6 Cornell University Library B 430.A5W44 1892 The Nicomachean ethics of Aristotle / 3 1924 012 537 001 The original of tliis book is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924012537001 i/(sH^^¥^ THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF AEISTOTLE THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE n I TKANSLATED WITH AN ANALYSIS AND CRITICAL NOTES BT J. E. C. WELLDON, M.A. HEAD UASTEB OF HABBOW SCHOOL. Honiron : MACMILLAN AND CO. AND NEW YOEK. 1892 [The Right of Translation is reserved.] URIS LIBRARY JUL 06 W ^,,^\e s)asj^ ffiamStiljae: PEINTBD BY C. J. OLAT, M.A. & SONS, AT TBB UNIVEBBITT PKEBS. We t/xD |o(?/ U PREFACE. AFTER an interval of four years it is per- -OL mitted me to follow up my translations of the Politics and Rhetoric of Aristotle with a translation of his Nicomachean Ethics. I have had a good deal of work to do in those four years at Harrow and elsewhere, and it is, I fear, only too likely that the translation will exhibit some traces of the broken manner in which it has been written. But it has been a help to me in teaching my pupils the art of translation to be myself a translator, and the pleasure of entering into the mind of Aristotle, as none but a tra ^p^le s)as^ FEINTED BY 0. J. CLAT, M.A. & SONS, AT THE DNIVEBBITT PEESS. PREFACE. AFTER an interval of four years it is per- -t\- mitted. me to follow up my translations of the Politics and Rhetoric of Aristotle with a translation of his Nicomachean Ethics. I have had. a good deal of work to do in those four years at Harrow and. elsewhere, and it is, I fear, only too likely that the translation will exhibit some traces of the broken manner in which it has been written. But it has been a help to me in teaching my pupils the art of translation to be myself a translator, and the pleasure of entering into the mind of Aristotle, as none but a translator of his writings can, is a sufficient reward for the pains which it is necessary to take in translating them. It hardly falls within the province of a translator to give his reasons for the view which he takes of particular passages. But if I feel some confidence that in adopting my own viev/ T have not ignored the views of others who ".ave gone before me, it is in part at least w. N. E. h VI PREFACE. because I have had the good fortune of sub- mitting my proof-sheets as they were passing through the press to the careful and thoughtful criticism of my friend Mr A. H. Cruickshank, one of my colleagues at Harrow, and Fellow of New College, Oxford, to whom I owe, and desire to express, my sincere thanks. In trans- lating the Nicomachean Ethics I have, I think, made use of all the recent editions and commen- taries (they are not very numerous), though Mr Bywater's latest contributions to the study of Aristotle were not within my reach during the earlier portion of my work. It is perhaps right to say that I refrained from consulting such translations as had already been published in England until I had finished my own in- dependently; but in revising it I have not scrupled to refer to them and occasionally to borrow a hint from them. Thus to Mr Williams and to Mr Peters, different as their translations are, I am alike indebted. Perhaps the object which I have chiefly kept in view has been to make each sentence of my translation as clear as possible ; the rendering may be wrong or right in various passages, but at least I hope it is intelligible. It may be well to add that PREFACE. Vll I have deliberately rejected the principle of trying to translate the same Greek word by the same word in English, and that, where circumstances seemed to call for it, I have sometimes used two English words to represent one word of the Greek. But when all is said, the difficulty of translating Aristotle remains great ; nobody knows it so well as he who has felt it by actual trial ; but I cherish the hope that this translation may be the means of bringing the master-treatise upon Ethics into the hands of some one who has not known or appreciated it before. J. E. C. WELLDON. Habkow School, October 14, 1892. N.B. The text from which this translation is made is that of Bekker's Octavo Edition, published in 1881. The marginal references are to the pages of the translation, the references in the footnotes to passages of the Nicomachean Ethics are to the pages and lines of Bekker's text. In referring to other works of Aristotle than the NicoTnachean Ethics I have quoted the pages and lines of the Berlin Edition. Where the words of the translation are printed in italics, they have generally been inserted for the sake of elucidating the sense. &2 ANALYSIS. BOOK I. CHAPTER I. BvEEr art, every science, every action or purpose, aims at some good. The good {rayaOov) is that at which all things aim. The ends are either activities {ivipycmi) or results {ipya) beyond the activities. Where the result is an end beyond the activity, the result is superior to the activity. As there are various actions, arts and sciences, the ends are also various. The ends of the architectonic arts or sciences are more desirable than those of the subordinate arts and sciences. The end which we wish for its own sake, and for the sake of which we wish everything else, is the good, or the supreme good (to SpiOTOv). The knowledge of the supreme good is of great importance as regulating the aim or object of human life. The architectonic science or faculty is the political. Its end comprehends the ends of all other sciences and is therefore the true good of mankind. Ethids becomes then a department of Politics. It is not an exact science. Ethical truth can be ascertained only roughly and generally; it must always admit of dispute. The young, having no experience of life, are ill judges of ethical reasonings, which are conclusions from the premisses of fact. X ANALYSIS. CHAPTER II. The supreme good is admitted on all hands to be happiness (tuSat/ioi/i'a). But happiness is differently conceived. By some it is defined as a visible and palpable good, e.g. pleasure, wealth or honour; by others as an absolute or abstract good, which is the cause of goodness in all other goods. All reasoning is either deductive or inductive. Ethical reasoning starts from ascertained and known facts. But facts may be known either absolutely or relatively to the person.s who know them. It is facts relatively known which form the basis of Ethics. Hence the importance of a good moral training, as supplying the first principles of ethical reasoning. CHAPTER III. The lives of men may be described as (1) sensual (2) political (3) speculative. The sensual life is the choice of slavish or brutish men. The political life aims at honour. But honour is not identi- fiable with happiness, as it depends more upon the people who pay it than upon the person to whom it is paid, and is therefore not something proper to the person himself. Nor again are virtue {aperij) and! happiness (evbaifwvla) identi- cal, as virtue is consistent with a life of torpor or misfortune. The speculative life will be investigated hereafter. CHAPTER IV. Objections to the Platonic theory of the universal good. (1) Plato did not recognise ideas of things of which priority and posteriority are predicable. But good is predicated of rela- tion as well as of essence, and the relative is necessarily posterior to the essential. (2) Good is predicated in all the categories. But if so it cannot be a common universal idea. ANALYSIS. X^ (3) There is no single science of all good things, as there would be if the idea of good were single. (4) Good would not become more good by being eternal, if it were a universal idea. The Pythagorean doctrine that unity is a good is more reasonable than the Platonic doctrine that the good is a unity. It has been suggested that the Platonic theory does not apply to all goods and that there are two kinds of goods, viz. (1) abso- lute (2) secondary. But what are absolute goods 1 If nothing is an absolute good except the idea (iSe'a), the idea will comprise no particulars. If the particulars are absolute goods, the conception of the good will be the same in them all, But it is not the same, e.g. in honour, wisdom, and pleasure. Good then is not a common term falling under one idea. CHAPTER V. The practicable good is different in different actions or arts. e.g. in medicine, strategy, etc. But in each it is that for the sake of which all else is done. If then there is a certain end of all action, it will be this which is the practicable good ; or if there are several such ends, it will be these. Happiness answers to this description of the supreme good; for whereas other goods are desired partly for their own sakes and partly as means to happiness, happiness is always desired for its own sake. Also the final good may be assumed to be self-sufficient, and happiness is pre-eminently self-sufficient. Also happiness is distinct from other good things, as being the end or object of them. CHAPTER VI. The nature of happiness depends on the proper function of Man. As every part of Man, e.g. his eye, his hand, his foot, has its function, so has Man himself. What is his function ? XU ANALYSIS. Not the life of nutrition and increase (i) Spctttik^ koI av^rjriKr} iwij), for that is common to man with the plants; nor the life of sensation (ij aiV^iyriKi;), for that is common to man with the lower animals. It is the practical life of the rational part of man's being (irpaKTiKij ns tov Xayov.ex""^"^)- The function of man defined as an activity of soul in accord- ance with reason or not independently of reason {fjnxv^ ivipyeia Kara \6yov rj ovK avev \6yov). But the functions of a person of a certain kind, and of a person who is good of his kind, e.g. of a harpist and a good harpist, are the same. The function of the good man then will be an activity of soul in accordance with virtue, or if there are several virtues, in accordance with the best and most complete virtue, that activity being exhibited not in a chance period of time but in a complete life [iv /Si'ij) reXeioi). CHAPTEK VII. The degree of accuracy attainable in Ethics is not greater than is proper to the subject. We must be content vrith such accuracy as is attainable. Ethical science proceeds from first principles, and these prin- ciples are discovered sometimes by induction, sometimes by perception, sometimes by habituation and so on. CHAPTER, VIII. Goods are divisible into three classes viz. (1) External goods (2) Goods of the soul, (3) Goods of the body. ' Of these the goods of the soul are goods in the strictest sense. The end of human life then will be some good of the soul Accordingly the happy man will live well and do well as happiness is a kind of living and doing well {d^mla tJ koI €v7rpa^ia). ANALYSIS. xm CHAPTER IX. This definition of happiness embraces and includes the con- ceptions of happiness as prudence or wisdom whether (a) absolute or (6) associated with pleasure or external prosperity. For if happiness is activity in accordance with virtue, it implies virtue. KB. Happiness must be an activity rather than a moral state (eJis), as a moral state may exist and yet may be unpro- ductive, but activity implies action. Activity in accordance with virtue implies pleasure, as if a person is good, he finds pleasure in noble actions. Lastly, activity in accordance with virtue implies nobleness. Happiness then is the best and pleasantest and noblest thing in the world. But it requires the addition of external goods, as nobleness of action is impossible without external means. CHAPTER X. It is questioned whether happiness can be learnt or acquired, or is a gift of Heaven. Happiness, as being the best of human things, may be reason- ably supposed to be a divine gift ; for how can the best of things be left to chance ? But even if it can be acquired by learning or discipline, still in its nature it is divine. It is also of wide extent, as being capable of realization in all persons, except such as are' morally deformed. The definition of happiness agrees with the end of political science as already defined ; for the end of political science is to produce a character of goodness in the citizens. The lower animals are incapable of happiness, as being in- capable of virtuous activity. Children are incapable of happiness, except prospectively, for happiness requires complete virtue and a complete life. CHAPTER XI. Can a man be called happy so long as he is alive 1 The Solonian dictum that it is necessary to look to the end would seem to forbid the ascription of happiness to any one XIV ANALYSIS. until after he is dead. But if happiness is a species of activity, how can a person be happy not in his life time, but after his death ? Nor is it right to conceive a person to be happy after his death, as being at last exempt from the changes and chances of Mfe; for it may reasonably be believed that the dead are affected more or less by such good or evil as occurs to their children and descendants. To call a person happy after his death is to predicate happi- ness of him, not when the happiness exists, but when it has existed and is past. Again, to make happiness dependent upon the fortune of the moment is to destroy its stability and completeness. But no human function is so constant or stable as activity in accordance with virtue. The conclusion is that happiness possesses the element of stability. It is not affected by petty incidents of good or ill fortune, nor is it destroyed, although it may be impeded, by serious pains and calamities. Happiness being determined by virtuous activity the happy man can never become miserable, as he will never commit mean actions. His happiness will be seldom disturbed, but if disturbed, as e.g. by heavy misfortune, will be only slowly restored. The happy man then is one whose activity accords with perfect virtue, and who is adequately furnished with external goods, not for a casual period of time, but for a complete life- time. It is probable that a person after death is affected, but not affected to any great extent, by the fortunes of his descendants or friends, i.e. they do not create or destroy his happiness. CHAPTER XII. Is happmess properly an object of praise or an object of honour ? Praise implies a certain character and a certain relation to somebody or something else in the object of praise. Hence praise is inapplicable to the Gods, as they stand above com- parison. It follows that praise is inapplicable to the highest goods. ANALYSIS. XV Happiness then, as being the supreme good, is an object, not of praise, but of something higher than praise, yiz. honour. Prom another point of view happiness, as being a first prin- ciple {apx^f), is equally an object of honour. CHAPTER XIII. Happiness being an activity of soul in accordance with com- plete or perfect virtue, the consideration of virtue aflfords the best insight into happiness. Human excellence or virtue is not that of the body but that of the soul. Now the soul has two parts, one irrational (aXoyov) the other rational (XoyoK e^ov). The rational part is also capable of division into (1) the "vegetative part which is common to man with all living things, and is removed from the sphere of virtue (2) the emotional or concupiscent part, which is irrational, and yet may be said to partake of reason, not as possessing or understanding reason, but as being capable of obedience to reason. There are therefore in man (1) Intellectual virtues (Siai/oijTjKoi dperaC) Le. virtues of the rational part of his soul, e.g. wisdom and prudence, (2) Moral virtues (ijSucal apercu) i.e. virtues of the irra- tional part of his .soul when acting in obedience to reason, e.g. liberality and temperance. BOOK II. CHAPTER I. Virtue or excellence (dpenj) then is twofold, viz. (1) Intellectual (2) Moral Intellectual virtue is originated and fostered mainly by teaching ; it therefore demands time and experience. XVI ANALYSIS. Moral virtue is created by habit. It follows that moral virtue is not implanted by nature, as a law of nature cannot be altered by habituation. Nature affords the capacity for virtue, and that capacity is perfected by habit. There is a marked difference between the natural powers or faculties {Swafj-eis) of man and his virtues. The faculties are acquired before the corresponding activities are displayed. Thus the faculty of sight or hearing precedes its active exercise. But the virtues are acquired by their exercise ; justice by just action, temperance by temperate action, and so on. Legislation aims at making the citizens good by discipline of the habits. It is true of virtue as of art that the causes and means by which it is produced, and by which it is destroyed, are the same. A person becomes a good or bad musician by practising music well or badly. Similarly he becomes brave or cowardly by acting rightly or wrongly in the face of danger. In a word, moral states are the results of activities cor- responding to the moral states themselves. Hence the serious importance of the training of the habits from early days. CHAPTER II. The study of Ethics is not speculative only but practical. Our object is not merely to know the naturQ of virtue, but to become ourselves virtuous. It is necessary therefore to consider the principle of right action. But reasoning upon practical matters cannot be scientifi- cally exact ; it can only be tentative or approximate. Excess and deficiency are alike fatal in conduct. Excess or deficiency of gymnastic exercise is fatal to strength, excess or deficiency of, meat and drink to health. Similarly in respect of courage, temperance, and the other virtues, excess or deficiency is destructive, the mean or intermediate state is preservative, of the virtues. As the causes and agencies which produce, increase, and destroy the moral states are the same, so is the sphere of their activity the same also. Strength e.g. is produced by taking food ANAIiYSIS. XVII and undergoing toil ; but nobody can take so much food or undergo so much toil as the strong man. The same is true of courage or temperance. The pleasure or pain which follows upon actions is the test of a person's moral state. The essential quality of courage lies in facing dangers with pleasure, or of temperance in abstaining from physical gratifica- tions with pleasure. Hence the importance of such a training as produces pleasure and pain in presence of the right objects. This is the true education. The connexion of virtue with pleasures and pains follows (1) because the virtues are concerned with actions and emotions, and every action or emotion is attended by pleasure and pain (2) because the employment of pains as means of punish- ment implies the pleasantness of the condition which punish- ments are intended to remedy. Certain philosophers, e.g. the Cynics, seeing the influence of pleasures and pains upon conduct, have been led to define the virtues as apathetic states. Moral virtue then tends to produce the best action in respect of pleasures and pains. Again, there are three natural objects of desire, viz. the noble, the expedient, and the pleasant, and three natural objects of avoidance, viz. the shameful, the injurious, and the painful It follows that the good man vrill take a right line in respect of all these, but especially of pleasure, as pleasure is an element of nobleness and expediency. Also pleasure is a sentiment fostered in men from early childhood. Pleasure and pain too are in a greater or less degree the standards of human action. The study of Ethics then is throughout concerned vrith plea- sures and pains, as right or wrong pleasures and pains have a mat-erial influence upon actions. CHAPTER III. When it is said that a person becomes just by just aqtion, or temperate by temperate action, justice and temperance as quali- ties imply not only the corresponding actions but the correspond- ing knowledge or motive. XVm ANALYSIS. In order to just or temperate actions it is necessary- (1) that a person should know what he is doing (2) that he should deliberately choose to do it (3) that he should choose to do it for its own sake (4) that it should be an instance or evidence of a fixed and immutable moral state. Hence virtue, as necessitating these conditions, differs from art, which requires none of these conditions or only the condition of knowledge. CHAPTER IV. The nature op Viktue. The qualities of the soul are three (viz.) (1) emotions {rrddri) (2) faculties (Swa/icn) (3) moral states (e^ets). Virtue then must be one of these three. But the virtues like the vices are not emotions, for (1) praise and blame attach to virtues or vices but not to emotions (2) the virtues imply, but the emotions do not imply, deliberate purpose (3) a person is said to be moved {Kive'ia-dai) in respect of his emotions, but to have a certain disposition (SiaKflo-fiai was) in respect of his virtues or vices. Nor again are the virtues faculties, for (1) it is not an abstract capacity for emotion which is the subject of praise or censure (2) the faculties are gifts of nature, the virtues are not. If then the virtues are neither emotions nor faculties, they must be moral states. ANALYSIS. XIX CHAPTER V. It is not enough to show that virtue is a moral state, it is necessary to describe the character of that moral state. Every virtue or excellence has the effect of producing a good condition of that of which it is a virtue or excellence, and of enabling it to perform its function well. The excellence of the eye e.g. makes the eye good and its function good. Similarly tlie excellence or virtue of a man will be such a moral state as makes him good and able to perform his proper function well. In everything there is (1) a greater (2) a smaller (3) an equal whether (a) absolute or (6) relative to ourselves. The equal is a mean between excess and deficiency. The absolute mean is equally distant from both extremes, the relative mean is neither too much nor too little for ourselves. In practical matters the wise man seeks and chooses the relative mean. Every science or art, if it is to perform its function well, must regard the mean and refer its productions to the mean. Accordingly, successful productions are those to which nothing can be added, and from which nothing can be taken. But virtue is superior to any science or art. Virtue therefore will aim at the mean. All emotions and actions admit of excess and deficiency, they admit also of the mean. To experience emotions at the right times, on the right occasions, towards the right persons, for the right causes, and in the right manner is the mean, or the supreme good, and this is characteristic of virtue. Virtue then is a mean state as aiming at the mean. Again, there are many different ways of going wrong, but there is only one way of going right. Evil is infinite, good finite; hence excess and deficiency are characteristics of vice, and the mean state is characteristic of virtue. XX ANALYSIS. CHAPTER VI. Definition op Viktue. Virtue is a state of deliberate moral purpose, consisting in a mean that is relative to ourselves, the mean being determined by reason or as a prudent man would determine it (e|is jrpoaiptTiKij, iv lictTOTrjTi ottra T^ irpos iJ/iSs, dpuTfiivri Xdym Km oSs av 6 ^povifioi opLceuv). It is a mean state (1) as lying between the two vices of excess and deficiency (2) as discovering and embracing the mean in emotions and actions. But while virtue is a mean state if regarded in its essence, it is an extreme if regarded from the point of view of the supreme good. It is not every action or every emotion that admits of a mean state. Some emotions, e.g. malice and envy, some actions, e.g. theft and murder, are intrinsically wicked. These actions and emo- tions are in themselves excesses or deficiencies ; they do not therefore admit of a mean state. CHAPTER VII. Paeticular vietubs as exemplifications of the mean state. Excess Mean State D^iency {vmp^o'Kri) {p.ecr6Tr]s) (S^Xei\^is) Foolhardiness Courage Cowardice {6paa-os) (di/Spei'a) _ (gfiXi'a) Licentiousness Temperance Insensibility (aKoXaa-la) {aai^poavvrj) (dvaur6rja-ia) Prodigality Liberality lUiberality (aa-ana) (eXeu^epjorTjf) (dve\ev6epla) Vulgarity Magnificence Meanness (^avavcria) ■ (jicyaKoirpiircia) {piKponpin€i.a) Vanity ^ Highmindedness Littlemindedness {xavvoTrjs) (juyaXofvxla) {luKpo^vxla) N.B. Magnificence diflFers from liberality as having to do with large sums of money. ANALYSIS. XXI Excess Mean State Deficiency Ambition Lack of ambition ((^iXoTt/iia) {diXctTifiia) N.B. There is no name for the mean state ; hence sometimes ambition, sometimes lack of ambition is praised. Excess Mean State Passionateness Gentleness (opyiXdnjs) (n-paorijr) Boastfulness Truthfulness (aXa^oxei'a) (oXij^eui) Buffoonery Wittiness (^miioKoxia) {evrpaneXia) Obsequiousness (if Friendliness disinterested {(fnXla) {ApeiTKeia) or Flattery (if inte- rested) ((coXaMia) Bashfolness Modesty (? KaTcar\j)^is) {alSdtj Envy Righteous Indigna- {(pBovos) tion {v€fie(ris) N.B. This last example is inexact, as Aristotle saw in his Rhetoric Envy and Malice are not opposites, but compatible and co-existent. Deficiency Impassivity {aopyT]aia) Self-depreciation or Irony (elpavela) Boorishness (aypoott'a) Quarrelsomeness {bvo-KoXia) Shamelessness {avaurxvvria) Malice {eTTixatpeKaKLo) CHAPTER VIII. The extremes are opposed both to the mean and to each other; the mean is opposed to the extremes. But the opposition between the two extremes is greater than that between either extreme and the mean. In some cases the excess, in others the deficiency, is the more opposed to the mean. Foolhardiness e.g. is more opposed to courage than cowardice, licentiousness is more opposed to tem- perance than insensibility. The reason of this greater opposition lies partly>in the nature of the thing itself, partly in the greater inclination of human nature to one extreme than to the other. W. N. E. XXU ANALYSIS. CHAPTER IX. Moral virtue then is a mean state as lying between two vioes^ and as aiming at the mean in the emotions and actions. Hence the difficulty of virtuous living, as it is always difficult to find the mean. Practical rules for human life. (1) To depart from that extreme which is the more opposed to the mean. (2) To pull ourselves in the direction opposite to our natural inclination. (3) Where the attainment of the mean is impossible, to choose the lesser of two evils. Beyond these rules it is impossible to go. No theory will define the limits of right conduct. BOOK III. CHAPTER I. Virtue being concerned with emotions and actions, and volun- tary emotions and actions being subjects of praise and blame, but involuntary emotions and actions the subjects of pardon or pity, it is necessary to distinguish what is voluntary from what is. involuntary. Actions done under compulsion or from ignorance are involun- tary. But an action is compulsory if its origin is external to the person who does it, e.g. if the wind carries him out of his course. It is sometimes difficult to decide whether a particular action is voluntary or involuntary, e.g. if a person does some shameful action at a tyrant's command to save the lives of his parents or children, or if he throws his goods overboard to save his ship. Such actions may be said to be voluntary, as being chosen by the person at the time of doing them, but in the abstract they are involuntary. ANALYSIS. Xxm They may be either laudable or censurable or simply pardon- able. Yet there are probably some actions which a good man could not be compelled to do ; he would rather die any death, however dreadful. As a general rule it is a mistake to lay the blame of wrong actions upon external causes rathep than upon our own moral weakness. CHAPTER II. An action which is due to ignorance is non-voluntary, but it is not involuntary unless it is followed by a feeling of pain and regret. To act yrojM ignorance is one thing, to act in ignorance is another. A person e.g. who is intoxicated acts not from ignor- ance, but from intoxication, but he acts in ignorance. Ignorance is a frequent cause of injustice. But the ignorance which is the cause of injustice is ignorance which affects the moral purpose ; it is also ignorance of the universal ; but the ignorance which is the cause of involuntary action is ignorance of particulars, i.e. of the particular circumstances and occasion of the action. This latter ignorance admits of pity and forgiveness. The particulars of action are (1) the agent. (2) the action itself. (3) its occasion, or circumstances {vepi ri fj iv rivi). We may add (4) the instrument. (5) the object {evcKa tIvos). (6) the manner of acting. Nobody but a madman' can be ignorant of all these particulars ; but a person may be said to have acted involuntarily if he was ignorant of any one of them, especially if he was ignorant of the most important particulars, although an action cannot be called involuntary in respect of such ignorance, unless it occasions pain and regret to the agent. c2 XXIV ANALYSIS. CHAPTER III. Action being involuntary, if done under compulsion or from ignorance, it appears to be voluntary, if the agent originates it with a knowledge of the particular circumstances of the action. Actions due to passion or. desire are not involuntary for (1) if they were, no lower animal would act voluntarily (2) it cannot be supposed that nothing which is done from desire or passion is voluntary, or that noble actions are voluntary and shameful actions involuntary. There are certain things which ought to be objects of desire, and it cannot be said that these are desired involuntarily. Again, what is involuntary is painful, what is done from desire is pleasant. Again, there is no difference in respect of involuntariness between errors of reason and errors of passion ; it is a duty to avoid both. CHAPTER IV. MoKAL Purpose {irpoalpcms). It is closely related to virtue and is a better criterion of character than actions. Moral purpose is voluntary (eKova-iov), but volition is a wider term than moral purpose for (1) children and the lower animals have volition, but not moral purpose (2) actions done on the spur of the moment are voluntary but lack moral purpose. (1) Moral purpose is not desire (eVi^u/ii'a), for (a) irrational creatures are capable of desire, but not of moral purpose. (6) Moral purpose, but not desire, is proper to continence ; desire, but not moral purpose, to incontinence. (c) desire is contrary to moral purpose, but one desire is not contrary to another (d) pleasure is the object of desire, but not of moral purpose. ANALYSIS. XXV (2) Moral purpose is not passion {6vn6s) ; for where actions are due to anger, they are not directed by moral purpose. (3) Moral purpose is not wish (/SowXTjo-ir), for (a) we may wish for impossibilities, e.g. immortality, but we do not purpose them (p) we may wish for things which are possible in themselves but lie wholly beyond our own power ; but we do not purpose things, unless it is more or less in our own power to effect them. (c) Wish is directed to the end, moral purpose to the means. (4) Moral purpose is not opinion (So^a), for (a) Opinion applies to all things, i.e. to things which are eternal or impossible, as well as to things which lie within our own power ; moral purpose is confined to things which lie within our own power. (6) Opinion is distinguished by being true or false, moral purpose by being good or evil. Nor is moral purpose opinion of a particular kind ; for character depends upon purposing good or evil, not upon holding particular opinions. (c) Opinion relates to the nature of things, moral purpose to the duty of accepting or avoiding things. (d) Moral purpose is praised rather as being directed to a proper end than as being correct, opinion is praised as being true. (e) We purpose such things as we best know to be good ; we foi-m an opinion of things of which we have no knowledge. (/) The power of forming the best opinion does not imply the power of making the best moral- choice ; for a person may form a good opinion, but, being vicious, may not purpose good action. Moral purpose is not only voluntary, but implies previous deliberation. CHAPTER Y. What are the proper subjects of deliberation (jSouXfuujr) ? A subject of deliberation must be understood to be that about which a sensible person would deliberate. It will not be then (as) A thing which is eternal or immutable, e.g. the universe XXVI ANALYSIS. or the incommensurability of the diagonal and the side of a square. (p) A thing which follows the same invariable course, e.g. the rising and setting of the sun. (c) A thing which is wholly irregular, e.g. the rain. {d) A mere accident, e.g. the finding of a treasure. Nor will it be any human aflfair which lies beyond the control of our own action; the matters about which we deliberate are practical matters within our own power. Deliberation relates not to ends but to means. A doctor does not deliberate whether he shall cure his patients, but how he shall cure them. All deliberation is investigation (fijTijo-is) ; but there are forms of investigation, e.g. mathematical investigations, which are not forms of deliberation. The objects of deliberation and of moral purpose are the same, except that the object of moral purpose is itself the result of deliberation. Moral purpose then is a deliberative desire of something which it is in our power to effect (/3ou\«ur«i7 Spf^is rav ((j) ruiiv). CHAPTER VI. The wish is directed to the end; but what is the end? Is it the good (ro aya66v), or what appears to be the good (ro aiv6ii€vov aya66v) ? In an absolute sense it is the good which is the object of wish, but in reference to the individual it is that which appears to be good. The true good is good relatively to the virtuous man, as the truly wholesome is that which is wholesome to a person in a good state of health. Pleasure is a frequent cause of erroneous moral purpose, as appearing to be, but not actually being, good. CHAPTER VII. Virtue and vice are both voluntary ; for if it is in our power to act, it is in our power to refrain from acting, and if it is in our power to refrain from acting, it is in our power to act. This is the justification of the rewards attached to good and the punishments inflicted for evil, action. Ignorance itself is punishable, if it is due to vice or negligence. ANALYSIS. XXVll A person is responsible for his own demoralization. It is no excuse for injustice or licentiousness that a person has formed the habit of unjust or licentious action ; he ought not to have formed the habit. Vices of the body, as well as of the soul, are censurable, if they are the results of intemperance or folly. The appreciation of virtue is itself the consequence of moral discipline. CHAPTER VIII. Actions (jrp(i|«r) and moral states (e|«r) are both voluntary, but not voluntary in the same sense or degree. Actions are voluntary throughout, moral states are voluntary in their inception but not in their development. CHAPTER IX. Discussion of the several Virtues. I. Courage (dvSpeia). It has been defined as a mean state in regard to sentiments of fear and confidence (^etrdrijr Trepl <^oj3oue ral Bapptj). All evil things are objects of fear, but they do not all afford scope for a display of courage. There are some things which it is right to fear, and disgraceful not to fear, e.g. ignominy. Poverty or sick- ness, as not being vicious or the consequence of vice, is not a proper object of fear, although it is an evil. A person is not necessarily courageous if he does not fear poverty or sickness, nor is he cowardly, if he fears insult offered to his wife or children. What are then the fearful things in regard to which a courageous man displays his courage 1 Firstly death. Secondly, the perils of death, and therefore especially the chances of war. CHAPTER X. II. Fear (,t\oniiia). CHAPTER XI. VIL Gentleness (npaanis). Gentleness, or good temper, is a mean state in respect of angry feelings (fieo-onyr Trepi opyds) ; the excess is irascibility (opyiXon/s), the deficiency may be described as a phlegmatic disposition (dopyiiiria). The excess may take the form of XXXVl ANALYSIS. (a) irascibility {opyiXorrji). (6) quick temper (aitpoxoXia). (c) sullenness {m.Kpim]s). (d) sternness (xaKeircmis). The mean state, i.e. good temper, is tlie state of a person who does not get angry, except with the right persons, on the right occasions, in the right manner etc. CHAPTER XII. VIII. Friendliness ((piKia). There is no name for the mean state between complaisance '{apea-Keiaj and surliness (Svo-KoX/a) ; it most nearly resembles friendliness. It is the state of a person who in association with other people is neither over-anxious to give pleasure nor over- indifferent about giving pain. If a person seeks to give pleasure without any ulterior object, it is called complaisance, if he seeks to give it for the sake of some personal advantage, it is called ftattery (itoXaiceia). CHAPTER XIII. IX. Truthfulness {dX^6cia). There is also no name for the mean state between boastfulness (aXaCoveia) and irony or self- depreciation {elpaveia). The inter- mediate character is a species of truthfulness. A departure from truth on the side of exaggeration may be either pretentiousness or boastfulness; such a departure on the side of depreciation is irony or if it applies to small things, humbug ; but exaggerated deficiency, as well as excess, is a form of boastfulness. Boastfulness is more opposed to truthfulness than irony. CHAPTER XIV. X. Wittiness {fvrpaireXia). In respect of relaxation (avdirava-is) or diversion (Staymyij) the excess is buffoonery {^apoKoxla), the deficiency boorislmess ■.(aypioTtjs), the mean state is wittiness (cvrpairfXia). ANALYSIS. XXXvii The characteristic of wittiness is tact (im&e^iorrjs). A re6ned gentleman is in action and conversation a law to himself. CHAPTER XV. Shame {alBai) is rather an emotion than a moral state. It is an emotion appropriate not to all ages, but to youth. It is virtuous only hypothetically, i.e. it is virtue subsequent to deeds which are wrong in themselves, and ought not to have been done. BOOK V. CHAPTER I. JUSTICB (Sucaiatru'i/ij) AND INJUSTICE (dfioem). Justice is the moral state which makes people capable of doing what is just and makes them just in action and intention. Injustice is the opposite moral state. The moral states (?^«s) are different from the sciences («Vt- arrjfiai,) and faculties (SuKa/iets) ; for the same faculty or science applies to contraries, but one of two contrary moral states does not apply to its contraries. One of two contrary moral states may be ascertained from the other, or moral states may be ascertained from a considera- tion of their phenomena. CHAPTER II. The words justice and injustice are used in a plurality of senses, and the various senses being closely allied are apt to be confiised. A person is said to be unjust (a) if he breaks the law of the land (b) if he takes more than his share of anything. Similarly he is said to be just (a) if he keeps the law (6) if he acts fairly towards others. W. N. E. d XXXVm ANALYSIS. Where injustice is equivalent to unfairness, i.e. where it means taking more than one's share (n-Xeow^ia), it is concerned with the goods of fortune. CHAPTER III. The law-breaker being unjust and the law-abiding person just, it follows that whatever is lawful is in some sense jjist. The object of laws is the interest of the community as a whole. All that tends then to create and to conserve happiness in the body- politic is in one sense just. Justice as so defined is complete virtue in relation to one's neighbours ; hence justice alone of the virtues seems to be the good of others. This justice is not a part of virtue but the whole of virtue ; the corresponding injustice is not a part of vice but , the whole of vice. CHAPTER IV. Justice then is either virtue as a whole or a part of virtue; injustice either vice as a whole or a part of vice. In the large sense justice and injustice are concerned with the whole sphere of virtiious or vicious action, in the narrow sense with the goods of fortune, i.e. honour, property etc. CHAPTER V. The unjust then is (a) the illegal ■ (J?) the unfair. Similarly the just is (a) the legal (6) the fair. But illegality stands to unfairness in the relation of the whole to its part. The partial justice and injustice then are parts of justice and injustice as wholes. Justice and injustice as wholes are generally determinable by law; they are coextensive with the field of legal enactments. Particular justice may take two forms, viz. ANALYSIS. XXXIX (1) the distribution of honour, wealth etc. among the members of the community (2) the correction of wrong in private transactions. Private transactions again may be (a) voluntary, such as buying, selling, etc. (6) involuntary : and, further, involuntary transactions may be {a) secret, e.g. theft, adultery etc. (&) violent, e.g. assault, rape, murder etc. CHAPTER VI. Particular injustice being equivalent to unfairness, the mean state is fairness or equality {to io-ok). But fairness or equality implies twO' persons or things at least. The just then is (1) a mean (2) fair or equal, (3) relative to certain persons. Consequently the just implies four terms at least, the persons relatively to whom it is just being two, and the things in which it consists being also two. Also, if the persons are equal, the things will be equal, and where there is inequality of persons, there ought to be inequality in the shares of the things. Justice then is a sort of proportion [avoKoyov n). Proportion implies four terms ; hence the just requires four terms at least, and an equality of ratio between them. Thus, if A and B are persons, C and D things, as A is to B, so will C be to Z>. CHAPTER VII. The conjunction of A with C and of B with D will be what is just in distribution {8tavoiJ,ri). This justice is a mean between the violations of proportion, it is in mathematical language a geome- trical proportion. Hence injustice, being disproportionate, may take the form either of excess or defect, or rather of excess on the one side and of defect on the other. d2 xl ANALYSIS, Corrective justice (ro hiop6aTiK.6v) occurs in private trans- actions, whether voluntary or involuntary. It is also a form of proportion, but it is an arithmetical not a geometrical proportion. It presupposes an injustice, i.e. an unfairness or unequality, and aims at redressing it by taking away so much from one party and adding so much to the other. Fairness or inequality in this sense is the mean between excess and defect. It is as if a line be divided into unequal segments, and the part by which the larger of the two segments exceeds the half be cut oflf and added to the smaller segment. It aims at placing people, after ex- change, in the same position in which they stood before it. CHAPTER VIII. Retaliation (to avmreirovBos) is not equivalent to justice whether distributive {hiaveiofriKov) or corrective {hmpBanKov). Retaliation takes no account of {a) a person's character or office (6) his will. Requital may be requital either of good or evil. Propor- tionate requital is produced by cross conjunction (ij Kara 8ta/*e- rpov avCfv^ts). Suppose .4 is a builder, B a cobbler, C a house, D a shoe. In order that retaliation or reciprocity {avrairoSoa-is) may be attained, it is necessary to equate the goods, viz. the house and the shoe; in other words, the subjects of exchange must be comparable. Money (j/o/xto-;ua) is the means of comparison or equation between objects of exchange. It serves as a single universal standard of measurement. Society rests upon thfe demand for mutual services. Money is the most stable of goods, its value is the most cdnstant. Thus society implies exchange, exchange equality of goods, equality commensurability, and commensura- bility money. CHAPTER IX. Just conduct then is a mean between committing and suffer- ing injustice. Injustice is an extreme, whether of excess or of defect, justice a mean. ANALYSIS. xli CHAPTER X. It does not follow, if a person commits injustice (dS««T), that he is necessarily unjust (S&ikos). To be uiyust is not to commit an unjust action but to have the moral state of injustice. Justice, i.e. political justice, implies law, it can only exist where the relations of people are legally defined. A magistrate is a guardian of justice and therefore of equality. Justice as between masters and slaves or between parents and children is different from political justice. Political justice is partly natural, partly conventional The part of political justice which is natural is that which has the same authority everywhere and is independent of opinion. The part which is conventional is dependent upon law or custom and differs in different places. It is wrong to hold that all political justice is conventional. Every rule of justice or law stands to individual actions in the relation of the universal to particulars. Just or unjust action implies that a person acts voluntarily. Voluntary action has been defined to be such action as is in a person's power and is done by him knowingly; involuntary action such aa is not done knowingly or is done knowingly but is not in a person's power or is done by him imder compulsion. If a person performs just or unjust actions involuntarily, the justice or injustice is accidental, it is not inherent in the actions. Voluntary actions are done either with or without deliberate purpose. An action done in ignorance is called a mistake (d/uip- TTjiia), if the person affected, or the thing done or the instrument or the effect is not such as the agent supposed. It is called a mishap (i-rvxriiia) if the hurt done is contrary to the expectation of the agent. But an unjust action done vrith knowledge though vrithout deliberation, is an act of injustice {dSUrjfia). But it is only when the action is the result of deliberate purpose that the agent deserves to be called unjust. Involuntary actions are either venial or not. They are venial, if they are committed not only in ignorance but Jrom ignorance. They are not venial, if they are not committed from ignorance but in ignorance and from an emotion which is neither natural nor human. xlii ANALYSIS. CHAPTER XI. Is it possible for a person to suffer injustice voluntarily ? The answer seems to depend upon the definition of doing injustice. If to do injustice means simply to hurt somebody voluntarily, and voluntariliness implies knowledge of the person, the instrument, and the manner, then a person, e.g. an inconti- nent person, if he hurts himself voluntarily, may be said to suffer injustice voluntarily. But if, as is probable, to do injustice implies action contrary to the wish of the person to whom it is done, the suffering of injustice cannot be voluntary. CHAPTER XII. (1) Is it he who assigns to somebody else more than he deserves, or he who enjoys it, thkt commits injustice ? (2) Can a person do injustice to himself ? It is the distributor who commits the injustice, for his action is voluntary. An action, unless it is voluntary, cannot be unjust. CHAPTER XIII. Justice is difficult of attainment, as it consists not in actions but in a moral state. Consequently the idea that it is not less characteristic of the just man to act unjustly than to act justly is absurd. CHAPTER XIV. Equity [muiKeia). Equity is not identical with justice nor is it generically diffe- rent from it. The just and the equitable are both good, but the equitable is better. The equitable is just, but it is not just in the eye of the law; it is a rectification of legal justice. For all law is couched in general terms ; but there are cases upon which it is impossible to pronounce correctly in general terms, and equity applies to these cases. Equity in fact represents the mind, as opposed to the rule, of the legislator. ANALYSIS. xliii CHAPTER XV. The question of acting unjustly to oneself affects the right of suicide. The suicide acts unjustly, but unjustly to the state, not to himself. This is the reason why the state punishes suicide. An act of injustice is not only voluntary and deUberate but prior in time to the injury received ; but if a person can act unjustly to himself, he will be simultaneously the author and the victim of the same injustice. It is bad to suffer injustice and bad to commit it, but worse to commit it than to suffer it. Speaking metaphorically we may say that there is a justice between the different parts of a man's being ; it is in respect of these different parts that a person may be said to be capable of injustice to himself. BOOK VI. CHAPTER I. The mean lies between the excess and the deficiency. It is also such as right reason decides. But it is necessary to explain this definition of the mean and to explain it by defining the nature of right reason. CHAPTER II. It has been laid down that the soul is divisible into two parts, (1) the rational (to \6yov txP") (2) the irrational {to aXoyov). But the rational p:irt may be similarly subdivided. It includes {a) the scientific part {to ivurrriiioviKov), i.e. the part with which we contemplate such existences as have invariable prin- ciples {to. ovra Sacov al apxai. lO) ev84xovTai aWas fx^'")- (6) the ratiocinative part (to XoyianKov), i.e. the part with which we contemplate such existences as are variable (ra fV8e- XOfieva SKkas cx^"')- xliv ANALYSIS. It is necessary to ascertain the perfect state of each of these parts of the soul. There are three faculties of the soul which determine action and truth, viz. (1) Sensation (ata-Sria-is) (2) Reason (voOt) (3) Appetite or Desire (opef«). Sensation cannot originate moral action, for brutes possess sensation but are incapable of such action. But as moral virtue is a state of deliberate moral purpose, and moral pui-pose is deliberative desire, it follows that moral virtue implies (a) truth of reason, (6) Tightness of desire. Moral purpose then is the origin of action. The mere intel- lect by itself possesses no motive power, it must be intellect directed to a certain end, i.e. it must be practical. The moral purpose can have no relation to the past; it is the future or contingent, not the past, which is the subject of deliberation. CHAPTER III. There are five means by which the soul arrives at truth, viz. (1) Art («'x>^) (2) Science {emtn-rijui) (3) Prudence {i^povrjais) (4) Wisdom {(Tofpia) (5) Intuitive Reason (voCi). (1) Whatever is the object of science is invariable and eternal. It is also capable of being learnt, whether by induction (inayayij) or by syllogism ((ruXXoyttr/idt). Science then is a demonstrative state of mind ; it implies certainty. CHAPTER IV. (2) That which is variable includes the objects (a) of production (6) of action. ANALYSIS. Xlv Art may be defined as a rationally productive state of mind ; it relates to the creation of things -whose existence was not necessary but contingent, and whose original cause lies in the producer himself. The end of art is production, not action. CHAPTER V. (3) Prudence is the capacity of deliberating well upon what is good or expedient for oneself, not in a particular but in a general or comprehensive sense. But deliberation does not apply to such matters as are incapable of alteration or as lie beyond one's own power of action ; its end is not production but action. Prudence therefore is neither a science nor an art. It may be said to be a true rational and practical state of mind in the field of human good and evil. Prudence differs from art {a) as not admitting of excellence (&) as preferring involuntary error to voluntary. It is, in fact, virtue of the opiniative (to So|aoT«oy) part of the soul. CHAPTER VI. (4) The first principles of scientific truth are not the subjects of science or art or prudence, neither are they the subjects of wisdom, as the wise man sometimes proceeds from premisses which are not themselves demonstrable. (5) There remains only the intuitive reason as the means by which these principles are apprehended. CHAPTER VII. Wisdom is either special, as referring to a particular art, or general. General wisdom is the most consummate of the sciences. It is the union of intuitive reason and science. It is higher than statesmanship, as its subjects are, or may be, higher than Man ; it is the union of science and intuitive reason in the sphere of things of the most honourable nature. xlvi ANALYSIS. CHAPTER VIII. Prudence deals with such things as are of human interest and admit of deliberation. It is a practical virtue, and, as being practical, has to do, not with universals only, but primarily with particulars. The architectonic or supreme form of prudence is statesmanship. But prudence in the strict sense is generally taken to relate to one's own individual interests. CHAPTER IX. Prudence then is the knowledge of one's own interests. Such knowledge implies experience, and experience is inconsistent with youth. Prudence is the antithesis of intuitive reason, as dealing with particular facts which are matters not of scientific knowledge, but of perception. CHAPTER X. Deliberation is a particular form of investigation. "Wise deliberation is (a) not science {iirumjfirj) (6) not happy conjecture {eia-Toxta) (c) not sagacity {dyxivoia) (d) not opinion (So^a) of any kind. But it necessarily implies the exercise of reason. It remains that wise deliberation must be correctness of thought in delibe- ration. Not that all correct deliberation is wise deliberation; for it is possible to arrive at what is good by a false syllogism. It is correctness of object, manner, and time, in matters of expediency. Also it may be either absolute or relative to a certain end; in a word it may be defined as correctness in matters of expediency with reference to a particular end. ' ANALYSIS. xlvii CHAPTER XI. Intelligence (o-uxfo-ii) is dififerent from opinion. If it were not, everybody would be intelligent. It is also different from prudence, although its sphere is the same. Intelligence is critical, i.e. it makes distinctions ; prudence is imperative, i.e. it issues commands. Judgment or consideration (yviifiri) is a correct determination of what is equitable ; hence equity is a disposition to forgiveness. CHAPTER XII. Intuitive reason, prudence, intelligence, and judgment may be all regarded as having the same tendency; they are all concerned with matters of action, i.e. with ultimate truths; for both the first principles and the particular facts with which intuitive reason deals are ultimate truths (lo-xara). Demonstration (otto- 8«|w) starts from the truths of intuitive reason and is through- out concerned vrith those truths. CHAPTER XIII. What is the utility of wisdom and prudence ? (a) They are desirable in themselves, as being each a virtue of one of the two parts of the soul. (6) They are in a sense productive, (c) They are essential to the discharge of a person's proper function. While virtue ensures the correctness of the moral purpose, prudence decides upon such means as are natural in order to give that purpose effect. The faculty of hitting upon the means conducive to a given object is called cleverness (Seivorris). Prudence is cleverness tempered by virtue, just as virtue properly so called is natural virtue fortified by reason. Goodness then in a proper sense is impossible without prudence, prudence is impossible without moral virtue. Prudence does not employ, but aims at producing wisdom ; it does not rule wisdom but rules in the interests of wisdom. xlviii ANALYSIS. BOOK VII. CHAPTER I. There are three species of moral character to be avoided, viz. vice (KaKia) incontinence (aKpacrla) and brutality (dripionis). The opposite of vice is virtue ; the opposite of incontinence is conti- nence; the opposite of brutality may be called heroic or divine virtue. CHAPTER II. It is generally held that the continent man (a) abides by his calculations (6) is prevented by his reason from foUovping his wrong desires, and that the incontinent man (a) departs from his calculations (b) is led by his emotions to do what he knows to be wrong. The relations of continence, temperance, and steadfastness (xaprcpia) and again of incontinence and licentiousness, are matters of dispute. CHAPTER III. How is it that a person, if his conceptions of duty are right, acts incontinently ? The Socratic denial of incontinence, on the ground that nobody who has a conception of what is best acts against it, is at variance with the facts of experience. Incontinence implies the existence of strong and base desires; temperance implies the absence of such desires. Continence, although it implies adher- ence to opinion, does not imply adherence to every opinion ; for if an opinion is wrong, it is better not to adhere to it. Again, if there is incontinence in all things and not in regard to the sensual emotions alone, who is continent in an absolute sense 1 ANALYSIS. xlix CHAPTER IV. Three questions necessarily arise respecting continence, (1) Can incontinent people be said to act with knowledge, and if so, what is the nature of that knowledge ? (2) What is the sphere of continence or incontinence 1 (3) Are the continent person and the steadfast person the same or different ? CHAPTER V. The word knowledge is used in two distinct senses ; it may mean (a) that a person possesses knowledge, but does not apply it, (6) that he applies his knowledge. It is only when wrong action is taken after reflexion that it appears strange. An incontinent person is like a person who is asleep, or mad, or intoxicated ; in one sense he possesses, but in another sense he does not possess, knowledge. Brutes are not said to be incontinent, as having no universal conceptions. The deliverance of an incontinent person from ignorance and his restoration to knowledge is similar to a person's recovery from intoxication, or his awakening after sleep. Incontinence then occurs when a person possesses not knowledge in a full sense but only such knowledge as depends on sensation. CHAPTER VI. Can a person be incontinent in an absolute sense, and if so what is the sphere of such a person's incontinence ? Pleasures and pains are the sphere in which continence and in- continence are displayed. But the things which produce pleasure are (a) necessary, e.g. the processes of nutrition and of sexual love, (6) not necessary but desirable in themselves, e.g. victory, honour, wealth. If a person exceeds the limits of right reason in the latter class of things, he is not called incontinent in an absolute sense 1 ANALYSIS. but incontinent in respect of money, honour etc. ; but if he exceeds those limits in respect of bodily or sensual enjoyments, and exceeds them not of deliberate purpose but contrary to his purpose and intelligence, he is called incontinent in an absolute sense. States of brutality, however produced, lie beyond the pale of human vice and therefore of human incontinence. CHAPTER VII. Incontinence in respect of angry passion is less disgraceful than incontinence in respect of sensual desire ; for (1) Passion follows reason in a sense ; desire disobeys and disregards reason. (2) Passion is more natural than the desire of excessive pleasure. (3) Passion is less cunning than desire. (4) Passionate action involves pain, but wantonness is associated with pleasure. Continence and incontinence then are properly concerned with bodily desires and pleasures and with such of these desires and pleasures as are human ; hence brutes are not called continent or temperate. Brutality is not so bad as vice, but it is more formidable. CHAPTER VIII. The licentious person is worse than the incontinent, as he acts in cold blood, or without a strong momentary desire. Continence is preferable to steadfastness, as it implies not mere resistance to pain but victory over pleasure. The love of amusement is rather effeminacy than licentious- ness. Incontinence assumes the form sometimes of impetuosity, at other times of weakness. ANALYSIS. li CHAPTER IX. Licentiousness is indisposed to repentance, it is tlierefore in- curable; incontinence is disposed to repentance, it is therefore curable. Vice may be unconscious, incontinence cannot. Incontinence, unlike licentiousness, does not imply loss of principle. CHAPTER X. A person is incontinent, if he does not abide by moral purpose or reason, i.e. by right moral purpose and true reason. A person who abides by his opinion at all costs is called obstinate llaxvpo- yvdfuov). Obstinate people are (1) self-opinionated {IStoyvdnoves). (2) ignorant (a^adeis). (3) boorish (aypoiKoi). CHAPTER XI. Continence is the mean state between excess and deficiency of pleasure in bodily gratifications. Both the excess and the defi- ciency are vicious, but the deficiency is rarely seen. The difference between continence and temperance is that the incontinent person and the licentious person both pursue bodily pleasures, but the former does not, and the latter does, regard it as right to pursue them. Prudence and incontinence are incompatible, as prudence implies virtuous character. There are various kinds of incontinence. The incontinence which is the result of habit is more easily curable than the incon- tinence which is the result of nature. CHAPTER XII. Three opinions respecting pleasure, (I) That no pleasure is a good either essentially or acci- dentallv. Hi ANALYSIS. (2) That some pleasures are good, but the majority are bad. (3) That even if every pleasure is a good, the supreme good cannot be pleasure. (1) In general pleasure ia not a good ; for {a) Every pleasure is a process to a natural state, it is not an end. (6) Pleasure is eschewed by the temperate man. (c) Not pleasure but painlessness is pursued by the prudent man. {d) Pleasure is an impediment to thought. («) There is no art of pleasure. (/) Children and brute beasts pursue pleasure. (2) Pleasures are not all virtuous ; for some are disreputable. (3) Pleasure is not the supreme good, as it is not an end but a process. CHAPTER XIII. Good is of two kinds, viz. (a) Absolute. (6) Relative. Moral states then, and also motions and processes, will be of two kinds. The good is (a) an activity (eWpyeia), (6) a moral state (l^is). Hence such processes as restore a person to his rational con- dition are only pleasant in an accidental sense ; they are not natural or absolute pleasures. Nor is it true that in all pleasures there is an end distinct from the pleasures themselves. Pleasure should therefore be defined as an unimpeded activity of the natural state of one's being {aveiiiroSiaros evepyna Trjs Kara fjivcriv e^eas). Some pleasures may be injurious, but it does not follow that all pleasures are bad. ANALYSIS. liii No moral state is impeded by the pleasure which it produces ; it is impeded only by alien pleasures. If pleasure is not a product of art, neither is any other activity. Children and brute beasts pursue pleasures, but not absolute pleasures. CHAPTER XIV. As pain is an evil, either absolutely or relatively, its opposite, viz. pleasure, must be a good. Also happiness is an activity and an unimpeded activity, but such unimpeded activity is pleasure. Pleasure of some kind then is the supreme good. External goods, and goods of fortune are necessary as ac- cessories to happiness ; they do not themselves constitute happi- ness. The fact that all brutes and all men pursue pleasure is an indication that pleasure is in some sense the supreme good; but it is a mistake to identify pleasure with bodily pleasures. CHAPTER XV. Reasons why bodily pleasures appear more desirable than other pleasures. (1) Such pleasures drive out pain. (2) They are violent, and are therefore pursued by people who are incapable of other pleasures. Human nature, not being simple, requires change of pleasures. God enjoys one simple pleasure everlastingly. W. N. E. liv ANALYSIS, BOOK VIII. CHAPTER I. Pkibndship or Love ((jtiKia). (1) It is indispensable at all ages and in all the circum- stances of life. (2) It is natural, as is seen in the natural love of parents for their offspring, not only among human beings, but throughout the animal world. (3) It is social, as being the bond which holds states together. (4) It is noble, and is therefore the subject of praise. CHAPTER II. What is the nature of friendship or love ? It has been defined as a sort of likeness {o/jioiorrjs). But like- ness whether of temper or of occupation has been also held to be prejudicial to friendship or love. In order to understand friendship or kve it is necessary to understand what is lovable. The lovable is that which is good or pleasant or useful, and a thing is useful if it is a means to what is good or pleasant. It is relative good, i.e. good considered not absolutely but in relation to an individual, that is lovable in his eyes. The term friendship or love is not applicable to the affection felt for inanimate things, for (1) such things cannot reciprocate affection, (2) we do not wish the good of such things, e.g. we cannot be said to wish the good of wine. Friendship or love as distinguished from mere good will (eSvoia) requires (a) that it should be reciprocated (6) that it should not be unknown to either person. ANALYSIS. Iv CHAPTER III. As the motives of friendship are three, there will be three kinds of friendship. Where the motive is utility or pleasure, the friendship is not disinterested ; it is tlierefore accidental and easily dissoluble. Friendships of utility are most common among the old, friendships of pleasure among the young. CHAPTER IV. Perfect friendship or love is the friendship or love of people who are good and alike in virtue. (1) It implies (a) goodness, both absolute and relative, in the two friends, {b) pleasantness. (2) It satisfies the conditions of permanency, (3) it is rare, as such people are rare, and it takes time to know them. CHAPTER V. Friendships based upon pleasure or upon utility resemble the perfect friendship, as the good are both pleasant and useful to one another. But it is only the good who are friends for the friends' own sake. It is only the good whose friendship cannot be destroyed by calumnies. Other friendships than those of the good may be said to be called friendships by analogy. CHAPTER VI. Bad people then may be friends from motives of pleasure or utility ; good people are friends from love of the persons them- selves. The characteristic element of friendship or love may be either a moral state or an activity. Absence, e.g. does not destroy friendship. Friendship generally implies community of life ; hence it is difficult for old or austere people. e2 Ivi ANALYSIS. CHAPTER VII. Affection ((^iXijirw) resembles an emotion {wados), friendship (iKiai) are preserred by the principle of proportion (to dvdkoyov). The friendship of love is especially apt to be destroyed by the violation of that principle. Is the value of a benefaction to be settled by the author or by the recipient of the benefaction 1 They may clearly set different values upon it. It would seem that the recipient should settle it, but should settle it with regard to his feelings before he received it, not to his feelings when he has actually received it. CHAPTER II. • Questions of casuistry relating to friendship, e.g. Is the respect and obedience due to a father unlimited? Ought a person to serve a friend in preference to a virtuous man 1 Ought he to repay a debt to a benefactor rather than make a present to a comrade ? The general rule is that it is a duty to repay services in preference to conferring favours, but the rule is open to excep- tions. A father does not possess a claim to unlimited respect, although his claim to the highest degree of respect is indis- putable. It is an especial duty to afford parents the means of living. But generally every person or class of persons to whom we stand in relation is entitled to a particular respect, and we must pay due respect to each. CHAPTER III. Ought we to dissolve friendships with people whose character is no longer what it once was 1 If the motive of the friendship was utility or pleasure, the dissolution appears to be reasonable. If it was character, the dissolution is inevitable, unless indeed it appears that the vice Ix ANALYSIS. trhich dissolves the friendship may be cured. Any wide moral discrepancy leads to dissolution of friendship ; but he who has once been a friend cannot be altogether as a stranger. CHAPTER IV. The lore of friends is an expansion of self-love. The charac- teristics of friendship are all found in the relation of the virtuous man to himself They do not exist in the relation of a vicious man to himself; for vice destroys the sympathy of parts and unity of purpose which are indispensable to friendship or love. CHAPTER ^. Goodwill (eSwoia) .resembles friendship (i^iXia), but differs from it, as goodwill may be directed towards people who are unknown to us and who do not know that we wish them well. Goodwill differs from aflfection {ij)iKrjva-ei) (2) by habit (?56t) (3) by teaching (SiSaxff)- Virtue presupposes a certain suitability of character ; but the character needs education under virtuous laws. It needs also the habitual practice of what is right in after-life. Hence the importance of education and of the rewards and punishments appointed by law. It is only in Sparta and a few other states that education or the discipline of the character has been under- ANALYSIS. Ixvii stood to fall within the province of legialation. In education individual methods are superior to general, as it demands the study of individual character. But this individual study must itself be based upon an understanding of principles. The prin- ciples of legislation are taught not by statesmen but by sophists, but the sophists are ignorant of the true nature of statesmanship. It is necessary therefore to investigate legislation and for that purpose to collect and compare political constitutions, to consider their merits and defects, and to determine the means by which they are preserved or destroyed. Thus Ethics leads up to Politics. THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. BOOK I. Every art and every scientific inquiry, and similarly Chap. i. every action and purpose, may be said to aim at some S*'™®^* good. Hence the good has been well defined as that at which all things aim. But it is clear that there is a difference in the ends ; for the ends are sometimes Difference activities, and sometimes results beyond the mere ™*''®^"^^ activities. Also, where there are certain ends beyond the actions, the results are naturally superior to the activities. As there are various actions, arts, and sciences, it Snbor- foUows that the ends are also various. Thus health arts and " is the end of medicine, a vessel of shipbuilding, victory sciences. of strategy, and wealth of domestic economy. It often happens that there are a number of such arts or sciences which fall under a single faculty, as the art of making bridles, and all such other arts as make W. N. E. «P 1 2 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK I. the instruments of horsemanship, under horsemanship, and this again as well as every military action under strategy, and in the same way other arts or sciences under other faculties. But in all these cases the ends of the architectonic arts or sciences, whatever they may be, are more desirable than those of the subordi- nate arts or sciences, as it is for the sake of the former that the latter are themselves sought after. It makes no difference to the argument whether the activities themselves are the ends of the actions, or something else beyond the activities as in the above mentioned sciences. If it is true that in the sphere of action there is an end which we wish for its own sake, and for the sake of which we wish everything else, and that we do not desire all things for the sake of something else (for, if that is so, the process will go on ad infinitvjm, and our desire will be idle and futile) it is clear that this will be the good or the supreme good. Import- Does it not follow then that the knowledge of this 9iTic6 or knowing Supreme good is of great importance for the conduct preine of life, and that, if we hnow it, we shall be like good. archers who have a mark at which to aim, we shall have a better chance of attaining what we want? But, if this is the case, we must endeavour to compre- hend, at least in outline, its nature, and the science or faculty to which it belongs. Science or It would Seem that this is the most authoritative the"su^°* or architectonic science or faculty, and such is evi- good'^ dently the political ; for it is the political science or Ethics a faculty which determines what sciences are necessary of PouSos * ill states, and what kind of sciences should be learnt, CHAP. I.J OF ARISTOTLE. 3 and how far they should be ]eamt by particular people. We perceive too that the faculties which are held in the highest esteem, e.g. strategy, domestic economy, and rhetoric, are subordinate to it. But as it makes use of the other practical sciences, and also legislates upon the things to be done and the things to be left undone, it follows that its end will comprehend the ends of all the other sciences, and wiU therefore be the true good of mankind. For although the good of an individual is identical with the good of a state, yet the good of the state, whether in attainment or in preservation, is evidently greater and more perfect. For while in an individual by himself it is something to be thankful for, it is nobler and more divine in a nation or state. These then are the objects at which the present inquiry aims, and it is in a sense a political' inquiry. But our statement of the case will be adequate, if it Ethics not be made with all such clearness as the subject-matter science. admits ; for it would be as wrong to expect the same degree of accuracy in all reasonings as in all manu- factures. Things noble and just, which are the subjects of investigation in political science, exhibit so great a diversity and uncertainty that they are sometimes thought to have only a conventional, and not a natural, existence. There is the same sort of uncertainty in regard to good things, as it often happens that injuries result from them ; thus there have been cases in which people were ruined by 1 It is characteristic of Aristotle's philosophy to treat Ethics as a branch or department of Politics. 1—2 4 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK J. wealth, or again by courage. As our subjects then and our premisses are of this nature, we must be content to indicate the truth roughly and in outline ; and as our subjects and premisses are true generally hut not universally, we must be content to arrive at conclusions which are only generally true. It is right to receive the particular statements which are made in the same spirit ; for an educated person will expect accuracy in each subject only so far as the nature of the subject allows ; he might as well accept probable reasoning from a mathematician as require demonstrative proofs from a rhetorician. But everybody is competent to judge the subjects which he understands, and is a good judge of them. It follows that in particular subjects it is a person of special education, and in general a person of Theyotmg universal education, who is a good judge. Hence the fled to be young^ are not proper students of political science, Ses'^ °* as they have no experience of the actions of life which form the premisses and s ubjects of the reaso n- jj^s^ Also it may be added~that from their tendency to follow their emotions they will not study the subject to any purpose or profit, as its end is not knowledge but action. It makes no difference whether a person is young in years or youthful in character ; for the defect of which I speak is not one of time but is due to the emotional character of his 1 This is belipved to be the passage which Shakespeare had in mind, though the reference to it is put in Hector's mouth, "young men, whom Aristotle thought Unfit to hear moral philosophy." Troilus and Cresrida, Act iL Scene 2, CHAP. II.] OP ARISTOTLE. 5 life and pursuits. Knowledge is as useless to such a person a? it is to an intemperate person. But where the desires and actions of people are regulated by reason the knowledge of these subjects will be extremely valuable. But having said so much by way of preface as to chap. ii. the students of political science, the spirit in which it should be studied, and the object which we set before ourselves, let us resume our argument as follows : As every knowledge and moral purpose aspires to some good, what is in our view the good at which the political science aims, and what is the highest of all The end of practical goods ? As to its name there is, I may say, science. a general agreement. The masses and the cultured classes agree in calling it happiness, and conceive Happiness. that "to live well" or "to do well" is the same thing as " to be happy." But as to the nature of happiness Nature of they do not agree, nor do the masses give the same *pp™*^^' account of it as the philosophers. The former define it as something visible and palpable, e.g. pleasure, wealth, or honour ; different people give different definitions of it, and often the same person gives different definitions at different times ; for when a person has been ill, it is health, when he is poor, it is wealth, and, if he is conscious of his own ignorance, he envies people who use grand language above his own comprehension. Some philosophers^ on the other hand have held that, besides these various goods, there is an absolute good which is "the cause of goodness in them all. It would perhaps be a waste , of time to examine all these opinions, it will be ,' Aristotle is thinking of the Platonic " ideas." 6 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK I. enough to examine such as are most popular or as seem to be more or less reasonable. Deductive But we must not fail to observe the distinction ive reason- between the reasonings which proceed from first p^dpies. principles and the reasonings which lead up to first principles. For Plato* was right in raising the diflHcult question whether the true way was from first principles or to first principles, as in the race-course from the judges to the goal, or vice versa. We must begin then with such facts as are known. But facts may be known in two ways, i.e. either relatively to ourselves or absolutely. It is probable then that we must begin with such facts as are known to us, i.e. relatively. It is necessary therefore, if a person is to be a competent student of what is noble and just and of politics in general, that he should have re- ceived a good moral training. For the fact that a thing is so is a first principle or starting-point^, and, if the fact is suflSciently clear, it will not be necessary to go on to ask the reason of it. But a person who has received a good moral training either possesses first principles, or will have no difficulty in acquiring them. But if he does not possess them, and cannot acquire them, he had better lay to heart Hesiod's lines' : ^ The reference is probably not to any special passage in the dialogues of Plato, but to the general drift or scope of the Socratic dialectics. 2 Aristotle's reasoning depends in part on the double meaning of dpxv viz. (1) starting-point or beginning, (2) iirst principle or axiomatic truth. 3 "Epya Kat "H;iepai 291—296. CHAP. III.] OF ARISTOTLE. 7. " Far best is he who is himself all-wise, And he, too, good who listens to wise words ; But whoso is not wise nor lays to heart Another's wisdom is a useless man." But to return from our digression : It seems not Chap. iix. unreasonable that peoplelshould derive their concep- ^o^gg™' tion of the good or of happiness from men's lives, tions of Thus ordinary or vulgar people conceive it to be pleasure, and accordingly approve a life of enjoyment. For there are practically three prominent lives, the sensual, the politicaJ, and, thirdly, the speculative. Now the mass of men present an absolutely slavish appearance, as choosing the life of brute beasts, but they meet with consideration because so many persons in authority share the tastes of Sardanapalus ^ Cultivated and practical people, on the other hand, identify happiness with honour, as honour is the general end of political life. But this appears too superficial for our present purpose ; for honour seems to depend more upon the people who pay it than upon the person to whom it is paid, and we have an intuitive feeling that the good is something which is proper to a man himself and cannot easily be taken away from him. It seems too that the reason why men seek honour is that they may be confident of their own goodness. Accordingly they seek it at the hands of the wise and of those who know them well, and they seek it on the ground of virtue ; hence it is clear that in their judgment at any rate virtue is superior to honour. It would perhaps be right then to look upon virtue rather than honour as being the end of 1 The most luxurious, and the last, Assyrian monarch. 8 THE NIOOMACHEAN ETHICS [boOK I. the political life. Yet virtue again, it appears, lacks completeness ; for it seems that a man may possess virtue and yet be asleep or inactive throughout life, and, not only so but he may experience the greatest calamities and misfortunes. But nobody would call such a life a life of happiness, unless he were main- taining a paradox. It is not necessary to dwell further on this subject, as it is sufficiently discussed in the popular philosophical treatises'. The third life is the speculative which we will investigate hereafter^ The life of money-making is in a sense a life of constraint, and it is clear that wealth is not the good of which we are in quest ; for it is useful in part as a means to something else. It would be a more reasonable view therefore that the things men- tioned before, viz. sensiial pleasure, honour and virtiie, are ends than that wealth is, as they are things which are desired on their own account. Yet these too are apparently not ends, although much argument has been employed' to show that they are. Chap. IV. "We may now dismiss this subject ; but it will universal perhaps be best to consider the imiversal good, and good. to discuss the meaning in which the phrase is used, 1 The "popular philosophical treatises'' ra eyKVKKia (jjiKoa-o- (pijfiaTa as they are called ircpi ovpavov i. ch, 9, p. 279 A30 represent, as I suppose, the discussions and conclusions of thinkers outside the Aristotelian school and are in fact the same as the d^wTcpiKol \6yoi, ' The investigation of the speculative life occurs in Book x. 3 The usage of Aristotle is in favour of taking KaTa^i^Xrjvrai to mean "has been employed" rather than "has been wasted"; see especially wtpi Koo-^iov ch. 6, p. 397 Bjj. CHAP. IV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 9 although there is this diflBculty in such an enquiry, that the doctrine of ideas has been introduced by Doctrine of our friends'. Yet it will perhaps seem the best, and ' **'" indeed the right course, at least when the truth is at stake, to go so far as to sacrifice what is near and dear to us, especially as we are philosophers. For friends and truth are both dear to us, but it is a sacred duty to prefer the truth. Now the authors of this theory did not make ideas of things in which they predicated priority and posteriority. Hence they did not constitute an idea of numbers. But good is predicated equally ofNonni- substance, quality and relation, and the absolute or ol^good? essential, i.e. substance, is in its nature prior to the relative, as relativity is like an ofishoot or accident of existence ; hence there cannot be an idea which is common to them both. Again, there are as many ways of predicating good as of predicating existence ; for it is predicated of substance as e.g. of God or the mind, or of quality as of the virtues, or of quantity as of the mean, or of relativity as of the usefiil, or of time as of opportunity, or of place as of a habitation, and so on. It is clear then that it cannot be a common universal idea or a unity ; otherwise it would not be predicated in all the categories'' but only in one. Thirdly, as there is a single science of all such things as fall under a single idea, there would have been a single science of all good things, if the idea of "good" were single ; but in fact there are many sciences even of such good things as fall under 1 In reference, of course, to Plato. 2 For the " categories ", see Kan/yopiat ch. 4. 10 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK I. a single category, strategy, e.g. being the science of opportunity in war, and medicine the science of opportunity in disease, medicine again being the science of the niean in respect of food, and gymnastic the science of the mean in respect of exercise. It would be difficult, too, to say what is meant by the " absolute" in anything, if in " absolute man" and in "man" there is one and the same conception of man. For there will be no difference between them in respect of manhood, and, if so, neither will there be any difference between "absolute good" and "good" in respect of goodness. Nor again will good be more good if it is eternal, since a white thing which lasts for a long time is not whiter than that which lasts for a single day. There seems to be more plausibility in the doctrine of the Pythagoreans' who place unity in the catalogue of goods, and Speusippus* apparently agrees with them. How- ever these are questions which may be deferred to another occasion ; but there is an objection to my arguments which suggests itself, viz. that the Platonic theory does not apply to every good, that the things which in themselves are sought after and welcomed are reckoned as one species and the things which tend to produce or in any sense preserve these or to prevent their opposites are reckoned as goods in a secondary sense as being means to these. It is clear • ' The point is that it is apparently more reasonable to describe unity as a good than to describe good as a unity. The Pytha- goreans, or some of them, drew up catalogues of opposites (o-utrroix'a')) ^.s Aristotle explains Metaph. i. ch. 5. 2 Plato's nephew and successor in the Academy. CHAP. IV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 11 then that there will be two kinds of goods, some Two kmcis being absolute goods, and others secondary. Let us ikeaf and ' then separate goods which are merely serviceable ^^le''"' from absolute goods and consider if they are conceived as falling under a single idea. But what kind of things is it that may be defined as absolute goods ? Will it be all such as are sought after independently of their consequences, e.g. wisdom, sight, and certain pleasures and honours? For granting that we seek after these sometimes as means to something else, still we may define them as absolute goods. Or is none of these things an absolute good, nor anything else except the idea? But then the type or idea will be purposeless, i.e. it will -not comprise any particulars. If, on the other hand, these things too are absolute goods, the conception of the good will necessarily appear the same in them all, as the conception of whiteness appears the same in snow and in white lead. But the conception of honour, wisdom and pleasure, are distinct and different in respect of goodness. " Good" then is not a common term falling under one idea. But in what sense is the term used? For it does not seem to be an accidental homonymy'. Is it because all goods issue from one source or all tend to one end ; or is it rather a case of analogy ? for as the sight is to the body, so is the mind to the soul, i.e. the mind may Tie called the eye of the soul, and so on. But it will 1 "What is meant by an "accidental homonymy" or equivo- cation is easily seen in the various senses of a single English word such as bulL 12 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK I. perhaps be well to leave this subject for the present, as an exact discussion of it would belong rather to a diflFerent branch of philosophy. But the same is true of the idea ; for even if there is some one good which is predicated of all these things, or some abstract and absolute good, it will plainly not be such as a man finds practicable and attainable, and therefore will not be such a good as we are in search of. It will possibly be held, however, that it is worth while to apprehend this universal good, as having a relation to the goods which are attainable and practicable ; for if we have this as a model, we shall be better able to know the things which are good relatively to ourselves, and, knowing them, to acquire them. Now although there is a certain plausibility in this theory, it seems not to harmonize with scientific experience ; for while all sciences aim at a certain good and seek to supply a deficiency, they omit the knowledge of the universal good. Yet it is not reasonable to suppose that what would be so extremely helpful is ignored, and not sought at all by artists generally. But it is difiicult to see what benefit a cobbler or carpenter will get in reference to his art by knowing the absolute good, or how the contemplation of the absolute idea will make a person a better physician or general. For it appears that a physician does not regard health abstractedly, but regards the health of man or rather perhaps of a particular man, as he gives his medicine to individuals. Chap.v. But leaving this subject for the present let us Nature of j.xj.i i/.i.i . theprac- revcrt to the good ot which we are in quest and good!* consider what its nature may be. For it is clearly CHAP, v.] OF AKISTOTLE. 13 diflFerent in different actions or arts ; it is one thing in medicine, another in strategy, and so on. What then is the good in each of these instances ? It is presumably that for the sake of which all else is done. This in medicine is health, in strategy, victory, in domestic architectxire, a house, and so on. But in every action and purpose it is the end, as it is for the sake of the end that people all do everything else. If then there is a certain end of all action, it will be this which is the practicable good, and if there are several such ends it wiU be these. Our argument has arrived by a different path at the same conclusion as before ; but we must endea- vour to elucidate it still further. As it appears that there are more ends than one and some of these, e.g. wealth, flutes, and instruments generally we desire as means to something else, it is evident that they are not all final ends. But the highest good is clearly something final Hence if there is only one final end. Final good. this will be the object of which we are in search, and if there are more than one, it will be the most final of them. We speak of that which is sought after for its own sake as more final than that which is sought after as a means to something else ; we speak of that which is never desired as a means to something else as more final than the things which are desired both in themselves and as means to something else ; and we speak of a thing as absolutely final, if it is always desired in itself and never as a means to something else. It seems that happiness preeminently answers to Happiness 14 THE NICOMACHBAN ETHICS [BOOK I. the final this description, as we always desire happiness for its ^°° ' own sake and never as a means to something else, whereas we desire honour, pleasure, intellect, and every virtue, partly for their own sakes (for we should desire them independently of what might result from them) but partly also as being means to happiness, because we suppose they will prove the instruments of happiness. Happiness, on the other hand, nobody desires for the sake of these things, nor indeed as a means to anything else at all. We come to the same conclusion if we start from the consideration of self-sufficiency, if it may be assumed that the final good is self-sufficient. But when we speak of self-sufficiency, we do not mean that a person leads a solitary life all by himself, but that he has parents, children, wife, and friends, and fellow-citizens in general, as man is naturally a social being. But here it is necessary to prescribe some limit ; for if the circle be extended so as to include parents, descendants, and friends' friends, it will go on indefinitely. Leaving this point, however, for future investigation, we define the self-sufficient as that which, taken by itself, makes life desirable, and wholly free from want, and this is our conception of happiness. Again, we conceive happiness to be the most desirable of all things, and that not merely as one among other good things. If it were one among other good things, the addition of the smallest good would increase its desirableness ; for the accession makes a superiority of goods, and the greater of CHAP. VI. J OF ARISTOTLE. 15 two goods is always the more desirable. It appears then that happiness is something final and self- sufficient, being the end of all action. Perhaps, however, it seems a truth which is Chap. vi. generally admitted, that happiness is the supreme good ; what is wanted is to define its nature a little Nature of more clearly. The best way of arriving at such a'^^^^*"^'^- definition will probably be to ascertain the function of Man. For, as with a flute-player, a statuary, or any artisan, or in fact anybody who has a definite function and action, his goodness, or excellence seems to lie in his function, so it would seem to be with Man, if indeed he has a definite function. Can it be said then that, while a carpenter and a cobbler have definite functions and actions, Man, unlike them, is naturally functionless ? The reasonable view is that, as the eye, the hand, the foot, and similarly each several part of the body has a definite function, so Man may be regarded as having a definite function apart from all these. What then, can this function be ? It is not life ; for life is apparently something which man shares with the plants ; and it is some- thing peculiar to him that we are looking for. We must exclude therefore the life of nutrition and increase. There is next what may be called the life of sensation. But this too, is apparently shared by Man with horses, cattle, and aU other animals. There remains what I may call the practical life of the rational part of Man's being. But the rational part is twofold ; it is rational partly in the sense of being obedient to reason, and partly in the sense of possess- ing reason and intelligence. The practical life too 16 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS fBOOK I. \'>^'^ may be conceived of in two ways', viz., either as a moral state, or as a moral activity: but we must understand by it the life of activity, as this seems to be the truer form of the conception. ^"notion The function of Man then is an activity of soul in accordance with reason, or not independently of reason. Again the functions of a person of a certain kind, and of such a person who is good of his kind e.g. of a harpist and a good harpist, are in our view generically the same, and this view is true of people of all kinds without exception, the superior excellence being only an addition to the function ; for it is the function of a harpist to play the harp, and of a good harpist to play the harp well. This being so, if we define the function of Man as a kind of life, and this life as an activity of soul, or a course of action in conformity with reason, if the function of a good man is such activity or action of a good and noble kind, and if everything is successfully performed when it is performed in accordance with its proper excellence, Definition it foUows that the good of Man is an activity of soul of Man °° in accordance with virtue or, if there are more virtues than one, in accordance with the best and most complete virtue. But it is necessary to add the words "in a complete life.'' For as one swallow or one day does not make a spring, so one day or a short time does not make a fortunate or happy man. Chap. VII. This may be taken as a sufficiently accurate sketch of the good; for it is right, I think, to draw the ' In other words life may be taken to mean either the mere possession of certain faculties or their active exercise. CHAP. VII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 17 outlines first and afterwards to fill in the details. It would seem that anybody can carry on and complete what has been sati^actorily sketched in outline, and that time is a good inventor or cooperator in so doing. This is the way in which the arts have made their advances, as anybody can supply a deficiency. But bearing in mind what has been already said. Degree of we must not look for the same degree of accuracy in attainable all subjects; we must be content in each class of™ '^' subjects with accuracy of such a kind as the subject- matter allows, and to such an extent as is proper to the inquiry. For while a carpenter and a geometri- cian both want to find a right angle, they do not want to find it in the same sense ; the one wants only such an approximation to it as will serve his practical pur- pose, the other, as being concerned with truth, wants to know its nature or character. We must follow the same course in other subjects, or we shall sacrifice the main points to such as are subordinate. Again, we must not insist with equal emphasis in all sub- jects upon ascertaining the reason of things. We must sometimes e.g. in dealing with first principles be content with the proper evidence of a fact ; the fact itself is a first point or principle! But there are various ways of discovering first principles ; some are discovered by induction, others hy perception, others by what maybe called habituation, and so on. We must try to apprehend them all in the natural or appropriate way, and must take pains to define them satisfactorily, as they have a vital influence upon all that follows from them. For it seems that the first w. N. E. 2 18 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK I. principle or beginning is more than half the whole, and is the means of arriving at a clear conception of many points which are under investigation. CHAP.vni. In considering the first principle we must pay regard not only to the conclusion and the premisses of our argument, but also to such views as are popularly held about it. For while all experience harmonizes with the truth, it is never long before truth clashes with falsehood. ciassifica- Goods havc been divided into three classes, viz. goods! external goods as they are called, goods of the soul and goods of the body. Of these three classes we consider the goods of the soul to be goods in the strictest or most literal sense. But it is to the soul that we ascribe psychicaP actions and activities. Thus our definition is a good one, at least according to this theory, which is not only ancient but is accepted by students of philosophy at the present time. It is right too, inasmuch as certain actions and activities are said to be the end ; for thus it appears that the end is some good of the soul and not an external good. It is in harmony with this definition that the happy man should live well and do well, as p. 5. happiness, it has been said, is in fact a kind of living and doing well. ' Chap. IX. It appears too that the requisite characteristics of happiness are all contained in the definition ; for some people hold that happiness is virtue, others that it is 1 In allusion to the adage apxv ^jutmi iravros, in which however apxr) means " beginning." 2 It is a pity that the English language does not possess a word which stands to "soul" in the relation of i/fux"«>s to V'«X'7- CHAP. IX.] OF AHISTOTLE. 19 prudence', others that it is wisdom of some kind, Concep- others that it is these things or one of them conjoined happiness. with pleasure or not dissociated from pleasm-e, others again include external prosperity. Some of these views are held by many ancient thinkers, others by a few thinkers of high repute. It is probable that neither side is altogether wrong, but that in some one point; if not in most points, they are both right. Now the definition is in harmony with the view of Happiness those who hold that happiness is virtue or excellence preme of some sort ; for activity in accordance Avith virtue ^°°* implies vii-tue. But it would seem that there is a considerable diflFerence between taking the supreme good to consist in acquisition or in use, in a moral state or in an activity. For a moral state, although it exists, may produce nothing good, e.g. if a person is asleep, or has in any other way become inactive. But this cannot be the case with an activity, as activity implies action and good action. As in the Olympian games it is not the most beautiful and strongest persons who receive the crown but they who actually enter the lists as combatants — for it is some of these who become victors — so it is they who act rightly that attain to what is noble and good in life. Again, their life is pleasant in itself. For pleasure is a psychical fact, and whatever a man is said to be fond of is pleasant to him, e.g. a horse to one who is fond of horses, a spectacle to one who is fond ^ The difference between p6vT]a-is " prudence " or " practical wisdom" and ia "speculative" or "theoretical wisdom'' is commonly assumed by Aristotle. 2—2 20 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK I. of spectacles, and similarly just actions to a lover of justice, and virtuous actions in general io a lover of virtue. Now most men find a sense of discord in their pleasures, because their pleasures are not such as are naturally pleasant. But to the lovers of nobleness natural pleasures are pleasant. It is actions in accordance with virtue that are naturally pleasant. Such actions then are pleasant both relatively to these persons and in themselves. JN'or does their life meed that pleasure should be attached to it as a sort of amulet ; it possesses pleasure in itself. For it may be added that a person is not good, if he does not take delight in noble actions, as nobody would call a person just if he did not take delight in just actions, or liberal if he did not take delight in liberal aetiojiB, and so on. But if this is so, it follows that actions m accordance with virtue are pleasant in themselves. But they are also good and noble, and good and noble in the highest degree, if the judgment of the virtuous man upon them is right, his judgment being such as we have described. Happiness then is the best and noblest and pleasantest thing in the world, nor is there any such distinction between goodness, nobleness, and pleasure as the epigram at Delos suggests: " Justice is nablest, Health is best, To gain one?s end is pleasantest." iFor these are all essential characteristics of the best activities, and we hold that happiness consists in these or in one and the noblest of these. StiU it is clear that happiness requires the addition of external p. 19. goods, as we said ; for it is impossible, or at least CHAP. X.] OF ARISTOTLE. 21 diflBcult for a person to do what is noble unless he is famished with, external means. For there are many things which can only be done through the instru- mentality of friends or wealth or political power, and there are some things the lack of which must mar felicity, e.g. noble birth, a prosperous fiimily, and personal beauty. For a person is incapable of happi- ness if he is absolutely ugly in appearance, or low born, or solitary and childless, and perhaps still more so, if he has exceedingly bad children or friends, or has had good children or friends and has lost them by death. As we said, then, it seems that prosperity of this kind is an indispensable addition to virtue. It is for this reason that some persons identify good fortune, and others virtue, with happiness. The question is consequently raised whether hap- Chap. x. piness is something that can be learnt or acquired by ^™ ^l^^^' habit or discipline of any other kind, or whether it leamt or comes by some divine dispensation or even by chance. Now if there is anything in the world that is a Happiness gift of the Gods to men, it is reasonable to suppose the Gods, that happiness is a divine gift, especially as it is the best of human things. This however is perhaps a point which is more appropriate to another investigar tion than the present. But even if happiness is not sent by the Gods but is the result of virtue and of learning or discipline of some kind, it is apparently one of the most divine things in the world ; for it would appear that that which is the prize and end of virtue is the supreme good and is in its nature divine and Messed. It will also be widely extended ,- for it will be capable of being produced in all persons. 22 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK I. except such as are morally deformed, by a process of study or care. And if it is better that happiness should be produced in this way than by chance, it may reasonably be supposed that it is so produced, as the order of things is the best possible in Nature and so too in art, and in causation generally, and most of all in the highest kind of causation. But it would be altogether inconsistent to leave what is greatest and noblest to chance. But the definition oj happiness itself helps to clear up the question ; for happiness has been defined as a certain kind of activity of the soul in accordance with virtue. Of the other goods, i.e. of goods besides those of the soul, some are necessary as antecedent conditions of happiness, others are in their nature co-operative and service- able as instruments of happiness. The conclusion at which we have arrived agrees with our original position. For we laid it down that the end of political science is the supreme good ; and Object of political science is concerned Avith nothing so much science, as with producing a certain character in the citizens, or in other words with making them good, and Animals, capable of performing noble actions. It is reasonable young, then not to speak of an ox, or a horse, or any other oThappi* animal as happy ; for none of them is capable of ness. participating in activity as so defined. For the same reason no child can be happy, as the age of a child makes it impossible for him to display this activity at present, and if a child is ever said to be happy, the ground of the felicitation is his promise, rather than his actual performamce. For happiness demands, as p. 16. we said, a complete virtue and a complete life. For CHAP. XI.] OF ARISTOTLE. 23 there are all sorts of changes and chances in life, and it is possible that the most prosperous of men will, in his old age, fall into extreme calamities as is told of Priam in the heroic legends. But if a person has experienced such chances, and has died a miserable death, nobody calls him happy. Is it the case then that nobody in the world may Chap. xi. be called happy so long as he is alive ? Must we fe/s^ be adopt Solon's^ rule of looking to the end ? and, if we ^^ . follow Solon, can it be said that a man is really happy Ws ufe- after his death ? Surely such a view is wholly absurd, ""*" especially for us who define happiness as a species of activity. But if we do not speak of one who is dead as happy, and if Solon's meaning is not this but rather that it is only when a man is dead that it is safe to call him fortunate as being exempt at last from evils and calamities, this again is a view which is open to some objection. For it seems that one who is dead is capable of being affected both by good and by evil in the same way as one who is living but unconscious, e.g. by honours and dishonours and by the successes or reverses of his children and his de- scendants generally. But here again a difficulty occurs. For if a person has lived a fortunate life up to old age, and has died a fortunate death, it is possible that he may experience many vicissitudes of fortune in the persons of his descendants. Some of them may be good and may enjoy such a life as they deserve ; others may be bad and may have a bad life. ^ Herodotus i. ch. 32 is the authority for the celebrated warning which Solon is said to have addressed to Croesus. 24 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [BOOK I. It is clear, too, that descendants may stand in all sorts of different degrees of relationship to thehr ancestor. It would be an extraordinary result, if the dead man were to share the vicissitudes of their fortune and to become happy at one time and miser- able at another, as they became either happy or miserable. But it would be equally extraordinary, if the future of descendants should not affect their parents at all or for a certain time. It will be best, however, to revert to the difficulty which was raised before, as it will perhaps afford an answer to the present question. If it is right to look to the end, and when the end comes to felicitate a person not as being fortunate but as having been so before, surely it is an extraordinary thing that at the time when he is happy we should not speak the truth about him, because we do not wish to call the living happy in view of the vicissitudes to which they are liable and because we have formed a conception of happiness as something that is permanent and exempt from the possibility of change and because the same persons are liable to many revolutions of fortune. For it is clear that, if we follow the changes of fortune, we shall often call the same person happy at one time, and miserable at another, representing the happy man as " a* sort of chameleon without any stability of position," It cannot be right to follow the changes of fortune. It is not upon these that good or evil depends ; they are necessary accessories of human p. 20. life, as we said ; but it is a man's activities in accord- ^ Apparently an Iambic line. CHAP. XI.j OF ARISTOTLE. 25 ance with virtae that constitute his happiness and the opposite activities that constitute his misery. The difficulty which has now been discussed is itself a witness that this is the true view. For there is no human function so constant as the activities in ac- Constancy cordance with virtue ; they seem to be more perma- virtnous nent than the sciences themselves. Among these *''**"''*^' activities, too, it is the most hcHiourable which are the most permanent, as it is in them that the life of the fortunate chiefly and most continuously consists. For this is apparently the reason why such activities are not liable to be forgotten'. The element of permanency which is required will be found in the happy man, and he will preserve his character throughout life ; for he will constantly or in a preeminent degree pursue such actions and speculations as accord with virtue ; nor is there any- body who will bear the chances of life so nobly, with such a perfect and complete harmony, as he who is truly good and "foursquare without a flaw'." Now 1 Aristotle means that it is comparatively easy to forget scientific truths, when they have once been learnt, but it is difficult, if not impossible, to lose the habit of virtuous activity. In other words, he means that knowledge is less stable, and therefore less valuable, than character. ' The phrase "foursquare without a flaw" is taken from Simonides, as Plato says in his Protagoras p. 339, b, where the passage in which the phrase occurs is quoted at length. Cp. Rhetoric m. ch. 11 p. 1411 'R^. In a similar, but not identical sense a modem poet speaks of the great Duke of Wellington as "that tower of strength Which stood foursquare to all the winds that blew." 26 THE NICOMACHBAN ETHICS [bOOK I. the events of chance are numerous and of diflPerent magnitudes. It is clear then that small incidents of good fortune, or the reverse, do not turn the scale of life, but that such incidents as are great and nume- rous augment the felicity of Ufe, if they are fortunate, as they tend naturally to embellish it and the use of them is noble and virtuous, and on the other hand, if they are of a contrary character, mar and mutilate its felicity by causing pains and hindrances to various activities. Still even in these circumstances nobility shines out, when a person bears the weight of accu- mulated misfortunes with calmness, not from insensi- bility but from innate dignity and magnanimity. The happy But if it is the activities which determine the capable of life, as wc Said, nobody who is fortunate can become ™^7' miserable ; for he will never do what is hateful and mean. For our conception of the truly good and sensible man is that he bears all the chances of life with decorum and always does what is noblest in the circumstances, as a good general uses the forces at his command to the best advantage in war, a good cobbler makes the best shoe with the leather that is given him, and so on through the whole series of the arts. If this is so, it follows that the happy man can never become miserable; I do not say that he will be fortunate, if he meets such chances of life as Priam. Yet he will not be variable or liable to frequent change, as he will not be moved from his happi- ness easily or by ordinary misfortunes but only by such misfortunes as are great and numerous ; and after them it will not be soon that he will regain his happiness, but, if he regains it at all, it will be only in CHAP. XI.] OF ARISTOTLE. 27 a long and complete period of time and after attain- ing in it to great and noble results. We may safely then define a happy man as one Definition whose activity accords with perfect virtue and who is nesa.^^' adequately furnished with external goods, not for a casual period of time but for a complete or perfect lifetime. But perhaps we ought to add, tliat he wiU always live so, and wiU die as he lives ; for it is not given us to foresee the future, but we take happiness to be an end, and to be altogether perfect and complete, and, this being so, we shall call people fortunate during their lifetime, if they possess and wiU possess these characteristics, but fortunate only so far as men may be fortunate. But to leave the discussion of this subject : The The idea that the fortunes of one's descendants and oftheSing* one's friends generally have no influence at all upon thg^^ead"^ oneself seems exceedingly harsh, and contrary to received opinions. But as the events of life are numerous and present all sorts of difierences, and some are of more concern to us than others, it would be clearly a long, if not an infinite task, to define them individually; we must, I think, be content to describe them generally and in outline. Now, as in personal misfortunes some have a certain weight and influence upon our life, and others, it seems, are comparatively light, so it is with such misfortunes as affect our friends generally. But as the difference between the experiences of the living or the dead is far greater than the difference between terrible crimes when enacted upon the stage in tragedies and the same crimes when merely assumed to have already 28 THE inCOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK I. occurred, it is necessary" to take account of this difference also, and still more perhaps of the serious doubt which has been raised as to the participation of the dead in any good or evil. For it is probable in this view that if anything, whether good or evil, reaches the dead at all, it is feeble and insignificant, either absolutely, or in relation to them, or if not, is of such a magnitude and character as to be incapable of making people happy if they are not happy or of depriving them of their felicity, if they are. It would seem then that the dead are affected or influenced in some way by the prosperity and the adversity of their iriends, but that the influence is of such a kind and degree as not to make people happy, if they are not happy, nor to have any similar effect. Chap. xh. Having determined these points, let us consider ness"'^"' whether happiness belongs rather to such things as object of are objects of praise or to such things as are obiects praise or of . . , , honour? of honour. Jcor it IS clearly not a mere potential good. It appears that whatever is an object of praise is praised as possessing a certain character, and standing in a certain relation to something. For we praise one who is just and manly and good in any way,, or we praise virtue, because of their actions and pro- ductions. We praise one who is strong and swift and so on, as naturally possessing a certain character and standing in a certain relation to something that is itself good and estiinable. The truth of this statement becomes clear, if we take the case of praises bestowed upon the Gods. Such praise appears ridiculous as implying a reference to ourselves, and there must be CHAP. XII.J OF AUISTOTLE. 29 such a reference, because, as we said, praise invariaMy implies a reference to a higher standard. But if this is the nature of praise, it is clear that it is not praise but something greater and better which is a,x^opriate to all that is best, as indeed is evident ; for we speak of the Gods as "blessed" and "happy" rather than as "praiseworthy" and we speak of the most godlike men as "blessed." It is the same with goods ; for nobody praises happiness as he praises justice, but he calls it blessed, as being in its nature better and more divine. It is sometimes held on these grounds that Eudoxus' was right in advocating the supremacy of pleasure ; for the fact that pleasure is a good and yet is not praised, indicates, as he thought, that it is higher than the objects of praise, as God and the good are higher, these being the standards to which everything else is referred. For praises* are appro- priate to virtue, as it is virtue which makes us capable of noble deeds ; but panegyrics to accomplished re- sults, whether they be results of the body or of the souL But it may be said that an exact discussion of these points belongs more properly to the special study of panegyrics. We see clearly, however, from what has been said, that happiness is something ^ A pupil of Plato, whose personal character is favourably noticed by Aristotle in Book x. ch. 2. He was an astronomer as well as a philosopher. 2 The distinction between the e|is of virtue as deserving praise (ormwos) and the tpyov as deserving panegyric {iyiwiuov) which is drawn out in the Rhetoric Book m. ch 9 is introduced a little awkwardly here, where the point is that virtue, as being a subject of praise, was in the Budoxian view inferior to pleasure. 30 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS ,[bOOK I. honourable and final. And that it is so seems to follow also from the fact that it is a first principle ; for it is for the sake of happiness that we all do everything else, and the first principle or the cause of all that is good we regard as something honourable and divine. CHAP.xni. Inasmuch as happiness is an activity of soul in J^^'Jgj^gjjj accordance with complete or perfect virtue, it is ofhappi- necessary to consider virtue, as this will perhaps be the best way of studying happiness. It appears that virtue is the object upon which the true statesman has expended the largest amount of trouble, as it is his wish to make the citizens virtuous and obedient to the laws. We have instances of such statesmen in the legislators of Crete and Lacedaemon and such other legislators as have re- sembled them. But if this inquiry is proper to political science, it will clearly accord with our original purpose to pursue it. But it is clear that it is human virtue which we have to consider ; for the good of p. 16. which we are in search is, as we said, human good, and the happiness, human happiness. By human virtue or excellence we mean not that of the body, but that of the soul, and by happiness we mean an activity of the soul. Import- If this is so, it is clearly necessary for statesmen psyohoiogy to have some knowledge of the nature of the soul in statolman. ^^^ ^^^ '^^J ^ ^* i® uecessary for one who is to treat the eye or any part of the body, to have some knowledge of it, and all the more as political science is better and more honourable than medical science. Clever doctors take a great deal of trouble to under- CHAP. XIII.] OF AMSTOTLE. 31 stand the body, and similarly the statesman must make a study of the soul. But he must study it with a view to his particular object and so far only as his object requires ; for to elaborate the study of it further would, I think, be to aggravate undidy the labour of our present undertaking. There are some facts concerning the soul which are adequately stated in the popular or exoterical discourses, and these we may rightly adopt. It is Analysis of stated e.g. that the soul has two parts, one irrational and the other possessing reason. But whether these parts are distinguished like the parts of the body and like everything that is itself divisible, or whether they are theoretically distinct, but in fact inseparable, as convex and concave in the circumference of a circle, is of no importance to the present inquiry. Again, it seems that of the irrational part of the soul one part is common, i.e. shared by man with all living things, and vegetative ; I mean the part which is the cause of nutrition and increase. For we may assume such a faculty of the soul to exist in all things that receive nutrition, even in embryos, and the same faculty to exist in things that are full grown, as it is more reasonable to suppose that it is the same faculty than that it is different. It is clear then that the virtue or excellence of this faculty is not distinc- tively human but is shared by man with aU living things ; for it seems that this part and this faculty are especially active in sleep, whereas good and bad people are never so little distinguishable as in sleep — whence the saying that there is no difference between the happy and the misei-able during half their life- 32 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [BOOK I. time. And this is only natural ; for sleep is an inactivity of the soul in respect of its virtue or vice, except in so far as certain impulses affect it to a slight extent, and make the visions of the virtuous better than those of ordinary people. But enough has been said on this point, and we must now leave the principle of nutrition, as it possesses no natural share in human virtue. It seems that there is another natural principle of the soul which is irrational and yet in a sense partakes of reason. For in a continent or incontinent person we praise the reason, and that part of the soul which possesses reason, as it exhorts men rightly and exhorts them to the best conduct. But it is clear that there is in them another principle which is naturally different from reason and fights and contends against reason. For just as the paralysed parts of the body, when we iatend to move them to the right, are drawn away in a contrary direction to the left, so it is with the soul ; the impulses of incontinent people run counter to reason. But there is this difference, however, that while in the body we see the part which is drawn astray, in the soul we do not see it. But it is probaibly right to suppose with equal certainty that there is in the soul too something different from reason, which opposes and thwarts it, although the sense in which it is distinct from reason is immaterial. But it appears that this part too par- takes of reason, as we said ; at all events in a con- tinent person it obeys reason, while in a temperate or courageous person it is probably still more obedient, as being absolutely harmonious with reason. CHAP. XIII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 33 It appears then that the irrational part of the soul is itself twofold ; for the vegetative faculty does not participate at all in reason, but the fikculty of desire or general concupiscence participates in it more or less, in so far as it is submissive and obedient to reason. But it is obedient in the sense in which we speak of "paying attention to a father" or "to Mends," but not in the sense in which we speak of "paying attention to mathematics." All correction, rebuke and exhortation is a witness that the irra- tional part of the soul is in a sense subject to the influence of reason. But if we are to say that this part 'too possesses reason, then the part which possesses reason will have two divisions, one possess- ing reason absolutely and in itself, the other listening to it as a child listens to its father. Virtue or excellence again, admits of a distinction which depends on this diflerence. For we speak of some virtues as intellectual and of others as moral, inteUectnai wisdom, intelligence and prudence, being intellectual, ^tiJ^"^*^ liberality and temperance being moral, virtues. For when we describe a person's character, we do not say that he is wise or intelligent but that he is gentle or temperate. Yet we praise a wise man too in respect of his mental state, and such mental states as deserve to be praised we call virtuous. W. ST. E. BOOK II. Chap. I. ViKTUB OF excellence being twofold, partly intellec- tual and partly moral, intellectual virtue is both originated and fostered mainly by teaching; it Genesis therefore demands experience and time. Moral* viiS'e™' virtue on the other hand is the outcome of habit, and accordingly its name {■^diKtj dpert]) is derived by a slight deflexion from habit (e6o^)\ From this fact it is clear that no moral virtue is implanted in us by nature; a law of nature cannot be altered by habituation. Thus a stone naturally tends to fall downwards, and it cannot be habituated or trained to rise upwards, even if we were to habituate it by throwing it upwards ten thousand times ; nor again can fire be trained to sink downwards, nor anything else that follows one natural law be habituated or trained to follow another. It is neither by nature then nor in defiance of nature that virtues are im- 1 The student of Aristotle must familiarize himself with the conception of intellectual as well as of moral virtues, although it is not the rule in modem philosophy to speak of the " virtues " of the intellect. ' The approximation of Wos (habit) and ^5or (character) cannot be represented in English. CHAP. I.] NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. 35 planted in us. Nature gives us the capacity of re- ceiving them, and that capacity is perfected by habit. Again, if we take the various natural powers which belong to us, we first acquire the proper faculties and afterwards display the activities. It is clearly so with the senses. It was not by seeing frequently or hearing frequently that we acquired the senses of seeing or hearing ; on the contrary it was because we possessed the senses that we made use of them, not by making use of them that we obtained them. But the virtues we acquire by first exercising them, as is the case with all the arts, for it is by doing what we ought to do when we have learnt the arts that we learn the arts themselves ; we become e.g. builders by building and harpists by playing the harp. Simi- larly it is by doing just acts that we become just, by doing temperate acts that Ave become temperate, by doing courageous acts that we become courageous. The experience of states is a witness to this truth, for it is by training the habits that legislators make the citizens good. This is the object which all legislators have at heart ; if a legislator does not succeed in it, he fails of his purpose, and it constitutes the distinc- tion between a good polity and a bad one. Again, the causes and means by which any virtue is produced and by which it is destroyed are the same ; and it is equally so with any art ; for it is by playing the harp that both good and bad harpists are produced and the case of builders and all other a/rtisans is similar, as it is by building well that they will be good builders and by building badly that they win be bad builders. If it were not so, there would 3—2 36 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK II. be no need of anybody to teach them ; they would all be born good or bad in their several trades. The case of the virtues is the same. It is by acting in such transactions as take place between man and man that we become either just or unjust. It is by acting in the face of danger and by habituating ourselves to fear or courage that we become either cowardly or courageous. It is much the same with our desires and angry passions. Some people become temperate and gentle, others become licentious and passionate, according as they conduct themselves in one way or another way in particular circumstances. In a word moral states are the residts of activities corre- sponding to the moral states themselves. It is our duty therefore to give a certain character to the activities, as the moral states depend upon the differences of the activities. Accordingly the differ- ence between one training of the habits and another from early days is not a light matter, but is serious or rather all-important. Chap. n. Our present study is not, like other studies', inducing purely speculative, in its intention; for the object of to virtue, our enquiry is not to know the nature of virtue but to become ourselves virtuous, as that is the sole benefit which it conveys. It is necessary therefore to consider the right way of performing actions, for it is p. 35. actions as we have said that determine the character of the resulting moral states. That we should act in accordance with right I i.e. such studies as generally occupied the attention of the Aristotelian school. CHAP, II.J OF ARISTOTLE. 37 reason is a common general principle, ■which may here be taken for granted. The nature of right reason, and its relation to the virtues generally, will be subjects of discussion hereafter. But it must be admitted at the outset that all reasoning upon practi- cal matters must be like a sketch in outline, it cannot be scientifically exact. We began by laying down the Scientific principle that the kind of reasoning demanded in any impossible. subject must be such as the subject-matter itself allows ; and questions of practice and expediency no more admit of invariable rules than questions of health. But if this is true of general reasoning m^otc Ethics, still more true is it that scientific exactitude is impossible in reasoning upon particular ethical cases. They do not fall umder any art or any law, but the agents themselves are always bound to pay regard to the circumstances of the moment as much as in medicine or navigation. Still, although such is the nature of the present argument, we must try to make the best of it. The first point to be observed then is that in such matters as we are considering deficiency and excess Deficiency are equally fatal. It is so, as we observe, in regard both?aTaL to health and strength ; for we must judge of what we cannot see by the evidence of what we do see. Excess or deficiency of gymnastic exercise is fatal to strength. Similarly an excess or deficiency of meat and drink is fatal to health, whereas a suitable amount produces, augments and sustains it. It is the same then with temperance, courage, and the other virtues. A person who avoids and is afi:aid of every- 38 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK II. thing and faces nothing becomes a coward ; a person who is not afraid of anything but is ready to face everything becomes foolhardy. Similarly he who enjoys every pleasure and never abstains from any pleasure is licentious ; he who eschews all pleasures like a boor is an insensible sort of person. For temperance and courage are destroyed by excess and deficiency but preserved by the mean state. Again, not only are the causes and the agencies of production, increase and destruction in the moral states the same, but the sphere of their activity will be proved to be the same also. It is so in other instances which are more conspicuous, e.g. in strength ; for strength is produced by taking a great deal of food and undergoing a great deal of labour, and it is the strong man who is able to take most food and to undergo most labour. The same is the case with the virtues. It is by abstinence from pleasures that we become temperate, and, when we have become temperate, we are best able to abstain from them. So too with courage; it is by habituating ourselves to despise and face alarms that we become coura- geous, and, when we have become courageous, we shall be best able to face them. The pleasure or pain which follows upon actions may be regarded as a test of a person's moral state. He who abstains from physical pleasures and feels delight in so doing is temperate ; but he who feels pain at so doing is hcei3!te»8L^IIe who faces dangers with pleasure, or at least withompiin, is courageous ; Virtue in but he who feels pain at facir^them is a coward. relation to _ i • ^ t -, . , '^""^^a. pleasures *or moral Virtue is concerned with pleasures and and pains. CHAP. II.] OF ARISTOTLE. 39 pains. It is pleasure which makes us do what is base, and pain which makes us abstain from doing what is noble. Hence the importance of having had a certain training from very early days, as Plato' says, such a training as produces pleasure and pain at the right objects ; for this is the true education. Again, if the virtues are concerned with actions and emotions, and every action and every emotion is attended by pleasure and pain, this will be another reason why virtue should be concerned with pleasures and pains. There is also a proof of this fact in the use of pleasure and pain as means of punishment ; for pimishments are in a sense remedial measures, and the means employed as remedies are naturally the opposites of the diseases to which they are applied, p- 35. Again, as we said before, every moral state of the soul is in its nature relative to, and concerned with, the thing by which it is naturally made better or worse. But it is pleasures and pains which produce vicious moral states, if we pursue and avoid such pleasures and pains as are wrong, or pursue and avoid them at the wrong time or in the wrong manner, or in any other of the various ways in which it is logically possible to do wrong. Hence it is that people^ actually define the virtues as certain apathe- tic or quiescent states ; but they are wrong in using this absolute language, and not qualifying it by the addition of the right or wrong manner, time and so on. It may be assumed then that moral virtue tends ^ Laws II. p. 653 A — c. ' As e.g. the Cyiiics. 40 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK II. to produce the best action in respect of pleasures and pains, and that vice is its opposite. But there is another way in which we may see the same truth. There are three things which influence us to desire them, viz. the noble', the expedient, and the pleasant; and three opposite things which influence us to eschew them, viz. the shameful, the injurious, and the painful. The good man then will be likely to take a right line, and the bad man to take a wrong one, in respect of all these, but especially in respect of pleasure ; for pleasure is felt not by Man only but by the lower animals, and is associated with all things that are matters of desire, as the noble and the expedient alike appear pleasant. Pleasure too is fostered in us all from early childhood, so that it is difficult to get rid of the emotion of pleasure, as it is deeply ingrain- ed in our life. Again, we make pleasure and pain in a greater or less degree the standard of our actions. It is inevitable therefore that our present study should be concerned from first to last with pleasures and pains ; for right or wrong feelings of pleasure or pain have a material influence upon actions. Again, it is more difiicult to contend against pleasure than against anger, as Heraclitus' says, and it is not what is easy but what is comparatively difficult that 1 It must be remembered that to koKSv and to alaxpov may mean "the beautiful" and "the ugly" as well aa "the noble'' and the "shameful," but it is the moral meaning which preponderates here. 2 The saying of Heraclitus, as given in Eudem. Eth. XL 7, p. 1223 B23, is simply ^^aXeirov Bvy,^ iidxetrBat' i/fux^s yap ave'irai, the last words meaning that a person will gratify his anger even at the risk of his life. CHAP, in.] OF ARISTOTLE. 41 is in all cases the sphere of art or Tirtue, as the value of success is proportionate to the diflSculty. This then is another reason why moral virtue and political science should be exclusively occupied with pleasures and pains ; for to make a good use of pleasures and pains is to be a good man, and to make a bad use of them is to be a bad man. We may regard it then as established that virtue is concerned with pleasures and pains, that the causes which produce it are also the means by which it is augmented, or, if they assume a different character, is destroyed, and that the sphere of its activity is the things which were themselves the causes of its production. But it may be asked what we mean by saying that Chap. m. people must become just by doing what is just and ^°™^f*"' temperate by doing what ia temperate. For if they virtues ana do what is just and temperate, they are ipso facto proved, it will be said, to be just and temperate in the same way as, if they practise grammar and music, they are proved to be grammarians and musicians. But is not the answer that the case of the arts is not the same? For a person may do something that is grammatical either by chance or at the sug- gestion of somebody else ; hence he will not be a grammarian unless he not only does what is gram- matical but does it in a grammatical manner, i.e. in virtue of the grammatical knowledge which he possesses. There is another point too of difference between the arts and the virtues. The productions of art have their excellence in themselves. It is enough 42 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK II. therefore that, -when they are produced, they should be of a certain character. But actions in accordance with virtue are not e.g. justly or temperately per- formed because they are in themselves just or temperate. It is necessary that the agent at the time of performing them should satisfy certain conditions, i.e. in the first place that he should know what he is doing, secondly that he should deliberately choose to do it and to do it for its own sake, and thirdly that he should do it as an instance of a settled and immutable moral state. If it be a question whether a person possesses any art, these conditions, except indeed the condition of knowledge, are not taken into account ; but if it be a question of possessing the virtues, the mere knowledge is of little or no avail, and it is the other conditions, which are the results of frequently performing just and tempe- rate actions, that are not of slight but of absolute importance. Accordingly deeds are said to be just and temperate, when they are such as a just or temperate person would do, and a just and temperate person is not merely one who does these deeds but one who does them in the spirit of the just and the temperate. It may fairly be said then that a just man becomes just by doing what is just and a temperate man becomes temperate by doing what is temperate, and if a man did not so act, he would not have so much as a chance of becoming good. But most people, instead of doing such actions, take refuge in theorizing; they imagine that they are philosophers and that philo- sophy will make them virtuous ; in fact they behave CHAP. IV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 43 like people who listen attentively to their doctors but never do anything that their doctors tell them. But it is as improbable that a healthy state of the soul will be produced by this kind of philosophizing as that a healthy state of the body will be produced by this kind of medical treatment. We have next to consider the nature of virtue. Chap. rv. Now, as the qualities of the soul are three, viz. ^emoy°n emotions, faculties and moral states, it follows that nor* virtue must be one of the three. By the emotions a moral I mean desire, anger, fear, courage, envy, joy, love, ^^^' hatred, regret, emulation, pity, in a word whatever is attended by pleasure or pain. I call those faculties in respect of which we are said to be capable of experiencing these emotions, e.g. capable of getting angry or being pained or feeling pity. And I call those moral states in respect of which we are well or ill disposed towards the emotions, ill-disposed e.g. towards the passion of anger, if our anger be too violent or too feeble, and well-disposed, if it be duly moderated, and similarly towards the other emotions. 'Now neither the virtues nor the vices are emotions ; for we are not called good or evil in respect of our emotions but in respect of our virtues or vices. Again, we are not praised or blamed in respect of our emotions ; a person is not praised for being afraid or being angry, nor blamed for being angry in an absolute sense, but only for being angry in a certain way ; but we are praised or blamed in respect of our virtues or vices. Again, whereas we are angry or afraid without deliberate purpose, the virtues are in some sense deliberate purposes, or do not exist in the 44 THE NICOMACHEAN" ETHICS [bOOK II. absence of deliberate purpose. It may be added that while we are said to be moved in respect of our emotions, in respect of our virtues or vices we are not said to be moved but to have a certain disposition. These reasons also prove that the virtues are not faculties. For we are not called either good or bad, nor are we praised or blamed, as having an abstract capacity for emotion. Also while Nature gives us our faculties, it is not Nature that makes us good or p. 35. bad, but this is a point which we have already discussed. If then the virtues are neither emotions nor faculties, it remains that they must be moral states. Chap. V. The nature of virtue has been now generically v^tue not (Jescribed. But it is not enough to state merely that moral state virtue IS a moral state, we must also describe the ctdar moral character of that moral state. ^*°''^' It must be laid down then that every virtue or excellence has the effect of producing a good con- dition of that of which it is a virtue or excellence, and of enabling it to perform its function well. Thus the excellence of the eye makes the eye good and its function good, as it is by the excellence of the eye that we see well. Similarly, the excellence of the horse makes a horse excellent and good at racing, at carrying its rider and at facing the enemy. If then this is universally true, the virtue or excellence of man will be such a moral state as makes a man good and able to perform his proper function p. 16. well. We have already explained how this will be the case, but another way of making it clear will be to study the nature or character of this virtue. CHAP, v.] OF AE.ISTOTLE. 45 Now in everything, whether it be continuous or Doctrine of discrete', it is possible to take a greater, a smaller, or * ™^*"' an equal amount,, and this either absolutely or in relation to ourselves, the equal being a mean between excess and deficiency. By the mean in respect of the thing itself, or the absolute mean, I understand that which is equally distinct from both extremes ; and this is one and the same thing for everybody. By the mean considered relatively to ourselves I understand that which is neither too much nor too little ; but this is not one thing, nor is it the same for everybody. Thus if 10 be too much and 2 too little we take 6 as a mesm in respect of the thing itself ; for 6 is as much greater than 2 as it is less than 10, and this is a mean in arithmetical proportion. But the mean considered relatively to ourselves must not be ascertained in this way. It does not follow that if 10 pounds of meat be too much and 2 be too little for a man to eat, a trainer will order him 6 pounds, as this may itself be too much or too little for the person who is to take it; it will be too little e.g. for Milo', but too much for a beginner in gymnastics. It will be the same with running and wrestling ; the right amount will vary vnth the individual. This being so, everybody who understands his business avoids alike excess and deficiency ; he seeks and chooses the mean, not the absolute mean, but the mean considered relatively to ourselves. ' In Aristotelian language, as Mr Peters says, a straight line is a " continuous quantity " but a rouleau of sovereigns a " discrete - quantity." 2 The famous Crotoniate wrestler. 46 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK II. Every science then performs its function well, if it regards the mean and refers the works which it produces to the mean. This is the reason why it is usually said of successful works that it is impossible to take anything from them or to add anything to them, which implies that excess or deficiency is fatal to excellence but that the mean state ensures it. Good' artists too, as we say, have an eye to the mean in their works. But virtue, like Nature herself, is more accurate and better than any art ; virtue there- fore will aim at the mean ; — I speak of moral virtue, as it is moral virtue which is concerned with emotions and actions, and it is these which admit of excess and deficiency and the mean. Thus it is possible to go too far, or not to go far enough, in respect of fear, courage, desire, anger, pity, and pleasure and pain generally, and the excess and the deficiency are alike wrong ; but to experience these emotions at the right times and on the right occasions and towards the right persons and for the right causes and in the right manner is the mean or the supreme good, which is characteristic of virtue. Similarly there may be excess, deficiency, or the mean, in regard to actions. But virtue is concerned with emotions and actions, and here excess is an error and deficiency a fault, whereas the mean is successful and laudable, and success and merit are both characteristics of virtue. Virtue a It appears then that virtue is a mean state, so far inter- at Icast as it aims at the mean. mediate state. 1 In the Greek text the parenthesis should be continued to the words jrpoj roiT-o ^Xfirovres epya^ovrat. CHAP. YI.] OF ARISTOTLE. 47 Again, there are many different ways of going wrong; for evil is in its nature infinite, to use the Pythagorean' figure, but good is finite. But there is only one possible way of going right. Accordingly the former is easy and the latter difficult ; it is easy to miss the mark but difficult to hit it. This again is a reason why excess and deficiency are characteristics of vice and the mean state a characteristic of virtue. "For good is simple, evil manifold 2." Virtue then is a state of deliberate moral purpose Chap, vl consisting in a mean that is relative to ourselves, the oj^^j,"" meaa being determined' by reason, or as a prudent man would determine it. It is a mean state firstly as lying between two vices, the vice of excess on the one hand, and the vice of deficiency on the other, and secondly because, whereas the vices either fall short of or go beyond what is proper in the emotions and actions, virtue not only discovers but embraces the mean. Accordingly, virtue, if regarded in its essence or Virtue theoretical conception, is a mean state, but, if regard- m^LVd ed from the point of view of the highest good, or of ^^^^^ excellence, it is an extreme. But it is not every action or every emotion that ^ The Pythagoreans, starting from the mystical significance of nnmber, took the opposite principles of " the finite " (t-o irepas or TO 7T€n-fparhich excite fear is more truly courageous than he who shows a proper spirit on the occasions which inspire confidence, p. 79. It is endurance of painful things, as has been said, that entitles people to be called courageous. Hence it is that courage is painful, and is justly a subject of praise ; for it is more difficult to endure pains than 1 The story is told by Xenophon, Hellenica it. ch. 10. CHAP. XII.] OF AHISTOTLE. 89 to abstain from pleasures. At the same time it would seem that the end which courage proposes to itself is pleasant, but that it is obscured by attendant circumstances, as happens also in gymnastic contests. For while the end or object which boxers have in view, viz. the crown and the honour, is pleasant, the blows which they receive, and all their exertions, are painful and grievous to flesh and blood, and, as these are numerous, while the object or prize itself is small, it appears not to afford any pleasure. If then the case in regard to courage is similar to this, death and wounds will be painflil to the courageous man and involuntary ; but he will endure them because endurance is honourable and avoidance disgraceful. Nay, in proportion as he possesses virtue in its fulness, and is happy, will be his pain at the prospect of death ; for to such an one life is pre- eminently valuable, and he will be consciously de- prived at death of the greatest blessings. But pain- ful as such deprivation is, he is none the less courageous, nay perhaps he is even more courageous, as he willingly sacrifices these blessings for noble conduct on the field of battle. It is not the case then that all the virtues imply a pleasurable activity, except in so far as one attains to the end. Still, it is true perhaps, after all, that people who enjoy a happy life are not such good soldiers as people who are less courageous but have nothing to lose, as these last are ready to face any danger, and will sell their lives for a small sum of money. This may be taken as a sufficient accoimt of 90 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK III. courage ; its nature may be easily comprehended, at least in outline, from what has been said. CHAP.xni. We will proceed to consider temperance, as it ance^^' seems that courage and temperance are the yirtues of the irrational parts of human nature, p. 49. We have already said that temperance is a mean state in respect of pleasures ; for it is not in the same degree or manner concerned with pains. Pleasure is also the sphere in which licentiousness displays itself. Let us therefore define now the character of these pleasures. We will accept the distinction which is commonly made between bodily and psychical or mental pleasures, such as ambition and the love of learning ; for he who is ambitious or fond of learning takes pleasure in the object of which he is fond, although it is not his body which is affected but his mind. But where pleasures of this kind are in question people are not called either temperate or licentious. It is the same with all such other pleasures as are not bodily. Thus people who are fond of talking and of telling stories, and who spend their days in trifling pursuits we call gossips, but we do not call them licentious, nor do we call people licenti- ous who feel pain at the loss of money or friends. Temperance then wiU apply to bodily pleasures only, but not to all even of these. For if people take pleasure in gratifications of the sight, e.g. in colours, forms, and painting, they are not called either temperate or licentious. Yet it would seem possible to take a right pleasure or an excessive or insufficient pleasure in these things as well as in others. It is CHAP. XIII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 91 the same with gratifications of the ear. Nobody speaks of such people as take an excessive pleasxire in music or acting as licentious, or of people who take a right pleasure as temperate. Nor again do we speak of people who enjoy gratifications of the smell as licentious or temperate, except accidentally. Thus we do not call people licentious if they take pleasure in the smell of apples or roses or incense, but rather if they take pleasure in the smell of unguents and relishes ; for it is in these that a licentious person takes pleasure, as they remind him of the objects of his desire. It is true that we may see other people, when they are hungry, taking pleasure in the smell of food ; but it is only a licentious person who habitu- ally takes pleasure in such things, as they are the objects of his desire. The lower animals again, are not, in general, capable of the pleasures of these senses, except accidentally. Dogs, e.g. do not take pleasure in scenting hares' flesh but only in eating it, although the smell gives them the sensation of eating. Again, a lion takes pleasure not in hearing an ox's lowing', but in devouring the ox, although, as it is the lowing by which he perceived that the ox is near, he appears to take pleasure in the lowing. Similarly it is not the sight or discovery of a stag or wild goat that gives him pleasure, but the prospect of a meal. Temperance and licentiousness then have to do Licentious- with pleasures of such a kind as the lower animals generally are capable of, and it is hence that these pleasures appear slavish and brutish. They are the ^ ^oi/g is a misprint for av^. 92^ THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK III. pleasures of the touch and the taste.' It appears that the taste comes little, if at all, into question ; for it is the taste which judges of flavours, as when people test wines or season dishes, but it is in no sense this judgment of flavours which gives pleasure, at least to such people as are licentious, but rather the actual enjoyment of them, and the medium of enjoyment is invariably the sense of touch, whether in meats or in drinks or in what are called the pleasures of love. This was the reason why a certain gourmand prayed that his throat might become longer than a crane's, showing that his pleasure was derived from the sense of touch. Thus the sense of which incontinence is predicable is the most universal of the senses. It would seem too that incontinence is justly censurable, as it is a characteristic not of our human, but of our animal, nature. To take delight and supreme satis- faction in such things is brutish ; for the most liberal or refined of the pleasures of the touch, such as the pleasures of rubbing and of taking a hot bath in the gymnasium, are denied to the profligate, as the sense of touch which an incontinent man cultivates belongs, not to the whole body, but only to certain parts of it. Desires It seems that some desires are universal and others nnnrersa ^^^ individual and acquired. Thus the desire of food indiTiduai. jg g^ natural desire. Everybody who feels want desires meat or drink or perhaps both. A young man, too, in the prime of life, says Homer', desires the love of a woman. But it is not equally true that everybody desires a particular form of gratification, or the same 1 The reference seems to be to Hiad xxiv. 129, the words addressed by Thetis to Achilles. CHAP. XUI.] OF ARISTOTLE. 93 forms. Hence the particular desire is peculiar to our- selves or individttal. Nevertheless, there is some- thing natural in it ; for although different people are pleased by different things, yet there are some things which are pleasanter to all people than others. Now in respect of such desires as are natural there are but few people who make a mistake, and their mistake is always on one side, viz. that of excess. For to eat or drink anything to the point of surfeit is to exceed the natural limit of quantity, as the natural desire does not go beyond the satisfaction of our want. Accordingly such persons are called gluttons because they go beyond what is right in satisfying their want. It is only exceedingly slavish people who behave in this way. In regard to such pleasures as are individual there are many people who go wrong, and they go wrong in many different ways. For if people are said to be unduly fond of particular things, either as taking pleasure in wrong things or as taking more pleasure than ordinary people' or as taking pleasure in a wrong way, the excess of which the licentious are guilty may assume all these forms. For they take pleasure in some things which are detestable and therefore wrong, and if these are things»in which it is right to take pleasure; they take a greater pleasure in them than is right or than most people take*. It is clear then that excess in respect of pleasures is licentiousness, and that it properly is a subject of ' The eu'y may probably be retained, but the text should be J) Tffl fiSXkov Tf as ol troXXot, without the comma after fioKkov. ' Omitting the comma after bet 94 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK III. censure. But in respect of pains there is this diflference between temperance and courage. A person is not called temperate if he bears pains bravely, and incontinent if he does not; but the incontinent person is so called because he feels more pain than is right at not obtaining pleasures, his pleasure being the cause of his pain, and the tempe- rate man is so called because he is not pained at the absence of pleasure and at his abstinence from it. Chap. XIV. The licentious man then desires all pleasures, or the greatest pleasures, and is led by his desire to prefer these to anything else. He feels a double pain therefore, viz. the pain of failing to obtain them and the pain of desiring them, as aU desire is attended by pain. Yet it seems paradoxical to assert that his pleasure is the cause of his pain. We never find people whose love of pleasures is deficient and whose delight in them is less than it ought to be. Such insensibility to pleasures is not human; for even the lower animals distinguish difierent kinds of food, liking some and disliking others. A being who should not take pleasure in anything, nor make any difierence between one thing and another, would be far from being a man. But there is no name for such a being, as he never exists. Character '^^ temperate man holds a mean position in of the respect of pleasures. He takes no pleasure in the temperate . . i . , , i man. thmgs m which the licentious man takes most pleasure ; he rather dislikes them; nor does he take pleasure at all in wrong things nor an excessive pleasure in anything that is pleasant, nor is he pained at the absence of such things, nor does he desire them. CHAP. XV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 95 except perhaps in moderation, nor does he desire them more than is right, or at the wrong time, and so on. But he will be eager in a moderate and right spirit for all such things as are pleasant and at the same time conducive to health or to a sound bodily condition, and for all other pleasures, so long as they are not prejudicial to these or inconsistent with noble conduct or extravagant beyond his means. For unless a person limits himself in this way, he affects such pleasures more than is right, whereas the temperate man follows the guidance of right reason. Licentiousness seems to have more the character chap. xv. of voluntary action than cowardice, as the former is Licentious- due to pleasure, and the latter to pain ; and whereas luntary pleasure is something that we choose, pain is some- ^warcUoe. thing that we avoid. Also, while pain distracts and destroys the nature of one who suffers it, pleasure has no such effect, but rather leaves the will free. Hence licentiousness deserves more severe reproach than cowardice ; for it is easier to train oneself to meet its temptations as they frequently occur in life, nor does the training involve any danger, whereas the contrary is the case in meeting alarms. It would seem too that cowardice as a moral state is not voluntary in the same degree as particular acts of cowardice. For cowardice in itself is painless, but particular acts of cowardice occur because people are so utterly driven out of their wits by pain that they throw away their arms and disgrace themselves generally, and this is the reason why such acts have the appearance of being compulsory. In the case of the licentious man on the other hand, the particular 96 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK III. acts are voluntary, as he eagerly desires them, but licentiousness as a whole is not so voluntary, as nobody desires to be licentious. We apply the term "licentiousness" (aKoXaa-ia), to the faults of children as well as to those of grown- up people, as there is a certain similarity between them. It does not matter to my present purpose which of the two kinds of faults is named after the other; but it is clear that the later is named after the earlier'. The metaphor^ (in the word aKoXaaia) is not, it seems, a bad one. For that which is prone to dis- graceful things, and capable of rapid growth, stands in need of pruning or chastisement (jceKoKdaOaL Set), but such proneness and such growth are preeminently characteristic of desire or of childhood ; for children, like licentious people, live by desire and not by reason, and the longing for pleasure is nowhere so strong as in them. If then this disposition is not obedient and subject to authority, it will greatly develope. For the longing for pleasure which a foolish person has is insatiable and universal, and the active exercise of the desire augments its native strength, until the desires, if they are strong or vehement, actually expel the reasoning power. They ought therefore to be moderate and few, and in no way contrary to reason. But we speak of such a 1 If the word " licentious" were used of a child in English, it would, I think, be used with a certaiu reservation. ^ The observation, which cannot be translated into English, depends upon the etymological connexion between axoKaa-ia " licentiousness " and KoXaa-is " chastisement." CHAP. XV.] OF AEISTOTLE. 97 disposition as obedient and chastened ; for as a child oaght to live according to the direction of his tutor' so ought the concupiscent element in man to live according to the reason. In the temperate man then the concupiscent element ought to live in harmony with the reason, as nobleness is the object of them both, and the temperate man desires what is right, and desires it in the right way, and at the right time, i.e. according to the law of reason. We may now bring our discussion of temperance to a close. ^ It will be understood that the waiSayayos was not so much a "tutor" in the modem sense as the confidential servant who took charge of a child. W. N. E. BOOK IV. Chap. I. The next Virtue to be considered is liberality. Liber- Liberahty. ^^jj^y gggjjjg ^q Y)e a mean state in regard to property. For the liberal man wins praise, not in war, nor in the same sphere as the temperate man, nor again in respect of his judgments, but in regard to the giving and taking of property and particularly in giving it. By property we understand all such things as have Prodi- their value measured by money. Prodigality and miberaiity. iUiberality are excesses and deficiencies in regard to property. We invariably apply the term "illiber- ality" to people whose hearts are set more than is right upon property, but we sometimes employ the term "prodigality" in a complex sense, speaking of people who are incontinent and who spend money in licentious living as "prodigals." Prodigals there- fore are held to be utterly worthless people as com- bining in themselves a number of vices. But this is not a proper application of the term "prodigal," it strictly means a person who has one particular vice, viz. that of wasting his substance, for a prodigal' is ^ The statement that the prodigal (ao-uros) ruins himself depends upon the derivation of aa-aros from d, a-d(fiv. CHAP. I.] THE ETHICS OF AKISTOTLE. 99 one who is ruining himself, and to waste one's sub- stance seems in a way to be ruining oneself, as this is the only means of life. It is in this sense then that we understand the term "prodigality." Things which admit of use' may be used either well or badly. But riches are a useful thing. Again, the person who makes the best use of anything is the person who possesses the virtue appropriate to that thing. Accordingly he will make the best use of riches who possesses the virtue which is appropriate to property, i.e. the liberal man. Further it seems that the use of property consists in spending and giving ; the taking and keeping of property should rather be described as acquisition. Hence it is more truly distinctive of the liberal man to give to the right people than to take from the right quarter and not to take from the wrong quarter. For it is more truly distinctive of virtue to be the author than to be the recipient of benefactions, and to do what is noble than to abstain from doing what is shameful. But it is clear that, while giving implies doing well and acting nobly, taking implies only being well treated or not behaving in a shameful manner. Gratitude too is the due of one who gives, not of one who does not take, and praise is his due in a higher degree. Also, it is easier to abstain from taking than to give, for people are less ready to throw away what is their own than to abstain from taking what belongs to somebody else. Again, people who give are called 1 Xpfi"! XPl"'^'"! XPIo^'fo^j XP'7/""'°j ^11 words occurring in this passage, are etymologically connected. 7—2 100 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. liberal, people who abstain from taking are not praised for liberality so much as for justice, but people who take are not praised at all. Of all virtu- ous people none are so much beloved as the liberal ; for they are benefactors, and their benefaction consists in their giving. Chap. II. Virtuous actions are noble and have a noble istics^of^'^ motive. The liberal man, being virtuous, then will Uberaiity. gj^g ^qjjj ^ noblc motive and in a right spirit ; for he will give the right amount, and will give it to the right persons and at the right time, and will satisfy all the other conditions of right giving. He will do all this too with pleasure or without pain ; for a virtuous action is pleasant or painless, and it is certainly any- thing but painful. But he who gives to the wrong people, or who gives not from a noble motive but for some other cause, will not be called liberal, but by some other name ; nor will he be so called, if giving is pain- ful to him, as in that case he would prefer the wealth to the noble action, and this preference is illiberal. Nor will the liberal man take from wrong sources ; for such taking, again, is unlike the character of one who is no admirer of property. Nor, again, will he be inclined to ask favours ; for one who is in the habit of conferring benefits will not be ready at any moment to receive them. When he does take, it will be from right sources, e.g. from his own possessions, and he will take not as if taking were noble, but because it is necessary, if he is to have the means of giving. He will not neglect his own property since he wishes to employ it in relieving other people. He will refrain from giving indiscriminately that he may have the CHAP. II.] OF ARISTOTLE. 101 means of giving to the right people, and at the times and in the places where giving is noble. If a man is excessively liberal, he will actually go too far in his giving, the result being that he will reserve too little for himself; for disregard of self is a characteristic of liberality. But in estimating liberality we must take account of a person's fortune ; for liberality consists, not in the amount of the money given, but in the moral state of the giver', and the moral state proportions the gift to the fortune of the giver. It is quite possible then that one who gives less than another may be more liberal, if his means are smaller. It seems that people who have not made their own fortune, but have inherited it, are more liberal, as they have never known what want is, and people are always fondest of their own productions, e.g. parents of their children, and poets of their poems. It is difficult for a liberal man to be rich, as he is not fond of getting or of saving money, but rather of spending it, and values wealth not for its own sake, but as affording an opportunity of giving. Hence it is a reproach often levelled against fortune that the people who deserve riches most have often the least. But the fact is easily explained ; for it is impossible to have wealth or anything else without taking the trouble to have it. At the same time the liberal man will not give to the wrong people, or on any wrong occasion, and so on ; for to do so would be to cease to act in a liberal spirit, and if he were to spend ' As in the parable of the widow's two mites. ■m 102 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. money upon these objects, he would not have the means of spending it upon the right objects. For the liberal man, as has been said, is one who spends in proportion to his substance, and who spends upon the right objects. But one who spends in excess of his fortune is a prodigal. Hence it is that we do not call despots prodigals, as it does not seem easy for them to exceed the amount of their property by their gifts and expenses. As liberality is a mean state in regard to the giving and taking of property, the liberal man will both give and spend on the right objects and to the right amount, whether in small matters or in great, and will feel pleasure in doing so. He will also take from the right sources and to the right amount. For as the virtue is a mean state in regard both to giving and to taking, he will do both in the right manner. For honourable taking is consistent with honourable giving ; but such taking as is not honourable is incompatible with it. Thus the giving and taking which are consistent are found to exist together in the same person, but the giving and taking which are incompatible are clearly not so found. If it happens that the liberal man spends more or less than is right and noble, he will feel pain, but it wiU be a moderate and right pain ; for virtue naturally feels pleasure and pain on the right occa- sions and in the right manner. Again, the liberal man is easy to deal with in money matters. He is one who can easily be cheated, as he does not care for money, and is more distressed at not having spent what is right than pained at CHAP. III.] OF ARISTOTLE. 103 having spent what is not right ; in fact he is a person who does not approve of Simonides'. The prodigal on the other hand goes wrong in Chap. in. these respects as in others; for he does not feel^^*^' pleasure or pain at the right causes or in the right manner, as we shall see more clearly when we proceed. We have said that prodigality and illiberality are excesses and deficiencies, and that they are so in two respects, viz. in giving and taking, for we reckon spending as a form of giving. Prodigality then exceeds in giving and not taking, but is deficient in taking. Illiberality is deficient in giving and exceeds in taking, but is deficient and exceeds in giving and taking on a small scale. Now the two characteristics of prodigality viz. giving cmd not taMng, are seldom combined in the same person. It is not easy for a person, if he has no source of revenue, to give to everybody ; for private persons, if they give in this way, soon find that their property runs short, and it is private persons who are commonly called prodigals. A prodigal of this kind however, if he existed, would seem to be far superior to an illiberal person ; for his faults are easily cured by age and lack of property, and he is capable of attaining to the mean or intermediate state. In fact he possesses the characteristics of a liberal man, as he gives and does not take, although 1 There are several dicta of Simonides, such as those which Sir A. Grant quotes, showing his appreciation of wealth, Cp. Bhetoric ii. ch. 16, p. 1391 Aj.jj. 104 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. in neither respect is his action right or good. If he were to be trained aright or otherwise reformed, he would be liberal ; for then he would give to the right people, and would not take from the wrong sources. It seems then that his character is not a bad one ; for it is not a vicious or ignoble nature, but a foolish one, which exceeds in giving and in abstinence from taking. A prodigal of this kind seems to be far superior to an illiberal person, not only for the reasons which have been given but because the former does good to many people while the latter does good to nobody, not even to himself. But most prodigals, as has been said, not only give to the wrong people but take from the wrong sources, and are so far illiberal. They become grasping because they are eager to spend, and are not able to do so easily, as their means soon run short ; they are therefore obliged to get the means from other sources. At the same time as nobleness is a matter of indiflference to them, they are reckless and indiscriminate in their taking ; for they are eager to give but they do not care at all how they give or how they get the means of giving. The result is that their very gifts are not liberal, as they are not noble in themselves or in their object or made in the right manner. These prodigals sometimes enrich people who ought to be poor, and, while they will not give a penny to persons of respectable character, they heap presents upon their flatterers or the ministers of their various pleasures. Thus they are generally licentious ; for as they are fond of spending, they squander money on licentious living among other things, and as nobleness is not the rule of their lives, they sink CHAP. III.J OF ARISTOTLE. 105 into being mere pleasure seekers. A prodigal then, if left destitute of guidance, commits these vagaries, but by careful training he may come to the mean or right state of life. IlliberaHty on the other hand is incurable ; for it ruiber- seems that old age and impotence of any kind makes ^' men illiberal. Also it runs in human nature more than prodigality ; for most people are fonder of money than of giving money away. It is of wide extent too, and assumes numerous forms ; there seem to be many aspects of illiberaUty. For as it consists in two things, viz. deficiency of giving and excess of taking, it is not always found in its entirety. It sometimes happens that the two parts are separated, and while some people go too far in taking, others do not go far enough in giving. The people who are described by such names as "niggards," "misers," and "curmudgeons," are aU deficient in giving, but they do not covet or wish to take other people's property. They are influenced in some cases by a sense of equity, and a desire of avoiding disgrace ; for there are some people who seem, or pretend, to hoard their money with the view of securing them- selves against ever being compelled to do wj^at is disgracefiil. This is the class of skinflints, and all such people whose names are derived from an exces- sive unwillingness to give to anybody. Others again are induced to abstain from taking other people's property by fear, feeling that it is difficult for them to take other people's property without having their own property taken by other people ; hence they choose neither to take nor to give. Others again go 106 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. too far in taking by taking anything from anybody, e.g. such people as pursue illiberal' or degraded occupations, keepers of brothels and the like, and usurers who lend small sums of money at extortionate rates of interest. AU these are people who take money from wrong sources, and take more than is right. It appears that a sordid love of gain is the common characteristic of them all, as they all con- sent to bear an evil name for the sake of gain, and this a trifling gain ; for if people take large sums from improper sources or of an improper kind, we do not call them illiberal. Thus we do not so speak of despots when they sack cities and plunder temples ; we rather speak of them as wicked, impious, and unjust. But cardsharpers, cutpurses' and robbers are illiberal people, as making gain by sordid or disgracefiil means ; for it is the love of gain which makes both cardsharpers and robbers ply their busi- ness and consent to bear an evil name. It is for profit that robbers face the greatest dangers, and cardsharpers make gain from their friends, to whom they ought to give. Both classes, as wishing to make gain from improper sources, may be said to have a sordid or disgraceful love of gain, and all such forms of taking are illiberal. It is reasonable to regard illiberality as the oppo- site of liberality ; for it is a greater evil than 1 The Greek word i\ev6cpos, like the English " liberal," may mean either "generous" or " honourable," and Aristotle hardly seems to be aware that he confuses the meanings. ' The Greek word means one who steals the clothes of some- body while he is bathing. CHAP. IV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 107 prodigality, and men are more likely to err on the side of illiberaJity than in the direction of prodigality as we have described it. This must suffice then, as our account of liberality and of the vices which are opposed to it. It would seem natural to discuss magnificence Chap. ly. next, as magnificence' seems also to be a virtue ^nfe^' which has to do with property. But it does not extend, like liberality, to all the uses of property ; it touches only such as involve a large expenditure, and here it exceeds liberality in scale ; for as the name^ itself suggests, magnificence is suitable expenditure upon a great scale. But the greatness is relative to the occasion ; for a person who fits out a trireme does not incur the same expense as one who is the head of a sacred legation. What is suitable then is relative to the person, occasion and circumstances. If a person spends money duly upon small or un- important occasions, if he can say, e.g. in the poet's words, "Oft to a vagrant gave IK" he is not called magnificent, but only if he makes such an expenditure upon great occasions; for al- though the magnificent person is liberal, it does not follow that the liberal person is magnificent. The deficiency of such a moral state is called Meanness, meanness ; its excess vulgarity, bad taste, and the ^*" ^' like, implying not so much an excessive expenditure 1 Beading avrri. ' fieyaXoirpeireia.. 3 Odyssey xvii. 420. It is Odysseus who speaks. 108 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. on right circumstances as an ostentatious expenditure on wrong occasions and in a wrong manner. But of this we will speak later. The magnificent man is like a connoisseur in art ; he has the faculty of perceiving what is suitable, and p. 44. of spending large sums of money with good taste. For as we said at the outset, a moral state is deter- mined by its activities and its objects. The expenses of the magnificent man then are large and suitable* ; so too are his results ; for this is the only way in which a large expenditure can at the same tirae be suitable to its result. It follows that the result ought to be worthy of the expenditure, and the expenditure worthy of the result, or of an even greater result. The motive of the magnificent man in incurring "this expense will be nobleness ; for nobleness is a charac- teristic of all the virtues. He will spend his money too in a cheerful and lavish spirit, as a minute calculation of expense is a mark of meanness. He will consider how a work can be made most beautiful and most suitable, rather than how much it will cost, and how it can be done in the cheapest way. The magnificent man will necessarily be liberal as well; for the liberal man too will spend the right amount of money and will spend it in the right manner. But here the greatness, i.e. the great scale, of the magnificent man, will appear, although liberality has the same field as magnificence ; with equal expendi- ture he will make the result more magnificent. For the virtue or excellence of a possession is not the ^ Again the argument turns upon the etymological meaning of lieydKonpiitfia. CHAP, v.] OF AHISTOTLE. 109 same as that of a result or a work of art; for it is the possession which is worth most that is the greatest prize or honour, as e.g. gold, but a work of art is prized for its greatness and nobleness. For the contempla- tion of such a work excites admiration, and what is magnificent is always admirable. In a word, magnifi- cence is excellence of work on a great scale. There is a kind of expenditure which we call Chap. v. honourable, such as expenditure upon the Gods, votive of'^''"^! oflerings, temples, and sacrifices, and similarly aUcence. that appertains to divine worship, or upon the favourite objects of patriotic rivalry, as when people consider it their duty to supply a chorus or fit out a tiireme or even to give a public dinner in a handsome style. But in all these matters, as has been said, there p. loi. must be a regard paid to the agent and his resources. The expenditure ought to be worthy of him and his resources, and to be suitable not only to the result but to its author. It follows that a poor man cannot be magnificent, as he does not possess the means of spending large sums of money suitably. He is foolish if he makes the attempt, as his expenditure will be neither proportionate to his means nor proper in itself, but unless a thing is done in a right way, it cannot be virtuous. But magnificence is suitable to people who are in possession of the necessary means, whether they have acquired them by their own eflForts or have inherited them from their ancestors or connexions, and to persons of rank and reputation and the like, as all these advantages confer importance and dignity. Such may be said to be, in general, the character 110 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. of the magnificent man, and such, as has been said, the expenditure in which his magnificence displays itself; for this is the greatest and most honourable kind of expenditure. It displays itself also on such private occasions as occur once in a lifetime, e.g. marriage and the like, or on any occasion of peculiar interest to the state or the upper classes, or in receiving foreigners and taking leave of them or in making an interchange of presents; for the magni- ficent man spends money not on himself but upon public objects, and gifts have a certain similarity to religious oflerings. Again, a magnificent man will erect a house in a manner suitable to his wealth ; for even a private house may be an ornament to the city. He will prefer to spend his money upon such works as are permanent, for none are so noble as these, and in all these cases he will observe the law of propriety ; for the same things are not appropriate to gods and to men, or in building a temple and in making a tomb. In his expenditure too, everything wiU be great of its kind ; there is nothing so mag- nificent as great expenditure on a great occasion, but, when that is impossible, the next thing is such great- ness as the particular occasion allows. There is a diflerence between greatness in the result and greatness in the expenditure. Thus the most beautiful of balls or bottles has a certain magnificence as a present for a child, although its price is trifiing and paltry. It is characteristic then of the magnificent man, whatever be the class of work that he produces, to produce it in a magnificent way ; for the result so produced cannot easily be surpassed. CHAP. VI.] OF ARISTOTLE. Ill and it is proportionate to the expenditure made upon it. Such then being the character of the magnificent t)^*^- ti. man, the man who is guilty of excess, or the Tulgar ^"^santy. man, exceeds in spending more than is right, as has been said ; for he spends large sums upon trifles and makes a display which is ofifensive to good taste, as e.g. by entertaining members of his club at a break- fast which is as sumptuous as a wedding-breakfast, or if he provides a comic chorus, by bringing the members of it on to the stage in purple dresses, after the manner of the Megarians. And all this he wiU do, not from a noble motive, but merely to exhibit his wealth, and because he thinks that it wiU win him admiration. Where he ought to spend a great deal, he will spend little, and where he ought to spend little, he wiU spend a great deal. The mean man, on the other hand, wiU be deficient Meanness. on all occasions, and after an enormous expenditure, will ruin the beauty of his work for a trifie, never doing anything without hesitating about it, and con- sidering how he can reduce his expenditure to a minimum, and grieving over it and always imagining he is doing things on a larger scale than is necessary. Thus these moral states, viz. vulga/rity and mean- ness, are vices, although they do not bring reproach upon us, as they are not injurious to others nor particularly indecorous. Highmindedness', as its very name suggests, chap. vn. Highmind- ^ One cannot help regretting that " magnanimity," which is edness. the precise English equivalent of fieyaXoi/rux'a, has come by usage to bear a limited sense. 112 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. seems to be occupied with high things. Let us begin then by ascertaining the character of those things. It makes no difference whether we consider the moral state or the person in whom the moral state is seen. A highminded person seems to be one who re- gards himself as worthy of high things, and who is worthy of them. For he who does so without being worthy is foolish, and no virtuous person is foolish or absurd. Such then is the highminded person. One who is worthy of smaU things, and who regards himself as worthy of them, is temperate or sensible, but he is not highminded; for highmindedness can only exist on a large scale as beauty can only exist in a tall person. Small people may be elegant and well pro- portioned, but not beautiful. He who regards himself as worthy of high things and is unworthy of them is conceited, although it is not eyeryone who takes an exaggerated view of his own worth that is a conceited person. He who takes too low a view of his own worth is mean-minded', whether it be high things, or moderate, or even small things that he is worthy of, so long as he underrates his deserts. This would seem to be especially a fault in one who is worthy of high things ; for what would he do, it may be asked, if his deserts were less than they are ? The highminded man, while he holds an extreme position by the greatness of his deserts, holds an 1 It would be desirable to use " lowmindedness " as the opposite of "highmindedness," but the word has received an inappropriate shade of meaning. CHAP. VII. J OP ARISTOTLE. 113 intermediate or mean position by the propriety of his conduct, as he estimates his own deserts aright, while others rate their deserts too high or too low. But if then he regards himself as worthy of high things, and is worthy of them, and especially if he is worthy of the highest things, there will be one particular object of his interest. Desert is a term used in reference to external goods, but we should naturally esteem that to be the greatest of external goods which we attribute to the gods, or which persons of high reputation most desire, or which is the prize awarded to the noblest actions. But honour answers to this description, as being the highest of external goods. The highminded man, then, bears himself in a right spirit towards honours and dishonours. It needs no proof that highminded people are concerned with honour ; for it is honour more than anything else -^ of which the great regard themselves, and deservedly regard themselves, as worthy. The mean-minded man Mean- underestimates himself both in respect of his own ness. deserts and in comparison with the acknowledged deserts of the highminded man. The conceited man Conceit. overestimates his own deserts, but he does not estimate his own deserts more highly than the highminded man. The highminded man, as being worthy of the highest things, will be in the highest degree good, for the better man is always worthy of the highest things, and the best man of the highest things. It follows then that the truly highminded man must be good. It would seem too that the highminded man possesses such greatness as belongs to every virtue, w. N. E. 8 114 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. It would be wholly inconsistent with the character of the highminded man to run away in hot haste, or to commit a crime ; for what should be his object in doing a disgraceful action, if nothing is great in his eyes ? If one examines the several points of character, it will appear quite ridiculous to say that the high- minded man need not be good. Were he vicious, he would not be worthy of honour at aU ; for honour is the prize of virtue, and is paid to none but the good. It seems then that highmindedness is, as it were, the crown of the virtues, as it enhances them, and cannot exist apart from them. Hence it is diflBcult to be truly highminded, as it is impossible without the perfection of good breeding. A highminded man then is especially concerned with honours and dishonours. He will be only moderately pleased at great honours conferred upon him by virtuous people, as feeling that he obtains what is naturally his due or even less than his due ; for it would be impossible to devise an honour that should be proportionate to perfect virtue ^ Never- theless he will accept honours, as people have nothing greater to confer upon him. But such honour as is paid by ordinary people and on trivial grounds, he will utterly despise, as he deserves something better than this. He will equally despise dishonour, feeling that it cannot justly attach to him. While the highminded man, then, as has been said, is principally concerned with honours, he will, at ' This sentence as showing Aristotle's exalted conception of "highmindedness," throws light upon several remarks before and after. CHAP. VII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 115 the same time, take a moderate view of wealth, political power, and good or ill fortmie of all kinds, however it may occur. He will not be excessively elated by good, or excessively depressed by ill fortune ; for he is not affected in this way by honour itself, as if honour were the greatest thing in the world. For it is honour which makes political power and wealth to be objects of desire ; at all events the possessors of power and wealth are eager to make use of them as means of gaining honour. He therefore who regards honour as insignificant will regard everything else in the same light. This is the reason why highmiuded people seem Chap.vtu. to be supercilious. It seems too that the gifts of fortune contribute to liighmindedness ; for people of high birth or great political power or wealth are considered to be worthy of honour, as they are in a position of superiority, and that which is superior in any good is always held in higher honour. It is thus that such gifts of fortune enhance a person's high- mindedness, as in conseqtience of them he receives honour from certain quarters. But in truth it is only the good man who deserves honour, although if a man possesses gifts of fortune as well as goodness he is considered to be in a higher sense worthy of honour. People who possess goods of this kind, without virtue, are not justified in considering themselves to be worthy of great things, nor is it right to call them higbminded, as neither greatness nor highmindedness is possible without complete virtue. The possessors of such goods belong to the class of people who are apt to become supercilious and insolent ; for without 8—2 116 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. virtue it is not easy to bear the gifts of fortune in good taste. Not being able to bear them, and imagining themselves to be superior to everybody else, such people treat others with contempt, and act according to their own sweet will ; for they imitate the highminded man without being like him, but they imitate him only so far as they have the power ; in other words they do not perform virtuous actions, but they treat other people with contempt. The highminded man is justified in his contempt for others, as he forms a true estimate of them, but ordinary people have no such justification. Again, the highminded man is not fond of encountering small dangers, nor is he fond of encountering dangers at all, as there are few things which he values enough to endanger himself for them. But he is ready to encounter great dangers, and in the hour of danger is reckless of his life, because he feels that life is not worth living without honour. He is capable of conferring benefits but ashamed of receiving them, as in the one case he feels his superiority, and in the other his inferiority. He will try to return a benefit which has been conferred upon him with interest, as then the original benefactor will actually become his debtor, and wiU have been the recipient of a benefit. It seems too that a highminded person remembers those upon whom he has conferred a benefit, but not those from whom he has received it; for the recipient of a benefaction is inferior to the benefactor, and the highminded man always aspires to superiority. Again, he is glad to be told of the benefits which he has conferred, but he cannot bear being told of those CHAP. Vin.] OF AEISTOTLE. 117 which he has received. That is the reason (he thinks) why Thetis' does not recount to Zeus the services which she has done him, and why the Lacedaemonians' in negotiating with the Athenians recounted not their services but their obligations. It is characteristic too of the highminded man that he never, or hardly ever, asks a favour, that he is ready to do anybody a service, and that, although his bearing is stately towards persons of dignity and affluence, it is unas- suming towards the middle class ; for while it is a difficult and dignified thing to be superior to the former, it is easy enough to be superior to the latter, and while a dignified demeanour in dealing with the former is a mark of nobility, it is a mark of vulgarity in dealing with the latter, as it is like a display of physical strength at the expense of an invalid. Such a person too will not be eager to win honours or to dispute the supremacy of other people. He will not bestir himself or be in a hurry to act, except where there is some great honour to be won, or some great result to be achieved. His performances will be rare, but they will be great and will win him a great name. He will, of course, be open in his hatreds and his friendships, as secrecy is an indication of fear. He will care for reality more than for reputation, he will be open in word and deed, as his superciliousness will lead him to speak his mind boldly. Accordingly 1 Iliad I. 503, 504. It is where Theiiiis invokes the aid of Zeus on behalf of Achilles. ^ ^ The occasion is said to have been one when the Thebans invaded Laconia. It may be assumed that the Lacedaemonians were seeking Athenian support. 118 THE mCOMACHEAN ETHICS [BOOK IV. he will tell the truth too, except where he is ironical, although he will U8e irony in dealing with ordinary people. He will be incapable of ordering his life so as to please anybody else, unless it be a friend, as such dependence would be servility. That is the reason why all toadies have the spirit of menials, and persons of a mean spirit are toadies. Nor again will he be given to admiration, as there is nothing which strikes him as great. Nor will he bear grudges ; for no one who is highminded will dwell upon the past, least of all upon past injuries ; he will prefer to over- look them. He will not be a gossip, he will not talk much about himself or about anybody else ; for he does not care to be praised himself or to get other people censured. On the other hand he will not be fond of praising other people. And not being a gossip, he will not speak evil of others, even of his enemies, except for the express purpose of insulting them. He will be the last person to set up a wailing or cry out for help when something happens which is inevitable or insignificant, as to do so is to attach great importance to it. He is the kind of person who would rather possess what is noble, although it does not bring in profit, than what is profitable but not noble, as such a preference argues self-sufiiciency. It seems too that the highminded man will be slow in his movements, his voice will be deep and his manner of speaking sedate ; for it is not likely that a man will be in a hurry, if there are not many things that he cares for, or that he will be emphatic, if he does not regard anything as important, and these are the causes which make people speak in shrill tones and use rapid movements. CHAP. IX.] OF ARISTOTLE. 119 Such then being the character of the highminded Chap. ix. man, whose character is the mean, he who is deficient is called meanminded, and he who exceeds is called conceited. , It does not follow that these persons are them- Mean- selves bad; they are not evil doers, they are only^™^**^" misguided ; for the meanminded man is one who, being worthy of good things, deprives himself of the things of which he is worthy, and seems to prejudice his own position by self-depreciation and self-ignor- ance, as otherwise he would try to get what he deserves, assuming it to be good. Not that people of this kind seem to be foolish, they are rather timorous. But it seems that their way of thinking deteriorates the character, as our aims always depend upon our estimate of our own deserts, and these people abandon the hope of noble actions and pursuits as well as of external goods from a feeling that they do not de- serve them. Conceited people on the other hand, are foolish Conceit. and ignorant of themselves, and make themselves conspicuous by being so ; for they try to obtain positions of honour under an impression of their own deserts, and then if they obtain them, prove failures. They get themselves up in fine dresses, and pose for efiect, and so on, and wish their good fortime to be known to all the world, and talk about themselves, as if that were the road to honour. Meanmindedness, rather than conceit, is opposed to highmindedness ; for it is a more common and a worse defect. Highmindedness then has to do with honour on a Chap. x. 120 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. viituoua large scale, as has been said. But there is apparently specting another virtue which has to do with honour, as was a°smiS ™ remarked at the outset. It would seem to be related scale. to highmindedness, as liberality is related to magnifi- ^' cence • for neither this virtue nor liberality is con- cerned with great things, but they both produce in us a right disposition in regard to things of moderate or small importance. As in the taking and giving of property there is a mean state, an excess, and a deficiency, so it is with the desire of honour. It is possible to desire honour too much or too little, or to desire to obtain it from Ambition, the right sourccs and in the right manner. We censure the ambitious man for desiring honour more than is right and for desiring to obtain it from wrong sources, and the unambitious man for not choosing to be honoured even for his noble deeds. But there are occasions when we praise the ambitious man as a man of spirit and a lover of nobleness, or praise the unambitious man for his moderation and self-restraint p. 50. as we said at the beginning. It is clear then that there are various senses in which a person is said to be fond of a thing. We do not always understand the word "ambitious" or " fond of honour," in the same sense ; when we use it as a term of praise we mean " ambitious more than ordinary people," and when as a term of censure we mean " ambitious more than is right." There is no name for the mean state, and it seems that both extremes lay claim to it, as if it were unoccupied ground. But where there is excess and deficiency, there is also a mean. People desire honour CHAP. X.] OP AMSTOTLE. 121 both more and less than is right; therefore they sometimes desire it also' in a right spirit. At least this moral state is a subject of praise, as being a mean state in respect of honour, although it has no recognized name. As compared with ambition, it appears to be lack of ambition, as compared with lack of ambition, it appears to be ambition, as compared with both, it appears to be a sort of combination of the two. It seems that this is the case with other virtues as well; but in this case it is the extremes which appear to be opposed to each other rather than to the mean, there being no name for the inter- mediate or mean state. Gentleness* or good temper is a mean state in Chap. xi. respect of angry feelings ; but there is no recognized ^ good*^^ name for the mean or indeed, it may be said, for the temper. extremes. • We apply the term " good temper " to the mean, although it inclines in sense to the deficiency which has no name. The excess may be described as a sort of angriness irasei or irascibility, for the emotion is anger, although the causes which produce it are many and various. A person is praised if he grows angry on the right occasion and with the right people, and also in the right manner, at the right times and for the right length of time; such a person will be good-tempered ^ Beadingf eirn fii) xai w! Sei. 2 There is no satisfactoty English equivalent for npabrrfs; "gentleness" and "mildness" are not specially limited to anger, and "placability," although it refers to it, denotes only one condition or aspect of the angry feelings. Perhaps "good temper " represents the Greek word as nearly as possible. 122 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. therefore, as good temper is a term of praise. For a good-tempered person is in effect one who Mdll be cool, and not carried away by his emotion but will wax wroth in such a manner, on such occasions, and for so long a time, as reason may prescribe. But it seems that he will err rather on the side of deficiency ; for a good-tempered or gentle person is inclined to forgiveness rather than to revenge. The deficiency, whether it be called a phlegmatic disposition or anything else, is a subject of censure, for people look foolish, if they do not grow angry on the right occasions or in the right way. For it seems that they have no feeling or no feeling of pain, and that, if they do not grow angry, they are incapable of defending themselves. But it is oidy a slavish nature which will submit to be insulted, or will let a friend be insulted, without protest. The excess may take any one of all these forms. We may be angry with the wrong people, or on the wrong occasions, or more than is right, or sooner, or for a longer time. I do not mean that all these faults are found in the same person ; that would be impos- sible, as evil is self-destructive, and, if it exists in its entirety, becomes intolerable. Irascible people then soon grow angry, and grow angry with the wrong person, or on the wrong occasions, or more than is right. But they soon cease beiiig angry; indeed, this is the best point in their character. The reason is that they do not control their anger ; they are so quick-tempered that • they retaliate in an open way and then have done. Quick Choleric people again are excessively quick- temper. CHAP, XI.] OP ARISTOTLE. 123 tempered, and get angry at every provocation and on every occasion ; hence their name'. Sullen people are slow to make friends again and, SnUen- as they keep their temper down, their anger lasts a "^^^' long time. Eetaliation brings a feeling of relief; for the revenge makes a person cease from his anger, by producing a state of pleasure instead of pain. But if this does not take place, the burden remains ; for as he does not reveal his anger, nobody helps to reason him out of it, and it takes time for a person to digest his anger in his own soul. Sullen people are the greatest possible nuisance to themselves and to their best friends. We call people stem if they wax wroth on the sternness. wrong occasions, and more than is right, and for a longer time, and if they will not make friends again without revenge or punishment. Such people are more diflBcult to live with than others ^ We gene- rally regard the excess, viz. the irascible rather than the phlegmatic disposition, as the opposite of good temper, as it is more frequent; for it is more natural to men to take vengeance than to forgive. This account of anger proves what has been p- 57. already said; it is not easy to define the right manner, objects, occasion, and duration of anger, or how far it may rightly go, and where it begins to be wrong; for we do not censure a person who deviates a little from the right, whether on the side of excess or of deficiency. Sometimes we praise people who ^ oKpoxoKos, connected with ;fdXor. ^ I have ventured to transpose this clause, as it clearly refers to " sternness.'' 124 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. are deficient and call them good-tempered; some- times we speak of people who exhibit a stern character as manly, believing them to be capable of rule. How far and in what way a person must deviate from the mean in order to be censurable is a question which it is not easy to decide theoretically ; for the judgment depends upon particular circumstances and is an aflair of the perception. So much however is clear, that the mean moral state is laudable, i.e. the state in which we grow angry with the right persbns and on the right occasions, and in the right manner and so on, whereas the excesses and deficiencies are censur- able, slightly censurable, if they go but a little way, censurable in a higher degree, if they go further, and exceedingly censurable, if they go a long way. It is clear then that we must cling to the mean moral state. Chap. xn. This must be a sufficient account of the moral states which have to do with anger. In human society, with its common life and as- sociation in words and deeds, there are some people obse- who seem to be obsequious. They are people who ness"^ try to please us by praising all that we do and never thwarting us, and who think they ought to avoid causing annoyance to anybody who comes in their way. There are others who take the contrary line of always thwarting us and never give a thought to the pain which they cause; these are called surly and Surliness, contcntious people. It is clear enough then that the moral states thus described are censurable, and that the intermediate or mean state, in virtue of which a person will assent CHAP. XII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 125 and similarly will object to the right things in the right spirit, is laudable. No special name is assigned to this mean state, but it most neariy resembles friendliness ; for the person in whom it exists answers Fnenau- to our idea of a virtuous friend, except that friendli- ness implies aflFection as well. It differs from friendli- ness in being destitute of emotion or affection for the people with whom one associates, as it is not iriend- ship or hatred that makes such a person assent to things in a right spirit but his own character. For he will so act alike to strangers and acquaintances, and to people with whom he is or is not intimate ; only in each case his action will be suitable ; for it is not natural to pay the same regard to strangers as to intimate friends, or to be equally scrupulous about causing them pain. While it is thus stated in general terms that such a person will associate with other people in a right spirit, it must be added that, in his endeavour to avoid causing pain or to cooperate in giving pleasure, he will never lose sight of what is noble and ex- pedient. For it seems that he has to do with such pleasures and pains as occur in human society. Whenever then it is not honourable for him or is injurious to cooperate in giving pleasure, he will object to giving it, and will prefer to cause pain ; or if a thing brings discredit and considerable discredit or injury upon its author, while opposition to it causes him only slight pain, he will not accept it but will raise an objection to it. He will not associate in the same spirit with people of high position and with ordinary people, or 126 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. with people whom he knows well and whom he knows only slightly, and so on as other differences may occur ; but he will render to each class its proper due. Again, while he chooses the promotion of pleasure in itself, and shrinks from the infliction of pain, he will be guided by a consideration of consequences, if they are greater than the immediate pleasure or pain, i.e. of nobleness and expediency ; in other words he will inflict slight pains for the sake of great subsequent pleasure. Such is then the intermediate or mean character, although it has no proper name. But if a person tries to promote the pleasure of others, he may either aim at being pleasant without having an ulterior object, and then he will be called complaisant, or it may be his object to get some personal advantage in the way of money or of the good things which money Flattery, brings with it, and then he will be called a flatterer. If a person on the other hand is disagreeable to everybody, be is a surly and contentious fellow, as p. 124. has been said. The extreme states here appear to be opposed to one another rather than to the mean state, because the mean state has no name. CHAP.xin. The mean state of which boastfulness is an ex- treme has very much the same sphere, and it' also is nameless. But it will be worth while to examine these states ; for we shall better understand the facts of character after discussing the moral characters severally, and shall be convinced that the virtues are mean states, by finding this to be the universal rule. 1 Beading avTri. CHAP. XIII. J OF ARISTOTLE. 127 • The people who in the converse and intercourse of life make it their object to give pleasure or pain have been already described. Let us now speak of such people as are truthful and false, whether in word or in deed or in their pretensions. It seems that the boaster is one who is fond of ^°*^'*°i- ness. pretending to possess the qualities which the world esteems, although he does not possess them, or does not possess them to the extent that he pretends. The ironicaP person on the contrary disclaims or irony, disparages what he possesses, the intermediate person, who is a sort of "plain dealer," is truthful both in life and in speech ; he admits the fact of his posses- sions, he neither exaggerates nor disparages them. It is possible to be both boastful and ironical either with or without an ulterior object. But every man speaks, acts and lives in accordance with his character, unless he has an ulterior object in view. Falsehood in itself is base and censurable, truth is noble and laudable; so too the truthful person, as holding a mean or intermediate position, is laudable, the'untruthful people are both censurable, but especi- ally the boaster. Let us speak of them both, beginning with the TrutUui- truthful person. We are not speaking of one who is °^^^" truthful in legal covenants, or in all such matters as lie within the domain of justice or injustice (for these would be matters belonging to a different virtue), but where without any such important issue at stake a ^ "Irony" is not an exact equivalent of the Greek elpavcla, which denotes the character of one who depreciates himself; " dissimulator opis propriae" in Horace's words. 128 THE NICOMACHBAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. person is truthful both in word and in life, because his moral state is truthful. Such a person would seem to be Tirtuous ; for he who is a lover of truth and truthful where truth is of no importance will be equally true where it is of greater importance. He will avoid falsehood in important matters as involving disgrace; for he avoided it in itself apart from its consequences; but so to avoid it is laudable. He inclines by preference to an understatement of the truth, as it appears to be in better taste than an overstatement, for all excesses are offensive. Preten- A pcrsou who pretends to greater things than he tiousness. -j? i i ij. • l- j. • j • possesses, it he has no ulterior object in doing so, seems to be a person of low character, as otherwise he would not take pleasure in a falsehood ; but he looks more like a fool than a knave. Supposing he has an " object, if the object be glory or honour, the pretenti- ous person, like the boaster*, is not highly censurable; but if it be money or the means of getting money, his Boastful- conduct is more discreditable. It is not a particular faculty, but a particular moral purpose, which consti- tutes the boaster ; for it is for virtue of his moral state and his character that he is a boaster, as a person is a liar, if he takes pleasure in falsehood for its own sake, or as a means of winning reputation or gain. Thus it is that boastful people, if their object is reputation, pretend to such qualities as win praise or congratulation, but if their object is gain, they pretend to such qualities as may be beneficial to their 1 The words cor 6 oKa^dv are probably spurious, as Mr Bywater has seen; they make good sense, but it would seem that the sense requires rather as ovSe 6 aKa(dv. CHAP. XIV.3 OF AEISTOTLE. 129 neighbours, and cannot be proTed not to exist, e.g. to skill in prophesying or medicine. This is the reason why the great majority of boasters pretend to such qualities as these, and make a boast of them as they are beneficial and it is difficult to disprove them. Ironical people, on the other hand, in depreciating tony, themselves, show a more refined character, for it seems that their object is not to make gain but to avoid pomposity. They are particularly fond of disclaiming the same qualities as the boaster aflects, viz. the qualities which the world esteems, as was the way, e.g. of Socrates. People, whose pretensions apply to such things Hnmbng. as are trivial and obvious, are called humbugs ; they deserve nothing but contempt. Sometimes irony itself appears to be boastfiilness, as in the dress of the Lacedaemonians ; for exaggerated deficiency is a form of boastfulness as well as excess. But people who employ irony with moderation, and upon such occasions as are not too obvious and palpable, present an appearance of refinement. The boaster appears to be the opposite of the truthful man, as being worse than the ironical man. As relaxation enters into life no less than business, Chap.xiv. and one element of relaxation is playful diversion, it seems that here too there is a manner of intercourse which is in good taste ; there are right things to say and a right way of saying them, and the same is true of listening. But the right way of speaking or listening will differ according to the class of people to whom one speaks or listens. It is clear that in this matter as in others it is w. N. E. 9 130 THE NICOMACHAEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. possible to go beyond, or to fall short of, the mean. Buf- Now they who exceed the proper limit in ridicule foonery. ^^^^ ^^ ^^ bufFoons and vulgar people, as their heart is set upon exciting ridicule at any cost, and they aim rather at raising a laugh than at using decorous Boorish- language and not giving pain to their butt. On the other hand they who will never themselves speak a word that is ridiculous, and who are indignant with everybody who speaks so, may be said to be boorish and rude. Wittiness. Peoplo whose fun is in good taste are called witty {evTpatreKoi), a name which implies the happy turns' of their art, as these happy turns may be described as movements of the character ; for charac- ters, like bodies, are judged by their movements. But as it is never necessary to look far for subjects of ridicule and as an excessive fondness for fun and mockery is pretty universal, it happens that not only true wits but bufFoons are described as witty, because they are amusing. But it is clear from what has been said that there is a diflference, and indeed a wide difference, between the two. Tact. The characteristic of the mean state is tact. A person of tact is one who will use and listen to such language only as is suitable to an honourable gentle- man; for there is such language as an honourable gentleman may fitly use and listen to in the way of fun, and the fun of a gentleman is different from that of a slavish person, and again, the fun of a cultivated person from that of one who is uncultivated. We ^ evrpaircXia is connected with Tpentiv "to turn." CHAP. XIV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 131 may see this to be so at once by a comparison of the old and the new comedy; in the former it was obscenity of language which raised a laugh, but in the latter it is rather innuendo, and this makes a great difference from the point of view of deconmi. Is it then to be the definition of a good jester that he uses such language as befits a gentleman, or that he does not give pain, or actually gives pleasure, to his listener? It is probably impossible to determine this point, as different things are detestable or agree- able to different people. But the language to which a person listens wiU correspond to the language which he uses ; for it seems that he will make such jests as he can bear to listen to. There wiU be some kinds of jest then that he wiU not make, for mockery is a species of reviling, and there are some kinds of re- viling which legislators prohibit ; they ought perhaps to have prohibited certain kinds of jesting as well. This will be therefore the moral state of the refined gentleman ; he will be, so to say, a law unto himself. Such is then the mean, or intermediate character, whether it be called tact or wittiness. But the buffoon is the slave of his own sense of humour; he wiU spare neither himself nor anybody else, if he can raise a laugh, and he wiU use such language as no person of refinement would use or sometimes even listen to. The boor is one who is useless for such social purposes; he contributes nothing, and takes offence at everything. Yet it seems that relaxation and fun are indispensable elements in life. 9—2 132 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IV. The mean states then in life which have been described, are three, viz. friendliness, tmihfulness, and wittiness. They are all concerned with the association of people in certain words and deeds. They are different in that one is concerned with truth and the others with pleasure, and, of the two which are concerned with pleasure, one finds its sphere in amusements, the other in the general intercourse of life. Chap. XV. It would not be right to speak of a sense of shame Shame. ^g g^ virtue, for it is more like an emotion than a moral state ; at least it may be defined as a kind of fear of ignominy, and in its effects it is analogous to the fear of dangers, for people blush when they are ashamed, and turn pale when they are afraid of death. It is clear then that both affections are in a sense corporeal, and this seems to be a mark of an emotion rather than of a moral state. The emotion is one which is appropriate not to all ages but to youth. We consider that the young ought to show a sense of shame, as their life being directed by emotion is fuU of mistakes, and it is shame which holds them in check. Again, while we praise young men for exhibiting a sense of shame, nobody would praise an old man for shamefacedness, as we hold that he ought not to do anything which occasions shame. Neither will a virtuous person feel shame, as shame is occasioned by misconduct ; for he ought not to misconduct himself. It makes no difference if there are some things which are really disgraceful, and others which are regarded as dis- graceful ; people ought not to do either, and therefore CHAP. XV.] or ARISTOTLE. 133 ought not to be ashamed. It is only a man of low character who will be capable of doing anything that is disgraceful. The idea of a person living in such a moral state that, if he were to do anything of the kind, he would be ashamed, and of his therefore imagining himself to be virtuous, is absurd; for shame is occasioned by voluntary actions alone, and the virtuous man will never voluntarily do what is base. Still shame can be virtuous only hypothetically. It implies that, if a person should act in a particular way, he would be ashamed; but there is nothing hypothetical in the virtuous. Again, granting that it is base to be shame- less and to feel no shame at doing disgraceful deeds, we need not conclude that it is virtuous to do them and to be ashamed of doing them. Similarly, continence' is not a virtue, but a sort of mixed state as will be shown in the sequel". But let us now proceed to consider justice. 1 The point of similarity is that continence (ty/cparcio) implies the presence of a wrong desire as shame (alSois) implies the performance of a wrong action. 2 In Book vii. BOOK V. Chap. I. We comc now to investigate justice and injustice. Justice. y^Q jjg^ye to consider what is the character of the actions with which they deal, what is the sense in which justice is a mean state, and what are the extremes between which the just is a mean. In our iuTestigation we will follow the same plan as in the virtues already described. We see that everybody who uses the term "justice" means by it the moral state which makes people capable of doing what is just, and which makes them just in action and in intention. In the same way injustice is the moral state which makes them unjust in action and in intention. Let us begin then by assuming this rough definition of justice and injustice. We regard justice as one moral state and injustice Difference as another. For the moral states are different in one morar° respect from the sciences and faculties. Whereas it states and geems that the same faculty or science applies to sciences or •' ^^^ faculties, contraries, one of two contrary moral or physical states' does not apply to its contraries; thus health 1 e|ir is a "state," in Latin habitus, generally, but not necessarily, a "moral state." CHAP. II.] NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. 135 does not produce results which are contrary to health but only results which are healthy ; for we speak of a person as walking healthily when he walks as a healthy person would walk. Now it is often possible to ascertain one of two contrary moittl states from the other, or to ascertain moral states from their phenomena, i.e. from their cavses and consequences. For if it is evident what is a good state of health, it becomes evident at once what is a bad state ; or again, a good state of health is evident from the conditions which produce good health, and the conditions which produce good health from the good state of health ; for if a good state of health is a state in which the flesh is plump, it necessarily follows that a bad state of health is a state in which the flesh is lean, and that that which produces plumpness of flesh is that which produces good health. Again, it follows as a general rule that, if one of two opposite terms be used in a plurality of senses, so is the other, e.g. if the word "just" has several senses, so has the word "unjust." It seems that the words "justice" and "injustice" Chap.il are used in a plurality of senses, but as the various senses are closely allied, their homonymy^ or ambi- guity escapes notice, and is not so evident, as it is when the various senses are wholly distinct ; for the diflFerence is striking when it is one of external ap- pearance, e.g. the ambiguous use of the word «\et? * A " homonym " in Ariatotelian phraseology is a word having two or more distinct senses, such as " bull," " bill " or " ball." . 136 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK V. for the clavicle of animals, and for the key which is used in locking doors. Different It ig necessarv therefore to ascertain all the various "justice" senses in which a person may be called unjust. He lustice™ is said to be unjust, if he breaks the law of the land ; he is also said to be unjust, if he takes more than his share of anything'. It is clear then that the just man will be (1) one who keeps the law, (2) one who is fair. Accordingly what is just is (1) what is lawful, (2) what is fair; what is unjust is (1) what is unlaw- fiil, (2) what is unfair. Sphere of Now, as the unjust man in the second of these two injustice!' seuscs is ouo who takes more than his share, he wiU have to do with goods, not indeed with all goods, but with all the goods of fortune, which are always good Goods in an absolute sense, but not always good relatively and to the individual. These are indeed the objects of men's prayers and pursuits ; but they ought rather to pray that such things as are absolutely good may be good also relatively to themselves, and to choose such things as are good for themselves. The unjust man does not always choose what is more than his share; on the contrary he chooses what is less than his share of such things as are absolutely evil. But as it seems that the less of two evils may, in a sense, be called a good, and to take more than one's share means to take more than one's share of what is good, he is regarded as taking more 1 I agree with Dr Jackson in omitting the words xal A avia-os and in thinking they were inserted by a copyist who did not see that " unfairness '' was implied in 6 irXfoviKrtjs. relative. CHAP. II.] OF ARISTOTLE. 137 than his share. Such a person may be called unfair; for unfairness is a general and comprehensive term. The law-breaker being, as we saw, unjust and the Chap. in. law-abiding person just, it is clear that whatever is lawful is in some sense just ; for such things as are prescribed by legislative authority are lawful, and all such things we call just. Laws pronounce upon all subjects with a view to the interest of the community as a whole, or of those who are its best or leading citizens whether in virtue or in any similar sense. Thus there is one sense in which we use the term "just" of all that tends to create and to conserve happiness and the elements of happiness in the body poHtia The law commands us to perform the actions of the courageous person, ie. not to leave the ranks, or run away, or throw down our arms ; the actions of the temperate person, i.e. to abstain from adultery and outrage, or the actions of the gentle person, i.e. to abstain from assault and abuse, and so with all the other virtues and vices, prescribing some actions and prohibiting others, and doing all this in a right spirit, if it be a right law, but in a spirit which is not equally right, if it be a law passed on the spur of the moment. Justice then, as so defined, is complete virtue Justice and although not complete in an absolute sense, but in relation to one's neighbours. Hence it is that justice is often regarded as the supreme virtue, "more glo- rious than the star of eve or dawn"'; or as the proverb runs "Justice is the summary of all Virtue 2." ^ It looks as if the expression were a poetical quotation. * A line attributed to Theognis, Phocylides and other poets. 138 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK V. It is in the highest sense complete virtue, as being an exercise of complete virtue'. It is complete too, because he who possesses it can employ his virtue in relation to his neighbours and not merely by himself; for there are many people who are capable of exhibit- ing virtue at home, but incapable of exhibiting it in relation to their neighbours. Accordingly there seems to be good sense in the saying of Bias that "oflace "will reveal a man,"- for one who is in office is at once brought into relation and association with others. It is this same reason which makes justice alone of the virtues seem to be the good of others, as it implies a relation to others, for it promotes the interests of somebody else, whether he be a ruler or a simple fellow-citizen. As then the worst of men is he who exhibits his depravity both in his own life and in relation to his friends, the best of men is he who exhibits his virtue not in his own life only but in relation to others ; for this is a difficult task. Justice therefore in this sense of the word, is not a part of virtue but the whole of virtue ; its opposite, injustice, not a part of vice but the whole of vice. If it be asked what is the difference between virtue and justice in this sense, it is clear from what has been already said; they are the same, but the underlying conception of them is different ; the moral state which, if regarded relatively to others, is justice, if regarded absolutely as a moral state, is virtue. Chap. IV. But we are investigating the justice which is a a part* ^' P^*^ of virtue ; for there is such a justice, as we hold. of virtue. 1 Reading Tfjs reXci'as dpeTtjs XPV"'"- CHAP. IV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 139 Similarly there is a particular iniustice which requires injnstico i • i . -.TT -I. ,1 . . i , . as a part investigation. We may inter the existence of thisoi-n a shoe. Then the builder ought to receive from the cobbler some part of his work, and to give him his own work in return. If then there is proportionate equality in the first in- stance, and retaliation or reciprocity follows, the result of which we are speaking wiU be attained*. Otherwise the exchange wiU not be equal or perma- nent. For there is no reason why the work of the one should not be superior to that of the other, and 1 The connexion of x«P" ^'t^ the xop'"? suggests the pro- priety of adopting the English word "grace" in translating this passage ; but x^P" is more strictly " favour " or " kindness " than "grace." 2 " Cross-conjunction " is a technical term which may be explained thus. Suppose that in the figure, A is the builder, B the cobbler, C the house and D the shoes, suppose too that A is combined with D and B with C, then the proportion A+I>:B+C::A : B, is the result of " cross-conjunction.'' 3 I think it is clear that the case here supposed is one in which two persons desiring to make an exchange of goods have goods of equal value to exchange ; then the simple exchange of one good for the other satisfies the law of retaliation or reci- procity. 152 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [BOOK V. therefore they ought to be equalized. ('This is equally the case with all the arts; they would be destroyed, if the eflfect upon the patient were not, in kind, quantity and quality, the same as the effort of the agent.) For association is formed, not by two doctors, but by a doctor and a husbandman, and generally by people who are different, and not equal, and who need to be equalized. It follows that such things as are the subjects of exchange must in some sense be comparable. This is the reason for the Money. invention of money. Money is a sort of medium or mean; for it measures everything and consequently measures among other things excess or defect, e.g. the number of shoes which are equivalent to a house or a meal. As a builder then is to a cobbler, so must so many shoes be to a house or a meal; for otherwise there would be no exchange or association. But this will be impossible, unless the shoes and the house or meal are in some sense equalized. Hence arises the necessity of a single universal standard of measurement, as was said before. This standard is in truth the demand for mutual services, which holds society together ; for if people had no wants, or their wants were dissimilar*, there would be either no exchange, or it would not be the same as it is now. 1 The sentence transposed from p. 87,1. 31 is most conveniently placed here, but at the beat it is an interruption of the argument. It seems to mean that in such an art or science as e.g. medicine a person by using certain means must be sure of producing certain effects. 2 I understand by " dissimilar wants" wants which cannot be at once supplied by mutual service. CHAP, vin.] oi/aristotle. 153 Money (vo/iia-fia) is a sort of recognized represen- tative of this demand. That is the reason why it is called money (v6/j.ia-/j,a), because it has not a natural but a conventional (voficp) existence, and because it is in our power to change it, and make it useless. Retaliation or reciprocity wiU take place, when the terms have been so equated that, as a husband- man is to a cobbler, so is the cobbler's ware to the husbandman's \ But we must bring the terms to a figure of proportion not* after the exchange has taken place — or one of the two extremes wiU have both advantages i.e. mil have its superiority counted ttoice over — but when both parties stiU retain their own wares; they will then be equal and capable of association, because it is possible to establish the proper equality between them. Thus let A be a husbandman, O food, B a cobbler, and D his wares, 1 Suppose the husbandman to ofiFer in exchange a quarter of corn and the cobbler a certain number of pairs of boots ; it is necessary to decide how many pairs of boots are equal in value to a quarter of corn before reciprocity (to avriTreTrovdos) can take place. ^ The ov should be retained ; but it is desirable to treat the words ei 8e fi^ . . . . axpov as parenthetical, and to place a comma after aKpov and a colon after ra ovtSv. If I understand this difficult sentence, it means that the husbandman (in the case supposed above) having received in exchange a number of pairs of boots calculated upon an estimate of his commercial superiority to the cobbler must not claim to have that superiority calculated again, when the exchange has already been effected. But to erepov aKpov is an incorrect phrase as the two parties of the exchange) are not the two oKpa in the "figure of proportion." See note on p. 151 of this translation. I incline to think that aKpov should be omitted. 154 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK V. which are equated to the food. But if this kind of reciprocity were impossible, there would be no asso- ciation. The fact that it is demand which is like a principle of unity binding society together is evident because, if there is no mutual demand on the part of two persons, if neither of them or one only needs the services of the other, they do not effect an exchange, whereas, if somebody wants what somebody else has, e.g. wine, they efifect an exchange, giving the wine e.g. in return for the right of importing corn. Here then the wine and the com must be equated. Money is serviceable with a view to future ex- change; it is a sort of security which we possess that, if we do not want a thing now, we shall be able to get it when we do want it ; for if a person brings money, it must be in his power to get what he wants. It is true that money is subject to the same laws as other things; its value is not always the same; still it tends to have a more constant value than any thing else. All things, then, must have a pecuniary value, as this will always facilitate exchange, and so will facilitate association. Money therefore is like a measure that equates things, by making them commensurable ; for associa- tion would be impossible without exchange, exchange without equality, and equality without commensura- bility. Although it is in reality impossible that things which are so widely different should become com- mensurable, they may become sufficiently so for prac- tical purposes. There must be some single standard CHAP. IX.] OF ARISTOTLE. 155 then, and that a standard upon which the world agrees; hence it is called money (vo/tto-^ia)', for it is this which makes all things commensurable, as money is the universal standard of measurement. Let A be a house, B ten minae, O a couch. Now A is half B if the house is worth, or is equal to, five minae. Again, the couch G is the tenth part of B. It is clear then that the number of couches which are equal to a house is five. It is clear too that this was the method of exchange before the invention of money; for it makes no diflerence whether it is five couches or the value of five couches that we give in exchange for a house. The nature of the just and the unjust has now Chap. ix. been described. The definitions which have been given make it clear that just conduct is a mean be- tween committing and suffering injustice; for to commit injustice is to have too much, and to suffer it is to have too little. But justice is a mean state, not Justice a • ,1 11 .J 1 J J 'I J mean state m the same sense as the virtues already described, b„t not in but rather as aiming at the mean, while injustice geLfas* aims at the extremes I It is justice which entitles o'lier vir- the just man to be regarded as capable of deliberately effecting what is just, and of making a distribution whether between himself and somebody else, or be- tween two other people, not in such a way as to give himself too large, and his neighbour too smaU a share 1 Again, the point lies in the connexion of vo/ucrpi '' money '' with wo/ios " convention " or " agreement." ^ Justice then is distinguished from the other virtues, inasmuch as the extremes of which it is the mean fall under the same, instead of under different vices. 156 THE mCOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK V. of what is desirable, and conversely to give himself too small and his neighbour too large a share of what is injurious, but to give both "himself and his neigh- bour such a share as is proportionately equal, and to do the same when the distribution is between other people. Injustice on the contrary aims at that which is unjust ; but that which is unjust is disproportionate excess and defect of what is profitable or injurious. Hence injustice is excess and defect, inasmuch as it aims at excess and defect, viz, excess of what is absolutely profitable, and defect of what is injurious in one's own case, while in the cases of other people, although they are generally similar, the violation of proportion may take the form either of excess or of defect. But the defect of unjust action is to suffer injustice, the excess is to inflict it. This then may be taken as a sufficient account of the nature of justice and injustice respectively, and similarly of that which is just or unjust in general. Chap.x. But a person may do injustice without being Mtion*not necessarily unjust. What then, is the nature of such the same unjust actions that, if a person commits them, he is thing as J . ± X. ■ i-i X injustice, proved at once to be m some particular respect unjust, e.g. to be a thief, an adulterer, or a robber? I think the answer is that there is no such distinct class of actions*, for a person may commit adultery with a woman, knowing who she is, although he commits it not from any original defect of moral purpose, but from the passion of the moment. Such 1 It is not the action but the moral purpose, which makes a man aSiKos : cp. p. 95, 1. 10 orav 5' ek irpoaipia-ems, abiKos xai llox6r)p6s. CHAP. X.] OF ARISTOTLE. 157 a person then, although he commits an act of injustice, la not unjust; thus he is not a thief, although he committed a theft, nor an adulterer, although he commit adultery, and so on\ The relation of retaliation to justice has been already described. But we must not forget that the object of our inquiry is at once justice in an absolute sense, and political justice" i.e. such justice as exists PoKticai among people who are associated in a common life '*" *^' with a view to independence, and who enjoy freedom and equality whether proportionate or arithmetical'. It follows that, where this condition does not exist, people are not capable of mutual political justice, but only of a certain justice which is analogous to it. For justice, strictly so called, can exist only where the relations* of people are determined by law, and the existence of law implies injustice, as the administra- tion Q/"justice is the determiaation of what is just and ' ^ Dr Jackson transfers the first two sentences of ch. 10, p. 91, IL 18 — 26 to p. 95, 1. 9, and the transference is clearly an improvement especially as the third sentence resumes the subject of retaliation and of justice generally. There is no such reason, I think, for disturbing the position of the words iras luv oSv cx« . . . eiptjTai TTporepoK 11. 26, 27. 2 I apprehend that "political justice" is not the same as "justice in an absolute sense" but is, as Dr Jackson says, "the most perfect representation of it." See p. 92, IL 15, sqq. Aristotle is led to a special consideration of " political justice '' by the political view which he always took of Ethics. s In an aristocracy or oligarchy the "equality " is, in Aristotle's language, " proportionate," in a democracy it is " arithmetical." The condition of "freedom" excludes the slave population from participation in "political justice." * jrpos avToiig is better than irpog ovtovs. 158 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK V. unjust. But injustice implies unjust action, although unjust action does not always imply injustice, and tmjust action consists in assigning to oneself an un- duly large share of such things as are good in an absolute sense, and an unduly small share of such things as are bad in an absolute sense. Hence we submit to the authority, not of an individual, but of the statute book, because an individual is apt to exercise his authority in his own interests, and to make himself despot. The magistrate is a guardian of justice, and, if of justice, then of equality. It seems that he gains no advantage /rom Ais q^e, as he is assumed to be just; for he does not assign to himself a larger share of what is absolutely good, unless indeed it be proper- . tionate to his own merit. Hence he labours' in the interest of others ; which is the reason why justice is p. 138. called the good of others, as we said before. Some reward therefore must be given him in the shape of honour or privilege ; and it is when a magistrate is not content with these rewards that he makes himself despot. Jnstice of Justice, as between masters and slaves, or between STddaves, fathers and children, is not the same as political '^^^gjj""* justice, i.e. justice between citizen cmd citizen, although it resembles it, for a man cannot commit injustice in an absolute or strict sense against what is his own; but his property" and his children, until they reach a ^ Reading novel. 2 It must be remembered that a slave was as much a KTJjfia of his master as any other chatteL CHAP. X.] OF ARISTOTLE. 159 certain age and become independent*, are, as it were, parts of himself, and nobody deliberately chooses to hurt himself; hence injustice to oneself is an im- possibility. It follows that political justice and in- justice are also impossible in the rdation of a master to slaves or of a father to children; for they depend, as we said, upon law, and exist only where law has a p. 157. natural existence i.e. among people who, as we saw, enjoy equality of rule and subjection. There is more scope then for justice in relation to a wife than in relation to children and property, for this, i.e. justice in the relation of husband and i<»/b, Jnstice of is domestic justice, although this again is different ana wSe.. from political justice. Political justice is partly natural and partly con- Political ventional. ^■"'"'"■ The part which is natural is that which has the (i) natural, same authority everywhere, and is independent of opinion ; that which is conventional is such that it (?) conven- does not matter in the first instance whether it takes one form or another, it only matters when it has been laid down, e.g. that the ransom of a prisoner should be a mina, or that a goat, and not two sheep, should be offered in sacrifice, and all legislative enactments which are made in particular cases, as the sacrifice in honour of Brasidas" at Amphipolis, and the provisions of an Act of Parliament. It is the opinion of some people that all the rules of justice are conventional, because that which is 1 The MSS. authority is in favour of omitting /xi) before 2 See Thucydides v. ch. 11. 160 THE mCOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK V. natural is immutable and has the same authority everywhere, as fire bums equally here and in Persia, but they see the rules of justice continually altering. But this is not altogether true, although it is true to some extent. Among the gods indeed it is pro- bably not true at aU; but in this world, although there is such a thing as natural justice, still all justice is variable. Nevertheless there is a justice which is, as well as a justice which is not, natural. Within the sphere of the contingent it is easy to see what kind of thing it is that is natural, and what kind that is not natural but legal and conventional, both kinds being similarly variable. The same dis- tinction will apply to other cases ; thus the right hand is naturally stronger than the left, although there is nobody' who may not acquire the power of using both hands alike. Such rules of justice as depend on convention and convenience may be compared to standard measures ; for the measures of wine and corn are not everywhere equal, but are larger where people buy and smaller where they seU'. Similarly, such rules of justice as exist not by nature, but by the will of Man, are not everywhere the same, as polities themselves are not everywhere the same, although there is everywhere only one naturally perfect polity. But every rule of justice or law stands to indivi- '■ Beading wavras with the MSS. 2 The buyers and sellers are, I conceive, the same people, viz. merchants who make wholesale purchases and sell them by retail. So Dr Jackson, who translates " being larger in wholesale, and smaller in retail, markets." CHAP. X.] OF AKISTOTLE. 161 dual actions in the relation of the universal to par- ticulars; for while actions are numerous, every such rule is one, as being universal. There is a difference between an act of injustice and that which is unjust, between an act of justice and that which is just. A thing is unjust by nature, or by ordinance ; but this very' thing, when it is done, is an act of injustice, although, before it is done, it is only unjust. The same is true of an act of justice ^ But the several kinds of acts of justice, or injustice, their number, and their sphere, will form subjects of investigation hereafter. "" Such being the things which are just and unjust, a person may be said to act justly or unjustly when he does them voluntarily. When he does them m- voluntarily, he does not act justly or unjustly, except in an accidental sense, i.e. he does what is accidentally just or unjust. The definition of an act of justice or injustice Voinntary depends upon its voluntary or involuntary character; of just a^d for when it is voluntary, it is open to censure, and it ^?^' is then also an act of injustice. It will be unjust then in a sense, but will not amount to an act of injustice, if it lacks voluntariness. By a voluntary action I mean, as has been already Voluntary . J 1 I. . . ) 1 . action. said, such an action as is m a person s power, and is p. 64. J- The best MSS. give airo 8e tovto. ^ After this sentence Aristotle remarks that the word for au " act of justice " is generally bmaumpayrifui, hixalaiia being re- stricted in meaning to the " correction of an act of injustice " but the remark, as it turns upon the correct use of the Greek words, is untranslateable. W. N. E. 11 162 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK V. performed by him knowingly, and not in ignorance of the person to whom he does it, or of the instrument with which he does it, or of the result, e.g. of the person whom he strikes, and the instrument with which he strikes, and the effect of his blow ; and not only so, but he must not perform it accidentally or under compulsion ; for if a person e.g. were to seize his hand and strike somebody else with it, it would not be a voluntary action, as not being in his own power. Again, it is possible that the person struck may be his father, and that he may know him to be a man or some one who is present, but may not know him to be his father. The same sort of distinction must be made in regard to the effect and to the action gene- rally. If an action is done in ignorance, or, although not done in ignorance, is not in a person's power, or if he is compelled to do it, it is involuntary ; for there are many things in the course of nature which we both do and suffer with full knowledge but which are not either voluntary or involuntary, as e.g. growing old or dying. The accidental character may belong equally to just and unjust actions. Thus a person may restore a deposit involuntarily and from motives of fear; but in that case it is not right to say that he does what is just or that his conduct is just, except acci- dentally. Similarly, if a person under compulsion and involuntarily refuses to restore a deposit, he must be said to be unjust and to do what is unjust acci- dentally. Voluntary actions we perform either with or with- out deliberate purpose — with it, if we perform them €HAP. X.] OF ARISTOTLE. 163 after previous deliberation, and without it, if without such deliberation. There are three ways in which people may hurt each other in society. An action done in ignorance is called a mistake, when the person affected, or the Mistake. thing done, or the instrument, or the effect, is not such as the agent supposed. For instance, he sup- posed that he would not hit or would not hit with the particular instrument or would not hit the par- ticular person, or that the blow would not have the particular effect ; but the effect proved different from his expectation, e.g. it was his intention to prick a person, and not to wound him, or the person was different, or the instrument'. Now when the hurt done is contrary to expecta- Mishap. tion, it is a mishap; but when, although it is not contrary to expectation, it does not imply malice, it is a mistake ; for a person makes a mistake, when the original culpability lies in himself, but he meets with a mishap, when it lies outside himself. When a person acts with knowledge, but without deliberation, it is an act of injustice, as in all human actions which Act of arise from anger and other necessary or natural ^'"^ "^' emotions; for in doing such hurt, and making such mistakes we are unjust, and they are acts of injustice, but it does not foUow that we are at once unjust or vicious, as the hurt is not the consequence of vice. But when the action is the result of deliberate injustice. ^ Beading poirivti, as derived in Eudemus' view from p6vtjiiK) on the other hand apprehends particular facts or duties which are also "ultimates" as being the last steps in the process of reasoning from " first principles " to knowledge or action ; but the "ultimates" are essentially different 13—2 reason. 196 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [BOOK VIw it is the capacity for judging of pradential matters that entitles a person to be considered a person of intelligence, and of sound or considerate judgment ; for equity is the common characteristic of all that is good in our relation to our neighbours. Another proof that these faculties havet he same tendency is that matters of action are always particular and ultimate ; for it is the business of the prudent man to understand them, and intelligence and judgment are also concerned with matters of action, i.e. with ultimate truths. Intuitive The intuitivc reason, too, deals with ultimate truths at both ends of the mental process ; for both the first and last terms, i.e. both first principles and, pmi/mdar facts, are intuitirely, and not logically, apprehended, and while on the one hand in demon- strative reasonings it apprehends the immutable first terms, on the other in matters of conduct it apprehends the ultimate or contingent term which forms the minor premiss of the syllogism ; for it is truths of the latter sort which are the first principles or original sources of the idea of the end or object of human life. As the universal law then is derived from par- ticular facts, these facts must be apprehended by perception, or in other words, by intuitive reason. This is why it is thought that these faculties are natural, and that while nobody is naturally wise, men are naturally gifted with judgment, intelligence, and intuitive reason. It is an argument in favour of this in the two cases. It is clear from p. H2, l,'26 that Eudemus does not use vovs here in its strict sense, but cp. p. 110, II. 10—13. CHAP. XII. J OF ARISTOTLE. 197 Tiew that we regard these faculties as accompanying the different periods of life, and that intuitive reason and judgment belong to a particular period ; which implies that they are the gifts of Nature. The intuitive reason then is at once beginning and end. It is from the truths of intuitive reason that demonstration starts, and with them that it is con- cerned. It is right therefore to pay no less attention to the undemonstrated assertions and opinions of such persona as are experienced and advanced in years or prudent than to their demonstrations; for their experienced eye gives them the power of correct vision ^ Thus the nature of prudence and of vrisdbm, the subjects with which they are severally concerned and the fact that each is a virtue of a different part of the soul, have now been explained. But it is still possible to raise the question inCHAP.xin. regard to them. What is their utility ? For wisdom ^^X^^ pays no regard to any thing which makes a man^dpru- happy, as it is wholly unproductive. Prudence on the other hand does regard happiness; but what is the good of it? For let it be granted that it is prudence which deals with all that is just and noble and good for a man, and that these are the things which a good man naturally does; still the mere ^ At the close of this difficult Chapter it may be obserred that -,_ Eudemus (so far as he expresses himself clearly) regards the "intuitive reason" (voOs) as having the power of apprehending (1) the universal axiomatic truths which deductive reasoning presupposes, (2) the particular facts In life which form the materials of induction. 198 THE NICOMACHBAN ETHICS [BOOK VI. knowledge of them no more augments our capacity of action, if the virtues are, as they are, moral states, than the knowledge of what is healthy or vigorous, i.e. healthy or vigorous in the sense not of producing health or vigour but of issuing from a healthy or vigorous state; for mere knowledge of medicine or gymnastics does not augment our capacity of action. If again it be assumed that a man is to be prudent, not in order that he may perform virtuous actions, but in order that he may become a virtuous man, it follows that prudence will not be of any use to virtuous people, nor indeed to people who are destitute of virtue; for it will make no difference whether they possess prudence themselves, or follow the advice of others who possess it. And, if so, we may be content to treat prudence as we treat health ; for although we desire to be healthy, we do not study medicine. Again, it would seem paradoxical that prudence, although inferior to wisdom should enjoy a higher authority, as it seems that it must; for it is the productive faculty which is the ruling and command- ing faculty everywhere. These are the questions which must be discussed ; at present we have merely raised difficulties in regard to them. Now the first remark to be made is that wisdom and prudence will be necessarily desirable in them- selves, inasmuch as each is a virtue of one of the two parts of the soul, even if neither of them produces anything. And the second is that they are produc- tive. Thus wisdom is productive of happiness, not CHAP. XITL] of ARISTOTLE. 199 indeed in the sense in which the medical art produces health, but in the sense in which health' itself produces it; that is to say, as wisdom is a part of complete Tirtue, the possession and exercise of it make a man happy. Again, a man discharges his proper function when he acts in accordance with prudence and moral virtue ; for while virtue ensures the correctness of the end which is in view, prudence ensures the correctness of the means to it. (The fourth part of the soul, viz. the vegetative part, possesses no moral virtue like the other parts; it has no power of performing or not performing moral action.) " If it be said that prudence does not augment our capacity of doing what is noble and just, let us go a little further back and look at it in this way. We admit that there are some people who, al- though they do what is just, are not yet themselves just, e.g, if they do what the laws prescribe, but do it either unwillingly or in ignorance, or for some secon- dary motive, and not for love of the thing itself, although indeed they do what is right, and do all that ' The carelessness of language is conspicuous ; but the meaning seems to be that when the state of the body is healthy, it k^jF capable of a healthy activity or, as Mr Peters puts it, the e^isM health produces the ivcpyeta of health. ^ ' ^ This sentence, which I have bracketed as being parenthetical, is an interruption of the argument. The soul (V^x"?') has been divided into the rational (7-6 \6yov exov) and the irrational {t6 SKoyov) parts, and the rational part has been farther subdivided. See p. 102, 11. 22 — 27. The virtues of these three parts have been described, and there remains only the irrational or vegetative (to OpeirTtKov) which is here excluded from the conception of virtue. 200 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VI. a virtuous man ought to do. It follows as a corollary that a person may be good in all his actions, if he is in a particular moral state, at the time of acting, i.e. if he acts from moral purpose, and for the sake of the actions themselves. Now, while it is virtue which ensures the correct- ness of the moral purpose, it is the function not of virtue but of a different faculty to decide upon such means as are natural in order to give effect to that purpose. But we must dwell upon this point with greater attention and exactness. csevemcss. There is a certain faculty which is called clever- ness. It is the faculty of hitting upon and acting upon the means which conduce to a given object. If then the object be noble, the faculty is laudable, but if ignoble, it is unscrupulousness; hence we speak of prudent people and unscrupulous' people alike as clever. Prudence is not cleverness, but neither can it exist without the faculty of cleverness. But this eye of the soul, i.e. prudence^ does not attain its perfect p. 199. condition without virtue, as has been already stated, and as is clear; for all such syllogisms as relate to action have this major premiss: "Since the end or supreme good is, so and so," whatever it may be ; for the sake of argument it may be whatever we like. But the supreme good is not apprehended except by the good man, as vice distorts and deceives the mind in regard to the principles of action. It is evident therefore that it is impossible for a man to be prudent unless he is good. 1 The sense of the passage seems to require rois iravoipyovs. CHAP. XIII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 201 We must resume then the consideration of virtue. For the case of virtue is much the same as that of prudence in relation to cleverness. Prudence, al- though not identical with cleverness, is akin to it;Virtne and similarly natural virtue is akin to virtue proper, and but is not identical with it For it seems that the ^^°^"- various moral qualities are in some sense innate in everybody. We are just, temperate, courageoiis, and the like, from our very birth. Nevertheless, when we speak of the good, properly so called, we mean something different from this, and we expect to find these qualities in another form; for the natural moral states exist even in children and the lower animals, but apart from reason they are clearly hurtful. How- ever this at least seems evident, that, as a strong body, if it moves without sight, stumbles heavily, because it cannot see, so it is Avith natural virtue; but let it acquire reason, and its action becomes excellent. When that, is the case, the moral state which before resembled virtue will be virtue properly so called. Hence, as in the. sphere of opinion there are two special forms, viz. cleverness and common sense, so in that of the moral character there are two, viz. natural virtue and virtue proper, and of these the latter is impossible without prudence. Accordingly some people hold that all the virtues are forms of pru- dence. Socrates who was one of them was partly right and partly wrong in his researches; he was wrong in thinking that all the virtues are forms of prudence, but right in saying that they cannot exist without prudence. -202 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VI. It is an evidence of this truth that at the present time everybody in defining virtue, after stating the subjects to which it relates, adds that it is the moral state which accords with right reason, and right reason is prudential reason. It seems then to be generally divined that such a moral state, viz. the moral state which is in accordance with prudence, is virtue, but it is necessary to make a slight change of expression. It is not only the moral state which is in accordance with jight reason but the moral state which is under the guidance of right reason, i.e. virtue ; but right reason in such matters is prudence. While Socrates then considered the virtues to be forms of reason, as being all sciences, we consider them to be under the guidance of reason. It is clear then from what has been said that goodness in the proper sense is impossible without prudence, and prudence without moral virtue. And not only so, but this is the answer to an objection which will perhaps be oirged in argument, viz. that the virtues are found apart one from another; for the same person is not perfectly disposed to all the virtues ; consequently he will already have acquired one virtue before he has acquired another. The answer is that, although this is possible in the case of the natural virtues, it is impossible in the case of such virtues as entitle a person io be called good in an absolute sense ; for if the one virtue of prudence exist, all the others will co-exist with it. It is clear that, even if prudence were not practi- cal, it would be requisite as being a virtue of its part of the soul; and because the moral purpose will not CHAP. XIIL] of ARISTOTLE. 203 be right without prudence or virtue, as the one, vis. virtiie, leads to the attainment of the end, and the other, viz. prudence, to the choice of the right means. At the same time prudence is not the mistress of wisdom or of the better part of the sovl, any more than medicine is the mistress of health. For pru- dence does not employ wisdom, but aims at producing it; nor does it rule wisdom, but rules in wisdom's interest. And to say that prudence rules wisdom is much the same thing as to say that statesmanship rules the Gods, because it regulates all the institu- tions, and among them the religious observances, of the State. BOOK VII. Chap. I. BuT it is time to make a fresh start by laying it dfM^acters: down that there are three species of moral character Vice, In- which ought to be avoided, viz. vice, incontinence, continence, i •■ i. Brutality, and brutality. The opposites of the two first are clear. We call the one virtue, and the other continence. As the opposite of brutality it will be most appropriate to name the virtue which is above us, i.e. what may be called heroic or divine virtue, as when Homer makes Priam say of Hector, that he was exceeding good "nor seemed The son of mortal man, but of some god'." If then it is true, as is often said, that apotheosis is the reward of preeminent human virtue, it is clear that the moral state which is opposite to the brutal, will be some such state of preeminent virtue ; for as in a brute, so too in a God, there is no such thing as virtue or vice, but in the one something more honour- able than virtue, and in the other something generi- cally different from vice. But as it is rare to find a 1 Iliad XXIV. 258, 259. CH. I.] NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. 205 "divine man V if one may use the fayourite phrase of the Lacedaemonians when they admire a person exceedingly, so too the brutal man is rare in the world. Brutality is found chiefly among the barba- BrntaJity. rians, although it is sometimes the result of disease and mutilation; and if people are preeminently vicious, we speak of them by the same opprobrious name. However, it will be right to say something about this sort of disposition later on', and we have already' discussed vice. We must therefore now speak of incontinence, effeminacy, and luxury on the one hand, and of continence and steadfastness on the other; for it would be wrong to regard these moral states as respectively identical with virtue and vice, or again as generically different from them. It will be proper here, as in other cases, to state the obvious or accepted views upon the subject, and after thoroughly discussing them, to establish the truth of all, or if not of all, of most, and the most important, of the popular opinions in regard to these emotions; for if the difficulties are solved, and the popular opinions hold their ground, the proof of them will be sufficient for our purpose. It is the popular opinion then that continence and Chap. n. steadfastness are virtuous and laudable, incontinence maSran^ and effeminacy wrong and censurable, and that th^^g^e^^gt. ness and 1 a-eios is the Laconian Doric for Oelos. It appears from Plato, Effemi- Meno, p. 99 d that the Lacedaemonians were fond of the word ^^' "divine" as descriptiTO of personal excellence. 2 In ch. 5. 2 In Books m. iv. v. 206 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VII. continent man is one who abides by his calculations, and the incontinent one who departs from them. Also that the incontinent man does what he knows to be wrong under the influence of emotion, but the continent man, knowing his desires to be wrong, is prevented by his reason from following them. Also that the temperate man is continent and steadfast ; but while some people hold that the continent and steadfast man is always temperate, others deny it, and while some speak of the licentious man as in- continent, and of the incontinent man as licentious indiscriminately, others make a distinction between them. Again, it is sometimes said that the prudent man cannot be incontinent, and at other times that some men who are prudent and clever are inconti- nent. And lastly men are called incontinent in respect, not of their sensual emotions only, but of angry passion, honour, and gain. Chap. HI. Such are the views generally entertained. Knowledge But the qucstion may be raised, How is it that a tinence!™ persou, if his Conceptions of duty are right, acts incontinently? Some people say that incontinence is impossible, if one has knowledge. It seems to them, strange, as Socrates thought, that, where knowledge exists in a man, something else should master it and drag it about like a slave. Socrates was wholly opposed to this idea; he denied the existence of incontinence, arguing that nobody with a conception of what was best could act against it, and that, if he did so act, his action must be due to ignorance. Now the Socratic theory is evidently at variance CHAP. III.] OF ABISTOTLE. 207 with the facts of experience, and if ignorance be the cause of the passion, i.e. of incontinence, it is necessary to inquire what is the nature of the ignorance. For there can be no doubt that a person who acts incontinently, however he may act, does not think his action to he right until he has got into a condition of incontinence. But there are some people who agree in part with this theory, and in part dissent from it; they admit that there is nothing which can master or overcome knowledge, but do not admit that nobody acts against what has seemed best to him. Accordingly they hold that the incontinent man, when he is mastered by his pleasures, possesses not knowledge, but only opinion. But it may be answered that, if this is opinion and not knowledge, if the resisting conception is not a strong, but a feeble one, as in cases where we hesitate how to act, a person is pardoned for not remaining true to it in the teeth of strong desires; whereas neither vice nor anything else that is cen- surable admits of pardon at alL Is it then when prudence resists the desires ^ thM a person is censured for yielding to them? For there is nothing so powerful as prudence. But that is an absurdity, as it implies that the same person is at once prudent and incontinent, and nobody will main- tain that a prudent person can voluntarily do the basest deeds. Moreover, it has been already shown that thep. i88. prudent person, whatever else he may be, is a man of ^ There should be a mark of interrogation after aurmuiovv^s. 208 THE NICOMACHBAN ETHICS [bOOK VII. action, for he is one who concerns himself with ultimate or particular facts, and he possesses the Continence other virtues as well as prudence. Again, if the per Jc^' existence of strong and base desires is essential to continence, the temperate man will not be continent, nor the continent man temperate; for it is inconsis- tent with the character of the temperate man to have extravagant or wrong desires. Yet it must be so with the continent man; for if his desires were good, the moral state which prevents his following them would be wrong, and therefore continence would not, in all cases, be virtuous. If on the other hand they were feeble and not wrong, it would be no great credit, and if they were wrong and feeble, it would be no great triumph to overcome them. Continence Again, if contiuence inclines a man to adhere to opinion, every opinion, whatever it may be, it is wrong, e.g. if it inclines him to adhere to a false opinion; and if incontinence inclines him to abandon every opinion, whatever it may be, there will be what may be called a virtuous incontinence. Thus Neoptolemus in the Philoctetes ' of Sophocles deserves praise for refusing to adhere to the line of action, which Odysseus had persuaded him to adopt, because of the pain which he felt at telling a lie. Again, if continence be defined as meaning that a person will adhere to his opinions at all costs, the sophistical argument", fallacious as it is, is perplexing. 1 The argument of Neoptolemus and Philoctetes, which illus- trates this passage, occurs in the Philoctetes w. 895 sqq. 2 It appears that "the sophistical argument" is the argument relating to folly and incontinence given below. CHAP. III.] OF ARISTOTLE. 209 The sophists, wishing to prove a paradox, and to be thought clever if they are successful in proving it, are fond of constructing a syllogism which perplexes their interlocutor. For he is caught in a logical trap, as he does not wish to acquiesce in a conclusion which is distasteful to him, and yet it is imijossible for him to escape as he cannot refute the argument. One such argument is used to prove that folly and incon- tinence together make virtue. It is urged that, if a person is foolish and incontinent, his incontinence leads him to do the opposite of that which he con- ceives to be good; but he conceives that what is really good is evil, and that it is his duty not to do it ; therefore he will do what is good and not what is evil. Again, if continence be so defined, it would seem that he who does and pursues what is pleasant from conviction and deliberate moral purpose is better than he who does so not from calculation but from incontinence ; for it is easier to cure the former, as he may be led to change his opinion. But the inconti- nent man is open to the proverbial saying "When water chokes you, what must you take to wash it down?" For if he had not already been convinced that his actions are wrong, he might have been converted and induced to give them up ; but in point of fact, although he is convinced of what is right, nevertheless he does something else. Again, if there is incontinence and continence in aU things, who is the continent man in an absolute sense ? For nobody exhibits all the forms of inconti- nence; yet there are people of whom we speak as W. N. E. 14 210 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK. VII. incontinent in an absolute sense, i.e. without qualifi- cation. Chap. IV. Such then more or less are diflaculties -which arise in regard to continence. Some of them we must ex- plain away, others we must leave; for it is impossible to solve a difficulty except by discovering a truth. It is necessary, then, to inquire (1) whether incontinent people can be said to act with knowledge or not, and if so, what is the nature of their knowledge ; (2) what is to be regarded as the sphere of continence or incontinence, i.e. whether it be pleasure or pain universally, or certain definite pleasures and pains; (3) whether the continent and the steadfast person are the same, or different, and to deal similarly with all such other questions as are germane to the present inquiry. Nature of But the first Step in the inquiry is to ask whether andinoon! the Continent and the incontinent person are distin- trnence. guished by the sphere or by the manner of their operation; in other words, whether the incontinent person is so called merely as being incontinent in certain matters, or rather as being incontinent in a certain way, or on both grounds. And the next step is to ask whether the sphere of continence and in- continence is universal or not. For one who is incontinent in an absolute sense exhibits his inconti- nence not in any and every sphere of action but in the same sphere as one who is licentious. Nor does incontinence consist in a mere indefinite disposition to certain action — ^in which case incontinence would be the same thing as licentiousness— but in a disposi- tion of a particular kind. CHAP. IV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 211 For the licentious person is led away of his own incontT- deliberate moral purpose, under the idea that he Licentious- ought always to pursue the pleasure of the moment, "^^^' but the incontinent person pursues it without any such idea. As to the theory then that it is true opinion, and Chap. v. not knowledge, against which people offend in their ^^^^^^Jlf' incontinence, it makes no difference to the argument ; nence is an for some people who have only opinions do not feel against doubt, but suppose that they have accurate know- ^nd^ ^ ^^ ledge. opinion. If it be said then that people who have opinions are more likely, owing to the weakness of their con- viction, to act against their conception of what is right than people who have knowledge, it may be answered that there is no such difference between knowledge and opinion; for some people are as strongly convinced of their opinions as others of their knowledge, as the example of Heraclitus' shows. But we use the word "knowledge" in two distinct Two senses senses; we speak of a person as "knowing" if he ledge." possesses knowledge but does not apply it, and also if he applies his knowledge. There will be a differ- ence then between doing wrong, when one possesses knowledge, but does not reflect upon it, and so doing when one not only possesses the knowledge but reflects upon it. It is in the latter case that wrong 1 The passages quoted by Sir A. Grant from Diogenes Laertius seem to show that Heraclitus was criticized in antiquity for his dogmatism upon subjects in which scientific knowledge was im- possible. 14—2 212 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VII. action appears strange, but not if it is taken without reflexion. Again, as the premisses of the syllogism are of two modes, the major premiss being universal and the minor particular, there is nothing to prevent a person, altliough he ' has both premisses, from acting against his knowledge, if in spite of having both he applies the universal and not the particular premiss ; for it is particulars which are matters of action. Nay, there is a distinction to be made in the universal or major premiss' itself; one part of it has reference to the person, the other part to the thing ; thus, the major premiss may he, "Dry things are good for every man,^' and the minor premiss "So and so is a man," or "Such a thing is dry," but the fact that the particular thing is of a particular kind may either be not known or may have no effect tipon the mind. These different modes of the premisses of the syllogism constitute an immense difference in the knowledge so required. There is nothing paradoxical then in saying that the incontinent person possesses knowledge of one kind ; but it would be surprising if he possessed knowledge of another. Again, it is possible for men to possess knowledge in a different manner from those which have just been described. For in a case where a person possesses knowledge 1 Aristotle is fond of expressing moral or mental truths syllogistically; and as knowledge in his view takes the form of the syllogism, his point is here that in the syllogism it is possible to go wrong either by neglecting one of the two premisses or by neglecting one of the two factors of which the major premiss consists. CHAP. V.J OF ARISTOTLE. 213 but does not apply it, we see that "possession" has a different meaning ; in fact there is a sense in which he possesses knowledge and another sense in which he does not possess it, as e.g. in sleep or madness or intoxication. But this is the very condition of people who are under the influence of passion; for fits of anger and the desires of sensual pleasures and some such things do unmistakeably produce a change in the condition of the body, and in some cases actually cause madness. It is clear then that we must regard incontinent Xjeople as being in much the same condition as people Avho are asleep or mad or intoxicated. Nor is it any proof of knowledge, i.e. of knowledge in the full sense, that they repeat such phrases as would seem to imply knowledge; for people who are mad or intoxi- cated repeat demonstrations and verses of Empedocles, and beginners in learning string phrases together, before they know their meaning. Assimilation is essential to full knowledge, and this is necessarily a Avork of time. We must suppose then that people in a state of incontinence repeat phrases in the same way as actors on the stage. Again, we may consider the reason of inconti- jience by examining its nature*, as follows: There is in the syllogism firstly an universal opinion, and secondly an opinion relating to particulars which fall under the dominion of sense. Now when a third opinion is formed from these two, it is necessary that 1 Aristotle seems to mean by va-iKas an investigation into the special character or principle of aKpareia. 214 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VII. the mind should on the one hand assent to the conclusion, and on the other should in practice give immediate effect to it. To take an example, if it is proper to taste everything that is sweet, — which is a wniversal opinion — and such or such a thing is sweet, — which is a particula/r opinion — it is necessary that one, who has the power and is not prevented, should at once act upon the conclusion, i.e. should taste if. When therefore there is in the mind one universal opinion which forbids tasting, and another which says that everything sweet is pleasant, and ought to be tasted, when there is the particular opinion that a certain thing is sweet, and this particular opinion is effective, and when there is the actual presence of desire, then, while the first universal opinion enjoins avoidance of the thing, desire impels to it ; for desire has the faculty of setting every one of our members in motion. The result is that a person may be said in some sense to be led into incontinence by reason or opinion, but it is an opinion which is not intrinsi- cally, but only accidentally, opposed to right reason; for it is really the desire and not the opinion which is opposed to right reason. Accordingly brutes are not said to be incontinent, because they have no universal conceptions, but only an image or recoUec* tion of particulars. If it be asked how the incontinent person is delivered from ignorance and restored to knowledge, it may be answered, that the process is the same as in the case of one who is intoxicated or asleep ; it is not peculiar to the condition of incontinence, and the proper authorities upon it are the physiologists. But CHAP. V.J OF ARISTOTLE. 215 as the minor premiss is an opinion of something that is an object of sensation, and as it determines actions, it follows that one who is in a condition of inconti- nence either does not possess an opinion, or possesses it in a sense in which possession, as we said, does not p- 213. mean knowledge but merely the repetition of phrases, as an intoxicated man may repeat the verses of Empedocles'. And as the minor term or premiss is not universal, and has apparently not the same scien- tific character as the universal, it seems too that the theory of Socrates^ is really true ; for it is not when knowledge properly so regarded is present to the mind that the condition of incontinence occurs, nor is it this knowledge which is twisted about by inconti- nence, but such knowledge only as is sensational or depends on sensation. So much then for the question whether a person. Chap. vi. when he acts incontinently, has knowledge or not, and in what sense it is possible for him to have know- ledge. The next thing is to state whether a person may inconti- be incontinent in an absolute sense, or all people are sointe and incontinent in some particular sense, and, if there is a p^*""^"^'- person who is incontinent in the absolute sense, what is the sphere of his incontinence. It is evident that pleasures and pains are the 1 There should be a full stop after'E/tTreSoKXeour in 1. 11 and no stop after opoi> in 1. 13. 2 The Socratic theory is that vice excludes knowledge; Aris- totle, while asserting that it is consistent with knowledge of some kind, admits that it excludes knowledge in the full or proper sense of the word. 216 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VII. sphere in which the continent and steadfast, or the incontinent and effeminate, display their characters- But some things which produce pleasure are neces- sary, others are desirable in themselves but admit of excess. By the former I mean physical processes, e.g. the processes of nutrition and sexual love, and such other physical processes as in our view afforded scope for licentiousness and temperance. By the latter, which although not necessary, are desirable in them- selves, I mean e.g. victory, honour, wealth, and other things of the same class which are good and pleasant. Now, if it is in reference to these last things that people transgress and exceed the limits of right reason, we do not call them " incontinent " in an absolute or unqualified sense, but we qualify the word by saying that they are incontinent in respect of money or gain or honour or angry passion. We do not speak of them as incontinent in an absolute sense, because they are different and are called incontinent only by analogy as the victor in the Olympian games was called Man ' ; for in his case the general definition of "mom" differed slightly from the special definition but still was distinct. It is signifi- cant of this difference that, while incontinence is censured not as a mistake only, but as a vice, whether a vice of an absolute or of some particular kind, nobody is censured for being incontinent in respect of money, gain, honour, and the like. If we look at bodily enjoyments, in regard to 1 I cannot make sense of the passage, unless it be supposed that 'Kvdpemoi, like Mann in English, is here a proper name. If so, it should be written 'Avepajros rather than av6pamos. CHAP. VI.] OF ARISTOTLE. 217 which we commonly speak of a man as temperate or licentious, "we see that one who pursues excessive pleasures, and avoids excessive pains, such as hunger, thirst, heat, cold, and the various sensations of the touch and taste, and who does so, not of deliberate purpose, but contrary to his purpose and intelligence, is called incontinent not with the qualification that he is incontinent in certain respects, as e.g. in respect of anger, but incontinent simply in an absolute sense. We may infer this to be the case, as people are similarly called effeminate in respect of pleasures and pains, but not in respect of wealth, gain, honour, and the like. This is the reason too why we class the incontinent man and the licentious man together, and again the continent man and the temperate man together, as being concerned more or less with the same pleasures and pains, while we do not place any of the others in the same class with them. They are concerned with the same things, but their attitude is different ; the licentioiis act with deliberate purpose, but the incontinent do not. Hence we should call a person more licentious, if without desire or without any strong desire he pursues excessive pleasures and avoids moderate pains, than if he does so from a violent' desire ; for what (it may bp asked) would such a person do if there should come upon him a fierce desire, and it were intensely painful to him to omit the gratification of his natural appetites? But there are some desires and pleasures which are noble and virtuous of their kind ; for according to our previous definition some pleasant things are naturally desirable, such as wealth, gain, victory, and 218 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VH, honour, others the opposite of these, and others intermediate. In regard to all such things as are desirable or intermediate, it is not for feeling emotion, desire and affection for them, that people are cen- sured, but for running into some kind of excess. Accordingly people are always censured, if they are unreasonably mastered by something that is naturally noble and good, or unreasonably pursue it, as e.g. if they are inordinately devoted to honour, or to chil- dren and parents ; for children and parents are goods as well as honour, and devotion to them is laudable. But even here there is a possibility of excess, as e.g. if one should vie with the gods themselves like Mobe^ or like Satyrus who was nicknamed "the filial" from his affection for his father, as it made him look exceedingly foolish. It is true that these cases do not admit of vice, and the reason has been already assigned, viz. that the objects are all desirable in themselves, although excess in them is wrong, and ought to be avoided ; nor again do they admit of incontinence, as incon- tinence is something that ought not only to be avoided but to be censured. Still the similarity of the emotional condition leads us to use the term "incontinence" in these cases, although we do not use it without qualification, as when we speak of a person as "a bad doctor " or "a bad actor," although we should not call him "bad" in an absolute sense. As in that instance then we do ^ The story of Niobe is well known; but Satyrus is only a name. CHAP. VI.] OF ARISTOTLE. 219 not use the term "bad" without qualification,, because bad doctoring or bad acting is not badness or vice, but only analogous to a vice, so here it is evident that we must regard nothing as being continence or in- continence in a strict sense, but what has the same sphere as temperance or licentiousness, and must not apply the terms "continence" and "incontinence" to anger, except by analogy. Accordingly we add a qualification and say, that a person is incontinent in respect of angry passion in the same sense as in respect of honour or gain. There are certain things which are naturally Bad moral states pleasant, some of them being pleasant in an absolute sense and others pleasant to particular classes of animals or men, while there are other things which are not naturally pleasant but owe their pleasantness to physical defects or habits or to depravity of nature ; and it is possible to discover moral states correspond- ing to each of these kinds of pleasures. What I mean is that there are brutal states as BrutaUty. e.g. in the female creature who is said to rip up pregnant women and devour their children, or in some savage tribes near the Black Sea which are said to delight in such practices as eating raw meat or human flesh, or in cannibals who lend their children to one another to feast upon, or as the story tells of Phalaris'. And if these are brutal states, there are others which are produced in some people by disease and madness, as when a person sacrificed and ate his 1 The "story" is the traditional belief that Phalaris ate his son in infancy. Cp. Bentley's Dissertation upon the Epistles of Pludaris xvl 220 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VII. mother, or another person ate the liver of his fellow- slave. Other such states again are the results of a morbid disposition or of habit, as e.g. the practice of plucking out one's hair, or biting one's nails, or eating cinders and earth, or of committing unnatural vice; for these hsibits are sometimes natural, when a person's nature is vicious, and sometimes acquired, as e.g. by those who are the victims of outrage from childhood. Now whenever nature is the cause of these habits, nobody would call people who give way to them incontinent, any more than we should call women incontinent for being not males, but females ; and the same is the case with people in whom habit has produced a morbid condition. These various habits, like brutality itself, lie beyond the pale of vice; but if a person in whom they exist becomes their master or slave, his conduct ought to be called continence or incontinence, not in an absolute, but in a metaphorical sense; just as if a person is mastered by his angry passions, he ought to be called incontinent in respect of anger, but not incontinent in an absolute sense. For all excess whether of folly, cowardice, incontinence, or savagery is either brutal or morbid. For if it is a person's nature to be frightened at everything, even at the noise of a mouse, he is such a coward as to be more like a brute beast than a human being; but it was disease which made the man' afraid of the weasel. Again, foolish people who are naturally irrational, and live a life of mere sensation, as e.g. some races of remote barbarians, are like brutes; but foolish people 1 In allusion to some story now forgotten. CHAP. VI.J OF ARISTOTLE. 221 "whose folly arises from disease e.g. from epilepsy, or from insanity, ai"e in a morbid state. A person may at times possess one of these habits "without being mastered by it, as e.g. if Phalaris had restrained his desire of eating a child or his unnatu- ral passions ; or again he may not only possess it but be mastered by it. As then human vice is sometimes called vice in an absolute sense, and at other times is qualified by the epithet "brutal" or "morbid," but is not called vice in an absolute sense, so it is clear that incontinence may be either brutal or morbid, but it is only inconti- nence in an absolute sense when it is coextensive with human licentiousness. It is evident therefore that continence and inconti- Chap. vn. nence have to do simply with the same matters as temperance and licentiousness, and that in other matters there is a different kind of incontinence which is called incontinence in a metaphorical, and not in an absolute, sense. It must be observed too that the incontinence of inconti- angry passion is not so disgraceful as the incontinence passion and of the desires. For it is as if the passion heard reason ™eMe*of more or less, but misheard it, like hasty servants, who desUe. run out before they have heard all that is said to thera, and so mistake their orders, or like dogs who bark at a person, if only he makes a noise, without waiting to see if he is a friend. In the same way the temper from its natural heat and impetuosity hears something, but does not hear the voice of command, when it rushes to revenge. For when the reason or fancy indicates that an insult or slight has been 222 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VII.- inflicted, the passion jumps, as it were, to the con- clusion that it must do battle with the person who inflicted it, and therefore gets into a fury at once. Desire, on the other hand, rushes to the enjoyment of a thing, if only reason or sensation says that it is pleasant. Thus passion follows reason in a sense, but desire does not. Desire is therefore the more dis- graceful; for the man of incontinent temper is in a sense the servant of reason, but the other is the servant of desire and not of reason. Again, there is more excuse for following natural impulses, as indeed there is for following all such desires as are common to all the world, and the more common they are, the more excusable are they also.^^ But passion and rage are more natural than the desires of excessive and superfluous pleasures, as appears in the case of the man who defended himself for striking his father by saying "Yes, for he struck his own father before and his own father struck his father," and pointing to his child " He too will strike me when he becomes a man ; it is in our blood." So too the man, who was being dragged out of the house by his son, told him to stop at the door, as he had himself dragged his father so far but not beyond it. Again, the greater the cunning, the greater is the injustice of an action. Now a passionate man i& not cunning nor is passion cunning; it is open. Desire, on the other hand, is cunning; thus Aphrodite is called the "Goddess of the Cyprian isle, Artisan of many a wileV 1 Tlie authorsliip of the phrase is unknown. GHAP. VII. J OF ARISTOTLE. 223 and Homer says of her embroidered girdle that on it was "Guile that doth cozen wisest men of wit^." Hence as this incontinence is more unjust and more disgraceful than incontinence of temper, it may be called incontinence in an absolute sense, and is in fact a species of "vice. Again, nobody feels pain when he commits a wanton "^ outrage. But anybody who acts in anger feels pain in his action, whereas wantonness is asso- ciated with pleasure. If then such things as are the most legitimate subjects of anger are properly re- garded as the most unjust, it follows that the inconti- nence which is due to desire is more unjust than the incontinence which is due to angry passion; for there is nothing of wantonness in angry passion. It is clear then that incontinence in respect of the desires is more disgraceful than incontinence in respect of angry passion, and that continence and incontinence are properly concerned with bodily desires and pleasures. But we have still to ascertain the differences in these desires and pleasures, for, as Differences has been said at the outset, some are human andSid^piea^ natural alike in kind and in degree, others are brutal, p°2i9. others again are the results of physical injuries and diseases. It is with the first of these alone that temperance and licentiousness are concerned. That is the reason why we do not speak of brutes as 1 Iliad XIV. 214—217. ^ S^pit may here be represented in English by " wanton outrage" or "wantonness,"' as it is clearly such outrageous con- duct as is the natural issue of desire. 224 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK. VII,. temperate or licentious except metaphorically, and where one kind of animal is absolutely distinguished from another by peculiar wantonness, destructiveness, voracity or the like; for animals do not possess moral purpose or ratiocinative power, they merely get into an unnatural state, like madmen. Bratauty Brutality is not so bad a thing as vice, but it is and Vice o ? more formidable, for it is not the corruption of the highest good in brutes as it is in men, but its non- existence. The comparison then of brutality with vice is like the comparison of inanimates with ani- mates in respect of wickedness ; for the depravity of that which has no originative principle is always less mischievous, and brutes lack reason, which is an originative principle. (It is much the same then as a comparison of injustice with an unjust man ; there is a sense in which each of them is worse than the other*.) For a bad man will do ten thousand times as much evil as a brute. Chap.viii. As to the pleasures and pains, desires and dislikes, of touch and taste, with which licentiousness and p. 216. temperance, as has been already defined, are con- cerned, it is possible to be in such a moral state that one is the slave of those of which most people are masters, or again to be in such a moral state that one is master of those of which most people are slaves. According as a person's state is one or the other in respect of pleasures he is continent or incontinent; 1 There should he a full stop at kAkiov, and tlie sentence irapairXrjaiov ovv-.-kclkiov should be regarded as virtually paren- thetical, if indeed it has a right to a place in the text at all. CHAP. VIII.] OF AEISTOTLE. 225 according as it is one or the other in respect of pains, he is courageous or effeminate. The moral state of the large majority of mankind lies between the two, even if they incline rather to the worse. Inasmuch as some pleasures are necessary, and others are not necessary, or are necessary only up to a certain point, and as neither the excesses nor the deficiencies of these pleasures are necessary, and it is the same with desires and pains, it follows that, if a person pursues pleasures of an excessive character, or pursues any pleasures in an excessive degree, or pursues them from moral purpose for their own sake, and not for the sake of anything that results irom them, he is licentious ; for he is necessarily incapable Licentioas- of repentance and is therefore incurable, as to be "''^^' incapable of repentance is to be incurable. The opposite state is the state of deficiency, the mean state is temperance. Similarly a person who avoids bodily pains, not from inability to endure them but from moral purpose, is also licentious. Where this moral purpose does not exist, a person may be moved either by pleasure or by avoidance of the pain resulting from desire. There is therefore a difference between these persons. But everybody will agree that a person is worse, if he does some- thing disgraceful without desire, or without any strong desire, than if he does it at a time when his desire is violent, and worse, if he deals a blow in cold blood than when he is angry; for what, it may be said, would such a person do if he were in a passion? ijcentions- Hence the licentious person is worse than the incon- inconti- , . . nence. tinent. w. N. E. 15 nacy. 226 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VII. Of the characters which have been described the one, viz. incontinence, is rather a kind of eflFeminacy, Continence the Other is liccntiousness. The opposite of the fastness, incontinent character is the continent, and of the effeminate the steadfast; for steadfastness consists in holding out against pain, and continence in over- coming pleasure, and it is one thing to hold out, and another to overcome, as it is one thing to escape being beaten and another to win a victory. Hence continence is preferable to steadfastness. If a person gives in where people generally resist and are capable of resisting, he deserves to be called Effemi- effeminate and luxurious; for luxury is a form of effeminacy. Such a person will let his cloak trail in the mud to avoid the trouble of lifting it up, or will give himself the airs of, an invalid without considering himself miserable, although he resembles one who is miserable. It is much the same with continence and inconti- nence. It is no wonder, if a person is mastered by strong and overwhelming pleasures or pains ; nay, it is pardonable, if he struggles agaibst them like Phi- loctetes when bitten by the snake in the play of Theodectes, or like Cercyon' in the Alope of Carcinus, or like people who in trying to suppress their laughter burst out in a loud guffaw, as happened to Xeno- phantus^ It is only unpardonable where a person is ' It is possible that the poet Carcinus represented in his Alope a struggle between the cruel disposition and the moral sense of Cercyon. ° The allusion is unknown. CHAP. VIII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 227 mastered by things against which most people succeed iu holding oat, and is impotent to struggle against them, unless his impotence be due to hereditary constitution or to disease, as effeminacy is hereditary in the kings of Scythia, or as a woman is naturally weaker than a man. If a person is fond of amusing himself, he is regarded as licentious, but he is really effeminate; for amusement, being a relaxation, is a recreation, and a person who is fond of amusing himself is one who carries his recreation to excess. Incontinence assumes sometimes the form of im-?'ormsof petuosity, and at other times that of weakness. Some nence. men deliberate, but their emotion prevents them from abiding by the result of their deliberation; others again do not deliberate, and are therefore carried away by their emotion. For as people cannot be tickled, if they are themselves the beginners in a tickling match ^, so some people, if they anticipate or foresee what is coming, and have roused themselves and their reason to resist it before it comes, are not overcome by their emotion, whether it be pleasant or painful. It is people of a quick and atrabilious temper whose incontinence is particularly apt to take the form of impetuosity ; for the rapidity or the violence of their feeling prevents them from waiting for the guidance of reason, as they are easily led away by their imagination. 1 The idea seems to be that, if a person anticipates tickling, he is in a sense armed against it; it depends for its effect upon sm-prise. 15—2 228 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VII. Chap. DC. The Ucentious person, as was said, is not disposed P-^^^- to repentance, as he abides by his purpose, but the incontinent person is always so disposed. The diffi- culty then which we raised does not exist. The former is incurable, the latter can be cured; for if rice may be compared to such a disease as dropsy or consumption, incontinence may be compared to epi- lepsy, the one being a chronic, the other an inter- inconti- mittcut depravity. There is in fact an absolutely v^cef"" generic distinction between incontinence and vice; for vice may be, but incontinence cannot be, uncon- scious, inconti- There are two classes of incontinent people, and twolkinds. thoso wlio simply lose command of themselves are better than those who possess reason but do not abide by it, as they are not overcome by so violent an emotion, nor do they act without previous delibera- tion like the others. For an incontinent person may be compared to one who gets intoxicated with a little wine, i.e. with less wine than ordinary people. It is evident then that incontinence is not vice (although there is, I think, a sense in Avhich it is a vice), for the former is contrary, and the latter is conformable, to moral parpose. Still they come to much the same thing as regards actions ; it is like the saying of Demodocus' about the Milesians, "The Milesians are not fools but they act just like fools" ; so the incontinent are not unjust but they act un- justly. The incontinent man then is the kind of person to 1 The epigrammatist of Leros. CHAP. IX.] OP ARISTOTLE. 229 pursue such bodily pleasures as are excessive and contrary to right reason, although not from convic- tion of their goodness, but the vicious man is con- vinced of their goodness because he is the kind of person to pursue them; hence it is easy to convert the foi-mer, but not the latter. For virtue is pre- servative, and vice destructive, of principle; but in actions the object is a first principle', like the hypo- theses or definitions in mathematics. In mathematics then it is not the reason which is capable of proving the first principle, nor is it in actions ; it is the virtue, whether natural or acquired, of forming a right opinion about the first principle, i.e. about the object of action. A person who possesses this virtue tlien is temperate ; a person who does not possess it is licentious. But there are people who are apt to be so carried away by emotion as to act contrary to right reason ; they are so far overcome by emotion as not to act in accordance with right reason, but not so far overcome as to be convinced that they ought to pursue such pleasures unreservedly. These are incontinent people ; they are superior to the licentious,.and not absolutely bad; for they have not lost, the highest good, viz. the first principle. Opposite to these is another class of people who are capable of abiding by their principle and are not liable to be carried away, at least by emotion. It is evident from these considerations that the moral state of the former is vicious and that of the latter is virtuous. ' There is again a play upon the two senses of dpx<7 (1) a beginning, (2) a first principle or moral assumption. 230 THE NICOMACHEAN IITHICS [bOOK VIT. Chap. X. It remains to ash then, Is a person continent, if ho ^«jj*^°^^°* abides by his reason and moral purpose, whatever to moral they may be, or only if he abides by them when they purpose. ^^^ right? Is he incontinent, if he does not abide by his moral purpose or reason, whatever they may be? or is it only, if he does not abide by true reason and right purpose'? This is a difficulty which has been p. 208. already raised. The answer seems to be that, al- though it may accidentally be any sort of reason or purpose, yet essentially it is true reason and right purpose, by which the one does, and the other does not, abide. For if a person chooses or pursues a thing which may be called A for the sake of some- thing else which may be called B, it is B which he pursues and chooses essentially, and A only accident- ally. By "essentially" we mean "absolutely," and therefore although in a certain sense it is any sort of opinion by which the one abides, and from which the other departs, yet in an absolute sense it is true opinion. ObBtinacy. There are certain people who are ready to abide by their opinion at all costs ; we call them obstinate. They are people, I mean, who are hard to persuade, and not easy to convert. Such people bear some resemblance to continent people, as do prodigals to liberal people, and foolhardy people to courageous, but there are many points of difference. For while the continent person does not veer about under the influence of emotion and desire, he is not immovable; 1 I follow Mr Bywater in reading r) 6 r^ fifj -^ivbtl \6y as has been said, why pleasure is thought not to be virtuous, viz. (1) That some pleasures are actions of a base nature, whether the baseness be congenital, as in a brute, or acquired, as in a vicious man. (2) That other pleasures are remedial, implying a want, and that the existence of the normal state is better than the process to that state ; these pleasures then are felt only when we are coming to a normal or perfect state; they' are there- fore only accidentally virtuous)". Bodily pleasures too, as being violent, are pursued by people who are incapable of finding gratification in other pleasures. Thus people sometimes make themselves thirsty in order to enjoy the pleasure of satisfying their thirst. So long as these pleasures are harmless, there is no ground for censuring them (although it is wrong to pursue them, when they are harmful), for people who pursue them have no other objects of gratification, and a neutral state of the sensations is naturally painful to many people. For an animal is constantly labouring, as we read in books on physical science, where it is said that seeing and hearing are painful, but we have got accustomed to ^ The stop after ytvea-dcu should be a colon. 2 The passage which I have placed in brackets is an evident interruption of the argument, CHAP. XV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 243 them by this time, as the saying is. Similarly in youth people, because they are growing, are much in the same state as drunken people, and youth is pleasant. Again, people of an atrabilious nature require constant medicine, as their temperament con- stantly frets their body away, and thus they are always in a state of strong desire. But pain is ex- pelled either by the pleasure which is its opjjosite, or by any pleasure if it be strong. This is why atra- bilious people fall into licentiousness and wicked- ness. Such pleasures on the other hand as have no Natural antecedent pains do not admit of excess ; they are ^ * naturally, and not merely accidentally pleasant. By "accidental pleasures" I mean such as are remedial in their effect; for as we are cured by the action of the remaining healthy part of our nature, the process of cure is pleasant. By "natural pleasures" I mean such as produce action of our whole nature in a healthy state. The same thing is never constantly pleasant to us, as our nature is not simple, but there exists in us a sort' of second nature, which makes us mortal beings. Thus if one element is active, it acts against the nature of the other, and when the two elements are in equilibrium, the action appears to be neither painful nor pleasant. If there were a being, whose nature is simple, the same action would always be supremely pleasant to him. It is thus that God enjoys one simple pleasure everlastingly; for there is an activity not only of motion but of immobility, and pleasure consists rather in rest than in motion. But 16—2 244 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [bK. VII. change, as the poet' says, is "the sweetest thing in the world," and the reason lies in a certain viciousness of our nature; for as the vicious man is fond of change, so too the nature which requires change is vicious, it is not simple or virtuous. We have now discussed continence and inconti- nence, pleasure and pain, their nature and the reason why some of them are good and others bad. It remains to discuss friendship or love. ' Euripides, Orestes, v. 234, but the reading there is yKviai. BOOK VIII. It will be natural to discuss friendship' or love Chap. i. next, for friendship is a kind of virtue or implies or^Love. ^^ virtue. It is also indispensable to life. For nobody J* '? would choose to live without friends, although he pensabie ; were in possession of every other good. Nay, it seems that if people are rich and hold official and authoritative positions, they have the greatest need of friends ; for what is the good of having this sort of prosperity if one is denied the opportunity of benefi- cence,' which is never so freely or so admirably exercised as towards friends? Or how can it be maintained in safety and security without friends? For the greater a person's importance, the more liable it is to disaster. In poverty and other mis- fortunes we regard our friends as our only refuge. Again, friends are helpful to us, when we are young, as guarding us from error, and when we are growing old, as taking care of us, and supplying such de- ^ If it were necessary to choose one word for ^iXta the best would be "friendship," but it corresponds as substantive to the meanings of the verb (^tXeiv and therefore rises at times in point of intensity to "love." 246 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VIII. ficiencies of action as are the consequences of phy- sical weakness, and when we are in the prime of life, as prompting us to noble actions, according to the adage "Two come together''; for two people have a greater power both of intelli- gence and gf action tlia/n either of the tivo by Mmsdf. (2) natural; It would Seem that friendship or love is the natural instinct of a parent towards a child, and of a child towards a parent, not only among men, but among birds and animals generally, and among crea- tures of the same race towards one another, especially among men. This is the reason why we praise men who are the friends of their fellow-men or philan- thropists. "We may observe too in travelling how near and dear every man is to his fellow-man. (3) social; Again, it seems that friendship or love is the bond which holds states together, and that legislators set more store by it than by justice; for concord is apparently akin to friendship, and it is concord that they especially seek to promote, and faction, as being hostility to the state, that they especially try to expel. If people are friends, there is no need of justice between them ; but people may be just, and yet need friendship. Indeed it seems that justice, in its su- preme form, assumes the character of friendship. 1 Iliad X. 224. It is where Biomedes expresses his desire for a companion in invading the Trojan camp. dW f" tIs fioi dvfip aji enoiro Koi aWos liaWov ^aXjrapi), Koi Bapo-aKedrcpov (irrai. ''t'«)- and such purpose is the outcome of a moral state. Again, we wish the good of those whom we love for their own sake, and the vrish is governed not by emotion but by the moral state. In loving our friend too, we love what is good for ourselves; as when a good man becomes a friend, he becomes a blessing to his friend. Accordingly each of two friends loves what is good for himself, and returns as much as he receives in good wishes and in pleasure ; for, as the proverb says, equality is friendship. These conditions then are best realized in the Friendship friendship or love of the good. Among austere and of the good. elderly people friendship arises less easily, as they are more peevish and less fond of society; for it is social intercourse which seems to be the principal element and cause of friendship. Thus it is that the young form friendships quickly, but old people do not, as they do not make friends with any body who is not delightful to them, nor do austere people. Such people, it is true, wish each other well; they desire each other's good, and render each other services ; but they are not reaUy friends, as they do not satisfy the principal condition of friendship by living together and delighting in each other's society. It is as impossible to be friends with a number of people in the perfect sense of friendship, as it is to be W. N. E. 17 258 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VIII. in love with a number of people at the same time ; for perfect friendship is in some sense an excess, and such excess of feeling is natural towards an individual, but it is not easy for a number of people to give intense pleasure to the same person at the same time, or, I may say, to be good at aU. Friendship too implies experience and familiarity, which are very difficult. But it is possible to find a number of people' who are pleasant, as affording profit or pleasure ; for people of this kind are numerous and their services do not occupy much time. Friendship Amoug such people the friendship which is based o p easure. ^p^^ pleasure more nearly resembles true friendship, when each party renders the same services to the other, and they are delighted with each other or with the same things, as e.g. in the friendships of the young ; for a liberal spirit is especially characteristic of these friendships. Friendship The friendship which rests upon utility is com- ° " '^' mercial in its character. Fortunate people do not want what is useful but what is pleasant. They want people to live with; and although for a short time they may bear pain, nobody would endure it con- tinuously; nobody would endure the good itself continuously, if it were painful to him. Hence it is that they require their friends to be pleasant. They ought perhaps to require them also to be good, and not only so, but good in relation to themselves ; for then they will have all the quaUties which friends ought to have. 1 Heading iroWoiis with fiamsauer. CHAP. VIII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 259 It appears that people in positions of authority make a distinction between their friends. Some are useful to them, and others are pleasant, but the same people arc not in general both useful and pleasant. For they do not look for friends who are virtuous as well as pleasant, or who will help them to attain noble ends; they look partly for amusing people when they want to be pleased, and partly for people who are clever at executing their commands, and these qualities are hardly ever united in the same person. It has been stated that a virtuous man is at once pleasant and useful; but such a man does not become the friend of one who is superior to him, unless he is himself superior^ to that person in virtue. Otherwise there is no such equality as occurs when his superiority in virtue is proportionate to his inferiority in some other respect. Friendships of this kind however are exceedingly rare. The friendships which have been described are CHAp.vin. based upon equality; for the services and sentiments Different of the two friends to one another are the same, or friendship they exchange one thing for another, e.g. pleasure ^eJ|: for profit. It has been already stated that friendships ^'^^f depending on exchange are less true and less perma- nent than others. As being at once similar and iwend- dissioular to the same thing, such friendships may exchange. be said both to be and not to be friendships. They look like friendships in respect of similarity to the friendship which depends upon virtue; for the one ^ The subject of vitepixr)TaL must be o im-epex"""- 17—2 260 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VIII. possesses pleasure, the other utility, and these are characteristics of virtuous friendships as well. But as Tirtuous friendship is undisturbed by calumnies, and is permanent, while these are quickly changed, and as there are many other diflferences between them, it seems that their dissimilarity to virtuous friendship makes them look as if they were not friend- ships at all. Friend- There is another kind of friendship or love s^M-iority depending upon superiority, e.g. the friendship or love and inferi- of a father for a son, or of any elder person for a younger, or of a husband for a wife, or of a ruler for a subject. These friendships are of different sorts; for the friendship or love of parents for children is not the same as that of rulers for subjects, nor indeed is the friendship or love of a father for a son the same as that of a son for a father, nor that of a husband for his wife the same as that of a wife for her husband. For in each of these there is a different virtue and a different function, and there are different motives; hence the affections and friend- ships are also different. It follows that the services rendered by each party to the other in these friend- ships are not the same, nor is it right to expect that they shoTild be the same ; but when children render to parents what is due to the authors of their being, and parents to children what is due to them, then such friendships are permanent and virtuous. In aU such friendships as depend upon the principle of superiority, the affection should be proportionate to the superiority ; i.e. the better or the more useful party, or whoever may be the CHAP. VIII.] OP AKISTOTLE. 261 superior, should receive more aiFection than he gives ; for it is when the affection is proportionate to the merit that a sort of equality is established, and this equality seems to be a condition of friendship. But it is apparently not the same with equality Chap.ix. in justice as with equality in friendship. In justice it £'jj^*^ is proportionate equality which is the first considera- j^^'^j^ tion, and quantitative equality which is the second, or love. but in friendship quantitative equality is first and proportionate second. This is clearly seen to be the case, if there be a wide distinction between two persons in respect of virtue, vice, affluence, or any- thing else. For persons so widely different cease to be friends; they do not even affect to be friends. But it is nowhere so conspicuous as in the case of the Gods ; for the Gods enjoy the greatest superiority in all good things. It is clear too in the case of kings ; for people who are greatly inferior to them do not expect to be their friends. Nor again do worthless people expect to be the friends of the best or wisest of mankind. No doubt in such cases it is impossible to define exactly the point up to which friendship may be carried ; it may suffer many deductions and yet continue, but where there is a great distinction, as between God and man, it ceases to be. This is a fact which has given rise to the question whether it is true that friends do really wish the greatest good of their friends, e.g. whether they wish them to be Gods; for then they will lose them as friends, and will therefore lose what are goods, as friends are goods. That being so, if it has been rightly said that a 262 THE NICOMACHBAN ETHICS [bOOK VIII. friend wishes his friend's good for the friend's sake, it will be necessary that the friend should remain such as he is. He will wish his friend the greatest good as a man. And yet perhaps he will not wish him every good, as every one wishes good in the highest sense to himself. It seems that ambition makes most people wish to be loved rather than to love others. That is the reason why most people are fond of flatterers ; for a flatterer is an inferior friend, or pretends to be so, and to give more love than he receives. But to be loved seems to approximate to being honoured, and honour is a general object of desire. Not that people, as it appears, desire honour for its own sake, they desire it only accidentally ; for it is hope which causes most people to delight in the honours paid them by persons of high position, as they think they will obtain from them whatever they may want, and therefore delight in honour as a symbol of prosperity in the future. But they who aspire to gain honour from persons of high character and wide information are eager to confirm their own opinion of themselves ; they delight therefore in a sense of their own goodness, having confidence in the judgment so expressed upon it. But people delight in being loved for their own sake. Hence it would seem to follow that it is better to be loved than to be honoured, and that friendship or love is desirable in itself. Chap. X. But friendship seems to consist rather in loving ^aaiefthan *^*^ ™^ hsmg loved. It may be seen to be so by the being loved delight which mothers have in loving; for mothers sometimes give their own children to be brought up CHAP. X.] OF ARISTOTLE. 263 by others, and although they know them and love toMend- them, do not look for love in return, if it be ^ ^' impossible both to love and to be loved, but are content, as it seems, to see their children doing well, and to give them their love, even if the children in their ignorance do not render them any such service as is a mother's due. As friendship consists in loving rather than in being loved, and people who are fond of their friends receive praise, it is in some sense a virtue of friends to love; hence where love is found in due proportion, people are^rmanent friends, and their friendship is permanent. It is in this way that, even where people are unequal, they may be friends, as they will be equalized. But equality and similarity constitute friendship, especially the similarity of the virtuous; for the virtuous, being exempt from change in themselves, remain unchanged also in relation to one another, and neither ask others to do wrong nor do wrong themselves to please others. It may even be said that they prevent it ; for good people neither do wrong themselves nor allow their friends to do it. But there is no stability in vicious friends ; for they do not remain like themselves, and if they become friends it is only for a short time, and from the gratification which they feel in each other's vice. But if people are useful and pleasant to each other, they remain friends for a longer time, i.e. they remain friends so long as they afford each other pleasure or assistance. The friendship which is based upon utility seems 264 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VIII. more than any other to be an union of opposites. It is e.g. such friendship as arises between a poor man and a rich man, or between an ignorant man and a well informed man; for if a man happens to be in want of something, his desire to get it makes him give something else in exchange. We may perhaps include a lover and his beloved, or a beautiful man and an ugly man, in this class of friends. It is thus that lovers sometimes make themselves look ridiculous by expecting to be loved as much as they love others. Such an expectation would perhaps be reasonable if they were equally lovable; but if there is nothing lovable about them, it is ridiculous. It is true, I think, that one opposite does not desire another in itself, but desires it only accidentally. What it really longs for is the mean, as the mean is a good. Thus it is good for what is dry not to become wet, but to arrive at the mean state, and similarly for what is hot, and so on. But we may dismiss these questions as being more or less foreign to our present purpose. Chap. XI. It appears, as has been said at the outset, that Evfelfashi fri^^dship and justice have the same occasions and or love the same sphere ; for every association seems to an JUS ice. jjjyQjyg justice of somc kind, and friendshiji as well. At all events we address our fellow-sailors and feUow- soldiers, and similarly the members of any other association to which we belong, as friends. The friendship too is coextensive with the association, for so also is the justice. The proverbial saying, "Friends' goods are common goods" is right, as friendship depends upon association. CHAP. XI.] OF AHISTOTLE. 265 Brothers and comrades have all things in common. Other people have certain definite things in common, some more, some fewer; for some friendships go further than others. Justice too is of difierent kinds ; it is not the same in the relation of parents to children as in that of brothers to each other, or in that of comrades and fellow citizens to each other, and similarly in other friendships. Injustice too assumes various forms in relation to these several classes. It is aggravating, if the friends whom it affects are nearer to each other. Thus it is a more dreadful thing to defraud a comrade of money than to defraud a fellow citizen, or to refuse help to a brother than to a stranger, or to assault a father than any body else. Justice itself too naturally grows as friendship grows ; for they have the same sphere and are equally extensive. All associations are, as it were, parts of the Political political association ; for when people take a journey tfon"* together, it is from motives of interest and for the sake of gaining something that their life requires. It seems too that interest was the motive with which the political association was originally formed, and with which it is continued ; for this is the goal which legislators have in view, and they describe the interest of the community as just. Now aU other associations aim at some particular Different interest or success. Thus sailors aim at a successful 00!^"^'"^^ voyage in the hope of making money or something of |P»"^to the kind, fellow-soldiers in an army at a successfiil assoda- campaign, whether it be spoil or victory or the 266 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VIII. capture of a city that is their aim, and it is much the same with members of a tribe or township. It seems too that some associations are formed on a basis of pleasure, as when people associate for a fete or a picnic; for there the object is sacrifice* and good fellowship. But these are all, as it were, subordi- : nate to the political association ; for the aim of the political association is the interest not of the moment but of all a life-time, in the sacrifices which people make and the meetings which they hold in connexion with the sacrifices, in the honours which they pay to the gods, and the pleasure and relaxation which they provide for themselves. For it appears that the ancient sacrifices and meetings take place after the ingathering of the fruits of the earth, e.g. the festival of the first-fruits, these having been the seasons of the greatest leisure. It appears then that all these associations are parts of the political association, and the proper friendships will correspond to the associations. Chap. xh. There are three kinds of polity and an equal Three number of perversions, or in other words corruptions, polity. of these three kinds. The polities are kingship, aristocracy, and a third depending upon a property qualification, which it seems proper to describe as timocratic, but it is usually designated as a polity in the limited sense. Of these, kingship is the best and timocracy the worst. The perversion of kingship is tyranny, both being monarchies although they are widely different, as the 1 The connexion of festivity with religion is eminently charac- teristic of Greek thought. CHAP. XII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 267 • tyrant considers his own interest, and the king the interest of his subjects ; for a king is not a Kingship. king unless he is self-sufficient and superior to his subjects in all that is good ; but if he is such, there is nothing more that he needs. Hence he will consider not his own interest but the interest of his subjects ; for if he were not a king after this fashion, he would be a sort of king of the ballots Tyranny is the opposite of kingship, as it pursues Tyianny. the good of th6 tyrant himself. It is clear that Mngship is the best form of polity; hut it is still clearer that tyranny is the worst. The opposite of the best is always worst. A polity changes from kingship to tyranny ; for Transfor- j . . . J. » 1 4 J • _i matiou of tyranny is a vicious form of monarchy. Accordingly pouties. the vicious king becomes a tyrant. Sd^'"^ An aristocracy is converted into an oligarchy tyranny. through the fault of the ruling class who make an cracy^and unfair distribution of political honours, who reserve "^g^^^y- all or nearly all the good things for themselves, and who keep the offices of state continually in the same hands, from the inordinate value that they set upon wealth. The result is that it is only a few people who hold office, and they are not the most virtuous, but wicked people. A timocracy is converted into a democracy ; for Timocracy they border closely upon each other, as timocracy cracy.™'° professes to have a democratic character, and all who possess the requisite property qualification are equals in a timocracy. 1 The King-Archon (Spxav ^aa-ikevs) at Athens, when all officers of state were appointed by ballot, might be so called. 268 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOIC VIII. Domestic associa- tions. and glare. Of the perversions democracy is the least vicious, as it departs but slightly from the character of the polity. These are the ways in which poMties are most easily transferred; for these are the least violent transformations. It is possible to discover models, and so to say patterns, of these constitutions in households. For (1) Father the association of a father with his sons takes dren?*"' the form of a kingship, as a father cares for his children. It is this care which makes Homer speak of Zeus as "father;" for kingship purports to be a parental rule. But in Persia the rule of the father is tyrannical; for there parents treat their sons as (2) Master slaves. The association of master and slave is also tyrannical, as it is the master's interest which is realized in it. Now the rule of a slave-master seems to be a right' form of tyranny, but the rule of a father in Persia seems to be a perverted form, as different people require to be ruled in different ways. The association of husband and wife seems to be aristocratical ; for the husband's rule depends upon merit, and is confined to its proper sphere. He assigns to the wife all that suitably belongs to her. If the husband is lord of everything, he changes the association to an oligarchy ; for then he acts unfairly, and not in virtue of his superior merit. Sometimes again the wife rules, as being an heiress. Such rule is not based upon merit, but depends upon wealth or power as in oligarchies. 1 Aristotle believes in a natural class of slaves. Op. Politics i. ch. 5. (3) Hus- band and wife. CHAP. XII.J OF ARISTOTLE. 269 The association of brothers resembles a timocracy ; (4) Bro- for they are equals except so far as they differ in sisters. years ; hence if the difference of years is very great, the friendship ceases to be fraternal. A democracy is chiefly found in such households as have no master, where everybody is equal to everybody else, or where the head of the house is weak, and everybody can do as he chooses, Now it appears that there is a friendship or love CHAP.xrn. which is proper to each of these several polities in g^pg ' the same degree as there is a justice proper to each. ^™f^„i°r The friendship or love of a king to his subjects polities. takes the form of superiority in benefaction. He treats his subjects well, as being good, and as caring for their welfare, like a shepherd for the welfare of his flock, whence Homer called Agamemnon "shep- herd of the folk." The love of a father for his child is similar in character, although it differs in the magnitude of the benefactions ; for a father is the author of the child's existence, which seems to be the greatest of all bene- factions, as well as of his nurture and education. These benefactions are ascribed also to ancestors, and it is Nature's law that a father should rule his sons, and ancestors their descendants, and a king his subjects. These friendships imply superiority ; hence parents are not only loved but honoured, as being superiors. Justice therefore in these cases implies not identical but proportionate treatment ; for so too does friend- ship. The friendship or love of husband and wife is the 270 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VIII. same as exists in an aristocracy ; for it depends upon virtue. The better party gets the greater good, and each gets what befits him or her, but this is equally the rule of justice. The friendship of brothers is like the friendship of comrades ; for they are equals and are persons of the same age, and when this is the case, people are generally alike in their feelings and characters. We may compare with this the friendship or love which is characteristic of a timocracy ; for in a timocracy the citizens profess to be equal and virtuous ; hence they hold office in turn and upon a principle of equality, and accordingly their friendship follows the same law. But in the perverted forms of polity justice does not go far, neither does friendship, and nowhere is its range so limited as in the worst of them. Friend- ship does not exist, or hardly exists, in a tyranny ; for where there is nothing in common between ruler and subject, there cannot be friendship between them, as there cannot be justice either. The relation is like that of an artisan to a tool, or of soul to body, or of master to servant ; for although all these are benefitted by the people who use them, there is no possibility of friendship or justice in the relation in which we stand to inanimate things nor indeed in our relation to a horse or an ox or to a slave qv/i slave. For there is nothing in common between a master and his slave ; the slave is an animate instrument, and the instru- ment an inanimate slave. It is impossible therefore to be friends with a slave qua slave, but not with a slave qua man, for there would seem to be a possi- CHAP. XIV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 271 bility of justice between every man and any one who is capable of participation in law and covenant, and therefore in friendship, in so far as he is man. Friendships therefore and justice exist only to a slight extent in tyrannies and have only a narrow range. Their range is widest in democracies, as it is when people are equals that they have most in common. All friendship then, as has been said, implies Chap.xiv. association. Still it is proper to distinguish the ^g^°^^^'°t" friendship of kinsmen and comrades from other friendship or lov6 friendships. The friendships of fellow-citizens, fellow- gpeciai tribesmen, feUow-saUors and the Uke, have a greater friendship . . , or love of resemblance to friendships of association, as they kinsmen appear to be based on a sort of compact. We may rades?™ rank the friendship of hospitality with these. The friendship of kinsmen too appears to be of various kinds, but to depend altogether upon the friendship or love of a parent for his child ; for Parental parents feel aflFection for their children as being a^ve. part of themselves, and children for their parents as the source of their being. But parents know their oflfepring better than the children know that they are sprung from them, and the author of another's being is more closely united to his offspring than the off- spring to the parent ; for that which proceeds from a person belongs to that from which it proceeds, as a tooth or a hair or anything to its possessor ; but that from which a thing proceeds does not belong to that which proceeds from it, or does not belong to it in the same degree. There is a difference too in respect of time; for parents love their children as soon as love, 272 THE NICOMACHBAN ETHICS [bOOK VIII. they are born, but children do not love their parents until they are advanced in years and have gained intelligence or sense. It is evident from these con- siderations why mothers love their children more than fathers. Parents then love children as themselves ; for their offspring are like second selves — second, only in the sense of being separated— and children love parents, Fraternal as being bom of them, and brothers one another, as being born of the same parents. For the identity of the children with their parents constitutes an identity between the children themselves. Hence we use such phrases as "the same blood" "the same stock" and so on, in speaking of brothers and sisters. They are therefore in a sense the same, although they are separate beings. It is a great help to friendship for people to have been brought up together, and to be of the same age ; for "two of the same age agree," as the proverb says, and intimate friends become comrades ; hence the friendship of brothers comes to resemble the friendship of comrades'. But cousins and all other kinsmen have the same bond of union to each other, as springing from the same source; they are more or less closely united according as their first ancestor is near or remote. The friendship or love of children for parents, and of men for the Gods, may be said to be love for what is good and higher than themselves ; for parents are 1 It is an instance of the part which comradeship or camara- derie played in Greek life that the mutual love of two brothers should be assimilated to the mutual love of two comrades. CHAP. XIV.J OF ARISTOTLE. 273 the authors of the greatest benefit to children, as to them children owe their existence and nurture and education from the day of their birth. There is more pleasure and utility in such a friendship than in the friendship of strangers, as their life has more in common. The characteristics of friendship among brothers are the same as among comrades; they are intensi- fied when the brothers are yirtuous, but they exist always in consequence of their likeness, inasmuch as brothers are more nearly related to each other than conu-ades and naturally love one another from birth, and as there is a greater similarity of character among people who are children of the same parents and are brought up together, and receive a similar education, nor is there any test so strong and sure as that of time. The elements of love among other kinsmen are proportionate to the nearness of their kinship. But the love of husband and wife seems to be a Love of natural law, as man is naturally more inclined to and w&e. contract a marriage than to constitute a state, inas- much as a house is prior to a state, and more neces- sary than a state, and the procreation of children is the more universal function of animals. In the case of other animals this is the limit of their association ; but men unite not only for the procreation of children but for the purposes of life. As soon as a man and a woman unite, a distribution of functions takes place. Some are proper to the husband and others to the wife; hence they supply one another's needs, each contributing his special W. N. E. 18 274 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VIII. gifts to the common stock. It is thus that utility and pleasure seem alike to be found in this friendship; but its basis will be virtue too, if the husband and wife are virtuous, as each of them has his or her proper virtue, and they will both delight in what is virtuous. It seems too that children are a bond of union between them ; hence such marriages as are childless are more easily dissolved, as children are the common blessing of both parents, and such community of interest is the bond of union between them. To ask how husband and wife and friends in general should live together, is, it appears, nothing else than to ask how it is just for them to live ; for justice is clearly not the same thing between one friend and another as towards a stranger or a com- rade or a fellow-traveller. Chap. XV. There are three kinds of friendship, as has been HMs of' ^^^^ ^* *^^ outset, and in each of them the friendship friendship may be constituted upon terms either of equality or of p. 250. superiority and inferiority; for people who are equals in goodness may become friends, or a better person may become the friend of a worse, and it is the same with pleasant people, and with people whose friend- ship rests upon utility, as their services may be either equal or diflferent. It is proper then that those who are equals should show themselves equal by an equality of love and of everything else, and those who are unequal by such a feeling to others as is proportionate to the superiority of each. Complaints Complaints and bickerings occur either exclu- Sgg^g''^''" sively or most frequently in a friendship which CHAP. XV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 275 depends upon utility, and it is reasonable that this ^*'^i'i?g should be so. For where the basis of friendship is virtue, friends are eager to do good to one another as a mark of Tirtue and friendship. Where their rivalry takes this form, there is no room for accu- sations or bickerings ; for nobody takes it ill that a person loves him and treats him well; on the con- trary, if he is a man of good feeling, he requites a kindness. Nor will the superior person find fault with his friend, as he obtains his desire ; for in such a friendship each of the friends desires the other's good. Again, such quarrelling hardly ever arises in a friendship of which pleasure is the motive ; for both parties get what they long for, if it is their great pleasure to live together. But one of them would make himself ridiculous if he were to complain of the other for not giving him pleasure, when he might leave off living in his company. It is such friendship as is based upon utility that gives rise to complaints; for as the parties in their dealings with each other have an eye to profit, each of them always wants the larger share, and imagines himself to possess less than is his due, and complains of not obtaining all that he requires and deserves, when it is impossible for the benefactor to supply all that the recipient of the benefaction requires. It seems that, as justice is twofold, being partly unwritten and partly embodied in law, the friendship Moral and which depends upon utility is either moral or legal, bfend- i.e. is based either upon character or upon convention, ^'p- Complaiuts then occur most frequently, if the terms 18—2 276 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VIII. of friendship are not the same when it is dissolved as Eeqniiai when it is formed. By legal friendship I mean such tions. as is formed on stated conditions, whether it be absolutely commercial, demanding cash payments, or more liberal in respect of time but still requiring a certain covenanted quid pro quo. In this friendship the debt is clear and indisputable, but the delay of which it admits is an element of friendliness. Accord- ingly some states do not recognise actions for debt. It is held that, if people have made a contract which presupposes good faith on both sides, they must take the consequences of making it. Moral friendship, on the other hand, has no stated conditions. If a gift or any other favour is bestowed upon a person, it is bestowed upon him as a friend ; but the giver expects^ to receive as much or more in return, regarding it not as a gift but as a loan. If he does not come out of the contract as well off as he was when he entered into it, he will complain. The reason of his complaint is that, although all people, or nearly all people, wish what is noble, they choose what is profitable, and it is noble to do good without expecting a return, but it is profitable to receive a benefaction. If a man has the power, it is his duty to return the full value of the services rendered to him, and to return it voluntarily ; for it is wrong to make a person a friend against his will. If the will is lacking, then we must suppose that we made a mistake in the first instance, and were the recipients of a benefaction from the wrong person i.e. not from a friend or some one who meant to confer it ; we must therefore dis- solve the friendship, as if the service had been done CHAP. XV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 277 US on certain stated terms of repayment. In stipu- lating to make the payment we must assume that it will be in our power to make it ; for if it is not, the giver himself would not have expected to be repaid. We must pay therefore, if we have the power, but not otherwise. But it is our duty to consider in the &st instance who it is that is benefitted and what are the terms of the benefaction, that so we may agree to accept it or not. It may be questioned whether the return is to be measured by the benefit conferred upon the recipient, and should be made proportionate to it, or should be measured by the benevolent intention of the bene- factor. For the recipients of a benefaction often adopt a depreciatory tone, pretending to have received from their benefactors services which did not cost the benefactors much, or which might have been done them by others. The benefactors, on the contrary, urge that the services were the greatest which it was in their power to render and such as could not have been rendered by others, and that they were rendered at a time of peril or some such urgent need. If then the basis of the friendship be utility, it would seem that the benefit done to the recipient is the true measure of repayment ; for it is the recipient who asks for the boon, and the benefactor assists him in the hope of receiving an equivalent. The service done then has been commensurate with the bene- faction received ; hence it is the duty of the recipient to repay the amount of his advance or even more, as this is the nobler course. But in such friendships as depend on virtue there 278 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK VIII. is no room for complaints ; it is the moral purpose of the benefactor which is, as it were, the measure of repayment, for it is the moral purpose which deter- mines virtue or character. Chap. XVI. Differences occur also in the friendships in which foieiS* oJi® party is superior to the other, for in such friend- ships, ships each party claims a larger share, and when he gets it, the friendship is dissolved. The better of the two friends thinks a larger share is his due, as a larger share is a due of the good. So too does the more helpful, as it is admitted that, if a person is useless, he ought not to have so much as one who is of use. The friendship (he says) ceases to be friend- ship and becomes mere public service, if the proceeds of the friendship are not proportionate to the works of the friends ; for people suppose, that as in a com- mercial association the larger contributors are the larger recipients, so it ought to be in friendship. The needy or inferior person takes an opposite view. He argues that it is the part of a good friend to assist the needy ; for what (he says) is the good of being the friend of a virtuous or powerful person, if one is to derive no benefit from it? It would seem that each is justified in his claim, and that each ought to receive a larger share as the result of the friendship, but not a larger share of the same things. The superior person ought to receive a larger share of honour, and the needy person a larger share of profit, as honour is the reward of virtue and beneficence, and money is the means of relieving distress. It appears that the same law holds good in poll- CHAP. XVI.] , OP AHISTOTLE. 279 tics. No honour is paid to the person who renders no service to the state ; for that which the state has to give is commonly given to the benefactor of the state, and honour is that which the state has to give. For it is impossible for a person at one and the same time to make money out of the community, and to receive honour from it, as nobody wiU submit to inferiority in all respects. We pay honour then to one who suffers pecuniary loss by holding oflBce, and we give money to one who is eager for a salary ; for it is the principle of proportion which effects equality andp. 26i. preserves friendship, as has been said. This then is the true principle of association among unequals. If a person is benefitted by another in purse or character, he must repay him in honour, as this is the repayment which it is in his power to make. For friendship looks for what is possible, not for what is proportionate or due to the merit of the friend; for there are cases where a due return is out of the question, as in the honours paid to the Gods and to parents. In such cases while nobody could ever make a due return, a person is considered to be virtuous, if he pays such regard as lies within his power. Hence it may be held that a son has no right to disown his father, although a fether may disown his son; for the son is a debtor, and must repay his debt, and as, whatever he does, it is not adequate to his obligation, he is a perpetual debtor. But the creditor may dismiss his debtor, and if so, then a father may dismiss his son. At the same time it seems, I think, that nobody would ever desert a son unless he were extraordinarily vicious; for 280 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OE AEISTOTLE. [bK. VIII. apart from the natural affection of father and son, it is human nature not to reject such support as his son may afford him in old age. But the son, if he is vicious, will look upon the duty of assisting his father as one which he should avoid, or at all events not eagerly embrace ; for the world in general wishes to receive benefits, but avoids the apparently unprofit- able task of conferring them. BOOK IX. This may be regarded as a sufficient discussion of Chap. i. these questions. But in all heterogeneous' friendships ^eous"^* it is the principle of proportion, as has been said, frfendsHps. which equalizes and preserves the friendship. It is ^' ^' ' so in the political friendship or association, where a cobbler gets due value in exchange for his shoe, and so does the weaver and any other tradesman. In this case a common measure has been provided by the currency to which everything is referred, and by which everything is measured. But in the friendship of love it happens that the lover sometimes complains that, when he is passionately in love, his love is not returned, although it may be there is nothing lovable in him, or that the object of love complains, as often happens, that his lover was once lavish in his promises and now does not perform any of them. Such cases occur because pleasure is the motive ^ By "heterogeneous friendships," as the context shows, Aristotle means such friendships as that of a lover and his beloved, in which the parties, although they seek some pleasure or profit each from the other, do not seek the same pleasm-e or profit. 282 THE nicomacheAjST ethics [book IX. of the affection which the lover feels for the object of his love, and utility the motive of the affection which the other feels for his lover, and they do not both reaUze their desires. For when these are the motives of friendship, it is dissolved as soon as the expecta- tions which induced the love are disappointed ; for it was not the persons themselves, but their possessions, that inspired the affection, and, as the possessions are not permanent, neither are the friendships. But a friendship which is a friendship of character exists p. 252. pf'T se, and is permanent, as has been said. Cause of Again, differences arise between friends when one aiSkig""^^ gets from the other something that is not what he friends" desires ; for it is like getting nothing at all, when a person does not get what he wants. For instance, there was once a person who promised a present to a harpist, and promised that the better he played, the larger should be his reward ; but next day when the harpist asked him to fulfil his promises, he said he had given him one pleasure' in payment for another. Now if this were what both wished for, it would be satisfactory ; but if the one wished for pleasure and the other for gain, and if the one has his wish and the other has not, the agreement between them will not be rightly carried out; for it is what a person happens to want that he sets his heart upon, and to get this, but nothing else, will he give the price. Value of a But It may be asked. Who is the proper person to ^^■taw settle the value of a benefaction ? Is it he who was ' The pleasure which the harpist had received must be the pleasure of anticipating payment. CHAP. I. J OF ARISTOTLE. 283 in the first instance the author, or he who was in the first instance the recipient of the benefaction? lt°^^7 seems as if the author leaves it to the recipient to settiea. settle the value. This, they say, was the practice of Protagoras, who, whenever he taught any subject, would tell his pupils to estimate the value of the knowledge in their own eyes, and would take just so much payment and no more. In such cases some people like the principle of " a stated wage"^; but if a person first takes his fee, and then does not fulfil any of his promises, because he has promised a great deal more than he can perform, it is reasonable to censure him for not carrying out his professions. The practice of taking payment in advance is probably forced upon the sophists, as otherwise nobody would pay them a fee for the knowledge which they impart. Such people then lie open to reasonable censure, if they do not do the work for which they receive payment. But it may happen that there is no distinct agreement as to the service rendered. Suppose A confers a benefaction upon JB for B's own sake^ then A, as has been said, is not p. 252. open to censure, as this is the character of a virtuous fiiendship. The return made must be such as corre- sponds to the moral purpose of the benefactor, as it is the moral purpose which constitutes a friend, or ^ The words iuitBos 8' avhpi are taken from a line of Hesiod which makes their meaning plain, liurdos S" dvSpl (j>iK* friend- do not know one another. Nor do we speak of persons who are united in judgment on any subject, e.g. on astronomy, as unanimous; for unanimity on these subjects is not a mark of friendship; but we speak of states as unanimous when they are united in judgment upon their interests, and have the same purposes and pursue a common policy. It is thus when people agree upon practical matters that they are said to be unanimous, especially when they agree upon such practical matters as are important and as are capable of belonging to both parties or to all. Thus a state is unanimous when all Unanimity the citizens are in favour of making the offices of state elective, or of forming an alliance with the Lacedaemonians, or of electing Pittacus governor, Pittacus himself having been at the time willing to govern. But when each of two parties wishes to be governor like Eteodes and Polynices in the Phoe- nissae^, there is not unanimity but discord; for 1 The scene in the Phoenissae of Euripides beginning at \. 586 will sufficiently explain this allusion. 296 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IX. unanimity does not mean that both parties entertain the same view whatever it may be, but that they entertain the same view as to the way of carrying it out, as when the masses and the upper classes agree in desiring the government of the best citizens ; for then they all gain their desire. Unanimity then' appears to be political friendship, and indeed it is often so described, as it touches the interests and concerns of life. Such unanimity can exist only among the virtuous; for they are unani- mous both in themselves'' and in their relation to each other. They are anchored, as it were, immovably, as their wishes are permanent, and do not ebb and flow like the Euripus ; the objects of their wishes are just and profitable, and they all agree in desiring these objects. It is impossible for bad men to be unanimous, as it is impossible for them to be friends, except to a slight extent ; for each desires an advantage over the other in all profits, and seeks to avoid his share of labours and public services, and while each person wishes to gain unfair advantage and to escape a fair share of duty, he criticizes and thwarts his neighbours' actions; for unless they keep an eye upon each other, their community is destroyed. The consequence is that they are always in a state of discord, each insistiQg that the other shall do what is just, and neither wishing to do it himself. ^ Reading Sfj. 2 To speak of a person as "unanimous in himself" is rather a Greek than an English mode of expression. CHAP. VII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 297 It seems that benefactors are better friends to the Chap. vn. recipients of their benefactions than are the recipients ^p"^' to their benefactors, and as this is a surprising fact, ^^^ authors people try to account for it. pients of The usual explanation is that the benefactors are tions.**^ creditors and the recipients debtors. Hence as in the case of loans the debtors would be glad if their creditors ceased to exist, but the creditors look anxiously to the safety of the debtors, so benefactors desire the existence of the recipients of their bene- factions, in the hope of receiving a return for the favours they have done them, but the debtors are not anxious to repay the debt. Supposing this to be the explanation, Epicharmus would perhaps say that to give it is to take a low view of mankind ; but it seems to be true to human nature, as people have generally short memories, and are more eager to receive benefits than to confer them. It would seem, however, that the reason lies deeper down in the nature of things. It is not like the reason which makes creditors care for their debtors ; for they have no affection for their debtors, and if they feel a wish for their safety, it is only in the hope of recovering the debt. But people who have conferred benefactions upon others feel love and affection for the recipients of their benefactions, even if these recipients do not and cannot do them any service. The same law holds good among artisans. Every artisan feels greater affection for his own work, than the work, if it were endowed with life, would feel for him. But nowhere I think is it so true as in (/ v/ 298 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IX. the case of poets ; they have an extraordinary affection for their own poems, and are as fond of them as if they were their children. It seems to be much the same with benefactors. The recipient of the benefaction is their work, and therefore they feel a greater affection for their work, than the work feels for its author. The reason is that existence is an object of desire and love to everybody, but we exist by activity i.e. by living and acting; the author of a work then may be said to exist by activity ; he is therefore fond of his work, because he is fond of existence. This affection of the author for his work is a natural law; for that which exists potentially is proved by the work to exist actively. It is also true that in the eyes of the benefactor the performance of his action is noble; he therefore delights in the person who affords him the opportunity of displaying it. The recipient of the benefaction, on the other hand, finds no nobleness, but at the best only profit, in its author, and profit is less pleasant and lovable than nobleness. Again, it is activity in the present which is pleasant, hope for the future, and recollection of the past ; but nothing is so pleasant or so lovable as the exercise of activity. Now a person who has conferred a benefit finds that his work is permanent, for noble- ness is longlived. But if he receives a benefaction, the profit is transitory. The memory too of noble deeds is pleasant, but that of useful deeds is less pleasant, if pleasant at all. It seems to be just the opposite with the expectation. Again, the feeling of CHAP. VIII.J OF ARISTOTLE. 299 aflFection is a sort of active, but the receiving of it a sort of passive, condition, and the feeling and exercise of affection naturally accompany superiority in the action. Again, we are all most fond of such things as have cost us trouble. Thus people who have made money are always fonder of it than people who have inherited it. Accordingly, as it takes no trouble to receive a benefaction, but is hard work to confer one, benefactors are more affectionate than the recipients of benefactions. This is the reason why mothers are more devoted to their children than fathers; it is that they suffer more in giving them birth and are more certain that they are their own. But this certainly belongs also to benefactors. It is often asked whether one ought to love CHAP.vrn. oneself or somebody else most should a *' person love We censure people who are exceedingly fond ofMmseifor themselves, and call them " lovers of self" by way of lis™mos^? reproach ; for it seems that a bad man has an eye to his own interest in all that he does, and all the more in proportion to his greater viciousness. Accordingly it is a charge against him that he does nothing without an eye to his own interest. The virtuous man, on the other hand, is moved by a motive of nobleness, and the better he is, the more strongly he is so moved; he acts in the interest of his friend, disregarding his own. The facts of life are at variance with these theories as indeed we might expect; for we ought, it is said, to love our best friend best ; but the best friend is he who, when he wishes the good of another, wishes it for the other's sake, and wishes it even if nobody will 300 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IX. know his wish. But these conditions and all such others as are characteristic of friendship, are best realized in the relation of a man to himself; for it ^- ^*^ has been said that aU the characteristics of friendship in the relation of a man to other men are dei'ived from his relation to himself. All the proverbial sayings agree with this view, such as "Friends have one soul," "Friends' goods are common goods," "Equality is friendship," and "Charity begins at hotne"; for all these conditions exist preeminently in relation to oneself, as every one is his own best Mend, and therefore must love himself best. It is not unnatural to ask. Which of these two lines of argument ought we to follow, as there is something convincing in both ? Perhaps then it will be well to analyse them and to determine how far and in what sense they are respectively true. Now the truth wiU I think become clear, if we ascertain Nature of the meaning of the word "self-love" in them both. When people use it as a term of reproach, they give the name "lovers of self" to people who assign themselves a larger share of money, honours, and bodily pleasures than belongs to them. These are the objects of desire to men in general. It is these that they conceive to be the highest goods, on these that they set ,their hearts, and it is for these therefore that they contend. Thus people who are eager to get an undue share of these things gratify their desires and emotions generally, or, in other words, the irrational parts of the soul. This is the character of men in general, and hence as men in general are bad, the term "self-love" has come to be used in a self-loTe. CHAP. VIII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 301 bad sense. It is right then to censure people who are lovers of self in this sense. It is easy to see that people ordinarily apply the term "self-love" to those who assign themselves an undue share of such things as money, honour, and pleasure ; for if a person were to set his heart always on preeminence in doing what is just or temperate or virtuous in any other respect, and were always and by all means to reserve to himself the noble part, nobody would accuse him of self-love or censure him for it. Yet it would seem that such a person is conspicuously a lover of self. At all events he assigns to himself what is in the highest sense good, and gratifies the supreme part of his nature and yields it an uiiqualified obedience. But as it is the supreme part of a state or any other corporation which seems to be in the truest sense the state or corporation itself, so it is with a man. Accordingly he is in the truest sense a lover of self, who loves and gratifies the supreme part of his being. Again, a person is called continent and incontinent according as reason is, or is not, the ruling faculty in his being. But to say this is to say that the reason is the man. Also it is when we act most rationally that we are held in the truest sense to have acted ourselves, and to have acted voluntarily. It is perfectly clear then that it is the rational part of a man which is the man himself, and that it is the virtuous man who feels the most affection for this part. It follows that the virtuous man is a lover of self, although not in the sense in which a man who is censured for self-love is a lover of self, but in a sense 302 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [BOOK TX. differing fi-om it as widely as a life directed by reason differs from a life directed by emotion, and as the desire for what is noble differs from a desire for what seems to be one's interest. Now if people set their hearts preeminently upon noble actions, we all approve and applaud them ; but if all people were eager in pursuit of what is noble and exerted themselves to the utmost to do the noblest deeds, then the state would have all its wants supplied, and an individual citizen would have the greatest of all goods, assuming that virtue is the greatest good. We conclude then that a good man ought to be a lover of self, as by his noble deeds he will benefit himself and serve others, but that the wicked man ought not to be a lover of self, as he will injure himself and other people too by following his evil passions. In the bad man then there is a discrepancy between what he ought to do and what he does, whereas the virtuous man does what he ought to do ; for reason always chooses what is best for itself, and the good man is obedient to his reason. It is true of the virtuous man that he will act often in the interest of his friends and of his country, and, if need be, will even die for them. He will surrender money, honour, and aU the goods for which the world contends, reserving only nobleness for himself, as he would rather enjoy an intense pleasure for a short time than a moderate pleasure long, and would rather live one year nobly than many years indifferently, and would rather perform one noble and lofty action than many poor actions. This is CHAP. VIII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 303 true of one who lays down his life for another ; he chooses great nobleness for his own. Such a man will surrender riches gladly if only he may enrich his friends ; for then while his friend gets the money, he gets the nobleness, and so assigns the greater good to himself. It is the same with honour and offices of state. All these he wiU surrender to his friend, but the surrender is noble and laudable in his eyes. It is reasonable then to call such a man virtuous, as he prefers nobleness to everything. He may even surrender the opportvuiity of action to his friend. It may be nobler for him to inspire his friend to act than to act himself. Wherever then the virtuous man deserves praise, it is clear that he assigns to himself a preponderant share of noble conduct. In this sense then it is right to be a lover of self, but not in the sense in which ordinary people love themselves. Another question in dispute is whether the happy Chap. ix. man will need friends or not. wpy man It is sometimes said that people, whose lives are need 1.-. 1 ,1 , n n • J friends? fortunate and mdependent, have no need or inenos, as they are already in possession of all good things. As being independent then they have no need of anything more, whereas a friend is like a second self, who supplies what it is not in our own power to supply. Hence the saying "Let but God bless us, what's the good of friends?^" But it looks absurd to assign all good things to 1 Euripides, Orestes 667. 304 THE NICOMACHBAN ETHICS [bOOK IX. the happy man, and yet not to assign friends — the greatest as it seems of all external goods. If it is more a friend's part to do good than to receive it, if beneficence is the part of the good man or of virtue, and if it is nobler to do good to one's friends than to strangers, the virtuous man will need somebody to do good to. Accordingly it is sometimes asked whether we need friends more in times of prosperity or in times of adversity, the idea being that an unfortunate man needs somebody to do him a service, and a fortunate man somebody for him to do good to. Again, it is I think absurd to place the fortunate man in solitude, as nobody would choose to possess all good things by himself. For man is a social being, and disposed to live with others. It follows that the fortunate man must live in society, as he possesses all natural goods. But it is clearly better to spend one's days with friends and virtuous people than with strangers, who may not be virtuous. It follows therefore that the happy man has need of friends. What is the meaning then of the first view', and in what sense is it true? It may be suggested that in the ordinary view friends are regarded as people who can be useful. Now the fortunate man will not need friends of this kind, as he already possesses all that is good, nor will he need friends to give him pleasure, or he will need them but little; for as his life is pleasant in itself, it has no need of adventitious pleasure. But as he does not need friends of this kind, it looks as if he did not need friends at all. 1 i.e. the view that the happy man haS no need of friends. CHAP. IX. J OF ARISTOTLE. 305 But this, I think, is not true, for it has been stated at p. le. the outset that happiness is a form of activity, and it is clear that an activity is always coming into being, and does not already exist, like a piece of property. But if happiness consists in life and activity, and the activity of the good man is virtuous and pleasant in itself, as has been said at the outset, if there is ap 20. pleasure in the sense that a thing is our own, and if we are better able to contemplate others than our- selves, and to contemplate the actions of others than our own, it follows that the actions of virtuous people, if they are friends, are pleasant to the good, as they contain both the elements' which are naturally pleasant The fortunate man then wiU need friends of this kind, as it is his choice to contemplate such actions as are good and belong to himself; for the actions of the good man who is his friend answer to this description. Again, it is supposed that the happy man must have a pleasant life. Now life is hard, if it be lived in solitude, as it is difficult for a man easily to maintain a constant activity by himself, but it is comparatively easy in the society of others and in relation to them. The activity in relation to others then will be more continuous, and it is pleasant in itself. It ought to be so in the case of the fortunate man ; for a virtuous man qva virtuous man delights in virtuous 1 The two elements are (1) that our friend's actions are good, (2) that they belong to us, our friend being, as Aristotle says, " a second self." W. N. E. 20 so 6 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IX. actions, but is offended at vicious actions, as a musician feels pleasure in good music and pain at bad music. There is a certain discipline too in virtue which may be derived from living in good society, as Theognis' says. But if we look more deeply into the nature of things, it seems that a virtuous friend is naturally ?. 20. desirable to a virtuous man; for that which is naturally good, as has been said, is good and pleasant Essential in itself to the virtuous man. But while life among jfe"'* ° the lower animals is defined by the faculty of sensa- tion, it is defined among men by the faculty of sensation or thought. But a faculty is intelligible only by reference to its activity. It is upon the activity that the faculty essentially depends. It seems then that life consists essentially in sensation or thought. Again, life is a thing that is good and pleasant in itself, for it possesses the definiteness* which is of the nature of the good ; but that which is naturally good is good also to the virtuous man. It is as being a natural good that life seems to be pleasant to everybody. But in speaking of life as pleasant, we must not take a vicious or corrupt life, or a life of pain; for such a life is indefinite, as are its conditions. But we will try to clear up the subject of pain 1 The saying of Theognis ivBXav iiev yap an itrffKa, which is quoted p. 179, 1. 19, may be taken as illustrating this opinion. 2 The idea of " definiteness" or " limitation" as a characteristic of the good is Pythagorean. Cp. to yap kokov tou meipov, as oi Hvdayopeioi cixaCop, to 8* dyaBou tou TTfirepaa-iievov, p. 29, IL 32 — 34. CHAP. IX.] OP ARISTOTLE. 307 hereafter. Life itself is good and pleasant. It seems to be so from the fiict that it is desired by people, and especially by the virtuous and fortunate ; for it is to them that life is most desirable, as it is theirs "which is the most fortunate life. One who sees perceives that he sees, and one who hears that he hears, and one who walks that he walks, and similarly in all our activities there is something in us which perceives that we exercise the activity ; and if so, it foUows that we can perceive that we perceive, and understand that we understand. But to perceive or understand that we perceive or understand, is to perceive or tmderstand that we exist' ; for existence consists, as we said, in perceiving or understanding. But the perception or sensation of life is a pleasure in itself; for life is naturally a good, and it is a pleasure to perceive good existing in oneself. Life is an object of desire, and to none so desirable as to the good, because existence is to them good and pleasant ; for they feel a pleasure in their consciousness of what is good in itself. But the virtuous man stands in the same relation to his friend as to himself ; for his friend is a second self. As then everyone desires his own existence, so or similarly he desires the existence of his friend. But the desirableness of existence, as p. 291. we saw, lies in the sense of one's own goodness, such a sensation being pleasant in itself. We require therefore the consciousness of our friend's existence, ' Sir A. Grant justly regards this statement of "the absolute unity of existence with thought" as anticipating the Cartesian formula, Cogito, ergo sum. 20—2 308 THE NICOMACHBAN ETHICS [bOOK IX. and this we shall get by living with him and asso- ciating with him in conversation and thought ; for it would seem that this is what we mean when we speak of living together in the case of men, we do not mean, as in the case of cattle, merely occupying the same feeding-ground. If the fortunate man then finds existence desirable in itself, as being naturally good and pleasant, and if a friend's existence is much the same as one's own, it follows that a friend will be a desirable thing. But that which is desirable a man ought to possess, or, if he does not possess it, he will be so far deficient. We conclude therefore that, if a person is to be happy, he will need virtuous friends, Ohap.x. Is it our duty then to make the largest possible mmber of iiumber of fricuds ? or is it with friendship generally, riends. as with the friendship of hospitality, where it has been neatly said "Give me not many friends, nor give me noneV' i.e. will it here too be proper neither to be fi-iendless nor again to have an excessive number of friends ? In the case of friends whose friendship we make from a motive of expediency the rule is a perfectly proper one, as it is a laborious task to return the services of a number of people, nor is life long enough for the task. A larger number of such friends then than are sufficient for one's own life would be superfiuous and prejudicial to noble living ; they are therefore unnecessary. Again, of those whom we make friends as being 1 Hesiod,*Epya KOI 'Hfiepat, 713. CHAP. X.] OF AEISTOTLE. 309 pleasant or sweet to us, few are enough, as a little sweetening is enough in our diet. But if we take the case of virtuous friends it may be asked. Should they be as numerous as possible, or is there a fixed limitation to the size of a circle of friends, as there is to the size of a state ? For ten people would not be enough to compose a state ; on the other hand, if the population rose to a hundred thousand, it would cease to be a state. It may be suggested, however, that the number of citizens is not a single fixed amount, but may be anything within certain definite limits. So too there will be a definite limit to the number of friends. It will, I think, be the highest niunber with whom a person could live. For it is community of life which we saw to be the especial characteristic of friendship, and it is easy to see that a person cannot live with a number of people and distribute himself among them. Again, a person's friends must themselves be friends of each other, if they are all to pass their days together, and this is a condition which can hardly exist among a number of people. It is hard for a person to sympathise fittingly with a number of people in their joys and sorrows ; for it will probably happen that at the very time when he is caUed upon to rejoice with one he will be called upon to sorrow with another. Perhaps it is well then not to try to have the largest possible munber of friends, but to have only so many as are sufficient for community of life, as it would seem to be impossible to be a devoted friend of a number of people. Hence it is impossible to be 310 THE NIOOMACHBAN ETHICS [bOOK IX. in love with several people ; for love is in its intention a sort of exaggerated friendship, and it is impossible to feel this exaggerated friendship except for an individual. So too it is impossible to be the devoted friend of more than a few people. This is what seems to be practically the case. We do not find that people have a number of friends who are as intimate with them as comrades. The classical friendships' of story too have all been friendships between two persons. People who have a host of friends, and who take everybody to their arms, seem to be nobody's friends, unless indeed in the sense in which all fellow-citizens are friends ; and if they have a host of friends, we call them complaisant people. Although then as a fellow-citizen it is possible for one to be the friend of a number of people and yet not to be complaisant, but to be truly virtuous, it is impossible to be the friend of a number of people as being virtuous and deserving of friendship for their own sake. We must be content if we can find only a ' few people who deserve such friendship. HAP. XI. It remains to ask. Is it in times of prosperity or in hettier timcs of advcrsity that friends are more needed? LfiUuS e more We require them at both times ; for in adversity we •Mperity need assistance, and in prosperity we need people to >rsit°^ live with and to do good to, as it is presumably our wish to do good. Friendship then is more necessary in times of 1 Such as the friendship of Achilles and Patroclus or of Damon and Pythias. CHAP. XI.] OF AHISTOTLB. 311 adversity ; therefore in adversity we want friends to help us; but it is nobler in times of pTosperity; therefore in times of prosperity we look for good people, as it is more desirable to do them services and to live in their society. For the mere presence of friends is pleasant even in adversity, as pain is alleviated by the sympathy of friends. Accordingly it may be doubted whether they take part of the burden as it were upon themselves, or it is rather the pleasure of their presence, and the thought of their sympathy, which diminishes the pain we feeL We need not now discuss whether this or some- thing else is the cause of the alleviation. It is clear, at all events, that the fact is as we state it. But it seems that the presence of friends is a source partly of comfort and partly of pain. There is a pleasure in the mere sight of friends, especially when one is in adversity, and something too of support against sorrow; for the look and voice of a friend are consoling to us if he be a person of tact, as he knows our character and the sources of our pleasure and pain. On the other hand it is painfiil to perceive that a person is pained at our own adversity, as everybody avoids being a cause of pain to his friends. Accordingly people of a courageous nature shrink from involving their friends in their pain, and such a person, unless he be extraordinarily indififerent to pain, cannot endure the pain which he causes themj nor can he in any way put up with people whose sympathy takes the form of lamentation, as he is not fond of indulging in lamentation himself It is only weak women and eflfeminate men who take delight in 312 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK IX. such people as ^display their sympathy by their groans and who love them as friends and sympathi- sers in their sorrow. But it is evident that we ought always to imitate one who is better than ourselves. The presence of friends in seasons of prosperity is a pleasant means of passing the time, and not only so, but it suggests the idea that they take pleasure in our own goods. It would seem a duty then to be forward in inviting friends to share our good fortune, as there is a nobleness in conferring benefactions, but to be slow in inviting them to share our ill fortune, as it is a duty to give them as small a share of our evils as possible, whence the saying "Enough that I am wretched^." But the time when we should be most ready to call them to our side is the time when it is probable that at the cost of but slight personal inconvenience they will have a chance of doing us a great service. On the other hand, it is, I think, proper for us to go to our friends when they are in trouble, even if they do not send for us, and to make a point of going, as it is a friendly act to do good, especially to those who are in need and have made no claim upon us; for this is the nobler and pleasanter course for both. It is proper too to be forward in helping them to enjoy themselves, as this again is a service that friends may render, but to be less forward in seeking 1 The words of Jocasta in the Oedipus Tyrannus 1061 oKis voaovcr' eyoj, are in sense, though not exactly in form, the same as this quotation. CHAP. XI.] OF ARISTOTLE. 313 to get enjoyment for ourselves, as there is nothing noble in being forward to receive benefits. Still we must, I think, be on our guard against seeming churlish, as sometimes happens, in rejecting their services. It appears then that the presence of friends is universally desirable. Nothing is so welcome to people who are in love Chap. xn. as the sight of one another. There is no sense that ^I^^X' they choose in preference to this, as it is upon this ^^ *?, , , more than upon anything else that the existence and friendship creation of their love depends. May we not say then that there is nothing which friends desire so much as community of life ? For the essence of friendship is association. Again, a man stands in the same relation to his friend as to himself; but the sense of his own existence is desirable; so too then is that of the existence of his friend. The activity of friends too is realized in living together. It is only reasonable therefore that they should desire community of life. Again, whatever it is that people regard as con- stituting existence, whatever it is that is their object in desiring life, it is in this that they wish to live with their friends. Accordingly some people are com- panions in drinking, others in gambUng, others in gymnastic exercises, or in the chase or in philosophy, and each class spends its days in that for which it cares more than for anything else in life ; for as it is their wish to live with their friends, they do the things and participate in the things which seem to them to constitute a common life. 3 1 4 NICOMACHBAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [bK; IX. Thus the friendship of the bad proves to be vicious ; for as they are unstable, they participate in what is bad, and become vicious by a process of mutual assimilation. But the friendship of the virtuous is virtuous; it grows as their intercourse grows, and they seem to be morally elevated by the exercise of their activity and by the correction of each other's faults ; for each models himself upon the pleasing features of the other's character, whence the saying "From good men learn good life^." This may be regarded as a sufficient discussion of friendship or love. We will proceed to discuss plea- sure. ' A saying of Theognis. Cp. p. 174 1. 31. BOOK X. It is natural, I think, to discuss pleasure next; Chap.i. for it seems that there is, in a preeminent degree, an ®*^""®' affinity between pleasure and our human nature, and that is the reason why, in the education of the young, we steer their course by the rudders of pleasure and pain. It seems too that there is no more important element in the formation of a virtuous character than a rightly directed sense of pleasure and dislike; for pleasure and pain are coextensive with life, and they exercise a powerful influence in promoting virtue and happiness of life, as we choose what is pleasant and avoid what is painfuL Considering, then, the importance of these ques- tions, it would seem to be clearly a duty not to pass them over, especially as they admit of much dispute. For some people say that the good' is pleasure ; ^^*|2^« others, on the contrary, that pleasure is something good, utterly bad, whether, as is possible, they are convinced that it really is so, or they think it better in the interest of human life to represent pleasure as an evU, even if it is not so, feeling that men are generally inclined to pleasure, and are the slaves of their 1 Aristotle in this "book speaks of "the good" {rayaSov), mean- ing the highest good or summum bonum. 316 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK X. pleasures, and that it is a duty therefore to lead them in the contrary direction, as they will so arrive at the mean or proper state. But I venture to think that this is not a right statement of the case. For in matters of the emotions and actions theories are not so trustworthy as facts ; and thus, when theories disagree with the facts of perception, they fall into contempt, and involve the truth itself in their destruction. For if a person censures pleasure and yet is seen at times to make pleasure his aim, he is thought to incline to pleasure as being entirely desirable; for it is beyond the power of ordinary people to make distinctions. It seems then the true theories are exceedingly useful, not only as the means of knowledge but as guides of life; for as being in harmony with facts, they are believed, and being believed they encourage people who understand them to regulate their lives in accordance with them. Enough then of such considerations ; let us review the various doctrines of pleasure. Chap. h. Eudoxus held that pleasure was the good, because EudSs. be saw that all things, whether rational or irrational, Heasnre make pleasure their aim. He argued that in all cases that which is desirable is good, and that which is most desirable is most good ; hence the fact of all things being drawn to the same object is an indication that that object is the best for all, as everything discovers what is good for itself in the same way as it discovers food; but^ that that which is good for all, and is the aim of all, is the good. 1 Reading bk. CHAP. II.] OF AEISTOTLE. 317 His theories were accepted, not so much for their intrinsic value as for the excellence of his moral character; for he was regarded as a person of exemplary temperance. It seemed then that he did not put forward these views as being a votary of pleasure, but that the truth was reaUy as he said. He held that this truth resulted with equal clearness from a consideration of the opposite of plea»u/re; for as pain is something which everybody should avoid, so too its opposite is something which everybody should desire. He argued that a thing is in the highest degree desirable, if we do not desire it for any ulterior reason, or with any ulterior motive, and this is admittedly the case with pleasure; for if a person is pleased, nobody asks the farther question. What is his motive in being pleased ? a fact which proves that pleasure is desirable in itself. And further that the addition of pleasure to any good, e.g. to just or temperate conduct, renders that good more desirable, and it follows that if the good is augmented by a thing, that thing must itself be a good. It seems then that this argument proves pleasure Pleasure to be a good, but not to be a good in a higher sense *" ^''° " than anything else; for any good whatever is more desirable with the addition of another good than when it stands alone. It is by a precisely similar argument that Plato tries to prove that pleastire is not the good. Pleasure (he says) is not the chief good, for the pleasant life is more desirable with the addition of prudence than without it; but if the combination is better, pleasure is not the good, as 318 THE mCOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK X. the good itself cannot be made more desirable by any addition. But it is clear that, if pleaswre is not the good, neither can anything else be which is made more desirable by the addition of any absolute good. What is it then which is incapable of such addition, but at the same time admits of our participating in it ? For it is a good of this kind which is the object of our research. Desire and People who argue on the other hand that that which all things aim at is not a; good may be said to talk nonsense ; for we accept the universal opinion as true, and one who upsets our trust in the universal opinion wiU find it hard to put forward any opinion that is more trustworthy. If it were only unintelligent beings that longed for pleasure, there would be some- thing in what he says ; but if intelligent beings also long for it, how can it be so? It is probable that even in the lower creatures there is some natural' principle which is superior to the creatures themselves, and aims at their proper good. Argninent3 Nor does it Seem that these people fairly meet pfeasure the argument drawn from the opposite of pleasure. go^d^ * They say it does not follow that, if pain is an evil, pleasure is a good, as not only is one evil opposed to another, but both are opposed to that which is neither one nor the other, hut a neutral state. This is true enough, but it does not apply to pleasure and pain. For if both pleasure and pain were evil, it would have been a duty to avoid both, and if neither 1 I cannot help thinking that aya^ov ought to be omitted from the text. CHAP. II.] OF ARISTOTLE. 319 were evil, it would have been a duty not to avoid either, or not to avoid one more than the other; whereas in fact it is clear that people avoid one as an evil, and desire the other as a good. It follows then that pleasure and pain are opposed to each other as good and evil. Nor again does it follow that, if pleasure is not a quality, neither is it a good, for the activities of virtue are not qualities, nor is happiness. It is argued too that good is definite, but pleasure is indefinite, as it admits of degrees. Now if the ground of this opinion is that it is possible to be pleased in a greater or a less degree, the same thing is true of justice and the other virtues. For here it is evident that we speak of persons as possessing the several virtues in a greater or less degree ; some people are just and courageous in a greater or less degree than others, and it is possible to act with a greater or less degree of justice and temperance. If however the meaning is that the indefiniteness resides in the pleasures, this is, I think, not the true explanation, supposing that some pleasures are mixed and others unmixed\ Again", health is definite, yet it admits of degrees; and why should it not be so with pleasure? For health is not the same symmetry or proportion of ^ Aristotle, following Plato's theory of " mixed " and " un- mixed" pleasures, argues that it is only such pleasures as are "mixed" which can be said to possess the character of "in- definiteness." Cp. Philebus p. 52. ^ Beading xal tL koiXvci. 320 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [BOOK X. elements in all people, nor is it always uniform in the same person ; it admits of relaxation up to a certain point, and of different degrees, -without ceasing to be health. Something of the same kind then may be also true of pleasure. Again, the opponents of pleaswe, looking upon the good as perfect or complete, and the processes of movement and production as imperfect or incomplete, try to prove that pleasure is motion or production. But they are wrong, I think, nor is pleasure a motion at all. For quickness and slowness are characteristic, it seems, of every motion, either absolutely, as of the motion of the universe, or else relatively, but neither of them is a condition inherent in pleasure. It is possible to become pleased, as it is to become angry, quickly, but not to be pleased quickly or relatively, i.e. in comparison with somebody else, as it is to walk or to grow quickly and so on. The transition then, to a state of pleasure may be quick or slow, but the active experience of pleasure, i.e. the state of being pleased, cannot be quick. Pleasure In what seuse, too, can pleasure be a process of pro- proeeBB ductiou ? It is apparently not the case that anything daS^on ^^° ^® produced out of anything ; it is the case that a thing is resolved into that out of which it is produced. Also, pain is the destruction of that of which plea- sure is the prdduction. It is said too that pain is /a deficiency of the natural state, and pleasure its satisfaction. But this deficiency and this satisfaction are emotions of the body. If, then, pleasure is a satisfaction of the natural state, it follows that the part which is the seat of the satisfaction will feel CHAP. II.] OF ARISTOTLE. 321 pleasure i.e. the body. But this seems not to be the case. We conclude therefore that pleasure is not a satisfaction of the natural state, although one may feel pleasure while the process of satisfaction is going on, as he may feel pain while undergoing' an opera- tion. This Tiew of pleasure, viz. that it is a process of satisfaction, seems to have originated in the pleasures and pains of eating and drinking, as in them we first feel a deficiency and an antecedent pain, and then feel pleasure at the satisfaction. But this is not true of all pleasures; the pleasures of mathematics e.g. have no such antecedent pain, nor among the plea- sures of the senses have those of the smell, nor again many sounds and sights, memories and hopes. What is there then of which these will be processes of pro- duction ? For in them there has been no deficiency to be satisfied. But if the instance of immoral pleasures be adduced to prove that pleasure is a bad thing, we may answer that these are not really pleasant. They may be pleasant to people who are in a bad condition, but it must not be inferred that they are pleasant except to such people, any more than that things are healthful or sweet or bitter in themselves, because they are so to invalids, or that things are white, because they appear so to people who are sufiering from ophthalmia. Perhaps the truth may be stated thus : Pleasures are desirable, but not if they are immoral in their 1 It is hardly likely that re/nvo/if yos is the true reading; but I have tried to give such sense as can be made of it. W. N. E. 21 322 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [^OOK X. origin, just as wealth is pleasant, but not if it be obtained at the cost of turning traitor to one's country, or health, but not at the cost of eating any food, however disagreeable. Or it may be said that plea- sures are of different kinds, those which are noble in their origin are different from those which are dishonourable, and it is impossible to enjoy the pleasure of the just man without being just, or that of the musician without being musical, and so on. The distinction drawn between a friend and a flatterer seems to bring out clearly the truth that pleasure is not a good, or that there are pleasures of different kinds; for it seems that while the object of the friend in social intercourse is good, that of the flatterer is pleasure, and while the flatterer is cen- sured, the friend for his disinterestedness is praised. Again, nobody would choose to live all his life with the mind of a child, although he should enjoy the pleasures of childhood to the utmost, or to delight in doing what is utterly shameful, although he were never to suffer pain for doing it. There are many things too upon which we should set our hearts, even if they brought no pleasure with them, e.g. sight, memory, knowledge, and the possession of the virtues; and if it be true that these are necessarily attended by pleasures, it is immaterial, as we should desire them even if no pleasure resulted from them. It seems to be clear then that pleasure is not the good, nor is every pleasure desirable, and that there are some pleasures which are desirable in themselves, and they differ in kind or in origin from the others. CHAP. II.] OF ARISTOTLE. 323 We may regard this as a sufficient account of such views as are held in regard to pleasure and pain. But the nature or character of pleasure wiU be Chap. m. , , .„ , „ Nature of more clearly seen, it we resume our argument irom pieasnre. the beginning. It seems that the act of sight is perfect or com- plete at any time; it does not lack anything which will afterwards be produced, and will make it perfect of its kind. Pleasure appears to resemble sight in this respect; it is a whole, nor is it possible at any time to find a pleasure which will be made perfect of its kind by increased duration. It follows that pleasure is not a motion; forP'«asnre , . . , . not " every motion takes a certam time, and aims at a motion or certain end. Thus the builder's art is perfect or production. complete when it has accomplished its object It is complete, either in respect of the whole time which the building took, or in respect of the moment when it was completed. But in the various parts of the time the various processes or motions are imperfect and different in kind from the whole and from one another; for the setting of the stones is different from the fluting of the pillar, and both from the building of the temple as a whole, and whereas the building of the temple is complete, nothing being wanting to the object proposed, that of the basement and the triglyph is incomplete, as each is only the building of a part of the temple. These processes or motions are therefore different in kind, and it is impossible at any time when the building is going on to find a motion which is complete or 21—2 324 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK X, perfect of its kind. Such a motion, if found at all, will be found only in the whole time. It is much the same with walking or any other process. For here again, although all locomotion is a motion from one place to another, there are different kinds of locomotion, such as flying, walking, jumping, and the like. And not only so, but walking itself is of different kinds; for the starting-point and the goal are not the same in the whole course, and in a part of it, or in one part of the course and in another ; nor is it the same thing to cross one line as to cross another; for it is not only that a person crosses a line, but the line which he crosses is in a certain place, and one line is in a different place from another. The subject of motion has been accurately dis- cussed in another treatise'. Motion is apparently not complete in any and every period of time; on the contrary, most motions are incomplete and diffe- rent in kind, inasmuch as the starting-point and the goal constitute a difference of kind. Pleasure on the other hand seems to be complete or perfect of its kind in any and every period of time. It is clear then that motion and pleasure must be distinct from one another, and that pleasure is some- thing which is whole and perfect. Another reason for holding this view is that motion is impossible except in a period of time, but pleasure is not; for the pleasure of a moment is a whole. * v(riK^ axpSatris, Books in. sqq. CHAP. III.] OF ARISTOTLE. 325 It is clear from these considerations that pleasure is not rightly described as a motion or process of production, for such a description is not appropriate to all things but only to such as are divisible into parts and are not wholes. For there is no process of production in an act of sight or in a mathematical point or in a unit, nor is any one of these things a motion or a process of production. It follows that there is no such process in pleasure, as it is a whole. Again, every sense exercises its activity upon its Chap. iv. own object, and the activity is perfect only when the of'a perfect sense itself is in a sound condition, and the object is activity. the noblest that falls within the domain of that sense ; for this seems to be preeminently the character of the perfect activity. We may say that it makes no difference whether we speak of the sense itself or of the organ in which it resides as exercising the activity; in every instance the activity is highest when the part which acts is in the best condition, and the object upon which it acts is the highest of the objects which fall within its domain. Such an activity win not only be the most perfect, but the most pleasant; for there is pleasure in all sensation, and similarly in all thought and speculation, and the activity wiU be pleasantest when it is most perfect, and it will be most perfect when it is the activity of the part being in a sound condition and acting upon the most excellent of the objects that fall within its domain. Pleasure perfects the activity, but not in the same way in which the excellence of the sense or of the object of sense perfects it, just as health is the 326 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK X. cause of our being in a healthy state in one sense and the doctor is the cause of it in another. It is clear that every sense has its proper pleasure ; for we speak of pleasant sights, pleasant sounds and so on. It is clear too that the pleasure is greatest when the sense is best, and its object is best ; but if the sentient subject and the sensible object are at their best, there will always be pleasure so long as there is a subject to act and an object to be acted upon. When it is said that pleasure perfects the activity, it is not as a state or quality inherent in the subject but as a perfection superadded to it, like the bloom of youth to people in the prime of life. So long then as the object of thought or sensation and the critical or contemplative subject are such as they ought to be, there will be pleasure in the exercise of the activity ; for this is the natural result if the agent and the patient remain in the same relation to each other. topossi- It may be asked then, How is it that nobody feels contmuous pleasure continuously? It is probably because we pleasure, gj.^^ weary. Human beings are incapable of con- tinuous activity, and as the activity comes to an end, so does the pleasure; for it is a concomitant of the activity. It is for the same reason that some things give pleasure when they are new, but give less pleasure afterwards; for the intelligence is called into play at first, and applies itself to its object with intense activity, as when we look a person full in the face in order to recognize him, but afterwards the activity ceases to be so intense and becomes remiss, and consequently the pleasure also fades away. CHAP. IV.] OF ARISTOTLE. 327 It may be supposed that everybody desires plea- sure, for' everybody clings to life. But life is a species of activity and a person's activity displays itself in the sphere and with the means which are after his own heart. Thus a musician exercises his ears in listening to music, a student his intellect in speculation, and so on. But pleasure perfects the activities ; it therefore'' perfects life, which is the aim of human desire. It is reasonable then to aim at pleasure, as it perfects life in each of us, and life is an object of desire. Whether we desire life for the sake of pleasure or Chap. v. pleasure for the sake of life, is a question which may anTiUe!^ be dismissed for the moment. For it appears that pleasure and life are yoked together and do not admit of separation, as pleasure is impossible with- out activity and every activity is perfected by plea- sure. If this be so, it seems to follow that pleasures are Keasnres ' "^ of different of different kinds, as we hold that things which are irinda. different in kind are perfected by things which are themselves different in kind. For this is apparently the rule in the works of nature or of art, e.g. animals, trees, pictures, statues, a house, or a piece of furniture. Similarly we hold that energies which are different in kind are perfected by things which are also different in kind. Now the pleasures of the intellect are different from the pleasures of the senses, and these again are different in kind from one another. It follows that ' Beading ort. " Beading 8^. 328 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [BOOK X. the pleasures which perfect them will also be dif- ferent. This conclusion would appear also to result from the intimate connexion of each pleasure with the activity Avhich it perfects. For the activity is in- creased by its proper pleasure, as if the activity is pleasant, we are more likely to arrive at a true judgment or an accurate result in any matter. It is BO e.g. with people who are fond of geometry ; they make better geometricians and understand the various problems of geometry better than other people. It is so too with people who are fond of music or architecture or any other subject; their progress in their particular subject is due to the pleasure which they take in it. Pleasure helps to increase activity, and that which helps to increase a thing must be closely connected with it. Where things then are different in kind, the things which are closely con- nected with them will also be different in kind. Pleasure TMs becomes still clearer when we observe that yity*"'^ the pleasures which spring irom one activity are impediments to the exercise of another. Thus people who are fond of the flute are incapable of attending to an argument, if they hear somebody playing the flute, as they take a greater pleasure in flute-playing than in the activity which they are called to exercise at the moment; hence the pleasure of the flute- playing destroys their argumentative activity. Much the same result occurs in other cases, when a person exercises his activity on two subjects simultaneously; the pleasanter of the two drives out the other, especially if it be much the pleasanter, until the CHAP, v.] OF ARISTOTLE. 329 activity of the other disappears. Accordingly, if we take intense delight in anything, we cannot do any- thing else at all. It is only when we do not care much for a thing that we do something else as well, just as people who eat sweetmeats in the theatres do so most when the actors are bad. As the pleasure then which is proper to an Pleasures activity refines it and gives it greater permanence ^opefto and excellence, while alien pleasures impair it, it is "■"'"'"e^- clear that there is a wide diflference between these pleasures. It may almost be said that the pleasures which are alien to it have the same effect as the pains which are proper to it; for the pains which are proper to an activity destroy it, as, when a person finds writing or thinking unpleasant and painful, he does not write or does not think, as the case may be. The pleasures and pains then which are proper to an activity have opposite effects upon it. I mean by "proper" such as are the consequences of the activity per se. But it has been already stated that alien pleasures have much the same effect as pain; they are destructive of the activity, although not destruc- tive of it in the same way. Again, as the activities differ in goodness and badness, some being desirable, some undesirable, and some neither the one nor the other, so it is with pleasures, as every activity has its proper pleasure. Thus the pleasure which is proper to a virtuous activity is good, and that which is proper to a low activity is vicious. For the desires of what is noble are themselves laudable, the desires of what is dis- graceful are censurable; but the pleasures which 330 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK X. reside in the activities are more strictly proper to them than the desires, as the latter are distinct' from the activities in time and nature, but the former are closely related in time to the activities, and are so difficult to distinguish from them that it is a question whether the activity is identical with the pleasure. It seems however that pleasure is not the same thing as thought or sensation ; it would be strange if it were so ; but the impossibility of separating them makes some people regard them as the same. As the activities then are different, so are the pleasures. Sight is different from or superior to touch in purity, hearing and smell are superior to taste; there is a corresponding difference therefore in their pleasures. The pleasures of the intellect too are different from or superior to these, and there are different kinds of pleasures of the senses or of the intellect. It seems that there is a pleasure, as there is a function, which is proper to every living thing, viz. the pleasure inherent in its activity. If we consider individual living things, we see this is so; for the pleasures of a horse, a dog, and a man are different, and as Heraclitus says, "a donkey would choose a bundle of hay in preference to gold; for fodder is pleasanter to donkeys than gold." As the pleasures then of beings who are different in kind are themselves different in kind, it would be reasonable to suppose that there is no difference between the pleasures of the same beings. But there ' The desire is distinct from the activity in time, as being antecedent to it, and in nature, as being less complete in itself. CHAP, v.] OF ARISTOTLE. 331 is a wide difference, at least in the case of men ; the same things give pleasure to some people and pain to others, to some they are painful and hateful, to others pleasant and lovable. This is true of sweet things ; the same things do not seem sweet to a person in a fever and to a person in good health, nor does the same thing seem hot to an invalid and to a person in a good physical condition. It is much the same with other things as weU. But in all these cases it seems that the thing Relation of really is what it appears to the virtuous man to be. aifa^'"* But if this is a true statement of the case, as it seems '"'*°®' to be, if virtue or the good man qua good is the measure of everything, it follows that it is such pleasures as appear pleasures to the good man that are really pleasures, and the things which afford him delight that are really pleasant. It is no wonder if what he finds disagreeable seems pleasant to some- body else, as men are liable to many corruptions and defilements ; but such things are not pleasant except to these people, and to them only when they are in this condition. It is clear then that we must not speak of pleasures which are admitted to be disgraceful as pleasures, except in relation to people who are thoroughly corrupt. But the question remains, Among such pleasures as are seen to be good, what is the character or nature of the pleasures that deserve to be called the proper pleasures of Man ? It is plain, I think, from a consideration of the activities ; for the activities bring pleasures in their train. Whether then there is one activity or there are several be- 332 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK X. longing to the perfect and fortunate man, it is the pleasures which perfect these activities that would be strictly described as the proper pleasures of Man. All other pleasures are only in a secondary or fractional sense the pleasures of Man, as are all other activities. Chap. Ti After this discussion of the kinds of virtue and appiness. fjjgjj^gijjp ^nd pleasure it remains to give a sketch of p. 5. happiness, since we defined happiness as the end of human things. We shall shorten our account of it if we begin by recapitulating our previous remarks. We said that happiness is not a moral state ; for, if it were, it would be predicable of one who spends his whole life in sleep, living the life of a vegetable, or of one who is utterly miserable. If then we cannot accept this view if we must rather define . Happiness happiucss as an activity of some kind, as has been vity. said before, and if activities are either necessary p- 16. and desirable as a means to something else or desirable in themselves, it is clear that we must define happiness as belonging to the class of activities which are desirable in themselves, and not desirable as means to something else; for happiness has no want, it is self-sufiicient. Again, activities are desirable in themselves, if nothing is expected from them beyond the activity. This seems to be the case with virtuous actions, as the practice of what is noble and virtuous is a thing desirable in itself. It seems to be the case also with such amusements as are pleasant, we do not desire them as means to other things; for they often do us harm rather than good by making us careless about our persons and our property. Such pastimes are CHAP. VI.] OF ARISTOTLE. 333 generally the resources of those whom the world calls happy. Accordingly people who are clever at such pastimes are generally popular in the courts of despots, as they make themselves pleasant to the despot in the matters which are the objects of his desire, and what he wants is to pass the time pleasantly. The reason why these things are regarded as elements of happiness is that people who occupy high positions devote their leisure to them. But such people are not, I think, a criterion. For a high position is no guarantee of virtue or intellect, which are the sources on which virtuous activities depend. And if these people, who have never tasted a pure and liberal pleasure, have recourse to the pleasures of the body, it must not be inferred that these pleasures are preferable; for even children suppose that such things as are valued or honoured among them are best. It is only reasonable then that, as meu and children differ in their estimate of what is honourable, so should good and bad people. As has been frequently said, therefore, it is the things which are honourable and pleasant to the virtuous man that are really honourable and pleasant. But everybody feels the activity which accords with his own moral state to be most desirable, and accord- ingly* the virtuous man regards the activity in accordance with virtue as most desirable. Happiness then does not consist in amusement. It would be paradoxical to hold that the end of ' Reading 817. 334 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [BOOK X. human life is amusement, and that we should toil and suffer all our life for the sake of amusing ourselves. For we may be said to desire all things as means to something else except indeed happiness, as happiness is the end or perfect state. It appears to be foolish and utterly childish to take serious trouble and pains for the sake of amusement. But to amuse oneself with a view to being serious seems to be right, as Anacharsis says; for amusement is a kind of relaxation, and it is because we cannot work for ever that we need relaxation. Beiaxation. Relaxation then is not an end. We enjoy it as a means to activity ; but it seems that the happy life is a Ufe of virtue, and such a life is serious, it is not one of mere amusement. We speak of serious' things too (for serious things are virtuous) as better than things which are ridiculous and amusing, and of the activity of the better part of man's being or of the better man as always the more virtuous. But the activity of that which is better is necessarily higher and happier. Anybody can enjoy bodily plea- sures, a slave can enjoy them as much as the best of men ; but nobody would allow that a slave is capable of happiness unless he is capable of hfe" ; for happi- ness consists not in such pastimes as I have been speaking of, but in virtuous activities, as has been already said. 1 The argument depends upon the connexion between o-TrouSi; "seriousness" and airovSaios, which here hovers in meaning be- tween "serious" and ''virtuous." " i.e. the life of a free Athenian citizen. CHAP. VII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 335 If happiness consists in virtuous activity, it is only Chap. vn. reasonable to suppose that it is the activity of the ^Xtolis highest virtue, or in other words, of the best part of activity. our nature. Whether it is the reason or something else which seems to exercise rule and authority by a natural right, and to have a conception of things noble and divine, either as being itself divine or as relatively the most divine part of our being, it is the activity of this part in accordance with its proper virtue which will be the perfect happiness. It has been already stated ^ that it is a speculative Happiness activity, i.e. an activity which takes the form of tiveaeti- contemplation. This is a conclusion which would ^'*^' seem to agree with our previous arguments and with the truth itself; for the speculative is the highest activity, as the intuitive reason is the highest of our faculties, and the objects with which the intuitive reason is concerned are the highest of things that can be known. It is also the most continuous; for our speculation can more easily be continuous than any kind of action. We consider too that pleasure is an essential element of happiness, and it is admitted that there is no virtuous activity so pleasant as the activity of wisdom or philosophic reflexion; at all events it appeairs that philosophy possesses pleasures of wonderful purity and certainty, and it is reasonable to suppose that people who possess knowledge pass 1 The reference is not clear; Sir A. Grant suggests, p. 21, IL 16 — 18; but the general drift of Aristotle's argument in Book VI. has tended to show the speculative or intellectual nature of happiness. 336 THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS LBOOK X. their time more pleasantly than people who are seekers after truth. Self-sufficiency too, as it is called, is preeminently a characteristic of the speculative activity ; for the wise man, the just man, and all others, need the necessaries of life; but when they are adequately provided with these things, the just man needs people to whom and with whom he may do justice, so do the temperate man, the courageous man and everyone else ; but the wise man is capable of specU' lation by himself, and the wiser he is, the more capable he is of such speculation. It is perhaps better for him in his speculation to have fellow- workers ; but nevertheless he is in the highest degree self-sufficient. It would seem too that the speculative is the only activity which is loved for its own sake as it has no result except speculation, whereas from all moral actions we gain something more or less besides the action itself. Happiness Again, happincss, it seems, requires leisure; for ' the object of our business is leisure, as the object of war is the enjoyment of peace. Now the activity of the practical virtues is displayed in politics or war, and actions of this sort seem incompatible with leisure. This is absolutely true of military actions, as nobody desires war, or prepares to go to war, for its own sake. A person would be regarded as absolutely bloodthirsty if he were to make enemies of his friends for the mere sake of fighting and bloodshed. But the activity of the statesman too is incompatible with leisure. It aims at securing some- CHAP. VII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 337 thing beyond and apart from politics, viz. the power and honour or at least the happiness of the statesman himself and his fellow citizens, which is diflFerent irom the political activity and is proved to be diflFerent by our search for it as something distinct. If then political and military actions are pre- eminent among virtuous actions in beauty and grandeur, if they are incompatible with leisure and aim at some end, and are not desired for their own sakes, if the activity of the intuitive reason seems to be superior in seriousness as being speculative, and not to aim at any end beyond itself, and to have its proper pleasure, and if this pleasure enhances the activity, it follows that such self-sufficiency and power of leisure and absence of fatigue as are possible to a man and all the other attributes of felicity are found to be realized in this activity. This then will be the perfect happiness of Man, if a perfect length of life is given it, for there is no imperfection in* happiness. But such a life will be too good for Man. He will enjoy such a life not in virtue of his humanity but in virtue of some divine element within him, and the superiority of this activity to the activity of any other virtue will be proportionate to the superiority of this divine element in man to his composite or material nature. If then the reason is divine in comparison -with Happiness the rest of Man's nature, the life which accords with tive reason. reason will be divine in comparison with human life in general Nor is it right to follow the advice of people who say that the thoughts of men should not be too high for humanity or the thoughts of mortals w. N. E. 22 338 THE, NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK X. too high for mortality; for a man, as far as in him lies, should seek immortality and do all that is in his power to live in accordance mth the highest part of his nature, as, although that part is insignificant in size, yet in power and honour it is far superior to all the rest. It would seem too that this is the true self of everyone, if a man's true self is his supreme or better part. It would be absurd then that a man should desire not the life which is properly his own but the life which properly belongs to some other being. The remark already made will be appropriate here. It is what is proper to everyone that is in its nature best and pleasantes.t for him. It is the life which accords with reason then that wiU be best and pjtg,santest for Man, as a man's reason is in the highest sense himself. This will therefore be also the happiest life. CHAp.vm. It is only in a secondary sense that the life which fi^f^nd accords with other, i.e. nonrspeeutative, virtue can be non-apecn- ga,i(j iq \)q happy ; for the activities of such virtue are lative vir- ^^•' ' , . . , --. . tue. human, they have no dwvne element. Our just or courageous actions or our virtuous actions of any kind we perfoi-m in relation to one another, when we observe the law of propriety in contracts and mutual services and the various moral actions and in our emotions. But all these actions appear to be human affairs. It seems too that moral virtue is in some respects actually the result of physical organization and is in many respects closely associated with the emotions. Again, prudence is indissolubly linked to moral virtue, and moral virtue to prudence, since the CHAP. VIII.] OF ARISTOTLE. 339 principles of prudence are determined by the moral virtues, and moral rectitude is determined by pru- dence. But the moral virtues, as being inseparably united with the emotions, must have to do with the composite or material part of our natwre, and the virtues of the composite part of our nature are human, and not divine, virtues. So too therefore is the life which accords with these virtues ; so too is the happiness which aceords with them. But the happiness which consists in the exer- cise of the reason is separated from these emotions. It must be enough to say so much about it; for to discuss it in detail would take us beyond our present purpose. It would seem too to require external resources only to a small extent or to a less extent than moral virtue. It may be granted that both will require the necessaries Homer's description of the Cyclopean life (to which Aris- totle frequently refers) is found in the Odyssey ix. 114, 115. CHAP. X.J OF ARISTOTLE. 347 of a number of people is apparently a matter of indifference, aa it is in music or gymnastic or other studies. For as in a state it is law and custom which are supreme, so in a household it is the paternal precepts and customs, and all the more because of the father's relationship to the members of his family, and of the benefits which he has conferred upon them; for the members of a family are naturally affectionate and obedient to the father from the first. . Again, there is a superiority in the individual as inOivid- against the general methods of education; it is much the education. same as in medicine where, although it is the general rule that a feverish patient needs to be kept quiet and to take no food, there may perhaps be some exceptions. Nor does a teacher of boxing teach all his pupils to box in the same style. It would seem then that a study of individual character is the best way of perfecting the education [/^ of the individual, as then everyone has a better chance of receiving such treatment as is suitable. Still the individual case may best be treated, whether in medicine or in gymnastic or in any other subject, by one who knows the general rule applicable to all people or to people of a particular kind; for the sciences are said to deal, and do deal, with general laws. At the same time there is no reason why even without scientific knowledge a person should not be successful in treating a particular case if he has made an accurate, although empirical, observation of the results which follow from a particular course of treatment, as there are some doctors who seem to be excellent doctors in their own cases, although they would be unable to reUeve anybody else. MB THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS [bOOK X. Need of Nevertheless if a person wishes to succeed in art ofk^^ia- or speculation, it is, I think, his duty to proceed to a Hon. universal principle and to make himself acquainted with it as far as possible; for sciences, as has been said, deal with universals. Also it is the duty of any one who wishes to elevate people, whether they be few or many, by his treatment, to try to learn the principles of legislation, if it is laws that are the natural means of making us good. So in education it is not everybody — it is at the most only the man of science — who can create a noble disposition in all who come to him as patients, as it is in medicine or in any other art which demands care and prudence. Is it not then our next step to consider the sources and means of learning the principles of legislation? It may be thought that here as else- where we must look to the persons v;ho practise the principles, i.e. to statesmen; for legislation, as we p. 346. saw, is apparently a branch of pohtics. But there is this difference between politics and all other sciences and faculties. In these it is the same people who are found to teach the faculties and to make practical use of them, e.g. doctors and painters ; whereas in Sophists, pohtics it is the sophists who profess to teach, but it is never they who practise. The practical people are the active statesmen who would seem to be guided in practical life by a kind of faculty or experience rather than by intelUgence; for we see that they never write or speak on these subjects, although it is perhaps a nobler task than the composition of forensic or parhamentary speeches, nor have they ever made their own sons or any other people whom they care for into statesmen. Yet it might be expected that CHAP. X.] OP ARISTOTLE. 349 they should do so, if it were in their power, for they could not have bequeathed any better legacy to their state, nor is there anything which they would have preferred for themselves or their dearest iriends to such a faculty. Still it must be admitted that experience does much good; otherwise people could not be made statesmen by familiarity with politics. It follows that, if people desire to understand politics, they need experience as well as theory. These sophists however who are lavish in their professions appear to be far from teaching statesman- ship; in fact they are absolutely ignorant of the sphere or nature of statesmanship. If it were not so they would not have made statesmanship identical with, or inferior to, rhetoric; they would not have thought it easy work to form a legislative code by merely collecting such laws as are held in high repute ; they would not have supposed that all they have to do is to make a selection of the best laws, as if the selection itself did not demand intelligence, and as if a right judgment were not a thing of the greatest difficulty in legislation no less than in music. For it is only such persons as possess experience of particular arts who can form a correct judgment of artistic works, and understand the means and manner of executing them, and the harmony of particular combinations. Inexperienced persons on the other hand are only too glad if they are alive to the fact that a work has been well or badly executed, as in painting. But laws are like the artistic works of political science. How then should a mere collection of laws make a person capable of legislating, or of deciding upon the best laws? It does not appear 350 mCOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [BK, X. that the study of medical books makes people good doctors; yet medical books affect not only to state methods of treatment, but to state the way of curing people, and the proper method of treating particular cases by classifying the various states of health. But all this, although it seems useful to the experienced, is useless to those who are ignorant of medical science. It may be supposed then that collections of laws and polities would be useful to those who are capable of considering and deciding what is right or wrong, and what is suitable to particular cases ; but if people who examine such questions have not the proper frame of mind, they wiU find it impossible to form a right judgment unless indeed by accident, although they may gain a more intelligent apprecia- tion of them. As previous writers have failed to investigate the subject of legislation, it will perhaps be better to examine it ourselves, and indeed to examine the whole subject of polities', in order that the philosophy of human life may be made as complete as possible. Let us try then, first of all, to recount such particular opinions as have been rightly expressed by our predecessors, then, in view of the polities which we have collected, to consider the preservatives and destructives of states and of particular polities, and the reasons why some polities are good and others bad. For when we have considered these, it will perhaps be easier to see what kind of polity is best, and what is the best way of ordering it and what are its laws and customs. > Aristotle thus paves the way for his Politics, a treatise published later than the NicomacJiean Ethics. INDEX. ^schylas 63 Agamenmoa 84 (note), 269 Agathon 180, 183 AlcmsBon 60, 165 (note) AmpMpolis 159 Anacharsis 334 Anaxagoras 188, 342 Anaxandrides 233 Aphrodite 222 Argives 88 Athenians 117 Bias 138 Boeotians 85 (note) Brasidas 159 Ccilypso 56 Garcinas 226 Celts 81 Cercyon 226 Coionean citizens 85 (note) Crete 30 Croesus 23 (note) Cydops 346 Delos 20 Demodicus 228 Diomedes 83, 167, 246 (note) Elensioian mysteries 63 (note) Empedocles 213, 215, 247 Endymion 341 Epidiarmus 297 Erii*yle 60 (note), 165 (note) Eteocles 295 Endoxus 29, 316 Euripides 60, 165, 190, 244, 247, 295, 303 Enripns 296 Eventis 234 Glauous 167 Graces 150 Hector 83, 84, 204 Helen 56, 57 HeracHtus 40, 211, 247, 330 Hermes 85 Herodotus 23 (note), 342 (note) Hesiod 6, 150, 240, 247 (note), 288, 308 Homer 56, 71, 83, 84, 86, 92, 107, 167, 186, 204, 223, 246, 268, 269, 846 IliiiinlSO Eing-Archon 267 (note) Lacedffimon 30, 346 LacedsBmonians 88, 117, 129, 205 Lesbian architecture 172 Megarians 111 • Merope 63 Milesians 228 MUo45 Neoptolemus 208, 231 Niobe 218 Odysseus 56 (note), 208, 231 Olympian games 19, 216 Pericles 184 Persia 160, 268 352 INDEX. Phalaris 219, 221 Phidias 186 PhUootetes 208 (note), 226 Phooylides 137 (note) Pittacus 74 (note), 295 Plato 5, 6, 9, 25 (note), 39, 205 (note), 317, 319 Polyclitus 186 Polydamas 83 Polynioes 295 Priam 23, 26, 204 Protagoras 283 Pythagoreans 10, 47, 150, 306 (note) Bhadamanthus 150 Sardanapalus 7 Satyrus 218 Scythians 68 Sicyonians 88 Simonides 25 (note), 103 Socrates 84, 129, 201, 202, 206, 215 Solon 23, 342 Sophocles 208, 231, 312 Speusippus 10, 238 Thales 188 Thebana 117 (note) Theodeotes 226 Theognis 137 (note), 306, 314, 343 Thetis 117 Trojans 83 Tydides 83 Xenophantus 226 Zeus 117, 268, 286 CAWBRTDGE : PBINTEB BT <3. Jr. d. — ON THE CONSTITUTION OF ATHENS. Translated by E. Poste, M.A., Fellow of Oriel CoUege, Oxford, Second Edition. Cr. 8vo. 3J. id. CICERO— SELECT LETTERS. Translated from Watson's Edition. By G. E. Jeans, M.A. ioj. dd. — A CADEMICS. By J. S. Reid, M.L., LittD. 8vo. 5^. td. HERODOTUS. By G. C. Macaulay, M.A. THE HISTORY. 2 vols. Cr. 8vo. iSj. HOMER— ODYSSEY. By Prof. S. H. Butcher, M.A., and A. Lang, M.A. ds. — ILIAD. By A. Lang, M.A., W. Leaf, Litt.D., and E. Myers, M.A. ^^s. 6d. — THE ODYSSEY, BOOKS I— XII, By the Earl OF Carnarvon. 8s. 6d. HORA CE. By J. Lonsdale, M.A., and S. Lee, M.A. is. 6d. JUVENAL— THIRTEEN SATIRES. By A. Leeper, M.A. Crown 8vo. 3J. 6d. LIVY— BOOKS XXI— XXV. By A. J. Church, and W. J. Brodribb. 7J-. 6d. PINDAR— ODES. By Ernest Myers, M.A. Second Edition. 5^. PLATO— REPUBLIC. By J. L. Davies, M.A., and D. J. Vaughan, M.A. IS. 6d. net. — EUTHYPHRO, APOLOGY, CRITO, AND PHMDO. By F. J. Church, is. 6d. net. — PH^DRUS, LYSIS, AND PROTAGORAS. By J. Wright, M.A. 4^. 6d. POLYBIUS—THE HISTORIES. By E. S. Shuck- burgh, M.A. 2 vols. 21s. SALLUST— CATILINE AND JUGURTHA. By A. W. Pollard, B. A. 6j. C^77Z/A'2 separately, 3J. TA CITUS. By A. J. Church, M.A. and W. J. Brodribb, M.A. HISTORY, 6s. ANNALS, Is. 6d. AGRICOLA AND GERMANIA, 4J. 6rf. THEOCRITUS, MOSCHUS, AND BION. By A. Lang, New Edit. i8mo. 4J. dd. VIRGIL— yENEID. By J. W. Mackail, M.A. ^s. dd. XENOPHON By H. G. Dakyns, M. A. 4 vols. Cr. Bvo. Vol. I. lar. 6rf. MACMILLAN AND CO., LONDON. l K