THE LIBRARY OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LOS ANGELES THE PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI MACMILLAN AND CO., Limited LONDON • BOMBAY • CALCUTTA MELBOURNE THE MACMILLAN COMPANY NEW YORK • BOSTON • CHICAGO ATLANTA • SAN FRANCISCO THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, Ltd. TORONTO THE PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI BY G. S. BRETT PROFKSSOR OF PHILOSOPHY, GOVKRNMBNT COLLBGE, LAHORE MACMILLAN AND CO. LIMITED ST. MARTIN'S STREET, LONDON 1908 OLASOOW: PRINTKD AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS BY ROBERT MACLEUOSE AND CO. LTD PREFACE Up to the present little attention has been paid to Gassendi. The want of a reliable account of his philosophy has caused him to be neglected, for the nature of his own v/ritings is such as would naturally obscure the value of his message. Hallam, in his Introduction to the Literature of Europe (Part IV. chap, iii.), indicates the extent to which Gassendi has been neglected and also the reasons. He refers to Gassendi's "prolixity of statement," " prodigality of learning," and " display of erudition," characteristics which have all militated against recognition of his real merits. In consequence he is little more than a name, or is known as the original of Bernier's work, and is either misunderstood or pushed aside as one who challenged Descartes from an antiquated and untenable standpoint. To remedy this error and supply what is un- doubtedly a page in the history of philosophy I have tried in this book to express briefly the main lines of Gassendi's thought. It has been necessary to condense the matter ruthlessly, but this could be done with all the less danger because so much of the contents of the volumes is historical. None the less it is natural that there should arise G53530 vi PREFACE the feeling that a process which condenses chapters into phrases and whole sections into sentences, is an injustice to an author. The atmosphere of com- prehensive learning which gives a peculiar charm to these volumes cannot be reproduced elsewhere : it is the breath of an age which every day puts further from us. In compensation for this loss I can only plead the advantages of conciseness. Time works toward the setting forth of the skeleton with the destruction of all else, and in the world of books we take an optimistic view of this unavoidable process and trust that it le^.ves us what is most enduring and most essential. That Gassendi deserves honourable mention in the history of philosophy will hardly be doubted. How far he is able to help in the solution of its problems is a point that the reader will estimate for himself. Now that we are recovering somewhat from that disturbance of equilibrium which char- acterised the development of Cartesianism, such work as that of Gassendi has an opportunity of asserting itself more effectively. If we pause to ask what is the true and abiding characteristic of a philosophic mind we shall see that it is compre- hensiveness of view, breadth of vision, combined with a power to see, and not merely look at, the vast array of the knowable. This comprehensiveness makes greatness : through it a man may be the spectator of all times and places. But he must not hope to gain this comprehensive outlook by occupying one solitary peak : he must not flatter himself that there is an essence of all essences, that he can condense all life and thought into one PREFACE vii magic drop. On the contrary he must keep the original wealth of material undiminished if he would have a world in which ' life's garden blows ' ; if he abstracts and simplifies the product is an ' essence,' a drop of scent in place of the living flower. This fact is gaining more recognition now than it did some time ago. We do not always remember that the necessity for emphasising the point was not formerly so great as it has been recently. A reading of Gassendi brings home to us the fact that philosophy has not always considered concentration its prime duty, and a return to the atmosphere of naive pluralism is a refreshing reminder that thought was once childishly unsophisticated. With no intention of denying the value of the progress that has been made, and no attempt to ignore crudities and fallacies, we can still go back with profit to a view of the world that is not obsessed with the tendencies of extreme idealism : we can even go back to the pre- Kantian days with profit so long as we remember that they are pre-Kantian. In some respects it is peculiarly profitable to see what could be ^done with the material of knowledge before Hume was sceptical or Kant awakened : in the case of Gassendi the moderation and liberality of his views makes him frequently strike the line to which thought was destined to return, and thus appear in close touch with later developments. In reference to this I may add that the quotations from the original have been limited as much as possible. As the whole account is a mere summary the original can be easily consulted, the chapters and divisions of my account indicate the parts of the author which viii PREFACE are being considered. But I have felt compelled to insert quotations and phrases wherever there seemed a possibility of confusion or grounds for suspecting that the language used by me was not justified by the original. In the parts of this book which profess to contain the thoughts and ideas of Gassendi I have aimed only at exhibiting those thoughts and ideas with no more additions than were required to bridge over gaps caused by omission and no interpretation beyond what was demanded to make clear the underlying connexions of the original work. All references to previous philosophers and interpretations of their meaning within that part (i.e. Parts i. to m.) are to be credited to Gassendi. My own remarks are only intended to set the essential elements of Gassendi's philosophy in what I conceive to be their true historical light. CONTENTS PAoa Introductory The "Works of Gassendi ------ xi Bibliography ..-----. xv Introduction - - xvii PAKT I. LOGIC 1 PAET II. PHYSICS SECTION A CHAP. I. Introductory 19 II. Time and Space 34 III. First Principles (a) The Material Principle 49 (6) Primary and Secondary Causes - - - 55 (c) Motion and Mutation ----- 59 (d) On Qualities ------- 65 (e) On the Origin and Decay of Things - - 82 X CONTENTS CHAP. PAGE SECTION B I. Ti[E Inanimate World 89 II. The Animate World (a) Introductory 98 {b) On Design in Nature 100 (c) The Theory of the Soul 106 {d) The Anima Humana Ill (e) The Basis of Psychic Life .... 115 III. Psychic Life (a) Sense and Sensation 121 (6) Imagination 129 (c) Intellect and its Functions . . . . 139 {d) The Habits of Intellect 150 (e) The Passions 153 IV. The Nature of Life (a) The Vis Motrix 161 (6) Life and Death 168 (c) The Constitution of Animals - - - - 172 PAKT III. ETHICS I. On Happiness 183 II. The Virtues 196 III. On Liberty, Fate, and Divination - - - 2i8 IV. On God 224 NoTK on Declination 230 PART IV. GENERAL REVIEW I. GaSSENDI 245 II. Later Views 270 Index 308 THE WORKS OF GASSENDI The following is a complete list of the contents of the edition of 1658. Volume I Syntagma philosophicum. Liber prooemialis. Pars prima quae est logica. I. De origine et varietate logica. II. De logicae fine. Institutio logica. 1. De simplice rerum imaginatione. 2. De propositi one. 3. De syllogismo. 4. De methodo. Pars secunda quae est physica. Section 1. Book 1. De universe et mundo. 2. De loco et tempore. 3. De material! principio. 4. De principio efficiente. 5. De motu et mutatione rerum. 6. De qualitatibus rerum, 7. De ortu et interitu. Section 2. De Eebus Caelestibus. (End of Vol. I. pp. 752.) xii THE WORKS OF GASSENDI Volume II Syntagma philosophicum (continned). Section 3. Part I. De rebus terrenis inanimis. Book 1. De globo ipso telluris. De vocatis vulgo meteoris (ventis, etc.). De lapidibus ac metallis. De plantis. Part II. De rebus terrenis viventibus. De varietate aninialium. De partibus animalium. De anima. De generatione animalium. De nvitritione. De sensu universe. De sensibus speciatim. De phantasia. De intellectu seu niente. De appetitu et affectibus animae. De vi motrice. De temperie. De vita et morte. De animorum immortalitate. ' Pars tertia quae est ethica. Book 1. De felicitate. „ 2. De virtutibus. „ 3. De libertate, fortuna, etc. (End of Vol. II. pp. 860.) Volume III 1. Philosophiae Epicuri Syntagma. 2. Exercitationes paradoxicae adversus Aristoteleos. 3. Fluddanae philosophiae examen. 4. Disquisitio metaphysica adversus Cartesium. 5-9. Epistulae. (End of Vol. III. pp. 662.) 2 I 3, ,, 4, Section 3. Book 1. 2. "„ 3, ,, 4. „ 5. „ 6. » 7. „ 8. „ 9. „ 10. „ 11. „ 12. „ 13. „ 14. THE WORKS OF GASSENDI xiii Volume IV Astronomica. Parts I.-V. pp. 536. Volume V 1. Diogenis Laertii Liber X, cum nova interpretatione et notis. 2. Vita Epicuri, Peireskii, Tychonis Brahei, Copernici, Peurbachii, et Kegioinontani. 3. Abacus sestertialis seu de valore antiquae monetae ad nostram redactae. 4. Romanum Calendarium compendiose expositum. 5. Manuductio ad theoriam musices. 6. Notitia ecclesiae Diniensis. (End of Vol. V. pp. 740.) Volume VI Epistulae et responsa. pp. 545. The whole of Gassendi's writings is thus contained in six Volumes folio, with a total of 4095 double-columned pages. BIBLIOGRAPHY (i.) The edition of the works to which reference is always made in this book is the edition of 1658 (Lyon). This contains all Gassendi's works (some slightly abridged), except some letters. On this point see Thomas, p. 28 : ' Celles qui ont et6 recueillies par M. de Montmor forment le sixieme volume du Syntagma : mais leur nombre a et6 considerablement augmente depuis, bien que beaucoup restent encore a publier. (Voy. " Documents inedits sur Gassendi," par Tamizey de Larroque : Revue des questions historiques, 1877, t. xxii. " Oraison funebre de P. Gassendi," par Nicolas Taxil, publiee par le meme, 1882. "Impressions de voyage de Pierre Gassendi," dans le Bulletin de la SociM scientifique et liitSraire des Basses- Alpes, 1887.)' I have no personal knowledge of these documents. (II.) Bernier, the traveller, a friend of Gassendi, com- piled an Abr4g4 de la Philoso;phie dc Gassendi, 8 vols., 1678; 2nd ed., 7 vols., 1684. This work is naturally far less cumbersome than Gassendi's own volumes. It is difficult to say quite what is wrong with it, but it is certainly wholly misleading, and, having been read to avoid the trouble of studying the original, has done much harm. I began with this work myself, but, after once looking into Gassendi, abandoned it. There is a wholly different atmosphere about Gassendi's writing, and perhaps the kindest criticism is to say that Bernier had more zeal as a friend than ability as a philosopher. (ill.) The only book on Gassendi which I have read is La Philosophie de Gassendi, par P.-F^lix Thomas, Paris, xvi BIBLIOGRAPHY 1889. I have read this since completing my own account of (iassendi, and owe to it some useful hints and references. Had it been other than it is, I should not have been justified in publishing a second study on the same subject. But the author seems to me to have done less than justice to Gassendi : he does not seem to have considered him an integral part of philosophy as a moving body of thought. Perhaps he is right, but to me Gas- sendi appears to have done more than patch up Epicurus : he has tried to unite the results, not only of philosophy in the narrower sense, but of all previous and contemporary thought into one whole, as consistent as he thought it could be. Hence we differ; but the student of Gassendi will get more insight into Gassendi from Thomas than he will from Bernier, and find this the conscientious work of one who has gone for his information to the fountain-head. (IV.) For the rest, I know of no other ' literature of the subject.' For the Life, Sorbiere's Sketch (vol. i.) is the chief authority. There is also a Vie de Gassendi by Bugerel (1737), and by Damiror {M4moire sur Gassendi, 1839). The best short account of Gassendi's philosophy is that of Eitter, to which I have referred elsewhere (p. 17). (v.) The manuscripts of Gassendi have been preserved, the majority at Tours, some in the Bibliotheque Rationale, and some in Provence (Thomas, p. 28). The edition of 1658, though published after the author's death, repre- sents his final corrections, and is acknowledged to be substantially accurate. INTRODUCTION The line of tliouo;ht which terminates in Gassendi began in Leucippus. The principal names in the history of its exposition are unfortunately little more than names, and in the case of both the main periods we are dependent on what may be called the second strings for the majority of our information. Thus of Leucippus we know but little, and he is usually taken in conjunction with Democritus, in order that together they may fill out a paragraph in the history of thought : similarly, while we are better off in the case of Epicurus, we none the less find it most convenient not to speak of Epicurus but of Epicureanism, and so give ourselves the lati- tude of using all the matter that can be collected from the whole school, in which the name of Lucretius stands forth prominently. As we desire to show the development of the subject we shall here try to keep the main points of the different epochs distinct : it will then be apparent how the theory grew and changed in face of new problems and changing conditions. I. Atomism and Epicureanism are very different things, but the beginnings of the theory of Epi- xviii PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI cunis^ are to be found in the atomic school, and the ditterences will be best understood if the growth of that doctrine is followed. The founder was Leucippus of Elea or Miletus. His standpoint does not seem to have been properly understood by historians of philosophy, but recent investigation has cleared our views on the significance of his lano-uage. He was in the first instance an Eleatic, and though the main principle of the Eleatic school, the unity and immovability of the One, seems so entirely opposed to the atomistic trend of thought that they could have nothing to do with each other, we find that in fact the opposition is not so great as appears at first sight, and the atomistic view is generated out of the Eleatic. In this interpretation we are guided by Aristotle, who says, ' Leucippus however thought he had a theory which was in harmony with sense-perception and did not do away with coming into being and passing away, nor motion nor the multiplicity of things. He made this concession to experience, while he conceded on the other hand to those who invented the One, that motion was impossible without the void, that the void was not real, and that nothino; of what was real was not real ! For,' said he, ' that which is strictly speaking real is an absolute plenum ; but the plenum is not one. On the ^Gasseudi says Epicurus was neither 'Primus nee solus qui Atomos defenderit.' Others are Mosohus — 'de quo Empiricus et Strabo etiam ante bellum Troianum' — Leucippus, Democritus, Metro- dorus, Ecphantus, Pythagoreus, Empedocles, Heracleitus, Plato (qui Enipedoclis instar, elementa coniposuit ex particulis prae exilitate inc