CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME OF THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND GIVEN IN 1891 BY HENRY WILLIAMS SAGE Cornell University Library B443.A5 P85 olin 3 1924 028 996 648 Cornell University Library The original of tiiis book is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924028996648 ARISTOTLE ON FALLACIES OE THE SOPHISTICI ELENCHI WITH A TRANSLATION AND NOTES BT EDWARD POSTE, M.A. PELLOW OF OBIEL COLLEOE, OXFORD ^wnbon MACMILLAN AND CO., __ • :^;, ./ 1866 9 />; f-^% '""///(laino^^' OXFORD: BT T. COUBE, M.A., E. PICEABD HALL, AND H. LATEAU, H.A. PRINTERS TO THE UNIVERSITY. PREFACE. Aristotle's explanation of the nature of Fallacies, if not satisfactory, seems to be as complete and iatel- ligible as any that has since been offered. As his doc- trines, indeed, are the source and substance of those of his successors, it appeared to the translator that the student of this theory would prefer to resort for instruction to the fountain-head, if it were made more easy of access. "Is not, however, the whole subject of Fallacies somewhat trumpery, and one that may be suffered, without much regret, to sink into oblivion 1" Possibly : but besides the doctrine of Fallacies, Aristotle offers either in this treatise, or in other pas- sages quoted in. the commentary, various glances over the world of science and opinion, various suggestions on problems which are still agitated, and a vivid pic- ture of the ancient system of dialectic, which it is hoped may be found both interesting and instructive. The text adopted is that of Bekker, except where emenda- tion was absolutely necessary to the sense. Attention is called in the Notes to all changes except mere changes of punctuation. TABLE OF CONTENTS. Chap. Pagb 1. Conception and existence of sophistry .... 2 2. Classification of reasoning 3. Five branches of sophistry ..... 4. First branch of sophistry. Fallacies dependent on diction 5. Fallacies not dependent on diction .... 6. All the fallacies may be deduced from the definition of con- futation ........ 7. All the fallacies arise from confusion, and must be solved by distinction ........ 8. Difiierence of paralogism and sophistic proof 9. Difierence of pseudographema and sophistic proof 4 6 6 10 18 22 24 28 10. Examination of a division of proofs into proofs addressed to the word and proofs addressed to the thought. Distinction of dialectic and didactic . . . .30 11. Sophistic proof is simulated pirastic, or simulated scientific, proof. Distinction of sophistic and eristic, sophistic and pseudo- graphic, scientific and pirastic, proof . . . .34 12. Second and third branches of sophistry. Reduction to falsehood and paradox . . . .40 13. Fourth branch of sophistry. Keduction to tautology or pleonasm . . . .42 14. Fifth branch of sophistry. Reduction to solecism ...... 44 vi TABLE OP CONTENTS. „ Pagb Chap. 15. Arrangement and tactics of the questioner 16. Utility of the study of sophistry . 19. Solution of the fallacies of homonymia and amphibolia . 20. Solution of the fallacies of composition and division 21. Solution of the fallacies of prosody . , . . 22. Solution of the fallacies of figura dictionis . 23. The solution of all fallacies dependent on diction contains an antithesis . 46 50 17. Kules of answering. The answerer must distinguish in all cases of ambiguity . 52 18. Three kinds of solution. The solution of inconclusive reasoning is distinction : the solution of conclusive reasoning is objection or counter- proof 58 60 62 64 6^. 70 24. Solution of the fallacies of accidens. Examination and rejec- tion of other solutions which refer the same examples to ignioratid elenchi or homonymia . . . . .72 25. Solution of the fallacies a dicto secundum quid ad dictum simpliciter *,....... 76 26. Solution of the fallacies of ignoratio elenchi . . . .80 27. Solution of the fallacies of petitio principii . . . .80 28. Solution of the fallacies of consequens . . . . .80 29. Solution of the fallacies of non causa pro causa . . .82 30. Solution of the fallacies of plures interrogationes . .82 31. Solution of reduction to tautology . . . .84 32. Solution of reduction to solecism . . . . .84 33. Degrees of ingenuity and difficulty of solution of fallacies . 88 34. Eecapitulatlon . 90 Notes • . . 97 TABLE OF CONTENTS. vii Pagb Appendix A. Petitio principii . . • 176 Appendix B. Non causa pro causa 186 Appendix C. Enstasis when a premiss is false . . . . . 192 Appendix D. Kotrai 'Apxai, or metkod-founding principles . . . 203 § I. The dialectic maxims or loci are premisses of u,ni- yersal, applicatioA 203 § 3. HofF far do the maxims of dialectic coincide with the axioms ,of science 1 The axioms are indispens- able to all reasoning, necessary^ and self-evident truths r the maxims have not these characters . 207 § 3. Peculiar principles of science and dialectic. Examina- tion of Mill's theory of definition . . .■ .209 § 4. The maxims are instrumental or auxiliary truths. When dialectic is purely logical, the loci or topical conceptions are the materials as well aff the instru- - ments' of proof ". . '. . . . 210 § g. Examination of Whately's distinction of logical and extra-logical fallacies 211 § 6. The maxims are metaphysical or ontological proposi- tions 212 § 7. The loci or maxims may all be grouped under the category of relation, or deduced from the definitions of the predicables or from the definition of definition 214 § 8. Dialectic is based on two definitions : the definition of proof supplies the loci of solution ; the definition of definition supplies the loci of invention . . .217 § 9. An earlier system attempted to obtain the loci of in- vention as well as the loci of solution from the definition of proof 219 viii TABLE OF CONTENTS. Page § lo. Dialectic like science is based on definitions, but on definitions of a different order from those which are the basis of science. Dialectic like art is based on definitions of the final cause, and its maxims are rather imperative than declaratory • • .221 § II. The definitions on which science is based are causal propositions ; therefore the branch of dialectic em- ployed to investigate the first principles of science should be founded on the definition of causation . 223 § 12. Comparison of dialectic with the modern method of scientific induction 227 § 13. Are definitions or the first principles of science sus- ceptible of demonstration 1 232 § 14. Specimens of dialectic maxims formulated by the schoolmen 236 Appendix E; Limited competence of pirastic 239 Appendix F. Quadrature of the circle by Hippocrates, Antipho, and Bryso 245 n EPi 50(DI5TIKnN EAErXQN. HEPI SOcDISTIKQN I. Hepl 8e tZu a-o^KTTiKcav k\iy)((ii>v Kol t&u (paiuo/iivo)!/ jikv fkiy)(a)u ovTcov Se irapaXoyia-fiwv aXX' ovk eXey^^eof Xeym/iev, dp^dfievoi Karii cpijcni' diro tS>v rrpdiToov. "On fikv ovv oi jikv eta-l a-v\Xoyi(r/j.oi, ol 8' ovk ovres SoKovm, (pavepov Sanep ykp Kal eirl tS>v dXXaiv tovto yiuerai Sid tlvos 6/j,0i6t7]Tos, Kal evl rmv Xoymv dxravroos ex^'- ^*' Y^P '''V^ ^l"*^ ol fiku e)(ova-iv eS ol Se ^aivovrai, aivetai Se Kard rfiv aia6rj(nv, otov rd jiev XiOapyipiva Kal rd KaTTiripiva dpyvpd, rd Se y^oXo^dipiva Xpvad. Tbv avTov Se Tp&irov Kal a-vXXoyi(Tfj.os Kal eXey)(oi 6 fiev ecTTiv, 6 S" ovk eari fiev, (fiaiperai Se Sid t^v dneipiav ol ydp drreipoi mcnrep df direyovTes iroppmOev Oecepovcnv. '0 fiev ydp avXXoyi(r/j,os eK rivS>v earl reQevTwv more Xeyeiv erepov ti k^ dvdyKrjs tS>v Keifievrnv Sid t&v Kei/ievcov eXey)(os Se avXXoyicTfibs fier di/ricjidarems rov TaTos 6 Sid tS>v ovofxaTOiv, Eirel ydp oAk ea-Tiv avrd Td irpdy/iara SiaXeyeaOai ipipovras^, aXXd ToTs ovofiaaiv dvrl twv Trpay/iaToov xpS/ieOa avfi^oXois, TO crvfi^aTvov enl Tmv ovofidrmv Kal knl t&v Trpay/iaTotv riyov- jieOa a-v/ifiaiveiv, KaQdnep eirl t5>v yjr'^^mv toTs Xoyi^oaevois. To S OVK ecTTiv ojioiov. Td jiev ydp ovojiaTa ireirepavTai Kal EAErXnN. B/e^ho^^ I. We propose to treat of Sophistical Confutations and those seeming confutations which are not really confutations but para- logisms^; and we thus begin, following the natural order of inquiry. The existence, over and above real proofs, of seeming but unreal proofs is evident. As in other departments resemblance generates semblance, so in reasoning. Bodily vigour is sometimes genuine, sometimes, as in the tribal choruses, simulated by the aid of dress : beauty is sometimes natural, sometimes counter- feited by cosmetics. So in lifeless objects : some bodies are genuine silver or gold, others are not silver or gold but seem such to the sense; as litharge® and tin seem to be silver, and yellow metal seems to be gold. So Proof and Con- futation are either real or only seem to be such to the inex- perienced. For the inexperienced resemble persons who view from a distance. Proof is a tissue of propositions so related that we of necessity assert some further proposition as their conse- quence^. Confutation is a proof whose conclusion is the contra- dictory of a given thesis. Some proofs and confutations have not really these characters, but seem to have them from various causes ; and one multitudinous and widespread division are those that owe their semblance to names. For, not being able to point to the things themselves that we reason about, we use names instead of the realities as their symbols, and then the consequences in the names appear to be consequences in the realities, as the consequences in the counters appear to the cal- culator to be consequences in the objects represented by the counters. But it is not so. For names, whether simple or B % 4 HE PI IOf>IITIKiiN TO tS,v Xoycop^ trXfjeos, to. 8e irpdyiiara rhv dpiO/iov dneipA ea-TLV. 'AvayKoiov o5v irXem rhv airrov Xoyov koX Tovvofia TO ty a-rj/iaiveiv. "Danep odv KUKeT ol fifj Seivol Tas fv^ovs \ ^epetv iiTTO tS)v iirio'Trj/j.oveov irapaKpovovTai, tov avTov Tporirov Kal eirl tS>v Xoycoy ol Tmv ovofidTcav ttjs Swafiecos aireipoi irapaXoyt^ovTai. Kal avTol SiaXeyo/ifj/oi Kal dXXeov aKovovTes . Aid [ikv ovv TavTijy ttjv aiTiav Kal Tds Xe)(_dr]croiJLevas earl Kai (TvXXoyi.a-/ios Kal eXeyxoy (paiv6fj,evos [ikv ovk cav Se. ' Eirel 8' ia-Ti Tieri [laXXov npo epyov to SoKeTv eivai. ao^oTs ^ TO etvai Kal fir} SoKeTi/ {^ittl yap rj ao^iaTiK^ (paivofievi] ao^ia ovaa S" oxj, Kal 6 o-o^iaTfjS ^rifiaTia-T^s dnb (f)aiyo/iivr)S ao(pias aXX OVK o^a-rjs), SrjXoy oti dvayKoiov tovtols Kal to tov aoavi^eiv SvvacrOai. Tavra 8' eaTi to fiev ev Tea SvvaaOai 8ovvai Xoyov, to 8' kv T^ Xa^elv^^. 'AvdyKt] ovv tovs ^ovXo/ievovs a-os KaXov/iev aoipLa-Tds, 8rjXov noaa 8' earlv ei8rj tZv Xoycov toiv aocftia-TiK&v, Kal e/c iTocrcov tov dpiOjiov rj 8{jvafiLS aijTr} avveaTrjKe, Kal irocra fiepr] Tvyydvei Trjs npay- ftaTeias ovTa, Kal nepl t&v aXXcov tS>v avvTeXovvTCov els Trjv Texfrjv Ta^TTjv ^Srj Xeyco/iev. II. "EcTTi 8^ Twv ev tS 8iaXeye(rdai Xoycov Terrapa yevrj, Si8aaKaXiKol Kal SiaXeKTiKol Kal veipacmKol Kal epia-TiKoi, AiSaaKaXtKol jxkv ot eK Toav oUemv dp)(6ov eKaarov fiaBrj- fiaTOS Kal oiiK eK Tcav tov dvoKpivo/ievov 8o^mv auXXoyi^o/ievoi {Set ydp mcTTeveiv tov fiavOdvovra), AiaXeKTiKol 8" 01 eK Tmv ev86^IITIKnN PeipaaTiKol S' oi e/c tS>v Sokovvtw t£ diroKpivo/ievcp Kal dvayKaiwv elSivai tS irpoo-TroLovixivc^ e)(eiy Tf]v emv ^aivojxkvcov kvSo^mv fif] ovtwv Se trvWoyiariKol i/j (paivo/ievoi avWoyiariKoi. riepl fikv ovv tS>v dnoSuKTiKSiv kv rofy ' AvaKvTiKois dprjrai, Trepl 8e rwy SiaKeKTiKcav Kal ireipaafiKcav kv TOis aWois' nepi 8e tS)v dycovKTTiKmv Kal kpiariKtov vvv Xiywfiev. III. ripwTov St) XrjTrrkov iroaoDv crToya^ovTai oi kv rois Xoyois dycavi^ojxevoi Kal Siavv/j.ia, dfKpi^oXia, avvdeais, SiaCpecris, npoa^Sta, a^rj/ia Xi^ems. Tovtov 8e tticttis ^ T€ Sia Trjs kirayoDyfjs Kal avXXoyia-fiSs, dv re Xri^Qfj tls dXXos, Kal oTi ToaavTa'^ms av rots aiiToTs ovofiaai Kal Xoyois firi Tairrh 8r]XoocraLiiev. Eicrl 8e irapk fiev t^v Sficovv/jiiav oi ToioiSe tcov Xoywv, olov OTi ixavOdvovaiv ol knia-Td/jtevof tA yap dnoaTOfiaTi^ofieva ^ p.av6dvovaiv ol ypap-fiaTiKoi. To yap fj.av6dveiv d/iwvv/jiov, to re iwievai xP^t^^'^O" W kniaTrj/jiri Kal to Xa/i^dveiv km- aTTj/iriv. < Kal irdXiv otl to. Aca/ca dyaBd- to. yap SkovTa dyaOd tA 8e KaKOL 8eovTa^, Aittov yctp Th 8eov, to t' dvayKaiov, h auu- EAErXQN. 7 Pirastic employ as premisses the opinions of the answerer on points that ought to be known by th%pretender to science, with the limitations elsewhere mentioned ^ : Eristic conclude from premisses which seem but are not probable, or only seem to conclude from probable premisses. Demonstrative reasonings having been discussed in the Analyt- ical, Dialectic and Pirastic elsewhere, contentious and Eristic reasonings remain to be investigated. III. Wb must first enumerate the objects aimed at when dis- putants are contentious and fight for victory. They are five : to confute the opponent, to drive him into false proposition, to drive him into paradox, to reduce him to solecism, and to reduce him to pleonasm, that is, to superfluous repetition : or the sem- blance of any one of these achievements without the reality. The end most desired is to confute the answerer, the next to shew that he holds a false opinion, the third to lead him into paradox, the fourth to land him in solecism, that is, to shew that his expression involves a violation of the laws of grammar, the fifth to force him to unmeaning repetition. IV. Seeming confutations fall under two divisions; those where the semblance depends on language, and those where it is independent of language. Language produces a false sem- blance of ratiocination from six causes ; the ambiguity of a term, the ambiguity of a proposition, the possibility of wrong disjunc- tion, the possibility of wrong conjunction, the possibility of wrong accentuation, and similarity of termination. This classi- fication may either be established by inspection of instances, or may be deduced (not to exclude other modes of deduction) from the fact that there are just so many ways by which a single term or proposition may have a plurality of meanings. ' Ambiguous terms may be found in the following instances : — Those that learn are those that already know, for it is those that know the use of the alphabet who learn (can write or spell) what is dictated. " Learn" is ambiguous, signifying either to appre- ciate, that is, to employ knowledge, or to acquire knowledge. Again : — ^Evil is good, for what is necessary is good, and evil is necessary. " Necessary" is ambiguous, meaning either the result 8 HEP I IOIITIKnN ^aivec TToWaKis Kai enl tZv KaKmv {ivTi yap KaKov Ti avay- KoiovS, Kal rdyaOit, 8e SiovToi ^afiev eivai. "En Tov aiirhv Ka6fja-6ai Kal iardvai, Kal KafiviLV Kal vyi- atveiv. "Otnrep yap dviaraTo, ea-rriKev, Kal ocrrrep iyid^ero, iyiaivei- dviaraTO S' 6 KaOrmevos Kal iyid^ero 6 Kdjivmv^. To yap TOV Kdjivovra otlovv ttoiuv ^ irda^eLv ovx e«' o''7/*a'»'e', dX\' ori /iev 8ti 6 vvv Ka/ivcav ^ Ka6ijfi€vos, ore S" os eKa/ive irpSrepov. HXrjv vyid^ero* jjikv Kal Kdfivmv Kal 6 Kd/iva>v iyiaivei S' oii Kafivayv dW' 6 Kdfivmv ov vvv oKKa irp&repov. fJapii, Se rriv d/i^t^oXiav oi ToioiSe, to ^o-uXeaBai Xa^eTv fif Toiis iroXe/iiovs. Kal dp' o Tis yivaxTKei, tovto yivdxTKei ; Kal yhp tov yivw- (TKOvTa Kal to yivaxTKOfievov kvBi^erai my yivataKovTa arjjifjvai TOVTO) Tffl X6ya>^. Kal dpa 8 opa tis, tovto 6pa ; Spa Se tov klovu, & Se irXeim, ^ to tA ypd/ifiara avrd eiriaTrifirjv e)(etv ^ T&v ypaiifidTcav dXXov. n fiev ovv d/M^i^oXia Kal S/icowfiia napd tovtovs roils Tp6- TTOvs ea-Tiv, napd Se Tr)v avvQemv Td ToidSe, oiov to SvvaaBai KaOrJuevov ^aSi(eiv Kal jirf ypdIITlKnN toy ex" Svvaniv rov fir) ypdipovra ypdiiv^ ^'""' * /'v avv6fj, oTi e^et Svvajiiv, ore ov ypd^ei, rov ypacpeiv. Kal [lavOdvei vvv ypd/ifiara, einep kiidvOavev & km(TTaTai^^. "En TO ev jiovov Swd/ievov ^epeiv noXXa SvvaaOai ^epeiv. riapa Se Tr)V Siaipeaiv, on ra nevT earl Svo Kal rpia, Kal wipiTrii Kal dpna. Kal rb /leT^ov i a eOrjKa SovXov opt eXevOepov ^^," Kal to " irevTriKovT dv8pS>v eKUTOP Xiire Sioi 'AxiXXevs." ' ,, Papa 8e Tfjv irpoaaiSiav ev jiev tois avev ypa(f>fjs SiaXeKTi- KoTs 01) paSiov iroirjcrai Xoyov, kv Se toTs yeypafi/jtevois Kal TTOirjiiaai /laXXov, otov Kal Tov"Ofn}pov euioi SiopOovvTai irpos Toiis eXeyypvTas eby droncos eiprjKOTa " to /lev o5 KaTairvOeTai ofi^pm." Avovai yap airrb rfj TrpotrcoSca, Xeyovres rb oil o^v- repov. Kal rb irepl rb kvmrviov rov ' Ayafie/ivovos, on ovk aiirbs 6 Zeds einev " SiSofiev Si ot eu^oy dpeaOai" dXXa ra kvvnvico evereXXero SiSSvat. T& jxev o5p roiavra Trapa rfjv irpoamSiav ecrriv. i 01 Se wapa rb a-yrjjia rijs Xe^eoos (TVii^aivovaiu, orav rb nrj ravrb ma-avrms epjxrjvevrirai., otov rb dppev 6fjXv ^ rb OrjXv dppev, fj rb fiera^i) Odrepov rovTcov, irj ndXiv rb iroibv irotrbv fj rb TToabv noiov, ^ rb iroiovv nd(T)(^ov ^ rb SiaKei/ievov noieiv, Kal rdXXa S , wy Si^prjrai nporepov. "Eari yap rb fir] rwv TToieTv ov d)S t5>v iroieiv ri rfj Xe^ei a-rj/iaiveiv. Otov rb vyiai- veiv ofioims rm airman rrjs Xe^ems Xiyerai rm re/Jiveiv ^ oiko- Sofieiv Kairoi rb jxev ttolov ri Kal SiaKeifievov irms SrjXoi, to Se TTOieTv ri. Tbv aiirbv Se rpimov Kal kwl rwv dXXcov. V. 01 fiev ovv Trapa Tfjv Xe^iv eAeyxot e/f tovtcov t5>v ronwv ela-LV rmv S' e^co rfjs Xe|ea)y napaXoyia-fimv etS-q karlv enrd, %v /lev Trapa rb a-Vfi^e^riKos, Sevrepov Se rb aTrXms V fifj ajrXZs dXXa irfj rj ttov ^ nore ^ Trpos n Xkyea-Qai, rpirov Se rb Trapa Tr)v rov kXiyxov dyvoiav, reraprov Se rb Trapa rb eTrS- EAErxnN. 11 " can^^ or with " walkj" and " not writing^' with "can" or with "write." • He knows the alphabet he had to learn. The lesser weight if you can hardly lift the greater weight you easily can lift. Of wrong disjunction the following are instances. Five is two and three : therefore five is even and odd ^^. The greater is equal to the less, for the greater is as much as the less— and something more. For the same words have different mean- ings when joined and disjoined ; as, I made thee a slave origi- nally free. Fifty warriors with Achilles fought a hundred of them hit the dust. Accentuation in unwritten discussion can hardly furnish a fallacious reasoning, but only in written controversy and criti- cism on the poets. Homer ^^, for instance, is emended against those who condemn the expression, "part thereof is rotten by the rain." Some meet the criticism by substituting an acute accent for the circumflex, making him say, " nought thereof is rotten by the rain." Again, in Agamemnon^s dream, instead of making Jove say, " I grant him triumph o'er his foes,'''' they make Jove command the dream to promise Agamemnon triumph o'er his foes ^*- These arguments, then, turn on accentuation. Similarity of termination produces fallacy when unlike things have names with a like inflexion, a male object a feminine name, a female object a masculine name, or a neuter a masculine or feminine ; or when a quantity has a name with the termination of a quality, or a quality a name with the termination of a quantity, or an agent a name with the termination of a patient, or a state a name with the termination of an action, and so on throughout the categories before enumerated ^^. For the name of what is not an action may terminate like a name of action, as " ailing" resembles in inflexion " cutting" and " build- ing,'" though it expresses a quality or state, while they express actions, and so in the other categories. V. Language, then, furnishes occasion for seeming confuta- tions in the modes we have mentioned. Independent of lan- guage, there are seven classes of paralogism arising from the equation of subject and accident ; from the confusion of an absolute statement with a statement limited in manner, place. 12 nEPI 20IITIKDN fievop, nifiTTTov Si to irapbi rh kv dpxv Xaii^dveiv, ?ktou Sk rh fifl airiov &s airiov rMvai, ^pSofiov Sk rh rh nXem tpcoT^iiara if TTOieTv. 01 fiev ovv napdi. to avfi^ePriKos^ vapaXoyia-fioi eicnv, orav ofioitos oTLovv d^LCoOrj TOO Trpdy/iaTi Kol ra crvfi^eprjKOTi tmap- Xeir. 'Enel yap Tm avTm iroWa avfi^e^riKev, ovk dvdyKr\ irdai Toty KaTtjyopovfievois, /cat Ka6' oS KaTrjyopeiTai, ravTh ■ndvTa imdpyf.iv. Olov el 6 KopiaKos eTepov dvOpmrov, avTm aiiTov sTepos' ecrTi yhp dvOpamos. *H el ZeoKpaTovs erepoi^ 6 Se ZcoKpdTTis dvOpcoTTOs, eTepov dvdpmrov ipaa-lv &fioXoyriKevat Sia TO arvfjLpe^rjKevai., ov e(pr]a'ev eTepov eivai,- tovtov eivat dvdpamov. 01 8e wapa to dnXms ToSe ^ nrj XeyeaBai Kal iifj Kvpim, oTav TO kv fiepei Xey6fievov d>s awXas elprjftevov Xri ttJ, OTi afia Td kvavTia iwdpyei. To Se toiovtov kw kviwv fiev TravTl Oecopjja-ai ^aSiov, olov el Xa^mv tov A lOiona elvai fieXava, Tois oSovTas epoiT el XevK6s' el ovv TavTrj XevKos, on /leXas Kal ov /leXas oi'oiTO SieiXeyOai, avXXoyia-TiK&s TeXeimaas t^v ep&TTja-iv. Bit kvuov Se XavOdvei iroXXaKis, k Xpova. Tbv avrov Se rp&jTov Kal ro \freva-acr6ai irepi tlvos. Evtoi Se aTToXtnovres ri ra>v Xex^evrmv ^aivovrai eXey^etj/, otov on ravro SiwXdaiov Kal ov SirrXdcnov ra ycip Svo rov jikv ivh 8iirXdS evSeyerai rb k^ dpyrjs alreiadai, (pai- vovrai S kXeyx^iv Sia rb firj Svvacrdai avvopav rb ravrbv Kal rb erepov. Se wapd rb errojievov eXey^oy Sia rb oieaOai dvriarpecfteiv rrjv dKoXovOrjatv. "Orav yccp rovSe ovros k^ avdyKr/s roSl 5, Kal rovSe Svros olovrai Kal Qdrepov eivai k^ dvdyKtjS. "OOev Kal at irepl rfjv So^av eK rfjs ala-OrjiTems dwdrai yivovrai. UoXXdKii yap rfjv )(o^W )"^^' inriXa^ov Siii rb eweaBai rb ^avObv XjOft'A'a tw fieXirr Kal krrel avfi^aivei rfjv yfjv vaavTOi yivecrOai Sid^po^ov, k&v' ^ Sid^po^os, inroXafiPdvoiJiev Saai. Tb S ovK dvayKaiov. Ev re roTs prjropiKoTs at Karit ro 6opa eaTai tis yiuearis kvavTiov 6 Sk BduaTOS (f)6opd Tis Kal kvavTLOv ^oarj, &, Kal Sti oi Soreov dnSKpia-iv, o?ov noTepov fj yfj OdXaTTa eariv fj 6 ovpavos^"; en evUov S' ?JTTov, Kal, m ivbs Svtos, ^ 6/ioXoyova-i r^ fi^ dnoKpi- vev Tb, /lev kiTTiv dyaOd T& S' oiK dyadd, ndvTa dyaOd ^ o't5/c dyaOd ; 6n6Tepov ykp dv ,pg Uti fjikv &s tXeyxov ^ ^evSos aiv6fievok EAErXDN. 17 it need not be that whatever has a beginning is generated, i. e. that whatever is not generated ha^no beginning : just as, because every man in a fever is hot, it does not follow that every man who is hot is in a fever. We mistake for a cause what is not a cause when an irre- levant proposition has been foisted into an argument as if it were one of the necessary premisses. This is practised in reduetio ad impossibile, for it is here that the proposition con- futed is one of the premisses. If, then, a foreign proposition be introduced among the premisses required to famish an im- possible consequence, it may be mistaken for the cause of that impossible consequence. Thus, to prove that Life and the Soul are not identical, a man assumes that the opposite of destruction is generation, and therefore the opposite of a par- ticular destruction is a particular generation. But Death is a particular destruction and its opposite is Life. Life there- fore is generation, and to live is to be generated. This is absurd : therefore Life and the Soul are not identical. There is no sequence here : for, independently of the identification of Life and the Soul, the impossible conclusion follows from the premisses that Life is the opposite of Death, that Death is destruction, and that the opposite of destruction is generation. Such an argument is not entirely inconclusive ; but it does not bear on the point in dispute, and of this the confuter himself is often unconscious''. The conversion of consequent and antecedent and false impu- tation of a residt to a cause gives rise to fallacies in the way we have explained : the union of several questions in one occasions a fallacy when the plurality of questions is not detected and no single answer is true. It is sometimes easy to see that there is more than one question, and that a single answer should not be given ; for instance. Is the ocean surrounded by the earth, and the earth by the sky? Sometimes it is not; and the answerer, supposing that the question is single, either confesses defeat by silence, or exposes himself to seeming confutation. For instance. Is A and B a man ? Yes. Then if you strike A and £ you strike not men but a man. Again ; if part is good and part evil, is the whole good or evil ? Whichever you answer you are open to a seeming confutation or conviction of c 18 HEP I IOIITIKDN Soieiev av noieiv rb yckp ^idvai t&v /Mfj dya6Zv ri eTuai dydr. 6hv ^ tS>v 6.ya6wv fi^ dyaShv ■^evSos. 'Ork 81 7rpoa-Xr,(j)6evrm rivcov K&v eXeyxos yivoiro dXTjOLvos, otov d ris Soir] dfioias tv Kal . TToXXcb Xiyea-dai XevKa Kol yv/iva. Kot TvfXd. El yap Tv<})Xbu TO fifj exov oi^iv ve^vKos 8' exe.iv, Kal TVXa ecrrai T& fi^ exovTo. o'^iv we^vKOTa 8' ex^iv. "Orav ovv to \ikv exi} TO 8k firi exUt ''^ oififfxa ea-Tai ■^ opmvTa t] rvt^iXd' oirep dStJi/aTov. I VI, *H Sfj oijToas SiaipiTiov tovs (paLvofiivovs avXXoyurjiLabi Kal kXkyxovs, ^ irdi/ras dvaKTeov els Trjp tov eXeyxov dyvoiav, dpxfjv TavTr]v TroLrjaafiii/ovs' eavepol yivovTai. Tbv avTbv yap opia-fibv SeT Kal tov eXeyxov yivea-6ai, nXfiv irpoa-KeTo-Qai t^v dvTi^aa-iv 6 yAp eXeyx"*, auXXoyicr/ibs dvTillTIKQN exei, avfi^i^riKi S' avTw axw'^ri eiuai v ^P^V^ ^PXVi on a-XVlJ-a fj apxr) ^ irp&rov tovto. Ov yap rj (rxnH'"' ov8 § irpmTov, dW rj rpiycovov, 77 diroSeL^LS. 'Ofioiws Se Kal ktrl t&v dWcov. "na-T ei 6 eXeyxos (rv\XoyLv dvema-Trjiiovav kXeyxovTw KaTh avjifie^riKos yii.p iroiovvTai Toiis avXXoyur/ji.ovs irpbs Toils eiSoTas. Ol 8' oil Swd/ievoi SiaipeTv ^ epa/rmfievoi 8iS6aa-tv fj ov Savres oiofTai 8e8eoKevai. Ol Se trapa to nrj Kal anXSis, otl ov tov aitov r) KaTafoffH Kal fi aTTOifyaa-is. Tov yap irrj XevKOV to vrj ov XevKov^'TOV S' anXms XevKov to arrXms ov XevKw dno^aais. El ovv 86vtos rrrj eivai XevKov my anX&s elprjfiivov Xafi^dpei, ov iroiu iXeyxov, ^atviTai 8\ 8ia ttiv dyvoiav tov ti kavepcaTaT0i 8e TrdvTceu ol trpoTepov Xex^^vTei iraph tov tov iXiyxov Siopio'fJ.ov 810 Kal irpoarjyopeuQrja'av ovTCOS' irapa yhp TOV X6yov ttjv iXXny^iv fj (pavTaa-ia ytveTai, Kal Siaipov- /leuois ovTCOi KOLvhu kirl Train tovtois OeTiov Trfv tov Xoyov eXXeii/ftj'^ J Ol fe iraph rh Xafi^dvdv to kv dpxij xal to dvaiTiov &i oLTiov TiOivai 8fjXoi Sth toC opLo-fiov. Ail yap to avfiirepacriili Tm TavT eTvai avfi^alveiv'', Svep ovk rjv kv toTs dvaiTioir Kal irdXiv fifj dpiO/iovfikvov tov k^ dpx^s, ovep ovk exovmv ol traph Trfv a'iTy\(nv tov kv dpxi). 01 Se irapoi, to eTrofievov fiepos fieri Tov aVfi^e^rjKOTOf to ySi.p knSiievov av/M^k^rjKe, SLa((>epei 8i tov (fV/Mpe^r]K6T0S, on to fiev (TV/Ml3€^r]K09 Utiv k' ivbs fiovov Xa^ecv, oTov ravrS etvai TO iav6bv Kal ftkXi Kal Tb XevKbv Kal kvkvov, rb Sh napiirS- ixevov del kv nXeioa-iv t& yb.p ivl TaiTw TavT&. Kal dXX^XoLS EAErXDN. 21 white is an accident of A, it does not follow that the fact is true of all that is white. If a triangle contains angles equal to two right angles, and figure, element, or principle is an accident of triangle, it does not follow that every figure, element, or principle contains angles equal to two right angles. For it is not figure, element, or principle, but triangle, that is essentially- connected with this property by the demonstratioti*. And so in other cases. Wherefore, if confutation is a species of proof, a reasoning that assumes the equivalence of subject and accident cannot be a confutation. It is by this assumption that artists and men of science are confuted by the unscientific. The latter assume the subject and accident to be interchange- able, and the men of science, knowing the essential subject of a law and unready at distinction, either ackaowledge the equivalence or imagine it has been acknowledged^. Fallacies from not distinguishing absolute and limited state- ments fail to deny the identical predicate that is affirmed in the thesis. The true negation of partially white is, not partially white; of totally white, not totally white. If, therefore, the admission that an object is partially white is used as an ad- mission that it is totally white, the confutation of the thesis that it is not totally white is only apparent, and depends on a false notion of confutation. Most readily referrible to misconception of confutation are the class which we mentioned as such before, and which hence received their special denomination, for their semblance arises from the want of a definition, though in making such a class we must admit that its difierentia is a character common to all the classes. Assuming the point in issue, and treating as a cause what is not a cause, are at pnee excluded by the definition of proof; for the conclusion must be a consequence of the premisses, which it is not when we mistake the cause ; and must not be assumed among the premisses, as it is in begging the question. Fallacies from the consequent are a species of those from the accident, and difier from other fallacies from accident because the latter identify the accident with a single subject, as, for instance, yellow with honey, and white with swan; while fallacies from a consequent connect the consequent with two 22 HEPI ZOTTia-LS. 'Eirel S' 6 ovXXoyKTfibs eK irpoTda-ecou, 6 8 eXeyxos ovXXoyKTjios, Kal 6 eXey\os ea-Tai eK irpoTaaemv. El oSv -fj npoTatTLS ev Ka& evos, ^avepbv oti Kal oStos ev Trj tov eXeyxov dyvoia,' (f>aiveTai ydp elvai Ttporacns 17 ovk ov(ra irpoTaa-is'. El jiev oSv SeScoKev drrSKpiaiv as irpbs fiMv epdiTTjaiv, eaivonevr] avTitpaais, owep rjv i'Siov Tov eXey^ov, ol S' dXXoi napd tov tov avXXoyicrfiov opov. VII. H S' dndTT) ytverai tS>v /j.ev napd ttjv dfimwuiav Kal TOV Xoyov Tffi fifj Svvaa-Oai SiaipeTv Tb noXXaxws Xeyo/xevov EAErXON. 23 antecedents. When two terms are identified with, a third, the axiom identifies them with one another ; ^nd it is this identifica- tion which gives rise to the fallacy from consequent. The axiom is not true if the identity in the premisses is only of subject and accident, else snow and swan, which have each an accidental identity with white, would be identical. Again : — the argu- ment of Melissus identifies what is generated with what has a beginning, and equality with having received the same magnitude. Because all that is generated has a beginning he assumes that all that has a beginning is generated, and, having identified what has a beginning^ with the finite in space, infers that all the finite in space is generated. So with equality. Because things which receive the same magnitude are equal, he assumes that things which are equal have received the same magnitude. That is to say, he converts two antecedents with the same consequent and thereby identifies the two antecedents. If, then, the fallacy from accident depends on a false idea of confutation, so does that from consequent. This topic must be handled again. Fallacies from the union of several questions in one may be shewn to be illegitimate by developing the definition of pro- position. Propositions conjoin a single subject and single predicate j_ for the definition of a class is the same as the definition of a single thing, that of man, for instance, as that of a single man, and so on. If, then, a single proposition conjoins a single subject and predicate, so does the class of proposition*. Now, as proof is composed of proposi^ons, and confutation is proof, confutation must be composed of proposi- tions. If, then, propositions ought to conjoin single subjects and predicates, the fallacies that fail in this shew a false con- ception of confutation, for they are composed of seeming but not genuine propositions. If an answer was given to a single question, there is a real confutation; if it only seemed to be given, a seeming confutation. All fallacies, then, are resolvable into a false conception of confatation; because some contain no genuine contradiction, which is peculiar to confutation, and others fail to satisfy the definition of proof. VII. In fallacies by ambiguous terms and propositions the deception arises from our inability to discriminate the differeht 24 HEP I ZOllTIXnN {ivLa yap oi,K eiSvopov SieXdy, ohv to ev Kul to ^u Kcti rh TairSv), tS>v Si irapb. a{,vBe iir^S^ oUv irapd to enofievov /lepos yap ti tw, xrv/i^e^Tj KOTOS to eirofievov. "Etc Kal eirl iroXXwv (^aiveTai Kai d^iovTai ovTcos, el ToSe dirb TovSe p-ij ^oopi^eTai^ firjS' dirb OaTepov )(copi^e(rOai OdTepov. TS>v Se irapd ttiv eXXei^jnv tov Xoyov Kal tS>v irapd Tb irfj Kal dirXms ev Tm irapd /iiKpbv rj diraTTj' ms ydp oiiSev irpocrcrrj/iawof to tI t/j nrj ^ nms fj Tb vvv KaOoXov avyywpovfiev. O/ioims Se Kal eirl tcov Tb ev dp^jj Xa/ij3av6vTcov Kal tS)v dvaiTicov, Kal o(roi ra irXe[a> epcoT^qfiaTa (BS ev voLovaiv ev diraai ydp fj diraTrj Sid Tb irapd jiiKpbv- ov ydp SiaKpi^ovfiev ovre ttjs irpoTaaecos o^Te tov avXXoyKTfiov Tbv opov Sid TTjv elprjfievriv a'lTiav. VIII. Enel S eyofiev irap' oaa yivovTai ot (f>aiv6fievoi a-vX- Xoyia-fioi, exofiev Kal nap' onoo-a oi (to^io-tikoI yevoivT dv EAErXDN. 25 significations of an equivocal word, for it is sometimes no easy- task to classify the meanings of an equivocal word ; for instance, of Unity, Being, Identity. In fallacies of conjunction and disjunction it arises from overlooking the difference produced by the conjunction or disjunction, because in other cases it is unimportant. So in fallacies of accentuation, because the tone or pitch of the voice is generally indifferent to the sense ^- In fallacies from similarity of termination the deception is due to the similarity, for it is hard to define when similar forms of expression indicate similar or dissimilar realities, and he who can do it must be far advanced in the pursuit of truth. We are seduced into error by our aptness to suppose that every pre- dicate is determinate and single and that something single and substantive is implied by determination and existence. This class, then, must be reckoned among the fallacies from language : firstly, because the deception is more common in reasoning with others than in reasoning by ourselves; for in reasoning with others we think the words, in reasoning by ourselves we think the realities^ : secondly, because in our solitary reasonings we are more likely to be deceived when we think by words : thirdly, because the deception arises from resemblance, and this lies in the words. In fallacies from accident the deception arises from inability to discriminate what is identical and different, one and plural, and what predicates and subjects have or have not all attributes in common. So in fallacies from consequent ; for a consequent is a species of accident, and in many cases it seems to be true and is treated as an axiom that, if A never exists without B, B never exists without A. In fallacies from not defining confutation and from identifying absolute and limited propositions the deception is due to the minuteness of the difference*. We suppose the qualification of manner, mode, relation, time, to be unimportant, and grant the unqualified proposition. And so in begging the question, and misassigning the cause, and uniting maijy propositions in one. In all these the minuteness of the difference creates the deception, for it makes us fail to entirely satisfy the definition of proposition and proofs. VIII. Possessing the sources of seeming proof we possess the sources of sophistic proof and confutation'. By sophistic con- 26 HEP I IOaLv6iievov eXeyypv euri, SrjXov OTi iraph TOcrama dv Kal tS>v ■^evSSiv etrjaav crvXXo- yia/iol trap' oa-a Kal 6 ^aivofievos eXey)(os. 8e ^aivofievos^ , irapa to, fiopia tov dXrjQivov eKaaTov yap eKXehrovTos (ftavevr\ dv eXeyxps, oTov 6 naph. to [it] avfifiaivov Sid tov Xoyov, 6 et$ TO dSiuvarov, Kal 6 ToiS 8vo epcoT'qaeis /iiav iroimv irapa ttjv irpa- TacTLv, Kal dvTl tov KaQ' airrb 6 irapa to o-v/^jSe/ST/KOS, Kai to tovtov fiopiov, 6 irapa to eirojievov eTi to p,r] kirl tov irpay[iar Tos dXX' eirl tov Xoyov crv/jifiaLveiv eiT dvTl tov kuOoXov Trjv dvTi^aa-iv Kal KaTd TavTo Kal irpbs TaiiTo Kal oKyavTcos irapa Te TO eiri ti ^ irap' eKaarov tovtcov en irapa Tb jjjj evapiS- fiov/ievov TOV ev dp-^y Xa/iPdveiv*. "Do-t eyoip-ev dv nap' otra yivovrai ol napaXoyia-p.oi^- napd nXeico p.ev yap ovk dv etev, napd Se Tcc elpij/xiva eaovTai ndvTes. EAErxnN. 27 futation, I mean not only proof or confutation which is seem- ing but unreal, hut that which thou^ real is seemingly but not really appropriate to the subject-matter. Such are those which fail to confute and prove ignorance within the peculiar sphere of the subjectj which is the function of Pirastic . Pirastic is a branch of Dialectic, and arrives at a false conclusion owing to the ignorance of the person examined . Sophistic confuta- tions, even when they prove the contradictory of a thesis, do not prove the ignorance of the respondent, for they may be brought to bear against the scientific. We know the sources of inappropriate proofs by the same method as those of unreal proofs. For the same causes that induce an audience to imagine the premisses admitted and the conclusion proved, will induce the respondent to imagine so, and wlU. furnish the premisses of a false proof; because, what a man has not been asked but thinks he has granted, he would grant if he were asked. Only sometimes we no sooner ask for the wanting premiss than we unmask its falsehood, as often occurs in verbal fallacies and in reductions to solecism. If, then, the paralogisms of contradiction are equal in number to the conditions of confutation that may be unfulfilled, the modes of sophistic confutation will be equally numerous 3. Paralogism arises from not fulfilling any of the elements into which true confutation may be decomposed. Any one that may be wanting will leave only a semblance of confutation. For instance, when the cause is misassigned in reduction to impossibility, there is no sequence : when two questions are put as one, there is no genuine proposition : when we replace a subject by its accident, we substitute for a term something else than its whole essence : when we convert a consequent we do the same, for this fallacy is a subdivision of the last : when the diction is fallacious, the sequence is not in the reality but in the words : when the conclusion is irrelevant, or limitations are neglected, the contradiction instead of being absolute and total is partial and restricted, or the terms are not taken in the same respect, relation, manner : and when we beg the question the premisses are not independent of the conclu- sion. We know, then, how many causes of sophistic proof there are; for there cannot be more than we have enumerated. 28 HEP I lO^IITIKDN "Ea-Ti S' 6 a-o(f>iaTi.Kos eXeyxoy ovx anX&s eXeyxos, aXU Trpos Tiva- Kat 6 avXXoyia-fios dxravTcos. ^^^ jJ-ev yap /itj Xd^H 6 re irapa to 6fia>vv/j.ov er (rrifiaiveiu, km 6 irapa t^v ofj.oioa-xvH'Oa-vvr]]/ to fiovov ToSi'^, Kal ol dXXoi dxravTcos, oir' eXeyxot ovTe avXXoyia-fiol ivovTai, ov6' AirXms oihe. irpbs tov epcoTWfiei/ov e&v Se Xd^ooai, nphs fiiv tov kpoDTSjiivov ecrovTai, dirXcos S' ovK ea-ovTar ov ydp %v ar]fiaTvov eiXrjtpaaiv, dXXii, (paivofievov, Kal irapd TovSe. IX. Hapd irocra 5' iXiyxovrai ol eXeyxofievoi, ov Sit tru- pdaOai Xafi^dveip dvev Trjs Twv ovToav eiriaT'q/ir]S diravTCov. TovTO S oiiSe/jLids ((ttI T^xyis' dweLpoi ydp fcrms at kirurTTJjuu, &a-Te SfjXov oTi Kal at aTToSei^eis. "EXeyxoi S' eia-l Kal aXjj- 6eTs' oa-a ydp e- fiiTpia dpxds Kal Td tovtoov a-v/iirepda-fiara, ol Se irapd rAy kv laTpiKfi, ol Se irapd Tcfcy tSiv dXXav kiria-Ttifiav. 'AXXd firjv Kal ol ■^evSeis eXeyxoi 6fioiv irapd ttjv SiaXeKTiK^v XrjiTTeov Toi>s toitovs' oStoi ydp KOLvol irpos diracrav Teyvriv Kal Svvafuv. Kal tov fiev KaO' eKdv ol evSo^oi cniXXoyia-fiol irepl otiovv, e)(piiev e^ mv 01 eXeyxcn' 6 ydp eXey^os ecmv dvTida-ecos crnXXoyiafios, &(TT Tj eis fj Svo a-vXXoyia-fiol dvTKpdaecos eXey^os kaTiv. "Expfiev apa nap' diroaa irdvTes elalv ol tolovtol, ei Se tovt' exofiev, Kal rds Xijcreis exofiev al ydp tovtcbv kva-Tdo-eis Xva-eis eicriv, , €XoiJ.ev Se Trap' oirocra yivovTai*. Kal tovs (paivofievovs^, (bai- vo/Mevovs Se ovx otwovv dXXd toTs ToioTaSe- dopiara ydp earcv. EAErXDN. 29 A sophistic confutation is not an absolute confutation or a confutation of the thesis, hut only wlative to the answerer; and so of sophistic proof. Unless it is granted that the am- biguous term has a single meaning, and that the similar termi- nation expresses a similar reality, and so on, there is no confu- tation or proof either absolute or relative to the answerer. If it is granted, there is relatiTC proof, but not absolute, for the meaning is not single, but only seemingly so, and none but this respondent would admit it to be so?. IX. All the sources of confutation could not be enumerated without universal knowledge, which belongs to no single art. Sciences and demonstrations are possibly infinite, and confuta- tions may be valid, for every demonstration confutes the con- tradictory thesis. The thesis, for instance, that the diagonal and side of the square are commensurate is confuted by the demonstration that they are incommensurate. To enumerate, then, all true confutations would require omniscience : for some confutations will be composed of principles and theorems of geometry, others of medicine, others of other sciences. More- over false confutations are infinite ; for every art has false proofs peculiar to it', geometry, geometrical proofs; physiology, phy- siological proofs. By peculiar I mean, moving exclusively in the sphere of its characteristic principles. Our present task, then, is to trace the sources not of all confutations but of all dialectical confutations ; for these are limited in number, though common to every art and faculty. Scientific confutations whether seeming or real, and if real, the reasons why they are real, must be investigated by the man of science-. The dialec- tician must investigate the common confutations, that belong exclusively to no particular sphere. If we know the sources of probable proofs that are common to every sphere, we know the sources of the common confutations. For confutation is con- tradictory proof, and one or two proofs with a contradictory conclusion are confutation. We have enumerated the sources of all these^, and, if so, we have enumerated the solutions; for the objections to these principles are the solutions, and we have explained the forms of objection. The dialectician must also enumerate the sources of apparent proofs, apparent, that is, not 30 HEP I I0 m eScoKev 8iavorj$eis. El Srj th irXdm (Tr]jiaivovTos Tov ovofiaTOS ocoito ev (rrjiiaiviiv Kal 6 ipooTwv Kal 6 epcoTWfJLevos, oiov t(7cos to hv rj to ev voXXa (rr]fiaii>ei, dWh Kal 6 aTTOKpivofievos Kal 6 kpcoT&v Zrjvoov ev oiojievos etvai rjpw- TT/a-e, Kal ecrTiv 6 Xoyos oti ev irdvra, oStos npbs Tovvojia earai ^ npbs Trjv Sidvoiav tov epayrcofj.ei'ov SieiXeyfiivos ; Ei 8e ye tis iroXXa oieTai crj/jiaiveiv^, SfjXov oti ov npbs Trjv 8td- voiav. flpcaTOv jiev yap nepl Toi)s tolovtovs ea-Tl Xoyovs Tb npbs Toijvofia Kal npbs Tr]v 8idvoiav oaoi nXeiw a-rj/iacvova-iv, eiTa nepl ovTivovv ecrTiv ov yap ev tw Xoyo) eo-xi Tb npbs Tr\v Sidvoiav elvai, dXX' ev t£ tov dnoKpivofievov ^X^"' "''"^ ""P"^ TO, 8e8o/j.eva. EiTa npbs To-Svojia ndvTas ev8e)(^eTai airrovs elvai. Tb yap npbs Toilvo/ia Tb jir} npbs t^iv 8idvoiav elvai eaTiv evTavOa. Ei ydp fifj ndvTes, eaovTai Tives eTepoi oxhe npbs Tovvofia ovT( npbs T^v Sidvoiav ol Si S, tovtcov elcri Tives oi napd Toilvofia. 'AToncos fiev ydp Kal eiprjTai to napd Tovvofia (pdvai ndvTas Tods napd Tf)v Xe^iv dXX' oSv flat Tives napaXoyia-fxol ov Tm Tbv dnoKpivo/ievov npbs tovtovs EAErXDN. 31 to any idiot, but to people of average intelligence : for it would be an endless work to inquire into tbe'sources of every idiotic belief. The dialecticiaUj then, has to discover what in the principles common to all spheres of thought are the sources of confutation whether real or apparent, that is, whether dialectic or seemingly dialectic, and whether pirastic or seemingly pirastic. X. Reasonings cannot be divided, as some propose, into reasonings addressed to the word and reasonings addressed to the thoughts It is a strange error to suppose that reasonings addressed to the word and reasonings addressed to the thought form distinct classes and are not the same reasonings under different circumstances. For not to address the thought is not to apply a name to the object which the respondent thought he was asked about when he made a concession, and is equivalent to addressing the word. To address the thought is to apply the name to the object which the respondent thought about when he granted the premiss. If, then, a name is ambiguous, but supposed to be unambiguous by the questioner as well as the answerer : as, for instance. Being and Unity are ambiguous, but were supposed to be unambiguous both by the answerer and by Zeno the questioner in the argument to prove the unity of all Being : was this argument addressed to the word, or was it not rather addressed to the thought ? If, on the contrary, the re- spondent thinks a term ambiguous when it is unambiguous the reasoning is clearly not addressed to his thought. For the possibility of being addressed to the word, or addressed to the thought, though it belongs primarily to fallacies of ambiguous term, belongs secondarily to aU reasonings ; because it does not depend on the nature of the reasoning but on the state of the respondent's mind. It follows that all reasonings, valid and invalid, may belong to the class addressed to the word ; for in this doctrine all those reasonings are addressed to the word which are not , addressed to the thought. Else there would be a third class, neither addressed to the word nor addressed to the thought ; but we are told that there is not, and that the division is exhaustive. But in truth reasonings addressed to the word are properly confined to fallacies of ambiguous term; and it is an abuse of language to extend the name even to all fallacies in diction. We hold. 32 nEPI IOIITIKnN exeiv TTCos, dXXoi. tZ toiovSI epSrrina top \6yov aiirbv exeiv, o TrXeico (rrj/iaivei. "OXrns re cltottov to irepi kXiyypv SiaXeyea-Bai, dXXii fir) nporepov Trepl ai.v6fievos eXey)(os. "Ecrri 8e 6 /lev tov criywvTa Xeytiv kv rrj dvTKpdareL, ovk kv tco avXXoyurfiw, 6 Se, a jir) iyoi Tis, Sovvai, kv d/i(j)oTv, 6 Se on rj Ofirjpov noirjiris a^rjua Stii TOV kvkXov kv TW avXXoyKTjim. "0 8' kv fJ.r]8eTepa> dXrjBrjf avXXoyi(T/J,6s. AXXa Sri, 86ev 6 Xoyoy ^X^e, irorepov 01 kv toTs fiad-q/iaai. Xoyoi irpos ttjv 8idvoidv eicnv, fj oij ; koi ei Tivi 8oKeL woXXa a-rj/xaivfiv to rpiymvov, Kol eScoKe /Mrj coy tovto to (T^rjlia, e^*^ ' o5 (TvveTrepdvaTo on Sijo 6p6ai, irorepov wpos rrfv 8idvoiav oSros SieiXeKTai rf/v kKeivov, fj oil; "En ei iroXXd /lev a-rj/iatvei Tovvo/j,a, 6 Se /j.fi voet firjS oierai, nms oSros ov irpbs Tr)v 8idvoiav 8ieiXeKTai ; *H irm Set kpmrdv TrXfjv Si86vai 8iaipes vai, el Srj ns Soirj fj.r]8a/juos 6 8k 8iaXe-)(6eir], dp' ov irpos Tfjv Sidvoiav SieiXeKTai ; Kairoi 6 Xoyoy 8oKec rmv irapd Toijvojia etvai. Ovk &pa ka-rl yivos n Xoycov to TTpoy rf/v Sidvoiav. 'AXX' 01 fiev irpos ToUvofid eicn- Kal roiovrot ov irdvres, ov^ on oi eXeyxoi, aXX' ov8' ol ^aivofievoi eXeyxoi. Elal ytip Kal fii) irapk T^v Xe^Lv ^aivo/ievoi eXeyxoi, oiov ol irapd rb av/JL^e^ ^rjKbs Kal erepoL. EAErXDN. 33 therij that there are certain paralogisms of equivocation which do not depend on the state of the respofdent's mind, but on the reasoning itself containing a term that is ambiguous. Again : we ought not to examine confutation before we have examined proof; for confutation is a species of proof. We ought a fortiori to examine proof before we examine false con- futation, which is the seeming proof of a contradictory. Its fault must be either in the proof, or in the contradiction, or in both, if the confutation is not genuine. In the argument that the outspoken may be silent, it lies in the contradiction, not in the proof. In the argument that a man can give away what he has not got, it lies in both. In the argument that the Homeric poems are a figure because they are a circle, it lies in the proof. Where there is no fault in either, the confutation is genuine*. But to resume * ; is it true that mathematical reasonings are always addressed to the thought ? If the respondent thought triangle ambiguous, and granted the premiss in a difierent acceptation from that in which it was afterwards proved to eon- tain angles equal to two right angles ; surely it cannot be said that the reasoning was addressed to his thought ? If, on the other hand^, a name is ambiguous, and the re- spondent thinks it unambiguous, is not the reasoning addressed to his thought ? If not, how ought the question to be framed in order that the reasoning may be addressed to the thought, if it is not enough to suggest to the answerer that he may draw a distinction ? If the opponent puts the question : Is it possible or impossible for the silent to be outspoken, or pos- sible in one sense, impossible in another ? and the respondent answers, It is not possible in any sense, whereupon the op- ponent proves it is : surely his reasoning is addressed to the thought of the respondent? This argument, however, -they class among those addressed to the word. We conclude that there is no distinct class of reasonings addressed to the thought as opposed to reasonings addressed to the word. There is a class of reasonings addressed to the word, but it does not include all confutations, nor even all fallacious confutations ^ • for some are independent of language, those, for instance, among others, that depend on the identification of subject and accident 9. 34 nEPI 20^1271 KQN El Si ris diwT Siaipuu, Sri \iySl TCI. 8' d>8r dX\a tovto y earl np&rov fiev drmov TO diiovv {eviore y&p ov SoksT to kpayrmfievov noWax&S ix^w, dSvyarov Se Siaipetv o /ifi oierai)- eireira to SiSdaKHv Ti dXXo ea-Tui ; 'Pavepov yap iroiriaei coy ex^' ■"■? /*'?'"' eo"f «/'/'«»'?> /"jr' elSoTi firjO' imoXan^dvovTi otl dWcos XeyeTai. Enfl Kal kv Tois p-f] SnrXoTs tl KcoXvei tovto noieTv^^ ; ^Apa laai at fioudSes rais Svdaiv kv rols TeTTapaiv ; Elo'l Se SvdSes at fi\v aSl evovcrai al Se mSi, Kal S.pa Tmv kvavTimv fiia kirivTrjiir) f) oxj ; "Ea-Ti S' kvavria to, fiev yvaxTTO, to. S" dyvwara. "flor eoiKev dyvoeiv 6 tovto d^imv otl eTepov to SiSdaKeiv tov 8ia- Xiyea-dai, Kal OTi Set top fiei/ SiSdaKovTa fir} kpcurav dX\' aiitov SfjXa noielv, tov S' kpandv. XI. "Eti to (pdvai ^ dwo(f)dvai d^iovv ov SeiKvvvTOS kariv, dXXa TreTpav Xaji^dvovTos. ' H yhp ireipaaTiKJ] kaTi StaXeKTiKri Tis Kal deoapei ov tov elSoTa dXXb, tov dyvoovvTa Kal irpoa- iroLovjievov. 'O jiev ovv KaTo, to vpdyfia Beapmv to. koivo, SiaXeKTiKos, 6 Se tovto (fyaivofieyms iroiwv (roaLv6/ievos avXXoyia/i6s nepl mv^ 17 SiaXeKTLKri neipaaTiKT] eort, kSLv dXj]6es TO av/nrepaa-fia rj- tov yiip Sid ri dwaTrfTiKos kern' Kal oa-oi fiT] ovTes Kara ttjv eKaarov /lidoSov vapaXoyiffjiol'^ SoKOva-iv eivai Kara Tfjv Texyrjv. Td ydp \lrevSoypa^rjfiaTa ovK kpia-TiKd {Kard ydp rd vno Tfjv Texvrfv 01 vapaXoyuTHoi)^ ovSe y ei ti kcrTi ^evSoypd^ri/j.a wepl dXriOes^, ohv to ' Ittito- KpaTOVs ^ 6 reTpaycovia/ibs 6 Sid twv /irjvia-Koav. '/IXX' m Bpva-mv kreTpaymviCe Thv k^kXov, ei Kal TeTpaycovi^erai kvkXos, dXX' oTi ov KaTd rb Trpdy/xa^ Sid tovto o-o^iaTiKot, EAErXnN. 35 If, in order that the reasoning: may be addressed to the thought, the questioner is required to drtw the distinction him- self, and say, for instance, that the silence of the outspoken may either mean this, or it may mean that ; the requirement cannot be enforced, for the questioner does not always suspect the ambiguity himself, and he cannot distinguish what he thinks unambiguous. Secondly, would not this be didactic reasoning ? For it discloses the truth to an answerer who has neither pre- viously considered nor discovered nor formed any belief about the ambiguity. And why not equally in the reasonings where no ambiguity is involved give him similar information? As thus : " Are the units in four equal to the twos ? Bear in mind that the twos may be taken either distributively or collec- tively." — " Is there one science of contraries ? Bear in mind that some contraries are knowable, others unknowable." This requirement, then, implies an ignorance of the difference be- tween didactic and dialectic reasoning, and of the principle that, while the teacher does not ask but informs, the dialectician asks ^1. XI. Again: — to challenge the respondent to affirm or deny is not the part of Didactic or the teacher, but the part of Pirastic or the examiner. For Pirastic is a species of Dialectic, and probes, not knowledge but, ignorance and false pretensions to knowledge. To do this by applying universal principles within a special sphere is dialectic : to do it in semblance only is sophistic. Accordingly, one kind of eristic or sophistic proof is proof which seems appropriate, though really inappropriate, to the problem which Dialectic undertakes under the form of Piras'tic, whether or not it has il true conclusion ; for even then it is iUusive as to the reason. A second are those proofs which are not confined to the special method of a science, though they pretend to be scientific. For the Pseudographema, or the mis- application of peculiar scientific principles, is not eristic, because confined to a special sphere, whether of art or science ; e. g. the reasoning of Hippocrates, or the squaring of the circle by lunules. But Bryso's method of squaring the circle, even if successful, is not mathematical, and is therefore not a pseudo- graphema but a sophism. Proof, then, that falsely pretends to D a 36 nEPI lOtPIITlKDN "Dare 6 re Trepl rwvSe ^awofieuos avWoyKT/ios epia-TLKos \6yos, Kal 6 Kark to wpdy/ia ^aiv6/j.evos crv\\oyLa-fi6s, kS.v ^ arvWo- yia-/j.6s, epLo-TiKos Xoyos- (f)aiv6fievos yap ea-ri Kara to irpdyjia, wcTT aTraTTiTiKos Kal dSiKos. "Dcnrep yap ij ei/ dymui dStKia eiSos ti e^^* f*' iv avTmv fikv elcriv ol (fiiXkpiSes Kal ao^iarai, aXX' ov tS>v avT&v evsKev. Kal Xoyos 6 aiiTos fiev earai ao^KTTiKos Kal kpia-TiKos, dXX' oii KaTb. tovtov, aXX' fj (lev viKTjs (f>aivo/j,evris, kpLaTiKos, rj Se v dpy(mv Kal avfirrepor anaTcav tS>v inrb ttjv Teyyrjv ■^evSoypas 'AvTKp&v eTeTpayoh vi^ev. *H et Tis /ifj ^aiij ^eXTiov elvai dirb Seiirvov nepi- iraTeTv Sia Tbv Z-qvmvos Xoyov, ovk laTpiKos- Koivbs yap. Ei /lev ovv wdvTri dfioicos eixev 6 kpiariKbs vpbs Tbv Sior EAErxnN. 37 be pirastic, or relevant to the problem^ is eristic, and so is proof that falsely pretends to be scientific, even though it be conclusive ; for, pretending to proceed from scientific know- ledge, it is deceptive and illegitimate. Trials of force or skill are sometimes the occasions of unfair play and illegitimate fighting : and Eristic is illegitimate fight- ing in disputation. The competitor who is bent on victory at all hazards sticks at no artifice; no more does the eristic reasoner. If victory is his final motive, he is called contentious and eristic ; if professional reputation and lucre, sophistic. For Sophistic is, as I said before, a money- making art, that trades on the semblance of philosophy, and therefore aims at producing the semblance of demonstration. The contentious disputant and the sophist use the same kind of arguments, but not from the same motive; and the same kind of argument is sophistic and eristic in difierent aspects. If semblance of victory is the motive, it is eristic j if the semblance of wisdom, sophistic; for sophistry is the semblance of philosophy without the reality. The eristic reasoner to a certain extent bears the same rela- tion to the dialectician as the false geometer bears to the true geometer : for he draws his principles from the same source as the dialectician, and the false geometer from the same source as the true geometer. The false geometer is not eristic, be- cause his premisses are exclusively drawn from the principles and theorems of a science, while Eristic constructs syllogisms from the principles of Dialectic. They may, however, handle the same problem. The mode of squaring the circle by lunules, for instance, is not eristic, but Bryso's is eristic. The one cannot be applied beyond the sphere of geometry, because it is based on geometrical principles ; the other can be employed against all disputants who do not know what is possible or impossible in their respective spheres, for it applies to subjects different in kind. The same may be said of Antipho's method of squaring the circle. If, again, a person controverted the expediency of walking after dinner by Zeno^s proof of the im- possibility of motion, such an argument would not be medical, because it has a catholic apphcation. If the relation of Eristic and Dialectic was exactly similar 38 nEPI IOIITIKnN XeKTLKw Tffl ^evSoypd^m npos tov yeoo/ierpvv, ovk av rjv nepl (Keivcov epia-TiKos. Nvv 8' ovK eariv 6 SiaXeKTiKos irepl yevos Ti a>pLa-/J.evov, oiiSe SeiKTiKos ovSevos, ovSe toiovtos o?os 6 /ca- 66\ov^. O^re yap eariv atravra kv evi Tivi yevei, oiSre d f.17], oiov Ti vTTo Tus avTois dpx&s uvai TO. ovTa. "iidT ovSifiia re\yrj tS>v SeLKvvovcraii' nvb. (pva-iv epayrrjriKrj^'-' eariv oii yhp e^eariv onoTtpovovv rS>v fiopicov Sovvar ovWoyKr/jibs yap ov yiverai e^ d/KpoTu. 'H _Se SiaXeKTiK^ epayrriTiKrj eariv. El 3' eSeiKvvev, el Kal fir] irdvra, dWa rd ye npcora Kal t^j oUeias dp^as ovk Slv ripwra. Mfj SiSovros yh.p ovk dv en ei)(ev k^ &v eri SiaKe^eTai irpos Tfjv evaraaiv. ' H 5" avT^ Kal TreipaaTiKTJ. OvSe yap r) neLpaariKT} Toiavrri earrlv oia i] yemfierpia, aXX' fju av e)^OL Kal fifi elSois ns, "E^ecTTi yap weTpav Xa^eTv Kal tov fifj elSoTa to irpayfia tov fii) elSoTos, ehrep Kal ScSaxriv ovk e^ &v oTSev ovS' eK twv ' iSicov, d\\ eK t&v eno/ievrnv, os ewayyeXXofievovi. ' TavTa S' eaTl rA Koivd- Taura yap ovSev fJTTov iiraaiv avroi, Kav SoKma-i Xiav e^a> Xeyeiv. 'EXeyxovaiv odv anavTer dTe^vw! yap /leTexova-i tovtov o5 evTexvm i) SiaXeKTiKr) ecTTi, Kal 6 Texvv avXXoyia-TiKfj ireipaaTiKos SiaXeKTiKos. 'Eirel 5' earl iroXXd fxh TavTa Kal KaTd ndvrmv, ov ToiavTa S" mtrTe (f)V(TCV^* Tiva eTvai Kal yevos, dXX' oiov al dwo^da-eis, Th S' oil roiavra dXXii, iSia, iaTiv eK Totrrav irepl andvTwv neipav Xa/i^dveiv,- EAErXDN. 39 to that of the false and the true geometerj there could not be eristic arguments on geometrical problems. But the fact is that Dialectic has no definite spherCj and demonstrates nothing categorically, and investigates no essential theorems. For there is no genus that embraces all Being, and, if there were, there could be no common principles of all Being '. No science that demonstrates categorically any positive theorem can interrogate or oflFer to accept either alternative, for either alternative would not furnish a proof. Dialectic interrogates. If it had to de- monstrate any theorems, it could not trust, at least for the elements and special principles of the proof, to interrogation : for . if they were denied by the respondent, it could have no weapons to oppose to his objection. Pirastic is a Dialectic : for it is not a speciality like geometry, but a faculty that may be possessed by the unscientific. He who does not know may examine the pretensions of another who does not know : for the theses and premisses granted by the re- spondent are not scientific truths nor theorems from which the primary laws may be obtained by analysis ^^, but consequences or derivative facts, which are such that, while to know them does not prove knowledge of the primary laws, not to know them proves ignorance. Pirastic, then, is not knowledge of any definite sphere, and therefore is conversant with every sphere : for all sciences have certain common elements or catholic principles. Accordingly, even the unscientific employ Dialectic and Pirastic, for all persons to a certain extent assume to test pretensions to knowledge. Pirastic and Dialectic are the application of those catholic principles, and these the unscientific possess as well as the scientific, though their expression of them may be very defective in precision. Accordingly, all practise confuta- tion. Unmethodically they perform the work which Dialectic performs methodically, and the examination of false pretensions by methodical reasoning is Dialectic. Such principles are nume- rous, and applicable to every province, but have no positive nature, and form no determinate genus, resembling, in this respect, negations : others, on the contrary, are limited to special spheres. The former enable us to examine pretensions in any province, and compose what is a kind of art, though 40 HEP I 10IITIKnN Kal ilvai T^yvrjv rivd, Kal jirj ToiavTrjv elvai oiai at S(iKv6- ovcrai. Aioirep 6 epia-TiKos ovk ea-riv oiircos eycov iravTrj ay 6 -JrevSoypadiOS' ov yap ecrrai irapaXoyiariKos £^ wpia/ievm Tivbs yifovs dp-)(S)V, dWii irf.pl irav yeuos icrrai 6 epiariKos. TpoTTOi p-kf ovv elalv oStol tS)v cro(j)icrTLK&v kXkyywv on S' ia-Ti Tov SiaXeKTiKov to deeopfjcrai nepl tovtcdv Kal Svvaadai ravra iroieTv, ov )(^a\eTrbv ISeiv rj yhp nepl rdis TrpordcrHS fiedoSos anaaav e)(et ravTrjv Tr}v 6ea>piav. XII. Kal Trepl /lep tS>v e\iy)(a)v eiprjrai tSiv ^aivofiivcov wepl Se TOV '^evSo/j.evov ti SeT^ai Kal tov \6yov els dSo^ov dyayeiv (tovto yap rji/ SevTepov Trjs crotpuTTiKrjs Trpoaipia-ems) irpmov p.\v ovv eK TOV TTVvOdvicrdai irms Kal 8id Trjs epcoTrja-tms (tvji- ^aivei fidXia-Ta. To ykp irpos (MrfSlv opicravTa Kiip.evov epcordv 6r]pevTiK6v kcrTi tovtcov eiK^ yap XiyovTes dpapTdvovai /iSX- Xov sIk^ Se XiyovcTLv, oTav p.T]Sev eyoaai TrpoKetpevov. To re ipoDT&v iroXXd, Koiv dtpia-fievov fj irpos h SiaXeyerai, Kal to rh SoKovvTa Xeyeiv d^iovv Troiei tiv eimoptav tov els dSo^ov dyayeiv ^ ■^evSos' edv re epcoTcofievos TJ ^ diro^^ tovtodv n, dyeiv TTpos St etnyeiprjp.aTOS einropei. AvvaTov Se vvv ?jttov KaKovpyeTv Sid tovtcov ^ irpoTepov diraiTovvTai yap ti tovto Trpbs TO ev dpyrj. ZT0i)(^eLov Se tov TV)(^eTv fj '^evSovs Tivos rj dSo^ov TO firjSefiiav evdvs epeoTav deariv, dXXd (pda-Keiv epcoTav jJLaOeiv ^ovXofievov y(a>pav yap eTTi^eip'^fiaTos fj a-Keyjns TToieT. npos Se to -^evSo/ievov SeT^ai iSios toitos 6 orocpicrTiKos, TO dyeiv Trpbs Toiavra vpbs St. evwopei Xoycav. "EcTTai Se Kal kuXms Kal n^i KoXm tovto iroteiv, KaOdirep eXe-^^Or} vpoTepov. fldXiv Trpbs Tb napdSo^a Xeyeiv aKorreiv eK Tivos yevovs 6 SiaXey6/ievos, eiT eirepcoTav 8 toTs ttoXXoTs oStoi Xeyovai TrapdSo^ov eaTi yap eKdaTois ti toiovtov. ZTOiveTov Se tov- T(ov Tb Tas eKda-Tcev elXtj^evai dea-eis ev Tais wpoTdaemv^. Ava-is Se Kal toiutcov ■q wpoa-rJKOva-a (jiipeTai Tb efKpavi^etv Sti oil Sid Tbv Xoyov avf^lSaivei Tb dSo^ov del Se tovto Kal fiovXeTai 6 dymvi^o/xevos. "Eti S' eK tS)v ^ovXijcrecov Kal t5>v ^avepmv So^mv. Oi EAErXDN. 41 very unlike the sciences that demonstrate. Eristic reasoning, then, is not exactly similar to false geometry; for it does not' consist of paralogisms drawn from a limited sphere of principles^ but of proofs drawn from catholic principles applicable to every sphere ^°. Such are the modes of sophistic confutation. The investiga- tion of them and power to apply them belong to Dialectic : for all these matters belong to the method of Proposition. XII. Unreal confutation has been examined. False or paradoxical statement, the second aim of the Sophist, is obtained by the mode of questioning and interrogating ; by questioning, for instance, without previous definition of the problem. For random answers are more likely to be wrong, and answers are made at random when there is no point in issue. If there is a definite point in issue, it is useful to multiply questions and request the respondent to give his genuine opinion, and if he states candidly his beliefs and disbeliefs, to lead him on to controversial ground^. This fraud is less practicable now, for the answerer will demand. What has this to do with the question? Another rule for obtaining a false or paradoxical statement is not to put a proposition with confidence, but to pretend to ask from a desire to learn : for consultation gives an opening to attack. Another artifice for proving error is to lead the discussion on to debatable ground. This may be done fairly in some cases, as we have already mentioned. Again : — paradox may be elicited by considering to what school the respondent belongs, and proposing some tenet of the school that the world pronounces to be a paradox ; for there are such tenets in every school. For this purpose it is useful to have made a collection of paradoxes. The proper solution is to shew that the paradox has no connexion with the thesis, as the dis- putant pretends. Another source of paradox is the opposition of secret wishes 42 HEPI I04>IITIKnN yitp raxna ^oiXovrai re koL ^acriV, aXKh. Xiyovai jih rovs ^vayrfjioveaTdrovi tS>v Xoyoov, PoUXovTat 8e rh ^aivo/iem \va-iTe\eTv, oiov re$pdvai Ka\m /idWov rj {fjp fiSims (f>a(rl Seiv Kal Trivsa-dai SiKaioas /idWov fj TrXovreTv aityyjiSas, ^ovXovtcu Se TavavTia. Tbv fikv ovv Xiyovra Kardi ras PovXrja-eii els ris ^avepd,s So^as aKriov, rov Se Karb, ravrai eU t^ls airoKiKpvfh^' /levas' d/i<}>0Tepvois rj tw iraTpl Set neiOecrOai, Kal rd avfi^epovTa wpaTTeiv ^ rd SiKaia, Kal dSiKeis oi iroXXoi, eirl rd rois kv Xoyw. aa-l ydp ol fiev e^ dvdyKrjs tov eiSaifiova S'lKaiov eivar toTs Se ttoXXoTs dSo^ov to ^aa-iXea fi^ evSaLjiovetv. "EcTTi Se Tb eis Td ovtods dSo^a avvdyeiv ro aiyrb raJ eh t^v KUTd (pvaiv Kai KaTd vop-ov imevavTicaaiv dyeiv 6 uev yap vo/jios So^a T&v noXXmv, ol Se ao^ol KaTd 6(riv Kal Kar dXriQeiav Xeyovaiv. XII r. Kal Td /lev TrapdSo^a Ik rovrmv Sei {riTeiv tS>v TmrmV irepl Se rov noifjaai dSoXeaxeiv, 8 fi'ev Xeyofiev Tb dSoXeIITIKDN TTouiv ei fiTjSy Siav Xoyoov iv re rois npos n, oaa firj fiopop t& yevq dXXa Kal aiiTa npos tl Xeyerai, Kal Trpbs TO avTo Kal tv diroSiSorai. Oiov f] re ope^is tivos ope^i^ Kal f) kmOvfita tivos emdv/iia, Kal to SivXdaiov tlvos SinXdv 17 ovaia^ ovk ovtoov irpos n oXcos, S)v elalp e^eis ^ ndQrj f] tl tolovtov, kv rm Xoyco airrm TTpocrSriXovTai, KaTriyopovjikvoiv knl tovtois. Oiop to irepirrov dpiOfihs jiktrov e)((ov eari 8' dpi6fios rrepiTTos' ecrriv apa dpc6/ibs fiiaov e)(a>u dpi6fx,6s. Kal ei to aijiov KoiXoTrjs ^ivos kcTTLv, ecTTi 8e pis (njirj, ecrriu dpa pis pis KOiXrj. 4>aivovTai Se TTOieTv ov iroiovvTes kviore Sih, to fir] npooTrvvOdveaOai a arjuaiveL ti Ka& avrb Xe^Oev Tb SiwXdcriov fj ovSev, Kal ei n arjfiaivei, norepov to airrb ^ erepov, dXXh Tb crvfnrepaap,a XkyiLv ev6vs. 'AXX&, (j>aiveTai 8ia to to 6vojj.a ravrb etvai Tairro Kal arijiaiveiv. XIV. ZoXoLKUTjibs S" oiov fiev ka-riv eiprjTai irpoTepov. "Ean 8e TOVTO Kal TroieTv Kal jir] iroiovvTa (ftaiveadai Kal noiovvra iifi 8oKeiv, KaOdirep 6 flpayrayopas eXeyev, el 6 /jirjvis Kal 6 nrjXrj^ dppev kcTTiv d fiev ydp Xiymv ovXofievrjv (roXoiKi^ei jiev Kar eKeivov, ov ^aiveTai Se roTs dXXois, 6 Se oiXo/ievov (paiveTai p-ev dXX oil aoXoiKi^ei, AfjXov ovv otl koLv re^vrj tls tovto SvvaiTo TToieTv Sib ttoXXoI tS>v Xoymv ov avXXoyi^o/ievoi aoXoi- Kia-fibv (j>aivovTai avXXoyi^eaQai, KaOdirep kv toTs eXey)(ois. Eia-L Se irdvTes a-)(€Sbv ol ^aivo/ievoi aoXoiKiajiol irapa to ToSe, Kal orav ■^ Trrma-is^ firJTe dppev fi^re QrjXv Sj]XoT dXXa Tb fieTa^v. To /lev oStos dppev arffiaivei, to S' a&TT] OfjXv to Se tovto 6iXei fiev to /leraiv a-qnatveiv, iroXXdKis Se a-rjuaivH EAErXQN. 45 Let us assume that an equivalent expression may always be substituted for a term. If, then, the double is double of its half, and double is equivalent to double of its half, it follows by substitution, that the double is double of its half of its half, and, by further substitution, double of its half of its half of its half. Again, if appetite is appetite of pleasure and appetite is equivalent to desire of pleasure, appetite is desire of pleasure of pleasure. All these reasonings turn on relatives where both the genus and the species^ is a relative and has the same correlative : as desire and appetite are both relatives and have the same correlative, pleasure; and double and double of half are both relatives and have the same correlative, half. Or they turn on terms which are not properly relatives but whose definition expresses the subject of which they are states, affections, or other attributes. E. g. if odd is equivalent to number that has a middle unit, odd number is number number that has a middle unit ; and if aquiline is equivalent to hooked nose, an aquiline nose is a hooked nose nose. The reduction to pleonasm is not genuine when the premiss has not been granted that the relative has a meaning by itself and means the same when joined with the correlative^. The conclusion is drawn without this premiss : because the term being the same, it is assumed to have the same meaning in both cases. XIV. Solecism we explained before to be barbarism in language. It may be either real and apparent, or real and unapparent, or apparent and unreal, as Protagoras said. If wrath and helmet are masculine nouns, he who gives them a feminine concord commits a real but unapparent solecism; he who gives them a masculine concord commits an apparent but unreal solecism. This appearance can be methodically pro- duced ; and there are methods which apparently but not really convict of solecism, as there are methods of apparent but not real confutation. Almost all seeming solecisms depend on the neuter pronoun That, and the masculine or feminine names of objects that are not really male or female but neuter. He denotes a male. She a female. That properly denotes a neuter, but often really 46 HEP I IO0IITIKDN KOLKiivmv eKdrepov, oTou rl tovto ; KaWiorrr), iiiXov, KopurKO?, Tov iikv ovv dppevos Kai tov di^Xeos Siafepovaiv at nTwrm atraaai, tov Se /leraid at fiev al S' otf. AodevTOS S^ woXXaKLS TOVTO tTvWoyi(ovTai coy eiprj/iepov tovtov ofiotass 81 Kal dWr/v iTTma-iv dvT dX\r]S. '0 Se irapaKoyurnos yiveTai Sia to koivov etvai to tovto wXeioucav irTaxreeov to y&p tovto a'TfjiaivH h\ fikv oStos oTe Se tovtov. AeT S' evaXXdt^ arjfiaiveiv, p-eTci fiev tov eoTi TO oStos, fieTk Se tov eivai to tovtov, olov eari Kopt- (TKos, eivai KopiaKov. Kal errl t&v BrjXeoov ovofiaTcav dxrairwi^ Kal eiri tcov Xeyojievoav jAv v, ey(pvTavepov oSv on TOV v dycaviariKcav Xoymv Kal jieprf Tmv eiScav Kal Tp&iroi ol eiptj/ievoi. Aiatpepei 5* ov jiLKpov, eav Ta)(6r] TTO)? TO. irepl ttjv epmTrjaiv irpbs to Xav6dveiv, &avepbv eavrbv iroieTv ^ovX6/ievov dSiKew Kal Tb irapdirap dvaitrxvvTeiv. 'Eti Tb evaXXd^ to, epayrrj/iaTa TiOevai, edv Tt irpbs Tavrb-irXeiovs tis exD Xoyovs, edv re Kal oti ovtcos koI EAErxnN. 47 denotes a male or female. What is that ? That is Calliope : That is wood : That is Coriscus. The Cases of masculine and feminine nouns are always distinguishable j not so those of neuters. When That in the premiss represents He, we may argue as if it represented Him, and vice versa : and a fallacy will arise from this variety of representation. It alternately represents He or Him, according as it accompanies the infini- tive or indicative mood. So it either represents She or Her, and either the nominative or the accusative of neuter objects which have masculine or feminine nam.es. For neuter objects ^ught to have names ending in On, and the other terminations ought to denote the male or female sex, but are sometimes applied to neuters, as askos (wine-skin) has a masculine termination, kline (bed) a feminine. The names of these objects, just like proper masculines and feminines, change their inflexion accord- ing as they accompany the indicative or infinitive, that is, dis- tinguish the nominative and accusative cases. Reduction to solecism resembles the fallacies that arise from similarity of termination or Figura dictionis. There we are cheated in the category of the things, here in the cases of their names ^, for man and white are both names and things. Solecism, then, is proved under the circumstances we have indicated. We have now enumerated the branches of sophistic disputa- tion and their subdivisions and methods. For concealment of his purpose. Arrangement is important to the sophist as to the dialectician. We therefore proceed to treat of Arrangement*. XV. Length is favourable to concealment; for it is hard to see the mutual relations of a long series of propositions. Length is to be produced by the methods abeady mentioned^. Quick- ness facilitates concealment, for the answerer has not time to foresee consequences. So, too, anger and the heat of dispute ; for any mental discomposure puts us off our guard. Anger may be produced by efirontery and open attempts to cheat. So, too, alternately proposing the premisses either of different arguments for the same conclusion, or of arguments to prove opposite con- clusions, for the answerer has to guard against different and 48 HEP I IOIITIKnN OTL ovx oiirms- a/ia ycLp avu^aivei ^ irpbs TrXew) ^ npos rdvav'- ria iroieTa$ai t^v ^vXaKriv. "OXm Se ndvTa rh. npos rfiv Kpiijyjnv \e-)(6kvTa vporepov xp'qcrifia /cat npos Toi)s dymvKTn- Koi)s Xoyovs' ^ yap Kp^yjns earl rod XaQeiv xoipiv, to Sk Xa6uv rfjs dndTrjs. flpos Se Tovs dvavevovras &tt' av ohfOooaiv etvai npos top Xoyov, e^ dnoaivovTai Si& Trjv T^s knayayyfjs /ivetav, d>s ovk av rjpayrrfukva /idrriv. Ev ots Te fir) ovofiaTi (rr/fiaipeTai to KaOoXov, dXXa Trj d/iotorijn XP'tJo'Tiov npos TO avfitpepov XavOdvei yap tj d/ioiorris noX- XaKis. flpos re to Xa^eTv Tfjv npoTaviv TOvvavTiov napapdX- XovTa XP^ TTwddfea-Oar oiov, el Seoi XaPeTv oti Set ndvra Tcp naTpl n€i6ev kvavTicov, Kal jiu^i^ Kal fieydXa ^aiveTai Kal X^^P"'' 'f*' jSeXTto) Tory dvOpwnois. Z' eavTOV Xeyi. fieva, ^ npos ot>s o/xoXoye? KaXSis Xeyeiv fj irpdrTeiv, in npos Toiis SoKovvras toiovtovs, ■n irpos tovs o/iolovs, ^ irpos Toiis nXei- (TTovs, rj vpbs irdvTai. "Do'irep re Kal diroKpivojievoL ttoXXAkk, orav eXeyxcovrai, iroiova-L Sittov, &v fieXXrj avfi^aii/eiv eXey^S^, &ecr6ai, Kal epcoTavras Xprja-Teov TTore rovTcp Trpbs Toiis kvuTTCt- fiivovs, dv mSl fikv av/i^aii/tj caSl Se /irj, on ovtcos eiXrj^fv, otov Q KXeocpav iroieT kv rm MavSpo^ovXcp. Ae? Se Kal dipiarank- vovs Tov Xoyov rb. Xoiird t&v e7ri)(eipr]fidTcov erriTe/jLveiv^j Kal Tov diroKptvofievov, dv irpoaicrOdvqTaL, irpoevicrTaa-OaL Kal trpo- ayopeveiv. EtriyeLprjTeov S' kviore Kal irpos dXXa tov dpi\- fievov, kKeivo kKXa^ovras, kdv fifj irpos to Kei/ievov e^?? "S eTn)(eLpeiV oirep 6 AvKoc^pcov kiroirjcye irpo^Xrjdii/Tos Xvpav kyKco/jLid^eLv. Flpos Se Toi)s drraiTovuTas irpos n emxeipeP",: kireiSrj SoKeT Seiy diroSiSovai Trjv ainav, Xey6evTs eirl Tb iroXij yivojievoi irapii, t^v Xi^iv d/ieivov exetj/ iroLovcri irpbs to iroaaySis eKaaTov Xeyerat, Kal iroia ofioims Kal iroia eTepcos kiri re t&v irpayfiaToav (TVfij3aivei, km kirl Twv ovofidTcav. AevTepov Se irpbs ray Kaff aiiTbv ^■qTrjo'eiS' 6 yap {icf> eTepov fiaSims irapaXoyi^ofievos Kal tovto fifj aitrdor vojxevos Kdv airrbs i>(p' aiiTov tovto irdOoi iroXXdKis. TpiToii Se Kal Tb XoiTTov eTi irpbs So^av, Tb irepl irdvra yeyvjivaffdm SoKelv Kal nr)Sevbs dneipcos exeiv to yap KoivwvovvTa Xoywv ylreyeiv Xoyovs, firjSev exovTa Siopi^eiv irepl ttjs (pavXorriTOt EAErXDN. 51 be developed between the thesis and the tenets either of the answerer or of those whom he aeknowleiges to be high autho- rities, or of those who are generally so acknowledged, or of those of his own school, or of those of the majority of people, or of those of all mankind s. And as the answerer avoids imminent confutation by drawing distinctions, so the questioner who fore- sees an objection that applies in one sense and not in another, should explain that he means the proposition in the unobjection* able sense, like Cleophon in the Mandrobulus. And digressing from the argument in hand he should by anticipation restrict the bearing of his other arguments, and the answerer similarly should meet his other arguments by anticipatory protestation and objection. Sometimes the questioner must attack a propo- sition diflFerent from the thesis, by means of misinterpretation, if he cannot attack the thesis, as Lyeophron did when required to deliver an encomium on the lyre. If the answerer demands what is the drift of a question, as the law is that the object of a question must be assigned on demand, and a definite answer might put him on his 'guard against the intended confutation, he should be told that the object is to prove the contradictory of his thesis, the affirmative of his negative, or the negative of his affirmative ; not that the object is to prove, say, that contraries fall under the same science, or that they fall under diffijrent sciences. The conclusion should not be asked as a proposi- tion. Some premisses should not be asked but assumed as granted. XVI. We have expounded the sources of questions and the modes of questioning in contentious disputation. We have now to discuss answers and solution and the use of this theory. It is useful to the lover of truth for two reasons. As it chiefly turns on language, it teaches us the various signification of words and the different sequences in the world of words and the world of realities. Again, it corrects our solitary reason- ings ; for he who is easily led by an opponent into undetected paralogisms, will often fall of himself into similar errors. Thirdly, it is useful to save us from the imputation of want of culture. For if we censure a mode of disputation without being E 2, 52 HEPI r04>IITIKnN avToav, vwoi^iav SiSma-i tov SoksTu Svcryepaivuv ov 5i& raXij^ey dXXii. Sl diTfipiav. ' AiroKpivo/iiuois Se ttqjs mravrrjTiov vpos rovs tolovtov? Xoyovs, (fiavepov, einep 6pdS>s elprJKafiev trporepov k^ mv dalv ol napa\oyicr/jLoi, kol tols kv r^ nvvOdvecrOaL nXeove^ias Uavm SieiXofiev. Ov ravrov S ka-Ti Xa^ovra re tov Xoyov ISeTv Kal XvcraL Tr)v fio)(drip(av, Kal kpcoratfieuoy OLTravTciv SwaaOac ra-. )(kcos. *0 y^p lafj-ev, ttoXXukis fieTaTidifievov dyvoovfiev. 'En 8 , wanep kv toTs dXXois to OoLttov Kal to ^paSvrepov eK rov yiyvfivdaOai yiveTai /laXXov, o'lrrca Kal knl twv Xoycov e^ft^ aiTTe, &v SrjXov fiev rjjuv f, dfieXiTr]TOi 8' a/iev, vaTepovjiiv t5>v Kaipcov TToXXaKis. Zv/i^aivei 8k voTe KaOdirep kv tok 8iaypd/j.fia(Tiv Kal yccp fKec dvaXvaavTes kviore avvQiivai irdXiv d8vvaTovft.€v ofjTco Kal kv toTs kXiy)(ois e/Sorey Trap' 8 o Xoyos avfi^aivei avveipaL, SiaXvcrai^ tov Xoyov dtropovfiev. XVII. flpmrov jjLiv ovv, axrirep epIITIKnN vai fj ov oTTOKpivfcrOai rbv epcorwfievov, eyiver' dv. Nvv Sk iih, TO /J.fj KaXms kpayrdv Toijs irvvOavofjiivovs dvaynr] irpoaatroKpi-- vetrdai ri tov epoorSfievov, SiopOovvra rfiv fioyfirjpiav rrjs TTpoTcia-eccs, €7re2 SieXofievov ye iKaySis rj vai -q ov dvdyKT] \kyuv TOV diroKpivofievov. El Si Tis vnoXri^^eTai tov Kara dfieovv/j.Lav e\ey)(ov e'cai, Tponov Tivdi oiiK ecrTai 8iar]aiv. AXX 'iams ov tovto a~rjfiaiver ovSe ykp kKii ToiSvo/xa. "DcTTe tl Siatpipei ; Ei 8e t£ jikv to airXm Xiyeiv KopicrKov dvoSwa-ei, tw Se TrpoaO'qaei to tivol fj TovSe, aTOTTOv ovSev yap fidXXov 6aTep(p- mroTtpa yap dv, ovSev Sia^epei. Ov /J.fjv aXX' eireiSfj dSrjXos fJ.iv kaTiv 6 fif] SiopKra/ievos ttjv dfKpifioXiav TTorepov kXrjXfyKTai rj ovk eXrjXeyKTai, SiSoTM ■S' kv ToTs Xoyois to SieXeTv, (pavepov oti to fir) SiopicravTa Sovvai TTjv epdoTTjaiv dXX' aTrXms d/xapT-qfid eaTiv, wcm Kav el /if) aiiTos, dXX' o ye Xoyos eXrjXeyfieveo ofioios eaTiv. Ivji- fiaivei fievTOL iroXXaKis dpmvras Tfjv diJ.(j)L^oXiav oKveTv Siaipei- aOai Sid rfjv TrvKvorrjra tS>v to, roiavTa TrpoTeivovTcov, onws fii] jrpbs dnav SoKmai SvaKoXaiveiv eiT ovk dv oirjOevTcov irapa TOVTO yevecrQai tov Xoyov, noXXaKi? dn'^VTrjcj-e wapdSo^ov. "D' ovO/J,a rjv erepois ovaiv ; ei yap TrXeKO Sr^Xol evos, nXeia EAErxnN. 55 must be simply Yes or Noj would then be practicable. As it is, the unfairness of the questions compels ^s to add something to them in our answer to correct their vices : though, if the distinction was properly made by the questioner, the answer should be simply Yes or No. If it is held that equivocal terms lead to genuine confutation, it is impossible for the answerer to avoid confutation. Where the same proper name denotes several individuals, he must perforce nominally deny what he affirmed, and affirm what he denied. The correction that some have proposed is ineffectual. Not Coriscus, they say, is musical and unmusical, but this Coriseus is musical and this Coriscus is unmusical. Here " this Coriscus" and " this Coriscus" are the same terms, and have contradictory predicates. " But they do not mean the same person." No more did the simple name : so that nothing is gained. To call one of them simply Coriscus, and the other, this or that Coriscus, is unjustifiable j for why should one rather than the other have the distinctive addition, when their right to it is equal ? As it is uncertain when we have not drawn the distinction whether we are confuted or no, and we have the right to draw distinctions, to grant a premiss absolutely and without distinc- tion is an error, and makes the answerer, or at least his answer, appear to be confuted. It often happens that we see an ambiguity but hesitate to distinguish, because the occasions are so numerous, for fear of seeming to be perversely obstructive. Then, never having suspected that a given point would be the hinge of the argument, we are surprised into paradox. As, then, we have the right 'of distinguishing, we must use it unhesitatingly, as I said before^ iS In equivocation if two questions were not put as one, there would be no paralogism, but either a genuine confutation or not even a seeming one. What is the difference between asking whether Callias and Themistocles are musical, and asking the same question about two different persons of the same name ? 56 HEPI 104>IITIKnN ■npayr-qcTiv. El ovv fifj 6p6ov npbs Svo kprnTrjans /Mtau dir'o^ Kpiaiv d^Lovv Xafi^dviiv &n\m, (pavepoy on ovSevl irpov'^m tS>v 6fieovv/i(ov dnoKpivea-daL UTrXm, ovS" el Karci irdvTTi]cns. ' Eyyatpel yap Koi /ivpia eTepa eprnT-qOevTa epcDTTJ- /Mara dtravTa fj vat fj ov dXrjOes eivai Xeyeiv dXX o/ims ovk dwoKpneov fiiS. diroKpicrev dvaipeiTai yap to SiaXeyea-Oai. Tovto S ojjloiov As el Kal to avro ovojia Tedeiij tois eTepois. El ovv fifj Sec wpbs Svo epcoTrjaeis [iiav diroKpiaiv SiSovai, ^avepov oTi oiiS enl twv djioivviJimv to vai 7} oxi XeKTeov. OvSk yap 6 elirmv dtroKeKpiTai dXX' eiprjKev. 'AXX' d^iovvrai ira>s ev T0L9 8iaXeyofj.evoLS Siii, to XavOdveiv to ov/i^aTvov. "Dcnrep ovv einonev, evetSijirep ovS' eXeyypi Tives ovTts SoKovcriv eivai, KaTO. tov aiiTOV Tpowov Kal Xvcreii So^ovciv elvai Tives ovk ovaai XvtreiS" &s Stj (pafiev kvioTe jiaXXov Seiv epeiv ^ Tas dXrjOels ev toTs dycavicTTiKoTs Xoyots Kal Trj npos TO SiTTov dnavTYiaei. AwoKpiTeov 8' eirl fiev t5>v Sokovvtcov TO eaTCo XeyovTa- Kal yap ovtcos ■^Kicrra yivoiT dv nape^e- Xey)(^os- dv Se ti irapdSo^ov dvayKa^rjTai Xeyeiv, evTavda HdXicTTa irpoadeTeov to SoKeTv oHitoi yap dv oUt eXey)(os ovre napdSo^ov yiveadai So^eiev. Ewel Se n&s alTedrai to ev dpyjj SfjXov, oiovTai Se ndvTei, av fi (Tvveyyvs, dvaipeTeov Kal fir) (TvyyonpTfTeov eivai evia c»y TO ev dpyrj aiTovvTos, OTav re * tolovtov d^ioi tcs o dvayKoiov fj,ev (rv/jL^aiveiv eK Trjs 6ecre(os, rj Se yjrevSos rj dSo^ov, tovto XeKTeov TO, yap e^ dvdyKijs avfi^aivovTa Trjs avTrjs eivai SoKei Oeerems. "Eti OTav to KaBoXov fir/ ovojiaTi Xr](f)6ri dXXh irapa^oXfj, XeKTeov oti ovx cor eSodrj ovS" toy irpovTeive Xaji^dvev Kai yap wapd tovto yiveTai voXXaKis eXey^os. ' E^eipyofievov Se TovTCov eirl to /ifj KaXm SeSeTxOai rropevTeov, dnavTrnvra KUTd TOV elprjfievov Siopicr/j.6v. EAErXfiN. 57 If the persons are two j the question is two. If, then^ it is wrong to give a single answer to two (questions, it is wrong to give a simple answer to an equivocal question, even when it is true in every signification, as some say you ought. It is just the same as asking, are Coriscus and Callias at home ? In either case, whether both are at home or neither, there are two ques- tions. The truth of a single predicate to several subjects does not make the questions one. Ten thousand questions might all be answerable by one single Yes or No, and yet it would not be a single answer : else there could be no dialectic. And the same is true if many subjects have one name. If, then, a plurality of questions must not receive a single answer, no more must an ambiguous proposition be answered Yes or No. This is not really an answer but a speech. It is made sometimes from not foreseeing the consequences. As there are unreal but seeming confutations, so, as we said before, there are unreal but seeming solutions, which must some- times be employed in preference to the true^ in contentious disputation and replying to arguments based on equivocation. When we admit premisses which we believe, we should use the formula, Granted, for this will preclude accessory confutation. When to save our thesis from confutation we must maintain a paradox, we should profess it to be our genuine opinion ; thus we avoid confutation and efface the character of paradox. We have explained what begging the question means, and it is allowed that when assumptions are closely connected with the issue we may deny them and refuse to concede them as pre- misses on the plea that they beg the question : similarly, if a necessary consequence of the thesis is false and improbable, we should use the same plea, for a necessary consequence seems to be part of the thesis. Again, if the subject of a premiss obtained by generalization is nameless, and only indicated by comparison, we must say that what was propounded and granted was not the principle now employed, for this is often the case?. Ex- cluded from these courses we must attempt to shew that the proof fails in some of the elements which we enumerated. 58 HEPI IOIITIKnN 'El/ /lev oSv ToTs Kvpims Xeyo/ievois ovofiaa-iv dvayKr} diro- Kpivea-Bai ^ dirXms ^ Siaipov/ievov. *>l 8e avwrroi/oovvTeh riOiHiv, ohv Sera firj aas dWa koXo^Sis kpcoTdrai, irapk TOVTO avfi^aivii 6 eXeyxoy, oioy dp' b &y ^ AQrjvaiaiv, KTTJfid kvTLv' A6rjvaLv ^fflcoi'. Tbv yap dvQpamov tSiv ^ma>v Xiyop-ev, ori ^mov eari, Kal AvaavSpov rmv AaKmvcav, on AdKcov. ArjXov oSv &s kv oh dara^ki to irpoTiivojievov ov crvy^^aiprjreov dnXms. "Orav Se SvoTv ovtoiv darepov fjikv ovtos e| dvdyKrjf Bdrepov ilvai SoK^, Oarepov Se tovto fir] e| dvdyKijs, kpayrwfievov npS- Tepov Set TO eXaTTOv SiSouar yaXeTrmrepov yap cruXXoyia-aaSai eK TrXeiovcov. Edv 8 kiriyeipfj on rm jiev ev Xeyovcriu oi iroXXol tov jirj arvyycupovvTa y^evSeadaL dv (paiev evia 8 oxi, oTov oa-a diufuSo^ovaiv (norepov yap v ^axov, ov 8id)pis ■^ 8idjieTpoi dcrvfifieTpos, eTi o5 TdXrjQes djKpiSo^eTTai, /idXia-ra nera^pav dv TLS XavOdvoi Ta ovo/iara irepl tovtwv (^8ioc. jiev yd,p to d8rjXov eivai iroTepms e^et TaXrjBes^, ov 86^ei aocpL^ea-Oai, Sia Se TO dfi(j)i8o^eTv ov So^ei ■yp'ev8ear6ai.Y j) 8e /leTa^opd Troirj(Tei tov Xoyov dve^eXeyKTOv. "Etl oa-a dv Tis irpoaia-OdvrjTai twv epayrrj/jidTCOV, npo- eva-TaTeov Kal vpoayopevTeov oiira yap dv fidXiara tov TTwdavo/ievov KoaXvcreiev. XVIII. Enel 8' ka-Tlv fj fiev 6p6^ Xvl2TIKnN vapa TL cpaiverai twv kpoDTrfudrmv SiopdeoaLS. "iicrre avfi^aiva tS>v Xoycav rovs fikv crvWeXoyiafievovs dveXovra, rovs oe (paivo- /levovs SieXovra \veiv. fldXiv S' kwel rcav ovXKiXoyKTji^vmv Xoymv 01 fitv dXrjOes ot 8e y^evSos exova-i to av/iTripaa-fia, to^s filv Kara, to avunipaafia yjrevSeis SL)(as kvSkyeTai Xve.LV Kal ydp TOO dveXiiv Ti tSiv rjpayrrjiJ,ei/a>v, Kal tw SeT^ai to trv/jTre- paarjia 'i^ov ou^ oijtcos" toi>s Se KaTo. tols npordaeii t5 dviXuv TL [loyov TO yap avinripaafia dXijOis. "Oa-re tols ^ovXofikuois XveLv Xoyov wpcorov fiev (TKenTeov et avXXeXoyiiTTaL fj dcrvWo- yiaTOS, eiTa troTepov dXrjBks to ovfiTrepaa/ia rj yjrevSoi, oirm rj SLaipovvTes ^ dvaLpovvTiS Xvco/iev, Kal dvaipovvTes tj &8e fj SiSi, Kaddirep eXe^^'? TrpoTspov. AiacjiipeL Se nXeLaTOv kpmTd>nevby Ti Kal fifi XvfLV Xoyov to fikv yhp rrpoiSeTv )(^aXeTr6v, to Se KaTOL a)(oX^v iSeiv ^aov. XIX. T5>v jxev ovv irapa tt}v o/jLoovv/iiai' Kal Trjv a/i^t|3o- Xiav kXkyycov ol fikv 'i)(ovaL tSiv kp(OTr)iidTs, &v jirj irpoffXd^rj TTjv dvTir](Tev dTre tovtov rvnTOfievov, Tovrm ervTrrero oSroy ; Kal & eTvirreTO, tovtw cri) eiSes ; e^et jiev ovv Ti KaK t&v dfufti^oKm epcoTrj/idrtov, dXX ian naph crvv6edvat l8eTv toTs otpOaXjim TVTTTOfievov. Kal 6 Evdv8Tifiov 8e Xoyos, ap oT8as (ri) vvv ovcras kv Heipaie? TpiTJpeis kv ZiKeXia av ; Kal trdXiv, ap ea-Tiv dyadbv ovTa a-Kvria fioyOripov eivai ; eir] 8 av ns dyaOos Cov (TKVTeiJs /jL0)(6rip6s' ma-T iarai dyaOos (TKVTeiiS fj.0)(6r]p6s. ''^Ap S)v al kiTKTTrifiai (TTTOvSaiat, yiyovas, dXX' ov vvv ykyovas. '^Ap d>s Svvaaai Kal h EAErXDN. 63 is to say, such and such a kind of knowledge ; for there is a difference between the restricted and unjestricted premiss. If the questioner argues without regard to the distinction^ we must contend that he has contradicted the name and not the reality, and therefore has not confuted. XX. It is evident how fallacies of composition and division are to be solved. If the composition or division produces a difference of signification, when the opponent draws his con- clusion from the premisses in one signification, we must say they bore the other. The following arguments depend on com- position and division. Was the man beaten with that with which you saw him beaten, and did you see him beaten with that with which he was beaten' ? The reasoning has something of the fallacy of ambiguous proposition, but belongs to a distinct class, the fallacy of composition. We have not here a single proposition with a double meaning, for the division produces two propositions, just as the characters, oros and horos, are the sign of two different sounds, distinguished by the breathing though not by the accent. The written word may be the same when it has the same letters in the same order, though even written words are now distinguished by accents and aspirates, but the spoken words are undeniably different. The fallacy of division, then, does not consist in ambiguity, nor is ambiguity the principle of all sophism, as some have asserted^. The answerer must distinguish and point out the difference be- tween seeing with the eyes a man beaten and seeing him beaten with the eyes. So in the argument of Euthydemus. Do you in Sicily know at this moment there are triremes in the Pirseus*? Again : a good shoemaker can be a bad shoemaker, for a good man may be a bad shoemaker, therefore he is both a good shoe- maker and a bad shoemaker^. Again: if the knowledge of a thing is good, it is a good thing to learn : the knowledge of evil is good, therefore evil is a good thing to learn. But evil is evil and a thing to learn, therefore it is an evil thing to learn. As it is true that the knowledge of evil is good (the fallacy must lie in the rest of the reasoning). It is true to say in the present moment you are bom : then you are born in the present moment. No : the division makes a difference : it is true in the present moment that you are born but not that you are 64 HEP I IOIZTIKnN Svvaaai, ovTW Kal ravra TTOLrjaais ay ; ov Ki6apiCa>v 5' exets Svva/iLv rov KL6api(iLV Kidapiaais &u dpa ov KiOapi^wv. *H oii TOVTOV €Y6t T^ 8vUCC/ilV TOV OV Kldupi^COV KlOapL^fLV, fflXX oVe oil noiei, rov noielv. AvovcTi Si TLves TovTOU Kal dXXcos. El yap eSooKev aiy Svyarai iroieLv, ov (fyacn ovii^aiviLv fifj KiQapi^ovra KiOapi^uv ov yap nduTcos m Swarai TroteTv SeSoa-Bai iroLrjO-^iv ov rairov S' eivai o)? Svvarai Kal navTCOi toy Swarai noieTv. 'AXXa v yap iraph ravTov Xoymv fi avrfj Xvcris, avrrj S ou^ apfioaei ejrl wavras ovSe iravrm epcoTcofievovs, dXX ecm irpos tov epcoT&vTa,- ov npos rov Xoyov. XXI. riapd 8k TTjv TrpoacpSiav Xoyoi fiev ovk ilaiv, ovre rS>v yeypa/jL/ievcov ovre tS>v Xeyofievcov, ttXtju et rcves oXiyoL yi- voivT dv, OLOv oStoj d Xoyoy. '^Apd y ka-rl to ov KaraXveis oiKia ■ Nai. OvKovv to ov KaTaXveis tov KaTaXveis aTro^aais ; Nai. "Ecprja-as S tivai to o5 KaToXijeis oiKiav fj oiKia dpa dn6av irpos tl rj iToaSiv, SoKovvTcov Se ti k. '^Ap ki/Se^^erai to airro dfia TTOieTv t€ koI ireiTOLriKevaL ; Oii. 'AXXa firjv opdv ye tl dfia Kal ewpaKevat TO avTo Kal KaTO, Tairrh kvSeyeTai. '^Ap kcrTi ti tSiv irda-yeiv TTOieiv TL ; Ov. OvKOVv TO Te/iveraL KaieTai aladdveTaL oholcos XkysTaL, Kal irdyra 7rda-)(^eLi' tl a-rj/iaiveL' woXlv Se to XeyeiV Tpeyeiv opdv ofioims aXXijXoiy XeyeTar aXXd firjv to y opdv ata-Odvea-Oai tl kcrTLV, wa-re Kal irdayeiv tl dfia Kal. iroieiv. El Se Tis kKei Soi)s /xfi kvSey^eaOaL dfia tovto iroLeiu Kal iretroir]- KevaL, TO opdv Kal icopaKevaL ^air] kyxoapeiv, oUnrn kXrjXeyKTaL, el fifj Xeyoi to opdv TroieTv tl dXXd irdcrxeLV irpocrSeT yb.p EAErXDN. 65 bom in the present moment. — Do you do what you can and as you can? Yes. Not harping, you* can harp. You harp, then, not harping. No : you have not the power to harp not harping, but when not harping you have the power to harp. The solution some propose is different. If it is granted that a man does a thing as he can, they say it does not follow that he harps not harping, because it was not granted that he does the thing in all the ways in which he can. The solution is clearly bad, for faUades identical in principle should admit of the same solution ; but this solution will not apply to other fallacies similar in principle, nor to every mode of interrogation. It is a solution relative to the individual arguer, not to the argument. XXI. AccENTTJATiOK scarcely gives rise to any fallacy either in writing or speaking, but a few might be invented like the following: — ^A house is where you lodge {ou with circumflex and aspirate), you do not lodge {ou with unwritten grave accent and soft breathing) is a negation, therefore a house is a nega- tion. The solution is plain, for the word is not the same when the accent is grave and when it is circumflex. XXII. It is plain that we must solve fallacies from similarity of expression by pointing out the difference of category denoted by similar words. The thesis denies the existence of a sub- stance, and the questioner proves the existence of a relation or quantity that seems to be a substance from the form of ex- pression. For instance ; can we be making and have made one and the same thing ? No ^. Why, we can be seeing and have seen one and the same thing. Can an action be a passion ? No. Why, to be cut, to be burnt, to be affected by a sensible object, are similar expressions, and all denote passions. Again, to say, to run, to see, are similar expressions. Now to see is to be affected by a sensible object, therefore it is both an action and a passion. In the former example, if I asserted in my thesis that one could not be making and have made the same thing, and granted that one could be seeing what one has seen, I am not confuted unless I grant that seeing is making. This addi- tional premiss is required, but the hearer thinks that when I F 66 PEPI IO

s o/ioioas Xeyo/ievov to Si Xe- veTM jikv ovx ofjioims, (ftaiverai, Se Sid Trfv Xt^iv. Th avrh Se (rvji^aivii onep kv tous 6p.a>vvfiiair oifTai ydp kv roh o/jLtov^fiois 6 dyycbs Tmv Xoywv o ecjirjaev d7ro(f)fja-aL irpayjia, oiiK Sfo/ia- TO Se eTi irpocrSeT kpcorijfiaTos, el ks e)(ei eva jilivov Kal o^BaX/iov Kal dXX' onovv 6 irXeim exS 8 ex^i eXa^ev^- eSiSov ydp fitav /j.6vov o&ros ■^fj^ov Kal oSToy EAErXQN. 67 granted that to be cutting is to be making, and to have cut to have made, I also granted that the rftnaining forms denote corresponding categories. The hearer himself grants that the remainder have a similar signification, whereas the signification is different, though the forms are similar. What happens in the fallacies of ambiguous term happens here. In the fallacies of ambiguous term the uninitiated fancy that the reality is contra- dicted as well as the name, whereas confutation requires a fur- ther admission, that one reality is denoted by the ambiguous name. If the answerer grants this, he is confuted. Similar to these reasonings are the following. What one had at first and has no longer he need not have lost, for if he had ten dice and loses one he has no longer ten. No. What he had at first and has no longer he must have lost ; though he need not have lost as much or as many as he had at first. The thesis spoke of the substance that he has no longer, the con- clusion speaks of the quantity. If it had been asked, when a man has a certain number of things at first and not subse- quently, must he have lost them all ? it would have been answered. No, he need not have lost them all, but he must have lost some of them. Again : — A man may give away what he has not got, for he may have many and give away only one. No. He does not give away a thing which he has not got, but a thing which is not related in the giving as it was in the having, if he had many and gives only one, for only denotes neither substance, nor quality, nor quantity, but relation, namely dissociation from others. When the thesis is that a man cannot give what he has not got, if it is granted that a man may give quickly what he has not got quickly, and I infer that a man may give what he has not got, my argument is inconclusive : for quickly does not denote sub- stance but manner, and the manner of giving may be different from the manner of having ; for a man may have with pleasure what he gives with pain. Similar, too, are the following : — Suppose the thesis to be, a man cannot see with an eye he has not nor strike with a hand he has not. But a two-eyed or two-handed man has not only one eye or hand but may see or strike with only one. Some meet the argument by contradicting the premiss which denies that a man has only one eye or anything else when he has more F 2 68 nEPI IOIITIKnN y ?Yet, ^aa-i, /iiav fiovrjv iraph, tovtov yjrfjtpoi'. 01 S' eiiBiis Trjv kpm"r}dapevTos kv rfj Aiji/ret, e^eiv' 6^vv. '/4XX' owep kXe\Brj Koi irpSrepov, oStoi iravres oi irpbi rbv \6yov aXXA irpoy tov dvOpamov Xvova-iv. Ei yhp rjv aSrr] Xv(ns, Bovra to dfTiKei/ievov oux ofov re Xijeiv, KaOdirep iirl rZv aXXwv otov, el ea-ri fikv t eari 8 t oi! rj Xvais, av anXwi SS Xeyea-dai, av/nrepaiverar k&.v de [irj avfiirepaivTjTai, ovk av fit] Xva-is' kv Se rots irpoeiprj/jLivois navTcav SiSo/iivoov- ov8k ^afJLev yii/eadai crvXXoyicriiov. "En 8e Kal 018" eial toutcdv rmv Xoymv. '^Ap h ykypavrai, eypa^iro^ ; /"eypawrat 5e vvv on ai KaBtjaai, ■^evSfis XSyor TJv 5' dXrjdrls, or kypd^iTO' dfia Spa kypd^ero yfrevBris Kai dXrjOijs. To yhp -^evBrj ^ dXrjOfj Xoyov fj 86§av eTvai ov roSt dXXdi, T0i6f8e a-r]/J.aivei' 6 yap airrbs Xoyos Kal kirl Ttjs 86^ri?. Kal dp' 8 navOdvei. 6 jiavQdvoiv, tovt kvrlv 8 fiavOdvei ; fiay- Bdvei 8k ns rh Ppa8i> Ta\v. Ov rotvvv 8 jiavBdvu aXX' ay fiavOdvii eiprjKev. Kal dp' 8 pa8i(ei TiS irarei ; ^a8i(H 8i rtjv ■fifiepav oXrjv. *H ovxt Pa8i(u dXX' ore Pa8i(H upt]K(.v. Ov8' &rav rr)v KvXiKa vivuv, 8 irivei dXX' e| o£. Kal dp' ns ot8ev, fj fiadrnv ^ eipmv otSev ; &v Se to ji^v eSpe to 5* e/iafle, Td diKJxo ov8kTepov. *H 8 filv d-rrav, A 8\ ovx airaura ®. Kal EAErxnN. • 69 than one. Or suppose the thesis to be. What a man has re- ceived and not parted with he possesses ; ^and the premisses, He received only one ballot, but, having several before, does not possess only one : conclusion. Therefore he does not possess what he received. Some solve this by contradicting a premiss, and maintaining that he possesses only one from this donor : others by contradicting the thesis, and asserting that it is pos- sible not to possess what one received; to receive sound wine, for instance, and if it was injured in the storage, to possess sour. All these solutions, like some mentioned before, are addressed, not to the argument but to the arguer. In every true solution, an admission contradicting the allegation of the solution would make the confutation valid, as in the other . examples. For instance, if the solution is a distinction, an admission that the premiss is true without distinction would make the conclusion valid. Where a valid conclusion .does not follow from the con- tradictory of the solution, that solution cannot be true. In the above examples, even if all is supplied which the proposed solu- tions allege to be wanting, there still is no conclusion *. The following arguments belong to the same class. Suppose the thesis to be, that the same statement cannot be both true and false. Then because what is written was written a certain time ago, and what is written, namely, that you are seated, is false now, though true when it was written ; the arguer con- cludes that what was written was both true and false. But the falsity or truth of a statement is not its substance (what is written) but its quality : and so of opinion. Again : — what a man learns is what he learns : a man learns a slow march quick (quickly), therefore quick is slow. Here the subject which a man learns is confused with the rate of his learning. Again : — what one walks he tramples on : a man walks a day ; therefore he tramples on the day. Here we change from space to time. Again : — when a man is said to drink a cup, the expression con- fuses the vessel and the wine. Again : — suppose the thesis to be, that the same thing cannot be both known and unknown ; then because all that a man knows he knows either by teaching or discovery ,• and if part of his knowledge was taught him, and part discovered, the whole was neither taught nor discovered, I conclude that the whole was both known and unknown. The 70 nEPI ZO^IITIKDN OTi eari ris rpiros dv^pumos'' vap aiiTov Kal Toi>s Ka6' e/co- a-Tov. To yhp dvOpamos Kal &irav to koivov ov roSe ti, dXXi ToiovSe Ti ^ npos ri rj irws ^ rwv towvtcov ti irrjfiaii/tl, 'OjiotoDt B\ Kal eirl tov KopiaKOS Kal KopiaKOS /lovaiKos, no- Tepov TavTov rj eTepov ; to /lev yhp ToSe ti to Si ToiovSe a-rj/jLaivei, &avepov oSv oti ov Soriov ToSe Ti eTvai to koivt} KaTTjyopov/ievov enl ndaiv, dXX' rjroi TTOiov 17 npos Ti ^ no! d)S oiiK e)(ei, oiov eva fiovov daTpdyaXov. '*Ap h iiriv eiriaTaTai ; 'AXX' ov-^ h eiriaTarai. Kal el & ^aSi^ec iraTeT, dXX' oi^x ore. 'O/ioms Se Kal eirl t&v dXXtov, EAErXiiN. 71 solution is, that the premiss asserted, that all he knew distri- butively, not all collectively, was from x)ne of these sources. Again, the proof of a third order of man, besides the individual man and the ideal man, depends on the confusion of category. For man and other generic terms are not names of substances, but of quality, or relation, or mode, or some other accident. So in the problem whether Coriscus and the musician Coriscus are different or the same, one term expresses a substance, the other a quality which cannot be really isolated. It is not, however, the isolation that produces the third order of man, but the assumption that the generic man is a substance, for without this, what is common to Callias and the generic man could not seem to be a substance. And what is isolated may be considered as not a substance, but merely a quality, without any logical inconvenience, for we shall still have a one besides the many, for instance, the generic man ^. We must maintain, then, that genera are not names of substances, but merely names of quali- ties, or relations, or quantities, or other accidents ^°. XXIII. When language is the source of fallacy, the opposite interpretation to that which produces the fallacy furnishes the solution. If composition produces the fallacy, division gives the solution ; if division, composition. If acute accentuation creates the fallacy, grave accentuation supplies the solution; if grave, acute. If an ambiguous term is misinterpreted, give the oppo- site interpretation. If the thesis said a thing was animate, and the terms prove it inanimate, interpret them so as to leave it animate : if your thesis said it was inanimate, and the terms prove it animate, interpret them so as to leave it inanimate : and so with ambiguou^ propositions. If similarity of expression leads to confutation by one interpretation, the opposite interpre- tation provides the solution. If the thesis is, that a man cannot give what he does not possess, then your concession must be ex- plained to be, that the possessor of many things who gives only one, gives, not a thing that he does not possess, but a thing that is not related to other gifts as it was to other possessions. Each element of a man's knowledge is known either by tradition or by discovery, not the sum total. A man tramples the way he goes, not the time. And so in the other cases. 72 nEPI IOepeiv rb ofov. Eial Se ndvres ol roLoiSe rmv Xoymv irapk to avfi^e^riKos. ''Ap oTSas o fj,eXX(o v dXXwv. Aijova-i Se Tives dvaipovvTes^ rfiv kpcorrjirLV aal yhp evoe- yeadai Tairrb irpay/ia elSevai Kal dyvoeiv, dXXd firj Kara Tairro- Tbv ovv npoaiSvTa ovk eiSSres, Tbv Se KopiaKOv eiSores, TavTb fiev eiSevai Kal dyvoeiv a(Tiv, dXX' ov Karh Tairo. KaiToi irpZTov fiev, KaOdtrep fjSri einofiev, SeT rmv irapa ToiiTb Xoycov t^v avr^v eTvai SiopOaxriv aiiTt) S' oiiK eIITIKDN yap in kviav tovt iarlv oKrjdh koI ei/8ex^Teu TaiiTo fl- Seuai Kal dyvoeiv, d\\' evravBa ovSev KotvoDveT to Xe^Oev. OvSev Se Ks dSvvaTOV, afiaprdvei, k&v h f/vpiaKis ■p cnXXeXoyitrfiivos' oii yap kariv avrrj Xvo-ts. ''Hv yiip fj Xvais kfi^avtcris ■^evSovs avXXoyur/ioG, nap' 8 ^^ei/fiijy ii ovv fifi cruXXeXoyta-rai rj Kal dXrjOes ^ yjrevSos enixeipu avvd- yeiv, 17 eKeivov SijXoxrty Xvcris eariv. "la-cos Se Kal tovt' eir' evmv ovSev KmXijei avfi^aiveiv nX^v kni ye To&rcov ovSe tovto So^eiev &v Kal yhp tov KopiaKov oti KopiaKos oi8e, koI rh npoaiov OTI npoa-iov. ' EvSkyeaOai 8e 8oKeT to airrb el8ivai Kal firj, oTov OTI jikv XeuKov el8evai, oti 8k /lovaiKov p.^ yva>pi((iv, o6t(o yaip TO aiiro o?8e Kal ovk oI8ev aXX' ov KaTa Taiirov. To 8f npotriov Kal Kopia-Kov, Kal oti npoaiw Kal oti KopiffKOt, oTSev. 'Ofioms 5' d/iapTavova-i Kal 01 XvovTes, on anas dpiS/ibs oXiyos, &(Tnep of>s eino/iev ei yap jiri avfinepaivo/ievov, tovto napaXinovTes, dXrjBes ovjinenepavQai a(ri, ndvra yhp ehai Kal noXtiv Kal oXiyov, ajxapTdvovaiv. "Evioi 8e Kal t& 8itt& Xvovai toUs avXXoyia/iovs, oTov on troy koTi naT^p ^ vibs ^ SoiiXos. Katroi (j>avepbv ms el naph Tb noXXa)(S>s Xeyea-Oai (ftaiveTai 6 eXey^os, 8ei Tovvo/ia fj tov Xoyov Kvpims efvai nXeiovcov Tb 8e t6v8' eivai TovSe TiKvov- ovSels Xeyet Kvpias, et SeanoTrjS koTi TeKvov dXXa naph to axip.^e^r]Kbs fi (ruvOeais^" kaTiv. '^Ap' karl tovto v kukwv kariv, oKK oil TOVTO tS)v KaKwv^^ ; Haph to irrj ovv Koi &ir\m (paiveTai. KaiToi evSi\eTai laoos dyaOov elvai Ti t5>v KaKwv SittSis, aXX ovK €7rt Tov Xoyov tovtov, aXX' et ti SovXov eir/ dyaOhv fio-)(6i]- pov, fiSXKov. "la-cos S' ovS' oijtcos' ov yap el dyaQov Koi tov- tov, dyaQov tovtov dfia. OvSe to tov avQpamov ^dvai tS>v ^mcav iivai oil Xeyerat TroWaySis' ov yhp ef woTi ti (Trjiiaivojiiv d(f>e\6vTfS, TOVTO Xeyerat TroXKayms' koi yap to ^fiiav drrov- T€s tov eirovs Sos fioi 'IXidSa crrjuaii/o/iey, olov to firjviv dfiSt Bid. XXV. Toils Se rrapa to Kvpicos T6Se ^ Trg ^ noO rj nm rj irpos Ti Xeyea-Qai Kal fifi dirXSis, XvTeoti (tkottovvti to avuirt- paafia rrpos Trji/ dvTi(]>aaiv, el evSeyeTai TOVTcav ti TreirovBevai. 7a yhp kvavTia Kal Tk. dvTiKeifieva Kal (f>da-iti Kal dirb^tKriv anXSts /iev dSvvaTov imdpyeiv t5 aiiTw, nfj fievToi eKdrepov fj irpos TL ^ TTcas, ^ TO jiev irfj to S' awXms, oiiSev KmXvei. "Hot' fl ToSe fiev &nX5>s ToSe Se nfj, oiiirpei tov aiiTov ajia r£ avT& weiOeaOai Kal dneiOeiv ; *H cure to ehai Ti Kal etvai TaiiTov ; to Se fifj ov ovk, el eari ti, Kal eariv dnXm' oiiT el eiiopKei ToSe ^ TJjSe, dvdyKt] Kal eiiopKelv o S 6[i6aas eiriopKTJa-eiv eiiopKei eTnopKwv tovto /lovov, evopKei Se o^ oiiS' 6 drrei$(ov TreiOeTai, dXXd ti ireiOeTai. "0/j.oios 8' 6 X6yos Kal irepl tov ^evSea-Oai tov aiiTov a/j.a Kal dXr/de^eiv dXXa Sih, TO fifi eivai eiiOediprjTov,^ irorepms dv tis diroSoir) to anXSis dXfjdeijeiv ^ ■'^evSeaOai, Svo-koXov ^aiveTai. KmXvei S' avTov. oiiSev dwXms p-ev etvai ■\lfevSfj, irfj S' dXr]6ii ^ tlvos, Kal eivai EAETXiiN. 77 we say man is of the animals we mean he is a species, not the propertyj of the animals ; that is to«iBay, the genitive may have either a possessive or a partitive force,) still when we express the relation of wisdom to evils by putting evils into the genitive, we do not mean that wisdom is absolutely of evils, but that wisdom is a correlative, namely, the knowledge of evils. The fallacy then lies not in ambiguity but in the con- fusion of absolute and restricted propositions. If, however, the expression that there is a good of evils, is not ambiguous when we aflSrm that wisdom is of evils, do we not obtain an ambigu- ous conclusion when we assume a good slave belonging to bad masters ? Perhaps not even then, for a thing that is good and of the bad is not therefore a good of the bad '2. The expression that man is of the animals is not ambiguous '", for ellipsis is not ambiguity, for we may call unambiguously for the Iliad by saying, "Achilles wrath"." XXV. Faxlacies from the confusion of absolute or unrestricted propositions with propositions restricted in mode, place, degree, or relation, are to be solved by comparing the conclusion with the thesis, to see whether there is any restriction on either side to prevent their being contradictory i. For contrary, opposite, negative and affirmative predicates cannot both belong to the same subject absolutely, but may both belong restrictedly, or one restrictedly and the other absolutely. If one belongs abso- lutely and the other restrictedly, there is no confutation. We must therefore compare the conclusion with the thesis. All the following arguments have this defect.— Thesis : what is not, cannot be. But what is not, is what is not. — Thesis : what is, cannot not-be. But what is, is not, for it is not some special thing. — ^Thesis : the same man cannot be perjured and keep his oath. — Thesis : the same man cannot at the same time obey and disobey the same command. In the first two ex- amples to be restrictedly something and absolutely to be, are not the same. What is not, is restrictedly something, but abso- lutely is not. Again, a man may be unforsworn in a definite particular but not absolutely. If he swore to perjure himself and keeps his oath, he is unperjured in this particular but not absolutely. Again, he who disobeys, though not obedient abso- lutely, may be obedient to a particular command. So it may 78 nEPI IOIITIKDN dXfjBTJ Tivd, dXrjOfj 8e jifi. '0/jlouos Se Kot ewl Tmv npos n Kal nov Kal ir&re' navres yitp ol toiovtoi \6yoi traph tovto avu^aivova-iv. "^Ap rj iyUia f] 6 irXovros dyaBov \ ' A}0\.h. tS £Si, Kal dwXms SiKaiov. 'Ofiotas Sk Kal dSiKa 6vTa ovSev KcoXvei Xeyeiv ye aiiTO, SiKaiov eivai' oil ydp ei Xeyeiv SiKaiov, dvdyKrj SiKaia elvai, &l2TIKnN XXVI. Tors Se napa rbv opia/iov yivo/iivois tov eXeyxov, KaBdirep inreypd^r) irporepov, diravTtjreov aKOirovai to oiz/i- irepaaua npbs Trju dvTi^aaiv, ortroas earai to avTo Kal kutSi to avTo Kal npos to avTo Kal d>cravT(os Kal kv t& avrm ')(fiovu ToiovTcov Xoyoov eis tov kpayrStvTa /leTaarpewTeov mv 01) SieiXeyiievov 6 yap eXeyxos dvev tov k^ dp-)(rji. EW on kSS&Tj oiJ^ o)S TOVTca )(pr]a-o/ievov, dXX as npbs tovto avXXoyi- ovfikvov TovvavTiov, f) knl Tmv nape^eXey)(cov. XXVIII. Kal Toi>s Sid tov napeiro/ievov s rS kv fiepei to KaOoXov, olov dv- Bpanco (aov d^iovTai ydp, ei tSSc jieTd TovSe, Kal t6S' elvai jieTd TovSe. *H KaTd Tds dvTiOeaeis^- et ydp ToSe T&Se aKO- XovBeT, Tw avTiKeifteva Tb dvTiKeifievov. flap' 8 Kal 6 tov MeXiaaov Xoyos' ei ydp rb yeyovbs €;(€« dp)(rjv, Tb dyevqrpv EAErxnN. 81 it is not wrong allegations that carry the judgment, for the things are right to allege though absolutsly wrongs and wrong to undergo. XXVI. Fallacies that omit some element in the definition of eonfiitationj as was suggested above, must be solved by ex- amining whether the conclusion is contradictory of the thesis, and regards the same terms, in the same portion, in the same re- lation, in the same manner, in the same time. The thesis when first advanced should admit that the same thing may be double and not double in any way that falls short of the conditions of contradiction. The following arguments depend on this. He who knows a subject to have a predicate knows the subject, and so he who is ignorant. If, then, I know that Coriscus is Coriscus, and am ignorant that he is musical, I know and am ignorant of the same subject. — A thing four cubits high is higher than a thing three cubits high : but what is three cubits high may grow to be foxa cubits high. What is greater is greater than what is less. The same thing, therefore, may be greater and less than itself, and in respect of the same dimen- sion, namely height. XXVII. In fallacies from begging and assuming the point in issue, if we are aware in time we should deny the proposition, even though it is probable, and say, as we fairly may, that it cannot be granted but must be proved. If it escaped us, the badness of the reasoning enables us to turn round and impute the blunder to the opponent, who ought to have known that it IS no confutation to assume a contradictory proposition : and we may say that we admitted the proposition, not as a premiss but as a thesis to be confuted, or as a premiss, not of the main reasoning, but of a by-confutation i. XXVIII. Fallacies from the relation of antecedent and con- sequent can only be exposed when the false conclusion is drawn. There are two modes of falsely inferred sequence. Either when animal, the universal, follows from man, the particular, it is in- ferred that man, the particular, reciprocally follows from animal, the universal : or, the relation of the contradictories of the ante- cedent and consequent is supposed to correspond directly to the relation of the antecedent and consequent. If A, that is, follows -B, it is assumed that not-^ follows not-5, as in Melissus' argu- G 82 HEP I lOfPIITIKDN d^ioT /irj eY^'"* ^''"''' ^' «y«'"7''''y ° oiipavos, kol airfipos. To 8' ovK eoTTiv dvairaXLV yap rj dKo\ov6r]aipoviJLevov crvfi^aivei firjSev tjttov to dSvvaTOv, KcLiriLTa TOVTO kii^avKTTeov, Kal XeKTeov w eScoKev ov^ my SoKovv dXX coy TrpbH tov Xoyov, 6 Se Kt\pr]Tai ovSev wpos tov Xoyov. XXX. ripos Se Toiis TO, nXeico epeoTrj/iaTa ev noiovvTas evOiis kv dp-j^rj SiopiaTeov. 'EpmTrja-is yap fita irpos ^v /iia diroKpLcrh ea-Tiv, acrT oilre irXeia Ka& ivbs oiiTe ev kutu iroX- Xwf, dXX tv KaB ivos (pareov fj dwoiia crvji- ^aivef OTav Se Tm fiev tZ Se /irj, ^ nXeioa KaTb, nXeiovav, Kai e(TTLv my {mdpyei dji^oTepa d/i^orepois, eari S coy ovx xmdpyii TrdXiv, &IITIKDN AvoTv re koL dviacov iKarepov aiirh aiirZ iffov, aa-re ha koX dviaa aiirk ai/ToTs. 'EfLTTiTTTOva-i filv ovv oStoc Kul els dWas Xva-eir Kal yctp TO dficpco Kal TO airavra irXeiat a-rj/iaiveL- oijKOVP TavTov, wXiji/ Svoua, avfi^aivei (pfjo'ai Kal aTTOipf\v dtraybvTctiv els ravro voXXaKis e/jreo/, ^avepov as ov Soriov twv npos Ti Xeyojikvcov a-rjuaiveiv n ycopi^onevas KaO' amhs Ths Karrfyopias, oTov SinXdaiov dvw Tov SnrXdtnov ■q/J.ta-eos^, oti e/j,aii'eTaL. Kal yap to, SeKa kv Tois ivbs Siovcri SiKa Kal Tb noLrja-ai kv tw jMrj iroirjirai, koI oXoDS kv Trj diro^daiL j) ^dcns' dXX Hfims ovk ei tls Xeyoi toSI /if/ eivai XevKov, Xkyei avTo XevKov eivai. Tb 8e SnrXdtrLov ovoe (rrjuaivei ovoev la-cos, cocnrep ovoe to ev Tfi awo^affei • ei S' dpa Kal arifiaivfi, dXX ov ravTb Kal avvrjprjfikvov. OvS ij kmaT'qfir} kv tw ei'Sei, oTov el ea-rtv rj laTpiKr) kmcTTrJiMr], airep TO KOivov kKelvo S" ^v kTrio'Trj/it] kincrTrjTOV. ' Ev Sk Tols Si &v SrjXovraL KaTtiyopovjiivois TdvTO^ XeKreov, (By ov Tb aiiTb )((opls Kal kv tZ Xoyco Tb SrjXovfJievov. Tb yap KoTXov Koivj] fjikv TO avTO Sr/XoT knl tov o-i/jlov Kal tov poiKov, wpocTTLdi/jLevov Sk oiiSkv KCoXijei, dXXd Tb p.kv Trj ^ivl to Sk tS (TAfeXet arj(j.aiv€L*' ivOa fikv ydp Tb ai/xov, ev6a Sk to ^ai^bv a-rj/xaiver Kal oiiSkv Sias Sk Xvreov, kir avrmv tcov X6ywv ea-Tai cpavepov. " AnavTes ydp ol ToioiSe tovto fiovXav- Tai KaraaKevd^eiv. ^Ap' 8 Xeyeiy dXrjOws, Kal eaTi tovto dXrjdws ; 4>jis S' ehat ti Xidov ea-Tiv dpa ti XiBov. *H to EAErXQN. 85 they are equal to themselves^ we may be interpreted to say that they are equal to one another. • These fallacies admit of other solutions, for themselves and all are ambiguouSj meaning either each respectively or all promis- cuously. So that only the same name, not the same thing, is affirmed and denied of the same subject ; which, we agreed, is no confutation. If however a single answer is not given, but a single predicate affirmed or denied of a single subject, no semblance of confutation can be fabricated *. XXXI. Reductions to pleonasm must be opposed by denying that a relative name has any meaning when separated from tlie correlative, as double separated from half in the phrase double of half, though it appears as a factor in the expression. For ten is a factor in the expression ten minus one, and doing in the expression not-doing, and the affirmative in all negative expres- sions : yet to deny a thing to be white is not to affirm it to be white. Double then, extracted and isolated, has no meaning any more than the affirmative in the negative expression : or, if it has a meaning, not the same as the factors combined. So when we name a specific science, say, medical science, the factor science is not the same as the genus science, for the latter is correlative to the general object of science. When the subject of an attribute enters the definition of the attribute, we must say that the attribute does not mean the same when conjoined with the subject and when separate. For though curved, the generic element, is only part of the meaning of aquiline and bandy when they are isolated, yet when these terms are joined to nose and leg they may lose the other part of their meaning; for aquiline nose and bandy leg mean no more than hooked nose and crooked leg. Further, we must deny the accuracy of the definition of aquiline and bandy ; for aquiline is not a hooked nose, but a nasal quality or shape ; and it is not strange that an aquiline nose should be a nose having a nasal curvature °. XXXII. Apparent solecisms depend on the cause that has been explained. The mode of solving them will be manifest in an example. The following arguments attempt to prove sole- cism. S (nominative) is {M) that (nominative) which (accusa- tive) you truly affirm S (accusative) to be. You affirm S (accu- 86 HEP I IOrifj.i eivaL tovtov, eo'Tiv oStos, ov tovtov oiiSe yap S.v iXXrjvi^oi oijTWS to epa>Trjp.a Xe)(^6ev. 'Ap eTria-Tatrai tovto; TOVTO 8' ecTTi Xi6os' eirio'Taa-ai dpa Xi6os. *H ov TavTo (tt)- jiaivei TO tovto kv rS dp' ewio'Taa'ai tovto kuI ev tZ tovto St XiQos, aXX' ev fiev rw irpwTm tovtov, kv Se rS vaTepm oinos. "^ Ap o5 eTn(TTr\p.y\v eyeis, eiria-Tacrai tovto ; eTriaTrjfirjv 8 e)(eis Xidov eTrta-Taaai dpa XiOov. *H to fiev tovtov XiOov Xeyeis, TO Se tovtov XiOov kSoOrj 8', oS eTrta-Trjfirjv ^X^'^' kwiaraa-dai, ov tovtov, dXXd tovto, Sctt' ov Xi6ov dXXa XiOov. "Otl p.tv ovv 01 TOLOVTOL T&v Xoyv elprjfievwv. EAErXDN. 87 sative) to be P (accusative). Therefore S (nominative) is P (accusative). No. When P the prediciite is masculine, the neater pronouns ikat and wAicA may be replaced by masculine pronouns which distinguish the nominative and accusative cases'. If I asserted with masculine pronouns^ S (nominative) is that (accusative) which you truly maintain it to be, I should speak ungrammatically, just as much as if I said a woman is he whom you affirm her to be. Neuter predicates do not distin- guish the nominative and accusative, and give rise to no apparent solecism. It is the masculine and feminine forms, whether the object denoted is really masculine and feminine or not, that occasion solecism. If I am impugning the thesis No man is a woman, and obtain the premiss, Coriscus is a man, if I say at once therefore a man is a woman, I have not proved the solecism, assuming Coriscus to be a woman, unless this premiss is granted by express concession. If Coriscus is not a woman, and not admitted to be a woman, 1 have not proved my conclusion either absolutely or relatively to this opponent. So in the first example it must be expressly granted as a major premiss, that M nominative is P the accusative : if it is not really so, and is not granted to be so, the conclusion does not follow. It seems to follow because in the neuter pronouns the nominative and accusative are not distinguished. The nomina- tive of S is (M) the nominative of the noun whose accusative you affirm the accusative of S to be. You affirm the accusative of S to be the accusative of P. Therefore the nominative of S is the accusative of P. This is a non sequitur ; for the nominative of S was affirmed in the minor premiss to be the nominative of a certain name. Again, from the premisses: This, man (nomi- native) is he (nominative) whom (accusative) you affirm him (accusative) to be : you affirm him (accusative) to be Cleona (accusative) J it does not follow that this man (nominative) is Cleona (accusative), for the major premiss does not affirm that he (nominative) whom you affirm him to be is Cleona (accusa- tive), and the minor premiss affirmed that S (nominative) was he (nominative) not him (accusative), and any other expression would have been ungrammatical. You know M (accusative) : M (nominative) is P (nominative) ; therefore you know P (nominative). No. if is anibiguous : in one premiss it is 88 HE PI IOt>IITIKDN XXXIII. AeT Se Kal Karavoeiv on TrdvToav tZv Xoycav ol fiiv eia-L /5aovs KariSeiv ol Se ■)(a\eirci)TipoL, napa t'l Kal kv t'ivi irapaXoyi^ovrai rbv aKovovra, voWdKis ol avTol eKeivoLS ovres. Tov adrov yap \6yov Set KaXeTv tov naph ravTo yivofievov 6 avTos Se Xoyos toTs fiev irapa Tr]v Xi^iv Toh Sk Trapb, to av/iPe^TjKbs ToTs Sk nap erepov So^eiev &.v eivai Siii, to /j,eTad)i- po/ievov^ eKaaTov /ztj o/j-oicos eivai SijXov. "Dairep ovv kv Toh naph TTjv ojMcovviiiav, ocnrep SoKeT Tpoiros evrjOecrTaTos eivai twv TTapaXoyLajiStv, to, fjikv Kal toTs Tvyovatv kari SrjXa (Kal yhp ol Xoyoi (TxeSbv ol yeXoToL TrdvTes eial irapa tt/v Xk^iv, olov dvrjp fv fiocov e/nrpoaOev re^eTai ; ovSeTepa, dXX oTTia-Qiv a[i(fxo. Kal KaOapbs 6 ^opias ; ov SfJTa' dwiK- TovrfKe yap Tbi> TrTW)(bv Kal tou wvovfievop*. ' Ap E'6apyo$] ov SfJTa, dXX AvoXXaiviSris. Tbv avTbv Se Tpairov Kal tw/ dXXcov a)(^eSbv ol nXeiaToi.^ Ta Se Kal tovs e/nretpoTaTovs (jtaiveTai XavQdveiv a-qfielov Se tovtcdv oti /j.d)(ovTai ttoXXukk irepl T&v ovo/idrcov, olov nSTepov TavTov arjiiaivti KaTO, iravrcov rb hv Kal to ev fj erepov. ToTs p-ev yap SoKeT TavTov (rrj/miveiv rb ov Kal to ev ol Se rbv Zrjvcovos Xoyov Kal HapfieviSov Xv- ov(n Sia rb TroXXa)(ws s irepl irdvrcov. " Eari 8k Sptfiij^ Xoyos octtis dnopetv iroieT ndXiara' SaKVfi yap oliTOS ndXia-ra. ' Airopia 8' ecrrt Sitttj, r) fikv kv tois (TvX- XeXoyicr/xevois, o ti dveXu tis twv eprnT-qfidTcav, r) S' kv rot? EAErXDN. 89 nominative in the other accusative. What (genitive) you have perception ofj that (accusative) you perceive. You have percep- tion of a stone (genitive); therefore you perceive of a stone (genitive). No. Of that (genitive) is of a stone, and the pre- miss waSj what you have perception of, not of that but, that (accusative) you perceive. Therefore you perceive — not of a stone but — a stone. These arguments then do not really prove solecism: why .they seem to do so, and how they are to be solved, is plain from what has been said*. XXXIII. It must be observed that in some arguments it is easy, in others difficult, to detect what and wherein is the fallacy, even when the arguments are identical. Arguments may be called identical when they depend on the same principle or belong to the same class. An identical argument may by one be referred to the head of equivocation ; by another to the equation of subject and accident, by another to another prin- ciple, because in its successive application to different spheres the principle is not equally patent or disguised. For instance, fallacies of ambiguity are supposed to be the easiest of detec- tion^, and some are obvious to the dullest, for almost all repar- tees and ridiculous turns depend on this principle 3. Thus : Down stairs a man tumbled (carried) — a chair. — ^Whither are you bound? (Where do you fasten the sails when you take them in?) To the yard arm. — Which cow will calve before (the other) ? Neither : both behind. — Is it a set (pure) Boreas ? No : he has killed a beggar. — Who was the purchaser ? Evar- chus ? No : ApoUonides (extravagant) : and so on. Others even the acutest fail to detect. A proof of this is the number of controversies that depend on words; for instance, on the ambiguity of Unity, and Being. Some suppose these tenns to be univocal ; others solve the arguments of Zeno and Parme- nides by shewing them to be equivocal. In the same way fallacies that depend on the equation of subject and accident and the other principles are sometimes easy sometimes hard of detec- tion. The classification, too, of a fallacy, and the decision whether an argument is fallacious or not, vary in difficulty. The cleverest argument is that which causes most doubt and embarrassment. Doubt is of two kinds : in dialectic reasoning we doubt which proposition is false ; in eristic reasoning we 90 HE PI IOv 6 Xoyoy /jLeTariOefiivrjs'' rrjs dvTi(f>dae(os airavras ofioiaus f^ei Toiis ovWoyLO-fiovs' del yap e^ kvSo^aav 6/j.oims ivSo^ov dvaip-qa-a ^ Karaa-Kevda-ei, Sioirep dnopeiy dvayKoiov. MakLora fuv oSv 6 TOLOVTOS SpLfivs, 6 k^ taov to crvfnrkpaafia troimv rotr kpwrrj- fiacri, SevTepos S' 6 k^ airdvT(ov dp,0L(ov ovtos - yap 6/j.oims noi'qa-et. dnopeiv ottoiov tSiv kpcoTrj/iaTcov dyaipereov. Tovro Se )(^a\eTr6v dvaiperkov plkv ydp, o tl 8 dvaiperkov, dSrjXov. T&v S kpuTTiKwv SpifivTaros fikv 6 npSiTov ei6i>s dSijXos iron- pov avXXeXoyicTTai fj oil, Kal TTOTepoy wapa ylrevSos ^ Siaipeaiv kcTTiv ri Xvaris, SeuTepos Se tS>v dXXwv 6 S^Xos /lev otl irapa Siaipecnv tj dvaipeaiv kari, /ifj ^avepbs S a>v Sea tivos t5>v r/pcorrjuevrnv dvaipeaiv fj SLalpecnv XvTeos kariv, dXXa, irorepov avTT] irapd to avfnrepa(r/j.a fj irapd Ti tS>v epayrrmdrcov kariv. ' EvioTe fiev oSv 6 jirj llTIKDN fidrcov, in wpos ri \pria-Liioi rravres ela-lv ot toiovtol Xoyot, Kal nepl diroKpia-eoos dirXm re irda-rjs Kal 7ra>s Xvriov tovs \6yovi Kal TOVS a-oXoiKia-jiovs, eipifcrSa) rrepl anavTCov r]fuv Tavrd. AoLTTOv Se irepl r^s e^ dpy^fis vpoBecrecos dvafivrjo-aaiv dnuv Ti Ppa-)(y TTepl avrfjs Kal reXos ewideTvai toTs eipr]fj.ivoL5. HpoeLXSfieOa jiev ovv ebpeiv S'dya/j.iv riva avXXoyis ov fiovov neTpav Svvarai Xa^elv Sia- XeKriK&s dXXd Kal coy elScus, Sid rovro ov fiovov ro XevOev epyov vireQeneQa rfjs irpayfiareias, to Xoyov Svvaadai Xa^eiv, aXXd Kal oircos Xoyov inreyovres v irapaXoyicr/imv SieXrj- XvOafiev, wamep elpiJKafiev ijSrj irporepov. "On fiev ovv e^ei reXos iKav&s & wpoeiXopieOa, avep6v. Aei 5' rifids /ifj XeXrjOevai to crvp.^e^rjKos irepl ravTrfv Trjv irpayiiareiav. Tmv ydp eiipiaKO/iivcov dwdvrwv rd ftev irap irepcov Xr]^6ivra irporepov neTTovrj/ieva Kard fiepos kmSeSmKev inrb tcov irapaXa^ovreov varepov rd S' e^ V7rap\fjs evpicrKo- fieva jJLiKpdv ro irpwrov eiriSoaiv Xaji^dveiv eicoOe, ^r/cripai^ repav /levroi ttoXXS rfjs varepov eK rovrcov av^rjorems. /Me- yiarov ydp ta-cos dpy(^ iravros, Scrirep Xiyerai' Sib Kal \aXe- wSrarov ocrm ydp Kpdna-rov rfj Svvdfiei, roaovrm p.iKpoTaTov hv rS jxeyeOei \aXeTrdyrar6v ecrnv 6(p6rjvai. Tavrrjs ^ eiprj- /levrjs ^aov rb rrpoa-nOevai Kal avvav^eiv rb Xonrov kanv orrep Kal irepl roi/s ^rjropiKods Xoyovs a-v/i^e^riKe, a)(eSov Si EAErXQN. 93 mentation^ the mode of answering and solving confutations and solecisms, have been successively examined* We may now recal to mind our original design and, with a few brief observations, bring our treatise to a close. Our aim was the invention of a method of reasoning on any problem from the most probable premisses that can be found *. This is the proper function of Dialectic and Pirastie. But it arrogates a further province from its vicinity to Sophistic, professing not only to test knowledge with the resources of Dialectic, but also to maintain any thesis with the infallibility of science. Besides, therefore, the above-named function, the examination of pretensions to knowledge, we included in the faculty we were investigating the power of defending any thesis by probable premisses without self-contradiction 3. The reason is what we mentioned before*, as may be seen from the fact that Socrates only questioned and never answered, because he con- fessed ignorance. We indicated the number of problems ^ and the sources or repertories of proofs, the right mode of question- ing and arrangement 7, the right mode of answering and solu- tion, and the other matters pertaining to the system; and we afterwards treated, as was just remarked, of paralogism. The task, then, which we undertook is completed. A fact, however, in the history of this art is worthy of notice. Inventions are either the final shaping of what has been partly ■elaborated by others, or they are original discoveries and but roughly shaped. The latter are the more important. The first step, according to the proverb, is the grand thing and the most diflScult; for first beginnings are as small and inconspicuous as 94 HEPI IO0IITIKON Kat irepl rocs dWas Trdaas rixi^as. Ot jikv yap ray apxati eiipovTes iravTeXms enl fiiKpov ti Trporjyayov ol 8e vvv eiSo- Kifiovvres irapaXa^ovres irapa iroWZv oiov e/c SiaSoxfjs Karbt. fiepos npoayayovTcov ovtcds rjv^rJKacn, Tia-ias fiev nerb, Toiis TrpaiTovs, Qpaa-vfiayips Se /xera Tiaiau, QeoScopos Se fiera rovTov, Kal voWol ttoXX^ avvevrjvoxacn /liprj' Sionep ovSev Oav/jLacTTov ex^"' ''"' '"'^V^'^^ '''V" tIxi/tj)/. TavTrjs 8e rf/s npay- fiareias oil to fiev ^v rb S' ovk ^v Trpoe^eipyaa-fievoy, aXX' ovSev TravTe\S>s VTrfjpxev. Kal yap t&v irepl Tois kpKTTiKov^ Xoyovs jiLcrQapvovvTaiv ofjioia rt? rjv ^ iraiSevcris rfj Fopyiov irpayfiaTiia. Aoyovs yap ol fiev prjTopiKOvs ol 8e kpayrrjTiKovs kSiSoaav kKjiavQdveiv, eh ofiy TrXeta-rdKLS kjirriiTTeLv wri6r](rav eKarepoL rois aXXriXcoi/ Xoyovs. Aiowep rayeia fuv dreyvos S' riv rj SiSaaKaXia toTs /iav6dvova-i nap avTwv ov yap Teyvrji' dXXa TO, aTTo rfjs reyyrjs SiSovres waiSeveiv VTreXd/i^avov, axTirep &v ei tis kinaTriiirjv fiS>v fj tS>v ■qKpoap.evaiv epyov Toh jiev irapaXeXeififiefOLS ttjs (leOoSov a-vyyvw/iriv tok S" eipri/iivoLS iroXXfjv exeiv ydpiv. EAErXDN. 95 they are potent. When they are once accomplished the re- mainder is easily added or developed. Ihis was the history of rhetorical composition and of most other arts. The original inventors made but small progress. The great modern profes- sors inherited from their predecessors many successive improve- ments and added others. Tisias after the first inventors, Thra- symaehus after Tisias, Theodorus after Thrasymachus, and many others, contributed various portions. Accordingly, it is no wonder that the art has now a certain amplitude^. But the system I have expounded had not been partially, though, imper- fectly, elaborated by others : its very foundations had to be laid 9. The education given to their pupils by the paid teachers of Eristic was like that given by Grorgias to his pupils in Rhetoric. B-eady-made speeches^", oratorical or interrogatory, which were considered to cover the topics of the rival professors, were given to the pupil to be learnt by heart. The training accordingly was rapid but unscientific. Instead of art, the pro- ducts of art were communicated, and tbis was called education. One might as well have promised to communicate an art for protecting the feet, and, instead of teaching the art of shoe- making, have presented the learner with an assortment of shoes. This would be supplying his wants but not teaching him an art. But the teachers of rhetoric inherited many prin- ciples that had been long ascertained : dialectic had absolutely no traditional doctrines. Our researches were tentative, long, and troublesome. If, then, starting from nothing, the system bears a comparison with others that have been developed by division of labour in successive generations, candid criticism will be readier to commend it for the degree of completeness to which it has attained than to find fault with it for falling short of perfection. NOTES. CHAPTER I. 1] For the difference between a sophistic proof and a paralo- gism see ch. viii. 2] For the meaning of Ifis, compare Topica, 8. % : Upo(j)epov(n yap OTi Trj vyitla, kX&TTOvi ovti ayaBZ rrjs ive^Cas, jj.e'iCov KaKOV avrUeiTai, ttjv yap vdcrov /xeifoz; KaKov (IvaiTrjs Ka^t^Cas. '(Against the assumption that the greater evil is opposed to the greater good), they adduce the enstasis that health, a lesser good than bodily vigour, has a greater evil for its opposite ; for sick- ness is a greater evil than want of bodily vigour/ And Topica, 5- 7- Ofiot'ftjs l^f' larpos re irpbs to ttoltjtikos vyieCas elvai koI yup.- vacTTTis Tipbs TO TiotTjrtKos fvf^ias. ' The function of the gymnastic trainer is the production of bodily vigour, as the function of the physician is the production of health/ 3] ^v\eTiK&s. This seems an allusion to the choral exhibi- tions at Athens. Each tribe (0iiA?}),' through its choragus, furnished a chorus, and was emulous for its reputation, which depended on its evavbpta, i. e. amfidTav p,iye6os nal pdp-ri, the size and strength of the choristers, as well as their vocal powers, ei^avia. Xenophon, Mem. 3. 3. Ot ^vXeTai, therefore, implied in ^vKiTiK&s, are 01 ■}(opevTaC. 4] Kop,pM(TavTfs. In the Gorgias sophistic is said to be the counterpart or analogon of Kopp.a>TiKri, a fraudulent art, which by means of shape and colour and sleekness and dress counterfeits the beauty and good condition which are properly produced by gymnastic. Ko/ix/iUTtK?) is to yvp-vaaTiK-fi, and dv|f07rot?jriKrj is to laTpiKTj, as croipia-Tturi is to vop.o6e.Ti.Krj, or pr]TopiKr\ is to StKaoTtKTj. H 98 NOTES. Chap. I. 5] AiOdpyvpos, ' a compound of silver and lead ; or, vitrified lead collected in separating lead and silver.' lAddell and Scott. 6] We have a similar definition in Topica, 1. 1, where speech {k6yos) is made the genus : 'Eori hr] trvkkoyicrixos Koyos iv iS rediv- Toov Tiv&v hipov Ti T&p KSLixivuiv ff avdyKTfs avix^aCvfl. bia rmv Keiixevcov. 7] Understand after &v, not alu&v, hut eX.iy■)^mv. To'iros is here used for yieos, for, speaking properly, the to'ttos or ahia is TO. ovoixara, the eXeyxoi are 8ia tS>v ovofiarmv. 8] Ta TTpdyimra ^IpovTas, ' moving, manipulating, the ob- jects,' appears to he a metaphor derived from the phrase raj ^j/^ijyovs (pepeiv, which shortly follows. 9] Aoyos may mean an argument, or a proposition, or a defi- nition, or a circumlocution. It usually means an argument, but when in close antithesis to ovojxa it means a circumlocution or a complex, as opposed to a simple, term. 10] Ot aKovovres are the audience present at a controversy. See ch. viii, Ilap' oa-a yap ^aiverai roTs a.K(y6ov(Ti,v as ■tipmvqp.iva, iTv\\ekoyL(rdai, irapa ravra kSi» tu diroKpti/ofx^vb) 8dfetev. Also eh. XV, 'Ez'foTe yap oLovrai koL ovtoI SeScok^vui koi tois aKovovai ^alvovrai. On this point an unknown paraphrast, edited by Spengel, says the only thing that he says worth quoting : Oi yap aKpoaral Ir Tois 6taAe'fe(Ti KpiTal ttjs vlKr)S rois aymn^oiiivots KdOrjmai. ' The audience present at a controversy are the judges who decide which disputant is victorious.' This writer trans- forms some of Aristotle's cramped statements into very sonorous periods, hut is of no value as a commentator. 11] In ordinary Greek SoSj'ai \6yov is to render an account, Xafieiv \6yov to audit an account. In logical language 8owoi \6yov is the function of the answerer, Ka^elv \6yov of the ques- tioner. In ch. xxxiv. the former of these functions is said to be the more sophistical branch of dialectic, because the answerer pretends to science, which the questioner disclaims. In ch. xi. it is explained how the pirastic questioner, himself making no pretensions to knowledge, may be competent to ex- amine the knowledge and expose the ignorance of the answerer. Throughout the present treatise however, in accordance with the title, it is usually the questioner that is supposed to be the sophist, and the respondent who is the honest reasoner. Chap. I. NOTES. 99 12] AijvaiJ,is, capacityj is in the intellect; •npoaipecris, purpose, in the will. The antithesis between thest terms may throw light on what Aristotle conceived to be the relation between sophistic and dialectic : 'Opav be koI et ri t&v yjreicT&v ^ (pevKT&v els hivafiiv 17 ro bwarov IdriKev, oXov rdv oro^toTTJi' fj bidjSoXov rj K^iirTTiv Tov bvvapi.evov \A0pa to, aWorpia Kke-nreiv. OvSeis yap t&v elpr)\i.ev(ii>v tu Swaros etvai ti tovtcov toiovtos kiyerai' bvvarai p.ev yap /cal 6 6eos kcu, 6 cnrovbaios to, ^av\a bpav, a\V ovk ettri toiovtoi' iravTei yap 01 (j)avXoi Kara mpoaipecnv Xeyovrai. "En ■naa-a Swajiis T&v dtper&V (cat yap al t&v av\a TrpoTTeiv. . . , H 6( ti t&v iv 8t;o yiveciv ^ Tr\e(ov 6 avWoyiajj.bs f, ri Ik Towirraiv h bid tivcov TTpc&Tcav Koi aXrjd&v TTJs TTfjol avTo, yvdxreuis t7\v ap^^v €^A.?j^e. AtaAe/trtKos b\ mWoyitT^i b e^ evbo^cov o-uAXoytfo/;i€vos. . . . 'Epiorixos 8' lort av\- Aoyio-/Ltos d Ik (jjaivoixevciiv fvbo^av jxr) ovTa>v be, koI 6 1^ evbo^cav rj aivo[i,ivmv ivbS^uiv (f)aLv6fj,evos .... 6 ^ev ovv Trporepos t&v prjBevrav ipUTTiK&v avWoyitrjx&v koX (TvWoyuTjws Xiyi(j6u>, 6 8e Xomos Ipt- erepots hxpi^ia-Tepov, irpbs be rrjv TtpoKeitiivi^v jxidohov 01 avToX tottoi xP')"''- iwi. Topica, 7- 3- But in the Analytica Posterior a the rules for estabhshing a definition are not given under the form of loci, and the words iv hipois may refer to some other treatise. The Sophistici Elenchi was written before the Hermeneutiea, which refers to it in ch. 11, under the name of to, mriKd. The seven- teenth chapter of the second book of the Analytica Priora refers to the Sophistici Elenchi under the name of to, Tomxti. This chapter therefore, and probably others in the second book, must have been added subsequently, as the mass of the treatise was written before the Sophistici Elenchi. The Rhetoric was written after the Topica and Analytica Priora, which it refers to in the second chapter of the first book. It speaks of to. epLcrriKd in the twenty-fifth chapter of the second book, but, to judge from the inferior precision with which it handles the subject of fallacies, was probably written before the Sophistici Elenchi. CHAPTER IV. 1] Verbal fallacies of course vanish in translation. In the following translations much licence has been taken, and the result is but lame. 104 NOTES. Chap. IV. rpanixaTiKiq is defined to be the art of reading and writing : eTsi(TTri)xr\ tov yp6ri\rai to vitoyopevOev koI tov avayv&vai. Topica, 6.5. The teacher was said to aTro(nofj,aTlCeiv, or {mayopeveiv, when he dictated a word to be written or spelt. The boy who caught and understood the word, that is, who could exactly appreciate a complex sound and decompose it into its letters or elementary sounds, was said in the language of the school to navOdveiv. He was ypap-p-ariKos, master of alphabetic science. The example is taken from the Euthydemus of Plato (§§ ia-i8): it may be thus analysed. Suppose that the thesis to be confuted is & nav- Bdvoiv avemcrTriiJLcov. We have two syllogisms : — 6 p,av6A.vmv to. a/noGTOiiaTi^6p,eva 6 jxavB6,vatv to. aTroa-ToixaTi^ofjteva 6 [xavBdvcov Major, Minor, ypap,p,ari,Kos' Conclusion, Again : p.av6dvii: ypajxixanKos. Major, 6 ypapLfiariKos fm(rTrip,(ov Minor, 6 fxavOdvuv ypaixp-ariKos' Conclusion, . ■ . 6 p,avddvcov eiri.a-T'qp.tov. The minor term (fjtavddvwv) is ambiguous. TO, biOVTa TO KUKa TO, KaKa ayaOd' hiovTa' ayadd. 2] Major, Minor, Conclusion, The middle term is ambiguous. 3] Major, Bajrep dvia-Taro Minor, 6 Kadii]p.ivos Conclusion, .•. 6 KaOrjpAvos The minor term is ambiguous. Major, 8a-7rep vyid^ero Minor, 6 Kdp,vmv Conclusion, .'. 6 KdfW(av The minor term is ambiguous. Whately is inclined to rest the claims of logic to considera- tion on the services she performs in teaching us the seat of the ambiguities on which fallacies are built. This, he repeatedly informs us, is the middle term. The above examples may shew on how precarious a foundation he rests the claims of logic. dvla-raro' ea-TTjKf. vyiaivef vyidCero' vyiaivfi. Chap. IV. NOTES. 105 4] Read uytdf eroi. In the next line we have MS. authority for omitting the article before irpoTepov. « 5] Supplying a minor we obtain this fallacy : — MajoTj Toiro o tis yivduKU yiv^cTxei' Minor, at ypaipal tovto S tis yivJxTKW Conclusion, . • . at ypa(\icu yiv(&(rKOV(n. The major premiss is taken to mean, aSrai &s ny yivdcTKei yiv^cTKOvcn. It really means, tIs yiV(otrK€L TOVTas hs ywdxTML. There are therefore more than three terms, or we may say that the middle is ambiguous. For a justification of the employment of the feminine and masculine pronouns in the analysis of this and the following fallacies, see eh. xxxii. 6] Major, tovto h Spa tis 6p^' Minor, 6 Kiatv tovto h opa Tts" Conclusion, .•. 6 idiav opa. The major premiss is ambiguous. It really means, tovtov, hv opa ns, opa : but it is taken to mean, o^tos, ov opa ris, opa. 7] Major, to (jifis elvai, ovtos hp (TV )v yp6.p.iw.Ta &iiep iiav- Q&vei eTiiarirai. 11] Major, Two and three (distributively) are even and odd; Minor, Two and three (collectively) are five ; Conclusion, .-. Five is even and odd. Whately adds : — Major, All the angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles ; Minor, J 5 C is an angle of a triangle ; Conclusion, .• . ABC is equal to two right angles. How does the fallacy of conjunction differ from the fallacy of disjunction? Whately says, when the middle is taken collec- tively in the major premiss and distributively in the minor, we have the fallacy of division; when it is taken distributively in the major and collectively in the minor, the fallacy of compo- sition. So when some other term and not the middle is am- biguous, we might say the fallacy was one of division or com- position, according as the term was taken collectively in the premiss and distributively in the conclusion or vice versa. Thus, Major, Three and two are two numbers ; Minor, Three and two are five ; Conclusion, . • . Five is two numbers ; would be a fallacy of composition ; whereas, Major, Five is one number; Minor, Three and two are five ; Conclusion, . • . Three and two are one number ; would be a fallacy of division. This is intelligible, but cannot have been Aristotle's view, for his first example of division would, according to Whately's test, be a fallacy of composition. The Chap. V. NOTES. 107 point is hardly worth deciding ; for the fallacies in diction may well be regarded as a single species^ or «t the utmost as two, homonymia and figura dictionis. 12] Buhle, comparing Terence's line in the Andria, Scis. Feci ex servo ut esses libertus mihi, infers that this is a line of Menander. But if our chronologies are correct and this line was quoted by Aristotle, it was older than Menander. For we are told that Aristotle died in B.C. 3355, and that Menander's first play was acted when he was still an ephebus, i. e. between 18 and 30 years old, in B.C. 331. 13] To find any fault (ajxafiTla) in Homer was thought to be a paradox, and adverse criticisms on him seem to have been considered a branch of dialectic or eristic. The critic treated the poet as pirastic treats the pretenders to other arts and sciences, that is, he attempted to prove by the poet's utterances that he was not a master of the art which he professed. Though, if such criticisms were, as they ought to have been, based on principles peculiar to esthetic science, when false, they would have been pseudographic (see chap, xi), not sophistic. Perhaps, however, the person confuted was not the poet, but the rhapsode, who often attributed universal science to Homer. In the Poetics, chap. 35, five loci («i8rj) of such criticisms (eTrtrtfujo-ets, vpo^k^- Hara) are given, and twelve solutions. Some of the criticisms are referred to the sophistic loci of accentuation, homonymia, amphi- boha, division, ignoratio elenchi ; but the text is very corrupt. 14] The defence of these two passages by a change of accen- tuation is attributed in the Poetics to Hippias of Thasos. The first occurs in Iliad 23. 338 ; the second does not occur in Aga- memnon's dream, but in Iliad ai. 297, where Achilles is encou- raged by Poseidon. We may infer that our present form of the text had not been established in the time of Aristotle. IS] See Topica, 1.9. CHAPTER V. 1] 2tijx^e;8)jKos here is opposed to ovcrCa, and means not only what is usually called accident, but every predicate except defi- nition or the whole essence of the subject. See ch. xxiv, where the fallacy of accidens is discussed: Movois yap rois Kara ttjv 108 NOTES. Chap. V. ova-Cav adLa6pois koI kv ovKpdTr)s &vdpmTror Minor, KopCa-Kos ov StoKptirjjs" Conclusion, . ■ . Kopla-Kos ovk avOpmnoi. We have an illicit process of the major. In the Euthydemus it is stated that Socrates is the son of Sophroniscus, and that Patrocles is the son of the mother of Socrates by her former husband, Chaeredemus. The sophist then attempts to prove that either Sophroniscus or Chseredemus is not a father. Oi/coi/z', rj 8' os, ^repos fjv Xatp^8r;/xos tov ■narpos; Tovixov y , etprjv ky(L. ^Ap' ovv TTarrjp rjv irepos i)v -narpos ; ri av d 6 avrbs tu kCda; A^boiKa jJiiv fyaiy, ^<^r]V, firj v xpijcov ov xpva-os ei; 'EtrTt raCro. Ovkovv koI 6 Xaipi- Srjixos, i(t>ri, ^repos &>v Trarpos ovk &v Tiarrip etr). "EoiKev, rjv f ky&, ov Trarfip eTvai. El yap 877 irov, ^(prj, irarrip eariv 6 Xaipehrifios, vTSoka^utv 6 EvdvbrjfjLos, irdXtv av 6 'Sica^povLcrKos trtpos &)V Ttarpos ov •narrip ecniv, ware av, S ^(iKpares, dirdTotp el. Euthydemus, § 6a. 'Chaeredemus then, said he, was other than a father? — Than mine, said I. — Then how could he be a father if he was other than a father? Are you the same as a stone? — I am afraid you will prove me so, said I, but I believe I am not. — Then you are other than a stone ? — Yes. — Being other than a stone you are not a stone ; and being other than gold you are not gold ? — True. — Chaeredemus, therefore, being other than a father is not a father. — It seems he is not a father.^At least if Chaeredemus Chap. V. NOTES. 109 is a father, said Euthydemus breaking in, Sophroniseus being other than a father is no father, and ydu, my Socrates, are fatherless.' 4] In the Topica it is given as a dialectic maxim that when a qualified assertion is true, the unqualified assertion is true; although it is allowed that the principle has numerous excep- tions. Toi> avTOV be rpo-nov a-KeTrriov Kcii im tov Kara tl koa, irore /cat TToC" ei yap Kara tl evS^x^'""'; '^"'■^ aTrX&s ei'Stxerot. . . . "EvarTacris oTi Kara n liev elcri (pvcru tr-novhaioi, otov k\ev6epioi r\ (juxppovLKoC, airk&s be ovk elal (j>v is afiirmed or denied of the one it is equally (ofiolas) afiSrmed or denied of the other, we shall have valid reasoning from a false assumption. Chap.VI. notes. Ill CHAPTER VI.* 1] Substantive names (nomina siibstantiva) properly and primarily belong to individual substances. Language extends them^ secondly, to the genera of these substances ; and, thirdly, to attributes (e. g. to-oVr/s, dvKroVjjs) . Realism ascribes substantive existence to the second of these classes, if not to the third. 2] Mill says : " Logic postulates to be allowed to assert the same meaning in any words which will express it — We require the liberty of substituting for a given assertion the same asser- tion in different words — We require the liberty of exchanging a proposition for any other that is equipollent with it.^^ Criticisms on Sir W. Hamilton, ch. 31. This postulate he identifies with the axiom or principle of identity, which he thus expresses : " Whatever is true in one form of words is true in every other form of words which conveys the same meaning.''^ The dialectic rule is not inconsistent with this, but only imposes on the dis- putant before he changes a formula the necessity of obtaining the assent of the respondent. A respondent could not refuse his assent to any reasonable proposition without exposing himself to the charge of hva-Kokia, perverse obstructiveness, which was equivalent to defeat. If, however, the respondent was prepared to brave the charge of Si/o-icoAta, the conditions imposed on the opponent must have sometimes enabled the respondent to avoid a formal confutation. Ov yap Ttpos rbv If m Koyov f/ diro'8eif is dWa Trpos Tov iv rfi \j/vxfi, eiiel ovbi ij.4Tpr)V d\A' ^ Kara avfi^e^rjKOS. "Ho-t ovK &v etjj fv dyea)/xeTf»j7-ois (Kpirais) Tiepl yeaj/xerptas biaXtKriov, Xrjcrei yap 6 ivbexop^^vov ye Kara i:ivTipeiv oKki^kav, X<»p« kkap^&viTo. Nw 8^ Ka66\ov beUvvTac ov yap § ypapp,al ri if &pidpol virrjpxev, aKk' fj Tobl h KaOokov vnoTidevTai. VTrapxetv. Ata TOVTO ovb'' av rts bd^y Kaff emaTov to TpCyutvov uTtobeiiei ^ piq ^ eT^po on bijo opdas ex«' ^laiTTov, to laoTskevpov x^jp's koL to aKakr\- vov Kal TO la-oo-Kekh, oiiwo) oT8e to Tpiyaivov on bvo 6p6als Xaov d prj Tov tro^idTiKov Tpoirov, ovb^ Ka66kov rpiymvov, ovb' d p.r)biv iffTi Tsaph Tama Tpiyodi/ov hepov ov yap § rpCycovov otbev, ovbi ■nav rpt- yccvov dAA.' rj Kar api6p.6v Kar €i8os 8' ov tiav, k. The slightest con- sideration will suffice to shew that the two classes of fallacy, in dictione and extra dictionem, do not correspond to sins against the two elements of confutation, contradiction and proof. Of the class in dictione, reasonings involving homonymia and am- phibolia may, indeed, be conclusive when the ambiguity lies in the extremes, but must be inconclusive when it lies in the middle term. Of the class extra dictionem, the fallacies non causa pro causa and ignoratio elenchi fail rather in contradiction than in proof. Aristotle has elsewhere spoken correctly. In the beginning of this chapter he implies (el /^eAXet eXeyxps rj itv\- \oyi(rp.bs eaea-dai) that some of the fallacies in dictione are devoid of proof as well as of confutation (contradiction). In ch. xix. he says that homonymia and amphibolia may afiect either the premisses or the conclusion, i. e. either the proof or the contra- I a 116 NOTES. Chap. VI. diction. And in ch. x. he gives an instance of homonymia (epic poems are a plane figure for they are a circle) affecting the middle term, that is^ the proof: and observes that figura dicti- onis may be treated as faulty either in the proof or in the' con- tradiction. In ch. XXV. he seems to say that secundum quid only fails in the contradiction, but it is clear that it may fail either in the contradiction or in the sequence. We may observe that we only give a semblance of unity to the theory of fallacies by lumping them all together under the definition of confutation, for the elements of that definition are obtained by no systematic subdivision, and form, as far as appears, a purely arbitrary and incoherent agglomeration. CHAPTER VII. 1] A man might misplace his accents and yet be understood in Greek society, unless the misplacement produced ambiguity. 2] 'Eir^oraTai. This must be wrong. We should read woiei, or ireWei, or ^Tticnra, or emo-Trarai, or something equivalent. In support of the last conjecture compare, ^Ap" ovv avro yiyvda-Koiv avix^Tis, 7] ere otov pv)xrj tis virb tov koyov crvviiOurixivov avviiriima- craro irpoi to za)(y TJ(Tai ; Sophistes, 46. ' Have you any good reason for your assent, or has the current of the language to which you are accustomed hurried you along into an ill- considered admission ?' Aristotle is thinking of realism or the theory of ideas, which he says, ch. xxii, is founded on this fallacy. 3] Reasoning to a certain extent is possible, as we see in brutes, without words. But the development of language must have been accompanied by a great increase of reasoning power. Thenceforth in all reasoning there are two parallel trains, the train of images and the train of words. When the train of words precedes it awakes the train of images, if the words are imitative, by the associative law of similarity. If the sounds are not imitative, but interjectional, that is, produced according to some physiological law by the action of the organs of sensa- tion on the organs of expression, they afterwards suggest the sensations that produced them by the associative law of eon- Chap.VII. notes. 117 tiguity in place and time. But in rapid thought the images are very imperfectly excited. The mind^ emboldened by habit, ventures to trust herself to the train of words through which she can pass with great celerity without stopping to realize them by images which would encumber her and clog her motion. Rapid and powerful reasoningj then, takes place chiefly by the verbal train. Reasoning without words is more likely to occur in meditation than in conversation. See this subject discussed by Mill, Examination of Sir W. Hamilton's PJdlosophy, ch. 17. 4] This sentence shews the afiinity, in Aristotle's mind, be- tween the fallacies ignoratio elenchi and secundum quid (see note 3 to ch. viii). In this treatise (see ch. v, vi, vii) e\- Aet\/fts is always used to denote ignoratio elenchi. In the Rhetoric, where the fallacies are enumerated, ignoratio elenchi is not mentioned and eXAeii/rts designates the fallacy secundum quid. 'AWos {totios) irapa ttjv fk\ei\jnv rod -nore nal ir&s' olov on bLKaC(os 'Ake^avbpos el\.afie ttjv 'EXfvrjv, aipecris yap avrfj iboOri Trapa Tov TTarpos. Ov yap ael tarais aWa to up&Tov nal yap 6 ■naT7]p fxexpi ToijTov Kvpios. *H e? ns (pairj to tvttthv tovs e\iv0€povs vfipiv elvaf ov yap ttAvtcds, dA.A' orav apx[l X^'^P^" &blKaiv. Rhetoric, 2,. 24. ' Another class of fallacies depends on the omission of limitations in time or manner : as the argument that Helen had a right to elope with Paris because her father granted her the option of her husband. But the option granted was not perpetual but one that determined with her first choice, for this was all her father had the power to grant. So the statement, that striking a freeman is an assault, requires limita- tion : for it is only an assault in him who strikes first.' The moderns have created a distinction by confining ignoratio elenchi to valid arguments with irrelevant conclusions, i. e. by confining the omitted limitations to such as afieet the contradiction. 5] This chapter explains why the solution (\vcns) of an inconclusive or illogical confutation is called Statpeerts (distinc- tion). A conclusive or lo^cal confutation can only be solved by shewing that one of the premisses is false {avaipea-isj . If this is shewn by certain simple topics, it is called enstasis; if by other topics, antisyllogism. Solution, then, is either enstasis, which includes biaCpea-is and one branch of avaipecns, or anti- syllogism, which is the other branch of avaCpea-is. Antisyllo- 118 NOTES. Chap. VII. gism, being a species of solution, is the disproof of one of the opponent's premisses, not of his conclusion j for it would be an abuse of language to call the disproof of a conclusion a solution of the argument supporting that conclusion. CHAPTER VIII. 1] Eristic proof is either inconclusive or contains a false pre- miss. But it is not every false premiss that makes a proof eristic. If the premiss, though unscientific, is a special proposi- tion, referring exclusively to a particular subject-matter, the proof is dialectic. Even the general propositions that charac- terize dialectic, the topical maxims, must be accepted with many limitations and exceptions, for dolus latet in generalibus ; and if they are applied without these limitations and exceptions they are open to enstasis, and the conclusion is false, but stiU, it appears, the proof is regarded as dialectic. The basis of genuine probability in these propositions saves their inaccurate applica- tion from the stigma of sophistry. The false maxims that constitute a proof eristic, that is, radically bad or vicious in principle, are thirteen false propositions corresponding to the thirteen fallacies. Ov yap irav to cj^aivonevov evbo^ov km, Io-tiv fvbo^ov. Ovdiv yap t&v Kiyoixivtov ^vho^av eTrnroXaiov iyii iravre- \&s TTjv (pavracriav, KaOAirep Ttepl ras r&v ipurnK&v \6ya>v apya^ (rvp,j34pr]Kev ex^iv, IJapaxprJua yap Kal &)s etti to ttoXt) tois koi juiKpa avvopav bwafievois (cardtSrjXos Iv avrois fj tov -^fybovs scttI v tlv&v (rv\koyip.evoLS hrjKov a)s fb Trddos toSto 81' ofioioTriTUiv Tiv&i> elmppvr), — TLyviTai yovv ovrtos. — 'Eariv ovv oirus TiyviKOS Icrrat fiera/3t/3a- iiiv Kara (rp,LKpov 8ia t&v op-oiOTriTWV, ano tov ovros exacrrore ewt 122 NOTES. Chap. IX. Tovvavrlov aitayatv, ^ avrhs tovto bia^evyew, 6 firj iyvapiKm & tanv 'iKacTTov r&v ovTotv ; — Ov firi wore. — Aoymv &pa rexyv^i ^ kraipf, 6 Trjv akrjOfLav im] flbiis, bo^as be Tfdr]pevK and belongs to the dialectician. Accordingly Aristotle bases dialectic on the definition of genuine confutation (a\r)6ris ekey- Xos), and makes solution proceed by division and discrimination (6iotpe(7ts). But, in addition to this, didactic requires similar definitions and divisions of the Ibiai. apxai. See Appendix E on the limits of pirastic. 3] The common sources of probable proof are enumerated in the Topica. 4] Does e)(oij.ev bi nap' oirocra yivovrai mean that the enstasis is derived from the same topics as the proof; or does it mean that in some lost chapters the varieties of enstasis had been examined? A phrase of the Rhetoric seems to establish the latter view : Ai 8' ei'o-Tcto-eis (jyepovrai, KaOdirep iv rois Towt/coty, Terpax&s. Rhet. 2. 25. 5] Kai Tovs (jjaivoixevovs [eXeyxofs] is connected, after a long parenthesis, with tov 6' ex t&v koiv5>v koX vno firjbepilav Ttxvqv [ikeyxov] r&v biakeKTiK&p [fcrrl Oeapeiv]. Chap. X. NOTES. 123 CHAPTER X. 1] Of the name of the theorist now criticised, and the precise nature of his theory, we have no information ; and without this information it is diflScult to decide whether Aristotle^s argu- ments are conclusive, and what is their precise drift. If we may trust a partly unintelligible fragment of Eudemus quoted by Simplicius, the theorist criticised in this chapter is no other than Plato himself : "Eo-rt Se, is lotKe, to bioplCeiv ^Kaa-rov TTocrax&s \4yeTai fi^ya Trpos aki^deiav. YIXAtohv re yap eicrayay^v to bicrabv TtoWas aTTopCas ehvae, ■npay\xaTu>v S>v vvv ol (TO(f>L(rTai KaTa^eiyovaiv mairep em ra ei'Sij, /cat irpos tovtois Tovvoixa t&v \6yaiv a(^(ltpiare. Simplicius on Phys. Ausc. i. 3. 'To distinguish the various meanings of equivocal terms is a great step in speculation. For Plato solved many difficulties by introducing the doctrine of various meanings and banished words from proof [distin- guished reasoning addressed to the word from reasoning addressed to the thought ?].^ But it would be rash to place much reliance on a corrupt fragment, and it would be strange if Aristotle spoke of Plato as ' certain persons.' The theorist seems to have hit, somewhat vaguely, upon the distinction between word-thinking and object-thinking, and to have held that the source of all error is word-thinking. The substance of Aristotle's criticism seems to be this : — (i) The trains of word- thinking and object-thinking are parallel : the same ratiocination may belong to both trains : and it is impossible to say when it belongs to each. But if the trains constituted two classes of reasoning, they ought to be contradistinguished and mutually exclusive. (2) Thought requires some further limitation to express object- thinking. All word-thinking is thinking. The expres- sion, addressed to the thought, therefore, is insufficient to exclude word-thinking. (3) The fact of being addressed to the thought is only an ex- ternal relation of an argument, its relation to the respon- dent. But the relations of a thing may vary by the change of its correlatives, while the thing itself remains unchanged. They are its most extrinsic and accidental attributes, and cannot form the principle of its subdivision. 124 NOTES. Chap. X. But, it may be answered, are there not some arguments whose essential nature is such that they cannot be represented by a train of object-thought ? Yes : and these are recognized under the head of fallacies in diction. But there is another class of reasonings, independent of diction, and therefore belonging pos- sibly to the train of object-thinking, which are yet fallacious. 2] So read for oloixtvos kpatTwrOai e dai Tipos TO yCvfcrOai. /car' avTO to Trpayna Koi fijj irpos TO ovofia Tovs otSe to Tptymvov oti b'do opBais, (I jxri rhv (TocfuaTLKOV rpoTtov, ovbi KaSokov Tpiyaivov, ovb' tl fxr\6iv kern Ttapa TavTa Tpiyavov ^T€pov. Ov yap fj rplyavov olbev. An. Post. I. 5. 'If one were to prove in detail of each species of triangle, equilateral, scalene, isosceles, the equality of their interior angles to two right angles, he might exhaust the possible cases, but his predicate would not be essential and commensurate, and he would only have a sophistical science.' Chap. XL NOTES. 129 To complete the statement of Aristotle's view, it should be added that essential propositions are* those whose predicate cannot be defined without paming the subject, or whose subject cannot be defined without naming the predicate. KaO' avra be {\4y(i>) oaa vmpxeL re ev rm tL etTTiv, olov Tpiydva ypaixfxri koX ypafxfxrf (TTiynr], r/ yap ovcria avr&v l/c Tovrtav eari, Koi ev 70) K6yio Tm KiyovTi tI ecrriv evvTtAp\ei,' koI o(tols t&v ewnapxovTmv avroii avTCL ev T(p Koyia evvna.p)(pvv awAdls e-nLa-TrjToiiv KaO' avra ovtios, as evvirdp^^eiv tols KaT-qyopovixevois r] evvnApxecrBai, bC ami. Te lort koX If av6.yKi]s- An. Post. T. 4. 'An attribute is essential that enters into the conception of the subject, as line enters into the conception of triangle and point of line. It helps to compose the essence of the subject, and is found in its defi- nition. Or, it is an attribute in whose definition the subject is contained. Straight and curved are attributes of line ; and even and odd, prime and compound, square and scalene, of number ; and we cannot define them without mentioning the subjects they attach to, line and number In the essential premisses, then, of absolute science, where the subject is either contained in the definition of the predicate, or contains the- predicate in its own definition, the essence of the terms is the cause of their con- junction and the conjunction is necessary.' A modern logician might admit that, as a condition of science, we must have pro- positions of causation, and that in causal propositions the ante- cedent and consequent terms must bear to one another a certain definite relation ; but he would insist that the test of this rela- tion was not definition, but the inductive methods of agreement and difierence. To reconcile these doctrines it would be neces- sary to assert that these methods are methods of definition. But even then a difierence would remain. For the modern logician would be satisfied by an objective relation, discovered by expe- rience : while Aristotle seems further to require a subjective rela- tion, viz. such that it should be impossible to conceive one of the terms without at the same time conceiving the other. 3] I do not know what distinction is intended between ^ev- e: 130 NOTES. Chap. XL boyp6,((>r)na and \}/evboyp6.(f)r]iJ,a itepl &\r)6is, unless it is that of art and science. It is evident that the quadrature of the circle by lunules was not the method of Hippocrates, as is generally supposed. His method was what Aristotle elsewhere calls the method of segments (see Appendix F). The problem of squaring the circle, i. e. of finding a square whose area shall equal that of a given circle, long occupied the scientific world; and, like the problem of perpetual motion, was a favourite arena of the unscientific long after the scientific had pronounced it insoluble. Modern mathematicians are agreed that it cannot be solved by arithmetic or geometry, the only methods of the ancients, and requires the method of infinitesimals. See an article on the quadrature of the circle, by De Morgan, in the National Encyclopedia. Aristotle seems to have suspected it was insoluble from his expression, Et koI TtrpayavC^eTal 6 kvkXos'. in the Categories he asserts that it had not been solved in his day : 'Ert to fiev eTriarrjTov avaipediv crwavaipei ttjv eiriar^jitjji', ^ be eincrT'^ixri to ^irtorjjror ov crvvavaipei olov Koi 6 tov kj^kAou TeTpaya>vi(Tij,6i el ye i(TTiv, (TtKTTrjfiri fiiv avrov ovk Icruv ovhitco, aMs 6^ fTiKTTTjTov luTiv. Cat. 7. 'Without a knowable there can be no knowledge, but without knowledge there may be a knowable : if, for instance, the quadrature of the circle is pos- sible, it is knowable, though at present it is not known.' 4] Kara to Ttpayp.a here means morak. than it did in the beginning of the chapter, where its force was limited by the words ret koivL There it meant, necessarily connected with a subject, though not coextensive with it. Here it is equivalent to Kara rqv olKilav jxiOobov, and means coextensive, or commen- surate, with a given sphere. 5] So read, as the sense requires, for tov yf(afj.eTpr)v. 6] Here p.iv is followed by no corresponding clause, and the text is doubtless corrupt. We might add, after bijKoi', aKKa Kh ■nepl Th yecoixeTpiKo. etr], or we might read, 6 6' v-nb Tfjv haheKTinTiv. Ufpl (lAvToi TaWa ort ipia-TtKos Icrn, brjKov, or something equivalent. In the first case rSWa would mean to, Kotvd, in the second case it would mean to, tbia, or, rather, to yta/jifTpiKd. In any case the drift is certain, viz. that the same problem, e. g. the quadrature of the circle, may be handled either in a sophism or in a pseudo- grapheme. Chap. XL NOTES. 131 7] 'ApixoTTiLv, or iv yeveaiv ipKTTiKos. For vuep^awovrmv [transcendent] Aristotle would have said, iXiTa^awovTcav. "D.m'' rj avK&s av&yKT] ro avTo thai yevos ^ mj, ei fiiKKei rj cntobei^Ls i^era^alveiv. An. Post. I. 7. 'Two sub- jects must be the same in species or genus, if a demonstration can be transferred from the one to the other.' 8] Kadokov must be taken in the sense in which it is de- scribed in the Analytic, as equivalent to KaB" avro, and therefore 6 KaOoKov will mean 6 eic r&v lUmv apx&v airobeiKTLKos. Even the philosopher (6 (piXoa-o^os) who has the most comprehensive sphere must deal with his problems commensurately and essen- tially (Ka96\ov, Kad^ avTo), and therefore is limited in his pre- misses and conclusions. Unlike the dialectician, he has nothing to say to geometrical problems. 9j Tas 6' avTas ap^as anAvrav etvai t&v avWoyio-pMV abvvaTov. Erepat yop itokK&v rw yivu al ap^ai Kal ovb' e^app.6TTova-ai.. Analytica Posteriora, 1.33. 'The principles of all deduction are not identical They are heterogeneous and vary with the sub- ject, and are inapplicable beyond their respective spheres.' The constitution of philosophy imagined by those who maintained the unity of first principles was probably such as we have in Hegel's system, where the laws of physic and ethic are repe- titions of the laws of the development of reason laid down in the logic : or in Herbert Spencer's philosophy, where tbe theo- rems of ethical and natural science are exemplifications of the general laws of evolution and its component processes of differ- entiation and integration, which themselves are again aflSliated K a 132 NOTES. Chap. XI. on -a primary axiom of the persistence of force, a principle which very mach resembles, if it is not identical with, the Aristoteliaii axiom. In the Metaphysic we are told that though all being" does not belong to a single geiins{Ka66Kov,-Kaff ev), yet as referribleto a common standard (irpos eV) it belongs to a single science, philosophy. To be 6v keyfTai fiiv iioWax&s, aXXa irpas h koI IJ-Cav Ttva (pvaiv, /tat ov)^ o/xoivv/icos Ov ixovov 6e [irept] t&v Kaff tv Xeyoiihmv e7rtoT?jfi?js iLcrTal tovtov jjifv vrtobiiovTai (rxwo^ ™ t^iAoird^b)' T] yap (roaLvoij.ivri jiovov troipia eori, Kai oi bia- AfKTtitol biaKiyovTai irepl anavTotv koivov bk iraai. to ov €(tti, bia- \iyovTai 8e iiepX tovtcov bfjX.ov on bia to Trjs (l>iX.o(TO(pCas etvat avTa oueia. Uepl pxv yap to avTo yivos ffTpi(peTai fj ao(^itTTiKr\ kw. ?/ bia- KiKTiKTi TTj 0iXo(TO(^^a, oAAa bi.aep€i t^v fiev ru Tpo-nia r^y bvvi.p£(itii, TTJs be ToC l3Cov ttj Ttpoaipecrei. "Eori be fj biaKeKTinri ireipaanKri irepl Stv r\ (pikoaocjiia yvotpicrTiKri, fj be v &fja bel^a> on ecruv eKilvo. '' AvTi,(TTpefL be jxaWov to, iv rots iJ,a6riiJ,acnv, oti ovb\v (rt;/ii;3e/3)j){oj XaiipdvovcTLv, &K\a koI Touro) biacpepovai. t&v ev rots biaXoyois, a\K' opiirixovs. Anal. Post. I. la. 'If true conclusions never resulted from false premisses, it would be easy to obtain by analytical reasoning the principles on which any theorem depends. For the principles and theorem would be related to one another as the terms of a convertible proposition. If the antecedent A involves the consequent B, when I knew the existence of B I might infer the existence of A. This reciprocal demonstration is more common in science than in dialectic, for the premisses of science are never' accidents but definitions.' 12] The introduction of the word nature ((pva-is) may remind us of a negative definition of logic in the pantheistic system of Hegel, where logic is defined to be reason before the creation of the world, or, reason antecedent to nature; the three succes- sive transformations of reason being logical truth, nature, and morality. In the passage before us, however, <^ijiTis jueludes moralities as well as laws of nature. 13] It appeai-s that a pseudographema would be legitimate in pirastic : for if the respondent could not solve it, it would prove his ignorance of the science (woiet brjKov el Ayvoel, ch. viii). The pseudographema, however, does not belong to pirastic ; for pirastic is not supposed to have sufficient knowledge of scientific principles to construct a pseudographema. Pirastic proof is intermediate between sophistic proof and scientific proof. The former has no particularity (Ibiov) ; the latter no universality {kolvov) ; pirastic has both particularity and universality. Scientific proof cannot be extended beyond its private sphere : sophistic confutation proves no ignorance in a particular sphere : pirastic confutation tests knowledge in a particular sphere by principles applicable to every sphere. Kara -ro TTpayfia, i. e. Iblies, deap&v to. koivcl, ■n-eipaori/co's. See above. For a further examination of to, Kotva. see Appendix D. Whately has divided fallacies into lexical and extra-logical. We shall see in Appendix D that this division will not bear exami- nation. Aristotle's division is into dialectical ((Toc/jiV/iara) and extra-dialectical or scientific {\j/fvboypa(l)ripi.ara). If we define dialectic to be opinionative reasoning and logic the science Chap. XIL NOTES. 135 of proof, we may divide dialectical fallacies into logical and extra-logical, but logical will include all^that Whately considers extra-logical. CHAPTER XII. 1] EiTi 6 crov, irpos tovto tox)s \6yovs woi^tou, TvyxAvrj be TOVTO TOIOVTOV &U TipOS & iVTtOpiiv ks, p,fi fi be, npos o ylyvovrai oi Koyoi, etre apvr\ua)j,evov tov TOV koyov virixovTOi, elre aitayotyrjs evbo^ov bia Trjs de(re(os irpos avTo ytvoixevris avaipeiv eiti)(eipei avTo' to be Kolttov, otov )M)Te avayKawv ^ jx-qTe (^aiv6p,evov Trpos b ylvovTat ol Xoyoi, dWias bi Tta- pe^e\iyxea-0aL crvii^aivr] tu d-noKpLvofiiva. Aei bi evka^eltrdai tov etryaTov t&v prjOevTcov Tpovcav' irajreAaij yap duripTrijxevos (cai aXKo- Tpios ioiKev eXvai ttjs biaXexTiKrjs. Ato Sei (cai tov ditOKpivofievov fii) bva-KoXaiveiv, dWa Tidevai to, pJri xpi^crtixa -npbs ttjv deinv, ima-rmai- v6p,evov ocra p.7i boKei ixev, TCOrjcn bi. MaWov yhp airopeiv as eTTiTO- Ttokv v 6 (Tv\\oy(.(Tpi6s, firi dfj 8' avTo. 6 a.TTOKpiv6iJ.evos bia to irvveyyvi elvai TOV e^ djOYTjs Koi Tipoopav to aviJ-firjaoixevov dW' tcrtas Khv (ntovbA(Teiev OTi fxaKuTTa yimpip-a Kal avveyyvs elvai to, dfidJ/^iaTa- e/c TOVTav yap oi em(TTr)p.oviKol crvXKoyuriMoi. Topica, 8. I. ' Invention of the 138 NOTES. Chap. XIV. method of argument belongs to philosophy and dialectic alike : the arrangement and shaping of the questions to dialectic alone. The philosopher and solitary inquirer, when he has discovered true and evident premisses, has no trouble from the refusal of the respondent to grant them, because they bear immediately on the problem, and manifestly confute his thesis. He is glad to have them connected as closely and evidently as possible with the problem ; for so they must be in scientific proof.' From the contents of the following chapter it appears that ra£ts ex- presses rather tactics than simply arrangement. CHAPTER XV. 1] For ikeyxfiv read kavOauuv. 2] It seems that Aristotle was capable of giving precepts for lengthiness, but they are not extant, unless he refers to what he said about unnecessary propositions in the Topica, 8. i. 3] Various methods of concealment are given in the Topica, 8. 1. E. g. to keep back till the last moment the conclusions of the inductions and prosyllogisms that furnish the premisses of confutation [fjJq biapOpotdivToiv t&v irpoTepav (rvWoyia-fi&i)) ; to leave the subject of dispute and obtain concessions respecting its cor- relatives or pai'onyms {to. (rvm-oixd) ; to smuggle in the important premiss with a quantity of irrelevant matter (iv ■napapmrif '}TpO(TTi9evTes KaOatap ol v^enSoypac^oCires) ; &c. 4] "En 8ia rrj? opioiorijTOS ■nvvddvea-daf Koi yap itiOavov km XavdAvei fxaWov ro KaOokov. Olov on Sxmep eirio-T77fXj; km ayvoia r&v evavrCiav f] alrri, ovTot Koi ata-drjcns t&v evavriuin r] avrr\, rj avairakiv, l7ret8^ aiudr^ais fi avTrj, kolL eTnaT-qjxrj. Tovto 8' icrnv Sp,oiop iiiaycayfj, ov fxijv tomtov ye. 'Exet p-iv yap airo t&v Kaff exacrra to KaOokov kap^dveTai, iiri be t&v ofioiav ovk hri TO kajX^avoiievov to Kadokov v(j) & ttAvtu to ofwid ia-n. Topica, 8. I. 'Another method of concealment is to reason by simi- litude, that is, to reason directly from particulars to similar particulars. The reasoning is persuasive and the immediate premiss is not disclosed. For instance, as the intellectual appreciation or non-appreciation of contraries is identical and simultaneous, so is the sensational, and vice versa. The mode of proof resembles induction, but differs, because it does Chap. XV. NOTES. 13y not express the universal proposition, but passes at once to the particular conclusion.^ This mode of raasoning has lately risen to distinction. Mill considers it the true or natural type of all reasoning, induction and syllogism being artificial. Grote finds here the long-sought criterion between true opinion and know- ledge : true opinion, so far as it is not merely a lucky guess but founded on evidence, passing immediately from particulars to particulars without recognizing the intermediate law. See his comment on the Meno. After aK\a in the text perhaps we should add avavvnov. 5] Kal TO. oKiydKis oKiya, so read, comparing ch. xxiv, for /cat TO TtoWaKis TioWd. 6] In the Rhetoric this artifice is given as the fallacy figura dictionis. Tottoi 8' eial t&v (^Mvofiivtav ivdvjxrjjx&Tiaiv its fiiv o ■napa Tr\v Xl^iv, kol to^tov kv ijt,ev /xepos coo-irep fv rot? biaXeKTiKois TO JUT) (TvWoyKTaiJievov o'vixTTepQ.criJ.aTiK&s to TfXfvToiov eraety, ovk &.[ta TO Kol TO, avdyKY] apa to koL to. Kal to tois ivOvp,T]y.a(nv \_olKiiovT\ TO avve(TTpap.p.H>ii>s icai avTiKeifxivms ilniiv (paCveTai (vdv- p.rj\xa. 'H yap ToiavTr] \efis X'^P" ^''''''i' ivdv^-f]p.aTos. KaJ lotKe to toioCtoi' ilvai napa to cF)(rnj.a t^s A^fews. Rhet. a. 24- ' One locus of seeming oratorical proof is diction. One division of this is, as in dialectic, without proving to conclude in the language of proof: "It follows, then, that this- must be true:" "It follows, then, that that must be false." For crowded and anti- thetical propositions look like proof, because such diction is the vehicle of proof : and the fallacy is figura dictionis.^ 7] *Ai' 8' iT^pov bo^av bia(j)v\dTTrj 6 d.-nOKpivofj.fvo's, brj\ov oti Ttpos Tr\v, (Kelvov bidvoLav a,7ro/3Ae7rovTa 6(Teov (Kaara Kal apvrf f.ov. Aio Koi 01 KopiCCovTis okKoTpCas bo^as, olov dyaObv Kal KaKOV etvuL ravTov, Kaddirfp 'Hp(iKAetTo's <^7](ri,v, ov biboaa-i, p.ri Tiapdvai &p,a ru avTio TavavTia, oi^ ^s ov boKovv avTols tovto, aAA on Kad' Upa- K\fiToi> ovToi KiKTtov. Topica, 8. 5. ' When the respondent de- fends the tenet of another person, the opinions of that person are the standard of what he ought or ought not to admit. Accordingly, the advocate of a dogma which he himself does not hold, — for instance, that good and evil are identical, as Hera- clitus said, — will not grant that contraries cannot coexist; not because he disbelieves it, but because it is inconsistent with the system of Heraclitus.' In the text ■npoKuiiivov seems to signify, 140 NOTES. Chap. XV. not, as usually, the thesis, but the conclusion of the argument, i. e. the contradictory of the thesis. So in Topica, 8. 5 : 'ASo'fot) yap ovaris rfji Oicreas ^I'bo^ov to (rviXTtepacriJia' (Sore bei to. Xap,fiav6- [jL€va evbo^a ti&vt etvai Koi p,a\\ov evbo^a roC irpoKeiiJtivov, ei p,eK\ei 81a r&v yvT&VTi trvKOCpavTeHv as bp.oiij>s K(yop,hov eweiSTJ woAAa t&v ovx_ op-oices \eyop.iva>v o/xotioj (fmlveTai. Xfyeadai. Topica, 8. 1. 'In induction it is sometimes difficult to word the generalization, because the point of similarity in the particulars has not been denoted in popular language by a common name. In generalizing we say. And so in all like eases, or, And so in all the members of the class. But it is excessively difiicult to define the class or determine what particulars are like : and hence many fallacies arise, one party maintaining the likeness of what is unlike, the other the unlikeness of what is like. We ought therefore ourselves to invent a name for the class, that the answerer may be unable to pretend the unlikeness of what is like, or the questioner the likeness of what is unlike, for what is really unlike often appeai-s to be like.^ It is curious to see the fundamental problem of induction treated so incidentally and perfunctorily. The definition of the antecedent term of a generalization is spoken of as if it were merely the process of inventing a name. It is really the problem, which Aristotle would allow to be all-important in science, of distinguishing essential (/cofl' avTo) and accidental propositions, or, as we should now say with Mill, of eliminating chance from causal conjunc- Chap. XVII. NOTES. 143 tions, and can only be solved by the methods of agreement and difference. • 8] 'ATio(t>dva-€Ls. So read for aTTo^direis, the perpetual error of the scribes. ■ 9] Perhaps for itoTipass ixei TaXrjdis, we should read ■noTspo}'} exet TO (riivrjdes, i.e. Ttorepas ftmOi keyedOai. But toA?j0€s, though an ill-selected word, may be the right reading, for it may refer to TCLS a\r)9fis boias, which occurs above. It would denote the real or symbolized meaning as opposed to the figure or imagery. The theorem that the side and diagonal of a square are incom- mensurate is demonstrated by Euclid, lo. 97, and is alluded to by Aristotle : Flept 6e t&v aCbCaiv ovhels fiovkeuerai, otov Trepl rov Koa-fiov, fi TTJs biajxiTpov Kol rrjs irXevpas on i.(nip\xiTpoi. Eth. Nic. 3. 3. We might suppose there was an allusion to the ambiguity of the terms, f) biApifTpos aaijp,p.iTpos, which may express either that the diagonal and side of a square, or that the diameter and circumference of a circle, are incommensurate. The latter pro- position was probably stnmbled on by those who were seeking a method of squaring the ciixjle; for they discovered that the area of the circle equals half the rectangle of the radius and circumference. But the interpretation given in the text seems better. There is a similarly constructed period in Topica, 8. 3 : T&v be opwp bvaeTti^fiprjTOTaToi -navTatv etcrtv oaoi Ki\privTai toiovtois ovo- Ixaa-LV h TTp&Tov ptiv 6,br]kA (ariv etre aiikm the -nokXax&s keyirai, ■npos be toutois /liijS^ yvd>piyt.a voTtpov Kupicos ^ Kara p,iTa^opav vtto Tov 6pia-ap.evov kiyeraf bia fiev yap to aa-a^rj thai ovk ex^' ^ '" XeLprip,aTa, bia be to ayvoelcrOai el itapa to Kara p.eTa(j)opav keyecrdai. tomvt' ecTTlv, ovK e^ei eiiiTLp.r](nv. ' Of all definitions the most diflScult to attack are those whose terms raise a doubt, firstly, whether they are ambiguous or unambiguous, and secondly, whether they bear their proper sense or are metaphors. The doubt whether they are ambiguous saves the definition from confutation as false, and the doubt whether they bear their proper sense saves it from condemnation as metaphorical.' 144 NOTES. Chap. XVIII. CHAPTER XVIII. 1] 'I'eiiSTjj 8e \dyos KaXeirai TfTpa)(&s' fva jjiev Tpoirov orav (pai- vrjTai trvjjL-nepaCvfaOai fxri a-vixiTepaivoixevos, 6s Ko\eiTat crv\\oyiiTp,6s ipicTTiKos- "AWov 8e oTav (ivp.T,epaivr\Tai jiiv, pifi p,ivToi irpoi to ttpo- KeCfxevov, oirep (Tvp,^alv€i p.akiaTa rois ets to ahvvaTov S,yov. *H Tipbs TO TTpoKiCp.evov ij,ev (Tvp,T!ipaivr]Tai,, yjfi fiivToi Kara rfiv oUdav ixedobov TOVTO Se ^cttiv eav 6 fXTj 5)v loTpiKos 6ok^ iarpiKos eivaf, fj yewjuerpiKos p.ri S)V yeaifj.eTpLK6s, rj biaXeKTiKos p.fi &>v 6ia\eKTuo's, &v Te -^j/fvbos av re aXrjdes s ''o crvixj3aivov. 'A\kov be Tpoirov iav 8ia •^revb&v (TVfjmepaCi'riTai' tovtov be earai wore piev to avun^paa-na \jffvbos wore 6e a\ri9es. Topica, 8. lo. 'False proof is of four kinds : firstly, inconclusive or eristic proof: secondly, conclusive but irrelevant proof, which chiefly occurs in reductio ad absur- dum : thirdly, relevant proof by an inappropriate method, i. e. proof that has a false pretence of being physiological or geo- metrical or dialectical, though it has a true conclusion : fourthly, proof from false premisses, whether the conclusion is true or false/ The first class is inconclusive syllogism. The second class is inconclusive confutation, including non causa pro causa and ignoratio elenchi (see ch. x, note 4<). The third class is simulated pirastic proof or simulated scientific proof, and may be identified with one of the significations of accidental or in- commensurate proof (ch. vi, note 5). The exposure of this class of fallacy is beyond the competence of pirastic, and de- mands science or at least education (see Appendix E). The fourth class is dialectic, sophistic, or pseudographic, according as the false premiss is a special opinion, a general maxim, or a special theorem. Perhaps Aristotle would also call it dialectic, if the general maxim was a really probable hypothesis. The first two classes exhaust the thirteen paralogisms. All the classes are sophistic, though the fourth class includes some mem- bers which are not. The sophistic members of the fourth class are discussed in chap, viii, where, however, they are not distm- guished from the fallacies of the third class. Are there any confutations which fall under the third class and not also under the fourth, that is, which are sophistic and yet conclusive and constructed of true premisses ? It is difiicult to conceive any Chap. XVIII. NOTES. 145 thing that fulfils these conditions except the confutation of a geometer, who is seduced into advaaeing an ungeometrical thesis. He would scarcely do this deliberately, but he might in the heat of a discursive debate, and would then expose him- self to a by-confutation (irapef Aeyxoy). We might, however, regard this as a case of non causa pro causa, that is, of the second class. See the mention of by-eonfutation in ch. xii, note 1. 2] Here the disproof of a conclusion is called counterproof, and spoken of as a solution of the argument in support of that conclusion. This is not only ijaanifestly inadmissible, but is flatly contradicted by Aristotle himself in ch. xxiv. ' Something more than the exposure of a fault is required in solution, for the falsity of the conclusion may be demonstrated without explain- ing why the reasoning is fallacious. To solve Zeno's proof of the impossibility of motion, we ought not to try to prove the opposite, for though we gave ten thousand valid proofs, this would be no solution, for it would not expose where the falsity of his argument Kes.' Elsewhere Aristotle clearly implies that antisyllogism or counterproof (he uses the synonymous term avTi-niyeipilv) is directed not against the conclusion but against a premiss. 'E'ffei h\ -naa-a TtpoTacns crvXkoy io-tikt] ?j ToijTOiv rk lariv ff &v 6 (rvWoyi(Tjj,os, -tj tivos Tovrmv evsKa {bfj\ov 8' orav eripov )(({pti; \ap.^avr)Tai tu irKeCo) to, of/,oia kparav ?j yap 8i' eiroymyTjs -q hi 6p,oi6Tr)Tos bis eiil to ttoXv to Ka66\ov Xap,^&vov(ny to jj.tv KaOe- Kaara navra Oeriov, hv fj aKrjdrj Kol evbo^a, irpos 8e to KadoKov iret- paTiov fva-raaiv (j)fpeiv. To yap &vfv evffTda-eois rj ovarjs ri boKOwris KUiKvfiv Tov Xoyov bvcrt to Kadokov fi^ ex"" evcrracnv, ipavepov oti bva-KO- Xaivii. "En b\ d p.7]b' avTeTiix^ipeiv exoi on ovk aXrides, p.aX\ov &v b6$fie bviTKohaCvdv. Kakoi oibe rovd' havov -noXXovs yap Xoyovs ivavrCovs i-)(pp,iv Tais,- So'^ais ofis xaXt-nov Xi'juv KuOdirtp tov Zrjvoi- vos OTi OVK fvbexeTai Kiveia-dai ovbe to aTAbwv buXBelv dX\' ov bia TovTO TO. avTiKdjxiva TovTOLs ov Oeriov. El ovv fiTjre drTeirixetpf tv lxJ' /nijre kvioTatrdai ov TCOrjai, bijXov ort 8i;£rKoXaii'€t. 'Eo-n yap f) fv X6yoLS bva-KoXCa AwoKptcrts ■napa tovs dpy}p.ivovi Tponovs a-vXXo- yio-juoi; ^OapTiKr). Topica, 8. 7. 'AH propositions are premisses of the final proof, or premisses of these premisses, as the particulars adduced in induction and simihtude. These particulars must 146 NOTES. Chap. XVIII. be admitted if they are true, and the universal inference opposed by enstasis. To resist an inference without adducing an enstasis, real or apparent, is perversity, or irrational obstructiveness. To resist without even adducing a counterproof, is still greater per- versity. Yet even this would be insufficient, for many proofs of paradoxes are hard to solve, like Zeno's about motion, and yet the respondent (in arguing on a different question) is bound to admit the opposite. If, then, the respondent refuses to admit a premiss without adducing either enstasis or counterproof, he is undeniably perverse. For logical perversity is withstanding proof without one of these modes of justification.^ The same is implied in the- Rhetoric : Ta be -Kpos tov avrChKov ovx erepov n «i8os, aWa Tmv Tiiarfoov iv&s, fcjiri 6 KTTjo-Mnros. T^ be; rj 8' os. Mrjbiv. 2i 6' Itreos ovk otei aiiTa opav. OfiTcoy 178^1? ei. 'AXAci /xot boKUi, 'EvO'ibriiJ.e, ov Ka0e6b(ov irnKSKOi- iJ.Ti(rjp.aTos, dvayKr] yap irpos to i(r){aTov aKpov hp,^OTtpa% Xa/Selv Tas TrpoT&ireis. Anal. Priora, 2. 8. 'The contrary of the major premiss cannot be proved by the minor premiss and the contrary of the conclusion, for the proof is in the third figure, the minor term becoming the middle and being made the sub- ject of both premisses.' AryAov 8e /cat on ev Unacn toXs o-xtjVc"^"' •OTav pjj yivrfrai avWoyicrfios, KarriyopiK&v {/.kv ^ a-TeprjTlk&v diJ,ofiivu>v yap t&v TipoTAcreatv avdyKr] to F tlvI t£ A fx-q vTrdpxeiv. Anal. Priora, 1.7' ' In all the figures, when the premisses are ineonclusivCj if one is afiirmative and the other universal negative, we get a con- clusion by making the major term the subject and the minor the predicate. E. g. Some M is P, No S is M, . • . Some F is not S, for conversion of both premisses gives us the first figure.' [Ari- stotle employs conversion because he did not recognize the fourth figure. Conclusions in which the relation of the major and minor terms is inverted were called by the Schoolmen Indirect moods.] Sometimes, however, the opos Tipos 6v designates the predicate of the conclusion. 'Ev fiiratri yap tois els to dh'ivaTov crvXkoyifyp.o'is avdyKrj kowov Tiva Xa^ilv Spov dXXov t&v VTiOKeifxivav, Trpos hv icTTai Tcni x^eiiSovs 6 m)XXoyia-p,6s, Si(tt avTiiTTpacpeicrris TavTr]S ttjs Trpord- (Ticos, Trji 8' er^pas ofioicos ixovremisses of ostensive proof.' I. e. supposing no 5 is P to be proved ostensively thus. No M is P, All 5 is M, .-. No/S- is P, we may prove it indirectly by combining its contradictory. Some S is P, with either of the ostensive premisses, thus : No M is P, Some S is P, . ■ . Some S is not M. Or Some S is P, All S is M, . • . Some M is P. In the former case, which is that which Aristotle examines, the 150 NOTES. Chap. XIX, new term, M, is the predicate of the false conclusion : in the se- cond ease it is the subject. We may observe that in the first of the passages which we have quoted^ Aristotle seems for the mo- ment to have overlooked the third figure, for there the minor term (irpo9 6v) is the predicate, not the subject, of the minor premiss. A proof is said to be addressed to a proposition (irpos tovto) when that proposition is the conclusion or contradictory of the conclusion. 'Ev Sjta ns, noTfpov OeTeov to, Toiavra r] ov. Topica, 8. 3. 'When a premiss or proposition is harder to prove than the thesis to disprove, it may be doubted whether the respondent ought or ought not to concede the proposition.' It appears, then, that wpos 3, when it denotes a term in a syl- logism, excludes the middle ; when it denotes a proposition, ex- cludes the premisses. In the Analytica wepl o denotes the sub- ject of demonstration, or minor term ; a the predicates, or major terms; ^f &i>, not the middle terms, but sometimes the pre- misses, sometimes the axioms or syllogistic canons, 0] No English word expresses the ambiguity of biovra. For want of a better let us take the word necessary, then we have the syllogism : What is evil ought not to be done, what is evil is necessary, therefore what is necessary ought not to he done. 6] I. e. TTiv 6ev bv(Txep&i> irepl tos ibeas €(TtCv. Ot S' d)S avayKOLOV etwep ecrovTai rivis ovaiai Trapa ras ala-Orirai Kal piovcras, xt<>/3tf ray eXvai, ahXas p-iv ovk ftx"") '"owas 8e Tas KadoKov Keyop,4vas eiidiaav. Met. I3. 9. 'Attention to universals received an impulse from the Socratic definitions : but Socrates did not separate them from particulars, and he did well, as the result shewed. For universals are indispensable to science, but their separation from the objects of sense produces the difficulties of idealism. The idealists saw that substances, if there were any besides the objects of sense, must have a separate existence, and not knowing what else to assign, hypostatized universals.' Compare, 'A\X' 6 ixev SaiicpiiTjjs to, Ka66\ov ov xv Toncav o'i t e/c t&v avTiKeifxivaiV Koi t&v crvcrroi- Xav KOL r&v TTTma-ecav o/nottos yap evbo^ov to dftSo-at. Topica, 3. 6, ' The most effective and universally applicable topics are those from opposites and those from paronyms, for a proposition transferred to an opposite or a paronym is just as probable as in its original form.' This is another instance of the proximity (yetrvtao-ts) of dialectic and sophistry. Paronymous words (irapdwixa.) are different modifications of the same root ; like-figured words {oixoiocrxruxova) are similar mo- difications of different roots. Homonymous words appear to denote things entirely identical; like-figured words appear to denote things belonging to the same class, order, or category ; paronymous words appear to denote things variously correlated to the same standard of reference {irpos ev) . In Greek the things 156 NOTES. Chap. XXII. not the words are called 6iJi.(avviJ,a and isapt&vviw., so that these definitions would require modification. CHAPTER XXIII. 1] For ffx^vxpv read a^vxpv. ^ ATTotfiria-avTa fir] elvai {a\jfV)(ov) denotes the thesis, and is equivalent to (jj-rja-avTa etvai fjxijfvj^ov Su/njSaii'ei denotes the conclusion of the confutation. CHAPTER XXIV. 1] Prom this it might seem that every solution by fitajpeo-ts, as well as every solution by avaipeuis, and every proposition of the questioner, was to be supported by induction : but Aristotle does not impose this obligation when speaking of any other fallacy. 2] Here the attribute (unknown) of the accident (about to be asked) is transferred to the subject (the summum bonum). It would be easy to state any of these fallacies so that the attribute of the subject should be transferred to the accident ; e. g. if we inferred that because the summum bonum was known, therefore the question about to be asked was known. [The fallacy seems really to be amphibolia. The premiss, nescis quid sim te roga- turus, is employed as if it were, non novisti quod sum te roga- turus.] 3] The fallacy seems really equivocation, a confiision between the two senses of knowledge, old acquaintance, and recognition on a particular occasion. 4] In these two examples there is no syllogism, for all the three terms appear in the quasi conclusion. There is only a pretence of expressing in one sentence what had previously been expressed in two. The principle of the fallacy seems the same as that of the good shoemaker, which was put under the head of composition and division. 5] This excentric syllogism may be illustrated by the follow- ing : Oxygen combined with hydrogen is water ; oxygen com- bined with hydrogen is oxygen, therefore oxygen is water. Or : Oxygen is gaseous j oxygen combined with hydrogen is oxygen ; therefore oxygen combined with hydrogen is gaseous. The fallacy may be regarded as equivocation. In one premiss, four Chap. XXIV. NOTES. 157 multiplied by four means the product of the factors, in the other, only the first-named factor. 6] For avaipovvTes read btaipovvres. 'Eptorrjo-ts here, as in ch. xxii, is the thesis. But when we point out an ignoratio elenchi, it is not necessary to remodel or abandon the thesis [avaipelv) . It is sufficient to shew that it is not contradicted {biaipe'iv). One MS. reads ov biaipovvTes. This seems to be the query of an intelligent reader. 7] See ch. xx. 8] Here again (see ch. xxii, note 3) we have by implication the strange expression of solving a fallacy by contradicting the thesis. The syllogism seems to have been : A four is a small number ; a four multiplied by a four is a four ; therefore a four multiplied by a four is a small number. 9] Aristotle does not speak very accurately. He said in ch. iv. that a term is ambiguous whether the plurality of signi- fication is (i) proper^ or (a) customary, or (3) merely arises in combination. 10] From this expression it might seem that Aristotle con- sidered the fallacy to belong equally to per accidens and to composition. 11] The pui-port of the passage seems to require a mark of interrogation after KaK&v. 12] Aristotle seems to mean that there would be a fallacy of composition. But if Davus is good and belongs to bad masters, the conclusion that something of the bad is good follows without any fallacy of composition. Aristotle is in difficulties from re- fusing to admit that the genitive is ambiguous, at least has a partitive and relative as well as a possessive force. Yet he repu- diates as an impossibility the proposition, elvai r&v kuk&v ti ayaOov. But what is there paradoxical in this unless its first and most obvious, i. e. proper, meaning is, that some evil, is good, in other words, unless the genitive is partitive ? This was recognised by subsequent grammarians as its original meaning, when they called it the genus-predicating case (yevurj ■nT&aris). 13] If the expression is not ambiguous, how would Aristotle solve the fallacy. What is of the animals is the property of the animals, man is of the animals, therefore man is the property of the animals ? He could not refer it to any of the heads of fallacy. 158 NOTES. Chap. XXIV. but apparently would be obliged to deny the minor (see eli. xvii, A^kov ovv fv oh a(ra(t>es to TipoTfivoixevov ov avyxP'nTiov awAws), which would be a very unsatisfactory mode of solution. 14] The fallacy per accidens has been generally misunder- stood, which seems to shew that it is an ill-defined species. We might do well to drop it from the list and distribute its contents among the other classes. The principle which, in order to solve it, Aristotle brings to bear against the sophist, namely that the predicate of a predicate cannot be inferred of the subject, unless one of the premisses is an essential proposition or even a defini- tion, is far too sweeping; and if admitted would upset nine- tenths of the syllogisms ever constructed. If we retain the class in order to comprehend the instances given in ch. v, i. e. all the cases of illicit process and undistributed middle that are not comprehended in eonsequens, it would be well to give the class a more appropriate name than accidens, and make one class represent both accidens and eonsequens. CHAPTER XXV. 1] Whately, followed by Mill and De Morgan, makes per accidens the converse of secundum quid. He confines the second to the ease where a term is first used with a limitation and afterwards without, and per accidens to the opposite ease, where a term is first used without and afterwards with a limitation. But it is plain that with Aristotle secundum quid included both the case where a term has a limitation in the premisses and not in the conclusion, and vice versa ; and both the case where the limitation is in the conclusion but not in the thesis, and that where it is in the thesis but not in the conclusion. 2] For vyiaCveiv read apxuv. 3] So we must read with one of the MSS. : the others give TO yap Xa^iiv aya6bv ayadov. 4] NiKai'. So read, in spite of MSS., for KpLvuv. Perhaps too, below, for hUaiov ea-riv iKav&s Xiyfiv, we should read bUaiov f(TTi viKCLV \eyovTa, or biKai,6i> eerri vLKav os \iyei. Chap. XXVIII. NOTES. 159 CHAPTER XXYI. 1] See eh. v. CHAPTER XXVn. 1] 'Eiret TO y epu>Tav afx^ilioKa xai to. napa ttjv oyL(iiwp.iav, oaai. T aX\aL TOLavrai •napaKpova-eis, koI tov aXi^dwov eXeyxov ac{>aviCei, KOI TOV iXeyxpixevov koX pH] iXeyj^opevov tiSrjAov Troiei. . . "ASjjXov yap d a\ri6rj Ae'yet vvv. . . Nvv be, ha to /xtj KaX&s eptoTav tovs T!vvdavop.ivovs, avdyK-q Trpo(Ta-noKp[ve(r9aC tl tov €poiTcap,evov, biop- dovvTa TT]V pL0)(6ripCav rfjs irpoTdaftos. Ch. xvii. CHAPTER XXVm. 1] For avTiOea-eis read avTicjida-eis. The generic term dvTiKei- p.evov which foUowSj and which caused the false readings is only- used because avTL(pr]p,i, has no perfect passive participle. If A and B are related as antecedent and consequent, that is, if all A is £, one form of fallacy is to assume that all £ is A. This in hypothetical reasoning is to infer the truth of the antecedent from the truth of the consequent. Another form is to assume that all noi-A is not-_B. This is to infer the falsehood of the consequent from the falsehood of the antecedent. ArjXov ovv otl Ttpbs afKpoi a.VTi,(TTpe(fiei r) Kara Trjv avT[(l>acriv anoKovBrjcns avairaKiv yivofiivT]. Topica, a. 8. ' Whether the original terms are aflBrma- tive or negative, in both cases the contradictories of the original terms have their sequence in an inverted order.^ The false read- ing is probably the origin of the name of the famous conversion by contra-position. The logicians who used the name used it without a m^eaning, and were not troubled by the fact that in the rest of their system avrCOeais had been translated opposition, not contra-position. In the above-quoted passage wpos ap.(j)ia avTHTTpicjiei yivop,ivr] = en aiJ.s yiviTai. IGO NOTES. Chap. XXX. CHAPTER XXX. 1] TavTa, so read for ravra. In the preceding line, after ■naXiv, add, or understand, avAyK-r] avii-ftaivnv {ntevavTiaiiia. 2] For eirel b" read ^iretdrj. 33 Read, ei to jjlIv dyaOov yiverai, to 5e KaKov, hvo yivovr hv ayada 7] hvo koku, or something similar. 4] Whately, forgetting that the names of the fallacies are taken from a treatise on Eristic, i. e. catechetical disputation, thinks that the questioning in plurium interrogationum is merely a rhetorical figure, and that this fallacy merely differs from homonymia because the orator, to give animation to his discourse, puts his assertions into the form of interrogations, making believe that he expects an answer. But the examples given shew that the peculiarity of plurium interrogationum is, that the premisses are in the form, A and B are X and T, and that there is no ambiguity in the principal terms A, B, X, Y, but only in pronouns and syncategorematic words, such as they, themselves, both, all. The error of treating two questions as one is independent of diction, and therefore Aristotle has placed this class among the fallacies extra dictionem : but as after this error has been com- mitted no fallacy arises unless the questioner takes advantage of an ambiguity, it seems it ought to be classed with the fallacies in dictione. But throughout this treatise Aristotle seems in- clined to differ from the logician, perhaps the theorist criticized in ch. X, who reduced all fallacies to equivocation. CHAPTER XXXI. 1] Perhaps we should read, otov StirA.dcnoi' &vev tov fmiatos h Tu hvn\ATu apa ^crri kCdos. The solecistic conclusion requires either the false and solecistic minor. To viioKil.p.evov ia-Ti tovtov hv Xiyen avTO flvai, which with the true major. To TOVTOV hv K^yeis ovto etvcu, arniaivii to \(,6ov, gives the conclusion, To VTroiceCfievov &pa ea-n \l9ov : or the false major. To oSros hv kiy (IS ovto eivai arjfiaCvei to \iQov. 2] F.lT!iiv. So read with one of the MSS. for Hiriv. After oSros add ^ tovtov. Then the complete sentence is, "SvKov 8' ehteiv oiroi t) tovtov ovbev bt,a(j}4pei, where oSros and tovtov merely represent cases, their gender being disregarded. 3] For Tov Kldov (rrip,alv€iv oSroy, read Kldov o-r/jnofoeu; to oStos. Here Aristotle assumes that the conclusion depends on a false major premiss ; above he assumed that it depended on a false minor. As the reasoning relates not to things but to words, the realistic copula eanv is replaced by the nominalistic copula aT]p,aCveL. 4] We have MS. authority for omitting the article before \l6ov. In the infancy of grammar Aristotle could not give a very lucid explanation from the want of technical terms : but he has sufficiently shewn that no solecism can enter a valid con- clusion unless there was already a solecism in the premisses; and that the paralogism of solecism depends on the ambiguity of the neuter pronoun, which has the same form for the nomina- tive and the accusative. Chap. XXXIII. NOTES. 163 CHAPTER XXXftl. 1] M€Ta(j>epe(Tdai. is the characteristic of a dialectical as opposed to a scientific principle^ or, within the limits of scieneCj of an axiom [kolvti ap)(fi) as opposed to a thesis {ibCa apxfi), that is, of a method as opposed to a doctrine. It is an ontolog^cal proposi- tion, and has no relation to any one object of thought more than to any other. [TSj" TSTpayv & iartv evbo^a Kal aXrjdil], koI p/f) ev Tois "npoa-kap.^avop.ivois j) 6 Ao'yos. 'A complete proof is of inferior merit to an incomplete proof, if the premisses of the former are more improbable than the conclusion requires, and the premisses to be supplied for the latter are both probable and true and only remotely related to the conclusion.' 11] 'Eo-Ti 81 \6yov KOjXCorat (Tvp,TTepdva<70ai Terpax&s. *H yap ave- kovra -nap' o yivexai to \|feSSos, rj irpbs tov epa>T&VTa evcTTatnv eVnovTa' TtoKk&Kis yap ovbk kikvKev, 6 p-ivToi Ttvv6av6fievos oil bvva- Tai -noppaTepm irpoayayeiv rptrov he irpos to, ripa)Tr]p,4va' avp,^aCri yap &v ex piev t&v fipa>TriiJ^v9 ep ojcrre Tioirj(Tai tov anoKpivdixevov to. dSoforara \iyeiv T&v bia ttjv Oiaiv avayKaiuiv, tov 8' emoKpwoixivov to pr/ bi aiiTov (patvea-Oai avpfiaivnv to abvvaTov rj rb irapAbo^ov aWa 8ia Trjv decriv fTfpa yap taws apapTia to OicrOai vp&Tov o pr] Set km to 6ipivov pj\ (f>v\6.^ai Kara TpoTiov. Topica, 8. 4. ' To determine rules for the answerer, we must first define the aims of the questioner and answerer. The aim of the questioner is so to conduct the reasoning as to force the answerer to the most improbable pro- positions necessitated by the thesis : the aim of the answerer to make the impossible or paradoxical propositions appear due not to himself but to the thesis. For it is a difierent fault to ad- vance a wrong thesis, and after advancing it not to defend it as well as one might.' KaTh Tpo-nov here, and opoTpo-nuts in the text, seem to mean, not consistently or without self-contradic- tion but, with a degree of probability that varies with the thesis. 'Etici 6' 6 koAus cruAXoytfo'/iiei'os ef ivbo^oTepaiv koI yvapir poiTepiov TO ■npo^Xr)d\v aTrobeiKvvcn, (pavfpbv ws &b6^ov pev ovtos Chap. XXXIV. NOTES. . 167 ciirX&s Tov KeijXivov ov horiov tu aiTOKpLVO[i,iv(a ovff h fxri boxet av\&s, ovff o boKsi fjLev tjttov 8^ tov criz/iiTreociir^aros Soxet. Topica, 8. 5. ' As premisses should be more probable and certain than •conclusions, when the thesis is improbable, the answerer may refuse both all improbable premisses and all which though pro- bable are less probable than the contradictory of the thesis.' Aoyov vitiyi'-v seems nearly the same as diaiv (pvXarTeiv. 'Tirix^iv hk KoX Oidw Kol opiajixiv avTov aiJru Set Trpoey)(eipri(TavTa. . . ^Abo^ov 8' VTrodeaiv evXa^rjTiov vnexuv. Topica, 8. 9. S] Throughout this treatise the questioner has represented the sophist ; so that we were hardly prepared for the announcement that answering is the sophistic side of dialectic. The rest of the Topica, however, is written more from the point of view of the questioner; and the answerer appears as a sophist. 'Ewtr^/xjjirts 6e \6yov kut ovtov re tov \6yov Kat orav epioToxai o^x V o'^''^- rioXXd/cts yap tov pifj Kah&i hieikexOai tov koyov 6 kpuiT^jxevos atnos ha TO p,fi avyxapfiv ef &v ^v bLa\e\drivai Ka\&s irphs ttjv 6fT&VTi TiapaTrjpfj ir/aocr- (TtripeACaiV. AvffKokaivovTes ovv ayavia-TiKhs Koi ov SiaXeKrtKOS tiol- ovvTai Tas Starpt/Sds 'Eirel be (jyavkos Koivoovbs 6 ipLTTobCCav to KOIVOV epyov, brjKov oti koi ev Ao'yu. Koivbv yip tl koI kv to^tols •npoKelixevov ecrTi, Ttkriv t&v aycaviCofievoov. TovTots 8' o£k ei biakiyeTai, o t iv t(3 &moKpi,veT&v ■nvdecOai. Topica, 8. II. "In criticising we must distinguish between the argument and the arguer. The badness of an argument is often imputable to the answerer who refuses to grant the premisses which would fairly confute the thesis. For it is not in the power of one of the disputants without the co-operation of the other to accomplish successfully their joint task. Accordingly, the questioner is sometimes forced to argue against the answerer instead of against the thesis, if the answerer takes every means of thwarting him with unscrupulous effrontery. This perversity makts the argumentation eristic He is a bad associate who impedes the common work in reasoning as in any other occu- 168 NOTES. Chap. XXXIV. pation. Both disputants attain their object in well-conducted argument, though not in eristic, for both cannot be victorious. It is equally reprehensible to spoil the common business by captious questions, and by refusing to admit what one really believes or pretending to misunderstand the questions.' Dpos yap top -nav- Tus ipia-Tajxevov TtAvrws avTiraKTeov kariv. Topica, 5. 4. 'The un- serupulousness of the respondent forces the questioner to be unscrupulous.' It is not solely in the province of the answerer, however, that we may see the contiguity [yeiTvlatris) of eristic and dialectic. A conclusive dialectic proof may be formed of false premisses. "EiTi 8' Ivti yv^xvaalas koL ireCpas yapiv aXK ov SiSatrxaXtas 01 toiov- Toi T&v Koywv, bfjKov &i ov jxavov Ta\r]6ri (rvWoyurreov aWa Kal \j/€vbos, ovbe fit' a\r]6&v cLel dW' ej^iore koI ^evb&v. HoWaKis yap a\r]6ovs reOevTos avaipeiv avdyKr] tov biaXeyojievov, (Sore irpoTareov TO, ^evb-q, 'Evfore be Kal \jfevbovs re^e'iros avaiperiov bia ^evh&v. Oiibev yap Kmkvei tlvI boKelv to. ixfi ovra \mKXov t&v akrjd&v, &(tt, l/c T&v fKeivio boKovvTav tov Xoyov yivofxevov, p-aWov eorai ireireto-- lJ,f.voi 7) &e\rjixivos. Aei 8e tov koXms jxtTa^i^&QovTa biaXiKTiK&i Kai fiT] €pi(TTLK&s lierapi^dCeLV, KaOdvep tov yeutfiiTpriv yecojxeTpiK&s, av re \j/fvbos av t dXTj^es jj to iyvp/nepaiv6p,ivov. Topica, 8. 11. 'As practice and mutual examination, not instruction, are the object of these argumentations, the dialectician must often prove a false conclusion, and employ false premisses : for if the thesis is true, the premisses of the confutation must be false. Even a false thesis must sometimes be confuted by false premisses : for the answerer may disbelieve the true premisses, and as the proof must be composed of his beliefs, he will be convinced but hardly enlightened. The proof, however, must be dialectic, not eristic, whether the conclusion is true or false : just as a proof by a geometer should be geometrical.' But dialectic proof may also be inconclusive or fallacious. We saw (ch. v, note 4) that the locus a dicto secundum quid is the common property of eristic and dialectic : we saw (ch. xii, note 1) that' the dialectician does not abstain from the locus non causa pro causa : we saw (ch. xxii, note \0\ that paronyms are in Greek a locus of dialectic, in English a locus of sophisms. It appears also that ambiguity is common ground to the dialectician and sophist. Xp^o-t/ioi' 6e to ■noa-ax&s XeyfTai ivevni^dai. . . , Kal wpos to TrapaXoyliraa-Qai. Elba- Chap. XXXIV. NOTES. 169 res yap iroa-ax&s X^yeroi, avroi epaiT&VTes bvvr](r6iJ,s6a napaXoyl- aaaBai, eav jxr] Tvy^Avrj eiScos 6 aTioKpivauevos Tioaax&s Xeyeroi. "EoTt 6e owK piKeTos 6 rpoTios oSros rrjs biaXeKTiKrjs' hib navreX&s eiika- fitfiov roTs 8taX€KriKoTs to towvtov, to Trpos roUrojua 8ia\^yecr9at, eaf fHj ns bXS.uis e^abwaTrj irepl tov ■npoKup.ivov biaKiyeardai. Topiea, 1. 1 8. 'A knowledge of the various meanings of a term is useful, because it enables us when questioning to construct falla- cies, if the answerer has not the same knowledge. This mode of reasoning is not characteristic of dialectic, and should be utterly avoided, unless there is no other possible means of attacking the thesis.^ Elsewhere the locus is recommended without even this slight admonition. "En eav iroWaxw XeyrjTai, Keip.evov he jj us vTiapyii 7] MS o^x vvApxn, Barepov beiKVvvai t&v TT\eova)(&s Aeyo- jxivai', eav p-r] &pv oibe, tov be \j/evb6pevov ep(f>avi^eiv blivacrdai. TaCro 8' ((ttI to p,iv ev to b-6va(r6ai bovvai Xoyov, Tb 8' kv TO Kafieiv. 5] The Topica begins with a classification of propositions and problems (theses). Y\p5>Tov oSv Oeaiprp-eov e/c tCviov f) pAOobos. Ei 6?j Xd^oipev Tipbs ■noaa Kal iroia Kal l/c rtVcoj; 01 XoyoL Kal ttSs To-ircav etmoprfio'opev, eyoipev hv iKav&s ro irpoKeipevov. Eort 8' apidp£ icra Kal TO, avTa, e^ &v Te ol Xoyoi koI -aepl &v oi (TvXXoyia-poi. TLvovrai p\v yap ol Aoyot J/c t&v TiporAo-ecoV Tiepl &v be ol avXXoyicrpx>l, to, 'npopXripaT6. eort. Ylatra be Ttporacns Kal vav irpo^Xripa rj yevos rj Xbwv ^ avp.pel3riKbs brjXoi. Topica, 1.4. ' We have first to ex- amine the elements of the method, that is, the number and 170 NOTES. Chap. XXXIV. nature of the points to vvhicli arguments are addressed, and of the elements of which they are composed, and how they are ohtained. The two questions are identical : for arguments are composed of propositions, and addressed to problems ; and every proposition and problem is a genus, definition, property, or accident.'' 6] The sources of proof are pointed out partly by describing the Spyava and partly by enumerating the loci. Ta fxev ovv yivri irepl S)v re oi Ao'yot koX ef Siv, biMpCirOaf to. 6' opyava, hi' &v tviro- pri(Jop,iv tS>v a-vKKoyia-^&v, etTrl Terrapa, ev fj,ev to TrporAa-eis Xa^eiv, bevTepov 8^ TTO(rax&s e/caoroi' XdyeraL bvvatrdai heXeiv, rpiTov ras bias einToprja-ai /.lerptus, x<^^f- wdv. Topica, 8. 14. 'A universal proposition is better worth remembering than a chain of proof : for a moderate command of principles and premisses is difficult to obtain.' He recommends however, like his predecessors, that whole arguments should be committed to memory. Opo's re to, ■nXfLCTTd.Kis ipraTtTovTa t&v 172 NOTES. Chap. XXXIV. TTpo^krjiA&TOiv ^evltTTaaOai Sei \6yovi, mi jxAXurra Ttepl rmv irpdrm diaeiav kv tovtois yap a-nobva-jreTova-iv ol a-noKpiv6\xevoi ttoWokis. 'We should get by heart arguments on the problems that oftenest arise, particularly on the elementary theses j for here chance often makes the answers take an unlucky turn.^ 'Airo- bvaireTovcnv is a metaphor from dice. First principles are so difficult to elicit by questioning that the questioner may be baffled without any skill on the part of the answerer. [Compare the use of evTrer^s. Kat yap iSeiv aiirbv Kal Ka^fiv napa t&v Ipco- Twp,iv(ov Tas Toiairai upoTd-a-m qvk. evveres. Topieaj 7- 5-3 ^'^' 8e Kal ■neTtoirjp.ivovs ^X^tv \6yovs irpos ra Toiavra t&v irpo^krjfWTmv, ev o?s ika^Cn-Taiv evitopi^cravTes irpbs irXeicrTa xpi7<''tM0DS ^^op-tv, oSrot 6' ela-lv ol KadoKov, Kal irpos ots -nopl^etrdai xakeTtdrepov e/c t&v irapa ■nobas. Topica, 8. 14. ' We should have ready-made arguments for the conclusions that depend on the fewest premisses and yet are oftenest wanted, namely, the most ahstraet, and for those problems whose proof is difficult to extemporize.'' 11] Read aWa Tpi^fj. ADDENDA. Ch. VIIj note 2. ^Etiicnraadai was a common term in the schools. E. g. 'H p.'kv afwSpa nal eKkvroi (l)avTacria om hv et?j KpiTqpiov ru yap firjTe aw^y ju^re to Tsoir\(Tav rpav&s evheinwdOai ov Trecfiviiev fjiMS TTfCdeiv oid' ell a(veTai yap Stto Kal tois Ttapak-qpovaiv, a\A.' eKeivq ixev e/c T&v Koyov beoiJ-ivcav, fj be prjTopiKrj Ik t&v ^8)j ^ovXevecrBai elcoOo- Toov. Rhetoric, i. a. 'Rhetoric, like dialectic, examines what is probable, not to any individuals, but to certain classes. Dia- lectical proof appeals, not to any opinions, for madmen have opinions, but to the opinions of those who want not understand- ing but evidence ; and rhetorical proof to the opinions of those who are accustomed to deliberate.^ 'Ek t&v Xoyov beop.h<(ov=:eK T&v evho^av tols \6yov beop.evoi.'s, and Ik t&v -ijbrj PovkeveaOai eto>66- Tv=:eii T&v irWav&v tois jjSjj fiovKeviaBai elmBocrLV. For the mean- ing of T&v \6yov beoixevav, compare, Ov beX be irav ■npofiXrjixa aibe iraa-av 6eTroi km vvv Kot TO TTpWTOP ffp^avro (fnXocTo^tiv, bei be els to evavriov /cal to a)j.ei- vov Kara ttiv irapoifxCav airoTekevTrja-ai, Met. 1.2,' Men began to philosophize because they wondered, but the end of philoso- phizing should be something better, the cessation of wonder,' he seems to have expected that, in any province of inquiry what- ever, if we carried the analysis far enough, when we arrived at the ultimate immediate conjunctions, whether of coexistent or of successive terms, we should find them neither inexplicable nor mysterious, but the evidently necessary result of determinate relations. Kara expresses causation (oAtos he to Kad' h l(Tax&s Koi to alnov VTiap^ei, uxTTe Koi to xa^' avTo itoKKax&s avdyKtj XeyeaOai.. Met. 4. 18). Accordingly the proposition, to A vitdpxei ™ B Ka6' avro, means that all the conditions of the conjunction of A and B are contained in A and B themselves : that we are not to look for its cause in the interposition of any third independent term. The conclusions of science, as well as the first principles, are KaO' avTo, v-ndpx^ovTa, that is, ro xad' avro v-ndp^eiv is not confined' to immediate conjunctions except so far as it excludes the inter- ADDENDA. 175 ference of any foreign cause. We may add that in the expres- sion, TO A virapxei t£ B ko^' ovto, avTo is either the subject or the predicate, i. e. KaQ'' ovto means, as appears from Aristotle's definition of the two classes of ko9' awo vv&pxovTa, either Kar avTO TO A, or kot ovto to B '. e. g. ypa/xjUTJ vrrdp\ii rpiydvio Kar . aiiTo TO TpCytavov, but to evdv wtipx^' VP^l^l^fi '"'^' o'^to to evOv. Ch. xXj note 3. Eudemus, the disciple of Aristotle, informs us more than once that the theory of ambiguity {to bLo-crov) was invented by Plato. napp,evLbov pikv ovv ayaa-deCr] hv tis ava^io- TTioTOis aKo\ov&il]v Tretjyv- KOTCoy Sl kKeivov SeiKvvcrOaL, Sid tovtodv dnoSeiKvivai to e^ dp^fjs. OTov, el TO A SeiKvvoiTo Sid tov B, to Se B Sid tov /", TO Se r ne^vKos eir] SeiKwa-QaL Sid tov A- avfi^aiyei yap avTo Sl iavTov to A SeiKVVvai Tois ovrco (TvXXoyL^ojievavs, "Oirep TTOiovcrLV ol Tds TrapaXXi]Xovs olojievoi ypd(peiv. Aav6d- fovcri yap avrol eavToiis ToiavTa Xaji^dvovTes d ov\ oeov Te dTToSei^ai firj ovcr&y t&v irapaXX'tjXav, "DaTe toTs oStco avXXo- yi^ojikvois crv/j.^aivei eKaaTOV Xeyeiv etvai el ecTTiv 'eKaeiv fj r£ errea-Oat to A t& B- to e| dp^rji ahehai Slit. TTjv aiTrji/ ahiav. To yap t| dpyrjs Ti SvvaTai, nporepov e'iprjTai fffiiv, Sri to Si' eavTOv SeiKvvyac to jxri Si' afiTOv SfjXoy. El oSv e<7Ti to kv dp)(fj ahelaQai to Si aiiTov SeiKvvvai to fifj Si avTov SfjXov, TOVTO Si eaTi to fifi SeiKvwai, oTav 6/ioim dSrjXmv ovTmv tov SeiKvvfievov Kal Si' o5 SeiKvvTai ®, jj r^ Tairra Tm aiiTw fj Tffl TavTov Toli avToTs {mdp-)(eiv''- ev [lev tZ jjiia-a ayrjuaTi oiiSeTepcos^ &v evSeypiTO to ev dpy^^ alTeTa6ai, ev Se KUTr/yopiKw avXXoyi dpxfj irei/raxaJs. avepa)TaTa fih Kal nprnrov d ris avrb to SeiKwaOai 8kov ah^aer tovto S' kit avToO fj-eu ov paSiov \av6dvew, kv 8e toTs avvcavvfiois Kal kv oa-ois TO ovofia Kal 6 \6yos to avTo a-ri/iaii/ei fidXXov. Aev- Tepov 8e oTOAi KCLTo. fiEpos 8iov dTToSeT^UL KadoXov TIS aiTTJoTj- olou el kTn-)(iip3>v otl tS>v kvavTicov jxiw kiricrTrjiir], oXws t&v dpTiKeifievcoy d^idxreie jiiav eivai' 8oKel yhp h e8ei KaB' aiiTO SeT^ai fjLeT aXXcav aheTa-OaL wXeiovcov. TpiTov e'l tis, to KaOoXov SeT^ai TTpoKeifievov, kutcc fiepos ahrjcreiev oiov el iravTcov tS>v kvavTioDV irpoKeijievov, T dpxfi is an atTrjyta APPENDIX A. 183 where the proposition assumed is the ebnclusion which ought to be proved. 2] It is not easy to say what is the vicious construction that Aristotle contemplates. Euclid postulates the power of drawing any circle from a given centre with a given radius, that is, the use of the compasses as well as of the ruler. Some geometer may have attempted the impracticable feat of solving the pro- blem without the help of this postulate. 3] Perhaps for tj trjXov on we should read bion ^. Compare below, fj ru avrurrpe^nv r) ru S-neadai. Or we might read, el hrjXovoTi, except that brjkovoTi in the sense of ' that is to say' belongs to a later period of Greek. 4] The meaning of rpoVos is not obvious. 5] Assuming the conclusion to be affirmative, let us examine a syllogism in Barbara : — All S is A, All C is S, .-. Ml C is A. And let us first suppose that the major premiss is a petitio prin- cipii, i. e. that the proposition All B is A is identical with the proposition All Gis A. This can only be because the terms B and G are identical. Next let us suppose that the minor premiss is a petitio prin- cipii, i. e. that the proposition All C is 5 is identical with the conclusion All Cis ^. This can only be because B and A are identical. The identity of the terms is their convertibility or their sequence {vTiapx^h ?wcTat). This, however, requires some limi- tation, for as the major is always predicated {vTidpxei, iireTai) of the middle and the middle of the minor, if this were enough to constitute petitio principii, every syllogism with a problematical premiss would be a petitio principii. 6] Perhaps for beUvvrai we should read bemvvriTai, which must otherwise be understood. 7] When the major premiss is the petitio, i. e. when B is A, and C is A, are identical, we may apply the formula ravro rots ovrois virdpxtij 184 NOTES TO A being rawo, and B and C to. aird. When the minor premiss is the petitio, i. e. when C is B, and C is A, are identical, we may apply the formula Tavra t<5 a-Jru vitapxei, B and A being TavTo. and G to avro. 8] Ovberepias. So read, disregarding the MSS., for koL rpha &IJ.(j)0T4pa)s. As the conclusion of the second figure is always negative, it can never be begged by an affirmative premiss, such as the above-cited formulas imply. 9] In the third figure in Disamis, Some £ is A, All ^ is C, . ■ . Some C is A, the major premiss may be a petitio principii, and we may apply the formula to ovto tois aiiTois virdpxei- The minor premiss can never be an assumption of the conclusiouj for their terms are dissimilar [ovk avrCa-Tpotpoi. See below]. 10] If the conclusion is negative, in Celarent of the first figure. No B is A, All C is B, .-. 'No C is A, and Bokardo of the third, Some B is not A, All B is G, . • . Some G is not A, the major premiss may be a petitio principii. The minor premiss cannot, because in these figures it is always affirmative ; besides which, in the third figure the minor premiss and conclusion are not composed of similar terms in similar positions (ovk hirri- orpo^oi) . We may here notice an inaccuracy of Aristotle, if the text is correct. An inspection of the symbols given above shews that the first and third figures require the formula &rh,v to avro knh T&v aiiT&v (diropf^Tai) , whereas the formula oTctv to, avTo, &.m rov aiiTov only applies to the second figure. 11] 'AvTUTTpe^iiv, i. e. &vTi(TTp6^(as ^x^iv. In the second APPENDIX A. 185 figure the only possible petitio principii is in the minor premiss of Camestres : All A is B, ' t No C is B, .-. No C is A. In Csesare, No A is B, All C is B, • .-.No C is A, no petitio principii is possible. Why not ? Because the major premiss and conclusion are not composed of analogous or corre- sponding terms [ovk avTLaTpo(j)OL oi opoi). For diroc^artKovs we should probably read some word expressing the mood which the moderns call Csesare. 186 APPENDIX B. NON CAUSA PRO CAUSA. To 8e /irj naph, tovto av/x^aiveiv rb ■\jrevSos, b TToWdiKLS kv Toh Xoyots elcoOa/jiey Xkyeiv, trpoarrov jikv kcrriv kv rofs eh to dSv- varov avWoyiafiots, orav irpos avri^aa-iv ff tovtov, b eSeiKwro rfj eis TO dSvuaTov^. O^re yap fir] dvTL(f>'^(7ayT0S^ epei to ov napa tovto, aXX &tl yjrevSos Ti eTeOr] tZv TrpoTepov ovt kv ttj SeiKWOva-T), ov yhp TiOrjai Tr]V avTi^acnv. " Etl 8e, OTav dvai- pe6^ TL SfiKTiK&s Slu t5>v a B r, ovK eoTiv eiiTf.iv oas ov iraph TO Keifievov yeykvr)Tai 6 o'vWoyia/ios. To yap fir/ irapit tovto yiveaQai Tore Xkyojiev, &Tav dvaipeOkvTOS ToiJTOv fir/Sev ^ttov Trepaivr/Tai 6 av\Xoyia/i6s. ' Otrep ovk ea-Tiv kv toTs SeiKTiKoir dvaipe6eca-r}s yap Trjs Okaeats ovS" 6 vpos TavTT]v eavepov ovv Sti kv tois els to dSvvaTov XkyeTai to firj irapb, tovto Kal, oTav ovtcds exTj npos to dSvvaTov tj k^ dp)(rj? iiiroOecris, &avepa)TaT0S TpoTTOS ka-rl tov /ifj wapa Trjv iiro- 6eaiv elvai to -^jrevSos, oTav dirb Trjs iinoOkaecos davvatrTOS jj dirb tS>v fieacov npbs Tb dSvvaTOv 6 avWoyia-iibs, wcrrrep eipr/Tai Kal kv ToTs ToTTiKoTs. Tb yhp rb dvaiTiov cos aiTiov TiBkvai TOVTO ka-Tiv. OIov, el ^ovXofievos SeT^ai otl doTJ/iiieTpos fj ■SidfieTpos, kiriyeipoir} Tbv Zrjveovos \6yov SeiKvvvai, d)S ovk ecn KLveicrBai, Kal els tovto drrdyoi Tb dSvvaTov oiiSafi&s yap ovSafifj avveyks^ ka-Ti. rb yjrevSos Trj (f)ds Se Kal a-TeprjTiKwv tZv avXXo- yicTfiZv ovTcov. 'Pavepbv ovv, on tov dSwdTov fifj npos Totbs k^ dpyji^ opovs oi'TOS, ov irapd ttjv Oeaiv a-vfi^aivei to fjrevSos. H ovS OVTCOS del Sid ttjv vTr66eaipe6evTos tovtov, Sid tZv XolttZv wpord- crecov to aiiTb TrepaivrjTai dSvvaTov kwel Tb avTo ye '^evSos irvfi^aiveLv Sid wXeiovmv vtrodeaewv ovSev lercos dTonov oTov to Tas irapaXXrjXovs avuniiTTeiv, Kal ei' fiei^oov kaTlv^ij kvTos Trjs eKTos, Kal ei Tb Tpiyatvov e^ei rrXeiovs 6p6ds SveTv. Anal. Prior, a. 19. APPENDIX B. 189 either from the attribute or superior term of the thesis, or from its subject or inferior term. As an illustration of a connexion with the inferior term, suppose the thesis to be, All B is A, the pre- misses, All D is C, All G is B, and the false conclusion, All B'lsB^. If, eliminating the superior term A, we can retain the premisses. All D is C, All G is B, the conclusion. All B is B, is independent of the thesis. Again, let us trace the connexion to the superior term, and suppose the thesis to be. All B is A, the premisses. All A is E, All E is F, and the conclusion, All A is F'^. Here, too, the conclusion is unaifected by the suppression of the thesis. But when the impossibility is connected with the more remote of the two terms of the thesis, it will be the consequence of the thesis. When, that is to say, an inferior series of terms com- posing the ratiocination is linked on to the superior term of the thesis, so that the first impossible conclusion is. All JD is A, the elimination of A eliminates the imjiossibility ; and when a superior series is linked on to the inferior term of the thesis, so that the first impossible conclusion is, All B is F, the elimination of B eliminates the conclusion. Similarly when the proposi- tions are negative. It is clear, then, that when the impossibility is not enchained to the remotest term of the thesis it is inde- pendent of the thesis, and when it so enchained it is dependent. Or may it not even then be independent? For if, instead of the thesis. All B is A, we had a thesis. All X is A, and the premisses. All JD is G, All G is X, the impossible conclusion. All I) is A, would still I'esult; and similarly if the ratiocination con- sisted of a superior series of terms. As, then, in spite of the suppression of the first thesis the impossibility remains, is not the first thesis irresponsible for the conclusion ? No. The independence of the conclusion and thesis does not mean that a different thesis might lead to the same conclusion, but that, if the first thesis were suppressed, the remaining existing premisses would of themselves involve the conclusion'. Por the same impossibility may easily result from various theses : for instance, parallels may be proved to meet both from the thesis that if a straight line fall upon two parallel straight lines it makes the exterior angle greater than the interior and opposite angle upon the same side^°, and from the thesis that a triangle contains angles equal to more than two right angles". 190 NOTES TO NOTES TO APPENDIX B. 1] This is oddly worded. Perhaps we should read Srav TTpoaiTocli'qa-r] tovto 6 Bet/criis to &bvvaTov, or, orav ■npbi avTl(j>amv TovTov beiKv6r]TaL to abvvaTov. 2] ' AvTicjyrjtravTos, So read for avTuprjo-as. One MS. gives avTiv dvTiKeifievwv fj on tlvS>v tSiv evavTicov rj avTrj Xeyojiev, oTov vyieivov Kal vocrwSovs. To fiev ovv TrdvTCov eK tov 7rpd>T0V, to Se tivcbv eK rov rpirov (^XV' fiaTos. AttX&s ydp ev nda-i, kuOoXov fiev eviardjievov, dvdyKr} rrpos TO KaOoXov tS>v TrpoTeLvo/ievoov ttjv, dvTi^acnv eiireiv. Oiov, el (irj T-qv aiiTTjv d^ioi tcov evavncav irdvTcov, elwovra rwv dvTi- Keifievcov jiiav. OCtco S' dvdyKr] to irpwrov etvai axv/^i^' l^fo'ov 193 APPENDIX C. ENSTASIS, OK OBJECTION. An enstasis^, or objection, is a proposition proving the contra- dictory or contrary of a premiss. It differs from a premiss be- cause it may be particular, while a premiss must be universal, at least for univeral conclusions. An objection has two degrees, and is urged in two figures : it has two degrees because it proves either the contrary or the contradictory of the premiss ; and it has two figures, because it proves the opposite of the premiss, and the opposite (at least if the premiss is negative) can only be proved in the first and third figure. If the premiss is a uni- versal afiirmative, the objection proves a universal negative or particular negative; in the first case the proof is in the first figure, in the second case in the third. Let A represent objects of the same knowledge, or simultaneously known, B contraries, C the knowable and unknowable, I) opposites, E health and dis- ease. If the premiss objected to is. All contraries are objects of the same knowledge, the objection may be either that no oppo- sites are objects of the same knowledge, and the proof will be in the first figure. No B is A, All B is B, .-. No -B is ^2. or it may be that the knowable and unknowable are not objects x)f the same knowledge, and the proof will be in the third figure : No C is A, All C is B, - • . Some B is not A '^- Similarly if the premiss objected to is negative. For if it asserts thg,t no contraries are objects of the same -knowledge, we may 194 APPENDIX C. yotp ytviTai to kuOoXov wpos to k^ ap^rji. ' Ev fiepei Si, npos 6 kvTi KaOoXov Kuff o5 XiyeraL rj irp&raa-ii, oTov yvaxTTOv Kal dyvwcTTOv fif] TTjv avTrjv T& yap kvavTia KaOoXov rrpbs Tavrv Kal yiveTai to TpiTov a-)(r)(JLa- fieaov yap to kv fiepei Xajx^a^ v6[iivov, oTov TO yvcccTTov Kal TO dyvcoa-TOv. E^ d>v yap kari (TvXXoyicTaaOaL TovvavTiov, kK tovtwv Kal t^s kyaTaaeis kiri- )^eipovfj.ev XkyeLv. Aib Kal kK fiovcov t&v axtjuaTaiv tovtodv (f>epofj,ev. Ev fiovois yhp tovtols ol avTiKiifUvoL avXXoyurjioi- Sik yhp Tov fiea-ov ovk ^v KaracpaTiKms. "En Se Kav Xoyov SeoLTO irXeiovos rj Sia tov fikaov (r)(^/j,aTOS' o?ov, ei [i^ Soirj to A tS B indpyeiv Sia to /J,fj aKoXovdeiv avT& to /". Tovto yap Si dXXoav vpoTcicremv SfjXov oii Set 5e els dXXa kKTpkirnrQai TTji' evcTTacnv, dXX evOvs auepav ex^"' "^^^ kTepav TrpoTacriv. Alb Kal Tb arjjif.'iov kK fiovov tovtov tov cr)(^iMaTos ovk ecrnv. ' EiriaKenTkov Se Kal irepl tSiv dXXmv kvcrTaaecov oiov nepl tS>v kK TOV kvavTiov, Kal tov o/ioiov, Kal tov KaTci, So^av Kal et Trjv kv fiepei e/c tov irpmTov ^ ttjv (rTfprjTiKfjv kK tov fikaov Swarov Xa^eTv. Anal. Prior, a. z8. flepl Se. Xvcrewv k)(6/j.ev6u kaTi twv elprjfievayv einelv. EiTTi Se Xveiy fj dvTCipovTai, KaOd- Trep Kal kv roTs tottikoTs, rerpax^y fj yap k^ eavrov, fj kK rod ofioLov, fj kK Tov kvavTiov, ^ e/c rmv KeKpifievmv. Aeyco Se a^ iavrov fikv olov, ei vepl eponTos eir] kvOv/xruia ws a-novSaios, 17 eva-racris Si^ms, ■?] yhp KaOoXov eiTTOvra on nacra evSeia novrj- pov, ^ Kara fiipos on oiiK &v kXeyero Kavvios epcoy el fifj ■rjo'av Kal irovrjpol epcores. E-rrl Se tov kvavnov evarairis (f>epeTai oiov, el TO evOvfiriiia rjv on 6 dyaObs dvrjp iravTas Tois iXovs ev TToie?, aXX' ov^ 6 iioyQTjpos kukcos. 'Ewi Se twv o/ioiav, el riv TO evdvfn]/jia on at KaKms iretrovBores alel /iiaovcnv, oti aXX' ovSe ol eS ireTTOvOoTes alel [ir]v e^eiv, dyvoovfTes yap afiapTavoxxnv, evaraiTii on, ovKovv 6 HiTTaKos alveTos' ov yap dv fiei^ovs (rijiiai kvon /loOeTTjtrev edv ns fie6v(Kovs ev TTOielv T6Tepa (fievKTa koX tov awroii ^Oovs To 8^ koma irdvTa TeTTapa iioui evavTi(i(nv. To yap tovs 0iAovs eS TToieXv tm tovs (^i\ovs Kan&s evavTiov. Topica, a. ']. ' The two first syntheses of contraries are not themselves contraries. Benefiting a friend is not contrary to hurting an enemy, for both are desirable and proceed from the same disposition; nor APPENDIX C. 201 is hurting a friend contrary to benefiting an enemy, for both are undesirable and proceed from the same disposition. But the other four combinations, benefiting a friend^ hurting a friend : benefiting an enemy, hurting an enemy : benefiting a friend, benefiting an enemy : hurting a friend, hurting an enemy j are all respectively contraries/ The fourfold division of enstasis may be illustrated by a four- fold character of propositions and organa. 'Eo-rt 6e irpo'iacrts Sta- XcKTiK^ fpOLS, koI TovToii ^ iraaiv ri rois TrXelarois rj tois fiaXtora yvapCixois, fir) itapa- bo^os. QeCrj yap av Tis to boKovv tois o-o(/)Ois, iav p-r] kvavriov tois T&v voKk&v bo^ais 77. EtVt 8e Trpordcreis biaKeKTiKoi Kai to rots iv- 60'fots ojioia, Koi TavavTia KOt' avTitfjaariv tois boKOV(nv fvbo^ois flvai. TipoTii.vop.iva, KOI o<7ot Bo'^ot KaTCL TtyvO'S etf' Tas evpr]ij,evas. Topica, 1. 10. 'A dialectic proposition is a proposition probable to all or to the majority of mankind ; or an opinion of all or the ma- jority of philosophers or the most eminent of them, not opposed to the opinion of the many ; or a similar proposition respecting similar subjects ; or an opposite proposition respecting opposites ; or any doctrine of the arts/ Tas p^lv'ovv irpoTdcreis fKkeKTeov 6(Tax&s biapta-dri....AeL be TrpoTeiveiv koI ras ivavrCas rals <(>aivop.4- vais fvbo^ois Kar avTi^a(nv \pri(np.ov b\ koH to iroieiv avTas iv T(3 tKXiyfiv firi jjLOVov tos oiio-as evbo^ovs dXAo Koi ras op-oias TOVTais. Topica, 1. 15. 'The propositions to be collected are, as was said before, the opinions of the many or of philosophers, or the doc- trines of the arts ; and we may use any propositions that bear a certain relation to these, i. e. where opposite antecedents have opposite consequents, or similar antecedents similar consequents/ In fact, propositions respecting a given subject, and, mutatis mutandis, respecting similar or opposite subjects, might be treated as identical. Enstasis was the only check on the inartificial induction by simple enumeration practised in dialectic. 'Ear yap eTil navrcov (jiaCvrjTaL biaipeaiv ti poeveynacnv rj em ttoW&v, ^.^lariov /cat KadoKov Tidivai, rt fvorraa-LV ij)epeiv inl tCvos ovx ovtms. 'Eav yap nr)b{Tepov Tutiricv iroifl, &totios (jiavfiTai p-rj TideCs. Topica, a. 3. 'If all or many of the particulars into which a class is divided present an attribute, we may demand either an admission that it is true of the whole class, or an assignment of instances in which it is not 202 NOTES TO APPENDIX C. true. If the respondent does neither one thing nor the other, he is unreasonable/ (Antisyllogism was considered hardly suffi- cient) "Ert 8' ev tols yevenv im^XeTrriov, biaipovvra kut etbr} jxi- Xpi T&v hTojxtov. "Av re yap iravrl (^afor;rat vndpxov av re ^.Trfiivi, TToKKa -npoeviyKavTi a^iaiTeov Ka06\ov o/^ioXoyeii', tj (^ipuv evaraa-LV ivl TWOS ovx ovrcos. Topica, 3. 6. ' Subdivision, as far as we can go, is useful; for whether we want an affirmative or negative proposition, we must first adduce particular examples in which it is true, and then challenge the respondent either to admit the general principle or to allege contradictory instances/ A disputant who is more accustomed to defence than attack may quicken his wits when he has to attack by imagining him- self on the defensive. "En to Trpo^Xruxa TtpoTacriv kavT^ Tioiovfifvov kvia-Taudai' fj yap eva-rains Icrrai ^TTixelprjixa irpbs Trjv Oecriv. Topica, 2. 2. 'The questioner may imagine the thesis to be a premiss against which he has to object as respondent : and his objection to the proposition as a premiss will be a confutation of the pro- position as a thesis.'' A common formula for urging an enstasis, especially when it is directed against a major premiss and is a proposition which the opponent is particularly interested not to contradict, is to say that his argument proves too much : that, if good for any- thing, it proves so and so (the contradictory of the enstasis). In this case, instead of being put directly or ostensively, the enstasis assumes the form of a reductio ad impossibile. 203 APPENDIX D. Koival dp)(ai, or, Method-founding principles. § I. To understand the nature of the common principles {koi- vdi apxai) is to understand Aristotle^s conception of sciencCj and, indeed, his conception of logic ; for his logic is resumed in the contrast of science and dialectic, and this is the antithesis of common and peculiar principles (Ktat Apxai). We propose in the following essay to collect some of the scattered indications of their nature ; and the necessity of explaining more or less com- pletely each passage as it is quoted must be our excuse if our observations seem to foUow one another without much arrange- ment. The most important passage is in the beginning of the Ehetoric : — T&v bi ev6viir\ixaTmv [leyCcTTri bLa(popa km i^dKiara XeArj^uta (r^e- bbv &iiavTas ea-rlv rjitep Koi Tsepl Trjv biaKeKTixriv fxedobov t&v avXko- yi.(T]j.S>v. Ta ju^v yap avT&v eari Kara rqv p7)TopiKr\v mairep Koi Kara Trjv biaKeKTiKTiv^ fiedobov t&v avWoyicrii&v, to. bi kut aWas Te)(vas Kal Swdjuets tcls \j.\v avcras ras 6e oiT:(o'KaTiiXr)p,jj.ivai. Ato Koi \av6avov(n tovs aKpoaras, kol jxaWov a-nTajxevoL r) KaTO, TpoTiov fxera- jSaivovcTLV f^ avT&v' ixoKXov be cra(^es eoroi to Xeyonevov bia TT\fi6- vo)v pr]div. Aeyco yap biaXeKTiKOvs re Kal prjTopLKOvs a-vX\oyicrij.ovs eivai trepl Zv tovs tottovs XiyofxsV ovtoi 8' eluXv ol KOivy irepl bLKa(a>v KOI s TravToiv. liporepov oZv etirw^jLev Trepl r&v elb&v. Rhet. I. 3. ' Between rhetorical proofs the most important distinction, a distinction which has been most commonly, not to say uni- versally, overlooked, is one which also exists between dialectical proofs : some are characteristic of rhetoric or dialectic, others properly belong to certain special sciences or arts, whether such sciences and arts are generally recognized or still remain to be invented. If the science has not yet been established, the theorems and proofs are not familiar to the audience to which they are addressed ; and if the prover adheres too closely to the scientific method, he abandons the proper rhetorical or dialectical method. This requires further explanation. Proofs that properly belong to rhetoric and dialectic are applications of a locus communis. Loci communes are principles that apply indiscriminately to ethical, physical, political problems and other heterogeneous spheres, as, for instance, the argument a fortiori or a minori. A dialectical or rhetorical proof of this character applies equally to ethical and physical questions and other subjects different in kind. Intransferable (that is, not properly rhetorical or dialectical) proofs are composed of propo- sitions which relate exclusively to particular departments of nature. For there are propositions respecting physical objects which furnish no rhetorical or dialectical proof on ethical ques- tions, and there are ethical propositions which furnish no proof on physic^:! problems, and so of the other provinces of science. APPENDIX D. 205 The common principles give no scientific knowledge of any class of things, for they do not constitute theu essence of any class : whereas the peculiar principles if well selected, though people may not be aware of the fact, go towards constituting a parti- cular science, distinct from rhetoric or dialectic. For if the prover happens to hit upon first principles his proof is not rhetorical or dialectical but scientific. Most rhetorical proofs are composed of specific, that is, particular and intransferable propositions ; only a minority are composed of common principles. A rhetorical treatise, therefore, like a dialectical treatise, must distinguish the specific principles of proof from the loci of proof. Specific principles are principles that exclusively belong to a particular class of problems j loci are methods (premisses) of proof that are equally applicable to all classes.' In the last sentence instead of tov9 koivovs we should have expected ras kowch [TrpoTdcreis]. But this passage is one instance of a certain indecision in Aristotle's mind whether to treat the loci as premisses or as methods, as indicative or imperative, as categorical or hypothetical, as constituent principles (in the language of Kant) or as regulative, as objective or subjective, as laws of nature or as rules of procedure. He avoids, there- fore, the unmistakeable term, wporda-ets, and uses the obscurer term, loci. However, even from the present passage, we may certainly infer that the word loci designates premisses. Aristotle does not say. Every proof has two elements ; one is formal or dialectical, the other is material or extra-dialectical : but He says. There are two divisions, two separate classes, of proofs ; one proof is properly dialectical, the other is not properly dialectical. As the specific or sectional character of the pre- misses is the differentia of the one class, the generic or catholic character of the premisses must be the differentia of the contra- distinguished class. We shall see further on [§ 6] that one branch of dialectic may consist entirely of such syllogisms : but considering the subjects handled by the orator, it is clear that in oratorical proofs the maxims [to kolvcl] and specific facts [to. ihia] will be usually combined in the same syllogism. Aristotle would therefore have done better in a rhetorical treatise to found on the distinction of Xbia and Koivd a division not of proofs {ivdvjj.rifj,dTv t&v elh&v T&v XRV'^H-'"^ """^ avayKaiav exovrai ol tottoi. 'E^iiKiynivai yap ai Trporderets wept 'iKacnov elcriv, war' [exojiiei'] ef Ssv Sei v koI e^euv axraH- Toos elkrjixfjievoi fjixiv virdp\ov(n TtpoTepov ol tottoi. 'Eti 6' aXXov Tpoirov KaBoKov Trepl anavTonv \yrjs' oTov el 6 avdpcuiTOi C'^"" '"o f*^ ^ \ap,fidveL. Evlas /*e'iToi eirnTTTj/itas ovbev KcaXvei Ivia Tovratv irapopav, otov rb yivos p,ri vvoTl9e(78ai thai, &i> fj avepov on lort. . . . Kal to, naOti fii) Xaptpdveiv tI , on yvdpiiwv, 'AA\' ovhev rJTTov - rf) ye c^j/o-ei Tpia tuvtSl iarTi, wept 8 Te beiKvvcrL koI h iiUvva-i Kal If &v. An. Post. I. lo. 'In all demonstrative science there are three elements: the subject, whose existence is as- sumed and whose essential laws are developed; the axioms, which belong alike to every science ; and the attributes, whose definition is assumed and whose existence in the subject is the law we demonstrate. When any one of these is obvious, it will be neglected : if the existence of the subject is obvious, an hypo- thesis is not needed : if the definition of a predicate is obvious, it may be omitted. The meaning in the axiom of subtracting equals from equals is too plain for definition. But really there 210 APPENDIX D. are always, three elements of demonstration, the subject, the attributes^ and the catholic canons of proof.' Any classification of the sciences that we choose to adopt will serve as a classification of the specific principles of dialectic {Spyava, elbi]). Aristotle gives one that has had a great currency both in ancient and modern times, though difierent from that which he adopts in his more philosophic writings. He says they may be roughly classed as physical, ethical, and logical (metaphysical). "Eart 8' ws rvira irepiXa^eiv r&v Trpordo-etov koI T&v irpofikrjfji.&Tcav p,€pri rpCa. At fiev yap ■qOiKoi t: porda- f is fl(rlv, al be ^vaiKai, al hi \oyiKaL 'H0i/cai pkv ovv al Toiamai, ohv Ttorepov 8ei rois yoveviri imWov ^ toTs v6p.ois ituQapyjEiv, iav hia- 0coi'5(n" KoyiKcii, hk, otov nonpov t&v evavricav fj avrr] lirior^^?; ^ oii" (f)V(nKa,\ be, Ttorepov 6 /cotrftos d'lSios rj oi' Sp-oias be nal to itpo- ^krni,aTa. Ooiat 8' ?KaoTai r&v TTpoeiprjfjJvav, opurpM nev tniK evTteres wnobovvai itepl avroii', rrj be bia rr]s eTTaya>yfjs a-vvrjOeia Ttei- pariov yviopl^eiv eKda-rriv avr&v, Kara ra npoeiprj^xeva napabeiy\iata ima-KOTtovvra. Topica, I. 14. 'Propositions and problems may be roughly thrown into three divisions, ethical, physical, and logical. Of ethical propositions the following is an instance: Should we obey our parents or the laws when their commands are inconsistent ? of logical the following : Are contraries simul- taneously known or not? of physical the following: Is the world eternal or not? And so of problems. To define these classes would not be easy, but we must endeavour to identify them by practice with the help of these examples.' § 4. In the Topica the word opyava denotes the particular premisses (eXbrj). Aristotle elsewhere, or whoever named his logical treatises opyavov, uses the word in a different significa- tion. In the Topica it signifies the materials (i/Xtj) which are furnished to the artist, and the loci or maxims, as contradis- tinguished from the materials, represent the tools with which he works. But when the name of organon is given to the whole of logic, it denotes the latter, i.e. the loci or purely logical principles, which constitute an organ or faculty of cognition, co-ordinate with the natural organs of perception [Kpir^pia), the eye, the ear, the hand, or with artificial organs of appreciation, the thermometer, chronometer, barometer. When the problem is ethical or physical, there is a difference APPENDIX D. 211 in kind between the organa and loci, and they present the con- trast of special and catholic principles. But when the problem belongs to the third divisionj that is, when it is logical, the dis- tinction disappears, the organa and loci coincide, and logical conceptions are the materials as well as the tools of the dialec- tician. Accordingly in another classification of problems Ari- stotle describes the third division (to. Xoyticci) as instrumental and subordinate theorems, that is, in terms which are equally appropriate to the loci. Ylpo^Kruxa 8' £(ttI biaXsKTiKov ds(&pritia to (niVTfivov rj irpbs aipe(Tiv koi ^vyriv, ?j irpos aXrjd^iav kcu yv&criv, rj avTO ff ms avvepyov Trpos ti trepov t&v toiovtcov. . . . "Evia fjiev yap T&v TtpofiktiixaTtov xp'qcri^wv eiievai Tipbs to kXicrOai r\ (jjvye'iv, olov •noTipov fi rjbovj] aiperbv rj ov, evia 8e irpos to eibivaL fiovov, olov voTepov 6 Koa-jjios Mbios fj oij, ivia h\ avTO, p.ev Kaff avTCL irpos ovbi- Tfpov TovTinv, (Tvvepyb, bi iari Trpos nva t&v roioijTcov. TioKKa yap avra iiip icafl' avTa ov ^ovkop.fQa yvapCCetv, eripcov S' IveKa, S-ncoi biM ToiTmv &XKo ti yvo)p((T(i>p,ev. Top. I. II. 'A dialectic problem is either a practical (ethical) or speculatiYC (physical) theorem, or is subservient to the decision of a practical or speculative question (logical). That is to say, the solution of some pro- blems is useful for our guidance in action, as whether pleasure is to be pursued ; that of others has no end beyond knowledge, as whether the world is eternal : another class are in themselves neither useful nor interesting but are ancillary to ulterior inquiries.' § 5. From our present point of view we may see that Whately's distinction of logical and extra-logical fallacies will not bear examination. He considers that some forms of fallacy, for in- stance, the fallacy of equivocation, are essentially extra-logical. Adopting the theory that logic is conversant not with things or ideas but with words, he says that, whenever to detect a fal- lacy it is necessary to understand the meaning of a word, the fallacy is extra-logical. The logician may happen to know the meaning of the word, but, if he does, he does so not as a logi- cian, but as a moralist or mathematician, or in some other capacity. This is untenable. It is clear that the logician must know the meaning of some terms. He must at least know the meaning of all the terms of his own science. Unless a parrot can be a logician, no one can be a logician to whom the terms P 2 212 APPENDIX D. universal, particular, antecedent, consequent, necessary, contin- gent, are mere words without meaning'. This list may be ex- tended almost indefinitely. If we reflect on what is discussed in logical treatises, we see that the logician requires all the conceptions as well as the vocabulary of — what till we find a better name we will call — ontology {to, \oyiKd). When, there- fore, the problem belongs to the sphere of ontology, the logician, by his logical knowledge, will be able to detect any fallacy that depends on the meaning of the terms, and such fallacies will be purely logical. The dialectician, however, has a still wider range than the pure logician. He has to deal with all ethical or physical conceptions that fall within common cognition (IfSofo, boKovvra tols iroWoTs). Ethical or physical premisses, though special or particular propositions in one sense, that is, in respect of the subjects to which they apply, are common or universal opinions in another sense, that is, in respect of the minds by which they are entertained. Fallacies from the application of principles that lie beyond the range of ordinary information are extra-dialectical (■^evboypaiprJiJ.aTa) . Whether ethical problems can furnish a pseudographema may be doubted. Even the physic of Aristotle's day, composed, as Bacon says with some truth, of vulgar notions loosely abstracted, could hardly farnish argu- ments beyond the competence of the dialectician. Accordingly the only examples of pseudographema that Aristotle gives, are, agreeably to the etymology of the name, geometrical. § 6. Without stopping to discuss the relation of logic in its modern sense to the logic {to, koyiKo) of the Topica, assuming, moreover, that the latter (of whose nature Aristotle has scarcely given us any means of judging beyond the passages already quoted) is the science to which the maxims properly belong, we may regard it as more or less completely identical with ontology or metaphysic. We have already seen (An. Post. i. ii, quoted in § 2), that the common principles are found alike in the par- ticular sciences, in dialectic and in a certain universal science. The name of this science is not given, but we are elsewhere told it is metaphysic or philosophia prima. 'Eirel bi 6 jiia9?jjoionicos XP^roi Tois KoivoHs IbCais, koI ras Toirav apyai h> etij ^ewp^o-ai t^s wpj^Tijs <^t\o(ro(^ios. Metaphysica, 11. 4. 'As the mathematician only makes a limited application of the common principles, their APPENDIX D. 213 adequate investigation belongs to metaphysic/ A paradox here arises. The common principles are the me%as by which the phi- losopher makes himself intelligible to the unphilosophic, they are the intellectual capital, the common sense, of the ignorant, npos 8^ Tas ivreij^ets xPW'^l^os V Ttpayiiarela, Siori ras t&v ■noKK&v KaTXipuBiuinevoi. bo^as ovk e/c t&v &X.\oTp[mv a\)C €k t&v olKelmv 8oy- I/Athv o^uXT^a-onev Ttpos avro-is, p-eTajii^dCovres Sn hv firi koK&s (jtaC- vmvTM Xiyeiv fnuv. Topica, 1.2. • Dialectic is useful to the phi- losopher in his intercourse with the world, because, giving him possession of the creed of the uneducated, it enables him to reason with them on their own principles and to influence their opinions when he thinks them mistaken.' To say that the igno- rant talk metaphysic without knowing it, and that metaphysical reasoning is the reasoning of the uneducated, seems paradoxical, and sounds like the sarcasm of a positivist. But though it is asserted that the principles of the ordinary public are in sub- stance metaphysical, it is not maintained that they apprehend or state them with any precision. Tmha yap (r& koivo) ovhiv rjrrov Itratriv avToC (01 ih&Tai) k&v boK&crt X(av Ifa) Xiyeiv. Sophistici Elenchi, II. 'The uneducated possess the common principles as well as the educated, though their expression of them may be very inaccurate.'' Besides, the truth is, that all reasoning, scientific and unscientific, involves metaphysical principles ; and unscientific reasoning is only called pre-eminently metaphysical, because it is composed in a larger proportion of those abstract principles which, either because they are innate or because they are the easiest and earliest generalizations, are of general accepta- tion, than of the specific facts which can only be learnt by a specially directed observation. 'En bl itpbs ^vfof s ovb' el ttjv aKpt- jSeordrTji; I)^oi/uei' Iwiottj/xiji/ pqbiov am sKeCvris Treiaai XeyovTas' 8i8a- (TKoXlas ydp fffnv 6 Kara ttjv ^■niiTT'qp.r]v \6yos, tovto be oMvarov aW av&yKi] bia t&v koiv&v itoieicrOai, rai iriorets Koi tovs \6yovs, &(n:ep koI ev tois roTTi/cois kKiyofiev irepl Trjs itpbs tovs itoXkovs ivTiiu^eods. Rhet. i. i. 'To some minds the most exact science would not enable us to convey persuasion. A teacher and a learner are implied in the proper scientific proof, and this rela- tion may be out of the question. Then the catholic methods are the only means of persuasion or conviction, as I said in the Topica about the intercourse of the philosopher with the world.' 214 APPENDIX D. Plutarch, or the author of Placita Philosophorum, says that the Stoics (who very likely took the doctrine from Aristotle) held that the axioms, or principles that constitute the logical faculty, are fully developed by seven years of age. T&v 6' ivvoimv al fih s, at 8' ^8)7 81' rjixerepas bibatTKakCas koX i-niixekeCas' avrai, fx^v oBv ^vvoiai KaXovvTai fiopov, SKt'ivaL b^ Kal wpoXTji/^ets. 'O 8^ Xoyos K&ff bv irpoir- ayopevopLfda koyiKol ex t&v •npokqy^remv avfiTiXripoviTdai Xiytrai Kara Trjv 7!p(!>Tr)v efibop.6.ba. 4. 1 1 . ' Ideas are either natural, that is, acquired in the way we have mentioned (sensation and expe- rience had been mentioned), and inartificial, or are artificial and the result of culture. The latter are specially called ideas, the former are specifically called anticipations (axioms). The rea- son, in virtue of which all men are called rational, is formed by the development of the anticipations in the first seven years of life.' In illustration of the statement that logical principles are metaphysical theorems, we might refer to the ontologieal inquiries on which the rudiments of logic are based in the Sophistes of Plato, to the position of the axioms in the Meta- physic of Aristotle, or to the metaphysical discussions in Mill's System of Logic, on the uniformity of nature, on the law of causation, on chance, &c. &c., which lay the foundation for his exposition of inductive method. § 7. After reviewing these general statements on the nature of the loci, if we proceed to examine the list of them given in the Topica and Rhetoric, our first impression is one of surprise. The loci given are not easy to reduce to any common principle, and their common principle, so far as it is perceptible, is not what we might have expected. From Aristotle's apparent iden- tification of the maxims and axioms, we might have expected to find the maxims to be applications or specifications or corol- laries of the axioms. For some reason or other, perhaps to reserve something for his immediate disciples, Aristotle has care- fully avoided giving the loci in the form of propositions, so that it would be rash to assert that the propositions which he con- ceived to be grouped under the loci bear no relation to the axioms : but we may safely say that no such relation is obvious. Many of the loci, most of those given in the Rhetoric, may APPENDIX D. 215 easily be grouped under the category of correlatives. When unable to demonstrate the attributes of any term taken by itself, that isj when we have not materials for scientific reasoning {KaO' avTO, Kar ovaCav), we still may reason dialectically {kut S,\\o, Kara avii^e^rjuos) , by leaving the term and examining another term to which it stands in some definite relation, and then, mutatis mutandis, transferring the attribute of the second term to the first. The mutation to be efiected, or the conditions of the transfer, may be supposed to be expressed in an axiom or topical maxim. Such correlatives are : Contraries, Similars, (giving rise to the methods of induction, analogy, argumen- tum a pari) ; Terms similar in quality and dissimilar in quantity (giving rise to the argument a fortiori and a minori) : Parts (giving rise to the methods of partition and division) : Elements, (giving rise to definition) : Antecedent, Consequent, Name (giving rise to the argument from etymology), &e. &e. But the vast majority of loci in the Topica are of a different nature, and are held together by a different bond of union. The nature of the arguments to be employed in a discussion, and of the rules for their invention, must be determined by the nature of the problem discussed or the thesis controverted. Every proposition that is supported or subverted must assert or deny a relation of subject and predicate, and this relation must be one of four, that is, if ^4 is the predicate and S the subject, the pro- position must assert or deny that A is an accident, or a genus, or a property, or the definition of £. Of course the definitions of accident, genus, property, definition, must decide respectively what is the nature of the proof required in support of any such conclusion. Aristotle accordingly breaks these four definitions mto as many fragments as possible, presents them under as many different aspects as he can imagine, and calls these frag- ments and aspects of the definitions by the name of loci. But the theories of accident, genus, property, are all resumed in the theory of definition : for definition must be a truth or matter of fact {aXriOh elveiv) like accident, and a law like genus and property, besides presenting its own peculiar characteristics. All the loci, therefore, that arise from these four definitions may be grouped under one head, the definition of definition. Up&Tov ovv d«opr]Tiov fK Tivv h'k ol avWoyurfwi, to, TrpojSXTj/xardt eori, Tiouxa h\ -npoTtuns Kal -nav TipoPKrjfm rl yfvos 17 ibiov rj (rvju/SejSrjKds StjXo?. Topica, I. 4. 'Let us first enquire of what branches the method' is composed, and when we have classified conclusions and pre- missesj and shewn how to obtain the latter, we shall have accom- plished our task. The classes of premisses and conclusions, that is, of propositions and problems, are identical ; for every propo- sition and problem expresses either a genus, a property, or an accident/ Property is then subdivided into property and defi- nition. M^ XavQaviTut 8' rums 8n to. irpbs to Xbtov koI to yivos koH Th (n;jw./3e^r;K(5s irdura Kot irpos tovs opuriMrus app.6afi Xiyecrdcu ilore Kara tov ip/npovdev amohoOivTa Koyov S/iravr &v ewj TpoTtov Tiva opiKa TO, KarripiOfiriniva. Topica, 1,6. ' The rules for pro- perty, genus, and accident all apply to definition: so that all the rules may be regarded as rules of definition.' Upos (xev oSv TO avfi^e^riKOi bia t&v toioiutwv koI oSrmy kTuxeiprfriov. Mera 8^ ToSro TsepX t&v npos to yivos Kal to ibiov liturKemiov. 'Eirn tik TavTa aroiysia t&v wpos tovs opovs' 'nepl aiiT&v 8^ ToiTiav oKvy&KK al o-KEi/cets yivovrai rots bidkeyofiivois. Topica, 4. I. 'After these rules for disproving accident, the rules for examining pretended genus and property must be expounded. These will be elements of the method of testing definition. Genus and property are seldom themselves the final object of dialectic discussion.' T^s 8^ TTfpl rois opovs TTpayixaTeCas ft^ipr] TtivTi kaTiv. *H yap on oAtos ovK iXrjO\s eLTteiv, Kaff' o5 Tovvop.a, Koi tov \6yov (Sei yap tov toS avOpdirov opKrpJbv Kara navros avBpditov akridev&Tdai) ^ on ^iiros yevovs ovk eOrjKev eis to yevos rj ovk els to oiKeiov yivos Idrj/ce (8ei yap tov opiCofievov (Is to yevos OivTa ray hia^opas itpoaaTtTeiv pA- Atora yap t&v ev tS opurp^ to yivos hoKel ttjv tov 6piCop,ivov ovcrlav (rriixaCveiv) , rj otl ovk tbtxis 6 Aoyos {bet yap Tbv opuifiov Ihiov eivoi), ri el Ti&VTa to. elprip.iva Treiroiijiccis ju^ &piv. Urns 6' evTroprja-oiiev avrol Ttpbs to TtOepifvov del (rv\Koyi(TiJ,&v, kcu, 6ta TToCas obov \r]\}f6iji,e6a ras irtpl iKaa-TOV apxAs, pvv rjbr) KiKTeov. Ov yap [iovov terms Sei ttjv yivediv Oecopeiv T&v avkXoyi,(Tfj,&v, aXKa koI ttjv bvvaixiv ^x^iv tov ■noulv. Anal. Priora, i. 37. ' The nature of syllogism and the number and relations of its terms and premisses, and the figures in which any conclusion may be proved, have been explained. It re- mains to point out the sources from which we may obtain them and the method of discovering premisses for each conclusion : for we want not only to know the way in which proofs are pro- ducedj but to acquire a power of producing them.' He after- wards recapitulates in similar terms. 'Er woVots p.iv olv v ?] TOWS optcrfiois 8i' Siv al aTrobfC^eis, ov 8ofa(ret dA\' iiriarrrjcreTai' el 8' dX?j5rj jxiv etvai, ov nivToi Tavrd ye ovtols vnApxeiv kut' ovalav KoJ Kara to eibos, Sofdo-ei Kot ovk eTTior^crerai dKr]d&s. An. Post. I. 33. ' When the belief of a necessary law is founded on defi- nitions which serve as the basis of demonstration, the belief is not opinionative (dialectic) but scientific : whereas a belief in the same proposition, without the knowledge that it is deducible from the definition or essence of the terms, is not science but opinion.' 'Eksivos 6' evXoycos efijret ro rC ecni, a-vWoyi^ecrdai yap ^■qTei, apxTj 8e t&v (rvWoyiafi&v to tC eanv. AiaXeKTiKT} yap to-xiis ojjffo) tot' ?jvj cSore bijvas, ror/s r' eTraKTiKoiis \6yovs Kal to opl^ea-dai Ka66\ov Tavra ydp eariv dju^o) irepl dpxrjv eniarrip.yii. Met. 12. 4. ' It was natural that Socrates should seek for definitions, for he wanted proof, and definitions are the foundation of proof. Men were not then aware of the resources of dialectic, which enable us to dispense with definitions in discussing the Socratic pro- blems ; and two procedures may be fairly assigned to Socrates, induction and definition ; both of which aim at laying the foundation of deductive science.'' From what has preceded, it appears that these statements must be accepted with some re- serve. Dialectic as well as science is based on definitions, though on definitions of objects of a different order. The defini- tions on which science rests are definitions of a peciiliar subject- matter and its attributes (tSta), those on which dialectic rests are definitions of fact, law, cause, experience, definition, proof, that is of certain catholic relations permeating every sphere (Koivd). Equipped with definitiqns of these shadowy abstractions, dialectic 222 APPENDIX D, in entering the controversial lists with the sole purpose of con- structing opinion can dispense with the more solid and concrete special information which scientific method requires for the evolution of genuine knowledge. Unsubstantialj however^ as are these ahstractions, they occupv in this art the position of final causes, so that, from this point of view, the maxims may be regarded rather as imperative and hypothetical than as indicative or categorical. This character is suggested by the formula Aei, which so often occurs in the Topica. (See end of § 7-) Another term, to, TraprjyyfXfieva, pre- cepts of art, suggests the same conclusion. T&v be irpos ramov KaTaa-Kivaa-TlK&v Toitav o^Sets \p-qv ttjs AiroSetJfws. Aiatf>4p€i yhp eheiv bia t[ ^povr^ koI tC ian ^povTrj. 'Epei yhp ovTia /x^v biSTL imotrfiivvvTai Tb "nvp Iv rots vetpeffC rl 8' iarX fipovTrj j \l/6(f)0s imoff^fvuvnivov itvpbs iv v^v a^twfiaraji; ayrri -nAvrav. Met. 3. 3. ' This is of all principles the most certain, and the one to which all demonstra- tion appeals in the last resort ; for it is the natural basis of all other axioms".^ From the preceding analysis it appears that a single step of the method of agreement is an application of a definition and postulate by an agglutination of at least six ele- mentary syllogisms.] Next let the problem be, to find the cause of a given effect. '' We may observe a in two different combinations, abc and ade; and if we know or can discover that the antecedent circum- stances in these cases respectively were A B G and ADE, we may conclude by a reasoning similar to that in the preceding 6 " A general proposition inductively obtained is only then proved to be truie, when the instances on which it rests are such that if they have been correctly observed, the falsity of the generalization would be inconsistent with the constancy of causation ; with the universality of the fact that the phenomena of nature take place according to invariable laws of succession." Mill on Positivism. APPENDIX D. example that A is the antecedent connected with the consequent a by a law of causation. B and C, we n^^y say, cannot be causes of a, since in its second occurrence they were not present ; nor are D and E, for they were not present on its first occurrence/' Method of difierence. "In the method of agreement we endeavoured to obtain instances which agreed in the given cir- cumstance but differed in every other : in the present method we require, on the contrary, two instances resembling one another in every other respect, but differing in the presence or absence of the phenomenon we wish to study. ... If the effect o{ A B G ia abc, and the effect of B C, he, it is evident that the effect of A is a. So again, if we begin at the other end, and desire to investigate the cause of an effect a, we must select an instance, as ahc, in which the effect occurs, and in which the antecedents were ABC, and we must look out'"' [kiti^XeitTiov] " for another instanee in which the remaining circumstances be occur without a. If the antecedents in ^hat instance are B G, we know that the cause of a must he A. . . . The axioms which are taken for granted in this method are evidently the following : WhatevefS antecedent cannot be excluded without preventing the pheno- menon, is a cause or a condition of that phenomenon ; whatever consequent can be excluded with no other difference in the ante- cedents than the absence of a particular one, is the effect of that/ one." [Definition, or corollaries from the definition, of cause or effect.] " Instead of comparing different instances of a pheno- menon to discover in what they agree, this method compares an instance of its occurrence with an instance of its non-occur- rence to discover in what they differ. The canon which is the ^■egulating principle of the method of difference may be expressed as foUows: — If an instance in which the phenomenon under investigation occurs, and an instance in which it does not occur, have every circumstance save one in common, that one occurrmg only in the former ; the circumstance in which alone the two instances differ is the effect or cause, or a necessary part of the .effect or cause, of the phenomenon. . . .The method of agreement stands on the ground that whatever can be eliminated" (can be absent consistently with the existence of the phenomenon) "is not connected with the phenomenon by any law. The method of difference has for its foundation, that whatever cannot be 230 APPENDIX D. eliminatedj is connected with the phenomenon by a law." [Defi- nitions, or corollaries from the definitionj of causation.] The preceding exposition suggests several observations. The\ foundation and keystone of inductive method, it appears, is ther definition of causation. The foundation of dialectic method isj the definition of definition. If a definition is a causal proposi- tion, as Aristotle asserts in the Analytica, these two foundations ought to coincide. But when Aristotle enumerated the loci of definition in the Topica, he does not seem to have attained to the view which he explains in the Analytica, that the scientific definition of a phenomenon is the declaration of its cause. The principal branch of his Logic is founded on the definition of science, which is declared to be the knowledge of causes. 'EirC- (rraa-Oai olofXiOa ^KacrTov orav Trjv t ahCav oltiixiOa yivdxTKfiv hi i}v TO -npayiiA kcrriv, on eKeivov airCa IcttI, koX fifi h'bexeaOai tovt ttXA-ffls Ixetv. An. Post. i. a. 'Science is the knowledge of necessary facts and their causes.' But instead of deducing from this conception the method of inductive science, a problem that asked the aid of the philosopher, he merely developes from it theorems respecting the nature of deductive science, a province which might have been safely left to the fostering care of the mathematicians. Hegel was full of the notion that certain metaphysical ideas were capable of being developed into regula- tive principles and furnishing methods of reasoning; but he never advanced beyond the haziest generalities, in which none but the cloudiest intellect could find satisfaction. It is to Mill that the honour belongs of solving the problem that had so long hovered before the eyes of philosophers, and shewing how the idea of cause can be developed into various methods of rigorous scientific inference. Definition, which perhaps at some periods in the history of logic was unduly exalted as a scientific process, undergoes in Mill's System of Logic, along with syllogism, a deal of vili- nihili-parvi-pauli-pili-nauci-fiocci-fication, and is degraded from all her dignities. But for the ultimate foundation and evi- dence, and the sole foundation and evidence, of inductive me- thod as expounded in this system, we are forced, as we have seen, to have recourse, reversing the bill of attainder passed against them, to definition and syllogism. Induction in its APPENDIX D. 231 strictest sense seems to be merely the idealization or universal- ization of a singular fact, the transformation of the proposition, this ^^C is followed hy abe, into the proposition, all ABC is followed by abc. The faculty of making this transformation can, doubtless, not be identified with, or made dependent on, the syllogistic faculty. But if, as in Mill's writings, the word in- duction is used to signify the whole process of discovering first principles (68os eTri rhs &px^i)) then it appears, as we noticed when quoting his exposition, that every single step of induction is a crowd, at least an ample cluster, of syllogisms. Instead, then, of declaring with Mill, that all deduction is induction, it appears more accurate to assert that all induction is deduction. The two elements, one general the other special, which Ari- stotle found in dialectic and demonstration, are also to be dis- tinguished in inductive science. Inductive method, as we saw (§ lo) was the case with dialectic, assumes one definition and proves another. The definition assumed, that of causation, throws equal light on all inquiries, i. e. is a catholic principle (koivt] apxifj) : the definition proved is a causal proposition, or law of causation in a special department of nature, and is a truth confined to a particular science {ibCa apxij). Here we may resume a former topic. Aristotle objected (see § 8, quoting Anal. Post. a. 6) to a proposed proof of definition, in which one premiss should express the conditions of definition, and the other assert their fulfilment, that every proof ought to have some apparent cogency prior to any express exhibition of logical rules and apparatus. If we consider the mode of reasoning in the methods of agreement and difference, we shall perceive that Aristotle's objection is by no means fatal, and that his requisition can be easily satisfied. The man who, assuming the validity of the methods of agreement and difference, shews the invariable and unconditional antecedent, let us say, for example, of dew, has demonstrated its definition without expressly invoking any logical or metaphysical canons. If an unconvinced critic de- mands further satisfaction, he may justify the process by appeal- ing in the way Mill indicates to the axioms and canons of in- duction. Another point that has been discussed will receive light from the same consideration. We observed (§ i) that the dialectic 232 APPENDIX D. maxims may either be regarded as constitutive or as regulative, i, e. either as premisses or as methods. The same is true of the inductive canons. Possibly no inductive operator ever reasoned as Mill reasons to shew the cogency of his methods. The in- vestigator of nature employs the methods without troubling himself about the metaphysical or ontologieal principles on which they are based. But if he would demonstrate the validity of the methods^ these metaphysical or ontologieal principles must be expressed and furnish the premisses of proof. § 1^. This seems the proper place for a few words concern- ing the celebrated question, whether definition is susceptible of proof? In the Topica Aristotle had asserted it is. Avaipiiv ij.\v oSv opov ovtcos km bia tovtoiv ael Tteipareov. 'Eav 6^ KaTaa-KtvdCeiv ^ouXcifieda, itp&Tov p.\v elbevai, bei on ovbels fj oAtyoi T&v biaXeyofi&iav opov (rvWoyi^ovrai, aWa irAvTes is cipXV^ 70 TOLovTov kap.^6.vov(TLV olov olVc Ttspl yebip.eTpiav xal apidnoiis kclL Tas oKkas ras rotavTas fxaOi^aeis. Ei9' on 6t' UKpi^eias piiu &\Kris fcrrl TipayixanCas AirobovvM kw, tl itmv opos koI ii&s opi^eaOai bti. NCj; 6 , B,(Tov iKavov vpos riji) ■napovirav xpeiav, too-ovtov p-ovov Ae/c- t4ov, on 8iii'aroi' yeveadai 6piap,ov kol tov tl ^v elvai (TvWoyiapAv. Et yap io'Tiv opos Aoyos 6 to tC ^v ilvai tu Tipayp.aTi bri\&v, itot 8el TO, fv 7(0 8p

avtpov, &)s et ns Aci/Soi Tavra povov ev r&i t( eort roi; ■npiyp.aTOS KaTriyop€ia-6aL, otl 6 TavTa ^)(a>v \6yos opos ii avdyicqs &v elrf ov yap kvbi)(iTai hepov eivai opov toiJ irpdypaTos, itreibri ovbfv iTfpov ev ru n' eort toS T,p6,yp,aTos KaTriyopilTai. "On p,ev ovv ky)(Uipv, crv\- Xoyicrpov opov yeviaOai, ^avepov. Topica, 7. 2. ' The disproof of a definition employs the foregoing topics. As to the proof, we must observe, in the first place, that defi- nitions are rarely or never proved by the questioner in dialectic discussion, but are assumed as a basis of proof, as in geometry, arithmetic, and similar sciences. In the second place, the exact rules for the form and process of definition belong to another method, and we have now merely to say what may suffice for the present occasion. We say, then, that essence and definition are susceptible of proof. For if definition is a proposition de- claring the essence of a thing, and is composed of all the predi- cates that say what it is, that is, of all its genera and differentise, APPENDIX D. 233 it follows that if certain predicates fulfil these conditions in re-- gard to a given ternij the proposition in which they are resumed is the definition of that term, and there can be no other defi- nition, for there are no other generic predicates. It is clear, then, that we may prove a definition/ This seems to be plausi- ble enough, and may be made more so if a little differently worded. If we assume a priori that a certain relation of terms is the relation of effect and cause, or of phenomenon and defi- nition, and find a posteriori by appropriate evidence that this Nation exists between two given terms, we may conclude that these terms are related as effect and cause, or as phenomenon and definition. In the Analytic, however, Aristotle asserts that such a proof, which he calls hypothetical, is vitiated by a petitio principii. 'AA\' Spa lori koI airobd^ai to tC icm kut ovcriav, ef VTroBicreats be, kafiovra to ijl^v tI rjv ewai sk t&v iv ra tC eariv Ibmv, Tabl be iv tu t[ eo-ri jiova, kcu, Ibiov to vav. Tovto yap iaTC TO ilvai. iKiivto. H TtaKiv fiKrj^e to tl rjv ftvai KWrkv tovt(o ; avayKt) yap bia tov /xeVov Setfat. An. Post. a. 6. ' Is definition sus- ceptible of a hypothetical proof, if we assume as our major that the i-eeiprocating or convertible combination of essential predi- cates is the definition ; and as our minor, that certain predicates are essential, and, when combined, reciprocate with the subject ; and then conclude that these predicates compose its definition ? No : here, as in the former case, the minor premiss is a petitio principii.' Accordingly his definitive doctrine appears to be that definitions are indemonstrable. *H to. irpma opicrixol iaovTai avaitobeiKToi. An. Post. 2. 3. ' The first principles are indemon- strable definitions.' Without controverting his assertion, that the proof of a definition is not demonstrative, we maintain that the reason he alleges is untenable. It is clear that if the prior definition assumed as a premiss in order to prove a definition is a definition of the same term, as in one of the modes of proving definition which Aristotle examines, there is a petitio principii, and, if the possession of the prior definition means anything beyond the power of rightly applying a name, or of recognizing an object when presented to sensation, such a proof hardly de- serves the name which Aristotle concedes it, of dialectical {Koyi- Kos] proof. Ovros fxiv ovv 6 Tpoiros 5tl ovk liv dr] anobeiiis, eipriTai tipoTepov, aW" iaTt KoyiKos (TvKKoyi.ffp.bs tov tC ia-Tiv. An. Post. a. 8. 234 APPENDIX D. But in the hypothetical proof, or, what is a similar process, the establishment of causal propositions by the methods of induction, the definition assumed (that of essence or cause) is a general or metaphysical definition (koivov), the definition to be established is a specific or scientific definition (tbiov). The things defined are quite disparate, the premisses are distinct from the conclu- sion, and therefore there is no petitio principii. How then did Aristotle come to imagine that there was this vice in the proof? The cause of the hallucination seems to have been his own tauto- logical way of defining definition or essence. His account, in efiect, amounts to this : Definition {t6 tC ^r eivai) is composed of — ^the elements of definition (ra ev tu tC eort), or, essence is composed of — the elements of essence. From so tautological and unmeaning a premiss it would have been strange if any conclu- sion could be drawn without a petitio principii. That he was doubtful of the conclusiveness of his own reasoning we may infer from his adding another objection, which we have already discussed, § 8. The true avenue to a possibility of error in the proof of essence or causation lies, as Mill has indicated, in the fallibiliiy of observation. " But if we cannot artificially produce the phe- nomenon A, the conclusion that it is the cause of a remains subject to very considerable doubt This arises from the diffi- culty of assuring ourselves that A is the only immediate ante- cedent common to both the instances. If we could be certain of having ascertained aU the invariable antecedents, we might be sure that the unconditional invariable antecedent or cause must be found somewhere among them.'' This applies to the method of agreement, and the method of difference may be vitiated by similar non-observation. Another method whereby it had been proposed to prove defi- nition entirely a priori, namely, the method of division, is justly charged by Aristotle with involving a series of petitiones prin- cipii. "On 6' ^ 8i^ T&v yev&v biaCpecris yuKpov rt fwpiov ecru rrjs elpriiJiivris p.ed6bov, pqbiov Ibeiv. "Ecm yhp fj biaCptcris oTov &(T0evris av\koyuTiM6s' h fiev yap bei bei^ai aheiTai, avXXoyC^eTai 6' aeC ti r&v ava>0ev. IIp&Tov 6' amb tovto i\e\rj6ei tovs xP"'!^^*"^'"^ "ir^ iidvTas, Koi TteiOeiv iTrexfCpovv m ovtos bvvarov Trepl ova-Cas aitobei^iv yCve- uQai Koi. Tov t( iv, k&v jutj <^5 " amoKpivo- aevos. An. Post. 3. 5. ' The conclusion of the process is deficient in necessity : now a conclusion should not be a matter of ques- 236" APPENDIX D. tion or concession, but the inevitable consequence of the pre-? misses, unaffected by concession or denial.' In the inductive method the decisive premisses are gained by interrogation, not of a disputant but, of nature : and a criterion, somewhat hastily rejected as unscientific, plays an essential part in the process. Tis 6vv d\Aos TpoTtos [jov Tr\v oviriav rj to tI kcTTi huKVvvaC] Koasos; ov yap bri Sei'fet ye rfj alaO'qa-ei rj tu baKTvXa. An. Post. 3. 7. ' What other method remains ? The definer, surely, does not point out the essence with his finger as an object of sensation ?' If, then, the coUigative or phenomenal definition cannot be proved, we still maintain, looking at the modern methods of in- duction, that the more important, the inductive or causal defini- tion, is capable of proof. The assumption, however, of so catho- lic a principle {kowti apxq) as the definition of causation, to say nothing of the admitted possibilities of error in observation, re- moves the proof from the sphere of deductive science or demon- stration (dTToSeifis), which rests exclusively on axioms and tbtai apxaC, to that of dialectic, or, to speak more accurately, philo- sophic, method. So much for the limit of the power of the catholic or methodic principles working on the special data of experiment and observation. § 14. The reader may desire to have some specimens of the dialectic maxims, about which so much has been said. As we have stated, Aristotle avoids formulating them in the Topica; but the schoolmen coined them in abundance after his indica- tions. The following are taken from Sanderson's Compendium. They are divested of all reference to the predicables, and to each maxim are appended certain limitations or exceptions, which he calls fallentise. In dialectic the falsity of the maxim, that is, its employment without due limitations and qualifications, though it led to a false conclusion, was not considered to make the argu- ment sophistic; but we have stated our opinion (see notes to ch. viii), that in pirastic at least such false premisses constitute the proof a sophism. Loci a causa et efiectu : — Posita causa, ponitur efiectus, et sublata tollitur. Fallit in causa impedita : ut gravia non semper descendunt, quia possunt ab aliquo impediente prohiberi. Posito effectu, ponitur causa, et sublato tollitur. APPENDIX D. 237 Fallit in effectu permanente post causam ; ut manet sedifieium mortuo sedificatore: in effectu prodnpibili a diversis causisj ut potest esse mors non epoto veneno : in effectu causse quae ali- quando fuit ; ut corruere potest sedifieium superstite sedificatore. Here we have the materials for the methods of agreement and difference, but the architect was wanting. Loci a subjecto et accidente : — Posito subjectOj ponitur accidens Sublato accidente, toUitur subjectum. Posito antecedente, concomitante, consequente, ponitur conse- quens, concomitans, anteeedens : ut, si est eclipsis, est plenilu- nium. Fallit si non est mutua necessitas ; ut quamvis, si est eclipsis, est plenilunium, non tamen si est plenilunium, continuo erit eclipsis. Loci ex oppositis et comparatis : — Posito altero relatorum ponitur reliquum, et sublato toUitur. Posito uno eontrariorum, tollitur alteram. Fallit in remissis qualitatibus ; quia remissio qualitatis fit semper per admistionem contrarii. Sublato uno eontrariorum, ponitur alteram. Fallit in contrariis mediatis-; ut mel nee album nee nigrum est, sed flavum. Contrariorum eontraria est ratio ; ut si frigus congregat hete- rogenea, calor secernit. Fallit in ratione subjecti; ut quia sanitas convenit animatis, non propterea morbus inanimatis: et in eausis quarum actio determinatur a dispositione materise; non enim emollit lutum frigus, quia indurat calor. Posito altero contradictoriorum, tollitur reliquum, et sublato ponitur. Similibus et proportionatis similia conveniunt et proportion- aliaj dissimilibus et improportionatis dissimilia et non propor- tionalia. Fallit nisi intelligatur reduplicative, de similibus qua similia ; omne enim simile est etiam dissimile : unde non sequitur corvum rationalem esse, quia ^Ethiops est rationaUs. Maximae comparatse rationis sunt istse : — Eorum quse seque sunt aut non sunt talia, si unum est tale, et reliquum, si non est, nee reliquum. 238 APPENDIX D. Si quod magis videtur esse tale, non est, etiam quod minus videtur esse, non eritj ut, non placuit omnibus Homerus, qui placebit Msevius ? Si quod minus videtur esse, est tale, etiam id quod magis ; ut, fur si est suspendio dignus, certe dignior sacrilegus. Loci a conjugatis (otJotoixo) : — Quorum unum convenit alteri, eorum conjugatum unius con- venit conjugate alterius et negative similiter ; ut, si albedo est color, et album erit coloratum. Fallit arguendo a eoncretis ad abstracta; ut, non propterea albedo est dulcedo, quia album est dulce : et arguendo ab ab- stractis ad conereta; ut, quia nulla albedo est dulcedo, non propterea nullum album erit dulce. Loci a toto et parte : — Posito toto, ponuntur partes. Fallit in toto mutilatoj ut potest esse homo, quantumvis amputato digito vel manu. Sublato toto, partes tolluntur. Positis partibus, ponitur totum. Loci a divisione : — Membrorum condividentium uno aut altero sublato, ponitur reliquum, et posito toUitur. &c., &c., &c. The criticism suggested by these numerous but inefficacious maxims is contained in a homely Greek proverb : — IloW olb' A\(^TTjjf, dW' i\ivos kv iifyd. ' Many tricks knows reynard ; one good one suffices the hedgehog.'' APPENDIX E. LIMITS TO THE COMPETENCE OP PIRASTIC. It would not be surprising, if, after the performances of Socrates with the elenchus, some of the Soeratici viri overesti- mated the power and value of pirastic. The professed function of pirastic is to examine a man's pretensions to a given science, although neither the examiner nor the auditory are themselves in possession of it j and in the infancy of all the sciences, and the absence of faculties or universities to pronounce on anybody's attainments, there was doubtless abundant scope for its exer- cise. In the Charmides, where pirastic as producing self-know- ledge is discussed under the name of sobriety, [i. e. a-ca(ppoa-6vri as opposed, not to aicokacrCa but, to )(avv6Tris or oA.afoi'eta, an am- biguity which we need not pause to discuss,] it is shewn that pirastic alone is not competent to the discharge of this function. To test a man's possession of a given science the examiner ought to possess not only the theory of science in general, i. e. logic, but also a knowledge of the theorems and methods peculiar to the particular science in question. "On /xev 8^ eTrurrrjiirjv rtva Ij^et, yvdcrfTai 6 caxfiputv top larpov kiti^eip&v h\ 8^ -neipav X.aj3etv iJTK kariv, aXKo tl a-Ke^erai 3iv tiv&v ; . . . Ovkovv iv tovtoh &vay- Koiov a-KOTteiv rbv ^ov\6p.evov larpiKriv a-KOTSiiir, kv ots ttot ea-riv. Oil yap briTTOv iv ye rois efo) ev oh ovk ^s OKOTSO'CjJ.evos, — ■"EotKev. — ''H oSv aveu laTpLKrjs b-6vaiT av ns Toirotv TioTipois kicaKoXovdr](TaL ; — Ov brjra. — 0^8^ ye &\kos ovbeCs, ws loiKe, Ttkriv iarpos, ovre 6?j 6 ^" ^^ "^^0 lJiO.vd6.vri, pa6v re fiadrj- trerai, koI ivapyia-repa TrdvTa avra ^aveirai, are irpos exdoTu s flTrfw ras r^xvas* aTjobCboiJifv 8^ to xpCvftv ovbiv tjttov TDK ■neiraibevp.fvot.s rj tois flb6(Tiv. "ETretra Koi Ttepl ri^v aXpecrw Tov avTov h.v bo^eiiv l)(eiv Tpoirov. Kal yap to e\4a-dai opO&s t&v ■€lhorrfi.iTp7)V re t&v y€a)p,eTpiK&v Kal KvjSepvi^- Ttiv T&v KV^fpvrjTiK&v. El yap KOi mpl fvicov epytav Kal rexv^v fieriypvai Kal t&v ibia>T&v Tivis, oKX' oiJrt t&v etboTav ye pJaXkov. . "Qo'Te (cara fiiv tovtov tov Kcyov ovk &v eijj to TrKijOos iroirjTiov Kvpiov oiTf T&v apxaipea-L&v ovre t&v evQvv&v. 'AW' Xfrws ov TT-dvTa TavTa kiyer^u Ka\&s bia re tov TidKai, \6yov. . . . koI on iiepl iviav otire fiovov 6 TToirjaas otjt api(TT &v KpCveiev, ocrmv r&pya yiyvdta-KOWi KoX ot p,r\ fxovTfs ttjv t^x*"?"! "^o" oiKiav ov fwvov eort yv&vai TOV irotijcrairos aWa Kal fie\Tiov 6 )(piip,evos avTfi nptvei, XpfJTat 8' 6 oiKov6p,os, Kal TtribdMov Kv^epv^T-qs rekTovos, xal Qoivr)v 6 baiTvpMv ak\' ovx b jxAyeipos. Pol. 3. ii. 'The hypothesis that the people are qualified to elect and oontrol the magistrates presents a difficulty, because to judge whether the medical func- tions have been rightly performed a man ought to be able to perform them himself, that is, ought to be a physician j and so in the other arts and sciences. As, then, a physician ought to be judged by physicians, so ought other functionaries to be judged by their peers. Now the title of physician may be given either to the person who practises, or to the person who com- bines practice Vidth theory, or to the person who does not prac- tise but has had an education in medical science. Some hold this position in every province, and are thought as competent to judge as the scientific. The same may be said in respect of the electoral power. Qualification to select requires knowledge, and a geometer can only be rightly selected by geometers, a pilot by those who know the pilot's art. If there are any func- tions and operations of which the uneducated are competent to judge yet they cannot be more competent than the educated. According to this reasoning the people should not have the power of election or control ; but perhaps it is open to objection. 242 APPENDIX E. both on other grounds and because there are certain operations of which the artist is not the sole nor the best judge, nor go good as a person who knows nothing about the art j as a house is better appreciated by the householder than by the architect, a rudder by the steersman than by the shipwright, a banquet by the banqueter than by the cook.'' llepl ■navav Oewpiav Koi fxidobov ojuouuf raiTfivoTepav re Kol TLixunTepav bvo (paivovTai rpSitoi Trjs ?^ea)s ftvai, &v TrjV iJ,iv iiiiv. Tolovtov yap brj Tiva xal rbv SAcos ire'naibevp.ivov OLop,ed ftvai, Kal TTeTtaibeiia-dai to bvvaaOai TTOifiv to flpripivov. TSkrjv TovTov iji,\v lapl irdvTcov as eiweiv two, KpiTiKov vop.l^op,€V, iva TOV apiOiwv ovra, tov hi Tiepi twos ^weus d^copLO-p^vris' elri yap &v TLs ^Tepos TOV avTov rpoTTov biaKeLiJ,fvos t^ €lpr\p,iv)s ia-TopCas bei Tivas vnap\(iv opovs toiovtovs, Trpos o^s avac^ipav amobi^erai tov TpSirov T&v beiKwixiviov \(iip\s tov Tt&s Ix*' TaK7)des, etre oiItcos e?T€ dAXms. De Partibus Animalium, i . i . ' Every theory and method, how- ever humble or exalted its function, has two degrees in which it may be mastered, one of which may be called science, the other education. Education makes a man a competent judge of the performances of the professional artist. Such a compe- tence belongs to universal education, and indeed constitutes its criterion. But while some are thus competent to criticize in every province, others have a corresponding power in a limited province. Physiology then, like other sciences, must have certain canons by which, as by a standard of reference, a critic will judge a writer's method of demonstration, irrespectively of the truth of his doctrines.' Prom this passage it is clear that, according to Aristotle, there are as many branches of education as of science ; and that if he speaks of logic as education it is not as universal education but only as one of many branches, though perhaps one of the most important. *Ocra 6' eyxeipoCcrt t&v XfyovTwv Tivis irepl rrjs oXt)- 6e[as hv TpoTTOV bei dTrobi^ea-Oai, 8i' &iraibev(T(av t&v Siva\vriK&v TovTO bp&tnv. Aei yap wept tovtoiv rJKfiv •npoeTtiarap.ivovs aXKa fwj iiKoiovTas Crireiv. Met. 3. 3. ' Discussions in the exposition of a physical system, respecting the method of demonstration to be APPENDIX E. required, betray a want of education in logic ; for such questions should be previously determined, and not investigated in a phy- sical treatise.' * The grand problem for the educated critic is the appropriate method of the particular science and the degree of accuracy {&.KpCfieLa) to be demanded in the demonstrations. Ae'yotro 6' hv iKavm el Kara tjjv v7T0Keifj.fvr]V vKr]V bia(Ta>s fv at!a(n Tots Ao'yois ktii^rfnjTeov, &tnrep 0118^ iv rois hr]fuovpyovfJi,ei>ois. . . . Tbv cwtov 6e rpdnov koI aitobexea-Oai xpi^v fKaffTov T&v Xeyofi^vaV ireiraiifvixevov yap kariv i-m. to<70vtov TUKpiPfs iTn(riTeiv Kaff kKacrrov yivos eij) oaov ij rod TtpdyfxaTos v(ns emSexerai. TlapaT:k-qa'iov yap (paCverai p.adr]fjt,aTi,KOV re Ttida- voKoyovvTos a/nohi^scrOai Kot prjTopiKov a/nobei^eis aTraiTeiV. Exa- tTTOs 8e Kpivei Ka\&s h yivdxTKH, Kal TO'VTav ityTiv ayaBbs Kptrjyy. Ka6' ^KauTov apa 6 TTeiTai^evixivos, airX&s bi 6 Ttepl irav ireTraibev- ptfvos. Ethica Nic. i. 3. 'The exposition is adequate if it is as precise as the subject admits. For the same amount of exacti- tude is not to be required in all sciences any more than in all arts. . . . General statements, then, must be admitted in ethical science, for the educated critic varies in his demand of precision in the different provinces of science, and no more asks for demonstration from the orator than he accepts probabilities from the mathematician. Competence to judge requires knowledge of the subject-matter, and belongs in each province to the educated ; ,universal competence, therefore, requires universal education.' We have seen that sophistic proof as differing from paralogism depends on the employment of an inappropriate method or inad- missible evidence -. the pretender to science proves a theorem by an unscientific method (ch. 6, note 5), or the questioner con- futes the answerer accidentally, i. e. on topics not essentially connected with the department he professes to have mastered (ch. 18, note i). The one case is simulated pirastic, the other simulated science (ch. xi). In neither can the sophism be detected by the ignorant judges (dicpoarat) of a pirastic con- troversy; for, as we have said "before, we must not limit the simulation of pirastic to the employment of thirteen principles covering the defects of the thirteen paralogisms. It is clear that the admission of legitimate and exclusion of illegitimate R a 244 APPENDIX E. evidence in proof of a scientific theorem or disproof of a man's pretensions to science is a function beyond the capacity of an ignorant jury and which requires an educated judge. 'Artaibev- tria ydp eort irepl ^kojttov ■npayfxa to imj hvvacrOai. Kpiveiv tovs t olKelovs \6yovs tov irpiyixaTos (cat roiis aWorplovs. Ethica Eud. I. 7. 'Those who are uneducated in a given department of science are unable to discriminate between the theorems and methods peculiar to it and those ^hich are alien/ This explains the recommendation to the genuine geometer (ch. 6, note 5) to decline the pirastic tribunal. A large branch, then, of sophisms, accidental or inappropriate confutations, and accidental or inappropriate demonstrations, are merely indicated, not ex- amined, in the present treatise. 245 APPENDIX F. THE QUADBATURE OP THE CIRCLE BY HIPPOCRATES, ANTIPHO, AND BBYSO. As the quadrature of the circle by Hippocrates and the quad- rature by lunules are the only examples which Aristotle gives of a pseudographema, it is desirable to examine them with some attention. The quadrature of the circle by means of lunules, i. e. spaces limited by the intersecting arcs of two circles, is as follows. We first invent a method of squaring a lunule : — On the diameter AB describe the semicircle AGB; in this inscribe the isosceles triangle A GB ; and on the sides A 0, GB describe the semicircles ADG, GEE. Because the angle A GB is inscribed in a semicircle, it is a right angle (Euclid, 3. 31), and the square of the hypotenuse AB is equal to the sum of the squares of the sides AO, OB (Euclid, 1.47). But circles, or semicircles, are to one another as the squares of their diameters (Euclid, la. 2,), therefore the semicircle AGB is equal to the sum of the semicircles ABC, GEB. Take away from these equals the segments AFG, CGB %hich are common to each, and the remaining triangle AGB is 246 APPENDIX F. equal to the sum of the lunules ABO FA, CEBGC, or the tri- angle ACE is equal to the lunule ABC FA. We therefore have found a rectilinear area equal to a given lunule. According to Alexander Aphrodisiensisj Hippocrates applied this to the quadrature of the circle in the following manner : — On the diameter AB describe the semicircle ACBJB ; in this inscribe three lines, AC, CB, BB, each equal to the radius AK (this is the same thing as inscribing a hexagon in the circle; Euclid, 4. 15). On these describe the semicircles AFC, CGB, BHB; and describe a fourth semicircle ^ equal to one of these. Then because circles or semicircles are as the squares of their diameters (Euclid, 1%. 3), the semicircle ACBB is equal to the sum of the semicircles E, AFC, CGB, BHB. Take away the segments which are common to these equals, and the remaining rectilinear area ACBB is equal to the sum of the semicircle F and the three lunules. But we discovered a method of deter- mining a rectilinear area equal to a lunule; take away, then, from the rectilinear area ACBB spaces equal to the three lunules, and the remaining rectilinear area will be equal to the semi- circle E. q. E. F. Wliat is the fallacy in this construction ? This : it is true that we found a method of squaring a particular kind of lunule, that is, one whose upper arc was a semicircle and whose lower arc was the fourth of a circle; but we found no method of squaring such a lunule as we now have, i. e. one whose upper arc is a semicircle and whose lower arc is the sixth of a circle. This is clearly the quadrature by lunules, and therefore (see ch. xi) was not the method of Hippocrates. His method is described by Simplicius on Phys. Ausc. i. a, on the authority APPENDIX F. 247 of Eudemus, disciple of Aristotle, a witness whose evidence on the question must be taken as decisive. « According to Eudemus, Hippocrates not only squared a lunule whose outer arc was a semicircle, hut also lunules whose outer arc was greater or less than a semicircle. He then proceeded to ■square the circle in the following manner : — Let AC, BC he the radii of two concentric circles, and let AC^ equal 6 £C^. In the inner circle inscribe a hexagon {Euclid, 4. 15). Producing the radii CD &c. to the outer circle, and joining AG, GE, &c., we inscribe a hexagon in the outer circle. Join AM, and on. AE describe a segment A HE similar to the segment A G (Euclid, 3. 33) . The inner circle plus the lunule AG E H sh&W. equal the triangle AGE plus the hexagon in the inner circle. Because AEF, being an angle inscribed in a semicircle, is a right angle (Euclid, 3. 31), therefore AE'^ equals AF'^ minus FE^ (Euclid, I. 47). But AF'^ equals ^AC^ ; and FE, being the side of an inscribed hexagon, equals the radius AC (Euclid, 4. 15): therefore AE^ equals ^AC^. But the radius ^C equals the side of the hexagon AG ov GE, and A C^ by construction equals 6BC^ or 6BD'^. Therefore AE^ equals AG^ plus GE^ plus 6BD^. But similar segments are as the squares of their chords [Hippocrates deduced this from the theorem that circles are as the squares of their diameters (Euclid, la. a)]: therefore the segment AHE equals the segment AG plus the segment 248 APPENDIX F. GE plus the six segments of tbe inner circle. To these equals add the area inclosed by the arc AHE and the straight lines AG, GB; therefore the triangle AGE equals the lunule AG EH plus the six segments. To these equals add the hexagon in the inner circle; therefore the triangle plus the hexagon equals the lunule plus the inner circle. To complete the quadrature of the circle Hippocrates must have added: But we have shewn how to square any lunule: deduct, then, from the triangle and hexagon an area equal to the lunule, and the remaining rectilinear space is equal to the circle. Next construct a square equal to this rectilinear space (Euclid, 3. 14), and we have found a square equal to a circle. q. E. F. It is obvious that the fallacy of this is the same as that of the previous method. Hippocrates was the first who wrote a treatise of elementary geometry. Montucla (Histoire des Mathema- tiques) suggests what is very probable, that the construction was offered as a specimen of fallacious reasoning, and that Hip- pocrates as a geometer only intended to assert that we should solve the problem of squaring the circle as soon as we could square all the lunules as satisfactorily as he had squared certain definite lunules. This seems to have been Aristotle^s view ; at least be gives the proof by lunules, which has the same defect as the proof of Hippocrates, as an instance of abduction or reduction {aitayatyri), i. e. a ratiocination which, though incom- plete, advances one step towards the solution of a problem. 'ATra- yatyri 8' iarlv orav roJ n^v \xi(T(si to rrpmrov brj\ov fj vTrdp)(op, ra 6 i the elimination of the lunules that enter into an equation we have discovered, this preliminary equation is an advance towards solving the problem SP, i. e. finding the equation of the circle to a square/ An expression of Aristotle's that apparently refers to this subject (Tm yap ^ to. ^^iiievKXia irepiypacpeiv imtj as bei, rj ypajxixds Tivas ayeiv p/q &s &v aydeirjiTav, tov irapaKoyurpov itoLflTaL [o yjrevSo- ypav seems a reminiscence of Aristotle's definition of sophistic principles : OvOev yap t&v Keyop,eva>v evbo- foij; firiiroKauJV l^^i itavrek&s TrjV ^avracrCav, Kada/nep Trepl ras t&v epianK&v \6y(ov &pxas s Oixoiov brj to aKOireiv «t ovtoos Iv koI irpos aX\r]v deaiv oTtoiavovv bia\eyevi(Tp.ov tov p,ev bia t&v Tp.r]iJ,dTa>v yewixeTpLKOv biaXva-ai, tov bi ' Avtkjj&vtos ov yemp.eTpiKov. Ov pr)v &KK e-neibri Tiepl (ftvcrecas pi^v ov, (ftvo'iKas be airopCas avpL^aCvei kiyeiv avTois, ta-ios ^x^l Ka\&s IttJ piKpoii biaXexOfjvai Tiepl avT&v, eyet yap