^^SC-\^\ Xv^S^S^ *^\S^^«!>^ a;iSW-'-'V?-'-«iS4!i;» A>-wa*r- A^ 'jww wii tw iiff i^ rw"** !!^ v --.^ ^^,.^T^„ • »■< COllNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME OF THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND GIVEN IN 1 89 1 BY HENRY WILLIAMS SAGE / Cornell University Library B430.A5 H36 olln 3 1924 028 995 921 Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924028995921 THE MORAL PHILOSOPHY ARISTOTLE. THE MOKAL PHILOSOPHY 01' AEISTOTLE: CONSISTING OF A TRANSLATION OF THE NICOMAGHEAN ETHICS, AND OF THE PARAPHRASE ATTRIBUTED TO ANDRONIGUS OF RHODES, WITH AN INTEODUCTOEY ANALYSIS OF EACH BOOK; BY THE LATE WALTER M. HATCH, M.A., FELLOW OF NEW COLLEGE, OXFORD, AND RECTOR OF BIRCHANGER, ESSEX : SOMETIME WARDEN OF ST. PAUL'S COLLEGE, STONY STRATFORD, COMPLETED AFTER HIS DEATH BY OTHEES. LONDON: JOHN MUEEAY, ALBEMAELE STEEET. 1879. [All Mights Meserved.] XCRN iyNIVLRS^TY'l K LIBRAR \f LONDON : BBADBUEY, AGNEW, & 00. PKINTEES, WHITEFEIAES, PEEFACE. Four years ago^one.'of the most eminent of English Aristotelians exj)ressed the opinion that "the problem how to translate Aristotle into English has not yet been solved .... The problem is how to convey, in readable English, a philosophical style, full of technical terms for which we have no exact representatives. "Circumlocution, or paraphrase, becomes necessary ; the question is, how to use this with the greatest tact, so as, while conveying Aristotle's exact meaning, to retain something of his manner." (Sir Alexander Grant, art. Aristotle, in the ' Encyclopaedia Britannica,' 9th edition, vol. ii. p. 523.) The present work, though planned and begun before these remarks appeared, may be regarded as being, to some extent, an answer to the challenge which they imply. Its aim is to make the Nicomaohean Ethics of Aristotle intelligible to a modern reader. It endeavours to do so chiefly by modifying the style in which the original is written. Eor whether it be that the mind of an average Greek student was capable of greater con- centration than the mind of an average English student, or that what remains is rather a rough draft than a com- pleted treatise, there is no doubt that the style of Aristotle's work is to most modern readers intricate and obscure. "A considerable fund of metaphysical imagina- tion is necessary in order to give a logical coherence, to his vi Preface. expressions. But the metapliysical imagination is con- fined to the few: the ordinary reader needs not only definite expressions and clear ideas, but also that the sequence and interdependence of those ideas should be clearly marked." The attempt has consequently been made to supply what an ordinary reader needs : missing links of thought have been inserted: hints which were contained in brief condensed phrases have been expanded : that which was in some cases an imapparent inference beneath the surface has been brought into the light. The extent to which this has been done has been measured rather by the probable needs of those who are beginning the study of Aristotle than of those who have already been trained to follow the rapid transitions of his thought : but no additions have been made to his statements, and no inferences have been inserted which his words do not strictly and immediately imply. Three other kinds of help are offered to the student : (1.) Every Book is preceded by an analysis of its con- tents, which, without adhering too closely to the order or words of the original, omits no questions of importance which Aristotle raises, but re-states them in the form in which they might be stated by a modem writer. (2.) The chapters and sections into which the Greek text has been divided, have been disregarded, and new divisions and subdivisions have been made, each of which has been furnished with a heading and a marginal analysis, in order to lessen the difficulty which a student not infre- quently finds in determining what is the particular point under discussion, and what is its bearing upon the general argument. (3.) To each section of the text of Aristotle has been added a translation of the best Imowa of existing Greek Preface. . vii paraphrases. This, which, is distinguished from Ai-istotle's text by being printed in smaller type, is offered in lieu of a commentary. For until the Gre«k text has been more accurately determined, and greater unanimity prevails among scholars as to many disputed questions of Aris- totelian philosophy, a commentary, which must necessarily be both controversial and elaborate, would almost inevitably tend rather to confuse than to explain. In the absence of a commentary, and perhaps even after it has been made, the best interpretation is that which was current in the Aristotelian schools. Por it is known to have been the practice in them as in the other schools of Greek philosophy to interpret the meaning of an author, not only by notes or scholia, but also by rewriting the text in the form of a paraphrase. Of such paraphrases of the Nicomachean Ethics several still remain, and one has been printed: they have the value to scholars of preserving early traditions of Aristotle's meaning, and in some cases of pointing to an earlier text than that of any existing manuscript : they have the value to an ordinary reader of making some obscure thoughts clear by varying and expanding their expression.* Such is the plan which my brother proposed to himself. He had prepared himself for its execution by much special study. He had carefully collated several MSS., especially the New College MS., of which he conceived that too little * The paraphrase was first printed by is anonymous (see Lambecius, de Sib- D. Heinsius at Leyden in 1607, and has liot?i. Ccesar, ed. Kollar.vol.vli. col. 229) : been several times reprinted, especially the Bodleian MS. attributes it to Olym- at Cambridge in 1679, and at Oxford in piodorus. It may be mentioned that 1809. Its authorship is unknown : a later although in translating Aristotle's text hand had added to the MS. which Hein- the interpretation which is given by the siuB used the name of Andronious of Pai-aphrast has always been taken into Rhodes : the Paris MS. attributes it to consideration, that interpretation has Heliodorus of Prusa (see Spengel in the not always been followed, and that con- Abltandlungen der pidlos.-pldUl. Classe sequently discrepancies may sometimes der Mnigl. Bayerieelicn Almd. der Wis- be noted in the translation betvireen thq sensch., Bd, iii, p. 455) : the Vienna MS, te^t and the paraphrase, viii • Preface. use had been made by editors of the text. He had not only read every modern edition and commentary, but had given especial attention to the Eenaissance translators and inter- preters (and more particularly to the Latin version of Aretinus, the pupil of Chrysoloras), under the impression that they carried on to some extent the traditional inter- pretation which, he believed, had never wholly passed away from the Greek schools. The results of these special studies were intended to be shown not only in this trans- lation, but also partly in supplementary essays and partly in a critically revised text with philological notes. But before even so much of his plan as is embodied in the present volume was finished, his thirty-three years of life came to a sudden end. He died on December 2 (Advent Sunday), 1877, a few minutes after preaching an afternoon sermon in the Essex village of which he had recently become the Eector. The strain of the work which he had imposed upon himself had proved to be too great, and the 'silver cord' of liis life snapped with but a moment's warning. For his mental energy was altogether out of proportion to his physical strength, and the eleven years which had passed since he took his degree at Oxford had been years of imresting activity. The greater part of that activity was spent in the work of a schoolmaster. He had succeeded in raising one school (St. Paul's College, Stony Stratford) to a high level of excellence : and, though at length baflied by legal and other difficulties, he had gone far to establish a new public school on a large scale in the jS^orth of England. The life which had begun to succeed this activity as a schoolmaster promised to be rich in literary fruit. In addition to the present work and the other work on the Nicomachean Ethics with which he in- tended to supplement it, he had gathered considerable Preface. ix materials for the remaining volumes of Lord Shaftesbury's Characteristics^ the fii"st volume of which he had edited, with notes, in 1870 : and also for a life of Ijord Shaft esbmy and a survey of his relations to both English and other moralists. AH- this came to a sudden end; and there only remains, in the memory of those who knew- him, the recollection of his exquisite softness of manner and felicity of literary expression; of his singular combination of subtlety of thought with energy of action; of the versatile per- suasiveness with which he impressed his views upon his contemporaries, and of the sympathetic enthusiasm with which he won the young. It is obvious that a work which appears without its author's final revision must claim some indulgence. At my brother's death. Books I. — VI. were already written out for the printer, with occasional marks which indicated that they were to be subjected to a further correction; part of the rest was in a rougher form ; of Books VIII. and IX. scarcely any MS. could be found. But with all its in- completeness, the scheme and execution of the work seemed to several Aristotelian scholars to be so good, and its publi- cation so likely to be useful, especially to students at the Universities, that it was resolved to finish rather than to destroy it. The translation of Books VIII. and IX. was generously undertaken by my brother's college friend and contemporary, the Eev. W. A. Spooner, M.A., Fellow and Lecturer of New College. The whole of the rest has been revised by Mr. E. D. A. Morshead, M.A., formerly Eellow of New College, and now one of the Masters at "Winchester. Parts of it have had the great advantage of revision by Professor Chandler and Mr. Alfred Kobinson, M.A,, Fellow of New College. X Preface. To each of these gentlemen I owe and offer grateful thanks. But it would be unfair to make their kindness a reason for throwing upon them the blame of the book's inevitable shortcomings. For these I accept the responsi- bility. I was my brother's earliest tutor in Aristotelian philosophy, nor did he. ever widely depart from the Hues which I traced for him. And although in the present work there are some points upon which his interpretation may be open to question, yet where my brother gave evidence of having carefully considered a rendering, I have not felt at liberty to change it, confining myself to the occasional alteration of such passages as were clearly in- tended for further revision. I venture to express the' hope that the book, with what- ever imperfections it may be marked, wiU meet with a kiadly criticism from scholars, as an attempt to make one of the masterpieces of ancient thought intelligible to a modem mind, and to show that most of the subjects which Aristotle discusses are not mere fossils of philosophical palaeontology, but living questions of modem life. EDWIN HATCH. St. Maet Hall, Oxford, Oetoler 24, 1879. CONTENTS. BOOK I.— THEORY OF HAPPINESS. PAQE INTRODUCTOEY ANALYSIS .... 1 TEANSLATION U I.— Inteodtjction. Is theue a Perfection op Man, and how can it be ATTAINED ? i. — Arguments from ' Design in Nature ' in proof of Human Pei-feetibility . . 11 ii. — The Science -which takes cognizance of the Summum Bonum is Social Science . 13 iii. — The method to be pursued in Moral Science • .15 It. — Mental Eequisites for the Study of Ethics 17 II. — Eeview op Current Opinion upon Human Perfection. i.— What is to be understood by Human Perfection ? 18 (a) Vagueness and inconsistency of the popular conception of it . , . IS (fi) The true view of human perfection must be drawn from the facts of experience 20 ii. — Human Perfection is to be found neither in the life of Pleasure, nor in the life of Honour, nor in the pursuit of Wealth 22 iii. — ^Himian Perfection is not the realisation of the Platonic ' Idea of the Good '. . 2t (a) Necessity of e.^amiiiLng the Platonic theory 24 (5) Destructive criticisms upon the Platonic theory .... 25 1. Pirst Argument 25 2. Second Argument 26 3. Third Argument 26 4. Fourth Argument 27 5. Fifth Argument 27 (c) Eestatement of the Platonic theory, and new difficulties which it suggests 28 {d) Possible solutions of the question suggested 29 (e) The Platonic theory is transcendental, and valueless in practical life, even as an ideal SO in. — ^HUMAN PeEFECTION DEFINED AND EXPLAINED. i. — General conception of Happiness 31 (a) Happiness shown to be not a ' relative end,' but ' an end absolute and perfect'. - 32 (i) The perfection of happiness involves its self-sufficingness . . . 34 ii. — Exact and formal definition of Happiness 35 (a) Argument from final causes 35 (i) Explicit definition of happiness deduced from the consideration of man's final cause 37 (c) The definition of happiness must, from the nature of the case, bo provisional and in outliue 3§ xii Contents. lY.— Depinition op Human Perpeotion oompaeed -with other Theoiues akd DiPPIOULTIES SOLVED. PAGE i.— Our Definition satisfies the Conditions of Happiness implied both in the Popular View and in the Theories of previous Thinkers . . . . • .40 («) Common opinion confirms our definition as an activity of the Soul. . 40 (i) Statement of the principal opinions held in regard to happiness . . 41 (1) The view that 'happiness is virtue' discussed . . . 42 (2) Kelations of happiness to pleasure discussed ... 43 (3) Relation of happiness to external or physical conditions discussed 45 il. — Is Happiness within our own power; and, if so, what are the means for its attainment? 48 Without excluding other influences, man is himself the main and most important source of his own Happiness 46 iii. — Is Happiness still possible for a man, so long as sorrow may overtake him or his friends? ■ 48 (a) Solon's view variously stated and criticised : the ambiguities of it . . 48 (4) Solon's dictum disproved because the main element in happiness is a virtuous activity which is within a man's own power . . 60 (c) Still fortune has a certain influence, though it be a subordinate one, upon happiness 52 ((?) Happiness is, therefore, within our own control, but subject to the conditions of our mortality 53 iv. — Is Happiness possible for man after his decease ; or do the son'ows of earth still pursue him ? 54 V. — Is Happiness a thing of absolute or of relative value ? 56 v.— Classification op Vihtues eased upon an analysis op the Soul. i— Importance of a knowledge of Yii'tue 58 Human Tii-tues have then- seat in the divisions of the human soul . . 59 ii. — Division of the Soul into (1) Rational and (2) Irrational 60 iii. — Subdivision of the Irrational Element into («) Nutritive and (|3) Emotional . 60 iv. — Subdivision of the Rational Soul into (1) Emotional and (2) Intellectual . . 61 v.— Corresponding division of Virtue into Moral and Intellectual .... 63 BOOK TL— THEORY OF VIRTUE. INTRODUCTORY ANALYSIS TRANSLATION . 6S 72 I.— General Cuauacteristics op Virtue. i.— That Virtue is a permanent state of mind produced by our own Actions . . 72 (a) Dififercnt oiigin of moral and intellectual virtue . . , . ! 72 (A) Proofs that moral vii-tiie is tiot a gift of Nature, but a creation of habit .q (c) Summary : the importance of moral education . . . * , '. 75 ii.— Qualities exhibited by vii-tuous action jg (or) Need for a i-ule of life ' . . ' . " 76 {!>) ' Right ' cannot always be distinguished from ' wrong ' by a hard and fast line .. (c) Distinguishing features whereby right and wrong may be recognized' in the actual conduct of men ! 78 Contents. xlii PAfiE iii. — Qualities exhibited by actions prococding from a vii-tuous habit .... 79 (a) The easo with which the action is performed 79 (4) The pleasure consequent upon the performance of the action . . 80 iv. — The field of Morality is co-extensive with that of plea«ire and pain . . . 80 («) Proofs from the nature of the case 80 (J) Proofs from the natm-e of man 82 ,• (c) Summary of the conditions of a virtuous habit 84 v.— Morality of the Act distinguished from the Morality of the Agent . . . . 84 (a) Statement of objections to the theory of habit 84 (5) Eeply to the above objections 85 (c) Conclusion : for an act to be moral the agent must bo moral ; and the agent is moral by constant practice 86 n. — Formal Definition of Viktde. i. — What is the generic character of Vij-tue ? . . . . 87 1. Enumeration of the powers of the soul. ... 87 2. Virtue shown to be ' a habit ' . . .... 88 ii. — What are the distinguishing characteristics of Vh-tue .' 89 1. What is imijUed by the 'excellence' of a thing.' ' 89 2. The Idea of ' excellence ' illustrated by comparison with the idea of a ' mean ' or ' ideal ' 90 3. Application of the conception of ' the mean ' to the moral life . . . 92 4. Difficulties in the attainment of ' the mean ' 93 5. Eesume : complete definition of virtue 94 iii.— Certain exceptions to which the criterion of ' the Mean ' does not apply . . 94 1. Certain actions are absolutely right or absolutely wrong, irrespectively of circumstances and conditions 94 III. — Classification of Vihtues to illusteate the Law of 'the Mean.' i. — Self-regarding Virtues 96 1. Vii-tues displayed in circumstances of pleasure and pain . . . . 96 2. Virtues displayed in money-matters 97 3. Virtues displayed in the desire for esteem 98 ii. — Virtues shown in relation to others 99 1. Virtues displayed under provocation 99 2. Virtues displayed in social intercourse 99 iii. — Certain praiseworthy states of the Moral nature 100 1. Mental phases concerned with shame 100 2. Emotions experienced at the fortunes of otheri 101 rv. — Practical Conriberations for Determining the Mean. i. — Comparison of the Extremes and their opposition to the Mean . The Extremes and the Mean are all opposed to one another . 1. The sense in which the ' mean ' is opposed to the extremes . 2. The extremes are more opposed to one another than to the mean 3. Virtue is more opposed to one extreme than to another . 4. Bccapitulation ii. — Practical suggestions for the attainment of the Mean . . ... 1. How some of the difficulties of practical ethics may be solved . 2. The sphere and importance of a ' moral sense ' . . . 102 102 102 103 104 106 105 105 107 xiv Contents. BOOK III. Paet I.— analysis of MORAL ACTION. Part XL— EXAMINATION OF THE VIRTUES. fagb; INTRODUCTORY ANALYSIS . . • 109 TRANSLATION 121 ^ PAET L— ANALYSIS OF MORAL ACTION. I.— CONCEllNINO MOEAL RESPONSIBILITY. i. — Actions done under consteint 122 (a) Definition of ' positiye constraint ' 122 (i) ' Positive constraint ' distinguished from ' moral constraint ' . . 122 (c) Cases of moral constraint (or ' mixed actions ') must be regarded as voluntary 123 ((Q Limitations of moral constraint 124 (e) Difficulty of framing exact rules to meet the complications of life . . 125 (/) ' Constraint ' distinguished from ' motive ' - 126 ii. — Actions done through ignorance 127 (a) Repentance the test of involuntary ignorance . . • . . 127 (4) Ignorance as a moral disposition distinguished from ignorance as an accidental error 127 (c) Enumeration of conditions which may occasion involuntary ignorance 128 iii. — Actions done willingly 130 (a) Willingness is predicable of impulse and desire 130 - — ^ II. — Analysis op the ''Will' (or 'Rational Puhpose'). i. — The Will distinguished from kindred processes 131 (ff) The will not identical with ' the voluntary ' 131 (A) Thewill is not identical either with desire or with impulse. . . 132 (c) The ' will ' is not identical with ' wish ' .' 133 {S) The will not identical with opinion 134 (f) The will not identical with any special form of opinion . . . 134 (/) The will provisionally defined 135 ii. — The Will implies a process of deliberation 13g (a) The subject-matter of deliberation explained 136 (5) The method and efiect of deliberation 138 (c) Comparison between deliberation and choice 141 iii. — The Will implies a ' Wish for the good ' 142 (a) Is the object of wish the real or the apparent good ? . • . . 142 (i) Reconcilement of these two theories 143 iv. — The Win implies Moral Freedom 144 (a) Both virtue and vice are within our own power 144 (J) Refutation of the theory that vice is involuntary . . , .145 (c) Freedom in the foi-mation of character I47 () Temperance viewed in relation to pain 172 (c) Asceticism an undue avoidance of pleasure 173 {d) Characteristics of a perfect temperance 173 iii. — Subsidiary Considerations of Temperance and Intemperance .... 174 (o) Comparison between intemperance and cowai'dice 174 (J) Comparison between intemperance and the faults of childhood . . 175 (c) Here we must conclude our examination of temperance. . . . 176 BOOK IV.— EXAMINATION OF THE VIRTUES INTEODUCTORT ANALYSIS 178 TKANSLATION 188 C. — LiBEBALITY. i. — Characteristics of Liberality explained 188 (a) The sphere of liberality defined 188 (J)) Modes in which the principle of liberality is violated .... 188 (c) The virtue or vice of a thing dependent upon its uses . . . . 189 {d) The special use of money is in spending rather than in receiving . 190 (e) General conditions requisite in charitable giving 191 (/) General conditions requisite in charitable receiving .... 192 {g) Some further characteristics of the charitable man . . . . 192 (A) Bdsume : charity the moral ideal in regard to wealth . . . 194 ii. — Contrast between Liberality and Prodigality 196 («) Description of prodigality as a vice ^cr se 196 (5) Prodigality associated with other vices 197 iii. — Contrast between Liberality and Avarice 198 D.— MuNIPIOENCE. i. — Characteristics of Munificence explained 200 (a) Subject-matter of munificence and of its opposites defined . . . 200 (i) Conditions to which the conduct of the munificent man must conform . 202 xvi Contents. PAGE i. — Characteristics of Munificence explained — continued. (c) Munificence belongs chiefly to public life and to great men . . . 203 (d) Munificence may also be shown in private life 20i ii.— Contrast between Munificence and its extremes 206 (a) Comparison between munificence and ostentation .... 206 (i) Comparison between munificence and meanness 206 E.— Elevation or Soul. i.— Characteristics of elevation of Soul 207 ((f) Subject-matter of moral elevation and of its oppositos defined . . 207 (i) Honour the peculiar province in which moral elevation is shown . 209 (c) Eolation of moral elevation to the ideal of perfect virtue. . . 210 (rf) Eelation of moral elevation to honours and dignities . . . .211 («) Eelation of moral elevation to courage 213 (/) Relation of moral elevation to benevolence 214 (//') Kelation of moral elevation to the conduct and demeanour of social Ufe • . ... 215 ii. — Deviations from the ideal of Moral Elevation ; 217 (ff) Contrast between moral elevation and self-abasement . . . . 218 (4) Contrast between moral elevation and self-conceit . ' . . . 218 (c) Contrast between self-abasement and self-conceit 219 F. — Love of Honoue. (a) Definition of the subject-matter of love of honour .... 219 (i) Confusion of nomenclature between love of honour and its extremes . 220 G.— Good Tempbe. («) Definition of the subject-matter of good temper 222 (i) Good temper not incompatible with virtuous indignation . . . 222 (c) The entii-e absence of ' temper ' censm-able 223 {d) Excess of temper viewed under its various forms .... 223 (_nnJ— ^1T *r» -Phi V»in *,■■■• 505 (}) Belation of goodwill to friendship - • ^03 iii. — Unanimity (a) Its province determined °^" (i) Formal definition of unanimity ""6 (c) Dependence of unanimity on virtue 506 iv.— The relation of Benefactor and Eecipient 607 (ffl) Difficulty stated 607 Q>) Popular explanation of the difficulty 507 (c) A deeper explanation offered 508 v.— The relation of Self-love to love of Friends 611 (a) Conflicting views as to the character of self-love . . . .511 (}) The different senses of ' self-love ' determined 612 (c) The excellence of true ' self-love ' 614 {d) Coincidence of the love of our neighbour with true self-love . . . 615 Xn. — Eelation op Friendship to Happiness. i. General question proposed and discussed 616 ii._'Vyhy the happy are thought not to need Friends 617 iii.— That the happy do need true Friends 518 («) Moral arguments 518 (S) Metaphysical arguments 519 iv.^The number of Friends desirable. Their number must necessarily be limited . 522 (a) General considerations on the subject 522 (J) Practical considerations which limit the number of our friends . . 623 (c) Yerification of the position from facts and experience .... 624 V. ^The Uses and the Treatment of Friends 624 (o) The advantages of friends in prosperity and in adversity compared . 624 (}) The use of friends in adversity 525 (c) Their use in prosperity 526 {d) General directions for our conduct to our friends 626 vi. — Of the society of Friends 627 Contents. xxiii BOOK X. I.^CONCEENING PLEASUEE. • IL— CONCERNING HAPPINESS. III.— CONCERNING THE BORDER-LAND BETWEEN ETHICS AND POLITICS. PAOB rNTEODUCTOKT ANALYSIS ... 630 TEANSLATION 635 I.— CONCERNING PLEASURE. i. — Connection of Fleasuie with the theory of Morals 635 ii. — ^Examination of the theory of Eudoxua that Pleasure is the Summum Bonum . 637 (a) Statement of the arguments of Eudoxus 637 (d) Critioism upon the previous arguments 639 iil. — Examination of the theory of the Platonists that Pleasure is not a good . . 611 iv. — The true nature of Pleasure explained 647 (a) Comparison between pleasure and sight 647 (A) Pleasure implies neither change nor becoming 648 (c) Characteristics of temporal morement 648 (iZ) Characteristics of ' local ' movement 649 (e) Absolute completeness and independence of pleasure .... 649 (/) Psychological analysis of pleasure 650 (^) Seply to various difficulties upon the subject 562 T. — Varieties and differences of Pleasure 654 (a) Arguments from the difference of operations 654 (A) Arguments from the goodness and badness of pleasures. . . . 656 (o) Arguments from varieties of character in subjects capable of feeling pleasure 657 n.— CONCERNING HAPPINESS. i.— General conception of Happiness 660 (a) Happiness is not a passive condition 660 (i) Happiness an activity desirable per se 560 (c) Hence many think that happiness is identical with amusement which is also desired ^erse 661 ifl) But none but the perfect man is competent to pronounce upon moral questions 662 {e) Further arguments that pleasure is not summum bonum . . . 662 ii. — Happiness under its ideal aspects 564 (o) Happiness, being the activity of the highest part of our nature, is philosophic meditation 664 (4) Characteristics of the life of meditation 664 (c) Eesum^ : the constituent elements of the perfect life. . . . 667 (eQ This is not an unattainable nor transcendental ideal . . . . 668 iii. —Happiness under its social aspects compared with the ideal happiness of Reason . 669 (s) Contemplation is divine : action is human 669 (4) Contemplation is far less dependent upon outward circumstances than action is 670 (c) The life of the Gods should be our example, and their life is one of contemplation 672 (rf) The requirements of the philosopher are slight, and are sure to be provided by the Gods, who approve his pursuits 674 xxiv Contents. III.— THE BOEDEE-LAND BETWEEN ETHICS AND POLITICS. PAGE (a) The theory of morals subordinate to practical statesmauehip . . . 676 (4) The province of educationidentical with that of law;" . . . 578 (c) The reign of law must, therefore, extend to the whole of life . . 580 (rf) Difference between the legislation of the family and of the State . 681 (e) Necessity of a statesman-like spirit, even for private legislation . . 582 (/■) From whom may the principles of legislation be learnt.' . . , 685 (;) Introduction to the politics 588 THE MORAL PHILOSOPHY OF ARISTOTLE. BOOK I -THEOEY OF HAPPINESS. INTRODUCTOEY ANALYSIS. I— IS THERE A PEEPECTIOjST OP MAN? HOW CAN IT BE ATTAINED ? The subject of the Treatise is an_m^mrj_^irdo^§.,J^S!^3~sL^s S ummum BonTiSr: Wtet^cbiisliitates the_pfirfiac±i2n,.of man ? What is that ideal towards the attainment of which all the powers and tendencies of our nature are directed 1 What is the perfect life 1 Before entering upon the main subject, there is a prior question which we must answer : Is there such a perfecti on ? Is_the_fulnass_Q£-.satis&c- tion, t he perfec tion of all human aims and efforts^eyer^qomgletely realized or capable of bemg realized"? — — - The analogy of nature t'orces~m"to conclude that there is such an ideal an d that i^~'m asrba::^Hd-~ut'[ght''to~fae -arttajned. In outward Nature, scienx!£^iscovOTj;ojis_coordiiwti£n and>i^ : law and order. the adaptation of means to ends, prevail throughout the woflS! In th e natur e_of man, again, there are aims which, consciously or unconsciously, mfluence every movement of the_ mind, every activity of the body. Ttiere is design in all things — a ' good ' or purpose which Nature is incessantly striving to attain. Nor is this true only of isolated forms of activity. There is design equally in the larger groups of existences formed by the simpler modes of good. There is a gTadatiou of 'goods,' lower goods being subordi- nated to higher ones. The higher we ascend in the scale of being, the grander the design which we see manifested. But in the purposes of man there is a point where the subordination ceases and where the mind attains complete and absolute satisfaction. However noble its range there is a point where human conception can ascend no higher. There is a 'final good,' a supreme purpose satisfying all aspiration, comprehending in its completeness all lower forms of good. The result at which the strivings of our nature aim is no vague, unattainable 'infinite,' but a humccn good — a good which man can 2 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. attain by his own effort and in his own life. In one word, there is a perfection of human nature and we can attain to it. The same conclusion may be expressed more simply thus : When an action has attained its proper 'end' and fulfilled its proper design, that action is a perfect action. When therefore all actions have attained their proper ' end ' and fulfilled their proper design, life itself— as the sum of all human activities, will be perfect, and man will have attained his proper perfection, his Summum Bonum, and, with it, all that is possible of blessedness and felicity. But how can this perfection be attained ]— By a life in community, under the guidance of the State. There is no sphere in which a man's activities can be exercised or his virtues practised, save in the community of his fellows. There is no security for his freedom, save under the protection of the State. Nature herself teaches us so much : the very constitution of man marts him out as a ' social being.' The study of life will therefore be a study of dvil life ; and the study of man will be the study also of social organizations and of the influences which they exert upon him. Since human perfection can only be attained, as we have seen, in the State, the science of human perfection will be a form of the Science of Statesmanship. Statesmanship itself will be the supreme Science, sovereign of all other Sciences, the unique dispenser of human well-being, regulating the steps by which the soul must mount up to its perfection, givhig to each man his proper sphere, determining the Sciences which each must pursue, opening to all the practical means by which their proper genius can be most amply satisfied and perfected. The inquiry into ' human perfection ' merges itself, therefore, into a ' study of man as a member of an organized community ; ' and that is a wide and complicated subject. The interests of society are so varied and its issues' are so involved, that we must be well-content if we can delineate the main principles which should govern life and chai-acterise its broader features. Looking at the difficulties and complexities of the subject, the student, if he be au ediicated man, will be sympathetic and appreciative. He will not insist upon a rigid, unelastic method, but will be satisfied if the conclusions drawn are as exact as the premisses will warrant. In fine, the Method of Ethics will be Inductive, and its inductions will be general conclusions into which the element of probability will largely enter. Where the ccintingencies are so great as to baffle all minute calculations — which is the case in reference to the facts upon which Ethics arc based — ' probability must be the guide of life.' There is one other caution which must be borne in mind. The facts of life are unlike other facts in this respect : they are ' complex wholes.' The fact and the meaning of the fact are inseparably bound up, one with another. We see only so much of the facts of the moral life as cm- eyes have been trained to see. Experience is thus essential for one who would read aright the facts of the moral order. Hence, of course, it is impossible for the young to study morals with any profit to themselves. They have no experience to guide them to a sound judgment j and what they see they cannot understand, whilst the clouds of their own passions darken their conscience. Introductory Analysis: Book I. 3 o II.- REVIEW OF CURRENT OPINIONS UPON HUMAN PERFECTION. Assuming, then, that there is such a thing as human perfection, and that it is attainable, let us oxamiae more precisely wliat it is. What are the characteristics of that conception which denotes the satisfaction and fulfilment of the varied efforts and aims of human nature ? What is that ' end ' which civil communities were formed to realize in their members, and with which the Science of Statesmanship deals ? As far as words go, there is an universal agreement : all men identify . perfection with liwppiness, and tmderstand by happiness ' a good life and / a prosperous career.' But that is only a verbal agreement. The ideas which men practi- cally associate with happiness are various and conflicting, answering to the needs and wants of their own lives. Some give their preference to pleasure, others to honour, others to wealth, others to philosophy. There are others again who regard the Chief Good as something transcendental. We need not pass all possible conceptions under review. Sufficient for us to examine those views which are most generally entertained, or which admit of more intelligent criticism. [Here again a caution is necessary in reference to the spirit in which we ought to approach discussions of moral questions. There are two points which cannot be too often insisted upon : 1. That we must take our start from the facts of real experience, as exemplified in actual life (and not from d 'priori truths) ; 2. That in order to understand these facts, we need a specially trained intelligence, or an educated conscience. Early education and the discipline of sound habits must have fostered within us those moral dispositions that make it easy for us to recognize moral truth. Observation of moral facts becomes thus (in one who has been rightly educated) an intuition of a moral law. To detect right and wrong (which are the facts of morals) amid the entanglements of circumstance, is to detect a moral law. A conscience which has been so educated as to read aright the moral fact, has, whether latently or consciously, recognized the moral principle or ' law.'] Let us now proceed to criticise in detail the popular theories, though they are but the reflection of men's own lives, and the ideals which they picture take their form and colour from the surroundings in which men live. They may be characterized as follows : 1. There is the theory of animalism, which makes ' pleasure ' the goal of life. But this surely is a slavish type of life, unworthy of the true freeman, however much it may be countenanced by men in high station. 2. There is the theory of men of action, who see in 'honour' or ' dignity ' the culmination of their hopes. But this, again, is open to rnany objections : (a) it can be easily wrested from us ; (/3) it depends upon others rather than upon ourselves ; (y) it is not pursued for its own sake, but only as the sign and seal of virtue. [Indeed, on this B 2 4 The Moral Philosophy of Arislotle. hypothesis, it would appear rather that virtue had the stronger claim to the chief place. Yet neither is virtue adequate to meet the requirements of happiness ; for these reasons. (1) It may exist in complete inaction; (2) it depends upon external conditions which are likely enough to entail utter disaster and misery.] 3. There is, again, the theory of the mystic, which regards Meditation as the end of man. (The discussion of this theory will best be reserved for the end of the Treatise.) 4. Lastly, there is the theory of the money-maker ; but that is below notice. The life of commerce is obviously an unnatural existence for man. Moreover, money is not an end in itself; its value depending solely upon its uses. There is one other theory of great importance — the transcendental theory of the Platonists, which seems to represent all things which are ' good ' as falling under a common Ihia. It is a matter of diffidence to criticise the system of one whose niemory is so revered as that of Plato ; but reverence for truth is more sacred than affection for a friend. I. First of all let us assume that Plato's ' theory of ideas ' may be stated in some such way as this : ' whatever things are good may be grouped under one common notion, or law of the good, Ihia tov ayoBov' The following arguments are advanced in disproof of this position : — 1. Things which admit of priority and posteriority cannot have a common Ihia : The various forms of ' good' admit of priority' and posteriority : Therefore, the various forms of ' good 'cannot have a common I'S/a. The major in this Syllogism is admitted by the Platonists. The minor may be proved as follows : — Substance is a good. Quality is a good. Eolation is a good : But substance is prior to Quality, and Quality is prior to Relation : Therefore, some good is prior to some other good. 2. Things which are predicated in several categories cannot be a single Universal : But ' the good ' is predicated in several categories : Therefore, ' the good ' cannot be a single Universal. 3. If 'goods' fell under a single Ibia, they would be treated by a single Science : But they are not treated by a single Science : Therefore, they do not fall under a common Ihia. 4. Moreover, the Ibia is unnecessary and superfluous, at any rate as an abstraction subsisting independently of phenomena. The definition of ' a thing in itself is identical with that of the actual, existing thin<^ The definition of ' good in itself will therefore difter in no way from the definition of ' good' in its actual manifestation. ■ a' ,^°'"'.^P''™' 's it to the point to say that the Ibla is eternal and indestructible. It makes no difference in respect of the existence of a thing whether it be long or short-lived. (There is more plausibility in the view of the Pythagoreans. Unlike ' the Platonists who regarded the unity of the good to be its essence and i cause, the Pythagoreans, and with them apparently Speusippus, regarded unity as only a mark or characteristic of good, ranging unity as one Inirodticiory Analysis: Book I. 5 of a number (or ' roll ') of things perfect ; according to -which view 'unity ' is immanent in things and not (like the Platonic iScai) separable from thing's and independent of them). II. Perhaps, however, the theory of the Platonists may be stated differently. It is possible that the theory does not mean that every aspect or form of good may be brought under a single iSta, but rather that only ' absolute goods ' can be reduced to a single notion as coming under a single ' law,' and as having the unity of a single l&ea. Let us then put out of the consideration such ' goods ' as are merely relative or instrumental, and consider the case of ' absolute goods.' Now if there be any ' absolute goods,' they will be pre-eminently such things as sight and thought ; and we may regard them under two alternatives : (o.) If thought and sight are not ' absolute goods,' there will be no members to form the class which the Ihia toO ayadov assumes ; whereas if they are ' absolute goods ' there can be nothing ' more absolute ; ' and, therefore, the i8fa (as implying nothing beyond the members which come under it) will be superfluous. (S.) If thought and sight are ' absolute goods ' and come under a common liia, the definition of each would be identical. But their defini- tions are quite distinct. Therefore absolute goods do not form a common i8ea. III. Some possible solutions may be attempted of the problem which underlies the Platonic theory. There are three ways in which ' good things ' may come to have a common name : — (1.) As depending upon a single cause. (2.) As conducing to a single end. (3.) As having an analogy to one another. May not the latter be the true explanation ? IV. But a thorough discussion of these subjects belongs rather to a Treatise of Metaphysics. Our present concern is with the jiractical side of Ethics. That perfection which we are discussing in the present Book, is a human perfection, one which can be realized in life and carried out in action. The transcendental character of Plato's conception of the good removes it from the sphere of practical Ethics. It may however be retorted that though itself unattainable, the ' Law of the Perfect ' gives us an ideal which may ennoble our work and help us to realize what can be realizable in actual life. But this is not, in fact, the case. The various professions utterly ignore it ; nor truly is it easy to see how a man could be a better artist or a better surgeon by having contemplated ' the Absolute.' In art, and in the business of life, the important point is the specific detail, in which special know- ledge rather than transcendental conceptions, is of real avail. The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. Ill— HUMAN PERFECTION DEFINED AND EXPLAINED. Dismissing, therefore, the theories of the world and of the philosophers, let us now endeavour to construct a definition of our own, of human perfection. i. First we will enumerate the main characteristics of our conception of it: ,. (1.) It is 'the end of ends.' Every action has an end : architecture has its end, as medicine has its end, and all the arts their end. But one end is subservient to another : there is an ascending scale of ends, until at length we see all the purposes of life consummated in a supreme end. This final purpose, which is the culmination of all the purposes and interests of life, is ' the practical good,' the perfection of our life which we are endeavouring to describe. (2.) This supreme end is most absolute, highest, and most perfect. Some ends are imperfect ends, being 'good' only in relation to the purposes which they serve. A perfect end is one which is sought for its own sake ; and an absolutely perfect end is oue which is never sought but for its own sake. Such is ' happiness,' or ' the perfection ' of our nature i everything else that we do has reference to it, but there is no purpose beyond itself. (3.) It is completely 'self-sufficing': an absolutely perfect end is. thought to imply complete self-sufficiency— the satisfaction of whatever is wanting 'for its own realization. Nor is that all : in this conception there is further involved the idea of the well-being of a man's friends and relatives, nay, even of his fellow-citizens. But of course a reasonable limit must be placed upon this proviso : otherwise the circle of his interests would widen into infinity. (4.) It is ' unique ' and smi generis — not one among a number of other good things, but sovereign over all. ii. After this general description of human perfection, we may now proceed to work out an exact and formal definition of it. (1.) Everything in nature has its raison d'etre, a certain function to fulfil, a certain work to do. Man has, therefore, a certain function to fulfil, a certain work to do in the economy of all things. But man is a complex whole ; and in all complex unities there are special purposes in each part, and a general design for the whole. Man has a defined sphere for the exercise of each one of his faculties, whether of mind or of body : has he not also a defined sphere and a definite work for his nature as a whole or moral unity ? What then is there distinctive of man as man ? (a.) Not mere life ; for life is common to plants. ifi.) Not mere sensation ; for that is common to the horse and the ox, and to all organized creatures. The alternative is ' a life of action, inspired by the rational element of his soul ' — not merely a rational life, but a conscious exercise of the rational life— not a passive nor an emotional life, but a life of activity and work. (2.) But we are treating not merely of life but of perfect life, not of th? work of man merely, but of the perfected work of man. We must Introdtcciory Analysis : Book I. 7 therefore limit further our definition. In the perfect man ' the powers of reason will be developed in action in the most perfect way,' according to the standard of the truest excellence. (3.) One other condition must be added to ttie definition. The out- ward circumstances of life must be in harmony of the aims of the perfect man. The full definition of happiness will therefore be : ' A conscious play of the rational powers after the standard of the highest excellence manifested in an unbroken harmony of external circumstances.' [It will be understood that the above definition is wide and general in its scope ; and from the nature of the subject it could not be other- wise. But reasons will be given as we proceed with our argument." So far we have only drawn the outline of a picture, and are trusting to subsequent elaboration to render that outline more striking and expressive. A definition must in any case be adapted to the purpose for which it is required and to the conditions of the problem which it is framed to explain. Our piu-pose is not purely scientific, but pi'actical ; and an attempt at the rigorous accuracy of the mathematician or at the refine- ments of the metaphysician would be out of place, and tend to encumber needlessly the course of thought. For the same reasons we need not stop to discuss the ultimate principles upon which Ethics depends. The question for our considera- tion is rather into the fact ' whether, for instance, this is right or wrong,' rather than 'why it is so.' The recognition of the moral fact is (implicitly) the recognition of a moral law. The ' fact ' is thus a starting-point and ' a principle ' ; and the ' principle ' serves to elucidate many a truth of subsequent experience. We must endeavour, therefore, to trace out those simple facts of morals which may serve as ' principles ' or criteria for the discrimination of other truths ; and we must follow the guidance of nature if we would understand those principles as they really are. Some of these 'principles' can be apprehended by association of ideas, others by immediate perception, and others by the moral instinct which comes from education, and others in other ways.] IV.— DEFINITION COMPAKED WITH OTHER THEORIES AND DIFFICULTIES SOLVED. But if our definition be a true one, it must be capable of explaining all the recognized facts of the case, and must harmonize v/ith the universal verdict of experience. I. That happiness is ' an activity of the soul ' is in j)erfeot consistency with the common "impressions of mankind: (1.) Men regard the 'goods of the soul' as the highest goods. (2.) Certain actions are called their own ' end.' (3.) Happiness is called 'fair living and fair acting.' II. There are, in truth, five principal ideas which men associate with happiness, and these ideas (some of which are handed down from old times and supported by men of repute, while others are the views of 8 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. the world at large) are all comprehended in the definition which I have given. These ideas are— Virtue, Thought, Philosophy, Pleasure, and Pros- perity. Leaving Thought and Philosophy for Bk. VI. and X. we will examine the other three.. s 1. 'Happiness is Virtue :' our own definition being 'an activity of the Loul in accordance with mrtue.' We cannot suppose that our perfection Is a merely passive state ; and we must therefore premise that virtue is actively exercised, and that the happy man exhibits his virtue in the arena of the world, struggling amid the trials of life for its noblest meed. 2. ' Happiness is Pleasure :' certainly, the life of the happy man, being ex vi termini also the life of a virtuous man, will be a life of pleasant- ness.' The virtuous man being devoted to his virtue (as all men are de- voted to that in which they are specially interested) will necessarily take pleasure in displaying it. Indeed a man is not a virtuous man unless he has pleasure in his virtue. The life of perfection, therefore, is a life of virtue, and a life of virtue is a life of pleasure ; and these attributes are all indissolubly bound up, one with another. 3. ' Happiness involves prosperity ' : — of course the happy man requires certain favourable conditions and external resources for the exercise of his powers. There must be nothing in his circumstances to mar the completeness of his joy. Health, beauty, good birth, domestic consolations are all necessaiy to happiness, though of course they fire not identical with it. We will now proceed to consider certain difficulties which have been felt in regard to happiness, and offer such solutions as we can. I. Is happiness within our own power, capable of being compassed through our own agency 1 Or is it dependent upon the Divine Favour, or even upon Chance t (1.) Whether it come from God or no, it is certainly one of those things which are most divine. (2.) It is the ' reward of virtue,' and is therefore as wide in its range as virtue is. Yet virtue can exist in almost all whose consciences are not seared, by the help of discipline and education. (3.) Things are best when proceeding from law and defined causes and virtue : what proceeds from the highest cause will, therefore, be the very best result. Happiness, therefore, as the best of all things will proceed from the best of all causes— virtue. To leave it to chance, would be an utter discord in Nature's harmony. (4.) Tlie very definition of happiness as ' an activity of soul according to virtue,' other conditions being only secondary and subordinate, shows that the essential conception of it can be realized by a man's own self. (5.) The Science of Statesmanship rests upon the assumption that onr perfection depends upon our virtue. It therefore spends its utmost care in creatnig virtuous dispositions among the citizens : those creatures {e.ff. boys and animals) who are incapable of virtue, it assumes to be incapable also of happiness. (6.) So much, however, of fortune is assumed as may allow for the free play of the faculties and guard us from overwhelming calamities. Introdtictory Analysis : Book I. 9 II. But what is the limit of these human imcertainties, and what their influence upon happiness ? Can a man be really happy in this life, or is Solon's adage the true one, that 'we must wait and see the end?' Solon's view opens up another difficulty : If a man happy after his death? The relation of the dead to the living is a question full of mystery. Is death utter unconsciousness ? Or is there any communion between the living and the dead? If the dead are conscious of the fortunes which befall their survivors, what is the influence of the soitows of the living upon the souls of the departed ? Either hypothesis seems to lead to conclusions which men find difficulty in accepting. As for the original question, whether we may call a man happy in this life, that is surely reasonable to do : so long as a man really u happy, credit should be given him for his happiness. Indeed the whole idea underlying Solon's theory is false in principle. It implies that a man's weal or woe depends upon external conditions ; and that is untrue. The essential idea of happiness is ' a virtuous development of a man's powers ; ' and nothing is so permanent, nothing so stable as virtue ; so neither can anything be so abiding as the happi- ness which is the result and concomitant of virtue. Misfortune cannot, therefore, utterly take away a man's happiness. Indeed, if sorrow be slight, it will have no influence upon his life ; • though if it be incessant and appalling, it will take away the lustre and charm of his happiness. Yet at the worst, though the brightness of life be overclouded, he will simply be not happy : he will not be wretched : he will make the best of life, however great his reverses. The conclusion upon the whole question seems therefore to be, that happiness is as mucli within our own control as virtue is, yet still there are ' conditions of mortality ' to be taken into account which must modify all our statements. Whatever happiness is ours, it is a human happiness and one that is subject to the mutability of our human destinies. III. We must revert to the question which we left unanswered in reference to the condition of the departed : are they or are they not rendered unhappy when sorrow overtakes their friends on earth ? Two points must be taken into consideration : 1. The extent and nature of the calamity ; 2. The fact that the dead are not actual spectators, much less agents in the drama of earthly sorrow. The general conclusion seems to be that even if the affairs of earth penetrate to the world of spirits, they make no absolute difference to the departed, neither taking away their felicity from the blessed nor changing the condition of the lost. IV. One other question remains to be settled in regard to the properties of happiness : Is it a good of relative or of absolute worth ? Is it a good which is 'praiseworthy,' or one which is precious for its own sake and adored ? 1. It is not a merely relative term. Praise is inappropriate and inapplicable to it. Praise implies reference to a higher standard, and is a tribute paid to merit. But happiness can be referred to no standard higher than itself : it is a thing absolute and complete per se. 10 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. 2. It is a thing exceeding all price : we pay to it not encomium but reverence and awe : we acknowledge it to be its own ideal as a thing divine and blessed in its own right. v.— CLASSIFICATION OF THE VIRTUES, BASED UPON AN ANALYSIS OF SOUL. Now since the main element in happiness is virtue, we must examine with greater fulness into the nature of virtue. Virtue has ever been the chief coBcem of true statesmanship : witness for example the legislation of Crete and Sparta. As our own inquiry is a branch of statesmanship, we must examine the nature of virtue as the means whereby man may realize his perfection. But virtue is 'the excellence of the ioul' just as happiness is the activity of the mul. We must therefore in the first place study the nature of the soul if we would understand its excellence. For our present purpose it will be sufficient for us to adopt the main conclusions of Psychology which are discussed in my Public Lectures. There is an admitted distinction of soul into (1) rational, and (2) non- rational : whether that be a profound and real distinction, or only a convenient and notional one, matters not. 1. The non-rational may be subdivided again into (1) nutritive, and (2) emotional; but the nutritive element may be dismissed frOm our consideration for the following reasons : (a.) It is common to plants and not characteristic of man, as man, (A) It is most active in sleep. (2) The emotional soul is not entirely non-rational, but rather semi- rational. It is the seat of the desires and impulses which sometimes submit to reason and sometimes are opposed to it. It has not reason in its own right, but yet is capable of 'receiving reason' as a child listens to the counsels of his father. 2. Thus the 'rational soul' may be also subdivided into (1) semi- rational or emotional, and (2) purely rational or intellectual. The semi- rational soul is capable of receiving good impressions and forming virtuous dispositions. The intellectual soul has reason in its own right and independently of external influences. Corresponding to this division of conscious soul, is the division of Virtue into emotional (or moral) and intellectual. TEANSLATION. L— INTRODUCTION. IS THERE A PERFECTION OF MAN, AND HOW CAN IT BE ATTAINED 1 i. — Arguments from ' Design in Nature ' in proof of Human. Perfectibility. Eyery art and every step to knowledge, and similarly both every moral act and every decision of the will, seems to have some ' good ' or ' purpose ' at which J^"^^ ^^^ '^Arot it aims. The supreme good , therefore, or 'pur- nature and in all pose of all things ' is, as philosophers have well ^®^ activities of described it, ' that at which all things aim. ' But in the subordinate purposes or ' ends ' of nature there is a certain distinction to be observed. Some ends are simply ' modes of activity,' and o thers ari^aaterial results be yond_ the simp le e xercise of the facultie s ; anJ'wtreFe there are material results of any kmd reaching beyond tBFUctions, in such cases these results are more important than the activities which produced them. As, moreover, there are many forms of action, and many varieties of art and science, so also are"Tliefe" manyjjgndal resiiltrng-thecc- fi^mT^'the^entl of medicine, for instance, being health ; of ship-building, a ship ; of strategy, vie- ^""i '"'KP'i^J ''.f '„ , ^,. "' ^ -i,, Ti ? 1 ^0^^ activity Its tory; ot domestic economy, wealth. Jiut where 'end,' but these the arts through which these ends are realized, ' particular ends ' ,, "T s-Tf^ T- _ , i-, ,, 1 Ti ' are all subordinate themselves tall under someTiigher art (Wbridles; to 'higher ends.' maMng-and-similarr-fenctions "connected with the manufacture of horse-trappings fall under the general art of Riding, while Riding, again, and the whole business of war falls under the Master Art of Strategy; and as, in an exactly similar way, other subordinate arts fall under higher arts) — in all such cases, I say, the ends of the Master Arts are more important than those of the subordinate arts, the latter being pursued only for the sake of the former. [But, as regards the principle of subordination, it is immaterial 12 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 1. whether the ' ends ' be simple activities, or whether beyond the mental process there is a tangible result, as in the case of the sciences mentioned above.] If, then, this argument be a sound one, — if, Jhat is,.ih£re_be one end for all human interests and for all human pursuits, and if ' everything else which we desire b e relative a nd This bierareiiy of subordinat£to.thia final end, "and if we do not go 'XVenlr^^ rad* onlnterm'inably making our every choice for the ■whioh is therefore sake of something beyond (in which case our aims manfnfofaiihu ^""^'^ '^^^^ °° *° infinity, so that all our im- pucposea. pulses would be purposeless and void of effect) — if_thisjbe.triie,^itis._clear.that this end magt-be— the Bmrnmrni^mmr^^ of human aims. In every art and in every way to knowledge there is some ' good ' which, we seek to attain. The objects which determine human choice and action are those from which we expect to gain some ' good.' Hence some have properly defined the Summum Bonum as ' the good at which all things aim.' This is a universal law : not only things which are moved by conscious thought, aim. by that motion, at some good, but also things which are moved by the laws of nature are led towards the realization of some good end, or purpose, though it be unconsciously, like an arrow shot at a mark. There is thus an ' end ' in every form of moral action or of physical movement. But there is evidently a distinction to be noted in ' ends.' In some cases the end of action is a material result, as the end of the shipwright's craft is a ship. In other oases, again, the end of action is further action ; as the end of horse- manship is the practice of riding. Where the ' end ' is not action but a material result, in such cases the result is more important than the action. Since, moreover, actions are manifold, the ' ends ' of action are correspondingly manifold. The end of the art of medicine is health ; of the shipwright's art, a ship ; of the soldier's art, victory ; of the economic art, wealth. But it frequently happens that many actions and arts fall under some one faculty and art ; when, that is, they are pursued in view and for the sake of that art. For example, the art of saddlery, and the art of horsemanship, and aU military enterprise seek the same end as the art of generalship : — they are all pursued with a view to victory. These minor arts are, on this account, said to fall under the art of generalship ; and this again is called an architectonic or Master Ai't in reference to the aits subordinated to it, since it has exactly the same authority as a Master Builder among his workmen. Just as the Master Builder has an eye to the ' form ' of the complete structure, and bids his workmen execute the various works which tend to realize that form, so too the art of Generalship and all similar Master Arts lay down rules for the subordinate arts from the point of view of the end special to itself. Thus the bridle-maier, having regard to victory as the measure of his purpose, fashions the bridle to be convenient for the horseman when press- ing forward for victory. Another workman makes the saddle-cloth, and all such as are craftsmen skilled in cavalry equipments keep before them the ultimate purpose of the soldier's life. Soldiers again, cavalry and infantry alike, so dispose and shape their conduct that they may have strength to gain victory. In fine, the end of the art of generalship determines the character of the arts subordinated to it. There is, therefore, an end involved in each one of the arts subordinated to the Master Art, just as a bridle is the end in the art of the bridle-maker, and the practice of riding in the art of horsemanship, and so on in other ways. Yet there is also an end in the Master Art, just as victory is the end pursued in the art of Generalship. Nevertheless the end of the Master Art is better and more esteemed Bk. I. 1.] Translation. t^ than the minor ends, because, as has been e-cplained, the ends of the minor arts are puisned only in view of and in relation to the ultimate end. Even though the ends of our actions be not the actions themselves but material results beyond, there is nothing in that to prevent thB end of the Master Art (though it be only action) being better and more choiceworthy than even those material results. For example, the end of the bridle-maker's art iS/ a material result, \.e. a bridle, while the end of the art of generalship is action, i.e. victory; yet there is nothing to prevent victory being better and more choiceworthy than a bridle. A material result is better than mere action, not universally, but only in case where it is a consummation, as being the completed end of an action ; — since of course the end is always more esteemed than that which is ranged in reference to it. Thus it is that while many arts have but a single end — that of the Master Arts, yet all arts, in their totality, have one ultimate end f or the sake of which all_Qthe,r arts are pursued. This supreme ^d^ultimate end Jias.JU). oBjfict beyond itself, but is puisued"Torits own sake. Otherwise, if there be not some one supreme end, but we are incessantly to pursue objects for the sake of objects beyond ; — if at every moment we are to be pressing forward to ulterior ends in an interminable series, then shall we never attain the object at which we aim. The inference therefore follows, that unless there be a point at which the mind may rest as it is impelled to self-realization, all human striving is purposeless and vain. Universal failure such as that would be a monstrous anomaly, seeing that there is no impulse of nature that is in vain, Jt is, therefore, a thing of necessity that there should be some one end final and aBg0luLej_ajid_t]nsijgia.il3iu6t-fee» the SumS lLm D o uum, and lliaf whteh Is best tor inan. ii, — Th.e Science which, takes cognizance of the Summum Bonum is Social Science. Surely then the knowledgej)f this Summum Bonura_iaa a mighty influetice on the con duct of life : and if we have it before us~as W hl^rk at wMclT^ like archersTto aim, shall we not the more readily attain to what is meet ^'"^ st>«ty "f 'hu; and right? If then the importance of this amT of ^te radons knowledge be so great, we must strain our en- gradations comes under the 'Science o deavot trs to comprehend, at least m outline, w hat of Civil Life,' or th is Summum Borium really is, and under jwhich 'Politics' in its oQIiS-SiiicncE&^or Facultie s it falls. It would ™ve senTe'"^'^'' ^^' fl^Tpear to belong sp ecially to that Science which is most absolut e and jdij ch has th e widast and jnost compre- hensive range, ^tch obviously is the character of the ^ BcFenc e of Socie^' as being the science Avhich ordains what other sciences shall find a home in States, what sciences the various ranks of individuals shall learn, and within what limits. Even the most esteemed of the Arts and Faculties are, as we see, in subordination thereto ; for example, strategy, domestic economy, and rhetoric. Seeing then that the Science of Society uses the various Sciences concerned with action and production as subservient to its own high purposes, and further lays down laws of its own, prescribing what things men ought to do and from what they ought to abstain, 14 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 1. the ' end^_ofJhisJM:asier-^-S&icnce . will embrace_the_finds of all other..Scieiices, and will consequently be the Supremacy of Poti- highest good of man. Though the e nd of the whiclf investigates indivlduat-br^^ identical with that ofthe_State, how perfeotidn can yetTHe end of the State is" "recognized as ^ing communHiel"^ " " at any rate grander anymore pe"fIec rto~acqu ire andtJCpressrrer— Eren for-a-n individual, for his own sake, the Summum Bonum is an aim to be cherished : but for a nation and communities it is even more noble and divine. Such are the questions which the present Treatise aims at solving, being, as it were, a study of man in his relations to Societj^ The knowledge of this Summum Bonum will, therefore, be of great assistance to us in the conduct of life. The consequence of such a knowledge will be that we shall the more easily succeed in compassing that which is our duty, if like archers we have a mark at which to take our aim. If this be true, we must endeavour to define, so far as may be, in outline what precisely this ultimate ' end ' is, and to which of the sciences or departments of action it immediately belongs. Now there is, of course, an end which is common to evety art and to every faculty ; and there is also an end specially belonging to each single, separate faculty — just as the end of the Master Art is an end common to all the arts subordinated to it, while yet it is an end specially attaching to the architectonic art itself. It seems clear, therefore, that there is an ' end ' of that art which is sovereign over all other arts, and which is, in the highest sense, architectonic ; and such is the character of the art of Society. This a rt of So ciety prescribes to the other arts thei r rank an d proper_ season. It comes under its~eogTfisaiice alone" to oonSaeiTwhat Sciences ought to exist in States, and what Sciences the different ranks of men ought to learn, and within what limits. It alone is the guai-dian of the common good, expelling from the State such arts as are evil, nor permitting all the citizens indiscriminately to learn such arts as are beneficial, nor to practise them on all occasions. If a citizen have the abilities to be a General and to save the State, it suffers not such an one to be a shoemaker, and if he be competent as yet only as a private, it does not at once raise him from the ranks. It assigns to those concerned the proper season for the exercise of their art ; for instance, preventing a General fi-om leading out an army when it is fitting for him to remain at peace. The statesman will despatch the General when occasion makes it necessary, and will bid him remain inactive when it is the proper season for inaction. Though the General ofttimes determines for himself the proper time for fighting, yet that is not owing to his art as a General {but bccanxr. lu- ix also a statesman). All the rules of an art regard simply the end of that art : a rule which extends to opposite or alien considera- tions is not a rule of the art, as such. Consequently, when a General takes into consideration the circumstances under which he ought to fight, and in view of those circumstances frequently remains inactive and sends embassies to treat for peace, it is clear that he is not employing the rules of his art as a General, but the rules of another and distinct art, greater and more paramount than that of Generalship, the art of the Statesman. Sincej_jtherefore, ..this art of Society subordinates to i tself eve n the most e8tee mea5r The_ o^er^arts^ (I mean, General3Sig;:~Eag H5my, J Lhet^nlc',) and avowedly treats alfoSer arts concerned with action with a view to it^ own special end (for it ranges them all with a view to the common interests of the State, and for that reason lays down what the citizens ought to do and from Bk. I. 1.] Translation. \ 5 ■what they ought to abstain,) the end of the_ait_gf jStatfismanship-will^^fiomprise within its province the^ndteof]3roffier axEs. Biit-siiroerthB''BHa.'s"ol: aTffie" other arts are sought with a view to the well- heing of mankind, and the end of the art of Statesmanship is the one for the sake of which the ends of all the other arts are sought, it is evident that the end of this art of Statesmanship will be the Summum Bonum, the supreme good of men. It is evident also that though the end sought by the individual is identical with that sought by the State, yet the good of the Stat»Js recognized as being a grander and more perfect good for us to acquire, and to mUntain when acquired. Though the winning and keeping of this good be an aim to be coveted by each individual — whether he have the power of guarding it in the case of others or of his own self alone, yet is it an aim more glorious and divine for nations and for States, in proportion as the happiness of the many is better than that of the individual. Hence it wUl be more just to say that the end of Statesmanship is the ultimate end and the supreme good, inasmuch as it has regard, not to a single end, but to the ends of all other arts as proper to itself, being as it is of wide comprehension and embracing the whole interests of man as a social being. iii. — The Method to be pursued in Moral Science. In regard to method, the subj^atJssiUJba.ad£qaiaial^treated if it he elucid ated with..ag_inuch clearDess as the subject-rnatter of the snienne -axLmita. Rigorous exactnesT most noUje4©6ked for, to the same extjent, in alfsub- ^\'ieh°*SocTa'i jects of discussion, any more than an~equar"per- Science has to deal fect"[5rrffi^ish is looked for in all the different ''^ , exceedingly comfilex, and do products of handicraft. In fact questi ons of not admit of a rigid honour and of justice — the subjects wETcE~Sbcial JJJg*^"'' "^ *'^^*" Science~TnWsligates=^TesaDHr-str^lHTOfi~Ct)ntro- versy~andrTincertaintj_a^^o^j^ JipflEL^CUsfoiJi and opmionra ffigr than, up on essential right. An almost equal uncertainty prevails in regard to the good things of life from the fact that the results accruing from them are in many instances injurious : — ere now some men have been ruined by reason of their wealth, and others by reason of their bodily vigour. Arguing, then, as we are, upon such varying phffinomena and ' from such uncertain premisses, wejiuiaLi2fi~aaiis- fied if we can illustrate and expre ss the tru th in ^''° conclusions -i=\ 1- ""^ drawn must, tnere- a broad_and gCT.eraL sense^ and a_s_it-w^re, in fore, be general, outline. Where the premisses no less tlian the "■°'^,, P™''^'''.'''y ,.-, 1 • 1 • must be cm' guide. subject-matter upon which we are arguing, are only probable and contingent, we must be content to draw infer- ences of corresponding generality. In a similar spirit, each of my readers ought to accept what is here advanced upon the subject. It is th e characteristi c of an e(J]Kat£d-iHfln.JiaLla jequire scientific p recision upon any sub ject undeE_iuquiryj_Jo^ a degree beyond wha t the natur e of the case adjaits ; e.g. To demaiid~sc1entffic demonstrations from an orator i6 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 1. would be almost as incongruous as to allow a mathematician to make moral appeals. To us, in desiring to treat the subject of human perfection, any method of exposition will be found adequate which is suitable to the character of the subject- matter. We must not expect the same degree of precision in all investigations ; it is impossible to discover an absolute accuracy for all subject-matter, without distinction. In mathematics, doubtless, truth is pure and unalloyed, inasmuch as that is a science dealing with subject-matter which is necessary and invariable under all conditions.' and which presents no obstacles to rigorous scientific pre- cision. On the other hand, in investigations^ where the fact s to be dealt with are not^ecessary nor unchangeabTeTa iaethod of treatment is adiquateaji^atisfac- tory which draws inferences from facts which are only geueral_and_conijngent. This:Erinciple applies especially to the constructive arts. The form of art is not appHcabfe to the same extent to all kinds of material. In certain materials which are specially adapted to it, the form of art will be more perfectly finished off ; but in materials otherwise formed, this elaborate finish wiU not be practicable. The beauty of the human form will be differently represented, in their different materials, by the statuary and the painter. The painter represents the very colour of the original, while at the same time he is thought to reproduce the relative pro- portions and distinctions of form, since his material appliances enable him to do so. The statuaiy, too, will accommodate to the character of his material a certain external bulk of body ; but he is unable to reproduce the proper colom-s, owing to the natm-e of his materials. The same truth applies to the arts generally ; and for this reason we ought not to require the same degree of precision from every art alike, but only so much as the subject-matter allows. Correspondingly indeterminate, in reference to abstract truth, is the subject- matter with which Social Sciencp deals. QusstieirsT5f-ioiiouj_and_of-ju3tice, which Social Science investig'ates, and -prbich constitute^jts subject-matter, present dlver- genoies-and unceiSuties so groat, that it veritabjj appeJjiTEaTwtatlris Tioble is not' ndble"By right of nature, and that whatTrtnrt ISnbtJnherentiy just^ but only thrgug_aiind o.f^Qnventionality and custom. What is noble andlu^ in very truth is for this reason difficult to distinguish from what is just only in appear- ance. Nor is this all : even those good things of which happiness is thought to be composed- (I mean courage and wealth, and other moral qualities) even these admit of great uncertainty, owing to the fact that in many cases injury arises from them. Ere now some men have been ruined by reason of their wealth and others through their bodily vigour. We must be satisfied therefore, if, in treating of social facts of such complexity, and of ' the end ' which is based upon these contingencies, we can exhibit the truth roughly and in outline. 'And in general, when we discuss matters which are con- tingent and usual {not nri;e.mmj and invanaUe), and the ' end ' of such matters it is sufficient that we draw conclusions of corresponding generality. But just as the student who treats of Social Science is unable to discover a more rigorous accuracy than the nature of the subject-matter allows of ; so, too, the critic who passes judgment upon social theories will only judge fairly if, in the same spirit, he requires no greater precision than the nature of the case admits but is satisfied with what is possible. It is the characteristic of an educated man only to search for exactness in the various departments of inquiry, in the degree which the nature of the circumstances peimits. In the sphere of Mathematics, as has been shown, he will not aUow of any contingent statement. But in Logic or Physics, and subjects which are contingent and variable, he wiU take into account the element of chance or probabiUty. To tolerate a mathematician making moral appeals would of course be folly ; and almost as foolish would it be to demand from an orator scientific demonstrations. That is the proper spirit in which a judgment should be formed upon moral questions. Bk. I. 1.] Translation. 17 iv. — Mental BeqiilsiteB for the Study of Ethics. Now a ma n judges arig^ht oiiL g.-Q£jgbat-haJiimseIf knows, and only totfaaTfixteat-iH Iir n, piopec-^iic. A man, "therefore, who is educat ed in„ any special depart- ment ofknowledge, estimates soundly ilieTacts 61' such special department : and if he be educated in ever y dep artment of knowledge, his judgment will be absolutely sound. It^IIows that the young man is no fit student-oLSoGJal Science, He has no experiencS'"orhis own in the affairs of reajjlfejponj^ knowledge" orwE ic]S,_as-fheir w^Eole_2rovincej_mgj:al^iheoi-ies-4^end. More- over, as EeTsprone to follow his passjons, it will be idle and profitless "^r him to listen to moral_truthsI]QifiISSrof -^Meh-is; not intellectual but practicaLjiot knowledge but action. Whether siicir a student be young in age or only childish in character, is immaterial : his incompetence is not measured by length of time, but is due to his living and pursuing his several objects under the rule of his passions. To s uch as are i n this undiscipl ined state a knowledge of Ethics is found to be profitless, just as a sense of duty is powerless to c(^ti'oHhoge who" are weak of will. On the other haiid, to Jiich as .sEape tUeiL^isIres-aiLd, jagula te their conduct aft er the pattern of Beason,Jtjvill_ be of ext reme- Jalue -_tQ- haYe_a knowledge of morallscience. For a due appre- ciation of any science, a kncw- ledge of the facts of tliat scieuce ia essential. The yonng, there- fore, are incom- petent to study Ethics because (1) they have no real, personal knowledge of the facts, and (2) tlieir judgment is coloured by their passions. These remarks may serve as an Tntrodn^.tio n to indic ate (1) jyto ar e the proper students of Morals. (2) what_is— fehe-spirit- and m ethod with which the subject must be treated, (3) what_ia„the precisfi,sco|i£.Q£ihe-presettfe-Treatise. Now a man will judge rightly only of what he himself Jinuics, and only to that extent is he a competent judge. Hence, in regard to the Science of Life, a man will only judge aright if he has been trained in social questions and has gained experience therein as the result of long observation. The man who has been educated in a specific subject will judge aright of those specific circumstances ; and if he has been trained in cccri/ subject of knowledge, he wiU be a competent judge of whatever comes before him. For this reason a young man is no proper student of questions bearing upon conduct, being, as he is, without experience of the facts of practical life. Now moral theories have, in part, to decide upon particular factej__and_injgaxt to draw iufereaee* f rom them. ' Further, since the young man is not^et_of.an age to_ live by the law of RcasoB,. but follows still his passions and Inhscz-fam and mere wont, it wiU 'Be^vain andi prQfitlee8-that-lije.stU!3juaM)ial science. He will be powerless to attain to the true 1 8 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 2. end of Theory and to change his own disposition and to live according to reason, being, as he is, overpowered by the influence of his own habits. Yet the end, surely, of moral speculation is not Imowledge but action. But not merely one young in age, but also one young in character though he has passed the limits of youth, will gain equally little profit from the Lectures he may hear upon Ethical questions, because he continues to live a life that is suitable only to the young. In fact, in the case of the young in age, his short- comings are not entirely parallel with his age, but are owing to the fact that his life is not regulated by Reason but actuated by impulse, and that all his aims are directed by the impulse of the moment. To those who are in such a condition as this, the Imowledge of moral truth is a profitless knowledge, just in the same way as it is to those who are sensual and depraved, or to those who give way to the attractions of pleasvire. On the other hand, to those who shape their desires by the law of Reason and act in accordance therewith, it brings great assistance that they should know the bearings of moral questions. In men of that stamp, Reason will not only be able to perform the duties which it will understand, from the perception of moral truths, to be obligatory upon it, being emancipated, as in their case it is, from the slavery of the passions, but also, through having this moral freedom, wiU be able also to make use, instantaneously on all occasions, of its own proper strength. In the preceding Introduction, I have now sulnciently explained (1) what should be the character of one who would stt^y Moral Science ; (2) in what spirit we ought to judge of and accept Moral statemfents ; and (3) what is the precise scope which we have set before us iujjthe present Treatise. II,— REVIEW OF CURRENT OPINION UPON HUMAN PERFECTION. i.--What is to be understood by Human Perfection? (a) VAGUENESS AND INCONSISTENCY OP THE POPULAR CONCBPTIOK OP IT. Let US now take up the subject anew from the commencement ; and ass jiming that e very process of thought and tiiere"'^^ suoU^t e^^^^yj^fecisiOT^onEe" wilH^^ perfection of man, it stiuve's to realize, let us now ask what pre- what arc Ve pre- ciseTyTh'aF puf pose is which we say thaFTTis ciselytoimderstimd ,>— _j^__. ^n.,,- ^ . „ „ ^^-j. .-^^ _ jj by it? tneTrasmess^Tirtne Science of Society to atta m ? What is it which consummates all the 'good' things attainable by human activity? In regard at any rate to the name there is a pretty general consensus among the mass of men. The masses Men generally agree no less than the elite say that Happiness~^^'i '"perfection^' wM Summum Bouum, andnhey^are under tE^ ' m?- our ' happiness.' pressiou that ' living well and f aring well '_ is identical with ' being happy.' But if we go beyond this verbal agreement, and ask what the real nature of happiness is, there are many conflicting opinions ; and often inconsis- tent. Bk. I. 2.J Translation. 19 and men generally give a very dissimilar account of it from that which philosophers give. The masses define it as one of those obvious 'goods' which impress the senses,^uciras"pleasure or wealth of honour, and so on through many"" vi^ietlesT Even the same person will oftengive Slf Jr-blT a conflicting account of it : when suffering from pincss ' are vague illness a man says that health is happiness ; when straitened by poverty he says wealth is happiness. Others, again, self-conscious pX, their ignfijance,. ad- mire audenvy tEose^who utter "grand truths, transc.en,ding_their ownjjomon. ^ Others, again, have thought that beyond the various ' forms of good ' there is, besides, a ' Supreme Good,', jarhich is good in its own right and is the cause wJaich produces-goed in all lower varieties. But irts, surely, an unnecessary task to put each one of these theories to an examination : sufficient for us to criticise those views which are most in vogue and which appear to involve some ground of reason. Let us now take up the subject from tlie oommencement and proceed with its discussion. Since every process of thought and every movement of the will has some purpose at which it aims, what is that purpose at which we say that the Science of Life aims ? All actions being directed, as has been shown, to the realization of some purpose, what is that purpose towards which the Science of Society is directed, and what is that culmination of all good things attainable by action, which is ' the end ' of the Science of Society ? So far as this is a question of words, there is but one single name applied to this ultimate end by the mass of mankind ; and so far the masses are in perfect accord with the iliti' : — all men call this end hipxriness, and suppose that ' being happy ' is exactly equivalent to ' living well and faring well.' But as for what happiness really is, — upon that point men are at issue, and philosophers do not give the same account of it as mankind in general. The masses proclaim happiness to be one of those goods which are palpable and conspicuous, and which are commonly thought to be dear to men, such as pleasure or wealth or honour, different men preferring different objects, but all of the same character. Of ttimes even the same person will give a fluctuating account of it, now calling it one thing, now another {e.g. in sickness, health ; in poverty, riches) ; and generally, men apply the name of happiness to some particular thing for which they have a desire at the moment. Again, those who are enamoured of philosophy are eager to learn subjects of which they are conscious of being ignorant ; and hence admire and envy those who utter grand tmths transcending their own horizon. Others, again, consider that beyond the multitude of par- ticular goods, there is some other good, subsisting by itself, which constitutes happiness, and which is in tmth the cause to all other things of their goodness. To examine, however, all the opinions held about happiness is surely a futile task. Sufficient is it for our purpose if we examine the opinions which are most in vogue and approved by men generally or which seem to rest upon some ground of reason. 26 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 2. The method of arriving at the truth in Ethics is not a priori and demonstrative, hut inductive — based, that is, on the facts of exijerience. (b) THE TEUE VIEW OF HUMAN PEBFECTION MUST BE DEAWN FEOM THE FACTS OF EXPERIENCE. ■ But let us not forget that arguments drawn from first principles differ from arguments which lead up to first principles. There was wisdom_iii_the_guestion which Plato raised when he a sked wh ether the method of Science proceeds'l&CHn.gpiiafiiBlirTo'' particulars or from particulM;s_j2_4uimples, like the course in the Stadium, which is either from the umpire to the goal or from the goal to the umpire. Our own starting point at any rate in this Inquiry must, he from what is known ; and things are known i n two se nses, some relatively to individual p-ypgr i en cr'a n d'o'th" ers aEso IutelY andj n_the nature of things. Our own starting point, then, had probably better be file facts which are known to ourselves by our own experience. It follows, therefore, that (if a theory of morals depends wp^ •personal experience and careful perception qfpar- ticutiir facts,) the conscience of the studenTought to have been properly educated uuder_go0dr^TS=- cipline — if, that is, he would be a competent student of what is noble and great, and generally of what concerns our social well-being. The necessity for such an education is , obvious. The moral fact being the basis^Fthe moral principle, if theyac^ be perfectly clear to a man, he will have no further needtg seek fgr its principle. When a man's .conscience has been so educated that moral- facts are clearly and adequately known to him., sjuch an one either has moral principles latent in him or could -easily .acquire ■them. If on the other hand a man has no perception of moral facts nor fund of moral principles, let him listen to_ these lines of liesiod : — " Highest and best is he who all things himself comprehendeth ; Exoellout also is he who, wisely counselled, obeyeth. But whoso naught comprehendeth himself, nor to friend ever listeth, Pondering counsel in soul, he surely advantage quite lacketh." But since a theory of morals is a tlieory of moral principle (Qie ' end' of all our actions, that for the sake of ■which 'we do ■whatever -we do, being- the cause and ' principle' of those actions) -we have here to consider in -what way ■we must formu- late the question of principle — a question which admits of widely different aspects. We must at the outset discriminate, ■with a certain degree of exactnesB, the different nature of principles or ' causes.' One kind of cause is the ' final cause ; ' another the ' formal cause ; ' another the ' material cause ; ' another the ' effi- cient cause.' The efficient cause is the conscious agency of the artist. The material cause is,|or example, the wood and the stones of which the house is built, i But in order that these facts may be rightly read, the moral conscious- ness of the student ought to have been trained and disci- jjlined. Bk. I. 2,] Translation. . 2 1 The formal cause is the conception or ' form ' of the house in the mind of the artist. The final cause is the purpose for which the house has been constructed. Since these are the causes o.f their existing to all existences, they are also the causes of our Inunclcdgii of those existences : it is onlj^through these causes that things are able to be apprehended by us. If, for example, a man knows the art of the craftsman, in ac oordance with which he constructed the house, he will know also whether the house be good or bad, so far as it falls within the province of that art. In the same way, a man who knows the matter or the form of a bouse will know its whole char?icter. Again, if we know what is the end or purpose of the house, we shall know whether it is a good or a bad house. An inverse process is, however, sometimes found to be applicable — ^that we gain a knowledge of the causes from knowing the consummated idea of the work itself. A man who knows the completed house, will recognize the art of the builder ; and so in the case of the other arts. Hence our method of treatment must necessarily be twofold — either to demon- strate causes from efEects, or to deduce effects from, causes. In the present Treatise we must adopt either of these modes of treatment as occasion may require. We shall demonstrate our theory from principles when principles a,re obvious, and from efEects when effects are the more manifest. On this account Plato was right to raise the question of method, and to argue the point as a material one in certain cases, whether the proper course in scientific discussions was a deduction frum principles or an induction leading up to principles (as in the Stadium from the umpires to the goal or clcn rcrsd.') Since then a twofold method is open to us, whence must we take our start ? Is it not obvious that we must begin &om realized effects, i.e. from the facts of daily life of which the end of society constitutes the cause or inner principle .' These social facts are hiwn-ii to us, and we are bound to take our start from what is hnomn relatively to our own experience (and not in the nature of things). Things which ai'e known in their essential natnrc are called ' principles' and 'causes,' since nature exhibits or manifests' them prior to their effects, and has regard to them primarily and before all else. But relatively to ourselves effects are better known ; and therefore we must take our start therefrom. In this way the course of our argument will be clearly defined as proceeding from facts known to our own selves. If then the basis of morals be a clear perception of moral facts, it behoves a man who intends to study Ethics, to live in- the practice of noble and virtuous actions — if he is to have a chance of understanding moral questions aright and of foiining a sound judgment thereon, and of gaining profit for himself. Had we been demonstrating from abstract principles that a certain course of conduct was the right one, we might have won the ass§nt of a student though he had not been trained to the practice of goodness, constraining him by the irresistible force of argument. But since we intend rather to demonstrate our theories from the particular facts of social life, and it is necessary that an assumption be made, as a starting point for our demonstration, that 'such and such actions are right,' it is evident that a man cannot possibly be convinced unless he has learnt from personal experience of his own the truth upon which that assumption rests. If on the other hand a man accept the truth with an adequate conviction of his own, that ' such and such actions are right,' we shall have no further need of an inquiry into the ultimate cause of their being so. Such an one either knows the cause (('.r, the 'end') of moral action, or when he hears of it will readily recognize it. If. on the contrary, a man knows neither the moral fact nor the moral law, — if he neither knows himself nor has the power of learning from others, let him listen to these lines of Hesiod : " Highest and best is he -who all things himself comprehendeth, Guarding what £or the future is beat and what to the end appertaineth. Excellent also is he who, when counselled wisely, obeyeth ; But whoso naught comprehendeth hunself, uor to friend ever listelh. Pondering counsel in soul, he surely advantage quite lacketh." 22 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 3. ii,— Human Perfection is to be found neither in the life of Pleasure, nor in the life of Honour, nor in the pursuit of Wealth. Let US now return to the point from which, we digressed — what is to be understood by the Summum Bonum Popular views of or ' happiness ? ' Men seem to draw their views the Summum Bo- f ■. ^ unnaturally, from the needs of their num are partial "'^ j-i'j -^ "" ji and egoistic. own lives. The masses, and those who are spe- cially ' the sons of toil,' suppose that for them pleasure would be happiness ; hence the life they covet is a life full of bodily delight. There are, in fact, three types of lives particularly prominent : (1) the life of pleasure just referred to ; (2) the public or citizen- life ; and (3) the life of meditation. (1.) The masses, then, are seen to be absolutely 'slave-like' and sensual, since they adopt as their choice the The life of pleasure existence of mere animals ; but they have a plea Inl^uuworthf 'S to justify themselves in the fact that many men man. in high position show a self-indulgence like th^t of a Sardanapalus^ (2.) Men of refined tastes and men who are engaged in active pursuits make Jionour the goal of their lives, honour^rone the ^onour being pretty generally the ' end ' of a success of which is public man's Career. others^™' "^""^ B'l* it is evident that such an end is too super- ficial to form happiness,^which is our present quest. Honour seems to be dependent rather upon those who confer it tlian upon those upon whom it is conferred ; whereas we have a feeling within us that happiness is something pecu- liarly our own, and difiicult to be wrested from us. Moreovfer, the reason why men make honour their pursuit would seem to be that they may gain a full assurance of their own virtue. It is from men of high character, men by whom ^rrdathefoth: ^^^^ ^'% personally known, and that too on the standard of virtue, score of merit, that they seek to receive honour. It is evident, then, that even according to their own estimate virtue is better than honour. Perhaps, then, we might assume that virtue more truly than . honour is the end of a public career. Yet even quires*' mS"'con- virtue manifestly falls short of the requirements ditions satisfied for of happiness, Though a man be in possession of Bk. 1. 3.] Translation. 2 x virtue, it seems conceivable that he may be asleep its own realization, or inactive all life long, or even worse than that, ^md, therefore, can- be ill-treated and suffer the direst misfortunes, mum Bonum. ^™' But if a man lived under such conditions, no one would count him happy, unless to defend a paradox. But I will not here discuss this point further. An ample examination of the question will be found in my Public Lectures. (3.) The third life is that of the mystic or of The life of con- the philosopher, of whose claims I shall make a t^pi^tjf ^?y be „■,,'■ ....,, „ reserved for discus- lull exammation m the progress of my work. sion later on. [I pass by the life of commerce or of money-making as being in a way an unnatural existence for a man, its ' end,' wealth, being obviously not that ' good ' for which we are in search. Wealth is not ' an end in itself,' The life of com- but only useful as subservient to other things, merce is below tha TT • 1 J Ti T . ° dignity of man, Hence one might more readily suppose happiness and is obviously to consist in one of the ' ends ' enumerated above ^° mandf of 1° *?^ rather than in wealth, since both pleasure and ncss. honour are coveted for their own sake; but it is evident that not even are these our ' Summum Bonum,' though many an argument has been lavished to prove that they are.'\ Let us now return to the point under discussion before this last digression. The point of our argument was that men entertain divergent opinions upon the nature of happiness. In fact, every man defines happiness in such a way as to reflect the tenor and inclinations of his own life. Hence the masses (whose passions are unbridled) maintain that pleasure is happiness, and for that reason the life they love is the life of enjoyment. Indeed, if we look at the world as a, whole, there are three general types of lives : the life devoted to pleasure, the life- of social interests, and the life of contemplation. (1.) The first life, that of pleasure, has in it nothing that is sacred. Those who follow such a life are thoroughly slave-like, and live the life of mere animals. In fact their Ufe seems only worthy of consideration from the fact that there are many men in high positions who make it their choice, and cultivate tastes like those of a Sardanapalus. (2.) The second life is one which the bettor Idnd of men prefer. Those who ' follow a- line of noble conduct think that honour is their true end, honour being pretty generally the ' end ' of that social life to which I am referring, and the aim sought for by all. But it is evident that this is not the ultimate end of man : on the contrary, it must itself also be added to the list of those things which seem only to be good, and which have no existence beyond appearance. For that which is in very truth the good of man, and in virtae of which he is happy, must needs be something depending upon his own self. Honour, on the contrary, does not depend upon the person upon whom it is conferred, but rather on the person who confers it. Happiness, therefore, does not consist in honour ; if a man is to be happy, hia 'good' must be a thing peculiarly his own, and difficult to be wrested from him. 24 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 4. Moreover, the reason why men pursue honour, is that they may have an assm-anoe about themselves that they ai-e virtuous; hence they seek to be honoured by men of sound judgment by whom they are personally known, and to be honoui-ed on the ground of then- moral worth. It is clear, therefore, that the reason why men pui-sue honour is that they may have the reputation of being good and worthy men, and that on the score of their virtue ; and thus it is evident that honour is not pursued for its own sake, but on aoconnt of the vutne implied in it. Hence honour itself will not be our ultimate end, but rather virtue. Yet even virtue fails of being the ]>erfeot good, and therefore happiness which is our perfect good cannot consist in virtue. That virtue is imperfect, is evident. It is possible for a man to have a habit of virtue, though he be slumbering or in some other way inactive all life through, or though he be evil- entreated, or unfortunate, or fallen into great calamities, and, in consequence thereof, have his virtue marred and incomplete. If a man's life is thus situated/ no one would call him happy : — much less would one assume it as a fact that ' happiness is the habit of virtue,' and name it accordingly. (3.) Let these considerations suffice for discussing the claims of the life of self-indulgence and the life of social interests. • I have in fact treated the subject sufficiently in my Public Lectures. As for the life of meditation, I shall have to examine into that by-and-by. For the present I have a different object in view. [There is, however, still one other life, that of the money-maker ; but this has practically been already considered in the lives above described. The man who pursues pleasure, equally with the man who pursues honour, wishes to amass riches. Hence I said that there are three types of lives which are specially prominent, the life of the money-maker being included in our previous survey. Such a life is, in fact, an unnatural existence for a man. So far from pursuing that 'good' which is the 'perfect good' of man, it does not even profess to pursue it. Hence there are not many by whom it is embraced. Few there are who make it their choice to have money as the end of all their endeavours and interests in life. It is also evident that not even does the money- maker himself seek wealth as the ' chief good.' Wealth is sought only for the sake of its uses, and with a view to an ulterior purpose, for the sake, that is, of pleasure or honour. But the ' chief good ' must needs be good for its oicn sake. Hence one might rather consider the aims ref eiTed to above (I mean honour or pleasure) as the ' ends ' of life, riches being sought with a, view to the attain- ment of these. Yet it is evident that neither are pleasure and honour the perfect goods, though many an argument has been framed in their favour by many an old philosopher, some maintaining that pleasui'o, others that honour is the ' final good ' of man.] Here we must end our criticisms upon the popular theories. iii. — Human Perfection is not the realisation of the Platonic ' Idea of the Good.' (a) NECESSITY OF EXAMINING THE PLATONIC THEOEY. It is perhaps, better that we should here consider the nature of * the Universal Good,' and discuss thoroughly~the sense in which ,"~~ ~ ~tbe-terni is used; although the subject is ren- trrnsi'endental ^ered difficult from the fact that it was friends theory, which our of ours who introduced ' the theory of ideas ' to L1tot"Stt explain it. Yet assuredly it would seem to be to criticize. the better part, nay, our bounden duty, that as Bk. 1. 4.] Translation. 25 we -^xa ^tlie professed ' lov ers of wisdom,]^ we sJiQjil!Lj:eiu.ta aven cherished theories of our own in the interests and for the sake _Qf truth, 'i'tiough lnends~a5cT truth Be equally beloved, it is a sacred duty to pay to truth the greater reverence. Since our inquiry has reference to the supreme end of man, which is thought to be some one ' Universal Good,' we must consider, in regai'd to this tTniversal, in what sense it is predioable, and whether there is any one ' law ' or ' conception of the good.' This is, however, an aspect of the suhject which it is uncongenial for us to consider, because they are friends of our own who have introduced the ' Theory concerning Ideas ' — the theory, that is, that there is a certain iSe'a of each separate existence, and that this iSe'a is self -subsisting. But in spite of our regard for the Platonists, it would seem to be the better course, nay, our bounden duty, to sacri- fice even cherished opinions with a view of saving the truth, particularly as we are 'lovers of wisdom.' Though the author of this theory was our friend, as Truth is our friend, it is a sacred obligation to pay to Truth the greater reverence. (i) DESTRUCTIVE CRITICISMS UPON THE PLATONIC THEORY. 1. First Argument. Now those who b rought forwa rd this theoij^did. not frame ' ideas ' in cases where the matters oT^jtuch they we re~spgirM ngJ7^'e" prior oF^bsequeut J;o one The various forms another; and, for that reason, neither did they come under TcZ- COnS^Uet anv Ilia, of numbers. mon \Ua because _ But ^the'go od' is predk aki-simultaxmudy ^^td lo^tt in various, categories {e.g. Substance^-IJuaiity riority. arid _±lela5Sn), which are prior and subsequent to one another, S ubstance and Essence, -being -pnac__to Jlela- tfon^nT Eelation corresponding to an_o^sJiQi3t. ox ..accident of Substance. Tiie-fn:ferfiace is that, for these different forms of 'gpodj.. there can not be any one common tSe'a. Now those who introduced this Theory did not allow that there was any single Ihka of existences in which priority and posteriority was implied ; and for this reason did not construct of number any single iSta, since number admits of rela- tions of ' first ' and ' second.' But there is priority and posteriority also in the good ; and hence it is clear that there cannot be any single iSta (embracing all varieties of good). The proof that we can recognize priority and posteriority in ' the good ' is obvious. There is ' good ' in the category of existence (as mind or God), and in the category of quality (as the virtues), and in the category of relation (as ' the useful') and in the category of quantity (as ' the proportionate,') and in the category of place (as home — that being a place in which we pass our time pleasantly), and in the cate- gory of time (as opportunity — ^that being the time suitable for each purpose), and similarly in the other categories. But in saying that ' the good ' is predicated in many categories, we are saying that it admits of priority and posteriority : substance, for instance, is prior to 26 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk, I. 4. relation, both, because substance exists per se, whereas relation has its manifestation in a body alien to itself, and also because existence is devoid of form, whereas relation consists in form being, as it would seem, an offshoot and accident of existence, 2. Second Argument. Again : since 'the good ' is predicated in as m any senses as is existence {e.g. it is predicated in the categor y of Substance, as God and InteUect, and in the categoiZ-°£QS^3'y> TsLlie uTelt as the virtues • and in the categpry,i)Li2]iaatity, because it is pre- as_the proportionate; and in the category of Soriei" ''™''^ Relation, as the useful ; and in thejcategofy-of Time, as the seasonable, and inth e categ'ory of~ Place as home, and so on through all the caiegories), it is clear that ' the_good ' will not be any one common_notion.„l,h,a,t ia..hnth universalan^'one. Had it been so, it would have been predicated not in all the categories, but in one only. Again : since ' the good ' is predicated in as many ways as is existence, and existence is predicated in many ways, ' the good ' wiU also be predicated in many ways ; and there wiU not be any ' good ' that is ' common ' and ' universal ' and ' one : '—otherwise the ' good ' would not have been predicated (as it has been shown that it is) in all the categories, but in one only. 3. 'Third Argument. Again, as there is a single science of whatever falls under a single conception, so would there have_been a faii''™der a" com- Single sclencc of all ' goods,' had there been a mon lUa. because single ' iS^a.' .-.-'-— ^ by°IsiDgie*sdence. ^^^^ '^^ ^ matter of fact, there are many sciences even of things which fajl under a single category : for instance, under the category ' opportuneness,' in war, there is strategy ; in sickness, medicine ; again, under the category ' the Mean,' there is, in food, Therapeutics, and, in exercise, Gym- nastics. Again : since of a single Ibia there is one single science, there would have been a single science of aU good, had there been a single iSe'a of sR good. But in fact ' there is no single science of the good ; so neither is there any single Ihia of the good. It is indeed obvious that there ai'e many sciences of the good : not only is there no one single science of things existing in distinct categories, but not even of those which faU under una category. For example, in the category of time, the ' good ' IS the opportunity ; and this opportunity exists, of course, in war, and in sickness, but does not fall under the same category. The physiciau knows the crisis m disease, and the general the crisis in war. Again, ' the proportionate,' which belongs to the category of quantity, isappHoable both to food and exercise ; and m the one case it comes under the cognizance of the art of training-, and in the other under the art of healing. Bk. 1. 4:.] Translation. 27 4. Fourth Argument, One may further j^iss^thejjuestion as to what our friends^really mean by talking o f ja thing-in-itself,' bT^a'tmng_mJhe„al)stract' (wroeKgoToi'), seei ng, that i n the case of the ' ahsolute ' or' ' ideal ' man, and that of the individuaT, ^ctual~man, there is but o ne definitio n^ thatof man. So far fi,^® - '^^/"l"*^ as eithe r the individuaror the ideaTis man, the -with the definition types wiir'not'diler. If that 'brtraS-Df'^an,' of a thing, and .■■*■: ,, . /.• , ,1 iV — "^ ' — r. therefore also with It is eq naily trne 01 ' the g ood : in so lar as the thing itself. they are 'good,' the Hdeal good ' will not differ from the ' actual good.' Since, again, in the case of man and abstract man, there is one and the same definition, as also in the case of horse and abstract horse, that is, of course, of its Ihka (since, were the definition different, how could there be a common iSe'a of it ?) —it is evident that man qua, man differs in no way from ' man in the abstract ; ' and similarly in all cases. Hence it follows that ' good ' (qua good) differs not at all from ' good in the abstract.' 5. Fifth Argument. Furthermore, a ' good ' will not assuredly be more ' good ' by the^act^ of its being eternal ...... if it be true that what is white ..fist^ign-thenfid time ?5t:S„f,,t is not more white than whj,t is so-only. for a the character of the sin^ day. ''''"• It is further evident that the ideal good and the actual good will not differ, qua good, though the ideal good be eternal, and the actual good be not eternal, exactly as what is white for a long time is not more white than what lasts only for a day. Consequently there is not an i8ea beyond itself in the case of any Other class of existences, nor yet of ' the good.' [The Pythagoreans seem to argue with greater plausibility when th ey place ' unit y ' (ro .%v) in the .file jof-things whicTEfigoodr Speusippus, moreover, seems to p^jja^o^Ianf ^t follow in their track. But their speculations upon morepiausibiethau the subject can be reserved for another treatise. *^' "^ ^'^*°' The Pythagoreans, on their part, seem to speak of ' the good ' with greater plausibility, since they ranged ' unity ' in what they called ' the rank of the good ; ' and their view seems to be adopted by Speusippus. Their arrangement of the list of things which are good as opposed to things which are evil, was in this wise : — finite opposed to infinite straight opposed to crooked unequal „ equal light „ dark one „ many square ,, oblong right „ left calm „ agitated male „ female good „ evil] 28 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 4. (c) RESTATEMENT OF THE PLATONIC THEORY, AND NEW DIFFICUL- TIES WHICH IT SUGGESTS. But reverting to what was said above, a new difficulty is sug- gested by the fact that the argu ments of the, But assume that Platonists dojiot apjly to eve ry kind of ' good ,' the term 'goods' ^^^ lihiF~onlY things" wEicF are pursuM^'atd . IS limited to 'ab- , „ ,•' .-^ - ° -, — - — ^ — 3 t ^ Boiute goods' : will deslred for tTiRir own sake are..r apgea under ,a_ "lese ^'^absoiute gingje notion, whereas things w hich ar e^ pro- Tsingie is^a ?™ ^ ductive of thesc absolute goods ^.or-jpreservative of them, or preventive of th«H=-epp o 8i t e s, -are predicated only a^_' instrumental goods,'_andilaaluiuio©th&r sense. It Is clear,Then, that things may be predicated as 'goods' in two senses, some being ' absolute goods,' and others ' relative ' or 'subordinate goods.' Separating, therefore, things which are good absolutely from those which are good only as helps, let us examine whether these ' absolute goods ' are predicated under one single class or tSe'a. But what, pray, exactly are those goods which jjnejffiQiiId_class as 'absolute goods '? Are they not such as are pursued and de- ^~'' ■ sired even when isolated : for exanipFeTHie power Destructive criti- of^hOTTgllt Tntd-'slght and xei±aLa_jilfiasttFes and the'sis" '^ ^^''■- honours ? Surely they must be so : though there are~times when we pursue such things for ulterior reasons, yet one would certainly also rank them among absolute goods. , Here, then, is a dilemma. (1) If such thin gs as thought an d sight are not 'things good juer se;' and if, as there is nothing; else which can be put into competition with them, there is in \ fact, as Plato says^ ' nothing good except the Ihi a,' then the class which that Ma forms will be void of contents. (2) If, on the oTEer hand, sightjincLtliought are among the number of absolute goods, it will then benecessary that the definition of the_i^aod7r.shflold be seen to be identical in each and all of these cases (just as in the case of snow and of white lead the definition of whiteness is identical). So far, however, as thought, e.g., and honour are ' goods,' their definitions are various and conflicting ; and there- fore ' the good ' is not some one common attribute falling, under one general iSe'a. But we shall have another opportunity for discussing the bearings of the subject. We must now proceed to define more explicitly the nature of ' the good,' since the statements made above require further examination and refinement owing to the fact that the arguments of the Platonists were not used of and do not apply to every kind of ' good ' in specific detail. We must, therefore, dis- tinguish the various kinds of ' good ' ia order to make our theory more exact. Bk. 1. 4. J Translation. 29 Well, then : the ' good' is predicated in two senses. Some goods are good fcr se and are spoken of simply as ' goods ' and are coveted for their own saie. There are other goods which are not goods per se, but are good only on account of their results, heing pursued because they tend to prBserve or to produce goods which are so absolutely, or because they tend to counteract their opposite evils. Things good jyer se are health and virtue and the power of thought and sight. Things which are good but not per se are such as, for example, the training which conduces to a virtuous life, discipline, medicine and such things as are sought with a view to health. Goods of this class are called also ' instru- mental goods.' Distinguishing, therefore, instrumental goods from such as are good in their own right, let us examine whether there is any one single tSe'a 'of these absolute goods. Evidently, then, it is a matter of superfluity to speak of an Ihia of absolute goods. In what respect would the iSc'a differ from the members composing it, seeing that these members are as much ' absolute goods,' as the ' i8e'a of the good' itself is? The power of thought and of sight, and certain temperate pleEisures and honours, even though they are sought for other reasons, yet never- theless, apart from the addition of things external, are in and by themselves ohoiceworthy and objects of pursuit. Hence, in this respect they are ' goods ' per se and in their own right ; and we shall not have to limit that title simply to the ' Ibia of the good.' Again, if there be a single iSta of all things which are good per se, the same definition of the good will be appUoable to all things which are good, precisely as the same description of whiteness will be applicable in the case of snow and of white lead. But that is not true in the case of things which are ' good : ' since the definitions of thought and of pleasui'e, in the aspect vmder which they are 'good,' differ from one another. The 'good' of pleasure, for example, is one thing, and the ' good ' of thought a different one. {ct) POSSIBLE SOLUTIONS OF THE QUESTION SUGGESTED. Iq what sense, then, as a matter of fact, is the term 'good' predicated of different objects ? [Of course there is herein more than a chance identity of name.] understsinding^ fta 1 . Is_the-Xiam-nion4dea4nvolved in- the-eommon (5& by the iieaiist, name, owing to the %ct .thatall things which are f^.^SeSS. good,' afeHerlved from a single source ? 2r~0r is it because all things which are good, cgu tribute to a sLugle end ? "BTDr is it .not rather the result of metaghor and analogy ; for example, ' as si ght is in the body, so is reason in the soul,' and so on of other relations in other things ? But since, as has been shovra, good things are not predicated as synonyms, seeing that they have not the same definition, we must now ask in what sense they are predicated. They may be predicated :^- 1. Universally — as having the same sound but a different sense. 2. As things which flow from a common origin. 3. As things which contribute to a common result. 4. By way of analogy. [By analogy I mean, the figure by which r.;/. the mind is called ' an eye,' as holding the same relation to the sord which the eye does to the body. It is on the same principle that ' the good ' seems to be predicated : just as -wq speak of a ' good soul ' so we speak of a ' good time ' and ' a good place,' The relations i 6 30 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 4, o in such cases admit of an exact parallel. Corresponding to virtue in the soul is a fair opportunity in point of time or a fair dwelling in space, or symmetiy in point of quantity.] {e) THE PLATONIC THEORY IS TRANSCENDENTAL, AND VALUELESS IN rRACTICAL LIFE, EVEN AS AN IDEAL. Perhaps, however, it will be better to dismiss this subject for the present. To treat of the Platonic ' theory The discussion le- of ideas ' with metaphysical exactness belongs trMeta^hys^icr^ ^ more properly to another branch of Philosophy. For the same reason we will dismiss the farther discussion of the ' I lka of the good.' Even_if tke^ '.good'lvhich is predicatedTlis a common name be som e one q uality, or a thin g isolated J"rom phfenomena and absolute in itself, The question is one jt is clear that it will not be wlt]m-the_scQ£SSL outside the range . . i j V ■ i i i t> , ^^ of practical Ethics, action, nor a ..good attainamn, hy- man. But m morals the subject sought is a practical good, or a good that can be realized in action. But perhaps it mayjae thought by some to be better for us to have a krfdwledge of this ' absolute good^ in view Even as an 'ideal' of those goMs whiclTo^'attainable and produced t.mlT^^tZ by °"^ °^° eff°i-t- It may te "L8-ed that if we is valueless. have this ' absolut§_g.Qod ' aa.,Qur pa ttern or ide al, we shall the better understand wj bat thing s are ' good-'- ijL.relat|on to our own selves ; and that, if we have such a knowledge of these attainable goods, we shall succeed in attaining them. Such an ar gument has_at any rate a sho w of plausib ility ; but it see ms to be a tvariance with the lessons of t he sci ences. All the ScignceSjaimingThougE they severally do, aLs.ome.resjili,.an--traT;iT-nDTrt~tlre5e-^rinciples under the aspect in which they are severally presented % Nature, and use all dtligepce ^iialrtheir true import be properly marked oiit, since they possess^ great influence in determining what follows from thenn 'The start is morei thaii half the race;' and by hieans of a good start, or sound ' principle,' in Morals, it is thought that many_probleais_,Q£lhc_moral .liifi .ara.simultaneously made evident. The perfection of man may thus be defined as ' a conscious -activity of soul in harmony with Virtue in a complete life.' But this definition is only provisional. It is necessary of course, in the first instance, to sketch roughly our theory of the Summum Bouuiu, and afterwards to elaborate our sketch as an artist does the outlines of a picture. When the outlines of a subject have been skilfully traced, it would seem to be an easy task and one within the scope of any one who wills, to advance the work to perfection and to delineate every shade. Time itself contributes its share to this result, being, as it is, fertile in discoveries and an admirable promoter of improvements. It is owing to the work of Time that the development of the Arts has been brought about, since it is open to everyone to improve what may be defective. We must at the same time remember the cautions which were given at the outset, and not require the precision of science in all subjects alike, but in every point expect only that degree of accuracy which is consistent with the subject- matter, and never f m-ther than is suitable to the mode of treatment adopted. The carpenter does not require that his right angle shall be as faultless as the geometrician does ; but they severally require only such precision as may be in keeping with the business which they have in hand. The cai'penter seeks an angle of sufiicieirt accuracy to be of service to him in practical work ; whereas the geometrician seeks to know what a pm-e right angle is, what is its nature and what are its properties, without being desirous of effecting any material result by means of it, but seeking simply a true explanation of its real nature. We must act in this same spirit in other relations to prevent the accessories of our work growing to a greater bulk than the work itself. If, for instance, we were to demand from the carpenter a theory of the right angle — a question which is immaterial to him in view of his special work, he would be put to greater trouble in answering it, than in executing the practical work of his art. Nor, again, must we search for a cause to the same extent in all subjects. In certain cases it is sufficient that it be clearly proved that the /aci is so-and-so, even though we cannot add a reasmi for its being so. This is even found to be the case in regard to the principles of the Sciences. In regard to principles we shall not have to enquire why they are but simply as to the fact wliMltcr they are. This is the starting point of all scientific inquiry. If we had to examine into tlie cmise of our jJrinciplcs we should never make a start, but be ever groping fmther and further after an infinite ' why.' The particular facts (on the basis of which the ' principles ' of knowledge rest) are made evident to us either (1) through mental association, or (2) through the medium of the senses, or (3) through the moral instincts resulting- from education. (1.) ' Induction ' or ' mental association ' applies to such cases as that ' things which are equal to the same are equal to one another' — a truth which we can prove by bringing forward certain numbers and quantities, Induction being proof from particular instances. (2.) ' Sensation ' applies to such cases as when the student of Nature shows that ' fire is hot ' or ' water is cold ' — facts which are ' principles ' in his science. 40 The Moral Philosophy of AHstotle. [Bk. I. 8. (3.) ' Instinct ' or ' moral sense ' is the faculty by which the principles of Ethics are understood— a faculty which is the result of a moral education. It is, of course, impossible to attain to a knowledge of truths bearing upon virtue, uidess a man has spent his life in the practice of virtuous actions (as was shown in the Introduction to this Book). We must, therefore, endeavour to trace out the various ' principles ' of know- ledge as they may be severally capable of being proved, and take due care that they are made perfectly clear by means of definition, since they afford great assistance in establishing the truths which are consec[uent from them. Hence it is evident that ' the principle has a force equal to more than half the demonstra- tion ; ' and many truths of which we are in quest become evident by means thereof. In the Major Premiss ' the principle ' is invariably assumed ; and the Major Premiss carries with it almost the entire force of the Syllogism. It is for this reason — though for others also — that ' Major ' Premiss is so named. So much only need here be said, in a general way, upon the question of ' principles.' IV. — DEFINITION OF HUMAN PERFECTION COMPARED WITH OTHER THEORIES AND DIFFICULTIES SOLVED^ i. — Our Definition satisfies the Conditions of Happiness implied both in the Popular View and in the Theories of previous Thinkers. We must, however, discuss th e nat ure of_Happiness not merely from the terms of its deiinillJori_a]ld_Df_ilifi_ prb- be verified 'by the posftious in which that definition's stated, but evidence of popu- also from the view of j3opulaFQpin ion~fl.nd nif rrfint Suion.'"'^" ""'^ testimony, about it. The'attributes of a thing all harmonize with a true view of it; but the true nature of a thing is soon found to be at variance with attributes wrongly assigned to it. In regard, however, to the ' piinoiple ' which we have laid down as the basis of Ethics — I mean of course happiness, we must examine further into it, and discuss not merely the definition of happiness and the terms which make up that definition, but also whatever true conceptions were formed about it by men of old time, to see if they are consistent with that definition. If a definition be a tiue one, whatever is involved in the thing defined will be in haxmony with it ; and hence also, all that is rightly attributed to a thing, will be equally consistent with its definition ; whereas if the definition be a false one, the trath is soon at issue with it. (a) COMMON OPINION CONFIRMS OUR DEFINITION AS AN ACTIVITT OF THE SOJJL. Now thingswhich are good have been.diyidedmtojfchj-ee classes, Popular chssifiea- ^ T^ f^^ ^f f "^^^"'^ ' eitefnaUoods/" another tionadmitsthattho Dodily goods, and a third, ' spirituaLgaods,' or IrT'^the "'hiTeit ' ^^^^^^ ^^ ^oul' Of these various kinds of goods. %her!fore ' goods,' those which concem the soul, are, as we happiness, as the all admit, sovereign goods— goods, that is, in Bk. 1. 9.] Translation. 41 the very highest sense; and we define 'goods Summum Bonum, which concern the soul,' as 'moral actions- and ^lU be 'a good of the T^SiS^Iofithe-imier life, '-flFhiet-are-thf re- fore sovereign goods. {But in saying that ' moral actions and activities are sovereign goodtljoejm^^^t'th&f constitute Mp-pmemix happiness being par exce llence ' the sover eipn good; ' and) therefore hap^^ess may pro- perly be defined as ' an activity of tji&soul "... according, at any rate, to this view which has long been held and is admitted by all previous thinkers. The correctness of this view is further borne out by the fact that certain lines of conduct and activities of the.moral nature are S2id_to be '_the end' ; since thus it is proved that ' the end ' which comprehends all others, man's ' happiness ' or ' perfection,' belongs to itose^oods whicETaHectTEe'soM^, and~nort5'those goods which come from without. In harmony also with this definition is the common proverb that ' the happy man lives a noble life and acts a noble part,' happiness being itself pretty generally described as a kind of * noble living and noble acting.' Now things whieh are ' good ' are commonly divided into three classes, one class being called ' external goods,' another class ' goods relating to the soul,' and a third ' goods relating to the body.' Of these various kinds of goods, those which concern the soul are, as we all with one consent admit, ' sovereign goods ' — goods, that is, in the very highest sense. But by ' goods which concern the soul,' we mean moral actions and the exercise of our mental powers. Consequently the exercise of the vital powers in moral action and virtuous activities of our natui-e are goods in the highest and most paramount sense ; and, therefore, the sovereign and supreme good of man consists in a virtuous exercise of all the powers within the soul. And this is Happiness : it is, that is to say,, ' an activity of the soul in harmony with virtue ' — according to this view of it, which has long been held and is admitted by all thinkers. A certain mode of conduct and the development of the powers in a certain direction, is thus rightly styled ' happiness ; ' since, in this sense, happiness wUl come under the class of ' goods relating to the soul,' and not that of ' external goods.' It is for this reason also that the happy man is said to ' act a noble part and live a noble life' — terms which indicate a free play of the faculties and a certain line of moral action. (^) STATEMENT OF THE PRINCIPAL OPINIONS HELD IN REGARD TO HAPPINESS. It is also clear that the requisitions generally made on behalf of happiness are all implied in the definition above given. These requisitions are various. There are five rival Some men hold that happiness is 'virtue;' abou"happints:- otberSj that it is 'thought;' others that it is j.c. that it is— 42 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 9. (1) Vii-txie ; ' a fovm of philosophy; ' others, that it is all of (2) Thoiight ; j^j^ combined, or else one of them in combina- (3) A form of . ' x -ii i Philosopliy; tion With pleasure, or, at any rate, not witnout (5) p"^^^""^?.' pleasure. There are others, again, who would Ail"thertreories include 'asunny condition of external pros- probabiy contain at perity ' as iuvolvcd in the idea of happiness. InrutT^nrwiii S°^^^ ^f t^®^^ ^"^^^^ ^^^ advocated by the harmonize with our world generally and by men of old time; others o*n definition. i^^ t^^ £g^ ^^^ jjy jjjgjj ^f reputation. It is rea- sonable to assume that neither one nor the other are wholly and entirely mistaken, but that they are right at any rate in some particulars, or even in the greater part of what they say. It is also clear that the expectations generally formed by men on the score of happiness are all involved and satisfied in the definition above given. The requirement upon which some men insist is Virtue ; that of others is Thought ; that of others, some form of Philosophy. There are some again who think that happiness includes all these requirements ; others, again, that some om: of these conditions combined with pleasure (though a pleasure engendered by the actions themselves) satisfies the idea of happiness; while others, again, include • external prosperity ' in the notion. Some of these theories are advocated by men generally and by men of old ; others by the few and men of reputation. It is reasonable to assume that neither one nor the other miss the tmth in all points ; but fail, perhaps, only in some one particular, and are right in their main position. (1) The vlem that ' Happiness is Virtue^ discussed. As for those who hold that ' happiness is virtue ' or ' some form of virtue,' my own definition fully harmonizes tu^'^^!"!'!' ']t% ^^*^ ^^^''■®' ^°^' °^ course, ' an activity of the be premised that soul in accordance with virtue ' includes virtiie. lira'^comptl ^^Ki^ ''\-^ r^^ °f ^° ^l^g^t consequence activity. assuredly whether we understand 'the Chief Good' to consist in possession or in use, in a passive condition or in a conscious activity. It is conceivable for the passive condition to exist without effecting any good at all : it may be found in a man who is slumbering or who is rendered inactive from some other cause. But it is not possible for the active faculty to be unproductive : the possession of active virtue will of necessity lead to action and to right action. In the Olympic Games it is not the fairest nor the strongest who are crowned, but those who enter the lists, for among them the victors must be. Precisely so is it in practical life : only those who act aright find themselves the winners of its honours and fair ffuerdons. o As for those who hold that • happiness is perfect virtue,' or ' that particular virtue which among all other virtues is most perfect,' my own definition fully Bk. I. 9.] Translation. 43 harmonizes with theii-s, happiness being, aa I have defined it, ' in accordance with the activity of virtue.' But there is a difference between us on this pmnt : tl^ enthusiasts for vutne say that happiness consists in the pei-manent state or possession of virtue ; whereas I maintain that it consists in the use and conscious exercise of virtue. This is, indeed, a point of no slight consequenoe, whether we suppose that the CJhief Good consists in possession or in use — in a passive state or in a conscious activity. It is conceivable for a passive state to exist without effecting any good at all : it may be found in a man who is slumbering, or who is benumbed to a kind of torpor. But it is impossible for an activity to be unproductive. A man who has a mental power working within him, will of necessity act ; and if that power be a virtuous one, he wiU act virtuously, and that is equivalent to being happy. Just as at the Olympic Games it is not the fairest nor the strongest who are crowned, but those who are competitors in the lists, among whom alone must be the conquerors ; so also in regard to the honours and advantages to be gained in this life, it is not those who have the powers of acting aright who are successful, but those who put their powers to practical effect. (2) Relations of Happiness to Pleasure discussed. Now the life of sucli as are actively virtuous is intrinsically a pleasant life. The capacity for pleasure is indeed a property common to all conscious life ; but the ' Happiness in- actual pleasure which an individual feels is deter- . . . certainly; be- mined by the pursuits to which he is specially "^^''^e a man can- iT , ^ AT ■ yi J not be virtuons(anu addicted. A horse is a source of pleasure to a therefore cannot man who is fond of horses, a spectacle to one either be happy) 1 . n 1 /. . T , T 2.1 J.1 unless he delights who IS lond oi sights. In the same way the in his vii-tne. doing of just acts is pleasurable to one who is a lover of justice ; and, generally, acts conformable to virtue are pleasurable to one who is a lover of virtue. But as for the world at large, the objects which yield them delight are mutually antagonistic to one another, since they are not really pleasurable in their own nature. Only to the ' lovers of what is noble ' are things pleasurable which are so in their real nature ; to which class belong things done in obedience to virtue. To the cultured and noble, therefore, moral actions are pleasurable practically, as well as in the abstract. The life of the virtuous then has no need of pleasure as an amulet to liang about it, but involves a pleasure all its own, in right of itself. In fact, beyond the considerations already given, a man is not a good man at all unless he experiences pleasure at noble deeds. One could never call a man just, unless he took delight in acts of justice ; nor liberal, unless he took delight in acts of liberality ; and similarly in regard to other virtues. If this be so, it follows that whatever actions are done in obedience to virtue will be, in and by themselves, attended with pleasure to the agent. Nay, more than that : actions done in conformity with virtue, will themselves of course be virtuous and noble, and will possess 44 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 9. each of these characteristics in the very highest degree — if the good man be a true judge of such matters (and we have shown how he judges about them). Happiness is, therefore, a thing most excellent and noble, as well as being most pleasurable ; and these at- Pieasme and virtue tributes are all inseparably bound up one with bie *eieme"nte '^ta ^^^ °ther, and not severed as they are in the happmess. Delphian couplet ; " Justice is noblest of goods ; and Health bringeth ease, above all things : And to obtain what one loves, Nature makes sweetest of boons." Now all these attributes are found in man's highest activities, in the exercise, that is, of the highest part of his nature ; and we maintain that these activities (or some one of them that is the noblest of all) constitute happiness. Now the life of such as these is a pleasurable life in and by itself, and one that does not derive its pleasure from without. Seeing that the capacity for pleasure is a common property of the soul, there is nothing to prevent 'th^ activity of the soul in accordance with virtue' from being attended with pleasure, and it is evident that it is so attended. Since in all cases an object is pleasurable to a man when he is said to be specially inclined towards it, (a horse, e.)?., being a source of pleasure to a man who is fond of horses, and a spectacle to one who is fond of sights), virtue and actions done in accordance with virtue will be pleasurable to a man who is enamoured of virtue. As for the world at large, however, the objects thought pleasurable by them are inconsistent one with another. Some think one thing pleasurable, some another, and conversely with its ojiposite. The reason of this contrariety is that the things which the masses love are not things which are really pleasurable in their own true natme. On the other hand, to those who are lovers of the beautiful, only those objects appear pleasurable which are inherently pleasurable ; being, as they are, themselves of noblest frame, it is a natural consequence that they should pursue only such objects as are pleasurable in very truth, and hence the objects which they do in fact pursue, are actions that are in accordance with virtue. It is consequently obvious that actions in accordance with virtue are sources of pleasure to those who are lovers of virtue, and that for their own sake. When a thing is pleasurable by nature, its pleasantness is not owing to an alien cause. Hence the life of the virtuous requires no pleasm-e external to itself to be as it were a charm to adorn it from without : it contains a pleasure all its own, intermingled with itself. If there be any one who should aver that 'not all who are vu-tuous find delight in their virtue, since there are those who practise virtue without any sense of satisfaction in so doing,' we can only deny the fact and say that a man is neither virtuous nor good unless he feels pleasure in noble actions. No one could call a man just unless he took delight in acts of justice, nor liberal unless he took delight in acts of liberality ; and similarly in regard to the other virtues. If this be so, acts in accordance with virtue wUl be pleasurable for their own sake. ' Nay more ; such actions wUl not only be pleasurable, they will themselves be virtuous and noble ; and every such action will show these characteristics in the highest degree— if the good man be a tme judge of such matters (and that his judgment should eiT therein is hard to believe) ; and he judges that such actions ai'e virtuous and noble. Consequently happiness is a thing highest and noblest and sweetest ; and these Bk. 1. 9.] Translation. 45 attributes are all blended together ; not as in the Delphian couplet, where one thing is highest, another noblest, and something else sweetest : " Fairest is what is most just, yet 'twere best that health sh^Id be sound : Yea, sweeter than all by nature is this — to compass the aim that one loves. " All these attributes are found in man's highest activities, in the exercise, that is, of the highest part of man's natm-e ; and we maintain that these activities (or some one of them which is the noblest of all) constitute happiness. (3) Relation of Ha2}piiiess to External or Physical Conditions discussed. Nevertheless it is evident that happiness requires, as we have shown, certain external advantages. It is impos- sible, for example, or it is not easy to perform ' Happine,ss in- noble acts unless provided with outward means. vaiiia<'es'*°™^ ^''' There are many acts which have to be performed, since "the soul, to if performed at all, by the help of such agencies ^ '>^PPy, must J. . -, 1 1 T ■ T ■ ^ • navoanharmonioiis as inends, wealth, or political miluence. Again, sphere in which to there are certain things of which, if men be move and adequate deprived, they find the brightness of their hap- which to work. piness marred and its lustre gone : for instance, good birth, fair children, or beauty. A man is scarcely capable of happiness if he be distorted in appearance, or base-born, or a widower and childless, — even less so, surely, if he has worthless children or friends, or if he once had kind friends and dear children who are all deceased. A man requires, therefore, as I have said, certain favourable outward conditions to complete the sum of his happiness. Hence, some writers rank 'good luck' with happiness as others do virtue. The essential natule of happiness, therefore, consists, as I have shown, in virtuous actions. Nevertheless it is evident that it requires external advantages IJ is impossible, of com-se, or at any rate not easy to perfoim virtuous actions unless provided with external resources. Many of the best actions have to be done by the help of external means, as ' instruments,' as it were, to effect the result, whether friends, or wealth, or position in the State, or political power, or social influence. Ofttimes when men are deprived of such resources, they find their happiness to be deprived of its lustre : if, for example, he be devoid of good birth, or fair children, or personal beauty. A man cannot be perfectly happy if he be distorted in appearance, or base-born, or a widower or childless, or if he has vicious children, or if he once had dear children and has lost them. It is for these reasons that we say that happiness has need of favourable condi- tions external to itsebf, and of the sunshine of life, to keep it bright ; and with this view some have considered that the ' fair fortune ' which comes from with- out is identical with the happiness of which we are in quest, and others press the claims of virtue. The fact is, however, that there is need alike of ' fair fortune ' and of a virtuous mind to one who would be happy in the perfect sense of the term. 46 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. lo. ii. — Is Happiness within, our own power ; and, if so, what are the means for its attainment ? WITHOUT EXCLUDING OTHER INFLUENCES, MAN IS HIMSELF THE MAIN AND MOST IMPORTANT SOURCE OF HIS OWN HAPPINESS. This last discussion opens up a further question: By what means is happiness to be achieved ? Is it the But does happiness result of study, Or of moral discipline, or of some aSstMchr" for>ii Of philosophic Culture? _ Or does it rather himself can create, come to US by Way of Special Providence, or ZX ' thf S "^^y it even be owing to chance ? Will ? Now if there be any boon at all accorded by Gods to men, it is reasonable to believe that hap- piness is such a ' gift of heaven,' more especially as of all human blessings this is the highest and best. But this ^t^of^GociMs'a i^ ^ subject which will perhaps be more appro- question for Theo- priately dealt with in another Treatise. Still it logy : a,t any rate jg q^fte evident that even if Happiness be not a it IS divine and ■ p. i i i i -n- i , blessed.' gift bestowed on us by Heaven, but be a result attained by means of virtue or through some kind of study and philosophic culture, it is one of those things which are most divine. As the reward of virtue, it is undoubtedly the noblest ' end ' of man, and thus a thing divine and blessed. In any event, happiness must be within a wide and compre- hensive range: it is a thing capable of being virtue/'^Lrmust ^'^^^^^^'^ ^^ ^'^ ^^o«° progress in virtue has not therefore have a been stunted at the outset ; the means thereto wnge as wide as i^ging a kind of training and discipline. viiTjue itsfilt 5 yet -■■- . « 'i i 7 t almost aa can Moreover, it it be better that men should gain attain to virtue by happiuess by their own efforts rather than means of self-dis- .111 •, • , , , , cipiiue. through chance, it is reasonable to believe that such is in fact the case ; since whatever is in harmony with nature is so exquisitely designed that ' what- • ever is, is best." The same law of perfection J ^urJ^ie^ «^Pli^« to t^« o^^tio^s of art and to all that irj us to conclude that Owing to a defined cause, especially to that it is Ust that hap. noblest of all causes, virtue. It would surely be piness should come ■,. i , . "v/uiva auiv/ij "^ from virtue. discordant to our reason , to attribute to the capricej of chance what is grandest and fairest in life. ''i The question in dispute is indeed made self-evident by the defi- nition given of happiness, which was describei| tL°V'Ippiness ^ > conscious cxercise of the faculties, of r beoorrect,it5esaen- specific character, in conformitv with virtue.' As Bk. I. 10.] Translation. 47 for other ' goods ' there are some which it is tial chai-acter is a essential for a man to have if he is to be happy, ^Mch^neef "be- whilst others are in their nature co-operative ^d yond itself only few helpful in the way of instruments. tiot.'™^^^ ™'"''' This truth will be in accord with what was pre- mised at starting. We laid down the principle that the ' end ' of social science is the noblest of all ends. Now this Science regards it as its supreme concern to ^^,;i uff^'^^sujaes give to citizens a definite moral character and that happiness can to render them disposed to practise noble acts. fi^ed'aSs-it It is reasonable, therefore, that we should call virtuous activities; neither ox nor horse nor any mere animal f^' consistently •' . therewith we count ' happy,' seemg that not one of them is capable no one happy who of taking part in any virtuous activity from '®. ""' capable of which happiness could arise. For the same reason neither is a boy happy : owing to his youth he is as yet incapable of sucb activities as are requisite to acquire haj^piness. If ever boys are called happy, it is only because they are compli- mented by reason of the hopes formed of them. Happiness in a word requires matured virtue and jierfect harmony in its external relations, to last all life through. Many the reverses and many the These virtuous ac- changes which take place in the course of a long continued^aU life life. It is possible for a man in the highest pros- through, if the perity to incur great misfortunes as he nears old '°?™' freedom be I: J ^ o ^ taken away by ca- age, as terrible as those which the Myth records lamity, vii-tue and of Priam in the heroic poems. But if a man ^applness become ■^ impossible or dim- has encountered sorrows such as those, and has cult. ended his days in wretchedness, no one counts him a happy man. In view of this difficulty a question arises whether happiness be a result of study or is attained through some process of culture, or through constant habitu- ation to virtuous actions, or through some other form of discipline : or whether, on the contrary, it be a gift bestowed on men by the Gods, or even the effect of some chance. Jsow if there be any boon at all accorded by God to men, it would seem that' happiness is veritably that boon. Far more than all other blessings is happiness • a gift from Heaven,' in proportion as of all other human interests this is the greatest. But to argue upon these points belongs to a discussion upon Providence and to a different kind of Treatise. We must pursue our investigations upon grounds suitable to the plan which we have set before us. Still it is quite evident that even if happiness be not a ' boon of Heaven ' but be owing to virtue, or to some kind of philosophic culture, it is one of those things which are most divine. The reward of virtue and ' the end ' of man (which happiness itself exactly is), is manifestly of highest worth, and a thing divine and blessed. Wide and comprehensive for all will its range be found to be : it is possible for it to be the heritage of all who are not dwarfed in understanding nor incapable 48 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 11. of being incited to the pursuit of virtue, the means thereto being a kind of training and study. Indeed, happiness as resulting from exercise and discipline, will, it is reasonable to suppose, be greater and more perfect than anything resulting from chance. This principle is a universal one. Whatever is brought about by a defined cause, whether of art or of nature, is better than anything which is produced by chance • and more especially is that the case in the creations of that noblest of all causes, virtue. Besides, to entrust to fortune the keeping of the highest and noblest good, happiness, would prove an utter discord in nature. This truth is indeed self-evident from the definition of happiness which was laid down. Happiness was described as ' an activity of the soul according to virtue in a complete life.' As for other goods, they are partly bodily, resulting • from the body itself, and partly incidental to the body ; and of these some are necessary with a view to happiness, and others aie, as it were, instrumental to it. Necessary goods are bodily health and the sustaining of life, and those things in lack of which it is impossible for happiness to be completely realized. Instru- mental goods are such helps as wealth or friends. If, then, this is the definition of happiness, how could it possibly have its source and cause in chance ? An activity of the soul cannot result from chance. Hence what was said of ' the end ' of Social Science is consistent with this definition. We said that ' the end ' of Social Science was the Chief Good, and therefore happiness (i.e., the realization of the Chief Good) was to be found thereby. It is then with good reason that we assert that neither horse nor ox nor any mere animal is ' happy,' since not one of such creatures is there able to participate in the activities of social life ; and for this very reason neither is a child happy, since, that is, by reason of his tender age, he is incapable of per- forming moral or social acts. When children are called happy, it is because they are complimented on account of the hopes formed of them : the essential oondi- »' tions of virtue are, as we have shown, virtue and a complete life. '^i 1 say that an ' harmonious life ' is essential, because there are many reverses and all kinds of vicissitudes which befall men in the course of their lives. It is 'quite conceivable for a man who is in the very highest degree of prosperity to encounter storms of adversity as he nears old age, as in the myth which is told of Priam, in the heroic poems ; and when a man has met with misfortunes such as these and has died in. wretchedness, no one counts him happy. ill.— Is Happiness still possible for a Man, so long as sorrow may overtake him or Ms friends ? (ffl) SOLON'S VIEW VAEIOUSLY STATED AND CRITICISED: THE AMBIGUITIES OF IT. Is there then no man in all the world whom we may count . happy, so long as he is yet alive, but rather, 3 In view of possible as Solon's dictum is, must we wait to see his calamities, is any- ^^^ y one happy in life, ' or not until death? buppose the case to DC SO :— -still, is it true in fact that a man is happy even when he is dead ? Is not that an utterly inconsistent view for us to take that "^ -^ . •. T- • V, *^^^^ should be happiness in death, more par- \ Yet if happmess be +;„ „i„„i„ „ j j2 i - , ^ >. a virtuous aotivity, ticularly as we define happmess to be a mode and death be anni- of COnSCioUS activity ? hilation, how can a man be happy in death? Suppose another case, and that we say— not Bk. I. ll.J Translation. 4§ that the dead man is happy, and that such is not the idea which Solon intends, but rather that not until his death can we safeh' count a man to have been hapiiv, ?'^*„ suppose that , . 1 ,1 , o ■ ,. rm death IS not anni- as being only then out of reach of evil and hiiation : the con- sorrow; this opens up a new difficulty. It is fi°™"sf »* tj^e j.1. • 1 J j-i, i J. J 1 XI ■ 1-1 departed will be thought that even to a dead man there is a kind afflicted by the of good and evil : just as good or evil may ^onws of their befall a man in his lifetime without his being conscious of it : for example, honours and disgraces, successes and misfortunes, to his children and generally to his descendants. This latter view again presents a difficulty. A man who has lived happily until old age, and who has died as he has lived, may still encounter many reverses ^^^ '^**™ suppo- . , . , T n 1 ^.^xov^o sition seems mon- .in his descendants : some of them may be good strous :— that the and find a life in accordance with their deserts, ^^^^ ■ ^^°"^\ J'^ . r^-, conscious and that others again may experience the contrary. Clearly, their happiness then, it is quite conceivable for men, in their ?^°t-^'^ ^^ ^f '^^\ different degrees of relationship to their ancestors, their descendants to stand in all kinds of attitudes to them. But °" ^F^^- ^*''>' that the dead also should be conscious of all these ■htouH be the sup- vicissitudes, and change their own lot at every position that death ,. .. n ,T ^ !• iji ■ n • 11 • , IS mtconsciousness. alternation oi that of their iriends, becoming at one moment happy and at another wretched — that would be a mon- strous fate. Yet assuredly it would be none the less monstrous if we took the other alternative — that the fortunes of descendants do not for the very least moment penetrate to ancestors. But let us revert to the problem as originally stated : the ques- tion now raised may perhaps be explained by the light of it. Assuming then that it is necessary ' to see the end,' and not till then count a man happy (not on the Bcore of his actual happiness, but because he has once '^''^™ '^T'^^th""' been happy), surely it is absurd that while a who an happy man i& happj'^, the existence of his happiness shoxiid not be caWed should not be credited to him, merely from a rate'provisionaiiy. dislike to congratulate the living from appre- hension of possible reverses, or from having formed a con- ception that happiness is something abiding and by no means susceptible of change, whereas fortune is constantly alternating and reversing her position even in the lifetime of the same individuals. If we are to follow in the wake of fortune we shall clearly have to call the same person at one time wretched, at another time happy, revealing the happy man to be as changeful 5o The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. 1. 11. as a chameleon, and one whose condition rests on an insecure foundation. Is it right, then, to call any human being' happy whilst he is still alive, or ought we rather ' to see the end ' as Solon warns us. Suppose we assume this principle of Solon : will a man be really happy even when he is dead ? Is not such* a principle quite absurd, that a man shoiid gain his happiness by dying — especially as happiness was defined to be ' a mode of activity ? ' The inference from such a principle would evidently be that happineK consists in absolute inaction ! But suppose we state the case thus — ^that neither we ourselves nor Solon count the dead man happy on account of his having died, but because his life has been a life of blessedness right to the end, and because after a man's death one could safely count him happy, as being henceforth out of the reach of evils and misfortunes. Yet not even does this solution appear satisfactory. There is still a difficulty herein ... if we admit that to the dead man as to the living there is any Mnd of good or evil, and that he is conscious of it. Such an one will experience various phases of joy and sorrow, disgi-ace and honour. The successes of descendants, and children are put down to the account of the dead, to swell their felicity. Consequently the dead are happy and blessed on the score of the happiness of their descendants, and miserable on the score of theic misfortunes. This latter view again raises a still further difSculty. A man may have lived his own Hfe happily, and have died a death in harmony with his life ; and yet it is possible for many reverses to befall him in regard to his descendants, and for some of them to be good and to enjoy a life suitable to their deserts, and for others to be the reverse. It would however be a monstrous thing if the dead man's lot were to vary with every variation in the fortunes of his descendants,- and to become at one moment happy, at another moment miserable. On the other hand it seems an equally irrational view that the living should not impart their fprtune to those who are departed and are bound to them by nearness of race. But let us revert to the question as originally raised, and ask whether we ought not to count men happy whilst living, bu.t only after their decease. The question , which has since arisen may perhaps be elucidated by means thereof. '* If, then, it be necessary • to see the end ' and not till then count a man happy (not as though he were happy through having died, but because he was so formerly), surely it is absurd that whilst he ■('« happy, the quality which actually belongs to him should not be credited to him, but that we should shrink from calling him really happy, from an unwillingness to call the living happy and from having regard to the misfortunes of life, or from having formed a conviction that happiness is something abiding and least of all things subject to change, whereas fortune is the entire opposite. But if we foUow in the wake of fortune, we shall have to call the same man, time after time, now happy and now miserable, making the happy man to appear as changeful as the hues of a chameleon, or as one whose happiness rests on a rotten foundation. {b) SOLON'S DICTUM DISPRO'VED BECAUSE THE MAIN ELEMENT IN HAPPINESS IS A VIRTUOUS ACTIVITY 'WHICH IS -WITHIN A man's ows fo-wer. 4i Yet surely it is in no sense a right conclusion to say that our Solon's dictum is happiness follo'ws the course of fortune's caprica J in fact inconsistent Not upon fortune does it depend -whether we msi Bk. 1. 11.] Translation. 51 our life well or ill — though, for its completeness with the essential our human existence requires, as we have shown, '''''f °\ happiness certain external advantages. What deterniines ofthefaJuitw" our happiness is the exercise of our powers in conformity with virtue ; what causes our misery is the exercise of our powers in the practice of evil. This view of happiness is corroborated by the above argument concerning the insecurity of fortune. Stability is a property found in association with no per- Whatever be a formances of man so closely as it is with the Se"'' exe™se 'tf activities regulated by virtue. These virtuous hisfaonities accord- activities are thought to be more stable than ™s^ *'i/6 j^'^T, iiii. neither can they whether as successes or as reverses, clearly do not utterly destroy change the balance of a man's life. On the other hand, things important and constant, when they turn out auspiciously, will make a man's life happier still (since they are of a nature to heighten the lustre of life, and the employ- ment of his advantages becomes a source of honour and credit to ■ the possessor). When, on the contrary, a man's circumstances j take an adverse turn, they mar and disfigure his happiness : for they put upon him a burden of sorrow, and interfere with many of his activities. Nevertheless, even in adversity a man's true worth shines through the gloom of his surroundings, when he bears calmly and patiently -many and sore afiiictions, not because he is insensible to them, but as being a man stout-hearted and noble- minded. No one, then, who is happy will become miserable, if the causes which govern life be — not fortune, but the exer- i^evertecompiotdy "ise of a man's own powers, as we have shown. lost 30 long as a \Life being synonymous with activity^ and a happy Sious™"*™"^^ ''^' ^^-f^ '"'^^^^ * virtuous acticityl the happy man, being also a virtuous man, will never do aught that could make him unhappy — he will never commit deeds disgrace- ful or hateful. „, . , In fact, the idea that we have of a man who The virtuous man . .- , in it . ■ ,^ ^ gives a ' happy IS genumely good and oi sound discretion is, that tuni ' even to most he bears all the accidents of life with dignity and ^xln^H : he " is grace, and acts invariably in the most noble man- happy in spite of ncr to the extent of the means in his power and uniess™his'^ suSer^ ^^ circumstances admit ; just as a skilful General ings are incessant avails himself of his existing forces with all the thLhTafhfmS Strategy of war, or as a good shoemaker makes bocnishedbythem. the finest pair of shoes possible with the materials Bk. I. 11.] Translation. 53 at his command, and so on with artists generally. If this be true, the happy man can never become miserable, though cer- tainly he will not be perfectly happy if he coSies to be involved in sorrows like those of Priam. Yet of course he is not at any rate changeful, nor is he easily swayed to and fro : he will not lightly be dispossessed of his happiness, certainly not by ordinary misfortunes, but if at all, only by great and manifold sufferings. So too, after great trials, such a man will not regain his happi- ness in a short time, but, if ever, in the course only of a long career presenting an unbroken harmony to his activities, in which he has gained great honours and dignities. But as there are many things wMoh result from fortune, some of them being serious and others trifling, such as are trifling for weal or woe will not cause trouble nor anxiety to the good man, nor briug any change into his life. But when the changes of circumstance are numerous and important, if on the one hand they are tokens of prosperity, they will make his life one of greater blessedness : they add to the charm and lustre of happiness, since the good man turns them to the noblest and most beautiful uses. If on the other hand these changes are disastrous, they harass and mar the condition of his blessedness, and are hindrances to the play of many of his faculties. Nevertheless even in affliction the nobility of his character flashes through the gloom, when a man bears calmly and patiently many grave misfortunes, not through insensibility or callousness, but as being one who is stout-hearted and noble-minded. No one, indeed, of the happy can ever become unhappy — if it be true that happiness has its essence in the activities which are in accord with virtue : in other words, no one who is blessed will ever act in such a way as to bring about vmhappiness to himself : will never commit, that is, actions disgraceful and evil which alone can cause unhappiness. Indeed the idea which we all entertain of a man who is of sound discretion and genuine goodness, is that he will bear all chances and changes with befitting dignity. Just as the best workman displays the genius of his special art in common, ordinary material, and as a General manages the forces at his disposal, though they be inadequate, with the utmost strategy ; and as a clever shoemaker works the finest sandal from the materials given him, and all artists, likewise, in their special crafts ; precisely so the happy man will not always expect ' the favouring tide and prosperous breeze,' but will ever perform noblest deeds to the extent that his existing opportunities admit. For this reason the happy man will never become miserable, but wUl simply be ' not happy ' so far as fortune is con- cerned, should he encounter afflictions like those of Priam. Yet of course he will not be shifting nor prone to chabge : he will not easily be dispossessed of his happiness, and never by ordinary misfortunes, though perhaps he may be if they are serious and repeated. Not even by dire affliction will he be easily dispossessed. Moreover, even when relieved from the strain of affliction, not in a short time will he revert to that state of perfect good from which he has even slightly deviated, since he is a man not easily changed from one thing to another. StUl after a long interval he may become happy again, if he has meanwhile achieved great triumphs and dignities. {d) HAPPINESS IS, THEHEFOKE, WITHIN OUE OWN CONTKOL, BUT SUBJECT TO THE CONDITIONS OF OUR MORTALITY. What reason, then, is there to prevent our calling a man happy if he is developing a life in conformity with perfect virtue, and is 54 Tlie Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 11. sufficiently provided with external goods, and that, not for a casual period, but for his whole lifetime ? ... or TliB main coiiclu- must we add the limitation, ' who shall continue Samlu'r^b: tlie even tenor of his life and shall die a death in happy and may be harmony therewith ? ' Such a limitation is ne- i^tMs''''ufe, Tu" cessary, because the future is a thing hidden from his happiness is US, whereas we assert happiness to be ' an end,' tebUityoUlithiTs ^^'^ ^ *^^°o '^^^'^'^ ^ aspects ' complete and final human. in itself.' If this view be the true one, we may call all men blessed even in their lifetime, when the conditions here de- scribed are realized by them and continue to be realized until the end. But their blessedness will be such only as is possible for man. These limitations may suffice to define the influence of external circumstances upon the attainment of happiness. What reason, then, is there to prevent our calling a man of this stamp happy when he is developing a life in accord with perfect virtue, a man who, if he has met with misfortune in his outward career, will come back again to prosperity — a man, moreover, who is amply furnished with external resources, and that not for a casual period but until his death, and one who shall pass his whole life in this spirit and die a death in harmony therewith 1 [I only add the condition of ' external goods ' because happiness is the consummation of all human concern? and interests, and for this reason ought to be a. perfect good, and one deficient in no single particular.] If these conditions be fulfilled, we need not wait untU their death to call the happy by their rightful name ; but we may call all men happy in whose life the qualities enumerated above are found and continue until the end, and we may call them happy in their own lifetime. But they will be happy only as it is possible for men to be, with a human happiness — a happiness, that is, which does not admit of the realization of ' the good ' in an absolutely perfect form. Thus much only need be said to show that we ought to call men happy if they are happy, in their own lifetime. iv.— Is Happiness possible for man after Ms decease; or do the sorrows of earth still pursue him ? Now, in regard to the influence which the fortunes of our descendants and of our friends generally have But what of the . ^.i j. j_t n '' condition of men "Po^^ "s, to Say that they do not contribute in any after their decease? degree whatever to our condition hereafter, is heightenedTT evidently a misanthropic view and repugnant to minished by the the beliefs of men. fSon°Uhf ^^* ^ t^e fortunes which befall men are mani- fold and present all kinds of aspects, some reach- ing further home .than others, to distinguish each kind in detail Bk. 1. 11.] Translation. 55 would evidently be a tedious and interminable task : it will be sufficient for our purpose if the distinction be drawn broadly and in outline. • If, therefore, the case as it affects one's friends is parallel to the case of the sorrows which befall one's own self, some things entailing heavy affliction and Two points must exerting a powerful influence upon life, whilst srderatToV"-°the other trials resemble things of lighter burden ; relative importance and if, moreover, afflictions differ severally on °*j^u'°j^^'^""®' '. 1,11 -1 <, ^^"^ *"S difference this pomt, whether they happen m the case of between being the the living or of the dead, the difference being and'helrin'^'^iJIdf much greater than that between horrors openly rectiyofit.° enacted, and horrors assumed to have happened, on the stage — we must of course take these considerations into account in forming our judgment on the question at issue. Per- haps, indeed, we ought rather to argue out the prior question which arises in regard to the departed, whether they continue or not to share in earthly good or evil. Looking at the arguments stated above, it would seem that even if anything does penetrate to the dead, whether good or evil, it does so in a degree trifling and slight (either absolutely or relatively to their condition), or if not that, yet it is only of so much consequence and of such a character as not to make happy those who are unhappy, nor to take away their felicity from the blessed. To a certain extent, then, the fortunes of those whom they loved in life seem to contribute to the felicity of the departed ; and their misfortunes seem to detract fannot^ weiX*'so from that felicity ; yet only iu such a manner and heavily upon the only to such a degree as not to render the happy Sf/^hek lo? unhappy, nor to produce any such absolute in- from happiness to fluence upon their lot. ^^^^^' ""'^ ''''' We must now reply to that other question which was raised — whether the con- dition of the blessed will appear to them less blissful from their descendants or friends falling into soitow on earth. As for the view that nothing, whether good or evil, penetrates to the blessed from their posterity, or from those who are in any way related to them, — ^that is a misanthropic theory and at variance with the feelings of mankind, since man is a social and sympathetic being ; nay more, it is contrary to universal belief, since it is agreed by all men that the interests of their friends are common also to themselves. But as the accidents which befall the relatives of the blessed dead are various, and present every kind of phase, some contributing more and others less to happi- ness — to distinguish these various degrees of fortune in detail seems to be a vast and interminable task : it will be suflacient for our purpose if we distinguish them broadly, and, as it were, in outline. We will then discriminate between these various kinds of misfortune upon the same principle as those which befall the blessed in their own lifetime, and assume that certain oircimistances are great and important, and have great influence upon life, whilst others are trifling and of 56 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. 1. 12. less consequence. There is, moreover, a further difference between the circum- stances which befall relatives whilst the fortunate ones are still alive, and those which befall them after their death — a difEerence quite as great as is presented by crimes designed and carried out on the stage, and crimes assumed as having been already enacted, of which these representations are but shadows. We must, therefore, examine into this distinction. Better stOl is it that we should consider whether the blessed after their decease share with their relatives the vicissitudes of their fortunes. It is certainly evident that, even if aught reaches to them from their relatives, whether good or bad, it is trifling and slight, either as being so in its own nature, or because it is so relatively to their condition, even though it be found to be great on earth, because the blessed are no longer living a human life. But though earthly wants exercise a kind of influence, yet that influence is not of an extent nor of a character to make those happy who are unhappy, nor to take away their blessedness from such as are happy. The inference is that there is a, sympathy penetrating from the living to the dead, yet that the character and extent of that influence is such as in no wise to bring about a change in the condition of the departed. V. — Is Happiness a thing of absolute or of relative value ? Now that these questions have been decided, let us further .^ investigate the question whether happiness he- happiness take in longs to the class of things which are worthy our esteem ? Is it of praise, or to the class of things which are a good that IS credl- , i jt j.i • ^ table or a good that honoured for their own sake. is adorable ? [It is obvious, of course, that happiness is not potintLtgtor'" '^t ^i^y.rate one of those things which are in- determinate and potential.] Now it is quite evident that any object which obtains praise, earns that praise from the fact of its possessing ' credUabie"°'°or Certain qualities, or from bearing a certain rela- ' praiseworthy tion to a certain standard. For example, we pralst' impUc?'a ^^^'^^^ ^he just man, and the brave man, and standard of refer- generally the virtuous man, and virtue herself, on thrthhifpraise"^'." ^'^''O"^^ of the actions and effects which result therefrom; and in the same way we praise the strong man, and the swift runner and athletes generally, from the fact of their possessing severally certain natural gifts, and bearing a certain relation to what is good and excellent. This truth is palpable also from the case of praises offered to the Gods. They are made to appear ridiculous when referred to a human standard ; and this is a result owing to the fact that praises are bestowed, as I have explained, relatively to a perfect ideal. But if praise has reference to a higher standard, it is clear that it does not belong to what is highest and most excellent, but implies a something greater and better than the thing praised; as in fact is obvious. We do not praise what is beyond all praise— Bk. I. 12.] Translation. 57 2.e., the Grods : we count them blessed and happy, and we only- count men blessed In the degree of their 'nearness to God.' Similarly also in regard to what is ' good : * no man praises happiness as he would do justice ; but he calls happiness a state of blessedness as something grander and more divine. I think, also, that the arguments by which Eudoxus pleaded the cause of pleasure for the highest place among ' goods,' might apply here. He thought the fact that pleasure is not praised (as being itself ' a good,') proved it to be better than things which are praised ; and the only things of a similar character to pleasure are, he argued, God and the summum bonum, everything else being referred to these as a standard of value. In fact, praise implies merit; and is its proper meed. By praise, men are stirred to the performance of noble deeds, and such eulogies extend equally to the achievements of the body and the conquests of the mind. But, perhaps, the task of laying down precise rules upon these subjects is more suitable for those who have laboured upon the composition of panegyrics. To my own mind, however, it is clear, for the reasons stated above, that happiness is one of tho'se things which are honourable for their own sake, and are Happiness is its complete and perfect in themselves. Among other ^^ '"^^above"^ afi reasons it seems to me to hold this supreme rank, praise. Tiierefore from the fact of its being an ultimate principle : j.*^^"^^ forls^mi it is for the sake of happiness that we perform all sai^e. the actions of our lives, and that which is an ultimate principle and the cause of what is good, we rank as something honourable and divine. Now tliat these questions have been decided, we may proceed to examine whether happiness be one of the faculties, or one of those things which are worthy of praise, or one of those things which are honoured for their own sake. a. ' Faculties ' are the mental states or aptitudes for the arts ; as the faculty of the pilot's or physician's art is the possession of power to steer a boat or to heal a disease. /3. Things praiseworthy are such as have actually succeeded, things which, having come to the test of action, are found good. y. Things reverenced are such as are divine, and transcend the common ken. Such being the mutual relations of these three classes of things, we must inquire to which of them happiness belongs. 1. It is certainly not a faculty. Happiness is a perfect good, whereas a faculty is a thing imperfect. Moreover, happiaess is not a thing to be included amongst a multitude of others, as a faculty is, there being many kinds of faculties. Happi- ness, therefore, is not a faculty. 2. Nor assuredly is it among things which are praiseworthy. A thing is praised simply for having a share in some good. We praise the jusb and, the brave, and in fact, all good men, and virtue itself, on account of their sharing in a certain 58 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. 1. 13. quality of good, and from their having a defined relation in regard to something good and excellent. For this reason it is ridiculous to praixe. the Gods : to praise them is to bring them down to our own level — an anomaly consequent on the fact that praises are bestowed in view of the comparison they imply, and the relation they make between the thing praised and a standard of ' good.' Such, then, is the character of things which are praised ; but happiness does not bear this character, being, as it is, itself the Summum Bonum and the highest end of man. Praise is not applicable to the Summum Bonum nor to the ' highest end.' The Summum Bonum cannot be referred to the standard of any other good. For this reason we do not praisn the Gods, but call them blessed and happy ; and in the same rank we account men to be when they are most ' like to the Gods,' and also those ' goods ' which are goods in their own right, such as is happiness. No one praises happiness as one does justice ; but we account it a thing blessed, as being more God-like and excellent than ourselves, 3. Since, then, things which are praiseworthy are praised on account of soma good ' end ' which they serve, whereas happiness is not refeiTed to any ' end ' be- cause it is in itself the supreme end, happiness cannot be classed among things which are praiseworthy. The only alternative is, that happiness is one of those things to which rever- ence is paid. In this view of it Eudoxus also coincides. Being desirous of prov- ing that pleasui'e is the Chief Good and ' an end-in-itself ,' he maintained that his view of it was confirmed by the fact that pleasure does not belong to things which are praised, but is more excellent than they, being, as it is, ' an end in itself.' Of a similar nature, he said, was God and the Summum Bonum ; and that it was with reference to them as to a standard that all other things were compared, so as to be called ' good ' and to be worthy of praise. In fact virtue is praised because in consequence thereof men become capable of perfoiTning good and noble deeds. In the same way, actions which are virtuous are the subjects of encomium, whether they be owing to bodily strength or to mental power, because they tend to some good ' end.' But happiness cannot be praised, since it does not tend to any good ' end ' beyond itself, being, as has been shown, itself the ultimate ' end ' of man. However, to treat of encomia and praises, and to define to whom they are ap- plicable, is not within the scope of our subject, but belongs more uatm-ally to others to explain. Confining ourselves to the subject immediately before us, it is clear that happiness is one of those things to which reverence is paid, and which are perfect in themselves. It is clear also that happiness is the principle or source and cause of aU else being good, since we have it in view in all the actions of our lives. But the thing which is the principle and cause of all other goods we call precious and divine. v.— CLASSIFICATION OF VIRTUES BASED UPON AN ANALYSIS OF THE SOUL. i. — Importance of a knowledge of Virtue. Now since happiness is 'a mode of the soul's activity in To understand fully harmony with perfect virtue,' we must fiurther the nature of hap- consider the nature of virtue : we shall perchance examLtrenatoe g^i^ thereby a better insight into the nature of of virtue— a sub- happiness. Sa°ncer'prail' ^lus Subject is onc upon which all genuine cai statesmanship. Statesmen Seem to have spent greater pains than Bk. 1. 13.] Translation. 59 upon any other, from the desire which they have felt to render the citizens virtuous and obedient to the laws. As examples of men of this high purpose, we may take th? lawgivers of the Cretans, and those of the Lacedemonians and others like-minded, who have written in other States. If this subject, then, is one which concerns the Science of civil life, it is clear that the examination of it will come within the purpose which we assumed at starting. Ifow since happiness is ' a conscious exercise of the human faculties in harmony with perfect virtue ' we must further consider the nature of virtue : the examina- tion of it will render more distinct our theory of happiness. This is clearly a subject which all genuine statesmen must consider, from the desire which they must feel to render the citizens virtuous and obedient to the laws, as the legislators of the Cretans and Lacedemonians and others like-minded in the ancient States have done. Hence it is evident that an ' Inquiry concerning virtue ' wiU be consequent upon the scope originally laid down for our Treatise ; i.e . ' the end of the Science of civil life.' HUMAN TIKTUBS HAVE THEIK SEAT IN THE DIVISIONS OF THE HUMAN SOUL. / But the virtue into which we have to examine, is a virtue proper and peculiar to man ; precisely as ' the good ' of which we went in quest was a human Psychology is the -,■,., , t • 1 • proper basis of the good, and its consequent nappmess was such as is stuciyof the virtues. possible for man. By ' virtue proper to man ' I mean not the excellence of the body but the excellence of the soul, just as by ' happiness ' I mean an activity of the soul. If this be so, it clearly behoves the statesman to know to some extent the workings of the soul, just as the oculist who undertakes the cure of the eye should know also the economy of the whole body, and with greater reason, as the aim of statesmanship is far more precious and more excellent than that of medicine. Yet all physicians of repute study long and deep to gain a knowledge of the body. The statesman must therefore study the nature of the soul, limiting his investigations however to practical utility and to the extent which is sufficient for his particular purpose. We must, therefore, examine the nature of virtue — ^the virtue of course which is proper to man, since the happiness or perfection of which we went in search at starting was a perfection of man. Now since the special excellence of man is not an excellence of the body but of the mind or soul (indeed we define happiness as an activity of the souT), and since the excellence into which the statesman inquires is a human excellence, it is evident that he ought to know how the economy of the soul is constituted. In the same way it is essential that one who is to treat successfully an eye-disease should have a knowledge of the whole body. But even more than the physician, it is 6o The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. 1. 13. right that the statesman should understand the phsenomena of the soul in proportion as statesmanship is more excellent and of higher worth than is the ait of healing. Yet all physicians of repute labour earnestly to gain a knowledge of the body, so that it is only reasonable that statesmen also should understand the condition of the soul ; yet we need not carry our speculations further than may suffice to elucidate the theory of virtue. ii. — Division of the Soul into (1) Eational and (2) Irrational. To examine the psychology of the subject with any minuteness would be a superfluous task and beyond the scope Popular ciassifica- of the present Treatise. The bearings of the tion of the soul subject are sufficiently explained in my Public 'nm-r?Wo°nap'may Lectures ; and the conclusions there drawn maybe be adopted here. adopted here. It is, for example, admitted that ' part of the. soul is irrational, and part contains reason.' It is immaterial for our present purpose whether these two parts are distinct and separable from one another, like the different members of the body, and as everything is which can be broken up into separate parts ; or whether they are only distinguishable logically and in thought, being physically and in their own nature inseparable, just as much as the concave and convex in the circumference of a circle. To'elaborate a scientific theory of soul, and to exhibit its wider issues, would be beyond the scope of our puipose. I have already treated of psychology, not only in various compilations but also viva, voce with those whom I have met in discussion ; and I wUl here adopt some of the conclusions at which we have arrived. I premise then that there are two divisions of the soul, one rational, the other irrational. But as for the question whether these parts are separable and distinct from one another, as the parts of the body are, and as other things are which can be broken up into their component elements, or whether they are in fact one and only logically distinct (like the concave and convex in the circumference of a circle, which are in reality one and in their nature inseparable though differing ' in definition, that of the concave being one thing, that of the convex another)— this is a question which tends in no way to the elucidation of the problem before us. iii. — Subdivision of the Irrational Element into (a) Nutritive and (fi) Emotional. But in the irrational part of the soul there is one element re- sembling a property common to all organized life The -nutritive'eie- ^nd which is merely vegetative— I refer to that ment m the 'non- i • i • j.i p • ■ . , .1 rational ' part of which IS the cause ot receiving nourishment and the soul may be growth — such a power of soul as one would ^driursoop^e."" ' attribute to all creatures capable of increase, and even to animals in the foetus, a power identical Bk. 1. 13.] Translation. 61 also in creatures which are full-grown (since it is more natural to helieve that this latter power is identical with the power of increase, rather than diverse). , The excellence of this part of the soul is, however, evidently an excellence common to all organized life, and not one special to man. Indeed the nutritive part of the soul and the nutritive power itself seems to be most active in time of sleep ; but during sleep the good man is not in the very least distinguishable from the bad man ; and hence the proverb that ' for half their days the happy differ nowise from the wretched.' This is but a natural consequence, sleep being the repose of the soul in so far as it is said to be good or bad : — except that to some slight extent certain emotions penetrate into it, and in that way the^ dreams of the good are purer than those of ordinary persons. But enough of these speculations. We may omit the nutritive part of the soul from our consideration, since it is of a nature foreign to the special excellence of man. We will now proceed to speak of the irrational part of the soul. In this division there is one element which is vegetative — I am alluding to the power of nutrition and of growth which is common to all plants and animals. This power indeed is found in all things capahle of growth and even in embryos, and it is this self- same power which is found in creatures who are full grown (for it would he absurd to suppose it to be any other). In this faculty, however, it is impossible to detect the excellence of man in the proper sense of the term : its excellence is shared by all organized life. Indeed this power of Increase and of growth is of a nature to operate even when men are asleep, and more so then than at any other time ; but the special excellence of man is of a very different character from that. The good man is never so little distinguishable from the bad man as when asleep ; and for this reason men say that ' for half their days the happy are in no wise different from the wretched,' that is, duriug the period of sleep. There is good reason in the proverb, sleep being iuaction both to tlie good and to the vicious soul. Only one may say so much — ^that the slumbers of the good are purer and better than those of the bad ; since the physical inclinations of the daytime penetrate in a sense even to sleep ; and hence ' the visions of the night ' assume a healthier form to the good than to common mortals. But enough of these speculations : sufficient to have shown that the nutritive part of the soul is devoid of that human excellence with which our business lies. iv. — Subdivision of the Hational Soul into (1) Emotional and (2) Intellectual. But there seems to be another part of the soul which is irrational and yet has in some sense a share of reason. We praise the reason as well of the man whose The other element character is weak and immature, as of the man rational &a^\ whose will is strong and whose character is formed, 'emotional,' which We praise also that part of the soul which is the "Ift^son; special seat of reason ; since reason is man's true and capable of 62 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. I. 13. ' good impros- guardian and incites him to whatever is noble, sions.; It is thus yg(. t^^^^^^ jg evidently both in the strong and in sometimes resist- the weak character, a tendency to transgress ing, sometimes as- reason — a force that is at variance and conflict similatmg reason. . , ^ „ , . , . . , , , , , . , With reason. In tact it is with the soul as with paralysed parts of the body: when men assay to move to the right they swing to the left, contrary to the force exerted. But in the case of bodies, we see the thing that is borne in the wrong direction : in the case of the soul there is nothing that we can see. None the less however we may be quite assured that there is in the soul an element contrary to reason, thwarting its influ- ence and moving in an opposite direction to it. It is immaterial to discuss kotv this conflict arises. Yet even this irrational part of the sotil seems to have a share in reason, as I have said. At any rate in the case of the strong and matured character this element is obedient to reason ; and iu the case of the brave and temperate man the character is submis- sive to reason to an even greater degree, in their case every element of their nature being perfectly attuned to reason. Consequently the irrational part of the soul is also seen to he two-fold. The nutritive element has no part nor lot in reason, but the emotional and appetitive element and generally that j)ai't which is the seat of impulse, does share in reason in a certain sense ; — in so far, that is, as it is submissive and obedient to reason. AVitli this view we say in common language that we ' admit the reasons' of our friends, or of our father {i.e. submit to their guidance), but that in a very different sense from that iu which we ' admit the reasons ' of mathematical demonstrations. [_In the former case the mill and tlie character are parties to the assent: in the latter case the reason onlf/.] The statement that ' the irrational element is somehow under the control of the reason ' is further proved by the moral appeals which men make, and by the various sorts of reprimand and exhortation. If then we must admit that the emotional element of the soul also involves reason, the rational part of the soul will also be two- fold—one part absolutely and in its own right, the other part being attentive and deferential to reason as to the advice of a father. But there is another power or tendency in the soul not in every respect irrational (as the one first mentioned was) hut in a way participating in reason, and even entering into oonfliot with it. On this account we sometimes praise the reason of the strong-minded man, and sometimes that of the weak-minded man, since both hold out against a force opposed to them — in the one case as long as is right, and Bk. I. 13.] Translation. 63 in the other case at any rate up to a certain point. Hence there is evidently another power within them which contends and struggles against reason. In simple truth, just as paralytic parts of the body, when men strive to move them to the right, swing contrariwise hack to the left,^o is it also in regard to the soul. The impulses in men of weak character bear them back in a du-ec- tion contrary to the suggestions of reason. But in the case of bodies we see the part that is strained back ; whereas in the soul there is nothing that we can see. StiU. though this moral struggle is not seen with the eyes, it is a real fact, and we must take it into our consideration that there is a power within the soul besides reason, opposed to it, and in conflict with it. To describe the mode in which this conflict takes place is immaterial to the purpose which we have in hand. Yet this element also has Unmistakeably a share of reason, as we have shown, in so far as it is obedient to reason. This irrational element (I mean the impul- sive or appetitive part of the soul) is guided and governed by the reason of the strong-minded man : even more easily controlled and influenced is it by the reason of the temperate and brave man in whose character every element is in perfect accord with reason. Accordingly it is evident that the irrational part of the soul is twofold. In one respect it is absolutely irrational, as the principle of vegetation, of growth and of nutrition. In the other aspect it participates in reason up to a certain point, as the principle of impulse and desire — a principle which participates in reason in BO far as it is submissive and obedient thereto. That this irrational part is to a certain extent governed by reason is a fact rendered evident by the counsels and exhortations and reproaches which are addressed to it ; and by means of which many of our irrational inclinations are brought to order. But a man is said to ' share in reason ' in a double sense, just as he is said to ' have reason.' We speak of a man ' admitting the reasons ' of his father or friends — i.e. betaking himself to them and following the advice which they give. We speak also of a man ' admitting the reasons ' of mathematical demon- strations, i.e. comprehending their meaning and having knowledge or scientific perception of them. In an exactly similar way a man is said to ' ulinve in reason ' in a double sense. In one respect he is said to ' share in reason ' absolutely and in his own right just like the purely intellectual part of the soul. In another sense a man is said to share in reason on account of his being submissive to reason, in the way in which one is submissive to his father. V. — Corresponding divieion of Virtue into Moral and Intellectual. Corresponding with tliis division of the soul is the division of virtue into distinct forms. We say tliat certain virtues are moral, and that certain others are Accordingly the intellectual— wisdom, insight, and prudence for J)*pt4ei7mtional instance being intellectual, liberality and temper- (t.e., intdlect^mi), ance moral. In speaking of a man's moral nature ," *^' semi-rational , '^ , . °., .., , . ('•"•> emotional or we do not say that he is philosophic or that he has moral). insight, but that he is gentle and temperate; though we praise the student of philosophy too in respect of his mental powers. But whatever states of mind are praiseworthy we call virtues. Corresponding with this division of the soul is the classification of virtue into distinct forms. We say that certain virtues which belong to the rational part of the soul are intellectual virtues, and that certain others which belong to the 64 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. 1. 13. impulsive or appetitive part of the soiil are moral virtues. The intellectual virtues are such as philosophy, insight, and prudence ; and the moral virtues such as liberality and temperance. When we speak of a man's moral nature, we do not say that he is philosophic or that he has comprehension, but that he is, for instance, gentle and temperate ; though we praise the student of philosophy in respect of the excellence of his mental habit, which is in fact a virtue. For whatever states of mind are praiseworthy we call virtues. BOOK IL-THEORY OF VIRTUE. INTEODUCTOEY ANALYSIS. I.— GENERAL CHARACTERISTICS OF MORAL VIRTUE. In the preceding book we sketched a definition of human perfection which implied that virtue was its main element. We stated at the conclusion of the book that virtue was two-fold, moral and intellectual. But moral and intellectual virtue cannot be treated of together : they have a different origin and a different sphere. The important element in intellectual virtue is knowledge ; in moral virtue, training or discipline. Eeserving intellectual virtue to a later book, let us proceed with our analysis of moral virtue. It is necessary, first of all, to show the origin of moral virtue. How is it produced ? Is it dependent upon Divine Providence, or is it the gift of Nature, or is it the result of our own efforts ? i. Proofs are, therefore, first given in support of the view (a) that moral virtue does not depend upon Nature ; O) that it is capable of being engendered by human effort ; and (y) that it is consohdated into habit by the help of daily discipline. In brief, the arguments are as follows : — 1. What exists through a fixed constitution of Nature cannot be re- versed or made spontaneously to change its character. But, in fact moral qualities lose their character or acquire a fresh one through education and other influences. Therefore they are not the expression of unalterable law. 2. Natui-e, indeed, gives us certain capabilities, but these capabilities are unformed and indeterminate : education is necessary to mould them into shape. Nature does not effect her purpose per se, but requires our own co-operation to supplement her work. 3. Natural qualities exist prior to and independent of exercise. But moral qualities are only brought into existence by exercise. We have to learn how to be virtuous by practising the virtues. 4. All legislation assumes human responsibility, and is an appeal to our moral freedom. Assuming that man can be educated, and ought to be educated, legislation aims at producing a system of universal training. Yet training and education would be idle and useless if fatalism were true, and men were horn good or evil. 66 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle, 5. Further, if acts repeated form a tendency or ' habit,' and if every such act necessarily bears a character that is moral or immoral, our habits will reflect the character of the acts which formed them, and will be either moral or immoral. But the acts are under our own control : therefore also the moral tendencies which we make habitual to us, will bo under our own control also. By accustoming ourselves, therefore, to the practice of brave acts, we gronu to be brave ; and by accustoming ourselves to acts of self-denial, we grow to be self-controlled. Virtue is therefore not innate but acquired. The conclusion seems to be that a man's character for good or evil is not what nature created, but what education has fashioned it to be. Hence the extreme importance of early discipline. Our actions have an influence spreading all life through : every act tends to repeat itself, and to create an incipient habit ; and when repeated often, the act grows to be a confirmed habit or ' state ' of the moral nature. ii. But how are we to determine what actions are right, and what actions are wrong ? This is a question of extreme importance, more especially as Ethics is a practical Science. If we can detect what are the qualities in actions which constitute their goodness or their badness, we shall be able to take the first step towards virtue : the actions we per- form being virtuous actions, the habits which result therefrom will be virtuous habits, and thus we shall be enabled to develop a virtuous cliaracter. Of course there is the general principle which may be at once assumed, that a right action must be conformable to Right Keason. But that is a standard unattainable except to those whose intellects have been thoroughly trained, and who have developed an intuitive faculty of discriminating right and wrong. In a subsequent book we will examine morality under this aspect, and explain fully the nature of Right Reason. For the present we will look at the more obvious characteristics of right and wrong : — not that we can frame^infallible rules. Circumstances are too complex to admit of exact or scientific generalization. We can only indicate the more general features of good and evil, leaving the determination of particular cases to the moral sense of the agent, to be settled at the moment of action. Still it may conduce to the guidance of the student, and be a contribution to the philosophy of Ethics, if we describe the more prominent features of right and wrong. There is, then, this most characteristic impression which 'right' causes : — that it is a ' fitness ' of things, an exact adjustment between means and ends, a moderation, in absence of all extravagance whether of excess or defect. It is analogous to what health is in the body — freedom alike from superfluity or from want. It may be described as a harmony or ' consistency ' of life. iii. But how are we to distinguish an act which is isolated and accidental, from one which flows from a confirmed habit of virtue ? The act may be outwardly the same; but the following points must be noted : 1. There is a greater /a«7iYy seen in the performance of an act which flows from a settled state of the will : the inward struggle has disappeared. Introductory Analysis: Book II. 67 The man who has grown to be strong finds it easier to undergo toil than before ; and in precisely the same way, the man who has grown to be virtuous and who has, for instance, formed a ' habil^of temperance,' finds an ease and readiness which makes the burden of his self-denial light. 2. The virtuous action which flows from a virtuous habit, is accom- panied by pleasure to the agent. If a man performs a virtuous act, but finds the performance of it irksome and grievous to him, therein is proof that the virtue has not become natural nor habitual to him. But if a man feels pleasure in acts of virtue, therein is proof that he has attained to a state of mind that is congenial to him, and that the virtuous act flows from the virtuous habit. iv. But not only is it true that pleasure is the index of habit : it forms the whole sphere of morality. Virtue, as the perfection of the moral or emotional nature, is -necessarily concerned with the emotions ; as may be shown by the following arguments : 1. From the nature of the case : (1.) Pleasure, or the avoidance of pain, being the motive of our doing evil, we must, in order to be virtuous, learn to associate pleasure with what is right, and pain with what is evil : such a discipline and cultiva- tion of the feelings is the only right education. (2.) Virtue is the regulation of the emotions and of conduct, both of which are inseparably attended by pleasure or pain. Therefore, virtue is attended by pleasure and pain. (3.) The virtues are kept healthy by means of pain, as moral medicine or punishment for excess of pleasure (or vice). (4.) The moral states are formed under the influence of pleasure and pain, and continue what they are from their attitude thereto. Virtue is not the exemption from the feeling of pleasure, but the proper regula- tion of that feeling. 2. From our own susceptibilities : (1.) We are influenced to the choice of a thing by the consideration of the ' beautiful,' the ' expedient,' or the ' pleasurable ' ; and to the avoidance of a thing by their opposites. In all such cases the virtuous man is sure to be right in his choice, and most assuredly so in reference to pleasure, which enters as an element into everi/ consideration. (2.) Pleasure is engrained in the very tissue of our being : more or less, in different degrees we all make it the standard of our duties : it is the strongest motive from our childhood upwards. (3.) Pleasure remains the most difficult struggle for our maturer years, and excellence is ever concerned with what is difiicult of achievement. The following truths may now be regarded as being established : CI. Pleasure and pain constitute the domain in which moral virtue must be displayed, p. The emotions cannot become permanently virtuous, (i.e. virtuous ' habits ' cannot be formed) unless a definite line of conduct be persisted in. y. A virtuous ' habit ' being formed will reproduce the acts which led to its formation, F 2 I 68 Th Moral Philosophy oj Aristotle. V. Here we must explain a seeming inconsistency in our theory. How is it that men perform virtuous acts before they are themselves virtuousi Can an act be virtuous while the author of the act is vicious % Does not the analogy of the arts suggest that if a man does just acts he is him- self just — precisely as he would be a musician if he performed musical compositions % In answer to this difficulty we may reply : 1. The case of the arts is not quite a parallel one : a man may execute an artistic piece by chance or from the suggestion of others ; but he will not be an artist unless he has knowledge of his own. 2. If the analogy held good it would prove nothing. In conduct involving issues of right and wrong, it is not sufficient for the act to bear the impress of certain qualities : — the agent must have certain qualities. Besides the knowledge of his act (which the artist also must have) a man, in order to be moral, must have a formed attitude of heart and will, and also a firm, unwavering disposition. Our reply, therefore, is that the mere performance of a virtuous act does not make a man virtuous, nor an act virtuous in the true sense : virtue is meaningless, except as involving an assent of the will and expressing a formed disposition of heart. To create such a permanent disposition of virtue it is essential to perform virtuous acts. Such performance often repeated, will lead to the formation of a virtuous ' habit.' But mere knowledge of right, unless accompanied by the practice of it, is utterly futile : only practice can make us perfect. II.— FOEMAL DEFINITION OF VIETUK. The previous discussions have sufficiently cleared the ground for a more exact definition of virtue. It has been shown that virtue is not inherited from Nature, but acquired by our own efforts ; that it is, in fact, the result of constant practice of such acts as law prescribes, or reason suggests. We will, therefore, construct our definition, ' per genus et differentias.' i. The ' genus ' or material nature of virtue may be arrived at by au enumeration of the powers working in the soul, and by a gradual process of elimination. We may classify those powers as (1) 'feelings' — i.e. all states of consciousness which are attended by pleasure or pain ; (2) ' capacities,' or the dormant susceptibilities of our nature ; and (3) ' habits,' — %.t, permanent dispositions of soul. We may eliminate ' feelings,' because they do not involve any moral character, nor an assent of the will; and we may eliminate 'capacities,' because they do not imply any moral character, but are dependent ott4^ physical causes. \ There is, therefore, no alternative but that virtues fire ' habits.' ii. The definition of virtue as ' a habit ' is as inadequate to express its nature as it would be to describe a statue as ' stone-work.' We must consider what are the more distinguishing features of virtue : what is the ' form ' which ' habit' assumes when it is identical with virtue f m Introductory Analysis: Book II. 69 Now what is the simplest conception we have of ' excellence ' ?— Is it not that of a quality which enables an object to fulfil its proper function perfectly ? The excellence of man, therefore, (i.e. Mis virtue) will be that quality which enables him to make the function of his life perfect We may perhaps analyse this idea of perfection more definitely still, if we will take the illustrations which we may derive from mathematical proportion. Proportion implies excess and defect and ' a mean,' and that either absolutely in relation to tbe thing itself, or viewed in. relation to the circumstances of individuals. Relative proportion takes cognisance of the whole conditions ; and is such as the trainer has in view when he adjusts the dietary of his pupils according to their special needs, so as to attain a perfect ' fitness ' in every case. These ideas of art and of proportion may be applied to the moral life of man. Virtue, like art, is the perfect finish in the work of man : even more delicate than the touch of art, is that ideal beauty which virtue spreads over the life of man. Wherever feeling is displayed, virtue ensures its-perfect harmony with all its surroundings, guards it from all extravagance and all defect. Wherever action is necessary, virtue gives to it a genuine gracefulness. But it is no easy thing to realize this perfect beauty of the moral life, — to finish off our display of conduct and of emotion with the graceful pro- portions of an ideal virtue. The forms in which evil is possible are so manifold, so diverse and so infinite, that it is hard indeed to escape from every conceivable temptation. The definition of virtue is now fairly established. As to its material nature, it is ' a permanent disposition of the moral nature.' As to its form, it is moulded after an ideal of what is best relatively to the con- ditions of human nature ; but this ' form' changes with the vicissitudes of circumstance, and must be left to the judgment of Right Reason to determine under special connections ; and that Right Reason can only be developed after a manifold experience of real life. ill. But, after all, the conception of ' the mean ' is only a metaphor which may illustrate the idea of virtue under certain aspects, but is not of universal application. It can apply only to ' things indifferent ' — to those aspects of the moral life which are not good or evil per se, but only in their uses. There are, however, certain classes of actions which are good or evil independently of all conditions and of all limitations. Certain emotions — e.g., rejoicing at evil ; certain actions, e.g., adultery, are inherently and absolutely wicked ; and the idea of a mean is meaningless when applied to them ; there- is no ' Fine Art ' of murder; Such acts as murder do not depend upon any kind of condition ; but are evil under every conceivable circumstance,. , So neither can ' the mean ' be applied to things which are themselves deviations from a mean : there can be no ' mean ' in things which are excesses or defects ofanother mean. 70 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. III.-CLASSIFICATION OF VIRTUES TO ILLUSTRATE THE LAW OF THE MEAN. We may now proceed to show how the principle of proportion applies under different circumstances and conditions of the moral life— how virtue is the avoidance of all extravagance and inconsistency of life, and how the vices are the perversions of what is ' fitting ' both in feeling and in conduct. We may use the Diagram of the Virtues' and Vices for the purpose of our illustration. i. In questions of plea- sure and pain . ii. In giving and re- ceiving of money iii. In seeking honour (a) self-reoarding virtues. Excess. Mean. 1. Awidomci of pain, (a) In confidence Rasliness . . Courage . (h) In fear . . Cowardice . Courage . 2. Pursuit of \ gguguajigm . Temperance Defect. Cowardice. , Rashness. Asceticism. 1. Ordinarily. {a) In giving . Prodigality . Liberality (6) In receiving. Meanness . ^■' '■■'■■ ( Ostentation '. and want ( of taste . 2. In great wealth 1. In great honour 2. In small honour . , Meanness. , Prodigalily. Vain-glory Ambition . Liberality Magnificence . Stinginesi Magnanimity [ ] Unambitiqp. Littleness of soul. (b) VIRTUES RELATING TO SOCIETT. i. In regulation of temper Passionateness Good temper Listlessncss. Indifference. ii. In intercourse of society . . . i. In the emotions of shame. . . . 1. Regarding truth 2. Regarding agreeableness. ("^ \"on^"°*' I Buffoonery . Politeness . ih) In business . Adulation . | n ■ i i ■ Sycophancy ] ^nendsUip (C) SEMI-VIRTUES. Dumbfounded Modest Boastfulness . Truthfulness . Dissimulation. , Boorishness. . Churlishness. ii. In contemplating the [....;. Envious . \ ^ig^^teously fortunes of others \ _ j indignant . Shameless. Spiteful. IV.— PRACTICAL CONSIDERATIONS FOR DETERMINING THE MEAN. i. In comparing the various states of ' excess ' and ' defect ' with theii proper ideal, we note that they are all mutually opposed the one to the other. ' Introductory Analysis: Book II. "ji But the following points may be noted in reference to the degrees of opposition which are found among them : 1. The ' mean ' man in steering his course clear oftall extremes, pleases neither of the extremes : each of them call him by the name of the other. The temperate man, for instance, seems an ascetic in the eyes of the sensualist, and a sensualist in the eyes- of the ascetic. 2. The extremes are wider apart from one another than either from the mean. Between the mean and either of the extremes there is a kind of affinity and some elements in common, but the extremes are utterly dissimilar and at variance with one another. 3. The mean is more opposed to one extreme than to the other. There is a twofold reason why this should be so : (a) In the nature of the case there is a greater correspondence between one extreme and the mean, than between the other — the natural affinities being greater, (fi) From our own susceptibilities : we are more prone to one thing than to another ; and that extreme is the worst towards which we are the more easily led. ii; We have now said enough to show what is implied in the dictum that Virtue is a ' mean state ' : it is an ideal standard by which all conduct and all feeling might be made to assume the noblest conceivable form. But in delineating this perfect conception of our actual life we have implied that it is a difficult task to realize it. The beauty of life is so easily marred : the estimate of times and means which give the exact turn to action, is so easily mistaken, that it is difficult indeed to be virtuous after this ideal pattern. We may, however, suggest a few simple rules which may serve for our guidance in the effort to attain to the perfect ' fitness ' of virtue. 1. Avoid the worst extreme : — though you should rebound to the other extreme, choose the least of evils. 2. Avoid your besetting sin : set yourself resolutely against that form of evil to which your own tendencies incline you most easily. 3. Avoid pleasure above all things : admire and praise the charms which pleasure can afford, but dismiss it from your aims as the Greek counsellors voted to dismiss Helen. Still rules are for the most part futile : no system of casuistry can anticipate the infinite complications of circumstance. The varied shapes and combinations of circumstance must be judged separately, as each new phase arises. The only sure index is. the Moral Sense of the agent. [To train and educate that Moral Sense until it becomes an unerring instinct, or Conscience, is the work of life, and requires very favourable conditions of discipline and experience.] The Moral Sense must take an instantaneous survey of what has to be done imder the conditions of the moment, and its judgment, when fully educated, will be infallibly right. TEANSLATION. I.— GENERAL CHARACTERISTICS OF VIRTUE. i. — That Virtue is a permanent state of mind produced by our own Actions. - , (a) DIFFERENT ORIGIN OF MORAL AND INTELLECTUAL VIRTUE. There is, then, a two-fold excellence of the soul : there is * moral ' and ' intellectual ' virtue. The excel- of'^inteUectuai^ex- l^^'^^ °^ °^^ intellectual nature takes its earliest ceiience is know- rise and its aftergrowth for the most part from iltlw%l"tice! instruction, and hence requires experience and length of time to mature it. On the other hand the excellence of our moral nature is a result brought about by constant practice of moral acts, the term ' morality,' tj^ikt}, being in fact derived from edos, ' habit,' with only a slight change. Now since virtue is a perfection of the soul, and one element in the soul is rational and another element impulsive, it necessarily follows that virtue also is of a two-fold character : as the excellence of our intellectual nature it takes the form of Philosophy and Thought ; and as the excellence of ovir emotional nature, it is called Moral Virtue. To a certain extent intellectual excellence has its origin in Nature. It receives its earliest impulse from nature — man being by nature a receptive being, and capable of assimilating knowledge ; and it gains a certain degree of increase fi'om the natural disposition in certain cases. Yet, for the most part, and among men generally, it owes its earliest rise and its after development to instruction, and hence requires experience and length of years to mature it. The causes which produce mural excellence ai'e different from this. Moral excellence is a result brought about by the constant practice of moral acts. All that Nature contributes to moral excellence is the capacity she gives us for grow- ing to be virtuous ; and all that instruction contributes is the knowledge that it is our duty to be virtuous. But as for being virtuous in fact, and in our own per- sonal behaviour, nothing but constant practice of virtuous actions can secure that to us ; and hence it is that virtue has derived its name from habit, being called ' moral,' rjdLKi), from Wos, ' habituation,' with only a slight change in one letter. {b) PROOFS THAT MORAL VIRTUE IS NOT A GIFT OF NATURE, BUT A CREATION OF HABIT. 1. From this consideration it is further clear that no form of moral excellence is developed in us spontaneously, by a fixed Bk. II. 1.] Translation. . 73 constitution of nature. What belongs to the order of Nature can never be brought to act contrary to its law. A stone, naturally gravitating to the earth, could never be brought of its own accord to soar heavenwards : though l- Moral virtue is one were to try to form such a habit in it by ^^ttf^US:: hurling it into the air ten thousand times, it cannot be changed: could never be forced to change its own law. fixeJ aud'unaiter- Conversely, fire could never be habituated to able. move downwards. In fact, when things have a fixed tendency in obedience to a law of nature, they can never be made by practice to act contrary to that tendency. 2. It is not, therefore, through an irresistible law, nor yet in violation of any such law, that the various' forms of moral excellence are developed in man : nay, 2. Yet natnre sup- rather we are born with a nature capable of feriais"%McWe" virtue, but the realization of those capabilities iterated effort can can only be attained by means of habit. '?<"^'' ^°*? P^*'=J •' ■' shapes of moral beauty. 3. Again, where qualities attach to us by nature, we are first put in possession of latent powers, and then proceed to put our powers into outward effect. This truth is obvious in the case of the senses. 3. Qualities iu- We did not obtain the senses of seeing and hear- ,\l""* ?f Z^Zt '-' ale "pnor 10 Use ing from the fact of our having constantly and exercise ;moraZ seen and heard. On the contrary, we used our orn from the outset good or bad workmen. This truth presents a precisely similar aspect in the sphere of the vii-tues. According as we discharge our obligations to our fellows we grow to be, some of us just, some unjust — in the one case from acting invariably in a spirit of justice and in conformity with law, and in the other case from om' behaviour to our fellows being the reverse of just. When, again, we are thrown among circum- stances of peril, we grow into the habit of showing confidence or fear, and thus become, some of us brave and others cowards. Even in regard to our desires and impulses the same law holds good : from the habits which we form and the mode in which we comport ourselves when our feelings are called into play, we grow to be, some of us temperate and gentle, others dissolute and passionate. (c) SUMMARY: THE IMPORTANCE OF MORAL EDUCATION. To sum up the argument: the moral nature assumes certain permanent tendencies, or 'habits,' as the result of the various lines of conduct in which it has been jjj""^, ^^^^^ ""^ exercised ; and the character of these various ten- not inherited nor dencies corresponds to the character of the various g^,"^'^^ it'is*i„ "ur acts out of which they have sprung. Wherefore own power, by the 76 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. II. 2. help of education, it is our duty to give to our every act a definite to gire to our lives gjiaracter of moral worth, seeing that it is from whatever moral ' , .1 character we will. the quabties of thcse separate acts, through all the incidents of daily life, that our 'habits' (2.^., the permanent tendencies of our moral being,) take their tone and colour. It is a matter of no slight consequence, then, upon what principles and amid what influences we are trained from childhood; nay, rather, it is a matter of vast and even sovereign importancei To sum up the argument and to describe our theory of the origin of virtue in bne sentence : every ' habit ' or formed state of mind, is engendered from an exercise of the faculties, and the one corresponds to the other as cause and effect — when the activity is virtuous, the habit "wiU be virtuous, when the activity is evil, the habit will be evil. Looking to this relation between the activity and the habit, we must not say without qualification that ' the exercise of our powers is a cause of a virtuous habit,' but premise that such exercise must be a virtuous exercise ; nor must we say that a bad habit is owing simply to the exercise of our powers, but premise that such an exercise in that case must be a bad one. To take the case of house building : we must not say that the exercise of our pov/ers upon house building is the cause of a correct state of mind thereon, but rather that if the faculties have been exercised rightly upon house building, then a correct state of mind is brought about in reference thereto, and vice versa. In fine, we must assign to each one of our mental states certain definite activities as their cause. Our habits or permanent states of mind follow closely upon OTir activities through the varied changes of daily life. For these reasons it is a matter of great consequence, as determining the character of our habits or moral tendencies, whether the practices to which we become habituated from youth upwards be good or evU ; nay, rather, the entire difference in the character of our moral tendencies is owing to this early habituation. ii. — Qualities exMbited by virtuous action, (a) KEED FOR A RULE OF LIFE. Our present Inquiry, therefore, is not, as scientific Inquiries generally are, with a view simply to speculative muTt'te Tiddown knowledge. The aim which as moralists we have in for discriminating view is uot simply to gain a scientific theory of the quality of virtue, but rather that we may ourselves grow to actions. 1 ■ / 1 ■ ,1 . ' , ... be virtuous : — otherwise there is no practical utility in the study. It is essential, then, for us to consider upon what principles we ought to shape our conduct in th.e various circum- stances of life, since, as we have shown, our separate actions deter- mine the character which our ' habits ' or moral tendencies per- manently assume. The principle of That we should act under all circumstances ' in Ei|ht'''Ee^on'*is accordance with Right Reason'' is a common too vague and gene axiom, and may be assumed as true. But what '^*'' exactly ' Right Reason ' is, and in what relation it 3k, IL 2.3 . Translation. 77 ■stands to other forms of human excellence, is a subject which we must leave for discussion later on. • Since, therefore, our present Inquiry does not belong to the pm-ely speculative "branch of Philosopliy (whicli has for its end the simple contemplation of truth, being occupied with that class of existences which are objects of knowledge, and ■not ■vrith matters of action), but falls rather under the practical division of Philosophy, which has for its end the production of positive good (J.c. the purpose of our investigation is not merely to know what the nature of vii-tue is but to enable us ourselves to become virtuous : — otherwise, had our aim not been practical, there would have been no need for earnestness on our part, if we were not thereby achieving the aim of life,) .... since, I say, the end of our Inquiry is action and conduct, let us examine what are the conditions of moral action, seeing that moral action determines, as has been shown, the character of the ' habits ' formed thereby, whether they be good or whether they be e^vil, and it is upon the character of these habits that our theory of life depends. Now to take as our definition of ■virtuous actions ' such as are found to con- form to Right Reason,' and of evil actions ' such as are not conformable to Right Reason ' — that is true enough, but gives us no sufficient indication where- by to distinguish good from e^vdl. To say that ' Right action is in accordance with Right Reason ' is too vague and general : a definition of such u, kind is not sufBoient to indicate the character of a thing of which we are ignorant. If when we ask for a definition of ' man,' the definition ' animal ' is given, that is not sufficient to explain to us the whole meaning involved therein. This wider \iew may therefore be dismissed for the present. "We shall have to deal ■with it by ajid by, and to define what ' Right Reason ' is, and what is its relation to the other virtues. {h) 'right' cannot always be DISTmGUISHED FROM ' WRONG ' BY A HARD AND FAST LINE. Thus much, however, may at the outset be premised — that a rule to be applicable to real life must be delineated inoutline, rather than drawn out with the precision ^^ ml f of a scientific formula. As was explained at the duct must allow opening of this work, the explanations to be de- !?'' *®, ""^pi'"*- 1,/. <~i- ,1 -, ■ , *'°" of circum- manded from a Science must be relative to the stances, and must nature of the subject-matter. Questions of prac- ¥ sufficiently eias- ,. , , , 1 •., ,. „ ,.,., ^ , tic to allo-w ireedom tical conduct and considerations or utility present to the moral sense neither fixity nor uniformity, any more than do of the agent. the conditions of health. Such being the com- plexity of the main problem, there is even less exactness admis- sible in the treatment of specific details. Particular circumstances .do not completely fall under any art or under any set of rules. At the moment of action, in view of special complications, men must determine_/w themselves what tends to their true goal, in the same way as the physician judges for himself of the special symp- toms of his patients, or as the helmsman acts in a storm. Still though the difficulties of our subject are so embarrassing, we must endeavour to render help towards their solution. 78 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. II. 2. Thus much, however, may at the outset be premised — that our whole theory of duties, I mean the definition of what actions are right and what are wrong, must be framed not with the exactness of a scientific formula, but as it were in general outline. As we stated at the commencement of this Treatise, it is proper to require only such definitions of a subject as may be consistent with the con- ditions of that subject. Now actions, and the interests involved in action, are not uniform nor invariable, any more than are the momentary conditions of health. In regard to health, at one time one thing is beneficial, at another time the entire reverse, the conditions changing with the alternations of bodily health and with the vicissitudes of cii-cumstance. The case is precisely similar in regard to moral action. A line of conduct which at one time has been pernicious, at another time has brought great benefit often to the same individual But if a theory of the general truths of morality be thus incapable of being drawn out with the precision of a scientific definition, even more treacherous must a theory of detaUs be : with even less certainty than the imiversal are we able to understand particulars. The determination of particulars falls under no kind of art, nor under any defined mode of treatment, nor under any fijced set of rules. For this reason it is the duty of those who have to meet any difSculty to decide for themselves on each occasion upon the circumstances before them, and from the consideration thereof to seek for a principle to regfulate their conduct at such a crisis. Men will know whether their conduct be right or wrong if they survey the whole circumstances in this spuit. Such is the course which the physician and the helmsman take, judging of the course which is most consistent with their art from the nature of each crisis as it arises. StUl, though the subject before us is thus complicated, we must endeavour to contribute assistance to the elucidation of the truth which underlies it. (c) DISTINGUISHING FEATDBES WHEKKBT RIGHT AND WRONG MAY BE RECOGNIZED, IN THE ACTUAL CONDUCT OF MEN. The point, then, to be chiefly noted is that the attributes of morality are of a nature liable to be marred by r^cSLwS extravagance or defect, by want or superfluity;- failure are defect to employ, as WB must do, material analogies to virtTe™''*^''""^ °^ illustrate immaterial truths. We see this prin- ciple to be literally true in the case of health and strength. Strength is undermined if exercise be taken either too lavishly or too sparingly ; and in the same way, health is ruined if food or drink be either immoderate or insuflScient. On the other hand, if the amount of food or exercise taken be suitable to the individual, his health is promoted and strengthened and preserved. The same analogy holds good in regard to self-restraint and courage and the virtues generally. The man who flees before every danger, and shows fear at every alarm, and bears up agaihst not evfen the slightest evil, that man becomes a coward. On the other hand, the man whom no danger will daunt, but who goes to face all odds, becomes reckless. Similarly, when a man drains the full measure of every indulgence, and exercises no kind of self-restraint, he is a sensual man ; and, conversely, the man who shuns every form of enjoyment, as country boors do, he is a man devoid, as it Bk. II. 2.] Translation. 79 were, of the feelings of humanity. In other words, the virtues of temperance and of courage are lost by those qualities existing in superfluity or in defect, whereas they are foster*! and secured by a true fitness and equable moderation. The point, then, to be chiefly noted is, that ' actions conformable to virtue ' are of a nature to be marred by superfluity or want, just as we see is the case in regard to strength and health — to employ, as we must, illustrations from what is palpable to explain immaterial truths. Exercise which is excessive utterly ruins the strength of the body, as also does exercise which falls short of what is moderate and right. In precisely the same way the matter stands in regard to meat and drink : what is beyond or below what is fitting banishes health away, whereas moderation therein produces, strengthens, and presei-ves health. So also is it, in fact, in regard to temperance and courage, and other virtues. The man who flees before everything and is afraid at every alarm, and never holds his ground in face of panic, that man grows to be a coward. On the other hand, a man who is absolutely afraid of nothing, but goes to meet all dangers, he is a repHess man. Midway between these extremes is the man who has the virtue of bravery. In the same way temperance is marred by excess or defect : the man, for instance, who drains the full measure of every enjoyment and abstains from not a single one, he is a sensual man ; while, conversely, the man who shuns every pleasure, as country boors do, is devoid, as it were, of the feelings of humanity. Between these two extremes is the temperate man, temperance, like courage, being preserved by an equable moderation and a due fitness between desires and their object. iii. — Qualities exhibited by actions proceeding from a virtuous habit. (a) THE BAS^ WITH WHICH THE ACTION IS PERFORMED. But not only does each separate state of growth, of development and of decay in our moral life depend upon a repetition of acts akin to itself; not only is every phase under the influence of its original cause; tinuity in the moral but even after our habits have been formed, the •j^«= ^\^?^t p™: , ... T , ., ,. ., , ,, „ duces the habit and soul Will display its activity by the perform- the habit repro- ance of the self-same acts as those out of which 1 associate them with wrong. That is the only sound system of educa- 'the right ideas. tion. (2.) Again, since the virtues are exhibited in the various modes of feeling and action, and every feeling and every action is attended with pleasure and pain, the ^' . ^j^asure and inference is that the sphere of the virtues is the raWe from'°^con- sphere also of pleasure and pain. sciousness, must be ^ virtuous or vicious. (3.) A further indication of this truth is given in the fact that it is by means of pain that punishments are » p • • inflicted. Punishments are after their kind, as 'moral Ved^i- ' modes of moral cure ; ' and cures are naturally '^^■' brought about by means of things contrary to those which produced the disease. (4.) Moreover, as we have already shown, every attitude or condition of the sensitive soul bears a character which reflects and reproduces the influences by 4. influence of which it is naturally rendered better or worse, fn^the Tormati ''''S But the influences by which men's characters are character. rendered evil, are pleasure and pain: — in con- sequence, that is, of pursuing or avoiding the one or the other improperly or at unreasonable times or in an illegal manner, or violating other conditions deflned by Right Eeason. In view of the tyranny of pleasure and pain, there are some who positively define the virtues as ' modes of impassivity and of freedom from emotion ; ' inadequately, however, as such a defini- tion needs qualification to limit the impassivity to particular times and circumstances, with other necessary reservations. It is assumed, therefore, that virtue is that disposition towards pleasure and pain which we have described above, and which is qualified to produce the best results from them : and that vice is the exact reverse. 1. In fact the special sphere in which moral virtue is displayed is that of pleasure and pain. The evil that we do, has pleasure for its motive ; and when we gTirJTilr from noble deeds, that is owing to the pain they cost. Hence the importance of a training of the feelings. We ought, as Plato says, 82 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. II. 2. to regard it as a matter of grave concern that the habits we form shovild be vir- tuous habits, and that the actions we do should be virtuous actions, from our child- hood upwards, and that we should, even while children, be brought up to habits of such a character as would give us strength to find pleasure in what is right, and to feel pain where it is fitting for us to grieve. That is the only sound and rational system of education. 2. Again, since the virtues are either actions or feelings ; and whatsoever a man does or feels, he has pleasure when those actions and feelings are agreeab^' to his own wish, or else has pain when his actions and feelings are under con- straint from another — it is evident that all moral virtue is concerned with pleasure or pain. 3. This truth is further evident from the punishments which are inflicted in States. Lawgivers cause trouble to fall upon such as taie pleasure in vicious courses, and thus try to induce them to hate what is evil, and to find their pleasure rather in a virtuous life. Thus it is, by the moral discipline which they inculcate, that lawgivers i instil into men's minds the pleasure which is consequent upon virtue. Legal punishments thus fill a position analogous to medical remedies towards those who are diseased in their social relations. Just as the diseases aie opposed to the remedies which cure them (if, for instance, we see a physioimi •, employing a cold method of cure, we know at once that the disease has bem brought on by heat), so also we know from the painful nature of punishments that the vices which those punishments are designed to cure, arise from pleasure. 4. Moreover, as has been explained, every formed state of soul bears a character, in sympathy with the objects or circumstances through which it is engendered, and by which it is made better or worse ; — in fact it is only under the influenoa of such circumstances that a mental state consists at all. But it is under the influence of pleasure and pain that vicious states of mind are formed — ^through men pursuing pleasure in an improper manner or at an improper time, or through their avoiding pain at an improper time or in an improper manner, or in an improper place, or through violating other conditions which make the pursuit of pleasure and the avoidance of pain immoral. The case which virtue presents is very similar. A virtuous state is constituted by our pursuing pleasure and pain in a fitting manner and at fitting times. From these considerations it is clear that our mental states exhibit a character of virtue or of vice according to their attitude to pleasure and pain, and that it is under these influences that such states are formed. It is from this point of view that certain philosophers define the virtues as ' modes of impassivity ' or ' states of repose,' taking pleasure as the standpoiot for their definition : — incorrectly, however, in that they fonn their definition.' without necessary qualification, i.e. without adding to their idea of moral calm or repose the limitations ' as is right ' and ' when it is right,' and similar conditions. It may therefore be assumed that virtue is ' a state of mind which is virtuously disposed in relation to pleasure and pain ' (according to the qualification which we have just di-awn), and in those relations is ' capable of effecting the very best results.' Vice, on the other hand, is the exact opposite. (3) PROOFS FROM THE NATURE OF MAN. There are still other considerations from which this view may be made clear to us. There are three ideas which lead to our choice of an object, and three which tend to our aversion of an object, a"To" " motiv? On the one hand are ' the beautiful,' ' the expe- )5ut, indirectly, also dient,' and ' the pleasurable ; ' on the other hand, Bk. II. 2.] Translation. 83 and opposed to these, are 'the ugly,' < the influences our every hurtful,' and 'the painful.' In all these rela~ '^^°^'^^- tions, the good man is sure to be right, and the bad man is sure to be wrong, most of all where pleasure is involved. But pleasure is shared by all organized beings, and follows in the train of whatever objects fall under our choice, since even the beautiful and the expedient are thought to be also pleasur- able. It is, moreover, an element ingrained in all of us from childhood, and is proportionately difficult. to rub out, being, as it were, part of the very complexion of our life. Indeed, we all, though not all in an equal degree, estimate our duties in the balances of pleasure and pain, and regulate our conduct accordingly. For these reasons, then, our chief concern must necessarily be with the regulation of these emotions. It has no slight bearing upon our conduct, whether the pleasures and pains we feel are right or wrong. Moreover, it is even more difficult to fight against pleasure than against passion, as Heraclitus says ; and the special sphere both of art and of virtue is ever that which is most difficult to accomplish, excellence being, in such a case, more excellent still. Herein is a new reason why the problem concerning both virtue and statesmanship should resolve itself into one concerning pleasure and pain. The man who puts pleasure and pain to their true use, will be good, and the man who abuses the one or the other, will be a bad man. But we may gain a better understanding of the arguments here adduced from the following considerations. Since there are three feelings which may become motives in determining our choice, and three corresponding opposites which may be motives for our avoidance of a thing — those of the beautiful, the expedient, and the pleasurable opposed to those of the ugly, the injurious and the painful, the good man applies himself to every one of these considerations in a spirit of fairness, pursuing as he does what is really best, and avoiding what it were injurious to pursue ; whereas the bad man falls into error in his choice of considerations, especially in reference to what is pleasurable. Now pleasure is not only shared in by all organised beings, but is aJso a con- comitant element in all the ' objects of choice ' enumerated above. Whatever objects we mate our choice, in all of them we experience pleasure. What is beautiful or expedient is also in its nature pleasm'able ; and it is on this account that the wicked are deluded, by considering that whatever is pleasurable must be beautiful and expedient, and fancying that because pleasure is consequent upon whatever is beautiful and expedient, that therefore the terms are mutually convertible. Such, however, is not the fact, since many of those things which are pleasurable are disgraceful and ruinous. Hence it is evident that aU human action is found displayed in the field of pleasure and pain. Moreover, this feeling is part of our nature from childhood, and grows with our growth, being, as it were, ingrained in the very tissue of our lives. HeaBure G 2 84 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. II. 3. is in truth the standard by which we distinguish right and wrong: in conduct — according as they entail, the one pleasure and the other pain ; and thus it is that we regulate the activities of our own lives, if not in the same degree yet all of us more or less. Therefore it is that o.ur whole business is concerned with pleasure and pain. It is of no slight assistance to a man when he is inquiring what he ought to do, if he know what it is to have the feelings of pleasure and pain under virtuous control ; since it is a most important element in conduct that we should fed pleasure or pain in a right way. It is from the emotions which men exhibit of joy or sorrow that we have knowledge of their character, whether it be vii-tuous or immoral. Again, both virtue and art are displayed in achievements where it is not easy to succeed. In order to compass objects which are easy there is no need of a long- sustained habit, nor of a special course of training. In proportion therefore as things are more difficult, will they require the greater skiU. and the greater virtue, since it is more meritorious to achieve successfully what is specially difficult than it is to surmount what is easy. Virtue will therefore assume its highest form in what is most difficult, and circumstances of difficulty form its most characteristic sphere. But, as Heraolitus says, it is more dif5cnlt to fight against pleasure than even against passion. Herein, then, is a new reason why the whole business of our inquiry will lie with pleasure and pain, as well in view of private as of public morality. The man who turns pleasui-e and pain to a noble use is a good man ; while the man who abuses these emotions is a bad m.an. (c) SUMMARY OF THE CONDITIONS OF A VIRTOOUS HABIT. These arguments will be sufficient to prove : 1. The field in which virtue is displayed is pleasure and pain. 2. Virtue is strengthened when the acts from which it origi- nates are continued, and, contrariwise, is destroj'ed when those acts cease, or are changed. 3. Virtue continues to manifest itself under conditions like those by which it was formed. It has now been shown that : 1. The sphere of moral virtue is fonned by pleasure and pain. 2. Moral virtue is strengthened or destroyed under the conditions out of which it is fonned, according as our activities are displayed therein in one mode or an- other. 3. Moral virtue continues to manifest itself under conditions like those by which it was formed. v.— Morality of the Act distinguished from the Morality of the Agent. (a) STATEMENT OF OBJECTIONS TO THE THEORV OF HABIT. But perhaps a critic may raise a difficulty as to the precise sense in which we hold the view that, ' by per- Z'ilsLfd'epends forming right actions men grow to be righteous, upon the virtuous and by performing acts of self-restraint men wlot Sn! g>-°^ to be temperate.' _ He might object that, « if deiitiy of habit, as men perform acts of justice or of temperance, Bk. II. 3.] Translation. 85 they must by that very fact be already just and in the analogy of temperate, in the same way as they would be *'^®^'"''^-' scholars and musicians, if they showed the knowledge of the scholar, or the skill of the musician.' But here a critao may raise a difficulty. ' Wiat is the meaning,' he may ask, ' of saying that it is necessary for a man, who desires to become just, to do just actions, or temperate actions, if his desire is to be temperate. Those who per- form just acts are in every sense just men, and those who perform temperate acts are temperate men, precisely as those who execute musical or scholarly compo- sitions are musicians and scholars.' {b) REPLY TO THE ABOVE OBJECTIONS. 1 . But does this objection hold good even in the case of the arts ? It is surely possible for a man to show gram- matical knowledge by accident or the suggestion J;„^"even i^ the of others. A man will not be a scholar unless he ai-ts,' that the per- not only shows grammatical knowledge, but does y^"* erfect^hab^^^ so for scholarly reasons — in virtue, that is, of the scholarship which he possesses in himself and in his own right. 2. Moreover, the case is not parallel between the arts and the virtues. The results eifected by the arts have an excellence of their own independently of the 2. If it were true, artist: it is sufficient for them to bear the *tt hofiToorln impress of certain qualities. On the other hand, art the dispositions the results attained in the way of the virtues, are i^mtteriti*''* but not effected, for example, with justice and tern- they are of the veiy perance, by bearing certain characteristics of essence of nght ,.'•', ° , . , and wrong. their own, unless at the same time the agent who produces them himself possesses certain qualities. There are, in fact, three conditions for a perfect moral act. The agent must perform the act (1) consciously, (2) from deliberate preference (his choice being Three tests of the for a particular object for its own sake), and (3) ^°^f ^^ "* ^^^^ with firm and settled purpose. Now for the attainment of the various arts, these conditions (save the simple possession of knowledge) are not accounted necessary requisites in the artist. For the attainment of the virtues, on the contrary, knowledge is of slight or of no avail ; whereas it is of great, nay, of supreme importance, that the agent should himself be possessed of those moral qualities which ensue from the constant practice of justice and of temperance. In fact, moral acts can only be ranked as just or temperate when they are of such a nature as the just and temperate man would perform. 86 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. II. 3. But the just and temperate man is what he is, not by the mere performance of such and such actions, but by showinof the spirit and acting after the manner of one whose character is just and temperate. 1. In reply, I maintain that there is manifestly a difference between perform, ing just actions and being oneself just, and this difference appUes equally to the arts. It is conceivable for a man to execute a grammatical composition from chance, or at the suggestion of another, and yet not be himself a scholai-. A man wiU not be a scholar unless he not only executes scholarly work, but does so for scholarly reasons— foUowing, that is, consistently the standard of scholarship which he possesses within himself. By the same analogy it is quite conceivable for a man to perform acts of justice without being himself a just man. 2. Nay, rather, the difference upon these points is greater in the case of virtue than in that of the arts. In the ai-ts ' the good ' consists in the exercise of the artistic faculty. Consequently, if a man execute musical compositions with a knowledge of the musical art, there is nothing to prevent our calling him a mu- sician. He is none the less a musician, though the compositions he performs are not done with deliberate preference of his own, but under the constraint of an- other. But in the case of virtue the reverse is true ; a man will not be just though he perform just actions, unless, in addition to other conditions, he perform the actions with a positive wish of his own, and impelled to act by his own choice, without any constraint placed upon him. In fact, to be moral a man must satisfy the following conditions. In doing just actions he must, in the first place, Immv what he is doing ; secondly, he mustact from his own free choice ; and thirdly, his moral attitude in regard to such actions must be firm and unwavering. [The reasons for this last condition are that, ac- cording to our meaning of the word, a man wiU not be just, though he knows what justice is, and willingly acts up to his knowledge if he fancies that there axe times exempt from the obligations of justice.] But these conditions are not required in order to acquire the various aits, and to become artists in virtue thereof — excepting the one condition of knowledge. Devoid of knowledge, how could a man possibly be an artist at aJl ? But as for the other conditions, though a man practise his art without any deliberate pre- ference, or without having a firm, unfaltering attitude in regard to the handling of his art, he is not on that account hindered from being an artist. On the othel hand, in regard to moral virtue, the mere knowledge of what it is fitting for a man to know of his duty, serves little or no good purpose ; whereas the other qualifications are of great and even supreme importance — in view, that is, of grow- ing to be oneself good and virtuous. It is quite conceivable for a man to be a good and virtuous man, though he know not how to speak of virtue with any degree of precision ; but it is impossible for him to be good unless he have a deliberate preference for such and such a course, and an unwavering attitude in regard to virtue — and these are moral conditions which result from the repeated exercise of the faculties in a particular direction, as has been explained. Actions are, therefore, only just and temperate when they bear a character like that which the just and temperate man would show therein ; and a man is just and temperate not necessarily from doing such and such actions, but from doing them in the spirit which the just and temperate show. (c) CONCLUSION: FOR AN ACT TO BE MORAL THE AGENT MUST BE MORAL; AND THE AGENT IS MORAL BY CONSTANT PRACTICE. It is, therefore, rightly affirmed that ■ a man becomes just by performing just acts, and temperate by performing acta of self- Bk. II. 4. J Translation. 87 restraint ; whereas, by refraining from such acts a man would not even have a chance of becoming good.' The generality of men, however, instead *of ^''^ conclusion is practising the virtues, take shelter in arguing ma\es ^perfecH about them, and fancy that they are philosophers and that knowledge and that their speculations will make them good, canied into effect!^ Such conduct is just as foolish as that of in- valids who hearken zealously to their physicians, but carry out none of their directions. As these foolish patients will never attain to sound health by such a method of treatment, so neither will these doctrinaires attain to a virtuous state of soul by such a method of philosophising. The view, therefore, which I have maintained is the right one — that ' a man grows to be just by performing just acts, and temperate by performing acts of self-restraiat ; whereas a man who does not practise virtuous acts will never even have a chance of becoming good.' The generality of men, however, instead of practising the virtues, take refuge in philosophy and fine theories, and fancy that they are philosophers and virtuous men, simply on the ground that they know how to talk with subtle discrimina- tion upon the theory of virtue. Such conduct is much like that of invalids who hearken zealously to their physicians, yet carry out none of their directions. As these foolish patients will never attain to sound health by such a method of treat- ment, so neither will these moral dreamers make their souls more noble and vir- tuous by studying the philosophy of life in such a spirit of trifling. XL— FOEMAL DEFINITION OF VIRTUE. i. — What is the generic character of Virtue ? Our nest enquiry will be to settle what is the generic character of virtue. l.^JNUMEEATION OP THE POWERS OF THE SOUL. Now;^as there are three forces operating in the soul — emotions, capacities and habits — virtue must be one or other of them. "^^'f' °* ^''^ ^'"* _ moral powers. 1. I mean by ' emotions ' such feelings as desire, anger, fear, confidence, envy, joy, affection, hatred, longing, emulation, pity, — in fact, all those states of consciousness which are attended by pleasure and pain. 2. I mean by ' capacities ' those dispositions or tendencies from which such and such feelings may be evoked, and in virtue of which we are said to be ' capable ' of those feelings, capable, that is, of feeling anger, pity, or pain. 3. I mean by ' habits ' those dispositions in accordance with 88 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. II. 4. which we hold a certain attitude, whether right or wrong, towards particular emotions; for example, in regard to the feeling of anger, if the attitude of our minds he towards either violence or apathy, then our ' hahit ' is an improper one, whereas, if our attitude be one of due moderation, then our ' habit ' is a virtuous habit. The case is analogous with the other virtues. We win now go on to consider what is the generic character of virtue. Now there are three forces operating in the soul — emotions, capacities, and habits. 1. ' Emotions ' are such feelings as desire, anger, fear, confidence, envy, joy, affection, hatred, longing, emulation, pity — in fact all such states of consciousness as are attended with pleasure or pain. 2. ' Capacities ' are aptitudes and tendencies of soul for such and such and such emotions, and in virtue of which we are said to be capable of experiencing those emotions, eg., of being roused to anger or of feeling pain and pity. 3. ' Habits ' are the ■modes in which we are affected by the emotions, and in accordance with which our ' frame of mind ' is right or wrong. For example, in feeling anger or passion, if, on the one hand, our attitude be violent and un- controllable, or, on the other hand, apathetic and easy, our ' ha,bit ' or state of mind is a wrong one, whereas, if our attitude be one of due moderation, then our habit is a virtuous habit. The same analogy applies to other mental states. 2. VIETUE SHOWN TO BE 'A HABIT.' (a) There are the following reasons to prove that neither virtues nor vices are mere ' emotions ' : — 1. Considerations (1.) We are not Said to be either good or evil is° somTtMnr^ore ^^P^^ °^ *^^ S™"^'^ "^ o""" emotions, as we are than feeling. On the grouud of our virtues and vices. (2.) We are neither praised nor blamed on the score of our emotions as we are on the score of our virtues and vices : i.e.., a man is not praised simply because he has emotions of fear or of anger, nor is a man blamed simply on the ground of his anger, but only when anger is felt under unjustifiable cir- cumstances. (3.) We are moved to anger or to fear without a deliberate act of the will. But the virtues are ' forms of volition ' — or, at any rate, they are not devoid of some action of the will. (4.) Besides, in common language, we are said to be ' stirred ' or * roused ' in regard to our feelings, whereas in regard to the virtues j and vices we are said to be ' disposed'' in such and such a way. I {h) The above reasons show also that neither are the virtues simple ' capacities ; ' i.e., 2. Considerations (1.) We are not said to be either good or bad to show that virtue „■ ,„i„ ^ .„ -j. i. . . ° . is something more smipJy Irom a Capacity to receive impressions, than capacity. (2.) We are neither praised nor blamed for our capacities. J3k. II. 5.] Translation. 89 (3.) We are capable of receiving impressions by the very con- stitution of our nature, but we do not become, merely by nature, either good or bad. • (c) Seeing then that the virtues are neither ' emotions ' nor ' capacities,' it follows that they must be ' habits ' — i.e. permanent tendencies of our moral nature. To which of these three forces then, does virtue belong' 1 Is it an ' emotion,' a 'capacity,' or a ' habit ' ? 1. Certainly neither virtue nor vice is a mere emotion ; because — (1.) In respect of our virtue we are called virtuous, and in respect of our vice, vicious, but neither one nor the other in respect of our emotions. No man is either good or bad simply from having, for instance, the feeling of anger. Neither virtue nor vice, therefore, will be an emotion. (2.) In respect of our emotions we are neither praised nor blamed as we are in respect of our virtues or vices. (3.) We feel anger or fear without any distinct determination of the will (and so it is with all the other feelings we experience), but in the case of virtue and of vice there is the conscious assent of the will. Yirtue and vice are therefore not mere emotions. (1.) Again, in. regard to the emotions, we are not said to have such and such a disposition, but to be ' moved ' or ' stirred ' in respect thereto. But in respect of virtue, and similarly in respect to vice, we are said to be ' disposed ' in a certain way. Hence virtues and vices are not emotions. 2. The same reasons prove also that they are' not ' capacities : ' (1.) We are not caUed good or bad simply from having the capacity for being angered. (2.) Nor are we praised or blamed for such a capacity. (3.) We are not capable of being angered simply by having formed a resolution to be so, as is the case with moral virtue (the moral decision producing the moral state), but our capacity for emotion depends upon the natural constitution which is bom with us. As has been shown in the previous arguments we do not become by nature either good or bad. 3. If then the virtues are neither emotions nor capacities, the only alternative is that they must belong to the class of ' habits,' or tendencies fixed by practice of their acts. It has thus been proved that in its generic nature virtue is a ' habit.' ii. — ^What are the distinguisMng charaoteristies of Virtue ? It has now been explained what virtue is in its ' material ' nature. But we must not be content with this general explanation of it as ' a habit ' or ' perma- What 'form ' or nent tendency : ' we must further explain what Tef L "St rf is its ' formal ' nature or specific character. . virtue assume » 1. WHAT IS IMPLIED BY THE 'EXCELLENCE' OF A THING? Now it may be assumed that the ' excellence ' of a thing is that quality which finishes off, as with a touch of art, the object to which it attaches, and renders the result as a whole perfect. The 90 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. II. o. excellence of the eye, for instance, makes the eye good and its operation effectual: it is through the excellence Gfeneral conception of the eye that we scc well. In the same way "L^^S^: the excellence of the horse makes the horse Strong, and able to run and to bear its rider and to stand the shock of the enemy. If this definition] be, as it is, of universal application, the ' excellence ' of man will be a habit or fixed state of mind in virtue whereof he proves himself to be a goc^d man, and is enabled to finish off, with a perfect touch, his work as man. But we must not merely describe virtue as ' a habit ; ' we must add the further qualification what land, of |habit it is, i.e. that it is a virtnmis habit, while vice is a vicious habit. Now thus much may be at once assumed respecting virtue — ^that like all excellence, it adorns the object which possesses it, and causes it to be in a rigMi state, and brings the work which is effected by means thereof to an exceUefii effect. The exceUenoe of the eye, for instance, perfects the eye and makes it a good eye and renders its function, i.e. seeing, effectual : it is through the excellence of the eye that we see well. Similarly also the excellence of the horse distinguishes the horse itself and makes it a good horse and renders its operation effectual : it is through such excellence that it is able to bear its rider easily, and to gallop, and to stand the shock of the foe. Since this principle is of universal application, the excellence proper to man will show the same characteristics, and will be ' a habit of mind in virtue whereof a man proves himself a good man, and is enabled to accomplish the proper work of his life successfully and nobly.' 2. THE IDEA OF ' EXCELLEKCE ' ILLUSTRATED BY COMPARISON WITH THE IDEA OF A 'MEAN' OR ' IDEAL.' I have already^explained how this excellence may be attained ; but our view of it will be rendered yet clearer ih The mathematical the following light — by examining, that is, what proSio'^, and of ^^i" distinguishing natiu-e of excellence precisely is. 'the mean' in- Take the analogy of mathematical proportion : datf "further'^ the i° ^^^ quantity whether continuous or discrete, we idea of excellence, may take a part that is ' greater ' or * less ' or * equal ' — either absolutely in regard to the thing itself or relatively in regard to ourselves (the equal being that which is midway between excess and defect). By the ' absolute mean ' I understand a point equally distant from two extremes, a point which is one and the same for all persons. By the ' relative mean ' I understand'one which is neither in excess nor defect in regard to a particular purpose, or point of view of our own. The ' relative mean ' is then not a quantity which is one and the same for all. Suppose, for example, that ten be too much and two be insufficient, we take six as ' the absolute mean : ' it exceeds and is exceeded by the same number, and that is the mean according to Bk. II. 5.] Translation. 91 arithmetical proportion. But the ' relative mean ' must be regarded in a different light to this. Looking to the ' relative mean,' if ten pounds be too much for a man to eat and two pounds be too little, the trainer will not necessarily prescribe six pounds. Six pounds might be either too much or too little for the man who would have to take it : it would be too little for a Milo, and too much for a man who was just beginning gymnastic training. Similarly also in the case of running and wrestling. In this spirit every wise teacher avoids excess and defect, and adopts by preference ' a mean ' — not the mean that is absolute, but one that is proper and relative to ourselves and adapted to our own needs. How such a state can be brought about, was explained a few pages back. We showed that th^ man who was resolutely determined to live in the practice of virtue ever aimed at ' a mean state ' in regard to those impulses which lead to the forming of emotions, and further habituated himself to such a line of moderation. < This principle of moderation will be made yet more clear by the considerations which I will now proceed to give, from the careful examination, that is, of the distinctive and special characteristics of virtue or excellence as such. Let us, then, regard the matter in the following aspect. In everything which is continuous, for instance a line, a superficies, a, body, a speech, a period of time — in fact, in everything which is capable of being divided into parts, one may take a part which is greater or less or equal. In the case, for example, of extended space : if ten feet be too much and two feet too little, the ' equal ' wiU be that which contains six feet, and that is called also ' the mean,' because it exceeds two feet in the same proportion as it is exceeded by ten feet. The case is similar also in regard to ' discrete ' quantity. If 20 be too much and 10 too little, 15 wUl be a fair equality, because 15 exceeds 10 the less in the same proportion as it falls short of 20 the greater. An ' equal ' of this kind is called ' a mean,' and an arrangement of ratios of this kind is arithmetical proportion. In the case of discrete quantity it is not invariably necessary to find the arith- metical proportion (since we cannot caixy on our division to infinity) ; but in the case of continuous quantity we may do so (since that is capable of being divided into infinite parts). We do not, therefore, always determine this mean in the same manner. At one time we judge of it by the standard of the thing itself, at another time by a standaord that is relative to ourselves. In respect of the thing itself the mean between 10 and 2 is 6, 6 exceeding and being exceeded to the same extent. But a mean is relative to ourselves when the middle and the excess and the defect is taken from our own point of view. For instance, if it be too much for anyone to eat 10 pounds, and 2 pounds be too little for him, it does not follow that 6 pounds is the quantity which keeps the mean and is suitable to our constitution : it is possible that either more or less may be needed to satisfy. In respect there- fore of the thing itself, 6 pounds are the ' mean,' between 10 and 2, and what is equal ; but in reference to our own needs perhaps 7, perhaps 5, pounds, that is to say, whatever number of pounds is suitable to the constitution. A dinner of 6 pounds will be too little for a Milo, as being in a thorough state of training, and his trainer will provide him with u more ample allowance; whereas such a quantity would be excessive for a man who is just commencing systematic training. The same principle applies to running and wrestling : we judge of the ' mean' from the stand-point of those who are being trained for competition. Indeed, anyone who presides over the regulation of any profession seeks the mean, avoiding the excess or defect ; but the mean which he pursues is one relative to ourselves and to our own circumstances, and not the mean which is absolute. 92 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle- [Bk. II. 5. 3. APPLICATION OF THE CONCEPTION OP 'THE MEAN' TO THE MORAL LIFE. Seeing, then, that it is the genius of science to give an exact finish to its special functions, having regard to Comparison of vir- -j-g ^^^ i^g^i and referring to the standard of that tue to an art where ., , ,, ., i . j • xi. j. l- l the symmetry of all ideal all its products ; and seeing that artists are the parts produces yf(y[± to say of their works when finished off that a pe ec eau y. .^ .^ impossible to take away a line or to add a sino-le touch, under the helief that a line wanting or a stroke too ,, much spoil the beauty of a work, whereas a chastened moderation preserves it; seeing further, that skilled workmen make this ' finish of art ' as we call it, the ideal at which they ajm in working; and seeing, lastly, that virtue like nature is a thing far more exact and important than any art : — for all these reasons, clearly,. ' virtue will likewise aim at producing a perfect finish and realizing the noblest ideal. The virtue of which I am now speaking is moral, not intellectual virtue, the moral nature being alone concerned Truth and science ■^\ ' to things indiflfe- uessT^uvy, Or, m outward action, adultery, theit, "^^rt in ti^^ i™ mm'der— these things and such as these are re- herently wrong. probated from the fact of their being wicked, not in their states of excess or defect, but in them- selves and inherently. In relation to such sins as these, it is Bk. II. 6.] Translation. 95 never possible to be right, but one would certainly commit a crime on everj_oc.QasiQn ollhgir, indulgence. • (i) NoiL_doe8-fllS- righ tn esa^-jor, jgronggess of such an act as ad ultery depend _upon_ttLe_cgmmission of tlie~act witli_a^ particu lar person or in a particular^ man- No consideration of ner, but witEouT limitation or exception., to com- °i.'^°^™^*^."i'^,^ ,-j _ ' ,1 , • , ., y_^— affects the sinful- mit .gjiysucn act as that is to commit a sm. ness of murder. (c) It is equally futile to claim ' a mean ' or * an excess ' or ' a defect-'- -as -qnalii^ing. ia|jiaEca,3rl cowardice, of intemperance. On such a supposition there would '^^ '"■^ °* *iie ,, n .j.3j?j.> :\ L mean cannot either be ' a mean oi excess and delect and ' an excess be applied to things of excess' and ' a defect of defect.' But just as ^'ii<='i are them- there is neither exces s nor defect possibl g_ij. self- from a mean? '°°'* res traint or cour age, seeing that ' the mean state ' is in some sense an ideal limit or extreme ; so neither in these other cases is there ' a - .mean' nor an excess nor a defect.Jbut in wTiataofiver wayjjiAy -may Tig-committed,^ uch acts are absolutely sinful. In a word, there is no mean of excess and defect, nor excess and defect of a mean. 1, Still it is right for us to understand further that it is not every action nor every feeling that admits of this principle of ' the mean ' into which we have been making inquiry : the standard of ' fitness ' is not universally applicable. There are certain acts and certain emotions which, whether they are found in excess or in defect or in some kind of mean, are invariably sinful and evil — for example, in the emotions, shamelessness and envy, or in actions, adultery, theft, murder. All such things are not called evil from the fact of their going beyond a certain ' mean ' point therein, nor from falling below such a point ; but they are inher- ently evil in themselves. Under no circumstances whatever can the idea of ' fit- ness ' be applied to any form of such sins ; but under any and every form of their indulgence it is inevitable to commit a crime. In such cases one cannot deter- mine beforehand any limits within which such acts may be done, as may be done with the virtues generally. One cannot lay down rules for -housebreakers, deter- mining in what manner they may steal, upon what occasions, what things or from what persons ; but irrespective of all conditions, to do anything whatever of the kind is to commit a crime. In such cases as these, therefore, there is no ' mean ' nor ' excess ' nor ' defect ' any more than there are limits for the practice of justice or cowardice or sensuality. Some of these states are excesses, and others defects of virtue ; and it would be utterly absurd to seek for an ' excess of excess,' or for ' a defect of defect,' or ' a mean in excess and defect.' Just as there is neither excess nor defect, nor a mean of a mean (I am speaking of moral virtue,) but virtue is, so to speak, ' the extreme of the mean ; ' so neither can there be a mean or an excess or a defect in states of excess and defect, but iavariably, under whatever circumstances such acts are committed, they are sinful and wrong. In a word, there is no mean of excess and defect, nor excess and defect in a mean. 96 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. II. r. III.— CLASSIFICATION OF VIRTUES TO ILLUSTRATE THE LAW OF 'THE MEAN." But the princi^lesjof virtue must not simply be stated in this general way: we must show their adaptation to We may now pro- t]je special circumstances of life. In ethical aetw^themeau Speculation general _ propositions are somewhat' iu its various appii- impalpable: there is greater reality in specific' "4*1^.*°'^'°'^" truths which illustrate specific duties. As the whole range of action lies within particular circum- stances, our principles ought to be consistent when applied to them. "We will therefore take from our Catalogue of the virtues certain specimens of the special conditions of life, to show the application of our theory thereto. But we must not merely say in a general way that ' virtue is a mean state,' and that ' yice consists in extremes,' but we must further explain in detail what par- ticular virtue is a mean between what particular extremes. In discussions bear- ing upon conduct, while general propositions are more comprehensive, and are applicable to the larger number of instances, specific truthi are the more real and trustworthy, inasmuch as they fit on closely to actions for the very reason that actions always tate place under specific circumstances, and with the exigencies of specific circumstances true principles of course harmonize. We will therefore take such cases as we require from the Diagram which I have unfolded before you. As has been explained, virtue lies midway between an excess and defect in every single phase of the moral life (excepting only such as are inherently vicious ^e?' sr^. i.— Self-regarding Virtues. 1. VIRTUES DISPLAYED IN CIRCUMSTANCES OF PLEASURE AND ' PAIN. (ff) In regardto the leelin^s of fear and of con fidence, the proper attitude of mind is courage. Of the characters (a) Vurtues and which deviate from the true limits (a) the man IvoldanoTot p"in. '^^'^ errs from incapacity to feel fear, has no dis- tinctive name (as is the case with many other of our moral states), whereas (/3) if he go beyond the line through excess of confidence he is called reckless. If, on the other hand, a man outstrip the due limits of fear, and fall short of a proper confidence, then he is called a coward. (f)) In regardjto_plea^ures_and^ains (not all, however, and per- haps pains less than pleasures), the perfect at ti- (5) Virtues and tudeis temperance, and the excess sensuality. As vices shown m the « - ,,. -^ , J — ,_ -,-. _ ' pursuit of pleasure. lor lallmg Short m self-gratmcation, such cases hardly occur: hence the class have not met with a distinctive name. However, they may be called ' insensate.' Bk. II. 7.] Translation. 97 (1.) In reference to fear or confidence — these being emotions of tlie soul, the perfect frame of mind is Courage, while the extremes are cowardice as a defect, and recklessness as an excess. From the point of view of fear there is no special name for the excess, though there is from the point of view %f confidence. (There are indeed many such phases of mind which have no special name.) Moreover there is no special name for the excess of confidence, though there is a special idea — ^that of cowardice — drawn from the excess of fear. Hence, of the extremes the one derives its name from fear, the other from confidence. (2.) In reference to pleasures and pains, both the extremes and the mean states are for the most part without any distinctive name, especially in regard to pains. But in reference to such pleasures as are purely bodily there is a mean state, ' tem- perance,' and an excess, ' dissoluteness.' The defect has no special name, inas- much as there are few who entirely refrain themselves from every form of grati- fication : it may, however, be classed as ' insensateness.' 2. VIRTUES DISPLAYED IN MONEY-MATTERS. a. In regard Jojhe^ving and receiving of money, the true dis- po gition of min d is Hberality, the excess" prodi- galitijheiefectjstinginess. These extremes go "J^etionTofiS beyond the mark or fall short of it in inverse ratio to one another : the prodigal exceeds in giving, and falls short in receiving, while the stingy man exceeds in receiving, and fails in giving. [For the present we may be content with this simple enumeration, as we are only describing the virtues in out- line with a view to summarize them. By and by their definitions shall be settled with more scientific accuracy.] h. But there .are— other—disposition* of-mind -whieh—must be noted~.ia_jgference to money. Magnificence is a virtuous attitude (and this character of magni- *; In the disposi- ficence difiers, it must be observed, from liberality, ^raUh." ^^^'^^ in that the one is concerned with vast wealth, the latter with only moderate wealth). On the other hand, failure in ' one direction is seen in want of taste and~lJstentatiDn7~aiid in another direction in meanness ur~pettiness~(andnhese extremes again differ from the extremes of liberality : the point where they diverge shall be explained later on). (a) In reference to the feeling which we experience in giving or receiving money, the true disposition is liberality, while the perversions of the mean are prodigality as an excess, and niggardliness as a defect. Yet in certain conditions the reverse is true, that prodigality is a defect, and niggardliness an excess. In giving money, prodigality is an excess, and iUiberality a defect, whereas in re- ceiving money iUiberality is an excess, and prodigality a defect. [For the present we may be satisfied with this simple enumeration, as we are here only treating the subject in a cursory manner, and as it were in outline. By and by we shall have to describe these states with greater precision.] . (i) There is yet another form of the perfect state with corresponding extremes in reference to the giving and receiving of money ; and that is magnificence, difEer- ing from liberality in that it lavishes vast sums, whereas liberality has only small sums to lavish. The excess of this virtue is want of taste and vulgarity, and its defect meanness. These extremes again differ from the extremes of liberality : the points of difEerence shall be explained later on. 98 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. 11. 7. 3. VIBTDES DISPLAYED IN THE DESIRE FOR ESTEEM. a. In regard to Tinnmir atkI jisgrane , the virtii OHg-s t a fe i s Ti igTi- mmdedness^tlie excess being- ghat is called ^j ain- ter/'' ^^"^ "^*' g^o^y^' and the defect, Jittleness of soul. h. I just now explained the relation of liberality to magnificence to be that the former has a more circumscribed, sphere than the latter. There is a corresponding relation between high-mindedness which is concerned with great matt rs ^"^"'"^ honour, and another state which is concerned with ordinarj-- honour. It is of course possible to strive after honour rightly and becomingly, as well as in a way that is either extravagant or insufiicient. Now the man who is of excessive jmbition is called ambitions,, and the man who is wanting_ in ambiti£Ii,.-unambitious ; while the man who holds the true balance between the se extremes h as no speoifil name. Neither does language give name to the corres- ponding states of mind — save to that of the ambitious man, which is ambition. Hence it is that the two extreme characters dispute for the possession of the ground intervening between them. There are indeed times when we call the moderate man ambitious, and times when we call him unambitious. There are times when we praise the ambitious man, and times when we praise the unam- bitious man. The cause and ground of these variations of opinion shall be explained later on. We must now proceed to enumerate the remaining virtues, follow« ing the plan which has hitherto guided us. (a) In regard to the emotions involved in honour and dishonour, the perfect state is magnanimity, the excess ' vain-glory,' as it is called, and the defect, little- ness of soul. (J) Corresponding to the differences which we said existed in the dispositions' that relate to money, liberality and magnificence, the former being concerned with small sums, the latter with great sums, there is similarly in regard to honour a cer- tain disposition which differs from high-mindedness in being concerned with smaE interests, while high-mindedness is ooncemed with great interests. Now it is possible for a man to strive after honour as is fitting, or to a degree beyond what is right, or even less than is fitting. The man who is extravagant in his desires is an ambitions man, and his mental state ambitiousness. The man who lacks a proper ambition is an unambitious man (but his mental state has no dis- tinctive name). The perfect attitude in such matters is also nameless, but it differs from magnanimity upon the point which has been mentioned. Inasmuch as the virtuous character (Ic.the man who holds the true mean) has no special name of his own, he is called after the extremes, since he partakes of the character of both i at one time we call him ambitious, at another time un- ambitious, and at one time we praise the ambitious man, at another the unam- bitious man. The grounds upon which we do so will be explained in the sequel. Let us now proceed to enumerate the states of mind which still remain, seeking in each case for ' the mean ' and 'for the extremes. -Bk. II. 7.] Translation. 99 ii. — Virtues shown in relation to others. 1. VIETUES DISPLAYED UNDER PEOVOCATION. In reference, again, to anger there is excess and defect and a true 'mean.' These three states " have scarcely any recognized names; but if we call the ideal The regulation of •' ° ■ — the temper. cha racter ' th e goo(Wemj)ered_ man, we must name the corresponding disposition 'good temper.' Of the ex- tremes, the man who is exceaaJve in his anger may be classed as a 'passionate man,' and his vice as ' passionateness,' while the man who ifdeEcientJn a proper feeling of anger is a kind of impassive* person, and his mental state impassivity. "" In the matter of anger, the mean state is good temper, the ideal character being called the good-tempered man. The two extremes have no special name, though the excess may be named passionateness, and the man who shows the excess, the passionate man ; and deficiency of anger may be called impassivity, and the man who shows it, the impassive man. 2. VIETUES DISPLAYED IN SOCIAL INTEECOUESE. There are three other virtuous dispositions which have a kind of resemblance to one another, though with charac- teristic differences of their own. Their sphere is '^^^ , virtues of .,., . 1 iiiii social life depend social intercourse in word and deed between man upon the motives and man. shown and the cir- m, . , 1 • 1 ii Tzr • J.1 J. 1 ■! ciimstanceB which ihe point upon which they diner is that while fo^m their sphere. the one is concerned with th£_ita<^4— ia-v-oLv-ed in soc ial relations, the others are_concerned with_what-is-~;afea^a%^ in the saiae_c onnection ei ther (a) in relaxation, or (/3) in the various circumstances of dailj'- life. We must therefore consider the case of these dispositions, that we may the better understand that in all cases a true moderation is praiseworthy, while the extremes are neither right nor praise- worthy, but reprehensible. Of these relations the greater number have no special name of their own. Still we must endeavour (as we have already done in the case of others) to give them a name for ourselves, as well for the sake of perspicuity as to ensure our being intelligently followed. a. In respect, then,_o f truth, _jhe_4ier£gct_man^js the truthful man; a nd the perfe dLjtate oijiiiad--is-Jxuth£alness. ai^at^ay be called. On the other hand, assertion that errs on the side of exaggeration is boastfulness, and the corresponding character is the boastful man ; while assertion that errs on the side of sup- ir 2 lOO The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. Ii. 7. pression is reserve, and the corresponding character is the re- served man. h, In respect of what is agreeable : (a) In relaxation, the perfect man js the polite man; _^d the corresponding frame of mind is politeness, while excessive pleasantry is huffoonery, and tTie' maxTwFo indulges in it the buffoon. Defect of politeness, again, is boorishness, and the corresponding character the boor. (yS) In the circumstances of daily life^ the man who is agree- able as is .right and proper is a fr iend^r and his attitud e^ is that of » friendship. On the contrary, when a man goes into excess of pleasantness, if for no selfish motive, he is a courtier ; but if for purposes of his own, then he is a sycophant. Again, the man who is defective in courtesy, and in every way disagreeable, is a kind of churl and cross-grained fellow. There are fnitlier three other ' mean states,' which to a certain extent enter into one another, though they present also characteristic differences. In the actions we perform, and in the words we ntter in our intercourse with our fellow men, part of what we say and do is said and done for the sake of amusement, part for the sake of that general gratification which we find in life. Hence there are of necessity three ' mean states ' in respect thereto. In what is said or done with a view to tmth, the mean state is truthfulness ; and in reference to pleasure, the state which has reference to relaxation or amusement is politeness, and that which. is concerned with pleasantness generally is friend- liness. These three states all enter into one another, because they are aU concerned with intercourse in word and deed, but they are different the one from the other because the relations with which they are concerned are different. Their extremes have no special name, but we must find terms for them for the sake of perspicuity, and in order that our readers may readily foUow the course of the argument. 1. Let the extremes of truth, then, be named as follows : — assertion tending towards exaggeration, boastfulness, and the corresponding character, the boastful man ; while if the assertion tends towards suppression, it is reservation, and the corresponding character, the reserved man. 2. In regard to politeness, the excess is buffoonery, and the man who shows the excess the buffoon ; whUe the state which f aUs short of politeness ia boorishness, and the man who has such a deficiency, a boor. 3. In regard to friendship, the man who is excessive therein, and that with no selfish aim, may be called the courtier ; but if his motive be his own profit or advantage, then he is a flatterer. If, again, he falls short of friendliness, and is in every respect ungracious, then he is a man who is quarrelsome and cros- grained. iii.— Certain praiseworthy states of the Moral nature. 1. MENTAL PHASES CONCERNED WITH SHAME. There are also states of mora l per fgp*^^'"" i" rporgr rl to the feelings, and the CLrcums what time continue it. We have to judge for ourselves from the nature of the provocation and the attendant circumstances ; and we pronounce now in one way now in another. At one time we praise those who fall short in anger and call them gentle : at another time we praise those who are excessive in their anger and call them manly. Still the man who deviates but a little from the perfect state is not blamed, since he is thought to fall neither into excess nor defect. He is only blamed when he falls away from the perfect standard to such an extent as to attract notice. , But as for settling the point how far and to what extent we must deviate from the mean in order to be blameworthy — that is a matter which it is not possible to define in one comprehensive theory, nor indeed is generalization possible in any case which is found only in special connections and is as shifting as circumstance. Judgment upon such cases must have regard to their special limitations, and must depend upon the moral sense and the view which the moral sense takes of the whole surroundings generally. It is clear, therefore, that under all cu'cumstances that habit of mind which preserves a middle course between vicious extremes is the praiseworthy one ; and that, having regard to the tendencies of our own characters, it is right at some times to incline to excess and at other times to defect — i.e. to that particular ' extreme ' which is nearest akin to the mean. In this way we shall most easily attain to the moral mean and our own true perfection. BOOK III.-Part I. ANALYSIS OF MOBAL ACTION. Part H. EXAMINATION OF THE VIETUES. INTEODUCTOEY ANALYSIS. > Part I. — Analysis of Moral Action. In the last Book it was shown that Virtue implied an assent of tlie Will. In the present Book, before proceeding with his classification of virtues, Aristotle expands and illustrates his conception of ' the Will,' and shows its relation to the larger conception of ' the agreeable ' or ' the voluntary.' This subject is treated under two main theses : (1) that action cannot be considered as virtuous or vicious unless it is ' voluntary ' or agreeable to the agent ; and (2) that action is perfectly virtuous or perfectly vicious, when this voluntariness or liking for an action proceeds from a deliberate choice. In other words he examines first Voluntariness under the aspect of moral responsibility, and then Volitimi as the rational expression of the moral consciousness. I.— ANALYSIS OF MOEAL EESPONSIBILITY. A man is not held to be ' responsible' — he is not praised or blamed, for actions done without his free consent. Cases of ' non-responsibility ' may be classified according as their causes are (L) external or (ii.) internal. The agent has not free play when he is either under external constraint, physical or moral, or when he is ignorant of the circumstances under which he has to act. i. Absence of constraint is, therefore, the iirst condition of voluntary action. Constraint may be — 1. Physical constraint, where the agent is under the positive control of a force operating upon him. without any wish or liking of his own, as when he is taken prisoner. 2. Moral constraint, where the agent is sun-ounded by influences which force upon him a line of conduct which is distressing to him and in which he only acquiesces as being the least of evils. Actions of this latter kind, where the agent ' acts for the best ' in diflicult complications and under circumstances which are not within his own control, are ' mixed actions ' — partaking, that is, of the nature both I ro The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. of vohintariness and involuntariness. But, practically considered, they are more voluntary than involuntary, for the following reasons — (1) the end which is selected, though not good under all circumstances, is not only justifiable but commendable at a particular crisis. (2) The agent has the free use of his limbs, so as to act one way or another. (3) According as he acts in one way or another he is praised or blamed ; and praise or blame implies freedom of choice. On the other hand there are cases where constraint means necessity;" and where no mortal could hold out. Evil deeds committed in face of overwhelming pressure are practically involuntary, and deserve forgive- ness. Still no conceivable pressure ought to make a man violate the eternal principles of right and wrong, as for instance, to be a matricide. No definite rule can be laid down to anticipate every possible contin- gency of this kind. The degree of praise or blame which should be meted out to ' mixed actions ' depends upon the delicate adjustments of Castiistry. The complications of actual life seem to baffle all generiQ principles. In ordinary cases, however, the history of ' moral constraint ' is this : the actual pain of the moment or the future pain which their imagination conjures up as impending, weighs so unduly with nven that they will do any shameful thing to avoid it. There is a conflict between feeling and conviction, imagination and conscience. Still the definition given above of 'compulsory' and 'mixed' actions holds good. Actions are ' compulsory ' when the agent is powerless to prevent them and does nothing to bring them about : actions are ' mixed ' when the will does not assent to them except as an escape from worse evils. [Here we must draw a line of demarcation between ' constraint ' and ' motive.' The Cyrenaics maintained that actions done under the in- fluence of pleasure and pain were done ' under constraint.' But such a theory proves too much : in that view every action would be compulsory. Again, constraint implies pain — which is a direct negative of their theory. Lastly, their theory ignores the susceptibilities of the agent] ii. Ftill hvmledge of tlie nature of his act is the other condition of a man's acting voluntarily. If a man acts in ignorance of what he is doing and is full of regret and remorse when he finds out what he has done, he is an involuntary agent. If on the other hand he is not sorry for what he has done, though at the time he was ignorant what he was doing, he is a non- voluntary agent. But here it must be noted that there is a twofold aspect of ignorance. A distinction must be drawn between accidental and essential ignorance, between ignorance of details and ignorance of principles, between ignorance as a casual mistake and ignorance as a confirmed habit of mind. (1.) When ignorance amounts to a darkening of the moral sense and issues out of a bad heart, it is voluntary ignorance. (2.) When ignorance is only an accidental want of perception of some detail, of the surroundings or circumstances of action, it is then in- voluntary ignorance. Such an ignorance may be of any of the following j particulars — the agent, the act, the scope, the time, the place, the means, the instrument, the motive, the manner. Some of these details being more important than others, the degree of involuntariness must be measured accordingly. Introductory Analysis : Book III, 1 1 1 The conditions, therefore, which are requisite for voluntary action will be — (1) free origination by the agent, and absence of all constraint; (2) a full knowledge of the circumstances under which he is acting. [Here a question may be raised : Is a man responsible for his own feelings? Are actions done under the influence of desire or impulse voluntary actions? Most certainly. (1) Children act voluntarily, yet they act from impulse. (2) Even noble actions are sometimes done under impulse. (3) There are certain feelings which we are under a moral obligation to entertain. (4) Acts done under impulse are pleasurable : involuntary acts are painful. (5) Errors of impulse are as much to be avoided as errors of judgment. (6) Desire and impulse ai'e essential parts of human nature. (7) Desire as much as reason governs the moral life of man.] II.— ANALYSIS OF EATIONAL VOLITION. But voluntariness implies little more than that an action is agreeable to the agent ; and that is not an adequate explanation of moral action. Moral action implies not merely a movement of the heart, but also an assent of the Keason. Voluntariness is not 'volition' until it be associated with a purpose marked out by the Eeason. We may there- fore proceed to examine moral action under the special aspect of Kational Purpose. First of all we must distinguish it from kindred processes. i. ' Voluntariness ' is distinct from Volition : (1.) All sentient beings act voluntarily, i.e. agreeably to their nature, but not all are capable of a rational choice or moral purpose. (2.) Acts done ' on the spur of the moment ' are not rational, nor the result of a rational adjustment of means to end; and yet they are voluntary (i.«. not disagreeable to us). ii. ' Desire ' and ' Impulse ' are distinct from Volition : (1.) Volition is not found in irrational animals. (2.) Volition and impulse are mutually exclusive of one another in the case of the man of strong or weak character. The eyKparrjn has no impulse but strong volition : the aKparris has impulse and not volition. There is thus an antagonism between impulse and volition. (3.) Impulse is concerned with pleasure, Volition with honour. iii. ' Wish ' is distinct from Volition. (1.) A man may wish for the impossible, but he cannot ' will ' it. (2.) Wish is often concerned with things beyond a man's own com- pass ; but volition is concerned only with what comes within our own power. (3.) Wish is concerned with the 'end'; volition -with the means whereby the end wished for may be realized. iv. ' Opinion ' is distinct from Volition. (1.) The sphere of opinion is the whole universe ; the sphere of volition things within our own power. (2.) Opinion is true or false; volition is morally right or wrong. 1 1 2 The Moral Philosophy of AiHstolle. V. Volition is distinct from any special form of Opinion. (1.) Opinion does not imply in any case a moral nature ; volition does. (2.) Opinion does not imply pursuit or avoidance ; volition does. (3.) Opinion is praised for its form ; volition for its matter. (4.) Good opinions and good volitions are not coextensive nor convertible. (5.) Opinion implies only prohahUity ; volition moral certainty. Still Volition if not identical with any of these processes, seems to comprise elements derived from them all. It is a form of the voluntary, and consequently implies desire, what is voluntary being also what is agreeable or desirable. But it is something more : it is an intellectual as well as a moral or emotional process. It is not merely a free desire/ but a conscious survey of all the circumstances, and a deliberate adapta- tion of means to ends, with the striving necessary thereta We may now proceed to consider Volition under its double aspect of (1) Calculation or Deliberation, and (2) Wish, or Desire. A, Deliberation is identical with ' practical reason : ' it is ' the mind in council,' calculating what is or is not within its power to effect, and how best its object may be attained. The sphere of deliberation is, therefore, not coextensive with thought, but is limited to human interests. The following list will be excluded from it: — (1) the eternal and unalterable, (2) fixed laws of Nature, (3) the changes of outward phenomena, (4) the contingencies of chance, (5) even human interests which are beyond our own horizon. By inference also certain even of the arts must be excluded — such as have exact rules : only those arts which are , ,1,1 from Wish in being impossible ; and 11 a man were to say that he limited to things ' willed ' (or had ' deliberately resolved upon ') a ■^^'c'^ ^i^e possible ,1 • . -11 1 111 ii 1 i J. 1 and within our own thing- impossible, he would be thought to be control and in crazy. On the other hand Wish may have for being concerned its object such an impossibility, for instance, as ^ot'with'^Tnds.^" exemption from death. 2. Again, Wish is conversant with objects which never could have been compassed by a man's own self; for instance, that a particular athlete or actor should win a prize. But no one ' wills ' (or ' deliberately chooses ') anything of the kind : the only things which are objects of choice are such as a man thinks might be attained by his own self. 3. Moreover, Wish is concerned rather with ' the end ' of action, whereas the Will (or rational preference) is concerned with the means subsidiary to that end. For example, we ' wish ' to be in health, but we exercise our volition upon the means whereby we may attain health. Again, we Tvisk to be happy, and we often say so ; but it would be an incongruous expression to say that we ' have a volition to be happy.' In a word, the will (or ' rational purpose ') seems to be con- cerned only with things that are within our own power. Nor again assuredly is WiU the same thing as Wish, though the two seem very closely aldn to one another. 1. There is no volition in the case of things impossible : we do not form a reso- lution to take to ourselves wings and fly, nor to be exempt from death, though we may ivis/i that we could be. If a man formed any such ' resolution' he would be thought to be crazy. The Will, therefore, is not Wish. 2. We wish of ttimes for things which not we ourselves but others do ; for instance, that a particular actor may surpass all his rivals on the stage, or that a particular athlete may win a prize. But no one exercises his volition upon such things, nor in fact about anything except what he thinks may be compassed by his own efforts. 1 34 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. III. 4. 3. Again, Wish always refers to the ' end,' whereas the Volition has reference to the means which conduce to that end. We wish for health, but we ' mill' (or deliberately adopt) what tends to health— the means whereby it is possible to attain health. Again, we wish for happiness, and we say that we wish for it; but we do not say that we ' will ' to be happy — such an expression being in- consistent. In fact the Will seems to be concerned only with things that are within our own power. [d) THE WILL NOT IDENTICAL WITH OPINION. Nor assuredly is the Will identical with Opinion : 1. Opinion seems to have all things for its Volition is a term sphere, and is exercised no less upon things 01 narrower range \ i , liiiii i than Opinion; and eternal and Unalterable than upon such as are its sphere is not within our own powcr. truth and falsehood c\ r\ ■ • • j-ir x-iii i.T. ij_ > j hut good and evil. 2. Opinion IS ditterentiatea by the ' true and the ' false,' not by the ' good ' and the ' evil,' whereas the Will is characterised hy the latter rather than by the former. There is however no one who maintains, without reservation or limitation, that the Will is identical with Opinion. Nor assuredly is the Will identical with Opinion. 1. Opinion is concerned with every kind of matter, things eternal, things depending upon ourselves, and things that are impossible. 2. Opinion is differentiated by the ' false ' and the ' true : ' of two opinions we say that the one is true and the other false. On the other hand tiie Will is characterised by moral good and evil : of one will we say that it has ' the good' for its object, and of another will we say that it has ' the evil ' for its object. There is, however, no one who thinks that the WUl is identical with Opinion in the wide sense of the term. (e) THE WILL NOT IDENTICAL WITH ANY SPECIAL TOEM OF OPINION. Nay, more : the Will is not identical with any special form of Opinion : Moreover, Volition 1. According to the way in which we exercise JlJe^te^ Xch "are ^"^"^ ^'^^ ^'^'^ Z^'^^ 01" ^vil, wc gain a certain moral immjiteriai to mere character ; but the opinions we form have no f^r^tt^ideS such influence upon our lives. with any form of 2. We ' wiU ' (or ' rcsolve ') to take or to avoid Sy'dS^Lct t ^ tl^i'^?' O"^ to perform some act implying pursuit kind. or avoidance ; but we form opinions only of ab- stract questions : ' What is expedient ? ' ' For whom r or ' How ? ' We surely do not form an opinion to take or to avoid. 3. The will is praised rather for having a proper object than for Bk. III. 4.] Translation. 135 being formed in a certain mould of correctness ; whereas Opinion is praised by reason of its truth or falsehood. 4. Those who form the best opinions seem not to be of the same class with those who form the best resolutions. There are those who think rightly what is the better course, and yet through an evil disposition form unrighteous resolutions. 6. We make our choice deliberately of things which we know most surely to be goods ; but we form opinions upon things with which we are imperfectly acquainted. [It is immaterial to our purpose whether Opinion is antecedent to Volition or concomitant therewith : — that is not the point we are now discussing, but rather whether Volition is identical with any form of Opinion.] Nay more : not only is Volition not identical with Opinion in its wide sense : - it is not identical with any special form of Opinion. 1. In consequence of the volitions we make, we grow to be of a certain moral character : by consciously willing what is eTil, we grow to be evil in om'selves : by consciously willing and adopting what is right, we grow ourselves to be right- minded. But no such results flow from the Opinions we form. 2. We make a volition to do something or to forbear : — to take something or to avoid something of the same kind. But we form opinions upon the nature of the thing towards which we make a volition, or of some alternative course, or upon the question ' whose interest a thing serves,' or ' how.' But ' to take ' a thing, or to ' avoid ' it or to ' choose ' it — ^these are not thiags within the province of opinion. Volition therefore is not identical with Opinion. 3. Volition is praised when we exercise it upon things that are rlglit. Opinion is praised when what we hold as opinion is tme. 4. We exercise volition upon things of which we are quite satisfied that they are good ; but we form opinions which we are not quite sure are true. 5. The same man is not consistent in what he resolves upon and what he thinks : he ofttimes forms admirable opinions, thinking what is true, but at the same time resolves upon what is evil. Volition is, therefore, not identical with Opinion. [Though Opinion often precedes Volition or accompanies it, it does not follow that Volition and Opinion are identical : there is nothing in that to prevent their being in conflict.] (/) THE WILL PROVISIONALLY DEFINED, Seeing then that Volition is not identical with any of the mental processes enumerated above, what is its real nature, and its distinctive character ? Volition is, there- Obviously it is a thing that is voluntary ; but tie 'genus ' voiun- the converse is not true that 'all that is voluntary tary,'itsc«tj ^'l "■** the subject how we ought to form our letters), "^'^^'^'^s agrees. The things, I say, upon which we deliberate are such as are pro- duced by our own selves, though differently under different cir- cumstances ; in regard, for instance, to Medicine or Finance, or Seamanship more than about Gymnastic, since Seamanship is a less perfectly elaborated Science ; and similarly in regard to the other arts, though more so in regard to the Arts than the Sciences, inasmuch as we have more uncertainty about the former. The sphere of deliberation, then, is that of things contingent and general where there is uncertainty in what way they will result, and where there is an element The conditions, of indefiniteness. [In regard to serious issues we ti'^'-'^fore, implied , , ,. . J '- ° IT . in the subject- take others into our counsels, distrusting our matter of delibera- own judgment, as being incompetent to decide ^'°° "^/£^ contin- ji -| S^i^cy^ ^/j ajtsencG tnereon. J of a fixed rule, and (3) moral import- These general principles assumed, we may now proceed to ^™^" inquire whether it he possible to deliberate upon every sub- ject alike, or whether there be points upon which deliberation is impossible, so that we may ascertain thereby with what subjects Volition is concerned and what subjects are without its sphere. The sphere of volition is of coui-se the sphere of such matters as come under deliberation. [I mean by a ' matter for delibe- ration ' one about which (not the fool or the madman but) the man of sense would deliberate.] The sphere of deliberation must be narrowed by the exclusion of the following subjects : (1.) Deliberation is not concerned with things eternal, for instance, with the Universe : no one deliberates as to how the heavenly bodies ought to move ; nor is it concerned with things impossible to be altered, for instance, in reference to the side and diameter of a parallelogram, to effect such a proportion between them as that they should be commensurate. (2.) Nor is there deliberation upon things which are eternally moved in the same direction either by Necessity or by Nature or through some other cause ; for instance, the solstices and sun-risings. (3.) Nor are we likely to deliberate upon things which are variable, alternating now one way now another, for instance, drought and rains. (4.) Nor do we deliberate upon the accidents of chance ; for instance, the find- ing of a treasure ; inasmuch as not one of these things is dependent upon our- selves nor within the province of human effort. (5.) Nay, we are not likely to deliberate upon everything that does fall within the province of man, but only upon things that are within our own power and which we could effect of our own selves, either by our own direct agency or 138 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bt III. 5. througli otliers. Tbe Spartans are not likely to deliberate upon the constitution of the Scythians as to how they might be most satisfactorily governed. No such scheme as those indicated above, could be effected by our own agency. The things upon which we deliberate are such only as can be effected by our own selves, and these we wUl now investigate. There are three causes operating among existences— Nature, Necessity, and Chance. There is also Mind and whatever is produced by the agency of man — e.g., Art and certain other forms of activity. Now men do not deliberate upon things of which either Nature or Necessity or Chance are the causes ; but only upon things of which the cause is human design and human effort. Nay, they do not deliberate upon all the designs which are possible to man : there is no deliberation in reference to such sciences as are exact and independent, e.g., Philology — we never doubt how letters should be formed, that beiog a subject which is exactly known and of which the characteristics are aoom-ately defined. The subjects, I say, about which we deliberate are such as are produced by our own selves and which ai;e capable of being produced in a variety of ways ; in regard, for instance, to the course to be pursued in medicine — wherein the coureea are not perfectly defined ; or in regard to financial speculations, where it is possible to make money in a variety of ways ; or in regard to questions of navigation or training — though we have to deliberate more about matters of navigation than about matters of training, navigation being a less accurately defined science ; and similarly in other sciences. But we deliberate more about the Arts than the Sciences, since we are in greater hesitation in the Arts, their province being less accurately defined than that of the Sciences. The subjects then of deliberation are such as may conceivably take place as a matter of probability, but when the issue is uncertain in reference to such matters — i.c., in what way it will turn out and under what conditions, it is impossible that any definite deliberation should take place. [For this reason we associate with ourselves counsellors when the subject involves grave issues, wherein we are distrustful of ourselves as being incompetent to form a judgment.] {b) THE METHOD AND EFFECT OF DELIBERATION. But we do not deliberate about ' ends/ but about the means whereby to compass our ends. The physician of* contingency ^°^® ^^^ deliberate whether he should cure his apply only to the patient, nor the orator whether he should persuade " 0"°* action : ^^^ audience, nor the statesman whether he should Dehberation as- promote social Order; nor in the various contin- eXat starffng!^"" 8^°^^^^ of life does any one deliberate about the 'end' in view. "We assume a certain end, and then consider how and by what means it can be realized. In case the end appears possible to be realized by various means, we reflect further what means will be most easy and most honourable; if on the other hand the result is to be achieved by one way only, we consider how we may find that way and what will conduce to it, until we arrive at the original cause, which comes last in point of discovery. In fact a man when he is deliberating seems to be making a The method by Search and to be resolving a truth into its which Deliberation elements (in the way that I have described), Bk. III. 5.] Translation. 139 like a mathematical figure. [But obviously not proceeds is similar all forms of searcli are forms of deliberation : — to that of geometri- for instance, certain mathematical investigations are not ; though every case of deliberation is a form of search.] Hence the truth which is last in the analysis is first in the production. But if, on arriving at this ultimate fact, the thing to be done be found impracticable, we then desist from our deliberations — if, for example, there be need of When analysed into , ,1 T ■ • i. ia? J. 1 its simplest ele- money to carry the conclusion mto ettect, and money ments an action is cannot be found. If on the other hand the con- seen to be either elusion seems to be practicable, we then set our practicable. " ™' hands to work to carry it out. Things are, of course, only practicable when they can be compassed by our own agency, though in this category we must include things done by our friends, as being in a sense done by ourselves, since the origination thereof rests with ourselves. The object of this inquiry is thus alternately the instruments, and the mode of using them. Indeed in matters of action gene- rally the subject of deliberation is at one time the proper agency, at another time the proper manner, at another time the proper persons, to carry out cur purpose. It seems clear then, that man is, as has been explained, the author of his own actions; and his deliberations have reference only to things which can be com- Things are practi- passed by his own self, though his actions when ::f ,7c2pS performed, have reference to 'ends' beyond them- by our own agency, selves. Consequently the object of our delibera- tion is not 'the end' of our actions, but the means whereby we may attain those ends. [One other limitation must be made : particular matters of fact are not subjects for deliberation, as for instance whether this be bread or whether it has been Matters of fact are properly baked. Such matters are questions for ters of deliberation. the senses to decide. If one had to deliberate upon simple matters of fact, we should have nothing from which to start, and our deliberations would reach on to infinity.] But we do not deliberate about ' ends,' but about the means that are conducive to ends. The physician will not deliberate about giving health to his patient : — it is inconceivable that a physician should have regard for anything else, and therefore he wiU have no need of deliberation upon that point. The question which he will deliberate will be, what are the means which tend to produce health, and which may conceivably be compassed in. a variety of ways. Similarly the orator will not deliberate upon the question of persuasion, but only upon the line 140 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. III. 5. of argument that will conduce to persuasion. The statesman does not summon the Senate in order that he may ascertain the expediency of good government, since of course he is bound to secure a proper administration of affairs : the object of his deliberations will be the means which constitute and secure such a good government. In fact aU men in their several vocations assume or presuppose a certain 'end,' and inquire into the manner and the measures whereby they may attain to that end. If there be many ways by which it is possible for them to attain to the mark, they inquire into the means whereby they may most easily and most honourably realize their aim. If, on the other hand, there be only one way by which it is conceivable that they should succeed, they do not inquire fni-ther therein, except only as to the mode in which they ought to treat or handle this particular agency, and what course of conduct they ought to adopt in order to achieve their purpose. They have further to consider what measures will facilitate that course of conduct, and again what means wUl facilitate these other means, until they arrive at something which can be done without the intervention of anything else — and this ultimate fact is the original cause of the ' end,' though it be the last thing to be discovered. In this way the man who deliberates, starting from the ' end,' travels through the various means which lead to that end, breaking up the whole action into its elements, until he reaches to the original cause, — just in the same way as mathe- maticians analyse their figures. Deliberation, therefore, is a mode of search, though the two terms are not convertible. Yet, as has been shown, the man who is deliberating is making an analysis, no less than the man who is making a mathematical inquiry. The fact which is last to be discovered in maldng the analysis, becomes the first thing to be- done by the man who is deliberating. In precisely the same way the mathematician, assuming and positing the point which will be the last at which he will arrive in the course of his analysis, and, with this as a starting point, proceeding through the other points, demonstrates thereby the problem set before him. But both the one and the other desist from their inquiiy if, in the course of their analysis, they light upon things that are impracticable : — if, for example, there be need of money to compass the end that is sought for, and this end cannot be compassed except by money, and it be evident that money cannot possibly be found, men do not inquire further therein but desist altogether, whereas if money can be found, they then set their hands to work to effect their purpose. We call things ' practicable ' then, which can be effected by our own selves — including thereby the agency of friends, since the cause of their help depends upon ourselves. Among things that are practicable we have to deliberate at one time in regard to the proper instruments, at another time in regard to the proper use of those instruments, — and generally in regard to the means which tend to a given end, how they may be obtained, or else in regard to the mode in which we should employ those means, or as to the agency necessary. It is evident then, from what has been said, that the ' end ' is not a matter for deliberation. The subjects of deliberation are matters wher6 a man has power either to act or to forbear : wherever a man has such a power there is the sphere of human action. But human actions are invariably performed with a view to purposes beyond themselves, and whatever is done with a view to ulterior purposes, is not itself an ' end.' Hence the subject matter of deliberation is not • the end,' but the means to the end. Yet even among the means to ends there are certain things exempted — i.e., specific matters of fact — whether, for example, a loaf has been baked or manufactured as it ought to be. We know these specific facts by our own senses, not by deliberation or exercise of judgment. If one had to deliberate upon all occasions upon specific facts, we could never mark a start, but our deliberations would reach on to infinity. Bk. Ill, 5.] Translation. x\\ (c) COMPARISON BETWEEN DELIBERATION AND CHOICE. The province within which Deliberation is exercised is thus identical with that of Choice — except that a matter which has been adopted by the Choice is Kationai volition, one which is ipso facto defined and settled. A t'^^'^®?"''"' ^'^ t^ie 1 • 1 r 1 1,1- „ exercise of a ra- matter which has been selected m preference to tional choice, is anything else, after deliberation, is a matter j.*^™*^"^-*!^ ^ j./*^ which is ' purposed,' or rationally adopted by an ration. act of the Will. Everyone ceases to inquire how he shall act, when he has brought the final decision to himself, that is, to the sovereign power within him, which is the power of willing or purposing. An illustration of this power of Will may be drawn from the old polities or constitutions which Homer has described. There we see the Princes in consulta- Picture of the tion ; and after they have formed their purpose, Home™— °''^ ™ they announce. their Will to the crowd. Just so (i.) Princes de- the Eeason deliberates and announces its purpose itinerating what . r r measures to take. to the crowd of passions, for them to carry out. (2.) Choice of mea- sures and procla- _,. . , . , . _ _ mation to the crowd Since then a thing which has been purposed to carry them out. is a thing which has been deliberated upon, and which is consciously striven after, and a thing which is within our own power, purpose itself will be ' a striving after things within our own power, which have been deliberately determined upon.' After having deliberated we decide, and then strive after our object in accordance with our choice. Let this, then, suffice for an outlined definition of Choice, and for an account of its objects, and of its special concern with means. Such then is the province of Deliberation ; and a matter of Choice is such part of the province of Deliberation as has been determined upon. A matter is said to be 'purposed' or ' chosen,' when it has been selected in preference to something else after deliberatian. After having decided what we ought to do, we no longer deliberate upon the matter, bub know definitely how we ought to act : we bring down the power of originating (.dpxri) the desired object to our own wish, and we bring down our own decision and wish to our own Will, which is, 'ipsofaoto, the spring or ' cause ' of the action. This view of the Will may be illustrated from the old constitutions which Homer has described in his Ballads. He there introduces the Princes after a CoimcU announcing the course which they have determined upon, to the Demus, just as the Reason or Prerogative Power within us announces its decision to the Will, so that it may be carried into effect. Since then that which is ' purposed ' is what has been deliberated upon, aiming at objects dependent upon ourselves — a thing in fact for which we strive after deliberating thereon and which we are oursslvea able to effect, it is evident that 142 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. ill. 6. the Will may be defined as a ' deliberate striving after objects which are within our own power.' After having deliberated, we decide, and then strive after the object chosen in accordance with om- wish. Such is our definition of Will, or ' Rational Choice,' as far as is possible in a general outline ; and in this definition is implied the scope of the Will, which is not the ' end,' but the means which conduce to the end. iii. — The Will implies a 'Wish for the good.' (a) IS THE OBJECT OF WISH THE EEAL OR THE APfAKENT GOOD? It has been already shown that ' Wish ' h as relation to the 'end' of action; but there is a difierence of How far is a man opinlonr whether this 'end' is identicaljwith__the moraHmpressions? »'^«^ good, or whether it is identical only^wijft. Jie apparent good. 1. Now there is this difficulty facing those who say that it is the real good which is the.oi^fiaLQ£j5rish : — ^when h d^a dilit^ffS rf ^ Toaxi. adopts a particular course in error , that the real good, no for which he ii^wishing_is-aot-41ie-4r-«&-al:yficLof one wOTid make an j^jg ^jg]j_ Otherwise, had their theory been true, and That for which a man wished were really desirable, it would be a good ; but in the case that I am sup- posing, it might be actually aa evil. 2. On the other hand, those who maintain that it is the apparent good whichJ&Jhfi-_o]4ecLj2f_wish, are be onro/thrrp- ™®* "^^^^ *^^^ difficulty— that, according to their parent good, there theory, there would be nnthing good per Sfi. m^ is an end of moral j^ ^|jg nature of things, but whatever each man thought to be good, to him that thing would be good. But there are different things thought good by different individuals, and perchance, in possible cases, things which are antagonistic. We must now proceed to treat of the subject of Wish. It was shown in the previous discussion that Wish is concerned with ' the end' of action, but a controversy has been raised whether ' the end ' which the Wish has before it may be of any nature whatever, anything in fact which a man might desire to gain, or whether it must be the real good only. In fact some thinkers maintain that Wish is concerned simply with the true ' good,' others that it is concerned with what unems to be the good, whether it be so in reality or no. 1. Now there is this diflficulty facing those who say that it is the real good alone which is the object of Wish : — they imply that evil is not an object of Wish to the vicious man, though in fact it most assuredly is. 2. On the other hand, those who maintain that it is the apparent good which is the object of Wish, not by reason of any intrinsic quality, but just as each man temporarily thinks it good, are confronted by this difficulty : inasmuch 'as different things appear good to different individuals, what one man thinks good, appearing evil to another, and the same person ofttimes regarding things antago- nistic to each other to be good — according to this view, nothing can be an object of wish in its own nature and for its own sake. Bk. III. 6.] Translation. 143 {b) BECONCILEMENT OF THESE TWO THEORIES. If, therefore, neither of these theories be satisfactory, may we not say that ' absolutely, and in strict truth, the ob ject of Wish_^aat_^which is really good, ^ S t ^. thouglLJslatiyely_to_trie indivicIual'Tf is~EEe ap- versai, tut the im- parent good?' To" the-'good man, the object of ^r^^fil^J wisE~is" that which is coniormabla_tQ__ahaQlute with the variations truth; on the other hand, to the bad man the "f tteir own moral r^ ' . ' temperament. \ object of wish is anything that may chance. It is precisely the same in the case of physical tasks : when men are in a healthy state of body, things are wholesome that are really so, whereas if men are themselves diseased, things abnormal are wholesome in their eyes. In such cases, also, the sensations of bitter and sweet, hot and heavy, and so on, are similarly reversed. The fact is that it is onjythe_good_m|m jgfho., jjidgfifl„aright.of moraL-difihr£nces ; on non^HBut on him are the impressions made in every particular true and food' m^/th'Tt the just. Corresponding to the vavying^ conditions of impressions of good teinperanient, there are speciaTlmpressions of ^™J?^y The'morai what is noble and of what is agreeable ; and sense of men gene- herein is the good man pre-eminent.Above- others, "^^^'^ ^^ dimmed by ~ — .?? . ^;_jx ^ ? pleasure : that oi that lie .gees the truth^n^eyeryjnstance ; bemg, as the good man alone it were, himself the standard and measure of ^^ ^J^ ^"^ ™''™" truth in all its forms. On the other hand, in the min ds of men gene rally, error seems to grow up naturally, un der the influen ce of pleasure. ^ThougF pleasure is not itself a good, it has the appearance of being so in the eyes of the world : hence they make their choice of the pleasurable as of a good, and shun pain as an evil. But if neither of these views seems probable, we may state a solution of our own : — ^tbat it is the good which is the object of wish by nature, and in real truth, and in its own right, but that under certain aspects, and according to the standard of particular individuals, it is what meins to be the good that is the object of wish. Though a thing be not a good in real truth, yet in reference to given circumstances it may be good ; for instance, to steal clothes is by nature an evil thing, yet from the point of view of the footpad, under certain circum- stances it may be a good, and in so far as a thing is a good it is an object of wish. It consequently happens that what secnu to be good, is under a particular aspect an object of wish. To the good man, therefore, that which is veritably good is the object of wish, and to the bad man the object of wish is anything that may chance. Precisely similar is the case of our physical conditions. To those who are in sound health and in a good state of body, things appear to be healthy that are so in truth, but to those who are diseased, the contrary. Similarly in the case of things bitter or sweet : to those who axe in sound health, things that are in their 144 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. III. 7. own nature bitter or sweet, appear to be what they are. Such men judge rightly that such and such things are hot, or heavy, and so forth : on the other hand, those who are diseased in their senses, judge that things quite different from these are hot, or heavy, and so forth. The analogy applies exactly to things that are morally good or pleasant or evil. The good man thinks things good when they are so in reality : the bad man often thinks quite the reverse. Corresponding to the vaiious temperaments of men's souls, there are things which are specially good and pleasurable ; and herein the good man differs from the bad, in that he discriminates the good from the pleasant, and sees what is really true in every situation, having, as he has, become the standard and measure of truth, But the evU, from being unable to recognize the truth, are led astray by- pleasure, fancying that things pleasant are good, though they are not so by nature ; and similarly they shrink from things that are painful, though they are not in their own nature either evil or undesirable. iv.— The Will Implies Moral Freedom. (a) BOTH VIRTUE AND VICE ARE WITHIN OUE OWN POWER, Since, then, the end of actionals thejjbjecLof wish, and the meang of realizing the end are matters of delib eration The efficient causes ^nd choice, the actions conseguentjhereon wiUha being'^'Jrithin our in accordance wLth-our-own ^W4.U,-aBd-¥eluutary. own power, Virtue In this Sphere also the various formS-of moral be ™TuntS! ^°* excellency win be.eshibited. Consequenjl^moral exceltenbe isjistatewithiiuMir own power, as also, for similar reasons, is moral corruption. Where the power of action depends upon our own selves, in such cases there is also the power of forbearing ; and where there is a power of forbearing, there is also a power of acting. HencCj^ if action, when honou rable, is within onr pow er, the refraining from action when such refraining is disgrac eful, will also be within our power ; and if the power of not acting when such non-acTioiTts honourable depend upon ourselves, the power of acting when action is disgraceful will also depend upon ourselves. But if it be within our power to perform actions honourable and dishonourable, aud similarly to^ abstain therefrom (and that is equivalent to being good or bad), it will consequently rest with ourselves whether we be virtiifius or vicious. Since then the ends of action ?(i-e the objects of wish, and the means which conduce to those ends, objects of deliberation and rational choice, it is evident that the actions which result from these processes of deliberation and of choice will themselves be in accordance vsdth our own WiU, and voluntary. Of such a character are the actions which are conformable to virtue, since they are manifested in the same sphere as deliberation and choice. Virtue and vice are therefore dependent upon ourselves, since the actions by means of which we habituate ourselves to virtue are deliberately adopted or ' willed,' and are dependent upon om'selves. But if the doing of good be vrithia our own power, the refraining from good wiU be within our own power, since where there is ' nay ' there is also ' yea.' Hence if action, when honourable, be within our own power, the refraining Bk. III. 7.] Translation. 145 fi'om action, where such refraining is disgraceftd, will also be within our own power. If, that is, the refrainuig' from evU, when such refraining is rio-ht be within om- own power, the performing of evil, when such performsmoe is°evii, is also within our own power. But our line of conduct im such ciroumatauces makes us good or evil ; and consequently it is within our own power to be virtuous or vicious. {b) REFUTATION OF THE THEORY THAT VICE IS INVOLUNTARY, But as for saying that " None are wicked of their free will, nor 'gaiast their will are they happy," such a theory is partly true and partly untrue. Though no one is happy against his own inclination, wickedness iS^ still a votuntafy^tate to the wicked man. Disproof of the Otherwise we'iiiiist "raise, in opposition to the ^^^eory of EpichaT- tneory 01 voluntariness advanced above, a new involuntary' -.— issue, and argue that man is not the 'primal cause' and father of his own acts, as he is the father of his children. But if ou r own theory be, as it manifestly is, the true one, and we are not able to refer our actions to any causes beyond those which are within pur_gwn j)Ower, (l.) By the fact then, where the cai^ses of. actions depend upon of '^"iT arf within ouisfilves,^ -the ^feets- will -liljgwise. dep,ejid_upon our own power, ourselves, and our actions mU-be voluntary. Evidence of this moral freedom seems to be given not only by the individual consciousness of each, but also by the example of legislators, jrhqse codes inflict (?.) By the con- punishment and pen alty upon evil-doers (except Sat^o^^ aas^unfes where" ineiilict under constraint, and owing to human freedom, ignorance for which they are not themselves to blame) and, on the other hand, confer honours upon such as per- form noble exploits, the design and intention being to encourage the one in their heroism, and to deter the others from their wickedness. Yet of course, no lawgiver would urge . men_to_per- form actions which were neit her within their own control nor voluntar y, knowing that it would Jieas Jutile as .for a man-taJiave been pers uaded not ta ...feeUieat_ or pain or . hunger or other similar sensa tions : none the less for all the persuasion we shall continue liable to feel them. Furthermore, wh en a man seem s to be himself responsible for his own i gnorance, the laws punish_ jiim on t he simple gro und of his bei ng ignorant; for in- (3.)Bythefactthat stSHi7>nalties are doublidin the case of Sr^'punTsZ drunkards. In such cases, the first step depends doubly as an aggia- 146 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. Iii:7. vation of the upon the man's own self: it was possible for offence. j^j^j^ ^Q jjg^yg avoided the drunken excess which produced the ignorance. Again, men are punishe d for being ign flrant nf pmnts of law with which they^ught to have been familiar, and whic h are not tooabsEu seTor them t o understand. Men are, in fact, puniiEeTin all cases alike, when they are thought to be ignorant of their duties through their own neglect, upon the ground that it was within their own power not to have been ignorant : they were com- petent to have kept their duties in remembrance. But as for saying that " None are wicked of their free ■will, nor 'gainst their will are they happy," Buoh. a view seems to be partly true and partly false. It is true that no one can become happy against his will ; but the first half of the line is untrue. Wickedness is in no way a thing involuntary. It has been shown from the pre- vious arguments, that man is the cause of his own actions. But where the causes are within our own power, the effects are also within our own power, and voluntary. Hence, for this reason, every action of man, whether it be good or whether it be evil, is voluntary. This view is borne out by the com-se which both individuals and lawgivers take against evildoers. They cause vengeance or punishment to light upon those who do evil deeds, except where the wrong-doing is caused by some kind of external constraint, or in consequence of ignorance for which the agents are not themselves responsible (a man, for instance, would be responsible for his ignorance, as well as for his act, if he did anything evil when intoxicated, and so ignorant of the nature of his act : he has only himself to blame for the con- sequences). On the other hand, lawgivers honour those who act nobly, in order that they may thereby encourage others to noble deeds, and restrain them from doing evil. Hence it is evident that they consider it to be within our own power to be vicious, or to grow to be virtuous ; and it is with this view that they use their endeavours to inspire men with this conviction. Of course, where things are neither within our own power nor voluntary, no one in his right senses mges us to perform them : no one tries to persuade another not to experience heat or cold or hunger or other similar sensations over which we have no control, since no good could possibly accrue from such an exhortation, though we who were exhorted were ourselves to desire exceedingly to profit by it ; we should continue, all the same, subject to such sensations. Similarly when a man is involuntarOy ignorant from being unable to know, no one would m-ge him to have the power of knowing : it does not rest with the man himself, whether he knows or is ignorant. But if a man be personally .responsible for the ignorance under the influence of which he committed the evil, then he is punished for it : he seems to be in a state of ignorance of his own free will, because in that case it rests with himself whether he know or be ignorant, as with the drunkard, or one who through his own neglect is ignorant of the law, which he might easily have found out. An evildoer of this type 18 personally responsible, both for his ignorance and for his wickedness, and IB wicked of his own free wHl. The case is similar in regard to other points which it is possible for us to know, and from misunderstanding which we fall into error. It is owing to such faults that we are exposed to the penalties of the lawgivers. We are competent, that is, to avoid being ignorant, because it is within our own power not to be careless of such things, but to make it out own business to understand them. Bk. III. 7.] Translation. 147 (c) FREEDOM IN THE FORMATION OF CHAEACTEE. '• ' But,' it may be objected, „' a ,man-'s„jdis.p.osition is such that he could not take Eeed^ to such things.' . .ViS'ayVmen are themselves responsible for ^^/„ ^l^^ *^*^^^ having acquired s uch a character by living dis- the bent of Ms dis- soliitelyT'aiT so too are "they 'responsible for ^"o^e^^iiff^/;* Bein g unjust an d intemperate whetli^rT'as is the not responsible :— case with some, by wrong-doing, or, as is the ^■) ^iharacter is ., 1 • ji • T- ■ T ■ 1 • "'"y concentrated case with others, by passmg their lives in drinking habit, and habit and similar debauchery. It is indeed a law of depends npon our- life that the activities which are displayed in any particular direction, produce a corresponding chai'acter in the agent.' — From the analogy of those who practise for any contest or profession, an illustration of this law may be taken : to ensure success, they practise their art continuously and perseveringly. To be^gnorant, therefore, that ' habits ' are formed by men dev^]^ingtEeiFpowers~in'particular directions 'is the^mark of an utter^TinrSfl'gctive'cha;racter. Moreover, it is absurd that the man who performs unjust acts should not mish to be unjust, or that a man who acts intemperately should jnol-zzas^^t-o be intem- *^-^ Habitdepends ^ _ •' - '. . - „ upon separate ac- perate.' If a man not unwittingly performs acts tions which are un- froin the effects of which he will be^unjust, he is ^^t^keahiy in our „ , . . . ■Till "^"1 power. unjust 01 his own choice ; nay, verily, though he should afterwards desire it, he will not afterwards cease to be unjust and become just, any more than the invalid will gain sound health by desiring to do so. By li$ing.iBtemperately...and dis- obeyijn g his phy sicians, .xL_.maiL,is. voluntarily an invalid. Jja^the casejvhich I have_supposed : in the first instance it was possible for him to have avoided illness, but after a man has once thrown away his health, his chance is gone. Precisely in the same way when a man has discharged a stone, it is no longer possible for him to recover it ; yet the projecting or casting of the stone was an act depending upon himself — the primary impulse, that is, was within his own control. This analogy applies exactly to the soul and to such states as justice and intemperance : it was possible in the first instance not to have formed such evil tendencies. Hence men of this type, as of others, are what they are of their own free wUl ; but when once a cha,racter of this kind has been formed in them it is no longer possible for them to be different. But if any one be of such a nature as not to have the capacity for taking heed, he will not on that account escape punishment. Nay, rather, he will be L 2 148 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. III. 7. punished for that very reason— for having culpably grown into such a state as to have lost the capacity for taking heed, by living dissolutely and licentiously. From such a mode of life it is that men become for the most part wicked, unjust, and dissolute. In consequence, that is, of the imjust and dissolute practices to which men become habituated they grow to be unjust and dissolute ; and they grow like that, even though they have not wrong-doing as a settled plan before them, but yet live a dissolute life and delight in self-indulgence and luxmy. From a course of Ufe like this, men advance to the commission of actual wrong. It is indeed ever the case, that according to the nature of the activities which we habitually practise, we grow, as has been explained, to be virtuous or vicioM or acquire some other complexion in om- moral life. Just so we see men who wish to become athletes or to cultivate some pther profession or business, practising and exercising themselves in the performance of acts by means whereof they may attain to the accomplishment they desire. No one, in fact, is ignorant that it is from the performance of specific acts that we atcain to a fixed and permanent state of vice or of virtue — unless he be utterly without perception. If then this truth be manifest to all, it is clear also that all men understand the character of their own acts, whether, that is, they tend to virtue or to vice ; and if they know what they are doing, they are of their own free will either good or evU. It is, of course, quite absurd for a man who performs unjust acts to say that he does not wish to be unjust, or for a man who is dissolute to say that he does not ivUh to act dissolutely. If, though he wish to become just and temperate, he is yet unable to be so through being overpowered by the strength of long habits, even thus he is voluntarily vicious. Take the case of a man who adopts a depraved mode of life and is disobedient to his physicians and is consequently in sickness : such an one is voluntarily an invalid, since the mode of his life depended upon himself, and though he afterwards wish to be relieved of its consequences, he cannot be. Before he fell ill, it depended upon himself to guard his health, but when once he has thrown away his health, it is no longer in his iwwer to recall it. Or, to take another case, a man has it in his own power to oast a stone into the sea, but when once he has oast it he has it not in his power to recall it again ; yet still he cast it of his own free wiU, the act of castiag being dependent upon himself. Precisely so is it in the case of the unjust and of the dissolute man. Before they grew to be vicious and attained to the permanent habit thereof, it was in their power not to have become so ; but when once they have grown into a certain state, they have no power to alter it. {d) FREEDOM IN THE FORMATION OF BODILY STATES. But not only are the faults or corruptions of the soul voluntary, but in certain cases the diseases_of_the_bo^^re ^enXr'oTbodUy voluntary^lTsoTang: tEesB cases', when they occnr , faults, when, as is we regard with disapproval. JNo one of course are "elf-produced^'' tlaiheFthose who are naturally disfigured, unless their deformity aris?r from wairt-Tif-exercise-or from their own neglect. Similarly iri^r'egardr to cffisra-of weakness or of mutilation : no one would taunt a man who was blind from nature, or through disease or tlirough an accident, but we should rather pity such an one. If on the other hand a man were_hlind through drunkenness or intemperance, all men would censure him. Consequently in the- case "even of' bodily" distempers -fcose which are under our own control are blamed, whereas such as are out of our own power are not blamed ; and if this priaciple be of general 3k. III. 7. J Translation. 149 ipplication, those distempers which are blamed in other relations i¥ill also be within our own power. But not OBly are tlie faults or corruptions of the soul voluntary, but in the 3ase of certain individuals, bodily diseases are also voluntarily formed — those at least on account of which men are censured. Of course no one in his senses blames those who are naturally disfigured ; but we do censure those who have rained their physique through omitting to take exercise or other neglect or through depravity. We do not taunt a man who is blind by nature or through disease or from a blow, but we rather pity him. But when a man has injured his eyes through dissipation or some other depravity, we blame him and censure him. It is clear then that such bodily ailments as are voluntarily incuiTed are blamed by us, while such as are involuntary are in no way blamed. This law will apply similarly to other cases : such as are cases for punishment and for which penalties are provided are entirely voluntary and dependent upon ourselves : such as are not of this character, are involuntary. Vice therefore is voluntary. (e) FREEDOM APPLIES EQUALLY TO VIRTUE AND TO VICE. Bat in reply to the objection of those who urge _that ' all men Eiini_at_±li3t_which_apj)ears to them the good, statement of the but have no co ntrol, oyer _tha.Jmp££SsiflBg-Piade argument of neces- Lipon_them, but the end which appears good to ^an^iTthedate of a, man reflects exactly the tendency of his own Ws own nature moral character '- there are two alternative jT'odtetd — inswers : alter.' ^- . If every ma,n is, in some sense, responsible ^ ^^^ ^^^^^ .^^^ to himself for his moral state, he will also be, flow from the moral in some senseT responsible for the impressions state which «s to a \,-VVco i.-- J 1 --;..• -c , certain degree svhich dilterent ends niake upon him. under our own con- 2. If, on the coiitrary, no oneis_resp.Qnsible to *™i- himself for his moral states, but the evil .whichja 2. Assuming the mandoes Is 'done_lhrough ignorance of his real ^^^^^ J^^^*^: end, and froni,ja„mistaken fancy that by the tipn as stated by course he takes the best.resultwill_Mattained ; f^ necessitarians . — -- . ~- ,. , their argument it, moreover, the inclination tor a particular proves too much— 'end' be not self-produced, but a man must be that neither virtue I -i.! ii p ii s T • 1 J. 1 — t,- t, nor Vice are volun- born_wrth_Jhe_3cmty_of.mor^^ tary. to d_iscriminate_Jhmga_.,xightly_.aiid — ^to— select the go od which is so la truth (and the ' nobly-born ' is one in whom this moral perception is perfectly ingrained, and that is the highest and noblest gift, and one which cannot possibly be acquired or learnt by ourselves, but such as nature ^ave it will be its character, and to have this characteristic truly and nobly engrafted in us is the perfect and genuine nobility) . . . if veritably such a view be true, wherein is virtue more voluntary than vice ? In either case, in that of the good man as in that of the bad man, the '• end ' which they follow appears to them I50 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. III. 7. (whether by nature or however it may be) the real end, and is assumed to be so accordingly ; and whatever actions they perform under any circumstances that may arise they view in connection with the end which is thus assumed. Under either of these alternatives — whether,-JthaLis_to say, the end of mo ral action do^ s not prRspnt itsplf Under either hypo- ■ thenShtlt does by an unalterable law, .but thesis virtue must ® ~" — «• =^ — -. — — ^ : ^-^i be regarded as sub- there IS au element m each impression which ject to the same dgpends upon a man's 'OWEi" Self; or wEefher, conditions as vice. , , , . i . i , i — — - — __ — ., ' though the ' end be a creation 01 natiirGTTret virtue is voluntary, inasmuch as the good man performs all that is subsidiary to that end of his own free will, — for reasons equally strong vice will also be voluntary. The element of freedom exists in the bad man no less than in the go od man, in the perf ormltnce of separate actions, eve n if n ot in the choice of the ' end.' If therefore the virtues are,' aslias been shown, voluntary, (inasmuch as we are ourselves 'joint-authors' of our actions, and jointly responsible for them, and the ' end ' which at any time we propose to ourselves, depends upon the fact that we are our- selves of a certain character or disposition), our vices will also be voluntary, formed as they are under analogous conditions. But this view is thought by some to be inconsistent with Reason, and that upon the following grounds. ' Vice,' they^ argue, ' arises from our setting before our actions an evil end ; and this mistake is caused by our fancying that, instead of being evil, the end is a good one : but the Impressions which our fancy makes upon us as to good and bad, are not under our own control : we all strive after what seems to us a good, and are not ourselves responsible for oui impressions. Consequently vice is not voluntary.' In vindication of cm- own theory we show that this objection applies with equal force to the case of virtue, and yet virtue is voluntary, since no one is blessed against his will. 1. If, on the one hand, the ignorance of what is the real good arises from the mental state of the agent being vicious, and knowledge of the real good is consequent upon the mental state of the agent being virtuous, it is evident that we grow to be vicious or virtuovis of our own free wiU, inasmuch as we are ourselves the causes of our mental states and responsible to ourselves for them. 2. If, on the contrary, the knowledge of the end is not dependent upon otii mental state, nor requires the concuiTenoe of the will, but is like good eye-sight or some other physical quality, which if a man have not, it is impossible for him to acquire it elsewhere, or to provide it for himself out of his own resources, but it is essential that a man should be hoi-n with a power of moral discrimiQatian if he is to have a chance of judging aright, (a moral insight which constitutes the only perfect and genuine nobility,) — even if this be true, still vice is voluntwy no less than virtue, even in this view of it : there is a knowledge of the end both in the bad man and in the good, whether it be owing to a man's mental state or to natm-e, that the knowledge of the tviw end is realized or misappre- hended. (1) If, on the one hand, we say that virtue is voluntary becaiffle, though the ' end ' is owing to nature and rightly perceived by the good man, yet the means subservient to the end depend upon a man's own self to choose or not, what is there to prevent vice being voluntary for the same reasons .' (2) If, 0° the other hand, virtue is voluntary because the knowledge of the good is derived Bk. III. 8.] Translation. \ 5 1 from virtuous states of wHoh we are ourselves, in a certain sense, ' joint authors,' by the same reasoning vice -will be voluntary also, because our ignorance of the true end is owing to our vicious habits. • (/) EECAPITULATION OP THE THEORY OF VIRTUE. To sum a£j!lfitt.,iuii~ theory of „t]ae~-Kirtues : it has been shown that : 1. Virtues are, in their generic character, 'mean-states' (to use a metaphorya533.Iiermanent^sStes of mind:' 2. They tend to reproduce the actions from which they were themselves formed, "such reproduction heing/ spontaneous and essential. 3. xhey are within our own power, and voluntarj-. 4. They conform' exactly to the standard which Right Reason lays down. [Here it must be noticed, that ' habitslare-aaLyxiluntary in the same sense that actions are. We are responsible for our actions from beginning to end, since we Note the different know every condition which surrounds them, ^^s™^^ °^ freedom But we have control^OTil2_oveL-±h&--begmnings of and to babits. our^abits, the gradual growth of particular tendencies being imperceptible in the moral, as in the physical organism ; yet, inasmuch as we had it in our power at the outset to shape the circumstances of our lives according to one use or another, the habits which result from our conduct therein will con- sequently be voluntary also.] Let us now take up-again jthe^subjectjof special virtues, and show what their nature is, what their subject-matter, and what the mode of their action. It will incidentally be shown also what is their number and variety. What, then, is virtue ? Generally, ajid in. brief, it has been described, (1) as a ' mean state,' lying midway, that is between two faulty states, and (2) as a formed or permanent attitude of mind. It has been further shown (3) xmder what influences it is produced, and that, after having acquired a virtue we continue to perform the same acts and to manifest the same activities as those were by which the virtue was iirst made habitual to us. It has been shown, lastly, that virtue is dependent upon ourselves and voluntary. [But it must be noticed that the action and the habit are not voluntary in the same sense nor in thje same degree, though both are, as has been proved, voluntary. When we perform our actions we know their bearings in every particular, and consequently we have control over them in the purest sense of the term — ^to do them or not, as we will, from beginning to end. Actions are therefore voluntary in an absolute sense. On the other hand, the ' habit ' is not known to the full extent : it is known not through itself, but through the 152 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk, III. 9. actions by which it is formed. We thoroughly Trndergtamd the actions by wUoli the habit is formed, but we cease to understand our actions when consolidated into habit. A precisely similar case occurs with physical debUities. Knowing the character of a particular diet, we consciously adopt it ; and weak health imper- ceptibly follows in its train. A habit, therefore, is called voluntary on account of the activities by which it is formed being voluntary — since, that is, it was possible for us not to have caused those activities.] We must now proceed at once to enumerate our mental states in specific detail, and show the character of each one, with what emotions of the soul it is concerned, and in what way it is formed. Jt will be further evident in the course of the discussion what is the number and vai'iety of these moral states. PART II.— EXAMINATION OP THE VIRTUES. ' A.— COURAGE. i. — The subject-matter of Courage defined. (a) COUKAGE IMPLIES FEAE, AND THINGS FEAEi'UL AKE SYNONY- MOUS WITH EVILS. Now it has been already explained that ' Courage ' is a mean state in regard to subjects of confidence or fear. c^Slith thin^ What we fear are of course the things which are fearful which are fearful, and things fearful are, to speak in general evSr^""' "'* terms, evils. Hence philosophers define fear as ' an anticipation of evil.' We fear, in fact, all things that are evils, such as infamy, poverty, disease, loss of friends, and death. Yet the brave man does not seem to be one who is courageous in face of every object of fear. There are certain evils which a man is positively bound to fear, and where fearfulness is honourable and bravery would be unseemly bravado, as in the case of infamy. The man who fears infamy is a man of honour and of self-respect: the man who does not shrink from infamy is destitute of all sense of shame ; though, by a rhetorical figure, the shamelegs~man is regarded by some people as a daring man, from the correspondence there is between them in that the brave man is, like hijai, in a sense, devoid of fear. / Poverty, on the other hand, is surely not a thing TOich a man ought to fear ; nor yet illness, nor in fact any of those evils which fall upon a man through no fault of his own nor through his own agency. Nevertheless, the man who is fearless of such evils as these, is not on that account brave ; and if we so describe him, it is by a rhetorical figure. There are cases where men are cowards in the crisis of battle, though liberal minded in money matters, and of cheerful coutitenance in view of financial ruin. Bk..lII. 9.] Translation. 153 Again, if a man is fearful of outrage upon his wife or children, or of the power of envy, or of other sinister influences, he is not assuredly a coward ; nor, on the other hand, is Re brave, if he is cheerful when on the point of being flogged. It was made evident in tlie course of our previous enumeration of the virtues that the suhject-matter of Courage is fear and confidence, and that it is a mean state in reference thereto, going beyond timidity and falling short of rashness. We will now show with what states it stands in contrast. Now fear is spoken of in relation to things which are fearful ; and, in a general sense, all things are fearful that are thought to be evils. Hence, in defining fear, men say that it is ' an expectation of evil.' We fear, in fact, whatever things are evil — disgrace, poverty, disease, friendlessness, death. But courage does not stand in opposition to iiccry object of fear, the brave man not being concerned with evely thing that is fearful. The brave man fears only what is it right for him to fear, and it is not right for him to fear all these things, but only some of them. To fear disgrace is honourable, not to fear it disgraceful : the one attitude is that of a man of self-respect, the other that of a shameless man. StiU, even the shameless man is called brave by a metaphor, in that he has some of the featiu'es of a brave man in not fearing everything, the brave man being one who, in a certain sense, is devoid of fear. Poverty, on the contrary, it is not right to fear, nor in fact any of those evils which do not befall us through our own fault nor through our own agency. But just as the man who does not fear what he ought to fear is not therefore brave (except by a rhetorical figure), so neither is the man who does not fear what he ought not to fear, on that account a brave man, and is only so styled in virtue of a kiad of resemblance between the two characters. Many there are who though fearless of such evils as poverty, and of stout hearts in view of the' loss of their possessions, are cowards amid the dangers of war. But just as the man who fears what he ought not to fear is not brave, so neither is the man who does not fear what he ought to fear brave. For instance, the man who does fear outrage upon his wife or children is not a coward, and the man who does not fear such a thing is not brave. Nor again is a man brave if he does not fear but rather is cheerful when upon the point of being flogged. Men are not brave for not fearing what they ought to fear. (S) DESCRIPTION OF THE EVILS WHICH CONCERN THE BRAVE MAN. What kinds of evils, then, are they, in which a brave man shows his courage ? Are they not the evils that are direst and worst ? No one is there so capable of peSiy ^^ mTni- sustaining things which are terrible as is the fested in presence brave man. But of all things terrible death is LthtglorioT.^ the worst : it is indeed, the extreme of evils, since to the dead man, as it seems, nothing further can befall, whether good or evU. Yet it is not death in any and every form in face of which the brave man would seem to show his courage; not, for example, in face of death at sea, or in sickness. In what kinds of death, then, will his bravery be shown ? Must it not be in such as are most glorious ? and the most glorious are those which befall men in war, since war involves the greatest and most glorious hazards. 154 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. III. 9. Corresponding witTi tWs idea of perfect bravery are the honours paid to warriors both in free cities and in the Courts of Princes. A man will be called ' brave,' therefore, in the true and proper sense of the term, when he is fearless in regard to a noble death, or under instant pressure of evils which have death in their train; and such are emphatically the accidents and terrors of war. Still, even in a storm at sea or in sickness, the brave man is void of fear ; yet his courage in a storm is not like that of sailors. The brave man at such times has despaired of safety and is troubled at such a mode of death. Sailors, on the other hand, are coniident from the experience which they have had of previous storms. Moreover, the circumstances in which brave men exhibit their courage, are such as give room for prowess and make it glorious to die ; but in such disasters as shipwreck or pestilence neither of these conditions is found. The brave man, therefore, is one who does not fear the worst of evils : no one has such powers of endurance as he. Yet he is not on every occasion courageous to the same degree. There are certain terrors which make even the brave man quail through the mode in which they are brought upon him. For instance, death is thought to be the last extremity of evil, because it is an end of life, and it is impossible for anything further to betide a man when he is dead, whether good or evil, and therefore it is thought to be the worst and most terrible evil both to the good and also to the evil. But though the death which ensues from disgraceful causes is a thing which the brave man would fear, on the other hand, the death which is brought on by the highest causes, such" as that which befalls a man in war, is no longer terrible, but a thing very greatly to be coveted. The death again, which befalls a man in sickness or at sea will be terrible to the brave man, in so far as it has not come upon him on account of some grand cause, but on no account fearful in the proportion in which it is painful. A man may be called ' brave,' therefore, when he is fearless in regard to a noble death, (or at any rate a death that is not ignoble,) and in regard to the terrors which bring death in their train, coming with sudden visitation upon him, such as are the circumstances of war. The man who is resolute under perils which unexpectedly encompass him. affords manifest proof that he has advanced to = point where coui'age is habitual and natural to him. When a man endures a death that is noblest for man, then he is bravo in the fullest sense of the tenn. This principle applies also to the case of honours. When honours involve nothing sacred nor permanent, as in the case of honours con- ferred at the Courts of Tyrants, the brave man will despise them ; but when honours are constitutional and just, as they are in well-ordered States, the brave man will covet them. Sailors are also fearless in regard to death, but not in the same manner as the brave are. Brave men seem to be resolute under such circmnstances because they have absolutely despaired of safety ; whereas sailors are so because they expect, on the ground of past experience, that they wiU survive the dangers of the sea. In fact, however, it is impossible to show bravery in the perfect sense of the term under such circumstances as a storm at sea. A man shows true bravery where there is need of vigour or of spirit, and where death is grand aad ennobling. But in a storm or in a plague such considerations have no place: death is not then the occasion of any advantage to others, nor can we display' any spirit or vigour in face of it. Bk. III. 10.] Translation. 155 ii. — Various manifestations of Courage, (a) THE TRUE ' MEAN ' OF COURAGE DEFINED^ But what is fearful is not the same under all circumstances, nor to all persons, though of course there is a form of fear which we speak of as 'past human en- '^^ ?**';'^*^'^, "^ ■, , T , 111, -11, what IS fearful is durance, and such as would be terrible to any not an absolute but one who was in his right senses. Still, looking » relative one, and to things which are fearful and yet within the Eeasonr™"° limits of endurance, these differ in magnitude and in their relative degrees of intensity, as also do things which inspire confidence. In face even of these the brave man, though dauntless and undaunted, has still the feelings of a man : he will not be unmoved at the sight of things terrible, though his fear will be tempered by regard for the fitness of things and kept within the limits which Eeason will allow, his aim being the attainment of honour as the ideal of virtue. Yet it is possible to entertain fears of this kind excessively or insufficiently, and again to regard things which are not fearful as though they were. Of the ^^^^^ °* """"'^^ errors committed in these respects, one form arises from the fear being an unworthy one, another from the fear being immoderate, another from its being inopportune, and so on through manifold conditions. The same principle applies to the circumstances upon which we ground confidence. That man therefore is a brave man who endures hardship or yields to fear when it is right to do so, though always with a noble motive and to a proper The conduct of the degree and on fittingoccasions. Under opposite ^XS'tftt conditions again he is equally confident. In a ideal of Keason. word, the brave man is one whose inward feelings and outward actions are in harmony with a true dignity, and with the standard which Eight Keason prescribes. Now the ' end ' of every activity, (in order to be either virtuous or vicious,) must be one which corresponds with the fixed attitude of mind in the agent. To the mind of the brave man the display of his bravery is a source of pride and honour. The ' end ' of his every activity, therefore, is a feeling of honour, since the character of every action is determined by its ' end.' It follows that the motive for which the brave man incurs perils, and performs the a(its of bravery, is a sense of honour or a feeling of noble pride. The brave man, therefore, does not always hold the same attitude in regard to things which are fearful. Some things are more terrible to some men than to 156 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. III. 10. others. Men who are fond of money fear the loss of their possessions above all things ; others who care most of all for their reputations, fear disgrace more than anything ; and so through many varieties. There are things, again, which aie feared in different degrees by different persons or not at all ; and there are things which there is no mortal who does not fear, as for instance evils which transcend human endurance, like visitations of heaven, earthquakes or inundations of the sea — such things being terrible to all who are in their right mind. But though the brave man fears, his fear is always fitting and seemly, and in accord with what Reason enjoins, and honour is invariably the motive which actuates him. Honour is regarded by the good man as the piinciple which should regulate aU his personal feelings, and as the ' end' at which all his actions should aim ; and accordingly that is the motive which all excellence sets before it. Yet these calamities of nature do not affect aU men with the same degree of fear, some men being more afraid of them than others. Similarly also, the distresses which do not transcend our powers of endurance are not equally terrible to all men, as disgrace, poverty and the like ; and the good man wiU only be afraid of them when it is right to be so, and then only in a proper manner, as has been explained. Herein is the reason why the bad man errs : — he does not fear in a proper manner, nor at a proper season, nor from a proper motive ; and similarly in showing confidence he does not do so in a fitting manner nor at a fitting season. The man, therefore, is a brave man who shows fear or confidence at proper objects and with a proper motive and at a proper time ; his fear or confidence being regulated by what is fitting and by the standard which the " law ' or ' idea' of courage lays down. That is in fact the ' end ' of every activity in accordance with virtue — that it should be displayed in accordance with the conception of viitue as a formed or permanent state of mind. For example, acts confonnable to justice have as their ' end ' their being performed in accordance with the con- ception or standard of Justice as a pennaneut state of mind. In a general sense, the end of every action whatever that is virtuous, is the realization of a noble ideal (to koKov). The particular ideal which is before the mind of the brave maa is the conception Of bravery ; that before the mind of the just man, is the con- ception of justice : and similarly mth the other virtues. That indeed is the rationale of aU our actions — that they should be brought into conformity with a fixed state of the chai'acter. The limitations to which an action conforms (and which constitute its definition or essential notion) are identical with its ' end.' The brave man, therefore, takes his stand within the sphere of what is fitting and seemly. (^) MODES IN WHICH THE IDEAL OF COUEAGE IS VITIATED. Of the characters which pass the limits of this ideal, the man who fails through inability to fear has no distinc- Types of moral tive name. [As has been previously explained, of comrage w^'^^ ^^^^^ '^i'® many aspects of moral character which 1. Insensibility; have no Special name.] Such an one must he classed as a kind of madman or as a man devoid of human feelings — if, that is, he fears nothing, neither earth- quake nor the stormy sea, as they say is the case with the Celts. The man again who transgresses in being over-confident in regard to things which are fearful, is reckless; 2. Eeckiessuess ; ^^^ ^^ reckless man seems to be also a braggart and one who arrogates a claim to bravery which he does not possess. Such an one is anxious to appear to the world as resolute Bk.lII. 11.] Translation. 157 in regard to things fearful as the brave man is in reality : in fact lie jposes in the attitude of a brave man in such points as he can. Hence reckless men are as a rule, for all theft courageousness, cowards at heart : though they keep up a reckless mien in times of peril, they never stand the actual shock of danger. The man, again, who errs through excess of fear is a coward. Every mark of cowardice, — unworthy yielding to fear, an extravagant sense of fear, and similar ^' ^°^^^'<^«- excesses, are all found in such a character. He is at the same time deficient in the feeling of confidence, though he more readily betrays himself in pain and grief. He is therefore destitute, also, of hope, being as he is afraid of everything. The brave man is the exact opposite, a feeling of confidence being the mark of a hopeful man. So then the brave man has the same sphere of action as one who is reckless or a coward ; but these opposite characters comport themselves very difierently Practical contrasts therein. Those who are reckless or cowards go ancTitTextremesr beyond the proper limits or fall short of them, whereas the brave man holds a calm and even tenor. Eeckless men, again, are impetuous and precipitate, and before the danger comes they are eager to meet it, yet in the actual crisis they shrink away. On the other hand brave men are swift and keen enough in action, but calm and undemonstrative until it is time to act. Courage, therefore, is (consistently with the description of it given above) ' a true and virtuous frame of mind in reference to things which are grounds for either confidence or fear ' under the limi- tations which have been already laid down. The courageous man freely makes choice of peril or woe and submits to its consequences, because he has a noble pride in suffering and thinks scorn of a selfish shrinking from the sacrifices of duty. [But as for courting voluntary death with no motive beyond that of escaping from poverty or love or some other affliction — that is not the part of a brave man but rather of a coward. It is sheer effeminacy to shrink from a thing because it is difficult to bear; and the suicide meets his fate not because he thinks it noble to die, but because he hopes to escape from a present pang.] Such then are the more characteristic features of courage. Of those wlio pass the limits of this ideal, the man who errs by an extravagance of fearlessness, has no distinctive name. [As has been previously explained, there are many aspects of moral character which have no special name.] Stich an one may, however, be styled a madman, or one devoid of human feelings — if, that is, there is nothing that he fears, not even earthquake or stormy sea, as they say the case is with the Celts. 158 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. III. 11. The man, again, who, though in a less degree, transgresses in being over-con- fident in regard to things which are fearful, is reckless ; and the reckless man seems to be also a braggart and one who arrogates a claim to bravery which he does not possess. In fact he only slwnis to be brave : he is anxious only to appear in the eyes of the world as resolute as the brave man reaUy is, and 'he: ■poses in the attitude of a brave man in such points as he is able. Hence reckless men are, as a rule, cowards at heart : though they keep up a reckless mien in critical times, they never stand the actual shock of danger. The man, again, who eiTs through excess of fear is a coward, because he fears objects unworthy of fear, and that to an excessive degree. He is at the same time deficient in the feeling of confidence and extravagant in his griefs, and despond' ing withal, as fearful of everything. The brave man is the exact opposite : he is a man of hopeful temperament, his confidence being derived from his hoping ever for what is good. So then the brave man has the same sphere of action as the man who is reck- less, and the coward, — the sphere of what causes confidence or fear. But their relations therein are not identical, and they comport themselves very differently therein. Those who are reckless or cowards go beyond the line or fall short of it, whereas the brave man holds a calm and even tenor of life, and remains firm to the standard of what is fitting. Reckless men, again, are impetuous and precipitate, and before dangers come rush out to meet them, and are exceedingly solicitous of troubles to overcome ; but when they find themselves in the midst thereof, they i-ush away with a bound. Brave men show just the opposite' temperament : in the actual crisis they are swift and keen of puipose, but till the moment of action comes they keep quiet. Courage, therefore, is (consistently with the definition of it given above) 'a true and equable frame of mind in reference to things which inspire fear or confidence' in accord with an ideal standard. The courageous man makes his choice of peril and woe, and submits to the consequences involved, because he feels a noble pride in suffering for righteousness' sake, and thinks scorn of any shrinking from the sacrifices which duty demands. [But as for being desirous of meeting death on account of poverty or love — that is not a mark of courage but rather of cowardice. To try to avoid a thing because it is hard to bear — that is a mark of effeminacy and moral emptiness. Those who adopt such a death as that of the suicide, do not do so because it is noble, but because it is a relief from an evil which they are not able to bear ; and such a frame of mind is an indication of cowai-dice.] Such then are the more general features of Courage. iii. — Five less-perfect forms of Courage. A. — THE COURAGE OF SELF-INTEREST. ' There are yet other forms of courage as they are reputed to be, which fall under five groups, the first being the filner^prori- ^°"^^°® inspired by society. This form has the mates to true nearest resemblance to true courage. courage, though its j^ow it would Seem that the motives for which motive IS mere re- ,i •,• i i , ,,. gard for conse- the Citizens Undergo dangers are the penalties quencesratherthan inflicted by the laws upon cowards and the taunts dimity. ° * ™* of tlisir fellows and, withal, the honours to be won by bravery. Hence men appear to be the bravest in states where cowards are visited with infamy and brave men are in high esteem. Such is the feeling which inspires the Bk. III. 11.] Translation. i^g heroes whom Homer paints — Diomede for example, or Hector, who says ' First will Polydamas hurl scornful reproaches upoa me ; ' and Diomede says, ' Hector in time to come will say of me haranguing among the Trojans : Tydides by my hand . . . . ' This kind of bravery has a very close resemblance to the true courage described above, inasmuch as its actuating motive is a virtuous one : — it is inspired, that is, by a sense of shame and by a yearning for what is noble in the form of honour, and by a shrinking from reproach as from a thing disgraceful. We may also range under the same category soldiers forced by their commanders to be brave ; but such men are inferior to the former, inasmuch as they do not ^ ' pj^^af "^o°! act bravely from a sense of shame, but through straint must be physical fear, and it is not the disgrace, but the "^^ "^^^^^ *^'" penalty of cowardice which they shun. Such men are literally _/brceo? by their officers to be brave, as by the menace which Hector employs — ' Whomsoever I espy shirking in the rear of the fight, Nought shall avail him to escape the dogs.' Such also is the practice of those who lead the lines, since they strike their men if they begin to waver ; and such too is the intention of officers who range their men in front of trenches and similar outposts : they all strive to make their soldiers brave of necessity. Yet to be truly brave a man should be so not from compulsion, but actuated by a sense of noble pride. There are yet other forms of Courage, so reputed, whieh fall under five heads. The first of these is the courage inspired by society, in virtue whereof the citizens encounter dangers on behalf of the state, in view of the penalties inflicted by the laws on cowardice, and of the taunts of their fellows and of the honours conferred on the brave. Men seem indeed to be bravest in states where cowards are visited with Infamy, and brave men are in high esteem. Such is the character of those of whom Homer sings in his poems, for example Diomede, or Hector, who says — ' First will Polydamas hurl scornful reproaches upon me ; ' and Diomede says, ' Hector in time to come will say of me haranguing among the Trojans ; Tydides by my hand . . . . ' This kind of courage resembles the true courage described above, inasmuch as its motive is in a way a virtuous, one (just as the motive of true courage is a noble pride). The citizens act bravely from a sense of shame and a yearning for what is noble, and to avoid reproach as a thing disgraceful : the consideration which moves them to encounter dangers is a feeling of respect for the laws and of yearning for distinction. Inferior to this form of bravery is that which those exhibit who are compelled ]6o The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk.iir. n. by their generals to encoimter hardships, and to behave themselves resolutely in face of dangers. It is inferior to that fonn of courage which comes from the action of society, inasmuch as it arises from the influences of fear and not from love of good : those who show courage of this pattern do so to avoid the pain rather than the disgrace of cowardice. They are brave because they are literally compelled to be so by their officers, as may be seen in the menaces which Hector uses : ' Whomsoever I espy shirking in the rear of the fight, Nought shall avail him to escape the dogs . . . . ' Even though the generals be not themselves present to enforce their warnings and personally compel their soldiers to endure perils, yet they effect the same result by inspiring them with terror of conduct through which their comrades have often been scourged for abandoning their ranks. Thus, they seem to be brave from necessity ; but to be truly brave a man ought to choose bravery of his own free wiU — not from necessity, but because it is a noble thing to be brave. B. — THE COURAGE OF EXPERIENCE. The experience -whicli a man has in respect of special dangers seems also to be a form of courage ; and it was fedge?Hke thM ^f ™ j.i. j t. j.i_ pleasures are, in prOVmce must DC lurtlier narrOWed by the ex- certain cases, out clusion of Certain bodily sensations. temperance,°rj.,° !• When men feel pleasure in the impressions 1. The pleasures of which come through the sight, beautiful colours' ^^ ' and forms and paintings, they are not called either temperate or intemperate for so doing ; although it would seem possible even in these pleasures to maintain a proper moderation, or to give them an insufficient or else an undue pro- minence. 2. Again, in pleasures which come through hearing the same truth holds good. We do not call men ' intem- Boimd^ ^^^^"^^^ "* perate' who take extravagant delight in music or in acting, nor yet ' temperate ' though their pleasure therein be moderate and right. 3. Nor, again, do we call those who take pleasure in indulging the sense of smell, either temperate or intem- 3. The pleasures of perate — except through its accidental associations ; scent (except where % i-ijn -; l e associated with lor example, we do not caU men mtemperate tor other pleasures delighting in the sweet fragrance of fruit or of w jc ne on- y^ggg qj, ^f incense, but rather those whose delight is in unguents and condiments, these latter being the things in which intemperate men deliglat, since by such means a recollection is aroused within them of the things for which their passions crave. In support of this view of smelling, one may see men of different temperaments all delighting in the odour of food when they are hungry ; yet to delight in such odours is, pro tanto, a sign of a sensuous nature, savoury smells being desired by the sensual Bk. III. 13.] Translation. 169 man for their own sake. But among animals generally there is no pleasure arising from these sensations, except through ac- cidental associations. Dogs do not delight in the scent of hares but in the eating of them, though the scent has created an appetite. Nor does the lion rejoice at the lowing of the ox, but at the banquet of his flesh : by its lowing he has become aware that the ox is near, and hence seems to rejoice at the mere sound. Similarly the lion does not rejoice at having seen or found stag or wild goat, except in the belief that he will gain a feast thereby. Temperance, therefore, is not concerned with pleasures of the mind, but with the pleasures of the body. But even certain bodily pleasures are excluded from its range. Those, for instance, who delight in things which are pleasant to behold, beautiful colours or drawings or paintings, are not caUed either temperate or intemperate ; nor are they who are enamoured of certain sounds or musical airs, nor are they who love sweet smells. Yet ia regard to all these matters there are states of mind which are ideally best and fitting, and there are states which go beyond or fall short of a perfect standard ; but, notwithstanding, we do not call those who preserve the ideal mean ' temperate,' nor those who violate that mean ' intemperate.' In regard, however, to the pleasures connected with smeUiug, if we delight in the fragrance of apples or of roses or of incense, we are not called intemperate. If on the other hand we delight in the odours of ointments and condiinents, we are called intemperate ; but even then only from accidental associations — since, that is, these are things in which intemperate men delight because, by means thereof, a recoUeotion is aroused within them of things for which their passions crave. One may see, indeed, that all men, not only the iutemperate, delight in the smell of food when they are hungry. Hence it is clear that those who take pleasure in smeUs of that kind, only find their pleasure therein from accidental associations — because, that is, a recollection is awakened within them of the food and trifles generally in which sensual men delight. Neither in man, therefore, nor in any living creature is there any pleasure consequent upon the exercise of the senses enumerated above, except from casual associations. (I am now referring to pleasures in which the temperate and the dissolute man display themselves.) Dogs, for example, though they delight ia the smell of hares, yet that ia not for the sake of the scent simply, but in view of food foreseen : they pursue because they have gained from the scent an iastiuct of preying. Similarly the Hon does not delight in the scent or the lowing of the ox, biit in the eating of his flesh : only he perceives from the lowing, that his prey is near. He does not delight simply that he has seen or found a stag or wUd goat, but because he will gain food thereby. (c) TEMPEEANCE IS SPECIALLY CONCEENED WITH THE PLEASUEES OF TOUCH AiTD TASTE, The conclusion is that the pleasures with which temperance and intemperance are specially concerned, are those bodily pleasures which all living creatures share The sensations in with men, and which are consequently admitted temperance ilspt to be slavish and bestial — the pleasures, that "iaiiy necessary, is,' of touch and of taste. '^^^tlf *"''' Practically, however, men are found to indulge 1 70 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. III. 13. the sense of taste only to a slight extent or not at all. Taste is th h taat ■ f *^^ determination of questions of flavour, and is less the occasion of used chiefly by those who have to taste wines or temptation than season dishes. But men do not generally take delight in mere tasting, certainly not those who are sensual, but rather in that full enjoyment which comes en- tirely through touch, and is experienced in eating and drinking, and in the so-called ' pleasures of love.' Hence the wish which the noted epicure Philoxenus the son of Eryxis uttered, that * his throat might become longer than that of a crane ' — such was the delight he took in the pleasures of touch. Now this sense of touch, from the indulgence of which intem- perance arises, is the most widely diffused of all Touch is the most the senses ; and rightly does it seem to be Ssel!"fbut Stigmatised, because it does not belong to us so the pleasure it gives far as wc are men, but so far as we are animals, is of au pleasures rp^ ^^^ delight in pleasures of this kind and to least worthy of , . , ,, ° ,.,..,, . „ man. cherish them exceedingly, is simply the sign of a brutal nature. [But of course such of the plea- sures of touch as are really liberal, are exempted from this con- demnation ; as, for instance, the pleasure felt in the gymnasia from rubbing and heating. The touch from which the intemperate man derives pleasure does not extend to the whole body, but only to certain parts of it.] The pleasures, therefore, with which temperance and intemperance are con- cerned are the pleasures which we share with, all living creatures — the pleasures, that is, of touch and taste. Intemperate men are, therefore, seen to be of a bestial and slavish nature — in that they weaMy yield to allurements in which wild beasts find their pleasure. Generally, however, they find their pleasure in touch rather than in taste : per- haps, indeed, it were more correct to say that they do not delight in taste at all, but simply in touch. Men are not intemperate simply for taking delight in pleasures generally, but for their delight in eating and drinking. They do not delight in such things as things to be tasted (the proper business of tasting being to dis- criminate flavours, a thing chiefly done by those who test the quality of wines and prepare seasoned dishes); but rather as things to be touched. Hence, the wish whicE that noted epicure Philoxenus, the son of Eryxis, uttered, that ' his throat might become longer than a crane's,' — such was the pleasure he experienced in the tonch of his favourite relishes. Among all the senses, that of touch is the one most widely diffused : it is, in fact, by a kind of touch that all the senses arouse our consciousness. It is there- fore this sense of touch that forms the special province wherein sensuality is dis- .played : and rightly does it seem to be stigmatised because it belongs to us, not in so far as we are men, but in so far as we are brutes. To delight in pleasures of such a type, and to covet them above all things, is the sign of a bestial nature. [Still, there are certain liberal pleasures, even in respect of touch, of which the sensual man deprives himself: such are the pleasures which are experienced in the gymnasia through rubbing and heating. The pleasure of the dissolute man is not diffused throughout his body, but is confined to certain parts.] Bk. III. 13.] Translation. 171 ii. — Various Manifestations of Temperance. (a) TEMPERANCE VIEWED IN RELATION TO PLEASURES AND DESIRES. Among our desires there are some wliicli seem to be common to all men, and others which seem to be special to individuals and acquired. _ :h^:h"te"::pe'rc: As an instance of our common desires there is has to control are the natural craving for food. Every one when onl^ac'uir^d''^^'' exhausted desires food either to eat or to drink, and at times both ; and, as Homer says, those who are young and vigorous need rest and repose. But as for the particular food which different men require under different circumstances — that is another matter, men's tastes being as different as their needs : hence, each man thinks that a particular kind is specially ' his own.' Nevertheless, certain things are natural and universal: though particular things are pleasant to particular persons, there are certain things which all men feel to be more pleasurable than ordinary things are. In regard, however, to the common desires of nature few men err, and then, only in one respect — that of exces- sive indulgence. To swallow anything which are innocenttsoept comes to hand, or to drink until one is over- ■"'lien indulged to charged, is to violate the law of nature by satiety, ^^^-^^^s^"* «^'=««=- natural desires being the satisfying of real wants. Hence, gluttons are called ' slaves of their belly,' since they try to fill it beyond what is due — such the degradation to which men of thoroughly slavish tastes are brought. On the other hand, in regard to the pleasures special to indi- viduals, many are they who err, and manifold the occasions thereof. The reasons why men are (2.) Desires which called ' lovers of pleasure ' being, either that they acquire "fw ^our^ delight in what they ought not, or that they selves, are as mani- indulge themselves extravagantly or in improper forms of si"^ ^''^ modes, or that they follow the multitude to evil in all and each of these particulars, the intemperate fall into error : they take pleasure in things which they ouo-ht not, as being things which are hateful, and, where there are objects in which they may lawfully take pleasure, they indulge themselves to an extravagant extent, and as foolishly as do the multitude. It is clear, therefore, that intemperance is an excess in reference to pleasures, and a thing which is morally censurable. 172 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IILU. But since we have in natural sequence to treat of tlie desires, we must explain in what senses the term ' desire ' is used. One form of desire is common to all men, and natural ; another form is special to individuals, and acquired. An instance of a common desire is the striving for sustenance, either solid or liquid, when we find om'selves in need thereof. An in- stance of a special or acquired desii-e is the striving after some particular kind of sustenance iu preference to any other. This latter case — that of individual striv- ing after a particular thing — is neither natural nor universal. All men do not strive after the same things, nor to the same extent : some men yearn for one thing, some for another ; and those who strive after the same objects do not do so to the same extent, but some are more intently eager than others. Hence a desire of this kind is not universal nor natural, iu the absolute sense of the term, but acquired and formed from ideas which we have ourselves adopted. Still, in a certain sense, even an acquired desire is natural to a man, inasmuch as every man forms desires in a way that is consequent on the bias of his own nature. In regard, however, to natural desires, there are few who err thereia, and then only in a single way — when they indulge desires of this kind to an extent in excess of what is fitting ; when, for example, they eat more than is sufficient, as gluttons do who gorge their natural appetites beyond what is fitting. Such is the state to which men of brutal tastes are reduced. On the other hand, iu the case of desires which are personal and acquired, many are they who err, and many the forms their error takes. There are indeed many varieties of food and of drink and of clothing, and of other thiags which are natu- rally objects of desire ; and hence there are many ways in which men err in regard to desires of this kind, whether by taking pleasm-e in improper objects, or doing so to a greater degree than the majority. Now sensual men err in each and all of these particulars. Since they take pleasure in improper objects, though on occasions they may make choice of such pleasures as are seemly, they indulge in them to an extent beyond what is fitting, or what public opinion approves. It is clear, then, that Intemperance is an excess in regard to pleasures, and a thing that is morally censurable. {b) TEMPEEANCE VIEWED IN RELATION TO PAIN. In regard to pains, on the other hand, the attitude of the temperate man is different from that of the brave TOmitant of Intern- ^^'^ ' ^ ^^'^ ^® °°* Called temperate on the grotind perance, as being of Ms enduring pain, nor intemperate from want aninsatiableyearn- ^f endurance ; but he is intemperate from the mg for pleasure. . n i p ■> • p -i- , , ■ i ^ • griei he feels in laumg to attam to what is pleasant (pleasure being the cause which produces the pain in him), and he is temperate if he does not grieve at the privation of pleasure and at the self-restraint involved. So then the intemperate man is one who yearns for all pleasures or for such as are most vivid, and is driven along by his passion so as to choose his own gratification above all things. Hence he is positively pained as well when he is debarred from pleasure as when he is yearning for it — appetite being attended with pain. Yet it seems a marvellous thing that a man should feel pain for the sake of pleasure. In regard to pains, on the other hand, the case of Temperance is not parallel to that of cowardice and bravery (cowardice consisting, as was shown, in not Bk. III. 14.] Translation. 173 submitting to hardships nor brooking it) : Temperance is not the beariag of pain nor is intemperance a shrinking from pain. But intemperance is shown in regard to pains when a man grieves, at failing to attain wh^ is pleasant, to an extravagant degree and in an improper manner ; and, conversely, temperance is shown when a man grieves thereat only so far as is right and shows his grief only at proper objects and in a proper manner, and when the absence of pleasant things causes him no kind of pain. The sensual man yearns after everything that is pleasant or what is most vividly so, and is led about by his desires, so that he chooses things which are pleasant in preference to everything else. Consequently he feels pain in being deprived of things upon which he has set his heart, desire being attended with pain. It seems thus a, marvellous thing that a man should feel pain in a matter of pleasm-e, and that pleasure should be the cause of its opposite 1 Temperance, therefore, is an excess in regard to pleasure, as has been shown. (c) ASCETICISM AN tOSTDUE AVOIDANCE OF PLEASURE. As for men falling sliort in regard to pleasures, and taking less delight therein than is -natural — such a class is absolutely unknown. Asceticism of this extreme J^"f *f J^m "'such kind is, indeed, contrary to human nature : even pleasures as are irrational creatures distinguish their food, taking j.^"^^^ iMtlncts^f pleasure in one kind and rejecting another. If our human nature, there be a man to whom nothing is sweet, and to ^'^'^ is practically 1 TTI TiriRSi n I ft whom one taste is not different from another, such an one would be far from being a man. But such a class has not met with a special name, since, practically, it does not exist. The corresponding defect has no name to distinguish it, since it is absolutely unknown in fact. As for men being deficient in matters of pleasure and desiring pleasure less than is fitting, such a class simply does not exist. Asceticism of this extreme typ^ is, in fact, outside the pale of human nature : even in-ational animals distinguish between different kinds of food, delighting in what is pleasant and loathing what is unpleasant. If there be anyone who thinks nothing sweet, nor recognises any distinction between what is pleasant and what is unpleasant, such an one wHl be far from being a man. Defect and excess in regard to pleasures, then, are both alike morally faulty. (d) CHARACTEEISTICS OF A PEEFECT TEMPERANCE. But the temperate man holds a mid-course in reference to self- indulgence and self-restraint. He takes no pleasure in the things which most delight the in- The good man who temperate man, but is rather grieved and wearied tSugh contoUs thereat. , He will have no pleasure that is never guilty of un- unlawful: nor will he indulge himself even in 'awful excess nor ' ° __ . of undue cravmg lawful pleasures to an excessive extent. He is for pleasure : not pained when pleasures are denied him, nor JWii ^\ '^ s'^d ,1,, ., t It • 1 ,™ have pleasures, does he keep cravmg to supply their loss, except he does not grieve to some slight degree. He never pursues pleasure ^* ^^"^"^ ^°^- 1 74 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. III. 15. more than is becoming, nor at unseasonable times ; nor does he ever violate therein the conditions of a sober moderation. The rule of the temperate man, in fact, is this. In moderation and in a becoming manner, he will strive to gain whatever is pleasant and conducive to his health and well-being ; aye, and he will strive for other pleasures too, when they do not interfere with his higher interests, and are not in excess of his means to afford. The man who indulges himself at the expense of future loss, loves pleasures more than they are worth ; and that is not like the character of the temperate man, since he loves pleasures only so far as Right Eeason allows. The virtuous attitude of mind in reference to these matters is Temperaaofl, The temperate man is one who has no pleasure in the things in which the intemperate man finds his keenest delight, but, on the contraiy, is rather grieved and wearied at everything in which it is not right to find pleasure. When he does feel pleasure, he does not indulge the f eeUng. in excess of what is fitting j nor if pleasures are withheld from him, does he grieve thereat, nor does he keep craving to supply their loss ; — or, if he has a desire for them, he indulges it only in moderation and not more than is right, nor at unseasonable times. But such things as tend to promote his health and well-being, and are at the same time pleasant, or such things which are only in the very slightest degree detrimental to his health and well-being, — for all such things the temperate man does strive, with moderation, however, and in a proper manner. A man indulges his desires contrary to what is fitting when he desires pleasures which are found to be detrimental to his life, or at any rate to his well-being. The temperate man has a character very different to that, and regulates his desires by the standard of Bight Beason. iii. — Subsidiary Considerations of Temperance and Intemperance, (a) COMPARISON BETWEEN INTEMPERANCE AND COWARDICE. Intemperance has a closer affinity to a voluntary act than cowardice has. The motive of intemperance is Intemperance in- pleasure, the motive of cowardice pain; and of degree of self-con- these two motives pleasure is an object of desire, sciousness and of pain an object of aversion. Pain again distracts will than cowardice , ■, .1 , p., i-i-i doga. ■ and weakens the nature of the man who is subject to it; whereas pleasure acts in no such way. Hence pleasure is regarded as a more culpable motive, since it is easier for a man to become habituated to refrain from pleasure than it is for him to endure pain. Many such cases occur in actual experience where self-restraint is easily learnt, and the practice thereof attended by no danger. But in the case of cowardice the reverse is true, the practice of courage being painful and full of risk. But it would seem that cowardice as a mental state is not voluntary in the same sense nor in the same degree as single ada Bk. i;[1. 15.] Translation. 175 of cowardice are. In itself cowardice is painless and therefore voluntary ; but particular circumstances of danger so utterly distract a man through the intensity 0^ Yet cowardice is pain involved, that he turns coward for the [."^TeTesrft rf a moment, throws away his arms and in other formed state of ways acts unseemly. Hence particular acts of '^^^' cowardice seem at times to be compulsory. In the case of the intemperate man, on the contrary, particular acts of self-indulgence are voluntary, since he feels a desire for them and strives to attain the means for them. But since no man feels a desire to be intemperate, intemperance in itself, as a mental state, is not voluntary. But since intemperance aa well as cowardice is voluntary, we must examine whether they are both voluntary in the same degree. It would appear that these states are not parallel, but that intemperance is more voluntary than cowardice. Now the cause of cowardice is pain : we become cowaids from being afraid of pain ; but it is pleasure that produces intemperance. Of these two motives pleasure is an object of desire, pain an object of aversion ; but what we do for the sake of what is desirable is more voluntary than what is caused through a thing that is an object of aversion. Again, pain distracts and weakens the nature of the man who is under the influence of it, whereas pleasm-e has no result of the kind whatever. Consequently intemperance is more reprehensible than cowardice. Since a man is praised or blamed on the score of voluntary good or evil, it is evident that good and evil are respectively more praised or blamed iu exact proportion as each is more or less voluntary. Again, it is an easier task to shake off intemperance than cowardice. The processes of habituation by which tendencies of this kind are rectified, are in the case of cowardice fraught with danger (the practice of courage in war, or in the midst of similar perils by means whereof we learn to throw off our cowardice, being itself a danger, or very like one), whereas on the other hand lessons of self-control are absolutely free from perilous consequences. The inference is that intemperance is more voluntary than cowardice. But it would seem that cowardice in itself is voluntary in u different sense to that in which special acts of cowardice are voluntary. Cowardice in itself — that is to say as a mental state — is painless : by nothing painful are we com- pelled to be cowards ; hence cowardice is the more voluntary. But as for deeds done by reason of our cowardice — deeds done under the influence of pain or fear — we do them under the influence of a kind of constraint which drives out of us all self-control, and induces us to throw down our arms and in other respects to behave ourselves unseemly. For this reason special acts of cowardice are less voluntary than the mental state itself. In the case of intemperance, however, the reverse is true. No one desires intemperance for its own sake, nor does any one wish to be intemperate. But as for particular acts of intemperance, we do them with real enthusiasm. Hence intemperance in itself is less voluntary than specific acts thereof. (6) COMPAKISON BETWEEN INTEMPERANCE AND THE FAULTS OF CHILDHOOD. We also apply the term ' intemperate ' to characterise the faults of children, seeing that they bear a kind of re- 5^5 „at„e of in- semblance thereto. Whether intemperance be temperance maybe 176 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. III. 15. illustrated by its derived from youtliful weakness or mce versd, is etymology. quite immaterial to the present question, though grammatically it is evident that the first alternative is the true one. Indeed the transition of thought from the one case to the other seems to have been not inaptly made. A Temperance is syn- temper ought to be ' chastcned ' or curbed, which 'chastisement,' strives after things that are base and admits of ' discipline,' or j-^qIj ^ud rapid growth, and that is the character 'correction'; and ■, .^ n • , i. 3 ■ j •nj? the intemperate both of intemperate desires and specially of man is therefore children. Desito is the law by which children one whose desires ,. i ,1 ■ jr ^ • 1. are not 'chastened' live, and the craving for pleasure is most con- but are insubordi- picuously exhibited among them. troUed!""^ "°°°°' ^^ ^^^^ ^^^^ temperament be not submissive nor brought under control, it will grow to awoful extent, since there is in the mind of the foolish, an insatiable desire for pleasure whatever the source from which that pleasure may come, and the working of the desires strengthens such other desires as are kindred thereto, and, where those desires are strong and violent, they drive out of the mind all power of reflection. It is very needful, therefore, that the desires should be moderate and simple, and that they should be in no way Eeasonshonli^hoid antagonistic to Eeason. A temper in which the the same position , . ,, i. n i ti i ■ • and exercise the desires are thus Controlled, we call submissive same authority as and well-disciplined, since the appetitive soul children. " "^^"^ ought to live in obcdience to the law of Eeason, just as a child should live obedient to the com- mand of his Tutor. In the case of the temperate man, therefore, the whole of the appetitive part of his nature ought to be attuned to a perfect harmony with Reason. The aim of the temperate man is like the aim of Reason — the attainment of a noble ideal : — the temperate man is eager for what is right and seeks the right manner and the right time for compassing his desire ; and such is the ideal of life which Reason ordains. (c) HERE WE MUST CONCLUDE OUK EXAMINATION OP TEMPEEANCE. We also apply the term ' intemperance,' to characterise the faults of children : when children are Ul-behaved we caU them' ' undisciplined.' Faults of this kind bear, that is, a kind of resemblance to the ' uitemperance ' or want of self-conti'ol which has been described above. To inquire, however, which of these ideas is derived from the other, helps in no way to elucidate the question under dis- cussion : — only it is fair to say so much, that it is more rational to suppose that the latter is so named from the analogy of the former, and that the term was applied to intemperance from the comparison of childish faults by a metaphorical transition. This metaphor seems to have been used not inaptly, but with the Bk. III. 15.] Translation. 177 utmost propriety : just as one is bound to chastise a child when striving after things that are base, and to confine his impulses within a proper limit, bo also ought desire to be moderated (or ' chastened ' ) when it \^ assuming a rank growth. Unless the child be controlled by his Tutor, he will fall outside the limits of what is fitting, since he has an appetite for pleasure that is insatiable, especially caused by the waywardness of his youth. Desire also, unless it be moderated and chastened by Reason, will grow to a rank excess ; and strengthened as it is by the activities which are in sympathy with it, of ttimes it drives all power of thought out of the mind. Consequently our desires ought to be moderate and simple, and in no way to be antagonistic to Reason. Desires which are thus controlled we call submissive, temperate, or chastened ; so that the opposite frame of mind, both in the case of children and of the desires, is properly called ' intemperance ' or want of control. Just as a child ought to live according to the command of his Tutor, so ought the impulsive part of our nature to live by the law of Reason. In the temperate man therefore, the whole nature formed by the emotions ought to be attuned to the perfect harmony of Reason. The aim which Desire sets before itself is the same as that of Reason — the attainment of a noble ideal. The objects which the temperate man desires, the manner in which he expresses those desires and the seasons of their gratification, are all noble and becoming ; and such also are the conditions which Reason prescribes. Let this account suffice to explain the nature of Temperance. BOOK IV.-EXAMINATION OF THE VIETUES (Oontinueff). INTRODUCTORY ANALYSIS. Looking to the appetitive or purely self-regarding instincts of the soul, we shall have next to consider the virtues which regulate the disposal or acquisition of money ; and first of Charity or Liberality. Charity or charitableness may be defined as ' the attitude of mind which the perfect man shows in regard to questions of property.' It is the manifestation of the ' law of fitness ' (ro koKov) in the way in which money is bestowed or earned, where the bestowal or the earning is not a question of justice but of philanthropy. If charitableness be the ideal which virtue sets before men in such relations, there are two ways in which that ideal is vitiated, — by avarice on the one hand and by prodigality on the other. Avarice leads men to neglect the needs of others while selfishly absorbed in their own 'interests,' and is thus the state of mind which characterises narrow and selfish natui es. Prodigality is the exact opposite of this : — it is ' generosity gone mad ' — the state of mind of those who are so unmind- ful of their own interests as to ruin themselves for the sake of others [though it must be noted that prodigals are sometimes reckless not through unselfish generosity but from a dissolute love of their own pleasures, and thus one class of prodigals is a class of sensualists]. We will first consider charitableness per se, and then compare it with its vicious extremes. 1.— CHAEITY. (i.) CHARACTERISTICS OP CHARITY AND OF THE CHARITABLE MAN. The object-matter under review being money, a man will only deal rightly with money if he has the virtue corresponding thereto. What then is the right use of money ? Surely not its safe-keeping merely, nor its acquisition, but its proper bestowal : money is only put to its proper uses when it is virtuously bestowed or expended ; and that for many reasons. Virtue is active, not passive ; to give, is actively to do good ; to receive, is to be the passive recipient of good. No thanks nor praise are bestowed upon one who receives, but rather upon one who Introductory Analysis: Book IV. 179 gives. It is a harder task to give aright than it is to abstain from taking wrongfully. To forbear taking wrongfully is a mark of justice rather than of charity. To give charitably does more good, and makes the giver more beloved, than any other action does. The general principles of true benevolence may be seen (1) actively, and (2) passively : — (1.) Actively, in regard to giving : the measure of true charity, its object and inspiring motive, is ro koKov. Charity is the application of the ' law of the mean ' to the claims of society upon our good will ; and it shows all the features of moral fitness and the delicate adjustment of the relations involved which Eight Reason (opfioy Xdyos) prescribes. Conse- quently whatever the charitable man does will be gracefully done. He wUl give only to the poor and needy upon whom his help is fittingly bestowed. He will give just enough to effect the desired relief, and his gifts wiU be sent just at the time when the succour will be most effectual. His benevolence will in fact in all ways give proof of the nobility of the giver ; and it will be given ungrudgingly. As the charitable man knows that a noble deed is more precious than great riches, he will take delight in his gifts and give cheerfully and readily. (2.) Passively, in regard to the amassing of wealth,- the charitable man will here also show a delicate appreciation for the rights and feel- ings of others. He will not be so eager for wealth as to be unscrupulous of the source whence it comes ; nor will he be importunate in his desire to gain it. His soul is the soul of a benefactor, unused to favours from others. Nevertheless he will not refuse the legitimate revenues of his own estates, nor neglect the proper care of his own concerns, that he may have funds enough for future benefactions. There are other features to be noted in the charities of the benevolent man. He is not without discrimination in his charities, but confines himself to cases where his help will have real merit and moral beauty. He is also unselfish in what he does : in his love for his moral ideal (to KoKov) he will leave what is insufficient for his own use. Even if he has but little that he can give, he will give according to his means, knowing that the essence of charity is the spirit of the giver. [It is, of course, not to be expected that a charitable man should be wealthy : he is too unselfish to be anxious about his own interest as other men are. As a rule the charitable man is one who was ' born rich,' and who has never felt the sting of poverty like those who have toiled for their wealth and who clench it with morbid love.] He will also economise his charities, so as, whatever the amount of his wealth, he may employ it to the greatest possible effect and do with it the greatest possible amoiint of good. Nor will he let his charities ruin him : to go beyond his means will be a sign not of benevolence but of prodigality. To sum up : charity is the observance of the moral law of fitness both in reference to the bestowing and to the acquiring of money. Between both of these relations there must be sympathy and consistency. Eight giving and right receiving are mutually consequent the one upon the other. If either a man receives rightly but gives wrongly, or contrariwise, if he gives rightly but receives wrongly, the symmetry and perfection of his moral nature is violated : he has no true (e|«) disposition of charity. Of course the most charitable of men may make a mistake, but then he will be sorry for it. If, for instance, his charity proves to be mistimed i8o The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. and fails of to /ieo-w, a perfect effect, he will grieve, but his regret will be moderate and rational. Not only so ; but the comparative indifference he feels for money will render him very liable to be overreached : the courtesy and complaisance of his dealings will often be a snare to him. (ii.) CONTEASTS BETWEEN CHARITY AND PRODIGALITY. The ideal which the law of charity implies, is marred by the prodigal on the one hand and by the miser on the other. The prodigal is exces- sive in giving and careless of receiving \ the miser is keen to receive and reltictant to give. There are two kinds of prodigality which may be considered separately. 1. Prodigality in its strictest sense means the combination of two faults — excessive giving and defective receiving. That is a combination of faults which soon cures itself. The prodigal exhausts his property by extravagant benefactions ; and necessity teaches him the lesson of prudence. Age and experience tend to habituate him to self-controL The root of his fault is rather in folly than in vice ; and a riper know- ledge of the world and the teachings of his own life may cure him of that folly and bring him to a state of real charity. [Anyhow, prodigality is hetter than avarice, not only because it is curable, but also because it is of benefit to mankind, while avarice is fruitless and barren.] 2. But, as a rule, prodigality is associated with other and worse vices. Foolish generosity is associated with unlawful or unscrupulous gains : those who spend foolishly, acquire recklessly — careless whence the funds are drawn, so only that they can give as they list. But as there is nothing noble (/caXd) before the eyes of such, they are not really generous : their gifts have the stamp ofselfishness upon them, and are generally provoked by vanity or self illusion. Herein is the vicious point about prodigality : it involves other vices worse than itself, and thus becomes the handmaid of dissipation. The prodigal is thus often a sensualist : his easy gene- rosity to others provokes an equal self indulgence to himself. Neverthe- less if he can only meet with proper control and be brought under favour- able influences, this easy, self-indulgent good-nature of his youth may be sobered down to the ideal of perfect virtue. (iii.) CONTRASTS BETWEEN CHARITY AND AVABIOE. Worse than prodigality is avarice, both as being incurable and as fostering some of the worst passions of human nature. There are two ways in which Avarice displays itself, as meanness in giving or sordid rapacity in receiving. Sometimes, though not often, these two aspects of avarice are seen united in the same person ; but they generally branch off into distinct types. 1. Some men are deficient in giving, without being dishonest in receiv- ing ; such as are the stingy, the parsimonious and the niggardly. These all agree in giving nothing to anyone ; but there are diverse motives why they will not receive dishonestly. In some cases there is a natural sense of equity and a religious shrinking from positive wrongdoing; and that is the type of pimple meanness, or as we say, of one who would 'split a Introductory Analysis: Book IV. i8i pea.' The motive for honesty in others is a selfish fear lest if they accept any favour or take anything belonging to others they may be com- pelled to make a return ; and as their meanness re1>olts from giving, so they shrink from receiving. 2. Others are excessive in receiving, and have for their motto ' Quo- ounque mode ; ' such as are usurers, brothel keepers and others of that class, who will do or suffer any infamy to gratify their low avarice. It is immaterial almost what such men do with their wretched earnings : the stamp of baseness, is upon aU they touch, and their whole character is vitiated thereby. [It must be understood of course that such men's gains are petty gains : tyrants who are equally unscrupulous upon a large scale come under a different category.] 2.— MUNIFICENCE, (i.) CHAEACTEEISTICS OF MUNIFICENCE DELINEATED. Every virtue is limited to a particular subject-matter ; and as there is an essential difference between the ordinary conditions of life and striking and extraordinary circumstances in which money is expended, so there will be a corresponding difference in the virtues therein dis- played. The virtue which regulates the outlay of money on ordinary occasions, is, as we have seen, Charity. The virtue which enables a man to make an extraordinary expenditure with propriety and effect, is Munificence. The sphere, therefore, of the Munificent man is the sphere which grand opportunities present. Considerations of time, of place, of cir- cumstance, must modify any general conceptions of what a 'grand opportunity ' is, but the munificent man will show a true appreciation of all such considerations, and will act accordingly. He is a kind of ' moral artist ' where a great occasion arises, skilful to produce the splendour of a gi-and effect upon a grand scale. His aim throughout is the realization of moral beauty {to KoXiv) in the outward circumstances of his career ; and therein he attains his own perfect satisfaction. Whatever conduces to that end and aim, he gives generously and ungrudgingly. He is so absorbed in the aim before him that small economies will never occur to him ; and whatever he does, he does in the spirit of the charitable man, though on a grander scale. Even where the scale of his charity is not greater than that of common liberality, he will produce a more striking effect. Munificence does not consist in mere costliness, but in grandeur of conception. The charitable man may spend as much, but the munificent man will produce a more splendid and graceful result. The most natural expenses, however, wherein the munificent man can display his excellence, are costly expenses — public sacrifices, erection of Temples, the of&ces of the State. It follows that only public men and wealthy men can be properly munificent : there must be a fitting cor- respondence between the act and the agent. A poor man is a fool if he attempts to act munificently. Those to whom great undertakings are proper, are the nobly-born, those who inherit great traditions, or who have themselves great reputations, and wealth to add lustre to their •ptestige. 1 82 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. But there are also expenses of a 'private character in which munificence may be appropriately displayed. Such is the munificence which the entertainment of strangers, a marriage feast, the fitting up of an establishment, call for, though permanency of effect must be an element in the consideration. In all such circumstances the munificent man will preserve the relation that is fitting between means and ends, the outlay and the effect produced. (ii.) THE EXTREMES OP MUNIFICENCE. The vain-glorious and ostentatious man apes the gestures and character of the munificent man, and meets with no success. His attempts at munificence are ill-timed, awkward, and imgraceful. He faUs to adjust his outlay to the circumstances in view, and he is ever out of harmony with his surroundings. The motive, again, which actuates him is not (to icaXov) the sense of right, but rather a vulgar seeking for admiration ; and failure stamps his whole career. Meanness is the other extreme ; and its touch spoils the fairest endeavours, and mars the whole effect of the most promising under- takings. It is the low calculation of parsimony which gives what it has to give in a grudging spirit. It never gives quite enough, and is ever fearful of having given too much. 3.— ELEVATION OF SOUL. (i.) THE SPHERE AND CHABACTBEISTIC8 OF MORAL ELEVATION DELINEATED. The conception of the Munificent man who is grand and noble in the display of wealth, leads to the conception of a man who is grand and noble in all his surroundings. If a man have high merit, not in any isolated particular, but in his whole life and character, and shows the consciousness of his merit, he may be called ' a man of elevated soul.' If, on the other hand, a man esteems himself less highly than he ought, he is humble-minded ; while if his estimate of himself is in excess of his real merit, he is then vain-glorious or conceited. The sphere then of Moral Elevation is what is high and meritorious j and whether we look to th6 standard of the Gods or to that of great men, we see that Iwnoiir is the highest of all good things. Moral Elevation will, therefore, be concerned specially with honours. But honour implies desert or merit. If, therefore, the man of elevated soul is right in claiming the highest honours, he must have the highest personal worth : he must not merely be a good man but a perfect man. The consciousness of his elevation is but the glow and lustre which arise from the combination of all the virtues existing in his soul in their most intense and complete form. The possession of perfect virtue, and the consciousness which arises therefrom, give him a peculiar attitude in regard to external things and in particular in regard to honours. He knows that they cannot either add to his worth or take away from it. He only accepts honours ■ because honour is the best tribute which men are able to pay to good- ness. Still the honours which he accepts must be marked honours, aad Introduciory Analysis: Book IV. 183 conferred by distinguished men ; the ordinary compliments of life are not worthy of his notice. As it is with honours so also with the other |bod things of life. Prosperity or adversity are things external, and he holds the same dignified mien in regard to them which might almost be mistaken for superciliousness and apathy. It seems, however, the truth that pros- perity is more congenial to his character and more naturally his lot. Wealth and family and high station seem to be the natural concomitants of a character which knows so well how to bear itself gracefully and nobly : they indicate a superiority which is nothing unless it be associated with nobility of soul. This truth is again and again exem- plified in the case of men who inherit great traditions or who attain to high station which from lack of virtue they cannot adorn. Such men c.annot bear the burden of their prosperity, but wax wanton and dis- dainful and insolent ; and their attempts at grandeur and dignity are but the feeble caricature which confounds insolence with goodness. (ii.) EELATION OP THE MAN OF ELEVATED SOUL TO THE VIRTUES GENERALLY. 1. Courage. He is courageous, but he does not expose himself to risks where little glory can be won. He reserves his heroism for grand and striking occasions, where the display of his bravery will be glorious to him, whether the issue to himself be life or death. 2. Benevolence. He is a charitable man, ever ready to give and loath to receive. If he does require a kindness, he never rests vmtil he has repaid it, so as to be under obligation to no man : he loves rather to bestow favours upon others. To receive a favour is to be in a position of inferiority ; to confer a favour, of superiority. As he knows that out- ward superiority is due to the inward superiority of which he is con- scious, he prefers by his bounties to make his superiority manifest to all men. 3. General intercourse of life. He loves to overtop the mighty, while towards the lowly he is conciliatory and gentle. He avoids places where honour is cheaply won, or where others are in the ascendant. He never interests or bestirs himself, except where great honour is to be won, or great exploits achieved. He is open and sincere in his dealings, whether to show aversion or to express sympathy. Afraid of no one, he scorns dissimulation — unless at times a good-humoured disdain makes him ironical. He has nothing of the courtier or of the flatterer about him, though he unburdens himself to a friend. He is free from enthusiasm for anything except his own ideal. He never nurses revenge, as he will not demean himself to remember an injury. He does not concern him- self about other people's business, nor talk needlessly about his own. He is sparing of censure just as he is slow to praise. He is indifferent to the petty cares and vicissitudes of life, as they have no real concern to him. He shows his self-sufficiency by the very character of his establish- ment, his purchases being what is grand rather than what is useful or productive. Lastly, in his personal demeanour he carries about with him the consciousness of his greatness : the deep voice, the measured words, the solemn tread, are but the outward marks of inward dignity, 184 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. and well indicate the character of one ■who, being of highest worth, esteems himself accordingly. (iii.) RELATION OP MORAL ELEVATION TO ITS EXTREMES. 1. Self-abasement, or humility, is an attitude of mind which shrinks from the honours which are its due. There seems to be some lurking defect in a character which thus abases itself. It is almost incredible that a man should willingly abandon good things, if they were really his due. Anyhow, such a habit has a tendency to lower a man's moral ideal : the plea of imworthiness which makes a man retire from great honoui-s, makes him also shrink from taking part in great or noble achievements. 2. Self-conceit impels men to attempt what is beyond their ability to execute : and such men are laughed at for their failure and for tiieir folly. This is a habit compounded of ignorance and vanity, and suggEsts a real defect in the moral ideal — the defect of mistaking external pomp and circumstances, for real glory and dignity. 4.— LOVE OF HONOUR. UNCERTAINTIES OF THE EXACT IDEA IMPLIED IN ' LOVE OF HONOUR.' Besides the special and extraordinary occasions of honour in which Elevation of Soul is shown, there are the ordinary honours of common life in which virtue may also be shown. The man who shows a laudable ambition within the range of ordinary experience, is praised for his 'love of honour,' if it be in accordance with right. But here is a diificulty : what is ' right ' in regard to such honours ? Something very undefined and difficult to grasp. The shifting phases of circumstance, and the very nature of society as a complex organism, render it almost impossible to fix an absolute ' point of view.' The terms in which we commonly speak of ' ambition ' are equally vague. Love of honour is used, like 'ambition,' in both a good and a bad sense. In itself colourless, it derives its form and meaning from the associations with which it is blended. Yet, we may be sure, there is an ideal existing in the mind of the perfect man, and reproduced in his life, notwithstanding the fluctuations of society and the uncertainties of nomenclature. 5.— GOOD TEMPEE. (i.) GENERAL CONCEPTION OF GOOD TEMPER. In the regulation of the feelings of anger there is also an ideal state ; but the exact term whereby to express it is open to ambiguity. It may, however, not inappropriately be called 'Good temper' or 'Mildness' — though such an expression seems to suggest something like a defect of indignation. As an ideal, Good temper must of course conform to the conditiona which Eight Reason prescribes. It must be fired into anger when the Introductory Analysis: Book IV. 185 occasion is fitting and. -where there are objects to justify it ; and its anger must be shown in a proper manner and at a fitting time. Its tendency however will rather be to gentleness than4o severity. (ii.) GOOD TEMPER CONTBASTBD WITH ITS EXTREMES. 1. Entire absence of temper, or ' passionlessness,' is reprehensible. It seems to argue a servile callousness and insensibility, to submit to out- rage and insult and to have no instincts of self defence. It is at any rate folly to brook all such contumely. 2. Excess of temper is found under manifold varieties, all of which vio- late the perfect law. It bursts out against the wrong persons, at wrong times, with insufficient provocation, and lasts for too long a time ; though of course all these errors are not combined in the same person. There are two principal classes of ' extremely angry ' men — the passionate and the sulky, (a) The passionate are easily provoked and easily appeased ; such are liable to sudden and violent revulsions of feeling, quick-temper leading them constantly into excess. (|3) The sulky nourish their anger for a long time until they can gain perfect revenge ; such suffer from suppressed anger, and are implacable and vengeful. Of these two extremes the excess is in itself worse and is more diificulfc to cure ; and it is unhappily the more prevalent. But the boundary line is difficult to define, as it is difficult to particularise all the circumstances which may arise ; and wherever such circumstances arise, the judgment of the agent must decide for himself how far his conscience will sanction anger or forgiveness. Such occasions are eminently ' cases of con- science.' 6.— COUETESY. (i.) GENERAL CHARACTERISTICS OF COUETESY. In the ordinary intercourse of life there are men who will acquiesce in anything and allow no stint or limit in the praises which they bestow ; and there are others who are the very reverse, and show a constant antagonism to everybody and to everything. Both these extremes miss the moral ideal. The true attitude of mind in regard to society is that of a generous friendliness which prefers to give pleasure wherever pleasure is possible without injury to the higher interests of life. But it is a friendliness stript of emotion or personal affection ; and void of par- tiality it is unswervingly true to requirements of justice and social well- being. The rule of the courteous man is the rule of the ' beautiful ' and ' the expedient ; ' and whether he cause pleasure or pain, he will act con- scientiously by that rule. He will deliberately cause pain in cases where disgrace or injury to himself or others would be the result of his ac- quiescence. Still he will remember what is due to each man, according to his station ; and wiU by all means promote pleasure of his associates where honour and conscience permit. If he causes pain to others, it is only because pain is the least of evils in that case. 1 86 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. (ii.) EXTREMES OF COUHTESY. 1. The man whose law is the law of pleasure, violates the ideal of courtesy. If he simply follows pleasure, ho is obsequious ; if gain enter into his calculations, then he is a flatterer. 2. The man who violates the ideal of courtesy by way of defect is the peevish irritable man who quarrels with everyone. 7.— SINCEEITY. There is a virtue to be exhibited in the words which a man uses, in- dependently of the consequences which flow from them. Truthfulness, or sincerity, is the perfection of human converse. It is 'a mean' between the pretentiousness of the boastful man and the false modesty of the diffident man. The characteristics of Sincerity are, therefore, a religious horror of falsehood as a thing disgraceful and base per se, an uprightness and in- tegrity more delicate and penetrating than even justice itself. It is the disposition to speak the truth, though nothing seems to depend upon it ; and it has its roots in an honesty of purpose and its fruits in honesty and truthfulness of life. In its shrinking from exaggeration it is in- clined, if anything, to understate the truth ; reticence being less offen- sive than exaggeration. VIOLATIONS OP SINCERITY. 1. Boastfulness is the generic term to express various modes in which the ideal of integrity is violated in the direction of excess, (a) If boastfulness have no special purpose to serve, it is the outcome of empty- headedness and vice ; the boastful man of this type being a vain, foolish and worthless character. (8) If, however, boasting has a purpose to serve, and that purpose be glory or honour, it is not so very reprehensible ; but if its object be gain, it is a very discreditable habit. It is of course under either aspect a state of the will and not a merely latent tendency, and the will requires to be acted upon either by (a) the bent of the character or (^) a special motive operating at the moment. 2. Self-depreciation is that imdue fear of exaggeration which leads a man to say less than the truth, especially when speaking of his own merits. [There is, however, another form of self-disparagement, which is either ' false modesty,' or ' pridp aping humility,' and thinly disguises a conceited vanity.] Though self-depreciation is a falling short of perfect sincerity and straight-forwardness, it is often, in its moderate forms, the mark of a graceful refinement. 8.— HUMOUR. There is an element of rest in life, and rest gives room for relaxation, and relaxation calls for the exercise of an appropriate virtue. That virtue is humour — ' a mean ' between frivolity and moroseness. Introductory Analysis: Book IV. 187 (i.) CHABACTERISTICS OF PEEFECT HUMOUR. • The playful versatility of good-humour is analogous to the lithesome movements of the body. Its essential feature is that 'good-taste,' 'tact' or ' dexterity ' ; and that is best represented by the character of a perfect gentleman. There is a characteristic difference between the humour of an educated and of an uneducated man. The open scurrility of the Old Comedy is a very different thing from the polished innuendo of the New. Perfect humour, therefore, must be the humour of a gentleman ; and this condition will apply not only to what a man says, but also to the approval he gives of the jests of others. As there are things which a man will not do himself (and which even the legislator forbids him to do), so there are things to which he ought not to listen : he must be ' a Jaw to himself.' , (ii.) CHARACTERISTICS OP THE EXTREMES. 1. Buffoonery is wit, stript of all considerations of delicacy or opportuneness. 2. Boorishness is poverty of invention, combined with peevishness of temper. 9.— SENSE OF SHAME. Sense of Shame is not, properly speaking, a virtue; it is rather a physical emotion like fear than a formed attitude of the moral nature. Its definition as ' an apprehension of dishonour ' shows that it is rather emotional than moral. It is indeed but a check upon the passions of youth, and is inappropriate to age. Old men ought not to do anything for which to be ashamed : an honest life will be conscious of no evil, whether absolute or conventional evil. To be liable to a feeling of shame would be to argue the existence of passions which none but youth should know. Even in the case of youth it is only an hypothetical good : — ' if he were to do so and so, he would feel shame.' Better never to do evil than having done evil to feel ashamed of it. TRANSLATION. C— LIBERALITY, i. — Characteristics of Liberality explained. {a) THE SPHERE OF LIBERALITY DEFINED. Continuing our examination of the social virtues, let us now discuss the virtue of liberality, which is commonly raifty *'"'' °^ ^'^^' regarded as the perfect attitude of mind in regard to questions of property. The praise which is bestowed upon the liberal man is not for his exploits in war, nor for his behaviour under circumstances where self-control is tested, nor yet for the justice of his decisions, but has regard simply to the disposal or acquisition of property and more particularly to its disposal (' property ' being here used to denote anything which has a value which can be estimated in current coin). Liberality also is a form of excellence shown by the appetitive soul, and, therefore, it is a virtue which we may examine immediately after Temperance. Now liberality is an ideal state of mind in regard to njoney — an ideal which we realize, that is, when we spend neither more nor less than what is right, but give all that we have to spend in a befitting matter, upon deserving objects, and with right motives. When the liberal man is praised, it is not for his services in war, nor for acting as the temperate man acts, nor yet again for the equity of Ms awards (as the just man is), but for his dealings in the bestowal and acquisition, of property ; and praise is more abundantly accorded him for the way in which' he gives ; (' property ' being here used to include everything which has an appreciable value in current coin). (6) MODES IN "WHICH THE PRINCIPLE OF LIBERALITY IS VIOLATED. The states of excess and defect in money-matters are prodigality on the one hand, and avarice on the other. Failure of charity ^e apply the epithet ' avaricious ' uniformly ; 1 rnTTi 6XC6SS OT ■ . -i ■• _ , defect. to those who are more eager than they ought to be in regard to money. On the other hand we sometimes use the term ' prodigality ' with complex associations. Bk. IV. 1.] Translation. 189 We call men ' prodigals ' when they are weakly self-indulgent and spend their property upon vicious indulgences : and consequently men of this stamp are accountea ^,^« °* '"^'^s ■ '^°^- ,, , ,. 1 , p .1 • 1 • 1 1 • plex associations of the most dissolute 01 their kmd, as havmg many 'prodigaUty.' vices combined in one. But they are not called prodigals in the strict and natural sense of the word : the word ' prodigal ' is intended to mean one who has a single thought, that of wasting or ruining his property, the prodigal being one who is ruined through his own fault: i.e. the wasting of his property seems to be a form of ' self-destruction,' since his very life and livelihood depend upon the possession of means. It is in this strict sense, therefore, that I now employ the term ' pro- digality.' Liberality is, tlierefore, tlie ideal state in regard to money, while avarice is the corruption hy way of defect, and prodigality the corruption by way of excess. But we speak df prodigality not only as an excess iu regard to money, but sometimes we call even sensualists ' prodigals,' inasmuch as they squander large sums to gratify their selfish tastes, and prodigality of this type we call a vice. It is for this reason that prodigals of this class are the most abandoned of men, since they have many vices all in one, being at once ruined in fortune and dissolutely abandoned in the pursuit of pleasure. Hence they are not properly called by a single name indicating only a single vice (since the term ' prodigal ' is intended to imply one who has only a single vice, that of ruining his substance — the 'prodigal' being one who is ruined through his own fault, since the wasting of his substance seems to be a form of self-destruction, life and livelihood depending upon the possession of means). However, we call those also who are weakly self-indulgent, and who spend their money upon their own sensual gratifications, ' prodigals ; ' though we confine the tenn ' avaricious ' to those who grasp after money more keenly than is right, and who are defective in regard to liberality. (c) THE VIRTUE OK VICE OF A THING DEPENDENT UPON ITS USES. Now whatever admits of use may be put to a good or a bad use ; and as wealth is one of those things which are capable of use, and a man puts a thing to ^ney^^*the^vir^ its best use when he has the virtue related tuous disposition thereto, it follows that a man will put wealth to eLrity."°'"''^°® *° its best possible use when he has the virtue related to money : when, that is, he is liberal-minded. Now since it is possible for us to use everything which admits of use, well or ill {e.g., our reputation or our food), and wealth is of precisely this nature, since there is a definite use for it in the conduct of life, it is, therefore, possible to put wealth to a good or bad use ; and inasmuch as a man will put a thing to a proper use only when he has the virtue related to that tiling, he will only put his wealth to its most perfect use when he has the virtue related to money — when, that is, he is liberal-minded. I90 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IV. 1. (d) THE SPECIAL USE OF MONEY IS IN SPENDING BATHER THAN IN EECEIVING. Now the use of money seems to consist in spending and giving, while the acquisition of money lies rather in the The charMteristic receiving and safe keeping thereof; consequently. of chanty IS a viv- . . & f j. • j.- j? j.i i-i i tuous spending it IS more distmctly Characteristic 01 the liberal- rather than virtu- minded man that he gives to proper persons than ous receiving. , , , . !• 4. ^ x that he receives from proper persons, or than that he refrains from taking whence he ought not, 1. It is a greater proof of moral worth that a man confers benefits upon others, than that he receives them himself, and that he himself performs noble actions, than that he refrains from disgraceful ones. It is obvious that the effect consequent upon giving is that a man does a kindness to another, and is thus an instrument for noble deeds ; whereas the effect consequent upon his receiving is that he is himself the recipient of favours, or at most that he takes no unfair advantage. 2. Thanks are accorded to one who makes a gift, not to one who abstains from unlawful gains ; and of course praise is greater in proportion. 3. It is easier to abstain from taking than it is to give : men are far less disposed to give away what is their own than to for- bear taking what is another's. 4. Again, it is only those who give who have the name of ' charitable : ' those who forbear taking are not praised on the score of their charitableness, but, if at all, with special reference to their justice ; while those who simply receive what is their due are absolutely not praised at all. 5. Again, charitable men are, as a rule, more personally be- loved than any other class who are esteemed for their own worth, inasmuch as they are serviceable to their fellows ; but their service depends upon the gifts they make. Now the use of money is nothing else whatever but spending and giving. The receiving and saving of money seems to be not use but possession. Conse- quently the charitable man is more concerned vrith the expenditure of money than with the acquisition of it ; and it is of [more importance for him to know in what manner he ought to spend, and with what motives and upon what persons, than it is for him to know in what manner he ought to receive, and with what aims and from what class of persons. In fact the charitable man is concerned, as has been shown, with the use of wealth ; and use consists in giving rather than in receiving. 1. It seems to be a much greater merit to do a kindness than to receive one, to perform noble acts than to abstain from vicious ones ; and in the case of giving there is involved at once a kindness done to another and a noble deed performed by one's self ; whereas, in receiving, there lies only the having a Bk. IT. 2.] Translation. 191 favour conferred on one, or at most an abstention from dishonourable behaviour (for to receive from proper sources is to have a favour done one ; and to abstain from receiving whence one ought not, is to abstain from raijcighteous courses). 2. Conduct which is more highly praised, is more closely akin to virtue ; and the act of giving in a rightful manner is more highly praised than the act of receiving iu a rightful manner : since thanks and the praise consequent thereon fall rather to the man who gives than to the man who abstains from receiving. 3. Virtue is concerned especially with what is more difficult ; and it is more diflcult to give rightly than to receive or not to receive rightly : it is far more disagreeable to us to give up our own than it is to dismiss from our minds the property of another. Consequently, it is more suitable to the character of the charitable man to give rightly than it is to receive or not to receive rightly. 4. In fact we do not call men by the name of charitable simply because they do not receive from improper sources, but because they give to fitting and proper persons, the former being considered rather just than charitable and receiving praise on the score of their justice, while on the other hand, those who simply receive from the sources they are entitled to receive from, are absolutely not praised at all (ic. a man is only praised when he does something disagreeable to him with a virtuous motive, but a man who receives whence he has a right to receive, undergoes no inconvenience at all). 5. Lastly, charitable men are beloved more than any other class of virtuous men, inasmuch as they are useful to their fellows ; but their usefulness consists not in their forbearing to receive basely but in their giving nobly. Hence it is that the charitable man is thought to have more to do with giving than receiving : he is in fact one who bestows his wealth upon proper objects, and has always in view what is noble and right. (e) GENERAL CONDITIONS EEQUISITE IN CHAEITABLE GIVING. Now all actions that are conformable to virtue have in them- selves a noble effect and are inspired by a noble motive. If, therefore, a man has the virtue of In order to perfect charity, he will give from a noble motive, and his \^^ ^ °™ ""^ gifts will have a noble effect. Those to whom he i_ a sense of moral gives will be deserving recipients of his bounty ; fitness. and both the amount and the occasion of his g^g^^ bounty will be equally suitable and appropriate. 3. A deserving ob- He will invariably observe the conditions requisite ^^\-a, adequate to rightful giving. Moreover, whatever he does amount. he will do cheerfully, or at any rate without ^ieat^on^^^"^"**' pain, inasmuch as every act that is conformable 6. A cheerful spirit, to virtue is pleasurable to the agent, or at ' any rate devoid of pain — least of all can it be positively painful. If a man fail to meet these tests — if he gives to unworthy objects, or if he gives without any reference to a virtuous ideal, but to satisfy some lower aim, he is not a charitable man, but must be styled by some other name. Nor again is he charitable if he gives with reluctance or pain, since such an one would fain choose money in preference to noble acting, and that is very un- like the liberal-minded man. 192 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [BklV. 2. I say that the motive of the charitahle man will be a noble one, as in fact every action regulated by virtue must be inspired by a noble aim. But not only so : not only must charitable actions have a noble motive, and be done in favour of proper persons, and at fitting times, and observe all the other conditions which are entailed in rightful giving, but further they must be done with pleasure to the agent, or at any rate without regret. A man who gives with a feehng of reluctance has not grown to be a charitable man : he may perform charitable actions, but he is not in himself charitable : — ^he has not attained to the moral dispositions of heart involved in charity, otherwise we would have had no feeling of pain, aU actions regulated by virtue being either pleasurable or devoid of pain. If a man fail to meet these conditions — if he bestow his money upon unworthy objects, or without any noble motive, but from some other aim, he is not a charitable man, but must be styled by some other name. For simUar reasons, neither is a man charitable if he bestow his gifts with reluctance, as has been ex- plained : since a man of that stamp values his money more than noble acting, and on that account he is not a charitable man. (/) GENERAL CONDITIONS EEQUISITB IN CHARITABLE RECEIVING, The charitable man will never receive from sources whence he ought not, since such an acceptance of money is But the money ex- inconsistent with the character of one who regards penoed m charity , p i • i • , must be properly not money as 01 high importance. obtained : the cha- j^qj. -^'^ \^q \^q. importunate for money, since it ritable man wiU . . ti j.t i j. r i • i • i/- draw from his own IS not like the Character 01 one who is himself a funds but never benefactor to havo benefits conferred upon him others. ^ ^ """ lightly and without reserve. Still he will receive from proper and legitimate sources, e.g. the revenues of his own estates, — not as though it were meritorious so to do, but as a thing inevitable in order that he may have the means wherewith to make gifts to others ; and he will not be indifferent to the care of his own property, desiring as he does by the help thereof to assist the needs of others. But while on the one hand the charitable man will only give according as Eight Reason prescribes, so on the other hand he will never receive from souioes whence he ought not to receive ; and since he does not prize money highly, he will not ask for it : a man who loves to confer benefits on others, is not easily prevailed upon to receive a benefit himself. StOl he will receive from legitimate sources, as of course the revenues of his own estates — not that he thinks it meri- torious to earn money, but because it is essential for him so to do in view of the, gifts which he has to make. Consequently he will not be indifferent to the care of his own property, since he desu-es by the help thereof to assist the needs of others. {g) SOME FURTHER CHARACTERISTICS OF THE CHARITABLE MAN. But he will not give to all alike indiscriminately, that so he Hewiilnotbereck- ^^7 ^^^cp enough wherewith to give to deserving less of his gifts, persons at fitting times, and where his bounty is Bk. IV. 2.] Translation. 193 meritorious. It is, again, quite characteristic of though he -Bill the charitable man that his generosity in giving freely give what he is so extreme that he leaves insuflScient for hin^ ^'"^°' self: it is a sign of his perfect charity that he does not look to his own interests but to the good of others. But charity is to be measured by relation to the means of the individual, not by an absolute standard : the quality of charitableness does not consist in the '•'■'.'le spirit of the multitude of the things that are given, but in the extent of the gift! formed character of the giver, which leads him to '\ *^^ measure of give to the extent of the means at his command. ' ^' There is therefore nothing to prevent a man whose gifts are less than another's from being, for all that, the more liberal of the two — ^provided, that is, that the store from which he has to draw his gifts be less. [The most charitably-minded men seem to be found among those who have not amassed their wealth for themselves, but received it by inheritance, the The nobly-boru the 1 . ,, , ,, 1 11 . ' „ most chantabJe. reason bemg that they nave had no experience of actual want, and are also free from that inordinate love for their own which parents have for their offspring, or poets for their works. Yet it is no easy thing for a charitable man to be also wealthy, since he takes no care either to acquire or to preserve his wealth, but is ever ready to bestow it upon others, and prizes nut money for its own sake, but only for the sake of the gifts which it can provide. Hence it is laid as a charge at Fortune's door that those who are most deserving of riches are the least aflSuent of all ; — though that is an anomaly which very naturally occurs, since it is not possible for a man to have wealth if he take no care how he may gain it, neglect and loss being universally sissociated.] In virtue of his charity he will most assuredly never give to unworthy objects, nor at unseasonable times, nor . 1 , /, "^ '. . . , J.1 ■ Mutual interdepea- violate the proprieties in other ways : otherwise jien^e of the con- he would cease to act according to the law of ditions of true charity : exhausting his resources upon improper " ™ ^' objects, he would have nothing left to spend upon objects that really deserved his sympathy. As has been shown, a man only has the virtue of charity when his expenditure is not only propor- tioned to his means but is also confined to worthy objects. [The man who spends beyond his means is extravagant and prodigal. It would be improper then to call tyrants ' prodigals,' as it seems not easy to exceed the limit of their resources, what- ever gifts or expenditure they may make.] 9 194 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IV. 2. Nor win he give indiscriminately to all alike, that so he may keep enough to give to those who deserve his charity, where the occasion is fitting and meritorious. It is also a characteristic of one who is zealously charitable, that his generosity in giving is so great, that he actually leaves insufficient to himself : that being a sign of perfect charity — ^not to look to one's own need. Charity is not estimated by reference to the greatness or to the variety of things which are given, but in accordance with the proportion which things given bear to the means of the giver— that being the standard by which a generous disposition on the part of the giver is tested. Hence, there is nothing to prevent a man who gives less, being a more charitable man than one who gives more — provided that the man who gives less, has a less store from which to make his gifts. [It is found that men who have not had to make money for themselves, by their own exertions, but have gained their wealth by inheritance from others, have the reputation of being more charitable. Men who are 'bom rich have ' never felt the pains of want, and for that reason do not love their wealth witi overweening affection ; whereas those who have amassed riches for themselves, are like parents and poets — strongly enamoured of their own productions. But liberal men are not able to be very rich, since they are neither prompt to receive nor provident in guarding their property, but are rather disposed to lavish in charity aU they have, and do not prize money for its own sake, but only for the gifts it enables them to make. Hence we find fault with Fortune, because liberal men are not in affluence, though deserving of wealth and possessions. Still that is a state of things which might not unreasonably be expected : if a man takes no care to amass money, how is it possible for him to be rich 2 That is a truth of universal application : it is impossible for a man to have anything, if he will not take the measures necessary to procure it. Hence, the liberal man will not be able to be affluent, if he neither collects money from new sources, and yet scatters abroad what he has of his own.] Moreover, the charitable man never gives to improper objects, nor on any occasion that is not right, lest, if he spent his money upon unlawful things, he might be found incapable of meeting lawful claims, and fail to give to worthy objects on fitting occasions. As has been shown, a man is only charitable when he is spending in proportion to his means : the man who gives at random is a prodigal. Hence we do not call ' tyrants ' prodigal, though they give vast sums and keep no limits in giving, since the extent of their resources seems to exceed the extent of there gifts, and it is found that their means are greater than their expenditure. {K) ElfiStJMlfi: CHAEITY THE MOEAL IDEAL m EEGARD TO WEALTH. Since, therefore, charity is an ideal frame of mind in regard to the giving or receiving of money, the charitable law of Keaaou ap- Dian will give Ms money, or expend his money, plied to aU ques- only upon proper occasions and to proper amounts, tiona and moideuts ti • n • i. i i _:ii of wealth. Right ^u^^ m Small as m great concerns ; and he will giving as essential feel pleasure in so acting. [He will also recme as right receiving. ^-^^^ -^ ^^^^^ ^^^ j^j^ ^^ ^^^^^ ^_^^^ j^^^j sources. The virtue of charity being an ideal fitness in regard , both to giving and receiving, the charitable man will act rightly in both relations : — i.e., there is consequent upon suitable giving a corresponding receiving, whereas improper receiving is incon- sistent with proper giving. These two conditions, therefore, of proper giving and proper receiving, being mutually consequent Bk. IV. 3.] Translation. 195 upon one another, are found combined in the same person; whereas conditions which are not so consequent but are opposed to one another are not found to coexist, as obviously they cannot, in the same individual.] But if it should happen that he has spent his money contrary to what is right and appropriate, he will feel regret, but his regret will be temperate and seasonable. For it is a mark of virtue for a man to have feelings of pleasure or of pain in a suitable degree, and on fitting occasions. Again, the charitable man is courteous and affable in his dealings, and is a man capable of being over- reached, -since of course he sets no store on ^?? f "^^ of fitness money, and is more likely to be distressed if he makes a" Lan^s has omitted to spend what he ought to have ""^"'^ demeanour spent, than to be pained at having spent upon that which was not worthy of his charity. He is not one who would acquiesce in the maxim of Simonides. [On the other hand, the prodigal goes wrong upon these points as well as upon others : he never feels the proper pleasure in worthy objects and occasions, nor does he grieve where he ought to feel pain. This aspect of prodigality will be clearer as we proceed with our analysis.] Since, therefore, charity is an ideal frame of mind in reference to the giving and receiving of money, the charitable man 1^111 make gifts and expend his money npon worthy objects and to proper amounts, as well in great as in trifling concerns ; and, whether he gives, or whether he receives, he will show a oheerfid disposition, and will maintain a proper balance and fitness, since charity is an ideal ' mean,' as well in regard to the taking as to the giving of money. It is consequent upon a man's giving rightly, that hie should also receive rightly ; and that he should do both with pleasure. Hence he will feeljipain if he faU to give, or to receive, according to a fitting proportion ; and yet the pain he feels will not be extravagant or unseemly. The charitable man is also courteous and accessible in money relations, and is pleasant in all dealings that relate to money, inasmuch as, despising money as he does, he is not very much distressed if he is overreached or injured. He is more distressed if he has failed to spend what was fitting for him to have spent, than he is if he has spent what was fitting for him not to have spent. The spending on occasions beyond what is right, is simply a loss afEecting the purse, and that does not so very much grieve the charitable man ; whereas, on the other hand, failing to spend upon proper objects, becomes a loss in regard to duty and to virtue, and for that reason, causes keener pain. Hence, he will not either accept the counsel of Simonides when suggesting the opposite attitude of mind. On titie other hand, the prodigal is in error invariably both in regard to pleasure and to pain : he neither rejoices in worthy objects, nor does he show his joy in a proper manner (as wiU be explained more clearly in the course of our analysis), % 196 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IV. 3. ii. — Contrast between Liberality and Prodigality. (a) DESCRIPTION OF PRODIGALITY AS A VICE FES. BE. Now we have already shown that there are states of excess and of defect in regard to money, in prodigality on When either of ^q one hand and avarice on the other, in the rela- these conditions — .. ,..„.. i/> ••/it of right giving or tions Doth of givmg and 01 receiving (and here of right receiving, ^e put expenditure generally in the category of is violated, the , • • ,v n t vj. • l l c ■ result is vice. gi^mg ). rrodigality is a state 01 excess in regard to giving without equivalent, and is a state of defect in regard to receiving ; while, contrariwise, avarice is a state of defect in regard to giving, and of excess in regard to receiving — only on a small scale. But these opposing characteristics are rarely found united, since it is not easy for a man to give to every bo"tV*onSste o^J«?t ^^ ^^^re be no source from which he himself violated simuita- receives [for the term ' prodigal ' cannot be, it 'erson^-"in^re™d '^'^^^ Seem, applied to any but joraafe individuals to the excess of (not to tyrants), and the means which such giving and defect persons have of giving are soon exhausted!; of receiving. fu t, j? j-i? a ^ x -il though 01 course this type 01 extreme generositj would seem to be vastly superior to that of the avaricious man, as being more easily reformed under the influence of advancing age and personal exigencies, and being thus capable of attaining, to a perfect state. Such an one has, in fact, some of the attributes of the charitable man : he gives and is not fond of receiving, though he does neither the one nor the other rightly, nor in a becoming manner. If only he could be habituated to self- restraint, or were in some other way to reform, he would be a man of real charity. He would give to none but deserving objects, nor receive from any but legitimate sources. Hence the prodigal does not seem to be really depraved in _, J. 1 • disposition : it is not proof either of a wicked or The prodigal is . ^ -t.- ^ j • • ■ j i more foolish than ignoblc disposition to exceed m giving and not ^°i""s- receiving, but rather of a foolish one. A man who is prodigal after this fashion seems to be much better than a sordid man, as well for the reasons referred to above as also because the prodigal benefits many, but the sordid man no one, not even himself. Charity, then, is the ideal state of mind in regard to money; the vicious extreme in one direction being prodigality, and in another direction avarice. Prodigality exceeds in giving and in non-receiving, and is deficient in reoeiving» On the other hand, avarice is excessive in receiving, and defective in giving. Bk. IV. 3.] Translation. 197 Though both these states of mind are at variance with what is fitting, yet avarice is worse than prodigality. In the first place, prodigality is not able to endure as a permanent condition : when resources are IHl spent, it quickly changes, le„ wealth speedily fails those who spend if from merely private resources they keep giving immoderately, without receiving from any new fund of their own. On the other hand, avarice has no such cure for itself : If, on the one hand, his wealth increase, the avaricious man grows no better, and, on the other hand, if his wealth be exhausted, he becomes far worse. In the second place, it is possible for the prodigal to be cured as well by the iafluence of time, as by experience of the evils which flow from want, and so he may attain at last to a proper frame of mind. In fact, the prodigal is near to the perfect state : — i.e., he gives and is not fond of receiving, though his gifts are made to unworthy objects, and in an improper manner. Consequently, if only it could become habitual to him to give to worthy objects only, and only on worthy occasions, he would be a man of real charity, bestowing his gifts on deserving persons, and refraining from taking from improper sources. In this view the prodigal does not seem to be really depraved in heart : it is no mark of a wicked or ignoble nature to exceed in giving and to refrain from taldng, but rather of a foolish one. Hence the prodigal is a better man than the miser, as well for the reasons given above, as also because he does good service to his fellows, whereas the miser benefits no one, not even himself. (d) PRODIGALITY ASSOCIATED WITH OTHER VICES. But, as has already been shown, the greater number of those who are prodigal not only spend their money 1 1 ? 1 . ,1 . « As a rule, prodigals improperly, but also acquire their money from are indifferent L™ unlawful sources, and are on that score as well theygain the means as others, void of charity. They grow to be "^^P^^-^i^s- grasping after money, prompted by the desire to spend, and by their inability to spend as lavishly as they would without monej'. The means of spending soon fail them ; hence they are forced to provide funds from new sources. At the same time, from the indifference which they feel for what is noble and honourable, they make their gains with little scruple from any source whatever. In the passion they have for giving, it is a thing quite indifferent to them how they give or whence the funds are drawn. Hence the gifts of such men are not really charitable gifts : they are not nobly conceived, nor have they a noble motive, nor are they be- stowed in a proper manner ; at times they make men rich whom it were fitting to be poor, and while they will give nothing to men of sober and respectable lives, they lavish favours freely upon those who flatter them or in some way afford them amusement. Hence, prodigals are for the most part sensualists : reckless in their expenditure, they lavish their wealth upon their own lusts, and inasmuch as they do not The recklessness of live with any noble aim in view, they are diverted -^1^0^ oS"to to the pursuit of selfish indulgences. personal dissipa- However, though the prodigal swerves into *'°"" 198 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk, IV. 3. vicious practices like these, if he be unchecked in his course, yet, on the other hand, if he meet with guidance and control, he may, for all his extravagance, still attain to a perfect ideal of what is fitting and right. Hitherto I tave teen speaJking of the prodigal who is excessive ia the gifts he makes, and is defective in what he receives ; and we assumed this type to be an extreme compared with the charitable man. But as a rule, prodigals are also for the most part avaricious, being excessive as well in the receipts they accumu- late as in the gifts they make : they are of a grasping disposition, owing to the desire they have to spend, and their inability to indulge their desire. Their own resources being soon exhausted, they are compelled to replenish them by other means ; and at the same time, as they have no regard for what is fitting, they try to gain money from any and every source, as chance may enable them. They simply care for giving ; but as for how they ought to give or whence they ought to re- ceive — for that they have no further concern. Hence their gifts are not really charitable gifts : they are not nobly conceived, nor have they a noble motive, nor are they bestowed in a proper manner; but at times such men enrich those whom it were fitting to be poor; and while they will give nothing to men of sober character, they lavish their wealth freely upon those who flatter them, or who afford them some amusement. Hence prodigals are for the most part sensualists as well. In consequence of their not living according to the law of Eeason, they fall away to the pursuit of pleasures; and in consequence of being habituated to spend lavishly, they grow to be extravagant in their own selfish lusts, and are therefore intensely sensual. But while, on the one hand, the prodigal falls to this low depth of depravity, if he be left without guidance or control, on the other hand, if he be brought under discipline, and meet with proper supervision, he may still attain to a virtuous ideal. iii. — Contrast feetween Liberality and Avarice. On the other hand, avarice is incurable. It is old age and the Prodigality less "^^^d forms of helplessness, which are thought to vicious than make men avaricious. It is, moreover, more *'*™^' thoroughly innate in men than prodigality is, the mass of men being more fond of saving than of giving. It is also a fault of widest range, and assumes many shapes, there being apparently many forms which avarice L/S i^^th" ^^y *^^«- Consisting, as it may, of two condi- combiDation of ra- tions, defect of giving and excess of receiving, it ^"^•"'J!;'? ■"'*'' is 'lo*^ ^o™- •! ' ' Sincerity the ex- man, pression in life of Now in speaking of the ' sincere man ' I am »» upright and , t> • I 1 ij__Li^TT- truthful character. not reierring to one who speaks truthiully in regard to matters of compact, nor in regard to matters which fall within the sphere of Injustice or Justice (such questions belonging to a different form of moral excellence), but rather of the man who is truthful both in word and deed where no material interest is involved, and is truthful simply from having a moral nature which impels him to the true ; and such an one would seem to be an honest man. One who loves the truth, and speaks the truth even on points of immaterial importance, will even more surely speak the truth in questions which are material ; since he has grown to have a horror of falsehood per se, he will have the same horror of it as a thing practically disgraceful. Such a character is worthy of all esteem. In relation to the extremes, the sincere man inclines rather to say what is below than what is beyond the truth, because such a reticence is more in harmony with his character, as is obvious, exaggerations being specially repulsive to him. We win now treat of each of these characters separately, and first of the ideal or standard by which the extremes must be regarded : — i.e. of the sincere man. Now the sincere man is not identical with the man who speaks the truth in matters relating to agreements and similar questions which come under the sphere of Justice or of Injustice (such points forming the province of another and separate virtue), but he is a man who, apart from any sanction of law or of justice, and apart from any urgency of social good, is truthful of speech and consistent in life, simply because he has a moral nature disposing him to 232 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IV. 13. sincerity, and is actuated by the very noblest of motives. He is a man who in all that he says about himself wishes to appear in the eyes of others precisely in the character that in reality he bears. Such an one will of course be an honeet man. When men are truthful even in matters where there is no compulsion to be so, much more will they be true where they are bound to speak the truth in view of the good of society. If a man has a religious horror of falsehood per te, because it is an evil, surely he will avoid it by all means in his power when it entails positive disgrace — when, that is, it is not only an evil par te, but is recognised as such by the world at large. Such, then, is the character of the truthful man, and he is worthy of all esteem for guarding himself as he does from what is evil and disgraceful. In relation to the extremes, if it be necessary for him to deviate at all from the strict line of absolute truth, he will incline to the defect, not the excess : an understatement seems to be more in harmony with- his character, exaggerations being always offensive to him. (c) CHAEACTEKISTICS OF BOASTFTJLNESS. The man who lays claim to qualities superior to what he really possesses, without any particular object to serve, a different com- has a resemblaiicc to the vicious man — otherwise piexiou according }^q would have had no pleasure in falsehood: but as it has a special ,. ii- .i , ^ jjj.i -ij motive, or is the obviously he IS rather empty-headed than wicked, natural outcome of If on the Other hand he has a purpose to serve, tec ai-acter. ^^^ ^j^^^ purpose be glory or honour, he is not so very blameable (considering that it is his disposition to boast) ; yet if that purpose be gain or what is instrumental to gain, his conduct is much more unseemly. The boastful man, however, is what he is, not from having a latent power of boasting, but in virtue of the disposition of his own will — i.e., he is boastful in virtue of a certain bent of his own nature, and in consequence of having formed a certain character; precisely in the same way as the liax is, properly speaking, one who takes pleasure in sheer falsehood, though there are also those who lie from the eagerness with which they strive after honour or gain. So, when men boast themselves;, from a motive of ostentation, they lay claim to qualities for which they may be praised or congratulated ; but when their aim is gain, they lay claim to qualities from which advantage might be reaped by their neighbours ; they claim, for instance, to be clever soothsayers or doctors, and their pretensions, when un- founded, are yet of a nature to escape detection. These useful qualities are, therefore, those to which boastful men generally lay claim and upon which they found exaggerated pretensions, since all the advantages which I have named are found thereio. The boastful man is one who lays claim to higher qualities than he possesses, and supports his pretensions by word and deed. Now if he has no motive to serve in making these pretensions, he seems to be a feeble fellow — otherwise he Bk IV. 13.] Translation. 233 wotdd have no pleasure in falsehood, though obviously he is rather ' empty-headed' than vicious. But if he has an end to gain by hia pretensions, and if that end be glory or honour, the braggart is not so very reprehensible ; W, however, the end he has in view be money, or what amounts to the same thing as money, his conduct is much more unseemly. Now boastfulness does not consist in the latent power which the boastful man has : otherwise, if that had been the case, boastfulness would not have been reprehensible — i.«. it would not have belonged to the category of things voluntary and within our own power. Boastfulness depends upon a disposition of theWiU, and consequently it is shameful as well as reprehensible : — i.e. it is a certain state of the moral nature. It is thus in virtue of a certaiu attitude of mind that the boastful man comes to be what he is ; precisely in the same way as the liar who makes the pretences he does, not for the sake of glory or of money, but from sheer love of falsehood in itself. Those, however, who boast themselves with a view to glory lay claim to the possession of qualities whence praise accrues or the congratulations of others. Those again who boast themselves with a view to profit lay claim to the possession of qualities which are serviceable to their neighbours- — knowledge, for instance, of medicine, or of soothsaying. There aie men who pretend to be skilful doctors or soothsayers in order tiiat, by being thought serviceable to those who resort to them, they may make a profit of their dupes. Such, then, is the character of the boastful man. {d") CHAEACTEEISTICS OF SELF-DISPARAGEMENT. On the other hand, those who disparage themselves by under- stating what they mean, appear to be more winsome and seemly in their moral nature. The Self - depreciation motive which they seem to have in speaking thus delicate and praise- is not a sordid one, but only the avoidance of worthy reticence, what is pompous or self-conceited. What such "fon.^" ^^^ ^ '^'^ *' men are mostly found to deny is their own meritorious deeds, as Socrates used to do. As for those who make an ostentatious claim to merely trifling merits which are seen by all, they only show the affectation of snobs, and are deservedly despised. At times the boastful arrogance of such men peers out as * the pride which apes humility ' or the scant raiment of the Spartans. Extreme self-abasement is as much the cloak of vanity as is extreme boastfulness. However, those who show the diffidence of reserve only to a moderate extent, and depreciate themselves only in regard to things which are not very conspicuous nor plain, are thought to be men of good taste, and to show a graceful refinement. But obviously it is the boastful man who is the opposite of the truthful man, since he is more mischievous than the diffident man. On the other hand, ' the diffident ' or ' reserved ' man is one who lays claim to less merit than he might. Such a man is of course more delicately-minded than the boastful man. The motive for which he disparages himself is not a sordid one, but because he shrinks from ostentation or pomp and the assumption of grandeur. So then, the man who in self -depreciation repudiates the honom-able 2 34 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IV. 14. qualities which belong to him, as Socrates, for instance, used to do, seems to be a man of fine and delicate feeUng. If, however, he repudiates not only great and distinguished qualities but also trifling merits, and pretends not to be able to perform things which it is palpable that he can achieve, — such a man is called an ' affected snob,' and is deserving of contempt. For similar reasons such a man is sometimes called vain-glorious, acting in the spirit which the Spartans showed in the matter of their dress. Self-abasement is as much a sign of vanity as is self -exaltation. When, however, men use this reserve of speech in moderation, they appear only to show good taste — when, that is, they do not show their diffi- dence in matters that are trifling and cheap and perfectly obvious. So then the diffident man and the boastful man are both in opposition to the truthful man, but the boastful man is the more viddely opposed of the two. Boasting is a more mischievous evil than diffidence, as is obvious from the reasons given above. J.— HUMOUR. (a) SUBJECT-MATTEK OF HUMOUR AND OF ITS OPPOSITES DEFINED. But there is an element of rest in the conduct of life, and during rest there are pastimes for men which are attended hlvr'tS'^o™ ^y amusement; and here, too, as in more serious exigencies, and ad- pursuits, intercourse may take a graceful shape, rf^a °l edai virtue^ ^^^ ^ "^^'^ ^^^ ^^^ *^^ ^^^^ things which he ought to say in the most perfect manner, or listen to the words of others in the same spirit : (though there will be a differ- ence whether the man is a speaker or listener, and between the character of the audience, whatever it be in either case). It is evident that here, too, is a sphere of circumstance in which the ideal of perfect propriety may be violated either by excess or defect. Now those who are extravagant in their indulgence of humour are thought frivolous and vulgar people, being as they are eager for frivolity, in season and out of season, and more intent upon ex- citing laughter than on speaking what is becoming, or avoiding pain to the object of their ridicule. There are others again who could never of themselves have uttered a joke, and who show irritation against those who do; and they are regarded as morose and soured. But since there are times of relaxation and rest in human Ufe, and in snch times of relaxation there is a kind of pastime which goes hand in hand with diversion, there seems to be, here as elsewhere, a mode of intercourse which is at once graceful and virtuous, and it is possible for a man who requires such relax- ation to say just the things lyhich ought to be said and to say them in the most graceful manner, and in the same spirit to be a listener only when the subject is decorous and the manner in which it is said and the occasion of saying it are equally appropriate (though there is a difference between listening to things and sayiug them, whatever the character of the things said be in either case). It is evident, therefore, that in this kind of intercourse (as in that which is Bk. IV. 14.] Translation, 235 more serious,) there is one state of mind which is an extravagance, another which is a deficiency, and, between the two, the perfect mean of virtue. Now the extravagance of humour is called buffoonery, ani those who show it, buffoons and vulgar people : such are they who indulge in excess of merriment, and are more anxious to excite laughter than they are to say what is becoming or to avoid paining the object of their ridicule. The defect of humour is moroseness and sourness, and those who show it are ' morose and sour : such men never utter a joke of their own, and are annoyed at and detest those who do. {b) CHAEACTBKISTICS OF REAL AND PERFECT HUMOUR. Those who exhibit playfulness in good taste are called ' quick- witted,' being as it were lively and versatile. The playful movements of their wit seem to be move- M"^adrtatim*''of ments of the character ; and just as the nature of wit to the phases bodies is indicated by their movements, so is it ™gj,^acter^**"°^^ with the character. As, however, the sphere of merriment covers the very surface of society, and the mass of men delight in playfulness and the making of jests to an extent beyond what is right, frivolous people are also styled 'quick- witted ' as being amusing and pleasant to their companions ; though from what has been already said, it is clear that there is a difference, and that no slight difference, between the two. A further trait, characteristic of perfect humour, is that of tact or cleverness ; and the man of tact and 'cleverness is known by his making only such remarks him- ^^^* ^'"^combiTed self, or listening to them in others, as befits the with gentlemanly character of a considerate and right-minded iBstincta, essential ,1 „, ° . 1 . to perfect humour. gentleman. There are, 01 course, certain thmgs which it is consistent for a gentleman to say himself, or to listen to in others, in the way of fun, and the fun of a gentleman is a very different thing from that of a clown, as, again, the fun of an educated man is from that of an illiterate boor. This is a truth which we may see illustrated in the comedies of the Old School as contrasted with those of the New. In the Old Comedy wit meant scurrility and obscenity : in the New Comedy it means innuendo. These points make no slight difference in view of what is decorous. May we, then, define the man who makes a display of perfect humour by such limitations as that of his ' saying only what becomes a gentleman ? ' or by the condition of ' his avoiding giving pain to his hearers ? ' [or by the terms of ' his giving them pleasure ? ' — Is not such a limitation too vague, seeing that the idea of what is hateful or agreeable differs with different tempera- ments ?] 236 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IV. U. But the character of what he himself says will determine also the character of the things to which he will listen, since a man seems himself to do what he endures to hear from others. Cer- tainly there are things which he will not do : there are certain modes of scoffing which are of the nature of insult, and there are certain modes of insult which lawgivers forbid men to employ. [Still there are perchance sallies of humour which he is con- strained to make.] The man then who is courteous and high- minded will comport himself throughout as though he were ' a law to himself.' Such, then, is the ideal character therein, whether the name given to him be ' a man of tact ' or of social versatility. The ideal state is playfiibiess or politeness, and tliose who. show it are those who are polite. Their politeness is, as it were, a kind of quiok-wittedness, the shifting phases of their character seeming to be like the movements of the body ; and such is the aspect of those who disport themselves in good taste, and show their humour in a proper manner and on proper occasions. Just as physical movements show the character of bodies (e.^., movement upwards indicating fire and whatever is light, movement towards a centre indicating a heavy substance, and similarly in regard to bodies generally), so also from the outward movements of men that are obvious to aU, the mental dispositions of the soul and the phases of the character are made manifest. Now since souied men are very rarely found, and the mass of men delight in amusement and jokes, what is amusing is thought a good rather than what is solemn. Consequently buffoons ai'e called ' quick-witted ' as being amusing and pleasant. But from what has been said it is obvious that buffoons differ not inconsiderably from those who are really quick-witted and humorous. Men of this class who are quick-witted are also men of tact, and the quality they show may fairly be called ■' tact.' It marks the man of tact to say himself, and to listen to others saying, only such things as befit the character of a virtuous and high-minded gentleman. There are certain things which specially befit a gentleman to say and to listen to in the way of amusement. The pleasantries of the gentleman are a different thing from those of the vulgar, and those of the educated man are distinct from those of the uneducated. This difference may be niustrated from the Old and New Comedies. There are some comedians who represent low and vulgar life, and fancy that what is shameful is amusing and agreeable ; and there are others who represent clever, virtuous, and gentlemanlike characters, and use innuendo. These various phases differ in no slight degree in respect of seemliness. Whom, then, do we recognize as the ideal character in the amusements of life ? Is he not the man who \ okes cleverly, and who shows himself a gentleman in the best sense — one who is not offensive to his hearers, and is positively pleasing and agree- able ? That may be our definition of the ideal in respect of social amusements. This definition, however, seems in a way to be indefinite. The feelings of hate are not always entertained towards the same objects, nor do all men have pleasure in the same objects : one thing appears pleasant to one man, and another to another, and different things are painful to different persons. But what a man delights in, that it is about which he talks, and that it is which he does in his intercourse vidth his fellows. He utters himself such jests as he endures to hear from others. For there are some things which hewiU never say: there are certain taunts which lawgivers restrain men from employing. The joke is of the nature of a taunt. Inasmuch then as the^ objects which we hate, or in which we find pleasure are undefined and undefinable, it is consequently difficult to fix with scientific precision the nature of the ideal chaiacta' in social Bk. IV. 14.] Translation. ^2,7 amusements. The man wlio is high-minded and courteous will tehave as though he were ' a law to Mmaelf .' Such, then is the character of the ideal character hereii^ whether the name given to him he ' quick-witted,' or ' full of tact.' (c) CHAEACTERISTTCS OF BUFFOONERY. Oa the other hand, the buifoon is the slave of his own merri- ment. He cannot refrain from deriding either himself or others, if only he can raise a laugh, dulgeshiswitirre- though he say things which a courteous man spectiveiy of ail would under no circumstances say himself, and ™'*^*ions. even some things which such a man would not suffer others to say in his presence. The buffoon, on the other hand, in the craving he feels for merriment abstains from no single opportunity of saying or doiag aught that would provoke laughter, and therein he spares neither himself nor those who listen to him. In order simply to excite amusement he shames himself and his hearers by saying and doing things which a courteous man would on no terms say and do ; and some- times things which he would never endure to hear. {d) CHARACTERISTICS OF THE BOOR. The boor, again, is a man useless on all occasions of social re- laxation. Never contributing any amusement out of his own fund, he is surly to everybody else who ^^^ ^PPl, ^^ ""« 1 __,.'. / , ^1 who dislikes the does. Yet relaxation and amusement seem to be sunnier side of life, essential elements in the conduct of life. The boor, again, is a man useless on aU occasions of social relaxation. He is iaeither agreeable himself and he loathes those who are differently disposed. Such a character is censurable, inasmuch as relaxation and amusement are essential, ia view of the conditions of human life. (e) REVIEW OF THE VIRTUES MANIFESTED IN SOCIAL INTERCOURSE. There are, then, the three excellences which have been described shown in the intercourse of life, and they all have relation to the mingling of mind with mind in conversation or in business. The points upon which they differ are that one has regard to simple truth, the other two are concerned with what is agreeable. Of these latter, the one excellence is shown in times of gaiety, and the other in the social gatherings which take place in the general con- duct of life. There are then three forms of excellence shown in life in the intercourse which men have one with another. One form of excellence finds its sphere in Truth, having for its extremes on either side flattery and reserve ; and two other excellences find a province in the Agreeable, of which one is what is called 238 Tlie Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IV. 15. courtesy, having for its extremes on either side, flattery and peevishness, and the other is versatility and tact, of which the extremes are buffoonery on the one side, and sourness and boorishness on the other : for of course both the courteous and the versatile man cause a certain amount of pleasure in life. K.— SENSE OF SHAME. KEASONS WHY A SENSE OF SHAME IS ONLY A Q JT-^iSJ-VIETDE. It is improper to speak of the sense of shame as though it were one of the virtues. It has a nearer resemblance only aquasi-virtiie^ to an emotion than to a permanent state of mind, it is rather physi- The definition, at any rate, which is given of it, ca an mora . -^ ^^^^ ^j. ^^ ^^ Certain apprehension of dishonour.' The results which it produces are very nearly akin to a sense of fear in presence of dangers : those who are affected with shame turn red, just as men turn pale when in fear of death. It is evi- dent, therefore, that both these states are physical conditions; which seems to be characteristic of a passing emotion, rather than of a confirmed habit. Again, this is aa emotion which is not suitable to all times of , , . life, but only to the period of youth. We con- properiypredicated sider- it the duty of those who are young to only of the young, be modest and bashful, owing to the constant doubtful compli- faults they commit, living as they do the life of ment to pay even emotion and Under its control, and, on the other ^^' hand, owning the restraint of shame. Again, while we praise the young when they are bashful, no one would ever eulogise an old man on the ground of his being shamefaced : we think it the duty of an old man never to da anything on the score of which shame might arise. Shame is indeed no element in the life of an honest man, seeing that it is only occasioned by what is evil, and evil deeds he must never commit. As for some things being disgraceful per se in their veritable nature, while other things are only 'disgraceful conven- tionally, the difference is immaterial : we ought never to do a disgraceful deed of any kind, so that for neither ought we ever to feel shame. It marks a depraved nature to be of such a dis- position as ever to do an act that is disgraceful. Again, for a man to have such a disposition, as that he would feel shame if he mere to do aught disgraceful, and At best it is a hy- on that account to fancy himself a virtuous man f^Sctnoe is'beuer -^^^^ ^ ^n absurd idea :^shame only arises at than repentance Voluntary acts, and the virtuous man will never Bk. IV. 15.] Translation. 239 of his own accord do vicious acts. At best, shame (though if & man would only be conditionally a good thing: — sms, it is better to i.e. if a man were to do so and so, he would feel* shame ; but that is not a condition which applies to the virtues. Again, though shamelessness is an evil, as also the absence of awe in doing shameful things, none the more on that account is it a good that a man who commits evil deeds should feel shame. Even self-control is not a virtue, but only a complex combination of virtue and vice ; but of self-control a discussion will be held in the progress of the work We will now treat of Justice. Now a sense of Shame is not a virtue. It is not a permanent state of mind, hut only a passing emotion. So much is clear from its definition . it is defined as ' an apprehension of dishonour.' Very nearly the same conditions are found in the man who is ashamed as in the man who is fearful in regard to dangers. The man who is ashamed turns red, just as the man who is afraid of death turns pale. Both these sensations, shame and the fear of what is terrible, are evidently in. a sense pliysical sensations ; and being such they seem to be rather emotions than habits (and indeed they are never called habits). Again, the emotion of shame is not suitable to all times of life, but simply to the period of youth. It is right that the young should be modest and bashful on account of the many errors into which they fall. The young commit constant faults, inasmuch as they are influenced by feeling rather than by reason ; and thus, called to order by a sense of shame, they become better. Hence all young men who are modest are commended ; whereas no one would commend an elderly man on the ground that he was shamefaced. An elderly man bught not to commit deeds from which shame might arise. Shame of course is no characteristic of a virtuous man, since it only arises from evil courses. Again, though some things are disgraceful in veritable truth and per so, while other things are not so intrinsically but only by repute, it is a man's duty to flee from both alike if he would be virtuous. By thus fleeing from what is shameful, he wUl never experience a sense of shame. Again, as for a man fancying that the simple act of feeling shame is in itself a sign of a virtuous character, on the supposition of his doing any sliamef ul act, and fancying that this attitude of mind, itself incidental of evil, is virtuous, — that is absurd. Shame is caused on the consciousness of disgraceful deeds ; but the virtuous man wOl never voluntarily do on any occasion a disgraceful act. It is obvious, therefore, that shame is not a form of virtue, but rather an emotion. It is not under all circumstances commendable, nor can it absolutely and in itself be called a virtuous condition, but only conditionally. For example, if it should befall a man to commit a fault, it is right that he should have a sense of shame for his fault. But the virtues do not come under this condition ; they are rather permanent states, inasmuch as they are under all circumstances inherent in the soul. Again, though shame seems to be a kind of ' mean ' and is midway between nervousness and shamelessness, and the man who shows shame is praised while censure is given as well to those who are shameless in regard to disgraceful deeds as to those who are more sensitive than is right in reference thereto (whom we call the ' nervous '), shame is not any the more on that account a virtue. Though virtue is a mean state, not every mean state is a virtue : the two terms are not convertible. [So neither is Self-control a virtue but a kind of combination of virtue and vice. But an explanation will be given of this in the progress of this work.] We win now treat of Justice. BOOK V.-EXAMINATION OF THE VIRTUES {Continued). INTRODUCTORY ANALYSIS. L.— JUSTICE. The examination of the Moral Virtues concludes with Justice, which in one sense comprehends all the others. This subject occupies the whole of the Fifth Book, and is presented under a variety of changing aspects which represent a long vista of theories advanced by previous thinkers. At one time Justice is rightness of life, the perfect and unswerving allegiance of the will to the requirements of the moral law ; at another time it is the fair apportionment of civil honours or social burdens to the proper subjects of them; at another time it is the redressing of wrong, the award of punishment to adjust the inequalities of fraud and crime. The method of the Book is less developed than in the other parts of the Treatise. The transitions are less obvious, the repetitions more frequent. The first half of the book seems to be occupied rather with the distinctions of Justice and of Injustice as they are found in common life, and in the public relations of the citizens. The latter half leads rather to questions of casuistry, and to the grounds and origin of Justice. The whole book will fall not unnaturally under XV divisions, which rarely cross one another. (i.) GENEEAL OONOEPXION OP JUSTICE ATSD INJUSTICE : THEIR DEFINITIOIT AND DIVISION. There are three main aspects under which Justice may be regarded— as exemplified in the actual conduct of men, as a state of mind leading to conduct, and as an external standard. These three aspects are mutually involved in one another, but are all essential to the conception, as will be seen from a consideration of the Definition and Division of Justice. Justice as a virtue must be a formed state of mind or fixed tendency, (c|is), not a mere capacity for doing certain things. A capacity for one thing implies a capacity for another ; but a good tree cannot bring forth Introductory Analysis: Book V. 241 evil fruit, and the mental habit of the just man is so fixed, that he cannot do other than just actions. The perfect attitude of morality (f^is irpoaipETiKri) involves also a determination of the mil which again is inseparable from 'wish' or 'desire.' The definition of Justice will, therefore, be ' a formed attitude of the moral nature, in virtue whereof we are capable of performing just actions and actually do so, and have further a personal desire for what is just.' Injustice is the reverse of this — ' a habit which leads men to the commission of what is wrong and to wish for what is wrong.' The actions, however, which result from such a state of mind are various. If we take the case of a man who is unjust, we find the term used to denote either a man who is universally vicious, or a law-breaker in the widest -sense, or else a man who is unfair in his dealings — one who is 'unequal' in the apportionment of what lies within his own power to divide between himself and others. We can at once infer what the opposite of the unjust man is : he is either a man whose life fulfils all the requirements of law in their widest sense ; or else, in a more particular sense, is one who takes no advantage of others, but gives to each their due. Justice itself therefore will either be what is lawful or what is proportionate : Injustice what is unlawful or else what is dis- proportionate and unequal. The field in which Injustice of this narrower kind will be displayed, will be that of the external goods of hfe. The unjust man will strive to get an undue share of the gifts of fortune, and shrink from bearing his fair proportion of life's burdens. (ii.) CHARACTERISTICS OF UNIVERSAL JUSTICE AND INJUSTICE. If, then. Justice be in its widest sense conformity to law, and law covers the same ground as morality. Justice and Morality will be coextensive. That such is the case is manifest. The aim of law is to promote social happiness : its provisions are designed to secure the well- being of the state, and its sanctions are framed for the repression of those crimes which mar that well-being. The man, therefore, who obeys the laws promotes, so far as in him lies, the good of his fellows. He is a morally perfect man, and his perfection is of the highest order. He achieves what is so difi&cult of achievement — the exercise of virtue towards others : he is not good in the merely passive sense ; but he is actively benevolent and true in his dealings with the community. The only difference between Justice and Righteousness is this : Justice, while involving precisely the same moral conditions as Righteousness from the subjective point of view, has further relations with others, and is thus ' righteousness manifested in action.' Injustice is the exact reverse : utter and consummated depravity practised to the injury of others — not merely viciousness of nature, but the practical outcome of viciousness as seen in deeds of wrong from which society suffers. (iii.) CHARACTERISTICS OP CIVIL JUSTICE AS DISTINGUISHED FROM UNIVERSAL JUSTICE. The following arguments may be used to show that Universal is distinct from Particular Justice. 1, The coward often gets no advantage 242 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. from his cowardice, and therefore is not overreaching ; .while conversely the man who is overreaching is not otherwise vicious. 2. An action is altered in character by the motive for which it is done. Adultery for gain is a different thing from adultery for passion. 3. Overreaching will not come under the category of any other vice; and as all the varieties of moral failure must be classified, it must necessarily form a class by itself. But the genm of Universal Justice is the same as that of Particular Justice : they both have reference to other men. The objects, howevef, with which Particular Justice is concerned, are wealth, honour and social advantages ; whereas the objects upon which Universal Justice is exercised, are the various aspects of the moral ideal. For the purposes of the present examination. Universal Justice, or the realization of the moral ideal in practical life, may be dismissed : it belongs more properly to the sphere of Statesmanship and will be dealt with in the Treatise on Politics. (iv.) DIVISIONS OP CIVIL JUSTICE INTO (l) DISTRIBUTIVE, (2) CORRECTIVE. Civil Justice, as the application of the principle of equality to the trans- actions in which the citizens are concerned or in which they take part, has a twofold character corresponding to two main aspects of civil life — the adjustment of honours and burdens, and the remedying of wrongs. It is thus either ' distributive ' or ' remedial.' 1. Distributive Justice is the ' assigning to each his due ' in regard to the honours and emoluments, the burdens and responsibilities which enter into the common life of the citizens. What is ' due to each ' is what is ' equal ' ; and therefore distributive justice is the assigning to each member of the state ' the equality ' which is relative to his position. 2. Corrective Justice is the adjustment of the mutual rights which citizens have in their transactions and arrangements one with another. If those transactions are voluntary, such as are the contracts which men make for buying and selling, remedial justice rectifies any unfair advantage which one citizen may have taken over another. If again those relations are involuntary, remedial justice redresses the wrong done by the infliction of punishment j whether the wrong be of the nature of fraud, as theft or perjury, or whether it take the shape of violence, as outrage, assault or assassination. Application of Mathematical formulae to the principles of Civil Justice. Since what is unjust is what is unequal, what is just must be what is equal ; and since what is equal is a mean between two inequalities, what is just will also be a mean. But if the just is what is equal and a mean point, what is the principle by which this equality is determined? Evidently the principle of proportion, of which the geometrical form will be applicable to Distributive Justice, and the arithmetical form to Corrective Justice. Introductory Analysis: Book V. 243 (v.) DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE EXPLAINED. • DistributiTe Justice proceeds after the metliod of geometrical pro- portion. It does not regard the persons affected by the division of honours as simple units, but takes their separate worth into the account. It equalizes the honours to be divided with the character and merits of the persons among whom they are to be apportioned. For instance, the honour assigned to Ajax will bear precisely thg same relation to the honour paid to Achilles, that the worth of Ajax does to the worth of Achilles. Each term will therefore be compared with each other ; and this may be done either separately or in combination. If these con- siderations are neglected, and the differences between the persons and the things be not taken into the account, the distribution wiU be unequal, and there will be injustice. (vi.) COEEECTIVB JUSTICE EXPLAINED. Corrective Justice, on the other hand, proceeds on the method of arithmetical proportion, having simple regard to the equalizing of a wrong, without respect of persons. Its province is that of contracts and the transactions which are incidental to the personal relations between the citizens with one another. In these transactions one may gain an advantage over another, or inflict direct injury upon another. It is the business of the Judge to whom recourse is made by the persons aggrieved to take away from the aggressor or the man who has reaped the advantage from the transaction, an equivalent : he inflicts a punishment which will represent the measure of the wrong done. No account can be taken of the condition of the persons affected : the law simply looks to the violation of a contract, and redresses the wrong independently of the accidental associations of the case. A case of wrong is set right with the same impersonal impartiality as that with which a mathematician cuts off a section from the greater of two lines and adds it to the less. That is also the principle of commerce — ex- change being regulated by reciprocal accommodation, in which each gives as much as he receives : the buyer gets a fair equivalent for his money, and the seller for his goods. (vii.) EXAMINATION OF THE PTTHAGOBEAN THEOET OF JUSTICE, EETALIATION. There is a theory in some respects identical with the above — that Justice is ' retaliation.' The Pythagoreans, who held this view, claimed for it the authority of Rhadamanthus ; and it has indeed much to commend it, if it be duly qualified and adjusted to the actual circum- stances of life. But, boldly stated, it does not apply either to Dis- tributive or to Remedial Justice. (1) In Distributive Justice retribution cannot always be in kind — ' an eye for an eye, and a tooth for a tooth.' Regard must be paid to the differences which persons and circumstances make : an exact and literal retribution would create a worse wrong than that which it professed to right. (2) In Remedial Justice the relations between the wrong and its remedy are necessarily diverse ; E 2 244 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. and justice demands a proportionate and analogous retribution, not one identical in kind. Nevertheless retribution plays an important part in social life, and is an essential element in Justice. The return of kindnesses is the principle of gratitude : the return of injuries is the principle of punish- ment. But for the mutual interchange of kindly offices, the inner life of society would be destroyed ; and but for the avenging of wrongs, all freedom would be undermined. ^ Still the theory must not he applied without ample qualification : the retribution must not be an absolute one but be ' according to a due proportion.' That is the very principle of exchange. Society does not consist of a single class but of diverse classes : there are physicians, farmers, builders, vintners, &c. ; and their various claims and capabilities must be adjusted to a proper scale of proportion. They must first of all be compared one with another, and their relative values must be determined : the degree in which the one exceeds the other, or falls short, must be estimated. For example, if a vintner and a farmer wish to exchange commodities, a comparison must be made between a sack of corn and a bottle of wine, the com being worth twenty-four shillings and the wine eight, it will be evident that the proportion which the com will hold to the wine is that of 3 : 1 ; and hence the vintner will give three bottles of wine for one sack of corn. But what is the standard or measure of value ? The most time- honoured standard, and that which is most rooted in the nature of things, is that of demand : the value of a thing is determined by oiu* need of it and the uses which it consequently serves. But practically the value of a thing is determined by what it will fetch : by uniwsal convention money is the measure of value — money being the repre- sentative of want. Money represents a permanent possibility of supply : it is the security for the supply of numberless things which a man may not want for the present but which money will get for him at any timfe in the future. It is therefore the universal medium of exchange : there is nothing but what has a value, and that value can be estimated in money. Hence it is that money makes all things commensurable — capable of being compared one with another ; and though in itself money is purely a thing of convention and of artificial value, yet its associations have rendered it not merely a sign of value, but as valuable as commodities themselves. (viii.) JUSTICE OONSIDEEED AS A ' MEAN.' The moral virtues generally seem to depend entirely upon subjective conditions : they are themselves ' mean states,' and the ideal of which they are the expression is embodied in the moral consciousness. But in the case of Justice the moral conditions are rather external than internal. Justice is not merely nor mainly a state of mind, but rather conformity to outward law. The wish to do what is right is of course an integral part of the conception, but no less important is the know- ledge of the requirements of positive law, and the fulfilment of those requirements in practice. Justice is, therefore objective — a standard fixed by the statesman, and involved in the constitution of society : tlie Introductory Analysis: Book V. 245 corresponding attitude of mind is the desire and intention to regulate one's own conduct in conformity with, that standard, (ix.) DISTINCTION BETWEEN THE UNJUST ACT AND THE UNJUST CHAEAOTEE. It will consequently happen that at times the dispositions of the agent may be perfectly right and his act perfectly wrong, or conversely that the act will be just, though the disposition of the agent is to be unjust. The justice of the act is no proof of the justice of the agent, nor is the justice of the agent certain security for the justice of his act. (x.) METAPHOBICAL APPLICATIONS OF TH? IDEA OP JUSTICE. Justice in the strict sense of the term can only exist among citizens who share equal rights and have an equal claim to the protection of the law. Those who share in the government, and who have relations towards one another defined by law, can injure or be injured by one another. When a citizen has less than his fair share of the common emoluments or honours of the state, he has recourse to the law to redress his injury ; and when a citizen has had an advantage taken of him by another, the state equalizes the wrong done. The redressing of wrongs does not depend upon individual caprice, but upon the unfaltering standard of law. Justice in this sense as ' the adjustment of social relations between citizens in view of the harmonious development of the State ' cannot exist among slaves or children. The justice which regulates the con- duct of a father in dealing with his children, or the conduct of a master in dealing with his slaves, is only justice in a metaphorical sense. The child is a part of his father, and no one can injure himself. The slave again is a kind of possession. There is therefore no place for wrong among such beings as children or slaves : they are on no basis of equality with free citizens : they cannot claim the rights which are secured to those who are ' free and eqjial ': they have no recognised position in the State. (xi.) DISTINCTION BETWEEN NATURAL AND POSITIVE LAW. The basis of Justice has been variously sought in Nature aad in Law. Natural right is that which is independent of society, and has St sanction binding on the reason whether any particular nation accept it or no. Positive right is that which owes its sanction to the enactments of law. Natural right is unalterable : positive right may be abrogated by the power which enacted it. Natural right is the expression of immutable reason : positive right is a thing indifferent, per se, and deriving all its obligation from the penalties which sanction it. But as there are diverse kinds of commonwealths, so there are diverse kinds of laws ^ and this diversity has made men think that Justice is only convention or compact, and not a thing in itself immutable. But tlje changes in Justice refer only to such aspects as come within the cognisance of law : there is still an ideal independent of and superior to the exigencies of society. The genus is the same, though the species present innumerable variations. 246 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. (xii.) JUSTICE CONSIDERED IN RELATION TO THE WILL. It was shown in detail in Book III., that the WiU was the essential aspect of morality, and the conclusions there arrived at may be repeated here. In the analysis of moral action it was shown that a man was not to be accounted good or bad unless his will co-operated in a certain line of conduct. If an action is not agreeable to the agent, the character of that act is accidental : it may in its outward consequences be good or evil, but it is impossible to infer from it the state of the agent. There are two conditions essential to volvmtariness : (1) knowledge, and (2) power. The agent must know the circumstances of his action, its tendency and the various conditions which determine its nature. He must also have moral freedom, and act without compulsion except from his own conscience. Otherwise the act is involuntary, and its character accidental. The injuries therefore which men do will fall under three classes : 1. Wrongs which are done through ignorance of the circumstances, and which are errors or mishaps, as when he is unaware of the instrument he is using, and who it is that he is striking. 2. Wrongs which are done with an evil intent and maliciously. 3. Wrongs which are unintentional though the agent was notmicon- scious of what he was doing ; such as are the wrongs done through passion. These different kinds of wrongs will be regarded with different degrees of censure. Some are pardonable and others are not. Acts are pardon- able which are done through an error, or ignorance of the circumstanues, or through justifiable passion. Acts are not pardonable when done in consequence of a state of mind which is neither natural nor worthy of man. (1) Can the Will consent to the suffering of a wrong? There seems a contradiction of terms in supposing that the suffering of injury can be a voluntary act. Yet there is a difficulty in under- standing how certain acts can be otherwise than voluntary. Perhaps the solution of the difficulty may be found in the fact that there is a difference between being injured and suffering an injury. Just as a man may do unjust things either " voluntarily or involuntarily, though no one can act unjustly except by deliberate choice ; so, too, a man may suffer what is unjust, voluntarily or involuntarily, though no one can suffer imjustly except against his wiU. In the proper sense of the term therefore, the suffering of injury is always an involimtary act. If Glaucus gives an exchange with Diomede which is unequal, he is not acting against his own will, though he suffers loss. Nor again is the sensualist injured voluntarily : what he suffers is against his reason and real wish. (2) In an unjust distribution, who is unjust ? Is the man who makes an unjust distribution unjust, or rather the man who profits by it ? The man who makes the distribution has the responsibility of originating the action, and he is to blame rather than the man who receives the distribution : his will is free, whereas the Introductory Analysis: Book V. 247 will of the man who receives the distribution is not free. The latter simply is the recipient of what is assigned to him, and the fault does not lie at his door. • Is the man who assigns to himself less than his due thereby wronged \ Certainly not : though he appears to receive less of external goods, in fact, he is no loser. The loss which he appears to undergo is compen- sated for by far more precious advantages. He gains the praise of moderation, of scrupulosity, of generosity, and of kindred virtues. He conciliates the goodwill of his neighbours who trumpet his liberality. (xiii.) DIFFICULTY OF THE ATTA.INMENT OF JUSTICE. Men commonly think that it is an easy thing to be just for the reason that the opposite, injustice, is within our own power and dependent on our own will. But Justice is not simply the performance of just actions, but the performance of them with a certain intention, and as the out- come of a certain frame of mind. It requires therefore a certain mental habit, or formed disposition of character, which only the discipline of many years can instil into us. Men think again that it is not difficult to know what is just and what is unjust, since the requirements of justice are comprised in legal codes which are published for all men to read and digest. But Justice does not depend upon the knowledge of abstract principles, but rather in the details of action, in the fine distinctions of circumstance which have to be moulded and adjusted according to those abstract principles. Justice applies only to those who are equal. There are some who are immeasurably beyond ourselves, and to whom therefore we can never assign too much of worldly honour and dignity : such are the magistrates, or our parents. There are others who are correspondingly below us, such as convicts and others, who are so degraded that we can never assign them too little, lest they should abuse such things to their own destruction. Those to whom Justice, as the principle of equality, must be shown, are such as are sharers in common burdens and have an equal claim to the honours of the state, and neither a greater nor a less claim than ourselves. (xiv.) BELATIONS BETWEEN EQUITY AND JUSTICE DBTEKMINED. It is evident that the equitable is not identical with the just, because we praise the equitable man as being morally better than the just man when the equitable man yields something of his strict rights, which the just man will not do ; and, further, the equitable man is spoken of synonymously with the good man. But neither is- Equity contrary to Justice : both alike are estimable and meet with the approbation of the moral sense. The diiferences between Equity and Justice are mainly these. Equity is better than legal Justice : it softens the absolute rigour of written law and amends the wrongs which abstract right might cause. It does not depend upon written words and ' the letter which killeth,' but upon 248 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. the moral sense and educated perception of the good man. It does not deal with universals, but with particulars — not with general propositions, but with actual circumstances. Written law is of necessity sometimes at fault. The nature of circumstances presenting an ever-changing aspect cannot be always anticipated : the variations of the conditions of actual life baffle such generalization. Again, laws are always framed as universal propositions ; and must, in fact, become a kind of equity if they are to be applied honestly to particular cases. It follows that Equity is a supplementing or rectifying of the omissions of the law or of provisions which are not adequate to meet the complica- tions of particular circumstances. The equitable man interprets the intention of the legislator in framing the law ; and applies the same principle in spirit to the determination of his duty in the actual circum- stances before him. He endeavours to place himself in the position of the legislator, and to act as he would have acted had he foreseen such contingencies. Equity may, therefore, be defined as a rectification of legal enactments in such aspects where the law fails in a particular case owing to its universality. The equitable man accordingly is one whose desire is to waive his own strict rights, though the law would justify his claim, and whose temper leads him to interpret the law to his own hindrance rather than to that of his neighbours. (xv.) FURTHER SOLUTION OP TWO QUESTIONS RELATING TO JUSTICE. (1) Can a man injure himself? The arguments already advanced will have made it evident that a man cannot injure himself. There are, however, writers, who produce the case of the suicide as evidence that a man can injure himself. " The suicide," they say, " does an evil deed tacitly forbidden by law — since law forbids all slaughter which it does not expressly enjoin. Moreover, the suicide has no injury to requite, but deliberately does an evil deed ; and of course against himself." .... Nay, but it is not the man himself who suffers harm (since it was shown that no man is injured of his own wUl), but rather the State ; and it is the State consequently which inflicts a penalty upon him, depriving him of sepulture. There are yet other arguments to show that suicide is not self-injury. (1) Injustice implies relations with others : a man cannot isolate one part of himself against another, so as to fulfil this condition of Justice. (2) A man cannot be agent and patient in one. (3) A man cannot be injured voluntarily. (4) AU crime is harm to others : a man cannot harm himself. (5) The whole theory of 'the voluntary' is at variance with such an idea. (2) Is it worse, to do an injury or to receive one ? Both alike, as departures from the ideal of the mean, are evils, but the doing of injury is associated with a depravity in the agent, and is therefore, per se, the greater evil. TEANSLATION. L.— JUSTICE. i. — General coneeptions of Justice and of Injustice. {a) PROVISIONAL DEFINITION OF JUSTICE AND OF INJUSTICE. In treating of Justice and of Injustice the points which we have to consider are : CD what kjnd^ pf Jiftianii-.tliBv are in which Justice and Iniustice are displavecL Scope of the m- ____^^__„ ,..<-..«„.„. „•„«,,., »'V^>njw—--*--«--»-*™^''r°^ quiry, and expla- (2 ) wtot kaajafc a- naeaw juistice is,"as -an ia«ai nation of terms. frame of mind. a|nf^ ^(gj^ ' %V^^' aTe -lh e-iextremes ' ^l^een. which. Jaglaas*,J^s,jltomfll^^ The inquiry will be carried on according to the same plan as our previous investigations. We see at once that all men are willing to defin e Justice as \ a state of mind of such a complexion, that in conseq uenceT thereof ^ n are en abled to do just deeds , an^ln 'facT'^^_dealjus|I^ and have a d e sire fof -W^hafiij \\iM\: ' /and tJEaTcontrariwise Injustice is ' a F.tate of mmd which leads men to act unjustly, and to desire what is unjust.') This view of Justice may, at starting, be assumed as indicating in outline its real nature. [Justice is described as a ' frame of mind,' not a mere capacity, because the conditions involved in a 'frame of mind ' are very different from those involved in a Justice a_ formed mere faculty or intellectual capacity. A faculty ^ctv^^j{s%^a^s). or an intellectual capacity seems to be the same for opposites ; but a frame of mind, as a permanent disposition, cannot produce opposite effects. For instance, from a healthy state of body the only functions that can be developed are healthy functions, and not such as are destructive of itself : — we say that a man walks healthily when he walks as a man in perfect health should do.] We will now at once proceed to treat of Justice and of Injustice, and show tlie nature of the actions in which they are displayed, the nature of the ' mean ' which 250 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. V. 1. makes Justice an ideal frame of mind, the nature of Justice as ' abstract right ' and a 'mean' term between extremes, and the nature of the extremes which lie on either side of this ideal ' right.' We will conduct our inquiry upon the same method as that which ha« guided us in our inquiry into the other vii-tues. Now we see that all the world calls Justice a frajne of mind by the possession of which we are enabled to perform just actions, and in fact do act uprightly and desire what is just. Injustice men define on the same principle : they oaU Injustice a frame of mind, in consequence of which we act unjustly and desire what is unjust. We may here assume the accuracy of these common views ; and define Jiistice and Injustice respectively, in outline, as ' a frame of mind in virtue whereof we do (or do not) desire what is just.' [We must always attach to the moral virtues the condition of wish or purpose : it is impossible for them otherwise to be defined — except as modes of purpose or of wOl : — it is owing to the wish that a man has to be temperate and to act justly that he grows to be temperate and just. Of course in the case of faculties and intellectual capacities, the possession of power is essential, the wish to exercise that power is not essential : if a man have the power of curing disease, he is a physician whether he use his power or not ; and similarly in the case of the other intellectual powers. In the case, however, of the moral virtues, the con- ditions are changed. The power of doing just actions is often within the means even of an unjust man, but the desire to do just actions is characteristic of none but the just. Hence a man is just even though he be unable to perform just actions, provided he has the desire and possesses the frame of mind which charac- terises Justice. In the same way a man is unjust if he has the roish to be unjust, whether he carry out his purpose or not. Further, every faculty or inteUectuai habit is conversant with things that are contrary one to another : by one and the same science a man may know contraries ; e.g., one and the same science, that of Medicine, is concerned both with health and with disease, and by one and the same faculty contrary results are brought about. But a 'nim'al habit is incapable of producing oontraiy results. In virtue of our Justice we do not perform ac1ad!i|' that are, indifferently, just or unjust, any more than the movements of a diseaeaS ' body are the same as those of a sound body.] (})) DIVISIONS OF .TOSTICE AKD OF INJUSTICE. In many cases, however, the nature of a moral habit may be inferred from its corresponding opposite ; and in fatrZreriitnd "^^uy cases, again, moral habits may be under- Particular (derived stood from the concrete objects in which they SsitS "'"'"''*' ^^^^^^- ^' ^^^ example, the nature of sound health be manifest, the nature of its opposite, bad health, becomes equally plain. Again, from the nature of those who have sound health, the nature of sound health may be inferred, and from sound health may be inferred the conditions which produce it. If sound health be a certain compactness of flesh, it necessarily follows that bad health is a certain flabbiness of flesh, and further, that the cause of sound health is that which produces compactness of flesh. Furthermore it follows, for the most part, that if (Mie term be predicated iu a variety of ways, its opposite is predicated in corresponding ways : — if there be, for instance, many senses in what is ' right,' there will be many senses in the term ' wrong.' Bk. V. 2.] Translation. 251 It seems that the attributes 'just ' or 'unjust ' are predicated of a person in various senses ; yet inasmuch as the similarity of idea is very close, the distinction escapes notice, and i* is not like other terms which have the same sound, but a sense so widely different, that their divergence is plainly marked. (In such cases generally the difference which appeals to the eye is considerable : for instance, (the Greek word for) ' key ' is applied in an equivocal sense to the bone below the neck of animals, and to the instru- ment by which we fasten doors.) Let us now take the case of the term ' unjust,' and see in what different senses a man is called ' unjust.' It a,ppears to be commonly applied to (1) the law-b reaker, (2) t)b e"x>Y^^| ;.eaching and unfair ma n. It is c pns&guently clig^h^t Jhe., j,]J§twaft ffill be (1) the law-abiding man, and the (2) fair-minded maiDu. What • — 1 ' I , 1111 J Mimj i a»M n m j AMM L i w ij»M»^ a.V.^ , i'- • —■ ^w-W?**'*^*"-, , is rignt . o r ' just.,, , theiL.„wall-iie.. 1 Ij, what js saociiaaeawby JajK,^^ and (2) what is fa ir, and^ e qual : whatjs^ ' unjust ! or ' wrong ' „BiU» be (1) what IS in violation rtf law, and (2) what is unequal. a«is*WWX < )WiMbM>iiwieMU£««^'«i^^i^ However, the tendencies of habits may be inferred from those that are the exact contrary : if, for instance, a man knows that somid health is a compactness of flesh, he will infer that bad health is a flabbiness of flesh. Again, the nature of habits may be gathered from the conditions which produce them. Take, for in- stance, the case of health : the condition which produces the habit is healthf ul- uess — %£., that which tends to promote health. Now if we know that healthful- ness is that which produces compactness in the flesh, we know that good health itself is that very compactness in the flesh. There is this further consequence iavolved in habits, for the most part : — if of two contrary habits the one be predicated in a variety of senses, the other is pre- dicated in correspondingly opposite senses. For instance, if Temperance is a term with a variety of signifleations. Intemperance will have a corresponding variety of significations ; and if Justice be an equivocal term, and predicated of a variety of persons, Injustice will present the same character. [The limitation ' for the most part ' is made of this statement, because there are certain habits to which this 'law of contraries' is not found to hold. For instance, ' loving' is 'opposed to ' hating ; ' but ' loving ' is not a simple idea, but implies in Greek (1) affection, or (2) kissing with the lips ; whereas ' hatiug ' implies one single idea — that of aversion. These exceptions, however, are very rarely found : generally and for the most part a habit is predicated in the same senses in which its opposite is predicated.] Since, then, Justice is predicated in a number of senses. Injustice will be predi- cated in an equal number of opposite senses. Commonly it is thought that Jus- tice and Injustice have but a single signification, inasmuch as the ideas implied therein do not differ vastly from one another. Terms which are equivocal and have a variety of significations, only become apparent when the facts which they represent exhibit a palpable difference between one another. ' Key,' for example, is a term applied to the bone next to the neck of an animal, and to the instru- ment by which we fasten doors. In such oases, inasmuch as the difference in the things indicated is considerable, the equivocation and the variation of meaning are palpable. Since, then. Justice and Injustice are predicated in many senses, let us take the case of the Unjust man, and distinguish the senses in which the attribute ' unjust' is appUed to him. The term ' unjust' is applied (1) to the man who violates the laws, and (2) to the man who is unfair. Consequently the opposite character, the 2 52 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. V. 2. Just man, will be one (1) who observes tbe laws, and (2) who is fair and equal ; and ' wrong ' or injustice ^e?' se will be (1) ' what is in violation of law,' and (2) what is unequal. (c) SPHEKB OF JUSTICE, AND OF INJUSTICE. But since the unjust man is overreaching, the objects which will concern him, will be the good things of life the uS ""man " 1°* howevcr all good things, but such as form seeks to compass the province of good or bad fortune — things thfai s'of'life^'''(or ^^'^'^ i^ themselves and abstractedly are if needs must be) blessings though to individuals sometimes the the least of the reverse, (Though all men pray for these good things, and eagerly pursue after them, they are wrong in so doing ; their prayer ought rather to be that things which are blessings per se may be in truth blessings to them, and their own choice should be of things which are good for their own selves.) The unjust man does not invariably choose ' the more,' but in some cases he chooses ' the less ' — i.e. where his choice Hes between things which are absolutely evils. Inasmuch, however, as the lesser evil seems to be in some sense a good, and the over- reaching temper is concerned with what is good, the man who chooses the lesser evil is consequently thought to be an over- reaching man. He has at any rate an unfair share of the advan- tage in question. (' Unfairness' is a comprehensive term common to all aspects of injustice.) But since the unjust man is overreaching, and the overreaching spirit has re- ference to some form of ' good,' the object in reference to which the unjust man is overreaching wUl be some form of ' good.' Yet the ' good ' which he seeks is not that which is good for his own self, and which would make him in himself a better man. He does not seek to become more temperate than his neighbours, nor more skilled in medicine than the physicians, nor more charitable than other liberal men, nor does he seek for any other of the goods which are ' good ' abso- lutely and in themselves, and which render the possessor thereof good. The goods in reference to which he seeks to surpass his fellows are such as, while absolutely and in themselves ' good,' do not help him to progress in goodness, but ofttimes positively make him worse than before. Such goods are riches and power and bodUy strength : — these become in the case of the bad man material for increased depravity. So it is with the good things generally which form the province of good or bad fortune. The mass of men maJie their prayer for such things, and eagerly pursue after them. Yet they ought not so to do, but rather to pray that these things, which are good in themselves, may render them good, and be a benefit to them, and not render them worse than before. If the choice lie open before them, they ought to prefer, not the things which are good absolutely, but things which are good for their own selves, and such things as will have the effect of rendering them better in themselves. But the unjust man prays, for himself, for the goods which contribute to good fortune, and in reference thereto he always seeks to gain an advantage. He also makes his choice of the least of the evils involved in bad fortune, considering the lesser evil to be a good. Inasmuch aS he Bk. V. 3.] Translation. 253 is always overreaching, and tlie object in reference to wliicli Ms grasping spirit is shown is the ' good,' herein also he seems to be overreaching. He is also an imfair man, mif airness or inequality being a comprehensive term common to all the varieties of injustice : the law-breaking man is ia a way an unfair man, just as the grasping man is. ii. — Charaeteristics of Universal Justice and Injustice. Now as the law-breaker was seen to be unjust, and the law-abiding man just, it is clear that all the requirements of law are also requirements of ^° ^^^ ^ Justice is . , . rm ■ i /• 1 1 conformity with justice. The requirements 01 law are such as are law, it must reach defined by the science of Jurisprudence, and *" ^^^^y sphere of ■1 , , • c • 1.1 L • T L ^ action to which law every such enactment we say is just or ' right. jg applicable. But the laws make provision for every kind of circumstance, making it their aim to secure what is beneficial either for the state at large, or for the best men in the state, or for the ruling class, whether it be determined by merit or in any other similar way. In one sense therefore we call things just which are productive or preservative of happiness, and of the various ingredients of happiness for the whole social community. Law enjoins, for example, citizens to perform the duties of the brave man — not to quit their ranks, nor to take to flight, nor to throw down their arms. It enjoins, again, the exercise of self- control — -to refrain from adultery or insolence. It enjoins, again, the practice of patience and meekness — to forbear striking or railing. Through the whole range indeed of the virtues and vices, it enjoins a certain line of conduct and forbids its opposite ; and when a law has been correctly drawn, its provisions are true and just, though if it be passed on the chance of the moment, its provisions are less beneficial. Justice of this kind, or perfect conformity to law, is identical with the perfect excellence of the moral nature — not indeed viewed absolutely, but in relation to t'^tve^^SS! society. Hence it is that Justice is often stance of life, the regarded as the most eifective of all the Virtues ; ^^^Z\^ perfect and neither the Hesperus nor the Morning Star tion of every phase seem so marvellous in their beauty; and among °^--}^^':^ Justice i ■> o will thus be the adages ot daily lite we say : Kighteousness. " In Justice every virtue is contained." It is indeed the perfection of the moral nature in the highest sense, because it is the outward expression or exercise of that perfection : it is perfected virtue, because the man who pos- sesses it is able to display his goodness towards others, and not 254 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. V. 3. merely in his own life. There are many men who are ahle to exercise moral virtue in their domestic concerns, but fail to be equally virtuous in their relations with the world at large. The saying of Bias is therefore very apposite to such cases : ' Power is the touch-stone of character' — i.e. a man who wields power stands in relation to other men and his life is bound up with that of the community. For this very reason it is that Justice is thought to be ' the good of our neighbour ' pre-eminently among all the virtues, inasmuch as it brings a man into definite relation with his fellows: i.e. it effects what is for the interest of others, whether the ruler or the community at large. He, then, is most depraved who practises wickedness as well in his own life as in his dealings with his friends ; and he is most virtuous who dis- jjlays his goodness not only in his own character, but in his inter- course with his neighbours — which is indeed a hard task. Justice, then, of this kind is not merely an element or depart- ment of Virtue, but is itself complete and perfect virtue ; nor is its opposite Injustice a mere form or division of Yice, but is itself coextensive with vice. The point in which the aspect of the one differs from the aspect of the other, is clear from what has been said. Justice as a state of mind is identical with perfect virtue, but the mode of its manifestation is different: — when reflected upon others, it is Justice, but when viewed simply as a disposition of a particular kind it is Virtue. But since the law-breaker is in a sense an im]"nst man, and one who keeps the law a just man, it is evident that aU things which are ' lawful ' are in a sense things which are ' just.' Things are lawful which are defined by the science of Jurisprudence, and such things are called just : — every enactment of the laws being, as we say, a requirement also of justice. It consequently is found iliat Justice is conversant with precisely the same class of relations as are the laws. But the laws make provision for every detail of life, aiming to realize whatever is advantageous for the different forms of social polity, whether the constitution which they establish be a democracy or an oligarohy or of some other type. The acts which the laws enjoin are such as cover the whole field of moral virtue, for instance, acts of temperance, of justice and of courage. They enjoin the citizen not to quit his post, nor to take to flight — ^which is the conduct proper to the brave man ; nor to commit adultery nor to wax insolent — which is the business of the temperate man ; nor to strike nor to injure another — ^which is the characteristic of good temper. Similarly in regard to the virtues and vices generally, the law orders a certain line of conduct and forbids the opposite. When a law is scientifically framed, it is a right law viewed by the standard of Reason and Science ; but when it is framed at random and without consideration, its provisions and its sanctions are not in accordance with true science nor with the real fitness of things. Nevertheless, those sanctions and provisions relate to what is good or evil, that being the aim and end of aU law as such. If, then, the requirements of law are coextensive with those of Justice, and it is f oixnd that the sphere of law is coextensive vrith the sphere of Justice, thea Justice comprises every form of moral excellence, and is itself perfect virtue, inasmuch as it embraces all the virtues and is itself complete virtue. The only point in fact in which Justice is distinct from universal virtue is this : Virtue as Bk. V. 4.] Translation. 255 a state of mind is a tiling apart and independent and simply exists per se, whereas Justice is a perfect state of mind not absolutely but brought into relation with other society. The exercise of all the virtues with a view to^e interest of one's neighbours — that is what Justice implies. For this reason Justice i& thought to be the most eflfeetive of all the virtues ; and neither the Morning nor the Evening Star are so bright nor marvellous in their lustre. According to the common adage men use : — " In Justice every virtue is contained in miaiature." It is virtue in its most perfect form because it is the exercise of perfect virtue. The man who possesses justice is able to practise his virtue in his intercourse with his neighbours and not by himself merely. There are many men who benefit by their virtues their own selves, but are unable to help others by means thereof. The saying of Bias is, therefore, very apposite : ' Power will bring the character to the test,' power being nothing else than the communication of the moral virtues to the wellbeing of society. For this reason also Justice seems to be ' the good of others,' alone of all the virtues, because it seeks what is good not for a man's own self but for others also ; either, that is, for the state at large or for the ruler of it. The man then who injures both himself and his friends by his wickedness is most depraved, whereas the man who uses the moral excellencies which he possesses not merely for his own private good, but for the good of his neighbours also, is a man of perfect virtue, unselfishness being indeed a hard matter to practise. Justice, then, of this kind is not a mere division or element of virtue, but is itself complete and perfect virtue ; and for similar reasons. Injustice is no mere element of vice, but is itself complete and consummated vice. [The point in which universal virtue differs from Justice of this kind, has been already explained.] iii. — Cliaraoteristies of Civil Justice. (a) SPECIAL SENSE OF JUSTICE AND INJUSTICE DEFINBD BY CON- DITIONS OF EQUALITY. But the special object of our present investigation is that form of Justice which ranks as one of the divisions ot virtue rather than as co-extensive with it. There Arguments to prove , „ ^ T J- T that Universal IS such a narrower torm 01 Justice, as we have justice or Injustice just said. In the same way in regard to Injustice ^ distinct from we must examine into that form of it which is a ^r Injustice, distinct kind of vice. Herein is proof that such a special form of Justice exists. When a man's character takes the shape of ordinary depravity, though he is an evil-doer, he gets no advantage from his evil- doing ; as, for instance, if he has thrown down his shield through cowardice, or has abused his neighbour through ill-temper, or failed to succour the need of his friends through niggardliness. Con- Tersely, when a man takes unfair advantage of others, his over- reaching is often not in the direction of any one of these special vices (certainly not in the direction of all), yet still he acts in pursuance of a certain depravity of nature (otherwise we should not censure him), and, in consequence, of injustice. It follows. 256 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. V. 4. therefore, that there is a special kind of injustice which ranks as a form of universal injustice, and that there are acts of injustice whicll rank as special forms of universal Injustice or Unlawfulness, Again, suppose a man to commit adultery : if his motive be to make gain thereby, and he receives the reward he seeks, he would appear to be unjust rather than sensual, his act being obviously prompted by gain ; whereas if his crime be owing to his lust, and he pays the price of it and is injured thereby, he is sensual rather than overreaching. Again, in the case of offences generally, reference is invariably made to some particular form of vice ; for example, if a man has committed adultery, his crime is put down to his sensuality, or if he has deserted his comrade in action, his conduct is put down to his cowardice, or if he has assaulted anyone, his act is put down to passionateness. On the other hand, if a man has made again of another, his act is not imputed to any other depravity except simple injustice. But- there is another kind of Justice whicli is a special form of moral excellence, just as there is a kind of Injustice which is a special form of moral depravity. The following may be a proof that there is such a special form of Justice, and of Injustice. The man who shapes his life after the various forms of depravity, may he called an evil-doer, but by no means an overreaching man. Such is, for instance, a man who throws away his shield through cowardice, or who abuses his neighbour through ill-temper and inabOity to control the impetaositiy of Ms passion, or who fails through illiberality to assist with his wealth the wants of his neighbour : — men of this type are evil-doers, but not overreaching in any sense. Consequently the overreaching man is concerned with some other form of depravity, since his grasping has relation neither to any one of these vioeS; nor to all combined. There is, therefore, some special form of injustice ranking as a division of universal injustice ; and there are certain acts correspondrag which are particular forms of injustice, and separate divisions of universal injustice and violation of law. Again, supposing that one man commits adultery for the sake of gain and in fact receives his reward, while another man does so to gratify his own pleasure and is injured by his conduct and spends his substance upon his passions, the latter would be called a sensual but not an overreaching man, whereas the former would be called overreaching and unjust, but by no means a sensualist. Conse- quently, there is a form of injustice which does not include dissoluteness, and, therefore, is not identical with universal injustice, but is a special form of it. Again, every evil action is referred to some particular vice ; for instance, adultery is imputed to sensuality ; flight and the lirowing away of the shield, to cowardice ; abuse and striking, to passionateness. But to gain the property of others and advantages which in no way belong to oneself, — that is referred to no other cause beyond injustice. (J) COMPAEISON BETWEEN UNIVERSAL AND CIVIL JUSTICE AND INJUSTICE. It is consequently evident that besides Injustice as a whole (which is equivalent to vice) there is a special division of Injus- Bk. V. 5.] Translatio7t. 257 tice, ranking as a part of the whole, though having a common name inasmuch as its definition falls under the sameffewMs; — i.e. both forms have their signifi* Distinctions be- ■'t t i.-i ij_- , S tween Universal cance dependmg entirely upon relations to others; and Civil Justice but whereas the objects with which Civil Justice correspond to uis- ^ 1 ij.1 r J. tinctions of their IS concerned are honour, wealth, safety, or some- stibject-matter. thing, if such can be found, in which all these are comprised, and it is inspired by the pleasure which comes from gain, the objects on the other hand with which Universal Injustice is concerned are precisely the objects with which the virtuous man as such is concerned. It is clear, then, that there are several forms of Justice, and that there is a special form distinct from Justice as a whole. We must now try to grasp what that special kind of Justice is, and what are its characteristics. Well then, acts of injustice are divided into acts of law-breaking and acts of unfairness; and acts of justice are divided into acts conformable to law and acts of fairness. The Injustice described above will therefore be co-extensive with the violation of law. But just as what is 'unequal' and what is ' more ' are not iden- tical but distinct, as standing in the relation of a whole to a part, (the ' more ' being always ' unequal,' but the unequal not always ' more',) so the ' unjust ' and Injustice, in the civil or particular sense, are not the same as the universal forms, but are distinct from them, the one being ' parts,' the other ' wholes.' That is to say, Civil Injustice is a part of Universal Injustice, and for similar reasons Civil Justice is part of Universal Justice. We must there- fore treat of Justice in its particular aspects, and of Injustice in its particular aspects, and of the acts corresponding in the same manner. That form of Justice, then, or of Injustice which has a range co- extensive with the whole of virtue (the one being the practice of the whole of virtue and the other ^"J'tf dismissed the practice of the whole of vice in its relation to from the point of society) may be dismissed frona the present in- ™w of the present quiry. As for the acts which correspond to these forms of Universal Justice and Injustice, it is evident how they must be defined. The mass of things ' lawful ' pretty generally correspond with the acts performed in virtue of the complete ex- cellence of the moral nature : i.e. the law enjoins us to live in con- formity with each single virtue and deters us from conforming to any single vice. Again, the causes which produce this perfect virtue are the various enactments of law which have been made to regulate education in its bearings on social life, [We must leave 258 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. V. 5. for future discussion the question whether the education of indi- viduals, in virtue whereof a man is ' good ' in the absolute sense of the term, belongs to the Science of Statesmanship, or to some other. It is surely not the same thing in every case to be a good man and to be a good citizen.] It is, therefore, evident that there is a special form of Injustice though called hy the same name as Universal Justice (the definition of either kind belonging- to the same genus inasmuch as both aUke have their manifestation in the practice of goodness in relation to society). This special form of Injustice differs how- ever from Universal Injustice iaasmuch as the objects with which it is concerned are wealth and safety and the pleasure that comes from gain (or some similar conception if there be any, embracing all such objects) ; whereas the objects of Universal Injustice are all such as the virtuous man is conversant with. It is clear then from what has been said that the term ' injustice' is used in a variety of senses, and that there is a special form of it distinct from human per- fection in the wide sense of the term. We must now proceed to explain what this special form of Justice is. We have already shown that the ' unjust ' is divided into (1) what is in violation of a law, and (2) what is unequal or unfair, and that the ' just ' is divided into (1) what is conformable to law, and (2) what is fair and equal. Justice, ihere^ fore, in its fuUest sense is concerned with what is conformable to law, and Injus- tice in the wide sense with what is ia violation of law [as well as unequal]. But since what is ' more ' is not identical with what is ' unequal,' but the ' un- equal ' represents a whole of which ' the more ' is a part {i.e. what is ' more ' is always ' unequal,' but what is ' unequal ' is not always ' more ') there wiU also be another form of Injustice relating to the unequal : and these forms of Injustice will not be identical, but Injustice which is concerned with what is 'more' wUl be particular injustice, whereas the Injustice which is concerned with the ' unequal ' will be universal injustice. Particular injustice which bears the rela- tion towards consummate injustice of a part to a whole, is concerned with what is ' more,' (and this is what is meant by an ' overreaching ' or ' grasping spirit '). From these considerations it may be inferred what particular Justice is, so far as may be in outline ; but we shall have to treat of it with greater precision. Universal Justice, therefore, as has been explained, is perfect virtue and the practice of virtue in its entirety (just as Injustice is complete vice) in virtue of its conformity to law. Now Law does not merely order us to perform the actions of every virtue (as has been shown in previous explanations), but it trains the citizens so that they may become virtuous and attain to a state of mind represen- tative of absolute virtue. It is not the same thing to do deeds of virtue and to have a disposition of virtue ; and consequently it is a different thing to be a good cithi'ii and to be a virtuous iTian. A man is virtuous when he has a disposition of virtue : a citizen is a good citizen when he performs (from whatever motive) acts of virtue whereby he will benefit his own fellow-citizens in his pubUc life and generally is helpful towards his feUows. [Here a question may be raised as to the sense in which education belongs to the Science of Statesmanship — the education I mean in consequence whereof a man grows to be virtuous. That is a point upon which we shaJl have to speak later on.] Justice and Injustice, therefore, in their widest sense, are what I have described. iv. — ^Division of Civil Justice into (1) Distributive and (2) Cor- rective. Of Justice in its narrower sense and of the just relation corresponding thereto, there are two forms : Bk. v. 6.] Translation. 259 1. One form of Justice, as equality in the relations of civil life, is exhibited in the distribution and appor^ tionment of honour, money, and the advantages as the principle by generally which maybe divided among such as which the 'rights' ? T • J.1 ,.,,... of individual have a common share m the constitution ; smce in citizens are regu- all matters of that land it is possible to have what lated and adjusted is equal or what is unequal compared with others. ^" ^'" ^°^ ^ ' 2. The second form is ' corrective' or regulative of transactions between man and man ; and as some transactions are voluntary and others involuntary, this form of Justice has two subdivisions, (a) Voluntary transactions are such as buying or selling, lending or borrowing, accommodation, trust, or hiring ; the voluntariness consisting in the fact that the initial start in all such matters is voluntary. (/3) Involuntary transactions are either fraudulent or violent. Fraudulent transactions are, for example, theft, adultery, witchcraft, procuration, enticing of slaves, assassination and false witness. Violent transactions are such as outrage, bonds, death, abduction, maiming, calumny, insult. Of Justice in tlie special sense of civil equity and of the just relation corre- sponding thereto, there are two forms : 1. One form Is exhibited in apportionments among different citizens ; when it is necessary to apportion money or honour or anything else that is divisible among such as take rank in the civil community. In all such matters equality and inequality, what is less and what is more may be assigned to different people. For this reason it is a distinctive form of Justice to divide and to apportion to each according to principles of right. 2. The other form is corrective or regulative in transactions between man and man. Of this form, again, there are two subdivisions, inasmuch as contracts ai'e divided into two kinds, one being voluntary and the other involuntary. (a) Voluntary transactions are such, as buying, selling, lending, seoiuriug, ac- commodation (when for instance a man gives up his house or his horse to another . to make use of), depositing, hiring of a slave or of a craftsman. Such arrange- ments are called voluntary because the man who has taken or used such things will voluntarily give them back — and at any rate received them in the first instance voluntarily from one who gave them freely and because he desired to do so. And BO they are called ' voluntary.' (|3) Involuntary transactions are called either fraudulent or violent. Fraudu- lent contracts are such as theft, adultery, witchcraft, procuration, the cheating of anyone's slave, assassination, false witness. Violent contracts are such as blows, bonds, death, ravishment, maiming, calumny, insult ; and they are so called because a man who offends in relation thereto receives secretly and violently either money or pleasure, and pays back the price thereof in the courts of law, either through fine or death or being outraged or degraded. There are, then, these two forms of OivU Justice, one relating to the distribution of goods the other to matters of contracts, which again are either voluntary or involuntary. We will now proceed to speak of each form with greater precision. V. — The Principles of Distributive Justice explained. Since the unjust man is unjust in his dealings, and a thing that is unjust is a thing that is unequal, it is clear that there is a s 2 26o The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. V. 6. ' mean point ' in reference whereto such inequality is viewed ; and ^, . ., „ this ' mean point' is what is ' equal.' (Of course is a mean. The there must be what is equal in any sphere of just is 'equal;' action in which there is 'more' and 'less.') If the lust is a mean. ,, -\ l • • j. ■ t-j.- i ■l l • then what is unjust is what is unequal, what is just must be what is equal — an inference which all will draw without discussion ; and as what is ' equal ' is a ' mean point,' what is just will also be ' a mean point.' But ' the equal ' implies two quantities at least. It necessarily follows, therefore, that what is 'just,' as being a fm£ w: qSn' ' ^^an ' and a thing that is ' equal,' should imply tities and two a reference not only to .a certain standard but t~uftitiel'' ^ls° to certain particular persons; i.e. in so far as it is ''a mean,' it must be a mean between certain quantities — ' more ' or ' less,' and in so far as it is an ' equal,' it must mean an equality between two quantities, and in so far as it is 'just,' it implies a reference to particular persons. It necessarily follows that what is 'just' implies four terms at the least: for there are two persons concerned, Jiisticc, therefore, and the shares which they receive are two. And takes the form of ,, , .. -n i jt t , ,i a proportion. the relation Will be the same between the persons as between their shares. If, that is, the persons interested are not equal to one another, they will not receive equal shares ; nay, if those who are equal fail to receive equal shares, or if those who are unequal share equally, thence arise feuds and contentions in states. [This principle is further evident from the use of standards of „„„,., , merit. All men admit that what is iust in the iquality measured ,. ^^ ., ^. „ , , -^ ,, , by some standard distribution ot houours must be Conformable to ■whatever that gome standard of merit — though all do not accept" standard be. ,, , -, ■, ■, -r » -, the same standard ; e.ff. the lovers of democracy say that the standard should be [coextensive with] freedom, the oligarchs say that wealth is the true standard or high birth, and the lovers of an aristocracy say personal excellence.] Justice is, therefore, something 'proportionate.' Proportion is not only applicable fo pure number but tfti.. tinuous^proportiom quantity generally: it is an equality between ratios, and there must be four terms at least involved in it. [As for ' discrete proportion ' it is obvious that that implies four terms. But so also does 'continuous pro- portion,' since it employs one of its terms as two and names it twice over; e.ff. 'as A is to B, so is B to C The term B is, therefore, used twice ; and B being put down twice over, the terms of the proportion are four.] Bk. v. 7.] Translation. 261 Justice, then, (as a due proportion in the distribution of honours) involves four terms at least, and the ratio between the members of the two pairs of ^^'^'tj™ between , . '^ the tour terms of terms will be the same, smce the persons m- the proportion in terested and the things at stake are divided Distributive similarly. The proportion will then be — A : B :: C : D (or, alternando, A : :: B : D) ; and hence the whole A + C (which the distribution unites together) is proportionate to the whole B + D; and if they be united in the manner indicated, the distribution unites them in conformity with justice. The joining together, therefore, of the term A to the term C, and of the term B to the term D, is what is just in the distribu- tion of honours ; and this kind of justice is a mean point between whatever violates a due proportion ; what is proportionate being a mean and what is just being proportionate. Mathematicians call this kind of proportion ' geometrical ' (as opposed to ' arithmetical ' proportion) because in geometrical proportion the whole is related to the Arithmetical and whole precisely as each term is to each. [This portion™"^ '^'™" proportion is of course not continuous, since the person interested and the object at stake cannot be one in number.] Justice of this kind, therefore, is 'proportionate.' On the other hand what is 'unjust' is what violates a due proportion; and such a disproportionateness is found in the forms of ' the more ' and ' the less.' JX'of'p.opS." Such is the effect found in actual experience. The man who commits injustice has ' more ' than is due to him of what is good ; and the man who is injured has ' less ' than he should have of the good. Conversely in the case of what is ' evil : ' the lesser evil becomes an item in the account of what is ' good,' compared, that is, with the greater evil, since a lesser evil is more desirable than a greater one, that which is desirable being a good, and that which is more desirable being a greater good. This, then, is one aspect or form of Justice. What is ' just,' therefore, is what is ' a mean,' and what is ' equal,' and what is ' proportionate ; ' and Justice is the principle which produces a true ' mean ' and ' equality' and ' proportionateness ' in civil life. What is just is a ' mean ' because it is midway between what is ' too much ' and what is ' too little,' between what is above the right proportion and what is below it ; in that respect being lilre all the other virtues, since the law of the mean is applicable to all the forms of moral excellence. But its equality is a characteristic peculiar to Justice : it renders to each man what is appropriate and fitting for him to receive : and what it gives is equal relatively to the recipient {ij;. things which are appropriate are things which are fair and equal, and what is fitting is in a sense what is appro- priate). Moreover, since Injustice is inequality and what is unjust is what is unequal, it will only be natural that Justice should be an equality and that what IS just should be equal, as being a mean between what is ' too much ' and what is 262 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. V. 7. ' too little.' In any course of action in which ' the more ' and ' the less ' find a place, it is a consequence that there should be room for what is ' equal.' In fact without any argument of ours, that is the view which is universally approved— that what is just is (what is) equal. Justice is also ' proportionate ' because it makes what has to be divided proportionate to the recipients according to a standard of distribution. The things which are given bear the same proportion to one another that the recipients do to each other. If Achilles is, let us say, worth double of Ajax in respect of bravery, the honour which must be paid by the just man to Achilles, •will be twice as great as that which he will pay to Ajax. In so far as Justice is a ' mean,' it is a mean between many extremes, since the things which lie outside 'the mean' are many, being distant therefrom in varying degrees of nearness or remoteness. In so far, again, as Justice is an ' equality,' it is an equality between two specific things — the recipient of the gift and the gift itself. (' Equality ' is a term of relation and always implies some two objects between which there must be an equal relationship.) In so far, again, as Justice is proportionate, it implies, at the least, four terms. Proportion must of course always lie between four objects, being as it is an equality between two ratios, each ratio consisting of two terms; and so any proportion must imply four objects. Suppose, for instance, that the ratio is twofold or threefold : there is then a scheme of relation between two quantities, one of them being double, and the other half, the other — as 20 is related to 10. Hence there must be two terms in every single ratio. If we take this same ratio in two other terms, ic. between 12 and 6, we can. then form a proportion, and we shall have 'as 20 : 10 :: 12 : 6 ; ' and so proportion will always consist in four terms at the least, though of course it ma\j consist of more. [If it happens that we have taken three terms and constructed a proportion out of them, e.g. as 20 : 10 :: 10 : 5, then, as we take the 10 twice over, there are thus found to be four terms. This kind of proportion is called ' continuons,' whilst that which consists of four distinct terms, is called ' discrete.' Both kinds alike are distinguished by Mathematicians as ' Geometrical Proportion,' on account of there being yet another kind of Proportion which is called ' Arithmetical Proportion,' which is of this nature : ' A exceeds B, by as much as C exceeds D.'] But distributive Justice is proportionate according to the standard of geometrical proportion — for reasons which we will now state. Let us assume that the thing which is to be distributed is honour, and that the persons among whom the honour is to be conferred are Achilles and Ajax. The honour in the one case ought to bear the same relation to the honour in the other that Achilles does to Ajax ; and the honour of Achilles ought to bear the same relation to Achilles that the honour of Ajax does to Ajax ; or, oombiniag the terms together, the relation which AohiUes honoured bears to AchiUes ought to be the relation which Ajax honoui-ed does to Ajax ; and, inversely, the relation which Achilles honoured bears to Ajax honoured, ought to be the relation which Achilles bears to Ajax. Now the whole proportion when it is of this form is suitable to distribntlTe justice, being as it is of the kind which can be discovered not in arithmetical proportion, but solely in geometrical. It is shown by the geometrician that all these forms of proportion are found in geometrical proportion. But that it is impossible for them to be found in arithmetical proportion is clear fiom the following considerations. Suppose that there are four quantities in arithmetical proportion, 4, 3, 6, 5 : then 4 exceeds 3 by as much as 6 exceeds 5. But if yon combine the quantities in either ratio there will no longer be a proportion in the arithmetical sense : i.c. if 6 and 5 be added together the whole will exceed 6 by 6, whereas if i and 3 be added together the whole will exceed 3 by 4. Conse- quently these quantities only show an arithmetical proportion while disjoined (i.c. there is the same excess of 4 over 3 as there is of 6 over 5). If however these quantities are combined, there is no longer a proportion : — 11 exceeds 5 by inure than 7 exceeds 3. For these reasons, then, distributive justice is proportionate, according to the Bk, V. 7.] Translation. 263 principles of geometrical proportion, but tliat not of the continuous but of tbe discrete kind. The terms implied in it must be four in number, since it is impossible that the thing given and the recipient of the gjft should be one in Humber. Justice of this kind is proportionate so far as it consists of distributions — when, that is, a man receives what is proportionate to his merit, whether honour or money or what else there be that is to be divided. By such principles it is that peace and good order are established in communities ; since by different conditions civil strife and feuds and incriminations arise — when, that is, equals do not receive equal treatment, or those who are unequal are dealt with as equals. There is, moreover, this further point which makes it clear that a man who would effect an arrangement of society in accordance with justice aims at what is proportionate. All men consider that to be just which corresponds to each man's individual worth, but as to what the ' worth ' is, on account whereof a man is to be honoured, all men do not agree in their views. The lovers of a democracy say that the only condition of merit is personal freedom ; the oligarchs say that wealth is the ground of merit, and ai-istoorats say that it is personal excellence. Since, then, there are these divergent grounds of merit, if any one be desirous of apportioning honour to each man according to his worth, and upon a principle of justice, he will not make the apportionment equal but proportionate. Justice, therefore, is the proportionate, as has been explained. On the other hand, what is unjust is what is wide of the propoi-tionate relation — when, that is, the distribution is made on a principle of excess or of deficiency compared with the worth of the recipients ; and that is a result which is found in the general effects of wrong doing. The man who commits a wrong strives to get more good than the person injured and the person injured has less good in consequence. Conversely in the case of evil, the wrongdoer has less evil and the person injured has greater evil in consequence, since the lesser evil is more choiceworthy than the greater, and is sought for as a greater good. Such, then, is the distributive form of Justice : we may now treat at once of the other form. vi.— The Principles of Corrective Justice explained. There is one remaining form of Justice, Corrective Justice, which finds its sphere in business transactions '['Via SlDilSrG 111 between man and man whether entered into which Remedial freely or not. Justice is exercised Corrective Justice has a character quite distinct from Distributive Justice. Distributive Justice, dealing with the apportionment of public goods, proceeds invariably on the principle of geometrical proportion described above : — if distribu- tion be made to the citizens out of the public funds, the various apportionments must bear the same ratio to one another that the respective contributions of the diiferent citizens do. (Conversely the injustice which is the direct opposite of this kind of Justice, is in contravention of this kind of proportion.) On the other hand the Justice which arises from the transac- tions dependent on mutual intercourse, though a „ ,. , t x- kind of equality, as Injustice is inequality, yet is determined by the not an equality according to the standard of principles of arith- , ■ \ 1 l_ n -ii X- 1 L- T metioal proportion. geometrical but 01 arithmetical, proportion, in this view of Justice (as 'corrective' or 'remedial') it is immaterial 264 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. V, 7. whether the good man h^s cheated the bad man or whether it be the bad man who has cheated the good man ; or, again, whether the man who has committed an adultery be a good or a. bad man. The law looks simply to the different degrees of injury in different cases ; and where there is one man who has committed a wrong and another who has suffered it, or one man has done a harm and another man been the victim of it, the law treats the persons affected as equal (and deals simply with the inequality caused by the wrong). Wrong being an equality between the author of a wrong and its victim, the judge endeavours to make matters equal between them. When, for instance, one- man has been struck and another man has dealt the blow, or when one man has been killed and another man has done the murder, the action of the one and the suffering of the other form a division into two unequal parts; but the Judge endeavours to make the relation equal by the infliction of punishment, thus taking away from the man who has profited a proportionate amount of his ' gain.' [In transactions of this kind the advantage to the aggressor is called his 'gain,' while the result to the victim is called his 'loss'— though in some cases the term is inappropriate; yet when the whole circumstance is measured out in its consequences to the different parties, the consequence to the one is ' gain ' and to the other is ' loss.'] The ' equal,' therefore, is a mean point between ' too much ' and 'too little,' and ' gain ' is too much and ' loss ' contract' may^ be *°° little, in inverse ratio to one another — too represented as much of good and too little of evil, or too little of -too' much ^ISd g°°ii li pardonable. Ignorance, are pardonable. J3ut when such acts are not owing to ignorance, though the perpetrators thereof are in a state of ignorance in consequence of a passion which is neither natural nor proper to man, then they are not pardonable. The mjuries which are done in the intercourse between man and man are partly voluntary and partly involuntary. Of involuntary injuries some are called ' errors ' and others misfortunes. An error arises when a man injures another against his will though giving » certain cause or occasion of the injury. Suppose a man to be shooting an arrow on a road in which, it was conceivable that a traveller might pass, and actually to have kiUed someone ; he was an in- voluntary homicide, yet he afforded an occasion of a man's death by shooting an arrow in such a spot. A misfortune arises when an injury ocom-s contrary to all expectation ; as for instance when a man shooting in a desert, as it so chanced, killed a person passing by. In this latter case the harm has been done contrary to expectation and against probability, and the man who caused the harm con- tributed in no way to it, except by way of accident, the cause of death being entirely extraneous to him. Of the wrongs again which are voluntary, some are said to arise from a settled purpose and others not. Of settled purpose are wrongs such as have been deliberated upon beforehand — when, that is, a man after consideration and deliberation inflicts harm with the simple purpose that he i)iay commit harm. Wrongs which do not come from a settled purpose are such as proceed from passion and not from previous deliberation ; for example, when a man injures his neighbours promiscuously, constrained by sudden frenzy, or when a man has stolen from being overwhelmed by want, not wishing to do wrong in itself but only to soothe the pains of hunger. But whether his acts proceed from settled purpose or no, in either case they are called ' wrongs.' If we look, however, to the persons who are agents in these wrongs, the man who injures another of malice aforethought is unjust in himself and evil-minded ; whereas the man who does so from being stirred up by strong feeling, whether a natural feeling like anger or grief, or an unconquerable feeling Uke hunger or fear, such an one is not unjust in himself nor evil-minded. For this reason a distinction is made by Judges between the case of a man who is defending himself from that of a man who commenced the aggression. The man who acts in passion does not commence the wrong but the man who provoked him to wrong. The latter is accused as the wrong doer, having been the cause of the injury. In this view the man who commenced the feud denies that he did so, whereas the man who defends himself, while admitting the injury which he has done to the man who assaUed him, calls it only a requital or retaliation, inasmuch as he was stirred to anger not of his own motion but by the man upon whom he has wreaked vengeance. The point at issue in such cases does not stand on the same footing as in matters of contract. In questions of contract the matter at issue is a matter of fact ; for instance, whether a man received a deposit or a loan, and having received it faUed to restore it ; and if this fact be proved, the man is ipso facto unjust and evil-hearted — unless it be that he repudiated the transaction from having forgotten it. In a. case of passion, however, the fact is admitted and is evident (i.e. whatever a man dors in anger he does openly) ; but the question at issue is whether he struck the blow justly or unjustly. Consequently the man who commenced the feud and plotted against the other, being conscious of his injustice, for that reason does not admit that he is the assaUant ; while on the oliier hand the man who was 286 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. v. 11. provoked by him thinks that he is not unjust, and therefore admits the harm which he has done to his assailant. It is evident from this consideration that whatever wrongs a man does through passion or through strong emotion and not through evil intent, he is not in respect thereof unjust in himself. On the other hand, when a man does wrong of malice aforethought, he is unjust and evil-minded, not only in respect of Corrective Justice, but also in respect of Distributive Justice — if, that is, he apportions aught to himself iu violation of equality and proportion. For similar reasons a man is just according to the different kinds of justice when he does what is right not through feeling but for the sake of ' the Good.' A man who has dealt fairly being stirred thereto by a feeling, whether of pain or of love, has indeed performed just actions but is not just in himself. But since there are some cases of involuntary wrong which meet with paiflOn • and others which do not, we must explain which of them are pardonable and which of them are not. "Whatever errors a man commits not only in ignorance but also in consequence of that ignorance, are pardonable. But the errors which a man commits not in consequence of ignorance, though in a state of ignoranee, ' but in consequence of passion — I do not mean such passion as is natural antf' human, like that caused by fear or pain or hunger or some other compulsion, but some merely luxurious craving, as, for instance, to drink wine of fine, bouquet or to eat partridge — such errors are not pardonable. It is of conrse possible for a man to err at once ' through ignorance ' and ' in a state of igno- rance ; ' for instance, a man being in a state of ignorance in regard to the Universal that ' it is wrong to drive away one's father,' may also drive away his father by night in ignorance who he is. A man who does not know the Universal is said to act ' in a state of ignorance,' while the man who does not know the particular fact is said to act ' through ignorance.' If a man know neither the. one nor the other, he is said to err ' in ignorance ' and • through ignorance,' and he of course is pardoned. A man is said to act ' in ignorance ' when he is ignorant of the universal that ' it is wrong to steal,' but steals, not because he is ignorant but in consequence of wickedness and passion, — a passion that is neither unconquerable nor natural, as has been shown. {d) VOLUNTARINESS APPLIES TO THE RECEIVING OF WRONG EQUALLY WITH THE DOING OF IT. Here we must pause to ask whether we have sufficiently defined Difficulty in nnder- Suffering and committing wrong : is such a case standing how a. possible as that which Euripides has described wrong canbevolun- ^]jen ^^Q writes in his quaint way :— tarily suffered. ^ •' " I slew my mother :— there is the simple tinth." " With her consent and thine 1 or hers, not thine ? " Is it, as a matter of fact, possible for a man to be injured of his own accord, or is it not ? Or is the receiving of injury in every case involuntary, just as the doing of injury is in every case voluntary ? Or is it the fact that the rule is not absolute, but the receiving of injury, like the doing of injury, is sometimes voluntary and sometimes involuntary ? So too in respect to having right done to one ; as every case of right dealing is volun- tary, it is reasonable that having right done to one, and having wrong done to one, should be mutually opposed in respect to their k. V. 11.] Translation. 287 being voluntary or involuntary. Yet it would seem a strange thing if to be righted were always voluntary, since some men have justice done to them not of their own accord. One may, however, raise this further question : Is every man who has suffered a wrong injured, or is the case ^. . „ ™ . I , ,, , J} ,■ • ■ Distinction be- 01 suiiermg analogous to that 01 actmg, smce in tween suffering a the case hoth of acting and of suffering it is yi^o°s and snffer- conceivable for a man to have his due share of '"^ ■«^<"igiii y- what is just only per accidens and without his own will entering into the case. Clearly the same principle applies also in respect to what is unjust, since it is not the same thing to do unjust deeds and to be unjust, nor to suffer unjust things and to be wronged. Similarly also in regard to dealing fairly and being fairly dealt by. It is surely impossible to be wronged unless some one commits a wrong, or to have right done to one unless there be some one to do it. If, again, to wrong any one is in the absolute sense of the term to injure him voluntarily, and ' voluntarily ' „ „ . .,, 1 IT /. ,1 . . •', Suffering -wrong- mean With a knowledge 01 the person injured, fuiiy does not even of the means and manner in which he is injured, apply to the case of 1 .fi ,1 n 1 .11 1 • • 1 • -My the sensualist. and it the man ot weak will does injure himself, he will be wronged voluntarily, and it will thus be conceivable for a man to injure his own self. But this very point is one of the questions under dispute — whether it be possible for a man to injure himself. Again, a man might through his own sensual folly be injured by another voluntarily on the part of that other, so that it is possible for a man to be injured of his own accord. The definition may not be correct, but we must add to the terms ' hurt any one willingly, knowing the person, the instrument, and the manner,' the further limitation 'against that person's wish.' A man, therefore, is injured by his own consent and suffers what is unjust but is never wronged with his own consent. No one wishes for harm to himself, not even the weak sensualist, but he acts contrary to his wish. No one wishes for anything but what he fancies to be a good, and the sensualist does the very things which he thinks that he ought not to do. As for the man who gives away his property as Homer says that Grlaucus gave to Diomede : " Golden armour for brazen, the worth of a hundred oxen for the worth of nine." — such a man is not wronged, since the giving of a gift depends upon a man's own self, whereas the suffering of a wrong is not within a man's own power, but there must exist some one to do the wrong. In regard therefore to being injured, it is clear that it is not a voluntary act. 288 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. V. 11. It may be thought, however, that our definition of the Just and Unjust is as yet incomplete. Since the doing of wrong is opposed to the suffering of wrong and we divided the doing of wrong into the doing of wrong voluntarily and the doing of wrong involuntaiily, the suffering of wrong must also be distingnislied according aa it is voluntary or involuntary. Such a distinction is approved by Euripides, who says that it is possible to suffer wrong intentionally on one's own part. His verses run something like this : — " I slew my mother : — there is the simple truth." " With her consettt and thine ? or hers, not thine ?" Since these terms are mutually opposed, it is necessary either that every case of wrong doing should be voluntary and that every case of suffering wrong should be involuntary ; or else that as cases of committing wrong have been distin- guished into voluntary and involuntary, cases of suffering wrong shoTdd be similarly distinguished, that the several terms may be mutually opposed to one another. The case seems to stand upon the same footing in regard to doing right and having right done to one. Yet to suppose that every case in which right or wrong is done to a man is voluntary, that is absurd. Ofttimes a man is set right against his will — when, for instance, he has done wrong and is punished for it. Similarly, it is not true that there is any case in which wrong is volun- tarily incurred : in all cases when a man is wronged it is against his will ; though when a man has right done to him it is sometimes against his will, sometimes with his own consent. When a man does wrong and is punished for it, he is set right against his will : when a man suffers wrong, and is avenged of that wrong, he is righted with his own consent. What has been now advanced may suffice to explain the case of right being done to a person. We must now explain with greater precision the case of wrong being done to a person, and show that it is not possible that suffering wrong should be intentional. First of all we will state the reasons from which it seems to be inferred that a man may be voluntarily injured. Now since to iajure anyone unjustly, with knowledge of the injury done and the person injured, and without any ignorance of the whole circumstances attending the injmy, incited to the injury of one's own motion and not constrained thereto from without — since, I say, this con- stitutes intentional wrong-doing, it follows that to be voluntarily wronged is to suffer hurt contrary to justice, with knowledge of the injury and of the person committing it, with all the attendant circumstances, and yet to submit to the wrong while having it in one's power to shake it off. That such a phenomenon is found in fact is obvious. The weak sensualist is in fact injured by otiiers, while he knows the whole circumstances before him, yet submits to the wrong though he has the power of shaking it off. It is possible, therefore, for a man to be wronged of his own accord. Moreover the weak sensualist injures his own self, and that, moreover, voluntarily. Hence for a min to injure his own self voluntarily, is to suffer what is unjust. Yet a man does, at times, bear injustice intentionally ; for instance, men of scrupulous fairness in making distribntians receive by their own wish less than their due share, a thing which though unjuBt is voluntary. Such men are therefore injured voluntarily. There is then a certain form in which injury may be incurred voluntarily. But the contrary view to this holds that it is impossible for anyone to be injured voluntarily. A man is only injured when he suffers some injustice contrary to his own wish. To suffer aught contrary to one's own wish is opposed to the very definition of the voluntary : hence it is not possible for a man to wish to be injured, not even if he be weakly sensual. Even the sensualist wishes for what is good for himself and does not endure to be injured in the strict and unqualified sense of the term : if he submits to a particular injury he fancies that he will not be injured thereby. He considers that he ought to do such things as will be profitable to him, but practically he does things which hai-m him, fancying that they are not hannfuL Hence it is not possible for a man to be injured of his own choice. In this way the objections drawn from the contrary are solved. A man doea Bk. V. 12.] Translation. 289 wrong when he injures anyone voluntarily, contrary to the wish of the person injured. Similarly a man has wrong done to him when he suffers unjust treat- ment contrary to his own wish. But to suffer unjust treatment voluntarily is not the same thing as to be wronged. Just as to do what is unjus"is not in every case to act unjustly, nor is the man who does unjust things unjust (as was shown above) so neither is every one who suffers nnjiist treatment, necessarily wronged. But just as the physician who deceives his patient, or the person who steals the sword of a madman does what is unjust without being unjust himself, inasmuch as he looks to the safety of the invalid, and does not cause him to lose but to gain, so also a man who in distribution tates less than his worth, does not injure himself even though he suffers what is unfair. He submits to be rated below his merit not in order to injure himself but rather that he may profit thereby, gain- ing a reputation for moderation and scrupulous fairness. Moreover even if he does submit to injure himself, he is not thereby wronged, since he does not suffer injustice contrary to his own wish (and nothing but that is suffering wrong). A man who gives in exchange what is better for what is worse — as Homer says that Glancus made a present to Diomede of I " fiolden annour for brazen — the worth of a hundred oxen for the worth of nine," — ^is not wronged, since he gave by his own wish. A man who is wronged is injured against his vidll. It is not possible, therefore, for a man to be wronged of his own accord, though it is possible for him to suffer harm of his own (e) STATEMENT OF SOME QUESTIONS OF CASUISTRY BEAEING ON THE ABOVE. But there are still two questions for us to discuss connected with the subjects of which we have proposed to treat : (1) does a man who makes a division con- ^^^ ^^ ™J"^* *" J. J. X . . the case of an un- trary to true merit act unjustly, or the man who just distribution, profits hy it? and (2) is it possible for a man to the man who makes 1 • i i 1 • \ /. o -»-r ■ f , 1 ■ . • it or the man who be unjust to himself ? JNow 11 the position as- profits by it ? sumed above be possible and the man who makes the unjust distribution does wrong and not the man who profits by it, then, if a man assigns to anyone but to himself an advantage knowingly and voluntarily, this man injures his own self. This is precisely what ' moderate ' men appear to do ; since a man of scrupulous moderation is willing to take less than his share. But this is not an unvarnished view of the case. The person who seemed to be cheating himself was — it may so have chanced — coveting another good, such as fame or the glory of disinterestedness. Moreover the difficulty is solved by reference to the definition of ' wrong-doing ' : the man suffers nothing ' contrary to his own wish,' and consequently he is not injured at any rate on this score, or if at all, his injury is simply loss. Yet it is evident also that the man who makes unfair distribu- \ tion does a wrong, but not the man who profits by it in every case. It is not the man to whom the unjust share accrues who does the wrong, but the man to whom it has occurred to do the wrong 290 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. v. 12. voluntarily. This is the point upon which depends the origination of thte actual movement towards action, and this origination rests with the man who makes the division, not with the man who gains by it. Moreover, since acting is predicated in many senses, and there is a sense in which even inanimate things kill, or the hand, or the slave who does his master's bidding, so the distributor of an unjust apportionment may be the instrument of wrong, without being him- self an evil-doer. Again if a man makes a decision in ignorance, he does no wrong in the sense of legal justice, nor is his decision unrighteous, though in another point of view it is unjust; since justice according to law is different from abstract justice. If, on the other hand, he has given a decision knowingly, he seeks to gain an advantage thereby either of favour or of revenge. The man who from such motives has given an unjust decision has an advantage thereby, precisely as if he had a share in the proceeds of the injustice. For instance, a man who in a case of that kind has assigned away a field, has perhaps gained a sum of money if not the actual land. There is tKe point also wHoh must be explained — whetlier the wrong is done by the man who distributes things unjustly and not according to proportion, or by the man who receives more than his proper desert. It appears that the man who makes the distribution does a wrong in the absolute sense of the term, and the man who receives the profits does a wrong in the way of being an accidental accessory. That man does a vrrong per sc who makes an unjust distribution of his own choice ; and a man acts from his own choice when the cause and the original movement of action rest with himself. Now the original movement to action in the case of a distribution rests with the man who makes it : the man therefore who makes an unfair distribution does a wrong per se, and not the man who receives the benefit of that unfairness, since, as has been shown, the origination of the act does not rest with him. The doer of unjust things is not ipso facto said to do wrong, except by accident : for instance the hand, or a sword, or a stone are said to Idll, though l^e csose of death does not rest with them, nor do they act from their own motion : they are indeed instrumental to evU but are in no way evil in themselves. If theli, a man, who has made an unfair decision in ignorance of the laws, made his decision outside the range of legal justice, he has done no wrong according to law nor is his decision unrighteous. He does wrong, however, in another way — I mean of course in the way of natural right. Legal right is one thing, natural right another. Suppose, for instance, that there is a law that a hero should have a laigat share in distributions, and that the man who was making the distribution being in ignorance of this law, ranked the hero only on an equality with the rest. Since he was ignorant of the law he has committed no wrong in respect of legal justice (inasmuch as the man who acts wrongfully through ignorance is not a wrong- doer). Tet since it is a law of nature to requite our benefactors, and this man neglected this law (not being ignorant of it, as it is a law of nature), he iB_ un- righteous judged by that law. If, again, he had knowledge both of the poaitive law and of the law of nature, and yet neglected both and made an unjust deoioon, and assigned an advantage to one to whom it was not due, not only did he thereby cause the recipient to gain an advantag'e but himself also has an advantage like- yriae. In fact, whether through friendship or through hate or through bribes he ik. V. 13.] Translation. 29 j fas led astray, he has participation in the wrongful gains. The advantage to imself in which he participates is either favour with a friend, or revenge against n enemy, or a sum of money. Hence he shares in the profits (9 injustice with lie direct recipient. Suppose a man has assigned a field to whom it did not dong for a sum of money : he is said to have shared the field with the man i)sa received it : yet he himself did not receive the field but a sum of money, linularly the man who has acted unfairly in distributions, to serve his own iterests or to oblige a friend, participates in the advantage gained and has a tiaie of the fraud. The direct recipient has an advantage and has done what is nfair ; but he is not a wrong-doer unless he persuaded the better judgment of lie distributor by bribes or by some other inducement. But the distaributor does lave an advantage in the manner which has been described and is himself cajust. xiii. — Complexities of Justice make tlie attainment of it difficult. Now men think that the doing of injustice rests with them- elves, and therefore that justice is an easy thing practise ; yet such is not the case. Of course ^ ™ T t ■, the question. tnat they know with a perfect knowledge. If, then, it be owing to their having but a slight assurance, rather than a settled belief, and those who have opinions are more likely than those who have knowledge to act contrary to their impres- sions, knowledge will not differ in that aspect from opinion — in regard, that is, to its influence on the will. Some men have a no less assured conviction of what they think than others have of what they scientifically know, as the case of Heraclitus shows. As for the view that the knowledge which men who are morally weak possess, and which they violate in their conduct, is opinion and not real knowledge, the pomt is immaterial to our argument. The point which we have to examine into M whether the knowledge of the good which such an one has is firm or doubtful. It is frequently found that opinion is so firmly rooted in a man that it does not aiffffl- from knowledge, in respect of the opposition which it makes to the desires. Bonie men are as confident in the opinions which they hold as men of science are ^ the truths which they know through their Science ; as for instance Heraclitus thought that he knew with exact scientific knowledge the fancies of his own opunon, such as that there is no movement possible, and the rest of his assump- f ^■. ■^*' "^y ^^*2 a man who acts in opposition to an opinion about the good or this character differs in no respect from the man who has a scientific know- ledge of the good and is yet impelled to the pm-suit of what is pleasant. Both ^ike are wicked in so far as each of them wars against a strong conviction of '■TW 374 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk.VII. 5. Hence tlie difficulty which was raised in the previous chapter — ^how it is possible for a man who knows the good to choose the eyU — cannot possibly be solved in. this way. We must therefore enquire how it can be solved in some other way. (c) DIFFERENT SENSES OF THE TEEM ' KNOWLEDGE ' IN MORAL RELATIONS. 1. But seeing that we speak of ' knowing' in two senses, and . . that the man who has knowledge but does not reiatlons^^o morals exercise it, no less than the man who both has may be (1) latent knowledge and also applies it, is said ' to know,' an no ao ive, there will be a corresponding difference between the case of a man doing wrong when he has not his knowledge constantly present before him — though he is actually possessed of it, and the case of a man doing wrong when he is not only possessed of knowledge of right, but has that knowledge con- sciously realized at the moment. It seems a terrible sin for a man to know the right and deliberately do the wrong ; but the case is altered if a man, in doing wrong, is not for the moment conscious how wrong it is. -"o Let us then assume that the terms ' to know " and ' to understand in the way of Science ' have a double sense. A man is said ' to know ' (1) when he possesses knowledge and exercises it (just as when a man is a geomeliician, and exercises his knowledge, he is said to ' know ' of geometry) ; and (2) when he possesses knowledge but without exercising it (just as when a geometrician makes speecliea or otherwise occupies himself than in working geometrically.) Precisely then as in the case of a geometrician, it is a wonderful anomaly if, when exercising his knowledge, he draws false conclusions, though not so if, while making a speech, he fails to observe when a man is investigating the figures contraiy to the principles of geometry, so it is with the weak-minded man. Marvellous is it indeed if the weak-minded man has real knowledge of right, and puts that knowledge into exercise, and contemplates his conduct in the light thereof, and yet, notwithstanding, is impelled in a direction the very opposite of what he knows to be right. But one ought not to wonder if he does wrong when he is not using his knowledge, though he actually possesses it. 2. Again, in the moral syllogism into which action may be ,„, , , , analysed, there are two premisses : the major or (2) a knowledge n ,i • tc i j.1. „,« of one premiss only ^nd the minor, it a man possesses bota pre- of the moral syiio- misscs, yet makes application only of the Uni- ^^"' versal and not of the Particular, there is nothing to prevent his acting in despite of his knowledge. It is the particular or minor premiss which is all important, since conduct depends upon particular details. There is, further, a distinction to be made in the Universal itself. One kind of Universal is subjective, and has reference to the person who uses it ; another kind is objective, and has reference to an external fact. An instance of a subjective Universal would Bk. VII. 5.] Translation. 375 be : ' Dry food is good for all men ' (the corresponding minor being ' I am a man '). An instance of an obje«tive Universal would be : ' Dry food has such and such qualities . . .' But whether ' this particular object has these qualities ' (which would form the minor proposition), a man may not know or may not realize at the moment. Corresponding of course to these different kinds of premisses, there will be an incalculable difference in their moral bearings ; so that, where a premiss depends upon experience, it would seem to be nothing strange that a man should not know ; but in regard to subjective premisses it would be marvellous indeed. Yet even -when a man possesses knowledge and puts it into exercise, it is no maryel if he is still an evil-doer, unless lie uses Ms knowledge iu a perfect way. Since, I mean, there are two kinds of premisses, Universal and Particular, whereby a man who knows gains his knowledge in drawing a moral conclusion — if he ttses only one of the premisses, if, I mean, he uses the universal and not the ipairticular, there is no wonder if he is a wrong-doer. For example : a man knows that a particular thing is evil, and that he ought not to do what is evil, and consequently that he ought not to do this particular thing : now though both these premisses are in the soul at the moment when passion is stirring him to some evil course, it so befalls that he exercises the universal (that ' he ought not to do the evil '), and contemplates his conduct in relation to it at that moment, but does not also exercise the particular premiss (that ' this particular thing is evil'), nor consider it in its actual application, though he possesses that premiss withia him ; and consequently he proceeds to the commission of evil, just as though morally blinded. Such a case is in no way wonderful : though a man uses the universal premiss, yet is he not able to act upon his knowledge unless he also uses the particular premiss, which is paramount over moral action. If, for example, a man knows that he ought to use dry food but does not know that this particular food is dry, he will not any the more use dry food. The case is exactly the same in moral relations : if a man use the universal premiss and consciously realize it, yet does not at the same time use the particular, he gains no sort of advantage from his knowledge. Particular premisses also differ in kind. There is one kind which it is quite iaevitable for a man to know when the universal is known ; and others which do not follow this law. When, for instance, the universal is of such a character as to comprise also the person who frames the syllogism or a subject of the same species, then the particular premiss is known in virtue of the universal ; for instance, ' Hellebore is harmful to all men : he is himself a man ; therefore hellebore is harmful to him.' In such a case the minor premiss is understood in vh-tue of the major : no one is able to be ignorant that ' he is a man ; ' similarly when the universal comprises others of the same species, it is not possible that a man should not know them. On the other hand, when the universal compre- hends some external object, then there is no necessity that if the major premiss IS known, the minor should be known also. For example, ' aU hellebore is harmful: this particular thing is hellebore: therefore this particular thing is harmful.' In this case there is no necessity that the particular should be known although the universal be known. It is this latter kind of premiss which the weak-minded man either does not possess, or if he does possess, does not exercise. To use and not to use a premiss are so widely different from one another that we consider a man a monstrous fellow if he exercises his knowledge and stQI commits sin, and we marvel if there really be anyone in such a state ; but we are b;j no means astonished at a man's sinning if he does not exercise his faiowledge. 376 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VII. 5. 3. Again, there is anotlier sense, different from the modes referred to above, in wliich ' knowledge ' is found or (3) obscured by ^ ^^^^ rpj^g mental State implied in a man's passion ; ___._ ... havmg knowledge without using it, is, as we see, characteristic and peculiar ; implying that in one sense he has and in another sense he has not knowledge, as when he is in a state of sleep, or madness or drunkenness. But assuredly this is the state to which men are reduced when under the influence of their passions. In fact fits of passion or sensual gratification or other forms of moral depravity unmistakeably change even the bodily appearance; and in some cases actually cause madness. It is evident then that the state of those who are weakly sinful is analogous to the case of those who are physically unnerved. Again, men do not differ in this fact simply — that some have knowledgeamd also use it, while others have knowledge without using it, but they differ also' in respect of the actual possession. Those who have knowledge do not all possess their knowledge in the same way. It is possible for a man while possessing knowledge, to possess it not, if, for example, he be asleep or mad or dnmk. It is in this latter sense that men who are in the toils of passion possess knowledge. Men are drunk through indulging their desires, and they are mad throngli yielding to passion, and just as in the case of men who are mad or drunk, So also are the bodies of those who are weakly sinful changed and altered un- mistakeably in consequence of the passions to which they yield : their colour and aspect is altered, and sometimes they become raving mad. It is evident, there- fore, that the knowledge of those who are weakly sinful is of a similar character to that of men who are intoxicated or raving in madness. 4. Again, for a man to use arguments derived from Science is no proof of his own knowledge. Men who are and'alpaZtti^: ^^^'i^r the influence of their passions wiU often repeat learned demonstrations and the verses of Empedocles, just as boys when first taught will string together sentences of which they understand not a word. Knowledge, to be really knowledge, must be assimilated, and the process of assimilation is a work of time. Men who are weak and sinful must be understood to talk of moral truths only as actors recite them on the stage. Even though the weakly sinful use the arguments of Science, they are not proved on that account to be different from those mentioned above. Men who are drunk will utter learned demonstrations and the verses of Empedocles ; just in the same way that boys who are just beginning to learn, string together sentences but understand nothing before they have grown into a state of moral habitnation, and as it were assimilated their knowledge — a result to be attained only through a long training. Men who weakly and sinfully indulge themselves must be supposed to talk upon questions of duty only as actors upon the stage talk when they are representing certain characters, and repeating the verses which occur in the poems but understand not a word that they say. Bk. VIL 5.] Translation. 377 {d) PSYCHOLOGICAL EXPLANATION OF MOEAL EVIL. Again, we may also regard the cause of Moral Evil from the point of view of the psychologist, in the following light. In the Moral Syllogism into which the Operation of the . , 1 -J. ij? • r • i- 1 • 1 Practical Syllo- mind shapes itseii in lormmg practical judg- gig^, ments, there is first of all the Universal pro- position, and secondly an opinion bearing upon the particular fact of which the senses are immediately cognisant. When out of these two propositions a third has resulted, it necessarily follows that while in the sphere of speculative Ethics the mind should simply assert this conclusion, so in the sphere of practical Ethics, the mind should forthwith carry its conclusion into effect. As an lexample of practical reasoning, suppose that there is in the mind •the general proposition, e.g. ' One ought to taste whatever is sweet,' and also the particular proposition ' Such and such an object is sweet,' it inevitably results that a man who has the power, and is not hindered, should proceed to act upon the practical conclusion. When however there is in the mind a conflict of beliefs — when, for instance, there is one Universal which forbids him to taste, and another Universal which says ' All that is sweet is pleasant ' (with a minor premiss ' This particular thing is sweet ' actively operating in the mind), and a sensual desire happens to be asso- ciated therewith, what takes place is this : though the first Univer- sal says ' Avoid this,' yet desire leads and impels him to self-in- dulgence from the power which it has of setting in motion every bodily organ. The result of this mental conflict is that the weak man yields to temptation under the influence of Reason in a kind of way, and from a rational opinion, — an opinion which is not essentially, but only under these special circumstances, opposed to Reason : it is desire and not opinion which is opposed to Reason, ■ in such a case. [Herein is the reason why brutes are not ' morally weak : ' moral weakness implies the consciousness of a moral law, but brutes have no idea of law or conception of the Universal, but only sensuous impressions and a memory confined to particulars.] Again, one might consider the cause on account of which men who axe morally weak do not make choice of the good, though they know what it is, from the point of view of the psychologist, in the following light. In the Moral Syllogism into which we may analyse conduct, there is a Universal proposition, and there is also a particular judgment, which is of course concerned with particular objects of sense. Now when frgm this Universal and particular judgment we have inferred a third proposition, it necessarily follows that if that conclusion be a theoretical one, the understanding should affirm it and believe 378 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VII. 5. that it is so in reality. On the other hand if the conclusion be a practical one it necessarily follows that the man should forthwith carry it into effect, unless there be some one to hinder him. For example, it is a theoretical opinion that ' hellebore is harmful ' or that ' honey is sweet ; ' and if we have drawn such a conclusion we simply heliene it, we do not act it. An instance of a practical judgment would be ' we ought to taste whatever is sweet ; ' and if we have drawn such a conclusion, we immediately put it into effect and taste. When, therefore, there are opinions, as well general as particular, which urge a man to do some- thing (e.g. ' it is right to taste this thing because it is sweet,' and ' whatever is sweet ought to be tasted ') while at the same time there is Science and Universal Reason urging a man not to taste, yet withal a desire for the thing in questioi present in the mind, the conclusion drawn from these premisses finds iwstuall expression, and the man puts the conclusion into practice — the tTniversal for- bidding him to taste while desire associated with opinion is moving him to the thing to be tasted. Desire of course has power to influence each sepaiatei organ of sense (I mean the senses peculiar to the object of desire — ^if the pleasant object be visible, it draws to itself sight, and taste, if the object be one of taste. It consequently happens that moral weakness takes place under the influence of Reason and Opinion opposed to Reason. Opinion is not in itself opposed to Reason but on accoimt of its association with Desire : Opinion does not by its own strength overmaster Reason, since it is impossible that Opinion shonld prevail against Right Reason, but it is owing to the strength of Desire, which even transforms and alters the very constitution of a man. Moral Weakness is therefore brought about by a process of Reason, and of Opinion expressed in opposition to Right Reason, by means of Desire. [It is for this reason that brutes cannot be termed morally weak — because they have no reason against which desire is in opposition but only a sensuous representation of particular objects and a sensuous memory.] (e) THE PROCESS OF MOEAL KEFOEMATION. To explain how the ignorance of the weak man is dispelled and he comes again into possession of knowledge, no mtJ^sTnYioS special solution is needed: the principle which to the recovery explains this condition is not special, but the weXiess ^^^'''^'' same as that which explains the recovery of a man from intoxication, or the waking of the sleeper ; and for this we must refer to the psychologist. To explain how the ignorance of the weak man is dispelled when his passion is quenched, and he comes again to his sound senses, and developes his life in conformity with true Science, that is the same question which arises in the case of one who is drnnk or slumbering ; and the matter is one for the psychologists to determine. (_/) CONCLUSION : IT IS SENSUOUS AND NOT INTELLECTUAL KNOW- LEDGE WHICH IS COMPATIBLE WITH A WEAK WILL. To sum up : since the minor premiss of the Moral Syllogism is The Socratic soiu- an Opinion in regard to what falls within tiie tion is true : the range of the senses and has conti'ol over the CnofknfwieXe «°^duct of daily life, this premiss is_ either not in the strict sense, possesscd by a man who is under the influence of BkYII. 6.] Translation. 379 passion, or, if it be possessed, possession of Imowledge is not equivalent to the realizing of knowledge, but is only the bare repetition of words, like the reciting of EmpedocleS by a drunken man. Furthermore, since the minor premiss is not universal, and has not the same scientific character as the Universal, the solution which Socrates tried to present seems to be the real one : it is not knowledge in the strict sense which is present in the mind when the conflict of weakness arises, nor is it real know- ledge which is twirled about under the power of passion, but only sensuous or emotional knowledge. The explanations above given must suffice to answer the question whether it be possible for a man to yield to evil with a full know- ledge of his act, and to determine the sense which knowledge assumes under such circumstances, j! , When the man of weak will finds himself in the toils of passion, he either does Jnot possess at all, and does not know, the minor premiss which controls par- j^tionlai actions (the premiss which would tell him that ' such and such a thing is evil,') or he possesses it after the manner in which men who are drunk or raving- utter verses or demonstrations ; more particularly for the reason that the minor premiss is not, in fact, scientific by itself in the sense in which the universal and major premiss is. Hence it seems that the solution which Socrates tried to present is the real one. The moral temptation does not arise while knowledge' (I mean knowledge in the real and recognized sense, i.e. the Universal), is present : Desire has no power over this kind of knowledge ; — but it does arise in the presence of that Mnd of knowledge which is concerned with and has control over particular facts, i.c., the minor premiss. It is this particular knowledge which is violated by the man who acts under passion — ^this particular knowledge being concerned with actual oonduBt ; and it is this particular knowledge which is dragged about under temptation, and not the universal knowledge. The explanations here advanced must suffice in regard to the knowledge which men of weak wiU possess, in reply to the question whether they have knowledge at aU of ' the good,' and in what sense they have knowledge when they yield to temptation. ii. — The special conditions whieh test the weakness or strength of the character. (a) PLEASUEES BEING (l) NAXUKAL OE (2) UNNATUEAL OK (s) INDE- TEEMmATE, THEEE AEE COEEESPONDING DIVISIONS OF THE MOEAL CHAEACTEE. The question which comes next in order for us to discuss is this : Is there any absolute form of moral weak- ^ , _ -,-, n in PIT Is there any abso- ness, or are all cases ol moral weakness referable i^te form of moral to special failings ? Or, if a man can be morally weakness ? and weak in an absolute sense, what precisely are the '*'' ^ '» ^ ^ p subjects relatively to which he displays his weakness ? 380 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VII. 6. Evidently the sphere in which strength and manliness, self- indulgence and effeminacy are shown, is that of pleasure and pain. But pleasures and pains have in them important points of dis- tinction. Some of the objects which produce pleasure are in- evitable ; others again are desirable, though admitting of excess. (1) Inevitable pleasures are such as are natural to the body 5 such, I mean, as are associated with food and the satisfaction of the sensual instincts, in connection wherewith we placed sen- suality and temperance. (2) Objects which are neither inevitable nor essential, though in themselves desirable and delectable, are, I mean, such objects as victory, honour, wealth, and similar things that are good and delightful. Now when men are extravagant in reference to these innocent pleasures, though they violate the law of Eight within them- selves, we do not call them ' weak ' in the absolute sense, but we add a qualifying term and speak of them as ' weakly yielding to the temptations of riches or gain or ambition or passion.' We do not speak of such men as being weak absolutely, since they form a distinct class, and are only called weak relatively and through similarity of relations. The limitation in this case is like that implied in the description ' The man wlio was vidmcm at the Olympic Games .•' the general conception of man is not very different from the particular designation, though still a distinction is implied. In further proof of this distinction is this fact : moral weakness in the absolute sense of the term is blamed, not merely as an error, but actually as a kind of depravity, either in the full sense of sin or in some special relation ; whereas none of these men {i.e. the men who are called ' weak ' in one of these special senses) are blamed in that way. The man who is called ' morally weak,' in the absolute sense of the term (and without any qualification confining his weakness to special objects such as anger), is a man who, in reference to those bodily and personal indulgences which constitute the sphere of temperance or dissoluteness, pursues the excess of what is ]3leasurable and shrinks from the excess of what is painful — hunger and thirst, heat and cold, and whatever sensations are yssociated with touch and taste ; not in consequence of any choice that he has made, but contrary to the direction of his own will and judgment. Herein is a proof: men are called 'selfr indulgent ' or ' effeminate ' in regard to sensual indulgences, but not in regard to ideal aims, such as wealth, or honour. It is for this reason also that we place the weak and the vicious in the same category, and vice versd the strong-minded man and the temperate man, while we keep the other characters distinct JLVII. 6.] Translation. 381 rom either, the reason being, I say, that the former are both in I sense concerned with the same class of pleasures and pains. But in saying that the weak-minded and the viciou^ display their jliaracters upon similar objects, I do not mean that their attitude fi the same thereto : — the dissolute yield to temptation of their wa. free choice, and the weak-minded contrary to their better udo'ment. Hence we should call a man more thoroughly dissolute ffhen he pursues excessive pleasures and shirks even moderate inconveniences, not through the power of desire upon him (or frith such desire acting but slightly upon him), than the man ffho gives himself up to pleasure through the fierce domination rf the desires over him. What would such an one do, if there settled upon him the full passions of youth and a painful craving tf^satiate his bodily needs ? We mtLst now go on to explain wlietlier a man may be ' morally -weak ' in an ibsolute sense without any quaUfioation, or whether all men are weak in some rpeoial oonneotion, as for instance in regard to temper or reputation ; or, if a aan may be weak in an unqualified sense, what are the precise circumstances in wMoli his weakness will be shown. The general truth is evident that the objects with which men of resolute and manly character (both in the absolute and in the special sense), and men of weak Hidreffeminate character, are concerned are pleasures and pains. But inasmuch IS some objects which cause pleasure are essential, and others non-essential iough pleasant in themselves and desirable (by ' essential pleasures ' are meant iliose without which the human race collectively could not subsist, as, for ixample, marriage, or the individual, as food, rest, sleep, and such like ; and by non-essential ' pleasures those which are yet desirable and pleasurable by them- ielves and not from the constitution of man — wealth, honour, victory and such ike), it happens that there are excesses in both these forms of pleasure, as well n those which are essential as in those which are desirable for their own sake — yhen^that is, one indulges in them to a degree beyond what is right and beyond That Right Reason prescribes for their indulgence. Now a man who is extravagant in respect of pleasures which are not essential 8 not called ' weak ' absolutely without qualification ; but a man who weakly fields to the temptations of fame or wealth — the idea being that suoh an one is a iistinot character from the man who is weak in the perfect and absolute sense — B only called weak on account of a certain similarity with the other. In the lame way there is a distinction between ' the man nlio gained the prize at the, Oli/injiio Games ' and ' man ' generically : although the distinction between them 3 slight, stiU there is a distinction, and the former description is different from ihe latter on account of the special qualification. It is fm-ther evident that the weakness which is shown in regard to non- !SS6ntial pleasm'es is different from weakness in the absolute sense of the term, rom the fact that weakness in the fuU sense is censured, and is thought to be lot simply an error but also a vice, either completely or in some special relation ;■ !rhereas weakness in connection with a special qualification is not censured as a 'ice. Those then who are extravagant in regard to non-essential pleasures are lalled ' weak ' only with a special limitation. . On the other hand, those who are extravagant in reference to essential and icjdily pleasures, when Reason does not decide in their favour or assent to their adnlgence but sets itself in opposition to them, and who while pursuing in excess he pleasureis wherein the temperate and the vicious man are tested, avoid pains aore than is • becoming — ^the pains, for instance, of hunger and thirst, of heat 382 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VII. 6. and cold, and whatever is connected with touch and taste — such men are eaJled ' weak ' without any limitation, in the absolute sense of the term. This distinction is evident also from the fact that those who indulge eitiava- gantly in such pleasures are called ' dissolute,' but by no means are they so called who transgress in respect of indeterminate pleasures. Since in fact the tern-, perate and the manly character, or the weak and dissolute character, are found to be displayed in reference to the same kind of bodily pleasures, we place the temperate man in the same category as the strong-minded man, and the dissolute man in the same category as the weak man. Nevertheless these characteiss' do not respectively hold the same attitude in regard to these pleasures. The disso- lute man is hurried on to the satisfying of his desires of his own wish and choice, whereas the weak man in indulging his desires is not acting in accordance with his own choice but with Right Reason raising a conflict in his mind. However we place the weak man in the same class as the dissolute man, and the strong- minded man in the same class as the temperate man, and we say that they are both concerned with the same objects ; whUe on the contrary we place those who behave weakly in regard to pleasures that are not necessary in a claa apart. But although the weak man is concerned with the same objects as the dissolute man, yet the dissolute man is the more reprehensible as being the worse slave to his passions. The weak man is overmastered by very violent passions : — other- wise he could not be weak in face of the opposition which Reason makes. The dissolute man, on the other hand, is overmastered by trifling and weak passions inasmuch as Right Reason does nothing to counteract them ; and he seeks the excess of pleasm-e and avoids even moderate pains : wherefore if under the influence of even moderate desires, he is thus overpowered, what kind of character would he prove to be if there came upon him the full force of youth- ful passion and a painftil and violent craving for the satisfaction of physical needs ? {p) METAPHORICAL APPLICATION OF THE TERM 'WEAKNESS.' But since there is a distinction in pleasures and desires, some . , of them belonginer to the class of things honour- The answer is to be , , , ii j /• t • , n t • t • found in the dis- able and excellent (some objects of desire being tinction between in fact by nature desirable), while others are the proper and the .t i ±i ■ n i i metaphorical uses ™6 rcvcrse and others agam morally colourless of the term 'morai (such as Wealth and gain, victory and honour),- wea ness. according to the classification which we have already made, in reference to all such things whether good or evil or indeterminate, men are not blamed simply for being under the influence of such and such feelings, nor for having such and such desires and likings, but for yielding to a certain form of excess in their indulgence. Hence it is not a mark of depraviiy that men are overpowered by such influences contrary to Eeason, or that they pursue any of those objects which are in their nature noble and good (I mean, for example, when men are more keen than is right in the pursuit of honour or affection for their children and parents). In truth these are among things which are good, and men are praised for the interest they show about them; notwithstanding that there is a possible excess even in the pursuit of these simple and natural aims, if, for example, Bk. VII. 6.] Translation. 383 one contend, as Niobe did, even against the Gods, or as Satyrus, nicknamed 'father-doting,' did in regard to his father, since he was seen to be exceedingly foolish. However in ail such cases there is no kind of moral depravity implied, for the reason which Llhave stated — that every one of these objects is in and by itself desirable; although the various forms of excess which these aims may take are censurable, and evil, and to be avoided. For similar reasons neither is there any ' moral weakness ' im- plied in these relations, since moral weakness is not merely a thing to be avoided but one of those things which are positively censurable. I On account, however, of the similarity in the mental condition imphed, for example, in a weak yielding to ambition with the condition implied in a weak yielding to pleasure, men speak of ' moral weakness ' in connection with such things as honour or riches, adding however a term of qualification to limit the term to . that extent. In the same way we speak of a man as being a 'bad '' doctor ' or a ' bad actor ' whom we could never call a bad man without such a qualification. The same limitation is therefore implied in this use of the term ' moral weakness ' : as the desires for riches, or honour, and such things are not vices in themselves, though they bear a certain resemblance thereto from the fact of their being analogous, so obviously we must understand that to be the only real strength or weakness of character which is displayed in the sphere in which their opposites, self-restraint or dissolute- ness, are displayed. In describing any attitude towards anger as a moral weakness, we are only using a metaphor in virtue of a certain ideal correspondence. Hence it is that we use a term of limitation in such cases, and speak of a man as ' weakly yielding to anger,' just as he might yield to motives of ambition or of gain. Again, of things wMoh are pleasurable some are by nature good, some by nature evil and otliers indeterminate. Pleasures which are good by nature are such as we seek for their own sokes and not for ulterior objects ; for example, reputation, victory, health. Pleasures which are evil by nature are for example cannibalism or the drinking of human blood or unnatural sensualism. Pleasures which are indeterminate are such as in themselves are neither good nor evil but only subservient to some good as food, clothing or wedlock. Now when a man pursues pleasures which are good by nature or which are indeterminate, he is praised — if he does not transgress Right Reason but pursues his object in a proper manner. Excess of course is in all cases not praised, though in the case of things good by nature excess is not blamed, nor is it vicious, since the objects pursued are, as has been explained, by nature good and are sought for their own sake. Nevertheless, it is a thing to be avoided and evil. For instance though affection for children is by nature good, yet one ought to flee from the excess and not love them as Niobe did, who contended on 384 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VII. 6 their behalf even with the Gods, or act as Satyrus who invoked his father as a Gtoi (since he was thought to be utterly senseless thereby). Yet neither is this kind of excess ' moral weakness,' that being a thing noi merely to be avoided but one of those things which are positively censuiable Still it is commonly called ' weakness ' in virtue of a certain similarity which fo] example weakness in respect of gain or honour bears in relation to the quaUfieo weakness which has been explained. Such an one is not weak in the absolntf sense but weak only in respect of honour or philoprogenitiveness or some sncl thing ; just as we speak of a ' bad doctor,' one who treats his patients coutrarj to the rules of art, or of a ' bad actor,' one who does not copy accurately the person whom he is representing but not as ' bad ' in an unqualified sense. Failure of that kind is not a vice except by resemblance, in connection with a qualifying term. Excess, therefore, in regard to things which are in their natui'e good and pleasant presents the character described above. But the forms of excess in regard to things by nature indeteiToinate are morally evU and censurable : sncl things have not their character one way or the other from themselves ; but thej are good or evil in virtue of the end towards which they are directed. Where- fore, if they are designed to compass a wicked end, they are themselves wiokecf; and they are designed to meet a wicked end when they are pursued in excess, A man who gives way to excess in the use of viands or clothing or other things in themselves necessary and indulges therein contrary to Right Reason, brings them to a level that may serve sensual pleasure. For this reason excess in e^I such things is a species of wickedness. In regard to certain objects there ia weakness implied absolutely and without any qualification ; such, for example, are the objects which form the sphere of temperance or dissoluteness. (c) THE PLEASUKES OF BESTIALITY, NATUKAL OR ACQUIRED. Now wMle, on the other hand, some objects are by Nature pleasurable (either absolutely or else relatively to torbiT^ltates^rf different races of animals and of men), other ob- the physical and jects ou the Contrary are pleasurable only as the moral nature. consequence of jjhysical defects or evil habits or corruptions of nature. In reference, therefore, to these abnormal pleasures we may see states of the moral nature corresponding. The states to which I refer are bestial or savage conditions ; such as that of the woman who devoured little unborn children tearing them from their mothers' wombs, or the foul pleasures in which some of the brutalized tribes around the Euxine indulge, delight- ing in raw meat or the flesh of human beings, whUst others lend their children to one another to serve as a feast ; or such a story of cannibalism as that recorded of Phalaris. Besides these cases of simple savagery, there are other similar cases caused by disease or, in certain cases, by madness — as was that of the man who sacrificed his mother and devoured her flesh, or of the man who feasted on the heart of his fellow-slave. Other instances of abnormal conditions caused by disease or by bad habits would be the tearing out of the hair, the biting of the nails or the chewing of ashes or of earth, or, worst of all, unnatural lust between man and man. Such practices are found in some Bk. VII. 6.] Translation. 385 cases as a result of nature and in other cases as the result of habit, as when people are outraged from the time of childhood. • la the case of things which are evil by nature though they are also pleasurable, it is not simply the excesses which are wicked, but absolutely the moral incli- nation towards them at all, — \.e. states of bestiality, are in themselves wicked : nor in fact are such things iy nature pleasurable. Some objects of course are natmally jjJeasurable to all living beings, as food, sleep and such like ; whUe other things though naturally pleasurable are not so to all alike^for example, a parfcieular kind of food (for instance, particular kinds of food, such as grass or flesh, are naturally pleasant to some, though not to all, creatures), while other filmigs are not naturally pleasant in any sense, but are pleasant only through evil habituation or mutilation or depravity of disposition ; and these latter objects are in their nature evil. These unnatural conditions are those with which bestiality is concerned. Such is the case reported of a woman who devoured little unborn children, or that of the savage pleasure in which the brutalized inhabitants around the Buxine indulge who eat raw fish and uncooked flesh and lend their children to one another to serve for a banquet ; or of the conduct of Phalaris in eating his own son. Such evil courses assuredly though they be pleasurable, are not pleasurable by nature but only appear to be pleasurable through a taint of nature. There are other things again in which men delight in consequence of mutilation, or derangement, or some other malady. Instances of madness are such as when the madman eats the heart of his fellow slave, or sacrifices and eats his mother, and instances of disease are when a man eats earth or ashes. A man becomes bestial through habit when he has been habituated to pleasures which violate nature, from the very dawn of life, and delights in food in which no mortal takes pleasure unless he has deviated from the limits of nature and is dissolute with a sensualism that is contrary to nature. Under this category comes also the man who takes pleasure in tearing out his hair or gnawing his nails. All such practices arise through depravity of nature. [d] APPLICATION OF THE TERM ' WEAKNESS ' TO PUSELY MORBID CONDITIONS. Now where nature is the cause of depravity, no one would call its victims ' weak : ' as little would one find fault with a woman for being female instead of male ; ^'"^='1. ^^-eakness is and it is precisely the same with those whose tual, and must morbid condition is the consequence of evil habit, sometimes^ be qua- The possession indeed of these abnormal tenden- or^moAid.'^^'* cies is, in every case, beyond the pale of vice; and if a man possesses them, his subduing them or being subdued by them is only a sign of strength or weakness of character in an analogous or metaphorical and not an absolute sense — exactly as a man who is in an abnormal condition in regard to his angry passions may be called ' weak in respect of temper,' but not weak in an unqualified sense. All cases indeed of folly, or cowardice, or viciousness, or brutality, are either forms of bestiality or of disease. One man, for instance, is of a nature to be afraid of anything, even if a mouse rustle, having the cowardice character- istic of a brute ; another man was afraid of a cat, through disease. 386 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VII. 7. Some men, again, are void of reason 'through a defect of nature and live simply by sensation, and these are savages, like certain races of far-distant barbarians; others again are so through disease, as in cases of epilepsy, and of madness caused by illness. Now some of these ailments one may have for a certain time or occasion without being overmastered by them permanently :— I mean, for instance, that Phalaris might have refrained himself when the desire came upon him to devour a little child, or that unnatural desire for animal gratification might be curbed. It is, however, possible not merely to have these unnatural lusts, but to be overpowered by them. Precisely, then, as wickedness, when it is consistent with human nature, is called wickedness without qualification, whereas special kinds of wickedness require limi- tation (as being ' bestial ' or ' diseased ' ) ; so too it is clear that moral ' weakness ' has two additional or qualified forms, the ' bestial ' and the ' morbid,' and can only be spoken of absolutely when it induces that kind of sinfulness which is natural to man. It is evident, then, that the field in which strength or weakness of character are displayed, is the same exactly as that of vicious- ness and self-control ; and further in regard to the aims of hfe generally there is a distinct form of weakness which is called so by metaphorical analogy and not in an unqualified sense. When, however, men delight in what is naturally evil, through their own •depravity, they are not ' morally weak,' since there is no ' Kight Eeason ' in their case which they withstand. Similarly neither are acts done in consequence of evil habituation, or disease, or madness ; hut the fact of a man's taking pleasure in such things places him altogether outside the limits of vice. But if anyone is at one time master of his evil desires, and at another is Tuaslered by them, he is not called ' weak ' absolutely but with an addition, nor is he called strong simply, but strong' with an addition ; e.g. ' strong in curbing ■savage instincts ' or weai therein. Savagery is not concerned with the same circumstances as viciousness, as simple manliness is. Viciousness is concerned with natural pleasures in the same way that simple manliness is ; whereas savagery is concerned with pleasures that violate matter. Indeed all cases of vice, or folly or cowardice, or sensualism or bratahty that are indulged in to excess are either oases of savagery or of disease. One man, for instance, is of a character to fear everything, even if a mouse rustle, being a coward with the cowardice of a beast ; another is diseased such as was the man who through disease feared a cat. In the case again of folly some men are by nature devoid of the power of calculation and live by sense alone — as are some tribes of remote barbarians, being irrational after the manner of beasts. Now it is possible to have these mental characteristios without being over- mastered by them ; as for instance if Phalaris had restrained his lust at the time that he desired to devom- his son. It is possible also to be overmastered thereby. ■Weakness or strength, however, of this kind we must not call weakness or strength without qualification but must limit their meaning, as was explained above, as ' the weakness of the brute,' or ' the weakness of disease,' or ' strength in repressing savage instincts of vice or disease.' On the other hand, weakness in the absolute sense is simply that which is in the line of viciousness common ±0 man. Bk. VII. 7.] Translation. ^87 It has now been stown that weakness or strength of character has simply reference to the subjects with which dissoluteness or temperance is concerned • and further that the weakness which has reference to other obj flits of pleasure is a^Btinot form of weakness so called by metaphor and not in the perfect sense of the term. ;. Ill— COMPARISON OF THE VARIOUS FORMS OF MORAL EVIL. i. — Yielding to lust is worse than yielding to anger. We must now examine the position that ' a weak yielding to anger is less disgraceful than a weak yielding to the desires.' 1. Now anger seems in a kind of way to listen to Reason, though it listens amiss. It is like those over- eager servants who rush upon their errand before -^-ig™ listens to they understand what they are told and conse- fZ? ''''""*'"' quently miscarry their message ; or like dogs who begin to bark if anything rustle before considering whether it be friend or foe. In this way it is that Anger, through the heat and excitement of its nature, though it listens to Reason yet catches not the word of command but hurries away to find its satisfaction. In such cases if Reason or Imagination only make it clear that an insult or a slight has been cast upon it, Anger drawing the inference as it were that ' it is right to fight against such things,' fires forth into instant rage. On the other hand Desire is incessant in its craving : if Reason or Sense only whisper that ' such a thing is pleasant ' it rushes on to gratify its appetite. Anger, therefore, is in a kind of way, faithful to Reason whereas Desire is quite irrational: hence to obey Desire is more dis- graceful than to obey Anger. The man who yields to Anger is in a sense overmastered by Reason ; whereas in the other case a man 18 simply overmastered by his appetites and Reason has no voice in the matter. we must now enquire which form of weakness is the more disgfraceful — the ffeakneas which yields to appetite or that which yields to anger. It is commonly (nought that that which yields to Desire is worse than that which yields to iflger. 1. For the man who gives vent to anger does not in every sense refuse to obey ^ason, but in a kind of way listens to, yet mis-hears, the voice of Eeason ; just «e over-hasty servants who rush out before they have heard what the command fid upon them is ; and so fail to fulfil their errand ; or like dogs who bark at ;he merest rustle before considering whether the arrival be that of friend or foe. *'M thus that Anger, owing to the warmth and impetuosity of its natm-e, hearing iae voice of Reason but not hearing what its command is, rushes out to vent its c c 2 388 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VII. 7, resentment. In sucli cases there is a rational inference or impression indicating simply that ' sucli an one is insulting or despising or injnring a man ; ' anc Anger drawing the inference as it were that one ought to fight against sncl things, forthwith fires into a rage. Anger does thus in a certain sense follow th( guidance of Reason. On the other hand, Desire, if only sense or Reason vitiateo by sense whisper that such a thing is pleasant, rushes instantly to find its gratifi- cation therein. Consequently, Anger follows the g:nidance of Reason in a certaii sense, but Desire not at all ; and for this reason a man who is weai on the side of appetite is morally worse than the man who is morally weak on the side ol anger. The man who weakly yields to anger is in a kind of fashion controlled by Reason, whereas the man who weakly yields to Desire is controlled bj appetite. 2. Moreover, it is more pardonable for a man to follow his physical impulses : in fact it is more pardonable 2. Anger is more for him to foUow even his desires when those natural t n e- ^ggjj.gg ^re of a nature to be common to all men, and in the degree in which they are common, But Anger and harshness are more constitutional and natural than the desires, when those desires are in excess and are not natural. That there is excuse for a man who follows the bent of his nature may be illustrated by the story of the man who gave as his reason for beating his father the plea that his father had beaten his grandfather, and his grandfather his great grandfather ; and pointing to his son he said, ' This little fellow will beat me when he has grown to be a man : — it is a constitutional weakness in oui family.' Or one might take another instance of the same tendency in the case of the man who was being dragged about by his son, and begged of him to stop at the doors on the plea that he had never dragged his own father past the door. 2. Moreover it is a lighter evil to foUow natural impulses than such as are less natural : natural impulses having a greater claim to consideration. Bnt weak yielding to auger is more natural than weak yielding to appetitesr-I mean such desires as are not necessary and which are pursued in excess, such as money or honour. Hence the weakness of anger is a more tolerable evil than the weak- ness of the appetites ; and it is evident that what is more natural is also more excusable. For instance, a man being rebuked for beating his father, made it his excuse that anger of this kind and the weakness which yielded thereto was constitutional in him ; in fact that his own father was a beater of kU father and his grandfather before him, and, he added ' my own son will be like tib all and will beat me when he has grown to be a man.' There is another illustration of this tendency in the story of the man who when dragged along by his son begged him to stop at the door : ' I never dragged my own father,' he said ' f nrSier than that.' It is evident, then, that it affords some excuse for evil deeds that a man has a constitutional tendency towards them ; and this makes the crime more endurable. That it is more natural to yield to anger than to yield to appetite, is evident. To be enraged in the simple sense of the term is more natural than to desire what is not necessary. The feeling of anger was implanted in our nature for the preservation of our species — that we might shake off from ourselves what u harmful ; and that is the aim towards which it tends. On the oontraiy, desire BLVII. 7.] Translatioii. 389 for what is not necessary is not natural : it is possible to preserve our nature ■vrithout either victory or honour. Hence the feeling of anger has a wider range thaii the desires for what is not necessary. Anger is inheren-flfcin all men, and in all sentient beings ; whereas the desires are not universal even among men. Siaoe then the feeling of anger is more natural than desires of this kind, and the excesses of anger are more natural than excess in the appetites, the weakness which yields to anger is more natural, and therefore less blameable, than the ^fekness which yields to the appetites. 3. Again, men are the more evil the more they are deliberate in their wrongdoings. Now neither the angry man nor anger itself are the results of deliberate 3. Anger is less intention but are open and undisguised. On the [lesirr^ ^ ^^ other hand Desire is crafty in its working ; just as Aphrodite herself is said to be " The Goddess Cyprus-born, the weaver of deceit." In the same spirit Homer sings of her embroidered girdle, how jUpon it was " The temptress-tongue that guiles the thought e'en of the prudent mind." Consequently, since this form of moral evil is more wrongful, so also is it more disgraceful than weak yielding to anger ; and jindeed it is ' moral weakness ' in the strict sense of the term and io a kind of way moral depravity. 3. Again, among evU men those are the more evil whose sin. is the more medi- tated. But Desire is more deliberate than Anger ; therefore it is more sinful. That it is more deliberate, is obvious. It steals over a man imperceptibly, and does not come on with a rush, as Anger does. Men who vent their anger display their feelings openly, whereas those who indulge their lusts are scarcely noticed at all because they enjoy themselves secretly as it were and steal their gi-atifi- tation by secret guile ; and hence they are carried on of their ovni accord by a Jind of guile and deceit to the objects of their lusts. Homer too says of Aphro- 'ffii^ that she is ' the weaver of deceit ; ' and for this reason they ascribe to Apkrodite the embroidered girdle, representing thereby the cunning craftiness of Itoti-and thj phrase 'The temptress-tongue which guiles the thought e'en of the prudent mind," Sin the same direction. Consequently, if lust of this kind is more wrongful, tethe weakness which yields to it is more disgraceful than that which yields to ^^i ; and this form of weakness and dissoluteness is the perfect form and vice iH'fiie unqpaUfied sense. 4. Again, no one acts wantonly when wantonness gives him paija ; but whenever a man acts under the in- ftence of anger, his acts are painful to himself, pLinfuiTthTJrati- |nd not, as in the case of wantonness attended fication of desire is *ith pleasure. If then the things against which ^^"^^ ^°- fre ought to be most enraged, are those which are more evil, the weakness which is caused by lust will be more evil than the weak- 390 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. Vri,7. ness whicli yields to anger, since there is no wantonness nor pleasure in anger. It is clear, then, that moral weakness accompanying the desires is more disgraceful than that which attends anger ; and further that the special field in which strength or feebleness of the moral nature is shown, are the gratifications and pleasures of the body. 4. Again, no one feels pain in following abnormal pleasures, but everyone is pained when giving vent to anger. Now a man is more censured who taies delight in doing evil, than is the man who feels pain in doing evil. The mam who feels pain is thought to give some satisfaction for the error he commits, and for this reason is thought less guilty. Hence the man who follows unnatural pleasure is justly thought more guilty than the man who vents his anger. The weakness therefore which accompanies lust is a worse evil than the weaka^' which accompanies anger ; since things are more evil in proportion as resentment is more justly felt against them. It is clear then from what has been said that the weakness which yields to lust is more disgraceful than the weakness which yields to anger ; and further that the sphere in which strength or weakness of tlie moral nature is displayed is the sphere defined by the lusts and pleasures of the body. ii. — iContrast l)etweeii Weakness, Dissoluteness, Savagery, and Effeminacy. (a) DISSOLUTENESS WOESE THAN SAVAGERY. Here we must take into account the difierences between the different kinds of pleasure and desire. t^Tibie,''' but "less l& y . life that is free from pain ' and that ' children [hkt \ ' temper^e and animals pursue pleasure,' all such difficulties ™an avoids aU are solved in the same manner. It has been P^^""*- explained how that in a way there are pleasures which are good absolutely, and how that not all pleasures are good. The pleasures, then, which animals and children pursue are pleasures of an imperfect kind ; and it is from the pain of these false pleasures that the perfect man shrinks ; pleasures, I mean, which are attended by desire and pain (as truly they are), and the excesses of pleasure which bring a man to utter dissoluteness. Hence the temperate man flees from such pleasures as these, though there are pleasures in which even the temperate man may indulge. The difficulty which may arise from the fact that temperate men and men of practical wisdom avoid pleasure, and aim not so much at a life of pleasure as at a life that is free from pain, and from the fact that children and animals pursue pleasure, is solved by what has been said in a previous chapter. The solution is briefly this. Some pleasures being good absolutely, and others not absolutely, the latter class are pursued by animals and children, and avoided by temperate men, who in regard to them wish merely to be free from pain. So also with men of practical wisdom and all good men. I refer to the pleasures which are attended with desire and pain, the bodily pleasures, that is to say (for all bodily pleasures are of this kind), and the excesses of such pleasures, which form the sphere of the dissolute man and which are consequently avoided by the temperate man. The other class of pleasures, those which are such absolutely, are pursued by both the temperate man and the man of practical wisdom : they are temperate pleasures and are the activities of praiseworthy states of mind : the pleasures I mean of temperance, justice, ajid philosophical investigation. iv.— Befutation of the theory that no form of pleasure can be the chief good. (1.) PLEASURE SHOWN TO BE A GOOD BECAUSE PAIN IS AN EVIL. Nay, further, it is admitted that pain is an evil and a thing to he avoided : in one aspect it is an unqualified evil, in another aspect it is a relative evil as Pleasure is opposed impeding the action of the individval in some to &T^-i^ * ^°° way or another. But the opposite of what is to be avoided — in the degree in which it is an evil and a thing to be avoided, is a good. It necessarily follows then that pleasure is under certain aspects a good. 414 The Moral , Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VII. 14. [The explanation whereby Speusippus tried to evade this dilemma, does not turn out to be true. He and not as one evil argued that the greater was opposed to the equal as well as to the less : and that, similarly, pleasure and pain were both opposed to the good. But no one could say that pleasure could be defined as any form of evil.] Further, since pain is partly a good, and partly an evil and to be avoided ; and since that kind of pain wMch is to be avoided is to be subdivided as being so partly in an absolute sense, as for example the pain •which sometimes ensues upon the performance of a virtuous action, and partly in a relative sense, as for example the pain which ensues upon the infliction of a penalty, which falls under this class, as being an obstacle to philosophical investigation : it follows that the opposite of pain, I mean pleasure, must also be of two kinds, absolute and rela-i" tive. To pain in its absolute sense must be opposed pleasure in an absolutSj, sense : to pain in its relative sense must be opposed pleasure in a relative sense. Speusippus is not successful in his attempt to break the validity of this argument by a counter-argument ; he says that just as in mathematics the greater and iJie less are opposed to the equal, and as in the case of the virtues thacffare two extremes opposed to the mean : so pleasure and pain are both opposed to the mean state of painlessness, the former standing to it in the relation of excesal the latter in that of defect. In other words painlessness is a good, pleasure and paJS; are each of them evil. But this argument is in every respect improbable : fornoi one thinks pleasure to be an evil, nor would anyone assert that pleasure in itself, qua, pleasure, is an evil. (2.) THE EVIL OF PLEASURES DOES NOT AFFECT THE PLEASURE OP HAPPINESS. Nor is there any reason to prevent pleasure of a certain kind being the chief good, though certain pleasures Certain forms of gj-g gyj^ . precisely as knowledge of a certain evil, and yet plea- kind might be the chief good, even though there sure may be an are certain forms of knowledge which are worth- element in happi- i i -i nesg. less and evil. Surely, then, it is a necessary consequence that, if in the case of every mental state there are certain modes where its development is unimpeded (whether happiness be the activity which arises from all these states, or whether it be the activity which arises from some special form of them), if the activity be unimpeded, it is a thing most desirable; but this unimpeded activity is -pleasure. Consequently, the chief good may he a certain mode of pleasure, even though the majority of pleasures be, possibly, evil per se. For this reason all men think that the happy life is a pleasur- able life, and with good grounds entwine pleasure into the very conception of happiness, no mode of human activity being perfect if it be fettered and impeded, and happiness belonging to what is perfect. Bk. VII. 14.] Translation. 415 Hence also tlie happy man needs for his happiness the good things which depend upon the body and external advantages and prosperity, so that he may not be impeded in ^ch relations. As for those who say that a man who is being racked on a wheel, or who is plunged in dire calamities, is happy provided he be virtuous, they only talk nonsense whether intentionally or not. Another mistake is this. In consequence of the need of fortune to supplement the inner dispositions, happiness is thought by some people to be identical with prosperity. That is not the case : in fact if good fortune be excessive, it is a hindrance to happiness, in which case it is no longer right to call it 'good fortune,' since good fortune has sole reference to happiness as its standard and measure. Nor does the fact that some pleasures are bad prove that pleasure cannot be the chief good and the Absolutely Best : for in the same way the fact that mmy forms of knowledge are bad does not prove that knowledge is not the Chief Good. Indeed it is not only a possible but actually a necessary conclu- sion that pleasure is the Chief Good and the ultimate object of choice. For if every mental state has its corresponding mode of activity, and if Happiness and the Chief Good is an unimpeded activity of a perfect mental state, whether that perfect state be one or many, it necessarily follows that Happiness and the Chief Good is pleasure. Nor is this conclusion invalidated by the fact that some forms of pleasure are evil. Moreover it is manifest that happiness must be an unimpeded activity : for no adivity that is impeded can be perfect (which by the nature of the case happi- ness must be). Consequently, as was stated in an earlier book of this treatise, a happy man has need of external goods, that his activity may not be impeded. Those who say that a man whose life is marked by great inequaJities of fortune and who meets with great calamities is happy, only talk nonsense, whether intentionally or not. For the happy man requires certain external advantages, foi-example health, and long life, and the indispensable conditions of a sound Wy, and start in life which comes of good fortune. It is on this account that S)iue persons have gone so far as to think that the fortunate man and the happy Inan are identical : because without the favour of fortune no one can be genuinely happy. But they are not in. reality identical : for the happy man must be a good man, but not every fortunate man is good. Indeed good fortune sometimes stands in the way of moral excellence, and spoils a good man, if it be excessive : in which case it would not properly deserve even the name of good fortune, for it is of the essence of good fortune that it should contribute to happiness : it is in accordance with this fact that its definition also is given to it, and consequently its name. Hence it would not properly be called good fortune if it did not contribute to happiness. All this makes it clear that the attribute ' unimpeded ' should be added to the word ' activity ' when applied to the happy man. But an unimpeded activity is in fact pleasure. Happiness is tha'efore a certain form of pleasure. (3.) PLBASUEE IS mSEPARABLE FROM THE CHIEF GOOD. Further, the fact that all creatures both beasts and men pursue pleasure is a proof that in some sense pleasure is the Chief Good. " Mankind's universal voice falleth not wholly vain." 41 6 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk, VII. 14 But since there is no one state of nature which either is or ii recognised to be the best for all, so neither dc ^eltol'"^ Ifter ^^'i ^^ P'^^s'i^ *^^ ®^™^ pleasure, though pleasnn pleasure shows they all pursuc. Nay, perhaps uuconsciouslj ittThT^Zatl tl^ey ^^« ^0* P^'-^'^i^g tlie Pleasui-e they thini object of striving, they are and say they are, but, in reality, all alike g^d *''^ *'^^ *^^ ^^™®' ^''^^^^ ^^ ^ ^™'^ °^ instinct which all creatures alike possess by right of nature — a divine instinct (which justifies an appeal to universal nature). Yet inasmuch as bodily pleasures are those to which men most frequently resort and in which all men share, they have usurped full possession of the name of pleasure : because they are the only pleasures men know of, they think that they are the only pleasures which exist. In conclusion, it is evident that, if pleasure and the play of the faculties be not a good, it will be impossible that the happy man should live a pleasurable existence. With what object would a happy man need pleasure, if pleasure be not a good and if it be possible to live happily in the midst of pain ? In fact, if pleasure be neither a good nor an evil, neither will pain be good nor evE : why, then, should a man shrink from pain ? Moreover, if the activities of the good man are not more pleasurable than that of the bad, neither will the life of the good man be more pleasurable than that of the bad. Further, the fact that animals and men and all beings possessed of sensation pursue pleasure makes it clear that pleasure is the Chief Good. For all agree in shouting out that pleasure is a good and the highest good, and all press on in the pursuit of it. An.d "Mankind's universal voice faUeth not wholly vain." It is true that they do not all pursue the highest form of pleasure ; for, in the same way, they do not all have the same mental state or the same nature : but pleasure they do all pursue, though the -form of it be only in some oases good, and in others bad. Nay perhaps none of them even pursue or seek for a bad form of pleasure or aim at anything that is bad : the actual object of their pur- suit and seeking is not that which they intend to seek, or would admit that they pursue : what all of them really pursue is the highest form of pleasure, for all things naturally aim at what is really good, since in all things there is a diVme element, and the impulse of all things is towards a form of pleasure which is good, and which is pleasurable in the proper sense of the term : though it may be admitted that the bodily pleasures seem to men to be pleasures in the proper sense of the term, on account of their constant exposure to them and also on account of all men participating in them. They are, in fact, not oognizant of any others, and consequently think these to be the only forms of pleasnrs which exist. And since these forms of pleasure are not good nor are pleasnresin the proper sense of the term, men (knowing no others) have denied that any form of pleasure is a ' good.' But it is incontrovertible that (some form of) pleasure is a good. For if pleasure, and the play of the faculties which is in harmony with pleasure, , be not a good, it is not possible for the happy man to Uve pleasurably. But Bk. Vir. 14.] Translation,. 417 sniely there ia no doubt that a happy man's ' life must be accompanied with pleasure. Consequently it ia impossible that pleasure should not be a good. A further argument to prove the same point from the same premifses is that nothing which is evil, or in fact vrhich is not in the proper sense good, can be an element in happiness. Why, then, if pleasure be not a good, does the happy man pursue it ?. And again, if pleasure be not either a good or an evil, pain will not be either a good or an evil : consequently it will not be a thing to be avoided. Why then does the happy man avoid it ? He would not avoid it unless it were an evil : but as a matter of fact he cannot .help avoiding it; It is necessary, in short, that the happy life should be the pleasantest life : but this is impossible unless the modes iji, which the activities of the happy man manifest themselves are pleasant : for if otherwise how will the pleasantness of his life be realized ? If, then, pleasure be not either positively evil or negatively not good, it foUows that it is good. V. — Refutation of the argument from bodily pleasures. (1.) BODILY PLEASUKBS AEE, IN CBETAm CONNECTIONS, GOOD. Now the subject of bodily pleasures is one especially incumbent on those thinkers to examine who maintain that though certain pleasures, i.e. noble pleasures, are are ' only eTirT' emphatically desirable in a high degree, yet tli«r abuse and bodily pleasures and such as those in which the ^^°®^^- dissolute man indulges, are evil. If this view of theirs be true, why are the pains which are the opposite of pleasures grievous and evil ? Good and evil are, of corase, opposites. May the solution be this : are not necessary pleasures good in the sense that whatever is not an evil is a good ? or, are these bodily pleasures good up to a certain point? In the case of mental habits and processes where there is no excess possible as they increase from more to more, there is no excess possible either, in the pleasure resulting therefrom. On the contrary, where excess is possible from the increase and enhancement ot those processes, there also there is excess possible in the pleasure which ensues. Consequently excess is possible in the pleasures of the body ; and the bad man is bad in that he seeks that excess instead of seeking such pleasures as are necessary. All men find pleasure of a certain kind in dainties and wines and love ; though not all observe the proper standard therein. The converse is true in- the case of pain. Men shrink not merely from the excess of pam but from pain in general : pain is not opposed to the mere excess of pleasure — except in the case of the [very sensitive and self-indulgent] man who. pursues- the excess [and makes every defection from his own extravagant standard a pain]. It is possible for anyone to raise the question why it is that if some pleasures are good and choioeworthy, and some on the other hand evil — as for example the / 4i8 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VII. 15. bodily pleasures with whioli the dissolute man is concerned — every form of pain is vicious and to be avoided. For it would be reasonable to suppose that although the pain which is opposed to good pleasures is evil, the pain which is opposed to evil pleasm-es should be good — evil and good being in the relation of opposites, If on the contrary this form of pain is evil, it would seem as though the bodil; pleasures were good. Our answer to this question is as foUows : Bodily pleasures are good in the sense of not being bad : for whatever is not bad is good. This is true up to a certain point. For if they do not exceed a certain limit they are in this sense good : consequently the pains that are opposed to them are not gooi, For, since some states of mind and body exceed the due limit and what is best, whereas other states of mind and body do not so exceed, the necessary states of body, such as the state of requiring nourishment, are capable of excess, since they can be exercised to a greater extent than they should properly be exercised; on the other hand those which when subjected to tension do not go beyond the due limit are not capable of excess, but are always good, as for example the states of mind which are engaged in philosophical investigation. But since pleasmea follow upon states of mind, it necessarily follows that some pleasures exceed 1^ due limit, and some do not. All those which exceed the limit are bad, and it is with them that the dissolute and the weak-minded man are concerned. In the case of pains which are opposed to pleasures, it is not with excesnve pains that the dissolute man concerns himself : he pursues no doubt excessive pleasnieai tat avoids even smaU pains. From this it is manifest that the pains which in, the case of the dissolute man are opposed to his excessive pleasures are not excessive but moderate pains — such as no good man would avoid, because they do not in fact deserve the name of pains. This is the solution of the question which was raised : the pains which aie opposed to moderate pleasures are not good : for moderate bodily pleaenres are good, inasmuch as they are not evil : the pains which are opposed to excessive pleasures are moderate pains, in fact not pains at all, and consequently not tcn,be avoided. Every form of good is contrary to that which is to be avoided : suxd bad pleasures are opposed to good pains, just as good pleasures are to pains which shoiild be avoided. (2.) CAUSES OP THE UNIVERSAL PURSUIT OF PLEASURE. However, we must not only give a true account : we must also Why do bodily ^^P^^i"^ *^^ cause of the error; a thorough exposi- pieaaures seem to tion being highly conducive to winning conviction. most men to be es- "When a probable reason has been shown why a pecially desirable. j.t. i «,.,,. theory has an appearance of truth without being true, such an explanation makes us have a greater confidence in the truth itself. Hence we must explain why it is that bodily pleasures haVe the appearance of being more choiceworthy than others. (1.) In the first place, of course, bodily pleasure drives out pain. In face of excessive pain, as though it IctL^theTe'Jdies ^^^® ^ remedy for it, men strive after a pleasure Dfpaini correspondingly excessive— in fact, after bodily pleasure. Now these remedies are found to be powerful} and hence they are adopted because they are regarded in contrast to their opposites. Bk. VII. 15.] Translation. 419 [It is on account of these two causes that pleasure is thought not to be a good : (a) i.e. some pleasures, as we ]jp,ve explained, are the actions of a depraved nature, whether congenital as in the case of beasts, or the result of habit as in the case of vicious characters ; (/3) other pleasures, again, are remedies, because they are the actions of an imperfect nature. But, as for remedial pleasures, it is better to have a normal condition than to be arriving at one: yet these remedial pleasures only take place whilst we are arriving at a state of completeness : hence they are only * pleasures ' in an indirect and secondary sense.] (2.) Again, these bodily pleasures are sought on account of their powerfiil effect only by those who have lost the capacity for taking pleasure in simpler and want^of°^pa(^ty in purer tastes. At any rate men have to create most men for men. artificial excitements so as to satisfy their ab- *^' ^•^^"'^^s- normal tastes. Of course, if these indulgences do not hurt their health their conduct is not censurable ; but if they are injurious, then their conduct is morally evil. Men only indulge them in fact because they have nothing else in which they can take pleasure, and ' a state of impassivity ' is to many men painful by the constitution of their nature. ' The whole creation struggleth even until now,' as the writings of natural philosophers tell us ... . adding in fact that even the act of seeing or of hearing is painful ; only in time we become habituated to the pain, which is second nature to us (so they say). The same truth is conspicuous in time of youth : owing to the processes of growth, boys are in a physical state resembling that of the intoxicated, and boyhood is sweet and pleasant. Again, people of a nervous temperament are ever in need of an anodyne : their bodies are in a state of constant irritation, owing to their temperament, and they are incessantly in a state of vehement desire. Now pleasure, be it the opposite of a given pain, or be it what it may, provided it be strong enough, drives away the irritation ; and hence it is that nervous people become dissolute and depraved. However, we must not only give a true account : we must also explain tte cause of the error ; a thorough, exposition being highly conducive to winning' conviction of the truth. For when the reason has been shown why it is that what is in reality false has an appearance of truth, and the cause of the error has been exposed, the explanation makes us have a greater confidence in the truth itself. Hence we must explain why it is that bodily pleasures have the appearance of being more ohoiceworthy than those which are really good. (1.) In the first place bodily pleasures are of the nature of remedies for bodily pains. The pains may be great, but the strehgth of the pleasures exceeds the Btrength o£ the pain, and drives it out. Cohsequently, at the titae when bodily r. Y.% 420 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bt VII. 15 pain presses upon a man, pleasures are sought after, because they seem to b( strong and powerful remedies, and easily rid a man of the pain which comei from defect of pleasure. The second reason is that bodily pleasures are soughi after by those who are incapable of taking delight in other forms of pleasure And these persons form a numerous class : and consequently that which ihej seek after is thought to be good and choiceworthy. They are not content witl the satisfaction of natural desires, but they go on to devise artificial excitements creating for themselves, for example an artificial thirst, in order that they maj be always capable of delighting themselves with drink. No doubt if this praotici does not go beyond the limits of reason and moderation, it is not injurious, foj bodily pleasures in moderation do not injure the body, and to that extent the practice of which I have spoken is not to be censured. But if the pleasnrei which are to be pursued do go beyond the limit, and the pursuit of them ininres the body, the pursuit of them is morally evU. I assert that the use of bodilj pleasures in moderation is not to be censured, because it is absolutely necessaig for a man to find some things pleasant in life, because his natm-e is in process ol struggle, and requires some kind of pleasure which will serve, so to speak, at a repose. For the whole creation is always in process of struggle, as in fact natural philosophers tell us : for they say that even the act of seeing or oi hearing is in reality painful, though through habituation it does not seemi so Men, therefore, need some kind of pleasure, and if a man is insensible tfli in- tellectual pleasures, he is compelled to enjoy himself with the pleasures of the body. It follows, that those who use them in moderation, and in such a way af not to injure their body are not morally censured. The same truth is conspicuous in time of youth : the pleasures which aocompanj the nutritive part of our nature, just as they are by the dissolute man, under an impulse of nature struggling after growth. Youths are, in fact, in an analogoril position to men who are under the influence of wine ; for eating, drinking, aii^ sleeping continually, as they do, they have the desire which is stimulated bythea operations in a constant state of extreme vigour, just as those with whom I haw compared them are under the constant influence of thirst. It is for this reasoi that the period of youth is pleasant because its realization of the necessary condi' tions of existence is always accompanied with desire. In just the same way persons of a nervous temperament are always in a statf of vehement desire, and are always in need of an anodyne : for their bodies an always in a state of irritation on account of their temperament. These, therefore, are persons who seek after bodily pleasures, and these are the reasons why they seek them. Speaking generally, every bodily pleasm-e is soughi for in order that it may expel a bodily pain : for pleasure drives out pain, nor ii it necessary that the particular form of pleasure should be the exact opposite o) the particular form of pain ; for example, a pain which arises in the nntritivt part of us, is driven out not only by a pleasure which has its seat in the nutritive part of us, but by any other form of pleasure as well, if only it be strong enough It is for this reason that bodily pleasures are pursued, and it is hence that mei become dissolute or bad. (3.) THE PLEASURES OF THE MIND, HOWEVER, ARE PREFERABLE TC THOSE OF THE BODY. On the other hand, pleasures unaccompanied by pain do nol admit of excess : they are the satisfaction and Mental pleasures realization of things which are pleasurable in excess.' *^""* their own nature and not through adventitious circumstances. By 'pleasures of association' I mean such things as are of the nature of a remedy. Since il Bk..VII. 15.] Translation. 421 happens that we are relieved, owing to some operation of that part in us which continues sound, the object [which causes this result] seems to us to be itself pleasant. On the %ontrary things are Tiaturally pleasant when they produce the activity of a nature corresponding to their own. But the same object is never continuously pleasant to us, because our nature is not simple, butj there are in it other and diverse elements (in virtue of our corruptible nature). Hence when one element is in action, it thwarts the tendency of the ,second element ; and when the two elements are balanced, the result of their action appears to be ^.either painful nor pleasant. However, if there be any being whose nature is uncompounded, the same mode of action will be continuously and in the highest degree pleasurable to him. Hence it is, through the simplicity of His essence, God enjoys everlastingly one pure pleasure. There is an activity assuredly not only in change but in changelessness ; and pleasure is keener in a state of calm than in a state of motion. It is only, as the poet says, ' through the frailty of our mortal nature that change is the sweetest of all things.' It is the frail and faulty character yhich is fond of change ; and the nature which needs change bears the same stamp of imperfection, being neither sincere nor true. We must here conclude our account of moral strength and weakness, and of pleasure and pain, having defined the nature of each respectively and the sense in which they are right or wrong, good or evil. It now remains for us to proceed with our examination of Friendship. On the otlier iand, intellectual pleasures are not preceded by pain (for it is not necessary for us, as in tte case of bodily pleasures, to feel paiu before feeling the delight which they bring), and do not admit of excess. It is not possible for us to give play to the intellect beyond what is fitting : the pleasures which flow from the play of the intellect are always praiseworthy, for the objects which cause those pleasures are pleasant not accidentally, but always and absolutely. By things which are accidentally pleasurable I mean those which satisfy and heal bodily wants and pains ; for example, articles of food. For food is, as it were, a remedy to the nature of a hungry man, which is, so to speak, in an abnormal and morbid state, and it supplies what is lacking : when, that is to say, the man's natui-e is not defective or morbid in respect of its capacity of receiving nutriment, but possesses that capa- city, and is sound in respect of it, and gives it play, that is to say, feels a desire for food. Things of this kind are pleasurable, not in themselves, but through ad- ventitious circumstances, that is, because they happen to serve as remedies. On the other hand, things are naturally pleasurable which instead of filling up a de- ficiency in a man's nature, stimulate that nature into activity. Of this kind are the objects upon which the inteUeot employs itself, for they allow a perfect play to the activity of the mind. But since our nature is not simple but eemplez, and siace we do not live with 422 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. 'VII. 15. our minds only apart from our bodies, the same objects are not always pleasurable to us ; since even in the case of those things which are accidentally pleasurable, the same things are not always objects of pursuit, but we seek at one time one class of objects, at another time another. For when our bent is in the direction of our body, we feel pleasure in those things which are connected with our body, but when, on the other hand, we look beyond our body, we seek things which are not accidentally, but naturally pleasurable, for there is a conflict between the pleasures of the mind and the pleasures of the body : and the objects in which the mind feels delight seem to the body to be contrary to nature. At the same time, when the exercise of virtue has brought the mind and body into unison, then, although it is still true that the body does not feel delight in the objects round which lie mind delights to play — for they are not objects of sense, still, it is not objects of pain. Hence it is that to those beings whose nature is absolutely simple, the same course of action is always absolutely pleasant. For God enjoys everlastingly one pure pleasure. It is true that he is changeless, and that he has been thought on this account to be incapable of pleasure, for pleasure is a mode of activity, and activity is thought to be only a mode ef change. But it is not so : there is an activity not only in change, but in ohangelessness, and pleasure is keener in a state of calm than in a state of changeful motion. Change is the sweetest of all things, as the poet says, not to an absolutely g*od and perfect nature, but to a com- posite nature, owing to its frailty and its wickedness : for just as a wicked man is constantly changing, so also a wicked nature is in constant need of change, it is neither simple nor sincere. We must here conclude our account of moral strength and weakness, and of pleasure and pain, having defined the nature of each respectively, and the sense in which they are right or wrong, good or evil. It remains for us to speak of friendship. BOOK VIII.-CONCEKNING- FBIENDSHIP. INTEODUCTOEY ANALYSIS. — *— I.-GENEEAL CONCEPTION OF FRIENDSHIP. The general subject of these two books (VIII. and IX.) is FriendsMp. The subject has many claims on' the moralist for his attention. It deserves consideration (1) on account of its intimate connection with virtue. Friendship in all its higher forms is impossible without virtue, and IB in its turn of the greatest assistance towards leading a virtuous and so a happy life. (2.) It befits every condition and every- age of life. Ricih and poor, old young and middle-aged are all on different grounds indebted to friend- ship. (3.) Friendship is a principle deeply rooted in human nature ; not to speak of the natural affection subsisting between parent and child and even among animals towards those of their own kind, man has a natural attraction to man as man. We may see this in the way in which men casually thrown together make friends with one another, and even strangers are made welcome. (4.) As ' social philosophers ' we are Especially bound to consider it ; it is the chief tie that binds civil society together and is even more absolutely indispensable to its well-being than justice is, while (5.) The possession of friends is ' a crown of glory ' to a man, a distinc- tive addition to virtue itself. Yet as to the nature and origin of the sentiment there are a variety of differing, and even diametrically opposed, opinions. 1. Some Philosophers take the view that 'like is attracted by like.' 2. Others maintain that it is dissimilar natures that have affinities. Both alike trace the prevalence of one or other of these principles through the whole of nature. 3. Into these wider questions it is beyond our present purpose to enter. As moralists, we approach the question only from the moral side, and would confine our attention to such questions as these. What is the relation of friendship to virtue and to happiness? Are there different kinds of friendship, friendships which the vicious man may share as well as the virtuous, or in friendship the privilege of the virtuous alone ? 424 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. II.— ARE THERE DIFFERENT KINDS OF FRIENDSHIP! Let lis attempt to answer this last question first and consider — ' Are there different kinds of friendship, and if so how many they are,' In order to answer it, it will be necessary to analyse the grounds on which affection, and with it friendship, may rest. What are the objects of affection ? Now that which excites affection is always either the good, . or the agreeable or the useful. We love persons, or things, because they, are good, or pleasant or useful to us. But the useful,, if we consider what it really means, is that which conduces to our good, or conduces to our pleasure. Consequently goodness and pleasantness are the only ultimate grounds of affection, and, therefore, of friendship. (We may notice further that, though ideally it may be the truly good and the really pleasant which excite and command our affection, yet practically the feeling will be evoked in each individual by that which impresses him as good or as pleasant.) Yet mere affection for a person or an object, prompted by one or other of these motives does not, taken by itself alone, constitute friend- ship. If it did, we might be said to be friends with our wine, or with any other inanimate object which gives us gratification or amusement. Three other conditions have to be complied with before the idea of friendship can be regarded as complete. 1. The affection felt must be unselfish; it must be a genuine wish for the good of the person, or the object, loved. 2. The feeling must be reciprocated by the object towards which it is felt, and 3. Their mutual affection must not be unknown to the two parties concerned. ^ We are now in a position to answer the question with which we started, whether there are different Knds of friendship, and to answer it in the affirmative. Since the three objects of affection above enumerated are distinct in kind, and since an unselfish feeling of afiection, recipro- cated by, and not unknown to, the object of it, may arise on any one of ■ these grounds, it follows that there are three distinct kinds of friendship, corresponding to these three different objects of affection ; friendships that is, based upon goodness, friendships based upon pleasure, and ' friendships based upon interest. III.— THE THREE KINDS OF FRIENDSHIP CONTRASTED AND COMPARED. Of these three forms of friendship, the two which originate severally in interest and in pleasure, depend dot so much on the intrinsic character of the contracting parties as upon circumstances which are more or less accidental, and consequently the friendships have themselves something of an accidental character. This same fact renders them also hable to speedy dissolution, as interest and pleasure quickly change. These different kinds of friendship do not prevail equally among all classes. The old and the more mercenary of the young and the middle- aged form friendships of interest, while the young form friendships Introductory Analysis: Book VIII. 425 chiefly from delight in one another's society j but the changeableness of youth; and the uncertainty of pleasure, make s\ich frien^hips often only of short duration. 3Vje only 'perfect form of friendship is the friendship of the good, and it can alone be regarded as true and real friendship. (1) It is unselfish, and this gives it a true element of friendliness in which the other forms are wanting. (2) Being based on a mutual respect between the friends for each other's character, it is not affected by any external or accidental considerations. (3) It contains in itself the advantages of both the other kinds, as the good are both pleasant and profitable to one another. (4) It is lasting, for it has its roots in virtue and virtue wears well ; while (5) we have here that similarity of disposition which is essential to friendship. Of course such friendships are rare. Perfectly good men are scarce, and time and intimacy are requisite to bring friendship, in this its highest and completest form, to perfection. The two other forms are enduring, and approach the ideal form in varying degrees. 1. Of the imperfect forms that is most lasting, in which each of the friends is agreeable to the other and on the same grounds. Two wits, for instance, may often strike up a lasting friendship. But 2. Where, as in the case of lovers, the advantage sought is not of the same kind, but one seeks gratification, the other profit, the connexion is apt to be transitory, ceasing as the bloom of youth dies away and atten- tions cease to be paid as of old ; though of course cases occur in which love ripens into lasting friendship, if the lovers come mutually to esteem each other's characters. 3. Those friendships are least real, and least lasting, which are dictated by merely mercenary motives. 4. One other point in which all such friendships fall short of the ideal of true friendship is their liability to be destroyed by the breath of slander ; true friends, who have really proved one another, are superior to all its assaults. In all these respects, then, does true friendship transcend these its imperfect copies; yet since populai- usage extends the name of friendship also to them, we will follow it in this particular and speak of three kinds of friendship, one that true and ideal friendship which is confined to the good, the other two kinds shared by bad and good alike, being called friendships at all only by a kind of analogy or metaphor. If we turn next to consider the conditions which give vitality or reality to friendship, they seem to be summed up in these three. (1.) Constant intercourse and delight on the part of the friends in one another's society. (2.) A certain pleasantness and pliability of temper which makes such constant intercourse possible and delightful. (3.) A certain fixity of character and determination to do good to one's friend, which distinguishes true friendship from any passing afiection. Lastly, if we ask 42 & Ihe MoraC Philosophy of Aristotle. IV,— WHAT ARE THE LIMITS OF FRIENDSHIP? We shall observe 1. That the morose and the elderly, from hardness of character, seldom can make friends. 2. That ideal friendship being, like love, a highly-exalted state of feeling can be entertained only towards few at a time, all the more because it requires time and intimacy to mature it, 3. That friendships of interest and pleasure may be formed with a wide circle of friends. 4. That the powerful require many friends and friends of different kinds, but cannot often command the friendship of the good .except in those rare instances, where by reason of their superior excellence the good can repay their favours in honour without loss of self-respect. Thus, then, the results we have arrived at are the following: (1) that all forms of friendship imply equality, either an actual return of like for like, honour for honour, pleasure for pleasure, profit for profit ; or, if not that (stiU) an equivalent amount in some other kind, and (2) that the friendship of the good is the only ideal type, and that the two other forms are regarded as friendships only in virtue of their resemblance to this : but (3) friendships are formed as a matter of fact, not merely between equals but between men diifering widely in position, virtue, wealth, &c. With respect to these friendships of relative superiority and inferiority the following principles applicable to all their different cases may be laid down. 1. What each of the friends will, and should, look for in the other, is not an exact repayment of his own services but a different kind of service. 2. The payment should be based on principles of proportion rather than of strict equality, the greater service being repaid by more honour. 3. Such friendships cannot extend beyond a certain limit ; when one of the two parties is altogether in a different position from the other, friendship is no longer possible. Friendship herein differs from justice. In justice it does not matter how widely removed in station the two parties involved are ; justice can still be done between them ; all that we have to look to is their respective merits ; but in friendship a certain equality between the two parties is necessary. The very idea of friend- ship between those very widely removed in position is preposterous. Man does not claim to be the friend of God, nor a common man to be friends with princes. This fact furnishes a limit to the good wishes we can entertain for our friends. We cannot be absolutely unselfish in our good wishes ; we cannot wish them such advancement as wiU make them cease to he our friends, nor can we desire that their happiness should interfere with our own. v.— WHAT ARE THE MOTIVES IN WHICH FRIENDSHIP ORIGINATES? 1. Though the majority are more anxious to receive than to give affection, such a desire, like that of honour though in a less degi-ee, has Introductory Analysis: Book VII I. 427 always a certain element of selfisliness and self-seeking about it. In its nobler forms friendship consists more in loving than in being loved, as we see preeminently in the case of a mother's love for h# offspring, when any requital of the affection is often not even asked for. Consequently the outpouring of love must be regarded as more proper to, more charac- teristic of, true friendship than the being loved. 2. Friendships most frequently originate in a similarity of tastes and tharacter. This is seen most conspicuously in the case of the good who are drawn together by sympathy and a respect for one another's character. 3. Where there is not this similarity of character, the friendship is generally prompted by interest, a desire on the part of each to make good some deficiency in himself. In these cases it may well be that the Opposite does not really desire its opposite, but desires that balanced condition which is, as we have already seen, the true nature of ' the good.' VL— THE RELATION OF FRIENDSHIP AND JUSTICE. Justice and friendship have much in common ; they prevail for the most part between the same individuals, and find a place in the same transactions. Wherever two people are associated for any purpose, they wiE be found, as a rule, united by ties both of justice and of friendship, and the closer the tie uniting them, the more intimate will be the friend- ship, the more imperative the claims of justice. Furthermore, inasmuch as every form of association is entered into with a view to secure some particular advantage, while the political union was originally formed, and still continues to exist, with a view of promoting the well-being of man as a whole, consequently every special association may be regarded as subordinate to, and forming a part of ' that political \mion ' whose end thus comprises and includes the ends of them alL This is true even of those associations which are formed merely for purposes of pleasure and enjoyment. Pleasure and enjoyment and relaxation from toil are constituents of well-being, and so cannot be regarded as lying outside the scope of the aU-embracing political union. But the political union may itself take many forms of which the chief are these, kingly government, aristocracy, and timocracy. Each of these has its corresponding ' perversion ' or distorted form, tyranny being the perversion of kingly rule, oligarchy of aristocracy, democracy of timo- cracy. The perverted forms differ from the legitimate forms, in that in the former the governors aim at their own selfish ends, in the latter at the public good. Of the legitimate forms kingly rule — where the king looks solely to the interests of his subjects — is the best, timocracy the least good ; while in the perverted forms tyranny is the worst, democracy the least evil. It should further be noticed, that each of the three forms of government is apt to degenerate into its own allied perverted form. Human selfishness is for ever creeping in and perverting governments from their true ideal. Eelations corresponding to these different forms of government are to be met with in the household as well. Kingly rule is, or should be re- presented by a father's ' paternal rule.' Tyranny finds its counterpart in the harsh authority of ' Persian ' fathers, and, more legitimately, in the authority exercised by a master over bis slaves. 428 The Moral Philosophy, of Aristotle. Husband and wife — ^where the husband rules in virtue of his superioi merits, and assigns to the wife her proper sphere and duties — are on thi footing of an aristocracy and its subjects. If the husband interferei beyond his proper sphere, or where the wife, as having possession of the purse-strings, gets the upper hand, their relation degenerates intc oligarchy. Brothers again are on that footing of equality, which is the charac- teristic note of ' timocracy ; ' while in masterless houses, or when the father is weak, we see rampant the evils of democracy, in which each does that which is right in his own eyes. Now in state and household alike friendship is only possible, where the rights of all concerned are duly respected. Friendship between lulei and snlgeot, between father and child, will be found, only where .the rights and interests of each are properly respected by the other. Un- selfish care on the one side must be answered by due deference on tG other. In an aristocracy and in the case of husband and wife friendship will rest on a due recognition, on the part of the governed and of the wife, of superior merit in the ruling class and the husband respectively. The members of a ' timocracy,' like brothers in a household, are equals ; and their friendship will depend, accordingly, on the recognition by each of the others' equal right. On the other hand between a tyrant and his oppressed subjects, be- tween a master and his slaves there is no real community of interest and consequently no friendship, or scarcely any friendship. If a master feels friendship at all for his slave, it is, not as a slave, but, as a man that he loves him, and because he recognises in him the rights of a common humanity. The members of a democracy have many interests in common, and friendship is, therefore, of frequent occurrence between them. VII.— FAMILY AFFECTION. Family affection may be regarded as something distinct from all other forms of friendship. In all its different forms, it rests not on community of interests, but has its roots in a natural instinct or feeling. (1.) The love of parent for child is natural, for the child is almost a part of the parent's self, and the parent cannot fail to recognise the share it had in giving its child being. (2.) Brotherly love is a natural instinct, derived from the community of blood acting as an element common to both, uniting brothers together by a chord of sympathy. This natui-al feeling is further enhance4 tiy common bringing lap, similarity of age and common education. Cousins and more distant relatives are drawn together in the same way, but to a more limited extent, till the relationship fades away into nothing. (3.) The love of children for their parents rests on a sense of benefits received, while brothers are bound to one another, not merely by that community of blood, which we have above described, but also, by similar dispositions, close intimacy and a common education ; so that the ' love of brothers ' transcends every other form of friendship. (4.) Lastly nature also dictates the love of husband and wife ; it is Introductory Analysis : Book VIII. 429 more natural to man to live in pairs, even than in civil society. This is an instinct indeed that he shares with the animals ; but, while with them, the union continues only so long as is necessity for the rear- ing of offspring, man and wife find in it a means of enhancing the value of life by the supply of their mutual needs. This love, which has thus its roots in nature, is further increased by the possession of common children. VIII.— THE EIGHTS AND DUTIES OF FRIENDS. Having now settled what friendship is, what its different species are, what are ■ the conditions necessary to give it reality and what is its relation to justice, our next enquiry will be what are the rights and the duties of friends. Now the golden rule in friendship of whatever kind is that 'Equals should make one another equal returns, Unequals returns proportionate to the superiority. of the one side.' ,? iraotically, however, the question of the rights and duties of friends aa well as the heartburnings to which such questions giye rise, occur in respect of one only of the three species of friendship above distinguished, in that, namely, which originates in interest. Such questions can never arise between those who are bent on virtue, since each will exhibit a noble rivalry to do his friend every good that lies in his power. And those who seek one another's society on grounds of pleasure can always withdraw, if they cease to find their friend's society any longer attractive. (a). But in friendships, which rest on interest, such questions do very often occur, as in this case each is sure to get less than he wants, and less, consequently, than he considers he has a right to have. For in matters of interest, men are apt to make their wants the measure of their rights. Of these interested friendships, if we may so style them, there are two different kinds : (1.) Those in which the whole transaction is purely business-lilie and commercial where a stipulated service is rendered for a stipulated price or reward. But in respect of this we must again distinguish two dif- ferent cases, (a) that in which the return is made on the spot, as in trans- actions in the market ; (b) the second that, where delay is allowed in .the repayment, the article being given on trust, the amount of the re- pajrment to be made being still stipulated. This latter case has more the character of friendliness, and is less purely business-like than the former. (2.) The second kind admits certain moral considerations. For in this no precise stipulation is made as to the amoimt to be repaid, but the gift is given, or the service whatever it may be, is rendered, as to a friend. Still even here the benefactor will expect to get back as much as he has given, and will grumble, if he does not do so. Men wish indeed to realise a noble ideal, and so to give without hope of recom- pense or return, but when it comes to the point, they cannot help blroosing to get back an equivalent for what they have given and to nave their services repaid. And so the rules, which will regulate our conduct in these cases, will be these : 430 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. 1. Presume as little as possible on the friendly intentions of those who confer a favour. 2. Make repayment in full, wherever this is possible ; if it is impoa sible, your benefactor himself will not require it of you. 3. Make enquiries at the outset as to the terms on which the favom is bestowed, and so settle whether to receive it or no. There still arises the question, what are we to take as the measure of the repayment which should be made? Is it to be estimated by the good done to the recipient or by the benefit intended by the benefactor 1 On the one hand the recipient is always inclined to make light of the cost of the service rendered him, on the other, the author of the favour inclines to magnify it. In friendships of interest the return to be made should clearly be measured by the amount of the benefit received, since the author of it confers the benefit in the hopes of getting back as much as he actually gives. In an ideal friendship no disputes of the kind occur, but there the amount to be returned will rather be measured by the benefactor's intention than by the amount actually received ; since it is the benefactor's intention which gives its value and character to his act. (b.) Besides these friendships of interest, a second case in which disputes occur is where the two friends are in positions of relative superiority and inferiority. In these both claim, though on difierent grounds, to reap the larger harvest from the transaction. The superior thinks that his superior merits entitle him to a larger return, the inferior that his greater needs entitle him to greater consideration. . Both in a way are right ; the superior is entitled to a greater share of honour, the inferior is entitled to a greater share, a greater amount, of help. (That honour is the proper return for services gratuitously rendered may be seen from the instance of public men. They get honour only in those cases where they give their services to their country gratuitously.) Of course here again the repayment which will have to be made will have to be limited by the power of the recipient to make it. So a father has always a claim on his son for his services, since the son can never adequately and completely repay the services and the benefits he has received ; but the son has no corresponding claim on the father, since he remains always in his father's debt. A father has, therefore, a right to repudiate his son, but not the son his father. Still the father is scarcely likely, unless the son is very bad indeed, to exercise his right, as, independently of natural affection, he would be discarding thereby his best hope of assistance and protection for his old age. TEANSLATION. ,f, L— GENERAL CONCEPTION OF FEIENDSHIP. 1.— Connection of Friendship with the theory of Morals. The sutject whicli follows next in order for us to discuss is Friendship, for friendship is either a special vir- tue, or, at any rate, implies virtue as a constitu- i- Friendship is J. ■ 1 , • •. i/> either a virtue or tive element m itseli. impiies.it. Friendship is besides most essential to a com- plete career. Without friends no one would care to live, even though he had all other goods except them ; ,,1.1 J , 1 . ... n 2. Friends are in- to the rich, and to such as are in positions oi dispensable alike authority and high place, friends are in a special \^ prosperity and way indispensable. For what profit is there in '" ^^^^ ^' external advantages of this sort, if one has not the opportunity of doing good with them ? and it is to friends that the doing of good is at once most natural and most excellent. Again how could such external prosperity be maintained, or kept secure in the absence of friends ? In proportion to its greatness the more liable is it to accidents. In poverty, moreover, and all other mis- fortunes men think that their friends are their only sure refuge. To the young friends are a help to keep them free from errors ; to the old for the tendance they give and for supplying the lack of power to act which comes i" yitt, in age of weakness ; to those in their prime to promote ofUfe." *""' ^"""^ noble deeds. " And two going together (are better}." Two together are more capable of seeing what should be done, and of doing it. And nature too seems to implant affection in the parent to its " offspring, not in men only, but in birds and in most other animals as well, and in those of the 3. Nature implants _ . , 1,1 1 , (. friendly feelings m Bame species one towards another, and most of animals, even, to 432 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 1, those of their own all in men to men, so that we use the term kind, most of man to man. kind, most of all in < philanthropic,' or lovers of men, as a term of praise. One can see too on one's travels how every man is akin to and a friend with every other man. Moreover, friendship between the citizens is, it would seem, , ^ . , , . . the bond that holds states together : and leo-is- 4. Friendship is , , . , . i n . °,7: the great bond that lators are more anxious to promote such friendh- hoids states toge- ness eveu than to promote justice. For unani- mity is very much akin to friendship, and thus it is that legislators are most anxious to secure and to expel civil discord, which is a form of enmity. When men are friends jus- tice may be dispensed with, but men may be just and still require friendship in addition. And justice in its highest and most perfect form wears a character of friendliness. Friendship is not only indispensable, it^'is honourable also ; we speak with approbation of those who have many And 5. It is ho- friends ; and a ' wide circle of friends ' is thouffht nourable and con- , , , .,, /■ i , r-i , fers distinction. to DC a title 01 houour to a man. Some too there are who hold that it is the same individuals that make good men that make good friends. It wUl devolve on us to discuss next in order the question of friendship. For friendship is either a special virtue or a consequence of virtue. The virtue which falls intermediate between offensivenesa and obsequiousness if combined with affection, is friendship, as has been already stated in the Sixth Chapter of the Fourth Book. Friendship is also a consequent of complete virtue. For true friendship, as will be shown hereafter, will be found only between the good. Hence in our treatise on the virtues it will be quite relevant to discuss friendi ship also ; all the more because it is besides most indispensable to a complete career. Without friends no one would care to live, though he had all other possible blessings, since eveu the wealthy, endowed with office and high place, seem in a special manner to have need of friends. For what profit is there in all this worldly prosperity if they are not able to do good offices 1 And they cannot do good offices, if they have no friends. For the good offices, which are highest and most praised, are done to.f riends. Again how can a prosperous man continue and be kept safe in his prosperity without friends ? And in proportion as his prosperity is greater, the more is it exposed to risks. Not only have the prosperous need of friends but the unfortunate and poor at well, for all think that friends are their only haven of refuge. Again not only is friendship profitable to every variety of fortune but in every variety of age also. The young, friends lead into the paths of light reason, that they may not go astray through their inexperience of the good ; the old they tend, and make good their lack of power to act which comes of the weakness that age brings ; for those in the prime of life they add to their noble deeds, and make their works more excellent ; they are " Two going in company ; '' for hy the help of friends we become more capable of framing plans and carrying them out. And it is by nature too that friendship comes to us. It is nature that makes the parent to feel friendly to its offspring, and that not among men alone, but among birds as well, and most animals; moreover, not only does this hold Bk. VIII. 2.] Translation. 43 3 hetween parent and offspring', bnt also between those of the same kind one to another, and most of all between man and man : on these grounds we praise also those who are ' philanthropic,' as doing that which is natural *> man. And one can see too on one's travels how aJdn man is to man and friendly to boot ; those who stay at home entertain and tend with pleasure the traveller ; and the traveller, if only he falls in with his f eUowmen, has his heart g-laddened within him. Political communities also in the first instance grew out of friendship, and are still held together by it. Legislators, who form such communities, talce more thought to secure friendship even than justice : it is for the sake of unanimity that justice is desired, and unanimity is something like friendship, while party faction is like enmity, and it is this that legislators are ever anxious to banish from their states. Besides this, if the citizens are friends with one another there is no need for justice, but though they are just, the state still requires friendship. By its help they will be made more unanimous than by the help of justice. Farther, justice carried to its highest pitch seems to merge in friendship ; for, when a man observes all the claims of justice to his neighbour, even to the extent of punishing him, if it be necessary for him to be punished, he is aBooimted his friend. Hence friendship is even more sought after than justice by legislators, while it is necessary also to any genuine unanimity. Jirther, not only is friendship necessary, and conducive to other good besides itsSf , but it is itself also in itself noble and praiseworthy ; we praise those who are attached to their friends, and ' a wide circle of friends ' is thought to be also a distinction. Some besides maintain that there is no distinction between a good man and a good friend, but that they are absolutely identical. ii.— Eeview of conflicting opinions as to tlie origin and nature of Friendship. But not a few diametrically opposite opinions are held about it. Some make it consist in likeness, and maintain ^ „. ,. ,, , ,. mi • /. 1 Conflictmg views. that the like are friends. This fadt they say has j y^^ jg friend given rise to such proverbs as ' Like loves like,' to like. 'Birds of a feather flock together ' and so on, ^ho Ire friendf''' Others from an opposite point of view assert that 3. Views extended all sunilar characters are like ' two of a trade ' to *" ^ "^t^^- oneanother. And they push their researches on these points still further back and with a more philosophical analysis {^vaiKWipov), Euripides for instance saying " The parched earth yearns to the shower," and " The stately heaven charged with rain Yearns to fall upon the earth, " and Heracleitus ' the opposing conduces,' and ' from things that differ is the fairest harmony,' and ' all things come to the birth through strife.' At an opposite standpoint to these are such writers as Empe- docles ; ' like yearns to like,' he says. _ Such then is friendship, but not a few questions are raised concerning it. It >? asked whether likeness is friendship and it is the like who are friends, or 434 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 2. whether it is unlikenesa and it is the tmlike who make friends. Some make it consist in likeness and make the like friends, and this, they say, is the origin of such proverbs as ' Like to like,' ' Birds of a feather ' and so on, while others main- tain tiiat it is opposite characters that make friends, and carry up their argument into a wider and more philosophical region, Euripides maiutainiug that " The parched earth loves the shower ; The stately heaven charged with raia '-'% Loves to fall upon the earth," and Heracleitus too saying that ' the opposed conduces,' ' from things that differ is the fairest harmony ' and that ' all things come to the birth through strife.' From an opposite standpoint to these Empedocles, and many others with him, maintain respecting friendship that it is like that yearns to like. iii. — Iiimitation of these enquiries to 'moral' subjects. However the naturalistic aspects of these discussions may be dismissed as being alien to the scope of the tereBtSd\rt^e inquiry we have before us. Let us rather investi- morai aspects of gate the human aspect of these questions and suchtSonVj" such as reach up into character and human (1.) Is friendship emotion — such questions, I mean, as whether confined to the friendship originates in all minds or whether it, (2.) Are there dif- is impossible for men, while they are evil, to W' ferent k™da of friends, and again whether there is but one kind of friendship or more than one. (Those who restrict friendship to a single kind., because it admits of degreelpf more and less, have rested their belief on an insufficient proof. Things which are even different in kind still admit of degrees of more and less. But we have already stated our views on this subject.) But to carry up our discussion into such general and physical considerationfl, and to enquiie generally, how contraries yearn for their contraries and hke things for their likes, is not germane to our present investigation. Rather let us restrict our enquiries to those points which touch on the nature of man, that relate to character and emotions ; these are the proper subject- matter for our present treatise. We must ask then whether friendship originates in all men or is confined to the good, while it can find no place between the evU; and whether there are many Mnds of friendship or one only. It does not follow, that because friendship admits of degrees of more and less, that, therefore, there is but one kind of it : for things which even differ in kind admit of degrees of more and less ; substance for instance and accident, though they differ in kind, admit of degrees of more and less, the one is more existent than the other ; so that those who, because it admits of degrees of more and less, think that there is but one kind of friendship, have grounded their belief on an insufficient proof. But on these points we have stated our views in earlier Books. Bk. VIII. 2.] Translation. 435 II.— THE GROUND OF FRIENDSHIP. i. — De amabili (to (fiiKrjTov) : The object of a£fection. Perhaps, light will be thrown on this point, if we discover the object of affection. It is held that not everything b" t f ff is the object of affection, but that there is a tion is the good, specific quality in objects which inspires affection, ti^e pleasant, or and this is the good, the pleasant or the useful. A thing would seem to be useful when by means of it some eood or pleasure is called into existence ; conse- ™ . , ^ . , . , ° . \ , T . i. _rv i- 11 ™^ '*^* 'S desired quenuy the only objects 01 anection regarded as as a means not as ends, are the good or the pleasant. ^° ^°<^- Do, then, men love the good or that which is good for them ? "lometimes these two are at variance. The same question applies to the pleasant also. Now each ^^'^ *^« apparent A. XX X Tfl T n PT* "Ml f) T1 "f" Tip TPfil is thought to love what is good for his own self good and pleasant and, though in an ideal sense, it is the good ^iiich in indivi- 1 • 1 ■ ii 1 • J. j> ii? i.- J. J- 1 • J- dual cases is the which is the object of affection, yet tor each mdi- object of affection. vidual that is the object of affection which is good to him. And each loves, not that which is good for him, but, that which impresses him as such. Still this will make no difference, as the object of his affection will be also an apparent not a real object. ' Such, then, are the questions raised, hut they will be cleared up if the concep- tion'of the object of affection be made plain. It is not all things that we love but only such as are fitted by nature to be loved, being such as are loveable. Now the three objects which excite affection are the good, the pleasant, and the naefnl. Of these the good and the pleasant are loved for their own sake, while the useful is loved for the sake either of goodness or of pleasure. That is useful by means of which either goodness is brought about or pleasure, the eoBsequence of which is that while the good and pleasure are loved as ends, the useful is only loved as conducing to ends. Next let us investigate in what way the good is the object of affection : is it the absolute good that is loved or that which is good for him who feels the affection 1 These sometimes differ from one another, and that which is truly and properly a man's good may be quite one thing, what he may hold to be his good tpiite another ; similarly the ideally pleasant may differ from that which seems pleasant to this or that individual. Which of the two then is the object of affection? Is it not clearly that which they thinJi good and t/dnJd pleasant? Similaily useful things, that excite affection, are those that conduce to what lemts pleasant and seems good. Moreover it is not all things that seem pleasant and that seem good that excite there affection, but those that seem pleasant and Beem good to the people concerned. ii. — Other conditions 1)881(168 affection necessary to friendship. There being thus these three grounds of affection, the term friendship is not applied to the affection felt for inanimate p p 2 436 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 2. objects, as there is in this case no requital of affection nor wish for the good of such objects : it would be ridicu- The affection based j^^g £qj, instance to wish all happiness to wine : on one of these • i a. n -^ ■ grounds must be if we have any Wish at all, it is merely a wish ^''fdTiwnselBsh *'^**' ^'^ ^^°® °^^^ ^® ^^P*' ^^^® *^^* ^® ^^^ °"'^" ca e , unse s , ^^^^^ \^v& the enjoyment of it : but in the case of a friend men say we ought to wish him all happiness for his own sake. Those who wish good in this spirit we call well dis- posed, where the feeling is not reciprocated by the object of it — where the feeling is reciprocated, the kindly disposition be- comes at length friendship. Perhaps we should further add that it must not be unknown to the object of it, for thl^bj^cf"''"™*'' °^^^y '^'^^'^ ^ kindly feeling for those whom they have never seen, that is to say if they believe them to be good or serviceable, and this same feeling might be entertained in turn towards them by the objects of it, and thus the two would be kindly disposed to one another. But how could , they be called friends if they severally did not know of their feelings towards one another ? For men, then, to be friends it is needful that they entertain kindly feelings to one another, that they wish for "™" ■ each other's good and be known to do so, and that on one or other of the grounds above enumerated. There being thus three gromids of liking on account of one or other of whioh affection is felt, it does not follow in the case of all things that are liked,that friendship is felt towards them : for we like BTen inanimate objects on one of these three grounds ; but such a feeling does not amount to friendship. Friend- ship exists when the affection is reciprocated, and a man wishes all happiness to the object of his love, whUe that object in turn wishes it to him ; but he who loves, let us suppose, wine is neither loved in return by the wine, nor wishes all happiness to it, as it would be ridiculous to do so ; if he has any wish with respect to it, he wishes it to be kept safe, but that not for the sake of the wine but for his own that he may have the enjoyment of it ; to a friend on the other hand we wish all happiness for his sake. Consequently the affection felt for inanimate objects is not friendship. i Again, though a man love another man and wish him good, such a feeling may still' not amount to friendship ; his love must be returned in an equal degree ; if not, he is not a friend, but is spoken of as well disposed to the other. i It may moreover happen that some from a mutual belief in one another's good- ness, or serviceableness, or excellence, may even wish all happiness to one another and not know they do so. In this case we should not call Hhiira. frwnds in the proper sense, because they don't know that they are loved, nor how they are dis- posed to one another : we should rather call them well affected to one another. Thus, then, neither is the affection for inanimate objects friendship nor the affection of men for one another, when it lacks any of fie above conditions. But friendship does exist when men feel kindly to one another on the score of good- ness, pleasure or profit, and wish for each other's good, and each knows of the other's love. Bk. VIII. 3.] Translation. 437 III.— THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF FRIENDSHIP AND THEIR COMPARATIVE VALUE.* i. — Friendships differ in kind according to the grounds of the Affection. These grounds differ from one another in kind, consequently must the affections to which they give rise, and the friendships as well. Hence the kinds of ^«y« ^« *^=^«5 . . , , . ,1 1 ■ 1 i ii distinct kinds of friendship are three, equal m number to the friendship corre- obiects of affection : for on each ground there sponding to the ■* , ™ ,. J -i. 1 j; -i J. three grounds of may be anection, and a requital 01 it, not un- affection, known to those concerned. What then friendship is has been now explained. It is clear also from what we hare stated that there are three Tmnds of friendship. For since there are three grounds on which friendship originates, the pleasant, the good, and the useful, and these differ from one another in kind, the friendships must be equal ^ number to the objects of affection. For in virtue of each one of these separate grounds a friendship may originate, that is to say, an affection known to the object of it and a requital of that affection. Further also an unselfish wish f or each other's good ; for iu so far as' we love anything we wish good to that thing. There are, therefore, three kinds of friendship, corresponding to the good, the pleasant, and the serviceable. ii. — Imperfection of Friendships of Pleasure and Interest. Those who love one another wish good to one another in the way that corresponds to the character of their affection. Those who love one another on grounds Friendships for n „, 1 , , J.1 • 1 ^ 1 J. Pi^ofit and pleasure 01 profit, do not love one another in and tor what are (i) selfish, (2) they are, but only in so far as each gets some accidental in cha- advantage from the other. The same is the case brokeh off. ^^ ^ with those who love each other on the ground of pleasure. The witty are loved, not for their intrinsic character, but, because they are pleasant to their audience. So, then, both those who love on grounds of profit, feel affection on grounds of their own selfish good, and those who love on grounds of pleasure, on grounds of their own selfish pleasure, and they value their friend, not for what he is, but for his serviceableness or agreeableness ; consequently also these friendships are accidental in character, for the person loved is not loved according to what he is in himself, but according as those who profess to love him get in the one case good from him, in the other pleasure. . Another consequence is that friendships of this sort are easilj' broken off if the position of the parties alters ; for if such friends are no longer pleasant or profitable to their friends, they cease to 438 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 3. care for them. Interest is never permanent, but alters with alter- ing circumstances. When the object, then, of their friendship disappears, the friendship vanishes along with it, such friendship being strictly relative to the object. We must next enquire into each kind. Those, then, who love one another on grounds of interest, love each other not for vrhat they are in themselves but for the sake of the good or the pleasure which they are the instruments of providing, and they love each other only so long as they severally get some advantage from the other ; similarly those who love one another on grounds of pleasure do not love each other for their intrinsic worth. They love one another, not because they are respectively pleasant in the abstract, but because each finds the other pleasant to himself, for it would advance the friendship nothing if it was to others they were pleasant. Consequently both those who love for profit's sake, and those who love for pleasure's sake, feel affection not on account of goodnes; or pleasure absolutely, nor do they love the object of their friendship, !Kr and in what he is in himself, but only because he is pleasant or profitable' to them. It is clear, therefore, that friendships such as these are accidental in character : the person loved is not loved, because he is what he is, but because he furnishes in the one case profit, in the other entertainment. And such friendships are easily broken off : the agreeable, and the profitable, do not continue agreeable and profitable for ever ; we take pleasure at one time in one set of persons, at another in another, and our interest varies at varying times. Since, then, the cause of the friendship is not permanent, the friendship proceeding from it is not permanent either, but is broken off, as being strictly relative to these objects and having them for its ends. iii. — The sphere of the tw^o inferior forms of Friendship determined. It is amongst the elderly that friendships of interest are ob- served most frequently to prevail, since the old tersest prevail* most make not pleasure but profit the object of their among the old and pursuit, and among those in the prime of life, e mercenary. ^^^ ^^ young who havo an eye to the main chance. Men of this stamp do not in all cases even care to live in one another's society. Sometimes they are not agreeable to one another, and, consequently, do not feel the need for this sort of intercourse, unless there is profit to be got out of it : for they are agreeable to one another only just so far as they entertain hopes of gain from the other. Hereditary friendships are probably to be classed under this head. The friendship of the young on the contrary is ordinarily based upon pleasure. The young live under the rule of Friendships of plea- their passions, and for the most part take for the young.*"™^ * object of their pursuit what is pleasant to them and is close at hand. But as their age advances the character of their pleasures alters, so they make friends quickly and quickly cease to be friends : their friendship alters along with Bk. VIII. 4.] Translation. 439 their pleasure, and pleasure of this kind is liable to rapid changes. The young are moreover prone to fall in love, love being largely the result of passion and the desire of pleasure. On this account they speedily make friends and speedily cease to be such, changing often in the course of a single day. But these (unlike the last) do wish to spend their time together and to live in one another's company, the object of their friendship being in this way realised by them. IMendship of this transient sort is observed to prevail most among elderly men, since men of this stamp do not make pleasure strenuously, or continually, the objeot of pursuit. Consequently they abandon pleasurable friendship, and, devoting themselves to profit, form their friendships on gi'ounds of self-interest. And not the elderly only, but also those of the young who have an eye to interest more than to pleasure. Men of this stamp do not iu aU cases pass their lives together, for at times they take no delight in one another. They take delight in one another only so long as they are severally profitable to one another, or furnish lopes of advantage to one another. At other times they no longer find pleasuie igi one another, and, not finding pleasure, they don't care to live in the same house. Of this character it is maintained that hereditary friendships also are. These are contracted on grounds of self-interest. But the friendship of the young is, in the great majority of instances, based jipon pleasure. The young spend their lives under the away of passion, and for the most part make pleasure the object of their pursuit, and present pleastu'e rather than future advantage. Living as a rule by sense they delight in what is actually present and what tickles the senses. But as their age advances so do their pleasures also change, for which reason they quickly make friends and quickly cease to be friends, for as their pleasure drops through, their friend- ship di-ops through along with it. But pleasure of this kind drops through quickly, and so does the friendship which depends upon it. And the young are also ready to fall in love, as they live by the rule of passion and pleasure, for the sentiment of love is largely made up of passion and pleasure. Consequently they are quick to make friends, quick to cease to be friends, changing often in the course of a single day. Their friendships aie formed not at the dictates of reason and judgment but under the influence of passion. But these do wish to pass their time together and to live in one another's society. This is, indeed, the very source and origin of their friendship, and pleasure requires company for its realization. Such then is the friendship based on enjoyment and on self interest, imperfect and accidental in its character. iv.— Of ideal or perfect Friendship. But the friendship of the good, who are alike in the character of their virtue, is perfect : such in virtue of their goodness agree in wishing each other all good, ,^e\Speic? and their goodness is a goodness of character, for (i) it la un- But they who in an unselfish spirit wish their ^^'''^^\ (2) tased J'-jii n ™. ,. 11-1 upon character, iriends all good, are friends in the highest sense ; for they are friends not on any accidental grounds, but in virtue of their own inherent character, and their friendship continues as long as their goodness lasts, — ^^and virtue lasts well. Besides each 440 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 4. of them is good absolutely and good too to his friend, for the good are profitable to one another as well as absolutely good, and they are in the same way pleasant also, for the good are pleasant abso- lutely and pleasant to one another. Every man finds pleasure in his own peculiar acts, and those that resemble them, and the acts of all good men are either identical or at any rate similar in character. Friendship of this kind we consider, with good reason, to be lasting, since it combines in itself all the charac- as ing, teristics which friends should have. Every friend- ship is based on goodness or on pleasure (goodness and pleasure which are really such, or are viewed as such by the person feeling the friendship) and implies a certain resemblance. Now in this perfect form all these requisites are present, and (4) combines in it- present too in virtue of the character of those self all necessary j • -j. j. -ui i i. ,> conditions. Concerned ; in it we get resemblance between the friends and the remaining conditions, to wit absolute goodness and absolute pleasantness : these are the highest objects of affection ; consequently, where these are, there will be love and friendship in their highest and best forms. Bat it is likely that such friendships will be rare. Men of the character required are few, and the friendship Perfect fnendsmps -k i_- i • i- i i • -j i p are rare, (1) be- needs time and intimacy to bring it to periec- cause good men are tion ; for, as the proverb says, men cannot know scarce, ^^^ another till they have eaten, as the saying goes, salt together ; nor can they even be sure that they are friends till they have had time, each of them, to become manifestly loved by the other and to be trusted by him. But those who hastily strike up friendships with one another have a wish to be friends but are not such, un- (2) because time is less they are loved as well and know themselves them kf perfection *« be SO: a wish for friendship may arise speedily, but not friendship itself. We conclude, then, that friendship of this kind is perfect in respect of time and in all its other particulars, and that in all things each gets from the other an identical, or similar, advantage ; and this is the relation which should subsist between friends. But the friendship of good men, who are alike in virtue, baaed as it is on good- ness, is perfect and intrinsic friendship. For such, because they are good themselves, wish each other the enjoyment of all good, having no ulterior obfecit in view, but quite unselfishly. And those, who wish their friends the enjoyment of all good, on no personal.grounds but quite unselfishly, are fiiends in the highest sense of the term : they love their friends for their own sake and wish them all good with no arrifere pensfe and on no accidental grounds. Such friendship moreover is both stedfast and lasting. It lasts as long as the friends aie good Bk. Yin. 5.] Translation. 44 1 and excellent, and take pleasure in what is good, and virtue is lasting. And each oJ the two is both absolutely good in himself and good also to his friend. For the good are both good in themselves and good to one another. In a similar way they are pleasant and profitable as well ; since those who are ^od in themselves, and absolutely, are also pleasant to one another. Each takes delight in his own peculiar acts and is also delighted with those of the rest of the world, when they are like to, or the same as, his own acts. But the acts of all good and excellent men are either the same or at any rate alike ; and so it is plain that the good are pleasant both to themselves and to one another. Consequently such friendship as this is lasting. For those characteristics which the other two forms of friend- ship exhibit specially, and which are needful in friends, all these this friendship, and this feiendship alone, comprises in itself. It contains at once goodness, and pleasantness, and profitableness ; pleasantness and profitableness resulting from goodness ; and goodness of this sort is not merely good in itself but is also good to him who feels the affection. Moreover their very likeness to one another is productive of pleasure to friends of this kind. So this friendship has both pleasantness and profitableness in the highest degree. And in virtue of their likeness to this the two other kinds of friendship get their names. This is the best form of friendship ; and the causes which produce it are most properly and in the highest sense, objects of affection. It is likely enough that such friendships should be rare. Those who are good, in the sense we have described, are few and far between. And friendship of this kind requires not only virtue and good dispositions but time and intimacy as well to mature it. As the proverb says, you cannot know one another, tiU you have consumed together the proverbial salt. Nor is it possible heartily to receive and to love one another, till each has had time to become clearly loved by the other, and to be believed to love that other. Those, who strike up friendly rela- tions with one another in a hurry have a wish to be friends, but are not really such, unless they grow into each other's affections by length of time and intimacy and come to believe themselves to be loved. Consequently a wish for friendship may originate quickly, but not friendship itself. As a result of this the friend- ship of the good is complete in point of time as well as in all those other particulars which have been enumerated, and rests on all the different grounds of affection. Once more, each of the two friends gets from the other to an equal extent all those good offices, which should subsist between friends : both of these are alike in being good, alike in being pleasant to the other, and alike in being loved by that other. v. — Ideal rriendship compared with, the two inferior kinds. id) THEIE INFBKIOKITT FURTHER DEMONSTRATED, Still friendship, which has pleasure for its object, has a certain likeness to true friendship, since the good are agreeable to one another as well as to the rest of ^"Je'the^obS the world ; so too has friendship for profit's sake, sought by the two since the good are also profitable to one another, ^^'"^e^morfreli In these two cases, friendships are more likely to and more lasting be permanent where each of the two friends t'"^'\./ii«'^e t^^^r J. •■■■ T-ip •/. • I. are different. aerives a similar kmd of gratification from the other, pleasure say, and not only so but where this pleasure is drawn in both cases from the same source. This is so with the witty, but not so with the lover and his darling. These latter both 442 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. Vlli. 5. indeed feel pleasure, but not pleasure in the same objects. What the lover delights in is the sight of his darling, what the latter delights in is being courted by his lover. So when the bloom passes off, the friendship often drops ; the lover is no longer charmed by the sight of his darling, and so the latter no longer receives the same attentions as of old. Still in many cases such friendships are lasting, if the two from similarity of disposition come to love each other's characters. Those who, in their love affairs, interchange, not pleasure but . , profit, are not such real or such lasting friends, pieasurTmore'Lst- Those whom profit makes friends break off their ing than those of friendships as soon as the profit vanishes. It is ^™ ' not one another they are friends of, but their own selfish interests. Now on grounds of pleasure or of profit the bad may be friends with one another, and the good with the bad, and trae friendshirii) *^°^® ^^° ^^® neither one nor the other with any in unselfishness, of the three ; but to be friends for their friend's (2) m supenonty ^-^^ ^^^ jg clearly restricted to the good alone, to slander. . t t ■> i i • i Since the bad have no pleasure in one another, unless some advantage is to be gained. Furthermore, it is the friendship of the good that is alone un- ruffled by slander ; it is not easy to believe anyone's stories about a friend who has been proved over a long period of time. Between such friends perfect trust prevails and an assurance that their friend never could have injured them, and those other requi- sites which we look for in real friendship. But in the two other kinds there is nothing to prevent slander having its way. But tte friendship wMcli is based on pleasviie and that ■whicli is based on profit has a certain likeness to this kind. Goodness is that which is strietVy pleaeaat and profitable, and the good are in the highest sense pleasant and profitable to one another. And in the case of these ' friends by analogy,' as they may be called, their friendships are lasting when they give one another the same sort e( gratification, for instance when each is pleasant to the other or profitable ; they are not lasting where the one is pleasant the other profitable. But not only should they afford the same kind of gratification to one another, but also one derived from the same source, that Is to say if they are to keep up their friendship permanently : for instance if they are to give each other pleasure, they must give it by the same kind of dispositions, the witty, for example, gratifying one another by their wit and not being like the lover and the object of his affec- tion. In this case both give one another pleasure, yet not after the same manner. The lover delights in the sight of his darling, the latter in the attentions he receives from his lover. As the bloom dies off, the friendship often fades away, since the pleasure which gave rise to the friendship ceases ; neither is the lover pleased any longer by the sight of his darling, nor does the latter get his atten- tions. Still many under these circumstances do form lasting friendships, that is to say if being of similar dispositions, they come as a result of their intimacy to love each other's characters. Bk. VIII. 6.] Translation. 443 But those who give one another not the same kind of gratification do not form lasting friendships and, when they are friends, love each other less. As a general rule, those who are friends for profit's sake, when the rirofit ceases, cease to be friends and separate ; it was not one another that they cared for but their own interests. Such friendships, then, as these which rest on pleasure or profit, the bad even may experience ; and the bad man may be a friend in this sense as well as the good : on such grounds as these the bad man may love a bad man and may also love a good man, and a good man a bad, and an indifferSnt man either of them, for a good man may often have occasion to use a bad one. A man may well be an excellent admiral, or a first-rate general, without being very excellent morally ; and there is nothing to prevent a good man requiring the services of such. Moreover it is not impossible for the good to be pleased by the bad. Some there are who, though of a wholly alien character, by their skill in discussion and philosophy, and in hitting on truth and the good, make themselves agreeable to the good ; those, then, who are loved in this way are loved not on their own account but for their pleasantness or profitableness. But it is the good alone who are loved by the good for their own sakes ; and such friendship is indissoluble because it is tested and tiied by length of time aind perfect intimacy. About those who have been so tested it is not possible for one who has tested them to believe anything to their disadvantage. In such friendship there prevails perfect trust in one another and confidence on the all- important points, assurance that they never could do one another wrong and all those other things which we look for in those who desire to be friends in truth. But in all besides there is nothing to prevent the friends from being slandered to one another and injuring one another, by not maintaining equality, and from suffering other things as well. (5) TRUE FRIENDSHIP BELONGS TO THE GOOD ALONE. Since, however, men give the name of friends to those who love one another on grounds of interest, which is the case with states (for' the alliance which states form ^sag^ligifies such are held to be formed for the sake of mutual connexions by the advantage), and again to those who love one "^3°® "* fnend- another on the score of pleasure, which is the case with children — perhaps we too ought to call such friends, and to admit more kinds of friendship than one — the friendship of the good qud good, being friendship in the primary and strict sense of the term, the others friendships only by analogy. So far as there is some good in these latter or ^iipa''7ni"by'ana- likeness to the good, so far are they friends, since logy, and in virtue the pleasant is good to those who are fond of J^^^'frieSr' *° pleasure. Such friendships do not often coalesce, nor is it the same men that become friends on grounds of pleasure that become friends on the score of interest, such accidental quali- fications being not often coupled together. But since friendship may be divided into these different species, the bad will be friends either for pleasure or for profit, when they happen to agree in affording one ™ go^od™"*^""^ *" another pleasure or profit. But the good are friends for one another's own sakes : and friends because they are 444 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 6 good. Such, then, are friends in an absolute sense, the others onh accidentally, and in virtue of the resemblance they bear to them. For which reasbn men of this stamp are not friends at all in the proper aena of the term. But since men are wont to name tliose friends, who are held to gether by mutual need — as states for instance call their allies friends — or thosi who are held together by pleasure — as children who are intimate caU one anothei friends — accordingly we too must name them friends, only not fi-iends ia th( same way as the good ; we do not regard them as of the same species, but cal them ' friends by analogy.' For this same reason we speak also of several kindi of friendship. The friendship of the good, in virtue of their goodness, is friendl ship in the primary and proper sense of the term : the other two are frieudsMti only by analogy ; for the pleasant also, in so far as it is a kind of good, by is pleasantness holds men together : the pleasant is a sort of good to the lovers oi pleasure, and it is like good just because it seems good to them ; the profitable also seems good to him who is in the enjoyment of it. Hence it comes to paa that friendships which are prompted by these motives get called friendships ftoni their bieness to true friendship. But a fiiendship which grows out of a mixture of pleasure and profit, jn such a way that on the one side the affection arises from pleasure on the other from profit, is of rare occurrence ; that which binds friends together is only accidentally present in this case, for that which binds friends together is the delighting in the same things, the loving the same things. Socrates' love for Plato, for instance, is based on their common love to (the elder) Socrates and their common delight in his prosperity or, it may be, on their both loving pleasure, or both profit. Bnt in the case of this compound friendship they don't both take delight in the same thing, but one delights in the pleasant, the other in the profitable : it is only a matter of accident that they love the same thing, so far as each rejoices in the other's good and prays for his prosperity : stOl they don't do this for their friend's own sake, but because of pleasure or profit. For this reason, then, friendship of this kind does not often occur, because it is a pure accident that what is common to the two is united in one thing. But what is a single thing only by accident wiU not often hold men together. If, then, friendship be divided into these three species, the bad will be friends to get pleasure or profit, this being the point of resemblance between them, while the good alone will be friends unselfishly. Because they are both good, therefore do they love each other. Such men tiien are friends absolutely properly and essentially, the others only accidentally, having the name of friendship applied to them from their resemblance to the good. IV.— THE CONDITIONS FAVOURABLE TO FRIENDSHIP. i.— Constant intercourse is necessary to give reality to Friendship. Now, just as in respect of the virtues, some men are called good for their dispositions others for their acts, ^•rtTe^^'m eS ^° *'°° ^^ ^^ ^'^ respect of friendship — that is, some I^ a"potential dis- are Called friends for their friendly dispositions, position, or M an others for their friendly acts. Those who live courae is" required together delight in one another and supply one to make friend- another with blessings, while those who are ships act . asleep or separated by distance do not live in the performance of acts of actual friendship, though they may be dis- Bk. VIII. 6.] Translation. 445 posed to do so : distance destroys, not friendship in itself but, the actual exhibition of it ; and if the absence be protracted, even the ;£iaendship itself gets forgotten, a fact which has given rise to the sentiment, " Many are the friendships dissolved for want of interoonrse. " And, as in respect of the virtues, some men are called good for their dispo- sition, others for their actual conduct — some, for instance, have a disposition of justioe, but do not put it in practice, as they are prevented by external circum- stances, while others do put their justice in practice, acting in accordance with that disposition of justice which they have received — so too is it with friendship. Some there are, who live together, delight in one another's prosperity, and furnish each to the other all the good in their power, while others sleep, are separated by distance, and do not practise acts of friendship to one another, and yet are so disposed as to do so — since distance does not put an end to friendship in itself, only to the active exercise of it. But if the absence be long continued, then even the friendship itself grows forgotten, which has caused it to be said, " Many are the friendships dissolved for want of intercourse." ii. — A certain pliability and easiness of temper required. But the elderly and the austere don't appear to be good subjects for friendship ; there is little that is pleasinsr in them, and no one can pass his days ^'^^ elderly and ■ ,■,,,■-,■ ■ ■,^ 1 , austere do not often With what gives him pain or even with what make friends since gives him no pleasure, since nature seems to t^^y have no piea- , 1 , T, ^ 1 . ■ • ^ 1 1 J. sure in one an- shun beyond all else what is pamiul and to yearn other's company, for what is pleasant. Those who entertain esteem for one another but yet don't live together should be regarded rather as well dis- posed than as friends proper, there being nothing though mutual es- so distinctive of friends as their living together ; tremwdidispo"ei since the needy require assistance, the fortunate company, they least of all can afford to be solitary. But men cannot pass their time with one another if they are not agreeable to one another and don't take pleasure in the same pursuits, these sconditions being the bases on which companionship rests. . The elderly and the austere do not furnish promising material for friendship, as there is so little that is pleasant in them. But where there is no pleasure felt, men do not care to live together or pass their time in company, since no one would choose to pass his days with what is painful or even with what fails to please him. A man we cannot live with cannot become our friend, for it is intercourse and companionship that make friends. Those who esteem one another without living together are to be accounted weU-disposed rather than friends. There is nothing so distinctive of friends as living together. Not even those whom interest makes friends can do without living together ; if they are in want, they require each other's services, and these they cannot have without living 446 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 7. together. Nor can those who are friends for pleasure's sake get on much better, nor those either who are properly friends, I mean the blessed themselves : for though they may not stand in need of one another, they still are agreeable to one another. For this further reason it is impossible for them not to wish to live together, because there are none whom it so little becomes to be solitary as the blessed. They are bound to be in one another's company, taking pleasure in the same pursuits. But this taking pleasure in the same pursuits constitutes the boon companionship of the young, when they are keenly interested in the same objects. iii. — Friendship implieB a virtuous disposition and a settled determination of the will. It follows again from this that the friendship of the good is friendship in the highest sense, as has been ta ftemsXl'^tte already frequently stated. For it is absolute. conditions most es- goodness and' absolute pleasantness which are sential to friend- j^gj^ ^.q ^e most properly the objects of affection and desire (though for each individual these will be shaped by his own peculiar temperament), and in the good man both these desiderata are found combined. Moreover while affection may be regarded as a feeling, friend- , . , . ship bears more the character of a settled dispo- "wliicii IS no Tn ftTft passing phase of sition. Affection may be felt towards inanimate the affections, but objects ; but men can requite affection only by a character'* and™ e- determinate act of the will, and this itself is the termination of the result of a settled character ; and to have an un- ^ selfish wish for the good of the objects of our love is the result not of feeling but of character. Besides in loving their friend, men love what is good for themselves, since the good man, in becoming a friend, becomes a good to him whose friend he is. Accordingly in this case each at once loves what is good for himself and gives the other back an equivalent both in good will and in the kind of good ; and as friendship is said to consist in equality, therefore this essential is most completely realised in the friendship of the good. But since friendship is a virtue, and since in every virtue we can detect an element of feeling as well as a disposition, we must inquire what the feeling in friendship is and what the disposition. Now affection resembles a feeling, friend- ship a disposition. A feeling is that which rises in us without any choice of the will, but a disposition implies a determination of the will and is that in virtue of which we exhibit such determination of the will ; affection comprises both the love we entertain for inanimate objects and generally for objects from which no requital of our affection is possible ; and this is a feeling. We love in these cases not from any judgment or consideration or deliberate choice but simply because we are moved in respect of it, and this is feeling pure and simple. But friendship is love for those who love us, and this is a feeling implying an act of the will ; for we judge that we' mi^ht to love one who loves us ; and so we are moved not only from without but also from within ourselves and by considera- Bk. VIII. 7.] Translation. 447 tion ; but an emotion whicli implies consideration and an act of the will is the result of character. We conclude then that affection is a feeling', friendship a disposition. Once more, friends have an unselfish wish for the good or those they love. They do this not without consideration but on consideration of the grounds : but to wish good to those we love for their sake forms part of the idea of friendship. On this ground therefore also friendship implies a certain fixity of character. Once again, each man loves the good friend, in that he is a good to himself ; fot the good man, by becoming a friend, becomes good to his friend : each, con- M- gequently, loves the other as his own proper good, and they wish one another |i-W0ll an,d are pleasant to one another in the same way. And in every way each makes the other an equal return, friendship being called equality ; but to make such an equal return implies deliberate choice, and deliberate choice grows out of a settled character ; friendship, consequently, is a settled disposition, while affection, implying no deliberate choice, is simply a v.— LIMITATIONS OF FRIENDSHIP STATED. i. — The austere and the elderly seldom make friends. Between the austere and the elderly friendship is of less frequent occurrence, because they suffer more from infir- mities of temper and take less pleasure in society, '^^ austere and but good temper and the love of society are held barred from friend- to be in the highest degree elements of friendship "Mp by want of and productive of it. For this reason the young pathy. ^° ^^^' make friends quickly, not the old; since these can- not make friends with those in whom they take no delight. The same is the case with the austere. Such characters may very well be well wishers to one another : they wish each other good and come to the relief of one another's necessities — yet they are not friends proper, as they do not spend their days together or take delight in one another, things which are the very making of friendship. All the elements conducive to friendship and proper to friends occur in the case of the friendship of the good alone. Between the elderly and the austere friendship is of less frequent occurrence, inasmuch as they are more liable to infirmities of temper and have less taste for Society : society and company are held to be most productive of friendship. Consequently the young make friends quickly, the elderly do not : for it is not possible to become friends with a man whom you take no delight in and in whose society you feel no pleasm-e. To feel such pleasure occurs but seldom in the case of the elderly, they know so little what pleasure is. On these same grounds the austere also but seldom become friends, though such are often well vrishers to one another ; they wish one another good as far as their needs go, and they get from one another the help they each of them reed : but they are not friends, as they don't spend their days together or take delight in each other, and it is this that most constitutes friend- ship and promotes it. %. 448 TAe Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 7. ii. — The numbsr and oharaotsr of the friends -we should make. Next it is not possible to be on a footing' of perfect friendship with many at the same time, any more than it is possible to be in love with many people at once ; such friendship is a highly exalted state of feeling, and naturally can be entertained We can^be Mends to^ar^s but one at a time. Nor is it easy for sense only with many to be giving at once exquisite pleasure to very few at one ^j^g gg^jjjg individual. Nor perhaps does it oftea tune. 1 happen that you come across at the same time many who are good. You require further to have experience of them and to become intimate with them, a task of no pilare we'U ^^^^^^^ difficulty. But On grounds of interest and be friends with pleasure it is possible to please many at once; there F ■ ^'^hi s ""^"^of ^^^ many who will be pleased on these grounds, pleasure are more and to render such serviccs requires no great real than friend- length of time. Of these imperfect friendships, ships of profit, (1) , 1 ° 1 • . • I, J 1 1 ~ 5 ' there is something that which 18 bascd on pleasure has more of the more generous character of real friendship, at least in those about them, , ,, . . •, n x i j cases where there is reciprocity oi mutual favours and the two friends take delight in one another and in the same pursuits. This is the character of the friendships of the young. In tbem there is a larger element of generosity, and (2) it is such while it is mercenary characters that form friend- friends that the ,. ijri?j.Ti/r xij prosperous (who ShipS On grOUndS 01 pront. Moreover the tor- are able to choose tunate, though they don't require serviceable, do mostly look fOT^ want pleasant friends. They require some one to live with, and can submit to what is painful only for a little while, since no one can put up with it as a permanence. A man could not stand even the good itself for long if absolutely distasteful to him. Thus the friends they look yet they ought to for are agreeable friends. Yet they ought, I good'aswX " ^ think, while looking for such to see that they are good as well and good too for them; in this way they will secure what should be implied in friends. It is not possible for the g'ood man to be on terms of perfect friendship with many at onoe, just as it is not possible either to be in love with many at once. Perfect friendship is a kind of intensity of friendship, and such a feeling can be entertained towards only one at a time. To take great delight in the same objects is hardly possible among many, nor is it easy to meet with many who are good and estimable. Besides this, to perfect such ideal friendship requires long time, great iatimaoy, and n thorough proof of one another. To get these is difficult. In respect of the two other forms of friendship one may be friends with many. On the score of interest a man may delight many, and attract many by the Bk. VIII. T.*] Translation. 449 charm of his society. Many there are who take delight in such objects and who are moved to love by such motives ; and these do not require a long time either in order to make fuU trial of their friends, but profess at once affection on grounds of interest or pleasure. Perfect friendship, then, is*hat which is based on goodness, whUe the other two forms are friendships only by analogy, being respectively based on interest and on pleasure. But of these ' analogical ' friendships, that form of friendship for pleasure's sake, in which each gets the same sort of return from the other and both take delight in one another or in the same people, is more like true friendship. In the first place there is more generosity in friendships of pleasure than in friendships of profit. It is the mercenary and illiberal who form friendships on this latter ground. Besides, true friendship needs pleasure, but needs not proiit in any wise. The blessed while they have no need of what is profitable do need elements of pleasure. They want some one to live with, and cannot live with those who are disagreeable to them. They can bear with the disagreeable only for a little time ; indeed no one can endure to be pained perpetually, and no one would be able to put up with even the good itself for long, if it were distasteful to him. For this reason the excellent look for their friends being pleasant, while they are at the same time good, and good too to them ; in this way they Will have the qualities friends should have. On these grounds we may assume that friendship for pleasure has more the character of true friendship than friendship for profit. iii. — The Friends of th.e powerful. Those who are in high position seem to need a number of dif- ferent kinds of friends ; one set of men to be ser- viceable to them, another pleasant, while the same "^^ powerfal menarerarely, if eyer, both; for the powerful don't (i) the witty to look for friends who are at once asrreeable and have amuse them, (2) . , , „ 1 r. i 1 1 _p T the dever to serve Virtue also, nor for such as are prontable lor good them. works. They seek out the witty, when they wish for pleasure, the clever to carry out their orders ; these qualities are not often combined in the same man. We have indeed pointed out that the good man is pleasant and profitable „ , , .„ ° i- T. i I, J B"* tl'e good will at one and the same time, but sucn an one does not become their not make friends with his superior in position, friends, where they , 1/.T1. 10 1- .. 1 forfeit self-respect. unless he feels himself surpassed m virtue also ; unless this is so a balance is not struck by his being porportion- ately surpassed (in which case he would be able to repay the advantage he receives by the honour he would give); but such t, characters (preeminent at once in station and in virtue) are of rare occurrence. Those in high position do not employ the same friends as profitable and as agreeable. One set -of men are profitable to them, another agreeable ; but the same individuals are never, or scarcely ever, both. The reason of this is that profit and pleasure are combined only in perfect friendship, which is the friend- ship of the good. Those in authority do not, however, seek the good for their friends. They do not seek those whom virtue makes pleasant nor such as are profitable for good works. But they employ the witty to give them pleasure, the clever as useful tools to carry out their orders. These qualities are not often found together in the same individual. For, though the good man is at once 450 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 8. pleasant and profitable, as has been already said, still he does riot become friends with his superiors in station, unless that superior recognise his superiority in point of virtue and submit himself to the good man, and acknowledge liim for his better. In this way the good man will feel himself on a footing of equality^; with his superior iu station, by being superior and surpassed proportionately: and: ; feeling himself on an equality he wOl be his friend ; but unless he do so feel ' himself, he will not be. Since those in high position are not often of such a character, consequently neither are the good often friends with them. iv. — Summary of the general cliaraoter of the friendships based on equality. All the friendships we have described are based on an equality : for either the friends get the same advantages All these friend- ^^g i^Qxa. another and wish the same advantases ships imply an i i i i equality, an equal- One to another, or they make an exchange of one ■ity of gams given ^juor for another, pleasure for instance for profit. and received. t. i , ,i i , i n ■, , , But that these latter are less real and less lastmsr friendships we have already pointed out. They are held to he or not to be friendships at all according as men But *e *wo in- j^a,ve looked at their similarity or dissimilarity to friendship will be One and the Same thing : from their likeness to regarded as friend- friendship based on virtue they look like friend- cordin "asTe con- ship — the One promoting pleasure the other profit,' sider their likeness and thoso both belonging to ideal friendship, the idea\ type! *° ^^^ l^ecause true friendship is superior to slander and is lasting, while these quickly fall through and differ from it in many other particulars, they appear not to be friendships at all, from their unlikeness to the true. All the friendships above described are based on equality. In these the friends reap the same advantages from one another and wish the same good to one another or else exchange one thing for another, equal for equal, pleasure for instance for profit. That these last are less properly friendships than the rest, and are shorter lived, we have already said. But friendships which are based on pleasure or on profit, from one point of view may be regarded as friendships, from another not. In so far as they are like perfect friendship, they are friendships ; in so far as they are unlike it, they are not friendships. They are like it because perfect friendship has both goodness and profitableness ; they are unlike it, because while perfect friendship is enduring and superior to slander, they quickly fall through, and differ from it in many other respects besides. All these, then, are friendships by analogy and are based on equality. VI.— FRIENDSHIPS OP CONDESCENSION. i. — Such friendships admit a large number of varieties. There is, however, another form of friendship, involving a supe- riority on one side, for instance the friendship of a father for his son, and generally of the elder for the younger, of a man for a Bk. VIII. 8.] Translation. 45 1 woman and of the ruler in every instance for his subjects. And these also, as well as the former, differ from one another; the friendship of parents for their ^fXtlL' a?I children is not the same as that of rulers for formed among a their subjects, nor again is that of father to son, ™*J °^ different the same as that of son to father, nor even that of husband to wife the same as that of wife to husband. Each of these has a different form of excellence and a different function, and the grounds of their affec- ''^''''*j^^™™ '^'*^^^: tion are different also ; consequently the affection may be regarded as they severally feel is different and their friend- different kinds of , / n friendsuip. ships as well. But there is also another kind of friendship, which is based, not on equality, but on superiority on one side : for instance, that of father for son, and gener- ally between old and young, husband and wife, ruler and subject. MoreoTer, these differ from one another ; for the friendship of paj:ent and chil- dren is not the same as that of ruler and subject, nor even is that of father for son the same as that of son for father, nor of husband to wife the same as that of wife to husband, — so that, not only do the friendships differ in these cases, but the affection given, and that by which it is requited, are also different. The excellence of each of the friends is different, consequently their functions also, and the grounds on which they love one another. Therefore, also, are the affections and the friendships different too. In the friendships described above their perma- nence was produced by each of the friends getting precisely the same advantage from the other : but here this is niot the case. A father will not ask back from the son exactly what the son will expect from his father. ii.— But in all th.e return of affection should be proportionate, not equal. Accordingly neither does each get exactly the same kind ot return from the other, nor ought they to look for ^ .. -i , , T-ij ii • J. n J.1 J. In these the return It; but when children pay their parents all that made will be d) is due to those who have begotten them, and different on the parents their children all that children have a ^°^' ^^' right to, the friendship under these circumstances is lasting and excellent. But in all friendships involving superiority, the affection given should be proportionate ; I mean the better should receive more affection than he to the^meritT^of gives, as also the more profitable and in the same ti^e t^". rather way with the rest ; for, where there is accorded an ^" ^^*° ^^'" affection proportionate to merit, then in a way equality is secured, and this is rightly held to be distinctive of friendship. In the above described forms of friendship, what, as we showed, produces per- manence in them is, that each of the two gets the same advantage from the other, but in these cases it is not so : the father will not ask back from the son the same services that the son looks for from the father. Men ought not in such respects to attempt to secure an absolute equality ; but, > G G 2 452 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 9. when one receives from the other what he ought to give and the other to receive, their friendship is lasting and equitable. Furthermore, the affection also ought to be proportionate in friendships imply- ing superiority ; the better of the two, and the more profitable, and so too the other oases, ought to receive more affection than he gives ; for a certain kind of equality requires to be realised in these cases too, as it is this which cements friendship. iii. — Limits within wMoli such Friendships are possible. Equality does not seem to hold exactly the same position in respect of friendship that it holds in respect of i^^T Sen justice ; in justice what we look for first is an the two friends is equality which has regard to the proportiona!^. essential to friend- jQgj.j^.g ^f ^j^g ^wo parties, while absolute or numerical equality is only secondary, but in ' friendship this absolute equality is primary, and equality which is proportionate to merit is secondary. This is at fact^ that friend- ^"^^^ apparent if the discrepancy in virtue, wicked- ships are never ness, wealth or anything else be great : the two thought °k Te° °o longer make friends, nor think it right they tween those who shouM. This is bcst Seen in case of the Gods, as are very widely re- ^j^g^ surpass all othcrs most in evcrv kind of moved from one •' •'^ . . , . » i • another in posi- good ; yet it IS Clear even m the case of kings, tion, or in good- With them also those who are far their inferiors in station do not eyen think of making friends ; nor again with the very wise or the very good do men of no con- sideration. One can lay down no accurate definition in such cases up to what point two men can be friends. Though many advantages be removed, the friendship may still continue, but where the gap is very wide (as for instance between man and God) it is no longer possible. But equality after a sort is attained when affection is proportioned to superior merit, and by this equality the principle of justice is preserved. Yet equality does not stand in the same relation to friendship that it stands in to justice ; in justice the first requisite is an equality based on desert, and proportionate to those that receive, whUe equality in amount is only a secondary requisite ; for if the distri- bution be made according to merit and in proportion, it is just ; and even though the amounts differ very much there is nothing to prevent the standard of justice being maintained — indeed if the distribution made was equal in amount and not proportionate, it would not be just ; but with friendship just the reverse is the case ; the equality which is required in it is in the first place an equality in amount, and only in the second place an equality in proportion. For if two parties differ very much, and the interval between them is not small, but one is very much superior to the other in virtue, in wealth, or in anything else, they will not be friends ; they neither can be nor wish to be. It becomes quite obvious in the case of ourselves and God : He surpasses us infinitelyin every kind of good and, in consequence, in this instance friendship has no place ; it is clear too even in the case of kings ; those who are far their inferiors in rank don't even think of claiming friendship with them either ; nor do those of no account Bk. VIIL9.] Translation. 453 with such, as are very excellent and very wise. We conclude, then, that those who , ,^e very widely distant cannot be friends, but where the superiority is moderate in ; 'amonnt it is possible. • " ' How wide the interval may be it is impossible to say precisely or to give an ac- ienrate definition. For though many advantages are taken away from one of the two friends, and the other is put thereby in a position of great superiority, it may be that the friendship will still continue ; or it may be that it wiU be broken off, when the interval between the two becomes very wide — as wide, for instance, as that between ourselves and God. .. iv. — DifiB.culty stated and solved. -Hereupon a question is raised whether it can be that friends wish their friends the very greatest of goods, that is that they should be Gods, since in then, to the good that case they would cease to be their friends ? '«'hioh a friend can But if they don't wish them this, they don't wish them good ; and yet, as friends, they should wish them all good. . Now if we were right in saying that friends wish their friends good for those friends' own sake, it is a necessary condition of their wish that the friend should ^m tHelth^ln remain in the state he is in.; but a friend will the grade of being wish his friend the greatest of goods, compatible ^i^an he is ; nor With nis bemg a man, and yet not perhaps alter such an amount of all all good, since each must wish good to himself f °°** ^.JP'^. ^"*^'^' , %, ,, ° fere with his own above all others. happiness. On these grounds a question is also raised, whether, after all, friends can wish their friends the very ohiefest goods : did their wishes extend to this length, they would join in their prayer, that they might become Gods : but this would put am end to the friendship ; so that if they wish them the very chief est goods they wish in effect that they should no longer be their friends ; but to do this is opposed to the very idea of friendship, while besides they will be no longer good to them, if ihey are no longer their friends ; they don't, therefore, join in their prayers for goods of this hind. • But we may say in reply to this that the friend joins in his friend's prayer for good for that friend's sake ; consequently it is needful that his friend continue to be, that so goods may accrue to liim, ; but he wO continue to be, if he be still a man and does not become a God ia place of a man ; if he continue to be but a man, his friend will wish that the very greatest of all goods bef al him ; and yet not per- haps all after all, at least in the actual case of the majority of friends, since it is for himself that each wishes for good the most. VII.— THE ESSENCE OP FEIENDSHIP. i. — Friendship consists more in loving than in being loved. The majority are led by ambition to wish to receive rather than to bestow affection, (consequently the majority are lovers of flat- terers, as the flatterer is a friend who acknowledges his inferiority. 454 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 10. or pretends to do so,) and to love more than he is loved. To be loved is like being honoured, and on this most ^dfisliest '^r'the ^®" ^^* *^^"" liearts. desire to be loved, Yet they Seem not to covet honour for its own which the majority g^jjg^ jj^^ only ^y the Way. The mass of men ' delight in honour from those in high station on account of the hopes such honour inspires, thinking they will get from them what they may chance to want ; ^^i'(i h '\Sn^ the accordingly they rejoice in the honour they receive desire for honour, as a sign of benefits to be obtained, which is valued js^g^f ^hose who thirst for honour for the good either (a) as a sign jp.i--,-. i -Ui.? of influence, (b) as and from their mtimates have a wish to nave enhauciiig a man's their own good Opinion of themselves confirmed ; they revel in the feeling that they really are good, trusting to the judgment of such as these when they aflSrm that it is so. But men do delight in being loved for its own sake ; and so, it would seem, to be loved is better than to be honoured ; and friend- ship we should hold to be itself desirable. Friendship too would seem to consist more in loving than . . in being loved, a proof of which is furnished by forms (e. g. in a the delight that mothers take in pouring out their mother's love), jove. Some mothers even give their children to friendship consists ,, ,, t,i ^ •■i.i more in loving than ^e brought up by others, and, recognising them in being loved, and as their own, lovc them accordingly, and do not IS so unselfish. ^^^^ ^q^^ fop a requital of their love, if this cannot be combined with their children's continued prosperity, but are content, if only they see them prospering. And they continue to love them all the same, even though their children are prevented by their ignorance of them from performing to them any of those duties to which a mother has a right. But since friendship con- sists more in loving than in being loved, and it is those who love their friends that we single out for praise, therefore loving is thought to be the special virtue of friends; consequently those who exhibit this in a proper degree are lasting friends, and their friendship is lasting friendship. But the majority would seem to be led by ambitious motives to wish to be loved rather than to love ; consequently the majority are fond of flatterers, and take pleasure in the company of such, because they feel their superiority to them while they seem to be their friends ; but this superiority to their friends is pleasant to the ambitious, while flatterers pretend to profess their inferiority in all respects to those in whose company they are, and for this reason to love more than they are loved ; but to be loved is very near being honoured, and this it is that most men yearn for. Yet those who seek to be honoured seek it, not for its own sake, but, only acci- Bk.VIII. 10.] Translation. 455 dentally as indicating sometlinig more. Honour would seem to be regarded by them as a good on account of something other than itself. The majority desire to ; be honoured by their superiors for the hope such honour insjires. They think that they wiU get what they want at the hands of those who honour them, and take , pleasure in the honour as an indication of future benefits. But the better sort, " who have a craving to be honoured by the good, have as their reason for seeking ? honour that they wish to have sure grounds for entertaining a good opinion of ; themselves. And they have their good opinion of themselves confirmed by the suffrages of such men. Consequently they take pleasure in honour while it pro- ceeds from such a source, and feel confidence in their own goodness. We conclude, then, that to be honoured is sought for for something other than itself, but to be loved for its own sake. This is indeed pleasant and desirable in itself, consequently it would seem to be a better thing than to be honoured, and friendship would seem to be in itself de- sirable. For, since it consists both in being loved and in loving, and each of these ; is in 'itself desirable, it is clear that friendship too is in itself desirable ; accord- jinglynot only is being loved in itself desirable but loving also, and even more so as being the more excellent. Whence it follows that friendship consists also more in loving than in being loved ; as is proved by the pleasure that mothers take in pouring out ailection, without even seeking a return of it at the hands of their children. Some of them even make their own children the supposititious offspring of others, or, at any rate, give them to others to be brought up by them, and so, not being known to their children, are not even loved by them : of course they themselves do know their children and love them, but don't even seek to be loved by them in return, if this is incompatible with their children's prosperity, but are content if only they can see them well off. But if friendship consists more in loving than being loved, and if it is those who are fond of their friends that are praised, loving is a sort of virtue in friends. Accordingly where love is given in due proportion, the two are lasting friends and their friendship is sure. And in this way even the unequal may become friends ,t if they love one another in proper amounts, since by these means they will be made egual to one another, and friendliness means equality. ii. — In what sense likeness is essential to friendship. la this way those who are unequal in station may most readily be made friends, as they will be put thereby on a footing of equality. Equality and likeness con- ^ proportionate re- stitute friendship, most of all the likeness of those who observe the law of virtue ; being stedfast in themselves, they are stedfast to one another and neither ask for what is evil nor abet one another in evil; but, a?, rt ■ together, and are friends but for a brief space -wickedness is no from taking pleasure in iniquity. The serviceable abiding guarantee and the pleasant are more lasting friends. They at least continue friends, as long as they give one another either pleasure or profit. 456 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 10. But likeness of this kiad isfouad most perfectly and in the proper sense among the good. Among the bad it is scarcely to be found at aU, more among those whose aim is pleasure or profit. The good are at one with themselves : they do not easily change nor take pleasure now in one thing now in another, but only in good deeds. Virtue is lasting because it is a formed character, and consequently the good are ever like one another and abide in each other's friendship. And they neither ask for what is evil nor abet one another in it, but, so to speak, ever throw obstacles in the way. The good neither fall into sin themselves nor permit their friends to do evil. But the evil are evil too in this, that they don't take pleasure always in the same objects. For which reason they are not always like themselves nor like their friends, and hence they abide but a little while in their friendship, only so long as they take pleasure in one another's wickedness. But the serviceable and, the agreeable continue longer in their likeness to one another, as the search for the profitable and the pleasant is more lasting. Consequently they continue longer like themselves and each other, since both seek the profitable or the pleasant ; namely, so long as they furnish one another with pleasure or with profit. Such, then, are the friendships which arise from likeness. iii. — Cases where unlikeness produces friendship. But it is friendship based on profit which seems most often to be formed from opposites, for instance, the friend- it is friendships g^jp between rich and poor, ignorant and wise. for profit s sake -^j-^. . . j o a.i ■ i • i • that are formed W hen a man IS m need oi somethmg, his desire most often between for it impels him to give something in return. ters™with "which Under this class may be brought lover and loved, we may, perhaps, bcautiful and Ugly. For this reason lovers some- sMps!*""'''^'""^" t™^s ^PP^^'" ridiculous when they expect to be loved as much as they love. They would have, indeed, a right to ask it, if they were as deserving of affection ; but, when they are nothing of the kind, it is ridiculous in them to do so. But that form of friendship which is based on profit would seem to consist in contrariety. Take for instance the case of a poor man making friends with a rich, an ignorant with a learned man. Where a man feels in want of something, in his desire to get this he is prepared to give something else in exchange. Under this species may be classed the friendship between a lover and his darling, and the friendship of the beautiful and the ugly. For this reason lovers often appear ridiculous, when they claim to have their affection equally requited by the objects of it, being themselves ugly while those are beautiful. If they are at loveable, their claim is reasonable, and they have a right to be loved as much, but, if they are not, they make themselves ridiculous. iv.— The true ground of attraction in these cases. After all, perhaps, even in these cases it is not that opposite But what dissimi- jearns for opposite pure and simple, their doing lars yearn for is SO being merely accidental. What they really other?^'but°\hai Jeam for is ' a state of balance ' (for this is the 'balanced condi- good). The moist, for instance, desires not to BLVIII. ll.J Translation. 457 become dry but to reach the intermediate state, tion ' wMcii is m- the same being the case with that which is warm tweeu'\hem ^^" and with all the rest. However, let this pass, for Sttch speculations are somewhat alien to our inquiry. In these oases friendsMps are thought to be formed between men of opposite parts because the ugly love the fair — the rich the poor — ^the ignorant the learned. In nature also the dry yearns for the moist. Yet such friendships between opposites arise, not from their essential character, but only incidentally. It is not as loving one another that they are opposite, but it is an accident that they are such. The poor man loves a rich man, because he is profitable or serviceable to him. But a useful or serviceable tool is not essentially and in itself opposite to him who uses it. In that case every serviceable agent would be opposed to him who avails himself of it. But the soldier is not opposed to his general nor tlie disciple to his teacher. The lover also loves his darling because he is pleasant to him. But he who is pleasant is not opposed to him who is pleased. It is an accident only that they are in a relation of opposition. And ia nature that which is dry yearns properly not for its opposite moisture but for ' a mean state.' Their desire is for what is good, and it is this ' mean state ' which is good. Such subjects may, however, be dismissed ; they are not very germane to our =. present inquiry. VIII.— THE EELATION OF FEIENDSHIP AND JUSTICE. i. — Every association for whatever purpose implies at onee friendship and justice. Now, as we said at starting, friendship and justice seem to have the same sphere and to subsist among the ,, . . '^ . . " Men cannot asso- same individuals, in every association there ciate themselves seems to be justice of a sort and friendship as *<«■ any purpose T, ,1 , TT f.. 1^11 -without forming well, at least men dub as iriends leliow- voyagers friendships and ob- and fellow-soldiers, and in the same way any serving justice to who take part in any joint enterprises. And so °^'' ^™* ™' far as the association goes, so far does the friendship extend, and the justice also. And the proverb ' friends' goods are com- mon property ' is right, inasmuch as friendship is based on community. Now it would seem, as we said before, that both friendship and justice have the same sphere. "We look for justice in the associations which men form with one another, «nd it is in these also that friendship originates. Fellow-voyagers, feUow-soldiers, and generally all those who join with one another in any actions or pursuits, seek to observe justice as towards one another and are also friends with one another ; and as far as their association extends, so far do they love one another and do what is just to one another. Whence also the proverb has it, ', common are the goods of friends,' and rightly too, for friendship is based on community. 458 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 11. ii. — Friendship and justice vary alike with the closeness of the tie. Brothers and comrades have all things in common, all the rest only certain definite things, some more, others tice'atiMendS l^ss. And the ckims of justice difi-er also. The are more impera- claims parents have on their children are not the th7 tie* anT'^the ®^™® ^ thosc that brothers have on one another, greater is the in- nor have fellow-citizens the same claims as com- justice, if injustice j-ades. The Same is the case with all the other be committed. p/.-ii- <~,, ■, „ . . torms 01 iriendship. Bo too do acts of mjustice differ according as they are done to this man or to that, and grow in magnitude, the closer the friends are to whom they are done. For instance, to rob one's comrade of money is more atrocious than to rob a fellow-citizen, and to fail to help a brother is worse than to fail to help a stranger, and to strike one's father is worse than to strike anyone else. So justice and friendship grow side by side, holding good between the same persons, and within the same limits. But these associations differ. Brothers and comrades haTe all things in common, the rest of mankind not all things, but only certain definite things, some more, some less. With these different forms of association the friendships also correspond, some are more, others less, intimate, following the different forms of association. Similarly the claims of justice also are proportionate to the friendships. Brothers have not the same claims on one another that a father has on his son — ^nor hare citizens and comrades the same claims on one another but different, and the claims vary in degree, being more or less stringent as the friendships are more or less intimate. It is not equally unjust to rob a citizen and one's comrade of money, or to fail to help a stranger and a brother, or to strike one's father and any one else. The claims of justice grow with the friend- ship, holding good in the same cases and within the same limits. It is more grievous to injure a man who is dearer to us, who is associated more closely with us, who loves us more, than it is to injure one with whom the association is less close, the friendship less intimate. iii. — AU forms of association are but parts of the political union. But all subordinate associations are like parts of the political association. In them men band together with a The political union . ^ • i i , , , seeks to promote view to some Special advantage to get some one the interests of life of the elements of well-being, while the political ticulMLsociatfons Community also seems originally to have been some partial inte- formed, and to have been subsequently per- ^^^^' petuated for the sake of advantage as a whole. It is this which lawgivers also take for their aim ; and one defini- tion of justice is 'the common advantage.' Now all other forms of association aim only at some special part of our interest ; fellow-voyagers, for instance, are associated Bk. VIII. 11.] Translation. 459 to promote the interests of the voyage with a view to the making of money or some similar object. Fellow-sol- diers are associated with a view to success in ^^^g" f^meci^^for war, from a desire for wealth, or victory, or the pleasure still rank good of the state. The same is the case with ^^liH^nt.t fellow-tribesmen and 'fellow- parishioners.' But pleasure is an in- some associations would seem to be formed to ^redient in social , p . Ill well-being. get pleasure ; those, tor instance, who club toge- ther to offer a sacrifice or to get a dinner have the sacrifice or the dinner for their object. Still all alike would seem to be contained under the political association (for the political associa- tion aims not at present interest but at interest which looks to life as a whole). Under it men make sacrifices, contribute money for these purposes, giving at one and the same time to the gods their proper honours, and furnishing themselves with the means of relaxation and enjoyment. For the ancient sacrifices and gatherings seem especially to have been held after the ingathering of the harvest as a kind of first fruits, because it was at such seasons that men were most at leisure. Accordingly all forms of association seem but As the associations parts of the political union, and what is true about ^^^ th^Me'ndsMps the associations will hold equally about the cor- connected with responding friendships. *'^^™- But all associations, in which friendship and iustice have their sphere, are like parts of the political union. The political union exists to promote the general interest, for the sake of which society was formed at first and still continues to exist. But every association exists to promote some special interest or other, one to promote this, another that ; it is by means of associations that we each secure our own interests, and this is the ground of our associating with one another that we may get some of the essentials of well-being. And this, i.e. the common interest, lawgivers also make their aim, and say that that is just which is, to the common interest. All the other forms of association then, both as wholes, and the several parts of them, seek after some interest ; for example feUow-voyagera seek after success in their voyage, whether their object be money or something else ; feUow-soldiers aim at success in war, whether their object be money, victory, or their state. The same is the case with fellow-tribesmen and fellow- parishioners. Further some associations also have some form of pleasure for their aim and seem to have originated for the sake of pleasure, which is the case with those who join to make a sacrifice or a feast. The first are engaged in promoting a sacrifice, the second in promoting a common meal, and both sacrifice and meal are chiefly forms of enjoyment. Yet these are themselves also parts of the political association ; for these too, as promoting the common weal, are ranged under the domain of ' social science.' For this seeks not merely that which is expedient at the moment but also aims at that which, though not expedient at the moment, still ultimately will he so. It aims not only at present interest but at the interest of life as a whole, for which reason it takes into account sacrifices and social gatherings and pleasant convivial meetings and means of relaxation. For it was after the ingathering of the crops that social gatherings used to be made and sacrifices offered, being a sort of first fruits ; as men were most at ' leisure at these seasons. By such joint acts heaven was made piopitious to 460 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 12. them, and this they counted a gain, while they were themselves refreshed, and so undertook with new vigour their labours for the common weal. From this it appears that every form of aasociation — ^that which is formed for pleasure's sake no less than that which is formed directly for profit — has well-being for its ultimate object and aim, and consequently aU alike are parts of the political union. With these associations the friendships based on them accord ; the divisions which are to be found in the associations will be found in the friendships as well, and such as are the associations, such too in character will the corresponding friendships be. iv. — The different forms which, the political tmioii can assume. Now there are three forms of political constitution and three distorted forms which are, as it were, corrup- pouti^" nrire tions of them. The three legitimate forms of (1) kingly govern- political constitutions are kingship, aristocracy, Sacy. (fj '^til*o- ^"^^ t^e third which, as being hased upon a cracyi' and there is money assessment (rifj-rj), would have for its a d^torted form of proper name ' timocracy,' but which the majority have ordinarily styled ' a constitution ' (iroA.iTew) (par excellence). We must accordingly discuss political society. Of this there are three forms, kingly government, aristocracy, ' timocracy ' called usually by most writers ' a con- stitution ' par excellence, which has as its characteristic that it is based on an assessment of property ; men give money and get power, and so a timocracy is its appropriate name. V. — These different constitutions compared. Of these hingly government is the best, the worst is 'timocracy.' The distorted form of kingly rule is tyranny. i^'IfK'™* ^°^^ of them are the rule of one man, yet there king can pursue is the widest possible difference between them. most unselfishly rpj^g |. (. j^^ ^^ ^ j^j interests, the the public good, J. J.n • J. f /• l- T.- .L -r/ • and the opposite king, to the mterests 01 his subjects. He is of it, which IS jjQ ^j,yg jjjng -^^Q ig uot > self- contained ' and viousiy'the worst abundantly supplied with all goods; but he who form of govern- jg ^q t];iig position wants nothing more; con- ™™ ■ sequently he will be on the look-out not for his own interests but those of his subjects ; he who is not such is a mere ' pinchbeck ' king. Tyranny is in just the reverse position, for the tyrant pursues his own selfish good. Tyranny is clearly recognised as the worst form of government, and the worst is the opposite of the best. Of these constitutions the best is kingly government, the worst ' timocracy.' Such then are the different constitutions. The distorted forms, which are, so to speak, their corruptions, are — of kingly government, tyi-anny ; for they are both instances of personal rule, but there is the widest possible difference between Bk. VIII. 12.] Translation. 461 them. The tyrant looks after his own interests, the king the interests of his subjects; he is no king who is not self-contained and abundantly supplied •witi all good things. Such an one will not want to ab«)rb the goods of his subjects. Consequently he does not in his political measures, and in his public acts, look out for his own interests but only those of his subjects, as he wiU provide for his own interests not out of the public funds but from his own resources. And he who is not in this position may be a haphazard ruler but no true king. Tyranny, therefore, is the opposite of kingly rule ; for the tyrant pursues his own interests, and much more so even than the ' haphazard ' ruler. And the difference between him and a king is even more obvious as he is worse than the chance-chosen ruler. For this reason tyranny is the opposite of kingly rule, because the one is best the other worst, and the worst is opposite to the best. ■vi. — Order of the clianges in the constitution. Constitutions change as follows. One change is from kingly rule to tyranny ; for tyranny is a bad fofm of single rule ; accordingly it is the bad king who becomes Kingly rule dege- tyrant. Next, aristocracy changes into oligarchy ^^^^^ aristocracy through the badness of the rulers, who distribute into oligarchy, 'ti- the goods of the State contrary to merit, reserving ™°'J^^^_' '°*° '^'" all, or the great majority of good things, to them- selves, keeping offices always in the same hands, valuing the amassing of wealth above all things. The result is that but few get office, and they the baser sort instead of the very best. From * timocracy ' the change is to democracy, the two bordering close on one another ; for ' timocracy ' too means the rule of the multitude, and all are equal who are assessed at the necessary amount. Demo- cracy is the least evil of the distorted forms, as it is but a slight departure from the legitimate form of constitution. The above is the most ordinary way in which constitutions change, as the transition is in this way the smallest, and most easily made. Now the ordinary change in the forms of government is from kingly govern- ment to frfTanny : for tyranny is the corruption of personal rule, and the bad king passes into the tyrant. Of kingly government, then, tyranny is the perver- sion, but of aristocracy oligarchy : this comes about, when those who administer this form of government, assign themselves all the goods of the state in the teeth of desert ; if not aU the goods of the state then the giant's share ; their policy also is to entrust the same individuals perpetually with the management of the offices of the state, that they may bind them to themselves by ties of intimacy, and so be enabled by these means to batten on the public revenues. The result of this is that but few are entrusted with the management of affairs, and they the baser sort in place of the very best. Next of a ' timocracy ' the perversion is democracy : these border closely on one another, for a ' timocracy ' too means the rule of a multitude, and all who are assessed at the same amount, count as equal. Of all the perverted forms democracy is the least evil ; it departs but slightly from the ideal of n ' timocracy ' : it has more points in common Vidth it than points of difference from it ; it differs from it in dispensing with any property qualifica- tion, but it is at one with it in the equality it establishes (as in a ' timocracy ' all who have the same property qualification are on an equality) and in involving the rule of the multitude. 462 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 12. vii. — The counterparts of these different forms of government in the family. Similitudes and patterns of these different constitutions are to be found also in the family. The relation of a represented'^by^he father to his SOUS IS the Counterpart of kingly rule of a father rulc, as a father cares for his children. For this over Ma children. ^^^^^ ^om&r calls Zous ' father,' for kingly rule is a kind of paternal government. But in Persia the father's';'^ rule is tyrannical, for he treats his sons like In Persia this de- slavcs. Tyrannical also is a master's rule over fannyt which, how- his slavcs, for it is the interest of the master that ever, is the natural ig made the object in it. This would seem all relation of master •i. 3 e • -v i. i.x. -n • i. and slave. Tight and lair, but the I'ersian custom a wrong one, since those who differ should be ruled differently. The relations of husband and wife are aristocratical in character, for the man has in virtue of his superior merit a wife^iiveTnder^an ^'^S^^ *« ^ule, at least in thosc points that become aristocracy, which a man, while he gives over to his wife those degenerates into departments which suit a woman. But when a an oligarchy, if (a) ^ i i • . .^■^^ i • i the husband takes man lords it over everythmg, he changes his rule all authority into jq^-o ^.^ oligarchy. He does this in the teeth of his own hands, j . • • < r 1 • ■ -j. merit, and not in virtue ot his superiority. But sometimes wom en have rule, if they are heiresses ; in this case again rule is not based on merit, but on or (b) tiie woman -vfealth and power, as is the case in oligarchies, .. .- hand. * "^^^"^ Thirdly, the relations of brothers are like a ' timocracy ; ' they are equals, except so far as 3. Brothers make ,, t j-% • A j.i a 'timocracy,' there may be a dmerence in age. (Jonsequently if there be a very great discrepancy in age, their friendship is no longer the friendship of brothers. But democracies are mostly to be found in masterless houses — here all are on an equality — and in those homes rJtotdt'oTrl^t ^tere the ruler is weak, and every one has licence masterless houses. to do aS he pleases. It is to such changes as these that the different kinds of constitution are most liable. Each constitution is least liable to pass into the one opposed to it, but easily degenerates into its own perverted form. But there are also in the sphere of the household similitudes and, if one may say so, patterns of these constitu- tions. In households are to be seen kingly government, aristocracy, and so on. The relation of a father to his son exhibits the form of kingly rule, since the father cares for his children : and, on this ground Homer also calls Zeus 'father.^ Kingly rule has a tendency to become ' paternal ' government ; but ttah the Persians pervert into a tyranny, for they rule their sons like slaves. But the Bk. VIII. 13.] Translation. 463 rale over slaves is ' tyranny ; ' it is the master's interest that the slaves are always expected to promote, so that a rule of this sort over children is wrong-, whUe that which resembles kingly rale, has right on its side ; for a* a son differs from a slave, the rule exercised over them should be different also. So, then, the lolatiou of a father to his sons resembles kingly rule, while that of husband to wife is like aristocracy. The man rules by merit and as being the superior ; there will be an aristocracy then, when the husband reserves to himself what is suitable to a man and resigns to his wife the duties that befit a woman. But this relationship will step beyond the limits of aristocracy and degenerate into oligarchy, when the husband attempts to be master in all things ; this would be to go in the teeth of merit, and to rule no longer in virtue of his superiority. And sometimes women bear sway, when they are heiresses, and so surpass their husbands in wealth and power. Such a rule is not based on merit, but, as in oligarchy, on wealth and power. Such then are oligarchy and aristocracy in the household. The relation between brothers answers to ' timocracy ; ' they are equals, except so far as they differ in age ; for which reason, if they are very different indeed in age, there friendship is no longer of the fraternal sort, but resembles that of a father for his children. Democracy is mostly found in masterless households : here all are on an equal footing. It is found also in those in which the ruler is weak, and each member is, therefore, his own master. viii. — In. all these cases friendship and justice go hand in hand. Now in respect of each one of these different constitutions friendship seems to prevail just so far as justice does. There is friendship between a king and '^^ f^^ ^™^t' his subjects, resting on an overplus of benefits seension' between conferred by him ; for he is a benefactor of his * , ^™^ ^'^^ ^"^ subjects, if he is good, and takes care for their welfare, like a shepherd for his sheep ; for which reason Homer has styled Agamemnon ' shepherd of his people.' Such also is the position of a father, but he differs from the king in the greatness of the benefits conferred. He is the author of his children's being, which is ^^^ between a held to be the greatest of benefits, and of their children, a friend- nurture and education as well ; ancestors also ship resting on are treated with the same respect, for it is and^cknowiedged. natural for a father to rule his children, ancestors their descendants, and a king his subjects. But these friendships all imply superiority on one side, for which reason parents are also honoured ; and the claims of justice between the two parties are not identical but proportioned to merit; so it is on these terms also that the friendship is formed. And between a man and his wife there is the same friendship as subsists in an aristocracy. It is based on j„ ^„ aristocracy, virtue, the better getting the greater good, and and between hus- each what befits him; and this also is the frfendsMplmpfe character of the justice involved. suijerfority on the m 464 TAe Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. Vlli. 13. one side, defer- ence on the other. Brothers, and the members of a ' timocracy,' are equals ; and on this footing their friendship is con- cluded. But the intercourse of brothers is like that of corarades ; brothers are equals, and of the same age, and such are, as a rule, alike in feeling, alike in character. Like this is the regard which prevails in a ' timocracy ; ' the citizens should be equals and kindly to one another, they take it in turns to rule, and all rule alike ; such also is the character of the friendship. But in the perverted forms, as there is but little justice, so there is but little friendship either, least of all in the worst form; in a tyranny there is no friendship at all, or but very little. For where there is nothing in common between ruler and subject there can be no friendship, as there is no justice ; the relation is analogous to that between a workman and his tool, soul and body, a master and his slave. All these are well treated by those who use them, but there is no room for friendship or justice to inanimate objects ; no, nor even to horse or ox, nor towards a slave as a slave ; for the slave is a living tool, the tool a lifeless slave. Thus the master can feel no friendship to his slave as a slave, yet he may feel it towards him as a man. Every man is bound to recognise the claims of justice towards every one who can take part with him in law and contract ; consequently he must accord him friendship too so far as he is a man. The result of all this is that in tyrannies justice and friendship both alike find place to a verjr small extent ; but in democracies there is more scope for them, as equals have many things in common. In a ' tyranny, ' and between master and slave, there is no justice and no friendship ; there is no community of interests ; subjects and slaves alike are regarded as mere tools. But still the slave has, as a human being, claims on his master's recog- nition and regard. In a democracy friendship is more possible than in any other per- verted form of government. Such then are the different forms of association, whether in the body political or in the household. All these different forms of association may be accompanied by friendship, and are so accompanied, just so far as they rest on justice. Thus in the connexion of a kingr and his subjects the friendship rests on acknowledged superiority, the king having preeminence in respect of benefits conferred, since, if he is good, he benefits his subjects, and cares for their welfare, like a shepherd cares for his sheep. It is for this reason that Homer styles Agameinnon shepherd of his people. This too is the character of a father's friendship for his children ; it rests on recognized superiority. Yet it differs in the greatness of the benefits conferred, a father being the greater benefactor. He is the author of his child's being, and this is held to be the greatest of all benefits ; whUe, besides, he provides for its nurture and education. And simflsr claims are accorded to ancestors as well ; it is held nattiral for a father to rule his sons, ancestors their descendants, a king his subjects. So, then, all these friendships rest on a recognition of superiority, for which reason parents aie also Bk. VIII. U.] Trans lati07t. 465 hdi in honour. And the justice is such as the friendship is, involTing' not the same rights on either side, but superiority on the one side. A father's claims on his son are more urgent than a son's claims on his father, ifcice each ought to give in proportion to the other's merits. It is on this footing that the friendship hetweeii them stands. But it is not merely the relation between a king and his subjects that is accompanied by friendship, resting on recognised superiority, but aristocratical rale is so too. The better of the two parties receives the greater afEeotion ; and this is the character also of the friendship of husband and wife. The relation between them is aristocracy in the household. It is in virtue of his superior ;excelleuoe that the man rules, and because the better has a, right to expect the greater afEeotion. Consequently justice in this case also rests on recognised superiority. Thirdly, the relation of citizens in a ' timoeraoy,' like the relations of brothers to one another, is accompanied by a friendship like that of comrades, resting as it does on equality. Comrades are equals and of the same age, and such are, as a rule, alike in feeling, alike in character ; and these aie also characteristics of those who live under a ' timooracy.' Its citizens should be equals and kindly to one another ; they each take their share in ruling, and are ruled in turn. Friend- ship also in their case, and justice as well, are based on equality. Healthy con- stitutions then, and healthy relationships in the family, are attended alike by friendship and by justice. But in the perverted forms o£ government, as there is but little justice, so too there is but little friendship. And since of all the perverted forms of government tyranny is the worst, consequently friendship is not found at all under it or very little of it. For, where there is nothing in common between ruler and subject, there can be no friendship. There is no justice (or mutual respect for each other's rights) ; the relation between tyrant and subject, between master and slave is simply that between a workman and his tools, between soul and body. The tool is looked after by the workman, the body by the soul, but no friendship is felt in the one case or the other. There can be no friendship for inanimate things. Nor are any claims of justice recognized by those who make use of these things, since no such claims are recognized even towards ox or dog. In the same way a master can feel no friendship for his slave, a tyrant none for his subjects, inas- iniloh as they are slaves ; masters and slaves have nothing in common ; the slave is a living tool, the tool a lifeless slave. So far then as the slave is a slave, no ^ifeiendship can be felt for him, yet so far as he is a man friendship may be felt towards him. Every man must recognise certain claims of justice towards every other man, who can participate jointly vrith him in certain laws and ordinances, yor the participation in laws as regards one another, is what constitutes justice, and participation in justice brings in its ti'ain friendship as well. A tyrant, therefore, may feel friendship for his subjects so far as they are men, and so in this sense there can subsist a kind of dim justice and friendship. In democracy these are to be found more largely than in any other of the perverted forms of government : for equals have many things in common. 1X.--THE PEIENDSHIP WHICH RESTS ON TIES OP BLOOD. ; ■ i.— Distinetion 'between this and othei? kinds of friendship. Though all friendship thus involves ' common interests,' as we llave said, yet the friendships of blood relations and comrades form a class apart. For the friend- ^ektions spring ships of fellow-citizens, fellow-clansmen, fellow- less out of com- H u 466 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [BLVlItU. munity of interests vojagers, and all of that kind, are more like than other fnend- jegular partnersMps," resting, as they appear to do, on a kind of stipulation. With them may be classed also hereditary friendships. All friendship then rests on commimity of interests, as has been already said. But the friendship of relations and comrades alone does not rest on this basis. For the friendships which are concluded on certain set terms and on a regular agreement, like those of fellow-citizens, fellow-tribesmen, fellow-voyagers, and all similar ones, have the character of a partnership ; and with them may be classed hereditary friendships. ii. — Origin and character of parental affection. But the affection of relatives, in all its different forms, seema ultimately to be derived from the love of parent ^^renta love their and child ; parents love their children as a part partotlhemselvest ^^ themselves, children their parents as deriving their existence from them. Parents, however, know better the offspring they have given birth to, than their offspring know the source from which they are sprung : and this source of their being is more wrapped up in its offspring, than the offspring in that which created it. That which derives its origin from something else, is naturally dear to that which has produced it, a tooth for instance, or a hair, or anything else to the owner of it, while the source of its being is not dear to the thing produced, or at any rate much less dear. The that they are the Same result is brought about by the length of time authors of their over which the knowledge extends. Parents love ^'"^" their offspring directly they are born, but children their parents only after a lapse of time, when they have attained to understanding or perception. From this it is plain also why it is that mothers have the greater love. But the friendship of blood relations and of comrades is not based on any stipulation or agreement, but in the one case nature binds them together, in the other the accident of similarity of age and of interest in the same pursnita. We must now speak about the friendship of relations. This assumes many forms but is all to be traced back to parental affection — for by reason of their affec- tion for a common parent, or ancestor, brothers and other relations generally, are led to love one another. Parents love their children as being a part of themselvee, children their parents as deriving their origin from them, brothers brothers, as being sprung from the same parents. But parents know better that their children are sprung from them, than their offspring know, that they derive from them their origin ; and the cause, and the producer, is more wrapped up in that to which it has given birth, or which it has produced, than the creature is in its creator, or the offspring in that which has given it birth : that which has spmnj from anything is dear to that from which it has sprung, as a tooth, or a hair, is dear to its possessor, while its possessor is not dear to a tooth or a hair ; either, then, the cause is not dear at all to its effect, and the source of its being to that Bk. VIII. 14] Translation. 467 wHoh springs from it, and has no special connection with it, or if it has, has '"''" at any rate a less intimate connection than the effect has with its cause ; ^•'jisooordingly children love their parents less than they are lovlB. by them. S This is further evident from the time through which the connection lasts : parents love their offspring directly they are bom, but children their parents only W after an interval, when they have attained to understanding or perception. For li" , this reason mothers love their children more than fathers do, because they love them earher. Parents therefore love their children as themselves ; that which is sprung from them becomes to them, as it were, a kind of second self, differing Snly in having a separate existence, — while children love their parents because . they are bom of them. t iii.— Origin and nature of brotherly love. ^"* " Parents, therefore, love their children as themselves (that which IS horn of them becomes, so to speak, themselves f, Repeated, in virttieof its separate existence), while ^^er from °^r .children love their parents because they derive common blood, their being from them. But brothers love one f^ch draws them 11 . (. 1 together. another because of their origm from the same sources — their identity in respect of their parents identifies them with one another. Whence such expressions as ' same blood,' 'same stock' and so on, since there is a common element in their separate existences. Moreover their being brought up together, and being of an age, contribute greatly 1. ii • J. • 1 1 . .1 /. 1 i But IS mcreased by to tneir iriendship ; those ot an age seek out companionship in each other; and it is those who are similar in Joi^*. and simi- character that make bosom friends : this is the *" y " reason why the love of brothers is like that of bosom friends. But cousins, and all other relatives, derive their intimacy from this same source; being sprung from the same stock their intimacy is more or less close, accord- ^^l^^ ^Xough" in ing as the original source is nearer or further a less degree, of removed. ""IT" ^""^ °*''^' relations. Brothers love one another because they are sprung from the same parents. Their identity in relation to their parents creates an identity for them with one another, just as the identity of the root binds the branches one to another! whence such expressions as ' same blood ' ' same stock ' and so on. There is the same element running through each of them though many and diverse. The fact also of being brought up together and being of an age greatly |nlianoea their friendship ; those of an age love one another and 'tis those of like disposition that are comrades. Cousins, moreover, and all other relatives, .derive their intimacy from the brotherly relationship ; for, being derived from the same ancestors, they are in a way identified with one another. And relations are more or less closely bound together as the common ancestor of the race is nearer or more remote. Where the common ancestor is very remote, the conneO'< tion becomes enfeebled, being diminished at each stage of removal, tt H a 468 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 14. iv. — The love of children, to parents. The love felt by children for their parents, as that of men to ■ God, is based on goodness and a recognition of dren to parents Superiority. Our parents have conferred the rests on a sense of greatest benefits upon us. They are the authors favours received. n ,. -\ e 1-^.1 i 01 our being, and or our being nurtured ; and we owe to them our education too after we are born. The love of okildren towards their parents and of men to God rests on good- ness and a sense of superior merit ; parents are benefactors vrho have conferred' the greatest benefits, being, nurture, education ; but the affection of other relations to one another rests on equality. V. — Superiority of family afifection to all other kinds. Family affection has moreover pleasantness and profit in a greater, degree than the friendship of aliens can ever f?'iL 5'f ? liave, just because life in the family is lived more possesses every re- ' " •' quisite for friend- in commou. Brotherly love has all those charac-- ship m an en- teristics which are to be found in comradeship,' hanced degree. , , , . . 11 and nas them in a greater degree, where the brothers are good and alike in disposition, just because they are more intimate and start with having natural affection for one another from birth upwards, and also because those. who are sprung of the same parents, and are brought up together and educated alike, have more tastes in common ; while further, that proof of each other which time furnishes is in their case most complete and reliable. Thege elements of friendship are to be found proportionately in the case of other relations. And family affection has pleasantness and profitableness in a greater degree than that of those who are aliens in race, as family life is lived more in common, and the members of a family are more bound up with one another. Most of all is this true of brotherly love : it has all the characteristics which comradeship has, and has them even in a higher degree : and for this reason where brothers are good, and similar in character, they will love one another even more than comrades : they are more closely allied to one another, are more alike, have a natural affection for one another from then.' birth onwards, and have more kindred dispositions, as being bom of the same parents, and as having been educated alike. And the proof of each other which time gives is in their case greater and more sure. First, then, among family affections stands the love of brothers' ; all the rest are proportionate to their nearness in blood. vi.— The love of husband and wife. Affection between husband and wife is a natural instinct, for ^nan lives by nature in pairs even more than in civil society. A Bk. VIII. U.J Translation. 469 household is prior to, and even more absolutely indispensable than, a state, and the production of children is "a function which man shares with the animals. We between hns- In the case of the other animals the connexion natural instinott lasts only so long as is needful for this particular ^"^^ ^^ increased by 1 1 J T ± J.1 i tlie sense of mutual purpose, but men and women live together, not helpfulness, by merely with a view to the production of children, goodness, by the but also to supply their wants in life; their p°~" "^ <=hii- functions from the first are separate, and dif- ferent tasks are assigned to man and woman : consequently they help one another by bringing their several products into a com- mon fund. On these grounds there would seem to be both pleasure and profit in this form of friendship and on grounds of virtue also, • where husband and wife are good. They have their own specific ^^^xcellence and each can therefore take pleasure in the other's ' goodness. Children too would seem to be a bond of union be- tween the' parents, as is proved by the fact that the childless more readily separate ; children are a good common to both of them, and that which is common binds men together. Between man and woman, love seems a natural instinct. For man is even more disposed by nature to the production of children, than he is to living in a civil community, inasmuch as a household is even more indispensable than a civil govern- ment ; the production of offspring is also more widely shared by the beasts than is civil government. The former belongs to all animals, the latter to human beings alone : in other animals the connexion between the pair lasts only so long as is necessary for the rearing of offspring, but in the case of human beings the connexion is not formed merely to rear children, but extends to the supply of the other wants of life ; their functions are divided from the fli-st, and the duties of a husband are different from those of a wife ; consequently they help one another by bringing their several contributions into a common store. For this reason there seems to be profit and pleasure as well in this form of friendship ; and there will be good- ness and virtue also, if the two happen to be well-disposed : they have each their own special excellence ; and if each be good in the line of their own special excellence, this will lead them to take pleasure in one another. Children, too, seem to be a bond in maintaining affection of this sort, which is the reason why childless couples more readily separate : children are a good common to both parents, and that which is common holds together those who participate in it. vii. — The claims of friendship vary in these different cases. But the question of how a man should live with his wife, and generally a friend with a friend, is the same ques- mu , ■ tion as how they may live justly with one another; friendship vary a friend has different claims from a stranger, a with the closeness comrade from one who is merely a fellow pupil. tie. ^ °°"°^° ^"^ But the question how a man should live with his wife, a brother with a brother, and generally a friend with a friend, is the same question as how they iniiy do so 470 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. Vlir. 15. justly. Each kind of association is accompanied by its own special kind of justiee analogous to the friendship, which prevails in it, as we have several times stated. The claims which a friend has on his friend are not identical with those that a stranger has, or which a brother has, or a comrade, or a fellow pupil. X.— THE EIGHTS AND THE DUTIES OF FEIENDS. i. — General principle for their regulation enunciated. Now as there are three kinds of friendship, as was stated above, and as in respect of each of them the friends may The general prm- , ^ i- j> tj i • . cipie is that equals be on a looting ot equahty, or may he in a posi- shouid return tion of relative superiority and inferiority — ^fOr equal, unequals , i ii t i proportionate t^^o ^^n who are equally good may become amounts in each friends, or a better man may become friends with kind of friendship. ^^^ j^^^ ^^^^ . ^^^ ^j^-^ ^^^^ j^^^^^ ^^^^ ^^^ respect to those who are friends because they are agreeable to one another and with those who are friends for profit's sake — they may be equals in the benefits conferred, or the one may confer more the other less — equals should make each other an equal return in affection and in all else, unequals should make a return proportionate to the superior position of the one party. But as there are three kinds of friendship, based respectively on goodness, pleasantness, and profitableness, and as in respect of each of these three kinds soBi,6 friends maybe on a footing of equality, others on a footing of superiority and in- feriority (for men who aare the equals of one another in goodness in pleasantness in profitableness in some oases become friends, while in other cases the better her come friends with the less good), the general rule should be that equals should love one another equally, and make equal returns in all other respects, but that unequals should give and receive affection in amounts proportionate to their rela- tive superiority and inferiority. ii.— Limitation of the enquiry to friendships of interest. It is in friendship based on profit that recrimination and up- braidings occur either exclusively or at any rate Disputes do not most frequently ; and naturally SO. For those who occur between the ^--i , „ good, as they are are triends on grounds of excellence, are only anxious only to eager to do One another good, as this is the course another. ° °°^ dictated alike by friendship and by virtue, and between those who rival one another in this there is no room for recriminations and contentions. No one gets vexed with a man who loves him and does him good, only if the recipient be a man of honour he repays the benefits he receives. And even supposing one of the two to be the greater benefactor, if he gets what he desires, he will find no fault with his friend, as each pf thero is set op the good, Nov do quarrels oftep oqcur either Bk. VIII. 15.] T7'anslation. 471 between those whose friendship rests on pleasure. Both get at once what they desire, if they take delight in . each other's society. A man would be regarded f;;e.3rs,^''a; as ridiculous for grumbling at another for not they can withdraw pleasing him, when he might withdraw from his ^^^j'"'^ another's society. But friendship based on profit does give room for recriminations. As both parties make use of one another with a view to advantage, they always desire more than th'e interestX^as they get, think that they get less than their due, tiiey always want and find fault because they do not get, though "^''=^«ti'^"ti^«yset. they deserve it, as much as they want ; benefactors can never give as much help as the recipients of their favours want. But it is only in friendship, the motive of which is interest or in this princi- pally, that dissensions and fault-iindings between the friends occur, and natur- ally so. For those who are friends on grounds of virtue are anxious to do one another good ; this is the course dictated alike by virtue and friendship ; but where the friends vie with one another in this there is no room for charges and conten- tious. No one can get vexed with one who loves him and seeks his good : but if the recipient be a man of honour he returns the good he receives ; and even one who surpasses the other in his kindnesses, if he gets what he wants, will not find fault, with his friend ; each wishes for the good and to do good. Nor can those who are drawn together by pleasure often grumble at one another. Both get at once what they desire, if they take pleasure in passing their days to- gether : a man would be thought ridiculous for finding fault with his friend for not pleasing him, when he might please himself by going and passing his time with some one else. Accordingly neither does the friendship which rests upon goodness, nor does that which rests on pleasure, admit of grumblings and fault- But that which is based on interest is alone in being full of recriminations. For as the friends make use of one another with an eye to advantage, they always want more and think they get less than their due, and find fault because they don't get as much as they want, though they deserve to get it ; those who do them ser- vices can never help them as much as they want ; for those who are the recipients of favours always want more than their benefactors can do for them. {a) DIVISIONS OF INTERESTED FRIENDSHIPS. Now just in the same way as justice is twofold, one form of it unwritten the other embodied in written law, so there would seem to be two kinds of frpndship of S ''^ mV* be interest, one moral {i.e. resting to some extent divided into (i) on character), the other resting simply on con- "anted ; *b!it ""lo- tract. Now the most frequent cases of recrimina- venanted' friend- tion occur where men enter into a friendship on ^¥^^ ^into™^?a) one footing, break it off on another. By ' stipu- those that require lated ' friendship we must understand one which ™"t *'*|b, ^''^^J^ rests on stated terms — one form of it purely that 'allow a time commercial involving a transference of goods on ** S'^'^^' 472 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 15. the spot — tbe other more liberal in allowing time, but still im- plying an agreement for a definite return for a definite service. In this even the debt is recognised and is not questioned, stUl the delay it allows of has a friendly character. Consequently among some peoples no legal recovery is allowed in these cases, as they consider that those who have concluded a bargain on trust should abide by the result. But in ' moral ' friendship ship'ireiimi're- t^i^re are no stipulated terms— the gift or whatr turn, thougii not ever other service is rendered, is made as to a stiu"ixpeoted\nd ^i^iid, stiU the douor expects to get back an equi- disappointment valcnt, or cven a greater amount, supposing him- wiu be felt, if it ggif jjo(. ^Q jjg^Yo made a gift, but only lent a loan : IB not made. i • n i j? i • and if he comes out ot the transaction on less good terms than he entered it, he will grumble. But this comes about because, while all, or at any rate most men, wish to realise what is honourable, at the moment of choice, they choose what is profitable. Now, while it is honourable to do good without any hope of reward, it is profitable to be recompensed again. Now it seems that, just as justice is twofold, one form of it unwritten, an- other embodied in law, so too is it with, friendships of interest — there is a moral and there is a ' covenanted ' kind. We have an instance of covenanted interests whenever one man gives anything to another on condition of receiving a stipu- lated and definite return ; but a moral relation where one man makes a gift to another as to a friend, but still claims to get back an equal amount or even more, though not a stipulated or definite return ; but in respect of both forms of inte- rest recriminations and reproaches are apt to break out in the friendships based on them. Most frequently of all do they occur when one of the friends introduces into the transaction covenanted interests, the other moral considerations. Such friends are sure speedily to fall out. For, if the one confers an obligation in money and expects to be accommodated in the same way, and to get back just as large a sum as he has given, while the other confers a service of some other kind on him by way of repayment, they cannot continue in their friendship. But, again, of ' covenanted ' friendship one form is purely commercial, another, more liberal. For to refuse to give if one does not receive an equivalent on the spot, the goods passing there and then, is purely business-like ; but while giving, to allow delay in the repayment is more liberal. In this case, too, there may be an express agreement as to the terms of the exchange ; the one is a debtor, VoB debt being definite and not matter for dispute. Yet the delay allowed in the repayment makes the transaction at once more liberal and more friendly ; and so among some people no legal redress is allowed in these cases, nor can they sue one anotherv for debts, but it is considered that those who have made a bargain on trust oi^Mj to abide by the result. '. '■ But he who does a service to another on moral grounds, does the service on no stipulated terms, but gives the gift, or does any other service as to a friend ; still he expects to get back an equivalent amount or even more, considering himself not to have given a gift but made a loan, and if he does not get this back, he will grumble, yet not because it was a loan, but because the recipient was a friend. And this comes about because while all, or most men, at any rate, wish to do what is honourable, they yet choose what is profitable. Now to do good without any hope of return is honourable ; but it is profitable to be well done by; conse- quently men seek what profits them, but if they fail to get it, wish to be thought honoui-able. Bk. VIII. 15,] Translation. 47^ (i) GENEKAL EULES FOR EEGULATING THESE DIFFERENT CASES. **•■ Consequently he who can, should repay the full worth of what he has received (and must do so voluntarily); one has no right to treat a man as a friend i- Kepay in full, against his will. He should consider, then, that Zm^. ' '^ ^^' He made a mistake to start with and received a favour from one from whom he had no right to receive it — he ,?j "received it not from a friend nor was friendship the other's motive in conferring it — he must con- 2. Assume as little elude the transaction, accordingly, as if he had arpossfble."^ ™*^™ been served for a stipulated return ; and he should acknowledge that he would rep'ay if he could ; if he cannot, even the donor will not require it of him ; so that, if he is able he must repay. But he should ask, to start with, in what capacity and on what >; terms the donor confers the favour, that he may settle whether or no to enter on the transaction 3 Make mqmnes , , , at tne outset. on these terms. But such friends and all who do good to receive as much again, those who can should do good to with all their might, and should repay them the full worth of their services. For one ought not to drag by force into a true friendship those who do not wish it, but we should rather feel pain at having unwittingly received a service from one we ought not, that is from one who is not a friend and should seek how we may voluntarily wipe ofE disgraceful favours which we received involuntarily, through not knowing the character of our benefactor. In these cases good men will wipe them off, if they can, repaying them of their own accord, and concluding the business at once as if conditions had been stipulated ; but if they cannot do this, then they must acknowledge that they would have repaid at once, if they had been able ; but if they are absolutely unable to repay, not even the donors will ask back anything from them ; so that if they can, they must repay at once. But before receiving a beneiit each should look, by whom the benefit is conferred and on what termsj that so he may best .know whether to receive it or no. (c) HOW THE RETURN TO BE MADE IS TO BE ESTIMATED. But it is open to question whether the favour is to be measured by the benefit of the recipient and whether one should make one's return in accordance with this, ^\*' f^*"™ ^l^l or by the sacrifice made by the benefactor. On mated by the good the one hand the recipients declare, that what \^^^lf. f "^y t^e , , , . 1 f. T • n ,. • 1 benefit intended ? they have received from their benefactors is what it cost these little to give, and what they might have got from anyone else, thus making light of the favour; on the other hand, the donors assert that they have given the best they have to give, and vtiat the recipients could never, have got from any one else, 474 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. Bk. VIII. 16. and that it was given at a moment of danger or other urgent need. Must we not in answer to such questions In interested conclude that, since the friendship is one of inte- good receivedf ^ i"6st, the advantage to the recipient is the stan- dard of measurement ? It is he who makes the request, and the other will help him with a view to get an equal amount of help in return. The assistance given has been in amount just what he has profited by it ; consequently he must repay as much benefit as he has derived from it, or rather more, since this is the more honourable course. But in friendships founded on virtue, though there are no dis- putes, the intention of the benefactors is taken as In ideal fnendship ^ measure. The determining element in virtue the benefactor. and character is to be found in the intention. In this interchange of good offices between friends a difficulty meets us. Seeing that from great sacrifices on the part of the benefactor little advantage often accrues to the recipients of his favours, and from small sacrifices great advantage — for it may well be that though one has done much and spent much, one has done little good to one's friend — or the reverse may be the case — are we in returning the service to regard the advantage received, or the measure of the benefit conferred ? Another ground for asking the question is that the recipients contend that they have got from their benefactors what it was a very small matter for them to give and what they might have got from any one else, thus minimising the favours conferred : while the benefactors maintain juat the opposite. They say they have rendered the recipients the greatest services they could, services which they could never have got from others, and at jnoments of danger or other similar need. Accordingly the question is raised by which of the two we should measure the return to be made, by the advantage to the recipient or by the sacrifice of the benefactor. The case is not quite the same in every form of friendship ; in the case of friendship entered into for profit, the return wiU be proportionate to the benefit to the recipient or will even transcend it, as this is the more honourable course. It is the recipient who makes the request and the other helps him with a view of getting back an equal return ; the assistance, therefore, has been just as great as the amount of benefit which he has received from it, or rather more ; so in a general way it is right that he should measure the return by the benefit to himself for it is for the sake of this that he formed the friendship. But in the case of friendship which rests on virtue there are no dissensiong as there are in the kind where each wishes to turn the services rendered to his own profit, nor are the returns to be made measured by the profit to the recipients of the favours but by the intentions of the benefactors ; for the ohaiaoteristic feature in virtue and in character is the intention. Since, then, the two love each other for their virtue and they will measure the returns to be made by the inten- tion ; consequently friendship of this kind will be free from all dissensions, but the other two kinds are subject to them. ill. — "WTiy disputes occur in. ' rriendsMps of condescension.' Disputes also occur in ' friendships of condescension.' Each of the friends claim to have the largest share, and, where this occurs, th§ friendship is broken off, The better of the two thinks that BLVIII. IC] Ti'anslation. 475 the larger share is his due, as his goodness entitles him to more ; the more profitable in the same way thinks this ^ too : they maintain that the other party, being use- '^^^ superior party tuu , uii^^ 1 J J t3 considers that he less, ought not to get an equal amount, the con- should get the nexion (they urge) ceases to be friendship and larger share of pro- , ^ L -J. • T J.1 T, /. fit, as contributing hecomes gratuitous service unless the results ot more_ the friendship are distributed in proportion to the gerrices done : they consider that just as in a money partnership those who contribute more get more, so ought it to be in friend- ship. But the poor man and the inferior in . virtue hold just the opposite view. They hold he^shouTd°do so, that it is the part of a good friend to help his because his needs friends who are in need. What advantage (they ^^^ ^ ^^^^ ^"^^ ask) is it to be a friend of a good man or a powerful man, if one is to get nothing from it ? This is the case in friendships of condecension when a greater man is the frien d of the less, or a more profitable friend is friends with a less profitable ; the ^BMor party expects to get more in the one case on the grounds of his superior menti, in the other on account of his superior usefulness. For if, the one urges, each of the friends contributes to the extent of his powers, and gets no proportionate return, the connexion is a gratuitous service rather than a friendship ; conse- quently they say they ought to get not similar results out of the friendship but greater. They claim that, as in trade they who contribute more to the common stock get a larger share of the profits, so should it be in friendship. This is the case of the superiors, but the inferiors maintain that this is not what is due from friends in a superior position, but just the opposite. A good friend's part is to help his friends when in want. For what use is it, they say, to be friends with a good man, or a powerful, if you are to get nothing out of your friendship ? And thus finding fault with one another and each claiming to get the larger share, they yery easily break off the friendship. {a) PRINCIPLES ON "WHICH SUCH DISPUTES SHOULD BE SETTLED. After all, each of them seems to have reason in his claim, and each has a right to get ' more ' out of the friend- ship, only not ' more ' of the same kind, but the '^- ^^^ e^^ter be- , , , i.-, ■ i> • I 1 /> i neiactor should re- supenor ' more honour, the interior ' more profit, ceive more honour. For honour is the natural meed of virtue and of ^^ ^^° i^ ™ore in henefits conferred, while gain serves to-alleviate ^Tistance! ^' "'°™ distress. This same principle seems to hold good in public affairs ; he is- not honoured who brings no good to the commonwealth, for public property is ex- clusively given to the man who has benefited the (This principle thit °. ,, . IT "^ , _, honour must be common weal, and honour is public property. It given for services is not possible at one and the same time to make rendered holds money out of the commonwealth and to be Ts&us.)^ ^" '° honoured as well. No one can stand coming the worse oflf at all points, Accordingly to 9, public man, wjio suffers 476 The Moral Philosophy, of Aristotle. [Bk. VIII. 16. from a money point of view, the citizens give honour, while one who is opea to bribes gets money. It is the proportioning the return to merit that equalises and keeps up friendships, as we have already said. These, then, are the principles on which the unequal should conduct their intercourse; he who is benefited in point of money or in point of virtue must make repayment in honour, repaying the best he has to give. Friendship exacts the best a man can do, not exact proportion. An madi wm hav*e"to exactly proportionate return is not indeed possible be limited by the in all cases, for instance in the honour we pay to pLirto pay'' ^^'^^' *^^ ^°'^^ ^^ ^'^^ parents. Here no one can make a return which is really proportionate to the favour received, but he who serves them to the best of his powers is accounted good. For this reason it would parent'^\nd°'chiid ^^^™ '^°*' ^° ^^ allowable for a son to disown his considered in the father, though a father may his son ; a debtor is Se, a fSefh^ bound _to repay ; and nothing that the son can do the right to repu- Can wipe off what he has received, so that he mate tiie son not remains for ever a debtor. But those to whom a the son the lather. . debt IS owed are at liberty to remit it, conse- quently a father is at liberty to do so. Yet at the same time, we may presume, no father would part with his son unless that son were desperately bad : for, independently of natural affection, it is human nature not to discard assistance. But it may well be that the son, if he is bad, will shun giving assistance, or will not be anxious to give it. For the majority wish to receive favours and shun conferring them as being unprofitable. Let thus much suffice on these points. Each seems to have justice in his claim ; each has a right to get ' more ' out of the friendship, but not ' more ' of the same sort. The superior should have more honour given him, the inferior more of what he needs. Of virtue and of well- doing honour is the reward, while money profit or whatever else the man may need is the alleviation of poverty. The same seems to be the case also in public affairs ; it is to benefactors that honour is always awarded : he is not honoured who brings no good to the common weal ; public property is given to him who benefits the public and honour is public property. It is not possible at once to make money out of the public and to be honoured as well : the poor man receives money from the public purse, but is by no means honoured ; for no one can brook to come worse off at both points, both in respect of honour and in respect of money, but if he is to give the one he must receive the other. Consequently he who suffers loss from a money point of view in behalf of the public interest has honour given him, while he who is willing to receive bribes gets money. Proportionate returns equalise and keep up friend- ships, as has been said. On these principles unequal friends should conduct their intercourse ; the man who is benefited in point of money or virtue must repay in honour and repay to the extent of his ability. It is the best a man can do that friendship looks for, not an exact proportion. For »U caimot repay the full extent of the debt they owe, They cannot indeed Bk. VIII. 1 6.] Translation. 477 find a proportional equivalent in all cases. For instance, in the honours given to God or our parents, no one can repay the amount in full, but he who serves them to the best of his powers and as far as he has opportunity is «,ooounted a good man. For this reason it seems not lawful for a son to repudiate his father or to lefuse to listen to any of his requests ; for he is for ever his debtor and therefore ever bound to repay ; he has done for his father nothing equivalent to the benefits he has received from him. But a father niay repudiate his son, as benefactors may dismiss their debtors. Yet we may assume no father would ever part from his son, unless that son were superlatively bad ; natural affection constrains him not to do so, while at the same time it is human nature not to reject assistance. But if the son -w very bad, he will hate, or at any rate will not be anxious, to assist his father. Most people are willing to receive favours, but shun the doing them, as being unprofitable. Let thus much suffice on these subjects. BOOK IX.-CONCERNING FRIENDSHIP [Continued). INTEODUCTORY ANALYSIS. The break between Books VIII. and IX. is purely arbitrary. There ia no break in the connection at the point at which in our existing editions the Books are divided. No new subject is entered npon with the com- mencement of Book IX., scarcely a fresh division of a subject already begun. Book IX. opens with a continuation of the subject which was engaging our attention at the close of Book VIII., the question, namely, of the mutual rights and duties of friends and the circumstances under which disputes between them are apt to occur. The two cases, which have been already considered, are (1) Friend- ships of interest, in which it is difiicult to get the claims of each fully satisfied, and (2) those friendships involving superiority on the one side, inferiority on the other, where the difference in the claims to be con- sidered renders them hard to adjust. C. The third class of friendships in which disputes are apt to occur ia that of those in which the friendship is prompted by dififerent motives on the two sides — (1.) It is hard in these cases to assess the exact amoimt of the equivalent which should be repaid, since the benefits conferred cannot very well be expressed in terms of money-value. (2.) Such friendships being based, not on affection and admiration for one another's character, but on circumstances which are more or less accidental, if these circumstances alter, the friendships themselves aie apt to fade away since neither of the friends any longer derives that advantage from the connexion for which he looks. (3.) Dissatisfaction is felt most of all, if a friend's services are repaid in some other form than that on which he had set his heart. To take an extreme case. Imagine the harp-player's disappointment, when the tyrant, having promised him a reward for the pleasure he had given him, repaid him nothing at all : telling him by way of consolation that he had repaid him by the pleasures of hope for the pleasure of enjoyment which he had himself received. Here once more comes in the question with whom, then, does it rest to determine the amount of the repayment to be made f Should it be the original receiver or the original giver ? The question can hardly be 1% tntrodicdory Analysis : Book IX, 479 l, jnswered in all cases in the same way. The answer must to some extent ^depend upon circumstances. , ; (a.) In some cases, for instance, the giver agi-ees to leaare it in the hands of the recipient. This was what Protagoras did with his pupils. He gare them instruction first and then told them to pay him what they thought the knowledge they had acquired was worth. / (&.) The opposite course to this is followed by the majority of the ' Sophists.' They require payment in advance, and then egregiously " fail to fulfil the promises they have made. It may be that this is the only course that it is open to them to adopt. The knowledge they have , ^ to impart is for the most part so wor thless that no one would give them 7 lAy-^^- ■ anything for it, if it were not paid for in advance. (c.) By the good and by true students of philosophy the repayment to be made will be measured, not so much by the advantage received, as according to the intentions of the benefactor. ' The price of wisdom being above rubies ' the pupil will feel that, in giving his instructor the best he has to give, he is still making him too small a return. [d.) As a general rule it must be.left to the receiver to settle the amount he will repay. The giver of the favour has trusted to his honour and should abide by the consequences. Indeed in some countries no legal redress can be obtained at all, where the contract has been a purely voluntary one. The law holds, that a man who has trusted another, should end as he began. The principle which should guide the receiver in making repayment should be this. He should consider what he was prepared to give for the service he has received, before it was actually rendered him. He has no right to value it at what he is prepared to give for it now — for a gift already received loses value in our eyes. D. In the last place we are encountered by a number of questions of Camistrij when we are attempting to determine the respective rights and , duties of friends. Duties seem to conflict, and it is hard sometimes to determine their comparative obligatoriness. It may be asked, for instance, area father's claims upon us paramount? And again, are we bound to recompense a benefactor in preference to fulfilling any other obligation ? Of course such questions as these, like all other questions of moral casuistry, admit of no precise and accurate determination. All we can say is that, as a rule, the two following principles will be found to hold good. 1. Do not heap all your favours on the same individual. 2. Be just before you are generous. Yet the second rule has its exceptions. People may press their claims ungenerously upon us. Such we have a right to resist. Further, our duty to our parents takes precedence of all others. In this and in all other cases we should try to ascertain the exact line of conduct which the nature of the relationship prescribes and to act |ocordingly. Parents, for instance, have from the nature of the case a blaina upon us for support and for honour ; elders are entitled to marks of respect, brothers and comrades to frankness of speech and a readiness to impart to them, our relatives for interest in all family matters. When the conflicting claims are of the same kind, the decision between them is not very difiicult. The difficulty occurs where we have to decide between oompetiug claims of wholly difierent kinds, 480 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. Another question of casuistry, whicli demands an answer, is under what circumstances are we justified in breaking off a friendship once formed \ The answer will be dictated by the following considerations. (1.) When a friendship springs merely from interest or pleasure, it naturally comes to an end when the interest or pleasure is found no longer to exist. (2.) When one of the friends pretends to have an unselfish admiration for the other's chai'acter, but is really led into the friendship by motives of interest or pleasure, the discovery of such a fraud is a sufficient reason for breaking off the connexion. (3.) If one man makes friends with another believing him to be a good man, and this other turns out evil, the first is no longer bound, after such a discovery, to continue the friendship, that is supposing the second to prove irreclaimable. Yet he is bound, before renouncing the friendship, to make every effort to reclaim his friend. (4.) Where the one remains stationary, the other makes great strides in virtue, the friendship will, when a certain point is reached, naturally drop. The two will cease to have any community of tastes or interests. Still each is bound to retain a kindly recollection of their earlier intimacy. X.- STATES AKIN TO OE SUBOEDINATB TO FRIENDSHIP. I.— SELF-LOVE. It would seem as if our very idea of friendship and of our duties to our friends were derived from the relations in which a man stands and the duties which he owes, to himself. For friendship is ordinarily defined as consisting either (1) In an unselfish wish for, and effort to promote, the good of our neighbours ; or (2) In the desire for our friend's preservation and continued life ; or (3) In the taking pleasure in a man's company, or society ; or (4) In feeling sympathy with him in his sorrows and his joys. Now the good man, who must be taken, as so often observed, as the type or standard of human nature, exhibits each one of these dispositions in his own person, and in relation to himself. (1.) He wishes what is good for himself and desires it too with his whole nature. His wishes do not point one way, his desires another, but the two, and his whole nature, are absolutely at one. (2.) He desires his own preservation and continued existence. Above all he is anxious for the health and preservation of his intellectual nature, which is properly to be regarded as a man's true self. (3.) He is in perfect sympathy with himself, as his whole life is a consistent and harmonious whole ; while (4.) He takes pleasure in his own society, as he has nothing but pleasant memories and joyful hopes to occupy his thoughts. A life of virtue is, however, absolutely indispensable for the realisation of such true self-love, such friendly relations to oneself. The wholly depraved, far from being in this condition, don't even bear the semblance of being at one with themselves. They come at last, as a result of their vices, to loathe even their own existence. ' They cannot endure t.heJ Introductory Analysis: Book IX. 481 own- society. The bad of all sorts have little pleasure in their own company. They find little in themselves to draw out their affection, and consequently are little loved, even by themselves. II.- GOODWILL. This again has intimate relations to friendship. It differs from friendship, in that it is a feeling which may be felt towards strangers, and which need not be known to the objects of it. It differs from affec- tion in being destitute of warmth or strong feeling and in springing up sometimes quite suddenly, as, for instance, towards the combatants in the arena. Goodwill is thus a kind of passive, or inert, friendship, but developes into friendship, when matured by time and intimacy, and into friendship also of the true, or genuine, type. It is itself elicited neither by interest nor by pleasure but by some nobleness, or goodness. III.— UNANIMITY. This feeling is distinct from mere coincidence of opinion, being restricted in its sphere to those practical matters, where important public, or private, interests are at stake. Thus states are said to be unanimous, when they are agreed upon a course, or line, of policy, and are j^epared to carry it out in common. The citizens, again, of a state are unanimous when they entertain the same views for the conduct of their own public affairs. Unanimity may, therefore, be defined as a kind of ' political friend- ship,' and this is the accepted meaning of the term in ordinaiy parlance. It is a privilege, like friendship itself, confined, or almost confined, to the good. The bad, being bent on their own selfish interests, grow suspicious of one another and exacting in their requirements from one another, and this puts an end to all true harmony of feeling between them. IV.— THE RELATION OF BENEFACTOR AND BENEFITED. People often puzzle themselves why it should be that the bene- factor Ipves the recipient of his favours more than that recipient loves him. The popular explanation is that the two are in the position of creditor and debtor. Just as the creditor is more anxious for the debtor's safety and long life than the debtor is for the creditor's, so, they argue, the benefactor wishes for the safety and continued life of his client, that he may receive back his own with usury. Such an explanation is, indeed, founded on a dark view of human nature, yet it receives a certain confirmation from the conduct of the { --inajority, who are apt to be but little mindful of the favours they have X received. This explanation is, however, really inadequate to account for the fact —it does not account for the affection felt. The true causes must be sought deeper down. 482 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. 1. Probably a truer explanation is to be found in the analogy of the affection felt by an artist for his work, most notably by a poet for his own poems. This affection originates in the fact that a man's work is the proof, symbol, actualisation of his own existence. Our work makes us realise better, that we are alive and active ; and since existence is iu itself a good, that which gives reality to, and enhances our consciousness of, existence, must be good likewise. But a work done — a thing made — does this. Consequently the contemplation of such a work must afford pleasure and gratification. Now the recipient of our favours is in a way our ' work.' He is a monument of the activity of the benefactor; and so the benefactor can scarcely fail to take pleasure in that, which he has thus, iu a way, created. 2. The doing of favours gratifies that 'sense of nobility' which fumisfaffl us men with the noblest of all our pleasures. It must, thereforej"; be pleasant to a benefactor to have constantly before his eyes a monu- ment of the favours he has conferred, that is the living, actual presence of the person he has benefited. To be reminded, on the other hand, of the favours one has received is by no means an equal pleasure. Thus the recipient has not the same pleasure in the presence of his benefactor. 3. The feeling of having done a kindness carries with it a sense of superiority, which is iu itself a pleasure. So all that tends to keep this feeling alive is iu itself pleasant. 4. Whatever is attended with effort and difficulty gives pleasurf by the attainment of it. The conferring of favours involves trouble and effort, and so is viewed, when accomplished, with pleasure by those who have conferred the favours. v.— THE RELATION OF SELF-LOVE AND THE LOVE OF OTHERS. In examining the relation of self-love to the love of others, we are at once met by a difficulty. On the one hand self-love is denounced as a vice. It is the bad, it is urged, who are most actuated by self-regarding motives, and the worse a man is, the more selfish he is, the more entirely does he seek his own interests to the neglect of the interests of others. On the other hand, we have already pointed out how, in a certain sense, we are bound to be selfregarding, to be on terms of friendship with oneself, and how all the requirements of true friendship are best fulfilled in a man's relations to himself; so that in a certain sense it would seem that a man, both ought to be, and must be, self-regarding. The difficulty, however, and apparent contradiction — as is so often the case — will be got over by a more exact definition of the terms employed. When the many speak of a man as ' self-regarding,' what they mean by it is one who seeks to get for himself as large a share as possible of those things which, like money, honours, external advantages, are most prized by the vulgar. And since the lion's share for one of such advan- tages means loss to all the rest, the term, as thus employed, becomes properly a term of reproach. This is the popular use of the terra, con-espondiug with the popular view of what is desirable. Yet it is not the real, nor the proper, mean- Introductory Analysis: Book IX. 483 iug of the term ' self-loving,' ' self-regarding.' For what is a man's true Bclfr 'A man's life consisteth not iathe abundance o^the things which he possesses.' It is his reason, as we have already pointed out, which constitutes his true self. And so he who is truly ' self-regarding ' is the toan who provides, not for his material, but for his spiritual needs. Reason, not the passions, not his lower nature, is a man's real self ; and he whcf consults the interests of his reason, who gratifies his reason's dictates, that man must be pronounced truly ' self-regarding.' Now he who con- Bolts the dictates of his reason is the good man. He, consequently, deserves the title of ' self-regarding ' far more than the other. Only we must remember that, when we apply the term to him, we are using it in a widely different sense from that in which it is ordinarily applied, a Bense as different as is the life of reason from the life of passion, as is the effort after true nobility from the gratification of our lower desires. And since, by being ' self-regarding ' in this higher sense, a man will be at the same time promoting the happiness of others and the good of his country, it will follow that a good man ougM to be ' self regarding,' a bad man ought not, since this latter, by being self-regarding in his way, not only does harm to others but even to himself as well. And, though the good man gives up for his friends and his country honour, wealth, even life itself, he cannot for all that be counted a loser thereby. Rather he is gaining for himself the best of all rewards, the ' reward of having acted nobly, a reward worth more to him than all hesi4es. Yes ; even when he surrenders in his friend's favour the very chance of doing noble deeds he is not without his reward. He is a gainer of a still deeper sense of inward satisfaction. In this way the most absolute self-surrender becomes identified with the most absolute ' Belf-regard.' To be ' self-regarding ' in such a sense as this, securing, as it does, at once our own highest good and the good of others, is fitting and right. Oaly it must be remembered that it is a spirit as widely removed as possible from that selfishness, which by the vulgar is so often confounded with true self-love. XI.— THE RELATION OF FRIENDSHIP TO HAPPINESS. This last subject connects Books VIII. and IX. with the main current Bf the Treatise. If it can be shown, as Aristotle attempts to show, that friends are a neeessary element in true well-being, then the discussion of friendship clearly becomes germane to the definition of happiness and its constituent elements, which forms the main subject of the treatise. • The discussion opens at once with the question whether the presence of friends is, or is not, indispensable for the completion of the ideal of perfect happiness. The question is first approached from a dialectical point of view. On the one hand many maintain that friends are not required, on the ground that a man who is perfectly happy having, ex hypothesi, all goods at his command can have no possible call for, or need of, friends. Friends it is urged, are absolutely superfluous for him. _ On the other hand, these arguments are met by the following oon- Biderations ; I I 2 4B4 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. (1.) Friends are admittedly among the greatest of all goods. What right have -we, it is asked, to leave this feature out of our picture of ideal, or perfect, happiness % (2.) A happy man requires to do acts of benevolence, as in them, at least in part, his happiness must consist. There are no so appropriate objects for our benevolence as friends. Thus, from this point of vieWj friends will be requisite. (3.) Nature does not intend man to live alone ; he is naturally social. So his natural longing for society will be unsatisfied, if we do not accord him the society of friends, and his nature would be so far maimed and incomplete. (4.) It is not difficult to see how the mistake arose of supposing the happy not to require friends. It grows out of the unworthy conception which the world has formed of friendship. The only form of friendship which the world recognises is that which is based on interest. Since the happy do not require friends who will do them good turns, it has been hastily assumed that they do not require friends at all. That this is not really the case, that good friends are essential to perfect happiness, is more than plain from the following arguments, (1.) The sight of the good acts of ou.r friends excites in us a pleasure- able excitement, being indeed almost equivalent to the performance of good acts ourselves. And since in this — as we saw at the outset of this treatise — our happiness, or well-being, consists, the sight of friends doing well, which is almost equivalent to it, must also be a good. (2.) The performance of good acts is rendered easier, more pleasant, and consequently more continuous, by their being done in company. Since, then, the presence of friends has this effect, and to pass his time in well-doing constitutes man's true felicity, on this ground also friends will be necessary. (3.) Good friends further encourage one another in acquiring habits of virtue and so promote one another's happiness. We may, however, discover arguments reaching deeper into the nature of things, and approach the question from a more metaphysical point of view. Whatever is naturally good in itself is good and pleasant to the good man. Life is naturally good, so life is good and pleasant to a good man. But, since life is defined as a ■power of sensation, and thought and powera are only apprehended by the exercise of them, therefore sensation aa^ thought, as constituting life, must be good to a good man. Further, each act of sensation and thought is accompanied by a consciousness of it. Therefore this consciousness of sensation and thought must be good to a good man. This consciousness of sensation and thought we enjoy in the presence of friends. Therefore this presence must be a good. And so it is indispensable to the happy man, as he would otherwise be want- ing in an element of happiness which he might enjoy, and so fall short of perfect bliss. Introdtictory Analysis: Book IX. 485 *■' Xn.— THE NUMBEE AND THE USES OE^PEIENDS. But, if friends are tlius essential to complete happiness, are we, there- fore, to conclude that we should make as many friends as we possibly can, or should their number be limited ? Their number should clearly he limited, for 1. In the case of interested friendships, it is inconvenient to have to return a great number of good offices ; and life is not long enough to enable us to do so. 2. A limited number of pleasant acquaintances are enough to give a spice to our lives. 3. Even of the good we may have more than enough. We may make our friends so numerous as to mar, that roundness or completeness which the perfect life should exhibit. The exact number of friends permissible it is indeed impossible to fix, as impossible as it would be to settle the exact number of citizens who should go to make up a state. All we can do in either case is to determine certain limits. In the case of friends tlie limit will be found in the largest number that it is possible to live with comfortably. There are other considerations which tend also to limit the number of possible friends. (1.) Friends, as we have already seen, should live together and live in harmony. Where the circle is made unduly wide, this condition becomes very difficult to fulfil ; they are sure not all of them to share in one another's tastes and interests. (2.) Besides, if our friends are very numerous, their claims on our sympathies in their joys and their sorrows will be found to clash. (3.) Friendship, being an intense feeling, is necessarily very restricted in its range. (4.) These arguments receive confirmation from the facts of actual life. Men break themselves up into little bands of comrades, and the most celebrated friendships, such as those of Damon and Pythias, of Pylades and Orestes, have been restricted only to two. You may be, and ought to be ' civil ' to the whole world, but to be content with a few real friends. T Lastly, since friends are thus indispensable under all circumstances, a question has been raised in what circumstances they are most indis- pensable. Do we require them more in prosperity or in adversity 1 It would seem as if in prosperity they were more honourable, in |;j||dvei-sity more needful. J t; In adversity they are a comfort to us ; they share our load of grief ; iSiid, by sharing it, make it lighter to bear, and their very presence, being a delight to us, drives away part of the pain. And yet a good man in adversity will view their presence with mixed feelings. Though he is pleased to see them, he is grieved that the sight of his sufferings should cause them pain, and will be careful to inflict as little pain upon them as possible. Above all he will eschew encouraging them^ to make lamentation with him, for he is not fond of making lamentations himself. In prosperity the society of friends adds to our pleasure, and theif delight in our good fortune adds zest to pur o-wn. 486 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle, These considerations will furnish us with a code of rules for the uses to which we may put our friends. We shall summon them eagerly to share our good fortune, reluctantly to witness our misfortunes. When they are in adversity we shall voluntarily proffer our services, but shall be shy of intruding ourselves on their prosperity, lest we seem to be seeking for favours. Still, if good offices are offered us, we shall not decline them, lest we seem, as some- times happens, discourteous. In the ordinary course of life — as distinct from either prosperity or adversity — what friends chiefly desiderate is constant intercourse. Above all, men seek the participation of their friends in those interests, and those pursuits, which they deem the most important and to which they chiefly devote their lives. And thus it comes about that, while the intercourse of the evil ends only in confirming them in evil, the friendship of the good carries with it increased encouragement and greater strength in the performance of virtue. TBANSLATION. ' . — ' — X,— THE RIGHTS AND DUTIES OF FRIENDS {Continued). iv. — Disputes in Friendships of dissimilar aims. In all friendships, prompted on the two sides by dissimilar motives, it is the principle of proportion that , .1 . p ■ J T± 1 • 1- Quarrels occur places the two mends on an equality and mam- ,,ri,ere one or both tains the friendship, as has been already stated ; fell to get a pro- • , -ii. I. p-M-i. J.I portionate return. just so, m the sphere ot civil intercourse, the shoemaker gets for his shoes a proportionate return according to their worth, and so does the weaver, and so do all other artificers. In these cases, however, there has been provided a common measure in the shape of coined money, to which all these different products are compared and by which they all are measured. But in love affairs it sometimes happens that the „ ^, i, f i lover will complain because, though he loves to to get™he return distraction, his love is not requited; and yet it they severallywisli may well be, that he has nothing loveable about ' him. On the other hand the object of his affection will often grumble because, though formerly the lover made all kinds of promises, he now performs nothing. Now such cases come about, when the one loves the object of his affection for the pleasure he gives him, and this latter loves his lover from interested motives, and neither the one nor the other gets what he desires. For since the friendship was prompted simply by these motives it drops through when these objects are not gained ; it was not their friends themselves that the two severally loved, but certain attributes they possessed, which attributes are not enduring; consequently the friendships are not enduring either. But the friendship that is based on character, which is essential, is, as we have already said, lasting and permanent. Another cause of quarrel occurs when friends get by way of recompense something different from that on which they have set their heart; it is almost as bad as getting nothing at all, whea 488 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 1. one does not get what one desires ; we see this by the case of the tyrant and the harp-player, the tyrant promising Le^ntfeturrfrim *« ^^^^^rd him, and the better he played, the more that on which they he promised him; hut when in the morning he have set their came to Bsk for the fulfilment of his promises, hearts. . T ' the tyrant answered he had repaid him pleasure for pleasure (the pleasure of hope for the pleasure of enjoyment). Now if each of them had wished for pleasure, this would have been all very well; but if, as was actually the case, the one wanted pleasure and the other gain, and the one got what he wanted and the other did not, the result of the transaction could not be satisfactory. What a man happens to want he sets his heart upon ; and it is to get this and nothing else that he is ready to give what he has to give. Let us continue to speak about friendship, and state what we have to say in ad- dition to our previous remarks. In friendships based on equality friends should repay one another equal amounts, but in friendships where the friends are unlike one another, proportionate amounts, as has been already stated. It is proportion that sets friends on an equality in all civil transactions. The cobbler gets for his shoes not shoes, but their worth, that is a proportionate amount of some other commodity, as has been explained at length in the 5th Book; the same is the case with the weaver and all similar artificers ; f oif this is what maintains civil rela- tions, the giving and receiving of proportionate amounts, according as one is in need and another has a superfluity. In civil ti'ansactions money serves for a common measure, to which all commodities are referred, and by which we estimate the amounts to be given and the amounts to be received. But in moral and friendly relations there is no common measure by which dissimilar services may be esti» mated. For this reason such connexions aie always liable to disputes, as is the case with love affairs. Sometimes the lover will find fault with his darling, because, though he loves to distraction his love is not requited, he being, very likely, not deserving to be loved ; accordingly the darling on his side will often find fault with his lover, because he formerly promised him everything, and now accomplishes nothing. Now such cases occur when the one is prompted to love by pleasure, the other by interert, and then the one does not turn out agreeable, the other does not turn out profit- able ; for as the friendship was prompted by these considerations it is broken off, when they are not realised. The two did not love each other, but each other's at- tributes, which, being in their nature transitory, destroy the friendship also along with them when they fail. But those who love one another, and one another's characters, as is the case with the good, are steadfast in their friendship. They love each other for their own sakes and for nothing else; and remaining true to themselves they preserve the friendship at the same time. And friends of unlike character also quarrel when they get from their friends something else than what they desire. It is as bad as getting nothing when one does not get what one wishes for ; this was seen in the case of the tyrant, who promised the minstrel that the better he sang the more he woiild give him, and when the minstrel asked the next morning for what he had promised him, said he had given him pleasure for pleasure. If then each of them had wished for pleasure, the transaction would have been perfectly satisfactory ; but if, as was the case, the one wanted enjoyment, the other gain, and if the one got what he wanted and the other did not, the result of the transaction could not be satisfac- tory. For it is to get what he wants that every man is ready to give what he happens to possess. Bk. IX. 1.] Translation. 489 GENERAL PEINCIPLES FOR FIXING THE AMOUNT OF THE REPAYMFiNT IN THESE CASES. But whose business is it to settle the amount to be repaid — the original giver's or the original receiver's ? It would seem as if the original giver entrusted it ^; Sometimes the to the other, and this is what they say Protagoras X'^l^ reedver' to actually did. For when he gave any instruction, ^^tti^ t^e value of 1 1 i 1,'j !.• •! 1 i • ii 1 e the service after he used to bid his pupil determine the value of \^ \^^ received it. the knowledge he had acquired, and used to accept that amount in payment. But in such cases some like the principle " Let the labourer get his stipulated hire." But those who take their money beforehand and then fail to do what they said they would, on account of the extravagance of their promises, are justly liable aoife°bfthr^Soph- to reproach, as they don't perform what they had ists) a fixed pay- 5 -agreed to do. But this is what the Sophists are, |^'°dTanc°e''""' ™ perhaps, compelled to do, as no one would give them money for the knowledge they have actually acquired. •Such, then, as they fail to do what they received their payment for, are justly held in reproach. Again, in those cases where there is no agreement as to the service to be performed, those who perform ser- vices for their friends' own sakes are, as we have ^- Sometimes the already stated, not likely to find fault, this being confessedly inade- the character of the friendship which rests on I'^'S'*^. l'"* ^^^ ^^^^ ■ , -n , ,1 , .1 1 • 1 the receiver has to Virtue. But the return must be made in accord- give. ance with the intention of the donor, as befits a friend and virtue. And the same, it would seem, should be done to those who impart philosophy ; the value of this cannot be measured in money, and no adequate price can be given for it. "We should repay them, I presume (and this is sufficient), all we can give, just as we do to the gods or our parents. But, if the gift is not of this character, but is made for a stipu- lated return, the return made should be, if pos- ^^^^^j sible, such in amount as seems fair to both sides ; rule the original and, if this cannot be secured, then it would seem receiver will have ,' ,1 , . 1 • • 1 • 1 ij to fix the amount not only necessary that the original receiver should to be repaid, and settle the amount, but just as well ; for if the other « ^^ fe™^* ^^ gets from him an amount equivalent to the bene- fit received, or the amount which he would have been prepared to Pfive for the pleasure he has received, he will get from him what is 490 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 1. fair. This is what also seems to occur in purchases. In some countries there are laws forbidding suits for the enforcement of voluntary contracts, on the ground that, where one man has trusted another, he should settle with him on the same terms on which he entered into the transaction. The law further considers that it is more fair that the man in whom trust has been reposed, should settle the terms of repayment, than that the man who trusted him sliould do so. For in most cases those who have a thing do not value it at the same as those who wish to get it ; each is inclined to think his own goods and what he has to give very valuable. Any way the return made will be that which the Only he should fix Original receivers fix. But they ought, perhaps> it at the amount not to value it at what it appears to them to b^ he would have -wrorth, wheu they have got it, but at what they given before he re- ' , •, i e \l- -i. ceived the service, would have valued it bctore getting it. Thus, then, in these friendships of diverse motives it is proportion and a recog- nition of merit that is looked for. Still it is a question whose business it is to settle the proper requital, the original giver's or the original receiver's. It is urged the original giver seems to entrust the receiver with settling the proper retunj as was Protagoras' custom. He used to take payment from those who went to him for instruction, not fixing the amount himself, but bidding them estimate what they thought the knowledge they had acquired, was worth, and then accepting that amount. But in such transactions some are contented with the words ci Hesiod — " Let the man get his fitting reward." But mercenary folk, who enter into such arrangements on business principles, ask for more than this, and sometimes also when they have got their money, and have promised that they will repay it in kind at once, they fail to repay it and perform none of the things they undertook : and they are justly found fault with, because their promises outrun their performances. For this reason the Sophists, also, do not give lessons imtil they have received the fee for their instruction, because no one would in any other case have given them money for the things they have learnt from them, as they are worthless ; having promised to teach great things, they thus get their pay, and end by teaching most worthless stuff. These, then, since they fail to do that for which they have been paid are justly liable to reproach. In those transactions in which there is no agreement as to the return to be made, or the service to be rendered, those who benefit their friends unselfishly and sacrifice their own property for the sake of their friends, which is the case with the good, we have already said, are uncomplaining. This is the character of the friendship which rests on virtue ; and the return must be made in ac- cordance with the intention of the benefactor ; for this is the distinguishing feature alike of friendship and of virtue, as has been explained above. Such too is the character of the intercourse based on philosophy ; the teacher of philosophy does not ask from his pupil either money or honour to a definite amount, nor can there be any adequate requital for philosophy either in money or in honour ; but he looks to the wiU of his pupil ; he considers the service and the return adequate, if the disciple does the best he can ; and this is also the nature of the claim that the Gods and our parents have upon us. Those, then, who gratify their friends unselfishly measure in this way the amount of the requital to be made. But those vvhg perforai a service for a stipulateii rewarcl, whether they dg sofgr Bk. IX. 2.] Translation. 491 interest or for pleasure, will give suoli an amount and will receive sucli a return, as may seem fair to botli of them. In this way it will be brought about that their intercourse shall be free from all reproaches. But_if this cannot be effected and they cannot both agree on the proper return to Be made, but one or other or both of them object, the returns must necessarily be regulated in accordance with the decision of him who receives the benefits. For, if the one says that he is willing to give so much for such and such a service, and the other renders that service ou these terms, the one will give what he agreed that he would give, and will repay the service by giving pleasure or some other advan- tage, while the other is precluded from grumbling since he has got what he judged it fair that he should get. This is not only necessary and relieves the transaction from all trouble, it is also fair as weU. For if a man gets what he wishes, no injustice is done him ; and this seems to be the way in which matters are regulated in buying and selling ; the purchaser fixes the price and measures it by the profit, or the pleasure the article will bring to him, and says the thiug he wishes to buy is worth so much to him. In some countries more- over there is a law, that no suits shall lie for the enforcement of voluntary con- tracts, and that the parties shall not have recourse to any other judge in such covenants, or any other law, than the terms of the contract ; but as a man has trusted his neighbour and has given him his goods on trust, he must finish the transaction on the terms of his original agreement. Such nations consider it more just that he who has been trusted in the first instance should settle the amount of the return than the man who has trusted him. Otherwise, he who trusted his companion, wiU decide for the receiver, but no one is a trustworthy judge in his own cause. For as a general rule, each thinks that what is his own, and what he has to give, is worth a great deal. But he whb in the first instance was trusted to settle the return for the benefits he received, even though subsequently the man who parted with his goods to him, give him trouble on the ground of being inadequately recompensed, can still judge aright if he carry out the original conditions which the other assented to and he agreed upon : for he wiU not do what he now thinks right after having received the service, but what he valued it at when he had not yet got it. V. — Questions of casuistry stated and solved, (a) QUESTIONS STATED. The following kind of questions are also attended -with difficulty. Ought a man to give up all to his father and obey him in all things, or, when he is sick, obey '^'^^^ F*^ ^ ™™" his doctor, and when votmg lor one to serve the whicL it is doubt- office of general, vote for the man most skilled f"! '^^° y^ ^^^ o o- -T I 1 n n 1 ■ i prior claim upon m war? Similarly, should a man do a service to us. a friend in preference to a good man, and repay Ms benefactor a kindness in preference to giving money to a comrade, if it be impossible to do both ? Thus much on these points. But we must look also into the following ques- tions. Must we give all things and obey in all things our most honoured and our dearest ones, or are there some things which we shall give to those less honoured and less loved in preference to those who are more honoured and more loved ? For instance, shall we obey our father in all things, whatsoever and whenever he command us, or not always ? but, when we are sick, obey our physician, when we are at war, obey one fitted to command ? And ought we to vote for as general not our friend nor our father, but one who is skilled in war \ 492 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 2. In the same way to which of the two ought we to do a service, our friend or a good man ? And should we do a favour to our comrade or repay our benefactor and one to whom we may owe a debt if it is not possible to do them both a good turn ? (J) EXACT ANSWERS ARE IMPOSSIBLE. Is it not the case that to determine this class of cases exaotly „ , . is by no means easy! They are subject to all dUCII C^S68 01 C3.S11- -j* y»T*r¥» • • istry are too nu- kinds and Varieties oi dmerence in magnitude merous and intri- ^^^ pettiuess, in point of houourablcness and cate to be exactly . '■ . ' '■ solved. imperativeness. Now to settle all such oases individually and exactly is not easy. They are subject to all kinds and varieties of difference and they differ from one another variously in magnitude and insignificance, in honourableness and necessity. They are not all of them equally small or great, honourable, or necessary. Sometimes to tend a friend seems more imperative than to tend a good man, sometimes it is more honourable to do a service to a benefactor than a friend, sometimes the reverse ; hence it is not possible to lay down an exact rule on each one of these points. (c) TWO GENERAL RULES STATED. But that we ought not to heap all things on the same individual is clear enough. Also we should as a rule repay everytMng tootle benefits rather than confer favours on our com- same individual, radcs. For instance we should repay a debt to ^' w ^i^c ^°"^ the man to whom it is due rather than make a debts Defore you give away. present to a comrade. This is plain at any rate, that we should not give all things to the same individual, but as a rule it is more just to repay our benefactors the benefits they have conferred upon us than to gratify our comrade, for instance we should repay a debt to one who has lent us money, rather than make a present to % comrade. id) EXCEPTIONS STATED AND CONSIDERED, ' But, perhaps, not even this always, for instance if a man has' . , , been ransomed from robbers should he ransom 1. A father may , . , , , i u i have superior his ransomer, whoever he may be, or should he claims even to a repay him, if he has not indeed been captured ^ "■ but asks for repayment, or should he not ransom his father in preference? (Surely this latter) for it would seem as if one should ransom one's father even before oneself. As has been already said, then, though generally speaking we should repay a debt rather than bestow a favour, yet if the gift surpass the repayment of the debt in honourableness or obligatoriness,, we must incline rather to it : for sometimes it is not even fair to requite, a favour^ as in the instance where one man does a Bk. iX. 2.] Translation. ' 493 favour to anotlier knowing him to be good, while he to whom the return is to be made is, as he believes, a bad o,. , nji«2. Cases in which man. Sometimes we are not even bound to the repayment of repay a loan by another loan. A bad man knows favours is not oWi- very well that if he has lent his money to a good ^^ ™^' man he will get it back again, but the other has no expectation of getting his back from a bad man (and is not, therefore, bound to lend it). If this is in truth- the case, the claim, is no longer an equal one ; if it is not the case, but the one holds it to be the case, still we shall not consider his conduct strange. But I say as a general rule, because it may happen that the opposite course of oonduot is the more .just. For instance, supposing a man to have been ransomed from robbers, is he bound to ransom his ransomer whoever he may be, in return, or to repay him, if he has not been captured but asks for the money back again, or to ransom his father ? Surely the latter, as it would seem that he should ransom his father even before himself. Therefore it is that we said that as a general principle and as a rule we should pay a debt rather than gratify one whom we love. But if the gratifying our friends is so necessary or so honourable as to outweigh justice to our benefactors, we must incline rather to that side, since it is not always just even to recompense our benefactor if that benefactor be a bad man : for instance if a bad man has lent money to a good man, the good man wiU not be bound to lend money to the bad, for the one lent his money with the full knowledge that he would get it repaid, but the good man having no expectation of getting it back again does not act unjustly in not lending it. Whether then the good man is right in thinking about the bad man that he will be evil also in this, and so refuses to return his favour, he acts reasonably in refusing to advance the loan ; or if this is not the case, but he still thinks that it is, and consequently does not requite him by an equal service, in this case also he does not miss justice by much. For it is not fair that what- ever a bad man gives a good, this he should also get from him. -The gift of the bad man is not equal to that of the good, even though each does the same Berrioe to the other. The good man's gift becotties the greater by the reputation of the giver. Therefore it is that we have said, we must not always repay our benefactor in preference to conferring favours on our friends. (e) THE GENEEAL PEINCIPLB IS 'RENDER TO ALL THEIR DUE.' As we have often already said, discussions about feeling and fictions admit of precise definition only to the degree to which the subiect matter of which they ^^\ °^, *'''*' ^ ° . . "^ ■' on all other moral treat, admits it. That, then, we must not give subjects, cannot be the same service to all alike, and that we must laid dowmvith pre- . . , . „ ' oise accuracy. not give everything to a father, any more than we must sacrifice everything to Zeus, is obvious enough. But since parents and mothers, comrades and bene- factors have different claims upon us, we must ^f^^''''^™"/ iiief^'t render to each their due. And this is what men classes have differ. seem actually to do. To marriage feasts they ent claims upon us. ..,,,.•',,. . .I ° 1 , , •' Relatives are called invite their relations ; smce they are bound by in on occasions of the tie of a common race they naturally take family interest. 494 "The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 2 their part in all acts connected with it ; for the same reason men hold that relatives above others should attend funerals. Parents would seem, thus, to have a special claim upon ua for maintenance since we owe to them our own j Parents are enti- and those who are the authors of our being it is to^honour*-^"^ ^^ more honourable to provide for in this way even than to provide for ourselves. And honour too should be paid to parents as to" the Gods, only not all honour. Father and mother for instance have not a right to the same honour, nor to that which we pay a philosopher or our general,' but to that which befits a father and to that similarly which befits a mother. To every elder we should pay the re- lespec , gpggj; ^Q TY^ich their age entitles them, by rising up in their presence, making way for them at table and in other similar matters. Comrades on the other hand and brothers have a right to plainness of speech and to share our Comrades to frank- ^^^g ^-^^ ^g^ rp^ relations, to fellow-tribes- ness- and open- o p n • handedness. Every men, to follow-citizens, to all Others we must class has Its o\fn g^gj, |.j.„ |.q „jyg {hsi\x due, and seek to deter- special claims, . \ . ^ lui i x. • l i mine what properly belongs to each in respect of relationship, virtue or usefulness. When the claims are of the same sort, the decision is comparatively easy, where they are different in kind, it becomes more difficult, still w'foimd to°cra- ■^^ ™^^' ^°^ °^ t^"*' ground shrink from making flict. it, but decide to the best of our powers. As we have often remarked in our previous discussions, statements about feelings and actions must correspond to the feelings and actions, varying from time to time as they do. And it is not possible to give a precise and exact answer on every point. That we must not give the same things to all, nor everything to a father, as we must not sacrifice everything even to Zeus, is obvious. But since we owe one kind of duties to parents, a different kind to brothers, and a different set to benefactors and to comrades, we must render to each their due and what properly belongs to them. And this is what almost all men seem actually to do : to weddings they invite not their benefactors nor their intimates but their relations;' for, as their race is what they share with them, they call on them to partidpatei in acts which have reference to it ; and they consider that relatives are especially; bound to attend the funerals of relations for the same reason. It would further seem that we are bound to provide support for our parents, for them even before ourselves. Children are bound to maintain their parraitB in existence, as they themselves derive their own existence from them. And we ought also to pay them honour as we do to the Gods — yet not all honour nor honour of every kind. Father and mother are not entitled to the same honour, and to neither of them should we pay the honour due to the philosopher or the general — that I mean which we naturally pay to these two ; but to a father we should pay the honour due to a father, and to a mqther the honour due to a mother. And we should further render to every elderly person the respect due to their age ; a young man for instance should show his respect for an old one by rising up in his presence, making way for him, and in many such Bk. IX. 3.] Trans'laiion. 49 5 ways. To comrades and brotliers we should manifest frankness and readiness to impart, and so to relations, fellow-tribesmen, fellow-citizens, and all the rest. And we must try to give to each, his due, taking into accouft; the relationship in which each stands to oneself, or his usefulness, or his virtue, and measur- ing by these the honours and the intimacy to which we should severally admit them. Where the claims are the same in kind the decision is comparatively easy. What we ought to give to different relatives, or fellow-tribesmen, or fellow- citizens, or any others who are similarly related to us, we shall easily discover. But when the claims are various and diverse, to settle what we should render to each is a task of more difficulty. Still we are not entitled for all that to abandon the claims of equity, but we must decide in each case as best we can, and in respect of all we must observe the conduct which propriety dictates. Sg.fi'} vi. — Questions relating to the dissolution of rriendships. .;■:,<(») GASES WHICH JUSTIFY A DISSOLUTION OF FEIENDSHirS. BifBculties too surround the question whether we should or should not breah off our friendship with those who no longer continue to be what they were. „£ pL'Lsur'or in'te- Where men are friends on grounds of interest or rest the friendship of pleasure, it seems perfectly natural that they rend,"heSea- should part comipany when these motives no siu-e or interest is longer exist. It was by their interests or their ™ logger promoted & -^ by them. pleasure that they were bound, and where these fail, it is natural that their affection should come to an end. But a man would have a right to find fault if a friend „ .„ . , , , ., 11 1 ■ T ■ r J2 2. J? 1 2. Friendships fall while really lovmg mm tor profit or tor pleasure through where a should profess that he loved him on the score of ™an has been de- character. For as we said at the commencement moTive^ w°hich of the discussion, the most fruitful source of dis- prompted the sension is when men imagine they are friends "^° ^ '^' on different grounds from what they really are. When, then, a man has deceived himself and considers that he is loved on the score of his character, while his friend did nothing of the kind, he has himself td blame for it ; but when he is led astray by his friend's profession he has a right to find fault with him who has deceived him, even more than with the issuers of counterfeit coin, inasmuch as the ill deed touches a point of more vital interest. We have still the following point to investigate — should we or should we not break off friendships ! For it is matter of discussion whether in certain cases, where our friend still continues to feel affection for us and to love us, we should by our own act bring the friendship to an end. ■ Now our sentence is that when men are friends on grounds of interest or pleasure, it is not unreasonable for them to separate, when they no longer afford each other the one or the other : if the pleasure or the profit come to an end, which was what they reaUy oared for, it is quite natural that they should no longer feel affection, 496 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. Vt. %. But when those who really love from motives of interest or pleasure pretend thait they love on the score of character and goodness, and are convicted of dissolving the friendship on such unworthy grounds, they are guilty of a wrong and are justly subject to reproach. For as we said at the commencement of the discuB- siou, those friendships are sure to be full of complaints, where the two are not loved and do not feel affection on the same grounds and in a similar way, and do not think that they are loved in the way in which they actually are loved, but mga deceived. For then when the deception is laid bare, they find fault with onlB another. When, then, a man is deceived and thinks that he is loved on the score of character, though his friend does nothiug of the kind, nor says anything which befits one who feels affection on that ground, he shoxild by good right blame himself for the mistake he has made ; but when he has been led astray by his friend's pretence, he has a right to find fault with him for having led him astray, even more than with those who issue false coin, inasmuch as the ill deed touches more precious interests. Such then are the grounds which justify those, whom pleasure or profit makes friends, in breaking off their friendships. (^) CASES WHEEE CHANGES OF CHARACTEE LEAD TO A DISSOLUTION OF FRIENDSHIP. But if one man admit another to his friendship supposing him to be good, and that other turn out evil and show outab'ad^mSS himself to be such, is the first bound any longer is sufficient cause to love him ? Is it not impossible for him to do friendsMi°^°*^*'"' SO, sluce it is not everything that commands afi'ection, but only the good? The evil neither commands love nor ought to do so ; for we ought not to be lovers of evil nor to make ourselves like the evil. But we have already said that like is friend to like. Should we then at once cast off the friendship ? Surely not, except with those who are incurable in their should^^^Xst^ be wickedness. If they can still be reclaimed, we made to reclaim are bound to help them to recover their charactei even more than their property, inasmuch as to do so is more excellent and more properly a work of friendship. Still he who does break off his friendship cannot be regarded aa ctiug unreasonably, as he was never a friend with the man in the character which he actually bears. Since, then, he is unable to reclaim him now he has altered, he parts company with him. To take next the other case of the one continuing as he was , ^. . and the other greatly improving, so that there 4. If agam one • i • r i i , • • . greatly advances in comes a wicie mtcrval between them m virtue, is virtue the other t]^ second bound to treat the first as a friend, oi remains stationary, • •, • -i i ^ i ■ x i o mi their friendship IS it impossible for him to do SO ? The questior naturally comes to ■v^-jn be best answered bj'^ looking at an extrenK *"*" ■ case; such for instance as where the friendshij was contracted in childhood. If in this case the one were t( remain a child in intellect, the other were to develope into a mai 3k. TX. 3.] Translation. 497 of the noblest kind, how could they continue to be friends, when they neither take delight in the same pursuits, nor are pleased or pained by the same circumstances. Indeed they will no longer find any pleasure in one another, but without this it is impossible, as we shewed, for them to be friends, for they cannot live together. But this point we have already discussed. Ought the one, then, to treat the other exactly as if he had never been his friend? Should he not rather keep in mind their former intimacy? And just TndtXna as we think that we ought to do favours to friends kindly recollection rather than to strangers, on this same principle "* *''^'^ ^^ "'*'" we should give something to those who ^a«e been our friends on the score of previous friendship, that is to say where the friendship has not been broken off on account of extreme wickedness. But if one man love another for his character and admit him to his friendship siipposing him to he good, but that other should turn out evil, or should appear to his friend to do so, is the first bound to continue to love him or may he break ofl the connexion ? We conclude that it is not possible for one to be loved who does not seem good. It is goodness that commands love, badness has not even a right to do so ; for no one has a right to be a lover of evil, nor to assimilate himself to the bad ; but if he loves it, he is bound to grow like it, for we have already said that it is like that is friends with like. Should we then break off the friendship at once ? Ought we not rather not to break it off at once with all, but only with those who are incurably bad 1 With those who may still be cured of their disease and set right we must not break off our friendship, but must use all diligence to help them to regain their character and to preserve their virtue for them even more than their property. Virtue is more exceUeut than property, and to help one'rf friends in respect of this is more truly ain act of friendship than to guard their wealth for them. If, then, he who has the power is bound to ward off poverty from a friend's substance, much more is he bound to join in the recovery of his virtue, all the more as it is especially appropriate in him to do so, since it is with a view to virtue that they are friends. The better course then is to continue to love one's friend even when he has grown evil and to seek to restore him. Still if a man should break off the friendship at once, he is not thought to act unreasonably. He made friends in the first instance not with a bad man but with a good, and in ceasing to love one who is no longer good, he does wrong to no one ; if then he is unable to recover the good man . who has altered, he gives up his friendship with him. Supposing then our friend who was good to become evil, this is how we must act in breaking off our friendship. But if of two friends one should grow very much better than he was, and should greatly alter in point of virtue, the other should remain as he was — should the grood man treat the other who is not such, as a friend ? or is it not possible for him to do so, but must he break off the friendship ? The matter becomes plainest where the interval is very great. For suppose two children to be friends, drawn together by similarity of age, by living together and by sharing one another's amusements, and when they come to men's estate the one should turn out good and be a man in all things, and the other should remain with a child's character to the end, how can they be friends, if they neither taie pleasure in the same objects, nor are pained or pleased at the same things ? No ; one will not even find pleasure in the other, as neither has anything by the doing of which he can con- ciliate and give pleasure to his friend. And fnither they will not even be able K K 498 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 4. to live together ; yet without these things friendship caimot be maintained, as we have already said. Shoiild the good man then he disposed to the other exactly in the way he would have been, if he had never been his friend, or should he not rather bear in mind their former intimacy ?' And as we think that we are bound to oblige onr friends in preference to strangers, on the same principle are we not also bonn4 to do more for those who hcuoe been onr friends than for those who have never been so 1 We ought, therefore, it would seem, to recognise some obligation on the ground of previous friendship, unless that friendship has been broken off for flagrant wickedness. XI.— EXAMINATION OF DISPOSITIONS ALLIED TO FRIENDSHIP. i.— Of Self-love. f (a) CHARACTERISTIC FEATURES OP FRIENDSHIP. Now our different friendly relations to others, and the various characteristics by which friendships are defined, fineT— '"^ '^ ^^' seem to have been derived from a man's feelings (1) as wishing well ^^ himself. Men define a friend as one who and doing well to wishcs and does good, or what appears to him (2) as^°hlng for S°°^> *« ^'s neighbour unselfishly ; or as one that one's friend's life wishes for his friend's own sake his fi-iend's con- ('sf M Sg toge- tiiiiied existence and life — (this is the feeling that ther and following mothers entertain for their children, or friends the same pursuits, ^jjg^j. j^^yg {j^^ a quarrel for one another) ; others (4) as sympathising . . r- i i • a.- in one's friend's agam represent- mm as one who passes Jus tune joys and griefs. y^if}^ ]jjg neighbour, and follows the same pursuite^ or as one who sympathises with his neighbour's sorrows and joys. This is a feature again which is most frequently to be seen in mothers. It is by one or other of these attributes that friendship is defined. Such, then, are the grounds on which friendships may be properly broken off. But we have still some points we may discuss about friendship itself. The relations of friendship and the attributes by which friendship is constitated would seem to have a kind of measure and starting-point in the duties which a man owes to himself. Friends expect from one another what a man does for himself. Consequently they define a friend .as one who wishes and does good to his friend for that friend's own sake, or as one who wishes for its own sake for Ma friend's continued life and preservation, which is the feeling that mothers have for their children ; for they wish for their children's own sake that they should live and prosper, since often, even though they may not be loved by their children or even known by them, they still pray for their happiness and prosperity ; this too is the feeling of friends, who have had a quarrel or who have been alighted, but who yet, as far as they are concerned, continue to cherish their previoia affection ; they wish their friends all good, without hoping to participate in this good themselves, just for their friend's own sake. Others again define a friend 5k. IX. 4.] Translation. 499 \& one who sympathises with his friend in sorrow and in joy, which thing again fl what mothers beyond all others do in the case of their chiltou. From one or rther of these things the definition of friendship is derived, oeing drawn from iie definition of those who exhibit the characteristics in the same way as the lefinition of the temperate man furnishes us with the definition of temperance. 3noh then are the definitions of friendship and of friends. But they are taken Etom the duties owed by a man to himself, as has been already said. (J) A GOOD MAN IS HIS OWN TRUE FEIEND. Now each of these characteristics is to be found in a good man's relations to himself, while in all others they are „, , , . to be found just so far as they consider them- tics are all realised selves to be good. Virtue and the good man i^ ^ gooti ™a'»'s •L /., ■ T T ■ J ^ relation to himself. jeem, as we have oiten said, a kind ot measure of what each should be. First, the good man is at unison with himself and desires the same ends with every part of his soul; so too he ,,, tt • srishes for himself what is good and what im- -jrith himself, and presses him as such, and does good to himself ; it wishes and does is the special trait of the good to labour for that ^°° " ™^^ ' which is good and on his own account : for he does this for the sake of his intellectual nature, and this is held to be most pro- perly himself. He wishes too for his own con- tinued life and preservation, and most of all for (2) he wishes for flrnt of his thinking part ; for existence is good to tion for himself, a, good man. Yet it is for himself that each wishes good, and no one chooses to become something other than b is and that that new self should have everything, (he cannot, therefore, wish even to become God), for though G-od has even now the good, still it is by being that which He is. But ' thought ' would seem to constitute a man's personality, or to constitute it toore than anything besides. Such an one wishes, moreover, to pass his time in his own company ; he does this with pleasure, as the memories of his past deeds I^'m'^^oS* are delightful to him and his hopes for the future W good, and such memories and such hopes are pleasant. He has besides plenty of objects of contemplation for his intelligence. And he sympathises with himself in sorrow and in icy: the same things are ever pleasant, ever C*)^'® sympathises „ • ji^ii 1 • , ,1 • J.1 ii with himself m pamral to mm, not one thing now, another tben, gon-ow and in joy. for he has, as we may say, nothing to repent of. Seeing, then, that each of these characteristics is to be found in the good man in his relations to himself, and seeing that he is Hected to his friend as to himself— a friend being a kind of second self, friendship is, therefore, thought to consist in one or K K 2 500 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 4. other of these things, and a friend to be one in whom these dispositions are to be found. Wiat a true friend is to his friend, that in all respects is a good man to him- self ; and the good man and he who thinks himself good is in the truest sense a friend to himself. The fact that this cannot be said of all, but the bad are no true friends to themselves, does not bear upon our present argument. What the good and the excellent do is what is properly distinctive of man and of our common nature. It is virtue and the good man that are the measures of what feelings and what acts are proper to our human nature ; the objects which the evil seek are not regarded as proceeding from our human nature. For a decision on such points we go not to those who are sick but to those who are whole. But that a good man does perform all the offices of friendship to h imself is plain. In the first place he is at unity with himself and desires the same objects in respect of both his rational and his irrational nature and does not, like the man, lacking in self-restraint, seek conflicting objects, while his feelings are at war with his reason. Secondly the good m^n wishes what is good for himself, both those things which are really good and promote virtue, and also those things which appear good as being aids to virtue. Moreover he wishes what is good for himself for that self's own sake, while the bad man, if he wishes it at all, wishes it not for his true self's sake. It is his intellectual nature that makes man man, and it is for the sake of this that the good man does aU things and seeks all good things, but the bad man does nothing for its sake. The bad man takes as the end of his acts, not pure contemplation but evil pleasure, and so he does not wish good for himself for that self's own sake. Thirdly the good man wishes also for life and preservation for himself, and most of all for the continued ex- istence and preservation of his intellectual nature, and he does everythiug which he thinks good for himself and which contributes to his existence and preservatiem But of the rest those that are not wholly perverted from the right, but are ao circumstanced as to be able to imagine themselves good, seek also themselves what seems good and wish for life and preservation for themselves. But they are enabled to do this, because they are to some extent like the good. But they who are thoroughly bad and workers of nnhaJlowed deeds are not in this condition. They do not follow after what seems good, but their wishes lead them in one way their desires in another. This is the condition even of the self -controlled, but much more is it the state of those who are prevented by cowardice or sloth from doing what they think to be best for themselves. They, therefore, neither pursue what seems to them good, nor wish for themselves life and preservation. Some there are who from the many evil deeds that they have done have become objects of detestation on account of their exceeding wickedness, and they fly from life and make away with themselves. But the good man does wish for >iiTnap1f to live on, as existence is a good to the good man ; for he pursues the life of contemplation, as the personality of each consists in thought, or in this more than in anything besides. But he who wishes existence and preservation for his irrational nature and wishes good for a self which has deviated from its proper nature, cannot be said to wish good for himself, but for that into which he has been perverted. Moreover each wishes good for himself, expecting to remain what he is at present ; but if he were to be conscious that he had passed into something otha: than he was, he would not choose that that altered self should be possessed of all good things ; one might just as well wish good to some one else, as to one self when entirely altered. But no one is content that some one else should have everything that is good, for granted that all good things are even now the lot of God, still He too is that which He is, whatever that may be. Consequently we are not content, but we go on praying that goods may be granted to ourselves or to our friends, to our friends because they are in a way our second selves. Once more, the good man also wishes to pass his life in his own company, as he is self- sufficing and pleasant withal to himself ; he takes delight in remembering by himself what he has done and in hoping that he will still do good things and that good will befall him, and he has besides an abundance of noble objects Bk. IX. 4.] Translation. 501 for his thoughts to contemplate. All these things make him most agreeable to himself, and he takes pleasure in his leisure moments in being alone with him- self and in his own society. • (c) BUT A BAD MAN IS HIS OWN WOEST ENEMY. The question however whether a man can or cannot have friendship for himself may be dismissed for the present. It would seem as if he could have it ^ay\t ^sSd pr^ so far as two or more of the above conditions are ™ionaiiy to be fulfilled. This is also confirmed by the fact that ^^^"^ ^*^ ^- friendship, when pushed to its greatest length, becomes like the feeling a man entertains for himself. But the traits we have mentioned look as if they were to be found in the majority, bad though they be. Is _ it not the case, though, that they are to be found oiJy so for as Jen only so far as the majority are pleasing in their either are, or think own eyes and consider themselves to be good ? ^""^ ^^^' ^°° ' In the case of the wholly bad at any rate and workers of unhallowed deeds they are not to be found at all, ^, , , , , 11!. i 1 mi The hopelessly de- and don t even appear to be so. iney are praved don't even scarcely to be found at all, even in the bad. Such s«™ *" ^^ "" , . -ii ii 1 j_i • -1 friendly terms with are at variance with themselves, their wishes themselves, but pointing in one direction, their desires pulling in rather to loathe another, as is the case with men of imperfect emseves. self-control ; such choose, in place of what they themselves iecognize to be good for them, what is pleasant indeed but harm- ful, while others of them are induced by cowardice and by sloth to abstain from doing what they really consider to be the best for •themselves. Those once more by whom many dreadful deeds have been done and whose wickedness has made them objects of detes- tation, come to hate life itself and make away with themselves. And bad men seek companions to pass their time ^ -,1 T , ... T^■ 11 While all the bad witn and shun their own company. Disagreeable aUke shun as far memories crowd in upon them when they are by as may be their themselves, and they have only what is disagree- ''^™ company, able to look forward to, while when they are with others they forget their troubles ; having nothing to draw forth afi'ection in them they are conscious of no affection for themselves. Thus also they do not rejoice in their own joys nor grieve over their own sorrows : their soul is at strife with itself; part of it is made by its evil nature to grieve over the enjoyments which it is denied while the other part of it rejoices, part of it pulls in this way the other part in that, dragging the man, as it were, asunder. And if it so be, that it is not possible to be pained and pleased at one 502 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 4. and the same moment, then we must say that after a very little while the man is pained that he was pleased, and would not wish, if he could help it, to have found such things pleasant to him ; for the bad are full of regrets. We conclude, then, that the bad man does not seem to be friendly disposed even to himself, because he has nothing in him to call forth affection. But the evil want companions with whom to pass their time and shun their own company ; when they are by themselyes, unpleasant memories crowd in upon them, unpleasant expectations haunt them ; and they forget them when they are with others. Once more the good man more than otliers rejoices and grieves in sympathy with himself, because his wishes and his desires are at one and his rational nature is not at variance with his emotional. For thia reason the same thing is ever painful to him, the same thing ever pleasant, for he is unchangeable as far as may be. The evil are not thus. They have nothing in them to call forth affection and so feel no affection for themselves. Consequently they do not sympathise with themselves in joy or in sorrow. Their soul is at strife with itself, and the irrational natiu'e wars against the rational ; the irrational nature is grieved at having to desist from what is evil, but the rational nature does not then share in its grief but is pleased. So is it also in the opposite case. And generally spealdng the one part pulls in one direction, the other in the other, di-agging the soul asunder. And if we have to admit that it is not possible to be pained and pleased at one and the same time, then we shall say that after a little the soul is pained because just now it was pleased, for it did not wish that such a pleasure should have been felt by it. The evil are full of regrets. It appears, then, that the bad man is not friendlily disposed towards himself, as he has nothing in him to call forth affection. id') PRACTICAL BXHOETATION. But if to be in such a condition as this is very miserable, we „ , .„ , must earnestly shun vice, earnestly try to be Woodness will make , -x ,-, • -n i . i j a man friends with good. In this Way a man Will be at once placed himself and with on a friendly footing with himself and be made all the world. » • i ■. r i • • i i a Iriend with his neighbour. If to be in such a case is the height of misery we must shun wickedness with aU diligence and strive each one of us to be good and excellent, for by these means we shall be placed on a footing of friendship alike with ourselves and with our neighbours. Seeing, then, that what a man does to himself he should do for his friend likewise — for one ought to love one's friend as oneself— the friend being a second self — it is plain that what the good man wishes and does for himself, these are the obligations of friendship and in them friendship consists. But the question whether the love a man has for himself is, or is not, friend- ship, may be dismissed for the present. Friendship implies two or three, as is clear from what we have already said. If a man chooses to call a man's relation to himself friendship, it may be regarded as friendship so far as there are different parts in man and the feelings are at peace with the reason. Moreover, because friendship in its most perfect fonn approaches the love a man has for himself, this latter also may be called friendship. BL IX. 5.] Translation. 503 ii. — Goodwill. (a) DIFFERENCE OF GOODWILL FEOM FEIENDSHIP AND PEOM AI"FECTION. Goodwill is a kind of friendly disposition and yet it is not friendship. It can be felt towards strangers and without being recognised, friendship can not be. Goodwill differs This indeed has already been insisted on. Yet ^^^ m^L-^wli it is not affection either. It has no impetuosity strangers, and or emotion, but these are the concomitants of ^ognked ■ ^™^ ^^' affection. And affection implies intimacy, whereas goodwUl may be conceived on a sudden, which is what happens in the case of combatants in the arena. The spec- , ,, nj- jj. ji.T. j-i &om affection in tators grow well-disposed towards them and wish having no intensity them success, though not prepared to help them, and not implying For, as we have said, men become well-disposed ™ ™^^' on a sudden and feel a liking in a superficial way. Goodwill is like friendship, and yet is not friendship. We feel goodwill for those with whom we are not friends, and goodwill may spring up towards a stranger and without the knowledge of the ohject of it. But this is not possible in the case of friendship, as we have explained above at greater length. Thus goodwill is not friendship ; it does not even seem to be affection. Affection implies a certain impulse and movement towards the object of it. But' goodwill is not of this chaiaoter. The well-disposed wish good to those to whom they are well-disposed, and yet do not seek their company. And again, affection implies intimacy, as it is brought about only by time and intercourse, whereas goodwill may come all on a heap (if one may use the expression,) on those who experience it ; which is the way with spectators and the combatants in the arena. The specta- tors grow weU-disposed towards the combatants as soon as they see them winning and give them their good wishes, but they are not prepared to help theic efforts, as ihey have no affection for them from having loved them long and intimately, but were pleased with them the moment they saw them, and so their love is only superficial, and this is the character of goodwill. (5) EELATION OF GOODWILL TO FEIENDSHIP. ■ Now goodwill seems to be the originating cause of friendship in the same way as pleasure in the sight of a person is the originating cause of love. No one g^el'^j^ >dsMp! feels love who is not first pleased with his darling's outward form ; and yet he who does take pleasure in another's beauty does not for all that fall in love unless he comes besides to regret his darling's absence and to feel a desire for his presence. In the same way it is not possible for men to be friends without becoming first well-disposed to one another, and yet the well-disposed are not for all that friends. They only get 504- The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 5. as far as wishing good to those to whom they are well-disposed, but are not prepared to help them in their eflforts or to give themselves trouble on their account. Hence we might speak of it by a metaphor as inert friendship ; yet when it has gone on for a good time and has but requires time passed into an intimacy it developes into friend- maturr "X^^into ship, friendship of the true kind, not friendship friendship, after prompted by either pleasure or interest, since teue'friendshipr^^ goodwill itsclf does uot TCst ou these. He who has been benefited returns goodwill for the benefits he has received and is right in doing so, but he who wishes to do another a kindness, only in the hope of being en- riched by his neighbour, would seem to be well-disposed not so much to his neighbour as to himself ; just as a man would scarcely be reckoned a friend, if he serves his neighbour with a view to his own profit. So as a rule goodwill is felt on account of virtue and kindliness in cases where one man impresses another as fortVby^the°B§ht noble or brave or something of the kind, as we of nobiuty and ex- illustrated by the case of combatants in the ceUence. ^^^^^^ Thns then goodwill seems to be the begirming of friendship in the same way as pleasure in the sight of a person is the beginning of love. And just as it is not possible to fall in love without first being charmed by the fair form of the loved object — though you may be charmed without falUng in love, for yon cam only be said to be in love when you miss your darling, if absent, and eagerly desire his presence — ^in the same way it is not possible for two to become friends without being first well-disposed to one another, but they may be well-disposed without being friends. For the well-disposed wish good to those to whom they are well-disposed, but are not prepared to actively help them or to put themselves to trouble about them. Consequently one might speak of goodwill in meta- phorical language as inert friendship, for when time has passed over it and it has grown into intimacy it developes into friendship. And friendship not for interest nor for pleasure's saie, but friendship which rests on goodness. One man becomes well-disposed to another on account of virtue or excellence, when the one appears noble or brave in the other's eyes, or something of the kind. Whereas he who wishes to do another a good tnm for the sake of pleasui'e or. profit is not really well-disposed to that man but to himself, just as he is not a real friend either. In the same way he who wishes good to his benefactor because he has received benefits from him, will be properly speaking weU-disposed, but as he is only doing what is just and repaying gratitude for benefits he has received, he seems to be rejoicing not in his firiend's excellence but in his own goodness. We conclude then that goodwill is neither friendship nor affection but a beginning of friendship ; but that when coupled with time, intimacy, and the other requisites for friendship, it grows into friendship, friendship too of the kind which rests on goodness and virtue. Bk. IX. 6.] Translation. " 505 iii. — tTnaniinity. i (a) ITS PROVINCE DETERMINED. ^* Unanimity also has a friendly character, and this is what distinguishes it from mere coincidence of opinion. This latter might be found among those who are Unanimity differs complete strangers to one another. Nor is it enraoTopiMon"^'^" customary to speak of those who are of one mind on some special subject, as for instance about the movements of the heavens, as unanimous, for to be ijnanimous on such points has nothing friendly about it — but we do talk of states as unani- mous, when they are of one mind about their interests, and adopt the same line of policv and ^|™? comcidenoe ' ^ ^ i.- o J.1 i of opinion on proc- foUow out a common course 01 action. 80 that tied matters, and it is on matters of practice that men are unani- P"™*^ °^ common mous, on practical matters that is to say of im- ' portance, and such as concern both parties or all alike. States for instance are unanimous when all the citizens agree that offices should be elective or to make an alliance with the Lacedemonians, or to put Pittacus in power so long as he also wished it himself; but when each one of the citizens wishes to rule in his own person, as is represented in ' the Phanissae,' then they fall out. For unanimity does not consist in each wishing for a particular thing for himself, but in all wishing to see it in the same hands. For instance, the people and the upper classes are unanimous when they both wish the best men to be in office, as in that case all alike may get what they desire. Unanimity also has itself a friendly character and generally accompanies iriendahip. Unanimity consists not in holding the same views or in mere coin- cidence of opinion. Such coincidence of opinion might be found among those who are absolute strangers to one another, as there is nothing to prevent their holding the same views on the same subjects and having the same knowledge of the same points, even though they know nothing of one another. But unanimity exists only between those who are associated together and are on a footing of friendship. We speak for instance of states as unanimous, when they are of one mind about their interests and agree upon and carry out the same line of policy. Unanimity is, then, a coincidence of view in friends, a coincidence of view not on theoretical but on practical matters, and on practical matters of considera- tion and importance. For in respect of trifles neither states, nor friends, are spoken of as unanimous. For instance we do not tali about men being unanimous about staying at home or going to the market, or doing or saying anything from which no great benefit or harm is likely to result. On all these and such like points no one would say they were unanimous. But we do use the term where the matters, are important and to the interest of both the friends, or of the state at large : for instance when the whole state is agreed that its magistrates should not be returned to office by lot, or succeed in rotation but should be regularly elected, or when it is agreed to conclude an 5o6 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 6. alliance with the Lacedemonians, or to do anything else which is important and which makes a difference to the state at large. In the same way we speak of friends as unanimous when they adopt the same course of life and are agreed as to their highest interests and shim and pursue alike whatever tends to the hurt and to the advantage of both of them. For those who are to be unanimous must not only seek the same objects, but also seek them in the same way in aJl their bearings. For instance if both of two friends are agreed that one or other of them should be the guide of the other's life, but they should not agree as to which of the two, but each should wish to take the oflSce on himself, then they woidd not be unanimous ; for in that case, though .they have the same object ju view, they yet do not wish it to be realised in the same way. And in states also all the citizens will be unanimous in their choice of magistrates, when either all choose the same individual, or all choose the best men, and not each one himself, as Euripides represents them as doing in the Phanissae. In this latter case a result is not arrived at which pleases aU, and consequently there is not unanimity. But when all do get what they desire, then they are unanimous. (B) FORMAL DEFINITION OF UNAl^IMITT. It appears ttus that unanimity is ' political friendsMp,' and J , , this is the acceptation of the term in ordinarv and so may be de- t^ i ^ x • j. x , fined as a kind of language, it has reiereuce to our interests and 'political friend- ^11 that concems the general tenor of our lives. Thus, then, unanimity is a kind of political friendship, and this is the ordinary acceptation of the term. Its province is practical matters and what concems our interests and the general tenor of our lives, aH which fall under the sphere of ' social science.' (c) DEPENDENCE OF UNANIMITY ON VIETUE. Now unanimity of this kind is to be found among the good. They being, if one may use the expression, ^ given 'Tis the good alone up to ' the Same objocts, are of one mind with mous, themselves, and with one another. Their wishes are fixed and constant, and do not ebb and flow like the Euripus ; and their wishes point to what is at once just and expedient, and their desires are shared in by all of them alike. But the wicked cannot be unanimous, except to a very limited ., ., extent, any more than they can be friends : for the evU are sns- , , t .i • i , , , peoted and suspi- they have their heart set upon covetousness cious of one an- where their interests are concerned, while, where toil and voluntary services are in question, they lag behind. When each wishes for advantages for himself, he keeps his eye on his neighbour's doings and thwarts them ; for if they don't watch one another, the common interest suffers. The result is that they are ever quarrelling, as they are exact- ing on one another but are not themselves willing to do their fair share. BL IX. 1.] Translation. 507 Unanimity is to be found among the good, they are of one mind with them- selyes and with one another, being given up, if one may so say, to the same objects. The wishes of suoh are iixed and stable and do n(jt ebb and flow and shift about like the Buripua, and they wish for what is at onoe just and expedient and aU aUke desire it. But the evil cannot be unanimous — except to a very limited extent — any more than they can be steadfast friends, as they have their heart set upon oovetousuess i'^nd each seeks to get for himself a larger share of whatever is profitable, while in labours and in voluntary services undertaken in each other's behalf they are ever seeking to get out of them ; and each holding it is his due to have little trouble but great advantage is for ever calling his neighbour to account, and exacting from him the full amount of voluntary service and hindering him from enjoying his advantages as much as he likes, considering them too great for him, while he gives him his full share of disagreeable tasks. The result is that having no eye to the public advantage, but each an eye to his own, they quickly fall out, for they snap what holds them together, and that is a sense of community of interest and unanimity. But when the tie that holds them together is snapped they can no longer be united. The result is that they quarrel, as they demand friendly offices from one another but are not themselves prepared to do what is just. So it comes about that among the bad there can be no unanimity, but only among the good. iv. — The relation of Benefactor and Eecipient. (a) DIFFICULTY STATED. Now benefactors seem to love those they have benefited more than the receivers of favours love those that have done them ; and this fact as being something tors'^iove the°red- paradoxical is made a subject of speculation. pients of their fa- vours better than these recipients we must now proceed to investigate the following point — joyg them ? why it is that benefactors love the recipients of their favours more than they are themselves loved by them. The point attracts attention as being contrary to what we should naturally expect. {b) POPULAR EXPLANATION OF THE DIFFICULTY. The popular explanation is, that it is because the one are in the position of debtors the other of creditors; as, then, in the case of regular loans, debtors wish that The popiUar expia- those to whom they owe the debt should cease two^°stand to one to be, while the creditors are ever anxious about another in the re- the safety of their debtors, in the same way ^d°debtor.""^"°' benefactors wish that the recipients of their kind- ness may continue to live, that thus they may get back favours from them, while these don't specially care to repay what they have received. Epicharmus would, perhaps, maintain that in say- ing this they are regarding human nature in a dark light ; still it is human nature to act thus, for the majority are forgetful of kindnesses and more anxious to receive than to do good. 5o8 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 7. The majority say that the reason why benefactors feel the greater affection is the same as that which makes creditors also love those to whom they have lent, even though they are not loved by their debtors. They who have made a loan wish the safety of their debtors and promote it in every way in order that they may get their money back again, but the debtors have no such feeling witli respect to their creditors. These would be willing that their creditors shouia cease to exist, considering that they wiU be better off by being thus relieved of their debt. The same is the case, they maintain, with tiiese. Benefactors, they say, wish that the recipients of their kindness should live and be kept safe, supposing that they will thus get a requital of their favours, whereas the parties benefited do not greatly desire the safety of their benefactors. For men do not so much care to repay kindnesses as to get them repaid. This is what appears to the majority the cause from looking at ungrateful and evil men and, as Epicharmus says, from viewiug human nature on the dark side. Yet such is human nature. The majority are ungrateful, and more anxious to receive kindnesses than to do them. (c) A DEEPER EXPLANATION OFFERED. Yet the cause would seem to lie deeper in nature, and not really to be explained by the case of those who have Lt tr^be ft^°nd' ™f^<^^ a, loan. In their case there is no question for— ' of affection but a simple wish for the preser- L?'L''redpitt nation of their debtors in order to get back their of his favoiurs like money ; on the other hand those who have done any ajtist loves his ^ service do feel friendly to and love those who have been benefited by them, though they are of no advantage to them and never may be so. The same pheno- menon is to be observed in artists ; every one of them loves his handiwork more than he would be loved by it, were it endowed with life. Perhaps this is most conspicuously the case with poets. They love to distraction their own poems, doting on them like children. Very like this is it with benefactors. The person benefited is their handiwork, consequently they love him more than the handiwork loves its producers. Now ^\woi°''hS t^® ^^^son of this is that existence is desirable own personality ao- to and Valued by all. We exist in being active, tuaiised and in- ^^^^ ■ jjj 1-.^,^^ g^^^j doing. So that the creator tensified. i. i /^ i • , . . t j 01 a work nnds in a way his existence actuahsed in the work he has made. Therefore he loves his work because he loves existence. And this is only natural. For what before is only potential, this the work stamps as actual. At the same time to the benefactor the doing of his act is honourable, and so he takes pleasure in that in enjoys* the sense which this finds its Sphere, but to the recipient and the memory of no Sense of honour accrues from the transaction, honour won. y^^^ ^^^ ^^^^ p^.^^^ ^j^ j^^^^^^, .^ ^^^^ pleasant, less desirable. Moreover while of the present it is the actual Bk. IX. 7.] Translation, 509 p existence that is pleasant, of the future the hope, of the past the memory, the actual is at once the most pleasant and the most intensely loved. Therefore for the doer of the Wfeneflt his work abides, for the sense of honour is lasting, but for the recipient the profitableness soon passes away. The memory too of noble deeds is pleasant, but of advantages gained not pleasant at all or less so, whereas with expectation the reverse seems to hold good. Moreover loving is like the doing of something, being loved like the suffering of something. Love and friendly feelings are consequently the natural kindness'^'' tas"^ " possession of those who are conscious of SUpe- sense of superiority riority in their activity. affection** ^^^^ Once more all feel more natural affection for what is attended with trouble in the getting of it. For instance those who have made their money value it more than those who have inherited it. Now to receive ^- '■^e effort iu- favours is attended with no trouble, to do them the result oSneT is laborious. It is this same reason that makes J. mothers more devoted to their offspring, because the bearing of them is laborious and they are more fully assured that they are their own. This would seem to be just the position of benefactors as well. Tet the real cause would seem to lie further back iu nature, and not to be explained by the analogy of debtor and creditor. Between benefactors and the recipients of their kindnesses there grows up a real affection, but between creditor and debtor there is none. The creditor does not Ime the debtor but merely wishes for his safety, and that simply on the ground that he may recover Mb debt and get back his money. But those who have conferred benefits love and have a regard for tbe recipients of them, even though they are not serviceable to them and may never become so. This is also the case with artists. Every one of them loves Ms handiwork more than he would be loved by that work were it to be endowed with life. Above all others is this so with poets. They love their- own poems to distraction, doting on them as if they were their children. Something in this same way is it with benefactors also. They who have been benefited by them are to that extent their work and, therefore, they love them more than their work does them. The reason of this is that existence is desirable to and loved by all. Now we exist most perfectly when we are active ; and we exist in an active way by living and doing. So he who works is in a way made actual in his work. Architecture, for instance, which is the science of building, is aotualised in a house. And the house itself, so far forth as it is a house, is the ' • , workman made actual, so far forth as he is a workman. In the same way every one who works is identified with his work in its actuality. If then it is natural to desire existence, and existence consists in acting and the work is the agent himself in his actuality, it is clear that in so far as everyone seeks for existence for himself, so far he seeks also the existence of his work ; but it is natural for every man to love himself and to wish for his own existence ; it is natural, therefore, for every man to love his work. But since a man loves himself best and since each loves his omn work best, he will also love best the object of his y' kindness, in so far as he is his own work. For this reason, he will love him more 5IO The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk, IX. 7. than thiB latter loves his benefactor. For the greatest affection one can feel is that which one feels for oneself. A further reason is that the benefactor improTes himself by doing the kindness, and it is a good, to him to do the kindness, con- sequently he takes pleasure in the object of it, because in him he sees his own good. But the recipient is not improved by receiving the kindness, nor does he find any good iu the benefactor — for it is by what he does himself that a man is made better — since the good of man consists in active employment, as we ex- plained in an, earlier Book. Thus if the recipient finds any good in his benefactor it is not in the shape of good to himself but of advantage ; and advantage is not so pleasant or so estimable as goodness. Goodness is what advantage has for its ' end,' and it is on account of goodness that advantage is pleasant or estimable at all. The result is, the benefactor loves the recipient of his favours more than he is loved by him. Again both the actual presence, the hope, and the memory of the good are pleasant, the actuality of its presence and occuiTence,the hope of it in the future, the memory of it in the past. Yet good, when present, is more pleasant than when still future or when past, and the object of his kindness is a present good to the benefactor, for goodness abides and is enduring, and this is what the benefactor contemplates in the recipient ; but the goodness of the recipient is not enduring : it consisted, as we saw, in advantage and so passed away with the advantage ; nor is it properly speaking goodness at all : and con- sequently even if both were present, the good of the benefactor would be the more pleasant, or if both were past, the recollections of the benefactor would be more pleasant than those of the person benefited, inasmuch as the memoiy of goodness is pleasant in the highest degree, but the recollection of advantage not pleasant at all or far less so. With the expectation of advantage the opposite is the case : it is more pleasant than the recollection of good things which have passed away. It would seem, then, that on this ground too the benefactor would love the recipient of his favours more than he would be loved by him. Once more, loving is like the doing something, being loved like a passive state. To those, then, who actively do deeds of friendship (that is clearly to the bene- factors,) loving comes more naturally than to the recipients. Once more, we dote upon and love more what has come by toil than what has been got less easily. This is why those who have made their money love it more than those who have inherited it. Now to receive favours involves no effort, it is a work of difficulty to do them. To receive favours is the part played by the person benefited, to do them by the benefactor. On this ground also the person benefited is more loved than his benefactor. For this same reason mothers are more devoted to their children, because they have had labour in bearing them, than children are to their mothers — for their part has been only to be bom ; and mothers know better that the children are their offspring, than the children know that their mothers ushered them into Hfe. All this seems to suit also the case of benefactors. For not only do they under- take what is laborious on behalf of their clients, but they also know better that it is they who do the service, than the recipients know that the service is done by them. For it is quite possible that the benefactor confers the favour not on his own responsibility but as the agent for another, and consequently is not him- self the real author of the favours at all ; or it may be, that, though he confers the favour at his own prompting, still he does not do it for the sake of the person benefited but for his own sake and with a. view to profit. This too makes the recipient not feel absolutely sure of his benefactor. On the other hand nothing prevents the benefactor knowing perfectly the object of his favours, since he is absolutely sure of himself that he is a true and real benefactor. So on this ground in addition to the others the benefactor loves the recipient of his favours more than he is loved by him. Bk. IX. 8.] Translation. 511 V. — The relation of self-love to love of friends, (a) CONFLICTING VIEWS AS TO THE CHARACTEK OF SELF-LOVE. A question is raised moreover whether one ought to love one's self or one's neighbour best. On the one hand men blame those who love themselves best and bitL'eHnd'pS call them ' lovers of self as a term of reproach, ed. On the one and the had man is thought to do everything ^^fth^tVillht with a view to himself, and' the worse he is to do bad, who have an this the more completely. So men blame him f^f to their own n • -,1 r interests. because he does nothmg, without reference to himself. But the good man is held to act from a sense of nobility, and the better he is the more does he act from that motive and for the sake of his friend, and the more ready is he to neglect his own interests. Yet with such statements as these facts are at variance, and that not without good reason. For men say that we ought to love best him who is our best friend ; ^" ^^ °'^^'^ *^** and he is the best friend who wishes good to him bears to himself is to whom he wishes it absolutely for his own sake, the type and origin ., , 1 m 1 J? -J. T> i. of all other friend- even though no one shall ever know 01 it. iiut gjjip_ these conditions are best fulfilled in a man's own relations to himself, while we have here as well all those other ■characteristics by which a friend is defined. We have already pointed out how all our friendly relations to other men start from our own friendly relations to ourselves. Also all proverbial expressions fall in with this, such as that of friends ' having one soul,' ' having all things in common,' ' friendship's equality,' 'the knee is more than the covering of it.' All these expres- sions would be found most completely realised as between a man and himself. A man is his own best friend, and so must love himself best. Thus a doubt is raised which view we ought to Both ^ews have adopt, since both have so much to say for them- themselves. We should, perhaps, then, distinguish the different senses in which these and similar expressions are used, and thus determine to what extent and in what particulars they are severally true. So much on this head. But there is another point to be considered — whether one should love oneself or one's neighbour best. On the one hand to love oneself best is thought not to be proper to good men, and for this reason those who love themselves best are blamed and are called ' lovers of self ' as a term of reproach. Also the bad man is held to do everything from selfish motives, and so 512 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 8. much the more the worse he is. And he is reproached for this very reason that he seeks nothing more than his own interests but has himself in view in every- thing that he does. The good man on the contrary does everything from a sense of nobility, the more completely so the better and the more excellent he is. And for the sake of his friend, and in order that he may give to others the means of getting what they want, he is ready to sacrifice his own property. On these grounds it is held that one ought not to love oneself best of all. Yet with this view the facts of life are at variance, and that not without good reason. Men say that it is proper to love best one's best friend, and he is the best friend who observes all the obligations of friendship to him whom he loves. And thfe obligations of friendship are to wish one's friend good for his own sake, though no one shall ever know it, and to seek to live with him in preference to all others and to share his sorrows and his joys. Now aU these are obligatione which a man fulfils to himself ; and from a man's bearing to himself his duties to his neighbour have been derived, as was explained in the 4th chapter. And all proverbial expressions testify to this same truth. When men wish to say that men are very great friends, they talk of them as of ' one soul ; ' and also the saying 'the goods of friends are common ' has the same bearing; and 'friendship means equality ' and ' the Icaee is nearer to us than the covering of it.' For if community and equality and nearness constitute friendship, what can be closer to each than a man's self ? Consequently a man is his own best friend. But if one ought to love best one's best friend, then one ought to love oneself best. Since, then, both these statements seem to be true, it is naturally asked which of them we should adopt. We shall find, by distinguishing their different senses and defining them, to what extent and in what sense each of them is true. (h) THE DIFFERENT SENSES OF ' SELF-LOVE ' DETERMINED. Now if we discover in what sense the speakers severally employ ™ ^ the term ' self-regarding,' the difficulty wiU he, The apparent con- , , , ° ° •' ' tradiction is ex- perhaps, cleared up. plained by oonsi- Thosc, then, who usc the word as a term of dermg the different , i i.1, c -ic j- > j. j.i. senses of ' self- reproach apply the name ' self-regarding to those love' and 'self-re- who give themsclves more than their fair share gar mg. ^^ money, honours or bodily pleasures. It is on such things as these that the majority set their hearts and spend themselves for them as the best of all things ; ing,' as ordinarily this makcs them also to be the special objects understood, is of Contention. They, then, who are covetous in meant one who , ,, .•/• xi • ' i i j ii gratifies his own such matters gratify their lusts and generally desires at the ex- their passions and the irrational principle in peuse ers. ^qxt souls. This is the character of the ma- jority. And so the appellation has come to be applied in a bad sense, reflecting the badness of the majority. It is with justice, then, that those who are ' self-regarding ' in this sense are reproached. That it is those who assign to themselves such things as these that the world is wont to call ' self-regarding ' is plain enough. For if a man were to be for ever anxious, beyond every- thing else, to do what is just or what is temperate or whatever Bk. IX. 8.] Translation. 513 other conduct is dictated by any of the other virtues, and should Ks for ever seeking to gain true nobility for himself, such an one no one will call self-regarding nor find fault with him. Yet such an one would seem to be more really ' self-regarding ' thaa the other. At any rate he takes for his own share what is noblest and most excellent, and Mgiier^and™bete gratifies the highest part in him and obeys it in sense it is used of all things. And just as in a state or in any other ™^ tme°se!r*that ' system ' it is the ruling element in it that most is liis reason and properly constitutes that state or that system, so ''? , T^iMec m- • ■ ■ 1 ATI T 1 • stmots. IS it too with man. And he accordingly is most truly self-regarding who loves this part and gratifies this part. Moreover a man is called master of himself or wanting in self- mastery according as his reason has sway in him or not, imjDlying that it is reason which is a man's self. Also they are held to have acted of themselves and voluntarily who have acted most in conscious accordance with the dictates of their reason. That reason, then, constitutes a man's self or constitutes it more than anything else does, is plain; it is plain too that the good man loves this more than anything besides. Consequently he will have a claim to be considered most truly 'self-regarding,' only ' self-regarding ' in a different sense from that which is matter of reproach — in a sense as far removed from that other as living by the dictates of reason is removed from living by the dictates of passion, and as desiring true nobleness is removed from the desire of apparent interest. If we consider the meaning of the term ' self -regarding ' and the sense it is used in in the two different statements, we shall reach the solution we are in search of. The first statement means by ' self -regarding,' not thoss who simply love themselves, but, those who seek to get for themselves the larger share, and that, not in goodness or virtue, but in money, honours and bodily pleasures. Tor it is on these that the majority set their heart, and spend pains upon them as being the best things of all ; and this fact makes them also the common objects of conten- tion. Those, then, who are grasping in such matters, gratify their desires and their passions generally and the irrational element in their soul. This is the Sharacter of the majority, and for this reason the appellation has been given to such. For names are given in accordance with what generally occurs ; whereas things of rare occurrence are not unfrequently not named at all, since some of them are lot even known. Now the bad and those who assign to themselves things that seem good are many, while the good are few and far between. For this reason the many also, who are bad, get the name of self -regarding, and those who are self-regarding in this sense are with justice reproached. But that the majority do call those who are evilly disposed in the matter of their desires self -regarding is clear enough. For if a man were to be for ever anxious beyond all else to do what is just, or to do what is temperate or to follow out any of the other dictates of virtue, and were for ever seeking to win true nobility for himself, no one will oaB such a character self -regarding nor will find fault with him. The first state- ment then means by ' self -regarding ' a man who loves himself amiss, and is so far true tot one ougW not to love oaeself in this fashiou. But the second state- 514 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 8. ment applies the name to the good man, who is ever seeking; to win virtue and goodness for himself, and says that it is he who loves himself best. Kow such an one would seem to be in the more proper sense ' self -regarding.' He does gratify himself, as he gives to the most distinctive element in himself — his rational nature — what is noblest and best. He who gratifies the most dis- tinctive element in. himself, that man in the truest sense gratifies himself. For jiist as the highest element in a state is most properly the state, and it is the best of the citizens that most properly constitute it. in the same way the most distinotiva of the elements in man is most properly man. And so he too is most truly a lover of himself who most loves this and tries to g^ratify this. Besides, a man is called master of himself or wanting in self-mastery not simply by mastering or being mastered, but according as the reason rules the passions, or is ruled by them. So that, when reason masters, the man himself is said to be master, but when the passions are masters, he is not said himself to have the mastery, but rather to be mastered. From this it is plain that a man's rational principle is in a special sense a man's self. And he who loves his own rational nature and in -ivery way tries to gratify it will be properly called self -regarding in one sense of the term, but in a different sense from that when it is used as a term of reproach, — a sense as far removed from it as living by the law of reason is removed from living by the dictates of passion, and the desire of good is removed from evil lust. (c) THE EXCELLENCE OF TRUE ' SELF-LOVE.' All are ready to welcome and praise those who are pre-eminently zealous in doina: noble deeds. And if all were shoiM be encou- emulous to Win truc nobility and were earnest in raged in the good, doing what was noblest and best, all public dijouraged in the ^j^^jgg ^^^^^ ^^^ ^^ ^^^^ fulfilled, and each indi- vidually would reap the greatest of all possible goods, since this is the result of virtue. And so a good man ought to be self-regarding, for he will at once reap advantage to himself by doing what is noble and will benefit all besides. On the other hand the bad man ought not to be so. By being so, he will hurt himself and his neighbours — by following, that is, his evil passions. In the evil man then what he ought to do and what he does are at variance with one another, while the good man smoe m the one . n i ■, , ■, , , , ■, -rr duty and. interest actually does What he ought to do. r or reason coincide, in the evor chooses what is best for itself, and the good other they conflict. i , i.i Tj_i ^i- man hearkens to the dictates of his reason. Seeing, then, that all praise and applaud those who are good and excellent, and that aJl ought to be good (for if all were emulous of true nobilitiy and were zealous to do what is best, every good would be reaped both by the community at large and by every several member of it), it is plain that the good man ought to be self regarding. He will both benefit himself by doing what is noble and will spur others on to do the like. But the bad man has no right to be so. By loving and gratifying himself, that is by following his evil passions, he will do hurt both to himself and his neighbours. In the case of the good, what they actually do coincides ■^dth what they ought to do. For a good man identifies himself with his own reason, and reason chooses what is best for itself, and lie good obey. Bk. IX. 8.] Translation. 515 and follow reason. But in the case of the bad, their duty and what they actually do conflict. Hence such have no right to be self -regarding, but the others should iove themselves as much as they can. « {d) COINCIDENCE OF THE LOVE OF OUR NEIGHBOUR WITH TRUE SELF-LOVE. It is quite true of the good man that he does many things for the sake of his friends and his country, to the extent, if need be, of even dying for them ; he is good 'man benefits ready to give up for their sake money and honours i^Js friends and his and all the most coveted goods, thereby reaping ""^ ^^' for himself a true nobility ; for he would choose rather to feel an intense enjoyment for a little while than a poor enjoyment for a long time, and to live with honour for a single year, than to live for many years in an ordinary way, and to do one great and noble act rather than many small deeds. This is, perhaps, what actually happens in case of those who die for others. They choose, in doing so, a great honour for themselves. A good man will be ready too to sacrifice his own wealth, if his friends will get more there- by. For while his friend gets wealth, he gets honour, and so still reserves for himself the greater good. The same is the case with respect to honours and offices ; all these he will give up to his friends, as this is honourable for him and praiseworthy. It is thus with good reason that he is pronounced good, as t " th b he chooses honour before all else. It may be a more noble re- thathewill even surrender the chance of doing ward for ^^Mmseif noble deeds in his friend's favour, and thus reap honour and the the greater honour of being the occasion of his gratified sense of friend doing them, an honour greater even than ' " ^' that of doing them himself. It thus appears that in all praiseworthy deeds the good man assigns the lion's share of honour to himself. In this sense one may be ' self-regarding,' as has been already said, but in the popular sense, one should not. , . ^, . ^ -^ ' and m this way a man may be rightly Thus then the true definition of self-love has been deter- ' self-regarding. ' mined. And we must now explain the first statement, by which it appeared that the good man is not self -regarding in that he neglects his own interests and seeks those of his friends and his country, in behalf of which he is prepared to die, if need be. That such is the character of the good ' inau is perfectly true. Yet we may not for all this say that he is not in the highest sense self -regarding — ^nay rather, he is shown by these very things to beppaf-regarding. He gives up trifling matters to get great advantages, and by ?'&%wing away goods of little value he earns for himself the greatest rewards. ||ro his friends and to his country he surrenders wealth, honours and such like '*|hingB, but for himself he earns a character of honour and goodness, honesty, and patriotism aad S9 On, goo4s witli which thgg? gth^rs oarjngt gopipare. Yet, evea 5i6 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 9, when he dies for his friends and his coimtry and givea up his own life for them he still plains more than he gives up. He chooses to feel intensely for a short time a good and praiseworthy pleasure rather than a slight pleasure for a long time. He thinks that it is better for him that his life should be short and filled with great achievements, than that he should live long and not earn such praise — and to do om great and noble act than many little ones. This is the more noble course than the other. Noble deeds too, sometimes, he resigns in favour of his friend, and when he might do them himself, yields to him the distinction of doing them. In this case also he reaps for himself the greater good, since it is more glorious to be the cause of one's friend doing noble deeds even than to do them oneself. Consequently he is with justice considered to be good, since he chooses true nobility in preference to all besides, and seeks the lion's share for himself only in what is good and excellent. Thus, then, the good man is shown to love himself best, and on every occasion to get for himself the lion's share of true nobility. In this way, then, one ought to be ' self -regarding,' as has been already observed, but in the way the majority are so, one ought not. As to the in which, then, one ought to love oneself best let thus much be said. XII.— EELATION OF FRIENDSHIP TO HAPPINESS, i. — General question proposed and discussed. There is a question moreover raised, whether the happy man stands in need of friends or no. man need, o'^not ^n the One hand it is maintained that those need, friends ? who are perfectly blessed and self-sufficing have 1. Negative argu- no need of friends, for they possess already every Cr, he \1 blessing. If, then, they are self-sufficing, they have aa good, be Can need nothing more, while a friend in the not reSaem!'^ Capacity of a kind of second self fiu-nishes what one cannot get for oneself. Hence the line of the poet — " When heaven showers blessings, what need have we of friends ? " 1. And yet it would seem to be strange, when we are grantiag Counter ar i- "^^ ^i^PPJ ^^"^ ^11 good things, not to grant him ments™" ^^ ^^^' fricuds, a gift which is thought to be the greatest (i.) He who is to of all ' external ' goods. have friends,"the '^- If it is more characteristic of a friend to greatest of external confer favours than to receive them, and if it is ^°°'^^' the part of a good man and of virtue to be doing good acts — if, moreover, it is more honourable to do good to one's friend than to strangers, then the good man will (ii.) He requires require objects for his beuevolence. And this is them as objects tor ,, " , p ,i . . . , , his benevolence. the reason why a further question is raised whe- ther friends are more indispensable in prosperity or in adversity, gijice in adversity a man requires them to confer Bk. IX. 9.] Translation. 5 1 7 j| favours on him, in prosperity as objects on whom to confer his favours. • 3. Perhaps it would be also strange to make the happy man a '% solitary being, since no one would choose to have all blessings entirely alone by himself. Man is i^„\ ^r' ^nX> naturally social, framed by nature to live in com- be soiitaiy, and pany. Such accordingly must be the condition ^^fft^ooTth^ of the happy man, since he has {ex hypothesi) all native designs Mm the goods that nature designs him to have. It is *° ^''®' • plain also that it is more agreeable to spend one's time in the com- pany of good men and friends than of ordinary men and strangers. The happy man, then, does need friends. A question is raised with respect to the happy, whether they have need of friends or no. Men maintain that the blessed who are self-sufficient can have no need of them, for being self -sufficing and so having everything that is good, how can they want anything besides ? Friends want friends, to get by their help what they cannot get for themselves, the friend being a second self. But since <: the happy are sufficient for themselves they have no further need for friends, (whence the saying : !A " When heaven grants us good, what need we friends ? " On these grounds then it is thought that the happy stand in no need of friends. But from another point of view it seems strange that, when we are granting the happy man all blessings, we should not furnish him with friends, which are thought to be the greatest of all external goods. All the more is this the case because the doing of good offices is indispensable to happiness, and the form of it which is at once the noblest and the most eartoUed is that which is exercised towards friends. So the happy need friends, since they need to exercise the noblest form of benevolence. A fi-iend's most proper ^province is to do benefits and to receive them, and it is more honoiu-able to do good to friends than to aliens or strangers, who have no connexion with us either on the score of character or citizenship. On these grounds then the happy man does appear to require friends, and this causes the question to be asked whether friends are more needful in prosperity or in adversity. For the uu- - fortunate too needs friends to help and to mend his fortunes, the prosperous man |,needs them as objects for his benevolence. ■ It would be strange furthermore to regard a happy man as a solitary being who lives a life apart by himself ; happiness is indeed desirable, but no one would choose to be solitary. No one wishes to have all goods to himself, for man is social, and naturally desires to live in company. These characteristics the happy man too possesses, and he wishes to live in company. All the goods which nature ,; ctosigns for man he too possesses. But if the happy man must live in company, ;.it is plain he must live in the company of the most excellent and the most ;.Siiidred spirits. Such are friends and the excellent; and to live with them is better and is pleteanter than to live with strangers and ordinary men. So the good man does need friends. ii.— Why the happy are thought not to need friends. ■ What then is the meaning of the propounders of the first argu- ment, and how far arc they right ? Is not their contention based on the fact that the majority regard those who are serviceable 5i8 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 9. to us alone as friends. Now of such the happy man will indeed have no need, because he lias all goods secured The mistake of ^g \aTa. Nor does he need either friends for imagining that tlie . ,, ., T-ii,, happy need no pleasure s Sake, except to a very limited extent, friends arises from for ]iis life feeing pleasant in itself has no need an unworthy view «. iii aj j. t j>'t of friendship. 01 imported pleasure. And not needing iriends of this description he is thought not to need friends at all. But we must explain the original arguments, by -whioli it was conteEded that the blessed have no need of friends. We must point out what they mean and how far they are right. We maintain then that the majority count as friends only those who are useful to them, and consider that friends are loved not for their goodness but for their serviceableness, while sometimes they reckon in those who are loved for the pleasure they give. Such the happy man does not require : not the serviceable, for he has already all that heart can desire ; not the pleasant, for his life is pleasant in itself, and he requires no pleasure from the outside. But not needing such friends as these, he is thought not to need friends who are really friends, who are loved for their virtue's sake and for their goodness. iii. — That the happy do need true friends. {a) MORAL AEGtJMENTS. Yet this is, perhaps, not true ; we stated at the beginning of our Treatise that happiness is a form of activity, 1. Happiness, be- ^nd an activity is clearly for ever coming into ing an activity, is , . j j j. l\ ■' j ■ it. called out by the being, and does not permanently reside with us, contemplation of as a possessiou does. But, if being happy con- the good acts of . , K ,. . , .. ' ° ^^\ ,, our friends. sists in living and exerting ourselves, and the active presence of the good is excellent and plea- sant in itself, as we explained at starting, and if what is nearly related to us is pleasant ; if, once more, we can watch our neigh- bours better than ourselves, their acts better than our own, the conclusion of all this is that the acts of good men, if friends, are pleasant to the good — they contain both the elements which make them naturally pleasant. We conclude, then, that the happy man will require such friends, since he cannot but choose to contemplate excellent actions which he can claim for his own. Such are the acts of a good man if he be his friend. Moreover, men consider that a man to be happy should live pleasantly, but to a solitary man life is laborious. ance'^of ^^T^ ^^ ^^ ^."t.^^^y to be activB for long, when by one's is rendered easier, Self; it is far easier when with others and with more constant 'b' *^^™ *° ^°°^ *^°- Under thcsc latter circum- the company of the stances the activity will be more continuous for s°°'^' being in itself pleasant (and this it should be in the case of the happy man), for the good man, in virtue of being Bk. IX. 9.] Translation. 519 h a good man, must take pleasure in acts tbat embody virtue, while at acts that proceed from vice he feels disgust, yi the same way as a musical man takes pleasure in fair sounds, but is pained by Pjiiscords. tt"; And there will result also a certain practice ^- '^""'^ frfenda of virtue from living with the good, as Theognis other^aTiim^- ■ also says. *»«« "f ^\A-a.z. Yet this is not true, as is plaiti from the following considerations. Happiness, as we said at the beginning of this Treatise, is an activity, and an activity is con- stantly in course of being realised and has its essence in ' becoming,' and has not already come into being nor exists permanently, like a possession : nay, rather, , tappiness consists in living and acting. To be happy is to be living in the practice of virtue and to be doing good acts. But, since such activity is pleasant to the good man, both because it is good and pleasant in itself, as we stated at Btartiag, and also because it suits his character, therefore the contemplation of , Such activity is most pleasant to the happy man : and we can better contemplate the conduct of our neighbour than our own, and his acts than our own acta : consequently the happy man will best contemplate the actions of his friend, and, if they be good, will be most pleased by them. But if the happy man must experience good pleasure, it is plain the happy man will need friends in this capacity, since he wishes to contemplate good acts which touch him nearly, and this is the character of the acts of a good man, if he be his friend. iFurthermore, all regard the life of the happy man as most pleasant. But the life of the happy man consists in employing his faculties in obedience to the law of virtue. It is easier to employ oneself actively when in company with others, ■ more difficult when by oneself : for this reason a life of solitude is difficult ; besides, what is easier is pleasanter than what is difficult, and what is pleasanter is more proper to the happy man. At the same time their activity will be more con- tinuous for being pleasant. And this is appropriate to the happy man to be ; continuously exercised in virtue. And tliis in its turn will make his pleasure the , greater — as the good man, in virtue of being a good man, finds pleasure in acts embodying virtue, while acts which proceed from vice he loathes ; in the same way a musical man finds pleasm-e in fair strains, but is pained by discords. But not only will a happy man by living with the good exercise more con- tinuously a disposition which is already his, he will also acquire one he has not yet got, and vrill enhance the value of that he already has. There will come an increase of virtue fi'om living with the good, as Theognis also says : therefore the happy man lias need of friends. (5) METAPHYSICAL ARGUMENTS, ■ And if we look at the matter from a point of view going deeper into nature, the srood friend seems naturally de- ^ , . ^ ^, .,,,,,' "^j '' Lookmg at the SU-able to the good man. question from a Whatever is naturally good, we have already metaphysical point said, is in itself good and pleasant to the good i/^^'ateverTs"!" Hian. turally good and Life is defined in animals as a power of sensa- pleasant is so to tion, in man as a power 01 sensation or 01 thought ; power is relative to the exercise of it, and the distinctive feature resides in such active exercise ; so that life in its most distinctive form seems to be identical with sensation or thought, 520 The Moral Philoiopky of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 9. Now life is one of those things which are essentially good and pleasant (it is definite and distinct, and the Life, by which we definite is of the nature of the good), and what- mean a power of . , , . , i i sensation and ever IS naturaUij good is so to the good man ; *a™^''*' cod ""'nd ^^^ ^°'^' ^^^^ reason all hold it to be pleasant. pleasant ; it is, (Yet onc ought not to take as an instance of life therefore, good and ^^ gyji and corrupt life nor one passed in pain man. ^°° — such a life is indeterminate like its attributes are — in the next Book we will clear up further the nature of pain.) But if life in itself is good and pleasant (and it seems to be so from the fact that all desire it, and most of all the Bnt the conscious- good and blessed, since to them life is most de- accompanies life sirable and their life the most blessed), and if, ""^* *'® "^*"'^*^'y further, he who sees perceives that he does see; also. " ^ ^^^" he who hears, that he does hear ; he who walks, that he does walk ; and in the case of all other forms of activity, in the same way, there is a something that per- ceives we are active, so that we perceive that we do perceive and think that we do think ; and if, once more, to perceive that we do perceive and to think that we do think is to perceive that we exist — ^for existence consists, as we say, in perception or in thought ; — if again the perception that one is alive is in itself pleasant (for life is naturally a good, and to perceive that one This consciousness , i i i • / ir ■ ■ ■, to ^ must, therefore, be has a good bclongmg to onescit IS m itseJt plea- good and pleasant gant), and if life is desirable, and most of all so to the good man. . .1 j • • l ■ i j. j.i_ i to the good, smce existence is good to them and pleasant as well (for they take a pleasure in sharing the conscious- ness of what is absolutely a good) ; and if, to crown all, a good man feels to his friend exactly as he does to himself, as a friend is to him a second self; — we conclude from all this that exactly as existence for oneself is desirable to each individual, so is one's friend's existence desirable, or very nearly as much so. But existence is, as we shewed, desirable because of our con- sciousness of it as being a good, and such a consciousness is plea- sant in itself. To be happy we should, therefore, share in the consciousness „ ^ ^, . . of our friend's existence, and this will be secured But this conscious- , ,. . ■ ,1 -, ■ n , . .,i i • ness we enjoy in by our living With him and sharing with nim the presence of our words and thoughts. For this would seem to be ™" ^' the meaning of ' living together ' when spoken of men, and not the mere feeding together, which is all it means when applied to the brutes. Now if for the happy man existence is in itself desirable, being Bk. IX. 9.] Translation. 52 1 as H. is, naturally good and pleasant, and the existence of a friend counts nearly for the same as one's own^ E existence — supnosinff, that is, a friend. to be a ^J'"^ presence, P, . ,1 ^" . °' J -rj.! i I,- -u • • -i iJ? then, must be good p? desirable possession : and it that which is m itseii and pleasant to the desirable ought to belong to him, or he wUl so good man, far fall short of perfect happiness — he who is to and so he wui re- be perfectly happy will on this showing require ^^ that't' mly good friends. enjoy it. ' Once more this ■wUl be seen to be the case if we look at the matter from a more metaphysical point of view. Let na regard it in the light of facts which are not peculiar to the happy man, but extend to all equally. Life is by nature jv pleasant to aU living things ; but life may be defined in irrational animals as a *' power of sensation, in men as a power of perception or of thought. But power ^ , is rdative to the exercise of it, and the distinctive feature resides in that exercise. If, then, life consists in the power of perceiving or thinking, much more does it consist in actually perceiving, actually thinking. Actual perceiving, then, or actual thinking, constitutes life, and life is pleasant in itself and good, most of aE because life is a something determinate. But the determinate enters into the nature of the good, as the Pythagoreans also thought ; they classed the deter- » . .minate in the rank, or file, of goods. In the next place it is proved by the con- sideration that aU things desire life, and what all desire is good in itself and |i ' pleasant ; but when I talk of life, I mean not a bad life or one full of ten ll' thousand misfortunes. Such lives are indeterminate, li!i;e the accidents that occur in them. But we will discuss these points when we come to speak about pleasure. Since, then, life is in itself good and pleasant, and each feels delight and pleasure in witnessing in himself anything good and pleasant, therefore we are delighted and pleased by perceiving that we are alive. For we do perceive i?' ',;that we are aUve, just as, when we see, we perceive that we see ; when we hear, we perceive that we hear ; when we walk, that we walk ; and when we think or ■ perceive, we know that we think or perceive. But to perceive, or to think, itself B jS constitutes the existence of beings which perceive or think. We perceive, there- " " ■ fore, that we exist, and we have in us a power by which we know that we are active and that we are alive. But if life is a good, and to be conscious of a good in oneself is in itself pleasant, to know that we are alive is pleasant. Seeing, then, that what is naturally good and pleasant is good and pleasant to the good man, the good man will take pleasure in being alive, and even more so than other men, ;; inasmuch as his life is more desirable, more pleasant, more blessed than theirs. He will, therefore, also take pleasure in knowing that he is alive, and, as life consists in thinking, in knowing that he is thinking. Moreover the good man feels to his friend as he does towards himself, for the friend is a kind of second self ; it is, therefore, plain that as it is pleasant to him to live himself, to be and to be alive, in the same way he seeks for the existence of Ms friend — that is, that his friend should think. For existence and life are identical with thought. And as he takes delight in knowing that he thinks, so it is pleasant and agreeable to him to know that his friend thinks. But the knowledge that one's friend is thinking is made actual knowledge, when one knows what he is thinking about, not merely that his mind is active. This will be attained by living with one another, sharing in each other's reasonings and thoughts. This is the sense in wMoh we talk of men ' living together.' To be in one and the same plaoeis not to ' live together,' as we talk of beasts living together when they feed in the same pasture. To be in the company of friends, then, is desirable for the good man, and pleasant. But that which is desirable for him, this he ought to possess. If not he will so far be deficient, and this is opposed to the idea of happiness. The man, therefore, who is to be happy will require good friends, 522 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 10. iv. — The number of Friends desirable. Their number must neces- sarily be limited. (a) GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS ON THE SUBJECT. Must we, then, make as many friends as possible; or, as it would seem to have been well said in respect of It is not possible hereditary connexions, to nave more than " ' a limited number « Neither a man of many guest-friends nor yet wholly without them," SO too in the case of friendship will it befit us to be neither without friends, nor to be given to many friends fit'flake' ^" ^"" °^^^ '^"'^^ ' ^°^ ^^ f^'' ^ friends for advantage are concerned, the saying would seem to be thoroughly applicable. To return the services of many is a matter of difficulty, and life itself is not long enough to effect this. So that more than are required to meet the needs of our own proper life are superfluous and a hindrance in the way of living nobly. There is, therefore, no need of them. And of friends for pleasure few suffice, like a little pleasure's sake, no, flavouring in food. But in case of the good, nor of friends on should we make friends with the greatest possible groun s VI ue. pmnijer, or is there a limit to the number of friends, as there is a limit to the size of a state? A state cannot be made out of ten men ; when extended to ten thousand men it ceases to be a state any longer. The exact number which con- stitute a state is not, perhaps, any single quantity, but anything that comes between certain assignable limits. So too of possible friends there is a certain permissible number, the superior limit being, perhaps, represented by the number with which it is pos- sible to live as a permanence ; for this is, as we saw, the most essential thing in friendship. But since the happy man does need friends, we must inquire whether he should make friends with as many as he possibly can, or whether — as in the case of hereditary connexions, it has been said well and justly that a man should neither be without guest-friends nor yet guest-friend with all the world —so in the case of regular friendship too it is reasonable that he should neither be without friends nor yet friends with the whole world. We may begin by obsei-ving, that since friendship is divided into three kinds — one having profit for its object, a second pleasure, a third goodness and virtue — of friends for pleasure or for profit's sake our needs are limited, most of aU of friends for profit, because a man can help only a few in what they want, and to do services to many is laborious, particularly if they happen to be euperfluous, and should expect to be treated wath undue attention. Of friends for pleasure's sake a limited number suffice, because only a little pleasure and relaxation is necessary in life, just like a little flavouring in cooking. But of good, friends, who love us on grounds of virtue and goodnessj the Bk. IX. 10.] Translation. 523 i happy man will require more. Yet there will be a limit even to them. For just as there is a limit to a state, and a state can neither be made out of ten men, nor out of ten thousand, for suoh an aggregation of popnlatio* would cease to be f . a state any more, so our friends too must be restricted, and a certain limit must be set to them. And just as in the case of a state the exact amount of its ^: citizens cannot be determined, and you cannot state the precise number which a Btate may properly have, but only fix a number which it is not to exceed and a ', number which it is not to fall short of, and take all that lies between these limits as the number the state may possess — in the same way in the case of friends it is ( not possible to name a precise number, but they may be as many as a man can \ comfortably live with. To live with one's friends is, as we saw, the most essential condition for friendship. I' (i) PRACTICAL CONSIDERATIONS WHICH LIMIT THE NUMBER OP OUR FRIENDS. The reasons why it is not possible to live in company of many, and to divide oneself among them, are obvious ^' enough. It is further needful that they should number^ ranl^eep also be friends with one another, if they are to friends with one pass their days in one another's society. This ™° ^^' is a condition whicli it is difficult to have fulfilled, where many are concerned. It is difficult moreover to feel real sympathy with the sorrows and the joys of many at once, as it is very likely to happen that, at one and (2) ""r powers of the same time, one would have to be feeling joy ;tociJ'^ ^ ^^^ ™" with one, and sorrow with another. Perhaps, then, it is as well not to seek to be as widely friends as possible, but to limit one's friendship to the numbers one can comfortably live with. It would seem not even to be possible to be very close friends with many, any more SLs''io°giw'into than it would be possible to be in love with an intense feeling many. Friendship has a tendency to run into ii^^t^L^'if^ll;^;'" intensity, and this intense friendship can be felt for but one at a time, and close friendship with but few. That it is not possible to live with a large number and to divide oneself among them is clear enough. We ought besides to pass our days in the company of our * friends. If they are very many, this becomes irksome in the extreme. Further, We ought to feel close sympathy with their sorrows and their joys, and this again becomes difficult if one has many friends. For when they are many, some of them will be experiencing joy, others sorrow at one and the same time, and a friend should be portioning himself out to both of them, sjid this is matter of ||.' difBcnlty. Perhaps, then, it is as well not to seek to be veiy extended in one's friendships, but to admit only so many to our friendship as we can live with and pass our days with and share in their sorrows and their joys. But to treat many in this way is not. possible, any more than it is possible to be on a footing of loving friendship with many. The position of lovers is friendship pushed to an extreme, and consequently can be experienced only towards one at a time. In the same way, in the case of friendship that rests on virtue, it is not possible to love many dearly, and to observe' all the obligations of friendship in respect of them, but it is possible to treat a few in this way. 52^ The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 11. (c) VERIFICATION OF THE POSITION FROM FACTS AND EXPERIENCE. And this seems to be the case in the facts of actual life. Large , „, , ,. , numbers do not bind themselves in the ties of I. The relation of ii- -t ,^ p ■ ■, -t ■ n « comvadeshiij em- comradeship, and the iriendsliips ot renown, of braces only a few. -which poets sing, have been between two only, nowned ™°friend- Those who have a wide circle of friends, and ships have teen re- strike up an intimacy with any one, are thought stricte to two. ^^ -^^ ^^.^^ friends with no one, to be at most on terms of ' civility.' Such are called complaisant. Nay, on these terms of ' civility ' you may be friends with many, and tliat without being complaisant, but 3. While you can {xQxsx real goodness of heart. But on grounds of be 'civil to a large . ^ T j» ii • i , ■, number, you must Virtue and lor their own sakes you cannot be be content to find friends with many. You must be thankful if few true fnends. n ^ e i j • i you can nnd a lew such iriends. These considerations are confirmed by tbe facts of experience. Large numbers do not enter into the ties of comradeship, and the most celebrated friendships of this character are said to have been formed between, only two. Those who are friends with the whole world and strike up a friendship with all they come across, and in words and deeds "seem to give each one of the citizens his precise due, have a proper and true friendship with no one, but may be caJled friends in respect of what is called ' civil ' friendship. Of these some are complaisant, seeking to gratify all they are thrown with. About them we have spoken in a former book. Others are good, and have regard to truth and virtue in their conversation. They are called friends from the likeness of their be- haviour to friendship, and they are praiseworthy — they come intermediate, between the complaisant and the disagreeable, both of whom are blamed, as was shewn in the eighth chapter of the 4th Book. Any one may find many of such friends as these, but of real fi-iends we should be grateful if we find even a few, V. — The Uses and the Treatment of Friends. (a) THE ADVANTAGES OF FRIENDS IN PROSPERITY AND IN ADVER- SITY COMPARED. Are friends more needful in prosperity or in adversity ? We require them under both circumstances. Those Friends are more ^-y^^ ^^^ -^ misfortune require assistance, while necessary in mis- i /. • -r fortune, more the prosperous need friends to live with and as honourable in pros- objects for their kindness, since they have a wish to be doing good. In misfortune they are more indispensable, and therefore under these circumstances we require serviceable friends. In prosperity it is more honourable to possess them, and so in that case we seek out the good. The good are • the more desirable objects for our benevolence, the more desirable company to live with. Bk. IX. 11.] Translation. 525 But since the prosperous and the unfortunate have alike need of friends, we must inquire under wMcli circumstances friends are more needful. The un- fortunate require the assistance which is to be got frqp friends, and the prosperous require companions to live with, and objects for their benevolence. They are anxious to be doing good, and it is necessary to their happiness. In a certain way the unfortunate has more need of friends than the good man, in another way the prosperous has the greater need. The one on account of their indispensableness, the other on account of their honourablenesa. You must raiderstaud that friends are more indispensable to the unfortunate than to the prosperous. (5) THE USE OF FEIENDS IN ADVERSITY. The presence of friends is by itself pleasant even in naisfortunes ; those who grieve have their griefs lightened by friends sharing in their sorrows. And so it L',,rnl'fort might be asked whether they do not bear, if one in misfortune ; it may so say, an actual part of the burden, or l^^tens the load of whether it be that their presence being pleasant and the sense of their sympathy with our grief make the grief less. The question, however, whether it be for this reason or for some other that a man's load is lightened by the presence of friends may be dismissed ; in any case the fact is as we have stated it. Still their presence seems to give rise to mixed feelings. On the one hand the sight of friends is pleasant, ^ , ,ni,i ■• • n L. -\ ■ Still a brave man most of all when one is in misfortune, and is an cannot but regard assistance against giving way to grief. A friend their presence with is comforting both by look and by word, if he be "'"* ®® '"^^' a man of tact, as he knows our disposition and what gives us pleasure or pain. On the other hand, to see our friend grieved at our misfortunes is painful, for every one hates being an occasion of grief to a friend. For this ^e will give them reason manly characters are careful how they p^in ™''«<=^^s^^ summon their friends to share their griefs, and unless they be superior to their friends in the power of withstanding grief, do not suffer the pain of the sight of their misfortunes to be given to their friends ; and as a rule he does not call in others to make lamentation with him, because he is not inclined to make lamentations himself. On the iior does he encou- other hand weak women and men who are like umentatTons. "'''''" them delight in having others to groan with them and love them as sympathising friends. Yet we need scarcely remark, 'tis the better man's example we should follow in all things. -'&'- The very presence of friends is pleasant, even in misfortunes. Those who grieve have their grief lightened by their friends sharing their sorrows. For this reason a question may be raised, why it is that the gig-ht of our friends grieving 526 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle, [Bk. IX. 11. witJi us is an alleviation of our griefs. Grief is thought to be, a kind of burden ■which is lightened by being shared with one's friends. Yet this is not really the case. The fact is that the presence of friends and the sight of their sympathy with our grief being pleasant, make the grief less, for pleasure drives out pain. However, whether it be for this or for any other reason that our griefs are assuaged, we may forbear to ask for the present. In amy case, that those who grieve are comforted by the presence of friends is obvious. Yet it would seem that the good cannot take unmixed delight in their friends grieving with them, and that this pleasure is not without alloy — rather they grieve over it in part. In itself the sight of friends is pleasant, most of all to the unfortunate, and we find in them assistance against yielding to grief. A friend is comforting — the very sight of him and his words, if he be a man of tact. He knows his friend's character, what he is pained at, what he is pleased with, and so can easily comfort him. In this respect, then, the presence of friends is pleasant. On the other hand th,e seeing one's friend pained at our misfortunes makes his presence to that extent painful. For every one finds it painful to be the cause of pain to one's friends. Consequently manly characters are very careful how they invite their friends to share in their griefs, and unless the consolation gained be great and for the greatest misfortunes, and the pain caused to them, if they do share their griefs, small, they cannot briag themselves to make their friends partakers of their own troubles, and in any case they do not desire those who will make lamentation with them, because they are not themselves given to wailing, but bear up bravely against their ills. But weak women and womanly men take absolute pleasure in having people to groan along with them and love them as truly sympathetic friends. StiU we should imitate not these but the manly, for in all things we should follow the better example. In this way then friends are a help to the unfortunate. (c) THEIR USE m PROSPERITY. In prosperity the presence of friends enables us to pass our time more pleasantly, and gives us the sense of tiI7^1 Z ttieir being pleased at the blessings we enjoy. grounds — as com- panions to spend ^'^ prosperity the presence of friends is pleasant in two time with, and as ways : first because it is most pleasant to pass our time with l)artners in our joy. our friends just because they are our friends ; secondly be- cause we see them rejoicing at the blessings we enjoy, and this is the highest proof of goodwill. {d) GENERAL DIRECTIONS FOR OUR CONDUCT TO OUR FRIENDS. Accordingly it would seem that we ought to be forward to call (1) Be eager to in- ^° °^^ friends to share our good fortune (for it vite your Mends to is honourable to be forward to do kindnesses,) but share your good to hesitate before summoning them to share our (2) Wow to in- misfortunes— for we should impart our troubles vite them to share to others as little as may be — and hence the your misfortunes, saying of the poet, " I am enough to be unfortunate." Most readily may a man summon them, when at the cost of slight grief to themselves they may do him great service. Bk. IX, 12.] Translation. 527 Contrariwise, one ought to go to one's friends in adversity iinsummoned and of one's own accord. It is a friend's business to do kindnesses— most of al> tisit''you"frfends to those in need, who have not requested our in adversity, be services. It is more pleasant and more honour- ^1^'^° ™f *^*^™ able for both. Further, one should be ever ready to join in promoting a friend's prosperity — ^as it is for this that friends are needful, but one should be loath to put oneself under obligations to one's friend, as [*) ^^ ^^^l *" it is not honourable to be eager to be helped, te ^low "0 recede Still one should, perhaps, be on one's guard favours from him, , , .1 i? ' J • L • ^ yet not to the ex- against the appearance ot discourtesy m- repel- tent of discourtesy. ling such offers : for this sometimes happens. We have thus shown that the presence of Summary. friends is desirable under all circumstances. Seeing, tlien, that we grieve when we make our friends partners in our misfortunes, rejoice when we share with them our prosperity, it would seem that we ought eagerly to invite them to be spectators of our good fortune, but to be slow to do this in our adversities. To do good offices is honourable, but we should make others as little as possible partakers of our woes. Accordingly also the tragedian says, ' I ani enough to be unfortunate.' One ought not to fill one's friend with one's own private woes. Then, most of all may we summon our friends to share our griefs when they can greatly relieve our distress at slight fain to themselves. Contrariwise, however, friends ought to volunteer good offices to their friends when in misfortune, if free from misfortune themselves. One ought to seek out the unfortunate unasked and of one's own free will. It is a friend's part to do good offices, most of all to those in need who make no request. This is more pleasant and more honourable for both parties — for those who give and for those who receive. "When affairs are prospering with them we should go to our friends, and should be ready to help and abet them in securing their prosperity. We should have more scruple in accepting favours at their hands. It is not honour- able to show eagerness to be assisted. But if we show zeal and energy in assisting our friends, we should perhaps not reject or thrust aside their offers of services, lest we should seem to be discourteous to our friends. For this is sometimes the case. vi.— Of the society of Friends. Is it not the case, then, that just as lovers take special delight in the sight of the objects of their affection, and take more delight in the perceptions of this Constant inter- ,, . o ,1 ii 1 1 ■ -i course is essential sense than in any ot the others — love having its to friendship, being and originating cause in sight more than in any of the other senses — in the same way fellowship is more delightful to friends than anything besides ? Friendship means a community of interests, and one should feel towards one's friend as one does towards oneself. But in one's own case the consciousness that one exists is desirable, so too therefore is the consciousness that one's friend exists. But this consciousness 528 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. IX. 12. only becomes actual by their living together, so it is with good reason they desire this. Moreover, in whatever the existence of each is most truly centred and with a view to whatever in par- ticular they severally desire to live, in this above all they seek for their friends' society. Hence it is that some ^:Z t' \ts" drink together, others play dice together, others pursuits to which join together in the sports of the gymnasium, or voted ^'^^ '^ '^^ \\\ya.t together, or philosophise together, each passing their time together in those particular, occupations which they love best of all those that fill up their life. Wishing to live a common life with their friends, they do those things together and share those occupations in which they consider that that common life is realised the most. As a consequence of this, the friendship of bad men turns out „ , evil in its results. They participate in what is Such intercourse ., , l ^^ • \li -pi,- it among the evil evil, and are unstable m their loundations. And leads, it is true, they are made evil also by growing like one another. But the company of good men is good, strengthening with their growing intercourse. They seem fur- ther to improve by calling out one another's good iT^enhanoes activities and by correcting one another's de- knd promotes vir- fects. They take their stamp from one another, each feeling delight in the other. And so the saying of the poet — " From good, good things proceed." Thus much on the subject of friendship. It follows, then, from what has been said, that to live with one another is most desirable in the eyes of friends. And as lovers delight in the sight of one another's countenances, and they prefer to hold intercourse by this rather than by any other of the senses, implying thereby that through this sense love is boih bom in the first instance and is brought to maturity, so too among friends a common life is more desirable than any 'of the other means of promoting friendship. To live together is a form of communion and the most perfect form of communion, and friendship has its essence in communion, for friendship is communion. There are other grounds for this, but the chief one is that to be conscious of oneself is most desirable, as we have shown above : but our feelings to our friend are the same as our feelings to ourselves : cqusequently to be conscious of one's friend's existence will be desirable beyond everything else. And one becomes actually conscious of one's friend's existence by being with him, by living with him, and by passing one's time with him. So friends have good reason for desiring to live with one another. Consequently whatever view each takes of the proper object of man's activity, and on whatever grounds he chooses life and whatever he regards as the proper career for man, in this he wishes to live and to spend his time along with his friends. Some think that they ought to carouse with their friends, others that t'ley should play dies with them, others vrish to hunt or practise at the gymna- sium with them, because these we the objects that are valuable in their eyep, sncl Bk. IX. 12.] Translation. 529 it IB in such that they consider they ought to have the companionship of their friends, others again claim their companionship in philosophising ; and some make their friends participate in one kind of activity and life, others in other kinds, and in short each wish to pass their days with their friends in that particular pursuit they love the best of all the varied objects of their life. Wishing to live with their friends, they do those things and get them to partake in those things which are pleasant to both of them. On these terms it is possible to live together. Hence the friendship of the bad turns out evil, and they participate with one another in evil, and their friendship is not steadfast ; they are inconstant, and theyl degenerate by growing like one another and by encouraging one another in evil courses. But the friendship of the good is good and steadfast, ever growing with?the growth of their intimacy ; and they seem to improve by their efforts towards good, correcting one another's faults. They receive from one another the stamp of each other's good qualities, for the sake of which they love one another. Hence a certain poet says, 1 " From good, good things proceed." From good we reap good results ; from evil, evU results. On Friendship let this suffice. The subject next in order for us to discuss will be Pleasure. BOOK X. L— CONCERNING PLEASURE. II.— CONCERNING HAPPINESS. III.— CONCERNING THE BORDER-LAND BETWEEN ETHICS AND POLITICS. INTRODUCTORY ANALYSIS. I. — Concerning Pleasure. Thbee are several grounds upon whicli we are bound to proceed to the consideration of Pleasure. It is £tn essential element of human life : it is an indispensable instrument of education : its proper direction and control are of the greatest importance in relation to a virtuous and happy life. In addition to its proper claims to consideration, it has the further claim of having been the object of much oontroversy.- Opinions about it have varied widely : on the one hand Eudoxus has maintained it to be the Chief Good : on the other hand the Platonists have maintained it to be an unmixed evil. [This latter view has pro- bably been maintained to some extent on educational grounds : what- ever be the real nature of pleasure, they may have thought, men are naturally so prone to it that the true policy of a moralist is to draw them away from it by representing it as an evil This is, however, a mistaken policy : men will not be deluded by false pictures : they test theories by experience and observation : and a demonstrably false theoiy which is put forward, with however excellent an intention, not only fails of its purpose but brings the truth itself into discredit.] We shall begin, according to our custom, by examining these two theories of the nature of pleasure. I. Eudoxus used four arguments to prove his thesis : and it may be added that the excellence of his personal character gave his arguments a force which was not inherent in them, by making it clear that they were not a mere cloak for voluptuousness. (1.) 'Since every object of desire is a good, the supreme object of desire will be the Chief Good. But pleasure is the supreme object of Introductory Analysis: Book X. 531 desire. It is consequently the Chief Good.' As far as the major premiss goes, this argument is sound. The appeal to universal .^ experience is valid and proper. • (2.) ' The same line of argument may be used in reference to pain : it is the object of universal avoidance as being an evil : the inference may be drawn that its opposite, pleasure, is a good.' This opposition between pain and pleasure has been denied : but upon insufficient ^grounds. If, as is sometimes alleged, they were both evils, then both 'would be avoided : but, as a fact, one of them is avoided, the other is not : consequently the opposition between them is real. (3.) ' Pleasure is desired not as a means to something else, but in and for itself This must be admitted of certain forms of pleasure. (4.) ' Whatever makes every other good more desirable must be the Chief Good : pleasure does so, and is therefore the Chief Good.' But it may be urged in reply that, assuming the minor premiss to be true, it only proves pleasure to be a good : every good is more desirable when joined to another good. At the same time Plato's use of the argument to prove that pleasure is not the Chief Good cannot be admitted, because it proceeds upon a couoeption of the Chief Good which is transcendental and impossible to be realized in human life : whereas th'e Chief Good of which we are in search is essentially human. II. The theory of the Platonists is supported by several arguments which we will examine in turn. (1.) ' Pleasure is not a quality, and is therefore not a good, since all goods are qualities.' This argument proves too much : for it would exclude justice or happiness itself ^-om the list of goods. [In other words, justice or any other virtue is only a good so far as a man consciously exercises it : that conscious exercise is not a quality but an activity : the fact, therefore, that pleasure is not a quality but an asfcivity does not prove it to be not a good.] (2.) ' Pleasure is indeterminate : it admits of degrees of intensity : but every good is determinate : therefore pleasure is not a good,' This argument also proves too much : for it is applicable to virtues as well as to pleasures : and, moreover, it makes no distinction between pure pleasures which do not admit' of greater or less perfection, and pleasures which are alloyed with pain, which are realized, as health is, in varying degrees in different individuals. (3.) ' Pleasure is a movement and process of becoming : as such it is necessarily incomplete, and is consequently not a good.' The assump- tion is not true : pleasure is neither a movement nor a process of becoming : some pleasures may be so, at least in a metaphorical sense, , but other pleasures are not so : consequently the definition cannot be true of pleasure in itself. (4.) ' If pleasure were a good, no pleasures would be bad : but some pleasures are bad.' In the first place the minor premiss is not true : what are called bad pleasm-es are pleasures only to morbid minds. In the second place a distinction must be drawn between pleasures them- selves and the means by which they are procured. ' There are other arguments which are adduced to prove the same thesis, and which may be criticised in a similar way. The general M u 2 532 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. result of the examination of current opinions on the subject seems to be that (1.) Pleasure is not the Chief Good : (2.) Pleasures differ in kind : some being choiceworthy for their own sake : some not being proper objects of choice at aU. But let us proceed to examine in a more positive way — What is pleasure in itself? In the first place it is, like sight, complete at each moment of its exercise : consequently it is not a movement or ' process of becoming,' for movement is at each moment incomplete. In the second place it ia the result of a perfect and healthy consciousness, acting in the presence of the highest object which can come within its range : it supervenes upon such a consciousness, and marks the perfection of its activity. Consequently, this perfect state of any form of consciousness being, as our nature is constituted, transient and not permanent, pleasure is transient also. It follows the weakening and the waning of the con- sciousness upon which it supervenes. On the other hand the desire for pleasure is as universal and as constant as the desire for the full activity of consciousness, which is, in other words, the desire for life. The two desires are inextricably intertwined : which of them is prior or superior, is difficult to determine. It follows from this account of the nature of pleasure that 'pleasures not only vary in intensity, but also differ in kind. There are different forms of consciousness, and different kinds of feeling that supervene upon and mark the perfection of those different forms. That they are different in kind as ■well as in degree is proved not only by the difference in their antecedents but by the difference in then- effects : some pleasures are antagonistic to other pleasures, and that which under other circumstances might be a pleasure is, when it is alien to an existing pleasure, of the nature of a pain. Again, the moral qualities of pleasures vary as the moral qualities of states of consciousness vary : some are desirable, others blameworthy, others indifferent. They vstry also as types of character vary : for each species of animals, whose nature is simple and who are ruled by instinct, there may be one kind of pleasure : but for man, with his complex nature and his free power of choice, pleasures are as various in kind as are the forms of his activity. The highest kind of pleasure is that of the highest type of character — the character of the virtuous man : all other binds of pleasure are secondary and subordinate, and must be referred to that highest kind as a standard. II. — Conoemiag Happiness. It remains for us to consider briefly the nature of happiness. It has been shown in preceding Books that happiness must be not a passive state of mind, but an activity, and not only an activity, but an activity which is desirable for its owh sake. This view of the nature of happiness is so universally held as to have led many persons to confound happiness with pleasure : for pleasure also is an activity, though at the Introductory Analysis: Book X, 533 same time what is commonly called pleasure does not satisfy the other requisites of happiness, for it is not desirable for its own sake, nor is it on activity of the higher and better parts of ou? nature, or such a one as a perfectly virtuous man, who is the true standard, would approve. The activity which constitutes happiness is the activity of a perfectly developed life — one which has reached the highest form of which it is capable. The highest form of the life of man is Reason : the activity of Reason, or in other words the life of philosophic meditation, will con- sequently be the realization of happiness. There are many corrobora- tions of this view : such an activity is not only the highest form of activity, but also the most abiding and the most pleasurable : it is self- ■ sufficient, for though the bodily part of the philosopher will still require food and rest, his life qm philosopher will be independent of all external circumstances : it is desirable for its own sake : it is free from care. Other forms of life may have greater iclat and seem to fill a more im- portant place in human society : but they all have drawbacks from which the life of philosophic meditation is free, and which make it im- possible that they should be the perfect and final aim of man. Indeed, the life of which we are speaking vindicates for itself the position which we have claimed for it by almost rising out of the sphere of humanity and approaching what is divine : the fact that it does so is an additional obligation to pursue it, by proving it to be the highest life which is possible to us, and that which is most distinctively our own. There are, no doubt, other forms of happiness. For man is a social being, and there are virtues which rise out of his relations to society, and the life which consists in the exercise of those virtues must be, as far as it goes, a happy life. But* such happiness, however real, is secondary «Dd subordinate to the happiness which we have been describing : the former is relative to human life, the latter is absolute : the former is more or less the creature of circumstances, the latter is independent of them. Moreover the life of philosophic meditation is the life of the Gods, who should be our pattern and to whose level we should aspire : we shall be blessed in proportion as we approach them, and we shall approach them in proportion as we share their ' Beatific Vision.' The external conditions of this life must be such as to give it play. A philosopher will not want wealth, but he must have a sound body, and sufficient means to satisfy the wants of that body without exertion or care. Excess of wealth or power is not necessary even for the development of moral virtue : much less for philosophical meditation. But requiring as he does only moderate means, a philosopher need not be anxious about them : let him have faith in the providence of the Gods, who will not desert one who is striving to be like them. III.— Concerning the Border-land between Ethics and Politics. If our Treatise ended here, its purpose would seem to be not practical but speculative. But since the reverse is the case, we must go on to consider how the ideal which we have sketched of virtue and happiness is to be actually realized in human life. Neither theory nor argument 534 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. will bring about such a realization, for. the mass of men are dead to moral appeals and cannot be reformed by logic. The link between theory and practice is law : for the instrument of law is fear : and fear alone is the ultimate deterrent from Tice. But law may be made to act in forming habits : and the formation of habits is in fact education. The province of law is thus identical with the province of education. Other means of making men good are sometimes discussed : some persons think that goodness is a gift of nature : some, again, think that it is a product of teaching : but it will be found that habituation, and especially early habituation, is the only real power. This process of forming moral habits by the agency of law, acting through rewards and punishments, should begin when persons are young ; but it does not cease when they become older : in fact it goes on all through life. The chief difference in its operation i^ that the particular rewards and punishments vary with various classes of persons and with various periods of life. The function* Qf the State will be to provide and to apply such rewards and ^nishments ; it must cover the •vrhole of a man's life, ordering it from first to last by the rule of reason, and by the force of physical coercion. (- No other authority but that of the State is competent for the task: the authority of a father or the will of an individual is deficient in power of coercion : and indeed we tend to rebel against any constraint except that which the State puts upon us. But the majority of States fail of their duty : they all have laws, but those laws do not sufficiently cover the ground of moral education. The defect has to be supplied by private education, and, where the State fails, it is not only the function but the duty of the private citizen to do his best for the moral education of both his children and his friends. ' Such private education, as we have seen, is deficient in coercive power ; but it is analogous to, and follows the same principle as, educatioii by the State. Both the one and the other are based en law J and consequently, any one who takes part in private education must cultivate the spirit of the legislator. He must acquaint himself with general principles, and with the application of such principles; to particular cases. From whom is he to learn such principles ? Should we not say, primA fade, from those who profess and apply them, i.e. from practical states- men? But there is this difficulty, that hitherto statesmen have known such principles only empirically. Beyond question experience is the basis upon which the principles of legislation must be based ; but on the other hand it is insufficient for the student without a knowledge of causes. The materials lie ready to hand, but the science is not yet built. The sophists indeed have professed to teach the subject; but their theories are useless because they have ignored experience, and disregarded the conditions of the problem. We have therefore ourselves, for the first time, to construct from the materials which experience has furnished a Science of StatesmansMp» and to find out by the help of that science what is the ideal state of society, and by what laws that ideal state will fashion the lives of its citizens to the standard of perfect virtue. We proceed at once, therefore, from Ethics to Politics. TEANSLATION. kd'. I— CONCEENING PLEASURE. Ss' i.— Conneotion of Pleastire wltli tlie theory of Morals. 1. The sutject whicli foUaws next in order for us to discuss is perhaps Pleasure. It is thought that Pleasure is bound up in closest union with the nature of essential element man. Hence, in educating the young, we use °* human life; 1 J . ,, ,1 . • ^ n ■ hence its Import- pleasure and pain as the rudders to guide their ance in edacation lives (through the storms of passion). and in the forma- 2. Furthermore, as a help to the formation of *'™ " * ' ' personal character, it is thought to be of the highest moment that men should have the feelings of joy or of aver- sion in reference to the proper objects. These pleasure and the feelings in fact spread over the whole course of avoidance of pain TP Ti j>i-j] liT are the strongest lite, and have a poweriul mnuence and tendency and most pema- to make a life virtuous and happy. The objects "^nt motives to which men set before themselves as the objects of their choice are things pleasurable : the objects they seek to avoid are things painful. 3. But since pleasures and pains involve such issues, it would seem not to be right on any account to omit their jSonsideration, more particularly as the subject is of pleasure is one that opens up much discussion. strongly oontro- (1.) Some philosophers declare Pleasure to be [lo Some maintain the * absolute good.' pleasure to be the (2.) Others on the contrary declare it to be an ^2™™otherr"view unqualified evil. it as an unmixed evil. Of these rival theorists, those who uphold pleasure do so, perhaps, with a genuine conviction that it is the source of all good. Their opponents are influenced by the opinion that it is better, in view of practical life, to exhibit pleasure among things that are evn, even though in fact it be not, and by observing that the 536 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 2. mass of men are naturally predisposed to yield to pleasure and to become slaves of their appetites. They arffue, Those -who decry . j.r j. -i. • • i-i. j. j i.u pleasure do 30 often m consequence, that it IS right to draw them from prudential ^ a contrary direction, in the hope that they considerations, and ,, i i.i i. x- -a in order to conn- ™ay, through these counteracting influences, teraot the undue attain to a proper moderation, pursuit it. J (Jq^Ijj. ■^^iiether such a theory is prudent or politic. Theories that bear on human emotions and practical con- duct are les^ credited than observed facts. When defeats its own therefore, theories are at variance with the facts t""^^' t- ^^^*' come under personal observation they are ters men always derided and bring the truth itself into an equal bring theories to discredit. For example, if the philosopher who the test of their , • i • i^. i j j. j.- ownexperienceaud consures pleasure IS himselt observed at any time the obsei-vations of to be eager for some pleasure of his own, he is which manifeTt^ thought to have such a leaning for it, as though contradicts expe- it were altogether and entirely a thing to covet. pTon? the'^°i^ten- •'•^ ^^'^ c^^.^^ it is not characteristic of the world tion) brings disore- generally to make fine distinctions, dit on the author. Theories, however, that are true and can be verified, are of extreme utility, not merely with a view to know- ing our duty, but also in their bearing on practical TJeories, however, jifg. Being consistent with the facts of expe- that are cased on . ,. ° ,., , , ii x- fact, are accepted nenco they are accredited, and consequently stimu- by the reason and la^g thoso who Understand their importance, to made a rule of ,. ■ j -j-i- i.i • i i j life. live m accordance with their standard. But enough of general remarks. Let us proceed to the discus- sion of the theories that have been maintained on this subject of pleasure. In what follows, we must, aooording to the scheme of our argnment, disonss more fully the nature of Pleasure ; for Pleasm-e is in a sense congenital, and an essential element in our nature. This is the reason why, as teachers of the yotmg,. we guide them by Pleasure and Pain ; leading them, by infliction of the latter, away from what is base, and by means of the former inciting them to what fe. noble. Which process clearly proves that by nature we shrink from pain and pursue after pleasure. Therefore, since our Treatise concerns the emotions of mankind and their actions as well, it is but reasonable and consistent with oui scheme, that we should accurately discriminate in the matter of Pleasure, afEeoting as it does both emotions and actions. Further, it appears to contribute in no small degree to the acquisition of Moral Virtue, that we should feel delight and dislike just when suoh feelings are appropriate. For these feelings are co- extensive with human life : joy and sorrow, in their respective objects, are always with us : and, if felt duly and fittingly, both in kind and amount, and consistently with Eight Reason, they contribute largely to the formation of the virtuous character, and to the life of true happiness. Nor would it be at all reasonable to omit such a subject as Pleasure : for, in its consideration, there is nothing so simple or obvious as not to require copious Bk. X. 2.] Translation. 537 and weighty discussion. On the contrary, so great, somehow, is the divergence of opinion about Pleasure, that some aflfirm it to be the very Chief Good, while others affirm that it is not a ' good ' at all, but exactly the opposite an intrinsically base thing. Of those who maintain the latter view, some do actually themselves believe it, having been convinced that pleasure is a base thing ; whUe others, believing, " themselves, that this or that pleasure may be good, yet wish to persuade their neighbours that all pleasure is bad, thinking that this is a safer canon for the conduct of life, and that men in general would be advantaged by a conviction that Pleasure is a base thing. This they support by pleading the natural propensity of all men to pleasure, and consequently, how essential it is to give them a stoong wrench in the opposite direction, by drawing them, once for all, by all available means, away from pleasures, and enabling them thereby to reach the condition which we called ' the mean state,' and so to adopt eventually the right attitude towards Pleasure in the abstract. This plea is fallacious. Such a process will never wean the majority of mankind from base pleasures. Human emotions and actions cany more conviction to those who behold them, than do arguments about them. Whenever therefore such teachers are f ovmd to condemn Pleasure by their words, but to approve it by their practice and by their feelings towards it, they contradict themselves, and become a laughing-stock to those who hear their words, and see their conduct ; and such teachers progress not one step towards aiding mankind, for all their words, the insincerity of which is proved by their actions. He who condemns Pleasure, if at any time he is detected in its pursuit, is concluded to have deserted to its side, and to be approving it as a good ; nay, more, he causes those, who observe his defection, to imagine, not merely that some pleasure may be a good, but that all Pleasure may be approved as such. For distinction and discrimination — as, that one class of pleasure may be good, while another pleasure may possibly be base — are too subtle for the multitude : which no sooner sees a man of mind delighting in some pleasure, than it leaps to the conclusion that aU pleasure is a thing good in itself and choice-worthy. ■Whereby such teachers as we have described not only fail to establish their own views, but bring the truth to naught, into the bargain. Thus it is clear that true moral theories, and such only, can have real usefulness to the mind, in purging it of all error, and can also have a profitable influence on the conduct of life. Such theories win acceptance by being seen to coincide with the best actions of those who hold them. Enough however about erroneous views : let us return to the discussion of Pleasure itself ; and, iirst, we will set forth the opinions of the ancients about it. ii,— Exandnation of the theory of Eudoxus that Pleasure is the Summum Bonum. (a) STATEMENT OF THE ARGUMENTS OF EUDOXUS. Now Eudoxus regarded pleasure as the summum bonum, and used the following arguments : 1. He saw all creatures, as well rational as irrational, eagerly striving to attain it. ' In all cases that which is ]. 'That which is desired is a thing; good and right, and that which desired is a good. . , . , . ,, r- T i. 1 ■ 1 J.1 That which is de- is desired in the highest degree is by the same ^j^ed in the high- s reasoning the highest good. Consequently, the est degree is the fact that all creatures alike are impelled to the B™'°pTeasii°re™s pursuit of pleasure^ proves that for all alike desired in the 538 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 2. highest degree and pleasure IS the greatest good. Everything, eo by all. Therefore j^g argued, finds out what is good for its own Summum Bouom.' Self, just as it unas out its proper looa ; hence, a thing which is good for all beings, a thing for which they all strive, that is the chiefest good. [These arguments of Eudoxus gained credit on account of the excellence of his personal character, rather than had' grea^'^ight through their own cogency. He was known from the pure and to be a pre-eminently temperate man ; conse- temperate oharac- q^ently he was thought to hold these opinions not as the votary of pleasure, but from real conviction of their truth.] 2. He maintained, too, that the correctness of his view was equally plain from a consideration of pain, which 2. The same truth ■ ^j^g opposite of pleasure. Pain, he said, was IS seen conversely. , . i i i n i ., . 'Pain is shunned a thmg shunucd by all creatures as an evil m as unirersaily as itgglf; and by parity of reasoning its opposite, Teted""^^ '^ pleasure, was a good to be coveted. 8. Now an object is, in the highest degree, an object of choice when we desire it not on account of something 3. Pleasure is a, gjgg jjqj. ^jj.Jj g^jjy ulterior aim ; and, confessedly, nght and satisfies pleasure is an object of this kind : if a man feels -per se. Therefore pleasure, no oue asks him further what his motive it is the summum Tj.,. j.ii.j>t i i_- j . T , argument to prove When it is per se and apart irom wisdom ; and that pleasure is he drew the conclusion that, if the combination »"* tiie summum bonum. be better, then pleasure is not per se the sum- mum bonum. The absolute summum bonum cannot be made more desirable whatever may be added to it. But [Plato proves too much :] it is evident that \^^^ omato,™ ow- according to this argument neither pleasure nor ever, was some- anything else can be the summum bonum : for ^^^ Z^Z't there is nothing in the world that does not be- gument has no real come more desirable by association with some of ' wMoh ^we ^are absolute other thing good in itself. What, then, talking is of course is there that satisfies Plato's requirements, and is ^^^^^P"^'"'^'' «7«- yet a good in which we mortals have a share? [None] : and yet this is a necessary attribute of the good which is the object of our search. Those, again, who take exception to the theory that ' an object 540 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 2. at which all things aim is a good,' and maintain the contrary, are surely mistaken in their view. When an opinion is held by all men, I maintain that it is true. The theorist who destroys this universal ground of confidence will have no greater assur- ance of certainty for what he may himself adduce. If it were only irrational beings who yearned for pleasures, there would have been some reason in the objection, but since even rational creatures have the same impulses, on what grounds can their objection possibly rest ? It is probable that even in depraved natures there is an instinctive good, higher than the level of themselves, which aims at an ' end ' congenial to itself. (2) The jkssl argu- ment of Eudoxus is confirmed — so far as his premis- ses go. The appeal to uni- versal experience is a valid and proper one. The pursuit of pleasure by all living things proves it to be A good (though not the sumnium bonum). (3) The second ar- gument of Eudoxus is challenged by Speusippus, but upon insufiScient grounds. Eudoxus was right in as- suming an opposi- tion between plea- sure and pain, as one is t^fvKirhv and the other is not. 2. Nor, again, do the criticisms of the opponents of Eudoxus on his argument from pain as the contrary of pleasure seem to be soundly based. They deny that it follows that if pain is an evil, pleasure is therefore a good. They maintain that evil may be opposed to evil, and both extremes to a state of indifference or impassivity ; and so far their reasoning is not amiss, though they are not right in their inferences in regard to the question now before us. If pleasure and pain were both evils, then both of them ought to have been equally avoided ; if neither were evils, then neither ought to have been avoided, or both alike in exact proportion. But, as a matter of fact, men are seen to shun pain as an evil and to desire pleasure as a good. Consequently pleasure and pain are, in reality, opposed the one to the other. But this is not the case. That which, added to a good, maies it better, must itself be a good : but it need not be the ultimate Good, nor indeed better than any other good. Every ' good ' added to another of coui'se enhances it qua ' good ; ' the whole must invariably be greater than the part. Such, at any rate, were the views of Eudoxus about Pleasure. Plato, on the other hand, used to maintain that Pleasure could not be the ultimate Good ; for which position he em^oyed the very arguments by which Eudoxus attempted to prove that it was. For since — he says — that ' good,' a greater good than which can be found, cannot be the ultimate Good — (for the ultimate Good must be the greatest of all)— it follows that any good which, by the addition of another, becomes greater and more ohoiceworthy, cannot itself be the ultimate Good ; for it is not the greatest good, but admits of a superior. Such a ' good,' Pleasure is : the life of pleasure becomes more pleasurable and ohoiceworthy by the addition of Wisdom, or of Temperance : which proves that there is something better than Pleastu'e. Pleasure, therefore, according to Plato, is not the ultimate Good ; it is a good, but in the same sense as are the virtues, the sciences, and the other endowments of our nature. Now this ia the veiy Bk. X. 2.] Translation. 541 doctrine we are anxious in the present case to prove — that pleasure is a good of this class ; thereby avoiding the error of those who, pleading against Eudoxus' theories, affirmed it to be not a ' good ' at all, though aU thmgs aim at it. Their position is absurd, for that which all men unanimously thmk true is what vre call the truth. There is no other canon of truth ; and any one who annuls this doctrine of common consent, and endeavours to shake the faith based upon it, will be ill able to substitute a better. And all men of common sense agree that a thing at which all things aim must be a good. They clearly hold it to be a good, for they pursue it through every means that conduces to it. The case would be different if only irrational beings aimed at it : for then we might think it was only a good to them ; and their suffrage might be inadequate to prove that it was truly a good. But we find, by the means they take to obtain it, that things irrational and rational alike consider it to be a good ; and why then should it not be an absolute good ? For indeed, even irrational beings have in them a certain natural affinity to the Good, which supersedes, as it were, their inferiority, and qualifies them to aim at the good, by an inner attraction to it. Such is the objection brought against the first part of Eudoxus' theory. As against the second, which is baaed upon the law of opposition, they deny that it follows that pleasure is a good, because pain is an evil. If a thing be an evil, its opposite need not be a good ; an evil may be the opposite of an evU, as, apathy for instance, of intemperance, both being evils ; and both are opposites to tem- perance. So far they are right — but they are in error about pleasure. For if pleasure and pain were both evils, both would be worthy of avoidance, just as, if both were goods, both would be choioeworihy, or, if both were neither good nor bad, neither would be really choiceworthy. But, as it is, we avoid pain as an evil, and choose pleasure as a good ; and so, plainly, pain is opposed to pleasure as an evil to a good, ill. — ExaminatLon of the theory of the Flatonlsts that Pleasure is not a good. 1. Nor assuredly does it follow that, because pleasure does not come under the class of qualities, therefore ^ < pleasure i neither does it come under the class of things not a quality : that are good. Neither happiness nor the various ^™?7 good is a modes in which virtue is displayed are qualities, sure is not a good.' yet they are certainly goods. [Aristotle denies 2. The Platonists urge, further, that, whereas * the good ' is a thing defined and determinate, pleasure is a 2. 'Pleasure is thing undefined and indeterminate, because it not defined: Every admits of degrees of greater or less intensity. ,._ pleasure is not There are two senses in which this objection a good." , , , « [Whatever admits may be taken : — of degrees is not (1.) If they draw their inference from the defined: Pleasure sensations of pleasure which men feel, their ^"He^ureTsTot criticism will apply equally to Justice and the defined.] virtues generally, in respect of which they dis- J^^^e'e^i^^^JJ ^ tinctly say that men are found with corresponding (o) proving too dispositions to a greater or less degree. Some foeitrbli^ men are just and some are brave to a greater relative. 542 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 2. degree than others ; and acts of justice and self-restraint may be more complete in some cases than in others. (2.) But if they rest their criticism on the pleasures them- selves, they are surely mistaken in the true ^"•i, . . , reason (of their apparent indeterminatenessV (;8) Ignoring the • .i . i j ,1. "" differences be- Seeing that some pleasures are pure and others tweeu ' pure ^ are alloyed with pain. What is there to prevent p"easuresr pleasures from being realized in varying degrees in precisely the same way that health, though it be a thing defined and determinate, admits of a greater or less perfection ? The same completeness of development is not found in all men alike, nor is it uniformly maintained in the same individual. Yet even when the health is lowered, it continues within certain limits, and differs only in alternations of more or less completeness. It is of course conceivable that the case of pleasure should be precisely similar. 3. Assuming * the good ' to be a thing absolute and complete, whUe processes of ' movement ' or of ' becoming ' ■Pleasure is move- are transitional and incomplete, they endeavour ment and becom- ,, i.-\ , ^ • /., ,. ing, Movement and to show that pleasure IS a process of ' movement ' becoming are im- and of ' becoming ' (and therefore not * the perfect: .*. Plea- n (1 '^ sure is imperfect.' gOOO. ). i. But, in the first place, our' critics seem to he But (iOPleaBiire is ■ xi • ■ i.i. j. i • /• not a movement. wroug m their View that pleasure is a process of movement or change. A characteristic of all change seems to be swiftness or slow- ness of motion, if not absolutely, as in the o. Movement im- motions of the Cosmos, yet taken in comparison OT ^^Xw^es^ with something else. But neither swiftness nor either abso- slowness are proper attributes of pleasure. It is tiTC. " ^^ ' possible indeed to come into a state of pleasure quickly, just as it is to get into a state of rage quickly ; yet quickness or slowness are impossible attributes of the feelings themselves. Nor yet, again, can we predicate such attributes of one man's pleasure as compared with that of another in the way in which we can of such changes as ' walking ' or ' growing,' and similar processes where comparisons of degree are natural and correct. While, therefore, the transition to a state of pleasure may be a slow or a rapid one; on the other hand, the j8. s-wiftness or enjoyment of a consciousness in conformity onTbeaMi^ therewith (I refer to the actual sensation of dental conoo- pleasure) cannot be either slow or rapid. Bk. X. 2.] Translation. 543 mitanli, essential the idea. not to (ii.) Pleasure is no* a ' becoming : ' u. If it were, the result would be like the cause ; but in fact it is dis- tinct. |3. Pleasure is a 'restoration' only meta- phorically. ii. In the next place, how can pleasure pos- sibly be ' a process of becoming ' ? Such a theory can be disproved by a number of arguments : — • (1.) It is evident that every effect is formed out of definite causes, and may be resolved again into the elements out of which it was produced. [Accordingly, if pleasure were ' a becoming,' its elements would also be pleasurable. But, as a matter of fact,] it is not pleasure but pain that results from the breaking up of pleasure. [Therefore pleasure cannot be ' a becoming.'] (2.) In opposition also to the theory which they use, that ' pain is the want of attaining to a natural con- dition, and pleasure the satisfying of that need,' there are two answers : (a) These emotions, upon which this theory relies, are simply bodily and physical emotions. (/3) If pleasure be the recovery of a natural condition, the part in which the restoration takes place, will be the part that will feel the pleasure; i.e., it will be the body. But, as a matter of fact, the seat of pleasure is evidently not the body, but the mind. Consequently pleasure is not the restoration to a bodily state, though whilst such a restoration is going on, a man will be conscious of pleasure, just as, when || ^dergoing a medical operation, he will be conscious of pain. * [This last opinion, that pleasure is a process of recovery, seems to have originated from the feelings incidental to hunger and thirst : when men experience want and endure the pangs of hunger, they are conscious of pleasure at the satisfying of their wants. But such conditions are not found in regard to all pleasures. Some pleasures have no back- ground of pain; for example, the pleasures of learning, and, among such as follow the gratification of the senses, pleasures that come through fragrant odours, or pleasant sounds and sights and recollections and hopes. What is there of ' becoming ' which such pleasures could be ' processes ? ' No need has been experienced from satisfying which the pleasure could arise.] [The explanation of pleasure as 'a restoration' is at best only applicable to bodily pleasures, and is a metaphor derived from asso- ciations of hunger and thirst] 4. In reply to those who adduce the fact that certain pleasures are disgraceful (in order to prove that pleasure cannot be ' the good ') (1) one may deny the fact *;,/ ^bonu^^o that such gratifications are really pleasurable, pleasure would be 544 The Moral Philosophy oj Aristotle. [Bk. X. 2. bad. But many pleasures are dis- graceful . ■ . Plea- sure is not bouum. ' But (a) Bad pleasures are not really pleasures. Even though they be gratifying to men whose moral state is corrupt, one must not imagine that they are gratifying to any one else. In precisely the same way things are not really wholesome or sweet or bitter because they appear to be so to people in bad health, any more than things are white that appear so to patients suffer- ing from ophthalmia. (2) Or may not the true statement of the case be that pleasures are desirable per se, yet not assuredly from un- lawful means — ^precisely as wealth is per se desirable, yet not for one who has turned traitor to get it ; or as health is desirable, yet not to the man who has had to eat unnatural food. (3) Or may it not be that pleasures differ in kind ? Pleasures derived from noble acts are surely different from those that come from disgraceful acts. Every pleasure implies a corresponding character in the man who feels it. For example, unless a man himself be just, he cannot feel the pleasure that the just man feels ; nor can he feel the pleasure of the musician unless he have musical tastes of his own ; and so on through the whole (;8) Pleasure is only desirable ■when the means thereof are lawful. (7) Pleasures differ in kind : it does not fol- low because «ome pleasures are bad that therefore aU pleasures are bad. list of pleasures. 5. Again, it is urged that the case of the friend as being different from the flatterer seems to show that pleasure is not identical with ' the good,' or that pleasures differ in kind. The true friend is thought to shape his intercourse with a view to moral well-being, whereas the flatterer has no other aim than pleasure. Hence the flatterer is censured, whereas men praise a true friend, know- ing that his intercourse points to higher objects. 5. ' If oM pleasure ■were good, the flat- terer would not be blamed. But the flatterer {> blamed. . • . Pleasure is not a good.' [But con- fessedly pleasures differ in ki'nd.'] 6. ' If all pleasure ■were good, the life of a child might be a desirable life. But no one ■would hare such a life. .■. Pleasure is not a good.' [But plea- sures differ in kind.] 7. [For similar rea- sons no one would have pleasure or avoid pain if the price were dis- graceful.] 6. Again, no one, they say, would care to live all his days with the * intellect only of a child ; ' with the very keenest delight, but only with the pleasures of a young child. 7. Nor would a man care to have enjoyment at the price of doing most disgraceful acts, though he were never likely to meet with pain for doing so. Bk. X. 2.] Translation. 545 8. Lastly, to show that pleasure is not identical with the good, they remind us that there are many things about which we should he enthusiastic, even though' IJ-'^^^llt they entailed no sense of pleasure; e.g., sight, by any and every , memory, knowledge, and the possession of Sr,:;i^:*t' wlic" { moral excellences. It makes no difference to we covet irrespec- . the argument that, as a matter of fact, pleasures ^^^'^ "L^"'' p'^^" m attend the possession of these things : we bring, should choose them though no pleasure resulted Therefore pleasure therefrom. ^^^^^_ The conclusions then that seem to be evident from the above discussion are : — (1.) Pleasure is not the Chief Good. (2.) It is not every pleasure that is choiceworthy. (3.) Certain pleasures are choiceworthy for their own sake, but they either differ in kind from others or in the circumstances out of which they arise. This examination must suffice for the theories that are current in regard to pleasure and pain. others agaia say that pleasure is not a good, because it is not a quaKty. This argument has no real cogency ; for it would equally prove that the activities of the different virtues, and happiness itself, not being qualities, vrere not goods : but there is clearly nothing that can really disprove their being goods. Again, they pleaded that Pleasure could not be a good because it is indetermi- nate, while the good must be determinate. And they called Pleasure indetermi- nate because it fluctuates, and admits of more and less. This would be cogent and true if the more and less were discernible in Pleasure itself : but in fact the sharpening and slackening in the sense of pleasure takes place in the subjects of it, and is relative to their capacity for it ; as is the case also with the virtues. These may be just, or manly, and act justly, or live temperately, all in a greater or less degree ; but that does not make these virtues in themselves indeterminate. Precisely in the same way Pleasure is not in itself indeterminate, but allows its am^e to sharpen or slacken in those who feel it, because it is not in all alike, nor in an equal degree pure and unalloyed with pain. Such is the case with Health ; it is determinate, yet in its subjects it is made intense or relaxed as the case may be ; for aJl men have not the same balance of the vital power, nor has any one man the same balance always ; but the power fluctuates, now to more, now to less ; and at one time the body is purely healthy, and at another it contains a germ of disease. Precisely analogous to this may be the case of Pleasure. Again, it was argued that Pleasure could not be a good, from the following considera- tions. Pleasure is a process of motion and development ; and motion and development are, ipso facto, imperfect, and what is imperfect cannot be a good ; for what is good has perfection : therefore. Pleasure cannot be a good. Here the minor premiss is false : pleasure is not =• process of motion, nor of development, as we will proceed to show. In all motion, there would seem to be a natural quality of swiftness or slow- ness : and if any motion appear to have no such quality in itself and absolutely, (that is, to have no increase or decrease of speed in its material subjects, such as there is in things which move irregularly), stUl, those material subjects, if compared not with themselves but with some other things, are seen and said to 546 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 2 have swiftness or slowness. The revolution of the heavens, for instance, is in itself equable and unchangeable : but considered relatively to the motion of the stars it may be called swift. So it is that every motion has its special quality of speed or slowness, whereas Pleasure has no such quality, therefore Pleasure is not a process of motion. And that Pleasure has no such quality is plaiu from the following considerations. A man is said to ' be pleased ' gimldy, just as he may ' be angered ' quickly. That is, he may change quickly from the condition of not being pleased to that of being so : but he cannot be said to feel Pleasure itseU quickly or slowly ; neither relatively to himself, (as the things which move irregularly were said to have speed or slowness relatively to themselves) nor in comparison with anything else (as the things, whose motion was equable, were said to have). Progression, growth, change, and all modes of motion are contem- plated in connection with swiftness or slowness ; and so may the lapse, or sudden shifting, into the condition of pleasure. But there is no swiftness or slowness in the activity of Pleasure itself. Pleasure is a sort of goal or term of motion ; it is a sort of rest, and therefore cannot itself be motion of any kind : and this, as we consider, we have proved. Nor, as we have said, is it a process of development ; for, if it were, its opposite. Pain, would be a process of dissolution ; and of that, of which Pleasure was the development. Pain would be the dissolu- tion : for neither development nor dissolution is casual, nor are they casuaJly connected ; but from whatsoever anything is developed, into that, and nothing else, does it naturally dissolve. Again, if it be true, as is said, that Pain is a depletion of the natural condition, it will follow that Pleasure is a renovation thereof ; and this depletion and renovation are clearly bodily processes. And so, if Pleasure is a renovation of some natural condition, that which has Jhe renovation — to wit, the body — will feel, and be the subject of, the pleasure : and pleasure will be corporeal purely. But this is not the fact ; all agree that the sense of pleasure appertains' to the soul. Therefore Pleasure, we conclude, is not a process of development and renova- tion ; but it is consequent on a renovation, just as Pain is on a depletion, of the natural state : we certainly feel pleasure whUe a renovation is taJdng place, and pain, e.g., when amputation is being performed. The view we have been criticising seems to have been derived from a con- sideration of bodily pleasures and pains, and, especially those of eating and drinking : wherein it is certainly true that we first feel and are pained by deple- tion, and then pleased by renovation. But this does not hold with all pleasures : e.g,, with those of mathematical science, and those of mental perception. Cer- tainly the pleasures of hearing, smelling, seeing, take place witii no antecedent pain, nor are they in any sense a renovation following on depletion. Hope, again, and remembrance of things good, are among the most pleasurable things : but can these pleasures be called a development ? and if so, of what ? There was in their subjects no previous depletion of which they could be the renovation. All which proves Pleasure not to be a development. Others again aver that pleasure is not a good, and plead the instances of pleasures which are disreputable. So when we reply that things are not pleasura- ble because base men think them so ; the true canon of pleasure is not ' that which pleases the ill-disposed.' Such pleasures are relative to such men, not real — ^just as, to sick appetites, tilings appear wholesome, or sweet, or bitter, which are not such in fact, but only relatively to the vitiated taste : or as, to diseased eyes, tilings appear white which are not actually white. So it is evident, in spite of these theories, that the claim of pleasure to be a good is not disproved; For we allege specially ' (i.) That the pleasures of the dissolute are not really pleasures. (ii) If we grant they are pleasures, stUl it does not follow that Pleasure in itself is base : for pleasure is not homogeneous, but manifold ; that is, some kinds may be base while others are good, and those derived from honourable and laudable objects are of one quality, and those derived from base objects, of another : in short, some pleasures are good, and some detestable, in themselves. Take as an analogy the case of wealth or health. There is an honourable wealth, Bk. X. 3.] Translation. 547 wMoh. a man obtains without wronging any one, and a dislionourable wealth, obtained by treachery to one's country, or by selling childxen or relations into slavery. There is, again, a proper health, obtained by a natural and human mode of life ; and an improper health, obtained by unnatural and discreditable means ; and so on, in other matters. Precisely the same is the case of pleasures. They are absolutely distinct in kind ; e.g., the musician's pleasure cannot be shared by the unmusical, nor that of the just man by any one who is not just ; clearly therefore the musician's pleasure is ' sui generis,' and the just man's also, and so on. Therefore, — even if we grant that the pleasure of base men is a base thing, — it does not follow that Pleasure, in itself, is worthy of avoidance. Others again have argued that Pleasure could not be a good, from consideration of the difEerence between a flatterer and a friend. The flatterer is censured, be- cause in his intercourse he has only, the design of pleasiag ; while the friend is praised because he aims, not at giving pleasure, but at telling truth, and doing good to his friend. Hence it seems to have been inferred that Pleasure was cen- surable. But the inference is not good ; it would be sounder to conclude that the pleasures differ in kind, and that one is censurable and the other laudable. Every- body knows that a friend is agreeable, and gives pleasure to the object of his at- tachment ; whence it is clear that all intercoui-se between man and man has a mutual pleasure ; but, because friendship is exalted in motive, its pleasure is praised ; whereas flattery being unworthy in motive, its pleasure is censured. Others again have argued that pleasure is censurable, because no man of sound mind would choose to live a life of mere childiBh pleasures, with the ideas and deUghts of children, nor make any other mean choice merely for pleasure's sake. But this no way proves Pleasure to be a base thing. A man of sound mind does not avoid the life of mere childishness and petty actions because it ia pleasur- able, but because, for a man, it is intrinsically base. Many things, again, which conduce to Pleasure we aim at, not for the pleasure, but for their own desirability. For example, if there were no pleasure in sight, memory, knowledge, virtue, we should still choose them. It makes no difference f principle, even if we admit that each of these has a pleasure inseparable from : we should desire them for ourselves, even if that were not so. It is therefore clear, — (i.) That all pleasure is not choiceworthy nor good. (ii.) That there are certain pleasures meritorious in themselves and distinct from the base pleasures, both in kind and in origin. iv. — The true nature of Pleasure explained. But it will become more evident what the true nature of pleasure is and what are its characteristics, if we take up the 'Subject again from the beginning. . {a) COMPARISON BETWEEN PLEASUBE AND SIGHT. Now the sense of sight is thought to be perfect at any moment of its exercise : it needs nothing to happen at a future time in order that its nature may be per- Measure is of a, J. , . ■, T ■ -, n 1 -,1 nature simple, lected. This is the kmd 01 phEenomenon with uncompounded, which pleasure must be compared: pleasure is unique, complete, . -t ■ ■ Tj- J. ■ J. L ij 3.nd perfect m an a thing complete in itseli — at no instant coula instant. one find a pleasure whose nature would be more fully consummated if its sensation were protracted for a longer time. 548 The. Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 3. We have thus recoimted the ctaTent sayings about Pleasure and Pain. Now we are concerned to iuyestigate about the former, what it intrinsically or generic- ally is ; and this would be most clearly shown by a resumption of an earlier part of the argument, in which we affirmed Pleasure to be perfect in itself — just aa, e.g., at any moment of its exercise sight is perfect ; and it is impossible to discri- minate any part of the time occupied in seeing, during which sight is developed : it is complete during the whole time. (5) PLEASURE IMPLIES NEITHEB OHAN&E NOE BECOMING. Wherefore pleasure is not a process of change or of movement. Every movement takes place in a certain time and Pleasure being j^^s reference to a certain end ; e.q. the process of complete m an m- , , ., .. . , i , -i • i divisible particle of housebuilding IS not Complete until it has accom- time cannot be ' a pHshed the design which it had in view. When I process of move- " , . j. ■ j.- , t -^x. l -^y ■ ment.' Say 'in a certain time i mean either ' withm a certain period ' or ' at a particular moment.' (c) CHAEACTEEISTICS OF TEMPOEAL MOVEMENT. But in relation to particular sections of time all movements are incomplete. Every point of the movement is Temporal move- distinct in kind from the process as a whole, and to pleasure, im- cvcry point from every other. The laying of the pUes (1) division bricks is distinct from the fluting of the columns, distiMt ' end.' ^ ^'^^ these again from the structure of the whole temple. The structure of the temple is complete and perfect : it lacks nothing in view of the purpose for which it was conceived ; whereas the structure of the base and the sculpture of the beams are incomplete, each being the structure only of a part. Such processes, therefore, all differ in kind, and d^erent element i* ^^ impossible to find at any exact_ instant a of movement are process of movement that is complete in its idea Sr anTfrZ ^^^ a™, Or, if conceivably at all, withm some the whole. period regarded as a whole. Herein, we may observe, sight differs from motion, which is imperfect, so to speak, in each part, and heterogeneous ; the parts differ from the whole motion and from one another : just as do the parts in the process of house-building. Take, for instance, the entire construction of a temple, — the process of combining the stone-work is one thing, £md that of moulding the pUlars another ; and they differ both as compared to one another and to the complete result, which — as being fully worked out in aU essential parts — may be called perfect ; but the work of the basement and of the triglyph is in itself imperfect, because each is only the construction of a part. Therefore the parts of motion differ generically ; and in no sub-division of time — I mean of course the time occupied in the motion — can you make any subdi- vision of the motion perfect according to the standard of the completed motion — which is consmnmated in the full period only. Bk. X. 3.] Translation. 549 (flO CHAEACTEEISTICS OF ' LOCAL ' MOVEMENT. The case applies similarly to walking and to all local move- ments. If it be the fact that locomotion is a movement from one place to another, here too S'^'^'^ly ™ i°<^l ^ " motion not only there will be differences corresponding to the are the variouB different kinds of locomotion, such as flying, tinds distinct, but . . »T • ■ J oi those Kinds are walking, leaping and so on. Nor is it only so ; further subdivided but there are distinctions to be made in actual 'ito other varieties ,, . , T,ir , /. , , , . equally distinct. walking. ' Movement from one place to another is not the same thing in the stadium as a whole as in particular sections of it, nor are all the sections equal nor is it the same thing to pass this line and that. A man does not merely pass over a line, but that line exists in a particular place, and one line differs from another in position. [I have argued the question of locomotion in another Treatise with scientific precision. The conclusion seems to be that motion is not a thing complete at any and every moment, but the majority of motions are incomplete, as standing in the relation of co- , ordinate species to a common genus, assuming, that is, that the ; * whence ' and the ' whither ' constitute different species of motion.] ; Such, also is the case in waUdng and all other modes of motion. Progression f. comprises divers kinds of motions, such as leaping, flying, walking ; all of which *'' are modes of progression, but specifically distinct from each, other. Nay, more, in each of these motions there aie specifically distinct kinds of progression. The terms, for instance, the ' whence ' and the ' whither,' aie different. And as the terms differ, the modes of motion specifically differ, as in the race-course any part of the race differs, in point of terms, from the race regarded as a whole ; and not ■ only that, but from all the other parts of the race. Suppose the whole race to be from the point A to the point B, — the portion of the race between A and B is different in terms from the whole race, and from the other portions, viz., B to c, c to D, and D to B. And as the terms differ, so are the portions specifically distinct. If each motion traversed one and the same line, it would be otherwise ; but, as each Une lies in its ovm place, and the places differ, the motions that traverse each line also differ. "We have elsewhere written our scientific account of motion ; here we need only affirm that motion as such is only complete in its whole period, not at any and every point of the time it occupies; the portional motions which, combined, make the whole motion, are in themselves incomplete and diverse from each other, if, as is clear, the terms of motion, the ' whence ' and ' whither,' constitute specific differences. , (e) ABSOLUTE COMPLETENESS AND INDEPENDENCE OF PLEASURE. In regard to pleasure on the other hand, its nature or logical conception is realized at any given moment whatever. It is clear 550 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 4, therefore that various pleasures will be distinct from one another, and that the sensation of pleasure itself will be contrary is a thing One of thoso things that are ' wholes ' (or ' uni- absoiuteiy unique ties ' ) and complete in themselves, m eax: ins an . 'YSxis, vicw wiU be also evident from the fact that it is impossible for motion to take place except within a cer- tain time, whereas pleasure can be instantaneous ; what is instan- taneous, being a ' whole ' or ' unity ' in itself. From these considerations it is clear that writers are in error who describe pleasure as a process of transition foTTantdi: or of becoming. 'Change' or 'becoming' are visible 'whole,' terms not predicable of all facts, but only of imTeT arts'^"^* *^°^® ^^^^ *^^* "^^5^ ^^ analysed into parts and that are not ' units ' in themselves. There is no ' process of becoming ' in the case of sight nor of a point nor of a monad : in not one of these cases is either ' movement ' or ' becoming ' possible, nor assuredly in the case of pleasure either, pleasure being an ultimate fact, ' a unity ' or ' whole ' in itself. But with Pleasnre the case is different ; at any point of time it is specifically complete — therein, differing from motion ; the former being something whole and complete in itself, the latter incomplete in itself and needing a certain dnration of time for completion. Complete motion, e.g. is impossible in the momentajy, present, and indivisible point of time, while complete and entire pleasure is possible therein. All which proves that Pleasure is neither a process of motion, nor of develop- ment. Development is not of aU things, but of parts rather than of wholes ; e.g. we do not talk of the development of sight, or of a point, or of the unit. Each of these is a whole and indivisible, and does not develop and come to completion by lapse of time, but is, at any moment, whole and complete in itself. The unit, for instance, and the Point are not perfect in one part and imperfect in another, nor are they brought to development by lapse of time ; and Sight is, at each moment of the time we are exercising the faculty, complete in itself ; as indeed the activity of every sense, working on its appropriate subject, is perfect at every moment of its exercise. (/) PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS OF PLEASURE. If, then, every sense comes into operation when in presence ot Pleasure is the re- ^° °^J®°* °^ ®^°^.® ' ^'^^ ^.^ ^^^ operation is perfect suit of when the sense itself is in a normal state and is (a)asen8eheaith. j^ ^j^g presence of the highest object that can ily constituted ; \ . f J (/8) an object come withm its range (the perfect operation coming within the l3eing thought to be pre-eminently of -this descrip- sense and adapted tion, and the difference being immaterial whether *" it- we say that the sense itself operates or the sub- The highest plea- jg^j; jq which the sense resides") .... in every sure will be that •< iii-ii,--,-i /. where these two casc, i Say, the highest activity is that of a man Bk. X. 4] Translation. 551 who is most perfectly constituted, and is in factors are the presence of the highest object that can fall within. S'L Uend^'to- his senses. Such an activity will be most perfect getter. and most pleasurable. In fact pleasure follows in the wake of every sensation, and in like manner also of every process of reasoning or play of thought, and the most pleasurable activity This law applies .Ail,-!.- 1 j?i.ij.i J. 1} 1. also to the intel- is that which is most perfect, and the most perfect lectual 5w(£/ieis. activity is that of the man who is in a normal state when it is brought to bear upon the noblest object that can come before it. It is indeed the pleasure resulting from it that makes the activity perfect. Yet pleasure does not perfect the activity in the same way that the sensation ^}^^Z^^ "etute^ and its object do, when they are normal and of the activity, but right Pleasure is not essentially, but only ac- ™J^ a'ccXntXs'^" cidentally, the result of the activity. Just in the same way healthfulness is the cause of a man's being hale and well, in a different sense than that in which the physician is the cause. But it is clear that pleasure ensues as a consequence of each state of sensation : we say that sights and sounds are I'pleasant, and evidently the pleasure will be greatest when the sensation is most excellent and the object in presence of which it operates is of a corresponding excellence. So often as the object felt and the person who is conscious of the sensation are mutually excellent, then invariably pleasure will arise — so often, that is, as the object that is to produce the sensation and the person who is to experience it are both present and are brought into contact. Pleasure, then, makes the activity perfect — not as a permanent state inherent in the patient, but as a kind of perfection super- vening, like the bloom of health on the cheeks of youth. So long, therefore, as the object of our intellectual or sensuous consciousness be of a right and normal character, and the faculty of discriminating or of contem- S^^y^Cmfl' plating be likewise in a normal condition, then pervening when- there will be pleasure in the activity that ensues :;f3„™5,l7g'j:X' from the contact So long, that is, as the two forces of the mind, the active and the passive, mutually corre- spond, the attitude of each being analogous to that of the other, this same result must from the nature of things always supervene. i Pleasure follows on the activities of Sense and of Intellect ; especially when Sense and Intellect are both in the condition of soundness, and so put forth their 552 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 4. most complete activity, and that in tie best direction — Sense to the fairest goal among things sensible, and Intellect to that among things inteUectnal ; for it is with that object in view that activity, or the active habit (the name is indiffer- ent) most specially and adequately operates. Such activity {e.g. of sight) is perfect ■when we behold, healthfully and adequately, some one of the noblest objects of. vision ; and so with the Intellect and all the other senses ; and that which is most perfect is, ipso facto, the sweetest also. That there is a pleasure of the Intelleot, and of each of our senses, is clear ; we speak of matters intellectual as pleasiag us, and we enjoy the objects of our contemplation, and are delighted with sights and sounds ; and this, especially, as we have said, when our activities are com- plete ; and we see best, and contemplate best, and have all our senses most at command. For as long as Sense and Intelleot, with their respective objects, are what they are, there must be pleasure in their exercise ; so long, that is, as Intellect and Sense are affected by the presence of their objects. Therefore Pleasure follows on each activity, and forms its consummation ; only not in tlie same sense as habituation has been shown to develop its subject from the state of potential capacity to that of actual exercise. Architecture, e.g, develops the man who has a capacity for it, and makes him an actual arohiteet-: but it is in another sense that we speak of Pleasure as working complet^n. Health is the cause, in one sense, of a man being sound ; in another sense, the physician is ; the former superinduces the activity of healthf ulness, though it is not identical with it ; the latter guards and protects it, and labours for its per- manence. Nor again does Pleasure work completion of the activity of its subjects in the same sense as the object of Intelleot may be said to perfect Intellect, or the object of Sense to perfect sense. Habit and the object lead the active faculty on from the potential state to that of actual exercise ; while Pleasure, which is contemporaneous with this exercise, guards and protects the active faculty, and urges it on to exercise, being a sort of second completion of the activity, as beauty is of youths in their prime ; and it is inseparable from it so long as Sense and Intellect subsist in activity with regard to their proper objects ; and especially when they are in their best and soundest state, and thdr activity is most fittingly directed. ig) EEPLT TO VARIOUS DIFFICULTIES UPON THE SUBJECT. 1. ' How is it, then, that no one retains an uninterrupted , ,, , , consciousness of pleasure ? ' Is not the answer 1. If a man could ,, . ,, , . „, . ,. -.,. work incessantly, this — that a man weanes oi his sensations. JNone he would feel in- of the faculties of man are capable of being cessant pleasure. . , •l_^ i. l- -xi i exercised without cessation; so neither does pleasure last for ever, being, as it is, only a concomitant upon the exercise of our faculties. 2. For the same reason also, there are things which please while their novelty lasts, yet by and by lose their \ t'eakenef'the ^arly charm. At first the mind is excited and pleasure is weak- concentrates itself with sustained attention upon ened also to a cor- ^j^g matter before it It is precisely so with respondmg degree. -t,. Ai..Ci iij-j-i v, sight. At first men look steadily upon an ob- ject ; but the mental strain is not maintained, but is by and by relaxed and weakened, and the pleasure consequently becomes less vivid. Bk. X. 5.] Translation. 553 3. One may suppose that all men strive after pleasure, since all are eager likewise to live. Life is, in a sens^ a development of the faculties; and the objects desire^of^piJ^me upon which and for the sake of which every man '^ ^^ "^^suit of the spends his energies, are the objects he most truly Mediae telng^c- loves. For example, the musician cultivates the tivity, and pleasure sense of hearing, to catch the modulations of "« <=<«^'=°'^t^"t)- sound, and the student cultivates the understanding, to catch the thoughts that underlie the music ; and so on in the various other pursuits. But it is pleasure that in every case makes the exercise of the faculties perfect, and therein also life itself for which men yearn. Hence it is natural that men should strive after pleasure, per- fecting as it does for each man his life, and life being confes- sedly an object of desire. 4. The question may be dismissed for the present, whether we desire life for the sake of pleasure, or pleasure for the sake of life. The two conditions are evidently *: Measure is a intertwined one with the other and do not admit faction of ^desire of separation : pleasure is not felt without the ^'^^ i . therefore be drawn Corrupt and debased lorms 01 human nature; from disgraceful and it is Only to such and such like that the peasures. things which a good man abhors appear plea- sant : they are not really so. Pleasures however that are confessedly disgraceful cannot, it is clear, be rightly called pleasures, except to the vicious and abandoned. But among pleasures that appear honest and true, of what nature can we say is the distinctive pleasure of Ltglhe'taXd ^«'*-'' I« it °ot' evidently, the pleasure that of right, the ac- flows from the conscious exercise and develop- Bk. X. 5.] Translation. 559 ment of his faculties, every form of such de- tivities of such an velopment being attended by a pleasure of its "'.'^'^'''.sive the '•„ ' " IS. highest pleasure. own i " Whether therefore there be one activity or many forms of activity that are proper to the perfect and happy man, the pleasures which consummate those ac- intellect, theve- tivities may be emphatically called the proper *"^ (whether spe- 1 c ^\L^ ^ • culative or prac- pleasures 01 man. Other pleasures are so in a ticai), -will be the Becondary sense, through many gradations and highest pleasures ; ranges, just as are the activities from which they :°J "^k'y arise. relation to this standard. Further, it appears that each living thing, having its own function, has there- with its own pleasure. Because, if each activity has its concomitant pleasure, and if each living thing has its special natural activity, each must have its gpecial pleasure ; as individual instances demonstrate. There is one pleasure of a horse, another of a dog, another of a man ; Heraclitus notes this point, when he says ' the ass prefers his wisp of hay to gold ; fodder is sweeter than gold — to asses.' So, at any rate, pleasures akin to different activities are themselves different : while, as is natural, those akin to the same activities are akin to one another — in kind, that is ; for in quantity they may differ. Everybody knows that an activity gives very varying amounts of pleasure to different men ; so much 80 indeed that one and the same activity is the delight of one man and the 'detestation of another. Thus, for instance, men do not all think the same things sweet ; the fever- patient and the healthy man differ widely on this point, and so do the weakly and . the strong, about heat — and so in other cases. Still, just as in those cases we can learn to discriminate the truly sweet from the seemingly sweet by a reference to fce taste of sound and healthy men — so can- we discriminate the moral pleasures from others by a reference to men of a sound moral condition — good men, in short. And if this be an accurate saying, that ' virtue is the measure of each thing, and each man is good in right of such virtue as he possesses ' — ^then the true definition of pleasures will be ' such things as the good man considers pleasures,' and of things agreeable, ' those in which the good man feels delight : ' while things for which he has a distaste, can in no true sense be called agreeable, nor pleasures. And if corrupted men think such things agreeable, it is not matter for wonder ; for there are many polluted and debased instincts, which are agreeable to corrupted men, but not in a true sense agree- able. Plainly then we must not say that confessedly base pleasures are pleasures, unless with the saving clause ' to corrupted men.' But of the honourable pleasures, which shall we name the expressly human pleasure ? This too is clear from the preceding discussion. Since each pleasure is akin to the activity it accompanies, let us find the human activity — that of man quS, man — (whether it be one or more activities) : then, the pleasures which perfect that activity, or those activities, as found in the perfect and happy man, are the pre-eminently human pleasm-es ; the others may be called human, like their activities, in a secondary sense and iu a more multifarious classification. 560 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 6. IL— CONCERNING HAPPINESS. i. — Greneral conception of Happiness. The examination of the Yirtues and of Friendship and of Pleasure T3 /^i. ^ • ^ beinff now concluded, it remains for us to describe From (the efficient . ° . . ' „ _. . cause) virtues, m outlme the nature 01 Happmess — regardmg friendship, and happiness, as we do, as the consummati«n of pleasure, we now i • . pass to (the final human mterests. cause) happiness. The discussion Will certainly be expedited if we recapitulate the arguments already advanced upon the subject. We have thus discussed the Virtues, and Friendship, and Pleasure : it remains to deal in outline with Happiness, because it is, by oonunon consent, the end and aim of all human action. We shall give the clearest and readiest account of it by recalling our previous statements on the subject. (a) HAPPINESS IS NOT A PASSIVE CONBITION. We have already shown that happiness is not a merely passive condition of mind. If it were so, it might be If^happinessjere possessed by a man who slumbered aU his life belong to a man in through, having an existence like that of plants, sleep; or (2) m or bv a man who was suffering from the direst great affliction. . n , misfortunes. I We stated in the thirteenth chapter of the first Book that Happiness is not a mere condition of mind : for, if it were, a man who lay asleep all his lite, or lived the merely vegetative life, and even the man of many and great woes, might have to be called happy : for such lives may bef al a man who yet has the habit of virtue. {b) HAPPINESS AN ACTIVITY DESIRABLE PBR SM. If, however, such a view would not satisfy our idea of happiness, and we must rather rank it as a conscious, active Happiness being an pja,y of the faculties (as has been explained in the modes^of activity preceding Books), and all such modes of human being (1) subordi- activity are either (1) unavoidable and only desir- hrte)' "will be^°a ^^^^ ^^ means to ends, or (2) desirable for their mode of activity own Sake, it is evident that we must regard worthyper st"'*"^' bappiness as one of those states that are desirable for their own sake, and not as one of those that are desirable relatively to something else. Happiness lacks nothing for its completeness, but is perfect in and by itself. Now those mental activities are absolutely choiceworthy from which nothing is expected beyond their own free exercise; and ' Bk. X. 6. J Translation. 561 acts that are regulated by a moral law seem to be of this char- acter, since the performance of good and nobl^ acts comes under the category of things desirable Definition of abso- J, ,, . 1 lute activities. for their own sake. ■ If, tlien, it seems absurd to call such a man happy, it remains to us to conclude that Happiness is an activity : so we must certainly inquire wMoh of the human ^,'aotiTities it is. For some activities are perfunctory, and tend to aims other than pliliemselves, and are sought, consequently, as means, not as ends ; while others are in themselves desirable. Hence it is apparent that Happiness is to be reckoned J in the latter class, as being adequate in itself and in no way imperfect; whUe j whatever is chosen as means to an object, clearly needs the addition of that ; object, to be in itself desirable and good. ; But activities according to the virtues (which are sought not as means but as ends), are adequate in themselves; to do things honourably and well is among the things ohoioeworthy ■per se. I (C) HENCE MANY THINK THAT HAPPINESS IS IDENTICAL WITH ' AMUSEMENT WHICH IS ALSO DESIRED PER SE. Amusements, again, that are pleasurable, seem to be of this character : men desire them, irrespective of con- sequences. Indeed the tendency of amusements But 'amusement' . ,, , . . 1,1 .1 1 m J comes within this 18 that men are injured rather than benetitea definition of per- thereby, disregarding, as they do, health and feet activities: will ,.„.•".,, ° .°' '' ' amusement then be I lortune in the pursuit. happiness ? I ; But the majority of those whom the world ac- I counts happy, have recourse to amusements of this kind, because at the courts of Princes men skilled in such like pastimes are in high favonr, as making themselves The mass of men '■ ,1 . , , ■ , 1} 1 • 1 T> • thiuli SO, and tuose agreeable m entertainments tor wnicn rnnces .,^110 have greatest V crave : indeed ' such courtiers are necessary for po'^'er arc those them. Still, though such things are popularly Llmu^ement.'"'' thought essential to happiness because men in |high office divert themselves therein, yet men of this type are surely "no real criterion of what happiness is. In the mere exercise of power there is implied neither ^f^y"*''*^''^^ 'the moral worth nor intellectual perception, whence powerful ' are true alone right dispositions and a good life have their f^^^^^^'"' '''"^ " rise. Pleasant amusements are no doubt in this same category: that is, they are chosen for their own sakes, and when chosen bring no ulterior advantage, But rather loss ; for they lead to neglect of health, and of such possessions as tend to health. Thus it happens that many of the fortunate, whose life's com-se nms smoothly, betake themselves eagerly to the life of amusement, and highly esteem men of ready and amusing disposition ; and, at the courts of tyrants, skilled jesters gain much populai-ity, by pleasantly providing their masters with the amusement which they desire, and think necessary for their so-called Happi- ness, "VYell, such Jtmu^ements are thought tg opnstitijte happiness, because men 562 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 6. in high power spend so much time in them ; but they do not really constitute it, and the suffrage of such men is quite inadequate as a proof. Power is no guarantee of virtue nor of healthiaess of mind, and it is these whicb produce sound activities. [d) BUT NONE BUT THE PERFECT MAN IS COMPETENT TO PBO- NOUNCE UPON MORAL QUESTIONS. The mere fact that men who have never had a taste of genuine and noble pleasures, hurry away to bo,dily enjoy- WortUessness of ments, must not lead us to infer that a life of ki mssfons! ^°^"' self-indulgence is therefore more desirable than a life of virtue : — that would be to argue like children, who fancy that things prized among themselves are things most excellent. It is very natural therefore that there should be a wide difference between the feelings of the good and the bad, precisely as there is between the impressions of children and of men. "We come back therefore to the view which has been often . explained in this Treatise, that things are only aU^men is'coirared pleasurable in reality when thej' appear so to the hy their character, mind of the good man : whilst to each individual Only the virtunus ,-, ,■ ■, • i. i • i i i_- i ■ • j man therefore can the activity IS most desirable which IS in accoraance determine ques- with liis own peculiar state ; so, too, the activity tions vir ue. most desirable in the eyes of the good man is one that is regulated by the standard of virtue. The fact that men, being wholly and lastingly devoid of taste for noble and genuine pleasru'e, betake themselves to mere carnal delights, does not lead us to conclude that such delights are in any sense preferable to genuine pleasures. Children think then- own pet toys the finest of all things, but such childish Qdvgs are valueless to men; and, correspondingly, honest men will not admire what base men think admirable ; for the former are attracted by the reality, the latter by the semblance, of pleasure. Therefore, as we began by saying, the true definition of things honourable and noble is 'those which the righteous man thinks such.' And since each man aims at and prefers such activities as correspond to the inner habits of his soul, and the righteous man lives according to the habit of virtue, it is plain that his pleasure will be in activities according to virtue, and that these, and these alone, win seem to him either honourable or pleasant ; while mere amusements, as being alien to his soul's habit, will seem contemptible, Such a man's decision will be sound and correct. (e) FUETHER ARGUMENTS THAT PLEASURE IS NOT SUMMUM BONUM. Happiness, then, does not consist of Amusement. It would surely be absurd that the Chief End of mar ld:Zr%^t should be amusement, and that men should in itself. spend their energies and endure hardship all lift Bk. X. 6.] Tj'mtslaiion. 563 long for the sake of subsequently diverting themselves. There is nothing but what has an end beyond itself, ^xcept happiness ; to speak generally, everything else that we desire has regard to something beyond. But happiness is an end complete and absolute in itself. Again, to devote ourselves to a life of labour and of privation, ;;with only amusement for a motive, is evidently the sheerest folly and childishness. Oq the con- d'etre of 'amuse" trary, the right course seems to be, as Anacharsis mept is subsequent says, to take amusement only to qualify us for ^° "^ ^' the strain of serious work. Amusement has, in fact, a resemblance ■to relaxation, and all men require relaxation, being unable to labour without intermission. Consequently 'relaxation' is not ;; itself a ' final end,' being taken only with a view to subsequent activity. Furthermore, it is thought that the happy life 3. Amusement is is one in conformity with virtue; but virtue i^rvliy^ider'of involves a spirit of earnestness, and does not the happy life, consist in amusement. We say too that things earnest are better than things frivolous or things that bring amusement, and that the activity of Eeason as the highest faculty and of nomy of our na- man as the noblest creature, is more earnest and t™^, the activity more important than any other ; and the activity powers is happier of that which is highest is at once better and tiiau that of the , fraught with greater happiness. As for bodily or sensuous pleasures, that is a happiness which j; any one might enioy — the slave no less than the ^ . ' T , n -X , n 1 5. Amusement in? best 01 men. 13 ut no one allows a slave any volves dissipation claim to real happiness, any more than to real and may be enjoyed life. True happiness is not possible in such pur- the ^siave™ life "is ^. suits as those of a slave, nor in fact under any inconsistout with other circumstances than the free development of '"'I'p™^^^- a life in harmony with virtue, as has been already explained. f. We may, therefore, conclude that mere amusement is not a thing to be held ! inhonour, and that true Happiness is not to be found in it. Indeed it is absurd to conceive of amusement as being the ' end ' of human life, and to devote one- self utterly to labour and trouble all one's life, to secure amusement : yet this must be allowed to be necessary, if one suppose amusement to be hdppiness. For whatever else we seek, we seek as a means to happiness ; and it is the extreme of folly, and childishness itself, to sweat and stmggle through life to obtain amuse- Sineut ! But to choose amusement on the principle of Anacharsis — that we may do serious work the better for it — is the trae and proper course. For amusement is a kind of respite to those who live a life of effort, inasmuch as they cannot keep up a continuous strain ; it revives their power and restores them to their task refreshed and invigorated j so feat the respite is qot an ' end ' in itself, but Q 9 2 564 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 7. the activity is the ' end ' of the respite. Besides, everybody allows that the truly happy life must be in accordance with virtue ; it must therefore be an earnest life ; and the earnest man is such in virtue of his serious hours, not of those of amusement. Further, we say that things serious are in themselves of higher type than matters jocose and comic ; and that the activity of the better part of the soul' is of a higher type than that of the worse part ; and that which is itself better and has a better origin is more akin to true happiness. Further, indulgence in cai-nal pleasures is common to aU — ^to ordinary men, to base men, to slaves — and to the most villainous as much as to the best ; 'but happiness is said to appertain to the good and to them only ; for no one could ascribe it to the base as well, any more than he could say that the base and the best lived an identical life : because Happiness is not incident to a low standard of living, but resides, as we have already said, in activities which are in accordance with virtue. ii. — Happiness under its ideal aspects. . (a) HAPPINESS, BEING THE ACTIVITY OF THE HIGHEST PART OF OUB NATURE, IS PHILOSOPHIC MEDITATION. If, theu, happiness be the u nfoldiiiff of a life in harmony with virtue,_its^standard must naturally Jje the highest Happiness, is an virtue — i.e. the ^tiid of'IhaFwhichis Jughest. to^'S'Td'Sr® Consequently whate veF thfs beTwhether Intellect /ec« virtue is the Or some Other faculty which,_by_nature's right Isfpart-tltit' seemsTo~rule"anarT6~take pre-eminence and to Ferfect happiness have anr instinctive perception concerning objects will thereiore, be y^^ ^^ ^— ^^ /^jjether it be itself divine, or intellectual acti- y. n -i ■ i . • i yity. whether of all attributes within us it be most divine) — the activity of this faculty, in accordance with its own proper excellence _an3 jeg.HiingTFs^ g^n standard, will be perfect, absoliiEe. happiness ; and, as has been explained, such~airactivity will be meditative or philosophic. It being proved, then, that Happiness resides in activities according to virtue; if there be among such activities any pre-eminent one, that will be the special abode of Happines. For Happiness is pre-eminent and the crown of all things ; and our crovming activity is that of the best among our powers — (that power, I mean, which by nature rules and guides us towards truth and the good ; whether we call it Spirit or by some other name, matters not ; it is that part ih us which comprehends things honourable and divine, and is itself divine, or, at any rate, the most divine of our powers). The activity of this power, well and fitly developed and in accordance with its special virtue, must be Perfect Happiness, • (5) CHARACTERISTICS OF THE LIFE OF MEDITATION. This view-^f-Jiap^iness wil l be s een (from the accompanying Intellectual acti- description') to harmaaizgjwith our p revious state- vity satisfies fully ments and with the truth. all the requisite ' ^ conditions of hap- 1. The activity of Reason i s the highest form of Bt- X. 7.] Translation. 565 activrtyj^sinceJlea^OTiJsJlie highest faculty within us, and the sub- jects which come within the~cogmzrance"of Eeasoa areThe liigh est witEin the range~of thought. conceivable. "^ '^' 2. Moreover this activity is the most abiding : we are better ' abl e to meditate continuo us! v than To~cloT'"cnn- „ ,. ■ ^, . :; — ' - — ; ^ ■ ' 2. It 13 the most tmu ously, augn t else whatever. permanent. 3. This activity ins pired by Philosophy is confessedly more I than_jll.othfiiL_aciivlti^ JhaOJElconf om^ ''■■' virtue, most vIsasimiMe ; and we all think it ^" ■'*, f ""'** '^^^'^' |; essential that pleasure should be mtermmgled with happiness. It is believed at any rate that Philosophy entails pleasures^ ^k?L*_-9?®--™5;?I?ll2BL^°-'^lL.i?- JMitl.J:n32^ ; and it is but natural that the pursuits of those who have attained ito knowledge should be more delectable than the pursuits of others who are searching for it. ' " * 4. Further, the ' self-sufficiejwj'' of. which I have spok en, will be most surely found_iii_the practice of medita- tioBv- Of course the mere necessaries of life are ^'.Z* if perfectly tt . ITT T-1 1 11 seli-sumcing. I required as much by the philosopher as by the man of honour and all others. But, assuming men to be amply provided with necessaries, the uprightjnMLjiaa.^tillJxuihex...need of societyj)f his fellow-citizens, towards whom and in-reeiprocity with_whom he may display his integrity. Similarly in the case of the temperate and brave man — social surroundings are essen- tial. The philosopher, on the contrary, is able to meditate even in isolation, and the more profound a philosopher he is, the better able is he so to meditate. It were, perhaps, preferable that he should have fellow-workers ; still he is in himself per- fectly independent and sufficient for the development of his own life. ^ 5. Again, thejiotiyity of reason, eyen^whgn quite alone, would seem to be cherished foi' its own sake. Nothing |accruesTromlhis''activity beyoiiTThe simple play ^^^^^_ '^ mdcpen- of thought; whereas from external activity we compass some result, greater or less, beyond the mere action itself. 6. Lastly, the activitv_o£ reason seems to impj ijhc-pjjssession of leisure. ^T'o'gain such leisure is the very aim |of all our business, just as the purpose of carry- ^^^ »= ^<^^ ^^ ing on war is to secure peace. 566 The Moral Philosophy of ^Aristotle. [Bk. X. 7. Now the exercise of the jpractical virtues takes .placfi.xitlier in "puBlIc life or in the career of the soldier; but [A.11 other forms of the actions incidental to politics or to war seem andanxtty.]""^"" to involve anxiety and labour— those of war absolutely so. The statesman never resolves on war for the simple purpose of fighting, nor does Tie make warlike preparations without an ulterior aim : he would be regarded as a perfect savage if he treated his friends as enemies simply that battles and slaughters might be brought about. The activity of the statesman also is laborious and_anxious, even beyond i3ie mere exercise of poirticalTuncJtions, aiming, as it does, at compassing ascendancy and honour, or at any rate liappi- ness for himself and his fellow citizens (happiness in thi» sense being distinct from national or public happiness, which in fact we seek as personal and private and distinct from the happiness of the community as such). Tliis Happiness is contoiqilatirc ; for both, our previous acconat of human activities, and the facts as they stand, are witnesses that perfect happiness lies in the activity of contemplation. For indeed (as we said in our treatise on Friend- ship) Intellect is our essential being, and consequently the activity of InteEect is our highest activity, and its discoveries are the highest of aU the discoveries of our senses : and therefore, if Happiness is the highest of all things, its province must certainly be that of Intellect, as the highest of our powers. Furthermore, we must ascribe continuance to Happiness. Perfect happiness is only possible to a man on condition of no sudden break occurring in it : and this condition is most possible to Contemplation, which admits of continuance more than anything else that we do. Further, we conceive that an admixture of Pleasure is necessary to Happiness ; and, of all activities in accordance with virtue, that of the philosophic mind is confessedly most pleasurable. Philosophy indeed appears to confer marvellous pleasures, because of its pui-ity and entire abstraction from matter, and its con- stant unchanging activity about subjects immutable and eternal. Herein it differs from practical activity, which needs matter to work on, and concerns things merely contingent, (i.e., the details of practice), and therefore presenting no scope for perfect Happiness. Further, the truly happy man must be adequate to himself — a quality con- ferred more by contemplative than by practical activity. The contemplative and the practical man alike require the necessaries of life ; in addition to which the practical man needs other things to develope his activity in accordance with virtue ; the just man, r.r/,, requires other men as objects and aids of hia just dealing, and so does the temperate man, and the brave man, and so on. But the Philosopher, even when alone, can philosophize, needing no other presence, and the greater philosopher he is, the less are his extraneous needs ; and even it he does requii'e companionship as an aid to better contemplation, still he is, most of all men, adequate to himself in practising perfectly his special activity. Again, Happiness must be ohoiceworthy in itself and desirable ; and the con- templative life answers to this requirement, being loved for itself. We seek no further end by its means, nor is there any collateral result of Contemplation, besides itself ; whereas by aU the practical virtues, there is some such object, greater or less, to be gained ; by courage, victory ; by temperance, serenity of soul ; by prudence, discovery of means to the supreme End ; by all alike, public prosperity. But Contemplation has no further result, with a view to which it Bk. X. 7.J Translation. 567 seems desirable, but is loved for its own sake. Therefore it appears to constitute human happiness. Again, Happiness must subsist in a certain serenity and iSsure for contempla- tion. For leisure, not work, is the true end ; we work hard, in order to win leisure, just as we fight in order to win peace. But the activities of the practical vu-tues are exercised in public affairs and in war, which, of all actions, seem furthest removed from serenity and leisure. This is especially true of war ; for, in that, serenity is impossible : (if it were otherwise, war would be sought for its own sake, which of course never happens ; no one wishes to cause a war as per se desirable ; it would be the act of a miscreant to maie friends into enemies for the sake of war and carnage). Public affairs, too, are clearly contrary to leisure ; the public man, besides managing the affairs of the state, has to obtain power and honours for himself, and happiness too, only not merely for himself but for 'the people as well ; and this is distinctly a double work ; as is proved by his own lattitude towards it ; he is not satisfied with his own happiness, but seeks that of the people, thereby showing that they are distinct. (c) E^SUMjfi : THE CONSTITUENT ELEMENTS OP THE PERFECT LIFE. If, thereforej_amajigL_a£iiQiis_TOnform|i^^ career of the statesman or of the soldier,_,though pre- emmenT in cclat and impQctance, ■ is -ajxxious Kxbaustive rie- , — , -; ; Yr ~- n • Bcription 01 the and subor dinate to nlt erior purposes, anggs not philosophic life and ch oiceworthy for it s own sake, whereas on the it-^ pre-eminenoo other hand, the activiiy of the intellect seems action. pre- eminent in moral w ortli (as being contempla- tive andphHosophic)^ and aims at_Tin_end heyorifl ..jtself, and involves a pleasure all its own and a pleasure which strengthens the power of~nrodrta±roirrtiriTd-Tfj4irrfller, the characteristics of 'self-sufficiency ' and ' freedom from care ' and ' unwearyingness ' (felatively to man), together with all other attributes that are commonly assigned to the tarppynilnTafe' "seen to follow in the Byak^ of th its . Ititsltg ntHar^tivity — this, assuredly, will be the perfect happiness of man, if taken to comprise within it a full term of life, nothing incomplete being compatible with the con- ditions of happiness. And since, of all actions according to virtue, those of public affairs and war n are most considerable in honour and importance, and at the same time are most contrary to leisure, and specially directed to some end, not being in themselves desirable ; while the activity of the intellect is of higher type, (as being the activity of the soul's noblest part.) and is sought for no object besides itself, nor itself aims at any other object, but possesses its special pleasure, and that a greater pleasure than attaches to the practical activities — which pleasure enhances the activity : since, also, the activity of Intellect is at once most adequate to it- self and most serene (as far at least as such states are possible to man), and shares, in a word, all the qualities specially ascribed to the happy man : since, I . say, all this is so, it is plain that Contemplation, which is the activity of the intellect in accordance with virtue, prolonged through a complete Ufa (for neither ; duration, nor any particular of happiness, should be imperfect) forms the perfect '/happiness of man. 568 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 7. Such a life is ideal ; yet it is attainable in virtue of the divinity of his nature. Moral obligation to follow the life of reason as the only true and proper lite of man (reason being the truest 'self.') {d) THIS IS NOT AN UNATTAINABLE NOR TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAL. A life that fulfils these conditions will be higher than the com- mon range of-nitniT — Ifo~one" can livea life l ike thiOoj[aras_h e is mere ly man, but injp far as there is a divme ele ment inherent i n bis nat ure. In the proportio n in which this divine element is superior to the complex organism of man, in that degree also his InteIIectiial~oF~spiritual~lictivities" will be superior to those which are' inspired by ordinary virtue. If, therefore, intellect_Jsdivine_relativel^to man, then the life wMchZis_conformable_ Jo_ injellectwill be divine relatively to the.liffijof man. But,^or all tha^^-^we-eraghtTTotto follow the advice of those who bid us think only of human interest as proper to our human life, and of that mortality which all men share. Rather ought we, so far as may be conf'pivable_aniL-pflsaible,-£rite]i_up. on immortalit y, and to shape pjii^eveixJhougli£^i.yi.Jhaaiinu3i'J.iviji^^ of the highest priDciple_w:ithin-us. Little though it be in bulk, intellect far surpasses all other powers in dignity and capacity : it would seem, in fact, to be each man's own ' self — if, that is, a man's ' self ' is the sovereign principle, and that which is highest within him. It would, therefore, be a monstrous thing if a man were to prefer not the life which is peculiarly his own, but a life that belongs to something else. The view maintained (in the last Book) will harmonize with the present :_that ^whicli is^ p^culiarlX-3sCT«, is naturally the best and most agreeabl e to ev ery creature.' So, too, if intellect be pre-eminently distinctive of man, the life regulated by intellect will be the life most pleasurable to man, and consequently also the life most truly blessed. The life of reason, being suited to the highest nature of man, will give him truest pleasure and hijjpiness. Such life, however, is superhuman : a man who lives it, lives it, not qua man, but in 60 far as he has an element of divineness in his nature. So then, by as much as the divine element excels the human admixture, by so much do its activities excel the other human activities— and its virtue, the rest of moral virtue. For if man is godlike qua Intellect, the life of Intellect is godlike as compared with all other human life. Let us not, however, foUow the principle inculcated by some, ' Let man think man's thoughts, and mortal man heed the things of the mortal state.' Rather, let each man, as far as lieth in him, grasp at immortality and do all that he can to live in accordance with the highest element within him. And this element in us ,ds Intellect. Granted, that in size and bulk it is inferior to all others, because it is above and apart from matter — it is yet the greatest of all in power and worth. It would be utterly absurd if a man v/ere to choose for himself, not his own life ^^- ^- S-] Translation. 569 tut that of some one else : yet, in simple fact, a, man's true self is that in him which is most eminent and best ; and he does not live for his true self, nor his : own proper and real life, unless he lives in accordance with this best element. ;. Indeed, what we said before will exactly apply here : what is proper and special to each man's nature is best and pleasantest to him ; and the thing most proper and special to man is activity according to Intellect (if, as appears to be true, a, man's Intellect is his real self) and, of each thing that has any activity, the special function is to develope that activity. AVhence we conclude that the life according to Intellect is the highest and pleasantest life for man, and makes him most truly happy, and is, consequently. Human Happiness, in a primary sense and degree. iii. — Happiness under Its social aspects compared with tlie ideal happiness of Reason. (a) CONTEMPLATION IS DIVINE : ACTION IS HUMAN. The life jnspired by other virtues is but s_cconcl in the scale of hanniaess. Actmties conformable to a law otlief Z ^ ] ,, *■ ., , n T, , T • Happiness for man than that 01 Iteason are proper _to man only in as a socmZ being is Lis social cbaraicter. it is only" by intercourse derived from the .., ^1 . • J 1 • moral virtues. one With another, in commerce, in the various kinds of business, and in the control of our feelings, that wc can display justice and courage and perform acts corresponding to the virtues, so as to maintain what is becoming in every relation and circumstance. But these actions and qualities are distinctive of our huinun rather than of our spiritual natui-e. Some of these q ualities seem in fact to resu lt from^ our_physical organization, and in manvways the excellence of „ ■J ^j t—- ..^—v ^ _ - Some moral virtues onr..jn.ojal jiatar.fi seems iaJ)aungepxably asso- ttredepeudentupon ciated withjbe feelings. the bodily consii- Further, the moral s.caae is_closely dependent " '"" ° ™™' upon _the_ excellence of the moral naiure",^ and this again reacts . upon the moral sense, since of course, the prin- ciples oT the moral sense' are such as to cor- The moral sense respond with the. mojal virtues, and the standard moral vii-tues, of the moral virtues is one that is regulated by the moral sense. These moral PYcpllpnnppj mnTP-omMyJw-H'fHl-tijL as they arejd-th the eBiotioB%-w-it I be di a play e d4 n mn n in „SQ->far as he isa comnauud-Ql soul and body, and the *"'l *''^ moral vir- ~;:, — -T^ — ■ = •' . tues are bound up excellences of man as a complex organism are with the affections. those which are proper to his distinctively human nature. Consequently both the 44£g-tiiatis-regulatcdi.by Hence the moral the virtiies_-aJidJlie~bappin£S§3JiidLisJJi^ hlppiies") \°Tu. duct-TCilLhfi-jJiar-a©teristTcalljT^«<»effl-%aiid-ada.pli3d man rather than to the frame of man. =*^=^*'= °^ ^P'^*"^'- 570 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 8. The happiness produced by pliilosophy, on the other hand, will be inflepp.iidp.nt nnd apart IroTT fhnmli. n intprpRt.a Whereas the spin- , , , >„ , , , , tnal life (and con- and liuwan needs. [bo much only need be templative _ happi- gaid about it: to examine the conception more ness) is divine. i- i i i j i i i i.i c particularly would be beyond the scope of our present purpose.] The second place is held by that happiness whicli attends the exercise of the other virtues. Their activities are purely human, and subsist in the mutual relations of mankind. For instance, we exhibit towards each other acts of justice, of courage, and of the other virtues, in mutual affairs, dealings, and compacts, and we tutor our own feelings by preserving a seemly regard for our neighbour : and all these things, combined, are the preservation of this life of ours, in so far as its mortal admixture is concerned ; they are, in fact, distino tively human. Again, the moral virtues are at times much influenced by corporeal conditions many, e.g., have naturally and constitutionally a tendency to temperance, or to bravery, or to magnanimity ; and, in a general way. Moral Virtue and Insight are closely connected with the feelings. (I couple together Moral Virtue ajid' Insight for reasons previously stated, \.c. because Insight has its first prin- ciples in the moral virtues, which supply to it the power of rightly conceiving the End ; while Insight confers on Moral Virtue the knowledge of Means to the End, as we have explained in the thirteenth chapter of the Sixth Book.) Siace, then. Moral Virtue concerns, and is closely connected with, human feelings, and Insight has been proved to be inseparable from Moral Virtue, it clearly follows that every virtue that is exhibited in action is closely coimeeted with the feelings ; that is, it concerns the admixture of the human element in ns, and the life centred in that element, the vu-tues of which are the distinctively human virtues. (Indeed, the definition of man is borrowed from the terms expressing the human admixture of his nature.) Consequently, the life and the happiness that are in accordance with these activities, are the distinctively human life and happiness : while only that life and happiness that are in accordance with Intellect are divine, being sundered" from things purely human. To explain exactly how they are sundered, and what their essential character is, would be beyond the scope of this Ti'eatise, and more suited to Theology, to declare. Let it sufiHoe at present to affirm that they are superhuman. (^) CONTEMPLATION IS FAR LESS CKPENDENT UPON OUTWARD CIRCUMSTANCES THAN ACTION IS. IntellectualJiappiQesi:miuld-seem.-s^^ extern al help only to a trifling_eilfint,J2LJiL any^^e far less fs^'frr^'tesf tk tl'f^a xioErihrh^ppiness^ of the m^al nature. creation of ciroum- Granted that the need of tliebiTe~riecessaries of moraro*Ldau£ ^i^"^ ^^ ^"^^^ "^ '^oth cascs to an equal extent, which presupposes thougli the citizcn of the world be more solicitous a suitable field for ^^^^ ^lie body and material thino-s :— the relative its {XCtlVltV. difference in either case will be but slight. In regard, however, to the exercise of their powers and faculties, the contrast ,l)g twcen theiL_extgr nal needs wil l be considerable. The liberal man wpl need resources to carry out his liberal purposes. Bk. X. 8.] Translation. 571 The jusl man •yvill need money to r eguite his oblig ations. [Mere ' good intentions ' are uncertain and pfecariouiT~even the unjust pretend that their desire is to act justly.] Theurave man, again, will reguire opp ortunitie sif he is to achieve any exploit worthy of his courage; and the temperaIeTItEnnvi-H~n«ed- moral freedom. How, otherwise, could he, or any other character, be made manifest ? f Upon this point-a_ controversY h as been raised-— whether the f'most4is±i»6ti¥e-paELi3£virtu£be the intention of "the jgffiUa:..flifi_performaice^^^^^^^ '^^ X^f^^l ; -iieing JjHplifid~iinjiei^,^thfiJ:-.aspect. Clearly the fore, dependent absolute or perfect form of virtue does not reside "P"' the perform- ^ ance oi acfs, and so, in either intention or act singly, but in the union absolutely inter- Ofboth. twined with extei- „ . , nal conditions?' However, tor the perlormance ot virtuous ac- ,; tions a ni an requires mai3y"~TaY"oural)^J^onditions ; and the sreater and more noble those actions are, the „ , , . , ° -— -. -...„__,, r\ ,-\ ltalogu£s_JiL,moral_j:elations, we ^hall find that they are all Jriflingj^n^^toojnad^uate^forjh^^ of Yet, notwithstanding, we haYe_all thlsjjcl ief of the Grods t hat they live, and hence that their existence is a- What then is the conscious and active existence : — we cannot of we^ exclude action course imagine that they sleep their life like and production? an Endymion. But in the case of one who thought'''*''"' "' ^«''"««» if action, and, still more, production, be taken out of his range, what is there left except meditation ? Bk- X- 8'] Tratislatton. 573 So, then, the activity o f the Gods, though excelling our own in blesse dness, will be thepractice of meditation ; ' au^Pa mong all the fom is~Qr~anTS3y3^irl-; ' a^ The life of the possibleLjfor^an^that will be most blessed that Sen^'^"'™ is nearest akin_tQjhe lit'e"of Ths~(jotis.- ■ There is a new proof of this view in the fact that the animal world generally have no share of happiness, de- j ,1 J} J.^ J} IX j> Ti ,• • The same truth is prived as they are ot the faculty of meditation m shown us by con- the true sense of the term. trast of the animal On the p art of the Gods, then, theirjwhole life '°° °™' is bleSSSd ; TuFonThe part of men, their life is only blessed so far as there is abiding in us some faint resem- blance to that heavenly contemplation. But of ^^^ therefore w^iii all living creatures not one, save man, is happy, be in exact ratio of as having in no sense any part in the ' Vision T" ?°^^'-' °* '^''"" Divine.' J The conolu&ian.^tli f!.refore. is th is : wide_ as is the range of i^tntelle ctual acti vi ty, so wide is the range of hap- piness TTEose^ to who„se_lat_it_ falls to have a power of eontem- more uninterrupted vista of truth, realize to an piation lasts, so , — r — ,• "t — I -TT' — r — 1 -'" - long does the con- equal exteiit-_ffiliat-4ti4S-to— be-happy — not un- sciousness of hap- certainly and as matter of chance, but in right p™^^ continue. of their powers of meditation, the vision of truth being precious and glorious in itself. In a word, then, happiness is a species of ec- J"on^andha*'''iif''" sta gy, o r meditation upon things diviiiei ~~~^ are identical. The follo"wingf consideration, also proves tliat perfect happiness subsists in the contemplative life. Contemplation is the sole fimction of God, who is purely blessed and happy. For what other occupation can we possibly ascribe to Him ? Cam we say He deals justly, for instance ? Nay, it is clearly absurd to conceive of Him as concluding bargains, restoring pledges, and so forth. Can we say He acts with couiage ? Nay, in what sense can He have to face things terrible or risk his life for honour ? The very expression is preposterous. Can He show liberality ? Nay, to whom can He show it, and by gift of what ? It is absurd to conceive of Him as having money which He needs for his own support, but gives to others for generous motives. And how can He be temperate, having no bad appetites to curb 1 All such practical qualities are petty and unworthy to be ascribed to God. But if, as all men conceive. He has life, He must have an activity — we cannot think that He lies torpid and inactive, like Bndymion ! ■ So, since He has an activity, but not, as we have shown, that of moral action, still less that of production, (for it is not reasonable to think of Him as continuously labouring, as handicraftsmen do, to produce material results,) what is left for us to ascribe to Him but Contemplation ? ' The activity, therefore, of God, being preeminent in blessedness, must be that of Contemplation ; and perfect HajDpiness must certainly subsist in the con- templative life, because there it wUl be most closely linked to the activity of Gfod. A further proof is, that no irrational beings have any share in true happi- ness, being wholly devoid of the activity of Contemplation. The whole life of 574 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 9. God is purely blessed : the life of man is blessed just so far as it bears tbe Hkenesa and stamp of tbe divine activity ; the life of animals is not purely blessed at all, inasmuch as they have no share in the contemplative faculty. All things there- fore that have any share in Contemplation, have Happiness, and the larger share of Contemplation, the more Happiness. In short. Happiness and Contemplation are co-extensive, and that not incidentally but in virtue of Contemplation being verily and indeed Happiness, and in itself honourable and precious. The conclusion is : ' Happiness, in its highest and most complete sense, is a sort of Contemplation,' {d) THE EEQUIKEMENTS OE THE PHILOSOPHER ABE SLIGHT, AND ARE SURE TO BE PROVIDED BY THE GODS, WHO APPROVE HIS PURSUITS. Bat on account of his human nature, the philosopher will require the circumstances around him to be sunny rcttemSion ^^^. ^^'ig^t. The nature of man is not sufficient, is not absolute in its isolation, for the development of the spiritual ::iffcfnd"ti:n: l^f^- his body must be sound and healthy: food are assumed ; e.g. and the conveniences of life must be provided for health and the ne- i^j^j^ Yet surely we must not suppose that, if a cessanes of Me. • , i i i -i, • , , man is to be happy, he will require a multitude of favourable conditions, though it be not competent for any one to be happy without certain external advantages. The true suf- ficiency of the philosopher does not depend upon superfluity; nor does our estimate of a man's character depend upon the abundance of his riches ; nor does the morality of the act depend upon the wealth of the agent. It is competent for a man to per- form noble deeds, though he be not ' lord of earth and sea : ' even with moderate resources a man may act worthy of his virtue. One may see unmistakable illustrations of this truth, since private individuals are thought to performhonour- Even moral yii-tue j^yg ^cts no less than potentates ; nay, even can exist without ^ ■ i. p j.1, 1- J ■ l great wealth or morc SO. it IS sumcient lor the practice of virtue power, though cer- tji^t a man havc a bare competency. However tain conditions , . , ,, ... , i-/< •^^ i must be assumed. poor his Worldly station, a mans life will be a happy life when he devotes his faculties to the practice of the virtues. Solon was probably correct in the portrait he drew of the happy oderate '^^^^'^ ^^"^ described them as being (1) moderately means are suffi- provided with external goods, (2) as having per- cient for the at- formed most noble deeds (as he reckoned them), nes^rsuppoi'tcd by ^^^ (3) as having lived a temperate and sober life. the authority of Thoiigh posscssed of Only moderate means, a man (1) Solon, ^^^. gj^jj- pgj.fQj.jj^ jjjg (jy(_y. jjj ^Y^ jj-g relations. Anaxagoras, again, seems to have understood by the happy rem, Bk. X. 9.] Translation. 575 not the rich and powerful, since he said that he should not be ^ surprised if the happy man were thought by the 'i multitude a mere unfortunate. The mass of mtn naxasoras. form their estimate by outward circumstances, of which alone have they any perception. The opinions, therefore, of our sages seem to harmonise with my own definitions. This agreement at any rate ~. T .. • n • /■ y-n Tile appeal to au- anords some presumption in their favour; still, thority must be in matters of conduct, strict truth can only be li"™^ °^^* by expe- I i-jui i- e li. ji?ii rience and fact. I ascertained by observation or results and of actual hfe. The important element in the question depends upon par- ticular circumstances. Consequently we must bring the opinions and theories I have mentioned to the test of experience and of real life ; and if our theories harmonize with facts we may accept them, whereas if they are at variance with facts we must regard them as ' idle words,' But when a man developes a life in harmony with Reason and ;, cherishes Reason above all things, he seems to be most perfectly constituted and most beloved of '^}^^'°- argument : TT o T -J? J. 1 Yi 1 • 1 1 ™s -wants of those Heaven. Surely it any watchfulness is shown by ^ho cherish things Gods for the interests of men (as men hold), it is di'^^e are sure to hut natural that they should take pleasure in UeSng"°of ^the that element of our nature which is highest and Gods, who care for . most akin to themselves, viz. Reason, and that what they love. "^^ they should requite with their blessing those who love and honour Reason most truly when they see them having reverence for what is pleasing to Heaven, and living just and noble lives. That all these qualities are found in the philosopher is no doubtful truth. The philosopher, therefore, is most beloved of the G-ods ; and it is but natural ^''"roachel^neTr^ert that he should also and by the same right be most to the ideal of the happy. Here then is a new proof by which philo- ^"'^^ ami is^ most Sophy and happiness are shown to be identical. Still, for tlie work of Contemplation, it is necessary to keep the body sound and healthy by external aids : for it is irrational to expect any man, as suoh, not to require these aids : human nature is not, in such points, self-supporting. I But, of these thing-s, the man of Contemplation will need less than the man of action. Absolutely, indeed, his requirements will not be many or great ; they will consist merely of the necessaries of life, and of those to a moderate amount. For it is not the abundance of wealth and other externals that makes the happy man adequate to himself, or that persuades htm to judg-e rightly in practical matters, or to do his duty therein. A man may act nobly, without possessing power by land and sea ; he anay, from moderate resources, effect such things as would well beseem men invested w'th dominions far and wide. We see this 576 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 10. clearly every day, wlieii we find private nien keeping the path of Honour and fair dealing, as well as, if not better than, men high in place and power. Such moderate external provision, then, is sufficient for the truly happy man ; it will enable him to practise his virtue, and to live the life of Happiness, without let or hindrance. Solon confirms this view, by defining Happiness, not as consisting in external goods, but as being the lot of those who have a competency of external goods, who have done deeds of fame, and have lived a temperate life : for, be it well noted, men of limited possessions may equally walk in the path of duty. Anaxagoras, also, it would appear, held that the'happy man need not be rich or powerful : nay (he says) the many. would think him an absurd personage ; and no wonder, for the many have no eye for anything but externals and appear- ances, and are quite capable of thinking the really good and happy man a poor sorry creature. Thus the opinions of these philosophers agree with our theories as here set forth — a fact which adds a certain confirmation to what we have said : though of course the main confirmation of moral theories is the agreement of the facts of life with them, just as their main refutation is a discrepancy of those facts. Practical facts are the standing test of theory : let us therefore consider the foregoing treatise and apply it to human actions and life, and, where it harmo- nizes, let us accept it as ti'ue ; where it is at variance, let us presume it to be words and wind. Lastly, the following argument evinces the superior happiness of the man whose activity is of the Intellect. He is the most beloved of God — whioli, in itself, is the summit of Happiness. For if (as is held by all men, and, surely, with trath) God has any regard for things human and any care for their condition, in what, of aU the possessions of man, should He more fittingly delight than in the noblest element of Humanity, which is most akin to Himself, namely in Intellect 1 And if this be His principal delight. He wiU repay with all favour those who love, honour, and exercise Intellect, as being guardians of that which He most loves and to which He is most akin, and as acting in other respects well and nobly. Such is the character of the true philosopher, whose activity is that of the Intellect; and he, consequently, is most loved of God, and is, naturally, the happiest of men withal. The conclusion, therefore, is that the philosopher is the tnily happy man, and that Happiness subsists in the life of Contemplation. III.— THE BORDER- LAND BETWEEN ETHICS AND POLITICS. (a) THE THEORY OF MORALS SUBORDINATE TO PRACTICAL STATESMANSHIP. Now that a sufficient description has been given to explain in general outline my theory of life and virtue, of The aim of Ethics friendship and of pleasure, are we to suppose IS not merely the ,i , .i cl^ • m \- ■ ■, , ^T -r anatomy of social that the purpose 01 this Treatise is complete ? Is duties but the real- it not rather the truth that, as the savins: is, in ization of virtue m . • . -,,,•, , . ° ' practical life. questions concerning conduct, the end is not to speculate nor to comprehend the bearing of every duty, but rather to carry them into effect ? Neither assuredly, in Bk. X. 10.] Translation. 577 the case of virtue, is it enough to understand its meaning, we must endeavour to possess it for ourselves and to put it to prac- tical use, or to adopt any other means theft be by which we may ourselves become virtuous. Had theories of virtue been sufficient to make men virtuous, most deservedly, as Theognis says, would they have carried off many and great rewards, and it ^""^^^ speculations .-, , 1,1 • 1 areperae profitless, would have been our duty to have equipped our- except as an encou- selves with them. In fact, however, theories are ragement to tiie only found to have influence enough to urge forward, and encourage to virtue, such of the young as are noble- minded, and even to keep obedient to virtue characters high- tempered and truly enamoured of virtue, amid the assaults of evU; but on the other hand they are powerless to incite the masses to the practice of virtue and the sentiment of honour. Such in fact is the tendency of the masses, that they are con- trolled by fear rather than by self-respect, and they refrain from what is base through apprehen- '^^^ J°-^^ <>* ™s" • c ■ ^ I.J.1 J.1 j> p require penal sanc- Bion 01 punishment rather than irom a sense 01 tions rather than shame. Living by the rule of their passions, "^oral appeals to they foUow after such pleasures as are congenial ^ance^to duty.* ^" to them, and compass opportunities by which such pleasures may be gained ; so, too, they try to avoid the pains that conflict with their pleasures, and they have not so much as a notion of what is noble and inherently pleasurable, never having tasted its sweetness. When men have a character such as this, what argument can possibly bring them to order ? It is an impos- „ , ., ,., ,, ,.,• , (T Hopelessness of Bible task, or at least it is no easy one, to reiorm attaining a social by means of argument impressions that have reformation by /.I,. T, 1 ill L means of argument. tor a long time been stamped upon the character. It is surely a result to be satisfied with, if, when all conditions are provided through which we are thought likely to become good, we may even so gain some share of virtue. We have, in whac we have said, given a suitable and sufficient sketch of the Virtues and of Friendship, and of Pleasure, and of Happiness : and our Treatise needs no fm"ther account of them. Is then our whole design accomplished, and has our task reached the proper oonclusion ? Not so, for our Philosophy has Action in view, and must be summed up and completed in conformity with that design — whUe to know what Virtue is, o* what Friendship, and soon, is theory only. Therefore, even as the man who is aiming at vii'tue must not close his effort P P 578 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 10. when he has learnt what he should do and from what he should abstain, and what Virtue is, and what Vice, and what the supreme end and object of Humanity — but must apply himself to Action, and do the right and avoid the wrong and strain erery nerve to reach true Happiness — even so, I say, he whom we may call the athlete of Virtue must not be satisfied with what we have hitherto said (which only shows him what each of these things — Virtue, Friendship, Pleasure, Happiness — is in itself) ; he must go further and learn, as it were, to bring them into being aright, and having learnt, must teach the same, feeUng that thus only can he be an actual Teacher of Virtue. For the Teacher must so shape his teaching as to perfect his pupil ; and perfection, for the athlete of virtue, lies in becoming truly virtuous and a willing doer of all that is honourable. Clearly therefore we must add, to what we have said about the virtues, direc- tions for practice — what actions a man must do and what disposition he must develop to make himself really akiu to Virtue and the Good, and really inclined to hear expositions of Virtue, and capable of living according to her laws. For thus our treatise on Virtue would be adequate to its own aim, by preserving throughout the result it develops — viz., the virtuous character. Therefore we must try to exhibit the method of teaching that leads to action j for if a mere treatise on Virtue could induce men to be virtuous, I should indeed, in the words of Theognis, 'Win me a manifold wage, ample and merited meed,' and my Treatise would be of high value and much to be sought after. As it is, such words seem able to stimulate and exhort to virtue and its practice and habit, all the better and more liberal, noble, and aspiring dispositions among our youth ; but not yet able to do the same by the many : of whom no one can be led to choose honour and eschew baseness, merely by means of words and per- suasion. For they are not led by a fine seiise of shame to abhor the veiy idea of appearing base^ — but, if at all, by fear of consequences : and they do not ab- stain from mean actions because they are mean and because to do them is base, but because of the penalties. And the cause of this is, that such men do not live by Reason, the parent of Honour — but in obedience to their instincts, and consequently in pursuit of the pleasures which follow those instincts, and in avoidance of the pains which thwart them. And avoidance of pains is Fear ; and when men are in this state, and, never having tasted of things truly honourable and right are unable even to conceive of them, what mere Treatise can set them in a better way? It is impossible, or next to it, for mere argument to remove qualities engrained and confirmed by lapse of time. Other means are required ; and, even with them, we must be well satisfied if one or two, out of the many, turn to Virtue and good principles. It being allowed, then, that words are not adequate to secure the object in view, we must inquire what that is which is needed as a substratum, to enable argument to persuade men to the Good. (^i5) THE PROVINCE OF EDUCATION IDENTICAL WITH THAT OF LAW. The means whereby men are made good, are variously ex- plained. Some philosophers think that goodness ^ioh Ke'usT^ ^s * gif<^ of nature : others that it is a formation the attainment of of habit : others again, that it is the product of ture"^(2f Train^*" histruction Or philosophy. (3) Philosophy. ' Now, evidently, a gift of nature does not depend (1) Nature is the "P°° '^'^'^ ^^^ control : it results from * chance instrument of Pro- divine,' and falls only to the lot of those who are « irfencc. ^j.y|y , favourites of fortune. ' Bk. X. lO.J Translation, 579 Reason and instruction certainly are not equally effectual in all cases, but (to secure their influence) the soui of the student must be previously moulded by the gleriiBrTliLut formation of habits, with the aim that the plea- (2) previous Train- sures or aversions it feels may be true and right '°^ " ^''"'P'^'^^- — the soul being like the ground that is to nourish the good seed. If a man live by the law of his passions he will not hear the voice of reason dissuading him from his evil ways, nor yet again will he understand ; and when a man is in such a frame of mind, how is it possible to convince him of his folly ? In a word, passion seems to yield not to Reason but to force. Hence it is essential that the character or temper of a boy should be previously shaped in some way or other ,1. ill ■• D • L ■> ■ Essential import- so as to be naturally receptive of virtue, loving auce of cow/ha- what is noble and scorning what is base. But it bituation to the is difficult for a boy to secure a right education P'""'^"' °^ ^''^'''■ unless he be reared from early youth under the discipline of laws framed for moral ends. To live a life of temperance and of endurance is not agreeable to men in general, least of all tctthe young. Their diet and pursuits ought, therefore, to be controlled by legal sanctions : such a discipline will not* be painful if it be made habitual. Th.e causes of Virtue in man are, it is allowed, three— Nature, Instruction, Habit. Of these, Nature is plainly not under our own control. To have a natural, disposition to Virtue comes to the truly fortunate by some divine agency. Instruction, and mere argument about virtues, cannot, in every case, persuade or convince, as we have already shown. Habit is necessary, before argument. That is, the soul of him who listens to the argument needs a previous equipment of good habits, whereby he feels delight in, and dislike for, the proper objects. This is the right preparation for Instruction — the soil, as it were, beat fitted for the seed : and without such preparation, how can one yield to any argiunent that dissuades from Pleasure 1 nay, how can he, who lives according to his instincts alone, even comprehend such argument ? and if he cannot comprehend it, how can it convince him of error ? To make instincts yield to Keason plainly requires something more than argument — a certain/«rcc. The words of Reason, then, being incapable by them- selves of making men good. Habit must form the soil for Instruction to sow ; that is. Habit must aid Instruction to qualify the leai-ner for closer Idnship with Virtue, more love of the noble, more hatred of the base. Thus we have shown that Habit, and a certain preparation of soul, must precede Virtue. How is good Habit, and sound guidance and direction towards Virtue, to be secured without rules of conduct, themselves right and just and conducive to Virtue? Such rules are necessary for our education, from childhood itself. For temperate and hardy life is not pleasant to average men, especially in youth ; and consequently their practice, nurture, and life in general, must be placed under rules ; a process which only habituation can make otherwise than painful to usi r P 2 580 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. \JS&. X. 10. (c) THE REIGN OF LAW MUST, THEREFOEB, EXTEND TO THE WHOLE OF LIFE. Yet it is not sufficient, surely, that we should enjoy a proper course of diet, and supervision only as boys: S»d'Zt"be even When grown to man's estate, we must continued by the practise the traditions of our boyhood and live Se fee^'' *''' l^y tabit ; in the regulation of our habits, there- fore, and generally in the whole conduct of life, we shall need the control and guidance of the laws. Compulsion rather than reason is the motive to which the masses yield obedience: pains and penalties are more efficacious with them than the sense of right. Looking to the diiferent motiVes which influence men, some „, „, ^ , philosophers think that our legislators in framing The State must f , , , r i- i i P adopt a system of laws ought to encourage and stimulate men to rewards and pu- the practice of virtue for the sake of what is tives to influence noble and right, with the conviction that those different classes of -^^lio have been rightly brought up by a course 01 izens. ^£ habits will hearken to such an appeal ; on the other hand, if men will not heed the call of duty, but are of too ignoble a nature, then ought our legislators to inflict punish- ments and penalties upon them, and absolutely to banish from the State such as are incurable. The man who is upright and guides his life by the law of honour will, they rightly think, be obedient to the voice of reason ; whereas the bad man while striving after pleasure is controlled, like a refractory steed, by the infliction of pain. For the same reason they also maintain that the pains inflicted by the laws ought to be of a character the exact reverse of the pleasures which the delinquents have unduly loved. If it be the fact, then, that, as has been explained, a man must „, „ , , , be morally and nobly trained and moulded to The State must be i- i i i -^ •/.,-, i -, ^ the guardian of the particular habits II he IS to be a good man, and whole life of its then, after his character has been thus formed, citizens, directing i • Tr • -l l- i-i l everything to a P^'SS his lite m pursuits or occupations that are noble and virtuous honourable and right, and under no circum- ^" ■ stances, voluntarily or involuntarily, commit dis- graceful deeds ; — these conditions, I say, can only be secured when men's lives are ordered and their conduct constrained by some form of Eeason and by a moral discipline carrying with it a power of coercion. It is not. in youth only that rules ate liecessaxy, but iti matiliOod &lsO : i(X proper nurture ill youth will not suffice to make men good ; they inUst, Whefl Bk. X. 10.] Translation. 581 grown-up, practise honourable deeds and acoustom themselves to Virtue. So that, at that stage also, and indeed aU through life, rules will be required. For most men obey compulsion better than Eeason, and pen^ties better than the call of Honour. This has induced some men to think that law-givers should begin by virging people to Virtue and the Good, by words and exhortations, in the name of Honour ; for that the good would become better by being thus habituated to the idea of excellence — and then the law-gi»ers should proceed to lay penalties and inflict chastisements on the recalcitrant and less noble natures ; and, finally, should banish the incurably vicious from the society of those who are, or may become, sound men. The natural discipline is that the righteous man, who lives for Honour, should yield loyal obedience to Reason ; and that the base man, who is always craving for pleasure and obeying his animal instincts, should be chastened, like a beast of burden, into obedience and improvement. Thus, we are told, irrational men must be chastised by infliction of those pains which are directly opposed to the pleasures they love : e.g., the covetous man should be despoiled of what he has ; the hectoring braggart should be treated with con- tumely ; the debauched man should be whipped, and so on. Now if all this preliminary discipline be hard and unlovely, and if, for all that, it is essential for every man to be honest and good— the process of proper nurture and education must begin early. We cannot be too soon taught the habit of honour, and to learn and cleave to the good practice thereof, so as to do no mean- ness, either without or with intention. This result can be reached by living a life in obedience to a certain discipline and to fixed rules that hav€ both authority and efficacy. {d) DIFFEBENCE BETWEEN THE LEGISLATION OF THE tAMILY AND OF THE STATE. Now the government of a father has no stability nor any bind- ing, compulsory force. Nor, again, has the ordinance of any single individual a constrain- N" authority, save , , , T . « that of the State, mg power, unless he be a king or a person of ig sufficiently pow- similar authority. On the contrary. Law involves erfui to undertake . , ,. . . -i 1 • • • the education of a power 01 obligation, smce its decision is one ^\^^ citizens. that issues from a kind of Moral Insight and Abstract Reason. Again we hate those who on their own re- sponsibility oppose our inclinations, even though they are right in doing so. On the other hand Law is not offensive to us, since it ordains only what is abstract right. It is only, however, in the city of the Lacedeemonians with a few others that the legislator seems to have made provision for rejrulatino: the diet and pursuits of ^^^ even the , . . T ji • -1 n ci. Z States (excepting the Citizens, in the majority 01 btates a com- that of Sparta) are plete disregard for such matters prevails, and indifferent to their every citizen lives the life he chooses, after the j/^s? ^^^'^^ '" fashion of the Cyclops 'legislating for his childreh and his wife.' The best cotti'sej however, is that there should be a system of 582 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 10. moral education common to all the citizens, and that the legis- Thou h the State ^^^^^^ shoTild have authority to make it compul- is the proper guar- sory. But where National Education is neglected dian of education, ^jy the State, it would seem to be the duty of in default of action i •-,•■-, t , -\ ij.- t- t ^i- by the State pri- each individual to do what m him lies lor his vate and individual children and friends to promote morality among action is necessary. ^^^^^ ^^ ^^ ^^^ ^^^^ ^^ ^^^^ ^^^ ^^g.^.^ ^^ intention of doing so. It would seem from what has been said, that a man would have the best chance of carrying out his purpose by cultivating the spirit of the legislator. For it is evident that the administration of the State is carried out by means of laws, and when the laws are good the administration will be good also. The commands of parents, however, to their children, are not, as a rule, efflca- cious in compelling : nor, indeed, have those of any individual (unless he be a despotic ruler or a king) force to drive average men against their will into the path of Honour. But what the commands of men cannot enforce, the Law can, because it is believed to have been instituted by some superior ipind and judgment. So it is that the multitude detests those who oppose, however rightly, its impulses ; but no one bears amy grudge against the Law, and its directions to do the |;ood and renounce the bad. For, while human teachers of virtue can be suspected of inflicting pain for malicious or jealous reasons, the Law, being impersonal, cannot so be suspected. Laws, therefore, of direction and control, operating in favour of virtue, are necessary to us from childhood. Among communities, however, only that of the Lacedaemonians, with, perhaps, a very few others, has such laws. Most countries have disregarded the necessity of them — and, in such countries, each man orders his life and household as he will, with a sway as absolute as that of the Cyclops — ' O'er wife and children.' The true course is,_to have proper public ordinances, so that all may be able to follow, and live according to, rule and Bight Reason. Where this is not so, and where, consequently, the public interest is neglected, it seems to be the duty of each man to help his children and friends onward on Virtue's path— or, at any rate, to be ready and anxious so to help them when opportunity offers ; and a careful study of the requisite laws will enable every one so to help his neighbours. Now Laws are the essence of careful improvement; and pubUo improvement results from public laws, and all honest and seemly improvements and instructions from corresponding — i.e., honest and seemly — laws. (e) NECESSITY OP A STATESMAN-LIKE SPIRIT, EVEN FOE PRIVATE LEGISLATION. It would seem to be immaterial whether the laws are written or unwritten, or, again, whether they are such But private edu- ^j^^t one pcrson or many will be trained by cation* must be ,, ,i • , . p • -, i- based upon law as them ; their precepts, i.e., are of universal appli- much as State edu- cation, like those of Music or Gymnastic or cation. - _ - similar professions. Bk. X. 10.] Translation. 583 In fact the counsels of a father and the traditions he sets have precisely the same influence in private families as institutions and customs have in States ; nfty, tion'^arfather^'oo- even more so, through the tie of blood and the "upies the position benefits received. In families the members start ° * * ***®' with a store of affection, and are obedient from an instinct of nature. There are, moreover, positive differences in the training suited to private life and in that adapted to the com- „ .. m, . , T ■ .1 Private education munity. There is an exact analogy m the case ss indeed more in- of medicine. As a matter of general theory, dividual and em- repose and low diet are best for a man who is in ^'"°' a fever, but in a particular instance possibly the reverse may be the best. Again, the professor of boxing does not lay down the same method of defence for all his pupils. It would seem, there- fore, that special peculiarities are best and most exactly provided for when the treatment bestowed is personal; the individual being in that case most likely to meet with what is suitable to his own condition. But, notwithstanding, a man will deal most successfully with individual cases, whether as physician, or as trainer, or as a professor generally, if he knows ^^l^Jl^:^ ^'^^^^ the general principle that '. . . . such and such be based upon 00m- is good for all, or for particular classes or sub- ^f^j^^"^'^^ ^"°' jects.' The sciences are said to be, and truly are, concerned with general truths. [Still for all that, though a man be a mere empiric, there is nothing to prevent his providing rightly for some particular case, if he has accurately observed from his own experience the special symptoms attending that particular case. Just in the same way some men seem to be their own best physicians, though unable to render relief to any one else.] None the less on that account would it seem that if a man wishes to become a true artist and to have a knowledge of the principles of things, he ought ■^eng^°^^f^ f surely to go forward to the Universal and ascer- essential to success tain under what conditions it may be realised, ™ treating indivi- since the Universal, as has been explained, constitutes the subject-matter of the Sciences. For the same reasons, I venture to think that the man who wishes by his personal guidance to make his fellows better, wbethey or a larger or smaller scale, i»iigt endeavour to gaiu 584 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 10. the mind of a statesman, since it is only by laws that we are made good. It is not within the power of an Therefore the pri- ordinary person to frame a law at will, nor to should ouitivatethe determine the- character of a law already made: faculty of framing if practical statesmanship is possible at all, it is Sic^tior"'"^' possible only for the scientific student, just as in the case of medicine and other subjects which involve a kind of personal supervision and practical judgment, or ' insight.' It makes no difference whether these laws be written or unwritten, nor whether our concern be to teach many or to regulate the conduct of one — as indeed is also the case with Music, Gymnastics, and the other aocomplighmente. That which will develop one athlete, will develop any number ; and what wiU make one man a musician, will ' ceteris parilms' make any number of men musicians — and, pice versa, what will make many men musicians, wiU make an individual a musician. Correspondingly, a man who has only a single family to direct and regulate, or only one man to teach, may be a legislator, in practice and theory, as much as the man who governs a whole city or nation. Just as a city feels the authority of its manners and customs, a single family feels the authority of the father's commands : and his approval, in the matter of conduct, has a great influ- ence, on the children and the rest of the household, in favour of that conduct — and the gi'eater influence, because of his relationship and their obligations to him; which form a much closer bond between children and their father than any which subsists between citizens and their law-giver. Therefore it is that children, though in other matters obstinate, are pretty easily led by their father, and obey the laws laid down by him better, because of a natural and original affection for him. Besides, private laws are more exact in detail than public laws, and therefore more effective. An analogy to this may be found in Medicine — in which indi- vidual prescriptions, adapted to the constitution of a single person, are more effective than universal precepts. Universal precepts afl&rm, e.g., that a spare diet and rest are good for fever : but an individual case of fever may be better treated in the reverse way. Thus he who prescribes for one patient will be more exactly right than he who merely issues an universal order. And a boxer — if he make his game by careful observation of successive opponents and by a judicious varying of his defence according to circumstances, will be a better boxer. In short, everything will be more advantageously treated if it gets special individual attention ; for so its true requirements are more likely to be discovered. It is plain then that he who knows the universal rule — be it in Medicine, Gymnastic, or Legislation — will be a better manager of an individual case, or of a small number of cases, in proportion as he can modify his scientific universal by application of it to the particular case. He knows already what is good for all men ia this or that condition — (for Sciences are said to be, and aie, of the Universal,) but the application is also necessaiy. Indeed, a man, ignorant of the Universal, but a careful observer of special symptoms, may very likely Eocceed in an individual case. Some men, e.g. with no knowledge how to heal others, are yet good physicians of their own bodies. So it is also with the other professions ; yet, however experience may suffice, in each profession, to deal with individual cases, he who wishes to become really skilled in an art, or truly capable of con- templation, must diligently press on to Science, and to the Universal mth which Science is concerned. This Universal, in the sciences of Medicine, Legislation, or the like, is not to be looked upon as immovable and unchangeable, but as decidedly ooiiingent : for such sciences are theipselves of things contingent, not of things imSbvable. Therefore, as we must in each case aim at the Science, the man who wishes to Bk. X. 10.] Translation. 585 improve other men, whether many or few, must study the Science of Legislation : for it is by means of the Law that we progress towards the Good and towards Virtue. As things are, it is not in the power of any casual man to direct ai-ight either many or even one of his neighbours, nor to teach'them a proper relation to Virtue. This is only possible, if at all, to him among men who knows how to estimate existing laws and to lay down others that are required. (/) FROM WHOM MAY THK PRINCIPLES OF LEGISLATION BE LEARNT ? Shall we, therefore, go on to consider from what sources and how a man may acquire the faculty of making laws ? Is it here, as in analogous cases, from those Politics have not whose profession it is, i.e. from statesmen? For treateYa^ a sepa° legislation seemed to us, and is commonly classed rate study, nor are as, a branch of statesmanship. Or is there jL^reliS"'" obviously no correspondence between the case of Statesmanship and that of the sciences and professions generally ? For in the various arts the artists lay down rules for their art and work out those rules in their own practice, examples being painters and physicians. In regard to statesmanship, on the other hand, though the Sophists undertake to teach the subject, there is tj^ c },• t ii not one of them that puts his theories into framed theories, practice. Practical statesmanship is left to the }>"* ^^^^ theories ,.,. . , 11 , 1 -111 have not been politicians, who would seem to be guided by a based upon expe- kind of native talent and experience rather than "^ience. Politicians, by reasoned conviction. Statesmen are not found ™iio have^'exp&'il to write nor to speak upon the method of politics, ence, have left us though perhaps that were a nobler occupation than ''"sener t eones. elaborating speeches for the law-courts and for the forum ; nor yet again do they appear to have made statesmen of their own sons nor any others of their friends : yet that were a natural thing for them to have assayed, if they had had the power ; nor could they have bequeathed any nobler heritage to their several states, nor could they have preferred any higher faculty to be reserved for themselves and those dearest to them. Yet, assuredly, experience seems to contribute in no slight degree to statesmanship : otherwise men would not have become, as they do, better statesmen Jut experience is ,, , T,. 1 • i- 1 • i found to make po- through^ political associations and intercourse, uticiacs better. Hence those who desire to understand the science of statesmanship seem further to have need of experience. As for the Sophists, those who promise highly are found to be 586 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 10. far from teaching the science of Politics : in fact, they do not so ^ „ , . , much as know what, the distinctive nature of the The Sophists have „ . . i ^ • -j. u- i. j.j. i.i shown an utter dis- Science IS nor what is its subject-matter : other- regard for the con- -vy^ige they would not have ranked it on the same probiTm," ^^ level as Rhetoric or even inferior to it; nor f d would they have supposed that it is easy to legis- oonfused and un- late by Collecting together the most approved worthy notions of among existing laws. ' It is an easy matter,' * ^" ^^° ■ they say, ' to make a selection of the best laws : ' — as though the very selection were not a matter of moral insight, and as though a wise discrimination were not a matter of gravest difficulty, as it is in what relates to musical composition. Now it is only men of experience who judge of facts correctly in all their bearings and who understand the proper The Science of Po- means and the proper manner for bringing about litics must be based . ■,, ji.i-i i>i i upon a thorough each rcsult, and what kinds oi phenomena har- examination of so- monize together. On the other hand, men without nomenl? ^""^ ^^*' experience may be well content if they are not deceived in their estimate whether a particular piece of workmanship has been constructed well or ill, as they might judge of the case of a painting. But ' laws ' correspond to the results of statesmanship, as its products. How then could a man become fit to 'Laws' must be legislate or how could ho decide what laws are viewed [in conneo- , ° „ , . . , , ■ n /->i tion with the facts bcst from a merely empirical observation ? Ob- they are framed to vjouslv it is as impossible as for men to become meet physicians by the mere study of prescriptions. Yet, notwithstanding, men endeavour at any rate to tell us not only difiorent methods of treatment, but also how liticia^^view poii- individuals may be cured and how we ought to ticai 'effects' apart treat each case, merely classifying the various from t eir causes. bodily Conditions. Such an enumeration of par- ticular instances seems to be useful enough to experienced physi- cians, but profitless to such as are unscientific. Assuredly, therefore, collections of Codes and of constitutions are most useful to those who are able to under- Political constitu- stand the theory of them, and to iudge aright what* tions are only use- ■'. ' ■',° °ii, fui to those who enactments are just or the contrary, and what understand poU- gQcial Conditions best harmonize together. But tioal phenomena. .i ^ 'i. i< • j • • i_j. ^ -i • the faculty ot judging aright cannot reside m those who merely enumerate such particulars without an indepen- dent power of their own (unless such a judgmeot could be spoo- Bk. X. 10.] Translation, 587 taneous and innate), though they may perhaps become more expert upon such subjects. Thus we have proved that he whom we have called ' the athlete of Virtue ' muBt study legislation ; we must now inquire how that study is to be pursued. As one leams to be a scholar, or a musician, from one who is already such, so it is evident, one must learn to be a legislator from one who understands legisla- tion — that is, from a statesman ; for Legislation is a branch of Statecraft. Statecraft appears to differ, in some points, from other faculties and sciences, in which the same men teach the methods and practise the activities of their profession. A physician, and a painter, each practises his own art and teaches it as well. But with Statecraft the case is different. The Sophists announce them- selves as teaching the art of politics, though they never practise it : statesmen practise it, but never teach it ; nor indeed could they do so, for they employ no method or science in their practice of politics, but proceed by a sort of natural aptitude, and rather by experience than by pure intelligence. The ability to teach they clearly have not ; they never do teach, nor tell others by speech or writing, anything about their business — though, if they could, they surely would speak of it. It would surely contribute more to satisfy their ambition, if they could compose works on politics, than all their forensic or popular speeches. Certainly also, if they knew how to communicate the art of politics, they would malce statesmen of their sons, or of some of tfieir friends : for, if they had the power, they would naturally have the will, thus to benefit their friends or nearest relations. Indeed the greatest and most useful gift they could bequeath to their country would be written exposition and instruction in the art of Politics ; nor could they desire for themselves, their sons, or their friends, anything better than the ability to communicate that art. Plainly, then, if they could teach Politics, they would wish to do so, and would do so. As they obviously do not do so, it is plain that they cannot : it is plain that they have not themselves acquired it by any rational or scientific method, but by experience oiJy. And experience, no doubt, does contribute a good deal to enable one to deal with practical politics. Men really do become statesmen, or something like it, by practical familiarity with affairs of state : which .there- fore ought to be acquired, as well as scientific knowledge of statecraft, by those ambitious to become statesmen. The Sophists, indeed, announce themselves as teachers of Legislation ; but they do not teach it, for all their professions. Nay, so devoid are they of power to speak of it aright, that they do not even imderstand its essence nor its nature. They regard it as merely identical with or inferior to the Art of Rhetoric, and consider it so easy as to be in the scope of every man. To collect the most approved codes, and to select out of them the best laws, is their idea of Legisla- tion ; and such estimation and selection they consider easy. But — in the first place — it is not easy, nor possible to every man who happens to wish it, to acquire the faculty of rightly judging each part of a code : it requires remark- able shrewdness and intelligence to do so. Only those experienced in the details of the whole subject can judge rightly of them : just as it needs a skilled musician to estimate a musical performance, and a scholar to decide literary questions, and so on. Such persons know how each of these performances are produced ; what combinations are suitable ; what each detail implies : while the inexperienced, knowing none of these things, will be unable to select, from the whole, the fairer and most excellent parts. We may weU be satisfied if they reach the simple knowledge that the whole result is good, or that it is bad. Exactly thus it is with painting. One need not be a painter, to know of a first-rate picture that it is well painted. To know that it is really first-rate, and wherein its superiority lies, one needs to comprehend the art, or, at any rate, to have had some experience in it. Therefore neither the painter's work, nor the musician's, nor the scholar's, can be rightly estimated without some study of tjjeir respective scieiioes ; aft4 Qoi-res- 588 The Moral Philosophy of Aristotle. [Bk. X. 10. pondingly, the statesman's business — which is the Law — cannot be estimated without study of political science. In the first place then, we repeat, it is not possible to compare laws and select the best, without experience in politics. Secondly — if we allow the possibility of correct selection and compilation of laws by one unversed in politics — even this will not suffice to make a man a statesman and legislator — any more than a compilation and perusal of medical works will make men physicians. There are such men, no doubt, who pretend to write prescriptions and boast of the recovery of their patients, and prate about proper treatment and specific qualities of each complaint : but they are not phy- sicians for all that : they are without the necessary experience and familiarity with disease. Of course, book-learning- and such abstract processes, do improve those who have aheady some experience — but they no way enable the inexperienced to practise the art of healing. So it is in matters of Law and Government. To compile laws and investigate different forms of government is indeed a most profitable work for those who have experience enough to contemplate each point, and take a proper purview of faults, merits, and possible adaptations of those governments. Such men improve thereby their own political judgment. Bui men who, with no such experience and practice, investigate other forms of government, waste their energy entirely as far as their ovtTi legislative faculty is concerned. Only by mere luck will they ever judge rightly of what they see : though it may be that by picking up some stray political laiowledge, they may become somewhat shi'ewder politicians. The conclusion is, that neither the Sophists nor our public men have developed, as a rule, any power of teaching statecraft and legislation. (^) INTEODUCTION TO THE POLITICS. Inasmuch, therefore, as previous •writers have left the subject of legislation unexplored, it is better surely that s^bject^ ^ "'"^ we should ourselves investigate it more thoroughly, and, in a word, the whole subject of Statesman- ship, so that our survey of Social Philosophy may be brought to a due completion. In the first place, then, let us endeavour to follow out any true explanations that have been given bv previous But a certain num- ,% , . • i i i /. i ■ , ber of useful ma- philosophers ot spccial branches oi our subject, teriais has been Then, from the Consideration of the Forms of may ° throw "light Government thus brought together, let us exa- upon the decHne or mine into the causes which preserve or ruin growth of states. gtates, and the conditions favourable or the re- verse to each particular constitution, and the circumstances through which some States are successfully administered and others are in decay. When these questions have been scientifically explained, we The real problem, ^^^3,11 perhaps more clearly recognize what kind however, is: 'what of Constitution is the perfect one, what is the f:l''SS ^^«* "^^^^ '-"^ ^bi°^ ^""^^ sli°"ld be organized ef society ?' wjd wUat laws wA customs it should adopt, Bk. X. 10.] Translation. 589 Let us then begin tlie Study of Politics from its simplest conception. , Since, as we have already proved, it ^s^ the natural duty of any Teacher of Virtue to deal thoroughly with these subjects also : and since former thinkers have neglected the investigation and exposition of Law and Statecraft, we had hetter turn our attention thereto, and so bring to a, close, and complete in every essential particular, the philosophic design which we set before us — that, namely, of expounding fully human feelings and conduct in aU their bearings. Firstly, therefore, let us go through, point by point, any wise sayings of our predecessors on .the subject : secondly, let us compare the different forms of Government, and consider by their examples tl;e causes of decay and of prosperity in States, and also, what tends to establish, and what to destroy, each form of Government : what, for instance, is the special strength of Monarchy, and what of Democracy, and the rest : and what, again, is their special danger. Further, let us consider from what causes some States are weU administered, and some the reverse. For by duly surveying all these things, we shall best recognize what Form of Govern- ment is best, and what ordinances, laws, and manners will most profit the citizen under each form of Government. Here therefore let us commence our treatise on Politics. THE END. LIST OF WORKS ADMIEALTT PUBLICATIONS ; Issued by direction of the Lords GommisBioners of the Admiralty: — A MANUAL OP SCIENTIFIC ENQUIRY, for the Use of Travellers. Fourth Edition. Edited by RoBEBi Main, M.A. Woodcnts. Post Sto. 3s. 6d. GREENWICH ASTRONOMICAL OBSERVATIONS, 1841 to 1847, SBd 1847 to 1871. Royal 4fo. 20s. each. GREENWICH OBSERVATIONS. 1848 to 1855. 20s, f ach. MAGNBTICAL AND METEOROLOGICAL OBSERVATIONS, 1844 to 1847. Royal 4to. 20s. each. APPENDICES TO OBSERVATIONS. 1837. Logarithms of Sines and Cosines in Time. 3s. 1842. Catalogue of 1439 Stars, from Observations made in 1838 1841. 4s. 1P45. Longitude of Valentia (Chronometrical). 3s. 1847. Description of Altazimuth. 3s. Twelve Years' Catalogue of Stars, firom Observations made in 1836 to 1847. 4». Description of Photographic Apparatus. 2ff. 1851. Maskelyne's Ledger of Stars. 3s. 1852. I. Description of Che Transit Circle. 3s. ItSS. Refraction Tables. Ss. 1854, Description of the Zenith Tube. 3s. Six Years' Catalogue of Stars, from Observations. 184S to 1833, 4s. Flanof Ground Buildings. 3>. Longitude of Valentia (Galvanic). 2s. 1864, Moon's Semid. from Occultations. 2s. Planetary Observations, 1881 to 1835. 2s. 18G8. Corrections of Elements of Jupiter and Saturn, Ss. Second Seven Years' Catalogue of 2760 Stars for 1861 to 1867. 4s. Description of the Great Equatorial, 3a. 1856. Descriptive Chronograph, 3*. 1860. Reduction of Deep Thermometer Observations. 2s, 1871. History and Description of Water Telescope. 3s. 1873. Regulations of the Royal Observatory, Ss. Cape of Good Hope Observations (Star Ledgers} : 18S6 to 1863. 2s, ■■ ■ : 1856. 5s. ■■ Astronomical Results. 1857tol858. 5s. Cape Catalogue of 1159 Stars, reduced to the Epoch 1860. 3s. Cape of Good Hope Astronamical Results. ]869tol860. Ss, 1871 to 1873. 5s. — 1874. 6s. Report on Teneriffe Astronomical Experiment 1836. 6s, Paramatta Catalogue of 7385 Stars. 1822 to 1826. 4s. ASTRONOAIICAI. RESULTS. 1847 to 1876. 4to, 8s. each. MAGNETICAL AND METEOROLOGICAL RESULTS. 1848 to 1S75. 4ro, 3s. each. REDUCTION OF THE OBSERVATIONS OP PLANETS. 1760 to 1830. Royal 4to, 20s ench. ' ' ^ — — LUNAR. OBSERVATJIONS. 1750 to 1880, 2 Vols. Royal 4to, 20s, each. lasltnlSSl. 4to, 10s. each. BBKNOULLI'S SEXCENTEN4.RV TABLE, 1779. 4to, 5s. BESSEL'S AUXILIARY TABLES FOR HIS METHOD OE CLEAB- ING LUNAR DISTANCES' 8vo. 2s. ENCKE'S BERLINER JAHRBUCH, for 830. CeriiB, 1828. 8vo. 9s. HANSEN'S TABLES DK LA l.UNE, 4to. 20«, ' LAX'S TABLES FOR FINDING THE LATITUDE AND LONGI- TUDE. 1821 Ivo 10s LUNAR OBSERVATIONS at GREENWICH. 1783 to 1819. Compared with the Tables, 1821 4to, 7s, Bd. MACLEAR ON LACAILLE'S ARC OF MERIDIAN. 2 Vols. SOs.eaeh. PUBLISHED BY MK. MURRA^. Admiraltit Publications — continued. MAYER'S DISTANCES of the MOON'S CENTBE from the PLANETS. 1822, 39.; 1823, 4s. 6i2. 1824 to 1835. Sro. Is.each TABULjB MOTUUM SOLIS ET LUN^. 1770. B». ASTRONOMICAL OBSEKVATIONS MADE AT GOT- TINGEN, from 1766 to 1761. 1826. Folio. 7f . 6*. NAUTICAL ALMANACS, flrom 1767 to 1877, 80». 2s. 6d. each. SELECTIONS FBOM, ap to 1812. 8to. it. 1834.S4. 6s. 2s. each. SUPPLEMENTS, 1828 to 1833, 1837 and 1838. TABLE requisite to be used with the N.A. 1781. Sto. 5s. SABINE'S PENDULUM EXPERIMENTS to Dkteemihs tm Fiqdes OF THE EABTH. 1825. 4tO. 40s. SHEPHERD'S TABLES for Cosbeotisq LmiAB Dibtahoeb. 1772. RoTal4to. 21s. TABLES, GENERAL, of the MOON'S DISTANCE from the SUN, and 10 STARS. 1767. Folio. 6s. Bd. TAYLOR'S SEXAGESIMAL TABLE. 1780. 4to. 15». TABLES OF LOGARITHMS. 4to. 60s. TIABK'S ASTBONOMICAL OBSBBVATIONS for the Losoituds OfMAOEIBA. 1822. 4to. 6s. CHEONOMETRICAL OBSERVATIONS for Dufkbisoeb of LoNOiTODE hetween Dovbb, Pobtsuouth, an Falmouth. 1823. 4to. 5>. TENUS and JUPITEB: Obbkevationb of, compared with the Tablsb. Lmidm, 1822. 4to. 2s. ■WALES AND BAYLY'S ASTRONOMICAL OBSERVATIONS. 1777. 4to. 21s. REDUCTION OP ASTBONOMICAL OBSERVATIONS HADE i» the Bouthebk Hehisphkee. 1784—1771. 1788. 4to. 10s. 6d. BAEBATJLD (Mrs.). Hymns in Prose for Children. With Illastrations. Crown 8vo. BARCLAY (JOSEPH, LL.D.); Selected Extracts from the Tal- mud, chiefly illustratiog the Teaching of the Bible. With an Intro- duction. lUuatrations. 8vo. 14s. BAEKLEY (H. C). Five Years among the Bulgarians and Turks between the Danube and the Black Sea. Post 8vo. 10s. 6d. Bulgaria Before the War ; during a Seven Years' Experience of European Turkey and its Inhabitants. Post 8vo. lOs. ed. My Boyhood : a True Story. A Book for School- boys and others. With Illustrations. Post 8to. 6s. BAKEOW (Sir John). Autobiographical Memoir, from Early Life to Advanced Age. Portrait. 8to. 168. (John) Life, Exploits, and Voyages of Sir Francis Drake. PostSvo. 2s. BAREY (Sir Charles). Life and Works. By Canoh Barrt. With Portrait and IliustratioOB. Medium 8to. 16s. BATES (H. W.) Eecords of a Naturalist on the Eiver Amazon during eleven years of Adventure and TraTOl. Illustrations. Post 8yo. 7«. ed. BAX (Capt. E.!?.). EussianTartary, Eastern Siberia, China, Japan, and Formosa. A Narrative of a Cruito in the Eastern Seas. With Map and Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 12s. BELCHER (Ladt). Account of the Mutineers of the 'Bounty, and their Descendants ; with tb^iir aatllemenls in Pitcaim and Norfolk Islands. With lUuslra-.ions. PostSvo, 12s. BELL (Sir Cbas.). ramlliar Letters. Portrait. Post 8vo. 12s. * ' B 2 LIST OF WORKS BELL (DoTNH C). Notioea of the Historic Persons buried in the Chapel of St. ?eter ad Yincula, in the Toirer of London, with an account of the diacoTer7 of the supposed remains of Queen Anne Boleyn. With ZUaBtrations. Grown 87c. 145. BELT (Thos.). The Naturalist in Kicaragua. A Residence at the Gold Mines of Cbontales, with Journeys in the Savannahs and Forests and Observations on Animals and Flaute. Illustrations. Post 8to, 12a. BERTRAM (Jas. G.). Harvest of the Sea : an Account of British Food Fishes, including sketches of Fisheries and Fisher Folk, With 60 Illustrations. 8to. 9b. BIBLE COMMENTARY. The Old Testament. Explahatort and Cbitjoal. With a Reviston of the Teanslation. By BISHOPS and CLERGY of the ANGLICAN CHURCH. Edited by F. 0. Cook, M.A., Canon of Exeter. 6 Vols, Medium 8to. 61. 15$. /Gbhbbis. Vol T lExoDHB. ''"«• I Ndmbebs. Idbdtebonouy Vols. II. and III. 36<. 'Joshua, Judges, KtrrH, Sahubl, KlKGS, Ghbo- KIOLB8, EZBA, Neheuiah, ESTBBB. Medium 8to. Job. FSALHS. PaorBBBS. ECGIiESIASTEB. (Song of Solouon. Vol. V. ( Isaiah. 20s. I Jbbbuiah. {EZEEIBL. Daniel. MiNOB Fbophbts. Ths New Testameht. 4 Vols. Medium 8to. ^ROUAHS, COEISTHIiNS, Vol. IV. I 249. ' Vol. VI. 25s. Vol. II. I St. Johh. Acts. Vol. IV. /-iNTBODnOTIOK. | GALATIAHS, PHIUPPIiUS, Vol. I. J St. Matthew. _ , ..- J Ephbsiahs, Colcssians, 18s. 1st. Maek. *"• "'• i Thbssalokiahs, Phile- ISt. Luke. | mis, Pastokal Epistles, \^ Hebrews. f St. James, St. John, St. •I Peteb, St.Jude, Eevb- ( lation. The Student's. Edition. Abridged and Edited by John M. Fulleb, M.A., Vicar of B«ley. (To be completed in 6 Volumes.) Vol. I. Crown 8to. 7«. 6d. BIGG- WITHER (T. P.). Pioneering in South Brazil; three years of forest and prairie life in the province of Parana. Map and Illustrations. 2 vols. Grown 8vo. 24>. BIRCH (Samuel). A History of Ancient Pottery and Porcelain : Egyptian, Assyrian, Greek, Koman, and Etruscan. With Coloured Plates and 200 Illustrations. Medium 8vo. 42s. BIRD (Isabella). The Hawaiian Archipelago; or Sir Months among the Palm Groves, Coral Reefs, and Volranoes of the Sandwich Islands. With IllustrationGT. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. BISSET (General Sir John). Sport and War in South Africa from li^l to 1867, with a Narrative of the Duke of Edinburgh's Visit. With Map and Illustrations Crown 8vo. 14s BLACKSTONE'S COMMENTARIES; adapted to the Present state of the Law. By R. Malcolm Keee, LL.D. RevUed EdUum incorporating all the Recent Changes in the Law. 4 vols. Svo. 60s.* BLUNT (BJet. J. J.). Undesigned Coincidences in the Writings of the Old and NewTeBtaments,an Argument of their Veracity. Post Svo. 6s. Histoiy of the Church in the First Three Centuries Po^ Svo. 6>. Parish Priest; His Duties, Acquirements and Obliffa- tlons, Post Svo. 6s. ° University Sermons. Post 8yo. 6«. PUBLISHED BY MR. MURRAY. B LITNT (Ladt Anhb). The Bedouins of the Euphrates Valley With a lu'l account of ihe Ardbii and their Horses. By ■Wilfbid Blust. w ith Map and Illustrations, 2 vols. Crown 8to. BOSWELL'S Life of Samuel Johnson, LL.D. Including the Tour to the Hebrides. Edited by Mr. Cbokeb. Seventh Milion, Portraits, 1 vol. Medium 8vo, 12s, BRACE (C. L,). Manual of Ethnology; or the Eaces of the Old World. Post 8vo. 6s, BOOK OF COMMON PEATEE. Illustrated with Coloured Borders, Initial Letters, and Woodcuts. Svo. 18s. BOEEOW (Georqe). Bible in Spain; or the Journeys, AdTentures, and Imprisonments of an Englishman in an Attempt to circulate the Scriptures In the Peninsula. Post Svo, bs, Gypsies of Spain ; their Manners, Customs, Ee- ligion, and Language. With Portrait. Post Svo. 5«. -The Gypsy — and the Priest. Lavengro ; The Scholar - Post Svo. 58. Eomany Eye — a Sequel to " Lavengro." Post 8to. Ss. Wild Wales : its People, Language, and Scenery. Post Svo. 5», Eomano Lavo-Lil; Word- Book of the Eomany, or English Gypsy Language; with Specimens of their Poetry, and an account of certain Gypsyries. Post Svo. 10s, 6d. BEAT (Mks.). Life of Thomas Stothard, E.A. and 60 Woodcuts. 4to. 21s. BEITISH ASSOCIATIOlf EEPOETS, York and Oxford, 1831-32, ia», 6d. Cambridge, 1833, 12s. Edinburgh, 1834, 16s. Dublin, ISSS, 13s. 6d, , Bristol, 1836, 12s. Liverpool, 1837, 16s. erf. Newcastle, 1S3S, 16s. Birmingham, 1839, 13s. 6il. Glasgow, 1840, 16s. Plymouth, 1841, 13s. 6dl, Manchester, 1842, 10s. 6. 6<2. Life and Poetical Works. Popular Edition. Portraits. 2to1s, Boyal 8vo. ISs. Poetical Works. Library Edition. Portrait. 6 Vole. 8vo. iSs. Poetical Works. Cabinet Edition. Plates. lOVols. 12mo. 30s. Poetical Works. Pocket Ed. 8 Vols. 16mo. In a ease. 21s. Poetical Works. Popular Edition. Plates. Boyal 8vo. ts. M. Poetical Works. Pearl Edition. CroTrn 8to. 2«. 6d. Childe Harold. With 80 Engrarings. Crown 8to. \2s. Childe Harold. 16mo. 2«. €<{. CMiLDE Harold. Vignettes. 16mo. 1«. __. Childe Harold. Portrait. 16mo, 6d. Tales and Poems. 16mo. 2«. 6d. Miscellaneous. 2 Vols. 16mo. 5s. Dramas and Plays. 2 Vols. ]6mo. 5s. Don Jcan and Bepfo. 2 Vols. 16mo. as. Beauties. Poetry and Prose. Portrait. Fcap. 8to. 38.6(2. CALLCOTT (Ladt). Little Arthur's History of England. New Edition, troughtdoum to iSli. With Woodcuts. Fcap. Bro. Is. Gd. CAMPBELL (Lord). Lord Chancellors and Keepers of the Great Seal of England. From the Earliest Times to the Death of Lord Eldon in 1638. 10 Vols. Crown 8vo. 6s. each. Chief Justices of England. From the Norman Conquest to the Death of LordTenterden. 4 Vols. Crown 8vo. 6s. each. Lord Bacon. Fcap. 8vo. 2». id. PUBLISHED BY MR. MURRAY. "^'^^K/tlXU^S ?„st»^^*^-' ^"-^ Short CARTWBIGHT (W C). The Jesuits: their Constitution and Teaching. An Historical Sketch. 8vo. 9s. CAVALCASELLE'S WOEKS. [See Cbowe.] CESNOLA (Geh.). Cyprus ; its Ancient Cities, Tombs, and Tem- ples. Researches and Excavations during Ten Yfars' Ki-sidence io that Island. With Map and 40u lUustraiions. Medium 8vo. 5U». CHILD (Chaplih). Benedicite ; or. Song of the Three Children ; being Illustrations of the Power, Beneficence, and Design manifested oy the Creator in his works. Post 8vo. 6s. CHISHOLM (Mrs.). Perils of the Polar Seas ; True Stories of Arctic Discovery and AdTenlnre. Illustrations. Post 8vo. 6<. OHTJKTON (Akohdeacon). Poetical Bemains, Translations and Imitations. Portrait. Post 8vo. 7s. ed. CLASSIC PBEACHEES OP THE ENGLISH CHURCH. St. James's Lectures, 1877. Donbe, by Canon Lightfoot ; BiBEOW, by Prof. Wace; Sooth, by the Dean of Durham; Betbbidoe, by Eev. W. K. Clark; Wilson, by Canon Parrar; Butleb, by the Dean of Norwith. With an Intrtduction by J. B. Kemne. M.A.. Kector. Post 8vo. 75. 6d. i- f i — — 1678, BnLL, by Eev. \Y. 'Warburtou ; Homlet, by the Bishop of Ely; Tailob, by Canon Barry; Sandebsoh, by the Bishop of Deiry; Tillotsok, by Rev. W. G. Humpbry, tS.U.; Andbbiteb, bv Rev. H. J. North. Post 8vo. 7s. M. OLIVE'S (Lobd) Life. By Ekv, 6. E. Gleio. Post 8to. 3«. 6i. CLODB (C. M.). Military Forces of the Crown ; their Administra- tion and Government. 2 Vols. Svo. 21s. each. Administration of Justice under Military and Martial Law, as applicable to the Army, Navy, Maiine, and Auxiliaiy Forces. 8vo. Vis. COLERIDGE'S (SAMtiBL Tayloe) Table-Talk. Portrait. 12mo. 3s.6d. COLONIAL LIBEART. [See Home and Colonial Library.] COMPANIONS FOE THE DEVOUT LIFE. A Series of Lec- tures on well-knoTvn Devotional Works. Crown bvo. 6s. DexuitationeChbisti. CanonFarrar. PBNPfiBS OS BLAI9B PASCAL. Dean Church. S. Fban^oib de Sales. Dean Goulburn. Baxtrb'b Saints' Best. Archbishop of Dublin. S.AuonsTiNE's Confessions. 6ishr>p of Deny. Jbbbitt Taylor's Holt Living and TnEOLOoiA Gebuanica. Canon Ashwell. F£velon's CEovres Spieitdelles. Rev. T.T. Carter. Andbewes' Devotions. Bishop of Ely. CilalsTiAN Yeab. Canon Barry. PABADtbE Lust. Rev. a. H. Bicker- stetta. Pilgeim's Pbogrkbs. Dean Howsou. Dying. Rev. Dr. Humphry. ; Prayee Book. Deau Burgon. COOK (Canon). Sermons Preached at Lincoln's Inn. 8to. COOKE (E. W.). Leaves from my Sketeh-Book. Being a selec- tion from sketchf 8 made during many tonrB. With DeECriptive Text, eo Flatea. 8 vols. Small folio. 31>. 6d. each. COOKERY (ModerhDomebtio). Pounded on Principles of Economy and Practical Knowledge. By a Lady. Woodcuts. Fcap. 8vo. 5a. COOPER (T. T.). Travels of a Pioneer of Commerce on an Overlnnd Journey from China towards India. Illustrations. 8vo. 16«. CRAB BE (Rev. Geoege). Life and Poetical Works. With Illus- trations. Royal 8vo. Is. CRAWFORD & BALCARRES (Earl of). Etruscan InecriptionB. Analyzed, Translated, and Commented upon. 8to. 12a. CRIPPS (Wilfred). Old English Plate : Ecclesiastical, Decorative, and Domestic, its mabers and marks. Illustrations. Medium 8vo. 2l£, CEOKER (J. W.). Progressive Geography for Children. 18mo. Is.Gd, Stories for Children, Selected from the History of England. Woodcuts. 16mo. 2«. 6(2. Boswell's Life of Johnson. Including the Tonr to the Hehrides. Seventh Edition. Portraits. 8vo. 125. Early Period of the French Revolution. 8vo. 15s. Historical Essay on the Guillotine. Fcap. 8vo. la. CROWE AND CAVALCASELLE. Lives of the Eariy Flemish Painters. Woodcuts. Post 8vo, 10«. 6d. ; or Large Paper, 8vo, 15s. History of Painting in North Italy, from 14th to 16th Century. Derived from Researches in that Country. With 11. lustrations. 2 VoIh. 8vo. 42«. Life and Times of Titian, with gome Acconnt of his Family, chiefiy from new and unpublibhed records. With Portrait and Illustrations. 2 vols. 870. 42«. GUMMING (R. Gobdon). Five Tears of a Hunter's Life in the Far Interior of South Africa. Woodcuts. Post 8to. 6a. CUNTNGHAME (Sir Aktbue). Travels in the Eastern Cancasus, on the Caspian and Blitck Seas, in Daghestan and the Frontiers of Persia and Turkey. With Map and Illustrations. 8vo. 18«. CUETIUS' (Professor) Student's Greek Grammar, for the Upper Forms. Edited hy De. Wm. Smith. Post 8to. 6«. Elucidations of the above Grammar. Translated by Evelyn Abbot. Post 8vo. 7s. 6d. Smaller Greek Grammar for the Middle and Lower Forms. Abridged from the larger work. 12mo. Ss. Qd. Accidence of the Greek Language. Extracted from the above work. 12mo. 2a. 6d. . Principles of Greek Etymology. Translated by A. S. WiLEiNB, M.A., and E. B. England, B.A. 2 vols. 8to. 16a. each. The Greek Verb, its Structure and Development. Translated into English, with the Author's sanction, by A. S. \Vilkihs, M.A.. and E. B. Lnqland, M.A. 8vo. CURZON (Hon. Robert). Visits to the Monasteries of the Levant. lUnstrations. Post 8vo. 7a. 6d. OUST (Geseeai). Warriors of the 17th Century— The Thirty Tears' War. 2 Vols. 16a. Civil Wars of France and England. 2 Vols. 16a. Commanders of Fleets and Armies. 2 Vols. ]8a. Annals of the Wars — 18th & 19th Century, 1700—1815. With Maps. 9 Vi.Is. Post 8to. 6s. each. DAVT (SiK HnMPHRT). Consolations in Travel; or. Last Days of a Fbilosoptaer, Woodcuts. Fcap, 8to. 38. Gd. Salmonia; or. Days of Ply FisMng. Woodcuts. Fcap. 8to. 3s. 6d. DAEWIN (Charles) WOEKS :— Journal op a Natcbalist btjeihg a Voyage kouhd the WoBLD. Crown 8vo. 9«. Origin of Species by Means of Natueal Selection; or, the Preservation of Favoured Kaces in the Struggle for Life. Woodcuts. Crown Svo. 7i. 6d. Variation of Animals and Plants under Domestication. Woodcuts. 2 Vols. Crown Svo, 18s. Descent op Man, and' Selection in Delation to Sex. Woodcuts. Crown Svo. 9s. Expressions op the Emotions in Man and Animals. With Illustrations. Grown Svo. l'2s. Various Contrivances by ■which Orchids are Tertilized BY Im SECTS. Woodcuts. Crown 8vo. 9s. Movements and Habits of Climbikg Plants. Woodcuts, Crown Svo. 6s. Insectivorous Plants. Woodcuts. Crown Svo. 14«. Effects op Cross and Self-Peetilization in the Vegetable Kingdom. Crown Svo. 12s. Different Forms of Flowers on Plants of the same Species. Crown Svo. 10s. €d. Pacts and Argument foe Daewin. By Peitz Mullee. Translated by W. S. Dallas. Woodcuts. Post Svo. 6s. DE COSSON (B. A.). The Cradle of the Blue Nile; a Journey through Ahyssinia and Soudan, and a residence at the Court of King John of Ethiopia. Map and llluBtrations. 2 vols. Post Svo. 21s. DENNIS (Geoeqe). The Cities and Cemeteries of Etruria. A new Edition, revised, recording all the latest Discoveries. With 20 Plans and 200 Illustrations. 2 vols. Medium Svo. 42s. DENT (Emma). Annals of Winchcombe and Sudeley. With 120 Fortiaits, Plates and Woodcuts. 4to. 42s. DEEBT (Earl op). Iliad of Homer rendered into English Blank Verse. 10(A Sditim. With Portrait. 2 Vols. Post Svo. 10s. DEEEY (Bishop op). Witness of the Psalms to Christ and Chris- tianity. The Bampton Lectures for 1876. ifes and enlarged Hditim. Svo. Ms. DEUTSCH (Emanuel). Talmud, Islam, The Targums and other Literary Remains, Svo. 12s. DILKE (Sie C. W.). Papers of a Critic. Selected from the Writings of the late ChjiB. Wentwobth Dilke. With a Biographi- es.! Sketch. 2 Vols. Svo. 24s. DOG-BKEAKING, with Odds and Ends for those who love the Dog and Gun. By Gek. Hbtchimbok. With 40 Illustrations, down Svo. 7s. 6d. 10 LIST OF WORKS DOMESTIC MODERN' COOKERY. Founded on Principles of Economy and Fractb»l Knowledge, and adapted for Private FamilleB. Woodcuta. Fcap. 8to. Bt. DOUGLAS'S (Sib Howard) Life and Adventures. Portrait. 8vo. 15*. Tlieory and Practice of Gunnery. Plates. Svo. 21s. Construction of Bridges and the Passage of Rivers in Military Operations. Plates. 8to. 2U. (Wu.) Horse-Shoeing; As ic Is, and As it Shonld be. Illustrations. Post 8to. 79. 6d. DRAKE'S (Sib Fbamois) Life, Voyages, and Exploits, by Sea and Land. By John Basbow. Post 8to. is. DRINKWATER (Johh). History of the Siege of Gibraltar, 1779-1783. With a Oescriptioc and Account of that Garrison from the Earliest Periods. Post Svo. 2<. DTJCANGE'S Mbdi^ital Latih-Eholish Dictionary. Translated and Edited by fiev. £. A. Dayuan and J. H. tlESSSLS, Small 4to. {In preparation^ DIT CHAILLU (Paul B.). Equaiobial Africa, with Acconnts of the Gorilla, the Nest-building Ape, Chimpanzee, Crocodile, &c. Illustratlans. Svo. 21<. Journey to Ashango Land; and Farther Pene- tration into Equatorial Africa, lllustratioas. Svo. 2U. DUFPBRIN (LoBD). Letters from High Latitudes; a Yacht Voyage to Iceland, Jan Mayen, and Spitzbergen. Woodcuts. Post Svo. la.M. DUNCAN (Major). History of the Eojal Artillery. Com- piled from the Original Records. With Portraits. 2 Vols. Svo. SOs. Englieh in Spain; or, The Story of the War of Suc- cession, 1834 aud 1840. Compiled from the Reports of the Britiah Commissioners With Illustrations. Svo. 16s. EASTLAEE (Sib Charles). Contributions to the Literature of the Fine Arts. With Memoir of the Author, and Selections from his Correspondence. By Lauy Eaiitt.akb. 2 Vols. 6vo. 24s. EDWARDS (W. H.). Voyage np the River Amazon, including a Visit toTara. Post Svo. 2». EIGHT M02iITHS AT ROME/ during the Vatican Council, with a Daily Account of the Procef.dings. By Fouponio Lbto. Trans- lated Irqm the Original. Svo. 12s. BLDON'S (Lobd) Public and Private Life, with Selections from his Correspondence and Diaries. By Hobaob Twisb. Portrait. 2 Vols. Post Svo. 21s. ELGIK (Lobd). Letters and Journals. Edited by Thxsdobe Walkosd. With Preface by Dean SUnley. Svo. 14s. ELLESMERB (Lord). Two Sieges of Vienna by the Turks. Translated from the German. Post Svo. 2s. ELLIS (W.). Madagaccar Eevieited. Setting forth the Perse- cutions and Heroic Sufferings of the Native Christiaus. Illustrations. 8va. 16s, Memoir. By His Sou. With his Character and Work. By Rev. Hemev Allon, D.D. Portrait. Svo. 10s. 6d. (EoBissoH) Poems and Fragments of Catullus. 16mo. 5s. ELPHINSTONE (Hoh. MonHTSTOABi). History of India— the Hindoo and Mahomedan Periods. Edited by Peofessoe Cowbll. Map. Svo, 18s. PUBLISHED BY MR, MURIPAY. U ELPHINSTONB (H. W.) Pattema for Turning; Comprising Elliptical and other Figures cut on the Lathe without the use of any Ornamental Chuck. With 70 Illustrations. Small 4to. 16». ELTON (Capt.) and H. B. COTTEEILL. Adventures and DiscoTeriea Among the Lakes and Monntains of Eastern and Central Africa. With Map and illustrations. 870. ENGLAND. See Calioott, Ceoker, Hdmk, Makkham, Smith, and Stambopb. ESSAYS ON CATHEDRALS. With an Introduction, By Dean Howson. 870. 125. ELZE (Karl). Life of Lord Byron. With a Critical Essay on his Place in Literature. Translated from the German. Witji Portrait. 8vo. 16». FEEGUSSON (James). History of Architecture in all Countries from the Earliest Times. With 1,600 Illustrations. 4 Vols. Medium Svo. Vol. I. & IL Ancient and Mediseval. 6Ss. Vol. in. Indian & Eastern. 42«. Vol. I"V . Modem. Sls.6d. Eude Stone Monuments in all Countries; their Age and Uses. With 230 Illustrations. Medium Svo. 24i, Holy Sepulchre and the Temple at Jerasalem. Woodcuts. 8vo. 78. 6d. Temples of the Jews and other buildings in the Huram Area at Jerusalem. With lUustrationa. 4to. 42a. FLEMING (Profesbor). Student's Manual of Moral Philosophy. With Quotations and Beferences. Post Svo. 7s. Qd. FLOWER GARDEN. By Rev. Thos. James. Fcap. Svo. 1«. FORBES (Capt. C. J. F. S.J British Burma and its People; sketches of Native Manners, Customs, and Religion. Gr. Svo. ICb. Gd. FORD (Richard). Gatherings from Spain. Post Svo. Zs. 6d. FORSYTH (Wiliiam). Hortensius; an Historical Essay on the Office and Duties of an Advocate. Illustrations. 8to. 129. Novels and Novelists of the 18th Century, in Illustrationof the Manners and Moials of the Age. PostSvo. 10a. ed. FORTUNE (Robert). Narrative of Two Visits to the Tea Countries of China, 1843-52. Woodcuts. 2 Vols. Post Svo. 18s. FOESTEE (John). The Early Life of Jonathan Swift. 1667-1711. With Portrait Svo. 15>. FOSS (Edwaed). Biographia Juridica, or Biographical Dictionary of tke Judges of England, from the Conquest to the Present Time, 1066-1870. Medium 8vo. 2U. FRANCE (History os). See Makkham — Smith — Students'. FEBNCH IN ALGIERS; The Soldier of the Foreign Legion— and the Prisoners of Abd-el-Eadir. Translated bj Ladv Dc;f Gosdoh. Post Svo. 2s. FEEEB (Sir Bartle). Indian Missions. Small Svo. 2s. 6d. Eastern Africa as a field for Missionary Labour. With Map. CrovnSvo. ba. ■■ — Bengal Famine. How it will be Met and How to Prevent Future Famines in India. With Maps. Crown Svo. 55. 12 LIST OP WORKS GALTON (F.). Art of Travel ; or. Hints on the SUftB and Con- trivances availfible in Wild Countries. Woodcuts. Post 8vo. 7«. 6d. GEOGRAPHY. See Choker — Smith— Students'. GEOGRAPHICAL, SOCIETY'S JOURNAL. {Published Yearly.) GEORGE (Bbhbst). The Mosel ; a Series of Twenty Etchings, with Descriptive Letterpress. Imperial 4to. 42^. Loire and South of France; a Series of Twenty Etchings, with Descripdre Text. Folio. 428. GERMANY (History op). See Markham. GIBBON (Edward). History of the Decline and Pall of the Roman Empire. Edited by MituAN, Gdizot, and Dr. Wm. Smith. Maps. 8 Yols. 8vo. 60s. The Student's Edition; an Epitome of the above work, incorporating the Researches of Recent Commentators. By Dr. Wh. Smith. Woodcuts. Post 8vo. 7s. 6d. GIPPARD (Edward). Deeds of Naval Daring ; or. Anecdotes of the British Navy. Fcap. 8vo. 3s. 6d. GILL (Mrs.). Six Months in Ascension. An TTnscientific Ac- count of a Scientific Expedition. Map. Crown 8vo. 9s. GLADSTONE (W. E.). Rome and the Newest Pashion's in Religion. Three Tracts. 8vo. la. Sd. Essays. I. Personal and Literary. II. Ecclesi- astical and Theological. III. European and Historical. Small 8vo. GLEIG (G. R.). Campaigns of the British Army at Washington and New Orleans. Post Svo. 2s. Story of the Battle of Waterloo. Post Svo. Zs. 6d. Narrative of Sale's Brigade in Affghanistan. Post Svo. 2«. Life of Lord Clive. Post Svo. 3«. 6d. Sir Thomas Munro. Post Svo. Zs. 6d. GLYNNE (Sir Stepheh B.). Notes on the Churches of Kent. With Preface by W. H. Gladstone, M.P. Illustrations. Svo. 12s. GOLDSMITH'S (Oliver) Works. Edited with Notes by Peteb Cdnhhioeah. Vignettes. 4 Vols. 8vo. 30s. GORDON (Sib Alez.). Sketches of German Life, and Scenes from the War of Liberation. Post Svo. 3s.6ii. (Ladt Ddff) Amber- Witch: A Trial for Witch- craft. Post Svo. 2s. Prench in Algiers. 1. The Soldier of the Foreign Legion. 2. The Prisoners of Abd-el-Eadir. Post Svo. 2s. GRAMMARS. See Curtiub ; Hall : Knro Edward ; Matthi.« ; Maetzmhb; Smith. GREECE (History op). See Grote— Smith— Students'. GROTE'S (Gboroe) WORKS :— History op Greece. From the Earliest Times to the close of the generation contemporary with the death of Alexander the Great. Library Edition. Portrait, Maps, and Plans. 10 Vols. Svo. 120s. Cabinet Edition. Portrait and Flans. 12 Vols. Post Svo. 6s. each. Plato, and other Companions of Socrates. 3 Vols. Svo. 45s. Minor Works. With Critical Remarks. By Alex. Bain. Portrait. Svo. 14s. Letters on Switzerland in 1847. 6s. Personal Lipe. Compiled from Family Docnments, Original Letters, Ac. By Mrs. Geotb. Portrait, Svo. 12s. PUBLISHED BY MR. MURRAY. 13 HALL'S (T. D;) School Manual of English Grammar. With Copious Exercises. 12mo. 3s. 6i. Primary English Grammar for Elementary Schools. Based on the above work. 16mo. Is, Child's First Latin Book, including a Systematic Treat- ment of the New Pronunciation, and a full Praxis of Nouns, Adje&> tives. and Fionouns. 16mo. Is. Sd, HALLAM'S (HuNBY) WORKS :— The Constiiutiosal Histortt of Enohhd, from the Acces- sion of Henry the Seventh to the Death of George the Second. Cabinet Edition, 3 Vols. PostSTO. 129. Student's Edition of the above work. Edited by Wm. SiuTB, D.C.Ii. Post 8to. 7s. 6d. History of Bhrope DURiiia the Middle Aoes. Library Sditim. S Vols. 8to. SOs. Caiinet Sdition 3 Vols. Post Svo. 129, Student's Edition of the above work. Edited by Wm. Smith, D.CL. Post Svo. 7a. 6d. LiTERABir History of Bhrope dhriko the 15th, 16th, and 17th Oehtdbiks. lAbrn/ry Editim. 3 Vols. Svo. 86s. Oaiinet Edition. 4 Vols. Post Svo. 16s. HALLAM'S (Arthur) Literary Bemains; in Verse and Prose. Portrait. Fcap. Svo. 3s. M. HAMILTON (Geh. Sib P. W.). History of the Grenadier Guards. From Original Documents in the Kolls' Records, War Otice, Regimental Records, Ac. With Illustrations. 3 Vols. Svo. eSs. HAET'S AKMT LIST. {Published Qaarterly amdAnnuaUy.) HAT (Sir J. H. DRnMMOnD). Western Barbary, its Wild Tribes and Savage Animals. Post Svo. 2s. HEAD'S (Sib Fbahois) WOEKS :— The Eoyal Enqineeb. lUustrations. Svo. 12«. Life of Sir John BnRqoYHB. Post Svo. Is. Bapid Jodbseys across the Pampas. Post Svo. 2s. Bubbles from the Bruhnen of Nassau. Illastrations. Post Svo. 7s. 6d. Stokers and Pokers; or, the London and North Western Hallway. Post Svo. 2s. HEBEE'S (Bishop) Journals in India. 2 Vols. Post Svo. 7s. Poetical Works. Portrait. Fcap. Svo. 3s. 6d. . — Hymns adapted to the Church Service. 18mo. Is. 6d. 14 LIST OF WORKS FOREIGN HANDBOOKS. HAND-BOOK— TRAVEL-TALK. English, French, German, and Italian. 18mo. 3a. 6d. ^ — HOLLAND AND BELGIITM. Map and Plans. Post'Svo. 6«. NORTH GEEMANT and THE RHINE,— The Black Forest, the Hartz. ThUringerwald, Sazon Switzerland, BUgen the Giant Mountains, Taunus, Odenvald, Elass, and X.oth- ringen. Map and Plans, Post 8vo, IO5. SOUTH GERMANY, — Wnrtembnrg, Bavaria, Austria, Styria, Salzburg, the Anstrian and Bavarian Alps, Tyrol, Hun- gary, and the Danube, from Ulm to the Black Sea. Map. Post 8vo. 10b, PAINTING. German, Flemish, and Dutch Schools. Illustrations. 2 Vols. Post 8vo. 24j. LIVES OF EARLY FLEMISH PAINTERS. By Cbowb and Cavalcabbllb. lUuBtrations. Post 8vo. 10a. 6(2. SWITZERLAND, Alps of Savoy, and Piedmont, Maps. Post 8to. 9a. FRANCE, Part I. Normandy, Brittany, the French Alps, the Loire, the Seine, the Garonne, and Pyrenees. PostSvo. 7t.ed. Part II. Central France, Auvergne, the Gevennes. Burgundy, the Rhone and Saone, Provence, Nimes, Aries, Marseilles, the French Alps, Alsace, Lorraine, Champagne, &c. ' Maps. Post 8vo. 7s. M. MEDITERRANEAN ISLANDS— Malta, Corsica, Sardinia, and Sicily. Maps. Fost 8vo. [7^ the Press ALGERIA AND TUNIS. Algiers, Constantine, Oran, the Atlas Range, Map. PostSvo. PARIS, and its Environs. Map. 16mo. 3s. 6d. SPAIN, Madrid, The Castiles, The Basque Provinces, Leon, The Asturias, Galicia, Estreniadura, Andalusia, Ronda, Granada Murcia, Talencia, Catalonia, Aragon, Navarre, The Balearic Islands,' lie.&e. Maps. PostSvo. 20<. PORTUGAL, LisBOH, Porto, Cintra, Mafra, &c. Map. Fost8vo. 12s. NORTH ITALY, Turin, Milan, Cremona, the Italian Lakes, Bergamo, Brescia, Verona, Mantua, Vicenza, Padua, Ferrara, Bologna, Raveiioa, Rimini, Piacenza, Genoa, the Riviera, Venice, Parma, Modena, a-nd. Romagna. Map. Post 8vo. 10b. > CENTRAL ITALY, Florence, Lucca, Tuscany, The Marches, Umbiia, and late Patrimony of St. Peter's. Map. Post 8vo. 10«. ROME AHD ITS Ekvirohs, Map. Post 8vo. 10». SOUTH ITALY, Naples, Pompeii, Herculaneum, and Vesuvius. Map. Post Svo. IDs. PAINTING. The ItaUan Schools. Ulustratjons. 2 Vols. Post 8vo. -:lIVES OP ITALIAN PAINTERS, Aon Cihabob to Bassaho. By Mrs. Jauesoh. Portraits. Post Svo. 128. NORWAY, Christiania, Bergen, Trondhjem. The Fjelds and Fjords. Map. Po»t Svo. 9». SWEDEN, Stockholm, Upsala, Gothenburg, the Shores of the Baltic, &c. Poet8vo. 6>>. DENMARK, Sleswig, H olstein, ] Copenhagen, Jut- land, Icelaud. Map. Post 8^0. 6j!. PUBLISHED BY MR. MURRJKy, 16 HAND-BOOK— RUSSIA, St. Petersburg, Moscow, Poland, and Finland. Maps. PostSvo. 18a. GREECE, the Ionian Islands, Continental Greece, Athens, the Feloponnesna, the Islands of the ^gean Sea, Albania, Thessalf , and Macedoaia. Maps. Post 8vo. 16s. TURKEY Ilir ASIA— Constantinople, the Bos- phorus, Dardanelles, Brousa, Plain of Troy, Crete, Cyprus, Smyrna, Ephesus, the Seven Churches, Coasts of the Black Sea, Armenia, Euphrates Valley, Route to India, &c. Maps. Post Svo. 155. EGYPT, including Descriptions of the Course of the 'Nile through Egypt and Nubia, Alexandria, Cairo, and Thebes, the Suez Canal, the Pyramids, the Peninsula of Sinai, the Oases, the Fyoom, &c. Map. Post 8vo. 165. HOLY LAND — Stria, Palestine, Peninsula of Sinai, Edom, Syrian Deserts, Petra, Damascus ; and Palmyra. Maps. Post 8to. 20s. %* Travelling Map of Palestine, la a case. 125. INDIA — Bombay and Madras. Map. 2 Vols. Post 8vo. 125. each. ENGLISH HAND-BOOKS. HAND-BOOK— ENGLAND AND WALES. An Alphabetical Hand-Book. Condensed into One Volume for the Use of Travellera. With a Map Post 8vo. 10s. ^ MODERN LONDON. Map. 16ino. 3s. 6d. ■ ENVIRONS OF LONDON within a, circuit of 20 miles. 2 Vols. Crown 8vo. 21s. EASTERN COUNTIES, Chelmsford, Harwich, Col- chester, Maldon, Cambridge, Ely, Newmarket, Buiy St. Edmunds, Ipswich, Woodbridge, Felixstowe, Lowestoft, Norwich, Yarmouth, Cromer, &c. Map and Plans. Post 8vo. 12s. CATHEDRALS of Oxford, Peterborough, Norwich, Ely, and Lincoln. With 90 Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 18s. KENT, Canterbury, Dover, Eamsgate, Sheerness, Bochester, Chatham, Woolwich. Map. Post 8to. 7«. 6d. ■ SUSSEX, Brighton, Chichester, Worthing, Hastings, Lewes, Arundel, &o. Map. Post 8vo. 6s. SURREY AND HANTS, Kingston, Croydon, Eei- ^ate, Guildford, Dorking, Boxhill, Winchester, Southampton, New Forest, Portsmouth, and Isle of Wight. Maps. Post 8vo. 30s. BERKS, BUCKS, AND OXON, Windsor, Eton, Heading, Aylesbury. Uxbridge, Wycombe, Henley, the City and Uni- versity of Oxford, Blenheim, and the Descent of the Thames. Map. Post 8vo. 7s. ed. WILTS, DORSET, AND SOMERSET, Salisbury, Chippenham, WeymouOi, Sherborne, Wells, Bath, Bristol, Taunton, &c. Map. Post 8vo. 10s. DEVON AND CORNWALL, Exeter, Ilfracombe, Linton, Sidmoutb, Dawlish, Teignmonth, Plymouth, Devonport, Toi^ quay, Launceston, Truro, Penzance, Falmouth, the Lizard, Land's End, &c. Maps. PostSvo. 12s. -CATHEDRALS of Winchester, Salisbury, Exeter, Wells, Chichester, Rochester, Canterbury, and St. Albans. With 130 Illustrations. 2 Vols. Crown 8vo. 388. St. Albans separately, crown 8vo. St. _. GLOUCESTER, HEREFORD, asd WORCESTITR Cirencester, Cheltenham, Stroud, Tewkesbury, Leominster, Ross. Mal- vern, Kidderminster, Dudley, Bromsgrove, Evesham. Map. Post 8vo. 9s. HAND-BOOK — CATHEDRALS of Bristol, Gloacester, Hereford, Worcester, and Liohfield. With 60 lUustrations. Grovn^ro. 16<. NORTH WALES, Bangor, Camarron, Beaumaris, Snovdon, LUnberis, Dolgelly, Oader Idris, Coawij, &c. Map. Post 8vo. 79. SOUTH WALES, Monmouth, Llandaflf, Merthyr, Vale of Neath, Pembroke, Carmarthen, Tenby, Snransea, The Wye, &c. Map. Post 8vo, 7s. CATHEDRALS OF BANGOR, ST. ASAPH, LlaudaiT, and St. Daviil's. With Illustrations. Post 8to. 15». NORTHAMPTONSHIRE AND RUTLAND— Northampton, Peterborough, Towcestpr, Daventry, Market; Har- borough, Kettering, WallingborouKli, Tlirapston, Stamford, Uppiag- ham, Oakham. Map. Post Bro. 78. 6d. DERBY, NOTTS, LEICESTER, STAFFORD, Matlock, Bakevell, Ghatsworth, The Peak, Buxton, Hardwick, Dove Dale, Aehborne, Southwell, Mansfield, Retford, Burton, Belvoir, Melton Mowbray, Wolrerhampton, Lichfield, Walsall, Tamwortb. Map. Post 8vo. St. SHROPSHIRE, CHESHIRE and LANCASHIRE — Shrewsbury, Ludlow, Bridgnorth, Oswestry, Chester, Crewe, Alderley, Stockport, Birkenhead, Warrington, Bury, Manchester, Liverpool, Burnley, Glitheroe, Bolton, Blackburn, Wigan, PrBSton, Rochdale, Lancaster. Southport, Blackpool, &c. Map. Post 8vo. IQi. YORKSHIRE, Doncaster, Hull, Selby, Beverley, Scarborough, Whitby, Harrogate, RipoQ, Leeds, Wakefield, Bradford, Halifax, Huddersfield, Sheffield. Map and Plans. Post 8vo. I2a. CATHEDRALS of York, Ripon, Durham, Carlisle, Chester, and Manchester. With 60 lUustratlous. 2 Vols. Grown Svo. 21>. DURHAM AND NORTHUMBERLAND, New- castle, Darlington, Gateshead, Bishop Auckland, Stockton, Hartlepool, Sunderland, Shields, Berwick*on-Tweed, Morpeth, Tynemouth, Cold- stream, Alnwick, &c. Map. Post Svo. 95. WESTMORLAND and CUMBERLAND— Lan- caster, Fnmess Abbey, Ambleside, Kendal, Windermere, Coniston, Keawick, Grasmere, Ulswater, Carlisle, Cockermoutb, Penrith, Appleby, Map. Post Svo. 69. *>• MnsBAY'a Map of the Lake Distbict, on canvas, 3i. Sd. SCOTLAND, Edinburgh, Melrose, Kelso, Glasgow, Dumfries, Ayr, Stirling, Arran, The Clyde, Oban, Inverary, Loch Lomond, Loch Katrine and Trossachs, Caledonian Canal, Inverness, Perth, Dundee, AberdeeD, Braemar, Skye, Caithness, Ross, Suther- land, &c. Mans and Plans. Post Svo. 9«. IRELAND, Dublin, Belfast, the Giant's Cause- way, Donegal, Galway, Wexford, Cork. Limerick. Walerford. Killar- ney, Bantry, Glengariff, &c. Maps and Plans. Post Svo. iQs, HERODOTUS. A New EngUsh Version. Edited, with Notes and Essays, historical, ethnographical, and geographical, by Canon Rawunboh, assisted by Sib Hshbt Rawunson and Sib J. 0. Wil- kinson. Maps and Woodcuts. 4 Vols. Svo. 489. HERSCHEL'S (Cakolike) Memoir and Correspondence. By Mrs. John Hbbbchbl. With Portraits. Crown Svo 129. HATHERLEY (Lord). The Continuity of Scripture, as Declared by the Testimony of our Lord and of the Evangelists and Apostles. Svo. 69. Popular Edition. Post Svo. 2f. Gd. HOLLWAY (J. G.). A Month in Norway. Pcap. 8to. 2». HONEY BEE. By Ret. Thomas Jamhs. Fcap. 8to. Is. • HOOK (Dean). Church Dictionary. 8to. ie«. PUBLISHED BY MR. MURHliY. 17 HOME AND COLONIAL LIBRARY. A Series of Works aff^pted for all circles and claBses of Readers, having been selected for their acknowledged interest, and ability of the Authors, Post 8vo. Published at 2*. and 3s. 6d, each, and arranged under two distinctlTe heads as follows : — CLASS A. HISTORY, BIOGRAPHY, 1. SIEGE OF GIBRALTAR. By John Dbikkwatsb. 2s. 2. THE AMBER-WITCH. By Last Duft Gobdon. 2s. 3. CROMWELL AND BCN^AN. By BOBEBT SOUTBEY. 2s. 4. LIFEoir Sib FRANCIS DRAKE. By John Babbott. 2s. 5. CAMPAIGNS AT WASHING- TON. By Bkt. G. R. Glbio. 2s. 6. THE FRENCH IN ALGIERS. By Ladt Dotv Gobdoh. 2s. 7. THE FALL OF THE JESUITS. Si. 8. LITONIAN TALES. 2». 9. LIFE OF 00ND£. ByLoBD Ma- HOH. 3s. 6d. 10. SALE'S BRIGADE. By Rbt. Q. R. Gl.xia. 2s. AND HISTORIC TALES. 11. THE SIEGES OP VIENNA. By LoED Ellbbubbe. 2s. 12. THE WAYSIDE CROSS. By Caft. Milmak. 2s. 13. SKETCHES OF GERMAN LIFE. By Sib A. Gobdox. 8s. 6<2, 14. THE BATTLE OF WATERLOO. By Rev. G. R. Gleio. 8». 6d. 16. AUTOBIOGRAPHY OF STEP. FENS. 2». 16. THE BRITISH POETS. By Thouas Gaufbell. 3s. Gd. 17. HISTORICAL ESSAYS. By LoBD Mahoh. S>. 6d. 18. LIFE OP LORD CLIVE. By Rev. G. R. Gleio. 3s. 6i, 19. NORTH - WESTERN RAIL- WAY. BySiBP.B.HlAD. it. 20. LIFE OF MUNRO. By Ret. G. R. Gleio. 3s. Sd. CLASS B. VOYAGES, TRAVELS, AND ADVENTURES. 1. BIBLE IN SPAIN. By Geobok BOBBOW. 3s. Gd. 2. GYPSIES OF SPAIN. ByGEOBOB BOBEOW. Ss. Gd. 3&i. JOURNALS IN INDIA. By Bishop Hebeb. 2 Vols. 7s. 6. TRAVELS IN THE HOLY LAND. By Iebt and Manqleb. 2s. 6. MOROCCO ANB THE MOORS. By J. Dbuumond Hay. 2s. 7. LETTERS FROM the BALTIC. By a Lady. 8. NEW SOUTH WALES. ByMas. Mebedith. 2s. 9. THE WEST INDIES. By M. G. Lewis. 28. 10. SKETCHES OF PERSIA. By Sib John Malcolm. 3s. Gd. 11. MEMOIRS OF FATHER RIP A. 2s. 12 & 13. TYPEE AND OMOO. By Hebuann Melville. 2 Vols. 7s. 14. MISSIONARY LIFE IN CAN- ADA. By Rev. J. Abbott. 2s. %* Each work may 16. LETTERS FROM MADRAS. By a Lady. 2s. 16. HIGHLAND SPORTS. By CHABiiEB St. John. 3s. Gd. 17. PAMPAS JOURNEYS. By Sis F. B. Head. 2s. IS. GATHERINGS FROM SPAIN. By RiOHABD FoBD. 3s. Gd, 19. THE RIVER AMAZON. By W. H. Edwabdb. 2s. 20. MANNERS & CUSTOMS OP INDIA. ByREV.C.AOLAHD. 2s. 21. ADVENTURES IN MEXICO. By G. F. RnzioH. 3s. Gd. 22. PORTUGAL AND GALICIA. By LoBB Gabnaevon. 3s. Gd. 23. BUSH LIFE IN AUSTRALIA. By Rev. H. W. Hayoaeth. 2s. 24. THE LIBYAN DESERT. By Batle St. John. 2s. 25. SIERRA LEONE. By A Lady. Ss.ed. be bad separately. 18 LIST OP WORKS HOOK'S (Thkodobb) Life. By J. G. Lookhaet. Tcap. 8to. la. HOPE (A. J. Berbsfokd) Worsliip in die Church of England. 8to. 9s., or, Popular Selections from. 8to. 2«. 6d. HOBAOE ; a Kew Edition of the Text. Edited by Dean Kilhan. With 100 Woodcuts. Crown 8to. 7». 6d. Life of. By Dhah MiIiHak. lUastrations. 8to. 9a. HOUGHTON'S (Lord) Monographs, Personal and Social With Portraits. Crown 8vo.* 10». 6d. PoEiioAi WoBKS. Collected Edition. With Por- trait. 2 Yola. Fcap. 8to. 128. HUME (The Student's). A Histoty of Euglaud, from the Inva- ' sion of Julias Ceesar to the Revolution of 1686. Corrected and con- tinned to 1868. Woodcuts. FoBtSvo. 7i.6d. HUTCHIKSON (Gen.) Dog Breaking, with Odds and Ends for those who love the Dog and the Gun. With 40 Illustrations. Mh edition. Is, 6(2. HUTTON (H.E.). PrincipiaGrseca; an Introduction to the Study of Greek. Comprehending Grammar, Delectus, and Exercise-book, with Vocabularies. Sixth Edition, 12mo. 8s. 6(2. IRBT AND MANGLES' Travels in Egypt, Nubia, Syria, and the Holy Land. Post 8vo. 29. JAMES' (Rev. Thomas) Fables of .Ssop. A New Translation, with Historical Preface. With 100 Woodcuts by TxmriEL and Wolf. Post 8vo. is. ed. JAMESON (Mes.). Lives of the Early Italian Painters— and the Progress of Fainting in Italy — Cimahue to Bassano. With 60 Portraits. Post 8vo. 12<. JENi^INGS (LoBis J.). Field Paths and Green Lanes in Surrey and Sussex. Illustrations. Post 8vo. lOs, 6d. JEEVIS (Set. W. H.). The Gallican Chutch, from the Con- cordat of Bologna, 1516, to the Revolution. With an Introduction. Portraits. 2 Vols. Svo. 28s. JESSE (Edwabd). Gleanings in Natural History. Fcp. 8vo. 3a, 6d, JEX-BLAKE (Eev. T. W.). Life in Faith : Sermons Preached at Gbtltenham and Rugby. Fcap. Svo. 3s. Gd, JOHNS (Bet. B. G). Blind People; their Works and Ways. With Sketches of the Lives of some famous Blind Men. With Illustrations Post Svo. 7s. ed. JOHNSON'S (Dr. Samuel) Life. By James Boswell. Including the Tour to the Hebrides. Edited by Mb. Cbokbb. 1 vol. Royal Svo. 12s. New Edition, Portraits. 4 Vols. Svo. [/n Prejparation, Lives of the most eminent English Poets, irith Critical Observations on their Works. Edired with Notes, Corrective and Explanatory, by Peteb Cdkhihohah. S vols. Svo. 22<. 6d. JUNIUS' Hahdweitiho Professionally investigated. By Mr. Chabot Expert. With Preface and Collateral Evidence, by the Hon. Edwabd TwisLBTos. With Faciiuiiles, Woodcuts, &c. 4to. £S Ss, PUBLISHED BY MR. MUHlkAY. 19 KBIT'S (BiBHOP) Life. By a Latmah. Portrait. 2 Vols. 8vo. 18s. EEBK (Eoeest). Small Country House. A Brief Practical Discourse on the Platining of a Kesideoce from 2000Z, to 60002. "With Supplementary Estimates to 70002. Post 8vo. 3s. Ancient Lights; a Book for Architects, Surveyors, Lawyers, and Landlords. 8vo. 69. Gd. (R. Maloolm) Student's Blaeketone. A Systematic Abridgment of the entire Commentaries, adapted to the present state of the law. PostSvo. 7s. 6*. KING EDWAED VIth's Latin Grammar. 12mo. Ss. 6d. -! First Latin Book. 12mo. 2». 6d. KING (K. J.). Archaeology, Travel and Art ; being Sketches and Studies, Historical and Descriptive. 870. 12a, KIEK (J. Foster). History of Charles the Bold, Duke of Bur- gundy. Portrait. 3 Vols. 8vo. 45s, KIEKES' Handbook of Physiology. Edited by W. MoEEisi Bakkb, F.R.C.S. With 400 Illustrations. Post 8vo." 14». KUGLER'S Handbook of Painting.— The Italian Schools. Ee- vised and Remodelled from the most recent Researches. By Lady Eabtlake. With 140 Illustrations. 2 Vols. Crown Bvo. 30s. Handbook of Painting. — The German, Flemish, and Dutch Schools. Revised and in part re-written. By J. A. Cbowb. With 60 nlustratiODS. 2 Vols. Crown 8vo. 24>, LANE (E. W.). Account of the Manners and Customs of Modern Egyptians. With Illustrations. 2 Vols. Post 8vo. 12s LAWEENCE (Sir Geo.). Eeminifcences of Forty-three Tears' Service in India ; including Captivities in Cabul among the Afighans and among the Sikhs, and a iMarrative of the Mutiny in Rajputana. Crown 8vo. IDs. Od, LAYAED (A. H.). Nineveh and its Eemains. Being a Nar- ' rative of Researches and Discoveries amidst the Ruins of Assyria. With an Account of th^ Chaldean Christians of Knrdistan ; the Yezedis, or ifevil-worshippers ; and .an Enquiry into the Manners and Arts 01 the Ancient Assyrians. Plates and Woodcuts. 2 Vols. 6vo, 36s. *«^ A PopiTLAa Edition of the ahove work. With Illustrations. Post 8vo. 7s. 6d. Nineveh and Babylon ; being the Narrative of Dis- coverieB in the Ruins, with Travels in Armenia, Kurdistan and the Desert, during a Second Expedition to Assyria. With Map and Plates. 8vo. 21> %• A PopDiAB Editios of the ahove work. With IllustratiooB Post Bvo. 7s. ed, LEATHBS' (Staklet) Practical Hebrew Grammar. With the Hebrew Text of Genesis i. — vi., and Psalms i. — vi. Grammatical Analysis and Vocabulary. Post Bvo. 7s, 6d, LENNEP (Rev. H. J. Van). Missionary Travels in Asia Minor. With lUiistrationfl of Biblical History and Arcbteology. With Map and Woodcuts. 2 Vols. Post Bvo. 24s. Modem Customs and Manners of Bible Lands in Illustration of Scripture. With Coloured Maps and 300 Illustrations. 2 Vols. 8vo. 21s. LESLIE (C. E.). Handbook for Young Painters. With IKustra- tions. Post 8vo. 7s. 6d. Life and Works of Sir Joshua Eeynolds. Portraits aud Illustrations. 2 Vols. 8vo, 42s. 2 20 LIST OF WORKS LETO (PoMPOHio). Eight Months at Eome during the Tatican Council. With a daily account of the proceedings. Translated from the original. 8vo. 12s LETTERS Fbou the Baltic. By a Ladt. Post 8vo. 2* Madras. By a Ladt. Post 8to. 2s. SiEBBA Leonb. By a Ladt. Post 8to. 3«. Cd. LEVI (Lkohe). History of British Commerce ; and of the Eco- nomic Progress of the Nation, from 1763 to 1870. Svo. 16*. LEX SA.LICA; the Ten Emended Texts with the Glosses. Edited (the Interpretation'of the Glosses) hy Da. H. KsBir, of Leyden, The Texts, newly collated, with Glossary, Introduction, &c , by J. H. LIDDELL (Dear). Student's History of Rome, from the earliest Timesto theestahlislimentof theEmuire. Woodcuts. FostSvo. 7g.6d, LISPINGS from LOW LATITUDES;' or, the Journal of the Hon. ImpnlsiaG UBhmgton. Edited by Loan Dufferih . With 24 Plates.lto. 21s. LITINGSTONB (Db). Popular Account of his First Expedition to Africa, 1840-56. Illustrations. Post 8V8. 7s. 6d. Second Expedition to Africa, 1858-64. Illustra- tions. FostSvo. 7s. 6(f. Last Journals in Central Africa, from 1865 to his Death. Continued by a Narrative of his last moments and sufferings. By Rev. HoHACB Wallbb. Maps and Illustrations. 2 Vols. 8vo. 26s. LIVINGSTONIA. Journal of Adventures in Exploring Lake Nyassa, and ^Establishing a Missionary Settlement there. By E. D, yooNG, R.N. Revised by Rev. Hobagb Walleb. Maps. Post 8vo. 7s. 6d. LIVONIAN TALES. By the Author of " Letters from the Baltic." PostSvo. 2s. LLOTB (W. Watkiss). History of Sicily to the Athenian War ; with Elucidations of the Sicilian Odes of Pindar. With Map. 8vo. 14s. LOCH (H. B.). Personal Narrative of Events during Lord Elgin's Second Embassy to China. With lUnstrations. Post 8to. 9s. LOCKHART (J. G.). Ancient Spanish Ballads. Hiftorical and Komantlc. Translated, with Notes. With Portrait and Illustrations. Crown 8to. 6s. Life of Theodore Hook. Pcap. 8vo. 1». LOUDOK (Mbs.). Gardening for Ladies. With Directions and Calendar of Operations for Every Month. Woodcuts. Fcap. Svo. 3s. Sd. LYKLL (Sib Ceakles). Principles of Geology; or, the Modem Changes of the Earth and its Inhabitants considered as illustrative of Geology. With Illustrations. 2 Vols. Svo. 32s. Student's Elements of Geology. With Table of British Fossils and 600 Illustrations. Third Edition, Revised. Post Svo. 9s. Geological Evidences of the Antiquity of Man, including an Outline of Glacial Post-Tertiary Geology, and Remarks on the Origin of Species. Illustrations. 8vo. }4s. (K. M.). Geographical Handbook of Perns. With Tables to show their Diatdbution. Post Svo. 7s. 6d, LYTTON (LoBD). A Memoir of Julian Fane. With Portrait. Post Svo. 5s. MoCLINTOCK (Sir L.).. Narrative of the Discovery of the Fate of Sir John Franklin and bis Companions in the Arctic Seas. With Illustrations. PostSvo. 7s. 6d. MACDOUGALL (Col.). Modern Warfare as Influenced by Modem Artillery. With Plans. Post Svo. 12j. PUBLISHED BY MR. MUilRAY. 21 MACGEEQOK (J.)- Rob Eoy on the Jordan, Nile, Bed Sea, 6en- neaaietb, &c. A Canoe Ci'uise in Palestine and Egypt and the Waters of Damascus. With Mao and 70 Illustrations. Cron-nSro. 7a. 6d, MAETZNEE'S Ekgiish GHAMMiK. A Methodical, Analytical, and Historical Treatise on the Orthography, Prosody, Inflections, and Syntax of the English Tongue. Translated from the German. By ClaieJ. Geeoe, LL.D. 3 Vols. 8vo. 36s. MAHON (Lobd), see Stashope. MAINE (Sib H. Suunek). Ancient Law : its Connection with the Early History of Society, and its Relation to Modem Ideas. Sro. 12s. Village Communities in the East and West. 870. 12s. Early History of Institutions. 8vo. 12s. MALCOLM (Sir John). Sketches of Persia. Post 8vo. 3«. 6d. MANSEL (Dean). Limits of Eeligious Thought Examined, Post 8vo. 8s. 6i. Letters, Lectures, and Papers, including the Phrontis- terion, or Oxford in the XlXth Century. Edited by H. W. Chandleb, M.A. 8vo. 12s. Gnostic Heresies of the First and Second Centuries. With a sketch of bis life and character. By Lord Gabnabtok. Edited by Canon LiaHTPOOT, 8vo. 10s. 6d. MANUAL OF SCIENTIFIC ENQUIEY. For the Use of Travellers. Edited by Ret. R. Main. Post 8to. 3s. Sd. {PuiUshed iy order of tha Lords qf the Admiralty.) MAECO POLO, The Book of Ser Marco Polo, the Venetian. Concerning the Kiagdoms and Marvels of the East. A new English Version. Illustrated by the light of Oriental Writers and Modem Travels. By Col. Henbt Ydle. Maps and Illustrations, i Vols. Medium Svo. 63s. MAEKHAM (Clements E.). The Introduction of Bark Culture into the British Dominions, containing a narrative of Journeys in Peru and Icdia, and some account of the Chincona Plantatibna already formed. lUastrations. 8vo. [InthePreai. (Mrs.) History of England. From the First Invap sion by the Romans to 1867. Woodcuts. 12mo. 3s. 6d. History of France. From the Conquest by the Gauls to 1861. Woodcuts, 12mo. 3s. 6d. : History of Germany. From the Invasion by Marius . Earlt Chbistiabitt, &am the Birth of Christ to the Aboli- tion of Paganism in the Roman Empire. 8 Vols. Post Svo. 18f . Latin Chbistiasiit, including that of the Popes to the Pontificate of Nicholas V. 9 Vols. Post Svo. 64>. Ahnais op St. Paul's Cathedral, from the Bomans to the funeral of Wellington. Illustrations. Svo. Character and Conduct of the Aeosiles considered as an Evidence of Christianity. Svo. 10<. 6d. Qdinti Hobatii Flaoci Opera. With 100 Woodcuts. Small Svo. 7s. ed. Life of Qdintus Horaiius Placoos. With lUustiationB. Svo. 9s. Fall of Jerusalem. Pcap. 8to. Is. MILMAN (Cam. E. A.) Wayside Cross. Post 8to. 2«. MIVABT (St. Geobse). Lessons from Nature ; as manifested in Mind and Matter. Svo. 13s. UOOBE (Thomas). Life and Letters of Lord Byron. Cabinet Sditicn. With Plates. 8 Vols. Fcap. 8vo. 18s.; Poptttar Bditim, with Portraits. Roya! Svo. 7s. 6iJ. MORESBY (Capt.), 'B.V. DiscoTeries in New Gninea, Polynesia, Torres Struts, &c., during the cruise of H.M.S. Basilisk. Map and Illustratioaa. Svo. 15s. MOTLEY (J. L.). History of the United Netherlands : from the DeathofWilliam the Silent to the Twelve Years' Truce, 1609. Portraits. 4 Vols. PostSvo. 6s. each. Life and Death of John of Bamereld, Advocate of Holland. With a View of the Primary Causes and Movements of the Thirty Yenra' War. Library Bdition. IllustratioDS. 2 Vols. Svo. aSs. Oabintl AUilion. 2 vols. Post Svo. I2i. MOSSMAU (Samoel). New Japan ; the Land of the Rising Sun : its Annals and Progress during the past Twenty Years, recording the remarkable Progress of the Japanese in Western Civilisation. With Map. 870. 15f, MOZLBY (Canoh). Treatise on the Augustiniaa doctrine of Predestination. Crown 8vo. 9*. Primitive Doctrine of Baptismal Regeneration. S. f 8vo 9». MOTRHEAD (Jab.). The Vaux-de-Tire of Maiatre Jean Le Houx, Advocate of Vire. Translated and Edited. With Portrait and Illus- trations. Svo. 21s. MUNRO'S (Qbnerai) Life and Letters. By Ret. G, E. Glbio. Post Svo. 33. ed. MURCHISON (SiK Rodbriok). Silaria ; or, a History' of the Oldest rocks containing Oreanlc Remains. Map and Plates. Svo. 18s. Memoirs. With Notices of his Contemporaries, and Rise and Progress of Palaeozoic Geology. By Abchibald Geikie Portraits. 2 Vole. Svo. 30s. MURRAY'S RAILWAY READING. Containing :— NiBIBODOHTHB ChASB, Is. HoLLWAt'b NoQWAT. 2f, MOBIO AND SbBIS. MilhaVb Fall of Jbruhalsm. 1«. LirB ov Thbodosb Hook. Is. Tbb Hohbx Bbb. li. Nimbod ow thb Tobf. la. fid. CBOKBR on THB QuiLLOTina. 1j. Uaubbl'b Wbllihston. la. fid. CAUfBBLL'B LivB or Bacon. 2«. 6i. Tas Flowhb Gabobit. la. Rbjbcxbd Addbbsbbb. Is. Fbnm'b Himtb oh AHBLiHa. la. MITSTBRS* (Capt.) Pataironiaua ; a Year's "Wanderings over Untrodden Ground from the Straits of Magellan to tlie Kio Negro. Illustrations. Post Svo. 7«. 6d. NAPIER (Sir "Wm.). English Battles and Sieges of the Peninsular War. Portrait. Post S^'O, 9a. NAP0LE013" AT PoNTAiNEBLEATT AND Elba. Journal of Occurrencfls and Notes of Conversations. By Sia Neil Campbell, With a Memoir. By Kev. A. N. C. Maclachlan. Portrait, 8vo. 16« , NARES (Sir George), R.l^. Official Report to the Admiralty of the recent Arctic Expedition. Map. Svo. 28. Gd. NASMYTH AND CARPEI^TER. The Mo^n. Considered aa a Planet, a World, and a Satellite. VVitli Illustrations ixom Drawings made with the aid of Powerful Telescopes, Woodcuts, &c. 4to. SOs. NAUTICAL ALMANAC (The). {By Authority,) 28, 6d ; NAVY LIST. (Monthly and Quarterly.) Post 8to. NEW TESTAMENT. "With Short Explanatory Commentary, By Abohdeagon CmmToif, M.A., and Archdsacon Basil Jones, M.A, With 110 authentic Views, &c. 2 Vols. Crown Svo 21b. bound. NEWTH (Samuel). First Book of Natural Philosophy; an Intro- duction to the Study of Statics, Dynamics, Hydrostatics, Light, Heat. and Sound, with numerous Examples. Small Svo.. 33.6^2. _^— • Elements of Mechanics, iacludiag Hydrostatics, with numerous Examples. Small Svo. 8s. Gd. Mathematical Examples. A Graduated Series of Elementary Examples in Arithmetic, Algebra, Logarithms, Trigo- nometry, and Mechanics. Small Svo. Sa. Gd. NIC^OLS' (J. G.) Pilgrimages to "Walsingham and Canterbury. ByBRASMQS. Translated, with Notes- With Illustrations. Post Svo. 6s. (Sir G.) History of the English Poor Laws. 2 Vols. 8to. 28«. 24 LIST OP WORKS NICOLAS (Sir Harms) Historic Peerage of England. Exhi- biting the Origin, Descant, and Present State of every Title of Peer- age which has existed in thin Coantry since the Conquest, By WlLLUU COURTHOFE. 8vO, 80<. NIMEOD, On the Chace— Turf— and Eoad. With Portrait and Plates, Crown 8vo, 6«. Orwlth Colonred Plates, Is. 6d. NOKDHOFP (Chas,), Communistic Societies" of the United states; including Detailed Accounts of the Shal^ers, The Amana, Oneida, Bethell, Aurora, Icarian and other existing Societies; with Fartlcnlars of their Religious Creeds, Industries, and Prtsent Condi- tion. With 40 lllustiations. 8vo. 15s, NORTHCOTE'S (Sir Johh) Kotebook in the Long Parliament. Containing Proceedings during its First Session, 1640, Edited, with a Memoir, by A. H. A. Hamilton, Crown Svo, 9s. OWEN (LiEni.-CoL,), Principles and Practice of Modern Artillery, including Artillery Material, Gunnery, and Organisation and Use ol Artillery in Warfare, With Illustrations. 8to, I5s. OXENHA JS. (Bev, W.), English Notes for Latin Elegiacs ; designed for early Proficients in the Art of Latin ^Versification, widi Pre&tory Rules of Composition in Elegiac Metre, 12mo, 3s. fid. PALGEATE (E, H. 1,). Local Taxation of Great Britain and Ireland, Svo, 6s, Notes on Banking in Great Britain and Ireland, Sweden, Denmark, and Hamburg, with some Remarks on the amonnt of Bills in circulation, both Inland and Foreign. Svo, €«. PALLISEE (Mrs.). Brittany and its Bjeways, its Inhabitants, and Antiquities, With Illustrations. Post Svo. 125. Mottoes for Monuments, or Epitaphs selected for General Use and Study. With Illustrations. Crown Svo, 7s. ft*. PAEIS (Dr,) Philosophy in Sport made Science in Earnest ; or, the First Principles of Natural Philosophy Inculcated by aid of the Toys and Sports of Youth, Woodcuts, Post Svo. Is.ed. PAEKTNS' (Masspieid) Three Years' Eesidence in Abyssinia: with Travels in that Country. With Illustrations. Post Svo, 7». 64 PEEK PEIZE ESSAYS. The Maintenance of the Church of England as an Established Church. By Rev. Ceabi,X3 Holz— Bev. R, Watboh Dixon— and Rev, Jnuns Llotd, §vo, 10». 6d. PEEL'S (Sir Eobert) Memoirs. 2 Vols. Post Svo. 15«. FENN (Eiohard), Maxims and Hints for an Angler and Chess- player, Woodcuts. Fcap. Svo. la. PEECY (John, M.D.). Metallurgy. 1st Division. — Pobl, Wood, Peat, Coal, Charcoal, Coke, Fire-CIays, New Edition. With Illustrations, Svo, 309 2nd Division, — Copper, Zinc, and Brass. JWw Edition. With Illustrations. [In the Press. 3rd Division, — Iron and Steel, New Edition. With Illustrations. [/„ PreparoHon. — ' 4th Division, — Lead, including part of Silver, With Illustrations. 30s. 5th Division.— Silver. With Illustrations, [Nearly Ready. 6th Division,— Gold, Mercury, Platinum, Tin, Nickel, Cobalt, Antimony, Bismuth, Arsenic, and other Metals, With Illus- trations, [/b Fr^pamtim. PBREY (Bev. Canoh). Life of St, Hugh of Avalon, Bishop of Lincoln. Post Svo. PUBLISHED BY MR. Mrj^RAY. 26 PHILLIPS' (John) Memoirs of William Smith. 8ro. 7a.6d. - Geology of Yorkshire, The Coast, and Limestone District. Plates. 2 Vols. 4to. Sis. 6(2. each. (Samuel). Literary Essays from " The Times." With Portrait. 2 Vols. Fcap. 8yo. Is. POPE'S (Alexahdeb) Works. With Introductions and Notes, byEEV. WhitwellElwin. Tols. I., II., VI., VII., VIII. With Por- traits. 8vo, 10s. 6d. each. PORTER (Rev. J. L.). Damaaons, Palmyra, and Lebanon, With Travels among the Giant Cities of Bashan and the Uauran. Map and Woodcuts. Post 8vo, 7s. &d. PRATER-BOOK (Illustbated), with Borders, Initials, Vig- nettes, &c. Edited, with Notes, by Rev. Thos. James. Medium 8vo, 18s. cloth ; 31s. 6f{. calf ; 36s. morocco. PRIKCESS CHARLOTTE OP WALES. A Brief Memoir. With Selections from her Correspondence and other unpublished Papers. By Ladt Rose Weioall. With Portrait. Svo. 8s. Si. PRIVY COUNCIL JUDGMENTS in Ecclesiastical Cases re- lating to Doctrine and Discipline, With Historical Introduction, by G. C. BsoBBiCE and W. H. Iebmantle. 8to. 10s. 6d. PUSS IN BOOTS. With 12 Illustrations. By Otto Spkoktee. 16mo. Is. 6d. Or coloured, 2s. id. QUARTERLY REVIEW (The). 8to. ««. RAE (Edwabd). Country of the Moors. A Journey from Tripoli iu Barbary to the Holy City of Kairwan. Map aud Etchings. Crown Sto. 10s. 6d. RAMBLES in the Syrian Deserts. Post Svo. 10«. 6rf. RASSAM (Hormuzd). Narrative of the British Mission to Abys- sinia. With Notices of the Goantries Traversed from Massowah to Magdala, Illustrations. 2 Vols. 8vo, 28s, RAWLINSON'S (Canon) Herodotus. A New English Ver- sion. Edited with Notes and Essays. Maps and Woodcut. 4 Vols. 8vo. 4Ss. Five Great Monarchies of Chaldsea, Assyria, Media, Babylonia, and Persia. With Maps and Illustrations. 3 Vols. Svo. 42s. (Sir Henkt) England and Russia in the East ; a Series of Papers on the Political and Geographical Condition of Central Asia. Map, Svo, 12s, REED (E. J.) Iron-Clad Ships ; their Qualities, Performances, and Cost, With Chapters on Turret Ships, Iron-Clad Rams, &c. With Illustrations. Svo. 12s. Letters from Russia in 1875. 8to. 5a REJECTED ADDRESSES (The). By James and Hobaob Smith. Woodcuts. Post Svo. 3s. &d. \ or Popular Edition^ Fcap, Svo. Is. EEMBRANDTf A Descriptive Catalogue of his Etched Work ; with Life and Introductions, By Chas, H. Middleton, 6. A. Woodcuts. Medium Svo. Bis. 6d, BETNOLDS' (Sir Joshua) Life and Times. By C. K. Leslie, R.A. and Ton Taylob. Portraits. 2 Vols. Svo. 42s. EICAKDO'S (Datid) PoUtlcal Works. With a Notice of his Life and Writings. By J. B, M'Cin.i.oaB. Svo. 16s. BIPA (Father). Thirteen Years at the Conrt of Peking. Post Svo. 2s. 26 LIST OF WORKS ROBERTSON (Oahoh). History of the ChrisUam Church, from the Apostolic Age to the Reformation, 1517. Uhrary Edition. 4Yala. Bvo. CaKnet Edition, 8 Vols. Post 8vo. 6(. each. ROBINSON (Rsy. Db.). Biblical ReBearches in Palestine and the Ai^acentBegions, 183&— 52. Haps. 3 Tola. 8yo. 42>. — PhysicalGeographyoftheHolyLand. PoatSyo. 10s. 6i. (Wm.) Alpine Flowers for English Gardens. With 70 Illastrations. Grown 8to. 12«. Sub-Tropical Garden. Illastrations. Small 8to. 7». 6d. ROBSON (E. R.). SoHooii Arohiteottob. Being Practical Re- marks on the Planning, Designing, Building, and Furnisldng of School-houses. With 300 Illustrations. Medium Bvo. I83. ROME (HiSTOKT Of). See Liddeil and Smith. RirXT0N(GE0.F.). Travels in Mexico; with Adventrs. among Wild Trihes and Animals of the Prairies and Rocky M3antalns. Post Svo. ZsSd. SALE'S (Sib Robert) Brigade in Affghanistan. With an Acconnt of the Defence of Jellalabad. By Rev. G. R. Glbig. Post 8to. St. SCEPTICISM IN GEOLOGY; and the Reasons for It. An assemhlage of facts from Nature combining to refute the theory of "Causes noir in Action.'" By Vehifibe. Woodcuts. Cro^Svo. 6*. SCHLIEMANN (Dr. Henry). Troy and Its Remains. A Narra- tive of Researches and Discoveries made on the 8ite of lUum, and in the ' TrojanPlain. With Maps, Views, and 500 Illustrations. Medium 8yo. 42f. ■ Discoveries on the Sites of Ancient Mycense and Tiiyns. With Maps and 600 Illustrations, Medium Svo. &0s. SCOTT (Sir Giiberi). Lectures on the Rise and Development of MedissTal Architecture. Delivered at the Royal Academy. With 400 Illustrations. 2 Vols. Medium 8to. 42>. Secular and Domestic Architecture, Present and Future. Svo. 9«. (Dean) University Sermons. Post Svo. 8«. 6d. SCROPE (G, P.). Geology and Extinct Yolcaaoes of Central France. Illustrations. Medium Svo, SOs. SELBORNE (Lord). Notes on some Passages in the Liturgical History of the Reformed English Church. Svo. 6t. SHADOWS OP A SICK ROOM. With a Preface hy Canon LiDnoK. lemo. 2i. ed. SHAH OF PERSIA'S Diary during his Tour through Europe in 1873. Translated from the Original. By J. W. Rbdhodbb. With Portrait and Coloured Title. Crown Bvo. 12s. SMILES' (Samuel, LL.D.) WORKS :— British Ensineees ; from the Earliest Period to the death of the Stephensons, With Illustrations. 5 Vols. Crown Svo. la. 6d. each. Life op a Scotch Naturalist. With Portrait and IUm- tratioDS. Crown Svo. IOa. 6(i » Life of Robert Dick (Baker of Thubbo), Geoloqist ahd BOTAHIST. With Portrait and Illustrations. Crown Svo. 10«. 6d. HuGUEHOTS IK Ekolahd AHD Irelahd. Crown 8vo. Ts.6d. Sblf-Help. With Illustrations of Conduct and Persever- ance. Post Svo. 6<. Or in French, 6.1. Character. A Sequel to " Sklp-Help." Post Svo. 6«. Thrift. A Book of Domestic Counsel. Post Svo. 6». Industrial Biography; or. Iron Workers and Tool Makers. Post 8vo. 6». Boy's Voyage RouHD THE World. Illustrations. Post Svo. 6«. PUBLISHED BY MR. MURRAY. 27 SMITH'S (Db. Wm.). DICTIONAiaiES :— DiOTioNART OE THE BiBLB ; its Autiqultiea, Biography, Geography, and Natural History. Illustrations. 3 Vols. 8vo. 105a. CoKoiSB Bible Diotiohabt. With 300 IlIustrationB. Medium 8to. 21s. Smahbk Bible Dioiionart. With lUuatrationB. Post 8vo. 7a. 64 Christiak Antiquities. Comprising the History, Insti- tutlouB, and Antiquities of the Christian Church. With Illustrations, Vol. I. 8to. 31s. ed. (To he completed in 2 vols.) Cheistian Bioqbapht, Litebatorb, Seois, and Doctrines ; from the Times of the Apostles to the Age of Charlemagne. Vol. I. 8vo 31s. Gd. (To he completed in 3 vols.) Greek and Koman ANTicioiTiES. With 500 Illustrations. Medium 8vo. 28». Greek and Roman Bioseapht and MiiHOLoaT. With 600 lllu:itr.itisiis. 3 Vols. Medium 8vo. U. 4s. Greek and Roman Geoobapht. 2 Vols. With 500 Illustra- tions. Medium 8vo. 568. Atlas of Anoieni Geoqkapht — Biblical and Classical. Folio. 61.69. Classical Dictionary of Mtthoiog^t, BioaBAPHi, and Geoqeapht. 1 Vol. With 750 Woodcuts. 8to. 18s. Smaller Classical Dichonaet. With 200 Woodcuts. Crown 8to. 7s. 6d. Smaller Greek and Roman Antiquities. With 200 Wood- cuts. Crown 8vo. . 7s. Gd. Complete LATiN-ENflLiss Diotionabt. With Tables of the Koman Calendar, Measures, Weights, and Money. 8to. 21s. Smallee Latin-TJnolish Dictionary. 12mo. 7s. 6d. Copious and Critical English-Latin Dictionary. 8to. 2l«. Smaller English-Latin Dictionary. 12mo. 7«. 6d. SMITH'S (De. Wm.) ENGLISH COURSE :— School Manual op English Gkammae, with Copious Exercises. Post 8vo. 3s, Gd, School Manual of Modern GEosEApaY, Physical and Political. Post 870. 5s. Primary English Grammar. 16mo. Is. Primary History of Britain. 12ino. 2s. Sd. SMITH'S (Dr. Wm.) GERMAN COURSE :- German Peinoipia. Part I. A Pirst German Course, con- taining a Grammar, Delectus, Exercise Book, and Vocabularies. 12mo. 3s, Gd, German Peinoipia. Part II. A Reading Book ; containing Fables, Stories, and Anecdotes, Natural History, and Scenes from the Historf of Geiiany. With Grammatical Questions, Notes, and Die- tioaarf . 12nio. 3«, Gd. Practical German anAMMAR. Post 8vo. Ss. 6A] 28 LIST OP WORKS SMITH'S (Dr. Wm.) FBENCH COUESE :— Pbenoh Pkinoipia. Part I. A First Course, containing a Crrammar, Delectus, Exercises, and Vocabularies. 12mo. 85. 6d. French PninctFiA. Part II. A Beading Book, containing Fables. Stories, aud Anecdotes, Natural History, and Scenes from the Hlstor]^ of France. With Grammatical Questions, Notes and copious Etymological Dictionary. 12mo. 4s. Gd. Fbekoh Prikcipia. Part III. Prose Composition, containing a Systematic Oourse of Exercises on the Syntax, with the Principal Rules of Syntax. 12mo. [fn the Press. Student's French Grammar. By C. Hbroh-Wall. With lotroduction by M. Littre. Post Sto. 7«. 6'i. Shaller Grammar of the French Language. Abridged from the above. 12mo. 3s. 6d. SMITH'S (Dr. Wm.) LATIN COURSE :— Prinoipia Latina. Part I. First Latin Course, containing a Grammar,Delectus,and Exercise Book, with Vocabularies. 12mo. 3s.6d. *#* In this Edition the Cases of the Nouns, Adjectives, and Pronouns are arranged both as in the obdinaby Gbamuabs and as in the Public School Pbimbb, together with the corresponding Exercises. Appendix to Prinoipia Latina Part I.; being Additional Exercises, with Examination Papers. 12mo. 23. 6d. Prinoipia Latina. Part II. A Reading-book of Mythology, Geography, Roman Antiquities, aud History. With Notes and Dic- tionary. 12mo. 3«. 6d. Prinoipia Latina. Part III. A Poetry Book. Hexameters and Pentameters ; Eclog. Ovidiauffi ; Latin Prosody. 12mo. 3s. 6d. Prinoipia Latina. Part IV. Prose Composition. Bules of Syntax with Examples, Explanations of Synonyms, and Exercisea on the Syntax. 12mo. . Bs, 6d. Prinoipia Latina, Part V. Short Tales and Anecdotes for Translation into Latin. I2mo Ss. Latin-English Vooabulart and First Latin-English DlCTlONABTFOfiPHiEDBUS, CoBNELIUSNepOS, ANdC^SAK. 12mo. Ss.Gd. Student's Latin Grammar. Post 8to. 6s. Smaller Latin Grammar. 12mo, 3s. 6d. Tacitus, Geemania, Agricola, &c. With English Notes. 12mo. 3<. ed. SMITH'S (Dr. Wm.) GEEEK COURSE:— InitlaGr^oa. Parti. A First Greek Course, containing a Gram- mar, Delectus, and Exercise-book. With Vocabularies. 12mo. 3s. Gd. Initia Ge^oa. Part II. A Reading Book. Containing Short Tales, Anecdotes, Fables, Mythology, and Grecian History 12mo. 3s. ed. Initia Greoa. Part III. Prose Composition. Containing the Rules of Syntax, with copious Examples and Exercises. ll2mo. 35. 6d. Student's Greek Grammar. By Curtius. Post 8to. 6s. Smaller Greek Grammar. 12mo. 8s. 6d. Greek Accidence. ISmo. 2s. 6d. Plato, Apology op Socrates, &c. With Notes, 12mo. 3s. Sd. SMITH'S (Dr. Wm.) SMALLER HISTORIES :— Scripture History. Woodcuts. 16mo. 3s. 6d. Ancient Histort. Woodcuts. 16mo. 3s. 6d Ancient Geography. Woodcuts. 16mo. Ss. 6d, BoME. Woodcuts. 16mo. 8s. 6d. Greece. Woodcuts. 16mo. 3«. 6rf. PUBLISHED BY MR. MURRAY. 29 SMITH'S (De. Wm.) smaller HISTOBIES ;— Classical Mttholoqt. Woodcuts. 16mo. Zs.Sd. BuaLAND, Woodonts. 16iuo. Ss. 6d. Bkqlish Litebatube, 16mo. Ss. 6d. Sfeoiuens of Euslish Litebatube. 16mo. 3s. Sd. SMITH (Geo., LL.D.) Life of John WiUon, D.D., F.B.S., of Bombay, Fifty Years Missionary and Pbilauthropist in the East. With Portrait and Illustrations. 8to. IBs* (Philip). A History of the Ancient World, from the Creation to the Fall of the Komau Empire, A.D. 476. Fourth Edition, 3 Vols. 8to. 31j. 6d. SHAW (T. B.). Manual of English Literature. Post 8to. 7s. 6d. ■ Specimens of English Literature. Selected from the Chief Writers. Post 8vo. 7». 6d. . (Robbet). Visit to High Tartary, Tarkand, and Kashgar (formerly Chinese Tartary), and Ketorn Journey over the Karakomm Pass. With Map and IIluBtrations. 8vo. 16«. SIBKEA LEONE ; Described in Letters to Friends at Home. By A Lady. Post 8to. 3». BH. SIMMONS (Capt.). Constitution and Practice of Courts-Mar- tial. Seventh Sditim. 8vo. 15». STANLEY'S (Dean) WORKS :— Sinai and Palestine, in connexion with their History. Map. 8to. 14}. Bible in the Holt Laud ; Extracted from the above Work. Woodcuts. Fcap. 8to 2t.6d, Basteen Chcboh. Plans. 8to. 12s. Jewish Chuboh. From the Earliest Times to the Christian Era. 3 Vols. 8yo. 38s. Epistles of St. Paul to the Cobinthians. 8to. IBs. Life of De. Aehold, of Rugby. With selections from his Correspondence. With portrait. 2 vols. Crown 8vo. 12s. Chukch of Scotland, 8vo. 7s. Gd. Memoeials of Cantebbuet Cathbdeal. Woodcuts. Post 8vo. 7». ed. Westminstee Abbey. With Illustrations. 8vo. 15s, Seemons dueiks a Toue in the East. 8vo. 9s. Addbesbeb and Chaboes op the late Bishop Stanley. With Memoir. 8vo. 10s. Gd. ST. HUGH OF AVALON, Bishop of Lincoln ; his Life by G. 6. PERBy, Canon of Lincoln. Post 8vo. ST. JOHN (Chableb). Wild Sports and Natural History of the Highlands of Scotland. New, and heautifuUy illnstrated Edition. Crown 8to. IBs. Cheap Edition, Post 8yo. 3s. «d. . (Bayle) Adventures in the Libyan Desert. Post 8vo. 2s. SUMNER'S (Bishop) Life and Episcopate during 40 Years. By Rev. G. H. SOMNES. Portrait. 8to. 14s. STREET (G. E.) Gothic Architecture in Spain. From Personal Observations made during several Journeys. With IllubtratioDS. Royal 8vo. 30«. , . , . - . -d • i. j :__ Italy, chiefly in Brick and Marble. With Notes of Tours in the North of Italy. With 80 Il- lustrations. Royal 8vo. 26s. STUDBKTS' MANUALS:— OiD Testament Hibtort ; from the Creation to the Betam of the Jews from Captirity. Maps and Woodcuts. Post 8vo. 7<. Bi. New Testament Histort. With an Introduction connecting the History of the Old and Neir Testamentg. Maps and Woodcuts. PostSro. 7a. 6d Eoolesiastioal History. The Christian Church during the First Ten Centuries ; From its Foundation to the full establishment of the Holy Bonian Empire and the Papal Power, Post 8to, 7s. &f. English Chuboh History, from the accesBion of Henry Till. to the silencing of Convocation in the 18th Century. By Rev. G. G. FsBBT. Post 8vo. 7s. Gd. Anoieht History op the East ; Egypt, Assyria. Babylonia, > Media, Persia, Asia Minor, and Phoenicia. Woodcuts. Po8(8vo. 7<. 6d. Ancient Geosraphy. By Kev. W. L. Sevan. Woodcuts. Post 8vo. 7s. Bd. History oe Greece ; from the Earliest Times to the Boman Conquest. By Wh. Sihtb, D.C.L. Woodcuts. Crown 8vo. 7a. M, \* Questions on the above Work, 12mo. 2a. History op Bome; from the Earliest Times to the Estab- lishment of the Empire. By Dean Liddsll. Woodcnts. Crown Svo 7s. ed. Gibbon's Decline and Fall of the Boman-Empibb. Woodcuts. Post 8vo. 7s. ed. Hallam's History of Eitrope during the Middle Ages. PostSvo, 7s. 6d. Hallam's History of England ; from the Accession of Henry VII. to the Death of George II. Post 8vo. 7a. 6d. ^ Hume's History op England from the Inyasien at Julius Cnsar to the Revolution in 1638. Continued down to 1868. Wood- cuts. Post 8vo. 7>. 6d. *»• Questions on the above Woik, 12mo. 2s. History op Eeanoe ; from the Earliest Times to the Estab- lishment of the Second Empire, 1852. By Rev. H. W. Jebvis. Wood- cuts. Post 8vo. 7a. 6d. • English Langttage. By Geo. P. Marsh. Post 8ro. 7s. ed. English Literature. By T. B. Shaw, M.A. Post Svo. 7g.6d. Specimens op English Literature from the Chief Writers. By T. B. Shaw. Post Svo. 7«. ed. Modern Geography ; Mathematical, Physical and Descriptive, ByRiv.W. L. Bevak. Woodcuts. Po8t8vo. 79.6d. , Moral Philosophy. By Wm. Fleming, D.D. Post Svo. 7s. 6d. Blaokstone's Commentaries on the Laws of England. By R. Malcolm Kebb, LL.D. PostSvo. 7<. 6<2. STTFFE (Khctt). Strength of Iron and Steel, Plates. Svo. 12», SOMEBVILLE (Mary). Personal BecoUections from Early Life to Old Age. With her Correspondence. Portrait. Crown Svo. 12». Physical Geography. Portrait. Post Svo. 9s. Connexion of the Physical Sciences, Portrait PostSvo. 99. Molecular and Microscopic Science. Illustra- tions. 2 Vols, Post Sro. 2l9. PUBLISHED BY MR. MURRAY. 31 STANHOPE'3 (Eabl) WORKS :— HisioaY OF England pucm the Eeiqh of Queen Anne to THB Peace 07 Versailles 1701-83, 9 toIb. PostSvo. 6a. each . British India, from its Okioin to 1783. 8to. Sa. 6d, HisTOKT of " FoETT-FivE." Post 8vo.» 3«. Historical and Critioal Essays- Post Syo. 3s. Sd. Frehoe Betseat from Moscow, and other Essays. Post 870. 7». 6i. Life of Belisabids. Post 8to. 10<. 6d. Life of Condb. Post 8vo. 3«. 6d, Miscellanies. 2 Yols. Post 8to. 13s. Story of Joan of Arc. Fcap. 8to. Is. Addresses on Various Occasions. 16mo. Is. SOUTHET (Robt). Lives of Bunyan and Cromwell. Post Syo. 2s. SWAINSON (Canon). Nicene and Apostles' Creeds; Their Literary History ; together with some Account of " Ttie Creed ef St. Atbanasius." Svo. ISs. STBBL (VoK) History of Europe during the French ReYolution, 1789—1795. 4 Vols. Svo. 48». STMONDS' (Eev. W.) Records of the Eocts; or Notes on the Geology, Natural History, and Antiquities of North and South Wales, Siluria, Devon, and Cornwall. With Illustrations. Grown Svo. 125. THIBAUT'S (Akioihe) Purity in Musical Art. Translated from the German. With a prefatory Memoir by W. H. Gladstone, M.P. Post Svo. 6s. I THIELMANN (Baron). Journey through the Caucasus to Tabreez, Knrdlstau, down the Tigris and Euphrates to Nineveh and Pabylon, and across the Desert to Palmyra. Traoalated by Chas. Henbaoe. Illustrations. 2 Vols. FostSro. ISi. THOMS (W. J.). Longevity of Man; its Facts and its Fiction. With Observations on the more Kemarkablu Instances. Post Svo. lOi. 6d. THOMSON (Archbishop). Lincoln's Inn Sermons. 8yo. 10s. 6d. Life in the Light of God's Word. Post Svo. 5s. TITIAN'S LIFE AND TIMES. With some account of his Family, chieBy from new an^ unpublished Records. By Ceowe and Cavaloaselle. With Poitrait and Illustrations. 2 Vols. Svo. 42b. TOCQUBVILLE'S ^tate of Society in Prance before the Bevolution, 17S9, and on the Causes which led to that Event. Translated by Henbt Bbevb. Svo. 14^. TOMLINSON (Chas.) ; The Sonnet ; Its Origin, Structure, and Place in Poetry. With translations from Dante, Petrarch, &c. Post Svo. 9j. TOZBR (Eev. H. F.) Highlands of Turkey, with Visits to Mounts Ida, Athos, Olympus, and Pellon. 2 Vols Crown Svo. 24i. Lectures on the Geography of Greece. Map. Post Svo. s>. TRISTRAM (Canon) Great Sahara. Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 15«. . LandofMoab; Travels and Discoveries on the East Side of tbe Dead Sea and the Jordan. Illustrations. Crown Svo. 15a. TEUEO (Bishop OF).— Tlie Cathedral: its Necessary Place in thi liife and Work of the Church. Crown Svo. 82 LIST OF WORKS PUBLISHED BY MR. MURRAY. TWENTY YEAES' RESIDBITCE among the Greeks, Albanians, Turks, Armenians, and Bulgarians. By an Enolish Ladt. Edited by Stanley Lane Poole. 2 Vols. Crown 8vo. 21s. TWISLETON (Edward). The Tongue not Essential to Speech, with lUastrations of the Power of Speech in the case of the African Confessors. FostSvo. 6s. TWISS' (HoiAOB) Life of Lord Eldon. 2 Vols. Post 8vo. 21«. TYLOK (E. B.) Researches into the Early History of Mankind, and Development of Civilization, 3rd Edition Revised. 8vo. 12s. Primitive Culture ; the Development of Mythology, Philosophy, Religion, Art, and Custom, 2 Yols, 8vo. 24s. VAMBERY (Abmihkb) Travels from Teheran across the Turko- manDesertonthe Eastern Shore of the Caspian. Illustrations. 8vo. 21s. VAN LENNEP (Henet J.) Travels in Asia Minor, With llluBtratlons of Biblical Literature, and Archeeology. With Woodcuts, 2 Vols, Post Svo, 24j. ^ Modern Customs and Manners of Bible Lands, in illustration of Scripture. With Maps and 300 lUuatrations. 2 Vols. Svo. 2I«. VIRCHOW (Professok). The Freedom of Science in the Modem State. Foap, Svo. 2s. WELLINGTON'S Despatches durlDg his Campaigns in India, Denmark, Portugal, Spain, the Low Countries, and France. 8 Vols. Svo. 20s. each. Supplementary Despatches, relating to India, Ireland, Denmark, Spanish America, Spain, Portugal, France, Con- gress of Vienna, Waterloo and Paris. 14 Vols. Svo. 20s. each. •.' An Index. Svo. 20s. Civil and Political Correspondence. Vols. I. to VII. Svo. 20s. each. Speeches in Parliament. 2 Vols. 8to. 42«. WHEELER (G.). Choice of a Dwelling ; a Practical Handbook of Useful loformation on Building a House. Flans. Post Svo. 7s. 6(2. WHITE (W. H.). Manual of Naval Architecture, for the use of Naval Officers. Shipowners, Shipbuilders, and Yachtsmen. Illustra- tions. Svo. 245. WILBBRFORCE'S (Bishop) Life of William Wilberforce. Portrait. Crown Svo. 6s. (Samdbl, LL.D.), Lord Bishop of Oxford and Winchester; his Life, Edited by A. Rawson Ashwell, D.D., Canon of Chichester. With Portraits, &c. S Vols. Svo. WILKINSON (Sia J. G.). Manners and Customs of the Ancient Egyptians, their Private Life, Laws. Arts, Religion, &c. A new edition. Edited by Samuel Bibch, LL.D. Illustrations. S Vols. Svo. 84s. Popular Account of the Ancient Egyptians. With 600 Woodcuts. 2 Vols. Post Svo. 12s. WILSON (John, D.D.), of Bombay, Fifty Years a Philanthropist and Missionary in the East; his Lire. By Geobqe Smitb, LL.D. With Portrait and IllustratiODS. Svo. ISs. WOOD'S (Captain) Source of the Oxus. With the Geography of the Valley of the Oius. By Col. Ydle. Map, Svo. I2s. WORDS OP HUMAN WISDOM. Collected and Arranged by E. S, With a Preface by Canon Lidoon. Fcap. Svo, 3a, 6d. YULE'S (Colonbl) Book of Marco Polo, Illustrated by the Light of Oriental Writers and Modem Travels, With Maps and 80 Plates. 2 Vols. Medium Svo, 63s, BRADBITRT, AQNEW, & CO,, FBtNTERS, WHtTBFRIARS, ■- ,%.»jJt*w;,MiBt»-;Vwi»w^)W.-Wv^<<* ^ 'V ti< c««*;9iiSi?iWW<»s,*«?^^^^ vviiS^i^v».iiiMaSSSaiisii*v*MiS«^w^^ > -WsS**»Jrt#*v^i*««B8*«ttBS» »«w«r-««s*m\«»wiwt>,'"