S|;J M' m: f^%^'^ :'i{|. '':^Tf.i^^V'>'V'f;^|,if1< AFFIRMATIONS. AFFIRMATIONS BY HAVELOCK ELLIS LONDON: WALTER SCOTT, LIMITED PATERNOSTER SQUARE 1898 I.ltJiiAllI LhiVE: J'TY OF CALIFORiM SAM A BARBARA PREFACE. There are at least two ways of looking at books and at the personalities books express. In its chief but rarer aspect Hterature is the medium of art, and as such can raise no ethical problems. Whatever morality or immorality art may hold is quiescent, or lifted into an atmo- sphere of radiant immortality where questioning is irrelevant. Of the literature that is all art we need not even speak, unless by chance we too approach it as artists, trying to grasp it by im- aginative insight. In literature, as elsewhere, art should only be approached as we would approach Paradise, for the sake of its joy. It would be well, indeed, if we could destroy or forget all that has ever been written about the world's great books, even if it were once worth while to write those books about books. How happy, for instance, the world might be if there were no literature about the Bible, if Augustine and Aquinas and Calvin and thousands of iv Preface. smaller men had not danced on it so loncj, stamping every page of it into mire, that now the vision of a single line, in its simple sense, is almost an effort of inspiration. All my life long I have been casting away the knowledge I have gained from books about literature, and from opinions about life, and coming to literature itself or to life itself, a slow and painful progress towards that Heaven of knowledge where a child is king. But there is another kind of literature, a literature which is not all art — the literature of life. Literature differs from design or music by being closer to life, by being fundamentally not an art at all, but merely the development of ordinary speech, only rising at intervals into the region of art. It is so close to life that largely it comes before us much as the actual facts of life come before us. So that while we were best silent about the literature of art, sanctified by time and the reverence of many men, we cannot question too keenly the literature of life. In this book I deal with questions of life as they are expressed in literature, or as they are suggested by literature. Throughout I am dis- cussing morality as revealed or disguised by literature. I may not care, indeed, to pervert my subjects in order to emphasise my opinions, but I frankly take my subjects chiefly on those sides which suit my own pleasure, and I select Preface. v them solely because they do that so well, I use them as the ancient device of the stalking-horse was used, to creep up more closely to the game that my soul loves best. So far as possible I dwell most on those aspects of my subjects which are most question- able. It was once brought against me that I had a predilection for such aspects. Assuredly it is so. If a subject is not questionable it seems to me a waste of time to discuss it. The great facts of the world are not questionable; they are there for us to enjoy, or to suffer, in silence, not to talk about. Our best energies should be spent in attacking and settling questionable things that so we may enlarge the sphere of the unquestionable — the sphere of real life — and be ready to meet new questions as they arise. It is only by dealing with the questionable aspects of the world that criticism of life can ever have any saving virtue for us. It is waste of life to use literature for pawing over the unquestionable. Even a healthy dog, having once ascertained the essential virtue of a bone, contentedly eats it, or buries it. And yet, it may well be, there is a time for affirming the simple eternal facts of life, a time, even, when those simple eternal facts have drifted so far from us that we count them also question- able. The present moment has seemed to me a fitting one to set a few such affirmations in vi Preface. order. The century now nearly over has per- formed many dirty and laborious tasks ; it has had to organise its own unwieldiness, to cleanse its Augean stables of the filth it has itself deposited, to pull down the buildings it has itself erected. When we witness such work carried out — blunderingly, it may be, but yet, we thought, humbly — we mc-»y well point out what splendid fellows these modest, begrimed toilers really were, what useful and noble work they were engaged in, how large a promise they bear for the future. That was my own point of view. But the case is altered when these yet unwashed toilers rise up around us in half- intoxicated jubilation over the triumphs of their own little epoch, well assured that there never was such an age or such a race since the world began. Then we may well pause. It is time to recall the simple eternal facts of life. It is time to affirm the existence of those verities which are wrought into our very structure everywhere and always, and in the face of which the paltry triumphs of an "era" fall back into insignificance. Yet every man must make his own affirma- tions. The great questions of life are immortal, only because no one can answer them for his fellows. I claim no general validity for my affirmations. It has been well said that certain books possess a value that is in the ratio of the Preface. vii spiritual vigour of those who use them, acting as a tonic to the strong, still further dissolving and enfeebling the weakness of the weak. It would be presumptious to claim any potent and pecu- liar energy for this book; but the observation is one which a reader may do well always to bear in mind. The final value of any book is not in the beliefs which it may give us or take away from us, but in its power to reveal to us our own real selves. If I can stimulate any one in the search for his own proper affirmations, he and I may well rest content. He is welcome to cast aside mine as the idle conclusions of a dreamer lying in the sunshine. Our own affirma- tions are always the best. Let us but be sure that they are our own, that they have grown up slowly and quietly, fed with the strength of our own blood and brain. Only with the help of such affirmations can we find a staff to comfort us through the valley of life. It is only when they utter affirmations, one has said, that the wands of the angels blossom. H. E. August 1897. CONTENTS. NIETZSCHE ... CASANOVA ... ZOLA HUYSMANS ... ST. FRANCIS AND OTHERS PAGE I 86 131 158 212 AFFIRMATIONS. NIETZSCHE. For some years the name of Friedrich Nietzsche has been the war-cry of opposing factions in Germany. It is not easy to take up a German periodical without finding some trace of the passionate admiration or denunciation which this man has called forth. If we turn to Scandinavia or to France, whither his fame and his work are also penetrating, we find that the same results have followed. And we may expect a similar outburst in England now that the translation of his works has at last begun. At present, however, I know of no attempt to deal with Nietzsche from the British point of view, and that is my excuse for trying to define his personality and influence.^ I do not come forward as the champion of Nietz- schianism or of Anti-Nietzschianism. It appears to me that any human individuality that has _ 1 This statement (made at the end of 1895) ''^s ceased to be true, but it explains the genesis of this study, and I leave it standing. I 2 Affu'inations. strongly aroused the love and hatred of men must be far too complex for absolute con- demnation or absolute approval. Apart from praise or blame, which seem here alike imper- tinent, Nietzsche is without doubt an extra- ordinarily interesting figure. He is the modern incarnation of that image of intellectual pride which Marlowe created in Faustus. A man who has certainly stood at the finest summit of modern culture, who has thence made the most determined effort ever made to destroy modern morals, and who now leads a life as near to death as any life outside the grave can be, must needs be a tragic figure. It is a figure full of significance, for it represents one of the greatest spiritual forces which have appeared since Goethe, full of interest also to the psycho- logist, and surely not without its pathos, perhaps its horror, for the man in the street I. It has only lately become possible to study Nietzsche's life-history. For a considerable period the Nietzsche-Archiv at Naumburg and Weimar has been accumulating copious materials which have now been utilised by Nietzsche's sister, Elizabeth Forster-Nietzsche, in the pro- duction of an authoritative biography. This sister is herself a remarkable person ; for many NietzscJie. 3 years she lived in close association with her brother, so that she was supposed, though without reason, to have exerted an influence over his thought; then she married Dr. Fdrster, the founder of the New Germany colony in Paraguay ; on his death she returned home to write the history of the colony, and has since devoted herself to the care of her brother and his fame. Only the first two volumes of the Leben Nietzsche^s have yet appeared, but they enable us to trace his development to his departure from Basel, and throw light on his whole career. Nietzsche belonged, according to the ancestral tradition (though the name, I am told, is a com- mon one in Wendish Silesia), to a noble Polish family called Nietzky, who on account of strong Protestant convictions abandoned their country and their title during the eighteenth century and settled in Germany. Notwithstanding the large amount of German blood in his veins, he always regarded himself as essentially a Pole. The Poles seemed to him the best endowed and most knightly of Sclavonic peoples, and he once remarked that it was only by virtue of a strong mixture of Sclavonic blood that the Germans entered the ranks of gifted nations. Pie termed the Polish Chopin the deliverer of music from German heaviness and stupidity, and when he speaks of another Pole, Copernicus, 4 Affirmation:^. who reversed the judgment of the whole world, one may divine a reference to what in later years Nietzsche regarded as his own mission. In adult life Nietzsche's keen and strongly marked features were distinctly Polish, and when abroad he was frequently greeted by Poles as a fellow- countryman ; at Sorrento, where he once spent a winter, the country people called him II Polacco. Like Emerson (to whose writings he was strongly attracted throughout life) and many another strenuous philosophic revolutionary, Nietzsche came of a long race of Christian ministers. On both sides his ancestors were preachers, and from first to last the preacher's fervour was in his own blood. The eldest of three children (of whom one died in infancy), Friedrich Nietzsche was born in 1844 at Rocken, near Liitzen, in Saxony. His father — who shortly after his son's birth fell down the par- sonage steps, injuring his head so severely that he died within twelve months — is described as a man of noble and poetic, nature, with a special talent for music, inherited by his son ; though once described by his son as " a tender, lovable, morbid man," he belonged to a large and very healthy family, who mostly lived to an extreme old age, preserving their mental and physical vigour to the last. The Nietzsches were a proud, sincere folk, very clannish, look- incr askance at all who were not Nietzsches. Nietzsche. 5 Nietzsche's mother, said to be a charming woman and possessed of much physical vigour, was again a clergyman's daughter. The Oehler family, to which she belonged, was also very large, very health}^, and very long-lived ; she was only eighteen at her son's birth, and is still alive to care for him in his complete mental decay. I note these facts, which are given with much precision and detail in the biography, because they certainly help us to understand Nietzsche. It is evident that he is no frail hectic flame of a degenerating race. There seems to be no trace of insanity or nervous dis- order at any point in the family history, as far back as it is possible to go. On the contrary, he belonged to extremely vigorous stocks, pos- sessing unusual moral and physical force, people of" character." A similar condition of things is not seldom found in the history of genius. In such a case the machine is, as it were, too highly charged with inherited energy, and works at a pressure which ultimately brings it to perdition. All genius must work without rest, it cannot do otherwise ; only the most happily constituted genius works without haste. The sister's account of the children's early life is a very charming part of this record, and one which in the nature of things rarely finds place in a biography. She describes her first memories of the boy's pretty face, his long fair 6 Affirvialions. hair, and large, dark, serious eyes. He could not speak until he was nearly three years old, but at four he began to read and write. He was a quiet, rather obstinate child, with fits of passion which he learnt to control at a very early age ; his self-control became so great that, as a boy, on more than one occasion he deliberately burnt his hand, to show that Mucius Scaevola's act was but a trifling matter. The widowed mother went with her children to settle at Naumburg on the Saale with her husband's mother, a woman of fine character with views of her own, one of which was that children of all classes should first be brought up together. Little Fritz was therefore sent to the town school, but the experiment was not alto- gether successful. He was a serious child, fond of solitude, and was called " the little parson " by his comrades. " The fundamental note of his disposition," writes a schoolfellow in after-life, " was a certain melancholy which expressed itself in his whole being." He avoided his fellows and sought beautiful scenery, as he con- tinued to do throughout life. At the same time he was a well-developed, vigorous boy, who loved games of various kinds, especially those of his own invention. But although the child- ren lived to the full the fantastic life of childhood, the sister regretfully confesses that they re- mained models of propriety, Fritz was " a very NielzscJie. 7 pious child ; he thought much about rch'gious matters, and was always concerned to put his thoughts into practice." It is curious that, not- withstanding his instinctive sympathy with the Greek spirit and his philological aptitudes, he found Greek specially difficult to learn. At the age of ten appeared his taste for verse-making, and also for music, and he soon began to show that inherited gift for improvisation by which he was always able to hold his audience spell- bound. Even as a boy the future moralist made a deep impression on those who knew him, and he reminded one person of the youthful Jesus in the Temple. " We Nietzsches hate lies," an aunt was accustomed to say ; in Fried- rich sincerity was a very deep-rooted trait, and he exercised an involuntary educational influence on those who came near him. In 1858 a place was found for him at Pforta, a remarkable school of almost military discipline. Here many of the lines of his future activity were definitely laid down. At an even earlier date, excited by the influence of Humboldt, he had been fascinated by the ideal of universal culture, and at Pforta his intellectual energies began to expand. Here also, in 1859, when a piano- forte edition of Iristaji was first published, Nietzsche became an enthusiastic Wagnerian, and even to the last Tristan remained for him " music par excellence^ Here, too, he began '8 Affinnations. those philological studies which led some years later to a professorship. He turned to philology, however, as he himself recognised, because of the need he felt to anchor himself to some cool logical study which would not grip his heart like the restless and exciting artistic instincts which had hitherto chiefly moved him. During the latter part of his stay at this very strenu- ous educational establishment young Nietzsche was a less brilliant pupil than during the earlier part His own individuality was silently growing beneath the disciplinary pressure which would have dwarfed a less vigorous individuality. His philosophic aptitudes began to develop and take form ; he wished also to devote himself to music ; and he pined at the confinement, long- ing for the forest and the woodman's axe. It was the beginning of a long struggle between the impulses of his own self-centred nature and the duties imposed from without, by the school, the university, and, later, his professorship ; he always strove to broaden and deepen these duties to the scope of his own nature, but the struggle remained. It was the immediate result of this double strain that, during 1862, strong and healthy as the youth appeared, he began to suffer from headaches and eye-troubles, cured by temporary removal from the school. He remained extremely short-sighted, and it was only by an absurd error in the routine examina- Nietasclie. 9 tion that, some years later, he was passed for mihtary service in the artillery. In the following year, 1863, Nietzsche met a schoolfellow's sister, an ethereal little Berlin girl, who for a while appealed to " the large, broad- shouldered, shy, rather solemn and stiff youth." To this early experience, which never went beyond poetic Schwdrmerei, his sister is inclined to trace the origin of Nietzsche's view of women as very fragile, tender little buds. The experience is also interesting because it appears to stand alone in his life. We strike here on an or- ganic abnormality in this congenital philosopher. Nietzsche's attitude was not the crude misogyny of Schopenhauer, who knew women chiefly as women of the streets. Nietzsche knew many of the finest women of his time, and he sometimes speaks with insight and sympathy of the world as it appears to women ; but there was clearly nothing in him to answer to any appeal to passion, and his attitude is well summed up in an aphorism of his own Zarathustra : "It is better to fall into the hands of a murderer than into the dreams of an ardent woman." " All bis life long," his sister writes, "my brother remained completely apart from cither great passion or vulgar pleasure. His whole passion lay in the world of knowledge ; only very temperate emo- tions remained over for anything else. In later life he was grieved that he had never attained lO Affirmations. to amour passion, and that every inclination to a feminine personality quickly changed to a tender friendship, however fascinatingly pretty the fair one might be." He would expend much sympathy on unhappy lovers, yet he would shake his head, saying to himself or others : "And all that over a little girl!" Young Nietzsche left Pforta, in 1863, with the most various and incompatible scientific tastes and interests (always excepting in mathematics, for which he never possessed any aptitude), but, as he himself remarked, none that would fit him for any career. One point in regard to the termination of his school-life is noteworthy: he chose Thcognis as the subject of his valedictory dissertation. His meditations on this moralist and aristocrat, so contemptuous of popular rule, may have served as the starting-point of some of his own later views on Greek culture. In 1864 he became a student at Bonn, and the year that followed was of special import in his inner development; he finally threw off the beliefs of his early youth; he discovered his keen critical faculty; and self-contained independence became a visible mark of his character, though always disguised by amiable and courteous manners. At Bonn his life seems to have been fairly happy, though he was by no means a typical German student. He spent much money, but it was chiefly on his artistic tastes — music Nietzsche, i r and the theatre — or on Httlc tours. No one could spend less on eating and drinking; like Goethe and like Heine, he had no love for tobacco or for beer, and he was repelled by the thick, beery good-humour of the German student. People who drink beer and smoke pipes every evening, he always held, were in- capable of understanding his philosophy; for they could not possibly possess the clarity of mind needed to grasp any delicate or complex intellectual problem. He returned home from Bonn " a picture of health and strength, broad- shouldered, brown, with rather fair thick hair, and exactly the same height as Goethe;" and then went to continue his studies at Leipzig. Notwithstanding the youth's efforts to subdue his emotional and aesthetic restlessness by cool and hard work, he was clearly tortured by the effort to find a philosophic home for himself in the world. This effort absorbed him all day long, frequently nearly all the night. At this time he chanced to take up on a bookstall a totally unknown work, entitled Der Weii als Wille und Vorstelbing ; in obedience to an unusual impulse he bought the book without consideration, and from that moment began an acquaintance with Schopenhauer which for many years exerted a deep influence on his life. At that time, probably, he could have had no better guide into paths of peace; but even as a student 1 2 AJfiruiations. he was a keen critic of Schopenhauer's system, valuing him chiefly as, in opposition to Kant, " the philosopher of a re-a\vakencd classical period, a Germanised Hellenism." Schumann's music and long solitary walks aided in the work of recuperation. A year or two later Nietzsche met the other great god who shared with Scho- penhauer his early worship. " I cannot bring my heart to any degree of critical coolness before this music," he wrote, in 1868, after listening to the overture to the Meistersinger; "every fibre and nerve in me thrills; it is a long time since I have been so carried away." I quote these words, for we shall, I think, find later that they have their significance. A few weeks afterwards he was invited to meet the master, and thus began a relationship that for Nietzsche was fateful. Meanwhile his philological studies were bring- ing him distinction. A lecture on Theognis was pronounced by Ritschl to be the best work by a student of Nietzsche's standing that he had ever met with. Then followed investigations into the sources of Suidas, a lengthy examination De fontibus Diogenis Laertii, and palaeographic studies in connection with Terence, Statins, and Orosius. He was now also consciously perfect- ing his German style, treating language, he remarks, as a musical instrument on which one must be able to improvise, as well as play what Nietzsche. 1 3 is merely learnt by heart. In 1S69, when only in his twenty-sixth year, and before he had taken his doctor's degree, he accepted the chair of classical philology at Basel. He was certainl)', as he himself said, not a born philologist. He had devoted himself to philology — I wish to insist on this significant point — as a sedative and tonic to his restless energy; in this he was doubtless wise, though his sister seems to suggest that he thereby increased his mental strain. But he had no real vocation for philolo;:zy, and it is curious that when the Basel chair was offered to him he was proposing to himself to throw aside philology for chemistry. Philologists, he declares again and again, arc but factory hands in the service of science. At the best philology is a waste of acuteness, since it merely enables us to state facts which the study of the present ' would teach us much more swiftly and surely. Thus it was that he instinctively broadened and deepened every philological question he took up, making it a channel for philosophy and morals. With his specifically philological work we are not further concerned. I have been careful to present the main facts in Nietzsche's early development because they seem to me to throw light on the whole of his later development. So far he had published nothing except in philological journals. In 14 Affiyniatioiis. 1 3/ 1, after he had settled at Basel, appeared his first work, an essay entitled Die Geburt der Trag'ddie aiis devi Geiste der Mnsik, dedicated to Wagner. The conception of this essay was academic, but in Nietzsche's hands the origin of tragedy became merely the text for an exposition of his own philosophy of art at this period. He traces two art impulses in ancient Greece : one, starting in the phenomena of dreaming, which he associates with Apollo; the other, starting in the phenomena of intoxication, associated with Dionysus, and through singing, music and dithyramb leading up to the lyric. The union of these, which both imply a pessimistic view of life, produced folk- song and finally tragedy, which is thus the outcome of Dionysiac music fertilised by Apol- lonian imagery. Socrates the optimist, with his views concerning virtue as knowledge, vice as ignorance, and his identification of virtue with happiness, led to the decay of tragedy and the triumph of Alexandrian culture, in the net of which the whole modern world is still held. Now, however, German music is producing a new birth of tragedy through Wagner, who has again united music and myth, inaugurated an era of art culture, and built the bridge to a new German heathenism. This remarkable essay produced considerable controversy and much consternation among Nietzsche's philological NietzscJie. 1 5 friends and teachers, who resented — reasonably enough, we may well admit — the subordination of philology to modern philosophy and art, and could not understand the marvellous swan they had hatched. A philologist Nietzsche could never have continued, but this book publicly put an end to any hope of academic advance- ment It remains characteristic of Nietzsche's first period, as we may call whatever he wrote before 1876, in its insistence on the primary im- portance of aesthetic as opposed to intellectual culture; and it is characteristic of his whole work in its grip of the connection between the prob- lems and solutions of Hellenic times and the problems and solutions of the modern world. For Nietzsche the Greek world was not the model of beautiful mediocrity imagined by Winckelmann and Goethe, nor did it date from the era of rhetorical idealism inaugurated by Plato. The real Hellenic world came earlier, and the true Hellenes were sturdy realists enamoured of life, reverencing all its manifestations and signs, and holding in highest honour that sexual symbol of life which Christianity, with its denial of life, despises. Plato Nietzsche hated ; he had wandered from all the funda- mental instincts of the Hellene. His childish dialectic can only appeal, Nietzsche said, to those who are ignorant of French masters like Fontenelle. The best cure for Plato, he held, 1 6 Affirmations. is Thucydides, the last of the old Hellenes who were brave in the face of reality; Plato fled from reality into the ideal and was a Christian before his time. Heraclitus was Nietzsche's favourite Greek thinker, and he liked to point out that the moralists of the Stoa may be traced back to the great philosopher of Ephesus. Die Geburt der Trag'ddie is the prelude to all Nietzsche's work. He outgrew it, but in one point at least it sounds a note which recurs throughout all his v/ork. He ever regarded the Greek conception of Dionysus as the key to the mystery of life. In Gdtseiiddmmening, the last of his works, this is still affirmed, more distinctly than ever. " The fundamental Hellenic in- stinct," he there wrote, " was first revealed in the Dionysiac mysteries. What was it the Greek assured to himself in these mysteries? Eternal life, the eternal return of life, the future promised and consecrated in the present, the triumphal affirmation of life over death and change, true life or immortality through pro- creation, through the mysteries of sexuality. Thus the sexual symbol was to the Greeks the profoundest and most venerable symbol in the whole range of ancient piety. Every in- dividual act of reproduction, of conception, of birth was a festival awaking the loftiest emotions. The doctrine of the mysteries proclaimed the Nietzsche. 1 7 holiness of pain ; the pangs of childbirth sancti- fied all pain. All growth and development, every promise for the future, is conditioned by pain. To ensure the eternal pleasure of creation, the eternal affirmation of the will to live, the eternity of birth-pangs is absolutely required. All this is signified by the word Dionysus : I know no higher symbolism than this Greek Dion^siac symbolism. In it the deepest instinct of life, of the future of life, the eternity of life, is experienced religiously; generation, the way to life, is regarded as a sacred way. Christianity alone, with its funda- mental horror of life, has made sexuality an impure thing, casting filth on the beginning, the very condition, of our life." Between 1873 and 1876 Nietzsche wrote four essays — on David Strauss, the Use and Abuse of History in relation to Life, Schopenhauer as an Educator, and Richard Wagner — which were published as a series of Unseitgemdsse Betracht- imge?i. The essay on Strauss was written soon after the great war, amid the resulting outburst of flamboyant patriotism and the widely-expressed conviction that the war was a victory of " Ger- man culture." Fresh from the world of Greece, Nietzsche pours contempt on that assumption. Culture, he says, is, above all, unity of artistic style in every expression of a people's life. The exuberance of knowledge in which a German 2 1 8 Affirmations. glories is neither a necessary means of culture nor a sign of it, being, indeed, more allied to the opposite of culture — to barbarism. It is in this barbarism that the modern German lives, that is to say, in a chaotic mixture of all styles. Look at his clothing, Nietzsche continues, his houses, his streets, all his manners and customs. They are a turmoil of all styles in which he peacefully lives and moves. Such culture is really a phleg- matic absence of all sense of culture. Largely, also, it is merely a bad imitation of the real and productive culture of France which it is sup- posed to have conquered in 1870. Let there be no chatter, he concludes, about the triumph of German culture, for at present no real German culture exists. The heroic figures of the German past were not " classics," as some imagine; they were seekers after a genuine German culture, and so regarded themselves. The would-be children of culture in Germany to-day are Philistines without knowing it, and the only unity they have achieved is a methodical barbarism. Nietzsche attacks Strauss by no means as a theologian, but as a typical "culture- Philistine." He was moved to this by the recent publication of Der Alte nnd der Naie Glniibc. I can well understand the emotions with which that book filled him, for I, too, read it soon after its publication, and can vividly recall the painful impression made on me by its homely pedes- I^ictzscJic. 19 trianism, the dull unimaginativeness of the man who could only compare the world to a piece of machinery, an engine that creaks in the work- ing, a sort of vast Lancashire mill in which we must spend every moment in feverish labour, and for our trouble perhaps be caught between the wheels and cogs. But I was young, and my youthful idealism, eager for some vital and passionate picture of the world, inevitably revolted against so tawdry and mechanical a conception. Nietzsche, then and ever, failed to perceive that there is room, after all, for the modest sturdy bourgeois labourer who, at the end of a hard life in the service of truth, sits down to enjoy his brown beer and Haydn's quartettes, and to repeat his homely confession of faith in the world as he sees it. Nietzsche failed to realise that Strauss's limitations were essential to the work he had to do, and that he remained a not unworthy follower of those German heroes who were not "classics," but honest seekers after the highest they knew. In this hypertrophied repulsion for the everyday work of the intellectual world we touch on a defect in Nietzsche's temperament which we must regard as fundamental, and which wrought in him at last to wildest issues. In another of these essays, Schopenhauer als Ercicher, Nietzsche sets forth his opinions con- cerning his early master in philosophy. It is 20 Affirmations. a significant indication of the qualities that attracted him to Schopenhauer that he com- pares him to Montaigne, thus at once revealing his own essential optimism, and the admiration- which he then and always felt for the great French masters of wisdom. He regards Scho- penhauer as the leader from Kant's caves of critical scepticism to the open sky with its consoling stars. Schopenhauer saw the world as a whole, and was not befooled by the analysis of the colours and canvas where- with the picture is painted. Kant, in spite of the impulse of his genius, never became a philosopher. " If any one thinks I am thus doing Kant an injustice, he cannot know what a philosopher is, i.e., not merely a great thinker but also a real man; " and he goes on to explain that the mere scholar who is accustomed to let opinions, ideas, and things in books always intervene between him and facts, will never see facts, and will never be a fact to himself; whereas the philosopher must regard himself as the symbol and abbreviation of all the facts of the world. It remained an axiom with Nietzsche that the philosopher must first of all be a " real man." In this essay, which Nietzsche always pre- ferred to his other early works, he thus for the first time clearly sets forth his conception of the philosopher as a teacher, a liberator, a guide Nietzsche. 2 1 to fine living; Schopenhauer's metaphysical doctrine he casts aside with indifference. Un- consciously, as in late years he seems to have admitted, he was speaking of himself and setting forth his own aims. Thus it is characteristic that he here also first expressed his conception of the value of individuality. Shakespeare had asked : " Which can say more Than this rich praise, that you alone are you ?" But Shakespeare was only addressing a single beloved friend. Nietzsche addresses the same thought to the common "you." "At bottom every man well knows that he can only live one single life in the world, and that never again will so strange a chance shake together into unity such singularly varied elements as he holds: he knows that, but he hides it like a bad conscience." This was a sane and democratic individualism; in later years, as we shall see, it assumed stranger shapes. At Basel Nietzsche lived in close communion with Wagner and Frau Cosima, who at this time regarded him as the prophet of the music- drama. The essay on Wagner, which starts from the standpoint reached in the previous essays, seems to justify this confidence. There is a deep analogy for those to whom distance is no obscuring cloud, Nietzsche remarks, between 22 Affinnatiofis. Kant and the Eleatics, Schopenhauer and Empedocles, Wagner and i^schylus. " The world has been orientalised long enough, and men now seek to be hellcniscd." The Gordian knot has been cut and its strands are fluttering to the ends of the world; we need a series of Anti-Alexanders mighty enough to bring to- gether the scattered threads of life. Wagner is such an Anti-Alexander, a great astringent force in the world. For " it is not possible to present the highest and purest operations of dramatic art, and not therewith to renew morals and the state, education and affairs." Bayreuth is the sacred consecration on the morning of battle. " The battles which art brings before us are a simplification of the actual battles of life; its problems are an abbreviation of the endlessly involved reckoning of human action and aspiration. But herein lies the greatness and value of art, that it calls forth the appear- ance of a simpler world, a shorter solution of the problems of life. No one who suffers in life can dispense with that appearance, just as no one can dispense with sleep." Wagner has simplified the world, Nietzsche continues; he has related m.usic to life, the drama to music; he has intensified the visible things of the world, and made the audible visible. Just as Goethe found in poetry an expression for the painter's vocation he had missed, so Wagner utilised in music his dramatic NietzscJie. 23 instinct. And Nietzsche further notes the democratic nature of Wagner's art, so strenu- ously warm and bright as to reach even the lowliest in spirit. Wagner takes off the stigma that clings to the word " common," and brings to all the means of attaining spiritual freedom. " For," says Nietzsche, "whosoever will be free, must make himself free; freedom is no fairy's gift to fall into any man's lap." Such are the leading thoughts in an essay which remains an interesting philosophic appreciation of the place of Wagner's art in the modern world; yet one may well admit that it is often over-strained, with a strain that expresses the obscure struggle of nascent antagonism. It is, indeed, Wagner in BayretitJi which brings to an end Nietzsche's first period, and leads up to the crash which inaugurated his later period. Hitherto Nietzsche's work was unques- tionably sane both in substance and form. No doubt it had called forth much criticism; work so vigorous, sincere, and independent could not fail to arouse hostility. But as we look back to-day, these fine essays represent, with much youthful enthusiasm, the best that was known and thought in Germany a quarter of a century ago. Nietzsche's opinions on Wagner and Schopenhauer, on individualism and democracy, the significance of early Hellenism for moderns, the danger of an excessive historical sense, the 24 Affirmations. conception of culture less as a striving after intellectual knowledge than as that which arouses within us the philosopher, the artist, and the saint — all these ideas, wild as some of them seemed to Nietzsche's German contempor- aries, are the ideas v/hich have now largely permeated European culture. The same cannot be said of his later ideas. It was at the first Bayreuth festival in 1876 that this chapter in Nietzsche's life was finally closed. His profound admiration for Wagner, his intimate intercourse with the greatest fig-ure in the German world of art, had hitherto been the chief fact in his life. All his ideals of life and his hopes for the future had grown up around the figure of Wagner, who seemed the leader into a new Promised Land. During the previous two years, however, Nietzsche had seen little of Wagner, who had left Switzerland, and he had been unable to realise either his own development or Wagner's. Whatever enthusi- asm Nietzsche may have felt in early life for a return to German heathenism, he was yet by race and training and taste by no means allied to primitive Germanism ; it was towards Greece and towards France that his conception of national culture really drew him. Wagner was far more profoundly Teutonic, and in the Nibelung cycle, which Nietzsche was about to witness for the first time on the stage, Wagner Nietzsche. 2 5 had incarnated the spirit of Teutonic heathenism with an overwhelming barbaric energy which, as Nietzsche could now realise, was utterly alien to his own most native instincts. Thus it was that Bayreuth marked the crisis of a subtle but profound realisation, the most intense self- realisation he had yet attained. The whole history of this Wagner episode in Nietzsche's life is full of interest. The circum- stantial narrative in the second volume of the Leben Nietzsche s renders it clear at every point, and reveals a tragedy which has its significance for the study of genius generally. Nietzsche, it must be remembered, was more than thirty years younger than Wagner. He was younger, and also he was less corrupted by the world than Wagner. Tiie great artist of the music- drama possessed, or had acquired, a practical good sense in all that concerned the realisation of his own mighty projects such as always marks the greatest and most successful of the world's supreme artists. Like Shakespeare, he knew that the dyer's hand must ever be a little subdued to what it works in, if the radiant beauty of his stuffs is ever to be perfectly achieved. But Nietzsche could never endure any fleck on his hand; he shrank with horror from every soiling contact ; he was an artist who regarded life itself as the highest art. He could never have carried through the rou^h 26 Affirmations. task of dying the gorgeous garments of a narrower but more perfectly attainable art. Nietzsche's idealised admiration for Wagner was complicated, after his appointment to the Basel chair, by a deep personal friendship for the Master, the chief friendship of his life. And his friendships were deeper than those of most; although they show no traces of sexual tincture they were hypertrophied by the defective sex- uality of the man who always regarded friend- ship as a more massive and poignant emotion than love. That there were on either side any petty faults to cause a rift in friendship there is no reason whatever to believe. Nietzsche was above such, and Wagner's friendship was always hearty until he realised that Nietzsche was no longer his disciple, and then he dropped him, silently, as a workman drops a useless tool. In addition it must be noted that Nietzsche was probably at this time often over-strained, almost hysterical, — at least so, we may gather, he im- pressed Wagner, who urged him to marry a rich wife and to travel, — and he was still afflicted by a disorder which not even genius can escape in youth, he was still something of what we vulgarly call a "prig"; he had not yet quite outgrown " the youthful Jesus in the Temple." " Your brother with his air of delicate distinction is a most uncomfortable fellow," said Wagner to Frau Forster-Nietzsche; Nietzsche. 27 " one can always see what he is thinking; sonne- times he is quite embarrassed at my jokes — and then I crack them more madly than ever." Wagner's jokes, it appears, were of a homely and plebeian sort, not appealing to one who lived naturally and habitually in an atmosphere of keen intellectual activity. Bearing all this in mind, one can imagine the impression made upon Nietzsche by the inaugural festival at Bayreuth for which he had just written an impassioned and yet philosophic prologue. Wagner was absorbed in using all his consider- able powers of managing men in finally van- quishing the difficulties in his way. To any one who could see the festival from the inside, as Nietzsche was able to see it, there were all the inevitable squabbles and scandals and comic contretemps which must always mark the in- ception of a great undertaking, but which to- day are hidden from us, pilgrims from many lands, as we ascend to that hillside structure which is the chief living shrine of art in Europe. And the people who were crowding in to this "sacred consecration on the morning of battle" were aristocrats and plutocrats — bejewelled, corpulent, commonplace — headed by the old Emperor, anxious to do his duty, decorously joining in the applause as he whispered "Horrible! horrible ! " to his aide-de-camp, and hurrying away as quickly as possible to the military 28 Affinnations. manoeuvres. There was more than enough here to make his own just issued battle-cry seem farcical to Nietzsche. All was conspiring to one end. The conception of the sanctity of Bayreuth, his personal reverence for Wagner were slipping away together, and at the same time he was forced to realise that the barbaric Ger- manism of this overpowering Nibelung music was not the music for him. His development would inevitably have carried him away from Wagner, but the festival brought on the crisis with a sudden clash. Nietzsche had finally conquered the mightiest of his false ideals, and stood for ever after free and independent of all his early gods; but the wounds of that victory were never quite closed to the last: a completely serene and harmonious conception of things, so far as Wagner was concerned, Nietzsche never attained. It may well be that the change was also physical. The excitement of the festival pre- cipitated an organic catastrophe towards which he had long been tending. His sister finds the original source of this catastrophe in the war of 1870. He desired to serve his country as a com- batant, but the University would only allow him leave to attend to the wounded. The physical and emotional over-tension involved by his con- stant care of six young wounded men culminated in a severe illness, which led on to a never-end- Nietzsche. 29 ing train of symptoms — eye-troublcs, dyspepsia, headache, insomnia — which were perhaps aggra- vated by the reckless use of drugs. I have already noted passages which indicate that he was himself aware of a consuming flame within, and that from time to time he made efforts to check its ravages. That it was this internal flame which largely produced the breakdown is shown by the narrative of Nietzsche's friend. Dr. Kretzer, who was with him at Bayreuth. It was evident he was seriously ill, Kretzer tells us, utterly changed and broken down. His eye-troubles were associated, if not with actual brain disease, at all events with a high degree of neurasthenia.^ At Bayreuth, Nietzsche was 1 The most convincing word-portrait of Nietzsche I have met with (by M. Schure) dates from the visit to Bayreuth : — "I was struck both by the superiority of his intellect and the strangeness of his face. A broad forehead, short hair brushed back, the prominent cheek-bones of the Slav. The heavy moustache and the bold outline of the face would have given him the aspect of a cavalry officer if it had not been for his timid and haughty air. The musical voice and slow speech indicated the artist's organi- sation, while the circumspect meditative carriage was that of a philosopher. Nothing more deceptive than the apparent calm of his expression. The fixed eye revealed the painful travail of thought. It was at once the eye of an acute observer and a fanatical visionary. The double character of this gaze produced a disquieted and disquieting impression, all the more so since it seemed to be always fixed on a single point. In moments of effusion this gaze was softened to a dream-like sweetness, but soon became hostile again." This picture is confirmed by Nietzsche's sister, who also refers to his "unusually large, beautiful, and brilliant eyes." 30 Affirmations. forced to realise the peril of his position as he had never realised it before. He could no longer disguise from himself that he must break with all the passionate interests of his past. It was an' essential measure of hygiene, almost a surgical operation. This is indeed how he has himself put the matter. In the preface to Der Fall Wagner, he said that it had been to him a necessary self-discipline to take part against all that was morbid within himself, against Wagner, against Schopenhauer, against all the impassioning interests of modern life, and to view the world, so far as possible, with the philosopher's eyes, from an immense height. And again he speaks of Wagner's art as a beaker of ecstasy so subtle and profound that it acts like poison and leaves no remedy at last but flight from the siren's cave. Nietzsche was henceforth in the position of a gouty subject who is forced to abandon port wine and straight- way becomes an apostle of total abstinence. The remedy seems to have been fairly success- ful. But the disease was in his bones. Im- passioning interests that were far more subtly poisonous slowly developed within him, and twelve years later flight had become impossible, even if he was still able to realise the need for flight. Nietzsche brol'ce very thoroughly with his past, yet the break has been exaggerated, and he Nietzsche. 3 1 himself often helped to exagf^erate it. He was in the position of a beleaguered city which has been forced to abandon its outer walls and concentrate itself in the citadel ; and however it may have been in ancient warfare, in spiritual affairs such a state of things involves an offensive attitude towards the former line of defence. The positions we have abandoned constitute a danger to the positions we have taken up. Many of the world's fiercest persecutors have but persecuted their old selves, and there seems to be psychological necessity for such an atti- tude. Yet a careful study of Nietzsche's earlier activity reveals many germs of later develop- ments. The critical attitude towards conven- tional morality, the individualism, the optimism, the ideal of heroism, which dominate his later thought, exist as germs in his earlier work. Even the flagrant contrast between Richard Wagner ifi BayreutJi and Der Fall Wagner was the outcome of a gradual development. In the earlier essay Nietzsche had justly pointed out that Wagner's instincts were fundamentally dramatic. As years went on he brooded over this idea ; the nimble and lambent wit of his later days played around it until Wagner be- came a mere actor in his work and in his life, a rhetorician, an incarnate falsehood, the personi- fication of latter-day decadence, the Victor Hugo of music, the Bernini of music, the modern 32 Affirmations. Cagliostro. At the same time he admits that Wagner represents the modern spirit, and that it is reasonable for a musician to say that though he hates Wagner he can tolerate no other music. The fact is, one may well repeat, that Nietzsche was not Teuton enough to abide for ever with Wagner. He compares him con- temptuously with Hegel, cloud-compellers both, masters of German mists and German mysticism, worshippers of Wotan, the god of bad weather, the god of the Germans. " How could they miss what we, we Halcyonians, miss in Wagner — la gaya scienza^ the light feet, wit, fire, grace, strong logic, the dance of the stars, arrogant intellectuality, the quivering light of the south, the smooth sea — perfection ? " It was scarcely, however, the Halcyonian in Nietzsche that stood between him and Wagner. That is well shown by his attitude towards Parsifal. Whatever we may think of the ideas embodied in Parsifal, it may yet seem to us the most solemn, the most graciously calm and beautiful spectacle that has ■ ever been fitly set to music. In Nietzsche the thinker and the moralist were so much stronger than the artist that he could see nothing here but bad psychology, bad thinking, and bad religion. The rebellion against Wagner was inevitable. It is evident that Nietzsche had not gained com- plete mastery of his own personality in his earlier Nietasc/ic. 33 work. It is brilliant, full of fine perceptions and critical insight, but as a personal utterance in- complete. It renders the best ideas of the time, not the best ideas that Nietzsche could contribute to the time. The shock of i ^y6 may have been a step towards the disintegration of his intellect, but it was also a rally, a step towards a higher self- realisation. Nietzsche had no genuine affinity with Schopenhauer or with Wagner, though they were helpful to his development ; he was no pessimist, he was no democrat. As he himself said, "I understood the philosophic pessimism of the nineteenth century as the symptom of a finer strength of thought, a more victorious fulness of life. In the same way Wagner's music signified to me the expression of a Dionysiac mightiness of soul in which I seemed to hear, as in an earthquake, the upheaval of the primitive powers of life, after age-long re- pression." Now he only needed relief, "golden, tender, oily melodies," to soothe the leaden weight of life, and these he found in Carmen. Any discussion of the merits of the question as between Wagner and Bizet, the earlier and the later Nietzsche, seems to me out of place, though much has been made of it by those who delight to see a giant turn and rend himself. Nietzsche himself said he was writing for psy- chologists, and it is not unfair to add that it is less " Wagner's case " that he presents to us than 3 34 Affirmations. " Nietzsche's case." As to the merits of the case, we may alike admit that Nietzsche's en- thusiasm for Wagner was not excessive, and that the pleasant things he said of Carmen are fully justified; we may address both the early and the late Nietzsche in the words habitually used by the landlord of the " Rainbow" : " You're both wrong and you're both right, as I alius says." Most of the mighty quarrels that have sent men to battle and the stake might have been appeased had each side recognised that both were right in their affirmations, both wrong in their denials. Nietzsche occupied his chair at Basel for some years longer; in i88o his health forced him to resign and he was liberally pensioned. As a professor he treated the most difficult questions of Greek study, and devoted his chief attention to his best pupils, who in their turn adored him. Basel is an admirable residence for a cosmo- politan thinker ; it was easy for Nietzsche to keep in touch with all that went on from Paris to St Petersburg. He was also on terms of more or less intimate friendship with the finest spirits in Switzerland, with Keller the novelist, Bocklin the painter, Burckhardt the historian. We are told that he was a man of great per- sonal charm in social intercourse. But his associates at Basel never suspected that in this courteous and amiable professor was stored up Nietzsche. 3 5 an explosive energy which would one day be felt in every civilised land. With pen in hand his criticism of life was unflinching, his sincerity arrogant ; when the pen was dropped he became modest, reserved, almost timorous. The work he produced between 1877 ^"d 1882 seems to me to represent the maturity of his genius. It includes MenscJiliches, AUsumen- scJiliches, Morgenrothe, and Die Frdhliclie Wis- senschaft. In form all these volumes belong to pensee literature. They deal with art, with re- ligion, with morals and philosophy, with the relation of all these to life. Nietzsche shows himself in these pensees above all a freethinker, emancipated from every law save that of sin- cerity, wide-ranging, serious, penetrative, often impassioned, as yet always able to follow his own ideal of self-restraint. After leaving Basel he spent the following nine years chiefly at health resorts and in tra- velling. We find him at Sorrento, Venice, Genoa, Turin, Sils Maria, as well as at Leipzig. Doubtless his fresh and poignant pensees are largely the outcome of strenuous solitary walks in the Engadine or among the Italian lakes. We may assume that during most of these years he was fighting, on the whole successfully fighting, for mental health. Yet passages that occur throughout his books seem to suggest that his thoughts may have sometimes turned 36 Affirmations. to the jToal towards which he was tending^. It is a mistake, he points out, to suppose that insanity is always the symptom of a degenerat- ing culture, although to nod towards the asylum is a convenient modern way of slaying spiritual tyrants ; it is in primitive and developing stages of culture that insanity has played its chief part ; only by virtue of what seemed to be the "Divine" turbulence of insanity and epilepsy could any new moral law make progress among early cultures. Just as for us there seems a little madness in all genius, so for them there seemed a little genius in all madness; sorcerers and saints agonised in solitude and abstinence for some gleam of madness which would bring them faith in themselves and openly justify their mission. What may perhaps be called Nietzsche's third period began in 1883 with Also sprach Zara- thustra, the most extraordinary of all his works, mystical and oracular in form, but not mystical in substance. Zarathustra has only a distant relationship to his prototype Zoroaster, though " Nietzsche had a natural sympathy with the symbolism of fire and water, with the reverence for light and purity, which mark the rites asso- ciated with the name of the Bactrian prophet; he has here allowed himself to set forth his own ideas and ideals in the free and oracular manner of all ancient scriptures, and is thus Nietzsche, 37 enabled to present his visions in a concrete form. Zarathustra, for the first and last time, gave scope to the artist within Nietzsche, and with all its extravagance and imperfection it must remain for good or evil his most per- sonal utterance. It was followed by Jenseits von Gut imd Bose, Zur Genealogie der Moral, Der Fall Wagner, and Gdtzenddtnmerung. It is during this period that we trace the growth of the magnification of his own personal mission which finally became a sort of megalomania. (" I have given to men the deepest book they possess, my Zarathustra" he wrote towards the end.) In form the books of this period are sometimes less fragmentary than those of the second period ; in substance they are marked by their emphatic, often extravagant, almost reckless insistence on certain views of morality. If in the first period he was an apostle of culture, in the second a freethinker, pronouncing judg- ment on all things in heaven and earth, he was now exclusively a moralist, or, as he would prefer to say, an immoralist. It was during this period that he worked out his " master morality" — the duty to be strong — in opposition to the "slave morality" of Christianity, with its glorifi- cation of weakness and pity, and that he con- sistently sought to analyse and destroy the traditional conceptions of good and evil on which our current morality rests. The last work which 38 Affirmations. he planned, but never completed, was a re-valua- tion of all values, UmwertJuing aller Werthe, which would have been his final indictment of the modern world, and the full statement of his own immoralism and Dionysiac philosophy. It is sometimes said that Nietzsche's mastery of his thoug:ht and style was increasing up to the last. This I can scarcely admit, even as regards style. No doubt there is at the best a light and swift vigour of movement in these last writings which before he had never attained. He can pour out now a shimmering stream of golden phrases with which he has intoxicated himself, and tries to intoxicate us. We may lend ourselves to the charm, but it has no enduring hold. This master of gay or bitter invective no longer possesses the keenly reasoned and piercing insight of the earlier Nietzsche. We feel that he has become the victim of obsessions which drive him like a leaf before the wind, and all his exuberant wit is unsub- stantial and pathetic as that of Falstafif. The devouring flame has at length eaten the core out of the man and his style, leaving only this coruscating shell. And at a touch even this thin shell collapsed into smouldering embers. From a child Nietzsche was subject to strangely prophetic dreams. In a dream which, when a boy, he put into literary form, he tells how he seemed to be travelling forward amid a glorious Nietzsche. 39 landscape, while carolling larks ascended to the clouds, and his whole life seemed to stretch before him in a vista of happy years ; " and suddenly a shrill cry reached our ears ; it came from the neighbouring lunatic asylum." Even in 1876 his friends began to see that Nietzsche attached extraordinary importance to his own work. After he wrote Zarathustra^ this self- exaltation increased, and began to find expres- sion in his work. Latterly, it is said, he came to regard himself as the incarnation of the genius of humanity. It has always been found a terrible matter to war with the moral system of one's age ; it will have its revenge, one way or another, from within or from without, what- ever happens after. Nietzsche strove for nothing less than to remodel the moral world after his own heart's desire, and his brain was perishing of exhaustion in the immense effort. In 18S9 — at the moment when his work at last began to attract attention — he became hopelessly insane. A period of severe hallucinatory delirium led on to complete dementia, and he passes beyond our sight. II. Nietzsche was by temperament a philosopher after the manner of the Greeks. In other words, philosophy was not to him, as to the average modern philosopher, a matter of books and the 40 Affirmations. study, but a life to be lived. It seemed to him to have much less concern with "truth" than with the essentials of fine living. He loved travel and movement, he loved scenery, he loved cities and the spectacle of men ; above all, he loved solitude. The solitude of cities drew him strongly; he envied Heraclitus his desert study amid the porticoes and peristyles of the immense temple of Diana. He had, however, his own favourite place of work, to which he often alludes, the Piazza di San IMarco at Venice, amid the doves, in front of the strange and beautiful structure which he " loved, feared, and envied ;" and here in the spring, between ten o'clock and midday, he found his best philo- sophic laboratory. It was in Italy that Nietzsche seems to have found himself most at home, although there are no signs that he felt any special sympathy with the Italians, that is to say in later than Renais- sance days. For the most part he possessed very decided sympathies and antipathies. His antipathy to his own Germans lay in the nature of things. Every prophet's message is primarily directed to his own people. And Nietzsche was unsparing in his keen criticism of the Germans. He tells somewhere with a certain humour how people abroad would ask him if Germany had produced of late no great thinker or artist, no really good book, and how with the courage of Niet::scJic. 4 1 despair he would at last reply, "Yes, Bismarck!" Nietzsche was willing enough to recognise the kind of virtue personified in Bismarck. But with that recognition nearly all was said in favour of Germany that Nietzsche had to say. There is little in the German spirit that answered to his demands. He admired clearness, analytic precision, and highly organised intelligence, light and alert. He saw no sufficient reason why profundity should lack a fine superficies, nor why strength should be ungainly. His in- stinctive comparison for a good thinker was always a good dancer. As a child he had been struck by seeing a rope-dancer, and throughout life dancing seemed to him the image of the finest culture, supple to bend, strong to retain its own equilibrium, an exercise demanding the highest training and energy of all the muscles of a well-knit organism. But the indubitable intellectual virtues of the bulky and plodding German are scarcely those which can well be symbolised by an Otero or a Caicedo. " There is too much beer in the German intellect," Nietzsche said. For the last ten centuries Germany has wilfully stultified herself; "no- where else has there been so vicious a misuse of the two great European narcotics, alcohol and Christianity," to which he was inclined to add music. ("The theatre and music," he re- marked in Die FrbJdicJic Wisscnschaft, " are 42 Affinnadons. the haschisch and betel of Europeans, and the history of the so-called higher culture is largely the history of narcotics.") " Germans regard bad writing," he said, " as a national privilege ; they do not write prose as one works at a statue, they only improvise." Even " German virtue" — and this was the unkindest cut of all — • had its origin in eighteenth century France, as its early preachers, such as Kant and Schiller, fully recognised. Thus it happens that the German has no perceptions — coupling his Goethe with a Schiller, and his Schopenhauer with a Hartmann — and no tact, "no finger for nuances" his fingers are all claws. The few persons of high culture whom he had met in Germany, he noted towards the end of his life, and especially Frau Cosima Wagner, were all of French origin. Nietzsche regarded it as merely an accident that he was himself born in Ger- many, just as it was merely an accident that Heine the Jew, and Schopenhauer the Dutch- man, were born there. Yet, as I have already hinted, we may take these utterances too seriously. There are passages in his works — though we meet them rarely — which show that Nietzsche recognised and admired the elemental energy, the depth and the contradictions in the German character ; he attributed them largely to mixture of races. Nietzsche was not much attracted to the NictzscJte. 43 English, It is true that he names Landor as one of the four masters of prose this century- has produced, while another of these is Emerson, with whom he had genuine affinity, although his own intellect was keener and more passionate, with less sunny serenity. For Shakespeare, also, his admiration was deep. And when he had outgrown his early enthusiasm for Schopenhauer, the fine qualities which he still recognised in that thinker — his concreteness, lucidity, reasonable- ness — seemed to him English. He was usually less flattering towards English thought Dar- winism, for instance, he thought, savoured too much of the population question, and was invented by English men of science who were oppressed by the problems of poverty. The struggle for existence, he said, is only an excep- tion in nature; it is exuberance, an even reckless superfluity, which rules. For English philosophic thought generally he had little but contempt. J. S. Mill was one of his "impossibilities"; the English and French sociologists of to-day, he said, have only known degenerating types of society, devoid of organising force, and they take their own debased instincts as the standard of social codes in general. Modern democracy, modern utilitarianism, are largely of English manufacture, and he came at last to hate them both. During the past century, he asserted, they have reduced the whole spiritual currcnc}'- 44 Affirmations. of Europe to a dull plebeian level, and they are the chief causes of European vulgarity. It is the English, he also asserted — George Eliot, for instance — who, while abolishing Christian belief, have sought to bolster up the moral system which was created by Christianity, and which must necessarily fall with it. It is, moreover, the English, who with this democratic and utilitarian plebeianism have seduced and per- verted the fine genius of France. Just as we owe to England the vulgarity v/hich threatens to overspread Europe, so to France we owe the conception of a habit of nobility, in every best sense of the word. On that point Nietzsche's opinion never wavered. The present subjection of the French spirit to this damnable Anglo-mania, he declared, must never lead us to forget the ardent and pas- sionate energy, the intellectual distinction, which belonged to the France of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries.^ The French, as Nietzsche ^ One may be allowed to regret that Nietzsche was not equally discriminating in his judgment of our country. Had he not been blinded by the spiritual plebeianism of the nineteenth century in England, he might also have discerned in certain periods some of the same ardent and heroic qualities which he recognised in sixteenth century France, the more easily since at that time the same Renaissance wave had effected a consider- able degree of spiritual union between France and England. In George Chapman, for instance, at his finest and lucidest moments the typical ethical representative of our greatest literary age, Nietzsche would have found a man after his own heart, NietzscJie. 45 always held, are the one modern European nation which may be compared with the Greeks. In MenscJilicJies, AUzumenschliches he names six French writers — Montaigne, La Rochefoucauld, La Bruyere, Fontenelle (in the Dialogues des Moris), Vauvenai'Ljcs, Chamfort — who bring us nearer to Greek antiquity than any other group of modern authors, and contain more real thought than all the books of the German philosophers put together. The only French writer of the present century for whom he cared much (putting aside Merimee) was Stendhal, who possesses some of the characters of the earlier group. The French, he points out, are the most Christian of all nations, and have produced the greatest saints. He enumer- ates Pascal (" the first among Christians, who was able to unite fervour, intellect, and candour; — think of what that means !"), Fenelon, Mme. de Guyon, De Ranee, the founder of the Trappists who have flourished nowhere but in France, the Huguenots, Port-Royal — truly, he exclaims, the great French freethinkers encountered foemen worthy of their steel! The land which produced the most perfect types of Anti-Christianity pro- not only one who scarcely yielded to himself in generous admir- ation of the great qualities of the French spirit but a man of " absolute and full soul " who was almost a precursor of his own " immoralism," a lover of freeilom, of stoic self-reliance, one who was ever seeking to enlarije the discipline of a fine culture in the direction of moral freedom and dignity. 46 Affirmations. duced also the most perfect types of Christianity. He defends, also, that seeming superficiality which in a great Frenchman, he says, is but the natural epidermis of a rich and deep nature, while a great German's profundity is too often strangely bottled up from the light in a dark and contorted phial. I have briefly stated Nietzsche's feeling as regards each of the three chief European peoples, because we are thus led up to the central points of his philosophy — his attitude towards modern religion and his attitude to- wards modern morals. We are often apt to regard these matters as of little practical im- portance; we think it the reasonable duty of practical social politics to attend to the im- mediate questions in hand, and leave these wider questions to settle themselves. Rightly or wrongly, that was not how Nietzsche looked at the matter. He was too much of a philo- sopher, he had too keen a sense of the vital relation of things, to be content with the policy of tinkering society, wherever it seems to need mending most badly, avoiding any reference to the whole. That is our English method, and no doubt it is a very sane and safe method, but, as we have seen, Nietzsche was not in sympathy with English methods. His whole significance lies in the thorough and passionate analysis with which he sought to dissect and to dissolve, first, NietzscJie. 47 "German culture," then Christianity, and lastly, modern morals, with all that these involve. It is scarcely necessary to point out, that though Nietzsche rejoiced in the title of free- thinker, he can by no means be confounded with the ordinary secularist. He is not bent on destroying religion from any anaesthesia of the religious sense, or even in order to set up some religion of science which is practically no religion at all. He is thus on different ground from the great freethinkers of France, and to some extent of England. Nietzsche was himself of the stuff of which great religious teachers are made, of the race of apostles. So when he writes of the founder of Christianity and the great Christian types, it is often with a poignant sympathy which the secularist can never know; and if his knife seems keen and cruel, it is not the easy indifferent cruelty of the pachyder- matous scoffer. When he analyses the souls of these men and the impulses which have moved them, he knows with what he is dealing : he is analysing his own soul. A mystic Nietzsche certainly was not ; he had no moods of joyous resignation. It is chiefly the religious ecstasy of active moral energy that he was at one with. The sword of the spirit is his weapon rather than the merely defensive breastplate of faith. St. Paul is the consum- mate type of such religious forces, and whatever 48 Affirmations. Nietzsche wrote of that apostle — the inventor of Christianity, as he truly calls him — is peculiarly interesting. He hates him, indeed, but even his hatred thrills with a tone of intimate sym- pathy. It is thus in a remarkable passage in Morgenrolhe, v/here he tells briefly the history and struggles of that importunate soul, so super- stitious and yet so shrewd, without whom there would have been no Christianity. He describes the self-torture of the neurotic, sensual, refined "Jewish Pascal," who flagellated himself with the law that he came to hate with the hatred of one who had a genius for hatred ; who in one dazzling flash of illumination realised that Jesus by accomplishing the law had annihilated it, and so furnished him with the instrument he desired to wreak his passionate hatred on the law, and to revel in the freedom of his joy, Nietzsche possesses a natural insight in probing the wounds of self-torturing souls. He excels also in describing the efi*ects of extreme pain in chasing away the mists from life, in showing to a man his own naked personality, in bringing us face to face with the cold and terrible fact. It is thus that, coupling the greatest figure in history with the greatest figure in fiction, he compares the pathetic utterance of Jesus on the cross — " My God, my God, why hast thou for- saken me?" — with the disillusionment of the dying Don Quixote. Of Jesus himself he Nietzsche. 49 speaks no harsh word, but ho regarded the atmosphere of Roman decay and languor — though very favourable for the production of fine personalities — as ill-adapted to the develop- ment of a great religion. The Gospels lead us into the atmosphere of a Russian novel, he remarks in one of his last writings, Der A?iii- christ, an atmosphere in which the figure of Jesus had to be coarsened to be understood; it became moulded in men's minds by memories of more familiar types — prophet, Messiah, wonder- worker, judge; the real man they could not even see. "It must ever be a matter for regret that no Dostoievsky lived in the neighbourhood of this most interesting decadent, I mean some one who could understand the enthralling charm of just this mixture of the sublime, the morbid, and the child-like." Jesus, he continues, never denied the world, the state, culture, work; he simply never knew or realised their existence ; his own inner experience — "life," "light," "truth" — was all in all to him. The only realities to him were inner realities, so living that they make one feel " in Heaven " and " eternal " ; this it was to be " saved." And Nietzsche notes, as so many have noted before him, that the fact that men should bow the knee in Christ's name to the very opposite of all these things, and consecrate in the " Church " all that he threw behind him, is an insoluble 4 50 Affinnations. example of historical irony. " Strictly speaking, there has only been one Christian, and he died on the cross. The Gospel died on the cross." There may seem a savour of contempt in the allusion to Jesus as an "interesting decadent^' and undoubtedly there is in Der Antichrist a passionate bitterness which is not found in Nietzsche's earlier books. But he habitually used the word decadent in a somewhat extended and peculiar sense. The decadent, as Nietzsche understood him, was the product of an age in which virility was dead and weakness was sanctified ; it was so with the Buddhist as well as with the Christian, they both owe their origin and their progress to " some monstrous disease of will." They sprang up among creatures who craved for some " Thou shalt," and who were apt only for that one form of energy which the weak possess, fanaticism. By an instinct which may be regarded as sound by those who do not accept his disparagement of either, Nietzsche ahvays coupled the Christian and the anarchist; to him they were both products of decadence. Both wish to revenge their own discomfort on this present world, he asserted, the anarchist immediately, the Christian at the last day. Instead of feeling, "/ am worth nothing," the decadent says, ''Life is worth nothing," — a terribly contagious state of mind which has covered the world with the vitality of a tropical Nietzsche. 5 1 jungle. It cannot be too often repeated, Nietzsche continues, that Christianity was born of the decay of antiquity, and on the degenerate people of that time it worked like a soothing balm ; their eyes and ears were sealed by age and they could no longer understand Epicurus and Epictetus. At such a time purity and beneficence, large promises of future life, worked sweetly and wholesomely. But for fresh young barbarians Christianity is poison. It produces a fundamental enfeeblement of such heroic, childlike, and animal natures as the ancient Germans, and to that enfeeblement, indeed, we owe the revival of classic culture ; so that the conclusion of the whole matter is here, as ever, Nietzsche remarks, that " it is impossible to say whether, in the language of Christianity, God owes more thanks to the Devil, or the Devil to God, for the way in which things have come about." But in the interaction of the classic spirit and the Christian spirit, Nietzsche's own instincts were not on the side of Christianity, and as the years went on he expresses himself in ever more unmeasured language. He could not take up the Initiation of Christ — the very word " imitation " being, as indeed Michelet had said before, the whole of Christianity — without physical repugnance. And in the Gdtsenddni- iiiening" he compares the Bible with the Laws of Manu (though at the same time asserting that 5 2 Affirmations. it is a sin to name the two books in the same- breath) : " The sun Hes on the whole book. All those things on which Christianity vents its bottomless vulgarity — procreation, for example, woman, marriage — are here handled earnestly and reverently, with love and trust. I know no book in which so many tender and gracious things are said about women as in the Laws of Manu." Again in Der Aittichrist — which repre- sents, I repeat, the unbalanced judgments of his last period — he tells how he turns from Paul with delight to Petronius, a book of which it can be said e tutto festo, " immortally sound, immortally serene." In the whole New Testa- ment, he adds, there is only one figure we can genuinely honour — that of Pilate. On the whole, Nietzsche's attitude towards Christianity was one of repulsion and antagon- ism. At first he appears indifferent, then he becomes calmly judicial, finally he is bitterly hostile. He admits that Christianity possesses, the virtues of a cunningly concocted narcotic to soothe the leaden griefs and depressions of men- whose souls are physiologically weak. But from first to last there is no sign of any genuine personal sympathy with the religion of the poor in spirit. Epicureanism, the pagan doc- trine of salvation, had in it an element of Greek energy, but the Christian doctrine of salvation, he declares, raises its sublime development of NietsscJie. 5 3 hedonism on a thoroughly morbid foundation. Christianity hates the body ; the first act of Christian triumph over the Moors, he recalls, was to close the public baths which they had everywhere erected. "With its contempt for the body Christianity was the greatest mis- fortune that ever befell humanity." And at the end of Der Antichrist he sums up his concen- trated hatred : " I condenm Christianity ; I raise against the Christian Church the most terrible accusation that any accuser has ever uttered. It is to me the most profound of all thinkable corruptions." It is scarcely necessary to add that Nietzsche's condemnation of Christianity extended to the Christian God. He even went so far as to assert that it was the development of Christian morality itself — " the father-confessor sensitive- ness of the Christian conscience translated and sublimed into a scientific conscience" — which had finally conquered the Christian God. He held that polytheism had played an important part in the evolution of culture. Gods, heroes, supernatural beings generally, were inestimable schoolmasters to bring us to the sovereignty of the individual. Polytheism opened up divine horizons of freedom to humanity, "Ye shall be as gods." But it has not been so with monotheism. The doctrine of a single God, in whose presence all others were false gods, 54 Affirviations. favours stagnation and unity of type; mono- theism has thus perhaps constituted " the greatest danger which humanity has had to meet in past ages." Nor are we yet freed from its influence, " For centuries after Buddha died men showed his shadow in a cave — a vast terrible shadow. God is dead : but thousands of years hence there will probably be caves in which his shadow may yet be seen. And we — we must go on fighting that shadow ! " How deeply rooted Nietzsche believed faith in a god to be is shown by the fantastic conclusion to ZaratJmstra. A strange collection of Ueber- vtenschen — the men of the future — are gathered together in Zarathustra's cave : two kings, the last of the popes — thrown out of work by the death of God — and many miscellaneous creatures, including a donkey. As Zarathustra returns to his cave he hears the sound of prayer and smells the odour of incense ; on entering he finds the Uebennenschen on their knees in- toning an extraordinary litany to the donkey, who has "created us all in his own image." In his opposition to the Christian faith and the Christian God, Nietzsche by no means stands alone, however independent he may have been in the method and standpoint of his attack. But in his opposition to Christian morality he was more radically original. There is a very general tendency among those who reject NietzscJie. 5 5 Christian theology to shore up the superstruc- ture of Christian morahty which rests on that theology, George Eliot, in her writings at all events, has been an eloquent and distinguished advocate of this process ; Mr. Myers, in an oft- quoted passage, has described with considerable melodramatic vigour the "sibyl in the gloom" of the Trinity Fellows' Garden at Cambridge, who withdrew God and Immortality from his grasp, but, to his consternation, told him to go on obeying Duty. What George Eliot pro- posed was one of those compromises so dear to our British minds. Nietzsche would none of it. Hence his contemptuous treatment of George Eliot, of J. S. Mill, of Herbert Spencer, and so many more of our favourite intellectual heroes who have striven to preserve Christian morality while denying Christian theology. Nietzsche regarded our current moral ideals, whether formulated by bishops or by anarchists, as alike founded on a Christian basis, and when that foundation is sapped they cannot stand. The motive of modern morality is pity, its principle is altruistic, its motto is " Love your neighbour as yourself," its ideal self-abnegation, its end the greatest good of the greatest number. All these things were abhorrent to Nietzsche, or so far as he accepted them, it was in forms which gave them new values. Modern morality, he said, is founded on an extravagant dread of 56 Affirmations. pain, in ourselves primarily, secondarily in others. Sympathy is fellow-suffering; to love one's neighbour as oneself is to dread his pain as we dread our own pain. The religion of love is built upon the fear of pain. " On n'est bon que par la pitie ; " the acceptance of that doc- trine Nietzsche considers the chief outcome of Christianity, although, he thinks, not essential to Christianity, which rested on the egoistic basis of personal salvation : " One thing is needful." But it remains the most important by-product of Christianity, and has ever been gaining strength. Spinoza and Kant stood firmly outside the stream, but the French free- thinkers, from Voltaire onwards, were not to be outdone in this direction by Christians, while Comte with his " Vivre pour autrui" even out- Christianised Christianity, and Schopenhauer in Germany, J. S. Mill in England, carried on the same doctrine. " The great question of life," said Benjamin Constant in Adolphe — and it is a saying that our finest emotions are quick to echo — " is the pain that we cause." Both the sympathetic man and the unsym- pathetic man, Nietzsche argues, are egoists. But the unsympathetic man he held to be a more admirable kind of egoist. It is best to win the strength that comes of experience and suffering, and to allow others also to play their own cards and win the same strength, shedding our tears Niet::;scJie. 5 7 in private, and abhorring soft-hearted ncss as the foe of all manhood and courage. To call the unsympathetic man " wicked," and the sympa- thetic man "good," seemed to Nietzsche a fashion in morals, a fashion which will have its day. He believed he was the first to point out the danger of the prevailing fashion as a sort of moral impressionism, the outcome of the hyperaesthesia peculiar to periods of decadence. Not indeed that Christianity is, or could be, carried out among us to its fullest extent : " That would be a serious matter. If we were ever to become the object to others of the same stupidities and importunities which they expend on themselves, we should flee wildly as soon as we saw our 'neighbour' approach, and curse sympathy as heartily as we now curse egoism." Our deepest and most personal griefs, Nietzsche remarks elsewhere, remain unrevealed and in- comprehensible to nearly all other persons, even to the " neighbour" who eats out of the same dish with us. And even though my grief should become visible, the dear sym- pathetic neighbour can know nothing of its complexity and results, of the organic economy of my soul. That my grief may be bound up with my happiness troubles him little. The devotee of the "religion of pity" will heal my sorrows without a moment's delay; he knows not that the path to my Heaven must lie 58 Affirmatio7ts. through my own Hell, that happiness and unhappiness are twin sisters who grow up to- gether, or remain stunted together. " Morality is the mob-instinct working in the individual." It rests, Nietzsche asserts, on two thoughts : " the community is worth more than the individual," and " a permanent advantage is better than a temporary advantage ; " whence it follows that all the advantages of the com- munity are preferable to those of the individual. Morality thus becomes a string of negative injunctions, a series of " Thou shalt nots," with scarcely a positive command amongst them ; witness the well-known table of Jewish com- mandments. Now Nietzsche could not endure mere negative virtues. He resented the subtle change which has taken place in the very meaning of the word " virtue," and which has perverted it from an expression of positive masculine qualities into one of merely negative feminine qualities. In his earliest essay he referred to " active sin " as the Promethean virtue which distinguishes the Aryans. The only moral codes that commended themselves to him were those that contained positive com- mands alone : " Do this ! Do it with all your heart, and all your strength, and all your dreams ! — and all other things shall be taken away from you ! " For if we are truly devoted to the things that are good to do we need Nietzsche. 59 trouble ourselves little about the things that are good to leave undone. Nietzsche compared himself to a mole boring down into the ground and undermining what philosophers have for a couple of thousand years considered the very surest ground to build on — the trust in morals. One of his favourite methods of attack is by the analysis of the " conscience." He points out that whatever we were regularly required to do in youth by those we honoured and feared created our "good conscience." The dictates of conscience, how- ever urgent, thus have no true validity as regards the person who experiences them. " But," some one protests, " must we not trust our feelings ? " " Yes," replies Nietzsche, " trust your feelings, but still remember that the in- spiration which springs from feelings is the grandchild of an opinion, often a false one, and in any case not your own. To trust one's feelings — that means to yield more obedience to one's grandfather and grandmother and their grandparents than to the gods within our ozvn breasts: our own reason and our own experi- ence." Faith in authority is thus the source of conscience; it is not the voice of God in the human heart but the voice of man. The sphere of the moral is the sphere of tradition, and a man is moral because he is dependent on a tradition and not on himself. Originally every- 6o Affirmations. thing was within the sjDhere of morals, and it was only possible to escape from that sphere by becoming a law-giver, medicine-man, demigod — that is to say by making morals. To be customary is to be moral, — I still closely follow Nietzsche's thought and expression, — to be individual is to be wicked. Every kind of originality involves a bad conscience. Nietzsche insists with fine eloquence, again and again, that every good gift that has been given to man put a bad conscience into the heart of the giver. Every good thing was once new, unaccustomed, immoral, and gnawed at the vitals of the finder like a worm. Primitive men lived in hordes, and must obey the horde-voice within them. Every new doctrine is vv-ickcd. Science has always come into the world with a bad con- science, with the emotions of a criminal, at least of a smuggler. No man can be disobedient to custom and not be immoral, and feel that he is immoral. The artist, the actor, the merchant, the freethinker, the discoverer, were once all criminals, and were persecuted, crushed, rendered morbid, as all persons must be when their virtues are not the virtues idealised by the community. The whole phenomena of morals are animal-like, and have their origin in the search for prey and the avoidance of pursuit. Progress is thus a gradual emancipation from morals. We have to recognise the services of Nietzsche. 6 1 the men who fight in this stnrj^glc against morals, and who arc crushed into the ranks of criminals. Not that we need pity them. " It is a new justice that is called for, a new mot (Tordye. We need new philosophers. The moral world also is round. The moral world also has its antipodes, and the antipodes also have their right to exist. A new world remains to be discovered — and more than one ! Hoist sail, O philosophers ! " "Men must become both better mid wickeder^ So spake Zarathustra; or, as he elsewhere has it, " It is with man as with a tree, the higher he would climb into the brightness above, the more vigorously his roots must strive earthwards, downwards, into the darkness and the depths — into the wicked." Wickedness is just as in- dispensable as goodness. It is the ploughshare of wickedness which turns up and fertilises the exhausted fields of goodness. We must no longer be afraid to be wicked; we must no longer be afraid to be hard. " Only the noblest things are very hard. This new command, O my brothers, I lay upon you — become hard." In renewing our moral ideas we need also to renew our whole conception of the function and value of morals. Nietzsche advises moralists to change their tactics: " Deny moral values, deprive them of the applause of the crowd, create obstacles to their free circulation; let 62 Affiymations. them be the shame-faced secrets of a few solitary souls; forbid morality! In so doin^ you may perhaps accredit these things among the only men whom one need have on one's side, I mean heroic men. Let it be said of morality to-day as Meister Eckard said: *I pray God that he may rid me of God ! ' " We have altogether over-estimated the importance of morality. Christianity knew better when it placed " grace " above morals, and so also did Buddhism. And if we turn to literature, Nietzsche maintains, it is a vast mistake to suppose that, for instance, great tragedies have, or were intended to have, any moral effect. Look at Macbeth, at Tristan unci Isolde, at CEdipiLs. In all these cases it would have been easy to make guilt the pivot of the drama. But the great poet is in love with passion. " He calls to us: It is the charm of charms, this exciting, changing, dangerous, gloomy, yet often sun-filled existence ! It is an adventure to live — take this side or that, it will always be the same ! ' So he speaks to us out of a restless and vigorous time, half drunken and dazed with excess of blood and energy, out of a wickeder time than ours is; and we are obliged to set to rights the aim of a Shakespeare and make it righteous, that is to say, to misunderstand it." We have to recognise a diversity of moral ideals. Nothing is more profoundly dangerous Nietzsche. 63 than, with Kant, to create impersonal categorical imperatives after the Chinese fashion, to general- ise "virtue," "duty," and "goodness," and sacri- fice them to the Moloch of abstraction. " Every- man must find his own virtue, his own categori- cal imperative ; " it must be founded on inner necessity, on deep personal choice. Only the simpleton says : " Men ought to be like this or like that." The real world presents to us a dazzling wealth of types, a prodigious play of forms and metamorphoses. Yet up comes a poor devil of a moralist, and says to us : " No ! men ought to be something quite different!" and straightway he paints a picture of himself on the wall, and exclaims : " Ecce homo ! " But one thing is needful, that a man should attain the fullest satisfaction. Every man must be his own moralist. These views might be regarded as " lax," as predisposing to easy self-indulgence. Nietzsche would have smiled at such a notion. Not yield- ing, but mastering, was the key to his personal morality. " Every day is badly spent," he said, "in which a man has not once denied himself; this gymnastic is inevitable if a man will retain the joy of being his own master." The four cardinal virtues, as Nietzsche understood morals, are sincerity, courage, generosity, and courtesy. " Do what you will," said Zarathustra, " but first be one of those who are able to will. Love your 64 Affirmations. neighbour as yourself — but first be one of those who are able to love themselves." And again Zarathustra spoke : " He who belongs to me must be strong of bone and light of foot, eager for fight and for feast, no sulker, no John o' Dreams, as ready for the hardest task as for a feast, sound and hale. The best things belong to me and mine, and if men give us nothing, then we take them : the best food, the purest sky, the strongest thoughts, the fairest women ! " There was no desire here to suppress effort and pain. That Nietzsche regarded as a mark of modern Christian morals. It is pain, more pain and deeper, that we need. The discipline of suffering alone creates man's pre-eminence. " Man unites in himself the creature and the creator: there is in him the stuff of things, the fragmentary and the superfluous, clay, mud, madness, chaos ; but there is also in him the creator, the sculptor, the hardness of the hammer, the divine blessedness of the spectator on the seventh day." Do you pity, he asks, what must be fashioned, broken, forged, refined as by fire? But our pity is spent on one thing alone, the most effeminate of all weaknesses — pity. This was the source of Nietzsche's admiration for war, and indifference to its horror ; he regarded it as the symbol of that spiritual warfare and bloodshed in which to him all human progress consisted. He might, had Nietzsche. 65 he pleased, have said with the Jew and the Christian, that without shedding of blood there shall be no remission of sins. But with a difference, for as he looked at the matter, every man must be his own saviour, and it is his own blood that must be shed ; there is no salvation by proxy. That was expressed in his favourite motto : Virescit volnere virtus. Nietzsche's ideal man is the man of Epictetus, as he describes him in Morgenr'dthe, the laconic, brave, self-contained man, not lusting after ex- pression like the modern idealist The man whom Epictetus loved hated fanaticism, he hated notoriety, he knew how to smile. And the best was, added Nietzsche, that he had no fear of God before his eyes ; he believed firmly in reason, and relied, not on divine grace, but on himself. Of all Shakespeare's plays Julius CcBsar seemed to Nietzsche the greatest, because it glorifies Brutus ; the finest thing that can be said in Shakespeare's honour, Nietzsche thought, was that — aided perhaps by some secret and intimate experience — he believed in Brutus and the virtues that Brutus personified. In course of time, however, while not losing his sympathy with Stoicism, it was Epicureanism, the heroic aspects of Epicureanism, which chiefly appealed to Nietzsche. He regarded Epicurus as one of the world's greatest men, the discoverer of the heroically idyllic method of living a philosophy; 5 66 Affirinaiions. for one to whom happiness could never be more than an unending self-discipline, and whose ideal of life had ever been that of a spiritual nomad, the methods of Epicurus seemed to yield the finest secrets of good living. Socrates, with his joy in life and in himself, was also an object of Nietzsche's admiration. Among later thinkers, Helvetius appealed to him strongly. Goethe and Napoleon were naturally among his favourite heroes, as were Alcibiades and Caesar. The latest great age of heroes was to him the Italian Renaissance. Then came Luther, opposing the rights of the peasants, yet himself initiating a peasants' revolt of the intellect, and preparing the way for that shallow plebeianism of the spirit which has marked the last two centuries. Latterly, in tracing the genealogy of modern morals, Nietzsche's opinions hardened into a formula. He recognised three stages of moral evolution : first, the /r^-w^/vz/ period of primitive times, when the beast of prey was the model of conduct, and the worth of an action was judged by its results. Then came the moral period, when the worth of an action was judged not by its results, but by its origin ; this period has been the triumph of what Nietzsche calls slave- morality, the morality of the mob; the goodness and badness of actions is determined by atavism, at best by survivals ; every man is occupied in laying down laws for his neighbour instead of Nietzsche. 67 for himself, and all arc tamed and chastised into weakness in order that they may be able to obey these prescriptions. Nietzsche ingeniously connected his slave-morality with the accepted fact that for many centuries the large, fair- haired aristocratic race has been dying out in Europe, and the older down-trodden race- short, dark, and broad-headed— has been slowly gaining predominance. But now we stand at the threshold of the extra-moral period. Slave- morality, Nietzsche asserted, is about to give way to master-morality; the lion will take the place of the camel. The instincts of life, refusing to allow that anything is forbidden, will again assert themselves, sweeping away the feeble negative democratic morality of our time. The day has now come for the man who is able to rule himself, and who will be tolerant to others not out of his weakness, but out of his strength; to him nothing is forbidden, for he has passed beyond goodness and beyond wickedness. III. So far I have attempted to follow with little or no comment what seems to me the main current of Nietzsche's thought. It may be admitted that there is some question as to which is the main current. For my own part I have no hesitation in asserting that it is the 68 Affirmations. current which expands to its fullest extent between 1876 and 1883 in what I term Nietzsche's second or middle period ; up to then he had not gained complete individuality; afterwards began the period of uncontrolled aberrations. Thus I am inclined to pass lightly over the third period, during which the conception of "master-morality" attained its chief and most rigid emphasis, although I gather that to Nietzsche's disciples as to his foes this conception seems of primary import- ance. This idea of "master-morality" is in fact a solid fossilised chunk, easy to handle for friendly or unfriendly hands. The earlier and more living work — the work of the man who truly said that it is with thinkers as with snakes : those that cannot shed their skins die — is less obviously tangible. So the " master- morality" it is that your true Nietzschian is most likely to close his fist over. It would be unkind to say more, for Nietzsche himself has been careful to scatter through his works, on the subject of disciples and followers generally, very scathing remarks which must be sufficiently painful to any faithful Nietzschian. We are helped in understanding Nietzsche's philosophic significance if we understand his precise ideal. The psychological analysis of every great thinker's work seems to reveal some underlying fundamental image or thought — Nietzsche. 6g often enough simple and homely in character — which he has carried with him into the most abstract regions. Thus Fraser has found good reason to suppose that Hegel's main ideas were suggested by the then recent discovery of galvanism. In Nietzsche's case this key is to be found in the persistent image of an attitude. As a child, his sister tells us, he had been greatly impressed by a rope-dancer who had performed his feats over the market-place at Naumburg, and throughout his work, as soon as he had attained to real self-expression, we may trace the image of the dancer. " I do not know," he somewhere says, " what the mind of a philo- sopher need desire more than to be a good dancer. For dancing is his ideal, his art also, indeed his only piety, his 'divine worship.'" In all Nietzsche's best work we are conscious of this ideal of the dancer, strong, supple, vigorous, yet harmonious and well-balanced. It is the dance of the athlete and the acrobat rather than the make-believe of the ball-room, and behind the easy equipoise of such dancing lie patient training and effort. The chief character of good dancing is its union of the maximum of energetic movement with the maximum of well-balanced grace. The whole muscular system is alive to restrain any excess, so that however wild and free the movement may seem it is always measured ; excess would /O Affirmations. mean ignominious collapse. When in his later years Nietzsche began, as he said, to " philoso- phise with the hammer," and to lay about him savagely at every hollow " idol " within reach, he departed from his better ideal of dancing, and his thinking became intemperate, reckless, desperate. Nietzsche had no system, probably because the idea that dominated his thought was an image, and not a formula, the usual obsession of philosophers, such as may be clapped on the universe at any desired point. He remarks in one place that a philosopher believes the worth of his philosophy to lie in the structure, but that what we ultimately value are the finely carven and separate stones with which he builded, and he was clearly anxious to supply the elaborated stones direct. In time he came to call himself a realist, using the term, in no philosophic sense, to indicate his reverence for the real and essential facts of life, the things that conduce to fine living. He desired to detach the " bad conscience " from the things that are merely wicked traditionally, and to attach it to the things that are anti-natural, anti-instinctive, anti-sensuous. He sought to inculcate veneration for the deep-lying sources of life, to take us down to the bed-rock of life, the rock whence we are hewn. He held that man, as a reality, with all his courage and Nietzsche. 7^ cunning, is himself worthy of honour, but that man's ideals are absurd and morbid, the mere dregs in the drained cup of life; or, as he eventually said— and it is a saying which will doubtless seal his fate in the minds of many estimable persons— man's ideals are his only partie honteuse, of which we may avoid any close examination. Nietzsche's " realism " was thus simply a vigorous hatred of all dreaming that tends to depreciate the value of life, and a vivid sense that man himself is the ens realisshniim. A noteworthy point in Nietzsche's concep- tion of philosophy is his increasingly clear conception of its fundamentally psychological character. I mean to say that Nietzsche knows that a man's philosophy, to be real, must be the inevitable outcome of his own psychic con- stitution. It is a point that philosophers have never seen. Perhaps Nietzsche was the first, however hesitatingly, to realise it. It is only in the recognition of this fact that the eirenicon of philosophies— and one might add, of religions —can ever be found. The philosopher of old said: "This is my conception of the universe;" it was well. But he was apt to add: " It is t/ie conception of the universe," and so put himself hopelessly in the wrong. It is as undignified to think another man's philosophy as to wear another man's cast-off clothes. Only the poor 72 Affirmations, in spirit or in purse can find any satisfaction in doing either. A philosophy or reh'gion can only fit the man for whom it was made. "There has only been one Christian," as Nietzsche put it, " and he died on the cross." But why waste energy in trying to manufacture a second Christian ? We may be very sure that we can never find another Christian whom Christianity would fit so admirably as it once fitted Christ. Why not rest content with Christ? Let Brown be a Brownite and Robin- son a Robinsonian. It is not good that they should exchange their philosophies, or that either should insist on thrusting his threadbare misfits on Jones, who prefers to be metaphysi- cally naked. When men have generally begun to realise this the world will be a richer and an honester world, and a pleasanter one as well. That Nietzsche had vaguely begun to realise it seems to me his chief claim to distinction in the purely philosophic field. To recognise the free and direct but dis- connected nature of Nietzsche's many-sided vision of the world is to lessen the force of his own antagonisms as well as of the antagonisms he has excited. Much of Nietzsche's work, especially in the third period, is the utterance of profound half-truths, keenly and personally felt, but still half-truths of which he has himself elsewhere supplied the complements. The Nietzsche. 73 reason is that during that period he was not so much expressing himself as appealing pas- sionately against himself to those failing forces whose tonic influence he thirsted after. The hardness, the keen sword, the reckless energy he idealised were the things that had slipped utterly away and left him defenceless to the world. He grew to worship cruel strength as the consumptive Keats, the sickly Thoreau, loved beauty and health, with " the desire of the moth for the star." Such an attitude has its rightness and power, so long as we understand it, though it comes short of the serenity of the greatest spirits who seek, like Goethe, to live at each moment in the whole. The master-morality of Nietzsche's later days, on which friends and foes have alike insisted, is a case in point. This appears to have been hailed, or resented, as a death-blow struck at the modern democratic regime. To take a broad view of Nietzsche's philosophic attitude is to realise that both views are alike out of place. On this matter, as on many others, Nietzsche moved in a line which led him to face an opposite direction in his decay from that which he faced in his imma- turity. He began by regarding democracy as the standard of righteousness, and ended by asserting that the world only exists for the pro- duction of a few great men. It would be foolish to regard either of the termini as the last out- 74 Affinnations. post of wisdom. But in the passage between these two points many excellent things are said by the way. Nietzsche was never enamoured of socialism or democracy for its own sake; reasonably enough, he will not even admit that we have yet attained democracy; though the horses, indeed, are new, as yet "the roads are the same old roads, the wheels the same old wheels." But he points out that the value of democracy lies in its guarantee of individual freedom: Cyclopean walls are being built, with much toil and dust, but the walls will be a rampart against any invasion of barbarians or any new slavery, against the despotism of capital and the despotism of party. The workers may regard the walls as an end in themselves; we are free to value them for the fine flowers of culture which will grow in the gardens they inclose. To me, at least, this attitude of Nietzsche's maturity seems the ample justifi- cation of democracy. Nietzsche was not, however, greatly interested in questions of government ; he was far more deeply interested in questions of morals. In his treatment of morals — no doubt chiefly in the last period — there is a certain element of paradox. It must again be pointed out that this is to be explained by the organic demands of Nietzsche's own nature. In attacking the excessive tendency to sympathy which he Nietzsche. 75 seemed to see around him he was hygienically defending himself from his own excessive sym- pathy. His sister quotes with a smile the declaration that his Paradise lay beneath the shadow of his sword ; we scarcely need her assurance of his tender-hearted sensitiveness. He could attack relentlessly, but he never attacked a person save as the symbol of what he regarded as a false principle held in un- deserved honour. When he realised that the subject of such attack was really a living person he was full of remorse. He attacked Strauss because Strauss was the successful representa- tive of a narrow ideal of culture ; a few months later Strauss died, having, it now appears, borne the onset philosophically enough, and Nietzsche was full of grief lest he had em- bittered the dying man's last hours. It was because he had himself suffered from the excesses of his own sympathy that he was able so keenly to analyse the secrets of sym- pathy. He spoke as the Spanish poet says that every poet — and indeed every seer — must always speak, /^ir la hoca de sic hen'da, through the mouth of his wound. That is why his voice is often so poignantly intimate ; it is also why we sometimes find this falsetto note of paradox. In his last period, Nietzsche grows altogether impatient of morals, calls himself an immoralist, fervently exhorts us to become wickeder. But y6 Affirmations. if any young disciple came to the teacher asking, "What must I do to become wickeder?" it docs not appear that Nietzsche bade him to steal, bear false witness, commit adultery, or do any other of the familiar and commonly- accepted wickednesses. Nietzsche preached wickedness with the same solemn exaltation that Carducci lauded Satan. What he desired was far indeed from any rehabilitation of easy vice ; it was the justification of neglected and unsanctified virtues. At the same time, and while Nietzsche's immoralist is just as austere a person as the mere moralists who have haunted the world for many thousand years, it is clear that Nietzsche wished strictly to limit the sphere of morals. He never fails to point out how large a region of life and art lies legitimately out- side the moral jurisdiction. In an age in which many moralists desire to force morals into every part of life and art — and even assume a certain air of virtue in so doing — the " immoralist " who lawfully vindicates any region for free cultivation is engaged in a proper and wholesome task. No doubt, however, there will be some to question the value of such a task. Nietzsche the immoralist can scarcely be welcome in every camp, although he remains always a force to be reckoned with. The same may be said of Nietzsche the freethinker. He was, perhaps, Nietzsche. yj the typical freethinker of the age that comes after Renan. Nietzsche had nothing of Renan's genial scepticism and smiling disillusionment; he was less tender to human weakness, for all his long Christian ancestry less Christian, than the Breton seminarist remained to the last. He seems to have shaken himself altogether free of Christianity — so free, that except in his last period he even speaks of it without bitterness — though by no means wholly untouched by that nostalgia of the cloister which now and then pursues even those of us who are farthest from any faith in Christian dogma. He never sought, as among ourselves Pater sought, the germ of Christianity in things pagan, the undying essence of paganism in things Christian. Heathen as he was, I do not think even Heine's visions of the gods in exile could have touched him ; he never felt the charm of fading and faded things. It is remarkable. It is scarcely less remarkable that, far as he was from Christianity, he was equall\' far from what we usually call "paganism," the pasteboard paganism of easy self-indulg- ence and cheerful irresponsibility. It was not so that he understood Hellenism. Matthew Arnold once remarked that the Greeks were never sick or sad. Nietzsche knew better. The greater part of Greek literature bears witness that the Hellenes were for ever 78 Affirmations. wrestling with the problems of pain. And none who came after have more poignantly- uttered the pangs of human affairs, or more sweetly the consolations of those pangs, than the great disciples of the Greeks who created the Roman world. The classic world of nymphs and fauns is an invention of the moderns. The real classic world, like the modern world, was a world of suffering. The difference lay in the method of facing that suffering. Nietzsche chose the classic method from no desire to sport with Amaryllis in the shade, but because he had known forms of torture for which the mild complacencies of modern faith seemed to offer no relief. If we must regard Nietzsche as a pagan, it is as the Pascal of paganism. The freethinker, it is true, was more cheerful and hopeful than the believer, but there is the same tragic sincerity, the same restless self- torment, the same sense of the abyss.^ ^ Pater's description of the transition we may trace from the easy prose of Pascal's first book to the " perpetual agonia " of his later work, applies with scarcely a change to the similar transition in Nietzsche : — " Everywhere in the Letters he had seemed so great a master — a master of himself — never at a loss, taking the conflict so lightly, with so light a heart : in the great Atlantean travail of the Thoughts his feet sometimes ' are almost gone.' In his soul's agony theological abstractions seem to become personal powers. ... In truth, into his typical diagnosis, as it may seem, of the tragedy of the human soul, there have passed not merely the personal feelings, the tempera- ment of an individual, but his malady also, a physical malady." Nietzsche. 79 There still remains Nietzsche, the apostle of culture, the philosopher engaged in the criticism of life. From first to last, wherever you open his books, you light on sayings that cut to the core of the questions that every modern thinking man must face. I take, almost at random, a few passages from a single book : of convictions he writes that "a man possesses opinions as he possesses fish, in so far as he owns a fishing-net; a man must go fishing and be lucky, then he has his own fish, his own opinions ; I speak of living opinions, living fish. Some men are content to possess fossils in their cabinets — and convictions in their heads." Of the problem of the relation of science to culture he says well : " The best and wholesomest thing in science, as in mountains, is the air that blows there. It is because of that air that we spiritual weaklings avoid and defame science;" and he points out that the work of science — with its need for sincerity, infinite patience, complete self-abnegation — calls for men of nobler make than poetry needs. When we have learnt to trust science and to learn from it, then it will be possible so to tell natural history that " every one who hears it is inspired to health and gladness as the heir and continuer of humanity." This is how he rebukes those foolish persons who grow impatient with critics : " Remember that critics are insects who only 8o Affirmations. sting to live and not to hurt : they want our blood and not our pain." And he utters this wise saying, himself forgetting it in later years: " Growth in wisdom may be exactly measured by decrease in bitterness." Nietzsche desires to prove nothing, and is reckless of consistency. He looks at every question that comes before him with the same simple, intent, penetrative gaze, and whether the aspects that he reveals are new or old, he seldom fails to bring us a fresh stimulus. Culture, as he understood it, consists for the modern man in the task of choosing the simple and indispensable things from the chaos of crude material which to-day overwhelms us. The man who will live at the level of the culture of his time is like the juggler who must keep a number of plates spinning in the air ; his life must be a constant training in suppleness and skill so that he may be a good athlete. But he is also called on to exert his skill in the selection and limitation of his task. Nietzsche is greatly occupied with the simpli- fication of culture. Our suppleness and skill must be exercised alone on the things that are vital, essential, primitive ; the rest may be thrown aside. He is for ever challenging the multifarious materials for culture, testing them with eye and hand ; we cannot prove them too severely, he seems to say, nor cast aside too contemptuously the things that a real man has Nietzsche. 8 1 no need of for fine living. What must I do to be saved? What do I need for the best and fullest life? — that is the everlasting question that the teacher of life is called upon to answer. And we cannot be too grateful to Nietzsche for the stern penetration — the more acute for his ever-present sense of the limits of energy — with which he points from amid the mass to the things which most surely belong to our eternal peace. Nietzsche's style has often been praised. The style was certainly the man. There can be little doubt, moreover, that there is scarcely any other German style to compare with it, though such eminence means far less in a country where style has rarely been cultivated than it would mean in France or even England. Sallust awoke his sense for style, and may account for some characteristics of his style. He also enthusiastically admired Horace as the writer who had produced the maximum of energy with the minimum of material. A concentrated Roman style, significant and weighty at every point, cere perennius, was always his ideal. Cer- tainly the philologist's aptitudes helped here to teach him the value and force of words, as jewels for the goldsmith to work with, and not as mere worn-out counters to slip through the fingers. One may call it a muscular style, a style wrought with the skilful strength of hand and 6 82 Affirmations. arm. It scarcely appeals to the ear. It lacks the restful simplicity of the greatest masters, the plangent melody, the seemingly unconscious magic quivering along our finest-fibred nerves. Such effects we seem to hear now and again in Schopenhauer, but rarely or never from any other German. This style is titanic rather than divine, but the titanic virtues it certainly pos- sesses in fullest measure : robust and well-tem- pered vigour, concentration, wonderful plastic force in moulding expression. It becomes over-emphatic at last. When Nietzsche threw aside the dancer's ideal in order to " philosophise with the hammer," the result on his style was as disastrous as on his thought ; both alike took on the violent and graceless character of the same implement. He speaks indeed of the virtue of hitting a nail on the head, but it is a less skilled form of virtue than good dancing. Whether he was dancing or hammering, how- ever, Nietzsche certainly converted the whole of himself into his work, as in his view every philo- sopher is bound to do, " for just that art of transformation is philosophy." That he was entirely successful in being a " real man " one may doubt. His excessive sensitiveness to the commonplace in life, and his deficiency in the sexual instinct — however highly he may have rated the importance of sex in life — largely cut Nietzsche, 83 him off from true fellowship with the men who are most " real " to us. He was less tolerant and less humane than his master Goethe ; his incisive insight, and, in many respects, better intellectual equipment, are more than compen- sated by this lack of breadth. But, as his friend the historian Burckhardt has said, he worked mightily for the increase of independence in the world. Every man, indeed, works with the limitations of his qualities, just as we all struggle beneath the weight of the superin- cumbent atmosphere ; our defects are even a part of our qualities, and it would be foolish to quarrel with them. Nietzsche succeeded in being himself, and it was a finely rare success. Whether he was a "real man" matters less. With passionate sincerity he expressed his real self and his best self, abhorring, on the one hand, what with Voltaire and Verlaine he called "litera- ture," and, on the other, all that mere indigested material, the result of mental dyspepsia, of which he regarded Carlyle as the supreme warning. A man's real self, as he repeated so often, consists of the things which he has truly digested and assimilated ; he must always " con- quer" his opinions; it is only such conquests which he has the right to report to men as his own. His thoughts are born of his pain ; he has imparted to them of his own blood, his own pleasure and torment. Nietzsche himself held 84 Ajjirmations. that sufifcring' and even disease are almost in- dispensable to the philosopher ; great pain is the final emancipator of the spirit," those great slow pains that take their time, and burn us up like green wood. " I doubt whether such pain betters us," he remarks, " but I know that it deepens us." That is the stuff of Nietzsche's Hellenism, as expressed in the most light- hearted of his books. Virescit volmre virtus. It is that which makes him, when all is said, a great critic of life. It is a consolation to many — I have seen it so stated in a respectable review — that Nietzsche went mad. No doubt also it was once a con- solation to many- that Socrates was poisoned, that Jesus was crucified, that Bruno was burnt. But hemlock and the cross and the stake proved sorry weapons against the might of ideas even in those days, and there is no reason to suppose that a doctor's certificate will be more effectual in our own. Of old time we killed our great men as soon as i^heir visionary claims became inconvenient ; now, in our mercy, we leave the tragedy of genius to unroll itself to the bitter close. The devils to whom the modern Faustus is committed have waxed cunning with the ages. Nietzsche has met, in its most re- lentless form, the fate of Pascal and Swift and Rousseau. That fact may carry what weight it will in any final estimate of his place as a moral Nietzsche. 85 teacher : it cannot touch his position as an aboriginal force. He remains in the first rank of the distinguished and significant personalities our century has produced. 86 CASANOVA. There are few more delightful books in the world than Casanova's Manoires. — That is a statement I have long vainly sought to see in print. It is true, one learns casually that various eminent literary personages have cherished a high regard for this autobiography, have even considered it the ideal autobiography, that Wendell Holmes was once heard defending Casanova, that Thackeray found him good enough to steal from. But these eminent personages — and how many more we shall never know — locked up the secret of their admiration for this book in some remote casket of their breasts ; they never confided it to the cynical world. Every properly constituted "man of letters" has always recognised that any public allusion to Casanova should begin and end with lofty moral reprobation of his unspeakable turpitude. No doubt whatever — and this apart from the question as to whether his autobiography should be counted as moral or immoral literature — Casanova delivered himself bound into the Casanova. 87 hands of the moralists. He recognised this ; his autobiography, as he himself truly said, was " a confession, if ever there was one," But he wrote at the end of a long and full life, in the friendly seclusion of a lonely Bohemian castle, when all things had become indifferent to him save the vivid memories of the past. It mattered little to him that the whirlwind of 1789 had just swept away the eighteenth century together with the moral maxims that passed current in that century. We have to accept these facts at the outset when we approach Casanova. And if a dweller in the highly respectable nineteenth century may be forgiven a first exclamation of horror at Casa- nova's wickedness, he has wofully failed in critical insight if he allows that exclamation to be his last word concerning these Mhnoires. There are at least three points of view from which Casanova's Memoires are of deep and permanent interest. In the first place they constitute an important psychological docu- ment as the full and veracious presentation of a certain human type in its most complete development. In the second place, as a mere story of adventure and without reference to their veracity, the Memories have never been surpassed, and only equalled by books written on a much smaller scale. In the third place, we here possess an unrivalled picture of the 88 Affirmations. eighteenth century in its most characteristic aspects throughout Europe. I. Casanovi lived in an age which seems to have been favourable to the spontaneous revela- tion of human nature in literature. It was not only the age in which the novel reached full development ; it was the age of diaries and autobiographies. Pepys, indeed, though he died in the eighteenth century, had written his diary long before ; but during Casanova's lifetime Boswell was writing that biography which is so wonderful largely because it is so nearly an autobiography. Casanova's communicative countryman, Gozzi, was also his contemporary. Rousseau's Confessions only preceded Casanova's Memoires by a few years, and a little later Restif de la Bretonne wrote Monsieur Nicolas, and Madame Roland her Memoires Particulieres. All these autobiographies are very unlike Casa- nova's. They mostly seem to present the shady sides of otherwise eminent and respectable lives. The highly-placed government official of versatile intellectual tastes exhibits himself as a monster of petty weaknesses ; the eloquent apostle of the return to Nature uncovers the corroding morbidities we should else never suspect ; the philanthropic pioneer in social Casanova. 89 reform exposes himself in a state of almost maniacal eroticism ; the austere heroine who was nourished on Plutarch confesses that she is the victim of unhappy passion. We are conscious of no such discords in Casanova's autobiography. Partly it may be because we have no other picture of Casanova before our eyes. Moreover, he had no conventional ideals to fall short of; he was an adventurer from the first. " I am proud because I am nothing," he used to say. He could not boast of his birth; he never held high position ; for the greatest part of his active career he was an exile ; at every moment of his life he was forced to rely on his own real and personal qualities. But the chief reason why we feel no disturbing discord in Casanova's Mchnoires lies in the admirable skill with which he has therein exploited his unquestionable sincerity. He is a consummate master in the dignified narration of undignified experiences. Fortified, it is true, by a confessed and excessive amour propre, he never loses his fine sense of equilibrium, his power of presenting his own personality broadly and harmoniously. He has done a few dubious things in his time, he seems to say, and now and again found himself in positions that were ridiculous enough ; but as he looks back he feels that the like may have happened to any of us. He views these things with complete 90 Affirmations. human tolerance as a necessary part of the whole picture, which it would be idle to slur over or apologise for. He records them simply, not without a sense of humour, but with no undue sense of shame. In his heart, perhaps, he is confident that he has given the world one of its greatest books, and that posterity will require of him no such rhetorical justification as Rousseau placed at the head of his Con- fessions. In the preface to the Me'vioires, Casanova is sufficiently frank. He has not scrupled, he tells us, to defraud fools and rascals, " when neces- sary," and he has never regretted it. But such incidents have been but episodes in his life. He is not a sensualist, he says, for he has never neglected his duty — " when I had any " — for the allurements of sense ; yet the main business of his life has ever been in the world of sense ; "there is none of greater importance." " I have always loved women and have done my best to make them love me. I have also delighted in good cheer, and I have passionately followed whatever has excited my curiosity." Now in old age he reviews the joys of his life. He has learnt to be content with one meal a day, in spite of a sound digestion, but he recalls the dishes that delighted him: Neapolitan macaroni, Spanish olla podrida, Newfoundland cod, high- flavoured game, old cheese (has he not collected Casanoz'a. 91 material for a Dicttonnaire des Froinogcs ?), and without any consciousness of abrupt transition he passes on to speak of the fragrant sweetness of the women he had loved. Then with a smile of pity he turns on those who call such tastes depraved, the poor insensate fools who think the Almighty is only able to enjoy our sorrow and abstinence, and bestows upon us for nought the gift of self-respect, the love of praise, the desire to excel, energy, strength, courage, and the power to kill ourselves when we will. And with the strain of Stoicism which is ever present to give fibre to his Epicureanism, he quotes the maxim which might well belong to both philo- sophies : " Nemo lasditur nisi a seipso." The fact that Casanova was on one side a Venetian must count for something in any attempt to explain him. Not indeed that Venice ever produced more than one Casanova; I would imply no such disrespect to Venice — or to Casanova — but the racial soil was favourable to such a personality. The Venetians are a branch of a more northern people who long since settled by the southern sea to grow mellow in the sunshine. It suited them well, for they expanded into one of the finest races in Christendom, and certainly one of the least Christian races there, a solid, well-tempered race, self-controlled and self-respecting. The Venetian genius is the genius of sensuous en- 92 Affirmations. joymcnt, of tolerant humanity, of unashamed earthHness. Whatever was sane and stable in Casanova, and his instinctive distaste for the morbid and perverse, he owes to his Venetian maternal ancestry. If it is true that he was not a mere sensualist, it was by no means because of his devotion to duty — "when I had any," — but because the genuine sensualist is only alive on the passive side of his nature, and in Casanova's nervous system the development of the sensory fibres is compensated and held in balance by the equal vigour of the motor fibres; what he is quick to enjoy he is strong and alert to achieve. Thus he lived the full and varied life that he created for himself at his own good pleasure out of nothing, by the sole power of his own magnificent wits. And now the self- sufficing Venetian sits down to survey his vvork and finds that it is good. It has not always been found so since. A " self-made " man, if ever there was one, Casanova is not revered by those who worship self-help. The record of his life will easily outlive the largest fortune ever made in any counting-house, but the life itself remains what we call a " wasted " life. Thrift, prudence, modesty, scrupulous integrity, strict attention to business — it is useless to come to Casanova for any of these virtues. They were not even in his blood ; he was only half Venetian. Casajiova. 93 The Casanova family was originally Spanish. The first Casanova on record was a certain Don Jacobo, of illegitimate birth, who in the middle of the fifteenth century became secretary to King Alfonso. He fell in love with a lady destined to the religious life, and the day after she had pronounced her vows he carried her off from her convent to Rome, where he finally obtained the forgiveness and bene- diction of the Pope. The son of this union, Don Juan, killed an officer of the King of Naples, fled from Rome, and sought fortune with Columbus, dying on the voyage. Don Juan's son, Marcantonio, secretary to a cardinal, was noted in his day as an epigrammatic poet; but his satire was too keen, and he also had to flee from Rome. His son became a colonel, and, unlike his forefathers, died peacefully, in extreme old age, in France. In this soldier's grandson, Casanova's father, the adventurous impulsiveness of the family again came out ; he ran away from home at nineteen with a young actress, and himself became an actor; subsequently he left the actress and then fell in love with a young Venetian beauty of sixteen, Zanetta P^arusi, a shoemaker's daughter. But a mere actor could find no favour in a respectable family, so the young couple ran away and were married ; the hero of these Me moires^ born on the 2nd April, 1725, was 94 Affirmations. their first-born. There is probably no reason to doubt the substantial accuracy of this family history, but if one desired to invent an ancestry for Casanova he could scarcely better it. His race helps to account for Casanova, but the real explanation of the man can only lie in his own congenital organisation. That he was a radically abnormal person is fairly clear. Not that he was morbid either in body or mind. On the contrary, he was a man of fine presence, of abounding health — always looking ten years younger than his age — of the most robust appetites, a great eater, who delighted to see others, especially women, eat heartily also, a man of indubitable sexual vigour ; however great the demands he made upon his physical energy it seldom failed to respond, and his capacity for rest was equally great ; he could sleep nineteen hours at a stretch. His mental health was not less sound. The most punctilious alienist, with this frank and copious history before him, could not commit Casanova to an asylum. Whatever offences against social codes he may have committed, Casanova can scarcely be said to have sinned against natural laws. He was only abnormal because so natural a person within the gates of civilisation is neces- sarily abnormal and at war with his environ- ment. Far from being the victim of morbidities and perversities, Casanova presents to us the Casanova. 95 natural man in excelsis. He was a man for whom the external world existed, and who reacted to all the stimuli it presents to the healthy normal organism. His intelligence was immensely keen and alert, his resourcefulness, his sagacious audacity, his presence of mind, were all of the first order. He was equally swift to feel, to conceive, and to act. His mental organisation was thus singularly har- monious, and hence his success in gratifying his eager and immense appetite for the world, an appetite unsatiated and insatiable even to the last, or he would have found no pleasure in writing these M^moires. Casanova has been described as a psychological type of instability. That is to view him superficially. A man who adapts himself so readily and so effectively to any change in his environment or in his desires only exhibits the instability which marks the most intensely vital organisms. The energy and ability which Casanova displayed in gratify- ing his instincts would have sufficed to make a reputation of the first importance in any depart- ment, as a popular statesman, a great judge, a merchant prince, and enabled him to die worn out by the monotonous and feverish toil of the senate, the court, or the counting-house. Casa- nova chose to live. A crude and barbarous choice it seems to us, with our hereditary instinct to spend our lives in wasting the 9^ Affirmations. reasons for living. But it is certain that Casa- nova never repented his choice. Assuredly we need not, for few judges, statesmen, or merchants have ever left for the joy of humanity any legacy of their toil equal to these Meinoires. But such swift energy of vital action and reaction, such ardour of deed in keeping pace with desire, are in themselves scarcely normal. Casanova's abnormality is suggested by the tendency to abnormality which we find in his family. We have seen what men his ancestors were ; in reading the Meinoires we gather incidentally that one of his brothers had married, though impotent, and another brother is described as a somewhat feeble- minded ne'er-do-well. All the physical and mental potency of the family was intensely concentrated in Casanova. Yet he himself in early childhood seems to have been little better than an idiot either in body or mind. He could recall nothing that happened before he was eight years of age. He was not expected to live; he suffered from prolonged haemorrhages from the nose, and the vision of blood was his earliest memory. As a child he habitually kept his mouth open, and his face was stupid. " Thickness of the blood," said the physicians of those days; it seems probable that he suffered from growths in the nose which, as we now know, produce such physical and mental inferiority as Casa- Casanova. 97 nova describes. The cure was spontaneous. He was taken to Padua, and shortly afterwards began to develop wonderfully both in stature and intelligence. In after years he had little cause to complain either of health or intellect. It is notable, however, that when, still a boy, he commenced his ecclesiastical training (against his wishes, for he had chosen to be a doctor), he failed miserably as a preacher, and broke down in the pulpit ; thus the Church lost a strange ornament. Moreover, with all his swift sensa- tion and alert response, there was in Casanova an anomalous dulness of moral sensibility. The insults to Holy Religion which seem to have brought him to that prison from which he effected his marvellous escape, were scarcely the serious protests of a convinced heretic ; his deliberate trickery of Mme. d'Urfe was not only criminal but cruel. His sense of the bonds of society was always somewhat veiled, and although the veil never became thick, and might be called the natural result of an adven- turer's life, one might also, perhaps, maintain that it was a certain degree of what is sometimes called moral imbecility that made Casanova an adventurer. But while we thus have to recognise that he was a man of dulled moral sensibility, we must also recognise that he possessed a vigorous moral consciousness of his own, or we misunderstand him altogether. 7 98 AffirjuaiioHS. The point to be remembered is that the thres- hold of his moral sensibility was not easily reached. There are some people whose tactile sensibility is so obtuse that it requires a very wide separation of the aesthesiometer to get the right response. It was so with Casanova's moral sensitiveness. But, once aroused, his conscience responded energetically enough. It seems doubtful whether, from his own point of view, he ever fell into grave sin, and therefore he is happily free from remorse. No great credit is thus due to him ; the same psycho- logical characteristic is familiar in all criminals. It is not difficult to avoid plucking the apples of shame when so singularly few grow on your tree. Casanova's moral sensibility and its limits come out, where a man's moral sensibility will come out, in his relations with women. Women played a large part in Casanova's life; he was nearly always in love. We may use the word " love " here in no euphemistic sense, for al- though Casanova's passions grew and ripened with the rapidity born of long experience in these matters, so fresh is the vitality of the man that there is ever a virginal bloom on every new ardour. He was as far removed from the cold-blooded libertine typified in Laclos's Val- mont, unscrupulously using women as the in- struments of his own lust, as from Laura's Casanova. 99 sonneteering lover. He had fully grasped what the latest writer on the scientific psychology of sex calls the secondary law of courting, namely, the development. in the male of an imaginative attentiveness to the psychical and bodily states of the female, in place of an exclusive attentive- ness to his own gratification. It is not impossible that in these matters Casanova could have given a lesson to many virtuous husbands of our own highly moral century. He never sank to the level of the vulgar maxim that " all's fair in love and war." He sought his pleasure in the pleasure, and not in the complaisance, of the women he loved, and they seem to have grate- fully and tenderly recognised his skill in the art of love-making. Casanova loved many women, but broke few hearts. The same women appear again and again through his pages, and for the most part no lapse of years seems to deaden the gladness with which he goes forth to meet them anew. That he knew himself well enough never to take either wife or mistress must be counted as a virtue, such as it was, in this incomparable lover of so many women. A man of finer moral fibre could scarcely have loved so many women ; a man of coarser fibre could never have left so many women happy. This very lack of moral delicacy which shuts Casanova off from the finest human development is an advantage to the autobiographer. It in- 100 Affirmations. sures his sincerity because he is unconscious of offence ; it saves us from any wearisome self- justification, because, for all his amused self- criticism, he sees no real need for justification. In Rousseau's Confessions we hear the passionate pleader against men at the tribunal of God; here we are conscious neither of opponent nor tribunal. Casanova is neither a pillar of society nor yet one of the moral Samsons who delight to pull down the pillars of society; he has taken the world as it is, and he has taken himself as he is, and he has enjoyed them both hugely. So he is free to set forth the whole of himself, his achievements, his audacities, his failures, his little weaknesses and superstitions, his amours, his quarrels, his good fortune and his bad fortune in the world that on the whole he has found so interesting and happy a place to dwell in. And his book remains an unending source of delight- ful study of the man of impulse and action in all his moods. The self-reliant man, immensely apt for enjoyment, who plants himself solidly with his single keen wit before the mighty oyster of the world, has never revealed himself so clearly before. What manner of man Casanova seemed to his contemporaries has only been discovered of recent years ; and while the picture which we obtain of him has been furnished by his enemies, and was not meant to flatter, it admirably Casanova. loi supports the Memoir es. In 1755 a spy of the Venetian Inquisition reported that Casanova united impiety, imposture, and wantonness to a degree that inspired horror. It was in that same year that he was arrested, chiefly on the charge of contempt for reh'gion, and sentenced to five years' imprisonment. Fif- teen months later he had effected his famous escape, and was able to pursue his career as an assured and accompHshed adventurer who had brilhantly completed his apprenticeship. It is not until many years later, in 1772, when his long efforts to obtain pardon from his country still remained unsuccessful, that we obtain an admirable picture of him from the Venetian agent at Ancona. " He comes and goes where he will," the agent reports, " with open face and haughty mien, always well equipped. He is a man of some forty years at most [really about forty-eight, thus confirming Casanova's state- ment that he was always taken for some ten years younger than his years], of lofty stature, of fine and vigorous aspect, with bright eyes and very brown skin. He wears a short, chestnut-coloured peruke. I am told that his character is bold and disdainful, but especially that he is full of speech, and of witty and well- instructed speech." Two years later Casanova was at last permitted to return to Venice. He there accepted the post of secret agent of the I02 Affirmations. State Inquisition for service within the city. Like Defoe and Toland, who were also secret political agents, he attempted to justify himself on grounds of public duty. In a few years, however, he was dismissed, perhaps, as Baschet suggests, on account of the fact that his reports contained too much philosophy and not enough espionage; probably it was realised that a man of such powerful individuality and independence was not fitted for servile uses. Finally, in 1782, he was banished from Venice for an offence to which the blood of the Casanovas had always been easily inclined — he published an audacious satire against a patrician. From Venice he went to Trieste, and thence to Vienna. There he met Count Waldstein, a fervent adept of Kabba- listic science, a subject in which Casanova him- self claimed to be proficient; he had found it useful in certain dealings with credulous people. In 1784 the count offered him the post of librarian, with a salary of one thousand florins, at his castle of Dux, in Bohemia. It is said to be a fine castle, and is still noted for its charm- ing park. Here this prince of Bohemians spent the remainder of his life, devoting seven years to the Memoires, on which he was still engaged at his death. A terra-cotta bust discovered at the castle (and etched some years ago for Le Livre) shows him in mature age, a handsome, energetic, and imposing head, with somewhat Co sail ova. 103 deep-set eyes; it is by no means the head of a scamp, but rather that of a philosopher, a philosopher with unusual experience of affairs, a successful statesman, one might say. A medallion portrait, of later date, which has also been reproduced, shows him at the age of sixty- three with lean, eager face, and lofty, though receding forehead, the type of the man of quick perception and swift action, the eagle type of man. The Prince de Ligne has also left a description of him as he appeared in old age, now grown very irritable, ready to flare up at any imagined insult, engaged in perpetual war- fare with domestics, but receiving the highest consideration from those who knew how to appreciate the great qualities of the man and his unequalled experiences, and who knew also how to indulge his susceptibilities and smile at his antique fashions. Once he went off in a huff to Weimar, and was graciously received by the Duke, but he soon came back again ; all the favours there were showered on a certain court favourite, one Goethe. It is clear, as we read the Prince de Ligne's detailed description, that the restless old adventurer had need, even in the peaceful seclusion of Dux, of all the con- solation yielded by Socrates, Horace, Seneca, and Boethius, his favourite philosophers. Here, at Dux, on the 4th of June 1798, Casanova died. " Bear witness that I have lived as a philosopher 1 04 Affirmations. and die as a Christian ; " that, we are told, was his last utterance after he had received the sacra- ments. From that moment Casanova with everything that concerned him was covered by a pall of oblivion. He seems to have been carelessly cast aside, together with the century of which he was so characteristic, and, as it now appears, so memorable a child. The world in which he had lived so joyously and completely had been transformed by the Revolution. The new age of strenuous commercialism and complacent philanthropy was in its vigorous youth, a sword in its right hand and a Bible in its left. The only adventurer who found favour now was he who took the glad news of salvation to the heathen, or mowed them down to make new openings for trade. Had he been born later, we may be well assured, Casanova would have known how to play his part; he would not have fallen short of Borrow, who became an agent of the Bible Society. But as it was, what had the new age to do with Casanova ? No one cared, no one even yet has cared, so much as to examine the drawers and cupboards full of papers which he left behind at Dux. Only on the 13th of February, 1820, was the oblivion a little stirred. On that date a certain Carlo Angiolieri appeared at Leipzig in the office of the famous publisher, Brockhaus, carrying a Casanova. 105 voluminous manuscript in the handwriting (as we now know) of Casanova and bearing the title, Histoire de ma Viejusqu'a Van 1797. But even the appearance of Carlo Angiolieri failed to dissipate the gloom. Fifty years more were to pass before the figure of Casanova again became clear. This man, so ardently alive in every fibre, had now become a myth. The sagacious world — which imparts the largest dole of contempt to the pilgrim who brings back to it the largest gifts — refused to take Casanova seriously. The shrewd critic wondered who wrote Casanova, just as he has since wondered who wrote Shakespeare. Paul Lacroix paid Stendhal the huge compliment of suggesting that he had written the M^moireSy a sufificiently ingenious suggestion, for in Stendhal's Dauphiny spirit there is something of that love of adven- ture which is supremely illustrated in Casanova. But we now know that, as Armand Baschet first proved, Casanova himself really wrote his own Menioires. Moreover, so far as investigation has yet been able to go, he wrote with strict regard to truth. Wherever it is possible to test Casanova, his essential veracity has always been vindicated. In the nature of things it is im- possible to verify much that he narrates. When, however, we remember that he was telling the story of his life primarily for his own pleasure, it is clear that he had no motive for deception ; io6 Affirvialions. and when we consider the surpassingly discredit- able episodes which he has recorded, we may- recall that he has given not indeed positive proof of sincerity, but certainly the best that can be given in the absence of direct proof. It remains a question how far a man is able to recollect the details of the far past — the con- versations he held, the garments he wore, the meals he ate — so precisely as Casanova professes to recollect them. This is a psychological problem which has not yet been experimentally examined. There are, however, great individual differences in memory, and there is reason to believe that an organisation, such as Casanova's, for which the external world is so vivid, is associated with memory-power of high quality. That this history is narrated with absolute precision of detail Casanova himself would probably not have asserted. But there is no reason to doubt his good faith, and there is ex- cellent reason to accept the substantial accuracy of his narrative. It remains a personal docu- ment of a value which will increase rather than diminish as time goes by. It is one of the great autobiographical revelations which the ages have left us, with Augustine's, Cellini's, Rous- seau's, of its own kind supreme. Casanova. 107 II. The Menioires are authentic ; they give us what they profess to give us— the true story of a man who unites (as it has been well said) the characters of Gil Bias and of Figaro. Thus Casanova was the incarnation in real life of the two most typical imaginative figures of his century. Yet even if the Mhnoires had been the invention of some novelist of surpassing genius they would still possess extraordinary interest. We may forget that the book is an autobiography, and still find it, as a story of adventure, the apotheosis of the picaresque novel. The picaresque novel — although a French- man brought it to perfection in Gil Bias — arose and flourished in Spain, Casanova's ancestral country, and its piquancy, variety, and audacity seem to have been very congenial to the Spanish spirit and the Spanish soil. Casanova's Menioires carry this form of story on to a broader and in some respects higher plane. The old picai-o never dared affront the world ; he cringed before it and slunk behind its back to make grimaces. Casanova, too, was an adventurer living by his wits, but he approached the world with the same self-confidence as he approached a beautiful woman, and having won its favours treats it with the same consideration. Unlike the picaro 1 08 Affirmations. whose delight it is to reveal the pettinesses of the men he has duped, Casanova shows his magnificence in adventure by regarding the world as a foeman worthy of all his courtesy; and with incomparable impartiality, as well as skill, he presents to us the narrative of all the perils he encountered or sought. Few old men sitting down in the evening of their days to chatter of old times have been so free as Casanova from the vices of senile literature. He never maunders of the things that are so dear to the aged merely because they are past; he introduces no superfluous reflections or com- ments. We recognise that the hand which keeps this pen so surely to the point is the hand of a man of action. Casanova's skill in narrative is conspicuously shown in the love - adventures which form so large and important a part of his book, as of his life. (Men usually regard love as a bagatelle, he says somewhere, but, for his own part, he adds, he has found no more important business in life.) There would seem to be nothing so difficult as to tell a long series of amours, unshrinkingly, from first to last, with- out drawing a curtain at any stage. Nearly every writer in fiction or in autobiography who has attempted this has only produced an effect of weary monotony or else of oppressive close- ness. But Casanova succeeds. Partly this is due to the variety and individuality he is able Casanova. 109 to give, not only to every incident, but to every woman he meets ; so that his book is a gallery of delightful women, drawn with an art that almost recalls his great contemporary, Goethe. Partly it seems he was aided by his vivid and sympathetic Venetian temperament ; his swift, unliterary style finds time for no voluptuous languors. He was aided even by his im- modesty, for in literature as in the plastic arts and in life itself, the nude is nearer to virtue than the decollete. The firm and absolute pre- cision of every episode in these ]\Itinoires leaves no room for any undue dallying with the fringes of love's garments. Casanova tells his story swiftly and boldly, with no more delay than is needed to record every essential detail ; he is the absolute anti-type to Sterne as a narrator; the most libertine of authors, he is yet free from prurience. Thus the man of action covers the romancer with confusion; this supreme book of adventures is a real man's record of his own real life. But let us forget that it is an autobiography and take it merely as a story. Its immense range of human interest, its audacious realism, its freedom from perversity, entitle us to regard it as a typical story of adventure. And I ask myself: What is the relation of such a book to life ? what is the moral worth of Casanova's Mhnoires ? I lO Affirmations. . A foolish, superfluous question, I know, it seems to many. And I am willing to admit that there may possibly be things in life which it is desirable to do, and yet undesirable to moralise over ; I would even assert that the moral worth of many of our actions lies precisely in their unconsciousness of any moral worth. Yet beneath the freest moral movements there must be a solid basis of social law, just as beneath the most gracious movements of the human body there lies the regulated play of mechanical law. When we find it assumed that there are things which are good to do and not good to justify we may strongly suspect that we have come across a mental muddle. To see the matter rightly we must take it at the beginning. No one can rightly see the moral place of immoral literature — the literature of adventure — in the case of adults unless he sees it in the case of children. Of late years the people who write in newspapers and magazines have loudly abused all stories of the crudely heroic order, the stories of im- possible virtue and unheard-of villainy in far- away lands, of marvellously brave bands under extravagantly reckless leaders, who march on through careless bloodshed to incredible victory or incalculable treasure. The hero of the average boy — magnificent sombrero on head, pi-stols in belt, galloping off on his Casanova. in mighty charger, a villain grasped by the scruff of the neck in each outstretched hand — has been severely mauled. The suggestions offered for the displacement of this literature furnish documents for the psychologist. Let us have cheap lives of Jesus and the Apostle Paul! let us flood the world with the sober romances licensed by religious societies ! — say those good people in the newspapers and the magazines. If they have ever themselves been children, and if so, how they came into the world shrouded in an impenetrable caul which will for ever shut them out from insight into the hearts of the young, is not known, and perhaps is no matter. Putting aside these estimable persons, there is in every heart a chamber dedicated to the impossible, and the younger the heart the larger is this golden ventricle. For the child who can just read, Jack the Giant-killer, and the story of those human-souled swans which make the swan a mystic bird for all our lives, are better worth knowing than any fact of the visible world. Some day the Life of Jesus, and even perhaps the Life of Paul, will seem to be among the sweetest and strangest of the world's fairy- tales; but that day will hardly come until every church and chapel has been spiritually razed to the ground. It cannot come to the genera- tion which has had the name of Jesus thrust down its throat in Sunday-schools and board- 112 Affinnations. schools. We English are a practical, common- sense people, and we cure our children of any hearty taste for religion as confectioners are said to cure their assistants of any excessive taste for sweets, by a preliminary surfeit. No doubt we are very wise, but we postpone in- definitely the day when children will come to our religious tales in the pure gladness of their joy in the marvellous. In the meantime there ought not to be any doubt that children should be fed on fairy-tales as their souls' most natural food. Nothing can make up for the lack of them at the outset, just as no later supply of milk can compensate for the starvation involved in feeding infants on starch. The power of assimilating fairy-tales is soon lost, and unless the child has a rarely powerful creative imagination its spiritual growth on this side at least remains for ever stunted. If then childhood needs its pure fairy-land, and youth its fairy-land of impossible adventure, what fairy-land is left for adult age? Scarcely the novel. The modern novel in its finest manifesta- tions, however engrossingly interesting, takes us but a little step from the passionate interests of our own lives. If I turn to the two recent novels which have most powerfully interested me — Huysmans' En Route and Hardy's yi«^<2 the Obscure — I find that their interest lies largely in the skill with which they present and concentrate Casanova. 1 1 3 two mighty problems of actual life, the greatest of all problems, religion and sex. In adult life we seek a fairy-land occupied by beings at once as real as ourselves, and yet far removed from the sphere of our own actual interests and the heavy burden of the atmosphere under which we live; only so can it fascinate the imaginations of those who have outgrown the simple imagin- ative joys of early life. Casanova's Memoires is the perfected type of the books which answer these requirements. It is unflinchingly real, immensely varied, the audaciously truthful narrative of undeniably human impulses. And yet it carries us out of relation with the prob- lems of our actual life; it leads us into the realm of fairy-land. But — analysing the matter a little more closely — it may still fairly be asked whether a book which, in spite of its remoteness, represents a form of human life, must not have a certain bearing on morals. Is not a part of its attrac- tion, and indeed that of all fairy-lands, the existence of a different code of morals? It seems to me that this is so. But precisely in that lies the moral value of such literature. Indeed the whole question of the moral value of art — that is to say, of aisthetic enjoyment — is really involved here. The matter is worth looking into. It is one of Schopenhauer's unforgettable 1 14 Affirmations. sayings, that whatever course of action we take in life there is always some element in our nature which could only find satisfaction in an exactly contrary course; so that, take what road we will, we yet always remain restless and unsatisfied in part To Schopenhauer that re- flection made for pessimism; it need not The more finely and adequately we adjust ourselves to the actual conditions of our life the larger, no doubt, the unused and unsatisfied region within us. But it is just here that art comes in. Art largely counts for its effects on playing on these unused fibres of our organism, and by so doing it serves to bring them into a state of harmoni- ous satisfaction — moralises them, if you will. Alienists have described a distressing form of insanity peculiar to old maids who have led honourable lives of abstinence and abnegation. After years of seeming content with the con- ditions of their lot they begin to manifest uncontrollable obsessions and erotic impulses; the unused elements of life, which they had shut down in the cellars of their souls and almost forgotten, have at last arisen in rebellion, clamouring tumultuously for satisfaction. The old orgies — the Saturn alian festival at Christmas and the Midsummer Festival on St John's Day — bear witness that the ancients in their wisdom recognised that the bonds of the actual daily moral life must sometimes be relaxed lest they Casanova. 1 1 5 break from over-tension. We have lost the orgy, but in its place we have art. Our respect- able matrons no longer send out their daughters with torches at midnight into the woods and among the hills, where dancing and wine and blood may lash into their flesh the knowledge of the mysteries of life, but they take them to Tristan, and are fortunately unable to see into those carefully brought-up young souls on such occasions. The moral- ising force of art lies, not in its capacity to present a timid imitation of our experiences, but in its power to go beyond our experience, satisfying and harmonising the unfulfilled activi- ties of our nature. That art should have such an effect on those who contemplate it is not surprising when we remember that, to some extent, art has a similar influence on its creators. " Libertin d'esprit mais sage de moeurs," it was said of Watteau. Mohammed when he wrote 50 voluptuously of the black-eyed houris of Paradise was still young and the blameless husband of an aged woman. " Singing is sweet ; but be sure of this, Lips only sing when they cannot kiss." It has been said of Wagner that he had in him the instincts of an ascetic and of a satyr, and the first is just as necessary as the second to the making of a great artist. It is a very ancient ir6 Affirmations. observation that the most unchaste verse has often been written by the chastest poets, and that the writers who have written most purely have found their compensation in living im- purely.i In the same manner it has always been found in Christendom, both among Catho- lics and Protestants, that much of the most licentious literature has been written by the clergy, by no means because the clergy arc a depraved class, but precisely because the austerity of their lives renders necessary for them these emotional athletics. Of course, from the standpoint of simple nature, such literature is bad, it is merely a form of that obscenity which, as Huysmans has acutely remarked, can only be produced by those who are chaste; in Nature desire passes swiftly into action, leaving little or no trace on the mind. A certain degree of continence — I do not mean merely in the region of sex but in the other fields of human action also — is needed as a breeding- ground for the dreams and images of desire to ' I take the first example which comes to hand, for whatever it may be worth: — " Luttrell was talking of Moore and Rogers — the pqetry of the former so licentious, that of the latter so- pure; much of its popularity owing to its being so carefully weeded of everything approaching to indelicacy; and the con- trast between the lives and the works of the two men — the former a pattern of conjugal and domestic regularity, the latter of all the men he had ever known the greatest sensualist " (Greville's lilemoirs, vol. iii. p. 324). Casanova. 1 1 7 develop into the perfected visions of art. But the point of view of society is scarcely that of unadulterated nature. In society we have not always room for the swift and free passage of impulse into action; to avoid the evils of re- pressed impulse this play of the emotions on a higher and serener plane becomes essential. Just as we need athletics to expand and har- monise the coarser unused energies of the organism, so we need art and literature to ex- pand and harmonise its finer energies, emotion being, as it may not be superfluous to point out, itself largely a muscular process, motion in a more or less arrested form, so that there is here more than a mere analogy. Art from this point of view is the athletics of the emotions. The adventures of fairy-land — of which for our age I take Casanova's Memoires as the type — constitute an important part of this athletics. It may be abused, just as we have the grosser excesses of the runner and the cyclist; but it is the abuse and not the use which is pernicious, and under the artificial conditions of civilisation the contemplation of the life and adventures of the heroically natural man is an exercise with fine spiritual uses. Such literature thus has a moral value : it helps us to live peacefully within the highly specialised routine of civilisa- tion. That is the underlying justification for Casa- 1 1 8 Affirmations. nova's Metnoires as moral literature. But there is no reason why it should emerge into con- sciousness when we take up these Meuioires, any more than a man need take up a branch of physical athletics with any definite hygienic aim. It is sufficient to be moved by the pure enjoyment of it. And there must be something unwholesome and abnormal — something corrupt at the core — in any civilised man or woman who cannot win some enjoyment from this book. III. The more I contemplate the eighteenth cen- tury the more interesting I find it. In my youth it seemed to me unworthy of a glance. The books and the men, Shelley above all, who stirred my young blood belonged to the early nine- teenth century. I was led to regard the last century as a dull period of stagnation and decay, a tomb into which the spirit of man sank after the slow death which folloAved the Renaissance. The dawn of the nineteenth century was an Easter Day of the human soul, rising from the sepulchre and flinging aside the old eighteenth century winding-sheet. I have nothing yet to say against the early nineteenth century, which was indeed only the outcome of the years that went before, but I have gained a new delight in the men of the Casanova. 1 1 9 eighteenth century. It was in that age that the Enghsh spirit found its most complete intel- lectual expression, unaffected by foreign in- fluence. When that spirit, reviving after the wars that lamentably cut short the develop- ment of Chaucer's magnificent song, again began its free literary development — no doubt with some stimulus from Humanism — it was suddenly smothered at birth by the Renaissance wave from Italy and France. We may divine how it would have developed independently if we think of John Hey wood's dramatic sketches — pale as those are after the Miller's talc in which for the first and last time Chaucer perfectly mated English realism to the lyric grace of English idealism — and to some extent, also, when we turn to the later Heywood's plays, or Dekker's, and especially to the robust and tolerant humanity, the sober artistic breadth of the one play of Porter's which has come down to us. But the intoxicating melodies of Ronsard and his fellows were heard from over sea, and the men of the English Renaissance arose — Lyly and Lodge and Campion with their refinements, Greene and Nash with their gay and brilliant music, Marlowe with his arrogant, irresistible energy — and brought to birth an absolutely new spirit, which may have been English enough in its rich and virginal elements, but received the seminal principle 1 20 Affirmations. from abroad. It needed a century and more for that magnificent tumult to subside, and for the old English spirit to reappear and reach at last full maturity, by happy chance again in association with France, though this time it is England that chiefly plays the mas- culine part and impregnates France. Thus the eighteenth century was an age in which the English spirit found complete self-expression, and also an age in which England and France joined hands intellectually, and stood together at the summit of civilisation, with no rivals, unless Goethe and Kant may suffice to stand for a whole people. In the great Englishmen of these days we find the qualities which are truly native to Britain, and which have too often been torn and distracted by insane aber- rations. There is a fine sobriety and sagacity in the English spirit, a mellow human solidity, such as the Romans possessed always, but which we in our misty and storm-swept island have often exchanged, perhaps for better, but certainly for other qualities. It was not so in the eighteenth century, and by no accident the historian who has most finely expressed the genius of Rome was an eighteenth century Englishman. All the most typical men of that age possessed in varying degree the same qualities: Locke, Swift, Fielding, Hume, Richardson, Goldsmith, Hogarth, Johnson, God- Casanova. 1 2 1 win. Thus the eighteenth century should un- doubtedly be a source of pride to the British heart. England's reputation in the world rests largely on our poetic aptitudes and our political capacity. Eighteenth century England is not obviously pre-eminent in either respect, although it was the great age of our political development and the seed-time of our second great poetic age; it produced scarcely more than a single first-class poet exclusively within its limits, and it lost America. Yet our greatest philo- sopher, our greatest historian, our greatest biographer, nearly all our greatest novelists, our great initiators in painting, who were in- directly the initiators of the greater art of France, belong wholly to this century, and an unequalled cluster of our greatest poets belongs to its close. And these men were marked by sanity and catholicity, a superb solidity of spirit; they became genuinely cosmopolitan without losing any of their indigenous virtues. Without the eighteenth century we should never have known many of the greatest qualities which are latent, and too often only latent, in our race. Landor and Wordsworth alone were left to carry something of the spirit of the English eighteenth century far on into the literature of our own wholly alien century. And their brothers of France were their most worthy peers. This spirit, indeed, which we see 122 Affirmations. so conspicuously in the finest men of their age in England and France, was singularly wide- spread throughout Europe, a cheerful sobriety, a solid humanit}', little troubled by any of those " movements " which were to become so prolific and so noisy in the next century. Christianity, it seemed, was decaying. Diderot, well informed on English affairs, wrote to a friend that in a few years it would be extinct, and looking at the state of the English Church at that time, no one could reasonably have surmised that Zinzendorf in Germany, and after him Wesley in England on a lower plane and Law on a higher plane, had already initiated that revival of Christianity which in our own century was des- tined to work itself out so obstreperously. But the world seemed none the worse for the apparent subsidence of Christianity ; in the opinion of many it seemed to be very much the better. The tolerant paganism of classic days appeared to be reasserting itself, robustly in England, with a delicate refinement in France, — setting the paganism of Watteau against the paganism of Fielding — while Goethe and the Germans generally were striving to rescue and harmonise the best of Christianity with the best of antiquity. European civilisation was fully expanded; for a long time no great disturbing force had arisen, and though on every side the tender buds of coming growths might have been detected, they Casanova. 123 could not yet reveal their strength. Such a period certainly has its terrible defects; mellowness is not far from rottenness. But then youth also has its defects, and its crude acidity is still further from perfection. The nineteenth century has a higher moral standard than the eighteenth, so at least we in our self-righteous- ness have been accustomed to think. But even if so, the abstract existence of a high moral standard is another thing from the prevalence of high moral living. Whatever the standard may be, it is a question whether the lives are much different. In the one case the standard is much above the practice, in the other only a little above it — that is the chief difference. And the advantages of winding the standard up to the higher pitch are not so unmixed as is sometimes assumed. One need not question these advantages, well recognised in the present century. But the advantages of a lower standard are less often recognised. There is especially the great advantage that we attain a higher degree of sincerity, and sincerity, if not itself the prime virtue, is surely, whatever the virtue may be, its chief accompaniment A life that is swathed and deformed in much drapery is not so wholesome or so effective as one that can live nearer to the sun. And the unrecognisable villain is most pernicious; the brigand who holds a revolver at your head is better than the sleek 124 Affirmations. and well-dressed thief who opens the proceed- ings with prayer. The eighteenth has been called a gross and unintelligent century. In the department of criticism, indeed, this century in England (for it was far otherwise in Germany) comes very short of our own century, and it is largely this failure to measure the precise value of things in aesthetic perception which now makes that age seem so shocking. From this point of view every great age — and not least our own greatest Elizabethan age — is equally defective. A period of energetic life cannot afford to spend much time on the solitary contemplation of its own bowels of aesthetic emotion. To produce a Pater is the one exquisite function of a spiritually barren and exhausted age. And still the eighteenth century redeems its critical grossness by making even this later development possible ; it lifted the man of letters from the place of a dependent to the place of a free man boldly prophesying in his own right ; and, moreover, it was the first century which dared to claim the complete equality of men and women with all which that involves. If it has required a certain insight for the child of our own century to discover the great qualities of the last century, there cannot be much doubt about the final judgment of the most competent judges. The eighteenth was, Casanova. 1 2 3 as Renouvicr has called it, the first century of humanity since Christ, while at the same time, as Lange has said, it was penetrated through by the search for the ideal, or, as a more recent thinker concludes, it was a century dominated by the maxim Sahis popidi supreina est lex, holding in its noble aspirations after general happiness the germs of all modern socialism. In art and literature it saw the fresh spring of those blossoms which opened so splendidly and faded so swiftly in our century; it was the century not only of Hogarth and Fielding and Voltaire, but of Blake and Rousseau, of Diderot, of Swedenborg and Mesmer, of the development of modern music with Mozart and Beethoven, of the unparalleled enthusiasm awakened by the discovery of the Keltic world. And as its crowning glory the eighteenth century claims Goethe. Men will scarcely look back to our own century as so good to live in. One may well say that he would have gladly lived in the thirteenth century, perhaps the most interesting of all since Christ, or in the sixteenth, probably the most alive of all, or the eighteenth, surely the most human. But why have lived in the nine- teenth, the golden age of machinery, and of men used as machines ? Eighteenth century Europe, being what it was, formed a perfect stage for Casanova to play 1 26 AffirviafwJis. his part on. With his Spanish and Itah'an blood, he was of the race of those who had come so actively to the front in the last days of old classic Rome, and his immediate ancestors had lived in the centre of the pagan Rome of the Renaissance. Thus he carried with him traditions which consorted well with much in the eighteenth century. And he had that in him, moreover, which no tradition can give, the incommunicable vitality in the presence of which all tradition shrivels into nothingness, Casanova knew not only Italy, France, Eng- land, Germany, and Holland; he had visited Spain, Russia, Poland, Greece, Turkey, and Asia Minor. He was received by Benedict XH., by Frederick H. of Prussia, by the Empress Catherine, by Joseph H. He was at home in Paris, in London, in Berlin, in Vienna; he knew Munich, Dresden, Moscow, St. Petersburg, War- saw, Barcelona. His picture of London is of great interest. He spent much of the year 1763 there, and some of his most interest- ing experiences, romantic and psychological, occurred during that period. He even dated the close of what he calls the second act in the comedy of his life from that visit to London, the next and concluding act being one of slow declination. So profound was his depression at this time that one day he went towards the Thames at the Tower with the deliberate Casanova. 127 intention of drowning himself, having first filled his pockets with bullets to ensure sinking. Fortunately an English friend (to whom the world owes thanks) met him on the way, read his resolve in his face, and insisted on carrying him off to a very convivial party, whose in- decorous proceedings, although Casanova only remained a passive witness, served to dissipate all thoughts of suicide. He is not, however, prejudiced against England; on the contrary, he finds that no nation offers so many interesting peculiarities to the attentive observer. As usual, in London Casanova mixed indiscriminately with the best and the worst society; his wit, his knowledge, his imperturbable effrontery, his charming conversation, served to open any door that he desired to open. He gives us curious glimpses into the lives of English noblemen of the day, and not less intimate pictures of the chevaliers d'industri'e who preyed upon them. In the course of one adventure with people of the latter sort he was haled before the eminent blind magistrate Sir John Fielding, whom he seems to have mistaken, though this is not quite clear, for his yet more eminent brother Henry. He also met Kitty Fischer, the most fashionable cocotte of her day, whom we may yet see as Reynolds caught her in a well-inspired moment, dilating her sensitive nostrils, radiantly inhaling the joy of life, and 128 Affirmations. he tells us anecdotes of her extravagance, of the jewels she wore, of the thousand guinea bank- note which she ate in a sandwich.^ Throughout Europe Casanova knew many of the most celebrated people of his time, though it is clear — as one would expect from a man of his impartial humanity — he seldom went out of his way to meet them. His visit to Voltaire is a distinct contribution to our knowledge of that sage; he admired Helvetius, and wondered how a man of so many virtues could have denied virtue; D'Alembert he thought the most truly modest man he had ever met, an interesting ^ For another side of life we may read his description of the English Sunday: — "On Sunday one dares neither to play at cards nor to perform music. The numerous spies who infest the streets of this capital listen to the sounds which come from the parlours of the houses, and if they suspect any gaming or singing they conceal themselves and slip in at the first opportunity to seize those bad Christians who dare to profane the Lord's Day by amusements which everywhere else are counted innocent. In revenge the English may go with impunity to sanctify the holy day in the taverns and brothels which are so plentiful in this city." One may compare with this Mme. de Stael's almost Dantesque description — so at least it remains in the memory — of the gloom of the Scotch Sabbath in the days of Burns. This statement of the matter remained substantially accurate until almost yesterday. So long it remained for the English spirit to re-conquer Sunday ! It must be remembered that Puritanism, while always a part of the English spirit, was not originally its predominant note ; it only became so as an inevitable re- action against the exotic Renaissance movement. Mary Stuart made Knox, Charles I. made Cromwell, and both monarchs were intimately associated with the last wave of the Renaissance. Casanova. \ 29 tribute from the most truly immodest man of that period. The value of Casanova's record of the eighteenth century h'es, however, by no means in the glimpses he has given us of great personalities: that has been much better done by much more insignificant writers. It is as a picture of the manners and customs of the eighteenth century throughout Europe that the Manoires are invaluable. Casanova saw Europe from the courts of kings to the lowest bas fonds. He lived in the castles of French and Italian nobles, in the comfortable homes of Dutch merchants, in his own house in Pall Mall, in taverns and inns and peasants' cottages any- where. He had no intellectual prejudices, he had an immense versatility in tastes and practical aptitudes, he was genuinely interested in all human things. Thus he approached life with no stereotyped set of opinions, but with all the aloofness of an unclassed adventurer, who was at the same time a scholar and a man of letters. It can scarcely be that there is any record to compare with this as a vivid and impartial picture of the eighteenth century, in its robust solidity, its cheerful and tolerant scepticism, its serene and easy gaiety, its mellow decay. That is our final debt to this unique and immortal book. What should be our last word about Casa- 9 1 30 Affiruiatio7ts. nova? It is true that although — if indeed one should not say because — he was so heroically natural Casanova was not an average normal man. It is scarcely given to the average man to expend such versatile and reckless skill in the field of the world, or to find so large a part wherein to play off that skill. But neither are the saints and philosophers normal ; St. Bernard was not normal, nor yet Spmoza. And surely it is a poor picture of the world which would show us St. Bernard and Spinoza and shut out Casanova. "Vous avez I'outil universel," Fabrice said to Gil Bias. Casanova's brain was just such a tool of universal use, and he never failed to use it. For if you would find the supreme type of the human animal in the completest development of his rankness and cunning, in the very plenitude of his most excellent wits, I know not where you may more safely go than to the Memoires of the self-ennobled Jacques Casanova Chevalier de Seingalt. I^I ZOLA. Zola's name — a barbarous, explosive name, like an anarchist's bomb — has been tossed about amid hoots and yells for a quarter of a century. In every civilised country we have heard of the man who has dragged literature into the gutter, who has gone down to pick up the filth of the streets, and has put it into books for the filthy to read. And in every civilised country his books have been read, by the hundred thousand. To-day, his great life-work is completed. At the same time, the uproar that it aroused has, to a large extent, fallen silent. Not that there is any general agreement as to the rank of the author of the Rougon-Macquart series; but the storms that greeted it have worn themselves out, and it is recognised that there are at least two sides to this as to any other question. Such a time is favourable to the calm discussion of Zola's precise position. The fundamental assertion of those who, in their irreconcilable opposition to Zola, have rightly felt that abuse is not argument, has always been that Zola is no artist. The matter 132 Affirmations. has usually presented itself to them as a ques- tion of Idealism versus Realism. Idealism, as used by the literary critic, seems to mean a careful selection of the facts of life for artistic treatment, certain facts being suited for treat- ment in the novel, certain other facts being not so suited ; while the realist, from the literary critic's point of view, is one who flings all facts indiscriminately into his pages. I think that is a fair statement of the matter, for the literary critic does not define very clearly; still less does he ask himself how far the idealism he advocates is merely traditional, nor, usually, to what extent the manner of presentation should influence us. He does not ask himself these questions, nor need we ask him, for in the case of Zola (or, indeed, of any other so-called " realist ") there is no such distinction. There is no absolute realism, merely a variety of idealisms; the only absolute realism would be a phonographic record, illustrated photographically, after the manner of the cinematograph. Zola is just as much an idealist as George Sand. It is true that he selects very largely from material things, and that he selects very profusely. But the selection remains, and where there is deliberate selection there is art. We need not trouble ourselves here — and I doubt whether we are ever called upon to trouble ourselves — about " Realism " and " Idealism." The questions are: Zola. 133 Has the artist selected the right materials? Has he selected them with due restraint? The first question is a large one, and, in Zola's case at all events, it cannot, I think, be answered on purely aesthetic grounds; the second may be answered without difficulty. Zola has himself answered it; he admits that he has been carried away by his enthusiasm, and perhaps, also, by his extraordinary memory for recently- acquired facts (a memory like a sponge, as he has put it, quickly swollen and quickly emptied); he has sown details across his page with too profuse a hand. It is the same kind of error as Whitman made, impelled by the same kind of enthusiasm. Zola expends immense trouble to get his facts ; he has told how he ransacked the theologians to obtain body and colour for La Faute de I' Abbe Moiiret, perhaps the best of his earlier books. But he certainly spent no more preliminary labour on it than Flaubert spent on Madame Bovary, very far less than Flaubert spent on the study of Carthage for Salammbd. But the results are different ; the one artist gets his effects by profusion and multiplicity of touches, the other by the de- liberate self-restraint with which he selects and emphasises solely the salient and significant touches. The latter method seems to strike more swiftly and deeply the ends of art Three strokes with the brush of Frans Hals are worth 1 34 Affirmations. a thousand of Denner's. Rich and minute detail may impress us, but it irritates and wearies in the end. If a man takes his two children on to his knees, it matters Httle whether he places Lenore on his right knee and Henri on his left, or the other way about ; the man himself may fail to know or to realise, and the more intense his feelings the less likely is he to know. When we are living deeply, the facts of our external life do not present themselves to us in elaborate detail ; a very few points are — as it has been termed — focal in consciousness, while the rest are marginal in subconsciousness. A few things stand out vividly at each moment of life ; the rest are dim. The supreme artist is shown by the insight and boldness with which he seizes and illuminates these bright points at each stage, leaving the marginal elements in due subordination. Dramatists so unlike as Ford and Ibsen, novelists so unlike as Flaubert and Tolstoi, yet alike impress us by the simple vividness of their artistic effects. The methods adopted by Zola render such effects extremely difficult of attainment Perhaps the best proof of Zola's I'emarkable art is the skill with which he has neutralised the evil results of his ponderous method. In his most characteristic novels, as UAssommoir, Nana, Germinal, his efforts to attain salient perspective in the mass of trivial or technical things — to build a single elaborate Zola. 135 effect out of manifold details— are often admir- ably conducted. Take, for instance, the Voreux, the coal-pit which may almost be said to be the hero of Germinal rather than any of the persons in the book. The details are not interesting, but they are carefully elaborated, and the Voreux is finally symbolised as a stupendous idol, sated with human blood, crouching in its mysterious sanctuary. Whenever Zola wishes to bring the Voreux before us, this formula is repeated. And it is the same, in a slighter degree, with the other material personalities of the book. Some- times, in the case of a crowd, this formula is simply a cry. It is so with the Parisian mob who yell "A Berlin!" in the highly-wrought conclusion to Nana; it is so with the crowd of strikers in Germinal who shout for bread. It is more than the tricky repetition of a word or a gesture, overdone by Dickens and others ; it is the artful manipulation of a carefully-elaborated, significant phrase. Zola seems to have been the first who has, deliberately and systematically, introduced this sort of leit-motiv into literature, as a method of summarising a complex mass of details, and bringing the total impression of them before the reader. In this way he contrives to minimise the defects of his method, and to render his complex detail focal. He sometimes attains poignantly simple effects by the mere repetition of a leit-motiv at the right moment. And he is 1 36 Affirmations. able at times, also, to throw aside his detailed method altogether, and to reach effects of tragic intensity. The mutilation of Maigrat's corpse is a scene which can scarcely have been described in a novel before. Given the subject, Zola's treatment of it has the strength, brevity, and certainty of touch which only belong to great masters of art. That Zola is a great master of his art, L Assommoir and Ger^ninal — which, so far as I have read Zola, seem his two finest works — are enough to prove. Such works are related to the ordinary novel much as Wagner's music-dramas are related to the ordinary Italian opera. Wagner reaches a loftier height of art than Zola ; he had a more complete grasp of all the elements he took in hand to unite. Zola has not seen with sufficient clearness the point of view of science, and the limits of its capacity for harmonising with fiction ; nor has he with perfect sureness of vision always realised the ends of art. He has left far too much of the scaffolding standing amid his huge literary structures ; there is too much mere brute fact which has not been wrought into art. But, if Zola is not among the world's greatest artists, I do not think we can finally deny that he is a great artist. To look at Zola from the purely artistic stand- point, however, is scarcely to see him at all. His significance for the world generally, and Zola, 137 even for literature, lies less in a certain method of using his material — as it maybe said to lie, for example, in the case of the Goncourts — than in the material itself, and the impulses and ideas that prompted his selection of that material. These growing piles of large books are the volcanic ejecta of an original and exuberant temperament. To understand them we must investigate this temperament. A considerable and confused amount of racial energy was stored up in Zola. At once French, Italian, and Greek — with a mother from the central Beauce country of France, more fruitful in corn than in intellect, and a father of mixed Italian and Greek race, a mechanical genius in his way, with enthusiastic energies and large schemes — he presents a curious combination of potential forces, perhaps not altogether a very promising combination. One notes that the mechanical engineer in the father seems to have persisted in the son, not necessarily by heredity, but perhaps by early familiarity and association. Young Zola was a delicate child and by no means a brilliant schoolboy, though he once won a prize for memory; such ability as he showed was in the direction of science; he had no literary aptitudes. He seems to have adopted literature chiefly because pen and ink come handiest to the eager energies of a poor clerk. It is scarcely fanciful to detect the 138 Affirnia tio )is. mechanical aptitudes still. Just as all Huxley's natural instincts were towards mechanics, and in physiology he always sought for the "go" of the organism, so Zola, however imperfect his scientific equipment may be, has always sought for the "go" of the social organism. The history of the Rougon-Macquart family is a study in social mathematics: given certain family strains, what is the dynamic hereditary outcome of their contact ? To the making of Zola there went, therefore, this curious racial blend, as a soil ready to be fertilised by any new seed, and a certain almost instinctive tendency to look at things from the mechanical and material point of view. To these, in very early life, a third factor was added of the first importance. During long years after his father's death, Zola, as a child and youth, suffered from poverty, poverty almost amounting to actual starvation, the terrible poverty of respectability. The whole temper of his work and his outlook on the world are clearly con- ditioned by this prolonged starvation of adoles- cence. The timid and reserved youth — for such, it is said, has been Zola's character both in youth and manhood — was shut up with his fresh energies in a garret while the panorama of the Paris world was unfolded below him. Forced both by circumstances and by tempera- ment to practise the strictest chastity and Zoln. 139 sobriety, there was but one indulgence left open to him, an orgy of vision. Of this, as we read his books, we cannot doubt that he fully availed himself, for each volume of the Rougon-Mac- quart series is an orgy of material vision.^ Zola remained chaste, and, it is said, he is still sober— though we are told that his melancholy morose face lights up like a gourmet's at the hour of his abstemious dinner— but this early eagerness to absorb the sights as well as the sounds, and ' " Mes souvenirs," he told a psychological interviewer, " ont une puissance, un relief extraordinaire ; ma memoire est cn