J. PETER MAYER LIBRARY AN EXAMINATION SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY AND OF THE PRINCIPAL PHILOSOPHICAL QUESTIONS DISCUSSED IN HIS WRITINGS JOHN STUAET MILL FIFTH EDITION LONDON LONGMANS, GREEN, READER, AND DYER. 1878 LONDON : 8AYILL, EDWARD3 AND CO., PRINTERS, CHANDOS STRKM, OOYENT GARDEN. JUilStt AJR. I UNIVERSITY ( F CALIFORNIA SANTA BARBARA PEEFACE THE THIED EDITION. IN former writings I have perhaps seemed to go in search of objectors, whom I might have disregarded, but who enabled me to bring out my opinions into greater clearness and relief. My present condition is far different; for a host of writers, whose mode of philosophic thought was either directly or indirectly implicated in the criticisms made by this volume on Sir W. Hamilton, have taken up arms against it, and fought -as pro arts et focis. Among these are included, not solely friends or followers of Sir W. Hamilton, who were under some obligation to say whatever could fairly be said in his defence, but many who stand almost as widely apart from him as I do, though mostly on the reverse side. To leave these attacks unanswered, would be to desert the principles which as a speculative thinker I have maintained all my life, and which the progress of my thoughts has constantly strengthened. The criticisms which have come under my notice (omitting the daily and weekly journals) are the following; there may be others : Mr. Mansel : " The Philosophy of the Conditioned ; comprising some remarks on Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy, and on Mr. J. S. Mill's Examination of that VI PREFACE. Philosophy." (First published in Nos. 1 and 2 of the Contemporary Review.) " The Battle of the Two Philosophies ; by an In- quirer." Dr. M'Cosh : " An Examination of Mr. J. S. Mill's Philosophy, being a Defence of Fundamental Truth." Dr. Calderwood : " The Sensational Philosophy Mr. J. S. Mill and Dr. M'Cosh;" in the British and Foreign Evangelical Review for April 1866. Dr. Henry B. Smith : " Mill v. Hamilton," in the American Presbyterian and Theological Review for January 1866. Mr. H. F. O'Hanlon : " A Criticism of John Stuart Mill's Pure Idealism ; and an Attempt to show that, if logically carried out, it is Pure Nihilism." Review of this work in Blackwood's Magazine for January 1866. (The two last mentioned are confined to the doctrine of Permanent Possibilities of Sensation). Mr. J. P. Mahaffy, in the Introduction to his transla- tion of Professor Kuno Fischer's account of Kant's Kritik. (Confined to the doctrine of Permanent Possibilities, and the subject of Necessary Truths.) Mr. Patrick Proctor Alexander : " An Examination of Mr. John Stuart Mill's Doctrine of Causation in Relation to Moral Freedom ;" forming the greater part of a volume entitled " Mill and Carlyle." Reviews of this work in the Dublin Review for October 1865 (with the signature R. E. G.), and in the Edinburgh Review for July 1866. And, earlier than all these, the able and interesting volume of my friend Professor Masson, entitled " Recent British Philosophy: a Review, with Criticisms; including some comments on Mr. Mill's Answer to Sir William Hamilton." PREFACE. Vll All these, in regard to such of the main questions as they severally discuss, are unqualifiedly hostile ; though some of the writers are, in a personal point of view, most courteous, and even over-complimentary ; and the last eminently friendly as well as flattering. The following are only partially adverse: Review of the present work in the North British Review for September 1865, attributed to Professor Fraser, and bearing the strongest internal marks of that origin. This able thinker, though he considers me to have often misunderstood Sir W. Hamilton, is, on the substantive philosophic doctrines principally concerned, a most valuable ally ; to whom I might almost have left the defence of our common opinions. Mr. Herbert Spencer : " Mill v. Hamilton The Test of Truth;" in the Fortnightly Review for July 15, 1865. Review of the present work in the North American Review for July 1866. The only important criticism, in all essentials favour- able, to which I am able to refer, is that in the West- minster Review for January 1866, by an illustrious his- torian and philosopher, who, of all men now living, is the one by whom I should most wish that any writing of mine, on a subject in speculative philosophy, should be approved. There have also been published since the first edition of the present work, two remarkable books, which, if they do not give me direct support, effect a powerful diversion in my favour. One is Mr. Bolton's " Inquisitio Philosophica ; an Examination of the Prin- ciples of Kant and Hamilton ;" which, along with much other valuable matter, contains a vigorous assault upon my most conspicuous assailant, Mr. Mansel. The other is Mr. Stirling's "Sir William Hamilton, being the Philosophy of Perception ; an Analysis :" an able and Vlli PREFACE. most svere criticism on Sir ~W. Hamilton's inconsis- tencies, and on his general character as a philosopher, taken from a different point of view from mine, and expressed with far greater asperity than I should myself think justifiable ; legitimated, no doubt, to the writer's mind by " a certain vein of disingenuousness" which he finds in Sir W. Hamilton, but which I have not found, and shall not believe until I see it proved. I must have been quite incapable of profiting by cri- ticism, if I had learnt nothing from assailants so nume- rous, all of more or less, and some of very considerable, ability. They have detected not a few inadvertences of expression, as well as some of thought : and partly by their help, partly without it, I have discovered others. They have not shaken any statement or opinion of real moment; but I am sincerely indebted to them, both for the errors they have corrected, and for compelling me to strengthen my defences. The point in which it was to be expected that they would ofteuest prevail, was in showing me to have erroneously interpreted Sir W. Hamilton. The difficulty to any thinker is so great, in these high regions of speculation, of placing himself com- pletely at the point of view of a different philosophy, and even of thoroughly understanding its language, that it would be very presumptuous in me to imagine that I had always overcome that difficulty ; and that too with the warning before me, of the absolute failure of able and accomplished minds on the other side in philosophy, to accomplish this in regard to the modes of thinking with which I am most familiar. I have been surprised, therefore, to find in how few instances, and those how little important, the defenders of Sir W. Hamilton have been able to show that I have misunderstood or incor- rectly stated his opinions or arguments. I cannot doubt that more such mistakes remain to be pointed out : and PREFACE. IX I regret that the greater part of the volume has not yet, in its relation to Sir W. Hamilton, had the benefit of a sufficiently minute scrutiny. Had the unsparing criti- cism of Mr. Mansel on the first few chapters been con- tinued to the remainder, he would doubtless have pointed out real mistakes ; he might perhaps have thrown light on some of the topics from his own thoughts ; and I should at least have had to thank him for additional confi- dence in the statements and opinions which had passed unharmed through the ordeal of his attacks. Where criticism or reconsideration has convinced me that anything in the book was erroneous, or that any improvement was required in the mode of stating and setting forth the truth, I have made the requisite alterations. When the case seemed to require that I should call the reader's attention to the change, I have done so ; but I have not made this an invariable rule. Mere answers to objectors I have generally relegated to notes. With so many volumes to deal with, I could not take express notice of every criticism which they contained. When any of my critics finds that he, or some of his objections, are not individually referred to, let him be assured that it is from no disrespect, but either because I consider them to have been answered by the reply made to some one else, or because their best confutation is to remand the objector to the work itself, or because the edge of the objection has been turned by some, perhaps quite unapparent, correction of the text. A slight modification in a sentence, or even in a phrase, which a person acquainted with the former editions might read without observing it, and of which, even if he observed it, he would most likely not perceive the purpose, has sometimes effaced many pages of hostile criticism. X PREFACE. Of the assailants to whom I replied, two only have published a rejoinder ; Dean Mansel, in the Contemporary Eeviewfor September 1867, and Dr.M'Cosh,in the British and Foreign Evangelical Eeview for April 1868. Neither of them appears to me to have added much of value to what he had previously advanced ; and so far as concerns Dean Mansel, his regretted death has put a final termination to the controversy between us. I am not, however, thereby exempted from taking notice, however briefly, of such points in his rejoinder as appear to require it. Dr. M'Cosh seems to think it a great triumph of his assaults upon me, that many of them were not noticed in my replies to critics. It is a little unreasonable in Dr. M'Cosh to suppose that in a work, the subject of which is the philosophy of Sir William Hamilton, I was bound to fight a pitched battle with Dr. M'Cosh on the whole line. His book was an attack directed against the whole of my philosophical opinions. I answered such parts of it as had reference to the present work, when they seemed to require an answer, and not to have received it sufficiently in what I had already written. And I have done the same, in the present edition, with his rejoinder. Besides several unpublished criticisms which I owe to the kindness of correspondence, and which have helped me to correct or otherwise improve some of the details of the work; two more attacks have been made upon it subsequently to the third edition. Professor Veitch, in the Appendices to his interesting Memoir of Sir W. Hamilton, has commented sharply on what I have said respecting Sir W. Hamilton's mode of understanding the Eelativity of human knowledge, and respecting his failure to apprehend correctly the general character of Hume and Leibnitz as philosophers, as well as some par- ticular passages of Aristotle. On the first subject, that PREFACE. XI of Relativity, I find so much difficulty in reducing Pro- fessor Veitch's statement to distinct propositions, and, so far as I understand his meaning, it differs so little, and that little not to its advantage, from what I have already commented on in answering Mr. Mansel, that I do not think it necessary to burthen this volume with an express reply to him. With regard to Hume and Leibnitz I am content that they who have a competent knowledge of those philosophers should form their own opinion. As regards Sir W. Hamilton's interpretation of Aristotle, Professor Veitch has convicted me of a mistake in treat- ing a citation made by his editors as if it had been made by himself, and of an overstatement of one of Sir W. Hamilton's opinions which I only noticed incidentally. These errors I have corrected, in their places, and it will be found that they do not affect anything of importance in the criticism there made upon Sir W. Hamilton. Professor Veitch* considers it unfair that I should press against Sir W. Hamilton anything contained in his Lectures, these having been hastily written under pressure from time, and not being the most matured expression of some of his opinions. But though thus written, it is admitted that they continued to be delivered by Sir W. Hamilton as long as he performed the duties of Professor ; which would not have been the case if he had no longer considered them as a fair repre- sentation of his philosophy. A complete representation I never pretended that they were; a correct representation I am bound to think them ; for it cannot be believed that he would have gone on delivering to his pupils matter which he judged to be inconsistent with the subsequent developments of his philosophy. The other thinker who has taken the field against my psychological opinions is Dr. Ward, who, in the Dublin * Memoir of Sir William Hamilton, pp. 212, 213. Xll PREFACE. Review for October 1871, has made an able attack on the views I have expressed in this and other writings on the subject of what is called Necessary Truth. Some of Dr. Ward's observations are more particularly directed against a portion of my System of Logic, and the fittest place for their discussion is in connexion with that treatise. But the greater part of his article principally regards the chapter of the present work which relates to Inseparable Association, and a reply to it will be found in a note which I have added at the end of that chapter. CONTENTS. CHAPTER I. MAI INTRODUCTORY REMARKS ..... . 1 CHAPTER II. THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 5 CHAPTER III. THE DOCTRINE OF THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE, AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON 17 CHAPTER IV. IN WHAT RESPECT SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON REALLY DIFFERS FROM THE PHILOSOPHERS OF THE ABSOLUTE 45 CHAPTER V. WHAT IS REJECTED AS KNOWLEDGE BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON, BROUGHT BACK UNDER THE NAME OF BELIEF 74 I CHAPTER VI. THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED 82 XIV CONTENTS. CHAPTER VII. turn THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED, AS APPLIED BY MR. MANSEL TO THE LIMITS OF RELIGIOUS THOUGHT Ill CHAPTER VIII. OF CONSCIOUSNESS, AS UNDERSTOOD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON . 136 X ' ^ CHAPTER IX. ON THE INTERPRETATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS 157 CHAPTER X. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S VIEW OF THE DIFFERENT THEORIES RESPECTING THE BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD .... 187 CHAPTER XL THE PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY OF THE BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD "... 225 CHAPTER XII. THE PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY OF THE BELIEF IN MATTER, HOW FAR APPLICABLE TO MIND 240 APPENDIX TO THE TWO PRECEDING CHAPTERS ....... 250 CHAPTER XIII. THE PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY OF THE PRIMARY QUALITIES OF MATTER . 265 CHAPTER XIV. HOW SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AND MR. MANSEL DISPOSE OF THE LAW OF INSEPARABLE ASSOCIATION 314 CONTENTS. XV CHAPTER XV. FAGl SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S DOCTRINE OF UNCONSCIOUS MENTAL MODIFICATIONS 341 CHAPTER XVI. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S THEORY OF CAUSATION 359 CHAPTER XVII. THE DOCTRINE OF CONCEPTS, OR GENERAL NOTIONS 380 CHAPTER XVIII. OF JUDGMENT 414 CHAPTER XIX. OF REASONING 438 CHAPTER XX. ON SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC AS A SCIENCE. IS LOGIC THE SCIENCE OF THE LAWS OR FORMS OF THOUGHT? 446 CHAPTER XXI. THE FUNDAMENTAL LAWS OF THOUGHT ACCORDING TO SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON 479 CHAPTER XXII. OF SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S SUPPOSED IMPROVEMENTS IN FORMAL LOGIC 496 CHAPTER XXHI. OF SOME MINOR PECULIARITIES OF DOCTRINE IN SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S VIEW OF FORMAL LOGIC 521 XVI CONTENTS. CHAPTER XXIV. MM OF SOME NATURAL PREJUDICES COUNTENANCED BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON, AND SOME- FALLACIES WHICH HE CONSIDERS IN- SOLUBLE 539 CHAPTER XXV. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S THEORY OF PLEASURE AND PAIN . . . 553 CHAPTER XXVI. ON THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL 561 CHAPTER XXVII. SIB WILLIAM HAMILTON'S OPINIONS ON THE STUDY OF MATHE- MATICS 591 CHAPTER XXVIII. CONCLUDING REMARKS . . . 617 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY, CHAPTER I. INTRODUCTORY REMARKS. AMONG the philosophical writers of the present century in these islands, no one occupies a higher position than Sir William Hamilton. He alone, of our metaphysicians of this and the preceding generation, has acquired, merely as such, an European celebrity : while, in our own country, he has not only had power to produce a revival of interest in a study which had ceased to be popular, but has made himself, in some sense, the founder of a school of thought. The school, indeed, is not essentially new ; for its fundamental doctrines are those of the philo- sophy which has everywhere been in the ascendant since the setting in of the reaction against Locke and Hume, which dates from Reid among ourselves and from Kant for the rest of Europe. But that general scheme of philosophy is split into many divisions, and the Hamil- tonian form of it is distinguished by as marked pecu- liarities as belong to any other of its acknowledged varieties. From the later German and French develop- ments of the common doctrine, it is separated by dif- ferences great in reality, and still greater in appearance ; while it stands superior to the earlier Scottish and Eng- lish forms by the whole difference of level which has 2 INTRODUCTORY REMARKS. been gained to philosophy through the powerful nega- tive criticism of Kant. It thus unites to the prestige of independent originality, the recommendation of a general harmony with the prevailing tone of thought. These advantages, combined with an intellect highly trained and in many respects highly fitted for the subject, and a knowledge probably never equalled in extent and accu- racy of whatever had been previously thought and written in his department, have caused Sir William Hamilton to be justly recognised as, in the province of abstract speculation, one of the important figures of the age. The acknowledged position of Sir W. Hamilton at the head, so far as regards this country, of the school of philosophy to which he belongs, has principally deter- mined me to connect with his name and writings the speculations and criticisms contained in the present work. The justification of the work itself lies in the importance of the questions, to the discussion of which it is a contribution. England is often reproached by Continental thinkers, with indifference to the higher philosophy. But England did not always deserve this reproach, and is already showing, by no doubtful symp- toms, that she will not deserve it much longer. Her thinkers are again beginning to see, what they had only temporarily forgotten, that a true Psychology is the indispensable scientific basis of Morals, of Politics, of the science and art of Education ; that the difficulties of Metaphysics lie at the root of all science ; that those diffi- culties can only be quieted by being resolved, and that until they are resolved, positively whenever possible, but at any rate negatively, we are never assured that any human knowledge, even physical, stands on solid foun- dations. My subject, therefore, is less Sir W. Hamilton, than the questions which Sir W. Hamilton discussed. It is, however, impossible to write on those questions in our own country and in our own time, without incessant reference, express or tacit, to his treatment of them. On INTRODUCTORY REMARKS. O all the subjects on which he touched, he is either one of the most powerful allies of what I deem a sound philo- sophy, or (more frequently) by far its most formidable antagonist ; both because he came the latest, and wrote with a full knowledge of the flaws which had been de- tected in his predecessors, and because he was one of the ablest, the most far-sighted, and the most candid. Whenever any opinion which he deliberately expressed, is contended against, his form of the opinion, and his arguments for it, are those which especially require to be faced and carefully appreciated : and it being thus im- possible that any fit discussion of his topics should not involve an estimate of his doctrines, it seems worth while that the estimate should be rendered as complete as practicable, by being extended to all the subjects on which he has made, or on which he is believed to have made, any important contribution to thought. In thus attempting to anticipate, as far as is yet possible, the judgment of posterity on Sir W. Hamilton's labours, I sincerely lament that on the many points on which I am at issue with him, I have the unfair advantage pos- sessed by one whose opponent is no longer in a condition to reply. Personally I might have had small cause to congratulate myself on the reply which I might have received, for though a strictly honourable, he was a most unsparing controversialist, and whoever assailed even the most unimportant of his opinions, might look for hard blows in return. But it would have been worth far more, even to myself, than any polemical success, to have known with certainty in what manner he would have met the objections raised in the present volume. T feel keenly, with Plato, how much more is to be learnt by discussing with a man, who can question and answer, than with a book, which cannot. But it was not possible to take a general review of Sir W. Hamilton's doctrines while they were only known to the world in the frag- mentary state in which they were published during his life. His Lectures, the fullest and the only consecutive exposition (as far as it goes) of his philosophy, are a B 2 4 INTRODUCTORY REMARKS. posthumous publication; while the latest and most matured expression of many of his opinions, the Disser- tations on Eeid, left off, scarcely half finished, in the middle of a sentence ; and so long as he lived, his readers were still hoping for the remainder. The Lectures, it is true, have added less than might have been expected to the knowledge we already possessed of the author's doc- trines ; but it is something to know that we have now all that is to be had ; and though we should have been glad to have his opinions on more subjects, we could scarcely have known more thoroughly than we are now at last enabled to do, what his thoughts were on the points to which he attached the greatest importance, and which are most identified with his name and fame. CHAPTEE II. THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. THE doctrine which is thought to belong in the most especial manner to Sir W. Hamilton, and which was the ground of his opposition to the transcendentalism of the later French and German metaphysicians, is that which he and others have called the Eelativity of Human Knowledge. It is the subject of the most generally known, and most impressive, of all his writings, the one which first revealed to the English metaphysical reader that a new power had arisen in philosophy ; and, together with its developments, it composes the " Philosophy of the Conditioned," which he opposed to the German and French philosophies of the Absolute, and which is re- garded by most of his admirers as the greatest of his titles to a permanent place in the history of metaphy- sical thought. But the " relativity of human knowledge," like most other phrases into which the words relative or relation enter, is vague, and admits of a great variety of meanings. In one of its senses, it stands for a proposition respecting the nature and limits of our knowledge, in my judgment true, fundamental, and lull of important consequences in philosophy. From this amplitude of meaning its significance shades down through a number of gradations, successively more thin and unsubstantial, till it fades into a truism leading to no consequences, and hardly worth enunciating in words. When, therefore, a philo- sopher lays great stress upon the relativity of our know- ledge, it is necessary to cross-examine his writings, and compel them to disclose in which of its many degrees of meaning he understands the phrase. 6 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. There is one of its acceptations, which, for the pur- pose now in view, may be put aside, though in itself defensible, and though, when thus employed, it expresses a real and important law of our mental nature. This is, that we only know anything, by knowing it as distin- guished from something else ; that all consciousness is of difference ; that two objects are the smallest number required to constitute consciousness ; that a thing is only seen to be what it is, by contrast with what it is not. The employment of the proposition, that all human knowledge is relative, to express this meaning, is sanctioned by high authorities,* and I have no fault to find with that use of the phrase. But we are not concerned with it in the present case ; for it is not in this sense, that the expression is ordinarily or intentionally used by Sir W. Hamilton ; though he fully recognises the truth which, when thus used, it serves to express. In general, when he says that all our knowledge is relative, the relation he has in view is not between the thing known and other objects compared with it, but between the thing known and the mind knowing. All language recognises a distinction between myself the Ego and a world, either material, or spiritual, or both, external to me, but of which I can, in some mode and measure, take cognizance. The most fundamental ques- tions in philosophy are those which seek to determine what we are able to know of these external objects, and by what evidence we know it. In examining the different opinions which are or may be entertained on this subject, it will simplify the ex- position very much, if we at first limit ourselves to the case of physical, or what are commonly called material objects. These objects are of course known to us through the senses. By those channels and no otherwise do we learn whatever we do learn concerning them. Without the senses we should not know nor suspect that such things existed. We know no more of what they are, than the * In particular by Mr. Bain, who habitually uses the phrase " relativity of knowledge" in this sense. THE RELATIVITY OP HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. 7 senses tell us, nor does nature afford us any means of knowing more. Thus much, in the obvious meaning of the terms, is denied by no one, though there are thinkers who prefer to express the meaning in other language. There are, however, conflicting opinions as to wliat it is that the senses tell us concerning objects. About one part of the information they give, there is no dispute. They tell us our sensations. The objects excite, or awaken in us, certain states of feeling. A part, at least, of what we know of the objects, is the feelings to which they give rise. What we term the properties of an object, are the powers it exerts of producing sensations in our consciousness. Take any familiar object, such as- an orange. It is yellow ; that is, it affects us, through our sense of sight, with a particular sensation of colour. It is soft ; in other words it produces a sensation, through our muscular feelings, of resistance overcome by a slight effort. It is sweet; for it causes a peculiar kind of pleasurable sensation through our organ of taste. It is- of a globular figure, somewhat flattened at the ends : we affirm this on account of sensations that it causes in us, respecting which it is still in dispute among psycholo- gists whether they originally came to us solely through touch and the muscles, or also through the organ of sight. When it is cut open, we discover a certain ar- rangement of parts, distinguishable as being, in certain respects, unlike one another ; but of their vmlikeness we have no measure or proof except that they give us dif- ferent sensations. The rind, the pulp, the juice, differ from one another in colour, in taste, in small, in degree of consistency (that is, of resistance to pressure) all of which are differences in our feelings. The parts are, moreover, outside one another, occupying different por- tions of space : and even this distinction, it is maintained (though the doctrine is vehemently protested against by some) may be resolved into a difference in our sensations. When thus analysed, it is affirmed that all the attributes which we ascribe to objects, consist in their having the power of exciting one or another variety of sensation in 3 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. our rnind ; that to us the properties of an object have this and no other meaning ; that an object is to us no- thing else than that which affects our senses in a certain manner ; that we are incapable of attaching to the word object, any other meaning ; that even an imaginary ob- ject is but a conception, such as we are able to form, of something which would affect our senses in some new way; so that our knowledge of objects, and even our fancies about objects, consist of nothing but the sensa- tions which they excite, or which we imagine them ex- . citing in ourselves. This is the doctrine of the Eelativity of Knowledge to the knowing mind, in the simplest, purest, arid, as I think, the most proper acceptation of the words. There are, however, two forms of this doctrine, which differ materially from one another. According to one of the forms, the sensations which, in common parlance, we are said to receive from objects, are not only all that we can possibly know of the objects, but are all that we have any ground for believing to exist. What we term an object is but a complex con- ception made up by the laws of association, out of the ideas of various sensations which we are accustomed to receive simultaneously. There is nothing real in the process but these sensations. They do not, indeed, ac- company or succeed one another at random ; they are held together by a law, that is, they occur in fixed groups, and a fixed order of succession : but we have no evidence of anything which, not being itself a sensation, is a sub- stratum or hidden cause of sensations. The idea of such a substratum is a purely mental creation, to which we have no reason to think that there is any corresponding reality exterior to our minds. Those who hold this opinion are said to doubt or deny the existence of matter. They are sometimes called by the name Idealists, some- times by that of Sceptics, according to the other opinions which they hold. They include the followers of Berkeley and those of Hume. Among recent thinkers, the acute and accomplished Professor Ferrier, though by a circuitous THE RELATIVITY OP HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. 9 path, and expressing himself in a very different phrase- ology, seems to have arrived at essentially the same point of view. These philosophers maintain the Rela- tivity of our knowledge in the most extreme form in which the doctrine can be understood, since they con- tend, not merely that all we can possibly know of any- thing is the manner in which it affects the human faculties, but that there is nothing else to be known ; that affections of human or of some other minds are all that we can know to exist. This, however, is far from being the shape in which the doctrine of the Relativity of our knowledge is usu- ally held. To most of those who hold it, the difference between the Ego and the Non-Ego is not one of lan- guage only, nor a formal distinction between two aspects of the same reality, but denotes two realities, each having a separate existence, and neither dependent on the other. In the phraseology borrowed from the School- men by the German Transcendentalists, they regard the .Noumenon as in itself a different thing from the Phae- j nomenon, and equally real ; many of them would say, \ much more real, being the permanent Reality, of which the other is but the passing manifestation. They be- lieve that there is a real universe of " Things in Them- selves/' and that whenever there is an impression on our senses, there is a " Thing in itself," which is behind the phaenomenon, and is the cause of it. But as to what this Thing is "in itself," we, having no organs except our senses for communicating with it, can only know what our senses tell us ; and as they tell us nothing but the impression which the thiug makes upon us, we do not know what it is in itself at all. We suppose (at least these philosophers suppose) that it must be some- thing " in itself," but all that we know it to be is merely relative to us, consisting in the power of affecting us in certain ways, or, as it is technically called, of producing Phenomena. External things exist, and have an in- most nature, but their inmost nature is inaccessible to our faculties. We know it not, and can assert nothing 10 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. of it with a meaning, Of the ultimate Realities, as such, we know the existence, and nothing more. But the impressions which these Realities make on us i;he sensations they excite, the similitudes, groupings, and successions of those sensations, or, to sum up all this in a common though improper expression, the represen- tations generated in our minds by the action of the Things themselves these we may know, and these are all that we can know respecting them. In some future state of existence it is conceivable that we may know more, and more may be known by intelligences superior to us. Yet even this can only be true in the same sense in which a person with the use of his eyes knows more than is known to one born blind, or in which we should know more than we do if we were endowed with two or three additional senses. We should have more sensa- tions ; phamornena would exist to us of which we have at present no conception ; and we might know better than we now do, many of those which are within our present experience; for if the new impressions were linked with the old, as the old are with one anoiher, by uniformities of succession and coexistence, we should now have new marks indicating to us known phseno- mena in cases in which we should otherwise have been unaware of them. But all this additional knowledge would be, like that which we now possess, merely phae- nomenal. We should not, any more than at present, know things as they are in themselves, but merely an increased number of relations between them and us. And in the only meaning which we are able to attach to the term, a^L^^ii^g^ by however exalted an In- telligence, can only be relative to the knowing Mind. ]i[ Things have an inmost nature, apart not only troni the impressions which they produce, but from ail those which they are fitted to produce, on any sentient being, this inmost nature is unknowable, inscrutable, and in- conceivable, not to us merely, but to every other crea- ture. To say that even the Creator could know it,, is to use language which to us has no meaning, because THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. 11 we have no faculties by which to apprehend that there \ is any such thing for him to know. It is in this form that the doctrine of the Eelativity of Knowledge is held by the greater number of those who profess to hold it, attaching any definite idea to the term. These again are divided into several distinct schools of thinkers, by some of whom the doctrine is held with a modification of considerable importance. Agreeing in the opinion that what we know of Nou- mena, or Things in themselves, is but their bare exis- tence, all our other knowledge of Things being but a knowledge of something in ourselves which derives its origin from them ; there is a class of thinkers who hold that our mere sensations, and an outward cause which \ produces them, do not compose the whole of this relative v/ A/sh knowledge. The Attributes which we ascribe to out- * // ward things, or such at least as are inseparable from them in thought, contain, it is affirmed, other elements, over and above sensations plus an unknowable cause. TTiese additional elements are still only relative, for they are not in the objects themselves, nor have we evidence of anything in the objects that answers to them. They are added by the mind itself, and belong, not to the ' Things, but to our perceptions and conceptions of them. < Such properties as the objects can be conceived divested of, suck as sweetness or sourness, hardness or softness, hotness or coldness, whiteness, redness, or blackness these, it is sometimes admitted, exist in our sensations only. But the attributes of filling space, and occupying a portion of time, are not properties of our sensations in their crude state, neither, again, are they properties of the objects, nor is there in the objects any prototype of them. They result from the nature and structure of the Mind itself : which is so constituted that it cannot take any impressions from objects except in those par- ticular modes. We see a thing in a place, not because the Noumenon, the Thing in itself, is in any place, but because it is the law of our perceptive faculty that we must see as in some place, whatever we see at all. Place 12 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. is not a property of the Thing, but a mode in which the mind is compelled to represent it. Time and Space are only modes of our perceptions, not modes of existence, and higher Intelligences are possibly not bound by them. Things, in themselves, are neither in time nor in space, though we cannot represent them to ourselves except under that twofold condition. Again, when we predicate of a thing that it is one or many, a whole or a part of a whole, a Substance possessing Accidents, or an Accident inhering in a Substance when we think of it as producing Effects, or as produced by a Cause, (I omit other attributes not necessary to be here enumerated,) we are ascribing to it properties which do not exist in the Thing itself, but with which it is clothed by the laws of our conceptive faculty properties not of the Things, but of our mode of conceiving them. We are compelled by our nature to construe things to ourselves under these forms, but they are not forms of the Things. The attributes exist only in relation to us, and as in- herent laws of the human faculties ; but differ from Succession and Duration in being laws of our intel- lectual, not our sensitive faculty; technically termed Categories of the Understanding. This is the doctrine of the .Relativity of our knowledge as held by Kant, who has been followed in it by many subsequent thinkers, German, English, and French. By the side of this there is another philosophy, older in date, which, though temporarily eclipsed and often .^contemptuously treated by it, is, according to present appearances, likely to survive it. Taking the same view with Kant of the unknowableness ot Things in them- selves, and also agreeing with him that we mentally invest the objects of our perceptions with attributes which do not all point, like whiteness and sweetness, to specific sensations, but are in some cases constructed by the mind's own laws ; this philosophy, however, does not think it necessary to ascribe to the mind certain innate forms, in which the objects are (as it were) moulded into these appearances, but holds that Place, Extension, Substance, Uause, and the rest, are conceptions RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. 13 put together out of ideas of sensation by the known ^laws of association. This, the doctrine of Hartley, of James Mill, of Professor Bain, and other eminent thinkers, and which is compatible with either the acceptance or the rejection of the Berkeleian theory, is the extreme form of one mode of the doctrine of Relati- vity, as Kant's is of another. Both schemes accept the doctrine in its widest sense the entire inaccessibility to our faculties of any other knowledge of Things than that of the impressions which they produce in our mental consciousness. Between these there are many intermediate systems, according as different thinkers have assigned more or less to the original furniture of the mind on the one hand, or to the associations generated by experience on the other. Brown, for example, regards our notion of Space or Extension as a product of association, while many of our intellectual ideas are regarded by him as ultimate and undecomposable facts. But he accepts, in its full extent, the doctrine of the Relativity of our knowledge, being of opinion that though we are assured of the objective existence of a world external to the mind, our knowledge of that world is absolutely limited to the modes in which we are affected by it. The same doctrine is very impressively taught by one of the acutest metaphysicians of recent times, Mr. Herbert Spencer, who, in his " First Principles," insists with equal force upon the certainty of the existence of Things in Themselves, and upon their absolute and eternal relegation to the region of the Unknowable.* This is also, apparently, the doctrine of Auguste Comte : though while maintaining with great emphasis the unknow- ableness of Noumena by our faculties, his aversion to metaphysics prevented him from giving any definite opinion as to their real existence, which, however, his language always by implication assumes. It is obvious that what has been said respecting the ' unknowableness of Things " in themselves," forms no * See, however, below, a note near the end of chap. ix. 14 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. obstacle to our ascribing attributes or properties to them, provided these are always conceived as relative to us. If a thing produces effects of which our sight, hearing, or touch can take cognizance, it follows, and indeed is but the same statement in other words, that the thing hasj^ftfr to produce those effects. These variousjpowers are its properties, and of such, an indefinite multitude is open to our knowledge. But this knowledge is merely phenomenal. The object is known to us only in one special relation, namely, as that which produces, or is capa- ble of producing, certain impressions on our senses ; and all that we really know is these impressions. This nega- tive meaning is all that should be understood by the assertion, that we cannot know the Thing in itself; that we cannot know its inmost nature or essence. The in : most nature or essence of a Thing is apt to be regarded as something unknown, which, if we knew it, would ex- . plain and account for all the phenomena which the thing ' exhibits to us. But this unknown something is a sup- -' 'position without evidence. We have no ground for supposing that there is anything which if known to us would afford to our intellect this satisfaction ; would sum up, as it were, the knowable attributes of the object in a single sentence. Moreover, if there were such a central property, it would not answer to the idea of an " inmost nature ;" for if knowable by any intelligence, it must, like other properties, be relative to the intelligence which knows it, that is, it must solely consist in pro- ducing in that intelligence some specifically definite state of consciousness ; for this is the only idea we have of knowing; the only sense in which the verb "to know" means anything. It would, no doubt, be absurd to assume that our words exhaust the possibilities of Being. There may be innumerable modes of it which are inaccessible to our faculties, and which consequently we are unable to name. But we ought not to speak of these modes of Being by any of the names we possess. These are all inapplicable, because they all stand for known modes of Being. We might invent new names for such unknown modes ; but THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. 15 the new names would have no more meaning than the x, y, z, of Algebra. The only name we can give them which really expresses an attribute, is the word Unknow- able. The doctrine of the Relativity of our knowledge, in the sense which has now been explained, is one of great weight and significance, which impresses a character on the whole mode of philosophical thinking of whoever receives it, and is the key-stone of one of the only two possible systems of Metaphysics and Psychology. But the doctrine is capable of being, and is, understood in at least two other senses. In one of them, instead of a definite and important tenet, it means something quite insignificant, which no one ever did or could call in question. Suppose a philosopher to maintain that cer- tain properties of objects are in the Thing, and not in our senses ; in the thing itself, not as whiteness may be said to be in the thing (namely, that there is in the thing a power whereby it produces in us the sensation of white), but in quite another manner ; and are known to us nol; indirectly, as the inferred causes of our sensa- tions, but by direct perception of them in the. outward object. Suppose the same philosopher nevertheless to affirm strenuously that all our knowledge is merely phaenomenal, and relative to ourselves; that we do not and cannot know anything of outward objects, except relatively to our own faculties. I think our first feeling respecting a thinker who professed both these doctrines, would be to wonder what he could possibly mean by the latter of them. It would seem that he must mean one of two trivialities ; either that we can only know what we have the power of knowing, or else that all our know- ledge is relative to us inasmuch as it is we that know it. There is another mode of understanding the doctrine of Relativity, intermediate between these insignificant truisms and the substantial doctrine previously ex- pounded. The position taken may be, that perception of Things as they are in themselves is not entirely denied to us, but is so mixed and confounded with impressions derived from their action on us, as to 16 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. give a relative character to the whole aggregate. Our absolute knowledge may be vitiated and disguised by the presence, of a relative element. Our faculty (it may be said) of perceiving tilings as they are in themselves, though real, has its own laws, its own conditions, and necessary mode of operation : our cognitions subse- quently depend, not solely on the nature of the things to be known, but also on that of the knowing faculty, as our sight depends not solely upon the object seen, but upon that together with the structure of the eye. If the eye were not achromatic, we should see all visible objects with colours derived from the organ, as well as with those truly emanating from the object. Supposing, there- fore, that Things in themselves are the natural and proper object of our knowing faculty, and that this faculty carries to the mind a report of what is in the Thing itself, apart from its effects on us, there would still be a portion of uncertainty in these reports, inasmuch as we could not be sure that the eye of our mind is achromatic, and that the message it brings from the Noumenon does not arrive tinged and falsified, in an unknown degree, through an influence arising from the necessary conditions of the mind's action. We may, in short, be looking at Things in themselves, but through imperfect glasses : what we see may be the very Thing, but the colours and forms which the glass conveys to us may be partly an optical illusion. This is a possible opinion : and one who, holding this opinion, should speak of the Eelativity of our knowledge, would not use the term wholly without meaning. But he could not, con- sistently, assert that all our knowledge is relative ; since his opinion would be that we have a capacity of Absolute knowledge, but that we are liable to mistake relative knowledge for it. In which, if in any, of these various meanings, was the doctrine of Relativity held by Sir W. Hamilton ? To this question, a more puzzling one than might have been expected, we shall endeavour in the succeeding chapter to find an answer. 17 CHAPTER III. THE DOCTRINE OF THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE, AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. IT is hardly possible to affirm more strongly or more ex- plicity than Sir W. Hamilton has done, that Things in themselves are to us altogether unknowable, and that all we can know of anything is its relation to us, composed of, and limited to, the Phsenomena which it exhibits to our organs. Let me cite a passage from one of the Appendices to the " Discussions/ 3 * " Our whole knowledge of kind and of matter is re- " lative, conditioned relatively conditioned. Of things " absolutely or in themselves, be they external, be they " internal, we know nothing, or know them only as in- " cognisable; and become aware of their incomprehensible " existence, only as this is indirectly and accidentally re- " vealed to us, through certain qualities related to our " faculties of knowledge, and which qualities, again, we " cannot think as unconditioned, irrelative, existent in " and of themselves. All that we know is therefore " phenomenal, phenomenal of the unknown .... " Nor is this denied; for it has been commonly confessed, " that, as substances, we know not what is Matter, and " are ignorant of what is Mind." This passage might be matched by many others, equally emphatic, and in appearance equaiiy decisive ; several of which I shall have occasion to quote. Yet in the sense which the author's phrases seem to convey- in the only important meaning capable of being attached to them the doctrine they assert was certainly not held * " Discussions on Philosophy," p. 643. C 18 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE by Sir W. Hamilton. He by no means admits that we know nothing of objects except their existence, and the impressions produced by them upon the human mind. He affirms this in regard to what have been called by metaphysicians the Secondary Qualities of Matter, but denies it of the Primary. On this point his declarations are very explicit. One of the most elaborate of his Dissertations on Reid is devoted to expounding the distinction. The Disserta- tion begins thus :* " The developed doctrine of Real Presentationism, the " basis of Natural Realism" (the doctrine of the author himself) " asserts the consciousness or immediate per- " ception of certain essential attributes of Matter ob- jectively existing; while it admits that other properties " of body are unknown in themselves, and only inferred " as causes to account for certain subjective affections of " which we are cognizant in ourselves. This discrimina- " tion, which to other systems is contingent, superficial, " extraneous, but to Natural Realism necessary, radical, " intrinsic, coincides with what since the time of Locke " has been generally known as the distinction of the " Qualities of Matter or Body, using these terms as con- " vertible, into Primary and Secondary." Further on,f he states, in additional development of so-called Natural Realism, " that we have not merely a "' notion, a conception, an imagination, a subjective re- " presentation of Extension, for example called up or " suggested in some incomprehensible manner to the " mind, on occasion of an extended object being pre- " sented to the sense ; but that in the perception of such " an object we really have, as by nature we believe we " have, an immediate knowledge of that external object " as extended." " If J we are not percipient of any extended reality, " we are not percipient of body as existing ; for body * Dissertations appended to Sir W. Hamilton's Edition of Reid's Works, p. 825. f Dissertations, p. 842. J Ibid. AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 19 " exists, and can only be known immediately, and in (< itself, as extended. The material world, on this sup- " position, sinks into something unknown and proble- " matical ; and its existence, if not denied, can, at least, be " only precariously affirmed, as the occult cause, or in- o* J!k0 ' " comprehensible occasion, of certain subjective affections " we experience in the form either of a sensation of the " secondary quality or of a perception of the primary." Not only, in Sir W. Hamilton's opinion, do we know, ^vA" 3 by direct consciousness or perception, certain properties vy/*- of Things as they exist in the Things themselves, but ^ , we may also know those properties as in the Things, by demonstration a priori. " The notion* of body being " given, every primary quality is to be evolved out of " that notion, as necessarily involved in it, independently " altogether of any experience of sense." " Thef Pri- " mary Qualities may be deduced a priori, the bare notion " of matter being given ; they being, in fact, only evo- " lutions of the conditions which that notion necessarily " implies." He goes so far as to say, that our belief of the Primary Qualities is, not merely necessary as in- volved in a fact of which we have a direct perception, but necessary in itself, by our mental constitution. He] speaks j of " that absolute or insuperable resistance which f " we are compelled, independently of experience, to think " that every part of matter would oppose to any attempt " to deprive it of its space, by compressing it into an in- 1 " extended." The following is still more specific. " The Primary" Qualities " are apprehended as they are in bodies ; the Secondary, as they are in us: the Secundo-primary" (a third class created by himself, comprising the me- chanical as distinguished from the geometrical properties of Body) " as they are in bodies and as they are in us. . . . " We know the Primary qualities immediately as objects " of perception ; the Secundo-primary both immediately " as objects of perception and mediately as causes of sen- * Dissertations, p. 844. f Ibid. p. 846. I Ibid. p. 848. Ibid. pp. 857, 853. c 2 20 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE " sation ; the Secondary only mediately as causes of sen- " sation. In other words : The Primary are known im- " mediately in themselves ; the Secundo-primary, both " immediately in themselves and mediately in their effects " on us ; the Secondary, only mediately in their effects on " us We are conscious, as objects, in the " Primary Qualities, of the modes of a not-self; in the " Secondary, of the modes of self; in the Secundo-pri- " mary, of the modes of self and of a not-self at once." There is nothing wonderful in Sir W. Hamilton's entertaining these opinions ; they are held by perhaps a majority of metaphysicians. But it is surprising that, entertaining them, he should have believed himself, and been believed by others, to maintain the Relativity of all our knowledge. What he deems to be relative, in any sense of the term that is not insignificant, is only our knowledge of the Secondary Qualities of objects. Exten- sion and the other Primary Qualities he positively asserts that we have an immediate intuition of, " as they are in bodies" "as modes of a not-self ;" in express contra- distinction to being known merely as causes of certain impressions on our senses or on our minds. As there cannot have been, in his own thoughts, a flat contradic- tion between what he would have admitted to be the two cardinal doctrines of his philosophy, the only question that can arise is, which of the two is to be taken in a non-natural sense. Is it the doctrine that we know certain properties as they are in the Things ? Were we to judge from a foot-note to the same Dissertation, we might suppose so. He there observes* " In saying " that a thing is known in itself, I do not mean that this " object is known in its absolute existence, that is, out " of relation to us. This is impossible : for our know- " ledge is only of the relative. To know a thing in itself " or immediately, is an expression I use merely in con- " trast to the knowledge of a thing in a representation, " or mediately :" in other words, he merely means that we perceive objects directly, and not through the species * P. 866. AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 21 sensibiles of Lucretius, the Ideas of Locke, or the Mental Modifications of Brown. Let us suppose this granted, and that the knowledge we have of objects is gained by direct perception. Still, the question has to be answered whether the knowledge so acquired is of the objects as they are in themselves, or only as they are relatively to us. Now what, according to Sir W. * Hamilton, is this knowledge ? Is it a knowledge of the ^-T^ Thing, merely in its effects on us, or is it a knowledge of ,.] ' somewhat in the Thing, ulterior to any effect on us ? He asserts in the plainest terms that it is the latter. t ,r Then it is not a knowledge wholly relative to us. If what we perceive in the Thing is something of which we QJ#>* are only aware as existing, and as causing impressions on \f* us, our knowledge of the Thing is only relative. But yP- if what we perceive and cognise is not merely a cause of our subjective impressions, but a Thing possessing, in itso^*^,. own nature and essence, a long listof properties, Extension, ^ Impenetrability, Number, Magnitude, Figure, Mobility,^ Position, all perceived as " essential attributes " of the % Thing as " objectively existing" all as " Modes of a Not-Self" and by no means as an occult cause or causes of any Modes of Self (and that such is the case Sir W. Hamilton asserts in every form of language, leaving no stone unturned to make us apprehend tlie breadth of the distinction) then I am willing to believe that in affirming this knowledge to be entirely relative to Self, such a thinker as Sir W. Hamilton had a meaning, but I have no small difficulty in discovering what it is. The place where we should expect to find this difficulty cleared up, is the formal exposition of the Relativity of Human Knowledge, in the first volume of the Lectures. He declares his intention* of " now stating and ex- " plaining the great axiom that all human knowledge, " consequently that all human philosophy, is only of the " relative or phenomenal. In this proposition, the term " relative is opposed to the term absolute ; and therefore, " in saying that we know only the relative, I virtually * Lectures, i. 136-8. 22 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE " assert that we know nothing absolute, nothing exist - " ing absolutely, that is, in and for itself, and without rela- " tion to us and our faculties. I shall illustrate this by " its application. Our knowledge is either of matter or " of mind. Now, what is matter? What do we know " of matter ? Matter, or body, is to us the name either " of something known, or of something unknown. In so " far as matter is a name for something known, it means " that which appears to us under the forms of extension, " solidity, divisibility, figure, motion, roughness, smooth- " ness, colour, heat, cold, &c. ; in short, it is a common " name for a certain series, or aggregate, or complement " of appearances or phsenomena manifested in coexistence. " But as these phenomena appear only in conjunction, " we are compelled by the constitution of our nature to " think them conjoined in and by something ; and as they " are phsenomena, we cannot think them the phsenomena " of nothing, but must regard them as the properties or " qualities of something that is extended, solid, figured, " &c. But this something, absolutely and in itself, " i.e. considered apart from its phsenomena is to us as " zero. It is only in its qualities, only in its effects, in " its relative or phaenomenal existence, that it is cogniz- ! " able or conceivable ; and it is only by a law of thought " which compels us to think something absolute and un- " known, as the basis or condition of the relative and " known, that this something obtains a kind of incom- * O " prehensible reality to us. Now, that which manifests " its qualities in other words, that in which the appear- " ing causes inhere, that to which they belong, is called " their subject, or substance, or substratum. To this sub- " ject of the phsenomena of extension, solidity, &c., the " term matter or material substance is commonly given ; " and therefore, as contradistinguished from these quali- " ties, it is the name of something unknown and incon- " ceivable. " The same is true in regard to the term mind. In so " far as mind is the common name for the states of " knowing, willing, feeling, desiring, &c., of which I am AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 23 " conscious, it is only the name for a certain series of " connected phsenomena or qualities, and, consequently, " expresses only what is known. But in so far as it " denotes that subject or substance in which the phseno- " mena of knowing, willing, &c., inhere -something be- " hind or under these phenomena it expresses what, " in itself or in its absolute existence, is unknown. " Thus, mind and matter, as known or knowable, are " only two different series of phsenomena or qualities ; " mind and matter, as unknown and unknowable, are " the two substances, in which these two different series " of phsenomena or qualities are supposed to inhere. " The existence of an unknown substance is only an in- " ference we are compelled to make from the existence " of known phsenomena ; and the distinction of two sub- " stances is only inferred from the seeming incompati- " bility of the two series of phsenomena to coinhere in "oneT~ " Our whole knowledge of mind and matter is thus, " as we have said, only relative ; of existence, absolutely " and in itself, we know nothing : and we may say of " man what Virgil said of tineas, contemplating in the " prophetic sculpture of his shield the future glories of " Koine " Rerumque ignarus, imagine gaudet," Here is an exposition of the nature and limits of our knowledge, which would have satisfied Hartley, Brown, and even Comte. It cannot be more explicitly laid down, that Matter, as known to us, is but the incom- prehensible and incognisable basis or substratum of a bundle of sensible qualities, appearances, phsenomena; that we know it "only in its effects;" that its very existence is " only an inference we are compelled to make " from those sensible appearances. On the subject of Mind, again, could it have been more explicitly affirmed, that all we know of Mind is its successive states " of knowing, willing, feeling, desiring, &c.," and that Mind, considered as " something behind or under these phaenomena," is to us unknowable ? 24 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE Subsequently he says, that not only all the know- ledge we have of anything, but all which we could have if we were a thousandfold better endowed than we are, would still be only knowledge of the mode in which the thing would affect us. Had we as many senses (the illustration is his own) as the inhabitants of Sirius, in the " Micromegas" of Voltaire ; were there, as there may well be, a thousand modes of real existence as definitely distinguished from one another as are tnose which manifest themselves to our present senses, and " had we,* for each of these thousand modes, a separate " organ competent to make it known to us, still would " our whole knowledge be, as it is at present, only of " the relative. Of existence, absolutely and in itself, we " should then be as ignorant as we are now. We should " still apprehend existence only in certain special modes " only in certain relations to our faculties of knowledge." Nothing can be truer or more clearly stated than all this : but the clearer it is, the more irreconcileable does . .^ it appear with our author's doctrine of the direct cog- v . ' noscibility of the Primary Qualities. If it be true that Extension, Figure, and the other qualities enumerated, are known " immediately in themselves," and not, like Secondary qualities, " in their eifects on us ;" if the former are " apprehended as they are in bodies," and not, like the Secondary, " as they are in us ;" if it is these last exclusively that are " unknown in themselves, and only " inferred as causes to account for certain subjective " affections in ourselves :" while, of the former, we are immediately conscious as ''attributes of matter objec- tively existing;" and if it is not to be endured that matter should "sink into something unknown and problematical," whose existence "can be only precari- " ouslv affirmed as the occult cause or incomprehensible " occasion of certain subjective affections we experience " in the form either of a sensation of the secondary qua- " lity or of a perception of the primary" (being pre- cisely what Sir YV. Hamilton, in the preceding quota- * Lectures, i. 153. AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 25 tions, appeared to say that it is) ; if these things be so, our faculties, as far as the Primary Qualities are con- cerned, do cognise and know Matter as it is in itself, and not merely as an unknowable and incomprehensible substratum ; they do cognise and know it as it exists absolutely, and not merely in relation to us ; it is known to us directly, and not as a mere " inference " from Phenomena. Will it be said that the attributes of extension, figure, number, magnitude, and the rest, though known as in the Things themselves, are yet known only relatively to us, because it is by our faculties that we know them, and because appropriate faculties are the necessary con- dition of knowledge? If so, the "great axiom" of Relativity is reduced to this, that we can know things as they are m themselves, but can know no more of them than our faculties are competent to inform us of. If such be the meaning of Relativity, our author might well maintain* that it is a truth "harmoniously re- echoed by every philosopher of every school ;" nor need he have added " with the exception of a few late Ab- solute theorizers in Germany;" for certainly neither Schelling nor Hegel claims for us any other knowledge than such as our faculties are, in their opinion, compe- tent to give. is it possible, that by knowledge of qualities " as they are in Bodies," no more was meant than knowing that the Body must have qualities whereby it produces the aifection of which we are conscious in ourselves ? But this is the very knowledge which our author pre- dicates of Secondary Qualities, as contradistinguished from the Primary. Secondary he frankly acknowledges to be occult qualities : we really, in his opinion, have no knowledge, and no conception, what that is in an object, by virtue of which it has its specific smell or taste. But Primary qualities, according to him, we know all about : there is nothing occult or mysterious to us in these; we perceive and conceive them as they are in * Discussions, Appendix, p. 644. 26 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE themselves, and as they are in the body they belong to. They are manifested to us, not, like the Secondary qualities, only in their effects, in the sensations they excite in us, but in their own nature and essence. Perhaps it may be surmised, that in calling knowledge of this sort by the epithet Relative, Sir W. Hamilton meant that though we know those qualities as they are in themselves, we only discover them through their re- lation to certain effects in us ; that in order that there may be Perception there must also be Sensation ; and we thus know the Primary Qualities, in their effects on us and also in themselves. But neither will this ex- planation serve. This theory of Primary Qualities does not clash with the Secondary, but it runs against the Secundo-primary. It is this third class, which, as he told us, are known " both immediately in themselves and mediately in their effects on us." The Primary are only known " immediately in themselves." He has thus with his own hands deliberately extruded from our knowledge of the Primary qualities the element of rela- tivity to us :- except, to be sure,' in the acceptation in which knowing is itself a relation, inasmuch as it implies a knower ; whereby instead of the doctrine that Things in themselves are not possible objects of knowledge, we obtain the " great axiom " that they cannot be known unless there is somebody to know them. Can any light be derived from the statement that we do not know any qualities of things except those which are in connextion with our faculties, or, as our author expresses it (surely by a very strained use of language), which are " analogous to our faculties ?"* If, by " our faculties," is to be understood our knowing faculty, this proposition is but the trivial one already noticed, tiiat we can know only what we can know. And this is what the author actually seems to mean for in a sentence immediately following,! he paraphrases the expression " analogous to our faculties," by the phrase that we must " possess faculties accommodated to their apprehension." * Lectures, i. 141, 153. f P. 153. AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 27 To be able to see, we must have a faculty accommodated to seeing. Is this what we are intended to understand by the " great axiom ?" But if " our faculties " does not here mean our knowing faculty, it must mean our sensitive faculties ; and the statement is, that, to be known by us, a quality must be " analogous " (meaning, I suppose, related) to our senses. But what is meant by being related to our senses ? That it must be fitted to give us sensations. We thus return as before to an identical proposition. There is still another possible supposition ; that, in calling oar knowledge relative in contradistinction to absolute, Sir W. Hamilton was not thinking of our knowledge of qualities, but of substances of Matter and Mind ; and meant that qualities might be cognised absolutely, or as they are in themselves, but that, since substances are only known through their qualities, the knowledge of substances is not knowledge of them as they are in themselves, but is merely relative. Accord- ing to this interpretation, the relativity which Sir W. Hamilton ascribes to our knowledge of substances is re- lativity not to us, but to their attributes : we " become " aware of their incomprehensible existence only as this " is revealed to us through certain qualities." And when he adds, " which qualities, again, we cannot think " as unconditioned, irrelative, existent in and of theni- " selves," thus predicating relativity of attributes also (considered as known or conceived by us), he means rela- tivity to a substance. We can only know a substance through its qualities, but also, we can only know quali- ties as inhering in a substance. Substance and attri- bute are correlative, and can only be thought together : the knowledge of each, therefore, is relative to the other ; but need not be, and indeed is not, relative to us. For we know attributes as they are in themselves, and our knowledge of them is only relative inasmuch as attri- butes have only a relative existence. It is relative knowledge in a sense not contradictory to absolute. It is an absolute knowledge, though of things which only 28 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE . exist in a necessary relation to another thing called a substance.* 1 am not disposed to deny that this interpretation of Sir W. Hamilton's doctrine is, to a certain point, correct. He did draw a distinction between our manner of know- ing attributes and our manner of knowing substances ; and did regard certain attributes (the primary qualities) as objects of direct and immediate knowledge ; which, in his opinion, substances are not, but are merely as- sumed or inferred from phenomena, by a law of our nature which compels us to think phsenomena as attributes of something beyond themselves. I do not doubt that when he said that our knowledge of attributes is relative, the necessity of thinking every attribute as an attribute of a substance was present to his mind, and formed a part of his meaning. There is, however, abundant evi- dence that the relativity which Sir W. Hamilton ascribed to our knowledge of attributes was not merely relativity to their substances, but also relativity to us. He affirms of attributes as positively as of substances, that all our knowledge of them is relative to us. The passages already quoted apply as much to attributes as to sub- stances. " In saying that we know only the relative, I " virtually assert that we know nothing absolute nothing " existing absolutely, that is, in and for itself, vxAwithuut " relation to us and our /acuities!^ " In saying that a " thing is known in itself, I do not mean that this object " is known in its absolute existence, that is, out of rela- " tion to us. This is impossible, for our knowledge is only " of the relative." I In the following passages he is speaking solely of attributes. " By the expression what " they are in themselves, in reference to the primary <{ qualities, and of relative notion in reference to the " secondary, Reid cannot mean that the former are " known to us absolutely and in themselves, that is, out * This is essentially the interpretation put on Sir W. Hamilton's meaning by the ingenious reviewer of the present work in the Edinburgh Heview. f Lectures, i. 137. % Dissertations, p. 866. AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 29 " of relation to our cognitive faculties ; for he elsewhere " admits that all our knowledge is relative."* " We " can know, we can conceive, only what is relative. " Our knowledge of qualities or phenomena is neces- " sarily relative ; for these exist only as they exist in " relation to our faculties. "f The distinction, therefore, which Sir W. Hamilton recognises between our know- ledge of substances and that of attributes, though authentically a part of his philosophy, is quite irrelevant here. He affirms without reservation, that certain at- tributes (extension, figure, &c.) arejknown to us as they really exist out of ourselves; and also that ajl our knowledge of them is relative to us. And these two assertions are only reconcileable, if relativity to us is understood in the altogether trivial sense, that we know them only so far as our faculties permit. J The conclusion I cannot help drawing from this col- lation of passages is, that Sir W. Hamilton either never held, or when he wrote the Dissertations had ceased to hold (for his theory respecting knowledge of the Primarv Qualities does not occur in the Lectures) the doctrine for which he has been so often praised and nearly as often attacked the Relativity of Human Knowledge. He certainly did sincerely believe that he held it. But he repudiated it in every sense which makes it other than a barren truism. In the only meaning in which he really maintained it, there is nothing to maintain. It is an identical proposition, and nothing more. And to this, or something next to this, he reduces it in the first portion of the summary with which he con- cludes its exposition. " From what has been said," he * Footnote to Reid, p. 313. f Ib. p. 320. I am indebted to Mr. Hansel (Philosophy of the Con- ditioned, p. 79) for reminding me of the last two passages. 1 should not have failed to quote them in the first edition, if I had kept references to them. | I may add that even the Edinburgh Reviewer's supposition does not save either the relativity of human knowledge to us, or its relativity in the sense in which relative is opposed to absolute, as doctrines of Sir W. Hamilton: for by the Reviewer's interpretation our knowledge of attributes would be relative only to their substances ; absolute in their cognition by us. 01 dfy Out, V*i-fi^ . 1 UK. 30 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE observes,* "you will be able, I hope, to understand " what is meant by the proposition, that all our know- " ledge is only relative. It is relative, 1st. Because ex- " istence is not cognisable absolutely in itself, but only " in special modes ; 2nd. Because these modes can be " known only if they stand in a certain relation to our " faculties." Whoever can find anything more in these two statements, than that we do not know all about a Thing, but only as much about it as we are capable of knowing, is more ingenious or more fortunate than myself. He adds, however, to these reasons why our know- ledge is only relative, a third reason. " 3rd. Because the " modes, thus relative to our faculties, are assented to, and " known by, the mind only under modifications deter- " mined by those faculties themselves." Of this addition to the theory we took notice near the conclusion of the preceding chapter. It shall have the advantage of a fuller explanation in Sir W. Hamilton's words. " Inf the perception of an external object, the mind " does not know it in immediate relation to itself, but " mediately, in relation to the material organs of sense. " If, therefore, we were to throw these organs out of " consideration, and did not take into account what they " contribute to, and how they modify, our knowledge of " that object, it is evident that our conclusion in regard " to the nature of external perception would be erroneous. " Again, an object of perception may not even stand in " immediate relation to the organ of sense, but may " make its impression on that organ through an inter- " vening medium. Now, if this medium be thrown out " of account, and if it be not considered that the real " external object is the sum of all that externally con- " tributes to affect the sense, we shall, in like manner, " run into error. For example, I see a book I see that " book through an external medium (what that medium " is, we do not now inquire) and I see it through my " organ of sight, the eye. Now, as the full object pre- * Lectures, i. 148. f Ibid. pp. 146-148. AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 31 " seated to the mind (observe that T say the miud) in : ' perception, is an object compounded of the external " object emitting or reflecting light, i.e., modifying the " external medium of this external medium and of " the living organ of sense, in their mutual relation, ' let us suppose, in the example I have taken, that the " full or adequate object perceived is equal to twelve, and " that this amount is made up of three several parts ; of " four, contributed by the book, of four, contributed by " all that intervenes between the book and the organ, " and of four, contributed by the living organ itself. I " use this illustration to show that the phenomenon of " the external object is not presented immediately to " the mind, but is known by it only as modified " through certain intermediate agencies ; and to show, " that sense itself may be a source of error, if we do " not analyze and distinguish what elements, in an act " of perception, belong to the outward reality, what to " the outward medium, and what to thj action of sense " itself. But this source of error is not limited to our " perceptions ; and we are liable to be deceived, not " merely by not distinguishing in an act of knowledge " what is contributed by sense, but by not distinguishing " what is contributed by the mind itself. This is the " most difficult and important function of philosophy ; " and the greater number of its higher problems arise in " the attempt to determine the shares to which the " knowing subject, and the object known, may pretend " in the total act of cognition. For according as we " attribute a larger or a smaller proportion to each, we " either run into the extremes of Idealism and Mate- " rialism, or maintain an equilibrium between the two." The proposition, that our cognitions of objects are only in part dependent on the objects themselves, and in part on elements supentdded by our organs or by our minds, is not identical, nor prima facie absurd. It can- not, however, warrant the assertion that all our know- ledge, but only that the part so added, is relative. If our author had gone as far as Kant, and had said that all 32 the primary qualities which we think we perceive in bodies, are put in by the mind itself, he would have really held, in one of its forms, the doctrine of the Relativity of our knowledge. But what he does say, far from implying that the whole of our knowledge is relative, distinctly imports that all of it which is real and authentic is the reverse. If any part of what we fancy that we perceive in the objects themselves, origi- nates in the perceiving organs or in the cognising mind, thus much is purely relative ; but since, by supposition, it does not all so originate, the part that does not, is as much absolute as if it were not liable to be mixed up with these delusive subjective impressions. The ad- mixture of the relative element not only does not take away the absolute character of the remainder, but does not even (if our author is right) prevent us from recog- nising it. The confusion, according to him, is not in- extricable. It is for us to " analyze and distinguish what elements" in an " act of knowledge" are contributed by the object, and what by our organs, or by the mind. We may neglect to do this, and as far as the mind's share is concerned, can only do it by the help of philo- sophy ; but it is a task to which in his opinion philosophy is equal. By thus stripping off such of the elements in our apparent cognitions of Things as are but 'cognitions of something in us, and consequently relative, we may succeed in uncovering the pure nucleus, the direct in- tuitions of Things in themselves ; as we correct the observed positions of the heavenly bodies by allowing for the error due to the refracting influence of the atmospheric medium, an influence which does not alter the facts, but only our perception of them. This last doctrine, however, that the mind's own con- stitution contributes along with the outward object, to make up what is called our knowledge of the object, is what Mr. Mansel maintains Sir W. Hamilton to have meant by the assertion that our whole knowledge of the object is relative. And this is the foundation of all that Mr. Mansel presents as a refutation of the present chapter. AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 33 If it be true (to use Mr. Hansel's words)* that, in the constitution of our knowledge, the mind " reacts on the " objects affecting it, so as to produce a result different " from that which would be produced, were it merely a " passive recipient," this modifying action of the mind must consist, as is affirmed by Kant and by all others who profess the doctrine, in making us ascribe to the object, and apprehend as in the object, properties which are not really in the object, but are merely lent to it by the constitution of our mental nature. Now, if the attri- butes which we perceive, or think we perceive, in objects, are partly given by the mind, but not wholly, being also partly given by the nature of the object itself (which is admitted to be Sir W. Hamilton's opinion) ; this joint agency of the object and of the mind's own laws in gene- rating what we call our knowledge of the object, may be conceived in two ways. First : The two factors may be jointly operative in every part of the effect. Every attribute with which we per- ceive the thing as invested, may be a joint product of the thing itself and of the modifying action of the mind. If this be the case, we do not really know any property as it is in the object : we have no reason to think that the object as we apprehend it, and as we figure to our- selves that we perceive and know it, agrees in any respect with the object that exists without us ; but only that it depends upon that outward object, as one of its joint causes. Such was the opinion of Karit ; and whoever is of this opinion, holds, in one of its forms, as I have ex- pressly admitted, the genuine doctrine of the Relativity of our knowledge. For all must agree with Mr. Mansel when he says, that an object of thought, into which the mind puts a positive element of its own, thereby making it different from what it otherwise would be, is that which it is, only relatively to the mind. This seems to be Mr. Mansel's own mode of representing to himself the com- bined action of the mind and the object in perception. * Mansel, p. 64. D 34 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE For he compares it* to the action of an acid and an alkali in forming a neutral salt ; andf to a chemical fusion together of two elements, in contradistinction to a mere mechanical juxtaposition. If we had never seen, and could not get at, the acid or the alkali except as united in the salt, Mr. Mansel could not think that our knowledge of the salt gave us any knowledge of the acid or the alkali them- selves. But, secondly : There is another mode in which the co-operation of the object and the mind's own properties in producing our cognition of the object, may be con- ceived as taking place. Instead of there being joint agents in producing our cognitions of all the attributes with which we mentally clothe the object, some of the attributes as cognised by us may come from the object only, and some from the mind only, or from both. Now it is not open to a holder of this second opinion, as it is to one of the first, to affirm that all the attributes are only known relatively to us. Such of them, indeed, as are made to be that which they are by what the mind puts into them, are, on this theory, only known relatively to the mind : they have even no existence except rela- tively to the mind. But those into which no positive element is introduced by the mind's laws (I say no posi- tive element, because a mere negative limitation by the mind's capacities is nothing to the purpose), these, as their cognition contains nothing but what is presented in the external object, must be held to be known not rela- tively, but absolutely. The doubt how much of what we apprehend in them is due to our own constitution, and how much to the external world, has no place here : they are, by supposition, wholly perceptions of something in the external world. Now, this second view of the joint action of the mind and the outward thing, as the two factors in our cog- nition of the thing, is Sir W. Hamilton's. The pas- sages in which he characterizes our knowledge of the * Mansel, p. 71. f Ibid. p. 75. AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 35 Primary Qualities place this beyond question. He affirms \ clearly and consistently that extension, figure, and the other Primary Qualities are known by us " as they are in bodies," and not " as they are in us ;" that they are known as " essential attributes of matter objectively existing ;" as " modes of a not-self," not even combined, as in the Secundo-primary, with any " modes of self;" so that no element originating in our subjective constitution in- terferes with the purity of the apperception. In this respect the physical phenomena which Mr. Mansel calls in as illustrations afford no parallel. No one would say that the acid in a neutral salt is perceived and known by us in the salt as what it is as an acid. Indeed, the discrimination which Sir W. Hamilton i thinks it possible for philosophy to make, between that in our knowledge which the object contributes and that which the mind contributes, almost requires as its con- dition that some attributes should be wholly contributed by the one and some by the other : for if every attribute was the joint product of both, it is difficult to see what means the case could afford of making the discrimination, any more than of discriminating between the acid and the alkali in Mr. Mansel's salt. The question, how much of the salt is due to the acid and how much to the alkali, is not merely unresolvable, but intrinsically absurd.* * Sir W. Hamilton has the appearance of disclaiming the opinion here attributed to him, and professing the alternative opinion that every attri- bute is a joint product of the object and the mind, in the following foot- note to Eeid (p. 313) : "The distinctions of perception and sensation, and of primary and ' secondary qualities, may be reduced to one higher principle. Knowledge ' is partly objective, partly subjective ; both these elements are essential ' to every cognition, but in every cognition they are always in the inverse ' ratio of each other. Now, in_rjercepjtipn and the primary qualities, the objective element preponderates ; whereas the subjective element pre- p.. migrates in sensation and the secondary qualities. See Notes D 'andD*." But a reference to the Notes in question will shew, that in admitting a subjective element in the Primary Qualities, he only meant that a sub- jective element accompanies our apprehension of them; that whenever we perceive the primary qualities we are conscious of a sensation also. " Sensation proper," he says, " is the conditio sine qua non of a Perception D 2 36 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE Mr. Mansel's mode of reconciling Sir W. Hamilton's emphatic declaration, that we know the Primary Qualities as they are in objects, with his assertion of the entire incognoscibility of Things in themselves, is by saying* that " objects" are not identical with " things in them- selves." " Objective existence," he says,f " does not mean " existence per se ; and a phenomenon does not mean a " mere mode of mind. Objective existence is existence as " an object, in perception, and therefore in relation; and " a phenomenon may be material, as well as mental. The " thing per se may be only the unknown cause of what " we directly know ; but what we directly know is some- " thing more than our own sensations. In other words, " the phenomenal effect is material as well as the cause, " and is, indeed, that from which our primary conceptions " of matter are derived." Now, this is a possible opinion ; it was really the opinion of Kant. That philosopher did recognise a direct object of our perceptions, different from the thing itself, and intermediate between it and the perceiving mind. And it was open to Kant to do so ; because he held what Sir W. Hamilton calls a representative theory of perception. He maintained that the object of our perception, and of our knowledge, is a representation in our own minds. In his philosophy, both object and sub- ject are accommodated within the mind itself the object within the subject. The mind has no perception of the external thing, nor comes into any contact with it in the " proper of the Primary qualities." And again, " Every Perception proper " has a Sensation proper as its condition." " The fact of Sensation proper " and the fact of Perception proper imply each other :" they always co- exist, though " in the degree or intensity of their existence they are always " found in an inverse ratio to one another" (Reid, p. 886). This co- existence does not prevent the two from being entirely distinct. " The " apprehensions of the Primary" qualities " are perceptions, not sensa- " tions ; of the Secondary, sensations, not perceptions ; of the Secundo- " primary, perceptions and sensations together" (p. 858). Perceptions, the apprehensions of the Primary qualities, are themselves wholly objective. * Hansel, p. 79. f Ibid. p. 82. AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 37 act of perception.* Was this Sir W. Hamilton's opinion? On the contrary, if there be a doctrine of his philosophy which he has laboured at beyond any other, against, as he affirms, nearly all philosophers, it is, that the thing we perceive is the real thing which exists outside us, and that the perceiving mind is in direct contact with it, without any intermediate link whatever. We never I hear from Sir W. Hamilton of three elements in our cognition of the outward world, but of two only, the mind, and the real object ; which he sometimes calls the external object, sometimes Body, sometimes Matter, some- times a Non-ego. Yet, according to Mr. Mansel, he ' must have believed that this object, which he so strenu- ously contended to be the very thing itself, is not the very thing in itself, but that behind it there is another Thing in itself, the unknown cause of it. I can discover no trace in Sir W. Hamilton's writings of any such entity. The outward things which he believed to exist, he believed that we perceive and know : not, indeed, " absolutely or in themselves," because only in such of their attributes as we have senses to reveal to us ; but yet as they really are. He did not believe in, or recognise, a | Thing per se, itself unknowable, but engendering another material object called a phenomenon, which is knowable. I The only distinction he recognised between a phsenome- non and a Thing per se, was that between attributes and a substance. But he believed the primary attributes to i be known by us as they exist in the substance, and not , in some intermediate object.f * Such, at least, is the doctrine of Kant in the first edition of the Kritik, though, in the so-called Refutation of Idealism introduced into the second, he is sometimes supposed to have intended to explain it away; but Mr. Mahaffy (Introd. part iv. and notes to Appendix C) seems to have explained away the explanation ; and Mr. Stirling, who holds (p. 30) " the second edition of the Kritik of Pure Reason to supersede the first," still credits Kant with this doctrine, interpreting in a sense consistent with it, the externality which Kant ascribes to objects in space. Kant's external and internal were both internal to the mind. Nothing but the noumenon was external to it. f If any doubt could remain that Mr. Mansel defends Sir W. Hamil- ton by ascribing to him an opinion he never held, the following passage 38 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE The mark by which Mr. Mansel distinguishes between the object and the Thing in itself, is that the object is in space and time, but the Thing out of space and time ; space and time having merely a subjective existence, in us, not in external nature. This is Kantism, but it is not Hamiltonism. I do not believe that the expression " out of space and time" is to be found once in all Sir would dispel it. " If, indeed," says Mr. Mansell (p. 83) " Hamilton had " said with Locke, that the primary qualities are in the bodies themselves, " whether we perceive them or no, he would have laid himself open to " Mr. Mill's criticism. But he expressly rejects this statement, and con- " trasts it with the more cautious language of Descartes, ' ut sunt, vel " saltern esse possunt.' " Sir W. Hamilton may never have said, totidem verbis, that the Primary Qualities are in the bodies even when we do not perceive them : but can any one who has read his writings doubt that this was his opinion ? The passage which Mr. Mansel refers to as "reject- ing" it (Dissertations, p. 839) runs as follows : " On the doctrine of " both philosophers" (Locke and Descartes) " we know nothing of material "existence in itself: we know it only as represented, or in idea. When " Locke, therefore, is asked, how he became aware that the known idea ' truly represents the unknown reality, he can make no answer. On the " first principles of his philosophy, he is wholly and necessarily ignorant ' whether the idea does or does not represent to his mind the attributes ' of matter, as they exist in nature. His assertion is, therefore, con- ' fessedly without a warrant ; it transcends, ex hypothesi, the sphere of ' possible knowledge. Descartes is more cautious. He only says, that ' our ideas of the qualities in question represent those qualities as they ' are, or as they may exist ; ' ut sunt, vel saltern esse possunt.' The ' Cosmothetic Idealist can only assert to them a problematical reality." Mr. Mansel actually thinks this an adoption of Descartes' opinion ; and does not see that Sir W. Hamilton merely pronounces Descartes to be right and Locke wrong from their own point of view, that of Cosmothetic Idealism. As Cosmothetic Idealists, they have, he says, no evidence that the qualities we perceive are in the object itself, and are as we perceive them. Not admitting that we directly perceive the qualities in the object, they cannot do more than assert problematically that the qualities are in the object ; and this Descartes saw, and Locke, more inconsistently, did not see. But what they as Cosmothetic Idealists could not affirm, Sir W. Hamilton, as a Natural Realist, could ; because, as a Natural Realist, he held that we directly perceive the qualities in the object. Mr. Mansel mistakes one of the thousand statements by Sir W. Hamilton of hjs difference with the Cosmothetic Idealists, for an adhesion to them. (Mr. Mansel, in his rejoinder, admits and withdraws this error.) Sir W. Hamilton, as Professor Fraser observes (p. 22), believed that " the ' solid and extended percepts which our sensations reveal to us, exist, " whether we are conscious or not." He believed that bodies exist whether we perceive them or not, and that they always carry their "essential attributes," the Primary Qualities, with them : if, therefore, he had thought that the Primary Qualities only exist while we perceive them, he must have thought so of the bodies likewise, and must have believed that we create the bodies in the act of perceiving them; which Kant, who AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 39 W. Hamilton's writings. It belongs to the Kantian, not to the Hamiltoniaii philosophy. Sir W. Hamilton does indeed hold with Kant, and on Kant's shewing, that space and time are a priori forms of the mind, but he believes that they are also external realities, known empirically.* And it is worth notice, that he grounds the outward reality of Space, not on his favourite evi- dence, that of our Natural Beliefs, but on the specific reason, that (Extension being only another name for Space), if Space was not an outward thing cognizable deemed the body we perceive to be really in tlie mind, did believe ; but if Sir W. Hamilton did, his whole philosophy of perception is without a meaning. In the essay in his " Discussions," headed " Philosophy of Perception," Sir W. Hamilton speaks of the knowledge of external objects claimed by a Natural Realist, ipsissimis verbis, as knowledge of " things in them- selves." (Discussions, p. 57, in the statement of the opinion of Hypo- thetical Realists.) For a critical examination of the doctrine ascribed to Sir W. Hamilton by Mr. Mansel, that of an external object cognizable by us, and an un- cognizable Noumenon besides, I may refer to Mr. Bolton's able work, pp. 218 et seqq. Mr. Mansel, in his rejoinder, though he does not give up the theory of the tertium quid, does not further insist on it ; but attempts to shew that when Sir W. Hamilton speaks of knowing the Primary qualities as they are in themselves, and as they are in the body, he means knowing them in immediate relation to the mind, in contradistinction to knowing them mediately through a mental representation, or merely inferring them as the hypothetical cause of a mental state. I admit, and have already admitted, that Sir W. Hamilton did mean this, and did say that he meant it. But the " immediate relation to the mind" which Sir W. Hamilton thus distinguished from the different modes of mediate relation, is no other than that between perceiver and perceived : and to say that all our knowledge is relative, meaning only this relation, is but to say, that we know of external things only what we perceive of them, and that in order that we may know an object of sense it must be presented to our senses. The knowledge, when we do get it, according to Sir W. Hamilton, is not (in the case of Primary qualities) knowledge of an impression made on our own sensitive faculty, which would be really relative knowledge j it is knowledge of the Thing as it exists in itself, independently of our per- ceptions. It is this which, as I have pointed out, reduces the pretended Relativity to a name. It is a great confirmation of the unmeaningness of the Relativity Doc- trine in Sir W. Hamilton's hands, that those who have most studied his philosophy, Dean Mansel and Professor Veitch, are reduced to such straits in the attempt to find a meaning for it, and do not always find the same meaning. * See Lectures, ii. 113, 114 ; Discussions, p. 16; Dissertations, p. 882 ; and, in further illustration, foot note to Reid, p. 12t> ; passages strangely overlooked by Mr. Mansel (p. 138). 40 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE a posteriori, we could not, as he affirms that we do, cognize Extension as an external reality. He must therefore have thought, not that Space is a mere form in which our perceptions of objects are clothed by the laws of our perceiving faculty, but that we perceive real things in real space.* Mr. Mansel is not the only one of my critics who has interpreted Sir W. Hamilton's doctrine of our direct knowledge of outward objects, as if those outward objects were a tertium quid, between the mind and the real out- ward, or if the expression may be permitted, the outer outward object. For, irreconcilable as this supposition is with the evidence of his writings, it is the only one which can be thought of to give a substantial meaning to his doctrine of Kelativity, consistent with the external reality of the Primary Qualities. Professor Mason con- sequently had already taken refuge in the same inter- pretation as Mr. Mansel ; but propounded it in the modest form of an hypothesis, not a dogmatical asser- tion. The North American Ke viewer in like manner saysf : " An existence non-ego may be immediately cog- " nizable consistently with the doctrine of the relativity " of knowledge, provided this non-ego be phenomenal, " that is, necessarily dependent on some other incogniz- " able existence among the real causes of things " If the meaning of the word phenomenon which we " have attributed to Hamilton be a valid one, his philo- " sophy escapes from this criticism by affirming that the " primary qualities of matter, that is, the having exten- " sion, figure, &c., though not cognized as the effects of * When Sir W. Hamilton says (Dissertations, p. 841) that although Space is a native, necessary, a priori form of imagination, we yet have an immediate perception of a really objective extended world, Mr. Mansel imagines that Sir W. Hamilton is maintaining at once the subjectivity of Space, and the objectivity of bodies as occupying space. But Sir W. Hamilton himself declares unequivocally that these two opinions contra- dict one another, unless reconciled by the suppositiou that Space ia objective and external to us as well as subjective : not, therefore, properly a form of our mind, but an outward reality which has a form of our mind corresponding to it* See the whole of the passages referred to in the last note. f Pp. 252, 253. AS HELD BT SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 41 " matter on us, are yet modes of existence implying an " unknown substance, and are hence phenomenal in ' Hamilton's meaning of the word." This explanation might pass, if Sir W. Hamilton's assertion of the rela- tivity of our knowledge to our mind were all contained in the word phsenomenal, and could be explained away by supposing that word to mean relativity not to us, but to an unknown cause. But I need not requote his declaration that our knowledge of Qualities is all relative to us, nor his assertion that nevertheless certain qualities are in the object, and are perceived and known in the object, and that the object perceived and known is no other than the real Thing itself. Nowhere in his works do I find any recognition of another real Thing, which is not the Thing perceived by us through its attributes. He does not tell us of a Body perceived, and an unper- ceived Substance in the background : the Body is the Substance. He does indeed say that the Substance is only an inference from the Attributes ; but he also says that certain attributes are perceived as in the real exter- nal Thing ; and he never drops the smallest hint of any real external thing in which the attributes can be, except the Substance itself, which he expressly defines as " that which manifests its qualities," that in which " the phaenomena or qualities are supposed to in- " here." Professor Fraser, in the (in many respects) profound Essay of which he has done this work the honour of making it the occasion, vindicates at once the consistency of Sir W. Hamilton, and the substantial significance of his doctrine of Kelativity, by ascribing to him, in oppo- sition to his incessant declarations, Mr. Eraser's own far clearer views of the subject. Mr. Fraser, like myself, believes the Primary Qualities to have no more existence out of our own or other minds, than the Secondary * Qualities have, or than our pains and pleasures have ; and he asks,* " Where does he " (Sir W. Hamilton) " say * Fraser, p. 16. 42 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE " that we have an absolute knowledge of the primary " qualities of matter, in any other sense than that in " which he says that we have a like knowledge of a feel- " ing of pain or pleasure in our minds while it is being " felt, or of an act of consciousness while it is being " acted?" To this "where," I answer, in every place where he says that we know the Primary Qualities not as they are in us, but as they are in the Body. That is asserting an absolute knowledge of them, as distinguished from relativity to us : and he would not have made a similar assertion of our pains and pleasures, or of our acts of internal consciousness. Again, asks Air. Fraser,* " How does the assertion that we are percipient directly, " and not through a medium, of phenomena of solidity " and extension, contradict the principle that all our " knowledge is relative, when the assertion that we are " percipient, directly and not through a medium, of the " phenomena of sensation or emotion or intelligence " does not ?'' Because the phenomena of sensation or emotion or intelligence are admitted to be perceived or felt as facts that have no reality out of us, and the facts being only relative to us, the knowledge of the facts partakes of the same relativity : but the phenomena of solidity and extension are alleged by Sir W. Hamilton to be perceived as facts whose reality is out of our minds, and in the material object : which is indeed know- v ' ^o*** ing them relatively to the outward object, but is the diametrical opposite of knowing them relatively to us.f It has now been shown, by accumulated proof, that * Fraser, p. 15. f Mr. Fraser affirms (p. 20) with me, and contrary to Mr. Mansel and the North American Reviewer, that in Sir W. Hamilton's opinion '' there " is nothing behind the proper objects of sense-consciousness, these being " the very things or realities themselves which we call material, external, " extended, solid." Instead of recognizing three elements, a .Noumenal real thing, a Phenomenal real thing, and the perceiving mind, the middle one of the three being that which the mind cognizes, Mr. Fraser sees that Sir W. Hamilton recognised but one real Thing, the very Thing which we perceive ; unknown to us in its essence, but perceived and known through its attributes ; and by means of those attributes, actually brought into what Sir W. Hamilton calls our consciousness. This Mr. Fraser regards as "a distinct and important contribution by Sir W.Hamilton to the AS HELD BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 43 Sir W. Hamilton did not hold any opinion in virtue of which it could rationally be asserted that all human knowledge is relative ; but did hold, as one of the main elements of his philosophical creed, the opposite doctrine, of the cognoscibility of external Things, in certain of their aspects, as they are in themselves, absolutely. But if this be true, what becomes of his dispute with " theory of matter previously common in this country," because bringing matter into our consciousness is part of the way towards making it (what Mr. Fraser believes it to be) wholly a phenomenon of mind. But Sir W. Hamilton did not intend his doctrine to lead to this ; he admits Matter into our consciousness because, contrary to the general opinion of philo- sophers, he thinks (see below, chap, viii.) that we can be conscious of .s what is outside our mind. Sir W. Hamilton, in short, was not a Berkeleian, a.s Mr. Fraser is, and as that philosopher almost admits (p. 2b') that the interpretation which he would like to put on Sir W. Hamilton's doctrine would make Sir W. Hamilton. Mr. Fraser seems to me, throughout his defence of Sir W. Hamilton, to have yielded to the natural tendency of a consistent thinker when standing up for an inconsistent one, to interpret ambiguous utterances which face two ways, as if they looked only one way ; though the part of their author's philosophy towards which those expressions face on their other side, is thereby set at nought and abolished. Since the publication of the third edition of this work, my attention has been drawn to a passage (unfortunately left unfinished) in the post- humous continuation of Sir W. Hamilton's Dissertations on Reid, which strikingly confirms the opinion I have expressed, that the relativity of human knowledge, as understood by him, is a mere identical proposition. " That all knowledge consists in a certain relation of the object known " to the subject knowing, is self-evident. What is the nature of this " relation, and what are its conditions, is not, and never can be, known to " us ; because we know only the qualities of our own faculties of know- " ledge, as relations to their objects, and we only know the qualities of " their objects, as relations to our minds. All qualities both of mind and " of matter are therefore only known to us as relations ; we know nothing " in itself. We know not the cause of this relation, we know nothing of " its conditions, the fact is all. The relation is the relation of knowledge. " We know nothing consequently of the kind of the relation ; we have no " consciousness and no possible knowledge whether the relation of knpw- ' ledge has any analogy to the relations of similarity, contrariety, identity, ' difference we have no consciousness that it is like any other, or any ' modification of any other : these are all relations of a different kind ' between object and object ; this between subject and object : we can * institute no point of comparison" (Reid, p. 965). That is to say, we know nothing except in relation to us, but that relation is simply the relation of being known by us, and this is the only relation cognizable by us which exists between the knower and the known. Our knowledge is relative, but only in the sense that knowing is itself a relation. Would Cousin, or Hegel, or Schelling, have had the slightest objection to admit that onr knowledge even of the Absolute is relative, in the sense that it is we that know it ? 44 THE RELATIVITY OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. Cousin, and with Cousin's German predecessors and teachers ? That celebrated controversy surely meant something. Where there was so much smoke there must have been some fire. Some difference of opinion must really have existed between Sir W. Hamilton and his antagonists. Assuredly there was a difference, and one of great im- portance from the point of view of either disputant ; not unimportant in the view of those who dissent from them both. In the succeeding chapter I shall endeavour to point out what the difference was. 45 CHAPTER IV. IN WHAT RESPECT SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON REALLY DIFFERS FROM THE PHILOSOPHERS OF THE ABSOLUTE. THE question really at issue in Sir W. Hamilton's cele- brated and striking review of Cousin's philosophy, is this : Have we, or have we not, an immediate intuition of God. The name of God is veiled under two ex- tremely abstract phrases, " The Infinite" and " The Absolute," perhaps from a reverential feeling : such, at least, is the reason given by Sir W. Hamilton's disciple, Mr. Mansel,* for preferring the more vague expressions. But it is one of the most unquestionable of all logical maxims, that the meaning of the abstract must be sought for in the concrete, and not conversely; and we shall see, both in the case of Sir W. Hamilton and of Mr. Mansel, that the process cannot be reversed with im- punity.f * Bampton Lectures. (The Limits of Religious Thought.) Fourth edition, p. 42. f Mr. Mansel (pp. 90 98) denies the correctness of the representations made in this paragraph ; and at least seems to assert, that the question between M. Cousin and Sir W. Hamilton did not relate to the possibility of knowing the Infinite Being, but to a " pseudo-concept of the Infinite," which Sir W. Hamilton believed to be not a proper predicate of God, but a representation of a non-entity. And Mr. Mansel affirms (p. 92) that to substitute the name of God in the place of the Infinite and the Absolute, is" exactly to reverse Sir W. Hamilton's argument. We have here a direct issue of fact, of which every one is a judge who will take the trouble to read Sir W. Hamilton's Essay. I maintain that what M. Cousin affirms and Sir W. Hamilton denies, is the cognoscibility not of an Infinite and Absolute which is not God, but of the Infinite and Absolute which is God. I might refer to almost any page of the Essay ; I will only quote the application which Sir W. Hamilton himself makes of his own doctrine (Disc. p. 15, note). " True, therefore, are the declarations of a pious phi- " losophy : ' A God understood would be no God at all.' ' To think that " God is, as we can think him to be, is blasphemy.' The Divinity, In a 46 SIR WII.LTAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. I proceed to state, chiefly in the words of Sir W. Hamilton, the opinions of the two parties to the con- troversy. Both undertake to decide what are the facts which (in their own phraseology) are given in Conscious- ness ; or, as others say, of which we have intuitive knowledge. According to Cousin, there are, in every act of consciousness, three elements ; three things of which we are intuitively aware. There is a finite ele- ment; an element of plurality, compounded of a Self or Ego, and something different from Self, or Non-ego. There is also an infinite element ; a consciousness of something infinite. " At* the same instant when we are " certain sense, is revealed ; in a certain sense, is concealed : he is at once " known and unknown. But the last and highest consecration of all true "religion, must be an altar 'Ayyoborw 6eo> ' To the unknown and unknow- " able God.' " When this is what the author of the Essay presents as its practical result, it is too much to tell us that the Essay is not con- cerned about God but about a " Pseudo-Infinite," and that we are not entitled, when we find in it an assertion about the Infinite, to hold the author to the assertion as applicable to God. We shall next be told that Mr. Mansel himself, in his Bampton Lectures, is not treating the question of our knowledge of God. It is very true that the only, Infinite about which either Sir W. Hamilton or Mr. Mansel proves anything, is a Pseudo-Infinite ; but they are not in the least aware of this ; they fancy that this Pseudo- Infinite is the real Infinite, and that in proving it to be unknowable by us, they prove the same thing of God. The reader who desires further elucidation of this point, may consult the sixth chapter of Mr. Bolton's Inquisitio Philosophica. That acute thinker also points out various inconsistencies and other logical errors in Mr. Mansel's work, with which I am not here concerned, my object in answering him not being recrimination, but to maintain my original assertions against his denial. Mr. Mansel, in his rejoinder, quotes from his Bampton Lectures some passages in which he says, and others in which he implies, that " our " human conception of the Infinite is not the true one," and that " the " infinite of philosophy is not the true Infinite :" and thinks it very unfair that, with these passages before me, I should accuse him of mistaking a pseudo-infinite for the real Infinite. But the mistake from which he clears himself is not that which I charged him with. I maintained, that the abstraction " The Infinite," in whatever manner understood, as dis- tinguished from some particular attribute possessed in an infinite degree, has no existence, and is a pseudo-infinite. Mr. Mansel, on the contrary, affirmed throughout, and affirms in the very passages which he quotes, that "The Infinite" has a real existence, and is God: though when we attempt to conceive what it is, we only reach a mass of contradictions, which is a pseudo-infinite. Mr. Mansel did not suppose his pseudo-infinite to be the true Infinite ; but my assertion, which stands unrefuted, is, that his " true Infinite" is a pseudo-infinite ; and that in proving it to be un- knowable by us, he mistakenly fancied that he had proved this of God. * Discussions, p. 9. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. 47 " conscious of these [finite] existences, plural, relative, " and contingent, we are conscious likewise of a superior " unity in which they are contained, and by which they " are explained ; a unity absolute as they are conditioned, " substantive as they are phenomenal, and an infinite " cause as they are finite causes. This unity is God." The first two elements being the Finite and God, the third element is the relation between the Finite and God, which is that of cause and effect. These three things are immediately given in every act of consciousness, and are, therefore, apprehended as real existences by direct intuition. Of these alleged elements of Consciousness, Sir W. Hamilton only admits the first ; the Finite element, com- pounded of Self and a Not-self, " limiting and condition- ing one another." He denies that God is given in immediate consciousness is apprehended by direct intui- tion. It is in no such way as this that God, according to him, is known to us : and as an Infinite and Absolute Being he is not, and cannot be, known to us at all ; for we have no faculties capable of apprehending the Infinite or the Absolute. The second of M. Cousin's elements being thus excluded, the third (the Relation between the first and second) falls with it; and Consciousness remains limited to the finite element, compounded of an Ego and a Non-ego. In this contest it is almost superfluous for me to say, that I am entirely with Sir W. Hamilton. The doctrine, that we have an immediate or intuitive knowledge of God, I consider to be bad metaphysics, involving a false conception of the nature and limits of the human facul- ties, and grounded on a superficial and erroneous psycho- logy. Whatever relates to God I hold to be matter of inference ; I would add, of inference a posteriori. And in so far as Sir W. Hamilton has contributed, which he has done very materially, towards discrediting the oppo- site doctrine, he has rendered, in my estimation, a valuable service to philosophy. But thougli 1 assent to his con- clusion, his arguments seem to me very far from inex- 48 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. pugnable : a sufficient answer, I conceive, might without difficulty be given to most of them, though I do not say that it was always competent to M. Cousin to give it. And the arguments, in the present case, are of as much importance as the conclusion : not only because they are quite as essential a part of Sir W. Hamilton's philosophy, but because they afford the premises from which some of his followers, if not himself, have drawn inferences which I venture to think extremely mischievous. While, therefore, I sincerely applaud the scope and purpose of this celebrated piece of philosophical criticism, I think it important to sift with some minuteness the reasonings it employs, and the general mode of thought which it exemplifies. The question is, as already remarked, whether we have a direct intuition of " ihe Infinite" and " the Absolute :" M. Cousin maintaining that we have Sir W. Hamilton that we have not ; that the Infinite and the Absolute are inconceivable to us, and, by consequence, unknowable. It is proper to explain to any reader not familiar with these controversies, the meaning of the terms. Infinite requires no explanation. It is universally understood to signify that, to the magnitude of which there is no limit. If we speak of infinite duration, or infinite space, we are supposed to mean duration which never ceases, and extension which nowhere comes to an end. Absolute is much more obscure, being a word of several meanings ; but, in the sense in which it stands related to Infinite, it means (conformably to its etymology) that which is finished or completed. There are some things of which the utmost ideal amount is a limited quantity, though a quantity never actually reached. In this sense, the relation between the Absolute and the Infinite is (as Bentham would have said) a tolerably close one, namely a relation of contrariety. For example, to assert an absolute minimum of matter, is to deny its infinite divisibility. Again, we may speak of absolutely, but not of infinitely, pure water. The purity of water is not a fact of which, whatever degree we suppose attained, there re- SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. 49 mains a greater beyond. It has an absolute limit : it is capable of being finished or complete, in thought, if not in reality. The extraneous substances existing in any vessel of water cannot be of more than finite amount, and if we suppose them all withdrawn, the purity of the water cannot, even in idea, admit of further increase. The idea of Absolute, in this sense of the term, being thus contrasted with that of Infinite, they cannot, both of them, be truly predicated of God ; or, if truly, not in respect of the same attributes. But the word Absolute, without losing the signification of perfect or complete, may drop that of limited. It may continue to mean the whole of that to which it is applied ; but without requiring that this whole should be finite. Granted (for instance) a being of infinite power, that Being's know- ledge, if supposed perfect, must be infinite ; and may therefore, in an admissible sense of the term, be said to be both absolute and infinite.* In this acceptation there is no inconsistency or incongruity in predicating both these words of God. * In the first edition of this work it was maintained, that though Power admits of being regarded as Infinite, Knowledge does not ; because " the " highest degree of knowledge that can be spoken of with a meaning, only " amounts to knowing all that there is to be known." But Mr. Hansel and the " Inquirer" (author of "The Battle of the Two Philosophies'") have justly remarked, that on the supposition of an Infinite Being, "all that there is to be known" includes all which a Being of infinite power can think or create; consequently, the power being infinite, the know- ledge, if supposed complete, must be infinite too. In regard to the moral attributes, it was said in the first edition, that Absolute is the proper word for them, and not Infinite, since those attributes "cannot be more " than perfect. There are not infinite degrees of right. The will is " either entirely right, or wrong in different degrees." In this I did not properly distinguish between moral Tightness or justice as predicated of acts or mental states, and the same regarded as attributes of a person. Conformity to the standard of right has a positive limit, which can only be reached, not surpassed ; but persons, though all exactly conforming to the standard, may differ in the strength of their adherence to it : in- fluences (temptations for example) might detach one of them from it, which would have no effect upon another. There are thus, consistently with complete observance of the rule of right, innumerable gradations of the attribute considered as in a person. But. on the other hand, there is an extreme limit to these gradations the idea of a Person whom no influences or causes, either in or out of himself, can deflect iu the minutest degree from the law of right. This I apprehend to be a conception of absolute, not of infinite, righteousness. The ductrine, therefore, or the firt edition, E 50 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. The word Absolute, however, has other meanings, which have nothing to do with perfection or complete- ness, though often mixed and confounded with it ; the more readily as they are all habitually predicated of the Deity. By Absolute is often meant the opposite of Re- lative ; and this is rather many meanings than one ; for Relative also is a term used very indefinitely, and wherever it is employed, the word Absolute alwa\ 7 s accompanies it as its negative. In another of its senses, Absolute means that which is independent of anything else : which exists, and is what it is, by its own nature, and not because of any other thing. In this fourth sense as in the third, Absolute stands for the negation of a relation ; not now of Relation in general, but of the specific relation expressed by the term Effect. In this signification it is synonymous with uncaused, and is therefore most naturally identified with the First Cause. The meaning of a First Cause is, that all other things exist, and are what they are, by reason of it and of its properties, but that it is not itself made to exist, nor to be what it is, by anything else. It does not depend, for its existence or attributes, on other things : there is nothing upon the existence of which its own is con- ditional : it exists absolutely. In which of these meanings is the term used in the polemic with M. Cousin ? M. Cousin makes no dis- tinction at all between the Infinite and the Absolute. Sir W. Hamilton distinguishes them as two species of a higher genus, the Unconditioned ; and defines the Infi- nite as "the unconditionally unlimited," the Absolute as "the unconditionally limited/''* Here is a new word introduced, the word " unconditionally ;" of which we look in vain for any direct explanation, but which needs it as much as either of the words which it is em- ployed to explain. In the Essay itself, this is the only that an Infinite Being may have attributes which are absolute, but not infinite, still appears to me maintainable. But as it is immaterial to my argument, and was only the illustration nearest at hand of the meaning of the terms, I withdraw it from the discussion. * Discussions, p. 13. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIV. 51 attempt made to define the Absolute : but in the reprint Sir W. Hamilton appends the following note :* " The term Absolute is of a twofold (if not threefold) " ambiguity, corresponding to the double (or treble) sig- " nification of the word in Latin." The third applica- tion he, with reason, dismisses, as here irrelevant. The other two are as follows : " 1. Absolutum means what is freed or loosed : in " which sense the Absolute will be what is aloof from " relation, comparison, limitation, condition, dependence, " &c., and thus is tantamount to TO a-n-oXvTov of the lower " Greeks. In this meaning the Absolute is not opposed " to the Infinite." This is an amplification of my third meaning. " 2. Absolut urn means finished, perfected, completed ; in " which sense the Absolute will be what is out oi " relation, &c. as finished, perfect, complete, total, and " thus corresponds to TO oXov and TO Tf'Xaoi/ of Aristotle. " In this acceptation and it is that in which for myself " I exclusively use it, the Absolute is diametrically " opposed to, is contradictory of, the Infinite." This second meaning of Sir W. Hamilton, which I, in the first edition, by a blameable inadvertence, confounded with my own first meaning,! must be reckoned as a fifth, compounded of the first and third of the idea of finished or completed, and the idea of being out of rela- tion. How to make an intelligible meaning out of the two combined, is the question. One can, with some difficulty, find a meaning in being " aloof from relation, " comparison, limitation, condition, dependence ;" but what is meant by being all this " as finished, perfect, " complete, total ?" Does it mean, being both out of rela- tion and also complete ? and must the Absolute in Sir * Discussions, p. 14, note. f And, in consequence, erroneously charged Sir W. Hamilton with having, in one of his arguments against Cousin, departed from his own meaning of the term. I have freed the text from everything which de- pended on this error, the only serious misrepresention of Sir W. Hamil- ton which has been established against me. E 2 52 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. W. Hamilton's second sense be also Absolute in his first, and be out of all relation whatever ? or does the particle "as" signify that it is out of relation only in in respect of its completeness, which (I suppose) means that it does not depend for its completeness on anything but itself? Mr. Hansel's comment, which otherwise does not help us much, decides for the latter. " Out of " relation as completed" means (he says*) " self-existent " in its completeness, and not implying the existence of " anything else."t Without further attempt to clear up the obscurity, let it suffice that Sir W. Hamilton's Absolute, though not synonymous with a " finished, perfected, completed," but limited, whole, includes that idea, and is therefore incompatible with Infinite. J Having premised these verbal explanations, I proceed to state, as far as possible in Sir W. Hamilton's own words, the heads of his argumentation to prove that the Absolute and Infinite are unknowable. His first summary statement of the doctrine is as follows :$ " The unconditionally unlimited, or the Infinite, the " unconditionally limited, or the Absolute, cannot posi- " tively be construed to the mind : they can be conceived " only by a thinking away from, or abstraction of, those " very conditions under which thought itself is realized ; " consequently, the notion of the Unconditioned is only " negative ; negative of the conceivable itself. For " example : On the one hand, we can positively conceive * Mansel, p. 104. f But the assimilation with TO 0X01* and TO re\fiov again throws us out ; for TO 6Xof , with all Greek thinkers, meant either the completed aggregate of all that exists, or an abstract entity which they conceived aa the Prin- ciple of Wuoleness in virtue of which, and by participation in which, that universal aggregate and all other wholes owe wholes. Either of these would be an additional meaning for the word Absolute, different from all which have yet been mentioned. J I demur, however, to Sir W. Hamilton's assertion, that for himself he exclusively uses the term in this meaning. In the whole of the discussion respecting the relativity of our knowledge, Absolute, with Sir W. Hamilton, is simply the opposite of relative, and contains no implication of " finished, perfected, completed." Moreover, in this very Essay, when arguing against M. Cousin, who uses Absolute in a sense compatible with Infinite, Sir W. Hamilton continually falls into M. Cousin's sense. Discussions, p. lo. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. 53 " neither an absolute whole, that is, a whole so great " that we cannot also conceive it as a relative part of a " still greater whole ; nor an absolute part, that is, a part " so small that we cannot also conceive it as a relative " whole divisible into smaller parts. On the other hand, " we cannot positively represent, or realize, or construe " to the mind (as here Understanding and Imagination " coincide) an infinite whole, for this could only be done " by the infinite synthesis in thought of finite wholes, " which would itself require an infinite time for its "accomplishment; nor, for the same reason, can we " follow out in thought an infinite divisibility of parts. " The result is the same, whether we apply the process " to limitation in space, in time, or in degree. The un- " conditional negation, and the unconditional affirmation " of limitation ; in other words, the Infinite and the " Absolute properly so called, are thus equally incon- " ceivable to us." This argument, that the Infinite and the Absolute are unknowable by us because the only conceptions we are able to form of them are negative, is stated still more emphatically a few pages later.* " Kant has clearly " shown, that the Idea of the Unconditioned can have " no objective reality, that it conveys no knowledge, " and that it involves the most insoluble contradictions. " But he ought to have shown that the Unconditioned " had no objective application, because it had, in fact, no " subjective affirmation; that it afforded no real know- " ledge, because it contained nothing even conceivable ; " and that it is self-contradictory, because it is not a " notion, either simple or positive, but only a fasciculus of " negations negations of the Conditioned in its opposite " extremes, and bound together merely by the aid of " language, and their common character of incompre- '- hensibility." Let us note, then, as the first and most fundamental of Sir W. Hamilton's arguments, that our ideas of the Infinite and the Absolute are purely negative, and the * Discussions, p. 17. 54 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. Unconditioned which combines the two, " a fasciculus of negations." I reserve consideration of the validity of this and every other part of the argumentation,, until we have the whole before us. He proceeds :* " As the conditionally limited (which we may briefly " call the Conditioned) is thus the only possible object of " knowledge and of positive thought, thought neces- " saril.y supposes condition. To think is to condition ; and " conditional limitation is the fundamental law of the " possibility of thought. For, as the greyhound cannot " outstrip his shadow, nor (by a more appropriate simile) " the eagle outsoar the atmosphere in which he floats, " and by which alone he is supported ; so the mind " cannot transcend that sphere of limitation, within and " through which exclusively the possibility of thought " is realized. Thought is only of the conditioned ; be- " cause, as we have said, to think is simply to condition; " The Absolute is conceived merely by a negation of con- t: ceivability ; and all that we know, is known as " Won from the cold and formless Infinite." " How, indeed, it could ever be doubted that thought " is only of the conditioned, may well be deemed a " matter of the profoundest admiration. Thought cannot " transcend consciousness ; consciousness is only possible " under the antithesis of a subject and object of thought " known only in correlation, and mutually limiting each " other ; while, independently of this, all that we know " either of subject or object, either of mind or matter, " is only a knowledge in each of the particular, of the " plural, of the different, of the modified, of the phaeno- " menal. We admit that the consequence of this doc- " trine is that philosophy, if viewed as more than a " science of the conditioned, is impossible. Departing " from the particular, we admit that we can never, in " our highest generalizations, rise above the Finite ; that " our knowledge, whether of mind or matter, can be O * ' " nothing more than a knowledge of the relative maiu- * Discussions, p. 13. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. 55 " festatinns of an existence which in itself it is our " highest wisdom to recognise as beyond the reach of " philosophy. This is what, in the language of St. " Austin, Cognoscendo ignoratur, et ignoratione cognoscitur" The dictum that " to think is to condition" (the meaning of which will be examined hereafter) may be noted as our author's second argument. And here ends the positive part of his argumentation. There remains his refutation of opponents. After an examination of Schelling's opinion, into which 1 need not follow him, he grapples with M. Cousin, against whom he undertakes to show,* that " his argument to prove the correality of his " three Ideas proves directly the reverse ;" " that the " conditions under which alone he allows intelligence to " be possible, necessarily exclude the possibility of a " knowledge, not to say a conception, of the Absolute ;" and "that the Absolute, as defined by him, is only a re- " lative and a conditioned." Of this argument in three parts, if we pass over (or, as our author would say, dis- count) as much as is only ad hominem, what is of general application is as follows : First: M. Cousin and our author are agreed that there can be no knowledge except " where there exists a plurality of terms ;" there are at least a perceived and a perceiver, a knower and a known. But this necessity of " difference and plurality" as a condition of know- ledge, is inconsistent with the meaning of the Absolute, which " as absolutely universal, is absolutely one. Ab- " solute unity is convertible with the absolute negation " of plurality and difference The condition " of the Absolute as existing, and under which it must, " be known, and the condition of intelligence, as capable " of knowing, are incompatible. For, if we suppose the " Absolute cognizable : it must be identified either 1, " with the subject knowing : or, 2, with the object " known ; or, 5, with the indifference of both. The " first hypothesis, and the second, are contradictory of " the Absolute. For in these the Absolute is supposed * Discussions, p. 25. 00 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON' AGAINST COUSIN. " to be known, either as contradistinguished from the " knowing subject, or as contradistinguished from the " object known : in other words, the Absolute is asserted "to be known as absolute unity, i.e., as the negation of " all plurality, while the very act by which it is known, " affirms plurality as the condition of its own possibility. " The third hypothesis, on the other hand, is contradic- " tory of the plurality of intelligence ; for if the subject " and the object of consciousness be known as one, a " plurality of terms is not the necessary condition of " intelligence. The alternative is therefore necessary : " either the Absolute cannot be known or conceived at "all; or. our author is wrong in subjecting thought to " the conditions of plurality and difference."* Secondly : In order to make the Absolute knowable by us, M. Cousin, says the author, is obliged to present it in the light of an absolute cause : now causation is a relation ; therefore M. Cousin's Absolute is but a relative. Moreover, " what exists merely as a cause, exists merely " for the sake of something else is not final in itself, " but simply a mean towards an end. . . . Abstractly " considered, the effect is therefore superior to the cause." Hence an absolute cause " is dependent on the effect for " its perfection ;" and, indeed, " even for its reality. For " to what extent a thing exists necessarily as a cause, to " that extent it is not all-sufficient to itself; since to that " extent it is dependent on the effect, as on the condition " through which it realizes its existence ; and what " exists absolutely as a cause, exists therefore in abso- " lute dependence on the effect for the reality of its " existence. An absolute cause, in truth, only exists in its " effects : it never is, it always becomes : for it is an exis- " tence in potentia, and not an existence in actu, except ' : through and by its effects. The Absolute is thus, at " best, something merely inchoative and imperfect. "f * Discussions, pp. 32, 33. f Discussions, pp. 34, 33. In the first edition three points of our author's argument were discussed, instead of two only : but I now perceive that the remaining argument is ad hominem merely, and has reference to M. Cousin's confusion of the Absolute with the Infinite. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. 57 Let me ask, en passant, why M. Cousin is under an obligation to think that if the Absolute, or, to speak plainly, if God, is only known to us in the character of a cause, he must therefore u exist merely as a cause," and be merely "a mean towards an end?" It is surelv possible to maintain that the Deity is known to us only as he who feeds the ravens, without supposing that the Divine Intelligence exists solely in order that the ravens may be fed.* * A passage follows, which being only directed against a special doctrine of M. Cousin, (that God is determined to create by the necessity of his own nature that an absolute creative force cannot but pass into creative activity) I. should have left unmentioned, were it not worth notice as a specimen of the kind of arguments which Sir VV. Hamilton can sometimes use. On M. Cousin's hypothesis, says our author, (p. 36) " One of two " alternatives must be admitted. God, as necessarily determined to pass " from absolute essence to relative manifestation, is determined to pass " either from the better to the worse, or from the worse to the better. A " third possibility, that both states are equal, as contradictory in itself and '' as contradicted by our author, it is not necessary to consider. The first " supposition must be rejected. The necessity in this case determines " God to pass from the better to the worse, that is, operates to his partial " annihilation. The power which compels this must be external and hostile, " for nothing operates willingly to its own delerioration ; and as superior " to the pretended God, is either itself the real deity, if an intelligent and " free cause, or a negation of all deity, if a blind force or fate. The second " is equally inadmissible: that God, passing into the universe, passes from " a stateof comparative imperfection into a state of comparative perfection. " The divine nature is identical with the most perfect nature, and is also " identical with the first cause. If the first cause be not identical with " the most perfect nature, there is no God, for the two essential conditions " of his existence are not in combination. K ow, on the present supposition, " the most perfect nature is the derived ; nay, the universe, the creation, " the yivoptvov, is, in relation to its cause, the actual, the oiro>r ov. It would ' also be the divine, but that divinity supposes also the notion of cause, '' while the universe, ex hypothesi, is only an effect." This curious subtlety, that creation must be either passing from the better to the worse or from the worse to the better (which, if true, would prove that God cannot have created anything unless from all eternity) can be likened to nothing but the Eleatic argument that motion is impossible, because if a body moves it must either move where it is or where it is not ; an argument, by the way, for which Sir W. Hamilton often expresses high respect ; and of which he has here produced a very successful imita- tion. It it were worth while expending serious argument upon such a curiosity of dialectics, one might say it assumes that whatever is now worse must always have been worse, and that whatever is now better must always have been better. For, on the opposite supposition, perfect wisdom would have begun to will the new state at the precise moment when it began to be better than the old. We may add that our author's argument, though never so irrefragable, in no way avails him against M. Cousin ; for (as he has himself said, only a sentence before) on M. Cousin's theory the uni- 58 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. fn reviewing- the series of arguments adduced by Sir W. Hamilton for the incognoscibility and inconceivability of the Absolute, the first remark that occurs is, that most of them lose their application by simply substituting for the metaphysical abstraction " The Absolute," the more intelligible concrete expression "Something Absolute,' If the first phrase has any meaning, it must be capable of being expressed in terras of the other. When we are told of an " Absolute" in the abstract, or of an Abso- lute Being, even though called God, we are entitled, and if we would know what we are talking about, are bound to ask, absolute in what? Do you mean, 1'or ex- ample, absolute in goodness, or absolute in know ledge ? or do you, perchance, mean absolute in ignorance, or absolute in wickedness? for any one of these is as much an Ab- solute as any other. And when you talk of something in the abstract which is called the Absolute, does it mean one, or more than one, of these? or does it, peradventure, mean all of them ? When (descending to a. less lofty height of abstraction) we speak ot The Horse, we mean to include every object of which the name horse can be predicated. Or, to take our examples from the same region of thought to which the controversy belongs verse can never have had a beginning, and God, therefore, never was iu the dilemma supposed. [On this Mr. ivlansel remarks (p. 107), " Hamilton is not speaking of " states of things, but of states of the divine nature, as creative or not " creative : and Mr. Mill's argument, to refute Hamilton, must suppose a " time when the new nature of God begins to be better than the old." This is not a happy specimen of Mr. Mausel's powers of confutation. If God made the universe at the precise moment when it was wisest and best to do so and if the universe was made by a perfectly wise and good being, this must have been the case who besides Mr. Manse), or, accord- ing to him, Sir W. Hamilton, would assert that God, in doing so, acquired anew nature? or passed out of one state into another state ot his own nature? Did he not simply remain in the state of perfect wisdom and goodness in which he was before ? Mr. Mausel makes the odd assertion, that this argument of Sir W. Hamilton is taken from Plato. There is very little in common between it and the passage in the .Republic in which bocrates, to disprove the fabulous metamorphoses of the gods into the forms of men, animals, or inanimate things, argues that no being would voluntarily change itself from better to worse. I cannot be mistaken in the passage of Plato which Mr. Mansel has in view, for he had himself cited a part of it, with the same intention, in the notes to his Bampton Lectures ^p. 2uy.)J SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. 59 when The True or The Beautiful are spoken of, the phrase is meant to include all things whatever that are true, or all things whatever that are beautiful.* If this rule is good for other abstractions, it is good for the Absolute. The word is devoid of meaning unless in O reference to predicates of some sort. What is absolute must be absolutely something; absolutely this or ab- solutely that. The Absolute, then, ought to be a genus comprehending whatever is absolutely anything whatever possesses any predicate in finished completeness. If we are told therefore that there is some one Being who is, or which is, The Absolute not something abso- lute, but the Absolute itself, the proposition can be understood in no other sense than that the supposed Being possesses in absolute completeness all predicates ; is absolutely good, and absolutely bad; absolutely wise, and absolutely stupid ; and so forth. f The conception o.f * Mr. Mansel (pp. 108, 109) considers this sentence a curious specimen of my reading in philosophy, and informs me that " Plato expressly d;-- " tinguishes between ' the beautiful ' and ' things that are beautif 1 ' an " the One in contrast to the Many the Heal in contrast to the Apparent.'' Mr. Mansel will doubtless be glad to hear that I already possessed the very elementary knowledge of Plato which he seeks to impart to mt' ; indeed (if it were of any consequence) I have elsewhere given an accouut of this theory of Plato, and made the excuses which may justly be made for such a doctrine ia Plato's time. But to recognise it as a theory whicii it is necessary to take into consideration now, is to follow the example of the later German transcendentalists in putting philosophy back to its very incunabula. f The " Inquirer" objects, that merely negative predicates should be excluded from the account; and that many of those here mentioned are merely negative : absolute littleness being but the negation of greatness ; weakness, ot strength; folly, of wisdom; evil, of good (p. 22). But (without meddling with the very disputable position, that all bad qualities are merely deficiency of good ones) the question is, not whether the qualities which the " Inquirer" enumerates are negative, but whether they are capable of being predicated as absolute. If they are, the general or abstract Absolute logically includes them. And, surely, negations are still more susceptible of being absolute than positive qualities. The " Inquirer" will hardly deny that " absolutely none" is as correct an em- ployment of the word absolute as " absolutely all." With regard to Infinite, the same writer says, " To talk of infinite littleness infinite non- " extension or non-duration is to talk of infinite nothing. Which is " indeed to talk, we must not say infinite, but absolute nonsense." It is hardly fair to refer a pupil of Sir W. Hamilton to mathematics ; but the "Inquirer" might have learnt from Sir W. Hamilton himself that it is not nonsense to talk of infinitely small quantities. 60 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. such a being, I will not say of such a God, is worse than a " fasciculus of negations ;" it is a fasciculus of con- tradictions : and our author might have spared himself the trouble of proving a thing to be unknowable, which cannot be spoken of but in words implying the impos- sibility of its existence. To insist on such a truism is not superfluous, for there have been philosophers who saw that this must be the meaning of " The Absolute," and yet accepted it as a reality. " What kind of an " Absolute Being is that," asked Hegel,* " which does " not contain in itself all that is actual, even evil "included?" Undoubtedly: and it is therefore neces- sary to admit, either that there is no Absolute Being, or that the law, that contradictory propositions cannot both be true, does not apply to the Absolute. Hegel chose the latter side of the alternative ; and by this, among other things, has fairly earned the honour which will probably be awarded to him by posterity, of having logi- cally extinguished transcendental metaphysics by a series of reductiones ad absardissimum. What I have said of the Absolute is true, mutatis mutandis, of the Infinite. This also is a phrase of no meaning, except in reference to some particular predi- cate; it must mean the infinite in something as in size, in duration, or in power. These are intelligible conceptions. But an abstract Infinite, a Being not merely infinite in one or in several attributes, but which is " The Infinite" itself, must be not only infinite in greatness, but also in littleness ; its duration is not only infinitely long, but infinitely short; it is not only infinitely awful, but infinitely contemptible ; it is the same mass of contradictions as its companion the Abso- lute. There is no need to prove that neither of them is knowable, since, it the universal law of Belief is of objective validity, neither of them exists. It is these unmeaning abstractions, however, these muddles of self-contradiction, which alone our author has proved, against Cousin and others, to be unknowable. * Quoted by Mr. Mansel, " The Limits of Religious Thought," p. 30. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. 61 He has shown, without difficulty, that we cannot know The Infinite or The Absolute. He has not shown that we cannot know a concrete reality as infinite or as abso- lute. Applied to this latter thesis, his reasoning breaks down. We have seen his principal argument, the one on which he substantially relies. It is, that the Infinite and the Absolute are unknowable because inconceivable, and in- conceivable because the only notions we can have of them are purely negative. If he is right in his antecedent, the consequent follows. A conception made up of nega- tions is a conception of Nothing. It is not a conception at all. But is a conception, by the fact of its being a con- ception of something infinite, reduced to a negation ? This is quite true of the senseless abstraction " The Infinite." That indeed is purely negative, being formed by excluding from the concrete conceptions classed under it, all their positive elements. But in place of " the Infinite," put the idea of Something infinite, and the argument collapses at once. " Something infinite" is a conception which, like most of our complex ideas, con- tains a negative element, but which contains positive elements also. Infinite space, for instance : is there no- thing positive in that? The negative part of this con- ception is the absence of bounds. The positive are, the idea of space, and of space greater than any finite space. So of infinite duration : so far as it signifies " without end" it is only known or conceived negatively ; but in so far as it means time, and time longer than any given time, the conception is positive. The existence of a negative element in a conception does not make the con- ception itself negative and a non-entity. It would sur- prise most people to be told that " the life eternal" is a purely negative conception ; that immortality is incon- ceivable. Those who hope for it for themselves have & very positive conception of what they hope for. True we cannot have an adequate conception of space or dura- tion as infinite ; but between a conception which though SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. inadequate is real, and correct as far as it goes, and the impossibility of any conception, there is a wide difference. Sir W. Hamilton does not admit this difference. He thinks the distinction without meaning. " To say* that " the infinite can be thought, but only inadequately " thought, is a contradiction in adjecto ; it is the same as " saying that the infinite can be known, but only known " as finite." I answer, that to know it as greater than anything finite is not to know it as finite. The conception of Infinite as that which is greater than any given quan- tity, is a conception we all possess, sufficient for all human purposes, and as genuine and good a positive conception as one need wish to have. It is not adequate ; our con- ception of a reality never is. But it is positive ; and the assertion that there is nothing positive in the idea of infinity can only be maintained by leaving out and ignoring, as Sir W. Hamilton invariably does, the very element which constitutes the idea. Considering how many recondite laws of physical nature, afterwards veri- fied by experience, have been arrived at by trains of mathematical reasoning grounded on what, if Sir W. Hamilton's doctrine be correct, is a non-existent con- ception, one would be obliged to suppose that conjuring is a highly successful mode of the investigation of nature. If, indeed, we trifle by setting up an imaginary Infinite which is infinite in nothing in particular, our notion of it is truly nothing, and a " fasciculus of negations." But this is a good example of the bewildering effect of putting nonsensical abstractions in the place of concrete realities. Would Sir W. Hamilton have said that the idea of God is but a negation, or a fasciculus of negations ? As having nothing greater than himself, he is indeed conceived negatively. But as himself greater than all other real or imaginable existences, the conception of him is positive. Put Absolute instead of Infinite, and we come to the same result. " The Absolute," as already shown, is a heap of contradictions, but " absolute" in reference to * Lectures, ii. 375. Wux 4 &( " menon, relative cause, the finite, determined thought, &c ," Sir W. Hamilton says, " we would style the Conditioned." This, 1 think, is as near as he ever comes to an explanation of what he means by these words. It is obviously no explanation at all. It tells us what (in logical language) 70 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. The probability is that when our author asserts that " to think is to condition," he uses the word Condition in neither of these senses, but in a third meaning, equally i'amiliar to him, and recurring constantly in such phrases as " the conditions of our thinking faculty," " conditions of thought," and the like. He means by Conditions something similar to Kant's Forms of Sense and Categories of Understanding ; a meaning more correctly expressed by another* of his phrases, " Necessary Laws of Thought." He is applying to the mind the scholastic maxim, " Quicquid recipitur, re- cipitur ad modum recipientis." He means that our perceptive and conceptive faculties have their own laws, which not only determine what we are capable of per- ceiving and conceiving, but put into our perceptions and conceptions elements not derived from the thing per- ceived or conceived, but from the mind itself: That, therefore, we cannot at once infer that whatever we find in our perception or conception of an object, has necessarily a prototype in the object itself: and that we must, in each instance, determine this question by philosophic investi- gation. According to this doctrine, which no fault can be found with our author for maintaining, though often \ for not carrying it far enough the "conditions of thought" would mean the attributes with which, it is supposed, the mind cannot help investing every object of thought the elements which, derived from its own structure, cannot but enter into every conception it is able to form ; even if there should be nothing cor- responding in the object which is the prototype of the conception : though our author, in most cases, (therein differing from Kant) believes that there is this cor- respondence. We have here an intelligible meaning for the doctrine the terms denote, but not what they connote. An enumeration of the things called by a name is not a definition. If the name, for instance, were " dog," it would be no definition to say that what are variously denominated spaniels, mastiffs, and so forth, " we would style " dogs. The thing wanted is to know what attributes common to all these the word signifies, what is affirmed of a thing by calling it a dog. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. 71 that to think is to condition ; and as Mr. Mansel, in his reply, guarantees this as the true meaning of Sir W. Hamilton, I will accept it as being so. If, then (which I do not here discuss), the philosophical doctrine be true, which was held partially by Sir W. Hamilton, and in a more thorough-going manner by Kant, viz. that, in the act of thought, the mind, by an a priori necessity, invests the object of thought with attributes which are not in itself, but are created by the mind's own laws ; and if we consent to call these necessities of thought the conditions of thought ; then evidently to think is to condition, and to think the Unconditioned would be to think the unthinkable. But the Unconditioned, in this application of the term, is not identical with the Infinite 1 plus the Absolute. The Infinite and the Absolute are Jj not necessarily, in this sense, unconditioned. The ' words infinite and absolute, as \[ have already said, have j no meaning save as expressing some concrete reality or supposed reality, possessing infinitely or absolutely attributes of some sort, which attributes, as finite and limited, we are able to think. In thinking these attri- butes, we are not able to divest ourselves of our mental conditions, but we can think the attributes as surpassing \ the conditions. " To condition," and " to think under conditions," are ambiguous phrases. An Infinite Being may be thought, and is thought, with reference to the conditions, but not as limited by them. The most familiar examples of the alleged necessary conditions of thought, are Time and Space : we cannot, it is affirmed, think anything, except in time and space. Now, an Infinite Being is not thought as in time and space, if this means as occupying a portion of time or a portion of space. But (substituting for Time the word Duration, to get rid of the theological antithesis of Time and Eternity) we do actually conceive Grod in, reference to Duration and Extension, namely, as occupy- ing the whole of both ; and these being conceived as infinite, to conceive a Being as occupying the whole of them is to conceive that Being as infinite. If thinking 72 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. God as eternal and omnipresent is thinking him in Space and Time, we do think God in Space and Time : if thinking him as eternal and omnipresent is not thinking him in Space and Time, we are capable of thinking something out of Space and Time. Mr. Mansel may make his choice between the two opinions. I have already shown that the ideas of infinite space and time are real and positive conceptions : that of a Being who is in all Space and in all Time is no less so. To think anything, must of course be to condition it by attributes which are themselves thinkable ; but not necessarily to condition it by a limited quantum of those attributes : on the contrary, we may think it under a degree of them greater than all limited degrees, and this is to think it as infinite.* If we now ask ourselves, as the result of this long discussion, what Sir W. Hamilton can be considered as having accomplished in this celebrated Essay, our answer must be : That he has established, more thoroughly perhaps than he intended, the futility of all speculation respecting those meaningless abstractions " The Infi- nite" and " The Absolute," notions contradictory in themselves, and to which no corresponding realities do or can exist, f Respecting the unknowableness, not of * " To be conceived as unconditioned," says Mr. Mansel (pp. 17, 18), " God must be conceived as exempt from action in time : to be conceived " as a person, if his personality resembles ours, he must be conceived as " acting in time." Exempt from action in time, as much as you please ; in other words, not necessitated to it, nor restricted by its conditions ; but did any one ever conceive the Deity as not acting in time ? Nay, even if he is not conceived as a person, but only as the first principle of the uni- verse, " one absolutely first principle on which everything else depends," a belief which is held by Mr. Mansel along with the Christian doctrine of the Divine Personality (pp. 7 to 18) ; even so, the first principle of every- thing which takes place in Time, must, from the very meaning of the words, not only be conceived as acting in Time, but must really act in Time, and in all Time. Action in Time does not belong to the Deity as a Person, but quite as much to the Deity as the first principle of all things, which is what Mr. Mansel means by the Unconditioned. f On this Mr. Mansel's remark is (pp. 110, 111) that Sir W. Hamilton did not assert these to be unmeaning abstractions. I never pretended that he did ; the gist of my complaint against him is, that he did not per- ceive them to be unmeaning. " Hamilton," says Mr. Mansel, "maintains " that the terms absolute and infinite are perfectly intelligible as abstrac- SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON AGAINST COUSIN. . 73 " the Infinite," or "the Absolute," but of concrete persons or things possessing infinitely or absolutely certain specific attributes, I cannot think that our author has proved anything ; nor do I think it possible to prove them any otherwise unknowable, than that they can only be known in their relations to us, and not as Noumena, or Things in themselves. This, however, is true of the finite as well as of the infinite, of the imperfect as well as of the completed or absolute. Our author has merely proved the uncognoscibility of a being which is nothing but in- finite. or nothing but absolute : and since nobody supposes that there is such a being, but only beings which are something positive carried to the infinite, or to the abso- lute, to have established this point cannot be regarded as any great achievement. He has not even refuted M. Cousin ; whose doctrine of an intuitive cognition of the Deity, like every other doctrine relating to intuition, can only be disproved by showing it to be a mistaken inter- pretation of facts; which, again, as we shall see here- after, can only be done by pointing out in what other way the seeming perceptions may have originated, which are erroneously supposed to be ^intuitive. " tions, as much so as relative and finite." Quis dubitavit ? It is not the terms absolute and infinite that are unmeaning; it is "The Infinite" and " The Absolute." Infinite and Absolute are real attributes, abstracted from concrete objects of thought, if not of experience, which are at least believed to possess those attributes. "The Infinite" and "The Absolute" are illegitimate abstractions of what never were, nor could without self- contradiction be supposed to be, attributes of any concrete. 1 regret to difiev, on this point, from my distinguished reviewer in the Westminster Review, who considers these to be intelligible abstractions, though of a higher reach of abstraction than the preceding (p. 14). The distinction is seized by one of my American critics, Dr. H. B. Smith (p. 134), who re- gards it as the difference between talking " about the Infinite and Abso- lute as entities," and considering them " simply as modes or predicates of real existences." That there are persons " in Laputa or the Empire" (as Sir W. Hamilton phrases it) who do talk about them as entities, up to any pitch of wild nonsense, I am quite aware ; and against these Sir W. Hamilton's Essay, as the protest, though the insufficient protest, of a rival Transcendentalist, has its value. vL 74 CHAPTER V. WHAT IS REJECTED AS KNOWLEDGE BY SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON, BROUGHT BACK UNDER THE \AME OF BELIEF. WE have found Sir W. Hamilton maintaining with great earnestness, and taking as the basis of his philosophy; an opinion respecting the limitation of human know- ledge, which, if he did not mean so much by it as the language in which he often clothed it seemed to imply, meant at least this, that the Absolute, the Infinite, the Unconditioned, are necessarily unknowable by us. I have discussed this opinion as a serious philosophical dogma, expressing a definite view of the relation between the universe and human apprehension, and fitted to guide us in distinguishing the questions which it is of any avail to ask, from those which are altogether closed to our investigations. But had the doctrine, in the mind of Sir VV. Hamilton, neant ten times more than it did had he upheld the relativity of human knowledge in the fullest, instead of the scantiest meaning of which the words are susceptible the question would still have been reduced to naught, or to a mere verbal controversy, by his admission of a second kind of intellectual conviction called Belief; which is anterior to knowledge, is the foundation of it, and is not subject to its limitations ; and through the medium of which we may have, and are justified in having, a full assurance of all the things which he has pronounced unknowable to us ; and this not exclusively by revelation, that is, on the supposed testimony of a Being whom we have ground for trusting as veracious, but by our natural faculties. BKLIEF WITHOUT KNOWLEDGE. 75 From some philosophers, this distinction would have the appearance of a mere fetch one of those transparent evasions which have sometimes been resorted to by the assailants of received opinions, that they might have an opportunity of ruining the rational foundations of a doctrine without exposing themselves to odium by its direct denial : as the writers against Christianity in the eighteenth century, after declaring some doctrine to be contradictory to reason, and exhibiting it in the absurdest possible light, were wont to add that this was not of the smallest consequence, religion being an affair of faith, not of reason. But Sir W. Hamilton evidently meant what he says ; he was expressing a serious conviction, and one of the tenets of his philosophy : he really recog- nised under the name of Belief a substantive source, I was going to say, of knowledge ; I may at all events say of trustworthy evidence. This appears in the following passages : " The* sphere of our belief is much more extensive " than the sphere of our knowledge, and therefore, when " I deny that the Infinite can by us be known, I am far " from denying that by us it is, must, and ought to be, " believed. This I have indeed anxiously evinced, both " by reasoning and authority." " St. Austinf accurately says, 'We know, what rests " upon reason ; but believe, what rests upon authority.* " But reason itself must rest at last upon authority; for " the original data of reason do not rest on reason, but " are necessarily accepted by reason on the authority of " what is beyond itself. These data are, therefore, in " rigid propriety, Beliefs or Trusts. Thus it is that in " the last resort we must perforce philosophically admit, " that belief is the primary condition of reason, and not " reason the ultimate ground of belief. We are com- " pelled to surrender the proud Intellige ut credas of Abe- " lard, to content ourselves with the humble Crede ut " intelligas of Anselm." * Letter to Mr. Calderwood, in Appendix to Lectures, ii. 530, 531. t Dissertations on Reid, p. 760, 76 BELIEF WITHOUT KNOWLEDGE. Arid in another part of the same Dissertation,* (he is arguing that we do not believe, but know, the external world) " If asked, indeed, how we know that we know " it ? how we know that what we apprehend in sensible " perception is, as consciousness assures us, an object, " external, extended, and numerically different from the " conscious subject ? how we know that this object is not " a mere mode of mind, illusively presented to us as a " mere mode of matter ; then indeed we must reply that " we do not in propriety know that what we are com- " pelled to perceive as not-self is not a perception of self, " and that we can only on reflection bdieve such to be " the case, in reliance on the original necessity of so " believing-, imposed on us by our nature." It thus appears that, in Sir W. Hamilton's opinion, Belief is a conviction of higher authority than Know- ledge ; Belief is ultimate, knowledge only derivative ; Knowledge itself finally rests on Belief; natural beliefs are the sole warrant for all our knowledge. Knowledge, therefore, is an inferior ground of assurance to natural Belief; and as we have beliefs which tell us that we know, and without which we could not be assured of the truth of our knowledge, so we have, and are warranted in having, beliefs beyond our knowledge ; beliefs re- specting the Unconditioned respecting that which is in itself unknowable. I am not now considering what it is that, in our author's opinion, we are bound to believe concerning the unknowable. What here concerns us is, the nullity to which this doctrine reduces the position to which our author seemed to cling so firmly viz., that our know- ledge is relative to ourselves, and that we can have no knowledge of the infinite and absolute. In telling us that it is impossible to the human faculties to know any- thing about Things in themselves, we naturally suppose he intends to warn us off the ground to bid us under- stand that this subject of enquiry is closed to us, and * Pp. 749, 750. BELIEF WITHOUT KNOWLEDGE. 77 exhort us to turn our attention elsewhere. It appears that nothing of the kind was intended : we are to un- derstand, on the contrary, that we may have the best grounded and most complete assurance of the things which were declared unknowable an assurance not only equal or greater in degree, but the same in nature, as we have for the truth of our knowledge : and that the matter in dispute was only whether this assurance or conviction shall be called knowledge, or by another name. If this be all, I must say I think it not of the smallest consequence. If no more than this be intended by the " great axiom " and the elaborate argument against Cousin, a great deal of trouble has been taken to very little purpose ; and the subject would have been better left where Reid left it, who did not trouble himself with nice distinctions between belief and knowledge, but was content to consider us as knowing that which, by the constitution of our nature, we are forced, with entire conviction, to believe. According to Sir W. Hamilton, we believe premises, but know the conclusions from them. The ultimate facts of consciousness* are " given less in " the form of cognitions than of beliefs :" " Conscious- " ness in its last analysis, in other words our primary " experience, is a faith." But if we know the theorems of Euclid, and do not know the definitions and axioms on which they rest, the word knowledge, thus singularly applied, must be taken in a merely technical sense. To say that we believe the premises, but know the conclu- sion, would be understood by every one as meaning that we had other independent evidence of the conclusion. If we only know it through the premises, the same name V^A ought in reason to be given to our assurance of both.f^ -. lu common language, when Belief and Knowledge are distinguished, Knowledge is understood to mean complete * Discussions, p. 86. f Accordingly Sir W. Hamilton himself, in one of the Dissertations on Keid (p. 76'3), says that " the principles of our knowledge must be them- < " selves' knowledge " And there are few who will not approve this use of language, and condemn the other. 73 BELIEF WITHOUT KNOWLEDGE. conviction, Belief a conviction somewhat short of com- plete ; or else we are said to believe when the evidence is probable (as that of testimony), but to know, when it is intuitive, or demonstrative from intuitive premises : we believe, for example, that there is a Continent of America, but know that we are alive, that two and two 1 make four, and that the sum of any two sides of a triangle is greater than the third side. This is a distinction of practical value : but in Sir W. Hamilton's use of the term, it is the intuitive convictions that are the Beliefs, and those which are dependent and contingent upon them, compose our knowledge. Whether a particular portion of our convictions, which are not more certain, but if anything less certain, than the remainder, and according to our author rest on the same ultimate basis, shall in opposition to the common usage of mankind, receive exclusively the appellation of knowledge, is at ^f l the most a question of terminology, and can only be made to appear philosophically important by confound- ing difference of name with difference of fact. That anything capable of being said on such a subject should *&* pass for a fundamental principle of philosophy, and be \\ vA>ne of the chief sources of the reputation of a meta- ^A C physical system, is but an example how the mere forms of logic and metaphysics can blind mankind to the total absence of their substance. It must not be supposed, from anything which has been here said, that I wish to abolish the distinction between Knowledge and Belief (meaning True Belief) or maintain that it is necessarily a distinction without a difference. Those terms are employed to denote more than one real difference, and neither of them can conve- niently be dispensed with in philosophy.* What con- * There is much dispute among philosophers as to the difference between Knowledge and Belief; and the strife is not likely to terminate, until they perceive that the real question is, not what the distinction is, but what it shall be ; what one among several differences already known and recognised, the words shall be employed to denote. "The word belief," says Dr. M'Cosh (p. 36), in this more discerning than the generality, "is " unfortunately a very vague one, and may stand for a number of very BELIEF WITHOUT KNOWLEDGE. 79 cerns us in the present chapter is not the rationale of the distinction between knowledge and belief, but whether that distinction is relevant to the question between Sir "W. Hamilton and M. Cousin about the Infinite and the Absolute ; and whether Sir W. Hamilton is warranted in giving back under the name of Belief, the assurance or conviction respecting these objects which he refuses under the name of knowledge. My position is, that the Infinite and Absolute which Sir W. Hamilton has " different mental affections. When I am speaking of first or intuitive " principles, 1 use the term to signify our conviction of the existence of ' an object not now present, and thus I distinguish primitive faith from " primitive knowledge, in which the object is present." This distinction agrees well with usage in the cases to which Dr. M'Cosh applies it : we know that which we perceive by the senses, and believe that which we only re- member : we know that we ourselves, and (while we look at them) our house and garden, exist, and believe the existence of the Czar of Eussia and the Island of Ceylou. Every definition of Belief, as distinguished from Knowledge, must include these cases, because in them the conviction which receives the name of Belief falls short of the complete assurance implied in the word knowledge : our memory may deceive us ; the Czar or the island may have beeu swallowed up by an earthquake. But if we attempt to carry out Dr. M'Cosh's distinction through the entire region of thought, the whole of what we call our scientific knowledge, except the primary facts or intuitions on which it is grounded, has to pass into the category of Belief ; for the objects with which it is conversant are seldom present. Mr. Mansel might be supposed to be adopting Dr. M'Cosh's distinction, when he says (p. 126), "We believe that the true distinction between " knowledge and belief may ultimately be referred to the presence or " absence of the corresponding intuition." But his criterion of the dis- tinction, and, according to him, bir W. Hamilton's also, is the following : we believe that a thing is, but do not know even that it is, unless we can conceive how, or in what manner, it is. " When I say that I believe in ' the existence of a spiritual being who can see without eyes, I cannot ' conceive the manner in which seeing co-exists with the absence of the ' bodily organ of sight" (p. 126). " We cannot conceive the manner in which the unconditioned and the personal are united in the Divine ' Nature ; yet we may believe that, in some manner unknown to us, they ' are so united. To conceive the union of two attributes in one object of ' thought, I must be able to conceive them as united in some particular ' manner : when this cannot be done, I may nevertheless believe thai the ' union is possible, though I am unable to conceive how it is possible." This may be more briefly expressed by saying that we can believe what is inconceivable, but can know only what is conceivable ; and undoubtedly Coin these contrasted propositions are maintained by Sir W. Hamilton. But to regard them as a clue to the distinction in his mind between knowledge and belief, would be to misunderstand his opinions : for the convictions which he most emphatically characterized as beliefs, in contra- distinction to knowledge, are what he calls our natural and necessary 80 BELIEF WITHOUT KNOWLEDGE. been proving to be unknowable, being made up of con- tradictions, are as incapable of being believed as of being known ; that the only attitude in reference to them, of any intellect which apprehends the meaning of language, is that of disbelief. On the other hand, there are In- finites and Absolutes which, not being self-contradictory, admit of being believed, namely, concrete realities sup- posed to be infinite or absolute in respect of certain attributes : but Sir W. Hamilton, as I maintain, has done nothing towards proving that such concrete reali- ties cannot be known, in the way in which we know other things, namely, in their relations to us. When, therefore, he affirms that though the Infinite cannot by us be known, " by us it is, must, and ought to be be- " lieved," I answer, that the Infinite which, as he has so laboriously proved, cannot be known, neither is, must, nor ought to be believed ; not because it cannot be known, but because there exists no such thing for us to beliefs, "the original data of reason," which, far from being inconceivable, are usually tested by being themselves conceivable while their negations are not. If knowledge were distinguished from belief by our being aware of the manner as well as the fact, we could not believe and know the same fact ; our knowledge could not rest, as he says it does, on a belief that it is itself true. But indeed, this notion of Sir W. Hamilton that we have two convic- tions on the same poiut, one guaranteeing the other our knowledge of a truth, and a belief in the truth of that knowledge seems to me apiece of ' false philosophy, resembling the doctrine he elsewhere rejects, that we have both a feeling and a consciousness of the feeling. We do not know a truth and believe it besides; the belief is the knowledge. Belief, altogether, is a genus which includes knowledge : according to the usage of language we believe whatever we assent to ; but some of our beliefs are knowledge, others are only belief. The first requisite which, by universal admission, a belief must possess, to constitute it knowledge, is that it be true. The second is, that it be well grounded ; for what we believe by accident, or on evidence not sufficient, we are not said to know. The grounds must, moreover, be sufficient for the very highest degree of assu- rance; for we do not consider ourselves to know, as long as we think there is any possibility (I mean any appreciable possibility) of our being mis- taken. But when a belief is true, is held with the strongest conviction we ever have, and held on grounds sufficient to justify that strongest con- viction, most people would think it worthy of the name of knowledge, whether it be grounded on our personal investigations, or on the appro- priate testimony, and whether we know only the fact itself, or the manner of the fact. And I am inclined to think that the purposes of philosophy, as well as those of common life, are best answered by making this the line of demarcation. BELIE! 1 WITHOUT KNOWLEDGE. 81 know ; unless, with Hegel, we hold that the Absolute is not subject to the Law of Contradiction, but is at once a real existence and the synthesis of contradictories. And, on the other hand, the Infinite and Absolute which are really capable of being believed, are also, for anything Sir W. Hamilton has shown to the contrary, capable of being, in certain of their aspects, known. m ex q 1 > v \, j| T^W/ , J * CUX. io OAX (3^. U*JU*l trtKW QtU^X A &^ CStovitX' LiCx fc******* Ha ( {lC (. %*v - v of the lower " Greeks." May it not be surmised that the vagueness in which the master here leaves the conception, was for the purpose of avoiding difficulties upon which the pupil, in his desire of greater precision, has unwarily run ? Mr. Mansel certainly gains nothing by the more definite character of his language. The words, " having no necessary relation to any other Bein^," admit of two constructions. The words, in their natural sense, only mean, capable of existing out of relation to anything else. The argument requires that they should mean, incapable of existing in relation with anything else. Mr. Mansel cannot intend the latter. He cannot mean that the Absolute is incapable of entering into relation with any other being ; for he would not affirm this of God ; on the contrary, he is continually speaking of God's rela- tions to the world and to us. Moreover, he accepts, from Dr. Calderwood, an interpretation inconsistent with this.f This, however, is the meaning necessary to support his case. For what is his first argument ? * Discussions, p. 14, note. f Limits of Religious Thought, p. 200. AS APPLIED BY MR. MANSEL TO RELIGION. 115 That God cannot be known by us as Cause, as Abso- lute, and as Infinite, because these attributes are, to our conception, incompatible with one another. And why incompatible ? Because* " a Cause cannot, as such, be " absolute ; the Absolute cannot, as such, be a cause. " The cause, as such, exists only in relation to its effect : "the cause is a cause of the effect ; the effect is an effect " of the cause. On the other hand, the conception of " the Absolute involves a possible existence out of all " relation." But in what manner is a possible existence out of all relation, incompatible with the notion of a cause? Have not causes a possible existence apart from their effects ? Would the sun (for example) not exist if there were no earth or planets for it to illuminate ? Mr. Mansel seems to think that what is capable of existing out of relation, cannot possibly be conceived or known in rela- tion. But this is not so. Anything which is capable of existing in relation, is capable of being conceived or known in relation. If the Absolute Being cannot be conceived as Cause, it must be that he cannot exist as Cause ; he must be incapable of causing. If he can be in any relation whatever to any finite thing, he is con- ceivable and knowable in that relation, if no otherwise. Freed from this confusion of ideas, Mr. Mansel's argu- ment resolves itself into this the same Being cannot be thought by us both as Cause and as Absolute, because a Cause as such is not Absolute, and Absolute as such is not a Cause ; which is exactly as if he had said that Newton cannot be thought by us both as an Englishman and as a mathematician, because an English- man, as such, is not a mathematician, nor a mathema- tician, as such, an Englishman.! * Limits of Eeligious Thought, p. 31. t Mr. Mausel, in his reply (p. 151) accuses me of mutilating hia argu- ment. I therefore add the remainder of it. " We attempt to escape from " this apparent contradiction by introducing the idea of succession in " time. The Absolute exists first by itself, and afterwards becomes a " Cause. But here we are checked by the third conception, that of the " Infinite. How can the Infinite beco'me that which it was not from the " first ? If Causation is a possible mode of existence, that which exists i 2 116 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED Again, Mr. Mansel argues,* that, " supposing the Ab- solute to become a cause," since ex m termini it is not necessitated to do so, it must be a voluntary agent, and therefore conscious ; for " volition is only possible in a conscious being." But consciousness, again, is only conceivable as a relation; and any relation conflicts with the notion of the Absolute, since relatives are mutually dependent on one another. Here it comes out distinctly as a premise in the reasoning, that to be in a relation at all, even if only a relation to itself, the relation of being " conscious of itself," is inconsistent with being the Absolute.! Mr. Mansel, therefore, must alter his definition of the Absolute if he would maintain his argument. He must " without causing is not infinite ; that which becomes a cause has passed " beyond its former limits." (Limits of Eeligious Thought, pp. 31, 32.) This alleged inconsistency of thought in supposing the Infinite to become a cause, because to do so would be to become something which it was not from the first, applies, like nearly all the rest of Mr. Mansel's argumentation, only to the self-contradictory fiction, " The Infinite," which is supposed either infinite without reference to any attributes, or infinite in all possible attributes. Substitute for this the notion of a Being infinite in given attributes, and the incompatibility disappears. Surely the most familiar form of the notion of an infinite being, is that of a Being infinite in power. Power is not only compatible with, but actually means, capability of causing. Can we be told that a Being infinite in its capability of causing, cannot to our conceptions, consis- tently with its infinity, actually cause anything, but the power, because infinite, must remain dormant through eternity ? or, as the opposite alternative, that this Being must be conceived as having exercised from all eternity the whole of its infinite power of causing, because any later exercise of that power would be passing into causation ? Either hypo- thesis Mr. Mansel affirms (Limits of Religious Thought, p. 204) to be 'inconceivable of an Infinite Being. But if an Infinite Being means a Being of infinite wisdom and goodness as well as power, the conception of that infinite power as only partly exercised is so far from being a contra- diction, that it is not even a paradox. * Limits of Religious Thought, p. 32. f- How does Mr. Mansel reconcile this argument with the definition of the Absolute which he himself accepts from Dr. Calderwood (Limits of Religious Thought, p. 200) ? " The Absolute is that which is free from " all necessary relation, that is, which is free from every relation as a conV, " dition of existence ; but it may exist in relation, provided that rela-i :' " tion be not a necessary condition of its existence, that is, provided the) "relation maybe removed without affecting its existence." A better]/ definition of an Absolute Being could scarcely be devised ; and that Mr.^ Mansel should borrow it, and then deny the latter half of it, proves him to be greatly inferior to Dr. Calderwood in the important accomplishment of understanding his own meaning. For before it can be maintained that AS APPLIED BY MR. M ANSEL TO EELIGION. 117 either fall back on the happy ambiguity of Sir W. Hamilton's definition, " what is aloof from relation," which does not decide whether the meaning is merely that it can exist out of relation, or that it is incapable of existing in it ; or he must take courage, and affirm that an Absolute Being is incapable of all relation. But as he will certainly refuse to predicate this of God, the consequence follows, that God is not an Absolute Being. The whole of Mr. Hansel's arguments for the incon- ceivability of the Infinite and of the Absolute is one long ignoratio elenchi. It has been pointed out in a former chapter that the words Absolute and Infinite have no real meaning, unless we understand by them that which is absolute or infinite in some given attri- bute ; as space is called infinite, meaning that it is infi- nite in extension ; and as God is termed infinite in the sense of possessing infinite power, and absolute in the sense of absolute goodness, or knowledge. It has also been shown that Sir W. Hamilton's arguments for the unknowableness of the Unconditioned, do not prove that we cannot know an object which is absolute or infinite in some specific attribute, but only that we cannot know an abstraction called "The Absolute" or "The Infinite," which is supposed to have all attributes at once. The same remark is applicable to Mr. Mansel,* with only this to be a conscious being contradicts the notion of the Absolnte, because consciousness is a relation, the power just admitted in the Absolute of existing in relation provided it is not bound to any relation, must be either denied or forgotten. [Mr. Mansel, in his rejoinder, says that he did not mean to admit the second half of Dr. Calderwood's definition ; and he holds to the doctrine " The absolute, as such, must be out of all relation " (not merely capable of existing out of relation) " and consequently cannot be conceived in the relation of plurality." (Philosophy of the Conditioned, p. 117).] * Mr. Mansel (pp. 153, 154) protests against this passage, as attribu- ting to him the use of the word " Absolute" in the sense attached to it by Sir W. Hamilton, which includes perfection, though he had expressly stated that he used the term in a different sense. " When Mr. Mill ' charges Mr. Mansel with undertaking to prove the impossibility of con- ' ceiving a Being absolutely just or absolutely wise (i.e. as he supposes, ' perfectly just or wise) he actually forgets that he has just been criti- ' cisiug Mr. Mansei's definition of the Absolute, as something having a 1 ' possible existence out of relation." And he asks what I can mean by 118 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED difference, that he, with the laudable ambition I have already noticed of stating everything explicitly, draws this important distinction himself, and says, of his own motion, that the Absolute he means is the abstrac- tion. He says,* that the Absolute and Infinite can be " nothing less than the sum of all reality," the complex of all positive predicates, even those which are exclusive of one another ; and expressly identifies it with Hegel's Absolute Being, which contains in itself " all that is " actual, even evil included." "That which is conceived " as absolute and infinite," says Mr. Mansel, f " must be " conceived as containing within itself the sum not only " of all actual, but of all possible modes of being." One may well agree with Mr. Mansel that this farrago of goodness or knowledge " out of all relation." If I have, in this passage, exchanged Mr. Hansel's definition of the Absolute for Sir W. Hamilton's, by including in it the notion of " finished, perfected, completed," Mr. Mansel had set me the example. As long as he kept to his own definition, 1 did the same : I only followed him when he himself imported the idea of perfection from the other meaning of the term, and reasoned from it as one of the characteristics of the Absolute. Does the reader doubt this ? He shall see. We cannot, says Mr. Mansel, reconcile the idea of the Absolute with that of a Cause, because " if the condition of causal ac- tivity is a higher state than that of quiescence, the Absolute, whether acting voluntarily or involuntarily, has passed from a condition of com- parative imperfection to one of comparative perfection, and therefore was not originally perfect. If the state of activity is an inferior state to that of quiescence, the Absolute, in becoming a cause, has lost its original perfection." (Limits of Religious Thought, pp. 34, 35. The talics are my own.) Again (p. 3b) " While it is impossible to represent in thought any object except as finite, it is equally impossible to repre- sent any finite object, or any aggregate of finite objects, as exhausting the universe of being. Thus the hypothesis which would annihilate the Infinite is itself shattered to pieces against the rock of the Absolute." In spite, therefore, of his own definition, Mr. Mansel thinks it part of the notion of the Absolute that it is the Perfect, and that it exhausts the uni- verse of being, i.e., is the completed whole of existence. It thus appears that if 1 am chargeable with anything, it is with having neglected to point out one confusion of ideas the more in Mr. Mansel, and, this time, a confusion between two ideas which he had ex- pressly discriminated. But even I had really committed the blunder he imputes to me, it would not have affected the question between us : for he always (and, as I. think, rightly) assumes that the Being whose conceiva- bility by us is the subject of discussion, has to be conceived both as abso- lute and as infinite (the infinito-Absolute of Sir W. Hamilton); and if he had escaped untouched trom my criticism of Sir W. Hamilton in respect of the Absolute, he would still have been inextricably involved in it as regards the Infinite. * Limits of Religious Thought, p. 30. f Ibid. p. 31. AS APPLIED BY MR. HANSEL TO RELIGION. 119 contradictory attributes cannot be conceived : but what shall we say of his equally positive averment that it must be believed ? If this be what the Absolute is, what does he mean by saying that we must believe God to be the Absolute ? The remainder of Mr. Mansell's argumentation is suitable to this commencement. The Absolute, as con- ceived, that is, as he defines it, cannot be " a whole* com- " posed of parts," or " a substance consisting of attri- " butes," or a " conscious subject in antithesis to an " object. For if there is in the absolute any principle of " unity, distinct from the mere accumulation of parts or " attributes, this principle alone is the true absolute. If, " on the other hand, there is no such principle, then " there is no absolute at all, but only a plurality of rela- " tives. The almost unanimous voice of philosophy, in " pronouncing that the absolute is both one and simple, " must be accepted as a voice of reason also, so far as " reason has any voice in the matter. But this absolute " unity, as indifferent and containing no attributes, " can neither be distinguished from the multiplicity " of finite beings by any characteristic feature, nor be " identified with them in their multiplicity." It will be noticed that the Absolute, which was just before defined as having all attributes, is here declared to have none : but this, Mr. Mansel would say, is merely one of the contradictions inherent in the attempt to con- ceive what is inconceivable. " Thus we are landed in " an inextricable dilemma. The Absolute cannot be " conceived as conscious, neither can it be conceived as " unconscious : it cannot be conceived as complex, neither "can it be conceived as simple: it cannot be conceived " by difference, neither can it be conceived by the ab- " sence of difference : it cannot be identified with the " universe, neither can it be distinguished from it." Is this chimerical abstraction the Absolute Being whom anybody need be concerned about, either as knowable or as unknowable? Is the inconceivableness of this iinpos- * Limits of Religious Thought, p. 33. 120 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED sible fiction any argument against tLe possibility of conceiving God, who is neither supposed to have no attributes nor to have all attributes, but to have good attributes? Is it any hindrance to our being able to conceive a Being absolutely just, for example, or abso- lutely wise ? Yet it is of this that Mr. Mansel undertoqk to prove the impossibility. Again, of the Infinite : according to Mr. Mansel,* being " that than which a greater is inconceivable," it " consequently can receive no additional attribute or " mode of existence which it had not from all eternity." It must therefore be the same complex of all possible predicates which the Absolute is, and all of them infinite in degree. It " cannot be regarded as consisting of a "limited number of attributes, each unlimited in its " kind. It cannot be conceived, for example, after the "analogy of a line, infinite in length, but not in " breadth ; or of a surface, infinite in two dimensions of " space, but bounded in the third ; or of an intelligent " being, possessing some one or more modes of conscious- " ness in an infinite degree, but devoid of others." This Infinite, which is infinite in all attributes, and not solely in those which it would be thought decent to predicate of God, cannot, as Mr. Mansel very truly says, be conceived. Forf "the Infinite, if it is to be conceived " at all, must be conceived as potentially everything and " actually nothing ; for if there is anything general which " it cannot become, it is thereby limited ; and if there is " anything in particular which it actually is, it is thereby " excluded from being any other thing. But again, " it must also be conceived as actually everything and " potentially nothing ; for an unrealized potentiality is " likewise a limitation. If the infinite can be that which " it is not, it is by that very possibility marked out as " incomplete, and capable of a higher perfection. If it " is actually everything, it possesses no characteristic " feature by which it can be distinguished from anything " else, and discerned as an object ol consciousness." Here * Limits of Beligious Thought, p. 30. f Ibid. p. 48. AS APPLIED BY MR. MANSEL TO RELIGION. 121 certainly is an Infinite whose infinity does not seem to be of much use to it. But can a writer be serious who bids us conjure up a conception of something which possesses infinitely all conflicting attributes, and because we cannot do this without contradiction, would bave us believe that there is a contradiction in the idea of infinite goodness, or infinite wisdom ? Instead of " the Infinite," substitute " an infinitely good Being," and Mr. Hansel's argument reads thus : If there is anything which an infinitely good Being cannot become if he cannot be- come bad that is a limitation, and the goodness cannot be infinite. If there is anything which an infinitely good Being actually is (namely good), he is excluded from being any other thing, as from being wise or powerful. I hardly think that Sir W. Hamilton would patronize this logic, learnt though it be in his school.* It cannot be necessary to follow up Mr. Mansel's metaphysical dissertation any farther. It is all, as I have said, the same ignoratio elenc/ti. I have been able to find only one short passage in which he attempts to show that we are unable to represent in thought a particular attribute carried to the infinite. For the sake of fairness, * By the time Mr. Mansel gets to this place, he grows tired of giving relevant answers, and thinks that any verbal repartee will suffice. To the first half of my statement, his answer is this ^p. 158) : " Is becoming bad a higher perfection?" I reply, that Mr. Mansel seems to think so; inasmuch as he says " If the infinite can be that which it is not, it is by " that very possibility marked out as incomplete, and capable of a higher " perfection." If the infinite is God, and, as such, good, to become bad would be to become what it is not, and consequently, according to Mr. Mansel, to attain a higher perfection. To the second half he replies by identifying the manner in which the Infinite, by being anything in par- ticular, is excluded from being any other thing, with the manner in which a thing, by being a horse, is excluded from being a dog. Let me remind him that a horse and a dog are substances, and that we are talking about attributes. A substance cannot become another substance, but it may put on any number of additional attributes. Does not the whole of the discussion turn upon attributes ? Does the question, what the Infinite can or cannot be or become, mean anything but what attributes it can have or acquire ? As a Substance the Infinite is the Infinite, and cannot become anything else. Does it follow from this that by possessing one attribute, it is excluded from possessing any other ? Or is it possible that Mr. Mansel means, that the " Infinite, if it is to be conceived at all," must be conceived as capable of changing its substance, and becoming a finite dog, thereby excluding itself from being a horse ? That would indeed be a stretch beyond anything I have charged him with. 122 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED I cite it in a note.* All the argument that I can dis- cover in it, I conceive that I have already answered, as stated much better by Sir W. Hamilton. Mr. Mansel thinks it necessary to declare f that the contradictions are not in "the nature of the Absolute" or Infinite " in itself, but only" in " our own conception of that nature." He did not mean to say that the Divine Nature is itself contradictory. But he saysj " We are compelled by the constitution of our minds, " to believe in the existence of an Absolute and Infinite "Being." Such being the case, I ask, is the Being, whom we must believe to be infinite and absolute, infinite and absolute in the meaning which those terms bear in Mr. Mansel's definition of them ? If not, he is bound to tell us in what other meaning. Believing God to be infinite and absolute must be believing something, and it must be possible to say what. If Mr. Mansel means that we must believe the reality of an Infinite and Absolute Being in some other sense than that in which he has proved such a Being to be inconceivable, his point is not made out, since he undertook to prove the inconceiva- bility of the very Being in whose reality we are required to believe. But the truth is that the Infinite and Abso- lute which he says we must believe in, are the very Infinite and Absolute of his definitions. The Infinite is that which is opposed to the Finite ; the Absolute, that which is opposed to the Relative. He has therefore * " A thing an object an attribute a person or any other term sig- ' nifying one out of many possible objects of consciousness, is by that very ' relation necessarily declared to be finite. An infinite thing, or object, or ' attribute, or person, is therefore in the same moment declared to be both finite and infinite. . . And on the other hand, if all human attributes are conceived under the conditions of difference, and relation, and time, and personality, we cannot represent in thought any such attribute magnified to infinity ; for this again is to conceive it as finite and infinite at the same time. We can conceive such attributes, at the utmost, only indefi- nitely ; that is to say, we may withdraw our thoughts, for the moment, from the fact of their being limited ; but we cannot conceive them as infinite ; that is to say, we cannot positively think of the absence of the limit; for, the instant we attempt to do so, the antagonist elements of the conception exclude one another, and annihilate the whole." Limits of Eeligious Thought, p. bU. f ibid. p. 39. J Ibid. p. 45. AS APPLIED BY MR. M ANSEL TO RELIGION. 123 either proved nothing, or vastly more than he intended. For the contradictions which he asserts to be involved in the notions, do not follow from an imperfect mode of apprehending the Infinite and Absolute, but lie in the definitions of them ; in the meaning of the phrases themselves. The contradictions are in the very object which we are called upon to believe. If, therefore, Mr. Mansel would escape from the conclusion that an Infi- nite and Absolute Being is intrinsically impossible, it must be by affirming, with Hegel, that the law of Contradiction does not apply to the Absolute ; that, respecting the Absolute, contradictory propositions may both be true.* Let us now pass from Mr. Mansel's metaphysical argumentation on an irrelevant issue, to a much more important subject, that of his practical conclusion,namely, that we cannot know the divine attributes in such a manner, as can entitle us to reject any statement respect- * Mr. Mansel's summary of his reply on this portion of the case is as follows (pp.161, 162): "The reader may now, perhaps, understand the " reason of an assertion which Mr. Mill regards as supremely absurd, ' namely, that we must believe in the existence of an absolute and infinite ' Being, though unable to conceive the nature of such a Being. To be- ' lieve in such a Being is simply to believe that God made the world : to ' declare the nature of such a Being inconceivable, is simply to say that ' we do not know how the world was made. If we believe that God made ' the world, we must believe that there was a time when the world was not, ' and when God alone existed, out of relation to any other being. But ' the mode of that sole existence we are unable to conceive, nor in what ' manner the first act took place by which the absolute and self -existent * gave existence to the relative and dependent." I know not how Mr. Mansel discovers that I regard as supremely absurd the notion that we may believe, and may have good grounds for believing, things which are inconceivable to us. As he most truly says, there is no one with whose mode of thinking such an opinion would more flagrantly conflict. But I venture to think that one may deem it possible to have a real and positive, though inadequate, conception of an infinite Being, without supposing oneself to know how God made the world. Mr. Mansel resumes (p. J63) " Where is the incongruity of saying, I believe that a " being exists possessing certain attributes, though I am unable in mjr " present state of knowledge to conceive the manner of that existence ? ' Assuredly, nowhere : provided that you do not invest the object of your belief with contradictory attributes ; for my admission of the believability of what is inconceivable, stops at the self-contradictory : consequently I do not admit the believability of such an Absolute and Infinite as Mr. Mansel has been mystifying us with. The sum of what I am maintaining against him is, that the Absolute and Infinite which are believable, and 124 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED ing the Deity, on the ground of its being inconsistent with his character. Let us examine whether this asser- tion is a legitimate corollary from the relativity of human knowledge, either as it really is, or as it is under- stood to he by Sir W. Hamilton and by Mr. Mansel. The fundamental property of our knowledge of God, Mr. Mansel says, is that we do not and cannot know him as he is in himself: certain persons, therefore, whom he calls Rationalists, he condemns as unphilosophical, when they reject any statement as inconsistent with the character of God. This is a valid answer, as far as words go, to some of the later Transcendentalists to those who think that we have an intuition of the Divine Nature ; though even as to them it would not be difficult to show that the answer is but skin-deep. But those " Rationalists" who hold, with Mr. Mansel himself, the relativity of human knowledge, are not touched by his reasoning. We cannot know God as he is in himself (they reply) ; granted : and what then ? Can we know man as he is in himself, or matter as it is in itself? the Absolute and Infinite which are inconceivable, are different things ' That the Absolute and Infinite of which, as he has shown, the conception annihilates itself by the contradictions it involves, is that which possesses absolutely and infinitely all attributes, and that this is as unbelievable as it is inconceivable : That the Absolute and Infinite which is believable is that which possesses absolutely and infinitely some given attributes, which in their finite degrees are known to us, and is therefore conceivable; and involves no contradiction, unless we include among the attributes some that contradict one another, in which case it is indeed inconceivable, but also unbelievable. When Mr. Mansel maintains (pp. 14-18, and 142) that being infinite is, to our conceptive faculty, inconsistent with being a Person, I answer, that it is being " The Infinite " which is so. When he insists (if he does insist) that the Creator must, in some manner inconceivable to us, be this non- entity ; when he identifies the Creator (p: 100) with something which we must believe to be " the sole existence, having no plurality beyond itself," and " simple, having no plurality within itself," thus literally annihilating all plurality in the universe ; when he says (pp. 28, 29) " we believe that " God's " own nature is simple and uniform, admitting of no distinction between various attributes, nor between any attribute and its subject," buyet conceivable by us " only by means of various attributes, distinct from the subject and from each other," i.e. conceived by us as he is nut ; it appears to me that in thus following the old theologians in the mystical metaphysics which is always at the service of mystical theology, he en- cumbers Theism and Christianity with (to say the least) very unnecessary difficulties. AS APPLIED BY MR. M ANSEL TO RELIGION. 125 We do not claim any other knowledge of God than such as we have of man or of matter. Because I do not know my fellow-men, nor any of the powers of nature, as they are in themselves, am T therefore not at liberty to disbelieve anything I hear respecting them as being inconsistent with their character ? I know something of Man and Nature, not as they are in themselves, but as they are relatively to us ; and it is as relative to us, and not as he is in himself, that I suppose myself to know anything of God. The attributes which I ascribe to him, as goodness, knowledge, power, are all relative. They are attributes (says the rationalist) which my expe- rience enables me to conceive, and which I consider as proved, not absolutely, by an intuition of God, but phaeno- menally, by his action on the creation, as known through my senses and my rational faculty. These relative attributes, each of them in an infinite degree, are all I pretend to predicate of God. When I reject a doctrine as inconsistent with God's nature, it is not as being in- consistent with what God is in himself, but with what he is as manifested to us. If my knowledge of him is only phenomenal, the assertions which I reject are phenomenal too. If those assertions are inconsistent with my relative knowledge of him, it is no answer to say that all my knowledge of him is relative. That is no more a reason against disbelieving an alleged fact as unworthy of God, than against disbelieving another alleged fact as unworthy of Turgot, or of Washington, whom also I do not know as Noumena, but only as Phenomena. There is but one way for Mr. Mansel out of this diffi- culty, and he adopts it. He must maintain, not merely that an Absolute Being is unknowable in himself, but that the Relative attributes of an Absolute Being are unknowable likewise. He must say that we do not know what Wisdom, Justice, Benevolence, Mercy, are, as they exist in God. Accordingly he does say so. The follow- ing are his direct utterances on the subject : as an im- plied doctrine, it pervades his whole argument. 126 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED " It is a fact * which experience forces upon us, and " which it is useless, were it possible, to disguise, that " the representation of God after the model of the " highest human morality which we are capable of " conceiving, is not sufficient to account for all the " phenomena exhibited by the course of his natural " Providence. The infliction of physical suffering, " the permission of moral evil, the adversity of the *' good, the prosperity of the wicked, the crimes of the " guilty involving the misery of the innocent, the tardy " appearance and partial distribution of moral and reli- " gious knowledge in the world these are facts which " no doubt are reconcilable, we know not how, with the " Infinite Goodness of God, but which certainly are not " to be explained on the supposition that its sole and " sufficient type is to be found in the finite goodness of " man." In other words, it is necessary to suppose that the infinite goodness ascribed to God is not the goodness which we know and love in our fellow-creatures, distin- guished only as infinite in degree, but is different in kind, and another quality altogether. When we call the one finite goodness and the other infinite goodness, we do not mean what the words assert, but something else : we intentionally apply the same name to things which we regard as different. Accordingly Mr. Mansel combats, as a heresy of his opponents, the opinion that infinite goodness differs only in degree from finite goodness. The notion f " that the " attributes of God differ from those of man in degree " only, not in kind, and hence that certain mental and " moral qualities of which we are immediately conscious " in ourselves, furnish at the same time a true and " adequate image of the infinite perfections of God," (the word adequate must have slipped in by inadvertence, since otherwise it would be an inexcusable misrepresenta- tion) he identifies with " the vulgar Eationalism which "regards the reason of man, in its ordinary and normal * Limits of Beligious Thought, Preface to the fourth edition, p. 13, f Ibid. p. 26. AS APPLIED BY MR. M ANSEL TO RELIGION. 127 " operation, as the supreme criterion of religious truth." And in characterizing the mode of arguing of this vulgar Rationalism, he declares its principles to be, that* " all " the excellences of which we are conscious in the " creature, must necessarily exist in the same manner, " though in a higher degree, in the Creator. God is " indeed more wise, more just, more merciful, than man; " but for that very reason, his wisdom and justice and " mercy must contain nothing that is incompatible with . THE INTERPRETATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 169 absence of contrary evidence ; that, the Divine Being, like a prisoner at the bar, should be presumed innocent until proved .guilty. Far, however, from intending this remark in any invidious sense against Sir W. Hamilton, I regard it as one of his titles to honour, that he has not been afraid, as many men would have been, to subject a proposition surrounded by reverence to the same logical treatment as any other statement, and has not felt him- self obliged, as a philosopher, to consider it from the first as final. My complaint could only be, that his logic is not sufficiently consistent; and that the divine veracity is entitled either to more or to less weight than he accords to it. He is bound by the laws of correct reasoning to prove his premise without the aid of the conclusion which he means to draw from it. If he can do this if the divine veracity is certified by stronger evidence than the testimony of consciousness, it may be appealed to, not merely as a presumption, but as a proof. If not, it is entitled to no place in the discussion, even as a presumption. There is no intermediate position for it, good enough for the one purpose, but not good enough tor the other. It would be a new view of the fallacy of petitio principii to contend that a conclusion is no proof of the premises from which it is deduced, but is prima facie evidence of them. Our author, however, cannot be convicted of petitio principii. Though he has not stated, I think he has enabled us to see, in what manner he avoided it. True, he has deduced the trustworthiness of consciousness from the veracity of the Deity ; and the veracity of the Deity can only be known from the evidence of con- sciousness. But he may fall back upon the distinction between facts given in consciousness itself, and facts " to the reality of which it only bears evidence." It is for the trustworthiness of these last, that he assigns as pre- sumptive evidence (which the absence of counter-evidence raises into proof) the divine veracity. That veracity itself, he may say, is proved by consciousness, but to prove it requires only the other class of facts of consciousness, 170 THE INTERPRETATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS. those given in the act of consciousness itself. There are thus two steps in the argument. " The phenomena of consciousness considered merely in themselves," with reference to which " scepticism is confessedly impos- sible/'* suffice (we must suppose him to think) for proving the divine veracity ; and that veracity, being proved, is in its turn a reason for trusting the testimony which consciousness pronounces to facts without and beyond itself. Unless, therefore, Sir W. Hamilton was guilty of a paralogism, by adducing religion in proof of what is ne- cessary to the proof of religion, his opinion must have been that our knowledge of Grod rests upon the affirma- tion which Consciousness makes of itself, and not of anything beyond itself; that the divine existence and attributes may be proved without assuming that con- sciousness testifies to anything but our own feelings and mental operations. If this be so, we have Sir W. Hamilton's authority for affirming, that even the most extreme form of philosophical scepticism, the Nihilism (as our author calls it) of Hume, which denies the ob- jective existence of both Matter and Mind, does not touch the evidences of Natural Religion. And it really does not touch any evidences but such as religion can well spare. But what a mass of religious prejudice has been directed against this philosophical doctrine, on the strength of what we have now Sir W. Hamilton's au- thority for treating as a mere misapprehension.! But something more is necessary to render the divine veracity available in support of the testimony of con- sciousness, against those, if such there be, who admit the fact of the testimony, but hesitate to admit its * Dissertations on Reid, p. 745. f Accordingly Sir W. Hamilton says elsewhere (Appendix to Lectures, i. 394) : " Religious disbelief and philosophical scepticism are not merely not the same, but have no natural connexion." I regret that this state- ment is followed by a declaration that the former " must ever be a matter" not merely "of regret," but of "reprobation." This imputation of moral blame to an opinion sincerely entertained and honestly arrived at, is a blot which one would willingly not have found in a thinker of so much ability, and in general of so high a moral tone. THE INTERPRETATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 171 truth. The divine veracity ^an only be implicated in the truth "oT any thing, by proving that the Divine Being intended it to be believed. As it is not pretended that Ee has made any revelation in the matter, his intention can only be interred from the result : and our author draws the inference from his having made it an original and indestructible part of our nature that our conscious- ness should declare to us certain facts. Now this is what the philosophers who disbelieve the facts, would not, any of them, admit. Many indeed have admitted that we have a natural tendency to believe something which they considered to be an illusion : but it cannot be affirmed that God intended us to do whatever we have a natural tendency to. On every theory of the divine government, it is carried on, intellectually as well as morally, not by the mere indulgence of our natural ten- dencies, but by the regulation and control of them. One philosopher, Hume, has said that the tendency in ques- tion seems to be an "instinct," and has called a psycho- logical doctrine, which he regarded as groundless, an " universal and primary opinion of all men." But he never dreamed of saying that we are compelled by our nature to believe it ; on the contrary, he says that this illusive opinion "is soon destroyed by the slightest philosophy." Of all eminent thinkers, the one who comes nearest to our author's description of those who reject the testimony of consciousness, is Kant. That philosopher did maintain that there is an illusion in- herent in our constitution; that we cannot help con- ceiving as belonging to Things themselves, attributes with which they are only clothed by the laws of our sensitive and intellectual faculties. But he drew a marked distinction between an illusion and a delusion. He did not believe in a mystification practised on us by the Supreme -Being, nor would he have admitted that God intended us permanently to mistake the conditions of our mental conceptions for properties of the things themselves. If God has provided us with the means of correcting an error, it is probable that he does not 172 THE INTERPRETATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS. intend us to be misled by it : and in' matters specula- tive as well as practical, it surely is more religious to see the purposes of Grod in the dictates of our deliberate reason, than in those of a "blind and powerful instinct of nature." As regards almost all, however, if not all philosophers, it may truly be said, that the questions which have divided them have never turned on the veracity of con- sciousness. Consciousness, in the sense usually attached to it by philosophers, consciousness of .the mind's own feelings and operations, cannot, as our author truly says, be disbelieved. The inward fact, the feeling in our own minds, was never doubted, since to do so would be to doubt that we feel what we feel. What our author calls the testimony of consciousness to some- thing beyond itself, may be, and is, denied ; but what is denied, has almost always been that consciousness gives the testimony ; not that, if given, it must be believed. At first sight it might seem as if there could not pos- sibly be any doubt whether our consciousness does or does not affirm any given thing. Nor can there, if con- * y^vsciousness means, as it usually does, self-consciousness. ^ If consciousness tells me that I have a certain thought or sensation, I assuredly have that thought or sensation. But if consciousness, as with Sir W. Hamilton, means a power which can tell me things that are not phenomena of my own mind, there is immediately the broadest divergence of opinion as to what are the things to whicli consciousness testifies. There is nothing which people do not think and say that they know by consciousness, provided they do not remember any time when they did not know or believe it, and are not aware in what manner they came by the belief. For Consciousness, in this extended sense, is, as I have so often observed, but another word for Intuitive Knowledge : and whatever other things we may know in that manner, we certainly do not know by intuition what knowledge is intuitive. It is a subject on which both the vulgar and the ablest THE INTERPRETATION OF CONSC OUSNESS. 1 73 thinkers are constantly making mistakes. No one is better aware of this than Sir W. Hamilton. I transcribe a few of the many passages in which he has acknow- ledged it. "Errors"* may arise by attributing to "in- " telligence as necessary and original data, what are " only contingent generalizations from experience, and " consequently, make no part of its complement of native " truths."! And again :J " Many philosophers have " attempted to establish on the principles of common " sense propositions which are not original data of con- " sciousness ; while the original data of consciousness, " from which their propositions were derived, and to " which they owed their whole necessity and truth these " data the same philosophers were (strange to say) not " disposed to admit." It fares still worse with the philosophers chargeable with this error, when Sir W. Hamilton comes into personal controversy with them. M. Cousin's mode of proceeding, for example, he charac- terizes thus: "Assertion is substituted for proof; facts " of consciousness are alleged, which consciousness never " knew ; and paradoxes that baffle argument, are pro- " mulgated as intuitive truths, above the necessity of " confirmation." M. Cousin's particular misinterpreta- tion of consciousness was, as we saw, that of supposing that each of its acts testifies to three things, of which three Sir W. Hamilton thinks that it testifies only to one. Besides the finite element, consisting of a Self and a Not-self, M. Cou*in believes that there are directly revealed in Consciousness an Infinite (God) and a rela- tion between this Infinite and the Finite. But it is not only M. Cousin who, in our author's opinion, mistakes the testimony of consciousness. He brings the same charge against a thinker with whom he agrees much * Lectures, iv. 137. f There are writers of reputation in the present day, who maintain in unqualified terms, that we know by intuition the impossibility of miracles. " La negation du miracle," says M. Nefftzer (Revue Gtrrmanique tor September 1863, p. 183), " n'est pas subordonne'e a I'expeVience ; elle est " une necessite logique et un fait de certitude interne ; elle doit e'tre le " premier article du credo de tout historien et de tout penseur." J Dissertations on Reid, p. 749. Discussions, p. 25. 174 THE INTERPRETATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS. oftener than with M. Cousin ; against Eeid. That philosopher, as we have seen, is of opinion, contrary to Sir W. Hamilton, that we have an immediate knowledge of things past. This is to be conscious of them in Sir W. Hamilton's sense of the word, though not in Reid's. Finally, Sir W. Hamilton imputes a similar error, no longer to any particular metaphysician, but to the world at large. He says that we do riot see the sun, but only a luminous image, in immediate contiguity to the eye, and that no two persons see the same sun, but every person a different one. Now it is assuredly the universal belief of mankind that all of them see the same sun, and that this is the very sun which rises and sets, and which is 95 (or according to more recent researches 92) millions' of miles distant from the earth. Nor can any of the appeals of Reid and Sir W. Hamilton from the sophistries of metaphysicians to Common Sense and the universal sentiment of mankind, be more emphatic than that to which Sir W. Hamilton here lays himself open from Eeid and from the non-metaphysical world.* We see, therefore, that it is rot enough to say that something is testified by Consciousness, and refer all * Reid himself places the "natural belief" which Sir W. Hamilton rejects, on exactly the level of those which he most strenuously maintains, saying ("Works, Hamilton's edition, p. 284) in a passage which our author himself quotes, " The vulgar are firmly persuaded that the very identical " objects which they perceive continue to exist when they do not perceive " them : and are no less firmly persuaded that when ten men look at the " sun or the moon, they all see the same individual object." And Eeid avows that he agrees with the vulgar in both opinions. But Sir W. Hamilton, while he upholds the former of these as one to deny which would be to declare our nature a lie, thinks that nothing can be more absurd than the latter of them. " Nothing," he says (Lectures, ii. 129), can be conceived more ridiculous than the opinion of philosophers in regard to this. For example, it has been curiously held (and Eeid is no exception) that in looking at the sun, moon, or any other object of sight, , we are, on the one doctrine, actually conscious of these distant objects, or, on the other, that these distant objects are those really represented in the mind. Nothing can be more absurd : we perceive, through no sense, aught external but what is in immediate relation and in immediate ' contact with its organ. . . . Through the eye we perceive nothing but ' the rays of light in relation to, and in contact with, the retina." The basis of the whole Ideal System, which it is thought to be the great merit of Eeid to have exploded, was a natural prejudice, supposed to be intuitively evident, namely, that that which knows, must be of a similar THE INTERPRETATION OP CONSCIOUSNESS. 175 dissentients to consciousness to prove it. Substitute for Consciousness the equivalent phrase (in our author's acceptation at least) Intuitive Knowledge, and it is seen that this is not a thing which can be proved by mere introspection of ourselves. Introspection can show us a present belief or conviction, attended with a greater or a less difficulty in accommodating the thoughts to a different view of the subject : but that this belief, or conviction, or knowledge, if we call it so, is intuitive, no mere introspection can ever show ; unless we are at liberty to assume that every mental process which is now as unhesitating and as rapid as intuition, was intuitive at its outset. Reid, in his commencements at least, often expressed himself as if he believed this to be the case : Sir W. Hamilton, wiser than ileid, knew better. With him (at least in his better moments) the question, what is and is not revealed by Consciousness, is a question for philosophers. " The first* problem of philosophy " is " to seek out, purify, and establish, by intellectual analysis " and criticism, the elementary feelings or beliefs, in " which are given the elementary truths of which all are " in possession :" this problem, he admits, is " of no easy nature to that which is known by it. " This principle," says our author (foot-note to Reid. p. 300), " has, perhaps, exerted a more extensive " influence on speculation than any other. ... It would be easy to show " that the belief, explicit or implicit, that what knows and what is imme- " diately known must be of an analogous nature, lies at the root of almost " every theory of cognition, from the very earliest to the very latest " speculations. . . . And yet it has not been proved, and is incapable of " proof, nay, is contradicted by the evidence of consciousness itself." But though Sir W. Hamilton manifests himself thus thoroughly aware how wide the differences of opinion may be and are respecting our intui- tive perceptions, I by no means intend to deny that he on certain occa- sions affirms the contrary. In the fourth volume of the Lectures (p. 95), he says, " I have here limited the possibility of error to Probable Reason - " ing, for in Intuition and Demonstration, there is but little possibility of " important error." After a certain amount of reading of Sir W. Hamilton, one is used to these contradictions. What he here asserts to be so nearly impossible, that no account needs to be taken of it in a classification of Error, he is continually fighting against in detail, and imputing to nearly all philosophers. And when he says (Lectures, i. 266) that the " revela- tion" of consciousness is " naturally clear," and only mistaken by philoso- phers because they resort to it solely for confirmation of their own opinions, he merely transports into psychology the dogmatism of theologians. * Dissertations on Reid, p. 752. 176 THE INTERPRETATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS. accomplishment;" and the "argument from common sense " is thus " manifestly dependent on philosophy as " an art, as an acquired dexterity, and cannot, notwith- " standing the errors which they have so frequently " committed, be taken out of the hands of the philoso- j " phers. Common sense is like Common Law. Each may " he laid down as the general rule of decision ; but in " the one case it must be left to the jurist, in the other " to the philosopher, to ascertain what are the contents " of the rule ; and though in both instances the common " man may be cited as a witness for the custom or the " fact, in neither can he be allowed to officiate as advo- " cate or as judge." So far, good. But now, it being conceded that the question, what do we know intuitively, or, in Sir W. Hamilton's phraseology, what does our consciousness testify, is not, as might be supposed, a matter of simple self-examination, but of science, it has still to be deter- mined in what manner science should set about it. And here emerges the distinction between two different me- thods of studying the problems of metaphysics, forming the radical difference between the two great schools into which metaphysicians are fundamentally divided. One -,.- of these I shall call, for distinction, the introspective method ; the other, the psychological. The elaborate and acute criticism on the philosophy . of Locke, which is perhaps the most striking portion of J\i. Cousin's Lectures on the History of Philosophy, sets out with a remark which sums up the characteristics of the two great schools of mental philosophy, by a summary description of their methods. M. Cousin observes, that Locke went wrong from the beginning, by placing before himself, as the question to be first resolved, the origin of our ideas. This was commencing at the wrong end. The proper course would have been to begin by determining what the ideas now are ; to ascertain what it is that consciousness actually tells us, postponing till afterwards the attempt to frame a theory concerning the origin of any of the mental phenomena. THE INTERPRETATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 177 I accept the question as M. Cousin states it, and I contend, that no attempt to determine what are the direct revelations of consciousness, can be successful, or entitled to any regard, unless preceded by what M. Cousin says ought only to follow it, an inquiry into the origin of our acquired ideas. For we have it not in our power to ascertain, by any direct process, what Consciousness told us at the time when its revelations were in their pristine purity. It only offers itself to our inspection as it exists now, when those original revelations are overlaid and buried under a mountainous heap of acquired notions and perceptions. It seerns to M. Cousin that if we examine, with care and minuteness, our present states of consciousness, dis- tinguishing and defining every ingredient which we find to enter into them every element that we seem to re- cognise as real, and cannot, by merely concentrating our attention upon it, analyse into anything simpler we reach the ultimate and primary truths, which are the sources of all our knowledge, and which cannot be denied or doubted without denying or doubting the evidence of consciousness itself, that is, the only evidence which there is for anything. I maintain this to be a misap- prehension of the conditions imposed on inquirers by the difficulties of psychological investigation. To begin the inquiry at the point where M. Cousin takes it up, is in fact to beg the question. For he must be aware, if not of the fact, at least of the belief of his opponents, that the laws of the mind the laws of association according to one class of thinkers, the Categories of the Understanding according to another are capable of creating, out of those data of con- ^ ^ sciousness which are uncontested, purely mental con- -j&fo ceptions, which become so identified in thought with all our states of consciousness, that we seem, and cannot but seem, to receive them by direct intuition ; and, for example, the belief in Matter, in the opinion of some of these thinkers, is, or at least may be, thus produced. Idealists, and Sceptics, contend that the belief in Matter N I IV^-CU-M v \/\tvwvw**v 178 THE INTERPRETATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS. is not an original fact of consciousness, as our sensations are, and is therefore wanting in the requisite which, in M. Cousin's and Sir W. Hamilton's opinion, gives to our subjective convictions objective authority. Now, be these persons right or wrong, they cannot be refuted in the mode in which M. Cousin and Sir W. Hamilton attempt to do so by appealing to Consciousness itself. ^ For we have no means of interrogating consciousness in the only circumstances in which it is possible for it to give a trustworthy answer. Could we try the ex- periment of the first consciousness in any infant its first reception of the impressions which we call external ; whatever was present in that first consciousness would be the genuine testimony of Consciousness, and would he as much entitled to credit, indeed there would be as little possibility of discrediting it, as our sensations themselves. But we have no means of now ascertaining, by direct evidence, whether we were conscious of out- ward and extended objects when we first opened our eyes to the light. That a belief or knowledge of such objects is in our consciousness now, whenever we use our eyes or our muscles, is no reason for concluding that it was there from the beginning, until we have settled the question whether it could possibly have been brought in since. If any mode can be pointed out in which within the compass of possibility it might have been brought in, the hypothesis must be examined and dis- proved before we are entitled to conclude that the con- viction is an original deliverance of consciousness. The proof that any of the alleged Universal Beliefs, or Prin- ciples of Common Sense, are affirmations of conscious- ness, supposes two things ; that the beliefs exist, and that there are no means by which they could have been acquired. The first is in most cases undisputed, but the second is a subject of inquiry which often taxes the utmost resources of psychology. Locke was therefore right in believing that " the origin of our ideas" is the main stress of the problem of mental science, and the subject which must be first considered in forming the THE INTERPRETATION OP CONSCIOUSNESS. 179 theory of the Mind. Being unable to examine the actual contents of our consciousness until our earliest, which are necessarily our most firmly knit associations, those which are most intimately interwoven with the original data of consciousness, are fully formed, we cannot study the original elements of mind in the facts of our pre- sent consciousness. Those original elements can only come to light as residual phenomena, by a previous study of the modes of generation of the mental facts which are confessedly not original ; a study sufficiently thorough to enable us to apply its results to the convic- tions, beliefs, or supposed intuitions which seem to be original, and to determine whether some of them may not have been generated in the same modes, so early as to have become inseparable from our consciousness before the time to which memory goes back. This mode of ascertaining the original elements of mind I call, for want of a better word, the psychological, as distinguished from the simply introspective mode. It is the known and approved method of physical science, adapted to the necessities of psychology.* It might be supposed from incidental expressions of Sir W. Hamilton that he was alive to the need of a methodical scientific investigation, to determine what o portion of our " natural beliefs" are really original, and * The " Inquirer" thinks he refutes the preceding paragraph when he says (pp. 52, 53) that Consciousness may not have given its full revelation in the infant, and that it would be "contrary to ail analogy" to suppose " that consciousness alone, of all our natural properties, needs no develop- ment, no education." If this supposed improvement of consciousness by exercise be admitted, it goes even harder with the Introspective Method than I had maintained. I pointed out an experiment not realizable, but conceivable, which by ascertaining the contents of consciousness ante- cedently to any acquired experience, would authenticate as the original data of consciousness whatever that experiment revealed. But if con- sciousness does not tell its tale at once, but requires time and practice to tell it, and does not get it completed until there has been time for impres- sions originating in experience to be formed, then there is no period at which the Introspective Method, applied to the case, would yield a con- clusive result : the natural and acquired testimonies of consciousness are inseparably blended at every stage, and to separate them by mere selt- observation, and show that any particular item belongs to the one and not to the other, involves a double impossibility, instead of the single ons I contended for. N 2 rv' ISO THE INTERPRKTATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS. what are inferences, or acquired impressions, mistakenly deemed intuitive.* To the declarations already quoted to this effect, the following may be added. Speaking of Descartes' plan, of commencing philosophy by a recon- sideration of all our fundamental opinions, he says, " There are among our prejudices, or pretended cog- -" nitions, a great many hasty conclusions, the investi- " gation of which requires much profound thought, " skill, and acquired knowledge To commence " philosophy by such a review, it is necessary for a man " to be a philosopher before he can attempt to become " one." And he elsewheref bestows high praise upon Aristotle for not falling " into the error of many modern " philosophers, in confounding the natural and necessary " with the habitual and acquired connexions of thought," nor attempting " to evolve the conditions under which we think from the tendencies generated by thinking ;" a praise which cannot be bestowed on our author him- self. But, notwithstanding the ample concession which he appeared to make when he admitted that the problem was one of extreme difficulty, essentially scientific, and ought to be reserved for philosophers, I regret to say that he as completely sets at naught the only possible method of solving it, as M. Cousin himself. He even expresses his contempt for that method. Speaking of Extension, he says,| " It is truly an idle problem to " attempt imagining the steps by which we may be sup- " posed to have acquired the notion of Extension, when " in fact, we are unable to imagine to ourselves the possi- " bility of that notion not being always in our posses-. " sion." That things which we " are unable to imagine to ourselves the possibility of," may be, and many of them must be, true, was a doctrine which we thought we had learnt from the author of the Philosophy of the Conditioned. That we cannot imagine a time at which we had no knowledge of Extension, is no evidence that there has not been such a time. There are mental laws, * Lectures, iv. 92. t Dissertations on Eeid, p. 894. J Ibid. p. 882. THE INTERPRETATION OF coNsciotsNEss. 181 recognised by Sir W. Hamilton himself which would inevitably cause such a state of things to become incon- ceivable to us, even if it once existed. There are artificial inconceivabilities equal in strength to any natural. In- deed it is questionable if there are any natural incon- ceivabilities, or ifjinything is inconceivable to us tor any other reason than because Nature does not afford the combinations in experience which are necessary to make it conceivable. I do not think that there can be found, in all Sir W. Hamilton's writings, a single . instance in which, before registering a belief as a part of our consciousness from the beginning, he thinks it necessary to ascertain that it can- not have grown up subsequently. He demands, indeed,* " that no fact be assumed as a fact of consciousness but what is ultimate and simple." But to pronounce it ultimate, the only condition he requires is that we be not able to " reduce it to a generalization from experience." This condition is realized by its possessing the " character " of necessity." "It must be impossible not to think it. " In fact, by its necessity alone can we recognise it as an- " original datum of intelligence, and distinguish it from " any mere result of generalization and custom." In this Sir VV. Hamilton is at one with the whole of his own section of the philosophical world ; with Eeid, with Stewart, with Cousin, with Whewell, and we may add, with Kant.f The test by which they all decide a belief .* Lectures, i. 268-270. f In the first edition I added, " and even with Mr. Herbert Spencer :" but that powerful thinker, in his paper in the Fortnightly Review, dis- claims the doctrine. As I now understand Mr. Spencer, he maintains that the impossibility of getting rid of a belief is a proof of its truth, and also of its being a primary, or ultimate, truth, but not of its being intui- tive, since even our primary forms of thought are, in Mr. Spencer's opinion, products of experience, either our own, or inherited by us from ancestors by the laws of the development of organization. I had confounded the two ideas, of a primary truth and an intuitive truth, which had never, as far as 1 know, been distinguished by any one except Mr. Spencer ; and had, therefore, ideatified his theory with the ordinary doctrine of the intuitive philosophy ; which I now see to be a misconception, though I think both theories open to refutation by the same arguments, and the difference between them not material to the test of truth, though highly important to psychology, i perceive also that I was mistaken, when, in an early chapter of this- j t>' ^ ^^ ^ n^, .the other is not, a state or modification of mind, but in A v"* both is distinct equally from the act of perception, and ,! from the external object : and the mind is cognizant of external object vicariously, through this third thing, of which alone it has immediate cognizance of which alone, therefore, it is, in Sir W. Hamilton's sense of the V/* word, conscious. Against both these theories Reid, Stewart, and our author, are completely triumphant, and ; I am in no way interested in pressing for a rehearing of , the cause. But the third opinion, which is Brown's, cannot with any justness of thought or propriety of language 'be called a theory of mediate or representative perception. Had Sir W. Hamilton taken half the pains to under- stand Brown which he took to understand far inferior thinkers, he never would have described Brown's doc- trine in terms so inappropriate. Representative knowledge is always understood by our author to be knowledge of a thing by means of an image of it ; by means of something which is like the thing itself. " Representative knowledge," he says, " is " only deserving of the name of knowledge in so far as " it is conformable with the intuitions which it repre- " sents."* The representation must stand in a rela- tion to what it represents, like that of a picture to its original : as the representation in memory of a past impression of sense, does to that past impression ; as a representation in imagination does to a supposed pos- sible presentation of sense ; and as the Ideas of the earlier Cosmothetic Idealists were supposed to do to the out- ward objects of which they were the image or impress. But the Mental Modifications of Brown and those who think with him, are not supposed to bear any resem- blance to the objects which excite them. These ob- jects are supposed to be unknown to us, except as the causes of the mental modifications. The only relation * Dissertations on Reid, p. 811. ON THE BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 197 between the two is that of cause and effect. Brown, being free from the vulgar < error that a cause must be like its effect, and admitting no knowledge of the cause (beyond its bare existence) except the effect itself, naturally found nothing in it which it was pos- sible to compare with the effect, or in virtue of which any resemblance could be affirmed to exist between the two. In another place,* Sir W. Hamilton makes an ostensible distinction between the fact of resembling and that of truly representing the objects ; but defines the last expression to mean, affording us " such a know- " ledge of their nature as we should have were an im- " mediate intuition of the reality in itself competent to " man." No one who is at all acquainted with Brown's opinions will pretend him to have maintained that we have anything of this sort. He did not believe that the mental modification afforded us any knowledge whatever of the nature of the external object. There is no need to quote passages in proof of this ; it is a fact patent to whoever reads his Lectures. It is the more strange that Sir W. Hamilton should have failed to recognise this opinion of Brown, because it is exactly the opinion which he him- self holds respecting our knowledge of objects in respect of 'their Secondary Qualities. These, he says, are " in their own nature occult and inconceivable," and are known only in their effects on us, that is, by the mental modifications which they produce.! Further, Brown's is not only not a theory of repre- sentative perception, but it is not even a theory of mediate perception. He assumes no tertium quid, no object of thought intermediate between the mind and the outward object. He recognises only the perceptive act ; which with him means, and is always declared to mean, the mind itself perceiving. It will hardly be pre- tended that the mind itself is the " representative object" interposed by him between itself and the outward thing * Dissertations on Eeid, p. 842. t Dissertations on Reid, p. b46 : aud the fuller explanation at pp. 8o4 and 857. 198 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S REVIEW OF THEORIES which is acting upon it ; and if it is not, there certainly is no other. But if Brown's theory is not a theory of mediate perception, it loses all that essentially distin- guishes it from Sir W. Hamilton's own doctrine. For Brown, also thinks that we have, on the occasion of certain sensations, an instantaneous and irresistible con- viction of an outward object. And if this conviction is immediate and necessitated by the constitution of our nature, in what does it differ from our author's direct consciousness ? Consciousness, immediate knowledge, and intuitive knowledge, are, Sir W. Hamilton tells us, . ~ convertible expressions ; and if it be granted that when- ever our senses are affected by a material object, we immediately and intuitively recognise that object as existing and distinct from us, it requires a great deal of ingenuity to make out any substantial difference between this immediate intuition of an external world, and Sir W. Hamilton's direct perception of it. The distinction which our author makes, resolves itself, as explained by him, into the difference of which he has said so much, but of which he seemed to have so confused an idea, between Belief and Knowledge. In Brown's opinion, and I will add, in Reid's, the mental modification which we experience from the presence of ' an object, raises in us an irresistible belief that the object exists. No, says Sir W. Hamilton : it is not a belief, but a knowledge : we have indeed a belief, and our knowledge is certified by the belief; but this belief of ours regarding the object is a belief that we know it. " In perception,* consciousness gives, as an ultimate " fact, a belief of the knowledge of the existence of somc- " thing different from self. As ultimate, this belief cannot " be reduced to a higher principle ; neither can it be " truly analysed into a double element. We only believe " that this something exists, because we believe that we " know (are conscious of) this something as existing ; " the belief of the existence is necessarily involved in the " belief of the knowledge of the existence. Bath are * Discussions, p. 89. M ON THE BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 199 " original, or neither. Does consciousness deceive us in " the latter, it necessarily deludes us in the former ; and " if the former, though a fact of consciousness, is false, " the latter, because a fact of consciousness, is not true. ' The beliefs contained in the two propositions, " 1. I believe that a material world exists ; " 2. I believe that I immediately know a material " world existing (in other words, I believe that " the external reality itself is the object of which " I am conscious in perception), " though distinguished by philosophers, are thus vir- " tually identical. The belief of an external world was " too powerful, not to compel an acquiescence in its truth. " But the philosophers yielded to nature, only in so far ' " as to coincide in the dominant result. They falsely " discriminated the belief in the existence, from the belief " in the knowledge. With a few exceptions, they held " fast by the truth of the first ; but they concurred, with " singular unanimity, in abjuring the second." Accordingly, Brown is rebuked because, while reject- ing our natural belief that we know the external object, he yet accepts our natural belief that it exists as a suffi- cient warrant for its existence. But what real distinction is there between Brown's intuitive belief of the existence of the object, and Sir W. Hamilton's intuitive knowledge of it ? Just three pages previous,* Sir W. Hamilton had said, " Our knowledge rests ultimately on certain facts of " consciousness, which as primitive, and consequently " incomprehensible, are given less in the form of cogni- " tions than of beliefs." The consciousness of an exter- nal world is, on his own showing, primitive and incomprehensible ; it therefore is less a cognition than a belief. But if we do not so much know as believe an external world, what is meant by saying that we believe that we know it ? Either we do not know, b it only believe it, and if so, Brown and the other philosophers assailed were right ; or knowledge and belief, in the case of ultimate facts, are identical, and then, believing that * Discussions, p. 86. 200 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S REVIEW or THEORIES we know is only believing that we believe, which accord- ing to our author's and to all rational principles, is but another word for simple believing. It would not be fair, however, to hold our author to his own confused use of the terms Belief and Knowledge. He never succeeds in making anything like an intelli- gible distinction between these two notions considered generally, but in particular cases we may be able to find something which he is attempting to express by them. In the present case his meaning seems to be, that Brown's Belief in an external object, though instanta- neous and irresistible, was supposed to be suggested to the mind by its own sensation; which suggestion Brown regarded as a case of a more general law, whereby every fact suggests the intuitive belief of a cause or antecedent with which it is invariably connected : while Sir W. Hamilton's Knowledge of the object is supposed to arise along with the sensation, and to be co-ordinate with it. And this is what Sir W. Hamilton means by calling Brown's a mediate, his own an immediate cognition of the object : the real difference being that, on Sir W. Hamilton's theory, the cognition of the ego or of its modification, and that of the non-ego, are simul- taneous, while on Brown's the one immediately precedes the other. Our author expresses this meaning, though much less clearly, when he declares* Brown's theory to be "that in perception, the external reality is not the " immediate object of consciousness, but that the ego is " only determined in some unknown manner to represent " the non-ego, which representation, though only a modi- " fication of mind or self, we are compelled by an illusion " of our nature, to mistake for a modification of matter, " or non-self." This being our author's conception of the doctrine which he has to refute, let us see in what manner he proceeds to refute it. "You will remark," he says,f "that Brown (and " Brown only speaks the language of all the philosophers " who do not allow the udnd a consciousness of aught * Lectures, ii. 86. f Ibid. ii. 106. ON THE BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 201 " beyond its own states,) misstates the phenomenon " when he asserts that, in perception, there is a reference " from the internal to the external, from the known to " the unknown. That this is not the fact, our observa- " tion of the phenomenon will at once convince you. " In an act of perception, I am conscious of something " as self and of something as not self : this is the simple " fact. The philosophers, on the contrary, who will not " accept this fact, misstate it. They say that we are " conscious of nothing but a certain modification of " mind ; but this modification involves a reference to, " in other words, a representation of, something external " as its object. Now this is untrue. We are conscious \ " of no reference, of no representation : we believe that J " the object of which we are conscious is the object which " " exists." To this argument (of the worth of which something has been said already) I shall return presently. But he subjoins a second. " Nor could there possibly be such reference or repre- " sentation ; for reference or representation supposes a " knowledge already possessed of the object referred to " or represented ; butjDerception is the faculty by which " our first knowledge is acquired, and therefore cannot " suppose a previous knowledge as its condition." And further on :* " Mark the vice of the procedure. We can " only, 1, assert the existence of an external world in- " asmuch as we know it to exist ; and we can only, 2, " assert that one thing is representative of another, mas- " much as the thing represented is known, independently " of the representation. But how does the hypothesis " of a representative perception proceed ? It actually " converts the fact into an hypothesis : actually converts " the hypothesis into a fact. On this theory, we do not " know the existence of an external world, except on the " supposition that that which we do know, truly repre- " sents it as existing. The hypothetical realist cannot, "therefore, establish the fact of the external world, " except upon the fact of its representation. This is * Lectures, ii. 138, 139. 202 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S REVIEW OF THEORIES " manifest. We have, therefore, next to ask him, how " he knows the fact, that the external world is actually " represented. A representation supposes something " represented, and the representation of the external " world supposes the existence of that world. Now the " hypothetical realist, when asked how he proves the " reality of the outer world, which, ex hypothesi, he does " not know, can only say that he infers its existence from " the fact of its representation. But the fact of the re- " presentation of an external world supposes the exis- " tence of that world ; therefore he is again at the " point from which he started. He has been arguing " in a circle." Let me first remark that this reasoning assumes the whole point in dispute ; it presupposes that the supposi- tion which it is brought to disprove is impossible. The theory of the third form of Cosmothetic Idealism is, that though we are conscious only of the sensations which 'an object gives us, we are determined by a necessity of our nature, which some call an instinct, others an intui- tion, others a fundamental law of belief, to ascribe these sensations to something external, as their substratum, or as their cause. There is surely nothing a priori impos- sible in this supposition. The supposed instinct or in- tuition seems to be of the same family with many other Laws of Thought, or Natural Beliefs, which our author not only admits without scruple, but enjoins obedience to, under the usual sanction, that otherwise our intelligence must be a lie. In the present case, however, he, without the smallest warrant, excludes this from the list of pos- sible hypotheses. He says that we cannot infer a reality from a mental representation, unless we already know the reality independently of the mental representation. Now he could hardly help being aware that this is the very matter in dispute. Those who hold the opinion he argues against, do not admit the premise upon which he argues. They say that we may be, and are, necessitated to infer a cause, of which we know nothing whatever except its effect. And why not ? Sir W. Hamilton ON THE BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 203 thinks us entitled to infer a substance from attributes, though he allows that we know nothing of the substance except its attributes. But this is not the worst, and there are few specimens of our author in which his deficiencies as a philosopher stand out in a stronger light. As Burke in politics, so Sir W. Hamilton in metaphysics, was too often a polemic rather than a connected thinker : the generali- zations of both, often extremely valuable, seem less the matured convictions of a scientific mind, than weapons snatched up for the service of a particular quarrel. If Sir W. Hamilton can only seize upon something which will strike a hard blow at an opponent, he seldom troubles himself how much of his own edifice may be knocked down by the shock. Had he examined the argument he here uses, sufficiently to determine whether he could stand by it as a deliberate opinion, he would have perceived that it committed him to the doctrine that there is no such thing as representative knowledge. But it is one of Sir W. Hamilton's most positive tenets that there is representative knowledge, and that Memory, among other things, is an example of it. Let us turn back to his discussion of that subject, and see what he, at that time, considered representative knowledge to be. "Every act,* and consequently every act of know- " ledge, exists only as it now exists ; and as it exists " only in the Now, it can be cognizant only of a now- " existent object. But the object known in memory is, " ex hypothesi, past ; consequently, we are reduced to " the dilemma, either of refusing a past object to be \ " known in memory at all, or of admitting it to be only 1 " mediately known, in and through a present object. / " That the latter alternative is the true one, it will ] " require a very few explanatory words to convince you. " What am the contents of an act of memory ? An act " of memory is merely a present state of mind which we ' " are conscious of not as absolute, but as relative to, and " representing, another state of mind, and accompanied with * Lectures, i. -219, 220. 204 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S REVIEW OF THEORIES .vv^it- 1 ***$** y >r 1 ' t^'u ^ ^^ >"%. ^ ^ " the belief that the state of mind, as now represented has " actually been. I remember an event I saw the land- " ing of George IV. at Leith. This remembrance is " only a consciousness of certain imaginations, involving " the conviction that these imaginations now represent ideally " what I formerly really experienced. All that is imme- " diately known in the act of memory, is the present " mental modification, that is, the representation and " concomitant belief. Beyond this mental modification " we know nothing; and this mental modification is not " only known to consciousness, but only exists in and " by consciousness. Of any past object, real or ideal, the " mind knows and can know nothing, for, ex hypothesi, no " such object now exists ; or if it be said to know such " an object, it can only be said to know it mediately, as " represented in the present mental modification. Properly " speaking, however, wel^now only the actual and pre- " sent, and all real knowledge is an immediate know- " ledge. What is said to be mediately known, is, in " truth not known to be, but only believed to be : for " its existence is only an inference resting on the belief, that " the mental modification truly represents what is in itself " beyond the sphere of knoivledge." Had Sir W. Hamilton totally forgotten all this, when a few lectures afterwards, having then in front of him a set of antagonists who needed the theory here laid down, he repudiated it denying altogether the possi- bility of the mental state so truly and clearly expressed in this passage, and affirming that we cannot possibly recognise a mental modification to be representative of something else, unless we have a present knowledge of that something else, otherwise obtained ? With merely the alteration of putting instead of a past state of mind, a present external object, the Cosmothetic Idealists might borrow his language down to the minutest detail. They, too, believe that the mental modification is a pre- sent state of mind, which we are conscious of, not as absolute, but as relative to, and representing, " an ex- " ternal object, and accompanied with the belief that jK ON THE BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 205 " the object as now represented, actually" is : that we know something (viz. matter) only " as represented in " the present mental modification," and that " its exis- " tence is only an inference, resting on the belief that " the mental modification truly represents what is in " itself beyond the sphere of knowledge." They do not, strictly speaking, require quite so much as this : for the word " represents," especially with " truly" joined to it, suggest the idea of a resemblance, such as does, in reality, exist between the picture of a fact in memory, and the present impression to which it corresponds ; but the Cosmothetic Idealists only maintain that the mental modification arises from something, and that the reality of this unknown something is testified by a natural belief. That they apply to one case the same theory which our author applies to another, does not, of course, prove them to be right ; but it proves the suicidal character (to use one of his favourite expressions) of our author's argument, when he scouts the supposition of an instinctive inference from a known effect to an un- known cause,, as an hypothesis which can in no possible case be legitimate ; forgetful that its legitimacy is re- quired by his own psychology, one of the leading doc- trines of which is entirely grounded on it. It is not only in treating of Memory, that Sir W. Hamilton requires a process of thought precisely similar '-. - to that which, when employed by opponents, he declares &t signified, and creates the belief of " iE + " It is by one particular principle of our con- " stitution that certain features express anger ; and by " another particular principle, that certain features ex- " press benevolence. It is, in like manner, by one parti " cular principle of our constitution that a certain sensa- " tion signifies hardness in the body which I handle ; " and it is by another particular principle that a certain " sensation signifies motion in that body." * Inquiry into the Human Mind, Works, p. 131. f Ibid. p. 188. J Ibid. pp. 19-i, lyd. Ibid. p. 195. 218 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S REVIEW OF THEORIES I doubt if it would be possible to extract from Brown himself an equal number of passages expressing as clearly and positively, and in terms as irreconcilable with any other opinion, the doctrine which our author terms the third form of Cosmothetic Idealism ; in the exact shape, too, in which Brown held it, unencumbered by the gratuitous addition which Sir W. Hamilton fastens on him, that the sign must " truly represent " the thing signified, a notion which Reid takes good care that he shall not be supposed to entertain, since he repeatedly declares that there is no resemblance be- tween them. That Reid, at least when he wrote the Inquiry, was a Cosmothetic Idealist ; that up to that time it had never occurred to him that the convictions of the existence and qualities of external objects could be regarded as anything but suggestions by, and con- clusions from, our sensations is too obvious to be questioned by any one who has the text fresh in his recollection. Accordingly Sir W. Hamilton acknow- ledges as much in his edition of Reid, both in the foot- notes and in the appended Dissertations. After restating his own doctrine, that our natural beliefs assure us of outward objects, only by assuring us that we are imme- diately conscious of them, he adds,* "Reid himself seems " to have become obscurely aware of this condition : and " though he never retracted his doctrine concerning the " mere suggestion of extension, we find in his Essays on " the Intellectual Powers assertions in regard to the " immediate perception of external things, which would " tend to show that his later views were more in unison " with the necessary convictions of mankind." And in another placef he says of the doctrine maintained by Reid " in his earlier work," that it is one which " if he " did not formally retract in his later writings, he did " not continue to profess." It is hard that Brown should be charged with blundering to a degree which is " por- tentous' 7 and " without a parallel in the whole history of philosophy," for attributing to Reid an opinion which * Foot-note to Reid, p. 129. f Dissertations on Reid, p. 821. /tCC Of W{ yrguft ' ^.p ON THE BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 219 Sir W. Hamilton confesses that Reid maintained in one of his only two important writings, and did not retract in the other. But Sir W. Hamilton is still more wrong than he confesses. He is in a mistake when he sa}-s that Reid, though he did not retract the opinion, did not continue to profess it. For some reason, not apparent, \ he did cease to employ the word Suggestion. But he / continued to use terms equivalent to it. " Every dif- " ferent perception is conjoined with a sensation that is \ " proper to it. The one is the sign, the other the thing ! " signified."* " I touch the table gently with my hand, j " and I feel it to be smooth, hard, and cold. These are " qualities of the table perceived by touch: but I perceive " them by means of a sensation which indicates them/'f " Observing that the agreeable sensation is raised when " the rose is near, and ceases when it is removed, I am " led by my nature to conclude some quality to be in the " rose, which is the cause of this sensation. This quality " in the rose is the object perceived ; and that act of my " mind by which I have the conviction andbelief of this " quality, is what in this case I call perception. "J Of this passage even Sir W. Hamilton honestly says in a foot-note, that it " appears to be an explicit disavowal of the doctrine of an intuitive or immediate perception." Again : " When a primary quality is perceived, ihe sen- " sation immediately leads our thought to ike quality signified " by it, and is itself forgot. . . . The sensations belonging " to primary qualities . . . carry the thought to the ex- " ternal object, and immediately disappear and are forgot. " Nature intended them only as signs; and when they have " served that purpose they vanish." " Nature has con- " nected our perception of external objects with certain " sensations. If the sensation is produced, the corresponding " perception follows, even when there is no object, and in "that case is apt to deceive us."|| "In perception, " whether original or acquired, there is something which " may be called the sign, and something which is signified * Essays on the Intellectual Powers, Works, p. 312. f Ibid. p. 311. J Ibid. p. 310. Ibid. p. 315, |1 Ibid. p. 320. Xf 220 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S REVIEW OF THEORIES " to us, or brought to our knowledge by that sign. In " original perception, the signs are the various sensations " which are produced by the impressions made upon our " organs. The things signified are the objects perceived " in consequence of those sensations, by the original " constitution of our nature. Thus, when I grasp an " ivory ball in my hand, I have a certain sensation of " touch. Although this sensation be in the mind, and " have no similitude to anything material ; yet, by the " laws of my constitution, it is immediately followed by the " conception and belief, that there is in my band a hard " smooth body of a spherical figure, and about an inch " and a half in diameter. This belief is grounded neither " upon reasoning, nor upon experience ; it is the imme- " diate effect of my constitution, and this I call original " perception."* All these are as unequivocal, and the last passage as full and precise a statement of Cosmothetic Idealism, as any in the Inquiry. In the Dissertations appended to Beid,f Sir W. Hamilton, who never fails in candour, acknowledges in the fullest manner the inferences which may be drawn from passages like these, but thinks that they are balanced by others which " seem to harmonize " exclusively with the conditions of natural presenta- " tionism/'j and on the whole is decidedly of opinion " that, as the great end the governing principle of Beid's " doctrine was to reconcile philosophy with the neces- " sary convictions of mankind, he intended a doctrine 11 of natural, consequently a doctrine of presentative, " realism ; and that he would have at once surrendered " as erroneous, every statement which was found at " variance with such a doctrine." But it is clear that the doctrine of perception through natural signs did not, in Beid's opinion, contradict " the necessary convictions of mankind ;" being brought into harmony with them by his doctrine, that the signs, after they have served * Essays on the Intellectual Powers, p. 332. f Dissertations on Eeid, pp. 819-824 and 882-885. J Ibid. p. 882. Ibid. p. 820. ON THE BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 221 their purpose, are "forgot," which, as he conclusively shows in many places, it was both natural and inevitable that they should be. The passages which Sir W. Hamilton cites as inconsistent with any doctrine but Natural Realism, are those in which Reid affirms that we perceive objects immediately, and that the external things which really exist are the very ones which we perceive. But Reid evidently did not think these expressions inconsistent with the doctrine that the notion and belief of external objects are irresistibly suggested through natural signs. Having this notion and belief irresistibly suggested, is what he means by perceiving the external object. He says so in more than one of the passages I have just quoted : and neither in his chapter on Perception, nor anywhere else, does he speak of perception as implying anything more. In that chapter he says,* " If we attend to that act of our mind " which we call the perception of an external object of " sense, we shall tind in it these three things : First. 0) " some conception or notion of the object perceived ; " Secondly, a strong and irresistible conviction and belief " of its present existence ; and, Thirdly, that this con- ' viction and belief are immediate, and not the effect of " reasoning." We see in this as in a hundred other places, what Reid meant when he said that our perception ot outward objects is immediate. He did not mean that it is not a conviction suggested by something else, but only that the conviction is not the effect of reasoning, "This convictionf is not only irresistible, but it ig " immediate ; that is, it is not by a train of reasoning " and argumentation that we come to be convinced oi - " the existence of what we perceive." As Nature has ' given us the signs, so it is by an original law of our nature that we are enabled to interpret them. When Reid means anything but this in contending for an immediate perception of objects, he merely means to deny that it takes place through an image in the brain * Essays on the Intellectual Powers, Essay ii. chap. v. p. 258. f Same Essay, p. 259. 2.22 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S REVIEW OF THEORIES or in the mind, as maintained by Cosmothetic Idealists of the first or the second class. The only plausible argument produced by Sir W. Hamilton in proof of Reid's Natural Realism, and against his having held, as Brown thought, Brown's own opinion, is, that when in the speculations of Arnauld he had before him exactly the same opinion, he failed to recognise it.* But on a careful examination of Reid's criticism on Arnauld, it will be seen, that as long as Reid had to do with Arnauld's direct statement of his opinion, he found nothing in it different from his own ; but was puzzled, and thought that Arnauld attempted to unite inconsistent opinions, because, after throwing over the "ideal theory," and saying that the only real ideas are our perceptions, he maintained that it is still true, in a sense, that we do not perceive things directly, but through our ideas. What ! asks Reid, do we perceive things through our perceptions ? But if we merely put the word sensations instead of perceptions,*the doctrine is exactly that of Reid in the Inquiry that we perceive things through our sensations. Most probably Arnauld meant this, but was not so understood by Reid. If he meant anything else, his opinion was not the same as Reid's, and we need no explanation of Reid's not recog- nising it. One of the collateral indications that Reid's opinion agreed with Brown's, and not with Sir W. Hamilton's, is that in treating this question he seldom or never uses the word Knowledge, but only Belief. On Sir W. Hamilton's doctrine, the distinction between these two terms, however vaguely and mistily conceived by him, is indispensable. The total absence of any recognition of it in Reid, Allows that of the two opinions, if there was one which he had never conceived the possibility of, it was not Brown's, as Sir W. Hamilton supposes, but Sir W. Hamilton's. In our author's mind this indica- * Same Essay, chap. xiii. For Sir W. Hamilton's remarks, see Lectures, ii. 50-53 ; Discussions, pp. 75-77 ; and Dissertations on Keid, p. 823. ON THE BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 223 tion ought to have decided the question: for in the case of another philosopher he, on precisely the same evidence, brings in a verdict of Cosmothetic Idealism. Krug's system, he says,* as first promulgated, " was, " like Kant's, a mere Cosmothetic Idealism ; for while " he allowed a knowledge of the internal world, he only " allowed a belief of the external." It is true, Reid did not believe in what onr author terms "representative perception," if by this be meant perception through an image in the mind, supposed, like the picture of a fact in memory, to be like its original. But neither (as I have repeatedly observed) did Brown. What Brown held was exactly the doctrine of Reid in * the passages that I have extracted. He thought that IS. certain sensations, irresistibly, and by a law of our nature, suggest, without any process of reasoning, and without the intervention of any tertium quid, the notion .of something external, and an invincible belief in its real existence. If representative perception be this, both Reid and Brown believed in it : if anything else, Brown believed in it no more than Reid. Not only was Reid a Cosmothetic Idealist of Brown's exact type, but in stating his own doctrine, he has furnished, as far as I am aware, the clearest and best statement extant of their common opinion. They differed, indeed, as to our having, in this or in any other manner, an intuitive perception of any of the attributes of objects ; Reid, like Sir W. Hamilton, affirming, while Brown denied, that we have a direct intuition of the Primary Qualities of bodies. But Brown did not deny, nor would Sir W. Hamilton accuse him of denying, the wide difference between his opinion and Reid's on this latter point. Before closing this chapter, I will notice the curious fact, that after insisting with so much emphasis upon the recognition of an Ego and a Non-ego as an element in all consciousness, Sir W. Hamilton is obliged to admit that the distinction is in certain cases a mistake, and that our consciousness sometimes recognises a Non-ego * Dissertations on Reid, p. 797. 224 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S REVIEW OF THEORIES. where there is only an Ego. It is a doctrine of his, repeated in many parts of his works, that in our internal consciousness there is no non-ego. Even the remem- brance of a past fact, or the mental image of an absent object, is not a thing separable or distinguishable from the mind's act in remembering, but is another name for that act itself. Now it is certain, that in thinking of an absent or an imaginary object, we naturally imagine ourselves to be thinking of an objective something, dis- tinguishable from the thinking act. Sir W. Hamilton, being obliged to acknowledge this, resolves the difficulty in the very manner for which he so often rebukes other thinkers by representing this apparent testimony of consciousness as a kind of illusion. " The object," he says,* " is in this case given as really identical with the " conscious ego, but still consciousness distinguishes it, c< as an accident from the ego, as the subject of that " accident : it projects, as it were, this subjective phae- " nomenon from itself, views it at a distance, in a " word, objectifies it." But if, in one-half of the domain of consciousness the internal half it is in the power of consciousness to " project " out of itself what is merely one of its own acts, and regard it as external and a non- ego, why are those accused of declaring consciousness a lie, who think that this may possibly be the case with the other half of its domain also, and that the non-ego altogether may be but a mode in which the mind repre- sents to itself the possible modifications of the ego ? How the truth stands in respect to this matter I will endeavour, in the following chapter, to investigate. For the present, I content myself with asking, why the same liberty in the interpretation of Consciousness, which Sir W. Hamilton's own doctrine cannot dispense with, should be held to be an insurmountable objection to the counter doctrine. * Lectures, ii. 432. 225 CHAPTER XI. THE PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY OF THE BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. WE have seen Sir W. Hamilton at work on the question of the reality of Matter, by the introspective method, and, as it seems, with little result. Let us now approach the same subject by the psychological. I proceed, therefore, to state the case of those who hold that the belief in an external world is not intuitive, but an acquired product. This theory postulates the following psychological truths, all of which are proved by experience, arid are not contested, though their force is seldom adequately felt, by Sir W. Hamilton and the other thinkers of the introspective school. It postulates, first, that the human mind is capable of Expectation. In other words, that after having had actual sensations, we are capable of forming the concep- tion of Possible sensations ; sensations which we are not feeling at the present moment, but which we might feel, and should feel if certain conditions were present, the nature of which conditions we' have, in many cases, learnt by experience. It postulates, secondly, the laws of the Association of Ideas. So far as we are here concerned, these laws are the following: 1st. Similar phaenomena tend to bethought of together. 2nd. Phenomena which have either been experienced or conceived in close contiguity to one another, tend to be thought of together. The conti- guity is of two kinds ; simultaneity, and immediate succession. Facts which have been experienced or 226 THE PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY OF THE thought of simultaneously, recall the thought of one another. Of facts which have been experienced or thought of in immediate succession, the antecedent, or the thought of it, recalls the thought of the consequent, bat not conversely. 3rd. Associations produced by contiguity become more certain and rapid by repetition. When two phenomena have been very often experienced j in conjunction, and have not, in any single instance, occurred separately either in experience or in thought, there is produced between them what has been called Inseparable, or less correctly, Indissoluble Association : by which is not meant that the association must inevitably last to the end of life that no subsequent experience or process of thought can possibly avail to dissolve it ; but only that as long as no such experience or process of thought has taken place, the association is irresistible ; it is impossible for us to think the one thing disjoined j from the other. 4th. When an association has acquired this character of inseparability when the bond between the two ideas has been thus firmly riveted, not only does the idea called up by association become, in our consciousness, inseparable from the idea which suggested it, but the facts or phsenomena answering to those ideas come at last to seem inseparable in existence : things which we are unable to conceive apart, appear incapable of existing apart ; and the belief we have in their co- existence, though really a product of experience, seems intuitive. Innumerable examples might be given of this law. One of the most familiar, as well as the most striking, is that of our acquired perceptions of sight. Even those who, with Mr. Bailey, consider the percep- tion of distance by the eye as not acquired, but intuitive, admit that there are many perceptions of sight which, though instantaneous and unhesitating, are not intuitive. What we see is a very minute fragment of what we think we see. We see artificially that one thing is hard, another soft. We see artificially that one thing is hot, another cold. We see artificially that what we see is a book, or a stone, each of these being not merely an BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 227 inference, but a heap of inferences, from the signs which we see, to things not visible. We see, and cannot help seeing, what we have learnt to infer, even when we know that the inference is erroneous, and that the apparent perception is deceptive. We cannot help - seeing the moon larger when near the horizon, though * we know that she is of precisely her usual size. We cannot help seeing a mountain as nearer to us and of less height, when we see it through a more than ordi- narily transparent atmosphere. Setting out from these premises, the Psychological Theory maintains, that there are associations naturally and even necessarily generated by the order of our sensations and of our reminiscences of sensation, which, supposing no intuition of an external world to have existed in consciousness, would inevitably generate the belief, and would cause it to be regarded as an intuition. What is it we mean, or what is it which leads us to say, that the objects we perceive are external to us, and not a part of our own thoughts ? We mean, that there is concerned in our perceptions something which exists when we are not thinking of it ; which existed before we had ever thought of it, and would exist if we were annihilated ; and further, that there exists things which we never saw, touched, or otherwise perceived, and things which never have been perceived by man. This i idea of something which is distinguished from our fleet- ing impressions by what, in Kantian language, is called Perdurability ; something which is fixed and the same, while our impressions vary ; something which exists whether we are aware of it or not, and which is always square (or of some other given figure) whether it appears to us square or round constitutes altogether our idea . of external substance. Whoever can assign an origin to this complex conception, has accounted for what we mean by the belief in matter. Now all this, according \ to the Psychological Theory, is but the form impres>.- t by the known laws of association, upon the conception or notion, obtained by experience, of Contingent Sensa 228 THE PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY OF THE tions ; by which are meant, sensations that are not in our present consciousness, and individually never were in our consciousness at all, but which in virtue of the laws to which we have learnt by experience that our sensations are subject, we know that we should have felt under given supposable circumstances, and under these same circumstances, might still feel. I see a piece of white paper on a table. I go into another room. If the phenomenon always followed me, or if, when it did not follow me, I believed it to dis- appear e rerum naturd, I should not believe it to be an external object. I should consider it as a phantom a mere affection of my senses : I should not believe that there had been any Body there. But, though I have ceased to see it, I am persuaded that the paper is still there. I no longer have the sensations which it gave me ; but I believe that when I again place myself in the circumstances in which I had those sensations, that is, when I go again into the room, I shall again have them ; and further, that there has been no intervening moment at which this would not have been the case. Owing to this property of my mind, my conception of the world at any given instant consists, in only a small proportion, of present sensations. Of these I may at the time have none at all, and they are in any case a most insignificant portion of the whole which I appre- hend. The conception I form of the world existing at any moment, comprises, along with the sensations I am feeling, a countless variety of possibilities of sensation : namely, the whole of those which past observation tells me that I could, under any supposable circumstances, experience at this moment, together with an indefinite and illimitable multitude of others which though I do not know that I could, yet it is possible that 1 might, experience in circumstances not known to me. These various possibilities are the important thing to me in the world. My present sensations are generally of little importance, and are moreover fugitive : the possibilities, on the contrary, are permanent, which is the character BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 229 that mainly distinguishes our idea of Substance or Matter from our notion of sensation. These possibilities, which are conditional certainties, need a special name to distinguish them from mere vague possibilities, which experience gives no warrant for reckoning upon. Now, \ as soon as a distinguishing name is given, though it be only to the same thing regarded in a different aspect, one of the most familiar experiences of our mental nature teaches us, that the different name comes to be considered as the name of a different thing. There is another important peculiarity of these certi- fied or guaranteed possibilities of sensation ; namely, that they have reference, not to single sensations, but to sensations joined together in groups. When we think of anything as a material substance, or body, we either have had, or we think that on some given supposition we should have, not some one sensation, but a great and even an indefinite number and variety of sensations, generally belonging to different senses, but so linked together, that the presence of one announces the possible presence at the very same instant of any or all of the rest. In our mind, therefore, not only is this particular Possibility of sensation invested with the quality of permanence when we are not actually feeling any of the sensations at all ; but when we are feeling some of them, the remaining sensations of the group are conceived by us in the form of Present Possibilities, which might be realized at the very moment. And as this happens in turn to all of them, the group as a whole presents itself to the mind as permanent, in contrast not solely with the temporal iness of my bodily presence, but also with the temporary character of each of the sensations composing the group ; in other words, as a kind of permanent substratum, under a set of passing experiences or manifestations : which is another leading character of our idea of substance or matter, as distinguished from sensation. Let us now take into consideration another of the general characters of our experience, namely, that in 230 THE PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY OF THE . addition to fixed groups, we also recognise a fixed Order in our sensations ; an Order of succession, which, when ascertained by observation, gives rise to the ideas of Cause and Effect, according to what T hold to be the true^ theory of that relation, and is on any theory the source of all our knowledge what causes produce what effects. Now, of what nature is this fixed order among our sensa- tions ? It is a constancy of antecedence and sequence. But the constant antecedence and sequence do not generally exist between one actual sensation and another. Very few such sequences are presented to us by experience. In almost all the constant sequences which occur in Nature, the antecedence and consequence do not obtain between sensations, but between the groups we have been speaking about, of which a ver}'- small portion is actual sensation, the greater part being permanent pos- sibilities of sensation, evidenced to us by a small and variable number of sensations actually present. Hence, our ideas of causation, power, activity, do not become connected in thought with our sensations as actual at all, save in the few physiological cases where these figure by themselves as the antecedents in some uniform sequence. Those ideas become connected, not with sensations, but with groups of possibilities of sensation. The sensations conceived do not, to our habitual thoughts, present themselves as sensations actually experienced, inasmuch as not only any one or any number of them may be supposed absent, but none of them need be present. We find that the modifications which are taking place more or less regularly in our possibilities of sensation, are mostly quite independent of our conscious- ness, and of our presence or absence. Whether we are asleep or awake the fire goes out, and puts an end to one particular possibility of warmth and light. Whether we are present or absent the corn ripens, and brings a new possibility of food. Hence we speedily learn to think of Nature as made up solely of these groups of possibilities, and the active force in Nature as manifested in the modification of some of these by others. The BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 231 sensations, though the original foundation of the whole, come to be looked upon as a sort of accident depending on us, and the possibilities as much more real than the actual sensations, nay, as the very realities of which these are only the representations, appearances, or effects. When this state of mind has been arrived at, then, and from that time forward, we are never conscious of a present sensation without instantaneously referring it to some one of the groups of possibilities into which a sensation of that particular description enters; and if we do not yet know to what group to refer it, we at least feel an irresistible conviction that it must belong to some group or other; i.e. that its presence proves the existence, here and now, of a great number and variety of possibilities of sensation, without which it would not have been. The whole set of sensations as possible, form a permanent background to any one or more of them that are, at a given moment, actual ; and the possibilities are conceived as standing to the actual sensations in the relation of a cause to its effects, or of canvas to the figures painted on it, or of a root to the trunk, leaves, and flowers, or of a substratum to that which is spread over it, or, in transcendental language, of Matter to Form. When this point has been reached, the Permanent Possibilities in question have assumed such unlikeness of aspect, and such difference of apparent relation to us, from any sensations, that it would be contrary to all we know of the constitution of human nature that they should not be conceived as, and believed to be, at least as different from sensations as sensations are from one another. Their groundwork in sensation is forgotten, and they are supposed to be something intrinsically dis- tinct from it. We can withdraw ourselves from any of our (external) sensations, or we can be withdrawn from them by some other agency. But though the sensations cease, the possibilities remain in existence; they are independent of our will, our presence, and everything which belongs to us. We find, too, that they belong as 232 THE PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY OF THE r much to other human or sentient beings as to ourselves. We find other people grounding their expectations and ; conduct upon the same permanent possibilities on which we ground ours. But we do not find them experiencing the same actual sensations. Other people do not have our sensations exactly when and as we have them : but they have our possibilities of sensation ; whatever indi- cates a present possibility of sensations to ourselves, in- dicates a present possibility of similar sensations to them, except so far as their organs of sensation may vary j from the type of ours. This puts the final seal to our conception of the groups of possibilities as the funda- mental reality in Nature. The permanent possibilities are common to us and to our fellow-creatures ; the actual sensations are not. That which other people become aware of when, and on the same grounds, as 1 do, seems more real to me than that which they do not know of unless I tell them. The world of Possible Sensations succeeding one another according to laws, is as much in other beings as it is in me ; it has therefore an existence ] outside me ; it is an External World. If this explanation of the origin and growth of the idea of Matter, or External Nature, contains nothing at variance with natural laws, it is at least an admissible \ supposition, that the element of Non-ego which Sir W. Hamilton regards as an original datum of consciousness, \. and which we certainly do find in what we now call our consciousness, may not be one of its primitive elements may not have existed at all in its first manifestations. But if this supposition be admissible, it ought, on Sir W. Hamilton's principles, to be received as true. The first of the laws laid down by him for the interpretation of Consciousness, the law (as he terms it) of Parcimony, forbids to suppose an original principle of our nature in order to account for phenomena which admit of possible explanation from known causes. If the supposed in- gredient of consciousness be one which might grow up (though we cannot prove that it did grow up) through later experience ; and if, when it had so grown up, it A" -^ y ' BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 233 would, by known laws of our nature, appear as completely intuitive as our sensations themselves ; we are bound, according to Sir W. Hamilton's and all sound philosophy, to assign to it that origin. Where there is a known cause adequate to account for a phseriomenon, there is no justification for ascribing it to an unknown one. And what evidence does Consciousness furnish of the intui- tiveness of an impression, except instantaneousness, apparent simplicity, and unconsciousness on our part of how the impression came into our minds ? These features can only prove the impression to be intuitive, on the hypothesis that there are no means of accounting for them otherwise. If they not only might, but naturally would, exist, even on the supposition that it is not intuitive, we must accept the conclusion to which we are led by the Psychological Method, and which the Introspective Method furnishes absolutely nothing to contradict. Matter, then, may be defined, a Permanent of Sensation. If I am asked, whether I believe in matter, I ask whether the questioner accepts this definition of it. If he does, I believe in matter : and so do all Berkeleians. In any other sense than this, I do not. But I affirm with confidence, that this con- ception of Matter includes the whole meaning attached to it by the common world, apart from philosophical, and sometimes from theological, theories. The reliance | of mankind on the real existence of visible and tangible objects, means reliance on the reality and permanence of Possibilities of visual and tactual sensations, when no such sensations are actually experienced. We are war- ranted in believing that this is the meaning of Matter in the minds of many of its most esteemed metaphysical champions, though they themselves would not admit as much : for example, of Ileid, Stewart, and Brown. For these three philosophers alleged that all mankind, in- cluding Berkeley and Hume, really believed in Matter, inasmuch as unless they did, they would not have turned aside to save themselves from running against a post. 234 THE PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY OF THE Now all which this man ceuvre really proved is, that they believed in Permanent Possibilities of Sensation. We have therefore the unintentional sanction of these three eminent defenders of the existence of matter, for affirming, that to believe in Permanent Possibilities of Sensation is believing in Matter. It is hardly necessary, after such authorities, to mention Dr. Johnson, or any one else who resorts to the argumentum. baculinum of knocking a stick against the ground. Sir W. Hamilton, a far subtler thinker than any of these, never reasons in this manner. He never supposes that a disbeliever in what he means by Matter, ought in consistency to act in any different mode from those who believe in it. He knew that the belief on which all the practical consequences depend, is the belief in Permanent Possibilities of Sensation, and that if nobody believed in a material universe in any other sense, life would go on exactly as it now does. He, however, did believe in more than this, but, I think, only because it had never occurred to him that mere Possibilities of Sensation could, to our artificial ized con- sciousness, present the character of objectivity which, as we have now shown, they not only can, but unless the known laws of the human mind were suspended, must necessarily, present. Perhaps it may be objected, that the very possibility of framing such a notion of Matter as Sir W. Hamilton's the capacity in the human mind of imagining an external world which is anything more than what the Psychological Theory makes it amounts to a disproof of the theory. If (it may be said) we had no revelation in consciousness, of a world which is not in some way or other identified with sensation, we should be unable to have the notion of such a world. If the only ideas we had of external objects were ideas of our sensations, supplemented by an acquired notion of permanent pos- sibilities of sensation, we must (it is thought) be in- capable of conceiving, and therefore still more incapable of fancying that we perceive, things which are not sensations at all. it being evident however that some BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 235 philosophers believe this, and it being maintainable that the mass of mankind do so, the existence of a perdurable basis of sensations, distinct from sensations themselves, is proved, it might be said, by the possibility of believ- ing it. Let me first restate what I apprehend the belief to be. We believe that we perceive a something closely related to all our sensations, but different from those which we are feeling at any particular minute ; and distinguished from sensations altogether, by being permanent and always the same, while these are fugitive, variable, and alternately displace one another. But these attributes of the object of perception are properties belonging to all the possibilities of sensation which experience guarantees. The belief in such permanent possibilities seems to me to include all that is essential or characteristic in the belief in substance. I believe that Calcutta exists, though I do not perceive it, and that it would still exist if every percipient inhabitant were suddenly to leave the place, or be struck dead. But when I analyse the belief, all I find in it is, that were these events to take place, the Permanent Possibility of Sensation which I call Calcutta would still remain ; that if I were suddenly transported to the banks of the Hoogly, I should still have the sensa- tions which, if now present, would lead me to affirm that Calcutta exists here and now. We may infer, therefore, that both philosophers and the world at large, when they think of matter, conceive it really as a Permanent Possibility of Sensation. But the majority of philosophers fancy that it is something more ; and the world at large', though they have really, as I con- ceive, nothing in their minds but a Permanent Possibility of Sensation, would, if asked the question, undoubtedly agree with the philosophers : and though this is suf- ficiently explained by the tendency of the human mind to infer difference of things from difference of names, I acknowledge the obligation of showing how it can be possible to believe in an existence transcending all possibilities of sensation, unless on the hypothesis 236 THE PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY OF THE tli at such an existence actually is, and that we actually perceive it. The explanation, however, is not difficult. It is an admitted fact, that we are capable of all conceptions which can be formed by generalizing from the observed laws of our sensations. Whatever relation we find to exist between any one of our sensations and something different from it, that same relation we have no difficulty in conceiving to exist between the sum of all .our sensa- tions and something different from them. The differences which our consciousness recognises between one sensation and another, give us the general notion of difference, and inseparably associate with every sensation we have, the feeling of its being different from other things : and when once this association has been formed, we can no longer conceive anything, without being able, and even being compelled, to form also the conception of something dif- ferent from it. This familiarity with the idea of some- thing different from each thing we know, makes it natural and easy to form the notion of something different from all things that we know, collectively as well as indi- vidual!}'. It is true we can form no conception of what such a thing can be ; our notion of it is merely negative ; but the idea of a substance, apart from its relation to the impressions which we conceive it as making on our senses, is a merely negative one. There is thus no psychological, obstacle to our forming the notion of a something which is neither a sensation nor a possibility of sensation, even if our consciousness does not testily to it ; and nothing is more likely than that the Perma- nent Possibilities of sensation, to which our conscious- ness does testify, should be confounded in our minds with this imaginary conception. All experience attests the strength of the tendency to mistake mental abstrac- tions, even negative ones, lor substantive realities ; and the Permanent Possibilities of sensation which experience guarantees, are so extremely unlike in many of their properties to actual sensations, that since we are capable of imagining something which transcends sensation, BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 237 there is a great natural probability that we should suppose these to be it. But this natural probability is converted into certainty, when we take into consideration that universal law of our experience which is termed the law of Causation, and which makes us mentally connect with the beginning of everything, some antecedent condition, or Cause. The case of Causation is one of the most marked of all the cases in which we extend to the sum total of our conscious- ness, a notion derived from its parts. It is a striking example of our power to conceive, and our tendency to believe, that a relation which subsists between every individual item of our experience and some other item, subsists also between our experience as a whole, and something not within the sphere of experience. By this extension to the sum of all our experiences, of the internal relations obtaining between its several parts, we are led to consider sensation itself the aggregate whole of our sensations as deriving its origin from antecedent existences transcending sensation. That we should do this, is a consequence of the particular character of the uniform sequences, which experience discloses to us among our sensations. As already remarked, the con- stant antecedent of a sensation is seldom another sensa- tion, or set of sensations, actually felt. It is much oftener the existence of a group of possibilities, not necessarily including any actual sensations, except such as are required to show that the possibilities are really present. Nor are actual sensations indispensable even for this purpose ; for the presence of the object (which is nothing more than the immediate presence of the possibilities) may be made known to us by the very sensation which we refer to it as its effect. Thus, the real antecedent of an effect the only antecedent which, being invariable and unconditional, we consider to be the cause may be, not any sensation really felt, but solely the presence, at that or the immediately preceding moment, of a group of possibilities of sensation Hence it is not with sensations as actually experienced, but 238 THE PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY OF THE with their Permanent Possibilities, that the idea of Cause comes to be identified : and we, by one and the same process, acquire the habit of regarding Sensation in general, like all our individual sensations, as an Effect, and also that of conceiving as the causes of most of our individual sensations, not other sensations, but general possibilities of sensation. If all these considerations put together do not completely explain and account for our conceiving these Possibilities as a class of independent and substantive entities, I know not what psychological analysis can be conclusive. It may perhaps be said, that the preceding theory gives, indeed, some account of the idea of Permanent Existence which forms part of our conception of matter, but gives no explanation of our believing these per- manent objects to be external, or out of ourselves. I apprehend, on the contrary, that the very idea of any- thing out of ourselves is derived solely from the know- ledge experience gives us of the Permanent Possibilities. Our sensations we carry with us wherever we go, and they never exist where we are not ; but when we change our place we do not carry away with us the Permanent Possibilities of Sensation : they remain until we return, or arise arid cease under conditions with which our presence has in general nothing to do. And more than all they are, and will be after we have ceased to feel, Per- manent Possibilities of sensation to other beings than ourselves. Thus our actual sensations and the per- manent possibilities of sensation, stand out in obtrusive contrast to one another : and when the idea of Cause has been acquired, and extended by generalization from the parts of our experience to its aggregate whole, nothing can be more natural than that the Permanent Possi- bilities should be classed by us as existences generically distinct from our sensations, but of which our sensations are the effect.* * My able American critic, Dr. H. B. Smith, contends through several pages (152-167 ,' that these facts afford no proofs that objects are external to us. I never pretended that they do. I am accounting tor our conceiving, BELIEF IN AN EXTERNAL WORLD. 239 The same theory which accounts for our ascribing to an aggregate of possibilities of sensation, a permanent existence which our sensations themselves do not possess, and consequently a greater reality than belongs to our sensations, also explains our attributing greater objec- tivity to the Primary Qualities of bodies than to the Secondary. For the sensations which correspond to what are called the Primary Qualities (as soon at least as we come to apprehend them by two senses, the eye as well as the touch) are always present when any part of the group is so. But colours, tastes, smells, and the like, being, in comparison, fugacious, are not, in the same degree, conceived as being always there, even when nobody is present to perceive them. The sensations answering to the Secondary Qualities are only occasional, those to the Primary, constant. The Secondary, more- over, vary with different persons, and with the temporary sensibility of our organs ; the Primary, when perceived at all, are, as far as we know, the same to all persons and &i all times. or representing to ourselves, the Permanent Possibilities as real objects external to us. I do not believe that the real externality to us of anything, except- other minds, is capable of proof. But the Permanent Possibilities are external to us in tne only sense we need care about ; they are not constructed by the mind itself, but merely recognised by it ; in Kantian language, they are given to us, and to other beings in common with us. Men cannot act, cannot live," says Professor Fraser (p. 26), " without' ' assuming an external world, in some conception of the term external. ' It is the business of the philosopher to explain what that conception \ ' ought to be. For ourselves we can conceive only (1) An externality to ' our present and transient experience in our own possible experience past ' and future, and (2) An externality to our own conscious experience, in ' the contemporaneous, as well as in the past or future experience of other [ ' minds." The view I take of externality, in the sense in which I acknow- ledge it as real, could not be more accurately expressed than in Professor Fraser's words. Dr. Smith's criticisms continually go wide of the mark because he has somehow imagined that I am defending, instead of attack- ing, the belief in Matter as an entity per se. As when he says (pp. 157- 158) that my reasoning assumes, contrary to my own opinion, " an "