I LLINO I S UNIVERSITY OF ILLINOIS AT URBANA-CHAMPAIGN PRODUCTION NOTE University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign Library Brittle Books Project, 2009. rTml m Ar I i L IP1 :,FR D 0 H W- q- 4 t,. THE UNIVERSITY OF ILLINOIS LIBRARY 335 ,. Y-- j - -- - - _ _ FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM CONTAINING A STUDY IN MARXIAN ECONOMICS By H. W. PARKINSON Member of the Institution of Civil Engineers THE LABOUR PUBLISHING COMPANY LIMITED LONDON 38 GREAT ORMOND ST. W.C. i Published in Great Britain in zga5. TO MY DAUGHTER ELSA TI 580343 Preface. The author wishes to record his grateful appreciation of the assistance received by him from Henry Alcock, M.A., Pro- fessor of History and Economics, University of Queensland, and from H. A. Talbot Tubbs, M.A., sometime Professor of Classics, University of New Zealand. It is hardly necessary to add that neither of these gentlemen is in the slightest degree responsible for the opinions expressed in the text. The author welcomes helpful criticism. H. W. PARKINSON. Clifton Gardens, Sydney, January, 1924. List of Illustrations. Figure. Page. 1. Tle Spiral of Progress ......................44 2. The Growth of Surplus Value...............78 3. Diagram I. Distribution of Wealth...........80 4. do. II. Australian Exports..............84 5. do. III. Value of Products...............86 6. do. IV. Quantity of Products............. 88 7. do. V. Time........................... 89 8. do. VI. Value and Quantity of Products .. 90 9. do. VII. Cost ........................... 92 10. do. VIII. Profit .......................... 96 11. Supply and Demand........................ 98 12. Diagram IX. Products.......:............... 101 13. First Form of Differential Rent ............. 107 1:4. Second Form of Differential Rent............. 109 16. The Pyramid of Credit ..................... 135 Contents. Chapter Page. I. Introduction ................... II. The History of Industry............ ........ 19 III. The Evolution of Industry................... 40 IV. Money .................................... 50 V. Value.................................... 54 VI. Surplus Value .............................. 77 VII. Exploitation.............................. 104 VIII. The Great Private Bank Fraud............... 122 IX. Economic Contradiction .................... 139 X. The Ethical Aspect ........................ 149 XI. The Philosophy of Capitalism............... 163 XII. The Mental Attitude............169 XIII. Capitalism ................................ 178 XIV. Palliatives ................................ 186 XV. Ecan ~m01.IR evolut .()n.................... 200 XVII. Freedom................................. 209 Appendix................................ 220 All Rights8Reserved. I. Introduction. That the industrial organisation of society as at present constituted is the outcome of a long period of growth and change few, if any, would wish to deny. Change and growth continue still; we ourselves are in the midst of them. Even in our own time we have seen handicraft give place to the factory system-the bootmaker is a maker no longer, and we do not go to him now to be measured but merely to "try on"; he is simply a seller of factory-made wares. A similar fate threatens even the tailor. Such changes are gradual, hardly perceived until they are complete; but their cumulative effect is very great, and in sum they make the history of industry. If then we would understand the present industrial organisa- tion of society we must be conversant with the history of its development. A brief preliminary review of that development needs no further apology. But merely to know the history of industry is not in itself sufficient. It is easy to plot the known portion of a curve, but unless its "law" is determined we cannot project it or follow its future course. So to knowledge of the past history of in- dustrial development must be added determination of the laws of development-if we are to forecast its further advance. Industry is a quasi-organism and all organisms develop in the same way-under the same laws. Those laws or ways of development are in brief integration and differentiation, of which something more must be said later. Armed with this two-fold knowledge, both of the history of industry and of the laws of its development or evolution, we shall be in a position to take up our main subject of re- search, the existing social method of producing and distribu- ting wealth-the method known as Capitalism. FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. The scale of this present work does not permit a detailed treatment of historical data. In Chapter II. there is given a summary view of past economic systems. Of the present system we take it to be plain without the need of elaboration that the distribution of wealth is very unequal. Great wealth comes to a few, comparative poverty to the many. Under Capitalism differentiation has outstripped integration, causing lack of harmony, a loss of balance and an unequal develop- ment. Happily there are already signs of a recovery of balance and of a more harmonious advance in the future. What those signs are and how advantage may be taken of them is the subject of the remaining, and constructive, portion of this book. It will be plain to the reader that, in general, the system of investigation adopted is that which became familiar through the monumental work of Karl Marx on capital, though the present writer would not be understood merely to echo the the views of that great propagandist. Marx did not live to edit the whole of his book "Das Kapital," but in any case his writings would not have been easy reading, and they demand from the reader earnest and patient study and some preliminary knowledge of economics and industrial history. Karl Marx died in 1883, but it can hardly be said that his work is as yet completely understood, or his greatness as a man and a thinker recognised. He stands with Darwin pre- eminent as one of the greatest intellectual forces of the nine- teenth century. A profound scholar, versed in the jurispru- dence, economics and philosophy of his day, he wrote and spoke German, French and English, knew Spanish, Italian and Russian, and was a critical scholar in Greek and Latin. He was a man of exemplary life, a loving husband and father and a kind-hearted man; ever ready to play with the children of the London streets, he was affectionately known to them as "Daddy." The poet Heine said of him: "Marx is the tenderest, gentlest man I have ever known"; yet there was in him a sternness, a contempt, almost amounting to intoler- ance, for what he regarded as error, and most certainly he did not "suffer fools gladly," but was perhaps too ready to believe that those who did not agree with him were fools. His scorn of shams was withering. It has been said of him that "he had the satire of Juvenal and the holy wrath of Dante," but he gave out more light than heat. The lightning stroke of his satire was not followed by reverberating thunder, and gave no warning to his victim of a second flash; it cauterised by the intensity of light, and mercilessly exposed the intel- lectual nakedness of his adversaries, the vulgar economists. In the picturesque language of Bernard Shaw, Marx "convicted 12 INTRODUCTION. private property of wholesale spoliation, murder and compul- sory prostitution; of plague, pestilence and famine, battle, murder and sudden death." It is hardly surprising that private property does not love him. But Marx dealt his hardest blows at systems, not at individuals. He struck at the latter only in so far as they personified a system; as he himself says: I paint the Capitalist and the Landlord in no sense couleur de rose. But here individuals are dealt with only in so far as they are the personifications of economic categories, embodiments of particular class-relations and class-interests. My standpoint from which the evolution of the economic formation of society is viewed as a process of natural history can less than any other make the individual respon- sible for relations whose creature he socially remains, however much he may subjectively raise himself above them. This is an admirable attitude, and one worthy of imitation. Marx not only gave the world his doctrine of surplus value, and his explanation of the capitalistic system of production, but he familiarised his generation with the vast importance of economic and material conditions in the formation of the social structure. His economic, or materialistic, conception of history is stated in the following words: In making their livelihood together men enter into certain neces- sary involuntary relations with each other, industrial relations which correspond to whatever stage society has reached in the development of its material productive forces. The totality of these industrial relations constitutes the economic structure of society, the real basis upon which the legal and political superstructure is built, and to which definite forms of social consciousness correspond. The method of pro- ducing the material livelihood determines the social, political and in- tellectual life process in general. It is not men's consciousness which determines their life; on the contrary, it is their social life which determines their consciousness. That is, the first requisite is to live-to obtain food, cloth- ing and shelter ;* then only, and only on the economic basis of a community formed for that purpose, can men concern them- selves with other things. But as Marx himself says: A social formation never passes away before all the productive forces immanent within it have had time to develop themselves, and new and higher relations of production never establish themselves before the material conditions of their existence have already been formed within the womb of the old society. That the economic factor is of immense importance in the evolution of society cannot be denied. That it is the only factor is obviously untrue. But permanently to straighten a crooked stick it is not sufficient merely to bend it straight; it must be bent crooked in the opposite direction, elastic re- action may then make it permanently straight. Both Marx and Engels probably understood this and acted accordingly. *As Aristotle said long years ago: "We must first secure a livelihood, then practise virtue." 13 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. Although Marx had outgrown Hegelism,# yet, as he him- self admits, he coquetted with Hegelian terms. He held that ideas were deeply rooted in reality, but did not deny the reality of matter. His thoughts were clear, but his very thoroughness, as well as his method of expression, often made it difficult for his readers properly to appreciate his meaning. When dealing with variable quantities his thoroughness led him to work out resolutely all their possible variations, with, in some cases, wearisome detail. Another cause of misunderstanding has been Marx's failure to define his terms. In some cases it is only by his repeated use of a term that we at last arrive at an understanding of its exact meaning. In the present work an endeavor has been made to clear up any obscurity which may attach to those of Marx' views which have been selected for confirmation or criticism. It is hoped that this work of clarification and modernisation will help the average reader to break through the mists of misconception-whether accidental or wilful- which most economic writers have helped to spread over the Marxian doctrines. Capitalism is a system of producing and distributing wealth. But wealth is the means of life, and the method there- fore of its production and distribution is of vital importance. "You take my life when you do take the means by which I live." To understand the capitalist system it is necessary in the first place that we should recognise in it the outcome of a long process of growth. To grow is one thing, to be made another. A house is made, a tree grows. The distinction is of the utmost importance. To regard modern industry as merely so many individuals at work is a serious error, as serious as to confound an armed mob, a haphazard collection of armed men, with an army. Even a house is not a haphazard collec- tion of bricks-there must be arrangement, organisation, in a word, construction. Further, the construction of a house is a problem in statics, the growth and organisation of industry are a problem-and a complex problem-in dynamics. A draw- ing, an oil painting may fairly present a house, but industry is a moving picture. Industry has changed, is changing, and -we may safely assert-will change. The materials of a house are inorganic, lifeless brick and timber: industry is an organ- *Thus Marx says of Hegel: "Nothing could be more comical than Hegel's development of private property in land. According to him, man as an individual must give reality to his will as the soul of external nature, and to this end must take possession of nature and make her his private pro- perty." It logically follows, as Marx says, that if all individuals act in this way a conflict as to possession arises. In which case Hegel tells us, "Here positive right must fix its boundaries, for nothing more can be deduced from the conception." Evidently a very barren sort of conception, and evidently Marx had outgrown Hegelism. 14 INTRODUCTION. isation of living, thinking men. Industry lives, and that which determines life is organic change and growth. We have used the terms that are sufficient for our present purpose, although we might go further and affirm-as we believe-that society is a living organism. The difficulty of the latter conception is pointed out by Professor L. T. Hob- house: In what terms are we to describe the reality of the social wholes is a standing difficulty of sociology. They are, as we have seen, of organic character, yet, if we speak of them as organisms, we are liable to confound them with animals or plants, which they are not. Essen- tially they are unities of mind. . . Yet if we speak of them as personalities, we are liable to the fallacy of the common self . But whatever term we use, the rule of logic is simple. Our reason- ings must always stand the test of substituting the thing defined, for the definition. ... If we speak of society as organic, we must not think of it as a great Leviathan, a whole related to individuals as a body to its cells. We must regard the organic as a genus into which animals and plants fall as species. . . . So considered, an organism is a whole constituted by the interconnection of parts which are them- selves maintained each by its interconnection with the remainder . It is on this character that social ethics depends. . . . It is by reference to this character that . . . development is to be measured. S. . There are societies in which . . . distinct and separate per- sonalities may develop in harmony and contribute to a collective achievement.* But we cannot subscribe entirely to that view. To call society a living organism is not mere analogy, mere simile, nor does it simply embody a simple truth. So much depends on what is meant by living organism. An animal is a living organism, so is a plant, and yet an animal is not a plant, nor is society either. Nor is the antithesis between individual and society complete. Nor is our conception of society perfect, but it can truly be said that Man is what he is because he is a member of society. We are at least on safe ground when we assert that society is an organisation of life and develops in accordance with the laws of evolution. "And what"--we ask with Coleridge-"is organisation but the connection of parts in and for a whole, so that each part is at once means and end?" Such an organisation is society-the whole-whose parts are individuals linked to- gether for the attainment of a common end, the purpose for which society is, the satisfaction of man's desire for wealth and life. To fulfil this purpose, to attain this end, industry, associated industry, exists. Various writers, by speaking of the evolution of industry, have acknowledged that it is subject to organic change. That admission, however, is not by itself sufficient. Evolution has become so familiar a word, that to many, perhaps most, it has *"Metaphysical Theory of the State," p. 131. 15 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. lost much of its fuller significance. To them evolution "has something to do with the survival of the fittest": they are vaguely conscious that it implies a gradual advance from a lower to a higher form. But while, if offered a concrete example, they may recognise readily enough that (let us say) a conger-eel is a higher form of life than a jelly-fish, yet, actually, they have a less distinct conception of what really constitutes a higher form than they have of evolution itself. Now growth follows certain laws, but by the laws of evo- lution we do not now mean the causes of the growth which results in a higher form of life, but merely those generalisations which express what is meant by the word higher. Those gene- ralisations or laws may be stated as: (1) Change from the relatively simple to the relatively complex, by (2) an increasing differentiation, or specialisation in the parts, accompanied by (3) an increasing integration, or oneness of the whole. Other laws there may be, but they do not concern us. (1) Complexity arises from a multiplication of parts and organs having distinct functions, and thus while, e.g., the jelly- fish-almost an amorphous mass, with a power of absorbing food by infiltration-has neither heart nor gills, internal skele- ton, nor eyes, nor brain, nor nervous system, the conger-eel is more complex, since it has all these and more. Compared with a jelly-fish, the conger-eel is a complex organism and a higher form of life. (2) Differentiation is the specialisation of parts of an organism or organisation to perform fewer functions or one particular function, but to perform it better; a development of the senses and powers of an organism by means of new or better organs. And the greater the number of organs and the more exclusive their function, the higher the differentiation and the form of life. (3) Integration (or solidarity) is the interdependence of the whole and its parts. A sponge can be cut in two, and each part will continue to live, but two conger-eels cannot be made by cutting one in halves. And the more necessary the parts are to the life of the whole, the higher the integration and the form of life. Thus the evolution of an organism or organisation from a lower to a higher form consists of an advance hand in hand of both integration and differentiation, and a progressive change from the relatively simple to the relatively complex. Evolution, as now understood, is not an unfolding of what already exists, although, etymologically speaking, that may be the first meaning of the word. But it is-in its accepted scientific application-a gradual growth-in-complexity of a race or species, and-through the species-of the individual. 16 INTRODUCTION. Mere change is not evolution: for since "evolution" is limited to a growth-in-complexity, it is obvious that not any and every change can be evolution-there may be a change from the complex to the simple. The full theory of evolution may, it is true, embrace a complete cycle, but we are only concerned with ascending phases, or with the phase of degradation only in so far as it applies to parts of an organism (useless organs) and not to an organism as a whole. Nor is mere development evolution; evolution is of the species, development of the indi- vidual. By development we understand those changes in the individual which take place in its growth to maturity. These changes, it is true, if we begin with the embryo, may, or do, rehearse the story of the evolution of the species. It may or may not be true that individual developments accidentally ac- quired are in some cases transmitted to, and persist in the off- spring; and that by such transmission the evolution of the species is affected, although it is believed that only individual changes that affect the germ-plasm are transmitted. The indi- vidual develops, the species evolves. This, then, is evolution properly so called, a growth of the species from the relatively simple to the relatively complex. It is hardly necessary to trace in detail the evolution of organic life or to follow the ascending phases of evolution in the species; but that 'higher' integration-passing beyond the individual to embrace society requires a moment's considera- tion. The life of society does not begin and end with the life of the: individuals of which-for the time-it is composed. The life history of-Greece and Rome extends beyond the life period of any individual Greek or Roman. Rome grew, reached its zenith, and decayed-but life in the world did not die with Rome-because Rome was only one of many societies. The merging of all societies into one constitutes the highest form of social integration, but to constitute the highest form of social organisation-the highest possible differentiation is also necessary. Thus a 'higher' form of organisation, whether of individual industry, or of social industry, or of world industry, consists in a more complex organisation; in parts specialised to perform effectively one function; in parts that are har- moniously related to each other, and to the whole; and in a whole whose life depends on the harmonious support of its parts. It is of the utmost importance to realise the organic connection between the individual and the society of which he forms a part. Before Darwin came 'life' was for us a con- geries of unrelated phenomena; we saw only the varied fruits of the genealogical tree of life, the tree itself and its branches were buried out of sight. And these' fruits superficially re- garded seemed to have no relation to each other. It was not B 17 18 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. easily seen that bird, reptile, fish and mammal were intimately related and rooted in the same stock. The belief that they were separate and independent acts of creation was as natural as the childish belief that the sun revolves round the earth. Before Marx came, 'industry' presented us with facts which the economists placed in separate and almost unrelated categories,-as rent, interest, profit, wages,-and it required the genius of Marx to discover their true relation to each other and the underlying laws of their being. The absurd attempt to tear the individual from the orgaa- ism of which he forms a part, to emasculate him and represent him as actuated by selfish motives alone was bound to end in failure. The 'economic man' was a creature who always moved accurately along the line of greatest personal gain:-as labourer, planting him- self in the trade and place where wages are highest, endowed with a chameleon-like capacity of adaptation, trammelled by no bonds of at- tachment which would retard the perfect fluidity of his movements in the labor-market; as capitalist, making with unerring instinct for the highest rate of profit, unfettered by foolish scruples about sweating, adulteration, or any malpractice, which attached to 'investments' as merchant, shopkeeper, or as consumer, knowing one law only, viz., 'to buy in the cheapest to sell in the dearest market.' No gain which the ignorance -or weakness of another placed his way would be rejected; no sentiment of compassion or generosity would be allowed to blunt the edge of his cupidity. Industrial society was conceived of as a society of these self- seekers.* But in fairness to the orthodox economist, it must be re- cognised that in his endeavour to simplify the problem and reduce it to a few elements he has, at least, put his finger on the most powerful motive underlying Capitalism, viz., self- interest. That there is a lack of harmony between the parts -between labourer, capitalist, merchant, shopkeeper and con- samer-only shows that Capitalism is defective and backward in integration, and consequently a 'low' form of industry. But that Capitalism has evolved, few or none will deny. Its growth is best studied in the light of evolution, because the general laws of evolution are the general laws of industrial organi- sation. Aided by that light we are enabled to trace, dimly it is true, the prehistoric beginnings and growth of industry. *J. A. Hobson, "The Social Problem," p. 29. THE HISTORY OF INDUSTRY. II. The History of Industry. Since industry is essential to life, the growth and develop- ment of industry is necessarily co-temporary with the life of man, and, indeed, with the life of his ape-like ancestors who found in hunger an incentive to 'industry.' Organised industry was, at first, founded on sex, later, on property and territory. In the earlier form the cares of motherhood kept the wo- man near the camping place. To her fell the more sedentary work, that of cooking, keeping the fire alight, making cooking utensils, plaiting baskets and sewing skins. But the men were free to hunt, to fish, to wander through the forest in search of food. To them fell the protection of the camp, the wmak'ng of weapons, the hunting and capture of animal food. Industrial organisation on the basis of sex lasted for thou- sands of years, and only at a comparatively recent date gave place to the second form of industry-that founded on pro- pery. "Modern institutions," says Lewis H. Morgan in his "Ancient Society," "plant their roots in the period of barbar- ism, into which their germs were transmitted from the pre- vious period of savagery. They have had a lineal descent through the ages." The first great form of industry-that founded on sex- developed with, and depended on, Group Marriage, a custom so remote and unfamiliar that it may be well to give a short account of it. The earliest form of 'marriage' was consan- guine marriage or indiscriminate intercourse between the sexes. The second-and most important from the industrial point of view-was group marriage. The group was formed by a num- ber of women of common descent, all of whom were considered to be 'sisters' and the 'mothers' in common to all the child- ren of the group. Of the children of Group A, the daughters remained in, and were essential to the group, or 'matriar. chate'; the sons were forbidden to marry in Group A-all the daughters being technically their sisters-they married into some other group and became, in common with others, the joint husbands of all the daughters in that group, say B, just as their 'sisters' became, in common, the wives of all the men in Group A. (Some even number of groups-four or more-was generally formed). The women thus constituted the permanent element in the group, and in common held its property. These groups are 19 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. termed gentes, and it was on this "crimson thread of kinship" that ancient society was organised. Since the status of woman is largely determined by her economic position, it is not sur- prising to. find that her status was never higher than under the gens system of social organisation. The system was a pure democracy, and its members, as in the case of the North American Indians, were noted for their manly independence and dignity of character. A number of different gentes--generally four, six, or eight --an even number was necessary-formed a phratry, or group of brother gentes, but it was the women in each gens that formed its stable element, and indeed owned its property in cnunmon. They never changed their names nor the gens in which they were born; but sons when they attained manhood were compelled to marry into some other gens. A number of phratries formed a tribe. An inspection of the illustration showing the first and second phratries of the Seneca-Iroquois tribe will give a good idea of the system. / SENECA-IROQUOIS TRIBE. FIRST PHRATRY (Brother Gentes). 1. BEAR. 2. WOLF 3. BEAVER. 4. TURTLE. Men Men Men Men 1mn WomenW Ie. I n Daughters - Sons 5. DEER. Men Women Daughters Sons - Daughters Daughters Sons Sons SECOND PHRATRY (Brother Gentes). 6. SNIPE. Men Women Daughters - Sons 7. HERON. Men SWomen SDaughters Sons 8. -HAWK. Men Women Daughters Sons O CD tbe r; ryst c The dwellings or long houses of each gens were sometimes built in the form of a cross with a fireplace in the centre and skin partitions between the sleeping cubicles. 1I 20 THE' HISTORY OF INDUSTRY. Originally �marriage was not only prohibited in the same -gens; but also in the same phratry-thus sons from the Turtle were not allowed to marry into the Bear, since both Turtle and Bear belonged to the 1st phratry, and although later this res- triction was removed, yet since all the women of the gens in which a man was born were technically either his mothers or his sisters, marriage within the gens was rigidly prohibited. If the whole gens is regarded as a single individual the relationships created will more easily be understood. Thus the whole gens was responsible for the acts of individual mem- bers. With these gentes as units the tribe was built up. The Seneca-Iroquois tribe consisted of eight phratries, each phratry of from four to eight gentes and each gens of 50 to 100 or more individuals. The later developments of the institution of marriage hardly concern us; they may be briefly mentioned, as (3) The Pairing Family, founded on temporary and, while it lasted, exclusive marriage of one male and one female; it was not, however, of a permanent nature. (4) The Patriarchal Family, or the marriage of one man to several wives. (5) The Mono- gamic Family or the permanent marriage of one man. to one woman. The institution of marriage exhibits in its evolution a gradual progression from the indefinite and general to the definite and particular, and has more or less affected the de- velopment of man himself, property, and industrial organi- sation. In tracing the development of industry-or indeed of any evolutionary growth-it should not be forgotten that the process is gradual, and more or less continuous. As such it is not naturally divisible into sections. But certain changes are relatively rapid, and may serve as milestones artificially to mark our progress. Morgan, for instance, divides the prehistoric development of society into two main periods: I. Savagery, II. Barbarism; and subdivides them into lower, middle and higher stages. I. Savagery. 1. The lower stage is the infancy of the human race, and may be said to have ended with the acquisition of a fish sub- stance and a knowledge of the use of fire. Men lived, partly at least, in trees, in tropical and subtropical forests; for only in this way could they escape large beasts of prey. Fruits, nuts and roots served as food. In this stage, which lasted for thousands of years, and to which may be ascribed the develop- ment of gesture and sounds into articulate speech, the only 'industry' was a rude struggle for subsistence, an appropria- tion of natural products. Page 21, 9th line from bottom of page-'"fish sub- stance" should read "fish subsistence" 21 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. 2. The middle stage of savagery commenced with the discovery of fire, rendering a general fish diet possible. Shell- fish, it is true, may be eaten raw, and some other fish when sun dried, but generally fish cannot be eaten in a raw state. Now began the first division of labour; the man searched for food, while the woman kept the fire alight and cooked the food when found. With a general fish diet possible human beings became independent of climate, and largely of locality. Following the course of rivers and coast lines, protected by fire at night from wild animals, or secure in caves, they spread over the greater part of the earth even while in a savage state. The so-called palaeolithic implements of the early stone age belong almost entirely to this period. Their wide distribution over the continents testifies to the extent of man's wander- ings. The increasing bent for exploration and invention, to- gether with the possession of fire, added new products to the bill. of fare, such as farinaceous roots and tubers, cooked in hot ashes or in baking pots or ground ovens. With the invention of the first weapons, the club, the boomerang and the spear, a meat diet was sometimes to be obtained, but tribes subsisting exclusively by hunting have never existed, for the proceeds of hunting were too uncertain. With savage man it was occasionally a feast, more often a famine,* and the precariousness of the sources of subsistence probably gave rise to cannibalism, which seems to have arisen in this stage and continued in force for a long time. Until quite recently we had in the aboriginal Australian an example of the middle stage of savagery. :It is characterised by some form of group marriage. 3. The higher stage of savagery is ushered in by the in- vention of the bow and arrow, making venison and other meats a regular part of the diet, and hunting a normal occupation. Bow, arrow, and cord, represent a rather complicated instrument, and its invention presupposes a long and accumu- lated experience, increased mental capacity and acquaintance with a number of other inventions. Thus among peoples that are familiar with the use of the bow and arrow (but not with the art of pottery) we find the beginnings of village settle- ments, control of food production, construction of vessels and utensils, weaving of bast fibre by hand (without a loom), baskets made of bast or reeds (chiefly by women), and sharp- ned stone implements. Fif'e and the stone axe furnished the dugout, and here and there timbers and slabs were used for house building. All these improvements were found, for example, among the Ame. *The carerfree, happy savage is entirely a creature of the poeitic imnagination. The fear of hunger was ever present. "Sacrifices" were food offerings to a hungry god. 22 THE HISTORY OF INDUSTRY. rican Indians of the North-West, who used bow and arrows, but knew nothing of the art of pottery. Bows and arrows were for the higher stage of savagery what the iron sword was for the higher stage of barbarism, and the firearm for civilisation --the weapon of supremacy. The struggle for existence grew into. a struggle, not only with nature and wild animals, but with other men. The higher stage of savagery is characterised by the matur- ity of the group system of marriage, and the formation of the gentile system of industry and government, and later by the beginnings of the pairing form of marriage and the decay of the gentile system. II. Barbarism. 1. Lower Stage.-This dates from the introduction of the art of pottery. The art is due probably in all cases (it is dis- tinctly traceable in many instances) to the custom of covering wooden or plaited vessels with clay, in order to render them fireproof. It did not, however, take long to find out that imoulded clay served the purpose without lining, or reinforce- nlent. At an earlier stage recourse was had to soapstone, steatite, or potstone, which will not fracture if suddenly cooled with water. We may assume the course of industrial development up to this stage to have been equally characteristic, in a general way, of all mankind without reference to locality, but at the beginning of barbarism a stage is reached where the differ- ence in natural resources makes itself felt. The salient feature of barbarism is the taming and raising of animals, and the -cultivation of plants. Now the old world contained nearly all the tameable animals and cultivable species of grain, while the Americans possessed only one tameable animal, the llama, in the south, and but few species of grain, al.hongh one of the best, viz., Indian corn. Thus the inhabi- tants of America, and of Asia and Europe, were led along dif- ferent and divergent roads, and the various stages of develop- ment in the Old and New World exhibit a pronounced dis- similarity. 2.: The middle stage in the West, or New World, com- mnienced with the cultivation and irrigation of food plants, and with the use of adobes-bricks baked in the sun-and stones for houses. At the time of their discovery by Europeans the Indians in the lower stage of barbarism (all those living east of the Mississippi) carried on cultivation (on a small scale) in gar- dens. Maize, perhaps also pumpkins, melons and some vege- tables were raised. A very essential part of their sustenance was produced in this manner. They lived in wooden houses, 23 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. and their villages were fortified. The tribes of the North- West, especially those of the region along the Colombia river, were still in the higher stage of savagery, ignorant of pottery, and the cultivation of plants. But the so-called Pueblo Indians in New Mexico, the Mexi- cans, Central Americans, and Peruvians were in the middle stage of barbarism. They lived in fortlike houses of adobe, or stone, cultivated maize: and other plants in artificially irri- gated gardens, and even kept a few tame animals-the Mexi- cans had domesticated the turkey and other birds, and the Peruvians the llama. They were familiar with the use of metals, iron excepted, but still retained stone weapons and implements. Their conquest by the Spaniards cut short all further independent development. In the East or Old World the middle stage of barbarism began with the taming of milk and meat-producing animals, while the cultivation of plants seems to have remained un- known far into this period. The taming and raising of ani- mals, and the forming of large herds seem to have caused a se'paration of Aryans and Semites from the rest of the bar- barians. In suitable localities this led to a nomadic life, and the search for pasture land. The Semites wandered about the grassy plains of the Euphrates and Tigris, and the Aryans in the plains of India, the Oxus, Jaxartes, Don and Dnieper, de- serting the forests that had been the homes of their ancestors. Their superior development may have been due in part to a copious milk and meat diet. At anyrate, cannibalism grad- ually disappeared during this stage, and the pairing family generally became more fixed in form and approached the monogamous family of a later date. 3. The higher stage of barbarism began with the melting of iron ore, and merged into the period of civilisation by the invention of letter script, and the use of written records. This higher stage of barbarism is richer in improvements and in production, than all the preceding stages put together. It is the stage of the Greek heroes, the Italians before the foun- dation of Rome, the Germans of Tacitus, and the Norsemen of the Viking age. Here first we have the iron-pointed plough- share drawn by animals and agriculture on a large scale resulting in a practically unlimited increase in the production of food, and, as consequence, the clearing of forests and their transformation into arable and pasture lands. Naturally these improvements led to a more rapid in- crease in population and to its higher concentration. There was a general improvement in tools, and inventions multi- plied: the bellows, the hand-mill, the potter's wheel, the :fashioning of metals, the waggon, the chariot, shipbuilding with 24 THE HISTORY OF INDUSTRY. beams and planks, the beginnings of artistic architecture, the pstablishment of towns surrounded by walls, with turrets and attlements, are all attributable to the higher stage of bar- barism. We may sum up the epochs as follows, giving possible or probable dates for the most advanced peoples: Savagery.-B.C. 100,000 to B.C. 40,000, period 60,000 years, the time during which there was merely an appropriation of natural products, and tools and weapons were chiefly invented for that purpose. Barbarism--B.C. 40,000 to B.C. 3000, period 37,000 years, the time during which natural productions were cultivated, and wild animals tamed and bred for the use of man; new tools and inventions being chiefly directed to purposes of agri- culture. Civilisation.--B.C. 3000 years to date, the time during which the raw materials of nature were manufactured, and machines for that purpose were invented. It may well be that this groping into the dim past contains somewhat of error; in what follows we are on surer ground. The social and in- dustrial history of mankind has not the character of an un- broken series, but each society apparently began with the gen- tile or kin system of organisation. If we continue with our own. civilisation when we were what the Romans called barbar- ians, the whole historical development of industry is illustrated, beginning with the gentes and ending with the capitalist sys- tem of our own time. When the Romans first came into contact with our bar- barian forefathers, they found them to be in the early stages of the village community form of organisation. The gentile sys- tem had broken down and passed away. Of the communities of villeins on French estates in early times Sir Henry Maine, in his "Early History of Institutions," writes: Now that the explanation has once been given, there can be no doubt that these associations were not really voluntary partnerships, but groups of kinsmen; not, however, so often organised on the ordin- ary type of the village-community as on that of the house-community, which has recently been examined in Dalmatia and Croatia. Each of them was what the Hindus call a joint-individual family, a collection of assumed descendants from a common ancestor, preserving a com- mon hearth and common meals during several generations. The gentile system may in some cases have passed gradually into the village-community and the village- community have gradually assumed the special characteristics of the feudal manorial system; or, in other cases, the growth of property, the intrusion of strangers, dispersion resulting from war, the pressure of a concentrated population on local 25 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. resources may have hastened a disintegration which finally resulted in separate and independent patriarchal families. With a wide territory to roam over there was at first no hindrance to the multiplication of such families or to their pos- session of large flocks of sheep and herds of cattle, but once again, as population increased, and as agriculture became of greater relative importance, these wandering units became fixed and entered into a new form of integration-the village community. Thus a union founded on property and territory took the place of a union founded on kin. As a rule the new communities consisted of men and of common descent, children of an original patriarch-like the children of Israel-but the coalescence of less nearly related families was not uncommon, and there was room even for strangers. Mutual aid in agri- culture and in resisting aggression had at length bound ad- jacent families into one community, and ultimately led to the manorial form of village community, as it existed in Britain at the time of the Roman conquest. The Britons at that time had already entered the higher stage of barbarism, and society was based on monogamy. No inconsiderable skill in weaving, metal-working, pottery and enamelling had been attained. Tin and lead mines had existed in Cornwall for a long time, but extraction and working of iron ore, as in the Severn Valley, was a recent development. On the rivers coracles of basket-work and hides still served, but overseas, as to Ireland, the native craft were flat-bottomed boats of oak secured by iron spikes with high bow and stern, and furnished with sails of hides. Although Julius Caesar first landed in B.C. 55 the real work of conquest began in A.D. 43 under Claudius, and was not completed until 89. Rome wanted corn, and so British land was allotted to Roman soldier-settlers, under whom the old inhabitants were employed to cultivate the soil they once had owned themselves. Under Roman demand a great increase in wheat production took place, and encouragement was given to various rudimentary industries. Further, the organisation of society in those parts of the country occupied by the Romans was broken up, and the inhabitants carried almost at a bound from barbarism into the earlier stages of civilisation. The Romans frankly regarded the conquered province as existing for their own benefit alone, and did not hesitate to expropriate and exploit the native population, very much as at a later date England, if less frankly, exploited, and still largely ex- ploits, India. During the first century of Roman occupation the Britons learned much from the Romans, but paid for their gain by the 26 THE HISTORY OF INDUSTRY. loss of self-respect and initiative. These qualities they had not regained, when, long after Rome had withdrawn her hand, they became in turn an easy spoil for the ruder but more vigorous Saxons, although in those parts of the country which had not been occupied by the Romans they put up a good fight. Wave after wave of conquest, not only by Saxons but by Danes, drove the Britons still to the West, and largely submerged their new-found civilisation. From the resultant 'confusion and intermingling of races there gradually emerged something of system of the feudal type. Individual cultiva- tors, families or groups of families, fell into the power, or sought the protection, of some military chief who, in return, exacted tribute either in kind or in service. Thus over the country there sprang up more or less isolated communities inder the protection of military chiefs. This was the state of England at the time of the Norman Conquest in A.D. 1066. The manors into which William found the country divided he distributed amongst his own followers. The principal sufferers were the Saxon thegns; to the bulk of the people it was no more than a change of masters. The manor consisted of the stronghold or castle of the lord (at a later date this had grown into a walled and fortified town), and round it nestled the ville consisting of the houses of cultivators and artisans; beyond the ville stretched the manor lands, strips of cultivation alternating with fallow and girt with an outer ring of common and waste up to the border of the forest. There was no enclosure of any kind, so that it was necessary, to prevent destruction of crops, that all livestock be herded. Originally, according to some historians, land was held in common, but with division of labour the problem arose of the just division of its products. If the artisan was to claim his products as his own, it was obviously but fair that the cultivator be allowed to do the like. To retain common own- ership of land, and yet permit individual or family occupation with private possession of its products, was a difficulty which arose definitely then, and has still to receive a satisfactory solution. In some regions of Europe, it is believed, the first attempt made at a solution involved the division of the land into portions for individual occupation, allowing each cultiva- tor to retain as his own the products of his allotment. From individual ownership of products to individual* ownership of land was a simple step; but as land varied in fertility it was parcelled into strips, and as each cultivator received portions of relatively good, bad and indifferent soil his holding was scat- tered about in different parts of the manor or township. This *At first the land vested in the family rather than the individual and was worked, by a mutual interchange of labor, by the whole community. 27 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. was the general Teutonic practice, even before the English came to Britain, and the lord's land was, not exempt from it: Pas- tures, common, and waste were, however, still held in com- mon. At the head of the manor still stood the lord who held his little world in fee. As he had gained his position so he re- tained it,--by force of arms,-later by force of law, as he and his kind made it. Supported by his squires and soldiery, and in case of need by other inhabitants of the manor, he de- fended the little community from outside aggression, exacting in return tribute in service and in kind. As a rule, each lord held more than one manor, and farmed out those in which he did not reside; thus first arose the large farmer. At the head of his subjects stood the socmen, or free tenants,-free in the sense that they paid in kind only and were exempt from ser- vice. The socmen were comparatively a small body, the bulk of the population of the manor being villeins. These latter were praedial serfs, bound to the soil, and to service upon it, and unable to leave the manor; they could not, e.g., marry a daugh- ter' or sell an ox, without the lord's consent, a consent which meant in effect a fine; for in those days exploitation was naked and unashamed. Below the villein was the cottar who pos- sessed only a few acres of land, and depended mainly on 'wages' for a living (paid chiefly in kind). At the bottom of all were the slaves, whose duties were mainly those of menial service. From time to time the artisan class was recruited from among the socmen or those of the villeins who, ambi- tious to rise, had by arrangement been able to commute per- sonal service into a payment to the lord, at first in kind, later in money. This payment was in effect a rent-quit rent it was called, as by it the villein was 'quit' of further service in person. Here then we have, it is important to note, the definite beginning of what is familiar to us as rent. Here, too, we may note, not the first, but the greatest, and the most important differentiation. Hitherto, each family had been, industrially, almost a self-contained unit; it supplied itself, almost entirely, with the tools it used, the food it ate, and the clothes it wore. It grew its own corn, ground it into flour, and made its own bread; it reared its own sheep, shore them, and manufactured the wool into its own clothing. It made for its own use. Even the towns and villages were associations of such self-contained families, but there was mutual help. Each family contri- buted animals to form a ploughing team, and combined with others to carry out work on each other's allotments. Now, some families and some individuals, from various causes, became divorced from the soil, and became artisan- 28 THE HISTORY OF INDUSTRY. merchants. They made exclusively for sale and not for their own use; but there was, at first, no speculative making for a market; they made to order only and were paid in goods. The artisans made tools for the agriculturists, and were paid in wheat and mutton, or later, when money came into general use (it was used exclusively for foreign trade at first), in money. This differentiation was perfecly natural: it is a part of the evolutionary process. Holders of land who became more expert as artisans than as farmers, or whose holding was too small to provide a living, sought to devote themselves exclus- ively to trade. Tied as they were to the soil, their only re- source was a commutation payment to the lord; and such payments were a valued source of income to the lord, who was able to supplement it by a further levy for a 'right to trade.' Thus the unhappy cultivator had to buy both a right to his own time and a right to trade, and these not only from his immediate overload, but from the King as well. The latter collected his tribute at first through the lords of the manors as his agents, but afterwards, or in addition, by special officers. In view of this situation the artisans, bound by community of interest, formed a guild. (If this was called a merchants' guild, as it was, it must be remembered that at first there was little or no distinction between an artisan and a merchant; the same man who made sold the goods; only as industry evolved there was differentiation, and making and selling fell into separate hands). Such a guild would, acting for all, arrange, if pos- sible, by an annual payment or by a lump sum for the right to the whole of their time for all its members. Similarly they would arrange for the right to trade, or, in other words, for open markets for their goods. This payment was made some- times to the lord, sometimes to the King, sometimes to both; and if the matter was arranged the town became free. When the right to trade was purchased it was on the understanding that it conferred an exclusive right of trade, and it was a function of the guild to preserve this privilege, resisting inter- lopers. Want of money, however, sometimes induced the King to re-sell the privilege to aliens; these formed their own or- ganisation, which was called a craft guild. The mere accident of the existence of an alien craft guild and a native merchant guild need not detain us; it is the guild system as a whole that demands our attention. The guild was the first great industrial differentiation if by 'industry' we mean both agriculture and manufacture; in the gentile system they were combined; in the earlier village-communities they were combined, but in the English manor, at the point we have now reached, they, for the first time, became separated. The 29 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. development of manufacture forged ahead, agriculture lagged behind. This dislocation causes much confusion in industrial his- tory; each branch of industry (agriculture and manufacture) must henceforth be considered separately. The guild was an association of artisan-merchants; the guild bound its members together; it was a great integra- tion; it regulated production, prescribing quality, weight, size and the price of goods. The guildsman as a member of his guild had a voice in fixing the regulations under which he worked; he was an honourable man who thought that shoddy work dishonoured his guild, nor had he any incentive to pro- duie shoddy work; he was not dependent on competition or the law of 'supply and demand.' His prices were fixed, and goods were made 'to order.' Compare his position with that of the smart business man of to-day, who lives on his wits, who is cunning, admittedly selfish, almost a trickster, to whom no trick is too shady if legal-or not likely to be found out! The guildsman held a dignified position, he worked in his own home, assisted by apprentices-their nunber and terms of apprenticeship were fixed by the guild-who expected in due course to become 'Masters' themselves; that is, they ex- pected to become merchants as well as artisans. Before considering the later developments of the guild system we must return to the man on the land. The process of deserting country for town had, as we have seen, begun when smaller holders secured release from labor- rents and became artisans, emigrating, in most cases, to the towns. The lands they vacated fell to the lord of the manor, and accumulation began. The process was greatly accentuated by what is a veritable landmark in English history, the black death,* which raged throughout the country from August, 1348, until the autumn of 1349, and carried off from one-third to one- half of the population. The effect was immediate. Wages rose 30, in some cases 200 per cent.; women who had worked for one penny a day demanded and received threepence. Small holders in increasing numbers threw up their holdings and became free labourers, tramping the country for work at the highest wages they could exact. The whole agricultural system broke down, and the lords of the manors were at their wits' end; their men had slipped away, whither none knew. The situa- tion was beyond measure difficult. As landlords exclusively constituted Parliament, the first remedy proposed was the restoration of the old rate of wage. This being passed was made, in intention, effective by enact- * The black death, however, was not confined to England. 30 THE HISTORY OF INDUSTRY. i4g that refusal to work be punishable by imprisonment. It was made illegal for workmen to leave their work; if they did leave they were declared outlaws. The notorious Statutes of Laborers were countered by the Peasants' Revolt, which however, was crushed by force. Unable to obtain labour for agriculture, landlords substi- tuted sheep-farming as requiring far less labour. Also they began to enclose their lands. The open-field system of hus- bandry had left England practically hedgeless; the lord might have his own demesne enclosed, but it was largely intermingled with strips of land held by villeins. In the lord's eyes land held by;villeins really belonged to him; the villein merely oc- cupied and paid rent. Actually such land did continually tend to pass to the lord's demesne, as when the villein died without heir; as, too, on a death, the lord could always refuse a new grant or make it intolerable to the new tenant by imposing too heavy a fine of entry, land constantly escheated to him. Again common and waste, used time out of mind for depasturing alike by lord and tenant, was, as especially suited for sheep, greedily enclosed. The enclosure of common land was, in fact, direct robbery. Many small holders, never able to live solely from their own land, had eked out a subsistence by part-time work on the lord's land. This privilege was now denied them, and they were consequently compelled to abandon their own too small allotments. The process went on for one hundred and fifty years; and, as :a-matter of history, the final result was>that the greater portion of the soil of England passed out of the hands of small holders and into those of comparatively few landlords. The expropriated men, deprived of one of the chief instruments of production, were thrown on the labour market. Though the Black Death was doubtless the immediate occasion of the change in England, it was not the cause. For that we must look deeper; for throughout Europe similar results followed as the feudal system broke up and passed away. All industrial history is marked by a constant improve- ment in the technical method of production, resulting in better or cheaper goods. Field-enclosure made possible improve- ments in agriculture; associated labour increased production by introducing specialisation; just as later, under Capitalism, the factory system improved production by machinery, 'prime- movers,' and large-scale manufacture. Yet with every improvement in method whole classes suf- fered; the few benefited, the many lost. Why, one may ask, did,. the many submit to their loss? And the answer must be: largely from an instinct, or inherited intuition, such as makes 31 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. the mother sacrifice herself for the sake of her child, the patriot die for his country, the individual suffer for the race. To neglect this impulse, very real as it is, and to found economics on a purely selfish basis, is the current, and somewhat absurd, mistake of most writers on economics, from Adam Smith down. The dull, if not stupid, acquiescence of the many, impelled by an irrational instinct, thus co-operates with the selfishness of the few to produce the one result. A remarkable instance of this,-of which by the way Marx reminds us,-is to be found in the story of the Scottish clans. Each clan owned the land on which it was settled: the clan's representative, its chief, was titular owner, in no fuller sense than the King of England is owner, titular owner, of the soil of England. On their own authority these chiefs transformed the nominal into an actual ownership: a King of England might as well claim the right to drive his subjects into the sea. A certain Duchess of Sutherland expelled her 'tenantry' (!) assigned them in lieu somne 6000 acres of the seashore,-2 acres to a family,-and magnanimously charged them no more than 2/6 per acre rent for this waste. Meantime she had divided the whole of the stolen clan land into 29 great sheep farms, supporting only 29 families and those chiefly Southerners. As for the clan it lived by fishing, finding a home half on land and half on water, and, frankly, gaining but half a livelihood from both. But the clan was to expiate even more bitterly the fault into which the inherited, romantic, instinct of loyalty to their chief had led them. In the smell of the fish which rose to the nostrils of the castle-folk there was a scent of profit -the seashore was let to the fishmongers of London: and the clansmen, a second time hunted from their own, were left to sell all they had, their labour-power, to Glasgow capitalists. Not content even now the 'owner' of the soil, self-styled as he was, turned his sheep-walks into deerforest, which offered a greater rate of income. The sheep followed the men into exile, and their place was taken by the 'things of the wild.' One may walk from the Earl of Dalhousie's estate in Forfarshire to John o' Groats without leaving forest land. Here now roam free the fox, the wild-cat, the marten, and the Alpine hare and 'the lesser wild'-rabbit, squirrel and rat-have found a sure home. The whole of this forest land is unproductive: it might just as well have been sunk under the waters of the German Ocean, so far as production is concerned: but it pays a high rent, drawn from the rich idler who in his turn has sweated it out of his 'workers.' How came it then that the Highlander tamely submitted to this tyranny? Implicit obedience had for generations been essential to the very existence of the clan the instinct per- 32 THE HISTORY OF INDUSTRY. sisted, the -Chief ordered, the clan obeyed, without thought of the future ruin. By instinct they unconsciously assisted the progress of industrial evolution; by reason man may yet con- sciously assist in his own industrial development. The- Black Death had merely accelerated the always inevit- able transition to better methods of production. Enclosure was not :wholly an evil. Following their lords' example the soemen, who had remained in the main cultivators, enclosed n; t only their own but as much also of adjoining land as they could get, and thus were able greatly to increase their output of -wheat by improved methods which only enclosure had rendered possible. In fact every change in method has qua production been an advance: it is a failure only qua distribu- tion. The combined effect of the changes which followed the Black Death entirely destroyed the Manorial System. The 'free' men found that they were unable to enter the 'ring' formed by the Guilds, and equally unable to get work as farm- laborers, from the holders of land which had now become, largely, sheep-runs. To borrow a modern expression, the 'labor-market was flooded,' and many were reduced to beg- gary. The position.. of a beggar was most cruel-branded as a felon, whipped and even executed; he was thrown aside as less -profitable than sheep. Contemporary feeling is ex- pressed in the following lines: "Sheep have eat up our meadows and our downes, Our-corn, our wood, whole villages and towns. Yea, they have eat up many wealthy men Beside widowes and orphan childeren: Besides our statutes and our iron laws Which they "have swallowed down into their maws: Till now I thought the proverb did but jeste Which said a black sheep was a biting beast." The enclosure movement began to slacken. The new sheep farms soon became sufficient to meet the demand for wool: labor was less difficult to get and the too rapid increase in enclosure had aroused general alarm which took effect in legis- lation designed to check it and encourage arable farming. Townsend-Warner sums up: The time of the enclosures, like all times of rapid displacement of labor, implied much distress, but this distress was mitigated by the ease with which laborers whose land had been taken from them found occupation in the woollen industries. The mitigation was, however, only temporary: unemploy- ment became chronic. Much land had been enclosed: about three-fifths were still unenclosed. It is to be remembered too that enclosure from the 13th century onwards involved no small expense. It required a C 33 34 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. private Act of Parliament which was beyond the means of the small farmer, and became still more so when, in the 17th century, he began to suffer in pocket from another cause. Hitherto he had been able to augment his income by some form of domestic industry, spinning or weaving, in which members of his family could assist. With the advent of the factory system this source of income was cut off. The result was that under the combined effects of cost of enclosure and decay of domestic manufacture he sank more and more into the position of an agricultural labourer or migrated to the towns. Only the large farmer with more knowledge and more money was left. (Peasant revolts in the 16th century marked agrarian revolution, just as machinery riots of the 18th century marked the revolution in manufacturing.) During all this time changes had been taking place in the guild system. The artisan-merchant had developed into an artisan and a merchant. The craft-guild, no longer an alien institution, had become the corporate representative of the artisan, as had the merchants' guild of the merchant. In the fourteenth century, the trades, crafts, or misteries were very definitely marked off from each other. The cobbler was very emphatic- ally required to stick to his last; he was not allowed to make shoes, and the shoemaker was not allowed to cobble them. . The making of a saddle involved not less than four separate crafts. . Speciali- sation was enforced in order to ensure efficiency; the workman was required to do one thing and do it well, lest he should endeavour to do many things and do them all badly. But the position was arrived at only by degrees. At the end of the eleventh century this division of labour was still in its early stages.* With the differentiation of artisan-merchant into artisan and merchant the guild system, pure and simple, began to break up, passing by an intermediate stage, known as the domestic system, into Capitalism. Under the domestic system the Master Craftsman still worked at home-hence the name of the system--but he no longer sold his wares to the consumer, or made them only to order: a market, as we understand the word, had come into being. From the reign of Edward III. the progress of industry had been rapid. Not only did trade increase in volume but it increased on a new system. Under this there were still masters who worked at home, took apprentices, and employed a journeyman or two, but these were no longer members of a guild: they did not work under guild regula- tions or sell at guild prices. In fact they were no longer merchants; they no longer sold to the consumer at all, but to a middleman, a clothier, who put out the wool to be broken and combed, received it again and sent it on to the carders and spinners, and receiving the yarn from them, passed it on to the weaver and fuller and dyer in *Innea' "England's Industrial Development." THE HISTORY OF INDUSTRY. turn. Thus the clothier was the central figure of the new system: he employed combers, carders, spinners, weavers, fullers, dyers and paid them for their work: the product was his, and he undertook the task of selling the finished goods: on him fell the risks of the market. The artisans had no longer to judge what they should make, nor had they to trouble to find a market for their wares: but they worked at what the clothier sent them and were paid by the piece at a regular price which would be common all over the district. This is a clear statement of the domestic system and of the beginnings of the factory system, the clothier representing the employer, the artisans the employees, but with an impor- tant difference: for the employees of the clothier, so far as they were, in however small a way, employers, owned the capital as represented by tools and work room: it was only their employees who, owning neither land nor tools, were in the position of the modern working man. The clothier controlled the policy of industry: the product was his. We shall see that further development in production eliminated the small master and concentrated capital in the hands of the clothier or em- ployer, driving the workmen into the factory. (At a later date, further development differentiated employers into own- ers of factories, concrete capital, and owners of money credit, money capital, and enabled the latter, as bankers, largely to control the policy of industry). The change from the piecework of the domestic system, in which the pieceworkers owned their tools and worked at home, to the capitalist system, under which men worked in a factory owned by their employer, constitutes what is known as 'the industrial revolution.' Simple production for use, i.e., hand-to-mouth production by means of simple tools, passed with the earliest specialization into simple production for exchange at guild prices and guild standards of quality and workmanship. As specialization increased the individual was restricted-not merely to the making of one article-but to the production of a single part of one article. The co-operation of many individuals became necessary to produce a complete commodity. This further specialization proved incompatible with the guild sys- tem and caused it to break up, but a form of transition,-the domestic system,-intervened between the earlier guild and the later factory systems. The essential feature of the guilds was regulation by authority:! but the domestic system meant not only increased specialization but, to some extent, the re- placement of local regulation by free competition. Piece- workers were able to compete against each other for employ- ment, and employers, by reducing the price of their goods, were able to compete against each other for trade. Work however was still, largely, carried on in the workman's own 35 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. home: it was not necessary for an employer to have a factory, and indeed a 'factory' still meant a trading depot, not a place of manufacture. Trade was more or less free and trading companies were numerous. The art of company-promotion was, even then, well understood so that Defoe's account written in 1697, allowing for a certain quaintness of diction, reads surprisingly modern. There are, and that too many, fair pretences of fine discoveries, new inventions, engines and I know not what, which being advanced in notion, and talked up to great things to be performed when such and such sums shall be advanced and such and such engines are made, have raised the fancies of credulous people to such a height that merely on the shadow of expectation they have formed companies, chose com- mittees, appointed officers, shares and books, raised great stock, and cried up an empty notion to that degree that people have been betrayed to part with their money for shares in a New-Nothing: and when the inventors have carried on the jest till they have sold all their own interest they leave the cloud to vanish of itself, and the poor purchasers to quarrel with one another and go to law about settlements, trans- ferrings, and some bone or other thrown among 'em by the subtilty of the author to lay the blame of miscarriage upon themselves. So I have seen shares in joint-stocks, patents, engines, and undertakings blown up by, the air of great words and the name of some man of credit concerned, to �100 for a 500th part or share, some more, and at last dwindle away till it has been stock-jobbed down to �12, �10, �9, or �8 a share, and at last no buyer: that is in short the fine new word for Nothing-worth and many families ruined by the purchase. If I should name linen manufactures, salt-petre works, copper mines, diving engines, and the like for instances of this, I should do no wrong to truth, or to some persons too visibly guilty. At certain times no scheme is too crazy. In 1825 men were found to subscribe to a company which was to "drain the Red Sea in order to recover the gold lost by the Egyptians when pursuing the Israelites." S The age of the domestic system was essentially one of trade expansion. In 1600 the great East India Company was formed: in 1719 its rival the South Sea Bubble burst. The accumulation of gold was thought to increase national power and trade to be the means of its acquisition: yet to trade, unless indeed we seize by force the riches of India or Peru, we must have something to give in exchange. The prosaic task of wealth-production did not, however, appeal to the adven- turous spirit of the age whose busy bees were all afire to steal their neighbours' honey. It was the age of buccaneers. Yet production retained its simple form, and was carried on in the homes of the workers with appliances,-the spinning wheel and hand-loom,--which had been in use for centuries. The advent of machinery and the factory system com- pleted, as we have said, the industrial revolution, and the transformation of the hand-worker into a proletarian. The 36 THE HISTORY OF INDUSTRY. history of the revolution is in the main the history of mechani- cal invention. Its first landmark is the invention of the flying shuttle by Kay in 1733: which completely upset the balance between spinners and weavers: already hard pressed the former could no longer keep pace with the latter. The balance was more than redressed however in 1764 when Har- graves patented his spinning-jenny : and Arkwright followed with an improvement on the jenny. His machine,-it was spinning by rollers,-being driven by water, was known as the water-frame. Finally Crompton combined jenny and frame in his "muslin-wheel" or, as it has been generally known since, mule. rThese machines introduced a new factor, of first import- ance, "power." As the power used was at that time water there came into being the "beckside" mills of Lancashire and York- shire which, situated in romantic glens at the foot of waterfalls, became veritable Houses of Lamentation, Temples of Moloch, slaughter-houses where calico was dyed red in the blood of little children. A new and more rapid development followed when steam replaced, water. Already in 1781 Boulton writing to Watt could say "the people in Manchester are all steam-mad." Within twenty years the new power was in general use: its adoption made effective Cartwright's power-loom (invented in 1785). And now invention crowded on invention. Cart- wright produced a machine for wool-combing: Bell followed with cylinder-printing of calico: Heathcote devised machinery for making lace, Murray for heckling and spinning flax: and Gott adapted cotton machinery to use in the woollen industry. These inventions caused an enormous increase in production and a corresponding fall in prices: they also caused the con- centration of factories in towns where the coal-supply was cheap, and so led ultimately to the evils of a congested popu- lation. There had been meantime a similar expansion in other industries. Even in the 17th century Dudley had experimented with coal for smelting iron. Now the steam-engine and mechanical blower supplied a better blast: smelting made a rapid development, the output of iron increased enormously, and all industries dependent upon -iron advanced with a like rapidity. If production increased enormously there was an equal decline in the condition of the workers, the proletarians. Pre- viously deprived of land they now found themselves deprived also of their only capital, the tools of their trade. Certainly they put up a stiff fight, but flesh and blood could not long compete with machinery: the hand-loom passed, and they were 37 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. bound hand and foot to the steam-driven looms of the capital- ist. The loom set the pace: and the evils of "speeding-up" began. To describe the poverty of the workers, their blind rage against the machines, their smashing of the looms, is a thankless task. A glimpse or two at their subsequent condi- tion will suffice. Thus Dr. Embleton in 1865: The rooms in which labourers in many cases live are situated in confined and unwholesome courts and yards, and for space, light, air and cleanliness are models of insufficiency and insalubrity, and a dis- grace to any civilised community: in them men, women and children lie at night huddled together: and as, in regard to the men, the night- shift succeeds the day-shift and the day-shift the night-shift in un- broken series for some time together, the beds have scarcely time to cool: the whole house is badly provided with water and worse with privies, dirty, unventilated and pestiferous. And the "Standard" of April 5th, 1866: A frightful spectacle was to be seen yesterday in one part of the metropolis. Although the unemployed thousands of the East End did not parade their black flags en masse, the human torrent was imposing enough. Let us remember these people suffer. They are dying of hunger. That is the simple and terrible fact. There are 40,000 of them. In our presence, in one quarter of this wonderful metropolis are packed,--next door to the most enormous accumulation of wealth the world ever saw,--cheek by jowl with this, 40,000 helpless starving people. These thousands are now breaking in Upon the others' quar- ters: always half-starving, they cry their misery in our ears, they cry to heaven, they tell us from their miserable dwellings that it is impossible for them to find work and useless for them to beg. Again Mr. Charlton, County Magistrate, 14th January, 1860: Children of nine and ten years are dragged from their squalid beds at two, three, and four o'clock in the morning and compelled to work for a bare subsistence until ten, eleven, or twelve at night, their faces whitening, and their humanity absolutely sinking into a stone-like tor- por, utterly horrible to contemplate. Such were the fruits of the economic philosophy of the time: avowedly based on selfishness, preaching free competi- tion, free trade, free contract, it condemned these little ones,-- in the sacred name of freedom,--to a living death. But the "cry of the children" arose to the ears and touched the hearts of men like Robert Owen and Lord Ashley, men who should be held in everlasting remembrance for their humanity. An employer himself Owen was able to demonstrate that profit need not be synonymous with cruelty. It must not be supposed that these cruelties were confined to England. Sismondi, the French economist, writing in 1818, says: "At this period I was keenly interested in the commer- cial crises which Europe had experienced during the past years and in the cruel sufferings of the factory hands, which I myself had witnessed in Italy, Switzerland and France, and which 38 THE HISTORY OF INDUSTRY. according to public reports were at least equally bad in England, Belgium and Germany." Capitalism in full flower produced these horrors, as un- restricted Capitalism does even to this day: witness the cruel working conditions of the wretched native cotton operatives of India, and the atrocities practised on the collectors of wild rubber in the Congo and on the Amazon,-matters whispered about or buried under a conspiracy of silence. Consider, e.g., the existing system of peonage in Latin-America worked by American, British, German and other foreign capital. The victim, usually a native but sometimes a white or half-breed, incurs a debt to the planter or merchant, and by the Latin-American law of debtor and creditor which knows no Truck Acts, becomes in effect, his slave until the debt is paid off. It never is paid off: the planter keeps the books. Under this transparent fiction of debt slaves are bought and sold, villages broken up, peasant landowners reduced to the level of serfs, and tribes carried off to distant scenes of oppres- sion. Children are bought and sold and young women driven into cornm - mercial prostitution. To-day (May, 1914) British capital is migrating to Russia. It finances a Siberian gold mine: and presently we read that the workers, who had revolted against the intolerable conditions, have been shot down literally by the hundred. To-morrow capital will be building factories in China, and the worst evils of our own nascent industrial era will be repeated under incomparably worse conditions If the general condition of the English wage-slave of to-day is better than it was in 1860,-and it certainly is,-- itJs only because Factory Acts have interfered with "freedom of contract," it is only because trade unionism has abolished 'free' labor. 39 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. III. The Evolution of Industry. Social research must be based upon a sane analysis of the all-round development of the best of mankind up to the present moment. The Historical Spirit consists in the due appreciation of the successive stages of human development as reflected in a succession of historical facts.-Comte. Whatever may be the causes of evolution-and we do not attempt to deal with them here-there can be no doubt that the path of the ascending phases of evolution along which a living species passes is marked by two pronounced character- istics: (1) an increasing integration or oneness of the whole accompanied by (2) an increasing differentiation or specializa- tion of the parts of that whole. The first makes for a more distinct individuality, for an increasing independence of others, yet at the same time for an increasing dependence of the whole on its parts. The second-differentiation--makes for complexity in the individual by separating out and multiplying the number of its organs whose functions become more and more specialized. Thus, one might say, from being a jack-of-all-trades an organ becomes a master-of-one. And that is true not only of an individual man, but of the various organs of industrial society. To take an illustration from the political sphere:---The cutting off of parts of New South Wales to form-first Vic- toria and then Queensland-although it seemed to be disinteg- ration was, in reality, a differentiation within the British Empire. At a later date the federation of Australian States seemed to be a return to the former condition of union, but differentiation into separate States remained: federation was only a higher integration, and both differentiation and integ- ration were continuous. There exist in Australia, at the present moment, two move- ments-one towards a closer union between the States, the other towards a further subdivision of the present States into smaller States: and within each State the delegation of power to local bodies and municipalities. And so of property in land (or capital). The old gentile or tribal ownership will never return. Private ownership of land is no doubt a necessary stage in evolution-a higher differentiation. It is justified, as Marx says, because it is a transient necessity. But the revival in a higher form of the communal ownership of land and the development therewith of some form of Socialism, although apparently a backward step, will in reality be a continued advance in integration, a 40 THE EVOLUTION OF INDUSTRY. return in plan, but at a higher elevation. The student of economic history must carefully distinguish between differ- entiation and disintegration. If then the development of private property in land and the other means of production is really an historical necessity, or, in other words, a necessary phase in the development of the social organism, neither Russia, nor any other nation, can overleap that phase and jump from what was in effect a feudal system, straight into the arms of Socialism. The Russian revolution so far as the peasants (who constitute some, eighty or ninety per cent. of the population) are concerned has merely advanced the evolutionary phase of private owner- ship. Nor is it clear how far manufacture can outrun agricul- ture in its development, or whether it is possible for manufac- tures to be socialised while agriculture remains ii the domestic stage, and has not even become capitalised. The time element produces confusion; yet history clearly shows us that every people has passed along the same course of development. It shows us, moreover, that different stages of development in different industries of the same people are reached at different times. Agriculture for example lags behind manufacture, and instances of the capitalistic system, the domestic system and even some relics of a family com- munism co-exist even in the most industrially advanced nations. This time-displacement makes a connected presentation of the subject'r difficult. It is not sufficient to consider industrial evolution in one nation or society. only; we are compelled, if our narrative is to be continuous, to confine ourselves to one industry in one nation. But, indeed, that is impossible because higher developments transcenhd the bounds of any one nation: the beginnings of an iintegration transcending national limits already exist. If then we make time our standard of reference we are compelled to jump from one nation to another. Yet advanced nations have one and all passed along the same course and followed the same path. The gentile system of group marriage and all it involves was world-wide, in essence, if not in. detail. It was practically universal. When Bachofen first drew attention to the maternal family in his epoch-making work, and Morgan described the clan-organisation,-- both concurring as to the almost general extension of these forms and maintaining that the marriage laws lie at the Very basis of the con- secutive steps of human evolution, they were accused of exaggeration. However, the most careful researches prosecuted since;, by a phalanx of students of ancient law, have proved that races of mankind bear traces of-having passed through similar stages of development of mar- riage laws, such as we now see in force among certain savages. See 41 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. the works of Post, Dargun, Kovalevsky, Lubbock, and their numerous folowers: Lippert, Mucke, etc.* As a system of industry the gens was an enlarged family communism with a common house, single hearth, common meals and a democratic rule with common ownership by the gens of all' its, gear. Commencing in savagery and continuing through barbarism, it remained until civilisation had commenced. . . . The Grecian gens, phratry and tribe, the Roman gens, curia and tribe find their analogues in the gens, phratry and tribe of the American aborigines. In like manner the Irish sept, the Scottish clan, the phrara of the Albanians, and the Sanskrit ganas are the same as the American Indian gens, which has already been called a clan. Gens, genos, and ganas (in Latin, Greek and Sanskrit) have alike the primary significance of Kin.t For a clear demonstration of the practical universality of group marriage the reader is referred to Lewis Morgan's "Ancient Society," its demonstration here need not then delay us. But not only the gens system but the village-community (which in many cases developed into a feudal system) was world wide and practically universal (in essence if not in detail). Sir Henry Maine tells us that: If very general language were employed the description of the Teutonic or Scandinavian village communities might actually serve as a description of the same institution in India.$ Says Kropotkin: We do not know one single human race, or one single nation that has not had its period of village-communities. . . . It prevailed in England during both the Saxon and Norman times . it was, at the bottom of the social organisation of old Scotland, old Ireland, and old Wales.... .It survived the Roman rule in Italy .... It was the rule with the Scandinavians, the Slavonians, the Finns. Elphinstone has described it among the Afghans.. . . It existed in Abyssinia, the Soudan, in -the interior of Africa, with the natives of both Americas, with all the small .and large "ribes of the Pacific archi- pelagoes . . . This fact alone disposes of the theory according to which the village-community in Europe would have been a servile growth. It is anterior to serfdom, and even servile submission was powerless to break it. It was a universal phase of evolution. This fact has not long been recognised; thus Professor Ashley writing in 1892 says: One gets up from reading these notes� with quite an uncanny feel- ing. We had known in a vague sort of way that there had been what was loosely called a 'feudal system' in Japan; and M. de Laveleye and other writers had prepared us for finding something that could be brought under the equally vague designation of a 'village-community.' But we were certainly not prepared to find that in most essential points mediaeval society in Japan was the exact counterpart of that in *Kropotkin's '"Mutual Aid," p. 85. tLewis Morgan's "Ancient Society." t"Villagse Communities," p. 107. �Notes by D. B. Simmons on the Land Tenure of Old Japan. 42 THE EVOLUTION OF INDUSTRY. Europe; that the development was apparently parallel not only in character but also in time..... It is as startling as if we had come upon our 'doubles.' That the domestic system and Capitalism are, or have been, world-wide is a matter of history. Thus amid some diversity, disguised in time and place, we discover the same great laws of evolution producing every- where similar effects :-the gentile system-the village com- munity or feudal manor,--the guild system-the domestic system and Capitalism. "History repeats itself" is a common saying, and the idea is illustrated by the swinging pendulum, but history never repeats itself. There is a return to a similar phase, but other- wise the position is quite different. Hegel, in his philosophy of history, goes nearer the mark. First a thesis, then anti-thesis, then synthesis. But the anti- thesis is not, as with Hegel, a schism between subjective and -objective, between mind and matter, Spirit and Nature: but between particular and general, between individual and State, between class and community. (With Hegel the reader will recognise the immense importance of the growth of conscious- ness in man-not only self-knowledge but a knowledge of his relation to other men and to nature.) The history of industry shows us that one system is followed by another. In every thesis, or integration, differentiation takes place, and when this progressive differentiation has reached a certain point-the thesis, integration, system-call it what you will-becomes too small, too narrow to contain, in harmony, all its parts, conflict, anti-thesis, class war, ensues, until the old integration is broken up and replaced by a higher, a larger, and a wider synthesis, integration, or system. The lower form of industry passes away entirely or leaves as relics some weak or rudimentary organs. These crises occur in the development, not only of societies, but of individual organisms, the chicken breaks its shell-the tadpole becomes a frog-the chrysalis, a butterfly. Individual species, De Vries tells us, pass through alternate periods of stability and transformation-although insensible variation is continually taking place; but when the period of mutability occurs new forms spring forth with unexpected suddenness. "All facts point to the conclusion that these periods of stability and mutability alternate more or less regularly with one an- other."* Whether this is true or not of species, industrial history shows us that it is true of industry; that after compara- tively long periods, during which a given system of industry has existed, a cumulative internal friction between the parts, *Hugo De Vries' "Species and Varieties: Their Origin by Mutation," p. 639. 43 FROMT CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. or classes, caused by advancing specialisation, results in a comparatively rapid and radical -change- a new and 'higher' form of industry taking the place of a worn-out system. The gentile system is dead-the manorial system is dead- the guild system is dead-of the domestic system there. remain but-enfeebled or rudimentary organs-the capitalist system in turn will- die. The -idea is illustrated by what we have called the spiral of -progress. - vto INTERNATIONAL SOC/AL/SM r NATIONAL SPECIALIZATION 54,te eyziafton - - - ---/300. ,-- - - - -NTIONAL GUILD- SOCAL/15 S CAPITALISM AD /600-1870 (Pr/vofle �nerproe) 401130.1510 TRA0E5) GUILD SYS TEA Demwe*System (L!/D)NEW PASTORAISM A40/350 -1560 fnchsed pamtm, 40.700-1200 /v4A'ORIAL SYSThI PA STORAL PAM/LIES l8/. C eCommn0hd Q ~(Pa~/riarchaI) N C /0.000 6� ENTLE SYSTEM:// herscA 11t w4 ? t!A AND(RING IILNT'RS &-FISHERS 8-c-50000 FIRE DISCOVERED (C) B C 80000 -T~~ionAmd/i o ~IS ulr (b) LIC/00 000 RVDOTWENTnRY SPEECH EESTU R� A, O VNItS a 6 MA'N OF PILTDOI$' AW I(LI TYPE (a) B C 300000 THE SPIRAL OF PROCRESS. Fig.:I 44 THE EVOLUTION OF INDUSTRY. The early dates* shown on the diagram are little better than mere guesswork, and indeed who is able to determine the time when man became man and ceased to be what-if he ap- peared to-day would be called an ape ? There is, however, some reason to believe that B.C. 300,000 should read B.C. 500,000 at least. Indeed the most recent method of determining the age of rocks, and consequently the age of the fossils they contain, viz., by the rate of transformation of uranium into uranium lead, indicates that man is probably 1,000,000 years old. If then we view the course of industrial history from above-in plan looking down-the cirele appears to close or nearly to close-history seems to repeat itself, but the elevation is quite different: the altitude is much greater. Industrial evolution is seen to be a continuous but irregular advance both towards a higher integration and a higher differ- entiation. At one time the forces of integration prevail and progress is chiefly towards a wider and higher solidarity and larger union; at another time the forces of differentiation prevail and progress is chiefly towards specialisation and more pronounced individualism. When the whole is large enough to contain all its parts harmony exists. This harmony is mechanical, but not only mechanical. It is organic also. From the mechanical stand- point, never passed by some people, it may be compared to the simplest machine-an ordinary bolt. A complete bolt con- sists of a shank uniting two heads. The shank holds together whatever lies between the heads, provided the heads-parts of the bolt-are connected to the shank. That is, provided the parts form an harmonious whole. If one or both heads are removable they are called nuts. The bolt is then no longer homogeneous. Its parts have become differentiated. The ends (or one end) of the shank carry helical threads which fit into corresponding grooves in the nuts. So long as this is the case, so long as the relation of nut and screw is harmonious, so long as they are of the same pitch, the end sought is attained. But if the nut does not fit the screw-if the pitch is different- there is discord between the parts and the whole is ineffective or useless. But society. is not merely a mechanical arrangement of parts. To be efficient, harmoniously to serve the end of social life there must be not only mechanical harmony but organic harmony, because society is not only a machine, it is also an organic growth, a phenomenon of life, not merely a mechanical collection of individuals-an industrial army, not a mob. Man is, what he is, because he is a part of a social whole. *Later dates show the dislocation between agriculture and manufacture, the latter advancing the more rapidly. 45 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. More clearly to illustrate the truth we must, then, take the ease of an organism, something that grows. Take a rose bush: the purpose of the perfume of the rose, its colored petals, and the nectar it contains, is to attract a bee, or other insect, so that pollen may be conveyed from stamen to ovary and the rose be fertilised. When this has been accomplished the petal has done its work, it is no longer of any use. For so long thereafter as it continues to live and draw nourishment from the plant it is a mere parasite-like the landlord and capitalist. If it is able to fasten itself on to the plant it becomes an element of discord sapping the plant's vigor and life and retarding the development of the seed. So it is with systems of industry. The landlord and the capitalist may still be ornamental, but they are no longer of any use. They have in fact become harmful. The gentile system founded on ties of blood relationship was broken up by a growing differentiation of its individual parts and gave place to the village-community, of which we have studied one form, viz., the feudal manor. Differentiation still persisted. The manor, integration, or cell contained within its walls both agriculture and manufacture conjoined, but now the cell subdivided, agriculture and manufacture drifted apart and no integration has as yet united them again- to the despair of Marx and all Socialists. Following the course of manufacture we find it integrated in the guilds, beginning to be disintegrated by a progressive differentiation in what is called the domestic system until gradually, with the growth of invention and power-machinery, it passed into the compara- tive chaos of Capitalism. Already we discern the signs of a new integration. Thus in accordance with the laws of evolution industry grew, and it could only grow out of pre-existing con- ditions; each development rested on a previous development: it was a cumulative unfolding life process in which the neces- sary conditions had to be present before further growth could take place, and growth, as we know, is gradual, it can only to a slight extent be forced. But although specialisation within the individual consti- tutes a higher form of individual life, yet, we may note in pass- ing, that the specialisation of individuals necessary to form a higher society, or industry, may have a crippling effect on the individual. If we are accustomed (says Comte) to deplore the spectacle among the artisan class, of a workman occupied during his whole life in nothing else but making pin's heads, we may find something quite as lamentable, in the intellectual class, in the exclusive employment of a human brain in resolving equations or classifying insects.... It occa- sions a miserable indifference about the general course of human affairs, as long as there are equations to solve or pins to manufacture. 46 THE EVOLUTION OF INDUSTRY. Even Darwin felt the crippling effect of specialisation. Thus, with characteristic modesty, he speaks of himself: A man with a mind more highly organised or better constituted than mine would not, I suppose, have suffered, and if I had to live my life again I would make a rule to read some poetry and listen t some music once a week, for perhaps the parts of my brain now atro- phied would thus have been kept active through use. The loss of these tastes is a loss of happiness, and may possibly be injurious to the intellect, and more probably to the moral character, by enfeebling the emotional part of our nature. Only by reducing 'working time' can the deleterious effect of the specialisation of the individual be avoided. The life of society, however, is not limited by the life of individual men, but individual men and societies have alike risen, as by stepping-stones on the dead bodies of their pre- decessors, and both advances imply a concomitant development of mind. Brain development is necessary to co-ordinate the various sense impressions, to combine the evidence of the senses both past and present-to draw conclusions, in fact, to reason. Man has probably evolved from a physically weak form of gregarious ape-like animal, because association is necessary to produce the brain development required to enable cunning and combination to overcome brute force. When once combination actually exists, it grows into a habit, and habit from a blind instinct grows into an idea, and the idea reacts on and helps to change conditions. One early form of combination-the gentile system founded on kinship persisted for centuries into historic times. The facts broke in upon the system before the new ideas, which were disguised as long as possible. Thus adoption-fictitious kinship-occasion- ally brought in the stranger. Improvements in the art of hut- building and in the conditions which made permanent homes possible, probably had much to do, in many races, with the conventionalising of individual marriage, so that an economic fact insensibly introduced a new social condition. The idea of private property did not at first exist, it had to grow. This idea was slowly formed in the human mind, remaining nascent and feeble through immense periods of time. Springing into life in savagery, it required all the experience of this period, and of the subsequent period of barbarism to develop the germ, and to prepare the human brain for the acceptance of its controlling influence. Its dominance as a passion over all other passions marks the commencement of civilisation. It not only led mankind to overcome the obstacles which delayed civil- isation, but to establish political society on the basis of territory and of property. Presents given to savages have been found abandoned in the woods: their indifference to property is in marked con- 47 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. trast with the avid greed of the modern man. For the savage use is the only claim to a transient possession. The progressive growth of the idea of property is illustrated by the appearance of testamentary dispositions established by Solon. This right was certain, of ultimate adoption; but it required time and experi- ence for its ultimate development. Plutarch remarks that 'Solon ac- quired celebrity by his law in relation to testaments which before that were not allowed; but the property and homestead must remain in the gens. When he permitted a person to devise his own property to anyone he pleased in case he had no children, he honored friendship, more than kindred, and made property the rightful possession of the owner.'* But before the idea of property was formed, the idea of kinship :existed, and on this idea the gentile system was founded. That system was at length broken up because, with the growth of new ideas and a self-asserting individualism, it became too narrow. For absolute strangers there was no room --for individual property there was no room-for individual marriage there was no room. Thus by the introduction of elements the gentile system was unable to absorb, the old inte- gration was strained to the breaking point and ultimately broke. The higher differentiation compelled a higher integra- tion, as it generally does. The disintegration of the gentile system gave rise, in many cases,: to wandering families of pastoralists of the patriarchal type. Individual property replaced common ownership, poly- gamy replaced group marriage, and, when these families settled down, agriculture largely replaced pastoral pursuits. Thus a new integration, the village-community, arose, a specific form of which, namely, the English manorial system, has been described briefly in our historical retrospect. Up to this point social and industrial development had proceeded hand in hand: now, agriculture began to be left behind by the rapid advance of manufacture. The effect of this differentiation was not only to break up the manorial sys- tem but to cut society in two: a town party and a country party have existed ever since. In agriculture the new pastor- alism, i.e., enclosed pasture for sheep, took the place of the open commons: in manufacture the guilds arose. Between the guild system and Capitalism there was inter- posed a state of transition known as the domestic system. Out of the domestic system there grew, as we have seen, Capitalism. Out of Capitalism is growing a new order; we have ventured into the realms of prophecy and termed it guild socialism. The curve of progress is swinging in the direction of a higher integration, the idea of unity still persists, "it flows still even now, and it seeks its way to find out a new *Morgan's "Ancient Society." 48 THE EVOLUTION OF INDUSTRY. expression which would not be the state, nor the medieval city, nor the village community of the barbarians, nor the savage clan, but would proceed from all of them, and yet be superior to them in its wider and more deeply humane conceptions.* Hitherto the growth of industrial society has been almost as independent of man's conscious action as is the growth of his body. In society the organ of consciousness resides in each of its individual parts, and although the action of each part may have been consciously directed to some limited end, yet remoter results, the cumulative effect of all individual actions on industry as a whole, was quite unforeseen. Thus uncon- sciously Capitalism emerged. "They builded better (or worse) than they knew." At last, with the growth of knowledge and development of mind,t man may consciously change his indus- trial system; to enable him to do that, with safety, he must understand the capitalist system and know why there is discord between its various industrial organs or classes. The first step is to understand the meaning and function of money. *Kropotkin's "Mutual Aid," p. 222. fiindeed; as Wallace pointed out, Darwin concurring, the present evolution of man consists chiefly in mental development, or, from the physical standpoint, in brain development. D 49 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. IV. Money. "Money makes the world go round"-or, at least, it circu- lates commodities, purchases services, commands respect. Without money the modern man is lost, with money-plenty of money-he is almost as a king. Money oils the wheels of commerce, increases the efficiency of exchange, and obviates the exasperating delays of barter. It is the world's dominant commodity. It casts a halo round the meanest man, and lights up with adventitious beauty the homeliest woman. It epi- tomizes a multitude of desires and realises a host of blessings. It is at once both a blessing and a curse. Yet the witchery of money must not blind us, as it has blinded so many others, to the real nature of this magic substance. Money has been described as "that which passes freely from hand to hand throughout the community in final dis- charge of debts and full payment for commodities, being accepted equally without reference to the character or credit of the person who offers it and without the intention of the person who received it to consume it, or enjoy it, or apply it to any other use than in turn to tender it to others in discharge of debts or payment for commodities." This description of what money is and what service money renders may fairly be abbreviated into such a definition as Walker gives :-"The term 'money' is applied to any commodity whatever its sub- stance or its form, which, whether by law or by convention, becomes the common medium of exchange in any community." Or as Irving Fisher has it :-"What is generally acceptable in exchange for goods." Two points need, in this connection, to 50 be emphasised. Gold, or any other form of money, though a commodity devoted to a special purpose, exchange, remains always itself a commodity. And secondly though it may be of great convenience it is not essential to exchange: for that can be, and for ages was, effected by barter alone. The earliest exchanges, it is probable, took place between groups or tribes rather than between individuals, and at first assumed the form of mutual presents. It is instructive to see trade in its lowest form among such tribes as the Australians. The tough greenstone valuable for making hatchets is carried hundreds of miles by natives, who receive from other tribes in return the prized products of their districts, such as red ochre to paint their bodies with; they have even got so far as to let peaceful traders pass unharmed through tribes at war, so that trains of youths might be met, each lad with a slab of sandstone on his head to be carried to his distant home, and shaped into a seed-crusher. When strangers visit a tribe they are received at a friendly gathering, and presents are given on both sides. No doubt there is a tacit understand- ing that the gifts are to be more or less fair exchange, and if either side is not satisfied there will be grumbling, but in this roughest kind of barter we do not find that clear notion of a unit of value which is the great step in trading. Giving of gifts becomes barter. Barter, growing keen, de- velops a conception of value: Of two articles exchanged one, the more durable, becomes the measure of this value. A third commodity, more durable still and more easily carried, measures the value of both. It passes where the bulkier, more perishable cannot. It is the medium of exchange. It is the standard of value. It is the means of deferred purchase or payment. It is money. When geus, family or tribe, was isolated and self- sufficient, there was no need for exchange (and therefore no need for money): clothing, food, and shelter belonged to the group and were distributed according to group-needs and group-custom. But isolation, if indeed it ever was, did not persist. Group neighboured group, and intercourse de- veloped. Group differed from group, and sought or made different goods. Group as against group possessed its own, had, in effect, property. Novelty awoke desire and group sought the property of group. The necessity for exchange had arisen, Differentiation went on apace. New goods, new forms of clothing, new tools and utensils came into use, strengthening the idea of property, communal and private, and increasing the desire for exchange. A detailed history of primitive ex- change is not possible after the lapse of ages, nor is it neces- sary. It is sufficient to illustrate the rise of a standard and measure of value and ultimately of money. A tribe whose MONEY. 51 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. staple diet was fish had food in plentiful and constant supply but insufficient means of covering. Contact with a tribe of hunters brought them skins in exchange for their fish. As skins were more durable, values came to be expressed in them. Become thus a measure of value they would pass to a third tribe as money, purchasing for the fishermen some primitive form of farinaceous food it may be, or a superior fibre for their lines and nets. Accepted by three tribes as a measure of value skins are now not only a desired commodity but a currency and medium of exchange. Almost endless is the variety of such media of exchange or commodity ihoneys, amongst different people and in dif- ferent stages of their development. In agricultural com- munities the purpose has been served by corn in ancient Greece (and even in modern Norway), by rice in Asia Minor, rock-salt in Abyssinia, black tea in Russia, dates in North Africa, cocoanuts in Central America. In other primitive communities currency has consisted of dried cod fish, pieces of cotton cloth, straw mats, cubes of beeswax, red feathers, whale's teeth, iron shovels, and hand-made nails. Leather was long current in Russia and in the Levant. The moneys of North America during the early days of the first settlers were sufficiently numerous to be tabulated by Del Mar in eleven classes- amongst them lignite, coal, ivory and bone money, gold, silver and copper coins, mica, pieces of lead, shells, pearls, agate, jasper, and beaver and marten skins. The early Euro- pean settlers in North America paid their debts in wheat, oats, barley, peas, bacon, pork, beef, fish, flax, wool, whisky, and even musket balls. Most of these articles are evidently quite unsuited for use as money, not only from their varying value, which is a characteristic of all commodities (not excluding gold), but from their bulky or perishable nature, the impossibility of dividing some of them without loss, and their varying weight or quality. The qualities required in commodity-money are port- ability, stability of value, uniformity, divisability, durability, and cognisability. These qualities are found combined in certain non-rusting metals, amongst which gold and silver, by common consent, have been generally recognised as most suitable for use as currency. All these commodities which have served (as they might serve again) as 'money' have something in common which makes them valuable. That something cannot be their service as money alone for it has been seen (1) that almost any commodity may be used as money and (2) that money is a 52 MONEY. 53 convenience only and not a necessity. If there were no money these commodities would still have a value and the same value. Money, in other words, is a commodity selected con- ventionally (not, as it might seem, arbitrarily) as a medium of exchange, and its value has the same basis as that of any other commodity. The term "money" has cast over the com- modity which serves that purpose a veil of mystery. This veil, which effectively obscures its true value, we may then tear away, and having done so may hope to discover that 'something' which makes this commodity, as it makes all commodities, valuable. We pass on then to consider what is the true nature of value. FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. V. Value. Though the question of value lies at the heart of the problem of economics, yet there is no part of the sabject in which greater confusion reigns, and has reigned. Writers on economics have-doubtless with the best intentions-added to the confusion by overworking the hyphen in some instances and by not consistently retaining it in others. They talk glibly of intrinsic-value, exchange-value, market-value, to say nothing of true-, scarcity-, and monopoly-value. That they are honestly seeking for clarity of thought may readily be conceded, as also that the multiplication of terms is a true indication of the complexity of the problem. And yet J. S. Mill had the self-assurance to say, "Happily there is nothing in the laws of value which remains for the present or any future writer to clear up: the theory of the subject is com- plete." One is reminded of Boehm-Bawerk's pretentious "Karl Marx and the Close of his System." It is easy enough for us to smile at hasty judgments by previous writers, but the fact remains: the laws of value are still unsettled and obscure. The words of Ricardo still stand true: "There is no source from which have flowed so many errors, and out of which have sprung so many diverse opinions in this science as from the vague and indefinite sense attached to the word 'value.' There are in effect many 'values'; of these we emphasise three. It may be said that a certain medicine is 'valuable': and the meaning is that it is effica- (ious, but not necessarily costly. Quinine is a 'valuable' medi- cine because, irrespective of its cost, it is useful-efficacious- in the treatment of disease; and it is in a similar sense that we speak of water and air as 'valuable.' Equally, but from a differing standpoint, hand-made lace, an in-laid table, are 54 'valuable'; where the meaning is that either article is the product of intense human effort. This meaning of 'value' is probably not so generally recognised. And yet it must be patent to everyone who has in act or thought made anything, it matters not what it is, that so soon as you have put forth effort, whatever direction that effort takes, you are sensible that a 'virtue' has gone out of you and you are conscious that, let the market say what it will, you have created a 'value.' For that is the meaning of the word. And thirdly, an Old Master is valuable; but less because it confers great pleasure, is useful, or the result of intense human effort, than because we can get a large sum of money in exchange for it. These three values are distinguished as (1) use-value, (2; intrinsic-value, and (3) exchange-value. The hyphen re- maine indispensable: for to use the term 'value' of any or all indifferently produces endless confusion. As some precon- ceptions have gathered round the word 'intrinsic' we shall adopt an entirely new term-inherent-and speak of (1) use- value, (2) inherent-value and (3) exchange-value. Most writers on economics mean by value the third of these or exchange-value: a variable quantity only to be ascer- tained, at any given place or time, by the "higgling of the market." Yet, even in a breath, they tell us also that an article may be sold above or below its 'true' value. This true- value-what is it? It cannot be identical with, since it may be greater or less than, exchange-value. Nor can it be use- value: for the usefulness of an article does not determine its exchange-value, otherwise air and water would have a greater exchange-value than diamonds. The phrase of the economist confesses a consciousness that there is something inherent in the article, apart from, independent of, the vagaries of the market. If markets, and by consequence exchange-value, did not exist, yet, it is felt, there is in the article that which, with- outreference to its usefulness, though usefulness is in a com- modity a sine qua non-is constant and gives it this 'true- value.' To this, whatever its nature, we give the name inherent- value. We shall endeavour further to show that inherent- value consists of human effort-of brain and muscle-as it is embodied in a utility or service: and that it is of such stuff that exchange-value is made. Our attitude to exchange-value forbids a definition of our own: we must adopt the meaning assigned to it by other economists. Though definitions are numerous they in the main agree with that of Professor Mar- shall who says: "Exchange-value is the amount of that second thing which can be got there and then in exchange for the first." Exchange-value is then the amount or quantity of the VALUE. 55 56 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. thing or things-with all they contain and are-which we accept in exchange for some other thing we give. Something determines what quantity shall be given-what is that some- thing ? Now by definition inherent-value means-is-labor-cost. We propose to show the 'something' in exchange-value is also labor-cost-not that inherent and exchange values are iden- tical, far from it, but that they are of the same kind. Broadly speaking writers on economics are divided into two schools-.on the question of value. The Jevons-Austrian school holds that value is subjective, that it has no objective reality, or, alternatively, that our subjective appreciation of value is the real or true value. The classical school, of which Marx was a descendant, held that value is an objective reality, and he and others maintain that the efficient cause of value is human effort or labor. To appreciate these divergent views it is essential that we should agree upon the meaning of 'subjective' and 'objective.' Suppose for example that I run my head against a stone wall, raising a lump on my forehead, it is said that I do not know that the wall exists, at best I only 'believe' it. The collision caused a shock to my brain, set the brain matter in move- ment, and "what I am pleased to call my mind" took note there- of. If I identify myself and my mind, I am told by meta- physicians that all that I 'know' is what I experience, and by physiological psychologists that all I experience is certain brain movements. I do not 'know' that the object-in this case the stone wall-really exists at all-the very lump on my forehead may be all imagination: probably Christian Scientists would tell me that it was. If, thinking to settle the matter, I again run my head against the wall and again experience similar results, still I am told, that is no proof of the objective existence of the wall: I may be eccentric, peculiar, abnormal. If in the interests of science my friends agree to repeat the experiment in their own persons, and meet the like result, that is all the proof we can offer of the objective existence of the wall-and for most people it will probably be sufficient. It is true, if we have not investigated farther, we 'know' only one aspect or quality of the wall. To attain complete knowledge the wall must be examined from every side, its constituents analysed, and that not by ourselves alone, but by others. But failure to see does not destroy ob- jective reality. One man may say that a red flag is grey: to him it is grey, because he is colour-blind. Aristotle knew nothing of X-rays or the long waves of radio-telegraphy: they are none the less objective realities. If, however, value is objective it has equally a subjective counterpart. They--objective and subjective--form a world of the same struc- ture as the phenomenal world. . . . In short every proposition having a communicable significance must be true of both worlds or of neither: the only difference must lie in just that essence of individuality which eludes words and baffles description, but which for that very reason is irrelevant to science.* Assuming then that we are agreed on what is meant by subjective and objective in regard to value, we may return to the more immediate question "what is value?" And we are more directly concerned, as is by now apparent, to show that exchange-value, though of the same kind as, is not identical with inherent-value. In plain fact exchange-value in a com- modity is the inherent-value contained in the other commodity, that commtodity for which the first is exchanged. To shorten the discussion we may with advantage quote from T. Veblen's book--"The Place of Science in Modern Civilisation" (pp. 419-20) : It is scarcely worth while to question what serves as the beginning of wisdom in the current criticism of Marx, viz., that he offers no adequate proof of his labor-value theory.' It is even safe to go farther and say he offers no proof of it. The feint which occupies the opening paragraphs of "Das Kapital" and the corresponding passages of "Zur Kritik" is not to be taken seriously as an attempt to prove his position by ordinary recourse to argument. It is rather a self-satisfied superior's playful mystification of those readers (critics) whose limited powers do not allow them to see that his proposition is self-evident. Taken on the Neo-Hegelian ground and seen in the light of the general rmaterialistic conception, the proposition that value=labor-cost, is self-evident, not to say tautological. . ... The materialistic conception of history translates the unfolding life of the spirit of man into terms of the unfolding-material--life of man in society. Insofar as 'goods' are the products of industry they are the product of this unfolding life ,of man . . ... The life-process which when it takes the specific form of an expenditure of labor-power goes to produce 'goods,' is a process of material forces, the spiritual or mental features of the life-process and of labor being only its unsubstantial reflex. It is consequently only in the material changes wrought by this expenditure of labor- power that the metaphysical substance of life-labor-power-can be embodied; but in these changes of material fact it cannot but be em- bodied since these are the end to which it is directed. The balance between goods in respect of their magnitude as an out- put of human labor holds good indefeasibly in point of the meta- physical reality of the life process. . . . Such is the value of the goods in reality: they are equivalents of one another in the proportion in which they partake of this substantial quality, although their true equivalence may never come to an adequate expression in the trans- actions involved in the distribution of the goods. This real or true value of the goods is a fact of production and holds true under all systems and methods of production, whereas the exchange-value-the 'phenomenal' form of the real value-is a fact of distribution and ex- *Bertrand Russell's "Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy." 57 VALUE. FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. presses the real -value more or less. adequately according as the scheme of distribution in force at the time conforms more or less closaly to the equities given by production. In this able statement of the case Veblen clearly recog- nises and distinguishes between real or true value end its phenomenal form, exchange-value. Thus to sum up :--in the light of the materialistic, i.e., the economic, conception of history the proposition that value equals labor-cost is self-evident. Yet, strangely enough, there are those who accept the economic conception of history and still reject the labor. theory of value. Yet in the light of evolution the proposition "value equals labor-cost" is no less self-evident. For what is evolution but a "cumulative unfold- ing life-process," a becoming? The general philosophical standpoint has no doubt changed considerably since Marx's day, but Marx was ahead of his time and the standpoint of to-day does not materially differ from his. That Marx had outgrown Hegel we have already pointed out and he was more evolutionary in his attitude than Neo-Hegelian. Only with his fatalism have we any quarrel. The conception of the Universe as a toy train wound up "in the beginning" and placed on rails already laid and leading to a fore-ordained end, a train that cannot leave the rails but must inevitably reach the allotted goal, unless the original impulse fails and everything stops, is a mechanistic, fatalistic, teleological view that is neither orthodox science, orthodox philosophy nor orthodox ieligion. Insofar as Marx adopts the view that Socialism, in every particular case, is inevitable we disagree with him. Evolution shows us that although movement towards a higher form of life may take place it only does so when the species, consciously or unconsciously, adjust themselves to changing circumstances. Species have evolved: species have become extinct: nations have flourished: civilisations have decayed: the issue is largely in our own hands, it is not inevitable. There is "just that essence of individuality which eludes science." If, however, Marx means, as perhaps he does, that only for those nations who continue indefinitely t exist Socialism is inevitable, then we agree. Socialism is, we believe, a necessary phase of industrial evolu- tion, which will result from a conscious organisation of in- dustry--a conscious effort to maintain national life. And not only is conscious effort necessary to maintain social life, it is necessary to produce commodities-the very means of life. The effort to make is one with the effort to live, and that effort embodied in goods constitutes inherent- value. 58 From the standpoint of evolution the proposition "value is labor-cost" is-to repeat-self-evident. But if we are to know and understand value we must not forget that while it is certainly a reality, it is yet a complex reality. In other words it must be envisaged from many angles of view. In itself one, it has yet a multiplicity of facets. And here a simile may help to a better comprehension. We would then compare value to a shield, made of steel in form circular but dished, the inner side electro-plated with silver, the outer coated with gold-leaf: but unless a man has seen it in the making the composite con- struction is discoverable only on analysis. If, as a spectator, one examines it from a given standpoint and in a given light but with one eye closed, the appearance is that of a circular disc of silver, flat, and of two dimensions: if, however, opening both eyes and with no change of position but only of light he regards it again, he will see a disc circular still, and still of silver, but concave and of three dimensions. Suppose now he walks slowly round the shield, the vision constantly changes- now he sees a plain surface bounded by an ellipse-then it is dished-now the ellipse lengthens, as the apparent ratio of major to minor axis increases-yet again he sees or seems to see a plain gold surface bounded by a straight line and a circu- lar arc-now convex in two degrees-now bounded by an ellipse but convex in one degree,-and finally a full circular convex gold disc. Since the shield is symmetrical, he has only to proceed beyond this point to find that the several visions repeat themselves but in reverse order, for all the world as though instead of continuing his progress he had retraced his steps. With, however, this difference-that, returning, he is presented with the same, but progressing, with similar, appear- ances. It is with value as it is with the shield. Exchange-value is similar to, but not the same as, inherent-value,; both have many aspects. However useful the material of which the shield is made, it is its form which constitutes it a shield. So, too, it is the force that forms, and not the material formed, that constitutes inherent-value-the true gold of our quest. The silver of exchange-value is merely the distorted reflection of the gold of inherent-value. But one side of a shield cannot reflect the other, and so one shield must be reflected in another shield. The exchange-value of a commodity is seen not in that commodity itself, but in the inherent-value of the other com- modity-(taken in exchange). Thus,-suppose human effort standardised, and that we can say that a given article-as A, is equal to six hours-six standard hours of labor. Now let A be exchanged for B the result of 8 S.H.: then A has been sold-exchanged-above, and VALUE. 59 60 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. B below, its inherent-value. Granted:--but observe this simple, and equally important, result, which is most readily expressed in tabular form: Inherent-value. Exchange-value. A ........... 6 .. 8 B ......... 8 .. 6 14 14 Or, in other form, when exchange takes place the total inherent-value is always equal to the total exchange-value. Thus the "plus equals the minus" :-inherent values are both distorted in their reflected exchange values, but in opposite directions: and the equation remains. If, however, the total labor time has been equally distributed over both articles the tabular form would have been: Inherent-value. Exchange-value. A ........... 7 .. 7 B ........... 7 .. 7 14 14 Now by comparison of both tables we have,-in figure form,-the first law of value, which in words runs thus Commodities exchange, or tend to exchange, in the ratio of their inherent values. If in the latter table the 'law,'-whether by law we mean "invariable sequence under given conditions" or "the nearest approximation to the history of observed fact",-is clear at a glance, in the former it tends to be obscured as we look at either A or B seeing a part and not the whole of the trans- action. But if the first table is read as a whole the law is as obvious there as in the second. What then are the conditions under which this first law of value has full and unrestricted play? Such conditions, it may be confessed, have never actually existed: the law is the abstract statement to which facts make always a more or less close approximation. It is in short just such an assumption as science makes in regard to its fictions of a straight line, a perfect vacuum, the absence of weight or friction. Granting such to be real, says science, certain results follow provided all disturbing causes are removed, but science well knows that in actuality it is impossible entirely to remove each disturbing factor. But if it is not possible to attain an absolute corre- spondence, yet on the other hand there has been a close approxi- mation in the past and that for relatively long periods. This was the case during the age of simple production, when, while exchange was active and free, the ownership of land and raw VALUE. 61 materials and tools was distributed with approximate equality amongst the aggregate of the community. To make the law an exact statement of fact there must be free, and equal, access to all raw materials and forces of nature, equal technological knowledge, equal possession of tools, in short equality of con- trol over all means of production. Engels rightly says: Marx' law of value was generally valid economically from the beginning of the period which, through the medium of exchange, turned products into commodities, down to the 15th century of our era. As the exchange of commodities dates from a time anterior to all written records in Egypt to at least 2,500 and perhaps 5,000 years and in Baby- lon as far perhaps as 6,000 years B.C., the law of value has been in force for anything between 5,000 and 7,000 years. How then has it come about that the law no longer holds with equal precision, or at least no longer with equal corre- spondence to fact? We may listen to Marx' own exposition of the reason for the difference: The whole difficulty arises from the fact that commodities are not exchanged simply as commodities but as products of (masses of) capital which claim equal shares of the total amount of surplus value, if they are of equal magnitude, or shares proportional to their magnitude. And he adds later: The exchange of commodities at their values, or approximately at their values, requires a much lower stage of capitalist development than their exchange at their price of production. A great many people, even a number of professed econo- mists, freely criticise Marx' theory: few have taken the pains to read in original or translation the full text of his work. Veblen is more than justified when he comments: Marx' critics commonly identify the concept of 'value' with that of 'exchange-value' and then show that the theory of 'value' does not square with the facts of price under the existing system of distri- bution-piously hoping thereby to have defeated the Marxian doctrine, whereas of course for the most part they have not touched it. That which is really self-evident is not susceptible of logical proof: though one may, in a sense, make its self-evidence more obvious. It is so with the equation, Inherent-value = labor cost. Marx in his discussion confines himself to commodi- ties, which are not only things desired by man-not necessarily beneficial but desired, whether good or bad,-but also things made by man. (We keep to this restriction: speaking later of nature's 'free gifts.') Two commodities 'face' each other, 20 yards of linen and one coat. Suppose them to be of equal value (inherent-value). Value then is the common property or mea- sure of their equality. If they had not this-or some other common property-they would be incommensurable. One may say an apple is equal to a pear, where the meaning is, or may FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. be, in respect to weight, color, form, nourishing power-each or all of these. But when it is said that two commodities or parcels of commodities are equal, value and value alone is the 'middle term' in respect of which equality is predicated. Other qualities, geometrical, physical, chemical, are not common to all commodities. As Marx puts it-"their physical qualities only claim attention insofar as they affect their utility . . . they make them use-values." There is but one property common to all alike, human labor, which is value. It is at this point that Boehm-Bawerk breaks in with the question: But do not there remain a number of other qualities? As (1) have they not the common quality of being scarce in proportion to demand? (2) Is it not common to them to be the object of demand and supply? (3) to be appropriated? (4) to be natural products? (5) to cause expense to their producers? Why then should not the principle of value reside in any one of these qualities as well as in the quality of being the product of labor? One wonders if Boehm-Bawerk is wholly serious or are some of his questions purely dialectical ?* We will pay him the compliment of assuming that he is serious and answer them seriatim. But it is necessary first to remind the reader that while we are dealing with value as an objective reality, Boehm- Bawerk criticises from the subjective standpoint: and, really, argument between those who start from these diametrically opposed points of view is "as futile as a discussion of solids in terms of two dimensions.'" For the subjectivist, inherent-value does not exist and exchange-value is but a creature of the imagination. Even though the discussion be futile, we reply to Boehm-Bawerk's questions thus:- (1) Scarcity is not common to all commodities nor is it inherent in commodities but relative to the wants of man. Scarcity is of two kinds (a) natural, (b) artificial, and the latter is the stuff of which monopoly-values are made: both forms, however, seriously interfere with and obscure the opera- tion of the first law of value, and we will give them fuller consideration later. (2) Supply and demand are not inherent in commodities but relative to man, who makes supply and creates demand. No treatment of economies, however, can be complete without some reference to these Siamese twins. (3) All commodities are appropriated, but 'appropriation' is not a quality but an accident. (4) With natural products we shall deal immediately. *Boehm-Bawerk was undoubtedly able, but the fact that he accuses Marx of trickery prejudices the mind against him, and renders it difficult to believe whole-heartedly in his intellectual honesty. 62 (5) If the "expense they cause their owners" is the labor of their production then that common property is the very 'value' we are seeking to establish. We return as promised to the question of scarcity,-or monopoly-value. One of the reasons for a discrepancy, which admittedly exists, between the magnitudes of inherent and ex- change values in a commodity has already been pointed out in a quotation from Marx and will be further elucidated in ,a following chapter on Surplus Value. There remains that common stumbling-block to acceptance of the labor theory of value, natural utilities, i.e., products useful to man which, as completed by Nature, can contain little or no labor.*' Virgin soil is a typical natural utility. It contains no labor (or little), but admittedly can command in exchange commodities which do contain labor. The key to the enigma is to be found in the nature of monopoly. Suppose that I own the only spring of water in a desert. If I am not myself there and no one else is, the spring is of neither use nor value to me or any other man. But let there arrive in the desert certain travellers dying of thirst: their presence at once gives to the water of my spring an exchange-value: of its magnitude, the first law of value has nothing to say. If I have the resources of law and order at my back, I may demand and get whatever of money or other valuable the travellers possess, to the last farthing: and the amount is determined by their capacity to pay not by the intensity or quantity of their thirst. That is the law of supply and demand and it explains really nothing. If I own the well the contract is free, I demand "what the traffic will bear": the "court awards it and the law doth give it." But exactly what has become of 'economic' law? When suppliers 'own' the raw material of Nature the law of supply and demand, and more especially demand by the owner becomes a disturbing factor of the first magnitude. Yet even supply and demand has its limitations. In the case supposed it would be useless to demand more than the travellers possessed, or indeed to destroy my future market. My act was legal profiteering: but did I not save the travellers' lives? Or, another case:-bushrangers 'stick up' a coach, demand, and get, the travellers' money at the pistol's point. This is illegal -robbery under arms-yet did not the bushrangers spare the travellers' lives? The price paid for life is in either case a force value: we may call it a pistol value and whether it be as here purely physical, or as in modern industrialism economic, or as often half political half economic, does not alter its essential nature. *Land to have exchange value must be, or be made, accessible; to be sold it must have been surveyed, a plan made, and title deeds written. VALUE. 63 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. That is the position of unimproved land 'value': virgin soil has utility, crops may be grown on it, houses may be built upon it, but land has no inherent-value, it is not the result of labor, but the presence of those who must use it, and incidentally, can pay for it, gives it a pistol value which masquerades under the name of exchange-value. In the absence of population, land and pistols are equally useless as a means of acquiring wealth for their owners. If we agree that at present wealth is distributed strictly in accordance with the magnitude of the respective 'pulls' of the various classes of an industrial community--and it may be so--then economics is a science of brute force, or politics, or law, or of diplomacy, bluff and chicane, whatever the 'pull' may be. Indeed, the sciences of psychology, politics, ethics and economics are so closely bound together, that it is impossible wholly to separate them to-day. Greek philosophy recognising the fact frankly united them, so far at least as concerned the first three: economics in the modern sense had hardly come into being. This inter-relation and inter-action of the four sciences inevitably affects, not altogether favourably, com- mon thought and language, and that not less among pro- fessed leaders of opinion than among the average of the com- munity. Failure to recognise this fact is responsible for many judgments upon the labor theory of value. If we regard only purely economic grounds, the 'value' of natural utilities does not exist. Where "might is right," there is no other appeal to justice, and "necessity knows no law," economic or otherwise. The value of natural utilities lies, in fact, outside the tacit assumptions of political economy. Another of the stuffed lions in the path of truth, stand- ing between and separating inherent-from exchange-value goes under the name of 'scarcity.' Ricardo brackets it with labor as joint parent of value-a somewhat anaemic parent. Scarcity is not a thing, it is a relation-a relation between utilities on one hand and human needs on the other-in fact, scarcity is a mere negation. Such as it is, it is of two kinds, artificial and natural. With the latter we have just dealt and resolved it under private owne:ship iLto 'pistol' value. Artificial scarcity so- called is also of two kinds: firstly, it represents and stands for an excess of labor. Gold is relatively scarce-but there is no pistol-value in gold, because there are hundreds of gold mines-as presented by nature-which do not 'pay' to work. For example, if coal is required, it is easier to mine the coal 64 than mine the gold necessary to purchase the coal. Scarcity here means that to render the commodity less scarce would involve a greater expenditure in labor than we are prepared to give. Artificial scarcity properly so-called is due to the deliberate withholding of goods from the market, or deliberate refusal to manufacture them in order to secure a pistol-value. It was necessary briefly to discuss monopoly and scarcity value which might otherwise prove a stumbling block, but we return now to the main argument. There remain, therefore, only two objective realities worth further c onsideration, namely, utility (the material qualities that satisfy human wants) and labor (the means by which those qualities are made available): both, admittedly, are neces- sary to produce a commodity-as in the case of our shield, or in the case of (say) steam. The material basis of steam is water, but heat is its efficient cause. Steam is composed of water, but the efficient cause 'of steam is heat-both, however, are essential. The quantity of steam varies with the quantity of heat. Heat makes steam exactly as labor makes commodities. Steam is latent in water, just as commodities are latent in natural materials. Heat does not create steam out of nothing, nor does labor create commodities, but as heat produces steam from water, so labor produces commodities from the crude materials of nature. Essentially, steam is heat, the steam engine is a heat engine. In the same sense value is labor, and labor is the efficient cause and measure of wealth-but if man is its father, yet the earth is its mother. The analogy stands. We have likened inherent-value to force, but the force of human labor is not merely mechanical energy as measured in foot-pounds, nor is it merely vital force, but vital force applied with intelligence and technological knowledge and as we shall discover later-assisted by appliances handed down by the experience and wisdom of the ages. As a further argu- ment it will be shown that labor can be measured, but that utility has not been measured, and, so far as one can see, eannot be measured-socially at any rate. Unless a thing can be measured, not estimated, as equal to, or so much greater or less than, some similar thing, there can be no science. Value may be an abstraction-like mathe- matics*-but, nevertheless, it is an abstraction we can under- *Bertrand Russell has said of mathematics that it is "the subject in which we never know what we are talking about, nor whether what we are saying is true!" Given certain relations (which may or may not be true) between certain entities, x, y, and z (what they are does not concern the mathematician), then it can be said certain results folllow. Abstraction implies reality from which we have taken for exclusive consideration certain properties or aspects. E VALUE. 65 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. stand; but if we are to assign definite magnitudes to reality (or to some of its properties), we must be able to measure it. That value may be an abstraction is not fatal to mensuration -time is an abstraction but we can measure it. Since usefulness is entirely relative to man, and utility in its subjective sense means the satisfaction or pleasure given to man by the useful thing, we must-if we are to measure utility-measure the pleasure utility gives, or the pain its absence causes. To measure anything we must use a measuring rod and the things to be measured must be of the same kind. Our measure must be the common measure of them all, i.e., the things must be commensurable. If we measure length, we need a foot rule; if time-a clock; if water-a meter; if weight -a pair of scales. A clock will not measure length, nor a foot rule weight, the things to be measured must be of the same kind. Measures are divided into a number of units of equal length, so that zero on the scale corresponds to the be- ginning of the thing to be measured and some unit on the scale coincides with its end. Between the beginning and the end we count the units-minutes, inches, cubic feet, pounds, de- grees, hours of labour. All measurements are relative to our measuring machine. Clearly the most urgent and important thing-if we wish to measure-is to invent our measuring machine and our unit of measurement. Now it has been pro- posed to measure usefulness or utility, by the intensity of the individual's desire for the useful thing, just as a ther- mometer measures the intensity of heat. But that is not sufficient even if it were possible. If heat were the stuff of which utility is made, we must ascertain its quantity, not its intensity. A large warm body may contain more heat than a small hot body. So, a passing impulse may contain less desire than a persistent longing. But if we could measure the intensity of one man's desire (although that is not suffi- cient) how are we to determine whether his desire is greater or less than another man's desire for the same commodity, and how much greater or less-how discover our unit? "By the sacrifice he is willing to make," it has been suggested. But that only shifts the difficulty. How are we to measure his sacrifice? By the amount of gold, the number of sovereigns or dollars, he is prepared to part with to obtain the desired thing? No other method seems to have been suggested. But evidently the same quantity of gold does not measure an equal intensity (or quantity) of desire in different men-one may be rich, the other poor. The ground is continually shifting under our feet. Or, our subjective individualist may take 66 refuge in what he calls a social measure. From the individu- ality which eludes us, and is irrelevant to science, he may fall back for support on the general mind, and it may be asserted that in any given market the quantity of desire as indicated by the bids made and accepted measures the value of a commodity; in fact that a commodity is worth just what it will fetch. (It cannot be sacrificed!) In other words we are forced back to the higgling of the market. The supposed uniform price is a convenient fiction, as every country fair will prove. At practically the same moment similar com- modities have different values. Finally, with all said and done, it is exchange- and not inherent-value we have been hunting. "The wind bloweth where it listeth," but it is more easy to discover its laws, than it is for our subjective theorists to explain the laws of value; with them it seems to come just to this : value is our idea of value. How then are wve to measure ideas ? If our subjectivists have discovered anything it is merely a 'sufficient reason' and not an 'efficient cause. The theory of marginal utility is not concerned with movement of any kind, but solely with the adjustment of exchange-value to a certain given situation. It is entirely deductive and is based on doubtful premises---in fact it is not scientific, since it has no inductive basis. It assumes private ownership, free contract, natural rights, and the hedonistic calculus, i.e., the measurement of pleasure and pain: It is carefully explained that (say) the utility of water varies with the use to which we are able or compelled to put it. If we are dying of thirst, its utility is a maximum, but that utility falls as we are able, for example, to use it for cooking or washing or watering our gardens, and what we are prepared to pay for water, i.e., its exchange-value, varies correspondingly. That is perfectly true, and if we were deal- inig with exchange.value the argument is perfectly sound. (Even so, we can only say what it has sold for, not what it will sell for. The test of science is prevision.) But we are dealing with inherent-value. And in any case, it is doubtful if individual pleasure and pain can be measured, and it is certain that there is no common measure of 'social' pleasure or pain--if such a thing exists. Nor is it true that the end sought is always the pleasure given by the consumption of final goods. As Veblen says: The hedonistically presumed final purchase of consumable goods is habitually not contemplated in the pursuit of business enterprise. Business men habitually aspire to accumulate wealth in excess of the limits of all practicable consumption, and wealth so accumulated is not VALUE. 67 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. intended to be converted by a final transaction into consumable goods or sensations of consumption. The attempt to measure utility by measuring pleasure signally fails, the feat has never been performed, nor has anyone invented a measuring instrument or shown us how to use it; until that has been done we are justified in saying that utility cannot be measured. We have now to show that the labor contained in a com- modity can be measured. Viewed from the individual standpoint, and under the primitive conditions of simple production in which the first law of value is clearly seen, the individual man consults his own ease. If A wants a spade which he is able to make as easily as a hoe which his neighbour B wants, then B, who has a surplus spade, can easily arrange for A to make a hoe and exchange it for B's surplus spade. Clearly it is a matter of indifference to A whether he makes a hoe or a spade and to oblige his neighbour, he will readily agree to make the hoe. Then the first law of value holds in the equivalence of A's, effort in either case and by that effort we arrive at the equation:- 1 hoe = 1 spade in value. But as industrial conditions gradually grow more complicated, the measure of exchange-value ceases to be an individual evaluation and becomes a matter of social evaluation. The point of view is changed; we have advanced a step on our way round the shield. Society estimating the value of the labor- power of a worker considers only the intensity and kind of his activity, and the result of his activity, but is in no sense concerned whether that activity is a pleasure or a pain- whether the worker is sick or in good health-it asks for re- sults and by the nature of those results the labor-power of an individual is rated as equal to, or greater, or less in value than some given standard; and, if the standard of value has been taken as the average intensity of labor of a common laborer, then exactly how much greater. A skilled laborer's natural hour of labor may be equal to two hours of common labor, i.e., to two standard hours. And here it may be remarked that all labor is some com- bination of mental and physical exertion. There is, and can be, no such thing as purely mental and purely physical labor. It is common to speak of skilled and unskilled labor, but there is in reality no such thing as unskilled labor, skill of some sort-no matter how low-there must always be; the terms are merely relative. How, it may be asked, is this social evalution of individual labor to be made? 68 A rough evaluation exists at present, but the present rough method is far from satisfactory: not only in its relative but in its absolute determinations. The estimation in which different qualities of labor are held (says Ricardo). comes soon to be adjusted in the market with sufficient pre- cision for all practical purposes, and depends on the comparative skill of the laborer, and the intensity of the work performed. The scale once fixed is liable to little alteration. If a day's labor of a working jeweller be more valuable than a day's labor of a common laborer, it has long ago been adjusted and placed in its proper position in the scale of value. If then we assume the standard-hour to be an hour of mechanical work, or with Ricardo, as an hour of common labor, then, for example, the effort of the jeweller (to keep to R icardo's illustration) equals, for one hour of his time, two "standard-hours"-' '-his effort having been determined in the market as worth twice that of a common laborer. (It is obvious that-assdming this equation-we could just as well say that the jeweller's time-hour was "standard" and the common laborer 's working hour therefore amounted only to half a standard hour). Following this process into more detail we can posit an adjustment, sufficiently accurate for our pre- sent purpose, of all the main forms of labor. Thus we get at the number of standard-hours embodied in a given com- modity, or what is the same thing, at the 'labor' value or inherent-value, of that commodity. But observe that in doing so we are really fixing wages as long as we accept the prin- ciple that each form of effort should be paid its worth in standard-hours. By 'fixing wages' we do not mean that partial and restricted sense in which the phrase is commonly used; we mean the total payment by society to the individual for his services, whether that payment be in cash or in the form of rent, interest, dividends, or wages in the narrow sense, or in some indirect form, for example, museums, public parks, free educa- tion, pensions for sick or aged. In fact to 'fix wages' is, if the words are rightly understood, nothing more or less than to solve the prdblem of the distribution of wealth. It follows that we by no means concur in the decision of the market as at present constituted,-or as it was constituted in Ricardo's time,-any more than we concur in the decision of the judge in an Australian Arbitration Court. Our 'market' is something very different. In the market which we recog- nise there must be free competition-in the full sense of the words-and equality of opportunity for all. Everyone must be in the market-all alike must be hirers and hired. Under such conditions the wages of every form and variety of labor would be fixed by "supply and demand."' If the supply of some forms of labor was too great the 'wage' would be re- VALUE. 69 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. duced, if too small the 'wage' would be increased. In that manner we should arrive at what we should have good grounds for calling a fair wage; in that way we should get a true social evaluation. That method, depending on human judgment, may not be perfect, but if man is not to measure the relative worth of his own and his fellow man's work, who is to do so? To turn aside for a moment: it may be confessed that the market we consider competent to fix wages justly is at present an ideal. In the real market as it exists at present, Swages are largely fixed from above-not by the Deity-as some would have us believe, but by employers,* whereas we would have them fixed both by those above and by those below conjointly. Yet even the decisions of the existing partial tribunal are probably approximately correct, insofar at least as relative wages are concerned, and we must perforce accept these decisions for the present. The Panama Canal was con- structed by men, whose wages were fixed-from highest to lowest--from Colonel Goethals to the common laborer from above by an existing system of state evaluation. No one has suggested that Colonel Goethals did not earn his wage. He may have earned more, so may all who worked with him. If relative wages are justly fixed in the ratios 1:2:3, then 2/-, 4/- and 6/- is the just relation: but 3/-, 6/- and 9/- may be the just wage. That is a matter we have still to deal with. But to return: our measuring stick is not yet marked with its units of measurement. What unit should be adopted? The selection of a unit of measurement is purely a matter of con- venience, a mere convention. Practical considerations alone decide whether we use the metre or the yard, the degree Fahrenheit or the degree Centigrade. We select then the hour worked by the common laborer as the unit of measurement and call that hour the standard-hour. In that case when rela- tive wages have been fixed, only one absolute wage, the basic wage, has to be determined. Suppose for instance we consider only three forms of labor: common, skilled, and intellectual, and the ratio of these three forms is by social evaluation fixed as 1 is to 2 is to 3; suppose further the basic wage is 2/- per S.H.; then for one hour's work the common laborer receives 2/-, the skilled laborer (2 S.H. at 2/-) 4/-, and the intellectual laborer (3 S.H. at 2/-) 6/-. The payment evidently need *But not entirely. In some countries, as Australia, the judge of the .Arbitration Court fixes the basic wage it is true, but he also fixes the rates for many kinds of labor, and he does this after hearing evidence both from above and from below; that is, from both employer and employee. On the other hand, it is only the wage-earners in the ordinary sense of the word who are subject to the jurisdiction of the Court. The wage of the capitalist is the outcome of many economic forces, of forces rooted in force, as history shows us; but already there are indications that his wages are coming under the jurisdiction of a Court-the State-and his profits fixed, or at least limited. 70 not be in cash, it may be in standard hour notes: then a 1 S.H. note will exchange for 2/- or anything that is worth 2/- We conclude then: labor can be measured in standard-hours, and the number of S.H's. of work performed by the individual per natural hour can be determined by social evaluation. When we have succeeded by social evaluation in correctly placing every man's lalbor-power in its correct place in the scale of value it is still necessary, by a process of time-keeping, to ascertain how much labor-how many individual standard hour - each commodity contains. Even this operation is less simple than it appears. Under simple forms of production, the determination was easy because the individual made the utility from first to last and the tools used were simple and inexpensive, but under the modern complex method of produc- tion, it is not so. Of the total labor-power embodied in a com- modity, some is present labor, some is past labor, some is direct labor, some is indirect labor. Raw material and partly finished manufactures alike con- tain past labor; only the final operation which produces a "consumption" good is present labor. Again, both present and past labor may be direct or indirect-actual work in making the commodity, or work in making the tools and machinery used and in organising and directing the labor-force employed. If a machine has cost a thousand standard hours and during its "life" can only make 1000 articles, then in every article there is embodied 1 S.H. of past indirect labor. Now, although it is not easy, or at least requires system and care, yet it is quite possible to make these calculations:-- costs-clerks are doing it every day-only they do it with money instead of with standard hours. If then we have determined by social evaluation the value of each man's work and reduced natural hours of labor to individual standard hours, so that the common laborer's natural hour is one S.H. and the scientist's natural hour is per- haps 5 S.H.: if further, we have by a process of time-keeping and assessment by cost-clerks determined exactly how many individual S.H. a commodity contains, it may be thought that the problem is solved, and that the inherent-value of every commodity and every service is known. That would be a great mistake--the problem of value is not so simple. We have to take another step-to advance further round our shield and view it fromi another standpoint-the social standpoint, because the inherent-value of a commodity depends not only on the number of individual S.H. the whole of its parts contain, but on the number of social S.H. it contains. It is exactly at this point that many labor leaders fall into error. Not only must the sum total of individual standard hours past and present, VALUE. 71 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. direct and indirect be ascertained-they must be reduced to social standard hours. The work two men can do working together is not the same in amount as that done by the same two men working separately-it is greater. Merely to add together individual standard hours will not give us social stan- dard hours, and it is the number of social S.H. contained in a commodity that constitutes its social inherent-value. Nor is that all. We cannot by mere summation of indi- vidual direct and indirect labor arrive at social inherent-value. (That fact is eagerly seized on by apologists for "capital" and its claims-as though "capital" could have any claims at all- but :it is convenient for such apologists to confuse "capital" with -capitalists.*) Indeed, as regards results (productivity) one individual standard hour of direct labor, combined with an individual S.H. of indirect labor, may produce ten times as much as two S.H. of direct individual labor. How are these new elements to be taken care of, and brought into theaccount? The reply is: by what is known as differential rent and profit. These matters will be dealt with later on. We have nearly gone round our shield but not quite. Marx defines value as "socially necessary labor." He says "'the value of each commodity is determined by the quantity of labor expended on and-materialised in it, by the working- time necessary under given social conditions, for its produc- tion." We have put in heavier type the particular words it-is necessary to emphasise. To grasp the full meaning of these words we must under- stand that wherever differentiation takes place the thing so modified must be regarded in its entirety if the matter is to be understood. Thus the production of any particular kind of commodity necessary to supply the wants of a community must be considered as a whole; limited views are always mis- leading. As when, for instance, we only see one of the two commodities involved in an exchange, or when we are asked the apparently ridiculous question: "How is it that undercut costs more than shin beef?" we might just as reasonably have been asked: "Why does wheat cost more than straw?" The cost of a bullock as a whole and the cost of producing the wheat including its straw is spread variously over all its parts. If we consider wheat only and wheat of the same quality, the cost of the whole harvest is spread--by the law of indifference---equally over the whole crop-although some portions of the crop may contain more individual standard hours than other portions. If the parts are not of equal quality --as, notably, in the case of a bullock-the summation of the parts gives the inherent-value of the whole, or rather, the *They wish to rationalise their interests; we all do. 72 inherent-value of the whole is divided variously among the parts-the cost per pound varies. Nor must we confine our- relves even to one bullock--all the bullocks requiredby a com- aunity must be brought into the reckoning. This differentiation between individual and social S.H. wl as we have said be dealt with more fully when we come to speak of differential rent and profit, but we must under- stald the principle involved now. Man produces wealth by modfying the materials he finds in the world. He modifies matirial by his own physical energy, which is indeed one of the f9rces of Nature. But man regards himself as a thing apart. Tohin all other things are related-are relative. The materials he can use, just as they are found in the world, he calls natural riches. The materials he has modified to make them useful he calh wealth: he has mixed his labor in them. But man is not tle only force in nature; he can direct to his assistance external natural forces: and he has inherited many of the methods and a. knowledge of such direction. The steam or inter- nal combustion engine, for example, gives him command of the energy of chemical combination: machinery, often 'self-acting,' assists him to produce bricks, just as 'fertile' soil and a good climate assist him to produce wheat. Of the total number of bricks required by a community some may, necessarily under existing social conditions, be made by hand; the rest by machinery. One S.H. of individual labor may be embodied in 100: hand-made bricks, and a similar quantity of labor in 400 machine-made bricks. Assuming they are of the same quality and neglecting for a moment the depreciation of the machinery used, the total cost is 2 S.H. per 500 bricks. Then 1 social S.H. per 250 bricks is the correct inherent-value of the bricks and not 1 individual S.H. per 100, or per 400, as the case may be. There cannot be two prices for similar things at the same place and time. The individual S.H. is the just basis of the individual's reward (assuming he is entitled to receive in the ratio of his output of individual standard hours), but the social S.H. is the just price. And it is in this correct adjustment between the individual and the social S.H. that the whole social problem-in its eco- nomic aspect-consists. But Marx takes the matter a step further-as he was perfectly entitled to do; but we prefer not to follow him, as the result is to make the already sufficiently complicated still more complicated. It is an attempt-futile we believe-to identify (in quantity) inherent and exchange values, as they arise under the capitalist mode of distribution. Thus Marx tells us: "'The labor-time socially necessary is that required to produce an article under the normal condi- tions of production, and with the average degree of skill and VALUE. 73 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. intensity prevalent at the time."* But Marx goes farthe than this: instead of drawing a clear distinction between 'true' value (inherent-value) and exchange-value he tries to identify them. Marx complicates his conception of "socially neces- sary" labor by, in effect, reversing the phrase and making it also mean "necessary social" labor. Thus he says: "Supp)se that every piece of linen in the market contains no more la)or- time than is socially necessary. In spite of this, all those pieces taken as a whole have had superfluous labor-time spent upon them. If the market cannot stomach the whole at the normal price of 2 shillings a yard, this proves that too great a pirtion of the total labor of the community has been expended in weaving. The effect is the same as if each individual had expended more labor-time upon his particular product than is socially necessary."'t That is, a certain quantity of socially necessary labor- necessary under the existing methods of manufacture was not the 'necessary social' labor to meet the demands of the existing market, i.e., the linen was oversupplied. In one case 'socially' means under the conditions of manu- facture; in the other it means under the conditions of the market. That, it seems to us, is to put more into the word 'socially' than it can really hold-to load it beyond its saturation point. On the other hand, Marx was perfectly entitled to give any meaning he pleased to his own phrase "socially necessary" provided he carefully defined it-as he did; and those writers who think they discover dishonesty in Marx, either convict themselves of stupidity or are themselves suspect. To disagree with a writer or his method of presenting his subject-matter is one thing-to suggest that he is dishonest is quite another. As Marx has not made the clear distinction we have drawn between inherent and exchange values, he is compelled to make them identical-that is involved in the restricted meaning he is compelled to give to 'utility,' namely, that if a thing is not immediately desired it has no utility. A utility may be over supplied, so that-for the moment- it cannot be given away; then it has no exchange-value, nor, according to Marx, value of any sort. But because it is poten- tially useful although not, for the moment, actually useful we hold it may have inherent-value. In the absence of definite distinction between inherent- and exchange-value, Marx was forced into the position he took up, yet he is sometimes com- pelled to fall back on 'true' value, in contradistinction to exchange-value or market price, and he laid himself open to *Capital, Vol. I., p. 46, Kerr's Edition, 1919. tCapital, Vol. I., p. 120, Kerr'q Edition, 1919. 74 the charge, so often made against him, that his value was entirely determined by the higgling of the market and had no independent existence. We see the same facts that Marx did, but prefer to present them in a different form. Finally, it is necessary to point out that our measuring rod of social standard hours varies with varying conditions in full accordance with the principle of relativity. Man's general mental and physical capacity for work may gradually change, yet the relations of men to each other in that respect remain the same as, for example, when the capacity of every worker alike is increased 10 per cent. But a quicker element of change--in a progressive community-lies in the introduc- tion of more or better machinery, technological methods and industrial organisation. If we measure present values we use present means of measurement. This preliminary investigation, incidental to the consideration of the problem of value, must, we think, already have shown that an intelligent social organ- isation of industrial society is a crying need of the present day and that the go-as-you-please of Capitalism, by courtesy called a system, is utterly inadequate to satisfy the dictates of social justice. In the next chapter on Surplus Value we deal exclusively with social S.H., but they may also be regarded as individual S.H. because the work of society is regarded as a whole; in effect each man is assisted equally by machinery and industrial organisation; but at the beginning of each year more machinery is introduced (the number of workers remain- ing constant). It follows that the productivity of labor increases from year to year and, as a consequence, the price of commodities (in S.H's.) continually falls and the output continually increases, that is to say: value varies inversely as the quantity (and efficiency) of the machinery used and directly as the number of social standard hours worked. But we are not yet in a position to formulate the laws of value. The first and fundamental law has been stated as follows: 1. Commodities exchange, or tend to exchange, in the ratio of their inherent values. That is the first and only law under 'simple production,' but as the methods of production grow more complex, these complexities modify the result of the first law, and must themselves be formulated into laws. Moreover, it has become clear that inherent-value has not a single and definite aspect-it is first individual-labor-time of the kind and intensity chosen by the individual-it is then the kind of labor tacitly agreed on by the two parties to an exchange-it is then the labor as rated by the community, i.e., by social evaluation-it is then this evaluated labor embodied in a specific commodity, and finally this evaluated labor em- VALUE. 75 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. bodied in the whole social output of that kind of commodity. Marx, as we have seen, carried the complexity still farther. Let us then distinguish clearly between three of these inherent values: 1. Socially determined or evaluated individual labor, which we may call shortly 'individual' inherent-value. 2. Individual inherent-value embodied in a given commodity which we may call the 'specific' inherent-value of that com- modity, and 3, the social inherent-value of a commodity, which we must further define. We saw in our illustration of hand- made and machine-made bricks that of the single whole class of 500 bricks, in one case 100 bricks had a specific inherent- value of 1 S.H. and in the other case 400 bricks had a specific inherent-value of 1 S.H. due to the use of machinery and methods of different efficiencies, but the "social inherent- value" of bricks as a class of commodity was 1 standard hour per 250 bricks. Thus to reduce the specific inherent-value of a unit commodity to its social inherent-value the number of units contained in the whole class must be divided by the number of specific (or individual) units of value the whole class contains. The distinction between individual units or standard hours and social units or standard hours is essential because individuals are (or should be) paid in accordance with their output of individual standard hours, but goods are sold (or should be) in accordance with the number of social stan- dard hours they contain. As we have already said this differ- entiation between individual (or specific) and social S.H's. constitutes the economic social problem. It is now probably quite clear that the dislocation between the two is caused chiefly by the varying amounts and effi- eiencies of the tools and machinery used, and to a lesser extent by the various degrees of industrial organisation. We shall ultimately show that total individual-value=total specific inherent-value=total social inherent-value=total exchange-value=total market prices. If the reader is disap- pointed at the complexity of the subject it should be remem- bered that truth is complex. If it were claimed that the number of natural hours of work that went to the making of a useful thing constituted its value-as some have thought was asserted -the matter would be simple indeed, and would be evidence- to those who know anything of the complexity of nature that the claim was untrue. Individual inherent-value embodied in goods constitutes their specific inherent-value, but the modifi- cation of specific into social inherent-value can best be ex- plained after the principles of surplus-value are understood. 76 SURPLUS VALUE. VI. Surplus Value. Surplus value is nearly as old as man himself. It casts its roots far back into the past. It arose when man first received in exchange more value than he gave. When by unequal distri- bution of wealth society became differentiated into rich and poor, when the rich lent of their abundance and received back not only what they lent but 'interest' as well, surplus value swelled in the bud: when large areas of land fell into the hands of individuals, while other men had none, and 'rent' became general, surplus value burst into flower: when tools and machinery were concentrated in factories and owned by few, whilst the many worked for wages and 'profit'-evolved, the fruit of surplus value loaded the tree of Capitalism to breaking point. Now, either the tree must break under the load, or the fruit fall and decay. Our historical sketch has reminded us of the gradual loss by the many of the agents of production and their engrossment by the few. Divorced from his land and his spinning-wheel the laborer could neither dig nor spin without concurrence of landlord or capitalist: all he had of his own to sell was his labor power. But he was no longer bound to the soil: he was free to roam the countryside in search of work. With the advent of the factory and wage-system the Industrial Revolu- tion was complete: the two chief features of which are: (1) ownership of factory and its products by, as a rule, those who do not work in the factory: (2) Payment of wages in money to those who do work in the factory. The present day has brought a further though by no means unimportant develop- ment in that factories are now generally owned by shareholders and operated by their appointees, directors to look after the 77 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. surplus value, managers to look after the men. Meantime the shareholder sits back and waits for his profits. And these profits arise? Primarily they are the difference between cost- price of production and sale-price of goods produced. 'Cost- price' includes maintenance of plant, purchase of raw or partly manufactured materials, and wages and salaries. 'Sale-price' is whatever can be obtained in the market for the goods. Thus profit is sale-price minus cost-price. A word of explanation as to wages. Wages are paid in money: but real wages are the goods that those money-wages purchase. Real wages for some centuries have not varied much: it is a matter in dispute whether they have increased at all: there can, however, be no doubt that the increase, if any, has been slow and small. They are fixed by custom or law on the existing standard of comfort of the working class, and no attempt is made to determine them by value of work done: they must however be sufficient to enable the laborer to live and rear a family.* Under the modern factory system of production it is obvious that if the rate of real wage paid in goods remain nearly constant and on the other hand the amount of goods produced is increased by the introduction of more and better machinery and by improved methods, a considerable increase in the quantity of surplus goods will result. Surplus value does not increase directly as surplus goods: Diagram VI. will show that the increase is much slower; but it does increase: how and to what extent will be better understood from the following illustration:- Fig. 2. Figure 2 shows squares drawn on lines whose lengths are 1, 2, and 3, and placed at distances 1, 2 and 3 from a reference *Where, as in Australia, wages are fixed by the Court, the rate enacted is based on the assumption that a man has a wife and children (two by the state courts of N.S.W., three by the Commonwealth courts), neither more nor less; and that he will be constantly enployed, but no guarantee of constancy of employment is given. 78 SURPLUS VALUE. point. These squares may be used for the purpose of illus- trating what is known as the law of inverse squares. That law is followed by all forces (such as light, heat, gravity, etc.) emanating from one point, as 0 in the figure, and spreading out equally in all directions. The law states that the intensity of the force varies inversely as the square of its distance from the point of origin. That is, the more the force spreads out, the weaker it becomes. Take the case of light, the square on distance 2, and the square on 3, are shown divided into 4 and 9 small squares respectively, and each of these small squares is of the same area as the square on distance 1. It will be seen that as the light illuminating the first small square at distance 1 is a constant quantity which spreads out and illumi- nates uniformly the whole of the square on distance 2, each of its four small squares must receive only one-quarter of the light which falls on the first small square at distance 1, so similarly each of the small squares at distance 3 gets only one- ninth the amount of light which shines on the first small square at distance 1. That is, the quantity of light per small square is reduced from 1 to I and 1-9. Now replace this unit of light by a unit of labor-one stan- dard hour-and suppose that by the introduction of machinery and the sub-division of labor, and generally by better methods of manufacture introduced from time to time the productivity of labor is gradually increased, so that instead of one article, ultimately nine articles of the same kind can be produced by one standard hour of labor. Then in the same labor-time nine articles are made instead of one. Suppose that at stage 1 there are no surplus products and the laborers receive in wages all the goods they make-repre- sented by the small square on distance 1. Then at stage 2- assuming, as we may, that real wages are constant-the laborers receive one small square, and the capitalists three; of the three one, let us say, goes to replace raw materials, and worn-out machinery, leaving a surplus of two small squares; then the value of these two squares constitutes surplus value. At stage 3 the laborers receive, say, 1- small squares (equal to a 50 per cent. increase in wages) and the capitalist 72 small squares, of which, say, 2 go to replace raw materials and plant, leaving a surplus of 5 squares as profit. That is how the capitalist makes his wealth. But the capi- talist, if he be not also his own landlord, is compelled to share this surplus with the landlord class. (How the landlords ex- tract this tribute from the capitalists we shall discover later on.) Thus landlords and capitalists as the receivers of surplus products, and surplus value, tend to become rich, while the 79 80 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. laborers remain in this respect stationary, or, at best, only slowly advance. Inequality. of wealth is the natural result. From the side of production, "the industrial machine is a lever,' continuously being lengthened by progress, which enables the burden of Atlas to be lifted with increasing-ease," but from the side of consumption a counterbalancing friction is developed which effectively prevents a general improvement in human welfare. This defect in consumption arises from de- fective distribution. DISTRIBUTION OF WEALTH 1S]HJ1l ]HI HuIM 9NINMi1N0lIVlfldOd boar 2'oG- %oo6,rw�v Zol Xo Z ' 2o oz-r ; T 0 7.0 9Q) 401 %o9 20,E 0 7 Z0430Z; 407 507. 607 707;807. 90%.toot', 74% 2 21 WORK(ERS LMIDDLE CLASS y sCAPITALLDTS POPULATION,- BEGINNING WITH THE POOREST Fig. 3. That wealth is very unequally divided-in. every capitalist community-is generally known, but an inspection of Diagram 1 will probably cause surprise. The diagram (Fig. 3) has been Z: bJ .Q zo 10 SURPLUS VALUE. constructed from official and non-official returns in England, America and Australia. Plotting the points given by statistics, it was found impracticable to distinguish between England and America--an average line has been drawn to represent both countries. No particular accuracy is therefore claimed-abso- lute accuracy is evidently-from the nature of the case-quite impossible. Indeed later returns indicate that even too much wealth has been ascribed to the workers, and the curves should hug the bottom line of no wealth more closely. But at least there is some approximation to the truth. In the diagram the population is arranged in the order of individual wealth. The base of the small square represents 2 per cent. Read- ing. along the bottom line it is seen that 74 per cent. of the population of England and America own only 7 per cent. of the private wealth of those countries. Consequently the balance of the wealth, 93 per cent., is owned by 26 per cent. of the popu- lation. If the diagram is held reversed-upside down-it will be seen that 7 per cent. of the population owns 80 per cent. of the wealth, and-a still more striking fact-1 per cent. of the population own nearly 55 per cent. of the wealth. It will be seen that the total population has been divided into: workers 74 per cent., middle class 22 per cent., and capi- talists 4 per cent. It is not asserted that there are no workers in the latter classes, or that all are employed in worker class. The middle class here shown consist chiefly of a combination of those whose income arises partly from personal exertion and partly from property, and has nothing to do with culture or social position. Before however showing in detail by a numerical illus- tration exactly how and why this inequality of wealth due to surplus value arises we must clearly realise the dynamic nature of wealth-production. Such production is, under any system, more or less continuous: under Capitalism it is practically an unbroken output,--in the language of the relativists it is a "space-time continuum." That the output continues means that it has movement or flow, that in effect there is a river of goods passing and always passing through all the stages of manufacture. In any one period, a day, a month, a year, every stage of production, from A to Z,-is going on; e.g., in the cotton industry, (1) clearing the soil, (2) planting cotton-seed, (3) reaping, (4) ginning, (5) transport to place of manufacture, (6) spinning into thread, (7) weaving into calico, (8) making into garments, (9) distributing to retailers, (10) distributing to consumer. Further, all these operations are interlocked and any notable change in the rate of flow in any one affects all other stages. F 81 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. Thus, if the rate of distribution to consumers slackens, shirts accumulate in the hands of retailers, then of wholesalers, and the check passes all along the line, and, if severe and continued, may bring the whole industry to a standstill. What we have here to observe is that properly to estimate the total wealth produced-in any given period-we must consider the state of the whole industry, from the first operation to the last, measuring against each other the beginning and end of the period. If these two are exactly equal, then the workers, in that industry, have produced within the period all the shirts sold :-in effect of course, for though the calico used in the first shirts sold had been made in an earlier period yet the exact amount of such calico remains in stock at the end to replace it. Hence, if, as is inevitable, our diagrams cut up a really continuous flow into artificial periods they still remain true in the sense just explained. Each factory receives its raw material in a partly manufactured state: its own product is the raw material of the next factory in the line. This is the necessary result of specialised production and must occur in any higher form of industry. To present a numerical illustration of the way in which surplus value arises, certain assumptions must be made, and the endeavour has been to assume average figures which correspond as closely as possible to reality, and in cases of doubt not to overstate the case against the capitalist. The following are the data as regards labor: 1. The number of laborers is constant. 2. The number of hours worked is constant, at 8 per diem. 3. Before the introduction of capital, wages are taken as seven-eighths of the whole of the products of labor. 4. Real wages (i.e., quantity of products received by the laborer in return for his labor-power) are steadily increased by 2 per cent. of the original wage every year (simple interest). As regards capital: 5. Fixed-capital in plant and capital in raw material is increased at the rate of 32 per cent. compound interest. 6. Concrete capital is equally divided between plant and raw materials. 7. The depreciation of plant is taken at 10 per cent. per annum. 8. The use of plant (i.e., prime movers, as steam engines, etc., and machinery) is assumed to increase the output of pro- ducts tenfold. 82 SURPLUS VALUE. A period of eighty years is considered and calculations made for every fifth year. The results are embodied in tables, and shown graphically in diagrams. With regard to the several data a word of explanation may be permitted. 1. " The number of laborers is constant." With so many varying quantities it is desirable, whenever possible, to assume constancy. A community with a fixed population, or rather a fixed number of workers, is therefore assumed: 2. "The number of hours worked is constant at eight." The same reason holds as in 1. 3. "The original * wage is taken at seven-eighths of the total production"; one-eighth being retained by capitalists as rent, interest or profit. Suppose for instance workers are em- ployed in gathering firewood, that they receive �700 in wages, and the firewood is sold for �800. If the �700 includes the cost of management by a foreman, etc., then �100 is the clear profit-or absolute surplus value as Marx calls it. (No machinery being employed.) 4. "Real wages are increased steadily by 2 per cent. per annum (simple interest) after the introduction of machinery." As a fact nominal wages fluctuate, but on the average nominal wages show a tendency to advance. Whether real wages actually increase 100 per cent. in fifty years and 300 per cent. in one hundred years, or not, is open to serious doubt, and it seems probable that the rate of increase is not correctly repre- sented by a straight line, as has been assumed. The assumption regarding real wages is, however, believed to be approximately true, or to state the case favorably for the capitalist. Thorold Rogers in his "Six Centuries of Work and Wages" says: "Relatively speaking the working man of to-day is not so well off as he was in the fifteenth century." 5. "Fixed" capital in plant and capital in raw materials is increased at the rate of 3- per cent. compound interest." There is not the slightest doubt that the capital employed in pr6gressive countries increases in some geometric progression, and there is reason to believe that 32 per cent. compounded is approximately the true rate. The exact rate, no doubt, varies at different times, and in different countries, but it is of little consequence whether the rate be 2- per cent. or 5 per cent. for the principles involved are the same. Unfor- tunately, owing to the backwardness of official statistics the rate cannot be directly obtained, but the growth of exports is known, and it is probable that these are proportional to the growth of capital. *As yet there is no machinery employed. FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. Diagram II. (Fig. 4) shows the growth of Australian exports from 1830 to 1920. MILLIONS A.D1920 70 30 40 0 60 70 80 90 190 1900 90 90 80 30 70 70 50 50 40 40 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 MILLIONS Fig. 4. These diagrams, or graphs, are easily read. Thus: To find the amount of exports in 1860, follow the horizontal line, marked 1860, due east until the curve is met, then go vertically due north to the figure 20. As these figures represent mil- lions, the exports from Australia in 1860 were in value nearly �20,000,000. It will be noticed that there is a considerable deviation about this time from the 32 per cent. curve, due no doubt to exceptionally large exports of gold. The gash in the upper right hand corner of the diagram in 1914-15 was due to restricted exports during the great European war, but generally the 3 per cent. compound in- terest curve fits the export figures pretty well. 6. It has been assumed that half the capital is in plant, and half'in raw niaterials. By plant is meant prime movers, as steam engines, internal combustion engines, water wheels, turbines, wind mills, etc., in fact any and every device by which the forces of nature are directed to the use and benefit of man; and not only prime movers, but machinery of all sorts 84 SURPLUS VALUE. which under the control of man and driven for the most part by the forces of nature manipulate the materials of nature. Thus the forces of nature are made to manipulate the materials of nature, and produce articles of use, or utility. (It is evident that the same kind of result is obtained by a machine whether it be driven by hand power, or steam power.) By 'raw materials' are meant not only crude materials as they occur in nature, as coal, iron ore, etc., but all partly- finished products up to the last stage of manufacture. Raw materials, plus wages, are often spoken of as 'circulating capital' in text books on economics, but wages (including salaries) are distinguished by Marx as 'variable capital.' In other words 'circulating capital' consists of 'variable capital," i.e., salaries and wages, plus the 'constant capital' in raw materials, coal, oil, etc., but it does not include the cost of plant. 7. "The average depreciation of plant is 10 per cent. per annum;" an ample allowance. 8. "The use of plant increases products ten-fold." Marx gives a number of cases in which the increased production due to the use of steam or water power in conjunction with machinery and human labor is on the average as high as sixty-fold. A more moderate estimate of a ten-fold increase has been assumed here, or rather since only half the capital is assumed to be invested in plant, the increased production by the total capital invested is only five-fold. These assump- tions have been tabulated and their results are shown in the diagrams, but the tables themselves and the detailed method of their calculation are to be found in the appendix. It should, however, be pointed out that the income capitalists can spend in consumption goods or on new capital goods is not in reality so great as is shown in the tables. No account has been taken of the loss of capital due to the introduction of new kinds of machinery which cause old plant to be scrapped before it is worn out. This matter will be referred to later on, but as these losses may be heavy, the fact should be noted now. Industry is a movemenj and we can only chart the course of a moving body by fixing points through which it passes during a given period-whether day, month or year is of no consequence. By connecting these points we obtain a graphic representation of the progress of industry. Times of 'turnover' would furnish the most correct period, but they vary; yearly periods are convenient because it is customary to state profits, interest, depreciation, etc., on that basis. The day originally adopted may, then, be taken to represent a year. 85 86 LFROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. 0P 000VI 0 0 0 L. _00 LC) 3v . L 2z liii KP CO- - - -f-I-~4- - -I-I--l-" 00 oJ2AN . L~4 ...I) i i i i i i f I i I i i 11 --d i F l .- -- - 4 - A te.--}-- }---} ,; i - --- {----i} T =;%- i 0 r-= . 66 I r-- i t f S JV2A SURPLUS VALUE. Diagram III. (figure 5) exhibits the growth of capitalistic industry, on the assum.ptions made, over a period of 80 years. The standard hour of labor adopted is the natural hour of 'common' labor to which all other kinds of labor, mental or physical, are reduced. The diagram is made up of two graphs with a common base line 0 -8. On the right (going East) from 0-8 we first meet the curve of. 'raw materials'; next, that of plant de- terioration; and finally the curve of total (constant) capital in plant and raw materials. On the left hand side of 0-8 (going West) we have the curve of wages, which when measurement is made from 8-80, instead of from 0-8, is also the curve of sur-plus value. Of the whole period of 80 years consider the position at the beginning, end, and middle point. In the zero year no constant capital at all is employed, merely the money capital used as wages, which Marx terms variable capital. We may suppose laborers to be exclusively employed in (say) gathering firewood to which they give a 'place' value, by placing it in a depot: they receive seven- eighths of this value-but relinquish one-eighth as 'rent' to a non-workcr who 'owns' the forest. That one hour's work (out of eight) is not paid for; Marx calls it unpaid labor or absolute surplus value. (Of -the total surplus value the diagram shows the absolute surplus value as a constant; in reality the ratio of absolute to relative surplus value depends on the degree of monopoly, but data is not available.) 1. If we express the division of the products of industry in quantities and not in values we have for the Zero year: Capitalists, 100. Laborers, 700. 2. In the 40th year of Capitalism the division of the pro- ducts is as follows: Capitalists, 635. Laborers, 1160. 3. In the 80th year (the end of the period examined) the -division is Capitalists, 2232. Laborers, 1820. Thus on our iniprobable assumption that real wages steadily increase by 2 per cent. per year, wages during the 80 years have risen from 700 to 1820: profits have risen from 100 to 2232. Stated in values, wages have decreased from 700 to 359: profits have increased from 100 to 441. Roughly, wages have been halved, profits have been multiplied by four. The figures quoted and the method of their calculation will be found in the appendix. 87 88 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. The reader will note that 'the halving of the value of wages goes hand ini hand with a (more than) doubling of the quantity of products received, yet relatively the laborer gets poorer and poorer and the capitalist richer and richer. There is constant confusion in economics between values and products, because the quantity of products increases much faster than the inherent-value incorporated in them. The same quantity of labor is continually making more products. The curve on the extreme right of diagram III. (figure 5) is the curve of 32 per cent. compound interest and is of the same character as the dotted curve shown in diagram II. (figure 4). It represents the growth of capital (assumption 5), which is probably nearly correct. Of the total capital, half (shown by the next curve marked raw materials) is invested in plant. The small area cut out of the other half, viz., plant (line.0 to 16), is the loss of plant by deterioration or depreciation; viz.: one-tenth per annum. MM WEAL TH TOTALOI D YcRYEARLYPA'ODIXTS C(S5JPUAffTKYI GOOLI _ TOTAtRAW MATERIALS AND PLANT USED __ PLU~S RRO lX ~-- 41AGE~S--- IPMY IYFD IINEtPE&-WWU PMTSE If MLlTEOV 8 4.3: 3 7 t$, -70 60--- 50 _i 30 -20I 10 10o . -1 r54 3 2 1 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8?e QUANTITIES Fig. 6. This depreciation and the whole of the raw. material actually' used in any one year is a first charge on the industry and is recovered in the price of the commodities. Marx divides the total value of the goods produced, into surplus-value 3, wages VT, and raw materials and plant consumed C. Thus SURPLUS VALUE. 8 S + V + C is the totalyearly (or periodical) value. V + C he calls the 'cost of production' when plant and raw materials arc purchased in their true (inherent) values. Diagram IV. (Fig. 6) shows the increasing quantity of daily or yearly products due to the increasing use of capital in plant, and also the gradually increasing amount of products incorporated in raw materials and plant. The enormous in- crease in the quantity of products made by living labour when assisted by machinery, is seen at 'a glance. DISPOSAL OF LABOR WORKING-TIME TME PRODUCJING TIME PROOLICING TIME PRODUC1NG CAPITALISTS CA P1TALIS TS PARTLY FINISHEDI)PPOOLrn WORKERS oFL5MPW) &GOB5 COM~UMPTILWIGUS $�0 2 3 4 55 6 7 SoR 70-7 -------------- S-------------- ---------70- 60- 6- 50 -50 30-30 20 oer - oZero VALUE Fig. 7. Diagram V. (Fig. 7) embodies the table of Labour Time, and has already been. explained. it will be seen howe the time devoted to the finishing. process which produces '.consumption goods' grows gradually less. and the time required to bring the 'raw materials' or partly-finished products to the finishing stage gradually increases. 89 I5 2 Y 90 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. The relation between 'value' and 'quantity' is exhibited in Diagram VI. (Fig. 8). Both are plotted to the same scale. Value has a tendency to remain constant, or to increase slowly. Under the conditions assumed 800 S. hours are worked per day throughout the whole period of 80 years. VALUE QUANTITY OF PRODUCTS 802 I 0 1 2 3 4 6 7 8 9 70 60 SI, Fig. 8. At a first glance it would appear as though the daily value producedought at all times to be 800, no matter what the quan- goods produced in the same time by the same number of work- ers the value of the goods should, it would appear, be halved labor (807 past and 800 present). The daily amount of SURPLUS VALUE. labor, past and present, direct and indirect, embodied in com- modities has practically been doubled. On the other hand, the quantity of goods produced has been increased more than five- fold, from 800 to 4052 (see column 8a, Table of Products). Or, if we consider present labor only, a man in the 80th year produces, with the assistance of capital, more than five times the products he could make in the Zero year, five times as many consumption goods. It is quite possible for the quantity of goods received in wages to increase, and the value of wages to fall. For in- stance, from the Zero year to the 80th year wages increase from 700 to 1820 in quantity (see column 7, Table of Products), but fall in value from 700 to 359 (see column 7, Table of Values), but, again it may be remarked, it is the quantity and not the value of the goods that counts in the welfare of a people. Quantity constitutes real wages: value or price, nominal wages. Diagram No. III. shows 'values' in the same form as Diagram No. IV. exhibits quantities. Diagram VII. (Fig. 9) exhibits the fall in the time (and value) required to produce an article, due to the use of mach- inery and the better organisation and subdivision of labor. The time is shown in standard minutes; if expressed in frac- tions of a standard hour, then Time x Quantity = Value (in Standard Hours). In the table of 'Values,' column 18 (see Appendix), it will be noticed that the rate of profit varies considerably, that is, the rate of profit on the true cost of production, C - V. The constant capital, C, consists of the partly finished mater- ials embodied in the consumption goods and the material and labor required to replace the worn-out machinery, and the variable capital, V, consists of the goods paid away as wages, or salaries. Surplus-value consists of rent, plus profit, plus interest. Some confusion may arise from the use of the word 'profit' to mean surplus-value. It is strictly a part of the total sur- plus value, but it is often used to denote the whole. In the Zero year the rate of surplus-value is 12- per cent. This rate of 'profit' continually increases until in the 55th year it reaches 46 per cent. It then continually falls and will continue to fall, no matter how long the period analysed, pro- vided the conditions assumed still continue to exist. It will also be noticed that the value of the total capital employed continually increases; from 700 in the Zero year to 1827 in the 80th year. The quantity of capital also increases from 700 to 9254. On the other hand the cost of the living labor-power employed decreases from 700 to 359, but the 91 92 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. quantity and inherent value of present labor-power remains constant, at 800 standard hours. Thus past labor becomes a larger and still larger pro- portion of the total labor employed, or, speaking in terms of COST OF PRODUCING ONE ARTICLE IN STANDARD MINUTES (PRESENT LABOR) to 2 0 40Af 80 -70 60 -60 '50 5 z 40 - - - - - - - - - 401" 30----3--- 0 20 - - - - - - - - - - - - 20 10 -. - - - 10 10 2U0 3U 40 .90 W 60 MWU7&; Fig. 9. capital, tlie constant capital continually. increases while re- latively the variable capital continually decreases. If we term the constant plus, the variable capital, the total capital (neglecting for the moment the capital not worn. out) fO t i1i Go SURPLUS VALUE. then total capitals with a higher proportion of constant capital are termed by Marx, capitals of higher organic composition. Each succeeding year our assumptions give capitals of higher organic composition than those used in the preceding year. Thus in the 10th year variable capital is 97.8 per cent. and constant capital only 2.2 per cent. of the total capital. In the 80th year the variable capital has fallen to 30.8 per cent. and the constant capital has risen to 69.2 per cent. The capital used in the 80th year is therefore of higher organic composi- tion than that used in the 10th year. Now Marx points out that with capitals of the same magnitude the percentage of profit is smaller in those of higher organic composition,- provided, and the proviso is vital, the degree of exploitation, or the percentage of surplus-value remains constant. Or to put it in another way: of two capitals of equal magnitude that in which the variable capital is greater, i.e., employs the most men, will return the higher rate of profit provided the per- centage of surplus value remains constant. That statement appears to contradict our figures, which show an increasing rate of profit in capitals of higher organic composition from the Zero to the 50th year. The explanation is that in our figures the percentage of surplus value does not remain constant. With the proviso Marx makes, his statement is perfectly correct. After the depreciation of plant has been made good and the raw material made in previous years has been replaced, the value of the surplus products available for consumption (or reinvestment) is distributed as follows: In the Zero year, 88 % to workers: 12 % to capitalists. In the 50th year, 592% to workers: 401% to capitalists. In the 80th year, 45 % to workers: 55 % to capitalists. The percentage of the total value of products taken by capitalists continually increases; the value taken by workers continually grows less, although the products taken by workers may slightly increase. If, however, the value taken by capitalists is expressed as a percentage on the total capital employed we have: Zero year, nil: 50th year, 35%: 80th year, 24%. After the 50th year the percentage on the total capital employed continually falls, because the capital employed in- creases faster than the total surplus value of the products, but the mass of value taken by capitalists continually increases while the mass of products taken by capitalists enormously inereases. We now come to the consideration of a fact which has been a great stumbling block (it has even been thought fatal) 93 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. to the labor theory of value as enunciated by Marx, viz.: the tendency of industries to yield an average rate of profit on the total capital employed. It has been shown that capitals of different organic com- position produce, or tend to produce, different rates of profit At any given time it is evident that existing industries use capitals of different degrees of organic composition. Some employ relatively more laborers, some less-the ratio of the amount spent in wages, to the amount spent in raw material and plant varies greatly. Industries of low organic composi- tion (those, i.e., employing a relatively large quantity of labor) should produce a high rate of profit. And yet, as a fact, all industries produce, or tend to produce (we neglect the growing results of monopoly) the same rate of profit-calculated on the total capital employed. How can this be explained? Our figures for any year are merely a statement of the average composition of all the then existing industries, and do not affirm that each industry has that particular capital compo- sition, i.e., the particular ratio of constant to variable capital, set down-they only state that the average composition of all the capitals in use in that year has that particular ratio. Our figures, in fact, are 'social' and not 'specific' inherent-values. Now suppose that instead of showing the growth of indus- try over a period of 80 years, the whole table of values and products should represent 17 industries working during one and the same year and having the various compositions of capital shown in the tables; such industries would yield ac- cording to the figures (column 20) profits varying from 12 per cent. to 35 per cent. Could such varying returns be main- tained? Obviously they could not. It must be quite evident that with money to invest even the densest capitalist would put it into the 11th or most profitable industry, and that this example would be followed by others. That this is what has occurred is as certain as it is that water will run down hill. When the deepest depressions in the field of industry have been filled the water-(the capital)-will flow into the minor depressions until we shall get, what in fact we have, a uniform level surface, a level rate of profit in all existing industries. What that level is, depends on the total quantity of profit avail- able, and the quantity available is the sum total of the 'specific' profits arising from all industries. This perfectly natural equalisation of profits under Capi- talism has been hailed with delfght by critics as a contradiction of the labor theory of value. It contradicts it exactly as a magnet contradicts the law of gravitation when it lifts a steel pen from the table--but in fact it is no contradiction at all; 94 SURPLUS VALUE. on the contrary, it fulfills the theory and is implicit in the term 'soeially necessary.' Marx had been accused of plagiarising Rodbertus* (a neglected writer whose works are well worth reading: his standpoint is even more evolutionary than that of Marx). Engels, as a consequence of this accusation, in his preface to the second' volume of "Das Kapital" (issued after the death of Marx), threw out a challenge to economists to show how the views of Rodbertus reconciled the average rate of profit with the labor theory of value, promising to give Marx' solution in the third volume. No one was able to do so. At length that solution appeared, but it was not-we may almost say it is not-understood because the full meaning of socially necessary is not realised. Yet the matter is not diffi- cult. In any self-contained community its full requirements for any particular commodity are met-in most cases--by several different factories of various degrees of efficiency, and working under different conditions. The most efficient makes the highest profit but cannot supply the whole market. From this necessary differentiation we must look for enlightenment to the industry as a whole-or the commodity as a whole- because what is true of one class of commodity is true of all commodities amongst themselves, we must look to the integra- tion in which this differentiation takes place; we must pass, in fact, from specific inherent-value to social inherent-value. The entire labor of production is distributed in the market throughout the -whole mass of commodity produced, just as a teaspoonful of sugar will, in time, diffuse itself uniformly throughout the whole cup of tea, or as salt penetrates the whole volume of contained fluid, or leaven leavens the whole lump. This aetion is known to science as saturation, or as endosmosis -a passing through a living membrane to mix with another fluid of a different density-so through the living membranes of labor, labor-powers of different densities are mixed. The whole cup may be represented by the manor, the guild market, the Hanseatic League, the nation or the civilised world--but within the limits of the cup this endosmosis takes place. Thus we have the effect of the unrestricted primary law of value modified by a secondary law, viz.: competition amongst capitalists. Once more we have to do, not with the making of value, but with its distribution when made; with the trans- formation of inherent value into exchange value. *Every writer, consciously or unconsciously, adopts the ideas of others, but Marx, like Shakespeare, so altered what he adopted as to make it his OWfl 95 9 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. This transformation is shown in Diagram VIII. (Fig. 10). The normal (full) line of surplus value is that due to the FIRST LAW Of VALUE: commodities exchange, or tend to exchange, in the ratio of their specific inherent-values. That law operates, no matter how it may be restricted or its effects modified, under every system: of production and exchange. NORMAL PROFIT AVERAGE RATE OF PROFIT 01 4 5 6 - r - - 1- 1- r -~r ~r - - - T-- T. 8 17 132 15 __ _itiiii~ 1 ' I - por AVERAGE 3 4 5 6 PROFIT OR SURPLUS VALUE IN STANDARD HOURS Fig. 10.. 7 8 c Under simple. production the effects of the .law are hardly modified at all, but under the complex system of production known as Capitalism a secondary law comes into play.. By endosmosis fluids of different- densities are diffused equally throughout the whole mass, so by the second law of value (r) v S 96 SURPLUS VALUE. specific inherent-value is transformed into social inherent- values or, using Marx' terms, specific profits are merged by competition between capitalists into an average rate of profit on the total capital employed, and capitals of different organic composition receive a uniform rate of profit. Marx calls this 'the price of production'; we term it social inherent-value. This variation from normal profit is represented in diagram VIII., figure 10, by. the dotted line. The area on the left of both lines is the same area, but the shape of the area is dif- ferent. Both represent the total surplus value, but the dis- tribution of profit (or surplus value) amongst the seventeen industries is different. THE SECOND LAW OF VALUE may be stated as fol- lows:-The exchange-value of a commodity is greater than its Specific inherent-value when the organic composition of the capital used in its production is high: conversely, the ex- change-value of a commodity is less than its specific inherent- value when the organic composition of the capital used in its production is low: in other words commodities exchange, or tend to exchange, in the ratio of their social inherent-values. It follows that when capitals of average organic composition are used their products exchange as though only the first law operated: provided their exchange is not affected by the operation of the third law of value. As a corollary to the second law we have: under free competition amongst capitalists the quantity of capital employed in the pro- duction of any commodity tends to increase or diminish until an average rate of profit results, on the total capi- tal employed in all industries. We have now reached nearly to the surface appearances of exchange-value, to the point, in fact, where we parted company with Marx in his presentation of the subject, viz., to that modification of 'social' inherent- value known as supply and demand, which results in ex- change-value or market price. Figure 11 shows in diagra- matie form the play of supply and demand. The figure was origihally intended to illustrate the variation of exchange value from: inherent value. If the reader will substitute, in his mind, market price for exchange-value, and "social" inherent-value, or, "the price of production" as Marx terms it, for inherent- value, the diagram can be used to illustrate the THIRD LAW OF VALUE, namely: The exchange-value of a commodity is greater than its social inherent-value when the commodity is scarce, but less when the commodity is abundant; in other words: commodities exchange at their market values. Of natural scarcity we have already spoken-the third law refers entirely-insofar as it is an economic law-to artificial scarcity. G 97 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. The straight horizontal line represents the normal line of inherent-value (price of production). Two com- pressed spiral springs represent supply and demand and carry at their junction a pencil which pormally traces out the straight line of inherent-value (price of production). Now suppose lateral oscillation is set up. As the spring of demand SUPPLY DEMAND Fig. 11. extends it weakens, as the spring of supply is compressed it strengthens until a reaction takes place and the pencil is car- ried in turn below the normal line of value. This action and reaction in the springs correctly illustrates the action and reaction of supply and demand. Suppose the pencil is carried forward from left to right, or, what comes to the same thing, the paper is carried under the pencil from right to left, then it will trace out the line of exchange-value (market-price). The illustration is in fact on the lines of the steam indicator diagram. Over a long period the sum of the areas above the line will be equal to the sum of the areas below the line, i.e., the pluses will equal the minuses. This play of demand and sup- ply assumes free competition, but Capitalism is changing and the economic laws of Capitalism must change too. It cannot be too clearly apprehended, that economic law is merely a generalisation of the principles of the system of industry (and the method of distributing its results) in vogue for the time being. When free competition no longer exists-and it is fast ceasing to exist-the law of demand and supply becomes the 'law' of economic (or political) force. When monopoly reigns supreme-and it is growing fast-it can be said of the laws of economics, as of snakes in Iceland, "there are none." Eco- nomie law is relative to, restricted to, and conditioned by a 98 SURPLUS VALUE. special system of industry, or body of reference; it is not universal, inexorable, immutable, eternal, or something equally drastic, beloved of our newspaper leader writers. The fallacy of treating exchange as a means of increasing the general wealth-(the things exchanged)-was trenchantly dealt with by Ruskin long ago: If in the exchange one man is able to give what cost him little labor, for what cost the other much, he 'acquires' a certain quantity of the produce of the other's labor. And precisely what he acquires, the other loses. In mercantile language, the person who acquires is com- monly said to have 'made a profit,' and I believe that many of our merchants are seriously under the impression that it is possible for everybody, somehow, to make a profit in this manner. Whereas, by the unfortunate constitution of the world we live in, the laws both of matter and of motion have quite rigorously forbidden universal acquisi- tion of this kind. Profit, or material gain, is attainable only by con- struction, or by discovery; not by exchange. Whenever material gain follows exchange, for every plus there is a precisely equal minus. Note that Ruskin says material gain. It is not denied that every voluntary exchange gives mutual satisfaction, or to one of the parties less dissatisfaction, notwithstanding the fact that both of the parties to the exchange may be aware that one of them is sacrificing a material or inherent-value; that one is making a profit, the other a loss, as measured under normal conditions. To illustrate the third law of value let us take a con- crete case. For greater clearness, it may be well here to re- place "standard hours" by the more familiar measure of value, --gold. Suppose then that a natural hour of work by a pick and shovel man working with the average degree of skill and intensity of his class has been adopted as a standard hour of labor. Suppose further that such a standard laborer works as a gold miner on a gold field of average richness and wins on the average 11.3 grains of pure gold per hour, then the standard hour expressed in pure gold is one-tenth of a sove- reign, i.e., two shillings and we have the equation:- 1 S.H. = 2/-. (There are reasons for believing that this estimate is ap- proximately correct). Replacing, then, the standard hour by its gold equivalent of 2/-, we will, as our illustration, take the case of a party of fishermen. In one day (or night) let us suppose that 50 S.H. of labor are expended in catching and selling fish. Then the specific inherent-value of the catch- large or small-is 100 shillings. If only one fish is caught it has cost �5, if 1,200 fish are caught, each fish is on the ave-. rage worth one penny. Suppose the average catch (for a similar expenditure of labor in the whole industry) is 100 99 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. fish, then the social inherent value of each fish is on the ave- age 1/-. That is the 'true,' 'real,' or 'normal' price per ave- rage-sized fish. Now -consider the market. Suppose that at id. each the market is glutted (at anything below that price our fishermen are not repaid for hawking them round and consequently will not do so): further, that above 2/- each no one will buy, we then have maximum and minimum limits. Further, suppose that our fishermen have previously tested the possibilities of their market, and find they can sell their fish in the quantities, and at the prices, shown in the following table :-- Exchange Specific value inherent- per fish. value per fish. 1,200 fish @ Id. = �5 0 0 1,200 @ ld. = �5 0 0 1,000 ,, @ 2d. = 8 6 8 1,000 @ lid. = 5 0 0 500,, 6d =1210 0 500 @ 2d.= 5 0 0 250 ,, @ 9d. = 9 3 6 250 @ 4d. = 5 0 0 *100 ,, @1/- = 5 00 100 @ 1/- = 5 0 0 50 , @ 1/6= 3 15 0 50 @ 2/- = 5 0 0 5 ,, @ 2/- = 05 0 0 Now although it is quite true that if all exchanges are taken into the account, things must on the average exchange at their real values, yet one industry may, and in fact does, per- sistently sell its goods above their value while another as per- sistently is compelled to sell them below their value. Our fishermen 'ought' to sell so as to realise 100/-, but (on the above schedule) it will pay them to restrict the supply to 500 fish per day and throw away the rest of their catch. Thus, whether it be our humble group of fishermen, or a capitalist octopus like the Standard Oil Trust, there is the same tempta- tion to seek the point of maximum gain; and the process is the same, it is a matter merely of keeping the consumer hungry. In Diagram IX., Fig. 12, this final modification of inherent- valuet into the exchange-value of the market is shown by a dotted line. Using Marx's terms we have 'true' value modi- fied into 'the price of production,' and finally into 'market prices.' In every case, no matter which line we take, the area of the figure (total value) whether to the right or the left is the same in magnitude. Labor and labor only makes value. *Exchange-value, specific inherent-value and social inherent-value all coincide at this point. tThe diagram shows quantities not values, but at any given moment quantities are proportional to inherent-values. 100 SURPLUS VALUE.10 Owing' to the use of two sets of terms (our own and Marx) it may be well to place them side by. side to illustrate the trans- formations. undergone by actual concrete labor-time until it s CAR'LAW 2. PRISE OF PRODUCTION IN GOODS - TERTIARY LAW -3 MARKET PRICE IN GOODS- PRIMARY LAW I. TRUE VALUE IN GOODS - r 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 515 3 - II r PAU MARKET PRICE IN GOODS. Fig. 12. results. in the exchange-value of the market; thus : Marx' Terms. Author's Terms., (a) Actual concrete labor. (b) Concrete labor in average hours. (c) Abstract labor. time in Commodities. (d) Price of production in average hours. (e) Exclawge value 'or mar-. ket-price. (a) Actual concrete labor. (b) Individual s ta nd ar d hours. (c) Specific standard hours in commodities. (d) Social inherent-value in standard hours. (e) Exchange value or mar- ket price. 101 II i 7 8 9I FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. The transformation from (a) to (b) is made by "social evaluation" from (b) to (c) by the embodiment of labor-time in commodities (or services) by -means of machinery, etc., of differing efficiencies; from (c) to (d) by differential rent- profit and interest; from (d) to (e) by "supply and demand." With differential-rent and -profit and with interest we shall deal in the next chapter. The reader is now in a position to appreciate both the strength and the weakness of Marx' position regarding 'value.' By giving a very comprehensive meaning to the term 'socially necessary' Marx is able correctly to assert that the exchange- value (or market price) of an article is exactly expressed by the number of socially necessary abstract hours of labor it contains, and for which it exchanged. But his 'value' cannot be expressed by a fixed number of standard hours because it is continually changing, and what it is-for the moment-can only be ascertained by actually selling or exchanging the article. That is an absurdly high price to pay for the merely verbal advantage of identifying the inherent- and exchange-value of a commodity in magnitude as well as in kind. iOn the other hand, by doing no violence to the term 'socially necessary,' or, if you will, by restricting its meaning, we are able to fix and define inherent-value and make of it a calculable quantity absolutely independent of the 'higgling of the market.' For example: If a community devotes 10,000 individual standard hours past and present to the production of one million bricks, the social inherent-value of each brick is exactly ten thousand divided by one million, or one-hundredth 10,000 1 of a standard hour per brick. 10000 1S.H. 1,000,000 100 In other words: the inherent-value of a commodity is its "cost of production" in standard hours. [Author's Note: Minor objections, sometimes raised, to the labor theory of value, deserve perhaps a note. 1. With the metaphysical idea of 'marginal utility' which offers an alternative theory of value, we have already dealt. 2. To the objection that "labor cannot be measured" we reply that our previous argument has shown demonstrably that labor can be' measured. 3. An objection has been raised by Mr. Beer, the author of a "History of British Socialism," who contends that the increase in wealth following the introduction of machinery and prime movers into England was sb great that the labor in the country could not possibly have made it all. It did not. The difference at that time between the ex- change value of British products and their inherent-value was so great that England was enabled to exploit other nations. It was largely the 102. SURPLUS VALUE. 103 labor of other nations that caused the wealth of England to increase "by leaps and bounds." 4. That value is a ratio is a statement that hardly merits a reply. Value, whether exchange or inherent, is one of the terms of a ratio. If four apples exchange for six pears, we may say the exchange-value of four apples is six pears, but to say that the value of four apples is 4: 6 is a palpable absurdity. Merely to assert-correctly no doubt- that all things are relative without telling us to what and how they are related is hardly calculated to" advance the sum total of human know- ledge.] FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. VII. Exploitation. We come now to those forms of Surplus Value which change specific values into social values, viz., rent, profit and interest. But these transforming agencies instead of equal- ising or proportionalising the rewards of individual effort, as expressed in output in standard hours, actually in virtue of private ownership direct the balances of specific values into the pockets of owners of land and capital. That is to say they are at present a means of exploitation. By exploitation is meant the legal acquisition of wealth in exchange for no effort, or no adequate effort. All men are more or less willing to exploit. Some do not know that they are exploiting, some believe that exploitation is not only legal but moral also; some are vastly indignant when told that private rent, profit and interest are exploitation, and that, in effect, they are only legalised forms of robbery. So familiar indeed are these terms that we are quite ready to believe that they express eternal laws given to us by Nature herself. How can we be exploiters, we who have never stolen a penny in our life, and scrupulously paid our debts? Though we may reasonably be content to leave for the time untouched the moral aspect of Capitalism, yet, right or wrong, wise or unwise, private rent, profit and interest are forms of surplus value and surplus value is exploitation. The term has a wide meaning; we may exploit nature, to some ex- tent we must exploit nature, because we are not able to replace the coal, iron ore and other materials taken out of the ground, although we can, in time, replace the trees cut from a virgin forest. In one sense this loss is a part of the cost of the com- modities. It is a real reduction of national riches and a per- manent loss to posterity against which, however, posterity must set its inheritance of advanced knowledge and technical methods. Differential rent and profit have then a natural as well as an artificial basis. They are payments for natural and social (industrial) advantages enjoyed by individuals or corpora- tions. The essential question is not so much whether differ- ential rent and profit per se are just (they are) but to whom they should be paid-the private individual or the community. But all rent and interest is not differential, part of it is, or may be. pure 'pistol' value. Rent, Profit and Interest. Of these "values" we deal first with "Rent," and with that particular form known as agricultural ground rent. 104 EXPLOITATION. Under Capitalism we have three parties: (1) Landlord, (2) Capitalist-Tenant-Farmer, (3) Agricultural Farm Labourer. The scene of operations for them all is land. Land has (or may have) exchange-value, otherwise it would be impossible to rent or sell it, and it is the fact that land is a utility in private ownership-a utility necessary to human existence-that gives to land its exchange-value. Rent, then, is what is paid for the use of land. For instance: if someone is willing to pay �20 a year for the exclusive right to occupy and use a certain piece of ground and if the current rate of interest is 5 per cent., then the pre- pent exchange-value of the land is �400, because �400 will buy an income of �20 per annum; but had the current rate of interest only been 4 per cent., the exchange-value of the land would be �500, because, at 4 per cent., �500 is required to buy an income of �20. Thus we see that the exchange-value of land rises or falls inversely as the rate of interest. (That is the ordinary investmeht aspect; we do not include those cases in which the motive of purchase is social position-or even a speculation in unearned increment-from a strictly business point of view such purchases are often bad investments). But if the rate of interest determines the exchange-value of land, what determines rent? What makes us willing to pay �20 a year for the use of ground. How does the rent of unimproved land arise, and by what laws is it governed? Note in the first place that under Capitalism, the tenant- farmer is engaged in producing commodities for the market, that is for sale and not for his personal use. That is the dis- tinguishing mark of social production under Capitalism. Let us suppose he is engaged in producing wheat for sale. The marketing of his product is then a part of his cost of produc- ttcn. If his land is far from his market, his costs are in- creased. Products, as we have seen, are not always, or even often, sold at their inherent-value, they are sold at market-prices, or if supply and demand are equal, they are sold at their prices of production. It is this fact that makes ground rent possible, but nlot this fact alone. The second fact, or factor, becomes apparent when we consider the true nature of capital. The essential and vital element in capital (machinery as an agent of production) lies in the fact that capital enables man to make use of some particular forces of nature. Thus anyone who possesses a steam engine can make use of the force known as heat, through the expansive power of steam. Steam suitably confined can be made to do work, and this 'work' belongs to the owner of the steam engine. It is free to every- one who can buy a steam engine-but it is not free to those 105 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. who do not own or cannot buy and use steam engines. It is, therefore, in reality, the monopoly of the wealthy, the mono- poly of capitalists; and we shall find monopoly at the root of rent, interest and profit. But it is not only by capital that man, or some men, util- ise the forces of nature-some particular forces of nature are utilised by land. Capital, by itself, cannot cause a single blade Uf grass to grow; but land, by itself, can produce utilities. Some land is said to be fertile, meaning that it is so con- stituted that it will grow vegetation profusely. But all land has not the same degree of fertility. If the most fertile land is already privately owned no one else can get such good land. If my neighbour has a good steam engine I can, if I have the money, get one exactly like it, but if the best land is already taken, no one can get land as good. Poor land may be made good, but it is then land, plus capital, and plus labor. It is not virgin land, the subject with which we are now deal- ing. We discover, therefore, a monopoly within a monopoly, an exclusive individual advantage multiplied by an exclusive class-advantage, an m2 so to speak, a higher power of monopoly. Only the wealthy or the fortunate can own land, only some of them can own the best land. This fact is the second, but fundamental, cause of differential ground-rent. This may be put concretely: Suppose A owns first-class land that will produce, say, 32 bushels of wheat to the acre, and that D's land is only fourth-class, producing 8 bushels. Suppose the cost of production in both cases to be 40 shillings per acre. (That is to say the capital expended by both in labour and depreciation of plant (V - C) is the same. Let however, the total capital invested by both be 80 shillings per acre). A has 32 bushels to sell, D has only 8 bushels. Let the quality be the same, then both get the same price per bushel. If the market needs D's wheat (and we will suppose it does), then supply and demand balance and the market-price of wheat is, in this case, the "price" of production, i.e., D's cost of production, plus the average rate of profit. That is to say the price of production (or, on our assumptions, the ordinary market-price) is the price of the wheat which re- quired the most labour per bushel to produce. The market- price cannot be less than that (except temporarily and under exceptional circumstances), otherwise D would not continue to invest his money in wheat-growing. If the price of wheat falls below D's price of production, he would receive less than the average rate of profit, or he might even suffer loss, in fact he must do so, if the "price" of production falls below his cost of production. If then the market price is D's price of produc- tion, wheat will be 7/6 per bushel. To yield a profit of 25 106 EXPLOITATION..10 per cent.. on 80 shillings (the total capital employed), a return of 20 shillings is required, and adding to this D's cost of pro- duction- 40 shillings-we get 60 shillings as his price of pro- duction. D then receives (8 x 7/6) 60 shillings, or his price of production, but A receives (32 x 7/6) 240 shillings, or180 shillings -more than D, in return for the same expenditure in plant' and labour. Now, it is evident that D could afford to rent A's land and pay to A 180 shillings per annum for the use of A's fertile land; but neither D nor anyone else could pay rent for D's poor land. His land, so long as the price of wheat does not rise above 7/6, can only.be worked rent free: it is, as economists say, on the margin of cultivation, it only returns a bare living. An inspection of Fig. 13 will make the matter clear. In the illustration the proportionate amount of rent has been greatly exaggerated. TOTAL CAPITAL lNVE5TEEP80/-.C+F40/- PRIEOFPRODCE IACRE 50V B ?IT CLASS o TORECRECEIPTPT2SX7 6 4x2180 YIELA5 401 C11 RENT=20-6 IACREI D ThCLASS RECEPTS7x7/660- YIELD 40/- ?20/ RffNT=0 -60 L i.1 .Acre blocks, owned by -B and C, of intermnediate degrees of. fertility* have been' interpolated to show how. differential rent arises. In. the diagram C + V is the cost. of production, and S that particular form' of surplus-value known as the average rate of profit;. the -sum of these two items forms the price of production. It may be noted here that land does not necessarily come into cultivation in the order of its fertility, but 'in the order 107 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. of the cost of production of its products, and the cost of clear ing the land of native growth, and of conveying the products to the market, is a part of the cost of production, and may be a large part. It has been shown that when the whole range of produc- tion is considered the total exchange-value equals the total in- herent value, and that the total inherent value consists of, and is measured by, the number of social standard hours embodied in utilities, or the individual standard hours given in service. In the tables and diagrams of value (see Appendix and chapter on Surplus-Value) in which the underlying laws of value are exhibited, it was assumed that plant and raw materials were stated at their true values (their social inherent-values), and not at their exchange-values, or their nominal values. The divergence between inherent and exchange-value may be very great. What, for example, is the inherent-value of the wheat produced by A, B, C and D, and what is its exchange-value? In all 32 +- 24 -3 16 + 8 = 80 bushels of wheat are produced and sold, at 7/6 per bushel. The total exchange-value is therefore 80 @ 7/6 = �30. Now what is the inherent-value? The question is more difficult. It depends on the average rate of exploitation of the worker-a reasonable assumption is 50 per cent. On that basis the inherent-value of each crop is 40 shillings plus 50 per cent.-60 shillings. And the inherent-value of the four crops is 4 x 60s. = 240s. -�12. Considering the four crops as one we have: Inherent-value �12: Exchange-value �30. The total crop is therefore (on our assumption) sold at 150 per cent. above its true value in S.H. Where does this value come from? It comes from the workers who manu- factured the articles virtually given in exchange for the wheat, but actually incorporated in the gold paid for the wheat. The worker receives �8, the capitalist-tenant-farmer �4. This �12 represents the true inherent-value of the wheat, but the land- lord gets �18 worth of exchange-value above the actual inherent- value of the wheat, a value which does not exist in the wheat at all. (The actual figures assumed are merely an illustra- tiion of the fact: and a fact of immense importance). The illustration indicates that exploitation of workers by the landlord is not confined to those who "rent" land but is passed on to every other class in the community. Agricul- tural ground rent rests on two supports, on one side the different degrees in fertility of different soils, and on the other hand the "price of production" involving the average rate of profit. The actual total return in bushels does not affect differential rent. Raise or lower the fertility all round and rent is unaffected, but increase the range of fertility,-the differ- 108 EXPLOITATION. 109 ences in fertility,-as when, for instance, fifth class land can be brought into cultivation, and the rent of the more fertile lands is increased. These differences form what is termed differential rent, as distinguished from pure monopoly rent. The 'price of production,' and its important constituent the 'average rate of profit,' depend on the general conditions of socialised industrial production, which determine the total surplus-value to be cut up. That constitutes, as we have said, one of the foundations of rent, a fact first pointed out by Marx. We have seen how the entrepreneur is exploited by the landlord in the first form of differential rent, but there is a second form which enables the landlord to increase his re- turns. It is a well-known fact that by better cultivation, and by the use of artificial manures, the fertility of land can be increased. But that costs money TOTALt CAPITAL INVESTZI /60/ PER ACRE. C-- V80/- PRCEOFPRODUCTION PRICE OF WH/EAT 7/6 PER BUSHEL IACRE COSTOFPRODY AvPROFIn A YtELDING C-+V . .TOTAL RECEIPTS = 3 - B�ELS 8o/- i 40/- RENT 360-120 = 340- I ACRE C YIELDING 80-7 40- 1lR - IACRE o aLng -. 10 RECE/PTS SO/- COST S- 12ELSPROFIT /0/ ORLES THANAVERAGE Fig. 14. NO RENT In the case under discussion the total amount of money capital applied to the land was 80 shillings per acre, with the results as stated. Suppose that by doubling this capital ex- penditure fertility in each case is increased 50 per cent. Will that investment pay in every case, and what will be the effect on rent? Assume that the demand for wheat increases at the same rate as increased production. Then the price of wheat will remain 7/6 per bushel. Further, assume that the same proportion of total capital invested, to capital used up, viz., one-half, still holds good. The result is shown in the dia- gram (figure 14). FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. It is seen that A, B and C have not only received the average rate of profit on their investment, but they have also received a share of 'rent' (provided their landlord has not been able to take it). A and B have gained considerably, and C to a lesser extent; but D, who made 20 shillings profit on the old basis, now finds he has only made 10 shillings on twice the amount of capital! Artificially enhanced fertility increases rent, but not always in proportion to the additional capital employed, and it enlarges, in some cases, the tenant's rate of profit, for so long as rent remains unchanged. Ultimately when leases are re- vised, the landlord is in a position to engross all the profit that exceeds the average rate. For the sake of simplicity we have in our illustration of the two forms of differential rent assumed that certain factors are constant. But just as the price of wheat, in reality, is rarely constant, but varies with supply and demand,-so there are other variable quantities in the equation. Marx takes some two dozen cases and thor- oughly exhausts the subject. It will be sufficient to refer the reader to his work for this more detailed treatment: enough has been said here to explain the general meaning of differ- ential rent. "Differential rent, however, is not confined to agricultural land: it affects also city and suburban land (used for build- ing), and mining properties. These have also their varying degrees of 'fertility.' By a larger outlay of capital, buildings of greater earning power can be erected, and by carrying these to a height of several stories the area of the site is virtually increased. Such "improvements" correspond to the use of fertilisers on agricultural land, and so bring city sites under the operations of differential rent in its second form. Here, too, ultimately, the landlord engrosses all above the average rate of profit. The same remark applies to suburban land, the most desirable sites command the highest price, or the great- est rent. It is the same in the case of mines: the fertility or rich- ness of a mine is the individual monopoly of its owner, and the rent (or 'royalty')* he can exact is determined precisely as in the case of agricultural lands by greater or less "rich- ness" and proximity to market. The introduction of more, or better, mining plant, creates the second form of differential rent. Nor is this all. In old countries, and indeed in some of the large cities of new countries-Sydney and Melbourne for example-another form of exploitation exists, or once existed. *The Royalties paid to the State are in most cases merely nominal. 110 EXPLOITATION. ':The overwhelming part of the land used in England for building purposes, but not -sold as freehold, is rented by the land-owners for 99 years, or for a shorter time if possible. After the lapse of this time the buildings fall into the hands of the land-owner, together with the land. The tenants are obliged to deliver the house to the great land-owner in a good habitable condition after the expiration of the lease, after having paid up to this time an exorbitant ground rent. Hardly has the lease expired, when the agent or inspector of the landlord comes,- inspects your house, takes care that you get it into good condition, takes possession of it, and annexes it to the domain of his landlord. The fact is that if this sys- tem is permitted to exert its full effects for some time longer, the entire ownership of houses as well as country real estate will be in the hands of the great landed proprietors. The whole of the West End of London, north and south of Temple Bar, belongs almost exclusively to half a dozen great landlords, is rented at enormous ground rents, and if the leases have not quite expired, most of them expire in rapid succession. The same applies in a greater or smaller degree to every city in the kingdom. But this greedy system of exclusiveness and mono- poly does not stop even here. Nearly all the docking facili- ties of :our port cities are in the hands of the great land levia- thans in consequence of the same process of usurpation."* As Marx says elsewhere, "One class of society is compelled to pay tribute to another class for permission to inhabit the earth." It is hardly a matter for wonder that single-taxers think they see in land-nationalisation a cure for all the eco- nomic ills of society. We have spoken of rent and of differential-rent almost as though they were interchangeable terms, But that is by no means so. A sharp distinction must be made between them. If all land had the same degree of 'fertility' then it is evident that differential-rentt would vanish with the differences on which it is founded. But rent would not vanish. Land, or its use, is at present sold and its price is affected by 'supply and demand' as well as by the rate of interest and the ave- rage rate of profit. Interest also is a form of surplus-value and surplus-value as a whole is increased by improvements in manufacturing. Thus, since these improvements reduce the inherent-value of real wages, a general increase in rent is due to improvements in agriculture. As Thorold Rogers points out: There is only one cause for a general rise in rent (population remaining constant): improvements in the process of agriculture. From the days of Henry III. to those of James I. no such economy or 111 *Das Kapital. tVifeenia-rntisofenteme eonmi rnt FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. improvement occurred. But from the time of James I., especially after the middle: of his reign, large and important improvements are made in agriculture, great economies discovered, and a rapid rise of rent ensues. It is to be regretted, though it is not to be wondered at, that these improvements and economies had no beneficial effect on the wages of labor. We have set forth the nature and incidence of rent under private ownership of land, and have glanced at the evils which arise iunder those conditions. It is not suggested that rent in itself is to be condemned. If at any stage of industrial development it is found desirable to allow the private and exclusive use of land by individuals-or even the private and exclusive use of capital-then the payment of rent by such individuals to the State-or of interest-is just, assuming that "nature" is, or should be, the common heritage of mankind. But private rent is always exploitation. Profit. The ambiguity of the terms used in the Science of Economics has already been noticed-"value" is one example, "profit" is another. It is as though botanists adopted common popular names to describe flowers--names varying with locality and possessing no underlying reference to structure, genus or family. Orthodox Economics has had no Linnaeus-not to say a Darwin. Perhaps a congress of professional economists will yet name and define the various phenomena of Capital- ism. In the meantime, failing all authority-even clear and definite convention-everyone is at liberty to coin his own terms. The retail grocer calls his net returns "profit," but he breaks down masses of products, the hundredweight or ton of sugar into pounds, and delivers these small quantities to the doors of consumers: performing a part of the work of distri- bution, he works, and his "profits" are "wages," or at least wages, plus profit, and possibly plus rent. Profit is what is left after cost (in its ordinary meaning) has been deducted from price, and delivery to the consumer constitutes a part of the cost of the product, if by production we mean an available product. Similarly to determine the profit of a merchant or a manu- facturer the wages of superintendence and all other costs for work done must first be deducted from total receipts because profit is a part of surplus-value-it is unpaid labor. Marx, as we have seen, divides surplus-value into absolute and rela- tive, and profit may be divided into monopoly-profit and differential-profit. Differential-profit and differential-rent 112 EXPLOITATION. arise from the exploitation of natural forces and materials and other exclusive industrial advantages. To illustrate that statement, let us suppose the existence of a community consisting of only two people, A and B. Sup- pose A cultivates the only acre of first-class land available yielding 32 bushels of wheat, and let B cultivate an acre of second-class land yielding 24 bushels. Let A and B work equally hard, use the same kind of implements and expend the same number 0f S.H1's on the work of cultivation. Then, as we have seen, A's differential-rent is the difference between the two returns (32-24), i.e., 8 bushels. Now take a case of differential profit. Suppose another community consisting of C and D, and let them shoot wild ducks: let C be armed with a shot gun-the only one available -and let D carry a bow and arrows. Let both work equally hard, .and: suppose C shoots 20. ducks and D shoots 6 ducks. The difference between the two returns (20-6), i.e., 14 ducks, is .differential profit. That is an example of differen- tial profit under simple production, it may be desirable to con- sider a ease under the more complex system known as Capi- talism. Suppose that in one place forty men coal a ship in four hours by carrying coal in a basket on their heads, while in another place four men do the same work in the same time by using a steam winch, or special coal-loading machinery. Let the cost of the fuel, &c., used for the winch and the deprecia- tion of the winch during the operation be represented by two mens work for four hours, then the work done is equivalent to six:men's work. Are these six men to reeeive the same re- mnuneration as the forty? If the average cost of the two coalings is �20, should the wages per man be �20 divided by six, i.e., �3/6/8 in one case, and �20 divided by forty, i.e., 10/- in the other? Would not the commensurate wage be two coalings at �20 equal �40 divided by forty-six men, i.e., 17/41 per man (4ssuming all the men to work equally hard) ? But if the rate of wages has been fixed by law or custom at 2/- per hour, then to the owner of the winch �17/12/- (�20 less six men at 8/- or �2/8/-) emerges as differential- profit. But the employer of the forty men only makes �4 (i.e., �20 less forty men at 8/- or �16) as profit, even when the workers supply their own baskets. The six men correspond to C, the forty men to D. Now if, in the first case, the community had consisted not, as has been premised, of A and B alone. but of several persons and classes then assuming modern conditions, the different re- turn to A would have passed, not to A himself but--as differ- ehtial rent-to a landlord. So in the second illustration had H :113 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. the community consisted, not of C and D alone but of several classes, the higher return to C would have passed not to C himself but in the form of differential profit to another mem- ber, the man whoever he was who furnished C with the gun and powder and shot. As in an enlarged community the land- lord can and does engross the difference in returns as rent, jso in an enlarged community the owner of the gun-the capi- talist-claims and receives the difference in return as profit. Only by presenting the case in vacuo by 'thinking away' land- lord and capitalist are we able to see how and whence differ- ential profit (like differential rent) arises. So far the position is clear. But in either illustration (from simple production) there has been omitted-for the sake of greater clearnests-an element of some importance, that of "indirect labor" or "wear and tear." The depreciation of capital is caused by the partial destruc- tion of the plant used. In effect a part of the labour contained in the plant passes over into the product whose manufacture has caused the "wear and tear" of the plant. This labour must be replaced, the capital must be maintained or made good. That its the necessary return to capital. That is the element we have, of purpose, overlooked. Suppose then that in the case of A and B the "wear and tear" of their plant costs 2 bushels, that either now or at some future time A and B must consume 2 bushels of wheat during the time they are making good the damage done to their plant by the cultivation of the particular acre in question. Their net returns are then (32-2), i.e., 30 bushels and (24-2), i.e., 22 bushels respectively, and A's true "differential rent" (which is really profit) is 30-22=8 bushels (as before).* But in the case of C and D who have not used the same kind of plant, suppose C who used the gun must consume 5 ducks while cleaning hits gun and making fresh powder and shot, while DT only consumes 1 duck in making fresh arrows. Their net returns are then (20---5), i.e., 15 and (6-1), i.e., 5 ducks respectively, and the true differential profit is (15-5), i.e., 10 ducks, and not 14 ducks as previously assumed. It may still be thought that the two caises taken from simple production are not parallel-that the forces contained in the land are the gift of Nature, but the forces contained in the gun are the gift of man. It maybe objected the differ- ence arises from the fact that although in one case man has made the forces of land available merely by making the land accessible, yet in the other case he has first to make the gun- *Here we see clearly that the total quantity haa nothing to do with the ase. It is the range of variation, the differences which determine "differ- ential rent" 114 EXPLOITATION. he must give to the materials of which it is compoksed useful form and adjustments--before he can make the explosive force of gunpowder available, and indeed he has to make the powder and shot or the arrows. That is true, but it is no less true that man has also to make the agricultural implements he uses before he can make available the forces of soil and sun and seed available. There is then no fundamental difference be- tween the two cases-they are clearly parallel: We assumed in the agricultural illustration that A and B used the same kind of implements, but they need not do tso, they might use different amounts of capital just as C and D did. To show the absolute identity of differential profit and the second form of differential rent take the case of E and F, in which both cultivate land yielding 16 bushels of wheat to the acre, but E uses a single furrow plough and two horses costing: �200, and F uses a four-furrow plough and six horses costing �400. Let E's cost of production be 3/- plus 37/- (C + V) = 40/- per acre and F's 6/- + 29/- (C + V) 35/- per acre. Had they both used the same kind of plant their costs would have been the same, either 40/- or 35/- per acre. As it is E's cost for 16 bushels is 40/-, while F's is only 35/-. The 5/- is clearly differential profit, because the fertility of the land is the same, it is the fertility of the capital that its differ- ent. Take another example: Suppose that the productivity of con- stant capital is five times as great as the productivity of variable capital and let the organic composition of four equal capitals of 80 owned by G, H, I and J be as shown below, then the products of c-+-v G are 5 x 70 + 10 360 products H ,, 5 x 60 +20 320 ,, I ,, 5 x 50 +30 = 280 ,, J ,, 5 x 40 40 = 240 ,, The total capital in each case is 80: the profits are proportional to the resulting products. The differences are: G 360 - 240 = 120 H 320- 240 = 80 I 280 -240 = 40 J 240- 240= - And these differences are due to the varying fertility of the capital employed, they are differential profit. Had these vary- ing differences been due to varying fertility of virgin soil individual landlords would have pocketed them as rent, why then cannot our capitalists pocket the differential profit due 115 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. to the use of machinery of various efficiencies ? Why must they share these profits on a total capital employed basis, among all the members of their class? The form of the question supplies the answer: because land is an individual pos:session, but capital is the possession of a class. Any capitalist can buy the same kind of plant as is used by any other capitalist. E, for instance, can purchase a four-furrow plough and six horses, and for the same price that F paid, but natural fertility cannot be made; each piece of land is unique. If we make: land fertile by artificial meants that fertility is due to labour (and capital), but the fertility natural to land is quite irrespective of our labour in getting at it or artificially improving it. The quantity of heat or gunpowder is the direct result of, and proportional to, the labor it con- tains: land cannot be made as: a gun, or a plough, is made. There is strict limitation in the quantity and position of land, but capital, although not unlimited, has not the same limita- tions. But, for so long as a capitalist remains alone in the possession and use of better machinery, or improved methods of production, for so long he can reap differential profit. If other capitalists are unable to enter into competition with him, or if he forms a trust or combine and keeps his machinery or trade process seecret, he, and the other members of the trust, can reap more than the average rate of profit. In a word, so long as capital or particular forms of capital, can be monopolised entirely, just for so long the monopolists can raise their profit above the average rate of profit. But it can only be done at the expense of others. There is only the total surplus-value to cut up, and it is axiomatic that the sum of the parts cannot be greater than the whole: only by making the whole greater can all the parts be increased. If, however, real wages are reduced, the total surplus-value is increased, and the capitalist's share is made greater. We have seen that when all land has the same degree of fertility differential rent vanishes--but monopoly rent does not vanish, becautse it depends on individual monopoly. When all capitals are of the same organic composition, and are equally well organised and managed, differential profit vanishes, but profit does not vanish because it depends on the difference between cost and price. Surplus-value equals rent, plus profit, plus intereast, and the total surplus-value can be increased (a) by increasing the total quantity of commodities (wages and prices remaining constant), or (b) by reducing wages (the quantity of com- modities and their prices remaining constant), or (c) by a combination of (a) and (b). 116 EXPLOITATION. A general increase of rent, profit and intereast is only possible by increasing the total amount of surplus-value by increasing the number of workers, or the rate of exploitation, but a.particular increase in rent, or profit, or interest is pos- sible if the share of one, or both, of the other constituents of surpluys-value is reduced. Interest. Interest is a part of surplus-value. It is a payment by the entrepreneur (or 'c.mpany') to his sleeping partner, the money-capitalist or banker. Interest is gross, material, tan- gible, there is nothing ethereal about it. It does not drop- like the gentle rain-from heaven. It is not a mental state, an abtstraction, or a mere idea. It is a concrete return-under Capitalism--for the loan of money. The money does not breed, but with money the instruments of production-land, machinery and raw materials-can be bought and wages paid. Interest comes from the exploitation of the labourer. The prejudice-almost universal-against interest has, therefore, a rational basis. Like rent, interest has an historical develop- ment. It is an historical necessity, a part of the system of Capitalism, but it existed before Capitalism, in its full name, came into being. Interest is a part of surplus-value, but so is rent, and interest may be paid out of rent. In olden days the large land-owner borrowed to spend money in display or in riotous living; the small land-owner borrowed, as he does to-day, to assist his individual production, or to keep the wolf from the door. Thus both large and small land-owners often fall into the clutches of the usurer. Not until the other prerequisites of capitalist production are present, does usury become a means of assisting in the formation of the new mode of production by ruining the feudal lord and small scale pro- duction on the one hand and centralising the means of production into capital on the other. Several theories of interest have been put forward by one or another economist, but, that it its the reward of abstinence! is perhaps the orthodox explanation, and the rate of interest depends upon-the rate of impatience! Chickens exist be- cause we 'abstain' from eating eggs and the rich are rich because they patiently abstain from the enjoyment of their wealth-or they have done so in the past, or if not, then their fathers have-with intelligent foresight preferring future benefit to present joy. And, in a sense, the theory is true, in so far at least as it affirms that 'someone' has abstained from the consumption of wealth. How otherwise can capital come into existence? 117 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. The Saxons abstained from the consumption of the goods taken from them by the robber barons who came over with William the Conqueror, they abstained from using the land granted by William to individual Normans, they abstained from using the products of the labour they spent on the lord's land, just as the modern labourer abstains from consuming that portion of the goods he produces which constitutes ksur- plus-value. Interest, then, is truly the result of abstinence, the abstinence of the 'other fellow.' It follows naturally that the rate of interest depends on the rate of impatience, that it is, in fact, directly proportional to the rate of impatience!- an impatience effectively restrained by the force of circum- stances-the poor circum-stances of the labourer. Man is so constituted that he would "rather have it now than wait until he gets it" in the ordinary course of events-impatient man! But it is the labourer's necessity rather than his impatience which compels him to discount (i.e., in part to sacrifice), daily or weekly, the contribution his work has made towards exchange-value. His labour has added inherent-value to the articles he has worked on and has made or partly made, before he receives his wages, although the exchange-value of those goods may not have been realised, i.e., the goods may not have been sold. Wages are not in reality paid in advance. And it is just on this time element that Boehm-Bawerk founds his theory of interetst. It is an agio--blessed word. Well, time and space are the field of all activities (time is the fourth dimension) and consequently rent and wages, sudden death and a future life are all agios. But exactly what does 'agio' mean ? In olden days debased and clipped coin was taken to a bank and "good" money called Bank Money of exactly the same value was issued in exchange. Bank money was always at a premium or agio compared with equal quantities of de- based money-but there was no increase in value, fewer good coins were issued in exchange for debased coins, but in sum both were of equal value. There is nothing whatever in the word to explain interest. The fact its that technological processes take time. Interest js a return of which time is a special function. Otherwise time has nothing to do with the case. Time, which improves wine, turns cider sour and generally causes deterioration in com- modities. Behind Boehm-Bawerk's time-movement lies the 'fructifi- cation' theory of interest-if you live long enough, instead of an acorn you shall receive an oak tree, and indeed the oak claimed to-day was an acorn once. The theory is a return to the exploded ideas of the Physiocrats who thought that only Nature created surplus-value; it is, in fact, a monopoly claim 118 oni the bounties of Nature. An increase in the quantity of products is not necessarily an increase in exchange value; but, in any case, the claim is a claim for the exclusive owner- ship of a natural product. We discover in nearly every theory of interest a sufficient reason but not an efficient cause; how, when, .and where we get the interest, we are called upon to pay, is not explained. On the other hand, we have explained the natural and artificial causes of differential rent and differ- ential profit, and the cause of interest. How to abolish mono- poly :rent, profit and interest and the correct method of dis- tributing differential rent and profit constitute, in fact, the industrial social problem. Rate of Interest.-We have seen that of the total surplus- value landlords are able to engross as rent all that portion which rises above the average rate of profit on the total capital employed. They do this by increasing the price of the raw materials manufacturers use. The manufactuer or entrepreneur has then to reckon with the Money-capitalist, generally the banker, that is if he has borrowed money to carry on his enterprise. How then, and on what terms, is the rest of the spoil to be divided? Spoil, we say, because the entrepreneur has already received his wages of supervision. Salaries and wages are not a part of surplus-value. In other words, what rate of interest must the entrepreneur pay to the banker? It is quite evident that the entrepreneur cannot pay more in interest than the profit he makes-his net profit-unless he suffers an actual loss. Nor will he agree to pay all the net profit he expects to make. Interest is a payment for the use of money, or, and more generally, for credit, i.e., for a claim on goods. Interest often takes the form of discount-the banker buys a bill for �100, payable in three months, and gives, say, �99 now: the rate of discount is then 4 per cent. We may then include discount when speaking of interest. Although the banker appears to be able to fix the rate of interest he must, in reality, follow the conditions of trade as they exhibit themselves in the rela- tion which his reserves (of gold) bear to his advances (loans of eredit). Under normal conditions of trade our banker has learned by experience-often bitter-that he must maintain a certain relation between his reserves and his advances, and he finds he can do this by varying the rate of interest (or dis- count). Under abnormal conditions the gold reserve cannot be big enough. Reserves and advances may be compared to two horses in a race whose relative positions must be maintained. The banker has power (during the race) to increase or reduce the handicap weight carried by Advances. If Advances gets EXPLOITATION. 119 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. too far ahead (of Reserves) he is loaded with a greater weight of interest. If Advances falls back too far he is relieved of some of the weight he carries. The load of interest is reduced, and in this $simple fashion the desired relative position is-if due care is exercised-maintained. We have admitted that-superficially at least-the amount of the banker's gold reserve does affect the rate of interest and it is no doubt true that a maladjustment of advances and reserves may precipitate a commercial crisis, but the cautses of such crises lie far deeper, they are embedded in the very con- stitution of Capitalism itself, as we shall see when we come to treat of its economic contradictions. For our present pur- pose it its neither necessary nor profitable to attempt to unravel the tangled threads which-as in the case of exchange-value- go to make up a knotty problem, viz., the rate of interest at any particular time and place. To clear up the dark mystery of private banking requires the illumination of a whole chap- ter. Rent, profit, and interest are capitalistic terms used by economists and accepted by them in their ordinary "business" se ;se, they are not scientific terms. We must perforce accept them, but, thanks to Marx, we can sum them up in the term surplus-value, and Marx has divided surplus-value into: (1) Absolute, and (2) Relative. We have attempted to show that relative surplus-value has a "natural' basis, and to define utilities more clearly have divided them into (a) natural and (b) artificial, meaning by (a) those forcers and materials which are useful to man as they are presented by Nature, and by (b) those forces and materials which must be made useful. We may then tabulate an analysis of surplus-value as below: Monopoly Rent Absolute ,, Profit ,, Interest Surplus- Value Differential Rent (natural forces and Relative materials) ,, Profit (artificial forces and Smaterials) If natural conditions are uniform-which they never are- differential rent would vanish. If industrial conditionts are uniform-as appears to be impossible-differential profit would vanish. If the agents of production, land and capital, are "socialised"--as is quite possible-absolute surplus-value would vanish. An analysis of Capitalism in tabulated form is shown below. Professional men and working farmers who own their land and plant, but who do not employ labourers (to whom 120 EXPLOITATION.12 should be added working jewellers and others) are remnants of a dying system (domestic), but although not of Capitalism they are in Capitalism, and if they do not own the whole of their means of production outright, are, to that extent, merely agents for the collection and payment of rent and interest to the real owners. Shopkeepers generally pay rent and are more and more squeezed out by emporiums and forced into the rank of shop assistants. 'Landlords' of public houses (tied houses), and shopkeepers too, tend to become mere agents for merchants and' are' practically receivers of wages on a piecework or com- mission basis. Yet they are ,often the ..fiercest opponents of Socialism! Landlord-=Capitalist Landlords Agri'i-la~nd Mine City Land Owners Owners Owner tenant Mining Merch'nts & Farmers Capita lts Shopkeepers Farm Miners. Clerks :and Lab'rei Shop Assts Capitalists Bankers Entre- y preneurs I I Managers Industrial and Clerks Workers 121. FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. VIII. The Great Private Bank Fraud. If the average man in the street is asked: "What is a bank?" he might reply: "It is a place where they lend money." If he is then asked: "Where do they get the money from?" he may reply: '-' The shareholders put up some of it, but for the most part it is lent to the bank at 3 or 4 per cent. by people who do not know how to invest it safely. The bank accepts these fixed deposits and lends them at 6 or 7 per cent., and so makes a profit." Wrong! Absolutely and utterly wrong, so far as the chief function of a modern bank is concerned-- as we hope to make perfectly clear in this chapter. We have already dealt with money; currency and credit naturally follow. Currency may be defined as any written promise to pay current coin or render a service which by mere transfer conveys to another the right to receive the coin or service specified in the document. By debt is meant a legal claim or right to money or service, and if such rights are transferable by merely passing some document from hand to hand, such documents are currency. To be transferable then a debt must take some material form such as bank notes, cheques, bills of exchange, post office orders, postage stamps, etc., but unless they represent debt they are not currency. Old coins do not represent debt, they are not current money. Strictly speaking current gold coin is not currency, it is the thing promised and not merely the material evidence of an obligation. Bank notes* are not currency unless and until they represent debt. A Government may print thousands of notes, but until they are paid away for something received they are not currency-they are not in circulation. An exchange, whether of goods or services, involves two things, the thing that is given and the thing that is received. Now suppose that the operation of exchange is only half completed, say that I have handed over some valuable thing, but have not received value in return, but merely a promise to pay, I am then a creditor, and have a legal right of action to e dforce, if necessary, my claim against the other party to * y currency we mean actual currency; bank notes before they are issued are potential currency. 122 THE GREAT PRIVATE BANK FRAUD. the exchange, who is now called a debtor. If the agreement between us is "spot cash," I can, if necessary, demand settlement at once; if, however, the agreement is that I am not to be paid for (say) three months from a given date, my right of action is suspended for three months from that date. The paper on which that deferred claim, or any other deferred claim, is recorded in writing constitutes currency, provided the claim can be transferred by merely handing the paper to someone else. Currency then represents the incomplete half of an exchange. Currency is a token of indebtedness, it May be a postage stamp, a railway ticket, a bank note, a bill of exchange-only when the letter has been carried, or the owner of the ticket taken to the place specified, or the gold coin paid, is the transaction completed. We say the gold coin paid because bank notes and bills of exchange are invariably promises to pay gold (in a certain form), but currency is a promise of what is to be paid. Some people think that gold coin represents debt; that is obviously erroneous. Gold coin (of the specified amount) completes the exchange; it is one of the things-and not a representative of the things-exchanged. The fact that we do not wear or eat or otherwise consume gold coin, but (gene- rally) only want the gold coin because we can exchange it for something else we do want to consume, only shows that gold coin is capital-a capital good-a means of acquiring a consumption good. Gold as we know is (by convention) one medium of exchange-but only one of many. But it is more than a means of exchange, it is commodity, it is actual wealth, whereas a bank note only represents wealth. Of course there is a sense in which paper promises to pay may be said to be commodities because as we shall see these promises to pay, or tokens of wealth, are what banks principally deal in, but it must always be remembered that they are not in themselves wealth and they are only valuable in so far as they are a means of obtaining real wealth. Some writers, e.g., Macleod, claim that these promises are actual wealth. The contention is manifestly absurd. A nation is not actually richer because all its possessions are embodied in promises to pay, it is in that case absolutely poor, nor is it actually richer here and now, because it holds the promises of other nations to pay (as France no doubt realises) it is only potentially richer. Currency then is not wealth, it only represents the actual wealth to be given in exchange for wealth actually received. The word, however, is not always used in that sense. In fact, here as elsewhere, in the so-called science of economics, we 123 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. find the utnmost confusion of terms. Unless we define we are undone, and the reader must try to put aside his own pre- conceptions. By Specie or Cash we mean hard cash, current coin in gold, silver or copper; actual wealth by which an exchange is completed. (Silver and copper coins are, however, in part wealth and in part tokens of wealth.) Gold means pure gold, but sometimes the word may mean bullion. Bullion is an alloy consisting of eleven parts of pure gold and one part of copper, of which current sovereigns are made. A sovereign weighs 123.274 grains of Troy (standard weight), but it only contains about 113 grains of pure gold (or, to be exact, 113 grains and one-six hundred and twenty- third of a grain). Money is whatever may be legally tendered or accepted in full satisfaction of debt. Generally it is bullion in the form of coin. It then not only satisfies the debt, it also completes the exchange. But when gold payments are legally suspended bank notes must be accepted in full satisfaction of debt though they do not complete the exchange. Currency is often held to mean money, or the circulating medium of coin and, notes; in fact to be synonymous with money. We give it a much wider and in some respects a narrower meaning and have defined it as whatever represents debt, and at the same time transfers, the specified "right" to the holder. Money in the form of gold coin does not represent debt, it completes an exchange. The only ambiguity consists in what is meant by transferable. Here we trench on the distinction between currency and credit. A bearer cheque, clearly, is cur- rency, but an order cheque is not, until it has been endorsed. A crossed cheque, not negotiable, is never currency--nor in- deed is it credit, it is an order to a bank to transfer credit. To explain that much misunderstood matter--credit-is the chief object of this chapter, and more especially that form of credit known as bank credit. But credit existed before banks were invented. Promises to pay gold coin, often called bills of exchange, were first used (in modern times) by the Italians. Thus Antonio's promise to pay Bernardo could be used by Bernardo to satisfy his debt to Luigi, if the latter was equally convinced of the good faith and solvency of Antonio. Thus Bernardo of Rome, having shipped to Antonio at Genoa 100 casks of wine, draws a bill on Antonio for their value, 10,000 lire; owing Luigi (of Rome) a similar sum for a house he has bought from him, Bernardo hands him in payment his bill or claim on Antonio. Luigi transmits it to Saladio of Genoa, from whom he has bought silk to a similar value, and Saladio 124 THE GREAT PRIVATE BANK FRAUD. ultimately receives from his fellow townsman Antonio the amount due in the first place to Bernardo, and thus the con- fidence of those men in the good faith of a fourth, and his ability to pay in gold, or other valuable commodity, if re- quired, has made it possible to complete those large trans- actions without the passing of anything more than a piece of paper. Obviously the process could be greatly extended, the bill might, on similar conditions-the soundness of Antonio's credit-pass through thirty or three hundred hands, but there will be a limit to those who know and trust Antonio. If for this. reason only, and there are many more, there is greater use for another form of representative or paper money, the bank note. The bank note is a piece of paper bearing the legend '. '�5 "The Bank of promises to pay to the bearer the sum of Five Pounds in gold on demand. "Signed " But there is still another form of promise to pay gold of far greater use and importance than the bank note, i.e., bank credit. Bank credit may provisionally be defined as bank book entries--figures written in the books of a bank-instead of on transferable pieces of paper. (Credit, clearly, is not cur- rency since it cannot be passed from hand to hand). First let us seek the origin and trace the history of such "book entries." The rudiments of banking were taught to the Romans by the Greeks, but we may confine our en- -quiries to the former nation. The "gens" or gentile system passed, as we have seen, into the patriarchal family, and some portions of the family possessions gradually became merged into the "right" of the head of the family. According to Maeleod the dominus, by custom or law, was compelled to keep a family ledger as strictly as that of a modern banker, showing all receipts and expenditures, money borrowed and money lent, and all profits and losses. These ledgers were carefully preserved in a safe placed in a special apartment of the house. But gradually, from being a record of family possessions, they become records of the personal possessions of the dominus, and in time ex- clusive possession by other members of the family was re- corded. Private ownership, in fact, evolved and exchange between individuals, as we know it, became possible. SAt first agreements to exchange or to complete an ex- change at a future date were merely verbal-a stipulation- with witnesses. Later these verbal stipulations were reduced to a written promise to pay on a specified date, and were then 125 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. termed "obligationes litteris." These written promises to pay, or Bills of Exchange, are the "goods" which modern banks buy. But note that these goods are merely promises to pay real goods, namely, gold coin, and are not in them- selves actual goods. We repeat this distinction so often be- cause it is essential to a clear understanding of the subject matter, since the principal function of a bank is to buy debts and to pay for them by credits, or book entries. The original owner of the debt or Bill of Exchange or promise to pay cash on some future date can, by his order (cheque) on the bank (to whom the Bill has been sold) obtain cash, or a transfer of credit, at once. For this advantage a discount is paid. But this essential bank function only evolved gradually. Money (cash) only became common in England about the middle of the 13th century. The receipts given to the Knights of the Holy Cross at the time of the Crusades, for gold plate, jewels and other valuables left for safekeeping, were the forerunners of the modern bank note-but the child was not exactly like its father. The actual things lent or left for storage were at first returned, but when those things took the form of cash, the property in the cash passed to the borrower, who gave to the lender a receipt or right of action for the return of a similar quantity or value in cash-the identical money lent was not returned. So if we lend our neighbour a spade we expect him to return the actual spade lent, but if we lend him a loaf of bread or a pound of sugar we expect another loaf and pound of sugar in return. The latter form of loan was called "Mutuum." Macleod persists in calling a debt a saleable commodity, whereas it is more correct to describe it as a saleable legal right of action against a debtor for the recovery of a com- modity. In any case, however, these "rights" or debts can be bought and sold. A Bill of Exchange generally takes the following form:- "�150. London, May 20th, 1907. Three months after date pay to John Smith (or to my- self) or order the sum of one hundred and fifty pounds for value received. To William Robinson, Esq.) (Signed) Henry Jones." New York. Henry Jones is the drawer, William Robinson the drawee, and John Smith the payee. Robinson accepts the bill by endors- ing it with his name. If Smith also endorses it, it becomes payable to bearer, that is, it becomes currency. If it is sold to a banker who "credits" the account of the seller with �150, debits him with the "discount" agreed on, it is bought 126 THE GREAT PRIVATE BANK FRAUD. with and exchanged for a bank credit and not for cash. Smith has then discounted the bill-obtained an immediate credit, for cash payable in the future. Now in this case what has really happened? Certain present goods actually exist and are mentioned in a Bill of Lading, the legal ownership of the Bill of Lading entitles the holder to receive the goods. The goods in question-we will suppose-were manufactured by Henry Jones in London and sold to William Robinson of New York. Jones instructs Rob- inson to pay the price of the goods (i.e., draws a bill on Rob- inson) to John Smith to whom Jones owes �150. Robinson agrees to do so (accepts the bill), and Smith, who wishes to use at once the money he is entitled to in three months, or so, sells the bill to a bank and the bank buys it for (say) �148, making a profit of �2 by the simple process of writing a few figures in its books. We have seen how Antonio's promise to pay (bill of ex- change) was able to settle the accounts of Bernado, Luigi, and Saladio-all of which (and there might have been hundreds instead of three or four) were finally completed by the single ash payment made by Bernado when his bill matured. Thus a single transfer of one sovereign may settle ten or twenty separate debts of �1 each. Probably everyone will remem- ber the ease with which, as school boys, we solved formidable looking sums in multiplication of fractions, and the pleasure with which we realised that it was quite unnecessary first to multiply by six and then divide by six, that even multipli- cation by twenty-four and division by eight could be reduced. by cancellation, to a simple multiplication by three. And it is this delightful process of cancelling-the mere transfer of figures in a bank's books-that enables a bank to erect such a huge superstructure of credit on such a small foundation of gold. Now-a-days banking in each nation is one great business. Competing banks no longer try to break each other as they once did. They are all--in effect-amalgamated in what is known as the "Clearing House." Cheques drawn on one bank, but paid into another bank, are mutually presented, and insofar as they are equal, cancelled. Only the margins, the final plus or minus of all transactions between two banks, are settled in cash (or notes). Indeed when there is a general cash reserve, held by a Bank of England or some State or Federal Authority, a mere book entry serves to transfer each bank's claim to cash, which all the time reposes peacefully in the common or general reserve. The nominal basis of credit -bullion-recedes more and more into the background as a medium of exchange; as a measure of value it still remains, y 127 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. since all credits, all bills of exchange, all purchases, all debts are expressed in terms of gold. But the real foundation of "credit" consists chiefly of the material goods represented by the bill of exchange (or by securities) bought for credit by the bank. The bank, in effect, turns our actual goods into purchasing power, before the goods are sold to consumers. It is enabled to do so by the confidence the public reposes in its power to pay (when and if required) gold coin, and thus complete the exchange. Note, then, that the owner of goods pays interest on his own wealth. The chief function of a bank is to turn solid wealth into purchasing power; to, in effect, liquify private wealth by the simple process of writing figures in a book. Suppose, for example, I am the owner of shares in, say, the British Tobacco Company, valued on the Stock Exchange at �2000 (exchange- value). If. i deposit my 'scrip' with a banker I may be able to arrange for an 'overdraft' of �1000. Bankers are always careful to leave a safe margin between exchange- and inherent- value. As a prelude to charging me, say, 7 per cent. for the accommodation my banker will probably tell me that 'money' is tight or scarce just now, and that my application must go before the Board..: The cost price of the service the bank renders me is about 21 per cent., the balance, 4 .per cent., is pure profit. Having arranged the matter, I draw a cheque for, say, �100 in favor of John Smith for goods received: Smith sends my cheque to his banker and asks him to credit his (Smith's) account. His banker collects �100 from my banker through the Clearing House. Now what has happened? (1) Debit entry for �100 has been made in my bank account, and a credit entry for the like amount in Smith's bank account. (2) I have become liable to my bank for 7 per cent. per annum on a hundred pounds' worth of my British Tobacco Company shares, which I have, in effect, temporarily or permanently transferred to John Smith in payment of my debt; that is, to complete the exchange. My bank has undoubtedly rendered me a service. When it honored my cheque for �100 it assured Smith that I was 'worth' (at least) �100. The bank, moreover, became liable to pay Smith (if and when called upon) �100 in gold or in bank notes. But the bank ran no risk.: its 'security' was .ample The cost price of the service it rendered (about 24 per cent.) .is. all it was justly entitled to, and with fewer banks or only one the cost of the service might be considerably reduced. A - pure profit of 41 per cent. may seem 'reasonable,' but consider: the profit made was profit on the capital (in com- 128 THE GREAT PRIVATE BANK FRAUD. modity form) owned by the bank's customer: on the money capital actually put up by the shareholders of the bank (ex- cluding capitalised profits) the profit was at least 40 per cent.: it may have been 400 per cent. It may in fact be said that banks make 40 per cent. (calculated on their own capital) out of the money capital of their -clients or customers and 400 per cent. out of their customers' commodity capital (securities). That seems incredible. In support of that statement we may quote from the work of an orthodox conservative economist-one who believes that value is a ratio! Macleod, in his "Theory and Practice of Banking," Vol. I., pp. 324-326, says:- We must now explain how a banker trades with money. Suppose his customers pay in �10,000 to their accounts: then the money becomes the banker's absolute property as a "mutuum." After such an opera- tion his accounts would stand thus:-- Liabilities. Assets. Deposits ......... �10,000 Cash ........ �10,000 It may be said, in ordinary and quiet times, a banker's balance in cash will seldom differ by more than one-thirty-sixth part from day to day. [Incomings and outgoings will balance to that extent.] So that if he retains one-tenth of his customers' cash to meet any demands which may be made upon him, that is ample and abundant in ordinary times. If then, in the above example, the banker retains �1,000 in cash to meet any demands upon him, he has �9,000 of his customers' money to trade with. Suppose that the "banker" buys �40,000 of commercial bills at three months, and that the agreed upon Profit was 4 per cent., then the sum to'be retained on the bills would be �400, leaving himself liable for �39,600. His accounts would stand thus:- Liabilities. Assets. Deposits ....... �49,600 Cash ............ �10,000 Bills of Exchange 40,000 �49,600 �50,000 the balance of �400 being his own property or profit. By this process the 'banker' has . . . created �39,600 in credit and his Profit is clear: he has not gained 4 per cent. on the �9,000 in cash, but 4 per cent. on �40,000. (Black type mine.) Note now a very common popular error: from the banker's point of view a deposit is not the Bill of Exchange placed afterpurchase, in the vaults of a bank; it is, by a natural trans- lation, the credit entry in the Bank's ledger in the account of Jones, or of whoever sells the Bill to the bank: it is a liability to pay money to Jones and not an asset. Many people imag- ine that a bank which has large deposits is in a strong posi- tion, whereas a deposit is a liability the bank has to meet. The granting of a credit gives an individual a legal claim against 129 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. the bank-a right of action-for the amount of the credit (in cash on demand). But because individuals believe they can get cash on demand they do not ask for it-for the most part they are satisfied with transfers of credit. In the example just given of the �10,000 cash shown as an asset, �9,600 is in reality a liability, only the �400 profit is a real asset. The fiction of mutuum need not deceive us. So much depends on the point of view. Thus we see that the special essence of a banker's busi- ness is, not to lend money, but on the basis of bullion to create a vast superstructure of credit, or as Macleod puts it:- A banker is a trader who buys Money and Debts by creating other Debts. Creating is Macleod's word, and here-from the banker's point of view-it is well chosen. The Messenians had a proverb- "There is a Profit before a Profit, and yet another Profit still"; and they laughed at the Natural Philosophers who said, "'Nothing can come from Nothing." Yet Macleod quotes this saying with approval, he actu- ally believes that credit is created out of nothing. Thus he sums up a long argument: "Hence we see that the mere will of man has created vast masses of Wealth out of Notli ing!" And then it is 'decreated'! Because a Bill of Exchange, unlike a Bill of Lading, can become detached from the actual goods that gave it being and can be used as money, or as a bank note, or other promise to pay, and can thus be made to represent the incomplete half of any exchange of equal value Macleod loses sight of the material reality on which it is founded. Take for example the Bill of Exchange for �150 drawn by Manufacturer Jones on Merchant Robinson (and accepted by him) in payment for goods received. Jones, after some (circumlocution, gets �148 spot cash for his �150 worth of goods. But the goods, we may suppose, have only cost Jones �140. Then of the �10 surplus value the goods contained Jones is compelled by the force of circumstances to yield �2 to the bank. The �2 is not "created," but made by Jones' workmen. But the bank acquires the �2 by the simple pro- cess of writing figures in its books and issuing a cheque book. The depositor then writes out a cheque and sends it by post to his private creditor-in nine cases out of ten he does not personally draw cash and personally hand the cash to his creditor. The result is that the banks find by experience that a little cash goes a long way. For the most part a mere transfer of figures in their books does the trick. 130 THE GREAT PRIVATE BANK FRAUD. 131 As Professor Agger, of Columbia University, says:- The significance of these matters to a bank's profit can be force- fully illustrated by assuming a hypothetical case. Suppose that a bank has cash deposits of 200,000 dollars, and suppose further that in the absence of any legal restriction the bank learns by experience that because of the general use of checks as currency in its community and because of the maintenance of comfortable balances by the de- positors, a cash reserve of 10 per cent. is adequate to meet direct demands for cash as well as possible debit balances at the clearing house. Twenty thousand dollars would then suffice to meet the cash demands of, and the clearing house requirements arising from the checks drawn by, the depositors of cash. One hundred and eighty thousand dollars would then be released to the bank for other pur- poses. If now borrowers from the bank have about the same relative cash needs as the depositors of cash, and if they maintain an approxi- mately equivalent balance, the whole of the 180,000 dollars may be used as a 10 per cent. reserve for the deposit liabilities that the bank may safely add to those assumed when the cash itself was deposited. In other words, instead of earning interest on only 180,000 dollars the bank may earn interest on just ten times that amount, namely, 1,800,000 dollars. On the basis of a 4 per cent. rate this would mean an annual income of 7,200 dollars, if the bank's lending power were limited to the actual cash held above the reserve required for cash depositors; but when this cash may itself be used as a 10 per cent. reserve against further deposits extended to the public, the annual income at the same rate leaps to 72,000 dollars. This is to say, on a 10 per cent. reserve basis every dollar in cash means an increase of 9 dollars in the bank's lending power. That explains why the bank can afford to maintain an expensive establishment, to supply stationery, and to undertake free of charge the collection of checks, coupons, etc., for its depositors. In the banking business nothing succeeds like de- posits. But let us take an actual case-the Bank of England. The facts and largely the words are taken from Macleod's book on Banking. Banking, in the modern sense of the word, had no exist- ence n England before the year 1640. Up to that period merchants had been, for a considerable time, in the habit of depositing their bullion and cash in the Mint in the Tower, for convenience and security, under the guardianship of the Crown. The King-Charles 1.-seized the merchants' bullion and cash in the Tower to the amount of �120,000. He was beheaded in 1649, nevertheless (!) in 1672 Charles II. seized �1,328,526; of this sum �416,725 belonged to Sir Robert Viner alone. The bankers, it is true, were not numerous, but the money they had belonged, in great part, to their customers, and of these were 10,000: some of their customers went mad, others committed suicide. The Act incorporating the Bank of England received the Royal assent on the 25th April, 1694. It directed that the sum of �100,000 a year should be granted to persons making *"Organised Banking," p. 32. FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. a voluntary war loan of �1,200,000 to the Government. The subscribers to the loan, on which slightly over 8 per cent. per annum was to be paid, were to be allowed to assign and trans- fer their stock and interest, and to receive the usual privileges of a corporation. They were to be allowed to deal in Bills of Exchange, buy and sell bullion, gold and silver, and to lend money on security. The Bank Act of 1697 provided that no other bank should be sanctioned by Act of Parliament. In 1704 and again in 1707 the bank was in difficulties, and agreed- 1. That interest on their original stock of �1,200,000 be reduced to 6 per cent. (�72,000 instead of �100,000), with an allowance of �4,000 for managing the debt. 2. That the bank would advance a further sum of �400,000 at 6 per cent. interest. 3. That they be allowed to double their present capital of �2,201,171 10s. at the price 115 per cent. for the new stock. Upon which they agreed to circulate �2,500,000 of Exchequer bills and receive an allowance of 6 per cent. on it, one-half for interest and the other for repayment of principal. 4. That their privileges* as a corporation should be con- tinued for 21 years from 1st August, 1711, to 1732. Thus the Bank actually lent to Government �1,200,000 plus �400,000, but still had it as stock, whilst the Government paid them a yearly sum of �246,000 and allowed the existing shareholders to take a bonus of �330,000 from incoming share- holders. Notwithstanding that fact, the new shareholders stood on velvet, and it is no wonder that when subscriptions for new stock opened on the 22nd of February, 1709, at nine in the, morning, it was fully subscribed by one o'clock the same day. No wonder the shareholders agreed with Macleod in thinking that wealth could be created! In 1716 the bank was empowered to borrow money at any rate of interest they pleased upon their bills, bonds and any obligation under their Common Seal, or upon the credit of their capital stock, and their existence was prolonged prac- tically indefinitely. The first Act of 1697 prevented the Bank from making advances to the Government without the express permission of Parliament, but Pitt in 1793 passed an Act to remove this restriction. The 'creation' of wealth by writing figures in a book then went on apace. The creation was performed by the Bank, the interest was paid by the Government. In a few months no *No other corporation exceeding six persons was to be allowed to issue Promissory Notes payable on demand, i.e., Bank Notes. 132 THE GREAT PRIVATE BANK FRAUD. less than �1,613,345 was created. These issues were all pro- mises to pay gold on demand, and as past and often bitter experience had taught the directors of the Bank the danger of credit issues enormously in excess of their gold reserves, they remonstrated with Mr. Pitt, who promised that advances on Treasury bills should be reduced to �500,000-a promise he never kept. On the contrary, in July, 1796, he asked for an- other �800,000 at once, and a similar sum in August. Re- luctantly the directors yielded. "Much would have more," and in the following November Pitt made a fresh demand for �2,750,000, and got it. It is so easy to create! i.e., to forestall taxation. In February, 1797, Pitt asked for �700,000, and hinted he would require a further sum of �200,000 for Ire- land. The Governor assured him that the drain of cash had been continuous and severe of late, and that such a demand was very dangerous. The demand for Ireland when made was for �1,500,000! The directors were dismayed and restricted their advances to merchants and others. At length, on Feb- ruary 25th, the crash came, and the Cabinet hurriedly author- ised the directors of the Bank to suspend cash payments and extend their issues of paper. The situation was at once re- lieved, and the stupidity of a gold basis was demonstrated. Brief mention may be made of the 'fatal' Act of 1844.* It divided the Bank into two departments, one for the issue of credits, i.e., purchase of Bills of Exchange, and the other for the issue of bank notes-as though bank notes and credits were not both credits! The Act shut the front door and left the back door wide open! Is it astonishing that the gold once more disappeared ? The issue of bank notes was strictly cur- tailed in relation to the cash reserve, the issue of credits was unlimited! Three years later in the crisis of 1847 the Bank was only saved by the Cabinet allowing it to violate the Act, and again in 1857, and in 1866 and 1914, it was found neces- sary to suspend the Act. The Act evidently is a failure, but so is the gold basis, or rather the present form of gold basis. The gold basis is for the banker as wood in the child- ren's game of 'touch wood,' for so long as you touch wood you are safe and immune; if you leave it, no matter how short the time or distance, fear and anxiety are your portion. At the approach of danger you must fly to its protecting virtues. So in fear and trembling the banker parts with his gold, and when commercial crises threaten, when public fear breaks into panic, panic into a run, a run into a stampede, the bank is 'broken,' and if some depositors escape ruin they are con- * This Act is admirably adapted "to bring the profits of industry periodically into the money bag of the usurer" by an increase in the rate of d!iscount-necessary to maintain the gold reserve. 133 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. sidered fortunate. And the whole arrangement is as unneces. sary as it is foolish. Chained to gold a bank is not free to exercise its proper function of issuing credits against all sound securities repre- senting real wealth. That wealth and not merely gold is the real basis of all Government bonds, and taxation is the means by which it is diverted from personal to communal use. Yet .n wealth they do not own the banks are allowed to levy tri- bute. As Marx says i*t "Is there anything more insane than, for instance, the Bank of England in 1797 to 1817, whose notes have credit only by backing of the State, taking payment from the State, to transform these same notes from paper into money and then to loan them to the State?" Now that is exactly what is taking place to-day. The title deeds to wealth (securities) are handed over to bankers who lock them up in their safes, and on this private wealth the owners are charged discount or interest in return practically for no more than a cheque book, and a few figures written in the bank's ledger, figures that give Inmediate purchasing power in virtue of public confidence. And we calmly permit this stark insanity to continuel It may be asked: "Is there no limit to this creation of wealth, or at least to this creation of credit?" Un- doubtedly there is. John Law, who was much saner than many of our modern Messenians, advocated the idea of representing all solid wealth, such as land, corn, silk, etc., in bank notes, or in bank credits. (A bank note is a bank credit). This, to a limited extent, is exactly what banks to-day-the question now is: What is the limit of that happy arrangement ? It is limited because bank notes and bank credits are pro- mises to pay current gold coin. Could these debts (bank notes and bank credits) be paid in paper, representing commodities instead of gold, there would be no other limit than the com- modities themselves to the creation of credit. The proposals of John Law would be perfectly sound. That this cannot now be done shows the foolishness of a gold basis. Yet it might be done, as we show in our chapter on Pallia- tives. We have taken a 10 per cent. cash reserve as ample provision against credit advances (in notes and book entries), but the bullion reserve against notes alone is often as high as one in three, while the reserve against notes and bank credits (and they are both liabilities) may fall as low as one in thirty. Ten per cent. is considered to be safe in ordinary times, but one in one is the only absolutely safe proportion. Such banks have existed at Amsterdam, Venice, Hamburg, and Nuremburg. Theywere purely deposit banks: did no discounting, and con- *"Capital," Vol. III., p. 638, Kerr's Fdition. Page 134, 19th line from bottom of page-"what banks to-day" should read "what banks do to-day" 134 THE- GREAT PRIVATE BANK FRAUD. 15 sequently made no profit. But, although, a cash reserveof one � sovereign for every �1 note issued-known as the Cur- rency Principle-is perfectly safe for the bank which does not give 'credits,' yet the volume of modern trade transactions is so great that gold coins, whether in their own form, or as represented by bank notes, would be utterly inadequate as the only medium of exchange. CO', N IONS ETCo I ' C ~ iov. ILI 160 - 15~OR 5TAILA ph OT N 5 Etl qSu '(.AN N o iT WLiliDS GOD Ilune, in his Essay on Money, says,: "The substitution of Paper for Metallic Currency is a national gain, any further in- crease of paper, beyond this is but a form of robbery." That form of robbery is perfectly legal, and is known now by the name of exploitation, but some- means of increasing the -media of exchange is. clearly necessary, and this necessity gave rise 135 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. first to: the issue of notes in excess of the coin reserve, and then to the issue of bank icredits. The great private bank fraud is not a deep and dark-laid scheme of robbery, but, like Topsy, it "just grow'd." Something had to be done, and so consciously or uncon- sciously the inverted pyramid of exchange media was erected. Founded entirely on a gold basis--credit at first took the form of bank notes in excess of the gold coin each note was supposed to represent: bank notes proving insufficient to meet the demands of trade promissory notes-bills of exchange -representing actual goods-were added to the unstable structure of credit, and finally leaving the solid ground of existing reality-past goods (already destroyed) and future goods, goods not yet in existence, and accommodation bills representing some vague capacity to pay, overhung the al- ready top-heavy edifice. Every one of the debts, bank notes, bills of exchange, pro- missory notes, interest on war bonds-all are payable in gold or' demand! Gold, in theory, is to complete every exchange. And there used to be an adage "as sound as a bank"! Banks are radically and essentially unsound-a breath of sus- picion-a wind of doubt-a run on a bank and over goes the crazy erection of credit. And periodically these winds of doubt must blow; one commercial crisis has followed and must follow another, so long as the capitalistic system lasts. Banks may aggravate such crises, but they cannot prevent them. As Macleod says: "It is entirely futile to expect that mercantile crises can be prevented, and they occur with precisely the same violence in places where there is a purely metallic currency as everywhere else." (We shall show the reason for and necessity of commercial crises in our next chapter)., All that can be done to mitigate their violence is to suspend by law gold payments and to issue whatever credits are required by sound trading institutions. No institution that can-ulti- mately-pay twenty shillings in the pound should be allowed to go insolvent, but those who cannot should not be assisted. As we have said, no reform in banking methods can pre- vent periodical crises, but what is known as "sound" banking may mitigate them. The most sensible reform would simply turn the solid part of the pyramid into the usual position adopted by all sober pyramids-that is a reform we shall sug- gest, but in the meantime what can be done by less radical measures? Something, but not much. Thus the 10 per cent. reserve might at least be preserved. Experience has proved that a 10 per cent. reserve against advances (notes and credits) is a sufficient provision in ordinary times. In times of severe 136 THE GREAT PRIVATE BANK FRAUD. crisis nothing short of a supply of gold to meet all possible demands is absolutely safe for the banks; and absolutely dis- astrous for traders. Assuming then that a 10 per cent. cash reserve against issued notes and- credits is the end bankers have in view, and that they voluntarily accept that limit to their (really un- limited) power to issue credits, the question is how can it be done? Originally each bank kept its own reserve of bullion. Even as late as November, 1914, American banks did so, But little pools soon dry up :--if all these small reserves are drained into one 'decent lake-spasmodic calls or runs on individual banks are easily met. Nearly every civilised nation now has a general gold reserve. But each bank is called upon to keep its own share of the pooled gold reserve at not less than 10 per cent. of its total advances. And that is-done-or attempted-by varying the rate of discount in consonance with foreign exchanges. A high rate of discount attracts gold; a low rate repels it. Suppose for example the rate of discount on bills or ex- change is 3 per cent. in London, and 8 per cent. in Paris-then gold will flow from London to Paris. The modus operandi is by means of Accommodation Bills, bogus bills which do not in reality represent actual sales of goods. Such a bill for (say, �100 can be sold in London for �97, and gold, not notes or. credit, is asked for; the gold is taken to Paris where a �100 bill can be bought for �92---a gross profit of �5. The cost of sending the bill is trifling, and when large sums are dealt with the cost of transmitting gold is a very small per- centage. There are other small hindrances to the transfer of gold from one country to another, but the difference between the two rates of discount is the governing factor. To prevent gold from leaving one country and going to another the dif- ference in the rate of discount in the two countries must not quite reach the gold point. To increase the quantity of gold in a country the rate of discount as compared with other coun- tries must exceed the gold point. Thus by altering the rate of discount, a 10 per cent. gold reserve against notes and credits can be maintained. Clearly it is the merchants who are the immediate sufferers from a deficiency in the gold reserve-the bankers make a profit out of it. "'There is a Profit before a Profit, and yet another Profit still," and it comes out of the pockets of our shrewd business men. Let us see what some of these profits are. All companies consisting of individual shareholders regard their profits as a matter that concerns themselves alone-all of them avoid the light of publicity as much as possible; secret reserves, unde- 137 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. clared profits, argue an uneasy conscience. Companies indig- nantly repel all inquiry, and loudly declare their right to manage their own business in their own way. As if the method by which wealth is made and distributed was of no vital interest to a nation, and was merely a matter of private .oncern ! There is considerable difficulty in obtaining reliable fig- ures. Roughly, every million pounds of gross banking profits may be divided as follows:- Net profit (66.6 per cent.) .......�666,667 Working expenses* (22 per cent.) 222,222 Taxation (11 per cent.) ...........111,111 �1,000,000 While the amount of credits advanced is about ten times as great as the paid up capital and ten times the amount of the gold reserve. The Commonwealth Bank of Australiat was founded in 1912 with a capital of five thousand pounds (�5000). In June, 1922, it had an accumulated capital of over �4,000,000, made entirely by charges in excess of the cost of the services rendered. A profit of �4,000,000 in ten years is an average profit per year of �400,000; and a profit of �400,000 a year on a capital of �5,000 is a profit of eight thousand (8,000) per cent. ! Our 400 per cent. was evidently far too modest. The total net yearly profit of all the banks in Aus- tralia in 1922 was over �8,000,000--gross returns on the basis assumed would be �12,000,000. Deducting working expenses 22 per cent. = �2,666,664 would leave a balance of �9,333,336 unnecessarily taken from the pockets of the people. Thus if the rate of discount is 6 per cent., it might be reduced to, say, 24 per cent.-affording great relief to traders and manufacturers, or, if directed into the coffers of the State, taxation could be reduced. If the total net banking profits in Britain are taken at twenty times the Australian profits, then �160,000,000 are every year taken from the pockets of its peo- ple, and put into the pockets of those who "own" the banks. Banks are only one form of exploitation. It is estimated that the so-called "public" limited liability companies in Australia make an annual net profit of �20,000,000. On the 20 to 1 basis such companies would in Britain acquire a profit of �400,000,000, and that leaves untouched the profit from rent and the profit of private firms. Is it any wonder that the 'people' of England are poor? *The highest shown (including directors' fees) in published statements. tOwned by the "people" of Australia. 138 ECONOMIC CONTRADICTION. Ix. Economic Contradiction. If we try to envisage the output of wealth by a nation we may regard it as a flow of the crude materials of Nature gradually changing shape from stage to stage until finality is reached in consumption or capital goods. The analogy is not however perfect: it is not the uninterrupted flow of a river: at this stage or that there may be stoppages, and goods may accumulate in heaps in warehouse or store: only when the flow is constant is the analogy sound. Though there is an intimate connection between the several stages of manufacture, the rate of "flow" is liable to vary, now hastening, now retarded, even, it may be, for a time stopping altogether. When the final stage is reached at last we see that the goods are either consumption or capital goods, are, i.e., goods to be consumed immediately or are goods to be used in the production of yet more goods! Whatever the kind of goods the rate of flow depends essentially on demand: though a limit, rarely if ever reached, is imposed by the capacity of producing agencies: we may fairly say that demand determines supply. Now at each stage,-we may name them A. B. to J.,-new value is added, and if A. J. represent the producers then while each of A.-----J. is credited with the particular value he has added, yet it is not till, finally, J. sells the ultimate goods that these values are realised. Again, A. ---J. may remain owners of the goods until the final sale by J., or they may sell their claim to banks or to other capitalists, at a discount, and these then become the real owners. In either case it is the real owners who decide what goods shall in future be pro- duced, or in other words decide the policy of industry: be- cause for the most part these goods are circulating capital, and can be used in any desired direction: the workers who consume them can be employed just as capitalists may decide. Claims on such goods,-recorded chiefly on floating paper or as credit in the books of a bank,-constitute purchasing power: and this power is held by aggregations of capital in 139 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. the hands of individuals or of banking corporations. These "claims" on wealth are often pure exploitation; as watered stock, vested privilege, and goodwill. Such immaterial wealth, preferential benefits of the nature of in- tangible assets, may be a matter of usage simply, as the vogue of a given public-house, or of a given tradesman, or of a brand of consum- able goods: or may be a matter of arrogation, as the King's customs in early times, or the once notorious Sounds Dues, or the closing of public highways by large landholders: or of contractual concession, as in the freedom of a city or guild, or a franchise in the Hanseatic League or in the Associated Press: or of Government concession, whether based on bargain or otherwise, as many of the trade monopolies of early mod - ern times, or a corporation charter, or a railway franchise, or letters of marque, or letters patent: or of statutory creation, as trade protec- tion by import, export or excise duties, or navigation laws: or of super- stitious punctilio, as the creation of a demand for wax by the devout obligatory consumption of consecrated tapers, or the similar devout consumption of and demand for fish during Lent.* As a result of these and other forms of exploitation re- ceivers of surplus value find themselves in possession of more ' claims" to wealth than they care to realise-of more money than they can possibly spend on consumption goods, they must save, i.e., they must "invest" their money in capital goods. And the manufacturer finds that he is unable to sell his goods at a profit-no matter how small that profit may be, conse- quently he must reduce his output or close his works. Let the manufacturer state his own case: "Unless I can sell my goods as cheaply as others, I cannot sell them at all, consequently I am compelled, under pain of bankruptcy, to reduce my costs to a minimum. I may do that in several or all of the following ways: I may reduce wages; lengthen hours; induce my men to work harder; introduce automatic and up- to-date machinery; improve my methods and organisation. I do not want to do these things, but I must if I am to live. I cannot afford to be a philanthropist, nor am I in business merely for "the good of my health." The plea must be admitted. Our manufacturer is evi- dently a creature of circumstances, and probably a very decent fellow. What then are the circumstances? More goods are produced than can be sold. And they cannot be sold for two reasons: firstly, because those who want the goods have not got the money to buy them; secondly, because those who have got the money, do not want them. That is the position in a nutshell. Remembering that the great bulk of consumers are wage and salary receivers, let us consider the effect of the measures our manufacturer was compelled to take. *Veblen, "Place of Science in Civilisation," p. 362. 140 ECONOMIC CONTRADICTION. To "reduce wages" is to reduce the purchasing power of wage-receivers. To "lengthen hours" means that fewer men are required-that less wages are paid and fewer goods can be sold. More "intense labour" has exactly the same result- fewer men-less wages-fewer goods sold. To introduce better methods and more automatic machinery has the same result: fewer men-less wages-fewer goods sold. There is no escape from the dilemma so far as the market made by the worker is concerned. Remains the market made by the wealthy capitalists themselves. Their consuming cap- acity is limited-let us stretch it with luxuries as far as pos- sible. And here we note that luxury is good for trade, and Ruskin's fine indignation was wasted. For production to continue goods must be consumed, whether by use, or waste, or fire, or luxury, or war, is, from the economic point of view, a matter of indifference. The almost agonised cry of the manufacturer is for a market his frenzied endeavour is to sell his goods. It has been seriously stated that it costs as much to sell as to produce an article. That is an enormous but beneficial waste. How otherwise would all those "travellers" live After an extensive fire men are employed-during the war men-and women too-were employed. Under the 'in- exorable' law of capitalist economics waste and fire and war are good in that they enable men to be employed. "Fair is foul and foul is fair" might well be adopted as the motto of the system. Seen "through the fog and filthy air" of Capitalism all virtues are distorted. Clearly the home market can only be improved by increasing wages, or by increasing the luxury of the rich. The foreign market may possibly be captured by reducing wages, etc. Let us see-perhaps it can be done-for a time. Trade is in reality an exchange of goods and services for goods and services. Foreign trade is chiefly an exchange of goods-(shipping is, however, a service). That being so, what are we to exchange? Of manufactured consuniption goods we already have too many-the home market is over- supplied; but we may take raw materials as wheat and wool, and in return we give our surplus manufactured goods, and all is well-for a time. Presently, other nations, having their own unemployed, raise a protective tariff and start manu- facturing for themselves. Still trade is good-for a time- because we are able to send machinery instead of, or in addi- tion to, manufactured consumption goods. Then comes a slump-a trade depression. Australia, for instance, is begin- ning to turn her own wool into cloth and blankets, etc. (how 141 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. will that affect Bradford?), and to make her own steel rails (how will that affect Sheffield?) and her own machinery (what has Leeds to say?), and soon cotton and cotton mills will follow. No-there is no permanent solution in foreign trade. Then "Economy" is the cry: reduce expense by dismis- sing unnecessary civil servants, cut down on naval, military, educational establishments: by an even greater amount you enlarge unemployment and therefore decrease the spending power of the community: still fewer goods are required by the market. Well, obviously, emigration: there is a land overseas: for men there is no call in England-unless there should be another war; or "Capital" may emigrate and employ "cheap" labour. It would be simpler to adopt Dean Swift's "remedy for the current distress in Ireland"-and practise infanticide and cannibalism. True the Dean's remedy is drastie: true that "it is the people that make the State, whose real riches lie in its inhabitants": but what else is there? One final refuge remains: Imperialism. There is an abundance of the "raw materials of nature" to be exploited: oil in Mosul, iron ore in China and Morocco, coal in the Ruhr and elsewhere, cotton-lands in Egypt and Australia, rubber in the Congo, and "concessions"' everywhere. Suppose the suggestion is ac- cepted, what then? War, destruction of "goods," and there- fore a market. Assuredly a market-for a year, or it may be five: and then? Surely we have seen it: Europe bankrupt, and as a last hope an attempt to make a market "within the Empire." Once we sold to the world: now we are trying to make a handful of dominions and colonies appear to us as if they were the world. In vain, absolutely in vain! It matters not whether the unit be state, nation, empire or world, sooner or later the fatal dislocation in distribution brings production to a standstill and a starving multitude faces warehouses bursting with merchandise, but between them flashes the sword of "law and order." Thus in sum it amounts to just this:-Assuming the pre- sent capitalist system, there are two and only two results- (a) Those who can, and are willing to, consume "goods" are unable to pay for them. (b) Those who can pay for them, cannot, or are unwilling to consume them. Or it may be expressed in one sentence: "Sale of consump- tion goods is restricted by the limited capacity of the worker's purse on the one hand, and the capitalist's stomach on the other." To sell cheapely, wages must be reduced: to reduce wages is to diminish the power of purchase: to sell freely, 142 ECONOMIC CONTRADICTION. purchasing power must be increased. Thus does Capitalism ring its own knell. We cannot at the same time both reduce wages to secure cheapness and increase them to provide a narket.v A system which attempts the impossible and absurd stands self-condemned, and is clamant for replacement. The position is aptly illustrated by an actual case from nature. A dead beast was found on a cattle "run" or ranch, one horn of the unfortunate animal having grown so as to pierce the eye and penetrate the brain. No doubt madness preceded death. That is exactly what is threatening the capitalist system-involuntary self-slaughter. And there is more than one mad cow in the arena. Now our own wealth commands us; we are destroyed by the works of our own hands by the very machinery we have ourselves invented. The more efficient production becomes, by specialisation and invention, the less efficient grows distri- bution because there has been no accompanying synthesis or integration. It may be well to consider for a moment the limits of existing~ industrial integrations. In olden times the manor was self-contained; it constituted an industrial unit. Later, the nation became the unit; some foreign trade certainly existed, but chiefly in luxuries not essential to the life of the nation. To-day foreign trade is essential to the life of England, and were she suddenly cut off from the outer world she would starve.* To fix the exact limits of her industrial integration is almost impossible, but they are international. In ordinary conversation we speak of 'England's' trade with, say, 'America.' But England does not trade with America: capital is now a private possession and certain private individuals or firms in England trade with private individuals or firms in America. Under Socialism, whether 'State,' 'Guild,' 'Soviet,' or any other brand, England will trade with other socialised nations, if they exist, or with private individuals oi- firms in capitalistic nations, but she will trade as a whole. War, some day, will cease, but that day is not yet, is perhaps far off. In the meantime it would be wise for each nation to make itself as self-contained as possible. Hence, for the pre- sent, Protection is justified. Protection is indeed, if not a necessary, at least an advisable preliminary step towards Socialism. A higher integration (as Socialism) will be accom- panied by a higher differentiation, not only within, but of, the nation, as indicated in our spiral of progress. How foolish then it is for the Labor Party in England to oppose Protection, *"It is, quite erroneously, thought that England could not grow her own food: she could; as Kropotkin has pointed out. 143 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. although Protection,f in itself, is no remedy for the present mal-distribution of wealth. Over-production is, from. another point of view, under- production, and production is restricted, not because we are physically unable to produce more, but because we are unable to sell more. The slight extent to which we 'lived on our capital' during the war, by neglecting to maintain our plant, was but as a drop in the bucket compared with the loss of products since the war, due to our inability to sell; and we cannot sell because our 'people' are unable to buy. As Marx tells us: Within the capitalist system all methods. for raising the social productiveness of labor are brought about at the cost of the individual laborer; all means for the development of pro- duction transform themselves into means of domination over, and ex- ploitation of, the producers; they mutilate the laborer into a fragment of a man, degrade him to the level of an appendage of a machine, destroy every remnant of charm in his work and turn it into a hatred toil; they estrange from him the intellectual potentialities of the labor process in the same proportion as science is ihcorporated in it as an in- dependent power; they distort the conditions under which he works, subject him during the labor process to a despotism the more hateful for its meanness; they transform his life-time into working-time, and drag his wife and child beneath the Juggernaut of capital. But all methods for the production of surplus-value are at the same time methods of accumulation, and every extension of accumulation becomes again a means, for the development of those methods. It follows there- fore that in proportion as capital accumulates, the lot of the laborer, be his payment high or low, must grow worse. (Heavier type mine.) To which may be added that crowning degradation, un- certainty of employment. . "Wealth accumulates and men decay.", It is a feature of the system that there are always unem- ployed, though numbers vary greatly, as is but natural, with the state of trade. Even in 1886 Engels, after pointing out the tendency of production to exceed market needs, could say:--" The decennial cycle of stagnation, prosperity, over- production and credit, ever recurrent from 1825 to 1867, seems indeed to have run its course: but only to land us in the slough of despond of a permanent and chronic depression. The sighed-for period of prosperity will not come: as often as we seem to see the heralding symptoms, so often do they again t When the political and economic integration of the world is an accom- plished fact, Free Trade will be as obviously the correct system for the world as it is now for the internal trade of a nation. The chief objection to Protection lies in its psychological, rather than in its economic, effect. It tends to accentuate a selfish nationalism which not only proclaims "my nation first" but "the rest nowhere"; it tends to prolong the war dementia which saw in enemy atrocities the acts of devils; in our own; just reprisal by indignant heroes-an attitude, of mind, and a belief, common to all belligerents (!), but one which does not promote the difficult art of 'living together.' 144 ECONOMIC CONTRADICTION. vanish into thin air. Meanwhile each succeeding winter brings us afresh the great question-' What are we to do with the :unemployed ?' But while the number of the unemployed keeps swelling from year to year there is no one to answer the question." It is the purport of this book to attempt an answer. SUnder= Capitalism, trade-depressions and crises are in- evitable: they began with Capitalism and only with its end will they find theirs. 'Since 1763 they have recurred in the following years:-- 1772, 1782, 1793, 1803, 1810, 1814-1819, 1825, 1837-1839, 1847, 1857, 1864-6, 1873-9, 1882-4, 1890, 1893, 1900, 1907, .1921; and the nightmare of the last is still with us in 1923. These crises destroy a large amount of "capital"; not capital in the sense of material aids to production but eapital as represented by "'claims" on wealth. The "capital" destroyed in these recurrent crises consists of the power ob- tained by monopoly through trusts or trade-agreements to fix the price of goods by limiting supply. When this power fails demand is unable to keep pace with supply, and goods are either sold at a loss or not at all, or they cease to be produced. These trade crises do good in so far as they squeeze the "water" out of finance, and reduce the grosser over-capitalisa- tions. But "while the grass is growing the horse is starving.' and the knowledge that things are on the mend is sorry con- solation to those who, meanwhile, are unemployed, or those who, though employed, know that they are-to use their own expression-" working themselves out of a job" and merely hastening a fresh depression. The real meaning of a depression is that goods cannot be consumed, not that they cannot be produced: and whether the cause be defined as general over-production or specific under-consumption is of no moment. Economists of the classi- cal school are chiefly guilty in their insistence that general over-production is impossible. This is the error of the father of economics, Adam Smith: it is the error of Ricardo: and oily Sismondi lifts the voice of one crying in the wilderness: "Repent, repent, and from old errors turn! Who listen'd to his voice, obey'd his cry? Only the echoes, which he made relent, TRung from their flinty caves, Repent! Repent!" . At length, after more than a hundred years, some economists are beginning to listen and repent. .The reality of general over-production has been strenu- ously denied, and on the face of it, it appears to be so absurd, so impossible, that it may be well to go over the ground once more. 145 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. The position was stated by Sismondi in 1803, restated by Marx in 1867, yet we find economists of the present day, for example, Professor Rist in "A History of Economic Doctrine" (Gide and Rist) still asserting that Sismondi is wrong. Even some labour leaders (e.g., J. R. Clynes) appear not to have understood the matter as late as 1920. What then can be ex- pected from the "man in the street"? Mr. Lloyd George went nearer the mark when he told us that Europe was like a beggar in rags gazing with longing eyes into a British shop window, but he forgot to add that two-thirds of the inhabitants of Britain were in the same position. Professor Rist takes up the orthodox Ricardian position: there can be no general over-production-and although he admits the correctness of most of Sismondi's statements yet finds them vitiated by that fundamental error! Sismondi says goods cannot be sold unless someone can buy them-and, he might have added, consume them. M. Rist replies (p. 177 of the English translation): "At any one moment there may be too many, or too few products of a certain kind, . . . but of every product, at one and the same time, there can never be too much." In other words there cannot be general over-production. But what is meant by 'too much'? If merely that products are wanted by someone-and that is what the "man in the street" means then we agree with the Professor-the 'wants' of man are almost insatiable. But economists do not use 'want' in this naive sense. If by 'want' or 'never too much' is meant that there is always a demand for the products-demand in the economic sense of effective demand-then every shopkeeper in France, as well as England, will tell the Professor that he is wrong. M. Rist says of Sismondi (page 181): "He was unwilling to admit that the growth of production itself created this de- mand." It may be asked: Why do not those who own surplus goods exchange them with each other? No doubt the surplus products could be exchanged, but they are not, because the owners of surplus goods cannot consume them and nothing is gained by exchanging something we cannot use for something else we cannot use. All that can be done is to save the surplus even if exchange takes place. And, it may be added, if the products are consumption goods they can only be saved in warehouses and shops. If they are "capital"' goods-i.e., machinery and the like-they can be "invested," and more consumption goods, more surplus goods, produced. Surely the position is clear! That is what constitutes general over- production, and general over-production inevitably produces unemployment. 146 ECONOMIC CONTRADICTION. 2. Sismondi points out the immobility of fixed capital- -We cannot suddenly turn a sawmill into a Portland cement factory-therefore manufacturers limit production, they "go slow," and the automatic adjustment of supply and demand, through prices, entails a "frightful amount of suffering." M. Rist says (p. 180) : "The dictum . . . controls the policy of every trust and kartel of the present day." But (p. 191) "Sismondi's argument is vitiated by the same false idea that made him admit the possibility of general over-produc- tion!" 3. Sismondi was disgusted by the fact that not only were workers driven out of employment by machinery, but that even those who were employed received only a small share (if any) of the benefits of machinery. He says: "We have said it elsewhere, but think it essential to repeat it, that it is not the perfection of machinery that is the real calamity, but the unjust distribution of the goods produced." M. Rist comments (pp. 182) : "Here again Sismondi appears correct." But (page 183): "Sismondi's argument is open to the sante objection as was made above! (i.e., there cannot be general over-production)." 4. Sismondi says: "Pursuit of cheapness has forced the entrepreneur to economise not only in the matter of stuff, but Also of men. Competition has everywhere enticed women and children to bear the burden of production instead of adults . . . The earnings of an entrepreneur sometimes repre- sent nothing but the spoliation of the workmen." M. Rist comments (p. 183) : "It is futile to deny the justice of the argument." "But (p. 185) he (Sismondi) does not consider that appropriation by proprietors or capitalists of a portion of the social product is in itself unjust." Sismondi was not Marx, but here Sismondi is evidently thinking of the 'wages of superintendence.' The capitalist pure and simple hardly existed in Sismondi's day. Sismondi dubbed the economists of his day "orthodox"-in return they refused him the name of economist at all. Sismondi stated his celebrated winch argument. This is practically the query: "If all wealth could be produced by automatic machinery and the machinery is owned by the few-what are the many to do?" And Profes- sor Rist (footnote to p. 181), writing in the twentieth century, says the problem is insoluble! We venture to give three solu- tions: 1. Starve. 2. Fight. 3. Joint and common ownership of the instruments of production and exchange by society. Marx saw the beginnings of trade-unionism, and pointed out that this new force ran counter to, and modified, the un- restricted law of wages; that while unionism could not create 147 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. employment it might-within limits-increase the wages of those who were employed, even might ultimately take over the management of industry altogether. When the laborers discover that the degree of intensity of com- petition among themselves depends wholly on the pressure of relative surplus population, they try to organise a regular co-operation between employed and unemployed in order to destroy or to weaken the ruinous effects of this natural law of capitalistic production on their class. The fact is that at present the worker is degraded, and is, virtually, a slave. His labor-power is a commodity, sold in the open market like any other commodity; only by 'striking' can workers take a leaf out of the capitalists' book and limit supply. The lesson of all this is so obvious that it hardly needs to be pointed out. The failure is from the side of the distribution --not production-of wealth. The ownership of the means of production enables a few men to draw to themselves more wealth than they can possibly consume, The cure lies in the common ownership of the means of production and exchange, in an all-round increase in wages and salaries and the aboli- tion of privilege, so, and only so, can we have efficient distri- bution. Capitalism, like a blind Samson, is pulling down the pillars of its temple and involving one and all in universal ruin. 148 THE ETHICAL ASPECT. X. The Ethical Aspect. As we have contrasted the word freedom with Capitalism it may be desirable at this point to explain precisely what we mean by freedom. Individual action is limited by material conditions. Such limitations do not affect the freedom we mean. Nor do we mean by freedom the removal of all social restrictions, as in the case of Robinson Crusoe. Freedom is the action a man may enjoy, in a social state, as a part of a whole. Complete freedom' consists in a perfect adjust- ment of individuals to each otheir, and to society for mutual benefit. Society may be simple or complex, but its members are free if their adjustment to each other is perfect. Thus free- dom may exist in every form of society whether low or high, whether simple or complex. The individual is free, not because he possesses entirely unrestricted power to act, but because as a member of a perfect society he possesses the greatest possible power of action and of self-realisation. Freedom, then, consists in an harmonious and perfect adjustment of parts in and for each other and the whole. In defining freedom we have to a large extent defined justice. If we digress for a moment and ask why perfect adjust- ment is, at least, attempted, or what causes differentiation into parts, we can only say we do not know. All we know is that in the past economic changes.have been largely unconscious, the result apparently of a blind struggle between individuals, an interaction of the individual and his surroundings, or when action has been conscious its effect on society as a whole was not recognised. And yet, even so, society has grown, it has evolved, and the changes have been made by the action of individuals. There must therefore be something in man that makes for a 'higher' life. That something, whether we call it instinct, or intuition, or reason, or religion, whether a vague blind striving, a groping after truth, or clear conscious action, impels mankind to a higher life. That something lies at the 149 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. root alike of the self-sacrifice which promotes a higher integra- tion, and the self-assertion which leads to a higher differentia- tion. It lies, in fact, at the root of all efforts-conscious or unconscious--which tend to carry out the injunction, "Be ye therefore perfect." That something is the very spirit of re- ligion--the religion which impels a woman to sacrifice herself for her child, a man to die for his country, a Socrates to die for truth, a Christ to die for the world. When conscious, this spirit is called goodwill, and goodwill is now, we believe, a factor in industrial evolution. By goodwill the discordant elements in Capitalism can be removed, a higher integration effected and freedom attained. Freedom is an element in justice, but justice is something more than freedom. We may have a perfect society in the sense just defined, but not: the 'highest' form of society, and, we contend, those actions that lead to a higher form of society are just. Justice is therefore relative, not absolute. When we speak of social justice we include, in fact, those rearrange- ments in society which lead to a higher form of society. Justice is compounded of several elements, of which the first is equality-equality of conditions, equality of oppor- tunity. With natural inequalities we are not concerned. Jus- tice applies solely to arrangements made by man with men. We cannot alter the laws of matter, and their results are inevitable, and the inevitable is neither just nor unjust, it is-inevitable. We cannot alter the laws of Nature because we cannot alter the constitution of Nature. But the laws of economics-of capital- istic production-even when true, are only the laws of a man- created system-a system we can alter. We do not take our stand on the theory of greatest happi- ness, or on the doctrine of natural rights, but on the ground of evolution. There is no right to anything that stands in the way of a higher development of society, there is every right to whatever promotes that development. In this idea of justice, equality finds a place, but the idea of equality is widely misunderstood, and needs definition. Simply to say "all men are equal" at once provokes denial. It is so obvious that in many respects men are not equal. In what respect then are they equal? Man is not merely a means, he is an end. The equality we speak of is in personality. Every man is to himself the centre of the universe. His personality is unique, it contains "just that essence of individuality which eludes words and baffles description.'" He has, with others, an equal claim to consideration, to freedom, and to independence from the coer- cion, from the arbitrariness of others, in so far as this is com- patible, according to general laws, with the freedom of others. 150 THE ETHICAL ASPECT. Men "are equal by virtue of the illimitable value each personality represents, they are equal in relation to the con- sideration we owe to their interests." It is in that respect that equality is: claimed. But by justice we do not merely mean equality even in the restricted sense just defined. Justice is a relation between men-it is relative, proportionate. That is just which promotes the development of society towards a higher form of life, and by society we do not mean merely the living individuals form- ing the units of existing society, but also the individuals to be, the welfare of the race in fact. In that wider sense we interpret the phrase, "Salus populi suprema lex." The health, the welfare of the people or the society is the supreme law. By justice then we mean those relations or actions of man to man which best promote the ends of evolution; the upward striving of the human race. The end is not merely individual life and happiness, but the highest form of social life and happiness. Certain human relationships may, at one particular phase of development, best promote the development of the race, and so be just under those particular circumstances-later the same relationships may impede the development of the race, and so become unjust. That is what is meant when justice is said to be relative. To the man engaged in heavy physical toil justice allots more food than to one whose work is of a sedentary nature, If the food is divided in the just proportion both are equally well fed. Similarly we claim the equal right of all to participate in higher development, in opportunities, in chances in life, the equal right of all to inherit the earth, to be "heirs of all the ages." We advance then as self-evident truths the following statements: 1. The forces and materials of Nature should be the joint and common property of mankind. 2. The sum total of human knowledge should be the com- mon property of the race 3. The only just title, in a social state, to income is social service. 1. In so far as the forces and materials of Nature can be owned or utilised by man, all men by their common humanity appear to have an equal claim to them. If this is denied, if anyone asserts that some men have a better claim to own Nature than others (others that is of the same race, time, and culture) then on that man lies the onus of proof. But exclusive use is not incompatible with common ownership. To use does not necessarily mean to own. Exclusive individual use may co-exist with common ownership. It may be argued with Max Stirner that "might is right, and there is no right without might," that the weak ought to 151 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. give place to the strong, that this is the law of Nature, and that what is natural is just. To this we demur. It is indi- vidualism run mad. It is the denial of all social obligation. Nor is the appeal to Nature valid. Nature is neither moral, nor immoral, simply non-moral. Justice and injustice, as we have said, refer solely to arrangements made between men. That the materials and forces of Nature should be the common property of all men we hold to be axiomatic. We cannot prove that two and two make four. We cannot prove the right of all men to participate in the bounties of Nature. We regard it as an axiom, a self-evident truth. It goes to the root of the whole matter. It is fundamental. And to the forces and materials of Nature may be added time and space: matter and force, time and space, what can be more fundamental? These things are essential to life, we claim them as the common property, the joint inheritance of all men. If private property in land, if Capitalism and the wages system (as we know it) are now in the best interest of the race, then we agree that they are just. Capitalism may have been-we believe it was-a necessary phase in the evolution of industry and the way to a higher industrial development. It is on that ground justified by Marx. But because a system has been just, it does not follow that it is just. It may be objected, "the forces and materials of Nature are common property, they are free to all:the sun shines on rich and poor alike, the rain falls on the just and the unjust." The assertion that all materials of Nature are common property is clearly incorrect. Facts plainly contradict such a statement. But-it may again be urged-'" all men cannot work the same mine, or cultivate the same piece of land. The enclosure of land and its private ownership is surely justified by that fact." Again we demur. The private occupation of land may be justified, but not its private ownership. Exactly how to arrange for private occupation, and still retain common owner- ship, seems to have been too difficult a problem for our ances- tors to solve, but there is no doubt that it can be solved. Then as regards the forces of Nature, heat for example, how under Capitalism do workers retain their share of the benefits to be derived from the use of that great force? Probably no one will have the temerity to assert that the condition of the worker has improved "pari passu" with the command of man over the forces of Nature, and with the methods by which he has been able to harness them and make them his obedient servants. The worker can now travel in an electric tram ear, or in a railway carriage drawn by a steam locomotive; but 152 THE ETHICAL ASPECT. is: his condition any better if his wages are still on the bare subsistence line ? Has he received a real benefit from these inventions? Or granting that he has received some benefit, has he received a proportionate--a just---share of benefit? It cannot :truly be. said that he has. And it is the private owner- ship of capital that enables the capitalist to gain and keep a disproportionately great share of the benefits which arise from- the control of forces that are the common inheritance of all. It seems clear that if capitalists are allowed to receive, in the first instance, the entire benefit to be derived from the use of a force of Nature, they should, in justice, pay a royalty to those who are prevented from directly participating in that benefit, or, as an alternative, the means, that is, capital, should be owned in common. Nor does the argument end here, it can be applied to all social arrangements, which result in dispro- portionate benefit to individuals: or to classes. 2,: The: sum total of human knowledge should be the com- mon property of the race. It may be granted that thinkers, discoverers and inventors are entitled to a reward for their social service. But they have found, after diligent search perhaps, something which is the property of the race, they have not created it. It may be some unknown material, or force of Nature. It may be some means of utilising some known material or force of Nature--some relation of space, or time, or number, some discovery in higher mathematics. We may justly grant a patent, or copyright, or reward, a wage in fact for work done; but the inventor having received his reward, his invention, should belong to mankind. James Watt was the first:: to imake the steam engine turn a wheel, a discovery of enormous importance. Watt is dead and the benefit to be derived from, the use of the steam engine is; or should be, the common property of the race. Here again we find the capitalist class is enabled prac- tically to monopolise not only the forces and materials of Nature, but the brains of mankind, all discoveries, all inven- tions. "It is doubtful," says Mill, '"if all the mechanical in- ventions yet made have lightened the day's toil of any human being." Would it not be just for the rest of the community to require payment from the capitalists for the almost ex- clusive benefit they derive from such knowledge? With the possession of the steam engine capitalists annex, not only the force of heat, but the long line of discoveries that made the engine possible, and the benefit of the idea which the engine enshrines. 3. The only just claim to income is social service. If the welfare of the race and the common good is the supreme law, on what ground can the idle justly claim wealth ? 153 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. It -is obvious that Wealth does not make itself-all wealth is produced by man working in conjunction with Nature. "Man is its :father and the earth its mother," and if the earth, if Nature, is the common property of the race, work, and work only, is the just claim to wealth. This argument is as trite as it is true. The gospel of work has many propagandists. But although it is a true gospel, it is useless to preach it to the worker who knows he is already exploited and who suspects that the chief concern of those who admonish him is his further exploitation. He prefers to go-slow, to prevent, as he believes, at least some amount of exploitation. His attitude is perhaps deplorable, ill-advised, disastrous, but very natural. That it should be possible at all constitutes a grave indictment of the wages system. It must not, however, be forgotten that even with go-slow work, production can be greatly increased by the employment of more, and more efficient machinery, nor should it be forgotten that manufacturers also 'go-slow' by deliberately limiting production, and throwing men out of work. Work is no longer solitary individual work-work under Capitalism is socialised, and it is by the division of labor, by associated labor using capital that wealth can best be made. The individual is now a part of a great organised whole, and any attempt to return to the domestic system is to be depre- cated. We should go forwards not backwards. But is it fair that capitalists should "do nothing"-nothing useful to the community-and yet reap the greatest advantage from social- ised and organised labor? We find that capitalists not only monopolise the materials and forces of Nature, and the accu- mulated discoveries, inventions, and knowledge of mankind, but they receive the chief benefit from the organisation of labor, and the "law and orders' under which we all live. And, as has been said, "they do nothing!" Surely some crowning service must have been overlooked, some mighty good that they confer on mankind in exchange for all these benefits. It may be contended that we have overlooked the true function of eapitalists, viz., the adjustment of supply to demand. To that we reply: first, it is not the -capitalist pure and simple- the income-purchaser-who makes this adjustment; and secondly, the adjustment is more or less automatic. It is gene- rally the merchant, or the refiner, or finishing manufacturer, who is the chief regulator, but the impulse is passed all along the line from the consumer to the producer and price is the great indicator. For instance, demand slackens, the retailer makes a slight reduction in price to stimulate demand and cuts down his orders to wholesale merchants' travellers or agents- the steadying influence is passed on to merchants and through 154 THE ETHICAL ASPECT. them to manufacturers of the consumption goods, from them on to manufacturers of partly finished material, and so finally to suppliers of raw material and cultivators. These last have been blindly working up stocks and find themselves involved in loss. A reaction takes place and the impulse is transmitted in the other direction. The action and reaction are automatic, the capitalist pure and simple has nothing to do with the case and 'does nothing,' and the active merchant and others very little. As Sismondi says, "A certain kind of equilibrium, it is true, is re-established in the long run, but it is only after a frightful amount of suffering inherent in the blind play of economic forces." The capitalist then evidently does not adjust supply to demand. But perhaps the capitalist is the great stomach of the body politic-! He is not the captain of industry-he pays others to do that work, but he signs his cheques, even if he does not fill them in. And-yes, he saves; our curves show us that he saves. Crowning virtue! He cannot consume all he gets, so he saves 31 per cent. or more and reinvests the money, and his sacrifice, his self-denial, is belauded in every morning newspaper, and the virtue of thrift extolled. The worker who saves nothing, and is most improvident, is urged to follow this noble example. To save, the worker must lower his standard of comfort, and-since a "living wage" at the existing stan- dard of comfort is admittedly the basis on which wages are now fixed-saving on the part of the worker would make it possible to lower wages. It has been shown that, in reality, it is the limited stomach of the capitalist, and the undue exercise of the virtue of saving, that is the cause of recurring commercial crises, financial panics, over-production, and unemployment. But the capitalist should not be blamed for the limited capacity of his stomach- he does his best, but it is simply impossible for him to consume all he gets-he must save. Saving is the only virtue in which he is assured pre-eminence. The great war benefited the capitalist by destroying-and paying for-products which he could not himself consume, and which other people could not buy. Credit performed this miracle. Do the foregoing considerations lead to the belief that the 'owner' of capital is justly entitled to all, or nearly all, the benefits derived from its use? Had the capitalist discovered all the forces and materials he uses, had he invented all the machines, had he organised the working force (he does not even do this), had he found out all trade processes and directed the working force, still he would not be entitled to the bene- 155 156 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. fits he now receives. And he has done none of these things. (And with the capitalist we bracket the landlord.) What then is the Landlord-Capitalist? He is a parasite. A parasite of the body politic, a fever germ, both the cause and the result of the economic disorder of the world. I cannot at this point do better than quote from "The Social Problem" (p. 114) by J. A. Hobson, who himself begins with a quotation from J. Mussart and Emile Vandervelde's "Parasitism, Organic and Social," p. 75:- "We find that atrophy is both more rapid and more complete among parasites than elsewhere. Plants lose their roots and even their leaves. Among animals, the points of contact with the world are minimised in proportion to the degree of parasitism; the nervous system tends to disappear so completely, indeed, that in some species the individual ends in being little more than a sac with reproductive organs. In the world of human life, parasitic degeneration is, above all, cerebral. The intellectual faculties are the first to atrophy from disease; physical degeneration is a later and almost a reflex process." This slow working of the natural 'law in modern industrial societies is chiefly attributable to two causes. The first is that, so far as rent-drawers, sinecurists, and other "proprietary parasites" are con- cerned, they are frequently inheritors of an originally vigorous con- stit,tion which is transmitted to them but slightly, if at all, impaired by the parasitic life of their parents. This good start in life, favored by a healthy environment in childhood, enables them to stand out some- times for a long time against' the natural tendencies of the parasitic life. Then, again, parasitism does not, save in extreme cases, impose or admit complete inertia. Most parasites must either find a "host" or, if it be provided, as by inheritance, to the human parasite, some activity is enjoined in the very processes of feeding on him. Take, for instance, the landowner. A fine humour lurks in the common defence of landlordism upon the ground of the laborious energy the landlord must display in order to extract his full economic rents and administer his property for this purpose,--the labor of managing his estate... The "independent gentleman," for so with unconscious humor he styles himself, will practise for a while such forms of active self-expression as are fashionable, stir his emulation, and are not degraded by having attached to them any useful end; he may hunt, play golf, sit on the bench, enter Parliament, or even collect some sort of knowledge which shows well, and involves no arduous effort of attainment. But the property of another which he uses will gradually crush his own property, his capacity of vigorous self-expres- sion. Relieved of the necessity of painful effort, he will only undergo such efforts as are easy; so the habit of hard work disappears, and with it the zest of enjoyment which the reaction from hard work brings. The higher kinds of concentrated mental effort, with their corresponding enjoyments, go first; then the lower; even the physical exercises involving skill, constant practice, and play of mind, yield to the simpler forms of animal enjoyment. This is the normal and necessary effect of living upon another's property. One by one the higher activities are debilitated, and cease to work; the attempt to consume without producing, to enjoy without effort, at once lessens the quantity and lowers the quality of life. The logical end of a society living upon unearned incomes would be death by over-feeding, or by inability to digest and assimilate their food. No economic or THE ETHICAL ASPECT. moral defence of the right to receive rent or interest, or to take by inheritance or bequest another's property, however cogent it may appear, can abrogate this application of the natural law. Physical decay is a 'natural' consequence of attempted evasions of the physical law which imposes exercise as the condition of digestion. "Whosoever will not work neither can he eat" is the physical render- iuig of the moral law. For the physical diseases bred of stolen luxuries, and those which spring from chronic starvation, are literal counter- parts. The convex, congested paunch of the torpid plutocrat, who consumes without the effort of producing, implies as its equal and opposite the concave, anaemic body of the inefficient starveling. Here again the pluses equal the minuses, and yet in sober truth the landlord-capitalist deserves our pity. The idle rich are victims of circumstances, as much as are the idle poor. Our quarrel is not with men, our quarrel is with the capitalist system. The capitalist individually is often a good fellow, and everyone is trying hard to become a capitalist. But if the idle rich are to receive toleration now, and consideration in the future readjustment of society, they must change their mental attitude towards workers. One more word before we dismiss the landlord-capitalist. So persistently has the virtue of thrift been preached that the reader would hardly agree to any condemnation of it. Nor do we wish to condemn thrift per se: it is in itself a necessary virtue, and individual thrift is the royal road to fortune. In the outset of his career the capitalist does exercise self-denial, but when thrift ceases to be self-denial and becomes mere accumulation it is a virtue no longer. So far as thrift enables the man who saves to use his own capital to produce more with less effort it is "a consummation devoutly to be wished," it attains what may be called the natural end of saving. But thrift ceases to be a good if it enables a man to do no work himself but live on the efforts of others. Yet that unfor- tunately is the result-the unnatural result-when thrift passes into mere accumulation. accumulation into investment, and investment results in permanent idleness. That a man should -for a time-do no work is reasonable only if he is then con- suming what he has himself saved from his honest toil. But "to do nothing" continuously is as unnatural as it is mischiev- ous alike to the individual and the community. To save means to relinquish or abstain from using a consumable good, to sac- rifice the fleeting satisfaction of to-day for a-perhaps- greater satisfaction to-morrow. May not that sacrifice have its natural reward ? Certainly it may have its natural reward. The natural reward of not eating our cake to-day to be able to eat-not a larger one-but the same cake, somewhat staler, to.morrow. If a fresh cake of the same weight and quality is returned to-morrow for one given away to-day, the advantage, 157 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOIM. as in most exchanges, may be mutual. There is really no ques- tion of sacrifice at all. Legitimate anxiety to make provision for one's old age is --with many people-the chief impulse towards saving, but this provision can best be made by contribution to the pension fund of others. Just as a man who enjoys "free" education for his children pays in taxes-not merely during the time his children are at school, but during his whole working life-so also should he pay, indirectly, for his own old age pension. And the pension should be, and could be, not a beggarly pit- tance, but sufficient to keep him in the degree of comfort he has always enjoyed. The provision of such pensions should hold a foremost place in reform. It would remove the dread so many men now have of any alteration in the existing system of wealth distribution. Now let us imagine if we can that the forces and materials of Nature have been made common property-that everyone is a landlord and a capitalist. Shall we all sit down and live on our rent and interest? The idea is worth consideration. The 'wages' of capital, of capital apart from labor, would still be there, but these wages would not materialise. Clearly in reality they never were there. The wages of capital must be -earned for us by others or we must work. For as Gilbert has it: "When everybody's somebody, Why, no ,one's anybody." Since we cannot all live as capitalists the painful fact re- mains that all must work. By making everyone a landlord and a capitalist we have in effect eliminated both landlord and capitalist from our industrial system, leaving only workers. What then has justice to say to the workers when every- one is a worker? With the landlord-capitalist we have also eliminated private rent, private profit, and private interest, but we have not eliminated differential rent and differential profit, because they represent the aid-varying in degree- which "Nature" gives to man; the more or less fertile land, the rare waterfall, the greater or lesser utilisation of heat and elec- tricity. And not only do differential rent and profit represent differences in "Nature," they represent also differences-often necessary differences-in social organisation, inequalities en- tirely beyond the control of the individual, even beyond the control of a group. Now, clearly, if the justice of the common ownership of "Nature" is admitted, the group has no more right to claim the exclusive benefit of these differential ad- vantages than has the individual. That rules out the syndicalist 158 THE ETHICAL ASPECT. -the group of industrialists who claim as their own the entire product of some particular industry in which they happen to be engaged. The worker is not always entitled to the products of his own labour when that labour is aided by capital and social organisation. Such a claim is only just when the worker works under average conditions-with average natural ad- vantages-with machinery of the average amount and effi- ciency and under the average degree of industrial organisation. With more or less than average conditions the worker is en- titled to more or less than he produces. He is entitled to the value he gives out in labour, not the products he makes. Syn, dicalists overlook these facts, they fail to see that differential- rent and differential-profit justly belong to society as a whole. Capital is, in itself, a blessing and a good, an air from heaven, a spirit of health, an angel and a minister of grace, and not- as some would have it-a blast from hell, a goblin damn'd. But its blessings now fall in the wrong place, its kindly cur- rent has been turned awry. The contemptuous pity with which the superior person regards the weavers who wrecked the power looms is misplaced. In so far as the weavers own personal well-being was concerned, their smouldering rage, dull but instinctive, and breaking at length into a fierce flame, was a truer guide to their own interests than the intellectual blind- ness of those who see nothing but good in the use of machinery. Unwilling sacrifices, sacrifices as unnecessary as unwilling, they were the victims of the ignorance, greed, and stupidity of a society which was not able-and has not yet been able- to readjust itself to a changed environment. The so-called educated man of to-day rejoices in the conquest of Nature by man even though he darkly wonders why all these discoveries and inventions have not lightened the day's toil of every man. The educated man of to-day belongs chiefly to the stupid middle-classes, and he, in his turn, will receive the contemp- tuous pity of a later age. We are led, finally, to consider the right of bequest. Under the "gentile" system property remained in the gens. The gens was the undying individual. The gens as a lasting unit was essential to the life of ancient society. Rather than permit the death of such a unit, gentile society allowed a weak gens, by the fiction of adoption, to strengthen its numbers. When the system broke up, and the patriarchal family took its place, the life of the family was held to be continuous. When Solon permitted the Athenians to devise their movable property, they were not allQwed to disinherit their male des- cendants. With the growth of individualism the life of the 159 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. individual was held to .be continuous; his rights and duties were passed on to his heir who continued him rather than represented' him. Founded on Roman Law the existing right of bequest has grown into what it is to-day, a 'right' we believe to be one of the greatest wrongs ever inflicted on suffering humanity. Once useful it has become pernicious. With power founded on property, it was only natural that the father should wish to hand down his property-and power- to his son, but that society should permit the almost uncon- trolled power of bequest is quite another matter. That the will of a man no longer living should be imposed on the living is absurd; that, within limits, consideration on the ground of natural affection should be paid to the wishes of the dead is reasonable, but that the clutch of a dead hand should be allowed to choke posterity is as tragic as it is absurd. If we agree that certain property justly belongs to an individual we may concede-again within limits-the right of that individual to do what he will with his own. But when he is dead the :property is no longer his. What shall become of it would not indeed be a very important matter if it did not possess, under Capitalism, power, in the form of capital, to extract surplus value from the non-owners of capital, i.e., the work- ers. At present, for example, a wealthy woman has the power to leave the income extracted from the workers by perhaps a capital of half a million pounds sterling-to provide and support a home for stray cats-or even some less worthy ob- ject, although thousands of children may be underfed and neglected. A man is at present at liberty-in some countries -to cut off his son with a shilling and leave his wife and daughters in comparative want. (They manage these things better in the Argentine!) The absolute right of anyone to decide what shall be done with his property after his death is an absurd travesty of justice. That surely is the function of society. Even Senior,* the first occupant of the Chair of Political Economy in Oxford University, and the originator of the fashionable theory that interest is the reward of abstin- ence, says: "The inheritor cannot plead abstinence-the virtue is not transmissible, and he has no title to his fortune except just good luck." In all this it must not be thought that we are attacking private property. On the contrary we defend it. But there is private property and private property. All we ask is that "Senior is also the hero of the 'last hour' theory. He proved conclusively that the Lancashire cotton spinners made all their profit in the last hour. The hours were reduced from twelve to ten, and the manufacturers still made profits! 160 THE ETHICAL ASPECT. the reader should discriminate between two species. As a community we rightly refuse to permit the sewing machine of the poor seamstress to be distrained for rent. We recog- nise her right to use the means of her livelihood. It is 'proper'" that she should use her 'property.' The 'propriety' of that course no one denies. But we are not very logical. The property of the factory operative in the use of his means of livelihood is denied. It never strikes us that it is 'improper' to reduce the numlber of our hands,--that to do so is to violate the sacred right of private property. "The property which every man has in his own labour, as it is the original foundation of all other property, so it is the most sacred and inviolable. . . . To hinder him from employing his strength and dexterity . . . is a plain viola- tion of this most sacred property." (Adam Smith.) "The right of work . . . is the first, the most sacred, and the most imprescriptible of all kinds of property." (Turgot.) When the common or communal ownership of "Nature" is advocated, when we claim for every member of the com- munity an equal share of 'Nature,' we are defending the right of private property. If the labourer mixes his labour in his own share of 'Nature' the value thus created is, we contend, justly his. We defend his right to own that wealth against the wrong he now suffers from the employer who exploits him. It is the particular and exclusive ownership by indi- vidual or. class, not only of natural materials and forces, but of the chief benefits arising from social organis.tion and the in- herited knowledge of mankind: it is the leal monopoly of these things, which make the exploitation of the many by the few possible, that we condemn. The test is clear: The right to private property lies in the fact that-directly or indirectly -it is the result of our own exertion. Man lives in society. He is a social animal. Consequently, the exercise of some social function is his just claim to private property. And the city ground-landlord, the receiver of coal royalties, the holder of shares to whom are paid dividends, what social function do they perform? Clearly none whatever. Their disappear- ance would benefit the community. The landlord-capitalist has become a parasite, a hanger-on, a rudimentary organ, a mere appendix. His natural fate is, first, atrophy, then extinc- tion. That is the normal method by which Nature gets rid of functionless organs. Such organs may become a danger. Dis- ease no doubt is abnormal, yet Nature has her diseases. Men have died from appendicitis, nations have perished from in- ternal decay. K 161 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. A difficulty still remains, namely, what specifically is the wealth a man may justly claim on the ground of social services? How, in fact, is the wealth which results from the combined efforts of a community to be distributed amongst its members? These questions are answered completely in a later chapter. In the meantime it may be noted that whilst payment of differential rent and differential profit to the community is just, their diversion into private pockets is un- just. A test of justice is on every income tax paper: "In- come derived from personal exertion" is just: "Income derived from property" is theft, not legal, but moral theft. The dishonest system of Capitalism hangs this carcase -this long-dead albatross-round the neck of every landlord and capitalist. To some it is a necklace of spring violets, to others a dull opiate-a garland of poppies-to others-who know it for what it really is-it is a horror and a nightmare. "Who shall deliver us from the body of this death?" Justice, as we have said, is relative. It is summed up in the motto of each system: of Capitalism: "to each according to his economic strength" or "might is right": that is the justice of the brute: of socialism: "to each according to his deeds"; that is the justice of man: of communism: "to each accord- ing to his needs": that is the justice of the angel, and, as we are often told, men are not yet angels, but neither are they brutes! In the industrial society of to-day differentiation has so far outstripped integration that the bounds of society are strained to the breaking point. Unless integration becomes wider, advancing to a new and higher form, the disruption of society seems inevitable. The old integument is no longer large enough to contain in harmony the increased number of parts into which society has differentiated. That is the cause of the 'class war,' and on its issue depends the fate of the nation. That differentiation may pass into disintegration is the supreme danger. 162 THE PHILOSOPHY OF CAPITALISM. XI. The Philosophy of Capitalism. "In every historical epoch the prevailing mode of eco- nomic production and exchange, and the social organisation necessarily following from it, form the basis upon which is built up, and from which alone can be explained, the political and intellectual history of that epoch." (Marx.) We may then expect to find in the philosophy of Capital- ism a rationalisation of the economic interests of capitalists. That transient phase of industrial evolution which is, we be- lieve, only the intermediate stage between the Guild System and Guild Socialism, and which is known as Capitalism, has for a slogan "Freedom of Contract," and for philosophy the doctrine of Laissez-faire. As all of us are equally inclined to claim for our favourite doctrine the aegis of freedom, and to blazon on our individual banner that much-enduring word, so do the disciples of laissez-faire also call their system free- dom. There are many 'freedoms': there is a freedom from all restrictions, that is more properly called license: there is a freedom of just and equal conditions for all. So far as laissez-faire claims a freedom of its own, it is freedom from economic or political conditions imposed by the State, a free- dom doubtless essential in certain phases of evolution to break up an old or obsolete economic system. Such was the freedom of the individualist which paved the way to a higher synthe- sis, broke up the old guild regulations, released the labourer from his bondage to the soil, and established the free competi- tion of Capitalism. (Once by free competition the capitalist has climbed to power he kicks the ladder from beneath his feet and demands 'protection'). To-day, and of necessity, the cry is for curtail- ment of capitalistic freedom. Gradually, or it may be sud- denly, Capitalism must pass away before the dawn of a new and better system. That involves new political laws: for every economic order finds its reflection in political law. Order and law go hand in hand. To oppose the coming order is as futile as it is to try to prop up the ruins of an order already tumbling to decay. Yet every cause finds its quota of 163 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. "die-hards," who will fight till the last ditch and not always without some success. The advancing tide is not without its receding wave: for the moment,-1923,-the wave is receding and reaction prevails. Thus in England a reactionary Con- servative Government marks the same general movement as Fascism in Italy, the 'Swastika' in Bavaria, the Knupfal- Brigade in Austria, the Awakeners in Hungary, and Hacken- kreutzler in Czecho-Slovakia, while Poland has her Korfanty and Haller, Bulgaria her Macedon Commitadjis. Thus over a great part of Europe reaction is, for the moment, supreme. One had thought the doctrine of Laissez-faire dead beyond hope of resuscitation, riddled by criticism, shot to pieces by the heavier artillery of commonsense, a mere shapeless mass of ruins. More than a quarter of a century ago Frederic Har- rison said: The satanic doctrine of laissez-faire is dead. More than sixty years ago Comte wrote: It sets up as a universal dogma the absence of all regulat- ing intervention whatever as the best means of promoting the spontaneous rise of society; so that, on every serious occasion, this doctrine can respond to urgent practical needs only by the uni- form xeproduction of this systematic negation. Because it perceives a natural tendency in society to arrange itself in a certain order, not seeing in :this a suggestion of an order to be promoted by social ar- rangements, it preaches an absence of regulation which, if carried out to the limit of the principle, would lead to the methodical abolition of all government. . . it systematises anarchy . .. Such a doctrine publishes its own weakness by showing its want of relation to the aggregate of our practical needs. Yet the Rip Van Winkles of political life, oblivious of the past and refreshed by their long sleep, have delved to some purpose among the ruins, and "like a child from the womb, like a ghost from the tomb," they have risen and built it againt. It becomes then necessary to "slay again the already slain": crushing this hoary error that would fain pretend to be a growing youth: and therefore briefly to examine once more the bases on which the superstructure rests. There are four foundation stones: (1) The idea promulgated by Adam Smith that what is good for the individual must be good for the nation. (2) Malthus' "law of population." (3) Natural Selection or the "Survival of the Fittest." (4) The confusion of "State" with "Nation." Yet before we deal with the foundations we may be per- mitted to glance at the edifice. 164 THE PHILOSOPHY OF CAPITALISM. The apologists for laissez-faire contend that there is a natural balance or equilibrium towards which all creation tends: that the forces of Nature, if blind, are yet directed by an "invisible hand," so as to promote human welfare, and that therefore all we have to do is to give these forces free play: that unrestricted competition,--a sort of "devil take the hindmost,"-will finally result in an earthly paradise, so that to interfere is not only foolish but impious. It is a com- fortable doctrine,-for the rich. Those who would live tran- quil and undisturbed may well embrace it, false as in our be- lief the doctrine is. Yet there must be some basis of truth, or the doctrine could not have stood for a moment. We pro- pose therefore to examine carefully the ground on which it has been built up. (1). There is first the plausible idea put forward by Adam Smith that "what is good for the individual must be good for the nation." The idea found ready acceptance, it seemed self-evident: even to-day it is a commonplace. Let every individual member acquire virtue, strength, wealth, and the nation will be virtuous, strong and rich: the appeal is irresistible,- and sound,-if only every one does so acquire. Let every one seek his own self-interest, and he "is led in this, as in many other instances, by an invisible hand, to pro- mote an end that was no part of his intention"-in fact, the good of society. Yet, if I steal ten pounds from my neighbour society is no richer, even though he "seeks" to steal, and suc- ceeds in stealing ten pounds from me in return. What under- lies the misconception is a vague but strongly held idea that Nature or God arbitrarily interferes with, or by an innate tendency in things directs the unconscious or conscious actions of man: which is in reality a doctrine of fatalism or deter- minism, and the very antithesis of the individualism which fathers it. Or perhaps the unconscious action of man is con- sidered to be "natural," the conscious, if not unnatural, at least "artificial," an antithesis which if convenient is cer- tainly also misleading. The idea that the interests of the individual and the nation march always hand in hand is not in agreement with fact. It is the interest of the nation to be victorious in war, but the dead, though we may count them happy, are not en- vied, and had each soldier been guided by self-interest he would have run away. What is true of individual and nation is true also of class and nation:-as Cairnes says: "Let us not con- found the statement that human interests are at one with the statement that class interests are at one. .The latter, I be- 165 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. lieve to be as false as the former is true."* Indeed, the reality of the "class-war" is often denied on just this mistaken ground that all men have interests in common. Sheep and wolf are both, directly or indirectly, interested in grass: war, if bad for the soldier, is good for profiteers, and vultures live on the dead. (2). Nor, secondly, is there any reason to be disturbed over Nature's capacity to deal with the problem of popula- tion: she has her own, drastic, methods of reducing a surplus. Malthus' so-called law asserts that population increases or tends to increase in geometrical progression,-as 1, 2, 4, 8, 16, -while the means of subsistence increase in arithmetical pro- gression only,-i.e., as 1, 2, 3, 4, 5,-with the inevitable con- sequence that population is always tending to outrun sub- sistence. Thus "at Nature's feast no place is set for the children of the poor: she sternly bids them to begone." For all the show of mathematical accuracy that the Malthusian law presents, it is not true that population, whatever its tend- ency, has steadily increased in any geometrical progression: it would be enough to say that population had increased, was increasing, .and tended to increase, with which statement there would be little room to find fault. But it is otherwise with his assertion as to means of subsistence: that is absolutely false. Nature has given to every mouth a pair of hands to feed it: and two men working together can and do produce more than twice as much as one. Yet Malthus seriously asks us 'to believe that, for example, 16 men can produce only five times as much as one. Even human credulity has its limits. It may be, however, that to some economists the so-called "law of diminishing returns" seems to give support to the Malthusian view. The "law" might just as well have been "the law of increasing returns." What it means is that under given circumstances there is a certain ratio between human effort and "natural forces" which, once reached, yields a maximum effect or greatest return per unit of human effort. Thus,-a man may not only plough his field but may gather and spread manure on it, with the result that at harvest time he finds that his return, per hour worked, has increased: in the follow- ing year he devotes still more time to gathering and spreading manure, only to find that though his total return has again increased, yet the return per hour worked has actually diminished. After all, there is much virtue in a name: and if the "law" were called that of "increasing returns," few would find in it any suggestion of support for Malthus. The underlying truth in his theory is no more than this, that if human beings constantly increase in number there must * Essays on Political Economny, p. 245. 166 THE PHILOSOPHY OF CAPITALISM. ultimately come a time when there is not standing room for them on the earth, a bogey which is not likely to frighten the reader. As a matter of fact, history does not record constant increases of population, and does record many and great deereases. It may be of interest to add that Malthus himself was -no advocate of laissez-faire. Birth-control, by other means than those he advised, is now common, if not universal, and not least amongst the disciples of laissez-faire. (3). We turn now to 'Natural Selection,' or,-for it is but another name for the same thing,-the 'Survival of the Fittest.' Natural selection is only possible on two conditions: that individual animals and plants vary (thus affording ground for selection), and that Nature "red in tooth and claw," brings about a great destruction of life, the 'less fit' being destroyed, the 'more fit' surviving. The former of these conditions does apply to man, the latter does not. A sea mullet will lay in the season some 2,000,000 eggs: and, although all are fertile, not one per cent. will grow to maturity; the rest have perished not for lack of food so much as because they are themselves the food-supply of innumerable enemies: and if it were not so there would be no balance in nature, the prolific mullet would literally "eat up" the sea. Civilised men do not eat one another, and there is, in this age of the world, no animal capable of eating man, at least to the point of serious loss. Thus the biological law of the sur- vival of the fittest has little or no application to man. "Those," says Wallace, "who advocate our allowing natural selection to have free play among ourselves on the ground that we are interfering with Nature are totally ignorant of what they are talking about." All which is not to deny that, as is self-evident, if some are to be destroyed, the 'fittest' will survive. In modern war- fare the fittest to survive are those who stay at home because, perhaps, they are unfit for the ranks. The fittest must survive, it is mere tautology, but in the case of man it is not the 'blind forces' of Nature that alone hold sway: there is also man's conscious action, a new and very real factor in the equation. Now the mind of man is just as "natural" as any other func- tion or part of his being: yet the interference by man's con- scious self is, rather absurdly, classed as "artificial." This "artificial" action of man has given us for example the de- veloped strain of animal and plant life upon which modern civilisation is based. Artificial if it be called, it is surely just as natural as, say, the action of the heart. In effect Nature, or what you please to call the Power, has given us 167 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. reason and intelligence, and the fruits of the operation of these are just as 'natural' as those of the instinct of the beast. Thus it is that the whole of the laissez-faire philosophy basing itself on a mere play on the sense of the word 'natural' misleads, and has misled the world for longer than it profits to reckon. Selection may be 'natural,' that is, unconscious, as in plants and animals, including savage man; or it may be 'artificial,' that is, the result of man's conscious action; or it may be 'semi-conscious,' as birth-control at present directed to selfish personal ends, whose effect on the social organism is unrecognised and, in many cases, pernicious, as when, e.g., the mentally feeble have many children and the mentally strong, few. We should advocate an advance to 'conscious' selection, not a return to 'natural' selection. Man is a reasoning, tool-using animal, who also has the power to direct the forces of Nature to his benefit. But he can best do so by using his power consciously and delibe- rately to combine individual effort with those of his fellows towards the goal of organised social production. Such effort, directed and combined, is man's contribution to the advance- ment of the race. Only in a high form of social life is the highest form ,of individual life possible. (4). Finally as to the supposed identity of the "State" and "nation." If the advocates of laissez-faire mean by "the State" the ruling political party, or the department that ad- ministers on its behalf, in fact, a bureaucracy, then we agree that the State was not designed, and is not fitted to carry on the work of industry. Society must develop, is perhaps even now developing, an economic organ. And the sooner the bet- ter. Yet even now it might reasonably be argued that it is better for the State to manage industry badly than for 'pri- vate ownership' to manage it well. Of what use to us is an efficient machine if we do not receive the results of that efficiency, but only periodical unemployment? The question is not so much one of efficiency in produc- tioni as of efficiency in distribution. Capable managers can be bought by the "State" or "nation" as freely as by "private owners," ahd there is no reason why an industry "owned" by the community should not be managed as well as one "owned"'' by a private company. But it is foreign to our present pur- pose to discuss anything in the nature of "nationalisation" of -industry: all we are here concerned with is to emphasise the fundamental fallacy of laissez-faire-in other words, of "the philosophy of Capitalism." 168 THE MENTAL ATTITUDE. XII. The Mental Attitude. Mental action of some sort, conscious or unconscious, al- ways precedes physical action. Before we act we think, and what we think largely determines what we do. But similar sense impressions do not always produce, in different indi- viduals, similar action. Because they act on different and dissimilar minds, the reaction is different. Hence the importance, if we are to foretell or influence action, of knowing man's mental attitude. This is affected, among other influences, by theology, religion, philosophy, science, public opinion, prejudice, intuition, reason. Let us briefly-very briefly-examine some of these in- fluences. Fear is one of the strongest of our inherited instincts, and it lies at the root of theological ideas. Man has ever made God in his own image. The early Scandinavians saw in ice and snow their worst enemy, in heat and light their best friend. Their long winter, when the sun seemed lost and vanquished, must have been a nightmare to them. An eclipse of the sun caused them the greatest consternation, and their triumph when he reappeared knew no bounds. The apparent con- test is the origin of Sun Myths. God and devil, light and darkness, heat and cold, good and bad, are all twin ideas. In the howling tempest, crouching in cold and darkness, the Viking thought he heard the Wild Horsemen thunder by, and in imagination fled before them. And even yet, whether the pursuer seeks to save or to destroy, man flies in fear from the unknown. I fled Him, down the nights and down the days; I fled Him, down the arches of the years; I fled Him, down the labyrinthine ways Of my mind; and in the mist of tears I hid from Him, and under running laughter. Up vistaed hopes I sped; And shot, precipitated, Adown Titanic glooms of chasmed fears. From those strong Feet that followed, followed after. But with unhurrying chase, And unperturbed pace, Deliberate speed, majestic instancy, They beat-and a Voice beat More instant than the Feet- "All things betray thee, who betrayest Me." Page 169, 12th line from bottom of page-"Of my mind" should read "Of my own mind" 169 170 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. . . Across the margent of the world I fled, And troubled the gold gateways of the stars, Smiting for shelter on their clanged bars; Fretted to dulcet jars And silvern chatter the pale ports o' the moon. . . . To all swift things for swiftness did I sue; Clung to the whistling mane of every wind. But whether they swept, smoothly fleet, The long savannahs of the blue; Or whether, Thunder-driven, They clanged his chariot 'thwart a heaven Plashy with flying lightnings round the spurn o' their feet:- Fear wist not to evade as Love wist to pursue.* The Grecian saw in God beauty and sensuous joy personi- fied; to other nations his chief characteristic was power. Thor and his hammer, Jupiter hurling his thunderbolt, Nep- tune and his Trident. To the Hebrew he was a God of Battles, to the oppressed a God of Vengeance, or a Deliverer, or a God of Love and Consolation. In modern times the Hebrew God is relied on to excuse multitudinous murder and anon the Prince of Peace to stay the slaughter: our every mood is re- flected. If we are rich but grow uneasy regarding the dis- tribution of wealth, is it not written, "The poor ye have al- ways with you," and should not they learn to be content with the position in life in which it has pleased the Almighty to place them, and have not we chosen the better part? And the Sons of Mary smile and are blessed-they know the Angels are on their nide. They know in them is the Grace confessed, and for them are the Mercies multiplied. They sit at The Feet-they hear The Word-they see how truly the promise runs; They have cast their burden upon the Lord and-the Lord He lays it on Martha's sons! As Ruskin reverently says, "To call the confused wreck of social order and life, brought about by malicious confusion and competition, an arrangement of Providence is quite one of the most insolent and wicked ways in which it is possible to take the name of God in vain." It is utterly hopeless to look for help to creed-bound theologians. If we except the Society of Friends, how many sermons were preached, during the Great War, from the texts, "Love your enemies" and "Thou shalt not kill"? How many preachers of Christianity proved faithful to the teachings of their Master? Yet sack- cloth and ashes are still out of fashion. * One would like to quote the whole of Francis Thompson's noble poem, "The Hound of Heaven." THE MENTAL ATTITUDE. No,--from formal theology there is nothing to hope. It has undoubtedly been the greatest curse that has ever afflicted suffering humanity. "Christianity in practice, as we know it now, for all the Sermon on the Mount, is the religion of ag- gression, domination, combat. It waits upon the pushing trader and the lawless conqueror; and with obsequious thanks- giving it blesses his enterprise."*' "The growing temper of sac- erdotalism and the doctrine of authority well accord with mili- 'tarism and political autocracy. Force is the natural ally of superstition, and superstition knows it well."t From formal dogma there is nothing to hope, but true religion and unde- filed-the reverent recognition of a Great Mystery-the up- ward striving of the human spirit-the yearning to be at one with the Infinite-the spirit of service and self-sacrifice-the religion of humanity-is the sheet anchor of our hope. Yet man ever makes God in his own image. He is the reflection of man's own mind. But one mind acts and reacts on another, forms, and is formed by others until their sum constitutes the mental attitude of each age or period. Perhaps after Theology the 'dismal' science of Economics is most responsible for the later miseries of mankind. Next to the stupidity of consigning 'unbelievers' to eternal torment omes the crudity of an 'inexorable' law which condemns the wage-earner to life-long poverty, and condones the atrocities of a factory system. Economics, for long the happy hunting ground of theologian and metaphysician, is hardly yet a science. Many of its teachers still bow the knee in the orthodox Temple of Rimmon, but there are, and not a few, exceptions-some are among the martyrs. We need recall only the fate of Thorstein Veblen-a fate which spells eternal disgrace to his university.,, Nor, alas, does Veblen stand alone. The position as it affects especially the life of a university is well put by J. A. Hobson: It is not so much the weight of the 'dead hand' that is to be feared as that of the living: a college so unfortunate as to harbour teachers who, In handling vital issues of politics or economics, teach truths deeply and obviously antagonistic to the interests of the classes from whom financial aid was sought, would be committing suicide. Higher education has never been economically self-supporting; it has hardly ever been fully organised from public funds; everywhere it has re- mained parasitic on the private munificence of wealthy persons . Where universties are dependent for endowments and incomes upon the favor of the rich, upon the charity of millionaires, there will be: 'Safe teachers. Safe studies. Sound (i.e., orthodox) methods.' The coarse proverb which tells us that "he who pays the piper calls the tune" is quite applicable here as elsewhere, and no bluff regarding academic dignity and intellectual honesty must blind us to the fact. . The subservience to rank and money, even in our older English uni- *Harrison. t Hobson. 171 172 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. versities, has been of late evinced so nakedly, and the demand for monetary aid in developing new faculties necessarily looms so large in academic eyes, that the danger here indicated is an evergrowing one. . . The millionaire who endows Oxford does not buy its men of learning outright . . . but it is becoming more difficult for a scholar with the intellectual outlook of a John Morley, a Frederic Harrison, or a Goldwin Smith to secure election, or for a political economist with strong views on the necessity of controlling capital to be elected to a chair in Economics.* If that is true of British what must be said of American Universities ? This: the blight of Capitalism is over them all. Let anyone recall the early history of Chicago University. And of the so-called science of Economics itself what shall we say? Science tells us of the ways in wvhich force acts on matter-tells us that if certain conditions are present certain results invariably follow: of first causes she says nothing. But man demands an explanation. To the primitive man all causes are animistic: he. causes things to move, therefore, every movement he does not cause is the result of the ak'tion of some similar being, God or devil. Does he seek the cause of thunder? Jove is hurling his thunderbolts, although the "Hand" is hidden behind the thunder-cloud. Next he en- dows material things with a mind: and now we hear that Nature abhors a vacuum, or the,.subjective creates the objec- tive, interest is caused by abstinence, value is pain or pleasure, or an idea. Economics has not long left her misty Olympus, has hardly yet cast away the granite table of "inexorable" law. But we may yet hope to see her descend the mountain- side, and in the "common light of day" pace the valley of matter-of-fact with her sisters, and point to the cause of this, the effect of that-'"so far as she can tell," and subject always to correction, like every other modest science. At present she is a dangerous and uncertain guide. What is the use of a vast body of generalisations based on a spec- ial set of conditions, where those conditions vary indefinitely? The number of such bodies of laws is infinite. There may be a million sys- tems of Political Economy besides the one we have got, all just as true if we allow their data. What is the use of one more than another, unless we suppose some one of the sets of conditions permanent? The actual economic laws are certainly not true now, never can be true, and in the progress of civilisation may become less and less true inde- finitely. Let it be supposed, however, that they bear some relation to an actual state of society. But what if the actual state of society changes, what is the good of them then? We should want another set in relation to that change, and so on . . . Political Economy. . rests on the assumption that the social state is practically not cap- able of improvement, . . . Yet all reasonable social inquiry pro- ceeds on the ground that the social state requires much improvement. Directly it is improved, new economic principles will be needed. . * "Imperialism: A Study," p. 232-1. THE MENTAL ATTITUDE. One of the acutest of men, Machiavelli, studying one of the corruptest of human societies, once conceived the idea of reducing politics to a system on the assumption that men simply acted for their own inte- rests (the very assumption of the economists). . . . His "Prince" is a sort of Bible of Political Vice.* And of our subjective economists the words of Comte are still true: . .. Looking with an impartial eye upon their disputes . . . we might imagine ourselves present at a conference of scholiasts of the Middle Ages about the attributes of their metaphysical entities. With the philosophy of Capitalism we have already dealt. Theology, Religion, Economics, Philosophy-each and all affect man's mental attitude, but perhaps nothing is so potent for good or evil as the daily press. Once a week sermons are preached but for the most part not heard; six-nay seven- days a week into every man's ear the press whispers, suggests, insinuates, shrieks, or even thunders, in defence of Capitalism. Social prejudice is fostered, "go-slow "-by the workingman- is denounced, "Waste" is reprobated, "Economy"is ex- tolled, "Taxation" is anathematised; the doctrine of hard work-for the workers-is preached; the absolute futility of socialism is demonstrated; the transcendent glories of "capital" are displayed. Well, what else is to be expected? Editors and leader-writers 'must live,' and they can live most comfortably by prostituting their intel- lects and selling them to the highest bidder. In England and her Dominions the press is bought and sold, but it is in America that the press has fallen lowest. Read, for example, the letter of James H. Barry, Editor of the "San Francisco Star,"' addressed to Professor Ross, of the University of Wisconsin: You wish to know my confidential opinion as to the honesty of the Associated Press. My opinion, not confidential, is that it is damnedest, meanest monopoly on the face of the earth-wet-nurse for all other monopolies. It lies by day, it lies by night, and it lies for the very lust of lying. Or hear the Editor of the "New York Tribune" replying to the toast of "The Independent Press": There is no such thing as an independent press, unless it be in the country towns. You know it, and I know it. There's not one of you dares to write his honest opinions . . . any of you who would be so foolish . . . would be out on the streets looking for another job. The business of the press is to destroy the truth, to pervert, to vilify, to fawn at the feet of Mammon, and to sell his race and country * Frederic Harrison-"National and Social Problems," pp. 298-301. 173 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. for his daily bread. You know it, and I know it, and what folly is this to be toasting an 'Independent Press'? Thus self-interest sways the intellect and determines the mental attitude of each and every class in the community. The attitude of the capitalist is easily understood; he is out to fight his brother capitalist, or discreetly join hands with him, to "get rich quick," and if, as in a few cases, he thinks it is a disgrace to die rich, yet his selfishness is easily rationalised. It is so easy to be convinced when we want to be convinced. As the Spanish proverb runs: "When the devil is hungry he eats flies." No argument is too petty to con- vince when desire points the way. And how the toadies of Capitalism play up to their pat- rons! Thus, for example, your stockbroker in his monthly report: "It is no doubt hopeless to look for the abrogation of the tax on the so-called 'unimproved value' of land, an absurd- ity based on the Henry George fallacy. The Act is a model of tangled and self-contradictory stupidity, being the polished product of the brilliant disciples of the mad Karl Marx." Writ- ten evidently by a student of Marxian economics. It is, however, the blindness of the "great middle class" which is at once the most pitiful, astonishing, and dangerous of existing social phenomena. Those who belong to it cannot or will not see that although they may be more highly edu- cated, have attained to a higher standard of "culture," oc- cupy a different social position, nay, even ride first-class in railway trains, they are in exactly the same economic class as manual workers. Only the middle-class is blind; the manual worker does know he is exploited, and the capitalist knows he exploits. It cannot be really that the middle-class is more stupid than other classes; generally speaking, the reverse is probably true. What then is the explanation of this aston- ishing blindness? In the first place social prejudice. Middle- class people generally employ "servants," and they seem to imagine that the salary they themselves live on is something entirely different in its nature from the wages they pay. To the women, especially their servants, take shape as the 'work- ing-class'; they cannot realise that their husbands and fathers equally belong there. Even the men, though better able, and more willing, to recognise their true economic position, quickly lose sight of it when, as so many do, they come to live on interest from invested savings, and so dissociate income from active effort, mental or physical. And the second cause of blindness is their comparative indifference to, and ignorance of, economics. Already in fairly comfortable circumstances, associating-or perhaps trying to 174 TiE MENTAL ATTITUDE. associate--with the capitalist pure and simple, they have no incentive to study economics. The subject is, they find, un- popular; they would rather 'side with the angels.' If, on the other hand, they do study orthodox economics, what do they find? Necessarily false conclusions proceeding from the erroneous premise that selfishness is the only motive of economic conduct-or, at best, a mere exposition of economic fact, as it exists under Capitalism. If they seek their ideas of political economy from the brain-stupefying leaders in their morning papers, they are fed with words which carefully foster social prejudice. The one plain fact they do not learn, whether from newspaper or text-book, is that everyone who renders social service, whether by hand or brain, is a worker and should receive 'wages.' As a result of this teaching, good-hearted but (economically) muddle- headed people make a fetish of moderation and think all would be well if only masters and men would be more 'considerate' to each other; if the old 'paternal' relationship could be re- stored; if only landlords would be contented with 'fair' rents, capitalists with 'moderate' interest and tradesmen and manu- facturers with 'reasonable' profits. It is as though one were to approve of one's sister being 'moderately' virtuous. These good people are disposed to con- done the means by which wealth is acquired, if only it is used well. Ruskin tells us that under the feudal system, society was divided into peasants who lived by digging, priests who lived by begging, and knights who lived by pillaging; and (he adds, speaking of present-day exploitation) as the luminous public mind becomes fully cognisant of these facts, it will assuredly not suffer things to be alto- gether arranged that way any more. Under Capitalism churches are 'endowed,' knights live on rent, interest and profit, but peasants still dig. It is the gradual recognition of these facts by the public mind that is the cause of so much dissatisfaction. Prejudice still attaches to the name of labor union: and although in fact all professional men,--lawyers, doctors, engineers, architects, dentists and others,-have their unions, these are half-disguised as 'institutions,' or 'associations.' Pro- fessional fees, fixed by convention, are, in reality, wages, as are the salaries of high officials and business managers. The emoluments of judges and other highly placed individuals, the commissions of business men, even the profits of small trades- 175 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. men, are all wages, but the camouflage of a name disguises' the fact. The truth is that the middle-class, especially that "upper middle-class" Which tends to set the tone of the whole, looks forward to a time when its members will be living on an assured income derived from invested savings; so that throughout life their mental attitude is steadily approaching that of the capi- talist. Prejudice certainly is not confined to the middle-class and blindness to class-interest affects all grades of modern society. * But it is in the middle class that these two evils are most deeply rooted; and it is there that under present conditions of industrial organisation their influence upon the general welfare is most pernicious, may at any time become fatal. The position calls urgently for remedy. And a remedy can be found only in increased knowledge and a due appreciation of the true principles of economics. Prejudice is largely the result of ignorance. Vaguely to appeal for a "change of heart" is futile; a "change of head" is equally essential. Of the wage-earner it is hard to speak. The besotted, ignorant slave of industry still exists, here and there, but as a class he is rapidly passing away. The schoolmaster has been abroad and, at least, the worker can now read and has become conscious of his position. The. better class of workers are amongst the most intelligent of the nation and often get nearer to the truth than the orthodox economists. The fact is that essentially there is no difference at all between the classes. All are tarred with the same brush, and it is as useless as it is foolish for the pot to call the kettle black. We are trying to alter a worn-out system, not to vilify our fellow men. We are compelled to end on a note almost of despair. It really seems as though it were useless to appeal to reason; it seems as though all appeal to be effective must be to the emotions. When Germany, or Prussia, tore up her "scrap of paper" she gave us a splendid chance to make a moving emotional appeal, and we did not neglect the opportunity. When we tore up our scrap of paper---the fourteen points-on which the ink was hardly dry, we were looking the other way or were blind or deaf--certainly we were dumb, and its author, when it was pointed out to him that it was not reasonable or logical * The small shopkeeper does the community a service, he assists in the distribution of consumption goods. The payment he receives for this work he calls "profit,"' and if you tell him profit is exploitation of the worker, he does not believe you. He is thinking of one thing, whereas you are speaking of quite another. The "profit" he makes may not be a sufficient reward for his labor, and he does not regard himself as a laborer; on the other hand, it may greatly exceed the inherent-value of his work. 176 THE MENTAL ATTITUDE. to make Germany pay for military pensions when we (and he) had promised to confine reparations to civil damages, merely replied: "Damn logic," words that we fear will some day be washed out in rivers of blood. And Fohi, 3000 years before Christ taught the Chinese that Reason came from Heaven! A mere repudiation of logic might leave us cold: we may dispute the ground on which the argument stands: but in this particular case the condemnation of logic was also a repudia- tion of our plighted word and the betrayal of a disarmed nation. The 'peace' was the greatest atrocity of the war. It is on this stormy sea of angry passions and contending interests that we must perforce launch our bark. L 177 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. XIII. Capitalism. It is hardly necessary at this stage to define Capitalism, but it may be described briefly as a system in which one set of individuals makes goods and another set owns them. The preceding analysis, although far from complete, has perhaps raised some suspicion that Capitalism is by no means a perfect industrial system; but at least this can be said in its favor-it works: efficiently or inefficiently, it works. It is moreover the result of a long process of development. That it is perfect, few will be found to assert, but there are con- siderations of caution, which make us "rather bear those ills we have than fly to others that we know not of." The ills of Capitalism are admitted, but we must be convinced that there is a more excellent way before we agree to any change. That part of our subject comes later: at present we would stress the reality of the "ills we have." Some of those ills have already been exhibited, they will merely be catalogued here; others must receive some fuller notice. We arraign Capital- ism then on the following charges: 1. It is an inefficient mode of producing wealth. 2. It is an inefficient mode of distributing wealth. 3. It contains inherent contradictions. 4. It develops a functionless parasitic class. 5. It fetters education and contaminates the seats of learning. 6. It fosters class prejudice and the class war. 7. It promotes Imperialism and causes International war. 8. It develops a ruling class and consequently a ruled class, i.e., virtual slavery. To retort, in general answer to these charges, that "Capi- talism is a necessary stage in the evolution of industry," is beside the mark: our concern is not with what has been but 178 with what, in the present stage of industrial evolution, is neces- sary. That Capitalism is necessary now we unhesitatingly deny; with equal readiness we admit that it was, at a time, an advance in the method of producing wealth. '1. Summarily dismissing, as we certainly may, this general objection it remains to substantiate the individual accusations levelled against Capitalism. "Capitalism then," to repeat, "is an inefficient method of producing wealth." Now it is true that on the one hand large-scale production, power-driven machinery, division of labor under the factory system, the chief advances in industrial organisation made by Capitalism, do increase enormously the amount of wealth. But it is equally true: that the abolition of Capitalism would not make it neces- sary to surrender these advantages. Thus the relative effi- ciency of Capitalism is not lost. On the other hand Capitalism acts directly counter to efficiency in the following ways: (a) It creates unemployment-and that both of men and .machinery. For, as it fosters a go-slow policy on the part of the ::employees, so it teaches employers deliberately to reduce output when commodities cannot be sold at a sufficient profit --the go-slow policy of the capitalist. (b) It causes, through competition, unnecessary employ- ment. The number of banks, insurance companies, agents and middlemen of all kinds, to say nothing of retail shops, greatly exceeds the needs of the population. No observer can have missed the lesson which any street in any town offers any morning of the year,-a round half-dozen of carts delivering bread-or meat, or milk-where one could do the work as well or better. And to this must be added the waste of wealth in the advertisement of competing articles of trade, a system- inseparable from modern methods of trading-which increases up to 100 per cent. the price to the consumer. That is its objective side: (c) subjectively, efficiency de- mands that wealth should be distributed amongst the members of a community so as to produce the greatest amount of satis- faction. And here we join hands with those who point out that the final utility of a commodity should be as high as possible. The bread which satisfies the hunger of the worker is of higher utility, both to the individual and to the com- munity, than the cake which stimulates the cloyed appetite of the idle rich. As distributed at present wealth is often not a utility, but a futility, or even a disutility. The cake of the rich may become a poison rather than a food. Capitalism stimu- lates unnecessary production, especially of articles of luxury whose subjective value in the pleasure they give is far less than the pain entailed in their production. CAPITALISM. 179 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. 2. "Capitalism is an inefficient mode of distributing wealth." To substantiate this charge it is sufficient to refer the reader to the diagram of the distribution of wealth on page 80. 3. "Capitalism contains inherent contradictions." In- creased production might mean increase of wealth to each member of the community: whereas, under Capitalism, the greater the quantity of wealth produced the sooner a mass of wealth faces-across an impassable gulf-a mass of starving people. This is the meaning-and the lesson-of every de- pression in trade. 4. "Capitalism develops a functionless parasitic class." The man of 'independent means' is liable to be a nuisance to himself as he is certainly a danger to society. He has done the State no service. "Our criticism"-says J. A. Hobson- "of the present industrial system as an instrument of social economy is that it works too wastefully: it does not evoke productive energy 'according to powers' nor does it distribute the product 'according to needs.' The 'surplus' is at once the measure and the instrument of this waste. Its injury is three- fold. First as unearned individual income not merely does it fail to support or stimulate productive effort, but it diverts individual energies into non-productive channels, atrophies socially serviceable activities, and substitutes either a life of idleness or one of frivolous and socially injurious activity. ,Surplus acts on its recipients as an inhibition upon labor. Secondly, so far as it represents the result of sweating, rack- renting, or other processes of oppressive bargaining, it injures the productivity of labor by robbing the laboring classes of their natural stimulus to progressive efficiency. Thirdly, by enabling individuals to take for their private income what is produced by society and is required to satisfy the needs of social life, it damages the efficiency of the State and of the public services it is called upon to render." 5. "Capitalism fetters education and contaminates the seats of learning." In the four chief engines of popular education-church, press, schools and universities, and the political machine-the controlling lever is in the hands of capital. Thus Capitalism largely determines the mental attitude. 6. "It fosters social prejudice and the class war." The first we have already dealt with, the second we shall refer to later. 7. "Capitalism promotes 'Imperialism' and causes inter- national war." Imperialism appeals to national pride and pat- riotism. Just and good as these sentiments are-within limits 180 --few people understand how these virtues have been ex- ploited by capitalists. The capitalist himself, in his search for profit, knows no country. He does not invest in the country he lives in if a more profitable investment can be made in some other country. Wealth is the object of his desire and monopoly the means of its acquisition. Man working in co-operation with Nature produces wealth. Therefore, the capitalist must exploit men or Nature, or both. Cheap labor he regards as a boon, undeveloped natural resources are his delight, provided he is able to exploit them. If the labor of his own countrymen is dear, no spectre of unemployment prevents him from using cheaper foreign labor. Yet he is patriotic ! He enters on enterprises in foreign and undeveloped countries, but expects his country to guarantee his profits. The profit he makes may be enormous because of the risk of the investment, but although he discounts his risk he refuses to meet its bills. He demands the protection of his country. Hie prates of patriotism. He "extends the bounds of the Em- pire." In reality the capitalist has no country, he knows no nation, he belongs to a class that cuts athwart all political boundaries-the great international class of exploiters. Yet within that class there is competition. It is a case of diamond cut diamond and each jewel seeks a national setting, making a tool of diplomacy and fools of his fellow countrymen. England (Lord Cowdray and his friends) secures oil con- cessions in Central America or Persia (to the great annoyance of the Standard Oil Group). England (Lords Rothschild, Mil- ner, and their friends) "spoils the Egyptians." England (Lord Incheape and his friends) corners-or tries to corner-the overseas carrying trade. England (Lord Leverhulme and his friends) exploits West Africa. England (the concession hunters) exploits the inhabitants and the raw materials of India, Turkey, China, Egypt, down to that small speck in the Pacific-Nauru. Nothing is too common or unclean. And all this to the great annoyance of America and France and Ger- many and Japan. France (French capitalists) was much annoyed when Germany (German capitalists) wanted a slice of the iron-ore of Morocco. America (American capitalists) would, no doubt, scorn to take from China a concession grant- ing the exclusive right to build railways for the poor Chinese, and (incidentally) power to make the Chinese pay through the nose for this blessing of civilisation. It is as true to-day as when Sir Thomas More wrote the :words, "Everywhere do I perceive a certain conspiracy of rich men seeking their own advantage under the name and pretext of the Commonwealth." And it is these rich men who are CAPITALISM. 181 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. responsible 'for the Great War. Greed, greed and lust for personal power-in a word Imperialism-caused the war. And who are its victims? Of those who fell or were broken in the war the vast majority were workers. And that is equally true of those who are broken in the peace. For while it is certain that, if :Germany is to pay a huge indemnity, the stan- dard of her workers' life must be lowered, yet at least her people will be employed: but it is equally certain that the workers of France, England, America and Italy will suffer from unemployment. And the rich men have grown richer! Since the foregoing was written Rear-Admiral Consett in his "Triumph of Unarmed Forces" tells us that, with the know- ledge of the British Admiralty, profiteers in England, during the war, supplied Germany, via Scandinavian countries, with the sinews of war: coal, fodder, fertilisers, rope, petrol, tin, nickeI: cotton, etc., without which the war must have ended at least two years earlier. As J. A. Blaksley says in an article in the "National Review" (June, 1923), entitled "The Greatest Tragedy in History," "There is dark work, dirty work, my Masters, behind this business," but we are not so sanguine as he is when he adds, "As for the regiment of profiteers who made their millions by the death of Englishmen their punish- ment will come in due time." The time is already overdue. If these men are not traitors to their country and murderers there is no meaning in the words. That modern wars have been, almost exclusively, due to economic causes is profoundly true and these economic causes may be summed up in the word Imperialism. Imperialism de- notes those interests of a capitalist class which are diametri- cally opposed to those of the nation as a whole. Thus war largely arises from a lack of internal harmony. "The only safety of nations (says J. A. Hobson) lies in removing the unearned increments of income from the possessing classes, and adding them to the wage-income of the working classes or to the public income, in order that they may be spent in raising the standard of consumption." And there is much truth in Green's contention: "The source of war between States lies in the incomplete fulfilment of their function; in the fact that there is some defect in the maintenance or reconciliation of rights among their own subjects . . . It is nothing then in the necessary organisation of the State, but rather some defect of that organisation in relation to its proper function of maintaining and reconcil- ing rights, of giving scope to capacities, that leads to a conflict of apparent interests between one State and another. . . . The military system of Europe is no necessary incident of the 182 CAPITALISM. relations between independent States, but arises from the fact that organisation of State-life (national life), even with those peoples that have been brought under its influence at all, is so incomplete." Finally, while we condemn capitalist exploitation because it leads through Imperialism to war, we do not hold as corollary that the raw materials of countries inhabited by lower races must remain permanently unexploited by higher races. Here the dictum of Joseph Chamberlain, himself essentially a man of commerce, may stand: "Our rule over native terri- tories can only be justified if we can show that it adds to the happiness and prosperity of the natives." But by whose judg- ment shall it be determined that exploitation of a lower race so far from injuring them effectively promotes their develop- ment and happiness? We cannot allow the arbitrament of private enterprise or of an Imperialist clique-both equally profiteers-but only such a tribunal as may be formed when truly self-governing democracies are welded into a permanent League:of Nations, only by such a league of really inter- national governance can such exploitation be undertaken and controlled with proper security and success. 81 "Capitalism develops a ruling class and consequently a ruled class, i.e., virtual slavery." The distinction between the State and the nation has been already drawn. By the State we mean the government, that is, the real government-the ruling class. The State then is not the nation (although the word is often used in that sense). The State is the organisation by which a self-con- tained society is controlled-the ruling power. The government of a country-and at present the country or nation forms the boundary lines of different self-contained societies-tends to become, and ultimately must become, a reflection of the economic relationship of its members. Where ownership is in common, rulership is in common; where a dominant economic class exists, that class rules. When the elan or gentile system was broken up by the intrusion of private property, by the introduction of the cash nexus and by interest, profit and rent, there was substituted for blood relationship the private ownership of land; property and residence in a particular area became the title to a share in the control of the society. With the gradual loss, first of land and then of machinery, by the many, and accumulation of property by the few, control by the few followed-and control of the many by the few is despotism. The many became what they are to-day, virtually slaves. Only under * "Principlee of Political Obligation," pp. 172-3-7. 183 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. true democratic* government does liberty exist. In a com- pletet democracy there is no room for slaves. By many the term 'wage-slave' is resented as though it were mnere exaggeration. But there is no exaggeration. In sober truth the worker of to-day has not the security of a slave. "Speaking broadly, the slave was secure; his job was continu- ous and his master was obliged to maintain him in employ- ment and in unemployment, in sickness and in health. This security, which was a security, without rights, based upon the denial of freedom, the wage-system swept away. For an actual security based upon bondage it substituted a no less actual insecurity based upon an incomplete personal free- dom,. Our problem to-day is that of re-establishing security without re-instituting virtual chattel-slavery.'" The economic enslavement of the proletariat of to-day is a generally recognised fact, and modern so-called political free- dom is a delusion unless it translates itself into economic free- dom, because power necessarily rests in the hands of a domin- ant economic class. Where land and machinery are owned by a class--that class rules, no matter what the outward form of government may be. Conversely, economic freedom is the certain forerunner of a real democratic control. With com- man ownership we have control from below, with class owner- ship control from above. The first is freedom, the second slavery. Hitherto the accent has been laid on poverty. Many people seem to think that a mere redistribution of material wealth is the sole sum and end of Socialism. An equal or even greater stress should be laid on liberty. A system that permits one man to say to another, "Your services are no longer required" --a systemn that refuses to guarantee any employ- ment, that forces one man with cringing servility to suppli- cate another for an opportunity to work, is a system of * The so-called political democracy of America embodies an autocratic plutocracy and economic slavery of the most pronounced kind. oScott Nearing says: "A new-rich ruling class, backed by immense resources; controlling vast investment surpluses; strangling opposition at home while it buys power abroad-this is America." And he adds: "There are more than twenty men now (1923) in the Federal prisons who were. convicted of agitation against the war. They have served five or six years at hard labor, but since they were members of the hated I.W.W. they are kept behind the bars after the law under which they were convicted has lapsed and been repealed. Five members of the I.W.W. were convicted in Sacra- mento, California, and must serve one to fourteen year sentences in the penitentiary. These men were arrested for appearing as witnesses in a trial of a member of their organisation." tThe Athenian "Commonwealth" was a pure democracy, but not a coin- plete democracy. Slaves were called 'organa,' machines-they were not thought of as human beings, and ninety thousand citizens (including women ind children) were able to dominate 365.000 slaves. "The glory that was Greece" was nourished by the blood of slaves; and yet in some respects the Athenian slave was better off than the "wage-slave" of to-day. tG. D. H. Cole, "Self-Government in Industry." 184 virtual slavery. And not only wage, but salary receivers too, are in tiat position; men who have perhaps specialised in a certain business whose special knowledge of an individual business is perhaps their chief asset are often thrown on the market at a week's or a month's notice by perhaps the mere whim of some other man. And they, slaves as they are to a system, yet call themselves free, because they have a vote! Why, servitude extends into the ranks of capitalists them- selves! As we have seen employers must do certain things. "If we command our wealth we shall be rich and free; if our wealth commands us we are poor indeed." Capitalists not only devour the poor, they devour each other, and often they must, if they are to rem'ain capitalists. To many the cry "Self-government in industry" seems a strange cry. "What! Are the men whom I employ to be able to dictate to me how I am to manage my business?" is the indignant exclamation of many employers. But is it your business? You are (or should be) a servant of society, without whose aid you would starve in the wilderness! The power the present system gives to the privileged holders of wealth is a veiled tyranny. Take the case of bankers: the privilege the community places in their hands of granting credit enables them to control the policy of industry-to whom credit shall be given, and thus, what shall be made, and what shall not be made. See how the, ranufacturer cringes to his banker. And if we ask who made bankers into lords and rulers over us, "our own stupidity" is the only answer. Of more recent developments of Capitalism, merely a word. The trust, cartel, monopoly, holding company, integration- call it what you will-grows apace: no longer merely in a horizontal direction, absorbing some particular article or stage of manufacture, but vertically, also, co-ordinating the whole manufacture from A to Z. Above and beyond the manufacturer is seen the capitalist and beyond the capitalist the super-capitalist-men like Roths- child, Morgan and Stinnes, who organise trusts and 'combines' and amass wealth by the simple process of over-capitalisation. Their enormous accumulations are entirely independent of the 'average rate of profit.' Such combinations extend beyond national limits: the great financier is an international; he has no country. His machinations result in the 'acquisition' of wealth far in excess of his personal requirements. His chief object is power-a power which spells the economic enslavement of nations. Such, then, in sum, is the case against Capitalism. 185 CAPITALISM. FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. XIV. Palliatives. The development of industry from one system to another takes place more or less slowly, but the rate of change is by no means uniform. A type at one time may seem to be abso- lutely fixed, at another to be unstable and subject to rapid- even violent-change. How far reforms in a system of in- dustry preserve it, and to what extent they constitute the path of change from one system to another is an open question. Reforms or palliatives may be advocated (or opposed) from entirely opposite points of view. Some may oppose re- forms because they do not wish the existing state of things to be altered at all-others may oppose them because they believe that a policy of laissez-faire will inevitably result sooner or later in a violent explosion and the destruction of Capitalism. We shall consider these different views later on: in the meantime it is proposed to review some of the proposals which seek to mend rather than to end the system of Capitalism. Of some of these space will only allow of brief mention: of one or two others we shall treat more fully. "Let in the light." Under this heading may be advocated reform in the matter of statistics. Only those who have sought to obtain information regarding private wealth, profits made by "private" enterprises and the various secret sinks down which "gain" is poured, have any idea of the abysmal depths of ignorance and Egyptian darkness that exist. Secrecy is jealously claimed and guarded, it is held to be the "private" business of exploiters--"let the public," who are exploited, "mind their own business." Our Government statisticians should be clothed with enormously enhanced powers. This re- form is the first of all reforms-the parent of all others. Fixing the Purchasing Power of Paper Money. In chapter VIII. the stupidity of making one commodity, viz., gold, the only final means of exchange was referred to. Every debt, every bank note, every bank credit, every cheque, is a promise to pay a specified quantity of current gold coin on demand, yet if everyone demands gold at once, it would be a physical impossibility to meet that claim. To promise the impossible -what is known, under existing circumstances, to be impos- 186 sible--is absurd or dishonest. Moreover, to make one com- modity (gold) the measure of value, when all or many com- modities-taken together-might be adopted as the measure, is foolish Money is a means of purchasing goods. We borrow or lend purchasing power. That the thing actually lent or borrowed should always remain the same-that the purchasing power borrowed should be returned-neither more nor less- is essentially just and reasonable. That desirable result can be achieved by the use of paper money whose 'general' pur- chasing power is fixed, but whose 'particular' purchasing power (for gold) is not fixed. The thing is perfectly simple, its advantages are enormous. Why the reform has not been adopted long ago is really inexplicable. Any commodity might have been adopted as the measure of value, there is nothing unique about gold. Let us suppose for example that instead of representing a certain weight of gold the �1 note represents a certain weight or measure of wheat. Then we have fixed the price of wheat in paper money; our inverted pyramid now rests on wheat in- stead of on gold. If, say, 4 bushels of wheat are represented by a �1 note, we have fixed the price of wheat (instead of gold) in paper money; we have, so to speak, glued the �1 note to 4 bushels of wheat and made wheat the measure of value. Then, if 4 bushels of wheat will buy 123 grains of bullion (a sovereign consists of 123 grains of bullion) so will a �1 note: if 5 bushels are needed, then a �1 note will only buy four- fifths of 123 grains, i.e., 98 2-5 grains of bullion. Thus in fixing the price of wheat in paper money we have at the same time unfixed the price of gold (bullion) in paper money. In other words by varying from time to time the weight of gold given for a �1 note we have fixed the price of wheat. Biut it is not proposed merely to fix the price of one com- modity as wheat; it is proposed to fix "the general purchasing power" of the �1 note. It is proposed to fix "the general price level" and make paper money "legal tender." It is im- portant then to understand what is meant by "the general price level." Suppose, for example, we expend a �1 note as follows: s. d. llb. of butter ........... .......2 0 11b. of tea ........................ 3 0 1 doz. eggs ...................... 1 6 6 loaves of bread ................... 3 0 1 pair socks ....................... 3 0 1 shirt ............................ 7 6 Total .....................�1 0 0 187 PALLIATIVES. FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. The general price level of all those articles taken together is �1. Now, suppose that six months later we buy exactly the same articles as follows: s. d. 11b. of butter......................2 6 11b. of tea .......................... 2 9 1 doz. eggs ........................ 2 0 6 loaves of bread ...................3 3 1 pair socks ...................... 3 3 1 shirt ........................... 7 3 Total ..................... �1 0 0 Individual prices have varied, but "the general price level" is the same; had the second bill come to 22/- the "general price level" would have moved up from 20/- to 22/-, a general 10 per cent. increase in prices. Instead, however, of taking only six articles it is proposed to take 100, or better still 300, and of each article a definite and fixed quantity in accordance with human needs. For example, a greater weight of bread and meat than of pepper and salt, more wool than silk, more iron than tin, more water than whisky. This fixed schedule, budget, or bill of goods would take the place of gold as our measure of value. We should always be able to buy the entire budget for a �1 note, or a �100 note, according to the quantities assumed when making up our schedule. No matter how the prices of articles varied in rela- tion to gold, they (taken all together) would not vary in rela- tion to paper money, and that is made possible by the simple expedient of varying, from time to time, the weight of gold given in exchange for a �1 note. We have, then, succeeded in turning our pyramid on to its natural basis. It no longer rests on its gold point, or wheat point, but is broad based on 300 commodities. Commodities have become our measure of value; paper money our means of exchange, and gold a mere intermediary between paper and commodities. It by no means follows that the price of each individual commodity in our schedule is fixed: they may vary plus and minus, but the 300 articles taken together will always be pur- chasable for a fixed sum in paper money. There is nothing- except ignorance-to prevent this reform being adopted. And the gold basis (so-called), i.e., bullion payable on demand, could be resumed at once. But index numbers, representing the cost of our budget in gold, would still be required in order to fix-say, every two months-the amount of bullion to be paid on demand for a �1 note. There is nothing mysterious or difficult in 188 PALLIATIVES. ascertaining what the index number for the moment may be, because it is merely the wholesale spot cash price of our weighted schedule of 300 commodities taken together; the total bill in fact,-prices being stated in gold or bullion. Before explaining the use of these index numbers we may pause to answer a very natural question, viz.: "Even when a starting point has been adopted and we agree that a �1 note shall represent a certain weight of gold, yet if paper is to be our only money and the 'general price level' in paper is fixed, how are we to ascertain the 'general price level' in gold, or the price of your weighted schedule of 300 commodities in gold?" The fact is, it is not strictly correct to say, or imply, that the general purchasing power of the �1 note can be absolutely fixed. It can in truth only be fixed in the same sense and in the same way that the speed of a steam engine is fixed by its governor. A slight variation in the speed of an engine is necessary to induce its governor to act, so that in fact a governor does not absolutely fix and make perfectly constant the speed of a steam engine; but a variation in speed of one or two per cent. will actuate a sensi- tive governor. As a result, the speed of the engine is continu- ally varying from 1 per cent. above to 1 per cent. below its normal speed-but within those limits the speed is fixed. In the case we are considering slight variations in the exchange value of paper money act in a precisely similar manner. Ordinary price changes still go on as at present, but their effect is not cumulative because periodically the index number is altered, and this alteration brings the �1 note back to its normal purchasing power-the general price level is restored. If the index number is determined at short periods, say every two months, our price governor is sensitive and the general price variation will probably not exceed 1 per cent.; if only once in six months our governor is sluggish and price variation may amount to 3 or 4 per cent. (It is proposed to found the general price level on wholesale prices as more stable and less liable to local variation than retail prices.) Let us suppose that it has been decided to adopt this great reform; the first step would be to resume the payment of gold on demand. There is nothing whatever to prevent this provided the present value of the �1 note is taken as the starting point, i.e., about 111 grains of gold bullion to the �1 note. Indeed, the immediate resumption of gold payment on demand would be a great and immediate advantage to the nation. At present, we are steadily increasing our load of indebtedness, not only by fresh loans, but by the increasing 189 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. weight of old loans. We borrowed (in some cases) when the �1 note was only worth 80 grains of gold bullion; it is now (1923) worth 110 grains, and may go to 123 grains. Thus the weight of our indebtedness has increased-in some cases-by 37 per cent., and it may increase to 52 per cent. It is to be hoped the camel's back will not break! But, although the first step is to resume gold payments, Governments must retain and exercise when necessary-as in case of war or financial panic-their power to suspend gold payments, for the simple reason that there are more notes than gold in existence. To keep a sufficient supply of gold to meet ordinary and customary demands, it is only necessary to offer a small premium on gold. A national bank (national in reality and not merely in name) might offer a slightly higher rate of interest for gold than for note deposits, or raise its rate of discount, or buy bullion outright. With paper 'legal tender' gold would only be required to pay adverse foreign trade balances. In fact the balance of foreign trade whether favorable or adverse would still be paid in gold, but only paper money would be used for internal trade. (2) The second step is to decide on, and fix, a schedule of goods and the quantity of each good in the 100 or 300 articles adopted. The greater the number of articles the more nearly will the schedule approach the "general" price level. (3) Now determine the first index number. Suppose the quantity or weight of each article is so arranged that their total cost in notes is exactly �100; then with the �1 note worth 110 grains of gold bullion the cost of the whole schedule of goods in bullion is 110 x 100, or 11,000 grains, and 11000 is our first index number. (4) Now suppose that two months have elapsed and a fresh index number has to be determined. All that is neces- sary is to ascertain the wholesale spot cash price (in notes) of our schedule of goods. Suppose prices have slightly varied and that it now needs 101 �1 notes to buy the whole schedule of goods. Then clearly the bullion price of the goods is now 101 x 110 grains or 11,110 grains of gold, and the price of bullion in notes must be legally altered from 110 grains of bullion per �1 note to 111.1 grains per �1 note. When that alteration is made 100 �1 notes will again buy the whole schedule of goods. Suppose that prices (in notes) now begin to fall, and that two months later 99 �1 notes will buy the goods. Then the bullion price of the goods is 99 x 111.1 grains of gold bullion or 109.989 grains. Then, when 109.989 grains of gold bullion are declared the legal exchange for a �1 note, the whole schedule can again be purchased for 100 �1 notes. 190 Thus, within narrow limits, the general purchasing power of the �1 note has been fixed in a simple practicable manner. The �1 note, it must be remembered, is legal tender and gold (bullion) would only be required for international trade. The advantages of the reform are obvious. Wages once fixed at a definite "standard" would remain fixed, nominal wages would become real wages; class friction would be reduced; an element of uncertainty would be removed from all contracts and an element of hardship as between debtor and creditor. The purchasing power borrowed would always be repaid, neither more nor less. The wear and tear of gold would be reduced and its exchange-value in notes would be publicly known. Gold would still remain the basis of international trade. Exter- nally we should be no worse off, rather better; internally the benefits are unquestionably great. [Author's Note: It is one of the contradictions of Capitalism that a gradual depreciation of the value of (legal tender) paper money has many advantages. Such a depreciation is tantamount to a capital levy: it is a real. reduction of indebtedness. The depreciation of the mark practically cancelled Germany's internal indebtedness and stimu- lated her trade. It unquestionably reduced the German worker's real wage, but he is employed. It put enormous profits into the hands of German capitalists; but these profits have been invested in plant and factories, "thus increasing Germany's productive power and efficiency -an enormous advantage in the future fight for markets. It has ripened Capitalism in Germany by greatly increasing the concentration of capital, and power, in trusts and cartels, so that the country is almost ready for guild socialism. The very peace treaty which assisted these developments has acted like a boomerang and injured those who launched it. If Germany breaks up (politically), France will, no doubt, be satisfied, but to other nations the 'treaty' only spells economic loss and unemployment. There is only one method by which Germany can pay without injuring her creditors' trade, that is, by free gifts of con- sumption goods to individuals (in the creditor nations) who have no purchasing power. To, in effect, supply other nations with cheap goods is to absorb some of their purchasing power, and to that extent destroy their home market.] [Author's Note: The "Quantity Theory of .1oney" has recently been revived. It is, we believe, essentially erroneous if by 'money' is meant gold or any medium of exchange convertible into gold on demand. Marx(speaks of the theory as "the old fib-that changes in the quan- tity of gold existing in a certain country, by increasing or reducing the quantity of the medium of circulation in that country, must raise or lower the prices of commodities in that country." The purchasing power of gold tends to follow the first law of value, that is, gold tends to exchange directly as the number of standard hours of labor it (and the other commodity) contains. The discovery of enormously rich gold mines would, by reducing the inherent-value (per unit) of gold at the same time reduce its exchange-value. Only insofar as gold is-for the moment-relatively scarce (or abundant) is the first law modified by the third law of value. If that ephemeral and temporary variation is all that is claimed by the theory, why single out 'money' (i.e., gold)? All commodities are equally affected PALLIATIVES. 191 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. by the third law. The chief effect of a national gold coin scarcity is to raise the rate of interest in that nation and not to raise the price of commodities. If, however, by 'money' is meant paper money which cannot be converted into gold and which has no other com- modity backing-as e.g., in Russia and Germany-then the value of the paper depends on its use (as, for example, the payment of taxation and the legal discharge of old debts) and on the popular estimate as to how much (if any) gold can, at some future time, be got for the paper. Should the reform we have just advocated show a continually falling value in the �1 note, as measured in gold, it would be chiefly because the labor per unit commodity purchased continually grew less. We say 'chiefly' because interest is often included in the 'cost of production,' and tends to increase costs--and consequently prices-in those industries which use 'bank credit at a high rate of interest It is the grain of truth in a false theory which makes it dangerous, by tending to preserve it. When social inherent-values are scientifically fixed the standard hour note will be the equitable means of discharging debt; at present the quantity of many commodities (taken together) is more equitable than the quantity of one, viz., gold.] Taxation.-One obvious method of redressing the grosser inequalities of wealth is to make all national charges fall upon the rich by means of taxation. That method does not attempt to remove the causes of inequality, but deals in a mechanical way with -effects. Such reforms are simple and superficial; some people are under the impression that a mechanical re- distribution of wealth is all that Socialists propose, and they triumphantly retort, "Even if you do divide wealth equally, in a year or two inequalities will again exist; unless you can alter human nature," etc., etc. Everyone has heard, to boredom, these good people talk. Taxation of the rich is a palliative, may be a due and necessary reform, but can be only of very limited effect. The Single Tax, as advocated by Henry George, goes rather deeper. It is an attempt to nationalise differential rent and, indeed, monopoly-rent, but there it ends; it makes no attempt to nationalise profits. George, in fact, seems to have been totally ignorant of Karl Marx' work, and indeed defended interest on the old physiocratic ground that it was 'natural,' advocating what is now called the 'fructification' theory. George and his followers have a single eye; what they see, they see clearly, but exploitation by profits they do not see at all. If we are to deal in a mechanical way with effects it would be far better to make the single tax a tax on incomes. Society at present exercises its right to fix wages, a minimum or basic wage, with-above it-a scale of wage based on that minimum. We propose to carry that scale to its logical conclusion and fix not only a minimum but a maximum wage. One way of doing this is by existing governmental machinery, viz., by an income tax fixed on a sliding scale. Merely as 192 PALLIATIVES..19 an example of the form such a tax might take, and not as a recommendation of the rate, we suggest a simple formula, increasing taxation at ,the rate of 1-450th per cent. per pound of income'for married persons, and doubling the tax upon the single. .The result is to fix a maximum yearly wage or income of �10,250 for the married and �5,125 for the single. There would rbe exemption from taxation of incomes of �500 and under for the married and �250 for the single. Thus for the married the 501st pound is assessed at 1-450th per cent., say 4d. With an;income of-�510, the �10 is assessed at 10-450th per cent., say. 4s. 5d. The exemption for the single is an income of �250 and the tax on the 251st pound is, say, id., and on the first ten. pounds. over. �250, i.e., on �260, is about 8s. 10d. Probably -it would not pay to collect any amount under 1/-. PROPOSED INCOME TAX. (MARRIED PERSONS.) Icm.Rate of Amount of NtIcm. Rmrs ncm. Tax. Deduction. NtIcm. Rmrs � � s. d. � s. d. 1% 4 2%37 3t,% f75 5 % 125 .7j% 262 10.% 450 12*.% 687 15 % 975 20 % 1,700 25.% 2,625 30 % 3,750 35 % 5,075 40, % 6,600 45 % 8,325 50 % 10,250 50 % & 100 % 30,250 50. % & 100% 90,250 13 10 10 0 0 10 0 10 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 500,0 745 6 987 10. 1,462 10 1,925 0 2,125 0 3,2.37.10 4,050 0 4, 812 10 5,525 0 6,8.00 0 7,875 0 8,750 0 9,425 0 9,900 0 10,175 0 10,250 0 10,250 0 10,250 0 Free of taxation. The rate of taxa- tion increases by 1-450th per cent. per � of income. Tax on amount over �20,250 100 per -cent Such. a schedule ;is, we contend, absolutely just. For some countries the. rate might not be sufficient.. The rate, however, is of less moment ; the, method is all-important. Such a plan, and it contains no element of. Utopia, would, if adopted,. go far to solve the problem how to purchase existing 'capital.' M 1~00. 750, 1,000 1,500- 2,000, 2,500 3,500 4,5.00 5,500 .6, 500 8,500 10,500 12,500: .14,500 16,500. 18,500 20,500 40,500. 100,500 .193 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. In proposing a maximum wage we establish a principle of equity, that as there is a bottom level of comfort below which no man should be required to live, so there is an upper level of comfort (or luxury) which no man should exceed. As a means of acquiring communal ownership it is not the only method. A thoroughly feasible plan is to utilise death duties, and this we may present in the words of J. A. Hobson: If the State could' intercept, hold, and maintain a fifth of the larger properties which pass at death, treating it as public capital, it would at no distant time be the owner of a substantial share of the land and the industrial capital of the nation, without any of the incon- venience, expense and irritation ensuant upon more violent methods of expropriation with or without compensation. . . . If the State, receiving payment in land or in shares, kept possession of these in- struments, it would soon find itself a partner, in many of the large businesses of the country. . .. By changing the nature of the invest- ments which come into public ownership by death duties thus paid in kind, it would be feasible for the State to select those industries which by peaceful penetration it would 'socialise.'* These taxation proposals assume a Labor Government. The Douglas Scheme-" Producers' Banks."-The Douglas Scheme is comparatively new and has hardly been sufficiently criticised. It is founded on the Douglas Theory. Like many other theories the theory contains, we believe, an element of truth and an element of untruth. We propose to deal with the Theory first, then with the Scheme. Major Douglas suggests that we should reduce the price of home consumption goods in the ratio that the production of consumption goods bears to total goods-i.e., to consumption plus capital goods-to something like 25 per cent. of cost according to his estimate. A study of his book leads to the conclusion that what he really means is, not that consumption goods should be sold below their real cost, but that they should be sold at their real cost. On that point we are in full accord with Major Douglas. But we differ with him on the question of what constitutes the 'real cost' of consumption goods. Major Douglas tells us that when we buy consumption goods we are paying for, but do not receive, capital goods. That statement is, we believe, only partly true. Some capital goods we receive, some we do not. Some capital goods are converted by the process of manufacture into final goods (final is another name for con- sumption). Some capital is "permanent" (only partly con- sumed in one operation); other capital goods are entirely consumed in one operation. Of these latter are raw materials during the last operation which converts them into final goods, also coal, lubricating oil, etc. * "The Industrial System," p. 243. 194 PALLIATIVES. The real cost of a final good is the cost in 'time-energy' units (as Major Douglas calls labor) of all the constituents of the good. These include the cost of raw materials, coal, etc., consumed in production, depreciation (the cost of that portion of the machinery worn out), and wages. Major Douglas admits depreciation of machinery (say at 10 per cent. per annum) as a part of real cost. On what ground of reason does he refuse to admit that the depreciation of coal (100 per cent. per operation) is also a part of real cost? The production of final goods-all production, in fact- is a continuous operation; a flow, dynamic, not static, as Douglas correctly insists. Let us examine what takes place during a given period of flow resulting in the production of final goods. Assume a self-contained nation and regard its working population as all employed in one immense factory. From a former period of flow (higher up the river) raw materials (grown, mined or partly manufactured) have been bequeathed. So have the factory and the plant. During the period we are considering all operations from A to Z proceed. Goods are finally made into consumption goods, and the raw materials they contain are replaced by the production of more raw material. (1) If the production of raw material during the period exactly balances the raw material converted into final goods, and if the wear of plant is made good-neither more nor less- then the "real cost" of the final goods made consists of the wages paid, and nothing else. But (2) if more raw material is, during the period, pro- dueed than is turned into final goods, or additional plant or machinery is made (after providing for the depreciation of the existing plant), then the "real cost" and correct price F of a unit of final goods, say A = - of its present price, when F represents the total final goods produced, and K represents the total additional capital goods produced (during the period). (In this case (2) producing power has appre- ciated and-as Major Douglas suggests-additional credit may be issued to absorb its appreciation.) If, however, (3) the capital goods used have not been entirely replaced, the real cost and correct price of a unit F of final goods (A) =----- of its present price. F-K K now representing the depreciation of capital goods. 195 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. F In case (1) the real cost and correct price of A = of its F present price i.e., its present price-at which goods are com- monly sold-is its real cost and correct price. But in case (2) the fraction - is not likely at any time to reach such a F+K ridiculously small dimension as one-quarter, as is suggested by Major Douglas. The mistake of including all capital goods instead of additional capital goods in the fraction is, we be- lieve, now evident. So much for the Douglas Theory. We agree that price ought to be founded on real cost. But since that is not possible under Capitalism, because, if owners of factories cannot make a profit, or make a loss, they will not, or cannot, allow their factories to be used, we agree that a new scheme of distributing wealth is required. We agree that the existing method of fixing prices is archaic. We agree that the crux of the present economic problem is how to fix prices on real cost. But we disagree with Major Douglas when he allows private rent, profit, and interest to be included in the price of an article. Public differential rent and profit would virtually reduce all prices. We disagree with him when he fails to take stock of the goods on hand (both capital and final) at the beginning and end of the period of production- When he fails to add (or subtract) the stock at the end of the period to (or from) the stock at the beginning of the period. That is his vital and fundamental mistake. In his Credit Power and Democracy Major Douglas pro- pounds a scheme of joint ownership (of the coal-mining industry) by the present owners of coal mines, the workers in the mines, and the nation. The existing right of ownership, or rather the capital value at present held by private owners, is not to be disturbed, but capital for future extensions is to be contributed by the three parties named, i.e., present owners, mine workers, and the general community. But private owners are to receive, instead of their present divi- dends, a fixed and guaranteed rate of interest-6 per cent. is suggested-on the capital value of their mines. All wages and dividends are to be distributed by a Producers' Bank, whose directors are to manage the whole guild or industry. The price of coal is to be determined in three ways:-(1) to consumers-below cost; (2) to manufacturers-at cost; (3) to outsiders-at whatever can be obtained in the world's market. 196 PALLIATIVES. We have already explained what Major Douglas means by below cost and what we believe to be the error in his theory. We must refer the reader to Major Douglas' book for a fuller explanation of his Scheme, which we now propose to .criticise. The Scheme is an imperfect form of guild socialism-a syndicate in which both capitalists and workers join, but on unequal terms. That fact would probably not be admitted by Major Douglas, since he makes the astonishing statement (p. 80)'that the Guild Socialist movement has entirely omitted to allow for the unearned increment of association. It is a wise father that knows his own child. (Indeed there is an oracular obscurity in the enunciation of the whole Scheme that argues some confusion in its author's mind; but at least the fact of surplus value is stumbled over,-" wages and salaries do not represent the value produced"-if not quite recognised-more than half a century after Marx! And Major Douglas has the temerity to speak loftily of the "fallacy of Marxianism"!) The Scheme is admittedly a compromise-a half-hearted reform which looks only to the partial prevention of future wrongs. The capitalist is to be allowed to retain the exploiting power of his present capital-6 per cent. is suggested-and even to participate in future capital issues. We are told that it is "incredible that any of the ordinary Socialist proposals can be realised without a 'revolution' that would defeat their avowed object." That is as may be, but it is quite true that the establishment of a Producers' Bank would meet with less opposition than clean-cut Guild Socialism. It is at least some- thing to know that our present burdens will not, in future, be greatly increased, and, since compromise is the soul of practical economics, and half a loaf is better than no bread, it might be wiser to strive for a possible half-loaf than for an impossible loaf. Major Douglas sees in the financial power (banks chiefly) the arch villain of the play, and if "interest" constitutes the principal method of exploitation (which we question), there can be no doubt that the Major's sight is clear. But what has become of rent, and the balance of profit which is not interest? It is sufficient, according to Major Douglas, to guilderise credit and thus set free the wheels of industry. We do not forget that the control of credit enables the finan- cial power to control the policy of industry; or that the wheels of industry may be turned by slaves. The socialisation of credit is a tremendous reform-"a consummation devoutly to be wished"-but the guilderisation of 50, or even 75, per cent. 197 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. of the interest on future capital is not exactly the gate to an industrial paradise. Major Douglas spurns the ground of concrete reality and wings his way through cloudy symbols. Producing power is real credit; add selling power, and we get financial credit. By financial credit is meant the power, obtained from private banks, to liquefy solid securities-to turn securities into purchasing power. This power, as we have seen, really resides in the com- munity, and a national bank with a currency based on goods, in the manner just explained, would give to the community as well as to the "manufacturer all the advantages claimed by Major Douglas for his Producers' Bank, provided steps are also taken to transfer the ownership of concrete capital (machinery and land, etc.) to the community and not to the producer. Under the Douglas Scheme the board of directors of each Producers' Bank would fix prices for their own industry on cost in human effort. But who would fix them as between the different Producers' Banks when various quantities of commodity resulted from similar efforts? Who is to prevent one industry from exploiting another by holding or seizing natural advantages? Who is to equalise "wages" as between guilds? Society as a whole should own its land and capital. Society as a whole must develop a unified economic control of policy, not--a the Douglas Scheme would give us-twenty or more independent controls. That would be merely to replace 'class war' and company competition by a 'group war' and transfer the fight for differential rent and profit (natural and social advantages) to competing Producers' Banks. Group war, like every other war, can only be avoided by a higher integration, a controlling power resting on all the groups involved, and such a power is absent in the Douglas Scheme. The difficulties of crossing the stream-the time of 'revolution,' in fact-must be admitted, and are common to Producers' Banks and Guild Socialism alike. The Major's belief that the Trust and not the Trades Union will prove to be the parent of the Guild is not the least interesting of his views. Perhaps they will become joint parents. But how is the Producers' Bank to be generated? And can it be born piecemeal? Suppose that somehow (by political means?) a Miners' Bank or Guild has been estab- lished and the price of coal to the home consumer reduced by 30 per cent., as seems possible. The wages of other workers, outside a Guild, would still be fixed by the cost of living, and since the cost of living is reduced, wages would be 198 PALLIATIVES. reduced. Perhaps a legal minimum wage might meet this difficulty. Producers' Banks, like Single Tax, is a one-eyed scheme. The latter only sees exploitation in private rent, the former only sees it in private profit (prices). Each is a great reform, but neither of them is a complete solution of the economic problem. This chapter-already too long-might be indefinitely ex- tended. A few more "reforms" may, however, just be mentioned. Motherhood Endowment.-Given an income tax on the lines already proposed--the economic independence of woman might-to some extent-be assured, by making a payment to her of 10s. per week for every child under 14 years of age. Old Age Pensions.-The economic independence of old people might also be assured by a payment to every person over sixty or sixty-five of �100 per annum. One can imagine the horror of many people and their exclamation, "Where is the money to come from?" These are not wild suggestions of an impossible millennium, but sober, practical proposals that only need a firm-if necessary, stern- Labor Party to bring them into being. Nationalisation of Banking.-This great reform would provide funds for old age pensions, and is almost a necessary part of the plan of fixing the purchasing power of money. 199 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. XV. Evolution or Revolution. Hitherto we have been engaged in destructive rather than constructive criticism; we have pointed out that "the times are out of joint," that the dislocation between production and distribution is the cause of social discord. But having diagnosed the case we mnust, to be of any service, prescribe a remedy. Already we have foreshadowed our own opinion that the remedy is to be found in Guild Socialism. Before, however, describing the remedy in detail we propose to define the meaning of Guild Socialism and outline the means of its attainment. State Socialism differs in many respects from Guild Socialism; it differs as the nationalisation of industry differs from' its socialisation. Many have actually supposed the terms synonymous. There could be no greater mistake. By the 'nationalisation' of industry is meant not only joint and common ownership by a nation of the agencies of production, distribution and exchange, but their management by a State or municipal bureaucracy,--a condition of affairs in which everyone is a 'civil servant' in the sense in which that term is now understood. Such a nightmare of a system has been, rightly, named the 'servile State.' Those who are not at present wage or salary receivers may well shudder at the apparition: to the proletariat, however, it would be some relief from present servility: at least their 'jobs' would be secure. Political liberty, as embodied in the right to vote for parliamentary representatives, still leaves the individual work- man in economic bondage. Trade unionism merely loosens the bonds. State enterprises afford him no relief, even when well managed, since any profit they make merely reduces the burden of taxation on the rich. Even an income restriction on the rich-a maximum wage-by means of sliding-scale taxation (a mechanical and not an organic reform) would merely direct wealth into the coffers of the State. The problem of how to get it into the pocket of the worker would still remain to be solved, and even if it were solved the problem of self-government in industry would still exist. A political body is quite incapable of fixing, in detail, just working conditions: that could not be done even by a Labor Govern- 200 EVOLUTION OR REVOLUTION. ment. Self-government in industry, as the term is understood by working men, means the selection by the workers them- selves of those in direct authority over them. It does not mean that each man may do exactly what he pleases,-nor does it mean a control of the policy of industry (now in the hands of capitalists, chiefly bankers). By 'policy' we mean the determination when and what commodities shall be made and which manufacturer or guild shall make them. The problem of industry, then, has two aspects-first: the method of distributing wealth; second, the method of its social production. Nationalisation solves the first, socialisation solves both. The first involves the problem of differential rent and profit. Of any given utility, the quantity produced is not directly proportional to the number of individual standard hours of labor spent in its production, but-the number of individual standard hours being constant-it depends on the amount of assistance the worker receives from natural and social forces. In other words, the quantity of a utility produced varies directly with the quantity of social standard hours expended in its production. It is just this difference between individual and social values that constitutes the chief problem in distribution. Let us again state it, in its simplest form* preferably in terms of differential fertility. One field will produce ten, another fifteen bushels of wheat, with precisely the same labor-the difference in return is due solely to "natural fertility." Let either parcel contain the same number of "individual standard hours," as 5; then either producer receiving 5 "S.H. notes" has the just price of his labor, for social justice requires that he be paid the equivalent, not of the actual produce which may result from his labor, but of the labor itself-neither more nor less. The total produce is 25 bushels- the total cost 10 S.H.-the average cost per bushel * S.H. ( S.H. in the one case, A S.H. in the other). This then (% S.H. per bushel) is the social value of the wheat and the just price to the consumer. If the wheat is sold at this figure it means that as ':"the consumer'" is in reality the community as a whole, the entire difference due to "natural fertility" is returnable and returned to the community in the form of a net price which retrieves exactly the true cost of production. And social justice is satisfied. But as the community has rights against and claims upon its individual members-for services rendered-to meet these the price to the consumer may be raised to, e.g., the true cost * Such factors as rent, margin of cultivation, etc., emerging under the existing system, are obviously not here present. 201 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. of production of the more costly parcel of wheat, i.e., to J S.H. per bushel. The total produce, 25 bushels, sold at i S.H. per bushel, leaves, after payment as before of 5 S.H. to either cultivator, a balance of 2. S.H. If this balance is retained by the community, and expended solely on communal services (in which all individuals, including the cultivators, participate equally) social justice is again satisfied, the pro- ducer has received, and the consumer paid, a fair price. (Thus the problem requires for its solution a social or- ganisation which shall intercept the entire difference due to "natural fertility" and use it for the benefit of the community as a whole. Private ownership in the instruments of produc- tion is abolished, the community is its own landlord and its own capitalist and the competition of the market replaced by an intelligent control of prices. In a word, the solution is communal ownership and the nationalisation of what under the present system is differential-rent and profit: because what holds for differential rent in primary production holds equally for differential profit in manufacture. The second aspect of the problem, self-government in in- dustry, cannot be so briefly dismissed. Here we have to do with two questions, which in themselves distinct cannot in practice be kept wholly separate, the means by which a change is to be effected and the machinery by which the new system is to work smoothly and efficiently. It is clear that there must be a real-no mere sham-democracy not only of civil govern- ment, but also of industry; that there must be not political freedom only, but economic freedom also. But while there is general agreement as to the goal to be attained opinions differ widely as to the means. And of these notice is here due. There are those, for example, who announce that "the world is moving spontaneously towards economic freedom," and by implification require of us a policy of masterly inactivity. This, however, is merely to restore the old doctrine of laissez- faire, a doctrine which, if comforting to those who are well off, has long been discredited and is, in industry at any rate, wholly obsolete. It was given, by the "Manchester School," far more than a fair trial, with results disastrous and nearly fatal. Others again are strong for "meliorism," by which some- what barbarous term we are to understand a gradual lightening of the chains of wage-slavery as circumstances and time shall allow. And there are many who look hopefully to this policy of opportunism; in contrast with whom are advocates of a directly contrary method, which by aggravating the evils would increase the disease until the patient should in despera- tion "make an effort" and throw off the incubus once for all. 202 EVOLUTION OR REVOLUTION. A more serious attempt to solve the problem is by the method known as State Socialism. That method, it must be admitted, is a partial solution. It solves the first aspect of the question, the problem of the distribution of wealth, if by State Socialism is meant the absolute ownership by the com- munity in common of the instruments of production; but it leaves the problem of freedom or self-government in industry untouched. Unfortunately there exists to-day a spurious State and Municipal Socialism purporting to nationalise or municipalise certain industries or services, which so-called 'Socialism' constitutes in reality the last refuge of capitalists. State railways, State industries of various kinds, municipal services, gas, water, trams, electricity-all are examples of this spurious Socialism, which is in reality State Capitalism. It may be well to describe more fully a typical case such as the 'State' railways of Australia. These railways are nationalised but they are not socialised, and they certainly are not owned by the people of Australia, who, in fact, only hold the equity of redemption. They belong-except nominally -to the British capitalists who advanced the money which enabled the railways to be built. The "Government" of Australia merely acts as managing agent for these capitalists, and guarantees and collects the interest-payment agreed on. In this game the capitalists are "on a good wicket" and score heavily. It would in fact save them a lot of trouble if that kind of "nationalisation" became universal. To the burden of interest are added bureaucratic inefficiency and lack of business experience. Political intrigue is rampant, and rail- ways which cannot "pay " are built to enhance the value of land held by political supporters. While in theory the com- munity gains the difference between the average rate of profit and the rate of interest at which the money for construction was borrowed, in practice this saving is more than absorbed in the betterment of employees. For this advantage--and this advantage only-the State railways of Australia may claim that, viz., they are of greater benefit to the community than private railways. Unfortunately, this spurious form of Socialism-more properly State Capitalism-has condemned all Socialism in the eyes of a great number of people who mis- takenly imagine that it is the Socialism they are asked to support. Nationalisation in the form of State Capitalism has for years paraded as Socialism. In Australia the State railways (already mentioned), the Commonwealth Bank, and the Com- monwealth Shipping Line are all State industries. The two latter concerns made at one time enormous profits. Were 203 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. the workers benefited thereby? Certainly not-these profits merely reduce the taxation imposed on local capitalists. Only in so far as the State gives more constant employment, better wages and better conditions are some workers benefited, other- wise the benefits pass into, or remain in, the pockets of capitalists. But a real State Socialism, one in which it is not necessary to pay interest or rent to private persons, does not solve the problem of freedom; it only leads to the Servile State, it does not give self-government in industry. This fact is beginning to be recognised. Mr. Plumb, for instance, proposed that American railways should be adminis- tered by fifteen directors, five to represent the public, five the officials and five the employees. The proposal is interest- ing because it recognises that employees should have a voice in control, and also the fact that the "State" is not fitted to manage industry. The proposal, however, should admirably suit the capitalist because it guarantees his "interest." Self-control* in industry or industrial autonomy is an idea which, though familiar to a certain class of thinkers, has hardly yet impressed itself upon the consciousness of the general public. Exactly what it means will be made clear in the next chapter. IThe idea of self-control in industry is also brought out in the evidence of a working miner, given in Australia, before a Commission of Inquiry into working conditions in coal mines: "He did not think the mining industry could be carried on satisfactorily while the mines were in private hands. The miners objected to nationalisation in the ordinary acceptation of the term, as they would still be working for 'wages.' They objected to being corrupted by officialdom and believed that State Capitalism meant the Servile State. He thought it essen- tial to the success of the industry that the workers should have a voice in the control." Nationalisation-which is really State Capitalism-fails because (a) it does not completely solve the economic problem but merely saves to the community the difference between profit and interest, or, in the alternative, improves the standard of comfort of its employees, and (b) because it leaves entirely untouched the matter of economic freedom. Even State Socialism fails to provide a satisfactory solution, because although we grant that it can secure communal ownership of all the instruments of production and so sweep away most of *Control of industry may denote three entirely different things: 1. Technical control. 2. Control of policy. 3. Control of conditions of service. A general has complete technical control of his army, he decides how they shall fight; but an Emperor, or Cabinet, or ruling class decides on the policy of war, when to fight and whom to fight. Technical control should be in the hands of experts: control of policy in the hands of the nation as a whole: control of conditions (to some extent) in the hands of the workers. 204 EVOLUTION OR REVOLUTION. the evils of private ownership, it also leaves untouched the question of economic freedom. It is an obvious-and just- criticism that many reforms lead directly not to Guild-but to State-Socialism. Unless, however, the full scheme of Guild Socialism is to be established suddenly as by a coup-de- main,-and that would involve some more or less violent measure of expropriation,-we may well be content with (at first) a gradual socialisation of industries even though this brings in its train a temporary and passing stage of State Socialism. We cannot rest in State Socialism, but we may accept it as an intermediary, perhaps inevitable, to the per- fected form of social organism. It is at least half way to the goal of our ambition-it assures social ownership. If then the various methods discussed are all in greater or less degree insufficient wherein does the true solution lie? It lies, we believe, in restoring one of the forms of industrial organisation which, as we saw in our historical retrospect, had evolved naturally in the development of industry, but in "restoring" it in a perfected type modified and adapted to suit modern conditions:- in a word, it lies in Guild Socialism. For under Guild Socialism not only would the whole of the instruments of production, distribution and exchange be owned by the community and by, the community as a whole, but full provision is made also for assuring self-government in in- dustry, or (as we have sometimes called it) economic freedom. These terms deserve a word of explanation. We have defined freedom-in a social State-as the com- plete and harmonious adjustment of individuals to each other and to society, for their mutual benefit. Adjustment neces- sarily implies limitation. Already and in every conceivable state individual action is limited by material conditions. It is also limited by social conditions-social conditions which, in any case, have been imposed by a class. Modern industry is essentially social-only by men working together can the best result be achieved. Limitation, both material and social, must remain, but freedom consists in each individual having an equal voice in fixing these limits. In other words, industry, to be free, must be made democratic. If we have, for the moment, sufficiently defined the end in view we come to the important question: How in general terms is that end to be attained? By Evolution or by Revolution? And what is the exact meaning of those words? Marx, in a fine passage which reads like the "inspired utterance" of one of the Hebrew prophets, sums up the situa- tion and foretells the result:- As soon as the laborers are turned into proletarians, their means 205 206 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. of production into capital, as soon as the capitalist mode or production stands on its own feet, then the further socialisation of labor and the further transformation of the land and other means of production into socially exploited and, therefore, common means of production, as well as the further expropriation of private proprietors, takes a new form. That which is now to be expropriated is no longer the laborer working for himself, but the capitalist exploiting many laborers. This expro- priation is accomplished by the action of the immanent laws of capitalistic production itself, by the centralisation of capital. One capitalist always kills many. Hand in hand with this centralisation or this expropriation of many capitalists by few, develop on an ever- extending scale the co-operative form of the labor process, the con- scious technical application of science, the methodical cultivation of the soil, the transformation of the instruments of labor into instru- ments of labor only usable in common, the economising of all means of production by their use as the means of production of combined, socialised labor, the entanglement of all peoples in the net of the world market, and with t'his the international character of the capital- istic regime. Along with the constantly diminishing number of the magnates of capital, who usurp and monopolise all the advantages of this process of transformation, grows the mass of misery, oppression, slavery, degradation, exploitation; but always increasing in numbers, and disciplined, united, organised by the very mechanism of the process of capitalistic production itself. The monopoly of capital becomes a fetter upon the mode of production, which has sprung up and flourished along with and under it. Centralisation of the means of production and socialisation of labor at last reach a point where they become incompatible with the capitalist integument. This 'integument is burst asunder. The knell of capitalist property sounds. The expropriators are expropriated. All through the ages the spirit of man has been seeking the light of self-consciousness. Less and less he remains a mere automaton-a mere creature of reflex action, of superstition, of custom, of imposed law. More and more he begins to under- stand, to reason, to know, to will. As a new factor in industrial evolution, conscious mutual aid-combined action directed to a clearly defined end-begins to take the place of the unconscious social adjustment of the past-an adjustment due to the pressure of economic conditions on individuals and classes-a pressure whose cause was unrecognised. The man and the society both felt that some- thing was wrong, but did not know what that something was. That is still the position of many people-they recognise that something is awry, yet they are beginning to know what that something is, but when they do know we may expect conscious action. To a certain extent a beneficent social adjustment may take place as Adam Smith supposed; some approach to a working model may be arrived at by practice, but it is only when the principles are understood on which the model works that a perfect model can be made. Here then we have the means by which the transformation of Capitalism into Guild Socialism is to be effected, viz., the EVOLUTION OR REVOLUTION. workers themselves, "always increasing in numbers, dis- ciplined, united, organised"; in other words, it is to trade unionism that we must look for the emancipation of the world from Capitalism. "Who would be free themselves first must strike the blow." But only when the time is ripe, only when the few capitalists have killed the many, when huge monopolies have concentrated and organised industry. And in the meantime "reform," by all means reform, if we wish to escape a destruc- tive revolution. Reform makes for intelligence and intelli- gence for a constructive revolution-repression enslaves and results in a destructive revolution. Evolution and revolution are terms which may denote merely different degrees and rates of change. When we speak of the evolution of industry we mean a slow and gradual change: by revolution-the industrial revolution-we mean a rapid and what we call fundamental change, one of De Vries' periods of mutability. That is true of constructive revolution. But it must be confessed that revolution has another meaning- a change may simply be destructive. Instead of a new in- tegration, we then have disintegration. Some people imagine that a social revolution must inevitably result in Socialism: that is not our view. Revolutions may be either destructive or constructive. Socialism must be worked for, thought for, prayed for; if necessary, fought for. The rule is clear: a majority may justly use force to prevent the execution by force, of the will of a minority. The call is to every man to be up and doing, and the first thing to be done is to spread the light of knowledge. Nature has her constructive revolutions. Not only may a species have its periods of rapid change and mutability: they occur also in the development of the individual. Not only does the embryo rehearse the story of evolution, but 'revolutions' persist in later life. The child is born, the child becomes a man or woman, the woman ceases to be capable of bearing children. The chick breaks its shell; the chrysalis becomes a butterfly; the tadpole becomes a frog. Constructive revolu- tion is but a phase of evolution. Seen in the light of evolution, and indeed in the light of history-what do we find and what may we expect? An in- creasing complexity by a growing specialisation of function among the parts of the whole. Each national society has at present a political organ-parliament-which is every day developing more definitely an executive-an administration of law as distinct from a making of laws. 207 ,208 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. But as yet society as a whole has no economic* organ. We may-we must-expect the development by society of an economic organ, and in Trade Unions we see the embryo of such an organ. By analogy we may say that at present the directing brain of society consists of only one lobe-the political lobe; the economic lobe is rudimentary or entirely missing. Yet if the conduct of society in the economic as well as the political sphere is to be intelligently directed such a lobe must be developed. In politics we consciously direct our course, and it is to consciousness as a force in economic evolution we must look for future economic advance. And when the economic lobe has been developed the two lobes must be co-ordinated. The second lobe, i.e., the second House, will be a Trades Con- gress, and in cases of disagreement or difficulty the two Houses must sit together. The political "State" represents the whole of the consumers, and may still be elected on a geogra- phical basis; the economic congress would represent the pro- ducers and be elected on a trade or guild basis. Indeed in some recent constitutions, the Irish Free State and the constitution of Germany, for example, Economic Coun- cils. and Political Councils are associated. Article 165 of the German Constitution (A.D. 1919) reads as follows:- . The District Workman's Councils and the Federal Workman's Council meet, for the accomplishment of all economic tasks, and for co-operation in the execution of social laws, with the representatives of the employers and other sections of the nation concerned, to form District Economic Councils and a Federal Economic Council. These Economic Councils shall be so constituted to represent all important groups of occupations, in proportion to their economic and social im- portance. Drafts of laws of fundamental importance, involving social and economic policy shall be submitted by the Federal Government to the Federal Economic Council for approval before they are actually brought forward. The latter has the right of proposing such bills itself. Should the Federal Government not approve of them, it must nevertheless in- troduce them into the Reichstag, with a statement of its own views The Federal Economic Council may present its proposals to the Reich- stag by one of its own members . . .-From the official English translation. The black type is mine. Here we have, at least, the be- ginning of an economic congress, with a right of consultation and a power of initiative. *The relations of men to each other in society are not merely economic they are political also. Laws of marriage, of conduct, of personal obligation. "Thou shalt not kill"; "Thou shalt not commit adultery": "Thou shalt not exploit" are not economic, or purely economic, commands. Their sanction is the higher life of society. FREEDOM. XVI. Freedom. It has been necessary, even at the cost of some repetition, to bring together in a comprehensive survey the defects of the capitalistic system and the evils an injustice to which it gives rise. For we must have before our eyes a full and fresh realisa- tion of the errors of the past if we are to propound in exchange a system of dealing with the production and distribution of wealth which shall replace inefficiency by efficiency, injustice by justice, discord by harmony, tyranny by freedom. The social problem is far from simple, but its solution will be rendered the more easy if it is borne in mind that it has two parts or aspects, the one economic, the other political. And let it be frankly admitted at the outset that it may not be possible to follow out the solution to be offered into so detailed a treatment as has marked our criticism of the existing sy; tem; for, as is obvious, no plan of what we aim to do to-morrow can by the nature of the case be as meticulously precise as the history of what we have done to-day. But it will be possible to present the solution with precision and detail sufficient to convince the reader that a problem of prac- tical politics has been dealt with in a practical manner. A guild is an association of workers, a kind of glorified trades union. It is, at present, almost impossible for many people to overcome their active or latent prejudice to the name of union, but the guild of the future, involving everyone in its ranks, will be a very different thing from existing trade unions. Let such people, if they are professional men or em- ployers, think of their own associations; if financial men, of their directors' meetings and conferences. Doctors, lawyers, engineers, civil servants, retail traders all have their unions, call them what they will. Several detailed plans have been set forth to embody the principles of guild Socialism: one has been worked out by N 209 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. Mr. G. D. H. Cole, but such schemes are purely tentative and at present chiefly useful as a reply to impatient critics who exclaim, "Exactly what do you propose?" and who are, in most cases, found to be unwilling, to listen to, much less ex- amine, detailed proposals. Experience would immediately modify them, even if they could be put in force; but in any case we have not a tabula rasa, and, as we know, guild Social- ism, if it ever comes into being, must grow out of existing conditions. It seems better, then, to confine ourselves to the principles of guild Socialism. As a higher form of industry than Capitalism we may expect guild Socialism to exhibit a still more pronounced specialisation and, more especially, a stronger co-ordination, because it is in integration that Capitalism is conspicuously defective. Administration will be distinct from the Executive. Committees will determine the policy of industry. The execu- tion of definite duties will be in the hands of individuals. The sphere both of committees and individuals will be specified and clearly defined." Technical investigation will be in the hands of experts: team work will, however, be possible, but will be co-ordinated-as all team work must be. Everyone will have a voice in determining the conditions and surround- ings of his work, and be able to choose the kind of work he prefers. The guild may be compared to a democratic army in which the privates select the sergeants, the sergeants the captains, the captains the majors, the majors the colonels, the colonels the generals, and the generals the commander-in-chief. Once the executive has been selected orders flow in the opposite direction. So too on the administrative side which determines industrial policy. Shop committees will be elected by those who work in the shop: works committees by those engaged in the works: district committees by workers of the district; national committees or economic councils by all the workers in the nation. The functions of such bodies will be limited to action in their respective spheres, subject always to the next higher authority. Thus would a real control by the rank and file replace the existing autocracy in industry, and lead to a real, instead of a sham, democracy, not only in the policy of industry, but in social policy also. As the guild is the unit of this democracy of industry it may be well to show how the entire working population may be grouped in harmony with it. S. G. Hobson, in his "National Guilds," when dealing with the number and kind of guilds likely to be formed, suggests some twenty-two and says, speaking of Britain: 210 FREEDOM. 211 According to the 1901 census, the number of occupied persons was 18,261,146, out of a total population of 41,458,721.... These figures give us a fairly clear conspectus of the problem of organisation that the guilds must.solve. Number Class occupiers 1. Civil Service-General and Municipal..............253,865 2. Defence (excluding those abroad)...............203,998 3.Professional and Subordinate Services...........733,582 4. Domestic Services .............................2,199,517 5. Commercial Occupation............. ....... 712,465 6. Transit.......................................1,497,629 7. Agriculture .......................... ....2,262,454 8. Fishing................................. 61,925 9. Mines and Quarries (in and about)................943,880 10. Metals, Machines, Implements, etc...............1,475,410 11. Precious Metals, Jewels, Watches, Games.........168,344 12. Building and Construction......................1,335,820 13. Wood, Furniture, Fittings and Decorations. 307,632 14. Brick, Cement, Pottery and Glass................189,856 15. Chemicals ............................. 149,675 16. Leathers, Skins, Hair, Feathers-..................117,866 17. Paper, Printing, Books, Stationery................334,261 18. Textiles.......................................1,462,001 19. Clothing......................................1,395,795 20. Food, Tobacco, Drink and Lodging...............1,301,076 21. Gas, Water and Sanitary..........78,686 22. General and Undefined ............... l,075,414 These twenty-two groups, organised into guilds, would furnish at any rate a provisional arrangement of the entire industrial activity of the country. It.will be noticed that Mr. S. G. Hobson boldly includes agriculture amongstthe guilds. Can, then, the existing breach between agriculture and manufacture be healed? Until it is healed the integration of society remains incomplete, as it has remained since the days of the ancient gens. (Even in the early manor -integration was not complete.) In England and other- advanced countries we believe it can be healed : in other countries, Russia for example, the division is too wide, the time is not ripe. To what extent a higher integration is possible, in manufacture alone, is an -open question. In the more advanced nations agricuture has, largely, become capi- talistic. In Australia the 'squatter' is passing ; every drought, every financial crisis reduces his numbers ; 'runs' are rapidly passing into the hands of comipanies and are worked by mana- gers. In some countries the introduction of costly machinery, such as. ploughs with many shares drawn by. prime-movers: large power-driven reaping machinery : the employment of 'labor' to prepare the soil and reap the harvest: the growing necessity, in many cases, for large and costly irrigation works : the -establishment of rural banks and '.pools' for the better marketing of agricultural products-all point to the develop- FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. ment of communal action and the decay of individualism. In these countries the time is ripe for guild Socialism. We have now set forth, in sufficient detail, a scheme of the machinery of wealth-production and explained its organisa- tion, and have shown how through industrial democracy eco- nomic freedom is assured. Something is still to be said in explanation of the working of the system and in particular of its relation to civil government. Civil government is vested in the National Parliament, and this body forms, with addition of its executive officers, the entity we call "the State." Now the State is not without a voice in industrial affairs; for, as representative of the entire community, it is, in effect, the owner of the land and capital of the country. Further, though the National Trades-Congress represents all producers it does not represent all consumers. The sick, the aged, children, women (in part) and resident aliens-if they draw their in- come from other countries - are represented only in the National Parliament. Some integration therefore of State and Trades-Congress is required, and how that is brought about will best be seen as we develop other working details. Thus, for example, a standard of value and a medium of internal exchange are required. For these we propose the Standard Hour note. (Gold would still remain, in all prob- ability, the medium of foreign exchange, and the standard of international values. It would liquidate the "balance of trade.") Individuals would receive pay, not (in the present sense of the word) wages, and the rate ot pay would be fixed by social evaluation. Now, as has been already pointed out, the basis of the Standard Hour is purely a matter of convention and solely concerns the particular community which adopts it. But, the basis agreed upon, how is the social evaluation of each man's work not only in one guild but as between different guilds to be made? And here we touch that integration of National Parliament and Trades-Congress already desiderated. Firstly, each guild would fix ratios for all its members. (Members of the State Administration and Executive would form a guild of their own for a like purpose.) Secondly, Congress would co-ordinate these ratios for all guilds represented by it. Par- liament would do the like for its officers. And, finally, a joint sitting of Congress and Parliament would fib the pay- ment of all. Thus the functions of State and Trades-Congress are integrated. Awards of pay would be subject, from time to time, to revision; and this revision would be based upon the law of supply and demand. For, as every man is free to choose his 212 occupation and the guild he prefers to work in, if certain guilds attract too many workers the rates of pay in that guild would be lowered, if too few, increased, until an equilibrium was established. Thus by social evaluation direct and indirect pay would soon reach a more or less stable basis. Again it would be necessary to fix prices: for products are not directly proportionate to the r,~' ber of individual standard hours they contain. The rich mine, the fertile field, the industry employing the most or best machinery would still yield a disproportionately great return, and yet all other mines, fields, factories, might be socially necessary to supply all re- quirements of the community. In fixing prices, as in determin- ing rates of pay, "supply and demand" would furnish a guiding principle. But if the price of some articles is, say, raised, the price of others must be reduced: the pluses must always be equal to the minuses: the amount realised from the sale of the total goods (and services) produced must be equal to the "wages" paid. Thus, the equitable distribution of differential-rent and differential-profit, and the co-ordination of inherent and exchange-value would be the work of "con- gress" and of "its" officers appointed for that purpose. But the fixing of the general level of prices, so as to yield a surplus for communal purposes, would be the joint work of Parliament and Congress. The variation of individual prices, plus and minus, would not affect the general price level. The importance and, indeed, necessity of the integration of Parliament and Congress-which for brevity's sake we may call henceforth the "Congress-State "-are the more appreciated as we realise more fully what is implied in the significant act of price-fixing, which is in fact the crowning piece in the whole structure of economic justice. The value of the goods made by each guild must primarily pay the "true cost of pro- duction." This consists of "maintenance" (i.e., depreciation of plant used in manufacture) raw materials, and pay to the workers, but includes neither private rent, profit, nor interest (as it does under Capitalism). But the price of the goods may vary from their value, plus or minus, by differential profit or differential loss according as each guild, taken as a unit of production, uses more or less than the average amount of "natural or artificial advantages. Now under Capitalism the difference (of possible profit) between the least advan- tageously placed socially necessary industry and the most ad- vantageously placed passes into the pockets of private indi- viduals because no social organism has been developed to turn value into price and retail the difference for the community as a whole. But under guild Socialism the missing social or- FREEDOM. 213 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. gan --which appears in a rudimentary form in syndicalism"-is supplied and made perfect by the Congress-State. Conscious and intelligent action by the Congress-State replaces the erst- while blind play of economic forces, and prices are so fixed as not only to pay to each industry the individual inherent value of the goods it produces, but also to hold true the balance of justice bltween all industries in the community, and, if at such a rate as to retain a differential profit, then to keep that profit entire ;for the benefit of the community as a whole. But prices fixed in this manner to ensure a just return to each individual worker would be subject to variation from time to time to meet the varying and more or less fitful demands of consumers, that is, the 'wages' paid guild workers would not necessarily determine the price charged the con- sumer. Any profit or loss, however, resulting from a mal- adjustment of prices to values would fall to the community as a whole. Thus is guild Socialism not only economic free- dom but economic justice as well. Further, if, as is indeed advisable, in price-fixing more or less of differential profit is retained, then in the fund so created the Congress-State has the wherewithal to extend existing industries and undertake new enterprises. It may also elect to mete out this "surplus" State expenditure and all forms of "free service": or, in the alternative, these may be provided, as at present, out of taxation-it is purely a question of convenience. In the new State 'free services' would be far more numer- ous and varied than under present conditions. Naturally, the services of all State officials would be free, but we may expect to find the list extended to include, e.g., all members of the Education Guild, the Medical Guild (involving also den- tists), probably the Guild of Artists. And here we are reminded of a question too long deferred-what is to be done with the "Economic Rent" of ability, how, that is to say, would exceptional ability be remunerated and within what limits should its possessor receive the benefit? Abstract justice might reasonably demand that exceptional ability if acquired should be paid for and that inherited ability should be common property. But in practice it would be found too difficult, if not indeed impossible, to make such a distinction correctly, and relative justice would probably be content, under guild Socialism, if, while the indi- vidual guild fixed a high rate of pay for service of excep- *Under Syndicalism differential profits are retained by individual in- dustries-an injustice to the community on the one hand, and to less advan- tageously placed industries on the other. The organ which turns value into price is partial, not social, and therefore defective. 214 tional ability on the part of its members it received a still higher fee from those desirous of profiting by such service and- retained the difference. This would be, admittedly, a compromise-part of the 'economic rent' of ability would be- long to the individual "star" (to borrow a convenient, if somewhat colloquial term) and a part to the general com- munity. To any who might object that the incentive to exceptional ability would be unduly diminished we should retort that popular estimation would fully supply the de- ficiency. The various 'free services' and to those mentioned might be added free passenger transport-together with State expenditure on old age and invalid pensions, orphanhood, hos- pitals, police, and similar objects, will require the provision of a considerable revenue. This may be obtained solely by in- creasing the price of commodities, or by taxation, or by a com- bination of both methods. The matter is not vital-it is, as has already been said, a question of convenience. We would add merely that if taxation is preferred there is no just ground for a sliding scale: a percentage on all incomes would be the equitable method. We have now completed our brief survey of Guild Social- ism and have shown how it, and it alone, offers the solution of economic freedom and economic justice, that without it political freedom is a sham. Many details are omitted from a necessarily rapid sketch, but most of these the reader's own intelligence may be ,trusted to supply. One question remains, and that of the greatest practical moment, how, viz., if Guild Socialism be the true solution, is the goal to be reached and by what approaches? And here it must be recognised that if society is a living organism, Guild Socialism must evolve by natural growth and that only within certain (and narrow) limits can the growth of a living organism be forced. We hold, therefore, that the coming industrial reorganisation, if it is to be permanent, must be evolutionary, but also that conscious action by man is a necessary factor of that evolution. Guild Socialism must grow-out of Capitalism, and out of trade-unionism. The completed change will constitute a re- volution, and to hasten forward the revolution is the traditional mission of Labor. Nor need the word revolution excite dismay. We do not forecast events comparable to the French Revolution or those by which the Bolshevik rule was established in Russia, when (as in the violent contortions of Nature, her earthquake and volcanic eruptions) long pent-up forces suddenly find release FREEDOM. 215 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. and the social order dissolves into chaos. What we see in the future is a gradual and natural change culminating in a final stage whose comparative suddenness and reversal of a pre-existing order constitute a revolution-a peaceful re- volution and a bloodless. It is the birth of a child. For long months the child has developed in the mother's womb, nourished indirectly by the food she eats and the air she breathes. But there comes a crisis-the child is born, breathes for itself and digests its own food. There has been long preparation, but the event is sudden and the change complete. It is a phase of growth. It is a natural revolution. Historians have concurred in naming the change in indus- trial organisation which produced Capitalism an industrial revolution. In a precisely similar sense do we and others with us speak of a social revolution which will replace Capitalism by a more perfect system. As, however, conscious human action is a factor in this evolution it is well to consider briefly the nature of such intervention, the methods, more in detail, of hastening and helping the birth of a new system. Words of which so much is heard to-day, 'strike,' 'boycott,' 'direct action,' raise the question of force-what it is and how far it is allowable. Clearly we are speaking here of political force. Now since it is of the essence of democracy that the will of the majority should prevail, and as continuous unanimity in any community of men is unthinkable, any action of the majority overruling the opinions of a minority must in greater or less degree be of the nature of force. Further, the majority may legitimately use force (in a fuller sense, here) to prevent a minority from imposing (by material force) its will upon the community. A minority has one legitimate weapon-and one only - persuasion: but that weapon is its indisputable right.* From these premises it follows that if Labor forms a majority of the community, it may legitimately use the force of law, the direct action of a strike, to resist and destroy forcible exploitation by a minority. Force then is not, under circumstances, an improper method; on the contrary, it is justified if it is requisite to prevent the will of a minority imposing on the majority of a nation, and is in fact implicit in every action taken by a ruling majority. And now we may turn to consider by what practical steps Guild Socialism may be brought about, or at least, hastened. By history and tradition alike the task is assigned to Labor: but some divergence of opinion exists as to method. There are Guild Socialists who, like S. G. Hobson, would have Labor leave politics entirely alone, and devote itself solely to organ. *It is strange in this 20th century of ours to find this right disputed. 216 ising the "'One Big Union," which is to include all workers, not the skilled artisan alone, but the so-called 'middle class'- professional men, clerks, managers,-as well as the mass of unskilled laborers. Others again hold that the first object of Labor should be to capture the Legislature. Both views have reason on their side:-neither is sufficient in itself. The attack must be all along the line, no less on the political than on the economic front. Minor issues set aside, two objectives loom up large and palpable-democratic control of industry, communal owner- ship of the means of production. In practice perhaps not wholly separable, they are sufficiently diverse to be treated individually. Democratic control (which is really self-control) of industry it is Labor's task to secure. (In passing, we would rule out "Syndicalism," which, aiming as it does at class ownership, is a disintegrating force.) The first step will be greatly to strengthen, enlarge and unite existing Labor Unions: the next, by their means, to push more rapidly to a decisive issue the "class-war" which is already being waged in all capitalist countries. There are at least three prime needs. First, all workers must be enlisted. This involves (a) a true conception of what really constitutes a "worker," and this once realised will destroy the existing-and most mischievous -barrier between "Labor" and "Middle-class," whose inter- ests are in reality almost identical, (b) (and this is in effect a corollary) the adoption of the principle of "solidarity." Though sectional jealousy is still rife in Labor circles, it is slowly passing, and the ultimate triumph of "solidarity" is assured. Secondly, the army once enlisted, provision must be made for adequate training, equipment and direction. As yet, e.g., the "One Big Union" is little more than a crude though fer- tile idea. And thirdly, the commissariat must be organised. For this Labor must look to the Co-operative Store movement which, well advanced in England, Denmark, Italy and (to a less degree) Germany, is reaching high-water mark in Belgium, where its development since the war merits the epithet phe- nomenal. America, France, and Australia on the other hand are here notably deficient. Nor must Labor look for victory solely to one final coup; the class struggle must be continuous. Every fair means must be adopted, every 'concession' accepted; but the moral sense of the community should be educated-not violated. Sec- tional advantages may be won by 'raids,' but these raids merely assist and prepare for the general attack and keep the army 217 FREEDOM. FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. drilled, disciplined and 'fit.' Final victory is brought nearer by the seizure of strategic points, and it is not too soon to establish democratic control and communal ownership of--for a beginning-mines and railways. Guild Socialists, however, with every reason, refuse to pay 'money down' for industries communally acquired, objecting-and rightly-that this would merely substitute State Capitalism and so perpetuate wage-slavery. But, with a legislature captured for reform enacting democratic control and communal ownership, com- plete payment of capital and interest to, e.g., holders of railway stock, could be made in, let us say, 20 equal yearly amounts, the money being raised by increased taxes-on a sliding scale -levied upon land and income. 'Capital' ownership thus ex- tinguished, fares and freights could be lowered and wages in- creased in proportion to the load of interest removed from the shoulders of those who use the railways. Insensibly, but inevitably, in discussing methods for estab- lishing democratic control of industry we have been led to impinge upon the second of the two problems-how, viz., com- munal ownership is to be effected. Now while it is for the Labor Unions to contend for the control of industry, the fight for communal ownership is the business of the consumers, the business therefore of all members of the community, of society as a whole. It can be won by capturing the Legislature, and that in all democratic countries is a step neither difficult nor distant. It has been accomplished in Australia. Assuming then a legislature ready to enact communal ownership, we have to consider by what direct methods it is to be brought into being. The expropriators must be expro- priated-but how? In any case we must expect the words: robbery, spoliation, confiscation, repudiation, to be used by the expropriated who will indignantly appeal to justice. If Justice uses the words: restoration, restitution, reparation, taxation, they will not be understood. The system of private ownership in the instruments of production must go immediately that system is clearly understood by the bulk of the people. The plunderer has a legal and vested right to plunder. To cause that plunder to cease is to be called a plunderer. Nothing is to be gained for either side by each calling the other names. At present exploitation in the form of private rent, profit, and interest is legal: make such rent, profit and interest illegal and immediately exploitation becomes robbery which law and order may be invoked to prevent. "The welfare of the people is the supreme law." If necessary the few must suffer for the good of the many--but there need be no suffering. Guild Socialists propose to pension off capitalists, the pension to last for two generations. The proposal is not only just, but merciful. 218 It must never be forgotten that capitalists are mere creatures of circumstances, and not criminals. It is only right and fair that the 'revolution' should be made as easy for them as possible, but 'revolution' there must be. The difficulty is in the first step to be taken, in all probability before the real position is completely understood. Some compromise will probably be necessary if the change is to be made by a peaceful revolution. To that end we com- mend our taxation proposal (see page 193) in, perhaps, a less drastic form at first. But details after all will settle them- selves if the underlying principle is understood. We have pictured the land of promise, we have surveyed and measured the roads by which we may travel to it: many of us may not enter in, but others will. With the integration of the community in Guild Socialism, combining completeness of democratic control with full eco- nomic freedom and a real political democracy, the evolution of the social organism stands accomplished. There remains a still higher integration far, as yet, in the future, but certain of fulfilment-the international control of industry. With that we have not to deal. It must suffice merely to say that the same principles of justice which we have evoked in arguing the case of "the man versus the State" stand good when the case of "the nation versus the world" is considered. If the omen of the League of Nations does not mislead, political inte- gration must precede economic. But the time will surely come when the interdependence of nation upon nation will be fully recognised, the stupidity of war acknowledged, and the force to prevent force be found in a supreme World-Government. Government by an aristocracy has failed. Government by a plutocracy has failed. Power, political and economic alike, is passing into the hands of the people. And therein is the promise of a better and a nobler age. "Democracy is sudden like the sea, grows dark with storms and sweeps away many precious things; but like the sea, it reflects the light of the wide heavens and cleanses the shores of human life." FREEDOM. 219 220 FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. Appendix. EXPLANATION OF TABLES. A period of 80 years of Capitalism has been considered. One hundred men are assumed to work 8 hours per day. Each man is assumed to be an 'average' worker and the value of each man's work is taken as standard, so that one natural hour of work is one Standard Hour. The total output is, therefore, 800 S.H. per day. Since all use the same amount of machinery and form one organ- isation the "individual" and "social" standard hours are the same, viz., 800 per day. Each unit product-each pound, or yard, ounce or inch-is assumed to contain 1 S.H. in the zero year. With the growth of "capital," however, unit products contains a smaller and still smaller fraction of 1 iS.H. ,The 800 S.H. may be taken to represent any period-a day, a month, or a year. Real wages are paid in commodities, and in the zero year (assump- tion 3) the wages per hour for 100 men are 700, or 7 articles per man (see column 7, Table of Quantities). In the 80th year real wages (assumption 4) are 700 + (80 x 2% of 700)=700 + (80 x 14)=1820. It is in this manner that column 7 in the table of quantity of products has been calculated. The total number of commodities produced in the 80th year depends largely on the quantity of 'plant' used. By assumption (3) the capitalists' share of the commodities pro- duced in the zero year is one-eighth of 800=100, and of this amount 31 % is set aside each year as capital, and the total capital is increased by 3A per cent. of the previous capital; in the 80th year, therefore, at 3z per cent. compound interest this 100 * amounts to 1468, and one- half, or 734 is 'plant.' Then by assumption (8) we have for the total quantity of commodities produced: 800 x 10 (734)=8140. In this manner column 13 of the table of Quantity of Products is calculated, of this total, 8140, 1820 is paid in wages, leaving 6320. Out of this amount (6320) 3717 goes to replace raw material and 371 to replace worn-out plant, leaving a surplus of 2232 to the capitalist. By assumption (5) plant and raw material is increased each year by 31 per cent. The capitalists must therefore save 32 per cent. of 7434 (3717 + 3717) = 260 daily in the 80th year, leaving a net income in consumption goods of 2230 articles, pounds or yards, etc., of goods per day. In this manner the table of quantities is calculated. The table gives daily or yearly quantities. (If 300 working days per year are assumed the yearly results are obtained by multiplying by 300, but since the ratio is constant, the daily results may, for our purpose, be taken as yearly results.) The table of 'labor time' is similarly calculated. The total daily time is eight hours and the daily products (column 13) are in the APPENDIX. 221 80th year 8140, i.e., (C=4088) + (V=1820) + (S=2232)=8140. Of these products the workers receive 1820. Thus the time required to 1820 produce their own wages is - of 8=1.79 S. Hours per man. (In the 8140 zero year it was 7 S. Hours.) To replace the constant capital, raw and partly finished material and worn-out plant, 4088 goods are re- 4088 quired (column 6 of table of quantities), and to make these goods - 8140 of 8=4.02 hours per man are required. This is the necessary return of capital and is quite distinct from the unnecessary return to capi- talists. If, however, production is to continue to increase at the rate of 3j per cent. per annum, 260 goods must be saved; the work of a quarter of an hour per man per day. The balance of the time in the 80th year is 1.94 hours per day per man, and is occupied in producing the 1972 daily consumption goods, or surplus products which are taken by the capitalists as their net income. Thus the whole of the workers receive 1820 consumption goods and the whole of the capitalists 1972 in the 80th year. The table of values shows the value, that is, the number of S. Hours of labor, present and past, embodied in the goods. In the zero year each uit of goods costs and is of the value of one S. Hour. In the 80th year the cost per unit has fallen to .197 S. Hour; thus the quan- tity of goods increases much faster than the value of the goods, and it is the quantity of goods that counts in the welfare of a community or nation. The total value of the daily output in the 80th year is 1607, therefore that quantity must be divided in the same ratio as the 2232 goods, thus the surplus value is - of 1607=441, and in this way all 8140 the other values are obtained and tabulated. The present labor, it should be noted, is constant at 800, but the past labor gradually in- creases from zero to 807 in the 80th year. The inherent value of an article consists in the total labor (present or past) embodied in the article, or in the 80th year to 800+807=1607 S.H. * These 100 commodities or 100 S.H. may be represented by 100 sovereigns *Xxwenput 4..C 4 I4 C O a-0 rt- eo40'44 C ;o pag4XnK uo t;oad jo v 03CO O O OC co _co mco mCO oc CO CO CO ,-4 1-4 1-4 1-4 0000 a CO - d+ 44'1in co m n o toC a r+ GO o 4 �..� ill anjvA :tff, ,-Io 0i CO :- 4 4 40 COCO CO 40 mC 14 r+ nco0 00C O00C-k C~o ott0 C D r~ "Snotu PJICPU11W 0 w-4 CO 4 4- 0 1t4- CO 4:aoM- C C O c - "-- 1d-C CO cqCO '1 M~4 O'-4M 40 CO 0, i o r-0Co00 C0 +e-1 CO CoCO 0CO4 CC . 1-4 1;1. CO~ttr-M,{o 4t00t0COt44mw0 - O CO 000-iJ~ 00t0000 c00 Olo onpotcl + O O :40COCO1 M "UOT onp c. t+ MCO ,i.O m C. m (00 C) C.C) C) a) 0 00 LIUPLj 41 JO1-4d. - r1r1 - - poojdu Ts~iST1 V41 U 0 0 aI SlIT O~m wej *soTPipuiU100 pug Wil o11 t~o + C/i2 0 r-4 4: n a : -+ + f4404:,-i - : !-0r- CO cC 15r - r- 4 0 4: "iqMQ -I - 04:- r 004:- CO to i40 1-4 CO 40 COm 4 r O0 0l o 414 O O 4CO - o CO0C 4:. 0 404-0,-+r0 0- r4 r1 r-1O 04 :-C 0~C OC O~ 4- 00 o44 0 t CO 00404- CO o --:. o 0 Co o :. COm4 C 0Co 40C 04 - CO CO 0 cq r4- m0mCO CMC O 1-4ri0 C d om4- Co 4in d+C 40 t~ COCO C C 1 iIr ? CO CO CO0 d4COC~oo 0 r44 CO O 4tc~- (M 04- t4 CO 0 CO CO-44:- 40 co o~0 di d +Cd COm COmcc N C COCO-4 r-4 '-41.-41-41T-4 0 CO4: :- Co00 14 CO 1dCCO 0 2C -1co 4:- t- 4:- 0 40:o0 CO 404:- Ot CO C ~o 1~ o 00 CO CO C d4 di41{4d+440404040inCo Co tCOwco CL4- 4- r440 C COC 44CO Co R4 m0,-0 -444:- CO T-4 04:- 40 CO=4- '-4400 CO CO 04- 40C C w Coi CO4014 C mCCOr 14 - r-4 40) CO CO CO ,-CA400CO 40 c-4,- L14 id4 r-10 co~~m- 0n0CoC O'14COCetM- O ~COCOCO G~-iVrf co CO40 CO 0 4: CC -40COCO e t- c to co Q C -i -i ri 0 mO 14 40 Co T1441404 0 Co 4- COCo 01400 COri '-40 d+144C CO Co 14- M0CO 144 CO CO r 4:- CO 4014d'COmCO CO -4 -1-4 Co 0 O CooCo CoO 14414 CO CCo 0 O co cOt ,- CO o CO404:- 0CO C o mC 0eCOd144 C 144 C~O o CO 40144 C C C 1 44 CO 144 IC) d~44040d~gm0OCo0"44d00 4:.. 0I 4idq00CO It0iC CO d O T +t- Z - to I Om C ri4-4 00 CM Co0 ~C oC Co 00 0 CtO CO CDC C Co00 CoCO-4C Co~o CO 0 4- O Co CO 0 CO 14 Q4o CO 00CoC10 I CO CO .-0 000Co0Co0o0Co0C CO G ; ci r iriri 4 444 04004004=t0040040 0 )0 spoo oi U0d11fs -1100 UT OUIOOUT X1T11p S1sIT14:T JzO OflIVA snicTznS *sp0fpozd UT 111111( pao~Xosop 40U ;Uweld ;o a0Uel111 J4uo Uad 1 T00Jd ;oUU~nCI LWIOIa -4 1- 1- --I 1 I- i f i { { { I DO m r'' w.va& oaag "flnA 1000.03 Qalid 30JO oTW1AaP LI-91 a0uaJa;jI(] 000-0t- CO 1inC10Od~v*4CCCoroi-4v-4) CO 0 - -, 40 Co q r-~ 4 r1 qr100 Co4 0 Com000 0o- CO ekt"- 1-4 Co100 C o 00 Cor!-ho 000 r- 00C r, (8100) a ) 2 Co00-COmo-0 - Ch o" j4C1oyr4-4r-i --*ThI0Jd L~UL10N -4 444i - -00 Co Co d+ CO CO Q0 iCO - Co r-1Co Co 0 co 4 -4 CoI 00 Co r -4 0 CO 0 00 C Co 0- CO CO t- r-1 co r-a 00 CO C 0 100 1;0.1id ;o 01'14 COW-CO~o,400-COCO"1J4CoMoNoClo-4 1-4 ,-4COC00000C0O4CCo0Co-'-00 1 Lrej 1 C)p~dj CO00- 000 Co C l CO O 0-COtCo Co .-4 0001 jo onje e~u'Ltpxa 0-Z=u d fG2 rir1r- - - 00 -4 Cot- r4 00 CO CO r-1 Co 00 M00- r0 uoponposd + ,-C0C-O- 4 CO -4 0-CO CO CO 000 ~o soo unjoy �~' -0 O'~C 00- Q ko -4~m0 2C~4-I4r-4 C01n0 0Z0 0 0 CO CO0 XCJO ICOCO 0 "slanpOsid a 000COCO0CCOC00-Co 'wt 0000 AIJ~AJso 1 eQ +� 00co i d d My Oc 2r- ,-41r-I + N p~AOI~tU+)CO 0d+ 0 0 Co0- Co 0CO C 1 o 00 0- + O oua W C ,4rfL eotmC)-4( 0 P I CO. s4!I~CO CO0y4000Co- aCo0-Cao~o- - Co o 00Co -lCoo CO000-0 ~nC00-0CO Co 0 w *en IOOUI Q 0eo co - CO Co Co C 00 r- 0 Co - 100 0 0 Co 0-4Cor-4 r0 0+t COOM C - 0CO C 1Ot +0 o Co 0 9110U0C-inC O - O 000 Co CO - 00-I0 U soo SPOOR + Ol-14-4CO0o-00CCOoHCo-000 A -{-O0 - dtt CflSUOC0 o r810J00 uo izsuo 'ly.ImcI6 N l c ir - - . - 0 am Bs0flp0Jid ut juvejd pule si4?tIaffeW :poe~jdwo 4uejsuOD "pa4X0J1S p lou E or4?id jo O0U-e8- LI) 0t m Co 0 oM Co 00- C11 W InCd�Co c2 d+ CX)w 1 ? Cor CO 0 Om i Co~ O - o 0o 00 o 0 Co 00 - 1CO1Co r- 00 ,- CD O CO+mCoCo r-{41-4r-1-4 O r4 44 "1 4 4 000000000 0000000 C ~ r-rr~t mto coCO00'.-4 4-0 000 c oua t - +C OrO~~CoC -+ o000000o - 0- 00 r- Co 0- - 00 - CO iCO r-1 Co0000 - r- 00007 Cj -4 CO o0mCo d 0m0-0 Co 00 W Co -i 0o Co 0000 C-0- CO CoC -4+r-+ r -44 cO t40- Co 00 CoCO CO 1- ^ COd{1-4 Co 0 '444 O 1 40 iiON i1-4 Co O CO dF Co Co CO0 d+ i 4 0 CO 'M C Co4 - M oC r-1 -4.. *uifluue J.)T 1 Co 1-4 o00-COn d r-4 0-0 O ICOM00 Co 00 -' GACo 1- 0 a- COtoO OC o Co 1mN~- et~I0 CuoCad01 u Id 0- ooo-y 0-o 4 COCo -00 O 0 O C CO orCOCO0 rl 00-mc o 01- 0CO dit-0-1 r0- Co r4 ch ":um~iwt 13oJ. 0-0COo0aCO~t4Coio- al OT44- Pun 4UeLd recioa SriJ~cI pun ?AU?) -woe00p104? ;ed ujT sonpoJd re;os r-4 'Cuo 0 + t 000 =0 o0o CO 00 Co 0 CO 00- R4 + 000 Co m 0CO Co et 00 Co Co'400 0 0 - ~ C Co 0 - 4CO -Co C ' to o 1414 uaa Co Co a Co44' CO 14 Co -Coo m CcoCO CO C Co 4414-00 '4 0 0014X4 O c CO o 0000- C000m Cio 00a 74 CO00L 4 = C C O 0M r cC-400 CO Co 'Ir-140 0 4r- o o 44 4 OC no 0 CO ,CO O 00 O Z0 CO0 CO '.rasa, oo 00-r- COCCC ~~~Coooi t wmm0 i -,- C 0- t- 0 0 Coj Co - 0 Co CO 00 0- 0 co co 1 0 CO 0t Co 0- 0 Co 0- Co CO 1-4 0 00 1044 "14 -I CO ' 0- 0l 0- '4?e210M pu's salartSs - - i ---- i -1- -A - i. I 224 80 8.00 75 8.00 70 8.00 65 8.00 60 8&00 55 8.00 50 8.00 45 8.00 40 8.00 35 8.00 30 8.00 25 8.00 20 8.00 15 8.00 10 8.00 5 8.00 Zero 8.00 dl VV 194 2.06 2.22 2.30 2.34 2.40 2.35 2.28 2.13 1.98 1.82 159 1.41 1.26 1.13 1.01 1.00 0. rn bn I ~ ~rii .25 .23 .21 .19 .16 .14 .12 10 .09 .07 .06 1.05 .03 .02 .01 .01 0~U m~ SO C.02 3.68 3.28 2.92 2.60 2.21 1.91 1.60 1.36 1.11 .90 .70 .50 .34 .21 .10 0 H 1,79 2.03 2.29 2.59 2.90 3.25 3,62 4.02 4.42 4,84 5.22 5.66 6,06 6.38 6.66 &.88 7.00 H 11.9 80 127 75 13.9 70 15.2 65 16.7 60 18.4 55 20.4 50 22.5 45 25.3 40 28..3 35 31.5 30 35.6 25 39.6 20 44.1 15 49.1 10 54.8 5 60,0 Zero FROM CAPITALISM TO FREEDOM. DISTRIBUTION OF LABOR TIME. 8 HOUR DAY. 4-J --------------- -' APPENDIX. 225 FREE TRADE v. PROTECTION. Just now-the closing months of '23-it looks as though the old capitalist parties in England, the old 'Liberal' and old 'Conservative' (manufacturers and landlords) may succeed in drawing that red herring, the fiscal issue, across the path of the British Labor Party. If a coo-ee from Australia can 'be heard across the world, however faintly, let Labor beware. Forty (and more) years ago this millstone kept the Australian Labor Party submerged, and it was only when they cut themselves free of it that they rose triumphant. If the British Labor Party does not sink the fiscal issue, the fiscal issue will assuredly sink the party. How confident we free traders were in the old days! The Angel of Peace was to descend on the earth clad in untaxed Lancashire cotton: artificial national barriers were to be thrown down: other nations we believed would hasten to follow our noble example: and when they did not, it was with condescending pity, more in pained surprise than in anger, that we regarded their blindness. We had seen the vision splendid; why were they so blind? Perhaps after all our eyes were clearer and our practical commonsense was greater (!) than was the case with other nations. In plain English, the other eleven jurymen were (and are) excessively stupid. How the old 'Liberals' must now rejoice scenting the familiar battle ground again. 'A free breakfast table': 'taxing the people's food': what glorious battle cries and what a splendid split in the ranks of the Labor Party, half-two-thirds-of the party trooping back to the ancient and comfortable dug-outs, once more to fight under the glorious banner of freedom and laissez-faire. Again we hear the old victorious shout, "Let each country produce what it can best produce and freely exchange goods with its neighbors, thus reaching at one bound the harmony of a united world." Have we not heard the voice of the charmer? By this time it should be clear that neither free trade nor protection are of lasting benefit to the workers. Whether the breakfast table is taxed or free matters not one iota. Wages must buy the scanty meal, and if costs are high wages must be correspondingly high, real wages must keep body and soul together, and that is about all they will do under the present wage-system. Of course there may be no wages at all. Protectionist America has had her two millions of unemployed, free trade England her million (a percentage rather in favor of America). If there are no wages, then let Labor fight to increase the dole and cease its stupid opposition to taxation. 'Tax the rich' should be the cry. When England was the workshop of the world, free trade was her best policy. When she is (as now) threatened with the loss of some portion of her home market, protection is her best policy, but neither will help the worker-much. It hlas been stated that Britain's home market is twenty times as great as her foreign market; if so, the loss of five per cent. of her home trade would be equivalent to the loss of the whole of her foreign trade (including her Empire trade). The importance of her home market is immense, and her home market may be assured by protection. With protection and increased wages (real wages) the home market and the comfort of Britain's workers might be increased, but-fatal objection-the profits of her manufacturers and capitalists would not be increased. Thus, so long as capitalists rule the State neither protection nor free trade will greatly or permanently improve the position of the wage-receiver. Reform must go deeper. Let the British Labor Party concentrate on such reforms and let it beware the fiscal issue. Reader's Pencil Notes. This book is a preservation facsimile produced for the University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign. It is made in compliance with copyright law and produced on acid-free archival 60# book weight paper which meets the requirements of ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992 (permanence of paper). Preservation facsimile printing and binding by Northern Micrographics Brookhaven Bindery La Crosse, Wisconsin 2009