cf. Slipr. flela' fjpTT)Tai 8° £k tcov Beiav 294 b. dare pa. I O. * 8iavi']pciTi *] MSS. 8iav- 184 nAATONOS Bhould Ool)V KCtl TCOV TOVTOl? (VUVTICOV OVTOi? OVtTGLV dXflOn X). 20 S°9 alone be v , , , „ , , able to im- ootjav fiera (3€J3a.icoar€oo?, ottotolv iv yl/vyrus eyy'iyvrj- part tliis , v , f t , iv educa- r«f, ^/efa^ r/)j;/zt ei> daipovico yiyveaOat yevei. tion In the v/-v / l v natureBCa- NE. 20. rT/0€7Tet yOW OUrwy. pableofit. ,_ _ v N v v N , v Til.- ciieet 5 A^. 1 oj/ o?) ttoXltlkov koll tuv uyaaov VOp.0- (I of this ia , 9 , „ f , , , . to soften oeTiiv ap lapev otl irpoarjKtL povov Ovvutov the brave , „„ , ,v, nature, eivai tyj T119 paaiAiKij? povarj tovto avro epTroiav lighten the tok opOtos fjL€Ta\a(3ov(Ji 7rGu6Vay, oi)y iAtyopev gentle. „ » . vvv or) ; IO NE. 20. To yow ef/cos 1 . HE. ' Os 5' a^ fyjaf ye, w Sw/cpares-, d8vva.Tr] to toiovtov, fxi]8e7TOTe toIs vvv ftjTovpevois ovopaaiv avrov 7rpoo-ayopevco/i€v. NE. 20. 'OpdoTara. 15 HE. TV ow ; dvSpeia yj/v^r) Xap/Savopevrj tt}? TOiavrrjS dXr/0eia? dp* ov^ rjpepovTai koll tcov Sikclloov fidXiara outgo KOivooveiv dv iOeXr/aete, pr) peTaXa- e /3oDcra Se diroKXivei pdXXov 7rpos OrjpiooSr) tlvol (pvaiv ; 2 o NE. 20. FIw? 5' ov ; HE. T7 oY ; to tyj? Koaplas (pvcreco? dp ov tov- tcov p\v p.€TaXa(3bv tcov dotjoov ovtgos o-co(ppov kcu I. ovTas — /3e/3«iaxrecoy] "Real 913 c: KT>]pa dvrl KTi'jparos apei- true opinion with confirma- vov iv dpdvovt Knjo-dpevos, 8ikt]v tion : " i. e. knowledge, as de- iv rfj -tyvxrj ttKqvtov 7rpoTipr)- fined in Theset. sub. fin. and o-a?. Meno 98 a, b ; Phaxlo 76 ; 7. povo-rj] Cf. Rep. 6, 499 Tim. 51 d, e ; Legg. 2, 653 b. d : avrrj 17 povaa. This use is 3. 8aifiovi

v ^/vx^v : which is at least 1 2. 7-oTs vvv foTuvfiivois 6v6fia- Heaven-born, if not Divine. v\ Sc. (pafiev. " But in those characters which are at once noble in their first origin, and have been reared accord- ingly, in these alone this har- mony grows up when fostered by the laws, and this medi- cine is scientifically destined for them ; and, as we have said, this is the diviner bond, uniting parts of virtue by nature dissimilar, and diversely bent." re] MSS. ye. 13. tovtois] TheBodl. MS. has tovtovs with An. 14. deioTaTov] So the Bodl. MS., with AsnsY. Vulg. -Tepov. 15. * cpvaei *] The conj. of Stephanus for the MS. reading cpvaecos. The expression dpvareais may easily have slipt in from supr. Koo-p.ias cpvaeoos. Cf. SUpr. 308 b : popia dpeTTJs ov crp.iK.pa dWrjXots diatpepeadov (pixrei. 6. e7Tiyap,iwv — Koivoovrjcrc-cdv ] " Intermarriages, and giving and taking of children in mar- riage between states." The Koivcovia tcov naibcov is not to be thought of here. 8. £w§ovvTai\ Eather mid- dle voice with reciprocal mean- ing than passive : = " enter into mutual bonds." 12. biaypara ] Cf. Aesch. Eum. 136. 15. nepl ra yevrj] "About good family connexions." Stallbaum objects that what follows re- lates to individual character and not to birth, and suggests fjdr). But the transition from wealth to birth is so natural, that Plato here applies the latter notion metaphorically, which is so much the easier as the bold and gentle cha- racters are spoken of as yevrj, and as the argument requires them to be viewed as here- ditary. " People at present are too clannish in their alli- ances : the brave seeks union with the brave, the gentle with the gentle race." Cf. supr. a : rols evyevecri yevopevois. And in- fra : to 7Tep\ tx]v dvhpelav yevos — dpcporepa ra. yevrj. Also Legg. 3, 691 e : TJj Kara yevos aiidadel pa>p.y. This idea does not seem to be present in Tim. 18 e : oncos 01 kcikoI x^pis °' T * dya8o\ Tciis opolais eKarepoi £v\- \i]goi>Tai. But then in the Re- II0AITIK02. 187 jio. 7roLOvp.evtav eiripeXeiav, tovtcov irepi Xeyeiv, el tl p.r/ c /caret Tpoirov tt pan ovo tv. NE. 20. Ei/coy yap ovv. HE. YipdrTOvcn p.ev Sr) ovde i£ evb? 6p6ov Xoyov, rrjv ev tco 7rapa\prjpa dicoKOvre? paaTcovrjv Kai tco •■ rov9 p.ev irpocropoLovs avTois dairo^eaOaL, tovs <$' avopoiov? pi] , irXelcrTOv rfj Svo-x^pela pepos chrovepovTes. NE. 2ft. Um ; HE. Ot pev ttov KoapLioL to crcfieTepov avrcov ?)6o$ tflrovcri, kol Kara bvvapav yapoval re irapa tovtcov d /cat tol9 eKdtSope'va? irap avrcov el? tovtov? eKirep.- ttovctl iraXiv' coy <5' avTcos to irep\ ttjv dvhpeiav yevos i Thus the sober inter- marry with the sober, the bold ■with the bold. But they ought public and the opening of the Timseus it is assumed that in each individual the active and philosophic tempers are com- bined. In the Laws the harder natures are chosen for the highest offices, Legg. 5, 734 e : Kaddnep ovv 8tj Tiva ^vvvcprjv rj ■jrXeyp! aXX' otiovv, ovk e'< tcov avrcov oiov r c'otI tt]V t ecpvcprjv Kai tov o-Trjpova dnepyd^eaBai, biav CTrjpovav irpbs dpeTijv yevos' lo~xv- pov re yap Kai riva (HeftaioTTjTa iv tois rpoirois elX^cpos' to 8e paXa- Kcorepov kcu emetKeta tlv\ 8tKaia Xpmpevov" odev br) tovs peydXas dpxas iv rats iroXeo-iv cipi-ovras bel bLaKpiveo-6ai riva rpdnov Tavrij Kai tovs o-piKpa Tvai8eia (3ao~avL- crde'vTas eKacrTOTe KaTa Xoyov. Cf. Arist. Pol. I. 3 : (pi]crl yap 8eiv a>o~nep e£ eTepov to o~Ti]pdviov epiov yiverai ttjs KpoKrjs, ovtco Kai tovs apxovTas exetv 8elv Trpos tovs dp^opevovs. The same mixture of natures, however, is required in the other citizens, Legg. 6, 773 c • Tavra S17 81a Xoyov pev vopco irpoo-TaTTeiv prj yapelv nXov- criov nXovcriov pr]8e TroXXd 8vvd- pevov npaTTeiv aXXov tolovtov, BaTTOvs 8e rjBeai Trpos (3pabvTe- povs Kai (3pa8vTe'povs irpbs Quttovs dvayKa^eiv ttj tcov ydpav Koivcovia TTopeveadat, npos t<5 yeXola elvaL Bvpov av iyeipai ttoXXoIs' ov yap pa8iov ivvoelv oti ttoXiv eivai Set 8[kt)V KpaTTjpos KeKpapevqv, ov pawopevos pev oivos eyKexvpevos ^€i, KoXa£6pevos be vno vrjcpovros eTepov 6eov KaX?]v Koivwvlav Xaftcov ayaObv Trapa Kai perpiov direpyd- ferat. Compare also the com- bination of qualities required for the guardian in Eep. 2, and for the philosopher in Rep. 6 and the Thea?tetus. 5. ttjv — o-Tepyeiv ] There is a change of construction from the participial form to the dative of the manner. 7. TrXelo-Tov — dnovepovTes] " Giving far more importance to their dislike than to any other consideration." b 2 lcSS IIAATONOI Spa, ri]v aurov perahicaKOV (f)uaii>, 8eov iroLeiv dp(f)o- p. $l(\] { repa to. yevi] tovtcov tovvclvt'lov airav. NE. 20. ricoy, kol Stu tl; SE. Aiotl irtyvKtv dvSpela re eV 7roXXais yeve- 5 crecr^ apiKTo? yevucopevrj acotypovL (frvcrei Kara fxtv ap^as aKpa^ELv pcofirj, reXevTuxra Se l^avQelv iravTa- iraaL pLavious. NE. 20. Wlkos. SE. r H 8e oddovs ye av Xlav 7rXr)pr)9 yj/vx^ K.ai io uKepaaros toA/at)? dvSpelas, im Se yeveas 7roXXa? e our&> yevvYjOeicra, ucoOearepa (f)ve(ppovL (pvo~ei. 6, i^avOelv — fiaviais~\ Tragic. Cf. Soph. Ant. : ovto) rus pavias Beivov aTToura^ei av8r)pov re fievos, Kflvos eVe'yi/o) paviais K.t.X. Aescb. Pei'S. 821 : vfipis yap e^avOova' iKapnao-e trrdxyv cittjs. The dative p.aviais occurs with simi- lar meaning in Legg. 9, 869 a, ib. 881 b, ib. 6,783 a. 9. 'H Be K.r.A.] Sc. 7re(pVKe. alBovs ye] Bodl. re. II. vu>B. rov K.J I.e. a.Ka'ipa>s vcodrjs. Cf. SUpr. 276 e : evrjOe- arepa rov Biovros. 308 a. 14. Tovtovs Br] — eiriTpeneiu'] " It was of these bonds I said that there would be no diffi- culty in creating them, if only both the kinds were first im- bued with one opinion respect- ing what is honourable and good. Yes, this is the single work in which the whole pro- cess of the royal weaving is comprised, never to allow tem- perate natures to keep aloof from the brave, but, warping them together by common sen- timents, by honours, by repu- tation, and by interchange of pledges, to form of both a smooth and closely-woven web, and then to give into their hands the offices of state." Cf. supr. 310 a, b. Rep. 4, 429 c : Bid. TravTOs B' eXeyov avrr)v cra>- rrjpiav to — Biaaa>£eo-dai ovttjv K.T.X. 15- £vv8elv vtt.] Bodl. ijvuvw., not gvvBeiv £vwTT. (Stallb.) 16 kci\ dyaBa] Bodl. KayaQa. nOAITIKOS. 189 310. tovto yap ev koll oXov earl fiacriXiKr}? tjvvvtyavaea)? epyov, prj8eiroTe eav atyiaTaadai au>(f)pova diro twv dv8pelcov ijOrj, IjvyKepKitpvTa 8e bpodoijlcu? kcu TipaTs koll 86^ais koll bpr/peicov eK.86aeo~iv els dXXrjXovs, of truth and right. Com! these tw kinds by every avail- able in- » ~ \ \ » / c./ fluonce of 311. XeLOV KCU TO Xeyop.6VOV eV7]TpiOV VCpaapa ^VVayOVTUS opinionand custom, the kingly art will dele- gate all offices of state to their joint rule, where ejj avTcov, rds ev reus noXeaiv dpyas del KOivf) tov- tol9 iiriTpeireiv. NE. 20. n«y ; HE. Ov pev dv evbs apypvros \peia ijvpfialvr), tov Tama dpL(f)6repa e^ovTa alpovp.evov e7rio~TaTr)V io[^ e ° de C j r OV ft dl> TrXeiOVCOV, TOVTCOV p.epOS eKaTepcOV £vppi- fa^fo*** yvvvra. tcl pev yap aco(j)p6viov dpyovTwv rjdr) cr(j)6- j^'J^ Spa pev evXafirj Kal SiKaia Ka\ crcoTrjpia, 8pLp.vTT)T0? ta f es ' and Be Kal tivos lrap.6rr]T09 bj^eias Ka\ TrpaKTU yiyveaOai (f)apev TroXiTiKrjs irpd^eois, to tcov dv8p€L(£>V KOI aC0(f)p6va>V dv0p(O7TU)V 7)009, biTorav Ofiovola. Ka\ (f)iAla koivov ^vvayayovaa avTcov tov c (3iov r) fiacriXiKr] t4\vtj, iravTwv /x€yaXo7rpe7r€aTaTOv v(f)aa fidroiv Ka\ apiarov dnoTeXeaaaa, # a>V y * elvai io kolvov, rovs t aXXov? iv rah iroXecri irdvTas 8ovXovs kcu iXevOepovs dpm iaypvo a, crvveyr} tovtco tg> irXi- yfiaTt, Kal KaO' ocrov ev8aip.ovL Trpoo-qKtL ylyveaOai. TroXei, toutov /JL7]8a/mfj /jL7]8ev eXXehrovaa apyjl re /cat emo-Tarf}. 3' following. The words are re- jected by Ast, who conjectured Ira/Mov, and Stallb., who here, as elsewhere, unnecessarily sus- pects a gloss. Qy. to{j.6v ? Cf. Tim. 6 1 e. 4. Touto §77 — eVtorar^] " This, then, according to our view, is the perfection of the web of political action, directly woven — the brave and temperate in human character, when the kingly science has drawn the lives of such men into com- munion by unanimity and kind- ness, and having thus com- pleted the most glorious and noble of all webs that are of a public nature, and envelop- ing therewith all other denizens of cities, whether slaves or free, binds them by this con- texture into one, and leaving out no point of a city's happi- ness, in as far as it belongs to a city to attain to happiness, so governs and presides." For (vdvTrXoKia, here metaphorically applied, cf. supr. 283 a. £vfj.7r\aiy II. W. Chandler, M.A. Second Edition. i os. 6d. Farnell. The Cu IU of the Greek States. With Plates. By L. R. Farnell, M.A. Vols. I and II. Svo.' 32s. net. Volume III in Preparation. Grenfell. An Alexandrian Erotic Fragment and other Greek Papyri, chiefly Ptolemaic. Edited by B. P. Grenfell, M.A. Small 4 to. 8s. 6d. net. Grenfell and Hunt. Neiv Classical Fragments and other Greek and Latin Papyri. Edited by B. P. Grenfell, M.A., and A. S. Hunt, M.A. With Plates, 1 2s. 6d. net. Menanders Teooproc. A Revised Text of the Geneva Fragment. With a Translation and Notes by the same Editors. 8vo, stiff covers, is. 6d. Grenfell and Mahaffy. Rev- enue Laws of Ptolemy Philadelphia. 2 vols. Text and Plates, il. us. 6d. net. Haigh. The Attic Theatre. A Description of the Stage and Theatre of the Athenians, and of the Dramatic Performances at Athens. By A. E. Haigh, M.A. Second Edition, Bevised and Enlarged. Svo. 12s. 6d. GREEK WORKS. Haigh. The Tragic Drama of the Greeks. With Illustrations. 8vo. 1 2s. 6d. Head. Historia Numorum: A Manual of Greek Numismatics. By Barclay V. Head. Royal Svo, half-hound, 2l. 2s. Hicks. A Manual of Greek Historical Inscriptions. By E. L. Hicks, M.A. Svo. 10s. 6d. Hill. Sources for Greek His- tory between the Persian and Pelopon- nesian Wars. Collected and arranged by G. F. Hill, M.A. Svo. 10s. 6d. Kenyon. The Palaeography of Greek Papiyri- Ey Frederic G. Kenyon, M.A. Svo, with Twenty Facsimiles,and aTable of Alphabets. 1 os. 6rf. Liddell and Scott. A Greek- English Lexicon, by H. G. Liddell, D. D., and Robert Scott, D. D. Eighth Edition, Revised. 4to. il. 16s. Monro. Modes of Ancient Greek Music. By D. B. Monro, M.A. Svo. 8s. 6d. net. Paton and Hicks. The In- scriptions of Cos. By W. R. Paton and E. L. Hicks. Royal Svo, linen, with Map, 28s. Smyth. The Sounds and Inflections of the Greek Dialects (Ionic). By H. Weir Smyth, Ph.D. 8vo. 24s. Thompson. A Glossary of Greek Birds. By D'Arcy W. Thomp- son. Svo, buckram, 10s. net. Aeschinem et IsocvoXem, Scho- lia Graeca in. Edidit G. Dindorfius. Svo. 4s. Aeschylus. In Single Plays. With Introduction and Notes, by Arthur Sidgwick, M.A. New Edition. Extra fcap. Svo. 3s. each. I. Agamemnon. II. Choephoroi. III. Eumenides. IV. Prometheus Bound. With Introduction and Notes, by A. 0. Prickard, M.A. Third Edition. 2s. Aeschyli quae supersunt in Codice Laurentiano quoad effici potuit et ad cognitionem necesse est visum iypis descripta edidit R. Merkel. Small folio, il. is. Aeschylus : Tragoediae et Fragmenta, ex recensione Guil. Din- dorfii. Second Edition. Svo. 5s. 6d. Annotationes Guil. Din- dorfii. Partes II. Svo. 10s. London: Henry Frowde, Amen Coiner, E.C. STANDARD GREEK WORKS. Apsinis ct Longini Rhctoricc . E CodioibuB mss. rocensuit .Toll. Bakius. 8vo. 3s. Aristophanes. A Complete Concordance to the Comedies and Frag- ments. By H. Dunbar, M.D. 4to. ll. is. Comoediae et Fragmenta, ex recensione Guil. Dindorfii. Tomi II. Svo. 1 is. Annotationes Guil. Din- dorfii. Partes II. 8vo. 1 is. Scholia Graeca ex Co- dicibus aucta et emendata a Guil. Dindorfio. Partes III. 8vo. il. In Single Plays. Edited, with English Notes, Introductions, &c, by W. W. Merry, D.D. Extra fcap. Svo. TheAcharnians. Fourth Edition, 3s. The Birds. Third Edition, 3s. 6d. The Clouds. Third Edition, 3s. The Frogs. Third Edition, 3s. The Knights. Second Edition, 3s. The Wasps. 3s. 6d. Aristotle. Ex recensione Im. Bekkeri. Accedunt Indices Sylburgiani. Tomi XI. 8vo. 2I. 10s. The volumes (except I and IX) may be had separately, price 5s. 6d. each. Ethica Nicomachea, re- cognovit brevique Adnotatione critica instruxit I. Bywater. Svo. 6s. Also in crown 8vo, paper cover, 3s. 6d. Contributions to the Textual Criticism of the Nicoma- chean Ethics. By I. Bywater. 2s. 6d. Notes on the Nieoma- cheanEthics. ByJ.A. Stewart,M.A. 2 vols. 8vo. 32s. Selecta ex Organo A ris- toteleo Capitula. In usum Scho- larum Academicarum. Crown 8vo, stiff covers. 3s. 6d. Be Arte Poetica Liber. Kecognovit Brevique Adnotatione Critica Instruxit I. Bywater, Litter- arum Graecarum Professor Eegius. Post 8vo, stiff covers, is. 6d. Aristotle. The Politics, with Introductions, Notes, &c, by W. L. Newman, M.A. Vols. I and II. Medium Svo. 28s. Vols. Ill and IV. [/n the Press.'] The Politics, trans- lated into English, with Intro- duction, Marginal Analysis, Notes, and Indices, by B. Jowett, M.A. Medium Svo. 2 vols. 21s. The English Manuscripts of the Nicomachean Ethics, described in relation to Bekker's Manuscripts and other Sources. By J. A. Stewart, M.A. (Anecdota Oxon. ) Small 4to. 3s. 6d. Physics. Book VII. Collation of various mss. ; with In- troduction by R. Shute, M.A. (Anec- dota Oxon. ) Small 4to. 2s. Choerobosci Dictata in Theo- dosii Canones, necnon Epimerismi in Psalmos. E Codicibus mss. edidit Thomas Gaisford, S.T.P. Tomi III. 8vo. 15s. Demosthenes. Ex recensione G. Dindorfii. Tomi IX. 8vo. 2l. 6s. Separately — Text, il. is. Annotations, 15s. Scholia, 10s. Demosthenes and Aeschines. The Orations of Demosthenes and Aeschines on the Crown. With Introductory Essays and Notes. By G. A. Simcox, M.A., and W. H. Simcox, M.A. 8vo. 12s. Demosthenes. Orations against Philip. With Introduction and Notes, by Evelyn Abbott, M.A., and P. E. Matheson, M.A. Vol. I. Philippic I. Olynthiacs I-III. Extra fcap. 8vo. 3s. Vol. II. De Pace, Philippic II. De Chersoneso, Philippic III. Extra fcap. 8vo. 4s. 6d. Euripides. Tragoediae et Fragmenta, ex recensione Guil. Din- dorfii. Tomi II. 8vo. 10s. Oxford : Clarendon Press. STANDARD GREEK WORKS. Euripides. Guil. Dindorfii Annotationes Partes II. 8vo. Scholia Graeca, ex Codi- aibus aucta et emendata a Guil. Dindorfio. Tomi IV. 8vo. ll. 16s. Hephaestionis Enchiridion, Terentianus Maurus, Proclus, &c. Edidit T. Gaisford,S.T.P. Tomi II. ios. Heracliti Ephesii Reliquiae. Recensuit I. Bywater, M. A. Appen- dicis loco additae sunt Diogenis Laertii Vita Heracliti, Particulae Hippocratei De Diaeta Lib. I. , Epi- stolae Heracliteae. 8vo. 6s. Herodotus. Books V and VI, Terpsichore and Erato.- Edited, with Notes and Appendices, by- Evelyn Abbott, M.A., LL.D. 8vo, with two Maps, ios. 6d. Homer. A Complete Con- cordance to the Odyssey and Hymns of Homer; to which is added a Con- cordance to the Parallel Passages in the Iliad, Odyssey, and Hymns. By Henry Dunbar, M.D. 4to. iZ. is. A Grammar of the Ho- meric Dialed. By D. B. Monro, M. A. 8vo. Second Edition. 14s. Ilias, ex rec. Guil. Din- dorfii. 8vo. 5s. 6d. Scholia Graeca in Hiadem. Edited by W. Dindorf, after a new collation of the Venetian mss. by D. B. Monro, M.A. 4 vols. 8vo. 2l. ios. Scholia Graeca in Hiadem Townleyana. Recensuit Ernestus Maass. 2 vols. 8vo. il. 16s. ex rec. G. 5s. 6d. Graeca in Edidit Guil. Dindorfius. 8vo. 15s. 6d. Dindorfii. 8vo Scholia Tomi II. Homer. Odyssey. Books I- XII. Edited with English Notes, Appendices, &c. By W. W. Merry, D.D., and James Riddell, M.A. Srcoiul Villi ion. NV". 1 6s. Books B. Mom XIII- >, M.A. XXIV. By D. [In the Press.'] Hymni Homerici. Codi- cibus denuo collatis recensuit Alfred us Goodwin. Small folio. With four Plates. 2 is. net. Homeri Opera et Reliquiae. Monro. Crown 8vo. India Paper. Cloth, ios. 6d. net. Also in various leather bindings. Oratores Attici, ex recensione Bekkeri : Vol. III. Isaeus, Aeschines, Lycurgus, Dinarchus, &c. 8vo. 7s. [Vols. I and II are out of print] Index Andocideus, Ly- curgeus, Dinarcheus, confectus a Ludovico Learning Forman, Ph.D. 8vo. 7s. 6d. Paroemiographi Graeci, quo- rum pars nunc primum ex Codd. mss. vulgatur. Edidit T. Gaisford, S.T.P. 1836. 8vo. 5s. 6d. Plato. Apology, with a re- vised Text and English Notes, and a Digest of Platonic Idioms, by James Riddell, M.A. Svo. 8s. 6d. Philebus, with a revised Text and English Notes, by Edward Poste, M.A. Svo. 7s. 6d. Republic. The Greek Text. Edited, with Notes and Essays, by B. Jowett, M.A. and Lewis Campbell, M.A. In three vols. Medium Svo. 2I. 2s. Sophistes and Politicus, with a revised Text and English Notes, by L. Campbell, M.A. Svo. ios. 6d. London: Henry Frowde, Amen Corner, E.O. STANDARD GREEK WORKS Plato. T// ('<<<>!('/ tis, with a re- vised Text and English Notes, by L. Campbell, M.A. Second Edition. 8vo. i os. 6d. The Dialogues, trans- lated into English, with Analyses and Introductions, by B. Jowett, ! M.A. Third Edition. 5 vols, medium 8vo. Cloth, 4?. 4s.; half-morocco, 5?. The Republic, translated into English, with Analysis and Introduction, by B. Jowett, M.A. Third Edition. Medium 8vo. 1 2s. 6d. ; half- roan, 14s. With Introduction and Notes. By St. George Stock, M.A. Extra fcap. 8vo. I. The Apology, 2s. 6d. II. Crito, 2s. III. Meno, 2s. 6d. Selections. With Intro- ductions and Notes. By John Purves, M.A., and Preface by B. Jowett, M.A. Second Edition. Extra fcap. Svo. 5s. A Selection of Passages from Plato for English Readers; from the Translation byB. Jowett, M.A. Edited, with Introductions, by M. J. Knight. 2 vols. Crown Svo, gilt top. 12s. Plotinus. Ediclit F. Creuzer. Tomi III. 4to. il. 8s. Polybius. Selections. Edited by J. L. Strachan- Davidson, M.A. With Maps. Medium Svo. 2 is. Plutarehi Moralia, id est, Opera, exceptis Vitis, reliqua. Edidit Daniel Wyttenbach. Accedit Index Graecitatis. Tomi VIII. Partes XV. 1795-1830. Svo, cloth, 2,1. 1 os. Sophocles. The Plays and Fragments. With English Notes and Introductions, by Lewis Campbell, M.A. 2 vols. Svo, 1 6s. each. Vol.1. Oedipus Tyrannus. Oedi- pus Coloneus. Antigone. Vol. II. Ajax. Electra. Trachi- niae. Philoctetes. Fragments. Sophocles. Tragoediae et Fragmenta, ex recensions et cum • ■••in iii<-iit :irii.s Guil. Dindorfii. Third Edition. 2 vols. Fcap. Svo. Each Play separately, limp, t otim i. Third ll. 18. 28. 6rf. Tragoediae et Fragmenta cum Annotationibus Guil. Dindorfii. Tomi II. 8vo. 10s. The Text, Vol. I. 5s. 6d. The Notes, Vol. II. 4s. 6d. Stobaei Florilegium. Ad mss. fidem emendavit et supplevit T. Gaisford, S.T.P. Tomi IV. 8vo. it Eclogarum Physicarum et Ethicarum libri duo. Accedit Hieroclis Commentarius in aurea carmina Pythagoreorum. Ad mss. Codd. recensuit T. Gaisford, S.T.P. Tomi II. Svo. us. Strabo. Selections, with an Introduction on Strabo's Life and Works. By H. F. Tozer, M.A., F.R.G.S. Svo. With Maps and Plans. 12 s. Theodoreti Graecarum Affec- tionum Ouratio. Ad Codices mss. recensuit T. Gaisford, S.T.P. Svo. 7s. 6d. Thueydides. Translated into English, with Introduction, Mar- ginal Analysis, Notes, and Indices. By B. Jowett, M.A. [Reprinting.'] Xenophon. Ex recensione et cum annotationibus L. Dindorfii. Historia Graeca. Second Edition . Svo. 1 os. 6d. Expeditio Cyri. Second Edition. 8vo. ios.6d. Institutio Cyri. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Memorabilia Socratis. Svo. js. 6d. Opuscula Politica Eqtieslria et Venatica cum Arriani Libello de Venatione. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Oxford: Clarendon Press. MISCELLANEOUS STANDARD WORKS. 3. MISCELLANEOUS Arbuthnot. The Life and Works of John Arbuthnot. By George A. Aitken. Svo, cloth extra, with Portrait, 16s. Bacon. The Essays. Edited with Introduction and Illustrative Notes, by S. H. Reynolds, M.A. Svo, half-bound, 1 2s. 6d. Casaubon (Isaac), 1559-1614. By Mark Pattison, late Eector of Lincoln College. Second Edition. Svo. 1 6s. Finlay. A History of Greece from its Conquest by the Romans to the present time, B.C. 146 to a. d. 1864. By George Finlay, LL.D. A new Edition, revised throughout, and in part re-written, with considerable additions, by the Author, and edited by H. F. Tozer, M.A. 7 vols. Svo. ll. 1 os. Gaii Institutionum Juris Civilis Commentarii Quattuor ; or, Ele- ments of Eoman Law by Gaius. With a Translation and Commen- tary by Edward Poste, M.A. Third Edition. Svo. iSs. Hodgkin. Italy and her In- vaders. With Plates and Maps. By Thomas Hodgkin, D.C.L. a.d. 376-744. Svo. Vols. I and II, Second Edition, 2l. 2s. Vols. Ill and IV, Second Edition, ll. 16s. Vols. V and VI, it. 16s. Vol. VII. In the Press. Hooker, Sir J. D., and B. D. Jackson. Index Keivensis. 2 vols. 4to. 10I. 1 os. net. Ilbert. The Government of India ; being a Digest of the Statute Law relating thereto. With Historical Introduction and Illus- trative Documents. By Sir Courtenay Ilbert, K.C.S.I. Svo, half-roan, 2 is. STANDARD WORKS. Justinian. Imperatoris Tus- tiniam Institutionum Libri Quattuor', with Introductions, Commentary, Excursus and Translation. By 3 . B. Moyle, D.C.L. Third Edition. 2 vols. Svo. 22s. Machiavelli. II Principe. Edited by L. Arthur Burd. With an Introduction by Lord Acton. Svo. 14s. Pattison. Essays by the late Hark Pattison, sometime Rector of Lincoln College. Collected and Arranged by Henry Nettleship, M.A. 2 vols. 8vo. 24s. Payne. History of the Ne%v World called America. By E. J. Payne, M.A. Svo, Vol. I, 18s. ; Vol. II, 14s. Kalegh. Sir Walter Ralegh. A Biography. By W. Stebbing, M.A. Svo. 10s. 6d. Ramsay. The Cities and Bishoprics ofPhrygia ; being an Essay on the Local History of Phrygia, from the Earliest Times to the Turkish Conquest, By W. M. Ramsay,D.C.L.,LL.D. Vol.1. Part I. The Lycos Valley and South-Western Phrygia. Royal Svo, linen, 18s. net. Vol. I. Part II. West and West- Central Phrygia. Royal Svo, linen, 2 is. net. Stokes. The Anglo -Indian Codes. By Whitley Stokes, LL.D. Vol. I. Substantive Law. 8vo. 30s. Vol. II. Adjective Law. 8vo. 35s. Strachey. Hastings and The Bohilla War. By Sir John Strachey, G.C.S.I. Svo, cloth, 10s. 6d. Thomson. Notes on Recent Researches in Electricity and Magnetism. By J. J.Thomson, M.A.,F.R.S. Svo. iSs. 6d. Woodhouse. Aetolia; its Geography, Tojmgraphy, and Antiquities. By William J. Woodhouse, M.A., FlR.G.S. With Maps and Illus- trations. Royal Svo, linen, price 2 is. net. London : Henry Frowpe, Amen Corner, E.C. STANDARD THEOLOGICAL WORKS. 4. STANDARD THEOLOGICAL WORKS, &c. St. Basil : The Booh of St. Basil on the Holy Spirit. A Kevised Text, with Notes and Introduction by C. F. H. Johnston, M.A. Crown 8vo. 7.S. (til. The Coptic Version of the New Testament, in the Northern Dialect, otherwise called Memphitic and Bohairic. With Introduction, Criti- cal Apparatus, and Literal English Translation. The Gospels. 2 vols. 8vo. 2l. 2S. Bright. Chapters of Early English Church History. By W. Bright, D.D. Third Edition. 8vo. 1 2s. Canons of the First Four General Councils of Nicaea, Con- stantinople, Ephesus, and Chalcedon. With Notes, by W. Bright, D.D. Second Edition. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. The Book of Enoch. Trans- lated from Dillmann'sEthiopic Text (emended and revised), and Edited by K. H. Charles, M.A. Svo. 16s. Conybeare . Th e Key of Truth. A Manual of the Paulician Church of Armenia. The Armenian Text, edited and translated with illus- trative Documents and Intro- duction by F. C. Conybeare, M.A. Svo. 15s. net. Driver. The Parallel Psalter, being the Prayer-Book Version of the Psalms and a New Version, ar- ranged in parallel columns. With an Introduction and Glossaries. By the Rev. S. R. Driver, D.D., Litt.D. Extra fcap. Svo. 6s. Ecclesiasticus (xxxix. 15 — xlix. 11). The Original Hebrew, with Early Versions and Knglish Translations, itc. Edited by A. Cowley, M.A., and Ad. Neubaueb, M.A. 4to. 10s. 6d. net. Hatch and Redpath. A Con- corda/nce to the Greek Versions and J/inrrif/iltiil Jinnl.-s of the Old Testament. By the late Edwin Hatch, M.A., and H. A. Redpath, M.A. In Six Parts. Imperial 4to. 21s. each. Ommanney. A Critical Dis- sertation on the Athanasian Creed. Its Original Language, Bate, Authorship^ Titles, Text, Reception, and Use. By G. D. W. Ommanney, M.A. 8vo. 1 6s. Turner. Ecclesiae Occiden- talis Monumenta Iuris Antiquissima : Canonum et Conciliorum Grae- corum Interpretationes Latinae. Edidit Cuthbertus Hamilton Turner, A.M. Fasc. I. pars. I. 4to, stiff covers, 10s. 6d. Wordsworth and "White. Nouum Testamenlum Domini Nostri Iesu Christi Latine, secundum Edi- tionem Sancti Hieronymi. Ad Codicum Manuscriptorum fidem recensuit Iohannes Wordsworth, S.T.P., Episcopus Sarisburiensis ; in operis societatem adsumto Henrico Iuliano White, A.M. 4to. Pars I, buckram, 2l. 12s. bd. Also, separately — Fasc. I. 1 2s 6d. ; Fasc. II. 7s 6d. ; Fasc. III. 12s. 6d. ; Fasc. IV. 10s. 6d. Fasc. V. 10s. 6d. Oxfotb AT THE CLARENDON PRESS LONDON: HENRY FROWDE OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE, AMEN CORNER, E.C. *?-£$ ^ V ^o X , f fi X o N 2 . \ . -X' ^ ■«•, r> O V .cr c ° * " % ■v <$*, - : - >-- ^j ^ « f : £ '*** ^ %. ^ ^> V & \

v eri iroppcdOev ucjjecrTrjKOTCou eivai. aE. Toiyapovv r)i±eis ae otSe iravres neipaaofieOa Kai vvv 7reipu)/i€0a &>? iyyvrara avev roiv 7raOrjpdrcov hTrpocrayeiv. 7rep\ <5' ovv rod crocpiaTov rode /uloi Xeye' iroTepov rjSr) tovto croupe? on tcov yorjToov eari tl?, p. fli/X1]T1]9 OJV TCOV OVTOJV, 7] diaTatfifieV 6TL fir) 7T6/01 ocrcovTvep dvTiXeyeiv Sokcl 8vvolto? eivai, 7rep\ toctov- tcov kcu ra? eirxTTrjiias dX-qOcos k\cov Tvyyava ; i0 0EAI. Kcu 7tco? dv, co ije've ; dXXd ayebov rfSr) aa(j)€? €K tcov elprj/xevcov on tcov tyjs 7rou8ia9 fxere- \ovtcov earl n? fiepcov. lb. 10, 888 b : & nal, veos ef, npoicov 8e ae 6 xpovos 7rotrjaei iroXXa hv vvv §o£d£ei? peTafta- \6vra eirl rdvavria Tideadai. I. 'Cls epol — Kplvat = as epol Kpirfj. The infinitive is epexe- getic. 3. Toiyapovv r)pels ae o"i8e\ Cf. Legg. IO, 905 c : ravra el p,ev ae ire'idei Kkeivlas o8e ko.1 ^vpnaaa rjpwv r]8e r) yepovaia, Kakas av aoi Kai 6 debs avTbs £-vWap(Sdvoi. impels otSe] = {-evos, Qe68a>pos, 2a>KpaTr]s. 4. tSjv TradriixaTav] The article refers to 81a Tvadrjparav above. 5. 0' ovv] " But, to return." 7. prj expresses that an af- firmative answer to the question which it introduces is regarded as possible. I 2 . earl, tis pepav] Heindorf objects to p.epcbv on the ground that the only way of constru- ing the words as they stand is to suppose p-epuv to be go- verned by perexovrmv. " That he is one of those who par- take of the divisions of child's- play." But why may not the words be taken more simply? — "That he occupies (lit. is) one of the departments which partake of the nature of child's-play." The confusion of the man and his function, the juxtaposition of the masculine with the femi- nine and neuter, has already occurred several times in this dialogue, e. g. 225 a : to xPV- panariKov yevos, ipi.aTiK.rjs ov Texvrjs, — early — 6 ao(piarr)s. The article in ttjs 7rai8ias re- fers to p. 234 a : 7rai8iav — 7ratSta?. Accordingly, tcov ttjs 7ratoids perexovToov pepav IS equivalent to tS>v tt)s pipT)riKr)s pepwv. That pipr/TiKT] is divided into many parts is implied supr. 234 b, els ev iravTa gvWa- /3fflv, and in the epithet ttoiki- \ararov. Cf. also infr. C : Kara peprj rrjs pipr}TiKr)s. 235 a: ttjs pipr/TiKrjs to eiil tovtco pepos. lb. b : ttoXv tovto to p.epos Kara — p,ipr]TLKrjv. The conjecture ets, adopted by the Zurich edi- tors (earl tis pepav els. Totjtu), 2CXM2TH2. 75 p. 235. HE. Ely yoijTa ptev 81) Ka\ piiprjTrji/ apa OeTeov 0EAI. IlcSy yap ov OeTeov ; HE. 'Aye 81], vvv i-jfxlrepov epyov rj8rj tov Orjpa b prjKer aveivai' aye8ov yap avTov irepieiki^apiev evb ap.({)l(3Al1(TTpiKCp Tivl TCOV ev TOIS \6yOl9 7Tepl TO. roiavra opyavcov, coare ouk€t eK(pev£eTai Tooe ye. 0EAI. To ivoLov ; HE. To /uly] ov tov yevovs elvai tov tcov OavpiaTo- ttoicov Ti? eh. *< GEAI. Kdpiol tovto ye ovtco irep\ avTov ^vv8oKel. HE. Ae8etKTai tolvvv o tl Ta^iaTa 8iaipeiv rrjv But what □ he not ;t mimic and a maker I though involving only a slight change, is unmeaning and gives a wrong emphasis. The case is different below (235 b : ns els), where the point is that he cannot escape being some one amongst the varieties of the genus jug- gler. Here naiSias is the em- phatic word. The next words, els yorjTa, admit of a similar explanation. The masculine noun is substi- tuted for the neuter of the kind or genus. He must be referred to the genus sorcerer, and to a species of mimic. Cf. Polit. 281 C : irorepov ovv 6 nepl ttjs ixpavTiKrjs Adyo? Ixaveos corral ftiG>pi.o~pevos, eav ap' airrjv twv eTTipekeiav, OTrocrai ivep\ rrjv epedv ia6rjTa, els ttjv KaXKlarrjv kcu peylarr^v Tracrcov ridapev ; where, however, the Zurich editors have elal, but see note. Legg. 9, 867 b : els eluova pev ap(pco Belvat. Tim. 57 e : els dvcopaXo- TTjra ridapev. For a similar use of the concrete for the ab- stract, cf. Rep. 382 d : IloiTjTr]s apa yjsevbrjs ev Bern ovk. evi. i. yorjTa] So the art of the Xoyo7rotot is described in Euthyd. 289 e : eVn — ttjs rav eTTcpdap Te%vr]s popiov o~piKpa> tl eKeivrjs vnoSeearepa. 4. vvv rjperepov — aveivai] The near approach made in these words to an anapaestic tetra- meter can hardly be accidental. And there is a tone of bur- lesque tragedy in the order of the words. 6. dp. Cf. Theset. 197 a : tovtov t 76 nAATONOS It bo, we must take the art of image- making and pro- c< ed \\ iili our method of dr\ i- sions. ei8oj\o7roiLK7]v Te^iju, koll KaTafidvTas els avTr^v, iai> p. 235. /xeV i]fAas tvOvs 6 ao(j)icrTi)? VTrofielvrj, avAAa(3eli> avrov Kara ra e7rearaXp.eva imo rov (BacriXiKOv Xoyov, KUKelvcp napahovras diro^vac rrjv dypav' c 5 edv <5' dpa Kara p.epr) rrj? pup.rjrLKrjs' Bvtjtou 7rr), £vva- KoXovOelv aura), Siaipovvra? del rrjv VTrobeyop.evr)v avrov ptoipav, ecoarrep dv Xr}(j)6r}. rvdvrais ovre ovros ovre dXXo yevos ovdev p.r) irore eKfpvyhv errev^qrai ri]u rcov ovrco Svvap-evcov \xerievai kol@' eKacrra re koll loeVt iravra peOodov. av e'tpr] a7re)(e(T6ai, and note. Isocr. Nicocl. 36 : cprjpl 8fj TTpaTTUv eKaaTOv f]jj.a>v eVt/xeXws'. AedoKTcu, the reading of some MSS. and of the old editions, agrees well with the preced- ing context, but not so well Avith the new matter in what follows. Compare Kep. 4, 432 b : vvv Sj) rjpas Set axTTrep Kvvrjyhas Tivas dupvov TrepucrTacrdat., nvpo- cre)(OVTas ov rroWa eK(pevyeis Traidias errj. 8. oi — pr] noTe eKCpvyov enev- ijrjTai] This sounds like an echo of Soph. (Ed. Col. 1024: ovs ov ur) rrore ^copa? (pvyovres ttjo-8' eTrev^covrai Oeo'is. See oiiceT in- (pevgerai supr., and cf. Legg. IO, 900 a : ov pr) irore eirev^r/rat irepiyeveadai 6eav. II). 12, 969 b : to ye dvbpeioraros eivat 80- Kelv — ova incpev^ei irore. 9. naS" e/cacrra — iravra] Pass- ing over no kind and extend- 20I2TH2. 77 re i a p. 235. 0EAI. Aeyei? ev, /ecu tclvtcl ravrj) iroLi]Teov. SE. Kara dr/ tov 7rapeXt]Av6oTa Tpoirov tij? 8lul- ti d peaetos eycoye jjlol kcll vvv (j)alvopaL 8vo Kadopu.v e\8i] appu tt)s pip->]TiKi]9 Ti]v oe (r]Tovpevr)v Loeav, ev oiroTepo) iroO* rjplv ovaa Tvyyavei, KarapLaOeiv ovSe7rco p.0L$ 8okco vvv 8vvoltos eirai. 0EAI. 2?) <5' aAA' ei7re irpcoTov kcll 8leXe rjplv rive to) 8vo key as. £;E. Wllav /jl€V ti~jv eiKaarLKrjv bpcov ev avrrj The for- 1 » m <•/ /. f / v v mer, whicli Teyyr\v. ecrTL o avTrj jiaAicrTa, oiroTav Kara ra? tov 10 W e may ^ / / , / \ , r call a like- Trapaoeiy holtos avp^peTpLas tis ev p.7]K€i kcll irAarei n ess, is v Q //, \ n / y / j 5, in \ that in kcll pat/ei, kcll irpos tovtols erL yjpcopaTCL airooLOovs wn i c h the \ / «/ \ ~ / / propor- e tcl 7rpoai]Kovra e/cacrrcuy, tijv tov pipLrjpLaros yeveaLv tj ons and > t y colours of airepyaip-jTaL. the original 0EAI. Ti 8'; OV TTOLVTeS o\ pLlpLOVpevOL TL TOVT 15 pressed. eiTL)(eLpovaL 8pav ; £?E. Ovkovv ocroi ye tcov peydXcov ttov tl irXar- tovctlv epycov rj ypd(f)ovo-LV. el yap ci7ro8L8olev ttjv ing to all : at once special and general, individual and univer- sal. Compare Phaadr. 265-273. 7. 2u 8' aXX' eiVe] Cf. Xen. Hell. III. 4, 26 : ArroKpivopevov 8e tov 'AyrjaiXdov, on ovk ay TvoirjCTiu ravra civev ra>v o'Ikoi re\£>v, 2u 5' aX\a, ecos av irv6y ra irapa rrjs TroXeas, fiera^coprjcrov e re eivai K.a\ piprjri^v. 0. 6pcbv\ ra) 8110 Xeya IS understood from the preceding sentence. The ace. is governed partly by Xe'yco, partly by 6p£>v. r 13. t*}v tov piprjparos ykveo~iv\ The word yepeo-is frequently occurs in these dialogues with something of a technical mean- ing. Here it seems almost pleonastic. Cf. Legg. 4, 712 a : rore TToXire'ias rijs cipiCTTTjs cpverai ysvecris. Rep. 2, 37 I d : Ka7TT]\a>v — yeveaiv. Compare Cratyl. 432 c, where the fur- ther distinction is drawn be- tween KparvXov ei/cwj/ and 8vo KparvXoi. 15. 7rai/Te? ol pipovpevol ri] " All who try to imitate any- thing." 16. iTTixtipovcri Spav almost = bpSxri. Cf. Theaet. 196 d, Phsedr. 265 e, et passim. 17. irov\ "Anpvhere," "on any occasion." 78 nAATONOS The false image is that, in whichthese only seem to be lire- served, be- cause of the posi- tion of the spectator. tcov kciXcov dXijOivijv avp/JieTpiav, oia&' on a/JLiKpo- p. 235. repa fxev tov Se'ovTO? ra dvco, p.el(oo Se ru Karoo p. 236. (f)aii>OLT dv Sid to to. /xev TvoppobQev, to. 8 eyyvOev v(fi rjpicov bpdaOai. dp ovv ov yaipeiv to dXr/Oh 5 eacravTes 01 Srjpiiovpyol vvv ov tols ovaas avfipie- Tpia?, dXXd tos dofjovaas elvai koAo? rois eiScoXois evonrepyd(pvTai ; 0EAL Yldvv fxev ovv. /HE. To fxev dpa erepov ov Sikciiov, eiKO? ye ov, 10 eiKova KaXelv ; GEAI. No/. S*E. Kou 7-779 ye \xipx\i iKr}<$ to eiri tovtco ixepos b KXrjreov oirep emo\xev ev tco 7rp6o~0ev, eiKaaTiKTjv ; GEAI. KXrjTeov. J 5 SE. T/ oY; to (pa.ivop.evov p.ev Sid tt]V ovk e/c 1. tcov KaXmv] Badham conj. kqSKcov, but cf. KaXas infra, 1. 6. 5. vvv] " In point of fact." The position of tlie word is curious. Cf. supr., 218 b : ap)(op.evco rrpcoTov, cos epo\ cpaive- rai, vvv dno tov aocpicrrov. ras ovcras] tcov koKcov is pro- bably to be supplied in thought. 8. ndw fxev ovv] These words are not omitted in the Bod- leian MS., as Gaisford asserts. 9. et/eds ye ov] ye = are, as above, 2 2ic: to ye ovopa tovto 1 2. to eVl tovto] "Whose work this is." Cf. Kep. 5,477 d : 8wd- p.ecos 8' els eKelvo fiovov jSAeVeo, e(fi' co Te eo-TL Kcil o dnepyd^eTai. 13. ev tco TrpoaBev] 235 d. 15. 81a ttjv ovk eK xakov 6iav] Heindorf, following Schleier- macher, called this reading- senseless, and thought that ovk had arisen out of ex. And ovk is certainly omitted in Coisl. 2. Y., but Coisl. has e* KaXov p.T)8ap.cos. Stallbaum agrees with Heindorf, who renders £k Ka- Xov, ex loco opportune and quotes Aristoph. Thesm. 293 : TTOV, TTOV KCtdlfap.' iv KClkcO TCOV prjTopcov iv i^aKovoo. C. F. Her- mann conjectures 81a ttjv ciko- Xovdiav, " because of the con- gruity" (it is rather the ap- parent congruity) "of the proportions." The difficulty arises simply from misappre- hension. The point is that in addressing persons who are at a distance from the truth of things (jroppco ttjs dXi]delas dcpeo-TcoTas, supr. 234 c) the Sophist is able to give his arguments the appearance of wisdom. The unfavourable position in which his hearers stand is the cause of their delusion, as in the case of the 20 vop,o6e- tt]s 8e — to (tkotos dcpeXcov — Treio-ci — cos eo-Kiaypa (prjcriv eoiKe'vai] " Which it professes to resemble." 3 xa\ovp.ev] Future tense. (paiveTat pev\ eoiKevai, which is added in one or two MSS., is easily supplied from eoiKe S' ov. Cf. supr. 233 b : P-i]Te eKeivois ecpaivovTo, and note. 4. . HE. 'Ap' ovv avTO yLyvcocrKCov £vpL(prjs, y) ere olov pvfJLT] ti?, V7TO tov Xoyov crvveiOicrpevov, vvv eire- ocnrdcjcLTO irpo? to Tayy tjv/jL Aiovvcrodape ; One MS. (Flor. i) has ti. 15. jieo-Ta] Ora. Bodl. A 11. The v of io-Tiv was 20 6 Xoyo? ovtos vTVoOicrOai to /jltj ov elvar \jsev8os yap ovk av aXXoos lylyvero ov. Ylap- /xevlSrjs Be 6 [leyas, co 7rai, Traicriv jiev \i]plv\ ovaiv. first confused with the initial p., and then the remaining letters ecrra were lost. (15.) e" t<5 7Tp6adev xpQ vt ? KCH viv] Cf. These t. 187 c : Opdr- rei pi 7Tcos vvv re Kal tiXXoTe 8f] noKKcLKLS, s eivai, Kal tovto (fideytjdpevov ivavTioXoylq pf] o~v- vex^o-Bai. Heindorf, who is followed by Stallbaum, inter- prets the words differently : " Difficile enim prorsus est dictu, quomodo oporteat ali- quem, qui fieri posse cheat (dwovTa) ut falsa quis dicat aut cogitet, dum vel hoc pro- nuntiat (*ai tovto (fideygdpevov) non sibimet ipsum contraria proloqui." Snas is here unna- turally separated from elirovra : xpn is too remote from the infinitive o-vvixeo~8ai, and the meaning given to Kal is forced. For on-coy elnuvra XP*1 Xeyeiv, cf. Legg. 4, 709 b : TO 6"' eCTTL — ■ndvTa TavT tlnovra SoKelv ev Xeyeiv. 3. o-vvexeo-dtu expresses the state of distressing uncertainty to which the mind .is reduced by Eristic. Cf. Theset. 165 c : iv (ppiaTi o-vvexopevos. Al". Eth. Nic. VII. 3 : 8e8(Tui yap fj 8id- voia, orav peveiv pev pfj fiovXrjTai 81a t6 pfj dpicrKeiv to o-vpirepav- 6ev, npoievai 8e pf] 8vvrjTai 8id to pfj Xvaai e'xeiv tov Xoyov. 6. 6 Xo'yo? ovtos] Sc. \j/ev8ij ovtcos elvai. Cf. Rep. 4, 440 a : outos pevToi, ecprj, 6 Xoyos crrj- paivei k.t.X. 8. Traicriv pev [fjpiv] ovcriv, dpxd- pevos 8e Kal 8id Te'Xovs] " It was in our boyhood that we heard him, but he never ceased to inculcate the same lesson." The Stranger means to inti- mate that although he was young when he heard Parme- nides he had good reason to remember this warning, fjp'iv, omitted in most MSS., is read for pev in a B C i : S, with the edition of Stephanas, giving also ye for 8e. Hence Bekker reads iraio-iv fjplv ovaiv dpxdpevos re Kai 81a TeXovs. For how can we afKnii the existence of these, with out contra- M dieting the principle which Par- nienides taught us, ■' \\ I,:, I is not, never will be found to be?" 82 IIAATQNOS apyppevos be kol Sict reXovs tovto uirepapTupaTO, p. 237. neCr} re code eKaarore Xeycov kcu pera peTpcov' ov yap fxti irore tovt iovSa/xf]^, ateT|Tai, Kcii BaTepov ovtos dfa- 4>aii/ea0ai. 258 d (where the lines are quoted again) : 'Hpe'is 8e ye ov povov a>s eo~Ti to. pr) ovra dne8ei£apev, dXXd Kal to ei8os 6 Tvy%dvei ov tov pr) ovtos airefyv)- vdp.eQo.. lb. e : Mr) to'ivvv r)pds e'iirrf tls oti rovvavTiov tov ovtos to pr) ov 6.Tzo^>a\.v6p.evoi To'Xpai- pev \eyeiv cb? scttiv. lb. a : r) QaTepov (pvo-is €$&vr\ TCOV OVTCOV ovo-a. Legg. 7, 818 b : oi8e 6ebs dvdyxr] pr) tvots (pavr/ paxo- pevos. Kep. 7, 525 e : pij 7tot€ (pavjj. Karsten, followed by Stallbaum, defends the text on the ground that Parmeni- des is said to have given the maxim both in verse and prose. But it is puerile to imagine that he spoke verse and prose in the same breath, or that Plato would quote a conversational as part of a written utterance. It is cer- tainly remarkable that the same corruption should be found in the copies of Plato and Aristotle. 4. Sitfpevos] This is the reading of all the MSS. in this place. In the later pas- sage, 258 d, where the words are again quoted, 8i(,r)pevos is read in C. H. and Corr. B. : S. has Si^o-tos : the rest 8i£r)- o-ios. The latter is probably Parmenides' word ; but it is possible that Plato may have substituted the more prosaic 8i(r)p(vos for this, as in Theaet. 173 e, in the quotation from Pindar, (peperai is probably substituted for 7reVerat. The MS. reading is, therefore, re- tained in the text. 6. 6 Xdyos avTos] ovtos Bodl. rAHet pr. B. But see Theaet. 151 a, avTol, and note. The variation is probably due to 6 Xdyos ovtos above. 6 Xdyos, 20v \6yoov Troiovpevot. The words here are not ironical, but mark the real importance of the inquiry. The sentence is broken by the introduction of the supposition, " Let us not put the question in a spirit of strife or mockery, but suppose one of the hear- M ers of Parmenides had seri- ously to point out, after re- flection, to what this name Not-Being must be given, to what object or kind of objects do we imagine he would be able himself to ap- ply the term, and to direct the questioner to do so ?" Par- menides is conceived as thus questioning one of his hearers in defence of his thesis. It is also possible to make the first clause a part of the supposi- tion : " Suppose one of the hearers were asked, not in a spirit of strife or mockery, but in good earnest, to give his matured opinion." But the sentence when thus rendered, though more grammatical, is less conversational. Compare Phileb. 44 e : Set 8ij - Tapxe, Kaddnep e' ( uoi, kol tovtois toIs 8vo-x(palvovo-Lv d-TTOKpiveardai. Rep. 7, 516 e. IO. dTTO(pr)vaadai] The Bodl., with corr. AIJ and pr. BE, has drroKpivao-daL, which is probably a corruption arising out of the Kp in aKpoaTchv. 84 OAATONOS If Parme- nides had asked, Of what is Non-exist- ence pre- dicable? what should we reply ? Certainly not of any fyeiv 8oKovfj.€i> av els ti kcll hr\ ttolov uvtov re Kara- p. 237. \pi)craor6(u koll tco irvvOavofievoy deiKvvvai ; GEAI. XaXtwbv rjpov kcu aryebbv ebrelp oico ye ejjioi iravTairaaLv airopov. 5 aE. AAA' ovv tovto ye 8r)\ov, otl tg>v ovtcov e7TL TL TO (XT) OV OVK olcTTeOV- GEAI. TIcos yap av ; HE- Ovkovv eirehrep ovk €7rl to ov, ovS" eVt to t\ (pepcov 6p6w av tls (pepoi. to GEAI. nm 8j ; SiE. Kal tovto rj/jLiv ttov (pavepov, cbs Ka\ to tl d 1. exeiv] The Bocll. and Vat. have ™ : six other MSS. oti : Veil. II. ti' ex etv '• ^ e other nine have *x&,v. Stall- baum has adopted the Bod- leian reading, and translates : " Quid censemus ? cuinam rei et quali designando eum pu- tamus et ipsum illud adhibi- turum et quserenti demon- straturum V But he has not satisfactorily accounted for the appearance of e'xeiv, which makes perfectly good sense. For the emphatic position of els ti, cf. Prot. 3 1 8 d : 'imvoKpd- ttjs — fiekriav aneicri yevojievos Kal — eTTidaxrei els ti, &> Upcorayopa, Kai nepl tov ; also Polit. 265 e : 6 7to\itik6s ap enijxeXeiav e\ elv v ovtcov nepl to p.r) ov e(TTai ; which, however, is rather par- allel to the next dnopia. 1 1. Kai tovto rjplv ttov (pavepov\ " This also is surely plain to us." Kal refers to tout-o ye 8r]\ov above. to t\ tovto pTjp-aJ This word " something." pr)p.a seems to be thrown in by an after- thought, for the sake of ex- plicitness ; so giving ri the 20I2TH2. 85 p. 237. tovto prjfia iir ovtl Xeyopav e/caVrore" povov yap being— noi » \ .. / cf \ \> / , \ of BO] avro Xeyeiv, wairep yvp,vov kcli airi]pr)p(op.evov utto thing. F01 dSv tcov ovtcov airavTwv, aovvarov. 77 yap ; • GEAI. 'ASvvarov. HE. 3^/)a 7-f;<5e aKOirwv ^v/JL(f)7js &>? dvdyKrj tov 5 rt XeyovTa ev ye tl XeyeLv ; GEAI. OiW *•* ^E- 'E^o? ya/5 6\; ro ye tl (fyrjaeLS 1 arjpelov eivai, to 8e Tive 8volv, to 8e Tives iroXXwv. GEAI. Ilcoy yap ov ; 10 e aE. Toy 5e 5;; //r; ri XeyovTa avayKaiOTarov, 639 eoiK€, iravTCLTTacri p.r)8ev XeyeLv. GEAI. AvayKaioTaTOV p.ev ovv. HE. , Ap ovv ov8e tovto crvyytopryreov, to tov tol- ovtov Xeyeiv pkv fTif, Xeyeiv pkvTOi pr)8ev, «AA' oi>8e 15 Xeyeiv (fiaTeov, bs y av eiri^eipfi p.rj ov (pfleyyeaOai ; implies being. Bat •• aot-Bome ' is '• none,* 1 and to s|K-ak none is not to GEAI. Te'Aoy yovv av diropias 6 Adyoy e^ot. There fol- lows a force of an adjective, as in such expressions as 17 AiVoAi? avrrj ywT]. Heindorf conjectures rh pfjfia, which appears in two MSS. Stallbaurn renders prjpa eV ovri " as a predicate of being." 15. Xeyeiv [pev] frif] Tl, which appears in all the MSS., is not wanted, and, if genuine, is used in common parlance (cf. Slipr. 236 e, Xeyeiv pev arret) without reference to the pre- ceding argument, just as the ordinary sense of eivai, 8oKe1v, etc., is often found within a few lines of the technical use of the same words, pev, which the Bodleian (not however Vat. A.) omits, is probably right, though the omission may be defended from Theset. 160 b : alaBavopevov yap, pr]8ev6s 8e alaBavopevov. lb. : yXvKv yap, pr]8ev\ 8e y'KvKv. pr]8ev] I. e. pr]8e ev. The argument from pfj rolvw may be thus resumed. — What is denoted by pfj ov 1 No exist- ing thing: and therefore not something : for every " some- thing" exists : therefore, 6 pr) ov Xeywv ov n Xe'yet. But every something is some one thing : therefore, 6 ptj re Xe- yav oi8ev Xe'yet. But (6 ou8ev Xeyav) he who says nothing, does not say at all : there- fore 6 p.x) ov Xeycov oi8e Xe'yet. Compare Parm. 144 c, Thewt. 189 e. 17. TeXo? yovv av dnopias 6 80 nAATONOS graver dif- ficulty. If Not-Being is ii,.t pra- cticable, neither is aught pre- dicable of the non- existent. And yet Not-Being cannot be utteivd or even thought, without implying predicates, such as unity or plurality, which im- ply num- ber, which implies being. SE. Mi]7rco p.ey ehrr}? eri yap, co paKapie, eaTi, p. 238 K.a\ ravra ye twv airopiwv rj fieylaTT) koll irptoTT]. 7T€pl yap avrr)v avrov tt\v dp~)Q~\v ovaa TvyyaveL. 0EAI. rico? (jyfjs ; Xeye K.a\ pLrjbev diroKVYjar)?. 5 hhE. Tw fX€V OVTL 7TOV TTpOdyivOLT O.V TL T(OV ovtwv erepov. GEAI. II w? yap ov ; SE. Mrj ovtl 8e tl tcou ovTwv dpa irpoay'tyve- crOaL (jyrjcrofxev SvvaTov elvaL ; o GEAI. Kat Trco^ ; £?E. 'Apidpov 8r/ tov ^vpiravTa twv ovtcov TL0epLev. GEAI. Ei ne'p ye /ecu aAAo tl OeTeov w? ov. b 3*E. Mr) tolvvv fir]S eiTLyeLpcopLev apL0p.ov /jLrjTe ttXyjOos p-?)Te to ev 7rpo$ to pa] bv irpoo~(pepeLV. Xdyos ex 01 ] ° ~koyos, SC. to prj ov eiuai, as appears from avrov (sc. tov \6yov) below. " The saying must surely be thus reduced to the last stage of difficulty." I. Mtjttco pey einr}s\ There is a tragic tone in the expres- sion. Cf. Legg. 1, 638 a : 2> apiare, prj \eye ravra. S naKapie] "My simple friend !" Cf. Crat. 414c: & paKapie, ovk oiad' on K.r.X. ecrri] Sc. dnopia, to be sup- plied from dnopiav below. 3. nep\ airrju avrov rrp> dpyi]v\ One which affects the very be- ginning of the whole matter, i. e. enters into the substance of the term itself, pr\ ov. Cf. SUpr. 233 d : rrjv dpxrjv — tov \e\6(vros — dyvoe'is. The diffi- culty is this : the word pr/ op or jitJ7 ovra cannot be uttered or thought without a contra- diction : for JU17 ov has num- ber, being singular, and prj ovra has also number, being plural : and number is exist- ence : therefore, in uttering or thinking the word prj bv or p-r] 6vra we attach existence to non-existence. In the for- mer dnopla it was shewn that non-existence could not be an attribute. Here it is denied that non-existence can be the subject of any attribute : and yet the word cannot be ut- tered without implying attri- butes, such as unity or plu- rality. Cf. Parm. 164 b, quoted above, note on p. 84, 1. 8. 12. El' irep ye I2TH2. 87 >. 238. 0EAI. Ovkovv av bpOm ye, &>? eoiKev, e7ri\€L- poipLev, coy (f)i]aiv Aoyoy. SE. II go? ovv av i) Sid tov CTTopaTO? (jyQey^aiT dv TL9 r) kcu rfj Siavola to Traparrav Xafioi ra prj bvTa 7] to p.7] bv \c0p\9 dpi6\x.ov ; 5 0EAI. Aeye, irrj ; HE. M?) cWa yue^ iireiftav XeycopLtv, dpa ov 7rXrj- c 009 iin)(eLpovfxev dpi6p.ov •KpoarTiQevai ; 0EAI. Tifirji;; HE. Mt; 6f oV, a/?a ou ro et> av ; 10 0EAI. ^a(j)eaTaTa ye. HE. Kai /u?)i> oi>Ve SiKaiov ye out bpObv (pap.ev bv eirixeipelv pcrj bvn ivpoaappoTTeiv. GEAI. Aeyeis- dXrjOeaTaTa. HE. Hvvvoels ouz> co? oure <])0e'y£ao-0ai hvvaTov 15 Not-Being > /> ~ v>»- >/ <> /1- v v A >^ is therefore opucos ovt enreiv ovTe biavorjuiivai to par) ov avTO unutter- /!> > / >.. ^> v j (j, / /• v v v able and KaU avTO, aXX eaTiv aoiavoqTOv re /cat apprjTOV Kai inconceiv- v 1 /1 \ v» able. acptreyKTOv Kai aXoyov ; 0EAI. YlavTairacri p.ev ovv. el £?E. 'A/)' ouf ey^evadparjv apTi Xeycov tyjv peyi- 20 But the j , , , „ , greatest ar^f airopiav epeiv avTov Trepi ; paradox is 0EAI. Tt be ; eri pLel^co tlvol Xeyetv aXXrjv hind. expfiev ; HE. Tt oV, d> OavpLaaie ; ou/c evvoels avTOi? toIs 10. /xjj ov fie] Sc. eVetSai/ Xe- to speak of using it as a predi- ycofiev. cate or subject. 15. Svwoei?] "Do you gather 17. ddiavorjTov k.t.X.] " TJn- or collect" (as the sum of the thinkable, unspeakable, unut- preceding remarks). terable, and indescribable." 16. 6p6ms\ Cf. 6p86v supr. 20. r Ap ovv] " Was I then That it can be uttered appears wrong in saying just now that from our using the expression. I would tell you the greatest Cf. supr. 237 b : to fxr)8aix£>s ov difficulty 1 " I. e. A greater is ToXfiatpfv nov (pBe'yy(0~6ai. behind. avro naO* a\)To\ T. e. Not 24. Ti 6V, u> 6avpao-ie~\ I. e. 88 nAATONOS As Not- Being cannot be asserted or receive at- tributes, so neither can Not-Being lie denied. For in say- ing " it is unspeak- able," &c, we attri- bute Being to it, and also unity: which this very word "it" im- plies. XeyOelarLV otl /cat tov eXey^ovTa ety airoplav kolOl- p. 238. cm;o"t to fit] bv ovtcos cotrre, ottotolv civto eTriyeipf) tls eAe'yxetv, evavTia avrhv avTco irep\ emelvo dvay- Ka^eaQai Xeyeiv ; 5 GEAI. Ylco? v c to per] bv Selv fieTe^eiv, apTi tc /cat vvv ovtco? ev avTo elprjKa' to /it?) bv yap (f)r]pLi. Ijvviei? tol ; 10 GEAI. Nat. HE. Kat firjv at) /cat a/JUKpov epurpoaOev a(fi6ey- ktov T6 avTo /cat ap'pyrrov /cat aXoyov e(fiy]v elvai. ^vveirei ; GEAI. £?lW7T0/xat 7TCOS. *5 3?E. Ovkovv to ye eivai Trpoo~aTtTeiv ireipcdpLevos evavTia tols TTpoaOev eXeyov ; " I am surprised that you do not see." (24.) avTois rots XexOelaiv] Either the dative is governed by ev in iwoels, " Do you not see that this is implied even in what has been said?" cf. supr. 223 C, ev rot? TrpooSev elprjpevois cpdvTaapa 7rapex eTaL /c.r.X. j or (Heind. Stallb.) avTols toIs Xe- xOelaiv = Kai en to>v \i\6ivrav. Cf. Xen. Cyrop. 8, 1, 37 : rois npoetprfpevois 8fj\ov. I . Kai tov e\eyxovTa\ " Not- Being reduces its opponent, equally with its supporter, to the same straits," i. e. can neither be asserted nor denied. In the spirit of the Parmenides, Plato here points out that Not-Being neither is nor is not. Compare also Theretetus, 183 a, b. This ar- gument has an important bear- ing on the whole dialogue. The impossibility of criticising Not-Being when conceived ab- solutely leads to the necessity of modifying the conception of Negation. 3. inelvo] This pronoun is used for the sake of distinct- ness to prevent the further repetition of avros with refer- ence to a different subject. 8. apri] Supr. els anopiav ko.6- icrTrjO'i to fir) ov. vvv ovtois] Viz. in the pre- vious clause, to fir) ov 8eiv pere- X eiv. 9. gwiets tol ;] " You surely understand V Cf. Theeet. 155c: enei yap ttov, 2> 0. rt £2Yb, whence Stallb. ti. Cf. Men. 76 d : gvves toi Xe'yco (Pind.) 15. to ye elvai] This refers, 20s eVi &eAe- yopqv ; GEAI. No/. HE. Kat /x?)^ akoyov re Aeycoi' /cat appi]TOu /cats acfyOeyKTOf coy ye 7rpoy ef rot' Aoyoy i7roLov/j.rji>. 0EAI. rico? 5' ou; HE. Oa/xeV 6V ye Se?/^, ewre/o 6p6m ti? Ae'^et, /^re cos* ev p.r)re coy 7roAA« Siopl^eiv avro, [irjSe to Trapdirav clvto kolXuv' evbs yap e'ldec kol koto, two- io tt)v av rrjv irpoaprjaiv irpoaayopevoiTO. not, as Stallbaum says, to the preceding predicates generally, but to the word elvat in the previous sentence and eo-Tiv supra. (l6.) ivavr'ia to'ls Tvp6(r6ev\ Supr. 238 a : Mr) ovti &<=' rt to>v bvrav dpa npocryLyfeadai (ptjcropev dvvarov elvai \ Kal nibs ' } 2. tovto irpov — neipadr/Tij For a slightly different touch of ironical playfulness, (turning on the easiness and not, as here, on the difficulty of the question asked,) cf. Phileb. 65 b: fi\e\j/as els Tpia, vovv Ka\ dXrjdeiav Kai T]8ovr]v, noXvv emo-ftcM xpovov, anoKpivai aavTa k.t.X. 9. p'/re ovcriav — avrov] Com- 20$I2TH2. 91 p- 239 firjTe to ev fjLrjre irXrjQos aptOpLOv TrpoaTiOeh rw /xy ovtl, Kara to 6p6ov ^OeyfacrOai tl 7repl avTov. 0EAI. rioAA?) \xlvr av p.e koli aToiros e^pi irpo- Ovfila tyjs €7nxeipr)ae(o^, el ae Totavfr opcov iraayovTa ai)TO$ eTnyeipoLrjv. 5 HE. 'AAA' el 8oKel, ae /lev Kal ep.e yaipeiv ecoptev' ems 5' av tlvi 8vvap.eva> 8pav tout evTvyxavcoptev, pL^XP L T0VT0V XeycopLev co? iravros pLaWov iravovp- ycos els anropov 6 ao8e (pde'yyecrdai 8e1 ovBeV el 8e to ev eitelvo Kal pr] tiXko vnoKeiTat, pr) elvai, kol tov exeivov Ka\ SXKcoP ttoWwv avayKT) avTci peTe'ivai. 2. KaTa to 6p66v\ Cf. Thepet. 1 7 1 C : a8rjkov el kol ■napaQeo- fiev to 6p66v. Several MSS. have Kara tov dpdov \6yov. 3. 7rpo6vpia tt)S eTTixeipr]0-eas] Lit. " forwardness in attempt- ing :" gen. of respect. Cf. Phaedo 99 b : noXXrj av Ka\ pa- Kpa padvpia etr) tov Xoyov. 8. TravTos pdXkov Ka.Ta8e8vK.ev] " lias with unparalleled cunning hid himself in a very trouble- some cover." Cf. Rep. 4, 432 C : 8vo~(3aTos ye tis 6 tottos (pai- verai Kal enlo-KLos' eo-ri yovv ctko- reivos Kal 8vo-8upevvr]Tos. aX\a yap opas foeov. II. Toiyapovv — drroKpivelTai] " Therefore when we call his art phantastic, by this method he will easily grapple with us and disarm us, asking, when we call him an image-maker, what we mean by an image generally. We must consider, then, Thesetetus, what answer can be given to this question of our sinewy foe." (pavTao-TiKrjv Tex vr l v ] The main argument is here resumed from p. 236 c. 12. eK TavTr/g ttjs ^pei'as] "A- vailing himself of this line of argument." Viz. : that just indicated, by which appearance is shewn to rest on Not-Being : and Not-Being is proved to be inconceivable. eK here ex- presses the means. 13. dvTikapQavopevos — Xo'yovs] " He will grapple with us and retort our argument upon us, as it were binding our hands behind our backs." The implied metaphor in dvTi\ap(3dvecrdai — used frequently of an objector's arguments — suggests the bolder image taken from the common expression dnoo-Tpe^ai tlvos tos try to in- dent '.III.; rlll'lil i- r.\ - If this be impossible, the Sophist must be allowed to have hid himself in a very " dark tower." For if ac- cused of " phantas- tic" or of image- N 2, 92 IIAATQNOS making, be will aalt " What i. .■in image?" And if wc answer " a reflection, mould, or picture," lie will make as if he were blind, and ask for a definition that does not need the help of visible examples. arpexf/ei tov? Xoyovs, orav elScoXonoLoi' avTov kolXco- p. 239. fitv, dvtpcoTtov t'l 7iOT€ to irapcarav etocoXov Xeyo/xeu. CTKoirelu ow, w Qealryre, XP r h Ti TL $ TC P veavia. irpos to Ipontopievov caroKpivfiTai. 5 GEAI. ArjXov otl (jyrjaopiev to. T€ Iv Toh vdaai Kou KotTOTTTpoL? e'ldcoXa, en Kou Ta yeypa\xp.lva /cat TO. T€TV7rco/iei'a kou raAAa, baa ttov toluvtu Igtiv erepa ; SE. <&avep6?, co Gecc/r^re, el ao(pio-Tr)i> ov)( eco- e 10 pOLKCO?. GEAI. Tt 5tJ ; iH'E. Aotjet aoi p.veii> 77 iravTcmacTiv ovk e\eiv 6fx/j.aTa. GEAI. riw; 15 SE. Tr]V CLTTOKpiGlV OTCLV OVTC09 OLVTCp 8iOCpS, lav ev KaT07TTpoi9 r) TrXaafiacTL Xeyrj? ti, KciTayeXacreTai aov tcou Xoycov, otclv los (3Xe7rouTi Xeyrj? clvtco, TTpQCFTTOlOVlieVOS 0VT6 KCCTOTTTpa OVT6 vScLTa yiyVLO- xelpas. Cf. Legg. i , 6 2 6 e : naXiv tov \6yov dvaa-Tfje\JAcoij,ev. I. e. " Let us make the converse statement." Theast. 191 c : iravTa fierao~Tpe(povTa Xoyov j3a- (Tavi{eiv. tovs Xoyovs is brought in ivapa irpoo-doKiav at the end of the sentence. Compare the metaphorical use of o-vp.Trohi£eiv and Trap air ohi^eiv. I . orav el8a>\oTTOi6v\ For the double sentence (el — orav), cf. The?et. 199 b : orav — ore. So also immediately below, where orav is resumed by iav. 3. ra) veavia] Not necessarily = homo protervus vel insolens (Ast.). " This, fine fellow." " The young man," in a playful sense. Cf. Rep. 8, 549 b : Kal earn jxev — tolovtos tis o TijioKpa- tikos veavia':. Phsedr. 257 d : TeXolov y, o) veavia, to doyp,a Xeyeis. Eur. Ale. 698 : fj tov koXov o~ov rrpovdavev veaviov. 12. Ao£ei 0-01 p.veiv] " He will seem as one who has his eyes shut." 8oKe1v is used here to express an appearance volun- tarily assumed. For p,ieiv, cf. Theset. 163 e : fj Ka\ p.vo-as. 1 6. fj TrXdo-p.ao-t] Referring to to. yeypafj.jj.eva Kal to. TeTVTra>jj.eva supra. For iav resuming orav, which was doubted by Heindorf, cf. Rep. 4, 445 a, b ; lb. 7, 529 b, c — where there is similar va- riation in resuming with iav. 2CXM2TH2. 93 I 24O. (JKHV OVT€ TO TTapaiTaV O^TLV, TO 8' 6/C TO)V XoyoOV ipoiTrjorei ere fiovov. 0EAI. Uohu; HE. To 81a iravrwv tovtcov, a noXXa elirwv rjijloocras ein irpoaeLireiv ovopaTi, (^ey^d/.teuos 1 el- 5 SooXov eVrt iracriv u>s ev ov. Xeye ovv kou ol/jlvvov, IxrjSev vnoxcopcou, tov av8pa. GEAI. T/ SrjTct, (6 ijeve, e'lScoAov av (pai/neu eivat TrXrjV ye to irpos tolXtjOlvov d(j)cofxoicofx€i>oi> erepou What is that one nature, lie will ask, in right of which these various ob- jects have a common name ? Another like thing fashioned I . to 8" ex rmv \6yf lopdkoyeis. t&v Xo'ycoj/] The word is here used in the more restricted sense of " abstract reasoning." 4. to $ia TravTOiV tovtcov] " That which interpenetrates all these." Cf. infr. 253 d : fxlav I8eav 8ia ttoXXcov, evbs e/ca- o-rou Keipevov ^copi's, vavTr] 8ia- Terapevrjv. 5. pa>v tov civSpa, compares Phileb. 43 a : vneKCTTrjvai tov \6yov eViCpepo'yue- vov tovtov (3ov\opai. But the parallel is impaired by the participle enKpepopevov. 9. npos TaXrjdivov « koll paXa. HE. T7 <5e 8r) ; ttjv Te^vr/v avTOv Tiva d(popi- aavTes r)puv amois avpt(f)covelv oiol re eaop.e6a ; GEAI. Ilfj Kal TO TToloV TL (f)o(3ovp€V09 OVTO) Xeyeis ; 1 1 i- i. all} an unreal it v, though nut really anything. Thus tlie Sophist has forced us to ad- mit that that which is not, is. How then shall we 15 consis- For nas, cf. infr. : opoXoyelv eivai nms, rj ttcos eivai ra fj.rj8ajj.rj ovra, eivai irons ra iir) ovra. i. Ovkow'] Stallbaum reads ovkovv, with nine MSS., for the vulg. ovk ov. But the answer of Theretetus seems to require the negative ovkovv. ye, (prjs] Bodl. All, y eS ev tovtois 8ia7re7roiKi/\rai. Y. opas yovv on] The Bodl. MS. gives these words only in the margin, where Gaisford read opas ovv, but the y, though nearly lost, may be traced, where the words were blotted while the ink was still wet, on the opposite leaf. The Stranger recals Thesetetus from merely wondering at the result to ob- serve the point of the diffi- culty. 8. 8ia Trjs eTraWd^ecos rai/Trjs] " Through this reciprocation of opposites." TToXvKecpaXov] I. e. " whom we have already slain in so many shapes." There is of course an allusion to the hydra. Cf. Euthyd. 297 c : rg — v8pa, aocpiarpia oiiarj, Kal 8id tj)v cro- (piav avie'iarj, el piav Ke(paXr)v tov \6yov tis anorepoi, noWas dvrl rrjs pids. 9. r)vayKaKev] So Bodl., with the nine MSS. mentioned by Bekker. ^ulg. r)vdyKa ; 0EAI. 'AvdyKrj. HE. Ylorepov fir) elvat rd fir) ovra 8o^d^ovaav, rj was eivai rd firfiajicos ovra ; 0EAI. "Rival 7TC09 rd fir) ovra 8el ye, elirep \j/ev- 1 5 erera'i wore, ris tl Ka\ Kara (3pa)(y. HE. Tl 8'; ov K.a\ fi7]8afJLCos elvaL rd rcavTois ovra 8o^d^eraL ; 0EAI. No/. HE. Kat tovto 8rj \jsev8o9 ; ™ 0EAI. Kai tovto. HE. Kai \6yos, olfiat, \lsev8r)s ovrco Kara ravrd [ra,VTa\ vofiio~di]creTat rd re ovra Xeyu>v fir] elvat ko.\ rd fir] ovra elvat. 0EAI. Has yap av aAAeos tolovtos yevotro ; 6. ravavria to'is ovai] These- tetus is again made to assert the view of Not-Being as the opposite of Being, which is pre- sently modified. See below, 258 e : Mrj Toivvv fj/jias etirrj tis on TOU- fdl'TlOl' TOV OVTOS TO /JLT) OV UTTO(f)al- vofxevoi To\fxoofj.iv \eyeiv w? 'io-riv. 14. Set ye] Sc. Aeyeii/ avrrjv 8o£d(eiv. 19, 20, 21. Kai — Kai — KaY] = " Also." 21. Kara ravra [tovto] ] Tavra is omitted in nine MSS. 24. SKkcos] Most of the MSS. give aWos ; which if received would require 6 rd re ovra \eyav. The reading of the editions is preferable, as in- volving a slighter change. 2os" yap ov pLavOavoLiev, otl rdvavria (Prjo-et. Xeyeiv rj/xas T0I9 vvv 8rj, \j/evSr} ToXLirjaavTa? elirelv d>s eariv ev bo^ais re koI Kara Xoyov? ; rw yap lit) ovti to ov TrpoaaTrreLv r]fxas iroXXaxis dvay- h KatJEadai, SLOLioXoyrjo-a/ie'vov? vvv 8rj irov tovto elvai ic TravToov dSwaTGOTarov. HE. 'OpOce? d7T€Livr)p.6vevaas, dXX' wpa drj (3ov- XeveaOai t'l \pi) 8pav rod o-o(J)icttov irepi" ra? ydp dvTiXrjxf/eL? Kal d7ropla?, eav avrbv diepevvcofiev ev rfj II.: will turn upon 11 1 and a I. what has 1 to nth i- the wi r>l •Not- Being.' 2. fj Tis firixavri'] He adopts the tone of the Sophist. 4. 7rpo$ia>p.oXoyripevci\ " When it has been previously granted (supr. 238 d) that the very terms of the admissions which have just been made are un- utterable," &c. Cf. Tim. 78 a: Trpobioixukoyrjvcmevoi. Bodl. All, Tvpoa8cop.oXnyr)p.eva : whence C F. Hermann gives npos dicapo- \oyqp,iva. But this reading is without point. ra irpb tovtcov 6poXoyr]6e'v- ra] Heindorf observes that Plato uses this periphrasis to avoid the repetition of pfj ov. The words refer to the discus- sion (of the nature of a likeness) which precedes the mention of doga and Xoyos, and which bris- tles with the forbidden expres- sions. P. 2 40 b. Compare Phil eb. 50 C : ra vvv ttoKKclkis Xeyopeva. 5. a *Xe'yei*] Bekker, judg- ing from Gaisford's silence, re- ports \eyei as the Bodleian reading. Unfortunately, this MS. agrees with all the rest except Par. P. in giving Xeyeis. But the context leaves no room for doubting that Xeyei is right. The Stranger has been speak- ing in the Sophist's person. See (prjarei in the next line, and compare the defence of Pro- tagoras in Theast. 166. For pav6dvopev in the 1st pers. plur., cf. supr. 223 e, and note, also Phileb. 51 d: dA\' dpa pavBd- vo/j.ev, r] ttcos ] IIP. Tveipoipaa. pev, 6) Scoxpares. 8. Kara \6yovs] This use of Kara confirms the correction Kara biKao-rr)pia in Thefefc. 201 d. 13. tL xpn SpH Cf. Legg. 6j 777 c • 8iaTTopT](Tfie tl \pi] Spav we pi anavTcov to>v toiovtcov. 14. dvTiXfyeis] "Handles for objection." Lit. " Occasions for laying hold," as in wrest- ling. Cf. supr. 239 d. 98 IIAATQNQ2 And this is only the beginning of diffi- culties. Must we, then, give up in despair ? tcov \j/evSuvpyu>v kou yoi'-jTUiV reyyr\ TtQevTes. bpos cos' eviropoi kou iroXXal. 0EAI. Rat ptdXa. HE. yiunpov fxepo? toivvv avrcov SieXi]Xv0ap.ev, 5 ovcrcov coy ejro? eiireiv tmepavrow. 0EAI. ABvvarov yap [av], a>? eotKev, [en;] rov crofpurTrjv eXeiv, el ravra ovtcds e\ei. 3?E. TV ovv ; a.7roaTrja6pe0a vvv pLaXOaKiadevre^ ; GEAI. Ovkovv eycoye (f)T]pLi Sell/, el /cat /cara loapuKpov olol t eirLXafieaOai ny rdvSpo? eapev. HE. r/ E^et? olw avyyvco/xyv /cat KaOdirep vvv etVe? dyairrjcreLS, edv t?t\ kou Kara. (ipa^y irapaaTraawpeOa ovrois uryypov Xoyov ; p. 241. 6. 'aSiWtov yap] The Bod- leian has Tap (sic), which sug- gests the possibility of a read- ing rap' ( = rot cipa). But yap is probably right. Cf. Thetet. 190 e : ovre yap ravrrj ovre Kara. Ta itpdrepa (paiverai -^rev^ris iv Tjpuv ovcra bo^a. Gorg. 454 d: LrjXov yap av ort ov rairov ia-Tiv. And iEsch. Ag. 218 : Havaavepiov yap dvcrlas irap6eviov 0' alparos opyfj itepiopyas eitiBv- p.fiv dep,is. Eur. Med. 573. [av] — [e'irf] ] The former word is found in TACH, and by a later hand in 2B, the latter in every MS. except S. Possibly 'Aftvvarov yap (or rap'), a>s eoiK, av eirj may be the true reading. 11. Kadditep vvv elite?] viz. in saying el Ka\ Kara. crpiKpov k. t, A. 12. edv 7777 Ka\] Ka\ is pro- bably to be taken intensively with Kara j3paxv ; cf. supr. 240 e : elite p ■fyevo-eTal itore rls ti Kiii Kara ftpaxv. " If we should flinch a little from the grasp of such a sturdy ar- gument." The metaphor from wrestling is continued through- out. Cf. Phileb. 41 b: itpoiri- (TTuipeda S?) Kadditep d8\r]Ta\ itpos tovtov av t6v Xoyov. itapao-itaacop.e6a] Lit. " pull ourselves aside, draw aside ;" i. e. release ourselves from the contest. Cf. Soph. El. 732 : e£a> itapacrna (sc. tovs iititovs) KavaKwxevei. The middle voice is here directly reflexive, not as in Dem. Olynth. 1, 10 : p.r] itapao-itdo-rjTai ti tcov oXcov itpay- pdrcov. Compare the use of ditoo-rtdo-6ai in Xen. Anab. 1, 5. § 2 : itoXv yap diteaitdro (pevyovaa. Those, however, who prefer the latter meaning here (read- ing edv ttr] ti, with Badh. conj.), may compare Theset. 196 d : ti el eitixeiprjo'aip.ev avaio~xyvTelv ; For the personification, cf. ib. 148c: el — roil aKp.d£ovros Ka\ raxio-rov r)TTr)8r)s, 20I2TH2. 99 ). 241. GEAI. II coy yap 06% c'ijco \ d 3*E. To8e to'lvvv en p,aXXov irapaiTovpai ae. GEAI. To ttolou ; aE. Mt; yue chcw irarpaKoiav vnoXafir)? ylyvtaOai Tiva. GEAI. T/A75 EE. Toy roO iroLTpos Ylappevldov Xoyov avayKalov rjp.lv , which C. F. Hermann accordingly rejects, with the remaining words, retaining only cpaiverat. " Languidum additamentum totum circumscripsi." But it may be retoi-ted that, especi- ally considering the formal style of the dialogue, (paiverai alone in this place is abrupt O LofC. and bare. Cf. also Siupaxdpevoi, infr. 256 d. 13. ku\] To be taken with rv(f)Xcp : the words to \ey6uevov br) rouro being thrust in between. Cf. SUpr. 2l8 a, Kal, Kaddnep eiire SaiKpdrrjs, Tvdcri k. e. and note. See also Rep. 5, 465 d : ArjXov, e(prj, Kal rv(j)\a. 14. eXeyx6evTa>v] The Bodl., with AnBi, has pijre \ex6evrap, which is Weak ; eXeyxdevrtov is right. " Unless this refutation and this admission is secured." I. e. unless the saying of Parmenides is refuted and the existence of the non-ex- istent admitted. Cf. infr. 242 b : rov eXeyvov rovrov Kal rr)v d7r68eigiv. In Theaet. 188 d sqq., it is shewn to be impossible to think what is not, because all thought must have a real object. As Mr. Grote remarks, this and other negative arguments of the 100 nAATGNOS I Ulicrwi ie an art i f and, in- deed, all imitation, is Lncon- ceh able. p. 241, e o/JLoXoyijOevrcov cr^oXfj irore ns 616s re ear at irep\ Xoycov \J/ev8a>v Xeycov ?) 86{jr)v, elre el8a>Xa)v elre cikovcov elre fjaptr] /iareov elre (Ijavraaparcov, avrcov, rj kgu ire pi reyvcov rcov oaai 7repi ravra eicri, fxr] Kara- tyeXaaros elvat ra. evavrla avayKatpfievos avrco Xe'yeiv. 9EAI. 'AXirfe'arara. SE. Aia ravra fxevrot roXprjreov ewirldeadai rap. 242 irarpiKw Xoyco vvv, r\ to rrapairav iareov, el rovro n? lotipyet 8pav okvos. 0EAI. 'AAA' rjiias rovro ye prj8ev prjSapfj e'lp^r). £?E. Tplrov ro'ivvv en ere a/xiKpov ri TTapairr\- ao/JLai. 0EAI. Aeye fiovov. 15 HE. Wirrov 7rov vvv Srj Xeycov w? rrpos rov irep\ ravr e'Xeyxpv ael re a7reipr)Kco? iyco rvy^ava) Kal 8r) Kal ra vvv. 0EAI. EtTrey. Thesetetus are not directly re- futed in the Sophistes. It is rather the negative mode of arguing generally which is cri- ticized. 3. avrav, r) Kal ire pi Te)(vcov] " themselves, or the arts which relate to these." avribv refers to all the preceding genitives. Cf. Rep. 3, 398 a : ei rjplv depi- koito els rr)v ivokiv avros re Kal ra Tioirjpara (3ov\6pevos eViSei- ijacrdai.. The other rendering, according to which avrmv refers to (pavTaa-fidrcov alone as the very subject-matter of the Sophist's art, is not so good. 8. Ata ravra pevroi] " Ob- vious as this truth is, it com- pels us — " ra> TrarpiKU) \6y(o\ \6yos is personified, as in rod pao-i'KiKov \6yov supr. 235 C, and narptKos has the same force as in narpt- kos (f)iXos — " The theory which is invested with the sacred- ness of our father's autho- rity." 9 . to rrapdivav iareov ] to Trapdirav is probably adver- bial, and the object of iareov must be supplied, e. g. rov \6yov — " We must give up en- tirely." 1 1 . rovro -ye] Sc. &crre to napdnav iav. Cf. Polit. 268 d : rovro ro'ivvv — rjp.lv Troir)reov, el pr) peXXopev inl ra reXei Karaio-)(£>vai rov \6yov. N. 2. 'AXAa pr)v ovdapcos rovro ye bpao-reov. 2CXM2TH2. 101 ). 242. aE. <&ofiovpai Si) to, elpr/peva, pi) ttotc Sia Tama aot paviKOs eivai Sotjco irapa iroSa peTaftaXcov e'pav- 1) tov avoa kcu Karen. o~i)v yap Si) X a P lv £^YX eiu T0V \oyov 67ri8r)(Top€0a, lavirep eXeyxcopev. 0EAI. '0? tolvvv epoiye pr/Sapf) So^cov prjSlvS 7rXr)ppeXeii>, av eirt tov eAeyxov tovtov ko.1 tt)v cmo- Sei^LV lr)9, flappwv Wi tovtov ye eW/ca. £7E. €/0€ Si) ; Tiva apyj)v ti? av ap^aiTO irapa- KLvSvvevTLKOv Xoyov ; Sokcd pev yap ti)vS\ 00 7rai, tt)V bSov avayKatoranqv i)plv dvai TpeirecrOai. IC 0EAI. Uolav Si) ; SE. Ta SoKovvTa vvv evapyco? tX eiv €7rta-/ce^a- c aflat irpwTOV, pi) irr) Terapaypevoi pev copev 7repl With this view it will be necessary to exam i ue some idi a which are thought to be clear, but may prove to be confused. 1. $o/3ovpai] "I tremble, then, to think of what I have said, lest you should pronounce me wild." For dei re S17 inter- posed, cf. Rep. 2, 367 e: Kcu e'yco dKovcras, del pev drj rrjv (ftvcriv tov TXavKcovos ko.1 tov \beipdvTov rjydprjv, arap ovv kcu Tore ndvv ye rjadrjv : and for the meaning, compare supr. 242b: ml yap nakai Kai rd vvv rjTTTjpevov civ evpot. Theset. 187 c. 2. irapa 7rd8a] "At the first step ;" " at each step ;" "at every other step." The expression is used of persons in motion, as nap ttoSI, in Pindar, of persons at rest. Thus Soph. Phil. 838 : ttoXv napa noda Kpdros dpvvrai. In the present passage wapa seems to have the additional meaning of alternation, as in Trap' rjpepav. pera^aXav] The tense cor- responds to that of dogco, otherwise peTa/SdWccv would have seemed more natural, especially with uvea ku\ Kara. Cf. Phsed. 96 b: iroWdicis epav- tov civco Kara peTeftaWov. But in the present case only one change " to and fro " is spoken of. 3. arjv ydp 817 x<*P LV ] Com- pare the language of Socrates in the fifth book of the Re- public, before advancing his theory of communism, 450 e. See also ib. 473 c. Such ex- pressions of reluctance perhaps receive some light from the passages in the Epistles, if genuine, where it is said that the philosopher will not choose to fix his thought in writing. I O. avayKaiordrrjv — Tpe7Tecr6ai\ For the inf. after dvay KXcivla, 8okov(Tiv ol ndXai vopoderovvres yeyovtvai ku\ em crpiKpbv rmv av6pumiva>v @Xe- 7rovres re xai Stavoovp.evot vop,o- Serelv. " I think that Parmenides, and all who have hitherto arisen to determine the ulti- mate number and nature of existences, have shewn in then- conversation with us a sort of easy, good-humoured compo- sure." " In what way ?" " They seem to me to treat us like children, and to tell us stories, each one for himself; one relating that there are Beings three, which sometimes maintain a desultory warfare, but sometimes they make peace again, and marry, and bring forth children and rear them ; another speaks of Two, as Moist and Dry, or Hot and Cold, which he brings together and consorts in marriage. But the tribe of the Eleatics from our quarter, beginning with Xeno- phanes, or even earlier, are the authors of a different tale, and fable that what we call ' all things' are One Being. Then certain Muses of Ionia, and others of later birth in Sicily, in taking up the parable have seen that it is safer to combine both histories and to say that Being is Many and also One, held together by hate and love. For, say the Muses of firmer 2Q*I2TH2. 103 p. 242. 6ai kcu iras oari? Trwirore hri npicrw wp/njae tov to. bvra dioplaaaOai iroaa re kcu iroia lemv. 0EAI. Urj; SE. Mv06i> Tuva (lkolv. Rep. 8, 545 e : cos irpbs ivaibas fjpds. Illfr. 254 e : ov TVfpX rpicov cos OVTCOV UVTCOV. 6 pev cos tp'ia — eKbibcoaiv] The few remaining fragments of the earliest philosophy do not enable us to say what thinkers are thus briefly indi- cated : probably some belong- ing to the earlier Ionic school. The metaphorical language seems to point to a pe- riod when philosophy still re- tained a considerable tinge of others who have 1 oughl i" define the Dumber and nature of exist- ence, have Dot been careful t" 104 IIAATQNOS explain their meaning, but after throwing out that Being is three or two or one, or one and many, hot and cold, at peace or war, or that it is first united 8e dWijkoi? ivioTt olvtlov olttol 7rrj, Tore 8e koll (j)ika p. 242. yiyvoptva ydpovs re kou tokov? koll Tpo(f)d? tcov d dKyovoiV 7rape)(€Tai' 8uo 8e (repos elvrcou, vypov koll ^~lpov ?) Oepphv koll ^/vxpof, cfvvoikl^l re avrd koll $6k818co(TI. to 8e Trap rjp.(ov 'EAeari/co^ eOvo?, oltto A€VO(J)UVOV? T€ KOLL €TL TTpOtjQt-V dpj-dfltVOV, £09 evos ovtos tusv irdvTcov KaXovpevoiv ovrco 8i€^ep)(€Tai T0I9 fJivOoi?. 'IaSe? 8e kou 2i«:eAa/ rives varepov cosmogonical mythology. Thus Pherecydes might be said to have asserted three principles, Zeus, Time, and Earth, as the basis of his cosmogony. The dualists here mentioned have been supposed to include Arche- laus, who, according to Diog. Laert. II. 1 6, 17, ekeye bvo alrlas elvai yevicreas, deppov kcu tyvxpov, and who, in describing the production of the animals, says that they sprang from the increasing warmth in the lower parts of the Earth, oVou to Geppoy kol to vj/uxpof epio-yeTO. But, as Steinhart observes, (So- phist, note 22,) the dualism of heat and cold is a theory of the Universe probably older than Parmenides, who speaks of this as the philosophy of opinion. There is of course no allusion to Parmenides in these words. He is included in the 'EXeaTiKov Wvos mentioned immediately afterwards. 2. ydpovs — 7rape^erat] " Are found to marry," &c. 5. to fie 7rap' fjfiap] I. e. e£ 'Ekeas. Heindorf and Stall- baum prefer rjplv, which appears in C. H. 2, a. b. c, and in the quotations of Eusebius and Theodoret. But fjpwv is pre- ferable both as the reading of the best MSS. and as the less obvious reading: "The school that came forth from us." dno Sevofpdvovs Te Kal en npoo-dev ap^dpevov] "From Xe- nophanes downwards, and even before Xenophanes." This is conceived in the same spirit as the attempt in the Thetetetus to refer the Heraclitean dogma to an unknown antiquity. Thesst. 179 &'■ 7rep\ toutccv tcov 'HpaKXeiTeLoyv, fj Loo-rrep av keyeis 'Opr/peioov, Kal en TrakaioTepcov. Steinhart imagines a reference to the Pseudo-Orphic Fragment, Zeis dpx'Q, Zevs peacra, Ai6s 8" etc ndura reXetrru, which is elsewhere quoted by Plato, Legg. 4, 7 1 5 e. 7. evos ovtos t£>v navrcov] The participle, although agree- ing in sense with TravTuv, follows the number of the preceding word. Cf. Protag. 329 d : epos OVTOS TTJS dpeTTJS. 8. toIs pvOois] " In their tale of the Universe ;" referring to p,v66v nva supr. Cf. Theast. 156 c : ovtos 6 pvdns — viz. the theory of Sensation. 'idbes — Moiio-ai] The word vo-Tepov applies to the SiKeXai as compared with the 'ld8es povaai. Empedocles was later than 20? to bv 7roXXa re Kal kv £(ttiv, £X@P a $* KaL 0*A/a avpe)(€Tai' Siafapofievov yap del ljvfj.(f)€p€Tai, (jxxcriv at avvrovwrepat tcov M.ovo~cov' at Heraclitus, and his speculation is viewed by Plato as that of Heraclitus in a less exact form. See the speech of Eryximachus in the Symposium, who treats of Love in the spirit of Empe- docles (187 a, b) : to ev cprjo-iv ('HpuKXetros) 8ia(pepopevov avro ai'TG) {-Vfxipepeo-dai, uxnrep appovlav t6$-ov re Kal Xvpas. eo-ri 8e iroWrj dXoyla appovlav (pdvai 8ia(pepe- o~6ai t] €K 8ia(pepopevoov ert elvai. dXX' 'laws rode tj3ovX(To Xeyeiv, on £k 8ia(p(popevcov irporepov tov o^eos Kal fiapeos, eneira varepov opdXoyrjcrdvTav yeyovev vttu ttjs p.ovo~iKrjs rexvr]s. The Words 770XX7) aXoyia in this extract are a good comment on da8a, Trjo~8e re fiavreV aKovav ^uvvo&V re ra£ epov 77a\al(paff dpol $oi/3os fjvv- aev irore. dacpaXeo~TaTov] " The most irrefragable position." Cf. supr. 231 a : tov dacpaXr). Protag. 351 d, Polit. 262 b. 3. 8iaqbep6pevov — o-vpcp.) Sc. to bv fj to irdv. Cf. Symp. 1. C. 4. o-WTOva>Tepai p.aXaKa>T(- pai] These are musical terms, as Boeckh has shewn in his contribution to Heindorf's note upon this passage : " Desumpta vocabula o-wt. et paX. a colore s. XP"? m niusicis generibus. Etenim ex sex illis coloribus unus in enharmonico, duo in diiitonico, tres in chromatico genere sunt. In chromate est Color rjpioXi-os, color Tovtalos et juaXoKos, s. rjpioXiov xpeopa, tovl- aiov s. crvvrovov xpaipa et XP^P' 1 paXaKov. In diatono duo colores Sunt Siutovov avvTovov et 8taTovov p.aXciKov. Ilia crvvTOva Sunt ill— tentiora, paXaKo. molliora. Eu- clid. Introd. Harmon, p. 10, 11. Aristox. Harm. Elem. I. p. 24 sqq. Gaudent. Harmon. Intr. p. 17 : " Notandum autem illud exdXaaav, quod est in musicis in p.aXai eT«8^ to iv ClVTCp TTVKVOV xpeojua dvleTcii Te Kal eKkverai." Cf. also Rep. 3, 398 e : Tlves ovv paXaKul — tcov dp- povicov. 'lao-Ti, r/ 8' os, Kal XuSicrrt, a?Tives ^aXapat koXovv- Tai, where the " soft Lydian airs" are spoken of with a metaphorical meaning. The point here is that the union of one and many was more thorough in Heraclitus than in Empedocles. A similar appli- cation of these musical ex- pressions is made by Aristotle, Polit. IV. 3, in drawing a parallel between music and government, in both of which he says the ordinary kinds are divergences from the one or two best : 7rapeK/3ucm?, tcis pev tt/s ev KeKpape'vrjs dppovlas, Tas 8e Trjs dpLo~TT]s iroXiTelas, oXcyap- XtKas pev tcis o~vvTovu>Tepas Kal 8eo"rroTiKa>Tepas, Tas 8' dvaptvas Kal paXaKas 8rjpoTLKas. i.y love and then Bevered by hate, li--i\ e ■ M.ii.- ,:n-|i of them his own way. 106 riAATftNOS 8e fjLa\aK(OT€pui to fxlv aei ravO' ovt(ds tx €LV e X"^ a " P* 2 -+ 2 crav, cV fxepei 8e Tore f±ev eu eivai (j)aai to ttolv koli (j)[\ov vtt ' A^podiTt]?, rore 8e rroXXa koll iroXeiiLOv p. 243 avrb avrcp 8lol yet/coy tl. Tama 8e irdvTa d /iev 5 a\i]$a)9 Ttr r) purj tovtcov t'lprjKe, ^aXe7roi/, kcll ttXt]/!- fxeXh- ovtq) fxeyaXa icXeivols kcll iraXaiols av8puaiv iTTLTLfiav' tKtivo 8e aveirk^Oovov dTrotyrjvaaOaL. 0EAI. To Trolov ; SE. Otl Xlav Tu>v ttoXXmv r]p.u)i> v7repi86i>T€s loooXiyooprjcraW ovSev yap (f)povTLCTavT€s elr 67raKoXov- Oovpiev ai)Tols Xeyovcnv elre caroXenropLeOa, Trepaivovcri TO o-(f)€T€poi> aVTWV €KaO~TOl. 1) 0EAI. Ylas Xiyeis ; For when S*E. 'OtCLV T19 CWTWV (pOeyljrjTCU XtyCDV 0)9 6CTTIV they say , v * » \ ***** ' » Q "Many," 157; yeyovev r\ yiyvtrai iroXXa rj eu rj dvo, koli oepp.ov ■ One, Two," av the ad- ■^rv\pw avyKtpai'i'VfAei'Oi', aXXoOl irrj 8iaKpLO-€is 5. x a ^ en ° v ] Sc. elirelv, which medy. Cf. Phsedr. 275 d, e. is absorbed in what follows. 14. "Orav ris avra>v (pOeygrjrai] Ka\ nXrjppeXes — (iriTifxav ] " When one of them utters his Compare the structure of saying, 'Many, one, two, are, Theset. 146 b : w dmo-relv, o>; have been born, are created,' f'yw oljiai, ovre arii edeXrjcreis, ovre or speaks of heat interpenetrat- Oefiis rrep\ ra roiavra dv8p\ crotpco ing with cold, while he else- inLTaTTovTi veeorepov aTTeidelv. where postulates separations 6. ovtco [j-eydXa] Cogn. Ace. and combinations, I pray you, Sc. to pr] dXtjdun ravra elprfnevcu. Thesetetus, do you at all then " To make such grave accu- understand their meaning 1 " sations against men of ancient Note the l-edundant participle, renown." Heind. well compares as in ecprj Xeyw. Legg. 10, 886 c : el pev els aX- as — irroTtdeis] There is Xo ri koXcos 37 prj KaXat ex«, ol an emphasis on each of the pdhiov emripqv TraXatols oiio-tv. words eariv, yeyove, ylyverai, 7. eKelvo] " That former 7roXXa, ev, 8vo, 6eppov, \}/v)(pcp, thing," viz. what was implied SiaKplaeis, crvyKpio-eis. in (vkoXcos k.t.X. 16. aXXodl tttj] Either, "in 9. V7repc86vres] "Looking over some other part of his treatise," our heads." This was the error or " as taking place in some which Dialectic, or the Socratic other region." For 6epp. \j/. dialogue, was calculated to re- a-vyx., cf. Archelaus ap. Hippol. 20i€i? 6 tl Xeyovatv ; eytw pev yap ore pev rjv vecorepos, tovto fre^ to vvv diro- povptevov birore tis eliroL, to /jltj ov, a.Kpi(3co? wpirjv <~vvi£vai" vvv Se bpas %v la-p.lv avTov irepi ttjs air op las. c GEAI. 'Opu. HE. Ta^a tolvvv taoof ovx tjttov KaTa, to ov Tambv tovto irdOos ei\r}(j)6T€9 iv Tjj \j/v)(f) 7repl pcev tovto eviropeiv (pap.ev K.a\ pavOdvetv oTTOTav ti? ovto (j)0e'ytjr)Tai, irepl de Oarepov ov, irpbs ap.(poT€pa OpLOLOOS €)(OVT€?. GEAI. "lam. HE. Kou 7repl tcov dXXcov 8rj tcov 7rpoeipr)p.evGov y]plv TavTOv tovto eiprjaOco. GEAI. Uavvye. HE. Tcov piev tolvvv iroXXwv irept Ka\ p.€Ta tovto orKe\j/6pL€0\ av Soijr), Trepl 8e tov peylaTov re Kal d dpxoyov irpaoTOV vvv o-k€7tt60v. mixturi "i heat and cold," •■ are," " have been produced," "come into being," or 5 when they speak of the com- position and divi- sion of elements, do we understand them? 10 Not-Being may have once ap- peared an intelligible phrase, but see where it has brought us now. 5 Let us therefore turn and examine the most cardinal of all ideas, that of Being, Ref. Haer. I. 9 : deppaivopev)]s ttjs yrjs irpioTiov iv tco Karon pepei, ottov to deppbv Kal to y^v^pov ip-lcryeTo. I. tovtcov] Neut. 3. tovto j~Tef] re is with- out correlative : whence Herm. conj. ye, which has no meaning, Par. H. o-ov roVe, which cannot be right, but suggests the conj. tots ye. But, as the Bodleian MS. omits to, it seems most likely that to Avas first corrupted into t«, and then again inserted. Hence re is to be omitted. Otherwise we must suppose that the apodosis is absorbed in the words ro^a tolvvv tVws ovx t]ttov Kara to ov k.t.A. For which, cf. Ph.sedr.265 d: els p.iav re I8eav avvopcovTa ayeiv k.t.\. 5. iva ttjs aTropias] " What a point Ave have reached in the perplexity about Not-Being." The article is used because the difficulty attaching to the no- tion of p.fj ov is by this time familiar. 14. to>v aXXcov tcov Trpoeiprjpe'- vcov\ yeyovos, yeveais, 7roXXa, iv, 8vo, Oeppov, yj/v^pov, 8iaKpio-eis, avyKpiaeis. 1 8. Toil peylcTTOv Kal dp%riyov~\ " The mightiest and chiefest." Being is spoken of Avith pro- found reverence, as in Rep. 6, 108 nAATONOS in the light ..I existing theories. We first interrogate the philo- sophers who hold that all is resolvable into two ultimate existences. When they say that these two exist, what do they mean ? Do they postulate existence as a third element, or identify it with one 509 b, C '. ovk. ov(rias ovtos rod dyadov, dXk' ert iireneiva rrjs ov~ crias 7rpecr/3eta Kai dvvdpei imepe- XOVTOS. I. Tlvos ty Ae'yeis] " Sic seni- jjer in responsione negligitur prsegressa prepositio." Heind. — Cf. Rep. 7? 53 1 d : rov wpooi- jxlov — rj tlvos Xe'yeis ', , 4. Kara 7roSa (sc. erropevos) J " At the heels." " Following my footsteps closely." (Cf. Soph. (Ed. Col. 197 : iv — /3uo-« fiaaiv dpfxoo-ai.) The plural Kara ttoSos is the more usual form ; hut the sing, occurs again Legg. 11, 918 a: Ki@&r)\ois 8' eTTiTrjdevpao-iv eWerat Kara. Tr68a Ka~r)\e[as eniTrjSevpaTa. 6. avTu>v\ Probably em- phatic, " as if the men them- selves were personally present here." II. pr/ 8vo en Ka6 y u/xas] "And no longer two according to your theory." I. e. either, " must we give up your theory and make three principles in- stead of two 1" or, " must we understand you to assert three principles instead of two V The former way of taking the words is more pointed, but the latter is in better keeping with the context, 14. dpeporepms] "Both ways." I. e. either, " as Being is identi- fied with one only, and as the one term Being is predicated of both alike" (the latter part of this argument loses force when the nature of predication is clearly understood), or, perhaps better, dpeporepas = "Whichever of the two is identified with Being." BE A I. TtVo? 81) Xeyets ; ?/ Sr/Xov on to bv (ftys p. 243 irpcoTov Setv StepevvijaacrOai, t'l iro6' 61 AeyovTes avro Si]Xovv i)yovvTaL ; SE. Kara iroSa ye, co QealrrjTe, v7reXa(3e?. Xeyco 5 yap Si) ramrj 8eiv woielaOat ti]v pe6o8ov r)pas, oiov avToov irapovTwv avanvvQavopevovs u>8e' ( l>e'pe, biro- aoL 6epp.ov kol \J/vxpov rj Tive 8vo tolovtco ra iravT elvai (j)are, t'l irore apa tovt eif afi(f)oiv (jjOeyyeade, XeyovTes ap.(f)co Ka\ eKarepov elvai\ tl to eivai e lotovto i)Tro\d$(j£>p.ev vpLcov ; irbrepov rplrov irapa ra Svo eKelva, /cat rpia to ttolv, aXXa. p,r) Suo en Kad* vp.a.5 TL0copev ; ov yap ttov toIv ye Svolv KaAovvres OaTepov ov ap. CIS 8vVapiV TL 7TOT6 XtyOVCTL TO OV \ GEAI. ITcoy yap ov; jS?E. T68e tolvvv aTTOKpLveaOwaav. "E^ irov which is tan t ;l - mount to r 1 living all into one ? or do they give to both the one name of [icing, so making both one '. The same argument.-* '5 will apply to all who hold a plu- rality of natures. Then let those who 20 assert One i . ' AAA' apa] Stallb. and Herm. give apa. Cf. Kep. 2, 374 b. " But perhaps you mean to give the name to both toge- ther ]" The Bodl. MS. gives apa invariably, and is there- fore of no use in deciding be- tween apa and apa. 6. air a] This is the same vague use of the neuter of avros which is common inThucydides. Cf. ravru infr. 1. 8. 9. aop.e6ci\ Sc. yiyvdoaicf a', Cf. SUpr. 233 b: et /xijre dvre- Xeyov opdws P-iyre ineivois ep.eu p.av8dvet,v p.ev\ p.ev belongs to the two preced- ing words taken as one. Cf. Theset. 151b: pt] oo£cocr( ncos. 12. to 8e] "Whereas really. - ' Cf. Thetet. 157 b: to 8' ov 8e?, and note. 1 8. els 8vvap.iv] I.e. " So far as is possible when they are not present." Cf. Thetet. 184 a. 20. TdSe aTTOKpLveo-doia-ai/ ] " Let them give an answer to the following question." Cf. Legg. 10, 901 c: Nw 8r) 8v' owes rpio-iv rjplv ovaiv dnoKpi- vdo~8aio~av. 110 I7AATQN02 Being t.ll UB what the; mean \r ■ Being and Unity two names for the same thing ? It will puzzle them to answer this, or in- deed any question. For how can there be two names, or a name at all, when there is nothing beside the One Being? Unless the (j)aT€ pouov tlvai ; ^apev yap, (j)i]0~ovcrii>. r) p. 244. yap ; 0EAI. Nal. HE. 1/ 6Y ; bv KaXeiTe tl ; 5 0EAI. No/. HE. Iloreyoo^ O7T6/0 eV, eVf rco ai/rco Trpoa\ptopevoi c 5fOii» bvopacriv, ?) 7TGk ; 0EAI. TV's" 01)1/ avrol? r] fxera tovt , cb £eVe, airoKpicris ; 10 HE. A^Ao^, to QeaiTrjTe, otl rco ramrju ttjv viToOecriv inroOtfievw irpbs to vvv lpcoTr]6iv, koli Trpbs dXXo 8e otlovv, ov irdvTcov pacrrov diroKpivao-Qai. 0EAI. Ylm; HE. To re 8vo bvop.ara bpoXoyeiv eivai, pur)8ev \5 0epevov irXrjv ev, KarayeXacrTov ttov. GEAI. Ylm 8 ov; HE. Kcu to Trapdirav ye aTroSeyeaOai tov Xeyov- tos cos ecrTiv ovopLa tl, Xoyov ovk av e%ov. tl 6. onep ev\ Cf. the Aristo- telian use of Bnep, e. g. Phys. Ause. I. 3. 11. Ka\ Tvpb<; ciXXo Se otlovv] "And not only so, but in an- swer to any other question." 12. OV TTOLVTUiV pq0~T0v\ " Not the easiest thing in the world." Cf. supr. 2 1 8 c. I venture to think that this is the true reading also in Kep. 6, 497 d, instead of ov irdvTcos pqo-Tov. ndvTcos was the reading of Ste- phanas (apparently with C E) in this place, and of 2Y in 218 c. Cf. Legg. 6, 779 e : ov navTcov evKo\a>Ta.Tov. 18. Xoyov ovk av ex ov \ C. F. Hermann has reverted to the reading of the old edd. Xoy. ovk av ex.01. But it is unne- cessary to alter exov, which is the reading of the best MSS. The participle corresponds to the adjective KaTayeXaaTOV in the previous clause : and av is more forcible with the parti- ciple (" is a thing which can- not square with reason") than it would have been here with the optative (" would be un- reasonable"): eo-ri, not ei'77, must be supplied. Cf. Theaet. 164 a : emaTTjptev tovtov yeyovev oimep opav. Infr. 257 d : tovt ovv dvuivvpov epovpev rj tw e'xov e7Tcovvp.iav ; 6. exov. " This is an admission which they can never make consistently. For if the name is other than the 20M2TH2. Ill 6EAI. Uy; SE. TiOel? re Tovvopa rov TrpdypaTOS eTepov Svo XeyeL irov Tive. 0EAI. Nai iHE. Kat /x?7J> ai> tolvtov ye aura) 7^17 rovvopa, i] /ArjSevo? ovo/jlol avayKaaO-qaeTai XeyuV el Be tlvos avro (f)y]crei, orvfifirjcreTai to ovofia opo/jlclto? ovopa fiovov, aXXov Be ovBevos bv ; 6EAI. OurfflS". SE. Kai to ev ye, evos [ev] 6i> povov, koll tovto ovo/jloltos ~favTO ev bv j". name be identified with the thing, in w hich case it i.s either the- name of nothing or the name of itself, that is, of a name. And Being is but the name of One, which is a name. Further, their One Being is thing, there are two : if the same, the name either denotes nothing, or itself only. Hence if they admit that a name is anything, their One Being be- comes the name of a name." 6. r) /JLT]8ev6s el Se twos] Change of construction for rj ei TWOS. IO. Kat to ev ye] "And (it will result) that the One also is only one of one, and this ' One that is' again (tovto — av to ev ov) (proves to be the name) of a name." I.e. "Oneness is only predicable of The One, and this after all is but a name." So, a little differently from Heindorf, I would translate the words as they stand (reading av to). The omission of ep after evos, as in nine MSS., hardly af- fects the sense. Heindorf ren- ders : " Atque unum, quatenus est unius tantum unum, hoc quoque nominis rursus unum (das Eins eines Namens) esse efficietur. Pendet enim etiam postremum hoc bv a prcegresso (rv/iiS^o-erat." The place seems to be corrupt : but none of the emendations hitherto made are satisfactory. The Bod]., with A i, has tov ovo/jlotos. The MSS. give ovto ev ov. Stallb. : Kcu ov ttov 6v6u.citos avTO ev ov. (This is not dialectic but common sense.) Herm. : evos ev bvofia ov, Kai tovto ouofxaTos av to ev bv. Badham : Kai to ev ye, evos ev bv uovov 7, tolovt6v ye ov to ov p.€0~ov re koll eayara e'^ei, Tama 8e t\ov Tracra dvayKy ptepy tyeiv. y 7rco? ; GEAI. Ovrm. HE. 'AAAa fMyv to ye fxepepiapLevov iraQos pev p. roD ivos e'xe^ eVi rot? p.epeai iraaiv ovSev airoKto- S Auet, /cat TavTr) by ttolv re oi> /cat oAoz/ ei' eiVat. GEAI. TIS ov: 245- some marginal note (e. g. drrou tov ivos, explaining dvouaTos), and Plato may have written Kal t6 eV ye e>6s e> 6VofJia 5V, Kal touto ocojxaTOS. " And (it will result) that the One also is the one name of One, and that of a name." I. e. Not only is Being not another name for Unity, or Unity for Being, but Unity is the name only of a name." The drift of the pre- ceding argument is the fol- lowing : " Are IV and ov two names for the same thing ] " Are they even two names 1 Or can there be both name and thing 1 ? " Even the one name ev can only be the name of a name." 5. okov eorii/] Sc. TO ov. So far unity has been attained by merging all things in the mere name h> ov. But is not to okov still distinct from this 1 IO. uiaov re Kal eo-x aTa *X eL ] Cf. Parni. 145 a : okov ov Kal apx^v av e\oi Kal fiearov Kal Te- kcvTrjv ; rj oiov Te ti okov eivai uvev rpiav tuvtcov ' } K.T.k. 1 3. 7rd6os u.ev tov evbs €)(eiv] " That which has parts may indeed partake of unity in all the parts (i. e. may have unity impressed on them), and being thus an All and a Whole may be in this way one." For the distinction of rrav and okov, see Theset. 204, which passage Plato may have thought of here. The words 7rd0os and irdo-xetv are used in the same sense also in Parmen. 147, alib. See Grote's Plato, vol. ii. pp. 303-306. 20M2TH2. I 1 S 245. HE. To 8e ireirovOos ravra up ovk uSvvcitov avro ye to ev olvto elvai\ 0EAI. Um; HE. 'Apepe? 8rj wov 8et wavTeAco? to ye dArjOcos ev kclto, tov opObv Xoyov elprjcrdai. 5 0EAI. Aei yap ovv. b HE. To Se ye tolovtov £k ttoXXcov pepcov ov ov o-vjj.(f)Govr}crei tco Xoycp. 9EAI. MavOdvco. S*E. TioTepov 8r) irdOos eypv to *6v* rou eVo? 10 is Being (■/ r/ 3/ \ <•/,. ,\ / \ -. / then one ovtco? ev re eo~Tcti /cat oaoj>, 77 TTavTcmacn pr) Xeyccpev only by cf -y \ v participa- oAoz> eivai TO ov ; tion, or 0EAI. XaAe7n)i> TTpo(3el3XrjKa9 dlpeaiv. say that HE. ' AXrjOe'aTaTa pevTOi Aeyeis. ireirovOos re yap ^Xt whole ? for- v A t \ 9 / > j \ ,\ ~ « \ j / \ whole ro ov e^ eu>at 7ra>?, oi> tolvtqv ov tco evi (patveTcti, koli 15 i n the \/ ?< x ^ ' t \ 3/ mer case TrAeova or) tcl ircivTa evos ecrrat. Being ig GEAI. Na/. 1. To Se nenovBos ravra] agree in giving oXoi>, but 6i>, Compare the language of Parm. the correction of Schleier- 147 c-148 c: >? erepov ehai rnacher, is absolutely required. 7rej7op6e ra>v aXkav, Ka\ raKKa The same corruption occurs in eKeivov ao-avrcos, ravry ravrbv av Prot. 36 1 b. The Bodleian, •neirovBora elev to re ev rols ctXkois by giving rco oAo> Xdyw just Ka\ raXKa rw ivi k.t.X. above, betrays the tendency 2. to $v avro ehai] The which has produced the error, pronoun avro is added where Cf. Thea?t. 149 c, droKois (Bodl. the subject has been thrown droirois with dronararo? above) : back to the beginning of the lb. 158 c, 6V with xP° V0V eTno-rrjfxTjv -norepov dvvapiv riva below). (pfjs eivai avTrjv ; 1 3. XaXenfju — atpeo~iv\ Cf. IO. Uorepov £77] I. e. " Is Theset. 196 c: "Anopov aipeaiv Being one only by participa- npoTidrjs, w 2co/c/jare £eve, irporide- this way, or is Being not to peda rrjv alpecriv. be thought of as a whole at 14. 'AXijd^o-rara pevroi \eyeis] all?" "You are right. It is truly distinct from Unity tov evoi bs] The MSS. difficult, 114 IIAATQNOS and there arises a plurality of ele- ments. Ami in the latter case, supposing a whole to exist, there exists something outside of Being : and moreover there is again plurality. HE. Kai p.i)v edv ye rb ov f) firj oXov 8ia to ire- p. 245 TTOvOlvai TO VTT €K€Ll>OV 7TO.0O9, fj 8e OLVTO TO 0X0V, C ivSee? to ov eavTOv ijvp.(3alv€i. 0EAI. Tldvv ye. 5 SE. Kcu koltol tovtov 8rj tov Xoyov eavTov crTepb- \xevov ovk ov eaTou to ov. 0EAI. Ovrm. SE. Kcu evos ye av irXem tol iravTa yiyveTai, tov Te ovtos /ecu tov oXov x^P^ i8iav eKdTepov (f)V- locrtv eiXrjtyoTO?. 6EAI. Nat. HE. M?) ovtos 8e ye to irapdirav tov oXov, Tamd Te TavTa virdpyei ra ovtl kcu 7rpbs tg> pj] eivcu p.rj8' d av yeveadai ttotI ov. '5 0EAI. T/&J; HE. To yevoptevov ae\ yeyovev oXov, ScrTe ovtc i. fj fxrj S\ov] The order of words is inverted, as so often happens in this dialogue, pro- bably in order to point the antithesis by giving emphasis to \il). " If Being is not a whole through parcicipating in unity, and the nature of the whole exists, Being then falls short of Being" (does not contain all that exists). Is Being abstract or con- crete 1 If abstract, Being is not a whole, or finite. If con- crete, Being is separate from abstract Unity. In the latter case there are two principles. In the former, (a) if a whole exists, not only are there two principles, but something ex- ists apart from being : and (/3) if a whole does not exist, Being could never have come to be, for what has come to be is completed as a whole. This last argument is much in the spirit of the Parmenides. Compare also Phileb. 15 b: nebs (del vndXaufidvetv) p.iav eKa- arrjv ovcrav del 7-171/ avrrjv /cat pr]re yeveaiv pyre oXedpov Trpocrde)(o- pevrjv, o/xcoy elvai fteftaiorara piav ravrqu. The Eleatic would of course reply that he denies yeveo-is altogether. And so Plato would have reasoned at an earlier time. 12. ravrd re ravra VTrdp^et rco 6W1] ovk ov eari kcu 7r\eia> evos. Compare the language of the Parmenides. Bodl. ravra re ravra. I 6. yeyovev o\ov\ Cf. Parm. 153 C .' Kai prjv popid ye (prjcro- aev ravr elvai rrdvra rdWa rov oXov re Ka\ eVoV, avro be eKelvo 20irrH2. 245. overlap ovre yevecnv coy ovaav Set irpoaayopeveiv '\ro ev 77-j- to oXov ev rols overt, /jltj riOevra. 0EAI. YlavTairaaLv eoiKe ravO' ovto)? e^etv. £JE. Kal /jltjv ovS" birocrovovv ti Sec to /jitj oXov elvai- ttoctov tl yap ov, ottoctov av fj, toctovtov oXov avayKalov elvai. 0EAI. KofitBrj ye. SE. Kal TOivvv aXXa ptvpla airepavrovs a7roplas e eKaarov eiXrjtybs (paveirat rco to bv etre hvo rive elre ev fiovov elvai Xeyovn. 0EAI. ArjXoi o~xe$oi> Kal to. vvv virofyaivovTa' o-vvdirTeraL yap erepov etj dXXov, /j.e[^co Kal \aXe- ircoTepav (f)epov irepl tcov efiirpocrOev ael prjdevrcov TrXavrjv. £?E. Tovs jmu tolvvv hiaKpiftoXoyovixevovs OVTOS Sfia rfj rekevTrj yeyovevai ev re km. oXov. I. e. the use of the aorist yev6p.evov implies that an action has been completed. Cf. Theset. 155 b, c. 1. fro ev jjf] These words are in all the MSS., but there can be little doubt that they arise either from a gloss or from some corruption of the text. Heindorf conjectured -rot/ to okov, which is probably right. 8. aXka fivpla] " You know that innumerable other points will each be found involved in endless difficulties." Cf.Theset. 155 c j d : Kal SX\a 8r] p.vpia eVi [Jivpiois ovras e%ei, e'lnep Kal raiira TrapaSegoneda. For an illus- tration of the truth of this Plato would point to the Par- menides. 12. erepov i£ ciXKov] For the variety, cf. Phileb. 57 b : apa eWi tis erepas ciWr] Kadapmrepa e7no-rrjp.t]s iiuo-TT)pri. And for irepl twv e\mpoo~6ev k. t. A., Theset. 177 c: nXeico del eirip- peovra Karaycocret fj/xcov tov eg dpxrjs Xoyov. Ift.Tovs pev Tolvvv K.r.A.] "Well then, concerning those who treat exactly of Being and Not-Being, let so much suffice, although the subject is by no means exhausted. We must now turn and look at others who speak less precisely, that we may learn from the most general survey that Being is no less troublesome to com- prehend than Not-Being." "Let us approach them, then. Proceed." " I see them, through their dispute about the nature of Being, engaged in a warfare But if there is no 5 Whole, not only must there be plurality, (for then Being is not One) but Being cannot have come 10 into being, still less exist, for nothing is completed but as a whole. Nor can Being have number, 5 for, what- ever num- ber it has, it has this as a whole, or sum. Q 2 IK) nAATONOS re 7repi kcu }JLi) iravv [ilv ov ditAi]AuOafi€i>, ujicos 5e p. 245 which resembles thai of the ( Hauls and the < k)ds." •• What do you mean I" •■ The one faction would drag everything to Earth out of the Heaven of the Unseen, literally laying their grasp on rocks and trees. For they fasten upon everything of this kind, and contend uncompro- misingly that this alone exists Avhich affords resistance and is sensible to the touch : so they define Being and Body to be the same. But they utterly despise the rest of the world, whoever asserts that a bodiless thing has being, and, on hear- ing this, refuse to listen to another word." " They are indeed a fearful sort of men. I have encoun- tered many of them myself, ere now." " Yes, and that is why their opponents are so cautious in their defence, and fight with them from some invisible aery hold, contending in spite of all that True Being consists of certain bodiless forms, seen only by the mind : but the bodies to which the others cling, and the realities of which they speak, these little by little in their arguments disintegrate and crumble down, and describe them as not substance but a moving flux of change. Between these armies from time immemorial a battle has been joined, which continues with unabated fury." (l5-) diaKpij3oXoyovpevovs — aX- Xcos XeyovTas] In the former class are obviously contained all who have hitherto been mentioned — the Ionics, Elca- tics, Heraclitus, Empedocles : and the word ouixp. probably means " those who have defined precisely the number and the kinds of being." Cf.supr. 243 d : aims TTconore eVi Kplcriv copprjae rov ra ovra 8iopicracr6ai trnaa re Kai nold ecrriv. It is less certain who are spoken of as diaicp. ■rrepl tov pj ovtos. Perhaps the prohibition of Parmenides is alone referred to, perhaps Leucippus may be also in- tended. It does not seem probable that Gorgias, Pro- tagoras, Antisthenes, or the Megarians (as Heindorf sup- poses) are included in this ex- pression. The contemporaries of Socrates seem to be reserv- ed, with those of Plato, for the following section (p. 246). The meaning of aXXcos is best infer- red from that of 8m/cpt/3oXoyou- pevovs, to which aXXcos Xeyoi>ra<; is opposed. "Those who speak with less exactness." " Those who do not seek to determine the number or the kinds of Being." The schools which are now to be described are in truth engaged with a different problem : respecting the nature of Being or Essence, whether this be ideal or corporeal — a question with which mathe- matical or numerical exactness has little to do. For a simi- lar use of aXXws, cf. Hdt. V. 8 : oXXcos yfj Kpv\p-avres. Crat. 425 a: f/pus Se del etWp rexvi- kcos iniarrjC-upeBa (TKOTre'icrdcu avrci ndvTcij ovtco BLeXopevovs, e'tre Kara Tponov rd T€ 7Tpu>Ta ovopara K€~L- 7ai Kai tci vrrrepct, eire prj, ovtui 2CXM2TH2. 117 245- WWtwSs €)(€T(O m TOV? §6 CtAAcO? XtyOVTOLS (XV 0€aT€OV, IP €K TTOLVTWV el8cOfJL€l' OTl TO OV TOV fXJJ OVTOS OvStV 246. eviropcoTepov efareiv o ri ttot ecrTiv. GEAI. Qvkovv TropeveaOai xprj koll im tovtov?. t flE. Kcu fX1]V €01K€ y€ Iv aVTols olov yiyaVTO- 5 We pro- ceed to Bedadai. aXXws 8e avveipetv prj pev. 243 C : Tdxa to'lvvv 'laws k.t.X., and is more decidedly enforced infra 250 d. 5. yiyavTnuaxia] Plato notices amongst contemporary philo- sophers a conflict between ma- terialists and idealists, which he compares to the war of the Giants with the Go^s : the terrible children of the earth are seen hurling blind defi- ance at their opponents, who fortify themselves securely from this rude violence in an invisible Heaven. In a similar spirit, in the Politicus, p. 291 a, the statesmen of the day are compared to Centaurs and Satyrs and other monstrous forms. See Coleridge's Friend, vol. iii. p. 129. — The mate- rialist has no way upwards His " element is below." The idealist finds his way up, but not down again. 118 I1AATQN02 examine a different order of philosophic schools, Bomewhat in their announce- ments, whose end- less conflict respecting the nature of essence resembles that of the Giants with the Gods. The advo- cates of a bodilyprin- ciple,whose touchstone is the sense jxaxia T19 eivai 8 to. ti)v a/i(f)i(Tfir)T7)(nv irep\ ttjs P- 246. ovcrLas irpos aXX^Xovs. 0EAI. n eOe- Xovres aXXo aKoveiv. 0EAI. 'H Seivovs eipr/Kas avbpas' rjdr/ yap Kal eyco tovtoov avyyols 7rpoaerv)(ou. I. TTep\rr]S ovaias] No longer tov ovtos. This change of ter- minology indicates that we are entering on a new and more abstract phase of philosophy. 5. eXKovcn] " Drag by main force." The word is often used to indicate perversity in argument. Cf. iufr. d : rav els o~a>pa iravra eXKOvrcov /3tg. ov- pavos is elsewhere identified by Plato with the visible region, e. g. Rep. 6, 5°9 e : Sparov, Iva pfj ovpavov elirav 8okS> croi ao(pi- £eadac Trepl to ovopa. Earth and Heaven are here opposed, as there the visible and intel- lectual worlds. dre^vcos irerpas Kai 8pvs irepi- Xapftdvovres] C. F. Hermann inserts as before ireTpas. This is quite unnecessary, and takes from the liveliness of the image. The metaphor is continued, and the materialists are said, like the earth-born monsters, to lay their grasp on rocks and trees in their warfare. In Hesiod it is the hundred-handed sons of Heaven and Earth, the allies of Zeus, who throw the rocks up- on the Titans. Theog.675-7 15. But see Hor.Od.III. 4 : evulsis- que truncis Enceladus jaculator audax. irerpa Kal 8pvs are also in Homer the symbols of in- animate nature, as in the line quoted by Socrates in his De- fence : ov yap djrb 8pvos rjXvdov ovd' dno Trirprjs. Cf. Rep. 8, 544 e : rj o'lei eK 8pvos iroBev 77 Ik nerpas ras noXiTelas yiyveaduL ; 6. i(paTrT6pevoi] " Fastening upon all such objects" (for the purposes of their argument). Q. rav 8e ciXXav, ei tis (pr]0~ij " But, utterly despising all others, whosoever says that what has not body exists, and refusing to hear from them an- other word." Stephanus added ti, which is found (after tis) in C. H. re. B. 13. av^vols TTpoo-ervxov] Cf. 2CM>I2TH2. 119 246. SE. Toiyapovv oi irpos olvtovs dfj.(l)ta^r]TovvT€9 fiaXa evXaffcos avwOev eh dopdrov 7ro6ev dfAvvovTou, vorjTa OLTTa kou daco/xara elSrj fiiatpiievoi. ri]V dXrj- 6ivrjv ovaiav eivai' rd 8e eKelvcop acofxara kou ttjv Xeyop.evr]v vtt clvtwv dXrjOetau Kara a lllk pa Sia- '. c Opavovres kv rot? Xoyois yevecriv dvr ovaiav (fiepo- \x(vr\v riva irpoaayopevovaLi/. eV fxeacp 8e irep\ ravra aVAero? dfKporepwv \xdyr) tis, 00 Qeacryre, dei £vv£Tr). Phileb. 15 e : tovto ovre p.T] iravcriTal wore ovre ijp^aro VVV. Tim. 28 a: vTTep rjS Ttdev- Tai Trjs ovo-ias. I. e. vnep Trjs ovo-'ias, r)v TidevTCU. 12. Xd^copev Xoyov] Cf. Theset. 1 6 1 b : Xoyov nap' eTepov cro0ov Xa^etz/. Meno 7 O d : Xappdveiv Xoyov KaliXeyxe iv. Rep. I, 337 b. thing to ' earth out of the hea- ven of the Unseen. From thence an army, " lapped in proof eterne," carefully defend their aiiry citadel of , bodiless forms, and by their arguments reduce to a flux of transitory production 120 I1AATON02 the seem- ing reality of yonder l)0ilily sub stance. The prin- ciples of either school are called in question, and Thea?- tetus en- gages to impart to the Stranger the tenor of their replies. HE. Ylapa filv tcov ev eldeaiv avTifv TiOefievcav p. 24C paov' i)fiepc£>TepoL yap' irapa. 8e tcov els acofia iravTa. 4\k6vtcou (3la yaXeiroiTepov, taco? <5e kou d aSvvarov. a A A' d>8e poi <5eu> 8ok€l wept olvtmv S 8pav. 0EAI. n«?; HE. MaAiara /LteV, el ttt\ 8vvaTov rjv, epyco /3eA- t'lovs avTov? iroieZv el Be tovto ptrj eyyozpel, Aoyw 7TOL(Ofiei>, V7T0TL$e'fiei>0l VOpLipLCQTepOV OLVTOV9 7} vvv loedekovras av anroKpivacrQai. to yap bpLoXoyqOev irapa fieXTLovcDV irov Kvpicarepov y to irapa. \ €L P°~ vcov' rjixeh 8e ov tovtcov (f)povTi£op.ei>, aAAa Tak-qOes ^QTOV/JLeV. 0EAI. 'OpOoTaTa. e 15 HE. KeAeue 8rj tov? (3e\Tiovs yeyovoTa? diro- KplvaaOai aoi, Kal to XeyOev Trap avT&v a(pep- fxrjveve. 3. ^aX€7ra)Tepoi'] The diffi- culty of arguing with these men is different from that found with the Ephesian piov- res, who could not be made to dwell on an idea, and arises simply from their want of dia- lectical refinement. Cf. Thefet. 155 e: eicri yap, S> ttcu, p.a\' ev ap.ovo~oi. g. vop.ip.a>Tepov] I. e. More in accordance with the acknow- ledged rules of argument. IO. to yap opokoyrjdtv x (L ~ povav] For the serious applica- tion of this principle, cf. Legg. 2, 663 C : rfjv 8' aKrjdeiav rrjs Kpio-ecos TTorepav Kvpiatrepav eivai (fiCvpev ' } norepa rrjv rrjs xapovos yfrvxrjs rj ttjv rrjs fteXriovos ; 'Av- ayicaiov nov ttjv tt)s dpelvovos. 12. rjpets he ov tovtcop cppovri- Cop.ev\ Cf. Phsedo 91c: av epol Treidrjade, apiKpa. cppoi/Ticravres "S,u>Kparovs, ttjs 8e dXrjBeias 7ro\v paXXov, eav ftev n 8okS> dXrjdes Xe'yeiv, ^wop,o\oyr]o-eTe, el 8e pr], ttclvti \6ycp di/TiTeipere. Plato sometimes insists on the neces- sity of individual conviction, as in Protagoras 331 c (oi8ev yap Seo/xai to el ftovXei tovto /cat el aoi 8oKel eXey^eo-daL a\A' ifie re Kai (re), Gorg. 472 b, 4*74 a, b ; sometimes, as here, on consistency of argument alone. The former is the Socratic, the latter the Platonic, mode of asserting the supremacy of reason. 1 6. Trap' gvtcov] The preposi- tion is introduced because of the verb dqbeppfiveve. " Convey from them to me the tenour of their 2CWI2TH2. 121 246, 247^ 0EAI. Tavr earou. SfE. Aeyovroov 8rj dvqrov (coov el (f)aa)u ei- vai TL. 0EAI. ILSy $ oti; 3*E. Touto 8e ou aco/ia epi^rvxov bjioXoyovaiv ; 5 8EAI. Udvv ye. HE. TiOevres rt rcou ovtodv tyvyfjv ; 0EAI. Nat. SE. T7 8e ; tyvyrjv ov tyjv fiev StKalav, rr)v Se aSiKov (fyacrtv eivou, kou tt]v fiev (frpovifiov, ttjv 8ei a(ppova ; 0EAI. Ti/iiyy; HE. 'AAA' ou SiKouocrvvT)? eljei kou "jirapovaia^ ToiavTrjv olvtwv eKaaTr]v yiyvecrOou, kou tcov evavTiwv rr\v evavriav ; 1 0EAI. Nat, KOU TCLVTa ^VfJLCJXXOrtV. HE. 'AAAa p.^v to ye Svvoltov tco irapayiyveo-Qou ™?? he kou airoyiyveaOaL iravTms elva'i n (^r]crovo~iv. 0EAI. Qaal p.ev ovv. The coi [•'•- reali 1 are the more difficult, Imt.-iu-.- i.l tliuir dia- lectical rudenes8 and incom- petence. For the sake of ar- gument we must ima- gine them capable of making a wholesome answer. They ad- mit, then, the exist- ence of a mortal liv- ing crea- ture, which is a body- containing a soul. Soul, then, exists: and righteous or un- righteous, wise or un- b HE. Ovam OVV SlKaiOaVVr)? KOU (hpOVnaeWS KOU 20 wise, ac- cording as the soul has righteous- and wisdom, or the reverse. Righteous- ness and wisdom (i.e. virtue) rrjs aXXrj? apery? kou rcov evavrlcov, koll Srj kou yjsvxrjs ev f) ravra eyylyverai, rrorepov bparov kou arrrbv eival (paal ri avrcov rj irdvra dopara ; 0EAI. '2)(eb s bi> ovdev rovrcov ye bparov. reply." dcpepprjveve possibly (like aX\o39 supr.) imputes to these philosophers a want of clearness in expression. At all events, on the points in question an answer could only be obtained from them by way of inference. Cf., however, Legg. 2, 660 b : as (tv Kar Atyvirrov d(p€pp.T]i>eveis, where the word means to re- port from a foreign country. 13. 8ikciio(tvi>t)s e|et kci\ fnapov- cri'at] " The possession and pre- sence of justice." See note on Theset. 153 b : 17 S' eV tT) ^x'? 14. rcov evavricov] Sc. e£« ml Tcapovala. The plural suggests the conjecture that Plato wrote Sikcuoowtjs e£ei kcu (^povrjcreus. 24. ^xedov — opaTov] Cf.Legg. IO, 898 d. 122 IIAATQNOS are thus admitted to exist. And the soul and virtue are invi- sible. And of these in- visibles, though they may assert that the soul is in a man- ner bodily, theycannot maintain that virtue has a cor- poreal form. HE. TV 8e ; tow TOiovTu>v fxwv acofxu tl Xeyovaiv ]>• 247. 0EAI. ToVTO OVK€TL KCLTO, TOLVTOL CLTTOKpiVOVTai irav, uXXa tt]V fieu \j/V)(i]i> avri-jv 8oK€iP (T(f)lat aco/xa 5 Tl K€KTrj(70ai, (j)pOVrjCTLV 8e KOU TOUV uXXcOV tKfMJTOV on/ r/po)Tr]Kas, aicryyvovTai to ToXfiav 77 fJLrjdeif tcov ovTOiv avra bixoXoyelv rj ttolvt duai aco/xara dii(rx v ~ c plteaOai. aE. 2a0&)s" yap rjfuv, co Gecurr^re, fieXTiov? oyeyovaaiv avdpes, hrei tovtcdv 068' av ev eiraLo-)(yv- Ousv 61 ye avrcov airaproi re kou olvt6)(0ov€?, dXXa 1. Ti — i'o-^etv] Join t»i/ tui- OVTUIV Tl. 3. Tovro ovKen] " They an- swer this with a distinction, saying that the soul appears to them to have a bodily form of some kind, but with regard to wisdom and the other things of which you ask, they have not the face either to admit that these have no being, or any longer to insist that all things are bodily." 4. ttjv jiiv ■*\rvxh v ] See De- mocr. Fragmenta Physica (Mul- lach), esp. § 3. The word ivavra does not resume eppovr]- aiv k.t.\., but the sentence reverts to an independent con- struction. Cf. supr. 243 a, and note. 4. crco/na ti K€KTrjO-dai\ The invisibility of the atoms of Leucippus and Democritus is no objection to these philo- sophers being included here : for these words imply the ex- istence of an aopuTOv crw/xa. 6. to To~\fiav] The inf. has the force of a noun. Cf. ovS" ai> a> infra. 7. avTa] See note on airo, supr. 245 a. 11. anapToi] By an accumu- lation of similes not unusual with him (see Theaet. 169 b, Sciron and Antaeus), Plato in- troduces an allusion to the army of Cadmus rising from the dra- gon's teeth, and also to the first inhabitants of Attica, who, like the Giants, sprang from the ground. Cf. Rep. 3, 444 e, Qoivikikov ti, and Soph. (Ed. Col. 1534, (TTTapTCOV O.TT dv8p5lV. 01 avTa>u anapTol icai avro- xQoves] Plato has obviously some men in his eye, probably the same to whom he alludes in Theaet. 155 e. If it is true that Archelaus abandoned the ideal principle of Anaxagoras, and became a purely physical philosopher, he is perhaps in- cluded, as well as the contem- porary followers of Democri- tus. (See Introduction to These- tetus, p. xxx sqq.) But there appear to be some who, though holding a material principle, are thought capable of being improved into the position 20, 0)9 apa TOVTO Ov8ei> TO TTCLpOLTTOLV IcTTLV. 0EAI. ^ythov ola 8loli>oovi>toll Aeyeis. aE. UolAlv to'lvvv dvepcDTGO/uLev avTOvs' el yap tl koli crpLLKpov iOeXovcTL T(hv ovTcov avyxoopelv dcrco- 5 d ploltov, itjapKel. to yap eiri re tovtols dpLa /cat eV tKeivoLs oaa eyei awpta Ijv/Mpvt? yeyovo?, els o /3Ae- 7TOVT69 dpLfpoTepa elvai Xeyovai, tovto olvtols prrreov. Ta^' ovv to~co9 av diropolev' d Se tl tolovtov irewov- OaCTL, 0-K07T€L, 7TpOTeLVOpL€VCOV TjpLCOV, dp tOtAoLCV OLV io 8e)(€cr0aL /cat 6/ioAoyuv tolovS elvaL to ov. which is assigned them in what follows, who by dialec- tical pressure can be brought to substitute force for body. Perhaps the " disciples of Pro- tagoras," who said that "sen- sation was knoAvledge," are thus viewed as a more refined sort of materialists. If so, the irony with which, in the Theaetetus, they are opposed to the unini- tiate becomes manifest. Cer- tainly the words, ttjv \eyopivqv V7T aircjv akt)6eiav Kara afxiKpa Siadpavovres iv rois \6yois yeveaiv clvt ovcrias (pepop.evr]v riva npoa- ayopevovatv, are an exact de- scription of the " Megarian" treatment of Protagoras in the Tkeaetetus, and it may be that the notion of making the men better for the sake of argu- ment is suggested by the deve- lopment of the " sensational idealism," which is attributed to him in that dialogue. It is equally possible, however, that the argument is pointed at a supposed inconsistency be- tween the physical and ethical writings of Democritus. See the views on " the soul," "justice," "wisdom," in De- mocritus Fr. 1, 4, 5, 6, 35, 36, in, 127, 128, 129, 135 (Mullach's edition). I. ttov 6 prj dvvarol — elcri] For the " pendent" constr. of 7rai>, cf. SUpr. 219b: irav, onep k.t.X. tov p.ev ayovra -noielv, to 8e dyopevov Troieio~8al 7rov(pdp.ev. rats X e P ai o-vp.7ru£eip] The description of the dpvrjToi in Theset. 155 e is closely parallel, 01 ov8ev oAXo olopevoi elvai rj ov av dvvcovTai dirplg to'lv %epo'iv \a(3eo-8ai. Cf. Emped. 1. 356 : fjpeTfpais rj X e P°~ l ^afaw' rjirep re p.eyio~Tr) neidovs dvOpwiroicriv dpatjiTos els (ppeva 7tlttt(i. 6. eiri re toiitois] Cf. Theset. 185 c, supr. 243 d, e. 7. £vp(pves yeyovbs] " Which arises as a common nature." 10. irpoTeivopevav] The word TTpoTelvea-dai in this sense ac- quires a technical use in Aristo- tle, cf. Topica, p. 164, b. 2 : eo-n ydp, 8e Set Stai/oettr^at 7repi otovovv (pvcreois, npcoTov pev, airXovv r) iro\vei8es Icttlv eVetra 8e, iav pev arrhovv rj, cncoTvelv ttjv 8vvapiv avTov, rtVa 7rpos tl ire- cpvKev els to 8pav e%ov rj Tiva els to Tradelv vtto tuv. 6. cos eo-TLv\ Sc. to. ovra. 9. 8ex 0VTaL tovto] In a simi- lar spirit, in Legg. 10, 900, Clinias answers for the ob- jectors. Compare also the ima- ginary youth in the Phsedrus (p. 243 e). 10. KaAws] " They say well." Tbis refers to the modification of their assent implied in eVet- Trep awrot ovk e'xovcriv K.r.A. icrcos yap av elo~vo~Tepov (pavelrj] Cf. Legg. 7, 820 e : Kelcrdco pevTOi KaBairep eveyypa \\)CTLpa (K Trjs ciWrjs 7roAtTet'nf, eav rj tovs devTas r)pas rj kiu tovs 20 OLV (f)OLl>eir]. TTpOS /JL€V OVU TOVTOV? 248. tovto rjiAiv tvTavOa jX€vIt(d ^vvopoXoyqQev. 0EAI. Mem. HE. YIpos 8rj rovs ere'povs Xwfiev, rovs rwv el$a>v (f)t\ovs' av 8 7}plv koli tol irapa tovtwv u(])eppyueve. 5 Befxevovs ifxas /^Sojucor v et'Scoi/ (fiikovs] The word etSos indicates that the men here spoken of are Socratics, so far at least as the allusion is personal at all. Now they are certainly not Cynics ^KvTivBeveioi m\ 01 ovras ciTraidevTOi), still less Cyrenaics, with whom the only " essence" was a succession of momentary ndBrj. They are Socratics under an Eleatic or Pythagorean influence. Pro- clus, indeed, (Comment, in Parmen. p. 149) takes it for granted that Plato here al- ludes directly to the Pythago- rean school, whom Aristotle includes with the Platonists amongst the advocates of a " motionless essence," tu>v ras ukivi']tovs ovaias XcyovrwP, Met. XIV. 4, 1 09 1 b. But, besides the word eldos, the dialectical features and the way in which yeveois is separated from ota-ia, are inconsistent with this. Four possible suppositions re- main, if we believe the dia- logues to be the work of Plato. The "friends of forms" are either (1) Megarians (since Schleiermacher this has been the most general impression) ; or (2) Plato himself at an earlier stage ; or (3) Pla- tonists who have imperfectly understood Plato. The fourth hypothesis combines (2) and (3). The theory of Socher, who imagined the ' Sophist' to be a Megarian critique of Plato, would make the Megarians, in contradiction to the little which we know of them, to be the advocates of hvva^is, Kivrjais and yevccris. In favour of the first hypothesis, according to which the Megarian philosophers are the el8a>v 0/\ot, it may be urged that Plato, before writing these dialogues, had stood in a rela- tion of close intimacy with Euclides and the Megarian school, and that this passage is a friendly criticism of views with which he himself had at one time strongly sympathized. The name afios, expressing the object of definition, was a common inheritance of the So- cratics, and the tendency of the Megarians to rest in sharply defined, incommunicable ab- stractions, appears not only in the Sophisms of Eubulides but in the objection of Euclides to comparison, of which, as Plato hints in what follows, the An- tisthenean rejection of predica- tion and definition was but the caricature. As Zeno refuted motion by the movement of thought, so they by dialectic made logic impossible. But on the other hand we have no warrant apart from this pas- sage for supposing that they lorce, rc- ceptivity, in ;i word, power. Supposing this to In; ;iuc a7 " e 5 7 e ~ vkcnv 8e aXXore aAAcoy. b 0EAI. yap ovv. i° SE. To 06 67/ KOlV(£>VUV, CO iravrtov apiCTTOl, TL departed so far from the Ele- atics as to admit a plurality of C1S77. Euclides said that Being, or the Good, was one, though called by many names. And se- veral points in the description are favourable to the view to which we have seen reason to incline, which differs but slightly from those of Ueber- Aveg and of Mr. Grote : that Plato, while developing his own theory of knowledge with greater clearness, administers a gentle reproof to some of his own followers, who held tenaciously to a conception of the e"i8rj, based on immature statements of his own, and mixed with Eleatic and Pytha- gorean elements. (See the In- troduction to the ' Sophist.') The points which make for this conclusion are the following: — vo-qra cirra not dcrmpaTa e'l8r] (246 b) ; a-a/iari — SY alcrdi'jo-ems Koivoivdv 8ia \oyixf] 7rp6i ty]v ovtcos ova-'iav — de) Kara ravra coo-auras *X UV ( 2 4-8 b) ; the WOl'ds a> ndvTCOV apiUTOi, which might well be aimed at friends and pupils by Plato (cf. Theset. 148 b : "Apiara y dv6pa>- 7rcov, 6} 7rai8es) " and eytb 8e tcreuj 8ia crvvrjdeiav, supposing Plato to speak here as if in his own per- son : also fip.epu>Tepoi supra. 2. Teveaiv, ttjv 8e ovalav] Cf. SUpr. 221 e : vcvo~tikov pepovs, to 8e 7re£ov, and note. This omission of pev, like many other idioms which might ap- pear to be of late growth, is found already full-blown in Homer. 5. u-wpaTi] Dat. of the in- strument, answering to -fyvxfi in what follows. yeveaet] Dat. after KOiva- vfiv, answering to npos — ovo-lav. 7. yeve&iv 8e] The end of the sentence reverts to the begin- ning, turning out the obverse side of the chief statement, as so often in Plato. IO. To 8e 8r] KOivooveiv] The introduction of this word, which plays an important part in the sequel, should be noticed, as the emergence of a fresh ele- ment in the evolution of the thought. Cf. Gorg. 464 c. And see Rep. 6, 490 b. 2CXM2TH2. vzi 248. tovO' v/jLcis eV dp.(f)oiv Xe'yeiv (pcopev ; dp ov to i/0i> 5t; Trap rjpcov prjOev ; 0EAI. TottoIov; SE. YlaOrjpa ?; iro'irjpa e/c 8vvap.ea)9 twos oltto twv irpos aXXrjXa ijvvwvTcov yiyvoptevov. Ta^ ow, w QeaiTTjTe, avT&v ttjv Trpo? ravra airoKpicnv av piev ov KaraKovei9, eyco 8e 'laws 8id avvrjOeiav. 0EAI. TtV ow 81) Xeyovai Xoyov ; c iH'E. Ou orvyxfopovo-LV rjpuv to vvv 8rj pr/Oev irpbs tovs yrjyeve'is overlap ire pi. 0EAI. To Trolov ; aE. \kclvov eOepev bpov irov tcov ovtcov, otolv to) iraprj rj tov irdcryeiv 77 8pav kou irpos to crpuKpoTaTOV 8vvapas ; GEAI. Not. SE. E[/)oy 5?) Tama To8e Xeyovaiv, otl yeviaet ptev pi€T€o~TL tov irda\etv /cat iroitiv 8vvdpec£>s, irpos 8e ovalav tovtcov ov8eTtpov ttjv 8vvap.LV dppLOTTeiv (pacriv. I. eV a^Kpotv] Sc. yereffecos (cat ovaias. 4. eK Suwi/xecos Ttfos yiyvo- lievov] The account of sensation in the Thesetetus belongs to the line of thought which is here indicated : only the " power" is not there inferred from the act — since agent and patient are regarded as having no ex- istence except in act. Theast. 157 a: °^ Te jup Koiovv earl rt irp\v av tc3 iraax^vTi tjvveXdrj, ovre ndcrxou, 7rp\v av rw tvoiovvti. 7. 8ca (rvvrjdeiav ] If the Stranger is speaking in his own person, these words may naturally enough point to the contemporary Eleatics, i. e. the school of Megara. But if Pla- tonists are meant, the author must be supposed to speak from behind the mask ; as happens sometimes in the Laws. Cf. Kep. 9, 583. 16. Cti yev. — (paaiv] "That Be- coming has part in the power of doing and suffering, but that active and passive are qua- lities whose force is wholly inapplicable to being." The meaning of Swa^eas here is something between " power of acting " and " the power that is inherent in action." 18. rfjv 8vvap.1v] The word appears to be used here in a slightly different sense from fall of change. Well, fair sirs, but what is thi common nature of which ye 5 too apeak, under the name of ' participa- tion?' Shall we explain this by the definition which we just now gave to your oppo- nents, as an active or passive energy- arising from some power ? j - The Stran- ger's prac- tised ear discerns that from theirserene height they reply with scorn. Be- coming may have part in agency and passivity : but such language is inappli- cable to Being. 128 IIAATQNOS Without question- ing the propriety of this, we ask a fur- ther ques- tion : ' Whether the soul knows, and whether Being is known V On their assenting to this, we persevere : ' Is there agency, or passivity, or both, in knowing, or in being known 1 ?' They must of course say, 'Nei- ther.' They will, however, 0EAI. Ovkovv Key ova l rt ; p. 248 HE. Ylph? o ye XtKTtov y/xiu otl oeopeOa Trap avrwv en TTvOeaOat aa(j)eaTepoi>, ei 7rpoaopoXoyov(rL d ttjv fxev \j/v)(i]i> yiyvaxjKeiv, ttjv o* ovaiav yiyvm- 5 (TKecrOou. 0EAI. <&ao-\ prjv tovto ye. SE. Ti oY ; to yiyvtoo-Ktiv rj to yLyimcrK€0~6ai (fia.T6 TTOirjpa i] iraOos rj apcjyorepov ; rj to peu ttol- 07] pa, to oe Odrepov ; ?} iravTamaaLV ovherepov ov- Serepov tovtwv peTa\ap(3dv€ii> ; SrjAov coy ovSt'repou ouderepov' Tavavrla yap av rcuy e\nrpoaQev Xeyoiev. GEAI. Mav0dva>. SE. To <5e d>9 to yiyvcoaKEiv eXirep eo~Tai iroteiv bwdfieas immediately preced- ing, and more akin to the common one of " nature," "im- port," " meaning." Cf. Rep. 6, 511 e. 8. rj d/KpoTepov] I. e. Are the mind and the object of the mind each at once active aud passive in knowledge 1 Spinoza postulates the acti- vity of mind, cf.Eth.II. Deff. 3. Explic. : " Dico potius concep- tum quam perceptionem, quia perceptions nomen indicare videtur mentem ab objecto path At conceptus actionem mentis exprimere videtur." 13. For to be, or to be ye (sc. (palev av, cf. (flare — av — Xe'yoiev supr.), cf. Legg. 3,676 c : dcf> ov 7ro\eis t elo~\ k.t.X., boKew civ irore KaravoTjo-ai xpovov nXijdos oaov ye- yovev ; Ovkovv pabiov ye ovbapais. T6 8e ye,, <° s anXerdv re nai dprj- Xavov av e'lrj. lb. I, 640 : t6 fikv yap — as 6p6bv ap^ovra eivai, uavOdveis. lb. 5, 735- For the continuation of the in- direct form, cf. also Theret. 171 d: r) Kal ravrrj paXtora lara- o~6ai [sc. (paipevj rbv Xoyov. There is some difficulty about the arrangement of the speakers. Rejecting the read- ing of Stephanus and Hein- dorf, 6. brfXov — Xeyoiev. £?. Mavddvoo robe ye, we have to choose between that of the Zurich editors, 3. bijXov — Ae- yciev. 6. Mav6dva>. 3. To be ye — (or to be), where the Stranger answers his own ques- tion, as in Legg. 10, 894 a : tjvlk av t'l nddos fi • brjXuv ' to be ye — , in which, before proceeding further, he accepts Thesetetus' report of the an- swer of the elbebv cp!\oi. The former is more in keeping with Plato's later manner, and makes the anacoluthon easier. It has, therefore, been retained. 13. to yiyvwo-Keiv Trao-^eii/] The distinction between the 2CXM2TH2. 129 248. ti, to yiyvcoo-KopLevov dvayKalov av ijvpLfialveL ira- e cryeLV. ttjv ovoriav hr) /caret tov Xoyov tovtov yiyvco- crKopLevrjv vtto ttjs yvcocreco?, KatT oaov yiyvcoaKerai, Kara toctovtov KLvelaOat Slol to irao-yew, o drj (fiapLtv ovk av yeve'crOai irepl to ypepLodv. GEAI. 'OpOm. SE. T7 Se irpos Aioy ; chs dX^Ocos KLvqcrLV koll farjv Kai ^rv\r)v koll (ppovrjcriv 1) paSlto? 7T€La0r)a6- pLeOa Tffl 7T0LVTe\(OS OVTL pLT) TTOLptLVOLL, pLl]§6 {rjV CLVTO 249. pLr]8e (Ppovelv, dXXa, aepLvov koll dyLov, vovv ovk e^ov, aKLVYjTOV CCTT09 eivOLL ', 0EAI. &uvov p.(vT av, co Ijeve, Xoyov avyyco- polpLev. SE. 'AAAa vovv pc€v e)(€LV, £tor)v 8e pLt], (pcopev ; GEAI. KaiTrwss HE. 'AAAa Tama \x\v dpLfpoTepa ivovT avTco XeyopLev, 01) pLyv iv ^v\fj ye (pr/cropLev avTO eytLV active and passive verb, which probably appears here for the first time in Western litera- ture, is used to suggest that knowledge is a movement or process of some kind. Compare the use made of the grammati- cal distinction of ovopa and pqpa below, p. 262, and of the singu- lar and plural numbers above, p. 238. IO. aepvbv Kai ayiov\ There is an allusion to the statues of the gods. Cf. Phsedr. (of paintings) : ecrr^Ke pev cos ££>vtci, eav 8 avepr) ti, o~epv(bs iravv aiya. Phileb. 24, 53 d. Tim. 30b. These words are wrongly con- nected by some interpreters with vovv. (e. g. Hegel, Cousin.) For the thought, compare a striking passage in the Laws, 967 a-e, where it is said that the deepest study of astro- nomy, instead of encouraging the notion of a blind neces- sity, leads directly to the sup- position of a celestial mind or minds : viratTTeveTo to vvv ovtcos dedoypevov, oaoi tjjs dicpi- fteias qvtwv tjtttovto, onus pi'jTTOT av ctyv)(a bvra ovtcos et? aKpl- fteiav davpao-Tols \oyio-po7s av ixpr]To, vovv pr) KeKTi]peva, where the same result is reached a posteriori which is here ap- proached a priori. 11. elvai] "Exists," in the emphatic sense. make tlii.s hypo- thetical ad- mission, that, if to know is activity, to lie known 5 must be passivity. In which case.Being, in so far as it is the object of knowledge, is passive, and there- fore in this respect, is not at rest, but in mo- tion. And, the instant we touch on this con- r . ception, there is borne in upon us the convic- tion that Perfect Being can- not be in a 130 IIAATONOS state of Ilirlv nega- tive repose, a sacred form without thought, or life, or soul, or motion. For, as there is no thought without a soul, so that which has soul cannot be devoid of motion. Hence motion is insepara- ble from thought. But, on the other hand, thought is equally impossible without a principle of perma- nence and rest. 0EAI. Kou tlv av erepou eypi Tpbirov ; p. 249 S?E. 'AAA« Sfjra vovv ptev kcu <^coi]v kcu i\rvyr)V, CLKivrjTov fxevroL to 7rapa.7rai>, eu\j/V)(ov bv, ecrTuvai ; 0EAI. Ylavra epoiye aXoya tolvt eivai (f)aiveTai. h 5 3*E. Kat to Kivovpevov oV; /cat KLwqtriv avyxcopr)- T€OU CO? OVTOL. 0EAI. Urn 8 ov; SE. &ivfi(3alv€i 6" ow, co QeaiTr]T€, aKivrjTcov re ovtcov vovv prfic-vi irep\ p.r)8c-vo? elvac p.rj8ap.ov. 10 GEAI. KopLiSfj ptev ovv. SE. Kat ixrjv eav av (pepopeva roll KivovpLeva ttolvt eivai o-vy\copcop.ev, kcu tovtco tco Xoyco tcwtov tovto €K tcov ovtcov itjaiprjcropLev. GEAI. ILSy; *5 2JE. To /cara Tama /cat tocravTcos /cat 7repl to avTO 8ok€l croc x w /°^ crTaoreca? yevecrOai ttot av ; c GEAI. OvSapm. SE. Tt 6" ; avc-v tovtcov vovv KaOopa? bvTa rj yevoptevov av /cat ottovovv ; 1. exoi] " In what other way could Being hold them ] " This sense of e^oi is deter- mined by ex*iv preceding and the accusatives following. 3. aKtvrjTov — ep^vxov ov] The cogency of this argument is best seen by comparing Phaedr. 245 c, Legg. 10, 895 b, c. See also Arist. Eth. Nic. X. 8, of the life of the gods : aXka pr/P Ijjv ye iravres vneiXrjcpapev av- tovs Kcu evepyelv cipa' ov yap 8r) KaBevbeiv cocnrep tov '~Ev8vpicova. Metaph. XI. 1072 b : kcu far) 8e ye xmdpxei' rj yap vov evepyeia 5. o-vyxoiprjTeov ut ovra] There appears to be a logical inver- sion in reasoning from " Being has motion" to " Motion has Being." This, like many of Plato's arguments, had the Organon then existed, would have taken a different form. But his thoughts would have been substantially the same. 8. 8' ovv] " It follows from this, however." Thesetetus is warned to face the consequence of his admission : and this is implied in the adversative 6V. 1 2. ravrov tovto] Sc. vovv. 15. To koto. TavTa] " Do you think that permanent unity of condition and mode and sub- ject could ever arise without stability?" 20cM2TH2. 131 249- OEM. "HtacrTa. aE. K.gu firju 7rpo? ye tovtov ttolvtL Xoyco [xaye- Teoi>, by av eiriaT-qpL-qv ?) (fipovrjaiv ?) vovv dcfjavltcov Icr^vpt^rjTaL irepl tlvos birrjovv. 0EAI. ?(p68paye. £?E. Tw 8r] (f)L\ocr6(f)a) kou Tama fidXiara tl- fxavTL Tracra, cos* eoiKev, avdyKrj did Tama fxrjre tcov ev r) Ka\ ra 7roXXa eldrj Xeyomcov to irdv eaTtjKos d d7roSe')(€cr0ai, tcov re av iravTayr) to bv klvovvtcov fir)de to irapairav aKoveiv, dXXa KaTa tyjv tcov iral- Hence the philoso- pher, with whom thought is the highest being, can listen 10 wholly nei- ther to the i. "Hiao-ra] This was one clear result of the argument of the Thesetetus. Cf. also Crat. 440. 2. Trpos ye tovtov — paxereov, os av] Cf. Theset. 265 e : tovto (tovtov, Ast. CODJ.) fifj dnoSexa- p.e6a, bs civ Ae'yi?. 3. bs av — lo-xvpl^rjTacl Not merely because of the value of thought and knowledge, but because such a person stulti- fies himself. This is implied in the form of expression. " He who putting knowledge out of sight yet dogmatizes on any point." See Theret. 161, Euthyd. 286, alib. a. nAATQNOS ■■■ of O -I ■ of motion Init must s;ts with the chil- dren, that " both are best," when lie is de- fining the nature of Being. But he cannot rest there. 8cov ev^v oara aKivTjTa kul K(Kiv7]//.eva to bv re kul p. 249 to irav ^vvufx(j)OT€pa Xeyeiv. 0EAI. Wi-jOeo-TCLTa. HE. T7 ovv; dp ovk eVriet/cwsr rj%] ^aiv6p.e6a 7T€- 5 pi€i.\i](J)ei>ai Tcp Xoyco to bv; 0EAI. Haw p.ev ovv. HE. Bafiai ptevT \av\ apa, (0 QeatTrjTt, coV p.01 SoKovptev vvv auTov yvcoaeaOai nepi ttjv anropiav 777? o-Keyj/eoos. e 10 0EAI. Ylcos av koll t'l tovt elprjKas; HE. 'O pLCLKGCpie, OVK iwOUS OTL VVV €0~pL€V €V ayvoia tyj nXe'ccrTr} irep\ avTOv, (pa.Lv6pt.e6a 8e tl Ae- yuv rjpuv avTo'is ; 0EAI. 'E/MOi yovv' oirrj 5' av XeXr/Oapiev ovtcos 15 e'xpvTes, oi) Travv ^vvbqpu. cf. Rep. 5, 540 d : p) ™XV 5oK ff ehai 6 \6yos) : or perhaps to some common form of expres- sion in which they desired all things in the universe, move- able and immoveable, — or, it may be, " sacred and pro- fane," KivTjTa Kill dia.vT]Ta, what may and what may not be touched or stirred. 2. Xeyeiv] Bodl. Xeyei. 7. Ba/3al fjievr Tav'f apa\ av here is probably corrupt : pev- Tot, which some object to, is quite in point. The only way in which to make anything of av would be to take it, by a rather bold hyperbaton, with the future infinitive : which is out of the question. And it is better to reject av than to read, as Stallbaum suggests, fxevT av apa. Badham conjectures BaftaL- ov uevrapa co QeairrjTe' cos uoi 8okovu€V vvv avrov yevrjaeadai 7rep\ ttjv dnopiav rrjs o-Ke^ecos. But for j3aj3al — cos 8oKovp,ev, cf. Rep. 2, 361 d, /3«/3ai — co <£. TX., coy eppcopevcos k.t.A. I propose merely to omit av, which has probably crept in front supra a, Aeivov pevr av, and render, "Ah me ! on the contrary, Thesetetus, how I fear that Ave shall only now begin to know the diffi- culty of the question about Being." IO. IIcos av Ka\ tl tovt e"pr]Kas] The form of this question determines the punctuation of the more frequent form, 7ro>s « tovt etwes ' } not 7rcos ; tl tovt elnes ; 14. 'Eciot yovv] Sc. (paivofxedd ti Xeyet)/. ovtcos exovres] Sc. iv dyvoia tji Tr\ei(TTr) ovres. 20MFTH2. 133 p. 249. HE. 2K07T€i 8j] aacpe'crTepov, el Tama vvv £vv- 0. 250. opioXoyovvTes SiKalcti? av eirepa>Tr)6elpev direp clvtol totc rjpciiTco/xeu rovs Xeyovras eivai to ttolv Oepfxbv kou ^v\pov. 0EAI. Ilcua ; VTropvrjcrov p.e. HE. Yldvv pev ovv kou 7re1pa.aop.al ye Spav tovto epcoTcov ae KaOdirep eKelvov? Tore, Iva ap.a ti kou 7rpotcop.ev. 0EAI. 'Op0m. HE. JLlev 8r), Kivqaiv kou o~Tacriv dp ovk ivav- TicoTaTa Xeyeis dAXrjAois ; 0EAI. ITwy yap ov ; HE. Kou p,r)i> eivai ye 6/xotW (f)f)S dp.OV T11V T€ -)]l> (TvXXa(3u)l/, KOU UTTlScOV UVTCOU 7TpO? TT)V ttjs ovaius KOLVtoviav, ovtoos tivou Trpoareiire'i dfi(f)6- repa ; 5 GEAI. Ku>Svi>evopL€i> coy aArjOco? rplrov dirojxav- c reveaOai ri to ov, otolv klvyjo-lv kou ardaiv dvai Xeycofieu. HE. Ovk dpa KLvr)cris kou ardor is iarl £vvap.§o- repov to ov, aAA' krepov 8rj tl tovtcov. w 6EAI. "Eoikcv. SE. Kara tt)v clvtov (f)vcnv dpa to ov ovre earr]- K€V 0VT6 KlVeiTtU. 0EAI. 2 X 6 ^. 3E. Hot Br) XPV T W Bidvoiav en rphruv rov rfj yjsv)(rj e\0VTes Trapdheiypa. Theset. 155 ^ • Tavra br), oipai 6poXoyr)para Tpla pdxerai iv rjj rjperepa ^i/*??. I. ok in ineivov tt)v re crrd- criv Ka\ tt)v Kivrjaiv Trept.e)(op6vr]v crvWaPow] By deleting the comma after Trepiexopevrjv the syntax is improved ; and the inverted order of the words is in keeping with the style of the dialogue. "So then you conceived of Being as a third and distinct kind, under which, as embraced by it, you com- prehended motion and rest, and fixing your attention on their common participation in Being, you thus applied the term 'ex- istent' to them both." 5. dnopavTevcaBaij I. e. This truth of reflection is implied in language. Compare Rep. 6, 505 e ". b drj SicoKei irava ^v^r) dnop.avTevop.tvri rt eivai. 8. Ouk apa — tovtwv] " Being, then, is not motion and rest taken together, but is distinct from these." II. Kara — Kivelrai] In the spirit of the Parmenides it is shewn that Being, which has just been said to include rest and motion, in its own nature neither rests nor moves. For the position of ovk, which is emphatic, cf. Theaet. 161 a : as ovk aii i'xei ovrco ravra. The search for Being seems here to be relinquished as hopeless. The thread of argu- ment is not dropt, however ; for it is this absolute sever- ance of Being from rest and motion, after seeming to in- clude them, which suggests the fresh inquiry concerning the nature of difference or negation. 20M2TH2. 13.' 250. /3oi>Ao/xei>oi> ivapyes tl 7Tfpl avTov nap eavTco /3e- ^T^ 1 * 37E. Oifiat fiev ovSafioae kri pahiov. el yap tl BaLwaaaOai ; «""" ' 7 fchatathing 9EAI. Uol yap ; wl,id ' '» not at rest is not in motion, or fir} Kiveirai, ttcos ov\ eo~Tr)Kev; y to pr)8a/j.Lo? iarross ™ ce ver8& - d 7TCO? OVK av KlVeiTai ; TO Se OV TjfMV VVV e'/CTOy TOVTCOV therefore, - \ we ma y d/j,(PoTe'poov avoir etyavTai. rj SvvaTov ovv tovto ; take note 0EAI. UdvTCDV fiei> OVV dSwaTCOTaTOV . have found ,__, rr\'$ ' /i~ **' » v ' the defini- AE. Tooe tolvvv fivqadrivaL oiKaiov eiri tovtol?. tion of T N „ Being not 0EAI. \.0 7TOLOV; iolessdiffi- Wl? r /r| x v > zj/ v ... cult than Aii. yJTL tov fir) ovtos ep(£>TY]6evTe9 rovvofia e(p that of r, , 5, « , / / ' /) ' ' Not-Being. o ri 7rore oet (pepeLV, iracrr) o-vveo~ypp.eva airopia, whence z we derive fJL€/JLV7)0-aL ; a sort of /2*"C A T TT" v * despairing WJiiAl. Uw? ya/) oy; hope, that ^"C n/r" ? » »\ ' ' ~ » \ > / iY a ray of Aii<. Mcoj> ow ez/ eAaTTOvi tlvl vvv ecrpev airopia. 15 fight u least - _ \ % »/ on the one e TTepi TO OV, perplexity, GEAI. 'E/xoi /xeV, w £eVe, el SvvaTov elirelv, ev l^Ysoiu" HE. ToOro /xeV tolvvv evTavOa KelaOco dLrjTroprj- ^ome t^The fxevov eVetS?) 8e e£ tcrov to re ov /cat to fit) ov airo- "^f^to I. ivapyes tl] Cf. Zvapym, this, but the following remark, supr. p. 242 c. for which this prepares the way. Trap eavrai] Cf. Theost. 1 46 I 2. o-ni/eo-^o/xe^a ajropi'a] Supr. e : Xafielv 'iKavcos nap' e/xaur<5, 237—239. Cf. Theset. 1 65 b, iv and note. cppeari crwex6u.evos, where the 7. dvanecpavTai] " Has risen metaphor is more distinctly up before us." Cf. Theoet. kept in view. 155b: arret ttoV eVrt Tavra ra 18. cpaivofieQa] For the el- (pdo-pLaTa iv Tjj T/fierepa ^vxjj. lipse, cf. Theset. 172 c: Ovkovv Supr. 231 b : iv t 2d>KpciTes. 2. -irapcKpavevTi. Meno 85 d : dva- &aivop,e6a. KeKivrjvTai al boi-ai avrai. 1 9. §ir)noprip.£vov\ "A diffi- II. "On tov firj Svtos] These culty clearly stated." The words are in construction with word occurs in Plato in this fiepvrjo-ai. The thing which is technical sense only in the "worth taking note of" is not Sophist, Politicus, and Laws. 1536 IIAATQN02 steer the li.-nL of ..in discourse between this Scylla and that Chary bdia with as little dis- grace as may be. pia? /j.€TeiArj(f)aTOv, vuv k\ir\p.€@a, tov yovv Xoyov, p. 251. 5 07rr]7rep av 6101 re cofiev eimpeirlcrTaTa, Sioicro/JLeOa OVTC09 d/uL(f)ow dfia. 2. eire djAvdpoTfpov e'lre cra- (peo-Tepov'] The latter is chiefly meant, but the former is in- troduced in accordance with Plato's wish to omit no aspect of a case. Cf. Rep. 1, 339 b: ovrra> 8ij\ov old' el peydXrj. 5. diacropeda] " We shall fend off our argument from both :" " Steer clear of them," as between Scylla and Cha- rybdis, or the Symplegades. (Cf. Horn. Od. 12, 219: (ktos eepye vrja.) Compare the use of bia>6eiodai in Herodotus and in Democr. Fr. Ethic. 20 : kol ovk oXlyas Krjpas ev rco /3tw Siaxreai, (pBovov Ka\ £/?Xoz> (cat dvapfULTjv. The construction, however, is different here, and has driven the editors to con- jecture — Heindorf Siootjoneda, Stallbaum biacr6pe6a, C. F. Hermann 8ia6t]cr6peda. Of these Stallbaum's correction is the best, although not agreeing well with evTrpenea-Tara. But the construction may be de- fended, if we take the words to mean literally " We shall push our argument (vessel) through between them both (or, so as to avoid both at once) with such appearance as we may." The genitive dpcpoiv is then governed by the 81a in composition. Cf. Polyb. 22. IX, 17 : 8ia>6. rat craplo-aas 8ia Twv rp-qpdrav. Badham defends the text on slightly different grounds. His note deserves insertion here : "Juxta difficile esse ostendit, id quod est atque id quod non est explicare. Hinc auguratur, si quid lucis utrivis horum ali- cunde accedat, fore etiam ut alteram discerni possit : sin arnbo in tenebris maneant, quid turn ] Disputationem, servabimus, dispo?ie?nus, per- sequemur ? Imo, ita repelle- mus, ut si quis ex ejus quod non est natura negotium nobis facessit, eundem in eo quod est baud minus sibi contradi- centem efficianius. Accedit quod cum hoc verbo et hac sententia evTrpeireo-TaTa egregie convenit, at non cum con- traria notione, quae conjecturis supra commemoratis inest : parum enim hospitem Eleati- cum Sophistis infensum dece- ret speciosam disputationem promittere." It may be enough in order to defend our interpre- tation from this last objection to refer the student to Theae- tetus 196 e, where the con- fession of shamelessness is immediately followed by an avowal of the determination to continue the argument, and to infr. 254 d, supr. 241 d, especially the word (3iaCeo-dat. The unattainableness of a per- fectlyj " reasoned" method is 20M2TH2. IS7 ). 251 9EAI. K«Ac3y. £*E. Aeycopev 8r) kclO* ov tlvcl irore rpoirov iroX- Xols bvopacrL tclvtov tovto eKaarore Trpoaayopevopev. 0EAI. Qilov 87) tl\ TrapdSeiy/jLa elire. SE. Ae'yo/JL€i> avdpaiirov 8r) ttov 7roAA' clttcl eVo- j i'o/nd{pi>T€s, tcl re -)(p(Dpara iiriXpepovTts clvtco kcll to. a^rjpara kcll /xeyeOi] kcll /ca/c/ay kcll apeTas, ev oiy b ivacn kcll irepoL? fivploi? ov povov avOpwirov clvtov dvaL (pape'v, dXXa kcll dyaOov kcll erepa a7reipa, kcll rclkXa 8r) Kara tov clvtov Xoyov ovtoo? ev 6kclcttov II. b. 3. 1 •■. ; 1 1 1 1 I 1 1 . ■ mean l>y giving many names to one thing : as white, tall, good, bad, to man : whereby we afford excellent diversion , to the wits of youth, continually rising up before Plato. 2. ttoWoIs ovopacri raliTou tovto'] This recals the saying of Euclides, that the good was ev, 7roXXoTs ovopacri KaXovpevov, and in so far confirms the impression that the Megarians have been under criticism in what precedes. In this and other expressions they had perhaps implied a "commu- nion" of unity with variety, which was inconsistent with their logical principles. Com- pare also the saying quoted in Republic 6, 505 c, probably from the same source, that to ayaObv is cppovrjo-is dyaBov, whose authors failed in their attempt to isolate the concep- tion of good. We are now introduced to a new sort of philosophers, who serve (like the Si/cr^pei? of the Philebus) to reduce those just mentioned to the point of ab- surdity, and by a crucial in- stance to bring the question to a clear issue. They are the same who are ridiculed in the Euthydemus, and amongst them Antisthenes is most pro- bably included, whether or not the word oyjnpadeo-i and the phrase vno nevias r. t. (p. kt. are meant to convey a co- vert allusion to him. The passage certainly reads like personal satire. Compare Phi- lebus, pp. 13, 14, where a dif- ferent aspect of the same "child- ish puzzle" is described, and contrasted with the dialectical One and Many ; as also in Parm. 129 c,d. See also Phileb. 37 c. Cognate difficulties re- specting Predication are noticed by Aristotle, Phys. I. 2, § 15: 01 pev to ecrTiv acpel\ov, ao-jrep AvKo(pp(oV ol he tt)v Xegiv peTep- pvdpi^ov, oti 6 avBpamos ov \ev- kos eo~Tiv, dXka \e\evKCOTat,' — iva prj — 7roXXa elvai notcbo-i to ev. For eo-rrovhanocnv infra, cf. supr. 216 b : t5>v nepl Tas e'pihas eo-rrovhaKOTcov. 3. tovto ] I. e. " Anything which happens to be in ques- tion." Cf. Thea?t. 199 a: p) yap e^eiv T h v (TfiaTTjprjv tovtov alov re, and note. 138 IIAATQN02 and of oer- fiin an- (ii-iit t \ rns. w ho, from their po- verty in the having of wisdom, take pride in crying out upon ns that we have made the one many and the many one. They will allow us to say that good is good, and man is man: but not that man is good. Such are the refine- ments on which they spend a be- lated en- thusiasm. To omit no aspect of thought on the subject of Being, we address to these, as well as to the rest, the follow- ing ques- tion : Shall we conceive v7ro0e/jL€i>oi irdXiv avrb TroXXa koll iroXXols ovofiacri p. 251 Xeyoptei/. 0EAI. 'AAt?^ Aeye«. SE. 'QQev ye, olfiai, tols re veois koll twv yepov- $ts dhvvaTOV ra re iroXXtx ev koll to ev noXXd elvai, koll 8rj ttov \aL- povtJLv ovk ewvres dyadov Xeyeiv dvOpanrov, dXXa to fxev ayaOov ayaOov, tov 8e avOpcoirov dvOpcoTrov. c 10 evTvyyaveLS yap, (6 QealrrjTe, coy eycp/xat, 7roAAa/a9 to. roLavTa ecnrovSaKoaiv, evloTe 7rpeafivT€pOLS- dv- 0pa>7TOL9, /cat i>7To irevias Trjs 7repl (ppovrjaLv KTTjaeCOS 1 tol roiavTa TeOavpLaKOCTL, /cat Srj tl /cat 7rdao-o(pov olofievoLs tout avTO dvevpr/Kevai. 15 0EAI. Ilaj>i> fiev ovv. SE. '\va to'lvvv irpos diravTas rjfXLv 6 Xoyo? fj tov? 7rco7roTe 7repi ovala? koll otlovv 8taXe\6evTa?, eaTco /cat 7rpb? tovtovs /cat irpbs tovs aXXov?, oaoL? d epirpoaQev 8LeLXey/j.e0a, Ta vvv d>? ev epcoTrjaei XeyOrj- loabfxeva. GEAI. Ta 7rota drj ; SE. HoTepov firjTe ttjv ovalav KLvqcrei /cat o~Tao~et irpoadTTTa>p.ev firjTe aXXo aAAco p,rj8ev p,r)8evL, dXX 12. nevlas — KTrjcrean'] Geni- tive of respect : " Poverty in respect of the possession of knowledge." The tautology has been objected to, but might be paralleled from many pas- sages in these dialogues. Some passages in the Memorabilia and Symposium of Xenophon make it probable that these words contain a personal allu- sion to Antisthenes. r»7? nepl ttjv (ppovrjcriv kttj- crecos] Cf. Polit. 28 1 e: ttjs nepl ra dpfpuapara yevicreass. 13. iru(T(TO(pov olopevois] Cf. Phsedo 90 C : o'iovrai rarot yeyovevat re kcu KaravevorjKiPat povoi OTi ovre tS)P Trpaypdrcov ovdevos ovdev vyies ovre ra>v \6ya>v. 1 8. earroo] Sc. Xeyopeva, from ra — \ex6r)0~6peva infra. 2CXM2TH2. 139 351. a>s a/JLiKTa ovtol Koii dfivvarov peraXapfidveLv dXXij- Xcov ovrcos aura ev rots Trap r\\uv Xoyois riOcopev ; 77 Trdvra els ravrov fjvvdyoopev cos* Sward eTriKOivco- vetv dXXrjXois ; ?; ra pev, ra oe pr) ; Tovrwv, co e Qealrrjre, rl iror av avrovs irpoaipelcrOaL (prjaaipev ; 5 0EAI. 'Eyw pev virep avrwv ovSev eyco irpos ravra airoKplvaaOai. rl ovv ov KaO' ev diroKpivo- pevos e'0' eKaarov ra ijvpfialvovra eaKexj/co ; aE. KaAcoy Xeyeis, /cat ri6a>pev ye avrovs Xe'yetv, el (3ouAeL, Trpcorov prjdevl prjSev prjoeplav Svvapiv 10 eyeiv KOivoovlas els prjbev. ovkovv kIvt)cfIs re /cat ardais ovdapfj peOeijerov ovalas ; 252. 0EAI. Ov yap ovv. SE. Tt cV ; earai irorepov avrcov ova las pr/ 7rpoo~KOLva>vovv ; 15 0EAI. Qvk earai. HE. Tayy Sr) ravrrj ye rfj avvopoXoyla Trdvra I. a/MiKTa ovra Kai abvvarov (sc. bv) p,erdKapfidveiv dXXjjXcoi'] The sentence changes to the impersonal form. dovi/aTov Bodl. AIL Cett. ddivara. 6. 'Eyco pev — KaXcos Xf-yeij] ' 'Persons sic distribuendse : 'E-yco jxev — diroKp'ivaaOai : Tt ovv — e'crse- •fya : KaXaJs \eyeis : Kai riB&piv y avrovs k.t.X. Hie, ut ubique, respondentis partes Theoeteto tribuuntur : sed fraud em fecit librariis initium sermonis koi ridco/jLev ye, qui abruptior illis visus est, non animadvertenti- bus Hospitis verba ex iis quae supra dixerat continuari." Bad- ham. Perhaps : but ko\ nda- fiev ye k.t.X. seems too abrupt in the rejoinder, and in point of fact it is the Stranger who now proceeds to "give each answer in succession. 7. 7-t ovv ov] " Suppose you say Yes to each alternative in turn, and see what follows in each several case." 10. pydevl] Governed by koi- vaviaSi 1 1 . eis firfievl " For any re- sult." 1 4. earai irorepov avrS>v] " Can either of them be, without par- ticipating in Being 1 " 17. Ta X v8}i] Compare Theset. 183 a, where the assertion of absolute relativity is similarly reduced to nothingness (to 8 y cos e'oiKev, e(pavt], el Trdvra Kivelrai. irdo-a dnoKpio-is, nepl orov av tis aTVOKpivrjrai, Sfiolcos dpdrj eivai, ovra r e\eiv (pdvat Ka\ /at) ovrco), and ibid. 161 e. Trdvra dvdarara yeyovev] ol I;. in Motion, Kest, and .•ill other bhij] muni c;il)le witli each o1 hter I Or shall wo bring all into com- munion indiscrimi- nately? Or, thirdly, shall we say that some have, and others have not, commu- nion ? If we adopt the first hypothesis, Motion and Rest are non-exist- ent, for they have no commu- nion with Beinor 140 IIAATQNOS Thus havoc is made .-it once of all bhephiloso- phieswhich attribute Being to Motion, or to Rest, « bether as One or Many. And all theories of compo- sition or division, whether into an in- finite or a fixed num- ber of ele- mental forms, whe- ther the union and partition are con- ceived as alternating or as ever going on together, are equally avaarara yeyovev, a>? eotKev, apa re tcov to irav p. 252 KLVOVVTCOV KCLL TCOV to? eV LaTCCVTCOV KOU OCTOL KOLT elSi] to. ovtcl Kara raura diaavTcos eypvTa eivai (f)acriv aet' irdvTes yap ovtol to ye eivai irpoadirTovaiv, 01 pev 5 ovtlos KiveiaQai XeyovTes, oi 8e ovtcos eo~TX]K0Ta eivai. 0EAI. KopiSjj pev ovv. SE. Kat prjv Kai oaoi tote pev ^vvTiOeaai to. h ttccvto, tot€ 8e Siaipovcriv, ehe eis ev kou ifj evo9 lodireipa e'vre eh irepas eyovTa GTOiyeia hiaipovpevoi kou e\ tovtcov crvvTiOevTes, bpoltos pev edv ev pepei tovto TiOcoai yiyvopevov, bpoicos 8e Kai eav del, KaTa irdvTa Tama Xeyoiev dv ovde'v, ehrep prjdepla ecrTi &ppi£is. 15 0EAI. y O P 0m. HE. "Et£ Toivvv dv auTol iravTcov KaTayeXaaTO- TaTa peTLOiev tov Xoyov oi prjdev ecovTes Koivcovia 7ra8rjpaT0$ eWepov OaTepov irpocrayopeveiv. " All theories are hopelessly unsettled," or " swept away." " The ground is cut away from all." 1. apa T€ t5>v\ Qu. an le- gend, rd ? 2. bs ev i(TTavTCiv\ Sc. to ttuv. Kar ei'617] " In several ab- stract forms." 8. Kai iitjv] This sentence refers Avholly to Empedocles (cf. ev pepei) and Heraclitus (cf. dei), as Heindorf justly ob- serves, unless some of the earlier Ionians (e. g. Anaxime- nes) are included in the words f'| ivos cineipa. 12. Kara navra Tavra] These words resume the preceding clauses eure — crvvTi.6evTes, opolcos — dei. " In all or any of these modes their theory is nothing worth." 16. "En toivvv] Cf. Euthyd. 303 d : Kai rdSe av erepov dijpo- tlkov ti Kai ivpqov ev toIs Xdyots" onoTav CprjTe prjre KaXov eivai prj- 8ev prjTe aya86v npdypa prjre k.t.X. — tVTes\ " Who forbid us to call anything, be- 20M2TH2. 141 252. 0EAI. n«y; c SE. T&> re etVcu irov irepi irdvra a.vayKo£pvTcu XPwOaL KCU TU> Xddpis KCU TCp aXXcOV KCU T(p KOtO' avTO kcu uvplois {repots, (hv a.Kpare'i? ovre? eipytaOai kcu firj avvanrreiv eV toI? Xoyoi? ovk aXXcou deovrai 5 7W e^eXeytjovTcois, dXXa to Xeyofieuov oiKoOev tov iroXejiLov kcu ivavTLCdaouevov e\ovTts, evrbs virofyOey- yopLtvov wcnrep tov oltottov Ei)jOi>/cAea, irepKpepovres del TTopevovrcu. undone, ii all combi- nation is denied. But the most com- plete dis- comfiture attends the enemies of predication themselves. For they cannot help applying to the subject of their cause partaking of some affec- tion from another thing, by the name of that other." koiv. ira6. (t. = koiv. tov nda^eiv i(p' er. Cf. SUpr. 245 a : 7rd#os tov ivos i'xfiv. (18.) hepov is governed by na- BrjiMiTos. Similar language occurs in the passage of the Philebus already cited, p. 13 a : on 7rpo- crayopeveis avra, dvopoia ovto, eTepw, cprjaopev, ovopaTi. 2. T<5 re ehai 7rov] Cf. Theast. 157 b, 196 e, 202 a. 3. ciWav] Qu. an legend. d'Wrj'Kcov 1 4. hv aKpciTels ovres etpyeoSai kcu pr) o-vvciTTTeiv ev to'is Xdyots'] hv is governed by etpyeo-dai, but probably also connected by at- traction with dicpaTels. avv- cmTeiv is used absolutely. " So that having no power to re- frain from such expressions, or to banish connexion from their discourse." 6. dXXd to Xeyopevov] " But they always carry about their enemy, who haunts them, as the saying is, in their own house, and like the wondrous Eurycles, has a voice within them which mocks every syl- lable they utter." Compare Cratyl. 428 c, where the ac- count of self-deception is like that of self-contradiction here : orav yap prj8e apucpbv dnocrTaTf] aXX del 7rapfj 6 i^aTtari-jO'oiv, ttg>s ov h)eivov ; Cf. also Gorg. 482 b : ov croi 6po\oyrjo-fL KoXKiicKtjs, &> KaXhiicKeis, dXXd 8iaCpcovrjO-ei ev anavTi ra /3i'co. 8. tov ciTO-nov Eipu/cXea] (See Aristoph. Vesp. 10 14.) Eury- cles was a ventriloquist pro- phet. This passage seems to imply that he made his voice sound as if from within the person consulting him ; and this is also suggested by the Scholiast's absurd gloss on cltottov '. Tov prj edpaiov dXX' del €KToni£ovTa Xeyet. The story told by the Scholiast, that Eu- rycles suffered from having given an offensive response to some one, is probably a mis- taken attempt to explain the connexion between a>o-irep — Evpv/cXea and ohodev tov iro\e- piov. The meaning of course' is that they have their enemy and their opponent in their own breast, in the shape of a voice, which comes from within them, like the answer of Eury- cles, who used to speak in those 142 IIAATQN02 disoourae Buob words :is " is," '• apart," " from others," " by itself," and have thus an adversary within, who saves our labour by convict- ing them of self-con- tradiction out of their own mouths. But if all things are allowed to have com- munion, Motion will rest and Rest will move. The third case alone remains : that some things enter into combina- tion, and some do not. 0EAI. Ko/judf) Xe'yei? optoiov re /cat aXrjOes. p. 252 aJL. TV <5', av rravra dXXijXoi? eu>p.ev Svvapiv eyeiv e7riKoivcovla? ; 0EAI. Tovto pev 0109 re Kuyco SiaXveiv. 5 HE. U&s; 0EAI. Ort Kivqais re avrrj iravrairaaLV icttcut av /cat araais 1 av iraXiv avrrj klvolto, elrrep e7riyiyvoi~ aOr/v eV aXXr/Xoiv. EE. 'AAAa p.rjv tovto ye rrov reus peyiarai? to avayKais ddvvarov, KLvrjatv re \o~Tau6ai /cat crraaiv KLveiaOai. 0EAI. Xlcos yap ov ; aE. To rpirov 8r) povov Xonrov. 0EAI. Nat. 15 SE. Kat prjv ev ye tl tovtcov dvayKalov, r) rravra e 77 pj)bev rj ra p.ev e'OeXeiv, ra. 8e pr) o-vpplyvvaOai. 0EAI. TIco? yap ov ; HE. Kat p,rjv ra ye 8vo ddvvarov evpeOrj. 0EAI. Nat. 20 37E. rias* apa 6 /3ovXop.evo? 6p6a>s airoKpivecrOai to Xonrov tcov rpicov drjaeL. 0EAI. KopuSr) pev ovv. HE. Ore Sr/ ra pev eOeXei tovto Spav, ra 5' ov, who came to him. Cf. Rep. 7, 52 1 b : otKeto? av Kal evbov 6 toiovtos 7rdXe/ior avrovs re oXXvai Kal tt]v ciW-qv Ttokiv. I. ofxoiov re kci\ akrjdis] "Most true, your image is a very just one." Cf. Rep. 8, 579 d : Uav- raivacTiv, es row dXXwv olov 8ecrp.b? 8id iravrcov KeycoprjKeu, ware dvev Tivbs avrcov dSvvarov dp/jLOTTeiv kou tcdv aXXcov erepov ere pep. GEAI. Kal pdXa ye. 2?E. Has ovv ol8ev biroia ottoiol? Sward kolvcd- veiv, 77 Teyvrjs 8ei tcd p.eXXovTi 8pdv iKavco? avra ; GEAI. Te X v V ?. SE. Ylolas ; GEAI. T77? ypap/iaTiKr}?. dE?E. Tt 8e ; wepl tovs tcov ofjecov /ecu fiapeoov b (fyObyyovs dp ov X ovrcos ; 6 p.ev tovs avyKepavvv- . I ust a of 1 1,. I of the al- phabet some can and others cannot be combined, 5 and the same is true of mu- sical notes. It is also to he ob- served, that the vowels are distin- guished by the power which they have of entering into every combina- tion, and being jc indispen- sable to all. And as none but I. o-yeSov olov ra ypdupara] The example of letters is used to symbolize the nature of the ideas, as in Thea?t. 202 e (where it is shewn that the simple is known before the complex). Polit. 277, 278 (il- lustration of the argument from example). Rep. 3, 402 (education in uovo-ikti). Phileb. 18 (science determining the infinite). In the Theastetus and Philebus the parallel il- lustration from musical notes is also adduced, as here. 5. Ta fie' ye (pwvrjevra olov 8eo-fi6s] In this the vowels symbolize the highest ideas, or categories, Being, Identity, and Difference. Compare Theset. 197 d : in the image of the aviary, evias fie uovas 8ia ttoktcov 07177 av tvx^o-l neroaevas — where the same thing is intimated, and equally without explana- tion. 7. apuorreiv] Neuter verb. 10. lias ovv oldev] Compare Crat. 388 d : nas fie reKTcov rj 6 ttjv re^vrjv eya>p ; 11. 8pav Ikovcos aira] This expression has no distinct an- tecedent. But cf. Theast. 207 d (in a similar connexion), dpcovras avrd, and note. The conjectural emendation, 6po>, is therefore not absolutely re- quired ; though, if such were the true reading, it may easily have been corrupted froni 8pav supr. 252 e. 10. 6 — rexvrjv e'xcov yiyvao~Keiv\ " Who has the art of discern- ing." For the inf., cf. Thea?t. 169 a : v iropev- 10 ea6aL rov 6p9w9 pteXXovra 8ei^etv iroia iroiois avpL- (ficovel twv yevcov kou iroia aXXi]Xa ov Several ; kou 8r) KOU SlOC TTOLVTWV €L awl^OVTa TGLVT earii;, atari, c o-v/xpLiyvvcrOai 8vvard elvai ; kou ttolXlv ev tolls 8iou- pecreaiu, el 81 oXcov erepa tyjs Sicupeaecos alria ; 15 0EAI. Tla>? yap ovk eiricrTy]pa]S 8el, kou a^e86v ye 'lacos rrjs pteylar^s ; 4. rexv&v Kai dre)(via>v] "Arts and defects of art" — which can only be determined by refer- ence to the standard of the corresponding arts. For the mode of expression, which arises from Plato's love of complete statement, Hein- dorf well compares Legg. 2, 653 e : ovk e'xav aiadrjo-iv rS>v iv rais Kivi)afai rd^aov oi8e dra- £i QealrrjTe, Tavrr/v ; rj Trpbs Aib? eXa.dop.eu eis ttjv tcou eXev- Oepcou epjreaovTeg e7r lo-rrjpyv, kcu KiuSvuevopeu ^77- rovvres top o~o§io~Tr\v irporepov dvevpr)Kevai tov (f)i\6o-o(Pov ; 0EAI. Um XeyeLs ; d £?E. To Kara yevrj SiaipelaOai koll fxr/re tclvtov elSo? erepov -qyrjaaadai pLrjre erepov ov ravrbv p.cov ov Trj9 8ia\€KTiKrj? (f)rjcrop.ev 67ricrTr)p.r}? eivai ; 0EAI. Nat, (jyrjaopLev. EE. Ovkovv o ye tovto Svvarb? $pav piav \heav hia 7roXXa>v, eVoy eKacrrov Keipte'vov x a> p' L9 i ^olvtt] 81a- TerapLevrjv LKavcos SLaiaddverai, kou ttoXXols erepas aXXrjXcav virb puag e^oadev irepie)(op,evas, kcu p-iav av Sl oXcov iroXXwv ev ev\ tjvvr]p.p.evr]v, kou noXXas In search- ing foT the Sophi have found tlie philo- sopher, the " Freeman w\ 1 the 5 truth makes free." For dialectic is hie pro- vince, that is, the art by which one form is seen per- 10 vading a scattered multitude, and many distinct forms as contained in one, and again, one j r form com- bined from 2. Ttjv tSiv iXevdepcov] Al- though the Stranger was not present at the conversation of yesterday, he is made to allude to the description of the philo- sophic life which Socrates had then given. Theset. 172, sqq. Such a failure of the dramatic element could have no place in the Charmides, Protagoras, or Phsedrus, and is rather in the manner of the Laws. 7. prjre ravrov eidos erepov — ravrov] This closely corresponds with the account of dialectic in the Phsedrus, 265 d, e. 1 1. Ovkovv — eV i'] Com- pare Phileb. 16 d, e ; Legg. 12, 965 C: ap ovu aKpi^earepa crKe\|n? 6ea r av rvep\ brovovv 6ra>- ovv yiyvoiro rj rb 7rpbs piav Ideav i< ra>v iroKK&v kiu dvopoia>v 8wa- rbv elvai (Shftveiv. 12. evbs eKaarov Keipevov X^P'r] Cf. Tim. 83 c : koX to fiev koivov bvofia wacri tovtois rj Tives rav larpatv ttov -)(okov encavopaaav rj Kai tis &V hwarbs els tvoWcl pev Ka\ dvopoia PXe'neiv, opav §' ev avrols ev yevos evbv d£iov eircovv- plas ndo-i. Phajdr. 265. 15. 81 oXav 7roXXwv] These 146 nAATQNOS manyBuoh vcoph iravrr) hicopurpevas. tovto (V eaTiv, fj 7*6 p. 25I '■ ll „ „ ' fc, V r, / 5J / V Q forms, and Koivcovetv eKaara bvvarai /cat oirr) firj, 6La.Kpi.vuv koto. several , , , universal*, yevos eiritrTatroai. b ^ the C\T? A T TT ' * ? boundaries olhAl. ilavTcaracri pev ovv. of defini- __, > a \ \ v n ' ^ \ N ' "\ \ tion wholly 5 ArL.. AAAa p.i]v to ye otaAeKTiKov ovk aAAco sundered ->/ < > ? n^ ~ /1 ~ v £ ' from all ococrei?, co? eycppou, irA-qv tco Kavaptos re kou oiKaito? This is the (j)lAo(TO(pOVVTL. of the com- 0EAI. IleGc* yap av aAAco 8olr) tls ; munion and incommu- nicableness of kinds. In this sphere the philoso- pher is to be sought HE. Tov pev 8rj (pLA6cro(j)ov iv tolovtco tlvl tottco 10 kcu vvv kcu eireura avevpr/crop.ev, eav QjTcopev, Ibelv p.ev yaAeirov evapyco? kcu tovtov, erepov prjv rpoirov ]}• 254. r\ re tov crocpicrTov ^aAeiroTrj? i] Te tovtov. BEAI. Ucd?; shalTcome *^' '^ ^^ O-TroSLBpaCTKCOV eh TT]V TOV p.7) OVTOS hCTKOTeivoTrjTa, Tptfifj TrpoaamTopLevos avrr/?, Sea to CTKOTeivbv tov tottov KctTavorjcrou ^aAeTroy. rj yap ; and, like tkeSophist he is not easily dis- wholes are the ideas just men- some doubt is implied in the tioned, each of which extends words iav (■qrayp.iv. Cf. infr. b : to many individuals. Many av en fiovXopivois rjulv fj. From particulars are comprised in which it may perhaps be in- one universal, and many such ferred that Plato deliberately universals again unite in one. relinquished the task of writ- (15.) iv ei/1] Sc. oka, or, abso- ing the Philosophus dialogue, lutely, "in one." Cf. The?et. n. hepov prjv rponov] Sce'crfi* I 57 a : 67r ' ivos, Legg- 4, 7 T 8 C : or yiyverai. iv iv\ 7repiKaj36vTa oiov tivi Tima. ig. Tpi&fj~j rpiQrj ("knack," 6. Ka0apS)s] I.e. Without ad- "rule of thumb,") is several mixture of unphilosophic ele- times opposed even more ments; "one who has risen into strongly than ipireip'ia to the region of pure thought." knowledge and art, and is diKaias, i.e. neither dva£lo>s (Rep. pointedly applied in the Pha;- 5, 495) uor Trapav6pu>s (lb. 7, drus and Gorgias to the so- 538,9). For KaBapms, cf. Phaedo phistical rhetoric. Phasdr. 260 65 e, 67 a, b, 69 b. And for e : ovk eari Ttyyr), dXX' are- ScKaias, cf. Phsedo 83 a: ol 81- x vos rpifiv- lb. 270 b. Gorg. Kaicos (piXopadets. 463 b : ovk eort rexvi}, aW ip- IO. Ka\ eTreiTa] Viz. In the neipia Kai Tpifii]. See also Phi- " Philosopher," about the pro- lebus 55 e : ras ala6r)creis mra- duction of which, however, peXerav ipneipla Kai tivi rpi[3jj, 2CXM2TH2. 147 254- 6EAI. "Eoikcv. SE. 'O 8e ye (piAoaocPos, rfj rov ovtos aei Sia Xoyta/icov irpoaKeLjxevo^ Idea, 8ta to Xapurpov av tyjs \(opa9 ovSapLQ)? ev7rerrj? 6(j)0r}vcu' roc yap ttjs tcdis h ttoXXwv yjrv)(rjs ofifxara Kaprepelv irpos to Oelov d(f)o- , pcofTa abvvara. 0EAI. Kal ravra el/co? ov\ yyrrov eKeivcov ovtoos € X €IP. SE. Ovkovv irep\ p.ev toutov Kal raya e7n? ovk avereov, irpiv av iKavais avrov OeaawfieOa. rats tt]s d(iei'] The image of the cave in the Republic will occur to every reader. Cf. esp. Eep. 7, 518: biTTal Kal and birrcov yiyvovrai iniTapd^eis (*? iiriyiyv. rap. ]) dp.- fido-iv k.t.X. See also the re- markable passage in the Laws, IO, 897 dt prj roivvv e'£ ivavrias oiov els rjXiov dnofikirrovTes, vvara eV pear]p.(3piq. enayouevot, Troirjaco- p.e8a ttjv aTTOKpio-iv, cos vovv ttots 8vt}to1s dppacriv d^f6p.evoi re Kal yvcocrdp.evoi Ikovcos k.t.X. Com- pare with the whole passage Bacon, Advancement of Learn- ing (Ellis and Spedding's edi- tion), vol. iii. p. 286 : " Were it not better for a man in a fair room to set up one great light, or branching candlestick of bights, than to go about with a small watch candle into every corner ?" 9. Kal rdx] For Taxa = mox, "presently," cf. Phil. 53c: Ta^a S' — paXXov padr)0-6p.e8a TtpoiXBdv- tos rov Xdyov : alib. The sub- ject has been already proposed by Socrates, and will be ex- amined presently, as soon as the Sophist and Statesman shall have been defined. cerned: bat for adifli r- ent reason. The So- phist lurka amidst the darkness of Not- Being, nf which he knows the trick. The philoso- pher clings by the force of reason to the Form of Being, which is dark only with the excess of light, and because of the weak- U 2 148 nAATONOS 11 CSS (if mortal vision. Bui for fche presenl we IIIUSI |MT- severe in our effort to find the Sophist. II. c. Since we are agreed that some kinds ad- mit of com- bination and some i do not, and this in various de- grees, while 0EAI. KaAw9 etVey. p. 254 HE. "Or ovv 8r/ ra. ptv rjfxiv rwv yevcov eo/uoAo- yyjrat KOivuiveiv edeXeii' dWrjAot.?, ra 8e fxrj, kou ra I±T€S, fXT) 7T€pl TTOLVTCtiV TU)V e\8wV , "iVOL fir) TOLpOLT- rojpeda eV 7roA\oi?, aAAa rrpoeXopevoi tcov peyiartov Xeyopevcov arret, irpcorov ptev iroia €Kaard iarLv t o€7T€£Ta KOivtovias dWrjXcov irccs e^ei 8vvap.eco$, tva 2. "Or ovv a>jioK6yr]Tai\ Join copoXoyrjraL rjpiv. 3. Kal to. pev — KeKoivcovrjKevai] This was not distinctly said, but was partly implied in what was said of the vowels, supra, 253 a. 4. eV oXiyop] " To a small extent." £7tI 7J-0AX0] "Extending com- munication to many things." 6. £ui/e7rtcr7rco/xe(9a ra Xoya)] The ideas of Being, rest and motion, which are now chosen for examination, have been suggested by the preceding argument. 7. firj 7T€p\ TTO.VTCOV TCOV flSojJ/] Cf. Spinoz. Eth. II. 1 : Transeo jam ad explicanda quae ex Dei sive entis seterni et infiniti essentia necessario debuerunt sequi : non quidem omnia (in- fiuita enim infinitis modis ex ipsa debere sequi &c). tva pfj Taparrcopeda iv 7roX- Xot?] A similar reason is ad- duced for the use of the argu- ment from Example in Polit. 278c: fj ^rvxr] tcl pev avrcov afiff ye nrj tcov ovyKpdcrecov opdebs 8o£d£ei, peruridepeva be els tcis tcov npayparcov paxpas Kai pfj pa8ias avWafias ravra ravra nd- Xiv dyvoel. The contrast in the text, however, is not be- tween the simplicity of ideas and the complexity of facts, but between the few great ideas and the multiplicity of lesser ones. 8. Trpoe\6pevot\ Cf. Parm. I43 C : iav irpoe\cbpe6a avrcov e'ire ftovXei rrjv oicrlav Kal to ere- pov e'ire ttjv ovcrlav Kal to ev e'ire to ev Kal to erepov. Phileb. 45 e, 52 e. 10. dwdpecos] Gen. of respect, like pi^ecos supra. " How they stand in respect of capacity of intercommunion." tva to re ov d7raAAaTTeii>] "That, even if we cannot grasp with perfect clearness the no- tions of Being and Not-Being, we may at least exhaust the argument respecting them, in so far as the method of the present inquiry permits, and try if in any way we can force the point that Not-Being is really Not-Being, and take no harm." 2CXM2TH2;. 149 254- T0 T€ bv kcu fir) ov el urj wdarj aacjjrjvela. 8vvdp.eOa Xafitiv, dXX' ovv Xoyov ye evdeel? p.T]oev yiyvco\xeda irepi clvtcov, Ka6' ocrov 6 rpoiros evSe^erai ttjs vvv d aKetyeco?, edv dpa tjulv ny irapeiKaOr) to ay ov Key ova lv cos eariv ovtcos /x>) ov d6 cools dirciX- Xdrreiv. 0EAI. Ovkovv XPV- HE. Meyiara urjv twv yevcov, a vvv 8r] difjuev, to re ov ai)TO kcu aTacrLs kcu KLvrjais. 0EAI. UoXv ye. aE. Kal ut]v tco ye Svco (pauev avTolv d/juKTco Trpos dXXrjXco. 0EAI. 2, &C. 3. ko.6' ocrov — aiifyews] Thus even in the more exact of his dialogues Plato ever complains of an imperfect method. Cf. Eep. 435 d, 506 e, 533 a, Phsedo 85 c, Tim. 29 b. 4. irapeiKadi]] Bodl. napei- KaaOj). 8. a vvv S?) Sijj/iev] The ante- cedent is found in the following words. " The most important kinds are those which we have just been considering." 14. dpcpolv] Dative. " Being has admixture with both." Cf. ^^SS- 5> 733 d • rt,/ey °v v *<" iTocroi fieri f3iot, Z>v nepi Set 7rpo- eXopevov — Ibovra — ff/v u>s oiov T ecrriv avdpeoTTOV paKapia>Tara j Parm. 129 e : ra ei8?j, olov 6poLOTT]Ta re Kal dvopoiorrjTa Kal TrXijdos Kal to ev, Kal errdenv Kal Kivrjcriv. 19. Ovkovv — tovtov^ Compare the very similar manipulation of ideas in Theeet. p. 185. 150 TIAATONOI ally incom- municable, whileBeing communi- cates with them both. Thus there come to be three. And each is the same with itself, but other than the remain- ing two. We have thus men- tioned two more kinds, unless Same or Other can be identi- fied with Being, or Motion, or Rest. But Same and Other are predi- cable both of Rest and SE. Tl 7TOT aV VVV OVTCD? €Lp7)Ka/l€V TO T€ TUVTOl> p. %tfa kgu 6a.T€pov ; iroTepa 8vo yevrj tlvI aVTGO, TCOV jllv rpiwv aAAco, ^vfifxiyvvpevoi prjv iicelvois e£ dudyKT)? dei, kcu irep\ irtvTe a A A' ov 7repl rpicov coy ovrcov 5 avTcau (TKe7rT€oi>, 7) to re tuvtov tovto koll Odrepov coy (iKtivcov tl irpocrayopevovTes \av6dvop.ev rjfJLas p. 25^ avTOv? ; 0EAI. "Ia-co?. SE. 'AAA' ov tl fiyv KLvrjcri? ye Ks ovTa 15 f ke *? *?J' c 7rpoo-epov/j.ev. GEAI. 'AAAa firjv tovto ye ddvvaTov. HE. ' ASvvaTOv dpa TavTov /cat to ov ev elvai. GEAI. ^yeoov. ,_ ,_, m , o,\ \ ~ v ,,* 9^ Sameness, A'E. TeTapTOV Or) TTpOS TOW TpiCTlV eioecnv etOOff 20 therefore, y , x is a fourth to TavTov TLUcofxev ; and Rest both are, we should imply that they are both the ther rest or motion) which was so identified with the common predicable, becoming thus pre- dicate of both, will cause the other (whether motion or rest) to be changed, as thus parti- cipating (by the force of predi- cation) in the opposite nature. But sameness and difference are predicable both of motion and rest. Therefore neither mo- tion nor rest can be identified either with sameness or differ- ence. 7- Mj) toivvv] " Let us not therefore identify Same or Other with motion, nor yet with rest." Cf. Pha?do 103, 4. 13. 'AAV el — Trpoaepovfiei'] " But if the words Being and Sameness have no difference of meaning, then again in saying that motion and rest both are we shall speak of them as being both the same" 20. e'Sos] Omitted in Bodl. A. n., but probably genuine. The Same is not only separate from the remaining kinds, but is itself to be recognized as a kind, dis- tinct from the other three. 1 52 IIAATQNOS Nor can ( (thernesa be identi- fied willi Being : else tln'ivwmilil be an abso- lute Other- ness, as there is an absolute Being. But the Other is always relative to an Other. And so the Other is to be recognized as a fifth kind. And it is at the same time perceived to extend to all the kinds. For each of them has now been distin- guished from the 0EAI. n avv /xev ovv. p. 2jj AE. TV Se ; to Ourepov apa rjpuv XeKTeov we'/A- 7TT0V ; 1] TOVTO KOLL TO OV 6i ev . avaXafifidvovres. GEAI. My; £7E. TlpcDTOv jxev Kivncriv, coy eari Travrdirao-iv erepov o-rdaeoos. r) Iras Xeycop.ev ; GEAI. Ovtcos. SE. Ov ardai9 dp earlv. GEAI. OvSa/im. 256. JgE. "Ecrrt Be ye did to [xereyeiv tov ovtqs. GEAI. "Eotiv. 3. eV 01? Trpoaipovjj.e6aj Equi- valent to a irpoaip. ev is re- peated by attraction from the previous clause. " Posterius in his iv tanquam e precedente syllaba, natum expungerem, ni obstaret ejusdem modi exem- plum apud Xenoph. de Vectig. iv. I 3 : 'Air avrwv pev ovv eyaiye, d(p' av peXXa Xeyeiv, ovoev ri d£ia> 6avpd£ea6ai v irevre] These five " chief kinds of Being" are adopted by Plotinus, who, in forming his complex notion of the Highest Truth, prefers them, in combination with the ti-iple ovala of the Philebus, to the categories of Aristotle. Ennead V, b. 1, VI, b. 2. He makes a distinction, which in Plato is hardly present, be- tween a swrvmum genus and a constituent element of absolute Being. 1 1 . dva\ap,^dvovres] " Kesum- ing," a technical word in Pla- tonic discussion, cf. Theset. 187 c and note. Perhaps here used more literally, " taking them up to examine them one by one." 13. Kivrjaiv] Sc. Xeycopev. 1 6. Ov ardais tip* earlv] Here the Other is for the first time seen to be identical with Ne- gation. rest, not li> '1 of i. but through participa- tion in the Form of Otherness. ' Thus, first of all, Mo- tion is Other than Rest : i.e. is not Rest. YetMotion is, because Motion partakes of Being. Again, Motion is Other than the Same : is not the Same. Yet Motion partakes c of Same- ness, and is the same Motion. We must not quarrel with this result, that Motion is the Same and not the 154 nAATONOS Same, for each ex- pression is true, but in a differ- ent respect. Motion is the same w itli itself through participa- tion in the Form of Sameness, not the Same, through partaking of the Other, whereby it is separated and be- comes Other than the Form of the Same. Indeed, as we have shewn that in the na- ture of things there must S*E. AvOis Si) ttolXlv i) k'ivi-i? eiprjKapiev, aAA' birorav pcev ravrov, did rrjv p.eOe^iv ravrov 777)0? iavrtjv ovrco Xeyopev, orav be pj] rav- b rov, 81a. rrjv Koivcovlav av Oarepov, oY rjv aTro^copL^o- ip.£vr) ravrov yeyovev ovk eicelvo aAA' erepov, coo-re opOcos av Xeyerac ttoKlv ov ravrov. GEAI. Udvv pcev ovv. SE. Ovkovv kolv el tttj p.ereXap.(3avev avrrj klvt]- 1. Avdis 8tj irdXiv] "Again." I. e. To make a new beginning from the same point, viz. ki- vrjais. 7. avToii] Sc. rov ravrov. Cf. supr. 254 d, to which rjv refers. rrdvra is therefore re- stricted to being, rest, and motion, as 8ia navrcov — avruv, p. 255 d, to the five "kinds." av marks the opposition be- tween the reason now given and the words r) iclvr}o~is erepov ravrov ecTTiv. JO. 0x1 hvo-^epavreov] "We must not quarrel with this contra- diction ;'' cf. Theset. 155a: ov Svo-KoXaivovres. Gorg. 450 e : v7roXa/3ot av ris, el (HovXoiro 8vo-- Xepaiveiv iv rols Xoyois. ov yap — opoicos elprjicauev] Cf. Rep. 5, 454 b : eVecrKe^d- p.e6a he ovS" onyovv rl ethos to rrjs erepas re Ka\ rr/s avrrjs (pv- creas Kal irpbs rl relvov pi£6p.eda Tore k.t.X. 13. irpbs eavrTjv ovra> \eyouev\ " We call it so (the same) in relation to itself." orav — ravrov] " But when we speak of it as not the Same, this is because of the participa- tion in the Other, whereby it is severed from the Same, and has become not that but an Other, so that again it is rightly- spoken of as not the Same." 18. avrr) k'lvx]o-is] Here, and supr. 252 c!, distinguished from the Trddrjp.a Kivi]aeas. It is im- 20irrH2. 155 256. ats (TTaaecos, ovoev av aroirov r\v aTa.cnp.ov ai>Ti)v be a 00m- z munion of Trpoaayopeveiv ; kinds, wo apat T\ a' ' " " ~ should not WEAL UpuoTOLTa ye, enrep tcov yevcov avyywpr}- be stagger- cropieOa ra pev dXXrjXoi? eOeXetv p.lyvvcr$ai, to. oe p.rj. mgth&t r> Ipn IT v v ' ' N ' ' ' ' Motion, AJi.. J\ai pLYJV €7TL y€ TT]V TOUTOV TTpOTepOV CLTTO-B quaMo- » > * " ~ * J. ' /) » ■\ ' t v \ tion, was oei^iv y tcov vvv a(piKopeua, eXey^ovTes coy eorf Kara stationary, j / / if there puow raurr;. were any r>T^ at n « J v . manner of BEA1. llwy 7a/) ov ; commu . SE. Ae.ycop.ev 8rj irdXiv' 77 klvtjctls Icttlv erepov nion be- tween M tion and tov erepov, KaOdirep tglvtov re -qv aXXo kou tyjs 10 ^° n t ardaecos" ; 0EAI. ' ' AvayKctiov. £?E. Oi;^ erepov dp eo~Ti ny kou erepov Kara tov vvv Srj Xoyov. 0EAI. 'AX^. HE . Tt oi)j> £77 ro /uera tovto ; apa raw juez> Once more: Motion is Other than the Other, and so Other and not Other at once. And as we have 1 TpiQQV €T€pOV GLVTTJV (firjCTOpieV elvat, TOV Se TerdpTOV ken of five kinds, d p.7] (pcopiev, op.oXoyr/o~avTes avra eivou irevre, irepi cov there re- \ > 9 r\ Kip^cris ovtoo? ovk ov eucns aro- ttos tis eyKa6r)Tai pera^ii ri)s kivtj- creoos re Kal ardaecos, ev XP° V( ? ovdevl ovcra, Ka\ eh ravTTjv 8r) Ka\ en TavTrjs to Te Kivoipevov ueTa- /3d\Xet en\ to io-rdvai /cat to eo-Tos eVi to KivelaSai. 1*7. aneipov 8e ir\i]8ei to prj 6V] The argument is tacitly car- ried a step in advance. It 20 \ ^ v r/ than aE. Ol>/couV /cat ro 6^ afro raw aAAcov erepov remaining , kind, and elvai XeKTeOV. is once for , all itself, 0EAI. AvayKy. hut is ,„,/ —IT? x? v v * " » ' " r ' ' ' v "\\ timeswith- &&. l\ai to ov ap rjp.iv, oaa irep eari ra aAAa, 5 out num. \ ~ » v > ~ \ . ,\ ,v \ tier. We /cara roaavra ovk eariv. eKeiva yap ovk ov ev jiev must ac- > \ v ,/ j\ v > n \ -?x-v » cept these avTO earns, arrepavra be rov apiup.ov raAAa ovk apparent 3/ •? di.screpan- €/cow ot; /ecu ravra ov ovayepavreov, eirei- i° n j ono f 7re/9 e'xti KOtvooviav aAArjAoi? r) raiv yevmv (pvai?. el ^^^ 8e tls ravra fir] avy^copel, rreiaas rjficov rods e/iwpo- S^wtth a6ev Aoyovs ovrco TretOerco ra ftera ravra. ff't^ft 0EAI. AiKaiorara etprjKa?. that thesis. £?E. ,f I8a>[iev dr) real rode. 15 0EAI. To irolov ; SE. 'Q7r6rai> ro fir) ov Aeycop.ev, ws* eoinev, ovk evavrlov ri Aeyo/iev rov ovro?, aAA' erepov fiovov. 0EAI. Um; is assumed that the Baripov v dnoarpe- i|/-ei tovs \6yovs. 13. 7rei#eVa>] Sc. rjpas. By the same means, by which it is shewn that that- which-is-not is, the nature of that-whick-is-not is made plain. ISTot- Being is not the opposite of Being, but only other than Being. This is now further illustrated. According to the preceding argument /*?) ov must here include the negation of Being in the abstract and the negation of the several kinds of Beino-. FIAATONOS Not-Being, then, or negative determina- tion, is not contrary to Being, or positive determina- tion, but only differ- ent in each case from a particular positive determina- tion. aK. Olov otolv e'lTrwpev tl fir) pe'ya, TOTe paXXov p. 257.jp. tl aot (j)aLvope6a to apiKpov r] to taov hrfkovv tco pi)fiaTL ; 6EAI. Kal TTcGy; 5 SE. Ouk ap, IvavTiov mav u7ro(f)aaL9 Xeyrjrcu m-jpaiveLv, avy^coprjaopeda, too~ovtov 8e povov, otl tlov aXXcov tl pTjvvei to pr) kcu to ov irpoTLOepeva tcov eiriovTcov ovopaTtov, paXXov he tcov it pay 'pax cov c 7repl cltt av K€7]Tat Ta eirL(j)6eyyopeva vaTepov ttjs )oa.7ro(f)ao~€Q)S bvofiaTa. 0EAI. WavTanracri pev ovv. SE. T68e 8e 8iai>or)6cop€i>, el kcu cro\ ^vvhoKel. 0EAI. To 7rolov ; 2. r<5 pT]nari] " The expres- sion." The word is used, with exactness = the predicate : not ovofian or Xoya. 5. aTro'^acris] The word oc- curs only in the Soph., Cra- tylus, and Apology of Plato; and in this place signifies not the negative proposition, but the negative particle. 7. tu>v aXXaiv tl prjvvei'] Compare Kant, Kritik der Keinen Vernunft (Leipzig, 1853) page 101. Indefinite Judgments : — " Nun habe ich durch den Satz — die Seele ist nicht sterblich, zwar der logischen form nach wirklich bejaht, indem ich die Seele in den unbeschrankten Urn- fang der nicht Sterblichen Wesen setze. Weil nun von dem ganzen Umfange rnogli- cher Wesen das Sterbliche einen Theil enth'alt, das Nicht sterbende aber den anderen, so ist durch meinen Satz nicht anderes gesagt als dass die Seele eines von der Unendli- chem menge Dinge sei, die iibrig bleiben wenn ich das Sterbliche insgesammt weg- nehme," u. s. w. The difficulty of conceiving fifj ov as a yevos is parallel to that felt in the Philebus about the aneipov, p. 26 d : feat tol TToWd ye Kal to aneipov nape- axeTO yevrj, Spas §' enio-cppayi- u6(vTa to> tov paXXov Kal evav- t'iov yevei, \v ecpdvr]. 8. ovopaTav, paXXov 8e tq>v 7rpaypara>v] The genitives are governed by t5>v aXXcov. " The prefixes ov and p.rj point to something different from the words which follow them, or rather from the things which the words uttered after the negative import." 12. ToSe Se biavot]6u>pev\ "Let us, now, cari-y our minds through this matter." 2CMM2TH2. 159 25J. S*E. 'H Oarepov /jlol (f)vais (Palverai KarciKeKep- \iaricr6ai Kadairep eVr larr/pr]. GEM. nw. £?E. Mia ixev earl irov koll Ikuvt). to <$' liri rep Otherness , ' , „ r/ a\ > orDiffer- yiyvo\xzvov fiepo? avTrjs €kclo~toi> a(popLcruev eirwvv- 5 encehas r 3/ v , « » » / j,\ x \ ^ ' , as many d /xiocz/ Kj^ef r^a eavTrjs lOiav olo ttoAAoll re^vai r branches as , s , v , „ Knowledge eiai Aeyopevai koll €7ricrTi]fiaL. lias: each r\r< a t rr ' > 9 of which is UJliAl. llOLVV fJL€l> OVV. expressed /— J' ' ^ j y putting A£j. KJVKOVV KOLL TOL T7]S VCLTtpOV (pV(T€CdS /JLOpiOL the word fiLas ovar)? TavTOu ireirovOe tovto. 10 fore the 0EAI. Tax av' aAA' oirrj 8r) Xeycopev ; onToAhe 3*E. "Ecm r» KaAw rt darepov popiov olvtltl- knowledge. $€fxevov ; 0EAL *Earur. HE. Tour' ovv avcovvpLOv epovpev rj riv eypv eirca- 15 vvpclav ; GEAI. 'E^o^* o yap /A17 kolaov eKaarore (f)6ey- yo/ji€0a, tovto ovk aXXov twos erepov icrriu r) ttjs rod kolXov (pvaeoj?. £?E. 'Wi vvv, rode p.01 Ae'ye. 20 e GEAI. To iroiov ; SE. 'AAAo n tgsv ovtcov tivos \evos~\ yevovs Every such I. KaTaKeKcpiiaTiadai] For a by Te^vai Kai eTTiaTrjfiai follow- similar use of this favourite ing. word, cf. Parm. 144 b : (to $v) IO. tovtciv — tovto] eirawpiap KaTaKeKep/iaTio-Tai cipa a>s oioVre I8iav €KO.o~tov e^ei , but helped require that the words should 1 (>■() OAATONQ2 has a real U(f)Opl(T0ei> KGU irpos Tl TCOV OVTCOV CLV TToklV UVTLTt- p. 2^7 significance v r , . , 7 v v , and de- 0€l> OVTCO ^up/3el3l]K€U dvai TO fXI] KOiXov ; notes all Qp . r ^c that is dis- OJiAl. KJVTCOS. tinguished _, „ x * * I 1 ' 71 ' f * from the AEj. KJVT09 Ot) 7T/0O? OV |_??J UVTlUeCTlS, CO? €CU/C , object in 9 , , , - , v , question. 5 tlVCU JTLJ avpjdaiVeL TO /JL7] KGCAOV. 0EAI. 'OpflcWa. SE. Ti ow ; /carcc tovtov tov Xoyov dpa p.aX- Xov pev to kolXov rjpuv ear! tcov ovtcov, tjttov Se to paj kclXov ; be rendered thus : " Does not this constitute the existence of the Not-Beautiful 1 " (clXXo tl ovtco o-vp.^e',3rjKev elvai to lltj Kakov.) " ist, that it is parted off (a<$opio-8ev) as belonging to a certain kind of existences (rivbs yevovs tcov ovtcov : for the gen., cf. Eep. 4, 438 d); 2nd, that it is set over against something which exists." A simpler rendering of the words may possibly be right if suffi- cient stress is laid upon ehai. " The Not-Beautiful, as distin- guished from a certain kind of existence, and again as op- posed to an existing some- what, has thus an existence of its own." But the words av wd\iv indicate that the tl t£>v ovtcov is different from the yeW. The former interpreta- tion is confirmed by compar- ing supra 257 c in the cor- responding partition of know- ledge : to 8' inl Tcp yiyvo/xc-vov p-epos avTrjs € Sikolicd Kara TOOJTOL Oereou npb? to fir)8ei> tl fiaXXov eivai darepov Oarepov ; 9EAI. Tifirfv; 3?E. Kal rdXXa Sr) Tavrrj Xetjofieit, iirehrep r) 6a- repov (pvcris tcpavr) twv ovtcdv ovo~a, eKeivr)? Se ovarjs avayKq Sr) /cat tol fibpia ai)Tr)s fir)8evbs ryrrov ovtol TiOevai. 0EAI. ITa)? yap ov; SE- Ovkovv, 639 eoLKtv, r) tt/s Oarepov fiopiov — 6eriov\ " Be put in the same category with the just so far as their equally existing is concerned." For the limitation with 7rpo?, cf. Phsedo 75 a • Ta^T-O" y^p scttiv, 3> 2., TTpos ye o fiovXerai 8r)\ooo-ai 6 \6yos. 14. f) — avTideo-is] The order is 7] avTi6es koi (poplovj ttjs rov ovtos 7rp6s aWrfka avTiKeipevmv. The rendering of Heindorf and Stallbaum, " oppositio naturas partis alicujus," is objection- able, because the expression darepov (pdais has been already appropriated to the Other in general. Besides, the argument does not lead here to the con- trast of Being and all other ideas, but to that between ex- isting things and their nega- tions. The present is simply the generalization of the pre- ceding argument. The mean- ing is, in other words, that negation is, equally with affir- mation, a real determination of thought. 16. el depis elne'iv] Another expression of the awe in which the idea of Being was held (on which vid. supra p. 243 c) ; also marking anew the reluc- tance with which the authority of Parmenides is impugned. 162 nAATONOS And such negative determina- tions arc the Not- Being, of which we have been so long in Therefore, as Being includes all true deter- minations of thought, Not-Being is a kind of Being. ovcrla eo~Tiv, ovk evavTiov eKelvcp ayptalvovaa, aWa p. 258 toctovtov piovov, e\epov eKelvov. GEAI. 1a(f)eaTaTa ye. fiE. Tiv ovv avTrjv irpoaeLTToifiev ; 5 GEAI. Arjkov on to pr) ov, o Sia tov aocfjiarrju i£r)TOVfJL€is, avro ecm tovto. HE. UoTepov ovv, wairep ernes, eariv ovSevb? tcov aXXwv ovaias eXXet7rop.evov, /cat Sel OappovvTa rjSr) Xeyeiv otl to pnj bv /3e/3atW eo~Ti, tyjv avTOv (pvaiv ioevoi/, cocnrep to p.eya y)v pieya /cat to kolaov iiv Kakov c /cat to per) pceya *[p.r) pieya]* /cat to pur] KaXbv *[p.r) kcl- Xov]*, ovtco 8e /cat to p.r/ bv /cara Tambv rjv re /cat ecrTL pit) bv, evaptOpiov tcov 7roXXcov ovtcov elSo? ev ; 7] TLva eri irpb o~ov tt)s 8iavaias. 9. /3ei3aiW] " Incontrover- tibly." ecrri, ttjv] Edd. earl rrjv. I have changed the accentua- tion of io-rt, which does not seem here to be merely an auxiliary verb with ex ov - 11. Ka\ to fir] fj-eyaj The edi- tors have followed Boeckh in repeating /jltj /xeya and /at] ko\6v. This is possibly right, but not necessary, for the sense is easily completed by supplying tju } which is the emphatic word. 12. tjv re Kai eari] He passes from the r\v of reference (" We found it to be so") to that of certainty (" It proves to be so"), eo-ri is introduced as more plainly contradicting Parmenides. 13. ivapiOnov — ei8os ei>] Cf. Parm. 160 c. It is to be noticed here that while the notion of Not-Being is modified, there is a transi- tion also in that of Being. Through communion with Not- Being, i. e. with the Other or Difference, both in general and particular, Being has become concrete instead of merely ab- stract, logical instead of purely ideal. Being is the sum of all positive existences, at the same time having an existence separate from them (Other than their's). Socher observed this, but had not perceived the dialectical progress by which this result is appi-oached. 20I2TH2. 163 258. SE. OlaO' ovv otl Ylapfxevibr) ptaKpoTe'pm T/79 airopp-qcrews rj7TLaTr}Kap.ev ; 0EAI. Ti8ri\ £"E. YlXelov rj \elvos aTrehre aKOTreiv, rjpels els to irpoaOev en ^yTijaavres 1 a.Tre8el^apev avTco. GEAI. Um; d 2?E. Otl 6 fiev irov (f)r]o-Lv, ov yap fxr] 7Tore tovt iovSa/utji etvai fxr] eovra, aWa ?. SE. 'HjueFy 8i ye ov \xovov ws earTi to. firj ovtcl a7re8eLfja.iJ.ev, aAAct /cat to el8os b TvyyaveL bv tov per) 0VT09 a.7re(f)r)vdp,efla' ttjv yap OaTepov (f)vcriv a7ro8el- IjavTe? ovaav re /cat KaTaKeKeppLaTLaptevrjv hfi iravTa e to. ovTa Trpb? dXXrjXa, to Trpb? to ov eK.ao~Tov popLOv avTrjs dvTLTL0ep.evov eToXfirjaapLev elirelv wy avTO TOVTO eCTTLV OVTCO? TO fJLT} OV. GEAI. Kcu TTavTairaai ye, co ije've, dXrjOeaTard fiOL SoKodfiev elpijKevaL. £E. M.7) TOIVVV rjpLOLS eLTTYj TLS OTL TOVVaVTLOV TOV ■\Yt: have lint, only disobeyed Parmeni- des, but have de- fined the Nature of 5 that which he forbade us to Dame. Theessence of Not- Being is the nega- tive rela- tion be- tween each existing kind and that which is Other than it. 1. ncutporepcos Trjs anopprjo-eas] I. e. r) atrtinev fjpiv. 2. r]TVKTTrjKap,(v\ The use of this word immediately after airia-Tia, in a different sense, deserves to be noted. "We have carried onr disobedience to Parmenides beyond the let- ter of his prohibition." 8. fov8afij)-\-] I propose to read touto arj] here, as above, p. 237 a, q. v. diCrjp-evos occurs here also as a various reading, but it does not seem impos- sible that Plato should to quote the words of Parme- nides more exactly in one place than in another. 14. KaTaKeKeppaTicrp,<;v7]v] Plato is fond of this word. For a parallel use, cf. Parm. 144 c. 15. to 7Tp6? dvTiTi8ep.evov~\ Join to bv eKaarov, for which cf Rep. 5? 480 : avTO eKacrrov to ov. Cratyl. 389 C : els to epyov eKao-Tov. Compare also ra>v ovtcov eKao-Tov oXov in Theset. 174 a. 20. Mr} ovk ecrriv] " Let 110 man, then, say of us that we 2 164 nAATONOS ovtos to fly ov (hrocjjaLvoLievoi ToXpcopev Xeyeiv coy p. 258 eaTiv. ypei? ydp nepi pev evavTiov tivos olvtw yai- peiv iraXai Xeyopiev, eiT eanv e'/re per), Xoyov eypv rj kou iravTcmao-iv dXoyov. o Se vvv eiprjKa/JLev elvai to p. 259 sprj ov, rj iretaaTw ti? a>? ov KaXcos Xeyopcev eXeyjkus, ?; p-€XP L 7r€ P av ddvvaTr}, XeKTtov koli €K6iva> KaOairep 7]fid? "j~oWara~j~ tols Xeyopevoi? olov t elvai Ka6' eKaaTov Our argu- ment has shewn the worthless- IQ nessof that easy and childish logic which relies on the expo- sure of con- tradictions, when com- pared with 1 5 that which is at once difficult and valu- able, the real criti- cism of erepov) etvai pr) ov of eo-Tiv. The Words erepov rov ovros ov are ill agreement with rb erepov. 8. Kal — (pao-i] " If this ap- parent contradiction awaken doubt, let doubt lead to in- quiry. But if made the occa- sion of logomachy by men who delight in working out and bringing into relief the oppo- site sides of such antinomies, let such men learn from the above argument that it is childish to mistake the different for the incompatible." Mr. Grote ob- serves that this would be no unfair description of Plato's own procedure in the Parme- nides. To which it may be rejoined that, as Mr. Grote himself points out, the diffi- culties of the Parmenides are regarded by their author as a preparatory exercise, stimu- lating the mind to further study, whereas in the case here supposed the difficulties are raised for their own sake. II. rovs Xoyovs I'Xkcoi/] The picture of men tearing an argument "to tatters, to very rags," is one which frequently occurs. Cf. Phileb. 57 d : rots deivols Tvep\ \6ya>v 6\kj]V. 14. »cai ^akenov apa tcov tol- ovtcov aTTTeaflat, nat8apico8rj Kal pa8ta Kal acpodpa rots Xoyois ip- 7r68ia. The word is suspici- ous, and Badham conj. dvrjWTa. It is more likely that a few letters have dropt out, e. g. ravra idaavra cos 8vvar ov pd- \10-T\a. (18.) olov t etvai — 7r6repov] " To be able to apply his rea- son to each particular point in a discussion, and to bring any man to the test who says that what is other in some respect is the same, or what is the same is other, by reasoning with him on that ground and of that particular relation, in which he says that either of these predicates is applicable." I. iXeyxovra irraKoXovdelvj Cf. Rep. 7> 534 c: ^>°" 7Te p * v H-^xn $ ia iravrcov iXey^cov 8ie£iu>v — iv 7ruai tovtols dnrcoTi tco Xoyco 8t,cnro- ptvrjTai. 3. tear ineivo o = k. e. Ka6' 6] The want of this power is again noted as the defect of dvTikoyiKT) in Piep. 5, 454 c. This passage has been curi- ously mistranslated by Hegel : Geschichte der Phil. p. 210. See Introduction to Sophist, sub finem. 7. ov re tis veoyevTjS cov~\ " This is no real exercise of reason, but on the face of it the childish offspring of one who has but a recent ac- quaintance with the true ob- jects of thought." Cf. Rep. 7, 539 b : ol peipaKio-KOi, orav to 7rpa>rov Xoycov yevcovTai, cos 7rai8ia avTols Karaxpcovrai, del els dvTi- Xoy'iav xpco/xepot, Kal pipovpevoi tovs i£eXey%ovTas avrol aXXovs i£eXeyxovcn, ^a/poi/rer cocnrep ctkv- XaKia tco eXicew re Kal tTTrapdrreiv rbv ttXi]ctiov aet. 8. veoyevrjs] Cf. Theset. 160 e : tovto (pcopev crbv eivai olov veoyeves Tral8iov. Perhaps veo- yevrjs has here the meaning (which Hegel gives it) = viov yivvr]p.a. (Cf. Shakspeare's " the baby of a girl.") See the unusual meaning given to vvpcptVTrjs in Polit. 268 a. scxmsths. 167 259. 37E. K a i yap, <*> 'ya6e, to ye irav goto iravro? "commu : hri")(6Lpelv airoyodpLiJEiv aXXcos re ovk tufieXe? /ecu 8r) kinds" e kcu iravTairaaLv dfj-ovaov tivos kcu d(hiXoao(f)ou. be no dis- „ , , course. 0EAI. Tt 8y ; HE. TeXecoTaTr) irdvTcav Xoycov lariv dfyaviais to 5 8ia\v€t,v eKaarou goto ttolvtcdv' Sid yap tyjv dXXiiXcou twv elbwv arvpirXoKi]v 6 Aoyo? yeyovev 7)\uv. 0EAI. 'AXrflri. 360. 3*E. 2/C07T€i TOLVVV GO? €V KOLipW VVV 8rj TOl? TOl- ovtol? Sie/jLaxofxeOa kcu irpocnqvayKaipixev kav erepov 10 irepco fuyvvcrOaL. 0EAI. Upos 8r) ti; n d SE. IlpO? TO TOP XoyOV rjfJUV TWV OVT(£)V €V Tl And at the „ 436- 20, ev diavoia — yiyvop.evov~\ " Which thus arises in the re- gion of thought and speech." 20cM2TH2. 169 200. 0EAI. Nat. In other i— i \ y f r t words : AE. Kal p-nv airarm ovcrm el8coXcov re Kal eiKO- Negation ^ct)v 77<5?7 kcu (havTacrlas 1 navTa avayKi] fieara eivai. but False- ^^ „ N v hood is nut. 0EAI. llco? yap ov ; AE. To^ 8e cro(pi(TTrju e KOLTairefevyevcu pev, efjapvov 8e yeyovevai to ivapairav prfi eivai \j/ev8o9' to yap prj bv ovt€ 8ia- voelaOai Ttva ovte Xey&v' ovaia? yap ov8ev ovdapfj TO prj OV fieT€)(€ll/. 0EAI. 3 Hv Tama. IO SE. Nvv 8e ye tovto pev etydvrj peTeyov tov ovtos, dxrre TavTrj pev torcos ovk av pd\oiTO en' Taya 8' av (f)alr} tqjv el8cov to. pev peTeyeiv tov prj ovtos, to. 8' ov, Kal Xoyov 8rj real 8o£av eivai tcov ov peTeyovTcov. (00-T6 tt]v el8coXo7rouKrjv Kal (paPTaaTLKTjv, ev f] (f)apev 15 e avTov eivai, 8iapd\oiT av iraXiv d>9 TravTairacriv ovk eaTiv, e7rei8r) 86^a Kal Xoyos ov Koivoovei tov prj ov- tos' ^ev8o9 yap to irapanrav ovk eivai TavT7]s prj crvvio-Tapevris tyjs Koivwvias. 81a tovt ovv Xoyov Hence v *'f- v Jl ' £ r r, , there arises TrpcoTov Kai oo^av Kai (pavTacriav oiepevvr]Teov o tl 20 the neces- > v ?i , r v \ / j r, sity of ex- 7T0T eCTTLV, LVa (paveVTCOV Kai Tl)v KOLVCOViaV aVTCOV amining „s- . « x 3/ /j, 5,/ (nv \ 1 ^^ ,\ speech, 201. T(p pi] OVTl KaTlOCOpeV, KaTlOOVTeS Oe TO "^revOO? OV opinion, 3. ndvra — fieara eivai] Cf. communion is said to unite, Thepet. 170 c: ml ivavra tvov instead of the elements unit- Hea-ra ravOpcoTviva fyrovvrwv 81- ing in communion, just as 9 dao-Kcikovs re Kal cipxovras avrmv P-axV ovvivTarai is put for oi K.r.X. Crat. 411 C. paxop.evoi o-vvlaravrai els fiaxqv. 6. egapvov be yeyovevai] pp. 20. 8d|ai> Kal cpavrao-iav] This 239-241. distinction is in advance of the 1 5. (pavTaa-TiKTjv] Distinguish- psychology of the Theretetus. ed from elicao-TiKr), the Other 21. "iva KaTidapev] " That species of eldcoXonouKTi, supr. when we have found them, we p. 236 c. may. also observe their com- 16. irakiv] I. e. As before in munion with Not-Being." the case of p.f] ov. 22. to yj/evSos bv] "That 18. p.f] o-wio-rapev-qs] The falsehood exists." 170 riAATONOS and imagi- nation, that we may see whether or no they partake of Not-Being. The So- phist ap- pears likely to prove a very Sphinx, proposing to us one riddle after another. But we must not lose heart ; and, after all, his chief for- tress is already taken. diro8ei£ > tt)pev, diro8ei^avTes 8e tov cro(])iarTr)v eh avTo p. 261 1 €v8i]cra)fiei> i etirep evo\o9 eanu, rj /cat diroXvaavTes ev aXXco yevei {rjrcopev. 0EAI. KofuSf) 8e ye, a> £e've, eoiKev dXrjOe? eivai 5 to 7repi tov ao(f)iaTi]v /car dpyas XeyOev, on 8vo~0r}- pevTOv eirj to yevos. (pa'tverou yap ovv 7rpofiXr)paT0JV yep.eiv, &v e7ret8dv n 7rpo(3aXr), tovto wpoTepov dva- yKoiov 8iapdyeo~6ai nplv eV avTOv ifcelvov d(f)iKecr6ca. vvv yap poyis pcev to pr) ov coy ovk ecrTi 7rpo(3Xr)0ev 10 8ieirepdo-ap.ev, erepov 8e 7rpo(3e'(3Xr)Tai, /cat <5et 8rj \jsev- b 809 coy eo~TL /cat ire pi Xoyov /cat irepl 8ofjav a7ro5et£at, /cat /MeTa tovto tcrcoy erepov, /cat er aAAo per eKelvo' Kai nepas, coy eot/cez/, ov8ev tyavrjcreTai noTe. 212. Qappelv, cb QeaiTr)T€, %prj tov /cat crpLKpbv tl 15 8vvap.evov eh to irpocrOev del irpoievai. n yap o y' d6vp.wv ev tovtols 8paaeuev dv ev aAAoty, rj p.r)8ev ev e/cetVoty dvvTcov rj /cat irdXiv els TOviriuOev diratcrOeh ; o-)(oXfi 7Tov, to /caret tyjv irapoiplav Xeyop,evov, o ye 1. civto] to y^evbos. 2. etVep evoxos i>v yepeiv] Cf. Theset. 161 a : o'Ui p,e \6ycou riva eivai 6v\clkov kcu padicos e£e\6i>Ta ipeiv cos ovk av e'^ft ovT 'ya6e, c tovto o Aeyet? foaireirepavTcu, to tol peyiaTov rjpuv Ttlyps r/prj/ievov av etrj, tol 8" dXXa ySr] paa> kcu a/jLiKporepa. 0EAI. KaAcoy ei7rey. 5 2E. Aoyov 8r) irpojTOV koll Soijav, KaOdirep ipprjdt] vvv 8r}, Xd(3cop.€v, tv evapyearepov *d.7roXoyLO-(op.€@a*, TTorepov avTcov (mrerai to p.r) bv rj TravTairacriv dXrjdrj fiev io~TLV dp.(j)6r€pa ravTa, yj/evdos 1 Se ovSe- 7T0T€ ovderepov. IO 0EAI. 'Op6m. d S'E. <$>epe 8r), KaOdirep hri tcov eldcov Kcti tcov Our first ypap/xarcov eXeyopcev, wepl tcov ovo/xarcov ttoXlv be to ask (/",./ , z / / * n e same coaavTcos tTrLLTKeylrcopeOa. (paLverai yap tttj ravTrj question \ « >. / ' about TO VVV (rjTOVfXeVOV. 15 words v - ^ v v „ , e which we UEA1. lo 7TOLOV ovv or) irept rcov ovoparcov vira- have ai- f ready an- KOVCrreOV ; swered v*tt< T7"/ ' > \ n ' \ y ' *> about the 2E. Eire iravra aXXyXois ZjvvappoTTeL eire per)- letters of jite#a*] MSS. a7ro- \oyr)(Tcop.e6a. If the MS. read- ing were right, the following clauses would depend on Xd/3co- fiev, and there would be a con- tinuation of the metaphor from supr. 254 d : ddcpois aVaXXdr- retv. Cf. Legg. 10, 886 e. But the correction of Heindorf, received by Bekker and suc- ceeding editors, appears so exactly suited to the context, that it is here retained. " That we may reckon or infer more clearly." " That we may have better data for determining." diro as in dndKa^eiv, dnopavrev- ecrdat. 14. Cpaiverai yap ittj TavTy] Because words are the ele- ments of speech, as letters are of syllables, and ideas of thought. l6. T6 77010V VnaKOV(TT€Ov\ " What question must I an- swer about names?" z z 172 riAATONOS To what extent « 1 ■ » thej admit ofcombina- 1 1 • HI ' Scmif com- binations of words are signifi- cant, and some are not. For, as there are two chief parts of speech : the verb, which sig- nifies ac- tion, and the noun, which de- notes the agent, neither verbs with- out nouns nor nouns without verbs can be strung together so as to mean anything. SE. To TOiovfte XeytLS tcrcos, otl to. plv ifa^rjs p. 261. Xeyo/iepa koll 8r)XovvTa tl tjvvapfioTrei, to. 8e rfj e avve^eia pifiev aifixaivovTa uvapfioaTtL 0EAI. Ylcos tl tout wires ; 5 £?E. Oirep wi]6r)v viroXafiovra ere 7rpoaopoXo- yelv. ecrTL yap rj/xip irov tcou ttj (poavrj 7repl rrjv ov- er lav S^Xcofxarcof Slttop yevos. 0EAI. IlcSff; SE. To fiku ovofiara, to Se pr]p.ara kXtjOIv. p. 26a. to 0EAI. Et7re eKorepov. 3E. To fiev eVt tolls Trpd^ecrLV ov 8rjXcop.a pr)p,d 7rov Xeyofiev. 0EAI. Nai. HE. To Se y eV au rots' tKeiva irpaTTOvcn arj- 15 pelov Trjs (j)covf}s tTTLTeOev ovofm. 0EAI. KopLlSfj flCP OVV. SE. Ovkovv e£ ovopLccTcov i±ev fiopcop arvve)(css Xeyofievutv ovk kern iroTe Xoyos, ovS' av prjpLaTcov ■^copls 6po/jl(ztoc>i> Xey6evT(ov. 20 0EAI. TavT ovk e/iaOop. HE. ArjXou yap cos Trpos erepop tl (SXeiraov apTi b 9. To /iei> ovopara, to Se P77- /xara kXij&V] The distinction of noun and verb is here in- troduced as something wholly- new. Note that ovopa is used first in a generic and after- wards in a specific meaning : first for " word" (supr. d) and then for " noun." II. To pev — ovopa] " The one, which is an expression standing for actions, Ave call a verb : the other, which is an ar- ticulate mark set on those who do the actions, we call a noun." 14. i K eiva] The Bodl. MS. has eKeivas (sc. ras irpd^eis). 18. prjudrcov] The genitive is governed by e'£ in the pre- ceding line. 2 1. ArjXov yap] " ToU must surely have had something different in your eye when you agreed with me. For this is the very thing I meant in say- ing that these things (nouns or verbs) merely strung to- gether in this way do not make language." 20*I2TH2. 173 362. ^vvcofxoXoyeLS' eVei tout olvto i/3ovXo/jLr)i> enreiv, otl (rvveycos co8e Xeyo/xeva ravra ovk eari Xoyos. GEAI. Ife; HE. Oiov, fiaSiteL rpeyei KaOevSei, koll rdXXa 6v e'Xa- The most r/ r/ ,/ „ \ ,y 9 elementary OLiao~Vr), koli Kara ravrrju or) rr)v 10 tain at / '(>/ /-' n ' » ^ ' x least one avve^eiav ovoei? irco ^vvearr] Xoyos' ovoe/xiau yap ofeach v tf v » > / - y- > o.» > w > c> \ kind. And oure ovtcos ovr eKeivcos irpa^cv ovo airpa^tav ovoe the sim- >/ v »pn\ \ 3/ ?> \ ~ ^ j /i/ plest com- ovaiav ovtos ovoe fir) ovtos oyXoi. ra (pcovrjdevTa, binationof vv r> » / v <• / / /a noun and ivpiv av tis tols ovopaai ra pr/iiaTa Kepaay tote ver b ) ^^ 5' rjp/iioore re Ka\ Xoyos eyevero evOvs r) Trpcorr) o~v\x- 15 ^arns,"^ TrXoKr), a^eSbv tcov Xoycov 6 wpcoTos kcu o-pUKpo- ^sSSb^ rai 09. 2. ravra] Sc. ovofiara nai rjppaae re Kal — iyeveroj For pTjjiiara. the aorists cf. Theset. 156 e, 5. avr] So the Bodl. MS., and note. And for the whole with An. cett. avr. expression, cf. Phileb.47d: pigu 6. aTrepyd£erai\ The subject pia Xvtttjs re Kai rjdovrjs ^vpninTei is not tis, but Ta prjpaTa. yevopevr], 9. ovopara — a>vopao-drj\ Here 17 irpcaTT] irXeypari tovtco to loovopa ix dpporrei, rd 8e appbrrovra avTcov e 15 Xoyov direipydcraTO. 0EAI. Yiavrdiracri pev ovv. HE. "Ktl 8rj apLKpov To8e. GEAI. To irolov ; HE. Aoyov dvayKcuov, otclv irep fj, tlvos elvcu 2oXoyov, prj 8e tlvos dSvvarov. GEAI. Ovrm. HE. Ox kou 7T0L0V TLva avrov elvcu 8el ; 1. 2>oV] The adverb is used, instead of tovto, by a sort of attraction from n&s. 7- aXkd ti ire palvei] " But effects or determines some- thing." Cf. Theeet. 180 a : ne- paveis 8e ov8e Trore ov8ev irpbs ov8eva avrcov. 9. t<5 TrXeypan] The same metaphor is applied in the Politicus to the practical com- binations of the Statesman. 13. ra ttjs cpavrjs o-rjpela] "The vocal marks on things," i. e. words. 7rep\ = " in the region of," i. e. " amongst." 17. apiKpov rode] Sc. 'i8a>p.ev or \dfia>p.ev. Cf. Polit. 300 a : tl 8e To8e ; Compare the similar ellipse with h8e in Thetet. 191c: a\X S>8e. 1 9. twos ehai Xo'yoi'] " Must have a subject." Cf. Theast. 160 a : 'AvdyKT] 8e ye ipi re Tivbs yiyvecrOai, orav aladavopevos yi- yvcopai. ala6avopevov yap, pr]8evbs 8e alaOavopevop d8vva.Tovyiyvea6ai' eKelvo re tiv\ ylyveudai k.t.A. 20I2TH2. 175 26 3 . 0EAI. ITwy <$' ov; aE. Ilpoae^copeu Si] rov vovv r)puv avrois. 9EAI. Aei yovv. SE. Ae'Ao rolvvv aoi Xoyov, avvOeis Tvpfiypa For exam- , , , \ t/ cv> * ' ' ple:"The- 7Tpa^€L 01 OVOflOLTOS KOLL prjpKXTOS' OTOV O U.V O XoyOS 5 aetetusis ■? / , /<> sitting" is fj, (TV fJLOL (ppaQzlV. aproposi- 3 ^3* 0EAI. ToLVT 6OT0U Kara Svvap.IV. which The- SE. Qeairrjro? Kadrjrai. picov per) piaKpo? 6 Aoyoy; the subject. GEAI. Oi)/c, ctAAa pceTpios. SE. 2ov e/3yoj> 5?) (ppd^eiv 7vepl ov r earl kou io orou. 0EAI. A^Aoi^ OTl 7T€pl €/JLOV T€ KOLL €/XOS\ GEAI. IMos-; £?E. QeairrjTos, w vvv eyco SiaXeyopiai, wererou. i5"Thefete- 0EAI. Kat tovtov ovS av eh aXXa>s envoi 7vXr)v flying," is j / » ■? v \ » another, of ep.ov t eivai koll Tvepi eptov. which the VT? FT N £ ' ' 'A. ' " subject is Ah., Ho^of oe ye tivcl (papiev uvaytaxiov eKaorrov the same. 9 .. f But they eiVOLl TCOV XoyCOV. differ in b GEAI. NaL -Foft&one •—it? T'' fii> «' f ' J. ' 9 is mani- Ar*. Lovtcov or) woiov riva eKarepov (pareov eivai; f e8 ti y false, 2. JJpocrexco^ev — avToh] Cf. tive, it may be true or false, supra 233 d: 1 1 determines in accord- ance with reality. The false proposition also deter- something, as if real, but that something is different from the reality. Therefore, in the se- cond of the two in- stancesjust given, The- setetus is made the subject of an unreal determina- tion, and of another predicate, ■which is treated as if it were the same 0EAI. TW plv xj/evSr] 7rov, rov 8e dXrjOr}. p- HE. Ae'yei 8e avrwv o fxev dXijOys to. ovra w eari irep\ aov. GEAI. Ti p-ijv ; 5 HE. 'O 8e 8r) \lsev8r}? erepa tu>v ovtlov. GEAI. Nat. HE. Ta per) ovt apa &>? ovra Xeyei. GEAI. 2 X e86v. HE. 3 Ovtcdv 8e ye ovra ere pa irep\ gov. iroXXd io fxev yap € ovv. HE. *Oi> varepov 8r) Xoyov elprjKa irep\ gov, c TTpcorov fxev, e£ (bi> wpLadfieOa rl ttot eari Xoyos, izavayKaiOTarov amov eva tu>v fipa^VTaTGdV elvai. GEAI. Nvu 8r) yovv ravrrj ijvvcopLoXoyrjaapLev. HE. 'Kweira 8e ye twos. GEAI. OuW HE. Ei 8e fir) ecrTL aos, ovk aXXov ye ov8evos. the object of negation, and de- scribed as false. In tbe Phile- bus also (37 e) by the quality of an opinion is meant truth or falsity : v 8e ye ovra erepa nepi a-ov] " Really being different from what really is concerning you : for we said that in re- gard to each thing there ex- ists much that is and much that is not." I. e. the propo- sition has a real significance, though a significance which is different from the true one. 10. ttov is to be construed vwep^aTas with ecpapev. N\ B. It is possible that in the phrase ovkovv 6(tol ye tcov peyakav irou ti k.t.X., supr. 235 e, i7ov ought to have been taken virepfiaTas with the whole sentence : = " I presume you know." 15. eva reov ^pa^vrdrmv eivai\ Because a subject and a pre- dicate are essential to every sentence. 19. Ei' be p.r] — oiBevos] The object of these words, and of a> vvv eya) 8ia\eyopai supra a, is to bring out the falsity of the proposition, by making it per- fectly clear that Thesetetus is the subject of whom "flying" 20o? elvai Xoyov. 0EAI. 'Optforara. d HE. rie/3i drj crov Xeyo/ieva fievroi flare pa coy to. avrd Ka\ fir) ovra coy ovra, iravrdiracriv a>? eomev r] roiavrrj crvvflecrLS e/c re prjfidrcou yiyvop.evri Ka\ ovo/xdroov ourcD? re kol dXr]0co? yiyveaOat Xoyos yj/evdr)?. 0EAI. ' AXyflearara p.ev ovv. jSJE. TV Se Sr) ; Stdvoid re /ecu 86{ja /cat (^avracrla, which be- longs to him. And BUch .'1 combina- ti> «ti of noun and veil) amounts 5 really and truly to falsehood in speech. But if speech may be false, so may thought, opinion, 10 and ima- gining. For thought and speech are the is predicated. If the propo- sition had no subject, it would not be a proposition, for it was shewn that every propo- sition has a subject : but it belongs to no subject except Thea^tetus. Therefore These- tetus is the subject. This conclusion is resumed in the WOl'ds itep\ brj crov \ey6pevct. Mr. Grote objects that here and in Theset. 201, Plato, who decries the " facts of sense," selects an example of which sense alone can judge. It may- be replied that, in choosing the simplest examples, he naturally lights on what is obvious to the senses. But, first, even in this case the truth or falsehood is not given by sense, but by reason- ing upon sense ; and, secondly, Plato would have said that these " sensible analogies " (al- o-drjTaL 6poi6rt]Tes, Polit. 285 e) were only symbols of the higher truths of which he spoke. 3. rjv] The past tense is used not only because of the aorist cnrtcprivapev, but also to expi-ess that which is unalter- able. 6. nepl Sj) o-ov] Compare the similar " ad hominem" il- lustration at the end of the Thesetetus, p. 209 b : 6Zs yap pe 8iavoovpevoi> cos ecrriv ovtos QeClLTTjTOS K.T.X. Uepl 8tj — pevroi Qarepa ] The position of pevroc has caused suspicion as to the soundness of the text, but may be accounted for by the em- phasis on o-ov. Cf. nov supr. b, and note. Xeyopeva — . 261 a\rj9r) irdvO' r/pcov eV rah \j/V)(ou? iyylyverai ; GEAI. nw; HE. '0.8' e'l&ei paov, av irpwrov Xdfiys, 77 TTOT 5 ecm kgu tl 8ca(j)epovaLi> eKacrr uXXyXcov. c GEAI. Aidov p.ovov. HE. Qvkovv 8iaifoia peu koll Xoyos tolvtov' TrXrjv 6 f.uv euros tyjs ^/v^r}? wpos amrjv 8iaXoyo? dvev (pcovrj? yiyvofxevos tout ccvto r/pui> encovopiaaOr], 10 8 idvoia ; GEAI. Yldvv p.ev ovv. HE. To 8e y air eKelvr\daiv re kgll dir6 KaXels ', Tl KcikSiv ; Ao- yOVj OV aVTTj TTpOS ClVTTjV 7] ^V)(r) dief-epXeTcii 7rep\ a>v av aKonf/. In the present passage, as also in Phileb. 38 d, (in the ac- count of $6ga,) the distinction, as well as the likeness, between inward and outward language, is marked out. 12. To 8e y 07J- 5 ineiprjs pevpa] Cf. Tkeset. 206 d : tt\v 86gav QK.TVTTOVjxeVOV (Is T7)V Sid TOV (TTO- [j.aTos por]v. Phileb. 1. c. : rd Te TTpos avTov pr/Liara evrelvas els (pcuvrjV Ttpbs tov napovra avra tout av irakiv (p8e'y$-at.TO, Knl Xdyos 8f] ylyovev ovtcos Tore 86£av eKaXovpev. 15. avTo] For airo, antici- pating the correlative word, though less distinctly than here, cf. Theset. 207 d : elra dpvrjpovels ev Trj tG>v ypapadrav fjiadrjcrei Kar dp^d? cravTov re Kal tovs aXXovs 8p£>VTas ai>Ta ; 0. 'Kpa Xeyeis k.t.X. 2. TavTa Xeya. Herm. unnecessarily conj. owrot : Wagner av t68\ See also supr. 243 a, eKelvo, and 256 d, where the antece- dent of aurd had not been distinctly expressed ; and cf. Polit. 262 a: tovto ye — NE. To 20 " TL 7r P 00 '' eiTrr)? avro ; GEAI. Kou irm ; SE. TV 5' oraz> /i?) /ca#' avryu dXXd Si alaOrj- aea>9 wapfj tlvl to tolovtov av irdOos, dp o\ov re 6p9(DS ehrziv erepou n irXrjv (j)avTao~[av ; GEAI. OvUv. iS?E. Qvkovv tTreiTTep Xoyos dXrjOrjs 1 rjv kcu \j/ev- Sr]?, tovtcov & ifpavi] Sidvoia plv avrrjs irpos eavrrju ifsvXV? SiaXoyo9) Soija 8e Siavoia? dTroTeXevrrjcris, (f) a [vera i de b Aeyofxev avppu^Ls aio-6r)o~€a>? kcu 86£r)9, dvdyKTj Srj kcu tovtcov tw Xoyco ^vyyevcav OVT(£>V \jf6vSr) T€ GtVTWV Q.VIO. KCU €VLOT€ HUGH. GEAI. Um V ov ; /HE. KcLTavoe'i? ovv otl wpoTepov evpeOr] ^€v8yj9 io Thought then being mental self- colloquy, Opinion the completion of thought, and Ima- gining the meeting- 15 point of Opinion and Sense, since speech may 2. "Orav — avro] The passage of the Philebus just quoted is exactly parallel. 6. pr) Kaff avrr]v~\ Sc. rfj ^\rvxfl. The distinction, here brought out underlies much of the later portion of the Thesetetus. The imagination of an absent ob- ject, which is omitted here, is described in Phileb. 38. 7. ai>] This word is to be taken by an hyperbaton with the whole clause. Trddos] Cf. Theset. 193 d : to tt)s 86£r]s nd&os. 11. tovtcov] Viz. the mental processes. 12. So^a Se Siavolas dnoTe'hfv- Trjo-is] This is vividly expressed in the passage of the Theretetus above quoted, p. 1 90 a : bWav Se (J) ^fvxr]) oplcracra, e'lre /3paSu- Tepov, eire kcu o^VTepov eirat^acra, to avTO i[8r) (fir) Kal prj Sierra^, 86£av TavTrjv Tideuev avrrj?. 13. (paiveTai 8e 6 Xe'yopevJ " What we speak of as Imagin- ing." The same form of ex- pression occurs in Theset. 164 b : to 8e ye ov% Spa ovk eViorornt eo~Tiv, e'nrep Kal to opa e7ri'crrarai. 14. 7<5 Aoya) cvyyevatv ovtg>v~\ This has been shewn in the preceding sentences, airmu is pleonastic. It is probably im- plied that mere alo-flrjcris is nei- ther true nor false. 15. -^revbrj elvai] This is shewn by an independent proof in the case of So'ga in the pas- sage of the Philebus above quoted (38 d). a a 2 ISO IIAATON02 be false, so also may these con- gl'IRTsVil" speech. The search for false- hood has ended sooner than we expected : and we may return with better courage to what re- mains of our origi- nal task. 86{ja Kca Xoyo9 y kcito. ri)u irpoaSoKiav yv i(j)ol3i]- p. 264. Ot]\x(.v apri, firj TTavrdiraaiv u.vi']vvtov kpyov €7Ti(3aX- Xoi/ieOa Q-jTovvres clvto ; 0EAI. Karafow. 5 SE. Mr) TOIVVV /ITjS' €19 TO. XoLTTO. O.6vflC0fJL€V. eVetS?) yap 7re(f)aPTaL raura, rwv epirpoaOiv avapvy- c aOcopLev /car e'ldr) ^Latpiaecov. 0EAI. UolcDv bfj ; HE. Aiei\6p.€0a Trj9 el8(oXo7rouK7Js eiSrj 8vo, rrjv 10 p.lv eucaoTiic/jv, rr)v 8e (pavTao-Tucqv. 0EAI. Nat. HE. Kai tov cro(f)LcrTr)u 6L7TOfi€V 0)9 airopoip.ev el9 birorepav 6r)crofiev. 6EAI. 3 H.v Tavra. 15 HE. Kai roi>#' rj/JLcov a7ropov/JL€vcov eri fxeiQav KT09 a>9 ovt€ eiKcov ovt€ ei8coXov OVT€ 9 d p.7]8e7TOT€ p.r)8apiov -^£v8o9 eivai. 1. r)v is 6p6a>s eVt^ejpot^' dv ToaoiiTOV eTTifiaXXopevos epyov. 6. Tutv ep.Trpoo~8ev — 8iaipco~e pev eVeiTrt kcit 6(p6aXpa>v x* ev u%Xvv. lb. II. 344 : Kara 8' ScpOaXpcov k£)(vt dxXvs. I2TH2. 181 64. 0EAI. Aeyei? oAjjfl}. £?E. Nvi> 8e y eireLdrj irtyavTai pcev Xoyo?, ttI- (pavTOLL 5' ovaa 8o£a \j/ev8ij9, iyxP*L &) fUfJLTjfJiaTa twv ovTUiV eivai koll riyvi-jv e'/c ravTTjS yiyveaOai tyjs 8ia0€(T€co9 airaTrjTUcqv. 5 0EAI. 'EyxcopeL S*E. Kal jjlt}v on y r\v 6 o~o([)i(rT7]S tovtwv tto- repov, SicofJLo\oyr)/uLei>ov rjfxiv iv tols irpoaOev rjv. 0EAI. Not. e 3?E. ITaA^ tolvvv liTL-)(eLpu>ixev, ayjitpvTes 8i)(f} to io irporeOev yevos, iropemcrOaL Kara tovtu Sefya del fxepos rov TjirjOevTO?, e^ofxevot tt}? tov ao^iarov KOivcovias, ecoy av avrov ra kolvol iravra Trepitkovres, rr]v OLKtiav XmovTes (f)vcriu eVtSe/^co/uei/ fidXicrTa plv p. 265. rjfXLV avrols; eireiTa Se /cat tow eyyvTarco yevet rrj? 15 TOLavrrjs fxeOoSov TretyvKocriv. 0EAI. 'Opdfc. Conch/r sion of I. After dis- tinguishing likeness- making into ini.-i'ji making and phan- tastic, we doubted in which com- partment to place the Sophist, when there arose the more im- portant doubt, which we have just resolved. 4. ravTT]s ttJs SiaBe&ecos] Sc. vvpa ne(pvKe, ra p.ev (TKaid, ra 8e 8e£ia Kkrjdivra k.t.X. 12. ixofxcvoi — noivavias\ I.e. Making the participation of the Sophist in each kind our test and clue. The notion of Koivaula, when once established, is well used. Cf. Theaet. 209 c, [xvrine'iov, and note. 15. to7s eyyvrdra) y£vei\ Cf. Soph. Ant. 174 : yevovs kcit dy- XUTreia : and for the meaning, Pluedr. 266 b : tovtcov — av- T0£ re epaarTjs — twv Suiipecrectv Kal crvvayayav — idv re tiv ciKKov rjyrjO-wpai Svvarov ets ev Kal em ttoXXci TreCpvKos opqv, tovtov diaxoy KaTo-rncrOe p.er' 'l^viov ware 6eo1o. For e7J-tSet£a>/nei>, cf. Slipr. 235 C (where the same thing is spoken of) : dTrocprjvat n)v aypav. 182 nAATONOS We are 11. iw at li- berty to continue our series of divisions, which be- gan with the distinc- tion of cre- ative and acquisitive art. Our previous definitions were ob- tained by following the sections of acquisi- tive art. But as he now ap- pears as an imitator, we must divide crea- : tive art, of which the making of imitations is obviously a branch. mE. Ovkovv tut€ fieis r)p^opaOa 7TQL^tlk^u kill p KT)]TiKr)i> T€)(i>7]u Siaipovpevoi ; 0EAI. kw. HE. Koci ttjs KTrjTiKrj? Iv 6i)pevTiKfj KCii uycovia 5KCU ifXTTOpLKYj Kal TLCTIV Iv T0L0VT019 U§€CTLV e(f)aVTU- (etf rjixiv ; GEAI. Haw pev ovv. HE. Nw 8e y iiretdr) papLrjTiKr) ire pie tXrjfev avTov re\vrj, SrjXov a>? avTrjv tt)v 7ron]TLKr)v oV^a SiatpeTtuv io7rpcoTi]v. 7] yap irov fAifirjcrL? 7rolr)pd(e. Compare also Aristotle's avdeKaa-roi tls. Etb. N. IV. 7, § 4. 18. kot dpxas] P. 219b: nav onep av p.rj irporepov tls oi> varepov els ovalav ayrj. 2 2. (pvra,o(TaT — citt]Ktci] The notion of I2TH2. 183 p. 265. ev yfj tjvplcrTaTca acofiara ttjktol kcu arrjKra, ptcov aXXov tlvos i] 6eov SrjpuovpyovvTOs d>7}(T0fi€v varepop yiypeaOcu irporepop ovk ovtcc ; i) tu> tcdp ttoXXcov Boy pan kcu piyxart \pchp.epoL ; 9EAI. Uolcp; iH'E. Ttp Ttiv (j)vcnv aura, yeppqv caro tlpos air Las auTopdrys kcu avev diapolas (frvovcrrjs' ?) perd Xoyov re kcu iTrMTTrjpLrp? Qeias diro Qeov yiypopLeprjs ; d 0EAI. 'Kya> uep lacos did tt]P yXiKiap ttoXXukls dpLffcorepa pLeraSofjatfi)' vvv p.i]v fiXerroop els ere kcu viroXapfidpcop dieaOal ere Kara ye 6ehv aura ylyve- aOai, Tavrrj kcu avros vevopuKa. £E. KaXcos ye, d> QealrrjTe. kcu el pep ye ere rjyovixeOa tcov els top eTretra \povop dXXcos ttcos So^a^oprcop elpca, vvv c\p tcd Xoyco pterd TreiOovs apayKaias eireyeipovpev iroielp opcoXoyeip' eirei^r] Se' aov KarapapOdpco tt)p (pvenp, on kcu avev twp Trap e iiawv Xoycop avrrj irpoaeicrip i(j) direp vvv eXKecrOcu Creative art is, 1st, divine and human. For i" ( rod, working by reason, run! not l" ;uiy mere spon- taneity of nature, is to be re- ferred the origin of animals, vegetables and mine- rals. Thesetetus, although young, is inclined to this opin- ion, and the Stran- ger, consi- dering the nobility of his nature, I. rrjKra kol arrjKTa] I.e. Me- tals and other minerals. 4. ypw/xei/oi ] Sc. (p7](ronev yiyveadai. The following passage con- tains the same religious spirit which is more fully expressed in the Tirnreus and in the 10th book of the Laws ; cf. esp. Legg. 10, 889-892. Also Phi- leb. 28 d, e. I I. Kara ye 6eov] " At least in accordance with the nature of God." 13. Kcikcos ye, a> Qeairijre.] With similar warmth in Theset. 185 e there is welcomed the assertion of the independent activity of the mind : KaA6s yap el, &> 6., — 6 yap KaXcos \eyoov, KaXos re KayaQos. 15. So%a£6vT(ov\ "Of that class of persons who in later life think otherwise." The present participle has almost become a noun, and has lost the tempo- ral meaning. fiera TreiBovs dvayKaias] This " demonstrative persuasion " is advanced in the 10th book of the Laws, where it is shewn that Mind is prior to the elements of Nature, and that the best mind rules. Cf. esp. pp. 888 e sqq., 891 c, 892 b, 896 c, 897 c. See also ib. 12, 967 c. Tim. 46 e. Treidovs di'ayKaias] " The per- suasion of demonstration." 184 nAATONOS thinks it unneces- sary, by further argument, to antici- pate the rll'i-rl of time. But, andly, divine and human art are each divided into an art of making realities and an art of likeness- making. 027$*, iucrco' xpovos yap e/c irepiTTov yiyvour av. p. a A Act Oijaco to. fxlv (fwaei Xeyo/xeva TroieladaL 6 da T ^X V V'> 7 "**»^' 6 ' K tovtcov vtt di't9pco7ra>v ^vviaTa/xeva dvdpco7rlvr], /cat Kara tovtov 8i) tov Xoyov 8vo ttoltj- 5 tlki~is ytvr\, to p.ev avOpamLvov elvai, to 8e Qeiov. 9EAI. *Op0m. SE. Te/xve 8rj 8vo1v ovaaiv 8'iya eKaTepav avOts. 0EAI. nc5y; aE. Olov tot€ fiev /cara 7rAaro? Tep.va)v tijv ttol- p. iorjTLKT]u Traaav, vvv 8e av /cara firJK09. 6EAI. TeTfiycrOco. ££E. TeTTapa fxrjv avTrjs ovtco to. irdvTa fie'pr) ylyveTai, 8vo fiev tol irpos rjfJLwv, dvOpumeia, 8vo 8' av to. irpbs Oecov, 0eia. is 9EAI. Nat. HE. Ta 8e y co? kripoa'S av 8ir\py}p.£va, fiepos fiev ev d(f) eKaTepa? Trj? pLepi8o9 avTOTroimLKov, tco 8* vttoXoittcq o~)(e8bv fiaXiaT av XeyoiaOrjv el8a>Xo- 7rouKco. K.a\ Kara Tama 8y] ttolXlv r/ 7roir]TiKr) 8l)(tj 20 SiaipeiTou. 0EAI. A eye otttj eKaTepa o.v6l$. b 1. XP° V0S y^p e ' K irepiTTov yi- yvoir av] " For to do other- wise would be to supersede the work of Time." 2. ra. — Cpvcrei] Either cpvcrei has almost the force of au adj., as in Rep. 6, 501 b (to cpvcrei Sinaiov k.t.X.) ; and Xeyopeva is added pleonastically, like the participle in heivor^res Sokov- ? is pleonastic, as in s,- OLKtlov re kcu aXXorpiov 7repl tol Xauirpa kcu Xela eh Divinely made like- nesses are, for in- stance, thosewhich appear in i. e| av ra] The same use of the article occurs in a simi- lar connexion in Protag. 320 c: Kai t&v oaa nvpl Kal yjj nepdv- WTai. 3. avra eicaora] Ut Supra : opposed to eKaarav e'i8co\a infra. 7. TrapeTrerai — infr. C, irapa- ko\ov6ovv\ So irapaKokovQel in Theset. 158 c, of dreams an- swering to realities. 1 1 . cpavrda-para avTO(pvrj\ Na- tural images, opposed to arti- ficial ones, such as those of the painter. o-Kia pev — 8nr\ovv 6V] The latter word is not forthcoming in Rep. 6, 510 a : Aeyw 6V rds elKovas 7fpa>TOp pev to? (TKids, eireira ra iv toi? v8a6vias o\j/ea>s ivavr'iav a'io~dr)o~iv refer to the transposition of right and left in the reflected irnace. B b 18() nAATONOS mid, in tin' day-time, sIiuiImV. -i and reflec- tions. And, as a house is a humanly- made real- ity, so the picture of a house is a sort of humanly- created waking dream. ev £vi>e\0oi> Tr/ Tivwv yevvrjp.a. 6. rjpeTepav] I. e. avOpasTvivqv. (prja-onev is to be. supplied from what follows. avTTjv — oIkiciv~\ " A real house." Not the ideal house, as in Eep. 10, 597 e : airrjv — 6 ear 1 KXlvrj. 8. ovap a.v6p£mivov~\ I. e. As dreams are a kind of divine pictures, so a picture may be described as a human dream. eyprjyopoo-iv] " For those who are awake." 11. Kara Suo] Like Kad' ev, Kar okiyov. " By twos." " In pairs." Cf. Theset. 156 b. 12. to — avro] "The thing itself." The grammar seems to require avTovpyinrjs eldcoXoTroi- iKrjs. But there may be a change of construction from epya. (ecrrt) rrjs ttoit]tik)]S to av- rovpyiKr] (eVrt 7Tot.ovo-a) to aiJTO. Compare the transition imme- diately below, from ^01777-4*07 to yswrjpa, from the art to the work. 14. 860 5t^»] "Two in two ways :" i.e. («) divine, human ; (b) reality, shadow. 1 5- T#ei'aT pev Ka\ fdvdpco7riVT] f] Probably Qeiav p. k. av&puiiivr]i>, as Heincl. observes. 16. avT&v] " Of things them- selves." Although the fourfold division, in Kep. 6 sub fin., of the intelligible and visible is different and has a different object, it is prompted by a fancy very similar to that which rules in the present passage. 1 7. yewrjpa] For this use of the neuter word where the 2CMI2TH2. 187 Next fol- lows the distinction which was before pro vieionally made, be- tween 5 Imaee- a real :uid an appa- rent like- p. 266. aE. Trjs tolvvv elSooXovpyucrjs dva/j.vt]aOcofJLev bri to fxev eiKaariKOv, to 8e \ -. > 1 n r ''£>£' tastic ; the UfXTjaofiev avTco vvv avapL(J)to-pi]Tr)Tcos eio?; duo ; creation of GEAI. No/. -). 2,6j. 3?E. To tolvvv (j)avTaorTiKov 8t X a. GEAI. Ufj; £*E. To /xei/ 6Y opydvcov yiyvofjtevov, to 8e avTov ^^ ded - irape^ovTOs iavTov opyavov tov ttoiqvvtos to vfj] Governed by xpw- fievos. 2 I . aTvoveifiaii(6a\ " Part off for our own share." Cf. Phsedr. 266 b, refivofxevos. E b 2 188 IIAAT0N02 veipwpeOa' to <$' aXXo nav d(jjaip.€v /xaXaKiaOevTes p. 267. ,; kcu 7rapei>Te? tTe'pcp avvayayelv re els ev Kai irpeirov- » crav e7ra>i>v/j.iav diro8ovvai tiv avTcp. 0EAI. NevepyaOoo, to 8e peOeiaOco. 5 SE. Kai firjv kcu. rovro eri 8iirXovv, co QeaiTrjTe, d^iov -qyelcrOai' 81 a 8e, o-KOirei. 0EAI. Aeye. Mimicry is £££. Tai Bikcliol pLrjBapLcos bvTes ; r) tovtov ttolv tov- volvtlov ; geai. mv. cl S*E. M.ifjL7)Tr)v Br) tovtov ye eTepov eKelvov XeKTeov olfJLOLl, TOV ayVOOVVTOL TOV ytyVCDO-KOVTOS. \ 0EAI. Nat. SE. Ylodev ovv ovopta i/carepcD T19 clvtcov XtyeTai irpeirov ; r) BtjXov By yaXeirbv ov, Blotl ttjs twv yevcov kolt etBrj Biaipecrecos iraXaia 77?, a>? eoiKev, instance, who per- sonate their own notion of justice, without knowing what jus- tice really is. For this branch of mimicry, through the remiss- ness of the first name- givers, it is >/~v /1 \>/ «■» a o,» difficult cuTia tol9 epnrpoauev Kan acrvvvovs 7raprju, coaTe ptrjo 10 10 find a hriyeipeiv prjBeva BicupelcrOaL' kclOo Br) tcov ovopLaTcov "Motion avayKX] \xr) o~(j)6Bpa eviropelv. opicos Be, kclv el ToXprj- "i'^S poTepov elprjaOat, diayvcoo-eco? evena tt)v p.ev pteTa ^a^Ti e B6£r)? pLiprjcriv Bo£opLipLr)TiKr)v 7rpocreL7ra>pLev, Tr)v Be j^eitiiei pLeT eTTLO-TrjpLr]? \cTTOplKr]V TIVCL pLlpLrjaiV. ^whenTh GEAI. "Eo-TCO. mimic is unconsci 5?E. QaTepCp TOLVVV XPy°" r * 0V ' ° 7lOTr)S pus of hi OVK e.V TOl? elBoaLV f)v, dXX eV TOW pLipLOVpLe- ordissei VOLS Br). thedisse bling no 0EAI. K.GU piaXa. 20 tion-min i. nr]8aiia>s ovrei] An under- current of strong feeling is per- ceptible here and in o-obodpa supra, as in Kep. 7, 531 e : ov yap ttov doKovai aoi oi ravra teivol BiaXeKTiKol eivai. Ov p.a tov At", e e'x9 dyvoei Tavra a 7rpo? tov? aXXovs (hs eidoo? icrx^fiaTiaTaL. GEAI. Yldvv fj.€v ovv ecmv tKarepov yevovs d>v 10 tiprjKas. HE. Ovkovv tov pt.lv dirXovv fUfirjTTjv Tiva, tov 8e elpcoviKOv pLLfirjTrjv Orjaofxev ; GEAI. Et/coy yovv. SE. Tovrov 5' av to ykvos ev y dvo (f)a!)fxev ; 15 GEAI. "Opa av. HE. 2/co7rco, /cat jjlol SiTTGo KaTa(paivea06v Tive' b tov fxev 8rj/ioaia re kcu piaKpoh Xoyois irpos irXrjOr) dvvaTOV elpcoveveaOai KaOopco, tov Se ioia re, koll 1. e'lre SwrXoV ] Various figures are employed to give greater vividness to the notion of division. Cf. supr. 229 b. Polit. 259 d : av apa iv avrrj Tiva 8ia(pvrjv KaTavorjO'aip.ev. lb. 260 : Oeareov e'l tttj SiecrTrjKe. lb. 261 : e'l Tiva TOfirjv en e\op.ev vtt- eluovarav iv tovtco. Phsedr. 268a: el apa kol crot (paiverai 8ieo~TT)Kos avTuv to r/Tpiov &o~nep epoi. 5. avrcov] tco/jL€0a rov fiaKpoXoycorepov elvaL ; irorepa woXltikov rj drj/xoXoytKov ; 5 0EAI. Ayp.oAoyLK.6v. SE, T/ Se rov erepov epovjuev ; ao(f)ov ?} ao(f)i- (TTIKOV ; 0EAI. *To* /xeV 7T0i» vvpLiov avrov ri Xr]\j/erai, kou a)(e8ov rjdr) fi€/j.dd7]Ka on rovrov Be? irpocremfiv aXr)6m avrov e\e?vov rov iravrairacnv ovrws aotyicrrriv. 3E. Ovkovv avvdrjaofiev avrov, KaOdirep epnrpo- crOev, rovvofia o-vfMrXe^avres 1 diro reAevrrj? eV'15 dpxqv ; 2. ivavTioXoyelv] It now ap- pears how much of the claim advanced in p. 231 a is granted to the Sophist. He is allowed to possess that portion of the Eristic art which is not based on knowledge, but on the prac- tice of argument. Cf. also p. 225 d, e. 9, *T6*] MSS. t6v. Ste- phanus, followed by the other editors, corrected this into to, with great probability. 11. TrapuvvfiLov] The vague- ness of this derivation renders it more correct than Hegel's from the imaginary o-oQifriv, " to make wise," or Bentham's, who took o-o^icrrTjj for a super- lative. 12. [iefj.a6r]Ka\ " I now clearly understand that this is he whom I must address as the very man of whom we are in search, the unmistakeably real and genuine Sophist." avrbv eReivov] There is again a transition from the name to the thing. 14. KaQairep epTrpoo-Qev] P. 226 a. For dirb TeXevrrjs ilf dp^rjv, cf. Legg. 1, 768 e: ttjv d.p^y]v vvv reAevrfl Trpoaafyas. By the process of division the Sophist is thrust down into the lowest sphere of imitative (i. e. unreal) art, much in the same way in which pleasure finds the lowest place in the Philebus ; and poetry, in Rep. 10, is thrice removed from truth (597 e), where there is also the same division of di- vine and human art. So the actual Politicians are found low down amongst the class of 192 nAATONOS 20 uvea, TaXr)OeaTaTa, wy eoiKev, epei. 0EAI. YlavTOLTracrL /xev ovv. servants (Polit. 289 d), and in the series of transmigrations given in the Phsedrus, 248 e, the eighth place (between the artificer and the tyrant) is as- signed to the life of the So- phist or the public man. 2. T6i> 8rj] I have ven- tured to retain top against Schleierniacher, who reads to, and to give dcpapio-pevov a middle signification. " The artist of the contradiction-caus- ing, conscious section of un- knowing mimicry, who has taken for his own the word- juggling portion of human, not divine, creation, in the phan- tastic species of likeness-mak- ing, such undeniably is the lineage of the true Sophist." Cf. SUpr. 267 b, dnoveipapeda. 4. dvdpamiKov, though hardly occurring elsewhere in Plato, may be regarded as probably genuine, because of the affec- tation of variety and novelty of diction which pervades the dialogue. 5. The Bodl. MS. has Bavpa- fTTOTroirjubv, not 8avp.aT0TV0irjTi.KbVj as Gaisford asserts. 6. TavTTjs ttjs — at/xaros] The words of Glaucus. II. Z. 211 : tovttjs toi yeverjs Te Ka\ atparos evxopai eivai. The derivation of kind from kind by 8taipeo-is is compared to a genealogy. Compare the modern idea of the genealogical derivation of species from a single type, and cf. Rep. 8, 547 a : TavTrjs toi yeveds xpl ^dvai eivai o~tclo~w. n O A I T I K o s INTRODUCTION TO THE STATESMAN. llIE contrast between the Sophist and the Philosopher is paralleled by that between the ideal and actual Statesman. The one of these is the philosopher under a different aspect, surveying from above and yet guiding the life of states : the other, in Plato's view, is the most sophistical of all sophists (tOV TTCLVTtoV V \xkyMTTOV yOT]Ta KCU TaVTTJS TtjS T^XVTjS 6/X- TrtLpoTaTov). But in the present inquiry, although this thought may be detected from the first (see 258 b and note, compared with 292 b), it is ironically kept back, and instead of starting from the known characteristics of a class of persons, the speakers begin by forming an a priori conception of what the States- man ought to be. In fact, this dialogue, in a different subject- matter, combines the problem of the Sophistes with that of the Philosophus, and seeks to determine, not only an existing coun- terfeit, but an ideal reality. At the same time it is shewn that the true Statesman and Governor cannot be defined without reference to the actual, mixed conditions of human things. The whole is intended by the author to be a study in scientific method. Further remarks on the dialogue will be better understood if they are prefaced with, a brief outline of the dialogue itself. § 1. It is assumed that the Statesman is master of a science : and that not a mere handicraft in which the thought cannot be separated from the work, but a theory, which however, as a theory of government, has an immediate reference to prac- tice. This theory must be essentially the same whether applied to a state or a household, and whether he who holds it be invested with authority or not. Further, the commands of the Statesman are not derivative, but issue from himself. These *b2 i> INTRODUCTION commands aim at controlling a work which affects living crea- tures in the aggregate. But what living creatures '( The respondent inclines to say " man" at once. But he is warned to be cautious, lest lie be making " a distinction without a difference." For what ground is there for supposing that the distinction between man and the brutes is more rational than that between Greek and Barbarian, or that man has more right than any other thinking animal, such as the crane, to set himself over against all other creatures ? By gradual sub- divisions, much as in the game called " Animal, vegetable, and mineral, 1 ' the human race is at last determined to be the sphere of statesmanship : mankind being in the last place distinguished by a merely mathematical and physical difference from the pig, or, as bipes implume, from the novcpovouv (\>v\a dpvidoov. (258 b — 267 c.) § 2. The King, then, has been denned as the herdsman, the nurturer or nourisher of men. But there now appears this difference between the king and other herdsmen, that, while the cowherd is everything to his own cattle, there are many others who, equally with the king, may claim to be the shep- herds of the human flock. The merchant, husbandman, baker, gymnast, physician, have all a share in their nurture. In order to perceive the reason of this difference we must call to our assistance an ancient tale. There has been, and will be again, a time when the king is the shepherd of his people, but not in the present cycle of the world's life. For there are alternate cycles, during one of which the universe is guided by the Divine hand, and then again, through many ages, the vast round fabric is left to revolve alone. Of the former time we have a dim tradition in the fables of the golden age and of the earth-born seed : and in the latter we and our fathers have been living. Of this " re- verse of doom" a trace remains in the story that Zeus once made the sun and the stars to return from their setting to their rising. The gifts of Triptolemus and Demeter, Prome- theus, Hephaestus and Athene, were rendered necessary by the naked and helpless state of man, when first left, with the whole universe, to his own guidance. For in that former state he lived under the care of a Divine shepherd, who was all- sufficient for his flock : happy if they used their golden hours TO THE STATESMAN. v in the improvement of their reason : otherwise, less happy than we may be. How great, then, was our error, when we mistook the Statesman, who is a man of like nurture and education with hia citizens, for the Deity who ruled and tended mankind under the perfect conditions of that former cycle, when all things, including man himself, sprang of themselves from the Earth, and hence there was no property nor any possession of wives and children. And there is another error of less moment which the tale makes clear. Our definition is at once too wide and too narrow : too wide, because including more than the Statesman ; too narrow, because not including him at all. He is not the feeder of his people, though he has the care of them. The word "care" would have included him also. But the general name "care of herds" must be divided until the King or Statesman is separated from all rivals and left quite alone. First, he is distinguished from the shepherd of the theo- cracy ; next, from the tyrant, who rules by force. The King or Statesman has the care of willing bipeds. (267 c — 276 e.) § 3. Still, even with the help of our tale, which grew upon our hands, we have made an unfinished work. This descrip- tion is a mere colourless sketch, which must be filled up by further argument. And for this purpose we must have recourse to an example. For as children in learning to read are taught to recognize the letters of words which they know not, by being shewn the same letters in words which they know, so the mind is taught the principles of things, which having seen in one form she fails to recognise in others more strange and complicated. This will be illustrated by the example which is now to be chosen. The art of weaving woollen cloth is one of the simplest we eould name. Yet we might describe it by a long series of divisions, distinguishing it from the making of other fabrics and coverings, without, after all, separating it from those arts to which it is most nearly related. For suppose we had thus defined it as " the art of working in wool." Is there not the process of carding, which is the opposite of weaving together, and those of spinning and fulling and of darning, all of which answer to the definition but are none of them included in the weaver's art ? Then there is the making of the loom and vi INTRODUCTION shuttle and other implements of weaving, which are adminicular to the art but different from the art itself. We distinguish; then, arts instrumental from arts operative. And of arts operative in wool-working there is a further dis- tinction, also depending on a universal division of the arts into combining and discriminating. Discriminating processes in wool-working are carding and one part of the use of the comb. But wool is combined, (i) By twisting: either hard with the spindle, to make the warp, or softly with the hand; to make the woof. (2) By the crossing and intertexture of the warp and woof, which is weaving. (277 a — 283 a.) § 3 b. Now it may be said that "this is too long;'''' and that we might have arrived at the definition without the intermediate steps. This leads us into a digression on Excess and Defect. For want of dialectic, men are apt to confuse that which is more with that which is too much. Whereas there are two ways of measuring size and number ; one, simply by comparison of greater and less, the other, by reference to the standard of what is meet or proper. Without such a standard there could be no art or science. This is the real meaning of the saying that the science of measurement embraces all things. So lamentable are the results of an unphilosophic method. And this suggests the further reflection, that as each reading lesson is learnt, not for its own sake, but for the sake of learn- ing to read; so our present inquiry is not so much on account of the Statesman as for our improvement in dialectic and in the alphabet of the ideal world. From all which we gather that the length of our discussion is to be judged, not by comparison, but by its meetness or fitness : and this not with a view to pleasure, nor chiefly to the ease or rapidity with which the object of search is found, but by its meetness or fitness to improve men in dialectic and awaken in them the faculty of invention. (283 b — 287 a.) § 3 c. We now endeavour to apply our example to the dis- covery of the King. His art is to be separated from those, adminicular and operative, which, like his own, are necessary to the life of the city. The productions of these are divided into seven kinds, viz. instruments, vessels, seats, shelters, sports, nourishments, and TO THE STATESMAN. vii materials: in none of which is the king's work discoverable. Next in the order of possessions come tamo animals of every kind, the art of herding which, including men, has been already distinguished from that of the king. Lastly, there is the class of slaves and other servants, amongst whom, strangely, appears the first glimpso of a character rivalling the king. Not amongst the slaves, of course, nor amongst tradesmen (though there is a political science of trade), nor heralds and other ministers of state. But first the prophet, herald of the Gods, and the priest who mediates between earth and heaven, have a kingly air. In Egypt the king must be a priest, and the Archon-Basileus at Athens performs sacred rites. At last our eye has caught the stragglers of a tumultuous throng, who presently sweep into full view — the actual rivals of the King. (287 b — 290 c) § 4. A motley crew, and monstrous to the philosopher's eye. Some fierce and cruel as centaurs, some weak but cunning. These greatest impostors of all sophists do the business of the state : but, though hard the task, they must be separated from the true Statesman and King. For of the three forms of government ordinarily recognized, Monarchy, Democracy, Oligarchy, with the additional branches of Tyranny and Aristo- cracy, can it be said that any one is determined by Eeason? How can the difference of many, few or one, of poor or rich, or even that which we have recognized between persuasion and force, distinguish the knowing from the ignorant ruler? True,, many cannot have this knowledge, nor can that rude multitude who call themselves the wealthy or the few. Those who are indeed the few, whether poor or rich, whether they rule by force or by persuasion, whether with or without law, and by whatever means, so long as they rule with knowledge for the good of the state, are the true rulers, and theirs is the true form of government. Those forms to which the name is given are imitations, better or worse, of this one form. (291 a —293 e.) § 4 b. The Greek mind is shocked by the suggestion that the true government may be without law. But the sove- reignty of law is not a perfect substitute for that of a wise and living will. For general rules, which are in their na- ture simple, cannot embrace every contingency which may viii [NTRODUCTION arise in the inlinitc complexity of human tilings. The law, like Croon, tv yOos ijlovvov €i> avTu r/jopei co? (j)i](Ttv avros, Kovbev ak\o, tovt opflcos ^eiv. Laws are necessary (like rules in the gymnasium), because the ruler is not able at every moment to be prescribing for individual cases : and also because the lawgiver will not always be with his people. But suppose a physician going into a far country, and writing memoranda for his patients to observe until his return : should he come back and find that from some change of climate his prescriptions are no longer suitable, must he be bound by what he has once written ? And if the true legislator, or one like him, were to come again on earth, must he be bound by the letter of the old precepts? It is commonly said, ' Let a man persuade his city, and so let him improve the laws/ But and if he forces a better law upon his countrymen, will he be any the less a good lawgiver ? The truth is, that, whether poor or rich, whether with or without law, whether by persuasion or force, the true statesman is he who governs Avisely, who does what is expedient, and preserves and makes better those committed to his care. (293 e — 397 b.) § 4 c. It was said above, that of the imitations of the true government some were better, others worse. Here the distinc- tion finds place which we before rejected, between the obser- vation and neglect of law. In the absence of the true sove- reign, it is best for every state to preserve its laws, which it may be presumed that the first lawgiver made after his conception of the ideal pattern. This is illustrated by an imaginary case (with evident allusion to Athens). Suppose that men, from their experience of the wickedness of physi- cians and pilots, determined to bind them by edicts, which they passed in their assembly or in their senate, at the sug- gestion of any unprofessional adviser who chose to speak, and regulated thereby the use of drugs and surgical instruments and the build and navigation of ships in peace and war. Sup- pose these edicts engraved on lasting marble, and on the no less lasting monuments of custom and tradition. Suppose, further, that our medical practitioners and naval captains were chosen annually in the same assembly, and were liable to be TO THE STATESMAN. ix indicted publicly by any citizen so soon as their annual term expired. A further sanction would be necessary. Were any found searching into the truth of navigation and medicine beyond what was written, he must first be set down by public opinion as a babbling, star-gazing sophist, and then accused in court of corrupting the youth : and if convicted of persuading any man to sail or to be healed contrary to the customs, he must suffer the last penalty : seeing that no man must be wiser than the laws, which he who runs may read. The result would be the hopeless extinction of these arts, and of any others to which this plan should be applied. Yet is a worse case conceivable : if, when the laws of any art had been thus laid down, those elected by suffrage or by lot were to despise the laws and act in defiance of them, not from the knowledge of any principle, but for the sake of gain or favour. For though the arts were destroyed, there was in the former case a certain ground of experience or probability, which is thus annihilated. Hence in the absence of the true lawgiver, the best course (though only a second best) is to maintain the laws. This distinction, between constitutional and unconstitutional government, was previously applied to monarchy and oligarchy, and is now extended to democracy. Whence there are now seven so-called forms of government, of which one only de- serves the name : — scientific monarchy, constitutional mon- archy, tyranny, aristocracy, oligarchy, constitutional demo- cracy, unconstitutional democracy. When we contemplate the six last named, the wonder is that cities should exist at all. Constitutional monarchy is better than aristocracy, and this is better than constitutional democracy. Of the remaining three, unconstitutional democracy, or anarchy, is the least bad, and tyranny is the worst of all. But all are to be rejected, as not answering to the object of our search. The heads of these false governments are not statesmen but partisans ; they are mere phantasms, like the constitutions which they administer ; the most egregious imita- tors, impostors, and sophists. (297 c — 303 b.) § 5. The actual statesmen being thus disposed of, the way is still further cleared towards the unveiling of the true king. Yet all that we have hitherto gained is negative, except that *c x INTRODUCTION lie rules men wisely, according to true principles. Like refiners of gold, we have purged away baser minerals, but have not yet eliminated those precious metals which have the strongest affinity for the gold. In other words, our definition would apply equally to the general, the judge, the wise and eloquent orator, as to the king. But the art of statecraft has this distinguishing note, that it directs the functions of the rest, and has a universal working. The orator knows how to persuade, the judge how incor- ruptibly to administer the law, the general how to conduct war successfully : but none except the king or statesman can determine where persuasion is to be used instead of force, what the law ought to be, whether war is to be levied, or peace preserved. Thus statecraft is, as was before anticipated, the commanding science, not herself acting, but directing those who have the power to act. And while each of the rest has a particular sphere, the office of the king embraces every func- tion of the common life. (303 c — 305 e.) We have now separated the king or statesman from all who were likely to be confounded with him. It remains, in accord- ance with our example, to describe the manner of his work. What are the warp and woof of the royal fabric ? and how is it woven ? First, we must note that there are two opposite qualities which merit praise, courage and gentleness, or, in other words, quickness and slowness : which, however, if they remain apart run to excess, and equally become blameable and even de- structive. Next, that every art of combination, even the humblest, seeks to bring together elements which have first been separated from what is worthless. Hence as the art of carding ministered to weaving, so the kingly art makes use of education and other tests for purging the good from the bad. The worst are cast forth by exile or death. The mean and ignorant are enslaved. Of the rest, the brave and gentle, that is the hard warp and soft woof, are combined : the eternal part being compacted with a divine, the mortal with a human, bond. The divine bond is right opinion confirmed by reason, and this is implanted in the mind — the divines particula aura? — thus imparting gentleness to the rugged and prudence to the smooth and yielding nature. TO THE STATESMAN. xi This is the most important and difficult branch of the ruling science. The human bonds are easily imposed where the di- vine exist. They arc the regulations concerning marriage, whereby the brave and gentle races are physically as well as mentally crossed and interwoven : though flesh and blood may find this saying hard. This having been effected, the offices of state are to be distributed amongst both kinds : the two natures being in each case either united in a single person, or equally repre- sented where more than one officer is required : that the state may act at once with energy and discretion. And so there is wrought the perfect web, whereby the true Statesman holds the whole city together in concord and amity, and secures for his subjects the happiest life which is possible for a society of men. (305 e — 311.) REMARKS. I. Dialectical Aspects. Relation to the Sophist. Amongst many differences of treatment which might be expected from the change of subject and the fertility of Plato's invention, the thoughts on method and the nature of know- ledge, which were thrown out in the Sophist, are not forgotten, but indirectly receive further development. a. The process of divisions has acquired new significance. The problem is explained to be, "to distinguish one kind of art from all others, and by stamping these with a single negative form, learn to conceive of all science under two heads, namely, statecraft, and that science which is not statecraft." (258 c.) This is clearly an application of the view of Not-Being which had just been given. But it soon appears that the mere abstract notion of Difference may be capriciously applied. To distinguish man from other animals, for example, or Greek from Barbarian, is a merely arbitrary procedure, unless we have found a rational ground for the distinction, which can only be done by a method of successive exclusions, each of which implies a certain knowledge of that which is excluded, as well as of that which is retained. Even so meagre a defi- nition of man as that he is a featherless biped implies the *c 2 v.. INTRODUCTION knowledge of at least two positive qualities of the class of birds. This thought is not worked out further at the time, but in the later stages of the argument the complexity of all real knowledge, implied already in the " communion of ideas," is more fully recognised than elsewhere in Plato. The defi- nition of the Sun which Socrates on the previous day hail thought sufficient, " that he is the brightest orb that rolls in Heaven about the earth," on to Xa^-pdrarov ecrrt t&v Kara tov ovpavbv Iovtgov irepl yijv (Thenat. 208 d), would not now satisfy the requirements of the Stranger. " It is not enough to describe wool-weaving as the greatest and fairest of all ministries that wait on the working of wool : the other attendant arts must be carefully stripped from round it." (281 c.) That is, each of these must be so far defined as to exclude weaving. The boundary line must be clearly drawn from either side. And thus the definition of the Statesman involves a certain account of the general, the judge, the orator, as well as a description of the no-constitutions of existing states. Here is an approach, though a very partial one, to the ideal of science which is made a test of the happiness or misery of the children of earth in Saturn's reign : " learning from every nature, what each by its proper faculty had perceived differently from others and could contribute to the treasury of knowledge." (272 c.) So much has been gained from perceiving the correlation of the positive and negative elements of knowledge. Closely akin to this was the reaction, which the " Sophist" justified 11 , from a merely negative and analytical method of knowledge. This also is continued in the Statesman. In their zeal for the method of divisions, the Stranger and his respondent fall into a natural error. In seeking to be definite they forget to be comprehensive, and omit a needful generalization. They divide the science of feeding ; whereas the king in this pre- sent cycle is not a feeder, although he has the care of a flock. This error is duly exposed and rectified ; and it is further shewn that the distinctions hitherto made have only brought out a colourless outline of the King. It is from this point that the more serious portion of the inquiry begins. a TeKeaiTarri lravroiv Xoywv £v bvvajxevwv TipaTTtiv) could hardly have been overlooked by the speakers themselves. The imperfection of mere external classifications being thus recognized, there follows the remark, already quoted, on the necessity of finding the mutual boundary between the object of search and all kindred species. (281 c.) In applying this to weaving we obtain two fresh thoughts, which are found valuable for the main argument : the distinc- tion of atria and ^vvaina, of operative and adminicular arts ; and the universality of the two great sciences of composition and division. The former affords the hint for the elimination from the work of the king of various arts, without which civil life could not proceed : the latter is the key-note of the final passage, in which the last touches are given to the image of the King. For by help of our example we are enabled to proceed fur- ther, even after all possible distinctions have been drawn : and when all rival arts have been stripped away we see in the royal function the twofold process of division and composition : division, by which, practically, good citizens are selected, and theoretically the brave and gentle elements are distin- guished : composition, by which the diverse materials thus cleansed and prepared are combined in a smooth and perfect web. These two are the counterpart of the twofold process of dialectic, by which the objects of thought are distinguished and combined according to truth. This process is incidentally described in a passage of the Politicus already quoted (285 a, b), in which the complex determinations of real knowledge are contrasted with the off-hand generalizations and distinc- tions of sciolism ; and which is in fact an application and development of the conception of scientific method expressed in Soph. 259 d. d Cf. Phsedr. 265 d : tb p.\v &\\a rw ovti 7rai5ia TreiraiaQai. TO THE STATESMAN. w c. These arc the chief points of that instruction in dialectic, which is commended to us by the Elcatic Stranger as the most valuable result of the dialogue. We may gather from them that Plato was at this time striving after a philosophy of the concrete, and endeavouring to substitute real and fruitful in- quiry for the barren logical excrcitations, the sweeping gene- ralizations and verbal distinctions of his contemporaries, per- haps of his own scholars. The aim constantly held before the mind is the attainment of greater definitcness and fulness. " This is true, but not explicit or complete " (aA?/0es jue*> ov jj,i]v adepts ye ovbe rikeov) is the repeated complaint. Since it has been proved in the Sophist that different ideas may have com- munion or correlation with each other, it becomes the task of philosophy to discern the threads which connect them. And nowhere, except in the Philebus and Parmenides, has Plato buckled to this task more earnestly. In the latter part of the Phaedrus indeed there is a conception of an art of rhetoric, which should be based on a complete science of psychology, the realization of which would far exceed in definiteness and completeness this somewhat desultory sketch. But it is one thing to imagine a science, and quite another thing to attempt, however imperfectly, to work it out. The " splendid ideal" of the Phaedrus, like other intuitions of that dialogue, is an anticipation rather than an embodiment of method : not neces- sarily an early anticipation, for if wildness of imagination marks a jugendschrift, what is to be said of the my thus in the Statesman ? In the sixth book of the Republic there is ex- pressed a more general conception of the ladder of hypotheses by which science climbs to the ideal world, whence she de- scends without the aid of the ladder by the chain of ideas. But this notion, though implying a connexion of ideas, is still vague, and gives less promise of the reality of science than the method employed in the Politicus. The Republic professes to be intelligible rather than exact, and to proceed by popular methods. Even the order of the sciences is not worked out as a dialectical problem, though the seventh book contains passages of great subtilty and depth. What is wanting in demonstration is " evened o'er'''' by the abundance of imagination. But Socrates hints more than once to Glaucon that there is a " longer way," which the dialectical xvi INTRODUCTION .student must learn to tread. It is possible that we have a sample of this in tin; present dialogue, which contains an ela- borate defence of lengthened argument, and in which Young Socrates is taken further afield than he had any thought of going. This struggle towards definitcness and reality is pro tanto an approach on Plato's part to the later philosophy of Aristotle. But there still remains between them an ineffaceable difference of character. Plato when most concrete retains an undimin- ished hold of the universal : ovpavu eorrjpiKro Kapi] kox It:\ ydovl fiaLvet. The idealizing spirit may be exorcised, "tamen usque recurrit." Gliscit intellectus altior. The true king, when adapting himself to the particular circumstances of his state? inflicting exile or death on some;- uniting others in marriage, is still the perfectly wise philosopher with his eye fixed on the pattern in the heavens. Contemplation and action are not sundered : the knowledge of the universal truth is not sup- posed to hinder the individual applications II. Socratic and Pythagorean Elements. a. Continuance of the Socratic Spirit. The question here treated by the Stranger, after being proposed by Socrates, is almost identical with some of those with which, according to Xenophon, the real Socrates was most engaged : u 7roAts ; n ttoXltikos ; ti apxv avQp&nutv ; tC apxt-«bs avOpunrcoi; ; And though his method of search on these topics, as recorded in the Memorabilia, is much simpler than that here used, it is evident that Plato has in many instances only followed up the hints given by his master. There is, first, the postulate on which the whole dialogue proceeds, that statesmanship is a science, that knowledge ought to govern. You would not doubt, says Socrates, whe- ther to place a skilful or unskilful pilot at the helm (I. i, 9) : nor would you choose a pilot, or a carpenter, or a flute-player, as you do your rulers, by casting lots (I. 2, 9). (Cf. Polit. 258 b, 290 e, 292 b, 298.) e " And therefore the speculation that all things by a scale did ascend to was excellent in Parmenides and Plato, Unity." — Bacon, though in them only a speculation, TO THE STATESMAN. xvii 2. The imago of a herdsman, under which the king is at first conceived, common enough certainly in poetry, was one which Socrates delighted to use. "It is a bad herdsman {fioG>v dye'A?;s j'o/xetk) who makes the number of the cattle less/' was his well-known censure of the thirty tyrants (I. 2, 32). The coincidence of language here is enough to justify the sup- position that there is some connexion of thought : although Plato evidently thinks that there arc cases where taking the heads of citizens may be a purgation of the common weal. (261 d alib., 293 d.) 3. The distinction of the king and tyrant in Mem. IV. 6, I2 f , is nearly the same with that which Plato accepts pro- visionally at one stage of the dialogue (277 d); and the same passage of XenophonS expresses what Plato speaks of as the commonly received mode of characterizing the several forms of government (291 e). The thought however is here so ob- vious that it would not be safe to lay much stress on this coincidence, if taken alone. 4. The general and the judge (aTparrjyLKos, 8i/caoriKos) are named by Socrates as next in dignity to the statesman (ttoXitl- kos). Mem. II. 6, 38. Cf. Polit. 305. But the chief traces of the historical Socrates in this dia- logue, as in the Sophistes, are the method of definition by exclusions, and the use of common examples to suggest hypo- theses 11 : both much extended, and if not systematized, yet made the objects of reflection and theory ; but in their en- larged features bearing unmistakeably the marks of their first origin. (See Sophist, sub. init., note on Sco/cpar?;?.) Turning from the Socrates of Xenophon to the Platonic Socrates, we find a passage of the Euthydemus, in which the f Ba elvaf otrov 5' e/c rifj.ijiJia.Toov, fj.ev a.fxvSe rot twv iroKiwv apxh", fiaffi\et Sco/cpares, SeTjtrei, T<2y Ti]v 8e o.k6vto}v Kal /xt? koto v6fxovs, oTcuTeW Kal twv tzktSvoop Kal rtav oAA' (jttws b iLpxw fiovXono, rvpav- x a ^ K€& " / ' Ka ^ T"P ol/j-at aiirovs ^8rj yj'5 a# KaTaTZTp?(pdai Siadpv\Aovfj.4vovs virb s Kal oirov fiev £k twv tos v6/j.ijj.a ctov Kal tuv (Sovk6\wv ye. Cf. e-rriTeXovvTaiv at apxal KaOitrravrai, Gorg. 491 a, Sympos. 221 e. TaVTf\V r))v -KoAiTiiav apis VVV elires rb /xerpiou el-rran/. aAAa ti 1 ivr\ yap 6 ayefxevu Kal &pxoov awau- rb /xerptov Kai oiroffov rjyreov. row debs els ael £d>v, jjlovijxos, aKivaros, They coincided with Socrates in avrbs avrcu 6/j.o7os, cirepos tSiv &\\ aw. xxii INTRODUCTION our present purpose. But it seems probable on the whole that the school at the earlier period of which wo speak combined a ceremonial asceticism with a noble and elevating morality. We know that such was the ethical teaching of Empedocles, who was a Pythagorean in this respect, and who at one time cries, Ou Tre'Aerat rots [xev Oe/xiTov Tobe, toIs 6° dOqurrrov a\Xa to fxev ttolvtcov vop.i[xov bid t zvpvpAbovTOs aWepos -qveKeuts rirarai, bid t' anXirov avytjs, and presently, with still greater vehemence, AeiAoi, TiavbeiXoC, Kvd\xa>v duo Yetpos €^ecr6i m ! i. The idea of an infinite past, and of great cycles of time, which took such hold of Plato's imagination, and which he himself refers to an Egyptian source, was probably common to him with the Pythagoreans, and if not derived from them, must have been strengthened by their teaching. According to Porphyry (V. Pyth. 19), "Pythagoras" taught that all events took place in cycles and there was nothing new : on Kara nepiobovs tlvcls to. yiyvo^vd ttotz irdXtv yiyverat, viov 8' ovbev dirX&s ecrrt. The bearing of this on the " great mythe " is sufficiently evident. 2. Plato also held in common with them, and may have partly received from them, a strong sense of the inevitable prevalence of evil in the world. It is not likely that he derived this from Socrates, who complained not of evil but of ignorance, and who refrained from cosmical speculation : and this vein of reflection is deepest in his latest works. Theophrastus (Met. 9. Ritter and Preller, no) speaks of Plato and the Pythagoreans as being at one on this subject. "The nature of the whole, they say, would be impossible without the existence of an absolute formlessness and indefi- niteness and disorder (cf. Polit. 273 d, ds top rrjs dvop,oioTr)Tos airetpov ovra roirov bvrj), which they oppose to the combination of the indefinite dyad and the One. This disorder has as it m It is perhaps worth notice that iroiov/xevovs ineivov fiaOrjTas ehai fj.aX- the ffiooirr) of the Pythagoreans was in Kov crfyuivTas Qavfjca^ovaiv ^ robs inl some shape contemporary with Plato. to? \4yew /j.eylo-T7ju b~6£av exovras. See Isocrates Busir. 29, tovs irpocr- TO THE STATESMAN. xxiii were an equal share with the other nature, or even exceeds it. Hence even God cannot be supposed able to bring all things to perfection; but, if he be the cause of things, this is only bo far as nature admits. And perhaps he would not choose to do so, since there must follow an annihilation of Being, which is composed of opposites." This passage, although probably describing at second -hand a theory not clearly understood, sufficiently proves that the prevalence of imperfection was a difficulty much discussed, by the semi-Pythagoreans of the Academy ; and it is this difficulty which suggests to Plato's imagination the occasional dereliction of the world by God. He modifies Pythagorean optimism, by bringing into prominence another side of their theory. The disorder out of which the whole was brought into the present order, the breaking out again of this disorder so as almost to bring Chaos back again, the fear that but for Divine interposition the world might founder in the " infinite abyss of dissimilitude," are touches vividly recalling this doctrine. The Politicus contains another trace of this cuxop^os ni\a phanes, about Pythagoras and the dog, iravra kou at/dpcoTroicn irpoin]VTJ cprjpes shew, however, something of a similar t' olccuoi re, r] re SeS-qei. tendency. And Empedocles comes xxiv INTRODUCTION existed, Plato has used it ( i ) to point liis irony, by telling us not hastily to distinguish man from the beasts, some of whom perhaps regard him with the same contempt with which he looks on them ; and (2) to adorn his talc by the circumstance of man confabulating with the other creatures, when "there was nothing wild." That abstinence from the flesh of animals was not unknown in Greece, at least in the way of tradition and theory, is cer- tain from a remark of Plato's on the " Orphic" way of life (Legg. 6, 782 c), and from the lines in which Empedocles vehe- mently condemns the opposite practice, on the ground that so men are devouring their own flesh and blood . (Compare Aristoph. Ran. 1032 p .) And it is probable that Plato alludes to this when he says that the creatures did not eat each other in the golden age (ovk rjv ayptov ovh\v ovbe aWyjkcov e5w8at). Another prohibition, having evidently the same origin, and ascribed by Herodotus to the Pythagoreans in common Vith. the Orphic mystics and the Egyptians, was that against bury- ing in wool. Closely allied to these Orphic notions is the idea of purifica- tion (KaOapubs) , of which there are several applications in this dialogue and in the Sophist. (Soph. 226 d ; Polit. 293 d, 303 d, 308 c, d. Compare the Phsedo.) Thus the idea of division or separation as well as that of combination (StaKpto-ts as well as avyKptais) had a root in the speculations of this school. 4. It remains to notice the most important, but unfortu- nately the most doubtful, of the points at which this dialogue touches on Pythagoreanism. The fancies hitherto mentioned belong to morals and religion. Must not a school which aimed at influencing states have had a political theory, how- ever simple ? ° Mop(p)]V 5' aWa^ayra naT-tjp /jLeydpoicri /ca/c?V aKeyvvaro Scura. uis 5' aureus Ttarep' vlbs lAaif ko.1 /J,rjrepa ircuSes, dvfj.bv aTroppaiaavre, iroi$ 7rapeo-x»?ju.au<7rai. — ©eopAp.6v evrL irpayp-a ftaariXda. (Diotog. Tiepl /3ao-tAeia?. Mullach. Fragm. PP- 534-5-) Xprj top fiauiXia aocpbv i]p.ev ovtco yap eo-eirai avrtrip-os ko\ (rjkdOTas r<3 Trpdrco 6eG>. Ovtos yap Ka\ v KOivbv dyadbv evappovTia tls koI tu>i> ttoWoJv 6p.o(p(t)Via p-erd ireiOovs avvaboLaas. 'O /car' dperdv e£dpxo>v /caAe- erai re j3acrL\evs Kal evrt, ravrav eyav (ptKiav re nal Koivoaviav ttotl rcos vtt' avravTov, dvitep 6 6eb$ ttotl re top Koap-ov Kal ra ev avr<2. "OXav be rav evvoLav XPV 7rapaanevdCea6aL irpdrov p.ev irapd tG> /3as f3a(n\evop.eva)S, bevrepov be irapd r&vbe 1 Compare with this the Oths Koyos of the Plnedo, 85 d : also the Parmenides, 134 c. xx vi INTRODUCTION es tov ftacrtXea, buoia ytvvdropos ttoti vUa kcu ttoti TToip.vav vo/xiws kcu v6\m ttotI xpw/aeWs- avrw. (Ecphantus, irepl fiaat- Aeias. Ibid. p. 537-) Xw fxev Oebs ovre ota/coVcos Zyj&v ovre vvapeTas ovt av Trpomd^i Tivl XP ( ^/ jtei '°S ovbe (TT€(j)avS)u ?) avayopevoov ra>s TT€tOop.£vo&s r] ariixafav rws aireiOeovTas — apyii — "^' ot/xai i;ap£yo>v d£io/Lu- [xarov kuivrov (a\ov ZvTtOrjTi ttchtl r?/s glvtgj (fwmos. ... 06 cTrCyijos Trap" ap.lv /3arnAei)s tiQ>s ov\ opt-oCm avrapKris ; aneiKafav re yap avTov, evl av aTreifcdtrae tu Kpartcrrw, /cat Ttd^res eauraK ireLpcop-evoi tovtm 6p.oiovv fiacnXtKol tcrovTai' ra 5' ocra /3ias ical av&yKas ivrl twv vitoTiTayfiivbiV, £viot<- e/ rav irepl rav p.ip,acnv irpoQvp.iav dcpaipeerar x^P's tvvoias yap dp.d)^avov e£o- [xoicadrjvai, a /xdAiara iravrav acpavi^t to (poftepov. I2s tide r\v ras avdptoiTLvas cpwio? bvvarbv acpekev rb Kal neiOovs rivas biecrOaL en^Lb-qnep TreiOii) epyov rl kvri irapoLKtov dvdyKa,' Ttpaxa yap a$ ra> KaA<2 xp?jrai, tovtols ovbep.(a ttzlOovs albcas' e7reiS?/7rep ovbe cpd/3o? avdyKas. 'KvepydaatTo 5' av p.6vos 6 /3ao-iAei>? av0puma> cpwei Kal robe to dyaOov, ws bta p.ip.acnv avTui tS> Kpicrcrovos ttotI to biov eirecrtfai. (Ibid. p. 53$ ■) There is much more to the same purport. Now are we to suppose that this somewhat crude represen- tation of what ought to be (resembling perhaps suspiciously in some features the Stoical wise man) is merely a caricature of Plato's philosopher-king, or had both pictures an ante- cedent in Pythagorean teaching ? However this may be, there is no mistaking the strong likeness between the ideal herein absolutely set forth, and that which Plato in the Politicus, according to his manner of treating contemporary views, first states, then gently sets aside, and in the sequel utilizes in a modified form. " In speaking of the king as the shepherd of his people, we borrowed the image of majesty from a theo- cratic time. Yet the true statesman is he who rules with knowledge, and harmonizes the state, bringing together the diverse elements of good, and rejecting the bad. He who does this not merely imitates but reproduces the divine image." On the above data, imperfect as they are, I hazard the following conjecture : That the idea of the rightful sovereignty TO THE STATESMAN. xxvii of wisdom existed in the Pythagorean school before Plato. That Plato's Republic, partly inspired by this, had given a fresh impulse to the same line of thought amongst the Pytha- gorizing students of the Academy ; and that Plato, having in the Sophistcs criticized the speculative idealism of these friends of his, being himself perhaps somewhat iVcsilhixiunnr, proceeds to call in question their equally premature idealism in politics : shewing, first, that a " paternal government " does not secure happiness unless it rouse intelligence ; and, secondly, that you must "first catch" your ideal king before you can apply your theory to practice. Even if this conjecture should prove baseless, it will hardly be questioned that the analogy which is more than hinted between the Cosmos and the State (w ^v\j.jxiixovixevoi koX avve- TToixevot k.t.K. — 274 d), the " purification" of the body politic, and the harmony of divers elements in the web of social life, are notions having a near affinity to Pythagorean teaching. Nor would it be rash to affirm the same of the theory of opposite virtues, which is certainly not Socratie, and is in- troduced as an unusual saying (ovk dwOora koyov ovhajx&s — 306 b). Speaking generally, the most obvious affinities to Pytha- goreanism in Plato's later writings are, 1. An inci'easingly religious spirit. 2. Intense interest in all scientific inquiries, to which the name $ikor(TIO\ We now turn from these preliminaries to examine Plato's thoughts as they arc presented to us in this dialogue. And here there are three topics which chiefly call for remark : the fable of Cronos ; the description of existing constitutions, and, in connexion with this, the theory of legislation. III. The Myth. This is not the place for discussing, except incidentally, the nature of Plato's myths as a general feature of his writings. But the solution of several questions which are suggested by this particular talc may perhaps throw some light on the wider problem. (i) What is the motive for interrupting the argument with this narrative '( (2) In how far, or in what sense, does Plato believe in the truth of his own story ? (3) Is there any humour mingled with the apparent solemnity of tone ? (4) What are the precise ideas to whose working this imaginative creation is due? (5) Can these ideas be reconciled with those which Plato has elsewhere expressed ? (6) What eifect has the narration in determining the course of argument which is pursued in the remainder of the dialogue ? (1.) The chief motive of the fable is to recal the mind from resting in a merely abstract ideal. " We are not living in the golden age :" that is, in forming our conception of true states- manship we must take account of the imperfect conditions of the actual world. In order to impress this lesson, the simple notion of one who should feed his flock like a shepherd is drawn out at length, embodied in a tale, and associated with a state of innocence and ease, before man eat bread by the sweat of his brow, when all creatures lived in harmony. And still further to point the contrast between the ideal and actual, the gates of this Eden are closed by the story of a change or fall, not caused by any antecedent sin or curse, but by the necessity inherent in created things. An air of probability and even of historic truth is given to this strange fiction, by finding in it an explanation of several fragments of early mythological tradition. The Stranger admits that he has allowed himself to ex- tend his fable beyond what was necessary for the argu- TO THE STATESMAN. xxix mcnt. Hence there is no reason why every detail .sliouM be made to square with the main design. Plato, as is his wont, passes at once from the immediate question to the more general one, of which it is a part ; from the imperfect con- ditions of human government to the origin ami necessity of evil; so that the cosmical features of the myth grow out of proportion to the political. But the language with which the myth is introduced and the after-comment leave no doubt as to the purpose for which it is inserted. " The king, unlike other herdsmen, has many rivals, who likewise feed the flock." " The reason of this difficulty is that our definition confounds the king with the Divine shepherd, whereas the statesman of our age cannot in any sense be a nourisher of his people." As the tale proceeds, there is developed a further lesson : namely, that the simple ideal of a state of innocence is not only impracticable but incomplete ; that a ft Cos reAeio?, a life under perfect conditions, is not necessarily the happiest life. The question is how the life is used: the philosophic spirit is the one essential of true happiness : even one whose choice of a life has been restricted, may, if he use opportunity with all his might, have a tolerable existence (nal reAevrcua> Itiiovti, £vv I'w khop.£vu>, avvTovcos (5>vtl Ktirai filos ayairriros, ov kclkos — Rep. 10, 619 b) ; though if the children of Cronos used their golden time rightly, no doubt they were far happier than we can be. (Cf. Rep. 6, 497 a : 'AAAd roi, r\ 8' 6s, ov ra lAd^cra av hia-npa^aixzvos airaWaTTOLTo. Oiibe ye, elirov, tcl p\iyiara^ p.r\ Tvyuv TtoXireias irpoariKovaj-js' kv yap rrj vpoo-rjKovar] avTos re fxaWov av£r}(T€Tai nal juera ray t8iW ra koivol acacrei.) Plato has shewn in two other passages that au ideal formed by abstracting from existing evils is no sufficient help towards the conception of political or moral excellence ; that virtue is not to be sought in the unconscious innocence of childhood ; — once in describing the simple or primitive state in the Republic, Glaucon's " city of pigs," where " man's life is cheap as beast's," and again in the endeavour to conceive the origin of society at the opening of the third book of the Laws. But in the former description man needs defence against the in- clemency of winter, is not exempt from work, and answers to the definition of a cooking animal, though his cooking is of the simplest. In the latter the mountain shepherds whom the xxx INTRODUCTION flood of Deucalion spared to be a sort of germ of future humanity, living peacefully together because they bad few companions and there was enough for all, when there were neither poor nor rich, nor insolence, nor injustice, nor envy, but simplicity and good faith, are not set forth as an ideal, though they arc said to be better than men after them, but are pictured in order to assist the conception of the origin of law, by imagining a previous state of " patriarchal" govern- ment in which the habits and traditions of each family were supreme. Legislation became necessary when these clashed in the early life of cities 8 . Here, on the other hand, Plato has given his fancy free scope to revel in the details of a spontaneous universal life : where there is no unsatisfied longing, no effort, no pangs of birth, no crying of the infant " that he is come to this great stage of fools*," no old age, no flesh that sees corruption : the more unlike his picture is to present realities, the better he attains his end, by enforcing the necessity (however unwelcome, Legg. 803 b, eon hi] Toivvv ra tu>v avOpuiroov Ttpay^aia }xzy6.\.r]s [xev v na\aiG>v a^o/xotoCiTes raj aA?/#ei to \j/evbos otl ixakiara, ovtco XPV (Ti l J - 0V TiOLovfxsv. Rep. 2, 382 d). A myth therefore, in the Platonic sense, is a fictitious narra- tive, (a) conveying true ideas, and (6) in reference to occurrences v "See Timeeus, 20 d, 21 a,d, 26 c. * " Gorgias, 523 a. Compare pp. And so Critias invokes Memory to help 526 d, 527 a ; Meno, Si d, e." him in relating the whole story." y " Politicus, 26S e, 269 a, b." xx.xii INTRODUCTION beyond the range of actual knowledge, supplying imagined probabilites for ascertained facts. The latter is Plato's version of the ordinary function of mythology (Critias, p. no a, ixvQo- \oyta yap aya{iJTr)arL$ re tu>v irakaiGiv //era crxoA//? afx ZttI ras 7ro'A.eis tpxcvdov) ; the former is the special condition or limit which he imposes on its nse. In practice this conception of the myth is further modified, by the dramatic and poetic form in which Plato's philosophy is cast. The myth in the Protagoras, for example, though closely parallel in some of the details to that in the Politicus, is meant to convey an idea which Socrates combats and which Plato evidently does not fully accept. So also the elaborate myth of Aristophanes in the Symposium contains a phase of thought about the origin of Love, which is afterwards glanced at as an hypothesis of little value (Symp. 205 e). And as the myth is coloured to suit the particular speaker, so it partakes of the peculiar spirit of the particular dialogue. We hear nothing in the Phaedrus about the judgment of the dead, nor in the Republic about the wings of the soul, nor in the Sym- posium about her previous existence and future life ; nor in the Gorgias about the edict of Lachesis. And if there is not perfect consistency in these greater matters, there is of course still more variety in the minor incidents with which Plato's fertile imagination when once set to work gives all the distinct- ness of reality (evdpyeiav) to each separate picture. The harmonist of Plato's myths would have a task only less difficult than the rationalist of the old mythology (are aypoiKp.€vos, TroXXrjs avr<2 cr)(oXri$ Se^oret). But Plato, like every poet, delights in making his fiction as like life as possible, and amongst other artifices is the asseveration of the truth of what is said. When Critias calls Mnemosyne to his aid, or when Socrates in the boldest part of the Phaedrus says, " We must speak the truth, especially since truth is our theme 2 ," is it possible not to detect a covert smile? And when the speaker in the Timaeus so carefully traces every link in the chain of tradition by which the tale of Atlantis had come through Egypt to Solon, and from Solon to the aged Critias, are we not at once reminded of the words * It is of this part that Socrates is somewhat abated, eoi/ce . . . tk \x\v says afterwards, when his fine frenzy &AAa 7rca5iS TrrnauffQai. TO THE STATESMAN. xxxiii of Pluedrus (which by the way have reference to an equally circumstantial tale), "0 Socrates, you can make Egyptian stories or any others with equal case" ? The words of Socrates to Calliclcs, " You will call this a story, but I call it a true account," must be interpreted by the remark which follows : "You will despise this as an old wives' fable, and indeed it would be natural to despise my words, if we could find any- thing better or truer, but in all our inquiries this one principle remains firm, that Ave must fly from doing more than from suffering wrong •" where Socrates insists on the truth, not of the myth itself, but of the lesson which the myth conveys. It is probably from the same artistic instinct and with the same purpose of giving an air of probability to his inventions, that he founds them, as it is indeed natural he should do, upon the traditions already familiar to his countrymen. These formed the common medium through which he could communi- cate his ideas. He moulds them, indeed, with great ingenuity to his purposes. Poets had always dealt freely with mythology. But by appealing to the story of Atreus, or Deucalion, or Prometheus, for confirmation of some part of his recital, he seemed to bridge the gulf between the known and unknown. This practice, as well as the groundwork of Pythagorean beliefs, with which Plato had, no doubt, strong personal sym- pathy, gives a degree of consistency to the body of the Platonic myths which they would not have otherwise. And he assumes Such an air of simple truthfulness in telling his story, that by this art concealing art, a certain probability is given to the wildest imaginations. " Uncertainties now crown themselves assured." It is chiefly in the latest dialogues that the myth is seriously applied by Plato to the second of the two purposes which he acknowledges in the Republic, the reproduction of prehistoric events. There seems to be a transition, or growth, on the imaginative side of his philosophy corresponding to that already noticed on the dialectical side : from the abstract to the concrete, from vague fancies instinct with speculative ideas, like the procession in the Phsedrus, to supposed facts, like the war of Athens with Atlantis. He seeks to apply his meta- physical philosophy, which by this time acknowledged a prin- ciple of change and production, to the interpretation of the actual world, and he supplies the defects of experience and *f xx\.\ 1\TI!0!)!(TION observation by the help of imagination. Ami he claims for his (ales the same degree of truth which he assigns to poetry (Legg. 3, 682 a): Qdlov yap ovv hi) Kal to ttoltitlkw evOearrriKov ov yeVos virviohovv irokkow tow kcit' aXi'jOeiav yiyvo\iivi>w £vv Tim Xdpim Kal Moixrais er/>a7rrerai kudo-Tore. This tendency may be illustrated by comparing the Republic, TimsBUS, and Laws, of which the order of sequence is undoubted. The city founded in the Republic has no local habitation on earth, unless in some unknown and distant land, " far enough out of our ken/' though perhaps such a state may have existed at some period in the infinite succession of past time. In the Tima3iis and Critias this state is discovered, not far away in place, but remote in time, the Athens of a forgotten age contending successfully against a nation who were all that historical Athens desired to be. The state for which the Athenian Stranger legislates in the Laws, is a new Cretan settlement, imaginary of course, but imagined under the conditions of Plato's own time. To return now to the Statesman and to apply some of the preceding remarks to the myth before us. The main incident, the change on which all other change depends, is mentioned nowhere else by Plato. The artistic completeness and unity of the Great Myth is very striking. Though it differs from other Platonic myths, it may be said to comprehend them from a greater imaginative height. He speaks in the Timaeus of periodic destructions of life upon the earth by earthquake, fire or flood, and in the Laws the same thing is assumed. But the reverse movement of the whole universe, the relinquish- ment of the helm of the great vessel, and the consequent gradual deterioration of all things, is a conception occurring nowhere else. It is adopted for the occasion, for the enforce- ment of a particular lesson. The old fable of the autochthones is one which Plato delights in using. It appears in the Prota- goras, Symposium, Republic, Sophist, Tima3us, Critias, and elsewhere. But it is nowhere else imagined that men coming fullgrown from the earth, go backwards through the stages of manhood, boyhood, infancy, and so pass away. There is a picture of a theocracy, founded on the reign of Cronos, in the Critias and Laws as well as here. But here only the other animals are placed under Divine superintendence as well TO THE STATESMAN. as man, and a reason is given for the cessation of this form of government. Again, while here and in the Laws the Divine guidance is immediate, in the Critias, Eephaestus and Athena act by creating good men as legislators. These dis- crepancies are not greater than those previously mentioned, and therefore cause no suspicion of spuriousness, but they suffice to shew how little wisdom there would be in taking Plato's meaning literally; or in attributing the care which is taken to provide a channel through which the tradition may have been preserved, or the solemn air with which disbelief is deprecated, to anything but the anxiety of a Defoe or Swift to make the illusion as complete as possible. (3.) This leads us to the third question proposed above — Is there an element of humour in the fable or in the manner of telling it? If on other grounds we believe Plato to be the author of the Politicus, we can hardly doubt that there is. He must have felt the humorousness of making the respondent answer so promptly to the first statement of the astounding fact, " All that you say seems extremely probable ;" and he must have shared the amusement of his reader in contem- plating the dwindling forms of the earth-born race: just as Empedocles (however firmly he believed it) must have smiled, if he had any humour, at his own invention of the Kopacu avav)(€ves, the /3pa)^[oves evvLbes wphyv, the fiovyevr) avbpo- Trpoopa, and avbpocpvrj fiovKpava. Having again alluded to this singular passage (Polit. 270 d, e). it may be well to take the opportunity of explaining the motives which seem to have suggested the addition of this peculiar feature. It has the twofold effect of giving greater consistency and completeness to the story, and of pointing the contrast between the two alternate cycles. A link was needed to combine the change in the heavenly motion with the production of mankind from earth, which Plato chose, for a purpose of his own, to associate with the spontaneous generation of all things in the reign of Saturn. A hint for this appeared in the description of Hesiod : " They had no old age : their death was like a sleep/'' Now if, like the heroes of Cadmus, they rose full- grown from the ground, and saw not grey hairs, since their age could not stand still, it must go backwards. And this would be only in accordance with the change in the universal motion, *f % txxvi [XTHOnrCTION a change of ku^o-is followed by a change of yeVeo-ts. But the more naturally the result follows from the premises, the more effectively it strikes the imagination with the greatness of the supposed revolution. Hence it is put in the foreground of the picture, p-eyuarov h\ -nobe k. t. A. And here there peeps out a deeper vein of ironical humour from beneath the matter-of- course gravity of the narration. " If ever there is a beneficent paternal government on earth/' Plato seems to say, " it will be when iron swims and rivers run back to their fountains*." But it need not be assumed that he has no sympathy with the ideal at which he smiles, as being ev^decrrepov tov biovros- Compare Theaet. 200 b, yeWois nepio-TtpeGxnv, Rep. 7, 536 b, yeko'iov 5' eyvyt koi kv rw Trapovn eoi/ca imdeZv, where Plato openly laughs at his own enthusiasm. (4.) But if the myth is poetry and not history, and is even tinged with humour, what are the serious thoughts which this strange medium is chosen to convey ? There is, first, the main purpose which has been already described, to lift the imagi- nation to the conception of a theocracy, and so to remove by a sort of "homoeopathic" remedy the crudities of a shallow optimism. Very similar means are used in the Laws to shew that unlimited monarchy is unsuitable for the present state of man. But when this principal thought is once admitted, other reflections crowd in. They are such as the following. In our present state, evil is inextricably mixed with good : and is indeed so predominant, that God would seem to have left the world to itself. For in all that is created, evil is the necessary consequence of freedom. The practical lesson for man is that he too is made the guardian of his own life, and in conjunction with necessity, the builder of his own destiny. And as the universe and the animal kingdom follow, so far as they can recall it, the pattern of the Divine cycle, so man should track out everywhere the vestiges of the Divine wisdom which still remain b : believing, that although the Creator has a The notion of " a life which is a rrw/xa acpo/j-oiov/xeva. " For the child is gradual disrobing of the spirit from its not Plato's type of the unclouded earthly dress," which one interpreter reason, the " best philosopher, seer finds here, is well imagined, but is blest" of Wordsworth, surely inconsistent with the words, b '6v Ka\u>v epyo)V 7) 7rpo? o\}/lv i] irpbs o.ko/]V tl -npoo-fiaXji, ctxnrep avpa (j)€povaa aub XP r l" (jtG)V TOTTOiV vyUiav, koX evdvs ck Ttaiboov XavOavrj ets o/xoidnjra re kcu (pikcav Kal ^vpxjmviav rw /caAw Ao'yw ayovrra — Rep. 3, 40 1 a) (6.) Plato often allows a theory which he has formally re- jected to influence the after-course of the discussion. Thus in commenting on the Theastetus it was observed that the theory of " impressions " although discarded is afterwards applied (209 c, Ttplv av r) o-i/xdrris avrr} btacpopov tl p,vr\\x^iov Trap" 1 qjiol €va-rnxr}vap.evr] Ky 5e a/x&Xii- pressed in the Laws is the religious repov. counterpart of the severance of the 1 4, 713. The sense of the distance ideal from the actual which is so of man from God so frequently ex- strongly felt in the Politicus. xiu (vntonucT'- nently in view. In the timocracy, wliich nearly corresponds to the Laconian ideal, the spirited clement gains predominance, and is emancipated from the control of the reason. In the other three forms,, Desire, first, of wealth, secondly, of unre- strained action, thirdly, of gratifying the ruling passion, has the upper hand. Three distinct arrangements are adopted in different places of the Laws, all different from that just mentioned : — i. The order of historical development. Legg. 3, 676-683. a. Single families, without written laws. 0e/Lucrrevei 5e e/caoros Tiaiha>v ?}8' ako^u>v o£S' a\Xi]\a)v aKeyovaup. b. Patriarchal Government, Bao-i\eiW Tjaaav Smclio- TaT7]V. c. The early life of cities, in which opposite customs are harmonized by legislation. d. Maritime cities are built ; the beginning of commerce, war, sedition. e. Return of the Heraclids. Laconian and Cretan con- stitutions. 2. Two prime forms, democracy and monarchy, representing the tendencies of the West and East. The best constitution must have an admixture of both, so as to secure order and liberty. The Laconian and Cretan settlements had this good fortune. Legg. 3, 691. 3. For the above-named reason, these alone of existing governments deserve the name of noXiTda. The four com- monly named, royalty, aristocracy, democracy, and tyranny, are not constitutions, but factious coteries (oracncoreiai), which govern, not for the interest of the state, but, as Thrasymachus said, for the maintenance of the existing authority. The only true constitution is that in which, instead of one part of the city being in subjection to another part, all are together subject to the rule of reason in the form of law. In the Politicus we have first an enumeration of the forms of government according to common notions : then a criticism of these, followed by a fresh enumeration. Common opinion is said to acknowledge five forms instead of the three vaunted by Thrasymachus in Rep. bk. 1. Instead TO THE STAT sliii of his "tyranny" we have the higher generalization of mon- archy (tho word twvapxia occurs only in the Folitieus and the Laws). This is subdivided into royalty and tyranny, according as the subjects are Avilling or unwilling. Instead of his "aristocracy" we have the more general ?} ittb twv 6kLyu>v hwaaTtta, (cf. Legg. 7 10 c, okiyapyjia ri]v tov tolovtov, i.e. tov vofJLoOerov, yivzcriv yakenuiTaTa bvvaiT b.v irpocrbtgacrOai' irkeurTot. yap Iv avr% hwacrrai yiyvovTCLi) : which is divided, according to the principle of wealth on tho one hand, and constitutionalism on the other, into oligarchy and aristocracy "of fair name" {ti]v ev(avvp.ov). The fifth is democracy, which, whether ruling by gentleness or violence, and whether constitutional or not, has the same name. But when tried by the standard of scientific government, not one of these is found to be based on principle : they are seen not to be forms of government at all (ov TroAireicu), but only imitations more or less remote of the one true form ; and the men who head them are not statesmen, but partisans, the phantom-guardians of phantom-states. Of the imitations however, some are better, some are worse. And here a principle is admitted which had no place in the perfect state. The better or worse of the bad states are distinguished by the observance or defiance of law. All else is accident, except the original wisdom of the Laws, and the degree in which they are obeyed. Hence the original classi- fication is thus modified. First, the scientific state is alone allowed the name, so that the five are swallowed up in one (to, nivTG dvojjMTa tG>v vvv keyopiivaiv TtokiTuG>v £v p.6vov yiyovev)- But of the false states there are now 1. Monarchy with law, 2. Monarchy without law, called fiatnXtta. TvpavvCs. 3. The dynasty of a few 4. The dynasty of a few observing the laws = defying the laws = apio-TOKparia. okiyapyjia. 5. Democracy with law. 6. Democracy without law. The true state being kept apart, &ev vopcav (6). 5. oAr/apx''" (4)- 6. tv pawls (2). Now this order differs at the first glance in two important respects from that given in the eighth and ninth hooks of the Republic. These are, first, the addition of /3ao-i\eta as one of the lower forms, and, secondly, the depression of dkiyapyj-a below br]iJ.0KpaT[a. 'Ayoioro/cparta may be allowed to correspond to the TifioKparCa of the Republic. But it so happens that on both these points there is a corresponding difference between the Republic and the Laws. For in that dialogue, as we have seen, j3ao-iKe(a (a sort of eastern monarchy is probably intended) is one of the four forms commonly received to which the Athe- nian Stranger denies the name of constitution. And demo- cracy, as one of the two " mother polities'''' of which monarchy is the other, is throughout placed before oligarchy, against which Plato seems latterly to have conceived an increased enmity. (Even in the Republic he calls it o~vxvG>v yipiova-a KaK&v 7roAtreta.) When we add to these two points the coincidences of language above mentioned {p.ovapyj-a, hwaaTeia), a presump- tion is raised that the doctrine of the Politicus on this subject is nearer to the Laws than to the Republic. And on coming a little closer, we see that in the Republic these distinctions are thought to depend on essential differences of form (4, 445 d, dbrj fyovTes ; 8, 544 d, rj ti$ ko\ iv dbet bia(pavet tivi Ketrcu), and to have a natural order of sequence of which a reason can be given. But in the Politicus they are seen to be distinguished by no principle, the only real difference between states being first enlightenment or igno- rance in the ruler, and next the maintenance or the neglect of law. And not far removed from this view, though more adapted to a legislative treatise, is the assertion in the Laws that the constitutions commonly so called are not constitutions at all, and that the only true state is that where reason rules in the form of law. Once more, when in the Politicus the TO THE STATESMAN. xlv statesmen of existing states are said to be not what they pro- fess, lmt partisans (otj ttoAltlkoi d\\a o-raa-taortKot), this comes very near the remark in the Laws that the radical vice of all the received forms of government except the .Spartan and Cretan is that one part rules the rest for its own advantage. They arc not constitutions but coteries (ov 7roAiTe«u, dAAa o-rao-twreiat) . V. Theory of Legislation. The presumption thus raised is further confirmed when we examine the very curious piece of mingled satire and inquiry in which the distinction between constitutional and unconstitutional government is illustrated. " If the true sovereign and law- giver, or a second like him, were on earth/' we are told, " he would be above law ; which is only an imperfect substitute for the universal and immediate superintendence of the Per- fect Will/ - ' The physician is not bound to follow his old pre- scriptions under altered circumstances. But now he is " gone into a far country/'' or, as the myth would say, Providence has left us to ourselves : and men have despaired of finding their natural ruler, whom, when once found, they would follow like a swarm of bees. Therefore there is nothing left to them but to preserve their country's laws, which, it may be pre- sumed, were made at first after the Divine pattern, so far as those who framed them knew. What a poor business this is at best is shewn by the case of an imaginary state, in which the arts of navigation and medicine or any others should be practised according to ancient laws enacted in popular or oligarchical assemblies at the advice of chance persons. But w T hen the wretchedness of such a condition has been fully exhibited, a lower deep is opened, by imagining a state, whether democratical, oligarchical, or tyrannical, in which such laws, however imperfect, should be over-borne, not by higher knowledge, but by private gain or favour. Hence it is concluded that in the absence of a philosophic ruler, the best course possible (as a hzvrtpos nXovs) is a strict observance of the laws. Now in the Republic, the sanguine founders of that city in the heavens deliberately dispense with a minute xlvi INTRODUCTION code of laws. These aro thought unnecessary because in the greatest thing, viz. education, the whole community will be spontaneously obedient to the philosopher-king, and in little things those who have been thus educated will bo a law to themselves ; or in any case will be only what education makes them. The pages in which this thought is expressed (4, 423 e — 427 a), had they not been found in an earlier writing, might have been taken for a criticism of the Leges. It is indeed granted, in words which should acquit Plato of Utopianism (5, 472 b — 473 b), that practice can never attain to the perfection of theory, but the idea of lowering the sails of theory, in order to try a second course, when the first is hopeless, does not occur to Socrates, and certainly would be very far from acceptable to the impetuous Glaucon. The necessity of this humbler course is somewhat sadly admitted by the Athenian Stranger in the Laws. He prefaces the introduction of the very class of regulations (those which are over and above the rules for nurture and education), against which Socrates protests in the passage above quoted (9, 875 a), with the remark that laws are necessary, because no human being has at once the wisdom to see, and also the power and the will to do, at every moment what is for the universal interest, and to make his own interest always secondary. " Could one be found theoretically convinced that whatever was for the public good was on the whole good for him, yet, if placed in a position of absolute and irrespon- sible authority, he would be too weak to apply his theory consistently through a long life. His mortal nature shrinking from pain and desiring pleasure would darken his judgment of what is just and good. But if Providence were to send on earth such a nonpareil, whose nature was sufficient for this work, he would not need to place himself under the control of law. (Compare Polit. 295 b, (rx°^V <*v kavTu Oeir e/x7ro8tV- juara ypd(p(av tovs Xe^Oivras tovtovs vop.ovs.) It is because Nature has been so niggardly in this particular {vvv h\ — ov yap Zcttiv ovbapov ovbap-m, aAA' rj Kara (3pax.v) that we are forced to adopt a course which is only second-best, in enacting laws, whose application is general only, not universal." The reflection which prompts these words, viz. that prac- tical rules must be accommodated to our experience of human TO THE STATESMAN. xlvii weakness, pervades the whole dialogue, and should always be present to the reader of the Laws. It docs not follow that Plato has relinquished his ideal of life, because in recommend- ing a second-best polity to those who have refused his best, he admits some details which he had once rejected with scorn m . The feeling with which he does so could not be more clearly expressed than in the words with which he defends the admission within certain limits of election by lot: to yap €TTL€LK€S KCtl £vyjV(s)}XOV TOV TtktOV KCU (XKpl.(3oVS TiapCL hUl)V T1]V 6p0i]V eort TrapaT£0pau(xeVoi', orav yiyvrjTai n . This procedure follows naturally as a practical result from the reasoning in the Politicus. If, seeing that the philosopher- king cannot always be with his people, the only wise course for states is to maintain their laws, which have an imperfect and remote reflection of principles of divine government: suppose an occasion to arise for founding a new state, or some rare opportunity for remodelling an old one , what are the laws which, as the best possible substitute for the continual presence of an enlightened will, the true law-giver would actually impose? and what are their reasons and their sanctions? This is the problem which the Stranger in the Politicus im- plicitly suggests, but apparently despairs of answering : for the sketch with which the dialogue ends represents the highest statesmanship working without the instrumentality of law, though in a more practical way than in the Republic. m See esp. Legg. 5, 739 b : rb 5' states built on foundations which iartv opBdrara, el-rrelv /xev r-qv apiari]v reason pronounces ruinous, provokes TroAireiav kizI Sevripuv Ktxl Tpiri^v, 8ov- the reflection "what strength and vat Se elir6vra aipeaiv ktt&VTcp t£ t?/S tenacity there is in the very nature of crvvotKTicrtcos Kvp(w. a state" (&is i noticeable passage, in which human 951), though by no means an adequate art occupies only the third place with provision, for the constitutional amend- Providence and chance. There is an ment of the law. This is a step in approach to a similar feeling in Polit. advance of the political doctrine of the 302 a, where the longevity of many Statesman. xlviii INTRODUCTION An instructive parallel to the teaching of the Politicus on this subject appears in the Critias, in which three phases of political life arc described, which nearly exemplify the Elcatic Stranger's theory. First the people of prc-historic Athens, whose autochthon founders, created by Hephaestus and Athena, had been inspired by them to order their state" (as wc learn from the opening of the Timasus) in accordance with the provisions of the Republic. Next the kings of the race of Poseidon, each of whom had power of life and death in his own city, but was bound in his intercourse with the rest to obey the injunctions of their progenitor, as these had been recorded by the first of their race. These had remained unaltered as they were written in the beginning on a tablet of orichalcumi (a now fabulous metal which abounded in that realm). On this tablet was added a great curse pronounced on those who disobeyed: and a great oath, confirmed by the blood of a bull poured over the tablet, was renewed every five years : at which time also, in solemn nocturnal conclave, they condemned those who were convicted of ruling contrary to the laws. For many generations, so long as they observed these laws, and while the heroic blood remained in therm they lived happily enough, and perceiving that virtue is the true road even to earthly welfare, they bore up against the load of their material prosperity. But a time came when the human element prevailed and they were overcome by ambition and the pride of power. Then they seemed out- wardly most fortunate, but presented a pitiable spectacle to those who had an eye for deformity of soul. The fragment of the Critias ends with the resolve of Zeus to chasten them, but had the tale proceeded, we should have had placed before us the third companion picture, that of the misery of a state which, in the absence of a philosophic ruler, has a code of laws but is disobedient to them. These three con- ditions, set forth in the Critias, correspond nearly to the forms which the Politicus recognizes as alone essential : the Republic is ignorant of the distinction between the second and third : which, again, are brought into almost exclusive prominence in the Laws. p Critias, 109 d. 1 Compare the Kvpfeis of Polit. I. c. TO TIIH STATESMAN. . VI. Relation of the Politicus to the Leges. I. The description of the "Royal web" in the concluding passage of this dialogue is a more outline; yet if the sketch is anywhere finished this is not done in the Republic, but in the Laws. These both contain the idea of binding together and harmonizing the gentle and fierce elements in human nature: and the presence of this thought in the Politicus is, in so far, only a reason for grouping it with these two great works rather than with the Protagoras or any of the more Socratic dialogues, in which all virtue is simply referred to knowledge. But a more definite hypothesis is justified by a closer inspection. For, while the "divine bond" of know- ledge is a description so vague as to be equally applicable to either of the two imaginary schemes of education, the provisions respecting marriage which constitute the " human bonds " have no counterpart in the Republic, while they are re- peated almost without modification in the Laws. They imply in fact an accommodation to the existing condition of mankind which is more in accordance with the spirit of the latter than of the former dialogue. For "what need was there of uniting by mutual pledges those who never spoke of "I" or " mine/'' and who felt every grief of every member of the state with an individual sorrow? What need of qualifying opposite tendencies by intermarriage, when each individual, according to the principle on which he was selected and trained, had by nature and education the harmony of gentleness and courage within his own breast? This ideal polity is still acknowledged by the speaker in the Laws to be the one and only pattern. His object is to propound a second polity, i. c. a polity only once removed from the former, the closest imitation of the perfect government that is likely to be maintained without the presence of a succession of Divine kings. And his procedure, with the reasons for it, has several striking points of resemblance to that suggested at the con- clusion of the present dialogue. He observes that the purpose of the early legislators was not war, but peace as the reward of virtue : that in the early *h 1 INTRODUCTION life of cities it became necessary to bring together the opposite qualities of gentleness and fierceness, which, during the patri- archal period, had become embodied in the traditions of the different clans. (3, 681 b, KoapLKoTepaiv p.\v KocrpLutrepa, kol avhpiK&v avhpiKwrtpa. Cf. ib. 691 e, of the Spartan constitu- tion. Compare Polit. 310 c.) And in beginning his own legislation he compares the work he has to do (almost in the words of our dialogue) to a web composed of a warp and woof, of which the warp is stronger and so far better, having a certain firmness of disposition, but the woof is softer and has " a certain temperance which gives it smoothness." (Cf. Polit, 282 e, 309 b. In the Laws the highest rule is given to the stronger element.) But there is an earlier process to be gone through before this is begun. The state must be purged of all bad elements. Plato thinks worse of human nature than when he hoped that all children under ten years old with a few exceptions would receive the print of the new laws. (Rep. 7, sub. fin.) The purgation of the flock from tainted members must precede all else. If the legislator have supreme power, human kindness need not prevent him from taking the nearest way. Otherwise he may have recourse to the more " euphemious " plan of emigration. (5, 735. Compare with this Polit. 293 d, e, 308 b-d.) Once more, in applying the ideal which annihilates indi- vidual choice to the matter of marriage, this exhortation is made to precede the law. " The man must choose a partner not superior to himself in wealth : and, moreover, he who is conscious of a quick and forward spirit (trajuwrepoy ajj.a /ecu Oclttov tov biovTos irpbs Trdcras ras -npageis (pe.p6p.evov) should seek alliance with a family of gentle blood (Koo-piioov -naripav ylyvecrOai KTjSeor?^) : and he of the opposite temper should take the opposite course. For each should choose that marriage, not which is most pleasant to him, but which is most expedient for the common weal. Now natural inclination carries men to mate with their likes : the result of which is to accumulate differences both of fortune and character, to the manifest harm of cities. The motive of our injunction is that the state may be like a well-attempered bowl, in which the wine sparkles with maddening heat, but is chastened into smooth mellowness by the sober influence of a different power.'" TO THE STATESMAN. li (^» 773-) ft would be superfluous to draw out at length the many close resemblances between this passage and p. 310 of the Politicus. 2. The affinities of thought and doctrine, as well as of language, which we have found existing between this dialogue and the Laws, make it probable that the times of their com- position were not very far apart : and Socher's objection, that the Politicus agrees neither with the Republic nor with earlier dialogues, is met by the hypothesis that this dialogue is inter- mediate between the Republic and the Laws. To this, how- ever, it may be again objected, that while the Politicus and its immediate predecessor, the Sophistes, are amongst the most dialectical of the whole series, the very notion of dialectic in the Platonic sense is absent from the work on which the last years of Plato's life were spent. Nor is this peculiarity of his latest dialogue wholly to be accounted for by the nature of the subject. Although the method of the Republic is less exact than that of the Sophist or Philebus, yet the ideal theory which it contains is professedly made the groundwork of the political fabric, and Dialectic, as the science of ideas, and as the roof and crown of the sciences, which are them- selves viewed in their ideal aspect, is described as the in- dispensable completion of the education of the ruler. Nor yet will this further explanation suffice, that the Laws profess to take a lower ground and starting-point, and to provide only for what is second-best : and that hence, in the education of the vonoyr)) as pursued in these dia- logues. The duty of dividing according to the natural kinds is enforced in the following, amongst other passages : 2, 658 a, pi] Tayy to tolovtov Kptvwfxev, dAAa btaipovvres avrb Kara p.ipr] iTKoiru>\iz.Qa: 6, 751 a, bvo tlbi] ravra irepl 7roAireia? Koop.ov yiyv6p.zva Tvy\avti : 7, 814 e, bvo p.\v avTijs elbr] ^pj) vop.t(eiv ilvai .... Kal -nakiv tov (jiavkov re bvo Kal tov o-novbaiov bvo crepa : 10, 895 d, eari ttov Si^a biatpovpevov Iv aAAoi? re koI iv apL0p.<2: 12, 944 b, ay^ebbv ovv ii> toIs oveibeaiv e'xet Tiva Topvi]i> 7} tovt(i)v tG>v dvop.6.Tu>v £iri(pop&, where the phraseology of the Sophistes is repeated. Instances of the converse process, by which things apparently diverse are brought under one conception, are 7, 824 a, the description of the various kinds of OriptvTiKr}, which has several points of resemblance to these dialogues ; 8, 841 c, 'kv yivos ov, irtpikafibv ra rpia yevrj : 10, 894 b, &)? kv elbecri Xafie'iv : 12, 944 c, Kaipol Awews veW r\ (&OV TLVOS, OVS ZVTOVOVS T€ Kal VlTO&pLaTa Kal vevpoov Z-kitovovs, piav ovcrav (pvatv bLeo-napixivqv, ttoWcl^ov ttoXKoIs 6v6]j.aaL irpoa- ayopevovo-Lv. Much also of the terminology which arose out of the definitions of these dialogues is assumed in various places of the Laws, as has been sufficiently shewn in the General Introduction. The anomaly which we are considering will appear less wonderful, if we review the course which dialectical inquiry has taken in our two dialogues. The chief result of the Sophistes was the transition from a somewhat fanciful onto- logy to a true psychology, from a transcendental to a logical conception of Being ; first as the sum of positive determina- tions, then as the sum or ideal of true determinations, whether affirmative or negative. We have seen that this conception finds legitimate development in the Politicus in more complex views of knowledge and of the objects of know- ledge, which must be seen in various aspects and relations before they are fully known. The true affinities and discre- pancies of things are perceived by the higher faculty of the mind, not after a cursory glance at phenomena, but through a laborious process only made possible after long training. Science is the comprehension of these deeper resemblances TO THE STATESMAN. liii and differences: and scientific inquiry is the interrogation of all nature in order to discover what each kind can contribute to the store of universal knowledge. Tho only passages which remind us of the ontological or transcendental theory of the ideas are the /xerpLov (jiwij in p. 284, and the contrast between sensible and logical analogies in p. 286 a. Now the former of these is the exact expression of the philosophy which seeks to combine the absolute with the relative, as Plato seeks to com- bine these in the Philebus ; and the latter belongs to the antithesis between the things of mind and of sense, which is nowhere more strongly asserted than in the tenth book of the Laws. Even the ideal standard of to /uirpioi; is hardly con- ceived as existing apart from production (284 d, -npbs Tip rod fxerpLov yivecnv). Indeed, throughout the dialogue (see also Soph. 245 d) the Eleatic opposition between Being and Be- coming, and also between Knowledge and Opinion, appears to be softened, and even here and there obliterated. There is a sense, therefore, in which it may be truly said that, in these dialogues, metaphysical inquiry has been en- gaged in " getting rid of metaphysics/'' i. e. of transcendental ontology. The idea of scientific method takes the place of the mere enthusiastic exaltation of the ideas. That method is still held to be the privilege of a mind fitted by nature and training to discern ideas ; to discern them, however, not merely in themselves, but amidst the manifold complexities of the real world. Hence we need not wonder that in a dialogue later than the Politicus, the notion of an intellectual region, wholly separated from that of appearance and opinion, which stands out so prominently in the Republic, does not reappear. It is true that the chief interest in the Politicus is dialectical, in the Laws ethical and religious. But this, at all events, may be traced partly to the difference between a speculative and a practical treatise. As Plato himself says of his ideal state, (JMjauv eyet Trpa^LV \e£ttos t/ttov dArj^etaj itpdirTecrOaL. There is an analogous contrast between the Phasdrus and the Republic. In the infancy of the sciences, the development of a perfect method, and its application to a particular subject-matter, were achievements equally impossible. Practice and theory could not go hand in hand. As the method was necessarily immature liv INTRODUCTION (though rich in anticipative insight), so it was destined to remain unrealized. Plato often betrays his consciousness of this. He fails to seize "waking" the form which he had pursued "in a dream." At the same time it is not contended that the Politicus may not have been produced many years before the Leges were begun. In that last dialogue the method of inquiry which, theoretically at least, still rules in the Statesman and Sophist, has given place to what is virtually a method of exposition ; and the author's mind seems in both cases to be wholly possessed by the impulse which is dominant for the time. It is hardly credible that two such different modes of handling the same subject should have reigned simultaneously, and therefore it is best to suppose an interval. But this supposition does not weaken the force of the cumu- lative arguments by which it has been now sought to deter- mine approximately the relative position of this dialogue amongst the writings of Plato. And in the occasional abruptness and absence of connexion in the Politicus there are not wanting symptoms of the approaching loss of dialectical as well as of artistic freshness and power. VII. References to the Politicus in Aristotle. That Aristotle was acquainted with this dialogue appears from many coincidences of thought and expression. Several instances, chiefly from the Politics, will occur in the notes. (See especially, besides the passage mentioned below, Ar. Pol. I, i, oool [xev .... [XLKpav ttoXlv (cf. Polit. 259 a — c) : ibid., ayeXaiov (coov : ibid. 2 sub fin., rj be kti^tlki] OrjpevTLKrj : II, 5> °^ ov laTpiKT) djuoiws £x etv ( c ^ Polit- 298) : ibid. 7, to /x?/ Kara ypappiaTa frpyeiv, aXX' avToyi>(6p,ovas, iinacpaXes : III, 2, "Ecrri yap apxv becrnoTLKij biaKOVMas -npageis (cf. Polit. 259 c — 260 c, 304) : ibid. 6, larpos b" 1 . . . . rots dbocnv (cf. Polit. 259 a) : ibid. 8, axnrep yap debv ev avOpcairoLs (cf. Polit. 303 b) : ibid. 10, bone? brj toXs vop.i(ovo-i apyziv rj\i0Lov: IV, 12, apxp-s XeKTeov Tavras, oaais a7roSeSorai fiovXev- oacrQai re Ttepi rtvoov Kal Kplvai koI k-nira^ai, nal jwaAicrra tovto, to yap l-niTo.TTt.lv dpxtKwrepoV Igtiv (cf. Polit. 260 a) : VII, 13, ei TO THE STATESMAN. lv ixkv toLvvv apxtw kciI upxeaOat (cf. Polit. 301 d). It is true that, considering the common atmosphere of philosophical debate which surrounded both writers, these resemblances do not amount to proof; but they render it probable that Ari- stotle had read the dialogue and was familiar with some of its contents. Hence it is the more strange that in the one place in which he appears to refer directly to the Politicus, he not only omits the author's name (this would be no new pheno- menon), but gives him the vague designation ns t&v irpoTepov, "one of those who have preceded me." The passago occurs in the second chapter of Book IV, where the question is raised, which of the declensions (7rapeK,3dcreis) from the true forms of government is the least bad ? and is as follows : lieTpiooT&Tiiv be ti]v brjpoKpariav. 7/877 p.ev ovv tis a-necpijvaTO kcu ray irporepov ovras, ov fx-qv eh tolvto fiXexjms i]\uv e/ceiros p.ev yap expive, iraaQv p.ev ovcruv e7neiKcoi>, olov 6\iyap\(as re XPW 7 ^ /ecu tu>v aXXav, xeiplaTriv h-jp.OKpaTiav, (pavXtav be apicrTi]v. The superficial relevancy of this to Polit. 303 a, b is sufficiently obvious. We may notice, however, that, as usual with him in quoting Plato, Aristotle has forgotten the connexion. Plato condemns as strongly as Aristotle all the forms of government here mentioned. With him also it is a question not of good and bad, but of degrees of badness : rls — tS>v ovk opO&v ttoXl- TeiG>v tovtoov {JKLcrra xaXeTir) wCv v > Tia-v&v X a ^ €7T ® v ovacov, kcu tls (3apvTarri ; — and it may be that Aristotle's three "right forms" would have fared no better at his hands. The word eirieiK&v, which Aristotle attributes to him, is not used at all ; the nearest approach to such an expression is Koaixiav, which is explained by vofxifjLv /3eArioT77, this is only in the same relative sense in which Aristotle uses the words cpavXcov apia-Trjv. Indeed, were Aristotle's representation true, the two philosophers would be more nearly at accord : for demo- cracy would then be described by Plato as the least bad of three bad forms, each of which is (in this case) the declen- sion from a species of right government. This kind of inac- curacy is too common to afford any ground for the con- jecture that Aristotle is not referring to the Politicus, but hi INTRODUCTION to some other writing or utterance of a previous thinker' 1 , but it lessens the wonder which is naturally excited by the careless vagueness of the expression " some one in former time." When we consider how much more Aristotle seems to have relied on the living tradition of Plato's school than on his writings for the opinions of Plato; how lax he is in quotation generally, attributing to Circe the words of Ulysses to his pilot, and the like ; how impersonal he is ; how seldom he names Plato, though often alluding to him ; when we re- member that in all his writings there is no distinct reference to such a noticeable work as the Parmcnidcs, w t c need hardly be surprised if, at the moment of writing these lines, he was not clearly aware which of all the previous speculators on the subject of politics had pronounced this opinion. It would be easy to indulge in further conjecture, but it is needless. The anomaly remains. The fact is singular, though not unaccount- able. But, if what has been said in these pages has any force, this would indeed be slender evidence on which to question the genuineness of the Statesman. This dialogue is fastened by too many threads of contrast, as well as of resemblance, to the place which has been now assigned it in the Platonic canon, to be dropped from thence by the mere negligence of Plato's younger contemporary r . VIII. The " Philosopher " dialogue. The " Statesman" contains a sketch of the real as well of the counterfeit ruler. The " Sophist" was mainly occupied in proving the existence of a counterfeit of the philosopher. The last and (according to the "geometrical" proportion indicated in Polit. sub. init.) by far the greatest part of the Stranger's ?; kclto. Ti]v dvaXoyiav ti]v rr/9 v/JLerepas Te^vt]?. s GEO. E?3 ye vri tov rj/ierepov 6eov, co ^LcoKpare?, TOV "A/JL/ULCOVa, KOU SlKaLCO?, KOLL TTO.VV fieV 0VV fXVY}pLOVL- kcos hrejrXrj^ds ploi to irep\ tovs XoyicrpLOvs dfiap- Tyfia. kcu ere pcev dim. tovtcov elcravOis p.ereLp.C av 8' rjpiiv, co Ijeve, pLrjSapicos aTVOKapx^s yapi^opLevos, dXX oetjr}?, etre tov ttoXltlkov dvSpa irpoTepov elre tov (piXocrocpov irpoaipei, irpoeXopLevo? die^eXde. SE. TavT, co QeoScope, 7roir)Teov iirearep anatj ye eyKe^eiprjKapiev, ovk dirocrTOLTeov irp\v av avTcov p. 2< 2. Tav dvSpoov] Cf. Soph, 221 d: rjyvorjKapev Tavftpos tov avdpa ovra gvyyevr). The ideal Sophist, Statesman, Philoso- pher, are treated with fami- liarity, as persons with whom a transaction is being held. 2. *&Vro S *] All the MSS. have Bevres, but the correction of Heindorf is unquestionably right. The corruption is pro- bably due to uKrjKooTes preced- ing. Note the variety of expres- sion in df-ias — TI/J.TJ. 3. ifkeov — depeardo-tv^ Cf. Legg. 4, 722 b : ov dnrXa 6a- repa rav irepcov hiaTr]v alTrjaavTcov X^P iv ' lb. d : to S' av crol pfj x a P L C*°~6ai nal roTcrSe. d\\' igijs, etre] For the in- terruption of the sentence with etre, cf. Theset. 156 e : XevKov, etre £v\ov, etre ~\ido$ k.t.A. 12. TTOLrjTtov — aTrocrrare'oi/] For the apposition, cf. Protag. 348 a : TOVS TOLOVTOVS poi SoKet xPV vat IAip.elo~6ai epe re nal ae, KaTaOepe- vovs tovs TTOirjTas avTovs 81 rjpmv auTOiv tovs \6yovs TroielcrBai. The inferior MSS. insert ko.\ before ovk, probably from conjecture. 1 3. avTcov] " The matters in hand." Compare the frequent riOAITIKOS. Tirpos to re'Aos 1 eXdcofxev. aAAa yap irep\ Qeam-jTov TovSe tl XPV $pav fie ; GEO. Tov wept ; 3*E. AiavaTravacopev avTov /x€raAa/3cWe? avTov tov avyyvfivao~Ti]v TovSe Sco/cpar?; ; ?; ncos crvpfiov- { Xevei? ; GEO. Ka.da.7rep elrre?, fieTakd/ifiave' veco yap ovTe paov olaeTov iravTa ttovov dvaTravo/ievco. 20. Kal flTjV KLvSweveTOV, CO ij€l>€, a/JL(j)Q) iroOev i/xol ^vyyeveiav eyeiv Tivd. tov fiev ye ovv vp.el.9 Kara ttjv tov TrpoacoTrov v a^Gaipai^ Kai rovhe Trapa\T)-*\t6i.u8a ~2asKpa.Tr), tov ScDKparovs pev apmvvpov, ipbv he 7)AiKiu>Ti)v kcu o~vyyvpvao~Trjv, 0} avvSiairoveiv per epov to. 7roWa ovk dr)des. The word here, like navTa tvovov below, implies men- tal as well as bodily labour. Cf. Eep. 6, 498 b : ■Kpo'iovo-rjs he tt)s r)\u yap 6Vre] We per- ceive in Theodorus something of the consciousness of the contrast between youth and age, which appears also in the Eleate and in the Athenian Stranger in the Laws. Cf. Theaet. 146 b, 162 b. 9. nodev] " From some cause or other," " in some respect." 10. tov pev ye — olKeioTrjTa] There is a sort of humour in the conscious technicality of the language, (cpvo~LV — (patveadai — K\r)cris — opwvvpos — Trpocrprjo-ts — oixf toT?jra,)which also reminds us that we are engaged in dia- lectic. 11. opoiov epoli] Theagt. 143 e. 12. r)plv] The plural gives a more courteous turn to the expression. The dative, al- though governed by 6pa>vvpo<; — oUeioTrjTa, has something of an ethical force. Cf. Soph. 216 e. 14. dm Xoyuv] " By means of The latter at once re- sumes the leadership of the dis- cussion, and prescribes the States- man rather than the Philoso- pher for the next subject of definition.' The States- man, also, like the Sophist, is a man of art, and the arts and sciences must be again di- vided. 4 I1AAT0N02 pi&iv. QeaLTi]TU) pev ovv civtos re crvvf.p.L^a yOes p. 25 8id Xoycov kou vvv dia]Koa d7roKpivap.evov, ^.coKparovs oe ovberepa' del 8t aKe^/aaOat kou tovtov. tfioi p.ev ovv elaav0L9, 9 ip.o\ (palverai, tov ttoXltlkov avdpa Siatr/relv vav. koli p.01 Xeye, irorepov tcov i7TLO-T1]p.6vOJV TLV rjpUV KOU TOVTOV $€T€OV, Y) 770)? ', 15 NE. 20. Ovtcds. HE. Tec? einaTrjiias apa StaXrjTTTeov, wcnrep rjvLKa TOV irpOTtpOV io-K07T0VfJL€V \ NE. 20. Tax av. HE. Ou p.ev Sr) Kara tovtov ye, co ^coKpare^ 20 (f)a[veTal pot Tp.rjpa. argument," i. e. as to their men- tal qualities. Cf. Theset. 145. Socrates here shews the same urbanity as in the opening of the Thesetetus and Sophist. Compare with the structure of the sentence and the introduc- tion of the minor premiss with Sij (Bel 8)7) Theset. 143 d : ao\ drj ovk oXiyiaroi TrXrjO-id^ovat — ei 8fj ovv fjbecos av ttvOol^v, And for ye, resuming what has been already said, cf. infr. 260 c, deo-rro^ovrd ye. 12. tov noXiriKov] Bodl. A, pr. n, ttcXltixov tov. This illustrates a frequent source of corrup- tion in MSS., the inversion of the order of words. 14. The requirement that the king shall be eTTLo-TTj/icov tivos, the possessor of a perfect science, is upheld throughout the dialogue, and hence the definition of the king excludes all the actual rulers of existing communities. The question in the text is asked not without ironical allusion to this " crowd of satyrs and centaurs " (infr. 303 c), whose art, like that of the Sophist, proves to be a mere sham. Ka\ tovtov] " As well as riOAITIKOS. 258. NE. ID. TifLrjv, £?E. Kar aAAo. NE. 20. "Eolk6 ye. S"E. T?)j> ow ttoXltlkt]V drpairbv 7rfj T19 avev- pr/aei ; 8ei yap avrifv avevpelv, kgu x^P^ aTos 5 airo 7W aXXcov Ibeav amy \xlav iTrKJCppayuraaOai, Ka\ Tals aXXais exTpoirals ev aXXo eibos eiriarifiriva- jxevovs Tracras ras i7rtaTr)fjLas cos* ovcras Svo eldj] 81a- voijOrjvat tt)v ^/v\tjv i]\x r 2v woLrjaai. NE. 212. Tour' rfSr) crop, olfiai, to epyov, a> ijei/e, 10 aXX ovk kjiov ylyverai. HE. Act ye /j.r)i>, co ~2c$KpaT€9, avrb elvai /cat ar6i>, orav £fjL(f)ai>€? tj/jlIv yevrjTai. the angler (Soph. 219 a) and the Sophist (lb. 221 c)." 1. Ti fxrjv] "What then]" This less frequent signification of tl fiTjv probably contains the explanation of the general use to signify assent. " What else V = "surely." Cf. Parm. 139 d: "On ovk €TT€i8av tcivtov yevrjTai tco ti, £i> yiyverai. 'AAXa ti pr)v; k.t.\. The&'t. 142 a : nov pr)v } 4. aTpair6v~\ The Stranger recurs to the metaphor "which he employed in Soph. 222 a. This appears clearly from the word eKTpo7rah, which recals e<- Tpen€s ovaas 8uo eidrj] As constituting two classes or kinds. 12. kci\ a6v] I.e. You must make the distinction your own, go through the process for yourself. In his more systematic dialogues Plato still insists on the importance of tbe learner's following every step of an inquiry. Tly wliat path, then, does the - diverge from the bi aten way of know- Led -','■ in general ? It is the duty alike of ques- tioner and respondent to deter- mine this, while part- ing off all other by- ways, and 6 nAATONOS stamping them with a sing le negative form. The theory of numbers is an ex- ample of a class of sciences, in which knowledge is wholly separable from ac- tion. Whereas in carpentry and other handi- crafts, knowledge is bound up with NE. 20. KaAwy tines, p. 25* 1 SE. ' Ap OVV OVK dpi0fl7]TlKrj peV KCLL TlVeS €T€p(XL TavTr) avyyevels riyyo.i \J/lAou twv Trpdijecov eiai, to 8e yvwvai irapecr^ovTO povov ; 5 NE. 20. "Ear us OVTCOS. aE. Ai 8e ye wepl t€ktovlkt)v av koll avpiracrav ■yeipovpyiav dairep ev tolls Trpd^eaLV evovcrais avp(f)u- TOV TYJIS eTTLaTrjprjV KeKTrjVTCLL, KOLL (TVVOLTTOTeXoVO-L tol e yiyisopeisa vir clvtcqv aiopaTa, irporepov ovk oistol. 10 NE. 20. T/ firju ; 3(E. TaVTYj TOLVVV (TVpJTT 0L(T0L9 iTTLCTTrjpaS BldipU, tt)V peis 7rpa.KTiK.rjv TrpoatLTTCDV, tyjv 8e povov yvco- (TTLK7\V. 2. apidjirjTLKT] fJL€U — fiovov] This in modern language is the distinction between science and art. Cf. Phileb. 56, 57. 3. ■tyihai rcov Trpd^eu>v\ " Dis- engaged from pi-actice," i. e. abstract. The same word is used, infr. 299 e, to distinguish " pure arithmetic" from geo- metry and astronomy. apidp.7]- tiktj (the theory of numbers, not arithmetic in the modern sense, which more nearly an- swers to Xoyia-TLKrj,) is always spoken of by Greek philosophers as the most abstract of the ma- thematical sciences. E. g. Ar. Met. I. 2 : al e£ eXarrovcov — tcov sk 7rpo(rde'(T(a>s, oxmep dpi6p.rjTiKr] yeaiperplas. Again, in Theset. 165 a Dialectics are opposed, as yf/ikol Xoyoi, " mere abstrac- tion," to mathematics gene- rally. 4. TTapeaxovTO ] For this 'poetical' use of the aorist, cf. TheaBt. 156 d: iyepero — 7Tepuirkrj(T6rj, and note. 6. At 8e ye — KeKTrjvrai] " But in the case of carpentry and the sister arts, and of every handicraft, the knowledge is as it were merged or inherent in the operations ; and they assist in perfecting the struc- tures which result from them." Note the expression al (rexvai) eTVLO-Trjprjv KeKTijvTai. By a fu- sion of abstract and concrete common in these dialogues, the attributes of the artist are attached to the art. Cf. Phileb. 41 e: el to ^ovkt]pa — j3ov\erai. 8. avv(nroTe\ovo~i\ Sc. tri/v rals npd^eaiv. wr avTwv, SC Tap irpa^euv. 9. yiyvopeva — tvpoTepov ovk ovtcl\ Whereas the objects of the abstract sciences are never produced, but exist always. 12. tj]V peu] Sc. emo-Tr/pr)!', i. e. twv eTno-TT)p.S>v ei8os. This helps the transition to the singular eVicT^s in what fol- lows. nOAITIKOS. 259- NE. 20. "ElTTCO (TOl TUvO* 0)9 flLOLS €TTiaT1]pr/S rrjs oA?;y ei'5/; 8uo. £,E. YloT€pOl> OVV TOV TToXlTLKOV KOU fiuaiXtU KOU SeaTTOTi-jv Ka\ er olK.ovop.ov drjao/xcp go? lv iravra ravra Trpoaayoptvovres, ?; Tooravra? re)(ua? auras elvai (j)6)fiev, oaairep 6vop.ara eppr}0ij ; MaXXov 8e fXOl SevpO €7T0V. NE. so. n^ ; £?E. Tjjde. ei tco tls twv Sr/fiocrievoPTov larpcou 'iKavos ijvfLJ3ovA€V€iv 18lcot6vcol> avro?, dp ovk dva- yKalov avTw 7rpoaayopevea0aL rovvop.a r-qs Tiyyrjs ravrou oirep q> avfi^ovXevet ; NE. 20. W. SE. TV 5'; oar is fiacriXevovTi \wpas dv8p\ ira- hihJ imme !y a-> pro- dactLon. Sci( ace, Hi. li. Lb either prac ileal or 5 theoi '1'.. which branch does the Statesman belong 1 Or, let us first ask, Arc S man, King, IO Master, House- holder, the sune or difFerent in respect of science ? One who is competent 3. Horepov ovv k.t.A. ] This question is closely connected with the one in hand. If government is an abstract science, then the conditions under which it is exercised and the number of the persons to be governed cannot alter the principles of government : and, conversely, if the prin- ciples are thus altered, it is not an abstract science. 4. Kal er oIkovojjlov ] en marks that this is an extreme step. 6i]0~opev — 7rpocrayopevovTes ] The participle, although re- quired to balance the clause after the introduction of iravra ravra, is redundant, as in e'977 \iya>v. ei> TTavra ravra] Cf. Phileb. 25 d, alib. 6. MaAAov 8e poi 8evpa e7rou] This is a natural touch. The Stranger feels that the ques- tion has been put too ab- strusely for his young re- spondent. 9. driiioa-ievovratv] " Practis- ing physicians." The 8r)pio- epyos is opposed to the iStcori]? (01 8i]pioepyol i'a(Tiv, p-avriv r\ Irjrijpa kcikcov). Cf. Al\ Pol. III. 6 '. 'larpos 8' ore 8r]piovpy6i Kal 6 dpx'.TexToviKos Kal rptros 6 ne- Trai8evpevos rrepl rr\v re)(VT]v. 10. up' ovk] " Is it not in- evitable that he should have the same professional designa- tion with the man whom he advises 1 ?" rovvopa tJ}? T€\vtjs (cogn. accus. after Trpoa-ayopev- eo-8ai) is added for the sake of greater precision. It appears from the Gorgias, p. 455 b, compared with Xen. Mem. IV. 2, 5, that certain public medi- cal officers were appointed by the ecclesia of Athens. Stall- baum thinks that these are meant by the Srjpoo-ievovres 8 FIAAT0N02 to advise :\ physician deserves the name of Physician, whether he practises or iidt. So one who can advise a king, though he may hold a private station, is a king in knowledge. Hence the Statesman is a kinar. paivelv t)eivos lSioott]? u>v avro?, dp ov (f)r)aop.(i' e\€W ]». 9 avrov T)]v e7ri(TTy)fJU]v iju e'Sei rov apypvTa olvtov kck- TrjaOat ; NE. 20. $rjo-on€v. HE. 'AAAa fxrjv rj ye aXrjOivov fiacriXeojS fiacre- h Xlky) ; NE. 20. No/. SE. Tavrrju 8e 6 KeKTTjp,evo9 ovk, av re ap^cou av T idicoTrjs a>v rvyyavrj, iravrois Kara ye rrjv re^y-qv avrrjv $o.(Jl\lkos 6p6(os Trpoap-qO-qaeTai ; NE. 20. AiKaiov yovv. iHE. Kai jirju oiKovofxos ye kou becnroriqs tolvtov* NE. 20. Ti firju ; HE. Ti 5e ; pieydXrjs a^qp-a OLKrjcrem r/ crfiLKpas av 7roXeco? bynos p-cov ti 737)09 apyrjv hiolaerov \ larpol, but it seems more probable that the distinction meant here and in Gorg. 514 d is simply that between one who practises and one who does not practise as a phy- sician — the professional and the amateur. This is quite sufficient for the requirements of the argument. For the form of expression, cf. Gorg. 474 c : Ti fie 8rj a'ia^iov ; ttotsoov k.t.A. 5. >7 y e ~] >3c. eiTKTrrjfir]. 8. TavTTjP fie 6 KeKTT/^eVoy] Note the emphatic position of TaVTTJV. 9. Tvyxdvrj is emphatic : " Whether it be his fortune to i"ule or to enjoy a private sta- tion." Kara, ye ttjv rk\vr]v avrr\v\ Compare the distinction in Republic B. I, between the ruler so-called, and the essen- tial ruler: esp. 1, 345 c. 10. /3ao-i>.iKo'f] "Fit for so- vereignty," whether actually sovereign or not. 14. peyakrjs Bioicrerop] The Politics of Aristotle (I. 1.) open with a criticism of this saying, in which it may be observed that tbe limitation expressed in the words irpbs dpxrjv is. overlooked. The difference of view, however, is real and characteristic. As in defining the Good in the Eepublic,- Plato refers all to a single principle, while Aristotle holds that the idea of Good is dif- erent in different things ; so in the present case, while Plato asserts that the idea of Go- vernment must be the same in the case of a house and a city, Aristotle contends that a house is essentially different from a city, because composed of different elements (the in- nOAITIKGS. 9 259- NE. 20. OvSe'v. c aE. Ovkovv, o vvv 8r) 8ieaKoirovp.eda, (fxzvepov uj? eiricrTypi] p.la ire pi iravr earl ravra. ravrijv 8e elre (3acri,\iKi]v elre ttoXltlki]v elre oiKovopiKTjV tis ovo- pioc^ei, p,r]8ev avrcp 8iap.e6a. 5 NE. 20. Tiydp ; fiE. AAAa p.rjv ro8e ye 8i]Xov, coy (3acriXevs airas X e P (TL KaL ^vpLiravTL rco cra>p.aTi apLiKp arret, els to Kare^etv ttjv ap^rju Bvvarai irpo? tt]v ttjs ^XV f avveaiv kcu pcopirjv. io NE. 20. Ai}Xov. SE. Trj? 8rj yvuxTTiKris paXkov y rrjs yeipoTexyL- kyjs kcu oXco? irpaKTLKrjs fiovXei tov fiaaiXea (j)cop.ev d oiKeiorepov eivai ; dividual being the unit of the family, and the family of the state), and hence the science of the management of each must be different also. They may be compared analogically, but must be carefully distinguished. The point is illustrative of the difference between the Plato- nic and the Aristotelian ova-la, — the former tending towards an abstract unity, the latter towards concrete definiteness and reality. Cf. Ar. Pol. III. 9. The Platonic view had a germ in Socrates. See Xen. Mem. III. 4, 12 : fj yap tg>v 18icov emp.e'Xeia TrXrjdei povov 8ia- (pepei ry~js rdv koivcov. Cf. Legg. 3, 68l : plav oIkiov koIvtjv Kal peyaXrjv dnoTeXovvres. lb. 1,626 c, 690 a; [Erast. 138 c ;] Meno 73 a ; Rep. 9, 578 d. (14.) o-x'JP-d, The word sug- gests the imposing appearance of a stately mansion. Cf. Eurip. Ale. 911 (of the palace of Admetus) : TdTT)v elvat — where the measure of compa- rison is at some distance from the adjective, as here. And he bouse v.. II haa tlio HruiK- art of govern- ment which man has. Therefore these forms of art or science differ only in name. And it is clour, at all events, that the royal function is a work of mind. Kingcraft, or State- craft, then, is a theo- retical science. 10 FIAATON02 Now theoretical science is not one entire and perfect chrysolite, but divides into Criti- cal and Command- ing. NE. 20. 17 pr)v ; P- 259 SE. Tr)v apa ttoXltlki]v koll ttoXltlkov kou fiacri- XiK)]V KOLL fioXTlXlKOV €LS TOLVTQV 0)9 tV TTO.VTa TLXVTa 5 NE. HO. AtjXov. HE. Ovkovv TTopevoineO* av eijr/9, d fierce Tama ttjv yvcocrrLKrjv SiopL^olfJieda ; NE. 20. Udvv ye. HE. Yipoae^e 8rj tov vovv, av apa iv amy} two. 10 8ia(fivr)v Karavo/jacofiev. NE. 20. fitJov tl irXeov epyov 8cocrofjL€i> r) to. yvu>- aOevra Kplvai ; NE. 20. 17 fir)V ; SE. Kat yap dpyiTeKT<£>v ye was ouk olvto? epya- tlko9, dXXd £pya.TU)V apyu>v. NE. 20. Nat. 3?E. JJape-^ofievos ye wov yvwaiv, dXX ov %€i- povpyiav. NE. 20. Ovrm. 2,6o. ££E. Aikolico? Srj fiereyeiv av XeyoiTO ttj? yvcDcm- kt]$ e7rio~Tr}firjs. NE. 20. Udvv ye. SE. Tovtco Se ye, oI/jlcu, irpoarjKeL Kpivavri /jltj reXos ^X av I* 7 ! *' aTrrjXXdyOai, KaOdirep 6 XoyicrTrj? diryjXXaKTO, irpoo-TaTTeiv Se eKaaroLS twv epyarow to ye irpoatyopov, ems av direpydo-^vTai to irpo- GTayOev. Arith- metic, for instanci . i ; purely cri- tical : the Master Builder, on the other hand, while his busi- ness is theory and not prac- tice, must superin- tend the 1 application of his theory. 2. Tpoicrt) Se 'KoyiariKfiJ " But when arithmetic has discerned the differences amongst num- bers, shall we give her any further office than to judge of that which she has discerned?" Ans. "How should we?" (ri 6. Kal yap apxireKToiv ye ttRs k.t.A.] ri fx-fjv expresses surprise that the question should have been asked. An example which justifies the question is, there- fore, introduced with yap. " I asked because there are branches of theoretical know- ledge which do not end in theory." There may seem at first sight to be a confusion in classing the master-carpenter under yvaxmicrj, when carpen- try has been placed amongst the practical sciences. But this helps to shew that the " commanding sciences," al- though independent of prac- tice, yet have an immediate relation to the practical. 1 8. to ye Trp6o-(popov\ He is not wholly engaged in directing his workmen, nor does he im- part all his knowledge to each of them, but he must direct each in so far as is required for the particular work ap- pointed them. This limitation is expressed by ye. C 2 12 FIAAT0N02 This dis- tinction being ad- mitted, it is easy to see that the King is not a mere spec- tator of the life of the city, but that his science, while theo- retical, is also com- manding^ NE. 20. 'OpOm. p- 26 HE. Qvkovv yvGXTTLKol ptv dl re toiolvtcu tjvp- TracraL kcu biroaai '^vveirovTai ttj Xoyio-TiKr}, Kplaet 8e Kai imraijei Siafpeperov aXXijkoLv rovrco too b 5 yevee ; NE. 20. v Kai Kplvai Ka\ eTTiTatjat.' Ka\ p.akio-Ta tovto, to yap emraTTfiv apxiKaTepov io~Tiv. lb. VII. 5 : apXOVTOs 6° eVtVn|i? Ka\ Kpio-is ecrrtV. 1 1 . 'AAAa p.i)v — j^aipeiv] The maxim is appropriately bor- rowed from political science (for opovoia is noXiTiKr/ (piXia) in order to assert the indepen- dence of the dialectical reason. The same thing is meant as in Gorgias 472 b ; Protag. 331 c, 348 a. 19. Kadcmep Tiva BeaTrjv] Plato recurs to the image of the theatre, which he employed in Thepet. 173 C : oibe 6eaTi)s, &o~- Trep iroirjTals. The notion of iiriTOKTiKr] may be compared with Kant's imperative of the reason : an ideal which has immediate re- ference to life. In Socrates, philosophy becomes practical without losing anything of the speculative impulse. nOAITIKOS. 13 260. 7rep Tiva 6eari']v ; ?) pdXXov Trjs eTriTaKTiKrj? o>9 ovra avrov T€)(V7]? O/jcropev, SeaTro^ovrd ye ; NE. 20. riwy yap ov p.dXXov ; HE. T?}^ eirLTaKTiKi-jV 81) reyyi]v ttolXlv dv elrj Oeareov el ttt) bieo-rrjKe. Kai fioi SoKei rfjSe Try, Ka6d- irep rj tcov Kair-qXtov reyyr\ tyjs tcov avT07TtoXcov 8lco- d picrTai ri)(yrj9, koll to fiaaiXiKov yevos eoiKev diro tov tcov KijpvKcov yevovs a(pa>pio-0ai. NE, 20. nc5y ; SE. YlcoXrjde'vra ttov irporepov epya dXXorpta TrapaSe\6pevoL SevTepov ttcoXovctl ttoXlv o'l KairrjXoL- NE. 20. Yiavv pep ovv. AE. Ovkovv koll to KTjpvKLKov cu? avyyeveaiv, at avfiTracrai to p. 26c y tiuTOLTTeiv eypvcriv ; 7) (3ovAei, KaOairep elKa^ppev vvv 8rj, kou Tovvopa irapeiKao-wpev, eireibi^ koll cr^eShv avcavvpov ov Tvyyavei to twv avTeirvraKToiv yevos, 5 kou TavTYf Tama SteXcopeda, to p.ev tcov fiao-iXecov yevos els ti]v avTeirtTaKTLKrjv OevTes, tov 8e aXXov iravTos apeArjaavTes, ovojicl erepov avTols irapayo>- prjcravTes OecrOai two. ; tov yap apyovTos eveica rjpuv 7} jjl€0o8o? rjv, aXX ov^l tov evavTiov. p. 26 10 NE. 20. Yldvv ptev ovv. aE. Ovkovv erreidr] tovto p.eTpiw9 atyeaTrjKev our eKeivcov, aXkoTpLOTTjTi Stopio-Oeu irpbs oiKeiOTrjTa, tovto avTO iraXiv av SiaLpelu avayKalov, el Tiva TOpLrjV eri eyppev vireUovaav ev tovtco ; 15 NE. 20. Uoipv ye. 1. tovtcov re)(yais cvyyeveaiv\ The order is Texvais avyyeveaiv tovtcov. Many other instances of inversion might have heen noticed. to y' itiiTaTTeiv ] I. e. hy whatever further characteristic they may be distinguished. 2. tcaBdrrep eiKa^opev — napei- Kao-afiev] " Shall we form the name analogically, in accordance Avith the comparison which we made just now" — viz. between the king and the avT07ra>\r]s 1 7. iTepov — Tiva] Lit. " Step- ping aside for some other to give them a name." The ac- cusative before 6eo-6ai is pre- ferred to the dative after 7rapaxpr]0-avTe<; to avoid the collision of two datives (eVepw avrols). There is a slight irony in Trapaxcoprjo-avTes, " yielding the merit to another." Cf. Soph. 267 b, Prot. 336 c. II. Ovkovv oIk(i6t^to\ Since then this kind has been dis- tinguished from the rest with tolerable clearness, being de- fined by contrasting what comes from others with that which originates with oneself. 1 3. el] Either " to divide, if we can find a line of sec- tion : " or, perhaps better, " to divide, and see whether we can find a line of section." Tiva roprjv — exopev ] This phraseology reappears in Legg. II, 944 b: exei Tiva TOfiriv 77 Tovrav tcov ovopdrav emcpopd. 14. Top.r]v] Cf. supr. p. 259 d, 8ia(pvrjv, and note. v7reUovo-av] " Yielding" to the sharp instrument of di- vision, the " dividing edge" of thought. Cf. Tim. 62 b: o-Kkrjpd SV, oaois oz> rjpS>v fj (rapt- vire'iKt), nOAITIKOS. 15 261. £?E. Kal fju)v i\>aivope6a €\€IV «AA' eiraKoXovOcov crvvrepve. NE. 20. Ufi ; SE. Hco/ray biroaovs av upypvTas 8Lavoi]0wp.ev eiriTa^ei Trpoor\pu>pevov9, dp ov\ evpr)aop.ev yevecrem b twos eveKa TrpoaraTTOvras ; NE. 20. Wmh' ov; SE. Kal prjv ra ye ytyvopeva iravra hlya Sia- Aa/3e«> ov iravrdirao-L yaXeirov. NE. 20. ufj ; £?E. Ta /^ey a\j/v)(a avrcoi/ earl ttov ^vpiravTcov, ra S' epy^vya. NE. SO. Nat. AE. TouVoiS 1 oV ye avTols to tov yvcocrTiKov pepos eiriraKTiKov ov, e'iirep fiov\6pe6a Tepveiv, repovp.ev. NE. 20. Kararl; SE. To p}v eVi tous* tcdv d^v^cov yeveo~ecriv av" c tov Tacro-ovTes, to <5' eVi Tats twv ep^v^wv. Kal irav ovtcos rfSrj diaiprjaeTaL 6Yx«« NE. 20. YlavTaTrao-L ye. 3E. To p.ev To'ivvv avTcou TrapaX'nrwpev, to <5' avaAa(3copLei>, avaXafiovTes 8e p,epLO~cope0a els 8vo to avpirav. There Is a further dis- tinction. All com- mands is- 5 8uev crvvrefive ] " Follow and divide with me." Cf. Soph. 228 c. 5. yeveaeas tlvos evena] "For the sake of some production." The word yeveo-is in Plato's later dialogues acquires a wide generality of meaning. Com- pare the following passages : Soph. 235 e ; Polit. 282 d, 283 d, 284 c j Phileb. 26 d, 27 a; Tim. 29 d ; Legg. 10, 889 a, 892 c, 11, 920 e. 14. Tovtois — avrols] Sc. tw d\l/vxcj> re ku\ e/x^v^cp. Cf. SUpr. 260a: Kpiaei — Kal intranet, ilifr. 264 e : ra TVT-qva re Kai 7re£cp. 17. To fiiv — avrov] " The one segment of it" (tov ttjs yva- CTTIKTJS fJLtpOVS (TTlTaKTlKOV). 18, Tah t5>v i/jL^uxoov] be. ye- vio-eo-L. " The pi-ocesses which affect living creatures." 22. to o-vp.Trav] Epexegetic in apposition with to 6V. 16 riAATONOS But the production and nur- ture of ani- mals may- be cared for either singly or in herds. The States- man is not a groom, hut a herds- man. And whether we give to this latter branch of animal- tending the name of herding, or of feed- ing in flocks, it matters little. Word- catching is not the way to get rich in thoughts. NE. 20. \eyeis 5' avroiv dvaXt-pvTeov elvai iro- Ttpov ; SE. UdvTcos' 7rov to 7repl to. £o3a limaKTiKov. ov yap 8r) to ye tyjs fiaaLXiKr)s e7ncrTr)p.r)s Icttl ttotz 5 Ttt)V d\j/U)(COV llTLCTTaTOVV^ 0L0V dp)(LTeKTOVLKOV, dXXa yevvaioTepov, ev toIs ^coois" kou Trepl amd Tama ttjv Svvapiv del KeKTr/pevov. NE. 20. 'Op0m. 3?E. Ttjv ye p.r)v tcov tjcooov yeveoriv K.a\ Tpo(f)r)v iott)i> p.ev tls av t8ot p,ovoTpopev ; 20 NE. 20. 'OiroTepov av ev tco Xoyco avp.^aivrj. SE. KaAaiy ye, co 2w/cpa7-es" kolv 8ia(f)vXdtjr)s to p.rj airovhd^eLv erri toIs ovoptaaL, irXovcrLcoTepos eis to p. 2f g. yeveaiv Ka\ Tpocprjv] The ambiguity of the word yeveais helps to conceal the error of confusing the king with the shepherd, which affords so much matter for discussion in what follows. 14. ^orjkarrjv] One who drives an ox : as, for instance, in ploughing. 1 6. Qaiverai — prjdev vvv] Cf. Soph. 226 d : S^eSoi/ ovTOi vvv AeX<9ee (paiverai, Rep. 7, 525 d, iwoa p7]6evros k.t.A., and com- pare the Homeric pe^dev Be re VTjTTLOi e'yvio. 2 1. to p.fj aivovha^eiv in\ rols ovofiaai ] Plato frequently dwells on the danger of being imposed on in philosophy by words ; and alludes to the viti- ating effect which a love of ver- bal distinction had on his con- temporaries. Cf. e. g. Thetet. 166 b, 177 e, 184 c ; Soph. 218 c ; Rep. 5, 454 a. 2 2. 7r\ovaia>Tepos (Is to yrjpas] Unlike the 6^np.a6a.s of Soph. nOAITIKOS. 17 261. yrjpas dva([)aviio~ei ijypovrjaeco^. vvv 8e tovto pev, Ka.6a.7rcp 8iai] He again varies the word in accordance with the preceding remark. " Do you perceive a way in which, by shewing the art of herding to be twofold, one may cause what is now sought amongst twice the number of things to be then sought amongst half that number?" rcls rip. the half, i. e. of the double number. 4. Si7rAao-toi(n] So H. Most MSS. have Sm'kao-iot.s ?/'(Bodl.i7). The Ionic form of the dative plural (which occurs again infr. 304 e) is one of the many co- incidences in point of language between this dialogue and the Laws. 14. to pepos ajia eiSos e'^fVco] The spirit of this passage may be compared with Phsedr. 265 e: kclt e'i8r] repveiv, — Ka\ pr] eVi- Xeipelv Karayvvvai jxepos p.rj8ev : Phileb. 14 e : tu peXij re km ap.a p-epr) die\a>v rw Ao'yw. Pep. 4, 445 d : oo-oi — iroKiTeimv rpo- 7rot €lo~\v e'i8rj e'xovres. The true dialectician is he who hits upon the real divisions of things : and the real divisions are those which a true dialec- tician would make. It is diffi- cult to say in how far the " form" here spoken of is ob- jective, and how far subjective. As we should say, "do not divide without a principle of division." 16. av 6p8a)s e'xn] "If your division proves to be the right one." Young Socrates is allowed IS nAATQNOS as we ''.-in in half, and making sure that we can assign a rational principle for each distinction. Thus our coun- t^nien make a great as- sumption when they t)(r), KaOairep oXiyov av npOTepov ob]0et? ^X eiv T ^ v P* 2< ^ 2 Siaipeaiv iTricnrtvaas tov Xoyov, iocov eV dv0pa>7rovs wopevoptevov. dXXa yap, co (fiiXe, XeirTovpyelv ovk aarcjiaXes, did pieacov oe dcr(f)aXeaT€pov levai Tepivov- 5Tcts, kou pdXXov iSe'ai? av ti? irpo(JTvy\dvoi. tovto oe Sia(f)e'peL to irdv irpos ras (r)Tr/? dpTi Spav ; to fall into a natural error, for the sake of illustrating the difference between the right and the wrong method. 1. Kaddnep — e\eiv\ Sc. opQcos. 2. eneaneva-as — Tropevopc-vov] " You hastened the steps of the inquiry when you saw them directed towards mankind." "The Argument" is still per- sonified. iireo~ntvo~as tov \6yov] Cf. Leo-a. 2, 6*8 a: fir) Taxy to toiovtov Kpivapeda, dWa Biai- povvTes kcito. peprj aKoncopeda, 3. Xe7rrovpyeTi/] " To make short work." "To cut off too small a piece." 5. tovto 8e 8ia(pepei to 7raid, Here, as in the latter part of the Phfedrus, the Idea is the true form, not separated from the matter, but discerned by dialectic amongst particulars : the objective element in each determination of thought. 8, etvvia Trjs o~rjs (pvaecos, w 2a> K pa.Tes] Cf. The^t. 1 85 ; Soph. 266 ; Parm. 130 : where the capacity of the hearer is likewise made the measure of the enunciation of some great truth. In Rep. 7, 529 e, on the contrary, "dear Glaucon" is not thought capable of fol- lowing the most abstract ac- count of dialectic. In the present passage also Plato breaks off abruptly : " It is impossible to explain it per- fectly at this present juncture." ev tco 7rapeo-TrjKOTi to. vvv. Per- haps all such discussions were reserved for the "Philosophus ;" and this may be one reason why that dialogue was never written. 1 1 . Trpoayaye'iv] Cf. Al\ Pol. III. 7 : KaXas 8' e%ei Kai vvv avaXaftovTas avTa npoayayelv. 13. Holov] Governed by ovk opBca — Spav, " What mistake do you say we have just made in our divisions V nOAITIKOS. 19 1 2^2. HE. ToiOvSt, 0101/ €£ 779 TUl/Opomtl/01/ €7TL)(€lpl')aa9 d 5/)(a SieXeaOcu yei/os 8icupoi KaOdirep ol -iroXXol tcoi/ ii/0a8e Siavt/jLOvcrt, to p.ei/ 'EXXiji/lkoi/ cos* €1/ diro iravTcoi/ adxiipovvres X 60 /^' 9 ? o-vp.iraaL 8e toIs uXXols ye'i/ecrii/, direipOLS overt, kcu (x/jliktoi? kcu davfJL(f)coi/0L9 npo? dXXrjXa, (Sdpfiapov p.ia kXh]ct€i irpocreLTrovTes avro, 8td ravrrji/ rr\v jxiav kXtjctii/ kcu ytvos ev avro elvcu 7rpoa8oKa>aii/' rj rov dpiOpov ris av vopLi^oi kclt eldi] Svo Diaipeiv pvpiada dirorepvopevos anro e TTOLVTCDV, MS €l> el8o? d.7TO)(C0pi(p)l/ f KCU TCp XoiTTCp 8r) ttgu/tl Oepevos ev ovopa, 8ia rrjv kXtjctlv av kcu tovt dijioi yevos eKelvov x^P^ erepov ev ylyvecrOai. KaX- Xlov Se irov kcu fiaXXov kclt etdrj kcil 8lxa Siaipolr av, el tov fiei/ dpiOfiov dpruo kcu TrepiTTCp ti? re/ivoi, divide mankind into ' and Barba- rian, and bo would any one who divi- 5 ded nuni- !■■ ra into ten thou- sand mtkI all i> ten thou- sand. It would be more scien- tific to dis- IO tiugniflh number into odd and even, and man- kind into male and female, and not to in- 3. ivddbe~\ Sc. Kara rrjv 'EX- XaSa. ro pev — TrpoadoKwaij These words are explanatory of Siave- ixoviri. Hence, as elsewhere explained, the absence of a connecting particle, or relative. Or perhaps it is better to sup- pose a return from the par- ticiple to the indicative in TvpoadoKaxri. 5. yeveaiv — Trpoaenrovres avro] There is a change of construc- tion : that at first intended being (3dp(3apov ev ovopa depevoi, or something of the kind. avro, which resumes o-vp.Tr. t. a. yev., is suggested by the accu- sative (Bdpfiapov. The grammar may, of course, be saved by omitting avro. But this is unnecessary : 7mXcu yap iapev dvdiikea> tcov tolovtcciv. dp'iKTots kci\ dvois~\ "Nei- ther holding any intercourse (or intermarrying, vid. inf. 265 e) nor understanding one an- other's speech." 8. vopl£oi] " Should use," " be wont," " adopt the custom of." Cf. Legg. 10, 908 e: to 6eois vopi^ov dpeXelv eL8os. 9. divoTepvopevos ] For the middle voice, cf. Soph. 287 a, Phsedr. 266 a. 13. pa\\ov — Si'xa] Compare the stress which is laid on the bisection, if possible, of each kind, in Phileb. 16 d : perd piav ovo, e'i ttcos eltri, ovco- ■nelv. Cf. supr. 262 a : 1-6 £7- rovpevov ev o"i7rXao-i'oicrt ravvv ev Tois ripicrecriv els Tore Troirjcrei fyrelcrdai : an injunction which suggested the rule which the answer has violated. There is here the same love of pro- portion and equality which appears in Aristotle's account of Justice. See especially his etymology of oWonfo quasi Ol^a(TTt]S. D 2 20 IIAATONOS troduce such acci- dental dif- f.T.'lii-i'S as Lydian or J 'In" gian (not to say Greek), until he were at a loss for a distinction which had a rational ground. But, it may be asked, how can we tell when a division is accidental and when real? This question is reserved : and we re- turn to the distinction of young- Socrates, between man and the brutes. Which is just as if that ra- tional and politic ani- mal the to 8e av tcov dvOpcoTrow yevos dppevi koll GrjXei, p. AvSov s 8e i] fypvyas rj TLvas eTepov? irpo? diravTa? TCLTTitiV U7rO(T)(L(j)L T0T6, TjVLKa OflTOpOL yeVO? CipLOL KOLL fxepo? evp[ ttcu, tip' alxeis, iroTepa Av8dv i) fypvya kokoIs eXavveiv apyvpa>- vtjtov ueOev) for that of "EXhrjves as opposed to Bapfiapoi : and the same view is continued presently, where, to shew the nature of the distinction be- tween men and beasts, cranes are put in the place of men, whom they are supposed in turn to include amongst the beasts. 5. tovto ai)To\ Sc. Xeye or 4>pa£e implied in the question. 13. KaBanep l%vevovTes] Cf. Theaet. 187 e : ovk. airb Kaipov TTtikiv (oo-rrep 'l^vos peTe\6elv. 14. pr) ivore 86^rjs auro] avTO is again used with a more dis- tinct reference to what follows than to what precedes. 17. eTepov] By attraction for eTepa. 19. 'Sis ei8os pev — awryfer;] Cf. Prot. 350 c, where the non- convertibility of a universal affirmative is similarly noticed as a new thought. See also nOAITIKOS. 21 263. XlyryraC pepos 8e dSo? ov8epla avayicr). ravrrj p.e 7] Keivr) fiaWov, a> ^LcoKpaTC?, da. (jjaOt Xcyeiv. NE. 20. Tavr earat. u SE. <\>pacrov Sij fj.01 to /xer« tovto. NE. 20. Uohv ; < SE. To tt)s airoTrXavr]ae(i)9 biroOtv rjpas Sevp rjyayeu. oificu pilv yap ptdXicrTa, oOev epcor^deh o~v ttjv dyeXaioTpofplav oivq StaLpereou aVe? paXa irpo- Ovficos oV tlvai ^cocou yevi], to pev dvOpomtvov, ere- pov Se T(ov aXXodv ^vpnrdvTtov Grjpicov ev. NE. 20. 'AX-qOTj. fiE. Kcu kpoiye Sr) tot e([)av7]s pepos d(f)atpcoi> rjyeixrOcu KaTaXtireiv to Xolttov av iravTcov yivos ev, otl TTOLcri tclvtov lirovopd^uv sayes ovopa, Orjpia KaXeaas. ] d NE. 20. 'H^ KOU TaVTCt 0VTC0S. SE. To 8e ye, co irdvTu>v dvSpeioTaTe, Tay av, crane wr< re to put cram in gory, and the "ili' i- animals, including men, in another, with, it may I"-, bhe Bame name of ' bruti -.' Such crude logic must be avoided here. ib. 329c! : Tvorepov — axnrep irpoa- a>7rcv ra p.6pia — aropa re kci\ pis k.t.A. fj &v yepdveov So/cet o~vp.(3alvetv. €KTOTTL^OVO-l yap fiaKpCLV, KO.I tig v\}sos tt£tovtm npos to Kadopav to. noppco' kcu iav 'idcoai ve(prj Kai Xmiepia, KciTaTVTacrai f]0-vxd£ov- criv. *Eti 8e ro ex elv f]yep-6va re kcu tovs eniavpiTTovTas iv rots ea^aTOLs, waTe KaraKOvecrdai ttjv (pa>vr]i>. "Orav 8e Kade£a>VTv. to tcov yepavcov] Sc. yivos, infr. Or simply = oi yipavoi. Cf. SUpr. : to Tjji airoTvKavrjCTecos. 2. * KCITO. TCLVTa] MSS. 6 KdTU TavTa. 6, which the Zurich editors reject and Bekker and Hermann include in brackets, is indefensible because inter- OOAITIKOI. 28 263. Siovopdlpi, KaOdirep koll v tjvA\ eh ravro ovSeu aXXo nXyu laws Orjpia irpoduiroL. TrtipaOcopev ovv -qpeis etjevXafleicrOai irdvb v OTroaa roiavra. 5 c NE. 20. Urn ; HE. M?) irdv to tgov (jooov ylvos Siacpovpevoi, Iva i-jttov avrd irdayaipev. NE. 20. OvSev yap Set. SE. Kal yap ovv koll Tore -qpaprdvero ravrrf. 10 NE. 20. T/&J; SE. Tfjs yvcoaTiKr}? ocrov tiriraKTiKOv rjplv pepos, yv ttov tov £coorpo(j)LKOV yevovs, ayeXaiwv prjv (jucov. v yap; rupting the sense between av and 8iovopd£oi, where the opt. is required by rrpoaeiiroi infr. 810- vofia£oi = distinguish in words. Note the return to the more direct constr. in irpocre'nroi. 2. crepvvvov iavro ] Cf. Phileb. 28 d: ol aocpoi, eavrovs euros crepvyvovres. 4. Trpoa-einoi] There is a re- turn from the participial to the more direct construction. 5. igevkafteiaOai — TOtavra ] " Keep ourselves quite free from any such error." Where the use of compounds is so frequent, it is unsafe to lay too much stress on the meaning of prefixes. Hence in Soph. 231 c (where see note) perhaps egava-rrvevaapev means simply " to recover breath," as in Phsedr. 254 c. 7. Mi) Trav to tu>v (a>a>v 8iaip.] " By not making the whole animal kingdom the object of our (final) division." I. e. By first subdividing it so as to deal with a part only. 8. avrd] Cf. Theast. 207 d : 8pu>vTas avrd. 9. OvBev yap Sei] Either " In- deed we must not :" or, if ovdev refers to tjttov, " We must avoid it altogether — be (not less liable but) not at all liable to this mistake." The former is more idiomatic. 1 o. Kal roVe] Also in a former division : viz. 261 d, where we distinguished 17 tS>v dyekaiav £ghov iiriTaKTLKr]. All animals, whether gregarious or other- wise, should have been first dis- inguished into wild and tame. 12. oo-oi/ — pe'pos] Sub. rjv from nest clause. 13. ayeKaianf u.rjv ^cocof] Cf. Legg. 3, 694 e (Cyrus is spoken of) : 6 fie' ye narrjp avTols av iroLpvia pev Kal irpofiara Kal ayeXas dvSpCop re Kal dXXtov noWa/v noX- We had already erred in the same direc- tion when we spoke of our " com- manding science" as concerned with herd- ed animals. 9A IIAATQNOS For there is a pre- vious divi- : i.iii of ani- mals into viM and tame, and this wo passed over. Let ns be more guarded, now that we have felt the truth of the proverb, " More haste, worse We may thus arrive at the same result, but it will be worked out for us in a more satis- factory way. NE. 20. NaL p. 2M SE. Air/p)]To tolvvv ydr] /cat tote £yp.7rav to (fi>oi> rep TL0aacp /cat aypicp. ra p}v yap tyovro. p. 264 TiOaaeveadaL (jjvaiv rjp.epa 7rpoo-elpi]Tai, ra Se fxi] 5 e^ovra aypia. NE. 20. KaAa*. HE. ' Hu 8e ye 61-jpevopev einaTr]fnt)v, Iv Toh i)}i£poL9 r\v re Kal kartv, eVrt rois ayeAat'ot? p.tv fyrrjTea OpepLjiacriv. 10 NE. 20. Nat. HE. Niij tolvvv Siacpcofieda wairep Tore, irpos airavra ajrofiXetyavTes, p.r)be crTrtvaavTes, u>a 8rj Tayv yevcofxeOa irpos rfj TroAtrt/cj}. ireiroirjKe yap b y/uias /cat vvv iraOtiv to KaTa Tt]v irapoi\xlav iraOos. 15 NE. 20. Uohv ; HE. Oi))( rjcrvypvs ev BiaipovvTas rjuvKevac fipabv- Tepov. NE. 20. Kat /caAcos* ye, d> £eW, ireTrou-jKev . HE. TavT eaTco. itolXlv <5' ovv i£ ocpxi^ ™rr)i> koivot potyatrjv 7T6ipcof.ieOa dtaipelv' tcra)? yap Kal tovto, o o~v 7rpodvjj.€?, dcaTrepaLvofievos 1 o Xa? eKTaro. lb. 5 j 735 • 7T <* a ' av dyeXrju noipip kcu /3oukoXo? rpo- (psvs re ovk aAXcos /z?;7rore eVtxei- pi]i> in av- Bp&movs 7ropevop.evov. dianepaiv6p,evos — pr/viiaa] Cf. nOAITIKOS. 25 2^>4- Xoyos avTO? aoi KaXXiov fxrjvvau. kcjll pot (j)pd£e. NE. 20. Uohv Si] ; HE. ToSe, el TLV(£>v 7ro\\aKi? apa SlOLKrjKOa 1 }' 01) c yap 8i) 7rpoo-TV)(rjs ye olvto? olS" on ye'yovas rats ev ra> NelXco TiOao-elai? tu>v lydvcov /cat tcou ev rah fiacriXiKcus Xlpvai?. ev p.ev yap K.pr\vais rax av 'term elrjg rjcrOrjpevos. NE. 20. Haw pev ovv Ka\ ravra redeap.at kul- Ktiva iroXXwv aKrjKoa. HE. Kat prjv \7)Vofi(x>Tias ye Kal yepavoficorla?, < . , garious tame ani- i mals in- clude shoals of fish and flocks of geese and cranes: as witness the fishponds of Egypt IO and Baby- lon and the plains of Thessaly. Le gg- 7> 199 e: K&v V M£' o8os avTT) 6X77 cr^ouera re'Aos iko.- va>s av pr/vvo-eie Kal to vvv 8uitto- povpevov. Al'ist. Pol. III. 3 : ovt6 yap (pavev to \ex@ev irotel bifkov. I. avTOS prjvvcrei] Cf. Thefet. 2 00 e : Tax' Q.V avTO (fiyjveie to ^Tovpevov. Phileb. 20 : irpo'ibv 8' €Ti aa(pe'arepov 8ei£ei. 4. TdoV, el Tivav\ " This, whether you have perhaps heard of it." Cf. Thetet. 158c: to ttoIov ' 6 noXkaKis ere olpat 8iaKt]Koivai ipcoTcovTcov k.t.X. It does not seem certain whether noXkaKis is here " perhaps" (cf. Laches 194 a, Protag. 361 c, Polit. infr. 283 b) or "often :" cf. noWmv infr. c. But the for- mer is more probable. 5. Trpoo-Tvxr]i] This word oc- curs again in the Laws and Epinomis, and nowhere else in Plato, or indeed in Greek. 6. Tidacreiais] This word, an abstract noun formed from Tidao-evco, occurs nowhere else in classical Greek. The plural of the abstract noun is used to express the concrete. tcov iv Tals (3. Xifivaii] Sc. Ixdvcov. As if the former phrase had been Tals tcov iv t>v Tidao-elais. " I know VOU have never had an opportunity of seeing how tame fish are kept in the Nile and in the ponds of the Great King." II. yepavoficoTias] The flocks of cranes are probably sug- gested by the previous mention of the crane. The crane is classed with man by Aristotle as not only dyeXaiov but ito\iti- kov &ov, the form of his con- stitution being a monarchy. De Anim. Hist. I. 1. § 11 : iro- \lTlKCL 8' ea-rlv cuv ev Tl Kal K01V0V yiyverai ndvTcov to epyov, onep ov TrdvTa Tvoiei to. dyikala. "Eari 8e tolovtov avdpconos, peXiTTa, (r rjyepova, pvppr]Kes 8e Kal pvpla r/XXa avapxa. Com- pare Plat. Phsfido 82 b: 7roXt- tikov re Kal ijpepov -yei/or, fj irov peXiTTcov, j) aqbrjKcov 7] pvpprjKcov — t] to dvdpairwov. ( 26 HAAT0N02 Hence the art of herd- ing may be divided into sub- aqueous and terrene. And of the terrene creatures, one kind are fledged. Statecraft is occupied with the walking terrene animals : and for dividing these, rea- son points out a longer and a short- er way. The former is more in accordance j with the principles above laid down, but, as we have lei- sure, we may try both — of course in 2 turn : tak- ing the longer way first, whilst we are fresh. el kcu fir) TreirXdirqaai irepi to. GerraAi/ca 7re8la, p. 264 7T€7TVaaL yOVV KCU 7TICTT€V€L9 elvOLl. NE. 20. Ti pr]v ; HE. Tovo' IveKCL toi ttolvtol r)pu)Tr}aa TOLVTO., SlOTl d rr)s tcqv dyeXalcov rpo(f)rjs eaTi fiev evvSpov, can 8e /cat ij-qpofiaTiKOis. NE. 20. "Ecrri yap ovv. HE. 'Ap ovv kou aoi £vv8ok€i ravrr] 8elv 8u^a- {jELV Tr}V KOlVOTpO(f)lKr)v €7T ICTTr) fir}V ', €0' eKarepcp TOV- tcov to fiepo? avrr)? kirivifiovras eKarepov, to fiev erepov vypoTpo TTTYjvcp T€ Kal ire(j£> diopiadfievos. NE. 20. ' K\r}6eo-TaTa. HE. Tt de' ; to ttoXltlkov *&>? nrepY* to ire^ov 4. ToCS' evena rot] Cf. Theset. 185 d : rov8e toi evena avrd croi diaKpi^ovfiai. 5. (grjpoPariKov r.) The words ewbpov and £r]po@aTLK.6v are ap- plied to birds by Aristotle, in the only other place where the latter word occurs in classical Greek. H. A. vi. 2. § 1 (ubi VulgO gripofticoTiKov). 14. Kal p.r)u Kal — iravri"] " If we divide thus, we shall also be saved the trouble of asking to which art the kingly func- tion belongs : for this will be evident to all," ovtcos = tovto 7T0irjaavres. 23. * cos nepl* to ire£6v] Stall- bauni is wrong in saying that Bekker took his reading el 7repl from the majority of MSS. The following are the varia- tions, as quoted by him : — el nepl ; axnrep E ; rj acrnep C et nOAITIKOS. Ti 264. £qrr)Teov ; rj ovk o'lei koll rhv d(j)povearaTov cos eVoy elirew Boijdfikiv ovtcov ; NE. 20. "Eycoye. HE. T?}^ 8e 7retpvoi±LKr]V) Ka.0a.7rep apriou dpi- Ofxov, 8el Tep.vop.evriv 8tya dirofyaiveiv . 5 NE. 20. ^\ou. HE. Kal /jlyju e(j) o ye fie'pos coppajKeir rjfiiv 6 \6yos, eV €K€Li>o 8vo TLve KaOopav 68a> rerafie'va (J)aiveTai, rrjv /xeV Odrrco, 7rpos fieya fiepos a/JUKpoi' 8LaLpov/j,€i>i]i>, ti-]v 8e, oirep ev ra irpocrOev eXeyofiev, 10 otl 8ei fjLecroTOfieiv u>s fiaXiara, tout e\ovaav /uaA- 265. \oi>, ixaKporepav ye fxrju. e^ecmv ovv, biroTepav av fiov\7]6ol>iiev, ravTTjv iropevOrjvaL. rcF; 17 (oo-jrep H ; toWep # r (i. e. the rest with Stephanus' eel.) Bekker's reading, el irepl t. ir., £rjTT)Teov, would be more plausible if Kal prjv — ov Cl T ^i~ aop.ev were immediately pre- ceding. Heindorf's, 9 nepl r. it. £., is not improbable in itself, but has weak MS. confirma- tion. If as nepl is right, this had probably been corrupted into fiepei roivvv eycoye ap.(f)OTepa$ at- h spovfxat. HE. 'PaSiov, e7rei8r} rb Xonrov ftpayv. kut ap\as /xr)i> kou fieaovcTLV a/JLa rrjs iropeLas ^aXeirbv av rjv i)fiiv to 7rp6arayfJLa' vvv 8\ eVeiS?) 8oKel ravrr), rrjv HOLKpoTepav irporepov 'IcopLeV veaXearepot yap ovre? topaov avrrjv wopevcropeOa. rrjv 8e 8y 8iaip€ 6avfj,acrT€^ " What a thing to ask !" This expres- sion throws some light on the common use of Z> davpaaie. 4. aptpOTepas] TropevOrjvai is probably to be supplied. 6. eTrei8rj — /3pavu] The poor youth is deceived into thinking that he is near the end of his journey : to 8° rjv apa, coy e'oiKe, irpoolptov. Kar dpxas] This is one of the expressions which occur frequently in the Politicus and Laws. 0. veaXeo-repoi'] " While still fresh." See Passow or Liddell and Scott sub. v. 1 5. rrjv yeveo-iv] " Their growth or mode of existence." yevecris here almost = ti)s aKepdrov. NE. 20. TaDr eara) ravrr) Xe\6evTa' TrdvTcos d yap iKat'wy <5e&/Acoraf. HE. Kat /X771/ o ye fiaonXev? t)puv av Kara- (j)avrj9 otl koXo(3ov dyeXrjv tlvol KepaTcov vo- fxevet. NE. 20. ritoy yap ov SrjXo? ; HE. Tavrrjv tolvvv KaraOpavcravTes, to yiyvo- fievov avrco ireipcoixeda airobovvaL. NE. 20. Udvv ye. HE. Ylorepov ovv fiovXei tco a\LCTTcp re kcu tw KaXovp.evo') /xcovv^l Siaipelv avTyv i] rfj Koivoyovla re /cat Xhioyovla ; \xav6dveis yap irov. NE. 20. To ttoIov ; HE. "Ort to ptev tcov Ittttcov koi ovcov Tref a hornless 10 herd. But hornless cattle are again di- vided by a double dis- tinction : into those which mix the breed 5 and divide not the hoof, and those which divide the foot and do not mix their breed. for should you attempt to name them, the result would be too complicated." The caution would apply still more point- edly to what follows. 4. tco Ttjs aKepdrov] Sc. fiepei. The genitive of apposition is used (instead of tco aKepdra) by attraction from dyeXrjs prece- ding. 9. KoXoftov — nepdrav] " A polled herd." The gen. after a privative adj., like o^oXkos do-TTl8cDV. 12. to yiyvopevav] "That which falls to him." Cf. Legg. 1 1, 920 C : Icjelv ~\rjpp.d re Ka\ dvd- Xcopa tL 7T0Te Tea Kcnrrp\co KepSos Troiet to peTpiov' ypd^avras 8e, 6eivai to Yiyi'ou.ei'oi/ dvdXcojia kci\ \rjp.pa' Kai (pvXdTTew. lb. 12, 949 d : to 8e vopiapa yiyvecr6ai TJj noXei. Thuc. V. 49 : 6 tco 6eco ylyverai avrol inep ineivcov eKricreiVi 15. tco Kcikovpevcp pcovv^i] This expression indicates the fact that pebw^ was a rare 'word out of Homer. The characteristic of having solid hoofs is found to be coincident with that of making hybrids. 30 nAATON02 The latter description includes only two kinds. For dogs, though so- ciable, are not grega- rious. The ground of distinction between these two should be obvious to a friend of Theretetus and a geo- metrician. Man walks by a power of two feet: the remain- ing kind is potentially represent- ed by the mE. To 6Y ye Xonrov eTi t^s - Ae/a? dyeAi]? tcdv p. ?]fMpcoi> dfiiye? yevei 7rpbs dXXrjXa. NE. 20. Ylw t? ov ; iHE. Tt 6° ; 6 7to\ltikos ap eVrt/xe'Aetaz/ eytw S (pcLLveraL iroTepa Koivoyevovs (frvaeco? rj rivos \8lo- yevovs ; NE. 20. ArjXoU OTL TYJ9 dflLKTOV. mE. TavTrju 8r) 8el Kaddwep rd e/nrpoorOev, &>? hoiKev, rjfids oV^a cWcrre'AAetJ/. io NE. 20. Aet yap ovv. SE. Kat firjv to ye ftaov, ocrov rjfiepov /cat dye- p. Xahv, o~)(eSoi> irXrjv yevolv 8volv irdv rj8r) KaraKeKep- fiano-Tcci. to yap tS>v Kwcav ovk eird^iov /car- api6p.elv yevos coy ev dyeXaiois OpefipLaaiv. 15 NE. 20. Ov yap ovv. dXXa t'ivl 8rj tco 8vo 8iaipovp.ev ; HE. 'Qnrep /cat 8iKaiov ye QeaiTrjTov re /cat ere 8iave/ieiv, eVetS?) /cat yecofieTpias diTTecrOov. NE. 20. Tco ; 20 ££E. Tfj 8ia/JLeTpcp 8r]Trov /cat irdXiv Trj r^y 8ta~ fxeTpov 8iaj±eTpop. 1. eVt] When the horse and ass are taken from the hornless cattle. Xe/as] I. e. KoXofioKepaTOv. 2. apiyes yevei] " Do not mix their breed." Dat. of the mode, like (pvo-ei. 4. 6 noXiriKos ap'] For the late position of the interroga- tive 7rdrepa in the sentence, compare Soph. 237 c : e'x €lv ^°- Kovfxeu hv els ti, and note. Supr. 261 C : \eyeis 8e — norepov. Rep. 9, 57 I C : Aeyeis 8e Kal rlvas ; 17. biKaiov] " It is to be ex- pected of you." Cf. Meno 85 e : dlicaios yap el elbevai. 20. Tfj 8iap.eTpa> Btjttov] The diameter of the unit square was the subject of some of the ear- liest lessons in that geometrical arithmetic through which alone numbers had hitherto been stu- died : and it had been observed that this diameter is equal to the square-root of two. Hence, a foot being always the unit, this line was known both as rj Sidperpos and as f] Bidperpos rj dvvdp.ei Sinovs : and it is the nOAITIKOS. 81 %66. NE. 20. Tlwy ewres ; b HE. 'H (J)v(tls, rjv to yivos t'lficov tgov uvOpwiroiv K€KT7]Tat, pLCOV CtAAo)? 7TQ)S €1? TtjV TTOpdaV 7T€(j)VK€V T) KaOoarep y diapLerpo? y Swa/iet. dinovs ; NE. 20. Ovk aAAwy. S?E. Kat /xt)j/ 77 ye rou Kolttov yevovs Tcakiv iari abbreviated form of the latter expression, viz. 8lnovs Bvvapis, which gives occasion to the Stranger's somewhat laborious pleasantry. The incommensurability of this diameter with the side of the square (of */ 2 with i) was one of the most familiar lessons of this early geometry. Hence, possibly a , the omission of 2 amongst the irpoprjiceis apidfidi in the demonstration of Theo- doras (Theset. 147 d : rrjs re rp'i nodos rrepi Ka\ nevTeTTodos K.T.A.), it being taken for granted, without proof, that the dlrrovs dvvapis Was pr]K.a. ov £vpp.(Tpos rjj 7ro8iaia. While these were still recent discoveries, philosophers were led to see fanciful analogies to them in other departments of knowledge. Plato here satir- izes a tendency from which he was not at this time himself wholly free. The smile is al- ready on his face which pre- sently breaks into a laugh. Our view has been restricted to tame gregarious animals : to tame animals that tread the ground, that cannot fly, that have no horns, that divide the foot : thus oxen, horses, asses are excluded ; dogs are not gre- garious. What remain 1 What but swine and men 1 Human progression is measured by the power of two feet, that of swine, the only remaining ani- mal, by the power of four. This interpretation has been well supported by Dr. Badham in the ' Epistola' prefixed to his edition of the Euthydemus and Laches. 1. Hwr fines ;] " What did you say 1 ?" Expressing a not very unnatural surprise. 6. e'crri Kara 8vvap.1v av ttjs riperepas 8vvdpecos 8idperpos] "Is again potentially expressed by the diameter of our diameter," i.e. the diameter of the square of which our diameter, a/ 2, is the side. As the diameter of the unit square is */2, so the dia- meter of the square of ^/ 2 is -v/4- This appears, without the help of arithmetic, from the following diagram : A. f ab 1 square foot ; c d dia- meter of a b, and side of 2 ft. square dee; de diameter of 2 ft. square ; df square on d e : = 4 square feet. a As suggested by a favourable critic in the National Review. of buman power or, in o! Ii r word . 1 1 a power of j low 32 IIAATQN02 Tims man is differen- tiated from the pig. Kara hvvay.iv av rrj? rjperepa? Svvdpeco? Sidperpo?, p. 266. eiirtp Svoiv ye ean ttoSolv SI? ?re(f)VKvla. NE. 20. Ylco? 6° ovk earn ; kcii Sr] kou o~)(eSbv o fiov\ei SrjXovv pav&dvco. 5 mE. n.pOS Si] TOVTOl? €T€pOV av Tl TCOV TV p09 yeXcora evSoKip-rjaavToov av, co ^(DKpare?, dpa KaOo- pcofiev rjplv yeyovo? iv tols Siyprfpevot? ', c NE. SO. To ttoIov ; SE. TdvOpwiTLvov rjpcov dpa yevo? ^vveiXrj-^b? 10 Kal ^vvSeSpapLrjKO? yevei rw tcov ovtcov yevvaioTaray kolL dfia evyepeaTaTco. 5. erepov av] Those who have found in these words a new division, and would intro- duce here some fresh kind, — as geese or other domestic fowls (Ast, Stallhaum), which were cut off, supr. 264 e, or apes (Winkelmann), which as tame animals are hardly dye\aia 6pep- fiara, unless M. Winkelmann can find the prototype of Bea- trice and her apes in classic story, — were right in supposing that a distinct step in the ar- gument must be here indi- cated. Man has been distin- guished in terms of mathema- tical progression from the only remaining quadruped, the pig. But it remains to be shewn of which kind the king is herds- man. It has been determined what two kinds are still in competition. But the result of their competition remains to be decided. tcov ivpos ye~ka>ra evboKLfirjadp- tiov dv] " Which might have become celebrated as a joke." " 'Might have won us a fellow- ship in a cry' of humourists." npos yeXcora lit. " In respect of the purpose of creating laughter." 9. f]p.a>v] Qu. an leg. ww, cf. Soph. 217c, where the same doubt occurs. " That it should be the lot of our human family to run a heat with the grandest, and at the same time the least fastidious, of all creatures." gweikrixds] " Having been appointed by lot to run with." Cf. Hdt. V. 2 2 : avve^emnTe t£> rrpccTO), and Schw. Lex. Hdt. S. V. CTVV€K77iTTTeil>. 10. yevvaLOTara) is ironical. Cf. Rep. 7 > 5 2 9 h : ovk dyevvcbs p.01 SoKeZy ttjv nepl to. civco pdOrjcriv \ap[3dveiv Trapa aavrco fj ecm. But there is perhaps a humoi'- ous allusion (as Badham sup^- poses) to the unwieldy bulk of the creature. 11. evxepe o-rdrco ] Whereas man, as it was said in the Thesetetus, is 8vo-ko\ov Kal im- fiovKov £5iov. Schleiermacher well quotes Bep. 7, 535 e : ev- Xep&s, cbvrrep 6rjpiov veiov — iv dp.adla p,o\vvrjrai. The conjec- ture yevvaioraTov is quite un- nOAITIKOS. 88 266. NE. 20. Ka$opa> Kai paX aToirtos tjvpfiaivov. mE. TV cT ; ot)/c tf/co? varara a(\)LKveio-Qai tu. (3pa8uraTa ; NE. 20. Ncu, rouro ye. 37 E. Tooe »5e oi)/c ivvoovpev, cos eri yeXoioTepos 5 6 fiaaiAev? (patveTai pera rijs dyt/\r)$ IjvvSiaOc-'cov kcu tjvvSpo/Jia TreTropevpLevos tco tcov dv8pcov av irpos d rov ev)(€prj ft'iov aptcna yeyvpLva.crp.evco ; NE. 20. na^raVa<7£ /xeV ovv. 37E. Nw yap, co ^coKpares, eKelvo Ictti Kara- 10 (paves p.dXXov to prjOev tot eV Trj irep). tov ao(pLCTTr)v &Tr}CT€l. called for. There is no real difficulty in the coordination of yevvaioraTO) with evxepeo-ri'iTcp, and the echo in yevet yew. is clearly intentional, as in 17 yevei yewaia v dye\aia>v Tivi. Cf. Hipp. Maj. 288 d : ov ko/jl^-os dXAa avpepe- tos. Illfr. 268 a: ov povov dye- Xaiav dvdpdmatv dXka Kai rmv apxovroov civt5)v. That man should be the con- gener of the pig is in keeping with the humour of Theset. l6l C : otl tvuvtcov xprjpdrav pe- rpov eo-Tiv vs k.t.'K. And the race between the king and the swineherd recals another touch of satire in the same dialogue, (174 d) : ftacrikea eyKtopia£6pevov OLOV (JVJ3u>Tt]U. 7. av] I. e. As the pig was ev^eptaraTou tcov 0T)piu>v. Tip. t. e. (3. yeyvp. is an OXy- •moroil. For yeyvpvacrpevco irpos, cf. Legg. i, 626 b : koXcqs ye & £eve, (paivei poi yeyvpvdcrdai npos to hieihe'vai to. Kprjrcov vopipa. Compare with the preceding- classification the fourfold divi- sion of living creatures accord- ing to the four elements in Tim. 40 a : pla pev ovpavitov 6eiov yevos, ci\\r) 8e kttjvov Kai depo- iropov, Tpirr) he evvbpbv eihos, Tte^bv he Kai xepaalov reraprov. 10. Nvv yap] A collateral in- ference is sometimes stated as a cause, e. g. Gorg. 454 d : Aq- \ov yap av otl ov tovtou eo~Tiv. Badham would read ye apa in all such cases. 11. ev Tt) — ^TTjaei] Soph. run J 1. I i t • •! 11 tlic nice. Man win-, the 1 nil ning ni.iti'li, of course. But tliis Btrange race be- t w < in men ami pig8 is accom- panied by one more absurd, be- tween the king and the swine- herd, who, of all his subjects is 34 IIAATONOS most com- pletely trained to a life of careless ease. Certainly, as was .said this morn- ing, Dialec- tic prefers truth to dignity. Now for the shorter way. NE. 20. To TToiov ; p. HE. 'Otl rf) Tota8e fieOoSo) row Xoycov ovre aep,vorepov fiaXXov epeX-qaev ?) prj, tov re afxiKpo- Tepov ov8ev r)Ti/xaK€ irpb tov /ue/^b^oy, del 8e ko.6 5 avTi)v Trepaivet TaXtjOecrTaTOV. NE. 20. "Eoucev. HE. OvKOVV fX€Ta TOVTO, "iVCL flT) fl€ (frOf}? epoj- r-qaas ttjv fipa)(UT€pav 68hv rjrts tote rjv eVt tov tov fiaaiAecos bpov, olvtos uoi irportpov eXdco ; e io NE. 20. 20o6> ye. HE. Aeyco 8rj 8elv Tore evOvs to ire^ov tco 8l7to8l irpos [to] TeTpdirovv yivos Siaveificu, kclt&ovtcl 8e TCLvOpteTTLVOV €Tl /JLOVCp TCp 7TTT}VCO ^VVElXtJ^O? T7]V 8nro8a dyeXrjv ttolXlv tco \jfi\cp kcu ra TTTEpo- [c,(f)veL te'/jlveiv, Tp.rj6eicrr)s 8e avTrj? koll tot rf8r) ttjs avdpomovopLiKrjs 8r)XcQ0Eio-r]? te\vyj9, (pEpovTa tov 227 b, where the spirit of scien- tific method and that of satire interpenetrate as they do here, so that it can be hardly known which of them is made the vehicle of the other. 3. fj firj\ Sc. aep.vorepov. II. tots evdvs to 7re£6v] It is impossible to exj)lain this pas- sage so as to acquit the Stran- ger of inexactness. Either he has forgotten that the class of winged creatures was cut off (264 e), or he purposely begins the shorter path from an earlier point than where he gave no- tice of the existence of the two ways. Pei-haps the words roVe eZ6vs may imply this (cf. supr. 263 e). In any case the word Tre(6v is used in a different sense from that in which it occurs above, where it was opposed to the same nrrjva which it here includes. Tre^o'v is therefore = gr]po&aTiKnv, and opposed to ewbpov, " on land," not " on the ground," by an ambiguity like that which belongs to the same word when applied to an armament. Cf. infr. 267 b: TregovopiKov. This ambiguity probably gives rise to the in- exact reference. Compare Rep. I, 354 : epneaovros av varepou \6yov — where the theory spo- ken of, although discussed later, had been introduced before the other. Soph. 223 d, 224 c : pera^XrjTiKr]. Such slight inac- curacies perhaps do not arise from mere neglect : they are caused by Plato's instinctive avoidance of an over-exactness, which would be unnatural in conversation. nOAlTIKOS. 8fi 266. ttoXltlkov kcu fiaaiXiKov, oiov rjvio\ov eh avTi)v ivcmjcravTa, TrapaSovvai ras Trjs iroXttos rjvias, coy olKela? koll aura) tolvtt]? ovo-qs rrjs emo-Tr/pLr)?. 7. NE. 213. KaAcoy kol KaOairepei \peos ovreScoKas p.01 tov Xoyov, irpoaOeis ti]v eKTpoir^v oiov tokov koll, avairXrjpcDcras amov. 3?E. (fre'pe Srj, kcu ^vveipco/xev iiraveXOovres hri rrjv dp^rjv /* e 'x/° f r ^ s> re ^ e ^7"^ tov Xoyov tov ovo- /JLaro? rrjs tov ttoXltlkov Te^yr)^. NE. 20. Ylctvv fiev ovv. SE. T^y yvwo-TiKrjs to'lvvv liviO'Tr\p.r] KareSrjKfv. 2. Trapa8ovvtu — enio-Tr]pT]sj " To give into his hands the reins of the state, believing that they are his, and that this art belongs to him." (ravTr/s SC. ttjs dvdpconovopiKrjs.) g. 7TpOO~8e\s TT)V eKTpOTTTjv] Cf. Legg.3, 683 a : vvv ovv 8tj toctov- tov irXeoveKTovpev 777 nXdvy tov Xoyov. oiov tokov] " By way of in- terest." Cf. Rep. 6, 507 a : (3ov- Xoiprjv civ, einov, epe Te 8vvao~6ai dno8ovvai feat vpds KopicraaBai^ dXXd prj &>o-Trep vvv tovs tokovs povov. tovtov 8e S17 ovv tov tokov Te kcu eKyovov avTov tov dyadov Kopio-aade. evXaj3elo-0e pevToi, prj 7777 e^anaTrja-co vpds, KLJ38r]Xov drro- 818011s tov Xoyov tov tokov. dva- 7r\r]pa>o~as avTov SC. tov Xoyov. " Having given the tale in full." Cf. Symp. 188 e: « n H-eXnrov, dvcnrXrjpwcrai. The " shorter path" might have seemed too bare if given alone. 7. &epe 8fj Ka\ £vvelpcopev] " Come, now let us proceed to link together." Cf. Soph. 224 d : 101 vvv avvaydycopev avTO. For the idiomatic kcu, cf. Soph. Aj. 803 : e'l Tco Ka\ Xcyi^eadai a^oXr], 8. tov Xoyov tov ovopctTos] " The definition of the name." The words are emphatically repeated in order to fami- liarize the distinction between Xo'-yos and ovopa. Cf. Soph. 218 C : Set 8e del navTos nepi to irpdypa qvto pdXXov 8td Xoycov r) Tovvopa povov avvopoXoyr)- o~ao~6ai x^P 15 Xoyov. 1 2. dneiKaaBevj " Having been illustrated by an analogy :" viz. that of the avTonaXeis. Supr. 260 e : 17 fiovXei, KaQdirep elKa- £opev vvv S17, Kat Tovvopa napeiKa- (rcopev. Cf. Soph. 221 b: an avrrjs Ttjs irpatjecos dqbopoicodev Tovvopa. F 2 S6 IIAAT0N02 TO /JLOpiOV aVT€7TtTaKTLK(W tpprjOl], £(00Tp0(f)lKr) Se p. TTOlXlV aVT€irLTaKTLKrj9 OV TO (TjllKpOTOLTOV tcov ytvoiv b a7reo-^/^ero* kcu £ojoTpo(j)iKr)S ei8o? dyeXaiOTpocfjiKOi/, ayeXaior po(j)LKOv <5' av ttc^ovojilkov. tov Se iretpvo- 5 flLKOV fldAlCTTa d7T€T€pi>€T0 TtyVT) TX] irpoaayopevwv. to & carb tovtov 10 TprjpLa, eir) iroipLvr) 8l7to8l fie'pos dv6p(x)7rovopiLKbv eri c XtKpOev fiovov, tovt avTO io~Tiv rjdr) to fyjTrjBev, ap.a fiacrL\iKov tglvto kXyjOcv /ecu ttoXltlkov. NE. 20. YlavTairaaL ptev ovv. HE, 'Apd y, co Sco/cparfS", dXiqOcos rjpuv tovto, 267.2' 4. dyeXaiorpocpiKov S' av 7reCovofXiKov] Vid. supr. 264 e. The gregarious were first di- vided into land and water ani- mals, and then land animals into fledged and unfledged, to Avhich latter the word ne(6v was applied. These two steps are here remembered as one only: the second of the two distinctions being dropped, and the word 7re£oi> being under- stood to mean " on land." This confirms what has been said above in the note on p. 266 d. 6. ovk eXaTTOv rpnrXovv] This is the reading of ten MSS., including the best, and is re- presented in the version of Ficinus, who probably joined to [iepos ovk eXarrov (ov) (" par- tem nequaquam minorem." Cf. supr. ov to arp.iKpoTa.Tov tcov ye- va>v), which, however, is in- consistent with the context, and hardly grammatical. It seems most probable that we have here an unusual construc- tion, of which another instance occurs in Legg. 12, 956 e: v(pfjv 8e pi) nXeov i'pyov yvvaiKos pias ep.p.r]vov, where there is no difference of reading. Cf. supr. 265 c. Three MSS., H2Y, have rpinXov, which Stallbaum adopts. 8. For yeveaeas, cf. SUpr. 261 d, infr. 271 a. MSS. fiiKTov vopevriKr/s. The correction is due to Boeckh and Heindorf. 10. em TTo'ipvrj 8l7to8i] This is the point where the two ways meet. " The art of man- herding being the only portion left which has to do with bipeds." 11. ajia — ttoXltlk6v\ Accord- ing to what was said at first : 259 c. nOAITIKOS. 87 267. KaOajrep av vvv elprjKas, ovtco? iar\ kui irtirpa- ypcevov ; NE. 20. To 7T010V $Y) ; HE. To TravToaraaiv iKavco? eiprjadai to irpo- TeOev. 7) tovt aura kcu paXiaTa ?} tyrrjcri? eXXei7rei, 5 to tov Xoyov elprjadai pcev wcos, ov prjv iravTairaaL ye TeXecos careipydaOai ; d NE. 20. rtwy ewres- ; HE. 'Eyco &w Treipdo-opou tout avTO, o diavoov- /LLai vvv eri fxaXXov SrjXcJocrca. IO NE. 20. Aeyotf eu>. HE. Ou/cow tcov vofievTLKwv rjplv woXXcov (pavei- acov apTL Teyvwv put Tis rjv 1) ttoXltikt) kcu fuels tivos dyeXi]$ eiripeXeia ; NE. 20. Nat. I5 HE. TavTrjv 8e ye Sicopi^ev 6 Xoyos ov\ tirwcov elvai Tpocpov ovd' aXXcov Orjplcov, aAA' dv6pco7rcov KOlVOTpOfpLKTjV eiT LCTTY] prjV . NE. 20. Ovrm. But it is not really at an end. For, when the king is designated as the Man- herd, it must not be forgot- ten that he I. KaBanep ov vvv ei'pijKas] Sc. TrnvTcnra.cn. Cf. Soph. 2l8 a. " Have we really (kcu) done as you say 1 " 4. to rrpoTfdev] Cf. Soph. 2 1 8 e : tL BrjTa TrpoTCt^aiped' civ. 5. fj tovt avTO cnreipyao6ai\ " Or is it in this very respect that our inquiry is especially defective, that the definition has in a way been given, but still has not entirely received final completion 1 ?" Cf. infr. 277 b : d.Te)(va)s 6 Xdyos rjplv coorrep £a>ov — tt]V ivdpyciav ovk cnrfi\r](pevai tto). 9. vmv ] Dialectic makes the subject of inquiry clearer to both the minds which are engaged. Treipa.oop.ai. tovt a\)To\ " I will endeavour to do this very thing, to make my meaning at this moment clearer for us both." I. e. I will endeavour to give my present thought, what I desiderate for the main argu- ment, a complete expression. 17. ovo' aXXcov 6T)p'ia)v\ He falls back into the common parlance for want of a col- lective word to express "ani- mals other than man." There is less danger in this, now that the requisite distinctions have been made. riAATONOI is unlike other herdsmen in this, thai he is not alone in feeding or in tending his flock, but has many com- petitors, such as the merchant, husband- man, baker, gymnast, physician. aR. To 8t) tow vofitaiv ttolvtojv 8id(j)opov> koll to p. twv fiao-iAecov Oeaaco/xeOa. e NE. 20. To ttoIov ; SE. El' Ti$ tcov clWodv ro), Te'xvr)? a\Xr}9 ovopa 5 e\oou, KOivf) tyjs ayeXrjS ^vvTpotyos elvai (j)rjo-l koll TrpocnroieiTai. NE. 2D. Um 07/9 ; SE. Giov 01 6fJL7TOpOL KOLL yecopyol KOLL CTlTOVpyOL 7rdi>Te?, koll irpos tovtols yvpLvaaTOLL koll to twv ■olaTpwv yevos, olxrd* otl toIs nepl tol avOpocnrLva i>oiJ.evcrLV, ovs ttoXltlkovs iKaXecrafiep, iravTOLTraorL too Xoyco SiapLoixoLPT av ovtol avp,7rai>T€9, 00? afals p. 268 I. To 8r) tcov vupiiov\ It has been assumed that the king is a herdsman of men, but it is now found necessary to distin- guish the king from the herds- man. In this curious form the imperfect conditions of human government are indicated. 7rdvT. /cat 8rj /cat twv dXXwv irepi vofiecov 6 avros rpoiros. 15 v yap; "Would contend in argument." Cf. Theset. 1 60 e and note ; and see \eyoiev infra. (12.) ovtoi to> arop-aTi] The meaning of y{/i\6s depends on that to which it is opposed or correlative. In Legg. 2, 669 d, instrumental music without the voice is spoken of as ^tXf? Kadapiaei re kcu avXrjo-ei, and is strongly ob- jected to : while Xo'yot \j/t\oi in the same passage are words without metre, or prose. 15. tcov n'AXcov Tre'pi vo/zeW] 40 I1AAT0NO2 sung or whistled, or " attem- pered tn tin- oaten Hut.." And thus do all herdsmen pxcepl the king of men : who cannot therefore be ade- quately de- fined until we have parted off from him this crowd of rivals, and set him forth alone and clear. For NE. 20. 'OpOorara. ]> HE. rico? ovv i)fXLu u Xoyos 6p6o$ (j)avelTUL kou UKepaio? 6 7repl tov /3acnAeW, otolv avrov vopcea kou TpO(j)OU dytXrjS avOpGdTTLVriS 6£>ptV p.OVOV £KKplVOVT€S c 5 pvpcoov dXXcov dp(f)ta(3i]TovvTO)v ; NE. 20. OvScLfim. HE. Ovkovv opOcos oXiyov epurpocrOev e(J)ofir]Or}- pev v7ro7TT6vaai>Te? per) Xtyovres pev rt Tvyyavoiptv ayr]p.a fiaaiXiKOv, ov pi]v dneipyaG p.evoL ye elpev iron ioSi aKpifielas tov woXltlkov, eco? av rovs 7T€piK€)(v- pevovs olvtw kou tyjs avvvopjjs avrcp dvTLTroiovpevovs 7repteXoPT€9 kou yapiaavTes drr eKetvcov Kadapov povov ovtov diro^vcopev ; 26h Either nepl is pleonastic (ut ssepe) or the genitive is to be repeated with rponos. 3. aKepaios] " Perfect, with- out a flaw." " How is our definition not impaired by the circumstance, — 1" Cf. Rep. I, 342 b : d[3\afii)s kci\ anepaios i(TTiv opQrj ovcra (17 Te^vrj), 4. povov eKKplvovTfs] Cf. infr. 303 b : ttuo~u>v yap eKelvrjv ye c'k- Kpireov. 7. dXiyov eprrpoadev] 267 C, d. e'(poj3T]dr]pev vnonTevaavTes] Cf. Soph. 264 b. 9. o~xrjpa fiacrChiKov — St' anpi- (3elas tov ttoXitikov] " The form we described was indeed royal, but did not accurately corre- spond with that of the States- man." It appears presently that Ave have been imagining the Divine Shepherd of the people as he existed in the golden age. 10. ivepiKexvpivovs] " Cl'OAvd- ing in upon him." Compare the description in the Gorgias, p. 452 a, of the physician, the gymnast, and the moneymaker disputing the claim of the rhetor to be the agent of the greatest good for man. on croi civt'ik av irapao-Taiev k.t.X. Also ib. 456. A still nearer parallel occurs in the sixth book of the Republic, Avhere the true philosophers are Avith difficulty separated from the pretenders to philosophy. Cf. esp. Rep. 6, 488 C : avToiis oe del tu vav- Kkrjpa) 7iepiKCxyo-8ai oeopevovs k.t.X. And see Ar. Pol. IV. 12 : "Eo-ti 8e ov8e tovto Stop'tacit. pdoiov, Tvoias Set KaXt'iv dp%ds' noX- Xaiv yap emaTarav rj itoXitiktj koi- vwvia bevrai. I I. ttjs o-vvvoprjs avTG> dvTinoi- ovpevovs] avTa is partly the ethical dative, and partly go- verned by ovv : " claiming to share AA r ith him the task of tending the herd." I 2. Kadapov povov] " Alone and clear." Cf. infr. 303 d, e, 304 a. nOAITIK02. 4J 268. NE. 20. 'OpOorara p.ev ovv. SE. ToDro roivuv, co ^coKpares, rjfxtv ttou]T€ov, el /j.7] pLeAAoifieis eVl tcq reXet KaTaicrxyvou tov \6yov. NE. 20. 'AAAa pcr]v ov8apLu>9 tovto ye Spaareou. SE. ITaA^ to'lvvv e'tj a'AAr?? apx>J? &i ko.8' irepav 68oi> Tropev6i]vat riva. NE. 20. rioiW 577 ; aE. ^ythov iraihiav eyKepaaapievovs' av^yw yap fxepei del fxeyaXov fivOov 7rpoa-)(p^craadai, kcu to Xolttov Srj, Kaddirep eV toI? TrpocrOev, fie'po? del fie'povs e dcpaipovpLtvovs eV axpov d(piKi>€io-6ou to {rjTovp.tvov. ovkovv XPV 5 NE. 20. Haw fxev ovv. tins pur- po e wt mu.s!, bej in afresh travel by a different way ing our dis- 5 cussion with an an- cient tale, before we resume our of divisions, and con- tinue them until we 10 read) t he desired summit. 2. (I (ir) fieWoifiev] " Un- less we were to — as we feared we should if we neglected this." The optative may be defended by supposing an attraction from the preceding optatives : the past tense being continued in thought. But it is equally pos- sible that this attraction (from Tvyxdvoifiev) may have influ- enced the scribes. Ast and Stallb. COirj. peWopev. 5. i£ ciXXrjs dpx^s — nad* ere- pav 686p] " From a fresh start- ing-point, and by another road," i. e. approaching the subject from a different side. The myth which follows, like the digression in the Thepetetus, affords a rest after the thorny path which has been trodden, and also presents a deeper and more religious aspect of the question. Cf. Prot. 317c: 17 avrr] pot apx*] eariv — ij^rep cipri. Arist. Eth. Nic. VII. 1, § 1 : aWrjv TTOirjcrapivov; dpxrp>. 8, crpiKpd y en 77poaxpf]o~Teou, ei peWopev eppe\a><: 7rcos 8t]Xa>- crat to vvv iparcopevov j 10. pe'pos — {jjTovpevov] Com- pare Bacon, Nov. Org. II. 16 : " Turn vero post rejectionem et exclusivam debitis modis factam, secundo loco, tanquam in fundo, manebit — forma affir- mativa, solicla, et vera, et bene terminata." I I . en (inpov drpinvelrrdai. to £.] " To arrive at the object of our search, as it were to the sum- mit of a steep ascent." Cf. Rep. 7 j 5 I 5 e • &ia rpa^fi'ay rr/s di'afBdaecos ko.1 dvdvTovs. T;ie mountain-path (aTpanos) is kept with difficulty. 42 OAATONOS HE. 'AAAa 8r) tu> /ivdcp fjiov irdvv irpocreye rov p. 268 1'" vovv, KaOanep 01 7rat<5es" ttolvtias ov ttoXXo. eK(f)evy€i$ 7raf5i«y errf. NE. 20. Aeyoi? av. j SE. 'H^ TOLVVV KCU €Tl t /cat a7rofir)/ioi>€veis- 6 (paai yeve- adai Tore. 1. 'AAAa 817 tu> pv8a> — KaGinrep oJ 7ra75es] Cf. Soph. 224 d : pvdov — iraiaiv as oiktiv fjplv. So the myth in the Phsedrus is said 7rotSm TvenaLadai. Phsedr. 265 d. 2. Tvavrcoa — er^] " You are not many years escaped from play." Cf. supr. d, iraibidv. Ste- phanus (anticipated Ly a few MSS.) raised a doubt about the accent, and read 7rai8las : 864 d naiSi 9, 004 CI : t) Traioia xP co l Jievos j oii8e 7TG) tu>v tolovtcov hiacpepav. He has been followed by some editors, who translate Traibias err/ " years of childhood." Stallbaum justly replies tbat " 3'ears of child's-play" would only be a more graceful way of saying the same thing. But he errs with the rest in joining Trai8ias with em, al- though he sees that with this rendering noKv is required instead of noWd. The present is only one of numberless in- stances of hyperbaton which occur in these dialogues. Cf. Soph. 235a: on tbi/ rrjs naidias perexovrmv itrri ris uepcov. The genitive in the MS. reading, 7rai8ias t is, however, ambiguous, and I have ventured to intro- duce the plural natBid^, which exactly suits the context, and occurs several times in the Laws. Cf. Ar. Pol. VIII. 2 : Ata tovto Bel naidias eladyeo-dai Kciipocpv\nKovvTas rfjv XP1 s Trpoadyovras qbnppaKelas X^P tv ' avecris yap 77 toicivti) kIvt], €TTTim6pov Te Spoprjpa TL\(iu8os,' ety 68bv uX\av Zevs /xern/3uAAet. See also ejusd. El. 734, where the truth of the same legend is questioned. The " golden lamb" seems to have been known, with variations, to the author of the cyclic poem Alcmreonis and to Pherecydes (Schol. in Eur. loc. cit.), but it is difficult not to connect the other portent, as well as the revolution imagined by Plato, with the tale told to Herodotus by the Egyptian priests, " that in the course of the 11,340 years during which Egypt had been a monarchy, there had been no god in human shape ; but the sun had reversed his course four times, and that without any convulsions of na- ture in the land of Egypt. To which they added, that before the 11,340 years gods had ruled in Egypt, one of whom had been at each time supreme : of whom Orus, the son of Osiris, was the last." Hdt. II. cc, 142, 144. There is no ground, however, for sup- posing, as Boeckh (Philol. p, 1 18) at one time imagined, that the Egyptians had anticipated (through the study of their own monuments) the scientific theory of the precession of G 2 44 IIAAT0NQ2 HE. OuSa/im, dXXa to irepl tyj? peTaPoXrjs 8v- p. (jecoy re kgu di'aroXrj? rjXlov koll t(du aXXwv acrrpcov, cos dpa oOev p.ev dvareXXeL vvv, el? tovtov Tore tov tottov tSvero, dveTeXXe 8' €/c tov evavTLOv, Tore be 8i] i fiapTvp-qaas dpa 6 Oebs 'At pel fieTefiaXev avTO eiri to vvv o~yr\\ia. NE. 20. Aeyerai yap ovv brj koll tovto. HE. Kat fjLrjv av koll ty]v ye fiao-Cheiav rjv f)pf;€ Kpovo? 7roXXcov aKrjKoapev. > NE. 20. YlXelcrTcov lieu ovv. HE. Tt be ; to rot*? epnrpocrQev (pveaOaL yrjyevels b Kat /a?) €^ aAA^Aeoy yevvdaOaL ; 2 6 9 | the equinoxes. The reason advanced by Plato himself may possibly have given rise to the fancy in the first instance. " All that is visible must suffer change." Compare Seneca, Ep. 71. § 11 : "Quid enim ruuta- tionis periculo exceptum % Non terra, non ccelum, non totus hie rerum omnium contextus, quamvis Deo agente ducatur. Non semper tenebit hunc or- dinem, sed ilium ex hoc cursu aliquis dies dejiciet." (2.) eo-Kov, aKrjBea Bvpbv fyovTes, | voacpiv cirep re ttovcov *cat ol£vos" ov8e ti 8eiX6v I yqpas eTTrjv, atei oe 7rdSas Kat xelpas opoloi TepirovT iv QaKirjcri, kcikcov eKToadev dirdv- Tcof" I dvrjaKov S' as vnvco fiefitt/;- fievoi' eadXd Se Tvdvra | rolcriv etjV Kapnov 8' i'epepe £el8a>pos apovpa \ avTopdrrj noXXov re *cat aU TTaXai XtyOtVTWV . HE. TaOra tolvvv tcrri pev ^vpiravTa Ik tqlvtov irdOovs, Kol irpbs tovtol? erepa fivpla koll tovtcou ert Oau/jLaarorepa, Scot 8e ^povov ttAtjOo? ra pev avrwv a.7rea(3r]K€, to. 8e bito-ira.pp.eva elprjTou x^P^ ^cacrra c got a.XXrjXcoi'. o 5' earl Tvacn tovtois airiov to ird- 609, ovSeh eiprjKe, vvv 8e 8rj Ae/creW* ei? yap ttjv tov fiacriXeco? dirofteL^iv 7rpe\j/€L pi-jOev. NE. 20. KaAAicrr' etVe?, kol Xeye pLrjSev iXXel- 7TC0U. HE. ' Akovol? av. to ydp irav ToSe tote p.ev avTOs 6 6eos £vp.7ro8riyei 7ropw6p.evov kol avyKvKXel, tote 8" and, onoe more, how there were giants in 1 ili I days, the off Bpring of the Earth. yevtls] " That the earlier race of men had their generation from Earth." Plato is fond of this no- tion, which, as usual, he colours variously with his own imagina- tion. Cf.Symp. 1 90 b, 1 9 1 c ; Rep. 3,414; Soph. 248 c;Prot.320c; Tim. 23 e; Critias 109 c. The fable spoke simply of earth-born men. Plato finds in this a hint for his " Phoenician" tale of an earlier and more perfect mode of generation. He seems to blend together Hesiod's children of the earth and the army of Cadmus. See also Ar. Pol. I. 5 : row? 7rpd>Tovs, eire yrjyeve'is r/crav, eire in (pQopas Tivbs iaoodrjo-av. 2. ek ravTov ira6ovi\ " These all arise out of one and the same occurrence" (viz. the reversal of the motion of the Cosmos). 4. 81a be xpovov nXr/dos] Com- pare the way in which proba- bility is given to the myth of Atlantis in Tim. 2 1 d : 81a, 8e Xpovov Kai (pdopav tu>v ipyao-api- vav ov dirjpneae 8evpo 6 Xoyos. 5. 8ieaLv r)8ij xpovov, to Se irakiv avTopurov 6£9 ravavrla irepidyeTai, foois ov koll typovqcnv elXrj- \09 e/c tov o-vvappoaavTO? amo kot dpyas. tovto 8e 5 avTW, to dvdiraXiv Uvoll, did to?) i$j dvdyKr]? tptyvTOV yeyovev. NE. 212. Aid. to irolov 8-q ; HE. To kclto. Tama kol coaavTois ^X iLV " 6 * KaL TavTov elvai toTs iravTcov OeioTaTOi? TrpocrrjKet povoi>>, io acopaTos 8e (})vo-ls ov TavTrj? ttjs Tafjecos. ov <5e ov- pavov Ka\ Koapov iwcovop-aKapev, iroXXwv pev K.a\ paKaplcov irapd tov yevvrjaavTO? peTelXrjfav, d\dp ovv 8rj K€koli>(oi>7]K€ ye kou crcopaTO?. oOev avTa> pe- p. 265 , rected and impelled by God. Cf. the interpretation of Hera- clitus by Mn. Gaz. (quoted by Lassalle, I. 124) : 'E^el KapaTos (ivtt) (rfj ijfvxf]} ru 8rjpLovpyS crvveneadai Kai avco peTa tov deov rdSe to irdv avpnepnroXew Kai in' eKelvov Terdxdai Kai apxecrBai, $ la tovto tjj tov rjpepelv imdvpiq Kai apXTJs eXnidi Kara (prjo-l rrjv ^'xh v (pepeo-Qai. i. avrjKev] The poetical aor- ist, used because a point of time is spoken of. Cf. Theset. 150 C : paieveo-Bat. pe 6 6eos dvayKa£ei, yevvqv be dneKa\vo-ev. orav — xp° vov ] " When the number of revolutions which make up the time appointed for the world have now reached their consummation. " Note the hyperbaton of xP° vnv i an ^ compare the " number of the state" in Kep. 8, 546, esp. the Words orav nepiTponal eKacTTOis kvkXwv Trepiq K )opa<; tjvvdnTcoo-t. 2. to 8e~\ Sc. to nav To8e. 3. &ov t>v] This is added to explain avropaTov. Compare Tim. 30 b : vovv pev ev yj/vxf}, y i /v Xl v °^ * v ~<*>l J - aTl £vvicTTas to 7rav £vveTfKTaLveT0 — ovtcqs ovv 8rj — 8el Xeyeiv Tov8e tov Kocrpov £a>ov epy\rvxov evvovv re Tjj 11X77- 6eiq 81a ttjv tov 6eov yeveo~8ai irpovoiav. Kai (ppovrjo-iv ] Cf. Soph. 248 e: pr]8e £jjv aiiTO pr]8e (ppoveiv ' 10. oh — ru^ewy] "Is of a dif- ferent order." Cf. Phileb. 49 c: f] 8e do-0evT]s (ciyvoia) rjplv tt/v twv yeXoiav rjp'iv e'iXrjxe Ta^iv re Kai (pvaiv. ovpavbv Kai Koapov] Cf. Phaedr. 245 e : ivavra re ovpavov rrao-dv re ye'veo-iv. 12. Trapa tov yevvrjo-avTos] Cf. Tim. 37 C : 6 yevvrjo-as iraTTjp. drhp ovv — o-capaTos] In the Timseus also the body is the source of all imperfection, 86 b: to. 8e 7Tepl \j/vx^]V (vocrrjpaTa) 8ta cruipaTos e£iv T0id8e. 13. Kai o-vpaTos] Cf. Tim. 32 c: o-oopaToei8es 8e 8r] — Set to yevopevov eivai. nOAITIKOS. 47 269. rafioArjs d/jLolpcp yiyvtadai 8td iravrhs ol8vvoltov, Kara bvvajiLV ye {11)1/ o ti /mAiara ev rw aura) kutoc ravra fitau (f)opau KLveLTai' 810 rr\v r)(T€(0? 7rapdAAa£iv. grade. Y<-t it lias the least possi- ble change of motion, when the direction of its rota- auro 8e eavro crTpe(peii> aei crye8ov ov8evi 8vvoltov 5 tion ia re- \ / 9 / t / versed. ttXtjv tco T03V KLVovfievcov av ttolvtcov r)yovp.evcp. KL- Nowitcan- I. Kara bvvap.iv ye pijv — Kivei- rai] Compare Laws 7, 821 c, d, where it is said to be impious to attribute an inconstant mo- tion to the sun, moon, and planets. So in the Timseus (p. 37) Time is created in order to bring the creature as near as possible to the Eter- nal archetype. 3 . 816 — rrapaXkagiv] Only the most Divine things can be always alike. The Uni- verse, having a body, must suffer change. It moves as nearly as possible always in the same way (but cannot attain perfectly even to this) : "Where- fore it hath allotted to it a reverse revolution, as the least possible alteration of its mo- tion." The reasoning would be more complete if for avrov we might read tciutoG. Of. Tim. 36 d, 39b, C. avaKvKKrjatv = to avaira- \iv Uvat supr. This meaning is required by the context here and in Rep. 10, 617 b, eVara/cv- Kkovjxevov : Tim. 40 C, enavanv- KXrjaeis : lb. 37 a, dvaKVK\ovpevr] ; in all which places a retrograde motion is in question. The force of the preposition seems to have been lost in the use of the word by later writers. A homely il- lustration of Plato's meaning may be taken from the game of cup and ball : in which, in order to ensure a steady mo- tion, the ball is spun from right to left, and the player waits until it has begun to re- volve in the opposite direc- tion. The resilience of the string, which is the cause of this, would correspond to the blind impulse (gvpepwos eVi- Bvpla) which makes the uni- verse rebound. 6. TOiu Kivovpevcov av iravTMV ijyovfievf ] The language of Plato respecting the relation of the individual to the uni- versal soul is not consistent. In the Tima^us the former is a " particle" taken from the latter. In the Republic and Phsedrus, and less clearly in the Phsedo, the individual per- sonality of each soul is re- cognized. Yet in the passage of the Phsedrus there are some expressions in which the na- ture of the soul is generalized. Cf. also Legg. 10, 894 c : ra>v 8t) 8eKa paXicrra rjplv KivrjO-eav t'iv av TrpoKpivaipev opdorara naacov eppcopeveo-TaTrjv re eivai na\ npaKTtKTjv biacpepovrois ; Mv- p'ua avdyicq nov Siacpepeiv ttjv avn)v avTTjv bwapevr/v Kivelv. lb. 12, 966 e: 6 irep\ ttjv \}/v)(f]u ekeyopev, coy TrpeafivTarov re Ka\ deioTarov ecrrt iravroiv gov kivtjctis yeveaiv irapakafiovcra. aevaov ov- aiav enopLO-ev. av implies a contrast be- tween the divinest of all things 48 nAAT0NQ2 ooj ill. . -. e itself al- ways : for that is the pi i\ Liege of mind. Nor can mind ori. ginate opposite move- ments. Hence the universe is not always veiv 8e tovtco rare yueV aAAcos", avQis Be ii/aurlco? ov p Oe'pi?. e/c TrduTOiV 8r] tovtgl>i> top Kocrpov prjTe abrov \pi] (fyavai aTpe(j)(ii> eavrov del, fxr/T av 6\ov del viro Oeov arpec^eaOai Slttol^ koL ivavrias irepiayoiyds, prjr sav Suo rive Oeco (j)povovi>T€ eavrol? ivavrla or ptfaiv p olvtov, dkX, 07T€p dpn lppi-]6r) kol povov Xonrov, tote pev vir dXXrjS tTvpiroSrjyeio-Oai Oela? airla?, to {tjv irdXtv e7TLKT(£>pevov koll XapfidvovTa dOavaariav iin- and the leader of all that is in motion. As the former alone can remain always the same, so the latter alone can revolve spontaneously for ever. The phraseology recals Phsedr. 245 c, where there is a similar appearance of demon- stration. See esp. the words ak\a kcll toIs aAAotj oaa Kivelrai tovto Trrjyrj Kai apxi Kivrjcreco^. A comparison of the above passages leaves little doubt that by the Leader of Motion here is meant Pure Soul in general, of which the Deity, who sustains the universe, is a particular example. The doctrine of the multiplicity of independent souls (Rep. 10, 611 a) is here left out of view. The argument may be thus stated. All that is bodily must suffer change. The Uni- verse suffers the least possible change (or " diverges least from the motion of the same") in revolving on an axis in one plane opposite ways alter- nately. But the Universe can- not always be the cause of its own motion : only Pure Soul moves spontaneously for ever. Nor can Soul be the cause of diverse and opposite motions. Hence the mighty fabric is not self-moved always, nor always moved by God : nor by two Gods alternately, for, as before stated, spirit cannot be op- posed to spirit. There re- mains only the case which has been given. 7. to (r\v "nakiv e7riKTa>fifvov] " Receiving a new influx of life." 8. \afjLJ3dvovTa ddavaaiav iiri- o-K(vao-TX]v ] The world re- news her immortality, which she receives afresh from her Creator's hand. imo-Kevao-T^v = repaired, refitted. The word is omitted in Ast's Lexi- con (edition of 1835). Of. Legg. 5, 738 b: ovt av Kaivrjv e'| dpxijs T '£ irotfj ovt av TraXaiav 8i€(p6apptvrjv emo~Kevd£rjTai (jro- Xti/). The World grown old, like Milton's hermit-soul, now " Prunes her feathers and lets go her wings," which, in following her own blind will, " Were all-to ruffled and some- times impaired." ddavaaiav] Not merely ex- emption from death, but good- ness, the one immortal thing. Cf. Legg. 4, 7 J 3 e: ° €0r}, Batt-moredj *> « v » v ,/ v v >, /)/ ^^^ uor moved Ot eavrov avrov tei/at, Kara Kaipov acpet/evTa tolovtov opposite &>crre avaTraXtv iropeveaOau 7ro\\as irepi6bu>v pivpi- either i>y /« is > v / * v , / » v one Deity aoay ow to \xeyunov ov kcll i(roppo7rcoTaToi> dirt or more / ~ «,% 5 / than one, apLLKpOTOLTOV pOUVOV 7TOOOS £€J>OU. 5 for mind ovpyov] Here, as in Tim. 41a, the universe is entirely de- pendent upon the Creator for immortality. The word 89/u- ovpyos in Plato is equivalent to 6 ^vvi(TTas, 6 £vvappoo-as, 6 yev- vT]a-as, and has only the faintest trace of the mystic solemnity with which it was afterwards invested. 2. fit' eavrov] Eusebius has eavrov, and the reading of the Bodleian (with An), fit' eavrov eavrov (sic Bodl.), perhaps indi- cates some confusion. But St' eavrov, signifying that the world at such a time is the ultimate cause of his own motion, is not certainly wrong. Cf. Legg. 10, 903 e : peraj3dX\ei — fit' eavrijv rj St' erepav -^rvx^v. Kara icaipbv d- rdrrjs KVKKrjaecos TrepioSos. 4. lo-oppoTTOirarov] Because it is the most perfect sphere. era arpiKpordrov fialvov 710- 80s] Moving on the smallest pivot — in fact, a mathemati- cal point — in modern lan- guage, the celestial south pole. Like the Indian tortoise, the Univei-se has no surface on which to rest. The image of the top, used for another pur- pose in Rep. 4, 436 d (orav ev ra airy irrj^avres to Kevrpov 7repL(pepcDVTat), has probably sug- gested this expression. The Uni- verse is like a great humming- top when " sleeping." Cf. Legg. IO, 893 d: /cat Tore pev eo-riv ore j3ao-ii/ evos KeKrrjpeva TLvbs Kevrpov. II 50 riAATON()2 cannot lie opposed tu mind. But, which alone re- mains, it is at one time guided l>\ its Divine Author, and re- ceives from him a re- newal of life and im- mortality. And again, being let go at the most au- spicious moment, it makes countless revolutions NE. 20. tbaiverai y ovv 5?) kcu pa\a etKorco? p- 27a €ipi]ir0at ttuvO' oaa 8l€\i]Xv0u9. SE. AoyiadpevoL 8r) ^vvvor)cra>pev to 7ra0o? e/c tcov vvv XeyOevTOiv, o tvv e'(.jjap€v elvat tcov Oav- 5 paaTcov aiTiov. eari yap ovv 8rj tovt clvto. NE. 20. To ttoiov; SE. To rr)v rov ttolvtos (j)opav totI p.tv €(/)' a vvv KVKXelrai (pepeaOcu, Tore <5' eiri tuvuvtm. NE. 20. Ilw? 8r) ; [ ° HE. TavTi]v Trjv p.era(3o\r)v ■qyeiaOcu Set tcov irc-pi rov ovpavov yiyvopevcov Tpoircov waacov elvai pe- c yiarrjv kcu TeXecoTUTt^v rpowr\v. NE. 20. "Eolk€ yovv. 1 . /xaXa eifcdrwy] The Stranger has indeed spoken with an ap- pearance of artless simplicity well ' calculated to impose on the imagination of youth. 3. Aoyiadpevot. 8ij] " Let US, reasoning on what has now been said, try to comprehend, in all its bearings, the fact which we described as the cause of all the phenomena that have excited our wonder." 7. (popciv — (pepecrdai] Cf. Theset. 153 d : rj nepicpopa rj Kivovpevrj. Legg. 10, 906 b : al — (prjpai (pacTLV. 9. Has 817 ;] Badh. " Haec omnia adeo lucid a explicata sunt, ut mireris cur Socrates etiamnum hsereat, et per ilia 7rwj Si) respondeat. Neque vero Hospes dubitantem do- cere dignatur, sed ulterius pergit." One point, however, was not made clear, namely, how the change of the direc- tion of revolution was the cause of the other two tradi- tions : and it is this which the Stranger (though beginning av- codev iroOev un dpxrjs) proceeds to explain. IO. t5>v 7rep\ rov ovpavov ytyVO- peVCOV Tp07TO>v] Tile TpOTTT) Tj\iOV, or solstice, is the change in the apparent motion of the sun's place on the horizon at rising and setting. Horn. Od. O, 404 ; Plat. Legg. 12, 945 d. The word rpoivr, is here gene- ralized and extended so as to include every cardinal change in the celestial motions : in the same lofty spirit in which the Great Year (reXeos eviavros) is spoken of in the Timseus, or as we speak of the year of Saturn or Uranus. The word seems to be used in the same general sense in Tim. 39 d : tcov ao~Tp(ov oo~a 81 ovpavov no- pc-vopeva eV^e rpoivas. Compare also Ar. de Ccelo II. 14, §1, who says that if the Earth has a double motion there must be rpoTta\ also of the fixed stars. riOAITIKOS. 51 270. BE. MeylcTTa? roivvv kcll /j.€Ta(3oAas xprj vo/jli(Jelv yiyvecrOcLL rore tols ivrh? yjlilv oXkovctlv clvtov. NE. 20. Kai TOUT €LK09. 37 E. MeTafioXa? Se fxeydXas kcll iroXXd? kcll ttclv- tolcls avfx0opcu roivvv i£ dvdyK7]9 rore fieyiorou £jv{a/3cllvovcti rwv re dXXcov (cocov, Kai 8r) kcll to tcov avOpcoiroov yivos oXiyov rt TrepiXelireTai. 7rep\ Se tov-io tovs aXXa re TradrjfxaTa iroXXa kcll 6av\iao~Ta kcll Kawd ijvfi7ri7fT€i, fie'yLcrTOv be rode kcll <~vveTto\ievov rfj rod iravTos dveiXlljei, rore OTav r) tt}? vvv Ka6e- (TTr)KVLas ivavTLCL yiyvr)TCLL Tpoirr). NE. 20. To iTOLov : 15 by itself, like .-i huge and per- Eectlj -ba- lanced top, revolving on the fill- -t \M-ji. This change is, as it were, the solstice of the great year. And this crown- ing change involves many lesser changes, destructive to the animal economy. Hence many crea- tures per- ish, and of mankind also but 2. rots euros rjfiiv oIkoxxtlv aired] This is one of the in- versions or alternations of words with which these dia- logues abound. 5. (rvpv. lb. 153 a: rocrovrov a-rpaTonehov. " When sorrows come, they come not single spies, but in battalions." g. rav re aXXcov Trepihe'i- Trerai] The sentence returns to the indicative mood al- though redundant, because the last clause contains the prin- cipal statement. Cf. Thuc. "VI. 32 : i\ex6rj(rav roioi'Se Xoyoi riVo re aXXcov Kai 'EppoKpdrqs 6 "Eppcovos — eXeye roidde. IO. TOVTOVs\ SC TOVS TCOV CLV- flpdmwv nepiXeLTTopevovs. yevos om. pr. n. 11. aXXd T£ Tvad^para — piyi- (ttov 8e ro'Se] Cf. Tim. 20 a : Tipaios re Kptriav Se — , alib. 12. gvpninTei] "Coincide." The meaning of £w is promi- nent, as in £vp(pepopevovs. gwerropevov] Following the analogy of the world's un- twisting. Consentaneous with the rebound and reverse mo- tion of the Great Whole. 13. orav fj rrjs vvv rponrj] r?7S vvv nadeaTTjKvias, SC. TpoTrrjs, which, like the plural rpoTrals below, 271 c, signifies not only the " turn," but the cycle of movement which follows. The double meaning of the English word "revolution" nearly cor- responds to this ambiguity of rpoTTTj. " When there occurs the transition to the cycle opposite to that in which we live." H 2 nAATQNOS SE. ''Hi/ rjAiKiav €KacTTOV eiye rwv £coa)v, avrrj p. 270 TTpcorov pclv eon) 7rdvTcou, Koi iiravcraro TTOLV 0(JOV rjv Ovr/Tov iiri to yepainpov ISfiv iropevopievov, /uera/3aA- Xov 8e 7ra\i.v irrl tovvolvtLov olov veoWepov kou anra- e few are left. And on these few there passes a mighty elian-e. As the movement 5 X(OTep0V €(t)V€TO. KOLl TtOV fJL6V TTptafivTepOdV CCl AeVKCU of the , , , m / , v world, so rpt)(€9 e/xeXaLUOUTO, tcov o av yeveuovrcov ai irapdiai i. T]\iKinv] " Condition, or appearance, in respect of youth or age." Cf. Euthyd. 271 b: pd\a ttoXv eViSeScoKeVai poi e'8o£e Kai — ov ttoXv tl ti]v t\K\.k\.o.v duicptpeiv KpiroftovXov. This use of the word affords a point of transition to the meaning of " size" or " stature." Cf. Hdt. III. 16, IV. in. 2. eTravaaro — 77opevopevov ] "All that is mortal ceases at such a time to advance towards a more ancient look." to yepal- Tepov Ibelv, " that which is more aged to look upon." Cf. Phsedr. 253 d : XevKos I8e7v. Tim. 52 d : 7ravToba7rrjV ISeiv. Soph. CEd. Col. 327 : Svcrpop' opav. 4. olov vearepov] " Younger to all appearance." Badham conj. I6v, which is free from objection. But olov vearepov exactly expresses " younger in appearance, though not in years." and corresponds with yepalrepov I8eiv supr. The instance of olov with an adj., given by Passow, ai olov o-we^els klvtj- o-eis, is from a late authority (Schol. Ap. Kh. 3, 1 01 8). But the use is so closely analogous to other uses as hardly to need defence. Cf. infr. 277 c: ttjv — olov roll v to. aco/xara Xeai- vopceva kcu crpiKpOTepa kolO* rjpiepav kcll vvktol £k- aarrjv yiyvop,eva iraAiv eh ttjv tov veoyevovs 7rai8os (f)vaiv a7rrjei, Kara re ttjv ^j/v)(7]v /cat Kara to aco/ia, dp.evov, to 8e 8r/ yrjye- ves rival 7tot€ yevos \e%Oev, tovt rjv to kolt eiceivov 4>6opa, which follows the great rponx], has now been described, and we are next informed as to the mode in which the Earth replenishes herself. The existing generation being thus " compounded with dust," the Earth, which had previously lain fallow, began to produce her crop of heroes. 6. d(popowvpeva ] Badham ingeniously conjectures cnro- pewupeva. But the ellipse is easily borne. 7. rav Te\evr — eo-Tip ore Kal ols, where much needless difficulty has arisen. The notion of the backward current being communicated to the process of animal life illustrates the ancient concep- tion of motion as including change, o-apa ova. Bodl. An. 13. to e'£ aX\r)\oov — yevvu>- pevov] Sc. yivos, or perhaps, as sometimes happens, the ac- tion of the verb is made the subject of the passive voice. For this, cf. Soph. 221 a : to — avao-ncopevov. In that case the concrete is put for the ab- stract to yevvapevov for to yevvao~8cu. 14. ev TJj Tore cpvaei] "Had no place in the course of na- ture which then obtained." For a similar use of t in earth arise again. This was bhe giant brood, of whose last relics the tov %povov e/c -}/?;? naAiv dvaar pecjjo/xevov -, d.7r€/J.vr)~ p. 271 /J.OV6V6T0 <5e v7ro tcov rjfxerepcov irpoyovcov tcov 7rptoTcov, 01 TtAevroocrr) /xtv rfj irpoTepa irepKpopa tov e'£?;r Xpovov iyeiTovovv, rrjcrSe <5e /car' apyas e((jvovTO' b STovtcdv yap ovtol KtjpvKe? iyevovO' t-jfuv tcov Xoycov, OL VVV V7TO TToXXwV OVK 6p0LO9 ClTTLCTTOVVTaL. TO yap evTevOev, oipai, ^pj) ^vvvoelv. eyppitvov yap Icttl too tov? TrpeafivTas eiri ttjv tov TraiSb? ievai (pvcriv, 4k tcov T€T€\€VTr)KOT0i)i> av, Kei/uevcov 8e iv yrj, iraXiv I. (K yi]s ttuKiv avaarp€(j:ope- vov] The bodies which Earth has absorbed she gives foi'th again to be the habitations of other souls. It appears cer- tain from infr. 273 (however strange the conception) that the yrjyevels are born like the army of Cadmus, in full matu- rity, and then follow the stages which are here described : first attaining to eai'ly man- hood, then to youthful prime, and then to childhood, and so disappearing from the Earth : old age being literally un- known, as in the description of Hesiod. 3. nepicpopa] . Not " period" but " revolution" = the time during which the Universe revolved in the former way. Cf. supr. a, tt] rare cpiia-ei : infr. 274 e, tov £k tyjs vvv wepicpopus Ka\ yevecrecos /3ao~i\ea. 4. eyeirovovv] " Were neigh- bours to" — i.e. next in point of time. Our first ancestors lived in the times immediately suc- ceeding the end of the former motion. en i/ecoo-ri tov Ai6j ttjv apxrjv exovros, Gorg. 5 2 3 b. 5. tovtcov yap ovtoi KrjpvKes — tcov \6yav] Compare the care which is taken, in Tim. 22, 23, to account for the preservation in Egypt of the legend of Atlantis, and the disappear- ance of the same in Greece. 6. vtto TvoWav — airto-rovvTcii] Cf. Plnedr. 229 c: o-v tovto ird- 6ei to p,vdo\6yrjfia dXrjdes eivai ' } K.T.\. to yap — avvvoelv ] " For we must seek to comprehend, methinks, that which follows what has now been said." 7. exop-fvov yap iaTi tw] The dative after ixopevov is curious, but exopevov eon is not quite the same as ex erai 5 an d the change of tg> into tov (if a change were required) would be easier and also better than Stallbaum's conjecture of eiro- p,evov for ex°l XfV0V - " Eor it is of a piece with (hangs together with) the aged men's returning to the nature of infancy that from the dead also," &c. 8. e'*c tu>v TeTekevTTjKOTav — (pvopevovs] The irregularity of the construction is caused by a feeling that the dead persons are not the same with those who rise. This does not, howevei", prevent the sentence from con- tinuing as if tovs TerfXevT- nOAITIKOS. 55 271. e\el ^vvKTTaixevovs kcll dva(Biodo-K.oiievovs,\*} rfj Tp07nj crvvavaKVKXovnevi-is els ravavrla ti^s yeveaecos, kou y-qyevels Srj Kara tovtov tov Xoyov e£ dvdyio]? (fjvo- c fievovs, ovtcos e\euv Tovvofia kou tov Xoyov, ocrovs fii] debs avTciov els aXXrjv fiolpav eKo/juaev. A few, in* deed, were exempted by Divine ordinance t]Koras were the subject. Cf. Thetet. 182 b : d\\' e'£ dp(po- Tepcov npbs aXXrjXa avyyiyvopevcov ras alcrdrjcreis Kal tci alcrdrjTa diro- TLKTOVTO. TO. [J.€V TVClld ClTTa yiyV€- crdai, ra be alcrOavopeva where see note. So that the yrjyeve Is are composed of the elements which have been restored to Earth from the life of the for- mer cycle. The Word yqyevels is a " tertiary predicate." " Being born by generation from the Earth." 1. dva(3tcjo-Koiievovs] " Com- ing to life again." This, as afterwards appears, is the quickening of a soul which has been "sown" into the earth, infr. 272 e. enecrdai, which is commonly inserted before rjj Tponr), is omitted in Bodl. A IT. The word is unnecessary, and is very likely to have been added, from con- jecture, by some one who thought the apodosis too long deferred. 2. avvavaKVKKovpevrjs] Stall- baum, following a hint of Schleiermacher, writes o-vvava- KVKXovpevovs, which he finds in one MS. (Zittav). But this only increases the obscurity, for the phrase els TavavTia ttjs yeveaecos is hardly intelligible. Teveo-is is here used in the widest and most abstract sense for the general process of Nature, the current of which is reversed with the motion of the Sphere (rfj rpoiTji = the change of mo- tion), whence the old gi - ow young, and the buried rise from earth again : diminution taking the place of growth, and generation of decay. See, for a parallel notion in mo- dern poetry, " The thoughts of men are widened with the process of the Suns j" and cf. infr. 273 c: ttjv em ttjv vvv yeve- trcv 686v. 274 c: rrjs vvv irepi- (popds Kal yeveaecos. Also Pha^dl*. 245 e : Ttdvra re ovpavbv Trdcrav re yeveatv. See also Tim. 82 c: Srav dvdiraXiv rj yevecris tovtcov tto- pevrjrai, Tore ravra 8iav yivos prj cpiXoaocp^o-avTi. Kal irav- TeXcos KaOapco ojtiovti ov Bepis dcpLKvelcrdat. tlXX' r] tco (piKopadel. Cf. Pha?dr. 249 a, 5. avrcov] I. e. of those who should have been born. The elements which should have been united with the soul are identified in the language with the soul herself. mg thus bo again. 5 There can ;6 nAATONOS expression, as m pecrai vvktss. IO. avTijs KVKkrjcreais] "For first the whole revolution was itself guided by the Divine care." avrrjs gives emphasis to KVKkrjcrecoi as Opposed to ra £cba. I. e. The universal movement which involves all else. ii. enifie\ovfj.evoi] It is per- haps implied that he acts only through the inferior deities. 12. Tws vvvf — dieikrjppeva^ The general meaning of this ap- pears from infr. 272 e : ol Kara TOVS TOTTOVS ovvapxovTcs TCp pe- y/oT<» halpovi 6eul. But the exact construction is not ob- vious. Stallbaum proposes to read 00s 8e vvv — tsovt tjv — Stft- X-qnneva. The words as they stand, however, will afford the same sense without any tor- ture, by supposing peprj to be, like tou Kokocpava in Theaet. 153 c, or 8vo pept) infr. 283 c, a cognate accusative in apposi- tion, expressing the mode of the action of ?ipx^. " The parts of the universe every way being divided under the rule of deities, just as is now the case in certain parts." (w9 vvv Kara ronovs ravrov tovto SC. yiyverai.) This last idea, though hardly consistent with the gene- ral spirit of the myth, receives some illustration from Legg. 5, 747 e, where the superiority of the inhabitants of particular re- gions is attributed to a Divine influence : as of? 6eia tis enl- ttvoui ? ev eKarepacs ^ypmliTTet tolls Tpoirals yiyveaOat. SE. KaAwy tco Xoyto ^vpTraprjKoXovOrjKas . o <$' rjpov irep\ tou iravTa avTopaTa ylyveadat T0I9 dv- OpcoiroLs, i]KiaTa Tr)$ vvv earl Ka@ecrT7]Kvia? (fiopas, toaAA' tjv teal tovto tt}$ epjrpoaOev. tote yap avTrjs irpcoTOV 77/9 KVKXrjo-eco? r)p\ ev e7rip.e\ov/i€v09 0A779 6 0609, '[COS" VVwf KaTOL T07T0VS TaVTOV TOVTO, VTTO 06COV 2. ak\a §r] tov fiiov] The fable of the yrjyevels has been applied : the application of the story of Atreus is evi- dent : it only now remains to find a place for the legend of the golden age : when mpnov ((peps £e[8wpos apovpa avTopciTT], In that former cycle the spon- taneous productiveness of the Earth was as apparent in the vegetable as in the animal kingdom. 3. rais Tponals] The plural marks the concrete form of nOAITIKOS. 57 271. dpypvToav ttclvty) tcl tov koct/jlov p-tprj SieiAyppeva. KOU 8r] KOU TCL {cOOL KCLTCL y€VY) KCLL dytAa? Olov l>OfJL€L9 Oeioi 8i€iAr)(f)€o-aL> 8atpoi>e9, avrdpict]? eh iravTa €kcl- e (ttos Ikolcttois wv oh clvtos eveptv, coare out dypiov r)v ov8lv ovre dXXrjAcou i8(o8al, iroAefios re ovk kvr\vh ov8e o-tolctls to irapcmav ccAXa 6' oaa Trjs TOiavT-qs eo~TL KaTaKoo~fii]o~€cos eiropeva, /jLvpi* av ely Xeyeiv. to 8 ovv t(dv dvOpteircov Ae)(6ev clvto/jLCltov irepi (3iov 8td to TOi6v8e eiprjTai. 6eos eve^iev clvtovs olvtos Deities, each of wli'iin was all-miffi- cient for his own flock in all things. Then was nothing wild: no devouring one an- other : no war or dis- cord of any kind. All eivai. For SieiXrjppeva, cf. Al\ Pol. VII. 6 : (3Xeyj/as — -rrpbs ttii- v eprjpa ehai iravra (Plat. Legg. 10, 908 c). It must be admitted that the text is not wholly free from suspicion. Cf. infr. 2y2e: 01 Kara rovs tottovs, and note. Qu. an. legend. wo-auTOJS 8' au Kara ronovs k.t.\.1 atirws being dropped from ho- moioteleuton, the remaining letters, S' av, might easily be corrupted into vvv. The go- vernment of fiept] is in this case less harsh : the clause v-nb 6ea>v — 8iei\rjfj.fif'va being explanatory of Kara tottovs ravrov rovro (sc. e8pa, i. e. rjpX ev eTnp.eXovp.evos rov Koo-p.ov). 2. Kai dyeXas] As the subdi- visions of each tribe. The word recals the previous discussion. 3. 8ieiXrjs\ The ge- nitive is accounted for by supposing the participle to be added pleonastically. " What belongs to this mode of ten- dance and is consonant there- to." Cf. however Rep. 6, 504 b : rav Trpoeiprjpevav enopevas drroSel^fis. 8. r6 8' ovv] "And accord- ingly (to return to the point) the tradition that mankind in particular had a spontaneous subsistence is to be accounted for in the following way." 9. debs eJTKTTaTow] The 58 nAATONOS iiruTTCLTMV, KaOdircp vvv avOpcoTroi, £coov ov erepov p. 271 Oeiorepov, dXXa yevrj (fxxvXorepa avrcov vop.evovcri. ve'p.ovTO? 8e ixeivov TroXiTelal re ovk rjaav ovde ktt)- (T6L9 yvvaiKcov kou 7ral8cov' €K yrjs yap avefiiaxTKOvTO p. 272 biravTes, ovSev p€p.vrjf.LevoL tcov irpocrOev. dXXa ra pev Toiavra cmrjv irdvra, Kapirovs 8e d(j)dovov9 ei)(Ov diro T€ SevSpoov kou 7roXXr)? vXrj? dXXijs, ov)( vtto yecopyia? (j)vopevovs, aAA' avToparrjs dvahiftovonqs tyjs yijs. yvp-voi 8e kou aorrpooToi OvpavXovvres ra iroXXa Ive- same belief in a past theo- cracy is expressed in the Laws, with a similar allusion to the Satumia regna, and is used to point the same lesson, — that a paternal government, as man- kind are now constituted, is a visionary dream, and that the rule of Law, devised by rea- son, which is all which re- mains to us of Divine guid- ance, is the best available substitute ; 4, 7 1 3 c : olov vvv TjpeTs 8pa>p.ev rots iroip.vioicri nai oo~a>v rjfxepot, elcriv aye\ai' ov j3ovs @o£>v oi8e aiyas alycbv ap^ovras noiovpev avroio-'i rivas, ahX facts avrcov 8ecrir6£op.ev, ilpeivov eKelvcov yevos. ravrbv 8f] (cat 6 deos apa (cat (pCkdvBpaTTOs mv to yevos cip.eivov T]p.a>v eCpicrTr] ro ra>v 8ai- p.6vv, elpijvrjv re /cat atSco (cat evvop,lav (cat d(pdoviav 8iKrjs Trapeyopevov daracriaaTa (cat ev- 8aipova ra ra>v dvdpdiTrcov dneip- yd£ero yevrj, I. e7ricrrarcoi>] Cf. Gorg. 523 C : 01 eirifieKrJTai. 3. 7roXiT€tat] Forms of go- vernment are rendered super- fluous by the presence of a Supreme Will. re] The apodosis is broken off through the expansion of this clause by an afterthought, and is resumed in ndpnovs 8e infr. Compare with this passage the description in the Protagoras, p. 321, of the state of man be- fore the introduction of the arts of life ; and Glaucon's va>i> 7roXis in the Republic, 2,372. The absence of property and mar- riage in the perfect state is again mentioned in the well-known passage of the Laws, 5, 739. 4. dvefiiwo-Kovro] Rising from the dust of former genei'ations. Cf. supr. 271 b. 5. ov8ev pepv7]p.evoi\ Hav- ing been steeped in the river of forgetfulness, Rep. 10, 62 1 e : and therefore ignorant of all previous relationships. 6. and re 8ev8pa>v] Cf. Hes. Op. et D. 233 : Wv8Uaio-i p.er dv8pao-i I Tolai (pepei fiev yaia ito\vv (Biov, ovpeat 8e 8pvs axpr) p.ev re Cpepei (Sakuvovs, p-eaar) 8e pe\lo-cras (c.r.X. ; and Horn. Od. T. Ill: Cpeprjai re yaia p.e\aiva 7rvpovs (cat KpiBds, ftpldrjo-i re 8ev- 8pea Kapna, quoted elsewhere by Plato, Rep. 2, 363. 9. evep-ovro] " Lived under their shepherd's care." nOAITIKOS. 59 272. fiovro' to yap tu>v tbpcov clvtols aXvirov €K€KpaTO, paXaKas Se evvcts ei^ov ava(pvop.evqs €K yi]9 noa? h a(})0ovov. tov Si] filov, co ^aiKpare?, aKovas pev tov twv eVi Kpovov Tovbe b\ ov # Xoyo? eVrt Aihs elvai, tov vvvl irapcov olvtos rjcrOrjaaL. Kplvat <5' avTolv tov ev8cupov€o~T€pov dp av dvvaio re kcu WeX-qaetas ; NE. 20. OvSapm. HE. BouAet SrjTa eyco aoi Tpoirov tivol SiaKplvco ; NE. 20. Haw p.ev ovv. HE. Ei pev tolvvv ol TpocptpoL tov Kpovov, ira- of wives and chil- dren, for they sprang fromEarth, not know- ing wlience they came. ' Contrast, their life, devoid of care, in a perfect cli- mate, tak- ing no more thought for raiment than the IO lilies of the I . to yap tcov copa>v ] Cf. Odyss. A. 565-8; Hdt. I. 142; Plat. Legg. 5, 747. 3. dKovets pev] Subaud. jjarBrja-ai S' ov (" although you have not seen"). 4. bv * Adyo? — eivai ] bv a>s CH rcB cos cett. This pro- bably implies the same feeling of half- credulous or ironical respect towards the popular religion which appears in Tim. 40 d. To Plato the mythology of his countrymen was but a rumour, an echo from the past. 5. iTapwv] " As an eye-wit- ness." So the word is fre- quently used (pleonastically as here) by Sophocles, e. g. (Ed. Col. 1587. Kplvai 8' — tov evhaipovecTTe- poi>] Compare the judgment between the just and unjust life in Rep. 2, 360 d, and be- tween pleasure and knowledge in Phileb. 52 e. 8. rpoTTov rti/a] I. e. hypo- thetically. 10. El pev — xP eias ] Compare with the doubt here expressed as to the happiness of the golden age, the rejection in the Republic (2, 372) of the simple or primitive state as a basis for the definition of jus- tice. The picture of an earthly paradise has been purposely heightened, in order to enforce the remark that this is not the chief good of man. Cf. Eu- thyd. 289 b : ovde ye el rts ecrriv e7no~Tr]pr], coore aOavarovs iroieiv civev tov inio-TacrdaL Tjj cidavacriq \prjO-8ai, ovbe tcivttjs eoiKev ocpe'hos ov8e'v. See also LyS. 221 e : Horepov, rjv A - ' eyco, npos Aios, eav to kcikov aTToXrjTcu, ovSe Treivfjv en ecrTai ov8e Biyp-fp, ov8e ciXXo ov8ev tcov toiovtcov k.t.X. The identification of the king with the shepherd, and the notion of a theocracy, to which Plato here inclines, but which he rejects as un- suited to the present state of man, seem to be of Pythago- rean origin. Cf. Pythagor. Fr. § 2. (Mullach p. 533) : *E X « 8e Kol cos 6e6s 7roTt Koapov paaiXevs Trpbs ivokiVj kcu cos iroXis ttotI koct- pov, /3acrtXei(S irpos 6e6v. a pev yap noXis Ik ttoXXcov Ka\ 8ia(pep6vTcov o-vvappocrdelcra Kocrpco avvTa^iv Ka\ appoviav peplpaTat, 6 8e /3a- criXeis cipxav e'xv koli per 5 aXX^Xcou optXovvTe?, kou irvv6av6p.evoL irapa Truo-rjs (puo-eo)9 ei TLva tls id lav Svvapiv eyovaa fjaOero tl diatyopov tcov aXXcov as* auvayupphv (ppovr)ar€cos, ev avopcoTTOis 7rapeo~x r ll JLaTLa " raL - Ibid. § 3, p. 535 ; 6c6iuii6v e'vrc n pay pa fiacriXeia. These fragments, however, belong to a later time. See Introduction to the Statesman, § 3. It is left uncertain what deity had charge of the human race. But the notion of Deity is so far generalized that this matters little. See, hoAvever, the words rav eir\ Kpovov — ol rpocpipoi rov Kpovov. (9.) ol rp6(pip.oi rov Kpovov] " The flock or charge (lit. 'nurslings') of Kpovos." The name is peculiarly applicable in the present case, where the Deity in charge not only go- verns, but attends to all the varied wants of those whom he governs, avrapKrjs $>v ols avros vep.ii. So also in Rep. and Laws, those for whose education the speakers are providing are spoken of by the same affectionate name. R e P- 7 j 5 2 ° d : 'AneiOrjO-ovo-iv rjp.1v ol rpocpipoi ; Legg. >], 804 a : ravrbv 8r) Kai tovs f/perepovs rpocpipovs Set. 2. dWa ko\ 6rjpiois~\ The traces of this in the regular mythology were few. (Cf. however, the stories of Procne, Philomela, and the like.) But the Fables of iEsop, and the cycle to which they belonged — partly invented to please the childish imagination, but probably not without sugges- tions from Egypt and the East — were sufficient to suggest the idea to Plato. See also Porphyr. V. Pythag. 1 9 : (llvOa- yopas Keiv ire(pvKev o>s aya66v. The close and friendly intercourse with Nature, which Plato here imagines, is well described in the little German fable 'The Story without an End.' One point of coinci- dence may be quoted — when the child goes to sleep in the cave, the grass springs up spon- taneously to make his pillow. nOAITIKOS. 61 272. tVKpiTOV OTL TCOV VVV OL TOT€ pVpLCp 7TpO$ CvSaLflOVLav fiiefepov, el 8e iparnrXapevoL ctltoov d8i]v koll ttotcov SieXeyovTo irpos dXXyXov? koll tol Orjpia fivOovs, ola d Srj koll tol vvv irep\ olvtcov XeyovTai, koll tovto, m ye Kara rrjv epyv doljav d7ro(j)ijvaadaL, koll paX' evKpL- rov. opco? <5' ovv ravra pev d(pcopev, eoo? av rjpiv /JLTJVVTrjS TL9 LKOLVOS (PoLvfj, 7TOT€pCO? 01 TOT€ TOLS IttlOv- p.iav koll ttj? tgov Xoycov Xpela?' 01) $ €V€kcl tov p.v6ov rjyelpapev, tovto Xck- tcov, Iva to fJLerd tovto els to irpocrOev irepaivcopev. 'R7T€LSr) yap irdvTcov tovtcov y^povos eTeXecodrj koll pL€Ta/3oXrfv edet yiyvecrOaL koll Srj koll to yqLvov rfSrj e 7rdv dvr/XcoTO yevos, irdcras eKao-Tr)? Trjs \j/vx^ Ta $ the way in which the Quislings <>f Baton) employed their gold- en time. Now when 5 that cycle was at an end, and each soul had ful- filled the number of her births from Earth, the pilot of the Uni- verse let go the helm. Rebound- ing with a shock, the mighty JO The same conception of in- quiry, as a conversation with the object of study, appears in Legg. 3, 689 e : Trdcras cos enos elnelv SirjpoorrjKa tcis Koivcovlas. " Inquiring from every nature, to see if one having some peculiar power had perceived something different from the rest which might be gathered into wisdom's treasury." 2. el Se ep.TriirXdp.evoi — ] Cf. Legg. 7, 807 d : toIs 8tj Tairrj KeKoaprjpevois apa ovdev Xeinope- vov eariv kciI Tvavrcnracnv Trpocrrj- kov, dXX' iv Tponcp Qoa-K-qparos etccKTTOv niaivopevov avrcov 8el grjv. Rep. 3, 407 a, b : 6 8e 8rj irXovaios ovdev e^ei toiovtov epyov itpoKelpevov, ov avayna^o- pevw dwexeadai dftiooTov. 3. ofa] Flor. b. Ven. S. 0T01. In either case pvdoi is to be sup- plied as the subject of Xeyovrai. 6. S' ovv] But to resume. 7. 7roTepcos] The clause de- pends on the verbal notion in prjvvTrjs. 9. tov pxiOov rjyelpapev] " We have waked from long slumber a ghost which seems unwilling to be laid." Cf. Rep. 5, 346 a : ocrov Xoyov rrdXiv Kivelre rrepl rrjs TroXiTelas ! — ovk tcrrf oaov eapov Xoycov irreyelpere. 10. iva — nepalvoopev] " That we may get forward with what is still before us." Cf. Rep. 1, 346 a : iva ti Kai 7repal.voop.ev. 11. ttcivtoov tovtcov ^po'i'os ] " The time required for all that has been described." 12. efiei] Cf. Prot. 321 c : ■q elpappevr/ rjpepa napr)v iv fj edei Kal avdpooTTov i£ievai etc yrjs els (pas. Compare Emped. w. 66- 69 : hvTap inel peya NelKos evi peXeeacriv edpeepGr] | es Tipas t dvopovcre, TeXeiopevoio \povoio, o acpiv dpoi(3a~tos TrXaTeos TrapeXrj- XaTat 'OpKOV. to yrjivov yevos ] " The race whose generation was from the Earth." 13. irda-as — a7ro8e8ooKvias ] " Having completed her pro- 62 IIAATQNQ2 y€V€(T€LS riTrodtSooKvias, haa r]v eKaaTrj irpoaruyOtv, p. 27s per cycle of births." For Pla- to's doctrine of transmigra- tion, see Phredo 82, 113, 114 ; Rep. 10,618-620; Pbsedr. 248, 249 ; Tim. 42. According to the Phsedrus (248 e), the pe- riod here spoken of must be at least 10,000 years. Empe- doclcs and Pindar speak of 30,000. Tpi? fiii> pvpias &pas dnu p aXaXrjadat. I. on a — Trecrovarjs] " Having fallen in so many sowings into the earth as it was appointed unto each (to fall) :" i. e. having been sown in earth so many times. Tbese words have oc- casioned some difficulty. Cor- narius, followed as usual by Stephanus, read ko.1 8vvcil ^mwv to 6eo(Tej3e(TTaTov. lb. 42 c!: ecmeipe tovs pev els yqv, tovs S' els ae\q- vqv, tovs 8' els TaWa Sera opyava Xpovov. to Se pera rbv a-nopov toIs veois irapeScoKe 6eo7s acopaTa TrkaTTeLV 6vr]Ta k.t.X. TllUS the souls are sown into the earth and there a body is given to each. The verbal meaning of oireppa ( = the act of sowing, not the seed,) occurs in Hes. nOAITIKOS. 63 ToaavTOL els yr\v aireppara 7T€aov(n]?, rare <5?/ rod ttolvtos 6 fiev KvfiepvrjTy?, olov irrj^aXicov omko? dr) re kcu ^v/x([)uto? 67ri0vpla. iravres ovv oi Kara tov? tottovs o-vvdpypv~ I destruction of all kinds of life: till, settling by degrees into his own path, he followed, as far as Op. et D. 77 9» weppaTos 8p£a- a6m, and Soph. CEd. Tyr. 1246, pvrjprjv iraKaiuiv (JTreppd- raiv exovfra. See Passow's Lex. s. v. Although the imagery is different, the word Treaovarjs recals not only the passage of the Timaeus just cpioted (4 1 e), but the prime calamity of the soul described in the Phsedrus. The above rendering is also given by C. F. Hermann. This additional reason for the ter- mination of the cycle gives fresh plausibility to the story. 1. rod tvclvtos 6 peu Kvfiepvi)- r?;y] tov ttovtos heads the sen- tence, displacing pev, because the Universe is the real sub- ject of all that follows. 2. 7TT]8a\[cQv ouikos] " The tiller of the helm." The o'lag was the part of the steering apparatus next the steersman's hand (Pollux, I. 89 : cf. iEsch. Ag. 649, o'Icikos tfiyo!)!'). 3. els tt)v avTov nepicoTrrju anio-rrj] " Retired to his own pinnacle of contemplation." Cf. Horn. II. g. 8, 23, 451 ; Od. K. 146. The conception of the Timseus is more ele- vated (42 e) : Ka\ 6 pev 8fj anavra ravra diaratjas ep.e\>€v ev to> eavrov Kara rpoirov fjdet. Though the idea of place is almost entirely absent here, it may be remembered that the central fire of the Pytha- goreans was called Aioy ei above, and the necessity pointed out in p. 269 d, e. Cf. Tim. 470, Sq