THE LIBRARY 
 
 OF 
 
 THE UNIVERSITY 
 
 OF CALIFORNIA 
 
 LOS ANGELES
 
 THE PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI
 
 MACMILLAN AND CO., Limited 
 
 LONDON • BOMBAY • CALCUTTA 
 MELBOURNE 
 
 THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 
 
 NEW YORK • BOSTON • CHICAGO 
 ATLANTA • SAN FRANCISCO 
 
 THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, Ltd. 
 
 TORONTO
 
 THE PHILOSOPHY OF 
 
 GASSENDI 
 
 BY 
 
 G. S. BRETT 
 
 PROFKSSOR OF PHILOSOPHY, GOVKRNMBNT COLLBGE, LAHORE 
 
 MACMILLAN AND CO. LIMITED 
 
 ST. MARTIN'S STREET, LONDON 
 
 1908
 
 OLASOOW: PRINTKD AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS 
 BY ROBERT MACLEUOSE AND CO. LTD
 
 
 PREFACE 
 
 Up to the present little attention has been paid 
 to Gassendi. The want of a reliable account of 
 his philosophy has caused him to be neglected, for 
 the nature of his own v/ritings is such as would 
 naturally obscure the value of his message. Hallam, 
 in his Introduction to the Literature of Europe 
 (Part IV. chap, iii.), indicates the extent to which 
 Gassendi has been neglected and also the reasons. 
 He refers to Gassendi's "prolixity of statement," 
 " prodigality of learning," and " display of erudition," 
 characteristics which have all militated against 
 recognition of his real merits. In consequence he is 
 little more than a name, or is known as the original 
 of Bernier's work, and is either misunderstood or 
 pushed aside as one who challenged Descartes from 
 an antiquated and untenable standpoint. 
 
 To remedy this error and supply what is un- 
 doubtedly a page in the history of philosophy I 
 have tried in this book to express briefly the 
 main lines of Gassendi's thought. It has been 
 necessary to condense the matter ruthlessly, but 
 this could be done with all the less danger because 
 so much of the contents of the volumes is historical. 
 None the less it is natural that there should arise 
 
 G53530
 
 vi PREFACE 
 
 the feeling that a process which condenses chapters 
 into phrases and whole sections into sentences, is an 
 injustice to an author. The atmosphere of com- 
 prehensive learning which gives a peculiar charm to 
 these volumes cannot be reproduced elsewhere : it 
 is the breath of an age which every day puts 
 further from us. In compensation for this loss I 
 can only plead the advantages of conciseness. Time 
 works toward the setting forth of the skeleton 
 with the destruction of all else, and in the world of 
 books we take an optimistic view of this unavoidable 
 process and trust that it le^.ves us what is most 
 enduring and most essential. 
 
 That Gassendi deserves honourable mention in 
 the history of philosophy will hardly be doubted. 
 How far he is able to help in the solution of its 
 problems is a point that the reader will estimate 
 for himself. Now that we are recovering somewhat 
 from that disturbance of equilibrium which char- 
 acterised the development of Cartesianism, such 
 work as that of Gassendi has an opportunity of 
 asserting itself more effectively. If we pause to ask 
 what is the true and abiding characteristic of a 
 philosophic mind we shall see that it is compre- 
 hensiveness of view, breadth of vision, combined 
 with a power to see, and not merely look at, the 
 vast array of the knowable. This comprehensiveness 
 makes greatness : through it a man may be the 
 spectator of all times and places. But he must 
 not hope to gain this comprehensive outlook by 
 occupying one solitary peak : he must not flatter 
 himself that there is an essence of all essences, 
 that he can condense all life and thought into one
 
 PREFACE vii 
 
 magic drop. On the contrary he must keep the 
 original wealth of material undiminished if he would 
 have a world in which ' life's garden blows ' ; if he 
 abstracts and simplifies the product is an ' essence,' 
 a drop of scent in place of the living flower. 
 
 This fact is gaining more recognition now than 
 it did some time ago. We do not always remember 
 that the necessity for emphasising the point was 
 not formerly so great as it has been recently. A 
 reading of Gassendi brings home to us the fact that 
 philosophy has not always considered concentration 
 its prime duty, and a return to the atmosphere 
 of naive pluralism is a refreshing reminder that 
 thought was once childishly unsophisticated. With 
 no intention of denying the value of the progress 
 that has been made, and no attempt to ignore 
 crudities and fallacies, we can still go back with 
 profit to a view of the world that is not obsessed 
 with the tendencies of extreme idealism : we can 
 even go back to the pre- Kantian days with profit 
 so long as we remember that they are pre-Kantian. 
 In some respects it is peculiarly profitable to see 
 what could be ^done with the material of knowledge 
 before Hume was sceptical or Kant awakened : in the 
 case of Gassendi the moderation and liberality of his 
 views makes him frequently strike the line to which 
 thought was destined to return, and thus appear in 
 close touch with later developments. In reference 
 to this I may add that the quotations from the 
 original have been limited as much as possible. As 
 the whole account is a mere summary the original 
 can be easily consulted, the chapters and divisions 
 of my account indicate the parts of the author which
 
 viii PREFACE 
 
 are being considered. But I have felt compelled to 
 insert quotations and phrases wherever there seemed 
 a possibility of confusion or grounds for suspecting 
 that the language used by me was not justified 
 by the original. In the parts of this book which 
 profess to contain the thoughts and ideas of Gassendi 
 I have aimed only at exhibiting those thoughts 
 and ideas with no more additions than were required 
 to bridge over gaps caused by omission and no 
 interpretation beyond what was demanded to make 
 clear the underlying connexions of the original 
 work. All references to previous philosophers and 
 interpretations of their meaning within that part 
 (i.e. Parts i. to m.) are to be credited to Gassendi. 
 My own remarks are only intended to set the 
 essential elements of Gassendi's philosophy in what 
 I conceive to be their true historical light.
 
 CONTENTS 
 
 PAoa 
 
 Introductory 
 
 The "Works of Gassendi ------ xi 
 
 Bibliography ..-----. xv 
 
 Introduction - - xvii 
 
 PAKT I. LOGIC 1 
 
 PAET II. PHYSICS 
 SECTION A 
 
 CHAP. 
 
 I. Introductory 19 
 
 II. Time and Space 34 
 
 III. First Principles 
 
 (a) The Material Principle 49 
 
 (6) Primary and Secondary Causes - - - 55 
 
 (c) Motion and Mutation ----- 59 
 
 (d) On Qualities ------- 65 
 
 (e) On the Origin and Decay of Things - - 82
 
 X CONTENTS 
 
 CHAP. PAGE 
 
 SECTION B 
 
 I. Ti[E Inanimate World 89 
 
 II. The Animate World 
 
 (a) Introductory 98 
 
 {b) On Design in Nature 100 
 
 (c) The Theory of the Soul 106 
 
 {d) The Anima Humana Ill 
 
 (e) The Basis of Psychic Life .... 115 
 
 III. Psychic Life 
 
 (a) Sense and Sensation 121 
 
 (6) Imagination 129 
 
 (c) Intellect and its Functions . . . . 139 
 
 {d) The Habits of Intellect 150 
 
 (e) The Passions 153 
 
 IV. The Nature of Life 
 
 (a) The Vis Motrix 161 
 
 (6) Life and Death 168 
 
 (c) The Constitution of Animals - - - - 172 
 
 PAKT III. ETHICS 
 
 I. On Happiness 183 
 
 II. The Virtues 196 
 
 III. On Liberty, Fate, and Divination - - - 2i8 
 
 IV. On God 224 
 
 NoTK on Declination 230 
 
 PART IV. GENERAL REVIEW 
 
 I. GaSSENDI 245 
 
 II. Later Views 270 
 
 Index 308
 
 THE WORKS OF GASSENDI 
 
 The following is a complete list of the contents of the 
 edition of 1658. 
 
 Volume I 
 
 Syntagma philosophicum. 
 
 Liber prooemialis. 
 
 Pars prima quae est logica. 
 
 I. De origine et varietate logica. 
 II. De logicae fine. 
 
 Institutio logica. 
 
 1. De simplice rerum imaginatione. 
 
 2. De propositi one. 
 
 3. De syllogismo. 
 
 4. De methodo. 
 
 Pars secunda quae est physica. 
 Section 1. 
 
 Book 1. De universe et mundo. 
 
 2. De loco et tempore. 
 
 3. De material! principio. 
 
 4. De principio efficiente. 
 
 5. De motu et mutatione rerum. 
 
 6. De qualitatibus rerum, 
 
 7. De ortu et interitu. 
 
 Section 2. De Eebus Caelestibus. 
 (End of Vol. I. pp. 752.)
 
 xii THE WORKS OF GASSENDI 
 
 Volume II 
 Syntagma philosophicum (continned). 
 
 Section 3. Part I. De rebus terrenis inanimis. 
 Book 1. De globo ipso telluris. 
 
 De vocatis vulgo meteoris (ventis, etc.). 
 De lapidibus ac metallis. 
 De plantis. 
 
 Part II. De rebus terrenis viventibus. 
 De varietate aninialium. 
 De partibus animalium. 
 De anima. 
 
 De generatione animalium. 
 De nvitritione. 
 De sensu universe. 
 De sensibus speciatim. 
 De phantasia. 
 De intellectu seu niente. 
 De appetitu et affectibus animae. 
 De vi motrice. 
 De temperie. 
 De vita et morte. 
 De animorum immortalitate. 
 
 ' Pars tertia quae est ethica. 
 Book 1. De felicitate. 
 „ 2. De virtutibus. 
 „ 3. De libertate, fortuna, etc. 
 (End of Vol. II. pp. 860.) 
 
 Volume III 
 
 1. Philosophiae Epicuri Syntagma. 
 
 2. Exercitationes paradoxicae adversus Aristoteleos. 
 
 3. Fluddanae philosophiae examen. 
 
 4. Disquisitio metaphysica adversus Cartesium. 
 5-9. Epistulae. 
 
 (End of Vol. III. pp. 662.) 
 
 2 
 
 I 3, 
 
 ,, 4, 
 
 Section 3. 
 
 Book 1. 
 
 2. 
 
 "„ 3, 
 
 ,, 4. 
 
 „ 5. 
 
 „ 6. 
 
 » 7. 
 
 „ 8. 
 
 „ 9. 
 
 „ 10. 
 
 „ 11. 
 
 „ 12. 
 
 „ 13. 
 
 „ 14.
 
 THE WORKS OF GASSENDI xiii 
 
 Volume IV 
 Astronomica. Parts I.-V. pp. 536. 
 
 Volume V 
 
 1. Diogenis Laertii Liber X, cum nova interpretatione et 
 
 notis. 
 
 2. Vita Epicuri, Peireskii, Tychonis Brahei, Copernici, 
 
 Peurbachii, et Kegioinontani. 
 
 3. Abacus sestertialis seu de valore antiquae monetae ad 
 
 nostram redactae. 
 
 4. Romanum Calendarium compendiose expositum. 
 
 5. Manuductio ad theoriam musices. 
 
 6. Notitia ecclesiae Diniensis. 
 
 (End of Vol. V. pp. 740.) 
 
 Volume VI 
 Epistulae et responsa. pp. 545. 
 
 The whole of Gassendi's writings is thus contained in 
 six Volumes folio, with a total of 4095 double-columned 
 pages.
 
 BIBLIOGRAPHY 
 
 (i.) The edition of the works to which reference is 
 always made in this book is the edition of 1658 (Lyon). 
 This contains all Gassendi's works (some slightly abridged), 
 except some letters. On this point see Thomas, p. 28 : 
 ' Celles qui ont et6 recueillies par M. de Montmor 
 forment le sixieme volume du Syntagma : mais leur 
 nombre a et6 considerablement augmente depuis, bien que 
 beaucoup restent encore a publier. (Voy. " Documents 
 inedits sur Gassendi," par Tamizey de Larroque : Revue 
 des questions historiques, 1877, t. xxii. " Oraison funebre 
 de P. Gassendi," par Nicolas Taxil, publiee par le meme, 
 1882. "Impressions de voyage de Pierre Gassendi," dans 
 le Bulletin de la SociM scientifique et liitSraire des Basses- 
 Alpes, 1887.)' I have no personal knowledge of these 
 documents. 
 
 (II.) Bernier, the traveller, a friend of Gassendi, com- 
 piled an Abr4g4 de la Philoso;phie dc Gassendi, 8 vols., 
 1678; 2nd ed., 7 vols., 1684. This work is naturally 
 far less cumbersome than Gassendi's own volumes. It 
 is difficult to say quite what is wrong with it, but it is 
 certainly wholly misleading, and, having been read to 
 avoid the trouble of studying the original, has done much 
 harm. I began with this work myself, but, after once 
 looking into Gassendi, abandoned it. There is a wholly 
 different atmosphere about Gassendi's writing, and perhaps 
 the kindest criticism is to say that Bernier had more 
 zeal as a friend than ability as a philosopher. 
 
 (ill.) The only book on Gassendi which I have read 
 is La Philosophie de Gassendi, par P.-F^lix Thomas, Paris,
 
 xvi BIBLIOGRAPHY 
 
 1889. I have read this since completing my own 
 account of (iassendi, and owe to it some useful hints and 
 references. Had it been other than it is, I should not 
 have been justified in publishing a second study on the 
 same subject. But the author seems to me to have done 
 less than justice to Gassendi : he does not seem to have 
 considered him an integral part of philosophy as a moving 
 body of thought. Perhaps he is right, but to me Gas- 
 sendi appears to have done more than patch up Epicurus : 
 he has tried to unite the results, not only of philosophy 
 in the narrower sense, but of all previous and contemporary 
 thought into one whole, as consistent as he thought it 
 could be. Hence we differ; but the student of Gassendi 
 will get more insight into Gassendi from Thomas than 
 he will from Bernier, and find this the conscientious 
 work of one who has gone for his information to the 
 fountain-head. 
 
 (IV.) For the rest, I know of no other ' literature of 
 the subject.' For the Life, Sorbiere's Sketch (vol. i.) is 
 the chief authority. There is also a Vie de Gassendi by 
 Bugerel (1737), and by Damiror {M4moire sur Gassendi, 
 1839). The best short account of Gassendi's philosophy 
 is that of Eitter, to which I have referred elsewhere 
 (p. 17). 
 
 (v.) The manuscripts of Gassendi have been preserved, 
 the majority at Tours, some in the Bibliotheque Rationale, 
 and some in Provence (Thomas, p. 28). The edition of 
 1658, though published after the author's death, repre- 
 sents his final corrections, and is acknowledged to be 
 substantially accurate.
 
 INTRODUCTION 
 
 The line of tliouo;ht which terminates in Gassendi 
 began in Leucippus. The principal names in the 
 history of its exposition are unfortunately little 
 more than names, and in the case of both the main 
 periods we are dependent on what may be called 
 the second strings for the majority of our information. 
 Thus of Leucippus we know but little, and he is 
 usually taken in conjunction with Democritus, in 
 order that together they may fill out a paragraph in 
 the history of thought : similarly, while we are better 
 off in the case of Epicurus, we none the less find 
 it most convenient not to speak of Epicurus but 
 of Epicureanism, and so give ourselves the lati- 
 tude of using all the matter that can be collected 
 from the whole school, in which the name of 
 Lucretius stands forth prominently. As we desire 
 to show the development of the subject we shall 
 here try to keep the main points of the different 
 epochs distinct : it will then be apparent how the 
 theory grew and changed in face of new problems 
 and changing conditions. 
 
 I. 
 
 Atomism and Epicureanism are very different 
 things, but the beginnings of the theory of Epi-
 
 xviii PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 cunis^ are to be found in the atomic school, and the 
 ditterences will be best understood if the growth 
 of that doctrine is followed. The founder was 
 Leucippus of Elea or Miletus. His standpoint does 
 not seem to have been properly understood by 
 historians of philosophy, but recent investigation 
 has cleared our views on the significance of his 
 lano-uage. He was in the first instance an Eleatic, 
 and though the main principle of the Eleatic school, 
 the unity and immovability of the One, seems so 
 entirely opposed to the atomistic trend of thought 
 that they could have nothing to do with each 
 other, we find that in fact the opposition is not 
 so great as appears at first sight, and the atomistic 
 view is generated out of the Eleatic. In this 
 interpretation we are guided by Aristotle, who says, 
 ' Leucippus however thought he had a theory which 
 was in harmony with sense-perception and did not 
 do away with coming into being and passing 
 away, nor motion nor the multiplicity of things. 
 He made this concession to experience, while he 
 conceded on the other hand to those who invented 
 the One, that motion was impossible without the 
 void, that the void was not real, and that nothino; 
 of what was real was not real ! For,' said he, 
 ' that which is strictly speaking real is an absolute 
 plenum ; but the plenum is not one. On the 
 
 ^Gasseudi says Epicurus was neither 'Primus nee solus qui 
 Atomos defenderit.' Others are Mosohus — 'de quo Empiricus et 
 Strabo etiam ante bellum Troianum' — Leucippus, Democritus, Metro- 
 dorus, Ecphantus, Pythagoreus, Empedocles, Heracleitus, Plato (qui 
 Enipedoclis instar, elementa coniposuit ex particulis prae exilitate 
 inc<jnspicuis) Xenocrates, Asclepiades, Heraclides, Diodorus, Arte- 
 midorus, Mnesitheus, alii' (vi. 160). Truly a cloud of witnesses.
 
 INTRODUCTIOxN xix 
 
 contrary, there are an infinite number of them, and 
 they are invisible owing to the smalluess of their 
 bulk. They move in the void (for there is a 
 void), and by their coming together they effect 
 coming into being : by their separation, passing 
 away.' ^ 
 
 Atomism is thus at its birth the opposite which 
 Eleaticism generates : the principles of Parmenides 
 are retained, but the One to which they are applied 
 is no longer the only One, not the Whole, but a 
 whole : ' to each of the atoms which he thus 
 arrived at, he ascribed all the predicates of the 
 Eleatic One' (Burnet, 079. cit. 355). The result 
 was a pluralism which avoided the dialectic of 
 Zeno of Elea : the attempts which had been made 
 to combine the two notions of a continuum and 
 divisibility had failed because they inevitably led 
 to the abyss of endless division : it was obvious 
 that if the continuum could be divided anywhere 
 it could be divided everywhere and finally elude 
 us altogether, and there was no way out of the 
 difficulty but to stand by common sense and declare 
 the ultimate indivisible. Two points are interesting 
 in this connexion : t-he first is the fact that the 
 earliest form of Atomism is grounded in the 
 opposition of a commonsense view to its con- 
 temporary idealism, a heritage of strife to be handed 
 on from generation to generation : the second is 
 the very partial nature of the severance from 
 idealistic modes of thought;/^ At this stage of 
 thought no one blushes to make reality a predicate, 
 but the limitations of language bring us to a 
 
 ^ For Leucippus v. Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy.
 
 XX PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 dilemma: the void is declared real and not real, 
 and the difficulty lies in the substantive use of 
 ' is ' : for the void is, but is not what is called 
 real : it must therefore belong to a class of existents 
 which we shall call the not-real : with all the 
 sturdy commonsense of a reformer Leucippus 
 says the categories must be made for the things 
 and not things for the category. Henceforth the 
 old reality was to be absorbed into a new Reality 
 which included both the real and the not-real of the 
 former category. The gist of all this argumentation 
 can be expressed in the phrase 'the non-corporeal 
 is as real as the corporeal.' This was first pro- 
 claimed by those who are usually regarded as 
 materialists ! For the rest we know that creation 
 was explained through the collision of the atoms, 
 in which atoms of like shape and form became 
 entangled, and from these entanglements of atoms 
 arose the heavenly bodies. Thus much we may 
 safely attribute to Leucippus, and if any one doubts 
 the reality of Leucippus, it is enough for our 
 purpose that he should stand for Atomism before 
 Democritus. This stage must certainly be dis- 
 tinguished, else we lose the significance of that 
 form of the doctrine in which we have as yet no 
 subjective elements and no attempt to think of 
 the atom as in any sense analysable. 
 
 II. 
 
 With Democritus w^e find atomism has undergone 
 a very important change, it has developed from a 
 mere sketch of a cosmogony to at least the 
 rudiments of a philosophy. By this we mean that
 
 INTRODUCTION xxi 
 
 it recognises a far wider range of topics, and at 
 least attempts to give explanations of phenomena 
 not touched by the theory in its original form. 
 The two main influences to be noticed in this 
 connection are those denoted by the names of 
 Protagoras and Anaxagoras. From Protagoras 
 comes the subjective tendency of the doctrine, 
 while the work of Anaxagoras has brought into 
 prominence the question of causality and its 
 incidence. The idea of ' homoiomerae ' has also 
 expressed a possible theory of the nature of the 
 ultimate parts of the material world which is 
 sufficiently near to atomism to compel the true 
 atomist to define his position more exactly. 
 
 In opposition to Anaxagoras, Democritus expressly 
 makes things themselves the cause of motion : 
 whatever else it may have meant, the ' nous ' of 
 Anaxagoras implied a cause outside of the material 
 thing. This dualism is now rejected, and we get 
 the explicit statement that the world is to be 
 regarded as a product of matter in motion. The 
 atoms are now said to differ in shape, order, and 
 position : they have no cause, being eternal : they 
 possess motion from the beginning by virtue of 
 their nature, and this motion is in the abstract 
 straight ; but in fact, owing to collision, it becomes 
 rotatory. It is difficult to say whether Democritus 
 ascribed weight to the atoms or not : this w^as the 
 sort of detail which was only specifically settled 
 when an opponent made it necessary to give a 
 deliverance ex cathedra. Wallace remarks on this 
 point : ' There are passages from which it seems 
 that Democritus regarded weight as not an attribute
 
 xxii PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 of the atoms, but only of tlie aggregations which 
 they compose. But probably these statements are 
 to be taken in a different sense. They may mean 
 that the atom in all cases, however it may vary 
 in size (and such variations are incalculably great), 
 never reaches a size which can be seen by the bodily 
 eye, and therefore, inasmuch as the weight varies 
 directly with the size in the case of the atoms, 
 the atom is never ponderable except when it 
 combines with other atoms to form a body.' It 
 follows from this that the atom has weight but 
 is not ponderable, and this is, I think, correct for 
 two reasons. In the first place, it would be much 
 more difficult to conceive the atoms as falling 
 (which is the first conception of their motion) 
 if they had no weight in theory ; and secondly, 
 it is always a principle of this school to work 
 analogically and infer from the presence of a 
 quality in the compound its analogical counterpart 
 in the primary parts which enter into that compound. 
 
 The compounds are formed by the natural union 
 of similar particles. This was a point on which 
 considerable stress was laid because it was in 
 direct opposition to the mythical tendencies of 
 the Love and Hate theories of affinity : it was 
 a part of the polemic against all mysticism which 
 was to become characteristic of the spirit of this 
 school. 
 
 With regard to the universe Democritus held 
 that the Earth had now come to rest : from the 
 Earth there had arisen by natural j)rocesses organised 
 beings. The soul was composed of atoms of the 
 nature of fire. The individual is conceived as
 
 INTRODUCTION xxiii 
 
 having specific organs each with its appointed 
 functions ; but these are very crudely differentiated : 
 the soul is in the head, and its function is thouglit : 
 eagerness is in the heart and desire in the liver. 
 Perception is caused by the effluxes ' sloughed 
 off ' from things : it is not wholly veracious and 
 requires to be corrected. Sense perception is indeed 
 explicitly opposed to the understanding, and the 
 latter is said to give us truth while the former 
 deceives. But this is not to be taken as implying 
 any very exact theory of knowledge : it is very 
 much the same to Democritus whether the deception 
 of the senses is due to physical conditions, such 
 as the distance of the object, or to what we 
 should call subjective conditions. In the same 
 elementary fashion we are told that we know 
 nothing, though we can go beyond our senses, 
 as we obviously do in arriving at a knowledge 
 of the atom ; a going beyond which is probably 
 most safely taken to mean reaching quantitatively 
 further, that is to say reaching to subtler forms of 
 matter than are given to the gross sense. 
 
 In his ethics Democritus is credited with having 
 uttered or quoted much that is sound ; but it is 
 too disjointed to be regarded as either system or 
 part of a system. We may note for further use 
 that he considered the soul the noblest part of 
 man and knowledge the source of true happiness : 
 he also laid stress on the will as the test of true 
 morality, and struck the keynote of later cosmo- 
 politanism in the saying that the country of the 
 wise man is the world.
 
 xxiv PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 III. 
 
 With Epicurus we come to a much more developed 
 phase of the original doctrine. At first we had 
 only a slender vein of cosmological reasoning : then 
 the theory was extended to psychology of a sort, 
 with an appendix on ethics to give it the appearance 
 of a full-grown theory : now ethics is made the prime 
 end and object of the philosophical treatment of 
 the world in which we live, and atomism is taken 
 as the guiding principle. There is considerable 
 difference between a theory of atoms and an atomic 
 theory of the universe : we shall be concerned 
 chiefly with the philosophical aspects as opposed 
 to what might be called the scientific elements, 
 and therefore for us it is especially important to 
 notice this phase and realise how the original 
 aims and scope of atomism were changed with 
 time, so that it became an instrument for general 
 us rather than a mere statement of what was 
 believed to be physical fact. 
 
 In order to understand the scope of a writer's 
 views we have to take some account of the 
 atmosphere in which he lived. In the case of the 
 earliest writers this is generally only possible in 
 the sense that we can detect some definite influence 
 against which he works : thus Leucippus founds 
 himself on and opposes himself to Parmenides : 
 Democritus takes up the very problem Anaxagoras 
 has striven to solve and finds in that opposite his 
 own definition. When we come to Epicurus, the 
 same principle holds good, but the stream of 
 thought has widened, and it bears along with it
 
 INTRODUCTION xxv 
 
 the sand of many shores, and therefore the influences 
 we have to consider are greater both in number 
 and range. 
 
 The first influence to be considered is that of the 
 political conditions under which the doctrine arose and 
 to which we trace the temper that made its appeal 
 so successful. At the time when Epicurus came to 
 Athens (307 B.C.), the prevailing characteristic of 
 life was its uncertainty. The city was a hotbed 
 of intrigue, and no one could predict which party 
 would be in power next. Athens had lost her 
 empire but still retained enough vitality to struggle 
 periodically into a semblance of independent exist- 
 ence under such a leader as Demetrius Ppliorcetes. 
 At other times the Macedonian power regained 
 its supremacy and Athens lapsed into vassalage. 
 In either case the situation of the individual was 
 much the same, and from this point of view the 
 days of Epicurus and of Seneca are identical. ^^ 
 both the individual, finding no objective point of 
 attachment, falls back upon himself, and the attitude 
 of the Epicurean in Athens is that of the Stoic in 
 Rome four hundred years later. With the upbreak 
 of a concentrated national life, the individual felt 
 that he belonged to nobody in the sense that he 
 belonged to himself, and nothing belonged to him 
 in the sense that his self belonged to him. Hence 
 the thinker keeps aloof from politics : he says 
 with Democritus, that the world is the wise man's 
 home ; but only in the negative sense, which means 
 abstraction from that immediate world of interests 
 in which alone is there a possibility of activity. 
 The first phase of cosmopolitanism is negative :
 
 xxvi PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 it renounces the living unity for a One which is 
 no more than a concept, which, having nothing 
 that can satisfy the heart, is for all practical 
 purposes nothing but a shroud for the burial of 
 hopes that have been sacrificed. Ignoring the 
 Whole, man turns to the parts, and the individual 
 occupies the first place in his thoughts. 
 
 Philosophically we can trace the same develop- 
 ment on different lines. Plato had been concerned 
 primarily with the scheme of the Whole as a 
 rational connected system. With Aristotle the 
 material of the system had emerged into prominence, 
 and his successors had gone still further, and ' the 
 speculative, transcendental element was eliminated, 
 and nothing left but "positive" science.'^ This 
 trend became more and more pronounced, and to it 
 we may trace the revival of materialistic types of 
 thought which are exemplified in both Stoicism and 
 Epicureanism. A third element is the consequence 
 of these influences, namely the importance attached 
 to ethics, ' if by ethics we mean an attempt to 
 discover what is the chief end of man, and how it 
 can be attained. ' " 
 
 These three points, then, ' their individualism in 
 morals, their subordination of all science to an 
 ethical end, and their materialistic realism,' are the 
 common characteristics of the great schools of this 
 period. We shall confine ourselves now to sketching 
 the main points of Epicureanism. The sources of 
 information are scattered, and it is difficult, if not 
 impossible, to say in many cases what was actually 
 taught by Epicurus and what was incorporated into 
 
 ^Wallace, Epicureanism, p. 6. '^ Ibid. p. 16.
 
 INTRODUCTION xxvii 
 
 the body of the doctrine by his disciples. For our 
 purpose it is sufficient to give a summary of the 
 teaching ascribed to Epicurus, merely noting those 
 details which we know were added later. The chief 
 source of information, apart from reports of Epicurus' 
 own teaching, is, of course, Lucretius : Gassendi's 
 version is not taken into consideration directly be- 
 •cause of the obvious danger of mixing his accbunt 
 of Epicurus with the views he proposed to graft 
 on the old stem. Epicurus divides the sphere of 
 thought into the three parts — Logic, Physics, and 
 Ethics : these headings we may as well preserve, 
 though examination of the details will show that 
 some of the subject-matter would hardly be so 
 classified now. 
 
 {a) The subjective sceptical element in the 
 philosophy of the period is reflected by the Logic 
 of Epicurus in the demand for a doctrine of criteria 
 of truth. The criteria enumerated are perceptions 
 and representations in the theoretical sphere, and 
 pleasure and pain in the practical. These form 
 the subject of the Canonica or doctrine of norms. 
 The idea in the mind of Epicurus is that we must 
 build entirely on the senses : these are in themselves 
 true and final in the sense that nothing can be 
 found to give us certainty when they fail. But he 
 also recognises that the mental life of the individual 
 goes beyond the exact moment during which the 
 sensation lasts ; and the persistent residue of the 
 sensation has also its function in the life of thought. 
 Hence he adds to the immediate sense-perception 
 the representations which are also called anticipations. 
 As criteria these must be regarded as bringing in
 
 xxviii PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 the elements of time and plurality. Epicurus does 
 not say in so many words tliat this is so, but a 
 moment's reflection on the use of these represen- 
 tations proves it. They are stored in the mind 
 and emerge into consciousness when the name of 
 the thing is uttered : moreover they function in the 
 strict capacity of norms in as much as they regulate 
 perceptions. 'To enable us to affirm that what 
 we see at a distance is a horse or an ox, we must 
 have some preconception in our minds which makes 
 us acquainted with the form of a horse and an 
 ox ' ; from which it is clear that the preconception 
 or secondary mental activity forms a standard of 
 reference to which we may return for a judgment 
 (criterium) on the presentation. This does not 
 upset the dogma that the perception as an affair 
 of the senses is always true : it merely tells us 
 how we may find out what the senses are, as it 
 were, trying to tell us. 
 
 From this stage we go a step further in the 
 formation of Opinion w^hich results from the presence 
 of the permanent residues in our minds. These 
 opinions may be true or false, and the natural 
 test is a return to experience. The opinion may 
 refer to the future or to the occult : in the former 
 case the test of direct experience is merely held 
 in abeyance. In the latter we have a problem, 
 for the opinion may be true but there is no way 
 of getting any collateral support : for this Epicurus 
 provides a negative justification in so far as we 
 are allowed to hold the opinion as true if no 
 contradictory evidence is forthcoming. 
 
 This constitutes the gist of the pure canonic of
 
 INTRODUCTION xxix 
 
 Epicurus, but we may add to this some notes on 
 the method employed by the Epicureans and the 
 theory of knowledge implied in them. In the 
 first place the criticism which Ueberweg makes 
 upon the idea that the immediate sensation is 
 reality, should be noticed. ' The hallucinations of 
 the insane, even, and dreams are true : for they 
 produce an impression, which the non-existing 
 could not do. It is obvious in connection with 
 this latter argument, that in Epicurus' conception 
 of truth, the latter, in the sense of agreement of the 
 psychical image with a real ^object, is confounded 
 with psychical reality.' JPIiis is undoubtedly true 
 as pointing out that tlie Epicurean doctrine did 
 not properly distinguish logical and psychological 
 certainty. The entire emphasis is thrown on the 
 psychological groundwork of knowledge, and in 
 consequence the explanation of the attainment of 
 any knowledge beyond the sense-given is neglected 
 to an extent which is wholly unjustifiable in view 
 of the fact that the atom itself is not a sense-datuny 
 This deficiency was apparently felt by such disciples 
 as Zeno and Philodemus, who attempted to give 
 some theory of induction. But, whether they 
 could justify it or not, the Epicureans did get 
 from the known to the unknown : moreover they 
 made no secret of it, but declared that the true 
 process of knowledge was from known to unknown. 
 In addition to induction they also made great 
 use of analogy and, surreptitiously, of deduction. 
 We now have from the Herculanean manuscripts 
 clear proof that analogy was not only used by the 
 Epicurean but itself a direct object of analysis :
 
 XXX PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 Lucretius made use of it in a manner that has 
 been described as ' violent ' ; and it remained in 
 the school as one of the prime instruments in the 
 advancement of knowledge. In addition to this 
 there were one or two first principles which 
 occasionally come into active service and justify 
 a deductive procedure. The most notable is the 
 dogma ' ex nihilo nihil,' to which must be added 
 the regulative principle that nothing happens by 
 chance. The former of these rules is most 
 frequently used to justify a regress from a 
 comj)ound to its parts : for, it is said, if the whole 
 has such and such qualities the parts must have 
 these qualities though they may not be directly 
 observable in the parts themselves. The most 
 striking use of this principle is the passage where 
 Lucretius asserts that the atoms must have the 
 power of free action,' ^ since we find that power 
 in that complex of atoms called the soul. The 
 use of analogy is best exhibited in the construction 
 of the concept of the gods and their mode of life. 
 (h) In dealing with the physics it will be 
 convenient to divide it into physics proper and 
 psychology. The Epicurean would doubtless have 
 denied that psychology was not physics 'proper,' 
 but the mixture is rather confusins; to the modern 
 mind. First then, as to physics proper. We have, 
 the mise en scene of Democritus, a vast place bound- 
 less in every direction, full of atoms too small to be 
 visible, from whose conjunctions will arise all the 
 manifold life of this and other worlds. While 
 agreeing in the main with Democritus, Epicurus 
 
 ^ Usually called ' free-will,' but see p. 230, Note on Declination.
 
 INTRODUCTION xxxi 
 
 diverges from his teaching in some details. With 
 regard to the motion of the atoms he attributes the 
 abandonment of the original line of movement 
 which was conceived as in a straight line downward, 
 to the voluntary swerving of the atoms. This is 
 the most striking example of the subordination 
 of physics to ethics, for the difference between 
 Democritus and Epicurus consists in just this, that 
 Democritus tried to settle the question of the 
 nature of the atomic movements from what he 
 knew of the mechanical laws : Epicurus directly 
 opposes himself to the mechanical laws of motion 
 in order to get a basis for the admission of free- 
 agency. It is, in all probability, a mistake to 
 say that Epicurus gave his atoms anything like 
 free-will or spontaneity as we should understand 
 it now : we have to keep in view the fact that 
 the mind to which that free-will has to be referred 
 would be formulated in terms of matter, and there- 
 fore all that is required is that the motion of 
 matter should not be regarded as fixed from all 
 eternity : if it is so fixed, my motion counts for 
 nothing : if not, my motion is itself a real factor ; 
 and if I am conscious that I move, I may also 
 be sure that my movement is the factor which 
 produces the result that follows. This is an 
 extremely interesting phase of what was later 
 to be the ' free-will ' controversy : the difficulty of 
 understanding it and the temptation to misunderstand 
 it, lies in the ideas of choice which we introduce : 
 we ask, 'Am I free to choose, am I free to be 
 what I am ? ' but before ideas of God and the 
 last judgment came in to produce these subjective
 
 xxxii PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 problems, the question of freedom was naturally 
 limited to the simple problem, ' Am I in my activity 
 a real agent?' and it is for this real agency that 
 Epicurus makes room.^ 
 
 A second point of difference is also of great 
 interest. So far our atom has been the ultimate : 
 it is itself beyond the senses and reached by 
 thought, yet it is conceived as sensuous inasmuch 
 as it might be presented to a sense acute enough 
 to detect it. Latent in the fact that the atom is 
 reached by an intellectual process, lies the possibility 
 of that development of the concept of the atom 
 as a concept, which we get in Leibnitz ; and in 
 Epicurus we do get so far as the acknowledgment 
 that the atom is logically divisible, this being 
 considered necessary for the explanation of variety 
 in shape. It is significant of the character of 
 thought at this period that it could employ a 
 principle that carried it beyond its own ultimate 
 unit, and yet never enquire whether the process 
 was a mere dividing of matter or a revelation of 
 the nature of thought and its categories. 
 
 In the construction of the world out of the 
 atoms Epicurus does more to tell us how it was 
 not done than how it was : his whole object is 
 to show that design has no share in the work, 
 there is no awful Power guiding and controlling 
 things : nature manages its own afiairs in perfect 
 contentment, and this spectre of a Providence is 
 nothing but the creation of the human imagination. 
 Out of dead matter comes life, and out of life 
 when it is sufficiently advanced comes consciousness. 
 
 ^v. Note, p. 239.
 
 I 
 
 INTRODUCTION xxxiii 
 
 Lucretius thinks that the phenomena of deep sleep 
 and swooning prove that life is motion, and it 
 must be allowed that he does not compromise his 
 orthodoxy by any truck with the sub-conscious ; but 
 regarding the motion of matter as the substratum 
 of conscious life, he consented when he lost hold 
 on consciousness to drop back into the region of 
 moving matter. The soul and the body form a 
 unity, so that the dissolution of death is annihilation 
 of the Self. This dreary prospect seems to have 
 been a comfort on the whole, both to the Greek 
 and the Eoman philosopher, which seems to be a 
 sufficiently severe expression of their views on the 
 charms of the life they led on earth ! 
 
 (c) On the border line, none too clearly defined, 
 of the physics and the psychology, comes the 
 question of the constitution of the soul, which we 
 ascribe to the psychology because the chief interest 
 centres on the question of the thinking part. 
 ' According to the statements given both by 
 Diogenes Laertius and Lucretius, the soul is a 
 complex of elements from air, fire, and wind, and 
 a fourth unnamed element. The last, which is the 
 difiierentiating constituent of the mind, suggests 
 that it is postulated by the feeling that there is 
 more in the psychical than physical analogies 
 altogether explain. And further, the introduction of 
 air, fire, and wind suggests that Epicurus supple- 
 ments the stricter atomic theory of Democritus by 
 additions from the early physicists who identify 
 the soul with air, or fire, or wind ; and from 
 Aristotle, in whose system the combination of the 
 four principles of cold, hot, wet, and dry played
 
 xxxiv PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 a main part, as explaining the processes of nature.' 
 The first elements are to be taken as composing 
 the anima, the fourth constitutes the animus. 
 This animus is the seat of will and thought in 
 Lucretius. The will we know, on the evidence of 
 direct experience, is free; but it should be noticed in 
 connection with what is said above, that its action 
 begins in the heart. Epicurus seems to have 
 regarded the breast as the seat of the rational soul, 
 a distinctly retrograde movement after Democritus 
 had placed it in the head. 
 
 With regard to the psychological activities, these 
 must be interpreted in a materialistic sense. The 
 secondary qualities have a material counterpart in 
 the existence of the finer particles which are the 
 cause of their perception : even the gods are known 
 by effluxes. 'This doctrine of sense-perception is 
 in a w^ay only part of a larger doctrine which has 
 important and direct bearings on the moral theory. 
 ,In the first place, not merely do the skins shed by 
 the objects around us meet the eye now ; but even 
 long after the objects to which they may have 
 belonged have ceased to exist, these phantom husks 
 float about the world. Thus it happens that the 
 forms of the departed may visit us long after their 
 decease.' Thus Epicurus combined with his denial 
 of spiritualism as a theory of the existence of dis- 
 embodied personalities a materialistic spiritism to 
 account for ghosts. This is another instance of the 
 way that physical theories may be dictated by 
 extraneous ideas, and is really an example of the 
 practical application of the view that ethical con- 
 siderations come first. For the advantage of the
 
 INTRODUCTION xxxv 
 
 view is that it permits those visions of gods and 
 divine beings which come to us in the night seasons, 
 and brighten our world with pictures of a blessedness 
 above and beyond our present attainments. How 
 such ideas could be of use to us as moral incentives 
 if we realised that the beings so revealed were not 
 personal, is a question we naturally ask now, but 
 get no answer from Epicureanism. 
 
 On the whole we may characterise this as a 
 theory of imagination. In it the intellect gets little 
 attention : even the ' imaginative impressions of the 
 intellect ' are to be taken as literally impressions. 
 If they are real they are effects, and all effects 
 have a cause which expresses itself in motion and 
 must therefore be in some sense material. The only 
 concession allowed to the intellectual impressions is 
 that they point to agents more subtle than those 
 which appeal to the senses. In one respect we have 
 traces of a less materialistic view of mental processes. 
 A certain degree of mental activity is implied in 
 the concession that we can form for ourselves fresh 
 ideas by ' new syntheses of sensations ' ; but the 
 suggestion is worth very little so long as we are 
 not expressly told whether this is or is not more 
 than a secondary movement of the particles of the 
 mind and purely mechanical. It avails nothing to 
 say that they are voluntary, for we have already 
 seen that any talk about the will carries us away 
 from Epicureanism if we venture to think of it as 
 other than materialistic in its nature. 
 
 I will close this summary of the main features 
 of Epicureanism with a passage from the work to 
 which I have already referred again and again : it
 
 xxxvi PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 expresses what I take to be the truth about Epicurus 
 in words that cannot be bettered.^ 'If we have 
 rightly understood Epicurus, he has simply ignored 
 the ego and consciousness and turned solely to 
 externality. He has adopted the attitude of science 
 and not of philosophy. He has fairly enough em- 
 ployed the ordinary conceptions of matter to explain 
 the processes of growth, nutrition, and sensation. 
 If not an adequate mode of conceiving these pro- 
 cesses, it has, at least for most minds, the merit of 
 affording an easy and simple rationale of them. 
 But as a philosopher he should have gone further. 
 His only answer, however, to the question, " What 
 are we ? " is, that we are what we see, and, if our 
 vision were expanded, might see. Each of us is an 
 object of sensitive and intellectual vision : of the 
 other fact that each is a subject, he says nothing. 
 And by a subject is not meant merely that each of 
 us is active as well as passive. For that matter 
 the same may be said of every piece of corporeal 
 substance in the universe : activity and passivity 
 are the very characteristics of existence in its every 
 shape. But in each of us there is the further element 
 of consciousness, sentiment, feeling, will, and know- 
 ledge. Of this Epicurus has no other explanation 
 than to say that it is nothing separable from certain 
 combinations of molecules, and may even be treated 
 as a mere aggregation of ethereal atoms.' 
 
 IV. 
 
 Between the days of Lucretius and the age of 
 Gassendi lie seventeen hundred years filled with 
 
 ^ W. Wallace, Epicureanism.
 
 INTRODUCTION xxxvii 
 
 the strife of minds and marked by much real 
 progress. The historians of philosophy have linked 
 together its different epochs, and he who would 
 comprehend how much was done in that time to 
 solve our human problems must turn to the 
 pages of the professed historian. He will find there 
 two main influences controlling the whole advance : 
 on the one hand, the theological and speculative 
 thinking of the patristic and scholastic periods : 
 on the other, the scientific trend of thought which 
 is most marked where Arabian influences pre- 
 dominate. These lines tend to converge, but there 
 are certain well-defined conditions which make 
 Faith and Science at present incapable of harmony. 
 Under these conditions, equally predominant in 
 modern times, the two parties present themselves 
 as rival claimants for the different areas within 
 the Kingdom of Thought : tract after tract was 
 claimed and lost or won by the alien forces of 
 reason, experience, or science. The real difficulty 
 for Dogma arose from the fact that it had assumed 
 control over regions of thought in which its forces 
 could never hold their own : its losses were rarely 
 such as could endanger its final stronghold ; but 
 every proof of decaying power was regarded as 
 hastening the final catastrophe. In the mean time 
 the two claimants establish a right to two kinds 
 of subjects : science claims to rule on all that can 
 be presented to the senses, dogma on all the 
 hyperphysical realities. With the main classes thus 
 determined, the discussion turns on the question 
 as to what is to be included under either head. 
 Slowly but surely the content of dogmatic philosophy
 
 xxxviii PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 is drained away until a daring spirit like Bruno 
 openly declares that the Bible is meant to teach 
 morals only — not physics. The growth of a non- 
 dogmatic philosophy is followed by a growth of 
 the spirit of enquiry itself. At first the opposition 
 to dogmatism takes the form of confronting theory 
 with fact ; this especially affected the authority 
 which grounded itself on Aristotle as one who is 
 above criticism, and proved most damaging wherever 
 the investigation of nature came into collision 
 with dogmatic deliverances on what ought to be 
 or happen in the physical world. As typical of 
 this collision between observation and groundless 
 theorising Galileo may be cited. But while we 
 speak of this as an awakening and as the triumph 
 of physics over metaphysics, it is necessary to 
 remember that the spirit of critical enquiry was 
 not yet freed from the matter to which it most 
 naturally allied itself: it w^as universally regarded 
 as applicable to all matter alike. A vigorous mind 
 like that of Valla might carry critical principles 
 from the sphere of the sciences into history : a 
 Montaigne might arise to suggest that even 
 Christianity was not beyond criticism ; but it was 
 still possible, or rather natural, for men to feel 
 that the hidden mysteries were a thing apart, 
 that the realities of faith must remain behind the 
 veil of the temple. For this reason it is incorrect 
 to suppose that those who still acknowledge the 
 rights of Faith are necessarily insincere, merely 
 compromising their beliefs to avoid public censure. 
 Much that is commonplace now was boldly original 
 in the sixteenth century ; and the boldness of
 
 INTRODUCTION 
 
 XXXIX 
 
 originality is not to be measured only by the 
 extent to which physical safety is jeopardised : it 
 must be measured also by the mental strain which 
 it involves and the feeling which comes to every 
 sincere mind that the opinion of the many may 
 have more truth than the individual perceives. 
 The foolish can have the courage of their convictions 
 and rush in where the angels have feared to tread : 
 the wise find their courage more severely taxed in 
 the attainment of convictions. Where the struggle 
 ends in some grand renunciation it gains our 
 applause : where it ends in the belief that neither 
 extreme is right we feel that it is less noble, less 
 brilliant, and too often do injustice to the temperate 
 soul not knowing that its refinement is of fire. 
 
 Such was the age in which Gassendi appeared, 
 tinged already with a deeper scepticism, but on the 
 whole not yet grappling with the final questions. 
 If we may judge from the face portrayed in the 
 Frontispiece of the edition of 1658, he was a genial 
 kindly soul, not given to brawling but yet filled 
 with the temper that resists wrong. Ah the con- 
 troversy with Descartes he showed his qualities 
 explicitly^ r at first he shuns the arena : once en- 
 gaged, ne stiffens against the onset of the enemy ; 
 his temper rises with the progress of the battle, 
 yet never so as to confuse hand or eye : the 
 opponent grows impatient, speaks hastily and rashly, 
 but he sharpens the pen again and pursues without 
 swerving the relentless analysis. Such was the 
 man when pitted against a worthy foe, yet it was 
 peace he loved, not war. His Epicureanism was of 
 the lofty type : ease and pleasure have their rights.
 
 xl PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 but they exist only as parts in a life that is 
 unified by a great purpose : they are the condi- 
 mentum vitae ; not the things on which we live, 
 but the temper that leavens the whole. Such a 
 frame of mind is only distinguished from Stoicism 
 by great liberality in the interpretation of life and 
 a greater ability to compromise. Some spirits break 
 rather than bend : his could bend in season, and 
 when after the strife Descartes came to him in 
 days of sickness as a friend, he thought it no 
 shame to forgive and to forget. 
 
 The facts of Gassendi's life are well known. 
 Born on Jan. 22nd, 1592, at Champtercier, near 
 Digne, in Provence, he went to the College of 
 Digne at an early age, and, like many of the 
 great thinkers of his day, combined linguistic with 
 mathematical studies, and was equally successful in 
 both. He must have been something of an infant 
 prodigy, for in his sixteenth year he was invited to 
 lecture. From Digne he went to Aix and studied 
 philosophy under Fesaye, returning in 1612 to 
 Digne as lecturer in Theology. Four years later 
 (1616) he became Doctor of Theology and was 
 ordained the following year. 
 
 Gassendi had now definitely entered the Church ; 
 but from this time his interest in Theology seems 
 to have waned. He returned to Aix for a short 
 time to lecture on philosophy, and though appointed 
 to a canonry at Grenoble, continued to devote 
 himself to the reform of Philosophy. In 1624 he 
 was persuaded to publish his criticisms of Aristo- 
 telianism, a work which had its origin in the 
 criticisms which he was in the habit of appending
 
 INTRODUCTION xU 
 
 to his formal expositions when lecturing at Aix. 
 The Exercitationes Paradoxicae adversus AHs- 
 toteleos were never finished. In this year (1624) 
 Book I. was published, and a fragment of Book ii. 
 was afterwards added in the collected works. A 
 note appended to this Fragment tells us that the 
 author abandoned the work after readino; the Pei^- 
 patetica of Franciscus Patricius. The part that 
 was published aroused considerable animosity, and 
 drew public attention at, once to the author's abilities 
 and mental attitude. /-Originality was not Gassendi's 
 strong point, and he showed in this work that his 
 strength lay in combining the ideas of others so as 
 to make them more effective^ In one respect the 
 work marks an epoch in his life : henceforth his 
 attitude toward Aristotle is defined by the declara- 
 tion that the Stagirite is to be taken as guide but 
 not worshipped as master and lord. In this, as 
 in other respects, his aim is not to be ' aut nimium 
 credulus aut parum plus' (vi. 172). While the 
 work of Patricius relieved him from the necessity 
 of pursuing these critical essays, he was also 
 enlightened by their efiect. He now saw that a 
 merely destructive criticism did little but raise the 
 dust. The true answer to existing systems could 
 only be made in another system which should include 
 in itself the whole range of human activity and 
 compel the thoughts of men to look at the Universe 
 as a whole./ Thus began the scheme of the Syn- 
 tagma, on which at least twenty years of labour 
 were expended. With a training in mathematics 
 supplemented by considerable knowledge of the 
 cognate sciences, of medicine also and such biology
 
 xl PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 but they exist only as parts in a life that is 
 unified by a great purpose : they are the condi- 
 mentum vitae ; not the things on which we live, 
 but the temper that leavens the whole. Such a 
 frame of mind is only distinguished from Stoicism 
 by great liberality in the interpretation of life and 
 a greater ability to compromise. Some spirits break 
 rather than bend : his could bend in season, and 
 when after the strife Descartes came to him in 
 days of sickness as a friend, he thought it no 
 shame to forgive and to forget. 
 
 The facts of Gassendi's life are well known. 
 Born on Jan. 22nd, 1592, at: Champtercier, near 
 Digne, in Provence, he went to the College of 
 Digne at an early age, and, like many of the 
 great thinkers of his day, combined linguistic with 
 mathematical studies, and was equally successful in 
 both. He must have been something of an infant 
 prodigy, for in his sixteenth year he was invited to 
 lecture. From Digne he went to Aix and studied 
 philosophy under Fesaye, returning in 1612 to 
 Digne as lecturer in Theology. Four years later 
 (1616) he became Doctor of Theology and was 
 ordained the following year. 
 
 Gassendi had now definitely entered the Church ; 
 but from this time his interest in Theology seems 
 to have waned. He returned to Aix for a short 
 time to lecture on philosophy, and though appointed 
 to a canonry at Grenoble, continued to devote 
 himself to the reform of Philosophy. In 1624 he 
 was persuaded to publish his criticisms of Aristo- 
 telianism, a work which had its origin in the 
 criticisms which he was in the habit of appending
 
 INTRODUCTION xli 
 
 to his formal expositions when lecturing at Aix. 
 The Exercitationes Paradoxicae adversus Aris- 
 toteleos were never finished. In this year (1624) 
 Book I. was published, and a fragment of Book ii. 
 was afterwards added in the collected works. A 
 note appended to this Fragment tells us that the 
 author abandoned the work after reading the Peri- 
 patetica of Franciscus Patricius. The part that 
 was published aroused considerable animosity, and 
 drew public attention at once to the author's abilities 
 and mental attitude. /Originality was not Gassendi's 
 strong point, and he showed in this work that his 
 strength lay in combining the ideas of others so as 
 to make them more effective^ In one respect the 
 work marks an epoch in his life : henceforth his 
 attitude toward Aristotle is defined by the declara- 
 tion that the Stagirite is to be taken as guide but 
 not worshipped as master and lord. In this, as 
 in other respects, his aim is not to be ' aut nimium 
 credulus aut parum pius ' (vi. 172). While the 
 work of Patricius relieved him from the necessity 
 of pursuing these critical essays, he was also 
 enlightened by their effect. He now saw that a 
 merely destructive criticism did little but raise the 
 dust. The true answer to existing systems could 
 only be made in another system which should include 
 in itself the whole range of human activity and 
 compel the thoughts of men to look at the Universe 
 as a whole. Thus began the scheme of the Syn- 
 tagma, on which at least twenty years of labour 
 were expended. With a training in mathematics 
 supplemented by considerable knowledge of the 
 cognate sciences, of medicine also and such biology
 
 xlii PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 as there was, Gassendi was naturally attracted to 
 the idea of developing the content of the universe 
 as subject of thought.^ He was struck with the 
 difference in value between an abstract and an 
 applied science ; and theory abstracted from the 
 living world seemed to him to have all the inutility 
 of numbers that are multiplied for the value of 
 multiplying, without application or objective refer- 
 ence. Such a science as anatomy elicits his fervent 
 admiration, demanding as it does the highest 
 development of method with a perpetual relation to 
 the actual thing. 
 
 The year 1624 then was one of great moment, but 
 no results were to be seen for many years. In 
 1628 .Gassendi was travelling in Flanders and 
 Holland with his friend Luillier. In 1631, at the 
 request of Mersenne, he undertook the criticism of 
 the mystical doctrine of Fludd. In 1633 he became 
 Provost of the Cathedral of Digne, and shortly after 
 began his travels in Provence with the Duke of 
 Angouleme. In 1645 he was appointed Professor 
 of Mathematics at the College Royal, Paris, but had 
 to resign in 1648 through ill-health. The disease 
 of the lungs from which he had long suffered soon 
 became acute, and he died at Paris in 1655. The 
 treatment of the disease seems to have been pecu- 
 liarly perverse, and Sorbiere speaks with much 
 
 ^The following anecdote given by Sorbifere illustrates Gassendi's 
 love of first-hand evidence : 'ut suspicionem autem prorsus amoliretur 
 quam de canali Cholidocho habuerat, quern Chylodochum dicere 
 maluerat, equos, in quibus omnino deficit, introspicere voluit. Et 
 raemini oflfendisse me aliquando euntem cum Martello, saeviente 
 admodum hieme, ad loca ilia in quae deportari solent viarum pur- 
 gamenta et trahi equorum cadavera quae plura, soluto pretio aperiri 
 jussit' (Gassendi, Of. Omnia., vol. i., Preface).
 
 INTRODUCTION xliii 
 
 bitterness of the persistent way in which the medici 
 continued to bleed the exhausted patient. 
 
 Between the years 1624 and the date of his death, 
 Gassendi published writings of three distinct types. 
 First, the critical writings include the examination 
 of Fludd's philosophy already noted (1631), and the 
 attack on the Cartesian doctrine in 1642. As a 
 critic, Gassendi has a keen eye for weak points, 
 and a convincing style of attack : his natural faults 
 are less in evidence here than anywhere. ' II est 
 difficile de traiter les discussions philosophiques 
 avec plus de clart^, d'agr^ment et de naturel : la 
 polemique de Gassendi, sauf peut-etre un peu de 
 rh^torique, merite encore aujourd'hui d'etre propos^e 
 comme un modele. ' ^ 
 
 The second class is that of the Lives, which were 
 famous in their day : the Vita Feireskii was trans- 
 lated in English, and had a considerable vogue. 
 
 ^ F. Bouillier, Histoire de la Philosophie Carte'sienne, quoted by 
 Thomas, p. 14. Thomas also quotes the following address to the 
 ' Lords of Mount Parnassus,' written by Boileau, which gives some 
 interesting sidelights on the opinions with which the Exercitationes 
 were received : ' Supplient humblement les maltres fes arts, prof- 
 fesseurs regens de I'Universite de Paris ; disant qu'il est de notoriete 
 publique que c'est le sublime et incomparable Aristote qui est sans 
 conteste le premier fondateur des quatre premiers Elements, le feu, 
 I'air, I'eau et la terre . . . ; et quoique pendant plusieurs sifecles il ait 
 6t6 maintenu d'un commun consentement dans une paisible possession 
 de tons ses droits, neanmoins depuis quelques annees en-gk, deux 
 particuliferes, nommees la Raison et I'Experience, se sont liguees 
 ensemble pour s'eriger un trone sur les ruines de son autorite ; et 
 pour parvenir plus adroitement k leurs fins ont excite certains esprits 
 fdcheux, qui sous les noms de Cartistes et de Gassendistes ont com- 
 mence h, secouer le joug du seigneur Aristote. ... Ce considere, 
 Nosseigneurs, il vous plaise ordonner . . . que Gassendi, Descartes, 
 Rohant, etc., et leurs adherents seront conduits a Athenes et con- 
 damnes d'y faire amende honorable devant tout la Gr5ce. . . .' (p. 9.)
 
 xliv PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI 
 
 The peculiar characteristic of Gassendi's work in this 
 direction is the easy way in which the whole is 
 seasoned with genial humanity.^ 
 
 In the third class may be reckoned the strictly 
 philosophical works. Though the work De Vita 
 morihus et doctrina Epicuri is a Life, and the notes 
 to the tenth book of Diogenes Laertius are critical, 
 they may both be reckoned as part of the working 
 out of an Epicurean Philosophy. They stand in 
 close relation to the Syntagma, which is the final 
 and all-embracing statement of his philosophy. As 
 this is to be the subject of the following pages, 
 only a remark or two need be made here. The 
 recorded judgments of the value of Gassendi's work 
 vary largely. Some think he has practically no 
 place in the history of philosophy : others regard 
 him as the forerunner of such modern philosophy 
 as concerns itself with the empirical rather than 
 the idealistic line of development. In my opinion 
 there is no fairer estimate of Gassendi than that 
 which Ritter gives in his Geschichte dei' Philosophie 
 (vol. X. p. 544). He says : ' Durch bedeutende 
 Erfindungen glanzte er nicht : dem neuem Ent- 
 
 1 ' Gassendi was one of the first after the revival of letters who 
 treated the literature of philosophy in a lively way. His writings 
 of this kind, though too laudatory and somewhat diffuse, have great 
 merit. They abound in those anecdotal details, natural yet not 
 obvious reflexions, and vivacious turns of thought which made 
 Gibbon style him, with some extravagance certainly, though it was 
 true enough up to Gassendi's time : ' Le meilleur philosophe des 
 litterateurs et le meilleur litterateur des philosophes ' {Encycl. Britt., 
 'Gassendi,' vol. x.). Eitter {Oeschichte der Philosophie, x. 544), 
 speaking of Gassendi's encyclopaedic knowledge, says, ' Nicht ohne 
 Grund hat Bayle von ihm gesagt, er sei unter den Philologen der 
 grosste Philosoph, unter den Philosophen der grosste Philolog 
 gewesen,' which looks like the prototype of Gibbon's remark.
 
 INTRODUCTION xlv 
 
 wicklimgsgange der Wissenschaften hatte er sich 
 doch nicht mit Eutschiedenheit angeschlossen ; gegen 
 das Copernikanische System hatte er nocli seine 
 Zweifel : die tlieologischen Fragen will er zwar 
 nicht der Philosophie beimischen, weil wir in dieser 
 nur dem Lichte der Natur zu folgen haben ' (544). 
 For some things the authority of the Church is 
 final : in the rest there is freedom : in philosophy 
 as such there is no one that must be taken as a 
 final authority ; his method of exposition belongs 
 to the earlier style in which all the authorities are 
 reviewed before a decision is made : he seeks a 
 middle course between scepticism and dogmatism. 
 He might indeed be reckoned among those who 
 had revived ancient systems in the earlier period 
 (this refers to Ritter's ' periods,' of which the last 
 brings the reader down to the reform of philosophy 
 by Bacon) but for the fact that his work is grounded 
 on the reformed methods of Bacon and ' ein bedeu- 
 tendes Glied fiir die systematische Entwicklung der 
 neuen Philosophie abgegeben hat' (545). This is 
 an accurate definition of Gassendi's position, and 
 shows that Ritter knew the actual contents of the 
 Syntagma at least. Its truth will be more apparent 
 when the summary of the Syntagma has been read 
 and the question of Gassendi's materialism can be 
 discussed in the light of his own statements.
 
 PART I. LOGIC
 
 LOGIC 
 
 I. 
 
 Logic is defined by Gassendi as the science of 
 intellect ' qua veri sequax.' ^ Its rules, being general, 
 conduct to all knowledge, not merely the knowledge 
 of nature, but knowledge of every description.^ The 
 term Logic Gassendi connects with Logos, which de- 
 notes the inner conversation of the mind, of which 
 Ratio is a species. 
 
 Logic, then, in the first instance is the science 
 of all mental operations that are in any sense 
 organised. This science may be Dialectic, Organic, 
 or, thirdly, Logic in the narrower sense. Logic in 
 the widest sense is ars cogitandi ; as Dialectic it is 
 ars disserendi ; as Organic it is ars dirigendi actiones 
 mentis : while the ars Logica in the narrower sense 
 is canonica or ars veri et falsi diiudicandi. This 
 second use of the term Logic is confined to the 
 ars bene cogitandi, which is held to be difi'erent 
 from the ars cogitandi, and identical with the ars 
 ratiocinandi. This is the real Logic as usually under- 
 
 ^ I. 31. 'objectum, seu tanquam scopus Intellectui propositus sit 
 Verum : objectum, seu scopus Voluntati propositus sit Bonum.' 
 
 ^ 1. 31. ' Quanquam et quia Eegulae huiusmodi generales sunt, ideo 
 inservire intellectui non modo ad scientiam naturae, sed etiam ad 
 omnem omnino cognitionem possunt.' 
 
 A
 
 v/ 
 
 y 
 
 2 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 stood, and the brancli that demands our serious 
 attention. Bene cogitare comprises bene imaginari, 
 proponere, colligere et ordinare : and in accord with 
 these our Logic will comprise the subjects of 
 Imagination, Proposition, Syllogism, and Method. 
 
 The action denoted by the verb ' imaginari ' is 
 that of forming an idea, also called species, notio, 
 praenotio, anticipatio, or conceptus. The ideas pre- 
 sent themselves to the mind as soon as the object 
 is named, and we, as it were, see right into them.^ 
 This intuitive perception we call simple imagination, 
 because it is limited to the mere image of the 
 thing without affirmation oi negation. The idea is 
 identical with the phantasma. The proposition is 
 an enunciative judgment : colligere denotes the 
 illative judgment; while the correct treatment of 
 a number of judgments in related syllogisms con- 
 stitutes the ars bene ordinandi. 
 
 II. 
 
 Logic is in the first instance Natural. Men had 
 thoughts before they evolved any method of think- 
 ing, and probably even in the earliest times there 
 was some method of thought even if there was no 
 thought of method. The serpent in the garden of 
 Eden doubtless used subtle arguments ; but these 
 primary forms of Logic are of no serious import- 
 ance : we may therefore pass them over, and confine 
 y/ our attention to Artificial Logic. 
 
 The earliest Logic in the proper sense is that of 
 Epicurus. Zeno's Logic was purely eristic, and a 
 
 ^ I. 33. ' nam simul ac res nominatur, obversari nobis in mente 
 experimur illarum imagines, in quas veluti intuamur.'
 
 I.] LOGIC 3 
 
 non-syllogistic method. Epicurus has been accused 
 of despising Logic, but it was really only the Logic 
 of the Stoics which he rejected. When he dropped 
 the term Logic for the name 'canons' it was only 
 the name that he really changed : ' nomen rejecit 
 rem retinuit' [i. 52]. 
 
 All questions, said Epicurus, are either about 
 things or words. When the question is about things 
 a criterion of Judgment is required. Things may 
 be classified as (a) naturales and (b) morales. In 
 the case of res naturales, we require sense and 
 mind : for res morales appetitus is required. As 
 there are three faculties, namely sense, mind, and 
 feeling, we have three criteria, namely sensation, 
 anticipation, and passion. 
 
 The term sense denotes both the faculty and the 
 function : as a criterion it denotes the function 
 primarily, for we judge by the perception of the 
 senses. The anticipatio is the image stored in the 
 mind ; the passio is the pleasure or pain which 
 controls choice. These will be better understood if 
 we quote the canons. 
 
 Canon i. Sensus nunquam fallitur : ac proinde 
 est omnis sensio omnisque Phantasiae sen appar- 
 entiae perceptio vera. 
 
 Canon ii. Opinio est consequens sensum sen- 
 sionique superadjecta in quam Veritas aut falsitas 
 cadit. 
 
 Canon iii. Opinio ilia vera est cui vel suflfragatur 
 vel non refragatur sensus evidentia. 
 
 Canon iv. Opinio ilia falsa est cui vel refragatur 
 vel non suffragatur sensus evidentia. 
 
 Canon v. Omnis quae in mente est anticipatio
 
 4 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 seu praenotio dependet a sensibus : idque vel 
 incursione, vel proportione, vel similitudine vel 
 composition e. 
 
 Canon vi. Anticipatio est ipsa rei notio sive 
 definitio, sine qua quidquam quaerere, dubitare, 
 opinari, imo et nominari non licet. 
 
 Canon vii. Est anticipatio in omni Ratiocinatione 
 principium, quasi nempe id ad quod attendentes 
 inferimus unum esse idem aut diversum, conjunctum 
 aut disjunctum. 
 
 Canon viii. Quod inevidens est ex rei evidentis 
 anticipation e demonstrari debet. 
 
 These eight canons are the basis of the theory 
 of knowledge, in so far as one is given us. We 
 y start with a blank mind capable of bare sensation : 
 the evidence of sense is one against which there 
 is no appeal.^ In the fifth canon we have some 
 new terms : ' incursio ' denotes the entrance of an 
 idea as such : proportio is the creation of an idea, 
 e.g. of a giant, by extending the idea of a man ; 
 similitudo is construction of an object not seen by 
 analogy with one we know ; lastly, compositio is 
 the voluntary union of ideas such as we perform 
 in constructing the notion of the centaur. In the 
 sixth canon the phrase 'notio sive definitio' covers 
 two aspects of the anticipatio. As a mental image 
 
 ' ' C'est en s'appuyant sur ces declarations, d'ailleurs formellea, 
 que les logiciens de Port-Royal et beaucoup de critiques k leur 
 suite, ont range Gassendi parmi les aensualistes. Nous verrons 
 bient^t ce qu'il faut penser de ce jugement lorsque, nous pla^ant 
 non plus au point de vue psychologique, nous etudierons de plus 
 prfes la formation de nos connaissons, et chercherons k determiner 
 avec plus de precision le role exact des deux facteurs dont elles 
 dependent : I'experience et la raison ' (P. Felix Thomas, La 
 Philosophie de Gassendi (Paris, 1889), p. 38). v. p. 1.3, note.
 
 L] LOGIC 5 
 
 the anticipatio is that visualizing of an object 
 which we perform when we hear a name significant 
 to us. This not being the product of a present 
 object, is producible at will and is that which we 
 recall and mentally survey in framing a definition. 
 A verbal definition is a secondary product and not 
 necessary except for one desiring to communicate 
 his ideas. The essential thing is a formal notion 
 or a notion described and accurately delimited ; ^ 
 and this is what Gassendi really wants. 
 
 III. 
 
 The remaining canons, ix. to xiv., are rules for 
 practical choice and clear speaking. Upon these 
 there follow summaries of the works of Lully, 
 Kamus, and Bacon. 
 
 The second book opens with the question of the 
 nature of that Truth which is considered to be 
 the end of Looic. 
 
 Truth is for Logic an end which is external to 
 it. The internal end for Logic is right think- 
 ing ; but right thoughts are higher and better 
 than this : Logic prepares the mind, and the end . 
 of this preparation is attained in applied thought. 
 The common distinction made between 'logica 
 docens ' and ' logica utens ' expresses this point. 
 The former is abjuncta a rebus, the latter conjuncta 
 cum rebus. It is only the latter, the concrete 
 applied logic, that concerns us at present. The 
 Truth whose nature we are pursuing is truth of 
 judgment. There is a truth of existence expressed 
 
 1 1. 54. ' impressa quaedam animo rei definitio ' : ' nisi taleni 
 quampiam animo deformatam habeamus.'
 
 6 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 in the formula ' everything is what it is ' ; Gassendi 
 y recognises that reality must always be real, and 
 a picture is not primarily ' falsus homo ' but ' vera 
 effigies ' ; ^ on the other hand, he clearly does not 
 suspect that the existence of which he predicates 
 truth is always a being for mind. To Being as 
 it is for thought belongs another kind of truth, 
 truth of judgment, which is the agreement of 
 judgment with fact. 
 
 Gassendi is now grappling with a difficult subject, 
 and allowance must be made for the crudeness of 
 the position on account of its novelty. Gassendi's 
 aim is to reach a common-sense position. It appears 
 to him that everything is what it is in itself: like 
 all other defenders of this point he goes upon the 
 tacit assumption that the phrase 'a thing is what 
 it is' means a thing is for itself what it is for 
 consciousness. As yet the animistic vein is not 
 quite explicitly eliminated from the world of nature 
 as we know it : the object is not properly conceived 
 as always relative to mind ; still less is the object 
 as related to mind expressly distinguished from the 
 thing as a further ultimate reality. But with all 
 its crudity the theory of Gassendi commands respect 
 as a straightforward treatment of the world of daily 
 life. The primary dogma that ' everything is what 
 it is' is supplemented by the notion that sense 
 shows us everything as it is. There is therefore no 
 thought of the bodily medium being itself the 
 destroyer of all knowledge : the immediate relation 
 is the psychic atom out of which the fabric of know- 
 ledge is built, and is itself irresolvable and wholly 
 
 ^i. 67.
 
 L] LOGIC 7 
 
 real. Immediate relations are, however, not always 
 possible. Things are not all of the same kind. 
 Some are ' manifestae,' and with them we have no 
 trouble ; others are ' occultae,' either ' penitus,' 
 ' natura,' or ' ad tempus.' ^ The first are hopeless : 
 the last may be left for Time to reveal : the second 
 form the sphere which it pays us to further 
 examine. It follows from this division that there 
 is an unknowable ; but that which is unknown is so 
 by reason of its own nature, not by reason of any 
 defect in us. The example given is the know- 
 ledge that the stars are even in number : the 
 unknown is in this case the answer to a problem, 
 and the knowledge that there is an answer depends 
 on a disjunctive judgment, 'stars are either odd 
 or even.' It would seem as though, if this is the 
 type of the unknowable, the unknowable ' penitus ' 
 is always a case of the ' unknown ad tempus.' 
 The ' res occultae natura ' are those which can be 
 reached by inference : as, for example, the existence 
 of pores in an apparently continuous surface deduced 
 from the excretion of sweat. To reach these truths 
 which lie below the surface we require a criterion, 
 or instrument. 
 
 Properly a criterion is a standard of judgment, as 
 Gassendi recognises, but it is also employed in the 
 sense of instrument. He divides criteria into (1) 
 those by which we live, and (2) those by which 
 we learn. The former are standards, such as ' lex 
 patriae,' ' consuetudo,' and the like, together with 
 the moral tests of Epicurus, pain and pleasure. 
 These do not really belong to Logic, which is 
 
 1 1. G8.
 
 8 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 concerned with the second class. This is subdivided 
 into (a) mechanical, and {h) natural criteria. The 
 former subdivision includes the foot-rule and 
 instruments of that kind ; the latter contains ' id 
 per quod ' and ' id secundum quod,' namely the 
 faculty and the function of the faculty. Some add 
 to these a third, ' a quo,' and define it as the 
 mind. But while for ascertaining the weight of a 
 thing we require the scales, the poising of the 
 scales, and the man to record the result, and also 
 for knowledge we require the sense, the function 
 of the sense, and the mind that knows the result, 
 the third is in both cases not a criterion, but a 
 judge.' 
 
 IV. 
 
 Now that we have determined the nature of the 
 world we confront and the criteria available for its 
 discovery, we must explore the question of the 
 possibility of knowledge, for that has been more 
 than once denied. 
 
 The Sceptics assert that man knows nothing in 
 the sense that he cannot penetrate into the inner 
 beings of things. The Dogmatists, on the other 
 hand, declare the criteria of sense and intellect to 
 be absolute : everything can be known through 
 them. Both the schools err from excess, and the 
 truth lies in the golden mean : some things are 
 known, and truly known, while others are obscure 
 and do not admit of more than probability. Truth 
 must be regarded as always possible, but not always 
 actual : what we do know is truth, but at the same 
 time we cannot be said to know all truth. 
 
 ^ I. 69. ' non ci'iterium, est enim potius crites.'
 
 I.] LOGIC J> 
 
 A difficulty arises here which Gassendi does not 
 seem to suspect. If we do not know all that might 
 be known, how does the ignorance arise, and how 
 is the present knowledge affected by the absence of 
 further knowledge ? Moreover, what do we require 
 to make our knowledge more complete ? Is it 
 more system or more senses ? Clearly if the whole 
 is regarded as a growing system, it is difficult to 
 avoid the conclusion that no one stage is in itself 
 finally true. On the other hand, if we imagine 
 that the world around us contains forces which 
 appeal to us in vain because we have no senses 
 that can respond to them, knowledge is bound to 
 remain cramped and imperfect for all time. The 
 atomism of Gassendi's standpoint now becomes 
 obvious. He thinks that a piece of the truth is 
 at least truth. The system of truths, then, only 
 differs from the individual truths in respect of 
 quantity. This point can be made clearer when we 
 have further considered the nature of knowledge. 
 
 In opposition to Gorgias, Gassendi asserts that 
 there must be something and some truth. Appear- 
 ances are admitted to be true : it is the occult truths 
 which give rise to doubt. To penetrate into the 
 occult truth we must advance by means of the known 
 to the unknown. A fact which is known and used 
 as the key to further knowledge is called 'signum, 
 medium, seu argumentum.' For example, in the 
 sentence ' if the sun shines it is day,' the signum 
 is 'if the sun shines.' Following Aristotle and 
 Quintilian,^ we divide the signa into (l) necessary 
 and (2) probable. The necessary signa are either (a) 
 
 ^i. 81. This equals the distinction of TeK^-npiov and (rrj/j.^ou.
 
 10 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 indicativa or (b) commonefactiva. When the signa 
 are indicativa they prove the existence of the occult 
 reality, as, for example, when sweat is taken as a 
 proof that pores exist in the skin. The commone- 
 factiva belong to the class of 'res ad tempus occultae.' 
 In this case both the objects concerned are possible 
 objects of experience. When a man sees smoke he 
 infers the presence of fire, and can proceed to verify 
 this by actual experience. It is not this but the 
 former case that the sceptics attack. The formula for 
 this is, ' If A is not, then B is not ' : hence given B, 
 A must be posited. The question therefore amounts 
 to this : can we have a perception that is not a sense- 
 perception, and none the less true ? Gassendi thinks 
 that we can. The signum is a sense-datum, and 
 must be given first ; but it has value only for a mind 
 that perceives and grasps it, so much so that the 
 mind is justified in revising and correcting its sense- 
 impressions. The position of the Sceptics that ex- 
 periences dijQTer and there is no universal truth is 
 refuted by the facts. For the experiences may differ, 
 but in recognising the differences we practically 
 admit that there are two fixed points, namely, the 
 cause and the disposition of the organism which is 
 affected. As knowledge is a relation the nature of 
 the relation may vary, and this may lead to partial 
 and confusing statements. We say ' the sun melts 
 the wax ' : we cannot say that the sun is in its own 
 nature 'melting,' any more than that it is 'hardening' 
 when it hardens the mud. The underlying fact is 
 that it radiates heat, which softens some bodies and 
 hardens others according to their dispositions. Our 
 limits are given at one erkl by the immediate cer-
 
 I.] LOGIC 11 
 
 tainty of sense, and at the other by the ' indubitata 
 principia ' of mind. It follows that single facts and 
 true propositions are alike self-evident. If the in- 
 tellect makes errors it also corrects them, and knows 
 the pure truth of axioms. 
 
 The critical point of this logic is the determination 
 of the relation of reason to sense. At first it looks 
 as though this was a theory purely sensualistic, but 
 the modifications introduced finally reverse that 
 judgment. Gassendi's real meaning appears to be 
 that experience gives us all we know ; we may get 
 out of experience much that is not apparent to the 
 senses, but we must never suppose that we can by 
 ourselves 'make experience : knowledge is a relation, 
 and therefore a pure creative activity of mind is a 
 sheer impossibility. Gassendi does not say that the 
 mind cannot know much that the senses never reveal, 
 or that we cannot confront experience with concepts 
 derived from reflection : all he says is that however 
 far we travel from the sources, there can be no truth 
 or reality in thoughts that cannot be brought back 
 to their contact with experience^"' Psychologically 
 this is expressed by saying that the intellect is a 
 supersensuous agent, which is in fact always allied 
 to a sensuous organism.^ 
 
 Gassendi thought Bacon and Descartes were both 
 extremists. Bacon confined himself too much to the 
 ars bene colligendi; his condemnation of the syllogism 
 was wrong, ' cum in syllogismo sit re ipsa robur 
 nervusque omnis ratiocinii ' : the syllogism is only 
 a failure because our universal is generally formed 
 ' ex propositionibus non satis perspectis.' Descartes, 
 
 *Cp. Ritter, Geschichte der Philosophie, x. 545-555.
 
 12 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 on the other hand, inclined to weave experience out 
 of his inner consciousness, to cultivate the ars bene 
 imaginandi without due regard to the material 
 (auxilia ad habendum veram germanamque rerum 
 notitiam, non tam ab ipsismet per se ac in se ex- 
 plorandis rebus, quam a solo, ipsoque a suis dumtaxat 
 cogitatis pendente Intellectu procedendum existimat, 
 I. 90). This definite expression of opinion makes it 
 clear that Gassendi was steering a middle course 
 between contemporary forms of empiricism and 
 rationalism (v. p. 134). 
 
 Gassendi has now finished defining his position 
 with regard to the relation of the mind to its world. 
 The position is obviously modelled on Aristotle, and 
 as was noticed above, is in a sense atomistic. A very 
 significant remark is to be found in the answer to 
 the Sceptics, who argued that, if a thing appears 
 diff'erently to diff'erent peojole, no one appearance 
 can be called the truth. Gassendi says that the 
 truth lies not in the appearance but in the 
 appearing. 
 
 Suppose an object appears to me to be of a certain 
 colour, I cannot say that this is ' ipsissima qualitas 
 quae sit in objecto,'^ but I can say that this is the 
 afi'ection due to this object, or this is the relation 
 which this object realises with me. The statement 
 that the object is not red to you cannot make it 
 cease to be red to me, while, on the other hand, the 
 fact that it is not to you what it is to me, proves 
 that it is what it is, for if there were no objective 
 reality the fact of diff'erence could not be explained 
 at all. This view logically implies that the object is 
 
 ii. 84.
 
 I.] LOGIC 13 
 
 essentially what it does, or in other words, it is a 
 * possibility of action.' 
 
 Atomism necessitates the recognition of the 'thing' 
 as a solid unchanging occupant of space. Whether 
 it naturally leads to the rejection of the category 
 of substance for that of function, to the change of 
 the formula of the thing from what it is to what it 
 does, is a question that confronts us vaguely, but 
 with promise of growing clearness. 
 
 V. 
 
 The Logic proper of Gassendi is divided into four 
 parts, and exhibited in the form of canons. The 
 parts deal with the idea, the proposition, the 
 syllogism, and method respectively. 
 
 The primary activity of the conscious being is 
 Imagination, or the reception of an image also called 
 idea. The idea is defined as the object of the mind 
 when it thinks (quae nobis rem quampiam cogitantibus 
 menti obversatur). All ideas come to us from the 
 senses, and we must endorse the saying : nihil in 
 Intellectu quod non prius fuerit in sensu (Canon iv.).^ 
 These ideas are supplemented by those which the 
 mind constructs by its own activities." From the 
 activity of the mind we derive general ideas. Both 
 
 'How is this td be understood? In a letter to Valerius (vi. 151, 
 dated 1642) Gassendi says : ' id ipsum est quod alii dicunt nihil 
 esse in Intellectu quod prius non fuerit in sensu ; insinuaturque 
 interim ut in sensu praefuerint quae videntur nunquam transisse 
 per sensum.' In respect of God he says : ' quas habemus species 
 huiusmodi rerum, non esse absque analogia ad res, ut corporeas sic 
 sensu perceptas.' This seems to interpi'et the formula as meaning 
 *all human thought is sensuous,' which is hardly half-way to 
 Condillac. 
 
 *v. p. 4.
 
 14 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. 
 
 singular and general ideas are ' perfect ' in proportion 
 as they accurately represent the object, and accuracy 
 is obtained by discriminating all the parts of the 
 object, singular or general. So Gassendi praises 
 Anatomy, Chemistry, and all analytical sciences as. 
 leading to accurate knowledge of particular objects. 
 In the case of the general idea, he says it is more 
 perfect according as it contains more distinct classes. 
 The general idea of man, for example, is more perfect 
 if it contains not only Europeans, Africans, and 
 Asiatics, but also Americans. It is difficult, he says, 
 to get the idea free from particular distinctions, but 
 it can be done. The reader of Canon viii. will find 
 it difficult to say whether Gassendi's universal is to 
 contain all particular distinctions or be formed by 
 neglecting them. Man, as a general idea, must be 
 ' omnibus discriminibus absolutum,' but at the same 
 time the universal concept cannot be gained by ab- 
 straction based on one individual, but results from 
 that process of explicating the essential, which is 
 grounded in the interaction of many particular ideas. 
 
 The Proposition is a union of ideas, and forms the 
 second stage of logical process. It is true when the 
 union it affirms is in agreement with objective reality. 
 The objective relation is that of substance and attri- 
 butes, and the Proposition unites substance and 
 attributes. As the union objectively considered is 
 sometimes necessary and sometimes contingent, so the 
 judgment contained in the proposition is sometimes 
 necessary (the opposite term being " impossible "), 
 sometimes probable. 
 
 The syllogism is a nexus of propositions, and is 
 treated by Gassendi in the ordinary formal way.
 
 I.] LOGIC 15 
 
 Method is three-fold : of invention, of judgment, 
 and of doctrine. The method of discovery is either 
 analytic or synthetic. It consists essentially in 
 tracking down a middle term or connecting link. 
 Suppose one is required to prove that man is a 
 substance. Taking the subject man we may analyse 
 it and show that it contains the notion of substance : 
 or taking substance we may qualify it (synthetically) 
 until we get that qualification which is identical 
 with man. The process is obviously a resolution 
 of the equation, ' Man = a substance,' in the form : 
 
 Man = rational livino^ thins;. 
 Some substance = rational living thing. 
 
 Man = some substance. 
 Gassendi's preference for mathematical methods 
 would have been quite obvious without his parti- 
 cular reference to geometry. 
 
 The method of judgment is likened to proof in 
 arithmetic when we combine addition with subtrac- 
 tion, and use them alternately to prove a result.^ 
 
 ' Gassendi uses this example to explain the distinction between 
 logica utens and docens. To learn to count is merely to learn a 
 method, good enough in itself but useless by itself, and only 
 acquired in order that it may be applied to things. To go on 
 with thought-processes in abstraction is like multiplying a number 
 by itself ad infinitum ; the result is true but true of nothing : hence 
 he insists on the return to experience as being a process of verifica- 
 tion. The inner significance of mathematical reasoning does not 
 seem to have struck Gassendi ; he merely sees that the assertion 
 ' twice two is four ' means that if two things have been given me 
 twice I ought to have four ; whether I have or not is a contingent 
 fact that requires immediate experience for its verification. In 
 both cases, mathematics and logic, we seem primarily to work 
 with ideas divorced from things ; but does this divorce extend to the 
 ideas which are intuitively guaranteed ? Gassendi apparently thinks 
 it does, for even the idea of God is 'verified' in the content of 
 experience.
 
 J 
 
 16 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. i. 
 
 The final verification is found in the criteria of sense 
 and judgment in which we must finally fix our faith. 
 The method of doctrine or teaching * begins with 
 resolution, and proceeds by composition' (Canon v.). 
 This is the method of all sciences, physical, mental, 
 and moral. In addition to this simple rule Gassendi 
 preaches clearness of language, clearness of division, 
 avoidance of useless digressions, and the necessity 
 of proceeding from the most common and essential 
 elements to the more obscure.
 
 PART II. PHYSICS 
 
 SECTION A
 
 CHAPTER I 
 
 INTRODUCTORY 
 
 By far the longest part of the Syyitagma of Gassendi 
 is comprised under the title ' Physics.' Of the 
 general nature of this work and its significance we 
 must speak later ; for the present we shall be 
 content to follow Gassendi's order of treatment and 
 reproduce his views on the various topics. 
 
 The Introduction is intended to clear our minds 
 as to the character and range of the subject. The 
 term nature is frequently used for two very distinct 
 things. If used with an active significance it denotes 
 a ' vis agendi,' a ' natura divina ' which sustains and 
 supports everything ; if used passively it denotes 
 simply the ' universitas rerum,' the totality of exist- 
 ing things. This distinction invites the use of two 
 terms made famous by Spinoza, naturans and 
 naturata. But terms live by their associations, 
 and as Gassendi does not use either of these verbal 
 forms, it is better to avoid them. Natura naturans 
 would indeed distort the meaning of 'vis agendi' 
 beyond recognition. In spite of the alternative 
 phrase, natura divina, this active aspect of nature 
 is in no sense God : the activity may be from God 
 and in its nature divine, but nature and God remain
 
 20 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 distinct realities without fusion of their being. The 
 manifestations of this activity are the ordinary 
 processes of life, including all that belongs neither 
 to art nor chance, which are the complementary 
 categories. 
 
 Nature as the sum of existing things may be 
 regarded in an abstract or a concrete way. The 
 true sphere of our Physics lies in this system of 
 things, and the true keynote of our method is 
 concreteness. Thales was the founder of the true 
 method, because he first sought the explanation of 
 natural phenomena in natural causes. To be scientific 
 we must be immanent ; our results will probably not 
 be final, but none the less our end will be attained. 
 That end is, according to Gassendi, ethical : he is 
 never tired of pointing out that if we desire finality 
 we labour in vain. The greatest lesson of past ages 
 is that we too are doomed to be superseded. None 
 the less we are not aimless or without an end : it 
 is meritorious to do what we may, and as it is a 
 duty so it is also a happiness to attain a knowledge 
 of the world in which we live, and through Nature 
 come to God. Of the limitations of our powers 
 Gassendi has no doubt ; with Bacon he finds in 
 nature a subtlety we cannot compass. But he has 
 no scepticism by which hope is numbed or enterprise 
 chilled. It is the quantity not the quality of know- 
 ledge that suffers : what we can know is in its way 
 true and final, and if we pass beyond it, the lower 
 stage had its own reality in its own day. 
 
 To revert to detail, a scheme is given us in this 
 introduction of the whole work.^ It is to deal with 
 
 'Cp, p. xi.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 21 
 
 (a) nature in general, (h) things celestial, (c) things 
 earthly. The subdivisions of the programme run 
 thus : 
 
 (a) De rebus naturae universe : 
 
 (1) The world — its number, parts, disposition. 
 
 (2) Time and place. 
 
 (3) Matter, causal principles, qualities, origin 
 
 and end. 
 
 (b) De rebus celestibus : 
 
 (1) The heavenly bodies, their motions and 
 
 the like. 
 
 (2) Predictions based on these. 
 
 (c) De rebus terrenis : 
 
 (1) Plants. 
 
 (2) Animals. 
 
 (3) Man and especially the soul. 
 
 This programme we shall follow as Gassendi has 
 followed it. 
 
 The discussions of the first section are prolix and 
 contain chiefly refutations of views which are gene- 
 rally of theological import and belong to an age of 
 thought so entirely superseded that they are no 
 longer of any interest. We can therefore pass it 
 over with a mere summary of conclusions. 
 
 The first question of the plurality of worlds was 
 generally treated in an a priori and speculative 
 manner for which it was peculiarly unfitted. One 
 prominent argument of the scholastic divines asserted 
 that an infinite God could not express himself in a 
 finite world. The word here used is mundus, and 
 must be taken to mean a habited or habitable globe,
 
 22 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 I 
 ^'^^ as there is no question of the plurality of the heavenly- 
 bodies. The answer to such a 'trifling proposition' is 
 easy but instructive. In the first place, the infinity 
 of worlds might be successive, which is the more 
 probable if we grant that the given world must 
 perish. Again, it does not follow that an effect must 
 be identical with its cause, and therefore, an infinite 
 cause need not produce an infinite effect. Finally, 
 the whole argument suggests that we can judge the 
 Divine Agent by human standards, which Gassendi 
 denies. Gassendi refuses to say that ' Deus propter 
 excellentiam non immerito nihil vocatur'; the concept 
 of God has to be formed through our concepts of all 
 that is highest on earth, but the sublimation is carried 
 far enough to justify the position that when regarded 
 as active and real, God cannot be brought under 
 ordinary categories of judgment. 
 
 Current opinion was divided between two views. 
 Some upheld that each star was a world and these 
 worlds were related to each other :^ others maintained 
 that there was a plurality of worlds, but each one 
 dwelt apart, dissociated from the rest. In the second 
 case it follows that we cannot know the others; while 
 the former statement is a mere assumption, since we 
 do not in fact know those relations. The assumption 
 of relations was a pure deduction from the assumed 
 unity of the whole, and was made valueless by the 
 fact that the relations asserted to be actual were 
 never revealed in experience. An entirely different 
 proof was based on the assumption that the number 
 of atoms was infinite and could only be exhausted by 
 an infinity of worlds. These so-called proofs Gassendi 
 
 'i. 138.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 23 
 
 rejects : his attitude is one of provisional scepticism 
 based on commonsense. There is no proof either for 
 or against, since the worlds if existent are certainly 
 unknown.^ He pours scorn on Lucretius for praising 
 Epicurus as though a proclamation of endless worlds 
 had broken down the barriers of human knowledge. 
 Lucretius exclaimed in vain 
 
 ' moenia mundi 
 discedunt : video totum per inane geri res.' 
 
 The one word ' video ' reduced the whole sentiment 
 to bathos : it expressed exactly what could not be 
 done ; and there is no gain in widening the realm of 
 the unknown: it is not the number of possible objects 
 that must be increased, but the powers of sense and 
 constructive imagination as based on sense. To in- 
 dulge an empty fancy in the ecstasy that the word 
 ''' infinite ' too often inspires is harmful rather than 
 advantageous : we must confine ourselves to what we 
 know, and curb the imagination within the limits 
 dictated by experience. In this reference at least 
 Gassendi seems to have been clear on the distinction 
 of unknown from unknowable, and to have felt the 
 futility of asserting existences to which we have no 
 relation. 
 
 II. 
 
 The fifth chapter takes up the question of the 
 World Soul, a subject which has been discussed from 
 time immemorable, and still retains something more 
 
 1 1. 141. 'Nam fatendum est quidem convinci demonstrationi non 
 posse, non esse niundos praeter hunc alios : quando profitemur 
 potuisse et posse adhuc condere Deuiu alios innumeiabileis. . . . 
 At vero tueri aliunde plureis mundos reipsa esse, praeter rationem 
 omnino est.'
 
 24 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 than a merely historical interest. Gassendi's treat- 
 ment of it is systematic and much more interesting 
 than some of his other discussions. 
 
 The root of the question is the opinion that the 
 world is an organised whole ; not a ' totum in- 
 ordinatum ' like a pile of stones, but ' ordinatum ' 
 or constituted of organised parts. ^ This position is 
 definitely though perhaps unconsciously advanced by 
 the addition of the idea that these parts stand to 
 each other in some relation other than that of mere 
 co-existence in space : it is universally admitted that 
 Earth, Sun, and Moon are interrelated (inter se 
 affectae relatione aliqua sint). This advance in the 
 doctrine really carries us over the crucial step from 
 the view of the world as organised to the declaration 
 that it is organic, from which an easy analogy brings 
 us to the all-pervading soul.^ It is this step that 
 we must defend or repudiate. In spite of the 
 example of the pile of stones, it may be possible 
 to have an ordered Universe without all the im- 
 plications of a universal soul. 
 
 The greatest advocates of the world soul are 
 Pythagoras and Plato, supported by i^j-istotle to a 
 certain extent, and the more recent 'chymici.' The 
 outline of the doctrine shows that the Soul of 
 the world was conceived as a very subtle sub- 
 stance pervading the Universe. Its nature is not 
 simple but twofold, being composed of a purer 
 and a grosser part, the latter being however 
 
 ij. 155. 
 
 "'Plerique . , . fatentur esse vim quandam per totum mundum 
 sic diffusam parteisque eius continentem cuiusraodi in Animali est 
 Anima.'
 
 IL] PHYSICS 25 
 
 * purissima ' as compared with the grossness of 
 corporeal entities. This forms a spiritual body 
 which mediates the entrance of the higher part 
 into the natural body.^ These parts are called 
 respectively Mens and Anima {fov?, ^^x^'i). The 
 term anima then denotes voO^ taken as conjoined 
 to some material existent, and can be used in this 
 discussion without further reference to vov^ or mens 
 per se. 
 
 The anima was defined by Pythagoras as a 
 harmony, not of course in a material sense as we 
 speak of vocal harmony, but in the sense of 
 proportion of parts. We naturally ask what are 
 the parts and what are the proportions, and we 
 look to Plato's Timaeus for the answer. That 
 exposition is taken by Gassendi to be the true 
 statement of what the Anima Mundi meant to the 
 original authors of the doctrine. Are we to accept 
 this Anima or not? Such expositions as we have 
 clearly indicate that it is an entity whose being 
 is not exhausted in these analogical descriptions. 
 To say it is a harmony is only to say that its 
 nature can be thus analogically described. What 
 is it in reality? If we take it to mean God there 
 is no objection so long as we speak of him as 
 
 ^This is Gassendi's interpretation of Plato's phrase, i'oi/:' /x^v iv ^vxvt 
 ^vxv" 5^ ^'' cwyuari (Timaeus, 30 b). * Stallbaum,' says Archer-Hind 
 {Timaeus, p. 93), 'following the misty light of neo-platonic inspiration, 
 says of \piixv> media est inter corpora atque nientem.' In Timaeus, 36 E, 
 we are told God constructed body within soul : hence voDs, i'vxv, and 
 ffufjM were conceived as each including the other, like three concentric 
 circles, with I'oi/s comprehending ^vxv, '^^xv comprehending irw/ua. The 
 relation of this to the view that ' vovs is simply the activity of \f/vx'n 
 according to her own proper nature ' (Archer-Hind), is obvious if not 
 orthodox : for vovt can think ^vx'l but not vice versa, includes but is 
 not included by ^pvxv-
 
 26 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 assistens, not pars, just as the pilot is in but not 
 part of the ship. Similarly it may be a fiery 
 substance (calor) if taken as immanent, not like 
 the sun's heat, irradiated. This interpretation 
 requires a further modification, inasmuch as the 
 position is radically altered by using the term 
 soul for a substance like calor. To use the term 
 soul in any intelligible way is to imply certain 
 functions such as generation and nutrition. These 
 are essential to life as we know it, either in 
 animals or plants, and without these the term 
 becomes meaningless. But one world does not 
 beget another, and therefore has no claim to be 
 recognised as an animal. Neither has the world 
 any functions of nutrition: Plato and the Stoics 
 have indeed spoken of the stars as being nourished 
 by exhalations from the earth, and the earth from 
 the water of the moon, but these are idle fables: 
 a commutation of parts there may be, but that is 
 not properly speaking nutrition. Finally, the earth 
 has no functions such as sight and hearing; and 
 if we speak of the 'heart' of the world, or make 
 it like a Cyclops with the Sun for an eye, these 
 are pure metaphors! Why, then, is the world said 
 to have a soul at all? The reason is, that without 
 it we cannot explain how there should be individual 
 souls. The only argument for it is a regress from 
 particular to universal. Lactantius expresses this 
 tersely : ' sic enim argumentatur : fieri non posse ut 
 sensu careat quod sensibilia ex se generat. Mundus 
 autem generat hominem, qui est sensu praeditus. 
 Ergo et ipsum sensibilem esse.' This argument 
 breaks down by generating its own contradiction:
 
 II.] PHYSICS 27 
 
 for many things in the world have no soul, and it 
 is equally possible to argue from them that the 
 world has no soul. That which has soul derives 
 its soul from the particular antecedent to which 
 it owes its production and not to a universal 
 entity. (Animam nimirum habet animal non ex 
 totali anima muudi sed ex speciali anima quae aut 
 in parentibus praeest. This applies not to anima 
 as such only, but to any specific nature, e.g. of 
 stone, I. 160.) 
 
 A second main argument is derived from the 
 belief that the soul is the architect of its own 
 body. Granted then that the world is an animal, 
 it must have a Soul. As this argument assumes 
 the World to be an animal, and deduces from 
 that the presence of a soul, we must attack the 
 assumption. This animal called the world must 
 either be eternal or have had a beginning. If it 
 is eternal, in what sense did the soul make it? — 
 and if it was created, this must have been done 
 by some agent other than itself If it began, but 
 not by creation, it was born either spontaneously 
 or of parents, which means it was due either to 
 chance or to definite purpose. In any case its 
 cause is outside itself, and therefore cannot be 
 its own anima. It appears then, that the theory 
 has no support so long as we take the term soul 
 exactly. If we take it to mean either God or 
 a substance such as fire, we either go beyond the 
 world for its soul, or we apply the term soul to 
 material forms of existence in a way that will 
 make havoc of our psychology.
 
 28 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 III. 
 
 Some additional questions remain to be settled, 
 but they are of minor importance. They comprise 
 a discussion on the leading theories of the universe 
 and their relative values, an enquiry into the 
 beginning and end of the world, and a description 
 of the known parts of the world. Of these the 
 last requires no notice, being a mere description 
 of the apparent place of things, e.g. the place of 
 the air, of the water, of the earth, and of the 
 heavenly bodies. This essay on physical geography 
 applied to the universe belongs, with its com- 
 plementary disquisition on the figure of the earth, 
 to an age still near the times when the earth was 
 thought to be flat, and may be consigned to the 
 limbo of forgotten problems. 
 
 The three main theories of the world were those 
 evolved by Ptolemy, Copernicus, and Tycho Brahe 
 respectively. Of these Gassendi considers that of 
 Tycho Brahe to be the best for reasons worth 
 noting. Ptolemy's system is dismissed for not ex- 
 plaining the movement of the heavenly bodies in a 
 satisfactory way : the Copernican system is most in 
 accord with facts, but the sacred texts attribute rest 
 to the earth and movement to the sun. Moreover, 
 there is a decree bidding us take this to mean not 
 apparent but real rest. Those, therefore, who respect 
 the decree must approve and defend Tycho Brahe's 
 modifications of the Copernican system. Here, as 
 elsewhere, Gassendi's language implies reluctant 
 acquiescence. He writes : ' Ideo superest ut tale 
 Decretum reverentibus Tychonicum potius systema 
 et probetur et defendetur ' ; and we can see through
 
 II.] PHYSICS 29 
 
 tlie veil of orthodoxy that the author's heart is 
 with Copernicus and the system which can so truth- 
 fully be called ' planius et concinnius.' 
 
 In dealing with the question of the world's 
 beginning Gassendi is supported by Epicurus and 
 the Bible. The doctrine of atoms implies a theory 
 of creation, and therefore puts its adherents in 
 opposition to Aristotle and the supporters of an 
 infinite and unproduced world. But while support 
 is thus gained for the theory of creation, the alleged 
 method cannot be accepted. A blind concursus of 
 atoms is not a method of creation that a good 
 Churchman can advocate. Fortunately it can be 
 rejected on rational no less than religious grounds. 
 The world gives us obvious proof that it was made 
 by design : this implies a cause, which must be 
 outside it ; and therefore production in time, for 
 the cause existed before it produced the world, and 
 the relation of before and after constitutes Time. 
 Again, every part of the world is corruptible and 
 perishing, and the whole must therefore be of the 
 nature of the corruptible and have its own creation 
 and decease. 
 
 To understand this second argument, we must 
 take it as an argument on categories.^ The assumed 
 question is, ' Does the world belong to the category 
 of the infinite or the finite ? ' If any reason can 
 be shown for including it under one category rather 
 than another, the consequences follow without further 
 argument. Gassendi's argument against the eternity 
 of the world is based on cruder views than might be 
 expected. He notes that the sea and the rivers 
 
 iCf. p. 226.
 
 30 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 continually reduce the land and even wear down 
 the mountains : ^ none of this matter is carried up 
 again, and therefore, if an eternity of time had 
 really elapsed, the whole earth must by now have 
 disappeared beneath the waters. This is a shame- 
 lessly eristic procedure for one who has just defended 
 the spherical form of the world. 
 
 There arises from this proof of a finite world one 
 problem which touches so nearly our views on 
 motion that it must not be left unsolved. Aristotle 
 had argued from the eternity of movement and 
 the necessity of God's continual action. Gassendi's 
 argument is also based on movement, for corruption 
 and decay may be regarded as primarily movements 
 and only apparent changes. It must also be borne 
 in mind that there are three indestructibles, namely 
 atoms, the void, and the universe. If the world 
 is composed of atoms, and atoms never perish, it 
 follows that the destruction of the world is neither 
 
 ^ ' It might almost be supposed that the following lines were 
 written by one of our own contemporaries : they are, however, 
 extracted from a chapter of Avicenna on the origin of mountains. 
 This author was born in the tenth century. Mountains may be 
 due to two causes. Either they are effects of upheavals of the 
 crust of the earth, such as might occur during a violent earthquake, 
 or they are the eflfect of water, which, cutting for itself a new 
 route, has denuded the valleys, the strata being of different kinds, 
 some soft, some hard. The winds and waters disintegrate the one, 
 but leave the other intact. Most of the eminences of the earth 
 have had this latter origin. It would require a long period of 
 time for all such changes to be accomplished, during which the 
 mountains themselves might be somewhat diminished in size. But 
 that water has been the main cause of these effects is proved by 
 the existence of fossil remains of aquatic and other animals on 
 many mountains' (The Intellectual Developme7it of Europe, Draper, 
 I. 410). Gassendi at least aflfects a knowledge of Avicenna, and 
 frequently refers to him.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 31 
 
 more nor less than the dissipation of its material. 
 Movement, then, would be eternal, and if the old 
 material forms a new world with never a break in 
 the history of its parts, why should this second 
 world be said to be created rather than evolved, 
 and why should not our present world be viewed 
 as evolved from a former world or even a former 
 condition of its own elements ? It may finally be 
 necessary to say that Gassendi never properly faced 
 this problem, but he seems to have been conscious 
 that such a problem was possible, and to have in 
 some degree anticipated it. His first defence is the 
 denial that time is dependent on motion. If time 
 and motion are inseparable, they must be coeval, 
 and motion is infinite, since it occupies all time : 
 to deny the dependence is to assert a time prior 
 to all motion, and thereby make motion a product 
 in time. The second is contained in the assertion 
 that the first cause need not be physical ; in other 
 words, a regress from motion to motion is not 
 infinite, but terminates in a First Cause, by whose 
 creative action motion itself first came into being. 
 The fact that all motion is, as motion, one, and 
 the term ' different motions ' must be taken to 
 mean motions of different ag-o-reoates of matter, 
 does not compel us to regard the creation of motion 
 as the imparting of one impulse to the whole : it 
 is possible, and even more probable, that in the 
 beginning many mobile bodies were created with 
 internal force of movement. As God's relation to 
 the world is purely external, and its movement is 
 for him a ' pure relation,' his essence is not aff'ected 
 by either its becoming or its dissolution.
 
 32 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 As we progress more and more with the Physics 
 it will become more and more apparent how empty 
 and vain are these arguments. They perhaps 
 weighed heavily against those who taught that the 
 world could never be destroyed, but would be 
 purified and adorned with flowers ' ad puerulorum 
 non initiatorum neque in caelum translatorum ob- 
 lectationem.' But as serious philosophy they cannot 
 stand examination, because Gassendi never makes it 
 clear whether he is talking as a practical man of 
 science or a theorist. His position is in fact meta- 
 physical, and relies on pure reasoning. His real 
 theorem, therefore, is whether the human mind can 
 think its world and its series of causes as truly 
 infinite. He would probably have decided that the 
 infinite can only be thought by an infinite mind. 
 Speculation of this kind is however quite out of 
 place, for Gassendi never thinks of dividing mind 
 and object in this way. The consequence is that, in 
 spite of the logical and metaphysical character of 
 the argument, the conclusions are purely physical. 
 For Gassendi there are no antinomies of pure reason, 
 and the problems of infinity never suggest a recon- 
 sideration of experience itself So, in spite of the 
 encouraging way in which Gassendi takes up time 
 and causation as the fundamental points in the 
 problem of infinitude, he gets no further than a 
 dogmatic assertion that what is logically possible 
 is physically actual. If we may say of any 
 theory of reality that it regards the actual as 
 necessarily thinkable, it would still be false to 
 regard the thinkable as necessarily actual ; and 
 from Gassendi's point of view neither proposition is
 
 II.] PHYSICS 33 
 
 defensible.^ The whole argument is therefore irrele- 
 vant and useless : our world as a subject for scientific 
 discussion is not affected by the conclusion ; and 
 the reader finds himself, after traversing a circle of 
 argument, for all practical purposes exactly where he 
 was before. It is impossible to suppose that Gassendi 
 was not aware of this, or that these forensic disputes 
 were left in such solemn isolation by mere accident. 
 The practical part of the treatise looks forward : the 
 theoretical serves a different purpose. 
 
 ^Gassendi would allow both the assertions, namely — (1) Reality 
 is wider than Thought ; (2) Thought is wider than Reality. The 
 former is correct, because knowledge is a relation, and there is no 
 a priori reason why all the existent should be in that relation. 
 Since the relation does not constitute the being of anything, that 
 may be which is not thus related ; in other words, the knowable 
 may include the unknown (not unknowable) as well as the known. 
 The latter is also correct, because we may outrun our data and 
 assert our subjective (imaginative) constructions as real.
 
 CHAPTER II 
 
 TIME AND SPACE 
 I. 
 
 The second book of the Physics on time and place 
 is so involved and subtle that its contents must be 
 stated in Gassendi's own way before any attempt 
 is made to formulate his views. 
 
 The title is peculiar and should be noticed. It 
 runs ' de loco et tempore seu spatio et duratione ' ; 
 and this duplication of terms persists throughout, 
 adding to the difficulty of interpretation. Gassendi 
 seems to have regarded the second pair as the 
 universals corresponding to the particular or specific 
 terms locus and tempus. He considers these two 
 identical in nature, so that anything we say about 
 space applies to time : we can therefore confine 
 ourselves to the more intelligible subject of space. 
 
 The traditional philosophy divides all being into 
 substance and accident, and declares that what is 
 neither of these is nothing. Space however is a 
 reality, and yet comes under neither of these heads. 
 In face of the facts authority must be disregarded 
 and a new classification be evolved. We must 
 recognise as distinct classes 
 
 (1) Substances — quae per se sunt. 
 
 (2) Accidents — quae per aliud sunt. 
 
 (3) Time and Space.
 
 TT. II.] PHYSICS 35 
 
 This third class shares with the first the quality of 
 being per se : they are therefore properly called 
 substances, but the term substance always conveys 
 the idea of corporeal existence, and is therefore 
 objectionable unless a qualification is added. It is 
 not incorrect to speak of an incorporeal substance, 
 and this would meet the requirements of the case : 
 as Aristotle used it of the mind and Epicurus of 
 the void, it is not wholly without authority. Having 
 settled this first step of classification, Gassendi 
 attacks the categories. Quantity is the category 
 that concerns us at present. Space falls under the 
 category of continuous quantity. The tyranny of 
 matter gave rise to the opinion that quantity was 
 an ' accidens corporeum,' and as space came under 
 the category of quantity it was also asserted to be 
 corporeal. Corporeal, when applied to accidents, 
 means 'dependent on a body.' Length, breadth, 
 and weight clearly require a material something to 
 which they can be referred. Space, according to 
 Gassendi, does not : it is therefore more than a 
 mere quantity, more than so much room : it is 
 not only the place of things, it is a place for things, 
 a difi'erence that must be more fully discussed later. 
 Space, then, may be defined as a quantitative reality 
 independent of matter. The consequences and diffi 
 culties of this definition have now to be considered. 
 (1) The most obvious objection is that a quantity 
 of nothing is nothing ; but Gassendi replies that 
 in this case the quantity is a quantity of Space, 
 and space is something. If a body be removed 
 from a given place, the space of that place remains. 
 This argument is greatly assisted by the traditional
 
 36 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 habit of obtaining a concept of matter per se by 
 abstracting all form : if tliis is possible why cannot 
 form be abstracted from all matter ? It follows 
 that the concept of the void is possible. 
 
 (2) As we may think of matter as reduced to 
 nothing, we may also think of it as infinitely great : 
 worlds may be infinite, and therefore space must be. 
 
 (3) As space has no faculties or actions, its adjec- 
 tives must be purely negative. It is infinite because 
 it is not finite, and incorporeal because it is not 
 corporeal. It cannot be a substance in the sense 
 that God is, else there are three equal substances, 
 and the being of God is not superior to the being 
 of space and time. 
 
 (4) The origin of space and time is an insoluble 
 problem. Gassendi does not say this in so many 
 words, but leaves it to be inferred. He merely 
 remarks that to say some essences are not properly 
 created by God is worse than admitting time and 
 space to be uncreated — a tortuous method of escaping 
 the dilemma. 
 
 (5) Space is imaginary, not in the sense of unreal 
 or fictitious, but as requiring to be constructed by 
 analogy. 
 
 The discussion thus summarised is followed by a 
 division of space according as it is (l) outside the 
 world, (2) dispersed among things, (3) collective. 
 The first is space left for new worlds, and is required 
 in order that God may not be limited in creating 
 new worlds ; the second is space as it occurs among 
 bodies which do not change ; the third is space as 
 it is produced by loss of volume or contraction. 
 This is technically called ' spatium coacervatum.'
 
 II.] PHYSICS 37 
 
 These three kinds of space seem to be really three 
 kinds of vacua : they are rather asserted than proved, 
 and their assertion raises more problems than it 
 solves. 
 
 II. 
 
 As Gassendi's doctrine of time is a mere appendix 
 to that of space, it is necessary to form some idea 
 of his views of space before venturing to consider 
 those of time. 
 
 Following the hint given by Bernier in the Abrdge, 
 we may take space and the universe to be com- 
 plementary concepts. Space is infinite in three 
 dimensions, and is the place of all things, whether 
 already produced or existing only in the mind of 
 God. The confusing element in Gassendi's treatment 
 is its complexity. It is never quite clear whether 
 we are treating space as a given reality which can 
 be directly known or a reality which must be 
 deduced. The statement that space is imaginary is 
 extremely obscure. By imagination Gassendi always 
 means a power of compounding elements given 
 through the senses in such a way as to produce a 
 new representation of some object not actually 
 presented. If space is a pure quantity, its construc- 
 tion in imagination has no principle of limitation, 
 and it will be the subject of an infinite process. 
 Here there appear to be two errors which can only 
 be explained through the tendency of Gassendi's 
 philosophy to develope rationalistic features. The 
 first error is committed when from the ancient argu- 
 ment that if a vessel is absolutely empty its sides 
 must either collapse or preserve a distance between
 
 38 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 them in which there is pure space, he infers that 
 a pure space can be given. Here there is a wholly 
 indefensible transition from the distinction of the 
 concepts of space and matter to a distinction of their 
 actual existence. As with the infinity of motion, 
 so here in the cognate subject of space the logical 
 conclusion is converted into a predicate of reality 
 in a way that implies a metaphysic unfortunately 
 not supplied by Gassendi. 
 
 The second error consists in supposing that we 
 have any right to regard as valid of reality a process 
 which is subjectively possible.^ Gassendi undoubtedly 
 commits this error because he uses the property of 
 numbers or mere quantity to enable him to assert 
 that our concept of space cannot stop at any given 
 point but must advance indefinitely. This, however, 
 is true of everything if taken abstractly in relation 
 to quantity, and has no special application to space. 
 The traditional problems gave a wrong turn to this 
 line of thought by putting it into a form half con- 
 crete and half abstract. If a man going to the end 
 of all things hurls a spear before him, what are we 
 
 ^It is perhaps necessary to point out that subjective does not 
 mean ' mental' : there is no 'mentalism' at this stage of the history 
 of thought : the subjective is ' the work of the mind,' and is practi- 
 cally always limited to the work of the Imagination. This is why 
 we find so much confusion in the interpretation of philosophies which 
 belong to this period of transition. It is frequently the case that 
 the work of the mind as reason is considered unimpeachable, while 
 the work of the mind as imagination is the source of constructions 
 which may be, as we still say, ' put upon ' things. The phrase here 
 means that an imaginative construction is not necessarily more than 
 imaginative. It seems strange that after his comprehension of the 
 futility of abstract counting (p. 712) Gassendi should not have avoided 
 this error. But Sjjace, in spite of being a substance, so combines plurality 
 and unity (for many spaces are one space) that Gassendi lost his way.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 39 
 
 to think ? Common sense replies that he was pro- 
 bably not at the end, but tradition says that it 
 follows that an end of space is unthinkable, and the 
 concrete reality of the spear gives the space, imagined 
 as its place, a fictitious reality. 
 
 We have here, then, a complete confusion between 
 the reality of our thoughts about space and the 
 reality of the space about which we think. Gassendi 
 does not know either how space originated in nature 
 or how it has become known. When he describes 
 it as form he speaks metaphorically ; it is not a 
 form either of sense or matter, but an independent 
 reality ; it is an immovable whole, otherwise a thing 
 might move and take its space with it, and so not 
 change its place even when moved. In a sense it 
 must be nothing, otherwise two things are in one 
 place, namely the thing and its space ; on the other 
 hand, it is a substance in relation to occupants of 
 space. In some cases, e.g. God and the angels, the 
 occupant is incorporeal. If a place is space occupied 
 by a body, can an incorporeal being have a space, 
 and if not, can it be and yet not be anywhere ? To 
 answer these questions Gassendi says space is ' quod 
 res locata occupat ' ; hence the angels have their 
 place where they are, and God is properly ' in se,' 
 which appears to mean that He is but does not exist, 
 has being but not spatial being. 
 
 This intricate maze of thought becomes entirely 
 unintelligible unless we accept it as the expression 
 of two views in one. In one part we are being told 
 what Space is in itself, in the other what it is in 
 experience. In the former aspect it is real, and that 
 is all we know ; definition, if any, must be negative,
 
 40 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 and its nature must be assumed to be all that it is 
 not irrational to suppose it.^ Ultimate space is thus 
 really a hypothesis which is proved to be actual, 
 because without it we cannot understand the world 
 of experience. The latter aspect concerns us when 
 we deal with reality as known in the senses. Space, 
 having no activities, cannot be known through the 
 senses except ' ex parte rei locatae.' It is combina- 
 tion with the thing that makes space an object of 
 perception and gives the required ground upon which 
 imagination may work.^ 
 
 III. 
 If Gassendi feels that space is an ultimate that 
 defies exact analysis and almost baffles description, 
 he is still more diffident about time. None the less 
 he feels that his position ought to redeem him from 
 blank despair. The words of St. Augustine sum up 
 the views of one class of thinker ; ^ to Gassendi 
 they seem justified only as the conclusion of a false 
 method. For if the corporeal is regarded as primary, 
 and our category of substance is practically confined 
 to the tangible, space and time alike become dis- 
 placed from reality and drift away through the pages- 
 of speculation like homeless phantoms refusing burial. 
 
 ^ This is a definite logical principle derived from Epicurus, v. p. 3, 
 Canon iii. 
 
 ^ Space, then, is perceived 'by sense in so far as it is given with 
 body. The question might be asked, Would an animal, having sense 
 only, perceive space ? I imagine Gassendi would have no answer to- 
 that : the a priori objectivity of space and the possibility of a sensi- 
 tive organism that did not think would both be endangered by its 
 discussion. 
 
 ^ I. 220. Gassendi quotes from the Confessions : ' Si nemo ex m& 
 quaerat quid sit Tempus, scio : si quaerenti explicare velim, nescio.*
 
 II.] PHYSICS 41 
 
 The rock on which Gassendi builds is good founda- 
 tion : come wliat may, these two are real, and it is 
 futile to try and explain away what we cannot 
 escape. 
 
 The majority of what has been said about space 
 can be transferred to time. The main conception 
 being the same, only one chapter is devoted to a 
 special discussion of time. Like space, it is a sub- 
 stance in its w^ay, incorporeal in its nature and not 
 in itself dependent on its content. The relation of 
 space to time is to be understood by the analogy 
 of corporeal entities ; for as the corporeal has a 
 permanent aspect, its extension, and also a successive 
 aspect, its movement, so we have in the incorporeal 
 sphere a permanent and a successive entity, which 
 are respectively the place of all extensions and the 
 place of all movements. As Space is really the Place 
 of all places, so Time is the Duration of all durations; 
 and as space has some unoccupied or potential places, 
 so Time overlaps the known durations and has its 
 'void.' In opposition to the Epicurean view, which 
 makes out that time would not be if there were no 
 minds or things,^ Gassendi holds to a lapse of time 
 before the beginning of the world and between 
 creations. He is really nearer the modern view than 
 at first appears ; for the Epicurean view did not 
 make time a form of perception, but merely regarded 
 
 ^i. 223. 'Jam vero neque Epicurus videtur posse dicere esse diem, 
 noctemque aut longam aut brevem ab eo tempore quod cogitatiDiie 
 ipsi aflBngimus.' The reference is to Diogenes Laertius, x. Cp. i. 222. 
 ' Videntur porro Stoici melius quam ipse Epicurus sensisse, reputantes 
 Tempus tale incorporeum, quod per se esse intelligatur, non tale 
 quod accidat rebus, eo sensu ut Tempus non foret, si res non esaent, 
 quae eo durarent, aut nisi etiani nostra mens durare ipsas cogitaret.'
 
 42 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 it as dependent on its contents. Gassendi, on the 
 other hand, considers that events derive their order 
 from time, and considers that time must therefore 
 precede change. In the case of space it seemed an 
 easy matter to say that the annihilation of the thing 
 placed was not identical with annihilation of the part 
 of space which formed the place. If we are to pre- 
 serve the analogy we must say that annihilation of 
 change would not annihilate time. This Gassendi 
 is prepared to say, but it is a hard saying. It 
 would seem as though the assertion of time without 
 change necessitated our regarding time as a per- 
 manent entity, which would sacrifice its essential 
 distinction from space. Time moves without any 
 doubt : it is however hardly like a stream : a better 
 simile is that of the flame of a candle, which as it 
 burns changes indeed, but in such a way as not to 
 lose its identity, and so gives us a better idea of 
 continuity and the retention of identity in difier- 
 ence.^ The point which Gassendi wishes to emphasise 
 is that, if time and change are identical, there is no 
 background to define the movement. If a thing, 
 when it moves, takes its place with it, it moves 
 without change of place, which is nothing at all : 
 similarly, if an event takes its time with it, the 
 time-series is reduced to nothing, a reduction to 
 absurdity which makes it necessary to say that the 
 time is not the change, but the change is in the time. 
 To this point Gassendi clings, but if we seek further 
 
 ^ I. 223. ' Appositum est magis comparare Tempus cum Lucernae 
 flamma, cuius esse ita in fluxu consistit, ut quovis momento alia ac 
 alia sit, et nusquam sit amplius quaecumque ante fuit, nusquam 
 adhuc sit, quaecumque est futura.'
 
 II.] PHYSICS 43 
 
 for some explanation of the permanence implied in 
 this we can find no answer that satisfies. It is 
 to be feared that, following the analogy of space, 
 Gassendi thought of time as ultimately the sum of 
 all times, and so the time of the universe. This 
 comprehensive term substance was the shibboleth 
 that reigned before the absolute, and it swayed 
 men's minds to create concepts beyond their grasp. 
 If my life falls within the life of the world, and 
 that again within the life of the universe, it is not 
 unnatural to picture successively widening areas of 
 time corresponding to the span of each existence up 
 to that last time of the Universe, and if we remem- 
 ber that the Universe is indestructible, it will follow 
 that ultimate time and space are infinite indestruct- 
 ible realities. But what is the difference between 
 ultimate time and any other time, and do we get 
 nearer reality by getting further away from our 
 experience ? Gassendi seems to have omitted to 
 think over the relation of time to our experience, 
 and that in spite of the excellent hint in a passage 
 quoted from Diogenes Laertius, where we are ex- 
 horted to notice not only days and nights, but also 
 ' passionibus et vacuitate ab ipsis.' In the absence of 
 definite information it must be assumed that Gassendi 
 did with time what he did with space: he constructed 
 a rational background to the data of sense, and thus 
 furnished himself with a double theory, one part 
 concerned with time as it is, the other with ultimate 
 time as it might be if it were at all. 
 
 Gassendi proves puzzling to the thoughtful reader 
 by his trick of abandoning one method for another. 
 It is natural to expect that a rationalistic position
 
 44 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 will be developed by deduction. Gassendi on the 
 contrary makes no attempt to develope his theories 
 at all, but simply returns to experience for a fresh 
 start. For all practical purposes he has reduced time 
 to a standstill, and the natural deduction is that the 
 present is illusion. Far from accepting this conse- 
 quence, Gassendi argues that as the present is real 
 time cannot be nothing, and those who consider it to 
 be nothing do so because they erroneously seek in 
 the successive for that which is natural only to the 
 permanent. This can only have one meaning : in 
 the permanent the given points co-exist, and are 
 capable of recurring in experience : in the successive 
 there is no return. Man lives in Space, but he lives 
 through time, and if reason compels us to think of 
 both as wholes, that difference of our experience 
 persists and makes it necessary to form a different 
 conception of each whole. 
 
 The analysis of different kinds of time gives us 
 the so-called real and imaginary times. This was 
 the ancient distinction between the time given in 
 actual experience (real) and that which was before 
 the world (imaginary). This distinction Gassendi 
 repudiates. His time is imaginary in the sense that 
 his space was, and the real time is only one section 
 of that. This shows the weakness of Gassendi's 
 position : for however good his intentions he cannot 
 avoid the conclusion that the time we experience and 
 the time we represent in constructive imagination are 
 identical : which amounts to saying that time is either 
 not experienced at all or is experienced as a whole ; 
 but this would most likely be beyond Gassendi, 
 though he would be quite capable of regarding All
 
 II.] PHYSICS 45 
 
 Time as one object/ especially as he must have 
 regarded the experience of time as essentially a 
 reflective consciousness of what a merely sensitive 
 organism could never comprehend. 
 
 A few more notes must close this summary. 
 Gassendi praises Posidonius for not taking the pre- 
 sent as a mere point. He argues against Aristotle 
 that time is not the measure of movement existing 
 
 o 
 
 only for the calculator, time does not depend on 
 movement, for plurality of movement does not involve 
 plurality of times, nor does a plurality of worlds. 
 In a subordinate sense movement may be said to 
 be the measure of time, as the movement of the sun 
 marks out periods of time. All points of space have 
 one time, i.e. every moment is the same everywhere. 
 On the other hand every point of space has all the 
 points of time, i.e. persists through the whole series 
 of moments.^ 
 
 These remarks cannot be put in any connexion, 
 for Gassendi gives none. He does not properly dis- 
 tinguish the different views of time which they imply. 
 The most noticeable feature is his omission of any 
 distinction of the psychological aspect, an omission 
 which compels us to take his ' moment of time ' as 
 an absolute quantity. While he is clear about the 
 artificial measurements of time, he does not oppose 
 them to the subjective measurement of time, as 
 modern psychology does, but to real parts : a pro- 
 
 1 1. 224. ' Ut Locus secundum se totum est illimitatus, sic Teuipus 
 secundum se totum nee principium nee finem habet.' 
 
 The syntax here shows that we must not call Time a Whole, but 
 say, 'time regarded as a whole.' 
 
 ^Ihid. ' Ut quodlibet Temporis momentum idem est in omnibus 
 locis — ita quaelibet Loci portio omnibus temporibus subest.'
 
 46 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 ceeding which is certainly consistent with his view of 
 time as a whole in some sense suljstantive.^ 
 
 The discussion of eternity which closes this chapter 
 is really concerned with the meaning of timeless, 
 though somewhat indirectly and perfunctorily treated. 
 Eternity might be defined as the time of God, which 
 is to say that it was popularly conceived as the 
 duration of God's life. The notion had passed into 
 philosophical treatises with all its crudities unanalysed. 
 Gassendi furnishes an analysis which dissipates the 
 common notions. He has however a further interest 
 which must be pointed out. The popular idea dis- 
 solves into nothing if we examine the phrase, 
 ' duration of the life of God ' : it at once becomes 
 clear that the foremost idea is that of life, and the 
 understanding of the problem as it concerns time is 
 obscured by the other notions introduced. But over 
 and above this trifling proposition we find a real 
 difficulty in reconciling the concept of God with our 
 concept of time. We must perforce think of God 
 as one to whom past, present, and future are always 
 present : for whom therefore All Time exists at all 
 times, so that ultimately time must be again reduced 
 to a standstill and our distinctions of times to illu- 
 sion. This attack touches Gassendi very nearly 
 because of the way in which he is compelled to 
 maintain that time is a totality : the nature of God 
 seems to turn the scale finally in favour of a static 
 totality. His reply is subtle, but not futile or 
 
 1 His reference to Posidonius must therefore be read as meaning 
 that the present is a piece of real Time, a quantity of duration 
 forming a unit, not a ' saddle-back ' of time ; and the whole is there- 
 fore an infinite multiplication of finite parts. In Time atomism finds 
 a particularly intractable item.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 47 
 
 perfunctory. He says, in brief, that God's he'm<r is 
 purely qualitative, not quantitative, and he is only 
 related to time extrinsically, which practically means 
 not at all. God's being is in fact not an experience 
 at all in our sense of the term. It may therefore 
 be a timeless experience, but it is not an experience 
 of the timeless. The latter phrase would imply that 
 the timeless was a possible object of any experience : 
 the former is one of those negative determinations 
 which, like inhuman, insensible, Gassendi delights to 
 regard as positive. The way in which this can be 
 understood will be best explained if we recall an 
 example by which Gassendi explains how the nature 
 of God is related to space. After remarking as to 
 the place of God, that ' Deus in se est' (i. 191), he 
 quotes the statement ' deum esse habendum prout est 
 in se,' and criticises it by saying God is unlimited, 
 ' sed haec illimitatio seu infinitudo non est quam 
 nomine proprio appellamus immensitatem.' The 
 perfection of God, in short, must be conceived 
 qualitatively : ' ut in lacte aliud est summe candidum 
 esse, aliud esse valde copiosum ' ; and what is thus 
 explained in relation to sj^ace must be analogously 
 applied to time. The idea of substituting intensity 
 for extensity was excellent : it opens up wide possi- 
 bilities for speculative minds. Gassendi, having 
 made it, leaves it alone, thereby showing much 
 wisdom. It is much easier to understand an intensity 
 which does not involve quantity of space than to 
 comprehend an intensity which avoids quantity of 
 time. It is true there is not more whiteness in the 
 milk when there is more of the milk : and similarly 
 we may say that God is not more wise because He
 
 48 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. ii. 
 
 is wise for a greater time. This evades the real 
 problem, which lies in the assertion that if God were 
 God for less time, He would be less a God. So 
 long as time pertains to the nature of God at all, 
 it must pertain as a whole : to answer that it per- 
 tains not wholly, but none the less completely by 
 being intensively perfect, is either to talk nonsense or 
 to confuse time and thought.^ 
 
 ' If it were not so far from Gassendi's general position, this point 
 ■would deserve further consideration. Modern psychology utilizes this 
 distinction of quality and quantity in oi^der to correlate the time-refer- 
 ence contained in an act of memory with the time-expanse of the 
 experience remembered. This line of txiought is entirely useless for the 
 explanation of Gassendi, because it is not the nature of thought but 
 the nature of real time that he is trying to explain. His position 
 therefore leaves him with an existence that has a Time but no times, 
 the whole without the parts. Timeless thought may or may not be 
 more intelligible, but it is certainly not Gassendi's present topic.
 
 CHAPTER III 
 
 FIRST PRINCIPLES 
 (a) THE MATERIAL PRINCIPLE 
 
 Leaving time and space we now descend the scale 
 of Being, and come to pure corporeal reality, the 
 subject to which the term 'physical science' is 
 usually restricted. A speculative element still 
 remains in so far as the nature of ultimate matter 
 is reached by inference, and not given in direct 
 experience. 
 
 The science of ultimate matter carries us beyond 
 the limits of our sensible world ; it takes us there- 
 fore deeper than the elements, which are mutable 
 compounds, to some thing which even the imagina- 
 tion cannot further analyse. It is essential to the 
 nature of ' principia ' that they should not be pro- 
 duced either from one another or from any foreign 
 bodies. Not only must our first matter be itself 
 irreducible to any lower terms, it must also be 
 capable of explaining the solidity of compounded 
 bodies. Its limits are thus theoretically fixable : 
 unity and indivisibility form the maximum ; the 
 mathematical point and the numerical zero form 
 the minimum. These limits must be fixed else our 
 hypothetical material will be incapable of serving 
 
 D
 
 50 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 the ends for which it was designed. As to the 
 maximum, if it be divisible it is not ultimate. As 
 regards the minimum, if it be nothing its multiples 
 remain nothing, and the actual world cannot be 
 generated from it. The danger in this direction is 
 exemplified by two current theories : some reduced 
 the unit of matter to a point which if taken mathe- 
 matically amounts to nothing ; others arrived at 
 the same practical result by going beyond the 
 simplest form of matter to pure form, which is 
 equally destructive of all return to the world of 
 common things. With characteristic ingenuity, some 
 acknowledging the force of argument, compromised 
 by giving matter the ' forma corporeitatis ' 1 
 
 Our ultimate then preserves its physical reality 
 and its 'corpus.' The criterion of this is activity, 
 which we further define as tangibility, for the incor- 
 poreal beings act, but only matter is an object of touch. 
 By ' touch ' Gassendi really means solidity or impene- 
 trability, for this may be a relation between two 
 inanimate bodies ; he thinks with his contemporaries 
 that matter may be taken as real apart from our 
 thought, and as maintaining in that absolute objecti- 
 vity some of the qualities by which we know it. 
 
 We may infer, from the multitude of forms, that 
 matter in itself must be indiff'erent to form. Its 
 quantity must be regarded as constant, change being 
 change of form. The dogma ' ex nihilo nihil ' is 
 a category valid for science, but it does not limit 
 God. This assertion is interesting as an example 
 of the way in which Gassendi is capable of keep- 
 ing to one point at a time. He has no intention 
 of regarding the doctrine ' ex nihilo nihil ' as any-
 
 II.] PHYSICS 51 
 
 thing but absolute ; at the same time it is only a 
 law of thought for the sphere of material production : 
 if we go beyond that sphere to the nature of God 
 or the human soul, its jurisdiction will cease. ^ 
 
 So far we have dealt with a priori necessary 
 determinations of matter : we have now to define 
 its nature somewhat more accurately. The history 
 of the subject presents several theories from which 
 to choose. There are (a) those who think matter 
 has qualities and (6) those who regard it as in 
 itself unqualified. Under (a) we have (1) those who 
 speak only of primary qualities and (2) those who 
 add secondary qualities. To begin with (a) (1) : 
 this class includes the physiologists who took earth, 
 air, fire, water, these being the typical embodiments 
 of the primary qualities heat, cold, etc. Gassendi 
 considers that the choice of one element was really 
 the choice of matter with one primary quality as 
 the unit and the ultimate unit. Under (a) (2) come 
 those who take actual complex substances as the 
 ultimates. Among the ancients Anaxagoras is the 
 example : while the contemporary chymici revived 
 his principles. The class {h) also divides into 
 (l) rationalist and (2) materialist thinkers. 
 Possibly ' spiritualist and materialist ' would have 
 been better terms. Here the atomists are classed as 
 materialist for want of a better term, but the limits 
 to the significance of the word must be remembered. 
 For Gassendi Plato and the Atomists are simply 
 two species of one genus, namely of those who 
 make the matter (A>/) airoiov, Gassendi's history 
 of the emergence of atomism is arranged so that 
 
 >i. 234.
 
 52 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 the first solutions of the problem of an ultimate 
 seem most complex : refinement brings us to an 
 ultimate that is as simple as possible, and we have 
 our choice between making it 'spiritual' (Plato, 
 Pythagoras, and the Stoics) or non-spiritual 
 (atomism). In hoth cases the ultimate is super- 
 sensuous, and therefore 'metaphysical.' 
 
 It is unnecessary to recall all the details which 
 Gassendi laboriously records ; but as it was certainly 
 part of the scheme of his work to furnish a history 
 of human thought before his time, it would be an 
 omission not to allow some praise to the excellent 
 way in which these chapters are arranged, or the 
 clever and, I believe, original classification which 
 enables the author to refine the doctrine down in 
 such a way that the mere history of the case seems 
 an unanswerable proof that the atomistic theory is 
 simplest and best. 
 
 The principal characteristics of the atom as a 
 material ultimate are too well known to need mention 
 here. The doctrine of the Atom does not occupy so 
 much space as might perhaps be expected : it is not 
 the atom but atomism that interests Gassendi. He 
 notes that Democritus gave the atom only Magnitude 
 and Figure, while Epicurus added weight (l. 266, 
 V. p. 3). Gassendi keeps the three. Resistance, he 
 says, is not so much a property as ' ipsammet corporis 
 tribus reliquis [proprietatibus] subjectam naturam 
 [to vTTOKetfievov).' It is, in fact, solidity. The 
 atom has parts (as with Epicurus), but is indi- 
 visible : it is not conjunct in the sense that it might 
 ever be disjunct ; in other words, there is no Void 
 in the body of the Atom. The Atom is said to have
 
 II.] PHYSICS 53 
 
 parts, inasmuch as these are required to account for 
 differences of Figure : there is no mention of motion 
 within the atom, though there is nothing in the 
 world of compound bodies that is not full of motion. 
 ' Considera metallum v.c. plumbum in carino fusum : 
 cum ad speciem nihil quietius, immotiusque videri 
 possit, putasne intra ipsum motus, sive itus atque 
 reditus brevissimis spatiis, celeritate incomprehensibili 
 non fiunt.' 
 
 In following Epicurus and Lucretius on this point, 
 Gassendi does not seem to have noticed that a 
 perfectly hard body is not elastic, and therefore 
 would finally come to rest : which means the 
 destruction of matter. 
 
 The chief point of dispute has always been how 
 far the atom can be conceived purely in terms of 
 reason. The mediaeval thinker was familiar with 
 a * punctum physicum,' a ' punctum metaphysicum,' 
 and a ' punctum mathematicum.' These are not 
 infrequently confused, and Gassendi shapes his argu- 
 ments against writers who were already moving 
 toward the view of an atom as an immaterial point, 
 a centre of force or some cognate form of the doctrine. 
 He resists this tendency because it appears to him 
 to be an excess of analysis, going so far as to preclude 
 all possibility of return.^ He attributes to his atoms 
 magnitude, figure, and weight. They are ultimate 
 so far as we are concerned with the world of things 
 and the category of quantity. In opposition to 
 the average atomist, Gassendi does not consider that 
 
 ' Atomi proinde non puncta sed tenuissima corpuscula sunt 
 praeditique adeo tantula magnitudine quae sit principium et quasi 
 radix magnitudinis omnium corporum.
 
 54 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 our knowledge stops where the quantitative analysis 
 ends. He denies that the atom is eternal or unpro- 
 duced or infinite. God as creator is above and beyond 
 the physical world. With dependence in the way of 
 creation there is combined independence of action : 
 atoms have not ' a seipsis vim motricem,' but they 
 are self-moving ' Dei gratia ' : a distinction which 
 leaves the man of science unhampered and does 
 not despoil the theologian. The theory of creation 
 can be sketched briefly. At first God created as 
 many atoms as were necessary to form this world : 
 the atoms were not necesscmly created separately, 
 but the created mass of matter was such as could 
 be resolved into ' corpuscula ' : each of these minute 
 bodies has its own affinities, and the command that 
 the earth and water should produce plants and 
 animals, was the act of uniting in one place those 
 atoms suited to become one seed : this process can 
 be repeated wherever and whenever such atoms 
 co-exist as are fitted to cohere ; from this we can 
 elaborate the whole scheme of generation and 
 corruption, coherence and dissolution, which makes 
 up the history of the natural world. 
 
 This view clearly involves a possibility of free 
 movement, and therefore raises the question whether 
 the Void is not a principle as much as atoms. 
 Gassendi acknowledges that both are primary parts 
 of the universe ; but he considers that they differ 
 inasmuch as the Void is of the nature of a condition 
 rather than a cause, ^ and only atoms are capable 
 of constituting 'res generabiles.' As matter is itself 
 not a primary but a secondary cause, the validity 
 
 ^ Inane vero solum locum discriminationemque ministiat.
 
 IL] PHYSICS 55 
 
 of this distinction might be disputed : as Gassendi's 
 intentions are clear the point need not be raised. 
 
 (6) PRIMARY AND SECONDARY CAUSES 
 
 A doctrine of causes naturally begins in some way 
 or other with Aristotle. In this case it begins with 
 criticism and selection. The word causa is not quite 
 identical with Aristotle's ahla, the former implying 
 activity, the latter having a somewhat wider denota- 
 tion and meaning origin rather than producing force. 
 Thus of the four causes Gassendi says that Form 
 is properly an effect, matter is not a cause at all, 
 end a wholly different subject, and only the efficient 
 cause a cause in the proper sense. Gassendi is 
 certainly right in pointing out that ' cause ' was a 
 term generally used to denote ' power,' and therefore 
 not identical with the Greek idea expressed in 
 •atVm. 
 
 Confining the word cause to efficient causes, we 
 find that these can be divided into external and 
 internal. An external cause is an object capable of 
 acting on another object, as the sun on wax. This 
 is the field of common observation, and requires no 
 further comment. The question of internal causality 
 carries us beyond this threshold into the secret heart 
 of nature. We have to discover not merely the fact 
 that an object can produce an effect, but also the 
 inner constitution which enables it to act thus. This 
 constitution is the temperament and the source of 
 motion : it might be called the form, since it is 
 the essential part that is the cause of motion. We 
 can say, for example, ' the man moves the stick ' ; 
 and the man is the external cause, but if we wish
 
 56 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 to speak accurately we must assign the activity to 
 the soul, which is the moving principle of the body. 
 There is also a sense in which the end is a cause, 
 in so far as the cause may act for an end, not only 
 blindly, as in instinct, but also consciously, with 
 a knowledge imparted by God, making the agent 
 more than a mere instrument. Gassendi does well 
 to distinguish this from Aristotle's meaning. 
 
 The classification of causes as external and internal 
 is a superficial separation of the popular from the 
 philosophical aspect of causality. The further dis- 
 tinction into primary and se^^ondary is of a diflerent 
 nature and affects the causes themselves. 
 
 We may dispose of the primary causes with the 
 statement that God, as creator and ruler, is the one 
 first cause. The secondary causes constitute the 
 world of nature : their causality is derived from 
 God, but we have much to learn about them, and 
 the acknowledgment of God's power in the world 
 is not to be made an excuse for avoiding the labours 
 of research. 
 
 We must first enquire into the nature of the 
 active principle in things, Some have thought it 
 incorporeal : the Stoics supported the claim of 
 spirits and Epicurus that of atoms. If we make it 
 incorporeal or spiritual, cause becomes separated 
 from matter, and our difficulties increase rather than 
 diminish. It is better therefore to take atoms as 
 the principle and make our cause concrete, that is, 
 call materia actuosa the cause. If the cause be 
 regarded as something immaterial, it becomes un- 
 intelligible : it requires to be united to matter in 
 order to be actual, and has in short all the failings,
 
 II.] PHYSICS 57 
 
 of an unjustifiable abstraction. If matter is declared 
 causal its activity must be its nature : it cannot be 
 said to be active by virtue of containing particles 
 of the anima mundi, for that again is the separation 
 of the activity from the active body. As the cause 
 is matter, matter is active : the particles of heat 
 appear to be most active, so we may fix on corporeal 
 heat {i.e. heat as a substance) as the principle of 
 motion, activity, and causation in things. 
 
 The causality at which we arrive is substantive 
 in every sense of the term. Specific causality may 
 be a relation, but all the relations in which one 
 object can stand to another presuppose a state or 
 condition of the things related, and this state gives 
 the relation its significance. As Gassendi says, this 
 treatment of causality is really an enquiry into 
 temperaments. Given an object A which acts on 
 another object B (external causality), we may call 
 A the cause of B becoming b. But this manifesta- 
 tion is as it were a form of the causality of A, just 
 as A itself is a form of primary matter ; and as from 
 the multiplicity of material forms we argue one 
 indifferent matter, so from the multiplicity of forms 
 of causality we infer one general, indifferent causality. 
 The universality of this causal state is shown in 
 its formula. The composition of any one body is 
 never purely homogeneous : there is consequently 
 ceaseless internal unrest, some atoms freeing them- 
 selves, others struggling vainly in the toils, some 
 striving upward, and others sinking in dull inertia :^ 
 
 ^ I. 3.35. ' Atorni ob sui cuiusque figuram ac moleni aut liberiores, 
 aolutioresque sint et sese facilius ab irretientibus extricent faciliusque 
 vias inveniant quibus per corpus discurrentes inque haereutiores 
 partes impingentes niotum iniprimant.'
 
 58 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 take any apparently inanimate object, and see how 
 it lives in every part of its complex substance : you 
 will then realise that causality is more than a 
 relation, it is a reality in (and perhaps for) every 
 organic and inorganic body. 
 
 Gassendi is often clearer in his thought than in 
 his language. His terms are usually defined with 
 scholastic accuracy ; but the terms themselves are 
 not as yet properly differentiated : they had still 
 to grow and add to slight differences an accretion 
 of argument and reference. It will have become 
 apparent long ago that causality in Gassendi means 
 simply activity. We cannot now speak of one 
 thing being causal, having now recognised that 
 causality is a relation ; but we do still speak as 
 though activity was the property of an isolated 
 object, though usually with an apology to nature 
 and a confession of ignorance. The tendency of 
 Gassendi's period is to take the object as a self- 
 subsisting entity and call it causal. If the analysis 
 is pushed further a curious reaction ensues. Desert- 
 ing the standpoint of the object, we penetrate to 
 that of the atom : causality is left behind, for in 
 the realm of the immutable it can have no place : 
 atom cannot change atom, and so no atom can be 
 causal : the universe viewed as a complex of atoms 
 must equally be void of causality, though replete 
 with activity. In this way even a thorough-going 
 physical realism finds its universal and particular 
 points of view at least superficially contradictory. 
 Gassendi is only dimly aware of this possibility : 
 he never dreams of opposing one part of knowledge 
 to another and dividing himself into the factions
 
 II.] PHYSICS 59 
 
 of appearance and reality ; but none the less he 
 finds that secondary causes ultimately slip through 
 his fingers : the world of change becomes a seething 
 cauldron of endless changes coincident rather than 
 correlated ; and causality driven to the boundaries 
 of the universe is safe only among the attributes 
 of God. 
 
 (c) MOTION AND MUTATION 
 
 The subject of Causality led us finally to the 
 question of internal movement or activity in bodies.^ 
 It is now necessary to discuss the possibility and 
 nature of movement in general. Seeing that the 
 action of secondary causes is as Gassendi here 
 admits, identical with this motion, this book does 
 not deal so much with another subject as with 
 another aspect of the same subject. 
 
 The motion to be discussed is neither the activity 
 referred to before, nor that called mutation : it is 
 
 ^ I. 337. ' Planius ergo did videtur cum in unaqnaque re princi- 
 pium actionis et motus sit pars ilia mobilissiraa, actuosissimaque et 
 quasi flos totius materiae quae et ipsa sit quam Formam solent 
 dicere, et haberi possit quasi tenuissima contextura subtilissiraarum, 
 mobilissiinarumque Atomorum ; ideo primara causam nioventem in 
 Physicis rebus esse Atomos : quod dum ipsae per se, et juxta vim a 
 suo authore ab initio usque acceptam moventur, motuui omnibus 
 rebus praebeant sintque adeo omnium quae in Natura sunt motuum, 
 origo, principium et causa.' 
 
 This quotation shows that Gassendi is confused. Motion in 
 bodies he attributes to the perpetual interaction of their parts, 
 which is possible, because some are finer than others. But the 
 original motion is in the Atom, which, as we have seen, being what 
 it is cannot have motion. To Gassendi this difficulty seems to be 
 overcome by saying God gave the motion to the Atoms. Gassendi's 
 atom is an ultimate, not only in the sense of being the last in 
 analysis, but also as the point at which physical explanation 
 collapses.
 
 60 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 merely local motion, which is best defined as 
 * migratio de loco in locum,' in spite of many- 
 objections, such as his who said the axle of a wheel 
 revolved without changing its place. Gassendi finds 
 it necessary to repel many such objections. These 
 can be passed over in favour of the really important 
 question whether motion is possible at all. 
 
 (1) A single body is always a priori capable of 
 motion, because it is never an abstract (mathema- 
 tical) point. As motion is only attributed to 
 physical bodies, it is irrelevant to reduce a body to 
 merely imaginary unity and still discuss the possi- 
 bility of motion. As every physical body has parts, 
 a change in the relations of these parts implies 
 transference from one place to another, and the 
 whole body may be said to move, though the place 
 of the whole is not changed. The revolving globe 
 is the example intended. 
 
 (2) The more comprehensive question concerning 
 motion in general carries us back to the dialectic 
 of Zeno. Zeno however was really concerned to 
 prove that motion was impossible if motion, time, 
 and space were all continua (ex insectilibus con- 
 starent) : ^ as the atomist does not support that 
 position Zeno's dilemmas may be dismissed. A 
 problem arises as to degree of motion. Suppose 
 a body A moves through a space x in half the 
 time that B takes, can we say the movement of A 
 differs from that oi Bl Gassendi thinks not : 
 movement as such he clearly takes in an absolute 
 sense ; the minima of space and time are indivisible 
 and cannot be reduced : as the body, if it moves 
 
 ii. 340.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 61 
 
 at all, must traverse a minimum of space in a 
 minimum of time, a given space as a multiple of 
 such minima must always be traversed in the same 
 time. For example, a body A which passes through 
 y, a minimum of space, in the minimum of time x, 
 will pass through any space ny in any time nx. 
 
 It follows from this that there are really no 
 degrees of motion : we must therefore explain 
 differences in rates of motion (tarditas et velocitas) 
 by supposing that the slower body has intervals of 
 rest. This is in harmony with the mixture of 
 opposites observable in other directions : for ' hac 
 ratione ex nivis lactisve candore ad corvi, carbonis 
 pervenitur nigritudinem.' 
 
 A final problem arises from the ancient declara- 
 tion, ' si quid movetur aut ubi est movetur aut ubi 
 non est.' This is dismissed by pointing out that 'est' 
 is here used absolutely : the object ' movetur ubi 
 est transeunter, movetur ubi non est permanenter ' ; 
 and with this aro-ument the last obstacle to the 
 recognition of local motion is removed. The jiroof, 
 in fact, consists in defending against time-worn 
 problems the doctrine of self-moving atoms and a 
 void : the position as such depends on these funda- 
 mental views which are to be taken as already 
 proved. 
 
 The next four chapters are a fairly elementary 
 treatise on motion, including the subjects of ac- 
 celeration, projection, and reflex motion. 
 
 Gassendi upholds the distinction of natural and 
 violent motion which Bacon condemns so scornfully. 
 The natural motion is that which atoms have by 
 their own nature : the violent is secondary and due
 
 62 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 to some application of force. If we take nature 
 universally, nothing can be other than natural : we 
 have the right however to distinguish natura 
 specialis from universalis ; and it is a correct scien- 
 tific procedure to distinguish motions according as 
 they are inherent or impressed. 
 
 There are two main principles of motion — impulse 
 and attraction. Gravitation is a form of attraction, 
 but not as some have thought attraction to a 
 place : place as such has no fitness to attract : it 
 is the earth that attracts. This attraction is not 
 to be understood in any vague or spiritual sense : 
 there must be some real, which means material, 
 communication between the earth and the attracted 
 object. How is a stone, wandering in the void, to 
 know where the earth is that it may return to her ? 
 There can only be one answer : ' Praeter id quod 
 in lapide est, transmissio sit quaedam ex terra in 
 ilium, unde ad ipsum pelliciatur.'^ The earth may 
 best be likened to a huge magnet. This position, 
 it should be remembered, is evolved in opposition 
 to the view that a thing had a tendency to move 
 to its ' own place,' or else a tendency to ' seek the 
 earth.' Gassendi rejects the idea of a pZace having 
 any attraction, and proposes to mend the second 
 theory by making both the terms participate in 
 the attraction. Previously the attraction was a 
 * vis insita,' a tendency inherent in the thing and 
 wholly independent of that to which the tendency 
 related. By demanding that the earth should 
 attract the stone Gassendi converts the attraction 
 from a ' vis ab intrinseco pellens ' to a ' vis ab 
 
 ^i. 346.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 03 
 
 extrinseco trahens,' which is a change for the better, 
 even though it falls short of the best. 
 
 It will be apparent from this that action from 
 a distance is not accepted by Gassendi. In dealing 
 with mutation he expressly denies it. Mutatio he 
 treats purely as a kind of motion, and the subject 
 would be of no interest were it not for its con- 
 nection with the question, ' qua ratione per muta- 
 tionem seu alterationem creari rerum concretarum 
 qualitates possint.' After a long and arid tract of 
 discussion on the simplest problems of dynamics, we 
 return to a question that revives our flagging 
 interest. Put briefly, it amounts to this : how can 
 a collection of atoms, having only magnitude, figure, 
 and weight, combine so as to produce other quali- 
 ties, such as taste, heat, and colour ? This is clearly 
 a crucial point for a thinker who is undertaking to 
 build up a highly complex system from simple 
 substances and their movements. 
 
 There is a technical distinction between ' con- 
 juncta,' or properties, and 'eventa.' Magnitude, 
 figure, and weight are conjuncta ; the rest are 
 eventa.^ The primary eventa are concretio, which 
 subserves generation ; and secretio, which subserves 
 corruption, with ordo and situs, which are the 
 foundation of alteratio. Generatio and corruptio 
 
 ^ Cp. I. 266. ' Praeter banc substantiam seu identitateni mavis seu 
 similitudinem dicere, attribuantur Atomis qualitates quaedaiii, sive 
 accidentia, quorum, ut jam aute insinuavimus, alia sunt Insepara- 
 bilia, ax'^pi-o'Ta (sic enim Plutarchus), et Lucretio Conjuncta vulgo 
 Propria appellitentur ; alia separabilia, et Lucretio Eventa, vulgo 
 accidentia communia dicantur : ideo sciendum est, agi heic non de 
 separabilibus, eventisve, qualia sunt concursus, connexio, positio, 
 ordo, etc., sed de inseparabilibus, conjunctisve, seu dicere inalis, 
 proprietatibus ' [e.g. magnitude, figure, weight].
 
 64 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 can however be viewed as alteratio, and we are 
 left with five necessary assumptions — magnitude, 
 weight, figure, order, and position. The first three 
 belong to the atom as such ; the last two are 
 relations between atoms. We are to conceive the 
 variations of composite bodies of atoms as analogous 
 to the various possible combinations of letters (e.g. 
 et, te, roma, armo, etc.). As letters may be worked 
 up into words, sentences, and books ; so endless 
 atoms, in endless combinations, form the great book 
 of nature. 
 
 The starting point is given in the natural dififer- 
 ences of atoms which make some tit to enter one 
 organ of sense, as the eye, and adapt others to other 
 organs, as the ear or the nose. The relation of 
 sensible qualities to the atoms is exemplified in the 
 whiteness of sea- foam or the yellowness of the 
 decaying leaf: in both cases a colour results from 
 a colourless substratum by mere alteration in the 
 disposition of the atoms. The mere fact of change 
 is taken to be a proof that the elements must be 
 neutral. If the atoms had any colour of their own, 
 a complex of atoms would always have the same 
 colour ; but natural changes, such as decay, produce 
 changes of quality ; so the quality must be referred 
 not to the atoms but to their relations. 
 
 This position must be taken in conjunction with 
 Gassendi's views on the senses. At present he 
 leaves the vital question of the relation between 
 mind and object untouched. It cannot be said that 
 he wholly ignores the mind : his reference to words 
 is meaningless unless the mind to which they are 
 presented is assumed as a factor. The letters A
 
 II.] PHYSICS G5 
 
 and B, he says, differ not only in shape but in 
 sound ; but in themselves they have no sound, and 
 only ' sensui diversum sonum exhibent.' He quotes 
 as his own opinion a passage from Galen containing 
 the words ' omnes qualitates sensibiles ex atomorum 
 concursu gigni, quatenus se habens ad nos qui 
 ipsarum sensum habemus.' Here is the first transi- 
 tion from a quantitative to a qualitative treatment 
 of the world in which we live : the task of producing 
 complexity from simplicity is solved by introducing 
 a new factor and correlating a composition of simple 
 elements with qualitative experiences which are not, 
 in that sense, composite at all. The remark already 
 referred to, that A and differ in sowid as well 
 as shape, is itself a comment on this point not to 
 be outdone in significance ! 
 
 {d) ON QUALITIES 
 
 To an empirical philosopher the doctrine of 
 qualities is one of supreme importance. As Gassendi 
 puts it, all reason depends on the senses and on 
 sense-perception : only qualities are perceived, and 
 they are therefore the foundation of our objective 
 world. Substance we only know through induction : 
 all direct knowledge is knowledge of qualities. 
 
 The impression which such a statement leaves 
 on one's mind is that knowledge fails to penetrate 
 into the inner reality of things and remains con- 
 versant only with the outer, and possibly deceptive, 
 surface. Gassendi however does something to miti- 
 gate this superficiality of knowledge. The quality, 
 as he points out, is properly that which answers to 
 the question ' qualis est ? ' Practically qualities are
 
 66 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 accidents, or rather a given state or condition 
 attributed to a substance is an accident, but taken 
 by itself is a quality. It follows that quality in 
 this sense goes deeper than quality in the sense 
 in which we oppose it to quantity : for quantity 
 will be a species of quality in some cases (e.g. tall 
 man) ; and quality will sometimes include relation 
 (e.g. slave). In these cases the determinations pass 
 from the usual category of quantity or relation into 
 that of quality by virtue of being essential. The 
 question then arises whether the absolutely essential 
 qualities of a thing are really qualities or are the 
 thing itself. From the point of view of physics 
 taken in the sense of natural science, the primary 
 qualities must clearly be the inner nucleus beyond 
 which nothing is required : primary qualities will 
 then be only the plural aspect of what we call 
 substance when regarded as a unity. The same 
 point can be looked at in another way. The form 
 of a thing must be a quality in every case in which 
 it is not identical with the spiritus : if the being 
 of a Being is a quality, it would seem that quality 
 ultimately merges into essence and absorbs all that 
 is denoted by substance ; but it must be remembered 
 that we are here speaking of things which are always 
 composite and plural, and so may have an existential 
 form realised in the disposition of parts. Prior to 
 such ' things ' is the single unitary substance which 
 they presuppose and which may be regarded as 
 lying deeper than the outward natures at present 
 under discussion. 
 
 The liberality of Gassendi's interpretation of the 
 term quality can be seen from his inclusion of
 
 II.] PHYSICS 67 
 
 * animal esse, sentire, vegetari, vivere ' in the listj 
 of qualities. A quality must have an objectivel 
 reality, it must be a reality apart from mind. Hence 1 
 a relation as such cannot be a quality, and quantity j 
 will only be a quality when it is essential. If we 
 say 'John is five feet in height' the quantity 
 indicated is a quality : if we say ' John is taller 
 than James ' the quantity is relative and no quality 
 is indicated.^ Gassendi very truly remarks that 
 relations are dialectical and not physical categories. 
 Motion is denied a place among qualities on the 
 ground that it is properly a process to a quality. 
 
 Coming now to the nature of qualities in our 
 world of things, it is obvious that they must all 
 be more or less simple ways of grouping the primary 
 non-qualitative elements of things : in short, the 
 qualities are deducible from the possible modes of 
 combining atoms. For example, density and rarity 
 depend on the proportions of void and matter, or 
 the number of ' vacua spatiola intercepta. ' Figure 
 we may pass over in silence, but weight calls for 
 some comment. Upon weight depends all vis motrix, 
 for the atoms in one body struggle together, and 
 motion follows the striving of the majority, modified 
 by mutual implications. The atoms of spiritual 
 natures are the freest and most mobile : hence they 
 are thought to be the seat of voluntary motion. 
 
 By nature all motion is straight. Divergence from 
 the straight must therefore be explained by percus- 
 sion and repercussion. In order to acquire as it were 
 a fulcrum, one of the moving bodies must be regarded 
 as an immobile. The law is laid down that an 
 
 ii 374.
 
 68 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 immovable part in a whole is essential to mobility. 
 The objection at once arises that, when an animal 
 runs, no part of it is immovable. In reply to this 
 Gassendi apparently practises a double evasion. He 
 first qualifies the law by admitting that the im- 
 movable part only requires to be comparatively such, 
 and then makes it impossible to say what is a 'whole' 
 in respect of motion. In the case of the animal, for 
 example, the modification of ' immovable ' to ' com- 
 paratively' immovable makes it possible to regard 
 the body as giving the required ' immovable ' for the 
 motion of the legs. If this did not satisfy the 
 opponent, Gassendi would doubtless include the earth 
 in the 'whole 'for purposes of motion. At present, 
 however, Gassendi's purpose is purely analytical. He 
 desires to say that motion is innate^ to atoms. This 
 innate motion is the original element of all motions : 
 it is circular, the atoms whirling among themselves 
 aimlessly. By collision new directions are imparted 
 to these atoms, but however much appearances may 
 seem to be against it the circular motion remains 
 at the root of everything. For the present, then, 
 our interest in animal motions may be summed up 
 and left with one conclusion : they have no ' motus 
 rectus qui non sit ex circularibus compositis.' 
 
 This view of motion as fundamentally one has 
 the advantage of reducing to one the various kinds 
 of motion. Impulsive motion is now clearly only 
 an aspect of self-motion : it is self-motion in relation 
 to some other body : similarly ' vis attractrix ' is self- 
 motion in relation to some other body. In opposition 
 to many of his contemporaries, Gassendi requires 
 
 i/.e. implanted by God ab initio.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 69 
 
 actual contact in attraction ; whether immediate or 
 mediate does not matter, but it must be a literal 
 laying hold of the object. 
 
 Faculty is vis motrix, for a faculty is just as 7 
 much as it can do : it is nothing if not active. To 
 this the faculty of Resistance seems ipso facto a 
 contradiction. But, says Gassendi, resistance is not 
 passivity ; immobility is self-centred force : in the 
 case of the earth we have an example of complete 
 rest produced by complete tension of all the parts. 
 (This perfect equilibrium was called motus tonicus.) 
 Having removed this difficulty we may define faculty 
 as ' in unaquaque re ipsummet movendi seu agendi 
 principium, nisi primarium quod formam vocant, 
 saltem Secundarium, seu ex forma profluens eiusque 
 velut instrumentum.' 
 
 The Faculties are not ' a tota substantia ' : they are 
 dependent on the spiritus, for it is the decay or 
 destruction of these principles that involves the loss 
 of the faculties. Gassendi goes further, and says 
 that the faculties and the spiritus are one : for 
 though the spirits mught appear to be a primary 
 organ of the faculties running through the body 
 from the central faculty, yet this is a distinction 
 that involves no difference, just as the waters that 
 run in the streams are distinct but not different 
 from the waters that run at the fountain. This 
 simile does not throw much light on the subject, 
 but is apparently intended to convey the idea that 
 the faculty is only nominally centralised ; in function 
 it is all-pervading. It also follows that all faculties 
 are species of faculty, since they are all reducible 
 to motions of the spirits. As faculty is the same
 
 70 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 as spirit, all faculties are innate. A faculty may- 
 be acquired, but only in the sense of actually absorb- 
 ing the matter to which the power is innate. Iron, 
 for example, only attains the faculty of heat by 
 acquiring the matter of fire, in which the faculty 
 of heat is inborn. We now see that a faculty is in 
 some sense the nature of a thing. It is, in ftict, the 
 nature of a thing looked at from the point of view 
 of active relations. It follows that there are as 
 many faculties as there are possible combinations of 
 atoms and possible relations of these combinations. 
 Speaking of the great varieties of faculties, Gassendi 
 says : ' id facit varietas tum multiformium corpuscu- 
 lorum, ex quibus una tota res constat : tum specialium 
 contexturarum quae varias partes attinent : tum 
 externarum facultatum quibus misceri ipsas con- 
 tingit.' In the apple, for example, different com- 
 binations produce smell and taste. If w^e take into 
 consideration the organ of the sentient being we find 
 still more variations, e.g. pleasant smell, sweet taste, 
 etc. This gives us a division of absolute and relative : 
 for smell is in the object one (absolute), but to the 
 sentient beings manifold (respective). 
 
 The classification of faculties is carried out thus : 
 first, according as the subjects are living or not 
 living. In the case of living things they are 
 (a) general (nutrition, procreation) ; 
 {h) special. 
 This method of classification applies to each class. 
 If we take from among animals. Quadrupeds, we may 
 have general and special faculties within these limits. 
 
 The second method of classification is quite 
 different. Here we divide into principal and
 
 IL] PHYSICS 71 
 
 subservient, the division being decided by the mutual 
 subordination of motions. 
 
 Though a faculty cannot be acquired it can be 
 improved both ' ut fortius operetur et ut expeditius.' 
 For the attainment of greater strength nutrition is 
 required, which means in this connexion the attain- 
 ment of more spirits. The quantitative growth may 
 be accompanied by increase of efficiency attained by 
 use. Habit is the name given to facility of action : 
 this facility may pertain to the spirits or to the organ 
 which they employ, and it is, if anything, more 
 important that it should be realised in the organ. 
 The organ is a crass and rigid thing, against whose 
 unyielding disposition the volatile spirits exert them- 
 selves in vain. 
 
 Matter is thus a hindrance to mind, and habit 
 gives freedom in the sense that when the organ is 
 properly trained the spirits are no longer baulked 
 of their purposes. If, on the other hand, there is 
 no use for the organ it relapses into its original 
 crude condition : for nutrition, continually renewing 
 the substance of the organ, removes by degrees all j 
 the parts that had learned the law, and puts in their | 
 place an untrained rabble.^ This is a rather novel 
 and poetical interpretation of what is generally 
 supposed to result in ' atrophy.' The principles of 
 habit, Gassendi adds, are applicable to all except 
 inanimata, whose changes are purely ab extra. 
 
 One more form of the vis motrix remains to be 
 noticed — that which is called Gravity or Levity. 
 Levity is to be taken as in se nihil, so that we 
 are left with degrees of Gravity. As might be 
 
 ^i. 387.
 
 72 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 expected, the gradation is due to admixture of vacua : 
 the inane is a principle not as acting, but as reduc- 
 ing the ratio of bulk to weight. It is important to 
 notice that Gassendi regards all the action of gravity 
 as extrinsic, thus shaking off once for all, any influ- 
 ences that his predecessors may have exerted toward 
 the acceptance of Love or Hate or any other mystic 
 principles. 
 
 The next qualities may be passed over summarily. 
 They are Heat, Cold, Fluiditas, Mollities, Taste, 
 Smell, Sound. A few points are of interest. Heat 
 may be used as a special term to denote felt heat, 
 or generally (objectively) to denote a condition of 
 body. Calor is a word which denotes, not a quality, 
 but atoms of a certain kind. The atomi caloris are 
 not ex se calidi, but are called so ex effectu. That 
 body is called hot which sends out these atoms : 
 the atoms themselves are not called hot : their power 
 of producing heat is 'objective,' dependent on special 
 forms and activities. We must distinguish then 
 between that Heat which is a real kind and that 
 which is hot either (a) potestate or (h) actu. A 
 thing is hot ' potestate ' ^ when the atoms of heat are 
 retained in it, and hot ' actu ' when the atoms are 
 sent out. Retention of atomi caloris explains the 
 heat of pepper and similar bodies. If a substance 
 contains atoms of heat, motion increases that heat : 
 motion however is not the cause of heat, because 
 substances such as water, which do not contain atoms 
 of heat, are not heated by motion. Gassendi dis- 
 tinguishes between calescere, an internal increase of 
 
 ' The difference between ' potestate ' and ' potentia ' should be 
 noticed.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 78 
 
 heat, which applies only to fats the atoms of which 
 are ' hamatiores,' and calefieri or the attainment of 
 heat from without. 
 
 Cold is the opposite or complementary of heat : 
 it is not privation of heat. This conclusion is based 
 on the differences of the effects : the effect of heat 
 is ' discutere et disgregare,' that of cold ' congregare 
 et compingere.' Further, the atoms of cold differ 
 from atoms of heat in figure : what figure is to be 
 assigned to atoms of cold is a point that the ancients 
 discussed elaborately. Gassendi accepts Lucretius' 
 view that they are 'dentata': our senses can judge 
 how biting is the cold. It should be noted that 
 though Fire is an element, Cold is not : Earth, Air, 
 and Water are not bodies cold by nature, and 
 therefore cannot be summed up as the Primum 
 Frigidum in opposition to Fire, the Primum Calidum. 
 
 In the case of Fluiditas and MoUities, with its 
 two species Ductilitas (as in gold) and Tractilitas 
 (as in our muscles, contraction), we have qualities 
 whose opposites are privations. This will be evident 
 if we consider that mollities, e.g. depends on the 
 degree of * inane ' contained in a body : the inane is 
 not soft, but the real, which is hard, can only give 
 the appearance of softness by including void spaces. 
 
 The next set of qualities are ' ad organum,' or 
 relative to the senses. They all depend ultimately on 
 Touch. In Taste we have particles that act on the 
 palate. Sound has been held incorporeal,^ but its 
 
 ^'Pythagoras, Plato, Aristoteles apud Plutarchum fecere sonum 
 incorporeum.' This was due to their considering the configuration of 
 the air the essence of sound : they took figure ' profunditatis exper- 
 tem,' or abstractly.
 
 74 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 corporeality is proved by the reflex motion required 
 for echoes and the necessity of different configura- 
 tions to produce different sounds. 
 
 In Light we have a subject which, for many 
 reasons, has been a time-honoured field of strife. 
 Gassendi begins with definitions : the object of sight 
 is colour ; the organ of sight the retina ; light is 
 the essence of colour, but is not itself visible. Lux 
 is defined as ' corpuscula tenuissima in corpore 
 lucido ' ; a body is lucidum when it is a fount and 
 source of light ; bodies that depend on others for 
 light are not lucida, but illu strata. To produce the 
 required effect on the organ of vision, Light must 
 be a substantial efiluence. Aristotle indeed thought 
 otherwise, but if we give up the substantiality of 
 Light it will be necessary to employ one of the 
 acknowledged substances as vehicle of light : this 
 vehicle will however be unknown to the organ, for 
 that is only concerned with the visible, so that Light 
 is either itself a substance or involves the inference 
 of a substance. The diaphanous or ' perspicuum ' is 
 the name given to the substance which is the 
 substratum to light. Aristotle conceived its activity 
 as the vibration of a chord and considered the 
 
 activity was the light {evepyeiav Tov Siacjyavov?). 
 
 Descartes adopted a very similar idea, but defined 
 his ' perspicuum ' as a texture of the spherical cor- 
 puscles which fill up the interstices of air, water, 
 glass, etc. — a sort of atmosphere of the second degree 
 of refinement. 
 
 Whatever the origin of light may be, it is itself 
 a corporeal substance somewhat like a bundle of cor- 
 puscles or rays formed of corpuscles. This physical
 
 IL] PHYSICS 75 
 
 reality is merely ' existens ' without relation to the 
 eye : it is ' completa ' when in relation with the eye 
 it produces light as an experience. 
 
 It is necessary to prove definitely that Light 
 is a substance, because this view is rarely accepted. 
 The proof consists in pointing out that Light has 
 certain powers which only a substance can have. 
 These are, first, local motion by which the rays 
 travel from the ' lucidum ' to the ' illustratum.' 
 Action at a distance is a fallacy, so that if the lumi- 
 nous body acts on a distant object, there must be 
 a transmission of the agent or agents through the 
 intervening sf)ace. The second and clearest proof 
 is that of Reflexion :^ for if light were incorporeal 
 it would not rebound from but pass through the 
 opposing body. A similar argument applies to 
 refraction, where the body does not entirely oppose 
 the passage of light but is in some degree 
 * transpicuum.' The similes which Gassendi uses 
 in this connexion are worth noting : speaking of 
 refliexion he compares the light to arrows or 
 javelins striking on a shield and rebounding : with 
 reference to action at a distance he says, if a foun- 
 tain wets your hand from afar it is because it projects 
 a stream of water on you : similarly a fire warms 
 by sending out a ray of heat, or as one might say 
 a spray of heat atoms, and light illuminates by 
 showering on the object 'streams of light.' 
 
 The objection which naturally arose against this 
 substantive view was that the motion of light 
 was too rapid to admit of any such corporeality. 
 Gassendi replies that if light is mere form it is 
 
 1 I. 426.
 
 76 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 everywhere at once and has no motion : if it moves 
 some vehicle is required, and it follows that the 
 vehicle does as a matter of fact move just as fast 
 as light, in spite of a priori objections. Gassendi 
 here seems to be applying a doctrine that was 
 greatly needed — namely that notions of substance 
 must conform to experience, and our experience 
 must not be distorted or even rejected to preserve 
 traditional views. 
 
 Colour is either light itself or something in things 
 to which light is the perfecting form. Light itself 
 is white or that which appears white (nihil esse 
 aliud quam candor candicansve color videatur). This 
 is the fundamental colour, if it be a colour, of which 
 all others are varieties, according to degrees of 
 mixture of darkness. 
 
 The last of the sensible qualities is the imago, or 
 visible species. This subject naturally follows the 
 discussion of Light and Colour, and is properly a 
 question of the perception of forms. As a question 
 of perception it comes under Vision ; but objectively 
 considered the species are qualities, and must there- 
 fore be considered in this place. The simplest course 
 is to say that the vision ^ of an object is the light 
 radiated from it and determined by its form and 
 colour. Gassendi declines to leave the matter there, 
 but as the question of the nature of these ' visions ' 
 has attracted so much attention he reviews the whole 
 history of the subject. 
 
 As nothing is absolutely smooth, but has on closer 
 
 ' The English word ' vision ' has exactly the double meaning (act 
 of seeing, thing seen) which expresses the problem that troubled the 
 ancients.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 77 
 
 inspection numerous 'faces,' the species can be pro- 
 jected in a straight line in any and every direction. 
 It follows that a thing can be viewed from any side, 
 and no two views will be exactly alike, though 
 generically alike. The objects in the field of vision 
 can be accommodated in the eye, in spite of their 
 great number, because the area surveyed is hemi- 
 spherical in shape, and the species are propelled 
 along lines which converge into a point. 
 
 The nature of the species has been differently 
 conceived by different schools of writers. The 
 ' nominaleis ' say they are accidents : if so, they 
 must be dependent for transmission on the air ; 
 but an accident is not a reality unless it can be 
 separated from the vehicle which it uses : in this 
 case no separation is possible, and therefore species 
 are not truly accidents. Again, from the analogy 
 of sounds the idea arose that the object as a whole 
 produced movements in the surrounding atmosphere, 
 and so, as it were, sent forth pictures of itself. 
 Against this Gassendi argues that the theory in- 
 volves a movement of the object which sends forth 
 the picture, whereas seen objects are frequently 
 motionless. 
 
 These two phases of the doctrine that species are 
 insubstantial are rejected, as might be expected from 
 what has been already said about Light. Epicurus 
 thought the species were corporeal and of two kinds, 
 namely (a) ' coagmentationes ' or spontaneous group- 
 ings of atoms, such as occurs in a mirage, and (b) 
 ' effluxiones.' It is with the second of these that 
 we are really concerned. Any given body as an 
 object of sight is supposed to be continually giving
 
 78 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 off atoms. These form a picture of the thing by 
 purely natural means. As all atoms move in straight 
 lines unless deflected, and all have the same rate 
 of speed, these ' exhalations,' as they may be called, 
 retain the original disposition of their parts and 
 so produce an effect symbolic of their origin and of 
 nothing else. It is necessary to notice the difference 
 between this and the other view, that the object 
 as a whole produces a picture of itself. Upon that 
 view Gassendi pours scorn: the rock we see would, 
 he says, be in that case a consummate painter, 
 obviously meaning that the theory has a mystical 
 element. The second theory is mechanical: the 
 motion required is not of the whole as such : there 
 is only the innate motion of the atoms : the retention 
 of the original form is due to the mechanical pro- 
 perties of atoms moving in a medium too subtle to 
 disturb them normally : and, finally, the effect is not 
 a picture in the sense of being itself a representation 
 of the thing : it is an effect upon the organ of sight 
 which by these means attains a picture of the object. 
 In the former case apparently a ' picture ' was 
 supposed to float in the air : in this case the atoms 
 are not the picture but the cause of the picture : 
 just as light was a reality but not a complete reality 
 apart from the eye, so the picture is only realised 
 for a beholder, and apart from any eye is only an 
 agglomeration of atoms. 
 
 Gassendi defends the view that ' effluxiones ' are 
 substantial, not because it is right but because it 
 is less wrong than the other view. The real difficulty 
 is to explain how things can go on giving off matter 
 and yet never be exhausted. The usual plan of
 
 II.] PHYSICS 79 
 
 explainiDg that the ' effluxiones ' are subtle beyond 
 all comprehension (omnem modum excedentes) is, 
 to say the least of it, feeble. But Gassendi attempts 
 no other, and appears to satisfy himself that it is 
 possible to have a substantial loss, which being 
 infinitely small only becomes perceptible in infinite 
 time. The real difference between an infinitely 
 subtle ' imago ' and an imago that is an accident, 
 is a question of terms and technicality rather than 
 commonsense. Gassendi apparently means us to 
 understand that what we see is the light from a 
 thing as that light is aff'ected by the thing : beyond 
 this there is nothing but tradition. 
 
 There remain now the so-called occult qualities. 
 These constitute a special class ; for certain qualities 
 are popularly regarded as peculiarly ' occult ' : in 
 reality all qualities are occult in some degree, and 
 the difference between ' occult ' and ' manifest ' is one 
 of degree only. What we look for is some explana- 
 tion of an effect : an occult cause is merely an 
 imperceptible quality which we attribute to an object 
 in order to explain the effects we believe to be 
 derived from it. The most typical of all these 
 qualities are the two know^n as Sympathy and 
 Antipathy. Now all the effects produced exhibit 
 the common forms of activity : we are therefore led 
 to assume that the cause can be interpreted in terms 
 of motion, though that motion may be too subtle 
 for our senses to perceive. 
 
 The assumption that all relations of cause and 
 effect are reducible to motion and communicated 
 motion, prepares us for a rationalistic explanation 
 of these miraculous qualities. When the chameleon
 
 80 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 puts forth its tongue to catch the fly, we see the 
 agent of attraction : when the electrical body attracts 
 other bodies, how can it draw them to itself if not by 
 ' innumerable rays darted out like tongues'? Beyond 
 the world of our senses lies another, identical in kind 
 but too minute for ordinary perception : if our senses 
 were magnified these invisible agents would start 
 into life : we should see the tiny thorns wherewith 
 the nettle stings us, and perceive the corpuscles 
 whose unsuitable shape makes the object painful to 
 our sight. All sympathy and antipathy then is a 
 question of physical causation, of 'corporea organula': 
 love and hate are ultimately physical, and friend is 
 literally like friend, for the essence of affection is 
 congruence of atoms ! The ancient philosophy of 
 Hate and Love is now completely inverted : physical 
 relations take the first place and repulsion or attrac- 
 tion explains all : repulsion need not be hate, but 
 hate is always repulsion. 
 
 The general theory of occult causes is now disposed 
 of: the discussion of particular instances has only a 
 secondary interest. The cases classed as ' general ' 
 are (a) conspiratio partium universi and (b) influxus 
 coelestis. The former is identical with the dread of 
 a vacuum attributed to nature : the latter is a subject 
 about which we know little so far as astrology is 
 concerned : the movement of the tides is not really 
 a case of 'influxus lunae.' 
 
 The special cases also need not detain the reader : 
 why the sponge attracts (sic) the water is a question 
 hardly more scientific in form and suggestion than 
 the later query, Why does a cock frighten a lion ? 
 Both these cases seem explicable in ways not par-
 
 II.] PHYSICS 81 
 
 ticularly 'occult.' In dealing with the occult qualities 
 of plants Gassendi shows a very interesting phase of 
 the development of thought : the love of the vine 
 for the elm might be pure poetry, but there were 
 relations between plants which were thought to be 
 of real importance : the female palm, for example, 
 was said to be fertile only when sown near the male : 
 the truth which might underlie this observation was 
 obscured by the notion of subtle ' effluviae ' trans- 
 mitted from one to the other.^ 
 
 Gassendi discusses very gravely the occult quality 
 of hate as existing between the sheep and the wolf : 
 he says, ' ovis quidem odit lupum, nee immerito : ab 
 illo enim dilaniatur ' : the wolf however does not hate 
 the sheep, for he is good to eat : the apple may hate 
 us, but we who eat it say we like it. There is a 
 subtle vein of animism in all these popular fancies 
 which the philosopher still finds himself compelled 
 to treat seriously. The evil eye, the power of incan- 
 tations, the virtue some plants possess of healing the 
 wounded by being applied to the sword that struck 
 the blow : these and many others mark the flights of 
 undisciplined imagination. In the last case Gassendi 
 makes an interesting remark : the power of the drug 
 applied to the sword was supposed to reach the 
 wounded man, however far away, because the soul 
 of the world is one, and so what affects one part 
 must aff"ect the whole and all parts : thus Unity 
 received an apotheosis almost before it was born ! 
 
 *Nehemiah Grew, whose investigations developed the idea of sex 
 in plants, was born in 1628, and did not publish his work until 1681. 
 It is improbable that Gassendi had an accurate knowledge of the 
 subject, though possibly it was 'in the air.'
 
 82 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 (e) ON THE ORIGIN AND DECAY OF THINGS 
 
 Whatever our ultimate views may be on creation 
 and annihilation, there remains untouched by these 
 the whole sphere of becoming. Becoming can be 
 regarded from two points of view, according as we 
 consider that which becomes or that which ceases 
 in order that something may become. The negative 
 aspect of the becoming of any one thing is the ceas- 
 ing of its antecedent, so long as we allow that the 
 antecedent is really and truly such : if however we 
 prefer to deny the antecedence and declare the whole 
 movement of Becoming illusory, change may be 
 refined away to nothing more than variation of 
 qualities. In order to be clear as to the scope of 
 this discussion, the terms employed must be care- 
 fully distinguished. The first is creation, which 
 means the production of something out of nothing : 
 the second is mutation, which denotes a change from 
 one state to another. Now this change may afiect only 
 the quality of a thing or the thing itself: in the former 
 case it is called Alteratio, in the latter Generatio. 
 
 These extreme points of view are represented on 
 the one hand by Parmenides and all who deny 
 motion, on the other by those who regard all new 
 forms as creations. The standpoint exemplified in 
 Parmenides is that of the monistic schools for which 
 substance means the Whole rather than the Thing. 
 From this interpretation it naturally follows that all 
 change is change of the Whole, and since the Whole 
 cannot become something other than itself, the change 
 is ultimately an illusion. If, on the other hand, 
 substance means Thing, change will mean that one
 
 II.] PHYSICS 83 
 
 thing becomes another thing, at least in the sense 
 that one thing gives place to another thing. But 
 even those who take substance in the pluralistic 
 sense do not agree in their explanation of change : 
 to many the idea of one thing becoming another 
 thing is repugnant : the tendency then is to return 
 to the position of Parmenides, but apply his doctrine 
 not to Substance but to substances. To do this suc- 
 cessfully we must establish our ultimate substances. 
 Common experiences can be appealed to as a proof 
 that we know what we mean by change. Every day 
 there is some new thing under the sun about which 
 we feel that to-day it is and yesterday it was not.^ 
 But if our ultimate substances are things each with 
 a character of its own, the alterations it can undergo 
 must be limited by the necessity of retaining the 
 character. An acorn may become an oak, but the 
 oak does not become an elm, says the opponent : 
 when pressed further he will explain that the acorn 
 is potentially an oak, and therefore its development 
 is determined. But either the acorn is or is not an 
 oak : if it is an oak the Becoming is pure illusion : 
 if it is not, what is the principle of becoming ? The 
 answer is combination of parts. As these parts pre- 
 cede the whole, they are themselves neutral, i.e. fit 
 to enter into any combination." Generation is now 
 
 ^ ' Perspicit abunde sagacitas tua, quo dicere sensu cum Sapiente 
 potuerim " nihil esse sub sole novum." Quare et lubens tibi sub- 
 scribo dum argumentaris nova esse omnia, ob continentem, quae in 
 rebus observitatur, mutationem ' {Ep. L. Valesio, 1647, vi. 264). 
 
 2 This must be taken with a limitation. The actual ultimate is 
 not the atom but the 'semina rerum,' i.e. atoms qualified to enter 
 into any combination of a given kind. The process of Generation is 
 ' assimilation,' or reunion of like with like, a process of selection as 
 well as combination.
 
 84 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 definable as mixture of parts : the matter is given 
 in plants and animals as much as in houses : the 
 mixture makes the thing ! 
 
 It is clear that our neutral elements are the atoms. 
 Creation is the act that produces these primary- 
 elements : the atoms are created, not the world : the 
 world is the product of atoms endowed with a motion 
 of their own. One difficulty, however, remains. If 
 the matter is always the same, and the thing is a 
 combination of parts differing from other things not 
 in the nature of the ultimate elements but in their 
 combination, is it not really the Form, and the 
 Form only, that is generated ? Gassendi attacks this 
 position with skilful dialectic. It is said that when 
 a combination is effected a form is educed : this form 
 was not present before actu but potentia : then how 
 can it be educed any more than gold can be educed 
 from an empty purse ? ^ If the form does not arise 
 out of the matter, we have not eductio but generatio : 
 a form, that is, is realised which did not exist before, 
 and that is just what we mean by generation. If 
 the form is asserted to be something distinct from 
 matter, and yet no matter is lost in producing Form, 
 the Form must be especially created and we are 
 committed to a constant miracle. 
 
 1 1. 468. 'Eespondent potestatem materiae respectu Formae 
 duplicem esse, unam eductivam, quatenus forma potest vi agentis 
 ex ilia educi : aliam receptivam quatenus potest eandem forman 
 ex se eductam recipere : sicque materiam utraque hac potentia 
 formam continere. Ac priraum continere aliquid eductivS, potentiS. 
 nihil aliud est quam habere actu in se, quod possit exinde educi. 
 Ita crumena, in qua sunt actu decern aurei, dicetur illos continere 
 eductiva potentia, quatenus inde educi possint : nam alioquin, nisi 
 actu in se haberet, ii ex ea educi non possent, neque crumena dici 
 posset continere eductiva potentiS,.'
 
 II.] PHYSICS 85 
 
 The result of our review of all previous doctrines 
 is then the survival as fittest of the common-sense 
 standpoint : and the achievement is perhaps greater 
 than it appears at first sight. At one point Gassendi's 
 position seems very much exposed, but the opponent 
 is silenced in anticipation. If mind is not matter, 
 have we not here a case in which a combination of 
 elements of one kind produces or conditions the 
 generation of a reality of a different order? The 
 point may be dealt with in two ways ; the first is 
 to stolidly assert that mind is a form of matter 
 generated by the particular combinations of matter 
 which it is found to accompany ; the second is to 
 attribute it to the act of God, and so leave it. 
 Gassendi chooses the second course, perhaps wisely.
 
 SECTION B
 
 CHAPTER I 
 THE INANIMATE WORLD 
 
 The second part of the Syntagma begins with a 
 treatise de rebus terrenis inanimis. The majority 
 of its contents are not worth reproduction in full or 
 with any degree of exactness. The connexion of 
 these chapters with the scheme of the whole work 
 may be gathered from the summary of the subject 
 matter already given (v. p. xii). A few points of 
 particular interest may be selected for special 
 comment. 
 
 After dealing with the land and the water, in- 
 cluding seas, rivers, and the tides, we advance to the 
 bodies that are found in the earth. These are 
 cla-ssified as ' mista perfecta ' in order to distinguish 
 them from the 'meteora' (winds, clouds, rains), which 
 are imperfecta : they are also called compositiora, 
 because they a,re compounded of more than one 
 element. This class includes Fossils, Plants, and 
 Animals. The term ' fossil ' is used in the bare 
 sense of things which have to be dug up : as a rule 
 this is limited to stones, metals, and minerals ; but 
 there are other treasures in the bosom of the earth 
 which are omitted by this limitation, and Gassendi 
 proposes to include under this heading the primar}-
 
 90 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 forms of matter which are ' liquidiora. ' We are now- 
 dealing with the very lowest forms of existence. 
 Gassendi's intention is to begin at the bottom of the 
 scale of existence and rise in orderly procession to 
 the highest. He is not content with starting from 
 even such elementary stages as are given in metals, 
 but desires to get deeper still, to the most formless 
 conditions of matter, and begin with what he calls 
 the ' mean forms ' out of which nature constructs 
 the comparatively developed things called metals. 
 These ' mean forms ' or first conditions of matter are 
 the various kinds of earth, the ' succi concreti ' and 
 the ' mista mineralia.' The kinds of earth are first 
 enumerated and their relative fertility is commented 
 on ; then the succi concreti are catalogued in the 
 two main classes macri et pingues (among the macri 
 salt comes first, among the pingues sulphur and 
 bitumen are the most important), and finally the 
 mista mineralia are given in their order. Beyond 
 being an integral part of Gassendi's universe these 
 have no interest for us now, but as part of that 
 conception they demand attention. As we are now 
 in the realm of things inorganic the question of 
 becoming is important. Each class of things has 
 / its own semina and each thing is formed by the 
 I cohesion of semina of one kind : that is to say, 
 1 generation is a simple process of cohesion of homo- 
 I geneous parts, and as there is no question of voluntary 
 \ unions, the production of any specimen of this class 
 I is dependent on the chance which collocates in one 
 place the kindred elements. Whatever we may have 
 to say later on about alimentation and the purposive 
 union of parts, this is the sphere in which we can
 
 II.] PHYSICS 91 
 
 subscribe unreservedly to the action of chance as it 
 was primarily conceived by the earlier atomists. 
 
 Passing over the intermediary discussion of vol- 
 canoes and earthquakes we can take up at once the 
 question of the formation of inorganic bodies as it 
 is described by Gassendi, with special reference to 
 ' lapides ' or stones in the sense in w^hich we use that 
 term when we speak of precious stones. It is absurd 
 to suppose that all these were created at the be- 
 ginning of things once and for all. Apart from the 
 inherent improbability of the idea, we can see for 
 ourselves that the process is going on around us 
 every day. The matter is in this as in every case 
 given. The point which calls for explanation is the 
 regularity with which similar forms are constantly 
 produced. For this we must postulate a formative 
 power, a vis interna, in this case a vis lapidifica : 
 there is no less reason for asserting the existence 
 of this formative power in the case of stones than 
 there is in the case of the plant or the chicken.^ 
 If any doubt remained it would be dispersed by the 
 instance of crystallisation in which the presence of 
 such a causa constans is indubitable. This vis 
 lapidifica is a form of vis seminalis, that being the 
 more general term : in the case of some animals 
 and in plants the vis seminalis is obscurior ; and in 
 the case of stones it is still more obscure, but not 
 
 * ' Quamobrem calor quidem et frigus conferre interdum ad niaturi- 
 orem coitionem indurationemque possunt aliquid, at debet esse 
 praeterea vis quaedam lapidifica, quani et seminalem dicere nihil 
 vetat . . . est praeterea vis seminalis quae ex preparata materia tam 
 plantam quam puUum delineet : ita quo lapides formentur debet 
 omnino praeter calorem aliudve agens extrinsecum esse interior quaedam 
 vis quae conformationem moliatur et seminalis censeri possit' (ii. 114).
 
 92 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 on that account to be denied altogether. We must 
 not however deduce from this too much : although 
 gems and all other stones are formed by the action 
 of this vis seminalis they are not on that account 
 to be called living things : they have not life in 
 the sense that the plants have : they are solid com- 
 pact bodies in which there is no circulation and no 
 alimentation, not even through that which they call 
 ' insensilem transpirationem ' : they do not grow in 
 the proper sense of the term, and we certainly cannot 
 infer from the fact that one gem is bigger than 
 another that it is therefore older, or ' grown up ' ! 
 The coral does indeed grow, but then it is a 
 plant ! 
 
 The most important topic in this book is that of 
 the magnet. Gassendi has used the magnet fre- 
 quently in the later parts of his w^ork by way of 
 example, and, as it is one of those marginal topics 
 which seem to have a mystical affinity with higher 
 forms of existence, it will be as well to examine 
 carefully what Gassendi has to say here, where he 
 treats the subject directly and in its proper con- 
 nexion. The point about the magnet is that it 
 exercises attraction. When the iron comes within 
 its range it is drawn tow^ard it by some invisible 
 power, and the data thus given to the ordinary senses 
 of man are exactly fitted to encourage idle specula- 
 tion. In the first place Gassendi asserts that the 
 action of the magnet is purely physical : it must 
 therefore be mediated action, not action at a distance, 
 and the mediation must be achieved by a substan- 
 tialis corporeusve effluxus : there is to be no shirking 
 of the question by introducing emanations of a
 
 PHYSICS 93 
 
 douuo- .1 order: if we had the required keenness of 
 sight we should see the hooks by which the magnet 
 lays hold of the iron. That is one question, and so 
 far we seem on safe ground ; but a more critical 
 point is raised by the two statements that the magnet 
 has something analogous to plants and to sense. 
 The analogy to plants turns out to be a similarity 
 of habits such that, as a cutting can only be grafted 
 on to a tree in one way, so the magnet can only 
 be joined to another magnet or a part of itself 
 according to the way the fibres run. As regards the 
 analogy of the magnet to that of the sensible agent, 
 the analogy consists in the following points of re- 
 semblance. (1) As the animal is attracted by the 
 object, so the iron is attracted by the magnet 
 (2) The action is in both cases per immissas species 
 that is, a definite something is emitted by the one 
 which passes over to the other. (3) The species thus 
 emitted enter into the soul of the object in both 
 cases and produce the disturbance which results in 
 the consequent movement. (4) The activity of motion 
 in both cases begins from the soul. 
 
 This language looks on the face of it extremely 
 animistic : none the less Gassendi does not mean 
 to imply that the magnet has a soul in the proper 
 sense of the term at all.^ He carefully adds every 
 
 ^ ' videri esse in magnete ac ferro vim quandaiu analogam sensui : 
 id nempe propter attractionem baud absimilem Animali. Nam ut 
 Animal specie quadam objecti externi perculsum, ipsura statim 
 appetit, et ad illud rapitur : ita minor magnes ac ferrum quani- 
 primum maioris sive potentioris magnetis specie percellitur, appetitu 
 quodam rapitur ad ipsum. Certe ut sensibile objectuiu non. . . . 
 Et ut objectum sensibile per immissam speciem convertit trabitque 
 ad se animam quae vi sua corpus quantumvis crassum una versus 
 objectum transfert : ita et magnes per transfusam speciem videtur
 
 94 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 time he mentions the word anima the qualifying 
 quasi : he distinguishes the other anima to which 
 this is analogous as anima sentiens, and assures us 
 that the magnet has only 'something analogous 
 to a soul' What we have in fact is a type of 
 motion ; what we might call responsive motion ; 
 and Gassendi is well aware that when he comes to 
 sensibility he will not be able to tell us much more 
 about it than can be summed up in some such phrase 
 as this of responsive motion. The significance of 
 this will be pointed out later (p. 262) : for the 
 present it is enough to show that we cannot assert 
 on the basis of what Gassendi has to say for himself 
 either that matter is always endowed with soul, 
 or that soul is always material : similarity does 
 not exclude diff*erence, nor does difference destroy 
 the possibility of co-existing similarity : the eagle 
 and the oyster are far enough apart, and yet 
 we find reason to put them on the same scale : 
 can we not then put the magnet and the animal 
 in some relation of similarity, though the mag- 
 net is no more an animal than the eao;le is an 
 oyster ? 
 
 The subject of Plants, which occupies the second 
 part of this section on things inanimate, is important 
 in one respect. We shall pass over all that is 
 
 ad se convertere trahereque ipsam quasi aniniam (seu florem sub- 
 stantiae) ferri, quae sua vi totam ferri massam versus magnetem 
 una abripiat. . . . Quare ut hoc modo subingressa speciei corpuscula 
 in substantiam animae (partisve sentientis ipsius) illam ita sollicitant 
 ut non sine quodam impetu in objectum feratur : ita videntur 
 corpuscula speciei magnetis subingressa ferri quasi animam, ipsius 
 corpuscula sic evolvere et in magnetem convertere ut hac ratione 
 sollicitata impetum vegetum in magnetem concipiat et quod amplius 
 est etiam parem speciem illico diffundat.'
 
 II.] PHYSICS 05 
 
 said on the kinds and classification of plants, and 
 confine our attention to the consideration of their 
 nature, and the place which they are to occupy in 
 our scheme of the universe. Gassendi begins with 
 the most important point, namely the question, have 
 the plants a soul ? Many writers had held this 
 theory : as a rule it was a deduction from the 
 doctrine of the world-soul, and there were great 
 differences in the extent to which the doctrine was 
 pushed : the Manichaeans, for example, ' sic dederunt 
 plantis animam rationalem ut florem aut fructum 
 decerpere foret homocidium patrare ' : ^ while Aristotle 
 represents the other extreme of moderation in attri- 
 buting to them only a nutritive soul. Epicurus is 
 in direct opposition to these ideas, and declares that 
 plants have no soul at all, an opinion with which 
 Gassendi finds himself in perfect accord. He reviews 
 the meanings attached to the word animatus : its 
 Greek counterpart -^i^x'' i^ from '^v)(eh, which is to 
 say, ' flando refrigerare,' and this we all know is 
 peculiar to animals ; plants are not even animals 
 in the strict sense of ^wa, much less animata corpora ; 
 and finally, if we think of the derivation from avefxo^, 
 i.e. spiritus, this too excludes plants from the class 
 of animata. But while he is thus clear that a plant 
 is not an animal Gassendi obviously feels that there 
 is some excuse for the general tendency to give plants 
 a place in the scale of nature much nearer to the 
 animal than to the stone : he therefore enumerates 
 all the ' wonders of plant life ' which were known 
 in his day and seem to have been as fruitful a source 
 of credulous wonder then as now. There is doubt- 
 
 ^11. 144.
 
 96 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 less much that is to us extremely wonderful in the 
 apparently purposeful activities of plants, but, says 
 Gassendi, however wonderful they may be, the 
 original question, are there any proofs of a soul?, 
 remains unanswered : anima is often used loosely, 
 and we speak of things as animated^ to which we 
 should not give a soul if required to do so explicitly ; 
 in other words, there is much we call animate that 
 we should never call animal. We are in fact caught 
 between the animal sphere and the too comprehensive 
 sphere of nature in general. Finally, Gassendi defines 
 the plant as corpus vegetabile sensu carens, admitting 
 that it would be more natural, if less exact, to say 
 corpus animatum, i.e. ' vivens quod nutriri, crescere, 
 sibi simile generare possit.' 
 
 This last point directs our attention to the question 
 of the origin and perpetuation of plant life. The first 
 plant in the world's history must have arisen from a 
 conjunction of like atoms, and this was in the usual 
 way fortuitous. But the tendency which united the 
 first group of atoms in the first plant works on a 
 smaller scale in keeping together those atoms which 
 are the specific semen : hence the process of reproduc- 
 tion is made easier, and the reason why plants are 
 localised is apparent. In this connection Gassendi 
 returns to the question of the soul : the marvel of 
 the structure of the plant with all its adaptations and 
 contrivances rouses him to further comment on that 
 formative power which is thus shown to be innate to 
 the plant. We must, in fact, allow that there is a 
 central principle, and we may even call it a soul 
 
 ^ We now speak of animated pictures as well as animated 
 nature !
 
 II.] PHYSICS 97 
 
 if it be ^remembered that by this term we denote 
 only a definite principle, a substance most like to 
 a flame, which is indeed spread through all the 
 plant, but is especially concentrated in the parts 
 which form the seed (ii. 172).
 
 CHAPTER II 
 
 THE ANIMATE WORLD 
 
 (a) INTRODUCTORY 
 
 The third section of the second part of the Syntagma 
 has two ' membra ' dealing with natural objects (rebus 
 terrenis) in general. We have discussed the former 
 part, and can now proceed to the second. The dis- 
 tinguishing characteristic of the subject-matter is 
 Life, in the sense which is implied by the title 
 Animate as opposed to all the previous existents 
 which have been classed as Inanimate. The highest 
 class of Inanimata comprised Plants : the specific 
 difi'erence which brings us to the next highest stage 
 is the appearance of Sensibility. The name Animal 
 is given ^«a rr^v aia-Orjcnv irpcoToog (ii. 193), hence we 
 shall not object to including under this title those 
 forms of organic life which have only the rudimentary 
 sensibility shown in reaction to touch, namely Zoo- 
 phytes (Plantanimalia), to which we can ascribe only 
 Tactus, and (perhaps) its localized form, Taste. With 
 this general determination of what constitutes an 
 Animal, we may proceed to classification. The stars 
 and the gods we may neglect, in/ sj)ite of Plato and 
 Aristotle : we have then terrestrial creatures left : 
 of these there are many traditional classifications.
 
 PT. II.] PHYSICS 99 
 
 (1) The division into Rational and Irrational is 
 bad : for it introduces a negative class, and does 
 not exclude immortal beings who might certainly 
 be rational. 
 
 (2) An obvious division would be according to 
 mode of motion, e.g. the classes Volatile, Natatile, 
 Gressile, Reptile, Tractile, Immotum ; but this is 
 unsatisfactory, since the classes overlap, and there 
 seems to be no principle of division. The question 
 indeed arises whether a classification which serves 
 all purposes can be found. Generally we classify 
 to suit some particular purpose (pro occasione 
 petimus) : we choose as our basis, mode of genera- 
 tion, distribution of parts, habits (mores), nature 
 of food (ratione victus), or even the locality in 
 which the creatures are found. In such cases the 
 end must justify the means, but no one of these 
 can claim to be a final and universally valid 
 classification. Gassendi finally adopts the division 
 into Sanguinea and Exsanguia, acknowledging its 
 many faults, but finding it more adapted than any 
 other to comprehend such a large and various range 
 of objects. In spite of scholastic objections we do 
 finally adopt a negative classification : Gassendi 
 realises that such a dichotomy may fail in face 
 of species which are neither, and weakens his posi- 
 tion in so far as he seems to intend, not so much 
 to classify all animals as to make a classification 
 under which the animals are to be subsumed, 
 whether they will or no. It is essentially a 
 scholastic trait to make the law first and then adapt 
 nature to it. The scheme of classification which 
 guides the author through the remainder of this
 
 100 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 book is so hopelessly out of touch with our concep- 
 tions that it may be consigned to oblivion : his 
 treatment of the subject is an excellent example of 
 his discursive style. He ranges from the elephant 
 to the fly, quotes authors innumerable, discusses 
 the probability of Centaurs and Sirens, and grants 
 respectful consideration to derivations of names too 
 ludicrous to be any longer amusing. 
 
 The Second Book opens with a formidable col- 
 lection in two chapters of all the names of the 
 parts of the human frame and of those parts which 
 are found in animals, but not in man. This too 
 is a mine of curious information, but hardly such 
 as would justify reproduction. The construction of 
 the sense organs we shall consider later, and pass 
 over the rest in silence. 
 
 (b) ON DESIGN IN NATURE 
 
 Under the heading ' Use of the parts in Animals ' 
 Gassendi elaborates his views on the teleological 
 question. Epicurus, in accordance with his theory 
 of atoms and their fortuitous concourse, had denied 
 that the parts of the body were dilFerentiated for 
 definite purposes. Eyes were not made for seeing, 
 nor ears for hearing : if the contrary is asserted, it 
 will follow that hearing existed before the ear, 
 seeing before the eye, which is nonsense : and 
 Epicurus finally leaves the difi'erentiation of organs 
 unexplained, but accounts for difference of function 
 by supposing that the application of the Soul to 
 the organ results in an activity determined by the 
 nature of the organ (e.g. seeing, when the applica- 
 tion is to the eye, and so on). This conclusion
 
 II.] PHYSICS 101 
 
 may be briefly stated by saying that the function 
 is the efl:ect and not the (final) cause of the organ. 
 Against this Gassendi argues at great length ; but 
 in spite of the clearness of his statement he seems 
 to have overlooked a rather obvious confusion, for, 
 if we speak of the eye, the ear, or the nose, we 
 naturally think of them as differing, because we 
 think of their correlatives in perception (sight, 
 hearing, smelling). If we resolutely exclude all 
 ideas of the sensations, and consider only the organ 
 as a mere compilation of atoms, the position of 
 Epicurus reduces itself to the unprovable proposition 
 that movements of difl"erent kinds of atomic groups 
 are different kinds of movement. This is not quite 
 such a quibble as it appears : for we have to 
 remember that Epicurus was not thinking of an 
 organism differentiated by the action of an environ- 
 ment which is the ground of variety in experience, 
 but of an organism which is in itself so differen- 
 tiated as to be able to produce variety in the 
 experience of a Soul which is a unitary thing going 
 out to its world. 
 
 While accepting the general theory of Epicurus, 
 Gassendi declines to commit himself to a rei2;n of 
 chance. His remarks are an instructive comment 
 on a stage of thought which so nearly arrived at 
 truths only recently appreciated. He recognises that 
 natural selection (natura electionis capax. ii. 228) 
 has determined what forms shall survive : from the 
 innumerable host of the created only some survive, 
 ' illas puta quas contigit habere parteis sic con- 
 stitutas ut nactae fuerint accommodatum ad sui ip- 
 sarum conservationem generationemque consimilium,
 
 102 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 usum.' Galen is quoted as the authority for an 
 opinion held by Epicureans that the tendons of the 
 hand are strong, not for use but from use. 
 Thirdly, the question is raised, if rain falls on the 
 crops by design, why does it also fall on the sea 
 and the rocks? We have here three distinct ques- 
 tions — first, as to creation ; secondly, as to develop- 
 ment ; lastly, as to God. 
 
 (1) The question of creation is taken as wholly 
 distinct from that of development : as the point 
 cannot be settled, Gassendi thinks it best to ascribe 
 creation to God, rather than chance. 
 
 (2) The remarks on development must be con- 
 sidered carefully, else it is easy to attribute to the 
 writer a position far beyond his actual attainment. 
 Instances are quoted of adaptation to circumstances, 
 as the hardening of the soles of the feet in people 
 who go barefoot : cases of useless parts in creatures 
 are noted, as, e.g., cur mares quoque expertes 
 lactis mammas haberent. But in neither case is 
 the real significance apprehended : for Gassendi 
 never seems to regard development in a way that 
 would admit of new species arising ; nor does it 
 occur to him that a structure that has no function 
 indicates a radical process of change. He was open- 
 minded enough to admit that a useless appendage 
 was no credit to Providence, but the idea that 
 development from one form to another might be 
 indicated by stages in which rudimentary organs 
 survived, belongs to a scheme of the universe not 
 revealed to Gassendi. For Gassendi, as for Epi- 
 curus, all process and becoming virtually ceased 
 when the world as it now is began to be. The
 
 IL] PHYSICS 103 
 
 primeval matter — the atoms — might of course pro- 
 duce new forms ; but practically it is assumed that 
 the number of successful possibilities is now ex- 
 hausted. In this way an evolutionary is combined 
 with a static view of nature. 
 
 (3) In dealing with the question of a Creator, 
 Gassendi is not so hampered by the claims of 
 orthodoxy as on some other occasions. His middle 
 course is not only suitable to his orthodoxy, but 
 philosophically possible. We must not admire the 
 temple and ignore the architect,^ and as some 
 creative power, both wise and intelligent, has to 
 be acknowledged, it matters little whether we call 
 it nature or God. Mingled with the rhapsody 
 which proclaims the Creator we find some shrewd 
 remarks : the order of the Universe compels us to 
 see behind it a mind ; but the compulsion is 
 aesthetic, and the assertion of God rests on faith 
 rather than argument : the crude teleology which 
 has raised such bitter discussions is annihilated by 
 the remark that function and organ cannot be 
 separated : one does not come before the other 
 either logically or in the time order, and the 
 creature cannot be considered in abstraction from 
 the world in which he lives. Thus Gassendi avoids 
 the dogmatic tone of Lactantius, and preserves his 
 faith without sacrificing his reason, while his asser- 
 tion that current teleology is based on a false 
 abstraction marks an enduring distinction between 
 those who acknowledge the fitness of things and 
 those who would advance beyond the given data 
 to prove special design. 
 
 In. 231.
 
 104 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENUI [pt. 
 
 To make Gassendi's position clearer, I may add 
 the following quotation from Wallace, Epicureanism 
 (p. 115): 
 
 ' Throughout the whole of his explanation of the 
 origin of the earth . . . Epicurus is careful to ex- 
 clude any reference to divine action. There was no 
 design, no plan determining beforehand the process 
 of evolution, and adapting one part of the cosmic 
 structure to co-operate with another. ... In all 
 its phases teleology is extruded. The very animals 
 which are found upon the earth have been made 
 what they are by slow processes of selection and 
 adaptation. . . . Plants and animals have the same 
 source as rocks and sands. It is from the seeds or 
 elements contained in the earth that the animals 
 have in some strange maternal throes (as Lucretius 
 somewhat j&guratively puts it) been evolved in their 
 season : they have not fallen from heaven. The 
 same naturalistic explanation is given of the special 
 endowments of human beings. The organs of sense 
 were not given us ready-made in order that we 
 might use them : that which is born in our body, 
 on the contrary, generates for itself a use. The 
 structure, for example, which we call the eye was 
 not given us as an organ of vision : it arose, we 
 need not enquire too curiously how, and it was found 
 to be useful for the perception of objects in the 
 light. Whether this use by degrees created an 
 organ more and more appropriate for its purpose — 
 function, as it were, perfecting the organ — is a 
 point apparently not discussed by Epicurus.' 
 
 Thus much about Epicurus. As regards Gassendi, 
 we may say that he does consider the last point
 
 n.] PHYSICS 105 
 
 mentioned as omitted by Epicurus, and this has led 
 him to see that there is a rehxtiou between the omau 
 and its function which is not expressed in a doctrine 
 of chance. In order to understand Gassendi, we 
 must keep in mind that there are three distinct 
 points of view. (1) We may rely on chance : this 
 excludes creation and design. (2) We may say that 
 the organ was designed for its function. This sounds 
 reasonable enough if taken wdth the significance that 
 the terms would have in modern parlance. In the 
 language of this period it implies that the function 
 existed before the organ, that there was a seeing 
 which was literally antecedent to the being of the 
 eye. This was easily shown to be absurd. In 
 modern evolution we have a totally different scheme, 
 the two factors given us in, e.g., Spencer's account, 
 are the sensitive material and light : in this scheme 
 it is light which exists before the eye ; in the other 
 scheme we have sight in place of light, which makes 
 all the difference. (3) We may refuse to accept 
 chance and decline to say that each organ w^as 
 specially created, but declare that the result proves 
 that there is design enough in the universe to 
 make possible those combinations of matter which 
 are required for these functions. If it were a case 
 of all chance, we might have only organs we did 
 not want, e.g. eyes in a world without light. 
 Selection can remove those organs we do not use, 
 but it could not create others. On the other hand, 
 if Providence controls every detail, the design would 
 be better than it is !
 
 • 
 
 106 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. 
 
 (c) THE THEORY OF THE SOUL 
 
 Gassendi discusses the nature of the Soul, not, as 
 might have been expected, in direct connection with 
 his psychological theory, but between the discussions 
 on the parts and the generation of animals respec- 
 tively. This will however be justified when we 
 understand the sense he attaches to the term Anima. 
 
 Primarily, it is the specific diff'erence which dis- 
 tinguishes the Animal from the inanimate and from 
 plants : for little as we may know about it, the soul 
 of the animal is assuredly something very distinct 
 from that soul which we may concede to plants. 
 Gassendi holds a modest opinion of his own ability 
 and the value of the discussion. We cannot expect, 
 he says, to learn the nature of the soul : it will be 
 enough to know what has been said about it ; the 
 Church alone gives us certainty on the subject. 
 With this tribute to orthodoxy, the philosopher 
 proceeds with the perilous theme in a manner which 
 his contemporaries must have regarded as dangerous 
 free thinking. 
 
 We are accustomed to confine psychology to the 
 study of phenomena in some degree intellectual.^ 
 The mediaeval thinker avoided this path to error 
 by keeping two terms for all that we include under 
 
 ^ I say ' in some degree intellectual ' without forgetting that the 
 tendency of much of our modern psychological writing is to go 
 beyond what we should ordinarily call intellectual phenomena. In 
 spite of this, and in spite of our 'animal psychology ' (which is largely 
 engaged in proving its own possibility) and our treatment of sub- 
 conscious phenomena, not to mention our phrenology and our analysis 
 of adolescence, we have not yet got to the point at which we could 
 speak of an active principle which did nothing but control digestion, 
 as a ' soul.'
 
 II.] PHYSICS 107 
 
 the name ' Soul.' For the intellectual agent the 
 term Animus is used : Anima is a more comprehen- 
 sive term, and may be translated 'principle of life.'^ 
 The historical discussion is, as usual, a splendid 
 display of erudition : one chapter deals with those 
 who consider the soul incorporeal, another with those 
 who regard it as corporeal. If it be regarded as 
 incorporeal, it may be either substance or attribute, 
 i.e. either an ' existens quidpiam in se,' or a form, 
 quality, accident, or inseparable adjunct. Pytha- 
 goras, Plato, and the Platonists are mentioned as 
 authorities for the view that it is a substance, 
 while to those who regard it as an attribute belong 
 Aristotle and all who define soul as a harmony 
 (Dicaearchus, Asclepiades), a theory best known by 
 the argument of Simmias in the Phaedo, though 
 others seem to have given it a different phase by 
 speaking of it as a harmony of the senses or a 
 temperament. The variations of the theory that the 
 soul is corporeal are scarcely worth recapitulating. 
 Gassendi notes that no one ever thought it of the 
 nature of earth — air and fire were the more usual 
 analogues — and quotes the well-known theories of 
 early Greek philosophy. More important than these 
 is the view that the soul was a ' spiritum ex sanguine 
 factum ' : so Virgil says, ' purpuream vomit ille 
 
 ^This would not be admissible in all cases. Some thought that the 
 possession of Anima constituted a degree of dignity which could not 
 be attributed to all creatures, an opinion which was due to the 
 tendency to confuse the Anima Mundi with God, and a consequent 
 repugnance to including in the Anima Mundi beings not worthy 
 of the heaven of the elect. Hence the term Anima came to mean 
 soul in the sense in which it is used in the phrase, 'the soul that 
 sinneth it shall die.' For that class of thinker animals must be 
 automata.
 
 108 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 aniraam,' and in the Bible we read, 'Vox sanguinis 
 fratris tui claniat ad me de Terra ! ' St. Augustine 
 thought the authority of the Scriptures indecisive, 
 for blood might be taken not as identical with, but 
 symbolic of, the soul : as the ' sedes immediata ' of 
 that all-pervasive principle of life. The ancients 
 too seem not to have meant sanguis, but rather 
 'sanguinis flos,' which is a possible interpretation of 
 * spiritus ex sanguine factus.' Galen and Hippocrates 
 supported this view, which ranked as the ' scientific 
 solution ' of the problem ; and here we have the 
 origin of those ' vital airs ' which played so large a 
 part in mediaeval psychology. 
 
 Gassendi is satisfied that the Anima is corporeal : 
 the inheritance of certain characteristics (non linea- 
 menta corporis solum sed etiam nota animae), the 
 fact that soul and body may be similarly affected, 
 that what nourishes the outer nourishes also the 
 inner man — these facts and the authority of the 
 fathers settle the question. It is characteristic of 
 Gassendi to settle one point at a time : so far we 
 conclude the soul to be corporeal, i.e. substantial, 
 not mere quality or disposition or symmetry of 
 material parts, but itself a ' principium agendi.' The 
 ' materialist ' to-day inclines to make the soul a 
 non-entity, an epiphenomenon. Gassendi argues that 
 it does act, and because it acts it must be itself a 
 reality, a thing not a shadow, substance not mere 
 relation (as in a 'harmony'). This decision that Anima 
 is under the Category of corpus, does not decide 
 what kind of corpus it is : so long as it is not mere 
 quantity or quality or relation it must be corpus. 
 Modern arguments turn mainly on the question
 
 II.] PHYSICS 109 
 
 whether a soul is body or spirit : Gasseudi's primary 
 task is to decide whether it is something or nothing : 
 whether the something is bodily matter or non- 
 bodily matter is a question of secondary importance. 
 An examination of the views of Epicurus leaves him 
 with no satisftictory position : ^ he feels moreover the 
 danger of dealing with the Anima in any way that 
 mig'ht bring him into collision with ecclesiastical 
 authority : he chooses therefore to express himself 
 de anima brutorum, though it is not the anima but 
 the animus which makes the crucial distinction and 
 
 ^ Cp. with the account of Epicurus the following remarks by 
 Gassendi (ii. 248-250) : ' Epicurus probably made the atoms of the 
 soul round : he does not seem to have said what they were so much 
 as what they were not : Lucretius says " fugiens nil corporis aufert," 
 which dematerialises the concept : "ad haec memorant Plutarchus et 
 alii Epicurum non fecisse simplicem Animae naturam sed esse 
 voluisse Kpa/xa (K T€cr<rdpoiv, e'/c ttoioO wvpwdovs, e/c TrotoC aepuiSovs, (k 
 iroioO TTvevfiaTiKov, e/c Terdprov TLvbs aKaTavofidffTov S 9jv avT(^ alcdi)TiK6v 
 (Stob. Ed. Phys. p. 798), temperatum quid ex quibusdam quattuor 
 nempe ex quodam igneo, ex quodam aereo, ex quodam flatuoso, ex 
 quarto quodam innoniinato quod ipsi est sentiendi vis": the four 
 mix in such a way as to produce a one (inde fiat una quaedam sub- 
 stantia). We see from this passage (1) that the matter is defined 
 so as to be practically immaterial ; (2) that a substance is introduced 
 simply to explain that which the others do not explain, sentience ; 
 (3) there is no suggestion of direct perception of a soul : it is an 
 inference, relying mainly on an induction from the data of a living 
 and a dead body by a method of diff"erences. The Logic of the 
 argument is curious. It is said, a dead body is not lighter than a 
 living body, hence the soul has no weight : a dead body does not 
 feel, hence the soul is that which has feeling, etc. These two argu- 
 ments alone would prove (1) that there was no soul, or else that it 
 stayed in the body, and (2) that death is loss of feeling — not of a 
 soul that feels. The assumption of the soul made these "proofs" 
 pass muster ; but it is obvious that it would change the position 
 very little indeed if we left out the soul as it is and confined 
 ourselves to what it does. 
 
 *Gass. sic. ToOro 5' Jjv Ritter et Preller 384.
 
 ^ 
 
 110 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 superiority of man.^ The following data seem cer- 
 tain : the anima is collateral with life ; vita est quasi 
 praesentia animae in corpore : and therefore neither 
 cor nor sanguis can be identified with it, since these 
 may remain unimpaired after death. Secondly, it is 
 aliquid pertenue, and in fact not an object of the 
 senses at all : it can be perceived only by reason 
 which deduces its actuality from the necessity of 
 finding a principle of motion and nutrition. The 
 deduction is not criticised by Gassendi, but is 
 obviously faulty : the proof says, ' when the soul is 
 in the body the functions are possible : when it 
 departs, they are impossible,' a use of the deductive 
 canon which assumes that existence of the soul is 
 previously established. Thirdly, soul cannot be either 
 a Form or a harmony of elements, for it must be an 
 active principle, and if we call it Form or Harmony 
 it becomes a mere relation. Thus we arrive at the 
 definition that Anima is very slender substance as 
 it w^ere the flower of matter, with a specific habit 
 or disposition or symmetry of its parts : as substance 
 its extreme mobility qualifies it to be the principle 
 of all action, and its particular symmetry determines 
 the quality or mode of activity. It is in fact, 
 
 ^11. 250. 'Principio vero distinguendum inter Animam Hominis 
 Animaliumque aliorum est : et cum operosior res sit circa Animam 
 Hominis, ideo videtur prius dicendum de caeterorum Anima, ut de 
 qua Mentis immortalis experte et philosophari liberius, et falli minore 
 cum periculo liceat.' It should be noted (1) that Gassendi expressly 
 says he will take for examination the Anima, 'quae sit in perfecto, 
 sanguineo, respiranteque animali,' and what is said of this will be 
 true of all ; (2) that Gassendi obviously thinks that what is said 
 about the Anima not conjoined with Mens will be true of the com- 
 posite Anima and mind. In both cases therefore the difference is in 
 the function, not the substance, for, as nothing is subtracted in lower 
 forms, so nothing is added in the higher.
 
 IL] PHYSICS 111 
 
 * corpus, id tamen tenuissimum ' ; the physical body- 
 is massa corporis crassioris, and it is only relatively 
 to the crass body that we call the Anima ' incor- 
 poreal.' Again, as substance it is a contextura of 
 very subtle atoms, which maintains its unity though 
 extended throughout the body, the heat of the body 
 depends on it, and therefore it must be of the nature 
 of fire, which is also proved by the necessity of 
 heat for digestion and nutrition. This is the reason 
 for the circulation of the blood, namely to prevent 
 it from coagulating and cooling ; this process causes 
 a distribution of heat from the heart, while the 
 action of the lungs cools the heat and provides an 
 escape for smoky vapours. The expansive power of 
 heat explains the efficiency of the soul : we shall 
 not marvel that the elephant can be moved by its 
 soul if we remember the force which heat can im- 
 part to a cannon-ball ! The cold-blooded animals 
 offer a problem which is solved by the concept of 
 
 * insensible heat,' and we need not be troubled about 
 the fish, for they seem to lack the right ventricle 
 which is the place of heat (in quo calescere incipiat) 
 and the lung which carries off the adverse humours : 
 hence the fire is somewhat dulled in them (calorem 
 obtundat). Gassendi will not endorse the opinion 
 ascribed to Empedocles that fish from excess of heat 
 took to the water refrigerationis gratia ! 
 
 (d) THE ANIMA HUMANA 
 
 The human soul might well be regarded as 
 differing from that of animals in degree only. The 
 objection to this is that it would place the brute 
 creation on the same scale as man, and make their
 
 y 
 
 112 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [PT. 
 
 equality with man possible. The ecclesiastic mind 
 therefore prefers to assume that only the human 
 soul is qualified to receive ' supernatural gifts,' and 
 deduce from that potentiality a distinction of kind. 
 At the same time it had to be admitted that the 
 human soul has a sentient and a vegetative capa- 
 city, and is in part dependent on natural generation, 
 so that any explanation which is to be satisfactory 
 must allow for both aspects. Two theories hold 
 the field : the first declares the soul to be a simple 
 substance with dual functions, viz. the inorganic, 
 or those which require no organs (e.g. Intellection 
 and Volition) ; and the organic, which requires 
 bodily organs (e.g. Nutrition). This soul, they say, 
 is put in the body by God ready equipped with its 
 faculties : authorities have differed in the explana- 
 tion of the process which results in the presence of 
 the soul, some ascribing it to a direct act of God, 
 others to an evolution in which the vital seed 
 acts as a medium. The second theory declares 
 that the soul is not simple but twofold, having 
 a rational and an irrational part. This is more in 
 conformity with theology ; and the unity is not 
 more incomprehensible than the unity of soul and 
 body, which we are accustomed to accept without 
 demur. 
 
 Gassendi adopts this position ; but it is impossible 
 to avoid feeling that he regarded the question as 
 one of small philosophical importance, or at least a 
 point at which right reasoning must conform to 
 orthodoxy. On the other hand, apart from opinions 
 on its origin and destiny, the human soul must be 
 a separate subject of enquiry in so far as it fur-
 
 II.] PHYSICS 113 
 
 nishes rational phenomena which are not available 
 from other sources. Gassendi tells us nothinsf of 
 the nature of the ' Anima humana ' in the sense in 
 which he determines the nature of the ' Anima 
 brutorum ' : he seems to have thought that the dis- 
 tinctive features of man belonged to the Animus ; 
 and while he is incapable of generating from the 
 corporeal soul of animals the incorporeal soul of 
 man he suggests that the combination of corporeal 
 and incorporeal soul in man is no more or less 
 difficult than the union of corporeal soul and crass 
 matter in the brute. It would seem therefore that 
 man only differed in the degree to which he is 
 divine ; and as Gassendi asserts that all life is 
 divine in its degree, it is difficult to avoid the 
 conclusion that he views the whole scale of being 
 as having differences of degree only. 
 
 When in Physicae, ill. 4. 4, he discusses the 
 generation of animals he makes the Anima a con- 
 tinuous existence, so that birth is not a stage giving 
 Anima, but a stage in the history of Anima — a 
 stage at which it becomes individualised, as the 
 Anima of a plant individualises itself when an off- 
 shoot becomes an independent existence (ii. 279). 
 The rational part, being given by God, cannot of 
 course share this continuity : none the less there is 
 no period when a soul destined to be rational is 
 without rationality, the organs of intellectual activity 
 may not be developed, but these are necessary, ' ut 
 operari anima, non item ut inesse possit.' Thus he 
 renders the distinctive birth of the rational soul 
 unprovable, and even asserts that its emergence at 
 some definite time in the history of the foetus or
 
 114 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 the child would be a case of ex nihilo quid ; ^ but 
 surely the phrase, ' corporis expers a Deo creetur 
 infundaturque in ipsum corpus,' either implies 
 absolute creation or means nothing at all. 
 
 My view of the point is that Gassendi purposely 
 states the received dogmas, with respect, and at the 
 same time intentionally reduces them to futility. 
 Whatever the value of this view may be, it is 
 derived from a careful study of his writing, and I 
 conclude that Gassendi's real view of the soul makes 
 it one in all entities, from the stones to man, but 
 with such obvious distinctions of degree that it is 
 no loss practically to admit differences of kind : 
 the common denominator cannot be shown ; and 
 just as a scale of colours is only a scale if we 
 look at it from the point of view of vibrations, but 
 in itself has differences of quality, so life has dif- 
 ferences of quality which cry aloud for reduction to 
 
 ^ II. 281. I.e. because if we could say at such and such a time 
 that the offspring is without the anima, and then afterwards that 
 it now has the Anima, the soul must be educed from nothing. 
 The whole passage is very interesting, but too long to quote. 
 Writing in 1629 to 'D. Thomae Fieno, in Inclyta Louaniensi 
 Academia, Professori Medico Primario,' Gassendi speaks as though 
 he had already made up his mind on the point. At first, he says, 
 I thought the child derived its Anima from the parent, being only 
 an offshoot, like the cutting from a tree (juvabat me exemplum 
 rami resecti ex salice). But this clashed with the testimony of the 
 Scriptures, while it was supported by the evidences of heredity ; 
 so the only solution was to acknowledge that the Anima was twofold, 
 and say the Anima sensitiva is ex parente, the Anima rationalis was 
 created and 'poured in' by God, 'statim atque decisione facta, seu 
 foetus seu seminis, rationalis Anima Parentis seu foetum seu semen in- 
 formare desineret' (vi. 19). This statement is at once more orthodox 
 and dogmatic than that in the Syntagma. The real reason for dis- 
 tinguishing the being of the Anima rationalis is the need for a position 
 that will combine the facts of heredity with the truth of immortality.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 115 
 
 unity, but cannot be reduced until some other term 
 is found, such that degrees of life can be formulated 
 as its powers. One such ' other term ' we have 
 always with us, viz. Motion : it is not the least 
 interesting part of our work to watch the extent 
 to which Gassendi employs it.^ 
 
 (e) THE BASIS OF PSYCHIC LIFE 
 
 Faculties are natural, vital, and animal : of the 
 animal faculties some are cognitive, and the most 
 fundamental is the sensitive. The word sensus 
 may mean the faculty or the function, the power 
 of feeling or the state of feeling. We have four 
 terms, sensus, cognitio, perceptio, apprehensio : per- 
 ception, apprehension, and knowledge, if taken in 
 the widest sense, mean the same. Sensus and 
 cognitio denote a more explicit state, i.e. a relation 
 of subject and object in which the two are dis- 
 tinguished : perceptio and apprehensio are used for 
 a more implicit state, i.e. for what goes on in the 
 subject, whether consciously recognised or not. This 
 is made clearer by an example : suppose a magnet, 
 a flint, and some iron to be together in one place : 
 the iron has a perception of the magnet which the 
 flint has not : again, suppose a goat and a fox to 
 be standing under one tree : the goat perceives the 
 tree (assuming it to have edible foliage) but the fox 
 
 ^Cp. with Gassendi's words what Lotze says in his Outlines of 
 Psychology (§ 81): 'At the place where, and at the moment when, 
 the germ of an organic being is formed amid the coherent system 
 of the physical course of nature, this fact furnishes the incitement 
 or moving reason which induces the all-comprehending One to beget 
 from himself, as a supplement to such physical fact, the soul 
 belonscinar to this orsranism.'
 
 116 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 does not : these are parallel cases, and yet neither 
 is an example of what we usually mean by sensation. 
 Suppose we say ' is vero est sensus qui finiri solet 
 facultas percipiendi objecta sensibilia ' : we then have 
 a definition which defines both the faculty and the 
 object : consequently relativity is introduced, and 
 we must admit sensibility everywhere : if you say 
 the magnet has not sensus, the answer will be it has 
 sensus for its own particular sensibilia, as the oyster 
 and the monkey in their degree. As there is then 
 no justification for limiting sense to man we must 
 accept this result ; but we may distinguish general 
 from special sensibility. The former may be defined 
 as any motile response, and covers the case of all 
 objects not animal — especially magnetic bodies and 
 plants : the latter is sensibility as we know it. 
 There is a distinction between these, and therefore 
 it is confusing to speak of the relation of inorganic 
 things as antipathy or sympathy. Sense taken uni- 
 versally is the capacity for affinities or simply natural 
 affinity : Sense taken specially is not merely a faculty 
 of receiving species, but a reaction in which we 
 know what the species is a species of. This might 
 be called a teleological distinction, for Gassendi 
 recognises that as reactions all sensibility might be 
 reduced to a capacity for reaction to an appropriate 
 stimulus : it would thus be reduced to a mode of 
 motion, and he says it must be taken ' primum 
 universe pro quacumque facultate rei cuilibet natura- 
 liter insita ad percipiendum aliquid, cuius perceptione 
 seu mavis apprehensione moveatur.' In recognition 
 of this he adds that the sensus in animals is one 
 with the vis motrix corpusculorum movendi sive
 
 II.] PHYSICS 117 
 
 agendi facultas {De Sensu Universe, ch. i.). This 
 activity is not transeunt but immanent, and is a 
 disturbance ^ of the ' sensitive ' organ. 
 
 It is obvious from what is said above that Gassendi 
 opposes those who translate lower functions into 
 higher. He will not allow that all ' motile response ' 
 is sensation. This point is so vital to the under- 
 standing of Gassendi and has been so consistently 
 misunderstood (from my point of view), especially in 
 reference to the magnet, that I feel justified in adding 
 still another note to what has been said elsewhere. 
 
 I will quote first a passage from The Atomic 
 Theory of Lucretius, by John Masson (1884), p. 141, 
 part of a note entitled ' Note on Professor Clifford's 
 theory of mind-stuff as anticipated by Gassendi ' : 
 " again, because all living things, even the meanest, 
 those spontaneously generated, come from seminal 
 molecules, each after its kind, which have existed 
 either from the beginning of the world or from a 
 later time, ' for this reason it cannot be said that 
 conscious things come from non-conscious, but rather 
 from particles, which, though they do not actually 
 possess consciousness, nevertheless actually are or 
 do contain the elements of consciousness (principia 
 sensus).' Are not these 'elements of consciousness' 
 contained in Gassendi's molecules much the same 
 as Clifford's simple elementary feelings or Mind- 
 Stuff? Gassendi does not, it is true, say that every 
 separate atom contains an element of sensation. In 
 reality, by his distinction between prima materies 
 or non-conscious atoms, and secunda materies or 
 molecules which possess in a faint form the rudiments 
 
 ^Alteratio, cp. Stoic, eTepoiuais.
 
 118 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 of sensation, he does not at all escape the difficulty 
 of the origin of consciousness, which indeed he, like 
 Epicurus, very slightly realises.' 
 
 My objection to this as an interpretation of 
 Gassendi is as follows. The mind-stuff theory starts 
 from the top and asserts that the mind is made up 
 of parts, each of which is in its own nature mental : 
 it is a theory of the evolution of mind. Gassendi, 
 on the contrary, only tries to work out the analogical 
 relations of natural forms so as to show the evolution 
 to mind. In the mind-stuff the common denominator 
 is mentality : in Gassendi it is motility. Clifford is 
 far nearer Leibnitz than Gassendi, and Gassendi 
 is a long way from Leibnitz. The difference finally 
 lies in the view one takes of the concept of poten- 
 tiality, and as we have pointed out this is a concept 
 to which Gassendi takes objection. On Masson's 
 own showing the 'particles do not actually possess 
 consciousness ' : he does not seem to have understood 
 that Gassendi would not entertain the idea of poten- 
 tial presence, and therefore the statement that the 
 particles do not possess consciousness 'actually,' means 
 that they do not possess it at all. As I have tried 
 to show, Gassendi, for better or for worse, prefers 
 to take it that the peculiar properties of each degree 
 of organic life cannot be found in the parts as they 
 are before they are found in the synthesis of the 
 organism, but supervene on the fact of that synthesis. 
 The effects are data to be co-ordinated, not explained. 
 Gassendi would have said of nature as a whole what 
 James says of mental phenomena, that the square 
 of a plus that of 6 is not the same as the square 
 of (a + 6).
 
 II.] PHYSICS 119 
 
 This point is, I am afraid, somewhat laboured. In 
 excuse I plead that it is vital, and has not been 
 understood by those who refer to Gassendi. As a 
 rule we are told that 'at any rate Gassendi says 
 the magnet has feeling,' so we may consider the 
 evidence on this point and take the conclusion as 
 proving the general position. In the chapter on 
 Gravitation we have the problem of attraction on a 
 large scale: Gassendi discusses it on the analogy of 
 the magnet, and we read, ' attractionem verbo fieri 
 a Terra, corpusculis missis, quibus illiciat lapidem, 
 eadem ratione qua et magnes emittit quibus pelliciat 
 ferrum' (i. 345). This, be it remembered, is stated 
 in explicit opposition to the idea that the stone 
 has any feeling after the earth, or any knowledge 
 where the earth is. On page 337 we read, ' vide- 
 licet praeter moralem metaphoricumque motorem 
 (the reference is to Aristotle's idea of that which 
 moves as end only) quaeritur quod sit in unaquaque 
 re quae per se agit ac movetur principium actionis 
 seu motionis primum. Neque enim cum puer ostenso 
 porno ad ipsum currit, requiritur solum quae meta- 
 phorica sit motio, qua pomum puer alliciat, sed 
 maxime etiam quae sit intra ipsum puerum physica 
 seu naturalis vis qua dirigitur ferturque ad pomum.' 
 This vis physica cannot be aroused by any but a 
 physical effluxus, and the movement of that which 
 wants to that which is wanted is primarily due to 
 an actual physical relation. Add to this what is 
 said in the preceding paragraph and it will be clear, 
 I think, that Gassendi is not trying to prove that 
 the magnet has a kind of feeling as we know it in 
 consciousness, but that the common denominator of
 
 120 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. ii. 
 
 the whole scale is motile response : whether it is 
 felt or not depends on whether it occurs in a con- 
 sciousness that can feel or in that which cannot. 
 I may add in confirmation of this, that those who 
 attribute sense to the magnet should also say the 
 earth has sense : which is a phase of the doctrine 
 of anima mundi expressly rejected by Gassendi.
 
 CHAPTER III 
 PSYCHIC LIFE 
 
 (a) SENSE AND SENSATION 
 
 Although we speak of the Soul as sensitive, there 
 are many facts which seem to prove that the seat 
 of sensation can be more distinctly defined. The 
 Soul may be diverted and not notice an affection 
 of the senses, or it may carry on functions like 
 those of nutrition in which no sense-elements are 
 consciously realised. The conclusion is that the 
 sensitive ' textura ' is a part and not the whole of 
 the sentient Anima. This is the first step toward 
 regarding the mind as multiplex, and is in agree- 
 ment with the views of Epicurus. But a difiiculty 
 arises due to the difiiculty of keeping the unity of 
 the soul while rejecting its 'simplicity.' Lucretius 
 had said that the soul possessed a particular vis 
 animai, which implied that it could maintain its 
 existence independent of the body.^ Epicurus, on 
 the other hand, declared that it had no such cause 
 of sentience (sentiendi causam) nisi quatenus corpus 
 illam fovet. It follows that so far as sentience is 
 concerned, we must take as our unity not Anima 
 but Animal, not the soul alone but the totum com- 
 
 iii. 330.
 
 1J2 PHILOSOPHV OF GASSENDI [PT. 
 
 positum. In either case the sense-organs need not 
 be regarded as mere channels ; but while Lucretius 
 might be so interpreted, Epicurus is quite definite. 
 It is true to say the mind sees or hears, but no 
 less true to say the eye sees or ear hears, just as 
 we say the hand writes. It may seem irrelevant 
 to discuss at this point the question of the vis 
 animae ; but the justification for so doing is the 
 fact that at this point we are deeply concerned with 
 the question of the unity of the soul and its 
 meaning. The rejection of a specific and separate 
 vis animae is one step toward the destruction of 
 the view that the soul is simple, in the technical 
 sense. Now, not only has it parts of which the 
 sensitive part is one, but it may be doubted whether 
 this part is a unity without difference. Clearly we 
 have many sense-organs, yet some say ' sense is 
 one ' ; and of course it is true that the senses are 
 all sense and in that way one, but that is not a 
 useful contention. To say the one Sense uses the 
 organs as a carpenter uses his various tools for 
 various purposes is to make a fallacious comparison. 
 It is the mind that is a unity relatively to the 
 senses ; and the opposition of the unitary sense to 
 the many kinds of sensation is a mere confusion 
 added to an assumption. Gassendi here seems to 
 realise the difficulty which attends the reduction of 
 all sense-affection to movement : whether we speak 
 of afferent or efferent activities, we are faced with 
 the fact that motions of different kinds of tissue 
 will not necessarily be different kinds of motion. 
 If differences of motion make differences in sensation, 
 since motions differ only in degree, we are liable to
 
 II.] PHYSICS 123 
 
 drift on to the conclusion that sight is an acute 
 form of hearing, and thus be wrecked. Now we 
 cannot give up the point that senses are (juali- 
 tatively different : we must therefore take tliat as 
 a proof that sense-organs differ in texture and that 
 the recipient soul is just as manifold as the currents 
 conveyed to it or from it. This is a decision but 
 not a solution of the problem; and we are left with 
 a working hypothesis, not a demonstrated conclu- 
 sion ; but Gassendi seems to realise that sensation 
 as a physical fact belongs to a totally different 
 point of view^ from that which regards sensation as 
 a psychic fact ; and the quantitative analysis of the 
 one cannot be wholly identified with the qualitative 
 distinctions of the other. 
 
 The actual number of senses is five : they cannot 
 be reduced to Touch, but they might conceivably be 
 increased in number, and we might even have a sense 
 for the inner nature of things. This is a character- 
 istically mediaeval notion. As it is, our senses only 
 give us knowledge of qualities ; but it should be 
 noted that our ignorance of the natures rerum inti- 
 mas is not an inherent fault of our way of attaining 
 knowledge, but a question of mere limitation in the 
 number of senses. 
 
 Perception is not in the organ, but in the In-ain, 
 whose media are the nerves. What then is the 
 nature of the nerve? The sensitive part of the 
 organ must be animata, the other parts need only 
 be ' vegetative ' : it must also be in some way sus- 
 ceptible of touch: these qualities are found in nerves. 
 These nerves must be regarded (after Galen) as a 
 sort of diffused brain, and the brain as a kind of
 
 124 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. 
 
 highly developed nerve : every membrane consists 
 of a sheath coverins; an inner membrane : the inner 
 part is a chain of soft particles with a hollow centre. 
 The mechanism is not sensitive in itself, for the 
 sensation only arises when some shock to the nerve 
 is transmitted to the brain : this transmission requires 
 a state of tension, and is therefore only possible when 
 the animal spirits inflate these nerve channels suffi- 
 ciently. This explains the possibility of a physical 
 affection of the nerves having no psychic effect. 
 Gassendi does not appear to consider the question 
 of subconscious states. The ' innervation ' caused by 
 the animal spirits is the essential condition of actual 
 sensibility : consequently, physical shocks at the 
 nerve extremities are cut off from the brain alto- 
 gether unless the innervation occurs. This becomes 
 more familiar as psychology if we describe this 
 tension of the nerve system as ' attention ' and say 
 that affections to which we do not attend are not part 
 of our experience. It is necessary here to distinguish 
 appulse as cause and tension as condition of sensation. 
 Gassendi regards the nerves as not sufficiently 
 straight or tense to be the bearers of sensation 
 (oblique divertuntur et remissiore tensione sunt). 
 He therefore says ' id probabilius videtur peragi rem 
 per spiritum ob continuitatem mobilitatemque ' : at 
 the same time he anticipates the possible misinter- 
 pretation of the phrase ' bearers of sensation,' and 
 points out that nothing is really carried into the 
 ^ brain •} it is the motion itself when actually arrived 
 in the brain that is the sensation. 
 
 ^ non aliquid immitti, sed remitti potius repellive videtur : spiritus 
 nempe nervis contentus. Bernier translates this by ' rebondissement.' 
 
 »/
 
 II.] PHYSICS 125 
 
 Tlie nature of the process called Sense-apprehcii- 
 sioD is thus described. All objects are known through 
 their ' species ' : not only in the case of sight, but in 
 the case of all the other sense-organs, the species are 
 the media of knowledge : these species are composed 
 of small corpuscula which enter the channels to 
 which they are suitable. It follows from the teach- 
 ing above, where all sense-organs were asserted to 
 have diflPerent textures, that there will be a certain 
 degree of selection, in so far as unsuitableness may 
 prevent some corpuscles from entering some channels. 
 These texturae of the various organs thus serve as 
 selective sieves : the species however have various 
 degrees of difference : over and above the differences 
 which make them unfitted to enter some organs at 
 all, they have further differences which make them 
 pleasurable or painful to an organ which can admit 
 them. 
 
 This seems written in a highly materialistic vein ; 
 but Gassendi's position is more physical than mater- 
 ialistic, which is to say he works out these problems 
 on mechanical lines without admitting that the 
 result is identical in kind with its original factors. 
 He diverges here from the common line by denying 
 that the species either are or need to be conveyed 
 to the sensorium or central faculty. He says, 'verisi- 
 milius tamen est non penetrare corpuscula sensoriis 
 externis allapsa in interiorem facultatem residentem 
 in cerebro sed fieri motionem nervorum spirituum- 
 que': which at least refines the material species down 
 to a brain-movement before it is finally transmuted 
 into thought. This modification is important in one 
 respect. If the species were the actual thing, sense-
 
 126 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 affection would be wholly and objectively true : if, 
 on the other hand, the thing is not itself transmitted 
 but is represented by a movement, the quality of the 
 movement will be the ground of judgment and error 
 will be possible, as e.g. when a man's leg has been 
 cut off he still feels pain in it, though this is clearly 
 not an affection of the parts, but an affection of the 
 central faculty interpreted as coming from those 
 extremities. Gassendi considers that the nvev uXr]^ 
 of Aristotle is to be thus explained/ 
 
 The sensibles then are perceived intercedente 
 
 y motione : as to the nature of these Sensibles but 
 little is said, and most of it is Aristotle ; but it is 
 noted that Aristotle's distinction of essential and 
 accidental sensibles is a confusion as the ' accidents ' 
 are perceived by the aid of Imagination and Memory. 
 This account of sensation has two points of particular 
 interest. Firstly, the object of the senses is not itself 
 
 y conveyed to the brain, but is symbolically represented 
 by the motion it creates : hence not only is it possible 
 to misjudge the given, but also that which is given 
 may itself be incurably false : Aristotle's saying, ' non 
 falli sensum circa ipsum,' is right in so far as it 
 means sense is what it is, but that will not help 
 us to decide whether it is wdiat it claims to be or 
 whether being what it is as effect it guarantees what 
 we think it ought to oruarantee as cause. But of 
 this more later. A more pressing question arises 
 from the general position. As we have already 
 remarked, Gassendi is quite aware that his scale of 
 the Universe is in imminent danger of resolving 
 
 ^ Trept i^vxv^ 424 a : i] fiev aiadrjais icrri. to deKTiKbv tCjv aldOrfTdv eidOiv
 
 II.] PHYSICS 127 
 
 itself into a series of disconnected stages : he is con- 
 tinually making ' synthetic assumptions,' taking a 
 stage A, for example, and advancing to yl + Z^ with 
 no explanation of the right to speak of A-{-B as the 
 next stage above A, when all we know is that the 
 addition of B makes A all that it was not before. 
 Sense is a case in point : for however much the 
 common mind may feel certain that plant, animal, 
 and man form an indisputable scale of ascending 
 dignity, it is not philosophic to accept the dogma 
 uncritically: on the other hand, if the problem is 
 squarely faced, it seems to present an absolute dilemma. 
 We might say Life is possible because all is animated 
 and so all is ' sensible ' ; but this is chaos, a night of 
 colourless reality. Rather than this, Gassendi clings 
 to the reality of distinctions and strives to defend 
 his position. Plants have ' quasi adumbratio sensus ' 
 inasmuch as in them too the vital fire burns and 
 processes of absorption and nutrition are carried on: 
 the fact that they require their food makes it 'gratum.' 
 Thus the sophistry of Gassendi ! for who authorises 
 that ' gratum ' ? Is it more than poetry to say the 
 thirsty plant rejoices in the rain ? Can I argue that 
 because my boot wants soling therefore it likes it ? 
 But Gassendi knows that these scales of existence 
 are artificial constructions, and his own is built on 
 that abstraction called Motion. His second argument 
 is an appeal to Analogy : in all natural development 
 there is an inexplicable element : the whole attains a 
 nature such as was found in none of the parts : when 
 the tree ripens it passes from sour to sweet (a passage 
 from Non-Being to Being almost Hegelian !), and 
 when flint and steel can produce a spark, shall we
 
 128 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 doubt that object and nerve may produce a sensa- 
 tion ? In short, quantitatively we can keep our 
 scale, if we look to quality our world falls apart at 
 every difference. 
 
 Gassendi appears well aware that the results will 
 not seem very satisfactory to those who desire greater 
 continuity. He says : ' Verumtamen, inquies, ex 
 verbis tam multis neque explicatur neque intelli- 
 gitur qua ration e fiat ut cum neque ipsa caloris, 
 flammulaeve corpuscula seorsim sumpta, et dum in 
 auras excedunt, sentiant : neque sentiant item parti- 
 culae corporis, quibus flammula inest, ac miscetur : 
 et ne ea quidem communi crassaque affectu, qua 
 quippiam tactu percipitur : quanam ratione, inquam, 
 fiat, ut ex iis commistis exoriatur sensio perceptiove 
 explicita, quam non possumus lucidiore dicere voce, 
 quam cognitionis, ac res proinde sentiens creetur ex 
 rebus insensilibus ? ' We have to confess our ignor- 
 ance, but this is only a special case of an ignorance 
 which is manifest in many other directions, in fact, 
 whenever we deal with qualities. 'Neque vero est 
 quare putes posse rem planius et agnosci et edisseri 
 in qualitatibus ceteris : siquidem ubi dixeris fructum 
 ex acerbo, e.g. dulcem fieri, etc. ... ex quo fit ut 
 cum idem dici proportione possit de qualitatibus 
 caeteris, mirum non sit, si cum ipsa quoque Qualitas 
 sentiendi difficilem adeo explicatum habeat . . . ex- 
 plicare non liceat, etc' This is a very clear state- 
 ment of the position, and shows beyond dispute that 
 Gassendi admits a complete break, not only here 
 but everywhere between the analytic and synthetic 
 aspects, our analysis and nature's synthesis. His 
 defence of Epicurus is that he did not make the
 
 II.] PHYSICS 129 
 
 atoms incapable of being anything, and other 
 theorists have not succeeded any better than he 
 did. As a matter of fact we can only go back, in 
 the case of sentient things, to the semen, not the 
 atom, so that ' non posse dici absolute res sensileis 
 fieri ex insensilibus,' that is to say we can uphold 
 that the sensile only comes from the sensile, but 
 only by refusing to go down to our ultimate, by 
 stopping at a complex state (secunda materies) which 
 has attained sensation and declinino; to ask where 
 that degree of sensation comes from ^ (ii. 347). 
 
 (6) IMAGINATION 
 
 There is no subject more interesting or more 
 critical for writers of the class to which Gassendi 
 belongs than that of Imagination. The peculiar 
 combination which the activity of this faculty 
 presents in its union of inner significance with 
 outer form, places it in the perilous transition from 
 objective existence to subjective being, and makes 
 it too often the root of those wild extravagances, 
 whose ultimate object is always to confound with 
 material figures of speech the problem of Reason. 
 It is necessary therefore to follow this discussion 
 with care, and try to define accurately the position 
 of Gassendi. With the subject of Phantasia we 
 penetrate into the inner sanctuary of thought : 
 'sequitur facultas cognoscens interna,' says Gassendi, 
 ' cuius nimirum tota functio sic interius peragitur 
 ut organum nullum exterius appareat.' We now 
 
 ^This is the passage quoted by Masson {v. p. 117). Clearly it has a 
 different meaning in its context from that which Masson gives it by 
 taking it out of that context. 
 
 I
 
 130 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 deal with the Animus : for ' ab anima quidem 
 vegetatio et sensus, ab animo vero cogitatio et 
 ratiocinatio pendent.' 
 
 In the first place we must decide whether this 
 faculty is one or many : for although the dogma of 
 the Fides Sacra is really all we can know, a little 
 additional enquiry will not be heterodox or useless ! 
 The division of the Animus called Cogitatio has 
 often been subdivided into Imaginatio, Cogitatio, 
 Opinio, Prudentia, Consilium, and so on. These 
 faculties are however all reducible to Phantasy, 
 which thus comes to mean any activity of thought 
 carried on in terms of sense and its ' imagines.' This 
 raises the question as to whether Imagination is not 
 really the culminating point of sensation, i.e. whether 
 it could not be identified with the sensus communis. 
 It has been said, 'What is sense but the understanding 
 of the sensible, or the understanding but a sense 
 of the intelligible ? ' (cp. Aristotle's phrase,^ Oiyyducov 
 Koi vouju), but this was error, and we can never admit 
 that sense and thought are one.^ The identification 
 of Imagination and the sensus communis may be 
 rejected then, for the following specific reasons : 
 no sense can be made to judge, therefore it is useless 
 placing any faculty of the nature of sense at the 
 meeting-place of nerves to function thus : if there 
 is any central point it must be ascribed to Imagina- 
 tion : knowledge of the functions of sense belongs 
 to something beyond them — a phrase which recalls 
 the phrase of a later writer that sensations cannot 
 sum themselves. 
 
 AVe conclude then that in men we have only two 
 
 ^3/et. 1072. b. 20. ^u. 398,
 
 II.] PHYSICS 131 
 
 divisions of Animus, viz. Reasoning and Imagina- 
 tion, though some would add Judgment. This 
 addition was due to a false analysis of Illusion. A 
 certain Theophilus, Medicus, though a man of good 
 judgment in other respects, was afflicted with the 
 Imagination that he could hear flute players perform- 
 ing in some corner of his house. It was argued from 
 this case that his judgment was sound, but his 
 imagination unsound ; and therefore these were 
 distinct. Here Gassendi shrewdly points out that 
 the Doctor judged as he imagined, and the imagina- 
 tion was not itself wrong, but was made wrong 
 by the error of the judgment of causation by which 
 the internal state was attributed to a wrong cause. 
 Thus the case does not refute our position that 
 imagination and judgment are one : for an illusion 
 is Teal as a subjective state, and the state of imagina- 
 tion is not an object of judgment, but is itself an 
 affection combined with an activity of judgment, 
 so that the cause of imagination is normally also 
 the object of judgment. This point is by no means 
 easy to comprehend : it involves the following 
 analysis of perception. An object A is cause of an 
 inner state B of the nature of an image ; but as this 
 is a conscious image it is itself, as an inner state, 
 a judgment a,iid not a judgment on itself but on A, 
 its external cause. If B could be judged as an 
 inner state and compared with A, judgment and 
 imagination could be distinguished : which we deny, 
 since it involves a double access to the object A^ 
 namely once by way of the image and once 
 immediately. 
 
 We are now fairly launched on the question of
 
 132 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 Perception, and must follow Gassendi closely. To 
 return to the question of reducing all faculties to 
 Phantasy — what becomes of Memory ? This is really 
 a defect of ' species ' ; loss of memory means loss of 
 the ' species servatas,' leaving one with an inner 
 world depleted of objects : hence, as failure of 
 memory is failure of relation among species, it 
 seems to follow that memory is only imagination 
 regarded from the point of view of a system of 
 species. Now, what are the imagines or species 
 which thus constitute a faculty co-extensive with 
 empirical knowledge ? Perception, we have been 
 told, depends on excitement of the outer organ by 
 a species or ' qualitas sensibilis ' : the nerves filled 
 with animal spirits are ' spiritual radii,' along which 
 the vibrations travel to the brain. From this 
 results (1) that the faculty of feeling in the 
 appropriate quarter at once knows the object ; (2) a 
 vestigium is left behind. Once this function is 
 ended, the sense-faculty cannot know the object 
 again without a second shock. Phantasy how- 
 ever is a higher faculty, and can know the absent 
 thing : this is its final distinction from sense : also 
 its capacity of acting without the presence of the 
 thing proves that its object or ground of activity 
 is in the brain : we must therefore be clear as to 
 these 'vestigia.' 
 
 Gassendi asserts emphatically that the cerebral 
 residuum (species, (pavTaa-iua^ visum) is in no sense 
 a thing : we cannot construct any inter-cranial thing 
 which will give the qualities of the object of thought. 
 Colours, sounds, etc., have no typus in cerebro (as 
 a thing might have a typus in cera), but the process
 
 II.] PHYSICS 133 
 
 is such ' ut per nervos contractos resilitio quaedam 
 spirituum in cerebrum fiat qua tarn cerebrum quam 
 facultas in eo residens percellatur ; ideo posse 
 sufiicere si id quod remanet cuiusmodi sit ut talis 
 perculsio eius interventu velut iteretur.'^ The impress 
 must therefore be taken as some efi*ect on brain 
 substance of the nature of a fold (quasi plicam 
 quandam in cerebro factam). This definite result 
 becomes the cause of reflective thought, a;s it gives 
 its character to those spirits which for any reason 
 move in its tracks : the imago impressa determines 
 what the thought shall be of, but we actually 
 envisage not the brain-fold, but the cause, i.e. the 
 original object now become a Phantasma : as we 
 think of an object without thinking of the sense- 
 apparatus or the brain, so in reflection we pass 
 beyond the immediate conditions to what lies 
 beyond. The impress belongs to the brain and 
 the phantasy regarded as a compound : that is to 
 say — when we say it is a brain-state, we do not 
 mean it is a state of the brain purely as matter, 
 but as a conscious agent. The materialistic difliculty 
 which might have arisen is thus anticipated l)y 
 refusing to consider the brain in abstraction from 
 its conscious functions, as though a dead brain were 
 still a brain in the fullest sense. Gassendi cannot 
 emphasise too much or repeat too often his belief 
 that the direct material of thought is purely symbolic 
 of the external reality : only the disposition of the 
 brain itself remains to testify to the action of an 
 object on the senses, and all the substantial nature 
 of things is reduced to a mode of motion of the 
 
 Mr. 405.
 
 134 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 brain-substance, out of which we may build again 
 an insubstantial pageant of reflection. 
 
 Memory is discussed in connection with Imagina- 
 tion, since it is really only an aspect of the function 
 which preserves ideas. By thus connecting it with 
 his theory of Imagination and folds, Gassendi breaks 
 with those who viewed Memory as a ' storehouse ' : 
 he says, ' non tamquam vas quoddam concipienda,' 
 and rejects the simile of wax with equal clearness : 
 he admits however other metaphors : videtur ergo 
 potius concipi non male quasi charta munda seu 
 papyri purissimae solium, but the paper is to be 
 considered as receiving folds, not marks. This is a 
 remarkable anticipation both of Locke and Leibnitz, 
 while it savours of much later psychological work. 
 The analysis of the whole process is even more 
 remarkable. The folds, which are innumerable, can 
 be repeated in their order : the new co-exists with 
 the old, and an excitement beginning from any 
 point in the series runs through them all (una plica 
 arrepta caeterae quae in eadem serie sunt, quasi 
 sponte sequuntur). The act of recollecting consists 
 in voluntarily making many folds until by chance 
 we hit on the right one or one in the right series : 
 thus the apparently forgotten may be revived. Folds 
 tend to become obliterated by the number of later 
 folds or by humidity of the brain in old age : 
 memories are good and bad according to the tempera- 
 ment, which here means the degree to which the 
 humid element preponderates. Total oblivion results 
 from material cerebral changes, by which the original 
 folds become entirely obliterated. 
 
 We may now survey the functions of Phantasy
 
 II.] PHYSICS 1 :{5 
 
 generally. They are three in number, namely simple 
 apprehension, composition or division, and Ratio- 
 cinatio, a list which proves that the term Phantasy 
 is not to be taken in any narrow sense. 
 
 The proper function is simple apprehension with- 
 out affirmation or denial, the most elementary 
 function of Imagination being naturally conceived 
 as the mere reception of imagines. This mere recep- 
 tion is however not a pure passivity : it follows from 
 the nature of the ' plica ' that there is some activity 
 of the organ or faculty : also there is here a principle 
 of unity if not exactly a unifying activity, for 
 Gassendi asks why we imagine one object only when 
 the spirits are agitated in many ' folds,' and bases 
 his answer on the unity of the fiiculty. This resolu- 
 tion of many movements into a unity is not strictly 
 intelligible so long as the relation between the 
 physical multiplicity and the psychical unity is left 
 without proper explanation. Gassendi also recognises 
 a selective activity, and points out that it is not 
 possible to attend to more than one thing at a time 
 unless the things are in some sense capable of 
 reduction to a unity : as a rule attention, which is 
 physically a movement of the spirits in one particular 
 direction, follows the greatest or dominant move- 
 ment, though a new movement may engage attention 
 in face of an older and stronger affection. 
 
 This treatment of attention looks better than it 
 really is : it might be good either physiologically or 
 psychically, but as stated it is a hopeless confusion. 
 In the first place, many movements might be the 
 physical counterpart of one thought ; but if the 
 unity of thought is described as a unity of move-
 
 136 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 ment the many movements must be one in themselves 
 and as movements ; which is meaningless. Secondly, 
 Gassendi seems to think a unity comprehending the 
 multiplicity is not distinct from the unity gained 
 by omission. For him attention must always be 
 attention to one thing because, being a movement, 
 it can only be in one place at one time. This is at 
 least intelligible as an exposition in terms of place 
 and movement, but it makes the whole theory of 
 attention hopelessly crude, and by itself excludes 
 the mental characteristics which Gassendi is anxious 
 to include in this stage of the psycho-physical life. 
 Although rooted in experience Phantasy can com- 
 bine its elements in new ways, e.g. the imagination 
 of the Hippogriff. This brings us to the second 
 degree of Phantasy, which is called Compositio et 
 divisio or assensio et dissensio, or affirmatio et 
 negatio. The combination of ideas such as gives 
 the centaur or the golden mountain is a combination 
 of separate ideas : the ' compositio ' to which we now 
 pass differs from this in being an assimilation of one 
 idea to a pre-existent group of ideas. It follows that 
 this function is secondary, in the sense that it pre- 
 supposes groups of ideas (aggeries) and that the 
 process is of the nature of subsumption under a 
 universal. As Gassendi draws upon animal life for 
 his examples we might compare this with the ' Logic 
 of Eecepts.' The process is assumed to be purely 
 psychological, and consists in the assimilation of a 
 present idea with a group of ideas accompanied by 
 definite consciousness of the act, and therefore in 
 some degree constituting a 'judicium.' The progress 
 of experience results in various aggregates of ' ves-
 
 II.] PHYSICS 137 
 
 tigia ' ill the brain : no one of these can be caUod 
 universal, but the common elements in them all may- 
 be taken to give a sort of type of the kind. Hence 
 a new perception may be identified as man rather 
 than lion, because, though not identical with any 
 existing man-image, it is more like a man's imai^e 
 than a lion's image. The difficulty of defining this 
 stage of psychic life is felt by all who study the 
 subject : it would be rash to assert that Gassendi 
 made it fully clear to himself. He is however clear 
 upon the point that if the activity is psychological 
 it must be positive. The emergence of the negative 
 marks the fully conscious proposition which is not 
 found at this stage. Thus Comparison, as found 
 here, is mere assimilation : it may be said ' this is 
 sweet' or 'this is bitter,' but not 'this is not sweet.' 
 If we are to refine to this degree, probably the terms 
 sweet and bitter would have to be ruled out, and 
 the psychic affirmative put in the form ' this is such.' 
 Gassendi would say that at this stage there is no 
 proposition at all, and thus save himself from the 
 accusation of such mental atomism as is implied in 
 the divorce of a positive notion (sweet) from its 
 correlative (not sweet). If the second operation 
 constitutes a perilous border region, how much more 
 the third, which is Ratiocinatio, argumentatio, or 
 discursus? But, ne voce ipsa statim oflfendamur, we 
 distinguish Reason as either Sensitiva or Intellectiva. 
 This is a distinction of kind which once for all settles 
 the difficulty which the Church had found in putting 
 beasts and men on one graduated scale. The difie- 
 rentia of this stage of Phantasy is found in the ability 
 of animals to go beyond the given : they anticipate
 
 138 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 results, as when the dog runs from the uplifted 
 stick ; or choose between a present and a future 
 pain, as when the ass endures the beating rather 
 than go forward over the precipice. If we admit 
 that the hare can reason that a leap breaks the scent 
 ^nd say with Gassendi ' esse speciem quandam 
 rationis in Brutis ' ; if we further discover that an 
 animal perceives agreement and disagreement, which 
 is the basis of propositions, where shall we limit 
 Phantasy ? The specious answer is to say that we 
 limit it by the capacities of animals, and after all 
 animals are not men. This might have been Gassendi's 
 reply ; but he seems satisfied with proving that 
 animals have some kind of Reason without troubling 
 to define it too accurately. The chapter ends with 
 a description of human reasoning which may have 
 been intended to suggest a superiority, but seems 
 more like a closure put on a discussion that threatened 
 to bring Faith into collision with Reason. The dis- 
 <jussion on Instinct begins with the definite statement 
 that the Brutes have common notions or general 
 propositions, which are rather innate to (ingenitae) 
 than produced by the Senses. The fundamental 
 faculty is Touch, and the dominant passions are 
 Pleasure and Pain : these are related respectively to 
 the good and the bad, and have as their active 
 aspects attraction and repulsion. The result is a 
 sort of innate proposition (notio sive habitus), such 
 as Faciendum quod juvat, non faciendum quod nocet. 
 The bull moves before the goad immediately; but 
 where action is undertaken to avoid a future pain, 
 we must admit argumentatio. The chapter adds 
 nothing to the theory of phantasy, but contains
 
 11] PHYSICS 139 
 
 some interesting remarks on the ethics of animal 
 life. Care for the young is derived from the parent's 
 care for itself, the embryo being a part of the parent : 
 this is a provision which has a teleological aspect, 
 being intended to secure preservation of the species 
 (ad generis conservationem). The series of instinctive 
 actions are expressions of subjective conditions : the 
 period of gestation is a state upon which follows the 
 presentiment to find a place for deposit and care of 
 the young : memory, imitation, and a natural sense 
 of the useful are the psychic elements of this state. 
 Gassendi sums up his own doctrine thus : Phantasy 
 is a faculty whose first function is to know ; then, 
 secondly, to arouse appetite and, thirdly, motive 
 faculty, whose effects differ according to the means 
 used. These effects include : 
 
 (1) Excitation of desires and passions — love, hate, 
 and the like. 
 
 (2) Motion of spirits through the body. 
 
 (3) Tension of the nerves and muscles, 
 
 (4) Agitation of humours as in palpitation and 
 blushing. 
 
 (5) Impressio ilia macularum similitudinisque et 
 deformitatis in foetu. 
 
 (6) External effects of any kind. These are in 
 fact usually myths : external action (as e.g. that of 
 the evil eye) is impossible, for the activity of Imagi- 
 natio is essentially immanent. 
 
 (c) INTELLECT AND ITS FUNCTIONS 
 I. 
 
 The mind or the Intellect of man is no mere 
 faculty : it is a ' pars essentialis substantialisve
 
 140 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 Hominis,' and therefore is the same as the Rational 
 Soul looked at as rational without regard to vegeta- 
 tive or sensitive parts. This view is the only one 
 possible if we remember that we must argue so as 
 to prove the Soul's immortality (' viam sternere ad 
 astruendum eius Immortalitatem,' ii. 425) : it would 
 be simpler to take mens and Phantasia as identical 
 in kind and different only in degree ; but that is 
 a priori impossible, as it leads to the admission that 
 brutes might win immortality. The theory that the 
 human anima is a part of the Anima Mundi must 
 be rejected : it does not follow from the existence 
 of stones that there must be a 'forma lapidis' 
 diffused through the universe, nor that the universe 
 has an anima because individual animae are found 
 on it : apart from this, if we admit the universal 
 mind, there is no sense in speaking of it as ' divided ' 
 or ' distributed,' since it is not corporeal. The doc- 
 trine of Eeminiscence, as taught by Plato, is the 
 stronghold of this position, but not impregnable. 
 Why must we have innate ideas ? Is it not enough 
 if we have the facultas intelligendi comparandique 
 ideas : we can then form ' notiones anticipatas,' and 
 so have all that is required for the more intellectual 
 functions. Another time-honoured fallacy is the 
 duality of mind taught by those who recognise a 
 passive and a universal (active) part. If the uni- 
 versal part is really other than our intellect, it is 
 outside of our intellect, and therefore an unknown : 
 if it is justified as the condition of our intelligence, 
 it is not thereby proved an intelligence itself, any 
 more than light is proved to be sight by being 
 posited as the condition of sight. This is in fact
 
 11] PHYSICS 141 
 
 regarded by Gassendi as a false attempt to go 
 beyond the intellectual sphere in order to explain 
 its functions : it ends in a hypostasis of mind to 
 explain minds : he himself looks rather to the unity 
 of mind as the source of illumination : we have 
 already found, he says, that a sort of general 
 phantasy arises in animals, which is actually nothing 
 but the co-existence and self-reflection of many par- 
 ticular acts of phantasy : why then may not the 
 light of reason be an immanent light and a self- 
 illumination ? (quorsum intelligibiles species non sua 
 quaeque speciali luce perfundantur ?). 
 
 II. 
 
 Gassendi, having rejected both Plato and Aristotle, 
 proceeds to develope his own view. A hint has 
 already been given us in the argument that the 
 existence of a stone is not a proof of any universal 
 form of stone pervading the universe. This argu- 
 ment is somewhat obscure, but it seems to mean 
 that from the point of view of Being, a specific form 
 implies not a general form, but a general substance 
 of which it is the form. Thus a stone presupposes 
 only matter-in-general, not stone-in-general, and the 
 matter is general not in esse suo, but in reference 
 to a special form. By analogy a specific mind will 
 not imply a universal mind, but might imply some 
 entity capable of standing in such a relation to the 
 particular mind as matter does to the particular 
 stone. This line of thought might seem to be lead- 
 ing us onward and upward to a mind above, but the 
 face of Gassendi is toward the origins ; and as matter 
 is a name for all existing atoms viewed as unity,
 
 142 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 so if we penetrate beyond the specious unity of 
 mind we come upon the ideas in their multiplicity. 
 We must not suppose that by calling the Anima 
 Rationalis a substance Gassendi makes it a thing ; 
 he means merely to exclude the views which make 
 it a dependent existence, such as an ' inseparabilis 
 perfectio ' or a ' harmonia ' must necessarily be.^ He 
 defines it as substantia incorporea, formam tanquam 
 informantem, and this combination of terms defines 
 our problem : we must first see from Gassendi's 
 statements how he conceives this entity called 
 mind. 
 
 Our philosophy has given us an exposition of 
 Phantasy. The first requisite is a distinction of 
 mind from Phantasy. The points of difference are 
 these : 
 
 ( 1 ) Phantasy is not capable of reflection : the 
 knowledge that we know denotes an incorporeal 
 agent, for it is a movement toward self, while the 
 movement of the corporeal is always toward another. 
 
 (2) Many objects of the mind are not imaginable : 
 they are intelligible, and the idea has significance, 
 but no sense representation is possible, i.e. we cannot 
 actually picture the sun as having the size which 
 we know it to have.^ 
 
 (3) Our knowledge of universality proves that we 
 have a faculty higher than phantasy : the object here 
 is incorporeal, and therefore requires an incorporeal 
 Agent to know it. Gassendi distinguishes between 
 having universals and knowing universality : as in the 
 
 III. 440. 
 
 2 This is not the question of opposition between the sun as it is and 
 as it appears, but of the limits to imaginative reproduction.
 
 II.] PHYSICS U3 
 
 case of animals, Phantasy may attain to universals 
 which Gassendi regards as purely psychological ; but 
 man is distinguished by having this ' knowledge of 
 universality,' which seems to be simply the existence 
 of the universal at a reflective stage of mind. 
 
 In these points the difference of mind and imagi- 
 nation are most marked ; but the existence and 
 nature of a higher faculty is made certain by other 
 proofs. Knowledge of God, though not intuitive, 
 demands a faculty that grasps the incorporeal. Will 
 aims at the good, and thereby indicates a faculty 
 capable of rising above the sense level, for which 
 pleasure and pain would be the only ends. 
 
 Having thus demonstrated the existence of Intellect 
 as a non-sensuous faculty, Gassendi proceeds to 
 further define the nature of the human mind. As 
 incorporeal and a form, the mind is in a sense ex 
 nihilo, and the passage from nothing to something- 
 being an infinite process requires God. This is a 
 declaration of war against the physical dogmas : the 
 categories of science may be adequate if we are only 
 concerned with things whose origin is really only a 
 fresh disposition of matter ; but w^hat if our regress 
 brings us to the whole ? Can it be treated as we 
 treat the parts ? Does not our physical system 
 demand for its own explanation something higher 
 and greater ? was not Daedalus greater than the 
 machines he made ? Ex nihilo nihil is, then, a 
 category which means that every combination of 
 elements postulates the existence of the elements 
 thus combined : it will not reach to substances 
 themselves, for we cannot show what elements or 
 what combinations are required to produce a soul :
 
 144 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 it is for us a limit, and as such has beyond it only 
 chaos, the Not-Being which is its only antecedent. 
 
 This production, though ex nihilo, is not un- 
 natural : the propagation of man is ordained in uno 
 ordine, and the production of the soul is in eodem 
 ordine : so long as the phenomenal regularity is ob- 
 served this remains a natural event. Thus Gassendi's 
 treatment of the soul as an original underived entity 
 does not carry him into idle speculations : it is a 
 treatment which (as he well knows) does not change 
 the nature of the Anima, but serves to define the 
 inadequacy of categories which were in danger of 
 encroaching : it is a treatment also which never 
 admits that quality can be generated out of mere 
 quantity. This last point is most important, and 
 Gassendi never swerves from his position : at this 
 crisis, when we require to unite soul with body, and 
 all the delicate gradations of ' very subtle move- 
 ments ' offer themselves as intermediary links, he 
 sweeps them all away at a blow, declaring ' seu 
 crassum seu tenue sit corpus,' the difficulty remains 
 untouched. The position is acute : mind and matter 
 having nothing in common, the sensitive soul will 
 not serve as a link, hybrid though it be : to ascribe 
 the unity to God is to say less than nothing : we 
 stand before a unity for whose bond we find no 
 ' gluten,' no grappling irons (ansis carentem), and 
 no supreme force. We may well pause to ask what 
 it is we propose to unite, and what manner of union 
 we have to expound ? 
 
 As to the nature of the soul confusion has arisen 
 through trying to unite entities which had previously 
 been so defined as to admit of no union : this
 
 II.] PHYSICS 145 
 
 difficulty can therefore be removed. It consists in 
 supposing that the pure Intelligences, i.e. the angels, 
 represent the real nature of our souls taken in 
 abstraction from the body ; but why should a human 
 soul cease to be human merely because it is free 
 from the human body ? No change of kind is 
 proved, only a change of condition. We have there- 
 fore no right to suppose that our souls, like the 
 angelic beings, have any actus purus : on the con- 
 trary, the actus of souls is either mixtus or nothing 
 at all. 
 
 Gassendi introduces this point of view by simply 
 asserting that there are three natures of things, the 
 purely spiritual, the purely corporeal, and the mixed. 
 This gives us what might be called a concrete as 
 opposed to the ordinary abstract view : for it is no 
 longer possible to assert that the condition of the 
 soul is an imprisonment by which its functions are 
 impaired : its action is what it is, not because of 
 its union with the body, but because of its own 
 nature : it is not forced into an unequal yoke, but 
 joined in a divine wedlock for which it was pre- 
 destined (ipsaque ad eas nuptias propendeat). The 
 original difficulty was made acute by the emphasis 
 laid on the difference between soul and body : this 
 is dissolved by Gassendi's view, which does not 
 demand that the two should be of one kind, but 
 that they should be, like male and female, comple- 
 mentary. This is a recognition of identity in 
 difference which promises much ; but there is one 
 point which qualifies our hopes. It is after all to 
 the sensitive soul that the Anima Rationalis is united ; 
 and so ' interventu sentientis corpori uniatur ' : we
 
 146 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 mighit conjecture that Gassendi foresaw a possible 
 difficulty in the fact that there are many forms of 
 matter to which Intellect does not ally itself: it 
 therefore became necessary to resolve both terms 
 and say, * it is the nature of Intellect to unite itself 
 to such matter as is of a nature to receive it.' We 
 may not perhaps be able to get much further on 
 the main issue, but it is well to see clearly how 
 much Gassendi really achieves. He is clearly right 
 in taking the unity as his standing point, and 
 not the absolute differences. He cannot be far 
 wrong in asserting that if the unity is (as it is) 
 a fact, the elements must be by nature adapted for 
 the unity. The root of his difficulty is the fact 
 that his terms do not represent these distinctions, 
 but are names for distinct beings, and, much as he 
 strives to get away from this, his factors, Soul and 
 Body, insist on starting into independent realities. 
 Here again the problem is confused by the terms, 
 for corpus is a term which implies more than mere 
 matter, and the union of the Anima Rationalis is 
 ultimately only a union with a corpus in so far as 
 that is previously Animatum (beseelt), though it has 
 a specious appearance of explaining the union of 
 opposites. To me this difficulty is made more 
 serious by the metaphor of the marriage : for that 
 clearly implies a tendency to introduce conceptions 
 of mutual attraction which are confusing. Gassendi's 
 statement that the sensitive soul is qualified to be 
 the recipient of the Anima Rationalis, not because 
 of its tenuity, but because of its function in phan- 
 tasy, shows that he rejects the attempt to make ' a 
 very subtle motion ' identical with a psychic activity.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 147 
 
 but equally clearly shows that he pushes back his 
 real problem of passing over from physical to 
 i^sychical into the more obscure regions of animal 
 psychology. 
 
 We may now sum up Gassendi's position. The 
 Anima rationalis is so far distinct from all other 
 entities as to be underivable from them : it is there- 
 fore a new creation : on the other hand, its creation 
 is conditional, for it is so united to the Body as to 
 be not merely co-existent (adsistans) but also co- 
 herent (informans) : this union proves the factors 
 not wholly antagonistic, but it requires definite 
 conditions, and as the unity is also the birth of the 
 Soul (for it is created by God in ordine naturae) 
 it will follow that these conditions enter into its 
 very being. 
 
 At the risk of some repetition, which is not alien 
 to the spirit of Gassendi, we must further elucidate 
 the nature of the Intellect by stating what our 
 author calls its functions. The spirit of Occam 
 inspires Gassendi to limit the machinery of thought : 
 he identifies Anima Rationalis and mens in oppo- 
 sition to those who regarded the Intellect as a 
 distinct faculty or an instrument : he rejects the 
 distinction of active and passive unless agens be 
 used to mean direct thought and patiens, indirect 
 or reflective thought, where since the mind acts on 
 itself, there must be some right to speak of it as 
 receiving action (nata est recipere actum a se pro- 
 ductum). 
 
 Ultimately Gassendi recognises only two faculties 
 as required for the function of understanding. The 
 phantasmata are the only objects : these are sensible 
 
 u.-**^
 
 148 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENUI [pt. 
 
 species, but they can be understood, and there is 
 therefore no need to interpose the so-called ' intelli- 
 gible ' species. Whatever the difficulties may be in 
 the way of asserting that sensible species are capable 
 of being understood, it is clearly better to take up 
 that position than to assert that the understanding 
 can have no objects except such as have already 
 been understood. This introduces a point of con- 
 siderable importance. The so-called ' intelligible ' 
 species were a distinct class of species which, as 
 opposed to the sensible, were qualified to be the 
 content of the mind ; but how qualified 1 Appa- 
 rently by being in some way the world of mind ; 
 but if we take a functional view of the mind, this 
 reduces itself to absurdity, for the content of the 
 mind will be its own functions, its only inducement 
 to action will be the actions themselves, and know- 
 ledge will be impossible. This view of intelligible 
 species, therefore, must be rejected if we once give 
 up the idea of a mind which stores in itself pictures 
 that are ' intelligible ' before the mind understands 
 them : we can only say species are intelligible in the 
 sense in which all species must be intelligible, i.e. 
 capable of being understood. 
 
 The rejection of this bridge over the gulf neces- 
 sitates further explanations. If the notion of the 
 mind as envisaging pictures of the intellectual order 
 is objectionable, the situation is made even worse 
 by substituting pictures of the sensuous order. 
 Gassendi sees this and proceeds consistently : he 
 takes a functional view, inasmuch as he regards 
 ideas as actions rather than things ; but his idea of 
 function can only be interpreted in terms of motion,
 
 II.] PHYSICS 149 
 
 and to these terms the ' picturing ' of phantasy must 
 be reduced. The image and the idea are now no longer 
 opposed entities ; they are both motions, and seem 
 ultimately the same motion. In the case of sight 
 we have a sense process ending in a perception : by 
 analogy we may have a process of phantasia ending 
 in an intellectual activity. Phantasy is subject to 
 appulse, but intellect is not : the phantasy is the 
 end of the motion of spirits, but in addition to the 
 perception there arises a conception : in eodem 
 momento intellectus contuetur, says Gassendi,^ and 
 if w^e take this with what has been said above 
 of the self-illumination of ideas, it will be seen that 
 contuetur means perception from the point of view 
 of a system : this action of mind is a reaction, and 
 by its nature cannot be explained as identical with 
 a motion ab extra : the passage from corporeal to 
 incorporeal must come somewhere, and in spite of 
 long delay, it remains at the last an unique process. 
 The terms in which Gassendi states the relation of 
 Intellect to Imagination are so far from conveying 
 any very definite idea that it may be best to elabo- 
 rate his position. He seems to mean that the agent, 
 whatever it be, of intellectual processes is so indi- 
 visibly one with the nature of man as thinking being 
 that any disturbance of any part must imply its 
 activity : a thrill runs through the whole mass if 
 the appulse once disturbs the equilibrium of the 
 sense machinery (dum phantasia percellitur, ipsi 
 coagat intellectus). To this we may make a most 
 important addition, viz. the converse : for if the 
 intellect acts, the Imagination responds as best 
 
 'II. 450.
 
 150 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 it may. The idea of God is not derived from the 
 senses, and yet cannot be presented in thought 
 without a sensuous form. Hence, from the point 
 of view of physical analysis. Intellect and Imagi- 
 nation are not distinguishable : Gassendi therefore 
 adds the proofs that they are not identical, the most 
 important of which is the direct consciousness that 
 understanding goes beyond sensuous forms, that we 
 mean more than we can put into the sense forms : 
 if we present God in anthropomorphic fashion it is 
 not the human form that is of prime importance, 
 but the concepts which we thus embody. 
 
 (d) THE HABITS OF INTELLECT 
 
 If any doubt remained as to the extent to which 
 Gassendi regards man as an organic unity, it 
 would be dispelled at once by the tone of this 
 chapter. The so-called Habits of the understanding 
 are really habits of the brain : habit presupposes a 
 substance with some rigidity ; and we must fall 
 back on Phantasia and the doctrine of vestigia to 
 supply this want. It follows that in memory we 
 may have what are really products of Intellect, for 
 the Intellect creates a symbolic phantasy to enable 
 it to recall non-sensuous facts through a sensuous 
 train of ideas. All failure of the understanding to 
 receive its ideas are failures of this cerebral 
 machinery : if we suppose that there is a memory 
 belonging to pure Intellect, it would not be pos- 
 sible to explain defects of memory, which are 
 experienced quite as much in the non-sensuous as 
 in the sensuous sphere. 
 
 This polemic is really directed against some con-
 
 II.] PHYSICS 151 
 
 temporary Platonism : it is therefore introductory 
 to the description of knowledge, and seems to clear 
 away all prejudices in favour of Reminiscence or 
 innate ideas. Three types of knowledge may be 
 distinguished : God knows intuitively by pure reason 
 and ' ideas innatas ' : angels know by virtue of 
 ' ideas concreatas,' a limited form of intuition : man 
 requires the discursive reason which deals with 
 ideas furnished in Phantasy, and ultimately derived 
 from sense. ^ Without Intellect Phantasy is blind 
 (Phantasia ab initio sit quasi caeca sen specierum 
 omnino expers) : it has ' percepts ' in a sense, but 
 its species represent only the ' externos cortices ' of 
 things ; the Intellect surveying these species and 
 detecting the nature of some (perspectis aliquibus 
 possit vi sua suspicari et conjecturam ducere de 
 interna aliqua proprietate) proceeds to collect in- 
 stances, and so by induction arrives beyond the 
 outer husk to the inner core. The result of the 
 Inductive process is a direct intuition : the ideal is 
 to make our Intellect absolutiorem, i.e. capable of 
 seeing the whole in the part : so that Plato may 
 be said to have given us the right ideal and 
 Aristotle the rio;ht method. Gassendi here follows 
 Descartes in making the understanding move in 
 intuitions ; the form of the syllogism is therefore 
 
 1 II. 447. ' videtur mens nostra, seu Rationalis anima donee degit 
 in corpore, non aliis uti speciebus quam iis quas corpus subniinistrat, 
 quaeque in Phantasia resident : ac turn dumtaxat pari cum Angelis 
 conditione evadere, cum excedenti a corpore, ac Angelorum instar 
 futurae separatae, Deus indit species eiusmodi rerum, cjuas nosse 
 eius interest, sive ignoratae in corpore fuerint, sive eae sint quarum 
 cognitarum meminisse sit opus.' It is therefore a bare soul that 
 arrives in Heaven, and Gassendi at least means that only in Heaven 
 can we have an actus purus.
 
 152 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 only of use for teaching others : the conclusion is 
 to the reasoner consistent with the premisses, and 
 forms with them a w^hole. As this process ends in 
 self-evident knowledge, Gassendi considers that all 
 the ' self-evident first principles ' dejDend on pro- 
 cesses : these truths are products of experience, and 
 all such products would be as self-evident as the 
 'axioms' if we knew as much about them. The 
 child from its birth sees objects with magnitude, 
 and therefore with parts : hence if the general pro- 
 position ' The whole is greater than its part ' is 
 propounded and the terms understood, the confused 
 experiences of a life-time leap into being and pro- 
 claim it true ; it will be equally self-evident that 
 the angles of a triangle are equal to two right 
 angles, when the mind is as familiar with the 
 nature of triangles. Gassendi objects to the com- 
 mon use of the phrase ' natura notiora ' : as applied 
 to universals it must mean better known by those 
 Avho know them, which is to say by us : it is 
 then false, for we know the particulars better : if 
 it means known to nature, it is wrong ; and if it 
 means in se nota it is nonsense, for knowledge is 
 a relation. In this last argument Gassendi strikes 
 at a position rooted in a substantive theory of 
 ideas : the tendency to regard thoughts as entities 
 made it possible to speak of ideas as possessing 
 knowledge much as substance possessed its primary 
 qualities, and by the same kind of ' inherence ' : 
 Gassendi's functional view enables him to see that 
 the reality of the known is to be known, its use 
 is intelligi, and the universals can have no quality 
 of knowableness, except such as our intellectual
 
 II.] PHYSICS 153 
 
 experience verifies ; ^ and by this criterion we may- 
 judge the universal to be 'better known' in pro- 
 portion as the particulars are better known, or, in 
 other words, in proportion as its content is developed. 
 The reason why universals appear better known 
 is that we tend to isolate intellect, and it then 
 appears to know its own work best. But the ideas 
 must come from the particulars : if not, they are 
 created by the mind ; but why should the mind 
 create universals rather than particulars ? It is 
 only by allowing a knowledge of particulars that 
 we can justify the existence of universals, since the 
 universality is essentially relative to the plurality 
 of particulars. In this way the universal idea 
 obtains its merits at the hand of Gassendi. It 
 loses its character as an entity, with universal 
 being, and survives as an idea wdth more than a 
 particular significance : further than this we need 
 not at present go. 
 
 (e) THE PASSIONS 
 
 In distinction from the Intellectual part of the 
 Soul called Cognoscens, the term Appetens denotes 
 that faculty by which the Soul apprehends and 
 moves toward the good and bad. The pars appetens, 
 or substantively the Appetitus, denotes both faculty 
 and function, being in fact the voO^ SpeKTiKo^ of 
 Aristotle, and comprising both ope^i? and opuy. It 
 might well be called the pars affectiva of the 
 Soul, for it is more than mere cupiditas, and com- 
 
 ^ Si notiora et manifestiora sunt, alicui ergo facultati cognoscenti 
 eiusmodi sunt, dici enim quid notuni, dici manifestum nisi respectu 
 eius cui innotescat manifestaturque, nou potest.
 
 154 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 prises all affections : it is also more than will, for 
 voluntas is the name of an action only, and not 
 of a faculty. We are now entering on the psy- 
 chology of the practical life. As we shall see 
 (p. 162) the question of activity does not trouble 
 Gassendi in this connexion, for he believes that 
 thought is always activity ; consequently, the real 
 distinction comes in the nature of the objects 
 toward which the Soul's activity is directed. In 
 the case of the pars cognoscens this object is 
 truth, for the pars appetens it is the good or the 
 bad which the understanding comprehends, and the 
 appetite seeks or avoids. In a sense this faculty is 
 secondary, for it implies knowledge, a cognoscente 
 excitatur et dirigitur. In accordance with the line 
 of thought indicated above, where it was shown 
 that Phantasy was subject to action both from 
 without and from within, we may distinguish the 
 affections which come to the mind from without, 
 and those which originate from within. Under- 
 standing and Phantasy can act without Appetite 
 (or appetency). It follows therefore that the bodily 
 affections due to appulse are not identical with 
 those called appetite. The point is this : an affec- 
 tion ab extra ends in an idea : it is a motion that 
 produces an image : an appetency is a motion too, 
 and at first sight seems to have no difference 
 except that it goes in the opposite direction 
 (emotion). But there is more than this, for all 
 ideas do not continue into emotions, and the 
 phantasy, we are told, though closely bound up 
 with sense, can act without disturbing appetite. 
 We can therefore think without emotional feeling :
 
 II.] PHYSICS 165 
 
 when the intellectual ' feeling ' does arouse appetite 
 we have the overflow of motion into the body 
 (appetitus functio in corpus redundet). For example, 
 if I see an apple and do not want it, the motion 
 terminates in perception : if on the contrary I do 
 want it, this want may exhibit itself in the overflow 
 of the spirits into the body : my mouth may water 
 or some other effect be produced. 
 
 The meaning of this is quite clear, but it is diffi- 
 cult to understand why a sensuous faculty, such as 
 phantasia, should have any functions that were not 
 in some degree emotional, why we should have 
 imaginations wholly free from any form of desire ; 
 and Gassendi seems here to have relied on the 
 distinction of motion inward and motion outward 
 with the accompanying idea that the reversal of the 
 motion would require a definite act of the central 
 organism. 
 
 If we can have perceptions without emotions in 
 the sphere of the phantasy, it might be thought 
 that the intellect would be self-contained, and either 
 have no emotions or only intellectual emotions. 
 Gassendi is however clear that an emotion is always 
 a bodily reaction, and he therefore expressly says 
 that even our most intellectual objects, if made 
 objects of desire, must arouse bodily reactions : he 
 is thus opposed to such an idea as the amor intel- 
 lectualis of Spinoza : quia Deus Rationalem Animara 
 corpori connectens ea conditione esse illam voluit ut 
 non modo res caeteras sed ipsum quoque gloriosum 
 Deum corporeo modo seu corporea aliqua specie quasi 
 obvelatum intelligat, nihil mirum est si voluntas 
 affectu quod am corporeo non modo in alia sed in
 
 156 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 Deum quoque ipsum feratur : ac Deus idcirco amari 
 se ab homine ut ex tota mente totaque anima, sic 
 ex toto corde omiiibusque viribus jubeat; quippe 
 quasi mens animave amare quidem debeat, sed 
 amorem tamen suum nisi corde viribusque etiam 
 corporeis exprimere non possit. 
 
 It must be remembered in this connexion that if 
 Gassendi asserts that the affections of the mind 
 (Animus) differ from those of the body, he is not 
 thereby proving that one is psychic and the other 
 not : it may be a question of the higher and lower 
 parts of the Soul (Anima). Cp. ii. 480, ' esse unum- 
 quemque speciali quadam temperie ac non modo 
 corpus sed Animam quoque, hoc est inferiorem 
 partem animae, quae corporea est, speciali esse con- 
 textura . . . ut in quam rem propendeat corpus, 
 propendeat ipsa anima.' Our likes and dislikes are 
 therefore always psychic : the obscure point is what 
 relation of Animus to Anima could unite the Animus 
 to the Anima without necessitating the reverse rela- 
 tion of the Anima to Animus and a free pathway 
 for motions in either direction. Gassendi says the 
 Soul moves the body : we ask why cannot the body 
 move the Soul ? 
 
 It is clear that in this point the doctrine of 
 motion has not been allowed to work itself out 
 free from prejudice. The inconsistency, such as it 
 is, seems due to Gassendi's tendency to give the 
 non-corporeal part of man its due position : he 
 even asserts in so many words that the affections 
 of the mind must be wholly different from those 
 of the body, and inclines to over-assert his opposi- 
 tion to a materialistic interpretation of emotions.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 1 57 
 
 The opinion ascribed to Epicurus was fundamentally 
 materialistic. The external stimuli, it was said, 
 penetrated to the senses and reached the Soul : if 
 they were agreeable, the Soul expanded, if disagree- 
 able it contracted, and the Soul being conscious of 
 its own movements, these expansions and contrac- 
 tions constituted emotions. The weak point of the 
 theory was its naive assumption that the motions 
 of the corpuscles could have any such character as 
 agreeableness or disagreeableness in themselves while 
 still on the way to the Soul. It is in opposition 
 to this that Gassendi asserts that the mind must 
 understand the impulse before there can be any 
 affection in the proper sense of the term : if this be 
 denied, only expansion and contraction will be left 
 to us, and these do not involve any kind of feeling 
 necessarily. Gassendi did w^ell to steer away from 
 such a shoal, but he can hardly be said to establish 
 an unambiguous result. If we consider the theory 
 further, it will be evident that the rationalistic 
 element which is generated by opposition to mate- 
 rialism, is itself arrested by a distinctly biological 
 vein of thought. Appetite is moved by contact, 
 and is therefore in a sense co-extensive with the 
 periphery of the body : all sense is touch and all 
 touch is either pleasant or painful. Pain is a breach 
 of continuity (dolorem ex ipsa continui solutione 
 oriri) : pleasure is the restitution of a normal con- 
 dition. This normal condition is Indolentia, a 
 mental state of complete equilibrium. Pleasure and 
 pain are states : the active element by which the 
 transition from one state to another is mediated, 
 is called Cupiditas. This middle term causes move-
 
 158 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 nient out of the state of equilibrium : it is therefore 
 DOt necessary that every pleasure be preceded by a 
 pain, for it is possible to go from a state of pleasure 
 into one of pain. The primary affections, Pleasure 
 and Pain, in their lowest forms do not imply 
 intellectual activity : hunger and sexual desires are 
 made unpleasant in order that they may excite 
 actions conducive to the maintenance of the species. 
 In the natural condition the pleasant is the good ; 
 but the memory is liable to retain the idea of 
 pleasure and seek the sensation when the conditions 
 are wanting {e.g. eating when already satisfied).^ It 
 follows from this that the lowest stage of life to 
 which we trace emotions, is capable of such intellec- 
 tual activities as are implied in Phantasia, which is 
 consistent with Gassendi's denial that animals are 
 automata. Those emotions which differ from the 
 primary affections are marked by the presence of 
 opinion : the mere universal is not enough : we must 
 realise that the particular is a good for us : this 
 causes a movement of the heart and so leads to 
 action, whereas a speculative knowledge remains in 
 the head. This seems the high-road to ' popular 
 philosophy,' and scarcely calls for further attention. 
 We have already pointed out that the ' pars 
 affectiva ' can, like the Phantasy, be considered both 
 from the point of view of the activities which it 
 originates, and that of the activities originated in 
 it. Similarly, we can regard the ' pars affectiva ' 
 either from the point of view of the feelings which 
 it undergoes or that of the feelings it originates. 
 Pain and pleasure are the fundamental affections, 
 
 ^Cp. Bradley, Ethical Studies, on Lust.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 169 
 
 and these terms are consequently the most com- 
 prehensive. The primary ground of feelings is the 
 actual physical effect which a thing is capable of 
 producing in the organism ; but if we are dealing, 
 as we now are, with complex organisms, there will 
 be more than the mere physical reactions which 
 lower organisms exhibit. Hence we find when we 
 come to classify the affections, that pleasure and 
 pain do not cover all the varieties of our experience. 
 
 The classification runs thus. Appetitus divides 
 into that which belongs to the ' anima rationales, ' 
 and that which belongs to the pars irrationalis. In 
 the former case the appetitus is based on the 
 understanding, in the latter, on the phantasy. As 
 to the former, Gassendi declares that the soul (anima 
 rationalis) has affection of its own such as the pure 
 love of the good, but the abstract nature of this 
 affection, though capable of distinction in theory, 
 is not capable of very exact definition because it is 
 rarely found in isolation. The seat of this affection 
 is in the brain, and it is therefore so united with 
 the general organism, that it almost always functions 
 with some bodily reactions. The only practicable 
 distinction of these affections is that they imply a 
 rational activity prior to their own manifestation. 
 
 The second class, on the contrary, do not imply 
 the antecedence of any act of judgment : they 
 depend on phantasy and are modified by the action 
 of Will. The species of this genus are very varied, 
 but can be to some extent classified if we take into 
 consideration the elements of which they are com- 
 posed. The specific forms of pleasure and pain are 
 joy and sorrow, that is to say pleasure and pain
 
 160 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. ii. 
 
 are the states whose effects are joy and sorrow : for 
 it must be remembered that pleasure and pain are 
 terms which primarily denote states, whereas the 
 affection is not a state viewed as a cause of feeling, 
 but the feeling itself. Gassendi here takes into 
 consideration the expression involved in an emotion, 
 and so distinguishes the emotion as an effect from 
 the state or condition which is its cause. If pleasure 
 is directly connected with an object it developes 
 into love : if to this be added the condition of 
 absence or futurity we have the state of desire or 
 hope, from which come confidence and audacity. 
 On the other side, taking pain as our basis, we get 
 corresponding to these, hate, aversion, fear, despair, 
 and pusillanimity. These are the elements which 
 unite to form character. 
 
 On the contents of this chapter, which have not 
 greatly impressed me, I quote the judgment of 
 another more in sympathy with the topic : ' Nul 
 avant lui n'avait etudie avec autant de methode 
 et de profondeur les passions de I'ame . . . il est le 
 premier qui ait ebauche la science du charactere, 
 qui a pris une si grand e importance de nos jours. 
 Sur ce point, d'ailleurs, comme sur beaucoup d'autres, 
 nul ecrivain ne cite les recherches de Gassendi.'^ Is 
 this true outside of France, or only in it ? 
 
 ^ Thomas : Gassendi, p. 194.
 
 CHAPTER IV 
 
 THE NATUEE OF LIFE 
 
 (a) THE VIS MOTRIX 
 
 The subject of motion naturally follows the dis- 
 cussions on the cognitive and appetitive functions. 
 Nature indeed added this power as the complement 
 of the others, that we might not only know and 
 desire the good, but also act for its attainment. 
 
 The functions which have been discussed hitherto 
 have been motions, but such as are usually called 
 immanent : our present subject is local motion, in 
 so far as that is related to will, or, to put it more 
 comprehensively, in so far as it is traceable to an 
 inner principle. The line of distinction is not so 
 easy to draw as might at first appear. We are to 
 speak of all changes of place, and these will include 
 not only movements of one body, but also move- 
 ments of the parts of one body. Among these 
 movements of the parts are many which can only 
 loosely be called subordinate to the Will : for if 
 we reject ' motus cordis, cerebri, intestinorum ven- 
 arumque,' and confine ourselves to ' motus brachii, 
 capitis, linguae,' we may still find a difiiculty in 
 bringing all their movements under the head of 
 voluntary movements. In fact what Gasseudi does
 
 162 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. 
 
 is to make the Vis motrix from the first an instru- 
 ment of Will, and, without trying to make all 
 movements of the parts actions of Will, merely 
 aims at showing how these motions, which we 
 ascribe to Will, are made possible in the economy 
 of nature. 
 
 The power of motion is fundamentally one with 
 life : it is ' ex ipsa natura contexturaque animae,' 
 for the soul is by nature a fire (cp. p. Ill), and its 
 very life is motion (insita mobilitate vigens).^ We 
 thus annihilate at a stroke many threatening diflicul- 
 ties, strangling them in the cradle. If the soul is 
 an active principle, activity will be the principle of 
 the soul : we do not require to bridge the gulf 
 from psychical to physical activity, since they will 
 be one in their foundations : it may be that the 
 deeper we go the more real the unity : that the 
 corpuscles rather than the contextura corpusculorum 
 are the real home of the mobilitas ; but at anyrate, 
 in the spiritus ignei of our organism (the complex 
 referred to as corpore animato) we find a fit starting 
 point. Grassendi explicitly derives mobilitas from 
 the natura ignea, and therefore, since fire was 
 chosen principally for its mobility, commits him- 
 self to a circle : moreover, he considers that a body 
 cannot communicate motion to another unless it be 
 itself mobile, which is reasonable enough, except for 
 the assumptions which it involves : for there could 
 be no motion at all on this theory unless we could 
 find a substance with innate mobility, and that 
 mobility were communicable : these two points 
 therefore have to be assumed. These questions 
 
 In. 505.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 163 
 
 we must leave for the present, and accept Gassendi's 
 position that the body is a living and moving 
 organism, of which a descriptive analysis (if not an 
 explanation) may be given. 
 
 The ' vis ' is the inner fire in its form of spirits : 
 its seat is decided according to the place where 
 the nerves arise, and therefore must be the brain, 
 not the heart : motion lags behind thought, because 
 the spirits must be moved through the whole area 
 of the body, and then re-directed to fresh courses. 
 The organ of the vis motrix is the muscular system : 
 a muscle includes vein, artery and nerve, the channels 
 respectively of blood, vital spirits and animal spirits : 
 anatomical experiments prove that the nerve is the 
 mediator or bearer of vis, and the medulla is a 
 subordinate centre or fountain of the virtus motrix 
 from the brain. The nature of the muscular move- 
 ment has been misunderstood by those who object 
 that a fixed point is required for contraction : the 
 muscle is not draw^n up to its head, it contracts in 
 the middle. Now, what is it that the nerve 
 contributes to this action? Gassendi says it is 
 an ' imperium ' : the essential part of the muscle 
 is the tendon, for that alone has an innate power 
 of contraction : the shock of the incoming current 
 of spirits awakens the dormant power and causes 
 action. This point is apparently considered to be 
 highly important : its significance seems to lie in 
 the fact that it dispenses with the necessity of any 
 power being conveyed from the centre to the seat 
 of action : tliere is no innervation in that .sense 
 of the term : the Mind or Phantasy issues its orders, 
 and nothing more, which is a metaphorical way of
 
 164 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 denying material activity to the mind. How far 
 this ' imperium ' is immaterial when it equals 
 ' appulsus spirituum ' is difficult to see, although 
 technically the spiritus are immaterial ; but it is 
 clear that Gassendi is content to relieve the brain 
 of the necessity of supplying the force that moves 
 the mass. 
 
 All movement is for some end : it applies there- 
 fore an antecedent phantasy giving the good as end. 
 Will then may be said to initiate movement, and 
 the difficulties which normally surround that pro- 
 position are dispersed if we remember that the 
 Appetitus Rationalis is one with the sensitivus and 
 Phantasy mediates sense and intellect. None the 
 less, ' sunt in hac re tria praesertim admiranda.' 
 They are (1) the choice of the nerves required ; 
 (2) the speed of the action ; (3) the amount of 
 the mechanical force. The first problem is shirked : 
 it is said that the branching of nerves is never a 
 division of a nerve, but only a dispersion of several 
 nerves joined together : hence any one nerve is 
 continuous, and the spirits will never be perplexed 
 like a traveller changing at a junction : this how- 
 ever is only an explanation of the persistence of 
 nerve-currents in one channel : what we hoped to 
 learn was how the current chooses the right course 
 at first. The second difficulty is settled by saying 
 that a fiery substance can of course act with the 
 rapidity of light ! As to the third, the answer has 
 already been given when it was pointed out that 
 the energy stored in the muscle is the immediate 
 cause of the mechanical motion. 
 
 The special treatment of the subject of motion
 
 II.] PHYSICS 165 
 
 contains very little of interest to the modern reader : 
 even contemporaries must have found its elaborate 
 details wearisome. It is divided into three parts 
 dealing with (a) movements of parts ; (h) vocalisa- 
 tion ; (c) movements of the whole or modes of 
 progression. The first and third divisions do not 
 require any notice : they are mainly concerned with 
 very elementary anatomy, relieved with the quaint, 
 if unconscious humour, which occasionally crops up 
 in unpromising places. The chapter on the voice ^ 
 is too characteristic to be passed over in silence. 
 In the first place the definition is carefully elaborated : 
 it runs thus : vox proprie est sonus emissione spiritus 
 in ore animalis aliquo affectu incitati creatus. The 
 word ' proprie ' excludes the ' voice ' of all instru- 
 ments ; ' emissione ' dismisses the theories of all 
 those who had not recognised that the act of 
 producing sound is that of expiration not inspira- 
 tion : aliquo affectu incitati is added to exclude 
 coughing, sighing, and the like. Sighing would 
 seem to be one of the ways of expressing ' affec- 
 tions ' ; but Gassendi explains that he means 
 ' affectus animi ' : in short, a sound to be properly 
 vocal must be significant and voluntary, following 
 on some definite act of imagination. The mental 
 activity precedes the physical : for this reason the 
 ancients often spoke of the inner voice, but this is 
 not really a distinction of kinds of voices : the inner 
 voice is nothing more than thought itself which tlu> 
 outer or physical organ interprets. There appear 
 to have been some narrow-minded attempts at con- 
 fining the possession of a voice to man alone, and 
 
 III. 520.
 
 166 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt 
 
 among other devices this voice of the mind was 
 invented that man might be distinguished from the 
 animals even in this detail : it would naturally 
 follow that the human voice was generically distinct 
 from that of animals, and capable of surviving the 
 dissolution of the body. This is one more instructive 
 example of the way entities can be multiplied to 
 serve irrelevant purposes. Gassendi's position is 
 comparatively a strong one : as the voice is the 
 servant of the imagination it will be just as coherent 
 in its expressions as the imagination is in its images. 
 Intelligibility is not an absolute quality, and animals 
 are probably intelligible to one another : their lan- 
 guage is foreign to us, but so is Chinese, and while 
 it may be ' impious ' to say they speak in the human 
 sense, each may be said to speak after its own kind 
 without offence. This correlation of the voice and 
 the faculty of images, puts Gassendi on a firm 
 basis capable of considerable expansion. When we 
 come to deal with the specifically human voice we 
 find the evolutionary aspect tending to obliterate 
 the hard and fast distinctions more natural to this 
 period of thought. The natural history of speech 
 must begin with a stage not so far removed from 
 that of the animals : infants make only vocal sounds : 
 fari non possunt, as the name witnesses ; and it is 
 only after time and experience that they reach the 
 varied articulations of developed speech. Gassendi 
 notes that pronunciation is directly related to 
 physical structure : it cannot be learned from 
 books, and in some degree remains always a birth- 
 right not to be won by labour. This point was 
 another blow at theorists who vaguely equated the
 
 II.] PHYSICS 107 
 
 power of speech with human nature in general and 
 ignored the facts. On the question ' sintne noiuina 
 natura vel instituto' Gassendi takes the same view 
 as Epicurus, and avoids both extremes : the primary 
 name is a sound significant of pleasure or pain ; 
 but people even in the same place would regard 
 the same thing differently, and hence designate it 
 by different names : so that intercourse would be 
 impossible if convention did not supplement nature 
 and carry out a natural selection of sounds until 
 one object had one name : for succeeding generations 
 this would be a nomen ex instituto acquired through 
 the medium of society. 
 
 Gassendi quotes an example of the contemporary 
 science of language which shows that he knew where 
 to stop. The doctrine of natural names had been 
 defended on the ground that the meaning and 
 the motion were often identical. Tu and ego, for 
 example, necessitate movements of the lips outward 
 and inward respectively, that is to say toward you 
 and toward myself! The error which had most to 
 be combated was the use of arbitrary as the opposite 
 of natural. There could be no question to an intelli- 
 gent mind of arbitrary names : though an arbitrium 
 might be exercised in the selection of words when 
 a language was consolidated, in the early stages such 
 words as became ex instituto would be so from a 
 natural process rather than any direct activity of 
 human choice.^ 
 
 1 Max Miiller, Science of Language, ii. 382 : ' And this, better than 
 anything else, will, I think, explain the strong objection which com- 
 parative philologists feel to what I called the Bow-wow and the 
 Pooh-i)ooh theories, names which, I am sorry to see, have given gieat 
 offence, but in framing which, I can honestly sjiy, I thought more of
 
 168 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 {b) LIFE AND DEATH 
 
 The definition of life is a task essayed by writers 
 in generation after generation. A broad distinction 
 can at once be made according as the writer takes 
 life in the sense of a thing or a process. If he 
 regards it statically as a being or entity he is not 
 likely to advance far : if he regards it dynamically 
 as a doing or function he will at least be on the 
 right track. In this respect a philosopher who in- 
 clines to use motion as his common denominator is 
 guided by his general attitude of mind into paths 
 that may reach the goal. At the same time vita 
 and operatio are not quite identical : it is truer to 
 say vita per operationem patescit, although it cannot 
 be understood sine ordine ad operationem. 
 
 Gassendi proposes as his definition ' quaedam quasi 
 usura sive possessio animae facultatisque operandi 
 ipsius,' obviously wishing to combine with the notion 
 of unintermittent function the idea of an agent. It 
 is however a fallacy to try and erect the means of 
 life into Life itself. To define life as mansionem 
 caloris (or calidi innati) is to commit such a fallacy. 
 TJie calor is really fomentum vitae : it is necessary, 
 but not more so than the elements : though in fact 
 it prevails and is the principium agens. Its activity 
 
 Epicurus than of living writers, and meant no offence to either.' 
 Ibid. 398 : ' Even Epicurus, who is reported to have said that in the 
 first formation of language men acted unconsciously, moved by 
 nature . . . admitted that this would only account for one half the 
 language, and that some agreement must have taken place before 
 language really began.' The 'reported to have said' refers us to 
 Proclus ad Plat. Crat. p. 9 : o yap 'EttLkovpos fKeyev 8tl ovxl iTn<TTr)iJ.hvws 
 o5toi idevTO ra dvo/xara, dXXa (pvaiKuis Kivovfxevoi, ws oi ^TjcraovTes Kal TrraipovTe's 
 Kdl fiVKw/xevoi Kal vXaKTovi>T€s /cat (Trevd^ovres.
 
 II.] PHYSICS l(i;> 
 
 is directed to the absorption of the liumours, which 
 are the pabulum vitae. All life is creation : the 
 individual is no isolated unit : the stream of bi-- 
 comino- flows throuoh him : as worlds, nations, and 
 generations arise and decay, so the individual moves 
 along, dying daily and daily regaining new life. 
 Generatio is continuatio vitae and vita is a contiiiens 
 generatio. Life abides as the flame of a candle, 
 kindling what it burns : its fuel is the humour, itself 
 the flame, but only he can distinguish the one from 
 the other who can separate the burning from what 
 is burnt. 
 
 This position carries with it the doctrine that 
 identity is continuity of action : the original seed 
 contains two forces, the heating and the heated : 
 calidum primigenium and humidum primigenium as 
 opposed to such heat as that of the sun or humours 
 such as are obtained in food. From the first then 
 there is a duality which makes action possible. The 
 heat-corpuscles by virtue of their nature fly off and 
 take with them the humid : the consequent exhaus- 
 tion is checked by alimentation, by which the humitl 
 elements are multiplied and detain the heat-elements. 
 The action of the heat-elements is then employed 
 in distributing the new elements throughout the 
 body and renewing its tissues. Life then is the 
 interaction of these two principles, a conclusion wliich 
 derives its imjDortance from the fact that the current 
 doctrines supported a substantia immutabilis as th<' 
 secret entity called life. This view was dictated b}- 
 the false view of identity. In place of a fixed 
 identity we can put the identity of equivalence : a 
 part remains to connect the changes, and the form
 
 170 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 is not lost in the flux of matter. From this however 
 Gassendi exempts the pars rationalis. Again, the 
 stages of growth are not reached per saltum : a 
 proportion is maintained and identity consists in 
 this proportion. As the brain also grows, thought- 
 identity cannot be absolute or immutable : empirically 
 at least it is partial : particles vanish and with them 
 parts of our experience : hence some things are for- 
 gotten and some remembered confusedly. There is 
 an unfortunate crudeness in speaking, as though an 
 experience could be attached to a brain particle ; 
 but it is redeemed by the last trenchant remark that 
 our identity abides because we have never been 
 separated from ourselves. 
 
 The processes of life as thus described would seem 
 to be unending, involving continual growth. There 
 are however natural conditions which prevent this. 
 Growth is checked by the hardening of parts wdiich 
 do not permit of accretion as they become closed 
 to the influx of new material. In the midst of life 
 there is death, and it is an error to confine the word 
 death to the act of expiring : death is properly the 
 whole course of failure to assimilate, unless it be 
 violent and due to some extraneous cause. Gassendi 
 discourses at large on all the legends of long life 
 in man and animals and also on all manner of violent 
 deaths : death by drowning was thought most awful, 
 for the soul being a flame is particularly averse to 
 water. 
 
 By regarding death as no less natural than life 
 Gassendi touches a question of great importance in 
 his day. His dictum, what has a natural birth has 
 also a natural death, was by no means generally
 
 II.] PHYSICS 171 
 
 accej)ted, and his summary of the opposite teaching 
 is an interesting commentary on contemporary 
 thought. It must be remembered that this dis- 
 cussion does not affect the question of the immor- 
 tality of the souh 
 
 The common teaching was based on that antithesis 
 of life and death which regarded death as a purely 
 negative term : the reality was life, death an un- 
 reality, and some method ought therefore to be 
 discoverable by which life might be made infinitely 
 continuous. At the bottom of this doctrine lies the 
 idea of the World Soul, which, as it is perpetually 
 taken up by us and lost again through the dispersion 
 of particles, might be retained if the nature of man 
 was purified and made perfect. The prescribed 
 process was as follows ; the Anima Mundi will 
 remain in the perfect substance : this is gold which 
 can be relaxed so as to absorb from the rays of the 
 sun the principle of life : being thus enclosed in one 
 substance, a vital elixir may be formed from this 
 substance, and the Anima Mundi be conveyed into 
 the body, which gradually becomes purified and 
 perfected, attaining all the qualities which belong 
 to the spiritual body mentioned in the Bible, and 
 fulfilling the prophecy that men should be almost 
 angels, being ' a little lower than the angels.' ' Sane 
 vero,' says Gassendi, ' haec sunt non tam refutanda 
 quam diris omnibus devovenda,' Criticism is hardly 
 necessary even to the extent of pointing out that 
 if gold admits the external principle so easily it 
 might no less easily part witli it. Tlic whole scheme 
 is the work of ill-trained imaginations urged on by 
 the desires which are common to all races and all
 
 172 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 times. The idea of reducing all things to one form 
 was based on the opinion that, if all things are forms 
 of matter, the matter must be some nature to which 
 all other natures were reducible, and through which 
 they could be transformed into any other given 
 nature. This fundamental common nature x being 
 a universal, its discovery would simplify all the 
 sciences, and especially that of medicine, making 
 possible a medicina catholica, for the unity of the 
 universal nature would admit of a medicine one 
 and universal, apparently because it would make a 
 plurality of diseases impossible. The tyranny of 
 the universal in the sciences has been noted often 
 enough : its power was at its highest when the 
 minds of men were dazzled by new discoveries, and 
 vague generalisations were suddenly quickened into 
 a new indefinite possibility of life by rumours of 
 great discoveries and vague echoes of unearthly 
 knowledge from the dim and superstitious cell of 
 the alchemist. 
 
 These two pages give an excellent account of the 
 essence of Alchemy as a magic science. Gassendi 
 also gives us a hint of the way in which Transub- 
 stantiation and Transmutation became confused : 
 ' gloriosum Christi sanguinem . . . edixerunt nihil 
 aliud esse quam Catholicam suam Medicinam ! ' 
 (ii. 615). 
 
 (c) THE CONSTITUTION OF ANIMALS 
 I. 
 
 The word temperament or temperies which is used 
 by Gassendi to denote the constitution of living 
 bodies was ambiguous in his own time, and has now
 
 II.] PHYSICS 173 
 
 diverged still further from its original meaning. The 
 complexity of meaning is however a true indication 
 of the evolution of the ideas the word denotes. The 
 Latin ' temperamentum ' originally meant no more 
 or less than the Kpaai^ of the Greeks, and is con- 
 vertible with ' commistio ' : it looks therefore entirely 
 to the physical composition of the body, and is a 
 name for the various ratios which may hold between 
 the elements in any ' totum compositum.' None the 
 less the purely physical aspect never excluded the 
 idea of character, which again, though applicable to 
 all things, tended to become restricted to psychical 
 character. In this way a natural course of develop- 
 ment carries us over from elements and atoms to 
 characters and dispositions. 
 
 The doctrine of Temperaments is a characteristic 
 element of mediaeval thought : its vaoueness gives 
 it a tinge of mysticism : it seems to unite the two 
 worlds of mind and matter in one comprehensive 
 grasp, and links the characters of our acquaintances 
 with the day of creation and the emergence of atoms 
 from chaos. Looked at from one point of view, 
 mediaeval thought will be seen to have no lack of 
 breadth : dogma was indeed a constricting power, but 
 it did not suppress the longing for universal terms 
 in which to state or solve problems, nor impose its 
 precision on minds that found much satisfaction in 
 undefined thoughts and over-defined diction. 
 
 Though the subject of temperament may now be 
 said to have vanished from what we usually call 
 philosophical works, much of what the mediaeval 
 thinker collected under that title can be found in 
 modern form in works that deal with the concrete
 
 174 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 individual, with the natures and dispositions of 
 children, hygiene, adolescence, and the like, and we 
 find in books on these topics a growing tendency 
 to vindicate the relation of physical to psychical 
 characteristics in that concrete way which the 
 theories called ' psycho-physical ' rarely or never 
 attempt. 
 
 If we now turn to Gassendi's pages we find that 
 he begins with a summary of qualities, enumerating 
 three different classes, and then states quite generally 
 that all qualities owe their origin to the ' temperies,' 
 and as the temperament is so will the qualities be. 
 The chief reason however for discussing the question 
 of temperament is that we may be able to advance 
 to the questions of health and disease, which are 
 only natural and unnatural conditions of tempera- 
 ment. In a sense the temperament is life, for it is 
 that equilibrium which must be maintained, and 
 which admits only a limited degree of disturbance. 
 
 The history of the theory of Temperament divides 
 naturally into two periods. In the earlier the 
 question is mainly of elements, and always of some 
 form or other of matter : in the latter chemical 
 principles take the place of primaeval elements. If 
 any one finds this a distinction without a difi"erence, 
 and complains that chemical principles are a form 
 of matter, he must recollect that such was not the 
 attitude of the fourteenth century, when men were 
 most at home with ' dead matter,' and felt a difficulty 
 in classifying many of the chemist's discoveries. 
 
 Those doctrines which take as their basis either 
 atoms or elements, go back to the earliest days of 
 Greek thought. They have however many difficul-
 
 II.] PHYSICS 175 
 
 ties. The nature of the combination is a fundamental 
 problem : the result has to be a mean of some kind ; 
 but if we deal with either atoms or elements as 
 irreducible ultimates, they must either (like grains 
 of corn) be simply co-existent, or they must inter- 
 penetrate. Co-existence clearly is not what is wanted, 
 and interpenetration implies that two bodies occupy 
 the same space. On the other hand, qualitative 
 difference is not obtainable if the elements are all 
 homogeneous : water added to water only gives a 
 difference of more or less : our combinations must 
 be different in kind, analogous rather to the mixture 
 of wine and water. This is in fact our type, and 
 we must explain the mixture as we have done in 
 discussing qualities, by introducing the concept of 
 intension. We have here really two questions. One 
 is of the temperamentum ex primis principiis : the 
 other of temperamentum ex contrariis. The former 
 goes deeper than the latter, and is an ulterior 
 question, the decision of which hardly affects the 
 second. Gassendi proceeds to deal with the latter. 
 As a theory it is really independent of the particular 
 given matter : it rests upon a category which may be 
 taken formally. Any combination x + y satisfies the 
 conditions if x and y are contrary. Hence there is 
 no a priori reason for taking only those four, earth, 
 air, fire, and water, to which the discussion is usually 
 confined. That choice is dictated by irrelevant 
 considerations of the physical constitution of the 
 universe : so far as our category goes, we might 
 employ such opposites as light, heavy, smooth, 
 rough, and the like. Avicenna indeed seems to have 
 been confused, and perhaps others with him : they
 
 176 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 took the four elements as typical of four qualities, 
 and so were led astray, speaking as though the 
 qualities might change and mingle, whereas the true 
 view is that of Galen, who refused to divorce quality 
 from substance, and remained on firmer ground in 
 trying to explain the Temperament (Kpaai?) as an 
 interrelation of substances (Galenus probandus dum 
 elementarum substantias misceri totas per totas 
 dicit).^ These points we leave and simply admit 
 four substances, a hot, a cold, a wet, and a dry, 
 which, wherever they have obtained their qualities, 
 are mingled and tempered. Their mingling results 
 in some corpus (lapis, planta, animal), and we may 
 define a temperament as ' congrua calidi et frigidi, 
 humidi et sicci mistura.' This dogmatic solution of 
 the question seems dictated by the medical views of 
 the time on humours and diseases, which Gassendi 
 was probably not in a position to criticise. According 
 to Galen, temperaments may be distinguished into 
 nine kinds, one the canon or norm, the rest abnormal, 
 due either to excess of one quality (which gives four 
 kinds) or of two (giving four more). A temperament 
 may be too hot or too dry (siccum et calidum), but 
 cannot be too hot and too cold (calidum et frigi- 
 dum) : these eight are therefore the only combinations 
 possible. The mean temperature is itself twofold 
 according to Avicenna, namely universal and specific. 
 The universal is ad pondus, i.e. a typical form 
 assumed as the nature of universal substance and 
 determined quantitatively, the mixture comprising 
 mathematically equal quantities of the four opposites. 
 This however is condemned by Galen as purely 
 
 ^n. 551.
 
 II.] PHYSICS 177 
 
 theoretical, and if it existed it would be a pure 
 equilibrium which could exhibit no action and no 
 metabolism (neque si qualitates sic tempera tiie exis- 
 terent actio exseri ab illis ulla posset). The second 
 or specific kind is ad justitiam, a proportion which 
 realises a mean, and which, while being the same in 
 the sense of always being a mean, is not absolute 
 quantity. This kind varies with the nature of the 
 being and the diflferent ages of the same being, 
 but in such a way as to maintain its chief char- 
 acteristics. There will be degrees of better and 
 worse in the types thus realised, and therefore we 
 may derive from this a true type without assuming 
 the typical absolute type ad pond us. Every animal 
 is heterogeneous, and therefore its temperament is 
 complex. Some of its parts are fluent, some fixed : 
 the fluent are called humours and their excess gives 
 the four types sanguine, phlegmatic, choleric, and 
 melancholic : the fixed comprise the ' partes sper- 
 maticas semineasve et sanguineas ' : the spermatic or 
 ex semine formatae are bone, cartilage, ligament, 
 tendon, nerve, artery, and membrane : those ex san- 
 guine procreatae are the softer parts, heart, kidneys, 
 liver, and lungs. The whole has a harmony of its 
 own, and the whole animal is a well-ordered republic. 
 
 II. 
 
 The progress of knowledge tended to relegate to 
 the limbo of myths all the ancients had said about 
 elements. The Chemists substituted for principles 
 and primary elements their own chemical elements. 
 Into the details of this doctrine we need not pene- 
 trate : in the place of the four elements five 
 
 M
 
 178 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 substances were recognised as the elements to 
 which all things could be reduced, and from which 
 they must therefore have arisen. Gassendi is not 
 concerned with the value of this position as a 
 scientific doctrine, but with its philosophic import. 
 He obviously regards it as pretentious, and his 
 criticism is an interesting composition of views on 
 the nature of things. There are four direct charges 
 against the doctrine ; the authors of it cannot agree 
 among themselves as to the number of ultimate 
 principles : special properties of natural objects, such 
 as the healing power of dictamum or the deadly 
 cold of hemlock, remain unexplained : no explana- 
 tion is given of the form of organic and inorganic 
 products ; and all the higher qualities such as saga- 
 city are completely overlooked. 
 
 Though these are details, they involve a principle 
 of the highest importance. The merely scientific 
 mind takes its stand on analysis : the chemist says 
 'analysis gives such and such elements, and therefore, 
 unintelligible as it may be, these must be the source 
 of all that we see.' But when is an analysis ex- 
 haustive ? If the chemists laugh at the ancient 
 physiologists, what will future ages say to the 
 chemists ? The assumption of finality is mocked by 
 progress ; and the progress we boast is part of a 
 movement to which we must succumb — a sentiment 
 that recalls the saying, ' the evolution of thought 
 is part of the whole evolution. ' When is an analysis 
 exhaustive ? Probably never, but at any rate only 
 when it admits of an adequate corresponding syn- 
 thesis. Gassendi shows that he clearly comprehended 
 this great principle. The chemist, he says, would
 
 II.] PHYSICS 179 
 
 lauo'h at a surwon who declared that the living 
 being was no more than a sum of the parts which 
 he could dissect and display. If we try to make 
 our analytic of constitution a complete explanation 
 of life, failure must necessarily ensue. ^ The reason 
 is clear : we strive to exhaust in terms of sense 
 what is not given to the senses : we cannot reach 
 the ultimate because the torch that lights the in- 
 tellect fails us on the road.^ For this reason it is 
 useless to substitute for principia any imaginary 
 sensuous agents such as mechanical spirits : the 
 complexity of life in all its forms, with all its end- 
 less adaptations, cannot be explained by mechanical 
 agents unless we abuse the term and ascribe to 
 such agents properties which are foreign to mechanism. 
 The construction of a palace appears to us marvellous 
 with its endless processes : the wood has to be 
 brought from the forest, the stone from the quarry, 
 
 ^This is one of the finest passages in Gassendi. The chemists, 
 he says, would laugh at a surgeon who said the body could only 
 be divided as far as anatomy divides it : they would say ' loe can 
 divide still further'; but 'quemadraodum sit tibi chirurgus ineptus 
 ... sic ipse videaris futurus ineptus . . . ineptus, inquara, ipsi 
 Naturae.' Even this more penetrating analysis cannot get to the 
 bottom of things : ' utcunque ergo nactus sis huiuscemodi quod dis- 
 solvat agens, non niagis tamen nactus es agens quod ab eo secreta 
 compingat, quam chirurgus ille organum quod parteis scalpello 
 secretas adunet. Atqui est praeterea in Natura agens quod com- 
 pingat coadunetque.' 
 
 (adunare is Gassendi's technical term for the producing of unity 
 by composition : it really denotes more than compingere, indicating 
 the view of the result as a whole, while compingere remains at 
 the point of view of the parts as being welded together.) 
 
 2 II. 558. 'neque intellectus, tanquam praeeunte face destitutus 
 penetrare suo acumine potest in illorum substantiam.' 
 
 'Sensibusdestituimurquibuspraeeuntibus Intellectus sua acutie prin- 
 cipia huiuscemodi deprehendat,a8sequatur, prolustret, introapiciat' (559).
 
 180 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. ii. 
 
 and all the parts have to be shaped and fitted 
 together ; but in this case we see the agents, archi- 
 tect, masons, and woodcutters, and if we still find 
 cause of wonder in this, how much more should we 
 marvel at the construction of a living body where 
 all the agents are unseen and the structure has to 
 be maintained by incessant repair ! ^ We must not 
 think that we can exhaust nature : there is some- 
 thing that does not fall in the range of human 
 powers, and while we cannot completely explain 
 Nature we must so far bow before it as to acknow- 
 ledge that the whole is more than the parts, the 
 synthesis greater than our analysis. 
 
 This criticism is strengthened by the restraint 
 it shows : it ends in no dogmatic introduction of a 
 creator which science might require to have demon- 
 strated : it is intended only to define the limits of 
 science.^ The question arises, are those limits 
 necessary or contingent ? No distinct answer is 
 here given, but Gassendi seems to consider that 
 in time (perhaps infinite time) the unknown might 
 become revealed, not to sense alone but to an intellect 
 guided by sense. After this philosophic digression, 
 the treatise returns to the question of diseases and 
 their cure, medicine being the science to which the 
 doctrine of temperaments is properly ancillary. For 
 our present purpose this part of the subject is 
 superfluous. 
 
 Mi. 557. 
 
 ^nullo non saccule Natura illud homini insusurret aut potius 
 inclamet, 
 
 'Tecum habita et noris quarn sit tibi curta suppellex.' 
 But 'nihil sit desperandum de humani ingenii sagacitate,' ii. 560.
 
 PART III. ETHICS
 
 CHAPTER I 
 ON HAPPINESS 
 
 I. 
 
 The student who enters on the task of discovering 
 Gassendi's views on ethics has before him a problem 
 of considerable magnitude. The mass of quotations 
 is enormous : repetition is frequent : and the main 
 line of thought is obscured by the two-fold purpose 
 of defending and at the same time modifying the 
 views of Epicurus. The whole literature of the 
 subject is ransacked : the Greek philosophers are 
 quoted in almost unreadable type : passages from 
 the Fathers and other authors innumerable occupy 
 whole pages : while the doctrine actually supported 
 is obscured by endless polemics against authors now 
 for the most part deservedly forgotten. To repre- 
 sent the learning of the original is almost impossible, 
 while omission of the quotations must necessarily 
 deprive the reader of a true idea of Gassendi's 
 method of treating the subject. The doctrine must 
 however be stripped of this robe of erudition, and 
 perhaps a method that leaves the truth naked will 
 not be without its advantages. 
 
 Gassendi's preface states his position. Moral 
 philosophy is not speculative or concerned only
 
 184 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 with theory : it is also a scientia activa, a treatise 
 de eligendis et fugiendis, a practical study. It is 
 a theory of Prudence rather than wisdom. As. 
 Gassendi notes, the word ' morals ' does not quite 
 equal the Greek ' ethics.' The latter indicates more 
 clearly the element of individual habituation ; and 
 virtue, though innate, requires education of the 
 soul. Man is solitarius, familiaris, and civilis. 
 Morality is properly concerned with man as soli- 
 tarius in the sense that the self is the foundation 
 of all, and thus this science is distinguished from 
 all others, such as Politics, which deal with man 
 in his relations to the society or the State. 
 
 We naturally expect from this a certain psycho- 
 logical and individual trend in the rest of the 
 treatment. The first book is on Felicity, the second 
 on the virtues, and the third on the kindred subjects 
 of Liberty, Fortune, Fate, and Divination. 
 
 II. 
 
 The discussion of Felicitas opens in a characteristic 
 way with twenty-seven pages of quotation. Felicity 
 is the end of life, but in what sense ? It is really a. 
 confusion of terms to make Felicity the summum 
 bonum, for felicity is the possession of the highest 
 good, which must therefore be determined separately. 
 The best of the many definitions of the summum 
 bonum is ' tranquillitas animi,' but we must conceive 
 that as an active state, a living, not a dead repose. 
 It is a permanent condition which must be reached 
 by the mind through its self-discipline. No external 
 means or sensual indulgences can produce the desired 
 state : meditation must free the soul from all care^
 
 III.] ETHICS 185 
 
 especially the meditation of death, which enables 
 men to see life steadily and see it whole. The con- 
 dition which results is a pleasant state, and therefore 
 pleasure is in a sense the end of life. This statement 
 has unfortunately led to many errors, and it must 
 not be left unguarded : we must find out the real 
 meaning of pleasure before proceeding further. 
 
 The defence of pleasure as vitae beatae finem is 
 really a defence of Epicurus, and is put in the form 
 of a discussion on what Epicurus meant by pleasure. 
 Some writers have represented Epicurus as taking 
 pleasure in a bad sense : among these Cicero and 
 Athenaeus are most noteworthy : Seneca, on the 
 other hand, with Plutarch, can be quoted as defend- 
 ing Epicurus. Cicero seems to have been led astray 
 by considering the objects which give pleasures (ludos 
 et cantus et formas eas et quibus oculi jucunde move- 
 antur) and not the state of mind produced. Unless 
 the pleasure as a mental state is considered there can 
 be no distinction of good and bad : for the same 
 outward object may affect different minds differently. 
 Plutarch points out this difference between Epicurus 
 and Aristippus : the pleasure which Epicurus means 
 is of the mind, that which Aristippus praises is of 
 the body. Laertius points out other differences. 
 Aristippus confines the term to pleasure in motu, 
 Epicurus lays more stress on pleasure in statu or 
 tranquillity. This distinction is the root of further 
 divergence. Aristippus considers pleasure of the 
 body the only true pleasure : Epicurus admits or 
 rather emphasises pleasures of mind. The real 
 difference in these views is to be found quite apart 
 from the question of sensual or non-sensual pleasures,
 
 186 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 in the problems of Being and Change. As Gassendi 
 points out, Pleasure (tjSopi'i) has never had a bad 
 significance in itself. The bad states were such as 
 luxury (rpvcf)/), mollities). To view the doctrines of 
 either Epicurus or Aristippus from the point of view 
 of moral and immoral pleasures is to misunderstand 
 the whole position : such a procedure is indeed natural 
 to us because we have become used to the morals of 
 the pulpit, which takes morality as the presupposi- 
 tion of its ethics : before the religious dogmas became 
 thus fixed ethical enquiry was the means by which 
 men hoped to attain a concept of the good, not 
 bolster up with theory what they had already deter- 
 mined to support. Thus it is a hysteron proteron 
 to condemn a pleasure as immoral, for the pleasant- 
 ness may prove the criterion of moralness. It is 
 true that the teaching both of Epicurus and of the 
 Cyrenaics was liable to be used as a justification 
 of sensuality ; but originally these thinkers were 
 more concerned with other problems, and especially 
 whether a pleasure could be anticipated, which 
 Aristippus denied and Epicurus affirmed. The kind 
 of dialectic employed here can easily be imagined. 
 Is the pleasure of anticipation a future pleasure or 
 a pleasure referred to the future ? What is the 
 relation of time involved in this ? Is not all pleasure 
 present pleasure, and will it not therefore be advan- 
 tageous to concentrate our powers upon the present ? 
 Is not rest a ceasing from action, and therefore from 
 the (active) enjoyment of pleasure, a lapsing from 
 life to nirvana ? At this last point the externality 
 of Aristippus' view shows itself only too plainly : the 
 quies or rest of contemplation is not a ceasing from
 
 III.] ETHICS 187 
 
 all action : it is the highest activity, though it may 
 not go beyond the subject. In these ditierences of 
 opinion about becoming and movement we must look 
 for the roots of the more superficial divergences of 
 Epicurean and Cyrenaic doctrine. If we can get rid 
 of those ideas of pleasure which attach themselves 
 exclusively to the senses, we shall see that in its 
 broader sense pleasure is the very essence of life. 
 This broader sense Epicurus must have taken : he 
 considers pains of mind greater than pains of body, 
 and never ceases to insist on the place due to 
 pleasures of mind. Taking it in this comprehensive 
 way, we may say virtue and pleasure are as insepar- 
 able as the sun is from the day : true pleasure flows 
 from virtue, and they are by nature one (virtutem 
 esse causam felicitatis effectricem). 
 
 We may pause here to ask what is meant by 'true 
 pleasure.' It seems as though vera felicitas was an 
 ambiguous term in Gassendi. So far as we concern 
 ourselves with pleasure, true must either mean be- 
 longing to a normal constitution or must carry with 
 it suggestions of some criterion other than pleasant- 
 ness. We may of course take up the narrow position 
 of some critics of psychological hedonism and say 
 that pleasure admits of no modifications except in 
 the way of quantity. But this criticism, if relevant 
 to later doctrines, would not touch Gassendi, whose 
 whole attitude of mind precludes the possibility of 
 so abstract a view. He would consider it a mockery 
 of moral philosophy to set up pleasure in the sense 
 of pleasantness, felt pleasure, as end or criterion. It 
 is not enough that you as man find pleasure in the 
 deed : you as moral subject must first prove yourself
 
 188 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 a fit judge. This brings us in sight of an old circle : 
 we seem on the verge of being told that we ought 
 to pursue pleasure and that we ought to find pleasure 
 only in that which we ought (for other reasons) to 
 pursue. We do in fact end in a dictum like that of 
 Aristotle : a true pleasure is such as a true man feels, 
 and if this avoids the difficulty of the man who finds 
 happiness in evil, it none the less gives us a concrete 
 norm. 
 
 Gassendi's solution, if such it be, of the problem 
 exhibits some familiar elements. To go back to the 
 question of kinds of pleasure. Though some say all 
 pleasure is good, all pain bad, it is true that some- 
 times pleasure is postponed to pain and vice versa. 
 The fallacy is discovered in the absolute use of the 
 term pleasure : Epicurus recognised several kinds, 
 some in tranquillitate, some in motu, including pro- 
 fligatorum voluptates. But this is not quite an 
 accurate statement : pleasure is not quite a motion, 
 it is rather ' condimentum actionis,' a pervading 
 sweetness. Moreover the suggested distinction of 
 motus animi and motus corporis is false : if the 
 mind moves there must also be corporeal move- 
 ment. Is pleasure essentially good (sua natura 
 bonum). Epicurus thought so : Antisthenes denied 
 it : the Stoics classed it as indilferens : some distin- 
 guish good and bad, and some say it is good, but not 
 the highest good. 
 
 The conclusion runs thus : all nature seeks what 
 is natural to it, and therefore seeks what is good 
 and pleasant. Bad pleasures must then be due to 
 some taint and to the fault of the agent. As the 
 good is per se attractive, all pleasures must be
 
 III.] ETHICS 189 
 
 desirable. The reason why a pleasure is rejected 
 is generally some anticipated evil consequence, e.g. 
 when we refuse to eat the honey because we suspect 
 that it is poisoned.^ The proof that animals have 
 connate desires for what is pleasant is taken from 
 Cicero. About this there are two points to be 
 noticed : these connate desires are apparently to be 
 regarded as conscious purposes but without proof of 
 this consciousness : secondly, the passage in Cicero 
 makes the end self-love not pleasure. It is obvious 
 that, do what we may to clarify Gassendi's state- 
 ments, confusion must remain, for we have no clear 
 distinction between three very different ideas. 
 The Good may mean 
 
 (1) That which is good for the animal according 
 to the divine plan, or in the sight of God. This 
 may be different for each being, but it is such as 
 fulfils that creature's wants, if those wants be re- 
 garded from an external point of view, such as 
 might be ascribed to God. 
 
 (2) That which is good for the creature who 
 regards himself as part of a system and has a 
 rational comprehension of ends higher than his 
 individual satisfaction. 
 
 (3) That which the creature thinks to be his good. 
 Of these three the first is not properly in the 
 
 sphere of ethical considerations at all, while the 
 third is a question of illusion, since it is always 
 practically assumed that the agent chooses under 
 some conditions that warp his natural judgment. 
 In trying to define the end as both good and 
 pleasant Gassendi errs (in good company, too) by 
 
 ^ii. 695.
 
 190 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 not seeing that he is arbitrarily modifying both 
 terms, the chooser and the chosen. Doubtless, given 
 a man whose pleasure was in the good, the good 
 would be to him pleasant ; but an ethic that modifies 
 both terms ceases to be practical : it becomes ima- 
 ginary, speculative, and abstract. Love of God, 
 says Gassendi, is in the highest degree good and 
 pleasant : he means presumably that it ought to be 
 if it is not. If we revert to man as he is, can we 
 still maintain these statements ? Gassendi thinks 
 we can, and that is just one more instance of the 
 latent universal. The keynote to the whole posi- 
 tion is to be found in the phrase, ' omne animal 
 e natura sua sic comparatur ut natura duce nihil 
 prius requirat ' : where natura is clearly taken in 
 abstraction, as though there were a natura pos- 
 sessed by all creatures and capable of being held 
 over against the sum of desires. Such a natura is 
 a deduction from observation, and even if we allow 
 that man might oppose his idea of the nature of 
 man to his actual nature, as expressed in his 
 desires, it is clearly absurd to read into the exist- 
 ence of the animal a duality which reflective thought 
 has constructed. Gassendi has not properly com- 
 prehended the fact that he encroaches on the 
 metaphysic of ethics in taking the question in this 
 universal way. There is however another side to 
 his argument, which must not be overlooked. He 
 is concerned to prove that a good is no less a good 
 for being associated with pleasure. In words that 
 remind us of Locke's well-know^n phrase, he attri- 
 butes the association of goodness with pleasure to 
 the act of God. This seems to be supported by
 
 Ill] ETHICS 191 
 
 such considerations as the union of goodness and 
 pleasantness in the acts of procreation or feeding ; 
 but it is significant that the position finds most 
 support from those forms of life which are furthest 
 removed from full consciousness as we know it, and 
 for which the goodness as such is presumably non- 
 existent. If we press the question we fall into 
 paradox : self-sacrifice we find is made for the 
 pleasure it gives : if Brutus killed his sons it was 
 because his sons were such as Brutus disliked, and 
 therefore it was a pleasure to Brutus to kill them : 
 a statement that shows that Gassendi was badly in 
 need of a distinction between what is pleasurable 
 and what is preferable. 
 
 III. 
 
 We should almost expect from the position 
 assigned to Pleasure that it would be pronounced 
 the end of all action. This is modified by a dis- 
 tinction between goods which are classified as 
 honestum, utile, and jucundum. The third class is 
 always chosen ob voluptatem : the others may not 
 be. Psychologically voluptas accompanies desire, and 
 desire is generated by want. The want comes first, 
 and the object is chosen as satisfying the want : 
 pleasure ceases with attainment, which in turn 
 generates a new want. This third class, things 
 jucunda, is meant to include those that satisfy 
 bodily wants. The first two classes generate pleasure, 
 because their absence is a want. Of these the class 
 Utile comprises objects which are not pleasant as 
 acts, but are sought with reference to the pleasure 
 to be obtained from them. Cooking, building, and
 
 192 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 singing are examples. The highest class honestum, 
 including all honores, causes some difi&culty. It has 
 been said that these must be chosen 'for them- 
 selves ' : the honestum is per se dignum. But the 
 worth is not impaired by any addition of pleasant- 
 ness ; and the desire to divorce the two is really 
 due to a confusion between seeking a high position 
 and seeking the material advantages of position. 
 The honestum must be at least a permanent 
 spiritual attainment : it is only a low mind that 
 seeks the material advantages by themselves.^ 
 
 IV. 
 
 As we foresaw, the practical solution of the ques- 
 tion What is the highest good ? has to be attained 
 by taking a concrete example. Though not expli- 
 citly stated, Gassendi clearly holds the opinion that 
 you know the good man when you see him. In 
 the chapter headed ' solum sapientem virtutem 
 moralem amplecti,' we have an analysis of the good 
 life from which we may learn the nature of the 
 highest good. This life is ' maxime naturalem, 
 maxime obtentu facilem, maxime durabilem, maxime 
 poenitentiae expertem.' It is based on tranquillitas 
 animi, which is not a state of death, but of sus- 
 tained equilibrium : ^ in it all desires are regulated 
 
 1 With this idea of the plebeian mind seeking praeter lucrum 
 nihil there is a close parallel in Ruskin, Crown of Wild Olive, § 32 : 
 ' In every nation there are a vast class who are ill-educated, cowardly, 
 and more or less stupid. And with these people just as certainly 
 the fee is first and the work second, as with brave people the work 
 is first and the fee second.' 
 
 "^ ' non voluit Epicurus tranquillitatem esse quasi merum toi^porem, 
 sed voluit potius esse statum in quo omnes vitae actiones placide 
 simul et jucunde peragerentur ' (ii. 716).
 
 III.] ETHICS 193 
 
 and co-ordinated : its end is final, an end in itself, 
 not creating a condition which is self-destructive, 
 but a persistent state. The good man will prefer 
 the contemplative life, but not in such a way as to 
 prevent him from sharing in the activities required 
 of a citizen. In short, the ideal is the familiar 
 wise man of the Stoics ; but there are certain modi- 
 fications which detract somewhat from the sternness 
 of that ideal. To suffer pain bravely is good ; to 
 escape suffering is better : goods of mind are most 
 excellent, but goods of body may be added. The 
 key of happiness is temperance, and the motto of 
 life should be parvo contentus. This is the tone of 
 an uncertain age, adopting in its anxiety the lesser 
 evil. It suited the unstable conditions of life that 
 inspired Stoicism : it appeals to men still, and 
 cannot lose its charm so long as fortune remains 
 fickle and life is a waiting for death. Yet would 
 not wealth be happiness if secure ? is it not better 
 to live on a higher level, having more and spending 
 more? The Roman Empire gave birth to a sick 
 man's ideal : the sage was to want little because 
 little was to be had, as the dyspeptic^ puts away 
 his desire for the full meal of the healthy : of 
 mental pleasures he might take his fill, for the hand 
 of the tyrant could not rob him of his store, but 
 the goods of this world he was to despise, for they 
 were insecure. 
 
 The conception of life which comes down to us 
 from Epicurus is one of extreme simplicity. It is 
 easy, we are told, to get what is necessary, nud 
 
 ^ This is meant purely metaphorically : it has however been sug- 
 gested that Epicurus' mode of life was a 'dietetic e.xperinient.' 
 
 N
 
 194 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 therefore life according to nature is always possible. 
 A quotation from Porphyry^ shows how little there 
 was of ' Epicureanism ' about Epicurus. Gassendi 
 accepts the natural life of Epicurus as the model : 
 he is content to prove that his teacher meant by 
 pleasure something more than self-indulgence, some- 
 thing lofty, spiritual, and in the highest sense 
 moral. This is good as an apology ; but if we are 
 to accept Gassendi as an independent teacher, it 
 seems impossible to avoid condemning his position 
 as weak. Mere transference of an ideal from one 
 age to another must necessarily be weak and 
 shallow : it implies an abstract attitude of mind 
 refusing to face the new conditions and new problems 
 that time unfolds : in spite of those elements of life 
 that are always with us, and those truths which 
 have been uttered once for all, such antiquarian lore 
 as fills the pages of Gassendi can only be dis- 
 appointing to a mind that looks for a theory in 
 touch at least with its own age, if not of value to 
 later generations. 
 
 In one respect perhaps this hardly does Gassendi 
 justice. His Insistence on the point that Pleasure 
 is not opposed to virtue, that we may be both 
 good and happy, was not merely the formal state- 
 ment of the Epicurean as opposed to the Stoic 
 ideal. Asceticism was still an ideal, and in general 
 men were impressed with the idea that the phrase, 
 'virtue for its own sake,' had a meaning. What 
 it had come to mean was that virtue was best by 
 itself, best if you mixed it with nothing, best if 
 taken in abstraction from the world and all that is 
 
 III. 729-730.
 
 III.] ETHICS 195 
 
 worldl}^ Against this Gassendi preaches the right 
 of all things in life to their due recognition ; he 
 would have said, with much the same shade of 
 meaning, that it was ' better to be worldly than 
 other-worldly.' Gassendi's biography shows that he 
 drifted away from the Church : it was the Church 
 that had divorced virtue and the best life.
 
 CHAPTER II 
 
 THE VIRTUES 
 
 The treatment of the special virtues, though con- 
 taining much that is too trite to need recording 
 again, adds a few points that are necessary to 
 complete our view of the Ethics. 
 
 The word ' virtue ' is not to be taken to denote 
 manliness, as its derivation might suggest, or a 
 specific function, such as is meant in phrases like 
 ' virtus equi.' By virtue is meant a habit of the 
 mind by which we are rightly disposed toward our 
 affections. It would have been more accurate to 
 have said organism instead of mind, and it is clearly 
 necessary to take animus here in a sense that in- 
 cludes reference to the bodily conditions. A habit 
 or condition must not be confounded either with a 
 faculty or an affection, says Gassendi, with obvious 
 reference to Aristotle. 
 
 The animus has two parts, and each has its virtue. 
 A right disposition of the intellectual part enables 
 it to attain truth when affected by the objects that 
 appeal to the senses : similarly a right disposition 
 of the non-intellectual part enables it to attain truth 
 in action, or goodness when affected by anything 
 that appeals to the passions. It is possible to regard
 
 VT. III.] ETHICS 197 
 
 this second part abstractly and divorce it trom the 
 intellect. We then have such habits and possi- 
 bilities of right action as are shared by the brutes, 
 but not completely moral action. To constitute 
 virtue a right habit must be so based on a right 
 mental state as to be constant and intentional. This 
 doctrine therefore recognises that goodness is possible 
 where there is only a low degree of intellect or none 
 at all. At the same time the degree of morality 
 must be judged relatively to the degree of intellectual 
 power possessed by the agent. As Gassendi does not 
 discuss the question of merit it is not easy to deter- 
 mine the significance of this point. The statement 
 that virtue requires knowledge may have either of 
 two meanings : it may imply that the agent must 
 be conscious of the end aimed at, that is consciously 
 adopt a course as good for him : it may also imply 
 that the agent must know how the end he adopts 
 is related to other ends, and ultimately to the universe 
 of ends. It is in the second sense that Gassendi 
 seems to use the phrase, but only with the intention 
 of dividing the ethical from natural virtues or the 
 ' nativam in Appetitu aptitudinem ad virtutem.' 
 Consciousness of the end adopted is naturally con- 
 nected with the subject of merit, because it is not 
 infrequently assumed that goodness is proportionate 
 to the difficulty of choice, or briefly, the greater the 
 strusforle the better the man. We are therefore left 
 in twofold darkness when neither merit nor the need 
 of conscious choice is fully treated. Some further 
 light may be got from the following discussion of 
 the mean. The Stoics considered the mean was a 
 pollution of virtue, a compromise between extremes
 
 198 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 of vice, and in itself nothing. Gassendi replying 
 in support of the doctrine, emphasises the distinction 
 between qualitative and quantitative means. In 
 Ethics we have to deal with qualitative distinctions, 
 and our mean is in se quid, not a vanishing point 
 between extremes but an extreme itself This decision 
 enables our author to deal very sensibly with another 
 question. As the extreme states are due to excess 
 of passion, ethical theory had tended to associate 
 with the mean state the absence of all passion. The 
 Stoics, considering that the passions were in the 
 rational part of the soul, saw no way short of com- 
 plete eradication. Epicurus, on the other hand, 
 declared the principal part of the soul to be free 
 from passion. This puts the passions in the position 
 of matter, upon which the moral agent may work 
 and makes possible their permanent retention. The 
 wise man of the Stoics was to be devoid of passion : 
 the ideal of Epicurus found room for pity and anger, 
 tears and sighs. There is however nothing which 
 could lead us to suppose that Gassendi or his teachers 
 attained to the idea of passions as natural forces 
 which could be employed for good : they are by 
 nature bad, without reference to the objects con- 
 cerned : consequently the only choice is between 
 extermination and limitation. The former leaves us 
 with a purely intellectual state, and if this is not 
 satisfactory we must take the second, admitting that 
 an immoral affection is moral if sufficiently limited. 
 But this is exactly what Gassendi repudiates as a 
 Stoic heresy when put in the form ' virtue is a mean 
 between vices,' or a mean vice. He points out that 
 a curve ) passing into ( is not a curve at all at the
 
 III.] ETHICS 109 
 
 mean point [) | (]; and so with our vices, of whicli 
 however he gives no example. The fallacy of the 
 position seems to lie in the failure to distinguish the 
 passion from its object, and so, for example, make 
 room for righteous indignation beside bad tem])er, 
 or the sorrow of the afflicted beside the self-abandon- 
 ment of suicide. 
 
 One satisfaction remains : our ethic will at least 
 deal with human nature and leave us our natural 
 material. More than that, it will assert the unity 
 of virtues, on the very sound principle that if we 
 deny the unity we make virtuous acts and not 
 virtuous natures the ground of our judgment. What 
 has been said already on the necessity of virtue 
 being a habit helps us out here. We are not good 
 for the sake of being good : the pure love of virtue 
 is nonsense : we are good to be happy. As all virtue 
 tends to happiness the virtues satisfy the scholastic 
 condition and are one both in origin and end, arising 
 from Prudence and ending in happiness. The sceptic 
 sneers at the suggestion that virtue always makes 
 for happiness, and it can hardly be reckoned among 
 the propositions proved by Gassendi. There is none 
 the less much truth in the corollary that the good 
 nian finds happiness in virtue : if he does not, the 
 virtue must somehow be foreign to his nature : 
 fear of the law must be coercing him or even a 
 guilty fear of God ; and this is not that state of 
 tranquillity which is the crown of the man whose 
 good actions flow from the right disposition of his 
 soul and body. 
 
 The special virtues are divided into four classes — 
 Prudence, Temperance, Fortitude, and Justice. In
 
 200 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 addition to these main heads there are other sub- 
 divisions which are differently enumerated by different 
 writers. Aristotle himself speaks of several virtues 
 not named in this first general division. The scho- 
 lastics desired to elaborate such general heads as 
 would include all the nameable virtues, and finally 
 produced the following scheme. First, there are the 
 three parts called Subjectae, seu species : ' deinde 
 Integrantes, seu quas instar partium totum integrum 
 compouentium, necesse est concurrere ad actum per- 
 fectum cuiuspiam virtutis : denique Potentialeis seu 
 quae potentiarum ipsius animae instar sunt virtutes 
 quasi adjunctae.' These divisions may be exemplified 
 by quoting the actual subdivisions of our main 
 classes. ' Sic parteis Prudentiae Subjectas distinguunt 
 Privatam Oeconomicam Politicam Militarem Regiam : 
 integranteis Memoriam Intellegentiam Docilitatem 
 Solertiam Rationem Providentiam Circumspectionem 
 Cautionem: Potentialeis . . . Eubuliam, Synesin, 
 Gnomen.' 
 
 The other virtues can be similarly divided, and the 
 result is a list which the scholastics at least thought 
 exhaustive of all the known virtues. 
 
 The first and greatest of the virtues is Prudence. 
 This, as we have seen, is of five kinds — privata^ 
 oeconomica, politica, regia, and militaria. Gassendi 
 deals with it under these heads. He begins w^ith 
 this virtue because it is, as Epicurus said, ' caput ac 
 fontem, sic quasi Reginam atque Principem caeter- 
 arum virtu tum.' We deal here with Prudence ' qua- 
 tenus est moralis virtus, quae omnes vitae actiones 
 recte moderatur,'and enables us to rightly distinguish 
 good and evil : it has been well defined by Cicero
 
 III.] ETHICS 201 
 
 as ' rerum expetendarum scientiam ' : it is a habit of 
 mind ' non certus (not, that is to say, concerned with 
 necessary and immutable truths) sed conjecturalis ' : 
 it is finally * ars vitae,' and the essential quality of 
 the practical man who does not concern himself with 
 the end, but accepting the end without question 
 devotes his energies to the elaboration of means. 
 The three great functions of Prudence are bene con- 
 sultare, intelligere, and finally imperare. The mental 
 qualities required are sollertia, sagacitas, and all 
 that makes for clear and prompt judgments on 
 afiairs. 
 
 We need hardly follow Gassendi through all the 
 ramifications of the subject : in justice to him be 
 it said that he seems to have omitted nothing that 
 the good moralist and the conscientious preacher 
 ought to say. He conducts through all the aspects 
 of life, including the choice of a profession, the choice 
 of a wife, the duties of man as father, landowner, 
 master of servants, and, in the wider sphere of the 
 State, controller of war and peace. It has been said 
 that in these pages Gassendi shows himself as 
 judicious in his Ethics as he is profound in his 
 metaphysics ; and this we need not deny, though 
 the subject is less abstruse, in fact somewhat common- 
 place, and the treatment even more laborious, with 
 very little that cannot be culled or deduced from 
 Aristotle, 
 
 An interesting discussion arises on the meaning 
 to be attributed to the phrase, 'follow nature.' 
 Epicurus had advocated this course. Gassendi takes 
 it to mean ' study your aptitudes ' : choose the course 
 of life that is most suited to your tastes. Whether
 
 202 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 the doctrine of motion is the implicit ground for 
 this doctrine or not I cannot say, as Gassendi gives 
 us no hint; but it would be very natural for a 
 philosopher imbued with ideas of force and motion 
 to adopt the idea of ' the line of least resistance.' 
 That this is the actual point of view cannot be 
 doubted. Every man has particular aptitudes : what 
 then is more natural or better than that he should 
 choose that mode of life which is calculated to 
 employ and improve those aptitudes rather than 
 limit or destroy them ? If we attempt tasks for 
 which nature has not designed us we make life an 
 uphill struggle, and labour perpetually ' Sisyphi 
 instar nixandi.' This seems a sensible point of view, 
 but Lactantius did not agree with it, and made it 
 a subject for censure. Epicurus, he said, aimed at 
 popularity, and made base concessions to the frailty 
 of human nature. As he states the opposite argu- 
 ment very fully the passage may be quoted at length : 
 ' Propterea ut ad se multitudinem contrahat (Epi- 
 curus), apposita singulis quibusque moribus loquitur. 
 Desidiosum vetat litteras discere : avarum populari 
 largitione liberat : ignavum prohibet accedere ad 
 rempublicam, pigrum exerceri, timidum militare. 
 Irreligiosus audit deos nihil curare, inhumanus 
 et suis commodis serviens jubetur nihil cuiquam 
 tribuere: omnia enim sui causa facere saj)ientem.' 
 In these and other respects Lactantius thinks that 
 vice is encouraged : if you hate your wife it follows 
 you should leave her : if children dislike their parents 
 it is right to rebel against them ; in short, life should 
 be made easy, and private inclinations indulged at 
 any cost. Gassendi's answer to this is that it is an
 
 Ill] ETHICS 208 
 
 extreme and unfair interpretation. It was probably 
 very typical of the treatment which Epicurean 
 philosophy received at the hands of extreme church- 
 men. To take one point in illustration. According 
 to Lactantius, Epicurus says if a man is lazy he need 
 not take exercise : according to Gassendi the doctrine 
 is, if nature has not intended you to be an athlete 
 do not try to become one. In other words, while 
 every one may know something about everything, we 
 must each of us choose some one thing in which we 
 aim to excel, and the economy of the universe 
 demands that the occupation chosen should be in 
 harmony with our nature. In this argument Gassendi 
 was on the winnino; side. 
 
 The second virtue is Courage, sometimes rather 
 unnecessarily labelled Fortitude, which is ' quandam 
 animi fortitudinem,' a fixed mental state rather than 
 brute force (in ipso robore et viribus corporis). It 
 differs from Temeritas and Feritas (ilia vocata 
 Aristoteli) in being a fixed disposition of mind, 
 and requiring for its highest realisation a clear 
 knowledge of the danger which is faced. In reality 
 the virtue is not primarily concerned with dangers 
 in the ordinary sense of the term : its permanent 
 function is the maintenance of a conviction once 
 it has been accepted, and the persistence which 
 endures and overcomes all difficulties in attaining 
 an ideal. It combines therefore in itself Constantia 
 et Persevcrantia, and its end may be expressed 
 generally as the maintenance of Justice : it is the 
 spirit which neither does nor suffers wrong. As a 
 fixed habit it enables us to endure all evils : these 
 may be public or priv9,te : the greatest is exile, but
 
 ^ 
 
 204 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [PT. 
 
 there are many others, such as infamy, imprisonment, 
 and the loss of friends or wealth/ 
 
 Temperance, the third virtue, is to be taken in 
 the Greek sense. It includes as partes subjectae 
 abstinentia et sobrietas (illam respectu cibi, hanc 
 respectu potus, says Gassendi, without telling us 
 why abstinence as such should differ for food and 
 for drink !) : as castitas et pudicitia : as integrantes, 
 verecundia et honestas : as Potentialeis, dementia, 
 humilitas, modestia itemque mansuetudo, miseri- 
 cordia, moderatio, decus, studiositas, eutrapelia seu 
 festivitas, urbanitas. This list certainly does not 
 seem to fail in respect of comprehensiveness. 
 
 Justice, the third virtue, is not subjected to 
 analysis under these standard heads. After remarks 
 based on Aristotle's discussion of this subject, we 
 come to the question of the origin of laws. Epicurus 
 had found the origin of laws in utility (Epicurus 
 omnem juris et aequi originem ab utilitate repetiit), 
 and had consequently been attacked by the sup- 
 porters of the opposite theory that laws are of 
 natural origin. Gassendi thinks the two theories 
 should be combined if we are to attain the truth. 
 Man may be regarded either absolutely as ' solitarius ' 
 or in his relations as ' sociabilis.' Man as ' solitarius ' 
 finds himself in a world filled with the gifts of 
 nature, and his instincts lead him to appropriate 
 them. In addition to these instincts he has the 
 faculty of self-preservation, with the implied right 
 to retain all that is necessary for this preservation : 
 here then is the root of the 'jus naturale ' (facultas 
 ista est in qua videtur dici posse consistere jus naturae 
 
 In. 770,
 
 III.] ETHICS 205 
 
 primarium). But the things so appropriated were 
 originally given by nature, and therefore the question 
 arises why should one man have them more than 
 another and ' inde enascantur rixae, rapinae, odia, 
 vulnera, caedes ' ? These somewhat violent relations 
 bring us to the second stage : quamobrem spectandus 
 iam homo posteriore modo, sive quatenus sociabilis 
 est, ac in naturae quasi modificatae statu : man 
 recognises the need of mutual help, and a condition 
 of harmony is brought about by the aid of laws. 
 Thus nature and utility as principles are reconciled : 
 G-assendi further recognises that the view of man 
 as solitarius is not only abstract, but also a pseudo- 
 historical process of accounting for the evolution of 
 laws which has little probability : so far as we can 
 say, society is as old as man, and that too not in 
 the sense in which we speak of brutes as sociable, 
 but in the full sense of a community of intelligent 
 human beings.^ 
 
 The root then of all law is the natural impulse 
 which drives men to form societies : for as soon as 
 we get beyond the individual as ' solitarius,' we find 
 that life is impossible without mutual agreement or 
 'pactiones.' These first charters are between man 
 and man, not contracts by which they surrender their 
 liberty to one ruler, but formal definitions of mutual 
 relations. Gassendi is not concerned to construct a 
 
 ^ II. 795. ' Itaque quicquid sit de ilia sen suppositione sen fictione 
 status, in quo seu Epicurus seu alii vixisse ali([uando dicunt primos 
 homines, tam esse profecto videtur ipsa societas hoininuni, quani 
 illorum est origo antiqua : ac non eo quideni solum modo ijuo bruta 
 generis eiusdem sociabilia inter se sunt, veruin illo etiam, quo 
 quatenus sunt et intelligentes et ratione praediti, agnoscunt non posse 
 ullam inter se societatem esse securam nisi ea conventionibus pactisque 
 mutuis constabiliatur.'
 
 206 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 theory in support of the rights of kings, so that his 
 ' pactiones ' must be taken to be agreements between 
 all the individuals in any one society without as yet 
 any question of a ruler. The law is in fact the true 
 ruler, so that there is no need to deal w^ith the 
 existence of personal rulers except in so far as their 
 authority has a natural origin in the necessity of 
 delegating: the task of making the laws of a com- 
 munity to those who are its wisest and best. The 
 head of the society then is he who has been chosen 
 to make, explain, and administer the laws : his claim 
 to the position is contained entirely in his personal 
 character and ability : he rules as the embodiment 
 of law, not arbitrarily, but acting as the mouthpiece 
 of laws which are higher and greater than he, rooted 
 in the earth and reaching to the heavens, the object 
 which all men worship, and in the cult of which he 
 is ordained high priest. 
 
 The jus to which we have been hitherto referring 
 is that known as jus civile, the recognition of the 
 rights possessed by the member of a civitas or society 
 as such. This we have seen was based on utility, 
 but always on a utility which is itself natural : in 
 other words, it supplies wants which are rooted 
 in the nature of man. There are however other 
 kinds of jus, such as the jus gentium and jus 
 naturale. As a rule, the jus gentium was regarded 
 as e natura, even by those who thought the jus 
 civile owed its origin to utilitas. Gassendi declares 
 that the difference between the two is purely a 
 question of numbers (discrimen ad magis et minus) : 
 in nature the two are identical, and both are grounded 
 in utility.
 
 III.] ETHICS 207 
 
 Now that we have expanded our view to include 
 all the kinds of Jus, we must discuss their relative 
 characters. The least comprehensive term is jus 
 civile, which has already been interpreted to mean 
 the rights constituted by citizenship. The term jus 
 gentium raises us to the higher level and a wider 
 outlook. It denotes the rights which men have 
 without reference to the particular society or state 
 to which they belong, the rights which they have 
 simply as men. Gassendi here becomes conscious of 
 a difficulty. The original significance of the phrase 
 jus gentium has been lost, now that humanity can 
 no longer be divided into Roman and non-Roman. 
 Consequently, jus gentium approaches very closely 
 to jus naturale, inasmuch as it indicates rights 
 which men may have apart from any definite 
 citizenship or special code. To avoid the confusion 
 which threatens us, we must go further into the 
 question of the scope of the jus naturale and the 
 limits of jus gentium.^ 
 
 Jus is a term which covers both the facultas and 
 the lex, says Gassendi : we may therefore look at it 
 from either point of view. Man possesses a jus 
 naturale in so far as he is an animal and has faculties 
 such as the faculty of feeling.^ But the term natu- 
 rale implies a jus grounded in a natura and nothing 
 more : since then the plants have a nature and 
 faculties (such as the facultas sugendi), they must 
 
 ^Voigt {Jus. Nat. vol. ii. 661) distinguishes Jus civile, Jus gen- 
 tium, and Jus naturale as the systems which applied respectively 
 to the citizen, the freeman, and the man. In the earlier stages of 
 its recognition it was an independent international private law 
 ■which, as such, regulated intercourse between peregrins, or between 
 peregrins and citizens, on the basis of their common libertas.
 
 208 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 have a jus naturale. To exactly define what is 
 usually included under jus naturale, we really 
 require a term 'jus animale' — or better still, 'jus 
 humanum.' 
 
 I find it difficult to determine the exact meaning 
 which Gassendi attaches to the phrase, 'jus is either 
 facultas or lex.' It seems most probable that he 
 thought of rights as primarily powers, the possession 
 of which constituted the individual's 'right' to the 
 advantages derived from their free exercise. These 
 rights become more extensive as we rise in the 
 scale of being : the plant has the least, the 
 savage man has more, the civilised man most. 
 We therefore rise from jus naturale to jus civile : 
 at the same time the lower species are most com- 
 prehensive, and therefore the jus naturale appears 
 more fundamental in proportion as it is more 
 universal. This however is only in appearance : the 
 jus naturale, though applied over a wider area, is in 
 itself more limited than the jus civile : it is man as 
 bare man that comes under its categories : as citizen 
 man enjoys laws which, if they are more limiting, 
 are also refined to far greater exactness. The facul- 
 tas which constitutes jus must be taken to be a 
 natural or social endowment which fits a being for 
 certain acts, and as it implies that nature intended 
 him to fulfil those functions for which he is thus 
 equipped, it also confers upon him a right to the 
 free use of those powers in the interests of the 
 universe at large. The plant has the power of 
 absorbing water, and so has a right to a supply of 
 water : the animal has a power of feeling and motion 
 entitling him to humane treatment and freedom.
 
 III.] ETHICS 209 
 
 Man as man has the distinctively human faculties, 
 and with them the privileges of the jus humanum, 
 while the citizen has the quality of civitas, wliich 
 is his claim to the highest privileges of life. Thus 
 we see that rio-hts are o;rounded in natures, and the 
 nature of the subject determines the character and 
 limits of the rights. The nature of a being is there- 
 fore best realised under laws that establish these 
 rights. At first the law seems a limitation of the 
 nature, but a little reflection shows a different side 
 to the question : if my desire to harm you is re- 
 strained, your freedom is enlarged : if I am not 
 allowed to take away your wife, at least I may 
 expect to possess my own in safety. So while the 
 established law hedges me round about, it also pro- 
 vides a barrier against hostile irruptions. 
 
 We now see that the jus gentium can be defined 
 by reference to its content. If we look for specifi- 
 cally human activities we find them in the faculties 
 of speech, writing, reasoning, forming societies, and 
 the like. These as common to all men, but not 
 shared by man with the brutes, must constitute the 
 sphere of the jus gentium. 
 
 The term lex, as opposed to jus, implies a definite 
 contract and an executive power to enforce obedi- 
 ence. There is therefore no lex gentium nor lex 
 naturale in the proper sense. There may be such 
 universal laws as the lex spontanea^ or law of 
 
 1 Ulpian speaks of a jus naturale common to man and lower animals, 
 which is substantially instinct. This is said to be a law of nature 
 not referred to by any other jurist. The idea of jus naturale was not 
 peculiar to Ulpian. Gaius and Justinian equate Jus naturale and 
 jus gentium ; but while the jus gentium is more natural than the 
 civile, it is far from identical with the naturale. The jus naturale is 
 
 O
 
 210 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. 
 
 instinctive action : there may also be a law of rational 
 action ; but this is law in a different sense, the 
 hypothetical precept which dictates the means for 
 fulfilling some particular purpose. Though these 
 are not laws in the full sense of the term, they 
 stand very close to law in the highest and noblest 
 use of the word. Man has reason : he can therefore 
 see and understand the laws of his nature in a way 
 that animals cannot : he can identify himself with 
 this law so that the law of nature becomes his 
 law, the law of his reason, and finally one with his 
 reason. 
 
 Now, taking lex naturalis as the law of human 
 nature and analysing it, we get the elements of 
 law in its ethical aspect, the elements that is to 
 say of the laws which are embedded in human 
 nature. In order to ensure our attaining the original 
 simple laws we must aim at two qualities, univer- 
 sality and freedom from prejudice ; in other words, 
 we must collect our evidence from a sufficiently 
 wide area and at the same time not allow any pre- 
 conceived ideas to bias our choice : we then get 
 the following rules of conduct : 
 
 1. The first law instructs us to aim always at 
 the good, which is to be interpreted as our own 
 
 essentially a speculative element. Its most noticeable features are : 
 '(1) its potential imiversal applicability to all men ; (2) among all 
 peoples ; (3) at all times ; and (4) its correspondence with the innate 
 conviction of right.' It included among its propositions (1) recogni- 
 tions of claims of blood ; (2) duty and faithfulness to engagements ; 
 (3) apportionment according to equity ; (4) voluntatis ratio. (For 
 these facts see Voigt, quoted in the Encycl. Brit., loc. cit.) It will 
 be obvious from these notes on the character of the jus naturale 
 that it was eminently fitted for becoming the basis of a universal 
 ethic.
 
 III.] ETHICS 211 
 
 good or advantage (primo itaque communissimum, 
 innatumque adeo est omnibus hominibus, ut quod 
 bonum, quod commodum, quod gratum fuerit, pro- 
 sequantur : quod vero malum, incommodum, ingra- 
 tumque refugiaut). The collateral use of the terms 
 denoting goodness and pleasantness should be 
 noticed : we shall have occasion to refer to them 
 later. It follows from this law that we are to love 
 our benefactors and hate our enemies : from this is 
 derived love of our children, our friends, and God, 
 as the greatest of benefactors. Gassendi apparently 
 assumes that all men will regard God as a benefactor : 
 the necessit}^ of worshipping him rests really on the 
 attitude adopted by the individual, but Gassendi 
 does not flice the problem of those who prefer to 
 'curse God and die.' 
 
 2. The second law is simple, * ut quisque se amet, 
 plusquam ceteros, seu ut sibi bene quam alteri malit.' 
 Some writers whom Gassendi contemptuously calls 
 ' popular ' have denied this law, but it is regarded 
 by our author as indisputably natural and original. 
 Thus Egoism is the point from which we must start : 
 we love ourselves best and with ourselves all that 
 is peculiarly ours : we benefit our own families before 
 those of others, and, as the proverb rightly says, 
 begin our charity at home ! From this egoism, if 
 so simple and sensible a doctrine can be called by 
 that highly technical term, a mild and inofieusive 
 altruism is naturally derived : in brief, Gassendi says 
 that if you have time and opportunity there is no 
 harm in doing good to another, provided it entails 
 no loss to yourself. For example, it is only nice 
 and kind to put the lost traveller on the right road,
 
 212 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 if otherwise convenient ; and from this comes profit, 
 for the deed has its reward in that most inestimable 
 sense of self-satisfaction (conscientia benefacti in- 
 estimabilis). 
 
 3. The third law is love of life, from which comes 
 the impulse to marry, beget children, and rear them 
 with all the advantages, such as education, which 
 one desires for oneself. 
 
 4. The fourth law is the love of society which has 
 its root and beginning in the union of the sexes. It 
 is not unnatural for a man to love the common good, 
 for he considers that his own is bound up in it. The 
 concluding remarks are of particular interest, and to 
 ensure their correct understanding I shall quote the 
 essential passages. As Gassendi does not divorce 
 the state and the individual, he does not raise the 
 question as to how an individual, intent on his own 
 good, ever gets to the point of considering the good 
 of others. From the first the concrete individual 
 is sociable, and therefore thinks of the public good 
 as only another aspect of his own, as that in which 
 his own is contained (quo intelligit contineri suum). 
 The end of society is not realised unless the indi- 
 viduals enter into it in this whole-hearted way and 
 take it up into their very natures. They must 
 realise the reciprocity which society implies and 
 which has been expressed in the fundamental law 
 'quod tibi fieri non vis, alteri ne feceris.' (I do 
 not know if Gassendi preferred the negative form 
 for any particular reason.) ^ In addition to this the 
 
 ^Merito vero quasi prima secundum naturam habetur lex ilia, 
 quod tibi fieri non vult, alteri ne fecei'is : quippe ea omneis leges 
 societatis sic continet ut nemo violet alienum jus, nisi quia legem
 
 Ill] ETHICS 213 
 
 citizen must not only abide by the law but also be 
 a law-abiding creature, he must not only do good 
 but also he good, as Leslie Stephen has put it. The 
 ideal condition is reached when no laws are required 
 but all are just by nature. 
 
 On these concluding remarks made by Gassendi, 
 Thomas ^ comments thus : ' Gassendi va meme plus 
 loin et ici sa doctrine s'dcarte de plus en plus de 
 celle d'Epicure : Ajoutons-nous, dit-il, que les saints 
 Ecritures ont excellemment dit que ce n'est pas au 
 juste que la loi est impos^e : parce que celui qui est 
 veritablement juste ne 1' observe pas par la crainte 
 des peines que les lois ordonnent, mais pour I'amour 
 meme de la justice et pour la veneration qu'il a 
 pour elle, de fa§on que quand il n'y aurait ni lois, 
 ni magistrats, il I'observerait toujours de meme.' 
 ' On s'explique mal en lisant ces textes les accusations 
 severes qu'on a si souvent port^es contre la morale 
 de Gassendi.' He adds in a note, ' Cette regie de 
 Gassendi ne nous fait- elle pas songer a celle de 
 Kant et aux commentaires qui I'accompagnent ? 
 "Agis toujours," nous dit Kant, " de telle sort que 
 la maxim de ton action puisse etre ^rigee en loi 
 universelle." ' 
 
 banc violat. . . . Manifestum quoque est finem societatis esse in eo, 
 ut cuique suo jure frui, absque impedimento liceat : . . . debet in 
 illis constans et perpetua voluntas tribuendi (hoc est conservandi 
 atque reponendi) suum cuique jus, reperiii : idee residere in ipsis 
 Publicam, communemve justitiam quasi tutricem ac vindicem juris 
 cuiusque singularis. If this is fully realised it follows supervacaneam ,i f 
 publicam illani fore. . . . Finally, vir vere Justus non ob intentas ^^ 
 a legibus poenas, quas exacturus niagistratus sit, sed ipsiusniet 
 Justitiae aniore reverentiaque colit, et legibus etiam niagistratibus(iue 
 sublatis prorsus culturus est. 
 
 ^Op. cit. 'ill. 
 
 I.
 
 214 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 On these comments I wish to make a few remarks 
 in order to further elucidate the view I take of 
 Gassendi's position and show why I cannot agree 
 with the suggestion that this is Kantian. Nothing 
 is easier than to lay hold of the suggestive phrases 
 so often found in Gassendi and make them appear 
 to anticipate some later doctrines. I do not mean 
 to suggest that this is a vice to which Thomas is 
 addicted : on the contrary, he often appears to me 
 to have stinted rather than amplified his author's 
 meaning ; but this is exactly the sort of point in 
 which two readers of the same book arrive at diffe- 
 rent conclusions through holding different opinions 
 on the way the subject should be studied : it is 
 thus an excellent opportunity of showing how and 
 why I venture to difier from my predecessor in the 
 task of expounding Gassendi. 
 
 The scope of Gassendi's ethic is defined by the 
 phrase an ethic of prudence : however far Gassendi 
 travels from that simple statement he never pretends 
 to rise above the sphere thus indicated. The very 
 laws given in detail show how Gassendi's good man 
 is far more concerned with a concrete immediate 
 welfare than is Kant's. 
 
 I have not avoided speaking of hypothetical and 
 categorical phases of the law ; but the transition 
 from one to the other can be expressed thus : the 
 hypothetical law of reason says, ' if you will to 
 attain this, you must act thus ' : the categorical 
 says, ' if you are what you are, you must act 
 thus ' ; but the former half of the sentence is 
 meaningless and can be omitted, leaving the simple 
 law, 'act thus.' But the being- what-you-are means
 
 III.] ETHICS 216 
 
 being a social creature and implies no trans- 
 cendental Self, nor even that semi-transcendental 
 ' dignity of man ' by which Mill so nearly arrived 
 at Kant's position. On the contrary, it is pure 
 common-sense, as though one should say ' being 
 man and not angel, you must walk to get there': 
 for the ' must ' refers to the means and not the 
 end which is given to all, namely Pleasure. 
 
 Again, Gassendi's law is formed by abstracting all 
 special conditions : it is in that sense a universal 
 law belonging to universal man ; but it is empirical 
 and objective, a solution of the problem of co-exist- 
 ence, not transcendental or subjective, or one that 
 must be obeyed ' though the heavens fall.' It is 
 true Gassendi says, * put yourself in his place ' and 
 ' do not do unto others what you will not have 
 done to yourself,' but that much is in the Bible, 
 and one sentence does not make a theory. Hobbes 
 had got as ftir as this without feeling the necessity 
 of going any further ; and as this element in ethics 
 has a very patent origin I prefer to judge it from 
 the point of view of its antecedents rather than 
 speculate on its relations to later theories. The 
 point to which I would draw special attention is 
 the nature of the universality implied in Gassendi's 
 words. Kant tells us the supreme principle of juris- 
 prudence is, ' act so that the free use of thy elective 
 will may not interfere with the freedom of any 
 man so far as it agrees with universal law,' and 
 this is surely what Thomas should have quoted if 
 anything was to be quoted out of Kant. This I 
 consider is exactly Gassendi's meaning, and there- 
 fore, so far from attaining the point of view which
 
 216 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 Kant would call ethical, he stops at that which Kant 
 expressly distinguishes as legal and external. 
 
 This question of the distinction of legal and ethical 
 principles is all the more interesting in view of what 
 I consider the real root of Gassendi's opinions. If 
 we say that according to Gassendi ethics is a matter 
 of relations between individuals and therefore always 
 external, the question is at once asked, ' What of the 
 clause about the pure love of justice ? ' In my opinion 
 this must be explained by reference to what the will 
 to be good meant to the lawyer ^ ? The influence 
 of philosophy, especially the Stoic, on Roman law, 
 was to make the emphasis fall on voluntas. ' The 
 desire to subordinate form to substance, the word 
 spoken to the will it was meant to manifest, the 
 abstract rule to the individual case to which it 
 was prepared to apply it' was, we are told, strong 
 in Cicero's time.^ Seeing that the pages of Gassendi 
 are full to overflowing with quotations from Cicero, 
 and the terms used not only follow a distinctly legal 
 argument, but are themselves legal, we seem justified 
 in thinking that this juridical development is the 
 source of Gassendi's inspiration, and he means no 
 more than that it is better to understand and 
 acquiesce in the natural laws of society than be 
 one of the victims of the good men, i.e. those 
 who have learned the secret of successful living. 
 Gassendi may well say *be good' as well as 'do 
 good,' since that course will bring most pleasure : 
 the idea of virtue for its own sake he has already 
 
 1 V. Encycl. Britt. vol. 20, p. 696 (tenth ed.). 
 
 ^'neque enim est cur putemus solam justitiam esse constantem 
 atque perpetuam voluntatem, ut Jurisconsulti definiunt' (vi. 113).
 
 HI.] ETHICS 217 
 
 dismissed. It would also be well if that phrase 
 were discarded by some other writers : it has the 
 appearance of making its advocate look more like 
 a saint than his fellow-men : in reality it means 
 nothing, being a stupid abstraction, as though virtue 
 could be cut off from life, and the good, the beauti- 
 ful, and the comfortable were not ideas that reacted 
 on each other. 
 
 But if we do not consider that Gassendi has 
 reached the heights of Kant, if he has most certainly 
 retained much that is ' pathological ' in his ultimate, 
 he certainly has, in the words of Lecky, ' abundantly 
 proved the possibility of uniting Epicureanism with 
 a high code of morals.' The tone throughout is that 
 of the Prudens, the man of even balance and shrewd 
 foresight, not given to useless asceticism or wasting 
 extravagances, but withal full-blooded in his righteous- 
 ness, and rejoicing in a godliness that is profitable 
 unto all things. If there is nothing of the self- 
 sacrificing strenuousness that makes Kant's ethics 
 so exacting and tense, there is a lofty humanism 
 which strikes the golden mean between the brute 
 that does not aspire and the god that does not 
 struggle.
 
 CHAPTER III 
 
 ON LIBERTY, FATE, AND DIVINATION 
 
 The discussion on Liberty, Fate, and Divination 
 forms a metaphysic of Etliic in so far as Gassendi 
 recognises tlie necessity of supplying an argument 
 for the possibility of morality. Ethically, freedom 
 must be taken to mean responsibility on which 
 depend praise and blame. The common phrase 
 refers freedom to the will ; but the will follows the 
 judgment, and it is therefore more accurate to refer 
 freedom to the reason. The real crisis of choice as 
 a psychological act comes when we have the alter- 
 natives before us, and then it is upon the attention 
 that the strain falls : we feel that strain and recog- 
 nise that the eflbrt thus made seals the action as 
 ours. 
 
 We must admit then a ratio libera in the sense 
 of a power to choose under given circumstances one 
 out of the many possibilities. The further question 
 as to whether we should have preferred other circum- 
 stances and other alternatives is postponed. The 
 essence of liberty is indifference : some have said 
 complete determination is the highest freedom ; but 
 this Gassendi calls spontaneity or actio e natura, 
 such as is exemplified in cases of gravitation. There
 
 PT. III.] ETHICS 219 
 
 is however a correct use of the term referriiifr not 
 to natura ipsa but natura informata, the * second 
 nature.' If the will for the good is such that evil 
 is not possible we may say voluntas sponte agit. 
 As freedom has been assigned to ratio rather than 
 voluntas the use of voluntas here should be noticed. 
 The spontaneity of will is a formed habit which has 
 reference only to some limited sphere : it leaves the 
 reason unfettered, and the whole man is not com- 
 pletely determined. If we extend spontaneity so as 
 to make all action so completely determined that 
 only one course is possible, we get the concept of 
 the Beatus Homo, who, like Aristotle's perfect man, 
 is not on the moral scale at all. Freedom to l)e 
 intelligible at all must be confined to the region of 
 those that struggle and can err. 
 
 Gassendi uses ' indifference ' in two senses. When 
 we used it above, it meant freedom from prior deter- 
 mination or from a bias. We may take the example 
 of the balance : the scales must be equal in weight 
 themselves if they are to act truly : they must be 
 'indifferent' before receiving any weights. They may 
 become ' indifferent ' again, namely when equally 
 w^eighted. So the will may be indifferent when the 
 reason has equal arguments on both sides. Here 
 then the will is indifferent not to but ivitJi the 
 arguments, and the indifference belongs properly to 
 the reason. Apparently wdll is to be regarded as 
 suffused by intellect, not intellect by will ; and as 
 we are told that Practical Reason and Appetite are 
 as inseparable as body and shadow, we seem com- 
 mitted to an intellectualism which entirely overlooks 
 the irrational elements in human conduct. Here as
 
 220 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 everywhere we find the concept of the man who 
 deliberately chooses evil has not yet made a place 
 for itself : consequently an ethical theory never gets 
 a broader view than that which an analysis of the 
 typical good man can give. In accordance with this 
 we get the feeble compromises common to all philo- 
 sophy of this type : evil is chosen only sub specie 
 boni : the will is moved by the veri species which 
 may be germana or fucata. It is interesting to note 
 that Gassendi seems to throw the blame for wrong 
 judgments not on the mind but on the species. 
 Human experience goes astray, but there is a lumen 
 supernaturale, and knowledge of absolute good is 
 absolute knowledge, which falls outside our sphere. 
 
 Having thus defined the nature and sphere of 
 liberty and so dismissed some errors which were 
 really due to illegitimate use of the term, we may 
 revert to an ulterior question raised above. I may 
 be free to choose whether I shall stay on the burning 
 ship or be thrown overboard, but what if I say I did 
 not choose the situation, and therefore my freedom 
 is a mockery ? That question raises the general 
 problem as to whether all things are not determined 
 from the beginning of creation, my circumstances 
 and my choice among them : whether, in short, 
 physical causation has not already swallowed up 
 liberty. This universal causation is called Fate or 
 Fortune, and these terms must now be discussed. 
 
 The question whether liberty is not precluded by 
 causation takes two forms according as the causation 
 is purely physical or regarded as divine : according, 
 that is, as we make it a question of Fate or pre- 
 destination. The former is the tenet of the atomic
 
 Ill] ETHICS 221 
 
 school, as we have ah'cady seen, and Gassendi's reply 
 is identical in spirit with that which we have already 
 had from Lucretius : he relies on the immediate testi- 
 mony of the moment of conscious choice :^ whether 
 this is a consciousness of freedom or only failure to 
 detect determination we are not told, but probably 
 Gassendi meant more by it than Lucretius did. We 
 have seen already that Gassendi gives us a clear and 
 accurate account of the act of choice so far as the 
 psychology is concerned ; and his idea of the differ- 
 ence between the freedom of the will and the freedom 
 of the reason justifies us in saying that he realised 
 the fact that our mental processes do not unwind 
 themselves before the reason but are definitely pre- 
 sented to and sanctioned or inhibited by the reason. 
 There is no trace of the ' declination ' theory of 
 Gassendi's predecessors, which seems to indicate that 
 Gassendi abandons entirely the attempt to make 
 freedom consist in irregularity of action, which is 
 all that the bare assumption of declination could give 
 us.^ The close union between thought and move- 
 ment which Gassendi assumes throughout saves him 
 the trouble of connecting the freedom of the will 
 with freedom of action : they are assumed to be the 
 same ; but the difficulty of resolves which never 
 result in action would have been shelved by Gassendi 
 by referring them to the reason and not the will. 
 
 The second aspect of the question is due to theo- 
 logical influences. The problem is simple, but it may 
 be doubted whether it seemed so simple in those 
 days as it does now to more rationalistic minds. 
 
 iv. p. 237. 
 
 2 II. 840. ' illi naturae lumini quo nos liberos esse exijeriiuur.'
 
 222 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 If, they said, God foresees action, liow can it be 
 free ? In order to understand the problem we must 
 connect it with the older form of the Peripatetics. 
 For the Peripatetic had already asked whether the 
 truth of the disjunctive judgment did not prove that 
 freedom was impossible. If it is true that to-morrow 
 it either rains or it does not, and the one excludes 
 the other, it follows that the weather for to-morrow 
 is fore-ordained, determined or necessary, and freedom 
 is illusion. To this the answer was easy : thought 
 does not determine existence and the necessity of 
 the disjunctive judgment is not a determination of 
 ' reality,' as then conceived.^ But if we suppose the 
 mind that judges to be the mind of the Almighty, 
 the question begins to look serious. To say that God 
 can consider two alternatives without the slightest 
 idea which will be realised is pure trifling : when the 
 Thought in question is creative, it seems as though 
 the thought of the future must be the creation of 
 the future, which therefore would only await develop- 
 ment in time. To this Gassendi's answer is that 
 as God foresees the choice so He also foresees the 
 freedom, a rather subtle turn of dialectic which 
 certainly seems calculated to throw the ordinary 
 opponent. It is to be assumed that God foresees 
 that there will be a necessity for choice, and also 
 that choice will be in accordance with the man's 
 
 ^ ' Cumque Aristoteles pi'opterea admitteret solum, ut verum, coiu- 
 plexum eiusmodi duarum disjuncti varum enunciationum, aut erit eras 
 bellum navale aut non erit : Epicurus quoque hoc solum complexum 
 admisit, ut verum, aut vivet eras Hermarchus aut non vivet : pervidit 
 enim, si alteram disjunctionum verani esse admitteret, fore ut necesse 
 esset vivere eras Hermarchum, aut necesse non vivere : "nulla autem 
 est," inquit in natura talis necessitas' (ii. 837).
 
 III.] ETHICS 223 
 
 nature : God's omniscience therefore enables him to 
 foresee what the result will be, but that result is left 
 entirely dependent on the nature of the individual 
 as a free agent. This sort of argument is none too 
 profitable, and there seems no need to pursue it 
 further. It might however be noticed that the argu- 
 ment seems to assume that there is a distinction 
 between the thought of God as knowing and as 
 creative, possibly due to the distinction in the case 
 of man between reason and will ; and also that it 
 puts indirectly but all the more effectively tlie most 
 complete bar to Pantheism that can be imagined in 
 thus severing the will of man from the will of God.
 
 CHAPTER IV 
 
 ON GOD 
 
 A WORD or two may liere be added on the nature 
 and attributes of God. We have already learnt 
 that Gassendi is in direct opposition to Epicurus 
 on this point. He treats the subject as primarily 
 a question of causality, and discusses it as the first 
 part of the subject of efficient causation. The 
 primary efficient cause is God : this is considered 
 to be proved from the character (as opposed to the 
 nature) of the world. The order of the universe 
 naturally suggests to the mind the being of some 
 Power that can regulate and control the march of 
 events. This action is not really distinct from that 
 of creation, for it was at creation that God gave 
 to matter certain determinations which it preserves.^ 
 
 ^ I. 316. ' Sed demus fuisse talem materiam seu Atomorum temere 
 volitantium infinitatera, annon difficultas est semper quomodo in 
 tanta ilia laxitate, et infinitate spatiorum tot Atomi convenerint 
 ut illico potuerint se tarn valide revincire, tarn concinne disponere, 
 absque revinciente et disponente causa 1 Nam quod aninialia quidem 
 adeo exquisite formentur, id habent ex seminibus ad certas formas 
 comparatis : Atomi vero ilia non se habuere ut semina : quatenus 
 comparata magis ad gignendum Mundum, quam ad quidvis aliud 
 non fuere.' This passage deserves particular attention, because it 
 shows how Gassendi sees that the necessity for going below 
 determinate to indeterminate matter is one with the necessity for 
 postulating a Creator : the Atom being nothing 7nai/ be everything, but 
 it need not be anything : the necessity falls outside the Atom as such.
 
 PT. III.] ETHICS 225 
 
 It is not enough, says Gassendi, to say that the 
 atoms were created, we must also allow that they 
 were created in certain kinds. In this point Gassendi 
 is really enlarging the hint given by Lucretius, who 
 had introduced the idea of atoms as ' semina rerum,' 
 which implies that certain lines of development 
 were prescribed. The common phrase that one atom 
 unites with another because it is like it, really 
 involves the same introduction of a pre-determina- 
 tion of the possible compositions of atoms. Before 
 Gassendi this argument was used to disprove the 
 necessity of a God. But here the purpose was 
 really extraneous to the argument : it was the 
 previous intention of getting rid of that watchful 
 providence which seemed to Epicurus nothing but 
 a source of fear, that dictated the conclusion. 
 Gassendi, setting out with the opposite purpose, 
 finds these arguments equally useful for the purpose 
 of establishing the being of God, and there is much 
 to be said for his view. He quotes from Lucretius 
 a passage which shows that this opponent of the gods 
 allows all the facts which he himself uses in the 
 defence of the one God. We must remember also 
 that as a believer in the Bible Gassendi would at 
 least be glad to find room for the idea of special 
 creation : in spite of the obvious connection between 
 his views and a theory of development, the times 
 were not yet ripe for any doctrine of the origin of 
 species, and it was tacitly assumed that in some 
 way or other the species found on the earth were 
 fixed and immutable. Now, the idea of semina 
 rerum supplies the required element : if we go 
 right back to the atom as purely indeterminate
 
 226 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. 
 
 it should be possible to get any combinations at 
 any time, and this was held to be opposed to the 
 laws of regular production. If we stop at the 
 semina rerum we have our actual elements given 
 with a considerable amount of determination, and 
 Gassendi seems to have been willing to go a step 
 further and say that the atoms were not created 
 at first in their isolation, but in complex masses 
 which were divisible into atomic parts. He is at 
 any rate quite clear that to begin with the atom 
 is a purely abstract and hypothetical result, which 
 could only be asserted to be in harmony with reality 
 if it solved all our problems, which it does not. 
 We are compelled to deduce from the nature of 
 the universe that there is something beside the 
 material cause, some Power which can supply the 
 elements of law and order, which moreover will 
 explain the creation of the atoms themselves. Thus 
 nature brings us to God both as creator and as rector 
 of the universe. The concession which is made to 
 science is that this does not imply perpetual interfer- 
 ence : once created with their guiding determinations 
 the world of matter is left to work out its own 
 laws. 
 
 The recognition of the reign of law, which was 
 so strongly insisted on by Lucretius, is now turned 
 against the materialist. The one thing that atoms 
 in themselves could not produce would be laws ; 
 and as law is, from the subjective point of view, 
 intelligibility, we may say that the atoms are not 
 capable of evolving an intelligible world. But the 
 intelligibility of the world is above all things that 
 which science demonstrates in the observation of
 
 III.] ETHICS 227 
 
 laws, and it is thus a means by which the nature 
 of the world as intelligible is unfolded before us. 
 But while it explains what the intelligible is, in 
 reference to its content, it does not explain how 
 the intelligibility itself came to be there ; and that 
 is where we require to supplement our science with 
 Faith and Reason. 
 
 Having thus established the a priori need for a 
 God, we turn to the question of the ways by which 
 we get our knowledge of God. The first is Faith ^ 
 and the second Reason ; but the difference between 
 these is not very great : in both the reaction of our 
 minds is the convincing point. As to faith, it is 
 the belief which arises in our minds when we hear 
 a description of God : we find that the idea has an 
 inner response which compels us to believe. The 
 effect is much the same in the case of reason : there 
 is formed within us an ' anticipatio ' as a sort of 
 residual impression produced by experience. This 
 is in a sense a priori. It is not derived from the 
 senses, but exhibited on the occasion of the sense- 
 
 * The justification of faith is somewhat over-subtle : ' jam vero 
 ista quae per sensus comprehenduntur occasiones sunt quae nos ad 
 formandum de Deo Anticipationem inducunt. Cum sit autem 
 duplex potissimum sensus, auditus scilicet et visus,' etc. (i. 292). 
 To auditus pertains the anticipatio which arises from hearing 
 about God, i.e. from authority, primarily the authority of the 
 Bible. It should be noted that this knowledge of God is an 
 intuition, like that which grasps axiomatic truths. In both cases 
 belief is due to 'seeing' (intuiting) the necessity of the conjunction 
 of ideas expressed in the words : it is therefore relative to the 
 individual's development. This argument is two-edged : for we 
 can either say ' idiots do not comprehend God,' or, ' those who do 
 not comprehend God are idiots' [ut quantumcunque aliqui hominum 
 mutili aut nascantur aut fiunt, hoc non obstat quin homines dicantur 
 habere ab ipsa natura suorum membrorum integritatem ita quantum- 
 vis aliqui aut nascantur aut fiant Athei, etc., i. 290.]
 
 228 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 impressions calling it forth. Technically we have 
 to distinguish between an ' anticipatio ' got directly 
 by comprehension, and those which are got indirectly 
 by comparison. The latter are formed on the basis 
 of sense-impressions, but are rational, requiring an 
 activity that goes beyond the senses, and constructs 
 what is never given to the senses. It is by this 
 latter faculty that we attain the idea of God, which 
 is thus a concept. If we ask whether this is innate, 
 the answer is that the faculty is innate, but its 
 exercise is dependent on the occasion furnished by 
 the senses. 
 
 As to the relation of God to man, we are told 
 that Epicurus erred in denying a special providence 
 watching over man. At the same time man is a 
 free agent, his freedom being the gift of God that 
 he may work out his own salvation,^ Religion, as 
 is natural, produces in Gassendi a cheerful optimism : 
 the good man does indeed suffer evils, and the 
 sinners seem to flourish unduly ; but the good man 
 himself acknowledges that his sufferings are profit- 
 able, and all things work together for good, which 
 is at least a tribute to the goodness of the good 
 man ; but if he was less good perhaps his opinion 
 might have been less in accord with our philosopher's 
 creed. 
 
 With regard to this theology, some have said 
 that it is no part of Gassendi's real philosophy. 
 This I think is wrong. Apart from the question of 
 
 ^ I. 331. 'Ad alia ut accedam, tametsi nos Deus sinit res nostras 
 agere : non minus idcirco illi curae sumus. Quippe qui naturS, 
 sumus liberi, idcirco nos, quae maxima ipsiua benignitas est, frui 
 patitur libertate nostra, ac nos interea procul dubio versus meliora 
 dirigit. Etenim vices parentis gerit,' etc.
 
 III.] ETHICS 229 
 
 religious training and fear of the Church, the prin- 
 ciples of Gassendi's philosophy require that the idea 
 of causality should carry us beyond the physical 
 world of things. If it be necessary to go beyond 
 at all there seems no particular objection to the 
 acceptance of theism, for pantheism is out of the 
 question. It is as a metaphysical requirement that 
 Gassendi introduces God, not as an appendix to his 
 philosophy, but right in the middle, at the heart of 
 the subject, when he is dealing with causation. The 
 idea is for his times considerably refined: it would 
 probably have been hailed at a later time as deism, 
 and unconsciously goes very near to that as it is, for 
 the world manages its own ajQfairs (vi. 155), and 
 even man is only watched from afar with paternal 
 interest and led on to his self-fulfilment indirectly; 
 but in spirit there is certainly no suggestion of such 
 a conclusion, and God is theoretically rector mundi 
 in the fullest sense of the term. The question which 
 usually proves so great a stumbling block, that of 
 personality, is not raised by Gassendi. He seems to 
 have found no difficulty in the idea of human per- 
 sonality, and consequently none in that of God ; 
 though he is careful to point out that anthropo- 
 morphism is not essential, he does not reconcile that 
 with the converse assertion he frequently makes, 
 that man is created in the likeness of God.
 
 NOTE ON DECLINATION 
 
 Gassendi discusses this point of declination very 
 fully. When I say (page 221) there is no trace of 
 it I mean that Gassendi does not build his own 
 theory on it in any way. As this ' declination ' 
 has been the subject of much dispute, it will be 
 worth while comparing Gassendi's view of it with 
 later opinions. The most important of these later 
 opinions is that of Guyau in La Morale d'Ejpicure 
 (2nd edition, Paris, 1881). The whole position taken 
 up by Guyau is criticised by Masson {The Atomic 
 Theory of Lucretius), and I shall first state that 
 position and the criticisms made by Masson : 
 
 'M. Guyau's explanation of the subject is in 
 several respects a novel one, and especially so in 
 regard to one point, viz. his account of Epicurus' 
 teaching as to Chance and the very important part 
 which M. Guyau supposes it to play in the Epi- 
 curean philosophy. According to him Epicurus 
 believed that the element of chance which we see 
 at work in the world every day is the manifestation 
 and outcome of a principle of " Spontaneity" existing 
 in Nature. This "Spontaneity" is the consequence 
 of the power of Declination possessed by the Atoms. 
 Thus Epicurus believed both Free-will in man and 
 the element of Chance in the world around him to
 
 PT. III.] ETHICS 231 
 
 be the result of the same power of Atomic Declina- 
 tion in its twofold working. Epicurus, says M. 
 Guyau, after having combated the religious idea of 
 Providence or Divine caprice, found himself con- 
 fronted with the scientific idea of necessity. Thus 
 his main philosophic aim was to escape from the 
 notion of gods interfering with nature on the one 
 hand and to steer clear of the doctrine of fate on 
 the other. It is well known that Epicurus solved 
 the difficulty in a way satisfactory to himself, by 
 assigning to the atoms the power of declination. 
 But for this power the world could never have 
 come into existence, for otherwise the atoms could 
 never have come into contact and produced the 
 earth or the life upon it. It is the same power of 
 spontaneous movement in the atoms of the soul 
 which alone originates and renders possible the 
 Free-will of man. ... It is commonly thought,' M. 
 Guyau continues, ' that Contingency, placed by Epi- 
 curus at the origin of things, existed, according to 
 him, at the origin alone, and then disappeared in 
 order again to leave room for necessity. The world 
 once made, the machine once constructed, why 
 should it not go on by itself without any need of 
 invoking any other force than Necessity ? ' (Masson, 
 pp. 210-214). 
 
 Further quotation shows that M. Guyau thinks, 
 in opposition to this common view, that Spontaneity 
 is always and everywhere active. The objection that 
 all production would then be of the nature of a 
 miracle is rebutted by saying that the idea of 
 miracles implies an agent outside the natural order ; 
 but here the agency is in the things whose sum is
 
 232 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 nature : moreover the effect produced by this spon- 
 taneity would be very slight. (Masson rightly 
 points out that this is wrong : ' the spontaneous 
 movement of a mass of matter, however slight, 
 might still be able to give the initial impulse 
 required to let loose a mighty force.') 
 
 The result of M. Guyau's position is then that 
 ' the Free-will which man possesses will exist every- 
 where in inferior degrees, but always ready to awake 
 and act. . . . The atoms which form our bodies 
 must possess a power of Free-will analogous to our 
 own, more or less extensive, more or less conscious, 
 but real.' The objections Masson makes to this, 
 apart from sundry obvious misinterpretations of 
 Lucretius,^ are that it destroys the concept of Law 
 in the universe which is so prominent a feature in 
 both Epicurus and Lucretius, and assumes, what 
 could not be proved from Epicurus, that masses of 
 matter would have the same freedom that the 
 atoms have. 
 
 The root of M. Guyau's view is his opinion that 
 'in Epicureanism there are no inconsistencies, but 
 only a few false deductions.' This cannot be allowed 
 if it means that Epicurus consciously recognised 
 both the fundamental difference of mind from matter 
 and the necessity for a final reunification. The great 
 error which it appears to me that M. Guyau has 
 committed is that he does not recognise the difference 
 of the ancient and modern methods : he looks at the 
 question himself from the standpoint of conscious- 
 ness as most important, and so inverts the position 
 
 ^ E.g. nee ratione loci for regione loci in the passage quoted, 
 p. 2.36.
 
 III.] ETHICS 233 
 
 of Epicurus. To this he was doubtless led by the 
 famous passage ^ of Lucretius. If we now quote the 
 remarks of Gassendi, we shall see how the matter 
 presented itself to one who was less biassed by 
 modern points of view, and probably far nearer the 
 truth. 
 
 ' Videtur itaque Epicurus ex eo saltem laudandus 
 quod vel auctore ipso Plutarcho, nullum non movit 
 lapidem ut libertatem arbitrii intemeratam tueretur : 
 tametsi ad versus Democritum non habuerit aliud 
 paratius effugium quam declinationem illam ato- 
 morum, dictam Plutarcho . . . rem adeo exilem, ac 
 tarn vilis pretii. Ecquonam porro modo potuit hocce 
 qualecunque commentum Libertati accomodare ? 
 Forte, quatenus cum attenderet esse in animalibus 
 et in hominibus praesertim, triplex genus motus, 
 nempe Naturalem Violentum et Voluntarium seu 
 Liberum, existimavit primariam causam petendam 
 esse ex atomis, a quibus omnis motus principium. 
 Quare et velle potuit radicem motus naturalis esse 
 ipsum motum Primarium atomis ingenitum, eum 
 scilicet qui dicitur gravitatis et ponderis et quo 
 Atomus dicitur ad lineam sive perpendiculum ferri. 
 Violenti vero motum Reflexionis seu ilium qui est 
 ex occursione, seu plaga ictuque alterius. Denique 
 Voluntarii ipsum motum declinationis cui nulla regio 
 determinata, nullum tempus praefixum est. . . . 
 Verumtamen videtur fuisse excepturus Democritus 
 nullatenus posse Epicurum commentatione hac adju- 
 vari. Quoniam, cum hie declinationis motus tam sit 
 naturalis atomisve congeneus, quam qui ad perpen- 
 diculum est (quippe quern non extrinsecus, sed a 
 
 1 Quoted below, p. 236.
 
 234 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 seipsis habeant) ideo tarn fient omnia Fato, tametsi 
 ille concedatur, quam si admissus non fuerit : cum 
 pari semper necessitate ea quae eveniunt sint eventura 
 pro varietate motuum, ictuum, repulsuum, clina- 
 minum, etc., aeterna quadam serie et quasi catena 
 sese consequentium : ac speciatim quidem quod ad 
 cognitionem appetitionemque attinet, ad quam referri 
 libertas debet. Etenim ut mens, sive animus earn 
 libertatem explicet, qua appetit, v.c. Pomum, debet 
 primo imago seu species visibilis pomi ex ipso pro- 
 cedere, trajectaque per oculos percellere mentem, ut 
 illud cognoscat. Pomum autem, ut speciem in oculum 
 transmitteret, debuit tali loco reponi ab eo, qui ex 
 arbore ipsum collegisset, collectumve aliunde habuisset. 
 Arbor vero praeter Solis radios, humoremque et terram, 
 unde adolesceret, etiam granum babuit, unde nasce- 
 retur. Id granum fuit ex pomo alio, hocque ex alia 
 arbore, huic non alio loco nee alio tempore sata : atque 
 ita retrogrediendo ad usque mundi initium, quo et 
 terra et terrena semina ortum habuere ex concur- 
 sionibus complexionibusque atomorum, quae ut iis 
 locis iisque modis convenirent, debuerunt exinde non 
 aliunde accedere : et ut accederent, debuerunt aut 
 ex inani aut ex alio sive uno sive multiplici Mundo 
 ita advenire ut per illud sive in illo ac isto non alio 
 modo fuerint : atque ita porro per totam antece- 
 dentem aeternitatem. Deinde, si animus quoque 
 coaluit ex atomis, debuere necessario tales atomi 
 contineri in parentum seminibus, debuere eo confluere 
 ex certis cibis, aere, sole. Debuere lii cibi, non alii 
 assumi : debuere ipsorum caeterae causae ex his 
 illisque non aliis esse atque ita rursus ab aeterno 
 tempore quod idem pari modo eveniet, quamcunque 
 
 1
 
 III.] ETHICS 235 
 
 ex causis quasi lateralibus, et concomitantibus quae 
 in immensum pene excrescunt, quovis modo assump- 
 seris adeo ut cuicunque illarum ex tota serie te 
 addixeris, deprehensus si retexendo, ipsam ea con- 
 catenatione teneri cum aliis ut ex tota serie ad tale 
 usque momentum producta, necessum fuerit consequi 
 huiusmodi appetitionem. Scilicet ex aeterno usque 
 causae causis sic cohaeserunt ut postremae istae 
 denique concurrerint, quibus positis mens non potuit 
 non cognoscere et appetere pomum. Quodque de 
 causis dicitur, idem semper est intelligendum de 
 atomis, ex quibus conflantur et ex quarum motibus 
 variis motiones derivant, propter quas sunt causae. 
 Praetereo autem, quod Cicero videatur eodem respex- 
 isse. . . . Adhaec autem, ut aliquid ex ipsa Epicuri 
 mente probabiliter respondeatur : assumendum est eam 
 esse animorum contexturam ex atomis, ut quae in ea 
 sunt declinantes, eam rigiditatem quae ex aliis est, 
 flectant, naturamque flexibilem in omnem partem 
 faciant : in quo sit radix libertatis. Quare et animum 
 allectum cuiuspiam rei imagine, abripi quidem versus 
 illam : sed non ita tamen quin, si aliunde imago alia 
 occurrerit, allici ea rursus et abripi posset : adeo, ut 
 a priore deflectens, constituatur quasi in bivio et ad 
 utramque partem indifferens sit : quod sane est 
 liberum esse. Quod animus autem, cum sit ita 
 fiexilis ac indifferens, sese ad unam potius partem 
 quam ad aliam determinet, id oriri ex impressione 
 unius imaginis vehementiore, quam alterius : sicque 
 election em sequi ad apprehensionem eius rei quam 
 imago sive bonum sive meliorem exhibuerit. Denique 
 animum, ubi quippiam elegit, aut voluit, esse quasi 
 principem machinam, ex cuius motione, intercedenti-
 
 236 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 busque spiritibus, qui per totum corpus discurrunt, 
 facultates omnes, ac membra exsequendo destinata, 
 excitentur eoque feratur quo tendit ipse animus. 
 Facere hue possunt, quae caiiit Lucretius, 
 
 * Declinamus item raotus, nee tempore certo, 
 iiec regiorie loci certa, sed ubi ipsa tulit mens. 
 Nam dubio procul his rebus sua quoique voluntas 
 principium dat : et heinc motus per membra vagantur. 
 
 ' Quo loco declinare est flectere ac dirigere motus : 
 illudque nee tempore certo, etc., notat cum ipsam 
 animi indifferentiam seu libertatem, quatenus animus 
 ex se non ad ista potius quam ad ilia fertur : tum 
 varietatem rerum occasionum, imaginum, quae neque 
 semper, neque eaedem neque eodem modo in eum 
 incidunt ipsumque alliciunt.' 
 
 This is by no means an easy passage to com- 
 prehend, but if the mind of the reader can be 
 cleared of all presuppositions, he will see that the 
 following points are established : 
 
 (1) Epicurus is opposed to Democritus. 
 
 (2) His answer to Democritus is based on the 
 
 idea of Declination. 
 
 (3) His position would not be overthrown by 
 
 any objection urged by the supporter of 
 Democritus to the effect that Declination 
 is an original force, and therefore only one 
 more form of determination. 
 
 (4) His own doctrine proves that the mind is 
 capable of aiiy motion, and therefore up 
 to the time it moves is wholly undeter- 
 mined : it moves entirely in accordance 
 with the laws of force, and is therefore 
 free. 
 
 i
 
 III.] ETHICS 237 
 
 This last is the point at which it seems to me 
 that our guides have led us astray. M. Guyau's 
 spontaneity surely means that the Will can and 
 does act in wholly indeterminate ways, i.e. in ways 
 which have no relation at all to the other co-existent 
 forces. Masson argues that this is a breach of law, 
 and therefore would not have been tolerated through- 
 out Nature (M. Guyau having thought it universal), 
 but is none the less valid of the mind : the ' fatis 
 avolsa potestas ' of Lucretius seems to have made 
 him think Lucretius exempted the Will from deter- 
 mination, though surely Lucretius must have seen 
 that one lawless element makes the whole lawless. 
 Masson's assumption seems to be that Law holds 
 in Nature only : hence Guyau's spontaneity in nature 
 must be a fiction. But the animus which we labour 
 to make free is also in Nature ; and therefore its 
 spontaneity is a fiction. Although Masson speaks 
 of ' the volition of the dead atoms,' I think he has 
 not really succeeded in putting himself entirely on 
 the material side and looking at things in the way 
 Lucretius did. If we can once begin to discuss 
 freedom without reference to consciousness as the 
 agent, if, that is, we can comprehend a freedom 
 revealed to consciousness but not dependent on 
 consciousness, we shall be on the right road. 
 
 Lucretius exactly formulates the position in the 
 phrase 'fatisque avolsa potestas.' The apparent 
 meaning of that is ' a power plucked from the grip 
 of Fate,' i.e. saved from the inexorable laws. But 
 that is just what it does not mean : on the contrary, 
 it means ' saved from the Fates in order to be 
 subject to law.' The Fates denote here the power
 
 238 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt 
 
 which overrules physical laws, which is therefore^ 
 from the point of view of Physics, an incommen- 
 surable quantity. Plato gives us this idea of Fate 
 in the Republic, Bk. x., for there we see that the 
 will of the individual is destined at one fell stroke 
 to follow out the chosen course of a whole life- 
 time. Now, express this in terms of Force. Two 
 forces act on the body ^ : as a result it moves in 
 direction x. 
 
 This is according to law : neither / nor /' produces 
 the direction x by itself — bat both together produce 
 
 'N 
 
 /' 
 
 a result which, given the factors involved, is always 
 calculable. Now if A moved in the direction M 
 or N, or any direction other than x, the reason 
 for that movement could only be found in some 
 determinant other than the given forces, i.e. in Fate. 
 Fate, then, is the contrary of regular law-abiding 
 action. Hence Gassendi says, ' Explodenda Democriti 
 sententia est . . . ilia Epicuri defendi quidem potest 
 quatenus Fatum et Naturam naturaleisve causas res 
 esse synonymas ducit.' It was then by making Fate 
 the same as Nature that Epicurus defended freedom \ 
 This seems paradoxical, but the difference lies just 
 in this, that Democritus said Nature is Fate, and 
 in any case we are bound hand and foot: Epicurus 
 said Fate is nothing unless it is law, and the law 
 is my nature, not something ' extrinsecus,' over- 
 ruling me. So long, says Epicurus, as natural forces
 
 III.] ETHICS 239 
 
 alone control action, I am free, for I am a real agent, 
 and when I say, / do this, there is no illusion : I 
 take my place among the forces of the world and 
 am content. 
 
 But if this is the opinion of Epicurus, what more 
 do we want ? Why does not Gassendi accept it ? 
 The answer is, that after all for us, as we now look 
 at it, with God and the hereafter to keep in mind, 
 this theory is useless. In it the future counts for 
 nothing : the forces all act a tergo : the what-I-am- 
 now alone counts : the future being, that which is 
 not, cannot have any place in a theory that aims 
 to be purely physical. As soon as Providence is 
 assumed and its implications examined, as they had 
 been in the literature of Christian philosophy, we 
 get the idea of end, and the possibility of the 
 consciousness of ends. Then the doctrine of Epicurus 
 must be relegated to the sphere of the animals, from 
 which it had been taken : the sphere that is of 
 those beings that move and think, but do not move 
 because of the thought. 
 
 Such is Gassendi's view and my conception of 
 its meaning. I add one or two remarks by way 
 of elucidation for which Gassendi is not responsible. 
 It might easily be said that Epicurus admitted the 
 influence of future happiness as determining present 
 choice, and therefore must have gone beyond the 
 sphere of physical action. To this there are two 
 answers: (l) The thought of the future is a present 
 thought, and therefore belongs, as active factor, to 
 the forces which are now and here. This I think 
 Epicurus would not have used. (2) The real answer 
 lies in the point that it is Freedom of the Will we
 
 240 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. 
 
 are discussing, not freedom of choice. Locke has 
 put this point very well. ' This then is evident, 
 that in all proposals of present action, a man is 
 not at liberty to will or not to will, because he 
 cannot forbear willing : liberty consisting in a power 
 to act, or to forbear acting, and in that only. For 
 a man that sits still is said yet to be at liberty, 
 because he can walk if he wills it. But if a man 
 sitting still has not a power to remove himself, he 
 is not at liberty : so likewise a man falling down a 
 precipice, though in motion, is not at liberty, because 
 he cannot stop that motion if he would ' (Essay, 
 Bk. ii. ch. xxi. § 24). This latter clause exactly 
 expresses the idea which Gassendi attributes to 
 r\r Epicurus. It is not a question of being free to 
 
 / choose, but of being able to do what one does 
 
 choose. Freedom of choice belongs to Ratio : would 
 any Greek talk of freedom of Reason ? Certainly 
 not an Epicurean : for him it is enough that the 
 action begins from the man, the ap-^^J] rm Trpa^ecDs, 
 the voluntas principium dat of Lucretius. 
 
 At the close of Gassendi's exposition quoted above, 
 we see that he says ' the more vehement image or 
 impression determines action, i.e. we always follow 
 the better course. The words vehementior and 
 melior come so close together that it seems 
 impossible to suppose that Gassendi was not con- 
 scious of the transition. On the contrary, I think 
 it is an intentional juxtaposition expressing his 
 opinion that for Epicurus and Lucretius the better 
 must always be the stronger : in which he was 
 probably right. For his own theory this is a diffi- 
 culty, and perhaps explains why he transfers the
 
 III.] ETHICS -241 
 
 liberty from voluntas to Ratio, a procedure which 
 is on the whole retrograde, and theological rather 
 than philosophical. After the Pelagian controversy 
 and the subtleties of posse non peccare and non posse 
 peccare, the moral quality of volitions was a more 
 important question than the efficiency of the will 
 as a factor in a world of motions.
 
 PART IV. GENERAL REVIEW
 
 245 
 
 CHAPTER I 
 GASSENDI 
 
 I. 
 
 We have now passed in review all the main features 
 of Gassendi's thought : what are we to say of it 
 as a whole 1 
 
 Here and there in the literature of philosophy one 
 finds references to Gassendi. As a rule they are 
 patently second hand, and often accompanied by the 
 remark that Gassendi has been unduly neglected, 
 without however any clear indications of what is to 
 be expected from the study of his works. ^ We are 
 now in a position to consider the value of Gassendi's 
 writings and show the reasons why he was neglected 
 and also why he deserves a better fate. 
 
 The first phase of modern philosophy as it is 
 described by historians was marked by the revival 
 of ancient systems and a tendency to revert to pre- 
 Aristotelian doctrines, especially atomism. No one 
 however attempted to reconstruct atomism as a 
 system : the atomistic principles only afiected certain 
 phases of the teaching of contemporary philosophers : 
 until at last Gassendi published his work. Un- 
 fortunately, it came too late to catch the general ear :
 
 246 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 already the keynote of modern thought had been 
 struck and a new point of view adopted by specu- 
 lative thinkers.^ The direct objectivity of Gassendi 
 could no longer find a responsive audience when 
 every mind was busily developing the new notions 
 of a subjective philosophy. Gassendi was ranked 
 among the ancients, true descendant of Democritus 
 and Epicurus : the world wanted no more of the 
 ancients : we, they said, are the ancients, and in the 
 history of thought the last is ripest and best. Not 
 only was Gassendi thus hampered by his relations 
 and discounted by being a disciple of Epicurus, he 
 was also regarded as materialistic, not in the sense 
 in which we might use the term now, but in opposi- 
 tion to the idealism which was daily gaining ground. 
 Descartes had at least succeeded in dividing mind 
 from matter, and so far laid the foundation of the 
 subjective movement in philosophy ; and for those 
 who cherished this position Gassendi's view of the 
 universe could have no attractions. The all-absorbing 
 question now was how to heal the wound that 
 thought had inflicted on itself, how to bridge the 
 gulf that these convulsions had made in the once 
 solid world of Being. Given a dualism of this kind 
 
 ^Thomas {op. cit. p. 24) gives two reasons for the neglect into 
 which Gassendi fell. The first, quoted from Brucker, is that Gassendi 
 was too modest : his manner was so hesitating that it failed to win 
 the confidence of the reader. The other is want of clearness and 
 conciseness in the exposition. I think the true reason is rather to 
 be found in the fact that the necessity of getting down to nature was 
 not yet fully recognised, and the ideas of systen) and subjectivity 
 were more akin to the spirit of the times than those of content 
 and empirical classification. Thomas is certainly right in saying that 
 Gassendi -was as much damaged by his friends as his foes: Epicurus in 
 one way, and Bernier in another, combined to damage his prospects.
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 247 
 
 the central problem must be that of re- unification, 
 and so, as a matter of history, it was, from Descartes 
 down to Kant. On the very edge of this era stands 
 Gassendi, as it were the last of the old school : after 
 him comes the long period of restless searching, with 
 its slow growth, through many abstractions to a new 
 concreteness and fresh satisfaction in the discovery 
 that after all the world is my world. 
 
 Across this sea of strife we look back to-day, and 
 are surprised to see how near to us that last beacon 
 seems : the longer way takes much time, and in the 
 end we are further on, but not so far as we could 
 wish, seeing how many toilsome years have elapsed. 
 We have still with us the old problems, many of 
 them not yet entirely obscured by the multiplicity 
 of solutions : we have still the old antagonisms, and 
 philosophers strive in vain to repudiate the titles 
 with which the critics successfully label them. I 
 am far enough from suggesting that man has not 
 progressed in the sphere of thought just as un- 
 doubtedly as he has progressed in the sciences and 
 in adaptation to his world ; but as one reads the 
 pages of Gassendi there grows the feeling that this 
 was the ' synthetic philosophy ' of its age : that 
 Gassendi aimed to do what Herbert Spencer has 
 aimed to do : that the difference of their material 
 is a significant comment on what has been done ; 
 and their similarity an equally significant connnent 
 on what has not been achieved : while between 
 Gassendi and his opponent lay just the kind of gulf 
 that lies now between the Spencerian and the noii- 
 Spencerian.^ 
 
 iSee p. 305.
 
 248 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pi\ 
 
 II. 
 
 In the list given by Ueberweg of those who revived 
 ancient doctrines we find ' Epicureanism by Gassendi.* 
 Further on we find a note on Gassendi which runs 
 thus : ' Gassendi sought to defend Epicureanism 
 against unjustified attacks, and to show that it 
 contained the best doctrine of physics, and at the 
 same time to combine it with Christian theology. 
 Gassendi's atomism is less a doctrine of dead nature 
 than is that of Epicurus. . . . From its relation to 
 the investigation of nature in modern times, Gassendi's 
 revival of Epicureanism is of far greater historical 
 importance than the renewal of any other system : 
 not unjustly does F. A. Lange consider Gassendi as 
 the one who may properly be styled the renewer in 
 modern times of systematic materialism.' These are 
 cautious words, and obviously more of Lange than 
 Gassendi : we may take them as our text, and see 
 how far they are true. 
 
 The passage quoted gives us two descriptions of 
 Gassendi : his philosophy is (1) Epicureanism modified 
 and (2) systematic materialism. The former defini- 
 tion does not help us much unless we know more 
 accurately how far the Epicureanism was modified, 
 and in any case Epicureanism was never a term of 
 very exact significance. We can leave this and take 
 up the second title, materialist, a label generally 
 affixed to the name of Gassendi and usually justified 
 by a reference to Lange, who seems to have been 
 more anxious to find a materialist in Gassendi than 
 to find out whether Gassendi was a materialist. 
 
 To define this term materialist we shall have to-
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 249 
 
 work backwards. It means in common use a phil- 
 osophy which starts from the object as something 
 distinct from and opposed to the subject. ' No object 
 without subject ' is, according to Schopenhauer, the 
 principle which for ever makes materiaUsm im- 
 possible : from which it seems to follow that object 
 without subject is the peculiar theme of the mate- 
 rialist. Certainly the materialist does not start from 
 ' notion ' or ego, and so ftxr forth he is the antithesis 
 of the idealist. But materialism implies far more 
 than this : it implies a view of the universe as 
 altogether objective, as all object and no subject, as 
 a self- organising, self-subsisting whole, known only 
 as it is reflected in a consciousness which is a by- 
 product of its activities. Whether we take materialist ; 
 in the widest or the narrowest sense in which it can j 
 be used, one point is essential : mind must be a 
 function of matter, and this alone justifies us in 
 denying that Gassendi is properly a materialist. At 
 the same time he is certainly not an idealist. But 
 the necessity of dividing all philosophers into one 
 or other of these classes is what we are prepared to 
 dispute ; and, finally, we may discover a more suitable 
 title than materialist while clearing our minds on 
 this point. 
 
 To begin with the historical aspect, Gassendi as 
 related to the ancients might more suitably be called 
 a physical than a materialist philosopher. After 
 Kant, idealism takes as its motto, ' no object without 
 subject.' Before that era of criticism there was 
 idealism of another kind that retained many objects 
 that were only partially, if at all, dependent on a 
 subject. The Cartesian doctrine is rightly called
 
 250 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 idealism in so far as it laid stress on the mind as 
 the centre of our universe of knowledge ; but that 
 world of knowledge lay in an ocean of Being that 
 stretched beyond its limits, unknown and as yet 
 unnamed. This idealism, the idealism that tells us 
 our world is known only through the mediation of 
 ideas, and so keeps asunder that world and the 
 cosmos of ideas, is far different from critical or 
 transcendental idealism, and its opposite is not mate- 
 rialism in the modern sense at all. How could it be, 
 seeing that the idealism in question kept its matter 
 a solid ' adverse occupant of space ' and carried the 
 reality of this matter up to the very threshold of 
 thought, even there trying to retain its being for 
 thought as the thought itself, and convert its gross- 
 ness into thought by refining it to its subtlest forms ? 
 History has done justice to Descartes, but hardly 
 to Gassendi. Even as contemporaries they were 
 mainly regarded as rival physicists, the one for atoms 
 and the other for vortices : yet one cannot help 
 thinking that if Gassendi had possessed the clearness 
 and directness of Descartes' or Hobbes' style he might 
 have commanded as much recognition as either. If 
 we take Descartes as the typical figure of this period, 
 and call his doctrine material idealism/ we shall 
 have a point which may enable us to determine the 
 bearings of Gassendi. The feature of that idealism is 
 that it makes extra-mental reality uncertain, or, to 
 put it more vigorously, draws the line of real and 
 unreal at the boundary of one's own skin. This 
 Gassendi does not do, so that title does not include 
 him. 
 
 ^ I take the phrase from Kant.
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 251 
 
 It appeared promising for a moment, since the 
 ground of that distinction of inner and outer exist- 
 ents lies in the doctrine of representative ideas. This 
 doctrine we have also in Gassendi in the form of 
 symbolic brain movements, so that a similar result 
 might have been expected : as it is not forthcoming 
 we cannot say more, but go back and start again. 
 
 If we look once more we see another common 
 point. In a sense Descartes and Gassendi both start 
 from experience ; both are in a way empirical. But 
 Descartes begins with a prejudice for rationalism : 
 the ' cogito ergo sum ' may not have been the actual 
 starting point of his system, but its final emergence 
 has been declared in the verdict of history to 
 guarantee rationalism as the tone of the system. 
 As compared with this, Gassendi works with a pure 
 experience. 
 
 Once more we digress to wrestle with our termi- 
 nology. What is experience as a basis of philosophy ? 
 In the language of the philosophy of to-day it is to 
 be taken as the most comprehensive of all terms, the 
 name for reality as it lives and moves, not merely 
 in us, or in thought, but in itself. From it, as 
 derivatives, spring subject and object and all other 
 antitheses, and the work of philosophy is the analysis 
 of this experience. This brings us back to idealism 
 as Schopenhauer defined it. This is the result of the 
 Kantian standpoint and his analysis of the object. 
 Before Kant the object was the same as the thing, a 
 given and not a product ; and thought based on 
 experience was called empirical, now become an 
 opprobrious epithet. Empiricism then is the science 
 of experience in this cruder form. But as a rule
 
 252 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 'empirical' as a philosophical label means subjective 
 in the sense that Locke's psychological method is 
 empirical. Philosophy rapidly took this psycho- 
 logical trend : it was the human understanding to 
 which all attention was directed, and with that the 
 question arose, ' how can I know what I know ? ' 
 drawing the curiosity of man after it with irresistible 
 attraction. 
 
 Compared with these later enquirers (Berkeley and 
 Hume) the position of Locke, and still more of 
 Descartes, appears crude and uncritical. Yet there 
 is an element of strength and comprehensiveness 
 about them that is reassuring. This is due to their 
 fresh simplicity in believing that what is actual must 
 be possible, that what our experience gives us must 
 be accepted even if it cannot be explained. Experi- 
 ence is then taken in the broadest possible way, and 
 its truth accepted. Descartes, for example, finds his 
 theory divides mind from matter : yet in experience 
 they are one, and so they are again united : the 
 critic pounces on the ' inconsistency,' but Descartes 
 does better in bending theory to fact, as he knew it, 
 than in distorting fact to save the theory. Modern 
 philosophy has too much of the element that damned 
 scholasticism when it casts the theory first and fits 
 in the facts after. The shibboleth of theory plays 
 in modern thought the part that authority played in 
 scholasticism. We lay down for ourselves laws of 
 what we must have, and in the seclusion of the study 
 we get it : outside the reality breaks loose, and we 
 envy Hume, who found the problems that seemed to 
 mock his efforts vanish when he stepped out into the 
 sunshine.
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 253 
 
 Descartes stood for sincerity as well as he could. 
 Gassendi too, barring graceful concessions to the 
 dogmas he neglects, strikes us as sincere. For both, 
 Experience was the last great fact, the first great 
 synthesis that no theoretical analysis could destroy. 
 For Gassendi experience is life, the life of thought 
 and will and feeling, and the subject matter of 
 philosophy. Hence his philosophy is grounded in 
 experience ; but it is an analysis of the experienced, 
 .not of experience itself : it is a mapping out, so far as 
 may be an organisation, of the known, the felt and 
 the willed : not a criticism of knowing or feeling or 
 willing itself. As yet criticism is far off, looming in 
 the horizon of the future : the darkness of the night 
 is passing away, and in the day of freedom just 
 beginning men rejoice in sorting out, arranging and 
 setting in order the realities with which they feel 
 themselves in living contact now that they no longer 
 need to see the world throu2;h the veil of traditions. 
 
 Gassendi's basis is this experience, to him at least 
 not known as crude, and we may call him empirical, 
 hoping that the term is sufficiently explained. 
 Empiricism includes empirical idealism and empirical 
 realism. The former ' makes ideas into things,' and 
 gets rid of the world in the sense that Berkeley 
 did.^ With this Gassendi has nothing to do : he 
 must therefore be classed as an empirical realist. 
 But neither is this quite satisfactory. It is true we 
 have the atoms, but atomism has more forms than 
 
 1 ' I shall not therefore be surprised if spme men imagine that I run 
 into the enthusiasm of Malebranche. . . . He asserts an absolute 
 external world, which I deny ' (the Second Dialogue between Hylas 
 and Philonous).
 
 254 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pi'. 
 
 one. It may be (l) pure physical atomism, such as 
 we associate with the name of Democritus ; or (2) 
 pure idealistic atomism, such as Leibnitz attempted ; 
 or finally, (3) a mixed form combining the atomistic 
 theory of the world with a non-materialistic view 
 of the mind. This is the construction of things 
 Gassendi gives us, and in this lies the great difficulty 
 of properly understanding him. The difficulty can of 
 course be overcome by saying that Gassendi was half- 
 hearted or allowed his theory to be ruined by his 
 orthodoxy. But is there any proof of this ? None, 
 I think, except that his construction does not work 
 out as some have thought it ought to ; does not 
 present the unity we demand in modern works. But 
 it is the prerogative of systems which start from 
 consciousness to attain unity to a degree we never 
 find in other systems ; and the lack of unity is 
 perhaps not so serious as appears at first, for if 
 matter does not carry us to the end we may find 
 that our pr-incij^les do, and we at least remain faithful 
 to our basis, experience. 
 
 The name atomism naturally allies itself with 
 materialism. We are accustomed to atomic theories 
 which belong to physical science, and therefore 
 remain within the realm of matter. But if we 
 reflect on atomism as a philosophical principle we 
 see that it is essentially a method or principle, not 
 a given matter, and therefore may be applied as a 
 principle to any given. I do not say that it can 
 rightly be applied ; but only that it does not of 
 itself necessitate matter being the only constituent 
 principle. Just as evolution is a way of looking 
 at things and does not tell us what that which
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 255 
 
 evolves must be in other respects, so atomism 
 merely lays down the law that a complex total 
 must be composed of indivisible parts : whether the 
 parts are material or spiritual is of no concern to 
 atomism as such. This is clear if we think of Locke's 
 atomic psychology, of W. K. Clifford's atomism, or 
 of Leibnitz ; and we need not fear the accusa- 
 tion of reversing history, for Giordano Bruno had 
 grasped before Gassendi the significance for idealism 
 of an atomistic doctrine, and rightly seen that 
 the speculative aspect of atomism is simply the 
 question of real minima. ^ The principle upon 
 which atomism works is that the ultimate is an 
 individuum, and this is not in any way touched 
 by having a spiritual as well as a material order : 
 whether there are to be more orders than one is a 
 question that must be decided on its own merits, 
 and Gassendi's reason for having a soul that is not 
 material is that he finds in his own life grounds 
 for belief in an immaterial entity, in other words 
 he takes it up from experience. For the present 
 we are content to point out that there is this 
 spiritual reality, and that it forms an integral pa it 
 of the whole doctrine. We must therefore be careful 
 to take our title ' empirical realism ' strictly to mean 
 
 ^On this point Gassendi in his correspondence diverged into 
 humour with a translation of duo quaedam epigrammata ex Antho- 
 logia : I quote the second : 
 
 ' Ex Atomis Epicurus ait consistere Munduni, 
 Alcime, quippe putans his nihil esse minus. 
 At si novisset Diophantum, constituisset 
 Ex ipso potius, qui minor est Atomis. 
 Aut alia ex Atomis texens, ipsas potuisset 
 Ex Diophanto Atomos coraposuisse prius.' 
 
 (VI. 160.)
 
 256 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 that our ground is experience, and our world is real 
 in the anti-idealistic sense that it is not made by 
 mind. 
 
 III. 
 
 Having defined the scope of this philosophy a 
 few remarks may be added on its main features : 
 as our account of Gassendi is itself nothing but 
 a summary, there is no need to add summary to 
 summary, and nothing will be said here beyond 
 what is necessary to indicate the view I take of 
 the philosophy as a whole. 
 
 Gassendi' s philosophy is an analysis of our 
 universe, attained by examining experience, and 
 presented synthetically, or we might say syntacti- 
 cally (in a syntagma). As synthetic the presentation 
 has a definite principle upon which it is worked out. 
 This principle is the idea of ascending degrees of 
 complexity. The unit is the atom : things are com- 
 plexes of atoms : and each degree of complexity 
 has its own peculiar attributes. We thus get a 
 scale of Being; as follows : 
 
 (a) The atomic scale. 
 
 (1) Primary complexes of atoms (kinds of earth). 
 
 (2) Secondary complexes of atoms (metals, etc.). 
 
 (3) Primary organic complexes : plants. 
 
 (4) Secondary organic complexes : animals. 
 
 This does not by any means exhaust the content 
 of reality : we have as well as (a) the atomic scale 
 also, 
 
 (b) Time and Space. 
 
 (c) The Soul. 
 
 (d) God.
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 257 
 
 About Time and Space Gassendi has little to tell 
 us : they were just the elements that could not be 
 satisfactorily treated on the basis which he had 
 chosen. But the difficulties which might have 
 made it impossible for him to proceed were in a 
 way solved by the method itself. If the world of 
 nature is resolvable into units that are ultimate, 
 impenetrable and irreducible, is there any objection 
 to the universe also being regarded as a sum of 
 irreducibles ? Gassendi often speaks of the universe 
 as a whole, and obviously thought of it as in some 
 way one : the way that unity is to be conceived is 
 an interesting question. 
 
 Must the whole be one ? In some form or other 
 philosophy has always answered yes. But there are 
 three distinct phases to this answer. The last is 
 that which is made possible by the subjective 
 character of modern idealism, in which the unity 
 is derived from the formative factor in know- 
 ledge. The first was the naive unity which appears 
 possible to a mind that can ask without qualifica- 
 tion for a single material principle. These extremes 
 have one point in common : they both regard the 
 unity as necessarily belonging to the constitutive 
 principle : they want to weave the universe of one 
 stufl" and relegate all diff"erences to the pattern. 
 The reason for this is the inequality of their 
 categories : categories as such should all be equal, 
 but in fact they are not : substance in the one case 
 and spirit in the other have swallowed up all the 
 other aspects of reality, and ceasing to be aspects 
 have become the stuff itself. Now, when the 
 crudeness of the primary standpoint has become
 
 258 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. 
 
 clear, the natural tendency is to move towards the 
 second ; and this movement being as yet bound up 
 with the progress of physical science, we find that 
 the first phase of a doctrine that gives its rights 
 to mind is the emphasis laid on law. To think of 
 the law and the matter in such a way as to separate 
 them is half-way toward making them collateral 
 realities, and for a time produces satisfaction in 
 minds that are dimly aware that all matter and no 
 mind makes a dull world. At this point, and while 
 we are as it were on tip- toe for the next develop- 
 ment, the addition of a corollary to the original 
 suggestion makes it into a useful basis for thought 
 of one type, and then it is defended against progress 
 as itself an ultimate standpoint. This phenomenon 
 we observe in the history of philosophy more than 
 once, namely the tendency for critical minds to 
 fortify what was originally nothing but a halting 
 ground, and sturdily refusing to go further, pro- 
 claim it the goal. The reason is not far to seek. 
 Some minds require to know what they can have, 
 others require to have what they desire : the latter 
 are always too eager for the delicate poise of a 
 mean position : they must fall one way or the 
 other ; but their more critical fellows fall neither 
 way, and reserve their energies for rescuing their 
 comrades and restoring once again the mean posi- 
 tion. Not indeed quite the same, for the ardent 
 souls ' fall to rise, are bafiled to fight better ' ; 
 and the rescuer himself never quite gets back to 
 the old footing, but to one sufficiently like it 
 to be recognisable. The mean position has always 
 got one characteristic, it has no constitutive
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 259 
 
 unity. Monism demands a constitutive unity : 
 whatever the stuff is, it must be one throughout. 
 As to the righteousness of this demand I have 
 nothing to say. I content myself with trying to 
 make clear what the man in the mean position has 
 to say for himself, for Gassendi is a type of that 
 class. 
 
 The constitutive unity, we can imagine him say- 
 ing, is an ideal, and no better than other ideals : if 
 it will not work it must be given up. The fact that 
 it appears to be the best ideal cannot help it if we 
 find that it is useless in practice. Further, it may 
 not be the best ideal if we think again, for that the 
 world should be One Being is no great advantage to 
 us, seeing that our interest does not lie in its being 
 but in its doing. What we want then is only a 
 world that is not One Being but one in its being, 
 one in its doing, in all its dealings with me, single 
 and not double. Its being is its being related to me, 
 and all I want is that the entities should be capable 
 of some sort of order, should be thinkable by me as 
 system.^ 
 
 It is at this point that the ardent soul runs ahead 
 of the man in the mean position. He hears his cue in 
 
 ^This question of the relations and comparative values of the 
 monistic and pluralistic ideals, of the One Being and the being at 
 one, is too big to be discussed incidentally. It has been touched 
 upon by Mr. F. C. S. Schiller in The Riddles of the Sphinx (p. 353) : 
 ' We may reasonably conclude then that monism is a failure, that by 
 assuming uniU/ at the outset it incapacitates itself for the task of 
 explaining phenomenal plurality, and a fortiori for the still higher 
 task of really uniting the Many in a significant imion' ; p. 355 : 'And 
 Leibnitz might well take for granted that as the Many do interact, 
 they must be capable of interacting, and that it was unnecessary to 
 demonstrate that what actually existed was also capable of existing.'
 
 260 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 the word ' thinkable,' and at once declares that the 
 thinkable is Thought, and therefore the objective 
 is ' ultimately' Thought, and possibly even its objec- 
 tivity is due to our having cast it from us, ' ejected ' 
 it in that carelessness of youth which can be re- 
 trieved only by again taking it back into ourselves. 
 But this was exactly what was not meant : we 
 did not w^ant this assimilation of natures : on the 
 contrary, we find it far easier to think of the recipro- 
 cal action of things different in nature. We do not 
 say that the iron must really be a magnet or that the 
 soul must be a body, but only that they must have 
 the required affinities. And what are those affinities? 
 Why, the affinities they have as a matter of fact got ! 
 Is this philosophy ? The ardent soul thinks not. 
 Yet what is the difference ? The one wants to make 
 the related factors one in nature, the other makes 
 them different ; but both want a relation, and ulti- 
 mately care nothing so long as there is a relation and 
 the possibility of relations. 
 
 We may by now seem to have rather wandered 
 from Gassendi, but the object of these more abstract 
 remarks is to suggest the outline of a position which 
 is none too easy to grasp, and is indeed not so explicit 
 in Gassendi as the above comparisons might suggest. 
 But a few data briefly recalled will bring us back to 
 our bearings. In Gassendi there are three substances — 
 corporeal, non-corporeal, and mixed. There are more 
 than three irreducibles, namely God, Time, Space, 
 the atom, and the Soul. 
 
 This is therefore pluralism. Numerical plurality 
 is not the point : else we should have to say there 
 were as many universes as there were atoms. It is
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 261 
 
 in qualitative plurality that we find the real irredu- 
 cibleness of the factors in our universe. But if 
 quality is the ground of plurality, where are we to 
 stop? Everything that is different from anything 
 else is qualitatively different, and in respect of the 
 quality is irreducible. The universe is therefore a 
 collection of irreducibles : it falls to pieces in our 
 hands : where is its unity ? Just here, in the fact 
 that, before we meddled with it, it succeeded well 
 enough : that if you give up meddling with it now it 
 will go on just as it did before :^ its unity is the bald 
 and simple fact that it holds together, and the philo- 
 sopher's business is simply to formulate the ways in 
 which that unity is in fact achieved. 
 
 The crudity of this is apparent, but we are not 
 concerned at present with the question is this a 
 good kind of philosophy, but rather is this a good 
 specimen of the kind. To gain further light on this 
 we shall examine three other points in detail, namely 
 (a) the place of motion in the system, (b) the use of 
 categories, and (c) the relation of quantity to quality. 
 
 (a) Any view of the universe that starts with 
 matter and mind as separate, relies largely on motion 
 to enable it to deal with the inert mass. But the 
 inertia of the matter is itself only a consequence of 
 the attempt to keep a bare entity as the type of all 
 things external : it is, in other words, a multiplica- 
 tion of entities which only leads us into difficulties 
 by driving us to separate in existence the things to 
 
 ^In a letter to Valesius (vi. Ill, dated 1641) Gassendi distinguishes 
 two kinds of philosophy, (1) quam appellare twv (paivoixivuv^ seu His- 
 toricam soleo, (2) qua intiinae rerum naturae proprietatesque cognos- 
 cantur : . , . haec est quam Deo totani concede.
 
 262 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. 
 
 which we have given distinction. If we revert to 
 experience we find no such thing as motion in rerum 
 natura, only moving things. We are thus compelled 
 to unite in the unity of common life that which 
 thought divided. For a philosophy like that of 
 Gassendi motion is fundamental and at the same 
 time fraught with temptations. There is always the 
 tendency to use motion as a means of transition 
 from one aspect of reality to another. Taken 
 abstractly, motion is a common denominator : it is 
 one and the same in all things, being nothing but 
 change of place of atoms. But in order to get this 
 common denominator we must pursue the abstraction 
 of matter to such a degree as to make the motion a 
 pure motion, a motion of nothing, and finally nothing 
 at all. If this reduction to non-entity is recognised, 
 motion remains distinct from the moving, and we 
 get another factor which by its ill-defined nature is 
 able to work miracles for us. Activity is then thrust 
 forward as the essential quality of spirit : the quality 
 is thought of as a thing, activity, and material 
 activity being also a kind of activity, it seems clear 
 that activity is the link between mind and matter, 
 and if we can refine the material activity sufficiently 
 we shall have got across the everlasting gulf. If we 
 condemn this as mere abstraction in the interests of 
 either mind or matter, the ' tu quoque ' is ready : for 
 if the activity is neither the matter nor the mind, it 
 is yet no worse than matter which does not mentalise 
 or mind that will not materialise. 
 
 This pitfall Gassendi avoids by making motion, 
 in the primary sense of inner motion, one with 
 matter. The formula is materia actuosa, not matter
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 263 
 
 et actio ; and this is possible because he refuses to 
 reduce the ultimate to a mere imaginary entity. 
 
 There are three critical points of transition, namely 
 from inorganic to organic, from non-sentient to 
 sentient, from unthinking to thinking. Extremists 
 say these are the same ; but not so Gasseudi, whose 
 scale is Inorganic,! 
 
 Organic, J non-sentient, 1 
 
 sentient, J non-intellectual, 
 intellectual. 
 Gassendi realises that there is some difficulty in this. 
 He lays emphasis on the distinctness of animus, but 
 when he comes to it, the distinctness is dissolved 
 away. Is it any greater jump from non-intellectual 
 to intellectual than it was from insensile to sensile ;' 
 Whatever we do with our scale, it must fall to pieces 
 if we try to look for real bonds : mind is not joined 
 to body by any gluten or hooks :^ it is a question 
 of the other aspect, the quality, the what-it-is in 
 its actual being. Through the material sphere we 
 get our transitions mediated objectively by the idea 
 of movement and co-ordination. In the sphere of 
 sensation we have the non- sensile affinities (magnet 
 and iron) leading up to the sensile affinities, 
 which again have endless degrees as we rise from 
 lowest (oyster, e.g.) to highest. Complexity is the 
 medium by which we graduate this scale and ' most 
 complex' is the formula for what we call highest. 
 But the fact of being graduated does not mar the 
 reality of the degrees : they remain realities which 
 we graduate but do not fuse. For Gassendi the 
 real difficulty of dealing with mind comes in the 
 
 ^ Cp. Lotze, Microcosmus, i. 237, ' a constantly renewed cement.'
 
 264 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 foct that it implies a kind of movement which is 
 not in line with the others, a movement which 
 returns upon itself as no motion does in the physical 
 sphere ; but that is not regarded as a reason for 
 rejecting it, but as a necessity compelling us to 
 recognise that there is more than one kind of 
 motion in the universe, and a kind of reality which 
 is not subject to appulse : there is just the same 
 reason why there should be a reality so superior 
 to sense as is the mind, as there is for the eagle 
 with its superiority over the oyster. In both cases 
 the ' should be ' is the point we cannot deal with : 
 we have them as facts. The reality of the graduated 
 as actual things, in opposition to the graduation, we 
 shall discuss in section (c). 
 
 (6) Gassendi's exposition of his philosophy is often 
 made more difficult for the reader by the fact that 
 many of the discussions are dialectical disputes about 
 categories. The categories in question are simply 
 recognised headings, and when disputing with some 
 scholastic author or current theory, Gassendi employs 
 the categories as rules of formal disputation. 
 
 The prime category is that of substance. Under 
 this fall all corporeal entities without dispute ; but 
 trouble arises when a reality is given which is not 
 corporeal, and yet cannot be simply denied. The case 
 then stands exactly as it did with Leucippus. The 
 reality being not-not-ens must be ens, and there- 
 fore substance. But this seems to leave us with no 
 protection against hypostatising any concept into a 
 substance. To a certain extent this is guarded 
 against by the use which Gassendi makes of the idea 
 of function. This idea enables us to retain as reali-
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 265 
 
 ties much that cannot be accurately defined in regard 
 to its being : for we substitute for the being of the 
 thing its doing. In spite of the objective existence 
 which Gassendi gives to things, he adopts the some- 
 what idealistic method of defining them, and even 
 formulating them from the point of view of their 
 relation to us. Believing that things are what they 
 seem, in all normal cases, we can consistently define 
 the ultimate reality from the experience of it, the 
 manifestation of reality being its own definition. 
 Thus space and time are real, because in experience 
 things and events have spatial and temporal order. 
 The atom, the void, and the soul are real on the 
 same principles. Taking substance in this sense, it 
 equals reality, and reality is for Gassendi a category. 
 Quantity and quality are also categories, of which 
 more later. The other category is that of relation. 
 This is identical with place in the system, and as 
 such it is the final determination of the existent. 
 When we have shown that a thing is, ivhat it is, 
 and ivhei'e it is, we have done all that man can 
 toward the production of an ordered system of 
 things. It is a noticeable fact that Gassendi makes 
 no use of potentiality as a category, though it was 
 commonly so used : he criticises the particular appli- 
 cations of the idea, but does not state his reasons 
 for rejecting it. It may be surmised, but it is only 
 a surmise, that he considered it a confusion between 
 the categories of relation and substance. In any 
 case it certainly amounted to that, for it made what 
 was only a relation between the parts of a process 
 into an actual property, and left it uncertain whether 
 a thincr was what it was or was what it was firoinsf
 
 266 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 to be. Gassendi was quite scholastic enough to argue 
 that the statement, ' the acorn is the oak,' involved 
 a false use of the verb ' to be,' whether you added 
 ' potentially ' or not : he was also philosopher enough 
 to see that it either meant nothing or it implied the 
 unreality of all process, or what he would call the 
 unreality of degrees of being. This was in direct 
 opposition to his own ideas about quantity and 
 quality and their relations. 
 
 (c) As a rule the category of relation was made 
 substantive : that is to say, the being in an order 
 is made to be a reality for the thing as well as for 
 the ordering mind ; and the whole order is therefore 
 significant for the individual at any individual stage. 
 Hence A is said to be potentially B. This means 
 that ^ to ^ is a process which we view as a series of 
 states ; but so is lowest to highest in any case: relation 
 is a category for all, and only per accidens a special 
 category for some. The relating as such being the 
 same for all, why should it be more easy to say that 
 the acorn is potentially an oak, than to say mud 
 is potentially a man ? Yet it is easier (for Gassendi 
 and his contemporaries at least), because there are 
 real, and, as it were, closed circles. Within the 
 species we can understand growth, because it is 
 nutrition and assimilation of the like. Hence, in the 
 closed circle relation is expressible as potentiality. 
 But the definition of the circles comes from experi- 
 ence. Potentiality is therefore not a universal solvent. 
 This seems arbitrary, because the expansion of the 
 given circles is not limited : why should we stop 
 short at any but the most universal terms, say 
 matter, and make everything potentially everything
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 267 
 
 else ? It seems, indeed, that we ought not to stop 
 anywhere short of the mutually exclusive realities, 
 mind and matter. But Gassendi is opposed to the 
 whole frame of mind implied in this, and so far 
 from working up to this irrational stop at the differ- 
 ence of mind from matter, he works down from it 
 to a totally dijfferent conclusion. He does not admit 
 that the step from matter to mind is unique : he 
 does not admit that the diflference between two 
 substances is really greater than the difference 
 between radical forms of one substance : in any 
 composite there is an unanalysable addition, the 
 form, the being-what-it-is which is revealed only 
 synthetically in the function, the being of the whole 
 as whole. Now mind, he says, is nothing apart from 
 matter : hence mind plus matter is a functional unit. 
 Where is the marvel ? This complex produces this 
 result, and why should there not be this complex, 
 and with it this result ? If you say it is unique, 
 so is every other qualitative phenomenon qua 
 qualitative. 
 
 This is, I think, the crucial point of Gassendi's 
 thought, and he cannot be understood unless it is 
 grasped. It is exemplified in his whole treatment 
 of the universe of things. It is, moreover, an idea 
 capable of much expansion, but the expansion is 
 what it did not eret at the hands of Gassendi. He is 
 
 o 
 
 doubtless right in keeping quantity and quality apart, 
 right in realising the limits of mechanism, and yet 
 not suppressing the quantitative aspect. It is this 
 grasp of qualitative distinctions that saves him from 
 materialism, it saves him from trying to compromise 
 between mind and matter. But after all quantity
 
 268 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 and quality are only categories, both alike objective, 
 ways in which the world of objects can be thought 
 of, formulae for its analysis. There we find the 
 weak point, right at the heart of the whole scheme : 
 so long as the object remains unanalysed and mind 
 and matter are equally objective, so long as the 
 categories are applied to a world of crude objects 
 such that mind and matter are both equally objective, 
 we reach the limit ; and our opinion on the value 
 of this point decides our estimate of Gassendi. 
 Criticism, aided by the development of philosophy 
 can find flaws only too easily, so much so that it 
 is not worth while to suggest any : yet there are 
 still many who will doubtless find that they can 
 read Gassendi with sympathy and, with all his 
 faults, recognise that he combined, with a vast 
 knowledge of facts, a truly philosophical attempt 
 to reach the truth that is in them. 
 
 The philosophical writings of Gassendi perpetually 
 recall to our minds the works of Leibnitz and Lotze 
 both in regard to matter and form. We have already 
 shown that Gassendi is not to be passed over lightly 
 as a mere materialist, a supporter of what Lotze calls 
 ' evil materialism ' : we now require to see how our 
 author is related to the later Realists and how far 
 he may be regarded as anticipating their work. 
 
 Before entering into the details of this subject a 
 word or two must be said with regard to its dangers. 
 A moment's reflection will show that Leibnitz and 
 Lotze can hardly fail to differ one from the other 
 in their whole outlook with that difference which 
 Kant brought into philosophical work of every kind. 
 If we speak of Realism as though it were a line of
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 269 
 
 thought maintaining itself through an unbroken 
 succession of writers and uninfluenced by other lines 
 of thought, it will soon be apparent that the terms 
 we use are almost the only permanent elements ; 
 the letter abides but the spirit changes, and the 
 line of progress which thought follows under one 
 name is often the slow fulfilment of a circle that 
 places it at last adverse to its own starting point. 
 Whole passages in Leibnitz breathe the sentiments 
 of Gassendi : the Mikf'okosmus is planned with the 
 same comprehensiveness and in the same spirit as 
 the Physics of the Syyitagrtia : the reader leaves 
 them both with a strong sense of their likeness to 
 Gassendi. In following out the relations and the 
 differences of these writers I shall work with a 
 view chiefly to elucidate Gassendi and limit my 
 remarks to that scope, diverging into some general 
 remarks on the character of the periods under con- 
 sideration only so far as that purpose requires.
 
 CHAPTER II 
 
 LATER VIEWS 
 
 (a) LEIBNITZ 
 
 To minds of a certain type works such as those 
 of Gassendi are irritating. They continually arouse 
 the question ' Is this philosophy ? ' and cause a 
 vague unrest which it is difficult to assign to any 
 one feature or characteristic. It is in fact due to 
 the way in which Gassendi and men of his class 
 stop short of the goal for which they seem bound, 
 stop short of the unity which is demanded by our 
 aesthetic nature. Their reason for so doing is a 
 conscientious recognition that they have not suc- 
 ceeded in making their universe truly a One. No 
 unity of the type required was possible until the 
 objective sphere of experience was united to the 
 subjective by such recognition of unity as Kant 
 was able to reach. The influence of Kant will be 
 considered when we come to Lotze : the point is 
 introduced here because we have in Leibnitz, as 
 compared with Gassendi, a most significant point 
 of difference, the logical element. 
 
 Gassendi follows the tradition of his school. His 
 logic is a book of canons. We feel that when it 
 is closed its power is at an end. In Leibnitz, on
 
 PT. IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 271 
 
 the contrary, the logical principles are the essence 
 of a logical aspect of all things, and analysis and 
 synthesis as applied to things are so intimately 
 related to the forms of judgment that it would 
 seem as though we might say of the world of 
 Leibnitz that it is a translation of loQ-ic into 
 
 o 
 
 ontology. 
 
 There is still some doubt apparent in the litera- 
 ture of philosophy as to whether Leibnitz is to be 
 called an idealist or a realist. This is due probably 
 to the way in which the suppressed logic of Leib- 
 nitz o;ives his realism an idealistic character. What 
 Leibnitz actually does is to talk of a world of real 
 objects whose whole existence depends upon their 
 being given, as though that fact of being given 
 were not in itself as important a characteristic of 
 things as any other. Leibnitz is therefore clear on 
 the point that there are realities and on the in- 
 dividual worth of each separate reality ; but in so 
 far as he inadequately recognises the point of 
 contact between self and not-self, he naturally fails 
 to give sufficient consideration to its significance. 
 The origin of this error on the part of Leibnitz is 
 to be found in the fact that he comes to his world 
 of objects with a conceptual attitude — a desire to 
 analyse, and consequently a tendency to say what 
 a thing is without asking how it is. 
 
 At this point the reader will perhaps pause, 
 recalling the words of Lotze : ' What things are is 
 thus not incomprehensible to us, for that which is 
 in them they exhibit in their outer manifestation ; 
 how they can exist and can manifest themselves 
 anyhow is the universal enigma.' It would seem
 
 272 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 then that we ask too much in demanding from 
 Leibnitz more information as to how the thing 
 becomes. But it is not because Leibnitz gives us 
 no answer that we complain ; it is because his 
 answer is given from a prejudicial standpoint. 
 Spinoza had dissipated the individual : his assertion 
 ' omnis determinatio est negatio ' left the logical 
 activities of the mind with no focus and deprived 
 conception of its material. Leibnitz, as compared 
 with Spinoza, seems to restore to us our real world. 
 It may not be very hard^ or very solid, or very 
 matter of fact — it may indeed be ' idealistic ' in a 
 sense — but it is at any rate pluralistic and active. 
 Where then is the ground for complaint ? 
 
 In his treatment of the doctrine of induction 
 Leibnitz shows that he wholly underrated the philo- 
 sophic value of the moment of perception. The 
 consequence of this is that he is capable of treating 
 as a subjective construction what he has never shown 
 to be subjective in its nature : he invades the 
 whole region of the not-self with an army of 
 notions whose success depends entirely on accurate 
 information as to the character of the opposing 
 realities. In spite of the appearance of remaining 
 within the legitimate sphere of analysis, and evolving 
 in the closed cell of the monad a mental pano- 
 rama of reflected Being, Leibnitz really does no 
 such thing ; he goes forth into the world of 
 syntheses, and absorbs the advantages of experience 
 without acknowledgment or appreciation. 
 
 If it is ever possible to keep two parallel lines 
 of Reality and unite them in a pre-established 
 harmony, it must at least be done with the clear
 
 iv] GENERAL REVIEW 273 
 
 recognition that all the predicates of reality are only- 
 predicates of experiences, that the experiences may 
 be real, but the reality may, none the less, remain 
 aloof, a thing-in-itself. This would only be possible 
 after an analytic of experience : it is not possible 
 if the basis of the position is no more than analytic 
 forms of judgment, because the judgment and the 
 mental machinery employed in it all presuppose a 
 given. 
 
 To justify Leibnitz in treating the world of 
 physics as he did we require from him some analysis 
 of the given. We assert that he did not furnish 
 this, that in place of analysing the given he treated 
 it as knowable deductively, as an existence to 
 which we can dictate what it must be. He thus 
 gets beyond Gassendi very rapidly, but not very 
 securely. The preponderance given to logic promises 
 us a more penetrative insight into experience as a 
 subjective construction based upon real activities : 
 we hope for just that element which was lacking in 
 Gassendi, a deeper comprehension of the extent to 
 which the understanding makes nature ; but in this 
 we are disappointed, for the logical standpoint gives 
 us nothing but categories that we vainly and un- 
 critically re-apply to a world of objects already 
 manufactured and passed without question. 
 
 Further attention must be given to this point, 
 because it is the centre of our discussion of the 
 relations between Gassendi and Leibnitz. This can 
 be shown if we return to those categories of experi- 
 ence which are implicit in Gassendi's work. 
 
 The category of substance {v. p. 264) is used by 
 Gassendi as a form for the classification of what
 
 274 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 are commonly called ' things ' ; it includes also 
 those objects to which experience testifies that they 
 are 'outer.' Gassendi goes so far as to ignore 
 anything that falls beyond the focus of experience : 
 that which the thing does is the actuality of it, and 
 therefore the same as that which the thing is. But 
 it does not follow that my limitations are limitations 
 of the given : the more a writer insists that the 
 being of a thing is the same as its doing, the more 
 strictly is he compelled to admit that the existence 
 of all things is a matter of relations, and in a 
 relation only those capacities can be developed for 
 which both the terms are qualified. 
 
 In this connexion it is necessary to remember that 
 the post-Kantian philosopher usually works on a 
 method the inverse of that which the pre- Kantian 
 naturally took. Noiv it would be natural to regard 
 the whole X as the given from which A and B 
 might be analytically eliminated. Then it was more 
 natural to start with A and B and regard X as the 
 resultant of their relations. The consequence is that 
 the philosopher is compelled to work with terms 
 never completely defined. Spinoza provides for this 
 incomplete exhaustion of the relatum in the case of 
 God : the infinite with infinite possibilities stands 
 over against the other term of the relation as some- 
 thing transcendent and overlapping. If we have in 
 place of a monism a pluralism of reals, every real 
 entity must have these same characteristics so long 
 as it is presupposed as a possibility of relations and 
 not merely regarded as the explicit recognition of 
 what out of the relation is nothing. 
 
 Atomism is, on the face of it, a theory of real
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 275 
 
 ultimates capable of relation and composition. As 
 objects they have no right to such qualities as are 
 regarded as peculiarly subjective. It will therefore 
 not be possible to assert that the atoms as such have 
 any power of appreciating the relations in which they 
 stand : their ' elective affinities ' must be inner states, 
 but not perceptions. Gassendi often speaks as though 
 the analogy between attraction in the magnet and 
 the animal was a ground for speculation : he does 
 not use it as a proof that perception has rudimentary 
 forms below the level of animal life. In convertinor 
 the atom into the monad Leibnitz commits himselfl 
 to a position he cannot defend, for he asserts that j 
 powers or qualities found in aggregates are also found | 
 in simple bodies, and thereby destroys at a blow the 
 value of organisation as the ground of functions. , 
 
 The notion of ' organism ' is used by Leibnitz in 
 a purely occasionalistic manner. He is obviously 
 prepared to recognise degrees of organisation as 
 connected in some manner with degrees of function- 
 ing power, and graduates his scale of real things 
 in the form of a scale of substances in which new 
 and higher powers are correlated wuth complexity 
 of structure. But the fact of being organised was 
 never given by Leibnitz due importance and rank 
 among the perceptual facts which make up the world 
 of physics. The reason for this is to be found in the 
 work of Leibnitz as a whole. 
 
 Criticism of Leibnitz seems at present to be in 
 vogue. A glance at contemporary literature will 
 show us science and philosophy are both in arms 
 against him. It will be sufficient if we note here 
 a few salient points.
 
 276 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 We have already noted that the atomism of Leib- 
 nitz differs from that of Gassendi in so far as the 
 former suffuses his whole doctrine with a logical 
 tone and colours it with rationalism. The result is 
 that facts are ignored in the interests of forms of 
 thought. Hence (1) the law of continuity combined 
 with the notion of substance enables Leibnitz to pass 
 from perceived perceptions out to un perceived percep- 
 tions, without recognising that thought can thus 
 overrun its material in any direction and must curb 
 its tendencies within the limits of the given. (2) The 
 monad is an atom qualified by irrelevant adjectives. 
 The logical process which begins in stripping off 
 predicates from a subject leaves the subject bare : 
 it does not follow that there can be in nature a 
 substance stripped of qualities. The monad which 
 we are thus wrongly led to think of as simple, appears 
 on reflection to require to be complex. We are 
 always tempted to think that our ultimate element 
 must be capable of entering into all relations, and 
 therefore be itself simple and indeterminate. On the 
 contrary, the possibility of relations is, from the point 
 of view of the thing, not a negative but a positive 
 quality, and that which can enter into all relations, 
 like a man capable of occupying any post, must be 
 * highly qualified.' The intensive quality of the 
 monad may have appeared to Leibnitz to anticipate 
 this difficulty. It is however difficult to conceive 
 how inner or outer qualities are of use to beings 
 whose actuality is not affected though all relations 
 are destroyed. 
 
 The last word on Leibnitz must be a recognition 
 of his genius with a confession of his failure. If he
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 277 
 
 could have reduced his thought to a system it would 
 have been chastened to its advantage. As it is, 
 different lines of thought perpetually open up, and no 
 one of them is fully worked out. For this reason we 
 find flaws and chasms in the structure : matter is one 
 thing physically (prima materia) and another thing 
 psychically : continuity of kind as in the derivation 
 of consciousness from petites perceptions is linked 
 with discontinuity of being in the real world : sub- 
 jective idealism is perpetually breached by that going- 
 beyond-itself which is the one thing their rational- 
 istic author has denied the monads. 
 
 But if the whole fails to exhibit cohesion it has 
 never lacked inspiration and the power to inspire. 
 This I attribute to one quality which it exhibits, — 
 the grasp of unity as required for the being and the 
 understanding of a world. This unity Leibnitz does 
 not attain : his pluralism produces want of unity 
 both in the world as an objective existent and in our 
 thoughts as a reconstruction of it ; but he never loses 
 sight of it as a guiding principle, and is only pre- 
 vented from working it out by the notions of 
 substance and of concepts by which he was incessantly 
 hampered. 
 
 As the thought of a unity is the thought of a 
 whole which implicitly contains many parts capable 
 of being themselves brought into prominence, so the 
 thought of the world as a unity has an implicit 
 content whose nature is irrelevant so far as the 
 unity is concerned. There has for so long been a 
 rooted tendency to confine unity to material unity 
 that it may not be out of place to elaborate this 
 point.
 
 278 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 The unity of the individual is not affected by the 
 diverse nature of its parts. The possibility of self- 
 unification may be grounded in one or more charac- 
 teristics. It may be asserted that I could not be 
 a unity unless I had a nervous organism so developed 
 as to have one supreme centre. To this the reply 
 is that the genesis of a unitary being may thus lie 
 in a condition which must first be fulfilled, but the 
 unity, when there is unity, includes its plurality 
 without reference to anything but the possibility of 
 co-operation. A human organism is a unity whose 
 parts are different : not only is a heart not a liver, 
 but one corpuscle is not another : yet the reality of 
 the unity cannot be denied. The fact is that when 
 we speak of a unity we must hold it over against 
 a plurality, and all we require of the parts of a 
 unity is that they should not be capable of collapsing 
 one into another : they must retain what we require 
 of them, namely the power to fill out the whole to 
 which we refer the unity. 
 
 Thus ultimate identity of nature, if it meant 
 identity of being, w^ould ruin both concepts, of 
 unity and of plurality : if it does not mean identity 
 of being it means nothing, for two ' identical ' natures 
 must always differ by one simple quality, that of 
 not being each other. 
 
 Many of these points Leibnitz adumbrates. He 
 seems, however, never to have grasped the relation 
 of conceptual unification to the unity of the per- 
 ceptually given world. In a word, the idea of unity 
 ran away with him in the form of continuity or 
 persistence of identical natures : a reference to 
 experience as perceptual knowledge of the world 
 
 i
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 279 
 
 around us would have shown that unity is not 
 translatable through substance into being (giving 
 an ultimate One in kind), but only through co- 
 operation into cohesion. It is useless to assert that 
 unity of nature is presupposed in unity of action : 
 that heart and liver are not different but only 
 distinct, being really qualified to belong to the 
 unity by virtue of unity of nature. This is pure 
 inversion : it is from the effects that we must 
 judge the nature : kinds are only subdivisions of 
 the unity which is not material but formal, which 
 embraces all kinds in the unity of co-operation 
 constituting the organism of nature. 
 
 (b) LOTZE 
 
 The philosophy of Leibnitz appears both disjointed 
 and distorted. Lotze gives us a far more syste- 
 matic view of things, and the advance he makes 
 is considerable. 
 
 Among the advantages which he enjoyed over 
 his predecessors, that of inheriting the results of 
 Kant's labours must necessarily be ranked high. 
 With Kant the opposing tendencies of rationalism 
 and sensationalism were to some extent reconciled : 
 the perceptual order regained the importance 
 rationalism had striven to take from it, and the 
 conceptual order lost none of its significance as 
 organisation of our inner conscious life. Kant gave 
 to his followers two main points : primarily, the 
 necessity for a point of contact between the knower 
 and that which was destined to be known : 
 secondarily, the necessity of recognising that the 
 origin of the object is to be looked for in a rela-
 
 280 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 tion. This second point implies that henceforth 
 the term ' object ' must be taken in a new sense : 
 it can no longer denote that which is given for 
 consciousness, but only that which is given in con- 
 sciousness as being outer. 
 
 This view of the object is however not satisfactory 
 if we confuse the idea of a reality capable of rela- 
 tions with the idea of qualities as potential or 
 germinal relations. So far as concerns the distinc- 
 tion of substantia phenomenon from its ground, 
 Kant seems to have allowed this confusion to arise.. 
 He clearly thinks of our conscious life as a vessel 
 filled from the greater vessel of the Universe : our 
 limitations are the reason why there is a surplus of 
 being over and above the known. The distinction 
 of Being (Beent) from Existent does not save the 
 situation : for Being cannot be thought of as relation - 
 less being, and is therefore either merely undiscovered 
 existence or pure nothing. 
 
 It would not be necessary to labour this point 
 if it were not that our thought naturally inclines 
 to regard development as an unfolding of a unitary 
 existence. Whether the thinker regards develop- 
 ment as ultimately timeless, or believes that all 
 development is in a real time, he rarely if ever 
 gets to the idea that continuity of development is- 
 not the same as unity of being. It is however 
 not less a ' rational ' dogma to assert that the seed 
 is the plant than to assert that all development 
 is timeless, more geometrico. The crux in either 
 case is the regress to the Whole, But in the case 
 of the plant our statement does not really concern 
 the whole plant but the whole life-history of the
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 281 
 
 plant, and obviously omits for its own purposes 
 the continuous natural synthesis involved in the 
 real development expressed in the perceptual order. 
 But if we cannot fix the plant as a Whole, on 
 account of its length, so to speak, in respect of 
 time, we feel we can fix the Universe as a Whole 
 because it is always itself. To properly combat 
 this view requires more digression than is here 
 justifiable. I merely state that there is primarily 
 the notorious difficulty of saying the Universe 
 is at all (of course if it is a Universe we beg 
 the question of its unity by naming it thus), 
 and secondly, that our right to omit the element 
 of real time is very dubious. If we do not 
 omit it, we come to the other view, that all 
 things are a co-existent unity which maintains 
 itself by perpetual re-adjustment of its parts, and 
 moves on from state to state through time. It would 
 be easy at this point to say progresses rather than 
 moves, but there is no need to beg the question as to 
 whether the movement is for better or for worse. 
 
 Kant's analysis of the object, then, we regard as 
 faulty in so far as it implies that ' we only know 
 phenomena.' We consider that the phrase appear- 
 ance of the real should be abolished, and our world 
 should be called not an appearance of reality but 
 the real as it appears. None the less the work 
 of Kant leaves its abiding eff"ect in the impossibility 
 of going back to naive realism ; and not acknow- 
 ledging that the percipient mind is a real factor 
 in the process of appearing, is in fact the comple- 
 mentary element which allows the real to express 
 itself in the terms of knowledge.
 
 282 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. 
 
 Lotze's philosophy interests us in many ways : 
 the form and matter of the Mikrohosmus in parti- 
 cular challenge comparison with the Syntagma of 
 Gassendi. We now desire to see especially how the 
 details are handled in the light of the progress made 
 between the days of Gassendi and Lotze. For in 
 a sense Lotze returns to the standpoint of Gassendi : 
 he eliminates in many ways the rationalistic elements 
 which Leibnitz had introduced, and his line of 
 thought can in the main be regarded as continuing 
 that of Gassendi. Leibnitz had tried to ' unite 
 Democritus and Spinoza ' : subsequent workers had 
 to eliminate the Spinozistic element, and thus free 
 from its encumbrances the Democritian line of 
 development. 
 
 The atoms of Democritus were meant to be physi- 
 cal points. The elaboration of the idea of ' points ' 
 into a theory of physical, metaphysical, and mathe- 
 matical points was retrograde. The mathematical 
 points are not points in any relevant sense, and the 
 metaphysical points are physical points interpreted 
 through the concept of mathematical points. The 
 idea that they must be indivisible for thought is 
 irrelevant, because they are perceptual entities. We 
 may think of any unit as twice its own half, but it 
 does not follow that the perceptual datum can be 
 given as a plurality : if, on the contrary, it is never 
 so given we are right in declaring it to be indivisible, 
 i.e. a real unit. 
 
 Granted that the atom is a real unit, the question 
 arises, How are we to interpret this reality ? Our 
 reality as a whole will naturally be regarded as the 
 sum of its parts, allowing that it is not a mere
 
 IV.] • GENERAL REVIEW 283 
 
 aggregation but rather an organic totality. Conse- 
 quently we shall expect the characteristics predicated 
 of the totality to be predicated of the parts. Now 
 Lotze's idea of the totality is coloured with the 
 notion that our aesthetic demands are a reality, and 
 the necessity of regarding the Universe as a whole 
 is not to be divided from the necessity of regarding 
 it as a whole of a certain kind. He therefore finally 
 concludes that the atom is unextended, because this 
 hypothesis alone enables us to regard it as animated 
 throughout.^ This however, besides being highly 
 conjectural, seems also unnecessary. We have already 
 been told that atoms do not require to be homo- 
 geneous, but may enter into composition equally wxll 
 if they are heterogeneous.^ From this it has been 
 correctly deduced that unity does not imply identity 
 in the elements : unity is the form in which we inter- 
 pret the cohesion of heterogeneous elements through 
 elective affinity in any single apparent whole. It 
 is therefore clearly possible that different natures 
 may so combine that the resultant has a nature 
 which belongs to none of its parts. The emergence 
 of this new functional value is dependent on the 
 recognition of something more than mechanical rela- 
 tions. The something more which is thus required 
 is provided by substituting chemical for mechanical 
 laws. 
 
 The influence of chemistry upon constructive 
 thought is extremely important for this one reason, 
 that it forces into recognition the fact that, regarded 
 as we must regard it from the point of view of its 
 doing, the whole is more than the sum of its parts. 
 
 ^ MikroJcosmus, iii. ch. iv. Engl. Tran. p. 360. "^ Ibid. p. 35.
 
 284 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 Man is thus no more to be regarded as a macliine. 
 Lotze rightly recognises that vitality is grounded 
 in a synthesis of co-operating elements : it is not a 
 separate entity to be imported into a mechanical 
 organism at birth and exported at death. It is out 
 of this aspect of functional activity as dependent on 
 organisation that Lotze gets the right to some of his 
 most pregnant assertions, such e.g. as the assertion 
 that the soul is where it acts. He formulates it 
 most definitely when he opposes the idea that Life 
 is something permanent, *a higher force' controlling 
 the changes of the body. On the contrary, he says, 
 life and death are not opposed realities : ' for why 
 should we not from this phenomenon {i.e. of corrup- 
 tion) rather draw the other conclusion, that the 
 activity of life can last only so long as the chemical 
 composition of the body yields the necessary con- 
 ditions and that the corruption of death is nothing 
 else than a disturbance of that composition which has 
 now become visible, but by which perhaps long since, 
 though less obviously, the conditions of life have 
 been aflPected ? ' ^ 
 
 The phraseology of this passage clearly indicates 
 that we are to regard the ' composition ' as the ' con- 
 dition of life.' On another page^ Lotze states this 
 more definitely. He speaks of life as maintaining 
 itself through ' motive shocks,' which are ' yielded by 
 the processes of constant forming and reforming ' : 
 it is like burning coal, developed ' not through what 
 it was or through what it is to be, but through the 
 motion of the transition itself.' There is therefore 
 no longer any room for a ' vital force ' : 'in the 
 
 ^ Mikrokosmus, iii. ch. iv. Engl. Tran. p. 52. ^ Ibid. p. 74.
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 285 
 
 living body every chemical change that takes place 
 sets to work forces not before in existence and brings 
 others to a pause ; thus at each moment there is laid 
 for subsequent development a new foundation, such 
 as gives occasion sometimes for a continuance of prior 
 states, sometimes for an evolution into new ones, 
 sometimes by a combination of both, for expansion 
 into a far fuller manifestation of character and 
 activity.'^ 
 
 These passages show clearly the view taken of 
 life. We may now enquire into its degrees and 
 their relation. In the inorganic sphere we have 
 no development and no power of self-maintenance.^ 
 Plant and animal life are of one kind in this respect : 
 they exhibit reactions which may be described as 
 expressions of their natural conation toward self- 
 preservation. But animal life is distinguished by 
 sentiency and human life by the presence of mental 
 powers. We might then expect a scale of the form 
 a, a + h, a-^b + c ; but what we are actually given 
 is a scale of the form a, x{ = a + b), y( = x + c). 
 This form of the scale implies that each stage is 
 more than the lower stage plus a quantitative 
 addition : it is emphatically a new stage. 
 
 Lotze denies that we can construct the scale 
 upward : we cannot start from the lower form and 
 deduce the higher form from a consideration of the 
 possible combination of elements. On the contrary, 
 mental life forms a new datum : our culture ' shows 
 the interval between the two spheres of existence 
 [animal and human] to be so vast that apparently 
 the addition of a wholly new germ of development 
 
 1 Ibid. p. 83. 2 jf,ifi_ p, 79^
 
 286 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 is absolutely necessary to explain the superiority of 
 human culture.'^ Mind is thus set over against 
 soul, but ' we cannot return to the naivete of con- 
 ception that sees in psychic life and mind two 
 different and separate entities.' ^ We must not think 
 of body, soul, and mind as three entities of inde- 
 pendent value : our only reason for distinguishing 
 one from the other in the highest unity, that of 
 man, is the fact that they are given separately in 
 the universe, that animals have sentience without 
 mind, and plants have living bodies without either.^ 
 A- real connexion for these must therefore be found, 
 ' for, in whatever reason may consist, it is clear 
 that the soul cannot receive the gift of a new 
 faculty, unless it be so grounded in its constitution 
 that it either must of necessity be evolved from it, 
 or else mi2:ht be evolved should favourable condi- 
 tions supervene.' ^ 
 
 The ' new faculty ' is not a new entity. A psychic 
 substance Lotze rejects : such a phrase implies the 
 reification of what is only given as a group of 
 unique reactions, a living content that ' by its own 
 specific nature directly acquires the capacity to act 
 and be acted on,' and so masquerades as a substance 
 for ' the unwary thinker.' But the idea of a group 
 of reactions has its dangers also. We may be led 
 to ignore the agent itself, whereas ' we cannot make 
 mi7id equivalent to the infinitive to think, but feel 
 that it must be that which thinks ; the essence of 
 things cannot be either existence or activity ; it 
 must be that which exists and that which acts.'^ 
 
 ^ Mikrokosmus, iii. ch. iv. Engl. Trail, p. 532. ^ Jbid. p, 535. 
 
 ■^Ibid. p. 536. *Ib{d. p. 548.
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 287 
 
 This doctrine of mind shows clearly the three 
 phases of Lotze's philosophic thinking, namely the 
 occasionalistic, the idealistic, and the realistic. It 
 will be necessary to make a few remarks on these 
 separately. 
 
 (l) Crude occasionalism is self-condemned by its 
 abstractness. Over against a world in itself 
 purely material stands the purely psychical : their 
 unity of action is a parallelism of simultaneous 
 action : the ground of the coincidences is in a third 
 nature. This line of thought may be regarded as 
 wholly antiquated, and its many faults require no 
 resurrection. Among others, it overlooked the fact 
 that a given simultaneity of action is normally a 
 proof of reciprocity unless we have some a priori 
 reasons for assuming reciprocity impossible. In that 
 case we modify our view in the direction of a pre- 
 established harmony. This gives us a certain degree 
 of concreteness in so far as we reduce our sphere 
 of enquiry to the actually given agents : ultimate 
 questions however bring us to a third factor, the 
 creative activity in whose Will we ground all 
 unity of action. But here still the whole necessity 
 of an explanation lies in the presuppositions with 
 which we approach our subject ; and this presup- 
 position is, in these cases, the belief that substances 
 are in themselves opposed to relations. 
 
 The occasionalism which Lotze offers us is still 
 further modified by continuing the process which 
 makes the view concrete. To do this it is necessary 
 to merge the abstractions into a more and more 
 comprehensive unity. The differences in the given 
 must first of all be modified so that we no longer
 
 288 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. 
 
 oppose one kind of being to another : then the 
 unifying agency must be vested in the totality thus 
 formed, so that we are able to account for all 
 relatedness or reciprocity of action as possible when 
 the totality admits of it, and impossible when it 
 does not so admit of it. 
 
 I consider that Lotze makes a great advance on 
 the position of Leibnitz in many respects, but prin- 
 cipally in those directions in which his scientific 
 training made him a more judicious and compre- 
 hensive thinker. The effect of scientific training is 
 obvious in — (1) those elements of thought which 
 are due to biological and chemical studies ; (2) in 
 the truly scientific unwillingness to blur distinctions, 
 and call the higher the same as the lower, or the 
 lower itself ' potentially ' a higher form ; and (3) 
 in the concept of unity, as somehow requiring to 
 be expressed in terms of action and not substance. 
 But while progress is manifest in these points, the 
 results cannot be of permanent value unless the 
 principles which are used bring us safely to the end. 
 
 (2) In occasionalism proper all action, looked at 
 by itself, is disjointed. In the doctrine of Leibnitz 
 it is so connected as to form chains of parallel 
 activities. The series of actions start from points 
 that have a fixed amount of separation, and they 
 maintain this separation throughout. But we refuse 
 to accept this parallelism as ultimate : we do not 
 want to think of one rail as merely accompanying 
 another, but of two rails as so accompanying each 
 other that they form what we rightly call one 
 railway line. The unity we require is not approxi- 
 mation, rather the maintenance of the distance is
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 289 
 
 essential to it. If our lines converge when pro- 
 duced ' ever so far,' they cannot serve our purpose : 
 they destroy their own reality by destroying their 
 significance. And as our rails cease to be a railway 
 line if they converge, so our self and our not-self 
 can only come to insignificance and unreality if they 
 lose their distance and merge. 
 
 This metaphor, though quite a legitimate adapta- 
 tion of Leibnitz's idea of the two clocks, is not 
 perhaps very clear. It is intended to make think- 
 able the notion of a unity which holds together a 
 plurality in such a way as does not contradict the 
 plurality, but rather insists on the plurality as the 
 one thing essential to the unity. This I take to 
 be the proper meaning of unity if taken concretely 
 or in direct relation to a content which it makes 
 no attempt to annihilate. 
 
 It seems to me that in his advance from 
 Occasionalism Lotze reached an idealism which was 
 not compatible with the fundamental idea of the 
 occasionalistic phase of thought. That fundamental 
 idea is that activity of one kind cannot become 
 activity of another kind : lines of activity do not 
 cross : material activity is never mental activity. 
 To this fundamental idea Occasionalism was itself 
 faithless more than once when it tried to run the 
 lines back to that ' ever so far,' in which they 
 might be thought to have met. To carry material 
 actuality back to abstract points and mental activity 
 back to the point at which it is at least so abstract 
 as to have lost its conscious characteristics, is to 
 yield up our clear convictions to the illusions of 
 an indefinite perspective. So crude an error cannot
 
 290 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt, 
 
 rashly be attributed to Lotze : whatever his errors are 
 they cannot but be refined, subtle, and significant. Yet 
 that his occasionalism is modified by strong idealism 
 cannot be denied, and it may be that the idealism 
 completes without improving the occasionalism. 
 
 As there is a danger that the following remarks 
 may be due to a misunderstanding of Lotze, I 
 shall not attempt to pad out my interpretation of 
 his thought with selected quotations : if the general 
 impression is wrong the selection of definite phrases 
 out of a book is only the addition of insult to 
 injury. I state my own view and leave it to the 
 reader to consult Lotze. 
 
 The vice of every system of philosophy is 
 always some degree of abstraction. From the 
 multitude of abstract points of view we trust we 
 are slowly arriving at a concrete view which shall 
 do justice to reality as we live it. Usually the 
 abstract view is patently an intrusion of the 
 influences of study : thought naturally occupies a 
 predominant place in a system which its author 
 has had to think out : less frequently it is an 
 intrusion of temperament, or a mere reaction from 
 the tyranny of the abstract thinker to a full-blooded 
 view of things. In Spinoza we recognise the retiring 
 thinker : in Leibnitz we see the eff"ect of mathematical 
 and logical thought mixed with the busy life of the 
 man of affairs, and the influence of relations in 
 which caution and impenetrability are of first 
 importance. In Lotze we have equally the effects 
 of scientific training, relieved however of any barrier 
 to frankness, and united with a strong ethical and 
 aesthetical tendency. 
 
 I
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 291 
 
 The ethical temperament, if that term may be 
 used, is on its psychological side prone to believe : 
 the aesthetical is prone to value form : the combina- 
 tion of the two makes possible a transcendent point 
 of view which grasps at form with a strong psycho- 
 logical conviction that it must have real active 
 value. The remarkable passage in which Lotze 
 pleads for the animation of nature is a shock to 
 the reader in its betrayal of new and startling- 
 elements in the author's idea of a constructive 
 philosophy. Apart from the particular point, which 
 we do not intend to discuss, the passage is the 
 first awakening of antagonism in a critical reader 
 who will at once proceed to ask whether the whole 
 construction is built on this foundation. He will, 
 I think, find that it is. 
 
 The crucial point in the idealism of Lotze is the 
 possibility of constructing and defending the unity 
 of the Whole. The beginning is made from the 
 Kantian element, the phenomenal character of the 
 matter of thought. Kant's view is modified in so 
 far as the doing which we know is related to the 
 being, the that-which-does, in an intimate way, such 
 as does not hold of noumena and phenomena : from 
 this it follows that the appearance is the life of 
 the real rather than its output, the actual doing 
 rather than the product of its work. It follows 
 also from the Kantian element that our construction 
 of reality is itself reality, real doing, though not 
 creative activity. In this concrete point of view 
 is involved the idea that our feelings, cravings, 
 and inspirations are reality, which is the justifica- 
 tion for demanding that reality should be presented
 
 292 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 as satisfying that craving. As we have a craving 
 for unity and form we can assert that Reality is 
 both one and formed. We see the force of the 
 argument : we ask, what is its value ? 
 
 To begin with — what is this craving ? Is it ever 
 universal, and if not, does the craving for unity in 
 particular spheres justify an advance to a universal 
 unity ? The personal element is so manifest here 
 that if consciousness cannot be shown to have that 
 craving as part of its own nature the whole position 
 is endangered. And it must be granted that con- 
 sciousness has not got it qua consciousness. To get 
 it at all we must take consciousness as intimately 
 bound up with impulse, will, and individual purpose, 
 and each of these elements, while it enriches the 
 notion of consciousness, draws me further away 
 from the concept of a Whole. I cannot admit that 
 impulse proceeds wholly from consciousness, or 
 that will is entirely guided by reason, or that 
 the unity I desire is capable of projection away 
 from my individual scope to a hyper-individual 
 Whole. 
 
 Reflection on the history of thought confirms the 
 belief that ultimate unity is generally made accept- 
 able by withdrawing oneself from the immediate 
 conditions of life. Tradition ascribes this character 
 to the philosopher, and the history of philosophy is 
 a record of attempts to reach the higher truth by 
 climbing down. Lotze gives us a fruitful idea in 
 the notion of a whole whose parts are unified by 
 reciprocal action. But here again he seems to have 
 overstrained his parallel, which I take to be human 
 society. In his war against abstractions he notes
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 293 
 
 the hypostatising tendency expressed in such phrases 
 as ' the mind of the people,' ' the spirit of the times.' 
 He does not however seem to have fully estimated 
 the value of these indications or seen how far they 
 show that a generalisation expressed in a general 
 term may be the sign of a real conceptual unity 
 which in spite of its reality is not capable of action 
 or reaction. Now, if unity lies in significance, does 
 not the unity of anything partake essentially of the 
 nature of concepts or ideas ? And if so, is not the 
 unity the one point about things of which nothing 
 can be said in respect of action or reaction ? This, I 
 think, must be allowed, and the consequence follows 
 that in a world of action and reaction unity must be 
 irrelevant. 
 
 The point can be stated more clearly and directly, 
 but I have put it in this form because that is the line 
 of argument which Lotze suggests, and which seems 
 to me to apply to him most aptly because it is the 
 inversion of his own progress. The simpler and 
 clearer way is to assert that the unity of the Whole 
 implies a consciousness for which the Whole is a 
 unity. This leads us to the idea of a God. But if 
 God is outside our whole there must conceivably be 
 a ' higher unity ' giving a whole which comprises 
 God. Either therefore the Whole is not truly the 
 Whole or there is an infinite progress of wholes con- 
 stituted by presentation to a unifying agency which 
 is merged with them in ever higher and higher 
 wholes. 
 
 We now seem to have reached a reductio ad 
 absurdum. As stated, it is such a reductio ; but 
 the absurdity consists in the inner contradiction due
 
 294 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 to calling that the Whole which we at the same 
 time do not make all inclusive. This contradiction 
 indicates that the thought movement has become 
 involved in itself. At the same time there emerges 
 ^n idea which is fruitful and which was partially 
 expressed in the doctrine of monads. The monad 
 is a unity : the ruling monad is also a unity : this 
 latter unity includes plurality, and is therefore pro- 
 perly a unity : the mere monad as simple nature 
 ought not to be called a unity at all. Now, leaving 
 out other implications of the term monad, we may 
 say that the idea of progressive wholes comprehend- 
 ing at each stage the lower wholes, is justifiable. 
 We associate with development range of adaptation, 
 and increased range of adaptation is the objective 
 manifestation of increased organisation of either 
 physical or psychical powers. At each stage the 
 being comprehends a wider plurality, and the scale 
 of being is capable of gradation on this basis. 
 
 But is there any unity which is not unity for a 
 mind ? If we say no, there is no course open but 
 to set over against our Whole a mind for which it is 
 one. This would be a finite God. Not being able 
 to comprehend a world that sums itself any more 
 than a series of feelings that sum themselves, I am 
 unable to see how a pantheistic solution helps us. 
 On the contrary, if I conceived unity to be necessary 
 to the existence of the world, I should deduce from 
 that unity the being of God, and admit that the 
 unity was not only known but also felt and willed, 
 but I could not admit that the world was the same 
 as God, and therefore should not admit that the 
 will was omnipotent. Thus the mere assertion of
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 295 
 
 unity seems to lead us back into a transcendental 
 dualism. 
 
 The conclusion of the whole matter is that unity 
 is meaningless unless that which is unified is unified 
 by some mind. In the first instance the unity will 
 be that of my mind, and we must start from that. 
 
 Now I take it that in my mind unity is the 
 product of purpose. I do not consciously unify, but 
 I do consciously subordinate : the tendency is to 
 think in what respects the one is many rather than 
 how the many can be one. This is due to the 
 primacy of our practical life, in which the end is 
 given with all its plurality implicit. In action this 
 is obvious : the end is first and the discovery of 
 means subserves it. In the world of things it may 
 be less evident, but that which I call function is 
 ultimately the power to fulfil my end or purpose, 
 and the object as I know it is the manifestation in 
 perception of the thing that has the function. What 
 it is to itself I cannot know and need not ask. 
 
 It seems to me futile to speak of all existence as 
 animated, or talk of the ' experience of the atoms ' 
 as Lotze does, if the nature of the whole cannot be 
 determined. It is only as parts of a whole that the 
 parts have any claim to these qualities, and if we 
 fail to construct our whole so as to get a new edition 
 of the old doctrine of a world soul (which Lotze 
 confessedly aims to do) the consequences dependent 
 on that proof must fail also. 
 
 Human society, coming last, seems the culminating 
 point of all development, and a revelation of the 
 significance of all lower forms of life. In it we have 
 the fullest exhibition of reciprocal activity. But its
 
 296 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 unity is dependent on mind, and only a spurious 
 
 analogy can enable us to regard the universe as a 
 
 society. If we are not tempted to think of the 
 
 material world as associated atoms, we may yet 
 
 feel an inclination to regard it as teleologically 
 
 designed ; we should then have formal unity of 
 
 purpose among diverse actions. But here again it 
 
 seems impossible to show that there is one supreme 
 
 end, unless the whole is a unity ; or that the whole 
 
 is a unity, unless there is a supreme end. These 
 
 ideas are so far implicated that a plurality of being 
 
 necessitates a plurality of ends. It is equally wrong 
 
 to reject or to accept teleology as usually advocated. 
 
 The ethical view is right in emphasising the fact 
 
 that there are ends in the world. But these ends 
 
 arise with consciousness, are brought by us into the 
 
 world, and take their place as forces because our 
 
 mind directs our action. The hierarchy of ends is 
 
 the ideal counterpart of the hierarchy of wholes, and 
 
 each whole which exists for a mind is dominated by 
 
 an end. But that there should be an end of ends 
 
 seems unnecessary : we do not seek to unify ends, 
 
 we seek to multiply them in their diversity : the 
 
 progress of society is a perpetual production of minds 
 
 which become more concrete in every generation, 
 
 each one more capable of interpreting through itself 
 
 the end for its society, and thereby increasing the 
 
 number of ends that are efficient factors in life. 
 
 Self-preservation is the root from which spring all 
 
 ends, and if the higher organism of society seems 
 
 to have its need of preservation and its end we must 
 
 not forget that its existence depends largely on the 
 
 extent to which individuals realise themselves by
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 297 
 
 negation. Is it conceivable that for the end of ends 
 negation is equally necessary? Leibnitz thought so 
 when he limited the existent to the compossible. 
 We too may think so if we admit that our totality 
 has emerged from a crowd of possible totalities by 
 a species of selection. If we are not prepared to 
 sublimate our conceptions in this way but return 
 to the world of unfulfilled purposes and unsatisfied 
 desires, let us bravely acknowledge that all things 
 need not work together for good, that for such 
 adjustment as we do achieve or help others to achieve 
 we are grateful each to each, and each to all ; but 
 at the same time 
 
 'could you and I with Him conspire 
 To grasp this sorry Scheme of Things entire, 
 Would we not shatter it to bits, and then 
 Remould it nearer to the Heart's Desire ? ' 
 
 (3) In addition to these points of view we have 
 in Lotze what may be called a realistic element. 
 To explain this is, I think, impossible : to explain 
 it away is unjustifiable. It is in opposition to 
 Panlogism that Lotze retains ' nuclei,' irreducible 
 elements, in his system of experience. This is the 
 Leibnitzian factor retained against the Spinozistic 
 trend : it is also the Democritean element preserved 
 through Leibnitz for succeeding writers. No defini- 
 tion of these nuclei is forthcoming : they are 
 primarily reached from the standpoint that all 
 determination is not negation ; that thought is a 
 system of relations, but reality includes over and 
 above relations the relata. 
 
 To define these nuclei is impossible, because 
 thought in its progress moves away from the
 
 298 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 immediate point of contact given in sensation, moves 
 away from the stimulus in which they are revealed, 
 and in working up its material ignores existence 
 in order to concentrate itself upon significance. 
 The nuclei are in this sense the irrational factors. 
 
 It is not necessary here to do more than draw 
 attention to this point. The preservation of these 
 nuclei is of course one of the ways in which Lotze 
 defends the content of common consciousness against 
 such idealistic systems as seem to him to dissolve 
 reality into the thin air of pure thought. His 
 general attitude toward this point must be under- 
 stood by reference to Kant's views as expressed in 
 the Critique of Pure Reason. We must also bear 
 in mind the fact that pluralism grounds itself in 
 some measure on the impenetrability of the indi- 
 vidual consciousness, an idea which leads us to think 
 of individual minds as being to themselves more 
 than they can ever be to others. Hence the monad 
 with its dual existence, as it is in itself and as it 
 is in other monads in which it is represented. 
 Hence, too, in more refined forms, the idea that to 
 be perfectly intelligible is not to be thought but 
 to be thinkable, an idea expressed by Lotze when 
 he speaks of knowledge as a relation which would 
 be destroyed if the thinker could he that which is 
 thought, and wholly absorbing into himself the 
 object, exhaust not only the intelligibility but also 
 the being of that which is known. 
 
 Criticism of this view would lead us to consider 
 the claims of a higher unity. This criticism will 
 not be attempted, for it is our immediate purpose 
 to accept Lotze as he is, and only indicate how he
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 299 
 
 remains in the mean position between the extremes 
 of an idealism for which thought seems to exhaust 
 being and a realism for which thought seems to 
 confront an object only partly intelligible. The 
 peculiar difficulty which Lotze creates for us lies 
 in the extent to which the idealism is carried. 
 For the nuclei certainly seem to be no more than 
 nuclei of sensations, and it is only in so far as these 
 have a peculiar unity which is given to us by the 
 supersensible ground of objects, and not given by 
 us to objects, that they maintain the character of 
 being more than phenomena. They cannot be 
 ' matter ' in the crude sense, and if they are the 
 matter of thought they seem to be ultimately sub- 
 jective affections in a sense that makes it difficult 
 to resist a progress toward pure idealism. Lotze's 
 refusal to make the advance must be ascribed to his 
 idea of the worth of the individual, which is so 
 bound up with the notion of consciousness that it 
 becomes necessary to re-interpret the idea of the 
 nuclei on the analogy of the individual consciousness 
 as non- spatial units that maintain themselves in a 
 unity of co-operation without fusion. 
 
 The revulsion which invariably follows excessive 
 systematisation seems to indicate that if ever a 
 ' stable equilibrium ' is attained by thought, it will 
 have more of the character of the mean position 
 than of either extreme. For this reason a peculiar 
 interest attaches to the line of thought whose last 
 great representative is Lotze. It may seem at first 
 sight paradoxical that realism should emerge finally 
 as idealistic ; but, from the first, atomism com- 
 bines with realism an idealistic element, and the
 
 300 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 preponderance of idealism finally is a natural result 
 due to the character of our progress in the realm 
 of thought. 
 
 Seeley has pointed out the way in which History 
 has gradually refined its content. At first it is a 
 complicated mass such as we find it in the times 
 of Livy or Pliny : from this mass various elements 
 detach themselves and evolve into independence : 
 natural history, for example, and political economy 
 are branches that have struck root and grow for 
 themselves, related to rather than dependent on the 
 residuum which now takes the place of the original 
 whole. In a similar way the progress of the sciences 
 has slowly depleted philosophy of its original con- 
 tent and at the same time defined its central 
 elements and true scope. A comparison between 
 such a magnum opus as that of Gassendi and the 
 worth of a modern philosopher shows the eff'ect of 
 progressive specialisation. It suggests also the ques- 
 tion, What is to be ultimately the real matter of 
 philosophy in the strict sense ? 
 
 The answer must be, in a sense, what it has 
 always been, that philosophy co-ordinates and 
 systematises the results of the special sciences. 
 There is however a strong and not unjustifiable 
 tendejicy to think that the peculiar function of 
 philosophy is the explanation of the -possibility of 
 the objects with which the sciences deal : in other 
 words, philosophy is epistemology. In any case it 
 seems clear that the duty of systematisation which 
 falls upon philosophy in no wise compels the philo- 
 sopher to unify his construction beyond the point 
 which his material will admit. That is to say, the
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 301 
 
 emphasis must be on co-ordination rather than 
 systematisation, and philosophy mistakes its function 
 if it in any way undertakes to dictate results to 
 the special sciences, as it has notoriously done in 
 some cases. We must, it seems, come back to the 
 view of philosophy as a dialectic of results, a sifting 
 of ends. Above all things, it must follow whither- 
 soever the w4nd carries it, and not pre-determine its 
 haven in the face of all the forces upon which it 
 relies for progress. 
 
 Philosophy is then more than mere epistemology. 
 But the epistemological problem is undoubtedly its 
 own peculiar centre. Upon the decision of the nature 
 of reality it centres its vital energies, and on this 
 point we seem to-day to have arrived at a temporary 
 decision that ' idealism based on realism ' is the 
 position which must be accepted for the present, 
 though we may hope it is not the last standpoint. 
 
 The reason why no further progress is possible is 
 that as yet the ' nucleus,' as Lotze understood it, 
 remains unresolved. However much may be done 
 to show that objects are ideal, that the ultimate 
 is a unit ideal in its character, the fact remains that 
 the unity characteristic of an existent thing is always 
 a unity whose actuality does not come from the 
 subjective side. It need not be disputed that a 
 thing is a complex of universals ; but this cannot 
 blind us to the fact that the reason for any one 
 object being this particular complex is to be found 
 in a determination of our activity which comes to 
 us, in perception, and does not go forth from us. 
 
 The realistic element then must not be over- 
 looked or ignored. But to advocate realism is not
 
 302 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [ft. 
 
 to advocate materialism in any form. This may- 
 be taken as self-evident. The formula, ' no object 
 without a subject,' is the last word on that point. 
 But neither is the advocacy of an idealism based 
 on realism any ground for reaching a monism on the 
 idealistic side. In one of its aspects, the formula 
 quoted above means no unity without a conscious- 
 ness for which the unity exists. And while 
 materialism generates its peculiar monism by ignor- 
 ing this, idealism advances to its monism by an 
 equal denial of the truth of the formula only 
 obscured by greater subtlety. For extreme idealism 
 expresses the unity of the whole under the form of 
 thought unifying itself, which involves the presen- 
 tation of thought to thought, or a thought that 
 thinks itself. It is only in default of an attempt 
 to work out this idea that it seems plausible. On 
 further consideration it becomes a regress to infinity 
 just as much as the constitution of a whole by pre- 
 sentation to the mind of God proved an infinite 
 process. The question of the reality of time is the 
 inner point which wrecks idealism of this type. 
 For the assertion of timeless thought is a deduction 
 from the concept of what such a totality would be 
 if there weye such a totality. In experience how- 
 ever we find a sequence of events which is not a 
 mere logical interdependence, but an actual order. 
 Time may, and I think we are safe in saying must, 
 be regarded as subjective ; but order in time implies 
 over and above the subjective form an extra-subjec- 
 tive determination. 
 
 These subjects are large, and deserve further 
 elaboration. For the present I only desire to
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 303 
 
 indicate some of the reasons which seem to force 
 one back from the extremes to a middle course 
 of some kind. To define that middle course pro- 
 perly, it would be necessary to write a metaphysic. 
 Gassendi would help but little, for two obvious 
 reasons : he has no epistemology, and his idealistic 
 tendencies are too embryonic, as they were bound 
 to be so long as he could neither estimate the 
 significance of the possibility of objects nor make 
 up his mind as to the nature of time and space. As 
 I have indicated above, criticism finds him an easy 
 victim from this point of attack. His weaknesses are 
 apparent ; the interesting point about his work is 
 the way in which it defines problems still unsolved. 
 If we look in modern philosophy for a match to 
 Gassendi, we shall probably find the nearest approach 
 to one in G. H. Lewes. His ' Reasoned Realism ' is 
 very much akin to ' Empirical Realism,' as used 
 above of Gassendi (v. Problems of Life ajid Mind, 
 I. 176). Spencer's position is defined by Lewes as 
 'Transfigured Realism' (p. 192), 'for that theory 
 professes to be a theory of Perception, and declares 
 Perception to be symbolical ; whereas, according to 
 the Principles here expounded. Perception being the 
 resultant of two factors, internal and external, the 
 conclusion deduced is that the object thus felt 
 exists precisely as it is felt : existing for us only 
 in Feeling, its reality is what we feel. . . . Percep- 
 tion, because it is a resultant, not a symbol, does 
 not alter the Real : on the contrary, the object 
 only is to us what we feel it to be — it exists in 
 that relation.' Lewes' language is somewhat inaccu- 
 rate : a few lines lower he says, ' this particular thing
 
 304 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 in this particular relation is what it is in this 
 relation, i.e. what it is felt to be.' Here ' thing ' 
 is put in place of ' object,' and which of the two 
 terms should be used I cannot say : if Lewes meant 
 ' thing,' the position is very like Gassendi's ; shall 
 we say ' no better than Gassendi's ' ? If he means 
 that 'thing' and 'object' are identical (except in 
 so far as the thing has more relations than it realises 
 with us), the position is one that Gassendi might 
 have endorsed : for that the real is the existent 
 which reveals itself to the senses, and has more 
 reality (in its unrelated self) than our senses are 
 adequate to, is just what he tries to say. 
 
 But we cannot extend to Lewes the consideration 
 which Gassendi deserves on account of his dis- 
 advantages. When Lewes says ' the object thus 
 felt exists precisely as it is felt,' he is simply re- 
 funding into both terms of the relation the product 
 of their relatedness : he might just as well say 
 that hydrogen and oxygen have each of them all 
 the properties of water. It may be true that per- 
 ception does not, as a process, alter, that is vitiate, 
 reality ; but that statement leaves it open to us to 
 regard the perception as a development of the real 
 grounds of perception and, as such, a process vital 
 to the real. In trying to get away from the notion 
 that being phenomenal is being unreal, Lewes has 
 fallen into the other pit and proves that perception 
 has no real ground : for if reality does not develope 
 in perception, its indifference amounts to non- 
 existence. With Lewes perception seems to be a 
 relation in which both terms are indifferent, and 
 that is not conceivable. If perception involves a
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 305 
 
 subjective advance from mere sensation to definite 
 apprehension, it must also involve an objective 
 advance from the mere stimulus to the true object. 
 
 Gassendi would be in principle nearer to Lewes 
 than to Spencer on the question of perception. It 
 is interesting to think over the points of resemblance 
 between the Synthetic Philosophy and the Syiitagma 
 Philosophicum. The scheme is so similar : the 
 matter so different. The progress of two centuries 
 is condensed in their differences. But the critical 
 question of the nature of the object-in-itself seems 
 to receive an answer from Spencer less acceptable 
 than that of Gassendi. We are however precluded 
 from discussion upon details by a primary difference 
 which completely swamps all similarity. This con- 
 sists in the deductive character of Spencer's synthetic 
 philosophy. In contrast to this Gassendi's method 
 is reductive. It is indeed true that Spencer gives 
 away his deduction by omitting that most important 
 element, the transition from inorganic to organic : 
 on consideration however it will be clear that the 
 deduction has really failed to vitally connect any 
 higher stage with a lower. If the deduction were 
 really successful at any point the evolutionary 
 doctrine could have passed from a method to a 
 theory, and attained that intuitive insight which, 
 as Leibnitz foresaw, would make it prophetic. 
 Spencer was overweighted with the possibilities of 
 a doctrine of Force : Gassendi was saved from that, 
 possibly by absence of temptation. 
 
 We cannot afford to overlook in modern philo- 
 sophy the recognition which scholasticism is receiving. 
 The best scholastic philosophy was marked l)y a
 
 306 PHILOSOPHY OF GASSENDI [pt. 
 
 firm grasp on certain ultimate points and by clear 
 if somewhat formal definitions. Its relation to 
 religion put it in close contact with the deepest 
 thought of all ages, while it tended to keep aloof 
 the encroaching sciences. While therefore it erred 
 in dogmatically asserting itself as an authority in 
 spheres over which its formulae had no jurisdiction 
 either by nature or origin, it at the same time 
 retained intact, by force of circumstances, what 
 modern philosophy is striving to redeem from the 
 grasp of an apparently all-victorious science. The 
 points which it thus retained, uncritically but 
 resolutely, were the reality of the spiritual and 
 the necessity of a creator. 
 
 The creative factor we still must have. The 
 concept of God is one of those concepts which suc- 
 cessive ages refine. But however much we refine 
 the idea, it cannot be wholly refined away. The 
 elimination of sensuous and imaginative elements is 
 only a purification : as culture advances, the con- 
 struction which we put upon the idea advances from 
 the crudeness of anthropomorphism to other forms 
 which correspond to the higher mental level of the 
 race. And as at one extreme the concept of God, 
 so at the other the concept of matter is perpetually 
 refined and re-edited. But neither seems as yet to 
 have reached the vanishing point, and however com- 
 prehensive our scheme of development, it retains the 
 three movements of a given which developes, a form 
 of development which implies more than mere 
 mechanism, and a mind without which the develop- 
 ment cannot have come to its recognition. 
 
 The first is the matter. The second is the possi-
 
 IV.] GENERAL REVIEW 307 
 
 bility of being intelligible, which must be reluctantly 
 allowed. The third is mind. As regards the second, 
 it must not be over-emphasised at present. To 
 assert that the given is purely intelligible overlooks 
 faults ; to assert that it is intelligence, leads to con- 
 fusion. For while it might be called ' intelligible ' 
 through and through, if we had any knowledge of 
 a mind for which it was thus intelligible, in the 
 absence of such knowledge we have to confess that 
 what is not given to our intelligence as intelligence 
 is as much an unintelligible as though there were 
 no such mind. And this limitation to which the 
 absence of any omniscience which we can show forces 
 us, leaves an irrational element which is foreign to us, 
 however much we prophesy its final elimination. 
 
 The attempt to remove this from the ethical side 
 is premature. The ethical import of the whole is 
 not a valid ground for universal statements, so long 
 as the whole is not given as such. A view which 
 makes the whole a self-revelation of a Divine mind 
 moves in a circle, constructing the concept of that 
 mind to support its own correlative, the Whole 
 viewed as a One intelligible and ethical in character. 
 It is sounder to regard ethical characteristics as not 
 ' cosmic,' else our will and our thought must be 
 regarded as identical with that which we attribute 
 to God, whereas Spinoza's determination of the 
 voluntas and cognitio Dei as only negatively deter- 
 minable, must be regarded as the true logical position.
 
 INDEX 
 
 Activity, 162. 
 
 Analysis, value of, 178. 
 
 Anima, 106 (v. Soul). Ratioualis, 
 
 142. 
 Animals, how classified, 99. 
 Appetitus, 153. 
 Atoms : as described by 
 
 Democritus, xxi. 
 
 as hyper-sensuous, xxxii, 52. 
 
 how different, 64. 
 Atomism, xvii. 
 
 its origins, xix. 
 
 of Democritus, xx-xxii. 
 
 as philosophy, xxiv, 255, 274. 
 
 its revival, 245. 
 
 in Leibnitz, 276. 
 Attraction, 62, 119. 
 Avicenna, 30 n., 176. 
 
 Bacon, 11. 
 
 Causality, 57. 
 Cause, efficient, 55. 
 Chymici, 24, 51. 
 
 their elements, 177. 
 
 criticism of, 178. 
 Clifford, W. K., 117. 
 Compositio, 136. 
 Copernicus, 29. 
 Courage, 203. 
 Cupiditas, 157. 
 
 Declination, xxxi. 
 note on, 230. 
 
 Democritus. 
 
 his doctrine, xx-xxiii. 
 
 referred to, 52. 
 Descartes, xxxix. 
 
 his logic, 11. 
 
 relation to Gassendi, 251. 
 
 Empiricism. 
 
 Gassendi's relation to, 12, 251. 
 Epicurus, xvii. 
 
 relation to atomism, xviii. 
 
 life and teaching, xxv-xxxvi. 
 
 Logic, xxvii, 3. 
 
 Physics, XXX. 
 
 Psychology, xxxiii, 109, 121. 
 
 on imagines, 77. 
 
 on origin of laws, 204. 
 
 referred to, 52, 56, 101, 104, 
 167 n., 185, 198, 225, 231. 
 Eternity, 46. 
 Experience : meaning of, 251, 253. 
 
 Faculties : nature of, 69, 115. 
 
 Gassendi : his times, xxxix, 246. 
 character, xxxix. 
 life, xl-xlv. 
 Logic, 1. 
 Physics, 19. 
 
 on plurality of worlds, 22. 
 on World Soul, 23, 140. 
 on theories of the Universe, £8. 
 use of categories, 29, 35, 257, 264 
 . on space, 34.
 
 INDEX 
 
 ^ 
 
 309 
 
 Gassendi : 
 on time, 40. 
 eternity, 46. 
 matter, 49. 
 the atom, 52-64. 
 efficient causes, 55. 
 pure causality, 57. 
 local motion, 60. 
 attraction, 62, 119. 
 qualities, 66. 
 
 nature of faculties, 69, 115. 
 gravity, 72. 
 light, 74. 
 
 visible species (imagines), 76. 
 Generation or Becoming, 83. 
 magnet, 92, 115, 119. 
 plants, 95. 
 
 classification of animals, 99. 
 teleology, 100. 
 de anima, 106. 
 the human soul, 111. 
 origin of soul, 113. 
 perception, 115, 123. 
 sensation, 116, 121. 
 mind-stuff theory, 118. 
 his scale of Being, 127, 263. 
 imagination, 129. 
 simple apprehension, 135. 
 compositio, 136. 
 Ratio Sensitiva, 137. 
 intellectus, 142. 
 appetitus, 153. 
 cupiditas, 157. 
 pleasure-pain, 157. 
 activity (vis motrix), 162. 
 vocal sounds, 165. 
 nature of life, 168. 
 identity and continuity, 169. 
 temperament, 174. 
 value of analysis, 178. 
 summum bonum, 184. 
 classes of goods, 191. 
 virtue defined, 196. 
 prudence, 200. 
 
 Gassendi : 
 
 on courage, 203. 
 temperance, 204. 
 justice, 204. 
 jus civile, 206. 
 jus naturale, 207. 
 jus gentium, 209. 
 natural law.s, 210. 
 liberty, 218. 
 predestination, 221. 
 God, 224. 
 Oassendi. 
 
 his position defined, 248. 
 character of his work, 256. 
 the concept of motion, 261. 
 Generation, 83. 
 God, 224. 
 
 relation to time, 47. 
 first cauise, 56. 
 Guyau, quoted 230. 
 
 Identity, 169. 
 Imagination, 13, 129. 
 Intellectus, 142. 
 
 Jus, civile, 206 ; naturale, 207 ; 
 
 gentium, 209. 
 Justice, 204. 
 
 Kant : his ethics in relation to 
 Gassendi, 214. 
 his influence, 274, 279. 
 
 Leibnitz : his logical standpoint, 
 271. 
 relation to Gassendi, 273. 
 defective idea of an organism, 
 
 275. 
 idea of unity, 277. 
 Leucippus, xvii. 
 development of his atomism, 
 xviii-xx. 
 Liberty, 218. 
 Life, defined, 168.
 
 310 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Light : nature of, 74. 
 Logic. 
 
 of Epicurus, xxvii, 3. 
 
 of Gassendi, 1. 
 Lotze. 
 
 his aesthetic standpoint, 283. 
 
 doing opposed to being, 284. 
 
 three moments of his philosophy, 
 287. 
 
 occasionalism, 287. 
 
 idealism, 288. 
 Lucretius, xvii. 
 
 on the soul, xxxiii, 121. 
 
 quoted 23, 109 n., 226, 237. 
 
 Magnet, 92, 115, 119. 
 
 Masson, John, quoted 117, 230. 
 
 Materialism, 249. 
 
 Matter, 49. 
 
 Mind-stufF, 118. 
 
 Motion. 
 
 as general principle, 261. 
 
 local motion, 60. 
 
 vis motrix, 162. 
 
 Natural laws, 210. 
 Nature, view of, 20. 
 
 Occasionalism, 288. 
 
 Perception, 115, 123. 
 
 Plants, 95. 
 
 Plato, Timaeus, quoted 25. 
 
 Posidonius, quoted 45, 46. 
 
 Potentiality, 266. 
 
 Potestas, 72. 
 
 Predestination, 221. 
 
 Prudence, 200. 
 
 Pythagoras, on the World Soul, 25. 
 
 Qualities, 66. 
 
 Quality : opposed to quantity, 
 
 267. 
 Quantity : category of, 268. 
 relation to quality, 66. 
 
 Ratio, kinds of, 137. 
 Relation, category of, 265. 
 
 Sensation, 116, 121. 
 Signa, 10. 
 Soul, 106. 
 
 human. 111. 
 
 origin of, 113. 
 
 and body, 263. 
 Space, 34. 
 
 Species (visible), 76. 
 Speech, 165. 
 
 Substance, category of, 264, 272. 
 Summum bonum, 184. 
 
 Teleology, 100. 
 
 Temperament, 174. 
 
 Temperance, 204. 
 
 Thomas, P. Felix, quoted xv, 
 
 xliii, 4, 160, 213. 
 Time, 40. 
 Timeless, meaning of, 46. 
 
 Ueberweg, quoted 248. 
 Unity, 257, 277. 
 in Lotze, 291. 
 
 Virtue, 196. 
 
 Wallace, Epicureanism, quoted 
 
 xxvi, XXXV, 104. 
 World Soul, 23, 140. 
 
 GLASGOW : PRINTED AT THE UNIVERSITY PRBSS BY ROBERT MACLEHOSE AND CO. LTD.
 
 By Professor HARALD HOFFDING 
 
 Two Vols. 8vo. it^s. net each 
 
 A HISTORY OF 
 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 A Sketch of the History of Philosophy from the Close 
 of the Renaissance to our own day 
 
 TRANSLATED FROM THE GERMAN EDITION BY 
 
 B. E. MEYER 
 
 Authorised Translation 
 
 Vol. I. contains : Introduction. Book I. The Philosophy of the 
 Renaissance, (a) The Discovery of Man ; {b) The New 
 Conception of the World. — Book II. The New Science. — 
 Book III. The Great Systems. — Book IV. English 
 Empirical Philosophy. — Book V. The French Enlighten- 
 ment Philosophy and Rousseau. — Notes. — Index. 
 
 Vol. II. contains: Book VI. The German Enlightenment Philosophy 
 and Lessing. — Book VII. Immanuel Kant and the Critical 
 Philosophy. — Book VIII. The Philosophy of Romanticism. 
 — Book IX. Positivism {a) Comte and French Philosophy; 
 {b) John Stuart Mill and the Revival of English Philosophy 
 in the Nineteenth Century ; {c) The Philosophy of Evolu- 
 tion. — Book X. Philosophy in Germany, 1850-1880. — 
 Notes. — Index. 
 
 ATHENj^UM. — "He understands the art of being interesting, and cultivates it to an 
 extent that is rare indeed amongst those whose business or inclination compels them to deal 
 with the great problems of logic, ethics, and metaphysics. . . . The present century has been 
 very prolific in histories of philosophy. . . . Professor Hoffding's work will, in point of 
 learning and ability, stand comparison with any of these. In point of interest it is very much 
 above most of them." 
 
 GU AR D I A N.—^^ T\i\?, work undoubtedly stands in the front rankof histories of philosophy, 
 not only on account of the eminence and learning of its author, but even more from the lucidity 
 of its plan and the consistency with which it is adhered to throughout. A history of philo- 
 sophy should, the author tells us, throw light on what philosophy really is ; and ilie present 
 book not only does this by distinguishing the chief problems of the philosopher and tracing 
 their rise and development, but also by making clear everywhere the intimate relation of 
 philosophy to political and social conditions and to scientific progress." 
 
 MACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED, LONDON
 
 By Professor HARALD HOFFDING 
 
 Svo. I2s. net 
 
 THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION 
 
 TRANSLATED FROM THE GERMAN EDITION BY 
 
 B. E. MEYER 
 
 Contents: — I. Problem and Procedure; II. Epistemological 
 Philosophy of Religion ; III. Psychological Philosophy of Religion ; 
 IV. Ethical Philosophy of Religion. 
 
 Crown Svo. 6s. ^- ^ 
 
 OUTLINES OF PSYCHOLOGY 
 
 Translated by MARY E. LOWNDES 
 
 GUARDIAN. — "A triumph of scientific grasp and literary skill. . . . With all its 
 abundance of profound and subtle observation, it succeeds in being lucid and even bright." 
 
 MIND. —"\t is one of the great merits of the book, for English students, that it was 
 originally written with diligent heed on the author's part to all the best work of English 
 psychologists. ... In the handy (and cheap) form given to the translation, it cannot fail to 
 find its way into educational use." 
 
 NATIOAAL OBSERVER .—" Vf^rhaps the most stimulating of recent manuals. _ The 
 Danish Professor is abreast his subject, and has given special attention to English thinkers 
 and workers." 
 
 ACADEMY. — "Will be a valuable addition to the library of the English student of 
 psychology. ... It is particularly interesting from its numerous references to the more 
 picturesque and striking manipulations of mind in genius, insanity, hypnotic sleep, etc. Its 
 literary allusions are also frequent and happy." 
 
 Globe Svo. 4^-. 6d. net 
 
 The PROBLEMS of PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Translated by GALEN M. FISHER 
 With a Preface by W. JAMES 
 
 Contents :— Introduction — Chapter I. The Problem of Consciousness; 
 II. The Problem of Knowledge; III. The Problem of Being; 
 IV. The Problem of Values, {a) The Ethical Problem, {b) The 
 Religious Problem. 
 
 MACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED, LONDON
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY .'^ 
 
 Los Angeles /• 
 
 This book is DUE on the last date stamped below. 
 
 
 JUL J. 
 
 RFC'D LDUm 
 
 DEC 1 9 ISt 
 
 v^ 
 
 JUN3 
 
 lOO^ 
 
 31983 
 
 JULL3 
 
 JAN 3 01996 
 
 
 J 
 
 s 
 
 ^ 
 
 AUGnS 1985 
 
 DATE SEf« 
 
 • FEB 1 1 198«* 
 
 DUE 3 MONTHS FHON 
 DATE RECEIVED 
 
 1-1,0 
 
 MARIS 
 
 
 mll'^f' ^^C 7 2002 
 
 4)584 
 
 •^iijLi, ijliili^lij 
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA 
 
 T /-kO! k. Xin'CT XHCJ
 
 3 1158 00116 9712 
 
 ; SOUTHFRN Rrr.lOMAl ' ipRA"V ^"'-il iTY 
 
 AA 000 939 611 o