hivj 
 
 
 iiPPiPiilPliv 
 
 i^ 1 
 
 
 l^.-'\''
 
 THE TEMPLE PRIMERS 
 
 A 
 HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 By 
 
 EDWARD JENKS, M.A. 
 
 Reader in Law to the University of Oxford 
 
 &c., &c.
 

 
 HISTORYPF 
 POLITICS 
 
 BY- EDWARD 
 JEnKSmA 
 
 i^OO^ Z^i^^Q t,L^^UBS> STREET 'JjOI^DOr^
 
 All rights reservft/
 
 THE I.IRRARY 
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA 
 
 SANTA BARBARA 
 
 PREFACE 
 
 Some ten years ago, Sir Frederick Pollock published a 
 valuable and interesting little book on the history of political 
 speculation.! But the author is not aware that any one has 
 yet attempted to summarize, in a brief, popular form, the 
 record of political action. It has occurred, therefore, to the 
 promoters of this Series, that such a summary might prove 
 interesting, if only by way of comparison. 
 
 These pages profess to give, then, a brief account of what 
 men have done, not of what they have thought^ in that im- 
 portant branch of human activity which we call Politics, or 
 the Art of Government. But if it should be objected, that 
 what men do is really always the outcome, more or less 
 perfect, of what they think, the answer is, that we recognize, 
 for practical purposes, a distinction between what the world, 
 in theory at least, believes to be best, and that which it 
 actually succeeds in achieving. And a comparison of the 
 two objects can hardly fail to be instructive. 
 
 ^ An Introduction to the History of the Science of Politics. By (Sir) 
 Frederick Pollock. London, 1890. A new edition has recently 
 been published.
 
 vi PREFACE 
 
 To the other, and inevitable objection, tliat it is impossible, 
 within the narrow limits of a popular sketch, to deal with 
 such a subject as the History of Politics, the author will 
 reply with the doctrine which, paradoxical as it may sound, 
 is yet maintained by very able writers, that the greater the 
 subject, the smaller the space in which it can be treated. 
 Readers who care to see parts of the subject worked out in 
 greater detail, may be referred to the author's Laau and 
 Politics in the Middle Jges (Murray, 1898). 
 
 Oxford, Januarij 1900
 
 CONTENTS 
 
 INTRODUCTORY 
 
 CHAP. 
 
 I. TYPES OF SOCIETY 
 
 PAGE 
 
 I 
 
 TYPE I.— SAVAGE SOCIETY 
 II. SAVAGE ORGANIZATION 
 
 TYPE II.— PATRIARCHAL SOCIETY 
 
 III. PATRIARCHAL SOCIETY IN GENERAL . 
 
 IV. THE DOMESTICATION OF ANIMALS 
 
 V. TRIBAL ORGANIZATION .... 
 VI. AGRICULTURE AND THE CLAN 
 VII. INDUSTRY AND THE GILD 
 
 15 
 22 
 
 43 
 
 60 
 
 TYPE III.— MODERN (POLITICAL) SOCIETY 
 
 VIII. THE STATE AND FEUDALISM 
 IX. EARLY POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS 
 X. THE STATE AND PROPERTY 
 
 71 
 
 81 
 
 93
 
 viii CONTENTS 
 
 CHAP. 
 
 XI. THE STATE AND JUSTICE 
 XII. THE STATE AND LEGISLATION 
 
 XIII. THE STATE AND ADMINISTRATION . 
 
 XIV. VARIETIES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 
 LIST OF AUTHORITIES . . . . 
 
 INDEX ...... 
 
 GLOSSARY . ....
 
 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 INTRODUCTORY 
 
 CHAPTER I 
 Types of Society 
 
 Politics, By Pol'Utcs we mean the business of Govern- 
 mentj that is to say, the control and management of people 
 living together in a society. A society, again, is a group or 
 mass of people, bound together by a certain common principle 
 or object, A mere chance crowd is not a society ; it has no 
 definite object, it collects and disperses at the whim of the 
 moment, its members recognize no duties towards one another. 
 It has no history, no organization. 
 
 Society. Societies are of many kinds. They may exist 
 for purposes of religion, commercial profit, amusement, educa- 
 tion, or a host of other objects. A good specimen of a 
 religious society is, of course, an ordinary church congrega- 
 tion, or a missionary society ; of a commercial society, an 
 ordinary trading company ; of an amusement society, a West- 
 end club ; of an educational society, an university or a college. 
 And the management and organization of any such society 
 may in strictness be considered a branch of Politics, But it 
 is convenient to reserve the term politics for matters concern- 
 ing one particular and very important class of societies, those 
 communities, namely, which are not formed for any special or 
 //WW objects, but which have grown up, almost spontaneously, 
 as part of the general history of mankind, and which are con- 
 cerned with its general interests. Men as a rule, live in these 
 
 B
 
 2 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 communities, not because they choose to do so, but because 
 they are born into them ; and, until quite recently, they were 
 not allowed to change them at their pleasure. In their most 
 advanced forms, we call these communities States ; Great 
 Britain, France, Holland, Germany, Spain, Russia, etc., are 
 undoubtedly States. And these States are the proper subject 
 matter of Politics, in the modern sense of the term. But, as 
 we study their history, we become aware that these com- 
 munities have gradually developed out of societies of quite 
 another type, organized on different principles. 
 
 Modern social groups. Now-a-days, the principle 
 which binds together these communities of the modern type, 
 is the tie of military allegiance. In the States which practise 
 conscription, or universal military service, this is very obvious. 
 The most heinous political offence which a Frenchman or a 
 German can commit, is attempting to evade military service ; 
 or, possibly worse, taking part in military service against his 
 own country. But even in Great Britain, where conscription 
 is not practised, the tie is really the same. It is unquestion- 
 able that the Queen, through her Ministers, has the right, in 
 case of necessity, to call upon every one of her male subjects 
 to render personal military service ; and any British subject 
 captured fighting against his country, would be liable to suffer 
 death as a traitor. In the older conditions of society, 
 however, to which allusion has been made, the tie was not 
 that of military allegiance, but kinship, which was at first, no 
 doubt, based on actual blood relationship, but was afterwards 
 extended by fictitious methods. To men living in such a 
 community, the inclusion of strangers in blood would have 
 appeared a monstrosity. The mere facts that these strangers 
 were settled in the same neighbourhood, or carried on trade 
 with the community in question, or even were willing to fight 
 its battles, would have seemed to such a community no argu- 
 ments at all for admitting them to membership. The most 
 conspicuous example in the world of a community organized 
 on such principles is, of course, the Jews, who, in spite of 
 their world-wide dispersal, still maintain intact their tribal
 
 TYPES OF SOCIETY 3 
 
 organization, at least in theory. The same ideas were at the 
 bottom of the famous struggle in early Roman history between 
 the patricians ^ and the plebeians ; and it is possible that some- 
 thing of the same kind may be unconsciously at the root of 
 the trouble between the Boers and the Uitlanders in the 
 Transvaal. The Welsh and the Irish before the Norman 
 Conquest, the Scottish Highlanders two or three centuries ago, 
 undoubtedly lived in communities of this type, which we may 
 call patriarchal, or tribal. 
 
 Still older groups. Until quite recently it was be- 
 lieved that this patriarchal type was the oldest type of 
 human community. Speculators on the history of society 
 started from the patriarchal household^ and worked down- 
 wards to the modern State. But the brilliant discoveries of 
 the last half century have revealed to us a still more primitive 
 type of society which, so far as the writer knows, has never 
 been described in a popular book, and which it takes some 
 considerable effort to realize, even when it is stated in the 
 simplest language. It is intensely interesting, both as adding 
 another whole province to the domain of scientific history, 
 and as revealing another step in the path by which man has 
 moved onward and upward. At present, too little is known 
 of its details to warrant more than a brief description ; but, 
 thanks to the labours of devoted students, who have faced 
 discomfort and hardship in order to examine this type of 
 society in its few surviving examples, the outlines are now 
 fairly clear. Unfortunately, it is hard to find a good name, 
 by which it may be distinguished. Its scientific name of 
 Totemistic is too elaborate and technical for popular use. 
 Perhaps it will be best to call it the savage type ; though it 
 must be clearly understood that the term implies neither con- 
 tempt nor blame. It merely signifies that the type in question 
 is Yery primitive or rudimentary. 
 
 Here then we have our three historical types of human 
 society — the savage , the patriarchal, and the military (or 
 "political" in the modern sense). And it will be the 
 
 ^ A " patrician " is one who has a " pater," or chief of kindred.
 
 4 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 business of A Short History of Politics to describe each of 
 them in turn, beginning with the oldest, and, if possible, to 
 point out the causes which led societies to abandon the older 
 for the newer types. To do this, we shall not require to 
 describe the histories of particular societies ; that will be the 
 task of other writers in the Series. But we shall endeavour to 
 trace a normal course for the development of societies, a course 
 which every community tends to follow, unless deflected from 
 its natural path by special circumstances. It is the fashion to 
 scoff at such attempts, and, doubtless, there is a danger in 
 ** general views." But there is, likewise, a danger in special- 
 ization ; and a man who uses the microscope only, loses the 
 treasures revealed by the telescope. It is a wise ideal of 
 study : to know something of everything, and everything of 
 something. 
 
 Our plan. But, if we start on a story of this kind, it is 
 quite evident that we must have something in the nature of a 
 plan. To plunge recklessly into the facts of universal history 
 would be to invite failure. To what pathway shall we trust 
 to bring us safely out of the forest ? 
 
 Institutions. There is a large part of the history of 
 every community which seems to leave no permanent traces 
 upon it. No doubt the results are there ; but they are too 
 vague and too subtle to be easily described. On the other 
 hand, the effects of other parts of the community's history are 
 plainly discernible, in the permanent and visible results which 
 they leave on the community itself. These results we call 
 institutions J i. e. the machinery by which the business of the 
 community is carried on. Perhaps it would be better to call 
 them limbs or organs of the community, for they resemble 
 natural growths far more than artificial creations. They 
 correspond in the body social with the limbs or organs of the 
 body natural, i. e. with those instruments by which the business 
 of the body — its absorption, digestion, defence, attack, etc., 
 are carried on. And so we use the metaphor organization, to 
 describe the development of institutions in the body social, or 
 community.
 
 TYPES OF SOCIETY 5 
 
 Their relative importance. These institutions may not 
 really be the most important part of the body social, any more 
 than the limbs and organs are the most important part of the 
 body natural. The really important thing in each is that 
 indefinable existence which we call life. But as no one has 
 yet succeeded in explaining what life is, even in the natural 
 body, still less in the social body, we shall be wiser to describe 
 the institutions of society, to show, if we can, how they 
 appeared, grew, and gradually changed, till they assumed the 
 shape in which we know them now. Only, as every fully 
 developed society has many kinds of institutions, political, 
 industrial, religious, educational, and so on, with all of which 
 it would be impossible to deal, we must remember that this 
 is a book on politics, and deals only, or chiefly, with those 
 institutions which are concerned directly with the business 
 of government. 
 
 This, then, will be the plan of our work : to describe, as 
 briefly and clearly as possible, the origin and development of the 
 institutions of government. 

 
 Type I. — Savage Society 
 
 CHAPTER II 
 
 Savage Organization 
 
 Savages* In spite of the constantly increasing intercourse 
 between the most remote parts of the world, and the civilizing 
 influences of commerce, there remain quite a considerable 
 number of peoples who still live under primitive or savage 
 conditions. Among them may be reckoned, the Andamanese 
 of the Bay of Bengal, the hill tribes of Madras, the Juangs of 
 Orissa, the Veddahs of Ceylon, the Bushmen and Akkas of 
 Africa, the Colorado Indians of North America, the Caribs 
 of the centre and the Brazilians of the south, the Dyaks 
 of Borneo, and the Eskimos of Greenland and Labrador. 
 The Tasmanians of Van Diemen's Land were, until their 
 recent extinction, perfect specimens of unadulterated savagery. 
 But by far the most important examples, because the most 
 remote from admixture and the most scientifically and 
 recently studied, are the aborigines ^ of Australia, who, in the 
 centre and north of that vast continent, still roam untouched 
 and unreclaimed. Their numbers are considerable, and, 
 though they are probably destined to disappear at no distant 
 date, they are at present in full possession of their primitive 
 organization. Owing to the praiseworthy efforts of a gener- 
 ation of students, prominent among them being Mr. A. W. 
 Howitt, the Rev. Lorimer Fison, Professor Baldwin Spencer, 
 
 1 The reader is cautioned that the term "Australian Native" is 
 by local custom reserved for the descendants of the white colonists, 
 and is rarely extended to the " blackfellow." 
 
 6
 
 SAVAGE ORGANIZATION 7 
 
 and Mr. Gillen, who have braved the hardships of the 
 Australian desert, and won their way into the confidence of 
 the savages by consistent kindness, we are now able to form 
 some tolerably correct ideas of savage life. Their accounts 
 may be profitably supplemented by the studies of the late Mr. 
 Lewis Morgan, who, in the Red Indians of America, found 
 a~people just emerging from savagery into the patriarchal stage 
 of society, and whose book on Ancient Society will ultimately 
 be recognized as one of the great scientific products of the 
 nineteenth century. 
 
 Savage life' The material side of Australian existence 
 may be best described in a series of negatives. The savages 
 understand neither the cultivation of the land nor the rearing 
 of sheep and cattle. Their only domestic animal (if "domestic" 
 it can be called) is the dog. They have no idea of dwellings 
 more advanced than a rude bough hut ; for the most part 
 they take shelter in caves, and behind pieces of bark propped 
 up against trees or rocks. They have no food but the scanty 
 game of the " bush " or forest, such as the wallaby and the 
 opossum, and the natural products of the earth. The art ot 
 fire-making, in a very primitive form, is known to them ; but 
 their notions of cooking are of the crudest. Still less have 
 they the knowledge of working in metals, either by hammer- 
 ing or by melting. The recently adopted iron tomahawk is 
 an article of barter, obtained from the enterprising traveller, 
 in exchange for natural products. The indigenous weapons 
 are the flint-headed spear and axe, and the wooden boomerang 
 or throwing-stick. Australian legends go back to a time 
 when even the use of stone knives was unknown, and opera- 
 tions, even on the human body, were performed with a charred 
 stick. The " pitchi " or bark-basket, and the digging-stick 
 of the women, appear to be almost the only articles which can 
 be classed as "tools." The clothing of the Australians may 
 be described as purely ornamental. It consists, in fact, of 
 certain decorations used in religious ceremonies ; in ordinary 
 life they are stark naked. The appalling feature of this 
 miserable existence, always bordering on starvation, is, that it
 
 8 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 seems to have gone on during countless ages. The fauna and 
 flora of Australia are, it is well known, of a thoroughly 
 archaic type ; the naturalist discovers in its forests and rivers 
 forms which have long since been extinct in other parts of the 
 world. And as there is no evidence whatever of any inter- 
 course between Australia and other lands during the period of 
 recorded history, as, in fact, Australia was, until three cen- 
 turies ago, an Unknown Land, we can only suppose that the 
 Australian has led his present life during thousands of years. 
 His isolation has been, no doubt, the chief cause of his 
 stagnation. 
 
 Savage Institutions. This view is entirely confirmed 
 by a study of the non-material side of Australian life. Crude 
 and primitive as it seems to us, its elaborateness of detail and 
 complexity of ceremonial point to a history of great, but un- 
 recorded, antiquity. When we consider the terror which all 
 novelty has for the savage, especially in religious matters, we 
 are bound to think that the elaborate ceremonies described in 
 Messrs. Spencer's and Gillen*s valuable book ^ must have taken 
 centuries, perhaps even thousands of years, to work out. 
 We may be very sure that no sudden change was made ; 
 but that only little by little was the elaborate ceremonial 
 introduced. We cannot here do more than describe its 
 leading features. 
 
 "Tribe'* or ** paclc,** It is the custom to speak of 
 the Australians and other savages as living in "tribes." 
 But the term is most misleading ; for the word " tribe " 
 always suggests to us the notion of descent from a common 
 ancestor, or, at any rate, of close blood relationship. Now 
 there Is, as we shall see, a most important stage in human 
 progress, in which descent from a common ancestor plays a 
 vital part in social organization. But the Australian " tribe " 
 does not really play a very important part in savage life, at 
 least on its social side. It appears to be mainly a group of 
 people engaged in hunting together, a co-operative or com- 
 munal society for the acquisition of food supply. It would 
 
 ^ The Native Trites of Central Australia. London, 1 899.
 
 SAVAGE ORGANIZATION 9 
 
 really be better to call it the " pack ; " for it far more 
 resembles a hunting than a social organization. All its 
 members are entitled to a share in the proceeds of the day*s 
 chase, and, quite naturally, they camp and live together. 
 But they are not sharply divided, for other purposes, from 
 other "packs" living in the neighbourhood. On the con- 
 trary, they frequently mingle with them ; and a social free- 
 masonry extends over vast areas of the continent. 
 
 Totem group. The real social unit of the Australians 
 is not the " tribe,'* but the tolem group. The word " totem ** 
 is not, of course, Australian ; ^ but it is generally accepted as 
 the name of an institution which is found almost universally 
 among savages. The totem group is, primarily, a body of 
 persons, distinguished by the sign of some natural object, such 
 as an animal or tree, who may not intermarry with one 
 another. In many cases, membership of the totem group 
 is settled by certain rules of inheritance, generally through 
 females. But among the Australians, new-born or (in some 
 cases) unborn infants are allotted by the wise men to par- 
 ticular totems ; and this arrangement has all the appearance 
 of extreme antiquity, for the savage has no idea of principles, 
 he requires hard and fast rules. 
 
 No marriage within the totem. The Australian 
 may not marry within his totem. " Snake may not marry 
 snake. Emu may not marry emu." That is the first rule 
 of savage social organization. Of its origin we have no 
 knowledge ; but there can be little doubt that its object was 
 to prevent the marriage of near relations. Though the 
 savage cannot argue on principles, he is capable of observing 
 facts. And the evils of close inbreeding must, one would 
 think, have ultimately forced themselves upon his notice. If 
 so, we can understand the rule, " Snake may not marry 
 snake." But this is conjecture. 
 
 Marriage with another totem. The other side of 
 the rule is equally startling. The savage may not marry 
 
 1 It seems to have been first used, in a slightly different form, by 
 the Ojibway Indians of North America.
 
 lo A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 within his totem, but he must marry into another totem 
 specially fixed for him. More than this, he not only marries 
 into the specified totem, but he marries the whole of the 
 women of that totem in his own generation. Thus, all the 
 men of the Snake totem are husbands of all the women of 
 the Emu totem in the same generation; and, as a natural con- 
 sequence, all the women of Snake totem are wives of all the 
 men of Emu totem. Of course, it must not be supposed, that 
 this condition of marital community really exists in practice. 
 As a matter of fact, each Australian contents himself with 
 one or two women from his marriage totem. But it is a fact, 
 that an Australian would see nothing wrong in a man living 
 as the husband of any woman of his marriage totem, provided 
 she were of his own generation. And if an Australian is 
 travelling from " tribe " to " tribe," he will, as a matter of 
 course, find a wife waiting for him in every " tribe " which 
 contains women of his marriage totem. It is facts such as 
 these which scandalized early missionaries, and often caused 
 them to shut their eyes to what was really a most valuable 
 object-lesson in social history. 
 
 No unmarried people. It will be obvious that, under 
 these arrangements, there are no bachelors or spinsters among 
 the Australian savages; but that, as Mr. Fison has well 
 observed, marriage is, among them, "a natural state into 
 which both parties are born.'* 
 
 Different generations. It has been hinted before, 
 that some classification is necessary to distinguish the different 
 degrees or generations within the totem group ; and this is 
 one of the objects of the mysterious corrohorees^ or ceremonial 
 gatherings, which play so large a part in the life of the 
 savage. Though it is extremely difficult, owing to the un- 
 willingness of savages to reveal the secrets of their rites, to 
 ascertain precisely the details of these ceremonies, it is fairly 
 clear that they serve more than one object. In the first 
 place, as was frankly admitted by an Australian mystery man 
 of repute, they effect the useful result of impressing the 
 ordinary members of the totem group with a sense of the
 
 SAVAGE ORGANIZATION n 
 
 importance and power of the "Birraark" or sorcerers, 
 usually old men, who conduct them. In the second, they un- 
 doubtedly seem to keep alive the legendary history of the totem 
 group, and thus to bind its members closer together. The 
 songs and dances of the ceremonies in many cases are supposed 
 to represent great events which have occurred in the " Al- 
 cheringa," or distant past. Finally, at the ceremonies, often 
 lasting for several days, the youths and maidens who have 
 attained to maturity are initiated into some of the mysteries 
 of the totem, often to the accompaniment of painful rites, 
 such as circumcision and other laceration. It is possible that, 
 on such occasions, the initiated are subjected to tattooing, with 
 a view of establishing their identity, and of allotting them to 
 a certain totem, and to a certain generation within that totem. 
 System of relationship. By this, or some other 
 artificial means, the curiously simple system of Australian 
 relationship is constructed. AH the women of his marriage 
 totem in his generation are a man's wives ; all their children 
 are his children ; all the members of his totem in the same 
 generation are his brothers and sisters (whom he may not 
 marry) ; all the members of his mother's totem are his parents 
 (for descent is nearly always reckoned through females). 
 Parent, child, brother, and sister are thus the only relationships 
 recognized. Rudimentary as this system appears to be, it is 
 widely spread throughout the Malay archipelago, and Mr. 
 Fison tells an amusing story of a missionary who, to increase 
 his familiarity with his native converts, was made by the pro- 
 cess of adoption the brother of his man-servant. Happening 
 to meet the man's wife, the missionary pleasantly explained 
 that he was now her brother. Whereupon the lady instantly 
 corrected him by saying — " Oh no, you are not my brother, 
 you are my husband." Mr. Morgan, indeed, who has studied 
 the natives of Hawaii and Honolulu, as well as his own Red 
 Indians, thinks that there are traces of still older systems, in 
 which marriage between brothers and sisters, and even between 
 lineal relations, was practised. Be this as it may, the Australian 
 system prevails widely among savages, and even, with certain
 
 12 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 modifications, among some highly civilized people, e. g, the 
 Chinese. 
 
 Totem questions. Whether the totem serves any 
 other purpose than that of prohibiting intermarriage of near 
 relations, and what is the precise connection which the savages 
 believe to exist between themselves and their totems, are much 
 disputed questions. With regard to the latter, it has been 
 suggested by recent observers, that the Australian believes 
 himself to be, in some mysterious way, the offspring of his 
 totem. There can also be little doubt that, in some cases at 
 least, the totem is an object of worship, a fetich which will 
 deal destruction if the rule of the intermarriage is not rigidly 
 observed. And, if this be so, we get an interesting glimpse 
 at the rudiments of two of the most powerful factors in human 
 progress — Religion and Lav/. It has been said that the 
 progress of religious ideas follows three stages. In the first, 
 Man worships some object entirely external to himself, a stone 
 or an animal. In the second, he worships a human being like 
 himself, usually one of his own ancestors. In the third, he 
 has risen to the idea of a God who is both divine and human, 
 unlike and distinct from himself, and yet like to and connected 
 with himself. The Australian totem would answer to the 
 first of these three stages. But it is somewhat significant to 
 notice, that the savage's view of his deity is usually that of a 
 malevolent Power, dealing disease and death, and thirsting for 
 human blood. It is to be feared that this view is largely the 
 reflection of the savage's only means of reasoning, viz. by 
 experience. He sees that any one of his fellows, who happens 
 to be exceptionally strong and clever, is apt to show his power 
 by the exercise of cruelty. He transfers this character to his 
 
 Savage Law. Closely connected with this viewt isThe 
 savage's rudimentary notion of Law. With him it is a purely 
 negative idea, a list of things which are prohibited, or taboo. 
 The origin of these prohibitions is often ludicrous, but they 
 are generally found to be connected with the apprehension of 
 danger. A man is walking along a path, and is struck by a
 
 SAVAGE ORGANIZATION 13 
 
 falling branch. Instead of attributing the blow to natural 
 causes, he assumes it to be the result of the anger of the Tree- 
 Spirit, offended by his action in using the path. In the future, 
 that path is taboo^ or forbidden. A rude log bridge is made 
 over a stream. It gives way beneath a passenger, and the man 
 is drowned. That (the savage thinks) is the vengeance of 
 the Water- Spirit, incensed at the insult offered by the exist- 
 ence of the bridge, which deprives him of his due number of 
 victims. But the convenience of the bridge is so great, that 
 men are tempted to build it again. And then a cunning man 
 suggests that, if a victim be sacrificed before the bridge is used, 
 the Water-Spirit will be satisfied. And so some poor wretch 
 is bound hand and foot and thrown into the torrent. Probably 
 the bridge is better built this time, and does not break. 
 The charm has worked. In such a way arises the notion 
 of sacrifice y which has played such a ghastly part in history. 
 Jacob Grimm, the great German scholar, found the practice 
 of bridge sacrifices in use in north-eastern Germany, happily 
 only in a mock form, as late as the beginning of the present 
 century. The practice of burying alive a victim in the found- 
 ations of a house, as a sacrifice to the Earth-Spirit, whose 
 domain is being invaded, is widely spread in savage countries. 
 Doubtless it had a similar origin. 
 
 Whether the totem bond also serves the purpose of uniting 
 its members together for offence and defence, is also a disputed 
 question. There are traces of such a state of things, and its 
 existence would certainly explain the development of a con- 
 spicuous feature of the second or patriarchal stage of society, 
 the blood-feud gxovL"^. But the relations of one group of savages 
 to another are obscure and uncertain. Doubtless the members 
 of a eroup, whether it be the " tribe " or hunting unit, or the 
 totemistic marriage group, do not recognize any duties towards 
 strangers. But their actual attitude is probably determined by 
 the state of the food supply, and the amount of elbow-room. 
 If game is abundant, and hunting-grounds large in proportion 
 to the population, distinct groups of savages may exist side 
 by side in a given area without conflict. But if game is
 
 14 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 scarce, and the land thickly peopled (in the savage state the 
 two things would probably go together), wars and murders 
 are, probably, frequent. Even the revolting practice of 
 cannibalism probably originated in hunger ; though there are 
 some races which seem unable to abandon it, even in times of 
 plenty, and plausible reasons are invented for its continuance. 
 But it is one of the surest laws of progress, that, with each 
 forward step, the same area is able to maintain an ever-increas- 
 ing number of people. And so, the temptations for war, or at 
 least the excuses for war, are happily ever diminishing. 
 
 Summary. It is a somewhat dark picture that we have 
 had to draw of the life of primitive man. And indeed the 
 noble savage, who passed his days in a sort of perpetual picnic, 
 surrounded by his family, who sported in the flowery meads 
 while he discoursed sweet music, was a last century fiction 
 which did more credit to the hearts than to the heads of an 
 unhistorical generation. The actual savage is usually a miser- 
 able, underfed, and undersized creature, naked and shivering, 
 houseless, in constant terror of dangers seen and unseen, with 
 no family ties as we understand them, with no certain food 
 supply, and no settled abode. And yet, even the savage life 
 contributes something to the total of civilization. The savage 
 hunter, dependent for his very existence on success in the 
 chase, learns to endure hardships without murmuring, in the 
 pursuit of his prey. Constantly on the look-out for danger, 
 he developes powers of observation which are the admiration 
 of his more civilized brother. He can trace the footsteps of 
 an enemy in a thicket, where a modern detective would declare 
 it impossible to read any sign. He can foretell the approach 
 of a storm from warnings which would escape a scientific 
 weather-prophet. He can hear sounds which to a civilized 
 man are simply inaudible. He has infinite patience, provided 
 only that the prospect of reward is palpable and immediate. 
 These are no mean contributions to the store of civilization.
 
 Type II. — Patriarchal Society 
 
 CHAPTER III 
 
 Patriarchal Society in General 
 
 Distinguishing features. We now approach the 
 consideration of the second stage of social development, 
 in which the binding ties are more distinctly marked, and 
 the organization more perfect, than in the preceding stage. 
 All patriarchal society is characterized by certain well- 
 marked features, which distinguish it from earlier as well as 
 from later types of society. These features are : — 
 
 1. Male Idnstllp, We saw that, in the savage type 
 of community, while something that might be called kinship 
 prevailed, it was so arbitrary and artificial, that it might be 
 regarded as a superstition rather than a fact. So far as there 
 was any recognition of blood relationship at all, it was relation- 
 ship through women, not through men. But, in the patriarchal 
 stage, paternity is the leading fact. Men are counted of kin 
 because they are descended from the same male ancestor. 
 Sometimes, no doubt, the relationship is fictitious rather than 
 real ; as when deficiencies in a family are made up by adoption 
 QV fosterage. But the very existence of such devices shows the 
 importance attached to descent through males. Leaving for 
 the present the question of how this important change came 
 about, we notice another feature of patriarchal society closely 
 connected with it. 
 
 2. Permanent marriage. Without such an addition,
 
 i6 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 the first feature could hardly develop. In a state of society 
 such as that of the Australians {^ante, p. lo), no one could 
 be certain who his father was. It is not until a woman 
 becomes the wife of one man only, that anything like cer- 
 tainty of fatherhood appears. But it must not be assumed 
 that marriage, as we understand it, /. e. permanent union of 
 one man with one woman, is a feature of all patriarchal 
 society. On the other hand, polygamy, i. e. the marriage of 
 one man to several women, is very characteristic of patriarchal 
 society in its earlier stages. Only in its later developments, 
 does it approach to the modern system of marriage. But the 
 existence oi polygamy is no bar to the recognition of kin- 
 ship through males ; on the contrary, it renders it increasingly 
 certain, by providing against a superfluity of unmarried women. 
 Finally, a third essential feature of patriarchal society must be 
 mentioned. 
 
 3. Paternal authority. The principles upon which 
 patriarchal society is conducted require, as we shall see, 
 the existence of groups presided over and controlled by the 
 well-nigh despotic ^authority of a male ancestor. This 
 ancestor controls, not only the business affairs of the group, 
 but its religion, and its conduct. He alone is responsible for 
 it, to the larger group of which it forms a part. The precise 
 limits of this authority differ in different stages. In early 
 Rome, as is well known, the patria potestas extended to all 
 the descendants of a living ancestor, no matter how old they 
 were, and even survived, in a modified form, over the female 
 descendants after his death. Moreover, it comprised even the 
 power of life and death, to say nothing of control and 
 chastisement. In later forms of the patriarchal system, this 
 power becomes greatly modified, but an interesting record of 
 Welsh society at the end of the patriarchal stage says of the 
 Mab, or youth under fourteen: (He is) "at his father's 
 platter, and his father lord over him, and he is to receive no 
 punishment but that of his father, and he is not to possess a 
 penny of his property during that time, only in common with
 
 PATRIARCHAL SOCIETY IN GENERAL 17 
 
 his father." In fact, for legal purposes, he has no separate 
 existence. 
 
 Actual examples. These are the universal features of 
 society in the patriarchal stage, whether we look at it among 
 Jewish tribes, or the early Greeks {e.g. the Homeric heroes) 
 or Romans, or among the Arabs of the desert, or the Hindus 
 and Mahommedans of Northern India, or the Afghans of the 
 frontier, or, better still, among our Teutonic forefathers in 
 their German homes, or, perhaps best of all, among the 
 branches of the Keltic race, the Welsh, the Irish, and the 
 Highland Scotch, with whom it lingered until a comparatively 
 late period. 
 
 Two stages of patriarchal society. But the study 
 of patriarchal society has, until quite lately, been rendered 
 very difficult by the practice, adopted by writers and 
 speakers, of treating all patriarchal society as though it were 
 of one kind. As a consequence, the picture has been con- 
 fused, inconsistencies and difficulties have arisen, and 
 impatient critics have been tempted to regard the patriarchal 
 stage of society as an ingenious fiction. 
 
 Tribal. As a matter of fact, a patient study of the 
 evidence soon reveals the truth, that patriarchal society falls 
 into two subordinate stages, represented by two different 
 groups or social units. The first of these may properly be 
 called the tribes the second the clan (or sept). The former 
 (the tribe) is a large group, consisting of several hundred 
 individuals, the fully qualified among whom certainly believe 
 themselves to be descended from a common male ancestor, 
 and are certainly bound together by the ties of kinship through 
 males. But, in most cases, if not all, the common ancestor 
 of the tribe is a fictitious person, invented to satisfy the 
 etiquette which has now come to regard descent from a 
 :ommon male ancestor as the only true basis of society ; and, 
 IS a matter of fact, the lawfully born children of all male 
 Tiembers of the tribe are entitled to be classed as tribesmen. 
 
 Clannish. The c/an, on the other hand, is a much 
 i smaller body, consisting of some three or four generations only, 
 
 c
 
 i8 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 in descent from a perfectly well-known male ancestor, and 
 breaking up, automatically, into new clans or septs, when the 
 proper limits have been reached. 
 
 Mistaken {older) theory. This distinction has been 
 perceived by many writers, who, however, have failed to 
 understand its true significance, and, consequently, its value 
 as a help to the study of patriarchal society. They have 
 been misled by the old theory, now definitely exploded, that 
 the beginnings of society are to be found in the single house- 
 hold^ or group of descendants of a living man. When such a 
 house-father died, they say, his sons would set up households 
 of similar pattern for themselves, and these households, 
 remembering their relationship, would form a clan ; when the 
 clan grew so big that its actual relationships became obscure, 
 it would become a tr'ile. To the Scottish historian, Mr. W. 
 F. Skene, may be attributed the merit of having shown, by 
 actual demonstration, that this account really reverses the 
 historical order of things. The tr'ihe, or larger unit, is the 
 oldest ; as it breaks up, clans are formed ; and the break up of 
 the clan-system leaves as independent units the households 
 formerly comprised within it. Finally, but not till long after 
 patriarchal society has passed away, the household is dissolved, 
 and the indhidual becomes the unit of society. 
 
 Supported by evidence of savage society. This 
 view, put forward by Mr. Skene in his Celtic Scotland (vol. 
 iii.) has been strengthened, in the most remarkable way, by 
 the discoveries concerning the nature of savage society 
 described in the preceding chapter. By these discoveries it 
 has been proved, that the earliest social group, so far from 
 being a small household of a single man and his wives, is a 
 large and loosely connected group or "pack," organized for 
 matrimonial purposes on a very artificial plan, which altogether 
 precludes the existence of the " single family." If it were 
 necessary, it could easily be shown that the origin of society 
 in " single families " is inherently impossible ; but it is 
 sufficient to point out that the evidence is against it. 
 
 Origin of ttie distinction. Although, however, the
 
 PATRIARCHAL SOCIETY IN GENERAL 19 
 
 author acknowledges his debt to Mr. Skene for the estaWish- 
 ment of the true relationship between the tribe and the clan, 
 he is not aware that the causes of the appearance of either 
 have been stated anywhere in brief form. He thinks it 
 better, therefore, even at the risk of anticipating matters a 
 little, to state clearly his own view, which is this : t/jai the 
 domestication of animdls converted the savage pack into the 
 patriarchal tribe ; and that the adoption of agriculture broke up 
 the tribe into clans. 
 
 Distinguishing marlcs of patriarctial society. 
 If this view be correct, obviously the first thing to do in 
 attempting the story of patriarchal society is to consider the 
 domestication of animals and its immediate results. But, as 
 this will require a chapter to itself, it will be well once more 
 to emphasize the distinction between patriarchal society and 
 modern or political society, in the strict sense, in order 
 that the reader may realize that he is going to deal with 
 ideas completely foreign to his own. Patriarchal society, 
 then, is distinguished from modern society by four leading 
 qualities. 
 
 Personal union. i. It is personal^ not territorial. 
 Although, as has been said, the basis of modern society is 
 military allegiance, the great factor which determines that 
 allegiance is residence in a fixed area. Doubtless, for certain 
 purposes, a citizen of State A may reside in the territory of 
 State B ; yet he is looked upon as an alien^ and he takes 
 no part in the political life of State B. On the other hand, 
 if a man qualifies as a citizen of a State by residence, we ask 
 no questions about his blood or race. " Every one born in 
 France is a Frenchman," says the Code Napoleon ; and, 
 broadly speaking, that is the rule in civilized countries at the 
 present day. But patriarchal society cares nothing for resid- 
 ence or locality. To be a member of a particular group, a 
 man must be of the blood of that group. If he is not, he 
 may pass his whole life in its service, but he will not be a 
 member. In fact, the whole group itself may move its 
 quarters at any time, without affecting its constitution in any
 
 20 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 way. At least, this is so in the earlier stages of patriarchal 
 society. 
 
 Bxclusiveness. 2. It is exclusive. Modern society 
 believes in large numbers. In spite of certain grumblings about 
 ** immigrant aliens,'* modern States are really anxious to 
 increase their numbers as much as possible, because they know 
 that an increase of numbers means an increase of ivealth and 
 oi Jighting-poiuer. To a community in the patriarchal stage, 
 an Immigration Bureau would appear to be a monstrosity. To 
 its members the immigrant is simply a thief, who comes to 
 stint the pasture and the corn land ; a heathen, who will 
 introduce strange customs and worships. If he is admitted, 
 he is admitted only as a serf or slave. 
 
 Communal character. 3. It is communal. In a 
 modern State, the supreme authority deals directly with each 
 individual. Of course there are intermediate authorities, but 
 they act only as subordinates or delegates of the supreme 
 power, which can set them aside. But, in patriarchal society, 
 each man is a member of a small group, which is itself a 
 member of a larger group, and so on. And each man is 
 responsible only to the head of his immediate group — the son, 
 wife, or slave to the housefather, the housefather to the head 
 of his clan, the head of the clan to the tribal chief. The 
 practical results of this principle are vitally important, as we 
 shall see later on. 
 
 No competition. 4. It is non-competitive. We are 
 accustomed to a state of society in which each man works at 
 what he thinks best, and in the way he thinks best. Subject 
 to certain laws, mostly of a police character, each man "does 
 as he likes." If a farmer thinks he can get a better crop by 
 sowing earlier than his neighbours, he does so. If a carpenter 
 thinks he can make a better box by using nails where screws 
 have hitherto been employed, he does so. If a draper thinks 
 he can attract customers by selling tea, he does so. But 
 patriarchal society would have looked on such practices with 
 horror. Its life was regulated by fixed custom, to deviate 
 from which was impiety. How this idea arose, and how it
 
 PATRIARCHAL SOCIETY IN GENERAL 21 
 
 gradually disappeared, we must inquire hereafter. At present, 
 we must simply bear it in mind in thinking of patriarchal 
 society. In patriarchal society, every one found his duties in 
 life prescribed for him ; and not only his duties, but the way 
 in which he should perform them. Any deviation from 
 customary rules was looked upon with disfavour. 
 
 We now come to deal with the great discovery which made 
 patriarchal society possible and inevitable.
 
 CHAPTER IV 
 The Domestication of Animals 
 
 The art of taming wild animals and making them serve 
 the purposes of man, is one of the great discoveries of the 
 world. Just as it is quite certain that there are some races, 
 e.g. the Australians, who have never acquired it, so it is 
 equally certain that many other races have learnt it, with 
 results of the greatest importance. But as to the man or 
 men who introduced it, we have no knowledge, except 
 through vague and obviously untrustworthy tradition. Like 
 many of the greatest benefactors of the human race, they 
 remain anonymous. In all probability, the discovery was 
 made independently by many different races, under combina- 
 tions of favourable circumstances. 
 
 Origin of domestication. But, if we cannot speak 
 with confidence of names and dates in the matter, we can 
 make certain tolerably shrewd guesses as to the way in which 
 domestication of animals came about. We start with the 
 fact, that the most valuable of the world's domestic animals, 
 the sheep, horse, ox, goat, etc., are known to exist, or to 
 have existed, in a wild state. It is, practically, impossible to 
 suppose that these wild animals are (except in rare cases) the 
 result of the escape from captivity of tame animals. It 
 follows, therefore, that the start which a pack of savages 
 could obtain in the matter of domestication would depend 
 upon the character of the wild animals in its neighbourhood. 
 For it is fairly obvious by this time, that many wild animals 
 are not suitable for taming. Thus, it is hardly possible that 
 the lion, tiger, or bear will ever really become domestic
 
 THE DOMESTICATION OF ANIMALS 23 
 
 animals, in spite of the fact that their strength and endurance 
 would prove valuable qualities if they could be used. And 
 so some peoples may have remained utterly savage, because of 
 the fact that their country does not produce animals capable of 
 domestication. Again, some races, like the Eskimos, appear 
 to have had only the wild ancestors of the dog and the 
 reindeer, and thus to have been very limited in their oppor- 
 tunities. Other races have been able to tame the sheep, one 
 of the most valuable aids to civilization ; others, again, have 
 had the still more valuable ox. 
 
 Superfluity of game. But still the question remains 
 — How was the process of domestication discovered ? Here, 
 again, we can only proceed by speculation ; but a most valu- 
 able account of his experiences in Southern Africa (Damara 
 Land), published by the late Sir Francis Galton in the middle 
 of the century, affords us most suggestive hints.i 
 
 Two of the most striking features of the savage character 
 are recklessness and greed. Being quite unable to make pro- 
 vision for the future, or even to realize the wants of the 
 future, the savage consumes in disgusting orgies the produce 
 of a successful hunt. A stroke of luck, such as the capture 
 of a big herd of game, simply means an opportunity for 
 gorging. But even the savage capacity for food has its 
 limits ; and, in exceptionally good seasons, there is a super- 
 fluity of game. A civilized man would strain every nerve 
 to store the surplus away against future wants. The savage 
 simply wastes it ; partly because he knows that meat will not 
 keep, partly because he cannot realize the needs of the future. 
 The " pemmican " or sun-dried meat of the Red Indian, 
 and his " caches," or buried hoards, are the limits of the 
 savage capacity for storing up against a rainy day. 
 
 Pets, But, if the savage is reckless and greedy, he is 
 often affectionate and playful. If he has had as much food 
 as he can eat, he will amuse himself by playing with his 
 captives, instead of killing them. At first, no doubt, there 
 is a good deal of the cat and the mouse in the relationship ; 
 
 ^ Narrative of an Explorer in Tropical South Africa. London, 1853.
 
 24 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 but, in time, the savage comes positively to love his captives, 
 and even to resist the pangs of hunger rather than kill them. 
 In other words, the earliest domestic animals were pets ; pre- 
 served, not with a view of profit, but for sport, or amusement. 
 And it is most important to observe, that animals so selected 
 would naturally be the handomest and finest of the catch, 
 whose appearance would delight the eye. The history of 
 the process is neatly summed up in the two meanings of the 
 English verb "to hke." In the primitive sense, "to like'' 
 means, " to like to eat " ; later on, it means " to like to keep," 
 or have by one. " I like mutton," or, " I like my dog." ^ 
 
 Food supply. But, of course, feelings of affection 
 would be bound to give way in the long run to feelings of 
 hunger. And then the tame animals would be slaughtered 
 for food. And so it would ultimately dawn on the savage, 
 that the keeping of pets was really a profitable business, 
 because it afforded some protection against y^w/W. Gradually 
 it would become more and more common. Finally, the 
 savage would learn by experience that, even without destroy- 
 ing them, his pets could be put to valuable use. Thus the 
 wool of sheep, the hair of goats, the milk of cows, would 
 be to a savage like a gift from an unknown Power. Still 
 more, the young of his captives would add to his delight in 
 his possessions ; and his forest lore, his keen observation of 
 the habits of animals in their wild condition, would come in 
 most usefully for his new occupation as a breeder and keeper 
 of flocks and herds. But, when he had got thus far, the 
 savage would have ceased to be a savage ; he would have 
 become a pastoralist. 
 
 Results of change. We must now notice the chief 
 effects upon social arrangements produced by the adoption of 
 pastoral pursuits. 
 
 Kinship through males. In the first place, it is not 
 very difficult to see how it would lead to the establishment of 
 
 ^ It has been suggested that the reverence of the savage for his 
 totem may also have had something to do with the preservation of 
 animals.
 
 THE DOMESTICATION OF ANIMALS 25 
 
 kinship through males. In the savage, or hunting stage, the 
 hunting was chiefly done by the men ; the women, though 
 in many cases they took part in the chase, being employed 
 chiefly in carrying weapons, setting traps, and other sub- 
 ordinate offices. Their real tasks were to mind camp, dress 
 the food, and, what has always and inevitably been woman's 
 work, to look after the children. Quite naturally, though 
 not, perhaps, very justly, the superfluous animals which were 
 left over after the hunger of the camp had been satisfied, 
 were looked upon as connected in some special way with the 
 man who had captured them. And he, therefore, would 
 have the training and management of them ; and, in course 
 of time, they would come to be looked upon as his property. 
 In speculations as to the origin of the important institution of 
 property^ it is often said, that capture is the first title to owner- 
 ship. This is hardly true ; for accounts of savage societies 
 generally show that the captured animals, so far as they are 
 required for foody are treated as the common stock of the 
 camp. But, when the claims of hunger have been satisfied, 
 the actual captors are allowed to retain the remainder as pets ; 
 and, as they become fonder and fonder of them, they resent 
 more and more any interference with them by other people. 
 It is just what happens with children ; who are, in many 
 respects, very like savages. What a child thinks of is not, 
 hoiv the toys came there ^ but who uses them. " I always play 
 with this doll, so it is mine.'* That is the feeling of the 
 savage for his ox or sheep. 
 
 Pastoral pursuits. And then, as all the advantages 
 of the rearing of animals come to be realized, the savage 
 " pack " gradually changes into a society of shepherds or 
 herdsmen, in which the men are engaged in tending cattle, 
 sheep, or goats, while to the women fall the subordinate 
 offices of spinning the wool, milking the cows and goats, and 
 making the butter and cheese. The men drive the flocks to 
 pasture and water, regulate the breeding, guard the folds 
 against enemies, decide which of the animals shall be killed 
 for food, and break in the beasts of burden.
 
 26 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 Value of labour. But in these tasks it gradually 
 becomes apparent to the men that labour is a valuable thing. 
 A man who has been very successful in cattle-rearing requires 
 a number of " hands " to keep his herds in order. Besides 
 the domestic labour performed by women, he requires the 
 outdoor labour of men, to prevent the cattle from straying or 
 being stolen, to drive them to pasture in the morning and 
 bring them back at night. To this demand for labour we 
 probably owe two of the great institutions of the pastoral age ; 
 permanent marriage and slavery. There is really, as we 
 shall see, nothing out of place in taking these two together, 
 odd as the connection may sound to modern ears. 
 
 Permanent marriage has been alluded to before as one 
 of the essential features of patriarchal society. By superficial 
 writers, its appearance is often attributed to some vague 
 improvement in morality or taste. Unhappily, the facts point 
 to a much less exalted origin, viz. the desire of the man to 
 secure for himself exclus'i'vely the labour of the ivoman and her 
 offspring. If the change had come about from exalted ideas 
 of morality, we should probably have found two features in 
 the new system — (i) equality of numbers between the man 
 and the woman ; ( 2 ) free consent to the marriage on both 
 sides. It is notorious that just the opposite are the facts 
 of the patriarchal system, at any rate at its earlier stages. 
 Polygamy, or plurality of wives, is the rule ; and, while the 
 husband is not at all particular about the conduct of his wife 
 with other men, he is intensely strict about appropriating the 
 whole of her labour ; and all her offspring, no matter who 
 is the real father, belong to him. Again, the ancient forms 
 of marriage, viz. marriage by capture and marriage by pur- 
 chase, point irresistibly to the conclusion that the woman had 
 little or no voice in the matter. In the case of marriage by 
 capture, the husband carried off his wife by force from a 
 neighbouring tribe; and, long after the reality of this practice 
 has disappeared, it survives, as is well known, in a fictitious 
 form all over the world. It is considered barely decent for 
 the girl to come to the marriage without a show of force.
 
 THE DOMESTICATION OF ANIMALS 27 
 
 Even in polite modern society the " best man " is said to 
 be a survival of the friends who went with the bridegroom in 
 ancient days to help him to carry off his bride, while the 
 bridesmaids are the lady's companions, who attempted to 
 defend her from the audacious robber, and the wedding 
 tour is a survival of the flight from the angry relatives of 
 the bride. In the more peaceful form of marriage hj purchase, 
 the lady has become an article of marketable value, whose 
 price is paid, usually in cattle or sheep, to her relatives or 
 owners. It is a refinement of modern days that the " bride- 
 price'^ should be settled on the lady herself, or contributed, 
 in the form of marriage gifts, to stock the future home. In 
 ancient times it was paid, if not in hard cash, at any rate in 
 solid cattle, to the damsel's relatives, who, by the marriage, 
 lost the value of her services. Jacob, we know, paid for his 
 wives by labour ; but this was probably an exception. In 
 patriarchal society, the father of a round dozen of strong and 
 well-favoured daughters is a rich man. 
 
 Slavery arises from the practice of keeping alive captives 
 taken in war, instead of putting them to death. In savage 
 days, wars are usually the result of scarcity of food, and, as 
 was pointed out previously (p. 14), result in the killing and 
 eating of members of a stranger "pack." But, with the 
 increasing certainty of food supply, resulting among other 
 benefits from pastoral pursuits, cannibalism becomes unneces- 
 sary, and captives are carefully kept alive, in order that they 
 may labour for their captors. It may sound odd to speak of 
 slavery as a beneficent institution, but one of the first lessons 
 which the student of history has to learn is, that things which 
 to us noiv seem very wicked, may have really been at one time 
 improvements on something much worse. Slavery is an ugly 
 thing, but it is better than cannibalism. Again, however, we 
 notice that the upward step was due, not to exalted morality, 
 but to practical convenience. Morality is the result, not the ■ 
 cause, of social amelioration. 
 
 The pastoral tribe. Thus we have seen that pastoral 
 pursuits have converted the savage "pack," with its loose
 
 28 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 system of association and marriage, into the pastoral tribe, 
 with its fixed marriages and its relationship based strictly on 
 kinship through males. The woman leaves her own tribe or 
 household, and becomes a member of that of her husband. 
 The clumsy expedients of capture and purchase are resorted 
 to, in order to continue the instinct, developed (as we have 
 seen) in the savage period, which forbids intermarriage between 
 near relations. The precise distance of relationship required 
 probably settles whether the woman is to be captured from a 
 neighbouring tribe, or bought from another household of the 
 same tribe. And this rule probably varies according to cir- 
 cumstances. But in either case the husband is the sole 
 authority in the household. His wives, children, slaves, and 
 animals are under his absolute control, and all stand pretty 
 much on the same footing. 
 
 Mode of transition. The precise steps in the moment- 
 ous change from the loose marital relationship of savages to 
 the definite (if somewhat brutal) institution of the pastoral 
 household, are very hard to trace. The process has been 
 very ingeniously suggested by the late Mr. Robertson Smith 
 in his Kinship and Alarriage in Early Arabia, where the 
 author points out the clear traces among the patriarchal Arabs 
 of the former existence of a savage state of society. It is 
 there suggested, that the existence of a long condition of war 
 and disturbance would have had a similar result ; by drawing 
 together the fighting males into groups for military purposes, 
 each male jealously guarding his own women and children. 
 But there are inseparable difficulties in the way of such an 
 explanation. The patriarchal household would have been 
 the last thing that a warrior would have cared to encumber 
 himself with ; and times of military licence are hardly times 
 in which the permanence of the marriage tie is developed. 
 On the whole, it seems tolerably certain, that the budding 
 institution o{ property has been the main factor in creating 
 the patriarchal tribe and family. Our very word " family " 
 is said to be derived from an old Italian V40xdi famel, meaning 
 " slave."
 
 THE DOMESTICATION OF ANIMALS 29 
 
 Other results of pastoral pursuits. To conclude 
 this chapter, we may just hastily mention one or two other 
 important contributions made to the progress of civilization 
 by the domestication of animals. Obviously it would tend 
 largely to increase numbers and to improve physique^ by the 
 greater abundance and regularity of food supply, and the 
 increase of clothing and shelter. But also it would have the 
 important effect of d'lfferentiating in strength and importance 
 one tribe from another, and one family from another. Savages 
 are, in the main, very much alike ; one savage tribe is a good 
 deal like another. But circumstances of climate, and skill 
 in breeding and rearing animals, would soon produce differ- 
 ences in the pastoral age. One tribe would become wealthy, 
 while another would remain poor. Even in the same tribe 
 some households would become richer than others, according 
 as, by superior strength or skill, one housefather acquired more 
 cattle than another. Early Irish society was elaborately 
 organized into classes, which distinguished between the ordinary 
 freemen [Neme) and the rich cattle owners [Boaire)^ and 
 between the various degrees of wealth among the latter. And 
 the primitive uniformity of membership ultimately became 
 quite broken up by the practice, adopted by the rich Boaire, 
 of lending their superfluous cattle to the poorer tribesmen in 
 return for rents or regular payments, as well as feasthigs or 
 occasional entertainments of the cattle-owner, who visited his 
 borrower from time to time, no doubt under the pretence of 
 seeing how his cattle were getting on. 
 
 New ideas. Once more, the domestication of animals 
 is responsible for two very important ideas, without which 
 civilized society could not hold together in its present form. 
 These are the ideas of profit and capital. The former is 
 now looked upon as the net gain in any commercial trans- 
 action. Originally it was the offspring of domestic animals. 
 The household which had a dozen goats in one year, 
 might find itself, without any further captures, in possession 
 of twenty in the following. The idea gradually spread, and 
 all modern industry is based on it. Again, even if there were
 
 30 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 no births in his flock, the pastoralist would find that, at any 
 rate for a time, he could go on living on the produce of his 
 animals, the milk of goats and cows, the wool of sheep, 
 without reducing his numbers. This discovery would tend 
 very powerfully to induce him to save his animals, /*. e. not to 
 slaughter them, in order that they might produce constant 
 income. That is precisely what we mean by the term capital. 
 It is wealth saved to produce future wealth. But there was 
 no room for these great ideas in savage society. They are 
 the direct outcome of pastoral pursuits. So we see that the 
 lazy and overfed savage, who amused himself by taming and 
 petting his superfluous captive animals, was really beginning a 
 revolution in the world's history. It is rather curious that 
 the power of taming new animals seems to be almost extinct 
 among civilized men. Is this because all the tamable animals 
 have been tamed, or because civilized man has become so 
 unlike wild animals, that he has lost the art of understanding 
 them ?
 
 CHAPTER V 
 Tribal Organization 
 
 We now come to deal with the way in which society organ- 
 izes itself to satisfy the requirements of this pastoral existence 
 which we have tried to describe. And, in dealing with this 
 subject, by preference we will borrow our illustrations from 
 the Keltic peoples of the British Islands, who, until compara- 
 tively recent times, occupied the patriarchal stage, and from 
 those subjects of our Indian Empire, such as the natives of 
 the Panjab, who, even at the present day, afford most valuable 
 opportunities for the study of patriarchal institutions. Occa- 
 sionally we may refer to other examples, such as the Homeric 
 Greeks, the ancient Romans, the Maoris of New Zealand, 
 and the Arabs, in order to broaden our horizon, and to 
 realize how widely spread is this phase of development. 
 But we shall gain in vividness by keeping close to one model. 
 
 The tribe. In society of the patriarchal type the im- 
 portant group is, as we have said, the tribe, or body of people 
 believing themselves to be descended strictly in the male line 
 from some far-off ancestor. We say " believing themselves,'* 
 advisedly ; for if our account of the origin of the tribe be 
 correct, the rule of male succession only developed after the 
 group had been in existence, perhaps for thousands of years. 
 But the intense belief in the existence from the beginning of 
 the so-called agnatic i rule of succession, is evidenced by the 
 amusing attempts of the tribesmen themselves to discover a 
 
 1 The term is derived from Roman Law, which contrasted agnatioy 
 or connection through male ancestors, with cognatio or ordinary 
 blood relationship. 
 
 31
 
 32 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 single male ancestor, or, as he is called by scientific writers, 
 an eponynii for their tribe. Thus, we find the chroniclers of 
 British history deriving the descent of their tribe from Brutus 
 of Troy, the grandson of ^neas ; the Cymry of Strathclyde 
 are, in an early document, said to be all descended from one 
 Coel Hen, whose name is supposed to survive in various 
 place names in Ayrshire ; each of the Teutonic tribes which 
 settled in Britain alleged its descent from the Scandinavian 
 hero Odin ; the Beluchis of the Panjab profess to be the 
 offspring of Mir Hamzah, an uncle of the prophet Mahomet ; 
 while the Pathans of the same neighbourhood claim descent 
 from Saul, the first king of Israel ! 
 
 Membership of the tribe. Such being the importance 
 attached to male kinship, it is not surprising to discover that, 
 in tribal society, no one can be regarded as a full member of 
 the tribe, unless he is the lawful child of a full tribesman. 
 Such a person is alone entitled, as of right, to a share in 
 the tribal possessions ; he alone can take part in the re- 
 ligious ceremonies of the tribe. But, as a matter of fact, 
 all patriarchal tribes are found to have living among them, 
 considerable numbers of strangers, who, though separated by 
 a great gulf from the full tribesmen, yet rank in various 
 degrees of social importance. There are, for example, the 
 mere "strangers,'* the Fu'idh'ir (as the Irish called them), 
 the Alltuds (as they are called by the Welsh Laws), who 
 appear to be broken men from other tribes, adopted or pro- 
 tected on more or less hospitable terms. Along with these, 
 probably, go the offspring of the tribeswomen through 
 marriages with such resident strangers. Occasionally, in 
 return for very great services, or after a residence of many 
 generations, such persons are fully adopted into the tribe. 
 
 Serfs. Then there were the various degrees of serfs or 
 bondmen ; for, as we have said, pastoral society was anxious to 
 secure cheap labour. These were, probably, the results of 
 forays upon neighbouring tribes, or people whom we should 
 call "convicts," who had become such through failure to pay 
 compensation for injuries committed by them, according to
 
 TRIBAL ORGANIZATION 33 
 
 the system to be afterwards explained. These servile persons 
 were either employed as herdsmen or (somewhat later) as 
 farm-labourers, such as the Sencleithe of Ireland, or the Taogs 
 of Wales ; or they were treated as domestic slaves {^Bothachs 
 or Caeths). 
 
 Ranks within tlie tribe. But it must not be supposed 
 that, even among the full tribesmen, equality of ranks was 
 the rule. True it is that every free tribesman was entitled to 
 his share of the grazing land, to his hunting in the waste, to 
 his oath of kindred (/. e. the protection of his immediate 
 relatives), and to his armour. But it is probable, as we have 
 said (p. 25), that, from the very first, the chief wealth of the 
 tribe, viz. its cattle and sheep, its camels and goats, were 
 looked upon as individual property ; and the tribesman who 
 was not fortunate enough to inherit or to capture a stock of 
 these was in a somewhat unenviable position. As the Irish 
 Laws put it, he was only a Fer Midba^ or "inferior man," 
 not a Boaire, or " lord of cattle." In fact, he was very 
 much in the position of the modern "free" workman, who 
 often finds that his boasted freedom means freedom to 
 starve. 
 
 Tile nobles. In this state of things, he very frequently 
 resorted to an expedient which is intensely interesting, as being 
 the earliest development of an institution which was destined 
 to play such a large part in the world's history : the institution 
 o£ landlordism. Only, it was not, in these early days, applied 
 to landy which was not regarded as capable of appropriation 
 by individuals, but to cattle. The rich Boaire loaned some 
 of his cattle to the poor Fer M'ldha^ who agreed to take some 
 of them for a certain period, and to pay an annual Bestigi or 
 food rent, being part of the produce, and to feast the Boatre 
 and his friends a certain number of times in the year. Having 
 the right to feed a certain number of cattle on the tribal land, 
 the borrower of cattle (or Ceile^ as he was called) could 
 probably make enough to live on out of the transaction. If 
 he had some cattle of his own, he was called a Saer Cede, or 
 free tenant ; but, if his whole herd was borrowed, he became
 
 34 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 the Daer Ce'ile of the owner ; not, technically, an unfree man, 
 but a man in a very inferior position. 
 
 Degrees of nobility. Among the rich men, or nobles, 
 of the tribe, there were also many social degrees, according 
 to their wealth ; these, however, are not of great importance, 
 except in relation to the system of blood fines, of which we 
 shall say something later. 
 
 Officials of ttte tribe. But, besides these divisions 
 into free and unfree, nobles and ordinary freemen, the tribe 
 had a very important official organization. 
 
 I . Ttie Ctlief, who was understood to represent the founder 
 of the tribe, and who was usually the oldest male in a particular 
 branch. Messrs. Spencer and Gillen have pointed out that 
 among the Australians, whom we have taken as our types of 
 savage society, there is nothing that can be called a chieftain- 
 ship, though there are, doubtless, often certain individuals 
 who, from their physical strength or supposed wisdom, have 
 great influence. But in patriarchal society, there is always a 
 representative of the tribe. The Irish called him a Ri\ the 
 Welsh a Perif the Scotch a Monnaer^ the Teutonic tribes a 
 Cyning (whence our " king "), the Biluches a Tumandar^ the 
 Pathans a Khan. He was hereditary, not in our sense, but 
 in the sense that the eldest male in the privileged line was 
 entitled to the office, unless disqualified by feebleness or 
 disease. The Welsh Laws picturesquely describe him as 
 "the oldest efficient man in the kindred to the ninth descent, 
 and a chief of household ; '' and they go on to enumerate his 
 duties thus : — 
 
 (^3[) He must speak on behalf of his kin, and be listened 
 to; 
 
 (Z-) He must fight on behalf of his kin, and be feared ; 
 
 (f) He must give security on behalf of his kin and be 
 accepted. 
 
 In other words, he must be eloquent, brave, and honest ; and 
 if a candidate for the position did not manifest these qualities, 
 he might be set aside. This is probably all that is meant by 
 certain writers, when they say that the tribal chief is "elective."
 
 TRIBAL ORGANIZATION 35 
 
 Of course he was long before the days of votes and ballot- 
 boxes. 
 
 But, by an arrangement which shows a good deal of wisdom, 
 some patriarchal tribes do not wait until the death of a chief 
 before accepting his successor. Amongst many of them 
 there is — 
 
 2. An Heir" Apparent, called by the Irish the Tanist^ 
 by the Welsh the Teishanteuleu, who is the person who will 
 next succeed to the chieftainship, in the ordinary way, after 
 the death of the existing chief. After the break-up of the 
 tribes into clans or septs in Ireland, this practice continued in 
 the smaller bodies ; and it was its existence which did more 
 than anything else to scandalize the Elizabethan statesmen 
 who tried to bring the Irish to English notions. In Russia, 
 the institution lingered for a long while in the person of the 
 Veliki Knia%, or Grand Prince, the eldest male of the house 
 of Rurik, the chief of the Varangian or Norman tribe which 
 conquered Russia in the ninth century. Still longer it con- 
 tinued to be a feature of the Holy Roman Empire, which, 
 in addition to its head, or Emperor, had of right also his 
 destined successor, the " King of the Romans." During the 
 life-time of the chief, the heir-apparent acted as his deputy, 
 and was, so to speak, "learning the business." 
 
 3. The Champion. This person, called among the 
 Irish and Scotch a Toisech, among the Welsh a Dialtvr (or 
 " avenger "), among the Teutonic tribes a Heretoch (or " host- 
 leader"), is very interesting, both on account of his ultimate 
 destiny, as well as because he is an early instance of what is 
 called "specialization of functions." Originally, as we have 
 seen, the hereditary chief was also the head warrior of the 
 tribe. But, as the chief was hereditary, it would often happen, 
 in spite of the power of rejection claimed by the tribe, that 
 the chief was unsuccessful as an actual warrior. He might 
 be wise and venerable, much respected and loved, but no 
 soldier. In times of stress, the tribe would naturally turn to 
 
 1 one of its members who had shown great bravery and skill in 
 fighting, and, by a sort of informal election, appoint him to
 
 36 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 lead them in battle, much as the Romans did, at a much later 
 stage, with their Dictator. Apparently, after this event had 
 occurred two or three times, the champion or head warrior 
 became a recognized institution. 
 
 All these three officials, the Chief, the Heir- Apparent, and 
 the Champion, seem to have been provided for by the endow- 
 ment of special rights in the tribal land, by an extra share 
 of the booty captured by the tribe on its plundering expedi- 
 tions, and by customary presents made on certain days of the 
 year by the members of their tribes. The first of these three 
 privileges is of special importance in the History of Politics. 
 
 4. The Councilf or group of seniors, called by the Irish 
 Brehons, by the Welsh Henadivr^ by the Teutons RachimbiirgSy 
 by the Mahommedan tribes Jirgah, and by the Hindus 
 Panchayat. This seems to have been a body of persons 
 gradually formed from the heads of the subordinate groups 
 in the tribe, by a process which we shall have to explain 
 in dealing with the formation of clans. Its great function was 
 to record the custom of the tribe, and regulate its ceremonies 
 and religion. It was, obviously, a most necessary institution 
 after the tribe had become numerous, and in days which could 
 boast no written records. It is most interesting as the germ 
 of future constitutional government, and may be regarded, 
 historically, as the mother of Law' Courts, Cabinets, and even 
 of Parliaments. Sometimes, as amongst the Welsh, and some 
 of the Teutonic tribes, it seems to have consisted of a small 
 number (seven); at others it was obviously larger, and may 
 have consisted of all the heads of households within the tribe. 
 Later on, its members appear to have developed individual 
 functions, as pedigree-keepers (called by the Irish and Scotch 
 Synnachies), priests (possibly, among the Welsh, Druids) y 
 medicine men, and so on. But it is with the elders as a body 
 or council, that we are most concerned : and the mention of it 
 brings us to the consideration of two closely connected topics, 
 viz. Tribal Religion and Tribal Law, with an account of 
 which this chapter may fitly end. 
 
 Tribal Religion is a striking testimony to the truth of
 
 TRIBAL ORGANIZATION 37 
 
 the view previously quoted (p. 12), that the second stage 
 of religious thought is that in which Man worships as his 
 gods beings who are, or have been, men like himself, who 
 are, in fact, his deceased ancestors. Ancestor ivorship, which, 
 even at the present day, is the religion of multitudes of the 
 human race, especially in the East, seems to arise from two 
 sources. The one is a profound belief in the existence of the 
 spirit-world, in which the dead live and move as in life ; and 
 which may, therefore, be fairly claimed as a crude form of 
 belief in the immortality of the soul. The second is the 
 profound deference to parental authority rendered during life 
 to the head of the patriarchal household, and which, after his 
 death, takes the form of ceremonial worship. In its more cruel 
 shape, this worship is celebrated with sacrifices, either by way 
 of vengeance upon the men who have caused, or are supposed 
 to have caused, the death of the ancestor, or by way of 
 providing him with comforts in the spirit-land. In its more 
 refined form, it is a continuance oi domestic tvorskipfSLS exhibited, 
 for example, in the picturesque ceremonial of the offerings of 
 cake and water, the sacrificial meal and the commemoration 
 hymns, of the Code of Manu and other Hindu rituals. The 
 centre of ancestor worship is the family hearth, with its sacred 
 fire and solemn festivities ; and its continued practice is thus 
 calculated to keep alive, in the most vivid way, that spirit of 
 kinship which is the very essence of patriarchal society. It 
 may, perhaps, be doubted whether ancestor-worship plays 
 quite such an important part in the daily life of the Hindu as 
 the Sacred Books would lead us to believe ; but it is un- 
 il i[ doubted that its existence accounts for much that is otherwise 
 h I obscui-e, not only in Oriental Society, but in the history of the 
 early Greeks and Romans. Readers who are interested in 
 pursuing this line of thought, may be advised to consult the late 
 Mr. Fustel de Coulanges' famous book La Cite Antique ; 
 here it will be sufficient to state, by way of contrast, two 
 or three of the leading features in which the ancestor worship 
 of patriarchal society differs from religion as understood by 
 the modern world.
 
 38 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 1 . It is not proselytizing. The great religions of the 
 modern world — Christianity, Mahommedanism, even Bud- 
 dhism — profess to be of universal application, and their mis- 
 sionaries seek to make converts in all lands. To an ancestor 
 worshipper, such a course would appear, not merely ridiculous, 
 but positively treacherous. His gods are for him and his 
 kindred alone ; he looks to them for favour and protection, as 
 one of their devout descendants. How could strangers possibly 
 have any share in their worship ? As a consequence, the 
 patriarchal man, who wandered away from his kindred, found 
 himself not only among strange people, but among strange 
 gods. To him, expulsion from the tribe meant the break up 
 of religious as well as social ties. An Englishman of the 
 present day who settles in France, Germany, Italy, or Spain, 
 enters a place of worship, and finds the same God worshi])ped, 
 under slightly different forms and in a different tongue (unless 
 he be a Catholic), but by worshippers of the same faith. To 
 an ancestor worshipper, such an experience would seem 
 incredible. 
 
 2. It is not theological. That is to say, it does not 
 profess to account for the origin and constitution of the universe. 
 No doubt the patriarchal man had certain crude ways of 
 explaining the existence of the world and its contents. But 
 these were not part of his religion. It was not until the later 
 speculative spirit, introduced into Europe by the Greeks, 
 attempted to link intellectual belief with religious duty, that 
 the modern kind of religion began. Even then, as we learn 
 from more than one passage in the New Testament,^ concern- 
 ing " meats offered to idols,'* some of the early Christian 
 converts considered it quite possible to combine an intellectual 
 acceptance of Christianity with a continuance of their ancestral 
 rites. Ancestor worship, in fact, was a purely practical 
 religion, imposing a code of duties on its followers, but 
 making no demands upon their belief. 
 
 3. It is secret. The view that their ancestors belonged 
 to them alone, naturally made the tribesmen very jealous of 
 
 ^ £. g. Acts XV. zj.
 
 TRIBAL ORGANIZATION 39 
 
 strangers acquiring any knowledge of their forms of worship. 
 Consequently, the most rigid care was taken by each tribe, 
 and, after the tribe spHt up into sections, by each section, to 
 prevent a knowledge of these ceremonies leaking out ; and 
 many of the most dramatic stories of ancient history turn upon 
 the vengeance taken upon interlopers who had succeeded in 
 penetrating the mysteries of religious celebrations. In each 
 household, the particulars of its sacred rites were passed on 
 from father to son in the greatest secrecy. The secrets of 
 the tribe were in the custody of the elders or wise men, who, 
 in somewhat more advanced times, formed themselves into 
 hereditary bodies, or colleges^ for their preservation and practice. 
 The very existence of the tribe was believed to depend upon 
 the safeguarding of these mysteries; and, if a disaster happened, 
 one of the readiest suggestions to account for the mishap was, 
 that the ancestors were offended, because " strange fire " had 
 been offered on their altar. 
 
 Tribal Law, Closely connected with Tribal Religion, 
 in fact originally part of it, was Tribal Law. One of the 
 direct results of ancestor worship was a religious adherence to 
 ancestral custom, that is, to the practices observed in life by 
 the revered ancestors. And this was the main idea of LatUf as 
 conceived by patriarchal society. The notion of Law as the 
 command of an absolute ruler, whether an individual or a body, 
 was yet far in the future. Law was not a thing to be made, 
 but a thing to be discovered. The old savage notion of taboo, 
 which, as we saw, was purely negative, had been largely super- 
 seded by the positive notion of custom. What was customary 
 was right, what was uncustomary was wrong. The desperate 
 tenacity with which patriarchal society clung to a practice, 
 merely because it was a practice, is illustrated, among hundreds 
 of other examples, by the well-known Roman custom of ex- 
 amining the entrails of victims to ascertain the prospects of an 
 expedition. Originally, no doubt, it was a practical expedient 
 adopted by the nomad tribes from which the Romans were 
 descended, in their wanderings through unknown country. 
 To test the fitness for food of the new herbs with which they
 
 40 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 came into contact, they caused a few of their cattle and sheep 
 to eat them, and then, by a sort of rude post-mortem, judged of 
 the result. The real origin of customs is often very hard, 
 however, to discover. Sometimes it seems to have been mere 
 accident. The ingenious account of the origin of roast 
 sucking pig, given by Charles Lamb in his well-known Essay, 
 though intended by him as a joke, may really be a brilliant 
 guess at the truth. In other cases, no doubt, an exceptionally 
 able man deliberately made an innovation, which was after- 
 wards copied by others, as it was found to be useful. But 
 such enterprise must have been very dangerous. The first 
 man who drank the milk of his cow probably paid for his 
 luxury with his life. In patriarchal society, innovation and 
 crime are almost co-incident. So little, indeed, is deliberate 
 departure from custom anticipated, that there seems to be no 
 regular punishment for it. The chief or elders will declare 
 the custom ; that is, or ought to be, sufficient. But if an 
 offender persists in his impiety, the outraged community will 
 banish him from its ranks. In the expressive language of the 
 Welsh Laws, he will be a " kin-shattered man," an outlaw, 
 in fact. If the tribe lives near the sea, he will probably be 
 set adrift on an open raft; this was the method with the 
 South Welsh. Other codes speak of turning the offender 
 " into the forest.'' In either case, the result would be much 
 the same. 
 
 The blood feud. For injuries to individual fellow- 
 tribesmen, the universal remedy was the lex talionis, adminis- 
 tered by the blood feud. Barbarous as such an institution 
 seems to us, it is probably one of the most important steps 
 ever taken towards civilization. A man is killed. Instead 
 of the murder producing indiscriminate slaughter, it gives rise 
 to an ordered scheme of vengeance, conducted by the imme- 
 diate relatives of the slain man against the murderer and his 
 immediate relatives. If there be any doubt about the facts, 
 certain rough tests are applied, which to us would appear very 
 unsatisfactory. The accused brings a certain number of his 
 relatives to swear to his innocence, or some rude sort of ordeal
 
 TRIBAL ORGANIZATION 4^ 
 
 is used.i If the accused is deemed guilty, the feud goes on, 
 unhappily for a very long time. 
 
 Blood fines. A great step further is taken, when, for 
 the right of vengeance, is substituted the payment of compen- 
 sation. The circumstances of pastoral society permit of this. 
 The existence of cattle and sheep form a standard! of value, by 
 which the life of a man can be measured. Starting with the 
 simple idea that a man is worth what he owns, and taking the 
 ordinary free tribesman as the unit, the tribe sets up an elaborate 
 scale of money Jines (the eric of the Irish, the galanas of the 
 Welsh, the<:ro of the Scotch, the nver of the Teutons) carefully 
 graduated according to ( i ) the importance of the injured party, 
 ( 2 ) the extent of the damage. Apparently, the proceedings 
 begin as before. The marks on the dead man's body are 
 examined, the bloody weapon is traced, the trail of the stolen 
 cattle is followed until it leads to the thiePs hut ; and then, 
 just as t\iQ feud is going to begin, the elders intervene, and urge 
 the acceptance of a Jine. At first, it would seem, the ac- 
 quiescence of the injured party is voluntary. Until quite late 
 in history, the ultimate right to battle cannot be denied. But 
 every effort is made by the elders to induce the parties to 
 " swear the peace." In the world-wide habit of shaking hands, 
 we probably have a dim survival of a practice insisted upon by 
 the early peace-makers, as a guarantee that the parties would 
 not use weapons against one another, at least till all other 
 remedies had been tried. For if the hand is clasped in 
 another's, it can hardly strike a blow. 
 
 No general rules of Tribal Law. It is obvious 
 from what has been said, that, while we may describe the 
 general character of Tribal Law, no enumeration of its rules 
 can be made. Each tribe has its own Law, binding only 
 upon members of its own tribe. General principles will, no 
 doubt, be found running through it all ; inheritance in the 
 
 1 One of these probably survives, in backward countries, to the 
 present day. Each of the mourners touches the body at a funeral. 
 The ancient belief was, that, if the touch was that of the murderer, 
 the corpse would bleed afresh.
 
 42 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 male line, prohibition of marriage outside the tribe (or inside, 
 as the case may be), relationship of classes, rights in pasture 
 land, and so on. But in details these will differ from tribe to 
 tribe, and even in branches of the same tribe. The investiga- 
 tions of the British Settlement Officers show, for example, that 
 there are at least several hundred different systems in force in 
 the British Panjab alone, though the population of that 
 country is a little less than the population of England. Long 
 before there is a Law of the Land, there is a Law of the 
 Tribe; and by his own Law alone will a tribesman consent to 
 rule his actions.
 
 CHAPTER VI 
 Agriculture and the Clan 
 
 Origin of Agriculture. As In the case of the taming 
 of wild animals, so in the case of tilling the ground, we are 
 left in the dark as to the benefactor who first made the price- 
 less discovery. Such scanty legends as exist on the subject, 
 are evidently the work of later times ; or refer to an importation 
 rather than to a discovery of the secret. 
 
 But, if we have no evidence on the subject, it is one on 
 which we may fairly indulge in scientific speculation. 
 Although the Australian aboriginals know nothing of 
 agriculture, they gather the seeds of a wild plant known as 
 nardoo^ and, after bruising them in a rude mortar, make them 
 into cakes. Let us suppose, in some country endowed with 
 greater natural wealth than Central Australia, that a pack of 
 savages, having gathered a greater store of wild seeds than it 
 could possibly consume, buried the surplus in some earth-heap 
 or mound, and left it in the summer camp till the return of 
 spring. Suppose an unusually wet winter, or an exceptionally 
 early spring. Returning to its summer quarters, the pack 
 might well discover that the stored-up grains had sprouted, 
 and assumed something like the shape in which they had 
 known the ears when they had gathered them in the forest 
 the previous autumn. Such an object-lesson would hardly be 
 lost, even on the savage mind. The same thing might well 
 happen to the wild yams or other edible roots which are some 
 of the earliest food of man. 
 
 Character of Agriculture. Whenever the savage 
 had begun to act upon the idea this suggested, agriculture, in 
 
 43
 
 44 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 its most primitive form, would have come into existence. The 
 rest was only a question of time. And it is quite possible 
 that agriculture, in a very imperfect form, was practised as 
 early as pastoral pursuits, at least in the majority of cases. 
 But it is not difficult to see why agriculture takes rank as a 
 development of human industry distinctly later than the tend- 
 ing of cattle and sheep. It is very much more laborious ; and 
 man, especially primitive man, has no love of work for its own 
 sake. Compared with the hard toil of the husbandman, the 
 life of the shepherd is easy and enjoyable. The capture and 
 breaking-in of wild animals is, to the savage nature, a 
 fascinating task ; the one gratifies his love of excitement, the 
 other amuses his hours of idleness. Even the driving abroad 
 of flocks and herds to daily pasture is no exacting task. The 
 milking, the dressing of skins, and the spinning and weaving 
 of the pastorahst's life are chiefly done by the women and 
 children. But the primitive curse is upon the tiller of the soil ; 
 " in the sweat of thy face shalt thou eat bread.*' 
 
 Reasons for its adoption. Agriculture, therefore, 
 remains for ages, even after its rudiments are known, a mere 
 supplementary pursuit, practised for the purpose of providing ai 
 few luxuries, rather than the substantial occupation of Man. It 
 is not adopted on a large scale till the increase of population 
 (always the result of a step forward in civilization) begins to 
 press upon the means of subsistence. One of the most 
 striking facts about agriculture is that, though its service is. 
 hard, its produce is infinitely greater than that of pasturage. A 
 learned German writer. Dr. August Meitzen, who ha» 
 devoted his life to the study of questions connected with land 
 settlement, calculates that an area which, used as a cattle-run^ 
 will maintain one hundred people, will, if brought under the 
 plough, feed three or four times that number, and leave a 
 substantial margin over. Probably the practice of agriculture,. 
 on a large scale, began in the Delta of the Nile and the 
 Mesopotamian countries, where the barren desert affbrdedi 
 little pasturage for cattle, but the rich alluvial valleys of the 
 great rivers rendered agriculture easy and profitable. From
 
 AGRICULTURE AND THE CLAN 45 
 
 thence it spread through Asia Minor, northwards and west- 
 wards, till it became known throughout Europe, and was 
 gradually adopted as the needs of the population demanded it. 
 When Cassar says of the Germans that they do not " study " 
 agriculture,^ he probably does not mean that they had never 
 heard of it, but that they found it easier to satisfy themselves 
 with milk, cheese, and flesh, the produce of pastoral pursuits. 
 There is a very interesting passage in the Book of the Ahhey of 
 Clonmacnohe, which tells of Ireland that " there was not ditch 
 nor fence nor stone wall round land till came the period of the 
 sons of Aed Slane (seventh century a.d.), but smooth fields. 
 Because of the abundance of the households in their period, there-- 
 fore it is that they introduced boundaries in IrelandJ*^ Some 
 writers [e.g. Mr. Seebohm) take this passage to refer to the 
 breaking-up of open arable fields into small enclosed holdings. 
 But there seems little doubt that what the chronicler is really 
 referring to is, the general adoption of agriculture in the place 
 of pasturage, because of the abundance of the households. There 
 is, in fact, plenty of evidence to prove that Ireland was once 
 a purely pastoral country. 
 
 Early methods of Agriculture. But we must not 
 suppose that the adoption of agriculture meant the adoption, all 
 at once, of farming as we understand it. Perhaps it will be 
 interesting to give a hasty sketch of the different stages 
 through which the cultivation of the ground has passed. 
 Afterwards we may pass to the still more important subject of 
 the results of the adoption of agriculture. 
 
 I. Forest clearings. The beginnings of agriculture 
 nearly always involved clearing the ground, for the simple reason 
 that the most fertile land is sure to be covered with the rank 
 growth of ages. Doubtless, much land had already been 
 cleared for pasture ; but people are unwilling to sacrifice this 
 for the apparently uncertain prospects of harvest. Sometimes 
 the forest is cleared by burning, the ashes being used as a sort 
 of primitive manure, and the seed being simply thrown in and 
 left to come up with the forest weeds. In other places, the 
 
 ^ Agriculture nan student. (^De Bella Gallico, vi. 21.)
 
 45 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 axe is used, and the ground, when cleared, broken up with the 
 mattock, or primitive hoe, which seems to have been an early 
 modification of the savage's digging-stick. 
 
 Extensive Cultivation. The ground thus cleared 
 is cropped year after year, until one of the fundamental laws 
 of nature begins to assert itself, viz. that a repetition of the 
 same crop on the same land tends to produce barrenness. The 
 returns are less and less each year, till the ground is abandoned 
 in despair (probably being deemed accursed), and a new patch 
 is taken into cultivation. This agriculture is technically called 
 extensive^ and is, of course, very extravagant, both in labour and 
 land. 
 
 2. Field=grass system. Although the clearings are thus 
 abandoned for purposes of sowing, they act as a sort of rough 
 pasture, or fal/o'w, for the cattle of the community, who pick 
 up a scanty subsistence from the shoots and weeds remaining 
 after the reaping of the last crop. In tropical countries, such 
 as India, and even in sub-tropical lands, such as the fertile 
 districts of southern Australia, abandoned patches speedily 
 become again converted into " jungle " or " bush," and ex- 
 plorers of later generations are startled to find, in the depths 
 of the forest, traces which point indisputably to the existence 
 of former cultivation. ^ 
 
 Alterations of crop and fallow. But, in temperate 
 zones, the land is not covered again with trees, and, after the 
 newly reclaimed patches have been themselves exhausted, the 
 tribesmen return to their old patches and plough these again, 
 to save themselves the trouble of further clearing. Then is 
 discovered another great secret of Nature, viz. that, though 
 successive crops of the same kind will exhaust a piece of land, 
 yet, if that same piece is left to lie falloiv for a time^ it tuill 
 recover its fertility. This discovery leads directly to — 
 
 3. The two-field system, in which the community 
 keeps two distinct patches of land at work, sowing one in each 
 alternate year, and leaving the other to lie fallow. This system 
 
 1 No doubt this fact accounts for a good many of the so-called 
 " discoveries of pre-historic races."
 
 AGRICULTURE AND THE CLAN 
 
 47 
 
 of agriculture is widely prevalent in backward countries at the 
 present day. 
 
 4. The three-field system. This, which is really an 
 improved variety of the last system, is due to the still further 
 discovery that, although a continuation of the saine crop on the 
 same piece of land exhausts it very quickly, an alternation of 
 crops will not exhaust it so quickly. The plan is, therefore, to 
 have three Jields and two different crops going on at once, the 
 third Jield lying fallozu once in every three years, instead of once 
 in every tavo. Thus in a course of three years — 
 
 I St year — Field A = oats B = beans C = fallow 
 
 2nd ,, — ,, B = oats C = beans A = fallow 
 
 3rd „ — ,, C = oats A = beans B = fallow 
 
 and so on for each triennial period. 
 
 Question between the two-field and the three- 
 field system. The advantages of this plan, in the increased 
 variety of crops, was early perceived ; but, for a long time, 
 people preferred to work it with the two-field system, by 
 dividing the ploughed field each year into two parts. In 
 fact, they were afraid that the other system would require too 
 much ploughing. During the later Middle Ages this was a 
 " burning question " in Western Europe. But the three-field 
 people won the day, as they were bound to do ; and their 
 argument is so triumphant and so neat, that it is worth while 
 to set it out. We take first an imaginary area of 1 80 acres, 
 divided into two fields, one of which lies fallow every year, 
 while the other is partly under oats and partly under beans 
 or pease. Thus — 
 
 A (90 acres). 
 
 B (90 acres). 
 
 A I. 
 
 (45 acres). 
 
 B I. 
 
 (45 acres). 
 
 A 2. 
 
 (45 acres). 
 
 B2. 
 
 (45 acres).
 
 48 
 
 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 Now take an imaginary course during any one year. 
 
 September. Plough A i, and sow oats... = 
 March. Plough A 2, and sow beans ... = 
 June. Plough B (whole) tivice ^ and leave 
 fallow ... ... = 
 
 45 acres 
 45 acres 
 
 = ISO acres 
 Total 270 acres ploughinj 
 
 Now take the same area divided into three Jields. 
 
 A (60 acres) B (60 acres) C (60 acres) 
 
 Again a year's ploughing : — 
 
 September. Plough A and sow oats 
 March. Plough B and sow beans... 
 June. Plough C tzvice, and leave fallow 
 
 = 60 acres 
 = 60 acres 
 = 120 acres 
 
 240 acres 
 
 i.e. actually 30 acres /ess of ploughing. But that is not all. 
 For, if we look back we see that, if we have worked our 
 lands on the two-field system, we have only harvested the 
 crops of 90 acres ; but, if we have used the three-field system, 
 we have taken the produce of 120 acres. Thus, the three- 
 field system beats the two-field, hands down ; and it is not 
 surprising to find that, in medieval Europe, it became the 
 rule in the most progressive countries, and developed a regular 
 
 1 This is necessary after the crop, to get rid of stubble.
 
 AGRICULTURE AND THE CLAN 49 
 
 set of names. Thus, in England, the autumn-sowing was 
 called the tilth grain, the spring-sowing the etch grain, and 
 the idle field t\\2 fallow; and there are corresponding terms in 
 many other countries. 
 
 5. Convertible husbandry. The three-field system 
 reigned supreme in Western Europe, until, at a comparatively 
 recent date, it was abandoned in favour of a still more economi- 
 cal plan, by which fallows are practically abolished, and, by a 
 great increase in the number and variety of crops, and the tise 
 of artificial manures, the land is never (in good hands) allowed 
 to get exhausted. This change, which came about in England 
 in the i8th century, and which was greatly due to special 
 circumstances, such as the Dutch connection and war prices, 
 is, however, closely connected with an important change, not 
 merely in the methods, but in the organization of agriculture, 
 that is to say, in the institutions by means of which agriculture 
 is worked.^ To this we must now turn our attention. 
 
 Organization of agriculture. At the end of the 
 Middle Ages (as we call them), that is to say, when the 
 revival of learning in Europe and the Reformation began to 
 break up the old order of things, the typical agricultural unit, 
 not only throughout Europe, but among the vast populations of 
 India, Egypt, and Persia, was the village or township* At 
 first sight, a village appears to be merely a collection of 
 farmers and labourers, cultivating pieces of land which happen 
 to be near together. And such, in fact, the modern village 
 of Western Europe generally is. The inhabitants are, in 
 fact, merely neighbours, nothing more. But the medieval 
 village was a great deal more ; and the difference is usually 
 expressed by describing it as a village community. There has 
 been a good deal of nonsense talked about the village community, 
 as if it necessarily meant a socialistic group of people, who do 
 their work and hold the proceeds in common. Such an asser- 
 tion cannot possibly be made of historical times. Whatever 
 may be our view of the origin of the medieval village, it is 
 
 ^ All these five stages of agricultural method may be observed at 
 work in Svireden at the present day. 
 
 B
 
 so A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 quite clear that, in historical times, we have practically no 
 evidence of an agricultural group (larger than a single house- 
 hold) cultivating its field in common and dividing the pro- 
 ceeds. So far as our evidence goes, each farmer has his own 
 land, and reaps and stores his own harvest. Nevertheless, 
 there is a real meaning in the phrase 'village community, and we 
 shall best bring out that meaning by enumerating half-a-dozen 
 points in which the average village of the sixteenth century 
 differed from the average English (or French or German) 
 village of the nineteenth century. 
 
 1. Open fields. In the first place, we notice a purely 
 physical difference. There 'were practically no hedges in the 
 medieval village. The arable land of the village lay in great 
 open Jields, many hundreds of acres in extent, separated from 
 one another and from the meadow and ivaste only by balks, 
 or banks of unploughed turf, on which grew trees here and 
 there. The beautiful hedges of the modern English country- 
 side are the result of the great enclosure movement, of which we 
 shall have to speak later on. This difference, of course, need 
 not have been connected with a difference in the methods of 
 agriculture. As a matter of fact it was so connected. 
 
 2. Equality of holdings. In a modern village, the farms 
 will be of all sorts of sizes, determined by the circumstances of 
 the case. But if we examine the terrier, or ground-plan, of a 
 medieval village, in which the lands worked by each farmer 
 are distinguished, we shall notice a curious thing. We shall 
 see that there is a tendency towards equality of holdings. 
 There will be a great many farmers with about 30 acres of 
 plough-land each. There will probably also be one or two 
 much larger holdings, e.g. 120 acres, also more or less equal 
 among themselves, and, what is still more curious, bearing a 
 fixed proportion to the smaller holdings, usually of 4 to i . 
 There will also be a number of people, obviously in an 
 inferior position, holding little plots or patches cleared from 
 the waste. Finally, there will probably be a great man, who 
 has a big house and park (or enclosure), as well as a great 
 deal of land in the openjields.
 
 AGRICULTURE AND THE CLAN 51 
 
 3. Forced labour. Corresponding with this strongly 
 marked division of classes, there will be found, if the affairs of 
 the medieval village be further investigated, a curious system, 
 by which the two poorer classes in the village render labour 
 services to the richer, not, as agricultural labourers do now, 
 for wages, but as part of the terms on which they hold their 
 lands. The poorer class, or cottagers, will, practically, be 
 working almost entirely for the lord, as he would be called in 
 Europe, for the agha in Persia, for the zamindar in India, 
 possibly also for the few rich farmers, if such existed. But 
 the ordinary small farmer, the yardling, as the English called 
 him, will also have to work for the lord, though, probably, 
 only a comparatively small part of his time. Indeed, in many 
 cases, he will probably have compounded for his labour dues by 
 payment of a fixed money rent, and so will be what we 
 should call an ordinary tenant farmer. Nevertheless he will 
 clearly at one time have been a serf ; i. e. a man who has to 
 work for another, whether he likes it or not. 
 
 4. Intermixed plots. Now-a-days, the land of each 
 farmer in a village lies in a more or less compact mass. The 
 farmer would consider it a great hardship and waste of time if 
 it did not. But the farmer in a medieval village not only had 
 his holding divided amongst the two (or three) great fields 
 into which the arable land of the village was marked off (for 
 cultivation according to the rotation of crops previously de- 
 scribed), but, even in each of these three fields, his holding 
 was not compact, it was split up into a large number of small 
 strips (usually about half an acre each) scattered all over the 
 field. Besides his 30 acres or so of arable, he would also 
 have the right to turn so many cattle and sheep into the 
 meadow of the village, except at the time of hay growth, 
 when the meadow would be temporarily enclosed with hurdles, 
 and then he would get the hay of a small plot. Finally, he 
 would have the right to turn so many inferior beasts — donkeys, 
 geese, swine — on to the waste, or uncultivated land of the 
 village, and also to cut turf and wood therefrom for fuel and 
 repairs. Thus we see that his holding, which always included
 
 52 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 a house in the village, was a complete outfit, so far as land 
 was concerned. 
 
 Closely connected with the " intermixed " character of the 
 farms, was the practice of shifting, or redistributing, the plots 
 held by a farmer at stated intervals. This practice had 
 ceased in the more progressive parts of Europe, long before 
 the end of the Middle Ages ; but in Sweden and Denmark 
 there were clear traces of its existence ; in India, under the 
 name of vesh, it was well known, and, in Persia, even at the 
 present day, it frequently takes place under the management of 
 the headman of the village. 
 
 5. Customary management. This feature which, 
 perhaps, distinguishes the medieval village more clearly than any 
 other from the modern village, was a necessary result of the 
 system of intermixed holdings. All the work of the village was 
 settled by a rigid system of rules, handed down from remote 
 ages, which prescribed exactly when and how each operation 
 should be begun, done, and ended. Now-a-days, each farmer 
 manages his lands as he thinks best, subject to the terms of 
 his agreement with his landlord. If farmer Jones thinks it 
 wise to cut his hay on Monday, he is not obliged to wait for 
 farmer Smith, who thinks that Thursday will be better. 
 Each farmer cuts his hay when he thinks best. But this sort 
 of independence would have been impossible when the lands 
 of all the different farmers were mixed up together. The 
 village was fixed in the grip of custom, and one of the chief 
 reasons why agriculture was for so many centuries unprogres- 
 sivc, was just because the enterprising farmer could not act 
 without convincing the nvhole of his fellow-villagers. 
 
 6. Officials, Now-a-days, the ordinary village perhaps 
 has its policeman, and, maybe, its ma'tre or chairman of parish 
 council ; but the policeman is probably appointed and paid by 
 a distant authority, and the maire or chairman has very little 
 real power. In the Middle Ages, each village had an 
 elaborate staff of officials, whose duty it was to work for the 
 whole village. First, there was the headman or reeve, 
 chosen from or, it may even be, by the villagers, who repre-
 
 AGRICULTURE AND THE CLAN 53 
 
 scnted the villagers as a whole, was responsible to the lord 
 for their labour dues, enforced the customs, and was the 
 mouthpiece of the village in its dealings with the outside 
 world. The position, though it doubtless carried (as it still 
 does in India and Persia) certain privileges, was not without 
 its drawbacks ; and there are some traces of a rule that its 
 acceptance was compulsory. Then, too, there was a constable 
 or beadle, whose duty it was to carry messages round the 
 village, to summon the villagers to meet under the sacred tree, 
 and generally to enforce the orders of the reeve and mooty or 
 meeting of the villagers. Then there was the pound-keeper, 
 who seized straying beasts and kept them in custody till their 
 owners made fine to the village chest ; the parker, or com- 
 mon-keeper, whose duty it was to tend the cattle and sheep in 
 the meadow, and to see that no one put in more than his 
 proper share or stint ; the stvine-herd, who led the swine of the 
 village daily to the wood to grub for acorns ; the goose-herd, 
 and so on. In many villages, all over the world, it was the 
 duty of the village to provide ivatchmen, at least during certain 
 times of the year, to guard the flocks at night. We find 
 our English Edward I. in his great Statute of Winchester, 
 insisting that the custom should be kept up; and the "Watch** 
 were a standing joke in Shakespeare's time. In India and 
 other Oriental countries, even at the present day, the village 
 carpenter, potter, blacksmith, cobbler, etc., are real ojicials, 
 provided for, like the other officials, by an allowance of land, 
 which is ploughed and sown for them by the farmers, while 
 they, in return, must give their labour to any villager who may 
 require it. Doubtless it was so at one time in Europe. 
 
 Origin of ttie village. This description will have 
 been sufficient to show that the medieval village, though 
 not that socialistic community which platform orators have 
 delighted to describe it, was a very highly organized and 
 closely compacted body, something utterly different from the 
 mere groups of independent farmers in modern Europe, usually 
 held together, if at all, only by the fact that they are tenants 
 of the same landlord.
 
 54 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 Two views. Now, concerning the origin of this village 
 community y a conflict fierce, and, it is to be feared, somewhat 
 acrimonious, has raged. For, whilst we have had great con- 
 troversiaHsts, such as Mr. Seebohm, Professor VinogradofF, 
 Professor Maitland (who can hardly be called a controver- 
 sialist at all), and M. Fustel de Coulanges, who have all 
 combined great learning with perfect courtesy, we have also, 
 unhappily, had inferior controversy from apologists of par- 
 ticular theories, who have not always observed the courtesies 
 of scholarship. Briefly speaking, and putting aside minor 
 details, the rival views are ( i ) that the typical village was 
 originally a band o^ kinsmen working for themselves; (2) that 
 it was originally a group of serfs (or slaves) working for a 
 master. Mr. Seebohm and M. Fustel de Coulanges take the 
 latter view; Professor VinogradofF and (with reservations) 
 Professor Maitland take the former. It is so extremely un- 
 likely that the views of any of these eminent and learned men 
 are totally baseless, that it is a pleasing task to the author to 
 suggest a solution of the difficulty which shall combine the 
 views of both sides. 
 
 Glancing back for a moment at our account of Tribal 
 Organization, wc shall remember, in the first place, that, 
 though what may be called the average tribesmen were free- 
 born kinsmen of each other, there was also attached to each 
 tribe a body of strangers , in a more or less inferior and servile 
 position. Furthermore, we shall remember that, among the 
 Irish and kindred races, the rich tribesman frequently loaned 
 out part of his cattle to poorer freemen, in return for an 
 annual payment or rent, and cena.in /eastings or entertainments. 
 Finally, we shall remember, that each tribe had its chief or 
 head, who was endowed with special privileges, and who 
 received various gifts and offerings from the tribesmen. Here 
 at once we have a division of patriarchal society into ranks, 
 which correspond in a most curious way with the divisions in 
 an ordinary village community, as described in this chapter. 
 The tribal chief corresponds with the village lord or agha, the 
 rich tribesmen with the holders of large farms, the poor tribes-
 
 AGRICULTURE AND THE CLAN 55 
 
 men with the yardlingsy or thirty-acre men, the " strangers '* 
 with the cottagers or serfs of the village. 
 
 Similarity between tribal and village organiz- 
 ation. But, after all, such a coincidence may be merely 
 casual. We have no right to say that it proves the connec- 
 tion between the tribe and the village. As a matter of fact, 
 there are substantial differences to be accounted for ; and it 
 is by the neglect to explain such differences that historians 
 claiming to be scientific incur ridicule. For example, in the 
 tribe, the poor Cei/e, or holders of stock, pay their rents, not 
 to the chief, but to their individual cattle-owners, while, in 
 the village, the labour services of the yardltngs are rendered 
 almost wholly to the lord. As a matter of fact, there is an 
 important transition step between the tribe and the village^ 
 namely, the clan ; and it is for evidence of the nature and 
 origin of this body that we must look. 
 
 The Flaith. Fortunately, it is not very hard to find. 
 If we look once more at our ^Indent Laivs of Ireland, we 
 shall find an important person known as the Flaithy who is 
 permanently connected with a definite territory upon which 
 are settled — 
 
 [a) His Ciniud, or agnatic kinsmen, grouped together in 
 
 an apparently artificial way, known as Fine ; 
 
 [b) His Ceile, or, as we should call them, tenants, who, 
 
 though tribesmen, have accepted stock from him in 
 manner before described; 
 
 [c) His Futdhtr, or strangers, who, apparently, have become 
 
 his peculiar charge, either by some kind of distri- 
 bution within the tribe, or by voluntary arrangement. 
 Apparently, in order to attain this position of Flaith, or land' 
 lord, the ordinary Boaire, or rich cattle-owner, must have 
 held his position for three generations. The third in descent 
 from the Boaire, if he is still rich and has maintained his 
 position on the same land, becomes a Flaith, But how did 
 he come to be settled permanently on this land ? 
 
 No sub'divisions of land in the pastoral period. 
 It is fairly clear that, during the purely pastoral epoch, there
 
 56 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 were no permanent divisions of the land within the tribe. 
 Each man's share of the tribal land was reckoned, not in 
 acres or other land measurement, but in cattle and sheep. It 
 was, obviously, much easier to reckon this way, than to go to 
 the trouble of measuring out the land and allotting a portion 
 to each man. The cattle wandered about, according to the 
 season of the year, followed by the tribesmen with their tents 
 and scanty goods ; and it is probable that this is all that a 
 good deal of the so-called nomadism amounted to. But now 
 we have to suppose the practice of agriculture slowly adopted, 
 " because of the abundance of the households." Gradually, 
 this wandering existence became more and more impossible. 
 Granted that, at first, the cultivators of the soil cleared and 
 broke up any part of the forest land not actually occupied 
 by their fellow-tribesmen. Sooner or later, the improve- 
 ments in agriculture described at the beginning of this chapter 
 rendered people unwilling to abandon their land. But who 
 were the earliest cultivators of the soil ? Obviously, the 
 strangers attached to the tribe, upon whom the rough work of 
 the community fell, and who would be the first to suffer from 
 scarcity of food. Gradually, the tribal territory thus got 
 broken up among the rich tribesmen, each with his Ce'ile or 
 dependents and his Fuidhir or strangers ; and, after three 
 generations of holding, he could not be dispossessed. This 
 view is strikingly suggested for Ireland by the famous poem 
 of Finntann on the battle of Magh Lena. He tells us that 
 of old Ireland was divided into one hundred and eighty-four 
 Tr'tcha Cedsy i. e. tribal territories, that each of them was sub- 
 divided into thirty Ballys, or clan lands, each maintaining 
 three hundred c^\.\\q, and having twelve setsrtghsy or ploughlands^ 
 each of one hundred and twenty acres. We are not bound 
 to suppose that the poet was entirely accurate in his figures ; 
 but he was not likely to have made a glaring misstatement of 
 obvious facts. We may accept his general description as 
 true, the more so as it is substantially supported by the 
 evidence of the Welsh Laws. 
 
 The Welsh evidence. For, in the Welsh Laws, we
 
 AGRICULTURE AND THE CLAN 57 
 
 have not only the i/«, or tribe, settled in its cantred, but we 
 have a subdivision known as the gnuely, under a hreyr, or 
 uchelwr, who is a sort of minor patriarch, at the head of a 
 Hving family of three generations. The term gively, which, 
 literally, means a bed or couch, is strongly suggestive of family 
 ties; and, as a matter of fact, we have in the Welsh Laws a 
 very interesting description of the ancient Welsh patriarchal 
 house, which seems to have been much of the same type as 
 the ordinary Gothic Church. Behind the pillars (gavels) 
 which supported the roof and formed the nave, were what we 
 should call, in modern architecture, the "transepts,'' but which 
 the Laws call the givelys, or couches ; and the Tir Gwelyaiug, 
 or ancestral land, is, like the Irish Orba, the land of a family 
 which has remained in possession of the same district for three 
 generations, and has tenants and serfs under it. In the Welsh 
 evidence too, it is also worth noting, that, primarily, the agri- 
 culture is supposed to be done by the Alltuds, or strangers; 
 the free tribesmen occupying themselves principally with 
 cattle-rearing. 
 
 The Scottish evidence. Lastly, in the Scottish evi- 
 dence, especially that part of it which relates to the High- 
 lands, we find the clan, or section of the tribe, permanently 
 settled as a land-occupying unit engaged in agriculture. Thus, 
 even after the feudalizing process, which began in the four- 
 teenth century, had made some little way, the davoch is found 
 to consist normally of four parts, viz. the thaneston, or lord's 
 demesne, the tenandries, or holdings of the superior class, 
 significantly known as " kindly tenants," usually on very pro- 
 fitable terms, the steelbotv lands, occupied (usually in holdings 
 of two oxgangs, or a husbandland of about twenty-six acres), 
 by small farmers who receive their stock from the thane, or 
 lord, and the servile lands, occupied in small patches by 
 cottagers who spend most of their time in working on the 
 lord's demesne. This looks extremely like the Orba of the 
 Irish Laws, and the Tir Givelyaivg of Wales. 
 
 Kinship in the village. Thus, we have seen, if our 
 account be correct, that those writers who contend for the
 
 58 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 origin of the village in a group of kinsmen, have a good deal 
 of truth on their side. And their contention is indirectly 
 supported by many significant, if indirect, survivals. One 
 of these is the widespread practice of fosterage in early 
 agricultural society, /'. e» the practice of the richer members of 
 the community putting out their children to be brought up by 
 the poorer. As is well kTio^fJJ^, fosterage ties were looked 
 upon in early times as almost equivalent to kinship ; and it 
 would seem that by this practice the community wished at 
 least to pretend that all its members were of kin. Then, too, 
 there is the equally widespread practice of the " maiden fee " 
 (Mercket as the Saxons called it, ylmobyr as it was known to 
 the Welsh). This consisted of a payment made to the chief 
 or lord on marriage of a villager's daughter, and represents, 
 no doubt, the ancient " bride-price " received by the wife's 
 kindred. Finally, expressions such as the " brotherhood," 
 to signify the village in certain parts of India, and the known 
 unwillingness in primitive countries at the present day to permit 
 a stranger to acquire lands in a village, all point to the same 
 conclusion. 
 
 Lordship in the village. On the other hand, the 
 writers who assert the origin of the village to be in lordship 
 rather than in kinships have much on their side. To say 
 nothing of the important part which, as we have seen, was 
 played by the subject stranger in the clan, we must not forget 
 that, wherever we find primitive agricultural society, we 
 always find something in the nature of dues or rents paid by 
 the farmer. Even if we put aside such obviously later intro- 
 ductions as the Danegelt in England, and the Khiraj of the 
 Mahommedan conquests, about which we must speak at a 
 later stage, we have still t\it food- rents and f eastings (see p. 33) 
 due from the receiver of stock to his lord, and from the latter 
 to his chief; while from all lands something in the nature of 
 tribute is paid to the tribal chief. The latter also, as well 
 as the heads of clans, has his special allotment of land for his 
 support, and this he frequently loans out to people who pay 
 him part of the produce in return, just as, in the earlier
 
 AGRICULTURE AND THE CLAN 59 
 
 pastoral days, the rich cattle-owner took food-rents and feast- 
 ings from his Ce'iley or receivers of stock. Once more, there 
 can be little doubt that, whilst land was still plentiful, any 
 enterprising clansman might colonize the tuaste lands of the 
 :lan, and found a new village with a band of followers whom 
 he collected round him ; and, in such a case, he would, 
 doubtless, become the lord of the new village. 
 
 The fact is, that in kinship and lordship we have two very 
 :'arly and very powerful principles of association. The former 
 appeals more to sentiment, and tends to produce harmony ; 
 ;he latter is founded upon respect for superior strength and 
 nasterful qualities, and tends to produce obedience. Both 
 larmony and obedience are essential to the successful ordering 
 3f a social unit, such as the agricultural village.
 
 CHAPTER VII 
 Industry and the Gild 
 
 Metal -working. By a somewhat unfair use of the term, 
 the word " industry '* is usually applied only to pursuits other 
 than hunting, cattle-tending, and agriculture. In a sense, 
 therefore, there is "industry" even in the savage epoch, 
 when the women of the pack skin and dress the captured 
 animals in the cave or bark hut ; still more so, in the pastoral 
 epoch, when the wife and daughters of the shepherd weave 
 the wool of the flocks into garments, and make the milk of 
 the herds into butter and cheese. But the great spur to 
 industry comes with the development of agriculture, when 
 there is a demand for ploughshares, reaping-hooks, spades, 
 mattocks, and hoes ; and this is itself connected with one of 
 the most important subjects in the history of civilization, viz. 
 the art of ivorking in metals. The primitive implements of 
 husbandry are, no doubt, made of wood and stone ; but no 
 great progress in agriculture can be made until metal tools are 
 employed. 
 
 Use of Iron. Now it is tolerably clear, that even 
 pastoral races have some knowledge of working in metals. 
 The brazen helmets and corselets of the Homeric heroes, 
 their swords and spears, the uncoined money (reckoned by 
 weight) of the Jewish patriarchs, the gold and silver orna- 
 ments of the African tribes, and the numerous bronze relics of 
 great antiquity constantly dug up, all point to the fact that the 
 art of working in metals is very ancient. But it is to be 
 noticed that all these are soft metals, which can be worked 
 with the stone hammer, and beaten out, whilst cold, into the 
 
 60
 
 INDUSTRY AND THE GILD 6i 
 
 ; required shape. The real revolution comes when men learn 
 
 ! to work in /><?//, which can only be moulded by being swelled 
 
 in the Jire, but which, when so worked, is infinitely harder 
 
 than the older metals, and can produce results which they 
 
 could never have produced. 
 
 There is a good deal of ground for conjecturing, that this 
 
 I important art of smelting metals did not originate in Europe, 
 
 ' but was imported from the East, possibly from Egypt, where 
 
 I iron was worked in very early times. A brilliant German 
 
 \ writer, who has endeavoured to draw a picture of primitive 
 
 Aryan society from the evidence of language, has pointed out, 
 
 i there is no general or widely-spread word for " iron '' among 
 
 the Aryan-speaking races. And from this fact he draws the 
 
 ! conclusion, that the knowledge of iron was acquired by the 
 
 European nations, after their migration into western Europe. 
 
 Be this as it may, it is quite certain that the European races 
 
 have long ago surpassed all the rest of the world in the art of 
 
 ivorking in iron. 
 
 The smith. It is evident then, that industry (in the 
 
 , modern sense of the term) begins with the important craft of 
 
 I the smithy from which, indeed, almost all other crafts may be 
 
 ' said to have sprung. The smith it was who forged and 
 
 \ mended the ploughshares and reaping-hooks of the village, and, 
 
 I still more important, its swords and spears. He it was who, 
 
 i as later improvements came, made the iron nails which took 
 
 I the place of the old bone and wooden skewers, and the metal 
 
 knives which superseded the old stone axes and sharp flints, 
 
 who substituted the iron hammer for the rude lump of quartz 
 
 i with a shaft stuck through it. If any one with the necessary 
 
 \ knowledge and patience would write a history of the craft of 
 
 • the smithy tracing its development in all ages and in all 
 
 ; countries, he would do yeoman service to the cause of social 
 
 , history. What little is known is very significant. For 
 
 ! example, it seems tolerably clear, that for many ages in 
 
 I Europe the craft was in the hands of travelling strangers, 
 
 perhaps the ancestors of our modern gypsies, who jealously 
 
 guarded their valuable secrets, and made no end of mystery of
 
 62 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 their calling. The many legends which have grown up round 
 the calling of the smith (of which the Wayland Smith episode 
 in Scott's Kenilivorth is a skilful adaptation) are fertile matter 
 for a thorough investigation. The gypsy idea is, of course, 
 quite in accordance with the suggestion, that the art of smelting 
 iron was brought into Europe by strangers. 
 
 Specialization of industry. But, as might have been 
 expected, the Indo-European peoples, with that capacity for 
 adaptation which has been one of the great secrets of their 
 brilliant success in the world, ultimately acquired the art ; and 
 the numerous families of the Smith name (^Schmidt in German, 
 Favre in French, etc. ) testify to the popularity of the pursuit. 
 Some other crafts branched off from it, e.g. the carpenter, who 
 worked in wood with the smith's nails, hammer, and chisel ; 
 the cobbler, who borrowed his needle and his knife ; the tailor^ 
 who adopted his shears and his needle ; the loriner (or leather 
 worker), the turner, the luheelwright, the cooper, and so on. 
 Even the older crafts felt the tendency towards specialization, 
 and, instead of each family doing its own weaving, thatching, 
 baking, and brewing, we get these crafts undertaken by special 
 bodies, the iveavers, tilers, bakers, and breivers.^ 
 
 Commerce, But, in remembering the makers or pro- 
 ducers, we must not forget another equally important class of 
 industrial workers, viz. the merchants or exchangers. Indeed, 
 there is some reason to believe that exchange precedes pro- 
 duction in the order of ideas. The Australian savages do not 
 make anything worth speaking of, but they exchange certain 
 of their natural advantages, for others which they need. 
 Thus, a pack which hunts a country abounding in a peculiar 
 green stone, greatly valued for the purpose of stone axes, will 
 send some of its young men with lumps of the precious article, 
 to exchange against the feathers of certain birds collected by 
 another tribe, which are greatly valued for decorative purposes. 
 These primitive merchants observe certain formalities in their 
 approach to the stranger camp ; and are, by immemorial 
 
 1 It is an interesting fact that, in England at least, the earliest 
 professional brewers (or should we say breweresses ?) were women
 
 INDUSTRY AND THE GILD 63 
 
 custom, entitled to be treated as giiesfs, not as enemies. The 
 custom of making presents on approaching an African chief as 
 a stranger, is said to be a survival of this ancient practice ; 
 for, it is to be noted, the chief always observes the etiquette 
 of offering return gifts. At any rate, we get here the earliest 
 appearances of the laiv of the market j which is again a notable 
 factor in the history of civilization. 
 
 Barter and sale. Trade is, of course, for long ages 
 conducted in its primitive form by means of barter, i. e. the 
 exchange of one article against another. The disadvantages 
 of such a form are obvious. One tribe or clan may have 
 plenty of ostrich feathers, for example, to dispose of, but may 
 not require the only articles which another has to offer. It 
 is clear that no business can be done between them. Inside 
 a community, the matter could be adjusted by a sort of debtor 
 and creditor account ; but between stranger, possibly rival 
 communities, such a course would not be possible. Occa- 
 sionally, some token, such as the African cowry shell, is 
 adopted as a standard of value, in which payments can be 
 made. But the objection to this course is, that these articles 
 are not really in themselves valuable, and may, therefore, 
 involve the community which takes them in a loss. A great 
 advance is made when some article of universal demand, such 
 as the ox, is adopted as a standard of value. We then get the 
 difference between barter and sale. The community which 
 requires the ostrich feathers, but which has no article specially 
 required by the other community to dispose of, pays so many 
 oxen in exchange for the feathers. The oxen are thus the 
 price, which, as economists tell us, is value expressed in terms 
 of money. A curious testimony to the truth of this account 
 is found in the fact that, when oxen are superseded as money 
 by the precious metals, which, as being more portable, and 
 less easily subject to depreciation, are really more suitable, 
 the earliest coins are often found to be stamped with an ox^s 
 head. But we must not suppose that coined money at once 
 takes the place of oxen. There is an intermediate stage of 
 uncoined money, which passes by nveight. Abundant evidence
 
 64 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 of this fact survives ; but we need not look farther than our 
 own word pounds which may mean either a iveight, or a coin 
 of a particular value. 
 
 Organization of Industry. Having now seen some- 
 thing of the way in which industry^ in its two branches oF 
 production and exchange, arose, we turn, in dealing with agri- 
 culture, to examine how industry was organized, i. e. what 
 institutions were developed to work it. 
 
 Village craftsmen. There can be little doubt that, at 
 first, there was an attempt to fit industry into the village 
 system. Although the smith, as a stranger, would not readilv 
 be absorbed in a group of kinsmen, although, as a matter of 
 fact, we generally find the smithy at a little distance from the 
 village, yet the "village blacksmith" became, and, indecil, 
 still is, a recognized village institution. So also with the 
 other early crafts. The carpenter, cobbler, and tailor, the 
 weaver, tiler, and baker, are, in Oriental countries at the 
 present day, and formerly in European countries were, 
 integral parts of the village system. As for the primitive 
 merchant, we find him in tlie humble guise of the pedlar, or 
 huckster, going about with his pack from village to village, 
 and 80 being, it not a villager, at least a connecting link 
 between villages. 
 
 Tlie market. But, as industry became more and more 
 specialized, as new crafts developed out of the old, it gradually 
 became clear that more rapid progress was made, and better 
 work done, if the workers in a particular craft collected 
 together in a centre, perhaps specially suited for the particular 
 industry ; and thus we get the beginning of that tendency for 
 industry to gravitate towards towns, which is so marked a 
 feature of modern industrial life. It may be that the gradual 
 collection of craftsmen formed the toivn, or it may be that the 
 existence of a fortified town attracted the craftsmen. That is 
 a much-disputed question. But it is tolerably certain, that one 
 of the earliest institutions in connection with towns was the 
 market, and that the existence of the market was closely con- 
 nected with the development of industry. The neighbouring
 
 INDUSTRY AND THE GILD 65 
 
 villages would not want to come to market for agricultural 
 produce ; but they would want to come for the produce of 
 what is specially known as *' industry.'* 
 
 Now, the very essence of the market is, that it is neutral 
 ground, on which the members of different communities can 
 meet without trespassing on one another's territories. As its 
 name implies, it was frequently on the march or boundary of 
 two or more districts. And, whether it was so or not, in any 
 particular instance, it was essential that it should be a place of 
 peace. The existence of the market cross in later days shows 
 that the Church took the market under her special protection. 
 And, also later, kings and emperors made a special point of 
 protecting the peace of their markets. How the peace was 
 guarded in the ancient days before Church and State, it is 
 difficult to say. In savage times, the essential point is, that 
 seller and buyer shall never actually come into contact. The 
 seller brings his article near the strange camp, lays it down on 
 the ground in full view, and retires. The intending purchaser 
 comes out, inspects the article, places beside it what he is 
 willing to give in exchange, and also retires. The seller once 
 more comes up, inspects the proffered exchange, and, if 
 satisfied, takes it away, leaving his own article to be fetched 
 by the purchaser. If he is dissatisfied with the offer, he takes 
 his own article away. Needless to observe, savage barter is a 
 trifle tedious ; but time is of no value to savages, who, indeed, 
 do not understand what it means. In patriarchal times, the 
 " gods of the market place " probably are supposed, in some 
 mysterious way, to guard the peace of the market. At any 
 ^ rate, the bazaar, which is the Oriental market, is a typical 
 I feature of town life in patriarchal countries at the present day. 
 I The gild. But it is totally contrary to the ideas of 
 primitive man to live as an individual, isolated and unprotected, 
 in a large society. We have seen that pastoral pursuits 
 developed the tribe, with its strong blood bond, its mutual 
 -;(; protection of its members by the blood feud, and its ancestor 
 worship. We have seen, too, that agriculture led to the 
 existence of the clan, with its strongly organized family 
 
 F
 
 66 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 system^ its elaborate arrangements of land occupation^ and its 
 reciprocal duties of protection and service between chief and 
 followers. Just in the same way, the appearance of industrial 
 pursuits produced the gild. The craftsman, finding himself 
 in a strange place, cut off from his own kindred, formed with 
 his fellows an association resembling as closely as possible the 
 association of kindred which he had left behind him. Perhaps 
 at first it was merely a peace-association, a frith-gild as the 
 Saxons called it; then it took on a religious character, 
 doubtless in imitation of the old ancestor ivorship of the clan. 
 The medieval gild always had its patron saint ; and, if its 
 members did not really believe themselves to be descended 
 from their patron saint, they often spoke as if they did. 
 Finally, the gild became more industrial in character ; busying 
 itself more and more with such matters as the regulation of 
 work and prices, the inspection of workshops, the fixing of 
 measures and qualities, the exclusion of strangers, and so on. 
 But, the more we study the gild, the more we see its likeness 
 to the old clan. Like the clan, it was strongly hereditary. 
 The best title to admission to the full privileges of a gild was 
 the fact that the applicant's father was, or had been, a member. 
 Failing birth, apprenticeship was the only alternative. But 
 apprenticeship is very like adoption. In the days of gilds, the 
 apprentice lived ii his master's house, fed at his master's table, 
 shared in his worship, was clothed and taught by him, just 
 like a son. Just as the member of a clan took the name of 
 the founder, and put before it or after it some sound which 
 indicated " son of," so the member of the gild called himself 
 by the name of his craft. While the clansman called himself 
 "7IfjfDougall,"or"Bill/«§'," ox'^ap Tudor," or "5^«hadad," 
 the craftsman called himself " Smith," "Turner," "Carpen- 
 ter," and so on. In fact, it is said by some competent 
 observers, that the Indian caste system is merely an elaboration 
 of hereditary craft-gilds. Moreover, the gild in later days 
 provided schools and orphanages for the children of its mem- 
 bers, attended their funerals, provided masses for their souls, 
 spoke of its members as "brethren," had an "elder man"
 
 INDUSTRY AND THE GILD 67 
 
 {^Ealdorman) for chief, settled disputes amongst its members, 
 and forbade its members to compete with one another, just as 
 a well-conducted association of kinsmen would do. Finally, 
 on its strongly developed social side, in its frequent drink- 
 ings, feastings, and merrymakings, the medieval gild strongly 
 resembled a great family group. 
 
 Thus we have seen, that patriarchal society had succeeded, 
 more or less completely, in making provision in its own way 
 for the needs of advancing civilization. As each new de- 
 velopment of human ingenuity brought a new occupation to 
 light, patriarchal society was equal to the task of organizing 
 itself to receive and carry it on. Obviously, patriarchal 
 society rested on principles which are, or were, very deep in 
 human nature, very capable of making themselves felt under 
 all sorts of circumstances. Once more, as we are leaving the 
 subject, it will be well to summarize briefly the distinctive 
 features in which patriarchal society differed from modern 
 or political society, the consideration of which lies immediately 
 before us. We cannot too clearly realize the contrast ; the 
 more clearly we realize it, the more shall we really understand 
 modern conditions. 
 
 1. Personal basis. Now-a-days we regard territory or 
 locality as the great basis of society. But, as we have seen, 
 despite the fact that nomadism or wandering life practically 
 ceased with the adoption of agriculture, patriarchal society 
 always considered itself as a body constituted by race, not by 
 territory. Even the ^ild, as we have seen, regarded itself as a 
 brotherhood, not as a mere neighbourhood. Though, doubtless, 
 the members of a particular gild often lived near to one another 
 in the same town, they lived together because they were 
 members of the gild ; they were not members of the gild 
 because they lived near together. Still more obviously are 
 the clan and the tribe personal, not territorial associations. 
 
 2. Bxclusiveness. This feature of patriarchal society 
 is a natural result of the former. Normally speaking, the only 
 means of obtaining membership of a race is by being born
 
 68 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 into that race. Patriarchal society went so far as to admit 
 the case of adoption, or fictitious birth, under carefully guarded 
 rules. But it would have recoiled in horror from the casual 
 hospitality which a modern State extends to all tolerable 
 immigrants. Modern States believe in large numbers ; 
 patriarchal communities do not. Some people are inclined 
 to think that patriarchal society was right. It is a question 
 of whether it is preferable to maintain purity of race, and be 
 extinguished as an independent community, or to admit alien 
 blood, and prosper. The history of the world shows that 
 these are the inevitable alternatives. Racial exclusiveness 
 wrecked the so-called " City State " of the Greeks ; it very 
 nearly wrecked the budding destinies of Rome. All the 
 world over the rule applies ; the pure-blooded races are weak, 
 the mixed races are strong. 
 
 3. Fixity of Custom, Custom plays, as we shall see, a 
 large part in modern life ; but modern custom is continually 
 being modified and changed. The custom of patriarchal 
 society is rigid. No doubt it changes a little ; but a society 
 whose chief moral duty is to continue the traditions of its 
 ancestors, is hardly likely to admit novelty if it can help it. 
 Sir Henry Maine tells a delightful story of an Indian village 
 which had had a water supply provided for it by a paternal 
 British Government. The villagers were notified, as a matter 
 of course, of the official regulations laid down for the proper 
 use of the water. An East End district of London would 
 be only too glad to get a good water supply on such terms. 
 But, to the patriarchal society of India, the notion that cus- 
 toms could be manufactured by an official pen was simply 
 incredible. And it was not until a wise official induced the 
 village elders (by what means is not stated) to persuade the 
 rank and file that the rules in question were really of im- 
 memorial antiquity, though their existence had only just been 
 discovered, that the difficulty was solved. Even the gild 
 prided itself on the antiquity of its statutes, though the gild 
 is, of course, the most modern form of patriarchal society. 
 The caste system of India is the extreme outcome of the
 
 INDUSTRY AND THE GILD 69 
 
 rigidity of patriarclial custom. When we speak of the 
 "unchanging East," we allude to countries which are still in 
 the grip of patriarchal principles. 
 
 As a consequence of its unchanging character, patriarchal 
 society is also, to a great extent, non-competitive. Competition 
 involves innovation at every turn ; the successful competitor 
 usually succeeds because he does things in a superior way of 
 his own. Doubtless it is also possible to succeed by doing 
 things in the same way as one's rivals, but doing them better. 
 And to this extent, presumably, patriarchal society is com- 
 petitive. But the trade offences known as " engrossing " and 
 "forestalling," which are recognized in quite the last stage of 
 patriarchal society, are amusing illustrations of the limited 
 extent to which that society allowed competition. " Fore- 
 stalling " merely means buying earlier than your neighbours, 
 in order to control the supply of commodities, and get better 
 prices. As its name implies, it is an attempt to buy goods 
 before they reach the market. " Engrossing " is simply 
 dealing in a large number of articles, instead of observing the 
 customary restrictions, in order to be able to sell cheap, and 
 so attract custom. It is pathetic to think that the harmless 
 and indeed useful " grocer " of modern times is, in origin, a 
 member of a criminal class. 
 
 4. Cotntnunalism, Observe, we do not say Communism. 
 Patriarchal society is not communisticy i. e. it does not refuse to 
 recognize individual rights, nor does it pool the productions 
 of its members and divide them equally. But it is communal, 
 in the sense that it is always organized in groups. The 
 smallest group of which it takes direct notice is the household, 
 which is, probably, very much larger than our modern house- 
 hold, and may contain two or three generations, with wives, 
 apprentices, and serfs. Within that household, the higher 
 authority does not penetrate. The same rule is observed in 
 an ascending scale. What the household is to the clan or 
 gild, that the clan is to the tribe. With us, the supreme 
 authority can control directly the actions of any individual. 
 The reason for that change will shortly appear. But in
 
 70 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 patriarchal society the tribal chief, after the break-up of the 
 tribe into clans, communicates directly with the clan chiefs 
 only, except that he probably has a clan of his own of which 
 he is tribal head as well as clan chief. The clan chief, like- 
 wise, communicates only with the heads of households within 
 his clan ; to the heads of households belongs the control over 
 the dwellers within their walls. But we really err in com- 
 paring the position of any patriarchal authority with that of 
 a modern State official. The latter is wielding the power of 
 a despotic ruler, whether that ruler be an individual or a 
 parliament. The former is merely administering the customs 
 of his race.
 
 Type III. — Modern (Political) Society 
 
 CHAPTER VIII 
 The State and Feudalism 
 
 The origin of the State, or Political Society, is to be found 
 in the development of the art of luarfare. It may be very 
 sad that this should be so ; but it is unquestionably true. 
 Historically speaking, there is not the slightest difficulty in 
 proving that all political communities of the modern type owe 
 their existence to successful warfare. As a natural con- 
 sequence, they are forced to be organized on military princi- 
 ples, tempered, doubtless, by a survival of older (patriarchal) 
 ideas. Happily, there is a good side, as well as a bad one, 
 to military life. 
 
 Development of warfare. The question may naturally 
 be asked at this stage — How came military principles to receive 
 such a startling development after society had, apparently, 
 succeeded in organizing itself on more peaceful lines ? Fight- 
 ing there had always been, of course ; wars between tribe and 
 tribe, clan and clan, even between village and village, town 
 and town. But this was more in the nature of a feud, a sort 
 of standing quarrel which broke out again and again, and then 
 slumbered for a while ; it was nothing like the organized and 
 determined warfare which resulted in the formation of States. 
 It may be described as amateur rather than professional 
 fighting. 
 
 Increase of population. Although we cannot speak 
 with certainty as to the causes of this development, it is not 
 
 71
 
 72 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 difficult to suggest one or two facts which may have led to it. 
 First and foremost comes the increase of population, with its 
 consequent pressure on the means of subsistence. This increase 
 is always, under normal circumstances, steadily going on; and 
 it is dealt with in various ways. Sometimes, a pestilence 
 breaks out ; and the super-abundant population, enfeebled by 
 short allowance of food, is swept away by disease. Some- 
 times, wholesale migrations take place to less thickly populated 
 districts ; this may be regarded as a real remedy, though 
 perhaps only a temporary one, for the trouble. Sometimes, 
 again, a great new invention enables a largely increased food 
 supply to be produced : the changes from hunting life to 
 pastoral life, and again from pastoral life to agriculture, are 
 examples. Finally, war may break out on a large scale; and 
 the weaker peoples may be either exterminated or (more 
 probably) reduced to subjection by the stronger. 
 
 Increase of wealth. Another cause may have been, 
 the great increase of realized tuealth attendant upon successful 
 agriculture, and, still more, industry. Pastoral wealth has 
 this advantage, that it can be moved about with tolerable ease. 
 A weak tribe can fold up its tents, and drive its cattle and 
 sheep out of harm's way. But the wealth of the husbandman 
 cannot be so disposed of. His wealth is in his fields, which 
 he has patiently cultivated, and in his barns and presses which 
 he has filled with corn and wine. He has built himself a 
 permanent house, and he will not leave it while a chance of 
 safety, or even of existence, remains. He is a very tempting 
 bait to the military adventurer. Still more is the craftsman, 
 with his rich store of wealth, a tempting object of plunder. 
 The sack of an industrial town, with its shops and its stores 
 of goods, is the dream of the freebooter. JVass fiir Plunder! 
 was Bliicher's exclamation, when he was shown London from 
 the dome of St. Paul's. It was the old instinct of the 
 professional soldier. 
 
 Improvement In weapons. Once more, it is natural 
 to suppose, that the improvement in the art of working in 
 metals did much to stimulate the military spirit. The
 
 THE STATE AND FEUDALISM 73 
 
 superiority of iron, still more of steel weapons and armour, 
 over the old wooden bows and arrows and leather shield and 
 corselet, would give a natural impetus to warfare. Above all, 
 with the tendency towards specialization which, as we have 
 seen, is one of the master principles of development, this 
 improvement in the means of warfare would tend to produce a 
 special military class, the professional warrior of the modern 
 world. In primitive times, every man was a soldier ; as 
 civilization progressed, the bulk, of people became interested in 
 other things, and fighting became the work of specialists. 
 This fact is directly connected with the origin of the State. 
 
 The German war^bands. In the interesting account 
 given by Tacitus of our Teutonic forefathers in their ancestral 
 homes, we notice one very significant feature. Not only does 
 the historian distinguish between the princeps, or tribal chief, 
 who was chosen for his noble birth, and the dux, or war 
 leader, who was chosen for his valour ; he shows us the latter 
 surrounded by a band of adventurous companions, who took 
 no part in the ordinary pastoral life of the tribe, but were 
 constantly engaged in warfare, either in defence of their own 
 tribe, or in plundering expeditions against strange tribes. 
 These " companions," as they are called, were fed at the 
 leader's table, were furnished with food and garments by the 
 women of his household, and shared the booty of their leader's 
 expeditions. The devoted loyalty which they displayed 
 towards their leader is described in a spirited and well-known 
 passage. They counted it a disgrace to leave the field alive, 
 if he was dead ; their dead bodies were found thickly piled 
 around his in the disastrous day of defeat. It is probable 
 that, at first, this band of companions was composed mainly 
 of the kinsmen of the leader, his gesiths, as the Saxons called 
 them ; but ultimately, they became simply volunteers who 
 joined the band from love of adventure and a military life. 
 They were the thanes (or servants) of the heretoch (or host- 
 leader). 
 
 Foundation of states. A State is founded when one 
 of these host-leaders with his band of warriors gets permanent
 
 74 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 control of a definite territory of a considerable size. And, 
 practically speaking, this always occurs in one of two ways. 
 
 Consolidation. The host-leader, after firmly establishing 
 his position as ruler of his own tribe, extends his authority over 
 neighbouring tribes, until he becomes ruler of a large territory. 
 This is what seems to have happened in the England of the 
 ninth century, when the so-called " tribal kingdoms " of the 
 Heptarchy, after fluctuating for many years between the 
 Bretivaldaship of the various tribal chiefs, became more or 
 less consolidated by conquest in the time of Egbert. The 
 same movement showed itself also in the neighbouring country 
 of Scandinavia, where, also in the ninth century, the innumer- 
 able tribes became gradually consolidated, as the result of hard 
 fighting, into the three historic kingdoms of Norway, 
 Denmark, and Sweden, under Harold Fairhair, Gorm the 
 Old, and Eric of Upsala, who, as the Heimsknngla strikingly 
 puts it, subsued all rival chiefs "with scatt (taxes), and 
 duties, and lordships." Much the same appears also to have 
 been done in the gradual consolidation of the Celtic tribes of 
 Scotland under the line of Malcolm Canmore, and of the 
 tribes of Wales under the hereditary Princes who were found 
 to be ruling the country at the Norman Conquest. In Ireland, 
 the trouble was, that no successful warrior succeeded in making 
 permanent a powerful dynasty. And, in central Europe, the 
 too ambitious efix)rts of the Prankish warriors, Clovis and his 
 successors, though brilliantly successful at first, resulted finally 
 in a similar period of anarchy, which is known by the expres- 
 sive name of the "Dark Ages." In fact, the State formed 
 by consolidation is always rather liable to break up into its 
 former elements. 
 
 Migration, Or a State is founded by the successful 
 migration and conquest by a band of warriors to and of a 
 strange country. This was the history, in very early times, 
 of the foundation of the kingdom of Lombardy (a Teutonic 
 conquest of a Latin land) ; likewise of the Visigothic king- 
 dom of Spain. Somewhat later it was the brilliant history 
 of the Normans or Northmen ; who, in the ninth century,
 
 THE STATE AND FEUDALISM 75 
 
 became the ruling power in Russia ; in the tenth founded the 
 practically independent Duchy of Normandy ; in the eleventh 
 the new kingdom of England ; in the twelfth the kingdom of 
 the Sicilies, and the short-lived kingdom of Jerusalem. 
 
 Character of the State, The new type of community 
 formed by these events differed fundamentally from that which 
 preceded it. In the first place, it was essentially territorial in 
 character. Though its rulers for some time continued to call 
 themselves by tribal names (" Kings of the English," "Kings 
 of the French," and so on), in reality the limits of their 
 authority were the limits of their territories. Whosoever 
 lived, nay, whosoever happened to be, within their dominions, 
 was their subject, their subditus, or subdued man, bound to 
 obey their commands, and, especially, bound to obey their call 
 to arms. The life of the new community was military alle- 
 giance, that faithful obedience to the orders of a commander 
 which had enabled the conqueror, with the aid of his devoted 
 followers, to place his foot on the necks of the conquered 
 tribes. Race feeling, no doubt, long counted for much ; no 
 prudent ruler could afford to neglect it. But it was no longer 
 the essential bond of unity. To begin with, the ruler and his 
 chief followers were probably of different blood, perhaps even 
 of different religion and speech, from the mass of the subject 
 population. Apart from this fact, the successful warrior, 
 knowing the value of numbers, was always trying to import 
 new followers, about whose race he cared little, provided only 
 that they could be relied on to do good service, either with 
 the sword or the pen. Finally, being generally a man of 
 superior enlightenment, the new ruler was often anxious to throw 
 open the country to foreign adventurers, whether merchants, 
 ecclesiastics, or teachers, believing that his fame and wealth 
 would thereby be increased. This policy was, as is well 
 known, the cause of much trouble in the early days of the 
 State ; but the new spirit ultimately got its way. 
 
 New type of religion. Again, the exclusiveness of the 
 old tribal systems was rudely broken down. It had rested 
 mainly, as we have seen, towards the end of its history, on the
 
 76 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 system of ancestor ivorship. But the establishment of the 
 western State was curiously coincident with the triumph of a 
 new type of religion, the chief characteristic of which was 
 universality. It may sound, at first hearing, ridiculous to 
 associate the meek religion of Christ with the aggressive 
 military institution of the State. Yet it is quite certain, that 
 Christianity had a great deal to do with breaking down tribal 
 prejudice, and with the establishment of great political com- 
 munities. To take the first and most glaring example which 
 presents itself. The conversion of Clovis to Christianity was 
 intimately connected with the formation of the brilliant, if 
 short-lived, Prankish empire. The heathen Burgundians and 
 Saxons were overcome by the Christian Franks. In the name 
 of Christianity, Charles the Great rolled back the tide of 
 Saracen invasion from the Pyrenees, and established the frontiers 
 of Christendom. Though Christianity, in its earliest days, had 
 been a mission to the poor and lowly, its great conquests in 
 Northern and Western Europe were due to the conversion of 
 kings and princes. The conversion of ^thelbirht of Kent 
 was the signal for the conversion of England. Christianity 
 passed from Court to Court of the Heptarchic kingdoms. 
 And Christianity well repaid the favour of princes. Under 
 the cry of " one church and one king," the older tribal 
 divisions were ultimately wiped out, and England became one 
 nation ; with Church and State in intimate alliance. Even 
 more obviously had Mahommedanism the result of breaking 
 down tribal divisions, and establishing mighty kingdoms, like 
 the kingdom of Akbar in India, the kingdom of Ismail in 
 Persia, and the kingdom of Mahomet at Constantinople. 
 
 The new nobility. Once more, the new political 
 organism, the State, no longer regarded custom as its guiding 
 star. By its very nature, militarism is competitive ; for 
 competition means strife, and strife is of the very essence of 
 war. Mimic warfare may be conducted according to fixed 
 tradition ; but, in that case, it is rather sport than war. 
 Real war is a death-struggle, and each combatant will strain 
 every nerve to gain the advantage. If any one will show
 
 THE STATE AND FEUDALISM -]■] 
 
 him a new dodge for defeating his enemy, he will take it 
 and be thankful. He will not ask if it is consecrated by the 
 wisdom of his ancestors. Even the very modern human- 
 itarian spirit has only succeeded in making slight inroads upon 
 the fierce competition of war ; and if it succeeds in making 
 further or serious inroads, it will destroy war, or reduce it to 
 the level of a sport, which is, of course, its object. The 
 founders of the State were, as we have seen, all successful 
 warriors, who had won success by new combinations, new 
 methods, daring disregard of tradition. It was hardly 
 probable that, under their regime^ the old traditional, customary 
 life would be continued. Their watchword was ahilttyy not 
 custom. If they saw a man who could fight well, or write 
 well, or sing well, they called him to their courts, regardless 
 of his race or social rank. They knew that their position 
 was precarious ; they could not afford to leave any stone 
 unturned to ensure their safety. And one of their surest 
 measures was to surround themselves with the ablest men on 
 whom they could lay their hands. All over Europe, the 
 break-up of patriarchal society is marked by a striking change 
 in the idea of nobility. The old noh'ility of birth, and wealth, 
 the members of the sacred families of the tribe and clan, the 
 great lords of cattle, are replaced by the royal nobility, whose 
 hall-mark is the choice of the king. In the Barbarian Codes 
 which tell us so much of early Teutonic society, the Atheling, 
 or hereditary noble, is displaced by the antrustion, or royal 
 servant. The latter may even have been at one time a slave; 
 it is enough that the king has recognized him as a comes, a 
 member of his band of followers. In England, the tribal 
 ealdorman, in Scotland the Ri or Mormaer, give way before 
 the Earl or simple thane. Doubtless, in many cases, the 
 change was more apparent than real. Doubdess the tribal 
 chief was willing to accept a title of nobility from the king ; 
 
 I just as the Irish chiefs of the fifteenth century, the O'Donnells 
 and the O'Neills, became the Irish earls of the sixteenth 
 century, the Tyrconnels and the Tyrones. But the difference 
 
 ! was, none the less, significant ; and it paved the way for further
 
 78 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 change. It marked the triumph of the State over the older 
 patriarchal society. 
 
 Feudalism, And, finally, the State was individual^ not 
 communal. Again we must be careful not to misunderstand 
 terms. The dream of the despot, who would like to govern 
 every man in his dominions by the immediate action of his 
 caprice, is, happily, never realized. But the tendency of the 
 State, from its very inception, was to break down all inter- 
 mediate barriers between itself and its individual subjects. 
 Every wise ruler is, however, aware that this can only be 
 done by degrees. The warriors who founded successful 
 States, whether they were alien adventurers, or enterprising 
 war-leaders of neighbouring tribes, found various degrees of 
 authority in existence among their subjects, exercised by men 
 who had been accustomed to deference, if not actually to 
 obedience. These men were rarely dispossessed by the 
 conqueror, unless they persisted in refusing all overtures. 
 The conqueror merely insisted that they should acknowledge 
 their authority to he derived from him. This seemed to be 
 such a purely theoretical matter, that the transaction was 
 usually attended with little difficulty. Even where the 
 demand oi fealty or faithfulness was accompanied by a demand 
 for tribute, there was little practical difficulty ; the conquered 
 chief reckoned with shrewd accuracy on getting the money 
 out of his followers, the humbler members of his tribe or clan. 
 If the conqueror chose to regard the land occupied by his 
 tribe or clan as a gift or trust for the conqueror himself, it 
 did not seem to matter much ; the important point was that 
 the tribe or the clan still kept its land. Where the native 
 chief was irreconcilable, or had been killed in the struggle, 
 the conqueror put one of his own "companions," his comes 
 or thane, into his place ; and thus, of course, obtained a really 
 stronger hold on the conquered territory. Quite naturally, 
 the conqueror's immediate vassals (as we may now begin 
 to call them) found it convenient to repeat the same process 
 with their inferiors. We have seen, in fact, that there were 
 the germs of such a relationship in the practice of cattle lending
 
 THE STATE AND FEUDALISM 79 
 
 practised by patriarchal society (p. 33). But then the 
 adoption of agriculture made land the important factor in 
 society; and so loans of land became the signs of subordination. 
 Sometimes the transaction was genuine ; as where one man 
 loaned to another land which he was really entitled to keep for 
 himself. Very often, however, it was merely fictitious ; as 
 when the inferior yielded up his own land to his superior, and 
 received it back again from him as a loan. This practice, 
 known technically as commendation, was very common in 
 Continental Europe in the Dark Ages, and was primarily 
 due to the fact that, in times of disturbance, the best chance 
 for the weak man is to acknowledge himself the vassal of a 
 strong man, who will protect him. But the tendency spread 
 beyond cattle and land. The customs of a gild, or a number 
 of gilds, their cherished rights of controlling their own 
 members, and excluding strangers from the town, came to be 
 held as privileges granted by a ruler ; and so town life was 
 brought within the same idea. Finally, even such a thing as 
 spiritual office (with the emoluments attaching thereto) was 
 held as a gift or loan from a superior ; and so indeed the 
 technical name for such a gift or loan, a benefice, came to be 
 specially associated with spiritual office. Thus the whole 
 social organism gradually assumed what we call a feudal 
 aspect, in some respects resembling the old patriarchal organ- 
 ization of groups within groups, but differing from it in the 
 important principle, that the rights of the individual were no 
 longer acquired by birthright, by membership of a social 
 group, but were at least deemed to be the grant of a superior, 
 in return for promised service. In the higher ranks, of course, 
 that service was military ; and in this the new system showed 
 its connection with the newer type of society. But, in the 
 lower ranks, money and labour service were more common. 
 The peasant rendered labour or paid rent to his lord, in return 
 for his land ; the craftsmen of a town paid an annual sum to 
 the king or earl for the charter of their privileges. Even 
 the beneficed clerk owed to his patron the duty of saying 
 prayers for the good of his soul.
 
 So A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 Evidence* We shall see more, as we go on, of the 
 nature and consequences oi feudalism. Here it is sufficient to 
 notice its place in the History of Politics. // is the connecting 
 link hetiueen purely patriarchal and purely political society. The 
 brilliant historical labours of M. Longnon have, to all intents 
 and purposes, established the geographical identity of the 
 great fiefs of the West Prankish Empire, with the tribal 
 settlements of early Gaul. Mr. Skene has been equally 
 successful in showing that the Scottish earldoms and thanages 
 of the eleventh century were really the old tribal and clan 
 chiefships in a feudal dress. Could we but get sufficient 
 evidence, we should, no doubt, find that the same was the 
 case in England and other countries. Feudal society has 
 often been reproached with vagueness and inconsistency. 
 These are precisely the qualities which we should expect 
 in a phase of development which is not in itself essential or 
 universal, but which is an easy and convenient means of 
 softening a change. In the popular form of entertainment 
 known as "dissolving views," one picture is not suddenly 
 replaced by another ; but the old picture gradually melts into 
 the new by a nebulous and misty process, rather fascinating to 
 watch, but not conveying any very clear ideas. In the 
 panorama of History, feudalism represents the blurred out- 
 lines and motley colours of the " dissolving view."
 
 CHAPTER IX 
 
 Early Political Institutions 
 
 Following our accustomed plan, having seen how the State 
 came into existence, we proceed to examine its organi-zatiorif 
 that is to say, the institutions by which its business is carried 
 on. Foremost amongst these institutions stands, of course — 
 I. The Kingship. It is a simple historical fact, that the 
 kingship of the modern State is the direct outcome of that 
 process of conquest and migration which founded the State 
 itself. Till the general break-up of things established, which 
 followed immediately on the French Revolution, many of the 
 descendants of the original conquerors of Europe continued to 
 sit on the thrones which their ancestors had established. 
 Now that the chain of hereditary succession has, in most 
 cases, been rudely broken, the position established by the 
 founders of the modern State still exists under other names. 
 Kingship is, perhaps, the most successful institution of Politics. 
 But we must be careful not to suppose that the first kings 
 were institutions ; they were merely individuals. The earliest 
 kings were, as we have seen, successful military adventurers, 
 who had managed to conquer territories of considerable size. 
 By their own personal skill and prowess they maintained their 
 I position, and enforced what they considered to be their rights. 
 What these rights were, we shall enquire a little later; here we 
 are concerned to notice, that the communities conquered by 
 ! the early host-leaders probably regarded the latter as temporary 
 } nuisances, who would in due course be removed by the hand 
 of death. Their position was totally opposed to the old ideas 
 of society ; they were much too stern, much too enterprising, 
 
 %i G
 
 82 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 much too neglectful of time-honoured practice, to suit the 
 easy-going ways of patriarchal society. They represented the 
 future, as the dying patriarchal society represented the past. 
 
 Permanence of the Kingship. The kings them- 
 selves were perfectly aware of this view. Probably, from the 
 very fact that they were successful warriors, they were men of 
 exceptional ability, not merely in war, but also in the manage- 
 ment of men. Leaders like Clovis, and Theodoric, and 
 Alaric, and Egbert, were not likely to make the mistake of 
 supposing that they could permanently maintain their positions 
 by the mere force of military prestige. And so, although they 
 clung tenaciously to their military powers, although the 
 military origin of modern kingship has never really been 
 forgotten, they began to buttress up their authority by appeals 
 to other sanctions. 
 
 Absorbs the chief ship. One of the most skilful of 
 these appeals was the appropriation by the kings of the character 
 and attributes of the tribal chief whom they had conquered or 
 dispossessed. It is possible that, in a few cases, they were, 
 really and truly, members of tribal aristocracies, though 
 probably not of the aristocracies of the tribes whom they had 
 conquered. In most cases, they were simply adventurers, 
 who had obtained their positions by sheer hard fighting. But 
 they soon, by a series of fictions which could only have been 
 accepted in a simple age, persuaded their subjects that they 
 really were members of the ancient families whom they had 
 overcome. The pedigree of an early European king generally 
 led up to some well-known Hero, who had long been 
 regarded with reverence as the mythical ancestor of the tribe 
 or tribes over which he was ruling. A simpler method by 
 which a conqueror attached himself to the tribal instincts of 
 his subjects was, by marrying the daughter of the greatest of 
 the conquered chiefs. Although by strict patriarchal law 
 none of the rights and privileges of a patriarch could go in 
 the female line, the union was valuable for sentimental purposes ; 
 and such a policy undoubtedly helped, as it has often done in 
 later times, to strengthen the position of an intruder.
 
 EARLY POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS 83 
 
 The great result of this skilful borrowing of patriarchal 
 ideas was, that the kingship quickly became hereditary. We 
 have seen that the position of host-leader was originally 
 elective^ not, of course, in the sense that it was balloted or 
 even voted for, like the chairmanship of a modern committee, 
 but in the sense that no one was entitled to it by right of birth. 
 The host-leader was chosen by the informal adherence of those 
 who admired his valour. But it was essential to the success 
 of kingship that it should become hereditary ; and, fortunately, 
 the desire to hand a great position over to one's children is 
 one of the deepest instincts of average humanity.^ So all the 
 energies of the early kings were bent towards this end ; and 
 their success was due chiefly to their skilful borrowing of 
 patriarchal ideas. The dream of an elective motiarchy is one 
 of the chimaeras of the political Utopian. According to his 
 amiable theory, freedom of election secures the best possible 
 man. In sober truth, as evidenced by the facts of history, 
 it results in one of three consequences. Either the country is 
 torn in pieces by contending factions — the fate of Poland. 
 Or the kingship is gradually shorn of its rights and 
 possessions, which are given away as bribes to important 
 electors by ambitious candidates — the fate of the Holy 
 Roman Empire. Or, finally, the electors deliberately choose 
 a nonentity, who has no enemies, and who will be an obedient 
 puppet in the hands of wire-pullers. This is the fate of 
 the electoral Presidency of the modern Republic, which is 
 a kingship in all but name. Only in times of extreme and 
 obvious danger, and even then only when the electors are 
 thoroughly honest, does an election produce a really good 
 king. 
 
 Traces of elective monarchy. As a matter of fact, 
 in the great majority of the European monarchies, the 
 tradition of an elective leader lingered for a few generations, 
 with just suflicient vitality to show that it had once been 
 genuine. It resulted, practically, in the notion that an heir- 
 
 1 Modern instances, of course, are to be found, e.g. Cromwell, and 
 Napoleon, both of whom tried to make their positions hereditary.
 
 84 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 apparent might be rejected for positive infirmity, whether of 
 body or mind. But, though the hereditary principle was 
 accepted, it was not the modern but the ancient or patri- 
 archal form of it, which for a long time prevailed, and 
 which gave the succession to the eldest male of the royal 
 house, not to the son of the last occupant of the throne. This 
 older form of hereditary succession lingered in Russia until 
 the seventeenth century. 
 
 Becomes religious. By these means, the kingship 
 became an institution, or permanent machine for carrying on 
 the business of government. People came to look upon it as 
 natural and inevitable that a king should rule over them. But 
 the early kings made another admirable move when they 
 assumed a religious position, by allying themselves with 
 the Church. We have seen something of the origin of 
 this alliance (p. 76) ; here it is only necessary to call 
 attention to the well-known fact of the close connection 
 between the kingship and the Church, in the early days of the 
 State. Throughout all Christendom, bishops and priests 
 were the most intimate counsellors and most enthusiastic 
 supporters of the Crown ; and the rich gifts of the kings were 
 amply repaid by the halo of sanctity which the grateful 
 Church threw around the person and office of the king. 
 From the day of his accession, when the sacred oil was 
 poured upon his head, to the day of his death, when his grave 
 was blessed by the Church, the monarch was surrounded and 
 guarded by ecclesiastics. In Oriental countries, in Mahoni- 
 medan States, the union is even closer ; for there the Head 
 of the State is also Head of the Church. But there is actu- 
 ally an example in outlying Christendom, in which the arch- 
 bishopric of the Church has become hereditary in the line of 
 secular rulers. And, even in Europe, the intimate connection 
 between the king and the Church was the best possible safe- 
 guard against any revival of patriarchalism, in connection with 
 ancestor worship. 
 
 2. The Council. We have seen (p. 73) that in the rude 
 beginnings of monarchy, the host-leader is found always to be
 
 EARLY POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS 85 
 
 surrounded by his follotuers or companions^ men devoted 
 entirely to his service, on the terms that he shall provide them 
 with maintenance, and opportunities for distinction. As the 
 host-leader developed into the king, this body of followers 
 became the council of the kingdom. Placed in the midst of 
 a hostile country, the king and his followers were absolutely 
 essential to one another's safety. Without their support, the 
 king could not hold his conquest ; without his master mind, 
 they would fall victims in detail to racial hostility. The 
 success of the king meant the enrichment of his followers ; 
 the contentment and prosperity of his followers meant the 
 safety of the king. We may put aside as premature any 
 definite theories about the right of the council, in those early 
 days, to control the actions of the king. All our accounts of 
 the relationship between the early king and his council go to 
 show, that the former, if he chose to run the risk of becoming 
 unpopular, could do what he liked. Although, perhaps, the 
 council gained somewhat in the eyes of the king's subjects 
 by being regarded as the successor of the old tribal council of 
 elders, yet, in reality, it was the body of the king s servants, 
 chosen by him at his pleasure. Nevertheless, the existence 
 of the council did soon undoubtedly become a substantial 
 check on the despotic tendencies of the king. A theory 
 grew up, that a good king consulted his council frequently, 
 that he listened to its advice. And from this point the 
 step was comparatively short, to the doctrine that the king 
 ought to consult, and, finally, that he must consult his council. 
 And thus, in reality, the council is the germ of what we 
 call constitutional go'uernment. But, long before it became 
 a bulwark of popular liberties, the council had rendered 
 invaluable service to the kingship as an institution, and this 
 in at least four ways. 
 
 («) It preserved the continuity. Kingship may be 
 perpetual ; but, in fact, the individual king dies. And, 
 between the death of one king and the succession of another, 
 there lies a critical moment. The forces of anarchy are 
 ready to break out. " The king died on the following day
 
 86 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 . . . then there was tribulation soon in the land, for every man 
 that could forthwith robbed another," says an old chronicler. 
 There is always the chance that old ideas may revive, and set 
 people longing for the good old days when every one did that 
 which was right in his own eyes. We must remember that a 
 successful monarchy really does run counter to a good many 
 cherished practices. It does not, for example, permit of 
 blood-feuds or tribal forays ; it probably has incurred the 
 resentment of old religions ; it has sanctioned practices which 
 ancient prejudice regards as monstrous ; it has, probably, 
 exacted a good deal of tribute. So there are always people 
 waiting for a good opportunity to revolt against it. But the 
 existence of the council tides over the dangerous moment. 
 Though, in strict theory, the death of the king dissolves his 
 council ; in fact, the members of council hold together, in 
 hopes of being appointed by his successor. And, in the 
 meantime, they keep the political machine going. 
 
 (b) It preserved the traditions. One of the greatest 
 dangers to the newly-established kingship is, the risk of 
 offending its subjects by exhibitions of caprice. It has to 
 deal with a community living according to immemorial custom. 
 It is bound to effect alterations to a certain extent ; but, if it 
 is wise, it will do so as little as possible. Above all, it must 
 avoid unnecessary changes. It is almost better, under some 
 conditions, to persevere in a bad policy, than to change it for 
 a good one. The average man, especially if he be of a 
 patriarchal type, suspects and hates change. But a body of 
 councillors is far less likely to be capricious than a single ruler ; 
 its members will, possibly, have something to lose by a change 
 of policy. Its influence will, in the vast majority of cases, 
 be against change. 
 
 [c) It brolce ttie obloquy. As we have said, govern- 
 ment, especially a newly-established government, is bound to be 
 unpopular, at least to a certain extent. If the whole of the 
 criticism provoked by its acts were to fall on the head of a 
 single individual, his position would become very precarious. 
 But if the blame can be distributed amongst his advisers, or if
 
 EARLY POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS 87 
 
 even, in extreme cases, one or more of these advisers can be 
 sacrificed to the popular discontent, much will be gained by 
 the Head of the State. Being an impersonal authority, a 
 council can stand criticism much better than an individual. 
 This may not be a very dignified or enjoyable function of the 
 council, but it is a very valuable one from this point of view of 
 the State. 
 
 {d) It increased the activity. The limits of the 
 activity of a single individual are soon reached. Even a king 
 like Frederick the Great cannot know, personally, very much 
 of what is going on in his dominions. But he would know still 
 less if it were not for his councillors. By their own observa- 
 tions, and through their agents, they find out things which are 
 going on, and repeat them to the king. As with knowledge, 
 so with action. The king can, personally, do but little. 
 Even in early days, when the king was still, in the main, a 
 warrior, he could not personally protect all his dominions at 
 once. Still less could he, when the business of his position 
 became (as it did become) enormously increased, conduct it 
 all himself. But his council could be increased to any size ; 
 and thus he could, as it were, provide himself with an unlimited 
 number of hands. 
 
 3. Tlie local agents. Hitherto we have assumed 
 that the king's councillors have, save for short intervals of 
 absence, surrounded his person, either on the battle-field 
 or in the palace or hall. This was, as we have seen, the 
 old idea. The war-leader's companions, in time of peace, 
 fed at his table and lived in his house. And the idea 
 has never been abandoned. The Court of the monarch, 
 even in modern times, is actually in attendance on the person 
 of the king. But, when the freebooting leader became the 
 king of a territory, he required supporters, not only round his 
 throne, but also all over his territory. We have already, in 
 the preceding chapter, had a glimpse of the readiest plan. 
 The conqueror accepted the allegiance of such of the old 
 patriarchal authorities as were willing to submit to him, and 
 continued them in thqir old positions, as his representatives.
 
 88 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 It was a dangerous practice, though, perhaps, less dangerous 
 than forcible dispossession. The king felt safer where the 
 circumstances allowed him to place one of his own trusted 
 followers in the room of a dead or banished chief. And, 
 as the old nobles died out, the polic}'- of replacing them by the 
 " king's thegns " was steadily pursued, until, by a silent but 
 revolutionary process, the country had been mapped out into 
 districts, each in charge of a representative of the central 
 government. In all probability, the districts themselves would 
 be little changed. In England, for example, the local divisions 
 which existed until the beginning of the present century, 
 represented in the main the ancient units of patriarchal society. 
 The county or shire was, in many cases at least, the district of 
 a tribal settlement — Sussex of the South Saxons, Dorsetshire 
 of the Dorsaetas, Somerset of the Somersaetas, and so on. 
 In other cases, as Dr. Freeman pointed out, it was an artificial 
 district commanded by a fortified town, such as Bedfordshire, 
 Huntingdonshire, Derbyshire, and so on. But this was a 
 much later formation. And there are strong reasons to believe 
 that the hundred^ the other great local division of the Middle 
 Ages, will ultimately be proved to have been the territory of 
 a clan. In later times, of course, the subdivision becomes 
 more minute, and we get the single manor,, under its lord ; 
 but enough has been said to show how feudalism began. 
 
 We must not, of course, suppose that the man who was 
 placed in charge of a local district was entirely excluded from 
 the Council which surrounded the person of the king. On 
 the contrary, there seems to be little doubt that the greatest 
 of the king's subordinates, the earls in England and Scotland, 
 the dukes and counts on the Continent, always sat, as of right, 
 in the Council, at any rate on its solemn days of session. We 
 distinguish in the Witan of the Anglo-Saxon kings, beside 
 the royal princes and the great ecclesiastics, two classes of 
 people, the ealdormen and the thegns. The former undoubt- 
 edly had a local position as heads of the shires ; the latter 
 were, probably, the humbler followers of the king, who lived 
 permanently at his court. But it is unlikely that the smaller
 
 EARLY POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS 89 
 
 local representatives, the " landed thegns *' (as we may call 
 them) sat in the Council. 
 
 To conclude this chapter, we may ask. What were the 
 duties imposed upon these local representatives by the early 
 kings? And we shall hardly get a better answer than by 
 referring once more to the picturesque words of the Heims- 
 kringla, which describe Harold Fairhair as subduing all 
 Norway " with scatt, and duties, and lordships/' 
 
 {a) Scatt or Tribute is, of course, one of the prime objects 
 of the conqueror. Historians sometimes speak of primitive 
 warriors as though they fought simply for the love of fighting. 
 No doubt there are some races — for example, the Maoris of 
 New Zealand half a century ago, — to whom the excitement of 
 the battle seems really to be an end in itself. But in the 
 majority of cases, ancient and modern, the stimulus of an 
 aggressive war has been either revenge^ or, in one form or 
 another, plunder. Sometimes the plunder has been merely of 
 a temporary kind, as in the raids of the Vikings. But the 
 warrior who is a little more far-seeing than the Viking, looks 
 forward to systematic and continuous plunder. To this end, 
 he establishes a kingdom ; and when he has established it, 
 he sets to work to exact a steady supply of tribute. Doubt- 
 less, to a man of the temperament we have tried to describe, 
 there is something in itself attractive in ruling over a mass 
 of subjects. But the notion that a ruler lives for the good of 
 his subjects is a very rare development in the early days of 
 the State. The real importance of tribute in the beginnings 
 of political organization may be most vividly realized in the 
 Mahommedan States of the East, such as the Empire of 
 Akbar in India in the sixteenth century, and in the Persian 
 and Turkish Empires at the present day. As Mr. Baden 
 Powell has well pointed out, it is, in its origin, primarily a 
 levy on agricultural produce, a " share of the heap on the 
 threshing-floor ; " and, in the case of the Moghul Empire, it 
 rose as high as one-third of the produce. In the harder-won 
 conquests of the founders of the European States, a more 
 decent disguise was adopted. The conquerors appropriated
 
 90 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 the customary offerings made by the tribesmen to their ancient 
 chiefs, the food rents^ and feast'ings of patriarchal times. 
 Also they appropriated the lands which had been set apart 
 for the maintenance of the patriarchal chiefs, and let them 
 out to tenants of their own who paid them a return in money 
 or kind. They established, probably also by virtue of ancient 
 custom, their privileged claims to certain profitable incidents, 
 such as "royal" fish, mines of precious metals, the contents 
 of wrecks, and the great game of the forests. All these 
 miscellaneous items, lumped together, were known in England 
 as the " farm of the shire ; " and long formed the bulk of the 
 royal revenue. Sometimes a more direct demand was made 
 of an additional sum for a special purpose, e.g, the Danegelt 
 in England, and the Dime in France. Privileged towns paid, 
 as we have said (p. 79), substantial sums in return for guarantees 
 of their trade privileges. Only, in Western Europe, there 
 was always some decent excuse, such as custom or bargain, 
 for a demand of tribute ; the Oriental meekness, which submits 
 to the absolute demands of the States tax-gatherer, has hardly 
 been known in the arena of modern civilization. 
 
 (^) Duties. Besides tribute, the conqueror has one other 
 imperative need, viz. military service. He has, of course, his 
 own special followers, his " professional soldiers " as we 
 might say ; and he takes care to recruit their ranks, by making 
 it worth the while of the most enterprising young men among 
 his subjects to join the service. But, besides this volunteer 
 army, he must have a reserve defensive force, in case some 
 rival warrior should attempt to repeat at his expense the 
 experiment which he has successfully conducted at the 
 expense of others. And so he lays it down generally, that 
 every man is bound to serve if called upon — the able-bodied 
 as combatants, the feebler as makers and repairers of roads, 
 bridges, and forts. Often an invidious distinction is drawn 
 between those who are actually expected to serve, and those 
 who are debarred by reason of social inferiority or heterodoxy 
 in religion. But these do not escape ; they are subjected to 
 a special tax in lieu of service. The practice afterwards
 
 EARLY POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS 9» 
 
 spreads, and a general commutation of war-service for tax- 
 ation is adopted. Then, perhaps, after a few generations, a 
 reforming i<.ing renews the liabihty to personal service — but 
 the taxation is not remitted. 
 
 (c) Lordships. These were,in fact, the great and character- 
 istic engine by which the head of the State obtained his taxes 
 and duties. In days in which means of communication were 
 very imperfect, it was impossible for the central government to 
 keep in touch with all its subjects. And so, as we have seen 
 (p. 78), the conquered territory was parcelled out among 
 the followers of the king, either his own fellow-adventurers, 
 or patriarchal authorities who had accepted his rule. From 
 the point of view of the king, these officials were servants ; 
 but, from the point of view of the inhabitants of their districts, 
 they were lords. In order that they might fulfil their tasks 
 of collecting tribute and soldiers, they were allowed to 
 exercise a good deal of authority over their districts. This 
 authority, no doubt, in many cases was looked upon, by 
 themselves and their subjects, as being of the old patriarchal 
 character ; but by the king it was always carefully treated as 
 a delegation from himself, and, in fact, it was largely the 
 knowledge that the local potentate would be backed, if 
 need were, by the royal army, that made his administration 
 effective. As the patriarchal nobility died out, the royal 
 character of the local official became more and more obvious ; 
 until at last he came to be looked upon exclusively as a royal 
 nominee, unless, indeed, as not unfrequently happened, he 
 tried to set up on his own account, as a feudal magnate. 
 
 Not only, however, was the local authority responsible for 
 tribute and for soldiers ; he was also answerable for the peace 
 of his district. It is one of the most honourable traditions of 
 monarchy, that it has everywhere set its face against internal 
 disorder. In patriarchal times, as we have seen, a man was 
 guaranteed against violence by his tribe, later by his clan or 
 gild. But this protection virtually resolved itself into a 
 liability to exact revenge ; and the plan did not, therefore, 
 tend to complete tranquillity. The monarchy, in its earlier
 
 92 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 days, preferred to entrust the maintenance of security to its 
 own agents, at any rate in the case of the lower ranks of 
 society. And so the local representative of the crown was 
 entrusted with what we should call very extensive police 
 poiverSf and, in return, his personal safety was protected by 
 exceptional penalties. In the earliest days of the monarchy, 
 the fact that a slain man was a " king's servant " rendered 
 his slayer liable to a three-fold murder fine. Somewhat later, 
 the same policy reappeared, in the same condemnation pro- 
 nounced upon any man who should dare to raise his hand 
 against his lord. For, with the duty of collecting tribute 
 from the people of his district, with the power of enrolling 
 them for military service, with the exercise over them of 
 disciplinary authority, the State's local representative had 
 indeed become the lord of his neighbours ; and so the words 
 of the Heimskringla are explained.
 
 CHAPTER X 
 The State and Property 
 
 No political institution is of greater importance, none has 
 been the subject of greater controversy, than the institution 
 of property. There is none, therefore, more fit for the 
 application of the historical method^ which knows no pre- 
 judices and admits no passions, but simply relates facts. 
 
 We begin, of course, by asking the question — What is 
 property ? And, leaving aside technicalities, a good simple 
 answer to the question is, that it is the right vested in a human 
 being, or a limited number of hiimati beings^ to absorb for his or 
 their own benefit the various advantages which can be derived 
 from a physical subject matter. 
 
 A right. There are one or two points to be specially 
 noted in this definition. First, what do we mean by a right P 
 And, again putting aside technicalities, we may define a right 
 as being a poaver enforced by public sentiment. If I have 
 bought a book in an open and honest way, public sentiment 
 approves of my dealing with the book as I please. In early 
 times, public opinion is expressed only in the vague form of 
 custom ; in later days, it is definitely expressed in legislation, 
 and enforced by tribunals and officials. It sometimes happens, 
 that the exercise of a right is opposed to public sentiment, 
 either because there are special circumstances which render a 
 particular application of it unpopular, or because public senti- 
 ment has changed. Nevertheless, a right is really the creation 
 of public sentiment, />(3J-/ or present. 
 
 Vested in human beings. Again, we have said that 
 property is a right vested in a human being or human beings, 
 
 93
 
 94 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 Many of the instincts and desires which have led to the 
 appearance of property among mankind are obviously present 
 in the brute creation. No one who has watched a dog bury 
 a bone, or has seen a monkey pilfer nuts, will for a moment 
 doubt this fact. But, nevertheless, we do not speak of animals 
 having property. Why ? Simply because public sentiment 
 does not support them in the exercise of their desires. We 
 recognize, perhaps, very faintly, the moral right of the 
 domesticated animal to a bare maintenance out of the pro- 
 duce of his labours — "Thou shalt not muzzle the ox that 
 treadeth out the corn." But we do not hesitate, if need be, 
 to withhold the corn, or to slaughter the ox. 
 
 In limited numbers. Again, property is a right vested 
 in a human being or a limited number of human beings. The 
 essence of it, as its name implies, is the appropriation^ the 
 making special to an individual or a small group of indi- 
 viduals, of a part of the common stock of things. Some- 
 times, it is true, we speak of public property ; but this is really 
 a contradiction in terms. We signify, in fact, that the thing 
 to which we allude is not any one's property at all, and, 
 therefore, that any one may use it. When we really mean 
 that the thing in question is claimed by a very large but 
 definite body, we do not use the word property, but some 
 word which conveys a different idea. Thus we say, that 
 England is the territory of the English people. If we called 
 it their property, we should at once have to admit that no 
 individual Englishmen could have any part of it as his 
 property ; which is notoriously untrue. 
 
 Exercised over subject matter. Once more, these 
 rights must be exercised over physical subject matter, for that 
 alone is really capable of appropriation. In a figurative way 
 we can, of course, speak o^ property in ideas ; but the extreme 
 difficulty which we find in protecting such property, shows 
 that it differs entirely from property in the correct sense of 
 the term. Ideas are spontaneous, the same ideas may spring 
 up independently in thousands of minds, they have no definite 
 beginning or ending, they are intangible. How can they be
 
 THE STATE AND PROPERTY 95 
 
 protected by agencies similar to those which we employ for 
 the protection of physical subject matter ? 
 
 For general purposes. Finally, the right of property 
 
 is a right to absorb the various advantages (known and un- 
 known) which are derivable from a thing. Here is the real 
 difficulty of the subject, and the key to its history. As the 
 jurists say, property is a genera/ right. If I have borrowed 
 a horse simply to ride from London to Putney, I do not 
 speak of him as my property. Even if I have jobbed him 
 for a whole season, I do not speak of him as mine. It is 
 only when I am related to the horse in such a way that I 
 may, if I please, ride him or drive him, or put him to plough 
 or to work in a milk-cart, may kill him or sell him, give him 
 away or turn him out to grass, in fact do anything with him 
 I please which does not conflict with the public sentiment of 
 the community, that I am entitled to speak of him as my 
 property. With the abolition of slavery, there ceased to be 
 property in human beings. Yet we all know that one man 
 may have special rights over another, e. g. a master over his 
 servant, a husband over his wife, and so on. But these are 
 limited and definite rights. 
 
 A modem idea. Therefore, we make a great mistake 
 if we take our very modern idea of property, and, looking 
 back into the early history of mankind, expect to find it 
 realized by people in those days. We start with the wrong 
 question. We should not ask — In whom was property vested 
 in those days ? but. Was there any property at all ? 
 
 If this sounds to modern ears an absurd question, it may 
 become less absurd when we consider a modern illustration. 
 Broadly speaking, the high seas are not, at the present day, 
 the ^ro/>^r/y of any one. Why? For the simple reason that, 
 at present y the only advantage to be derived from them is the 
 convenience of traffic. And as there is room enough and to 
 spare for all the ships in the world to pass over them, the 
 question of property in them does not arise. But we can very 
 easily foresee that it might arise ; in fact, we can guess pretty 
 shrewdly the lines 011 which it will arise some day. If the
 
 96 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 practice of laying ocean cables extends very much, or if 
 coastal waters no longer supply sufficient fish for the world's 
 consumption, we shall soon have the high seas eagerly claimed 
 as territory by different States. And, if this occurs, we shall 
 uhimately go a step furtlier, and see the territory of each State 
 divided up as property among its members, as the advantages 
 to be derived from it increase. We have reached the first 
 stage already, in what are called territorial waters ; where the 
 advantages to be derived from fishing, shipping, and gunning, 
 are sufficient to induce States to appropriate. 
 
 This then is the key to the history of property as an 
 institution — the groivth of kuo<wletlge. As men become more 
 and more awake to the advantages to be derived from the use 
 of physical things, the more anxiously and completely do 
 they appropriate them. And thus it was impossible for us 
 to study the history of proi)erty, until we realized how man's 
 knowledge of the resources of Nature had gradually grown. 
 Now we are in a position to summarize it clearly. 
 
 In the first, or hunting stage of society, the requirements 
 of men are limited to himting-grounds, camping-grounds, and 
 weapons. Men know that, the more the game is hunted in 
 a particular district, the less there will be to hunt. They 
 therefore manifest great jealousy of any interference with 
 their hunting-grounds. Similarly, their very existence may 
 depend on a camp with a proper supply of water. They 
 resent, therefore, any occupation of spots which they are 
 accustomed to use for camping. Unhajipily, the reports of 
 travellers upon savage society^ though dealing largely with the 
 physical character of primitive lucaponsy do not, apparently, 
 tell us much about the savage's ideas respecting their owner- 
 ship. But we shall probably not be far wrong in assuming, 
 that weapons were among the very earliest examples of 
 property ; the frequency with which they were used, die 
 extreme importance of their being kept in good order, the 
 ease with which they could be physically controlled, would 
 rapidly generate the idea of appropriation. The germ of 
 property, it nuist again be said, is user ; the captured booty
 
 THE STATE AND PROPERTY 97 
 
 is readily shared, but the favourite and often-used weapon is 
 jealously guarded. There is some evidence also to show that 
 religious paraphernalia, such as sacred belts and feathers and 
 stones, are early appropriated to groups of men. But a 
 savage's weapon can only be used by one man at a time ; and 
 so it lends itself the more readily to appropriation. 
 
 The hunting country. If we want to realize the 
 savage's immature notions of the advantages to be derived 
 from land, we may take the modern example of a hunting 
 country. The Hunt and its Master do not object to people 
 walking over the land, to pasturing cattle and sheep upon it, 
 to growing corn upon it, or even to building houses and living 
 upon it. So long as people do not disturb the foxes or put 
 up barbed wire, they are regarded with toleration. The Hunt 
 regards the country as its own, and jealously resents any 
 trespass by a strange pack. But it does not claim the 
 country as its property. 
 
 Pastoral stage. When we travel a stage further, we 
 find changes which develop still further the rudimentary idea 
 of property. The continued association of the herdsman 
 with his cattle and sheep, his perception of the increased 
 advantages which can be derived from them — their hides, 
 wool, and milk — strengthens the relationship between him 
 and them. In this stage, movable chattels (^i. e. "cattle") 
 may fairly be said to have reached the stage of property, even 
 of individual property. But so also must wives, children, and 
 slaves. As we have seen, the perception of the value of 
 human labour leads to a desire to appropriate it. The 
 words which, in primitive law, signify the relation between 
 a patriarch and his cattle, signify also the relationship between 
 him and his wives, children, and slaves. It is only in later 
 times that the different classes become differentiated. At 
 first, it would seem that birth in the patriarch's household is 
 the normal title to property. A very interesting old Swedish 
 formula, in the primitive procedure for theft, makes the 
 claimant say, that the ox alleged to have been stolen was bred 
 and reared in his stall. But it is probable that, as the tribe
 
 98 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 broke up into clans, and the clans into households, the old 
 idea, that booty was the general prize of the pack, died out ; 
 and the successful cattle-reiver appropriated the captive of 
 his own hands. Finally, as the notion of exchange developed, 
 a man claimed that which he had taken in exchange, or bought ; 
 but there is abundant evidence to show that, even in historical 
 times, purchase, especially of flocks and herds, was looked 
 upon with great suspicion, and that the man who was found 
 with a strange ox in his possession, ran a strong risk of being 
 branded as a thief. Only in markets and such like well- 
 known places, and before proper witnesses, could a sale be 
 safely conducted. And in English law at the present day, 
 the sale in open market has a very special force, which reminds 
 us of this ancient rule. 
 
 So far, then, we may tabulate our stages in the history of 
 property thus — 
 (i) User. 
 
 (2) Production. 
 
 (3) Seizure (perhaps). 
 
 (4) Exchange. 
 
 Agricultural stage. Now we have arrived at the 
 agricultural stage. And here, it is evident, we are on the 
 brink of a great development of the idea of property in land. 
 The pastoralist regards his " country " much as the hunter. 
 It is the feeding-ground for the herds of the tribe. Perhaps 
 the jealousy of strangers is a little keener, because tame cattle 
 are easier to steal than wild game. Probably also, the user 
 which the individual tribesman may make of the tribal land 
 is more strictly defined. But there is as yet no individual 
 right in land, for land is still regarded only as pasture and 
 hunting-ground ; and there is no need of partition for these 
 purposes. But the agriculturist soon forms news ideas. As 
 each new improvement in cultivation makes land more valu- 
 able, the clan, or the family, or the man who made the 
 improvement, becomes less willing to see it pass into the 
 hands of others, less willing to move on to other land on 
 which less labour has been expended. And so agricultural
 
 THE STATE AND PROPERTY 99 
 
 land became (as we have seen) appropriated to the clan, 
 amongst whose members it was periodically interchanged ; and, 
 finally, even this redistribution ceased, and the family, ulti- 
 mately the individual, became permanently associated with a 
 specific piece of land. 
 
 StiH far from modern ideas. This is a long step ; 
 but it is still very far from bringing us to the modern notion 
 ofpriimte property in land. All that we have arrived at is, 
 that the same man may go on year after year ploughing the 
 same piece of land, and, it may be, his children after him. 
 That would not satisfy the landowner of the present day. 
 
 Limited user. Observe, in the first place, the man may 
 only use the land for agriculture. It is true, that one of the 
 first real social results of agriculture was to substitute the 
 wooden house for the herdsman*s tent ; and the farmer was 
 allowed to build himself a house in the village, and to inhabit 
 it permanently. Also, he was allowed to enclose a little ioft 
 or garden space, and a croft or meadow, both near his house, 
 for the supply of his family and domestic animals. But the 
 bulk of "his" land (if we may call it so) he had still not 
 only to plough and reap, but to plough and reap in the regular 
 way at fixed times. (See p. 52,) If he had not, his fellow- 
 villagers would have complained. If he had attempted, for 
 example, to keep cattle and sheep in his strips, he would have 
 ruined their crops ; and he would likewise have incurred the 
 jealousy of those members of the clan who still longed for 
 broad pastures, and who regarded the new practice of 
 agriculture with dislike. The world's history is full of this 
 quarrel, from the days when patricians and plebeians in 
 Rome fought over the State lands, to the days when the 
 squatters (sheep-farmers) of Australia were at loggerheads 
 with the selectors (agriculturists) over a precisely similar 
 question. 
 
 No alienation* Again, the farmer had his house and 
 land, but he might not sell them. The agricultural village of 
 primitive times was, as we have explained (p. 58), a very 
 '* close " thing. No strangers could get a footing in it, at least
 
 100 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 without the unanimous consent of the village. And the 
 members of the clan would not want to buy lands, because they 
 could get them for nothing. 
 
 Action of the State. But the appearance of the State, 
 combined, no doubt, with economic influences, accomplished 
 the final stage in tlie evolution oi property. The results of its 
 policy may be said to have been two-fold. It created a land^ 
 lord clasSy and it dissolved the village community. 
 
 I. Landlordism. As we have seen (p. 88), one of the 
 earliest measures of the State was, to plant its representatives 
 in the various localities of its territory, for the purposes of 
 exacting tribute, levying soldiers, and maintaining order. We 
 may be fairly sure that, when the State made their appoint- 
 ments, it had no clear intention of converting the districts 
 entrusted to its representatives into property. When the 
 Crown at the present day appoints a man Collector of Customs 
 at the port of Liverpool, or Lord Lieutenant of the county 
 of Surrey, it does not make him owner of the soil on which 
 Liverpool stands, or of the county of Surrey. In the language 
 of early times, it was lordship the State meant to confer, not 
 property. 
 
 Inlieritance. But this lordship tended to ripen into 
 property. In the first place, the State's representative, as 
 we have seen (p. 87), probably was either a tribal or a clan 
 chief, or stood in the place of one. But the position of a 
 tribal or clan chief was hereditary. It is not surprising, there- 
 fore, to find that lordship became hereditary also ; much in 
 the same way as the Crown itself had done (p. 83). This 
 was, of course, one of the most striking features of feudalism. 
 But an office which can be inherited soon begins to look very 
 like property. 
 
 Rent, In the second place, the Crown's representative 
 had to pay a certain sum of money as the equivalent of his 
 lordship. If he did not, his lordship was taken away, and 
 given to some one else. In well-governed countries, the 
 amount which had to be rendered was fixed and reasonable; 
 but this very fact quickly tended to obscure its origin. In
 
 THE STATE AND PROPERTY loi 
 
 the course of a few generations, the representative would come 
 to look upon his district as his owriy subject to payment of a 
 fixed return, or rent. 
 
 Profit, For, in the third place, the State's representative 
 was from the first intended to make a profit out of his office. 
 The wholesome system of paying State officials by fixed 
 salaries, and rigidly demanding an account of all receipts, is 
 a very modern innovation ; and, even now, is very far from 
 complete, even in civilized countries. In the early days of 
 the State, the universal practice was to compound with the 
 official for a fixed sum, and to let him keep all the surplus 
 which he could collect. There was, therefore, a direct in- 
 ducement to the official to increase his demands upon the 
 people he was set to govern. And this, also, caused him to 
 look upon his district as his oivn. 
 
 Land. Finally, it must again be remembered that almost 
 everything in the way of taxes in early times came directly 
 from t\iQ projits of agriculture. In other words, it came direct 
 from the la?id. It was natural, therefore, that the Crown's 
 representative should look to the land of his subjects as the 
 real security for the tribute he intended to collect. And this 
 point of view had two important results, as population in- 
 creased and land became, accordingly, more valuable. It 
 made it very tempting for a lord to turn out one occupier who 
 did not pay his tribute. It also induced him to encourage 
 people to bring fresh land into cultivation, because such a 
 course meant more tribute. Such fresh settlements were made 
 at the lord's direction, and, of course, within the limits of his 
 district. By thus dealing with and disposing of the land of 
 his district, the lord became more and more to look upon 
 himself, and to be looked upon, as the owner of his district. 
 The " lord of land," as the old documents call him, became 
 the landlord of modern times. 
 
 It may be said, by hasty observers, that there is nothing 
 really of importance in this change, that it is really the old set 
 of things with a new set of names, that " lord," and " man," 
 and "tribute," merely become '* landlord," and "tenant,"
 
 102 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 and " rent.'* But a moment's thought will show this to be a 
 fallacy. It assumes that the value of land nvill always be the 
 same; whereas it is notorious that the value of land steadily 
 increases with the increase of population, /'. e, with the de- 
 mands made upon it. And the question is, tuho is to have the 
 increase in value, or, as it is often called, the unearned incre- 
 ment P Let jc represent the total annual value of an acre of 
 land in the thirteenth century. Let a represent the amount 
 which the State gets in tribute, ^ the amount received by 
 the " lord " (over and above that which he pays to the 
 State), y the amount pocketed by the occupier ; and suppose 
 a, Pi and y together just equal x. Now step forward six 
 centuries. The value of the annual produce of that same acre 
 may possibly be quite five times .v. Improved methods of 
 cultivation have rendered it much more productive, or coal 
 has been found under it, or it has been wanted for building, 
 or a valuable spring of water has been struck on it. Into 
 whose pockets does this increase go? And, broadly speaking, 
 all the world over, this increase has gone into the pockets of 
 the landlord class, who have succeeded in treating the land 
 as their property. As a general rule, they have succeeded 
 in preventing the State from increasing the sum payable to it 
 by themselves ; only in a comparatively small number of cases 
 have their " tenants " succeeded in preventing them exacting 
 increased tribute, in the form of rent. The consequence has 
 been, that, whilst the State above and the tenant below have 
 gained comparatively little from the increase in the value of 
 land, the intermediate, or landlord class, has became enor- 
 mously wealthy, especially in those countries in which progress 
 has been greatest. Landlordism has been the most splendidly 
 rewarded of all political services. The class which began 
 as revenue collectors, and local maintainers of order, has 
 become onvners of the soil, and arbiters of the comfort and 
 prosperity of millions of human beings. In the old centres 
 of industry, the position of the landlord is much less marked, 
 inasmuch as the old tribute pressed less heavily on the urban 
 classes, and they were less dependent on a particular piece of
 
 THE STATE AND PROPERTY 103 
 
 soil for their existence. Nevertheless, the existence of valu- 
 able market rights, tolls, and other town privileges in the 
 hands of great proprietors, reveals the fact that the tendencies 
 in the town were the same as in the country, though the 
 opportunities were less. And, where towns have grown up 
 since the development of the institution oi property in land, the 
 profits reaped by the fortunate landlords who have owned 
 property in their sites have, of course, been colossal. 
 
 2. Dissolution of tlie village community. It 
 would, however, be quite wrong to suppose that the develop- 
 ment of lordship into landlordship is solely accountable for the 
 institution of property in land. It accounts chiefly for great 
 landowners ; but there are small landowners as well as great. 
 
 In a sense, as we have seen, the ordinary villager of the 
 early agricultural epoch was in one sense a landonvner. That 
 is to say, he probably could not, in most cases, be turned out 
 of his land so long as he conformed to the village customs, so 
 long as he paid, in the form of labour or money, his share ot 
 the village liabilities, and so long as he conformed to the 
 customs of the village. But he had not the two important 
 rights which every owner of property now looks upon as part 
 of his ordinary powers, viz. the right to dispose of his interest 
 by sale or gift, and the right to use his land as he thinks fit. 
 Under these two heads we may consider the dissolution of the 
 village community. 
 
 (a) Disposal of interest. From the beginning of its 
 history, we find the State manifesting a dislike to the village com- 
 munity. The military character of the State inclines it to deal 
 with individuals rather than with communities. It prefers to deal 
 with the village through the individual lord ; where it recog- 
 nizes the existence of the village group, it deals with it through 
 its representatives (as we shall hereafter see). In the minds 
 of the early kings there was, manifestly, a feeling that the 
 existence of the village brotherhood was, in a way, a danger 
 to its own authority. There are abundant traces in the Bar- 
 barian Laws of a determination on the part of the kings that 
 the village shall not take upon itself to punish its own members.
 
 104 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 Another claim the kings obstinately insist upon, viz. that a 
 stranger, furnished by them with " letters of settlement," shall 
 be allowed to take up land in the village. In early times 
 there was no physical difficulty in such a course ; land was 
 plentiful, on the borders of every village there was waste land. 
 But it was hateful to the villagers, just as hateful as it would 
 be to a modern household to have a " paying guest " forcibly 
 thrust upon it. The newcomer might be a spy in disguise ; 
 to a certain extent the village would be responsible for his 
 misdeeds; he would probably have new-fangled notions of 
 farming. But the kings got their way. 
 
 Sales, A still further step was taken when the State 
 began to recognize sales of village land, at any rate sales to 
 outsiders. There is some reason to believe that, inside the 
 village group, a process had long been going on by which 
 several holdings had accumulated in a single hand. In this 
 way we may account for the appearance of the prosperous 
 yeoman class, which is such a striking feature of the later 
 Middle Ages in Europe. But to sell to a stranger was long 
 forbidden, and only after a severe struggle was the right 
 established. There can be little doubt that the most power- 
 ful ally of the State in this matter was the Church, which, 
 though provided for to a certain extent within the village 
 system, by the custom of paying ttthesy succeeded in acquiring, 
 by private gift, immense quantities of land. In particular, the 
 Church was clearly responsible, if not for the invention, at 
 least for the rapid development of the practice of leaving lands 
 by luilly a practice which probably did more than anything 
 else to break up the old kinship principles on which the village 
 system was largely based. Finally, the State put the finishing 
 touch on the legal dissolution of the village, by sanctioning the 
 taking of a debtor's land in satisfaction of his debts. This was 
 not, perhaps, such a violent disregard of patriarchal principles 
 as might at first sight appear. By these principles, as we have 
 seen (p. 40), a man's kindred were responsible for his mis- 
 deeds, and, in the times of which we are now speaking, debts 
 were usually the result of failure to pay the blood-Jine, But
 
 THE STATE AND PROPERTY 105 
 
 the old rule was, that the debtor paid with his body ; his land 
 never left the clan. In reversing this order of ideas, in giving 
 the creditor a remedy against the debtor's land, the State 
 was dealing a final blow at the communal character of the 
 village. 
 
 {b) Enclosure, The physical side of the dissolution took 
 the form of the enclosure of the openjields. So long as the 
 lands of the villagers lay in scattered strips in the openjields 
 (p. 50), so long was there, at least in appearance, and, to 
 some extent, in practical working, a community. Re-distribu- 
 tion of the lands might have long ceased, but independent 
 farming was still impossible. A man whose land consisted of 
 fifty or sixty little strips lying mixed among his neighbour's 
 strips, "hide-meal and acre-meal," could not try experiments, 
 could not use his own discretion. He had to follow the 
 course of husbandry sanctioned by the milage custom. But, 
 towards the end of the Middle Ages, there arose all over 
 Europe a controversy, sometimes picturesquely carried on in 
 verse, between what was called in England " champaign " and 
 "several " farming. The former was the old-fashioned method 
 of working in great open fields (campi), the latter the modern 
 system of cultivating in small compact Belds enclosed by hedges. 
 Of course the advocates of the new plan had little difficulty 
 in proving its superior efficiency. It protected the diligent 
 farmer against the wastrel who let his patches grow thistles ; it 
 enabled the enterprising man to try experiments ; it especially 
 allowed him to keep sl}eep instead of growing corn ; it thereby 
 enabled him to economize in labour (which was then scarce), 
 for sheep-farming employs less hands than agriculture. 0( 
 course the reformers got their way, and, for a wonder, the 
 reform brought artistic value with it, for it gave us, in England 
 at least, the exquisite hedgerows which are the glory of the 
 countryside. Instead of a bundle of scattered strips, the 
 farmer received a more or less compact block of the same 
 extent, which he could deal with as he liked.^ But the 
 
 1 The difference between land held on the old " open-field " system, 
 and the same land after an "enclosure" will be graphically realized
 
 io6 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 change was the end, or almost the end, of the village com- 
 munity ; and it gave us property in land of the most private 
 kind. For the scattered villagers, unless (as very rarely 
 happened) they succeeded in throwing off lordship as well as 
 village ties, found themselves, after the operation, isolated 
 tenants of a great landowner, with whom alone they had in 
 future to deal, instead of members of a village group, subject 
 indeed to the claims of lordships but strong in mutual pro- 
 tection. The wealthier of them signified their new attitude, 
 by moving away from the village proper, and building them- 
 selves new houses in the centres of their new farms. The 
 village became, more and more, merely the abode of the 
 cottagers ; the old yeoman houses fell into ruins, or were 
 divided up into tenements ; class separation became more 
 marked ; the labourers became more and more ivage-earnersy 
 and less and less villagers having an interest in the land. 
 Only the ivaste or common still survived, to mark the ancient 
 character of the village. In later times that has also in many 
 cases been broken up ; and the village has become the ideal of 
 the individualist, a place in which every man " does what he 
 wills with his own," 
 
 This has been a long story, and a difficult story to tell ; 
 but no one who has endeavoured to study for himself the 
 history of the institution oi property will ever pretend that it 
 is an easy task to relate it. Two points have, however, it is 
 hoped, been made clear. One is, that the institution of 
 property, as we have it now, is no sudden invention, which 
 can be explained in an epigrammatic phrase by a platform 
 orator. It is, on the contrary, the outcome of a long chain 
 of historical causes, each contributing its quota to the complex 
 result. To the elements, previously enumerated (p. 98), of 
 user, production, seizure, exchange, we must now add the ele- 
 ments of lordship, revenue, and economic progress, all of which 
 
 by a comparison of Plates A and B appended to this book. It will 
 be noticed that in Plate A the process of enclosure has only begun ; 
 in Plate B it has been completed.
 
 THE STATE AND PROPERTY 
 
 107 
 
 have some share in erecting the institution oi property. The 
 other point is, that while physical, or, as we may perhaps call 
 them, natural causes have contributed greatly to this result, the 
 most powerful factor has been the development of that particular 
 form of association which we term the State.
 
 CHAPTER XI 
 The State and Justice 
 
 We are so accustomed to look upon the administration of 
 justice as an inevitable duty of the State, that it requires an 
 effort to realize that this state of things also, like the rest of 
 our modern social organization, is the result of historical 
 growth. Now-a-days, all justice is (broadly speaking) 
 administered in England in the name of the Queen, that is, of 
 the Head of the State. But it was not always so. 
 
 Old ideas of justice. As we have already seen (p. 
 40), the first notion of justice was that it consisted oi revenge 
 or retaliation. The blood-feud was the earliest type of judicial 
 machinery, at least so far as private offences were concerned. 
 For offences so gross that they outraged the moral sense of 
 the community, there remained the drastic remedy of expulsion 
 from the community, by the community itself. 
 
 We have also seen (p. 41) that the first step towards a 
 milder state of things was the substitution of the blood-fne or 
 money-payment for the exercise oi revenge. The earliest offences 
 were nearly all offences of violence ; therefore the remedy 
 of revenge was obvious and natural. When the develop- 
 ment of the notion o^ property made theft a prominent offence, 
 restitution was naturally suggested ; and this fact, together with 
 a perception of the evils of revenge, may have led to a general 
 acceptance of the money-payment system. As we have before 
 said, early codes of law are often mainly composed of 
 elaborate tables oi fines to be exacted for particular offences. 
 
 Absence of autlioritative tribunals. But it is to 
 be observed that, in patriarchal society, there never seems to 
 
 108
 
 THE STATE AND JUSTICE 109 
 
 have been any authority capable oii enforcing the money-payment 
 system. It was a voluntary system. The elders of the tribe 
 or clan seem to have acted as a persuasive body, urging the 
 parties to receive and pay respectively the sum which they 
 (the elders) declared to be the proper fine for the offence. 
 But if their persuasions failed, the parties were entitled to 
 resort to the feud. Imagine a modern judge " persuading " 
 Mr. William Sikes to "make it up" with the relatives of his 
 victim, and, on his remaining obdurate, leaving the two families 
 to fight the matter out. Yet this course, quaint as it seems to 
 us, is quite in accord with the ideas of patriarchal justice. 
 
 Not applicable to public offences. And it is also 
 
 to be observed, that the system o^ fines did not touch pui/ic 
 
 offences. They were significantly described by the Teutonic 
 
 tribes as bootless ivrongs, i. e. wrongs for which no bot or 
 
 payment could atone. When they were perpetrated, the 
 
 tribe or clan arose in its wrath, raised the hue and cry, and 
 
 expelled the offender from its midst. This distinction is of 
 
 vital importance ; it was the germ of the modern distinction 
 
 between the crime which is prosecuted by the State, and the 
 
 civil ivrong which is left to be brought before the Courts by 
 
 the injured party. 
 
 Survivals of the notion of revenge. The funda- 
 
 I mental notion that a private wrong gave rise to a lawful 
 
 I exercise of revenge, unless the parties could be persuaded to 
 
 j " swear the peace," lingered to the very end of patriarchal 
 
 i times, and even passed over into politica' society. One of 
 
 [ its most curious manifestations was the right of reprisal 
 
 I practised. by merchants till quite the end of the Middle Ages. 
 
 If an Antwerp merchant, for example, did not pay a debt 
 
 \ which he owed to a Bristol merchant, the Bristol merchant's 
 
 gild seized the goods of any other Antwerp merchant who 
 
 • was unlucky enough to be in Bristol at the time. And in 
 
 feudal jurisdictions the trial by battle, which is, of course, 
 
 only a modified form of the blood-feud, lingered until feudal 
 
 jurisdictions were themselves swept away. 
 
 Action of the State. But in the matter of bootless
 
 no A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 crimesy the State very early began to make itself felt. It is 
 very probable that the old communal remedy was not rigorously 
 enforced. What is every one's business is no one's business ; 
 and so, no doubt, many a heinous offender escaped. But, 
 even if it was enforced, the result would not be satisfactory 
 to the State. The State did not want to lose its men, even 
 if they were criminals. They might have been very good 
 soldiers, for all that they were violent members of society. 
 And so we find the practice growing up of the State 
 *' redeeming the offender from the forest," as the Swedish 
 laws put it, i. e. of letting him return from banishment or 
 submitting to a penalty or punishment. The hue and cry was 
 raised at the instance of the State's official ; but the offender, 
 when caught, was punished and allowed to return. This 
 practice developed ultimately into the process known as out" 
 lanvry in the Middle Ages, and became exceedingly popular 
 with the State ; because, by a train of reasoning which it is 
 easy to follow, the outlaw's goods v/tve forfeited to the king. 
 The King^s peace. But the royal justice received a 
 great impetus from the development of another idea, the idea 
 of the King's peace. It was quite natural that a military 
 ruler should sternly resent anything like disorder or violence. 
 Hence the State soon lays down the doctrine, that all offences 
 of violence are offences against the State — " against the peace 
 of our Sovereign Lady the Queen," as a modern indictment 
 puts it. And a man who offends against the State must 
 expect punishment. In connection with this idea comes in 
 the institution of sanctuary, so important a modifier of violence 
 in primitive society. A man has, perhaps accidentally, 
 caused the death of another. Fearing the vengeance of the 
 dead man's kindred, he flies to the nearest place of refuge, 
 and claims the protection of its master. The process is 
 exactly described in the Mosaic books of the Old Testament,^ 
 and is immensely important in introducing the distinction 
 between intentional and accidental violence. In the case of 
 the Jews, the sanctuary was placed in charge of the Church 
 1 Numbers xxxv. 6-33 ; Deut. xix. ; Joshua xx
 
 THE STATE AND JUSTICE iii 
 
 (the Levites) ; and in medieval history the Church's peace 
 also played a great part in the suppression of the blood-feud. 
 But, in the end, the King's peace became the most important, 
 because it was the most powerful. An amusing modern form 
 of the idea has manifested itself in Persia, where the intro- 
 duction of the telegraph has enabled a suppliant to appeal to 
 the Shah for sanctuary from a great distance. Every one has 
 a right to approach the Shah by telegram, if he prepays a 
 reply. The man who apprehends violence goes to the tele- 
 graph office, dispatches his appeal, and sits down to await the 
 answer. As things in Persia move with deliberation, this is 
 probably several days in arriving. But as the telegraph office 
 is the Shah's property, it is sanctuary ; and the suppliant, so 
 long as he remains there, is safe. It is no uncommon thing, 
 therefore, to see a little group of suppliants, fortified with 
 food and drink by their relatives, crouching in the telegraph 
 office, while a corresponding group of avengers of blood waits 
 eagerly outside. 
 
 Extension of the King's peace. But it is quite 
 easy, by a little clever elaboration of the idea of the King's 
 peace, to make it cover a whole multitude of offences which 
 are not really crimes of violence at all. Take, for instance, 
 the offence of theft, which is not usually accompanied by 
 violence, and was originally, and in its nature, a private 
 off'ence against individuals. But the State says that a theft, 
 successful or unsuccessful, is apt to lead to reprisals, and 
 reprisals mean violence, and therefore theft is an offence against 
 the King's peace. After the king has been satisfied, the 
 injured party or his relatives may claim compensation ; but it 
 is generally found that, after the king has been satisfied, there 
 is not much left for any one else. And so theft and such 
 like offences become purely matters of criminal, or public law. 
 
 Treason. Thirdly, the State, as a military institution, 
 is peculiarly concerned with the allegiance of its subjects. 
 Anything that can be considered as a betrayal or defiance of 
 allegiance, is a direct attack upon its security, and is directly 
 visited by it with punishment. Thus arises the law of treason.
 
 112 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 And if we put together offences of peculiar enormity, offences 
 against the peace, and treason, we get the bulk of criminal 
 laiv, at least in early times. That is to say, we get the bulk 
 of that law which the State itself enforces, as opposed to that 
 law which is enforced by private individuals. 
 
 The State and private offences. The appearance 
 of the State in private laiusuits is much later, and we find an 
 important intermediate stage between the moot of the elders, 
 with its merely persuasive power, and the tribunal of the State 
 itself. This was the court of th^ feudal lord. Partly, no doubt, 
 this result was due to the action of the State in entrusting the 
 maintenance of order in the local districts to its representatives ; 
 still more, perhaps, it was due to the State's representative step- 
 ping into the shoes of the old tribal or clan chief, who, of 
 course, presided over the moot of the elders. The result of 
 the combination was a very tenacious and powerful jurisdic- 
 tion, which ultimately became a serious rival to the State. 
 On the one hand, it was military in character; for its president 
 was really the State's representative, and was endowed with 
 a certain amount of military force. Hence it was compara- 
 tively easy for him to stamp out the blood-feudy and to compel 
 the parties to it to bring their quarrels before him. Then, 
 "after due inquiry, and if compromise was impossible, it could 
 be settled by a final and conclusive combat or battle^ fought 
 under strict conditions. On the other hand, it -wzs patriarchal 
 also ; for it followed the lines of the old patriarchal settle- 
 ments, and it comprised (at least in cases where freemen were 
 interested) the homage of the Jief, whom we may strongly 
 suspect to have been largely identical with the elders of the 
 clan. A curious popular mistake has arisen on this point, in 
 connection with the expression, "trial by one's peers." This 
 is usually taken to mean *' trial by jury." As a matter of 
 fact, it was a phrase used to express abhorrence of trial by 
 jury, which, at the time when it became prominent, was a 
 very unpopular innovation, introduced by the royal officials. 
 "Trial by peers" really means "trial by the men of one's 
 fief" ; and it was a cry of feudalism against the new royal
 
 THE STATE AND JUSTICE 113 
 
 justice. Feudal jurisdiction in private lawsuits for a while 
 reigned, in fact, supreme ; and, even in criminal matters, it 
 succeeded in acquiring some part of the royal jurisdiction. 
 But the kings held on very tight to criminal justice, and 
 preferred to do their local work in such matters by means of 
 subordinate agents, such as the sheriffs^ who also gradually 
 took away from the feudal lords much of their jurisdiction in 
 military and revenue matters. Ultimately they also became 
 too powerful, and were superseded by the itinerant judges (for 
 judicial matters), by Exchequer officials (for revenue), and 
 by royal lieutenants or governors (for military affairs). At 
 least this was so, where the State succeeded in stamping out 
 feudalism. 
 
 Struggle between the State and feudalism. For 
 it is one of the ironies of history that the State has, in almost 
 all progressive countries, been obliged to enter into a death 
 struggle with a system which it has itself been the main 
 instrument in creating. In some cases it has been successful, 
 in other cases it has succumbed in the task ; but in all cases 
 the struggle has been severe. There were two main objections 
 to feudalism from a political aspect. 
 
 The first of these was its disintegrating character. Left to 
 itself, feudalism would have split the State in pieces. In 
 fact, it did so in some cases, notably in the case of the 
 medieval German Empire, where the great fiefs ultimately 
 became independent States. The reason is not very far to 
 seek. The inhabitants of a feudal district became so accus- 
 tomed to look upon their lord as their earthly providence, that 
 they lost sight of the power above him. They assembled 
 under his banner, paid their taxes to him, and were judged in 
 his Courts ; they hardly recognized the existence of the State 
 at all. Consequently, if a quarrel arose between their lord 
 and the king, they were quite as likely to support the former as 
 the latter. It was one of the great secrets of the stability of 
 the English throne in the Middle Ages, that the kings very 
 early and very skilfully, the circumstances favouring them, 
 put an end to this kind of thing. They insisted that all
 
 114 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 military service should be rendered to themselves, and them- 
 selves only. They established a new system of taxation 
 which, while it relieved the feudal lords of a great deal of 
 financial responsibility, deprived them of their former position 
 of tax-gatherers. And, finally (and this is the line we have 
 now to follow), they took away from them the administration 
 of justice. 
 
 In this they were greatly helped by the second objection 
 to feudalism, viz. its hereditary character. The right to hold 
 a feudal court came to be looked upon as a piece of property y 
 valuable because it yielded a substantial income. When we 
 notice the eagerness of the State to get hold of the adminis- 
 tration of justice, we must not suppose that it was entirely, or 
 even principally, because of the desire to supply pure justice 
 to the people. It was mainly due to a desire to secure the 
 profits of jurisdiction. In early times, presidents, judges, and 
 officials, as well as advocates and pleaders, were paid hy fees ^ 
 often, it is to be feared, by bribes. The more business, the 
 more fees. Hence the desire to enlarge jurisdiction. Possibly 
 this competition for the supply of justice would be a good 
 thing, if all litigants honestly desired the best tribunals. 
 Unfortunately there are always dishonest litigants, who are 
 only too glad to resort to corrupt, ignorant, and dilatory 
 tribunals. Still, as a matter of fact, we are bound to admit 
 that the State Justice has, in the end, succeeded in supersed- 
 ing Clan Justice, Feudal Justice, Merchant's Justice, and even 
 Ecclesiastical Justice, because on the whole it has proved itself 
 better than any other. Its superiority has consisted chiefly 
 in three qualities. 
 
 I . Strength. We have seen that the oldest type of law- 
 court, the moot of the elders, was a voluntary tribunal. If 
 the accused party did not choose to attend the summons of 
 his opponent, or to obey the doom of the court, the court could 
 not compel him. It had no executive machinery. Now a 
 voluntary tribunal may be all very well when both parties to 
 a quarrel are perfectly bond fide, and honestly wish to obtain 
 a fair decision. But, in nine cases out of ten, one party is
 
 THE STATE AND JUSTICE 115 
 
 not bondjide. He wants to gain time by delay, or fraud, or 
 obstinacy. A voluntary tribunal can do nothing with him. 
 But the royal officials would not stand any nonsense. If a 
 litigant would not obey their summons, his goods, and even 
 his land were seized, and, in the last resort, he was put in 
 prison against the day of trial. So likewise with the judg- 
 ment. If the litigant refused to obey, the judgment was 
 enforced against his property and his person. Of course the 
 feudal tribunals had also, to a limited extent, this coercive 
 power ; but it was the absence of it which really proved the 
 undoing of the tribunals of the clan, the gild, and the Church. 
 2. Skill, Again the royal officials, chosen from a wider 
 field, and selected exclusively for ability, naturally attained a 
 much higher level of judicial skill than the elders of the 
 moot, chosen mainly for their age, the feudal noble who had 
 inherited his position, or the ecclesiastic chosen for his piety. 
 No doubt the feudal baron and the ecclesiastic had also their 
 officials ; they did not always decide cases in person. But it is 
 very unlikely that these were as skilful as the king's officials. 
 Roughly speaking, the biggest employer gets the best servants ; 
 and the king was by far the biggest employer of labour in 
 judicial matters. There were many feudal barons and many 
 bishops and archdeacons ; but there was only one king. One 
 very striking evidence of the superiority of the royal over the 
 feudal and popular courts in the matter of official skill, is the 
 fact that, until comparatively late in history, the royal courts 
 I alone kept records of their proceedings in writing. 
 I 3. Simplicity. One of the most erroneous notions about 
 j primitive judicial procedure is, that it is simple and stratght- 
 j fornvard. When it is actually examined, it is found to be 
 \ full of traps and pitfalls. The parties must use exactly the 
 1 prescribed /ormj of nvords ; a slip or stammer will prove fatal. 
 \ This is extremely natural, when we remember that the oldest 
 j form of judicial procedure is a substitute for 2ifght^ and that, 
 j in a fight, the object of each man is to catch his opponent 
 i tripping. Moreover, the parties must only proceed upon the 
 correct days, or the whole proceedings will be worthless.
 
 ii6 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 The story of the Roman augurs, who succeeded in keeping 
 secret the whole of the legal forms and the lists of correct 
 Court days, so that no one dare go to law without consulting 
 them, is thoroughly characteristic of primitive procedure. It 
 is, as the Germans say, emphatically m'lt Gefahr ("with 
 risk"). But the royal officials., though they were not free 
 from official pedantry, swept away much of the ancient 
 Abracadabra of legal procedure. They announced openly 
 the days on which they would hold courts, and, upon 
 reasonable payment, issued correct forms. 
 
 Still more did they improve and simphfy the actual method 
 of triaL Broadly speaking, after the blood-feud had died 
 out, or had subsided into the trial by combat, the ancient 
 tribunals knew only two other methods of trial. If the 
 accused was respectable, he was allowed to clear himself by 
 his own oathy and that of a prescribed number of his relatives, 
 who now swore for him instead of fighting with him. If he 
 was a serf, or a man who bore a bad reputation, he was com- 
 pelled to submit to the ordeal, e. g. to plunge his arm into 
 boiling water, to walk blindfolded over red-hot ploughshares, 
 or to lift a mass of red-hot iron. If he was injured in the 
 process, he was held guilty ; if he escaped, he aa^s pronounced 
 innocent. As has been well remarked, it is difficult to see 
 how a man could have been convicted by the oath (unless his 
 kinsmen made a slip in the form), or have been acquitted by 
 the ordeal (unless the officials were bribed). In any case, 
 the whole trial was, as we should think, a mere farce. 
 
 The royal officials introduced greatly improved methods. 
 Without entirely discarding the trial by combat, they offered 
 attractive alternatives. For example, they allowed proof of 
 the complainant's accusation or the defendant's denial by 
 record, i. e. by appeal to the written files of the Court itself, 
 or to solemn documents. By this means they indirectly did 
 much to encourage the use of writing in daily transactions. 
 Again, they insisted that certain transactions should be con- 
 ducted before tvitnesses ; and then the witnesses could, of 
 course, be produced in Court to settle disputes. But their
 
 THE STATE AND JUSTICE 117 
 
 most famous innovation was the trial by jury y or trial concluded 
 by the answer given by a small body of neighbours, to a 
 question put to them by a royal official. This famous 
 institution, about which much nonsense has been talked, seems 
 to have been originally a royal privilege^ inherited by the 
 Emperor Charles the Great from the decaying Roman 
 Empire, and spread by his officials throughout Western 
 Europe. If the Emperor suspected that any of the Imperial 
 rights in any district had been misappropriated, his officials 
 could compel the neighbours to attend and answer on oath any 
 questions put to them concerning it. Needless to say, it was 
 at first an intensely unpopular institution, both with the men 
 who, as we should say, " sat on the jury," and the people 
 whose misdoings were thus revealed. But it suited admirably 
 the purpose of the State, and was taken up by king after 
 king in Western Europe. In return for a substantial pay- 
 ment, the kings sold to private litigants the privilege of 
 using it ; but, of course, it could only be used under the 
 presidency of a royal official, for the jury would not obey the 
 summons of any one else. After it had been in use some 
 years for royal business, e.g. revenue matters and criminal 
 prosecutions, honest litigants began to see the advantage of 
 it, and to employ it extensively. But its originally limited 
 character is shown by the fact that, in criminal cases, it was 
 long before the prisoner could be compelled to submit to a trial 
 by jury ; and the earliest criminal jury was one of accusation 
 cmly [grand jury), not of trial. Gradually, however, as 
 people began to see that trial by jury was a preferable alterna- 
 tive to being smuggled out of the way by the royal officials, 
 or being left to languish in prison, or taking their chance 
 amid the pitfalls of feudal procedure or in the judicial combat, 
 trial by jury became "popular" in the modern sense, and 
 was regarded as a bulwark of liberty. Unfortunately, in many 
 countries it died out altogether, just because at the critical 
 moment the State (/. e. the King) was too weak to urge its 
 adoption. So it has come to be regarded as a peculiarly 
 English institution. But it was not so originally.
 
 ii8 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 By these means the State succeeded, in most progressive 
 countries, in getting into its own hands the business of 
 administering justice. We may date this achievement, roughly 
 speaking, by the Reformation^ when the struggle with the 
 Church got rid, even in Catholic countries, of the last formid- 
 able rival to the State jurisdiction. In some cases, the State 
 abolished the local courts altogether, and set up new ones of 
 its own. This was what happened in France, and it led 
 to consequences which were disastrous, but which are too 
 technical to explain here. In other cases, notably in England, 
 the State pursued the much easier plan of converting the local 
 tribunals into tribunals of its own, thus, to a great extent, 
 preserving that continuity which is so important a factor in 
 political progress. 
 
 We have now to answer the important question, What was 
 the laiv administered by these various tribunals ? But this 
 question must be reserved for a separate chapter. It involves 
 a treatment of the important subject oi political representation.
 
 CHAPTER XII 
 The State and Legislation 
 
 As we have before stated (p. 39), the notion that law 
 could be made was unknown to primitive society. The 
 rudimentary idea of law, as it presented itself to people in the 
 patriarchal stage, was that of a custom or observance, sanctioned 
 by the approval and practice of ancestors. At first this idea, 
 like everything else in patriarchal society, was purely personal ; 
 a man's custom or la<w was the custom of his tribe or clan. 
 Comparatively late in European history, the rule was gravely 
 admitted, that each man was entitled to be judged by the law 
 of his race or folk, no matter where he might be. There is 
 even a faint survival of the notion in civilized countries at the 
 present day. That most persistent of all patriarchal societies, 
 the Jewish, retains to a certain extent its tribal laiv in the 
 Gentile cities of the West. 
 
 But, for the most part, the development of agriculture, 
 aided by the later development oi feudalism, made law a local 
 rather than a personal thing. Instead of the custom of the clan, 
 people began to speak and think of the custom of the village, 
 the custom of the fef, and the custom of the toivn. The 
 personal idea still lingered ; there was a strong feeling that no 
 one could claim the custom of the village but a villager, of 
 the fief but a vassal, of the town but a burgher. But this 
 element gradually dwindled, as residence took the place of 
 blood in the organization of society. 
 
 It is necessary, however, most carefully to remember that, 
 when we speak of law being local, we do not mean that the 
 same law applied to large areas ^ If, for example, we were 
 
 119
 
 120 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 to speak of the Laiv of France^ or the Law of Germany, in 
 connection with the tenth century, we should betray great 
 historical ignorance. In the tenth century, every Httle 
 district, almost every village and town, in France, Germany, 
 Spain, and even in England, had its own special law. In 
 England, for reasons which we are about to point out, this 
 state of things was modified very early ; yet, even in modern 
 England, at this very day, as all lawyers know, there are 
 hundreds of different viUage laivs, or rather manorial laws, 
 which, under the name of copyhold customs, regulate important 
 questions of property. And in France, Germany, Spain, and 
 other countries, there was no national law till the end of the 
 last century. 
 
 Three great agencies gradually swept away this (as we 
 should think) intolerable state of affairs, and created the 
 modern system of law and of legislation. 
 
 I. R_ecords. From the early Middle Ages, and from all 
 parts of Europe, there survive to us a deeply interesting body 
 or collection of codes, folk-laws as they are called, or Leges 
 Barharorum, We have them for the Teutonic kingdoms of 
 Italy and Spain, for Bavaria, Saxony, Burgundy, Frankland, 
 Swabia, Frisia, England, Wales, Ireland, even (to a slight ex- 
 tent) for Scotland, Denmark, Sweden, and Norway, and many 
 other districts. Though their actual dates differ very widely, 
 they nearly all come from the same relative period in the 
 history of each country, viz. the period at which the tribal 
 settlement is first becoming a fixed kingdom, under a conquer- 
 ing king. That is to say, they come from the very earliest 
 days of the State. They are due, almost universally, to one 
 and the same cause, viz. the desire of the conqueror to know 
 the customs of his conquered subjects. In many cases, he has 
 formally promised to respect these customs ; in no case does 
 he propose to sweep them away. But he must know what 
 they are ; he cannot respect what he does not know. 
 
 And so we see that the so-called Barbarian Codes are not 
 legislation, in the sense of law-making ; but statements or 
 declarations of custom. In nearly all cases, they are drawn up
 
 THE STATE AND LEGISLATION 121 
 
 as the result of a formal and careful inquiry amongst those 
 chiefs and elders who are supposed specially to know the 
 customs of their people. 
 
 Importance of the Step, Nevertheless, the drawing 
 up of these customs was a momentous event in the history of 
 Laiv. As we have seen (p. 40), unwritten custom does 
 alter ; but it alters itself automatically and imperceptibly. No 
 one is sacrilegious enough to propose deliberately to alter it. 
 But ^written custom cannot be altered imperceptibly ; it is 
 always possible to point to the exact text, and show what it 
 says. Nevertheless customs must alter in a progressive 
 society ; and so it was necessary to have successive editions of 
 the written Codes, as in fact happened. Thus people came 
 gradually to accept the idea that custom could be altered ; 
 and occasionally they even allowed the king, by way of 
 bargain or agreement, to introduce certain deliberate alterations. 
 No doubt a good many more alterations were secretly slipped 
 in, by the royal scribes who drew up the Codes. We must 
 remember the enormous respect paid in primitive times to the 
 newly discovered art of writing ; a written document was 
 looked upon as a sort of charm or magic power. To say of 
 a rule — '* it is written,^' was to claim for it almost a sacred 
 character. We have all heard of the Hindu who carried a 
 doctor's prescription about on his person, instead of taking it 
 to the apothecary to be made up. That is characteristic of 
 the veneration with which primitive people regard written 
 documents. And so we may very well suppose that, if a 
 passage was found in a written code, no inquiry would be 
 permitted as to how it got there. 
 
 2. Law Courts. We have seen, in the preceding chapter, 
 how the State gradually acquired the business of administering 
 justice. And, in the main, the royal officials, in performing 
 this business, bonestly tried to decide cases according to the 
 custom of the place in which they happened to be. But they 
 naturally became confused and impatient with the innumerable 
 petty differences of local custom, and leaned, perhaps uncon- 
 sciously, in favour of uniformity. Especially was this the
 
 122 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 case with the itinerant or circuit judges, to whom allusion has 
 been made (p. 113). Being attached to no particular locality, 
 they were free from local prejudice ; and, as they gathered 
 round the royal chair at the end of their journeys, they 
 probably discussed with one another the difficulties of their 
 task, and came to some agreement on general principles. 
 What they probably did was to take some general ruky which 
 represented the average practice of the local communities, and 
 agree to ignore local differences as much as possible. In this 
 way, at any rate, the English common laiv seems to have been 
 modelled ; it was the law which was common to all the districts 
 of the kingdom. Where a local custom was very tenacious, 
 it was allowed to prevail in its particular district. And it is 
 very significant that copyhold customs (p. 120) were not 
 harmonized, because the royal judges did not decide copyhold cases 
 till quite late in history. And the reason why, on the 
 Continent, there was no common laiv for centuries later than 
 in England, was just because, on the Continent, the State did 
 not get hold of the administration of justice till centuries after 
 it had done so in England. But, to show that the process 
 was not peculiar to England, we may point out that the same 
 result had occurred at a similar stage of Roman history ; 
 where the customs selected and harmonized by the prators 
 had become the common laiv of the mighty Roman Empire. 
 It may be remarked, as a matter of detail, that one of the 
 shrewdest moves by which the English judges pushed their 
 plan of making a common laiv was, by limiting the verdict of 
 the jury in every case to questions of fact. At first the jury 
 used to give answers both on laiv and fact ; and, being a 
 purely local body, they used, of course, to follow local custom. 
 For example, they would be asked : " Who is the heir of 
 A ? " ; and if they came from a district in which the youngest 
 son succeeded to his father, they would say, " X '^ (A's 
 youngest son). But later, the judges used to ask them, 
 " Who is A's eldest son ? " ; which is purely a question of 
 fact. And then the judges used to declare that the eldest son 
 was the heir. Thus, incidentally, we get the famous division
 
 THE STATE AND LEGISLATION 123 
 
 between the province of the judge and the province of the 
 jury. 
 
 3. Fictions, But these two methods, valuable as they 
 were in gradually preparing the public mind for the business of 
 law-making, were slow and imperfect processes. So also was 
 another very useful makeshift, viz. the use oijictions. If, for 
 example, a rule of custom said that land could not be sold, 
 and A wished to sell his land to B, B used to bring a lawsuit 
 against A, pretending that the land was really his (B's), and 
 that A was keeping him out of it. Acting in collusion, A 
 would make no defence ; and the Court would therefore 
 adjudge that the land belonged to B. The fiction there was, 
 that there had been no sale, but a correction of a former 
 mistake. Of course, that is a glaring fiction ; and it could 
 never succeed but for the willingness of the Courts to connive 
 at a change. But it is a well-known fact, that people will 
 accept a change under cover of a Jiction, which they would 
 spend the last drop of their blood in resisting as an avowed 
 alteration. Turkey will not give up her sovereignty over 
 Crete ; but, if the Turkish flag may fly in Crete as a symbol 
 of Turkish sovereignty, Turkey will withdraw all real control. 
 
 4. Legisiation. But, where progress and development are 
 rapid, new custom is, in fact, being rapidly made every day, 
 and all these makeshifts are inadequate to the task of declaring 
 it. Some more direct and speedy method must be adopted. 
 The answer to the difficulty is found in political representation. 
 
 To modern politicians, ^o//V/V«/ representation is a form of 
 agency, a means by which people express their wishes, and 
 elect people to carry them out. About the precise character 
 of the process there are, no doubt, great differences of opinion. 
 One school of politics holds, for example, that the represent- 
 atives are mere delegates of the electors, morally, if not legally 
 bound to obey their mandate. Another school takes the view 
 that the elector, in choosing his representative, puts himself 
 entirely in the latter's hands, and leaves him to act as he thinks 
 best. Both agree, however, in regarding an election as an oppor- 
 tunity for the elector to express his choice of a representative.
 
 124 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 But any one who is at all familiar with primitive society is 
 aware, that the idea of agency was quite unknown to that stage 
 of history. In primitive society, every transaction was apt to 
 end in a fight ; and it was important, therefore, we might even 
 say necessary, that it should be conducted by the parties 
 actually concerned. We must look elsewhere for the 
 beginning of political representation. 
 
 Let us take a totally different line. Primitive society 
 knew nothing of agency -, but it knew a great deal of joint 
 liability. A murdered B ; not only A, but A's relatives were 
 liable to the relatives of B. A (a mason) built B's house so 
 badly that it fell down ; not only A, but A's gild was liable 
 to B. A (a merchant) incurred a debt to B. Not only A, 
 but (as we have seen) A's town, was liable to B. 
 
 The State uses the idea. When the State was 
 established, it made abundant use of this idea. A man was 
 found dead on the king's highway ; the three neighbouring 
 villages had to produce the murderer, or pay the murder-fine. 
 There had been a cattle raid ; and the tracks of the stolen 
 beasts led to a certain village. That village must have pro- 
 duced the thief or paid the fine. There had been a row in a 
 market-place, and the king's flag had been torn down, or his 
 bailiff insulted. The town had to make amends. Or the 
 king had levied a tax ; and the hundred or the town had been 
 assessed at so much. It had to pay. 
 
 Enforcement of joint liability. But what if it could 
 not or would not pay ? According to our modern ideas, the 
 liability ought to have been divided proportionately or equally 
 amongst the individual members of the village, or town, or 
 hundred ; and each man ought to have been compelled to pay 
 his own share. But this course would have involved endless 
 trouble ; and the king had other things to do. He knew a 
 simpler and more effectual way. He sent his officer, who 
 seized a couple of the wealthiest and most respected inhabit- 
 ants of the village, or hundred, or town, and clapped them in 
 gaol till the money was paid. The village, no doubt, pro- 
 tested. Very well, let it find the money, and the men would
 
 THE STATE AND LEGISLATION 125 
 
 be restored. Brutal, perhaps, but effective. It is done every- 
 day in Oriental countries. The result is, that the captives 
 are ransomed by their relations and friends, who, by some 
 means or another, have managed to scrape together the money. 
 Incidentally, we may notice that this matter of raising the 
 money does a great deal towards building up what we may 
 call local self -government^ in the district affected. But, here, 
 our chief object is to notice its importance as a step in the 
 growth oi political representation. 
 
 Development of the idea. For we may be very 
 sure that a practice so convenient to the State grew and 
 spread. The State was always wanting money from its 
 subjects on some pretext or another. And so we are not at 
 all surprised to find that, quite early in the Middle Ages, 
 and all over Europe, the village headmen and elders got into 
 the habit of assembling at the hundred-moot and the county- 
 moot at fixed times in the year, to meet the royal officers, the 
 sheriff or his " junior," and to answer the royal demands. 
 Later on, as towns appeared, we find their headmen and 
 elders doing the like. No doubt on these occasions a good 
 deal of purely local business was discussed ; but we may be 
 very sure that the real thing which kept the practice alive 
 was the presence of the royal officers. Over and over again 
 we find the royal command issued : "Let the shire-moot and 
 the hundred-moot be held as it was aforetime, and let the 
 reeve and four men come," and so on. 
 
 Appearance of Parliament. Then, somewhere about 
 the end of the twelfth century, a great idea was born in 
 western Europe. Commerce was progressing rapidly; the 
 value of money was falling. In every country, the State was 
 wanting more money. Why not have a great national moot, 
 as well as many little hundred-moots and shire-moots ? And 
 so, all over Europe, in Spain, Sicily, France, Germany, 
 Scandinavia, England, Scotland, even Ireland, Parliaments 
 sprang up. But they were not entirely representative, still less 
 were they homogeneous. 
 
 The Nobles. For, it we turn our thoughts back to the
 
 126 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 earliest days of the State {Chapter IX), we shall remember, 
 that its first organization contained a councilor king's followers, 
 originally the comrades who had followed him in his con- 
 quest of the kingdom. This council had never died out, but 
 had, on the contrary, been enlarged by the gradual creation 
 of nobles, and by the admission of the great ecclesiastics, the 
 bishops and abbots. In fact, so large had it become, that, 
 for ordinary purposes, it was too bulky, and the daily work 
 of the State was done by a smaller body of officials, generally 
 known as the Curia or Court, which was always about the 
 person of the king. But, on solemn occasions, the Great 
 Council of nobles was always summoned, though probably the 
 humbler members did not often attend. So when the kings 
 determined to hold national moots, they naturally summoned 
 the members of their Great Councils. 
 
 The Clergy. In the meantime, a new and very im- 
 portant class of persons had grown up, viz. the cathedral 
 and parochial clergy. They had amassed great wealth by the 
 gifts of the pious ; it was calculated that something like one- 
 fifth of the land of Christendom was in the hands of the 
 Church. Just at the time of which we are speaking (twelfth 
 and thirteenth centuries) the Church had developed a policy 
 of isolation. Under the guidance of a succession of able 
 Popes, her clergy were withdrawing themselves from secular 
 affairs, and becoming a caste apart. They cut themselves off 
 from domestic life by adopting the rule of celibacy; they 
 refused to plead in the secular courts ; above all, they de- 
 clined to pay taxes to the State, on the ground that they 
 paid them to the Pope. Now, as the main object of the 
 kings in holding these national moots was to get money, it is 
 quite obvious that they could not afford to let the Church 
 escape. So they insisted on the representatives of the clergy — 
 the deans, archdeacons, and proctors, coming to Parliament. 
 The clergy did not like it ; but in most cases they had to 
 come. 
 
 The smaller landowners. Then the smaller land- 
 owners were represented. In England, this was done fairly
 
 THE STATE AND LEGISLATION 127 
 
 enough in one way, but not in another. The sheriff was told 
 to send two people from the county court ; but, instead of 
 sending villagers, he was told to send knights, i. e. land- 
 lords. No doubt the villagers were pleased at the time ; 
 but it was a bad thing for them in the long run. In other 
 countries, the villagers were often represented by men of their 
 own class. 
 
 The townsmen. Finally, the sheriff was told to send 
 people from the towns, burgesses or burghers as they were 
 called in England; and thus the medieval Parliament was 
 complete. It represented the estates of the realm, viz. nobles, 
 clergy, yeomen or peasants, and craftsmen. 
 
 But two things about it are well worth noticing. 
 
 [a) It was not, in any ordinary sense of the term, a 
 popular institution. On the other hand, for many years after 
 its appearance, it was intensely unpopular, both with " con- 
 stituencies " and representatives. The counties hated it, 
 because they had to pay the wages of their members. The 
 clergy hated it, because they did not want to acknowledge 
 the secular authority. The boroughs hated it, because (in 
 England at least) the parliamentary boroughs paid a higher 
 scale of taxation than their humbler sisters. And all hated 
 it, because a Parliament invariably meant taxation. The 
 members themselves disliked the odium of consenting to taxes, 
 which their constituents would have to pay. Only by the 
 most stringent pressure of the Crown were Parliaments main- 
 tained during the first century of their existence; and the 
 best proof of this assertion lies in the fact, that, in those 
 countries in which the Crown was weak. Parliament ulti- 
 mately ceased to assemble. T he no tion that Parliaments 
 were the result of a spontaneous deniocratic movement, can 
 :)e held by no one who has studied, ever so slightly, the facts 
 )f history. 
 
 [b) Parliament, at any rate the representative part of it, 
 vas, in its origin, concerned solely with the granting of money. 
 The nobles were, it is true, hereditary councillors of the Crown; 
 )ut the clerical proctors, and the members for the counties and
 
 128 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 boroughs, could claim no such position. There was no pre- 
 tence of such a thing in the early days of Parliament. It was 
 liability, and not privilegCy which was the basis of Parliamentary 
 representation ; it was the old idea of the seizure of the 
 village elders, carried out on a magnificent scale. 
 
 New character of Parliament. But it not unfre- 
 quently happens, that an institution created for one purpose is 
 found to serve quite another. If the representatives of shires 
 and boroughs might not advise, at any rate they might peti- 
 tion. And petitions come with a strong force from people 
 who are~being asked to grant sums of money. As a matter 
 1 of fact, the members, especially the members for the shires 
 and boroughs, petitioned loudly and frequently; and sessions 
 of Parliament very soon began to assume the character of 
 bargainings, in which the king undertook to grant petitions in 
 return for gifts of money. 
 
 But what has all this to do, it may be asked, with legislation ? 
 Just everything, as we shall now see. 
 
 Character of petitions. For if any group of petitions 
 presented by a Parliament be examined (in most cases they 
 have been carefully recorded) we shall find, that they fall 
 readily into two divisions. One division consists of mere 
 private requests, e.g. that a particular man may have a pension, 
 that a particular oppression by a royal official may be abolished, 
 and so on. These, if granted, only involve an executive or 
 administrative act on the part of the Crown. But the other 
 division consists of complaints of the breach oi good and ancient 
 customs, and a request for their confirmation. These, if 
 granted, result in declarations, or, we may say if we like, 
 makings, of latu, i. e. in legislation. It was already admitted 
 that the Crown had ordaining power. The king, as military 
 commander, could issue any orders which could fairly be 
 deemed necessary for the performance of his universally 
 recognized duties — viz. the defence of the country against 
 foreign attack, and the maintenance of order within. He 
 could order the ports to be closed, forbid the export of 
 precious metals, direct the town watches to be kept and the
 
 THE STATE AND LEGISLATION 129 
 
 militia to be maintained, and so on. He could, moreover, 
 make all regulations for the control of his own officials, and 
 for the conduct of proceedings in his own tribunals. All 
 this was inherent in his prerogative ; and, in a sense, it may be 
 deemed legislation. But not until the royal enactment was 
 combined with the popular petition was there real effective 
 legislation, law-declaring which affected every hole and corner 
 of a man's life, which turned the vague and badly-enforced 
 custom into definite and strictly enforced latu. And this, 
 even at the present day, will be found to be the character of 
 almost all successful legislation. It is custom adopted and en- 
 forced by the State. A wise legislator never attempts to devise 
 legislation out of his own head. Having made up his mind 
 that a grievance requires remedying, he makes inquiries, and 
 finds what the better and more enlightened people are spon- 
 taneously doing to remedy it. Then he endeavours to pass a 
 statute compelling all people to act up to the standard of the 
 more enlightened class. He does not take the exalted type 
 as his model, knowing that it is useless to legislate " over the 
 heads of the people." But he does take the "rather superior 
 citizen," and he insists that the inferior people shall toe the 
 line marked by him. At once the proposal receives support 
 from the people who have already spontaneously adopted it. 
 To the inevitable objection, that "it cannot be done," the 
 answer is obvious, — "but it is already done." And thus the 
 measure escapes the most damaging of all criticisms to a 
 statesman, that it is " unpractical." There is a well-known 
 academic moot which inquires — " what are the proper limits 
 of legislative interference ? " Somewhere in the direction 
 indicated will be found the practical answer to the problem. 
 For a Government, still more for a private individual, to 
 propose " fancy " legislation, is to proceed upon the entirely 
 unwarranted assumption, that the Government's servants, 
 or the private individual, understand the business of the nation 
 better than the nation itself understands it. 
 
 Majorities. Reverting, in conclusion, to the subject of 
 political representation^ we may say something about a feature
 
 I30 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 which has everywhere become identified with it, and without 
 which political representation, as understood at the present day, 
 could not be worked, viz. the doctrine of majorities. Strange 
 as it may sound to modern ears, it is yet unquestionably true, 
 that there once was a time (not so very long ago) when the 
 fact, that a proposal was supported by a majority^ was considered 
 no reason whatever for its acceptance. 
 
 This is the more curious, inasmuch as primitive society was 
 full of communities f i. e. groups of people having interests in 
 common, and conducting their business in common. Surely, 
 it will be said, these communities must have had some method 
 of settling differences of opinion by votes ? No. The answer 
 is, that if custom did not settle the matter, or compromise, 
 then the only remedy was a Jight, in which the strongest 
 party got its own way. Unanimity, or a fight, were the 
 alternatives of primitive times. This is one of the chief reasons 
 why primitive society was so almost stationary for centuries 
 together. 
 
 Originally no competition for post of represent- 
 ative. We cannot suppose that, in its origin as we have 
 seen \t, political representation found any urgent necessity for 
 contested elections. There would hardly be much competition 
 for the unpopular part of hostage, or even of member of an 
 early Parliament. Apparently, at first, the royal officials laid 
 hold of those whom they considered to be suitable persons, 
 and packed them off to Parliament. In the boroughs, there 
 are some traces of a rotation of service among the leading 
 burgesses. 1 
 
 But, as it began gradually to dawn upon people's minds that, 
 in some countries at least. Parliament was a very powerful 
 institution, and membership thereof a thing to be coveted, 
 contested elections began to make their appearance. In England, 
 by far the best example of early political representation, there 
 are traces that, at the commencement of the fifteenth century 
 (when Parliament was about two hundred years old), people 
 were beginning to covet the position of member of the 
 
 * This practice survived until quite late in the history of Spain.
 
 THE STATE AND LEGISLATION 131 
 
 Commons House. The old idea of the unwilling hostage had 
 died out. The new idea of agency ^ introduced, perhaps, from 
 the Roman Law by means of the Church, was offering a 
 more satisfactory explanation of the position of the Parlia- 
 mentary representative. He was the agent of his constituency, 
 therefore his constituents had a right to choose him. But how 
 if they disagreed ? The question evidently caused great diffi- 
 culties ; and though, unhappily, as in so many really interest- 
 ing matters of history, precise evidence is wanting, we can 
 make a shrewd guess as to what happened. 
 
 Blection fights. Most people, probably, have noticed 
 that the language of elections is somewhat bloodthirsty. We 
 speak of the " party war-chest," the " election-campaign," 
 the "enemy's stronghold," "laying siege to a constituency," 
 " leading troops to victory," " carrying the war into an 
 opponent's territory," and so on. Much of this is, no doubt, 
 the decorative language of the New Journalism; but it is 
 interesting to find that, the further back we go in history, the 
 more nearly does it tally with the actual facts. It is one of 
 the numerous examples of the survival, in language, of practices 
 which have passed away in reality. Most things in the Middle 
 Ages ended in a fight. The contested election was no ex- 
 ception. The victorious party routed its opponents, drove 
 them from the hustings, and carried their man, i. e. to the sheriff, 
 who forthwith recorded his name, and sent it up to the Clerk 
 of the Crown. 
 
 Fictions, But fighting, though it has its charms, has 
 
 ; also its drawbacks, especially when a royal official is standing 
 
 j Dy, who may inflict fines for breach of the peace. And so it 
 
 ■ tvould appear that 3.Jiction was gradually adopted, by which it 
 
 ffz.^ assumed that there nad been a fight, and that one party 
 
 lad gained the victory. 
 
 But which party ? Well, other things being equal, in any 
 
 iight the more numerous party will win. And so, it seems 
 o have gradually become the custom, where party feeling 
 vas not very strong, to settle the matter by counting heads 
 ' nstead of breaking them. Much of the machinery of voting
 
 132 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 recalls its origin. The first test is a shout. If one party 
 greatly preponderates, its shout will drown the other's, and 
 there will be no need to go further. But the shout is the 
 old battk'cry. If there is still doubt, the next step is Divide, 
 i. e. draw up in battle array » We do not allow this in parlia- 
 mentary ^/<?<r/io«j-, because the temptation to resort to the ancient 
 method would be too great. But, in calmer assemblies, it is 
 the regular procedure. 
 
 Parties. Thus we see what a rough test the verdict of the 
 majority is. It is not based, historically, on any ethical consider- 
 ations. It makes no allowance for difference of merit in the 
 combatants, or for generalship, both of which tell in real war- 
 fare. But it is a very simple and enormously useful practical 
 way of settling disputes, and it has had a world-wide success. 
 Curiously enough, it has often been reckoned the child of its 
 own offspring. It is usually said, that it is the logical result 
 of the equality of Man. Historically speaking, the dogma of 
 the equality of Man is the result of the adoption of the purely 
 practical machinery of the majority. But the adoption of the 
 majority principle is also responsible for another famous insti- 
 tution of modern politics — the party system. The party system 
 is an elaborate piece of machinery, designed to secure that 
 whenever an opportunity for a vote occurs, there shall always 
 be two opposing forces, at least, in existence to contest it. 
 Its chief advantages are, that it makes representative institu- 
 tions something of a reality, by interesting a large number of 
 people in politics, that it provides an effective criticism of the 
 existing government, that it affords a scope for the energies, 
 and an outlet for the ambition, of a large number of wealthy 
 and educated men, and that it guarantees a certain consistency 
 in policy. 
 
 These three institutions — political representation, verdict of 
 the majority, and the party system — are the mainsprings of 
 modern political machinery. They can be and are equally 
 applied to central and to local government ; and, by their 
 adaptability to all kinds of purposes, they are rapidly becom- 
 ing looked upon as ends in themselves, rather than as machinery
 
 THE STATE AND LEGISLATION 
 
 »33 
 
 for the achievement of ends. It is hardly necessary to point 
 out, that the best machine in the world will not produce good 
 results unless good material is put into it ; and this historical 
 account of the appearance of modern political institutions 
 may possibly be of service in placing them in their true 
 perspective.
 
 CHAPTER XIII 
 The State and Administration 
 
 Difficulty of tlie subject. We come now to the last, 
 and by far the most difficult department of State activity. 
 For whilst, in other departments, such as the dispensing of 
 Justice, and the making and enforcing of Law, the victory 
 of the State has been complete, and, with rare exceptions, has 
 become popular, this is by no means the case with regard to 
 that wide department which we call administration. Very 
 few persons now seriously argue, that private law courts or 
 private legislative bodies would be advantageous. But very 
 many people do most strenuously argue, that State interference 
 with the management of domestic, religious, and industrial 
 affairs, is thoroughly mischievous, and ought to be reduced 
 to a minimum. In order, therefore, to avoid all appearance 
 of dogmatism, this chapter will be confined, almost entirely, 
 to a very brief sketch of the process by which the State has 
 actually acquired its present administrative position. 
 
 Original character of the State. Once more we 
 must call to mind the initial fact, that the State was, in its 
 origin, a military organization. For many years after its 
 establishment, it consisted of a comparatively small body of 
 warriors and officials, under the headship of a king, control- 
 ling by force a much larger mass of people who inhabited a 
 definite territory. It was only by slow degrees, and as the 
 result of various agencies, that the State incorporated into 
 itself, mainly, as we have seen, by the process of political 
 representation, the people whom at one time it merely 
 governed. For no one can be properly said to be a member 
 
 134
 
 THE STATE AND ADMINISTRATION 135 
 
 of the State, unless he has some voice in the direction of its 
 policy. 
 
 Also, as we have seen, the State started upon its career, 
 with the primary function of maintaining external peace and 
 internal order. Quite naturally, its first efforts in the direc- 
 tion of administration were intimately connected with this 
 function. It had no decent pretence for interfering in the 
 lives of its subjects, except with the object of performing it. 
 
 Means of communication. To this fact we may 
 undoubtedly attribute the early activity of the State in de- 
 veloping the means of communication. The " king's highway " 
 is now regarded mainly as a convenience for public traffic ; 
 but, historically, it was laid down and maintained for the con- 
 venience of the royal armies. In the days in which commercial 
 intercourse between one part of the kingdom and another was 
 almost non-existent, the costly convenience of great trunk 
 roads would certainly never have been undertaken as a com- 
 mercial speculation. But roads were simply invaluable to a 
 king who wished to move his army about; and they were 
 always carefully maintained and protected by well-governed 
 States. A similar care was bestowed upon the great bridges, 
 which are, of course, merely highways across rivers. It is 
 one of the strongest proofs of the reality of local government 
 in England, that the care of the main roads and bridges is 
 entrusted to local authorities. In almost all other countries, 
 the State jealously maintains its immediate control. 
 
 Posts, The same ideas have been at work, though with 
 a modified force, in the later developments of communica- 
 tion. The earliest ^d?j-/j- were royal messengers; and although 
 in England railivays'^ are not administered by the State, they 
 frequently are so administered on the Continent ; and there 
 can be little doubt that motives of military ejjficiency largely 
 influence their administration. Finally it may be observed, 
 that land and ocean telegraphic connection is, in the majority 
 of cases, intimately connected with State control. 
 
 1 Is not this largely because England is a naval rather than a 
 military power?
 
 136 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 Police, On its internal side, the State's original function 
 of maintaining order, very early gave rise to a great develop- 
 ment of what is generally known as police administration. 
 Looked at from one point of view, this may be considered as 
 a branch of the dispensation of Justice, which, as we have 
 seen, ultimately became the exclusive function of the State. 
 But on its preventive side, police jurisdiction has a special 
 character of its own, which distinguishes it from ordinary 
 judicial work. In the curfew'^ of William the Conqueror, in 
 the enforcement of the ivatch, and the maintenance of the 
 tlthtngs or peace-associations, the State, in England at least, 
 showed very early that it realized the importance of prevent- 
 ing, as well as punishing disorder. The State regulation of 
 markets SLud fairs, the many galling restrictions on the harbour- 
 ing of strangers, and the stringent regulations on the subject 
 of inns, were amongst the earliest developments of State 
 police administration. On the Continent, as is well known, 
 this preventive policy expanded to an enormous extent, and 
 was made the excuse for all kinds of wanton State inter- 
 ference. In England, it was wisely left, to a great extent, 
 to local authorities ; the work of the central government being 
 mainly of a controlling or supervising character. 
 
 Revenue, Next to the maintenance "of safety and order, 
 the State in early days was, as we have seen, mainly con- 
 cerned with questions of revenue. To its desire to foster and 
 develop this important interest, we must undoubtedly attribute 
 many activities of the early State which, superficially examined, 
 look like vague attempts at philanthropy, or *' State-sociahsm" 
 in the modern sense. To this desire, for example, we may 
 attribute many early ordinances on the subject of luelghts and 
 measures, prices, qualities, and especially coinage. When the 
 income of the State was paid in kind, it was extremely im- 
 portant that a standard of measure and value should be gener- 
 ally accepted. The royal officials found themselves hampered 
 
 1 The pious theory of our school histories, that King William 
 laid down his curfew rule to prevent his subjects incurring the risk 
 of fires, must be taken with a genial cynicism.
 
 THE STATE AND ADMINISTRATION 137 
 
 at every turn by the numberless petty local and customary 
 differences on these subjects. And so, to render its accounts 
 easier, the State insisted upon certain standards being adopted, 
 and punished any attempt to revert to the old customary 
 methods. When the revenue of the State came to be paid 
 in coiriy the necessity for uniformity was still more obvious. 
 And so the State, not without some severe struggles, managed 
 to acquire a monopoly of coinage. The great convenience to 
 the/wMVofthe State's action in these matters is now uni- 
 versally recognized ; but it was not the original motive of the 
 State's policy. 
 
 Jealousy, A third, and very powerful motive for the 
 active interference of the State in administrative matters was, 
 undoubtedly, that jealousy of rivals which affects institutions 
 no less than individuals. The State is, no doubt, an institution, 
 bnt it is an institution composed of, or, at least, worked by, 
 human beings. There is, therefore, nothing absurd in attri- 
 buting to it human passions. We have already seen, in dealing 
 with the development oi property (Chapter X),how the action 
 of the State led to the dissolution of the village community, on 
 its proprietary side. On its personal side, as a group of de- 
 pendents upon a lord, the State was powerfully helped by a 
 great catastrophe which fell upon Europe in the fourteenth 
 century. This was the Plague, or Black Death, as it is often 
 called, which is calculated, in England alone, to have swept 
 away from one-half to one-third of the population. The 
 blow fell heaviest upon the labouring classes, and was followed 
 immediately by a great scarcity of labour. This scarcity made 
 itself felt principally in the agricultural districts, because the 
 surviving agricultural labourers rushed to fill the places of the 
 dead craftsmen in the towns. So great was the despair of 
 the landowners, that they appealed to the State for aid ; and 
 the State, not unwilling to intervene, issued stringent regula- 
 tions, compelling all people of the labouring classes to work 
 on the old terms. From that time, the State has always been 
 obliged to regard the regulation of labour as part of its func- 
 tions. The immediate effect of the step was, virtually, to
 
 138 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 dissolve the old labour bond of serfdom, and substitute for 
 it the regulation of labour by the State's officials. It is true 
 that these latter were, in many cases, the old feudal lords in 
 a new guise ; and so serfdom was, in fact, a long time in 
 dying out. And, of course, the interference of the State 
 could not really affect the economic position of the labourer ; 
 that was, and is, always fixed by economic causes. But it 
 altered his legal position. 
 
 The gild. Precisely the same policy was adopted, some- 
 what later, with regard to urban labour. No doubt, the gilds 
 also suffered severely by the Black Death, But they had 
 more vitality than the villages, and it seems to have been the 
 great geographical discoveries of the fifteenth and sixteenth 
 centuries which dealt them their death-blow. In the wake 
 of the great discoveries, came great commercial ventures, quite 
 beyond the power of the old gilds to manage. There sprang 
 up a new class of merchants, who despised the petty rv stric- 
 tions and ambitions of the gild-system, so far as they hampered 
 their own plans, though they were quite willing to accept 
 similar privileges themselves for the new trading companies 
 which they formed. Then, too, the old gilds were, as we 
 have seen, a good deal mixed up with Roman Catholicism ; 
 and this fact, in Protestant countries, went greatly against 
 them. Ultimately, the old gilds were dissolved by the State, 
 which then found itself compelled to lay down certain rules 
 for the control of artisan labour, and to enforce them by its 
 own officials. In both cases we see the invariable policy of 
 the State — to break down all intermediate authorities, and to 
 deal directly with the individual. One of the most striking 
 examples of this policy has been, of course, the dissolution of 
 the East India Company, which, so long as its trade monopoly 
 lasted, was simply a gigantic mercantile gild. The same policy 
 was manifest in the determined hostility displayed by the 
 State towards the modern labour associations, known as Trade 
 Unions, which date from about the end of the last century. 
 And, had it not been for the strong reaction against State 
 interference, brought about, not only in England, but on the
 
 THE STATE AND ADMINISTRATION 139 
 
 Continent, mainly by Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations, it is 
 not unlikely that the policy would have been once more 
 carried out. As it is, the State is now very much inclined 
 to wash its hands of a difficult problem, by proclaiming its 
 neutrality in industrial matters. But, unfortunately for itself, 
 it has raised a spectre by its destruction of the old labour 
 organizations ; and it must face the consequences of its policy. 
 The Poor Law. Incidentally, also, its action sowed 
 the seed of the great problem oi pauperism, or State relief 
 of the indigent. The State, of course, did not create 
 poverty ; but, by its destruction of the chief agencies, the 
 village system, the monasteries, and the gilds, which dealt 
 with it, the State practically assumed responsibility for its 
 treatment. It is a responsibility which, by reason of its far- 
 reaching consequences, the State has always been reluctant to 
 undertake. In nearly all cases, the actual administration of 
 the Poor Law, where it exists at all, is placed by it in the 
 hands of local authorities ; the action of the central govern- 
 ment being confined to supervision and criticism. This is, 
 unquestionably, the wisest policy on many grounds ; for Poor 
 Relief is just one of those matters in which, if corruption and 
 hypocrisy are not to be allowed to prevail, minute local 
 knowledge is absolutely essential. The dangers which are 
 attendant even on a local system of Poor Relief were, however, 
 well illustrated by the appalling condition of affairs which 
 prevailed in England during the half century which ended 
 with the appearance of the Reformed Parliament of 1832. 
 The great Poor Law Report of 1834 showed that, under 
 cover of the Poor Law system, a scheme of communism, of 
 the most degraded and vicious type, had practically estab- 
 lished itself in the rural districts of England. It is very 
 significant, that, in newly-developed countries, such as the 
 colonies of the British Empire, the State has, almost without 
 exception, declined to undertake responsibility for the relief 
 of poverty. And this is the more striking, when we consider 
 the political influence of the poorer classes in those countries, 
 and their leanings towards " State-socialism."
 
 HO A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 Sudden calamity. Once more, it may be pointed out, 
 that the occurrence of any sudden and overwhelming calamity 
 has always, at any rate since the great power of the State has 
 been generally recognized, been followed by a great increase 
 of administrative activity. It is, of course, perfectly natural 
 that, at such a crisis, men's minds should turn instinctively 
 for help to the most powerful agency with which they are 
 familiar, regardless of ultimate consequences. And the more 
 able and efficient the government of the State is, the more 
 readily will its assistance be invoked. The story is the same, 
 from the days of the Plague of the fourteenth century, to 
 those of the cholera in the nineteenth. A pestilence, a 
 famine, a great fire, a murrain of beasts, a flood, a tempest ; 
 paralysis of private effort ; application of State aid, followed 
 by permanent organization of State machinery to deal with 
 similar matters in the future. One of the best examples is, 
 of course, the vast and complicated machinery of the Public 
 Health department in England, which has rapidly grown up 
 as the result of the cholera visitations in the middle of the 
 present century. 
 
 New aspect of State administration. It should, 
 however, be pointed out, that the question of State adminis- 
 tration has received an altogether new character from the 
 great modern development of political representation. When 
 the State consisted entirely of a handful of officials and 
 privileged landowners, who had sprung from official ranks, an 
 increase of its administrative activity really meant the exten- 
 sion of interference by this limited class, with the daily lives 
 of the vast masses of men whom it governed. Moreover, it 
 was an interference which, however good its motives, almost 
 inevitably suffered from want of detailed knowledge of the 
 circumstances of those whom it was supposed to benefit. 
 Now that the State includes within its ranks a very large 
 proportion of the inhabitants of its territory, now that the 
 average man can make his voice effectively heard by means 
 of elections and netvspapers, the danger of arbitrary and 
 ignorant interference by the State is very greatly reduced.
 
 THE STATE AND ADMINISTRATION 141 
 
 It is, no doubt, a reflection of this kind, which has rendered 
 the increase of State activity so popular, in communities in 
 which the average man can make his power felt. In such 
 communities it is, in fact, often said, that the State is merely 
 the nation organized for governmental purposes, and, there- 
 fore, that its action is harmless. Although this view is, no 
 doubt, founded on an important truth, it contains by implica- 
 tion certain fallacies, which, as a final word, it may be well 
 to point out. It would be the worst kind of pedantry to 
 attempt to lay down any hard and fast lines for the limits 
 of State administration. But an honest recognition of the 
 dangers attending it will serve as a useful guide to the citizen, 
 in making up his mind on any particular proposal. 
 
 Fallacies in the argument. In the first place, even 
 in modern conditions, the State and the nation never are 
 identical. Even where the so-called "universal suffrage" 
 prevails, the parliamentary franchise is not (with rare excep- 
 tions) exercised by women; and where, as in New Zealand, 
 some women have the franchise, there are yet many inhabit- 
 ants of the country who take no direct part in the business of 
 government. It may be said, of course, that in such countries 
 all persons have the franchise who are fit to use it ; but that 
 is to beg a very large question. The fact remains, that, even 
 in the countries of so-called *' universal suffrage,'* an exten- 
 sion of State administration means an increased interference 
 by some persons with other persons' freedom of action. In 
 countries, such as England and Italy, in which the parlia- 
 mentary franchise is on a more restricted basis, the same 
 truth applies with still greater force. 
 
 Again, even if we are to admit that State and nation are 
 identical, we should still be very far from admitting that 
 State interference, especially in administrative matters, is 
 necessarily a good thing. Legislation^ indeed, especially if it 
 follows the policy of adopting and enforcing the practice of 
 the most enlightened members of the community, stands on a 
 somewhat different footing. For in ordinary legislation the 
 citizen is merely given general directions, and left to follow
 
 142 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 them out at his own risk ; whilst administrative activity not 
 only gives him directions, but stands over him to see that he 
 obeys them. In other words, legislation treats him as a man, 
 administration, as a child. Yet, even in legislative matters, 
 it might be well to allow the process of improvement to work 
 by example, rather than by precept. 
 
 And, in admiiilstration, there can be little doubt, that the 
 constant supervision and guidance of the individual by the 
 State tends to produce a somewhat feeble type of citizenship, 
 which is constantly looking for directions, instead of casting 
 about to help itself. This fact is very observable in the 
 much-governed countries of continental Europe; but it is 
 also noteworthy in some countries which should have inherited 
 a healthier tradition of independence, such as the Australian 
 colonies. 
 
 Finally, the modern indiscriminate advocacy of State 
 administration conceals the fallacy, that State officials must 
 necessarily prove more effective in their action than private 
 enterprise. In some respects, no doubt, there is ground for 
 this view. The private individual naturally shrinks from 
 rebuking practices which he knows to be harmful to the 
 community, even when they are contrary to express law. In 
 well-governed communities, the public official has, of course, 
 no such scruples. Moreover, in its higher ranks, the body 
 of State servants usually contains a majority of men of genuine 
 public spirit, of great ability, and of special training. The 
 dignity of their position is sufficient to compensate them for 
 the loss of that stimulus which, to human nature as we know 
 it, is usually best supplied by the hope of perbonal profit, to 
 be derived from hard work and ability. But, in the lower 
 ranks of the State service, the force of these considerations 
 diminishes rapidly, especially if the area of the State's opera- 
 tions be very large. The State has to compete with private 
 employers of labour, who can, perhaps, afford to oifer more 
 tempting rewards. The State has not the same apparent 
 interest in detecting laziness and inefficiency as the private 
 employer; nor has it, as a rule, the same facilities. It is
 
 THE STATE AND ADMINISTRATION 143 
 
 bound to move according to established routine ; it is often 
 tempted to stifle inquiries for the sake of avoiding scandals ; 
 it is peculiarly subject to pressure by outside influences. The 
 head of an administrative department is often obliged to allow, 
 among his subordinates, conduct which he would not for one 
 moment tolerate in the management of his own estate or his 
 own business. Add to this the unpleasant fact, that the 
 State, for various reasons, cannot, in many cases, even promise 
 security of tenure to its minor officials ; and it becomes 
 obvious that the attractions of the State service to a really 
 desirable class of men are very small. The result is, that 
 minor State officials are, in too many cases (though there are 
 numerous honourable exceptions), lazy, stupid, or corrupt, 
 and, therefore, inefficient. In other words, plans for the un- 
 limited extension of State administration stand between the 
 horns of an awkward dilemma. It will not be safe to carry 
 them out, until the progress of education and morality has 
 produced an unlimited supply of men and women, who are 
 capable of discharging important official duties with great 
 efficiency and absolute honesty, for comparatively small 
 reward. And, when such a supply has been created, the 
 [| extension of State interference will no longer be needed. 
 I Once more it must be admitted, that to dogmatize upon 
 \\ the proper limits of State interference would be pedantry of 
 I the worst type. But it will probably also be admitted by 
 ! careful observers, that no proposal for its extension should be 
 I entertained, except in cases of urgent necessity, in which the 
 J object to be attained is of more importance than the method 
 pf its attainment, in which uniformity is of greater value than 
 (.1 originality, and in which it is morally certain that the action 
 j { Df the State will be more effectual than private enterprise. 
 
 1 J 
 ( 
 
 J!
 
 CHAPTER XIV 
 Varieties of Political Society 
 
 Ancient Classification of States, Until a fewv 
 years ago, it was considered almost essential to begin every 
 discussion on Politics with a mention of the celebrated theme 
 of Aristotle, which classified States into Monarchies, Aris- 
 tocracies, and Democracies or Polities. One of the surest 
 signs that our knowledge of the History of Politics has greatly 
 advanced within the last few years, is the fact, that this once 
 famous classification has sunk into oblivion. It is neither 
 exhaustive, nor, whatever it may have been in Aristotle's day, 
 is it very important. Still more silent has fallen the once 
 noisy controversy, as to the respective merits of these three 
 forms of government. Slowly, but surely, people are coming 
 to the wise conclusion, that riJ form of government can be 
 said to be absolutely the lesi ; and that, in each case, that 
 is the best which is most suited to the circumstances of the 
 case. 
 
 Similarity of principle in all States. As a matter 
 of fact, all communities in the purely political stage will be 
 found to be varieties of a single type, the type namely which 
 is distinguished by the possession of sovereignty. Somewhere 
 or another, in all communities of this type, there resides an 
 authority which, in the last resort, controls absolutely and 
 beyond appeal the actions of every individual member of the 
 community. No doubt, as has been well pointed out, this 
 sovereign power recognizes certain moral limitations of its 
 action ; it proceeds, in fact, at the risk of revolution. But, 
 so far as iaiv is concerned, it acknowledges no superior and no 
 
 144
 
 VARIETIES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 145 
 
 limit. This condition of affairs has, no doubt, its drawbacks; 
 it has also immense advantages. Its great practical 
 convenience may be judged from the fact, that it is the type 
 of government in all the Great Powers of the modern world, 
 with the possible exception of the United States of America. 
 Varieties of organization. But, within these limits, 
 sovereignly may be organized in different ways. It may be 
 vested (in theory at least) in the hands of a single individual, 
 as, for example, in Russia. Or it may be vested, and this is 
 by far the commoner case, in a number of individuals or 
 bodies, as in the Crown, Lords, and Commons, in the British 
 Empire. As this latter arrangement always gives rise to a 
 good many elaborate rules concerning the relationship between 
 the different individuals or bodies composing the sovereign 
 power, it has received the name of constitutional government f 
 while the sovereignty vested in a single individual receives 
 the name of autocratic government. But we must be careful 
 to remember that, owing to political passions, these names 
 have received moral as well as scientific meanings. By 
 autocratic rule, many people mean arbitrary or capricious rule ; 
 by constitutional government, they mean mild or good govern- 
 ment. Of course the government of a numerous body may be, 
 and often is, just as arbitrary and capricious as the rule of a 
 single individual ; and vice versa. Needless to say, the pro- 
 portions in which sovereign power is divided among the 
 different members of a sovereign body varies almost infinitely 
 with each case. And so also do the methods by which the 
 kit various members are selected. Sometimes the executive and 
 ilj legislative powers are quite distinct, as in the German 
 tRj! empire, and, virtually, in Austria ; sometimes they are com- 
 "j bined, as in England. Sometimes the law courts are beyond 
 the control of the legislature, as in the United States of 
 I America ; sometimes they are, legally at least, subject to its 
 control, as, again, in the British Empire. Again, the head 
 of the State may be hereditary or elective, and this independ- 
 ently of the extent of his powers. The German Emperor, 
 with very great power, is hereditary ; the President of the
 
 146 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 United States, also with great power, is elective. The King 
 of the Netherlands, who has very little power, is hereditary ; 
 the President of the French Republic, also with small power, 
 is elective. 
 
 Another, and almost equally important variation of 
 sovereignties is, that some are what we may call ordinary^ 
 others extraordinary. That is to say, in some States the 
 sovereign authority is in constant action, or at least always 
 ready to act ; in others, it requires an elaborate machinery to 
 set it in motion. The British Empire is the best modern 
 example of the former class ; there, the powers of the 
 ordinary legislature are unlimited. Such was also the position 
 of most of the European governments at the close of the 
 last century. But this kind of sovereignty has grown much 
 out of favour in the last hundred years ; and the majority of 
 the ordinary legislatures of Europe do not now wield 
 sovere'ign powers. Thus, for example, the ordinary legisla- 
 tures of Spain, Belgium, Holland, and many of the German 
 States, cannot go beyond the terms of written documents 
 which place limits to their powers, and which are known as 
 their constitutions. If any further powers are required, they 
 must be sought from some extraordinary authority, such as a 
 vote of the whole electors or inhabitants. This fact, which 
 is extremely important, gives rise to the distinction between 
 fundamental and ordinary laws ; the former being those 
 which cannot be passed or altered by the ordinary legislature, 
 the latter, those which can. This distinction has been aptly 
 expressed by Mr. James Bryce, as the distinction between 
 rigid and Jlcxihle constitutions. It is closely, though not 
 inevitably, connected with the division of constitutions into 
 nvritten and unwritten. The ivritten constitution is nearly 
 always rigid ; because its framers do not really believe that it 
 ever will require alteration. The unwritten constitution, 
 which has grown rather than been made, is nearly always 
 flexible^ i. e. it can be altered by the ordinary legislature.* 
 
 1 Italy seems to be the most important exception. The constitu- 
 tion {Statuto) is written, but can be altered by the ordinary
 
 VARIETIES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 147 
 
 This is just one of those cases in which the doctrine, that the 
 circumstances of the case must determine the form of govern- 
 ment, is most appUcable. It would be an absurd piece of 
 academic folly for a country like England, which has 
 flourished for centuries with an unwritten constitution, to 
 attempt to reduce her constitution to writing. But the 
 circumstances under which most of the existing constitutions 
 of Europe came into existence, rendered written documents 
 essential. Oddly enough, however, England did set the 
 fashion of written constitutions, during the Civil War. After 
 the Restoration, England abandoned them ; but they were 
 taken up by the United States of America, when the latter 
 achieved their independence ; from America they passed to 
 France, and from France, after the French Revolution, 
 to the rest of Europe, and, ultimately, to the European 
 colonies. 
 
 Value of Local Government, The last dis- 
 tinction in point of form which we need point out, is 
 the important distinction between cenlralized and localised 
 States. This is a distinction which is nearly always to 
 be accounted for by the circumstances of history ; but its 
 practical importance is none the less on that account. Begin- 
 ning with the highly centralized States, we may notice that 
 they correspond closely with those States which have been 
 formed by the gradual conquest by one ruler over a group of 
 surrounding rulers, whose independence he has desired to 
 \ crush. Thus, modern France was formed by the victory of 
 the kings at Paris in a struggle, long and profound, with the 
 rulers of the neighbouring fiefs — Burgundy, Champagne, 
 Blois, Acquitaine, Gascony, Toulouse, Brittany, etc. ; and 
 France is the best example of a highly centralized country. 
 That is to say, the central government at Paris really controls 
 even petty local affairs throughout France, leaving practically 
 no independence to the so-called local authorities. Very 
 
 1 
 
 jgHtlegisIature. Austria and France seem to be on the border line ; but
 
 148 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 much the same is the case in Italy, where the State was 
 formed by the gradual victory of the House of Sardinia over 
 the neighbouring principalities, although, as the struggle was 
 very much less severe in that case, the centralization of Italy 
 is, perhaps, largely to be accounted for by the influence of 
 French models. On the other hand, a State which was 
 formed suddenly by the conquest of a foreign ruler, or in 
 which a long-established government has produced a real 
 fusion of the population, there is generally a considerable 
 allowance of genuine local Independence. That is to say, the 
 local authorities are genuinely chosen by the people whom 
 they have to govern ; they are not bound at every step to seek 
 instructions from the central government; and, so long as they 
 act within their legal powers, they cannot be interfered with 
 by the central authorities. The best kind of all local 
 government is that which is based upon ancient popular 
 divisions, such as England, where the local units, to a greater 
 or less extent, represent natural lines of race and settlement. 
 It is hardly necessary to enlarge on the merits of local 
 government. It stimulates and keeps alive political life in a 
 way that central government alone can never do ; it trains 
 independent poHticians for the service of the State ; it pre- 
 vents the establishment of that dead level of administrative 
 uniformity which is the ideal of a central bureaucracy ; and it 
 relieves the central government of an immense amount of routine 
 duty,which the latter could not perform satisfactorily. Its weak 
 points are equally apparent. It is apt to be narrow-minded, 
 ignorant, and selfish ; the smallness of its interests may fail to 
 attract men of the best type, and so it may become very 
 inefficient. But these dangers may be guarded against by the 
 criticism of the central government, a task which the latter is 
 admirably qualified to perform, by reason of its wider outlook 
 and greater experience. 
 
 Composite States, Of late years, the distinction 
 between centrahzed and localized States has taken a still more 
 important shape, about which something must also be said. 
 The really striking feature of the last century of politics has
 
 V VARIETIES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 149 
 
 been the establishment of federal States. The way had 
 been prepared by Switzerland, which has the distinguished 
 honour of being the first country to introduce the new type of 
 government to the modern world. Switzerland was followed 
 by the United States of America in 1777, by the series of 
 experiments which culminated in the Empire of Germany in 
 1870, and by the Dominion of Canada in 1867 ; while, at 
 the present day, we are deeply interested in watching the 
 success of another federal experiment in Australia. 
 
 Introduces a New Principle, To the historian of 
 Politics, the vital interest of the new tendency lies in the fact 
 that it is the introduction of a new principle into the organiza- 
 
 Ition of society, the principle of agreement or contract. No 
 doubt there has been other hifliiences at work in the formation 
 of federations. The military preponderance of Prussia, for 
 example, brought the German Empire into existence ; and 
 the Imperial authority of Great Britain urged the Canadian 
 provinces to unite. And so the German Empire and the 
 Federal Dominion are hardly ideal specimens of federation. 
 But the foundation of Switzerland, and the United States of 
 America, were, and (if it takes place) the union of the 
 Australian colonies will ht, purely voluntary. Lawyers know 
 that the contract is a somewhat late development in legal 
 systems. Primitive societies do not recognize it, or recognize 
 it but feebly. Perhaps the institution oi contract is going to 
 
 I play as great a part in politics as it has played in laiv. 
 
 Nature of Federation. Meantime, we may notice 
 
 • that a. federation takes place when a number of States, hitherto 
 independent of each other (though perhaps dependent on a 
 higher power ) desire union^ but not unity. They are willing 
 to join together for a greater or less number of purposes ; but 
 each of them desires to preserve its individual existence, so 
 far as his is consistent with common action. The terms of 
 federal unions are in no two cases alike ; but, putting aside 
 
 ; the cases of so-called personal unions,^ where two States 
 
 \ become, as it were, accidentally connected by dynastic ties, we 
 * Such, for example, as England and Hanover from 171410 1827.
 
 15© A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 may usefully classify them under the following heads, begin- 
 ning with the lowest and proceeding to the highest degree of 
 union. 
 
 1. Real Unions. These occur where two States agree 
 to accept permanently the same ruler, whilst retaining almost 
 intact their independent existence. The most conspicuous 
 example in modern politics is the case of Sweden and 
 Norway ; where the King of Sweden is, ipsojure, also King of 
 Norway, but where Norway retains her independent Parlia- 
 ment and local institutions, and even (it would now seem) her 
 independent foreign relations. The Act of Union of 1 707 
 converted the existing personal or dynastic union of England 
 and Scotland into a real union ; of a somewhat closer type 
 than Sweden-Norway, for the Parliaments of the two 
 countries were united, as well as their thrones. 
 
 2. Confederations. This, at one time a rather favourite 
 type of union, is now virtually discarded by civilized countries, 
 with, perhaps, one striking exception. It occurs when two 
 or more States join together, and delegate, either permanently 
 or for a limited time, a limited number of their inherent 
 powers to a central authority, but without in any way merging 
 their identity. The powers delegated are usually only of a 
 legislative and military character ; the execution and 
 administration of the laws of the central authority are left to 
 the officials of the different States in their own territories. 
 Sometimes, the powers of the central authority are so small, 
 that the union is hardly entitled to rank as a real example of 
 confederation ; as, for example, when a number of States 
 combine to form a Zollvereln, or Customs Union. But 
 usually the Confederate Government is empowered to main- 
 tain an army, a fact which almost necessarily implies control 
 of the foreign policy of the different States, and to legislate on 
 matters of common interest, such as posts and telegraphs, 
 coinage, criminal offences, and so on. Of this type was the 
 North German Confederation of 1866-70; and such it 
 seems, though the circumstances are peculiar, is the position of 
 the present German Empire, which, though it has vast
 
 VARIETIES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 151 
 
 legislative and military authority, has very little executive, 
 administrative, or judicial power. ^ In this last feature lies the 
 real weakness of the confederation as a type of union. The 
 central body, having no officials to enforce its statutes, is 
 obliged to resort to the clumsy expedient of so- called y>^<fr^/ 
 execution, in case of disobedience to its laws by one of its 
 members. This expedient involves invasion of the offend- 
 ing State by the confederate army, and, of course, usually 
 results in a break-up of the confederation. In Germany, 
 this unfortunate tradition was inherited from that political 
 monstrosity, the Holy Roman Empire. 
 
 Right of Secession. A very important question was 
 raised by the Southern States of the American Union, in the 
 unhappy civil war of the sixties, which has, in all probability, 
 done much to discredit this type of government. They 
 maintained, as will be remembered, that the Union was a 
 Confederation, and that, therefore, any of its members who 
 chose might luithdraiv. The event of the war was against 
 this contention, which was, indeed, untenable in the face of the 
 executive, administrative, and judicial organization of the 
 Union. Occasionally, however, the right of secession is 
 expressly reserved by the pact of union.^ 
 
 3. Federations. Far more important is the tme federal 
 type of State, in which the central authority is invested, not 
 merely with legislative and military, but with executive and 
 judicial authority. Some of the most important modern 
 examples of State-making fall under this head. It is the type 
 of the United States of America, of the Dominion of Canada, 
 and, probably in the near future, of the Commonwealth of 
 Australia. Indeed it seems to be the true type also of the 
 anomalous government of the British Empire, which, with a 
 
 1 Switzerland seems to stand on the border line. The confeder- 
 ate government has little direct administrative or judicial authority; 
 but it has a good deal of supervising and critical authority. 
 
 2 This is the case with the so-called "Federal Council of 
 Australasia," adopted as a temporary expedient in 1885. It had 
 very little success.
 
 152 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 few important but feasible alterations, would approximate 
 closely to a federal constitution. The essential features of a 
 federal constitution have been admirably sketched by Professor 
 Dicey, in his Introduction to the Study of the Constitution, and 
 may be summarized briefly thus : — 
 
 [a) A written supreme constitution, in order to prevent 
 disputes between the jurisdictions of the Federal 
 and the States' authorities ; 
 (^) A distribution of powers, between the central or 
 federal government and the governments of the 
 several States which comprise the union ; and prob- 
 ably also among the various parts of the federal 
 government ; 
 [c) A Supreme Court, charged with the duty of inter- 
 preting the constitution, and enforcing obedience to 
 it by the organs both of the Federal and States* 
 governments, and absolutely free from the influence 
 of both. 
 It cannot be denied, that the federal type of government, in all 
 its forms, has its weak points. Based obviously on compromise, 
 it is less likely than national or centralized government to awaken 
 profound enthusiasm, or to gather around it that halo of 
 patriotic sentiment, which is one of the greatest safeguards 
 of a State. Complicated as its machinery must inevitably be, 
 and slow in its working, it is apt to get out of order, and diffi- 
 cult to stir to prompt action. It was the first weakness which 
 caused the heroic founders of modern Italy to reject the 
 federal principle, when its adoption would, apparently, have 
 solved many of their greatest difficulties. The second weak- 
 ness has been unmistakably manifest in the history of the 
 United States of America ; and the third is daily obvious in 
 the procedure of Swiss politics. But, in spite of these draw- 
 backs, federalism has shown a marvellous capacity for adapting 
 itself to different circumstances and different peoples ; and it 
 is probably destined to play a large part in future political 
 history. 
 Common Law and prerogative States, The last
 
 VARIETIES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 153 
 
 classification of political societies which we shall notice is one 
 of extreme importance, but which has only of recent years 
 deserved the attention which it merits. It divides them on 
 the one hand into common la-xu^ and, on the other, into preroga- 
 tive States. In the former class, all persons, officials no less 
 than private individuals, are equal before the law, are judged 
 by the same tribunals, and are subject to the same rules. In 
 the latter, not only are there many privileged individuals, but 
 the whole great class of Government officials is exempt 
 (wholly or partially) from the jurisdiction of the ordinary 
 Courts of Justice. To the first class belong, substantially 
 speaking, only the English-speaking communities ; ^ to the 
 second all the other States of the civilized world. It is, 
 therefore, especially important that English readers should 
 quite understand what the distinction means. 
 
 Common Law States. It does not mean, of course, 
 that in English-speaking communities, a Government official 
 may not do what in a private person would be unlawful. 
 Every day we see Government officials imprisoning criminals, 
 seizing goods for debt, searching suspected houses, and doing 
 many other things which no private person may do. But it 
 does mean — 
 
 (i) That no Government official may do these things 
 without legal authority ; 
 
 (ii) That, if his authority is questioned, it must be proved 
 by him in precisely the same way, and before precisely the 
 same tribunals, as in the case of a private person accused of a 
 similar act.^ If the act would have been criminal in a private 
 
 1 The principle has been tried and abandoned in modern Italy ; 
 there is some trace of its existence in Switzerland and Scandinavia. 
 
 2 It must be admitted that, even in " common law " countries, 
 there are some exceptions to this rule. For example, in England, 
 the King or Queen is personally exempt from suit, though his or her 
 subordinates cannot plead orders as an excuse for illegal conduct. 
 Peers are privileged in the matter of tribunal (not of law). Members 
 of Parliament are temporarily privileged in respect of minor offences. 
 But these exceptions are infinitesimal compared with the list in 
 Continental countries.
 
 154 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 person, the official may be prosecuted in a criminal court ; if it 
 would have been only a civil wrong in a private person, the 
 official can be sued for it in an ordinary civil court. And 
 neither of these tribunals will accept any plea of " act of 
 State," or "superior orders," as an answer to such a com- 
 plaint, at any rate when the complaint is made by a citizen. 
 The net result is, that the Government officials in an EngHsh- 
 speaking country are subject to the ordinary or common latv. 
 
 Prerogative States. In other countries, just the oppo- 
 sive rules prevail. On the one hand. Government officials, 
 from the highest to the lowest, act in what they believe to be 
 the interest of the State, whether or no they have legal 
 authority for their actions. On the other, their acts cannot 
 be questioned by the ordinary tribunals, at any rate without 
 the consent of their official superiors. The net result is what 
 the French call droit administratif^ a phrase for which there is 
 really no English equivalent, but which means law upon which 
 only a Government official is entitled to act, and which is, in 
 effect, what the Government chooses to make it. Under cover 
 of this so-called " law," the ordinary citizen is subjected, in 
 foreign countries, to an amount of supervision and arbitrary 
 interference which would produce a revolution in England in 
 a twelvemonth. And this, in spite of the most solemn 
 guarantees of individual freedom in constitutional documents. 
 
 How the difference arose, A thoughtful American 
 writer, Mr. Lawrence Lowell, has indicated, no doubt with 
 accuracy, the cause for the existence of the distinction. It 
 is just one of those cases in which history furnishes the only 
 clue to the solution of a modern difficulty. In England, the 
 judicial side of State activity developed with great complete- 
 ness, long before the administrative side. Consequently, when 
 administrative activity began to increase, it found itself con- 
 fronted with a powerful and highly organized system of 
 judicial tribunals, which jealously kept it in check. There 
 was a severe struggle, which covered the whole of the seven- 
 teenth century in England, and lasted well on into the 
 eighteenth. But, in the long run, the laiv courts triumphed ;
 
 VARIETIES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 155 
 
 and Englishmen reaped the benefit, not only in their old 
 country, but in those new countries to which they carried the 
 birthright of English common law. On the Continent, on the 
 other hand, the administrative authority of the State developed 
 long before the judicial ; and men learned to look upon the 
 administrative officials of the State as earthly providences, 
 while the State's law courts were weak, and commanded no 
 particular respect. Quite naturally, when the State's law 
 courts were at length organized upon systematic lines, the 
 administrative officials declined to submit their conduct to the 
 scrutiny of the new tribunals. In fact, they utterly refused to 
 believe in the possibility of stable government on such terms. 
 In the view of every Continental Minister, Government 
 officials mustf if they wish to maintain order, frequently violate 
 the ordinary law. And to have their authority questioned by 
 ordinary tribunals would, he argues, be entirely subversive of 
 discipline. If it is pointed out to such a man that Anglo- 
 Saxon Governments, all the world over, enjoy a stability 
 which is certainly not less than that of their Continental 
 contemporaries, he shrugs his shoulders, and enters the fact as 
 one more of the peculiarities of the peculiar Anglo-Saxon. 
 One humorous feature of the situation should not, however, 
 be overlooked. When Montesquieu and other French writers 
 of the eighteenth century dilated to their countrymen upon the 
 virtues of the British constitution, one of the chief excellences 
 which they praised was the so-called ** separation of powers." 
 Now the real " separation of powers " which the British con- 
 stitution of the eighteenth century actually enjoyed, was the 
 freedom of the law courts from the control of the Ministers. 
 But the French, and, after them, the other politicians of the 
 Continent, took it to mean the freedom of the Ministers 
 from the control of the law courts. And, when the govern- 
 ments of the continent were reconstructed after the French 
 Revolution, this was the form in which the British principle 
 appeared. Truly, logic is sometimes a dangerous instrument. 
 
 Here must end our imperfect attempt to evolve order out
 
 156 A SHORT HISTORY OF POLITICS 
 
 of the chaos of History. Those readers to whom the political 
 arrangements of the world represent merely the outcome of a 
 series of local accidents, will have little sympathy with an 
 effort based on a totally different belief. But to those who, 
 with the writer, regard History as the outward manifestation of 
 great universal laws, capable of infinite variety in the circum- 
 stances of their application, but tending with irresistible impetus 
 to similar ends, this attempt may seem to have been made not 
 altogether in vain. Regarded from one standpoint, the Art 
 of Politics may appear to be nothing but the " scuffling of 
 kites and crows." Regarded from another, it is an effort, 
 miserable and imperfect perhaps, but still an effort, to realize 
 that deep-seated instinct of humanity, which bids Man turn 
 for help and guidance to his fellow Man. It is an affirmation, 
 on unmistakable lines, of that social side of our nature, which 
 may fairly be regarded as one of the fundamental facts of the 
 universe. As such, it is surely worth earnest and impartial 
 study ; and all the dreary and repellent accessories which 
 attend its practice cannot disguise its essential importance. 
 The day may be far distant, when the actual political arrange- 
 ments of the world will realize the highest ideal of which our 
 social instincts are capable. But every life honestly spent in 
 the faithful service of the common weal, every hour devoted 
 to the earnest study of the public good, brings that day more 
 surely within our reach.
 
 BRIEF BIBLIOGRAPHY »S7 
 
 A SHORT LIST OF 
 
 USEFUL AUTHORITIES 
 
 Type I. — Savage Society. 
 
 Spencer, W. B. and Gillen, F. J. 17je Native Tribes of 
 
 Central jlustralia. London, 1899. 
 FisoN, L. and Howitt, A. W. Kamilaroi and Kurnai. 
 
 Melbourne, 1880. 
 Morgan, L. H. Ancient Society. London, 1877. 
 
 Type II. — Patriarchal Society. 
 
 Seebohm, F. The Tribal System in Wales. London, 1895. 
 
 Do. The English Village Community. London, 1 883. 
 Roe, Sir C. A. Tribal Law in the Panjab. Lahore, n. d. 
 Skene, W. F. Celtic Scotland. (Vol. III.) Edinburgh, 
 
 1880. 
 Galton, Sir F. Narrative of an Explorer. London, 1853. 
 CouLANGES, F. de. La Cite Antique. Paris, 1864. 
 
 There have been English translations or adaptations of this 
 work, e.g. — 
 
 Small, W, The Ancient City. Boston, 1874. 
 Barker, T. C. Aryan Civilization. Chipping Norton, 
 1871. 
 Powell, B. H. Baden. The Indian Village Community. 
 London, 1896. 
 Larger works on the same subject by the same author are — ■ 
 The Land Systems of British India. Oxford, 1892. 
 Short Account of the Land Revenue Systems of British 
 India. Oxford, 1894. 
 Brentano, L. English Gilds. London, 1870.
 
 158 BRIEF BIBLIOGRAPHY 
 
 Type III. — Modern (Political) Society. 
 
 Dicey, A. V. The Laiv of the Constitution. London, 1885. 
 Lowell, A. L. Government and Parties in Continental 
 
 Europe* London, 1896. 
 Local Government and Taxation, London, 1875. 
 
 (A volume of Cobden Club Essays by various writers.) 
 Fyffe, C. a. a History of Modern Europe. London, 1 89 1. 
 Br YCE, James. The United States of j^merica. London, 189 1. 
 Bluntschli. The Theory of the State. Oxford, 1885. 
 
 Trans.
 
 INDEX 
 
 AUMiNISTRATlON, 1 34, 140, 154 
 
 aspects of, 140 
 
 and justice, 154 
 
 of justice, io8 
 
 Adoption, 15, 66, 68 
 Agency, 123, 124, 130 
 Agnatic succession, 36 
 Agriculture, 43, 44, 98 
 
 and the clan, 43, sqq. 
 
 early methods of, 45 
 
 organization of, 49 
 
 Alienation of land, 99 
 Allegiance, 2, 75 
 
 military, 75 
 
 Ancestor worship, 37, 38,66, 76 
 Animals, domestication of, 19, 22 
 Apprenticeship, 66 
 Australian aborigines, 6, 7, 43, 62 
 
 system of relationship, 11 
 
 Aristotle's Classification of States 
 144 
 
 Barter and sale, 63 
 
 Birth, as title to property, 97 
 
 Black Death, the, 137 
 
 Blood feud, the, 13, 40, 108, 109 
 
 III, 112 
 Blood fines, 40, 104 
 
 Capital, conception of, 29 
 Caste, Indian system of, 66 
 Cattle tending, 33, 78 
 Champion, the, 35 
 Chief, the, 34, 54 
 
 of the clan, 70 
 
 of the tribe, 70 
 
 Chiefship, disappearance of, 82 
 
 Christianity, effect of, 76 
 
 Church and State, 76, 84 
 
 Church, effect of the, on land, 104 
 
 Clan, the, 17, 69, etc. 
 
 Clergy, the, 126 
 
 Crime, 109 
 
 Criminal law in early times, 112 
 
 Codification, 120 
 
 Coined money, 63 
 
 Colleges, religious, 39 
 
 Commendation, 79 
 
 Commerce, 62 
 
 Common Law States, 153 
 
 Communication, means of, 135 
 
 Competition, 20 
 
 Composite States, 148 
 
 Confederations, 150 
 
 Conquest, 74 
 
 Constable, 53 
 
 Constitutional Government, 85 
 
 Constitutions, rigid or flexible, 146 
 
 Contract, principle of, in politics, 
 
 149 
 Convertible husbandry, 49 
 Council, the, 36, 84, 85-87, 126 
 Courts of law, 121 
 Crops, alternations of, 46 
 Cultivation, systems of, 46 
 Custom, 39, 52, 68, 76, 86, 121 
 
 enforced by State becomes 
 
 legislation, 129 
 Curfew, the, 136 
 Curia, the, 126 
 
 Debts, 104
 
 i6o 
 
 INDEX 
 
 de Coulanges, Fustel, 37, 54 
 Domestication of animals, 19,22 
 Dooms, 1 14 
 Droit Adm'nustratify 154 
 
 Ealdorman, the, 67 
 Elective Monarchy, 83 
 Enclosure movement, 50, 105, 106 
 Estates, representation of, 125-127 
 Exchange, 62, 96 
 Exclusiveness of patriarchal socie- 
 ties, 67 
 •^ of early States, 20 
 
 Fealty, 78 
 
 Federal Constitutions, 152 
 
 States, 149, etc. 
 
 Feudalism, 78, 113, 1 14 
 
 English form of, 113, 114 
 
 hereditary character of, 114 
 
 the State and, 113 
 
 Fictions, 123, 131 
 Field-grass system, 46 
 Fines, 41, 108 
 Forest clearings, 45 
 Forfeiture, no 
 Fosterage, 15, 58 
 
 Gild, the, 60, 65, 66, 69, 79, 138 
 
 character of the, 66 
 
 dissolution of the, 138 
 
 Government, i, 87 
 
 activity of, 87 
 
 constitutional, 85 
 
 constitutional and autocratic 
 
 145 
 
 Headman, the, 52 
 Heir-apparent, the, 35 
 Hereditary kingship, 83 
 Holdings of land, 50-52 
 Household, the, 18, 69 
 Hue and cry, no 
 Hundred-moot, the, 125 
 
 Industry, 60, 62, 64 
 
 specialization of, 62 
 
 Inheritance, 100 
 Institutions, 4, 81 
 Iron, use of, 60 
 Itinerant judges, 113, 122 
 
 Joint liability, 124 
 Judges, 114 
 
 itinerant, 113, 122 
 
 Jurisdiction of the Church, 118 
 Jury, origin of, 117 
 
 foundation of, 122 
 
 Justice, 108, sqq. 
 
 Justice and administration, con- 
 flict of, 154 
 
 King and council, 85 
 King's highway, 135 
 • peace, 91, no, in 
 
 representatives, 87 
 
 Kingship, 81-85 
 
 becomes elective, 83 
 
 becomes hereditary, 83 
 
 religious, 84 
 
 Kinship, 2, n, 37, 55, 57 
 male, 15, 24 
 
 Labour, 26, 51, 79, 97, 105, 137 
 
 State regulation of, 51, 137 
 
 Land, 55, 56, 96, 98, 99, 101-104 
 
 alienation of, 104 
 
 ownership of, 102, 103 
 
 private property in, 96-99 
 
 Landlordism, 100 
 Landlords and the State, 102 
 Landowners, representation of, 1 26 1 
 Law, 119, sqq. 
 
 Law courts, 121 
 
 savage, 12 
 
 tribal, 39, 41 
 
 uniformity of, 121 
 
 Laws, fundamental and ordinary, 
 
 146 
 Legal days, 115
 
 INDEX 
 
 i6i 
 
 Legal fictions, 123 
 
 forms, 1 15 
 
 J.egcs Barbarorum^ i 20 
 Legislation, 119, 123, 128 
 Lex talionis^ 40 
 Local govcniincnt, 125, 147 
 Lord and landlord, 101 
 Lordships, 91, 100, 106 
 
 Majorities, doctrine of, 130-132 
 Market, 63-65 
 Marriage, 9, 15, 26, 28 
 
 by capture, 26 
 
 by purchase, 28 
 
 rules of, 28 
 
 Meadow land, 51 
 Metals, precious, 63 
 
 work in, 60, 73 
 
 Migration, 74 
 Militarism, 76 
 Military allegiance, 75 
 
 service, 2, 79, 90 
 
 societies, type ol, 2 
 
 Modern political machinery, 132 
 
 religion, 38 
 
 societies, 67, 71 
 
 Money, 63 
 Moots, 125 
 
 Nation, not identical with State, 
 
 141 
 Nobility, degrees of, 34 
 
 new, 76, 77 
 
 Nobles, the, 126 
 Nomadism, 56 
 
 Oath of kindred, the. 33, 116 
 Offences, private, 112 
 
 public, 109 
 
 of violence, 108 
 
 Offices, ICO, etc. 
 
 hereditary, 100 
 
 Officials, 70 
 
 Government, riglits and lia- 
 bilities of, 153 
 of village, 52 
 
 Open fields, 50, 105 
 Ordaining power of Crown, 128 
 Ordeal, the, 116 
 Organization, varieties of, 145 
 Outlawry, no 
 
 Pack, the, 8, 18 
 Parliament, the, 125-128 
 
 original duties of, 127 
 
 Pastoral pursuits, 24, 25, 29 
 Paternal authority, 16 
 Fatria potestas, 1 6 
 Patriarchal household, 3 
 
 societies, 2, 3, 15, 17, 67, 69 
 
 and modern societies, 67 
 
 Patricians, 3 
 
 Peers, trial by, 1 12 
 
 Personal union, 19 
 
 Petitions, 128 
 
 Pets, keeping of, 23 
 
 Plague, the, 137 
 
 Plebeians, 3 
 
 I'olice, 136 
 
 Politics, I, 2 
 
 Political rei)resentation, 123, 140 
 
 society, varieties of, 71, 144 
 
 Polygamy, 16 
 
 Poor laws, 139 
 Posts, 135 
 Prerogative, 129 
 
 States, 153 
 
 Private offences, 112 
 
 property, 106 
 
 Production, 62 
 
 Profit, conception of, 29 
 
 of officials, loi 
 
 Property, 25, 28, 93-100, 106, 107 
 
 individual, 97 
 
 origin of, 25 
 
 private, in land, 99 
 
 stages in history of, 96, 98, 
 
 106 
 
 State and, 100, 107 
 
 Proselytism, 38 
 Public health, 140 
 
 property, 94 
 
 M
 
 l6l2 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Punishment, no 
 Purchase as giving title, 98 
 
 Ranks, 33, 34 
 Record, proof by, 116 
 Records, 120 
 
 Relationship, systems of, 11 
 Religion, 36, 38, 75, 84 
 modern, 38 
 
 tribal, 36 
 
 Religious colleges, 39 
 
 secrecy j 38 
 
 Rent, 51, 54, 58, 100 
 
 money, 51 
 
 Representation of estates, 125-12 
 
 political, 123, 140 
 
 Representatives, election of, 130 
 of King, 87 
 
 Revenue, 106, 136 
 Right, a, 93 
 
 Sacrifice, 13, 37 
 
 Sale, savage forms of, 65 
 
 of village land, 104 
 
 Sanctuary, no 
 
 Savage law, 8, 12 
 
 Scatt, 89 
 
 Scottish laws, 57 
 
 Sea, the, no property in, 96 
 
 Secession, 150 
 
 Separation of powers, 155 
 
 Sept, the, 17 
 
 Serfdom, dissolution of, 138 
 
 Serfs, 32, 51 
 
 Sheriffs, 113 
 
 Shire, the, 88 
 
 Shire-moot, 125 
 
 Slavery, 26, 27 
 
 Society, i 
 
 modern, political 
 
 State and administration, 134, etc 
 
 „ feudalism, 113 
 
 • J, landlords, 102 
 
 ,, legislation, 119 
 
 ,, property, 93, 100, 107 
 
 becomes individual, 78 
 
 character of, 75, 134 
 
 • Church and, 76, 84 
 
 interference, 141-143 
 
 justice of, 1 10, 114, 115 
 
 origin of modern, in warfare' 
 
 7i> 73 
 
 socialism, 136 
 
 the territorial, 75 
 
 7I States, classification of, 144, sqq. 
 
 common law ajid preroga 
 
 tive, 153 
 
 composite, 148 
 
 federal, 149 
 
 organization of, 81 
 
 Statute of Winchester, 53 
 Succession, agnatic, 36 
 
 Taxation, 127 
 Taxes, 101 
 Territorial States, 
 
 75 
 
 71, etc.; 
 
 [44 
 
 Sovereignty, 144, 146 
 Specialisation, 62, 73 
 Standards of measure and vahu 
 
 136 
 State administration, 140-143 
 
 union, 19 
 
 waters, 96 
 
 Theft, 108 
 Theology, 38 
 Three-field system, 47 
 Tithings, 136 
 Tokens, 63 
 Totem, the, 12 
 
 group, the, 9 
 
 Totemistic societies, 3, 9-12 
 
 Townsmen, representation oi, 1 
 
 Trade Unions, 138 
 
 Traditions, 86 
 
 Treason, 111 
 
 Trial by battle, 109, 116 
 
 by jury, 117 
 
 Tribal chief, the, 70 
 
 land, 36 
 
 law, 39, 41 
 
 organization, 31, etc., 54 
 
 ^.
 
 INDEX 
 
 163 
 
 Tribal religion, 36 
 Tribe, the, 8, 17, 31, 69 
 Tribes, consolidation of, 74 
 
 differentiation of, 29 
 
 membership of, 32 
 
 officials of, 34 
 
 pastoral, 27 
 
 Tribunals, 118 
 Tribute, forms of, 90 
 Two-field system, 46 
 
 Unearned increment, 102 
 
 Union and unity, 149 
 
 Unions, classification of, 150, etc, 
 
 real, 150 
 
 User of land, limited, 99 
 the germ of property, 96 
 
 Value, standards of, 63, 136 
 Vassals, 78 
 Village, the, 49, etc. 
 
 agricultural, the, 99, etc. 
 
 communities, 49, etc. 
 
 dissolution of, 103 
 
 Village craftsmen, 64 
 
 custom, 105 
 
 lordship, 58 
 
 officials, 52 
 
 organization, 55 
 
 origin of, 53, 54 
 
 Villagers, the, become tenants, 106 
 Violence, no 
 
 War, 71, 77, 89 
 
 bands, German, 73 
 
 Waste, 50, 51 
 Wealth, 72 
 
 of nations, 139 
 
 Weapons, 72, 96 
 Welsh chief, the, 34 
 
 laws, 56 
 
 societies, 16 
 
 Witnesses, 116 
 Worship, 37, 38, 66, 76 
 Wrongs, bootless, 109 
 
 ZoUverein, 150 
 
 GLOSSARY 
 
 kglia, 51, 54 
 Icheringa, the, 
 Alltud, 32, 57 
 
 Balks, 50 
 Ballys, 56 
 Birraark, the, 11 
 Boaire, the, 29, 33, 55 
 Bothach, 33 
 Brehons, 36 
 
 Taetli, 33 
 Jantred, 57 
 j -eile, 55, 59 
 
 Ciniud, 55 
 Corroboree, 10 
 Cro, 41 
 Cyning, 34 
 
 Davoch, 57 
 Dialwr, 35 
 
 Etch grain, 49 
 Engrossing, 69 
 Eric, 41 
 
 Feastings, 54, 58 
 Fer Midba, 33
 
 i64 
 
 GLOSSARY 
 
 Fine, 55 
 Flaith, the, 55 
 Forestalling, 69 
 Frith-gild, 66 
 Fuidhir, 32, 55 
 
 Galanas, 41 
 Gesith, 73 
 Gwely, 57 
 
 Heretoch, 35, 73 
 Henadwr, 36 
 Husbandland, 57 
 
 Jirgah, 36 
 
 Khan, 34 
 Khiraj, 58 
 
 Mab, the, 16 
 Maiden fee, 58 
 Moot, 53 
 Mormaer, 34 
 
 Nardoo, 43 
 Neme, 29 
 
 Panchayat, 36 
 Parker, 53 
 Pen, 34 
 Pound, 53 
 Princeps, 73 
 
 Rachimburg, 36 
 Reeve, 52, 53 
 Ri, 34 
 
 Seisrigh, 56 
 Sencleithe, the, 33 
 Steelbow lands, 57 
 Synnachies, 36 
 
 Taboo, 12 
 Txog, 33 
 Tanist, 35 
 Teisbanteuleu, 35 
 Tenandrie, 57 
 Thane, 73 
 Thaneston, 57 
 Tilth grain, 49 
 Tir Gwelyawg, 57 
 Toisech, 35 
 Tricha Ceds, 56 
 Tumandar, 34 
 
 Uchelwr, 57 
 
 Veliki Kniaz, 35 
 Vesh, 52 
 
 Wer, 41 
 
 Yardling, 51, 55 
 
 Zamindar, 51 
 
 Richard Clay Csf Sons, Limited, London Gf Bungay.
 
 i 
 
 >!p^ 
 
 
 THE LIBRARY 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA 
 
 Santa Barbara 
 
 t 
 
 THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE 
 STAMPED BELOW.
 
 UC SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY 
 
 B 000 010 689 8