‘sivarcity of Virginia Library TY OF VIRGINIA LIBRARY 31760BE eI CT ES AE aE Bape ns0 My cs Es : PERS PPL ISRL PSEC PIT ROIS PP ap aap ee ps T by aL whSTUDENTS’ CABINET LIBRARY OF USEFUL TRACTS. VOL. IX. EDINBURGH: THOMAS CLARK, 38. GEORGE STREET. LONDON—HAMILTON, ADAMS & CO. ; DUBLIN—CURRY & CO. MDCCCXLIII.CONTENTS OF VOL. IX. N. B.— Tike figures on the right-hand margin refer to the paging at the bottom. I; Cousins Philosopuical Bssayé,. .° 6. 5 (Being No. XXXII. of Students’ Cabinet Library of Useful Tracts.) Il. Cousin’s Exposition of Eclecticism, . . . . (Being No. XX XIII. of Students’ Cabinet Library of Useful Tracts.) III. Murpocx’s Sketches of Modern Philosophy, especially among the Germans, . ... . (Being No. XLIII. of Students’ Cabinet Library of Useful Tracts.) Page. 1-62 —198 ao 6 199—323PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAY 8; BY M. VICTOR COUSIN, PEER OF FRANCE, MEMBER OF THE INSTITUTE, AND OF THE COUNCII OF PUBLIC INSTRUCTION, AND DIRECTOR OF THE NORMAL SCHOOLS. TRANSLATED FROM THE FRENCH, WITH INTRODUCTORY AND CRITICAL NOTICES, GEORGE RIPLEY. EDINBURGH: THOMAS CLARK, 38. GEORGE STREET; LONDON—HAMILTON, ADAMS c& COs DUBLIN—CURRY & CO. MDCCCKXXIX.«¢ Non ambitione, non QiAoverxic, non semulatione, non ut sererem rixas, hee et institui et collegi, sed primum ut me ipsum erudirem, deinde ut aliquorum, qui hec legebant, honesta et pia studia adjuvarem.” MELANCHTHON, Pref. in loc. Theol. ais J. THOMSON, PRINTER, MILNE SQUARE-CONTENTS. Page BIOGRAPHICAL AND INTRODUCTORY NOTICE ° 5 ON THE DESTINY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY : ov NOTES. Note A.—Schelling’s Opinion of Cousin Nore B.—President Hopkins on Natural Theology 61Se ere i hake Ni Bi be hel Rett | rt E < pS t 5 Be sz i i ie es 2 2 S EMH seBIOGRAPHICAL INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. Victor Cousin was born at Paris, the 28th of No- vember, 1792. His parents, who were not in weal- thy circumstances, placed him for his early educa- tion, at the humble schools of his native city. He soon gave such indications of a love of learning, that they were induced, by the advice of his teachers, to allow him the advantage of a liberal education. The first public seminary which he entered was the Lycée Charlemagne of Paris, where he at once took the precedence of his fellow students, and gained the high rank in the classes which he never afterwards lost. He was every year honoured with numerous prizes, particularly with that for distinction in rheto- ric, a department in which he has since exhibited such eminent ability. He was indebted for his suc- cess, not only to his uncommon mental endowments, but to the unwearied industry which had become a habit with him at this earlyage. At that time, when the Empire enlisted in its service every variety of talent, and kindled a glowing ambition in all classes of society, different careers were every where open- ed to the most distinguished pupil of the Colleges of Paris. He was entitled, on account of having re- ceived the highest honours, to be exempt from con- scription, and to enter the Council of State as audi- tor with an annual grant of 5000 francs. But the NO. XXXII. B o eer yO Fk OGTR ST NPY Teeny area errr srr ar yecnos ‘tak. echacandiableg NRG se scarab regina eqempeemebnty peer ns ar ae ee Te as Wrenn ron6 BIOGRAPHICAL AND enthusiastic love of study was sfronger than any other consideration; and M. Gueroult, the celebrat- ed translator of Pliny, honorary counsellor of the University, commissioned by M. de Fontannes to organize the Normal School, decided the young student, whom he had known and patronized in his previous career, to engage in the profession o1 public instruction. His name was, accordingly, inscribed the first on the list of the pupils admitted into the Normal School, at its commencement. M. Cousin was eighteen years of age, when he first entered the Normal School in 1810, whieh he never afterwards quitted ; and of which he became the Principal, sub- sequent to the Revolution of 1830. After having remained in it for two years as a pupil, he was ap- pointed an instructer in the department of Litera- ture, at the close of 1812, and in 1814, was made Master of the Conferences, in the place. of M. Ville- main. At the same time, he was employed as assis- tant teacher in the different Lyceums of Paris. In 1815, he was entrusted, during the Hundred Days, with the class in philosophy at the Collége Bourbon. In this manner, M. Cousin passed through the suc- cessive functions of secondary instruction. He had not yet however discovered his true sphere. He has himself described in the preface to his Philosophical Fragments, the impression which he received, upon his entering the Normal School, from the Course of M. Laromiguiére, and a short time afterwards, from that of M. Royer-Collard. After hearing those celebrated professors, his heart was irrevocably given to philosophy. But his pa- tron, M. Gueroult, Principal of the Normal School, entertained different views with regard to him; and after many useless struggles, M. Cousin found him- self condemned, even by his very success, to the teaching of Literature. He did not lose his attach- ment, however, to his favourite science; and all his wishes were at last fulfilled, when towards the close of 1815, he was appointed by M. Royer-Collard, who 6 eee tyes Tak Ms ep. Se INTRODUCTORY NOTICE, < had been placed by the new government at the head of the University, to succeed him as Professor of Philosophy in the Faculty of Literature. From that time, M. Cousin devoted himself entire- ly to‘philosophy, at the University and at the Nor- mal School. For five years he sustained the burden of this double teaching. His Course at the Univer- sity gave a lively impulse to the public mind, and produced a more general taste for philosophical studies; while his teachings at the Normal School were adapted to call forth and cultivate those young men who have since so ably seconded his labours. ‘“‘ M. Cousin,” says Damiron,! « possessed a very simple, but very powerful means of success in his Lectures. This was the eloquence with which he was inspired by his thought. His manner of being taken possession of by his ideas; his facility in re- presenting metaphysical abstractions in graphic sketches; the lively bursts of his mind; the bold expressions of consciousness, which made up those improvisations, at once so animated and so serious, so graceful and so imposing,—all conspired to im- press and captivate his numerous auditory. As he was not merely a simple demonstrator, a cold and unimpassioned witness, but an earnest observer and an enthusiastic teacher, a philosopher and an orator at once, both in his chair and out of it, at the Normal School and in the familiar conversations which he was always ready to engage in with his young friends, he announced the truths of philosophy, with that glow of feeling, that profound earnestness, that ele- vation of thought, which moved and carried away every mind. His Lectures contained something beside doctrine. They displayed the labour by yeas it was prepared, the method which led to it, the love and the zeal with which it was investigated ; these passed from his soul to that of bien: a spired them with the very spirit of his philosophy. 1 Histoire de la Philosophie en France. kaa pee n Sek . + PUES ay eerie ee a a] y 7 a Paha hr aa A eee enh’ er Saal ey Lm) b yon) " Ml A . rs f + . eed Load : PH AE WC ICS NSS a Pye ediyth RS wh. de RET WEN mage rer hae rn) Seen arBIOGRAPHICAL AND Of his labours at the Normal School, M. Cousit has given an interesting account in the Appendix to his volume of Philosophical Fragments. He refers to the period from 1815 to 1820, during whieh, as he says, “in profound obscurity, master and pupils, equally feeble, but full of zeal, we were uninterrupt- edly employed in the reform of philosophical studies. The course of instruction at the Normal School in- cluded three years, after which the pupils were sent into the provinces to take possession of the vacant Chairs. As Master of the Philosophical Conferen- ces of the third year, it was my office to prepare them for the important duties on which they were about to enter. All the pupils of the third year at- tended my course; but it was particularly intended for the small number of them, who were destined to a philosophical career. They bore the weight of the labours of the Conference ; and were the principal source of the interest which was taken in those labours. They were present also at my Lectures in the Faculty of Literature, where they might have the opportunity of obtaining more general ideas, and breathing in a more vigorous life in an atmosphere of greater pub- licity. Within the interior of the school, the teach- ing was more didactic and rigid; the Course bore the name of Conferences, and deservedly so; for every Lecture occasioned a discussion in which all the pupils participated. Formed to the philosophical method, they made use of it with the professor as well as with themselves; they presented their doubts, their objections, their arguments, with perfect free- dom; and were thus exercised in that spirit of in- dependence and of criticism, which I trust, will one day bear its fruits. A truly fraternal confidence united the professor and pupils; if the pupils took the liberty to discuss the instructions which they re- ceived, the professor also felt authorised by reason of his duty, his intentions, and his friendship, to be eee At this day, we all love to recal that period, SE Waa ch ha tie ae Sh hr heSoc Sp Sg Va Puy St INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. a so cherished in our memory, when ignorant of the world and unknown by it, buried in the study of the eternal problems of the human mind, we passed our life in attempting those solutions of them, which, though they have since been modified, continue to interest us, on account of the labour which they cost us, and the sincere, earnest, and persevering research- es of which they were the result. It was under this austere discipline, but at the same time free from every narrow, mechanical restraint, that we were all formed ; and, in truth, if I do not deceive myself, many of my friends owe me some favour for my se- verity at that time, for having so often made them recommence their imperfect compositions, for having required more precision in the details and a closer connexion in the whole performance; and, above all, for having endeavoured to inculcate upon them so earnestly the spirit of philosophical method,—that psychological sense, that art of inward observation, without which man remains unknown to man, and philosophy is nothing but an assemblage of lifeless conceptions, of arbitrary formulas, more or less in- genious, bold, comprehensive, but always destitute of reality. For myself, I confess, that the exacting zeal of the Conference has often been of use to me; and I feel a pleasure in recording here the expression of my regret for that epoch, so tranquil and so studious, of my life.” In 1817 and 1818, M. Cousin employed his vaca- tions in travelling in Germany, with a view to in- creasing his acquaintance with the German philo- sophy. His intercourse with the most distinguished philosophers of that country is described in the Pre- face, which will form a subsequent number of this volume. In 1820, he made a voyage to the north of Italy, for the purpose of comparing the manuscripts in the public libraries, with reference to his contemplated edition of the unpublished works of Proclus. But on his return, he found a great change in the ete LA wh elk hoe i ne me Oe ae yeti * c a ON ra an Nree ee pee TT ear ris Les piba a er a eee 10 BIOGRAPHICAL AND of affairs in France. M. Royer-Collard was no longer at the head of the University. He had been dismissed from the Council of State, together with M. Guizot; and both the government and public instruction were subjected to a retrograde influence. M. Cousin himself was suspected of liberal views in polities ; his Course at the University was suspend- ed; and he remained in disgrace for seven years. The Normal School was suppressed in 1822. Dur- ing this interval, M. Cousin, though deprived of all public employment, and destitute of fortune, did not abandon his philosophical mission. His writings, at this time, served to increase his own reputation and to advance the cause of philosophy. A singular incident took place in 1824, which added, im no small degree, to his previous well-earned popularity. While travelling in Germany with the eldest son of Marshal Lannes, the Duke of Monto- bello, he was arrested at Dresden, and conducted to Berlin, where he was detained in prison for several months. This affair, however, terminated to his honour and to the shame of his enemies. He dis- played through the whole process a firmness and moderation which gained for him the high esteem of the Prussian government, and indeed of all the en- lightened men of Germany. It was demonstrated that M. Cousin was entirely innocent of all the plots which he had been accused of forming against the German governments, and that the whole secret was to be found in the policy of the Jesuits, who wished, by means of Germany, to be revenged upon him, tor his conduct in Frarice. In fact, although a phi- losopher, or rather because he was a philosopher, the pupil and friend of M. Royer-Collard could not remain a stranger to the affairs of his country ; and, at all times, he had exhibited the most liberal prin- ciples, and regulated his conduct in accordance with those principles. Thus, in 1822, having accidentally become acquainted at Paris with the Count de Santa- Rosa, who had taken such an honourable part in the G Feo ag aba aE SaiINTRODUCTORY NOTICE. il Piedmontese revolution of 1820, struck with the noble character of the unfortunate Italian, he formed an intimate and fraternal friendship with him. When without the slightest pretext, Santa-Rosa was arrest- ed and thrown into prison, M. Cousin did not hesi- tate to offer himself as security for his friend; and after the perfect innocence of Santa-Rosa had been proved by inquiry, and, as he could not be con- demned, he was banished to Alencon, M. Cousin went as his companion. It was for crimes like these that M. Cousin became odious to the Jesuits. As they dared not accuse him at Paris, they persecuted him in Germany. They only gave him the occa- sion, however, of gaining new titles to the esteem of every honourable man. M. Cousin displayed the utmost energy of character while a prisoner; and no less mildness after his restoration to liberty. Satisfied with the marks of respect which were given to him by the Prussian government, he forgot all feelings of resentment in the midst of the old friends whom he found at Berlin, and among others Schleier- macher and Hegel. Upon his return to France in 1825, he was not permitted to resume his Lectures. It was not until after the elections of 1827, when M. Royer-Collard was re-established in the Presidency of the Univer- sity, that he received a new appointment as Professor in the Faculty-of Literature. He resumed his course in 1828, with a brilliant success, such as has been rarely known in the history of philosophical instrue- tion. At the same time, his Lectures were distin- guished by the greatest moderation in philosophy, in religion, in politics, in every thing. At the Revolution of 1880, with the high reputa- tion of M. Cousin, his singular talents as an orator, his practical energy, and the popularity which een gained during the three celebrated days, he ou easily have entered into the Chamber of Deputies, ; ‘rs Wi is two col- and taken part in public affairs, with his two - ea ‘Tih nok yf" ‘ ENV REN CK ZR peas ee WERT Ta Ye YreeaUen ne tor er Lt eae LTS NEO Se te TCL eee nayeee rt DO tas ee NRIES Sho oes eye ert ee OE are ee pe re aE y aI ay Oe PEE ae i aa a al a Rape ae oP ALS aN aor ant ak 12 BIOGRAPHICAL AND leagues, M. Guizot and M. Villemain, and his friend M. Thiers. But M. Cousin declared that he would remain faithful to philosophy. <¢ Politics,” said he at that time, ‘‘are an episode with me; but the foun- dation of my life belongs to philosophy.” The only change, which he was willing to accept, was the pass- ing, according to the most rigid forms of University advancement, from the Faculty of Literature to the Royal Council of Public Instruction, and the princi- pal direction of the Normal School, which he re-esta- blished and organized. To give place to one of his most able pupils, M. Jouffroy, he exchanged the Chair of the History of Modern Philosophy, for that of the History of Ancient Philosophy. He refused to accept any political function, confined himself entirely to the University, and devoted his well- known activity, to the continuation of his philosophi- cal writings, which had been interrupted by his Lectures. From 1830 to 1835 he published a great number of works ; four new volumes of the transla- tion of Plato; a new edition of the Fragments, with the Preface already alluded to; an edition of the posthumous works of M. Maine de Biran, with a Pre- face, which is itself a treatise of philosophy; and finally, a labour of considerable magnitude on the Metaphysics of Aristotle; to Say nothing of nume- rous special memoirs and dissertations. He is now occupied with extensive researches on the Scholastic philosophy, and has just published the unprinted manuscripts of Abelard. The merits of M. Cousin, as an historian of philo- sophy, are admitted by all to be of the highest order. His labours embrace almost all of the great epochs in the history of philosophy. 1. For antiquity, a Trans- lation of Plate with Critical 7 fotes and Lntroductions, of which nine volumes have been already given tothe publics the Metaphysics of Aristotle ; six volumes of Alexandrine Commentaries 3; a volume entitled New Fragments, treating of the most difficult points of 12INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. 13 ancient philosophy. 2. For the Scholastic philo- sophy, a large quarto on Abelard. 38. For modern philosophy, a complete edition of Descartes and a multitude of special dissertations. 4. Finally, for the general history of philosophy, several volumes, comprising the most original and fruitful views, and at their side, the translation of the valuable Manual of Tennemann. The efforts of M. Cousin for the improvement of publie instruction have gained him no less honour and far more popularity than his philosophical career. ‘“‘ The edneation of the people and the progress of philosophy,’ says M. Cousin in a letter to an Ameri- can correspondent, “ are to: decide the future condi- tion both of your country and mine. These are the holy interests to which I would devote my life; and for which I rejoice to see so many good and useful exertions in a country called to such a high destiny as the United States.” The services of M. Cousin, to the cause of popular education are generally well known among us, and have awakened a deep interest in his name with many who are comparatively strangers to his philosophy. It is gratifying to per- ceive that the two great objects, which should never be separated—the instruction of the people and the advancement of philosophy—have found such an earnest advocate in the most popular philosophical writer of the day. M. Cousin is admirably qualified for the formation of an improved system of education, no less by his practical experience, than his native abilities. This subject, it is said, has too often occupied the atten- tion in France only of speculative men, like Rous- seau, who, unacquainted with the affairs of life, have proposed theories, without reference to existing facts, and which could not be realized without destroying the actual institutions ; or of men who were conver- sant only with practical details, and incapable of comprehending any general views. M. Cousin, ac- quainted at once with the schools and with ee a rare my mes is alate Ah he os CN a Pema hee ah ws. pan a? Re ag eects ost einen uw abe ae 14 BIOGRAPHICAL AND phy, combines all the elements which form an ac- complished teacher. As the historian and critic of the most important systems of philosophy, he could not remain the slave of ancient routine; and asa pupil and professor of the Imperial University he was not tempted to destroy the illustrious body, at whose bosom he had been nursed. Hence the course which he has pursued as one of the magistrates ap- pointed to preside over the interests of education. ft has been his endeavour to enlarge the frame-work of the University, without deforming it. From the commencement of his labours in the Council of Instruction, M. Cousin has been employ- ed with two principal objects, namely, the organiza- tion and direction of the Normal School, and the arrangement of philosophical studies, in the Colleges. He is the author of the present constitution of the Normal School, and of that admirable system of studies, which does the utmost honour to his practi- cal talents. Nor have his services been less valuable in the improvement of the teaching of philosophy in the Colleges of France. He has thus laid a broad foundation, which promises the happiest results for the growing advancement of philosophy in that coun- try, and consequently, in every country on which it exerts an influence. M. Cousin is no less interested in the schools for primary instruction. He has, in this way, acquired a new title to the gratitude of France. He is a true iriend of the people. He sprung from them. He wishes for their happiness. He delights to labour in their behalf. He is never weary in pleading their cause. He looks less, however, to chan s ment, than to their own elevation, for any permanent advantage. The regeneration of the people, he is persuaded, must come from within. He would have no pains spared to give them true light,—the light of morality no less than of knowledge 2 1 no ' e, of pure and virtuous principles as well as of scientific instruction. “« Primary instruction,” says M. Cousin, «is not to 14 ge of govern- Sah hae ae eas inte ene 7 re ae oP,INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. bDS be found in the Programme of the Hotel de Ville ; it is the genuine benefit which the Revolution of July should procure for France. The practical part of my life is devoted to the labour of procuring this instruction. Asa philosopher, I address myself to the é/ete of thinkers, to fifty individuals in Europe. in labouring for primary instruction, I labour for the masses of my countrymen.” In 1831, M. Cousin solicited of the French go- vernment, a special mission for examining the esta- blishments of public instruction in Germany. He received the appointment, and left Paris, May 24, 1831, for the discharge of its duties. He inspected all the public establishments of the city of Frankfort; of the Grand-Duchy of Weimar; of Saxony, and particularly of Leipsic; of Prussia, and particularly of Berlin; and was on his return to Paris about the middle of July, having sent his Reports to the minis- ter, dated at Frankfort, Weimar, Leipsic, and Berlin. These reports have been received with an almost universal interest in every civilized country of Eu- rope, and in the United States. M. Cousin has been elected a member of the French Academy,—an honour which was justly due to his eminent talents and extensive literary acqui- sitions. In 1832, he was made a Peer of France. He has recently been employed in examining the establishments for public instruction in Holland. The last work of his, which we have seen, is entitled De Vinstruction primaire a Rotterdam, Dec. 28, 1836. The philosophy of Vicror Cousin forms an im- portant epoch in the history of metaphysical science in France. It marks the period of transition from the sceptical and sensual theories of the eighteenth century, to the more elevated and spiritual views of the nature of man, which are the cheering result oi the philosophical investigations of the present a 5 pil mage emedivnieel + drpettbwes bet Py” es Ts — PE IT a es OL oy rg Oe Ne ee rae tenes eat ars 16 BIOGRAPHICAL AND The very name of French philosophy has been iden- tified, to a great extent, with materialism and infide- lity. The labours of Cousin have been directed, from the commencement of his career, not to clearing it from the accusation, but to placing it in a new path, and impressing it with a higher character. The de- sign of his teachings, in fact, has been to restore phi- Josophy to the eminence which it held in the golden days of English literature, and to revive the lofty spirit of Hooker, Cudworth, and Milton, in the midst of modern unbelief and selfishness. This has been the great problem of philosophical speculation since the appearance of the Critique of Pure Reason, by Immanuel Kant. That remarkable thinker clearly comprehended the magnitude of the work ; and though he did not complete it himself, he has furnished materials for future inquiry, the value and importance of which will always be more highly appreciated, in proportion as the soundness and depth of his thoughts are perceived through the obscurity of his language. His writings form an admirable pre- paration for a philosophy which reconciles the holiest instincts of man with the rigid precision of science ; which beats down the pretensions of scepticism by a skilful use of its own weapons; and which establishes the sublime convictions of the spiritual leaders of humanity on the basis of a thorough observation and analysis of facts. Among the promoters of this philosophical deve- lopment in France, Victor Cousin holds the most conspicuous place. The influence which he has eX- erted on the condition of thought in his own country is such as rarely falls to the lot of an individual; and the splendour of his intellectual endowments has won for him a distinguished reputation in almost every cultivated nation in Europe. The essential charac- teristics of his philosophy are opposition to all partial and exclusive theories, and the endeavour to compre- hend every element of human nature, in a broad and 16 ae, Pe tue we renee ee besINTRODUCTORY NOTICE. 17 universal system, which reposes on the foundation of actual inquiry and induction. The prevailing philosophy in France during the greater part of the eighteenth century was precisely the reverse of this. It was founded onan inadequate examination of the nature of man, and failed of doing justice to some of its most important elements. The results, at which it arrived in the regular course of logical deduction, were inconsistent with many ob- vious tendencies, many incontestable attributes of humanity. It placed itself in opposition to the uni- versal sentiments of our race. It attacked the foun- dation of the religious hopes and the moral convic- tions, which no force has ever been able to wrest from the great. mass of mankind. The history of the world, and the consciousness of individuals, were equally at war with the conclusions which it obtained, and the spirit which it breathed. Its doctrines produced a harsh dissonance with the whispers of that voice which is uttered, clearly though faintly, in the heart of every living man. Such a system could not gain a permanent footing, as the philosophy of an en- lightened and reflecting nation. It was doomed, sooner or later, to meet the fate of all error. It bore the seeds of corruption within itself, and, from its very nature, could not aveid coming to a more or less speedy end. It was inevitable that whenever the attention of free and original minds should be turned to the examination of this philosophy, its popularity should be unable to save it from destruc- tion. Its defective representations of human nature must be perceived, as soon as they were compared with the original reality ; the weakness of its foun- dation must be brought to light; and the authority which it had usurped over the minds of men must be called in question, and for ever set aside. Such is the character of the work in which Cousin has been called upon to engage. The errors of the dominant system had been long suspected,—a portion of its fallacies had been pointed out,—a new move- h7se iee seni bes ihanig Saas tpiitd CAM aE aaa ea SE Ra Oe Co or gee eee eo Le ae renee ean meaeee 18 BIOGRAPHICAL AND ment had been commenced in the opposite direction ; but a reformer was needed who should examine its pretensions to the bottom, exhibit the defects of the foundation on which it reposed, and invalidate its claims to universal reception, by the introduction of a purer and sounder philosophy. The appearance of Cousin as a public teacher was at the appropriate moment. Every thing was ready for his reception. He announced an order of ideas which met with a loud and sincere response. He raised the standard for which many eyes were looking, and around which a host of youthful disciples at once gathered with congenial enthusiasm and love. Cousin has felt the importance of his mission ; he comprehends the work which is demanded of him by his age; and has devoted himself to its accomplishment with a calm zeal, a wise and modest energy, such as nothing but strong convictions and disinterested purposes can inspire. The purity of sentiment which distinguishes his writings, the vigour and justness of his mtellect, the wealth of erudition which he brings to the illus- tration of truth, the clearness of his style, and the force of his eloquence, give him singular qualifications for the task with which he is occupied; and the brilliant success of his career, the glowing interest which he has excited in the abstractions of speculative philosophy, the dignity with which he has filled a wide and honourable sphere of action as well as of thought, display a beautiful example of fruitful intel- lectual effort, to which there are few parallels in modern times. In order to present a complete idea of the philo- sophical position and merits of Cousin, we must re- view the circumstances which led to his undertaking. A brief sketch of the history of opinion in France, prior to the new development of which he is at the head, will enable the reader to appreciate, with jus- tice, the character of his reform, and the tendency of his speculations. : Ws philosophy which prevailed in France during TE LP A ge LE ALOE LEG SE OL ONE EE LETTS GTO Ae EE LEERaa ad A ME PEE SRN TE Se Oe ee ETRE ee See Se oe Se eS ie Se Soe ot SSS a P ‘ey INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. 19 the eighteenth century has received the name of the Sensual system. ‘This name, it should be observed, is not given to it, in any invidious application, but as expressing with more precision than any other term, the exact idea which it is intended to convey. it is used not to denote its character or consequences, in a moral point of view, but to designate the prin- ciple which forms the basis of its theory, and with which it attempts to explain all the phenomena of human nature. The Sensual system, accordingly, admits the reality of no ideas but those which can be traced to sensation. It maintains that the mate- rials of our knowledge are all obtained from the im- pressions which are made on our senses by the ac- tion of external objects. The only legitimate cer- tainty is founded on the notices presented by the material organs; and as soon as we leave this sphere, we abandon the natural use of our faculties, and are lost in the regions of imagination and fiction. It is not difficult to account for the origin of this system, in the infancy of our scientiiie knowledge of the human mind. Like every system which has ex- tensively prevailed among sincere and _ intelligent seekers of truth, it is not altogether destitute of foundation in reality. It proceeds from the actual observation of incontestable facts; else it could never have met with such a general reception ; but it loses sight of another order of facts, no less im- portant, no less incontestable, no less capable of being submitted to observation; or it would never have been so earnestly and perseveringly called in question. If it can be shown that its establishment was the result of an hasty and imperfect analysis; of the error so common with incautious and impatient thinkers, in the ardour of discovery, of a precipitate generalization ; we shall not be surprised at the wide influence which it has obtained, and while we gain an insight into its narrow and superficial character, we may learn a lesson of philosophical toleration for its defenders and friends. : 1920 BIOGRAPHICAL AND The Sensual system is founded on a few simple principles, which, as Cousin has clearly demonstr at ed,! are of the utmost importance in the science ot human nature, so long as they are limited to their legitimate sphere, and are not perverted to the sup- port of bold and extravagant inductions. We find, upon a slight examination of conscious- ness, a certain number of phenomena which are dis- tinguished by the fact that they are altogether beyond our rcontroul. We can neither produce them, nor de- stroy them. They come and go, without our coope- ration, with no reference to our will. Such, for in- stance, are our emotions of every kind, our desires, our passions, our appetites, the feeling of pleasure and of pain. These phenomena are occasioned by an external impression which has been experienced, that is, by a sensation. ‘They are of unquestionable reality; they occupy an extensive sphere; they com- pose no small proportion of the motives of human action. It is true, moreover, that many of our most general ideas may be resolved, by a delicate analysis, into ideas that are less general; and that these, in their turn, by repeated decompositions, may be re- solved into ideas that proceed from sensation. Now these sensible phenomena are the first to attract the attention. They are submitted the most easily to observation. ‘They are found, not in the interior, but, as it were, on the surface of the soul. For this reason, they are the favourite subjects of reflection, in its early imperfect and feeble efforts. They afford it a useful exercise, and contribute to its growth ae improvement. The analysis which it undertakes, i not confined entirely to the phenomena of conscious- ness. It refers the sensation which it has received to the i impression made on the organ; and this im- pression again to external objects, w uch thus become the root of our sensations, and consequently of our * See Cours del’ Histoire de la Philosophie, par V. Cousin. Tom. I. p. 139. 20) NOS A he we tae Be, aa eee Dl be a yy ae ae A ata Pe OF i, oe ee Cr PP PPP Oy PT a oP Poe ole Pa oP or et er gly we eed yp gh — PoP PEP IL De BT aie a eaeh tk SE OE a a oh Ee ee INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. OT ideas. Hence the importance of the study of nature. Hence the desire and the ability to observe its phe- nomena and to ascertain its laws. The results which are obtained in this manner, enlarged and developed in the progress of ages, compose, together with phy- sical science, a certain science of humanity,—a phi- losophy, which is not without a portion of truth, of grandeur, and of utility. Now if this philosophy pretended only to explain a large number of the phenomena of consciousness on the principle of sensation, there would be no cause of objection to it. Such an explanation would be perfectly admissible. The conclusion would not go beyond the premises which have been furnished by a cantious induction ; and no error could be charg- ed upon the system. But the case, in fact, is very different from this. Reflection is obliged to divide the subject of its inquiries, and, for the sake of a more distinct view, to look at but one thing at a time. As it is feeble, when it commences its task, it is natural that it should stop with the part which it first studies, that it should regard this as the whole of reality, and that after having discovered an un- questionable order of facts, it should be so struck with their truth, their importance, their variety, their beauty, as to take notice of nothing else, and to be- lieve that they are the only phenomena contained in the consciousness. Reflection goes through with a process like the following. A certain number of our ideas are derived from sensation ; sensation accord- ingly explains and constitutes an important order of phenomena ; therefore, all our ideas are derived from sensation ; and there are no, phenomena in the con- sciousness which are not reducible to this source. Such is the foundation of the Sensual philosophy. The fundamental error of this system is no less obvious, than the manner in which it originated. it is essential to its truth, that there be no element in consciousness which cannot be explained by sensa- tion. But a slight analysis will show that this con NO. XXXII. S 21 Ae 5 ee anes Coad x + ta ay Age ee Eneet Ge 99 BIOGRAPHICAL AND dition does not hold. For instance, we find in con- sciousness certain acts of volition, free determina- tions. We know that we often resist passion and desire. But is it passion and desire which combat passion and desire? Is it sensation by which we overcome the force of sensation? If sensation be the only principle of all the phenomena of activity,— as it is the essential characteristic of sensation, and consequently of all the products of sensation, to be passive,—the free and voluntary activity is destroy- ed. The philosophy of sensation is thus reduced to Fatalism. Sensation, moreover, not only bears the stamp of necessity, but of variety. Our sensations, emotions, passions, desires, are constantly changing, assuming new forms, but this verpetual transtorma- tion does not include all the reality of which we are conscious. We believe, and cannot but believe, in our own personal identity, that we are the same to- day that we were yesterday, that we shall be the same to-morrow that we are to day. The identity, the unity of our being is in truth the principal fact of consciousness, or rather the very foundation of all consciousness. But how is identity to be obtained from variety ? How is the unity of our personal being to be derived from the multiplicity of sensible phenomena? This is clearly impossible. The phi- losophy of sensation has no means of arriving at the unity which combines, compares, and judges the variety of sensations. We have just seen that this philosophy destroys liberty. We now see that it destroys personality itself. It has just led us to Fa- talism; it now leads us to Materialism. Finally, as this system regards the soul of man as the result and the combination of our sensations, it is also compelled to regard the Deity only as the possibie result, the combination, the last generalization of all the pheno- mena of nature. God is a kind of soul of the world, which sustains the same relation to the world, as the soul that is admitted by the Sensual philosophy does to the body. The human soul, as it is regarded be ‘iy o anni i he ee pat ae taeEO ES A Rad etter te re Kes Sg eRe ee he INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. a5 by this philosophy, is an abstract, general, collective idea, which represents, in the last analysis, the diver- sity of our sensations. The Creator of the world, as he is regarded by this philosophy, is an abstraction of the same character, which may be successively de- composed into the different portions of the world which alone possesses reality, actual existence. But such a being is not the God of the human race. He is not a God distinct from the world. Now the ne- gation of a God distinct from the world has a well- known name in every language, as well as in philo- sophy. Such is the character of the system, considered in its elementary principles, against which the philoso- phy of Cousin is a declared revolt. The analyses that has been now given, abstract thought. The next step is to inquire into its historical development, with special reference to its position and consequences in the philosophy of France. I have only to follow in the path of Cousin, as I have hitherto done, to make this clear to every reader.! In the age of Bacon, the doctrines of a spiritual philosophy were generally prevalent, although mingled with singular exaggerations, and destitute of the sup- port of scientitic observation which they have since received irom the profound and accurate researches of modern times. It was a matter of course for the broad and comprehensive intellect of Bacon to per- ceive the absurdity of those subtile speculations which were connected with the bigher philosophy of his day; and to oppose to their airy texture, the substantial results of outward experience and observation. The tendency of his principles is to withdraw the attention from the contemplation of the mind, and to direct it exclusively to the study of the facts presented by ex~ ternal nature. He may accordingly be considered 1 S07 . . mF? ones mn. ‘ i {2 Cours de PV Histcire de la Philosophie. 'Tom. I. p. 443. “Zo 2 resents 1t as a process of ries 7 am Se er: re eet a | . niece) ace amepenaged! domcttbnee seeet tt eee ee SIRE PEPER PSM OCPRE RCE RISER ERA EEE PES DA BIOGRAPHICAL AND the father of the modern Sensual philosophy, although he was far from admitting its logical consequences, and occasionally advances principles which are in direct opposition to its procedure and results. The doctrines of Bacon, which regard experience as the sole foundation of our knowledge of reality, were adopted by the eminent English philosophers, Hobbes and Locke, and applied by them to the inves- tigation of human nature. The fundamental idea of Hobbes was the exclusive certainty of the senses. We can rely upon no testimony but that which they present. There is not a single idea in the mind ex- cepting those which we obtain through their medium. Every conviction which we cherish must be supported by their authority, or it rests on an insecure founda- tion. But the senses give us only the knowledge of material bodies. Therefore, only material bodies exist. Therefore, philosophy is only the science of material bodies. As all our ideas come from the senses ; all the phenomena of consciousness have their source in organization; and consciousness itself is only the result of organization. To think is to calcu- late; intelligence is nothing but arithmetic. Contin- gent ideas are all that exist ; the Finite alone can be conceived of by man; the Infinite is merely the ne- gation of the Finite; beyond this it is a mere word, ‘nvented to honour a being of whom we can know nothing. The idea of good and evil is founded on agreeable or disagreeable sensations; the only law of conduct is to pursue the one and to avoid the other ; hence the whole moral system of Hobbes. ‘This sys- tem is the foundation of his politics. Man is capa- ble of enjoyment and suffermg. His only law is to enjoy as much, and to suffer as little as possible; as he has no other law he has all the rights that are conferred by this law; he may do whatever he pleases for his preservation and happiness ; he is absolutely and completely selfish ; he has a right to sacrifice every thing to himself. Such is the condition in which we are placed on the earth. We are provided 242 be a ke Se Wea ad Teas a Tis ag Map hy ar tees as “ia ig ey ie NTRODUCTORY NOTICE. 2e with scanty means of enjoyment, to which all have a common right, by virtue of their capacity for enjoy- ment. This is the state of nature. It is always a state of war. It is disturbed by the anarchy of the passions, the combat of all with one another. But this state is contrary to the happiness of the majority of the individuals who compose it. Utility, the off- spring of selfishness, requires it to be changed into the social state. The social state is the institution of a public authority superior to the power of indivi- duals. But the passions of individuals constantly re- volt against this new authority. Hence this autho- rity cannot be too strong. Hence, again, the only alternative is between a complete anarchy and a despotism which is excellent in proportion as it is arbitrary. Hence, finally, in the opinion of Hobbes, absolute monarchy is the ideal of true government. According to his opinion, therefore, the Sensual philosophy is inconsistent with popular liberty. If Hobbes is the moralist and politician of this philosophy, Locke may be regarded as its metaphy- sician. He is the first who endeavoured to exhibit it in a regular and systematic form. The signal merits of this philosopher can never be forgotten by the lover of truth and independent inquiry. Neither should he be mentioned without the profound respect which is due to great abilities united with rare moral worth. But in judging of a system, we do not judge of a man. ‘The character of Locke is one before which we may bow in reverence. His doctrines are the proper object of critical examination and dis- . cussion. The peculiar excellence of the system of Locke consists in its distinct exhibition of the purpose oi philosophical investigation. This is to obtain a knowledge of the human mind, by the actual obser- vation of its laws, its operations, and its effects. This is the idea, at once simple and grand, which lies at the bottom of all his inquiries. This constitutes his best claim to originality ; and by this he has os fond & PRR re Tein my mers re eae cdBIOGRAPHICAL AND rendered an essential and lasting service to mental philosophy. But the greatest man is not exempt from inconsistency and error. While Locke opened the way which leads to true philosophy, he faltered in it himself; and was insensibly betrayed into the path of an exclusive and unfounded hypothesis. Locke institutes an inquiry with regard to the sources of human knowledge. He finds that these are two, namely, sensation and reflection ; reflection applied to the operations of the understanding, that is, in the last analysis, sensation and the operations of the understanding; for reflection applied to these operations is limited to informing us concerning their number and their character. These operations are comparison, reasoning, abstraction, composition, asso- ciation.—all of them faculties which separate or com- bine the elements that are derived from the other source of knowledge, sensation, but which add no- thing to them. Not one of these faculties has the power of introducing into the mind any portion of knowledge, any idea whatever peculiar to itself. The operations of the understanding therefore add nothing fundamental or essential to the ideas derived from sensation; all our knowledge therefore has its beginning and end in sensation. Such is the theory of Locke presented in its lowest terms. ‘Thus re- duced, it is already judged; it clearly belongs to the great Sensual school. ‘The principle once estab- lished, it is easy to foresee the consequences. ‘The native wisdom of Locke could not keep them back ; they every where escape from his system; and con- nect him with that chain of Sensual philosophers of which Hobbes formed the last link. Locke, in fact, is Hobbes, with such differences as the case requires. He hardly ever quotes him, but he constantly repro- duces him. Thus his chapter on the influence of language closely resembles the chapter of Hobbes on the same subject ; Hobbes was professedly a Nomin- alist; Locke should have been one in accordance 26 PSEC PSE PST pena e shri Pad SRL ae eanee ee ree at Ss ee Soe Od Te 3 te gt ae 6b ee es ke he BBN INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. with his system ; but although he did not openly avow Nominalism, he contributed to give it currency. Hobbes and the whole Sensual school assimilate the soul, to a greater or less degree, to the body, as is very well known. Locke does not go so far as that ; but with Occam and Scotus he maintains that it is difficult to prove, except by revelation, that the sub- ject of the operations of the understanding is spirit and not matter; and he suspects that God, in his omnipotence, might have endowed matter with the faculty of thought. Such is the character of the Sensual philosophy, in the earlier stages of its progress. It was reserved for the acute and intrepid thinkers of the French na- tion to carry it to its utmost logical consequences, and to present it in a form which may justly be said to bear the ghastliness of death. The principles of Locke were greatly aided in their reception in France by the authority of Voltaire. During his residence in England, he became acquaint- ed with the system, and at a subsequent period, de- voted the brilliant resources of his imagination and wit to its defence. It soon became the property of the saloons ; imperceptibly it took possession of the excited mind of the nation ; its adoption was deemed the standard of culture and taste; and, at last, it obtained an able expounder in the clear-minded and sagacious Condillac. This fertile writer not only illustrated the system of his predecessor by his la- minous exhibition of its principles, but enriched it with numerous observations of his own, reduced many of its scattered ideas to a compact form, and presented it in a style at once scientific and popular. The leading aim of his philosophy is to deduce the complete development of the human mind from the single principle of sensation. His writings containa more able and ingenious defence of. this doctrine than is to be found in the English successors ot Locke ; and, with the simplicity and good faith cos eT ee eer orePe eee eet Spee abe aree si 28 BIOGRAPHICAL AND which he always sets it forth, it is by no means sur- prising that he should have gained such a wide- spread influence over the national mind, 4 We should also do Condillac the justice, as a man, it 1s well remarked by a late French writer, “ to remem- ber that he did not follow out his system to 1ts ulti- mate disastrous consequences 5 perhaps he did not even perceive them; for this is not unfrequently the case. If Locke, religious before his philosophy, con- tinued religious after it, it would be inadmissible to conclude from it, that the philosophy of Locke is a religious philosophy. Materialism, in the form in which it has been seen in our own days, is only the necessary result of the philosophy of Locke, as inter- preted among us by Condillac.” It was not long after the establishment of this philosophy in France, that its legitimate conclusions began to be perceived. We have already seen the principles which it in- volves, when considered merely as an abstract but connected process of thought. The correctness of that analysis is verified by the actual manifestation of those principles in the progress of French philoso- phy. It has been shown that the sensual system leads to Materialism. In the hands of Cabanis, we find this doctrine fully developed. His great work on the Physical and Moral Relations of Man,' sup- ports the theory that the soul is not a separate prin- ciple in our nature, a real existence, but merely the product of the nervous system. Sensibility is the property of the nerves; and sensibility explains the moral faculties, the intelligence, the will, the whole inward nature of man. Man is a moral being be- cause he is capable of sensation; he is capable of sensation, because he has nerves; the nerves make the man. The brain secretes thought, as the liver secretes bile? In justice to Cabanis, however, it _* Rapports du Physique et du Moral de Homme, Paris, 2 Vols. 1824. ae as ; 4 See Daminon, Histoire de la Philosophie en France au ® e\ « dixneuvieme siecle. 288g ie Pe Se Sas tar ta ae hy Sey Sg ye, SG 4 a a Sen ar rs ig Sy SET ata Figg Ses ad Kgs Be ho ea INTRODUCTORY NOTICR. 29 should be added, that he modified his system before his death ; but not till it firmly established the doc- trines of Materialism among the most intelligent thinkers of his country. " The physiological theories of Cabanis were adopt- ed by Destutt de Tracy, and applied by him to the more complete explanation of the intellectual faculties, In his opinion, thought is nothing but sensation, or rather sensibility, of which sensation is the exercise. Thought is modified according to the nature of the impressions which are made on the sensibility. It becomes, in different cases, perception, memory, Judgment, will, as the external organs are acted on in a different manner. The will, therefore, is merely an affection of the sensibility; that is to say, the will is passive; that is to say again, the will is not will; man is deprived of liberty ; the Sensual philo- sophy is Fatalism. The moral results of this system were exhibited by Volney. His leading doctrine is, that man should act only for the sake of self-preservation. This is the great law of human nature. Accordingly, good is every thing which tends to the preservation of man ; evil every thing which tends to his injury and destruction. The greatest good is life; the greatest evil is death ; nothing is better than physical happi- ness ; nothing worse than bodily suffering; the main object is health; virtue and vice, therefore, are the voluntary habits which are in accordance with or contrary to the law of self-preservation. Every thing is right which contributes to enjoyment; every thing is wrong which interferes with enjoyment. This is the moral philosophy of the Sensual school. Finally, in the logical order, as the ultimate result of this school, we have the author of the System of Nature. His theory of the Universe resolves every thing into matter and motion. These exist from eternity, and are the causes of all the phenomena which take place. Matter can neither be created, nor destroyed: and the existence of a cause on which it depends a A) erent | dewetalemes re30 BIOGRAPHICAL AND be demonstrated The idea of a Godisa fiction 5 the hope of immortality a dream; and all the religious convictions of man are founded on self-flattery or fear. This is the limit of the Sensual philosophy. Its principles had been discussed in every point of view ; its consequences drawn forth with no common logical power ; and its foundation strengthened with all the aids that could be derived from skill in rea- soning, and ‘courage in examining. ‘The question now arose, whether this philosophy was to continue to be the prevailing system in Trance during the nineteenth century, as it had been, in its primary elements, during the eighteenth. The first symptom of a decided philosophical re- action was exhibited in the lectures of Laromiguiere, as Professor in the Faculty of Literature. These were delivered in the years 1811, 1812, and 1813, and were subsequently published in several editions. Soon after their appearance, it was observed by Cousin, in a Review inserted in the Philosophical Fragments, that “ the favourable reception given to this work was a proof, in the first place, that a phi- losophical revolution was secretly going on in indl- vidual minds ; and, secondly, that public opinion was already prepared for this revolution.” Laromiguiere had been formed in the school of Condillac, and hardly considered himself to have abandoned the system of his master. The struggle between his early associations and his new convic- tions is every where visible in his writings; but he is compelled to admit the defects of the popular views, and advances principles of his own which contain the germs of reform. After a long examination, La- romiguiere comes to the conclusion, that sensation is not the only principle of thought, of understanding, and of will. He maintains that there is a broad chasm between sensation and the faculties of our mind. These faculties, both of the understanding and the will, are referred to attention as their ultimate foun- 30we hp Me thes Gta, Sek Se eK Ee es Sy SEG - ad ate Se "hg Saad Yaris Dat Sg ' ME a a Of Os Se a ea te INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. ST dation. This is an important departure from the fun- damental principles of Condillac. The influence ex- erted by Laromiguiere in the philosophical culture of Cousin himself will be found alluded to by the latter in another part of this volume. A more important element, however, in the formation of his opinions, was derived from the teachings of Maine de Biran,— a philosopher whose name has gained its principal celebrity from the grateful commemoration of his elo- quent pupil; but whose uncommon ability in analy- tical investigation, as manifested in the few writings which he gave to the publie, entitle him to the praise of being one of the most profound and original thinkers, in his peculiar department of study, which France has produced. Maine de Biran was one of those fortunate indivi- duals who find the highest gratification of taste in the indulgence of severe meditation. He was far more desirous to ascertain the truth, for the satisfaction of his own mind, than to obtain the glory of communi- cating it to the world. He habitually fed on those rigid abstractions, which, though seemingly remote from all popular interests, are at the foundation of social improvement, and the progress of man. His love of philosophy was pure and single-hearted. He cultivated it, not for emolument or renown, for the sake of office or of fashion, but for the light it threw on the laws and destiny of our being. On this account, he took little pains to make his ideas known to others. Content in the calm pursuit of truth, he seems to have had no ambition of acting on the opinions of philosophers; but the progress which has since been made in France is indebted for some of its earliest and strongest impulses to his so- litary reflections. The principle, to the exposition of which Maine de Biran devoted almost exclusively his philosophical labours, was the activity of the human mind.! The + See Nouvelles Considérations sur les Rapports du wi Cae ls Tere ey a ere 7 Uc teeea abe payasscedetinat Car rs Pe ale eeeBIOGRAPHICAL AND prevailing philosophy, as we have seen, referred all our faculties, as well as all our ideas, to sensation, which it explained by the excitement of the brain produced by the impressions of outward objects upon the organs. Maine de Biran demonstrated that this was a merely hypothetical assumption, without the slightest foundation in truth. He pointed out among the elements that are essential to a complete science of man, a fact as certain as any which have been ob- served, which, though connected with sensation, can- not be explained by it, and which, though subject to organic conditions, is independent of organization. This fact is activity. Maine de Biran separates this from all the circumstances in which it is found, ana- lyzes its character, ascends to its original source, follows it to its ultimate developments, restores it to its rank in the intellectual life, and presents a theory of it which must hereafter hold an important | place in every sound philosophy. This theory, which will be found developed at length in the writings of Cousin, and applied with admirable success to some of the most difficult and important topics of philoso- phical inquiry. consists of the following elementary principles. 1. True activity is in the will. 2. The will is the essence of personality. It constitutes the whole of what we call me or seLF. 3. To will is to exercise causation. The first cause which we be- come acquainted with is ourselves. This may be proved by the phenomena of muscular effort. In every act of this kind, two things are to be taken into consideration. 1. A muscular sensation more or less lively. 2. The effort which produces it. Mus- cular sensation is not merely subsequent to the effort ; it is produced by it; the relation which connects them is not that of simple succession, but of cause and effect. This is attested by consciousness, and no proof of it is necessary, but the performance of et du Moralde Homme. Ouvrage posthume de M. MaIne DE Brran, publié par M. Cousin, Paris, 1834. Preface, p. ix. 32 SPER PSST ES PSS POST ROA PPT ee La ap Phe Pe oe SO a SRR Roky 6 OP ue ae a a SP EP aD oP ees CN NN 8 ON et ee tp tg te, DE eewt Sd eg Sere Lerten hy ee TS ek TT Me Ee Sr om, SO Sk Nae She ha a Sead Tat is Bs Sig a es eg eg er tg ee ca Sg Os Se hg Se ee INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. Bo the act. Now every effort implies volition. There is no such thing as an involuntary effort. Hence the will is the foundation of the effort in question, and the cause which operates is a voluntary cause. But, on the other hand, it is we who make the effort ; we certainly impute it to ourselves; the will which is the cause vf it is our own will. Will, cause, per- sonality, are therefore identical. I arrive at the con- sciousness of myself, by acting as a cause; and I act as a cause when I will, when I exercise a volition. Take away volition, that is, effort, and nothing re- mains; the whole fact disappears. This demonstration gives us the most fruitful con- sequences. For instance, as the will is the type of personality, and as the very essence of the will is liberty, it follows that the liberty of what we call SELF 1s identical with its existence, and immediately perceived by consciousness. Liberty is thus placed beyond the reach of every sophism ; since it is not revealed by a process of reasoning, but by the direct testimony of consciousness. The case is the same with regard to the spiritual nature of our being. That which every man considers as his true and proper self, that which he refers to when he says ME, is spiritual. This is not proved by a course of argumentation. The question can never be decided in this way. Hence the interminable con- troversies respecting it. The proof of the spirituality of our inward nature is to be found in the immediate perceptions of consciousness. It is made known to us in the unity and identity. of which we are conscious in every act of volition. These are not the properties of matter. In the continuity of effort, we feel that we always will, that we always act; we feel also that we are the same will, the same cause, even when the effects which we will and produce are various. Now this sEuF, conscious of unity and identity, dis- tinct from its variable effects, does not come within the sphere of the senses or the imagination ; it per- ceives itself directly in the continuity of its co Se so) mage emlshionieals Jrpettbabe seea4 BIOGRAPHICAL AND which it regards in fact as the continuity of its exist- ence ; it therefore exists incontestably in its own view, with an existence which escapes both the senses and the imagination; and this is precisely what we mean by a spiritual existence. No reasoning can produce this certainty, and no reasoning can destroy or weaken it; for it depends on one of the first principles which are perceived prior to reasoning, without which no reasoning can be carried on. In this manner, Spiritualism is reinstated in philo- sophy on the basis of experience. Not that extrava- gant Spiritualism, however, which has no connexion with the world we inhabit; for the spirit which we are, the being which we call srr is manifested to us in arelation of which it forms the first term, but of which the second term is a sensation, and a sensation which can be referred to a specific part of the body. The spirit, accordingly, is revealed to us together with its opposite, the inward and the outward world, man and nature at once. It was not, however, until the Lectures of Royer- Collard were commenced in the University of Paris, that a public and uncompromising attack was made on the philosophy of sensation. ‘hese were delivered in three courses, from 1811 to 1814; and since that time the reform of the prevailing philosophy has been in constant progress. Royer-Collard was singularly fitted by his character and talents for the work which he undertook. His personal qualities enabled him to speak with no common authority, and preserved him from the unthinking opposition to which the herald of new ideas is usually exposed. The vigour of his intellect was every where acknowledged ; he was understood to have mastered his subject by profound reflection; no one could doubt that his convictions were the result of inquiry; his sincerity was above suspicion. He was free from the charge of a love of innovation 5 a tendency to idle and extravagant spe- Te ee incompatible with the whole structure uo is mind; and it was evident to all, that the ob- ; Par Pe earet. tt eet ee ee nave hak hos are! Ta arr, eee ee Oe Se Oe sO Oe ae ns Rea as Saag as Sat She aa Sel ad ak 4 er Se gee es ee a INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. 35 jections which he brought against the theories of the day proceeded from meditation, and not from ca- price. The teachings of Royer-Collard were immediately connected with the philosophical inquiries of Reid. He was led by the study of Dr. Reid's writings to perceive the radical error of the Sensual philosophy, and to adopt a method founded on the natural laws of thought, and in accordance with the processes of en- lightened physical investigation. He could not fail to perceive that the arguments of the Scottish philo- sopher against the doctrines of Locke and of Hume were equally valid against those of Condillac. The principal subject to which Royer-Collard directed his attention was the same with that which chiefly occu- pied the inquiries of Dr. Reid,—the perception of external objects by the organs of sensation. But the influence which he exerted was not confined to any specific branch of philosophy ; it extended through the whole sphere of reflection ; it presented new as- pects of familiar truths, and revived ideas that had passed away; it inspired the youthful students of the nature of man, with a fresh and vigorous life; and thus gave birth to a movement of thought which forms one of the most important elements in the character of the nineteenth century. Victor Cousin was the favourite pupil, and soon be- came the intimate friend of Royer-Collard. They were united by similarity of tastes, devotion to the pursuits of science, zeal for the improvement of the age, and faith in a higher order of ideas than had been recognised in the popular philosophy of France. The wide fame which has since been acquired by the ac- complished pupil should not make us forget the signal merits of the sound and clear-sighted instructor. Cousin himself seems to lose no occasion of expressing the deepest gratitude and admiration towards his dis- tinguished master, and, with a modesty which is no less beautiful than it is rare, he always refers the com- mencement of his brilliant successes in pale ed36 BIOGRAPHICAL AND to the masculine and impressive wisdom of Royer- Collard. The advancement which has been given by the labours of Cousin to the philosophical reform, thus happily begun, will appear from the selections from his writings that are contained in the present work. They consist of the Preface to his Translation of Tennemann, his two celebrated Prefaces to the “ Phi- losophical Fragments,” and several of the most impor- tant shorter articles of that volume. The student of Cousin’s philosophy will find his knowledge refreshed by those compact, though luminous summaries of his principal ideas; while those who desire to obtain a just insight into the character and spirit of his pecu- liar system will be able to gratify their wishes, with- out the labour of perusing a multitude of voluminous works. The prefaces, in particular, have excited an extraordinary interest among the philosophical read- ers of Europe ; and it is not too much to hope that they may be made the subject of an earnest and en- lightened study by the reflecting lovers of truth and science in our own country. The philosophical merits of Cousin will probably not be new to the majority of the readers of this volume. ‘The translations which have been already made of two of his most important works, have con- tributed to give currency to his ideas, and in many cases, to awaken a lively zeal for the study of the original! I may venture to say that there is no liv- ing philosopher who has a greater number of readers in this country, and none, whose works have met with a more genuine sympathy, a more cordial recogni- tion. He is destined, in my opinion, to exert an 1 Introduction to the History of Philosophy. Translated by HENNING GorrrieD LinBeERG, Boston, 1832. Elements of Psychology ; included in a Critical Examination of Locke's Essay on the Human Understanding. Translated by C. 8. Henry. With an Introduction, Notes, and Additions. Hartford, 1834. 36eke oe Oi Wd fry he te? 8 A YA INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. DF important influence on the development of th lought and the condition of philosophy in our land. i do not mean that Cousin will ever be regarded as the founder of a philosophical sect among the thinkers of this nation. This is forbidden by the whole character of his system. It does not contain a single element which can lead to the establishment of an exclusive school. The happiest effect which he produces on the minds of his disciples is to lead them to think no less independently of him, than of others 5 to accept the fruits of his inquiries, as con- tributions to philosophy, rather than as a complete and ultimate philosophy ; to APPIAGIARE, with a wise and tolerant discrimination, the merits of every la- bourer in this boundless field; and to comprehend and value the forgotten ere aia of the past, as well as the splendid discoveries of modern times. The aim_of-his.philosophy is to furnish a criterion, taken from the actual observation of human nature, by which to estimate both the phenomena of daily experience, and the speculative systems which have been constructed for their explanation in every age of_the werld.— For these reasons, his foltowers-can never be linked together in the strong bands of an exclusive party. They will possess in common the admirable logical method of their teacher; they will start with himefrom the rigorous analysis of the facts of consciousness ; and they will search like him for the elements of truth in every system, through all ages. But they will not be bound to adopt any of his specific doctrines, except in so far as ee can verify them for themselves; nor, on any pretence, will ‘they be restrained, through deference to his authority, from ulterior inquiry and independent thought. This is the genuine spirit of the teachings of Cousin. He latices: to make students, rather than disciples ; sound and liberal thinkers, 1 rather than ad- herents to his system ; philosophers, rather than sec- tarians. t No. XXxIE D vd 4] } VON § ou thft AkBIOGRAPHICAL AND This characteristic is adapted to give his philoso- phy a favourable reception among ourselves. ‘The reign of authoritative dogmatic systems has never been firmly established over the mind of this nation ; every exclusive faith has called forth a hest in dis- sent ; and the time appears to have arrived when no opinions can gain a Benen al reception, unless they appeal to the spirit of inquiry, a nd disdain the aid of prescription or restraint. This tendency of thought will find a congenial object in the philosophy. of Cousin. It wil ‘be nourished by his calm and lucid expositions of truth; it will be supplied with mate- ri ials for the loftiest contemplation ; while no shackles will be placed upon its freedom, no system forced upon its reception, no sacrifice called for of its in- dependence. The writings of Cousin are no less distinguished by their Meni ebs and beauty of express Se than i their freedom from every thing like an exclusive and sectarian spirit. In this re spect, he may be compared advantageously with the best authors of his own or any other nation. It is not pretended, indeed, une he possesses the talent of making a ne subjec intelligible without profound study. He is not a be | ranked with those writers who are always clear, be- | cause they are never deep ; always popular, because they are always superficial. He cannot present th results of an exquisite analysis of thought in a , form i vhich shall be palpable at once to the coars¢st intel- leet; but it is certain that whatever illus derationn can be given to the subtile researches of the philo sopher by a skilful use of language is to be found in oh copious and expressive style. It would be saying little, to remark that he never affects mystery, and alw vays aims at being understood by the genera alreaden ea ts would do no Sustice to his mode of expression. t would be more correct to say that he re ens tl 1€ Mos t abstract ideas in such ipa dee diction, il ae cannot fail to impress themselves on the understanding of all who desire to be nceue tes In a8 CP OP Ge ae BP Bi oe ase Si Fee ah Sh ca Yas Se ws Say Fie Say Sas "Se 4 a aS ag Tage Ba Se Be Sa eres INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. 39 oe point of orderly arrangement, of continuous and sys- tematic reasoning tem: ¢, and of admira a taste in the se. jection of jon 18, Cousin presents a favourable contrast to the mos eminent philosophers of Germany. W W itl it Vor of SF 1 Ws the exce SHG on of Reinhold and Fries, to whom per- haps Jacobi should be added, I know of no modern German wri ae on — osophy to whose Sige we are not obliged to pardon much, through respect for the depth of their thou ghts, and the completeness of their investigz ations. They are compelled to suffer the severe penalty of addressing themselves to scholars ar kers by profession, instead of t! elligent population.! There is nothing more dangerous to correctness of thought ox ! of expres ssion, than for the literary 3 or € iterary men of a nation hdraw from the sympathies of the common sal and thus to lose the benefit of comparing the abstractions of speculation with the natn cood f the body of the pe The most sublime contemplations of the philosopher can Be translated into the language of the market; and unless they ot find a ae in the native feelings of nae y there is probably some error in the doctrine, or some defect in its exposition. This source of difficulty hes ie avoided by Cousin. Called upon to exhibit the easonings and conclusions of the ee philosophy toa a promiscuous audience in t hei iv ‘opolis of France, he ve addressed the popular n 1 with singular suc cess, and solved the cardinal sik em of presenting the highest truths of speculati ion in a form adapted to the average intelligence of enlighte ned society. He has put the gener: lt reader i 1 posses sion of the most aluable results of a pont philosophy: this is all that can be demanded of a teache er; more than th is beyond the reach of aby style, however clear ; and in order to con nuprehend the entire significance and fulness of the truth which is thus obtained, nothing will suffice but the voluntary exertion of our own in- 1 See Note A. oe) age aeeeritel + dryricbnes ceeAO BIOGRAPHICAL AND tellect, the free reproduction in our consciousness of the ideas we have received from the instruction of another. The characteristic which has now been alluded to in the writings of Cousin, presents an additional claim upon the attention of our countrymen. Our national taste—as far as it is formed—may certainly be said to repudiate all mystery and concealment. We have even less patience with obscurity of style, than with shallowness of thought. We are often tempted to slight or discard truths of unutterable consequence both to society and to individuals, on account of the unusual, it may he, the repulsive phraseology in which they are conveyed. ‘The first condition of popularity among us is the clear expression of dis- tinct thoughts. We forgive any thing sooner than those entanglements of words which leave us to guess at the meaning of the writer, and at last to remain doubtful whether we have read his riddle aright. For this reason the German philosophers, in their native costume, will never become extensively popular in this country. ‘The fruits of their inquiries will one day pass into general circulation among us ; but not till they have been refined and clarified by successive operations in different minds. ‘Their writ- ings will be studied by all who love philosophy for its own sake: the true-hearted scholar, who fears no toil, nor pain, in the pursuit of science, will descend with them to the darkest caverns of abstraction, so he may return with the pure ore of truth; and the lover of literary history will never cease to ponder, with thoughtful admiration, that great intellectual movement, in which even the political and material interests of a mighty nation have been comparatively forgotten. But they cannot be made the direct foun- dation of philosophical culture in a country like our own. We must start with the freer, more popular, more concrete, and more finished productions of the great French writers who have been formed in the German school; who retain its vigour and depth, and 40Tha gil, ah, he a Me PS OR Tg Oe Ya Ted Oe Sey Wr Oey in, SaaS gs ee saz a tag a Se Og ae he ere INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. Al combine with it the graceful ease of their own beauti- ful literature. Intimately connected with its distinctness of ex- oxression, is another essential characteristic of the philosophy of Cousin, which will serve to facilitate its advancement among the intelligent thinkers of this nation. Iallude to the substantial basis which it gives to the instinctive convictions of the human mind. This is the ultimate aim of all genuine philosophy. No system can be of any permanent utility which does not reproduce and legitimate the indestructible faith, that is cherished by the common sense of the mass of humanity.’ A philosopher who makes war upon this is guilty of the same absurdity with the artist who should make war on natural beauty. Of this fact, Cousin is not only fully aware himself; but he takes unwearied pains to explain its origin, to jus- tify its importance, and to urge its consequences upon the attention of the reader. Every primitive belief of humanity is invested in his eyes with a cha- racter of peculiar, I may say indeed, of awful sanctity. In following the process of his investigations con- cerning the essential elements of reason, the absolute foundation of faith, the instinctive convictions of our race which are found, to a certain extent, in every mind, and manifested, in a certain form, in every epoch of the world, we are led to forget the impulses of merely intellectual curiosity, and to yield ourselves up,—if I may so express it without temerity,—to a solemn emotion of religious reverence. He gives us the true key to the meaning of those remarkable ex~ pressions, which, in almost every language, indicate the conviction that the voice of God is uttered in the heart of man, that the light of the soul is a light from Heaven. The scientific interpretation and proof of these popular phrases are unfolded at length in the writings of Cousin. They form the substance of the doctrine which exhibits in a great variety of forms, as the spontaneous and reflective development of — PAL HOR & & homme ROT ‘ale ae eR Pr AH AR 9 COCBIOGRAPHICAL There is no portion of his philosophy, itappears to me, more original, or more truly valuable than this. Its importance is, certainly, not obvious to the inattentive reader; but it will be found upon examination, if I mistake not, to throw the brightest light on many of the darkest questions ; to contribute some essential elements towards the solution of the great problem of our age,—the reconcilement of faith and reason, authority and free conviction. The respect which is every where testified in the system of Cousin for the spontaneous belief of hu- manity, presents a bond of sympathy between the highly educated and the masses, which is strikingly adapted to the condition of society among ourselves. ‘The office of the true scholar in our republic is to connect himself in the most intimate and congenial relations with the energetic and busy population of which he is too often merely an insignificant unit. He is never to stand aloof from the concerns of the people; he is never to view them in the pride of su- perior culture or station as belonging to a distinct order from himself; he is never to set himselfabove them as their condescending instructor, from whom they are to receive wisdom and light, according to his estimate of their capacity ; but he is called upon to honour the common mind, to commune with the in- stinctive expressions of the mighty heart of a free nation, and to bring the aid of learning and philoso- phy to the endeavour of the people to comprehend their destiny, and to secure its accomplishment. The direct tendency of the system of Cousin is to produce this effect. It abases the proud and exalts the humble. ft destroys the arrogance of mere scholarship, and teaches us to listen to the voice of humanity, though uttered from the lowliest shrine. At the same time, it substantiates the principle of so- cial progress, and inspires a serene and patient faith in the promised fortunes of our race. I have already alluded to the religious character of i philcsophy in question. I will add, that it seems -Oe Sig Wert tant torte. tos tar erates See, PR Ne MT PRs SA Site Sire J INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. to me to contain more fully than any other system which is likely to gain adherents in this country, the principles which lie at the foundation of an elevated and spiritual philosophy of religion. Its accordance vith ¢ Christianity, 1 in the view of its author, is proba- bly too v ell known to the reader, for me to enlarge 11S place. It may be remarked, haw ever, fends to justify no sectarian views of Christi- ity, whether manifested in the form of attachment tot madi anee ideas, oF of love ap oe inno- rat d and in- estin cations of all beli ievers, form the essence of Chris- tianity, and the reception of which is deemed neces- sary to the salvation of the soul. It is with ee 2 to another department of theo- logy that I have referred to the religious influence of the philos¢ es of Cousin. In the opinion of many individuals,—and I own myself to be one of the num- ber,—the prevailing philosophical theories in this ecounEry, are not co inpletely adequate, to say the least. the scientific grounding of a spiritual religion. The wedded union of philosophy and religion, SO essential to the peace of the meditative mi nd, has not yet been oneninaeeild in the sanctuary of our holiest thoughts. This is the true cause of the ominous fact that an open dread of f philosophy and a secret doubt of religion are not unfrequent in the midst of us. This s the most candid, and probal bly the most just, ¢ expia- ae on that can be given of the strange aversion to inquiry, the mor bid sensitiveness to new manifesta- tions of truth which is sometimes exhibited by well- meaning and excellent individuals. If we felt the ground five beneath us, we should not fear the conse- quences of the most searching scrutiny into the foun- dation on which we stand. There is a repose, @ quietness, a a cheerful trust, a blessed assurance in the mind which has passed from unreiecting dogmatism to enlightened faith, in the enjoyment bon which it looks calmly on every free and ear nest working of the 43 S S eee ee 2? % DEAR AA OO fake ee CT pABIOGRAPHICAL AND oe 4 “ae intellect in pursuit of truth,—.confident that truth is always consistent with itself, and that no genuine ex- pression of the Deity or of the human soul can be set aside by any new discovery. But this state of mind ean be produced only by establishing an unbroken harmony between feeling and speculation, between the spontaneous impulses of the heart and the profound results of reflection. I should be glad to believe that we have a philosophy among us which is capable of doing this. The experience of several years, with some opportunities for observation, has convinced me however that this is not the case. There is an inter- ruption in the continuity of our thought. We are believers in a spiritual religion; but we are not mas- ters of a spiritual philosophy. There is little danger in this condition of things to those, with whom piety is such a strong natural sentiment, that no force can | pluck it out of their hearts. They will never feel the burden of doubt, or need the aid of philosophy to ex- plain the mysteries of their being. On those virgin souls no blight can fall; their robes are al ways white ; and they will pass upward unstained by the breath of unbelief. But our world, in this country, at the pre- sent age, is not composed of such beautiful spirits as these. ‘There are few who have not been ealled to test the validity of their dearest convictions, either by the assaults of scepticism from without, or the course of their own reflections. It must be a mind of extra- ordinary construction which has not felt the need of comprehending its own instincts more clearly ; of looking into the foundation of the primitive truths on which the well-being of man reposes; and of settling the lofty spiritual faith in which it has grown up on the firm ground ofa broad and clear philosophy. A sense of this want is widely spread in almost every circle of society, into which we enter. A deep con- viction of the reality of spiritual truth, and, at the same time, a strong desire for a philosophical system which shall explain and legitimate it, are every where ee among contemplative individuals. Too often A4Saas as hs a a ae eee yee A LA er iS hh ON TS INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. 45 however, the clearness and strength of the former are impaired, by failing to meet with the latter. More bs one young man has told me, in sadness of spirit, ot the struggle which was going on in the very depths of his being, between reflection and faith, between the convictions to which he clung, and the theories by which they were sustained. The same testimony is given by writers of the most opposite opinions and experience. One of the ablest metaphysicians in this country, in a masterly essay on the present state of philosophical speculation, thus speaks of the effect which is produced, within the sphere of his observa- tion, by the usual mode of presenting the argument for the foundation of religion. ‘Is it not indeed a fact, notwithstanding the abundant commendation be- stowed upon the work of Dr. Paley, the dependence placed upon it in our systems of instruction, and the assertion that a mind unsatisfied with this argument Is not to be satisfied at all, —is it not a fact, I say, that many young men of ingenuous minds, but at the same time logical and critical in their inquiries, are left unsatisfied with the results of the work? I fear there are many who, having been taught that this is the great and triumphant argument, the sure ground, on which a belief in the existence of God depends, find their faith rather weakened by it than confirmed, or at best lose more in regard to their views of his cha~ racter, than they gain in their belief of his existence. __How do we know, or how can we learn by this process of arguing, that the unknown cause of those effects, which Dr. Paley bas exhibited, that the mys- terious and dread ground of being in all, that exists and that we call nature, is not a necessitated as well as a necessary Being, or that it is even self-conscious and intelligent ¢ If now, as I trust will be the case, the reader shrinks with a conscious feeling of dread and abhorrence from such a conclusion, as impious, I would earnestly beg of him not to charge it upon me, and at the same time warn him not to ascribe ng which such a co SI ‘ould awaken, the feeling hicl I nelusion would awaken 45RIS Pa PS eg ite ae BIOGRAPHICAL AND to any convictions of the bemg and attributes of a personal God which the supposed strength and in- fluence of Paley’s argument may have been thought to produce. That faith in the being of God and that reverence for his holy and perfect character, in virtue of which we shrink from atheism, as a viola- tion of our moral being, as absurd and impious, lie far deeper, than those convictions of the mere un- derstanding, ‘the ene judging a according to sense,’ which may have been derived from the argument i in question.” The same train of thought is presented, with sin- gular ability and strength, in an article in a recent periodical publication,? which may perhaps be con- sidered as representing the views of a large class of thinking men, whose iics and habits entitle their opinion on a subject of metaphysical inquiry to a listened to with peculiar respect.s It is a distinc avowal that the philosophy of our day is rae coite to the support of the holiest religious convictions. From these and similar facts, I am led to conclude, that the want ofa higher system is more and more generally felt, « ale that the interests of a sound philosoph y and a true religion cannot much longer be separated from each other.’ It is by the prevalence of this feeling that I ac- count for the remarkable popularity of Mr. Colerid; ge as a philcsophical writer, with a great number of in- dividuals Heo cannot be insensible to his signal de- fects and in nperfections. The works of Mr. Coleridge, in my opinion, are exceedingly valuable to two 1 any ee See PRESIDENT Ma RSH’s Note to Coler idge’s Aids to Reflection, : 1e whole of his Prelimina ry Essay to the °O la which has desery eee creat attention, and w ae a may be reckoned, for the depth of its of the finest pieces of reasoning and the force of its style, one hich has appeared in our langua age Ss sume work,—; p hilosopt ical composition Ww for many years. ; American Quarterly Observer, No. II. Boston, 1833. See Note B. 46Nie te 6 Te ee a he ee ee ere ae ee INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. 47 classes of persons. To those, in the first place, on whom the light of spiritual truth is beginning te dawn; who are just awakened to the consciousness of the inward powers of their nature, and who need to have the sentiment of religion quickened into more vital activity ; and, secondly, to those, who have obtained as the fruit of their own reflections, a living system of spiritual faith. The former will find the elements of congenial truth profusely scat- tered over his pages; the latter will be able, from their own experience, to construct a systematic whole with the massive fragments which are almost buried beneath the magnificent confusion of his style. But Mr. Coleridge cannot satisfy the mind whose primary want is that of philosophical clearness and precision. He is the inspired poet, the enthusiastic prophet of a spiritual philosophy; but the practical architect, by whose skill the temple of faith is to be restored. cannot be looked for in him. The objects at which Mr. Coleridge aims, it seems to me, are in a great measure accomplished by the philosophy of Cousin. This philosophy demolishes, by one of the most beautiful specimens of scientific analysis that is any where to be met with, the system of sensation, against which Mr. Coleridge utters such eloquent and pathetic denunciations. It esta- blishes on a rock the truth of the everlasting senti- ments of the human heart. It exhibits to the specu- lative inquirer, in the rigorous forms of science, the reality of our instinctive faith in God, in Virtue, in the human Soul, in the Beauty of Holiness, and in the Immortality of Man. Such a philosopiy, I cannot but believe, will ulti- mately find a cherished abode in the youthful affec- tions of this nation, in whose history, from the be- ginning, the love of freedom, the love of philosopi- cal inquiry, and the love of religion have been com- bined in a thrice holy bond. We need a phil sophy like this to purify and enlighten our politics, to con- secrate our industry, to cheer and elevate society. 49 “tf eres Ce ed+ 8 BIOGRAPHICAL AND We need it for our own use.in the hours of mental misgiving and gloom; when the mystery of the uni- verse presses heavily upon our souls; when the fountains of the great deep are broken up, and the ‘* Intellectual Power Goes sounding on, a dim and perilous way,” over the troubled waters of the stormy sea. We need it for the use of our practical men, who, surrounded on every side with the objects of sense, engrossed with the competitions of business, the rivalries of public life, or the cares of professional duty, and ae- customed to look at the immediate and obvious utility of every thing which appeals to their notice, often acquire a distaste for all moral and religious inquiries; and, as an almost inevitable consequence, lose their interest, and often their belief, in the moral and religious faculties of their nature. We need it for the use of our young men, who are engaged in the active pursuits of life, or devoted to the cultiva- tion of literature. How many on the very threshold of manly responsibility, by the influence of a few un- happy mistakes, which an acquaintance with their higher nature, as unfolded by a sound religious phi- losophy, would have prevented, have consigned them- Selves to disgrace, remorse, and all the evils of a violated conscience! How many have become the dupes of the sophist’s eloquence, or the victims of the fanatic’s terrors, for whom the spirit of a true philosophy—-a philosophy « baptized in the pure fountain of eternal love,” would have preserved the charm and beauty of life. The elements of a philosophy of this character, I venture to think, are contained in the doctrines of Cousin and his distinguished pupil Jouffroy, as ex- hibited in the present volume. They do not profess to offer a complete exposition of the views of the authors, from whose writings translations are given. Their aim is a more humble one. If they shail in- crease the interest which is already felt in the works 48 fa al Ne GY OEP iP ae are P o ei ReINTRODUCTORY NOTICE. A9 of those eminent philosophers, and contribute in any degree to the better understanding of their ideas, their purpose will be accomplished. They are com- mended, with difidence in my own share of the work, but with confidence in the merits of the origi- nal writers, to the free spirit and candid judgment of the reader. } q 4 24 q ' “¢ “4 a : .50 DESTINY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY. poe ON THE DESTINY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY.! PuiLosorny, at the present day, can do only one of these three things : Hither abdicate, renounce its independence, st again to the ancient authority, return to the Middle 4 * A oes e ZA bay CS sbmit A. ° 5 Or continue its troubled motion in the circle of worn-out systems which mutually destroy each other; Or finally disengage what is true in each of these systems, and thus construct a philosophy superior to all systems, which shall govern. them.all by being above them.all, which shall be no longer this or that philosophy, but philosophy itself in its essence and in its unity. ‘The first course is impossible. For philosophy is onlyan effect andnot a cause. The independence, and, so to speak, the secularization of thought, are produced by the general progress of the spirit of independence and of secularization in every thing, in the State, in science, in art, in industry. This being laid down, the question is easily resolved. What wind could now root up that tree which has put forth in the midst of storms, and which has grown up moistened with the tears and blood of so many generations? Modern civilization cannot go back, nor consequently the phi- losophy which represents it. Here is the vanity of the Theocratic shool. Theocracy is the legitimate cradle of infant societies, but it does not accompany them in From the Preface to the Translation of ** Tennemann’s Outlines of the History of Philosophy.—1829, 30Vee ee ae oe he oh eae bar San ls Sas Se See ere, Se aed et Og Se oe Ser epee y Tyee SEA STINY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY. o| the progress of their development,—that Beene progress which is derived from the nee of things and as the nature of things cannot be e separated from the designs of providence, it fo rows that every strug- gle against the nature of things is in fact-direeted against Providence itself; and that ede the attempt to~arrest thecourse of civ lization, and to extinguish philosophy is an enterprize against God a the strength ‘of the world must fail of success. And besides, what is me foundation 3 | oH S ~ pom ©) acon ==) eS > 1 > . of the arrogant quarrel of theocracy against philoso- 1 2) aa) q pny: very body knows at the peut day; a par- a t alogism. It is with reason that they attack reason, ling to the very authority which they com- ine ey unde! ‘take to convict of impotence. A certain degree of rigour and co! asisteney has led the Theocratie school to reject, not this or that phi- losophical system, but the common spirit of all sys- tems, namely, f free reflection, that is to say, philoso- phy itself. A greater degree of rigour and consis- ot oe ener ern ey re tency would tae driven’ it to absolute scepticism, or restored it to philosophy. Without doubt, after the great x hovenients ot these e.modern times, which have p nance such various and such profound agi- tations in society.and.in. human thought, without sa- tisfving 1 Te oe hope of those who wish to sow p in a single day, the..appeal to the Middle APPS ‘and to blind. fait: would-nata rally-seduce.the weavied mind, by the allurement..of novelty. and the false ESDP SALSnCE Or..a.perfeet-consistency. Hence those philosophical abj rata the offspring of dis- couragement—and_despail es appeared to un- pra tised e eyes the signal for the defeat of philosophy and. for return to the ancl sa authority. But the sécret is now divulged. The innocence and peace of the Middle Ages are well understood ; an d the itself Pen te erent ate teneenes appeal to blind faith against reason by reason g only a misera ble Pa e a oe his truth a ares enceforth p a is convicted of bein The manifestation of tects philosophy ; and will arrest its deserters.2 DESTINY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY. Gr On the other hand, to leave philosophy in the state in which the nineteenth century received it from the preceding centuries, would be to make a use of reason that is by no means reasonable. It would be to con- sent to the decrial of philosophy by itself, and to place the most formidable weapons in the hands of the the- ocracy, and of its enemies, who observe the specta- cle. It would not be to combat the spirit of the age, but to remain behind it. In fact, the quality which most distinguishes us, which we seek with the great- est ardour; and cherish with the greatest pride, is uni- versality.. In every department, in politics, in the arts, in literature, we aspire to completeness; we re- fuse to be dazzled by a single aspect of things, how- ever brilliant it may be ; we wish to contemplate every aspect in succession, in order to form a true and per- fectidea of the objectin question. Here is the favour- able side. The evil consists~in the weakening or the absence of enthusiasm, and of great originality ; of great originality, I say, for of small originality, there is more than enough. In this state of the ge- geral mind, what can be the attraction of those aged systems, which modern philosophy produced at its birth, and which it has reproduced a hundred times within the last two centuries, without one of them having been able to sustain itselfr It is evident that no one of the systems which we have inherit- ed from the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, is absolutely false, since they were all able to exist; but it is equally evident also, that no one of these systems. is absolutely true, since they have all ceased to exist,—the contrary of absolute truth, which if it should appear, would at once enlighten, rally and subject the understandings of all. There is no one of these systems which has not been made the object of an overwhelming attack. There is no one which has not in some sort been pierced through and through, arraigned and convicted of intolerable ex- travagances. Let one of those principles be presented mich in its day has seduced so many excellent 3 snd TE Lf get A em ee 8 oyOe tae Tee Re eh ee SEO oe Oa DESTINY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 53 minds ; there is not a man who will not at once charge upon this principle the long array of conse- quences which it has successively produced, and which have betrayed and disgraced it. Do you pro- pose to explain intelligence by the celebrated prin- ciple of sensation, which formerly, in the hands of Locke and Condillae, exercised such an irresistible charm? At the present day, without any great outlay of sagacity or of logic, a little reading will suffice to point out behind this attractive principle its terrible consequences ; by the side of Locke, Mandeville and Collins; by the side of Condillac, @’Holbach and La- métrie, and all the Saturnalia of Materialism and of Atheism. Do you propose to explain all human knowledge by the mere force of the soul, of thought, and of its laws,—a very natural procedure. This noble Spiritualism has against-it-the equtvocal-repu- tation of the-sublime and chimerical abstractions, to which, so wise at_its starting-point, it has ended by conducting more than one. illustrious school, Are you disposed to make trial of doubt? The phan- tom of scepticism is there. Are you tempted to seek refuge in sentiment? But who will not an- nounce to you beforehand the tendency which pre- cipitates you towards mysticism? Thus, principles and consequences, there is nothing now unforeseen; hence, nothing which can deceive; for it cannot be denied, reason like the imagination, hardly wings its fight except after the Unknown and the Infinite. Now what system yet possesses this charm? It is the glory of human reason, that it submits only, I will not say to absolute truth, but to what it believes to be absolute truth; and at the present day, there is no mind of tolerable cultivation, which does not know very well, that all the systems presented by modern philosophy, are nothing, in the last analysis, but particular systems, which may indeed. contain a greater or less degree of truth, but which roe be ludicrous to propose or to receive as the complete and absolute truth. i NO. XXXII E veo4 DESTINY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY. The third course then remains. In the absence of fanaticism for this or that specific system, whick a tendency to enthusiasm and an incomplete view of things would perhaps produce, and of which we must almost despair with our present characteristics, both good and bad, J_see no resource left to philosophy, if it is unwilling to pass under the yoke of. theocracy, but equity, moderation, impartiality, wisdom. It is, [ confess, somewhat. of .a desperate resource, but for myself, I see no other. It would be strange if there were no longer any thing but common sense which could produce an effect on the imagination of men. But it is certain that every other charm appears to be worn out. All the parts of fanaticism in philosophy, all the parts which have been performed at once by injustice and by folly, that is to say again, all the in- ferior parts have been taken from the nineteenth cen- _tury by the preceding centuries ; it iscondemned to a. new part, the most humble in appearance, but the most elevated and important in reality—that of being just towards all systems, andthe dupe of none of them? of making them~all-the.object_of-study, and instead of following in the train of any-one, whatever it-may be, of enrolling them all under its own banner, and thus marching at their head to the discovery and the-eonquest of truth. This procedure—to reject no system and “to accept_none entirely, to neglect. this element-and to-take that,-to select in all what. ap- pears to be true and good, and consequently ever- lasting —this, in.a single word, is EcLEcricism. Tam not ignorant that this name alone arouses all the exclusive doctrines. But is it surprising that an opinion which appears a little novel should meet with lively opposition? Especially an opinion like Ke- lecticism. Propose then to the different parties, I beg of you, to lay aside-their tyrannical pretensions, in the service. of their common country. Every party will accuse-you_of being a bad citizen. Exclusive ~doetrines-are-in-philosophy what—parties are in the State. Felecticism tends to substitute for their vio- ™, wvhy Sysh a Soe Pod Nast tas its as ia DESTINY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY. lent and irrecular action-a-frm and--moderate-direc- tion, which shall-eall every foree-into-operation, but shall sacrifice to_none the interests of order, or the public good. Suppose, once more, that among those opinions which al] aspire to exclusive dominion, there was one, which, for more than half a century, had been in possession of universal and undisputed au- thority, accustomed to receive nothing but homage, and treated almost as if it were divine. Attempt to call in question the sovereignty of this proud idol; propose to it, as gently as possible, to come down from its throne, to enter the ring, to assert its rights for itself, in fine, to be only an opinion, like every other opinion, containing, like others, both what is true and what isfalse; accepted by someand rejected by others; in a word, propose to it to submit to the right of in- quiry, and you will soon hear a fine storm bursting about your ears. I had accordingly counted on a warm controversy; but, I had hoped, a serious and earnest one. Instead of objections, I have met only with declamations, with ecalumnies. In truth, I had believed that the Sensual school was stronger. Far trem wishing to weaker it;ifit-were-in my-power, I would rather fortify it, I would give it a serious repre- sentative, one worthy of it; for it comprises great truths ; it ought to hold an elevated rank in science 5 and I sincerely regard the deplorable state into which it has fallen among us as a real calamity. I heartily regret that M. de-Tracy, disarmed by—age, cannot enter.the-lists-with the new philosophy. It is not from the arsenal of Jesuitism that an adversary lik him would borrow his weapons. He would find them in the profound study of philosophical subjects, in the talent for analysis and the severe logic of which he has given so many proofs; and thus a truly honest and scientific controversy would be instituted. We are the first to demand this, for the general interests of science. Meanwhile, neither my friends nor myseli have hearts so feeble as to be retarded by the obsta- cles which are thrown in our path. We did not enter es JJ Sr) eur mosey i eee. et eee tee re ate aoe Vee 7 es56 DESTINY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY. our present career for the sake of frivolous applause, but to.serve the cause of philosophy. For my own part, it is along time since,—having studied and gone through with many different schools, attempting to ex- plain the attraction which by turns I found in each, and the credit of widely opposite systems, that of Con- dillac and that-of Reid for example, with the most enlightened minds and with the distinguished men, of whom I had been a pupil, M. Laromiguicre and M. Royer- Collard,—I discovered that the authority of these different systems proceeded from the fact that they all contain something which is true and good ; I suspected that in reality they were not all so com- pletely at war with each other as they pretended cod was convinced by degrees that, on certain conditions, they could ail go very well with each other; and I proposed. to. them a ireaty of peace on the basis of mutual.concessions.Sincethat.time I have used the word Eclecticism. If any are startled by it, I will gladly take back the word, provided they will allow me the thing. This word, however,—exact in itself, already employed by those who, in the course of ages, have had nearly the same idea, generally accepted in the language of the history of philosophy,—appears to me as good as any conventional expression can be, and I see no reason why it should be abandoned. As to the essential purpose of the enterprise itself, reflection and study have attached me to it more strongly than ever. Even the view of the fanaticism, to which an exclusive opinion may conduct, recom- mends moderation and wisdom more than ever in my eyes; and_it-is mydeliberate..wish, if not-my-hope, that Kclecticismimay-serve-as.a_cuide to the French philosophy -of.the nineteenth century. if this philosophy is to be Eclectic, it must also be sustained by the history of philosophy. In fact, it is evident that every Eclectic philosophy must necessa- rily have its foundation in a profound knowledge of 1€ ve it all the systems, of which it professes to combine the true and essential elements. Besides, what is theFlog He, Meet Pat Ye ine i an Sigg Cae Saye, Sy Ss Tat the ta de gatas ea Se Ey See 4 Se Se ee ag CPE A a DESTINY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. a7 whole history.of philosophy, but a perpetual lesson of Eclecticism ? What is taught by the history of philo- sophy, except that all systems are as old as itself, and inherent in the human mind, which produces them from the first moment, and reproduces them without end; that the wish to establish the dominion of any one exclusively. is.a vain attempt, which, if it should succeed, would prove the tomb of philosophy ; that consequently there is nothing to do, but to honour the human mind, to respect its liberty, to determine the laws which regulate it, and the fundamental sys- tems which grow out of these laws ; to improve con- tinually these different systems by means of each: other, without attempting to destroy any of them, by investigating and disengaging the everlasting portion of truth which each of them contains, and by which each of them _is made the brother of every other, and the legitimate offspring of the human mind. The_history of philosophy would have been sufficient by itself to produce Kelecticism, that_is_to—say, philosophical toleration; and as soon as this tolera- tion is brought to light, after the long reign. of fana- ticism, it necéssarily calls forth the desire and the “taste for a profound study of every system. OC . eC eee or . CROP) oh thats ey - a eS RS een S + ms * Tee A ab ra oe hk a ck ek be tk AST = cocek ote is “ ¢ ¥, sc Dh ee Daacnndbet ig AED Me pad dn ttm ticle lw jenn ne HO kK 2 why pa hen Minin o:0 sateen odes Neds a a| : i e aa ciety aeNOTES. NOTE A.—Pacz 39. SCHELLING’S OPINION OF COUSIN. THE cbscurity of style, which, to a greater or less degree, i found in the writings of the most eminent philosophers of Ger- many, and which repels so many from the study of their sys- tems, begins to be perceived and complained of by the Germans themselves. This is a good omen. It cannot be repeated too often, it cannot be insisted on too strongly, that truth is va- luable to the human mind only in proportion to its clearness ; and that all truth is intended to be the property of the world, not the monopoly of afew. The admirable reasonings of Kant on the immutability of moral distinctions, the absolute autho- rity of conscience, and the reality of disinterested virtue, are, in a great measure, lost to the world, by reason of the perplexed phraseology in which they are expressed. We can hardly be too grateful to students and writers, like Cousin and the school which he has formed, for their services in giving eurrency to ideas, in holding up to the popular mind in broad day-light, truths of universal interest and importance, which but for them would have remained loeked up in the iron abstractions of scholastic formulas. With regard to the merits of Cousin in this relation, we have a distinct confession from Schelling’s own lips, ‘* In his different visits to Germany,” he remarks, “‘ Cousin has won great personal esteem and friendship, not only among philosophers by profession, but among the German scholars in general. The peculiar cireumstance, however, which gives the Germans a permanent interest in his labours is, that he, toge- ther with the able and profoundly learned Guizot and a few others, was the first, after the restoration of peace from the wars of the Revolution, to awaken the attention of his country- men to German science and literature. Cousin aceomplished this particularly in regard to German philosophy. _ Whoever among us should imagine that the advantage of this is altoge- ther on the side of the French, would betray a singular nar- rowness. For it is now pretty generally acknowledged, that in point of a simple, lucid, and well-considered mode of exhibit- ing scientific subjects, we have something to learn from our Western neighbours. But style, if any value at all be ascribed o9 nepal sochetnksli+ deyettben dees er arr60 NOTES. to it, always reacts on thought, on the subject-matter of dis- cussion. ‘The Germans have so long philosophized merely among themselves, that they have been gradually departing more and more from what is universally intelligible, both in thought and expression, and the degree of this departure has at length been almost assumed as the standard of philosophical superiority. It is hardly necessary to adduce examples. As families, which, avoiding the general intercourse of society, live altogether with each other, at last, among other disagreeable peculiarities, come to use a singular phraseology, intelligible to none but themselves; so the Germans have proceeded in philo- sophy; and, as after many ineffectual attempts to spread the philosophy of Kant, beyond the limits of their country, they have renounced the idea of making themselves intelligible to other nations, they have been led also to regard philosophy as something existing for themselves alone, without considering that the original purpose of all philosophy,—which is never to be lost sight of, though it has been so often unsuccessful,—is to arrive at universal intelligibility. It certainly does not fol- low from this, that works of thought are to be judged of as exercises of style; but it does follow unquestionably that a philosophy, whose essential doctrines cannot be made compre- hensible to every cultivated nation, and accessible to all lan- guages, for that reason atone, cannot be the true and universal philosophy. The interest accordingly, which is manifested by foreign nations in German philosophy, cannot fail to exert a favourable influence upon that. The philosophical writer, who some ten years ago could not lay aside the scholastic language and forms which he had once assumed, without prejudice to his reputation as a scientific man, will more easily free himself from this restraint. He will seek for profoundness in his thoughts; and at least, a total incapacity and unskilfulness of expression, will not be considered, as has been the case, a to- ken of philosophical inspiration. ‘* Cousin has been reproached with his love for German phi- losophy, as an anti-national tendency; but, on the contrary, he has remained true to that national character, of which he says, that it makes an absolute point of purity, precision, and clear- ness of connexion. If any man is called to give to. France. a correct notion of the progress and the historical development of modern philosophy, it is Cousin, who combines,..in an. emi- nent degree, in himself,and_ has displayed through his whole scientific career, the indefatigable research, the acuteness, the moderation, the honourable impartiality, and in short, all the peculiar qualities. which forma philosophical historian of phi- losophy.””? 1 See Victor Cousin tiber franzosische und deutsche Philosophie, Von Dr. HuBeRT Beckers, Vorrede von SCHELLING, pp. iii.—v. xxviii. Stutt- gart und Tiibingen, 1834, 0NOTES. NOTE B.—Pace 46. PRESIDENT HOPKINS ON NATURAL THEOLOGY. Tue article here alluded to is entitled «Ar. gument from Nature, for the Divine Existence,” and is from the pen of the Rey . Mark Hopkins, President of Williams College. Its purpose ae discuss the e place which is held by the ar gument from design, as exhibited in external na ture, in producing the belief of a God in mankind at lar ge; and also the real import and logical validity of that arg acne It by no means follows, the writer maintains, that because the argument from design is generally stated as the formal proof of the being of a God, it is therefore the real ground of our belief; for it often pilin that we are fully convinced of a truth Gurcely es, and yet, when we would convinee others, we are obl liged to adduce a arguments, and in- ent media of proof entirely differ rent from those on which our own conviction rests. It is, moreoy er, a fact that the universal] belief in God is altogether disproportioned to the pere eon of design in the material universe. In the inf ancy of socie in the early stages of the civilization of ev ery country, the opera- tions of nature are obscure and perplexing. Design is often concealed. It is still oftener seen but indi istinetly, a unity of design is not seen at all. Yet a faith in God, in some form or other, is every where displayed. In like manner, the great import tance of this faith to the highest interests of our race, makes it Boe that it was not intended to be entirely de- pendent on the varying process of induction from outwa urd pre- mises. We may suppose that religion, which necessaril y in- volves the idea of God, must have its roots in the very founda- tion and elements of the soul of man. It is only on this sup- position that the common definition of man as a rel igious being can be sustained. This view is confirmed by a nee examination of the argu- ment from design. Such an examination forces us to the con- clusion, in the opinion of President Hopkins, that correct, logi- eal accuracy does not compel the deduction of a Be eing pos- sessing the highest attributes of intelligence,—that the ar- sument from design falls short of bei ing a strict proof of the ex- istence of a personal God. But if this argument be not logi- cally valid, as this writer shows, and as Kant had prey) iously shown, there is another argument, according to his theory, which may be pressed with perfect success. This is deriv ed fom n th nature of the human soul. The soul exhibits effects o dif. ferent character from any that are found in the material universe. These are spontaneous activity , thought, free-will, reason, con- science. The existence of a soul, endowed with these ats butes, is a direct proof, reasoning from ett rect to ealise, OLA creative Mind, and is indeed the only eondition on which the 6] rs62 NOTES. conception of such a mind can be formed, or. the knowledge of it brought to light. Having thus vérified our belief in the ex- istence of the Father of Spirits, we are led to the conviction, from the adaptation of the body to the mind, and their mutual action on each other, that one being was the Creator of both, and we again perceive the reality of God, as the Author of na- ture. ‘* We have therefore, as the source of all things, as the principle of unity in all things, instead of a blind, unconscious principle, which general laws would seem to indicate, and which men call nature, or by whatever name pleases them, one, free, all-pervading, all-inspecting, all-comprehending, personal God.” The above meagre sketch does little justice to an argument which is carried out by the author with a sufficient complete- ness of detail and great beauty of illustration. Allowing the principles which are established by a sound, spiritual philoso- phy, I know not how its force and conclusiveness can be invali- dated. It coincides, in the main, with the process of reasoning by which Cousin infers the Absolute Causality, or Free-Will of God, from the existence of those attributes, in a relative character, in the human soul; and also the moral and intellec- tual attributes of God, from a view of analogous attributes in man. The only thing wanting, as it seems to me, in the argu- ment of President Hopkins, is the legitimation of our reasoning from the Finite in ourselves to the Infinite in God. With this omission, it presents a vulnerable side to the Materialist, who contends that the soul itself, with all its attributes, is the result of organization ; and also to the Idealist, who should be disposed to maintain that the soul itself is the Absolute Existence, and implies no objective reality corresponding to the inward phe- nomena of which we are conscious. The true basis of our be- lief in God must be found, in the last analysis, in the two prin- ciples, that our own existence is relative, limited, finite, and that we are compelled, by the necessity of our reason, to admit an absolute, perfect, and infinite existence. This view is re- peatedly unfolded by Cousin, and indeed forms the principal element in his philosophical system, as may be seen in the pre- sent work. With the addition of these principles, the argument of Pre- sident Hopkins furnishes us with a conclusive vindication of the great, fundamental belief of humanity. If I mistake not, its value and importance will be more highly estimated by future inquirers, than it has yet been, as far as I am informed, among our philosophical theologians. The manner in which it is ex- hibited in the article referred to, indicates a mind of very rare analytical skill, and familiarity with the precise bearing of the various points, which it undertakes to set in order. It can searcely fail to meet with the attention which it deserves from the student of metaphysics, in proportion as that science is cul- tivated with freedom and earnestness. 62 ES bbw. by ae Ereee ee ee ee ee Mk eT Ke ok Tel id Ma OR Ue SE SESS Tatas Ye Se a ae Wir Oi Sion Se Sn hae gat ae oe Sar Yo Seg hg hy Sais Bg se oad Nal se is eg eae eek EST ee eat a 6 oe EXPOSITION ECLECTICISM. BY M. VICTOR COUSIN, PEER OF FRANCE, MEMBER OF THE INSTITUTE, AND OF THE COUNCIL O# PUBLIC INSTRUCTION, AND DIRECTOR OF THE NORMAL SCHOOLS, TRANSLATED FROM THE FRENCH, WITH CRITICAL NOTICES, BY GEORGE RIPLEY. EDINBURGH: THOMAS CLARK, 38. GEORGE STREET; LONDON—HAMILTON, ADAMS & CO.; DUBLIN—CURKY & CQ, MDCCCXXXIX. er gts he Dak k pac CS a Om Te es ak yews SOR a a OC fy 4 ee kk et ta eet he eo wr aon wale: . : : hon Mead ig ie bonsinnberinphbendot botc cin} x boc o¥s HL rn ee Pe a eee tr :} 2 \y i ‘ i p a b, ei hea/ ESE SRR SS ae Tg Se Ma a SY yr, 8 BSE ROM ee SS EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM’ TuEse fragments are now reprinted just as they appeared in 1826, with some corrections, which it is not important to indicate. Jt seemed to me proper that this work, if I may give the name to a collec- tion of detached pieces, should preserve its original character, the defects and the merits with which it was at first presented to the public. The Preface to these Fragments was all that de- served any considerable attention. It has met with it far beyond my expectation. Received in Germany with indulgence, it found an able interpreter in that country.2. A translation possessing an exactness which discovers a mind familiar with such subjects, made it known in the North of Italy.2 It even 1 Preface to “* Philosophical Fragments,’’ Second Edition. 1833. _2-Ffeligion und Philosophie in Frankreich, von F. W. Carove, Dr. der Philosophie. Géitingen, 1827, See anaccount of this translation and of the notes inthe Globe, 9 March 1800. 3 Manuale di Filosofia, di A. MaTHLA, traduzione di tedes- co con un saggio della nuovo Filosofia francese del signor Vou- sin. Lugano, 1829. : NO. XXXIII. B 69 Vos d ate Pe ree yenee on em hye wee havens? Ml a rye bi Bd refed! > Si se avedheednad teat igs EEF Ae once g BO ag 2 hematiteEXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. excited some interest in England ; and I was quite surprised to find that it had attracted the attention of transatlantic criticism! In France, it has been made the subject of a controversy which was not without use to the cause of philosophy. I do not now pro- pose, after the lapse of six years, to revive this con- troversy, of which the details are deservedly forgot- ten; I would merely say a few words in regard to it, which may not be out of place in the present state of things. The Preface to these Fragments was intended to give an idea of the general system, to which they re- late ; it could only indicate the system, but it at least described all its elements in their connexion and their harmony. The four pointsin this rapid sketch to which all the others may be referred are as follows: I. Method. II. Application of method to that part of philo- sophy, which method itself places at the head of the others, namely, psychology. iil. Passage from psychology to ontology and to the higher metaphysics. IV. General views on the history of philosophy. I. METHOD. I. Here, as elsewhere, as every where, as always, I declare for that method, which places the point of departure for all sound philosophy in the study of human nature, and consequently in observation, and which then appeals to induction and to reasoning, in order to obtain from observation all the consequences which it involves. We are deceived when we Say that true philosophy is a science of facts, unless we add that it is also a science of reasoning. It rests on : North American Review, No. LXIV. July, 1829. This article is by Mr. EVEREr T, ex-minister of the United States in Spain. 66 PSPS oP eS a> < DOR haem gt ft ae Aa ateh te ete Se oe Tal a EL A Uh PE ke 8 ee Sh be he eh eh eR ee a ‘ Mt EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. observation ; but it has no other lin 1its than those of reason itself, just as physical science starts from ob- servation, but does not ae with it, and rises by calculation to the general laws of nature, andto the system of the world. Now reasoning is in philoso- phy what calculation is in physical science; for after all, calculation is nothing but reasoning in its most simple form. Ca leulation is not a mysterious power ; it is the power of human reasoning itself; its eculiar character consists entirely in its language. Philosophy abdicates, it renounces its true end which is the understanding and the explanation of all things by the legitimate e nployment of our faculties, when it renounces the unlimited employment of rea- son; and, on the other hand, it falls into error, and eads reason itself into error, when it employs it at random, instead of placing it at the service of facts, which iN been scrupulously observed and rigo- rously classed. It is thus exposed to two perils; first, anill-regulated flight, which, disdaining obser ae going through it too rapidly, shoots i nto adventurou inducti Ons 5 “and secondly, a pusi a nimM0Us dale which, in spite of our deepest cravings and our most imperious instincts, chains itself down to the poverty of a barren observation. To hmit eee to 4 observation Hs whether we know it or not, to place it in the path to scepticism; to neglect abet vation, is to throw it into the ways ol hypothesis. Scepti- ism and oe esis,—tnese are the two rocks to which phi losophy 1 s exposed. The true method avoids them both. It does not be tthe end, it does ne end at the beginning. | 9 reasoning, but it supports it on sutficie for precisely in proportion to the value of © tion, will be the subsequent v Thus, while it preserves the right | employment of the resources oi intelligence, — phy cannot attach itself to observation with om care, and, like true physical science, 1f cannot too ok opnises no limits it observati hele ao ~~ nt bow) 2 se ee! * Co al ee _ ~~ ere et ees se oo I A re hd Ps Saha geay te Sea ee ne LS aA <9 ey » E Ponte Ov Cecil eatinctiviee ine eageriar’ ah pea red6 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. loudly proclaim observation, as its necessary point ot departure In that case, it is distinguished from physical science only by the nature of the phenomena which it observes. The peculiar phenomena of physical science are those of external nature, of that vast world of which man forms so small a part. The peculiar phenomena of philosophy are those of that other world, which every man bears within himself, and which he perceives by the aid of the inward light which is called consciousness, as he perceives the former by the senses. The phenomena of the inward world appear and disappear so rapidly, that conscious- ness perceives them, and loses sight of them almost at the same time. Itis not then sufficient to observe them transiently, and while they are passing over that changing scene; we must retain them as long as possible by attention. We may do even still more. We may call up a phenomenon from the bosom of the night into which it has vanished, summon it again to memory, and reproduce it in our minds for the sake of contemplating it at our ease; we may recall one part of it rather than another, leave the latter in the shade, so as to bring the former into view, vary the aspects in order to go through them all, and to embrace every side of the object; this is the office of reflection. Reflection is to consciousness what artificial instru- ments are to the senses. It is not sufficient to listen to nature, we must interrogate it; it is not enough to observe, we must experiment. Experience has always the same conditions and the same rules, to whatever object it be applied ; and it is by following these rules, that we arrive at exact classifications, no less in the science of man than in that of nature. these classifications contain all the primary part of philosophy, that which is at the head of all the other parts, and which,—on account of its peculiar subject, humanity, the human soul,—is called in the schools, ye Orey The science of man, psychology, is 68ae tek Tages og Cy ae Sata Nor Soe Sp ty Pts Pasi Sia has Waka EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. assuredly not the whole of philosophy, but it is the foundation of it. This point is one of the highest importance, for it is decisive of all the rest, and of the character of the entire system. It is to establish this point that I have consumed, not I hope without some fruit, the first years of my teaching. I have brought it forward on every occasion, and have built upon it, as upon a demonstrated fact, as upon a truth which is henceforth placed beyond the need of dis- cussion. It has been believed that it should yet be insisted on after me; and very justly, for in philoso- phy we cannot too much insist on the true method, provided that we do not at length make a common- place of it, in which we rest ourselves and confine others. I repeat it then, if psychology is not the limit of philosophy, it is the basis of it; and by this principle, which comprises so many others, the general charac- ter of my philosophical undertaking is strongly marked with the spirit of modern philosophy, which, since Descartes and Locke, admits no method but that of experience, and places the science of human nature at the head of philosophical science ; it con- nects itself still more closely with the philosophy of the eighteenth century, which it continues, while it modifies it; and separates itself, on the contrary, from the new German philosophy. . This philosophy, aspiring to reproduce in its con- ception the very order of things, commences with the Being of beings, so that it may afterwards descend through all degrees of existence till it comes to man, and to the various faculties with which he is en- dowed: it arrives at psychology, by ontology, by metaphysics and physics combined. And certainly, for my own part also, I am convinced that in the universal order, man is nothing but a result, the sum- mary of all that precedes, and that the root ony chology is to be found, at the bottom, 1n ontology. But how do I know this? How have I learned it ¢ : ry dieting Because, having made a study of man, having ie Dd ry Fr oe oD 5m, cee Mow Sh a Ph Hath Ae: , rn peer rete tas ee ee rate wren Y ee Sestinaeianed Pay! ila AUS. a ~ A 5 a eee ed 57 oeeed eS 5 Bi Sy her ess eS ES EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 15 can perceive its own mistakes, correct itself when it is deceived, restore itself when it is in error, call it- self to account, and pronounce upon itself the sen- tence of acquittal or of condemnation. And we must not imagine that reason waits for slow developments before it presents to man this threefold knowledge of himself, of the world, and of God; on the contrary, this threefold knowledge is given to us entirely in each of its parts, and even in every fact of conscious- ness, in the first as well as in the last. It is still] psy- chology which here explains ontology, but a psycho- logy to which only profound reflection can attain. Can there be a single fact of consciousness with- out a certain degree of attention? Let attention be weakened or entirely destroyed, and our thoughts become confused, they are gradually dissipated in obscure reveries which soon vanish of themselves, and are for us as if they were not. Even the per- ceptions of the senses are blunted by want of atten- tion, and degenerate into merely organic impressions. The organ is struck, often perhaps with force; but the mind being elsewhere, does not perceive the im- pression; there is no sensation; there is no con- sciousness. Attention therefore is the condition of all consciousness. Now is not every act: of attention more or less voluntary’? And is not every voluntary act charac- terized by the circumstance that we consider our- selves as the cause of it? And is it not this cause whose effects vary while it remains the same itself,— is it not this power which is revealed to us only by its acts, but which is distinguished from its acts and which its acts do not exhaust,—is it not, I say, this cause, this force, which we eall I, me, our individua- lity, our personality,—that personality of which we never doubt, which we never confound with any other, because we never refer to any other those vo- Juntary acts which give us the inward feeling, the immoveable conviction of its reality ? : The me is then revealed to us in the character s / eo 9 ee rer ony ain ‘ a A kh As an #0 EE BR gh sete Hs ae Hatin BAN Uae, net mi s . ae 7 A ce a a Fs ong Mar OVO TRY Yc a eal emia ae ‘ e.ecdedsneet 9h aeenkeee ee het ‘GN } sere ete ee teaer caer Datta Ce ee el Mn Chiara 16 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. cause, of force. But can this force, this cause which we are, do every thing which it wishes? Does it meet with no obstacles? It meets with them of all kinds, at every moment. A sense of our feebleness is constantly united with that of our power. A thou- sand impressions are at all times made upon us; take away attention and they do not come to our con- sciousness; let attention be applied to them, the phe- nomenon of sensation begins. Here then, at the same time that I refer the act of attention to myself, as its cause, I cannot, for the same reason, refer to myself the sensation to which attention has been applied; I cannot do this, but I cannot avoid referring it to some cause, to a cause necessarily other than myself, that is to say, to an exteral cause, and to an external cause whose existence is no less certain to me than my own existence, since the phenomenon which sug- gests it to me is no less certain than the phenomenon which suggested my own, and both the phenomena are presented to me with each other. We have here then two kinds of distinet causes. The one personal, placed in the very centre of con- sciousness—the other external, and beyond the sphere of consciousness. The cause which we are is evi- dently limited, imperfect, finite, since it constantly meets with bounds and obstacles among the variety of causes to which we necessarily refer the phenomena that we do not produee—the phenomena purely affec- tive, and not voluntary. On the other hand, these causes themselves are limited and finite, since we resist them to a certain degree as they resist us, we limit their action as they limit ours, and they also nutually limit each other. It is reason which reveals tous these two kinds of causes. It is reason, which, developing itself in our consciousness, and perceiving there at the same time attention and sensation, as soon as these two simultaneous phenomena are per- ceived, suggests to us immediately two kinds of dis- tinct causes, but correlative and mutually limited, to which they must be referred. But does reason stop 78Le CTR ee 9 Ok Oe as te At SS SOS Te tae a See Sas ie Wet eG Sg ae ara at cae Ya i eT ed ee ae EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. U7 ALU C c it is a fact, moreover, with this? B y no means. 1 ae Re that as soon as the notion of finite and limited causes is given, we cannot but conceive of a superior cause infinite a iH absolute, which is itself the first and ast cause of all others. Che internal and personal cause and external causes are incont testably causes in rela- tion to their own LL but the same reason which neveals them to us as causes, reveals them as lin imited and relative causes, and thus prevents us from stop. ping with them as causes Sica to clip ined Iirass and compels us to refer them to a supreme cause, which has ae them and which sustains them; which is in relation to them what they are in relation to the e phe- nomena that are peculiar to them; and which, as itis the Cause of all causes, and the Being of alt beings, is sufficient in itself, and sufficient to reason, which seeks and which finds nothing Peron: Let this fundamental point ‘be well considered. Its: consequences are of the mck importance. As the notion of the me is that of the cause to which we refer at phenomena of volition, so the notion of the eis contained entirely in that of the cause of Se a and involuntary phenomena. Now, as the being which we are and the external w one d are nothing but causes, it follows that the Being of | beings to which we refer them is e¢ jually revealed to us in the character of cause. God exists for us only in the relation of cause; without this, reason would no refer to him either humanity or the world. He is ab- solute substance only inasmuch as he is absolute cause, and his essence consists precisely in his crea- tive power. I snould here require a volume in order to describe completely and to place in a clear light the manner in which reason elevates us to the abso- lute cause, after having revealed to us the duality of the personal cause, and of external causes. I merely sum up in a few lines the long researches, of which the remains are to be seen in these Mragments, and the course in the Preface. It is only this course which 1 have wished to recall. ° cS poe io ae rd naa ok AN os Aa) <) Sas osc maMarpes.l S eo yp eenan en * Py18 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. Here is no hypothesis. We need only enter with- in our consciousness,—to a considerable depth it is true,—in order to find every thing which has been stated; for once more to sum up this summary, there is not a single fact of consciousness possible without the me; on the other hand, the me cannot know it- self without knowing the not-me; neither the one nor the other can be known with the reciprocal limitation which characterizes them, without the conception more or less distinct of an infinite and absolute Being, to which they must be referred. These three ideas of the me or of the free personality, of the not-me or of nature, of their absolute cause, of their substance, or of God, are intimately connected with each other, and compose one and the same fact of consciousness, the elements of which are inseparable. ‘There is not 9, man in the world who does not bear this fact, in all its parts, within his consciousness. Hence the natu- ral and permanent faith of the human race. But every man does not give an account to himself of what he knows. To know, without giving an account of our knowledge to ourselves; to know, and to give an account of our knowledge to ourselves,— this is the only possible difference between man and man, be- tween the people and the philosopher. In the one, reason is altogether spontaneous; it seizes at first upon its objects; but without returning upon itself and demanding an account of its procedure; in the other, reflection is added to reason; but this reflec- tion, in its most profound investigations, cannot add to natural reason, a single element which it does not already possess; it can add to it nothing but the knowledge of itself. Again, I say, reflection well- directed ; for if it be ill-directed, it does not compre- hend natural reason in all its parts; it leaves out some element, and repairs its mutilations only by ar- bitrary inventions. First, to omit, then to invent; this is the common vice of almost all systems of phi- losophy. The office of philosophy is to reproduce in its scientific formulas the pure faith of the human 50pp ee nee Ty te ee ot ok coe ag tu et Uh Pek Se Sa te eae y Ba ag Eb eg Sere ig rs 5 ts RA LA EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 19 race; nothing less than this faith; nothing more than this faith; this faith alone, but this faith in all its parts. Its peculiar characteristic is to build ontology on psychology, to pass from one to the other by the aid of a faculty, which is both psychological and on- tological, subjective and objective at once; which appears in us without properly belonging to us; which enlightens the shepherd as well as the philo- sopher; which is wanting to no one, and is sufficient for all. This faculty is reason, which from the bosom of consciousness extends to the Infinite and reaches at length to the Being of beings. A system so simple in its processes and its results, which, starting with the popular method of the age, discovers with it all the great elements of the eternal faith of the human race, and reconstructs positive doctrines with no other instrument than reason, could not fail to shock each of the two schools, into which, with us, philosophy is divided, like every thing else ; I mean the Sensual school and the Theological school, one of which chains down the reason within the li- mits of the phenomena of sense, while the other pro- scribes it altogether, and declares it incapable of attaining the truth. From the controversy of the Sensual school against the Fragments, I will take the two or three following arguments, because they have since been loudly re- peated, and have become in relation to me as the common-place of Sensualism. 1. There is a contradiction between the method of observation and of inducticn announced in the Pre- face and its systematic applications; for when we start from consciousness, we cannot legitimately ar- rive at ontology, In reply to this, I observe, that if we find in con- sciousness a faculty, the characteristic of which is that it is universal and absolute, the authority of this faculty is not confined to the limits of consciousness, because it falls within its sphere; otherwise Sen- sualism could not pass beyond those limits; for that NO, XXXIII. C 81 Ra Bans nape penta eres dew ttbmen sen oes + 4% a 5 bMigth | M er oaen 4 A i ss rh eat OR Rien er etree LT ed FONT SEM Tne = Fcpmeinirnt une eens Sk PURO RCIOSNS wah TO EEO Oe eee ns he wren on ae De seman Ft SAARC a LI —ae Soe te tke a ee aa mr na erhks hake hd W Pata peer ere i eee roe! Ao e hese te) pet eee ea eae: Weewrer ne os ew20 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. also starts from a fact given by consciousness, man. ONy sensation; and it is by means of this fact, that it knows by. consciousness, t that it arrives by reasoning the use of which again is attested to it by eonsoious- ness, at the knowledge of ou itward existence, that is to say, a t ontology. But the objection is not valid either against Sensualism or again ee m ea In fact, consciousness is nerely a witness. ‘The faculties of which it testifies do not cease, on ack oe to have their peculiar patient and their legitimate extent, which it is requisite to measure and ascertain; now sensation by itself is destitute of all light, and does not even know itself, while reason knows itself and knows all the rest, and goes beyond the sphere of the me; because it does not belong to the me. . This system, which pretends to restore Spiritu- a by establishing it on the basis of expemenee, . nothing, after all, in its last conclusions, but the cele- brated § system of Spinoza and the Eleatics, a ew, which completely destroys the received notion of God and of Providence. It is in reply to this accusation, which has found o many aloes even be syond the Sensual school, that have written a special dissertation on the Eleatic school, in which I fully explain myself, on the sub- ject of Pantheism, its philosophical and historical origin, the pruicipie of its errors, and also on that element in it which may be called good and even useful, Pantheism, properly speaking, is the ascribing of Divinity to the All, the grand Whole considered as God, the Universe-God of the greater part of my adversaries, of Saint Simon, for exam) Ble. It is in its essence a kind of genuine he sm, but with which qQ | ca S r i may be combined, as has been done, if not by Saint Simon, at least by his school, a certain religious i bs y nee to the ie world, without the sli htest 10se ideas of the Good and the Beautiful, of ae Teaite and of Unity, which belong only to the Supreme Cause, and are not to be met with in the 82wee Nae PM py ag eet Shen) Peat hee Rhy ed the OR ER Mh ae Yak Se ay Say See Say Son Sa es tae ee Ps EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 21 world, except in so far as, a every effect, it is the manifestation of all the powers aoe in the cause. he system opposed to Pantheism is that of absolute Unity, so far superior and bl or to the world, as to be foreign to it, and to make it impossible to compre- hend how this unity could ever depart from itself, and how from a princij ple like this, the vast Universe, with the variety of its forces anc phenomena, could proceed. This latter system is the abuse of meta- physical abstraction, as the former is the abuse of an enthusiastic contemplation of nature, retained, some- times uncons clously, in the bonds of the senses and the imagination. These two 5 Mineiies are more natu- ral than one would suppose, who was ignorant of the hi ance ot philosophy, or who had not himself passed through the different states of mind which produce them both. As a general rule, every naturalist — S wl uard against the former, and every metaphysici la nst the latter. The perfection, but at the same Ne Bache OS CSO tim e, = 1e difficulty, is not ? lose the sense of nature in the meditations of the school, and, in oe e presence of nature, to ascend, in cp irit and in trut th, to the in- visible principle, which is at once ek Se 8k * Ww acts bc! Lk A ia ae Ye eeeetn Sn) © Senn ier Sere we bs to BH aes oF manifested and : Marge laa kK ae a 1. I ¥ of } U Ty e concealed by the i set sing harmony of the Universe. é Would it be thought possible that it is the Sensual Z school which brings against a any one the accusation 5 of Pa — which brings it against myse elf? To 2 Ur pt ae emer 1 v4 eee accuse me of Pantheism, is to accuse me of confound- Ine th a At Q £ ite Cansca with the T) L ing the First, Absolute, Infinite Cause with the ue verse, that is to say, with the two relat ea a of the me and the not-me, of wiih ahi Bats and t the evident pears rare the foundat ~ a oe o a - b= = an © ot © oh S fq?) hy wv I jus) ; © x NS) 28 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. which starts precisely from the divorce of faith and reason was too much opposed to the results I had arrived at, to detain me long, or even to interest me, and I was, accordingly, strongly impressed only by the new philosophy. It yet divided and excited Ger- many, as at the time of its original appearance. Every school rung with the name of Schelling ; it was here celebrated, there almost caluminated, every where arousing that passionate interest, that concert ot glowing panegyrics and stormy attacks, which we call glory. I did not see Schelling at that time; but in his plaee, I accidentally, and without seeking it, met with Hegel at Heidleberg. I began with him, and with him I also ended in Germany. At that time, Hegel was far from being the cele- brated man that I have since found at Berlin, draw- ing all eyes upon himself, and at the head of a large and enthusiastic school. Hegel as yet had no repu- tation but that of a distinguished disciple of Schelling. He had published some books which were little read; and his teaching had hardly begun to make him better known. The Encyclopedia of the Philosophi- eal Sciences appeared just then, and I had one of the first copies. It wasa book all bristling with formulas of a sufficiently scholastic appearance, and written in a style by no means lucid, particularly for me. Hegel knew but little more French than I did Ger- man; and, buried in his studies, as yet uncertain of himself and of his reputation, he scarcely saw any body, and, to tell the truth, his personal qualities were not uncommonly attractive. I cannot under- stand how an obscure young man should have suc- ceeded in interesting him, butat theend ofanhour, we were on the best possible terms ; and to the last moment, our friendship, though often tried, was never impaired. From our first conversation, I divined what he was, I comprehended his whole reach, I felt that | was in the presence of a superior man; and when | continued my Journey from Heidleberg into ot! her parts of Germany, I proclaimed him wherever [| went, I pro- 90 yeastGrete ete te Ya ee ie Me Ue OE OR Sea a Si Sa ar Yar Sar age hg ey Shay Set Nag Ta i ie ha OS ae ee ge ae ee iy eat ge ety ca te ty ing a, Cok ee eS EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 99 phesied him, as ne we ne 5 and upon my return to France, I said to EY; friends ; gentlemen, I have see aman of aenane "Phe | impression Ww hich Hegel left upon me, was profound, but indistinct. The follow- ing year I went to Munich to seek out the author of the system himself. No two men can resemble each other lessthan did the disciple and the master. Hegel scar ely let drop some rare and’ profound words, a little enigmatical ; his diction strong but embarrassed; his countenance immova ible ; his brow covered with clouds, seemed the image of thought returning on itself. Schelling, on the other ha ind, iS thought in development ; his langua age, like his look, is full of fire and animation; he is natt iraliy eloquent; I passed a whole month with him and Jacobi at Mu- nich, in 1818, and there, for the first time, began to oe a a little more clearly into the Philosophy of Nature. Vhat me nis this philosophy? Can I describe it iere in a few words? Is it possible to give even the light a intelligible idea of it to those who have not assed through a ‘all the antecedents of this philosophy, ough all the degrees of the school of Kant? The ie resale of the philosophy « of Kant was the system of Fichte, and the last result of the e system of Fichte was the mu supposed, or rather supposing itself, as the sole principle. Having arrived at this extremity, it was necessary that the ina philosophy should either depart from it or perish. alka is the man who took it from the lepemimilina! of a psychology, at once ideal and sceptical, in order to restore it to re ality and life. Especially he vindicated the rights of the external world, of nature ; and it is from this circum- stance that his philosophy derives its name. In the ayetems of Kant and oh Fichte, all abso — and sub- stantial existence is merely an hypothesis, with no other fle than the want of the yenwe me, which admits it in order to satisfy itself. Schelling, in order to oopeee from the Relative and Subjective, takes his stand at once in the Objective. In his opi- nion, philosophy, if it wishes for substant ial eros J fomxeed Dm ea BES bah SN, GR MD i" Sere ra hath at AI heh eras ty Seer nya ohh hire or rt ene aLset hay henna area ster rolesheabiedanis hat Ti © 30 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. must leave psychology and dialectics, the me as well as the not-me, and without embarrassing itself with the objections of scepticism, rise at first even to the Absolute Being, the common substance and the com- mon ideal of the me and the not-me, which does not relate exclusively either to the one or the other, but which comprehends them both, and forms their iden- tity. This absolute identity of the me-and the not-me, of man and nature, is God. _It follows from this that God isin nature,_as well_asin- man. It follows more- over that this nature possesses in itself no less value than man, that it has its own truth no less than he, since it exists on the same ground, and that it must needs resemble him, since it is derived from the same principle; their only difference being that of con- sciousness and non-consciousness. On the other hand, God cannot be less in humanity than in nature; if nature, in some sense, is as rational as the spirit of man, the spirit of man must have laws as necessary as those of nature ; so that the world of humanity is as regularly constructed as the external world. Now the world of humanity is manifested in history ; history themtiasits laws; it forms then, in its different epochs, and in its apparent _abberrations, an harmonious SyS- tem,just as the external world is-one in the diversity of its phenomena. ~ F¥ronithese twofold consequences, and from their common principle, proceeds the high importance of historical studies and of the physical sciences. Hence, for the first time, Idealism intro- duced into the physical sciences, and Realism into history ; the two departments of philosophy hitherto enemies, psychology and physics, at length recon- ciled; an admirable sentiment composed at once of reason and of life, a sublime spirit of poetry spread through the whole sphere of philosophy ; and erown- ing all, the idea of God every where present, and forming, for the entire system, its principle and its light. The first years of the nineteenth century saw the appearance of this great system. Europe owes it to O oO faloe ee eae hee had et Rare Ee oh Me ls Ui SE SOR So Tae tae Na tak Ni tas Ca Sar Gy, 2 Man Sin re OM aegis he ER EOE IE OTe HY Na Tid Hag is Ba Oe, Me ng he ha Nita nk) a egg eM rea EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICisSM. ol Germany, and Germany to Schelling. This system is the truth; for it is the most complete expression of entire reality, of universal existence. Schelline brought this system into the world: but he left it filled with all manner of imperfections and defects. Hegel, coming after Schelling, belongs to his school. He is entitled to a separate place in it, not only for developing and enriching the system, but for giving it in many respects a new aspect. The admirers of Heégel-consider him as the Aristotle of a second Plato; the exclusive partisans of Schelling see in him only the Wolf of another Leibnitz. However it may be with these rather arrogant comparisons, no one can deny that the master is gifted with the talent of powerful invention, and the disciple with that of profound reflection. Hegel has borrowed much from Schelling. JI, far more feeble than either, have borrowed from both. It is folly to reproach me with it; and certainly no wonderful humility in me to acknowledge it. It is more than twelve years since, in the dedication of my edition of the Com- mentary of Proclus on the Parmenides, to Schelling and Hegel, I publicly called them both my masters and my. friends,-and—theleaders.of the philosophy of the present age. Ii is delightful to me to renew this homage here; and I can never repeat it enough to do justice to my sincere admiration and my heart- felt friendship. I thank God my soul is not so con- stituted as ever to be embarrassed by gratitude. But while I love to announce the resemblance which con- nects the philosophy I profess, with that. of these two great masters, I owe it also to truth to avow that I am separated from them by fundamental differences, even in spite of myself. A Scottish critic, whose eru- dition equals his sagacity, and who will certainly not be accused of flattery towards .me,has.setforth-these differenees*—TI should blush to insist upon them here. But Teannot help alluding to the first and the most 1 Sir Witi1aM Hamixtton. Edinburgh Review, No. XCIX. 93 Sg eS er tpt be? eS32 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. fruitful_of_all, that of method. As I have already said, my two-illustrious Tiends take their-stand-at once on the height of speculation; while T commence withéxperienee.” In order to avoid the subjective character of the inductions which proceed fro m an imperfect psychology, they begin with ontology, wh “a is then merely an hypothesis; [ be egin with psycho ey; and it is psychology itself which conducts me ib ontology, and saves me at once from scepticism and from hypothesis. Confident that truth bears with it its own evidence, and that it belongs moreover to the whole to justify its parts, Hegel starts with abstractions uid in his view are the foundation and the type of all reality; but he nowhere indicates or describes the process by which he. obtains.these.ab- stractions... Schelling indeed speaks sometimes of in- tellectual intuition as the process which lays hold of being.itself; but through fear of giving a ene choraeter to..this int ellectual:i intuition, he contend thatit does not fail within.the sphere of*conscious- ness; and thus, to my mind, makes it soba ies in- comprehensible. In ne theory, on the contrary, in- tellectual intuition, without being personal ad sub: jective, attains to the knowledge of ee from the bosom of consciousness ; it is a fact »f consciousnes: C838 no less real than the notions of reflection, only more difficult to seize, but still not beyond our reach, for in that case it Senll beas if it were not. Tn fine, to what faculty does the intellectual intuition of Schel ling belong? Is ita special faculty? Or is it not, as in my theory, merely a purer and more oe degree of reason itself? We are not permitted, i my y opinion, to slide over these points, nor many others, which I cannot even indicate. Far from it, | am strongly ee hat we cannot astral with too much care the pas age from psychology to on- tology, in order to pre seen the latter from being, or — at least from appearing to be, at issue of hypotheses nore or less artificial y woven together ae as aoe where, is manifested the gene C4 ‘al differenceee tent a ee ee Se oe wor ae as Ok Ue YE OS CEOS tartar fac > oie tas Sas Re eS ME Te MG RL at BO Se, Ma hg Ber Soar nets he ieee ae EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. o3 which separates me from the new German school, namely, the psychological character which. is im- pressed on all my views, and.to which I serupu- lously adhere as to a support for my..weakness.and a guarantee for my inductions.! ~skoueht perhaps to ask pardon for this apology, which seems more like a chapter of personal memoirs, than a discussion of philosophy. At present, cer- tainly, the reader knows as well as myself all the in- fluences which have acted on my mind and my ideas. As to my originality, I hold it at a very cheap rate. I have never sought, I still seek but one thing, that is, truth ; first to nourish and penetrate myself with it, then, to communicate it to my fellowmen. I have already had numerous masters; and I hope, even to my latest breath, to be always the disciple of any one who shall have new truth to communicate to my mund. { now pass to other adversaries, to accusations of a quite different nature, proceeding from the Theo- logical school.? What can be the quarrel between the Theological school and myself’ Am J then an enemy of Christi- anity and the Church? I have made many lectures and far too many books; can a word be found in one of them inconsistent with the reverence due to sacred things’ Leta single light or doubtful expression be pointed out, and I will retract it; I will disclaim it as unworthy of a philosopher. * See on the character of the Philosophy of Schelling, the excellent summary of Tennemann, Manuel de I’ Histoire de la Philosophie, French translation. Vol. 2, p. 294—312. or Heyel, it is sufficient to refer to the division of his Bneyclopadie der philosophischen Wissenschafien, 3d Ed. Berlin, 1530. First Part; Science of Logic, taken in the sense of Plats as the science of ideas in themselves, that is to say, of the neces- sary essence of things. Second Part; Philosophy of Nature. Third Part; Philosophy of Spirtt. This ‘Third Part of philo- sophical science contains psychology. Also in the Logic: 1. Being. 2. Essence. 3. Notion. And in Being. three de- grees, in the following order; Seyn, Daseyn, Fursichseyn. Noie G, 9 { & “St eee — Sas ah eaten, bn | ssid | Wie RRR CRORE, ae eer ee Meta tate yt a! tga ce yer + vt np eee ee nee «jenna ad a ary ‘ye so aS Th Hh i ON rail34 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISMe But, perbaps, without my knowledge or wish, the philosophy which I teach tends to weaken the Chris- tian Faith. This would be more dangerous and at the same time less criminal; for he is not always orthodox who wishes to be so. Let us look at it. What is the dogma which my theory places in peril ? Is it the dogma of the Word and of the Trinity ? Be it that or some other, let it be declared, let it be proved, let the attempt be made to prove it; there will then at least be a serious and truly theological discussion. I accept it, in advance ; I solicit it. No. This is not the point. I am not accused of speaking ill or of thinking ill of Christianity. It is not in any specific place that my philosophy is im- pious. Its impiety lies far deeper; for it is in its very existence. Its whole crime is that it is a philo- sophy, and not merely, as in the twelfth century, a simple commentary on the decisions of the Church and on the Holy Scriptures. Let us speak distinctly ; the Theological school, in order to defend religion to better advantage, under- takes to destroy philosophy, all philosophy, the good as well as the bad, and perhaps the good still more than the bad. This is the ground of its scepticism with regard to philosophy. But it is a mere game ; for all scepticism tends to the most outrageous dog- matism. lhe great argument of the Theological school, and, as it were, its war-cry, is the impotence of human reason. Here is the well-known argumentation of this school. Reason is a faculty altogether personal. When therefore we athirm any thing in the name of reason, it is in the name of our own reason that we affirm it; certainty in that case has no other basis, no other criterion than our individual sentiment; but this is absurd. Reason then cannot give us genuine certainty. Now, reason once proved to be impotent, we must. look for another authority. This authority is that of common sense opposed to individual sen- eee common sense preserved by tradition, madeEXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 35 visible by the Church, and promulgated by the Holy See. | This boasted scaffolding has been a hundred times overthrown. In the first place, we maintain, as phi- losophers, that what it pleases the Theological school to call individual reason is in fact the general and universal reason, which in every man is the epitome of the common sense of the human race. We main- tain that if this common sense actually exists in the human race, it cannot be composed of the fragments of different individual reasons, compared and com- bined with each other; for there can be no more in the collection than in each of its elements, and a thousand impotent, individual reasons cannot receive infallibility from their union. Who, moreover, would effect this union? Ina word, we maintain that the common sense of the human race exists, because every man is in possession of a reason, not individual, but general, which being the same in all, because it is individual in none, constitutes the true fraternity of men, and the common patrimony of human nature. Otherwise common sense is a mere hypothesis. Sup- pose that this hypothesis were a truth ; then for each one to submit his individual sentiment to the common sense of the race, it would at least be necessary that each could ascertain this common sense. -But how would he ascertainit? With his individual sentiment? Evidently he would, according to the system in ques- tion, for man has nothing better. But, in that case, with this individual! sentiment, how could the common sense be infallibly ascertained? It would be impossi- ble, under the penalty of concluding from the indi- vidual to the general, and of taking ourselves as the measure of certainty. We ought then to have a pre- vious measure of certainty in ourselves, in order to ascertain that which is proposed to us. We ought to possess still another, in order to ascertain that the Church in fact represents the comnion sense of the human race; for it is this relation of conformity which alone constitutes the authority of the Church. NO. XXXII. D 97 cto + ep eye Se eet Sia ook hk ; See SS St eo36 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. It is apparently a reasonable submission that is de- manded of us; but for this reasonable submission, the employment of reason is first necessary. All the eloquence and all the sophistry in the world, cannot conceal this perpetual paralogism. And yet this is the triumphant argument. Constantly over- thrown, it is constantly reproduced. It has ascend- ed from the Journals of party to the mandates of bishops,! it is the foundation of teaching in semi- naries, it fills the first chair? in Christendom; and that no inconsistency may be wanting, the Protest- ants have found it so admirable that they have not hesitated to borrow it of Catholicism. Open any of the Methodist publications; except in ability, you would think that you were reading the Abbé de la Mennais.2 The same principles, the same mode of reasoning, the same hatred of reason and philosophy ; the only difference is, that the word of God is sub- stituted for common sense, and the Holy Scriptures for the Church. In every philosophy, they say, it is always a man who speaks; it is a single man who addresses himself to our reason with his own; but we wish for no man between us and truth; we wish to surrender our minds only to God himself and to his word. Assuredly our adversaries are not dif- ficult ; but, I ask, who is to teach them that word ? Who will warrant them that it is the word of God? What ground have they for believing it? Who shall tell them that God has spoken? And by what sign shall they know it? The former propose to us, as proof, the researches of erudition and of historical criticism; the latter appeal to a sort of immediate illumination in the reading of the Holy Scriptures. But it is not a little strange to refer us to criticism through fear of philosophy ; to send us back to his- * See among other pieces of the same kind, the Pastoral in- struction of the Bishop of Chartres, against my Course of Phi- losophy, Quotidienne, 16 Feb. 1828. * De Methodo Philosophandi, pars prima, Rome, 1828, by Pere VentuRA, Professor in the College dela Sapienza. * See le Semeur, the Organ of the Methodist party. 98EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. ov tory in order to avoid the intervention of men be- tween truth and ourselves. As to immediate illumina- tion, the intervention of reason in that is less evident, but quite as real. Indeed, which of our faculties is it that in the reading of the Holy Scriptures must receive this sudden light? It is not sensibility, we presume ; it is not imagination; neither is it reason- ing. Examine and you will find that it must be rea- son. It is reason which, endowed with the power of recognising the True, the Good, the Beautiful, the Grand, the Holy, the Divine, wherever it is, recog- nises it in the Holy Scriptures, as it recognises it in nature, as it recognises it in conscience and in the soul, which is also a Bible in its own way. You would reduce philosophy to a commentary on the Holy Scriptures ; you then trust to him who makes this commentary. The Scriptures have their obscure and difficult passages; their language is that of the symbolical East; it cannot be comprehended and interpreted without the aid of a practised and deve- loped reason. It is reason, then, in the last analysis, to which we are compelled to return ; it is the testi- mony of reason which measures all other testimonies ; and the authority of reason on which repose all other authorities. If this authority be purely individual, as it is pretended, there is no certainty, no universal truth in the world. But if certainty is to be obtained, if there are universal truths, it is because reason, which teaches them to us, has in itself a sovereign and universal authority. Indeed, we cannot but smile to see a Protestant sect, after having separated from the Church in the name of the right of free inquiry, end with denying the authority of the faculty which in- quires. Let it then return to the Church; it will there find at least a uniform rule, a general discipline which will give it a support and a refuge against the extravagances of mysticism. I need not say that this question does not concern Christianity, nor the Church, nor the Holy Scriptures ; but merely the presumptuous war which a blind fe3 Bee ee il hike Sak bp Leave tse 3) maneciar sc 38 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. wages in their name against reason and philosophy. To separate faith from reason is doing a poor service to the faith of the nineteenth century. To reduce philosophy to theology is an intolerable anachronism. Philosophy is for ever emancipated. It is almost ludicrous to propose to it at this day to be nothing but the handmaid of theology. Let us yield to each of them a becoming indeperdence. They can exist together without difficulty. Their provinces are dis- tinct; and each is vast enough to prevent the need of intruding on the other. Religion, which addresses itself to all men, would fail of its end, if it were presented under a form which intelligence alone can reach ; for in that case its teachings would be lost for three quarters of the human race. It speaks not only to intelligence, but also to the heart, to the senses, to the imagination, to the whole man. It is this which renders its utility incomparably su- perior to that of philosophy, by the multitude of human beings on whom it acts. But this immense advantage brings with it difficulties which gradually show themselves in the progress of time and of civi- lization. Strictly speaking, religions are the found- ers and nurses of the human race. To them belong temples, public places, all great influences, popularity, power. It is not so with philosophy. That speaks /only to intelligence, and consequently to a very small number of men; but this small number js the select { portion and the van-guard of the human race. The functions of philosophy and of religion being so diffe- rent, why should they combat each other ? They both serve the human race; each in its own way and according to its own forms. The wish of philosophy to destroy religion would besenseless and criminal; for it could not hope to supply its place with the masses, who are unable to attend courses of metaphysical instruction. On the other hand, religion cannot de- stroy philosophy ; for philosophy represents the sacred right and theinvincible craving of human reason to give eC to itself of all things. A profound theo-EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICIsM, 39 logy, which understands its true ground, will never be hostile to philosophy, with which, in reality, it cannot Ispense ; and at the same time, a philosophy which understands the nature of philosophy, its true object, its compass and its limits, will never be tempted to impose its processes upon theology. It is always a bad philosophy and a bad tl eology which quarrel with each other. Christianity is the cradle of modern philosophy; and I have myself set forth more than one lofty truth concealed under the veil of the Chris- tian images. Let those holy and sublime images be early presented to the souls of our children, let them deposit there the germs of every truth; our country, humanity, philosophy itself will gain from it immense and priceless advantages ;! but let it not be pretended that reason should never attempt to give an account to itself of the truth under another form. This would be to lose sight of the diversity and the riches of the human faculties, their distinct wants and the legiti- mate sphere of these wants; it would be to stand in opposition to the necessary march of events, But in the midst of these aberrations, it is for philosophy, attacked and calumniated, to render good for evil, and, while maintaining its independence with an im- moveable firmness, to maintain also, as far as in it lies, the natural alliance which connects it with reli- gion.” It would moreover be a very superficial phi- losophy which should deem Christianity a burden. By that very fact, it would acknowledge itself con- victed of a manifest incompetency, since it would fail to comprehend, and could not explain the greatest event of the past, the most important institution of the present. T’his leads me to the last point on which it remains to say a few words, namely, the application of philosophy to history, and particularly to the his- tory of philosophy, so as not to forget the purpose of these /ragments, or too much extend this Preface already very long. 1 See Note H. 2 See Note I. 101EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. IV. GENERAL VIEWS ON THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. The views of every system on the history of the science to which it relates, furnish the most certain estimate of that system, the exact measure of its prin- ciples. Is it incomplete? Does it contain only a single element of consciousness and of reality? Is it founded only on a single principle, however brilliant and imposing itmay be? It is then compelled, in or- der to be consistent with itself, to perceive no truth in all the systems founded on a contrary principle, to discover no reason except in those which rest on the same principle. An historical conception like this is the final sentence of a system ; for it is a melancholy wisdom which has universal folly for its condition ; and to defend ourselves only by accusing every body else is to accuse and condemn ourselves. “But sup- pose a system which; by a patient and profound ob- servation, and an induction at once comprehensive and scrupulous, has succeeded in embracing all the ele- ments of consciousness and of reality ; when after- wards it shall give its attention to history, to what- ever side it turns, it will not find a single system of any considerable importance, in which there are not some of its own elements, and—with which it agrees, atleast, on certain points. In fact, it is no easy thing to wander so far from the common sense which is the giit of all men, as to fall into errors and remain in them, that are entirely destitute of truth ; error gains admission into the understanding only in the mask of a truth which she disfigures. A truly complete sys- tem;-therefore, can be applied with singular facility to history. It is not compelled to proscribe all systems, in order to justify itself; it is satisfied with disen- gaging the inevitable portion of error that is mixed with the portion of truth, which forms the life and strength of each of them; and by pursuing the same 102EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 41 course with them all, enemies as they were by their contrary errors, it makes them friends and brothers, by the truths which they contain, and thus purified and reconciled, it composes with them a_vast_whole, adequate to.the expression of complete and universal truth... Now this method, at—onee_philosophical and historical, which, in possession of truth, is able to find it scattered here and there in all systems, is. Eclecti- cism. We must-distinguish.three.things in Eclecti- cism; its point of departure, its processes, and its end ; its principle, its instruments, and its results. Eelec- ticism supposes a system which serves it as a point of departure and a principle in the labyrinth of history ; it demands as an instrument a rigid criticism sustained on a solid and extensive erudition; it has for its-pri- mary result the decomposition of all systems by the fire and steel of criticism, and for its definitive result their reconstruction in_a new system which is the complete_représentation of consciousness in history. Eclectieism-—bégins with a philosophy, and proceeds by-means.of history,to_the living demonstration of that philosophy... For this reason I said at the close of the Preface to the Fragments, after giving an ex- position of the system which I have now discussed ; «I shall pursue the reform of philosophical studies in France, in illustrating the history of philosophy by this system, and in demonstrating this system by the whole history of philosophy.” Would it_be thought after this, that. any--one-should_see_in Eclecticism only a blind Syncretism, which mingles. together all systems, approves all, confounds..the..True_and the False, good and evil ;. a. new fatalism ; the dream oi a deceived mind,.which, unable.to produce a system for itself, demands one of history ?... All these objec- tions will vanish of themselves before the slightest ex- amination. — Frrst Opsection. Eclecticism is a Syncretism which mingles together all systems. Answer. Eclecticism does not mingle together all systems; for it leaves no system entire ; it Te eas 2 = om se) mapa graben snes el) drncbebrin abeSeng tee ae nena tgp segeneta rag pte em ee pee mm uD + t " Nee en ee AELal EimaLeEhnn 4? EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. poses every system into two parts, the one false, the other true; it destroys the first, and admits only the second in the work of reconstruction. It is the true portion of each system which it adds to the true por- tion of another system, that is to say, truth to truth, in order to form a true whole. It never mingles one entire system with another entire system; therefore it does not mingle all systems. LEclecticism,. there- fore, is not Syncretism ; the one indeed is the oppo- site of the other; philosophically and etymologically, they resemble each other like choice and mixture, dis- crimination and confusion. SECOND Ogsection. Eclecticism approves every thing, confounds the True and the False, good and evil. Answer. Eclecticism does not approve every thing; for it maintains that in every system there is a considerable portion of error. It does not con- found the True and the False; on the contrary, it distinguishes them from each other, neglects the False, and makes use only of the True. Tuirp Oxzsection. LEclecticism is fatalism. ANSWER. It is not fatalism to say that man is so constituted as, with his noble intelligence, always to seize a portion of truth; and with the limits of his intelligence, above all, with his indolence, his super- ficialness, his presumption, to believe that he has at- tained the whole truth when he possesses only a part. Hence there is always a portion of the True and the False, of good and evil, in the works of man, and par- ticularly in philosophical systems. There is so much the less fatalism in this, as Eclecticism maintains that by great efforts with ourselves, by a double share of vigilance, attention, circumspection, we may suc- ceed in diminishing the chances of error; and as this is the result to which it aspires. Fourts Oxzszction. Eclecticism is the absence of all system. ANSWER. Eclecticism is not the absence of all system ; for it is the application of a system > it sup- x. 104 cre auEXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 43 poses a system,.jt.starts froma system. In fact,if we would collect and combine the truths scattered in dif- ferent systems, we must first separate them from the errors with which they are mingled; and in order to do this, we must know how to ascertain and distin- guish them ; but to ascertain whether a given opinion is true or false, we must know ourselves what is error and what is truth; we must therefore already. bein possession, or.at-least-think-that.we are in possession of truth ; we must have a system in order to judge all _ systems, Eclecticism-—supposes a system--already ‘formed, which.it continues.to illustrate and.enrich ; it is not therefore the absence of all system. I would now ask, if Eclecticism be a conception which belongs exclusively to myself? By no means, I should greatly distrust an idea which was entirely new in the world; which no one had ever thought of before. No, thank God, Eclecticism is not of yester- day. It was born the moment that asound head and a feeling heart undertook to.reconcile.two.passionate adversaries, by showing them that the opinions for which they combated were not irreconcilable in them- selves, and that, with a few mutual sacrifices, they might be brought together.. [clecticism was long | ago inthe mind of Plato; it was the professed enter- prise, whether legitimate or not, of the school “ot, Alexandria, Among the moderns, it was not merely professed by Leibnitz, it was constantly practised by him ; and it is every where presented in the rich his- torical views of the new German philosophy. ‘The time has arrived at last to elevate it to the precision and the dignity of a principle. This is what I have attempted to do. This word, long since fallen into deep oblivion, scarcely uttered by a single voice, has echoed from one end of Europe to the other, and the spirit of the nineteenth century has recognised itself in Eclecticism. They will know how to pursue their path together in spite of every obstacle. => In the midst of such success, when Eclecticism has already made so many unlooked for conauee ey 5 c. BN “ ‘ am Mom) + ode SEARO eee Bee rarer renee ore Picea rjfo ene gt oregon rind seteaheitarabeuinanainasisa nea teohali aa SFuIMIENEL END a 44 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. were a singular weakness, both of mind and charac- ter, to be surprised or wounded by the violent at- tacks of which it has been the object. It was inevi- table that all exclusive systems should rise against a system which undertook to put an end to their quar- rels, by crushing their opposite pretensions, and sub- mitting them to a common discipline. All extreme parties, therefore, are Jeagued against Eclecticism, under the honourable flag of the support of discord. Heaven knows what war they have waged, and with what arms! I have had the benefit of holding against me, for many years, the Sensual school and the Theological school united. In 1830, both schools descended into the arena of politics. The Sensual school naturally produced the party of demagogues ; and the Theological school quite as naturally took sides with Absolutism, except as from time to time it assumed the mask of the demagogues so as to sooner gain its ends, just as in philosophy it under- took to restore theocracy by means of scepticism. The system, on the contrary, which combated every exclusive principle in science must needs have re- jected also every exclusive principle in the State, and defended Representative Government. In 1828, I gave a theory of Representative Government and of the Charter, in which I still persist.! Convictions which are founded not on temporary circumstances, but on a profound study of humanity and of history, are not swept away by the wind of the first tempest. Three days have not changed the nature of things and the state of French society. Yes, as the human soul in its natural development contains many ele- ments of which true philosophy is the harmonious expression, so every civilized society possesses many elements altogether distinct, which true government ought to recognise and represent ; and the exclusive triumph of one of these elements in a simple govern- ment, under whatever name, could be nothing but a 1 See Note K. 106EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 45 FE ee Preheat ea are te Ret testy tyranny. A mixed government is the only one ap- propriate to a great nation like France. The Revo- lution of July is merely the English Revolution of 1688, but in France,—that is to say, with far less aristocracy and a little more democracy and monar- chy. The proportion of these elements may vary with circumstances ; but these three elements are ne- cessary. Let us leave republicanism to the youthful societies of America, and absolute monarchy to aged Asia. Placed between the old world and the new, at an equal distance from decrepitude and infancy, our Europe, in its vigorous maturity, contains all the elements of social life, brought to its complete de- velopment: it is therefore doomed as it were to Representative Government. This admirable form of government is a happy necessity of our times; and without the folly of proselytism, will make the tour of Europe. For France, the question I fear not to say, is that of existing in this manner, or of ceasing to exist at all. With Representative Government, I see public liberty, union, and power at home, and consequently the certain prospect of greatness and glory abroad. Let Representative Government be destroyed, and I perceive nothing but barren convul- sions, civil war with foreign war, a powerless imita- tion of agrand epoch for ever gone by, and as a com- plete novelty, perhaps the dismemberment of France, and the fate of Poland and Italy. I turn my eyes from a result like this, and desire nothing that can lead to it. My political faith is therefore in entire accordance with my philosophical faith ; and both the one and the other are above the outrages of party.E XPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUED.? Turse Fragments are articles inserted for the most part in the Journal des Savans and in the Archives Philosophiques from 1816 to 1819. Borrowed from my Lectures of that period, I cannot attempt to re- store them to a certain degree of unity without say- ing a few words on the teaching to which they relate, and which they represent as far as insulated pieces can represent a whole. Called upon to speak of my- self, I shall do so, without the precautions of modesty, which are of no value compared with simplicity and rectitude of intention; I will frankly relate every thing which I have done or wished to do, from the time of my appointment as Master of the Philosophi- cal Conferences in the Normal School, and Professor of the History of Modern Philosophy in the Faculty of Literature, when [ unreservedly and irrevocably devoted my whele-life..to the pursuit.of the philoso- phical reform so honourably commenced by M. Royer-Collard: in.the position in which I was placed, my first at- tention.was given to method. A system is scarcely any thing but the development ofa method applied to-certain. objects. Accordingly nothing is more important than to ascertain and determine, in the first place, the method, which we wish to pursue to give an account to ourselves of our good and our bad in- stincts, and of the direction in which they impel us, ' Preface to “ Philosophical Fragments.” 1826. 108 First edition,EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 47 and to which we must know whether or not we mean to consent; for our philosophy, like our destiny, must needs be.our_own. Undoubtedly, we should borrow it from truth and the necessity of things; but we ought also to receive it freely, with a perfect com- prehension of what we borrow and what we receive. Philosophy, whether. speculative or practical, is the alliance of necessity and liberty in the mind of the man, who spontaneously places himself in harmony with. the laws, of .universal.existence... The end is in the Infinite, but the point of departure is in ourselves, Open the books of history ; every philosopher who has respected his fellowmen, and who has not wish- ed to offer them merely the indefinite results of cer- tain dreams, has begun with the_consideration_of method. Every doctrine which has exercised any influence, has done so and could do so, only by the new _direction-which it has given to the mind, by the new-point-of view in-whieh-it-has presented the sub- jects-ef inquiry; that-is.to.say, by its method. Every philosophical reform has its avowed or secret prin- ciple in a change or in an advancement of method. My first effort. therefore must needs have been to examiné conscientiously the point from which I was to start, the direction which I was to take, the method whreh-I wasto émploy, and which contained the re- sults of every kind, yet unknown to me, to which its successive application would necessarily lead. Be- sides, as a public Professor, the Master of Confer- ences in a school of professors, who were destined by their teaching or their writings to influence the future condition of philosophy in France, I deemed it a sa- cred duty to inculcate upon them from the first the spirit_of free and critical inquiry, by which sooner or later, they might ascertain my errors, modify my teaching, or abandon it altogether. Conviction may be dangerous in proportion to its depth and sincerity ; and the honourable man who feels it at the bottom of his heart with the perilous authority which it gives him, is solemnly bound to absolve himself in cede 109 Sona al ee ea Ee © aT - P a8 a a LE FTA CLSTabee SCOLMN RCL Ls ti Aw a ann ~ 48 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. from the contagion of the errors which escape him, by arming his auditory against himself, by forming it to independence, by previously and constantly dis- cussing the general spirit of his teaching, that is to say, by insisting on method. This, then, was my first care. But what method have I taken up? That which was in accordancé with the spirit of the times,—éarnestly studied and freely accepted,—in accordance with the habits of the nation.as.well-as-my-own.Let.me-explain-myself. It is an incontestable fact that in England and France in the eighteenth century, Locke and Condil- lac took the piace of the great schools of a previous date, and have reigned without contradiction to the present day. Instead of being irritated at this fact, we should endeavour to comprehend it; for after all, facts do not create themselves; they have their laws which are connected “with the. generallaws_of the human race. If the philosophy of sensation actually gained credit in England and France, there must have been some reason for this phenomenon. Now this reason, when we come to reflect upon it, does honour and not injury to the human mind. It was not its fault, if it could not remain in the shackles of Cartesianism ; for it belonged to Cartesianism to pro- tect it, to satisfy all the conditions which can perpe- tuate a system. In the general movement of affairs and the progress of time, the spirit of analysis and observation must also have its place ; and this place it found in the eighteenth century. The spirit of the eighteenth century needs no apology. The apo- logy for a century is the fact of its existence ; for its_ existence is a decree _and-a-judgment-of..God_him- self; or else history is nothing but an_insignificant .phantasmagoria. ‘lhe modern spirit is often accused of incredulity and scepticism, but it is sceptical only with regard to what it does not understand, ineredu- lous only concerning what it cannot believe, that is to say, the condition of understanding and of believ- ing, at that epoch, as at many former epochs, having 110EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 49 been changed for the human race, it was indispensa- ble, on pain of surrendering its independence, that it should impose new conditions on every thing which aspired to govern its intelligence and its faith. Faith is neither exhausted nor diminished. The human race, like the individual, lives only by faith ; but the conditions of faith, however, are.constantly renewed. In the eighteenth century, the general condition of comprehending and of believing was that of having observed the object ; from that time, all philosophy which aspired to authority must needs be founded on observation. Now, Cartesianism, especially with the modifications whichit had received from Malebranche, Spinoza, Leibnitz, and Wolf,—Cartesianism, which in the second stage of its progress, abandons observa- tion and loses itself in ontological hypotheses and scholastic formulas, could.not pretend to the cha- racter_of experimental philosophy. Another system was presented in this character; and in this charac- ter, it was accepted. Such is the explanation of the fall of Cartesianism, and the unexampled success of the philosophy of Locke and Condillac. If we re- fect for a moment on the subject, the success of this miserable-philosophy still testifies to the dignity and independence of the human mind, which forsakesin its turn the systems which forsake it, and pursues its path even through the most deplorable errors, eather than not advance at all. It did not adopt the philosophy ofsensation on account ofits Materialism ; but on account of its-experimental--character; which toa. certain degree itactually possessed. The favour with which this philosophy wasreceived did not come from its dogmas, but from its method; and.this me- thod-was not itsown; but that of the age. And it is-true that the experimental method was the neces- sary fruit of time, and not the transient work of a sect in England and France; and that if we calmly examine the contemporary schools, the most opposed to that of Sensation, we shall find the same pretensions to observation and experience. Reid and ay aces So a EET 50 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. Scotland and in Germany,. had fought to the death, had overthrown from top to bottom, the doctrine of Locke; but with what weapons? Why, with those of Locke himself ; with the experimental method dif- ferently applied. Reid starts from the human mind ‘and its faculties, which he~analyzes in their actual operation, and. the laws of which he determines. Kant, separating reason from all its objects,.and-eon- sidering, if I may so speak, only its interior,gives a profound and exquisite statistical account_of.it-5—his philosophy is.a-Critique ; it_is always that of observa- tion and experience. Make the tour of Europe and of the world, you will every where find the same spi- rit, the same method; and this_in—-faet_constitutes the unity of.the age, since this unity—presents-itself in the wiidst-ofthe-mest striking diversities. Let us now lock at our own men, and especially the French of the nineteenth century. The spirit of ve j analysis has-destroyed.much around us. Born in the t+ (\ |midst_of ruins of every kind, we feel.the need of re- | \ | \yconstrueting this need is deep, pressing, imperious ; {if | \ \ ““theréts ro small peril for us in our present state; | \ \. \ “and yet if we are more just than our fathers towards | | the past, we can rest in it no more than they; we | absolve our fathers and‘the age; and we also have Ma . no faith but in observation and experience. This is our condition. We must submit to it with resig- nation. And is it after all such a great evil? Let us re- ' flect upon it. To be limited to observation and ex- | perience is.to..bedimited to human nature; for we observe only with ourselves, in proportion to our fa- culties and their laws. We are then limited to human nature. But what else would we have? If the ob- servation which goes as far as human nature can go, does not suffice for the attainment of all truths and all convictions, and for the completion of the whole cir- cle of science, the evil is certainly not in the method which limits us to‘ our natural means of knowledge, but in the weakness of those means and of our nature 112 Pe iiacie car fai ua iS hoch ins pLdanrcsnn heir tesroeeseaaeateiaates tabi it a aL Nee ee att atte te ilk abet " id ‘EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. from which we eanos escape. In fact, whatever nethod we ma y ad lopt, it is always ourselves who h 7 q . a y an . have made it or who employ it ; itis ae LYS en our- salyaag 1 - ET 2 ° 1 selves that we act; it is always human nature which, appearing to frags itseli, is alw Ae replace which does every thing that is done or attempted, even apparently: beyo nd its power. Hither we must_de- spair_of scienee;-or-human nature-ts-competent.to_at- tain it. “Observation, that is, human nature accepted as the sele instrument of discovery,_1s. competent, when properly employed, or ee is competent ; for we have nothing he and our predecessors had no more. Let us sry tne systems on Wi bey passed sentence ? Whi at has it destroyec could it destroy ? The hypothetical oe of systems. But what gave life and coherence to those hypotheses Merely certain hi discovered by of vser vation, which observati ° Q 1 covers, and oe rn possess, for that reasc same certainty and the same novelty as her W hat has ak SO o high and yet sustains the of Pythagoras, the ideas of Plato, the categories of Aristotle > bench enh chin) is aiaeneetraeSoe hen ROTOR Tall heey O ineed peeks ernie ett amare Re hihd at Seem tacut er trans i he nen errs raat heehee uid p i ; C 58 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. is a fact,..moreover,.that.this.principle-of causality is marked with the characteristics of universality and necessity. Ifit be universal and necessary, to limit it would be.to destroy it. Now in the phenomenon of sensation, the principle of causality intervenes uni-~ versally and necessarily, and refers this phenomenon to a cause; and our consciousness testifying that this cause is not the personal cause which the will repre- sents, it follows that the principle of causality in its irresistible application conducts to an impersonal cause, that is to say, to an external cause, which subsequently, and always irresistibly, the principle of causality enriches with the characteristics and laws, of which the aggregate is the Universe. Here then is an existence ; but.an existence revealed.by a prin- ciple which is itself attested by consciousness. Here is a primary-step in ontology, but by the pat! chology, -that.is.to say, ofobseryation. W.e..are led by similar processes to the Cause of all causes, to the substantial.Cause ; to.God, and not only to-a-God of Power, but.to.a.God.of Justice, a God of Holiness ; so that this experimental method, which, applied to a single order of phenomena, incomplete and exclusive, destroyed ontology and the higher elements of con- sciousness, applied with fidelity, firmness and com- pleteness, to all the phenomena, builds up that which it had overthrown, and ‘by itself furnishes. ontology with a.sureand.legitimateinstrument. Thus, having commenced with niodesty; we can end with results whose certainty is equalled by their importance. I have searcely indicated these results, but the reader will find them explained at large, with the methodical processes by which they are obtained and verified, in the Programme of my Lectures of the year 1817, which is inserted among these Frag- ments. in the year 1818, our labours were continued in the same path, and began to assume a character of greater profoundness andextent. The facts of consciousness fete been reduced the preceding year to three great c Or DSY- + veEXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM, 59 z ot classes, ey, sensible facts, voluntary facts, and rational facts, the fime had come fora more coniplete analysis of each of them, and e the relations by which they are united in { the indivisible unity of con- J AT sciousness. My attention was a articularly directed. to the voluntary facts and to the rational facts, be- cause these had been the most neglected in the French philosophy. Sensible facts are necessary. We do not impute them to ourselves. Rational facts are also necessary ; and reason is no less independent of the will than sen- ity. Voluntary facts alone are marked in the view of consciousness with the characteristics us personality and responsibility. he will alone is th person or the me. Th 1e me is the centre of the ier léctual sphere. So long as the me doesnot exist; the conditions of the existence-of-all-the-other phenomena might be in force, but, v wi ithout ey a the me, they ‘be for it as though they were not. On the other trand, the will creates none of the rational and sen- it even supposes them, since it does not apprehend itself, ae in distinction from them. We do not find ourse “ eRe in a foreign world, between two ord nenomena which do not per- tain to us, which we do not even perceive e, except on condition of oe. ourselves from them. Still aly é: » we do not perceive at ae xcept by-a light which does not come from ourselve 5 for our person- more 5 ball light com 2 ye . ' 1 allty is the will and nothing i qe he irom reason; and it is reason which perceives both itself, and the sensibility which env elopes it, and the wil which it obliges, without constraining. The element of knowledge i s rational by its essence ; and consciousness, although composed.of three integrant and insepara able élements, | borrows its most immediate foundation from reason, without which no knowled ive would be possible, and consequently no co gia ness. Sensibility is the/external condition of con- sciousness ; the will is its centre, and reason its light. TZ oe 67 ACK ek ick! ‘ + satget probed etndend) Lopebabenes chen} csintiasene 60 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. A profound and thorough analysis of reason is one of the most delicate undertakings of psychology. Reason is impersonal in its nature. It is not we who-vmaké if. It is so far from being individual, that ttspeculiar characteristics are the opposite of indi- _viduality, namely, universality and necessity ; since it is to reason that we owe the knowledge of universal ‘and necessary trutlis, of principles which we all obey, and which we.cannot but obey. The existence of these principles is then a preliminary fact which it was essential to establish in the first place upon the most complete evidence. It is a triumph of the me- thod of observation, to which it must have been in- debted for an incontestable basis. Then comes the question with regard to the precise number of these regulating principles of reason, which, as far as we are concerned, are reason itself. After having esta- blished the existence of such principles, it is the busi- fe) ness of method to attempt a complete enumeration and a rigorous classification of them, Plato, who following s Pythagoras, built_his philosophy_on these principles, neglected to count them ;, It seems as if he ao @® shrunk from permitting a profane analysis to touch those divine wings on which he soared into the world of ideas» The methodical Aristotle, faithful to his mas master, but still more faithful to analysis, after having changed ideas into categories, submitted them to a severe examination, and did not hesitate to give a list of them. This list, so much despised by frivolous minds as an arid nomenclature, is the boldest and the most hazardous effort of method. Is the_list.of Aris- totle- complete? T believe that-it-is. It-exhausts.the swhyect. Let this be-its-immortal glory. But if the enumeration is complete, is there nothing to be desired in the elassification and the arrangement of the cate- gories? Here commences the defect_of the list of Aristotle. In my opinion, its order is arbitrary, and does not correspond to the progressive development ofintelligence. Besides, does not this list contain re- 122 :EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 61 petitions ! ’ Would it not be possible to reduce it? I have no doubt of it. Among modern systems, Carte- Slanism recognises nece ssary truths 5 oi it makes no attempt at eomple ALeMeSs and_precision.with-regard-to them. In the eighteenth century, in France, neces- sary truths were set aside as by the previous question ; they did not even receive the honour of b yeing submit- ted to exam ait, ; they were guilty of being found in the old system; they must be sacrificed to_sen- sation, the only basis aa standard_ of. all possible truth. —~-FPhe-Scottish school, which restored.them-te honour, enumerated a pat rt of them, but did not think of making a complete account. It Wasixe eserved for Kant to renew.the unc Teas of Aristotle, and the first among the moderns to attempt to form a complete oe of the laws of thought.” Of these, Kant made an xact and profound review: and his labour, in this respect, is superior even to that of Aristotle; but, in my opinion, similar charges can be brought against him; and a long and detailed exami ation may nave ely 41. th demonstrated to those ae oe my Course of 1818, that if the list of Kant is complete, it is arbi- trary in its classification, and is susceptible of a legi- timate reduction. Tet have accomplished any thing useful in my teaching, it is perhaps on have at -least-renewed an important question ; Thave debated the two most celebrated wattonk ; and I a 5 have ventured to prope ose another, which time and this point. I Se anal discussion | have not yet_shaken. In my opinion, all the laws of thought may ce ee to £ wo, name ly, the Taw of Causality-a arrd—that-ef—sulstance. These are the two essential and fundamental laws, of which all others are only derivatives, developed in an order by no means arbitre ry. I have demonstrated, as I think, that if w e examine these two laws in the order the nature oi things, ine Hirst is that of substance es of J hia 4 and the second that of causality; while in the orue of the acquisition of our art the law of oa alee precedes that of “substamee; or rather both are given 123 Een PUrRPn TS paar mOneranee ee See eae : Se seemed to be imposed upon { 62 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. to us together, and are contemporary in our con- sciousness. “It is not sufficient to have enumerated, classed, and reduced to a system the laws of reason; we must prove that they are absolute, in order to prove that their consequences, whatever they may be, are also absolute. Here is the defect of the celebrated discussion of Kant respecting the Objective and Subjective in human knowledge. That great man, after seeing so clearly all the laws which preside over thought, struck with the character of necessity which they bear, that is to say, our inability not to recognise and follow them, supposed that he saw in this very-fact.a bond of dependence and relativeness with respect to the me, the peculiar and distinctive characteristic of which he was far from having com- pletely fathomed. “Now as soon as the laws of rea- son are degraded to being nothing but laws relative to the human condition, their whole compass is cir- cumscribed by the sphere of our personal nature ; and their widest consequences, always marked with an indelible character of subjectivity, engender only irresistible persuasions, if you please, but no inde- pendent truths. This is the procedure, by which that incomparable analyst, after having so well de- scribed all the laws of thought, reduces them to im- potence; and with all the conditions of certainty, arrives at an ontological scepticism, from which he finds no other asylum than the sublime inconse- quence of allowing more objectivity to the laws of practical reason than to those of speculative reason. Lhe whole endeavour of my Lectures of 1818, after a systematic catalogue of the laws of reason, was to free them _from-the~character.of subjectivity-which them by that of neces- sity; to reinstate them-in their-independences and toSave philosophy from the rock on which it-had been thrown the moment of reaching the port. Our public discussions, for several months, were devoted 124 tu ¥Oe Si a Sar vas ae EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 63 g that the laws of human reason are no- thing less than the laws of reason in itself. More faithful t} 1an ever to the psychological method, in- stead of departing from observation, I plunged into it more deeply ; and it is by observation that in the esses_of consciousness,-and—at—a depth.to-whieh { under the apparent relative- ness and subjectivity of the e_lecessary-prineiples-of thought, I detect ed _and_unfelded—the fact, instanta- neous but real, of the spontaneous peueenl 10n of truth, ‘ Which not reflecting itself 1 imme- without notice in the cas of con: liatéely, passes sclousness, but_is- ae aetual—basis-ofthat. which, at a 4 _subsequen it period, in..a.logical form, and in the ids of ction, becomes.a necessary conception. ae with all that is of a reflective cha- racter, expires in the spontaneity of perception. But the spontaneous perception. is_so_pure that_it escapes our_notice ; it is the reflected light which strikes us, but often obseur ‘Ing, by i its lee bright {- he purity of the primitive light. “Reason, it is Aen bjee 4+ true, becomes sui bjective byl a relation to the free ole me, the seat and the ty, pe of ‘all sub- mitself itis impersonal; it belongs to | ata rather than another within the 2 compass of humanity; it belongs 1 BOY even to huma- nity itself; and itsdlajs /consequently depend only on themselves. (They sia over and govern hu- nor the gies It mi rht even BS oF Ta ereater truth that nature and humanity belong to them; since they Have a 10 beauty or truth but by their r elation 19. ae intelligence, and since nature who the laws. which itis governed, and seen without the prin- ciples which guide it, would soon be Tost in the abyss of nothingness,.from which they could never escape. The laws of intelligence therefore constitute a sepa- rate world, which governs the visible world, pre canes over its movements, sustains..and. preserves it,Se 64 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. does not depend eon it. This is the intelligible world, the sphere of tdeas, distinct from and inde- pendent of their subjects, internal and external, which Plato had glimpses of, and which modern analysi is and psychology still discover at the present day in the dep ths of consciousness. The laws of thought having been demonstrated to be absolute, 1 imMCtON oe make use of them without hesitation ; and from absolute principles obtained by observation can legitima aie conduct us to a point beyond the immediate sp ohere of observation itself. Now,-ameng-the laws of thought given by psycho- logy, the two fundamental orae which contain all the Giers the law_of causality and thejaw_or substanee, irresistibly applied to themselves, elevate us imme- diately to their cause and their substance; and as they are absoluté, they elevate us to an absolute cause and an absolute substance. But an absolute Biran ; we shall find it in none of these cases, not even in the last, for it is possible that cee should be a paralysis of the sean which dep r over them, 1S ae Vk ‘LV eS th e W ill of pow YM tb ikEXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 67 makes it unproductive, incapable of being a cause, and consequently of suggesting the notion of it. But what no paralysis can prevent, is the action of the will on itself, the production of a resolution, that is to say, an act of causation entirely mental, the pri- mitive type of all causality, of which all external movements, commencing with the muscular effort and ending with the action of one ball on another, are only symbols more or less imperfect. The first cause for us therefore is the will, of which the first effect is a volition. This is at once the highest and the purest source of the notion of cause, which thus becomes identical with that of personality. And it is the taking possession, so to speak, of the cause in the willand the personality, which is the condition for us of the ulterior or simultaneous conception of external impersonal causes. The phenomenon of will presents the following ele- ments: I. to decide upon an act to be performed ; 2. to deliberate ; 3. to resolve. Now if we look at it, it is reason which composes the first element entirely, and even the second; for it is reason also which deli- berates, but itis not reason which resolves and deter- mines. Now reason, which isthus combined with will, is combined in a reflective form ; to conceive an end, to deliberate, involves the idea of reflection. Reflec- tion is therefore the condition of every voluntary act, if every voluntary act supposes a predetermination of its object and a process of deliberation. Now to act voluntarily, is, as we have seen, to act in this manner; and it is because the will is in fact reflective, that it presents such a striking phenomenon. But can a reflective operation be a primitive operation ? To will is,—with the consciousness that we can resolve and act,—to deliberate whether we shall resolve, whether we shall act in such or such a manner, and to decide in favour of one orthe other. The result of this choice, of this decision, preceded by deliberation and predetermination, is volition, the immediate effect of personal activity ; but in order to resolve and to NO. XXXIII F 129 ra anee ee eet ener aie et et eae cially See tes acter esis pe me 68 XPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. act in this manner, it was necessary to know that we could resolve and act, it was necessary that we should have previously resolved and acted in a different man- ner, without deliberation or predetermination, that is to say, without reflection. The operation previous to reflection is spontaneity. It is a fact that even now we often act without having deliberated, and that rational perception spontaneously making known to us the act to be performed, the personal activity also spontaneously enters into operation and resolves at once, not by a foreign impulse, but by a kind of im- mediate inspiration, prior to reflection, and often su- perior toit. The Qwil mourtt! of the old Horatius, the a mot, Auvergne ! of the brave d’Assas, are not blind impulses, and in consequence destitute of mora- lity ; but neither is it from reasoning or reflection that they are borrowed by heroism. The phenomenon of spontaneous activity therefore is no less real than that of voluntary activity. Only, as every thing which is reflective is completely determined, and for that rea- son distinct, the phenomenon of voluntary and reflec- tive activity is more clear than that of spontaneous activity, which is less determined and more obscure. Moreover, the characteristic of every voluntary act is the power of repeating itself at will, the power of being summoned, so to speak, before the tribunal of consciousness, which examines and describes it at its leisure; while, on the other hand, as it is the charac- teristic of aspontaneous act that itis not voluntary. the Spontaneous act is not repeated at will, and when it takes place, is either unperceived or irrevocable, and cannot be afterwards summoned back but on condi- tion of being reflective, that is to say, of being de- stroyed, as a spontaneous fact. Spontaneity is there- fore necessarily subjected to that obseurity which sur- rounds every thing which is primitive and instanta- neous. With all our seeking, we can discover no other modes of action. Reflection and spontaneity com- prise all the real forms of activity. | 130 ReeReflection as a principle and as a fact supposes and fohows-spontancity; but_as there ean be nothine-in the Reflective Which is not in the Spontaneous, all that we have said-of the one.will apply to the other ; and although spontaneity is not accompanied either with prédetermination™or~deliberation, it is no less 4 than will a real powerof~action, and consequently a productive-eause;-and-consequently. agaln,.a.personal cause-—Spontaneity then contains all that is contain- ed by the will; and_it contains it previously to that, in a less detérmined, but a purer form ; and hence we afrive at the immediate source of causality and.of the me. The me already exists with the productive power which characterises it in the flashing forth of spon- taneity; and it is in this instantaneous flashing forth that it instantaneously apprehends itself. We might say that it discoversitselfin spontaneity, and establish- .€s itself inreflection. The me, says Fichte, supposes it- selfin a voluntary determination. This point of view is that of reflection. In order for the me to suppose itself, as Fichte says, it is necessary that it should clearly distinguish itself from the not-me. To distinguis! is to deny ; to distinguish one thing from another, is to afirm again, but by denying; it is to affirm, after having denied. Now it is not true that the intellec- tual life commences with a negation; and before re- fection, and the fact, te the description of which Fichte has for ever attached his name, there is another operation, in which the me finds itself without seek- ing, supposes itself, if you please, but without having wished to suppose itself, by the sole virtue, the peculiar energy of the activity, which it recognises, as it mani- fests it, but without having previously known it; for the activity is revealed to itself only by its acts, and the first act must have been the effect of a power which has hitherto been ignorant of itself. What then is this power which is revealed only by its acts, which finds and perceives itself in spontan- eity, and again finds and reflects upon itself in roe % 4 3] L EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 69 ong Pe a Maeih chk ae ee . fa alt HB) (a 4 Soe: De ee lees i a hae ia ie Pie ois aah Rit Pa eon eed tAAdL LASERS REC IN ’ Cee eee een ee eam renee slid hs 70 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. Whether spontaneous or voluntary, all personal acts have this characteristic in common, that they can be referred immediately to a cause which has its point of departure altogether in itself, that is to say, that they are free ; such is the proper notion of liberty. Liberty cannot be confined to the will, for in that case, spontaneity would not be free; and, on the other hand, liberty cannot consist merely in sponta- neity, for then the will in its turn would not be free. If therefore the two phenomena are equally free, they can be so only on the condition, that we discard from the notion of liberty every thing which belongs exclu- sively either to the one or the other of the two pheno- mena, and that we allow to it only what is common to both. Now, what circumstance is common to both, except that they have their point of departure in themselves, and that they can be referred immediately to a cause, which is their proper cause, and which acts only by its own energy ? Liberty being the com- mon characteristic of spontaneity and of will, com.. prises both these phenomena itself; it ought te possess, and it consequently does possess, something more general than either, and which constitutes their identity. This is the only theory of liberty that agrees with the different facts which are announced as tree by the consciousness of the human race, and which in their diversities have occasioned theories in contradiction with each other, because they have been constructed exclusively for a specific order of phenomena. ‘Thus, for example, the theory which concentrates liberty in the will must needs admit no other than reflective liberty, preceded by a predeter- mination, accompanied with a process of deliberation, and marked with characteristics which greatly reduce the number of free acts, which take away liberty from every thing which is not reflective, from the enthu- siasm of the poet and artist in the moment of creation, trom the ignorance which reflects but little and scarcely acts otherwise than spontaneously, that is to say, from three quarters of the human race. Because 132Na See a 9 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 7h the expression free-will implies the idea of choice, of comparison, and of reflection, these conditions have been imposed on liberty, of which free-will is only one form; free-will is free-volition, that is to Say, vo- lition ; but will is so far from being adequate to the extent of liberty, that even language adds to it the epithet free, thus referring it to something still more general than itself. We may assert the same of spon- taneity. Disengaged from the accompaniment more or less tardy of reflection, of comparison, and of de- liberation, spontaneity manifests liberty in a purer form, but it is only one form of liberty, and not li- berty entire; the fundamental idea of liberty is that of a power which, under whatever form it act, acts only by an energy peculiar to itself} If liberty is distinct from free phenomena,—as the characteristic of every phenomenon is to be more or less determined, but always to be so in some de- gree,—it follows that the peculiar characteristic of liberty in its contrast with free phemonena, is inde- termination. Liberty, therefore, is not a form of ac- tivity, but activity in itself, the indetermined activity, which, precisely on that account, determines itself in one form or another. Hence it follows, once more, that the me or the personal activity, spontaneous or reflective, represents only the determined form of activity, but not its essence. Liberty is the ideal of the me; the me must needs constantly tend to it, without ever arriving at it; it participates in it, but is not identical with it. The me is liberty action, not liberty in power; it is a cause, but a cause phe- nomenal and not substantial, relative and not abso- lute. The absolute me of Fichte is a contradiction. The very terms imply that nothing absolute and sub- stantial is to be found in what is determined, that is to say, phenomenal. In respect to activity, substance then cannot be found but beyond and above all phe- nomenal activity, in power not yet passed into action, 1 See Note L. 133 Chae a ae Mae taupe eo) i 3 lan aed " , ot bs) kee oh eee er nebee Sel Hk aks het bab haan banal alc i gh tae | ie ey d 2 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. in the indetermined essence which is capable of self- determination, in liberty disengaged from its forms, which limit while they determine it. We are thus arrived then, in the analysis of the me, by the way of psychology still, at a new aspect of ontology, at a substantial activity, anterior and superior to all phe- nomenal activity, which produces all the phenomena of activity, survives them all and renews them all, immortal and inexhaustible in the destruction of its temporary manifestations. And it is a remarkable fact, again, that this absolute activity, in its develop- ment, assumes two forms parallel with those of reason, namely, spontaneity and reflection. These two ele- ments are found in one sphere as well as the other, and the principle of both is always a substantial causality. Activity and reason, liberty and intelli- gence, are therefore intimately combined with each other in the unity of substance. The last phenomenon of consciousness, which we have not yet analyzed, sensation, would require simi- lar developments, but thé time does not admit of them. I must content myself with afew words, which think- ers will comprehend, and which will serve at least as a touch-stone for my future-labours-on-the philosophy of natire. Sensation isa phenomenon of consciousness no less incontestable than either of the others ; now if this phenomenon is real, as no phenomenon is sufficient to itself, reason which-acts-under the-law_of causality and of substatice, compels us to-refer the phenomenon of-sensation-to.an existing cause; and as this cause is evidently not the me, it is necessary that reason should refer sensation to another cause, for the action of reason is irrestible 3 it refers it therefore to a cause foreign to the me, placed beyond the influence of the me, that is to Say, to an external cause; this is our notion of the outward world as opposed to the inward world, which the me constitutes and fills, our notion of an external object as opposed to the subject 134of Oe Sees ry ie I a pat ena a ae peer coat Ce Lh ok en erent EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 73 Cat ah which is personality itself, our notion of passivity as opposed to liberty. But let us not be deceived by the expression passivity; for the me is not passive and cannot be so, since it consists in free activity ; neither is the object any more passive, since it is made known to us only in the character of cause, of active force. Passivity therefore is nothing but a relation between two forces which act on each other. Vary and mul- tiply the phenomenon of sensation, reason always and necessarily refers it to a cause which it successively charges, in proportion to the extent of experience, not with the internal modification of the subject, but with the objective qualities capable of producing them, that is to say, it developes the notion of cause, but without departing from it, for qualities are always causes, and ean be known only as such. The external world there- fore is nothing but an assemblage of causes corre- sponding to our real or possible sensations ; the rela- tion of these causes with each other is the order of the world. The world accordingly is of the same stuff with ourselves, and nature is the sister of man ; it is active, living, animated like him; and its history is a drama no less than our own. Besides, as the development of the personal or hu- man force takes place in consciousness, in some sort, under the auspices of reason, which we recognise as our law even when we violate it; so the external forces are necessarily conceived of as submitted to laws in their development, or, to speak more correctly, the laws of external forces are nothing but their mode of development, the constancy of which forms what we call regularity. Force in nature 1s distinct from its law, as personality in us 1S distinct from reason ; distinct, I say, and not separate 5 for all force carries ‘ts law with it and manifests it in its action and by its Now, all law supposes a reason, and the laws manifested in an with action. ) of the world are nothing but reason as mal the world. Here then is a new relation of m Nature, like humanity, ts composed of laws nature. d of activit nd in thi ee Ivity; and 1 this and of forces, of reason and OF acliVily; § 135PiawLiaciee 13533) (ot bas Ua ae ne a eee rere a oie Saeaik / epee nee re See marae Ste f Say, every phenomenal cause and every phenomenal 136 74 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. point of view, the two worlds are again brought closely together. Ts there nothing further? As we have reduced the laws of reason and the modes of free force to two, could we not also attempt a reduction of the forces of nature and of their laws? Could we not reduce all the regular modes of the action of nature to two, which in their relation with the spontaneous and the reflec- tive action of the me and of reason, would exhibit a still more intimate harmony than that which we have Just indicated between the internal and the exterral world? It will be perceived that I here allude to ex- pansion and concentration ; but so long as methodical labours shall not have converted these conjectures into certainty, I will hope and be silent; I will content myself with remarking that the philosophical conside- rations which reduce the notion of the external world to that of force have already gained currency, and se- ceretly preside over modern Physics. What physical inquirer, since Euler, seeks any thing in nature but forces and laws? Who now speaks of atoms? And even molecules, the old atoms revived,—who defends them as any thing but an hypothesis? Ifthe fact be incontestable, if modern Physies be now employed only with forces and laws, I draw the rigorous conelu- sion from it, that the science of Physies, whether it know it or not, is no Jonger material, and that it be- came spiritual when it rejected every other method than observation and induction, which can never lead to aught but forces and laws. - Now what is there ma- terial in forces and laws? The physical sciences then themselves have entered into the broad path of an en- lightened Spiritualism; and they have only to march with a firm step, and to gain a more and more pro- found knowledge of forces and laws, in order to arrive at more important generalizations. Let us go still further. Asitisalaw already recognised of the same reason which governs humanity and nature, to refer every finite cause and every multiple law, that is toEXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM, 75 law, to something absolute which leaves nothing to be sought beyond it in relation to existence, that is to say, to a substance ; so this law refers the external world composed of forces and laws to a substance, which must needs be a cause in order to be the subject of the causes of this world, which must needs be an intelli- gence in order to be the subject of its laws, a sub- Stance, in fine, which must needs be the identity of activity and intelligence. We are thus arrived ac- cordingly, for the second time, by observation and in- duction in the external sphere, at precisely the same point to which observation and induction have suc- cessively conducted us in the sphere of personality and in that of reason; consciousness in its triplicity is therefore one; the physical and moral world is one, science is one, that is to say, in other words, God is One. Let us sum up these ideas, and at the same time more fully unfold them. In returning within our consciousness, we have seen that the relation of reason, of activity,-andof.sensa- tion is so intimate, that one of these elements being civen, the Other two immediately come into exercise, and that this element is the free activity. Without the free activity or the me, consciousness does not exist, thatis to say, the other two phenomena, whether they take place or not, areas if they weré not, for-the mé which does not yet exist,. Now the me does not exist for itself, does not and cannot perceive itself, but by distinguishing itself from sensation, which by that act is perceived, and which thus takes its place in consciousness. But as the me cannot perceive itself, nor perceive sensation except by.pereeiving, that is to say, by the intervention of reason, the necessary prin ciple of all perception, of all knowledge, it follows that the exercise of reason is contemporary with the exercise of personal. activity.and_with sensible impres- sions. . The triplicity of consciousness, the elements of which are distinct and irreducible one to the “ee : éen eine ie Lin. aera aS ater ee ad : 1: ; ‘ Y nnn ee Bic LRabeERInT ae - 76 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. is then resolved into.a single fact, as the unity.of een- sciousness exists only on condition of that triplicity. Moreover, if the three elementary phenomena of conselousness are contemporary, if reason immedi- ately illumines the activity which then distinguishes | itself from sensation ; as reason is only the action of the two great laws of causality and of substance, it is necessary that reason should immediately refer the action to an internal cause and substance, namely, the me, and sensation, to an external cause and sub- stance, the not-me; but as it cannot rest in them as causes truly substantial, both because their contin- gent and phenomenal character takes from them every claim to being absolute and substantial, and because as they are two, they limit each other, and thus ex- clude each other from the rank of substance, it is ’ necessary that reason should refer them to a single substantial cause, beyond which there is nothing to be sought in relation to existence, that is to say, in respect of cause and substance, for existence is the identity of both. The substantial and causative ex- istence, therefore, with the two finite causes or sub- stances in which it developes itself, is made known at the same tine with these two causes, with the differ- | ences which separate them, and the bond of nature na which connects them, that is to say, ontology is given to us at the same time in its completeness, and even at the same time with psychology. Thus, in the frst fact of consciousness, the psychologiéat unity_in its triplicity is found, so to speak, face to face with the ontological unity in. its parallel triplicity.. The fact of consciousness, which comprehends three internal elements, reveals to us also three external elements. Every fact of consciousness is psychological-and-onto- logical at once, and contains already the three great ideas which science afterwards divides or brings to- | gether, but which it eannot go beyond, namely, man, nature, and God. But man, hature, and God, as re- vealed by consciousness, are not vain formulas, but ee and realities. “Man is not in the consciousness > eeeEXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. VF without nature, nor nature without man, but both meet together in their opposition and their recipro- city, as causes, and as relative causes, the nature of which is always to develope themselves, and always by each other. The God of consciousness is not an abstract God, a solitary monarch exiled beyond the limits of creation, on the desert throne of a silent Eternity, and of an absolute existence which resem- bles even the negation of existence. He isa God at once true and real, at once substance and cause, always substance and always cause, being substance only in so far as he is cause, and cause only in so far as he is substance; that is to say, being absolute cause, one and many, eternity and time, space and number, essence and life, indivisibility and totality, principle, end and centre, at the sum- mit of Being and at its lowest degree, infinite and finite together, triple, in a word, that is to say, at the same time God, nature, and humanity. In fact, if God be not every thing, he is nothing; if he be ab- solutely indivisible in himself, he is inaccessible ; and consequently he is incomprehensible, and his incom- prehensibility is for us the same as his destruction. Incomprehensible as a formula and in the school, God is clearly visible in the world vhich manifests him, for the soul which feels and possesses him. Every where present he returns, as it were, to him- self in the consciousness of man, of which he indi- rectly constitutes the mechanism and the phenomenal triplicity by the reflection of his own nature and of the substantial triplicity of which he 1s the absolute identity. ! Having gained these heights, philosophy becomes more luminous as well as more grand ; universal har- mony enters into human thought, enlarges it, and gives it peace. The divorce of ontology and psychology, of speculation and obsérvation, of science and con) mon sense, is brought to an end by a method which 1 See Note M. 139 Ste oe Se oe Sa ce tea Ne ee 8 og og ae = —* *f ; —ae ot Lestat be Surat Mat a man, if he knows himself, knows all the rest, nature 78 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. arrives at-speculation by observation;-at ontology by psychology, in order then to confirm observation by speculation, psychology by ontology, and which, start= ing from the immediate facts-of Gonsciousness, of which the common sense of the human race is com- -posed;-derives-from-them.the-seience which contains nothing more than common sensé; but Which elevates it to its purest.and most rigid form, and-enablées it to comprehend itself, But I here approach a funda- mental point. v. If every fact of consciousness contains all the human faculties, sensibility, free activity, and reason, the me, the not-me,.and their absolute identity ; and if every fact of consciousness be equal to itself, it follows that every man who has the consciousness-ef himself pos- sesses;-and.cannot but possess, all the ideas that are necessarily contained in consciousness. Thus every and God at the same time with himself. Every man believes in his own existence, every man therefore believes in the existence of the world and of God; every man thinks, every man therefore thinks God, if we may so express it ; every human proposition, re- flecting the consciousness, reflects the idea of Unity and of Being that is essential to consciousness ; every human proposition therefore contains God 5 every man who speaks, speaks of God, and every word is an act of faith and a hymn. Atheism is a barren formula, a negation without reality, an abstraction of the mind, which cannot assert itself without self- destruction; for every assertion, even though nega- tive, is a judgment which contains the idea of being, and, consequently, God in his fulness. Atheism 18 the illusion of a few _sophists, who place their liberty — In opposition to their reason, and are unable even to give an account to themselves of what they think ; but the human race, which is never false to its consciousness, and never places itself in contradic- tien to its laws, possesses the knowledge of God, 140EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. elieves in him, and never ceases to proclaim him. ! in fact, the human race believes in reason, and can- not Hut believe in it, in that reason which is ma- nifested in consciousness, in a momentary relation with the me,—the pure though faint reflection of that primitive light which Hows from the bosom of the eternal substance, which is at once Substance, Cause, Intelligence. Without the manifestation ‘of reason in our cOhsciousness, there could be no knowledge,—neither psychological, nor still less, ontological. Reason is,1n.some_sort, the bridge be- tween-psychology.and_ontology,. between conscious- ness and being.5.di.rests at the same time on both ; it descends from God and ¢ approaches man 3 it makés its appearance in the enc ee S, as a guest who brings intelligence of an unknown world, of which it at once presents the idea and awakens the want. If reason were personal, it would have no value, no authority, beyond the limits of the individual subject. If it remained in the condition of primitive substance, without manifestation, it would be the same for the me, which would not know itself, as if it were not. It is necessary therefore that the intelligent substance should manifest itself; and this mat nifestation is the appearance of reason in the consciousness. Reason then is literally a revelation, a necessary and univer- sal revelation, which is wanting to nu man, a and which saliehtens every man on his coming into the world: stein omnem hominem venientem in hune mundum. Reason is the necessary mediator between God and man, the Adyog of Pythagoras and Plato, the Word made flesh, which serves as the interpreter of God and the teacher of man, divine anc human at the same time. It is not, indeed, the absolute God in his ma- jestic individuality, but his manifestation in spirit and in truth; it is not the Being of beings, but it is the revealed God of the ieee race. As God is never wanting to the human race, and never abandons 1 See Note N. L 14 ae Se ee Pace Sor at ee oe ieeee rere +) M EE 80 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. it, so the human race believes in God with an irre- sistible and unalterable faith, and this unity of faith is its own highest unity. If these convictions of faith be combined in every act of consciousness, and if consciousness be one in the whole human race, whence arises the prodigious diversity which seems to exist between man and man, and in what does this diversity consist? In truth, when we appear to perceive at first view so many differences between one individual and another, one country and another, one epoch of humanity and an- other, we feel a profound-emotion of melancholy ; and are tempted to regard an intellectual develop- ment so capricious, and even the whole of humanity, as a phenomenon without consistency, without gran- deur, and without interest. But it is demonstrated by a more-attentive observation of facts, that no-man—> isa stranger to either of the three great-ideas-which constitute -eonsélousness, namely, personality or.thes liberty of man, impersonality or the necessity of na- ture,-and-the-Providence-of-God. Every man com- prehends these three ideas immediately, because he found them at first and constantly finds them again within himself. The exceptions to this fact, by their small number, by the absurdities which they involve, by the difficulties which they create, serve only to exhibit, in a still clearer light, the universality of faith in the human race, the treasure of good sense deposited in truth, and the peace and happiness that there are fora human soul in not discarding the con- victions ofits kind. Leave out the exceptions which appear from time to time in certain critical periods of history, and you will perceive that the masses which alone have true existence, always and every where live in the same faith, of which the forms only vary. But the masses do not possess the secret of their convictions. Truth is not science. Truth is fer all; science for few. All truth exists in the hu- man race; but the human race is not made up of phi- losophers. In fact, philosophy is the aristocracy of 142 t/ paloma Neate a Kona ee eeEXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. Sl the human species. Its glory and its strength, like that of all true aristocracy, is not to separate itself from the people, but to sympathize and identify itself vith them, to labour for them, while it places its foundation in their hearts. Philosophical science is the rigorous account which reflection renders to itself of the ideas which it has not created. We have already shown, that reflection supposes a previous operation-to-whieh-it-applies itself, since reflection 1s merely a.return upon what has. gone-before. If there had been no prior operation, there could have been 1o-volintary repetition of this operation, that is to say, no reflection ; forreflection 1s nothing else ;_ it does not produce.; it verifies and dev elopes. There i8 therefore actually nothing morein reflection than in the operation _w hich precede sit, than in spon- taneity ; only reflection is..a.degree.of. intelligence, rarer and more elevated than spontaneity, and with the condition, moreover, that it faithfully represent it, and develope without d estroying it Mares in my opinion, humanity. aS-8 ASS TS spontancous and not reflective; humanity is inspired. ‘The divine breath which is in it, always and every where reveals to it all truths under one form or another, according to the place and the time. The soul of humanity is a poetical soul which discovers in itself the secrets of beings 3 and gives utterance.to them. in prophetic chants_which ning from.ageto.age. At the side of humanity is p! hilosophy, which listens with attention, gathers up its w oy. registers them, if we may so speak ; and when the moment of inspiration has pass- ed aw ay, presents them with reverence to the Te ra ble artist who had no consciousness of his genius, and who often does not recognise his own w a Spontaneity is the genius of human nature 5 refle tion is the genius of a few individuals. The differ- ence between reflection and spontaneity is the only difference possible in the identity of intelligence. I have poe as I flatter myself, that this is the only real difference in th e forms of reason, in those Vv : = a 495 oO PON cheney TN See See Sen eeHeoicintels SOC ETS , A peneasennal er Dod SGML ns nalaesconalbis ater coehaansebateota ns ALESIS RNG TENT Te ane : ; “yey bes fet Soe i ee 82 EXPOSITION OF BCLECTICISM. of activity, perhaps even in those of life; in history also, it is the only difference which separates a man from his fellow-men. Hence it follows that we are all penetrated with the same spirit, are all of the same family, children of the same Father, and that the brotherhood of man admits of no differences but such as are essential to individuality. Considered in this aspect, the differences of individuals exhibit some- thing noble and interesting, because they testify to the independence of each of us, and separate man from nature. We are men and not stars; we have movements that are peculiar to ourselves; but all our movements, however irregular in appearance, are accomplished within the circle of our nature, the two extremities of which are points essentially similar. Spontaneity is the point of departure; reflection the point of return; the entire circumference is the in- tellectual life; the centre isthe Absolute Intelligence which governs and explains the whole. These prin- ciples possess an inexhaustible fruitfulness. Go from human nature to external nature, you will there find spontaneity under the form of expansion ; reflection, under that of concentration. Extend your view to universal existence ; external nature there performs the part of spontaneity, humanity, that of reflection. In fine, in the history of the human species, the Ori- ental world represents that first movement, the vi- gorous spontaneity of which has furnished the race with an indestructible basis; and the Pagan world, and still more the Christian, represents reflection which gradually developes itself, combines with spon- taneity, decomposes and recomposes it with the li- berty which is its essence, while the spirit of the world hovers over allits forms, and remains at the centre ; but under allits forms, in every world, at all degrees of existence, physical, intellectual, or histori- cal, the same integrant elements are discovered in their variety and their harmony. Such is the character. of the system, in which, at 144———EXPOSITION@@E ECLECTICIS} the end of the year 1818, all the labour of the pre- ceding years terminated ; asystem undoubtedly very imperfect, and which has since been enlarged and modified in my mind. But I should still defend th. essential elements of this system, whicl the advantage, in spite of its defects, at th when it was conceived and set forth, of realising in part_the=denominant idea.of my whole life, that of reconstructing the eternal .convictions-of man in har- Meny..with-the spirit of the age, and of thus arrivin at unity, but by the path of the experimental method, This is the-peint.-of view.in which it should bé ex- amined..and.judged. se 0 This system was at the foundation of my teaching in the year 1818 ; and it is to this, that all the Frag- ments of which the present volume is composed, directly or indirectly relate; it forms their unity, and may serve as a clew in the midst of articles on differ- ent subjects and with different dates. ‘This is the li- \ 5 ¢ mit of my researches so far as the year 1819; and i | Tot] > : 1s A hictamesl de the foundation of all the dogmatic and histerical de- velopments of my teaching for the succeeding years. 4 Pe ce If we look at it, we find that the system which has a It was also applied from that time to the aiff doctrines which compose the history of philosophy, and numerous traces of this will be found in these Fragments ; but it has since assumed, bot 1D my own mind and in-my_labours,.animporiance of which it is impossible here to present.the slightest idea. I will only say that since 1819, my dogmatic and systematic point of view being somewhat confirmed and elevated, I quitted speculation for_a considerable time, or. rather, [pursued and realised it, by applying it more_ directly than.I.had.yet.done.to.the history of philosophy... Always faithful to the psychological method,-L-intredueed-it-into-history,.and cononung diferent systems with the facts of consciousness, de- manding of each a complete representation 01 con- NO. XXXII. G SO\- '| the path is open. 84 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. sciousness without being able to obtain it, I soon ar- rived at the result which my subsequent studies have so fully developed, namely ; that every system _re- presents an order of phenomena and of ideas,which is perfectly real and true, but which is not-the-only ,one-in consciousness, although in the system it holds van almost exclusive rank ; whence it follows that the |imdividual systems—are not false but. incomplete ;— | whenee—it—follows again- that~by~combining the va- | rious incomplete systems, we.should.have_a complete philosophy, corresponding to..the totality of con- isciousness. From_this,.to a true historical system, umiversal and precise,.at once, the interval is~un=— doubtedly great; but the first step has been taken ; I shall undertake to complete the ~work ;“T'shall undertake, in spite of every obstacle, to pursue the reform of philosophical studies in France, in illustrating the history of philosophy by a system, and.in.demonstrating this system by the whole his- tery_of philosophy.» With this object is connected the series of my _ historical publications, the whole. scope of which my friends only can comprehend ; and in pursuance of this plan, my teaching in the years 1819 and 1820, entered upon the history of the-philosephy_of the eighteenth century, in. France, in England, and.in-Germany. I may, perhaps, pub- lish those Lectures; but my previous Lectures from 1815 to 1818, will never see the light. They are studies which I have made before the public, and which I trust will not have been without use in re- storing a taste for philosophical subjects among my countrymen, and in communicating a salutary direc- tion to the pupils of the Normal School, and to the young men who attended my Courses in the Faculty of Literature. But I condemn them myself to ob- livion; they are too far-belrind the point at which we have all now arrived. I should even have to ask pardon for these Fragments which relate to those Lectures, and which certainly are inferior to them, if they had not been already printed, and their re- 146EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. 85 publication were not their final burial. I have thought, moreover, that without possessing sufficient generality to enter into.the wants_of the moment, and the discussions which the quarrels of parties have made the order-of-the day,..they might be useful in recalling the attention to _psyc chological details, arid without doubt, and destitute-of-all Lapparent-e grandeur, but which should never be lost sight of, since they are the legitimate point of departure for all the de- velopments which can be received by philosophy. Ihave also thought that at_a time when the parties of_industry-.and_of_theocracywere both endeavour- ing to seduce the mind from the broad and impartial paths of science, it was almost a duty for me to raise an independent flag, which is perhaps not forgotten, and to remind the friends of truth.of-the.only philo- sophical method which, in my opinion, can conduct tomits that’ method of observation and induction, which has raised all the physical sciences so high, and has carried them so far; which gives a movement to thought, at once vast and regular ; which_rests-only on Giivian nature, but w ich’ embraces the whole of human naturé; and with it attains the Infinite ; which _imposes-no_system on reality, but-undertakes-tode- monstrate that reality, if it_be entire, is_itselfa.sys- tem, a system-c omplete and living, in the conscious- ness and beyond the consciousness, in the Universe and in history ; that method>~which pone to itself no other task than that of co ae hending things as they are, accepts, explains, and respects every thing, apd destroys nothing but the artificial arrangements of exclusive hypotheses; that severe method, whose circumspect. character con ceals and justifies boldness, and be eyond which ali the move- ments of the mind are mere ely struggles without fruit for a or for others, for science, for the country, or for the future Finally, I have wished to take a formal leave of three years of my life which are endeared to me by the remembrance of the obscure and painful labour Ss Ay7 = Es E ay as : fe 3 f ie 86 EXPOSITION OF ECLECTICISM. with which they were filled; I here salute them for the last time and bid them a final adieu. It is from 1819 that my future publications will henceforth be dated.NOTES. NOTE C.—PaAcE 12. ME AND NOT-ME. THE expression equivalent to this is now so common in the philosophical language of continental Europe, that I might perhaps justly be charged with affectation, if I were to avoid the use of it in translating. At any rate, I could not do so, without an awkward circumlocution, by which nothing would be gained, either in respect of significance or grace. No one, indeed, is bound to be more scrupulous with regard to the in- troduction of foreign modes of speech into our native English, than the conscientious translator. If I have transgressed in this way, in the present instance and in some others, it has been by compulsion and not by choice ; and I shall look for the most speedy forgiveness from those who are best aware of the necessity of the case. As regards the phrase in question, it seems to be as forcible as any that could be selected for the ex- pression of the abstract idea of personality and its opposite ; an ¥dea which lies at the foundation of all philosophical inquiries concerning the higher nature of man. The old English writers were in the habit of using the corresponding Latin term, to ex- press the same idea; but I think this is more barbarous even than the modern phrase; and with the example of some good writ- ers and translators who have preceded me, I must solicit for it a hospitable reception from the reader. NOTE D.—Pace 22. PANTHEISM. “ Arrstorzie in his book on Xenophanes, Gorgias, and Zeno, Simplicius in his Commentary on the Physics of Aris- totle,2, and Theophrastus in Bessarion,® have preserved the substance of the argumentation, by which Xenophanes demon- strated that God had no beginning and could not have been born. It is impossible not to experience a profound and al- most a solemn impression, in considering this argumentation, 1 Ch. 3: 2 Ibid. 3 Contra calumniatorem Platonis, I. 11, p. a4 bod i hh oli Laine taal nas ee eT et et ee arlaeh Cheenti) MRAM Miah ae eer 88 NOTES. when we reflect that it is perhaps .the first time, at least in Greece, that the human mind has attempted to give an account to itself of its faith, and to convert its belief into theories. It is curious to be present at the birth of religious philosophy ; we behold it there, if we may so speak, in its swathing clothes $ as yet, it does but stammer on those formidable problems ; but it is the duty of the friend of humanity to hear with attention, and to gather up with care the half-formed words which escape from it, and to salute with respect the first appearance of rea- soning. Here is the'argumentation of Xenophanes, as preserv- ed by Aristotle and Simplicius. ‘It is impossible to apply to God the idea of birth, for every thing which is born must of necessity be born either of something like or of something un- like. Now each of these cases is impossible, for the like has no action on the like, and can no more produce it than it car be produced by it. On the other hand, the unlike cannot be born of the unlike ; for if the strongest is born of the weakest, or the greatest of the smallest, or the better of the worse, or on the contrary, the worse of the better, being would proceed from non-being, or non-being from being, which is impossible. God therefore must be eternal.’ We ought to read the same argumentation abridged in Simplicius, and still further reduced in Bessarion; we should not neglect even the passage of Plu- tarch in Eusebius, a passage which, in the midst of grave errors, contains happy illustrations of the fragment of Aristotle, and in which Plutarch expressly acknowledges that Xenophanes has here taken a path peculiar to himself; and in fact Diogenes asserts that Xenophanes was the first to demonstrate that every thing which is born must also perish. We here see the early dawn oi the principle, which was afterwards to become so celebrated : being cannot proceed from non-being, non-being can produce nothing, that is to say, nothing creates nothing. Here is per- haps the first expression of the principle of causality. Xeno- phanes did not invent this principle; it is inherent in the hu- man mind, which possessed it, made use of it, and applied it, or rather was governed by it in all its proceedings, though uncon- sciously ; for that which most escapes the notice of intelligence, is precisely that which lies the deepest in its nature. To draw forth this principle from the depths and obscurity, in which it acts spontaneously and developes itself in a concrete, living, and active form, to unfold it to the light of reflection, and to trans- form it into a law, into an abstract and general formula, of which the mind obtains the consciousness, and which it ex- amines in some sort, as an external object; this is the glory of philosophy. | ‘* The conclusion of this argumentation in Aristotle is that, ‘ since God cannot be born, he cannot perish, as every thing which is born must needs perish, while that which is not born, that is to say, that which does not become a being by means of another, but which is a beg in itself, is eternal.’ This is not 150 —_—_NOTES. 89 merely the principle of causality, it is the distinet conception of accident and of substance; of phenomenal being and of be- ing in itself, and the attributing of the notion of corruptibility to the one, and the notion of incorruptibility and eternity to the other, that is to say, the principle of substance, in all its extent and relations. ‘“The presence of two opposite tendencies in the physics and theology of Xenophanes is evident. It indicates two sorts of antecedents, through which it has passed, and of which it forms the point of reunion. But how has it combined these contrary elements? How is the Pythagorean theology united in Xenophanes with the Ionic physics? This is the question which ought to be settled, for it is precisely this combination which characterizes the original doctrine of Xenophanes, gives it a peculiar physiognomy, and assigns to it an independent yank in the history of the philosophy of this epoch. The Ionic school and the Pythagorean school introduced in- to the Greek philosophy, the two fundamental elements of all philosophy ; namely, physies and theology. We may thus see yaeas on Ceca} philosophy in Greece in possession of the two esse ntial which it turns, the idea of the world and that of God. The two extreme terms of all speculation, accordingly, being given, nothing remains but to discover their relation. Now, the first solution which presents itself to the human mind preoccupied, as it necessarily is, with the idea of unity, is the absorbin of one of the two terms in the other, the identifying of the world with God, or of God with the world, and thus cutting the knot in- stead of untying it. These two exclusive solutions are both per- fectly natural. {tis natural,_—when we possess the feeling of life, of this grand and diversified existence of which we are a part ; when we consider the extent of this visible v same time, the harmony which every where rei beauty which shines through all its parts,—that we should stop with the limits of the senses and the imagination, that we s ,0uld suppose that the beings of which this world is made up are the only beings which exist, that this great whole, so harmonious and so uniform, is the true subject and the last application of the idea of unity, that this whole, in a word, is God. Express this result in the Greek language, and we have Pantheism. Pantheism is the conception of the whole as the only God. <‘ On the other hand, when we discover that the apparent unitv of the whole is only a harmony and not an absolute unity, a harmony which admits an infinite variety, which strongly Te sembles a systematic war and revolution, it 1s no less natural, in that case, to detach from this world the idea of unity which is indestructible in our minds, and, thus detached from the ats perfect model of this visible world, to refer it < an nes being placed above and beyond this world, the sacred ty} : a =e i > conceive | absolute unity, beyond which there 15 nothing to be ¢ Ted es oO le world, and at the ee ee viel tas qo ons in It, and the PTS CRIrepeat nag aetap nena ern Tet tL Uk cele ber abies i, , sais gic neat Shale Mee ELS SO NOTES. or sought. Now, having once arrived at this absolute units if is no lor nger or to dep art from it, and to comp? rehend ho absolute unit ne given asa principle, it is possible ia arrive at bean x8 the consequence; for absolute unity ex- eludes all pl berate, Nothing remains then, i in relation to this consequence but to deny it, or at least, to despise it, and to re- gard the plurality of this visible world as a deceptive shadow of the absolute unity which alone exists, a fall hase iy compre- hen sible, a negation and an evil which we ought to escape from, in order to tend i: neessantly to the only true being, to the abso- lute unity, to hog: Here is the sy stem opposed to Pantheism. Call it whatever you please, it is nothing but the idea of unity applied lees to God, as Pantheism is the same idea applied ex clusively to the world. ‘* Now, once more, these two exclusive solutions of th 1e fun- damental pro pee em are both equally natural; and this is so true tha S nile return at every great epoch of the history of phi losophy,. with the modifications which are caused by the progress of time, but at the bottom always the same; and we may even say, that the his istory of their perpetual conflict, and of the aos nate dominion of ene or the other, has hitherto com- posed the history of Ee epephy itself. It is because these two eGlwnine belong to the foundations of thought, that it constaz atly ‘eproduces them, with an _egual inability ‘to dis spense with one or the other, and to satisf fy itself with either alone. In fact, neither taken separately, is sufficient for the human mind; and these two ) +1 ws ieY econ A Sebe s te points of view, so natur al, and consequently so durable and so vital, exclusive: as they are by themselves, for this very reascn, are cually defective and unsatisiactory, A cry is raised again e antheism. All the ability in the world ‘an never absolve t ce or reconcile 1¢ with the feel. ings of the aes race. If we are consistent, all our efforts are vain; we can arrive with it m sort rerely at a sort of 5 oul of the world as the e principle of things ; at fai tality as the only law; at the confounding together of good and evil; that is to sa LY, at their destruction, in the bosom of a vague and abstract unity, witl 10ut any fixed subject; for there is certain! y no absolute unity in any of the parts of this world taken separate ly; how eS on should it exist in their ageregate? As no effort can de- ve the Ab solute and the Nec cessary from the Relative and the added to itself as often as a ntingent, SO also from plura ality, you a se, NO generalization can derive u nity ; totality only is thus obtained. At bottom, Pantheism turns on the confusion of these two ideas, which are so essentially distinct. On the other hand, unity without plurality is no more real, than plu- rality without 1 unity is true. An absolute nny which does not dee fron itself, or which projects only a shadow, may over- whelm us with its grandeur, 1 may alate us with its mys- terious charm ; but it is all in vain; it does not enlighten the mind: at401 Ti J (} ming; 1¢ 1s ioudly contradicted by those faculties, which are in= 2 A OTES. posed c & our active and moral faculties, which would bea mockery, which would be an accusation again: st their atbOn: if the theatre in which they are called to exerci ise the amiselves, were only an illusion and a snare. A God without a world is no less false than a world without a God; a cause without effects which manifest it, or an indefinite series of effects without a primary cause; a substance which should never be developed, ora rich development of phenomena without a substance which sustains them ; reality borrowed only from the Visible or the Invisible ; in both these extremes, there are equal error and equal danger, equal forgetfulness of human nature, equal forgetfulness of one of the essential sides of cHoupht and of things. Between these two abysses, the good sense of the human race has long pursued its path ; far from systems and from schools, the human race has long believed with equal certainty in God and in the world. It believes in the world as a real and permanent effect, which it refers to a cause, not to animpotent and contradictory cause, which, forsaking its effect, would thus de estroy it, but toa cause relation with this world, and which attest its Tek and by al! ] ; CC pated ~ond worthy of the name, which constantly produci ng and reproduc- ing, deposits i its stren igth and its beauty, without ever exhaust- ing them in its work; it believes in the wor rid as an aggregate au 4 of phenom nena, which would cease to exist the moment the eternal substance should cease to sustain them; it believes in the wor de as the visil he manifestation of a hidden UARODE. which ees cs to it beneath this veil, and which it adores in nature and in its own consciousness. This is what, as a mass, the tein lieves, The glory of true philosophy would - to accept universal faith, and to give a legitimate ex- planation of it. But through want of supporting its elf on the human race, and of taking common sense for its gu ide, phi- losophy, hit coin ct bmet 7 ~ ele uy herto straying on the right hand and left, } has fallen by turns into one or the cues extreme of systems Oe are ec qually true in one relation and equally ft false in another; and both vicious for Poe same reason, because they are ‘equally hi , A fe exclusive and incomplete. ‘This is the everlasting rock to os which philosophy is Sapowdl ”___Nouveauxy Fragmens, pp. 8, et seq. Bs NOTE E.—Pace 27. PHILOSOPHY OF ENTHUSIASM. <‘T woLp that the highest degree of knowledge is intuitive knowledge. This know vledge , in many cases, —for e example, in regard to time, space, persone al identity, the Infinite, all sub- stantial existence, as on as the Beautiful and the Good, has this characteristic, that it is not founded on the senses or on AL l 5 3 Sls a een Seihaan ae ah at sere SR On SR APR OS BRSCe ET ae eine rn ee eta ety v4 an 99 NOTES. consciousness, but on reason, which, without the intervention of reasoning, arrives at its objects and conceives them with certainty. Now it is an attribute inherent in reason to believe in itself; this is the origin of faith; if therefore intuitive reason is above inductive and demonstrative reason, the faith of reason in itself, in intuition, is purer and more elevated than the faith of reason in itself, in induction and demonstration. Let it be remembered that the truths which reason intuitively discovers are not arbitrary, but necessary ; that they are not relative, but absolute; the authority of reason is absolute; it is therefore a characteristic of the faith which is attached to reason, that it is absolute like reason itself. Such are the admirable character- istics of reason, and of the faith of reason in itself. ** This is not all. Whenever we interrogate reason concern- ing itself, whenever we demand of it its peculiar principle and the source of the absolute authority which characterizes it, we are compelled to perceive that this reason is not our own, in the sense that itis we who constitute it, it is not in the power of our will, to cau not to give us such or such atruth. Independently of our will, reason intervenes, and certain conditions being accomplished, gives us, or rather imposes upon us, those truths. Reason is manifested in us, although it is not identical with us, and can never be confounded with our personality ; reason is imper- sonal. Whence then comes this wonderful guest? What is the principle of this reason which enlightens us, without be- longing to us? This principle is no other than Ged, the first and last principle of every thing. Now if reason has hitherto cherished an unbounded faith in itself, when it refers itself to its principle, when it knows that it comes from God, the faith which it before had in itself inereases, not in degree, but in nature. It receives, if I may so speak, all the superiority of the eternal substance over the finite substance, in which it is manifested. Faith thus gains a double energy in relation to those truths which the supreme reason makes known to us within these shadows of time, within the limits of our own frailty. “‘ Reason is thus elothed in its own eyes with divine autho- rity on account of the principle on which it rests. Now this state of reason which listens to and regards itself as the echo of God on earth, with the peculiar and extraordinary charac- teristics which then distinguish it, is what we call enthusiasm. The word is a sufficient explanation of the thing. Enthusiasm is the breath of God within us; it is immediate intuition opposed _to induction and demonstration; it js primitive spontaneity opposed to the ulterior development of reflection ; it Is the perception of the loftiest truths by reason, when it is most independent both of the senses and of our personality. Enthusiasm, in its highest degree, and, so to speak, in its crisis, 18 peculiar only to certain individuals, and again to 154 It is not in our power, se reason to give us, orNOTES. 93 eertain individuals in certain circumstances ; but in its faintest degree, enthusiasm is a fact like any other, a fact by no means extraordinary, which does not pertain to such or such a theory, individual, or epoch, but to human nature itself, in all men, in all conditions, and almost at every hour. Itis enthusiasm which produces spontaneous convictions and resolutions, on a small as well as on a large scale, in heroes, and in the feeblest woman. It is enthusiasm which forms the poetic spirit in every thing; and the poetic spirit, thank God, is not the ex- clusive property of poets; it has been given toall menin some degree, more or less pure, more or less elevated ; it appears especially in certain individuals and in certain movements of the life of those individuals who are Poets by way of eminence. It is enthusiasm, moreover, which gives birth to religions; for every religion supposes two things; namely, that the truths which it proclaims are absolute truths, and that it proclaims them in the name of God himself, by whom they are re- vealed. ‘¢ So far all is well, We are still within the sphere of hu- manity and of reason ; for it is reason which composes the foun- dation of faith and of enthusiasm, of heroism, of poetry and of religion; and when the poet or the priest repudiates reason in the name of faith and of enthusiasm, he does nothing else, whether he know it or not, and it is not the concern of either to know what he does, does nothing else, I say—than place one mode of reason above the other modes of the same reason; for if immediate intuition be above reasoning, it still pertains no less to reason; we attempt in vain to repudiate reason, we are always obliged to make use of it. Enthusiasm, therefore, is a rational fact which holds its place in the order of natural facts and in the history of the human mind; but this fact is one of singular delicacy, and enthusiasm can easily be converted into folly. We are here on the doubtful confines of reason and extravagance. Here is the universal, necessary and legitimate principle of religious philosophy, 01 religions, and:of mysticism, a principle which we should not confound with the aberrations which may corrupt it. Thus unfolded and illustrated by analysis, philosophy ought to recognise It, if it wishes to recognise all the essential facts, all the elements of reason and of humanity. ‘¢ Look now at the way in wh I repeat it, is the spontaneous intuition of truth by reason, in- dependent also as it can be of the personality and the senses, of induction and of demonstration,—a state, which we have discovered to be genuine, legitimate, and founded on the na- ture of human reason. But it often happens that the senses and the personality, which inspiration ought to surmount and reduce to silence, still continue and introduce themselves even into inspiration, and combine with it details one material character, which are at once arbitrary, false, ana ing ¢ nea £it ich error begins. Enthusiasm, Se Ee ge eee - Seng et esas eyEs etiat haee erhalinatae - Pot eet REO ET Th casted Mian hikh, alan lal DGC: aLaerscine Na naiakre) ener neennser iat ree gente Se eee aan net acter hel aiad 94 NOTES. It happens, moreover, that they who participate, to a remark- able degree, in that revelation of God, which is made to all men by reason and truth, imagine that it is peculiar to them- selves, that it has been refused to others, not only in the same degree, but totally and absolutely ; they constitute in their own minds, to their advantage, a sort of privilege of inspira- tion ; and as in inspiration we feel the duty of submitting our- selves to the truths which inspiration reveals to us, and the holy mission of proclaiming and spreading them, we often go so far as to suppose that it is also our duty, in submitting our- selves to those truths, to submit others with us; to impose them upon their reception, not by virtue of our personal light and authority, but by virtue of the superior power from which all inspiration proceeds ; bowing the knee before the principle of our enthusiasm and our faith, we wish also to make others bend under the same principle, to cause it to be adored and served for the same reason for which we adore and serve it ourselves. Hence religious authority; hence, in a short time, tyranny. We begin with believing in special revelations made in our favour; we end with regarding ourselves as the delegates of the Deity and of Providence, commissioned not only to enlighten and to save docile spirits, but to enlighten and to save those, whether they will or not, who offer resis- tance to the truth and to God. ‘The folly of enthusiasm soon conducts to the tyranny of enthusiasm.”—_Cours de ? Histoire de la Philosophie, Tom. Il. pp. 478485. The belief that reason and conscience possess an authority superior to that of our personal desires, is one of the common sentiments of humanity. The philosophical validity of this belief is established by Cousin in the above extract, as well as in many other passages of his writings. We find the same doctrine not unfrequently alluded to by the most profound philosophers both of ancient and modern times, but I have never met with any one who has developed it so clearly, and pointed out its foundation in human nature, with so much pre- cision, as Cousin has done in this passage, in the first and second Prefaces to the F ragmenis in the Programme of his Course on Absolute Truths, and in the sixth Lecture of his Intreduction to the History of Philosophy. Cousin himself quotes these striking expressions of Fenelon from his treatise on the Existence of God in illustration of his own views. They are doubtless familiar to most of my readers; but they ‘Tn truth, my reason is in deserve their repeated attention, myself; for I must constantly return within, in order to find it. But the superior reason which corrects me when neces- sary, and which I consult, does not belong to me; it makes no part of myself. Accordingly, that which appears to us the 156NOTES. most constantly, which seems to form the very essence of our- selves, I mean our reason, is that which is least of all our property, which we ou treasure. own ght the most to regard as a borrowed We receive, every moment, without cessation, reason superior to ourselves, just as we constantly breathe the air which is a foreign substance, or as we constantly see the objects around us by the light of the sun, the rays of which are bodies foreign to our eyes. There is an interior school, in which man receives what he can neither give himself, nor ob- tain from other men, who live like him on what is borrowed. Where is this perfect reason which is so near me, and yet so distinct from me? Where is this supreme reason? Is it not the God whom I seek ?” Cousin refers also to Bossuet, Introduction & la Philoso- phie. Ch. IV. Sec ‘t. O—9, and to the whole system of Ma- lebranche. 2 G& The excellent Reinhold, in the latter part of his philosophi- eal career, seems to have had a glimpse of the necessity of this doctrine, in order to escape from the too subjective conclu- sions of Kant. He failed, however, to reduce it toa satis factory systematic form, and probably never comprehended it in its full extent. The first hint of the independence of reason appears to have been suggested to him by his friend Bardili. An interesting account of the operations of his mind in regard _to this point is given by his biegrapher. ‘‘ Just before the conclusion of the century, late in the autumn of 1799, Reinhold became acquainted with Bardili’s Outlines of Logic, which had been recently published, Al- though he was not satisfied with the language and the tone of this book, his attention was strongly aroused by its principal thought, which, the more he considered it in a clear light, appeared to him to be important and true, it was a thought to which he had nearly approached himself in this expression, ‘that there is a power in a human being to perceive the being of God above nature, in a manner which transcends the acti- vity of our individual conception.’ This fundamental thought, as it presented itself to Reimhold, may be expressed in the fol- lowing propositions. Reason, as it is in itself, must be distin- guished from reason, as it is exhibited in human conscious- ness. Reason in itself is the manifestation of God, the prin- ciple of all being and knowing. It displays Hoo in our con- sciousness, where its development is conditioned by the na- ture of sensible intuition, and inseparably united with that, assumes the character of our human mode of thought; in the first place, by our reference of variety to unity, of consequen- ees to grounds, of effects to causes, of actions aug by the recognition of design, calculation, the ada “— he aCores Sit ad Se athe haies | Se ri le tn SaTnds betaai nian beanslaceaiaoala Aa musa) AK sa et eee ern eee er atetaal ee 96 NOTES. means to ends in the whole Universe; still further by the re- ference of unity in point of quantity to absolute unity, of grounds to the original ground, of causes to the ultimate cause, of intention and ends to the final end; in short, by the refer- ence of the Universe to the One in which and through which every thing is arranged, grounded, designed, and effected. While the philosopher is conscious of rational activity, which although it appears in man only in union with sensible intui- tion, bears the character of absolute, of divine thought, he will at the same time be conscious in it of the existence of all reality as determined by this thought.”! A quotation to the same effect from a valuable writer of the seventeenth century, is given by Mr. Coleridge in the Aids to Reflection. Mr. Coleridge says, “Take one passa among the many from the posthumous ‘l'racts (1660) of John Smith, not the least Star in that bright Constellation of Cam- bridge men, the cotemporaries of Jeremy ‘Taylor. ‘While we reflect on our own idea of Reason, we know that our own souls are not it, but only partake of it; and that we have it xara webcev and not xar’ oveimy, Neither can it be called a faculty, but far rather a light, which we enjoy, but the source of which is not in ourselves, nor rightly, by any individual, to be denominated mine.” This pure intelligence he then proceeds to contrast with the discursive faculty, i. e. the understanding.’ It is also clear, I think, from many passages in the writings of our great American metaphysician, Jonathan Edwards, that he had an indistinct conception of the character of reason as independent of personality, and involving a divine principle. He expresses this idea, it is true, in the language of his pecu- liar theology, and as Sir James Mackintosh justly observes of him in another connexion, “ thought it necessary to limit his doctrine to his own persuasion, by denying an insight into divine things to those Christians who did not take the Same view with him of their religion.’ No writer, however, is more strenuous in claiming for the human mind, under certain conditions, the power of perceiving and judging spiritual truth. This power is the result of a divine principle imparted to the nature of man, and as such possesses absolute and infallible authority. The essential difference between Edwards and Cousin is that the former regards the intuitive power as a special gift, and limited ] See REINHOLD’s Leben und litterari HOLD, S. 99. Jena, 1825. 2 dids to Refleciion, Note, p. 323, Burlington Ed. ) 158 sches Wirken, von Eranst RgeIN-NOTES. 97 to the sphere of religion, while the latter regards it aS an uni- versal attribute of humanity, and the ground of all knowledge. it would be no difficult thing to bring these views into harmo- ny, were this the place for it. With all its defects, the advo- cacy which Edwards has given to the faculty of spiritual intui- tion, forms an invaluable contribution to a sound religious phi- losophy, and in spite of great differences of opinion, must al- ways make him a favourite author with thinkers who wish to in- vestigate the ultimate grounds of truth. The following pas- sage trom his celebrated Discourse on the “ Reality of Spiritual Light” applies as well to the theory of Cousin, as to that which was had immediately in view by Edwards himself. ‘* It is rational to suppose, that this knowledge should be given immediately by God, and not be obtained by natural means. Upon what account would it seem unreasonable, that there should be any immediate communication between God and the creature? It is strange that men should make any matter of difficulty of it. Why should not he that made all things, still have something immediately to do with the things that he has made? Where lies the great difficulty, if we own the being of a God, and that he created all things out of nothing, of allowing some immediate influence of God on the creation still? Andif it be reasonable to suppose it with respect to any part of the creation, it is especially so with respect to rea- sonable intelligent creatures ; who are next to God in the gra- dation of the different orders of beings, and whose business is most immediately with (40d ; who were made on purpose for those exercises that do respect God, and wherein they have nextly to do with God: For reason teaches, that man was made to serve and glorify his Creator. And if it be rational to suppose that God immediately communicates himself to man in any af- fair, it isin this. It is rational to suppose that God would re- serve that knowledge and wisdom, that is of such a divine and excellent nature, to be bestowed immediately by himself, and that it should not be left in the power of second causes. Spi- ritual wisdom and grace is the highest and most excellent gift that ever God bestows on any creature: In this the highest ex- cellency and perfection of a rational creature consists. _ It is al- so immensely the most important of all divine gifts: It is that wherein man’s happiness consists, and on which his everlasting welfare depends. How rational is it to suppose that God, how- ever he has left meaner goods and lower gifts to second causes, and in some sort in their power, yet should reserve this most excellent, divine, and important of all divine communications, in his own hands, te be bestowed immediately by himself, as a thing too great for second causes to be concerned in? It is ra- tional to suppose, that this blessing should be immediately from God; for there is no gift or benefit that is in itself so nearly related to the divine nature, there is nothing the creature re- 15! Rican ess ierath baie et a Saees ies el at neiesln petes reesei aia eae RAY a —— Settee tases cen le os he oe tae: oem raices areal hai eae ea s > TS 98 NOTES. ceives that is so much of God, of his nature, so much a partici- pation of the Deity: It isa kind 6f emanation of God’s beauty, and is related to Ged as the light is to the sun.” —EDWwakDbDs’S Works, Vol. VIII. First American Edition. NOTE F.—Pace 27. JACOBI—REASON AND UNDERSTANDING. THE description which is here given of Jacobi’s philosophy is, Strictly speaking, applicable only to an early period of his in- vestigations. At the commencement of his career, his attention was almost exclusively directed to the faculty of perceiving su- per-sensual truth, in reference to its actual results, rather than to its character and authority. The primary fact of conscious- ness with which he commenced, was that the human mind is in possession of indestructible convictions, that are not the pro- duct either of sensation or of reasoning. These convictions, as he maintained, are grounded on immediate feeling, and on faith in the reality and certainty of feeling. At this point of his in- quiries he considered reason only as the faculty of reflection, of deducing logical consequences from given premises; but did not recognise it as the highest principle in man, the source of his holiest convictions, the universal and absolute teacher of spiritual truth. He was accordingly accused of making war upon reason in behalf of feeling, of elevating sentiment at the expense of science. His philosophy was reproached with being merely an individual product; grounded on his own personal experience and temperament ; and destitute of a legitimate foundation on universal principles. In the course of his inves- tigations he was led to perceive these defects of his system. His mind was thus turned to a more thorough examination of the nature of reason ; and the conclusions at which he arrived with regard to its ultimate authority, although expressed in a popular rather than in a scientific form, bear a close analogy to those maintained by Cousin, as the principal elements of his own philosophy. Jacobi, it must be confessed, was better able to obtain a genuine insight into super-sensual truth for himself, than to demonstrate its validity for the satisfaction of others. His writings, accordingly, are more valuable for their strong and eloquent statements of the essential facts of our nature, than for their elucidation of the manner in which those facts can be established to the conviction of the scientitic inquirer. They form an excellent preparatory study for the system of Cousin ; while that serves to complete and legitimate the spontaneous perceptions which they present. The leading principles of Jacohi’s philosophy are of such an interesting character, that perhaps, a slight exposition of them 160 ennNOTES. oy be gratifying to the reader. ‘The few extracts which I shall here give from his works, exhibit a favourable view of his personal character, his earnest and unwearied strivings after truth, his taste for the most elevated ideas, and the strong re- ligious tendency of his mind. Perhaps also they will throw some light on the distinction between reason and understand- ing, of which so much account is made by Mr. Coleridge, but which is no where so clearly unfolded as in the writings of Jacobi. f *¢ With the earliest thought that has remained in conscious- ness,” he tells us of himself, “ I have sought for the truth ; and afterwards have waited upon its steps, with every thought of my mind ; but, as at that time, so also at all subsequent pe- riods, never with the vain and idle desire of adorning myself with it, as if I had been the discoverer, as if it had first pro- ceeded from myself. I was craving for a truth, which should not be my creature, but of which I was the creature myself; a truth, which should turn my poverty into fulness; bring light into the darkness which surrounded me; eall forth the dawn before me and within me, according to the instinctive promises of my nature.””! ** My philosophical reflection was never without purpose, but always had a determinate object in view. It was not merely to obtain that self-understanding, which, regardless of its direction, begins sometimes in this way, and sometimes in that, turns first in one quarter and then in another; but I wished to come to the understanding of a specific fact, and that was, the inborn devotion which I felt toan unknown God. If self-understanding should lead me to the conclusion, that all faith in a God to whom we can pray—and devotion recognises no other,—was a folly ; then I should have become wise to my own injury; my great want would not be satisfied, namely, the want to discover God as the primary ground of all know- ledge, and to find him again every where. It was never my object to establish a system for the school; my writings came forth from the depths of my life; they possess an historical connexion; I composed them, as it were, not by my own will, not according to my own pleasure: but impelled by a higher and irresistible power.’’? ‘* The human soul seeks the Eternal, Unchangeable, Self- subsisting, Absolute ; it is not willingly deprived of truth ; but it wishes to discover, not the shadow, but that which casts the shadow. All men inwardly call something the truth, in anti- cipation ; of which they are not yet in possession ; after which they strive; and yet which they could not suppose, unless it 1 Scheiling’s Lehre u. s. Ww. ven FrieprRicH Koppsn, nebst drey Briefen verwandien Inhalts von F. H. JACOBI, quoted in JAcoBI’s Werke, B. rv. Vorrede, S. Xili. : 2 Werke, B. itv. Vorrede, S. xV1 isl NO. XXXIII. H hs eee Seattained Se eae vena ee S 100 WOoOmMpa 4N TES. had been manifested to them in some w vay already. The twi- hight opens their eye, and strangely announces to them a Sun which has no yetarisen. ‘The morning has broke, but the day has not come. God alone celebrates the § sabbath-rest ; but it is for man to keep it holy. Ifthe supposition of this truth be a mere personal de ception of ee ei ngs, if they have not ven the most dim intuition n of it, then is their inquiry vain and idle. * But not vain and idle is this inquiry ;? so prophecies devotion in the pee et AS 1b 1s relig igion which raises Man above the animals, asit is this which makes him a man. it is ANE also which makes him a anes pher. Does religious feeling strive with devout pur- se to fulfil +1 i he will of God, religious in sight more surely S the k nowledge of God, to discover that which is concealed. It was v ue this religion, the central point of all ulosophy had to do, not with the acqui- scientific ee which might be obtained vat phi ii Intercourse with nature was to help Foqumse. ith God. Eternal ly toremain in nature, to orget and to dispense with God init, I was unwilling, ‘* { appeal to an uncona pee resistless feeling a as the pri- di | of all pt hilosophy and religion ; to 1e perception and the consciousness, oe super-sensual. This sense I it from the senses which are conver- d. Such an appeal can be know; a CUuiare Srour a feeling LALA gives man t pe) fe: ry ny n condition of personality and con- he first ‘alr, first good, and first true, he contemplating Spirit ; and because he ows that a spirit ices in him, and Jasob, in one of his latest writin gs, that ‘roneous use of language, Cn account of ental distinction in our intellectual n a- nd understanding. This distinc ition, ” the terms just named, by the nue nta- ec or by the constitt lent laws s of human S of the sens ses, is so far from being an in- SS § be it y; that it is cons tantly recognised by ind , and is essential tial to a o¢ omprehensive ty a aE ve ko O vladoo F 7 > i ® OF Y > + 5 1 >? ] rel those truths whic ioundation of freedom an wisdom, and cf art. ““ We have started with the question, is human reason no- thing but understanding hovering over the intuitions of sense, and with no actual relation to any thing above them ; or is it a higher faculty, actually revealing to man, the True, the Beautiful, and the Good ; and not palming off upon him merely false and hollow images, that are destitute of objective reality ? “We have shewn, that the first is assumed in all philoso- phies since Plato, with and after Aristotle, until the time of Kant, both in the so-called rational philosophies of Leibnitz, Wolf, and Sulzer, and in the professedly merely sensual phi- losophies of Locke, Condillac, and Bonnet. “We could appeal for the truth of this assertion to the proofs given of it by Kant, which incontestably make out, that a reflective understanding, employed only on the sensible world and on itself, as the faculty of intellectual conceptions, whenever it attempts to pass beyond the bounds of sense falls into a void and barren sphere, in which it can only seize its own shadow, extended on all sides to Infinity. Hence, we have further concluded, that every thing super-sensual is a fiction, and the notion of it without significance,—or the knowledge of the super-sensual must be given to man by a higher faculty, which reveals what is true in and above exter- nal phenomena, in a manner of which the senses and the un- derstanding take no cognizance,’ / ‘“* The human reason is to be regarded, on the one hand, as the faculty of perceiving what is divine over and beyond man ; and on the other hand, as the faculty of perceiving what is di- vine in man,—and as this divine element itself. If our rational being were not originally of a Divive Nature, it would be im- possible for it to attain, by any means whatever, to the true 4 } . reasoning nor on e ee by ut On 1tS OWn essential nature q ; | FRY 7 ey | and inherent tendencies. These convictions are numerous and } wT, TAWNXT DO 7 } > ae | ie xy fh | profound in every mind; even in those individuals who stand +h SAC eae onines. kia 1; tue MOSt Upon reaso: ning Th ey are vital, but inexplical le, > y+ WT Om, 7 } we ig t 3 except by our eo ness of them. We believe these i . Yat 2 Q gar a. t : just as we sex white and the meado Such tie Pad eee iE f our \ is the make « OU] Cen rar r yi, Ka Pity ee. } 1 <4} God, and tutu, rity, ¢ placed b d the of reason- ino and : Pe } Ure’ ana experience ; rought within ¢t or SPU any Gencve ‘ ay Vita Bi 5 ‘ : 4 ey Gie Feveaiea tO US bY ene Cy Oz toe Soni tay ards 174 Jd &the Infinite and the Absolute; but they escape as soon as we attempt to seize them by reasoning and e Spaidtied. *¢ Tt is in this w ay, that we explain the eternal influence of these visi ipon humanity, in all of its manifestations. They do not come to man ; they form re Pee ssence of man. Re does not invent them; i. feels them in his soul w!} re 1enever | more powerful than when } te poweriul than when ne attempts with all his might to crush them. C 7? . . ** These convictions assurediy belong to a different sphere : from those at which we leoks within. They are never arrive by experience and syllogism. We need a word to distingui: sh them from others. ‘She w ord faith has been chosen, which, in this sense, is opposed to the snowledge given by experience a nd reas iain: a —Pp. 230-238 al OL metitie QO ICH *¢ It is evident that rel igion is inconsistent with every ma- rial system, under whatever for m it may be presented. Religion i the 2 ack nowledgment of a moral order, of a spiritual world, which the eyes cannot see, nor the hands touch; the recognition of a Ruler of this universe of intelligence and conscience ; the desire to regulate life, in view of thi s order, of this universe, of this Ros What have these eos in i common with c Scr anecles, organs of secretion, or transformed tiks ct LOPE bADE sensations ? Religion gains or loses, lives or dies, in the hu- man mind, in proportion as these systems obtain more or les authority. It canot co-exist with them. If this were not proved by specu! : i | ; ac sy . YA7 I - uight appeal to experienc WV her- ) 3 <8 2 ~ A acd hn ana ree ever the opinions of tk sts have prev wie , religion I ; u has recede | hem; and within our Own notice, we the ] ie eee than unferé eseen of a p! Sian tanght vY MM. Royer-Collard and M. Cous atie ~ it Toure nr ? +} mense advantage to religion, They have es the | shave dissi ipated the prejudices, without appeaene to ch were hostile to its progress VV itavut essing to ne its champions, pelle ey [Rane re > prepared the way for 0 ke she, in Hateeey as a mass, aie es ants, which are provided for by indust ke ae sort, from the chaos of compli- of humanity, which directs stations ; and this spirit has ts; it resembles reli- See eA Oy ta pp hy ote v= te Or toh arene ee el 7 ; retail e: Soretere Pats ae URS he tetas ee ettAili pinecnat secon oeanetedbadenasteiaaivasietaaibietaab wate hans SCE tee at, . 7 % + + rete teats it hires fas Cal enh teal es bet oleae i coat ot tainty | eet Ce) Nee ee ee eet eared de Da ai aeaE as " "i 3 a eee mi ole ries yoy eemre mente sett etvermines Nin ghee omen intial bt titer me +p Sow 114 NOTES. phy to Christianity, we must take into view its general spirit, its acknowledged tendency, rather than isolated and hasty ex- pressions. This spirit and tendency have been already de- scribed. They are eminently favourable to religion; can they be hostile to Christianity ? In order to answer this question, we should consider two things in Christianity, namely, what it came to teach, and the form in which its teachings are clothed. Whatever opinion may be held as to the origin of Christianity and the means by which it was given to man, it is plain that Christianity is a teaching, that it contains a doc- trine, that it sets forth a religious system. It is plain, more- over, that if there be a difference of opinion on any point, it is far more important to be agreed with regard to this religious system, this treasure of ideas so precious in the history of hu- manity, than with regard to the form in which it has been transmitted to us. I confess, therefore, that when I compare the impression which is produced on me by Christianity as a doctrine, and that which is produced by the new philosophical school, I find them connected in the most intimate relations. There is the same spirit, the same starting-point, the same idea concerning humanity, the same tendency, and I have no doubt, that in its developments, the new philosophical school will gra- dually arrive at the same conclusions and the same results. I have no doubt even that it will approach so near to the most mysterious dogmas of Christianity, that, by expressing its con- clusions ina somewhat human form, bv spiritualizing in phi- losophical language the declarations of Jesus and of his Apos- tles, the distance may be made very small and easy to be passed over, The new philosophy is eminently spiritual; so is Christianity ; it is that which first rendered Spiritualism po- pular. The new philosophy places man in consciousness ; it raises him above sensuality ; it recognises in him a destiny and faculties superior to those which the senses can discover, and which consciousness alone reveals. This fundamental idea is at the basis of Christianity. That also places man in con- sciousness ; it raises him above sensation ; it hrings into per- petual contrast, in its expressions at once so sublime and so popular, the flesh and the spirit, the man of consciousness and the man of sensation. “* After having restored the human consciousness, not only as the certain pledge of the existence of the spirit, but also as the organ of a law superior to matter, the new philosophy builds upon it all true and profound morality. It establishes in this sanctuary at once the dignity and the liberty of man. it for ever overthrows Hpicureanism, in whatever form it may be presented, and determines obligation, neither by interest, nor by pleasure, nor by any outward consequence, but by the pure law of morality, announced with authority by the con- science of man. Christianity does nothing else. If there be 176)X NOTES. focal bens QO 9 ve dale share of attention and perseverance, it is this. Pe ae guetly pe recalled man within his conscience. P fae ually he Spiritualized morality. Perpetually he declare d that if we act with a view to enjoyment, with a view to any interest what- ever, and not through respect to conscienc eA d the eternal order of which God is the centr oa re already received our reward. Perpetually he dec ale a oe it external actions are of no importance, except in theirr which they are the expression. Perpet ually he opposed, by every means in his power, the pret ensions of sacerdotal reli- gions, which believe that good is ef ser by passive obedience to legal forms, which lose sight of the conscience, that is to say of the man. : It is on this characteristic of pune ars and on all the wants vhich result from it, that the new school of philosophy attempts to establish the great truths of religion. According to this phi- losophy, it is in the heart rather than in the feflective intellect, that man is to find these truths. Conscience reveals liberty ; liberty, moral order, in opposition to physical order; moral order God and futurity, without which the human soul would be in- complete and mutilated ; without which nothing that takes place in it would have connexion or aim; withou tw No in short, it would be an incomprehensible mystery. Chi tianity has not presented these two great ideas in any other poi bof view. In that, God and futurity are closely united with man and with conscience. They are presented in the character which con- one point, to which we may say that Jesus Christ gave a ‘S science demands, and which it proclaims. in the midst of popu- Jar images and expressions, that were essenti jal as an aid to th he ur derstanding, we alwa Lys find, upon the slightest effort, he idea of God who is a Spirit, the Ruler of the moral world, and of a futurity, which is the necessary completion of the re- velations of conscience.—I repeat it, therefore, i n considering puly its e ssence, we thus far find an accordance between Christi - anity and the new philosophy.” —Pp. 245—243. joe CD ~ Tey he Ps 44 VU wy i\.—i AGE THEORY OF THE FRENCH CHARTER. ‘ ArTER the great political and religious movel 1ent which in Europe occupied the sixteenth ands seventeenth centuries, a new and still more 1m} portant movement became necessary 5 civilization was called to a new and amin somparably more deci- sive progress. ‘Tl he ei What was fie general cl haracter of It was the conflict of the old with the very idea of the eighteenth ceatury is tl : NO. XXXII. L L7é 4 hteenth century y- feento century ? ence, 2 entlemen, Lte of society 3; the ity of a Crisis. elations to couscience, of valet beaks ad + doscbsberbg chen) ais Rigen OT \ "Ret estate Usenet ac m 7) any eee Pieter Lhtkt: oh as id HOLD: rence wn ee shell a sehen Bh ee n r ; 5 NEY . 4 - eee eee erSTTer rs rrr eco cea ora aaiaaih hee aici bees cP OEE ee een teehee 116 NOTES. ‘* The French monarchy, after having marched from con- quest to conquest to its natural frontiers, and demolished suc- cessively all the powers that had attempted to oppose its pro- gress, had finally arrived, by the genius of Richelieu and of Louis the Fourteenth, almost to the last boundaries of its terri- tory and centralization. Nothing was wanting to France, thus Situated as to externals, but a better internal organization. But this new internal organization could not take place with- out overthrowing that which already existed; and to overthrow it was very easy, for the society organized of old had already fallen into ruins. In fact, what had become of the monarchy in the eighteenth century ? The monarchs themselves were a mere tradition of splendour and magnificence, without real] or apparent virtue. The monarchy which had been the pro- vidence of France, which had created it, had raised it and ren- dered it illustrious, was no longer sensibly perceptible to her. What did it do for the country abroad? What useful war, what glorious combats has it to show ? The seven years’ war and the battle of Rosbach. What did it doat home? What was the life of royalty ? It was the life of Versailles? ‘The French noblesse, who formerly had served their country so well, and had mingled their history with that of all the glorious feats of arms of France, had lost the manly habits of their an- cestors, and like royalty they slumbered amidst their pleasures. Lhe French clergy, which had in the seventeenth century, pro- duced the Church of France, had degenerated into a worldly clergy, among which impiety was almost held in honour, and which has produced the most envenomed adversaries of Chris- tianity. Finally, the French people itself, wearied witha royal- ty that no longer employed them, witha nobility that was nolong- er an example to them, with a clergy that faintly taught them articles of faith, which they no longer sustained by the authority of their morals ; the French people had sunk into a state of deplora- ble corruption, sufficiently betrayed by the success of the works that then circulated among all classes, and carried into all the poison of systematic immorality. In such a state of things, a revolution was necessary for a thousand reasons ; it took place, I come neither to defend nor to attack it; Iexplainit. It took place, and the throne, the noblesse, the clergy, the whole an- cient order fell to the ground. ‘the ancient order was the ex- clusive dominion of the monarchical principle, of the noblesse and of a religion of the state. In forsaking one exclusive sys- tem we are led into another exclusive system of an opposite nature. Hence the exclusive dominion of the monarchical principle, of a religion of the state, and of a privileged noblesse, was succeeded by the abolition of all public worship, by the so- vereignty of the people, and an absolute democracy. But this democracy, spreading terror around it, had soon to sustain for- midable conflicts with the rest of Europe. ‘Thence the neces- 178Meese Sa a Ss ci nl pened “I NOTES. sity of a government purely revolutionary, that is, of a council of war instead of a government. But after the sovereignty of the people, that it might defend itself the better, had resolved itself into a great council of war, it was necessary, in order to defend itself still more effectually, and to be able to act with greater energy, that it should resolve itself again into a great individual who charged himself with representing it: as has been said, the revolution became a man ; the sovereignty pass- ed from the council of war to the dictatorship, toa military dic- tatorship; thence our wars, our conquests, our victories, and our disasters. ‘< These revolutions were necessary, and they were beneficial to humanity; they have at least shaken if they have not re- animated the south of Kurope ; they have visited the benumbed and languid inhabitants of the two peninsulas, and apprized them that the hour of awakening was come. On the other hand, we have not appeared in vain upon the fields of battle in. Germany ; there also we have given the first impulse to a movement which has been useful and which endures. In the mean time the revolutionary system substituted in France for the ancient regime, exclusive as that which it had overturned, and more ardent and violent, was commissioned only to destroy what it has destroyed, without being itself established. It was only to appear, to do its work, and to disappear. It appeared for a moment with the convention ; it has disappeared for ever with the empire. “‘ Now let us cast our eyes towards the north, which is al- ways in the face of France; for France draws the south along with her without accounting to it for her actions; but she has always been compelled to reckon with the north, which possess- es a genius and a destiny of its own. What had been passing in the north ? What was the state of society in the north ? In a few words, gentlemen, you know that beyond the Rhine were thrones, absolute but paternal; a warlike noblesse that had covered itself with glory in the seven years’ war; a clergy reformed once for all, perfectly identified with the masses of population by their doctrines and morals, and in the enjoyment of boundless authority and veneration ; and nations, honest, sufficiently industrious, warlike, and moved to obedience by the spontaneous impulse of sympathy and love. By the side of the ancient Austria two new empires had arisen at the voice f ge- nius, young and consequently full of futurity ; deeply imbued with the new spirit, and at the same time absolute in their form and military in their manners. Here you see the fair side of the north. But we must not forget that the nations there vere S alsposea entirely in the power of their chiefs ; that these chiets « of them at will, and sometimes disposed of them badly. The people intervened not at all in their own affairs ; no national representation, no free emission of thought, unless by ey ys Bie ee et u iS ae La Te 6 aera ee rena ei RMN a TA ba beste Tres fos rm 2rinhiiacidiiid: aaanct Se eee nn tt i aaoasl one ene ere te ea . , ol freee Sea — een oe ee ee oe ae a 118 NOTES, privilege, and subject to the good pleasure of governments. Such an order of things was surely not produced by the last effort of German civilization, and consequently it was necessary that this order of things should come to its end. ‘The formid- able conflict of the north and south of Europe in the long war between France and Germany is nothing but the eonflict of ab- solute monarchies with democracy. The result has been the downial of democracy in France, and a considerable loss of ab- solute power to the monarchical governments of Germany. You know that it is not the masses of population which appear upon the fields of battle, but the ideas, the causes for which they combat. Thus at Leipsig and Waterloo the causes which en- countered each other were those of paternal monarchy and mi- litary democracy. Which prevailed, gentlemen ? Neither the one nor the other. Which was the conqueror? Which was vanquished at W'aterloo? Gentlemen, none was vanquished. No, I protest that none was vanquished: the only conquerors were Kuropean civilization and the charte. Yes, gentlemen, it was the charte, the voluntary present of Louis the Eigh- teenth, the charte maintained by Charles the Tenth, the charte called to rule over France, and destined to subdue, 1 say not its enemies, for it has none, it has none any more, but all who retarded French civilization ; it is the charte which has gone forth brilliantly from the sanguinary conflict of the two systems which now have equally served their time, namely, absolute monarchy and the extravagances of democracy. The fact, that from one end of Europe to the other the charte draws upon it- self the eyes of all, causes every heart to beat, and rallies around it the wishes and the hopes of all, is the most convincing proof that it is the true result of all the troubles and the wars that filled the conclusion of the last century and the commencement of the nineteenth. Imitations of it, which were unfortunate, and which | am far from approving, manifest sufficiently the deep sympathy of the south of Europe with the glorious results of the long labours of our nation. But also beyond the Rhine our ancient adversaries have hastened to claim the work of the new monarchy. In fact, gentlemen, all the banks of the Rhine are ruled according to excellent though imperfect imitations of our fine constitution. Bavaria, Wirtemburg, and Baden, have now representative governments; and preparatory experiments of inferior degrees of representative governments in the pro- vincial districts, are already extending their circle in the north, and reach even to the Baltic. Surely since 1815, European civilization has by no means receded; on the contrary, it has been in all parts extended and developed ; and I repeat it, this charte, which went forth from the disasters of Waterloo, now covers the greater and the better part of Kurope, and it is ex- pected and invoked by the rest. Now, if it is an incontestable fact that the future prospects of Europe depend upon it, and if 180NOTES. ie : this 1 . ae 1 more evidently th a case in regard to FE ce, let us rapidly examine what is the nature of the charte pie is called to such destinies. ' It appears, at first sight, as if the charte h oe sanctioned the social order anterior to the eighteenth century, and aes ae) ste é T which the eighteenth century has ove Rete In ‘fact, I | a0) Laue moe behold a king, a powe erful mon archy, and a throne efficient and re I behold a chamber of Bee in- r tac xxv 1t} OT U7 oO } vested W ae privile €¢ ges and surround ed with UDIV ersal vene- ration; I be Te an established religion which, taking our children in the cradle, teaches each of them, at an early hour, his duties, iis destiny, and a end of this life. And here we be ehold an element which does not proceed from the French revolution. It is neve ertheless there, get rtlemen, and it is necessary that it should be there; it is necessary that it sh cee from day to day be more firmly established, and win back for ever ‘both its respect and power ; but is this the Kate element in the charte? No, gentlemen. By the side of the throne and the Uhamber of Peers I also be- hold a Chamber of Deputies nominated directly by the people, and taking a part in the making of all the laws, that warrant and authorize all particular measures ; SO that nothing can be done in the last village of France in whi ch the Chamber of De- puties doesnot concur. Hereisanew element. I perceive some image of it to have fo merry existed in certain assemblies and but it was more jappareat than real ; certain judicial bodies in the wishes of the eig shteenth cen- 3 I find it in reality only tury, and in the irregular attempts of the French revolution to establish it. We have then on the one hand an element of the old government, and on the other an element of the revo- lutionary democracy. Upon what terms do these elements 2 In fact, gentlemen, they are there, subsist in the charte: and their union is so intimate that the Get skilful civilian would be much embar ee theoretically to define and to mark the limits of the particular agency of each of these two branches of the sovereign power ; and in this respect there ex- ists a certain obscurity which has precisely the eifect of bind- ing these two e elements more strongly together. In fact, our glorious constitution is no mati hematical fiction of the equi- librium of legislative and executive power, nor is it any of sh should be left to the those vain and empty abstra ctions whicl infancy of representative governn 1ent; our constitution is the real unition of the king and peop le, seeking jointly the best manner of governing and of serving their common country. This 1s not all ; in the charte _ woe notwithstanding the ex- istence of the Chamber of Peers, that all Frenchmen have ac- cess to all offices ; So that even ¢ oot nmon soldier, as the author of the charte said himself, carries his France in his cartridge box ; tae lowest Frenchman nea a ol batoon of a marshal of phe th Ny SASip ad ethehehe ot SEO SIG TL ieee os eee he al er ee a ei he a tte " . a Deen eae anels Ne enn aaa z ee 120 NOTES. every career ascend to the foot of- the throne. Notwithstand- ing the existence of an established religion, I behold in charac- ters equally manifest the liberty of every form of worship, and the liberty of the press; so that none may be destitute of re- ligious instruction, while at the same time the freedom of wor- ship permits every one to seek it in the different communions of the same Church ; and that, finally, thanks to the liberty of the press, no truth being suppressed, every Man may in. sin- cerity determine his own thoughts in favour of those opinions which seem to him the most true. Thus I behold in the charte all contrarieties; and this circumstance is what some men deplore. There are some who admire nothing in it but its democratical part, and would use that as the means of rendering all other parts powerless ; there are others who sigh over the introduction of democratical elements, and who turn unceasingly the monarchical parts of the constitution against the democratical elements which serve as their safeguard. On both sides equal error, equal prepossession in favour of the past, and equal ignorance of the present time. On _ both sides, gentlemen, there are men whose age is exceedingly respectable, and who, belonging some to the sevententh, and some to the eighteenth century, and not being the sons of the present epoch, are perfectly excusable in not comprehending the nineteenth century and its mission. But, thank God, every thing pro- mises that the irresistible march of time will by degrees unite the minds and hearts of all in the intelligence and in the love of this constitution, which contains at once the throne and the country, monarchy and democracy, order and liberty, aristo- cracy and equality, all the elements of history, of thought, and of things.’ Cours de I’ Histoire de la Philosophie, Introduction. Linsere’s Translation, p. 429—439, It gives me great pleasure to avail myself of Mr. Linberg’s accurate and elegant translation of the Introduction to the His« tory of Philosophy, in the above quotation, as well as in one or two others, which I have occasion to make from the same work. This translation, which was the first to introduce Cousin’s philosophy into the English language, is executed with uncommon ability, and does honour to the literature of our country. NOTE L.—Pace 41. COUSINS ANALYSIS OF THE WILL, THIs discussion would be incomplete without the admirable 182NOTES. analysis of the will which is given in Cousin’s critical ex- amination of the philosophy of Locke _ It is, therefore, insert- ed in this place. The principles, which it sets forth with such rare precision and clearness, shed more light on the funda- mental question of the free-agency of man, than most of the elaborate volumes that have been written on this controverted subject. In the hands of Cousin, the question is reduced Within a narrow compass 3 divested of extraneous considera- tions 5 and presented to the consciousness of every thinker, in a simple and intelligible form. The genuine lover of philosophical investigation, who is already familiar with this argument, I am sure will thank me, for bringing it again to his notice. As a model of accurate thought and lucid expres- sion, it can scarcely be too strongly recommended to the youth- ful student. ‘; All the facts, which can fall under the consciousness of man, and consequently under the reflection of the philosopher, may be resolved into three fundamental facts, which comprise all the rest,—three facts which without doubt in reality are never solitary, separated from one another ; but which never- theless are essentially distinct ; and which a scrupulous analy- sis must distinguish, without dividing, in the complex pheno- menon of intellectual life. These three facts are feeling, think- ing, acting. ‘¢T open a book and begin to read; let us decompose this fact, and we shall Gnd that it contains three elements. ‘S Suppose that I do not see the letters of which each page is composed, nor the order and form of those letters 5 it is quite clear that I shall not comprehend the meaning which custom has given to those letters, and that accordingly I shail not read. ‘Losee therefore is here the condition of reading. On the other hand, to see is not in itself to read ; for, the letters being seen, nothing would be done, if intelligence were not added to the sense of sight in order to comprehend the signification of the letters under my eye- ‘“ Here then are two facts which the most superficial analy- sis immediately distinguishes In the process of reading ; let us examine the characteristics of these two facts. <¢ Am I the cause of vision, and of sensation in general ? Am I conscious of being the cause of this phenomenon ; of commencing it, of continuing it, of interrupting it, of increasing it, of diminishing it, of sustaining it, and of destroying it at pleasure ? Let us take other examples that are more striking. Suppose that I press upon a sharp instrument; a disagreeable sansation is the result. I bring a rose to my smell ; an agree- able sensation is the result. Is it I who produce these two phenomena ? Can I put a stop to them? The suffering and the enjoyment—do they take place or cease as [like ? Not at 183Pe he head ele SOMERS FC a ee nis ibs at art heat seer ATTY ea ri, rane abe arava - - ho ho NOTES. all. I undergo the pleasure as well as the pain ; the one and the other come on, continue, and disappear without the con- currence of my will; in a word, sensation is a phenomenon marked, in the view of my consciousness, with the unquestion- able characteristic of necessity. ‘* Let us now examine the character of the other fact, which sensation precedes, but which it does not constitute. When a sensation is effected, intelligence is applied to this sensation, and, in the first place, it pronounces that the sensation has a canse, the sharp instrument, the rose, and here, to revert to our former example, the letters under the eye ; this is the first judgment which is passed by intelligence. Besides, as soon as the sensation is referred by intelligence to an outward cause, for instance, to the letters and the words which they form, the same intelligence conceives the sense of those letters and those words, and judges that the propositions which they compose are true or false. Intelligence therefore judges that the sensa- tion which is experienced has a cause ; but, I ask, could it judge the contrary? No, Intelligence can no more judge that this sensation had not a cause, than that it was possible for the sensation to exist or not to exist, when the sharp instru- ment was in the wounded flesh, or the rose under the smell, or the book under the eye. And not only does intelligence ne- cessarily judge that the sensation is to be referred to a cause, but it also necessarily judges that the propositions contained in the lines perceived by the eye are true or false, for example, that two and two make four, and not five and the like. This is incontestable. I ask again if it be inthe power of intelli. gence to judge at pleasure that such an action, of which the book speaks, is good or bad, such a form, which it describes beautiful or ugly ? By no means. ‘* Without doubt, different intelligences, or intelligence in different moments of its ‘xercise, will often pass very different judgments on the same thing. t will even often be deceived : it will judge that what is true js false, that what is good is bad, that what is beautiful is ugly, and the reverse; but at the mo- ment in which it judges that a proposition is true or false, that an action is good or bad, that a form js beautiful or ugly, at that moment, it is not in the power of intelligence to pass a different judgment from that which it does pass ; it obeys the laws of its nature which it did not make for itself ; it yields to motives which determine it without any concurrence of tite wal In a word, the phenomenon of intelligence, to compre- hend, to judge, to know, to think, whatever name we give to it, is marked by the same characteristic of necessity as the phenomenon of sensibility. If therefore sensibility and intel- ligence are under the dominion of necessity, it assuredly is not in them that we are to seek for liberty ? Where then shall we seek for it ? Nothing remains but to look for it in the third 184 asate TOY & a oN oS 123 fact, which is combined with the other two, and which we have not yet analyzed. We must find it in that; or we shall not find it at all; and liberty is only a chimera. ‘¢ To see and to feel, to judge and to comprehend,—these processes do not exhaust the complex fact, which is submitted to our analysis. If { do not consider the letters of this book, shall I see them, or at least, shall I see them distinctly ? If, seeing the letters, I do not give my attention to them, shall I comprehend them ? If instead of holding this book open, 1 close it, will the perception of the words and the understanding of their sense take place, and the complex fact of reading be accomplished ? Certainly not. Now what is it to open this book, to give our attention, to consider ? It is neither to feel nor to comprehend ; for to consider is not to perceive, if the organ of vision be wanting or be unfaithful ; to give our at- tention is not in itself to comprehend ; it is indeed an indispen- sable condition of comprehending, but not always a sufficient reason; it is not sufficient to be attentive to the statement of a problem in order to resolve the problem; in a word, atten- tion no more comprises understanding than does sensibility. To be attentive is to act, to produce a movement, internal or external,—a new phenomenon, vhich it is impossible to con- found with the former two, although it 1s perpetually com- bined with them, and together with them, completes the total and complex fact of which we would give an account. ‘¢ Let us examine the character of this third fact, the phe- 2a aoa nomenon of activity. Let us distinguish, in the first place, dif- ferent sorts of action. here are some actions which man does not refer to himself, although he is the subject in which they that we perform those are displayed. We are told by others actions $ for ourselves, we know nothing of them ; they are performed within us; we do not perform them. Ina lethar- gy, in a real or artificial sleep, in delirium, we execute a variety of movements which resemble actions, which even are actiols, if you please, but actions which present the following charac- teristics. “© We have no consciousness of we appear to perform them. “* We have no remembrance of havi! “¢ Consequently, we do refer them to ourselves, we are performing them, or after we have performed them. ‘© Consequently again, they do not pertain to us, and we do not impute them to ourselves, any more than to our neighbour, or to an inhabitant of another world. ‘¢ But are there no actions besidethese ? I open this book, consider its letters, I cive my attention to them ; these also re actions; do they resemble the preceding ? “¢ { open this book; am I conscious of doing so ? Yes. ? cc This action performed, do Iremember it? Yes. them at the moment when ng performed them. either while T i & aed pialehvenbsal? revbchebs ches . a f f Bh dat Procter red Syeda Tae bend eb Pigcie terjans res Serest yah wie hae Sit EOC eee ee rT wreroeret F i 5 Seis SN rind SEER eet Ties Rate AS ALSTON ; C \ o' *, . ae = . 124 NOTES. “Do I refer this action to myself as having performed it 2 "es. “Am I convinced that it pertains to me ? it to any other individual as well as to myself, or am I not solely and exclusively responsible for it in my own eyes ? Here again I answer yes to myself. ‘“ In fine, at the moment when I perform this action, h I not, with the consciousness of performing it, the conscious- ness also of being able not to perform it? When I open this book, have I not the consciousness of opening it, and the con- sciousness of being able not to open it?) When I consider, do I not know at the Same time, that I consider, and that I am able not to consider 2 When I give my attention, do I not know that I give it, and that I am able not to give it? Is not this a fact which each of us can repeat, whenever in himself and on a thousand occasions ? Is it not proved in- contestably by experience? And is it not, moreover, the uni- versal belief of the human race ? Let us generalise what has now been shown, and Say, that there are movements and ac. tions which we perform with the twofold consciousness of per- forming them and of being able not to perform them, Now, an action which we perform with the consciousness of being able not to perform it, is precisely what men have called a free action ; for here the characteristic of necessity no longer ex- ists. In the phenomenon of Sensation, I was unable not to enjoy when it was enjoyment which fell under my conscious- ness; I was unable not to suffer when it was suffering; I had the consciousness of feeling with the consciousness of being un- able not to feel. In the phenomenon of intelligence, I was unable not to judge that two and two make four; I had the consciousness of thinking this or that, with the consciousness of being unable not to think it. In certain movements, more. over, I had so little the consciousness of being able not to per- form them, that I had not even the consciousness of performing them at the moment that I did perform them. But ina great variety of cases, I perform certain actions with the consciousness of performing them and of being able not to perform them, of being able to suspend or to continue them, to complete or to de- Stroy them. This is a class of facts perfectly real, they are numerous, I have no doubt; but if there were but a single one of them sui generis, that would be sufficient to establish the existence of a special power in man, namely, liberty. Li- berty therefore does not fal] under sensibility or it falls under activity, and not under all the facts which are referred to this class, but under a certain number which are marked by peculiar characteristics, that is to say, those actions which we perform with the consciousness both of performing them and of being able not to perform them, 186 Can I impute ave he pleases, intelligence :a kk NOTES. , After having thus established the existence of free action, it 18 important to analyse it more attentively. “ Free action is a phenomenon which contains several dif- ferent elements combined together. To act freely, is to per- form an action with the consciousness of being ‘able not to perform it; now, to perform an action with the consciousness of being able not to perform it, supposes that we have prefer- red performing it to not performing it; to commence an action when we are able not to commence it, is to have preferred commencing it ; to continue it when we are able to suspend it, is to have preferred continuing it; to carry it through when we are able to abandon it, is to have preferred accomplishing it. Now, to prefer, supposes that we had motives for pre- ferring, motives for performing this action, and motives for not performing it, that we were acquainted with these mo- tives, and that we have preferred a part of them to the rest ; in a word, preference supposes the knowledge of motives for and against. Whether these motives are passions or ideas, errors or truths, this or that, is of no consequence ; it is im- portant only to ascertain what faculty is here in operation, that is tosay, what it is that recognises these motives, which prefers one to the other, which judges that one is preferable to the other; for this is precisely what we mean by preferring. Now what is it that knows, that judges, but intelligence. Intelligence, therefore, is the faculty which prefers. But in order to prefer certain motives to others, to judge that some are preferable to others, it is not sufficient to knov ferent motives, we must moreover have weighed and compared them ; we must have deliberated on these motives in order to form a conclusion : in fact, to prefer is to judge definitively, to conclude. What then is it to deliberate? It is nothing else than to examine with doubt, to estimate the relative value of different motives without yet perceiving it with the clear evidence that commands judgment, conviction, preference. Now, what is it that examines, what isit that doubts, what is it that judges that we should not yet judge 1n order to Juage better? Evidently it is intelligence, the same intelligence which, at a subsequent period, after having passed many pro- visional judgments, will abrogate them all, will judge that they are less true, less reasonable than a certain other, will ass this latter judgment, will conclude and prefer after hav- ing deliberated. Itis in intelligence that the pasiomen en: e preference takes place, as well as the other phenpmenert ue it supposes. hus far then we are still in the sphere 0 ante? ligence, and not in that of action. Assuredly intelligence is subjected to conditions ; no one examines who does not wish } 1 + : ; ° L1IV+t } ain to examine 5 and the will intervenes 1 deliberation; but this :s the simple condi tion, not the foundation of the phenomenon 5 for, if it be true; that w! y these dif- ‘thout the faculty of willing, all ona Q LOfHint tat bane at NC eae res SE eetaesek ate te Raa . " Re Une che a: mrt abies 7 woe Tt) nit s Vid bl HE DA at pan i i ¥ ¢ i eee a ee ee 4 * Gays : [ , eS rN Soe eaeat pieae ciel Gein te ahead ‘ , > aerate = 126 NOTES. mination and all d possible, it is also true that the faculty itself which examines and which delibe- rates, the faculty which is the pecul tion, of deliberation, and of all judgment, provisional or defi- nitive, is intelligence. Deliberation and conclusion, ference, are therefore facts purely intellectual. tinue our analysis, “We have conceived different motives for not performing an action ; we have deliberate tives, and we have preferred some of them too concluded that we ought to perform it form it; but to conclude that we ought to perform, and to perform, are not the same thing. When intelligence has judged that we ought to do this or that, for such or such mo- tives, i¢ remains to proceed to action, in the first place to re- solve, to assume our part, to say to ourselves, not I OUGHT to do, but I winx to do. Now, the faculty which says I ought to do, is not and cannot be the faculty which says I will to do, resolve todo. The office of intelligence here closes entirely. I ought to do is a judgment ; I will to do is not a judgment, nor consequently an intellectual phenomenon. In fact, at the solution of doing a particular ac. moment when we form the res tion, we form it with the consciousness of being able to form the contrary resolution. Here then is a new element which should not be confounded with the preceding : eliberation would be impossil V lar subject of examina- or pre- Let us con- performing or d on these mo- thers; we have rather than not to per- 83 this element is Will; just before it was our business to judge and to know ; HOw it is our business to will. To will, Tsay, and not to do; for precisely as to judge that we ought to do js not to will to G0, so to will to do is not initselfto do. To will is an act, not judgment: butan act altogether internal. It is evident that us act is not an action properly so called: in order to arrive &t action, we must pass from the internal sphere of will to the sphere of the external world, in which js definitively accom- plished the action which vou had at first,conceived, deliberated on, and preferred ; which you then willed ; and which it was necessary to execute. If there were no external world, there would be no consummated action ; and there must not only be an external world, the power of will also, which we have recognised after the power of comprehending and of judging, must be connected with another power, a physical power, which serves it as an instrument with which to attain the ex- ternal world. Suppose that the will were not connected with organization, there would be no bridge between the will and the external world » NO external action would be passible, The physical power, necessary to action, is organization; and in this organization, it is acknowledged that the muscular sys- tem is the special instrument of the will, Take away the muscular system, no effort would any longer be possible, con- sequently, no locomotion, no movement whatever would be 188ad NOTES. 197 possible; and if no movement were possible, no external ac- tion would be possible. ‘Thus, to r capitulate, the whole ac- tion which we undertook to analyze is resolved into three elements perfectly distinct: 1. The intellectual element, which is composed of the knowledge of the motives for and against, of deliberation, of preference, of choice; 2. the voluntary ele- ment, which consists entirely in an internal act, namely, the re- olution to do; 3. the physical element, or the external action. “ Tf these three elements exhaust action, that is to say, the phenomenon in which we have recognised the characteristic of liberty in opposition to the phenomena of intelligence and of sensation ; it is now the question to determine precisely, in which of these three elements we are to find liberty, that is to say, the power to do with the consciousness of being able not Ss 5 to do. Is this power to do, with the consciousness of the power not to do, to be found in the first element, the intellec- tual element of free action ? No; for it is not in the power of man to judge that one motive is preferable to another; we are not masters of our preferences 5 we prefer one motive to another, on this side or that, according to our intellectual na- ture which has its necessary laws, without having the con- sciousness of being able to prefer or to judge differently, and even with the consciousness of being unable not to prefer and to judge as we actually do. Itis not then in this element that we are toseek for liberty, neither is it in the third element, in the physical act ; for this act supposes the external world, an organization which corresponds to it, and in this organization a muscular system, sound and appropriate, without which the physical act is impossible. When we accomplish this, we are conscious of acting, but on condition of a theatre which is not nts which are imperfectly at at our disposal, and of instrumer our disposal, which we can neither restore, if they leave us, and they may leave us at any moment, nor set in order, if they become deranged and deceive Us; and which often do deceive us, and obey their own peculiar laws, over which we have no power, and with which we are scarcely even acquainted : whence it follows that we do not act here with the conscious- ness of being able to do the opposite of that which we do. It -s not then in this third element, any more than in the first, that we are to look for liberty 5 it can only be in the second 5 and there in fact we find it. “6 Neglect the first and the third element, the ju the physical act, and let the second element, the will, subsist alone, analysis discovers two terms stil le elen f will, and the power of will within us to which we refer this act. This act is an effect in relation to the power of will which is the cause of it; and this cause, 1 order to produce its effect, needs no otner theatre and no other directly, without any instrument than itself It produces 1t mi BL doement and > 1: Pees Tee lin this single element, namely, a special act 0setter hate teton SENSE 4 rn os , Hi eriLincBi lind. ain JUSE ShcoLns nuanscinebneriasra aes TaD Leto " Neen ee ee ee nn neers LTLia IRE aatne mt! Leas f Seay ge oN 4 iL ae " et te har Feit eee een nen neem eT EIOOeee teaeats NOTES. medium or condition ; it continues and completes it, or sus- pends and modifies it, creates it entirely or destroys it en- tirely ; and at the very moment when it exercises itself by a special act of any kind, we have the consciousness that it could exercise itself by a special act of a quite contrary kind, without any obstacle, without exhausting itself by such ac- tion, so that after having changed its acts a hundred times, the faculty remains absolutely the same, inexhaustible and identical with itself in the perpetual variety of its applications, always being able to do what it does not do, and not to do what it does. Here then in all its perfection is the characteristic of liberty.” —Cours de 1 Histoire de la Philosophie, Tom. II. Pp. 494-509. NOTE M. PAGE 77. MANIFESTATION OF GOD IN CREATION. “‘ THERE are men, reasonable beings, whose vocation it is to comprehend, and who believe in the existence of God, but who will believe in it only under the express condition that this existence is incomprehensible. What does this mean? Do they assert that this existence is absolutely incomprehensible ? But that which is absolutely incomprehensible, can have no relations which connect it with our intelligence, nor can it be in aly wise admitted by us. A God who is absolutely incom- prehensible by us, isa God who, ia regard to us, does not exist. In truth, what would a God be to us, who had not seen fit to give to us some portion of himself, and so much of intelligence as might enable his wretched creature to elevate himself ev unto Him, to comprehend Him, to believe in Him? Gent] what is it—to believe? It is, ina certain degree, to compre- hend. Faith, whatever be its form, whatever be its object, whether vulgar or sublime—faith cannot but be the consent of reason to that which reason comprehends as true. This is the foundation of all faith. Take away the possibility of know- ing, and there remains nothing to believe; for the very root of faith is removed. Will it be said that God is not altogether incomprehensible 2? That he is somewhat incomprehensible ? Be it so; but let the measure of this be determined ; and then f will maintain, that it is precisely the me hensibility of God, which will be the measure of human faith. So little is God incomprehensible, that his nature is constituted by ideas—by those ideas, whose nature it is to be intelligible. Many inquiries have indeed been made, to know whether ideas do or do not represent, whether they are or are not conformed to their objects. But in truth, the question is not whether ideas are representative, for ideas are above every thing; and the true philosophical question is, whether things are repre- 190 en. emen, asure of the compre-NOTES, sentative e; for ideas are not the reflection of things, but things are the reflection of ideas. Ged, the substance of ideas 1S eS~ sentially intelligent, and essentially intelligible.” “ God is; He is, with all that constitutes his true existence ; He is, with three necessary elements of intellectual existen 102. We must go on, gentlemen, we must proceed, from the idea of God to that of the universe; but how are we to proceed thi- ther ? What is the road that leads from God to the universe ? It is—creation. And what is creation ? What is ate create ? Shall I state to you its vulgar definition ? It is this, ‘ to cre- ate, is to make something out of nothing,” that is, to draw something forth out of nothing ; and this definition must ne- cessarily appear to be very satisfactory ; for, to this very day, it is every where and continually repeated. Now, Leucippus, Epicurus, Lucretius, Bayle, Spinoza, and indeed all w hose powers of thought are somewhat exer cised, demonstrate,' but too easily, that from nothing, nothing can be drawn forth, that out of nothi ing, nothing can come forth; whence it follows, that creation is impossible. Yet by pursuing a different, route, our investigations arrive at this very different result, viz. that creation is, I do not say possible, but necessary. But, in the first place, let us look a little into this definition,—that to create, is to draw forth from nothingness. ‘This definition is founded upon the very identical i idea, of nothingness. But what is this idea? It isa purely negative idea. ‘The mind of man possesses the power of making suppositions of every kind; he may, for instance,in the very presence of reality, suppose its contrary ; but truly, it is a most extravagant folly, from the meve possibility of a supposition, to infer the truth of that supposition. This supposition however has, in addition to those of many others, the misfortune of inv olving an abso- lute contradiction. Nothingness i is the denial of all existence ; but what is that, which in this instance, denies existence ? Who denies it? It is thought; that is, you who think ; so that you who think, and who exist, inasmuch as you think, and because you think, and who know that you exist, because you know that you think,— you yourself, in denying existence, deny your own existence, “your own thought, and your own denial of existence. If you will attend to the principle of your hy- pothesis, you will “find, either that it destroys your hypothesis, or that your hypothesis will destroy its own principle. W hat is said of doubt, what Descartes has demonstrated in regard to doubt, applies with ereaten force to the idea of nothingness. To doubt is to believe; for todoubt is tothink. Does he w ho doubts believe that he doubts, or does he doubt whether he doubt ornot ? Ifhedoubt w hether he doubt or not, he destroys his own sce epticism ; a ind if he believes that he doubts, es — stroys it again. Just so, to think is to be; and to know that we are ; it is to affirm existence; now, to ivrm the hypothetica 191Lscnad het haan tarot mapper ac ot Bey rie hiad Siri ne el mcecns toss mee ststeoherbaabeadi ails bulb seh DA ARUN erence Terbeal ani hae ot i betsy) " ee Me Re » se ae arr tata minal eaannnancnaatia hana ka Sina LDELSLS aR ned aN pa au eae og 130 NOTES. supposition of nothingness, is to think; therefore, it is to be and to know that we are; therefore, it is to construct the hy- pothesis of nothingness upon the supposition contradictory to it, that is, upon the supposition of the existence of thought, and of him who thinks. Vainly should we strive to go beyond thought, and to escape from the idea of existence. ivery ne- gation is founded upon some affirmation ; every hypothetical supposition of nothingness, implies as its necessary condition, the supposition of existence and of the existence of him who makes this very supposition of nothingness. We must therefore abandon the definition, that, to create is to draw forth from nothingness ; for nothingness is a chimera of thought implying a contradiction. Now, in abandoning this definition, we abandon its consequences 5 and the immedi- ate consequence of abandoning the hypothesis of nothingness as a condition of existence, is another hypothesis ; for, once enter- ed upon the career of hypothesis, we go on from one to another, without being able to get out of that career. Since God can- not create but by drawing forth from nothingness, and as nothing can be drawn forth from nothing, and nevertheless, the world incontestably, is, and could not have been drawn forth from nothing, it follows that it has not been created; when¢e it fol- lows again, that it is independent of God, and that it formed itself, by virtue of its proper nature, at d of the laws which are erived from its nature. Hence follows another hypothesis, that of a dualism, in which God is on one side and the world on the other, which is an absurdity. For all the conditions of the existence of God are precisely absolute contradictions of the in- dependent existence of the world. If the world is independent, it is sufficient for itself; it is absolute, eternal, infinite, al- mighty ; and God, if he is independent of the world, must be absolute, eternal, almighty. Here, therefore, are two entire powers, in contradiction one with the other. I will not plunge farther into this abyss of hypotheses and of absurdities. “© What is, to create?—not according to the hypothetical method, but the method we have followed,—that method which always borrows trom human cousciousness that which, by a higher induction, it afterwards applies to the divine essence. To create, is a thing which it is not difficult to conceive, for it is a thing which we do at every moment 5 in fact, we create whenever we perform a free action. I will, 1 form a resolu- tion, I form another, and another ; I modify it, I suspend it, I pursue it. What is it thatI do? I produce an effect which I do not refer to any other person, which I refer to myself as its cause, and as its only cause, so that, in regard to the exist- ence of this effect, 1 seek no cause above and beyond myself. his is to create. We create a free action, we create it, 1 say for we do not refer it to any principle superior to ourselves we impute it to ourselves exclusively. It was not; it begins Oo» es head we weAE 9 she, fig i Sy yeas Ses Saag te ete Sia a ate Sop CuORAn: Meee See a ligt NOTES. 13h to be, by virtue of that principle of causality which we possess. bus, to cause 1s to create; but with what ? with nothing ? Certainly not. On the contrary, with that which is the very xoundation of our existence; that is to Say, with all our crea- tive force, all our liberty, all our voluntary activity, with our personality. Man does not draw forth from nothingness the act which he has not yet done and is about to do; he draws it forth from the power which he has to do it; from himself, Here is the type of acreation, ‘The divine creation is the same in its nature. God, if he is a cause, can create; and if he is an absolute cause, he cannot but create; and in creating the uni- verse he does not draw it forth from nothingness, but from himself; from that power of causation, and of creation, of which we, feeble men, possess a portion ; and all the difference between our creation and that of God, is the general difference between God and man, the difference between absolute cause and a relative cause. “* I create, for I cause, I produce an effect; but this effect expires under the very eye of him who produces it ; it scarcely extends beyond his consciousness; often it dies there, and it never goes far beyond it ; and thus, in all the energy of his crea- tive force, man finds very easily its limits. These limits, in the interior world, are my passions, my weaknesses ; without, they are the world itself, which opposes the motions of my vo- lition. I wish to produce a motion, and often I produce only the volition of motion; the most paltry accident palsies my arm ; the most vulgar obstacle resists my power; and my cre- ations, like my creative power, are relative, contingent, bound- ed; but after all, they are creations, and there, is the type of the conception of the divine creation. “ God therefore creates; he creates by virtue of his creative power ; he draws forth the world, not from nothingness which is not, but from Him who is absolute existence. An absolute creative force, which cannot but pass into act, being eminently his characteristic, it follows, not that creation is possible, but that it is necessary; it follows, that God is creating without cessation and infinitely, and that creation is inexhaustible and sustains itself constantly. Wemaygofurther. The creations of God are from himself; therefore he creates with all the cha- racteristics which we have recognised in him, and which pass necessarily into his creations. God is in the universe, as the cause is in its effect; as we ourselves, feeble and bounded causes, are, in so far as we are causes, in the feeble and bound- ed effects which we produce. And if God is, in our conscious- ness, the unity of being and of intelligence and of power, with that variety which is inherent in him, and with the relation, equally necessary and equally eternal, which unites these two terms; it follows, that all these characteristics are also in the world, and in visible existence. Therefore, creation is not i NO. XXXIII. K 193MA dl ae a lb Laine had areas. Serra setae pratnenpeavennstaedtia nam AL SPRAIALDLESILanT eR aM TA ‘ i é veered Eee eee ee eee a Ge 132 NOTES. evil, but a good; and thus do the holy scriptures represent this truth, ‘and God saw that it was good.’ Why ? because it was more or less conformed to Him. ‘‘ Thus, gentlemen, we behold the universe created, neces- sarily created, and manifesting Him who created it. But this manifestation, in which the principle of manifestation renders itself apparent, does not exhaust that principle. Let me ex- plain myself. I will, and I produce an act of volition; my voluntary force appeared, by this act and in it; it appeared there, for it is to it that I refer this act. Then is it there. But how is it there ? Has it passed all entire into this act, so that there is nothing more left of it? No; for after having produced such an act, I may produce a new one,-I may modify it, I may change it. The interior principle of causation, while developing itself in its acts, retains that which constitutes it a principle and a cause, and is not absorbed in its effects. So, if God makes himself appear in the world, if God is in the world, if God is there with all the elements which constitute his being, he is nevertheless unexhausted ; and at once one and threefold, he remains, after having produced this world, not the less per- fect, in his essential unity and triplicity. ‘© We must therefore regard in two different points of view, the manifestation of God in the world, and the subsistence ot his divine essence itself; in order to see the true relation be- tween the world and God. For it is absurd to suppose t God, in manifesting himself, should not in some measure transfer himself into his manifestation; and itis equally ab- surd, to suppose that the principle of that manifestation should not still retain all the superiority of a cause to its effect. The universe is therefore an imperfect reflection, but still a re- flection of the divine essence.””—Cowrs de ’ Histoire de la Phi- losophie, LaNBERG’S Translation. —Pp. 132, 136—143. Do we not again find Cousin anticipated in some sort,— faintly shadowed forth, if nothing more, in this extract from one of the least known but most remarkable productions of President Edwards ? ‘¢ As there is an infinite fulness of all possible good in God, a fulness of every perfection, of all exceilency and beauty, and of infinite happiness; and as this fulness is capable f com- munication or emanation ad extra ; soit seems athing amiable and valuable in itself that it should be communicated or flow forth, that this infinite fountain of good should send forth abundant streams, that this infinite fountain of light should, diffusing its excellent fulness, pour forth light all around. And as this is in itself excellent, so a disposition to this, in the divine being, must be looked upon as a perfection or an excel- 194(tg? Ses Ee o> penne ees a LE AOC ACA LAA Se en NOTES. 133 lent disposition, such an emanation of good is, in some sense, a multiplication of its so far as the communication or exter- nal stream may be looked upon as any thing besides the foun- tain, so far it may be looked on as an increase of g good. And if the fulness of g good that is in the fountain, is in itself excellent and worthy to ‘exist, then the emanation, or that which is as it were an increase » repetition or multiplication of it, is excellent and worthy to exist. Thus it is fit, since there is an infinite fountain of light and knowledge, that this light should shine forth in beams of communicated kr nowledge and under standing : And as there is an infinite fountain of holines: s, moral excellence and beauty, so it should flow out in communicated holiness. And that as there is an infinite fulness of joy and happiness, so these should have an emanation, and become a fountain flowi ing out in abundant streams, as beams from the sun. ‘** From this view it appears another way to be a thing in it- self valuable, that there should be such things as the knowledge of God’s glory in other beings, and an high esteem of it, love to it, and delight and complacence in it: This appears, I say, in another w ay, ViZ. as these things are but the emanations of God’s own knowledge, holiness and joy. ‘* ‘Thus it appears reasonable to suppose, that it was what God had respect to as an ultimate end of his creating the world, to communicate of his own infinite fulness of good ; or rather it was his last ae that there might be a glorious ‘and abundant emanation of his infinite fulness of good ad extra, or without aiaseli; and the disposition to communicate him- self, or diffuse his own FULNESS, which we must conceive of as being originally in God as a perfection of his nature, was what moved him to create the world. But here, as much as possible to avoid confusion, I observe, that there is some im- propriety in saying that a disposition in God to communi- cate himself to the creature, moved him to create the world. For though the diffusive disposition in the nature of God, that moved him to create the world, doubtless inclines him to com- municate himself to the creature, when the creature exists ; yet this cannot be all: Because an inclination in God to com- municate himself to an object seems to presuppose the exist- ence of the object, at Jeast in idea. But the diffusive dispo- sition that excited God to give creatures existence, was rather a communicative disposition in general, or a disposition in the fulness of the divinity to flow out and diff use itself. Thus the disposition there is in the root and stock of a tree to diffuse and send forth its sap and life, is doubtless the reason of the communication of its sap and life to its buds, leaves and fms after these exist. Buta disposition to communicate of its life and sap to its {ruits, is not so properly the cause of its produc- ing those fr uits, as its disposition to communicate itself, or dif- fuse its sap and life in general. Therefore, to speak more 1995huni ns at aciecindn i ecea ehaledenad ih skabe nL arene Sar rar St Se ee enn eae eens aee cheats Swi rn a t a ATEN et teal reese —. a > et 134 NOTES. strictly according to truth, we may suppose, that a disposition in God, as an original property of his nature, to an emanation of his own infinite fulness, was what excited him to create the world ; and so that the emanation itself was aimed at by him as a last end of the creation.’? End for which God Created the World, Works, Vol. VI. p. 32. First American Edition. NOTE N.—Pace 79. ATHEISM CONTRARY TO NATURE. ** WHAT man, when he discovers himself in the act of ex- ercising the spontaneity of his intelligence, does not believe in himself and in the world ? This is evidently the case in respect to our personal existence, and of that of the world. Itis the same, in respect to the existence of God. Leibnitz said, there is being in every proposition. Now, a proposition is only the expression of a thought ; and in every proposition there is being, because there is being in every thought. The very idea of being implies, in its lowest degree, an idea, (more or less clear, vet real), of being itself, that is, of God. To think, is to know that we think; it is to confide in our thought, that is, to confide in the principle of thought, that is, to believe in the existence of that principle. As this does not imply that we be- lieve ourselves, or that we believe the world, and yet implies, that we believe ;—it is evident, that whether we know it or do not know it, it implies, that we believe in the absolute principle of thought ; so that all thought implies a spontanecus faith in God, and natural Atheism has no existence. I donot say only, that there exists not a language, in which this great name is not found; but if complete dictionaries of a language were placed before my eyes, in which that name were not to be found, I should vot falter. Is there one man who speaks that language, who thinks, and yet places no faith in his thought ? For instance, does he believe that he exists? If he believes this, I am satisfied ; for if he believes that he exists, he then believes that his thought—that he believes his existence—is worthy of faith; he therefore places faith in the principle of his thought,—now, there is God. Hecause every thought con- tains faith in the principle of thought, therefore, according to my doctrine, every word pronounced with confidence, is no- thing less than a profession of faith in reason in itself, that is, in God. Every word is an act of faith ; and so incontestable is this truth, that, in the cradle of societies, every primitive word is a hymn. Search in the history of languages, of societies, and of €évery remote epoch, and you will find nothing anterior to the lyric element, to hymns, to litanies ; such isthe intensity of the truth, that every primitive conception is a spontaneous percep- 196i ! ! i i i si eee NOTES, 135 tion, the impress of faith, and of an inspiration accompanied with enthusiasm,—that is to say, of a religious emotion. ‘lhere gentlemen, I repeat, is the identity of human kind. Prrecy where, In its instinctive and spontaneous form, reason ‘is equal to itself, in all the generations of humanity, and in all the individuals of which these different generations are composed. Whoever has not been cut off from the inheritance of thought, has not been cut off from the inheritance of those ideas which call forth its most immediate development, and which science afterwards presents to him with the apparatus, and under the affrighting title of the categories. In their simple and primi- tive form, these ideas are everywhere the same. This is, in a manner, the golden age of thought. Then, gentlemen, respect humanity, which everywhere in this form, possesses truth. Respect humanity in all its members; for in all its members there is a ray divine of intelligence and essential fraternity, in the unity of those fundamental ideas which are derived from the most immediate development of reason.” ** Let not the example of the sceptic, who doubts every thing, be brought as an objection to this doctrine. I shall re- ply, as [ replied, in my last lecture: Does he deny that he denies ? Does he doubt that he doubts ? Task him only that. If he believe that he doubts, if he affirm that he doubts, then, inasmuch as he affirms that he is doubting, he affirms that he exists. He therefore believes himself;—thisis something; and I would engage thus, successively to establish all the elements of general belief. Reflection, in its strongest aberrations, may always be brought back to truth; because its aberrations are always only partial; because recourse may always be had to some element of truth still existing in the mind; and because there cannot fail to exist at all times, some element of truth, even in the mind of him who may appear to be the most abso- lute of sceptics. In days of crisis and agitation, together with reflection, doubt and scepticism enter into the minds of many excellent men, who sigh over and are affrighted at their own ineredulity. I would undertake their defence against them- selves ; I would prove to them that they always place faith in something. HRegard things on their fair side, gentlemen. When you lack truth on one point, attach yourselves to that portion of truth which you still possess, and increase 1t succes- sively. So also, when you behold one of your fellow creatures who, not being able to deny his own existence, (an effort of strength to which few feel competent), sets about denying the existence of the world, (no very common occurrence either, ) and particularly the existence of God, (which without being so, seems more easy and is more common, ) say to yourselves, and repeat it constantly, that this being 1s not degraded ; that he still believes, because he still affirms something 5 and that his faith only lights upon, end is concentrated in'‘a slngie point, 197 BRR Rae nae eNOS OS — y ggg ree Sei jection ee Par hae eei Sabraa int “bh eh baetnalbin poche one needa Rte ote Shia ok bas Ld t " E br j . Z ' . [ : Tee ee Te utes! NOTES. and instead of incessantly viewing him in regard to what he wants, as an Atheist or a sceptics consider him rather, in re- gard to what still remains to him, as a man; and you will see that in the most partial, confined and sceptical reflection, there will always still remain a very considerable element of faith, and of strong and extensive convictions. So much for reflec- tion. But besides reflection there still exists spontaneity, which is within reflection; and when the scholar has denied the exist- ence of God, hear the man; ask him, take him at unawares, and you will see that all his words imply the idea of God; and that faith in God, is without his knowledge, at the bottom of his heart.”—Cours de I’ Histoire de la Philosophie, LianpeRa’s ranslation.—Pp. 1f72—176, 178—180.* P gy ka Se eT ee eee ea eos eaeniecese cae Sse Sie ee eed USP ma gle ka ow yy sts CI A +1 $e Aa AS CT al SKETCHES or MODERN PHILOSOPHY. ESPECIALLY AMONG THE GERMANS. JAMES MURDOCK, D.D. EDINBURGH: THOMAS CLARK, 38 GEORGE STREET. MDCCCXLIII.x yee enemas 3 F ; : EDINBURGH: Printed by JAMES BURNET.a oe Sa PREFACE. Tus work was commenced about a year ago, at the re- quest of several gentlemen, chiefly clergymen, who said they could obtain no definite ideas of the modern German Philosophy. To meet the wants of these friends, and others in like circumstances, the Author undertook to pub- lish some short Essays in the Congregational Observer, edited by Messrs Tyler and Porter of Hartford. Soon after the publication commenced, the editors proposed striking off a number of copies in the volume form ; and also en- couraged some enlargement and extension of the plan of the work. But before its completion, the Newspaper was discontinued ; and the two last Chapters now first appear in print. The piecemeal composition of the work will account for some want of uniformity in the style and man- ner of treating the subject : and the Author’s distance from the press, and the difficulty of Newspaper correction, must excuse several unfortunate errata. The Author here brings before the public no new system of philosophy, nor any attempted improvements of the science. Neither does he offer a critique upon the writings and speculations of others. He is not a philosopher; he has no favourite opinions to introduce and recommend ; and he does not assume the office of a teacher of philoso- phical science. He comes forward as a mere historian, narrating the progress of speculative philosophy in modern eG ures BR gis a Nt Noe OE Te ie CO aa ae eae Cree aS “4 SES teen ee eels aR Ae Seae nnneenne Seeeroer LT OT ETT ones To nul eatadt etind etate Ccnleinsben isle ele ialn ALUMNI Miia eit eed Shiad) jolie Wilkie Moco Bat si A ; ec aia) GN 4 We rat My Wem ye 8 ROO E oC te Mt | vs ft Pete Oe : % a CN yy Se J ha tates 4 f t ; he et , + Bah hed t * ee : RY Deri i Pye! Nee ae Na re Rae tahun HY Sanna soccer s 1V PREFACE. times, especially among the Germans. And for this pur- pose, after a brief statement of the two principal modes of philosophizing, he endeavours to describe summarily but distinctly, all the more noted systems proposed by the metaphysical philosophers, from the times of Des Cartes to the present day. In this survey, he endeavours to discri- minate accurately between the different systems men- tioned, to state clearly and concisely the fundamental principles of each system, its objects and aims, the estima- tion in which it was held, and the extent to which it has prevailed. The principal authorities consulted in the twelve first Chapters of the work, are W. G. Tennemann’s Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie, ed. 1829; 7. A. Riwner’s Handbuch der Gesch. der Philos. ed. 1822 ; W. T. Krug’s Encyclopadisch-Philosophisches Lexikon, ed, 1832-38 ; and the Algem. Deutsche Real-Encyclopadie, ed. 1824. In the remaining Chapters, the authorities are generally stated in the work. While writing the four Chapters on the Kantian Philosophy, the Author had not the Critik der reinen Vernunft before him, but relied upon very copious extracts which he made from that work about eight years ago. Since obtaining the Critik, he has not had leisure for a thorough verification ; but he hopes his statements | will be found substantially correct. JAMES MURDOCK. New Haven, Sept. 17, 1842.: ee ——? Sorte a ps . ‘ a ave Pepe Nee Ci Sa iene See Sate Sie a Pee TC eee ert rt a ete oe Th tat Bersales Para Pgs a eyes = eoeoe ats oo. ! SES Sgt Se See QT ate as SRA 78 RARE RLS EI x ce . sania PI a ET a Ga CONTENTS, CHAP. I, TWO MODES oF PHILOSOPHIZING. ne as Page. Description and Character of the two Modes, : 7 CHAP. IT, EMPIRICAL PH ILOSOPHIZING., Bacon, Locke, Berkeley, Reid, &e. é . : = iy CIFAP: TIT. METAPHYSICAL PHILOSOPHERS, Des Cartes, Spinoza, Malebranche, ; ‘ d ‘ cu Le CHAP. IV. THE FIRST GERMAN PHILOSOPHY, Leibnitz and Wolf, CHAP. V. KANT AND HIS CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Introductory Remarks.—Critie on Sensation.—Time and Space, 29 CHAP. VI. THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Understanding defined.—Its Conceptions.— CHAP. VII. THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Pure Reason.—-Transcendental Ideas,—Rational Theology, . 44 CHAP. VIII. THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Results to which this Philosophy arrives, 50 : é > - '@ ho Go The Categories, . 36at retin tem: eaanenetat sc tah bhikas a Het 4 he ; ee Mee & Oem tere : ae ean ary vin arin ewanrie GAD tity cone set Py > 4 Pf: ob wi \, pa sp! * : | P : Shae aM fe Ae a re wre eon. AUL Cn : rs 0) - ; CONTENTS. CHAP. IX. ANTI-CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Page. old’s Doctrine of Effects of the Critical Philosophy. —Reinh Thought.—Fichte’s Doctrine of Science, or Wissenschafts- : : . : : 4 00 lehre, ; : CHAP. X. PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. Schelling’s Doctrine of Identity, Identitatslehre.—Fichte’s alter- ed Doctrine of Science.—Other Pantheists : Bouterwek, Bardili, Eschenmayer, Wagner, Krause, 66 CHAP. XI. PANTHBHISTIC PHILOSOPHY, ¢ 74 Hegel's absolute Idealism.—Logic the only Metaphysics, CHAPS XIE INSTINCTIVE PHILOSOPHY. Jacobi’s Philosophy of Faith or Instinct. —His followers : Koep- pen, von Weiler, Salat.—Ability and Honesty of the German Philosophers. —Schulze, the only Sceptic among them, . 81 CHAP. XIII. FRENCH PHILOSOPHY. The New School in France.—Its Origin, and Present State. __lts Advocates.—Its Doctrines, : : 88 CHAP. XIV. GERMAN PHILOSOPHY IN AMERICA. its Introduction. —Coleridgeism, ; : . ° OM CHAP OXY. AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. Propriety of the Name.—Its Origin among us.—lts Radical : - 104 Principles, ‘ : : : CHAP. XVI. PHILOSOPHY OF DR RAUCH. Bographical Notice.—His Psychology—Transcendental —He- gelian.—Qutline of his Philosophy.—Its bearing on Theology, 117CHAPTER I. TWO MODES OF PHILOSOPHIZING. Description and Character of the two Modes. Two fundamentally different modes of Philosophizing have long prevailed, and have divided Philosophers into two general classes. Aristotle and Plato,— Bacon and Descartes,—Locke and Leibnitz,—the Scotch and English on the one hand, and the modern Germans with some of the recent French on the other,—represent the two classes. The first consider the human mind as born without knowledge, and as incapable of originat- ing any knowledge, from itself, or by the mere exercise of its own powers. It must, they say, receive from without, the subject matter of all knowledge; and this it does, especially through the senses. Reflection on its own sensations and perceptions, gives form and coisist- ency to the given matter derived from without; and thus leads to that true and perfect knowledge of things which is properly called philosophy.—The other class of philosophers do not deny, that the bodily senses are an inlet of knowledge; and that reflection on our sensa- tions and perceptions will give form and consistency to this sort of knowledge. But, say they, this is not pro- perly philosophical knowledge ; it is merely empirical knowledge, or knowledge derived from sensations and experience. It is the acquisition of the Intellect or Understanding, and not of the Reason, which is a higher power of the mind, and capable of a higher and more important kind of knowledge. According to some of this class, the human mind has certain znnate or connate B 209> Sea 8 TWO MODES OF PHILOSOPHIZING. ideas, which exactly correspond with the essence of things, by contemplating and comparing which, and by reasoning from them correctly, this higher and more 1m- portant knowledge is obtained. Others among them, not admitting of innate ideas, maintain that human Reason—that higher faculty of the soul—is capable of acquiring knowledge, by mere inspection or anturteon, and likewise by reasoning a priori ; and in these ways, it does acquire that higher and more perfect knowledge, which is properly called philosophical or rational know- ledge, that is, knowledge acquired by the aid of Meason. This rational or philosophical knowledge, they say, dif- fers essentially from empirical knowledge, or from the experimental knowledge acquired by the Understand- ing.—First ; itis more certain. For itis always either immediate vision, or it is derived from demonstration ; whereas empirical knowledge is derived directly or in- directly from the senses; which are always liable to fail us, and to give us either false impressions, or impressions too feeble and too indistinct to be relied upon.— Second- ly; it is more solid or fundamental. For it is know- ledge of the real nature and essence of things ; whereas empirical knowledge is always superiicial, and extends only to the phenomena or appearances of things. It does not acquaint us with things themselves, or with their internal nature and character, but only with their effects or operations upon our bodily organs.— Thirdly ; rational knowledge has a character of necessity and universality, which empirical knowledge never can have. When we see the real nature and essence of a thing, we know at once what must of necessity and universally be its operation. But when we know a thing only empirically, we actually know only what was the fact in the several instances in which we ob- served it, or put it to the test of experiment — We may illustrate the difference by a case in pure mathematics. Geometry demonstrates that the three angles of every right lined triangle are equal to two right angles. And the demonstration isso complete, that the mind is fully saan that this must, necessarily, and universally,ter ey ee OL 52s PR We ig la sa oe en eS ae RTE Sepee neg sina la uieaa aeRO Seo TWO MODES OF PHILOSOPHIZING. 9 hold good of every possible right lined triangle. But the empirical measurement of the angles of two, twenty, or a thousand triangles, could not produce the same re- sult. It would only prove to us, that all the triangles we had examined, had been found to be of this character, not that all others must necessarily and certainly be of the same character. And so of all general truths or prin- ciples, if Reason discovers them or brings us acquainted with them, they have this character of universality and necessity ; but if we have only empirical knowledge of them, they have not this character ; they are only maxims of experience, and though they may serve as useful guides in matters of common life, they cannot be made the foundation of demonstrative reasoning, or of absolute certainty ; they cannot be admitted into scientific reasoning; they belong not to the science of philosophy, but only to the mass of our empirical know- ledge. The two general modes of philosophizing above de- scribed, may be denominated the empirical and the metaphysical. The term empirical, so current among the Germans, comes from the Greek EMPEIRIA, ea'peri- ence, which is derived from PEIRAN, to try. It is not disrespectful in its import, and it well expresses the thing intended. The term metaphysical is used, as being suited to convey to Americans a correct idea of the other mode of philosophizing. The Germans do not use it in this connection, but call this mode of phi- losophizing the rational, and the scientific mode. — The manner in which these two classes of philoso- phers regard each other, may easily be conceived. The empirical class, not believing the human mind to possess any higher power than that of the intellect or under- standing, and supposing man to be incapable of any other than empirical knowledge, of course look upon the metaphysical philosophers as idle dreamers, who mis- take the working of the imagination, and unreal specu- lations, for truths of the highest order. Despising such fancied wisdom, they will not take pains ne acdsee themselves with it. It is to them all moonshine, aneeuch Rake RE Toh et ee ad . — eee eee icifiincia inal asin Mui dD) Ns BLT ENGRE No cian ocean ORD ve 4 4 $ ) i ber’ wes iy . ‘ ‘ : AP 8 , a — — Nee NE eee ee nian sie meaianiath AL PANU EGET ih re? et we p vey se " ark} > : " so ‘ % ye UNF 1 2 Ee 10 TWO MODES OF PHILOSOPHIZING. unworthy the attention of one who secks only for solid and useful knowledge. On the other hand, the meta- physical philosophers regard the empirical as mere children in science, and strangers to the noble powers of human Reason, that divine or godlike principle in man. Like the ancient navigators, they timidly coast along the shores of the vast ocean of human knowledge, keeping always in sight of land; they never venture to Jaunch forth in search of foreign realms, depending on the sure principles of science to guide their adventurous course. Such explorers, say the metaphysicians, may indeed advance the physical sciences by their close ob- servation of nature, and by their laborious experiments upon her phenomena; but they must ever remain strangers to even the first principles of true philosophy, and can never erect a solid and enduring system of phi- losophical science. For, although they actually adopt, unconsciously, many of the principles of rational know- ledge, and apply them in their philosophical investiga- tions, yet, not relying solely on such principles, or build- ing exclusively upon them, but relying equally upon empirical principles, commingling both, and _ erecting superstructures out of both, their systems lack entirely that character for certainty, solidity, and pure science, which will entitle them to confidence and to the appel- lation of true philosophy. We may add, that the spirit and the tendency of the two modes of philosophizing are very different. The one is slow, cautious, dubitating, and modest. It ex- amines every thing, fears deception and mistake, and seldom ventures to be positive or dogmatical. The other is more daring, bold, and self-confident : it feels its own strength, is proud of its lofty powers, and there- fore inclines to be dogmatical and overbearing. The former prompts men to inquire, to hesitate, to confine themselves down to sense, and to distrust all that cannot be put to the test of fair experiment. Hence it has actually led multitudes to scepticism, to materialism, and to infidelity. The other prompts to an overweening estimate of the powers of human reason, to bold and 208TE Tee 1 i at Si ie aon $9 ead a as ata Coa a eae Gt SI RERE AS SSS TIPS FESS RIDE ETAT SEIS Es bn me Storie eet ra EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHIZING, FI hasty conclusions, and to the excessive love of novelty and of paradox. And hence it has actually led to the exaltation of reason above revelation,-to bold and conf- dent dogmatism, to idealism, to pantheism, and to tran- scendent supernaturalism. Inconclusion, we remark that the English, the Scotch, and the Americans, almost universally, belone to the empirical school ; while nearly all the Germans, several of the latest French philosophers, with a very few in peo and America, belong to the metaphysical school. CHAPTER II. EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHIZING. Bacon, Locke, Berkeley, Reid, &c. In the first Chapter, two fundamentally different modes of philosophizing were described. The present Chapter will relate to the history of them, anterior to the recent German systems of philosophy. The founders of the two schools were Aristotle and Plato: the former pursuing the empirical, the latter the metaphysical method. During the middle ages, Aris- totle had most adherents, but Plato found here and there a few followers. Prior to the 17th century, the empirical philosophers made almost no experiments, but took up their first im- pressions as adequate, and proceeded immediately to generalization and the construction of systems. But in the beginning of this century, Francis Bacon, Lord Verulam, published his Chart of the Sciences, and his New Method of pursuing them—de Augmentis Scien- tiarum, in 1605, and Novum Organum, in 1620—in which he recommended dependence on reiterated and well conducted experiments, as being the only sure me- thod of advancing the physical sciences. Lord ee 2 atedLoeb cenhee hain Tacha nate Cee ee id tow bs ‘sl ancien acres teehee isan DR RT re nL Minldtaceh wed ks beds tats Terrttsstuaheccnea a haansiectanashals ALTARS MATa on : eH R) ‘ +4 “ * ry 4 Pp he! tye het " ag 2 EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHIZING. works put the friends of these sciences upon a new course ; which has been pursued to the present time, and with the most splendid results. The brilliant achievements of the empirical method in these depart- ments of knowledge, tended to bring the metaphysical method of philosophizing into discredit in regard to every branch of philosophy, especially in England and France ; yet, for a time, there were a few who pursued the metaphysical method, especially in ethics, natural theology, and the law of nations. Thus, Lord Herbert of Cherbury, a contemporary of Bacon, held to connate knowledge, or to general truths latent in the soul as it comes into life. And H. More and R. Cudworth, both Platonists, believed in moral and religious ideas either born with us, or coming to us by immediate inspiration from God. In France, also, Des Cartes attempted, though with little success, to revive the metaphysical method in all the sciences. In England, however, the metaphysical method was nearly extinct, when Mr Locke, in the year 1698, attacked it, and wholly exter- minated it from the British soil, by his famous Essay on the Human Understanding. In this elaborate and classical work, Mr Locke confutes the doctrine of innate or connate ideas, and maintains, that all human know- ledge is acquired, or 1s the result of sensation or reflec- tion; that is, it is either obtained directly through the bodily senses, or it originates from reflection on what is so obtained. In addition to these common and funda- mental principles of the empirie school, he maintained the objective reality of our knowledge of the external world. In this view, all our ideas are either simple or complex : the former are derived immediately from our sensations and reflection, and exactly correspond with the real nature and essence of things. The latter are formed by the understanding, being compounded of simple ideas; and when duly compounded, they also correspond with the nature of things. Mr Locke’s book has been classical, and its principles have maintained the highest authority, im all the empirical schools down © z . to the present time. The work was soon translated into 210— _ , aap tgertes eee 2. te Seer pee PNRM Pe roe re ; sek et te Ty cee ae! Fg ty aoe ar et aC le SE GSS SCE Seat SRE Ae IER: ONES — EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHIZING. 13 French, and subsequently into other languages; and for more than a century it was revered and followed, very much as the writings of Aristotle were in the days of the schoolmen. ; It has already been stated, that the spirit of this mode of philosophizing is slow, cautious, dubitating and modest: it examines every thing, fears deception and mistake, and seldom ventures to be positive or dogma- tical. At the same time, as it prompts men to inquire, to hesitate, to confine themselves much to the senses, and to distrust all that cannot be put to the test of ex- periment, it has led multitudes to scepticism, to mate- rialism, and to infidelity. The proof of this lies in the fact, that from this school have proceeded all the English and French freethinkers, deists, sceptics, materialists and atheists, from the age of Bacon down to the present day ; and that these, one and all, have depended on arguments which they derived from this philosophy, and from no other, to support their peculiar opinions; and they have claimed for themselves exclusively the appellation of philosophers, because they thus followed this philosophy to its legitimate results, unrestrained and untrammeled by vulgar prejudices and by traditional belief. Of the sceptics, David. Hume, and his imitators and admirers, are a striking example. As to the deists, we might cite the whole catalogue, both English and French: Hobbes, Blount, Rochester, Toland, Shaftesbury, Collins, Woolston, Tindal, Morgan, Chubb, Bolingbroke, Hume, Gibbon, &c. among the English ; and Rousseau, Voltaire, D’Argens, Toussaint, Buffon, Raynal, Condorcet, St. Lambert, Dupuis, D’Alembert and Diderot, the encyclopadists, and all the other infidel philosophers of France. Of material- ists from this school, (and I know of none from any other,) we may name as pre-eminent, Hobbes, Shaftes- bury, and Priestley, among the English; and De la Mettrie and Helvetius among the French. Among the avowed atheists in this school, we may mention De la Mettrie, Diderot, the Baron d’Holbach, Naigeon, Marechal, and the astronomer, De la Lande. BiPs ted or tclintaice tat narecreeSo Oi TS Th ™ eee Th teats mt er a ar} ayy eee een Serer — een erin re aes ; ~ en re ad 7 _ SR cei a asl 14 EMPIRICAL PIILOSOPHIZING. As all these erratic philosophers belonged to the em- pirical school, and professed only to follow this philoso- phy into its legitimate consequences, the defenders of the Bible and of Christianity have laboured much, to shew that this philosophy, instead of subverting Chris- tianity and all revealed religion, really confirms and supports them, if it be rightly understood and applied. And to make good this position, some of them -have ventured to modify certain tenets of Mr Locke, yet without departing from his fundamental principles. Thus, Bishop Berkeley discarded the idea, that by the bodily senses we apprehend material objects themselves, and become acquainted with their real nature. The senses, he maintained, can apprehend only the pheno- mena of external objects, or their impressions on our organs. Hence, he inferred, we know nothing of the nature of the world without, or the material world, ex- cept that it is an incomprehensible cause of various ef- fects or impressions on our bodily senses. And he deemed it most philosophical, to suppose that the oreat First Cause, and Author of all things, is himself the immediate producer of these sensations in us; and that material objects, as secondary and intervening causes between God and us, are mere fictions of our imagina- tions. In short, he denied the existence of matter alto- gether ; and maintained, that God and inferior or finite spirits, (angelic and human,) are the only real existences in the universe. By this amendment of Mr Locke’s system, the excellent Bishop hoped to bring all philoso- phers to believe, that they literally see and hear and feel the immediate power of God, present every moment with them, and operating all around them. And such a belief, he imagined, would banish infidelity and irre- ligion from every philosophic mind: but the idealism or spiritualism of Berkeley, has not met general appro- bation. After this, Tho. Reid, Ja. Beattie, and some others, in order to confute Hume's scepticism, Berkeley’s ideal- ism, and other aberrations from the common belief, with- out renouncing the empirical mode of philosophizing, 212a a Pap B Reach She ge acto . = FONE AG A =e he SSS ar as viheg B » Bui ealiels enROe SEGRE IS Tee - ra —— - EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHIZING, 15 called in the aid of common sense, or the common ap- prehensions of the unsophisticated mind, as a supreme arbiter in such controversies. They did not recal the long exploded doctrine of innate ideas, nor adopt that of the intuitions and judgments of reason, as a higher power of the mind—which would have been to take their stand among the metaphysical philosophers—but they held, that certain instinctive apprehensions of mankind at large, apprehensions which mysteriously accompany all our ordinary sensations, and are inde- pendent of all reasoning and all philosophy, are often more sound and correct than the apprehensions and con- clusions of the most acute philosophers. Thus, by making the principles of common sense, ora mysterious and incomprehensible instinct, more to be relied on than philosophical reasoning, and by teaching that the latter must succumb to the former in case of disagreement— they virtually taught, that the empirical mode of phi- losophizing is unsafe, without a regulator and a guide ; and, that unphilosophical conclusions are often more correct than those of philosophy. This new doctrine of common sense, without being formally recognised by all, has spread widely among empirical philosophers in England, France and America; and it has been the frequent refuge of many, when grappling with adver- saries whose arguments they were unable to confute by sound logical reasoning. Subsequent to these chief innovators upon Mr Locke’s system, Dugald Stewart, Tho. Brown, and others, have carefully revised, enlarged and perfected the whole sys- tem, by elaborate treatises on the Philosophy of the Human Mind, constructed on pure Baconian principles. In France also, the Abbe Condillac, Chas. de Bonnet, and some others, have attempted to improve upon cke. ’ ase valuable treatises of various individuals of this school, on particular branches of philosophy, ae 2 ethics, natural theology, the law of nations, oe : omitted, as not being necessary to the main object 0 these Essays, which is, to convey to Americans some 213 ——aa we Wein teroeens trai iat isa (> ba ALAM Sines it bd dete ieaihh ec bak reahathals ne Lyon Rat | \ herp ie hd A Td ee el oe hea hes eek are mrs WT " ary ia we ne me Ghee ertentnepeee ; 16 METAPHYSICAL PHILOSOPHERS. clear and correct ideas of the modern German philoso- phy. And for the same reason, the elaborate researches and invaluable discoveries of numerous successful ex- plorers of nature, in all her departments, are here pass- edin silence. The voluminous publications of thesocalled Philosophical Societies, and the numberless other pro- found works on natural science, show the wonderful achievements of experimental philosophy, when direct- ed to its proper objects, and prosecuted according to Lord Bacon’s rules. CHAP EER: EI METAPHYSICAL PHILOSOPHERS. Des Cartes, Spinoza, Malebranche. Tar metaphysical mode of philosophizing does not, like the empirical, decide every point separately, and on independent grounds; but it searches after general truths, or first principles, and by applying them to specific cases in a logical manner, it obtains a scientific answer to every question. The modern history of this mode of philosophizing commences with Rene Des Cartes, a French nobleman of fine talents, who flourished in the 9d quarter of the 17th century. Dissatisfied with all the systems of philosophy then prevailing, he undertook to form a more solid one, based on certain knowledge. He began with the inquiry, What does man know with perfect certainty? And he found an answer, In the consciousness that he was then thinking. He there- fore inferred his own existence to be certainly known : (cogito: ergo sum :) and also, that he was 4 thinking being. But he was likewise conscious, that his mental powers were very limited; he could comprehend only a small part of the numberlesg objects around him. At 214RED Rte, - es permeate Pomerat eee eee UUs weno ane METAPHYSICAL PHILOSOPHERS. ir? the same time, he could conceive of a mind capable of comprehending every thing; and not only capable of understanding, but also of creating and upholding all things, and possessing every possible perfection. This idea he found floating in his mind, and he was not con- scious of having designedly fabricated it: he therefore concluded, that it came to him from without, and from that infinite Being himself, of whom it was the idea. There is then a God, an all-perfect Being; and our idea of him is innate. He likewise proved the existence of God, by the marks of wisdom and design visible every- where in the natural world. And from the perfections of the divine Being who created us, he inferred the truth and infallibility of human reasoning, when pro- perly conducted; because it is not conceivable, that such a Creator would endow us with faculties calculat- ed to mislead us. Clearness and distinctness, he sup- posed, are the evidence of the truth or certainty of our knowledge. The bodily senses seldom afford clear and distinct knowledge ; and therefore such knowledge as they afford, cannot always be depended on. But, be- sides the preceptions of the senses, we have ideas formed in the mind, by reasoning and reflection ; and also inate ideas, or ideas implanted in our minds by our Creator. The last (our innate ideas) are the most clear and cer- tain, and therefore the best sources of argumentation. The ideas formed in the mind are the next in value for reasoning ; because they can be made clear and distinct, if weare only careful always tothink clearly and distinctly. Assuming the broad principle, that all clear and dis- tinct ideas contain true objective knowledge, Des Cartes was less careful to search for the origin, and to demon- strate the correctness of our ideas, than to make his own ideas clear and distinct. And this was the chief source of his many errors, and of his baseless theories: for when he had analyzed any of his conceptions, and made them very clear and distinct to his own mind, he con- ceived them to be objectively true, or to correspond with the real nature and essence of things. In this way, he was led to believe, that the very essence 01 » asore te Se, a for Pat ge —s- ee Cee een ante Fah y Seeman . 3 ‘ ‘ " parte , — ee ee en rei eee - ! | i] —_—_—— 18 METAPHYSICAL PHILOSOPIIERS. mind or spirit, consists in thinking ; and the very essence of matter in mere extension. Hence, he inferred, spirits can have no extension, and no parts ; and matter can never think, perceive, or will. And, as extension is the very essence of matter, there can be no void space, or space unoccupied by matter; and consequently, the material universe is an infinitely extended plenum ; and of course, all motion of bodies must produce a kind of voriices or whirlpools. The soul, having no exten- sion, is uncompounded; and therefore, it can never be dissolved or die, being in its very nature immortal. But the brutes are not immortal; of course they can have no souls, and are mere machines, with no thoughts, no volitions, and no preceptions. To explain the mode of communication between the soul and the body, he sup- posed a very subtile fluid, secreted from the blood and called animal spirits, to circulate in the nerves, and to convey intelligence from every part of the body to the soul resident in the pineal gland of the brain; and thence, also, to convey the commands of the soul to all the muscles employed in voluntary motion. Des Cartes was a man of genius, a fine writer, and, in general, a sound logical reasoner. Yet his premises were too often mere assumptions; and his conclusions of course, without support. He struck out many new thoughts, and he was the first in modern times to frame a regular system of philosophy based on metaphysical reasoning. His writings excited much attention, and they prompted many to engage in philosophical studies ; but they also met with great opposition. Gassendi and the adherents to the Baconian method, of course reject- ed Des Cartes’ views. The Jesuits in France, and many of the Protestants in Holland, did the same. In Eng- land, he scarcely had a follower. His principal adher- ents were, in France, several of the Messieurs de Port- Royal, especially Malebranche, and in Holland, Spinoza and a few others. The next metaphysical philosopher claiming a place in this sketch, was Benedict Spinoza, a learned Jew of Amsterdam, who died at the age of 45, in the year 1677. éle Bree itn teerae Re a "he, SPER EIST tee ee ae et rhe! 5 a oA tg Ae ol RPG Sis is ae iain ae METAPHYSICAL PHILOSOPHERS, 19 He had studied the Talmud, and was dissatisfied with its doctrines, Being discarded by the Jews for his opinions, he associated with Christians, and among them, read and admired the writings of Des Cartes. But he thought the system of that philosopher suscep- tible of improvement. Des Cartes had defined a substance to be, “a thing which so exists, as not to depend on anything «else for its existence.” And he had said, that in this its proper sense, the term belongs exclusively to the self-existent God. Relying on the correctness of this definition, Spinoza maintained, that there is but one proper sub- stance in the universe; namely, the self-existent and all-perfect God. All other creatures and things, not only originated from this one infinite substance, but in such a manner as to consist of it, and be inseparable from it. They exist in God, and God in them. As to essence or substance, the whole universe is God: God existing and operating in numberless modes and forms, which his infinite wisdom has devised. According to this theory, God himself is natura naturans, as the philosophers express it; and the created universe is natura naturata. Spinozism, however, is not the Ber- keleyan theory so extended as to include minds as well asmaterial things. Berkeley supposed material objects, to be nothing more than a constant divine operation, supplying the place of permanent material causes. But Spinoza did not suppose cither matter or mind, to be no- thing more than a divine operation; he admitted them to be a proper product, or rather efflux, of divine powér, (though sustained and actuated permanently by the divine Being,) and having in themselves the power of action, according to certain laws impressed upon them. With Des Cartes, be held the essence of mind to con~ sist in thinking, and the essence of matter to consist 1n extension, And believing that there is but one proper substance, or self-existent Being, from whom and in whom all created beings and things have their existence, he supposed this self-existing substance or Being, to be infini ind or thinking power, and infinite ex- at once, infinite mond or thinking power, an oe éo ? WA phabei tet gined oreenanedyn tary + & " Seren ae Dieta Ticks nite: aM fincas fee od eainaienl Lchenanseahadiedl » ihe ra f aC ee eee Seen ee ene cura an ai yg hgrove tvs eee setae angi piven tm eh st ener aE . ~ Ky ir OSs Hee rg eS ri ‘ Rat te) i A *) " 20 METAPHYSICAL PHILOSOPHERS. éension, and that when he creates finite minds, it 1s, by sending forth a portion of his thinking power, to think, and will, and choose, according to certain laws; and when he creates material objects, he in like manner sends forth a portion of his other essential nature, eaten- ston, to fill assigned places, to move and be moved, and to exhibit all the phenomena which we ascribe to ma- terial bodies. All actions he supposed to be necessary, or governed by the laws of causation: even those of God himself, who cannot act otherwise than he does, being compelled by his own infinite attributes. Yet we may say, God acts freely ; because he is self-moved, or acts only from internal impulses. Man, on the contrary, does not act freely ; not only because he is a dependent existence, but also, because he is a finite being, and is subject to a thousand influences from the objects around him, All the divine perceptions or ideas, he supposed, are absolutely perfect: and all our ideas would also fully accord with the nature of things, if we were always careful to think according to the laws of thinking. It is only illegitimate and careless thinking, that can lead to error; since the human mind, though finite, is an efflux of the infinite and all-perfect mind. The object which we can the most perfectly know or comprehend, is the divine Being himself; in whom we exist, and who is constantly developing himself in each and every ereated thing around us. To know and contemplate God, is man’s highest bliss ; and to obey his commands, is man’s highest freedom. Such is the best outline I can give of Spinoza’s pan- theistic system. It is manifest, that he carried his spe- culations quite beyond the bounds of human knowledge, and ran into downright transcendentism, in which ob- scurity must ever reign. But he also, wrote in very barbarous Latin, and is a very obscure writer. I have not relied so much upon my own power to unravel his enigmas, as on the labours of those Germans, who have attentively studied his works in order to compare his 2187 a Nae ‘ “ Neh gd 8 Eye ae ie a Rees eae ie ae SESE eee as Fas Sata to Sea METAPHYSICAL PHILOSOPHERS. 21 opinions with those of the recent German pantheists. Spinoza had scarcely a single follower, in the age in which he lived; and he was generally regarded with abhorrence, as being an atheist, and a subverter of all that is rational. And yet he is reported to have been a very amiable man, perfectly correct in morals, and devout also, in his way. The next philosopher we shall mention, was the pious Nicholas Malebranche, of the Congregation of the Ora- tory at Paris, who died in 1715, at the age of 77. His principal work was, the Search after Truth, first pub- lished in 1673, and afterwards, much altered and en- larged in 1712, only three years before his death. Malebranche, it has been said, was the most profound metaphysician that France ever produced. He was an original thinker; he called no man master. Yet he took much from Plato, Augustine, and Des Cartes. From the last he took, unaltered, his ideas of substance, of mind, and of matter. He undertook to search out, and to portray, the sources both of error and of true knowledge.—The great source of error, he supposed to be, the following of the senses and the imagination And the only source of true and certain knowledge, he held to be, God himself. His grand principle was, WE SEE ALL THINGS IN Gop. The manner in which we do so, (notwithstanding the pains he took toexplain himself, ) is not very clear. Some- times he seems to hold to a sort of mystical union and communion of the soul with God, in which God imparts knowledge to us.—At other times, and more generally, he seemstocome very near to Spinoza’s pantheistic notions. For he held the soul to be a portion of the divine Logos or Reason; and the material world, to be a develop- ment of the one infinite substance ; and both to exist still in God, and to be incapable of any action whatever, except as God works in them. The immediate objects of all our knowledge of things, he declares to be the ideas of things, not the things themselves. These ideas of things existed in the divine mind, or in God, before any thing was created ; and, when we direct our Bo tod> ~— "i Sas Ne en tt iets " Aad Palins, saan diel SAUL WT WoCan bs a nee barb netitia ete PR a Te! ‘ . " wire yi he eg henge F eeNS | - Te See ar he hy Mee ACE. ML ahs ee a Ste Tk ae teen ceeter ees he ‘ eT eer Se ee ieee eh eee hee ta ae eee ene aes ‘ y iat x ans \ r 4 " : t A " f 4 METAPHYSICAL PHILOSOPHERS. upon God, we behold these ideas of things, just as they exist in the divine mind; and this is true knowledge. These ideas of things, existing in God, and which we can behold in him, are not the ideas or images of indi- vidual objects, but general or abstract ideas, the ideas of the genera and species of things; by knowing which we know the very essence or the true nature of all things material and immaterial. And as these ideas of things are, at all times, to be seen in God, we may, by viewing them in him, have a true knowledge even ef objects that never fell under the cognizance of our senses, or were never the objects of our empirical knowledge. When we contemplate external objects only through the bodily senses, we obtain only indis- tinct images of those things; and we must turn our view to God, and contemplate the ideas of those things in him, or we cannot have any correct and adequate knowledge of them. So when we attend to our own internal consciousnesses, and endeavour thence to ob- tain a knowledge of our own souls or minds, we have only indistinct conceptions, until we look to God, and contemplate the idea of a soul, as it there exists in the most perfect form.— We may now see, why Malebranche considered reliance on empirical knowledge, as the grand source of all errors. We may also learn what he in- tended, when he said, God is our intelligible world. God himself, we are able to behold with immediate vision ; and in him, we may see the perfect ideas of all created things. Innate ideas, Malebranche did not admit ; such ideas being unnecessary for those who can at any moment see the perfect ideas of all things in the ever present God. The true religious spirit in which Malebranche wrote, his easy and alluring style, and his very ingenious reason- ing, caused his writings to be much read and admired ; but the complete ascendency of the empirical mode of philosophizing, prevented his views from gaining much currency, Q 20! THE FIRST GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. CHAPTER IV. THE FIRST GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. Leibnitz and Wolf. WE come now to the rise of the first German Philo- Sophy. Its author was Godfrey William von Leibnitz, a contemporary of Locke and Malebranche, and a man whom any nation might be proud to call its own. He was a general scholar, acute, ingenious, and indefatiga- ble in his exertions to advance both literature and science. Although he gave much of his time to the study of philosophy, and became the father of the first German system of that science, yet he had not leisure to compose a general treatise on the subject. He pursued the metaphysical method ; imitating in this the example of Plato and Des Cartes, whom he di- ligently studied, but did not servilely follow. His aim was, toreform the systems of his predecessors, and tomake philosophy as perfect a science of reason, as the pure mathematics. In this way, he hoped to put an end to all strife and all controversy, not only among philoso- phers themselves, but between them and theologians, moralists, and others. To accomplish this object, he proposed to treat philosophy in the mathematical man- ner; that is, by laying down such first principles as none can deny, and then giving logical demonstrations of every proposition. This method he deemed practica- ble, because necessary general truths are not confined to the mathematics, but belong equally tophilosophy. These truths, he justly supposed, are not the result of experi- ence, but have their foundation in the mind itself. He considered them to be innate, or a part of that intellec- tual furniture which we receive from the Creator, ma ‘ Csess blaladied seiiet being EON RIG . 1 oe Sate es r 7 5 yqeaveeneqarengebiess tet PARI ids sis AieDEL POS) UdN2 SLi WO CaSR bee ic iun rac ashen tit Path CORONER HE ry nh ne ne ere nr cari chara chains nate ORAL et * oo ce oN en ‘ 2 Se ~~ 24 THE FIRST GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. which become developed by reflection. The ground of their certainty, lies in the divine constitution of things; and the perception or knowledge of them, is what dis- tinouishes a rational soul from the souls of brutes. But, unfortunately, Leibnitz did not build his super- structure, entirely, of such solid materials. He held, (with Mr Locke,) that all simple ideas of sensation (simple perceptions by the senses) are objectively true ; thatis, they correspond perfectly with their objects. And he also maintained, (with Des Cartes and others,) that all the simple ideas of reason are objectively true, or ac- cord with the real nature and essence of things. At the same time, he confounded the logically true, viz. what involves no contradiction or absurdity, with the really true, or the true in fact. Hence he supposed that, by mere thinking, we may arrive at the knowledge of all those primary truths or first principles of things, from _which may be deduced, by logical reasoning, a complete system of philosophical knowledge. The Cartesian doctrine, that clearness and distinctness of ideas is ade- quate evidence of their truth or correctness, Leibnitz discarded as fallacious. He proposed more rational and logical tests of truth ; namely, for all abstract and gene- ral truths the principle which lies at the foundation of mathematical demonstrations, that of identity or contra- decltion; and for all questions of fact or real existence, the principle of adeguate cause, or, that whatever occurs or exists, must have a cause. Andon this last princi- ple of reasoning, he proved the being of a God from the existence of the world around us. He likewise deemed the ontological proof, or that derived from the concep- tion of a God in our own minds, to be valid proof. Ais specimens of his deductions from these first prin- eiples and laws of philosophizing, we may consider his doctrines of Monads, of pre-established Harmony, and of the Best System of the World. i, His doctrine of Monads. All the objects appre- bended by our senses, he said, are compounded bodies, er such as may be separated into parts. How far the subdivisions of matter may be carried, our senses, from EIOIC 2222 PRET EES GAGS Papeete EES cE Sota Basa ae Se Seed eer HERR S soe x ; : ae THE FIRST GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. their obtuseness, cannot determine. But infinite divi- sibility is inconceivable and absurd. Yet the smallest possible subdivisions of any and every substance, must have no parts; and of course, can have no dimensions, no figure or shape, and no exterior or interior, Such elementary parts, he denominated Monads. And as these Monadscan have no external qualities, (dimensions, shape, colour, &c.) all their qualities must be strictly internal, But the only strictly internal qualities are those of mind, such as sensibility, thought, volition, &c. Hence all Monads must be, in their nature, living, active beings, or minds.—Our knowledge extends to four kinds of Monads, and no more. First in the order of excel- lence is the self-existing God, the author and upholder of all the other Monads, the Monas Monadum, who is infinite in all his attributes. Next in order are finite spirits and human souls. These are distinguished from their great parent Monad, by being finite and dependent minds ; and they are distinguished from the lower or- ders of Monads, by possessing reason. The third order are the souls of brutes ; which have the power of percep- tion, thought, and volition, but are not capable of under- standing either general or necessary and eternal truths. The fourth and lowest order of Monads are sleeping, unconscious, and unthinking beings; yet they possess life, feeling, and the power of action ; and they are al- ways blindly struggling to change their condition. Ag- gregates of Monads of this fourth and lowest order, con- stitute material bodies. One Monad of the third order, surrounded by an organized aggregate of Monads of the fourth class, constitutes a brute animal. Andone Monad of the second order, surrounded by a similar aggregate of Monads of the lowest order, constitutes a man, or a human being. Such being the essential nature of all existing beings and things, space and time can be no- thing more than the arrangement of Monads, considered as co-existent or as existing in succession. Both are mere ideal things, or things without real existence. By this doctrine of Monads, Leibnitz supposed he could ex~ plain, what Plato intended by ideas, and Aristotle by cy} 9D 923a ietnd oneal y tiny ety tepmemeatrteerenan tree ae err eeenmrerena maT hoe! , ‘ yf ‘ ry ry u ! Sait MD Aah Neen nn nn einen? sates pines gen eet PTET RTT TT ToT YRS Pe 26 THE FIRST GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. his entelechias ; and likewise overthrow entirely the pantheism of Spinoza. 2. His doctrine of pre-established Harmony. As the created Monads have no external qualities, no shape, no dimensions, no interior or exterior parts,—it is impossi- ble, that they should act upon one another in a physical manner. One Monad cannot penetrate another, nor can one touch another externally. Each is, in its na- ture, as independent of all physical actions from the others, as it would be were it the only Monad in exist- ence. In other words, as Monads have only énternal qualities, or those of minds,—it is impossible that they should either act, or be acted upon, mechanically.—How then can we account for the constant action and reaction apparent throughout the material world ; and for the control of the mind over the body, and the influences of the body on the mind, in human beings? He replies, the created universe is an organized whole. Each Monad stands connected with the whole system, but has special relations to the Monads nearest to x and in every living being, the unthinking Monads form a sort of world around the intelligent Monad which is its soul. -Now, by a law of their Cr eator, impressed on them when they first issued from his hands, every finite Mo- nad is compelled to act conformably to its relations, or to do and to endure whatever its relations require, in order to a perfect harmony in all the movements of this vast and complicated machinery. And this law of the Creator is what he denominates the pre-established flarmony. Hence, the apparent action of finite Mo- nads on each other, is, in reality, divine action, or the result of an original law of the Creator; and by this law, God secures infallibly those results, which he con- templated when he formed the universe. 3. His Best System of the world. In his Théodicée, or Tissay on the goodness of God, free-will in man, and the origin of evil,—Leibnitz maintained that, among the many possible systems for a created universe, God has chosen the very best ; and that this may be proved from his perfections. His infinite wisdom could devise the 224THE FIRST GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 27 best system, his infinite goodness would choose it, and his infinite power would then produce it. Hence, the present system must be the best possible in its place ; and nothing could be changed, without changing the system, and rendering it less perfect. God indeed chooses nothing, for its own sake, but what is good. But physical evil or imperfection, is inseparable from whatever is finite; and, of course, such evil must per- vade a world of finite beings and things——From this imperfection of all finite beings and things, natural evils (pain and suffering) naturally and necessarily follow ; and moral evil or sin, is likewise a natural, though not a necessary consequence. Natural evil God chose; not indeed for its own sake, but as the means of good. He designed it for chastisement or punishment; and, by the pre-established Harmony of the universe, he causes it naturally to overtake sooner or later the transgressors. Moral evil or sin, arises naturally from the free-will of finite rational beings; and God does not choose it, but only permits it; and he permits it, because he could not otherwise have the best possible system.— Pree- will consists in acting according to our own choice, and with- out any compulsion, or physical necessity. But our choice is determined always by the circumstances in which we are placed. It therefore depends, in all cases, on the pre-established Harmony of the universe ; and, of course, it was from eternity, absolutely certain how we would choose in every instance. This system of philosophy spread rapidly, and soon became the national philosophy of Protestant Germany. The man who did the most to explain and recommend it to his countrymen, was Christian W olf, who died in 1754, at the age of 75. He drew out and expanded the princi- ples of Leibnitz into a complete system ; and composed for this purpose, elementary works on nearly every branch of the science. And as many of his treatises were written in the vernacular language, this philosophy spread among the common people. Wolf resolutely met every assailant, and spent his life in explaining and defending the Leibnitzian principles ; and hence, this 225. Seta L ais tetas anine tt ec ner Seay le Re a tt baer ease aaies toe IIA binead ia Seddon cinerea STS etait thd eo a eter. oat aaa ; ; yt) See rae oar no ell cea ’ ay Af} p N i eo hot Ss en eee eee te Sal " >. Tae Ra re THE FIRST GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. system has obtained the name of the Leibnitzian- Wolfian Philosophy. In regard to principles, Wolf scarcely deviated at all from Leibnitz ; except in deny- ing sensations to the lowest order of Monads, and in confining the so called pre-established Harmony to the mutual intercourse of the soul and body. But in prac- tical or moral philosophy, of which Leibnitz did not treat, Wolf devised a new central point, or fundamen- tal principle ; viz. that of perfection, as comprising all that is morally right and obligatory. According to this principle, the whole duty of man consists in striving after perfection, in himself and in all around him ; the perfection of his entire character and condition, for time and eternity. As Wolf surveyed the whole field of philosophy, so he distributed it into its several depart- ments ; a thing which had not before been done. He divided all philosophy into theoretical and practical, the former treating of rational knowledge, and the latter of rational conduct. Theoretical philosophy he divided in- to Logic and Metaphysics ; and under Metaphysics, he included Ontology, metaphysical (not empirical) Psy- chology, Cosmology, and natural Theology.—Practical or moral philosophy he divided into Ethics, the Law of Nature, and National Policy. And this classification of the Philosophical Sciences, with the addition of esthetics, has been generally followed in Germany quite to the present time. In all his elementary trea- tises, which were numerous, Wolf pursued strictly the mathematical method. He also introduced a multitude of new technical terms, derived chiefly from the Greek language ; nearly all of which have since passed inte common use in the German schools. Uhis Leibnitzian-Wolfian philosophy, reached its culminating point, about the middle of the 18th century. Soon afterwards, from various causes, 1t began to de- cline. Many had all along questioned the soundness of its principles, and still more, the tendencies of some of its doctrines. The downright pedantry of most of its ad- vocates, who dogmatized ostentatiously, and stuffed their writings with formal demonstrations of the sim~ aon azo Rice gnrpeenrr TT Jaa Ne reKANT AND HIS CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 29 plest truth, rendered it disgusting to well informed minds. About the same time, Mac Locke's principles, or those of the empirical school, found their way into Germany. And these principles were propagated in, and along with, the writings of the English and French deists and sceptics, (Hume, Voltaire, Rousseau, &c.) which began now to circulate extensively, and to produce in that country a set of free-thinkers and con- temners of long established opinions. The friends of revealed religion were alarmed at the progress of infidel- ity and scepticism, under the assumed name of philoso- phy; and they anxiously inquired, What is true philo- sopby? It wasamid this state of things, that Emanuel Kant appeared on the stage, as a master spirit control- ling and guiding public opinion by his superior talents.’ CHAPTER. V. KANT AND HIS CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Introductory Remarks.—Critic on Sensation.—Time and Space. EMANUEL Kant was born at Konigsberg, in the year 1724, and spent his whole life in that city, never having been more than 22 English miles from it. He first studied theology, then became a lecturer, and after- wards a professor of logic and metaphysics, in the unt- versity ; and died in 1804, at. the age of 80. That he was a man of great acuteness, and a patient investigator, his works evince; and that he was a man of pure morals, conscientious, upright, modest, and amiable, is the testimony of all who knew him. He has been call- ed the modern Socrates, and, emphatically, the Philo- sopher of Konigsberg. Kant arose at a most critical period in Germany. French and English infidelity had just broken into the country, and threatened to sweep away all the estab- Qn oe . = et Presa orere Cab pret a 2 ‘ sr sebabascisccen ase Macatee esterase SR Se 7 either, Se hth Ss tasted nae I, bs a See eC ere aN ro eer casei Ay bt enh. of H ; pee tna arias . ee ek J apeetee eaten eee etree git phere ictatet Hy ESP me He rept on epesngmteenn tay Hmmm array trina pena atten A root Sat 44 " es Sees he he ob et ee ¥ . oe 4 ul t ‘ THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. CHAPTER VII. THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Pure Reason.—Transcendental Ideas.—Rational Theology. Kant next brings theoretical Reason, that higher in- tellectual faculty of man, under a critical examination. The distinction between speculative or theoretical Rea- son, which imparts to us rational knowledge, and prac- tical or moral Reason, which enjoins upon us rational conduct, has already been noticed. Our present concern is with the former.—It will be recollected, that the sphere of theoretical Reason is the supersensible world, the world of spirits, of general truths, of virtue, &c.; that the objects with which it is concerned, are tdeas, things which the mind can contemplate, but which can never be subjected to the senses ; and that the product of its labours 1s rational knowledge, the knowledge of universal and necessary truths. The distinction between analytical and synthetical judgments, was stated in the Introduction to the Critic : and the power of Reason to form synthetic judgments, «@ priort, was there limited to the mere forms of our know- ledge ; that 1s, to the determining what is possible, and what is not possible, in human experience. In regard to all objects of real existence, she can form only analyti- cal judgments, unless the objects are given or already known. And hence, to form analytical judgments by means of middle terms, or to reason in the logical man- ner, 1s the only function of theoretical Reason in regard to our knowledge of whatever may exist around us, within us, or above us. But analytical judgments are those in which the predicate is really and truly con- tained in the subject of the proposition. Of course, theoretical or speculative Reason can never acquaint us 242THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 45 with any unknown object, that may exist within us, around us, or above us. She can only draw forth the knowledge of these objects, which we already possess, or can only present it to us in a different attitude and form. To establish these strong positions respecting the im- portance of speculative Reason, Kant institutes an ela- borate examination of what he calls the transcendental edeas of pure Reason, that is, the ideas which Reason attempts to form, by a logical deduction, of the nature and essential properties of the human soul, of the mate- rial world, and of God; and he shows, that the sup- posed logical deduction is unsound and fallacious. I. As to the idea of the soud:—The reasoning which attempts to educe a knowledge of its nature and of its inherent properties, from those acts of the soul of which we are all conscious, is a mere paralogism. In the as- sertions, f think, I love, I hate, I will, I choose, I re- member, Sc. various actions are affirmed of the subject Z ; and on the most solid grounds, because we are con- scious of those acts. But the actions of any being or thing, are notthe thing ttself; nor are they any part either ‘of its essential nature, or of its inherent attributes. We may indeed infer, that whatever acts, must really exist ; and that it must be of such a nature as to be capable of performing the acts ascribed toit. But all this implies no knowledge of the mode of its eaistence, or of those inherent qualities which make it capable of performing the acts. Hence, the following reasoning is wholly inconclusive. J think; therefore I am a thinking Sub- stance.—That substance is not perceived by the exter- nal senses, but only by internal consciousness ; it 1s therefore immaterial ora Spirit. It has no perceptible or conceivable parts ; it is therefore a simple Substance. Being a simple substance, and immaterial, it must be of an immortal or undying nature. It acts in and by the bodily organs; and therefore itis the Souw/, the anwat- ing principle of the body. All this is sophistical rea- soning ; because it mistakes the subject of the conscious- ness, for the object of that consciousness. It is sa——— oihdes Silat elias halts taba nabee at i ot Meath inc Ibias, cin AID MSCs Lan encanies cinnraemaaiea ak aeii aa as tae 1k a ARETE NE CNS SE Be hy! , Vr vistastah " ee CHEE NG HEY. , baal nen eT nn een aii Ne nn et manana 46 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Figure dictionis—But, though inconclusive as reason- ing, it may nevertheless be true: and it mayserve as a convenient basis of a system of psychology. II. The cosmological ideas of pure Reason, or those transcendental ideas which Reason forms of the external world, are equally baseless, considered as the results of logical reasoning. For, both the thesis and the anti- thesis of them, may be proved by very similar ar- guments. Thus it may be proved—(1.) That the world had a beginning in time, and is of limited or finite ex- tent ; and, on the contrary, that it had no beginning in time, and has no limits in extent.—(2.) That all sub- stances consist of simple elementary parts, (or Monads, as Leibnitz called them ;) and, on the contrary, that no substance whatever consists of such simple elements, because such simple elements cannot exist.—(3.) That physical causes cannot be the only causes in existence, there must be a free cause, to give existence to the phy- sical causes; and, on the contrary, that no free cause ean possibly exist, and consequently physical causes alone must exist—(4.) That there must be, either in the world, or beyond it, a Being who exists necessarily, and who is the first cause of all things; and, on the contrary, that no such Being exists, either in the world or beyond it. As specimens of the arguments adduced by Kant, take the following: The 3d Thesis is thus proved: Unless we assume a cause prior to the first physical cause, and commencing the series of physical causes, there will be no cause: for the whole series of physical causes, and of course none for any part of it. We must therefore suppose an un- caused cause, prior to the first physical cause. But an wncaused cause must be one that is free, or one that acts without being compelled to act, by any higher cause. The Antithesis is thus proved: Every causality is in itself a change, since it is the state of the cause when in action, which is different from its state when not in ace tion. Now as every change presupposes a cause, the change in the supposed free cause, by which it proceeds to action, must have a cause. And therefore, there can- 244THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 47 not be any free cause, or one that acts without beine caused to act. : The 4th Thesis is thus proved: The world is full of changes. But the existence of every change is condi- tioned ; 1. e. it presupposes something which is its con- dition, or a cause on which it depends. Now, if there were no existence that is absolutely unconditioned, the conditioned could not be conditioned. Consequently, there must be an absolutely necessary Being, whose ex- istence is unconditioned or uncaused: otherwise the se- ries of the conDITIONS or causes would be incomplete. The Antithesis is thus proved : Every member of a se- ries of changes must, of course, be conditioned. Hence, the supposed absolutely unconditioned Being, if in the world, and a part of the series, must himself bea condi- toned Being ; contrary to the thesis. And if such a Being existed out of the world, and commenced the se- ries of changes in the world, his causality at least would belong to the world, and of course he would con- stitute a part of the series : which contradicts itself. We must therefore reject the thesis altogether, in order to make the series of the conDITIONED complete. The objects of these cosmological ideas lie wholly be- yond the reach of experience. Hence, experience can never decide in favour of either the Theses or the Anti- theses. Reason alone must solve her own contradictions. The side of the Theses, is that which good men incline to take ; and it may be called the Dogmatism of pure feeason. The side of the Antitheses is that which is espoused by philosophizing sceptics ; and as its argu- ments are founded on the principles of pure emporicism, this side may be called the Empiricism of pure Reason. Critical Idealism, which admits and even demonstrates the existence of nowmena, or things lying beyond all sensible intuition, can alone solve these dialectical con- tradictions. This critical Idealism is equally removed from materialism, which supposes we can have sensible intuitions of nowmena, and from empirical Ldealism, which denies the existence of nowmena. Now this eri- tical Idealism, by maintaining’ that sensible a 245Mithaniscmien SON SROR TTL tic” Soar ah Plas ats tetahsaaneaiiad ey al Scans “sl guiness nactateereaaceablen ahs LG . ye See haat ot bar a } } in exe yr egenemeena gta SEALE EM TALC h Lehre ee eben Sp aghegetee nettpe ene einen ae higinit phempamomnyen tated yippee vee Po RUE LMS ; ue yan Pr Ween Ar ee YB A8 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY, extends only to phenomena, or that we have empiricad knowledge only of what is sensible, does not deny the possibility of some knowledge, other than empirical, of objects lying beyond the reach of our senses. It only warns us not to strive after empirical knowledge of such subjects, and not to reason about them upon the sup- position of such knowledge. Taking this stand, and carefully examining both the Theses and the Anti- theses respecting the cosmological ideas, critical Ideal- ism declares that both may be true, because they relate to different things. The Antitheses direct attention only to phenomena, or the objects of empirical knowledge ; but the Theses look beyond phenomena, to their cause ; and they consider the total series of phenomena as com- plete and dependent as a whole, on an intelligible cause lying without the bounds of nature. Hence, both the Theses and the Antitheses may be true; the one main- taining, e.g. that there is a God beyond nature, and the other, that there is no God within nature. And so in all the contradictions, one side includes an intelligible thing among the phenomena of nature; which the other . does not, but only reasons back through phenomena, to an intelligible thing lying beyond them. And therefore, though the side of the Theses failed of proving its asser- tions with apodictical certainty, yet the opposite party failed of proving the contrary, there not being any such contradiction as would make the one proof overthrow the other. Nor can the latter party overthrow the Theses of the former, unless it can prove, e.g. that out of and beyond nature there is no God, or in other words, that the supposition is itself absurd and self-contradic- tory, which it is not. II!. The third transcendental idea of pure Reason, is that of a supreme and all-perfect Being. Reason is disposed to admit the existence of such a Being, because she needs this perfect ideal of absolute excellence, and still more, because her moral wants demand it. But the arguments of speculative Reason, to prove that such a Being exists, are defective. The ontological proof, or that derived from the very 246THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 4 idea of a God, (that to be a perfect Being, he must be a necessary existence, and that a necessary existence can- not but exist,) is entirely fallacious, being a mere as- sumption of the thing to be proved, and then inferring it from that assumption. The cosmological proof, or that stated in the Theses of the third and fourth cosmo- Jogical ideas, besides the objections already noticed, can only prove a first cause, which is uncaused ; and not, that this first cause is the great ideal himself. This argument therefore rests upon the ontological for sup- port. And the physico-theological proof, or that found- ed on the marks of wisdom and design in the works of nature, is illogically reasoning from objects of experience among men, to objects lying wholly out of the reach of all human experience; and, moreover, if admitted, it does not prove the author of nature to be an infinite and perfect Being, but only a Being of sufficient intelligence and power, to produce such a world as this. Hence, this argument also falls back on the ontological proof. Kant here goes into a Critic of all Theology, on the ground of speculative Reason. Theology is the know- ledge of an Original Being, a God, the Author of all things. ‘This knowledge may be derived either from mere fteason or from Revelation. In the former case, it is rational theology, (theologia rationalis ;) in the latter case it is revealed theology, (theologia revelata.) Again ; rational theology is either transcendental theology, or it is natural theology. Transcendental theology, which is that of a Deist, contemplates its object as it is presented to us in those transcendental ideas, of which we have been treating. It therefore regards God as being known to us merely as the original cause of all things, (ens originarium, re- alissimum, ens entium.) Yet as it does not deny him to be an intelligent Being, we must say, that it admis the existence of a God. In so far as it takes the cosmo- logical ideas for its basis, it may be called cosmo-theology « and in so far as it relies on the ontological argument for proof, in may be called onto-theology. Natural theology is that of a Theist. It cons aa] AU LS FEAST AOA OR TERE ASIN Saorad sel icin ate ce aR ah are yarn) is eo M4 ae ies ar - yee’ yt ereteentomnngs petleny ket ee tee yet ttre cersaeatermeitayny mepemncln ray tuapeme: mene montane Bere ie Reece teens 5 50 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. its object as being an infinite Intelligence or Mind, of which the human mind is the finite image or likeness. It therefore recognizes a living God, a Being of bound- less intelligence, who by his wisdom and power created and governs the world. This theology alone can satis- fy the wants of man.—It is physico-theology, so far as it relies upon the physico-theological proof of the exist- ence of a God; that is, so far as it infers, from the beauty and order of the natural world, an all-wise Ar- chitect ; just as, from any production of human art, we infer that it had an intelligent fabricator. But it is moral theology, when, from the moral law within us, it infers a moral government of the rational universe ; and, of course, a supreme “awgiver and Judge, who takes account of human actions, and will reward or punish every man according to his deserts. From all that has been said in the preceding criticism of Reason, it will be seen, that every attempt to esta- blish theology on a scientific basis, by means of mere speculative Reason, must be futile. It cannot be done. Yet when practical Reason, by means of the moral law within us, has taught us to believe and to confide in God, speculative Reason may be of use, to purify our conceptions, and to give form and consistency to our theological views. CHAPTER VIII. THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. The Results to which this Philosophy leads. WE now come to the concluding part of the Critic of pure Reason. The author says: If we compare a system of tran- scendental philosophy with an edifice, the former part of this work has examined the materials of which the edifice 248 rar Se ER a Rc AS Sa apenas ezTHE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 51 is composed, and this second part will survey the plan of it. And here we shall have to treat of a Discipline, a Canon, an Architectonic, and a History of pure Reason. I. Discipline of pure reason.—A discipline is the op- posite of a culture. It restrains, and ultimately des- troys, the constant inclination to swerve from and over- leap the rules by which we should be governed. Cul- ture carries us forward in the right way; discipline keeps us back from pursuing wrong ways. (1.) Discipline of pure reason in its dogmatic use. Philosophical knowledge is rational knowledge, deriv- ed immediately from ideas or abstract conceptions. Ma-. thematical knowledge is rational knowledge, derived from the construction of such ideas or conceptions ; that is, from schemata, diagrams, or sensible representations of the conceptions. Mathematics is concerned only with quantities; which are always capable of being adequately constructed or represented to the eye. But philosophy is concerned with qualities, which cannot be thus constructed or represented. And this it is, makes the wide difference between mathematics and philo- sophy. For all our knowledge rests ultimately on intui- tions of the objects of it. But philosophical knowledge can have no other than empirical intuitions of its objects, while mathematical knowledge can make its most ab- stract conceptions the object of direct intuition by means of its constructions. ‘Thus we can construct a conical figure, which shall represent all cones; but we can “never construct the colour of a cone; nor can we draw any diagram which shall adequately represent simple existence, though we may easily draw one to represent extension or magnitude. For example; ask a mathe- matician what is the sum of the three angles of every right-lined triangle, and he will draw his diagram to re- present every possible triangle, and will demonstrate by it that the swm must be equal to two right angles ; and his diagram subjects the whole to our intuition. Now, ask a philosopher the same question, and he goes to analyzing his abstract conceptions of angles and lines, 249 ee ow ee < 4 I ee AE EEL ALS. AB AOation. Ce Lp ene bape wiasta Meet batted neue halve Sacbot onc me Lag a ett iets the eras a reais Sa wae Le ont w" ah ee ee ee v 5 Sete ee ate re weytnee pl oreeeeen: sah by ee oe 5 7 ny ij Se een 5 hy " M uy aestintitemee 52 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. but can never find an answer in this way. So the alge- braist represents adequately his quantities, known and unknown, by letters; and then by a regular process, he can solve his problems. But the philosopher cannot make out any such sensible representations of his general conceptions; he can only analyze them; unless he will recur to the sensible intuition of the objects themselves, i.e. of some individual thing under the genus; which will afford only empirical, and never philosophical knowledge of them. Hence, all purely philosophical reasoning is discursive, or purely logical, that is, is based immediately on our conceptions. But mathema- tical reasoning is not purely logical, as it rests on intui- tions of the general conceptions, by means of its construc- trons. Mathematics and philosophy are therefore es- sentially different sciences: and the precision and cer- tainty of the former can never be carried into the latter, Philosophy cannot make out complete DEFINITIONS of the objects of which it treats, as mathematics can do, For those objects are either empirical facts, with regard to which we are liable t0 much deception, and which are moreover always particular facts, and not universal truths ; or they are pure conceptions a prior, (e. Q. substance, cause, right, equity, &c.) and therefore SO obscure as to be incapable of any adequate description on which reliance can be placed. We can indeed ex- pound our conceptions of the things ; but we can never be certain that our conceptions correspond exactly with the things as they exist. On the contrary, the objects of the mathematician being always arbitrary combina- tions or creations of the mind, and also capable of con- struction, and of course of being tntwited, are the only objects that will admit of perfect definitions, Philosophy moreover cannot have her Axtoms, as mathematics can. For all axioms are propositions go clear and evident, from mere Inspection, as to need no proof. Now m athematics, by means of her constructions, can submit many of her fundamental positions to our immediate ¢nspection ; and therefore she has her axioms. —But philosophy, being unable to construct any thing, 250 :THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 03 has to depend wholly on discursive or logical reasoning, and therefore can have no axioms. For, all discursive reasoning is merely the analyzing of our conceptions, and therefore it can educe from those conceptions only what is really and truly contained in them. Philosophy can make no synthetic judgments a priori respecting the ob- jects of nature, but only empirical judgments: and she can reason about them only discursively, that is, logi- cally.— Direct synthetic judgments from perceptions, are Pogmata : similar judgments from construction, are Mathemata. Now all Dogmata are uncertain; Mathe- mata are not. (2.) Discipiine of pure reason in its polemic use.—By its polemic use, I intend, its use in defending positions against the dogmatical deniers of them, or in maintain- ing that the contrary cannot be proved, or even be shown to be more probable. Here Kant introduces those critical remarks on the theses and antitheses of reason in regard to her cosmo- logical ideas, which were quoted in our last Chapter. Me then proceeds: The Critic of pure reason is the proper tribunal, before which all the contests of pure reason should be brought.—Without the aid of this tribunal, reason is situated like men in a state of nature, where no impartial decision of controversies is practica- ble, but the parties must fight it out, and never ‘come to agreement, This critic may put us at ease, and dis- pel all fear lest the enemies of religion should suc- ceed in overthrowing the belief of a God, of the im- mortality of the soul, a future state, &c. They can never do any such thing. At the same time, it teaches us not to rely on the ordinary proofs, (the* ontological, cosmological, and physico-theological,) as alone ade- quate, and such as none but bad men can hesitate to ad- mit: and it shows us, that moral proofs, derived from practical reason, and from the reasonableness 01 the things themselves, must be our chief reliance. Such a critic should never lead us to become scepiics, like Hume and Priestley; but by showing us the true boundaries of rational knowledge, it should ete 20™ S atshealahind Aiba alba) hatha vain —— Til adeemertiershasin ai) UL TONNPER AEE HE ET eye prea epententg cite ha i saa perc? Moet t +A ae uo ye Saad Tip hag” ten fad See eal a ee oe ee : } iH s a ee Ar grt. He eM tac an Mest trae he fete sates cise a tat TO Retr ae rat my Sp ggg ee ge 54. THE CRITICAL PIILOSOPHY. from dogmatism. The first steps taken in matters of pure reason, are apt to make us dogmatists, as being yet but children in knowledge. The next steps bring us into perplexities, and seem to require universal scep- fcism. But the third and last steps (those of sound criticism) show us the limits of true rational knowledge, and dispel scepticism as well as dogmatism. (3.) Discipline of pure reason in regard to hypotheses. Admitting that the conclusions of pure reason in matters of fact are not proved with apodictical certain- ty, it may still be a question whether those conclusions may not be received as hypotheses, and be used advanta- geously as such. And undoubtedly they may be so re- ceived and used in certain cases, but not in all cases, and for all purposes. In particular, they may be used to answer objections; by showing the objector that his arguments are liable to exceptions. But they must never be made the foundation of any system of positive knowledge. In the field of speculative reason, this rule is necessary, in order that nothing may be assumed without the evidence of certainty. But in the field of practical reason, which does not aim to evince truth, but only to advance the best interests of man, the same caution in regard to hypotheses is not necessary. II. The Canon of pure reason.—By a Canon, he tells us, he intends a summary of the principles, a priori of the right use, in general, of any of our intellectual powers. ‘Thus the analysis of the powers of the under- standing, in the first part of the work, is a canon of pure understanding. (1.) Of the ultimate aims of the pure use of our rea- son.—It may be asked, What are the problems, which it is the ultimate aim of pure reason to solve? The answer is: The speculations of reason in her transcen- dental operations all centre on three subjects; viz. the Sreedom of the will, the ummortality of the soul, and the existence of a God. But the merely speculative inter- ests of reason in regard to all the three subjects, are very small, and hardly worth pursuing through so much toil. Because, the sum of our philosophical knowledge 252 ERT IE tart ela a er eee ore Se : arama = seat pe Sere es Sr aaa ami as RES Crapeaa 5 ee SSS > * nea aepecan aeeies i ayaa i eee cee Sa MIG PII THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 59 would be very little enlarged by an affirmative decision of these questions. But it is far otherwise in regard to practical reason, or when the question comes up, What ought we do. (2.) Of an idea of the supreme good, as determining the aim of pure reason.—All the interests of my reason unite in these three questions: I. What can I know ? II. What ought I todo? III. What may I hope for ? The frst question belongs wholly to speculative reason ; and it has, I trust, been adequately answered already. ——The second question belongs wholly to practical rea- son. It is not however transcendental, but moral ; and therefore does not belong to this Critic. The third question is both practical and theoretical; because, when. practical reason has decided it in a general manner, spe- culative reason must come in to define particularly what we may hope for. The second question, What ought I to do? inquires after a rule of duty, not after a mere rule of expediency, or a path to happiness. Complete happiness would con- sist in the full, entire, and eternal satisfaction of all our propensities or desires. Anda rule to guide us to such a state, must be founded on empirical principles ; because experience alone can show us what our propen- sities are, and what will satisfy them. A moral law, on the contrary, shows us what will render us worthy to be happy. It overlooks our propensities, and the means of their gratification. It treats us asfree rational beings, and points us to the conditions of our being made happy. It must therefore rest on the mere ideas of pure reason, and must be known a priort. I assume the existence of such a moral law ; and I refer to the moral judgment of every man, who will candidly examine his own moral feelings, for authority to make the assumption.— Pure reason, in her practical or moral exercise, 18 our voucher for some principles of the possibility ofexperience, namely, for the practicability of such actionsas will accord. with the precepts of the moral law. For, if the law imperatively commands certain actions, those actions must be possible, and the performance of them a E 293 b es rae os Pre a4 re ae ee A he en = Bre Seg Oa een ote EA Ee CM Be ALE, Jwt * root rant eactee etctrs Siicaes re eC ot . } a Y \ TETSPERER REET TE Pty orate boa Pesnle ahem et oer See * ee , Mhel chk dek a6 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. on our free-will. And hence, the principles of pure reason, in her practical or moral capacity, must have objective reality.—From the absolute demands of the moral law, we also infer the possibility of a moral system or unity ; of which, however, speculative reason can have no knowledge, because her province does not ex- tend over the territory of free-will. A moral world would be one conforming to all the precepts of the moral law. Such a world must be possible, in consequence of the freedom of the will; and such ought to be the cha- racter of the existing world. It must be an éntellectual world, and not a physical; because it must be free from all compulsion, and must make no allowances for the weaknesses and imperfections of human nature. The adea of such a world has objective reality, not from any actual intuition of it, but as an object of pure practical reason.—Thus we answer the first of the two questions of pure practical reason, (What must I do 2 )J—namely, obey perfectly the moral law; make the existence of @ moral world to be a reality ; or in other words, do that which will render you worthy of happiness. The last question is, Jf I do so, may I expect to be happy ? And, from the principles of pure practical reason, we infer an affirmative answer. For we have seen, that a moral world (one in which every man ‘shall do what he ought to do) ought to ewist; such being the imper- ative command of the moral law. But the possible ex- istence of such a world presupposes a supreme moral ruler or lawgiver who wills its existence ; because, no otherwise can such a world be possible. Blind nature could never produce it. So then, there must bea supreme Feason, which legislates on moral principles, and which is also the author of nature. Such an Intelligence, con- necting a perfect moral will in creatures with their high- est happiness, and thus causing all the happiness which results from morality, I denominate the ideal of the supreme good. Now, as we do not find the world around us, or the present state of things, to be such a moral world as we have seen should exist, and in which perfect happiness reigns, we necessarily infer a 204seat 2 esate aoe esr aa Saitatis Sg nas a egtalt OH ey di ; Tae BaF Sa a Sis ite ete Saar as “bas 2 tg Me eg TALS SS ee ree err tae nc ke ee et THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. on future State, an unseen world, in which all this shall be realized. This future state, as distinguished from the kingdom of nature, Leibnitz called the kingdom of grace. Practical reason commands us to connect ourselves with the kingdom of grace, and to expect happiness in it, provided we do not render ourselves unworthy of it. In order to our happiness, it is necessary that all our con- duct be regulated by moral maxims; that is, by the precepts of the moral law. But reason cannot feel this ne- cessity, if she regards the moral law as a mere idea with- out objective reality. Hence, she is obliged to assume the existence of an efficient cause, a Gop, the maker and executor of this law. For if there be no God, and no future unseen state, the ideas of morality may excite our admiration or wonder, but can never become efficient motives controlling the will and conduct. Neither hap- press alone, nor morality alone, (the latter considered as rendering man worthy of happiness,) can be reason’s supreme good. We must superadd the expectation of this happiness, on condition of being worthy of it. And hence the necessity of assuming that there is a Gop, the lawgiver, and the centre of the moral unity, or head of the moral world. This supreme Intelligence must be one, not many wills, because many wills would destroy the unity of the moral world. He must be omnipotent, to order all things in subserviency to the unity of the moral world; omniscient, to know the inmost thoughts and purposes of creatures and their moral deserts ; omnipresent, to order all events in sub- serviency to the interests of the moral world; and eternal, to conduct all events to their final issue. (3.) Of opinion, knowledge, and faith—Truth con- sists in the agreement of a proposition with the objects of real existence. The truth of a proposition may be admitted either on objective grounds, or on subjective 5 that is, either for causes existing in the thing, or for causes existing in our own minds. In the former case, the admission is conviction ; in the latter, it is persua- sion. In persuasion there is frequently an illusion, the subjective ground being mistaken for an objective. oe 255oo cad es —_ tal oa etheh hate ‘ets sehen tent og ete rd saeehia aid CNC ae . oe i Reid aes Lil Shad tan Tad cancel tae ak abled a ache mk a Pony Be Dnata wt tar rt A Seo tpiecee inter Secale meaTenb st need een aie aaa ea ae H ert Re Salter ot tes eh da it Sta eee ee eet ee eee Rab Ys fe Sate ape iF . ‘s Per UNG te Cue ron a eA ag THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY: prove whether we are under such illusion, propose the case to others, and see if their minds view it as we do. Yo admit without the consciousness of either subjec- tive or objective validity, is to presume or to be of opinion. If the ground of the admission is subjectively adequate, but not objectively so, the admission is faith or belief: as, e. g. when the object lies beyond our personal cognizance, and we admit the statement because we have confidence in the testimony of others, or for any other Satisfactory reason existing in our own minds. If the ground is both subjectively and objectively adequate, the regarding as true is knowledge ; we know it. We should never venture to hold an opinion, without knowing something about the thing, which may render it possibly true. In the judgments of pure speculative veason, opinions are wholly inadmissible: the propo- sition must contain what is known a priori, and therefore have apodictical certainty, or be rejected altogether. In the transcendental operations of pure reason, an opinion is too little, and knowledge too much to be expected. In the disquisitions of practical reason, Faith or belief is admissible ; and indeed, generally, itis all we can ex~ pect. The two remaining Chapters of the Critic of pure Reason, (viz. the Architectonic, or systematic arrange- ment, and the History of pure reason,) are so concise, and contain so little to interest the reader, that I pass them in silence. In these sketches, I have endeavoured faithfully to exhibit the leading views of Kant in his most celebrat- ed work, and to show in general the spirit and tendency of his Critical Philosophy. That I have in no instance misapprehended his meaning, is more than I dare assert. I can only say, I have done the best I could to repre- sent him fairly and intelligibly to my readers; so that they might be able to form some correct estimate of the merits and demerits of this corypheus of modern German philosophers,SET Ae mechs fe em Sg poe ag ie ser Sa tay Saeed a Se See ANTI-CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 59 CHAPTER IX. ANTI-CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Effects of the Critical Philosophy.—Reinhold’s Doctrine of Thought —Fichte’s Doctrine of Science, or Wissenschaftslehre. 5 Kant’s Critic of pure Reason, first published 1781, was little noticed for a few years; and then it suddenly arrested the attention of all Germany. The majority of the learned assailed it, as subverting many of the best established truths, narrowing far too much the boundaries of human knowledge, and rendering philo- sophy a meagre science of little value or importance. Lhe Wolfian dogmatists considered it as a direct attack upon their doctrines: and the philosophizing dogma- tists regarded it as little short of a protestation against all philosophy. Still it found numerous friends; and it was speedily admitted and expounded in all the uni- versities. And it was soon apparent, that it had com- pletely subverted the older systems of philosophy: and that it had roused the lovers of science throughout Germany, to high enthusiasm for metaphysical studies, and especially for investigating the foundation, source, and origin of rational knowledge. During a very few years, more new and essentially different bases for sys- tems of philosophy were brought forward, and elabor- ately discussed, in Germany, than in all the rest of Europe since the revival of learning. Some of these were only modifications of the Critical Philosophy ; others were intended to subvert it, and to res- tore the old philosophy remodeled and established on sounder principles; and others again sought to find entirely new principles, on which to establish a OR HP? sav g pee ae Aer) Cor Sect Ser are Sea, SMa died bai hain thal Narerat eat id ae 60 ANTI-CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. more perfect philosophy than had ever before beer dreamed of. The chief aim of most of these systems was, to pene- trate into the terra incognita of Kant, that is, into the region of noumena and of supersensible things. The au- thors were unwilling to believe we can know so little, as Kant had represented. They therefore attempted to rend the val, which conceals the unknowable; or to. bridge the unpassable gulf of Kant, which separates be- tween phenomena and noumena in the material world, and between ideas and the objects of them in the world of thought. One of the earliest of these projectors, was Charles Leonard Reinhold, @ professor at Jena and Kiel, who died in 1823, at the age of 65. His theory appeared as early as 1789. It was, that thinking (Vorstellen), or the representing a thing to our own mind, gives us the de- sired objective knowledge. For our consciousness assures us, that in all thinking there are present three things,— the thinker, the thought, and the thinking. The thinker is the sulyect of the action ; the thinking is the act of the thinker; and the thought is the product of that act. Now in this product there is—(1.) Something derived from the objects without the mind, and which is the matter or material of which the thought is composed : —(2.) Something derived from the mind itself, namely, the form of the thought :—and (3.) The consciousness that the material, when shaped by the mind, does take that particular form. But this theory was soon put down; and the author himself ingeniously abandoned it, when shown that it does not explain at all the na- ture of the matter of thought, but only the process of the mind in the act of thinking. This system was called Vorstellungslehre, the Doctrine of Thought. A far wider and more durable popularity attended the speculations of John Gottlieb Fichte, a professor of Jena, who died in 1814, at the age of 52. At first he embraced the Critical Philosophy of Kant; but after- wards he thought he discovered a way to carry absolute science into regions, of which Kant affirms, we can have 258E05 *: Peet Nee aks Se Se i ety tt ANTI-CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. no knowledge. His views were first published in 1794. His system is entitled the Doctrine of Science, (Wis- senschafislehre) ; and he describes it as being the Science, which establishes the possibility and the validity of all science. Such a preliminary science, he said, must rest on a single fundamental principle; and that principle must be so certain in itself as to need no proof from without, and so comprehensive as to embrace both the substance and the form of all scientific knowledge. And such a principle, he maintained, is found in the simple proposition, I am I. For, every thing 7s, what tt ts ; neither less nor more. This self-evident truth may be expressed thus: AA. Now, by substituting the J, of which every one is conscious, in the place of A; and the verb of existence Am, of which also we are conscious, in place of the copula; we obtain the proposition I am 1; of which our consciousness, as often as we reflect upon our own mental acts, furnishes the subject, the pre- dicate, and the copula. Of course, this proposition has apodictical certainty ; for it rests on the ground ofa perfect and known identity between the subject and the predicate. Now by affirming this proposition, a judgment is ex- pressed. But to judge, is to act. Here then is an act of the J. The Z directly affirms its own existence. It is the actor, and at the same time the object of 1ts own action ; and herein consists the consciousness which fur- nishes the knowledge of the proposition. But this act of the J, affirming itself to be J, and nothing more nor less, implies a stop, boundary, or limitation of the sphere of the Z: in other words, it postulates the exist- ence of something that limits the activity of the J, and confines it to its own sphere. Now, this something which limits the 7, whatever it may be, is certainly not J. And hence the proposition I am I, proves the exist- ence of two things or objects; namely, the LI which is affirmed, and the not £ which is postulated. It more- ever proves, that these two objects limit or bound each other ; so that neither of them, in so far as it is consid- 259 es EA ee ee pie bet Jer Tied ex ter or© AT Reese WILLD: ncaa nce or haiiels hata BSUS ete dee ty oe SE Paes | interne be reed ee " eset cr ee | - Sel ne beeen ta eae ataeett an Tela conchae tbe maies eae nee alae a ede Eee ey r ri cu ‘ ne Ss oe) 4 we Stn ; t : reenter Wek ey ee ay Prreneyearegpate cape. seater pe NE AS untAN HY oral srtah ainsi eae oI tate a arc A tbaorat es mtn) , | i, i A Y ‘4 1 eye vg - es Ah’ Ms be , : 4 oy Eerie’ . eat nr ot pe ‘ “ : ¥ . fee bam Wwe intellectual activity ; here he contemplates it asa free 260 62 ANTI-CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. ered as bounded by the other, is infinite or unlimited, but is finite. But what is this not J, which sets bounds to the 1? —Manifestly it is something which owes its existence to the J. For the Z, when reflecting upon itself and its operations, voluntarily or spontaneously limits and bounds itself; and thereby it gives up its claim to boundless existence and activity, and transfers a por- tion of existence and activity to the not-Z s which is to the Z the external world, or the universe without. This not-J, therefore, has no existence but what the [ gives to it, by the act of limiting itself in the judgment, Lam I. Of course the world around us, or the universe, is only an ideal existence, a world of own creation. We indeed conceive of it as real, when we consider i¢ as limiting the Z: but this limitation isofour own making ; the J is the only real actor. And this holds true of all the individual objects, material or immaterial, which the mind contemplates as exterior to itself, and to which collectively she gives the appellation not-L. For the J, in all its actions, meets with obstructions, boundaries, or limitations to its activity ; and according to the variety in the obstructions or limitations, it forms num- ‘berless conceptions or ideas of supposed or postulated objects, which are endlessly varied, and which develop themselves continually in new and unexpected forms. The conceptions, so endlessly various, are the postulated objects, considered as limitations of the f. But as the /, in all cases, voluntarily limits itself, or gives being to the obstructions to its own activity, the J is the only actor ; and the various conceptions of objects without, are only certain forms of the activity of the I; that is, they are all ideal existences, We now come to the practical or moral part of Fichte’s system. And here again, he takes the same proposition, I am I, for his fundamental principle: and he also reasons from it in much the same manner. But he contemplates the Zin a different character. In the first or theoretical part, he considered the J asa merelySE IS stat eee ANTI-CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. 63 agent, striving to accomplish objects or to attain ends. In itself, and as limiting the not-J, the practical J is absolute and free, infinite, and the only real existence. And as a free activity, it is a causality : but in its con- sceousness, or when it affirms itself in the form I am J, it always appears as something finite, something limit- ed by a not-T ; and its causality can manifest itself to the consciousness only as an effort to accomplish some- thing ; which effort is always obstructed and limited by the not-/. Hence the finite practical J contemplates it- self as acted upon, limited, and restrained by a not-L; while the absolute practical I contemplates itself as acting upon, restraining, and limiting the not-£, and therefore feels itself to be free, unlimited in action, and the only real existence. But the not-Z is a mere crea- ture of the J, as we have before seen. And hence, the inert and lifeless not-J, by which the practical J is limited in its free activity, is a mere ideal existence. And thus we arrive at a knowledge of the essential nature both of the practical J, and its opposing not-J ; just as we previously ascertained the essential nature of the theoretical / and its opposing nof-L£; and in both, we find the J to be the only actor, and the only real existence, and the not-J to be a postulated cdeal thing, which owes its existence entirely to the action of the J. ‘¢‘ After thus annihilating, by his idealism, the evi- dence of the objectivity of any sensible world, and leay- ing us only a system of empty images, (says Tennc- mann,) he labours to establish, by means of conscience, a belief in the reality not only of a sensible world, but also of an intellectual world independent of it, and of a supersensible order in the latter world; and moreover, the possibility of acting for ends, which may be realized by such action. He commences with the idea of free- dom, i. e. a universal and absolute independence, mani- festing itself in the tendency of the J, from which origin- ates the idea of independence. The principle of morals, therefore, or the moral law, (the law for free as 6]et Sr aa teshabia cies ta testa h Cla ig ‘ te * ey ‘ Rs wee tesens” ere katy — — — A saab aia POOLE ahaa ne tn nee haahacedlaaiitae 11 Oe LPO eM ae ‘ . a rae hae Sep! eo Mo . 4 Sch t Othe Soster tateshaameatietoe alle cnathneans Inaba: eneienneiimartiaael nemeamienameacanenenaa RTE! . ‘ d 5 ~~ mew Ne j Ny ta 7 bedi Me led ot ‘ by SE K 1"s Parte wpe AIG! ite ute ete . 4p ese’ be Te tet? SILL shania ipoiaetneieeeee naan eee ee ee nies Satie Soha aetaas et Wiaterataetetot CRUEILAL eee ee oe fr Se ae i) i ; ANTI-CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. consists in the necessary thought or purpose of an in- telligent being, to determine its free choice uncondition- ally, agreeably to the idea of independence ; or, in po- pular language, to follow conscience unconditionally. Lhis determines what is duty. Virtue consists in being im perfect harmony with ourselves.” (Tennemann, Grundriz, § 395, p. 500.) “But Fichte’s religious philosophy attracted most notice. For he there asserts expressly, that Gop is the moral order of the world; and that to this conclu- sion the J is brought, by the consciousness that its free activity is bound by the idea of duty. Yor by striving to realize duty, the J strives after a moral order in the world of its own creation; and thus it approximates to God, and has the life which comes from God. In this moral order of the world, happiness is the result of morality. But this happiness is not perfect felicity ; which never existed, andnevercan. And thus all regard for perfect felicity is excluded. We need no other God than this order of the world; although we are prone to think of a particular Being as the Creator of it: F or, (1.) It is not possible to ascribe intelligence and per- sonality to God, without making him a finite being like ourselves. (2.) To conceive of God as a particular sazb- stance, 1s idolatry, and militates with the very idea of him ; because a substance is something which has a sensible existence in time and place. (3.) We cannot ascribe eaistence to him, because existence belongs only to objects of sense. (4.) There has never yet been brought forward any intelligible word, by which we can express the creation of the world by God. (5.) The expectation of perfect felicity (Gluckseligkeit), is a chimera; and a God supposed to produce it, is an dol ministering to our pleasure,—the prince of this world. These representations, brought forward in extravagant paradoxes and with great assurance, (but which Fichte himself abandoned aiterwards,) were treated as real atheism ; and they drew upon him very disagreeable consequences, which he did not altogether merit.” (Lennem. p. 502.) 962 Ged NS SecalANTI-CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. “‘Fichte attempted, by various statements of his doc- trine, to bring people to understand him, and he also changed his views on some points; as, among others, in regard to the relation his system bears to the Critical Philosophy, (for at first, he maintained them to be in accordance, ) and in regard to the way in which the ori- ginal activity of the Z is brought into consciousness, (for he first attempted it by the mere laws of thinking, but afterwards by an intellectual intuition.) But the most striking difference between the more recent and the earlier form of his Doctrine of Science, is, that at first it was idealism, and afterwards realism. In the former, the starting point was the activity of the ; im the latter, it is the absolute existence of God, as the only veal Being, who is self-existent and life itself, and of whom the world and consciousness are a likeness or schema; and objective nature, he considered, as the absolute barrier or limitation of the divine activity. In producing this change in the Doctrine of Science, Schel- ling’s philosophy, as well as Fichte’s sense of religion, seems to have been operative. The Doctrine of Science excited great attention, and met with warm approba- tion and warm friends; and likewise with severe critics and strenuous opposers, especially among the Kantians. And at last, it had the fate of every system: for, notwithstanding its imposing tone, (by which it greatly promoted an extravagant love of speculation, and con- tempt for real knowledge,) it could not gain the stand- ing of a generally received philosophy. Yet it cannot be denied, that Fichte’s idealism had great influence on the spirit of his age; and, by the force of the authors peculiar eloquence, it fostered in many minds a strong predilection for the super-sensible.” ( Tennem. p. 509.)Me ete kon eae Se etter DLA pte her Sys Wee ha he | eM Sn Deere eee rane erty! im ra Th ae (ax) ye . + * AON yee TORN AY TTT Teer or erereatenetenry Ny ee We et ge Sto Sap ie) mot , APs me! Bed Mh Tad toby: Spray: ae ote ee fai oo : . Md * taller hierar eet ene eee ee acter 8 a Natit Te PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY; CHAP RE R X. PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. Schelling’s Doctrine of Identity, Identitatslehre.—Fichte’s altered Doctrine of Science.—Other Pantheists : Bouterwek, Bardili, Eschenmayer, Wagner, Krause. THe next system demanding our attention, is Schel- ling’s Doctrine of Identity, Identitatslehre ; so named, from its maintaining the perfect identity of the know- ledge of things and the things themselves, or the entire coincidence of the ideal and real, the subjective and the objective. It is also called the doctrine of ALL-ONE, Alleinhettslehre, or Alleinslehre : because it maintains that the universe is God, and God the universe ; or, that God developing himself in various forms, and according to general laws, is the only existence. The distinguished author of this system, Fred. Wm. Jos. von Schelling, was born in 1775, studied at Tubin- gen till he passed Philos. Dr., then at Leipsic, and after- wards at Jena under Fichte. In 1302 he became M.D., and the next year a professor of philosophy at Wurtz- burg: thence he removed to Munich in 1817, to Erlan- gen in 1820, and back to Munich in 1827, where he probably still lives, an academician, a court-counsellor, and a professor of philosophy. Schelling became an author at the age of 20, being then an admirer of Fichte’s philosophy, from which he soon swerved ; and at the age of 25, had published the ground-work of his new system, which he laboured to perfect during a few years, and then turned his attention to other objects. For nearly 30 years he has published very little on philosophy: and his system has never been so fully and so lucidly explained, that the philosophizing public could perfectly understand it. And this, in the opinion 264terion t eas PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY: of Krug, is one reason why his philosophy, which at first attracted so much notice and so many admirers, is now seldom mentioned in the German universities, and is sinking into oblivion. The philosophy of Schelling depends less on logical demonstrations, than on bold assumptions claiming to be intellectual intuitions. Yet it does not disclaim all support from sound reasoning. A fundamental princi- ple with the author is, that the very idea of philosophy presupposes the possibility of a perfect and known coin- cidence between our knowledge of things and the essen- tial nature of these things; because, it is only such a knowledge of things that can be justly called philoso- phical or true knowledge. Then, without stopping to inquire, as Kant has done, how far such knowledge can extend, he goes on the supposition that there are no de- finite limits to it; and therefore his only inquiry is, how such knowledge may be supposed to originate ; or, how can the fact be explained, that we have such know- ledge. Now, if the laws of nature were also the laws of hu- man consciousness, or if the former were always exactly coincident with the latter, then our consciousness would contain an exact transcript, a perfect fac-simile, of what is taking place in the natural world around us, at least so far as our cognizance of things without extends. In other words, our minds would be mirrors reflecting per- fect images of the things around us, and of all the changes they undergo. And hence, by looking into our own minds we might there read the laws of nature, and learn perfectly the true nature of every thing that falls within the circle of our obseryation. Now this suppo- sition so perfectly explains how philosophical knowledge is possible, and so pours broad day-light upon what was before dark and inexplicable, that we cannot reasonably hesitate to adopt it as true. It is therefore to be as- sumed with confidence. But still a difficulty remains; viz. How happens it, that these two mysterious streams (the course of nature in the objective world, and the course of human an 69 GFT PE eeoy 7 SN ae La eaten rete a tate ges mer yore lee St aiahaaaietiahansaenaabinammanemed ites cedebeemar emanate seems oe aTrnRAAE , bi © } mot atS hee ae ‘ are aa partes 68 PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. sciousness in the subjective or intellectual world,) should so perfectly agree, or be identical in all their meander- ings ? Our actual observations cannot trace them back to their source, nor follow them down to their final ter- mination ; what then can explain the mystery of their entire coincidence? Answer: Spinoza has shown us, that there is only one substance, or one real existence, in the universe, namely Gop, who is continually develop- ing himself, and by that development gives being to all that exists, whether material or immaterial. And here is a key to the mystery. The two streams flow from one and the same fountain, namely Gop, as he existed anterior to his development. They are equally in their nature Gop, or the divine first principle of all things, who unfolds himself alike in both. They are therefore not fwo, but one and the same, in their essential nature, and of course also in the laws of their movement. We thus arrive at the source, the grand central point, from which all things radiate, and in which all contrarieties and diversities meet and coalesce; viz. the Divine, the Absolute, the All- One, in its primitive state or form. And all true philosophy must begin with a knowledge of this primal All- One, and then, by tracing the deve~ lopments of this All-One till it expands itself into the universe around us, a complete and perfect system of philosophy will be obtained. This system, which Tennemann justly characterizes as the poetry of the human mind, attempts to explain ex- actly the process by which the Absolute or the All-One gradually developeditself, till it became the now existing universe. But it would carry us too far to go over the whole process, and we therefore only subjoin the fol- lowing general scheme of it. I. The primitive form of the Absolute or All-One, (God,) is that in which all contrarieties and diversities are completely merged and lost, and only an abstract identity of every thing can be apprehended. | II. This Absolute reveals itself in nature ; which is the Absolute in the copy. And it reveals itself under Ne general forms or aspects; the one form is that of onR aodNe oar ig Sa a ea Gs es et PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY, 69 real existences, or things; the other form is that of ideal existences, or objects which exist only in the mind, and which can never be subjected to the senses. The ob- jects belonging to each form possess different degrees or quantities of that essential nature which is common to them as a class ; and this difference in degree or quan- tity is denoted by the algebraic expressions for the power of quantities, a/, a7, a3. The real existences, or the proper things, are of three kinds or degrees; viz. 1. (a!) The ponderous, or mere matter. 2. (a*) The light, or motion, power, force. 3. (a®) The living, or organic beings. The crown and complement of all these real exist- ences, are (1.) Man, the microcosm or world in minia- ture; and (2.) The external Universe, as a whole. The ideal existences are also of three kinds or de- orees ; VIZ. 1. (a!) Truth, the subject of knowledge and ideas. 2. (a?) Goodness, the subject of religion and feeling. 3. (a?) Beauty, the subject of taste and the arts. The crown and complement of the zdeal existences, are (1.) Society; and (2.) the Aistory of man or of the human race. Schelling has devoted himself chiefly to the develop- ments of the Absolute in nature, or to the real side of his system; and has only occasionally, and in general terms, explained his views of the ideal and moral side of his scheme. Respecting morals, he maintains, that to know God is the foundation of all morality ; and that there can be no moral world, unless there is a God, Virtue is a state, in which the soul acts agreeably to the internal necessity of its nature, and not conformably to some law without. Morality is also happiness ; for happiness is not a mere perquisite of virtue, but is vir- tue itself, The tendency of the soul to be in union with its centre, God, is morality. Civil Society is col- lective life conformed to the primitive divine image, so far as respects religion, science, and the arts. It is an exterior organization of a self-erected harmony in the department of freedom itself. History, as a whole, is a 267 i Racarnernr yyy ewes ps epee entee a a nadia hans rameter tate aoe ae ie ere Oe et hd SU cok ec ARID Be Da hl nna partes oat aheribiall UR tithe 1 merci ae We Sere fet 4 pe tay) . Crue SEE ahet bebe a . PNET Y at pe be! ; See oe Se eee ete . rey he 70 PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. gradually developing revelation of the Absolute or of God. Beauty is “the infinite represented as finite.” Art, as an ability to represent ideas to the senses, is a clear perception of God by the mind. Tennemann objects to this philosophy: (1.) That it subverts all virtue and moral obligation, by subjecting every thing to blind fatality, or to a natural necessity ; for God must develop himself; and whatever occurs, must occur from the very laws of nature. ‘There is therefore no freedom of action, and of course no virtue, and no morality, in any being whatever. (2.) The system has no basis or foundation; for the Absolute, in which all things are said to originate, is a sheer nothing. Because an Absolute, i.e. an abstract Identity, without any relative identity, or without any things which are identical, can have no existence. (3.) The form of this system has only the appearance of being scientific. It exhibits no substantial proofs, no scientific deductions, but only positive assumptions, and naked hypotheses. (4.) It presumptuously claims to have a perfect know- ledge of God ; and it identifies him with external na- ture, and is so far panthersm ; and, moreover, it subjects God to the higher conditions or laws of his nature, and therefore denies him all freedom of action. As a whole, it is rather the poetry than the philosophy of a reason- ing mind. The pantheistic principle of Spinoza, or the doctrine that God developes and expands himself into the exist- ing universe, which Schelling thus revived and made the basis of his philosophy, was eagerly adopted by vast numbers in Germany ; and many who did not follow Schelling’s opinions on other points, embraced this doc- trine as true, and as shedding much light on philosophy. Hence, in different ways, it was wrought into various new systems of philosophy, of which it was made to be an essential element. Even Fichte himself, when he found how abhorrent to public sentiment was his former doctrine, (namely, that God is only the moral order of the world,) did not he- sitate to adopt Schelling’s idea of an Absolute Existence, 268 |ive GaN teed sae Se te Tek Sey Ste Griese re tea ete ce PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. Tt from which every thing finite is propagated or evolved. From the year 1804, till his death in 1813, instead of maintaining, as he had done, that the Jor the human mind is the only real existence in the universe, antece- dent to which nothing real ever existed, and around and above which nothing real now exists, he acknow- ledged an eternal self-existing God to be the only and the living source of all being; and that he, by develop- ing himself, gives real though not independent existence to all human minds. These finite human minds are still the Z of his philosophy ; and as they are divine in their origin and nature, being a part of God himself, they are capable of understanding and knowing God, and of loving and serving him. As to the external world, or the not-J, it is altogether inanimate and life- Jess; it is no part of the divine nature or essence, but is merely the abutting and bounding of the acts of God and of human minds, or the voluntary limitations which these acts affix to themselves; and therefore they are iz merely ideal things, the creations of the spontaneous 2 activity of the living or real beings, viz. God and his progeny. Fichte therefore no longer made the J the sole foundation and source of all philosophy ; but rather assumed a new foundation, namely the idea of God, of which the J, from its participation in the divine nature, is capable of an immediate and true knowledge. But the general opinion of the learned was, that Fichte’s new principle was entirely irreconcilable with all his former doctrines. And hence his attempt to improve his sys- tem, and to render it more acceptable to the public, on- ly tended to convince people that it had no solid found- ation; and thus to induce his followers to leave his school, and seek for other guides in philosophy. Professor Fred. Bouterwek, of Gottingen, likewise supposed that there is but one real existence in the uni- verse ; and that this absolute Existence pervades all things, and constitutes their reality. Whatever is real, or whatever truly exists, is a development of the Abso- lute, or of this one real Existence; all else is merely imaginary, or ideal, and destitute of objectivity. Andsss seit hate Stat oarcae a OL bk» We : A a ATEN Eta reateeeeenanhlatae heron pengtsemptepner /ftsencsemamtags ath a ete staat teat ties alin sous eeata laces tatiana sae ake mieaaed a etnaeaaaaad ie t er " 4 o ~*~! ait ie Sey Fie gr Myre . te Mila 1 ee Ne ee a ey Merge ' nee nee ia PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. therefore, to have any true objective knowledge of things, or to understand and know when our concep- tions have objective reality, must be simply to appre- hend the presence or the absence of the Absolute ; that is, it is merely to perceive where the Absolute exists, and where there is only the deceptive appearance of its pre- sence. But mere thinking and reasoning discursively on the subject can never detect the presence of the Ab- solute; for all thinking and discursive reasoning have to assume it as already known. And hence reason inust possess an absolute power of knowing the real; a power which neither thinks nor feels, but which is the foundation of all thinking and feeling on the subject. Entertaining these views, Professor Bouterwek pub- lished in 1799, what he called an Apodictic, or a demon- stration of true knowledge; in which he maintained that the human mind, as itself partaking of the Abso~ lute, has ¢mmediate perception or knowledge of the pre- sence or absence of reality in the objects of its contem- plation. But after a few years, recalling this opinion, he maintained that reason can have no immediate intui- tions of the Absolute himself, or of his actual presence in objects: nevertheless, feeling her power to rise above mere sense, reason confides in her conclusions or judg- ments respecting the presence of the Absolute. He moreover asserted, that it is the proper business of phi- losophy to investigate this whole subject ; and to as- certain definitely how far reason can go in detecting the presence or absence of the Absolute in objects, and where we must be contented with mere probabilities on this great question. Professor C. G. Bardili, of Stuttgard, brought out in 1800, a new method of connecting the Absolute, or the Original- One, (Ur- Eins, as he denominated it,) with philosophy. This Original-One is the subject-matter of all logical thinking ; so that Logic is a real science, and the only true metaphysics. All logical thinking, moreover, is computation or reckoning, in the mathe- matical sense. That is, it is the perpetual repetition and involution of one and the same unit, the Original- 7 ) 27a fare See Gin tha tae se te og oR Seg ag oe sa Soe Wate ales PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. qs One. But abstract thinking has reference to no definite object or finite being. It therefore does not afford us any objective knowledge, until we apply it to some definite object. It only shows us what is possible in the na- ture of things. But when we apply it to any definite object, then real or objective matter is brought into the process ; and a judgement is formed of that object, by which the object is pronounced to be a real existence, or only a possible existence. This seems to be the amount of his obscure treatise, entitled the Elements of the first Logic, &c. which puzzled the brains of speculators for a time, and then was rejected as a baseless phantom. Professor C. A. Eschenmayer, of Tubingen, at first agreed very well with Schelling; but in 1803, he de- parted essentially from him, by maintaining that the Absolute which reason intuits, is not directly and im- mediately the Absolute himself, the primary source of all that exists ; but is only an image or likeness of him. And hence philosophical knowledge is far more limited, than Schelling’s theory supposes. ‘The comprehensible and the explicable fall within the sphere of knowledge or philosophy ; but the Absolute himself, and whatever is incomprehensible and inexplicable, belong to the sphere of faith or religion. So also Professor J. Wagner, of Wurtzburg, left the ranks of Schelling’s adherents in 1804, and has ever since philosophized in his own way. The Absolute him- self, says Wagner, is no object of our direct knowledge ; but the created universe is the living form of him; and the laws of the universe are the type by which he displays himself. Hence we must recognise him as ex- isting beyond our ken, and as knowable only through the laws of nature. And as mathematics is the science which best investigates and defines the laws of nature, philosophy must depend chiefly on that science, in con- nection with the history of man and the study of ane Professor C. C. F. Krause, of Gottingen, coincided with the leading views of Eschenmayer, as above stated. Heheldthe Absolute, or the Original Being, (das He Resi SUS poeta te eaee So ee ter ene eter rr oat . J, w » ‘ * ) ag ‘ ‘ yi F x rn “1 ryt ne es mpbamaE te weAwE OS LE ye mmmp Pat hy 9 Me ee ea ater eter hy te tat Ne i ai Nese tee SU Me Tee HY ° aia i ae ae eo a ; . r ; i a) ee m * “oe a) : a i - supposed, that reason has direct intuition of the true na- CpPre & 74 PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. wesen, as he chose to call him,) to be the Eternal, far above both the natural and the intellectual worlds, those two spheres into which the created universe di- vides itself: and yet he is the essential principle of both, pervading them and giving them life and being, though not discoverable by us. In his opinion, philosophy na- turally divides itself into—(1.) General Philosophy, or Ontology ;—(2.) Intellectual Philosophy ;—(3.) Philoso- phy of Nature;—and (4.) Synthetic Philosophy. CHAPTER XI, PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. Hegel’s absolute Idealism.—Logic the only Metaphysics. THE most famous, and the most recent of the German pantheists, who have attempted to improve upon Schel- ling, is Dr Geo. Wm. Fred. Hegel, a professor at Berlin, who died in 1831, at the age of 61. He was born at Stuttgard, and educated at Tubingen, where he became intimate with Schelling, and adopted and for a time defended his philosophy. But at length, gradually de- viating from Schelling, he set up a new school, which became very popular, and has of late altogether eclipsed that of his former friend. Both maintained the identity of God and the uni- verse, and the perfect coincidence between subjective and objective knowledge. But Hegel’s was a system of absolute idealism; while Schelling’s was rather a system of realism. For Schelling, like Spinoza, consi- dered the original All-One as a real substance, which evolved itself into the existing universe; but Hegel considered mere ideas or conceptions, as the only real existences; he believed, that there is nothing in the universe more substantial or more real than what he calls concrete ideas and conceptions. Again; SchellingNES Oe Se SE eS es Bee ath Ser e 4 5 PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. 75 ture of things, or of the objects existing around us and without us; but Hegel denied any such intuition of objects without ; and maintained, that the mind only looks inward upon itself, its conceptions and ideas, and by analyzing them arrives at all philosophical know- ledge. And hence, according to Hegel, a logical ana- lysis of ideas and conceptions, is the only real meta- physics, or the true and proper science of things; and Logic, instead of being, what it has generally been re- garded, a mere formal science, or one that treats only of the abstract forms of thought, and the laws of correct reasoning, is really and truly a science of things, and the only source of true philosophical knowledge. In accordance with these views, Hegel divides all philosophy into three parts; namely, the science of Lo- gic or philosophy in general ; the philosophy of nature ; and the philosophy of mind. The first part, called Lo- gic, ig the science of things in general, and corresponds with what is usually termed Ontology and pure Meta~- physics. The second part, the philosophy of nature, treats of time and space, matter and motion, material bodies and their properties, and of organic nature, geo- logy, vegetables, and animals. The third part, the phi- losophy of mind, treats of the human soul and its facul- ties, of right and wrong, morality and duty, and of the arts, religion, and philosophy. Only the first part has been fully developed by the author, in his Science of Logic, in two vols. 8vo. first printed in 1812 and 1816. But he has given us a general treatise covering the whole ground in his Encyclopedia of the philosophical Sciences, in one vol. 8vo. first published in 1817, and again in 1827 and 1830. Both these works are now before me. Hegel is the most unintelligible writer I ever read. Even the most acute German philosophers complain of his style, as being not only very harsh and dry, but so extremely obscure that they cannot fully understand him. Although abundantly warned on this point, I had the temerity to take up his Encyclopedia, and read it attentively from beginning to end, and es iSees tes teeter ened le i ie et ge a Y mE HE Stet berkee Spge | Pare Wetet UL MTL ar ir i aha ie ee ete ee : 8 6 | ; ar Oe ey ‘ } r Nesta” wo ere - —— e a Sas a bare ie eeaheain mS shee bial eee’ toate nate’ rr a Ts me ad ; " re 8 y . rs , Ct PO ROW ae are ray Bit 8 OM MP z e ae ne . 76 PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. parts of it a second, a third, and even a fourth time, comparing it often with his Logic, vainly hoping to get some idea of that logical analysis which he tells us is the basis ofall philosophy. But after a fortnight’s hard study, I was nearly as ignorant of the whole process, and of every part of it, as when I first sat down to examine it. The most I could learn was, that he commences with the idea of entity (das Seyn) in the abstract. He then tells us, that his second definition of entity is, that it is nothing (das Nichts) ; and that the union of entity and nothing, or the transition of the one imto the other, constitutes actual existence (das Daseyn); which, he says, may be illustrated by the verb to become (werden), as whatever becomes any thing, passes over from noé being that thing, to being that thing. It may also be illustrated by the import of the noun beginning (An- fang), as beginning is a transition from non-existence to existence. After advancing thus far, I found myself in the midst of water so deep and so turbid, that F could neither reach nor see the bottom. Still I suffered him te carry me forward. When he had fully analyzed and ex- plained, as he averred, all that is material in the idea of pure entity, he proceeded to analyzeand explain the idea of being ( Wesen), or thing, in the abstract ; and then the ideas of phenomenon, and actuality, and lastly of eoncep- tion, and object, and sdeas. This closed the first part. On the philosophy of nature and of mind, he was equally obscure and incomprehensible : I could understand only here and there a detached thought. As I am unable to comprehend his works myself, I can do nothing better than detail the opinions of others. I will therefore translate from Krug, (Encyclop. Philo- soph. Lexicon,) such parts of his statements as seem most deserving a place in these sketches. In the body of his work, as printed in 1833, Krug thus writes: “Hegel was at first a true follower of Schelling, with whom he united in publishing a critical Journal of Philosophy, Tubing. 1802-3. In this period of his philosophizing also appeared his Tract on the difference oe Fichte’s system and that of Schelling. But hePANTHEISTIC PITILOSOPHY. Ve gradually separated himself from his master, and reject- ed in particular his doctrine of intellectual intuition, as being an unwarranted assumption. Yet he retained Schelling’s fundamental idea, namely the oneness of the subjective or ideal, and of the objective or real; and in the idea of this oneness he searches for that absolute knowledge and absolute truth, to which, according to the demands of this school, philosophizing must soar. Hence also, he maintained that pure conception in it- self, is entity ; and that real entity is nothing but pure conception. And this he does, without first demonstrat- ing the unity of entity and conception, or, as it should be called, (since conception is only the product of the thinking mind,) the oneness of entity and thinking. Equally arbitrary is his assertion, in a practical view, that whatever is rational is actual, and whatever is actual is also rational ; a position which may be consi- dered as making moral precepts, viewed as demands of reason upon the will, altogether nugatory and superflu- ous, since the will can make nothing to be real, but what will thereby become rational. But the weakest part of Hegel's system is the esthetical or the philoso- pay of art, and the theological or the philosophy of re- ligion. And here, one who was formerly avery warm ad- vocate of his system, but who on a better acquaintance with it cooled down considerably, ( Weisse, in his Syst. of Aisthetics,) says that Aisthetics and Theology begin, where Hegel leaves off; for, ‘ what we call ideas of the Beautiful and of God, Hegel recognises only as to their psychological and historical apparition : that is, he con- siders them as phenomena, and the science of them as a part of the phenomenology of mind,’ In short, Hegel seems not to have fully perfected his system. And as he was any thing rather than a master in the art of composition, and as his writings suffer as much from their obscurity as from a sort of dry harshness, 1t 1s scarcely possible to form a satisfactory judgment of his philosophy. Those who profess to comprehend it, dis- cover in it the consummated system of pure rational science. * * *: * *. * Moreover, it is a strik- 275 Se Ses Tg Dole ARTES Seta Sg a Sg eS a Set okt Sie ht sea dg ae Sane ae NINA AR te REPEL PA vatsrei * cows CR Ce renee bas ‘ , ‘ . i‘ n Cie od las UIA Dares foe ad eminence ae et daa alee Ci oaks rll Binet Seated ae he teehee : Tartare a toy © Nah ae a ee i+ a ee rote AX es ie aaa ee ; 5 AE “oh + " 4 Ce - ens 276 PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. ing fact, that among the numerous followers of Hegel, no one has hitherto been able to remove the obscurity, heaviness, and dryness of his mode of philosophizing, by a more clear, agreeable, and lively exhibition. All use the words, the phrases, and the turns of expression of their master; as if they were magi¢ formulas, which would lose their power by the slightest change. Jurare in verda magistrt seems to be no stranger in this school. Yet this renowned philosopher, who received special favour from the great, and thereby gained the more ad- herents, did not fail of opposers who assailed him with more or less ardour.” After recounting various attacks upon Hegel’s system, Krug proceeds: “It may here be asked, whether this school will be able to sustain it- self long, against so many, and certainly not inconsider- able opposers. To us it appears, this school no longer has internal union ; and therefore it is not likely to es- cape dissolution, whatever may be done from without to bolster it up, on the false supposition that it is better suited than any other to sustain theexisting order of things inchurch and state. Even the founder of it himself seems to have had some presentiment of such a result. For, agreeably to a letter from Berlin, (inserted in a Period- ical, Dec. 17, 1831, which in general speaks favourable of Hegel,) he said, a little before he died, that he was anxious respecting the fate of his philosophy after his decease, because among all his disciples only one un- derstood him, and that one misunderstood him.” In his supplemental volume, printed in 1838, Krug resumes his account of Hegel, thus: “The three prin- cipal parts of his system, are :—Logic, as being the sci- ence of idea in itself (an sich); Philosophy of N ature, as being the science of idea in its secondary state (in ihrem Andersein); and Philosophy of Mind, as being the science of idea in its reversion from its secondary state into itself. Accordingly, there appears every- where in this system a triplicity of subjects, together with their reconciling unity, in which they are all con- tained as momenta or elements. In this system the oneness of Entity and Conception is vindicated, on thecae oe ee Fa ee ed 2 aie Met oe he eee PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. ground of a supposed necessity inherent in Conception to move (develop) itself; and this it does, by a progres- sive negation ; so that, e.g. Entity, by a negation of it- self, passes into existence ; and God, by a negation of himself, passes into a World; &c. For God is in self (an sich), and must also be for self (fur sich) ; in order to which, he must become his second self (seinem An- dern,) and this is Nature, or the World. So in Hegel’s Lectures on the Philos. of Religion, (published by Mar- heineke in 1832,) this fundamental thought is various- ly drawn out, that God is the eternal, all-comprehend- ing process of the absolute idea, which returns from the form of its secondary state (ihres Anderseins), its mani- festation in nature, into itself, and, by means of human consciousness, attains to its individuality (ihrem Fur- sichsein) as Spirit. That this doctrine comes near to Pantheism, is not to be denied; notwithstanding Hegel and his school will not admit it, and by the use of biblical and religious phraseoloegy—to which, however, they annex a new and professedly deeper and more oc- cult meaning, they endeavour to give to their doctrine a colouring of orthodoxy. And hence Lschenmayer (in his Tract, entitled, Hegel’s religious philosophy ¢ompar- ed with the principles of Christianity, p. 100,) passes the following judgment on this philosophy: ‘It is no- thing but a Logic vaunting itself in Christian verities.’ And he goes on, perhaps with too much severity : ‘Hegel has a God without holiness, a Christ without free love, a Holy Ghost without illumination, a Gospel without faith, an Apostasy without sin, Wickedness without conscious guilt, an Atonement without remis- sion of sin, a Death without an offering, a religious As- sembly without divine worship, a Release without im- putation, Justice without a judge, Grace without re- demption, Dogmatic Theology without a revelation, a this Side without a that side, an Immortality without a personal existence, a Christian Religion without Chris- tianity, and in general, a Religion without religion.’ And in an Article on Hegel’s philosophy, (in the Allg. Kirchenzeit. 1836,) in which the religious and ecclesias- 277 19 b f Paton ST Had ( Sed Se eee eked tornnh ocibn hate eat sence a? iki 2 : ‘a oe TUNG RENT HT Pee eye inte eile gsyaninatgt aes NRT Petpet: pee temerNanaeiNmm ove he, aellaee” SETHE HEMET ¢ SES ILM et et ion c a (a Se aria ee net ; PESHAWAR ae aca geon ¢ Crp oe aw c Ne ee ee ee en a ‘ eet " grid be ‘ $ ‘ “) me ee Pe i oe ee ge ge Oe Rio he thr her Pea 5 : ‘oe ans ee nee PANTHEISTIC PHILOSOPHY. tical part of this philosophy is particularly reviewed, the following severe judgment is pronounced : ‘ Hegel’s philo- sophy is nothing i atse/f and by itself, nor was its author in himself but beside himself? Compare also the Words of a Layman on the Hegelian-Straussian Christology, Zurich 1636, 8vo. No less unsatisfactory have the ex- plorers of nature found Hegel’s theory of the philosophy of nature. Thus Link (in his Propylaen, &c. vol. I. p. 46.) tells us, that Hegel’s system, although framed with the greatest metaphysical acuteness, ‘is of no value in the science of nature; indeed, it is painful to see what blunders Hegel makes, when he speaks on subjects of natural science, astronomy, and mathematics. He is also so dictatorial and so bitter, that one would laugh over him, if it were a laughable thing to see such a man so self-deceived.’ ” After these remarks, Krug fills nearly three large 8vo. pages with notices of the numerous works for and against Hegel’s philosophy, which issued from the Ger- man press during about 12 years ending in 1837. After Hegel’s death in 1831, his devoted followers and ad- mirers, (chiefly young men, in and around Berlin,) re- solutely met the assailants of his system, and exerted themselves strenuously to recommend it and give it cur- rency. For this end they collected and published a voluminous edition of Hegel’s Works, including his pri- vate letters, and his manuscripts and notes for Lectures, with elaborate prefaces and introductions. On the other hand, numerous adversaries, (and among them were many of the older and graver philosophers, ) assailed the Hegelian philosophy in an uncompromising manner. They analyzed it, they confuted it, they ridiculed it, and held it up to scorn and contempt. The issueof the conflict, I have not the means of knowing. 278 a Ne a am raraiaaesae. : yeep par tax ta Oar Shree erpesnicaoerie ties 8 ASIN SC UG ie NE ae See epee Se Saas Sar ses ees INSTINCTIVE PHILOSOPHY. CEA aie XLT. INSTINCTIVE PHILOSOPHY. instinctive Philosophy:—Jacobi’s Philosophy of Faith or Instinct.—His follow- ers: Koeppen, von JVeiller, Salat.—Ability and Honesty of the German Philosophers.—Schulze, the only Sceptic among them. We have now taken a brief view of most of those systems of German philosophy, which profess to give us a true and scientific knowledge of supersensible things ; of which [Kant tells us, we can have no scien- tific knowledge. And we find, that all these systems end either in absolute Idealism, or in what may be called Panthersm ; that is, they either make all nou- mena and all supersensible things, together with their phenomena, to be nothing but conceptions and ideas ex- isting in our own minds, and existing nowhere else ; or they reduce all things to one primal substance, the All-One, or God, which develops itself according to certain laws inherent in its very nature, and thereby presents to us all the variety, beauty, and harmony of this great universe. And the latest and most renowned of these philosophers makes this primal All-One to be himself nothing but an idea or conception of the human mind. Opposed to all these schools, and also to the Kantian school, was the celebrated Fred. Henry Jacobi, and a very respectable number of philosophers and divines who coincided with him in his general views. Of this school we now proceed to give some account. Fred. Henry Jacobi, privy counsellor to the king of Bavaria, and president of the royal academy of science at Munich, was distinguished as a fine writer, a poet, and a philosopher. He died at Munich in 1819, aged 76. Disgusted with the speculations of the philoso- phers around him, he assailed them all in their oe adand neha haies eet saat cot heh i yee ‘ 4 . en eee ener on a reo oe ne Sere tetera baie hae a oi oe “Dae rate 4 beat Pas : ne Yt . yg - Ao ‘ cbt by Ot Bad be Ny See abs re ne : ; MS hake ant M P - ee Cr Ay oN he We Rohe be See ee \ \ aig Ba td NS ’ ie ty Mi , ee ee * . INSTINCTIVE PHILOSOPHY. yet with candour and discrimination. He was also more intent on overthrowing false systems, than on pro- pagating a better one of his own devising, To Kant he awarded great merit, for successfully prostrating the delusive speculations of the former dogmatists, and for establishing on a firm basis a pure system of moral or practical philosophy. But he thought that Kant laid too much stress on the necessity of demonstration in order to true knowledge; for, by this error, he subvert- ed all speculative knowledge of supersensible things, and then was unable to derive any satisfactory know- ledge of them from practical reason. But the other schools, in his view, were still more erroneous. Their entire schemes were fundamentally wrong, and when carried out, would necessarily lead to fatalism and to pantheism. He supposed that there is a source of true rational knowledge, which these philosophers overlook. They reject all speculative knowledge, which cannot be traced either to immediate rational intuitions, or to logical de- ductions from self-evident truths; thus making the intuitions of reason and the legitimate deductions from such intuitions the only sources of scientific or philosophical knowledge. But Jacobi supposed, that we have true knowledge by faith in the operations of our own faculties. This faith he considers as a ra- tional znstinct, a knowing from immediate mental feel- ing, a direct perception of the true and supersensible, without any intervening proof; and of course, it is en- tirely different from what is ordinarily called faith, or a belief founded on testimony. And the knowledge based on this faith, is essentially different from specula- tive or scientific knowledge; which is generally only second-hand knowledge, or knowledge derived from itervening evidence or proof. According to Jacobi, there are two grand sources or inlets of knowledge to the human mind: first, external sense, by which we acquire a knowledge of the external world, or of mate- rial objects ; and secondly, an internal sense, the organ a truth, (or, as he afterwards named it, Reason, the 0INSTINCTIVE PHILOSOPHY. power of immediate knowledge,) by which we acquire a knowledge of God, of what is foreseen, of free agency, of immortality, of virtue, in a word, of supersensible things. By this twofold revelation to him, (and Jacobi believed in no other divine revelation,) man is roused to self-consciousness, with a feeling of his elevation above blind nature, or of his free agency. He recognises God, and his own free agency, immediately, by means of Reason. Moral doctrines also are capable of confirm- ation only by feeling. Reason, as being the faculty of ideas, which reveal themselves in our inmost feelings, gives to philosophy its subject-matter ; and the Under- standing, as being the faculty of conceptions, gives to that subject-matter its form. At least, so Jacobi ex- presses himself in his latest writings. Previously he did not explain himself with sufficient clearness, res- pecting that faith or internal revelation which he regard- ed as the foundation of philosophy; but left the point in considerable obscurity. And from this source, and from his not making a clear distinction between Reason and Understanding, and finally, from the fact that his theistic doctrine of faith and internal feeling was de- veloped in a loose and unsystematic manner, chiefly in opposition to others, various misapprehensions and ob- jections originated. Still his merits, at least indirectly, in regard to the progress of philosophy among the Germans, are undeniable-—(Tennem. Grundritz, p. 531, &c.) Jacobi’s doctrine was well received, especially by those who place a higher value on faith and feeling than on the other manifestations of the mind. On the contrary, it was regarded as a subordinate mode of philosophizing, by those who give rational thinking a higher rank than feeling. But his want of clearness in discriminating between Reason and Understanding, seems to have led the cultivators of his philosophy to separate into two parties. For, some considered ideas as a divine revelation to the mind, through the medium. of Reason; and they supposed the conceptions of the Understanding to have a negative relation to ideas, or 281ee Sd ceaialnhais tet beeriet ee ak bk ep = a a i ee es Me bl hi Mie tad Cah a UM Siirhs foo “ol enter ol De a LEE co he a ree Anat aah ee a . —e My te tte tar ee . re! ll reel tal cont tee ee rl D oes ttgemre peste moneapeteew erp ynpumemtn ate yee INSTINCTIVE PHILOSOPHY. that ¢deas can never be reached by conceptions ; that ¢deas are incomprehensible and inexplicable, they mani- fest themselves in feeling ; and, that faith precedes all scientific knowledge. But others allowed a wider sphere for conceptions. They considered philosophy as con- sisting in the union of Reason and Understanding, de- riving its substance (Wessen) from the former, and its form from the latter: and to this opinion, Jacobi, in his latter years, was most inclined. In tho first party, Frederic Koeppen stands conspicuous; in the latter, James Salat. (Tennem. p. 533, &c.) f’rederic Koeppen, a friend and pupil of Jacobi, was born at Lubec in 1775, was first a preacher at Bremen, and then a professor of philosophy at Landshut, whence he removed to Munich in 1826, and afterwardsto Er- Jangen, where he probably still lives. Once cordially attached to his paternal friend and guide, he has since become dissatisfied with Jacobi’s philosophy, and now devotes himself to the study of the ancients, especially Plato. Asa follower of Jacobi, he made free agency his starting point; as Jacobi himself did. “Free agency is a self- determining, self-originating, and perfectly in- dependent activity. It is therefore an orginal cause, the ground of all existence ; it is Being properly so call- ed. But it is absolutely incomprehensible; even its possibility cannot be clearly perceived; nor its actual existence be demonstrated. It is an immediate matter of fact, in our knowing and acting. Necessity is an order of things established by free agency. The Divine activity is a perfect, absolute free agency. But the essence of humanity is, a combination of the internal and the external man; and of course, man’s free agency is limited. And hence philosophy is dualistic, reposing on both sense and reason. And from this dualism, arise the insurmountable contradictions of human science. And, we may add, ( Says Tennemann, ) another legitimate consequence, namely, that on this ground philosophy itself is impossible; and the problem, to establish it as a strict and proper science, falls of itself. Still, as a admits, the public ed ation of Koeppen’s views,$a Lee Sane Sa to Se We tpt Mee inetd Ser Sita ate Set INSTINCTIVE PHILOSOPHY. 85 as well as of Jacobi’s, had a salutary influence on the philosophy of the day, inasmuch as they opposed the philosophy and the blind dogmatism of the schools, and exhibited in a lively manner many thoughts, either ap- propriately their own, or borrowed from Plato. To this branch of Jacobi’s school, belonged Cajetan von Weiller, a learned clergyman of the Romish church, secretary of the Academy of Science at Munich, and a distinguished writer, who died in 1826, aged 64. But he did not, like Jacobi, make faith or feeling the sole basis of philosophy ; for he laboured to discover for it some other and more intelligible grounds. He was likewise a believer in supernatural revelation: which Jacobi was not. ‘To the same school belongs, Christian Weiss, born in 1774, first a professor of philosophy at Leipsic, and since, a school and government counsellor at Merseburg, a writer of considerable eminence. (Avrug, and Tennem.) Ja. Salat, a liberal Roman Catholic priest, born in 1766, professor at Munich, and afterwards at Landshut, where he still resides, a voluminous but inelegant writer, is a strenuous opposer of Romish bigotry, as well as of Schelling’s and Hegel’s philosophy. He takes a middle course between Kant and Jacobi, and founds philosophy on a revelation through the medium of Reason. That objective thing, which is to us the ground of philosophy, has two aspects; first, as being the subject-matter of philosophy ; and secondly, as being the foundation in us, or the innate faculty for philosophizing. This native faculty, when suitably brought into action, develops itself in an announcement of the Divine, anterior to any subjec- tiveaction of the mind. In consequence of this announce- ment, the mind recognises the Divine, and eagerly seizes upon it. This announcement is no logical act of the mind, but is a realization of the Divine in the mind's deepest recesses; whence it proceeds forth from the will. If this announcement is apprehended by the mind, it isnext to be comprehended, to be made intelli- gible, and to become something known; and this is what philosophy accomplishes by the aid of va~ Sc alia has Getter ot ja ees fi " , 7 a en eT ee eee ee eer wy aa has ala , . be , bs tae ah, * A "= Sire, DOF od baags oe wy Sy a : 5 hy Cth: j } eae) INSTINCTIVE PHILOSOPHY. standing. He considers Metaphysics as the whole of scientific philosophy ; and Logic, Anthropology, and the Criticism of the intellectual powers, as only prepar- atory studies. There are three branches of philosophy, — corresponding with the threefold relations of man; viz. moral philosophy, the philosophy of right, and the phi- losophy of religion. (Krug, and Tenn. p. 536.) We have now completed our survey of the various methods devised by Kant’s successors, for passing that impracticable gulf, which, as Kant supposed, must ever separate between noumena and phenomena in the ma- terial world, and between the objective and the subjec- tive in the spiritual world. Before we take our leave of these acute but adven- turous German philosophers, it seems pertinent to re- mark, that in general they appear to be, not only men of great learning and industry, but, what is more im- portant, sincere and honest inquirers after truth,—men who labour to discover a true and useful philosophy, a philosophy that will satisfy the wants of man as a ra- tional and immortal being. And hence, though whole schools of them have landed in Idealism, and Pantheism ; and though great numbers of them were rationalists or theists, disbelieving the divine inspiration of the Bible; yet not a single individual, since the publication of Kant’s Criticism, (so far as I know,) has professed either atheism or materialism, or advocated lax moral princi- ples, or treated religion with levity or contempt, or denied a future state of rewards and punishments, or, in a word, showed himself a disbeliever in the great prin- ciples of natural religion. And only a solitary indivi- dual among them has professed to be a sceptic ; and his scepticism was of a mild character, and was afterwards retracted or greatly modified. With some account of that individual, we shall close the present Chapter. Gottlob Ernst Schulze, (born in1761, Dr and Profes- sor of philosophy at Gottingen, and honorary member of the Philos, Acad. at Philadelphia in America, died at Gottingen in 1833,) published in 1792 an anony- ae work, in opposition to Reinhold’s theory, and toINSTINCTIVE PHILOSOPHY. 37 Kant’s Critic, entitled, AEnesidemus; or, on the found- ation of Prof. Reinhold’s Elemental Philosophy ; to- gether with a Defence of Scepticism, in regard to the pretensions of the Critic of Reason. This work pro- fessed to annihilate the illusions of imaginary know- ledge, and to carry farther than Kant had done, the self- knowledge of Reason, by detecting the hereditary faults of all philosophy. The result of the investigation was, that the origin of human knowledge is unknowable ; and therefore, there can be no philosophy which shall explain it; that all that the schools tell us respecting the origin of knowledge, is mere play upon words with- out meaning; and that our curiosity should be limited to inquiries respecting the constituent parts of know- ledge, the different kinds of it, and the laws by which conviction accompanies its several species. And this he called Scepticism, and likewise Antidogmatism, found- ed on the essential and necessary condition of the mind of man. This scepticism, moreover, recognised the so called facts of consciousness; and it maintained, that the human mind, from its very constitution, is obliged to recognise these facts of consciousness as real, and to govern itself by them in practice. After further in- quiry, Schulze narrowed down his scepticism still more ; for, while he still denied the possibility of infallible criteria of truth, i.e. of the agreement of our knowledge with the essential nature of things, he did not divest the mind of ability to discover how far our knowledge of particular objects is in harmony with the original con- stitution of the human mind, and to discriminate be- tween such knowledge, and that which originates from our peculiar temperament or character as individuals. At length, being fully convinced of the untenableness of scepticism, he attempted an investigation of the ori- gin, the truth, the perfectibility, and the limits of hu- man knowledge, according to the approved laws of na- tural science. His later views of philosophy approach near to the doctrines of Jacobi. He agrees with those who, taking Plato for their pattern, regard Reason (dis- tinct from the comparing faculty, the adeniange) G } Se Weloas $e A tag OE teas} Pix edie epee tae a2 ree siiat ba pl iesineschieerecs Ueda tiled Uh bathe as rill Leeneerer tetat iam aaiteaaiee a ee ihaliaehais eetatinaie 4 PAS E r Ser ated hd See y psy “> 5 (his ee D ay SE Sirhan ta bettas belt HI HO ey ee ee eh by be te ye % e ree ae n rf e : Da a ie eee eat ee ” si arsine edeereeadh hcenesetoiten ott an Labia nameteninaT ania eames aneeeaeinene neater nae te Ve See See Se . oe NG Ese Ses N a 38 FRENCH PHILOSOPHY. as a source of knowledge of supersensible things, and who endeavour by means of.it to solve the proper pro- blems of philosophy. With his eye on those feelings, which distinguish men from brutes, he divides philoso- phy into four grand departments ; viz. theoretical philo- sophy or metaphysics, explaining religious feeling ; practical philosophy, explaining moral feeling ; logic in the sense of the ancients, explaining intellectual feeling ; and esthetics, explaining the feeling of the beautiful. (Krug, and Tennem. p. 537, &c.) CHAPTER XIII. FRENCH PHILOSOPHY. The New School in France : its Origin, and Present State; its Advocates; its Doctrines. As a conclusion to these sketches, we shall notice the part which France has taken in the modern develop- ments of philosophy. From near the times of Mr Locke till quite recently, empiricism, and that of the grossest kind, has reigned undisturbed in France. About the middle of the last century, the Abbe Condillae expounded the philosophy of Locke, omitting reflection as a distinct source of know- ledge. Reflection, he said, can add nothing to the mat- ter on which it reflects. It can only recognise, com- pare, generalize, and give form to the ideas which sen- sation presents. Of course, all our ideas, in his view, are ideas of sensation, or in other words, are sensations. This became-the reigning doctrine in France. The in- fidels, Voltaire, the Encyclopeedists, &c. all embraced it : and many of them deduced from it the materiality of the soul, atheism, fatalism, and sensuality, as man’s chief good. A few ecclesiastics and others feebly resisted the tendencies of this philosophy ; but without exposing or 286Coa Sane ses tas ae ads FRENCH PHILOSOPHY, $9 clearly discerning the unsound basis on which it rests. During the first years of the revolution, (1789-95,) all eyes were directed to the portentous occurrences of the day, and the only branch of philosophy much regarded, was political philosophy ; and in that, man was consi- dered merely as a reasoning animal, whose interests are all confined to the present life. Under the Directorial government, (1795-99,) the Institute and the Normal Schools called some attention to education, and required the study of philosophy on the principles of Condillac, and the materialists. Under the Consular government, (1799-1804,) philosophy was more zealously pursued, but on the same general principles. Cabanis and Des- tutt de Tracy were the most distinguished writers on philosophy. Under the Imperial government, (1804- 14,) a reformation in philosophy commenced, and it had “De made some progress before the restoration of the Bour- bons. From that time onwards it has been steadily ad- vancing, and it now has the weight of talent and influ- ence on its side. The philosophers of the new school _assume the name of £iclectics ; and the name appears appropriate. We shall first notice the principal persons concerned in this reformation of philosophy, and then attempt some description of their principles. Peter Laromiguiere, born in 1757, first taught at Toulouse, and afterwards at Paris, where he was a member of the National Institute and a distinguished writer, till his death in 1837. He deviated considera- bly from Condillac; for he maintained that the soul is active, and not merely passive, in the acquisition of knowledge. Sensation indeed furnishes the materials for all our knowledge: but the mind gives form and shape to those materials. The activity of the mind is therefore a source of knowledge, as well as sensation. The two are co-ordinate. Laromiguiere being a charm- ing writer, and a man of great acuteness, his doctrines spread far, and were not without considerable influ- ence. Maine de Biran, who died at Paris in 1824, aged 58, obtained a prize from the Berlin Academy of eeete aoe Cae ete hy Se Wah at 6 J . ee eat ntehesee Le SP bl id dined Se hd aber eeath er ten oh heehee che ak ri a igh gr Sboh ikeneme st tam SES Wr AT Wire CM neta he es Wa hte. AN , ’ tikes olla ait a is Species aes] intniteeedeediateataretamnee ae niece Ome ee en ts re | -* et . bth , ath Ss oh ty het dete t ert ghetto manger aera ewet teeny aici at teed t pc CT te g : hi 4 Fs SO FRENCH PHILOSOPHY. in 1809, for the best essay on this question, Is there any immediate, internal, [intellectual] ¢ntwition; and how does it differ from sensible perception ? Cousin considered his works so valuable, that he undertook to edit them himself so late as 1834. De Biran was so opposed to the doctrines of the materialists, that he leaned towards universal idealism ; whence Cousin com- pares him with the German Fichte. He is said to have adopted Leibnitz’s doctrine of Monads, with some al- terations. He believed that all substances, or all real existences, are active powers or forces of some sort ; that minds or souls have intelligence, volition, &c. while material substances have only motive foree. He there- fore clearly distinguished the soul from the body ; and in examining the faculties and powers of the former, he commenced with consciousness. John Peter Fred. Ancillon was born in 1766 at Berlin, where his father was minister of the French Prot. Church. Ee was himself preacher to the same church, then pro- fessor of philosophy in the military academy at Berlin, member of the Acad. of Sciences, counsellor of state for foreign affairs, &c. ; and died in 1837. Ancillon wrote altogether in French; and he published vari- ous works on philosophical subjects, political, moral, &c.; in which he appeared pretty clearly to belong to the school of Jacobi. His works were read in France. Peter Paul Royer- Collard, born in 1763, was first an advocate in the Parliament of Paris, and then active but moderate in the revolution ; afterwards, being made Dean of the Faculty of Letters in the Normal School at Paris, he lectured on philosophy with great applause _. \ from 1811 to 1814, when he returned to political life, ~~—jand becamehead of the party called Doctrinaires, which / took middlé ground between the royalists and the ultra- ‘ republicans. In his lectures he brought forward Reid’s doctrine of Common Sense, as an independent source of true knowledge, and urged it strenuously and success- fully, in opposition to the doctrine of Condillac. This source of the knowledge of noumena and supersensible ae he called natural induction ; and he described itFRENCH PHILOSOPHY. Oo] as being a spontaneous and necessary action of the mind. His eloquence, and his acute and powerful reasoning, transfused this doctrine into nearly all his pupils ; and thus laid the foundation for the new French school in philosophy. Yet only one of his lectures has been pub- lished entire, although many extracts from them have been given to the public, especially in Jouffroy’s French edition of Reid’s Works, Paris 1828. Victor Cousin, born in 1792, and educated under Royer-Collard, succeeded him in the Normal School in 1815, and carried forward the reformation in philoso- phy begun by his predecessor. In 1820 he was dis-— placed for his too liberal political opinions, and retired to Germany ; but he returned im 1828, and resumed his lectures. His lectures for that year contain an In- troduction to the history of philosophy. These have been elegantly translated by H. G. Limberg, and were, published at Boston in 1832. They contain the best’ exposition I have seen of his philosophical opinions. In 1829, he published a course of lectures in two volumes, on the philosophy of the 18th century. The first vo- lume contains general views of philosophy and its his- tory. The second volume contains an elaborate criti- cism on Mr Locke’s Essay, which has been well trans- lated by the Rev. C. 8S. Henry, D. D. of New York. On the accession of Louis Philippe in 1830, Cousin was admitted into the French Academy ; and the next year, he was sent by the king to examine the literary institu- tions of Germany, especially of Berlin, and make report. On his return in 1832, he was made a peer of France ; and in 1840, minister of public instruction. He may_. be considered the corypheus of the eclectic or new school philosophers of France. But before we examine his philosophical doctrines, we will notice some others who have co-operated in the reformation of French phi- losophy. The Baron de Massias, for some time French consul- general at Dantzic, and then charge Waffaires at Berlin, published various philosophical works, between 182] and 1835; in which, it is said, he seems to come near 289eter) - ™ et ae eee Ter awake Bet Sak el aaa at eo ae Od teat ee ete ee er ies . Seen ae , 4 Seay Li Jak os w ehh Pie ‘ Phi * . a ‘4 : f f ; ter! a te AS Sag 7% Ct Seo : ‘ wae ME AS SS ERAA bah Sop art iad | aru oC forte a ap wear , ya ht ewe . . a TEM tot IP tn wai ty Worth a x rat Y Tot : Se Arh NS Net iast Ah ~ rt Ka : Rr erie hd ils fi rrgeaey ee rida debe eddaarvadnanecrnmead cheecamames on eter niece er a oe Nera tat it hy ANTE, t ‘ ; i , me er ic Mee : ye 5 \* RCH es : ae eee 92 FRENCH PHILOSOPHY. to Kantian principles; but he professes to differ from Kant, as well as from Royer-Collard and Reid. Krug could not exactly define his position; but tells us, he was ranked among the new eclectics of France. The Baron Degerando, born in 1772, and made a peer of France in 1837, the author of the Comparative Hist. of Philosophy, was a follower of Condillac in 1802 ; but when he published the 2d edit. of his History, in 1622-3, he accorded with Royer-Collard and Cousin, or was an eclectic. Berard, who died in 1828 at the age of 35, published a work in 1823, in which he maintained the immate- riality of the soul, and assailed the doctrines of the materialists openly and vigorously. And in the same year, Virey published a treatise on Vital Power, in which he takes the same ground. Lheodore Jouffroy, born in 1796, and now Professor of philosophy in the Faculty of Literature at Paris, is an active member of the eclectic school. In 1828, he published Reid’s Works in French, with abstracts from Reyer-Collard’s lectures; and likewise Dugald Stewart’s Outlines of Moral Philosophy. Jouffroy de- votes himself especially to Moral Philosophy ; and he comes frequently before the public in works which are said to be creditable both to his head and his heart. Philip Damiron, educated under Cousin, and now Pro- fessor of philosophy in the college of Louis le Grand at Paris, is the author of a History of Philosophy in France in the 19th century, 2 vols. first published in 1828, and again in 1830. From this work, Krug and Dr Henry ap- pear to have derived most of their information respecting the recent history of French philosophy ; and on them I am chiefly dependent. In 1831, Damiron commenced publishing a Course of Philosophy ; of which four yo- lumes had appeared in 1834, embracing Psychology and Morals. In his history, Damiron gives account of twenty-seven French philosophers of the 19th century ; whom he divides into three classes, viz. I. Sensualists; e.g. Azais, Cabanis, Destutt deTracy, Gall, Laromiguiere, Volney, &c. a 290$2 te se sete FRENCH PHILOSOPHY. Il. Theologists ; e. g. Vallanche, de Bonald, de Mais- tre, de la Mennais, &c. Til. Eiclectics ; e.g. Ancillon, Berard, Bonstettin, Cousin, Damiron, Degerando, Droz, Jouffroy, Keretray, Massias, Maine de Biran, Royer-Collard, Virey, &c. The French philosophers of the new school appear to be ingenuous, liberal-minded, honest men; men who have no selfish or sinister views, no vain ambition of applause, no pride of learning, in short, no other aim than to discover and to recommend the useful and the true, ina branch of knowledge long degraded and abus- ed in their country by superficial and reckless men. They are harmonious in their efforts to raise philosophy in France to the rank of an honourable and useful science, by the careful study of foreign writers. Differ-~ ing among themselves on various points, they are yet tolerant to each other, and assume the common name of Eclectics. Indeed they appear not yet to have matured~ their thoughts. They all read the Scotch philosophers, Reid and Stewart, and some of them also Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Jacobi, &c.; and from all these, as well as from Plato, Aristotle, Des Cartes, Leibnitz, &c. they take what seems to them plausible, and too often with~ eut due regard to the congruity and incongruity of that syncretism which they call eclecticism. At least this appears to me to be true of Cousin, the present leader of the school. Dr Henry has indeed exhibited a pretty coherent system, as being held and taught by Cousin. But he does not refer us to the works of the author for proofs; and as, with the three volumes of Cousin’s lec- tures before me, I cannot verify all his statements, and yet find in Cousin some dogmas and positions which are not distinctly mentioned by Dr Henry, instead of abridging the Professor's statement, IT will subjoin what I have been able to glean directly from Cousin. It should be recollected, that the works I consult are not precise and logical disquisitions, but loose popular lec- tures, and addressed also to a French audience, whose fancy must be pleased to secure their attention. Hence not only is the language often popular rather than scien- 29194 FRENCH PHILOSOPHY, petal hats teint nate ath akg oy * - tific, but in too many instances the reasoning also. Most of my references are to the Introduction to a History of Philos. &c. translated by Limberg, Boston, 1832. According to Cousin, philosophy is the science which strives to comprehend things, and to account for what “—~——.y- takes place. It is the result_of reflection, of the study of ideas and of thought ; and its aim is, 0 advance all fii ~~ the great interests of man. It is one of man’s most real ‘ag | wants, (p. 19-25, 51, 52, 367, &c.) Philosophy com- | ~——-mences with reflection, with a critical examination of ~— the human mind, or with what is called psychology, | (p. 368, &c.380, 390, &c.) From psychology it proceeds My to logic, metaphysics, ontology, natural theology, cos- | | mology, morality, &c. And its method or mode of pro- | ceeding is, to begin with observation and induction, or | careful researches a posteriori; and then to introduce analysis and deduction, or reasoning @ priori, (p. 416, &e. 95-103.) | | All the facts of psychology are found on the re- | cerds of consciousness ; and to these records we must | | go for a knowledge of them. It is by reflection, Bi that we inspect that record, and learn ‘those facts, | (p. 147, &c. 152, 159, 161, &c. 193.) Cousin recog- nises three faculties of the mind; viz. sensibility, or susceptibility of impressions from objects without ; vo- ition or the will, the source of voluntary action; and reason or intellect, the knowing, Judging, reasoning Ni faculty. On the first, (sensibility,) he says but little ii in this volume, and he seems to hold the common views ie | of philosophers. Respecting the will or voluntary power, | | he is singular in maintaining that this faculty is the sole foundation of personality. The other faculties are not of a personal nature; they are common properties of our race; and they would operate in the same man- ner, and with the same results, in all men, if they were not influenced in individuals by the personal faculty or the will, (p. 125, &c. 128, 169, 175, &c.) Reason, or intelligence, is nothing personal to us as individuals. There are not as many veasons as there are 2992 + eoterea LiTeC ois w - oy ei iad lle RE bieeel be bd alere k tenae! Wenge eer sr: prt otetene terme merge ot wn a On oe ee . +", RP eT Me ene OP wep be)FRENCH PHILOSOPHY. 95 reasoning beings; but there is one eternal reason, which is a sort of common property of all intelligent beings, and which they all use at pleasure, according to their ability. The infinite God, who is intelligence it- self, enjoys and uses it without any limitation ; but finite beings can make only a limited use of it, (p. 125-129, H67, 1:71,) Reason as a faculty of the human mind, operates in two ways; viz. spontaneously, or without the co-oper- ation of the will; and voluntarily, or under the guid- ance of the will, as when we intentionally reflect, think, judge, &c. From its first mode of operation we de- rive all our primary knowledge, and all those general truths which seem to be innate or connate. This ope- ration of reason is the Common Sense of Dr Reid ; and by Cousin it is denominated the instinctive perception ot truth, the instinct of reason, original perception, and also faith and inspiration. (P. 162-175, 193, 417; comp. his Hist. of Philos. II. 388-392.) Reason, in both her modes of operation, is governed by three fundamental laws or first principles; which he calls the elements of reason, and which occupy the same place in his system with the categories in the Kantian system : they give form, consistency, and unity to all our knowledge. Moreover, as reason is not sub- jective or personal to us, but is universal, or the common property of all intelligent beings, and is the same in man as in God; hence these laws or elements of reason are not merely the laws of owr mode of thinking, (as Kant erroneously maintained,) but they are the laws of all rational thinking, and the mode of God’s viewing things ; and of course they accord with the divine con- stitution of the universe, or with the real nature of things ; that is, they have objective validity. They are the basis, not only of human logic, but of true meta- physics, and of a solid system of ontology. According to these fundamental laws of reason, whatever exists above us, around us, or within us, falls under one or the other of these two categories; viz. (1.) the finite, the multiple, the particular, the limited, the dependent,Seen netet eae sect egy bens he ye Y te SM ee ee id a Sd le ka ar SEN Hoe ae ta we We 5 a - — 96 FRENCH PHILOSOPHY. phenomenal, &c.; or (2.) the infinite, the one, the uni- versal, the unlimited, the absolute, the substance, &c. These are the two first categories or fundamental laws of reason. The third is the result of an analysis of the two preceding. It is, that whatever exists under either of these categories, stands in immediate relation with its corresponding thing in the other category; so that neither can be conceived as existing, or as being possible without the other. Moreover, all the things existing under the first category, (the finite, the multiple, &c.) stand related to the corresponding things under the second category, as effects stand related to their causes ; that is, the infinite is the cause of the finite, the one of the multiple, the universal of the particular, the un- limited of the limited, the absolute of the dependent, the substantial of the phenomenal, &c. And finally, by summing up separately all that exists under each ‘of the two first categories, we have, as the sum total of the first, the world or nature; and as the sum total of the second, God the author of nature; and then this third category unites the two sums in a harmonious whole, which is the universe, (pp- 108-131, 158- 160, 418.) Cousin seems aware, that these views ap- proximate so near to those of Schelling, that they may expose him to the charge of pantheism ; a charge which he did not well know how to answer, (pp. 1382, 141- 143, 147, 158, 233, 420.) Yet he did not intend to identify God with nature, or to teach that there is no God distinct from the world, (pp. 16, 132,143.) Crea- tion he held to be a development of God’s power, an act of his wll ; and in some sense a necessary act, (pp. 186, &c. 142, 158.) It will also follow from these laws of reason, that God is as comprehensible by us, as any other object: and Cousin admits the inference, (pp. 132, 133.) Indeed he is so fara Hegelian, as to believe that ideas are real existences, and not the mere images or representatives of something else, (p. 21, &c. 193 ~125, 127, 129.) And he even tells us, that ideas | constitute the nature of God, (pp. 133, 134, 158, 165, “T66.) Cousin holds firmly to the providence and moral 294GERMAN PHILOSOPHY IN AMERICA. 97 government of God. He says: “ God’s perpetual agency, in respect to the world and to humanity, is providence.” ‘The great deeds recorded in history, are~~ the decrees of God’s moral government of the world,” (pp. 224, 225.) And he distinctly avows himself to be a Christian philosopher, (pp. 49, 57, 338, 339.) He says: “I believe that in Christianity all truths are contained ; but these eternal truths may and ought to be approached, disengaged, and illustrated by philoso- phy. Truth has but one foundation; but truth as- sumés two forms, namely, mystery ” [the form in which religion is presented to the mind in ordinances of wor- ship, and in representations intended to excite devo- tion] “ and scientific exposition : I revere the one, 1 am the organ and interpreter of the other.” CHAP TE Rs XV: GERMAN PHILOSOPHY IN AMERICA. Its Introduction.—Coleridgeism. Tuer original design of these sketches was merely to give a general idea of the principal systems of German philosophy. This object was pursued through the twelve first Chapters. Another Chapter was added, on the new eclectic philosophy in France. And now, it is deemed expedient to annex some account of those schemes of modified German philosophy which have excited most attention in our own country ; namely, the philosophy of Coleridge, as contained in his Aids to Reflection; the so called Transcendental Philosophy, contained in the Dial and other recent works published in Massachusetts; and the philosophic system of Dr Fred. A. Rauch, contained in his Psychology. fe: 5ST ea is ober naan . > “ ‘4 “ et on oo a penbaathed we eee Lie gememgmeparen | teens saree AE ‘ i> ee as mes . ~t bs +4 me Set Fhe bork nym te , hs Rea aT th eet OMT Ica aaa ‘ A es r we eee 5 ~ Cae ee ee ce ee POT ATs Ranar iar ee ee ene , : Ae atte pe" i545 ‘ \ " x tl ate . ‘ ee Py +S \ iad | bette M 98 GERMAN PHILOSOPHY IN AMERICA, Until within about twenty years, the empirical philosophy, as taught by Locke and the Scotch writers, and which was described in the first Chapter of these sketches, had dominion in all our colleges and schools, and was regarded everywhere as the only true philoso- phy. Berkeley’s idealism was indeed received by a few ; and if it did not originate, it doubtless helped to give currency to, that species of pantheism which is funda- mental in the theology of the Emmons school. Ber- keley made immediate divine agency the sole cause of all the phenomena of the material world; and Emmons extended the same immediate agency throughout the intellectual world. But neither of these very acute reasoners aimed to overthrow the empirical mode of philosophizing. The first only wished to stenethen the argument from experience for the being of a God, and the second to reconcile the doctrines of Calvinism with a sound philosophy. A little more than twenty years ago the German language, and with it, German literature and Science, began to be studied in this country ; and soon, here and there an individual was induced to look with some favour on German philosophy. But the perfect novelty of its principles, and its strange terminology, rendered it almost unintelligible. Under these circumstances, the writings of Samuel Taylor Coleridge, who had mastered and adopted some of the fundamental principles of Kant, found their way into the country, and were eagerly caught at and read by several of our younger theologians. His Biographia Literaria, his work entitled The F riend, and his Aids to Reflection, found as warm admirers in this country, as in England. In 1829, Pres. James Marsh, D.D. now a Professor in Burlington, Vt., published an American edition of the Aids to Reflection, with an elaborate Preliminary Essay vindicating and recom- mending the principles of the book. From that period Coleridgeism has spread very considerably in New Eng- land. The Biographia Literaria of Coleridge, and his Friend, which I read hastily soon after their publication,_ Ee ee a $s selec hgh rte oe FEE Sy Tem a ae BAL Uae Wr Cr Sagan Oe GERMAN PHILOSOPHY IN AMERICA. ' 99 are not now at hand, and I shall therefore confine my remarks to his Aids to Reflection. This work is not so much a treatise on philosophy, as a treatise on practical or experimental religion, and was intended especially for the nse of young men who are studying for the ministry. Dr Marsh well says: “ It might rather be denominated a philosophical statement and vindication of the distinctively spiritual and peculiar doctrines of the Christian system.” Coleridge was one of the most evangelical men of his times in the English Episcopal church: and he supposed he could explain and establish, in the most satisfactory manner, the reli- gious doctrines which he held in common with Abp. Leighton and other early Puritans, by means of those principles of the Kantian philosophy which he had 1m- bibed, and especially by means of what he calls the momentous distinction between Reason and Understand- ing. By means of this distinction, he thought he could establish more clearly and precisely the import of ecer- tain scriptural terms, such as carnal, fleshly; spiritual, the flesh, the spirit, &c.; and likewise “establish the distinct characters of Prudence, Morality, and Reli- gion ;” and finally, could shew the perfect harmony of ‘all the peculiar doctrines of the Christian faith” with reason or sound philosophy. (Aids, &c. pp. 62-64, ed. New York, 1840.) But Coleridge was a poet: and poets seldom write well.on metaphysical subjects. Besides, he has justly been pronounced a turgid and obscure writer: and al- though, in his Aids to Reflection, he aims at a more chastened and simple style than in his other prose wnit- ings, yet he has preposterously employed, in this purely didactic work, ArHorisms instead of logical definitions and fully developed arguments. Heassumes that his read- ers know too much, or that they can understand him from a mere hint, a passing remark, a brilliant fragment of thought, without any full and clear delineation of his new theological views; and, like a genuine poet, he leaps in medias res, and throws out his new and strange ideas, without preparing our minds to recezve ems oF mee gUM erat art senate baog of gE E IES» a See bead eae . _— . -_ ee aes ie ode Siial iithd tas ad orale acter sl heal sci taibe Zi ta el LP acre ee oi nena Sed Pe hee ae Der 54 pg 4° i aa J ee Pinter byte chaps i yo re Re en ete is SCM SS abe tte tet hata CN ey, ee ok sah eteeenn sania 100 GERMAN PHILOSOPHY IN AMERICA. even to understand them. Thus the all-important dis- tinction between Reason and Understanding, which is the basis of his whole system, but of which nine-tenths of the reading public have no clear idea, is everywhere held up to view as fundamental, and yet is nowhere described or defined. And his learned editor, catching too much of his spirit, says explicitly, (p. 46): “ What is the precise nature of the distinction between the un- derstanding and reason, it is not my province, nor have I undertaken, to shew. My object is merely to illus- trate its necessity.” The consequence is, most readers of the book are utterly unable to comprehend it; and therefore, they strongly suspect the author was groping in darkness, or that he did not see clearly those sha- dowy objects which he would not venture to describe. From the language and reasonings of Coleridge, as well as from his known partiality for German philosophy, it is presumable that he adopted substantially that dis- tinction between Reason and Understanding which was described in the sixth Chapter of these sketches. There, however, we had especially in view the distinc- tion between what is called theoretical or speculative Reason, and the Understanding considered as an intel- lectual faculty : but Coleridge is principally concerned with practical Reason, or Reason in its relation to the Will and to the moral actions of man ; in which relation Coleridge says, it is “the determinant of ultimate ends,” that is, it is the source of those pure ideas of right, of duty, of moral obligation, which should be the supreme law of action to a rational being. In distinc- tion from this faculty, the Understanding, considered as u principle of action, bears a striking resemblance to the Instinct of the more intelligent animals, the ant, the bee, the beaver, &c. It is the ability to select and ap- ply fit means to proximate ends. Its views are limited to the object in immediate contemplation ; and it is but another name for ingenuity, sagacity, practical Judgment in affairs, or the power of judging according to the maxims of experience. (See Aids, &c. p. 245 ae and p. 353.) Coleridge often calls it “the facultyGERMAN PHILOSOPHY IN AMERICA. 1G] of judging according to sense ;” that is, according to em- pirical wisdom. Now man, according to Coleridge, was endowed by his Creator with the faculties of Understanding and Reason, which he was to develop and employ in the fulfilment of his duties as a creature of God. His Un- derstanding was to supply in him the place of Instinct in the brutes; speculative Reason was to enable him to cul- tivate scientific knowledge; and practical Reason was to regulate and govern his moral conduct, or to enable him to yield rational obedience to the laws of his Crea- tor. But by the apostasy, in which all participate as soon as they become capable of moral action, the Will of man divorces itself from practical reason, and sub- mits to the control of the Understanding, and the natu- ral propensities. By so doing, fallen man turns away from those high and pure principles of right, of duty, of moral obligation, which should be his ultimate aims, and fixes his regards on proximate ends, or, in the lan- guage of an apostle, on “the lust of the flesh, the lust of the eyes, and the pride of life.” He practically, if not also theoretically, discards the idea of there being any thing higher or more excellent than personal enjoy- ment or individual happiness: and in determining what will make him happy, or what is his supreme good, he recurs to experience as the best and the proper criterion. Thus, by following his Understanding as his only guide, fallen man is selfish and earthly-minded, until, by the new birth, practical Reason is restored to her throne in the soul. But for the full understanding of this subject, the wide difference between nature and free- Will must not be overlooked: for, as Dr Marsh says, “The key to his system will be found in the distinctions which he makes and illustrates between nature and free-Will, and be- tween the Understanding and Reason.” (See Aids, &c. p. 17.)—Throughout the kingdom of nature, ac- cording to Coleridge, one universal law prevails, and has absolute control. It is that of the. necessary de- pendence of one thing on another, or the law of cause ae Aee _— a ae Sead an al aa st rele ea £9 rat acuet aeaatnn bey 9 HN, 7 i's Rem: te By peer te tM HL I WP Ae Bb os +44 ae aT, ces ity ‘ F Cid 13 bd a " a 5 " - i ok aealeeeantentiednennenten od teetee eee adie eee 102 GERMAN PHILOSOPHY IN AMERICA. effect. To this law not only all material bodies, but all vegetable and animal life, and all the sensitive and elective faculties both of brutes and of man’s ani- mal nature, are entirely subject. But the free- Will of a rational being, in his opinion, is not subject to this law. It acts spontaneously, and independently of any causation from without. It is not controlled by motives, as the proper causes of its elections: ‘“‘ Theman makes the motive, and not the motive the man,” (p. 106.) Now when the will renounces its allegiance to practical Reason, and subjects itself to the guidance of the Un- derstanding and the natural propensities, it renounces its high and spiritual character, and consents to become as it were a part of nature; and thus the whole man becomes carnal, earthly, selfish, and scarcely superior to the brutes, so far as the discharge of his duties and obligations as a creature of God is concerned. And this is the radical principle of sin or depravity in fallen man, or what the Scriptures denominate the flesh, the carnal mind, and the minding the things of the flesh. And consequently, the recovery of man from this sinful state, is making him spiritual or spiritually minded; it is exciting his debased and degraded Will to renounce its subjection to sense and to the Understanding, and be obedient to the commands of practical Reason, or to the law of right, of duty, of moral obligation. Now both Scripture and experience show, that when the Will has been long enslaved to sense, its energies are paralyzed, and divine aid or supernatural grace is ne- cessary to restore it to sound and healthy action. Besides, the guilt incurred by a course of criminal dis- obedience to the law of God, presents an additional ob- stacle to the restoration of the sinner to the favourable regards of his Creator. And hence the necessity of a divine Redeemer for fallen man, a Redeemer who can act both on and in the Will, and can stand up as a Me- diator between God and sinful man. (See Aids, &c. p. 297, &c.) Coleridge has moreover taken much pains to ascer- tain the precise import of the terms prudence, morality, 300en tats tart Gs hye te es 2 GERMAN PHILOSOPHY IN AMERICA. 103 and spiritual religion. Prudence, he says, has for its chief organs the senses and the understanding. Itssole aim is the advancement of our personal interest or well- being; and it is especially careful to guard agains, every thing that may do us harm, frustrate our planst or mar our happiness. Morality has for its chief organ the heart, or the natural affections and sympathies of our nature; and it seeks the happiness of others, be- cause we find pleasure in doing so. Spirtiual religion has for its organs free-Will and practical Reason; and sts sole aim is to make the whole conduct of the man to harmonize with the divine law. From these definitions it is manifest that a man may have and may exhibit much prudence and much morality, and yet be entirely destitute of spiritual religion. Such, according to Coleridge, are some of the radical principles of mental philosophy ; and they are of very high importance to the nght understanding and the vindication of the peculiar doctrines and precepts of Christianity. They give us clear and just conceptions of the apostasy of man, of both original aud actual sin, of that carnal mind which is enmity against God, be- cause it is not subject to the law of God, neither in- deed can be; and hence also, of that redemption which is by Jesus Christ, of regeneration by divine grace, and of that holiness without which no man shall see the Lord. Not that this philosophy, or any other, is com- petent to teach us originally all the peculiar doctrines of Christianity, or to demonstrate their truth, without the aid of revelation. But when these momentous truths are revealed to us, this philosophy enables us to somprehend them, and to see that they are reasonable, and are worthy of all acceptation as coming from God. wed« . Pe Roatan hele teh ake we’ - . att Ce ate bine Se ol ae Oe aa a ia Palate . i ’ o yur ; A ‘ ie laid ahneinenienete steens bali tcamelentaatadiir emai deter nie aeadoaoatemaiontoneiat dae ath em nn { Sao : ry ve ‘et NN. WN e nen oe —— 104 AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. CHAPTER XY. AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. Propriety of the Name.—Its Origin.—Its Radical Principles. Tut species of German Philosophy which has =Prng up among the Unitarian clergy of Massachusetts, an which is advocated especially in a recent Periodical called the Dial, is known by the appellation TRANSCcEN- DENTALIsM. The propriety, however, of the appellation, may be questioned. ant, who, so far as I know, first brought the term Transcendental into philosophy, would certainly not apply it to this or to any similar system. He would denominate it TRANSCENDENT, not Transcen- dental. The difference, according to his views, is im- mense. Both terms indeed denote the surpassing or transcending of certain limits; but the limits surpassed are entirely different. That is called Transcendental, which surpasses the limits of sensible or empirical knowledge, and expatiates in the region of pure thought or absolute science. It is therefore truly scientific ; and it serves to explain empirical truths, so far as they are explicable. On the other hand, that is called Transcendent, which not only goes beyond empiricism, but surpasses the boundaries of human knowledge. It expatiates in the shadowy region of imaginary truth. {t is, therefore, falsely called science: it is the opposite of true philosophy. A balloon sent up by a besieging army to overlook the ramparts of a fortification, if moored by cables, whereby its elevation, its movements, and its safe return into camp are secured, is a transcen- dental thing ; but if cut loose from its moorings and left to the mercy of the winds, it is transcendent ; it has no connection with any thing stable, no regulator; it 302. ed ~~ ~ < r s . ie Sg te Sar rer ear tha ei ds Be agp aes AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. rises or descends, moves this way or that way, at hap- hazard, and it will land, no one knows where or when. Now, according to the critical philosophy, all specula- tions in physical science that attempt to go beyond phenomena, and all speculations on supersensible things which attempt to explain their essential nature, are transcendent ; that is, they overleap the boundaries of human knowledge. In violation of these canons, Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel plunged headlong into such spe- culations, and yet called them Transcendental; and the new German philosophers of Massachusetts follow their example. Waving, however, this misnomer—as every real Kant- ian must regard it, we will call this philosophy Tran- scendental, since its advocates choose to call it so, and seeing the name has become current in our country. And we will first inquire into its origin among us, and then proceed to notice its prominent characteristics. Origin of Transcendentalism among us. According to their own representations, the believers iu this philosophy are Unitarian clergymen, who had for some time been dissatisfied with the Unitarian sys- tem of theology. They tell us, they found it to be a meagre, uninteresting system, which did not meet the religious wants of the community. While labouring to improve their system of theology, or to find a better, they cast their eyes on foreign countries. There they discovered a different philosophy prevailing ; a philoso- phy which gives an entirely new version to Christian- ity, invests it with a more spiritual character, with more power to move the soul, to call forth warm emotions, and to produce communion with God. This philosophy they have now embraced. Such, they inform us, was the origin of Transcendentalism among them. But 1t may be more satisfactory to give their own statements on this head. The Rev. G. Ripley, or whoever composed the long anonymous letter to Prof. Norton, on his Discourse be- fore the Alumni of the Cambridge Theological ae oaee gt a” oh 106 AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. 1839, says, (pp. 11, 12,): ‘In our happy state of society, as there is no broad line of distinction between the clergy and the rest of the community, they [the Alumni] had shared in the influences, which, within the last few years, have acted so strongly on the public mind: with intelligent and reflecting men of every pursuit and per- suasion, many of them had been led to feel the necessity of a more thorough reform in theology ; they were not satishied that the denial of the Trinity and its kindred doctrines gave them possession of all spiritual truth: they wished to press forward in the course which they had begun, to ascend to higher views, to gain a deeper insight into Christianity, to imbibe more fully its divine spirit, and to apply the truths of revelation to the wants of society and the progress of man. Their experience as pastors had brought them into contact with a great variety of minds; some of which were dissatisfied with the traditions they had been taught; the religion of the day seemed too cold, too lifeless, too mechanical formany of their flock ; they were called to settle difficulties in theology of which they had not been advised in the school; objections were presented by men of discern- ment and acuteness, which could not be set aside by the learning of books; it was discovered that many had become unable to rest their religious faith on the foundation of a material philosophy, [-viz. the empirical philosophy of Locke;] and that a new direction must be given to their ideas, or they would be lost to Chris- tianity, and possibly to virtue. The wants of such minds could not be concealed,” &¢........... aces” Im the course of the inquiries which they had entered into, for their own satisfaction, and the good of their people, they had become convinced of the superiority of the testimony of the sow! to the evidence of the external senses ; the essential character of Christianity, as a principle of spiritual faith, of reliance on the Universal F ather,” &c. The Rev. O. A. Browngon, in his Charles Elwood, (Boston, 1840, p. 261,) says: “It cannot have escaped general observation, that religion forsome time has fail- ed to exert that influence over the mind and the heart 304 a eoMoe Sn Ree ME Tie ee Os aE ty Bee sey ene EE a eT, Pee eee: — a pS Si Sut Set rig SSA Se Ts HT MSN OO Oi es Ss eer Ra te GaN GR se fess Se tale Sete AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. 107 that it should. There is not much open scepticism, not much avowed infidelity, but there is a vast amount of concealed doubt and untold difficulty. Few, very few among us but ask for more certain evidence of the Chris- tian faith than they possess. Many, many are the con- fessions to this effect, which I have received from men and women whose religious character stands fair in the eyes of the church. I have been told by men of un- questionable piety, that the only means they have to maintain their belief even in God, is never to suffer themselves to inquire into the grounds of that belief. The moment they ask for proofs, they say, they begin to doubt. Our churches are but partially filled, and the majority of those who attend them complain that they are not fed.”—“ Surely, then, it is time to turn Christianity over, and see if it have not a side which we have not hitherto observed. Perhaps when we come to see it on another side, in a new light, it will ap- pear unto us more beautiful, and have greater power to attract our love and reverence.” The Rev. R. W. Emerson, in his Address to the Se- nior Theological Class at Cambridge, in 1838, says, (p- 17,) “It is my duty to say to you, that the need was never greater of a new revelation than now. From the views I have already expressed, you will infer the sad conviction, which I have, I believe, with numbers, of the universal decay and now almost death of faith in society. The soul is not preached. The church seems to totter to its fall, almost all life extinct.” Again, (p- 94,) he says, “I think no man can go with his thoughts about him, into one of our churches, without feeling that what hold the public worship once had on men, 18 gone or going. It has lost its grasp on the affection of the good, and the fear of the bad. In the country neighbourhoods, half parishes are signing off; —to use the local term.”............And (on p. 21,) he says, “The prayers, and even the dogmas of our church, are like the zodiac of Denderah, and the astronomical in- struments of the Hindoos, wholly insulated from Ae 5Ps J Sd sbi ahs tetera nea kas Se ee) es 4. Loren, ‘% NATaa ol tae IR Benet fon ed eee ee Ve ne cae Sengtereprp rey j stot Me Wed Tl a hag i , PIE he hee ee 108 AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. thing now extant in the life and business of the people. They mark the height to which the waters once rose. For the perfect accuracy of these statements, I cannot vouch from my own personal knowledge. Nor are they here adduced to prove the actual state of the Unitarian congregations, but simply to show how defective the Transcendentalists consider the Unitarian theology, ‘and of course, the grounds of their dissatisfaction with it. The author of an elaborate and highly interesting article in the Dial for April 1841, entitled the Unitarian Movement in New England, has given a very philoso- phical account of the origin of the Unitarian community in this country, as well as of the recent rise of the sect of Transcendentalists in that community. According to this able writer, the doctrine of the Trinity, and the connected doctrines of man’s deep-rooted depravity, and his dependence on divine grace for a recovery to holiness and happiness, will.admit of a satisfactory explanation and vindication, only on the principles of the Platonic, or (as we have called it) the metaphysical philosophy. Onthe principles of thesensuous or empirical philosophy, as he supposes, a Trinity in the Godhead is an absurdity, and the connected doctrines mysterious and inexplicable. But, as is wellknown, from the days of Locke, this lat- ter philosophy held the ascendency, or rather, it was, until quiterecently, the only philosophy known in the country. While addicted to such a philosophy, our theologians could not reason closely on the articles of their faith, without meeting with difficulties and perplexities ; and they were in great danger of falling into different opi- nions respecting the Christian doctrines. At the same time, the orthodox creeds forbade any deviation from the established faith. The result was, that those most given to free inquiry, fell into Unitarianism, and the doctrines connected with that system. Thus originated, according to this writer, the Unitarian movement in New England: for he says expressly, (p. 431,) “We regard it [Unitarianism] as the result of an attempt to a Christianity by the sensual philosophy, instigat- 306ee eee = Fern Sts tata Si AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. 109 éd by a desire to get rid of mystery, and to make every thing clear and simple.” The proximate causes of the rise of Transcendentalism among the Unitarians, are thus described by this writer, (p. 422-3,) “The Unitarian movement disin- thralled the minds of men, and bade them wander wheresoever they might list in search of truth, and to rest in whatsoever views their own consciences might approve. The attention of our students was then called to the literature of foreign countries.—They wished to see how went the battle against sin and error there. They soon found a different philosophy in vogue, and one which seemed to explain the facts of their own expe- rience and observation more to their satisfaction, than the one they had been accustomed to meet in their books. In most cases the pleasure of the discovery was heightened by the fact, that these men, in their previous inquiries, had come to the same or similar conclusions. In some cases they had been too diffident to express them, while in others the expression of them had called forth manifest indications of disapprobation, if not of open persecution.”——The concluding sentences in this quotation show, that the Transcendentalists, before they became acquainted with foreign philosophy, were not satisfied with the Unitarian system of theology ; and that some of them had, at that time, arrived at nearly their present theological views, the expression of which then met the disapprobation, if not the open per- ecution, of the staunch Unitarians. The inconsistency of the Unitarian body in advocating unlimited freedom of inquiry, and then censuring the Transcendentalists for practising it, is severely rebuked in the following passage, (/p- 434,) “They have made a great movement in favour of freedom of inquiry, and thoroughness and fearlessness of investigation : and now, like the witch of Endor, they seem terrified at the spirit they have called up. This would seem to indicate that the move- ment in favour of freedom and liberty was not the off- spring of pure, disinterested love of truth and prin- ciple.”ae St tliat stent te oe ad ok Des CRE Relea Con ad re ne) al eke ated bide a he tac A neers tet saree addin tat eh ea sha bee ' hee 4 ae ee Sag ' 4 We 4 by behest ah - of epee ye An 110 AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. The defects of the Unitarian theology are described by this able writer in the following terms, (p. 436,) « Unitarians make Christianity too plain, plainer than from the very nature of the case it can possibly be.”— “There is, moreover, a degree of religious experience that Unitarianism fails to satisfy.” [P. 438]: “Uni- tarlanism is sound, sober, good sense. But the moment a preacher rises to eloquence, he rises out of his system.” [P. 440]: “ We think that, in its principles and logi- cal tendency, it is allied to the most barren of all systems.” Characteristics of the Transcendental Philosophy. None of the Transcendentalists of this country are philosophers by profession. Nearly all of them are clergymen of the Unitarian school; and their habits of thought, their feelings, and their aims, are manifestly theological. Nor do they give us proof that they have devoted very great attention to philosophy as a science. They have produced, I believe, no work pro- fessedly on the subject, not even an elementary treatise; and, if I do not mistake, they have brought forward no new views or principles in philosophy. So far as I can judge, they have merely taken up the philosophy of Victor Cousin, and after comparing it, according to their opportunity, with that of the more recent German schools, have modified a little some of its data, and ap- plied them freely to scientific and practical theology. At the same time, they take little pains to elucidate and explain the principles of their new philosophy. They address us, as if we all read and understood their favour- ite Cousin, and were not ignorant of the speculations of the German pantheists; and their chief aim seems to be, to shew us how much better this Gallo-Germanic philosophy explains the religion of nature and of the Bible, than the old philosophy of Locke and the Scot- tish school. Whoever, therefore, would understand the Transcendental writers, must first understand, if he can, the French philosopher Cousin, and the German pan- theists. 308AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. 11} The philosophy of Cousin, as well as that of the mo- dern Germans, we have attempted to describe very briefly in the preceding Chapters; and to them the reader is referred. Cousin maintains, that, by taking a higher point of observation, he has brought all previous systems of phi- losophy to harmonize with each other. [See his Introd. to Hist. of Phil. by Linberg, page 414.] He therefore adopts, and uses at pleasure, the peculiar phraseology of all the systems, as being all suited to express his own new views. This causes his writings to exhibit, not only great variety, but apparently, if not really, great inconsistency of terminology. And hence different per- sons, aiming to follow him as a guide, may easily mis- take his meaning, and adopt different principles ; or, if they adopt the same principles, they may express themselves in a very different manner. And, if we sup- pose the same persons, with only a moderate share of philosophic learning and philosophic tact, to attempt to reconstruct the philosophy of Cousin, by comparing it with the German systems from which it is taken, and at the same time to adopt Cousin’s lax use of language ; we may easily conceive, what confusion of thought and obscurity of statement may appear on their pages. Now tbe Transcendentalists, if I do not mistake, have thus followed Cousin. Of course, they differ considerably from one another: some following Cousin more closely, and others leaning more toward some German ; some preferring one set of Cousin’s terms, and others another, or coining new ones to suit their fancy. After all, Lin- berg’s translation of Cousin's Introduction to the His- tory of Philosophy may be considered as the great storehouse from which most of them—e. g. Brownson, Emerson, Parker, &c.—have derived their peculiar philosophical opinions, their modes of reasoning, and their forms of thought and expression. The radical principle of the Transcendental philoso- phy, the corner-stone of the whole edifice, is Cousin’s doctrine, that Spontaneous Reason acquainis us with the true and essential nature of things. According to this 309a - - yt e 7 Phos Hn MR AR sa es RAIN DN al rl ck domi Uh ca re ms rll Renee teeta etn iediahaha erhatnaiereed oe dee . : 4 ep Me | Me tm C ne Y . 1? a oe Py > che ps . : ‘ WM Wee by et LM Pe ie pe a i A on D oe , Wht A iiNet hh Ria Meat ialate seated heres notes admire ore arn - eer Gs * oar H ean a ebm . * : ah 112 AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. doctrine, Reason, when uncontrolled by the Will, or when left free to expatiate undirected and uninfluenced by the voluntary faculty, always apprehends things as they are, or has direct and absolute knowledge of the ob- jects of its contemplation. This clairvoyance of Reason, Cousin calls “an instinctive perception of truth, an entirely instinctive development of thought,’—*« an original, irresistible, and unreflective perception of truth,”"—“‘ pure apperception, and spontaneous faith,” —‘“‘ the absolute affirmation of truth, without reflection, —inspiration,—veritable revelation.”—[ Introd. &c. pp. 163, 167, 172, 166.] The characteristics of this kind of knowledge, as being immediate and infallible, though not always perfectly distinct at first, and as being di- wine, OY as coming from God either directly or indirect- ly, all Transcendentalists maintain. But in what man- ner, or by what mode of action, our Reason acquires this knowledge, they do not distinctly inform us. Whether our Creator has endowed us with an intellec- tual ¢nstinct, a power of rational intuition ; or whether the rational soul, as itself partaking of the divine na- ture, has this inherent sagacity in and of itself; or whether the divine Being, God himself, is always pre- sent in the soul, and acting in it by way of inspiration, these philosophers seem not to have decided. They use terms, however, which fairly impl¥ each and all of these hypotheses, and especially the last. But however undecided on this point, which is of so much importance in a philosophic view, on the general fact that all ra- tional beings do possess this knowledge, they are very explicit ; and some of them attempt to prove it, by reasoning from the necessity of such knowledge to us, and from the current belief of mankind. [ See Cousin’s Psychology, Chap. vi. and a writer in the Dial, vol. ii. page 86, &c.] The effects of this principle, when carried into theo- logy, are immense. It dispels all mysteries and all obscurities from this most profound of all sciences, and gives to human Reason absolute dominion over it. For, it makes the divine Being, his government and laws, 310eee en tt, eee eae C gigctig ee ge Pe reg ee rh ei tert - or aie Spe his z x Sa adae Sab gh Sia a TEE EME RS he FS SNS Tas mk ta her Mr Ca AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. Lies and our relations to him, and all our religious obliga- tions and interests,—every part of theology, theoretical or practical,—perfectly comprehensible to our Reason in its spontaneous operation. It makes all the doctrines of natural religion the objects of our direct, intuitive knowledge: we need no explanations and no confirma- tions from any books or teachers; we have only to listen to the voice of spontaneous Reason, or to the teachings of our own souls, the light that shines within us, and all will be perfectly intelligible and absolutely certain. And hence, we need no external revelation, no inspired teacher, to solve our doubts and difficulties, or to make any part of natural religion, or any princi- ple of moral duty, either more plain or more certain. We are, all of us, prophets of God, all inspired through our reason, and we need no one to instruct and enlighten us. The great Seers of ancient. times, Moses and the prophets, Christ and the apostles, were no otherwise inspired than we all are; they only cultivated and listened to spontaneous Reason more than ordinary men: and this enabled them to see fur- ther, and to speak and write better, than other men on religious subjects. If we would determine whether the Bible was written by inspired men, we need not pore upon the so called external evidences, miracles, prophe- cies, &c. but merely listen to the testimony of our own souls, the teachings of spontaneous Reason, or what is ealled the internal evidence, and we shall at once see the clear and infallible marks of inspiration. And to wn- derstand the Bible, we need no aid from learned inter- preters. Only give us the book in a language we can read, and the suggestions of our own inspired minds will enable us to comprehend perfectly the import of every sentence, and to see clearly what is divine, and what is human, or what originated from spontaneous Reason, and what from human infirmity, in the holy Scriptures. And, of course, every man is competent to decide, definitely and infallibly, all the controversies among theologians, and all the disputes between differ- ent sects of Christians, respecting the doctrines taught 31k= fenesaie sane Ses YT) ikke ’ ; theses mh Saad dlinetneyineeet earn othe teak ie Sa a a an - a ota aA eae ee an a 4% i sheepehiatiahe een iadhin i asnetanbatbiatetaaeebeemete in nti neato tenant ete pees te ech iea nada iii ics . oy . me m c ee . Fa we. iets ‘ $ 5 " Oe 114 AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. in the Bible. In short, not only the profound researches of philologists, antiquarians, and. biblical commentators, but also the elaborate discussions of didactic theologians, polemic, apologetic, and metaphysical, are all of little or no value in theology. Instead of depending on them, the theological inquirer should rather retire to solitude and silence; and while musing on religious subjects, with the Bible and the book of nature before him, he should refrain from giving any determinate direction to his thoughts, and allowing them to flow on spontaneously, he should listen to the voice of Reason as she expa- tiates freely in the open field of visions; then he will be caught up, as it were, to the third heaven, and will see all that the inspired prophets saw; his knowledge will be superhuman and divine. But to understand more fully the metaphysics of the Transcendental writers, we must not overlook their on-~ tological doctrines. If Reason acquaints us with the true and essential nature of all things, then the field of ontology is open fully to our inspection, and we may form there a perfectly solid and safe science. Accord- ingly, all Transcendentalists, on both sides of the Atlantic, assume some system of ontology as the basis of their speculations. The prevailing system among the modern Germans, and that to which Cousin and his American followers assent, is pantheistic : that is, it re~ solves the universe into one primordial Being, who de- velops himself in various finite forms: in other words, it supposes God and the developments of God, to be the only real existences, the ro way, the entire universe. But when they attempt to explain this general state- ment, the Germans bring forward different hypotheses. Some, following Spinoza, invest the primordial Being with the essential attributes of both a substance and a person ; and they suppose him to create from himself, or to form out of his own substance, all rational and sentient beings and all material things. Others, with Schelling, suppose him to be originally neither a person nor a substance, but the elementary principle of both, which, in developing itself, becomes first a person anda ai?Seats a elegy a RNG ASHER PaO Teen actes na tx Gr Tn LS are tao ae AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. 115 substance, and then a universe of beings and things. Others follow Hegel, and adopt a system of pure ideal~ ism. They suppose concrete ideas to be the only real existences, and the logical genesis of ideas to be the physical genesis of the universe. Take the simple idea of existence, and abstract from it every thing conceiv- able, so that it shall become evanescent; and in that evanescent state, while fluctuating between something and nothing, it is the primitive, the generative princi- ple of all things. For it is the most comprehensive or generical of all ideas, including all other ideas under it as subordinate genera and species; and therefore, when expanded or drawn out into the subordinate genera and species, it becomes the ro wav, the universe of beings and things. Vacillating among all these theories, especially between the two last, and trying to amalgamate them all in one, Cousin, without exhibiting any very definite ideas, merely declares the Infinite to be the primitive, and all that is finite to be derivative from the Infinite, while yet both the Infinite and the finite are so inseparable that neither can exist without the other.—The appellation Panthevsts, it appears, is unacceptable to Cousin, and to most of his American followers; but some of the latter voluntarily assume it ; and they unscrupulously apply it to all Transcendental- ists. That the doctrines of the Transcendentalists, as well as those of Spinoza, Schelling, and Hegel, are really and truly pantheistic, appears from the fact that they all hold to but one essence, or one substance, im the universe. They expressly deny, that God created or produced the world out of nothing, or that he gave ex~ istence to beings and things, the substance or matter of which had no previous existence: they say, he created or brought forth the world from himself, or formed it out of his own substance ; and also, that he still exists in the created universe, and the created universe in him, thus constituting an absolute unity, as to essence or sub- stance. That the epithet pantheistic may properly be applied to such doctrines, seems not to be deniable. [See Krug’s Philos. Lexicon; art. Pantheismus. | a4Se erecta a etc se tne ot ca . _ * setae nie! PEI peg em gt pegre tenwene: eipeninnsbgt an peter er yr neh ALR tae UT OEY: } ae Ney a oe Le hk : mE Hee Fhe barby, 1 <“ Oe Ot remnnens: Saal hi ot oalan ede arenteatene cele ate ela nee eee . VA. a | ‘ et ye 116 AMERICAN TRANSCENDENTALISM. As Pantheists, the Transcendentalists must behold God, or the divine nature and essence, in every thing that exists. Of course, none of them can ever doubt the existence of God, or be in the least danger of athe- ism ; for they cannot believe any thing to exist, with- out finding God in it; they see him, they feel him, they have sensible perception of his very substance in every object around. Moreover, if our souls are only portions of the Divinity, if they are really God working in us, then there is solid ground for the belief that spontaneous Reason always sees the true nature of things, or has divine knowledge of the objects of its contemplation. And again, if it is the Divine Nature which lives and acts in all creatures and things, then all their action is Divine action. All created intelligences think, and feel, and act, as God acts in them ; and of course, precisely as He would have them. There can, then, be nothing wrong, nothing sinful, in the character or conduct of any rational bemg. There may be imperfection, or imperfect action, because the whole power of God is not exerted ; but every act, so far as it goes, 1s just what it should be, just such as best pleases God. And hence, though men may sigh over their im- periections, or may ardently desire and strive to become more perfect, yet they can have no reason for repentance, for sorrow and shame and self-condemnation, for any- thing they have done or have omitted to do. Neither can they feel themselves to need any radical change of character, to make them acceptable to God; or any Redeemer, to rescue them from impending perdition. All they need is, to foster the divinity within, to give it more full scope and more perfect action; then they will become all that it is possible they should be, and all they can reasonably desire. These inferences from their principles, are not palmed upon Transcendentalists by their adversaries, but are admitted and defended by their ablest writers. Says one of them, whom we have before quoted, [Dial, vol. i. pp- 423-4,] « Holding as they do but one essence of all things, which essence is Se Pantheists must deny the existence of essentialee ee nunieeazana ce ES ~ eee = en - * me : “ atte ata Sabo eG ae NTE eerie en ae ee ee — _ Dg eas ee Sa St Sea US fate Getse PHILOSOPHY OF DR RAUCH. 11% evil. All evil is negative,—it is imperfection, non- ae It is a essential, but modal. Of come there é e no such i 1 i Gy inal inttocond gags ein atoms of a righteous law but the “diff Sie races which the Infinite meets wi a ae te init with in entering into the finite. Regeneration is nothing but an ingress of God into the soul, before which sin disappears as darkness before the rising sun. Pantheists hold also to the atonement, or at-one-ment between the soul and God. This is strict- ly a unity or oneness of essence, to be brought about by the incarnation of the spirit of God, [in us, ] which is going on In us as we grow in holiness. As we grow wise, just, and pure,—in a word, holy,—we grow to be one with him in mode, as we always were inessence. This atonement is effected by Christ, only in as far as he taught the manner in which it was to be accomplished more fully than any other, and gave us a better illustra- tion of the method and result in his own person than any one else that has ever lived.” CHAPTER XVI, PHILOSOPHY OF DR RAUCH. Biographical Notice.—His Psychology—Transcendental—Hegelian,—Outline of his Philosophy.—Its bearing on Theology. Tur Rev. Frederic A. Rauch, Ph. D., late President of Marshall College, Penn., was born in Hesse Darm- stadt, in the year 1806. His father, a pious and ortho- dox clergyman of the German Reformed Church, is still living, and is an active pastor in the vicinity of Frank- fort on the Maine. Dr Rauch received his education at Marburg, Giessen, and Heidelberg, and became @ Professor in the two last named places. In some of his | | 315ens eee el a oa > : ‘ | aieeapat hearah satin cited tennant aad Saeed Det Sek alte tediin ected heme aheed a ines ah aril ; ng Ra * Be egateg Bie rae et CTL. Ei rae Pe bee mS ‘ r 4 5 Try Pe rr ee ee 118 PHILOSOPHY OF DR RAUCH. lectures at Heidelberg he uttered his thoughts too freely on the affairs of government, and found it necessary to flee the country. He came to America in 183]. The next year he took charge of the classical school con- nected with the Theological Seminary of the German Reformed Synod at York, Pennsylvania 5 and on the re- moval of that Institution to Mercersberg in 1836, he was made President of the College and Professor of Biblical Literature in the Seminary. He died on the 2d of March, 1841, in the 35th year of his age. (See an Obituary Notice in the New York Observer, March 97, 1841; and the Preliminary Notice to Rawuch’s Psychology, 2d edition. ) Dr Rauch was one of that class of German philoso- phers, who, embracing fully the transcendental specu- lations of Schelling and Hegel, have laboured to reconcile them with the religion of the Bible. The two most prominent men of this party in Germany, have been Dr Philip Marheineke of Berlin, and Dr Charles Daub of Heidelberg. The former is still living, and is the editor of the Works of Hegel, and also of the Works of Daub, who died in 1836. The biographer of Dr Rauch characterizes Daub as being a “ giant in the sphere of mind,” and “aman who had followed Kant, Schelling, and Hegel, to the farthest bounds of speculation, with- out surrendering for 2 moment his firm hold upon the great objects of faith.” This metaphysical giant, who travelled the whole round from Kantism to Hegelism, is best known by his mystical work on the nature and origin of Evil, entitled, Judas Iscariot, or Evil in tts relation to Good; Heidelb. 1816-18. 8vo. Dr Rauch was the favourite pupil of Daub; who, it is said, “ had fixed his eye upon him asa young man of more than common promise, who might be expected to do good service in the cause of science, in the department to which he wished to consecrate his life.” The doctrines which Daub instilled into the mind of his pupil, Dr Rauch ap- pears to have brought with him to America, and to have retained as long as he lived. The first and only publication of Dr Rauch in this 316Pre erent et tee ae ee 7 = Sees cares ter gees to ere onl i . SAS sd SRE AC Rae gt Se at aes aes ea NG TRL IES TI SR SS Ge Ga Ss Sp He Sele SCRE SE, Bi3é tase sa tesesetey aS es ag PHILOSOPHY OF DR RAUCH. 119 country, was his Psychology, or View of the Human Soul, including Anthropology ; first published in 1840, and revised by him for a second edition, 184]. The subject of this work, like that of most German trea~ tises on Psychology, and like the Enolish treatises on Mental Philosophy, is Empirical Psychology, not Rational or Speculative Psychology. That is, it em- braces that knowledge of the human Mind, which is derived from eaperience and observation ; not that which is obtained by philosophical speculations on the nature and properties of the soul. It therefore has but little to do with Philosophy in the proper sense of the term, or with strictly rational science. It treats of empirical knowledge, not of that which is scientific. Still there is a philosophy underlying it, which itis not difficult to discover ; and that philosophy is manifestly transcendental, and derived from the school of Hegel. Dr Rauch, being a man of genius, and familiar with the numerous and learned works of the Germans on Psychology, and having access to the more recent in- vestigations of his countrymen in physical science, has been able to embody in his work much that is new and interesting to American readers, especially in the mode of explaining and illustrating the mental phenomena, In the first part of his work entitled Anthropology, he treats largely of Life, both in vegetables and animals ; of Instinct, as a part of animal nature; and of the in- fluence of external Nature on the Mind, and of the Mind on the body. In the second part, or Psychology pro- per, he treats of Self-consciousness, the distinguishing mark of a rational being: and of our two mental fa- culties, Feeason and Will. Reason in man has three modes of action, Sensation, Intellect, and Pure Thinking, The Will, in the natural or unregenerate man, follows the natural Desires, Inchinations, Emotions, and Pas- sions: in the regenerate, it follows the Divine Will. Some concise remarks on true and false Feligion, con- clude the work. The short Chapter on Pure Thinking, is the only part of the book that directly treats on spe- culative Philosophy: but philosophical remarks and observations occur throughout the work. I 317120 PHILOSOPHY OF DR RAUCH. As a philosopher, Dr Rauch was a Transcendentalist : for he maintains that our Reason gives us objective know- ledge of things, and not merely subjective knowledge. Thus, in the department of nature or the material world, he supposes our knowledge to extend beyond Pheno- mena, and to embrace what Kant calls Nowmena. Af- ter describing the Conceptions of the Understanding, as being mental Images of objects existing in nature, he says, page 227: “The image is the same as the thing it represents,...the same as the object ; for it cannot be without it, and unless it includes what the object in- cludes, it is not its true image...... The image has there- fore the same contents as the object, with this difference, the one has them as they exist im the mind ¢deally, the other as they are in the material thing really. We would say, therefore, by the power of conceiving, the contents of an object, and the object itself, become con- tents of our conceptions or images.” So also, m regard to supersensible objects, or things in the world of thought and of ideas, he supposes we have power to dis- cover their real essence, or their ontological nature.— Describing the objects which are the subject-matter of Pure Thinking, he says, page 281: “ They are wholly general ; and as such have no existence independent of thinking. Yet they truly eaist ; they are not a mere abstraction ; they are the pure being and nature of in- dividual things, their soul and life.” And we shall see as we proceed, that he undertakes to tell us precisely what is the essential nature of the human soul or mind; of life also, both in vegetable and animal bodies; and in- deed, of all the mysterious powers which operate in any part of the created universe. | Being a Transcendentalist, Dr Rauch was diametri- eally opposed to the views of Kant, whose Critical Phi- losophy has for its chief aim to overthrow all 7’ranscen- dentalism, or as Kant would rather call it, Transcen- dentism. Kant supposed an impassable gulf to lie be- tween subjective and objective knowledge in all created things. But Transcendentalists either discover no oulf there, or they suppose they have found out a way to transcend and faiuly get over it. 318ania Se cease ae squash er ercerer _ call ° SR ee ey Seen © Urge y The return of ALDERMAN LIBRARY this book is due on the date indicated below DUE Usually books are lent out for two weeks, but there are exceptions and the borrower should note carefully the date stamped above. Fines are charged for over-due books at the rate of five cents a day; for reserved books there are special rates and regulations. Books must be presented at the desk if renewal is desired. L-1RX 000 3448 3y3