NRLF
LIFE OF ARISTOTLE;
A CRITICAL DISCUSSION
QUESTIONS OF LITERARY HISTORY
CONNECTED WITH
HIS WORKS.
BY
JOSEPH WILLIAMS BLAKESLEY, M.A.
ft t
FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE.
CAMBRIDGE :
J. AND J. J. DEIGHTON.
LONDON: JOHN W. PARKER.
M.DCCC.XXX1X.
ADVERTISEMENT.
THE following Essay is intended by the author
to be preliminary to a few others in which he hopes
to give an account of the several systems of Ancient
Philosophy which converged in those of Plato and
Aristotle, to pursue some of the more important
branches of speculation in the course which they took
after leaving the hands of the latter, and to examine
the success which has attended their cultivation up to
the present time. Before this task could be attempted
with any advantage, it was necessary to enter upon some
points relative to the history of philosophical literature,
and, from the nature of these, no mode of discussing
them appeared preferable to interweaving them in a cri-
tical biography of the founder of the Peripatetic School.
The present treatise, however, although the first of a
series, is complete in itself, and it is the intention
of the writer to preserve a similar independence to
each of the others.
CHAPTER
INTRODUC W J I 7 E E SI f T!
&1
IF the acquaintance we possessed with the private
life of individuals were at all proportioned to the in-
fluence exerted by them on the destinies of mankind,
the biography of Aristotle would fill a library; for
without attempting here to discuss the merits of his
philosophy as compared with that of others, it_may
safely be asserted that no man has ever yet lived \vho
exerted so much influence upon the world. Absorbing
into his capacious mind the whole existing philosophy
of his age, he reproduced it, digested and transmuted,
in a form of which the main outlines are recognised at
the present day, and of which the language has pene-
trated into the inmost recesses of our daily life. Trans-
lated in the fifth century of the Christian^ era into
the Syriac language by the Nestorians who fled to
Persia, and from Syriac into Arabic four hundred years
later, his writings furnished the Mohammedan con-
querors of the East with a germ of science which, but
for the effect of their religious and political insti-
tutions, might have shot up into as tall a tree as it
did produce in the West ; while his logical works,
in the Latin translation which Boethius, " the last of the
Romans," bequeathed as a legacy to posterity, formed
the basis of that extraordinary phenomenon, the Philo-
sophy jrfthe Schoolmen. An empire like this, extending
over nearly twenty centuries of time, sometimes more
sometimes less despotically, but always with great force,
recognised in Bagdad and in Cordova, in Egypt and in
1
2 SCANTY MATERIALS.
Britain, and leaving abundan't traces of itself in the
language and modes of thought of every European nation,
is assuredly without a parallel. Yet of its founder's perso-
nal history all that we can learn is to be gathered from
meager compilations, scattered anecdotes, and accidental
notices, which contain much that is obviously false and
even contradictory, and from which a systematic account,
in which tolerable confidence may be placed, can only
be deduced by a careful and critical investigation. \J
It is not, however, to the indifference of his con-
temporaries, or to that of their immediate successors,
that the paucity of details relating to Aristotle's life
is due. If we may trust the account of a commenta-
tor, Ptolemy Philadelphus, the second of the Mace-
donian dynasty in Egypt, not only bestowed a great
deal of study upon the writings of the illustrious philoso-
pher, but also wrote a biography of him 1 . At any
rate, about the same time, Hermippus of Smyrna, one
of the Alexandrine school of learned men, whose re-
search and accuracy is highly praised by Josephus 2 ,
composed a work extending to some length, On the
Lives of Distinguished Philosophers and Orators, in
which Aristotle appears to have occupied a consider-
able space 3 . Another author, whose date there is no
1 David the Armenian, in a commentary on the Categories, cited
by Brandis in the Rheinisches Museum, Vol. i. p. 250, and since
published by him from two Vatican MSS., says, Twi/ 'Apio-roTeAiKwi/
(Tvyypa/jifjidTutv TroAA&H' owrmv ^i\i(av TOV apid/jLov, OK (ptjcri IlToAe//a?O9
o OiAa3eAt'Aov xpe Vit. sec. 31.
24 IS SAID TO HAVE DISPLEASED PLATO.
it appears that in spite of this there was by no means
a perfect congeniality in their feelings. Aristotle is
said to have offended his master not only by the
carefulness respecting his personal appearance which
we have just spoken of, but by a certain sarcastic
habit (juto/act) 1 , which showed itself in the expression
of his countenance. It is difficult to imagine that he
should have indulged this humour in a greater degree
than Socrates is represented to have done by Plato
himself. However, a vein of irony which would ap-
pear very graceful in the master whom he reverenced,
and whose views he enthusiastically embraced, might
seem quite the reverse in a youthful pupil who pro-
mised speedily to become a rival. An anecdote is
related by Julian 2 , from which we should infer that
overt hostility broke out between them. Aristotle, it
is said, taking advantage of the absence of Xenocrates
from Athens, and of the temporary confinement of
Speusippus by illness, attacked Plato in the presence
of his disciples with a series of subtle sophisms, which,
his powers being impaired by extreme old age, had
the effect of perplexing him and obliging him to retire in
confusion and shame from the walks of the Academy. Xe-
nocrates, however, returning three months after, drove
Aristotle away, and restored his master to his old
haunts. On this or some other occasion it is said that
Plato compared his pupil's conduct to that of the young
foals who kick at their dam as soon as dropped 3 . And
the opinion that Aristotle had in some way or other
behaved with ingratitude to his master, certainly had
obtained considerable currency in antiquity; but it is
1 JElisan, he. cit.
2 Ibid.
* Mian, Var. Hist. iv. 9.
PROBABLE ORIGIN OF THE STORY. 25
probable that this in a great measure arose from the
false interpretation of a passage in the biography of
Plato by Aristoxenus the musician, whom we have
noticed in the last chapter. This writer had related
that "while Plato was absent from Athens on his tra-
vels, certain individuals, who were foreigners, established
a school in opposition to him." "Some," adds Aristo-
cles, the Peripatetic philosopher 4 , after quoting this
passage, " have imagined that Aristotle was the per-
son here alluded to, but they forget that Aristoxenus,
throughout the whole of his work, speaks of Aristotle
in terms of praise." Every one who is conversant
with the productive power of Greek imagination, and
the rapidity with which in that fertile soil anecdotes
sprang up and assumed a more and more circumstan-
tial character on repetition, will not wonder that in
the course of five centuries which intervened between
Aristoxenus and ^Elian, the vague statement of the
first should have bourgeoned into the circumstantial
narrative of the second 5 .
* Ap. Eusebium, Prceparatio Evangelica, xv. 2. Aristocles, a
native of Messina, was the preceptor of the virtuous Emperor Alex-
ander Severus, not of Alexander Aphrodisiensis, and consequently
lived in the first half of the third century of the Christian era.
The work from which Eusebius extracts a passage of some length
relating to Aristotle, was a kind of History of Philosophy, in ten
books. Eusebius's extract is a part of the seventh. The learning
and discrimination of the writer is very great. He traces the
stories which he has occasion to mention up to their earliest ori-
gin, and refutes them in a masterly manner. There is a literary
notice of him in Fabricius's Bibliotkeca Grceca, iii. c. viii. where
see Heumann's note. It is curious that in the Latin Life Aristocles
is cited together with Aristoxenus as an authority for the very story
which he is concerned to refute.
The literary men of the declining period considered it a part
of their duty to supply all the details which their readers might
26 DISCREPANT ACCOUNTS.
Independently of the vulgar insolence with which
this story invests the character of Aristotle, a quality
of which there is not a trace in his writings, there
is much which may render us extremely suspicious of
receiving it. In the first place, other stories of equal
authority represent his feelings towards his master as
those of ardent admiration and deep respect. His bio-
grapher informs us that he dedicated an altar (by
which he probably means a cenotaph) to Plato, and
put an inscription on it to the purport that Plato " was
a man whom it was sacrilege for the bad even to
praise." There is certainly not much credit to be at-
tached to the literal truth of this story 1 ; but its cha-
desiderate in the more general notices of the classical writers. An
amusing instance of this kind of writer is Ptolemy, the son of He-
phaestion, whose book is described by Photius (Biblioth. p. 146 153,
Bekker), and strongly praised by him for its utility to those who
were desirous of -rroXv^adia foroputij. Not to mention the secret
history of the death of Hercules, Achilles, and various other cele-
brated characters, we are informed of the name of the Delphian, whom
Herodotus abstains from mentioning (i. 51), and of that of the
Queen of Candaules, which latter it seems was Nysia. The reason
of Herodotus abstaining from giving it was, that a youth named
Plesirrhoiis, to whom he was much attached, had fallen in love
with a lady of that appellation, and, not succeeding in his suit, had
hanged himself. This Ptolemy related in his fifth book. In the
third he had informed his readers that this very Plesirrhoiis inhe-
rited Herodotus s property, and wrote the preface to his History, the
commencement of it as left by the author having been with the
words Ilepo-ewi/ ol \6jioi. He probably knew that the readers for
whom he wrote, even if they read both anecdotes, would have
forgotten the first by the time they reached the second. Yet the
age, whose taste could render books of this description popular,
was no more recent than that of Hadrian, at whose court JElian and
Phavorinus lived and wrote.
1 The phrase in question is found in an elegy to Eudemus, cited
by Olympiodorus, Comment, ad Plalon. Gorgiam. (Bekk. p. 53.}
HIS OWN EXPRESSIONS XENOCRATES. 27
racter may be considered to indicate the view which the
authority followed hy the biographer took of Aristotle's
sentiments towards his master. Still better evidence
exists in the way in which Plato is spoken of in the
works of his pupil that have come down to us. His
opinions are often controverted, but always with fair-
ness, and never with discourtesy. If he is sometimes
misapprehended, the misapprehension never appears to
be wilful. In one rather remarkable instance there is
exhibited a singular tenderness and delicacy towards
him. The passage in question is near the commence-
ment of the Nicomachean Ethics 2 . To the doctrine of
Ideas or Archetypal Forms, as maintained by Plato,
Aristotle was opposed. It became necessary for him,
in the treatment of his subject, to discuss the bearing
of this doctrine upon it, and he complains that his task
is an unwelcome one, from the circumstance of persons
to whom he is attached (va-iv e'i\TO vaieiv
AI/T' *AKCt$7/A6ta$ fiopfiopov ei> Tr^o^oaiV.
although Plutarch applies it to his residence in Macedonia. The
cenotaph spoken of in the second line is probably the foundation for
32
36 REASONS FOR GOING THERE.
seem to deserve but little credit, when we consider
that the position which Plato had held was not recog-
nised in any public manner ; that there was neither
endowment nor dignity attached to it ; that all honour
or profit that could possibly arise from it was due solely
to the personal merits of the philosopher; that in all
probability Aristotle himself had occupied a similar
position before the death of Plato ; and, that if he felt
himself injured by the selection of Speusippus (Plato's
nephew), he had every opportunity of showing, by the
best of all tests, competition, how erroneous a judgment
had been formed of their respective merits. And with
regard to the second view, it will be sufficient to remark,
that for the twenty years preceding this epoch, as well
as afterwards, he possessed the option of living at the
court of Macedonia, where he probably had connexions,
and where there was equal scope for indulging the
tastes in question. We shall, therefore, feel no scruple
in referring this journey to other and more adequate
causes. The reader of Grecian history will not fail
to recollect that the suspicions which the Athenians
had for some time entertained of the ambitious designs
of Philip received a sudden confirmation just at this
moment by the successes of that monarch in the Chal-
cidian peninsula. The fall of Olynthus and the de-
struction of the Greek confederacy, of which that town
was at the head 1 , produced at Athens a feeling of in-
dignation mixed with fear, of which Demosthenes did
not fail to take advantage to kindle a strong hatred of
the " altar" to Plato, of which the latter writers speak. See above,
p. 7. Theocritus of Chios was a contemporary of Aristotle. The
Syracusah poet of the same name, in an Epigram ascribed to him,
protests against being identified with him.
1 Above, p. 13.
STATE OF POLITICS. 37
any thing belonging to Macedon. The modern ex-
ample of France will enable us readily to understand
how dangerous must have been the position of a
foreigner, by birth, connexions, or feelings in the
slightest degree mixed up with the unpopular party,
especially when resident in a democratic State, in
which the statute laws were every day subject to be
violated by the extemporaneous resolutions (^Yi^ia^ara)
of a popular assembly. Philip indeed was accustomed
or at any rate by his enemies believed to make use
of such aliens, as from any cause were allowed free
ingress to the States with which he was not on good
terms, as his emissaries 2 . It is scarcely possible under
these circumstances to conceive that the jealousy of
party hatred should fail to view the distinguished
philosopher, the friend of Antipater, and the son of a
Macedonian court-physician, with dislike and distrust,
especially if, as from Cicero's description appears highly
probable, political affairs entered considerably into the
course of his public instructions.
Here, then, we have a reason, quite independent of
any peculiar motive, for Aristotle's quitting Athens at
this especial time. And others, scarcely less weighty,
existed to take him to the court of Hermias. Some
little time before, the gigantic body of the Persian
empire had exhibited symptoms of breaking up. Egypt
had for a considerable period maintained itself in a
state of independence, and the success of the experi-
ment had produced the revolt of Phoenicia. The cities
of Asia Minor, whose intercourse with Greece Proper
was constant, naturally felt an even greater desire to
throw off the yoke, and about the year 349 before
The case of Anaxirious (see vEschines c. Ctes. p. 85. Demosth.
De Cor. p. 272.) may serve as one instance among many.
38 REVOLT OF PERSIAN DEPENDANCIES.
the Christian era, most of them were in a state of
open rebellion. Confederacies of greater or less extent
were formed among them for the purpose of maintaining
the common independence ; and over one of these, which
included Atarneus and Assos, one Eubulus, a native of
Bithynia, exercised a sway which Suidas represents as
that of an absolute prince 1 . This remarkable man, of
whom it is much to be regretted that we know so little,
is described as having carried on the trade of a banker 2
in one of these towns. If this be true, the train of
circumstances which led him to the pitch of power
which he seems to have reached was probably such a
one as, in more modern times made the son of a
brewer of Ghent Regent of Flanders, or the Medici
Dukes of Tuscany. A struggle for national existence
calls forth the confidence of the governed in those who
possess the genius which alone can preserve them, as
unboundedly as it stimulates that genius itself; and
there appears no reason why the name of tyrant or
dynast should have been bestowed upon Eubulus more
than upon Philip van Artevelde or William of Orange.
He was assisted in the duties of his government, and
afterwards succeeded by Hermias, who is termed by
Strabo his slave, an expression which a Greek would
apply no less to the Vizier than to the lowest menial
servant of an Asiatic potentate. He is also described
as an eunuch, but, whether this was the case or not,
he was a man of education and philosophy, and had
during a residence at Athens attended the instructions
of both Plato and Aristotle 3 . By the invitation of this
'ITOV. Strabo, xiii. vol. iii. p. 126.
3 Strabo, loc. cit.
SUPPRESSION OF THE REVOLT. 39
individual, the latter, accompanied by Xenocrates, passed
over at this particular juncture into Mysia ; and it will
surely not seem an improbable conjecture that the
especial object for which their presence was desired was
to frame a political constitution, in order that the little
confederacy, of which Hermias may perhaps be regarded
as the general and stadtholder, might be kept together
and enabled to maintain its independence in spite of
the formidable power of the Persian empire. Ably as
such a task would doubtless have been executed by so
wise a statesman, as even the fragmentary political
work that has come down to us proves Aristotle to have
been, it was not blessed with success. Fortune for a
time favoured the cause of freedom, but the barbarian's
hour was not yet come. The treachery of a Rhodian
leader of condottieri in the service of the revolted
Egyptians enabled the Persian king, Artaxerxes Ochus,
rapidly to overrun Phoenicia and Egypt, and to devote
the whole force of his empire to the reduction of Asia
Minor. Yet Hermias made his ground good, until
at last he suffered himself to be entrapped into a per-
sonal conference with the Greek general Mentor, the
traitor whose perfidy had ruined the Egyptian cause,
and who now commanded the Persian army that was
sent against Atarneus. In spite of the assurance of a
solemn oath, his person was seized and sent to the
court of the Persian king, who ordered him to be
strangled ; the fortresses which commanded the coun-
try surrendered at the sight of his signet ; and Atar-
neus and Assos were occupied by Persian troops'.
The two philosophers, surprised by these sudden
misfortunes, were however fortunate enough to succeed
4 Strabo. loc. cit. Diodorus, xvi. sec. 52, 53, 54.
40 MARRIAGE OF ARISTOTLE.
in escaping to Mytilene, whither they carried with them
a female named Pythias, who according to the most
probable accounts was the sister and adopted daughter
of Hermias l . It is singular that Aristotle's intercourse
with the Prince of Atarneus, and more especially that
part which related to his connection with this woman,
whom he married, should have brought more calumny
^non him than any other event of his life ; and the
angest thing of all, according to our modern habits
ol thinking, is that he himself should have thought
it necessary, for the satisfaction of his own friends, to
give a particular explanation of his motives to the mar-
riage. In a letter to Antipater, which is cited by Aris-
tocles 2 , he relates the circumstances which induced him
to take this step; and they are calculated to give us
as high an opinion of the goodness of his heart as his
works do of the power of his intellect. The calamity
which had befallen Hermias would necessarily have
entailed utter misery, and in all probability death, upon
his adopted daughter, had she been left behind. In
this conjuncture, respect for the memory of his murdered
friend, and compassion for the defenceless situation of
the girl, induced him, knowing her besides, as he says,
to be modest and amiable 3 , to take her as his wife. It
is a striking proof of the utter want of sentiment in the
intercourse between the sexes in Greece, that this noble
and generous conduct, as every European will at once
confess it to have been, should have drawn down ob-
loquy upon the head of its actor ; while, if he had left
the helpless creature to be carried off to a Persian ha-
rem, or sacrificed to the lust of a brutal soldiery, not
1 Aristocles, #p. Euseb. /be. cit.
- Ap. Euseb. loc. cit.
CALUMNIES AGAINST HIM. 41
a human being would have breathed the slightest word
of censure upon the atrocity. Even his apologists ap-
pear to have considered this as one of the most vul-
nerable points of his character. When Aristocles 4 dis-
cusses the charges which had been made against him,
he dismisses most of them with contempt as carrying
the marks of falsehood in their very front. " Two, how-
ever," he adds, "do appear to have obtained credit,
the one that he treated Plato with ingratitude, the
other that he married the daughter of Hermias." And
indeed the relation of Aristotle to the father furnished
a subject for many publications 5 in the second and third
centuries before Christ, and appears to have excited as
much interest among literary antiquarians of that day,
as the question of the Iron Mask or of who wrote the
Letters of Junius, might do in modern times. The
treatise of Apellicon of Teos, a wealthy antiquary and
bibliomaniac contemporary with Sylla, was regarded as
the classical work among them. We shall have occasion,
in the sequel, to say something more about this per-
sonage. Aristocles 6 speaks of his book as sufficient
to set the whole question at rest, and silence all the
calumniators of the philosopher for ever. Indeed, if
we may judge of the whole of their charges from the
few specimens that have come down to us, a further
refutation than their own extravagance was hardly
needful. The hand of Pythias is there represented
as purchased by a fulsome adulation of her adopted
father 7 , and a subserviency to the most loathsome
4 Ap. Euseb. loc. cit.
5 Aristocles, loc. cit.
6 Ap. Euseb. loc. cit.
7 She is in some accounts represented, not as his sister, but his
concubine. Others, not considering him an eunuch, call her his
42 SCOLIUM TO HERMIAS.
vices which human nature in its lowest state of de-
pravity can engender; and the husband is said, in
exultation at his good fortune, to have paid to his
father-in-law a service appropriated to the gods alone,
singing his praises, like those of Apollo, in a sacred
paean. Fortunately this composition has come down
to us, and turns out to be a common scolium, or drink-
ing song, similar in its nature to the celebrated one,
so popular at Athenian banquets, which records the
achievement of Harmodius and Aristogiton. It pos-
sesses no very high degree of poetical merit, but as an
expression of good feeling, and as a literary curiosity,
being the only remaining specimen of its author's powers
in this branch, it perhaps deserves a place in the note *.
daughter. One, probably to reconcile all accounts, calls her his
daughter, j?i/ KO.\ 0Aa3i\iov
KO\ 'Arapi/e
aeAiou ^rjpwtrev at-ya?.
Toiydp a'oi'BtjUO? epyots*
dOdvaTov TC fjnv av
re yepas fiefiaiov.
CHARGE OF BLASPHEMY. 43
The perfection of the manly character is personified as
a virgin, for whose charms it is an enviable lot even to
die, or to endure the severest hardships. The enthu-
siasm with which she inspires the hearts of her lovers
is more precious than gold, than parents, than the lux-
ury of soft-eyed sleep ! For her it was that Hercules
and the sons of Leda toiled, and Achilles and Ajax
died! her fair form, too, made Hermias, the nursling
of Atarneus, renounce the cheerful light of the sun.
Hence his deeds shall become the subjects of song,
and the Muses, daughters of memory, shall wed him
to immortality when they magnify the name of Jupiter
Xenius (i.e. Jupiter as the protector of the laws of
hospitality), and bestow its meed on firm and faith-
ful friendship I By comparing this relic with the sco-
lium to Harmodius and Aristogiton, which Athenaeus
has preserved on the page preceding the one from which
this is taken, the reader will at once see that Hermias
is mentioned together with Achilles and Ajax, and the
other heroes of mythology, only in the same manner as
Harmodius is ; yet not only did this performance hring
down on its author's head the calumnies we have men-
tioned, but many years after it was even made the basis
of a prosecution of him for blasphemy : such straws will
envy and malice grasp at !
The respect of the philosopher for his departed friend
was yet further attested by the erection of a statue, or,
as some say, a cenotaph, to him at Delphi, with an in-
scription, in which his death was recorded as wrought
in outrage of the sacred laws of the gods, by the mo-
This Scolium is preserved in Diogenes Laert. Vit. Arist. sec. 7 ;
Athenaeus, p. 696; and Stobaeus, Serm. i. p. 2. From the first,
sec. 27, we learn that Aristotle also composed some epic and some
elegiac poetry.
44 ARISTOTLE IN MACEDONIA.
narch of the bow-bearing Persians, not fairly by the
spear in the bloody battle-field, but through the false
pledge of a crafty villain ! / And " the nearer view
of wedded life " does not seem in any respect to have
diminished the good opinion he had originally formed
of his friend's daughter. She died, how soon after
their marriage we cannot say, leaving one orphan
daughter ; and not only was her memory honoured hy
the widower with a respect which exposed him, as in
the former instance of her father, to the charge of
idolatry 2 , but, in his will, made some time afterwards,
he provides that her hones should be taken up and
laid by the side of his, wherever he might be buried,
as, says he, she herself enjoined 3 .
At this epoch of Aristotle's life, when the clouds of
adversity appeared to be at the thickest, his brightest
fortunes were about to appear. He had fled to Myti-
lene an exile, deprived of his powerful friend, and ap-
parently cut off from all present opportunity of bringing
his gigantic powers of mind into play. But in Myti-
lene he received an invitation from Philip to undertake
the training of one who, in the World of Action, was
destined to achieve an empire, which only that of his
master in the World of Thought has ever surpassed.
A conjunction of two such spirits has not been yet
twice recorded in the annals of mankind ; and it is
impossible to conceive any thing more interesting and
fruitful than a good contemporary account of the in-
tercourse between them would have been. But, although
such a one did exist, as we shall see below, we are not
1 Diog. Fit. sec. 6.
2 Ibid. sec. 4.
; 7A/W. sec. 16.
PREVIOUSLY KNOWN TO PHILIP. 45
fortunate enough to possess it. The destroying hand
of time has been most active exactly where we should
most desire information as to details, and almost all the
description we can give of this period is founded upon
the scanty notices on the subject furnished by Plutarch
in his biography of the Great Conqueror.
How much the mere personal character of Aristotle
contributed to procuring him the invitation from Philip,
it is difficult to say. Cicero represents the King as
mainly determined to the step by the reputation of the
philosopher's rhetorical lectures 4 . But a letter preserved
by Aulus Gellius 5 , which is well known, but can
scarcely be genuine, would induce us to believe that,
from the very birth of Alexander, he was destined by
his father to grow up under the superintendence of his
latest instructor. It is, indeed, not unlikely that, at
this early period, Aristotle was well known to Philip.
We have seen that, not improbably, his earliest years
were passed at the court, where his father possessed the
highest confidence of the father of Philip. Moreover,
he is said, although neither the time nor the occasion
is specified, to have rendered services to the Athenians
as ambassador to the court of Macedon 6 . But if Gel-
lius's letter be genuine, how are we able to account for
the absence of the philosopher from his charge during the
thirteen years which elapsed between its professed date
and the second year of the 109th Olympiad, in which
we know for certain that he first entered upon his im-
portant task? For that it was not because he consi-
dered the influences exerted upon this tender age
4 De Oratore, iii. 55.
5 ix. 3.
6 Diog. Vit. sec. 2.
46 ALEXANDER'S EARLY PRECEPTORS
unimportant, is clear from the great stress he lays upon
their effect in the eighth book of his Politics, which
is entirely devoted to the details of this subject 1 . And
although Alexander was only thirteen years old when
his connection with Aristotle commenced, yet the seeds
of many vices had even at that early period been sown
by the unskilful hands of former instructors; and per-
haps the best means of estimating the value of Aris-
totle's services, is to compare what his pupil really
became with what he would naturally have been had
he been left under the care of these. Two are par-
ticularly noticed by Plutarch 2 , of totally opposite dis-
positions, and singularly calculated to produce, by their
combined action, that oscillation between asceticism and
luxury which, in the latter part of his life especially,
was so striking a feature in Alexander's character. The
first was Leonidas, a relation of his mother Olympias,
a rough and austere soldier, who appears to have di-
rected all his efforts to the production of a Spartan en-
durance of hardship and contempt of danger. He was
accustomed to ransack his pupil's trunks for the pur-
pose of discovering any luxurious dress or other means
of indulgence which might have been sent to him by his
mother : and, at the outset of Alexander's Asiatic expe-
dition, on the occasion of an entertainment by his adopted
mother, a Carian princess, he told her that Leonidas's
early discipline had made all culinary refinements a
matter of indifference to him ; that the only cook he had
ever been allowed to season his breakfast was a good
night's journey ; and the only one to improve his supper,
1 See especially p. 1334, col. 2, line 25, et seq. ; p. 1338, col. 1,
line 5, et seq. ed. Bekker.
2 Fit. Alex. sec. 5.
LEONIDAS LYSIMACHUS. 47
a scanty breakfast 3 . An education of which these traits
are characteristic might very well produce the personal
hardiness and animal courage for which Alexander was
distinguished; it might enable him to tame a Buce-
phalus, to surpass all his contemporaries in swiftness
of foot, to leap down alone amidst a crowd of enemies
from the ramparts of a besieged town, to kill a lion in
single combat 4 ; it might even inspire the passion for
military glory which vented itself in tears when there
was nothing left to conquer 5 ; but it would be almost
as favourable to the growth of the coarser vices as to the
developement of these ruder virtues, and we learn that,
to the day of his death, the ruffianly and intemperate
dispositions which belong to barbarian blood, and which
the influences of Leonidas had tended rather to increase
than diminish, were never entirely subdued by Alex-
ander 6 .
The character of Lysimachus, the other instructor
especially noticed by Plutarch, was very different, but
hardly likely to have produced a much more beneficial
effect. He was by birth an Acarnanian, and an expert
flatterer, by which means he is said to have gained
great favour. His favourite thought appears to have
been to compare Alexander to Achilles, Philip to Pe-
3 Plutarch, Vit. sec. 22.
4 Ibid. 640, &c.
5 Unus Pellceo juueni non sufficit orbis. Juv. Sat. x. 168.
6 Leonidas Alexandri pcedagogus, ut a Babylonia Diogene traditur,
quibusdam cum vitiis imbuit, quce robustum quoque et jam maximum
regem ab ilia institutione puerili sunt prosecuta. Quintilian, Inst.
Or. i. 1. 8. Is it not probable that Aristotle, in the seventh book
of his Politics, (p. 1324, col. 1, line 23, et seq., and p. 1333, col. 2,
line 10, et seq.) has a particular reference to the views of Leonidas?
See also above, p. 4-6. note 1 .
48 LITTLE GAIN FROM THEM.
leus, and himself to Phoenix, as the characters were
described in the epic poetry of Greece, and this insipid
stuff it was his delight to act out in the ordinary busi-
ness of life. At a later period, this passion for scene-
making nearly cost poor Phcenix and his master their
lives ' ; and to it is probably due, in a great measure,
the cormorant appetite for adulation which is the most
disgusting feature in the history of the latter.
To neither then of these two individuals, and if
not to these, of course much less to the crowd of mas-
ters in reading, writing, horsemanship, harp-playing,
and the other accomplishments included by ancient
education in its two branches of HOUVIKJ and yvfjivofrriKri,
can we ascribe a share in the production of that cha-
racter which distinguishes Alexander from any successful
military leader. But to Aristotle some of the ancients
attribute a degree and kind of merit in this respect
which is perfectly absurd. Plutarch says that his pupil
received from him more towards the accomplishment of
his schemes than from Philip 2 . Alexander himself was
accustomed to say, that he honoured Aristotle no less
than his own father, that to the one he owed life, but
to the other all that made life valuable 3 ; and it is
very likely that the misinterpretation of such phrases
as these led to the belief that the Conqueror had re-
ceived from his instructor direct advice for the accom-
1 Plutarch, Fit. sec. 24.
2 Plutarch, De Fortun. Alexandri. p. 327- See Ste. Croix,
Examen critique des historiens d' Alexandre-le-grand, p. 84. Such
expressions as these led later writers to yet more extravagant ones,
such as Roger Bacon's, per vias sapientice mundum Alexandra
tradidit Aristoteles ; and probably to the same source is to be traced
the romance of the philosopher having personally attended his
pupil in his expedition.
3 Plutarch, Vit. Alex. sec. 8.
EFFECTS PRODUCED BY ARISTOTLE. 49
plishment of the great exploit which has made him
known to posterity.ViBut the obligations to which he
really alluded were probably of a totally different
kind. Philip is said to have perceived at a very early
age that his son's disposition was a most peculiar one,
sensible in the highest degree of kindness, and tract-
able by gentle measures, but absolutely ungovernable
by force, and consequently requiring, instead of the
austerity of a Leonidas, or the flattery- of a Lysi-
machus, the influence of one who could by his cha-
racter and abilities command respect, and by his tact
and judgment preserve it. Such qualifications he found
in Aristotle, and the good effects seem to have speedily
shown themselves. From a rude and intemperate bar-
barian's his nature expanded and exhibited itself in an
attachment to philosophy, a desire of mental eultiva- /
tion, and a fondness for study. Klo completely did he
acquire higher and more civilized tastes, that while
at the extremity of Asia, in a letter to Harpalus he
desires that the works of Philistus the historian, the
tragedies of ^Eschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides, and
the dithyrambs of Telestes and Philoxenus, should be
sent to him. Homer was his constant travelling com- \
panion. A copy, corrected by Aristotle, was deposited
by the side of his dagger, under the pillow of the couch
on which he slept 4 ; and on the occasion of a magnifi-
cent casket being found among the spoils of Darius's
eamp, when a discussion arose as to how it should be
employed, the King declared that it should be appro-
priated to the use of containing this copy 5 . But his
education had not been confined to the lighter species
4 Plutarch, Vit. sec. 7, 8.
3 Plutarch, Vit. sec. 26. Strabo, xiii. Plin. Nat. Hist. v. SO.
4
50 HIS RAPID EDUCATION.
of literature ; on the contrary, he appears to have been
introduced to the gravest and most abstruse parts of
philosophy, to which the term of acroamatic was specifi-
cally applied. We shall in the sequel examine more
fully what exact notion is to be attached to this term:
in the mean time, it will be sufficient to observe that it
included the highest branches of the science of that day.
In a letter, then, preserved by Plutarch and Aulus
Gellius 1 , Alexander complains that his preceptor had
published those of his works to which this phrase was
applied. "How," he asks, "now that this is the case,
will he be able to maintain his superiority to others in
mental accomplishments, a superiority which he valued
more than the distinction he had won by his conquests?"
Gellius likewise gives us Aristotle's answer, in which he
excuses himself by saying, " that although the works in
question were published, they would be useless to all
who had not previously enjoyed the benefit of his oral
instructions." Whatever may be our opinion as to the
genuineness of these letters, which Gellius says he took
from the book of the philosopher Andronicus, (a contem-
porary of Cicero's, to whom we shall in the sequel
again revert,) it is quite clear that if they are forgeries,
they were forged in accordance with a general belief of
the time, that there was no department of knowledge
however recondite to which Aristotle had not taken
pains to introduce his pupil.
But the most extraordinary feature in the education
of Alexander is the short space of time which it occupied.
From the time of Aristotle's arrival in Macedonia to
the expedition of his pupil into Asia there elapsed eight
years, (i. e. from Olymp. cix. 2. to Olymp. cxi. 2.) But
1 Plutarch, Fit. Alex. sec. 7- Gellius, Noc. Ait. xx. 5.
BOOKS WRITTEN FOR HIM. 51
of this only a part, less than the half, can have been de-
voted to the purpose of systematic instruction. For in
the fourth year of this period 2 , we find Philip during an
expedition to Byzantium leaving his son sole and abso-
lute regent of the kingdom. Some barbarian subjects
having revolted, Alexander undertook an expedition in
person against them, and took their city, which he called
after his own name, Alexandropolis. From this time
he was continually engaged in business, now leading
the decisive charge at Chseronea, and now involved in
court intrigues against a party who endeavoured to gain
Philip's confidence and induce him to alter the succes-
sion 3 . It is clear therefore that all instruction, in the
stricter sense of the word, must have terminated. Yet
that a very considerable influence may have been still
exerted by Aristotle upon the mind of Alexander, is not
only in itself probable, but is confirmed by the titles of
some of his writings which are now lost. Ammonius,
in his division of the works of the philosopher, mentions
a certain class 4 as consisting of treatises written for the
behoof of particular individuals, and specifies among
them those books " which he composed at the request
of Alexander of Macedon, that On Monarchy, and In-
structions on the Mode of establishing Colonies." The
2 Plutarch, Fit. sec. 9- Diodorus, xvi. 77. See Clinton, Fast.
Hell a. 340, 339-
3 Plutarch, Vit. sec. 9, 10.
4 TO. MojOiKct. Ammon. Hermeneut. ad Aristot. Categor. p. 7- ed.
Aid. The two works alluded to are cited by the anonymous au-
thor of the Life printed by Buhle in his edition of Aristotle, p. 60
67, under the titles irep\ jSaa-tXeias and 'AAe'ai/fyjo, 17 wVep diroiKioiv.
Diogenes mentions the latter by the same name, and Pseudo-
Ammonius the former. The anonymous writer adds a third QTepi]
'A\eai/Bpou, 17 TTp\ ptJTopos 17 TroXiTiKou, by which he probably means
the ptfTopiKri 7rpo\ 'AXefrti/Spo*', which we have.
42
52 HIS POLICY AS A CONQUEROR.
titles of these works may lead us to conjecture that
the distinguishing characteristics of Alexander's sub-
sequent policy, the attempt to fuse into one mass his
old subjects and the people he had conquered, the as-
similation of their manners, especially by education and
intermarriages, the connection of remote regions by
building cities, making roads, and establishing com-
mercial enterprises, may be in no small measure due to
the counsels of his preceptor. A modern writer indeed
has imagined an analogy between this assimilative
policy of the conqueror, and the generalizing genius
of the philosopher 1 . And there really does seem some
ground for this belief, in spite of an observation of
Plutarch's 2 , which is at first sight diametrically oppo-
sed to it. After speaking of the Stoical notions of an
universal republic, he says, that magnificent as the
scheme was, it was never realized, but remained a mere
speculation of that school of philosophy; and he adds
that Alexander, who nearly realized it, did so in op-
position to the advice of Aristotle, who had recom-
mended him to treat the Greeks as a general,
vtKwsy) but the barbarians as a master, (^
the one as friends, the other as instruments. But
there is no other authority than Plutarch for this
story; and it seems far from improbable that it is en-
tirely built upon certain expressions used by Aristotle
in the first book of his Politics. In that place he
recognises the relation between master and slave as a
natural one; and he also maintains the superiority
of Greeks over barbarians to be so decided and per-
manent as to justify the supremacy of the one over
the other. Of the latter he argues that they have not
1 Joh. von Mueller, Allgemeine Geschickte, i. p. 160.
2 De Virt. et Fort. Alexandri. p. 329-
ARISTOTLE'S DOCTRINE OF SLAVERY. 53
the faculty of governing in them, and that therefore
the state of slavery is for them the natural and pro-
per form of the social relation 3 . But it should not
be overlooked, as by some modern writers it has been 4 ,
that Aristotle explicitly distinguishes between a slave
de facto and a slave de jure, and that he grounds his
vindication of slavery entirely on the principle that such
a relation shall be the most beneficial one possible to
both the parties concerned in it. Where this condition
is wanting, wherever the party governed is susceptible
of a higher order of government, he distinctly main-
tains that the relation is a false and unnatural one 5 -
If therefore his experience had made him acquainted
with the highly cultivated and generous races of upper
Asia to which Alexander penetrated, he must in
consistency with his own principle, that every man's
nature is to be developed to the highest point of which
it is capable, have advised that these should be treat-
ed on the same footing as the Greeks, and Alexander's
conduct would only appear a natural deduction from
the general principles inculcated by his master. As
far as concerned the barbarians with whom alone the
Greeks previously to Alexander's expedition had been
brought into contact, the neighbours of the Greek
3 P. 1252, col. 1, lin. 34, et seq.
* Paley, Moral and Political Philosophy, ch. v. p. 12. " Aristo-
tle lays down, as a fundamental and self-evident maxim, that nature
intended barbarians to be slaves; and proceeds to deduce from
this maxim a train of conclusions, calculated to justify the policy
which then prevailed. And I question whether the same maxim
be not still self-evident to the company of merchants trading to
the coast of Africa."
* See p. 1255, col. 1, line 5 ct scq. and col. 2, line 4. et seq, also
p. 1259, col. 2, line 21, ft seq.
54 STAGIRUS REBUILT.
cities in Asia Minor and the Propontis, the savage
hordes of Thrace, or the Nomad tribes inhabiting the
African Syrtis, Aristotle's position was a most reason-
able one. Christianity seems the only possible means
for the mutual pacification of races so different from
one another in every thought, feeling, and habit, as
these and the polished Greeks were : and Christianity
itself solves the problem not by those modifications of
social life through which alone the statesman acts, or
can act ; but by awakening all to the consciousness
that there exists a common bond higher than all so-
cial relations ; it does not aim at obliterating national
distinctions 1 9 but it dwarfs their importance in compa-
rison with the universal religious faith. If we would
really understand the opinions of a writer of antiquity,
we ought to understand the ground on which he rests,
and must rest. We have no right to require of a
pagan philosopher three centuries before Christ, that
in his system he should take account of the influ-
ences of Christianity; and they who scoff at the im-
portance which he attaches to the differences of race,
would do well to point out any instance in the his-
tory of the world where a barbarous people has be-
come amalgamated with a highly civilised one by any
other agency.
If Aristotle might reasonably feel proud of the
talents and acquirements of his pupil, his gratification
would be yet more enhanced by the nature of the
reward which his services received. We have men-
1 This was the essence of the Stoic theory, of which Plutarch
gives the substance, loc. cit. Ivn [iq Kara 9t<\eic, utj$e wrd
Bmt? 6Kao"rot duapur/nevoi BtKaio/c, aX\a iravra^ a
^tj/jLOTas KO.\ ?roArra, eis 6e pios y Ka\
called the river,
on whose banks Pella stood, by the name Bo'jo/3opo?.
2 Suidas, v. Ma^o-Ja?. That Callisthenes and Theophrastus
were together pupils of Aristotle appears from Diogenes, Vit.
Theoph. sec. 3$. And the Macedonian connections of both would
incline us to believe that it was in that country that this rela-
tion existed. Theophrastus was personally known to Philip and
treated with distinction by him. (/Elian, War. Hist. iv. 19.) And
if Callisthenes had been Aristotle's pupil at Athens, his character
would surely have been sufficiently developed eleven years after-
wards to exhibit his unfitness as an adviser of Alexander to
any eye, certainly to the sharp- sighted one of Aristotle. Besides,
it is not likely that Alexander would have chosen one whom he was
not already acquainted with, to attend him* in such a capacity as
Callisthenes did.
THEOPHRASTUS CALLISTHENES MARSYAS. 57
death of Alexander, when the generals of the monarch
divided their master's conquests among them, became
King of Lycia and Pamphylia. He was a soldier
and a man of letters ; and one work of his On the
Education of Alexander is perhaps as great a loss
to us as any composition of antiquity which could be
named.
UNIVERSITY
CHAPTER IV.
ARISTOTLE RETURNS TO ATHENS.
ON Alexander commencing his eastern expedition,
Aristotle, leaving his relation and pupil Callisthenes to
supply his own place as a friendly adviser to the youthful
monarch, whom he accompanied in the ostensible cha-
racter of historiographer 1 , returned to Athens. ^Whe-
ther this step was the consequence of any specific in-
vitation or not, it is difficult to say. Some accounts
state that he received a public request from the Athe-
nians to come, and conjointly with Xenocrates to suc-
ceed Speusippus 2 . But these views appear to proceed
upon the essentially false opinion that the position of
teacher was already a publicly recognised one, and be-
sides to imply the belief that Xenocrates and Aristotle
were at the time on their travels together; whereas we
know that the latter was in Macedonia till B.C. 335,
and that the former had four years before this time
succeeded Speusippus, not by virtue of any public ap-
pointment, but in consequence of his private wish 3 .
If any more precise reason be required for the philo-
sopher's change of residence than the one which pro-
bably determined him at first to visit Athens, namely
the superior attractions which that city possessed for
cultivated and refined minds, uve should incline to
believe that the greater mildness of climate was the
1 Arrhian, iv. 10.
2 Pseudo-Ammon. Vit. Lat.
3 Diog. Laert. iv. 3.
TEACHES TN THE LYCEUM. 59
influencing cause 1 . His health was unquestionably
delicate ; and perhaps it was a regard for this, com-
bined with the wish to economize time, that induced
him to deliver his instructions (or at least a part of
them) not sitting or standing, but walking backwards
and forwards in the open air. u-The extent to which
he carried this practice, although the example of Pro-
tagoras 5 in Plato's Dialogue is enough to show that
he did not originate it, procured for his scholars, who
of course were obliged to conform to this habit, the
soubriquet of Peripatetics, or Walkers backwards and
forwards 6 .]^ From the neighbouring temple and grove of
Apollo Lyceus, his school was commonly known by the
name of the Lyceum 7 ; and here every morning and even-
ing he delivered lectures to a numerous body of scholars.
Among these he appears to have made a division. The
morning course, or, as he called it from the place where
it was delivered, the morning walk, (ewdti/o? Tre^/Traros),
was attended only by the more highly disciplined part
of his auditory, the subjects of it belonging to the higher
branches of philosophy, and requiring a systematic at-
tention as well as a previously cultivated understanding
4 This seems to be the true interpretation of the expression of
Aristotle cited by Demetrius. De Elocut. sec. 29, 155: ejta CK ^eV
a rj\0ov /a TOV j3a, and Polit. vii. p. 1334, col.
1, line 1834.
62 STATE OF SOCIAL INTERCOURSE.
the youth of ancient Greece almost universally fell either
into a ruffianly asceticism, or a low and vulgar profli-
gacy. Some affected the austere manner and sordid
garb of the Lacadaemonians L , regarding as effeminate
all geniality of disposition, all taste for the refinements
of life, every thing in short which did not directly tend
to the production of mere energy : while others entirely
quenched the moral will and the higher mental facul-
ties in a debauchery of the coarsest kind 2 . To open
a new region of enjoyment to the choicer spirits of the
time and thus save them from the distortion or corrup-
tion to which they otherwise seemed doomed, was a
highly important service to the cause of civilization.
The pleasure and utility resulting from the institution
was very generally recognised. Xenocrates, the friend
of Aristotle, adopted it. Theophrastus, his successor,
left a sum of money in his will to be applied to defray-
ing the expenses of these meetings ; and there were
in after times similar periodical gatherings of the fol-
lowers of the Stoic philosophers, Diogenes* Antipater,
and Panaetius 3 . If some of these, or others of similar
nature, in the course of time degenerated into mere
excuses for sensual indulgence, as Athenseus seems to
hint, no argument can be thence derived against their
1 That the AaKowoucma so admirably hit off by Aristophanes (Av.
1729; e * se( l') tasted long after his time, is clear, not to mention other
arguments, from the evident prevalence of the views which Aristotle
(Politic, vii. p. 1324, col. 1, line 23, et seq., also p. 1332, col. 2,
line 20, p. 1334, col. 2, line 28) takes so much pains to controvert.
TTfcK yap ov
"ffivfi-v oi$> Koi fiiveiv /JLOVOV j Aristoph. Ran. 751.
The manners of the latter comedy, as preserved in Terence's
plays, are a sufficient evidence that this sarcasm was little less
applicable at Athens throughout the fourth century before the
Christian era.
3 Athenseus, p. 186.
DISCIPLINE OF THE SCHOLARS. 63
great utility while the spirit of the institution was pre-
served.
^Another arrangement made by Aristotle in the ma-
nagement of his instructions appears particularly wor-
thy of notice. In imitation, as some say, of a practice
of Xenocrates, he appointed one of his scholars to play
the part of a sort of president in his school, holding
the office for the space of ten days, after which another
took his place V^This peculiarity seems to derive illus-
tration from the practice of the universities of Europe
in the middle ages, in which, as is well known, it
was the custom for individuals on various occasions to
maintain certain theses against all who chose to con-
trovert them. A remnant of this practice remains to
this day in the Acts (as they are termed) which are
kept in the University of Cambridge by candidates
for a degree in either of the Faculties. It is an
* a\\ct KCU i/
%Ka rjpepcK; ap-^ovra -rroieiv. Diog. Laert. Fit. sec. 4. The follow-
ing passages from Cicero seem to furnish a kind of commentary
on these obscure expressions. Itaque mihi semper Peripateticorum
Academiasque consuetude de omnibus rebus in contrarias paries dis-
serendi non ob earn causam solum placuit, quod aliter non posset, quid
in qudque re veri smile esset, inveniri ; sed etiam quod esset ea
maxima dicendi exercitatio: qua princeps usus est Aristoteles, deinde,
eum qui secuti sunt. Tusc. Qu. ii. 3.
Sin aliquis extiterit aliquando, qui Aristotelio more de omnibus
rebus in utramque partem posset dicere, et in omni causa duas con-
trarias orationes, prceceptis illius cognitis, explicare ; aut hoc Arcesilce
modo ei Carneadi, contra omne quod propositum sit disserat;
quique ad earn rationem adjungat hunc rhetoricum usum mo-
remque dicendi, is sit verus, is perfectus, is solus orator. De
Oral. iii. 21.
The passage from Quintilian, (i. 2. 23.) quoted by Menage in
his note on Diogenes, (loc. cit.) refers to an essentially different
kind of discipline, arising out of other grounds and directed to
other, ends.
64 ANALOGOUS MODERN PRACTICES.
M~ ** & for$e */ '**-*- &J++0U+&, Ytfon.<
arrangement which results necessarily from the scarcity
of books of instruction, and is dropped or degenerates
into a mere form when this deficiency is removed.
While information on any given subject must be
derived entirely or mainly from the mouth of the
teacher, as was the case in the time of Aristotle no
less than that of Scotus and Aquinas, the most satis-
factory test of the learner's proficiency is his ability to
maintain the theory which he 'has received against all
arguments which may be brought against it. We
shall probably be right in supposing that this was the
duty of the president (ap-^wv) spoken of by Diogenes.
He was, in the language of the sixteenth century,
keeping an act. ^Re had for the space of ten days to
defend his own theory and to refute the objections,
(a.7ropiai) which his brother disciples might either en-
tertain or invent,Vthe master in the mean time taking
the place of a moderator, occasionally interposing to
show where issue must be joined, to prevent either party
from drawing illogical conclusions from acknowledged
premises, and, probably, after the discussion had been
continued for a sufficient time, to point out the ground
of the fallacy. This explanation will also serve to
account for a phenomenon, which cannot fail to strike
a reader on the perusal of any one of Aristotle's wri-
tings that have come down to us. The systematic
treatment of a subject is continually broken by an ap-
parently needless discussion of objections which may
be brought against some particular part. These are
stated more or less fully, and are likewise taken off;
or it sometimes happens that merely the principle on
which the solution must proceed is indicated, and it
is left to the ingenuity of the reader to fill up the
details. To return to our subject, it is quite obvious
EFFECT OF THE DISCIPLINE. 65
that such a discipline as we have described must have
had a wonderful effect in sharpening the dialectical
talent of the student, and in producing perhaps at
the expense of the more valuable faculty of deep
and systematic thought extraordinary astuteness and
agility in argumentation. Indeed, if we make ab-
straction of the subject-matter of the discussions, we
may very well regard the exercise as simply a practi-
cal instruction in the art of disputation, that which
formed the staple of the education of the Sophists.
And now we may understand how Gellius 1 , writing in
the second century after Christ, should place this art
among the branches which Aristotle's evening course
embraced, although in the sense in which the Sophists
taught it, he would have scorned to make any such
profession 2 . In what other light could this compiler
have viewed the fact, that insulated topics arising out
of a subject which they had heard fiystematicaUy
treated by their master in his lectures (d/f/ooaVets) of
the morning, were debated by Aristotle's more advanced
scholars, in the presence of the entire body, in the
evening, the master being himself present and regulat-
ing the whole discussion.
It is evident that in this species of exercise it is
not the faculty of comprehending philosophic truth
that plays the most prominent part. As regards the
subject-matter of such debates, nothing which is at all
incomplete, nothing unsusceptible of rigid definition
is available. Consequently the whole of that extensive
1 Noct. Alt. xx. 5. See above, p. 60.
2 See, for instance, the contempt with which he speaks of the
Sophistical principle, the one on which Isocrates taught rhetoric.
Rhetoric, i. inil.
5
66 ITS EFFECT ON PHILOSOPHY.
region, where knowledge exists in a state of growth
and gradual consolidation, the domain of half-evolved
truths, of observations and theories blended together
in varying proportions, of approximately ascertained
laws, in the main true, but still apparently irreconcil-
able with some phenomena, all this fertile soil, out
of which every particle of real knowledge has sprung
and must spring, will be neglected as barren and unpro-
fitable. Where public discussion is the only test to be
applied, an impregnable paradox will be more valued than
an imperfectly established truth 1 . And it is not only by
diverting the attention of the student away from the pro-
fitable fields of knowledge that a pernicious effect will be
produced. He will further be tempted to give, perhaps
unconsciously, an artificial roundness to established facts
by means of arbitrary definitions. In Nature every thing
is shaded off by imperceptible gradations into something
entirely different. Who can define the exact line which
separates the animal from the vegetable kingdom, or the
family of birds from that of animals ? Who can say ex-
actly where disinterestedness in the individual character
joins on to a well-regulated self-love ? or where fanati-
cism ends and hypocrisy begins? But on the other hand
the intellect refuses to apprehend what is not clear and
distinct. Hence a continual tendency to stretch Na-
ture on the Procrustes-bed of Logical Definition, where,
with more or less gentle truncation or extension, a
plausible theory will be formed. Should one weak point
after another be discovered in this, a new bulwark of
1 Sapientis hanc censet Arcesilas vim esse maximam, Zenoni
assentiens, cavere ne capiatur ; ne fallatur, videre. Cicero, Aca-
dem. Prior, ii. 21. Who can fail to recognise the disputatious habit
of mind which gave birth to this principle? Compare sec. 21.
Si ulli rei sapiens assentietur unquam, aliquando etiam opinabitur :
nunquam autem opinabitur ; nulli igitur rei assentietur.
ITS EFFECT ON PHILOSOPHERS. 67
hypothesis will be thrown up to protect it, and at last
the fort be made impregnable, but alas ! in the mean
time it has become a castle in the air. Should however
the genius of the disputant lie less in the power of
distinguishing and refining, than in that of presenting
his views in a broad and striking manner, should his
fancy be rich and his feelings strong, above all, should
he be one of a nation where eloquence is at once the
most common gift and the most envied attainment,
he will call in rhetoric to the aid of his cause; and,
in this event, as the accessory gradually encroaches and
elbows out that interest to aid which it was originally
introduced, as the handling of the question becomes
more important, and the question itself less so, there
will result, not, as in the former case, a Scholastic
Philosophy, but an arena for closet orators, who will 2
abandon the systematic study of philosophy, and var-
nish up declamations on set subjects. Such results
doubtless did not follow in the time of Aristotle and
Xenocrates. Under them, unquestionably, the original
purpose of this discipline was kept steadily in sight ;
and it was not suffered to pass from being the test
of clear and systematic thought to a mere substitute
for it. But the transition must have been to a con-
siderable extent effected when an Arcesilaus or a Car-
neades could deliver formal dissertations in opposition
to any question indifferently, and when Cicero could
regard the rhetorical practice as co-ordinate in import-
ance with the other advantages resulting to the stu-
dent 3 , In the very excellence and reputation then of
(j)i\oa'o(p6Tv TTjoay/jiaTJKto?, a'AAa dfcrets \r}Kvdifeiv, Strabo,
xiii. p. 124. ed Tauchnitz.
3 See the passages cited above p. 63. not. Compare also Acad.
Prior, ii. 18. Quis enim ista tarn aperte perspicueque et perversa et
68 RESOURCES OF ARISTOTLE.
this peculiar discipline of the founder of the Peripa-
tetic school, we have a germ adequate to produce a
rapid decay of his philosophy, and we have no occa-
sion to look either to external accidents or to the
internal nature of his doctrines for a reason of the
degeneracy of the Peripatetics after Theophrastus. The
importance of this remark will be seen in the sequel.
y It was probably in the course of this sojourn at
Athens, which lasted for the space of thirteen years,
that the greater number of Aristotle's works were pro-
duced. His external circumstances were at this time
most favourable. The Macedonian party was the pre-
valent one at Athens, so that he needed be under no
fears for his personal quiet; and the countenance and
assistance he received from Alexander enabled him to
prosecute his investigations without any interruption
from the scantiness of pecuniary means. The Con-
queror is said in Athenseus to have presented his
master with the sum of eight hundred talents (about
two hundred thousand pounds sterling), to meet the
expenses of his History of Anima&}aud enormous as
this sum is, it is only in proportion to the accounts
we have of the vast wealth acquired by the plunder
of the Persian treasures 2 . Pliny also relates that some
thousands of men were placed at his disposal for the
purpose of procuring zoological specimens which served
as materials for this celebrated treatise. The under-
falsa secutus esset, nisi tanta in Arcesila, multo etiam major in
Carneade, et copia rerum, et dicendi vis fuisset. Yet the eloquent
Arcesilaus and Carneades left nothing behind them in writing. (Plu-
tarch, Defort. Alex. p. 323. ed. Paris.)
1 Athenaeus, p. 3p8. E.
2 See the authorities on this subject collected by Ste. Croix. Eza-
men Hisiorique, pp. 428 430.
HIS NATURAL HISTORY. 69
taking, he says, originated in the express desire of
Alexander, who took a singular interest in the study
of Natural History 3 . For this particular object indeed, i
he is said to have received a considerable sum from i
Philip, so that we must probably regard the assistance
afforded him by Alexander, (no doubt after conquest
had enlarged his means), as having effected the ex-
tension and completion of a work begun at an earlier
period, previous to his second visit to Athens 4 . Inde-
pendently too of this princely liberality, the profits of
his occupation may have been very great 5 , and we
have before seen reason to suppose that his private for-
tune was not inconsiderable. *^It is likely therefore
that not only all the means and appliances of know-
ledge, but the luxuries and refinements of private life
were within his reach, and having as little of the cynic
as of the sensualist in his character, there is every pro-
bability that he availed himself of them.t-'Indeed the
charges of luxury which his enemies brought against
him after his death, absurd as they are in the form
in which they were put, appear to indicate a man that
could enjoy riches when possessing them as well as in
case of necessity he could endure poverty.
3 Hist. Nat. viii. 17-
4 &lia.n, Var. Hist. iv. 12.
5 See the beginning of the Hippias Major of Plato for the profits
of the sophists, which there is no reason to suppose were greater
than those of their more respectable successors. Hippias professes
to have made during a short circuit in Sicily more than six
hundred pounds, although the celebrated Protagoras was there as
a competitor. (5.) Hyperbolus's instructions in oratory cost him
a talent, or two hundred and fifty pounds. (Aristoph. Nub. 874.)
But there is nothing to enable us to determine whether Aristotle's
teaching was or was not gratuitous.
CHAPTER V.
TURBULENT POLITICS AT ATHENS.
FORTUNE, proverbially inconstant, was even more
fickle in the days of Aristotle than our own. At an
earlier period of his life, we have seen the virulence
of political partizanship rendering it desirable for him
to quit Athens. The same spirit it was which again,
in his old age, forced him to seek refuge in a less
agreeable but safer spot. The death of Alexander had
infused new courage into the anti-Macedonian party at
Athens, and a persecution of such as entertained con-
trary views naturally followed. Against Aristotle, the
intimate friend and correspondent of Antipater, (whom
Alexander on leaving Greece had left regent,) a pro-
secution was either instituted or threatened for an
alleged offence against religion 1 . The flimsiness of
this pretext for crushing a political opponent, or ra-
ther a wise and inoffensive man, whose very imparti-
ality was a tacit censure of the violent party-spirit of
his time, will appear at first sight of the particulars,
of the charge. Eurymedon the Hierophant, assisted by
Demophilus, accused him of the blasphemy of paying
divine honours to mortals. He had composed, it was
said, a paean and offered sacrifices to his father in law
Hermias, and also honoured the memory of his deceased
wife Pythias with libations such as were used in the
worship of Ceres. This p&an is the scolium 'Aperd
1 Phavorinus ap. Diog. Laert. Fit. 5. -flSlian, Far. Hist. iii. 36.
Athenaeus, p. 696. Origen c. Celsum, i. p. 51. ed. Spencer. Demo-
chares cited by Aristocles, (ap. Euseb. Prcep. Ev. xv. 2.)
ARISTOTLE GOES TO EUBO3A. 71
e, &c., which we have described above (p. 42.)
and although we cannot tell what the circumstance
was which gave rise to the latter half of the charge,
we may reasonably presume that it as little justified the
interpretation given to it as the ode does. That igno-
rance and bigotry stimulated by party hatred should find
matter in his writings to confirm a charge of impiety
founded on such a basis, was to be expected; and he
is related to have said to his friends, in allusion to
the fate of Socrates, "Let us leave Athens, and not
give the Athenians a second opportunity of committing
sacrilege against Philosophy." He was too well ac-
quainted with the character of "the many-headed
monster" to consider the absurdity of a charge as a
sufficient guarantee for security under such circumstan-
ces, and he retired with his property to Chalcis in
Euboea 2 , where at that time Macedonian influence pre-
vailed. In a letter to Antipater he expresses his regret
at leaving his old haunts, but applies a verse from
Homer in a way to intimate that the disposition that
prevailed there to vexatious and malignant calumnies
was incorrigible 3 . It is not impossible that his new
asylum had before this time afforded him an occasional
retreat from the noise and bustle of Athens 4 . Now
however he owed to it a greater obligation. He was
out of the reach of his enemies, and enabled to justify
himself in the opinion of all whose judgement was
2 Apollodorus, ap. Diog. Vit. 10. Lycon the Pythagorean cited
by Aristocles ap. Euseb. Prcep. Ev. xv. 2, grounds a charge of lux-
ury on the number of culinary utensils which were passed at the
custom-house in Chalcis.
3 Pseudo-Ammon. ^lian, V. H. iii. 36. (compare xii. 52.) Pha-
vorinus (ap. Diog. Fit. 9.)
4 Diog. Vii. Epicuri, 1. Strabo, x. p. 325.
72 IS PERSECUTED.
valuable by a written defence of his conduct 1 , and an
exposure of the absurdities which the accusation in-
volved. " Was it likely," he asks, " that if he had
contemplated Hermias in the light of a deity, he should
have set up a cenotaph to his memory as to that of a
dead man? Were funeral rites a natural step to apo-
theosis?" Arguments like these, reasonable as they are,
were not likely to produce much effect upon the minds
of his enemies. The person of their victim was beyond
their reach ; but such means of annoyance as still re-
mained were not neglected. Some mark of honour at
Delphi, probably a statue, had been on a former occa-
sion (perhaps the embassy alluded to above) decreed
him by a vote of the people. This vote seems to have
been at this time rescinded, an insult the more mor-
tifying, if, as appears likely, it was inflicted on the
pretext that he had acted the part of a spy in the
Macedonian interest 2 . In a letter to Antipater he
speaks of this proceeding in a tone of real greatness,
perfectly free from the least affectation of indifference.
He alleges 3 that it does not occasion him great uneasi-
1 Athenaeus, (p. 697.) quotes a passage from this work, to which
he gives the title of aVoAoyi'a aVe/Je/a?, but at the same time men-
tions a suspicion that it was not genuine. It might very well be
written by one of his scholars in his name, and embody his senti-
ments, just as the Apology of Plato does those of Socrates. This
is the more likely, as Aristotle at this time appears to have been
in a very weak state of health. It seems to be identical with the
\oyos ZLKUVIKOS mentioned by Phavorinus, (ap. Diog. Fit. 9.) and to
be so called because written in that form, although probably never
intended to be recited in court.
8 Demochares cited by Aristocles, (Euseb. Prcep. Ev. xv. 2.)
3 .ZElian, Var. Hist. xix. 1. OU'TW? e'}a>, cos nt'/re /not /ieV Si/i/aroc ai fieyaSj vovv ' OVK f*X ev '
mippus ap. Plutarch. Fit. Alex. 54.
74 CONDUCT OF CALLISTHENES.
his character, and to have advised him to abstain from
frequent interviews with the king, and when he did
converse with him, to be careful that his conversation
was agreeable and goodhumoured 1 . He probably judged
that the character and conduct of Callisthenes would of
itself work an effect with a generous disposition like
Alexander's, and that its influence could not be in-
creased, and would in all probability be much dimin-
ished, by the irritation of personal discussion, producing,
almost of necessity, altercation and invective. Callis-
thenes however did not abide by the instructions of
his master; and perhaps the ambition of martyrdom
contributed almost as much as the love of truth to his
neglect of them. The description of Kent, which Shaks-
peare puts into the mouth of Cornwall 2 would certainly
not do him justice ; but it is impossible to shut our
eyes to the fact that he made it " his occupation to be
plain." Disgusted at the ceremony of the salaam, and
the other oriental customs, which in the eyes of many
were a degradation to the dignity of freeborn Greeks, he
did not take the proper course, namely, to withdraw
himself from the royal banquets, and thus by his ab-
sence enter a practical protest against their adoption; but,
1 Valerius Maximus, vii. 2.
-This is some fellow,
Who, having been praised for bluntness, doth affect
A saucy roughness, and constrains the garb
Quite from his nature : He cannot flatter, he !
An honest mind and plain ! he must speak truth :
An they will take it, so: if not, he's plain.
These kind of knaves I know, which in this plainness
Harbour more craft and more corrupter ends,
Than twenty silly ducking observants
That stretch their duties nicely !
King Lear, Act ii sc. 2.
HIS HATRED OF ANAXAKCHUS. 75
while he still did not cease to attend these, he took every
opportunity of testifying his disapprobation of what he
saw, and his contempt of the favours which were he-
stowed on such as were less scrupulous than himself.
One of them who appears to have particularly excited
his dislike was the sophist Anaxarchus, an unprincipled
flatterer, who vindicated the worst actions and encou-
raged the most evil tendencies of his master 3 ; and per-
haps the jealousy of this miscreant and an unwillingness
to leave him the undivided empire over Alexander's
mind, was one reason which prevented him from adopt-
ing what would have been probably the most effectual
as well as the most dignified line of conduct. Some
anecdotes are related by Plutarch, which exhibit in a
very striking manner both the mutual hatred of the
philosophers breaking out in defiance of all the de-
cencies of a court, and the rude bluntness of Callisthe-
nes's manners. On one occasion, a discussion arose at
supper time, as to the comparative severity of the win-
3 When Alexander, after having slain his friend Clitus in a fit of
drunken passion, threw himself upon the earth, overwhelmed with
remorse, deaf to the solicitations of his friends, and obstinately
refusing to touch food, Callisthenes and Anaxarchus, the philoso-
phers of that day standing in the place of the priests of this, were
sent to offer him spiritual consolations. The latter, wise in his
generation, determined to sear the conscience which he could not
heal, and entered the tent with an expression of indignation and
surprize. "What," he cried, " is this Alexander on whom the eyes of
the whole world are bent ? is this he lying weeping like a slave, in fear
of the reproaches and the conventional laws of men, when he ought
to be himself the law and the standard of right and wrong to them ?
Why did he conquer the world but to rule and command it ; surely
not to be in bondage to it and its foolish opinions ? " " Dost thou
not know/' he continued, addressing the unhappy prince, "that
Justice and Law (A/K^i/ not Qcpiv) are represented the Assessors of
Jupiter, as a sign to all that whatever the mighty do is lawful and
just ? " Plutarch, Vit. Alex. 52.
76 HIS DISLIKE OF PERSIAN HABITS.
ters in Macedonia and in the part of the country where
they then were. Anaxarchus, is opposition to his rival,
strongly maintained the former to be the colder. Cal-
listhenes could not resist the temptation of a sneer
at his enemy. " You at least," said he, " should
hardly be of that opinion. In Greece you used to
get through the cold weather in a scrubby jacket,
(ev Tpifiwvi) ; here, I observe that you cannot sit down
to table with less than three thick mantels (SdiriSai)
on your back V* Anaxarchus, whose vulgar ostentation
of the wealth which his low servilities had procured him
was observed and ridiculed by all, could not turn off
this sarcasm ; but the meanest animal has its sting,
and he took care not to miss any opportunity for lower-
ing the credit of Callisthenes with Alexander, a task
which the unfortunate wrong-headedness 2 of the other
rendered only too easy. On the occasion of another
royal banquet, each of the guests as the cup passed
round, drank to the monarch from it, and then after
performing the salaam, received a salute from him,
a ceremony which was considered as an especial mark
of royal favour. Callisthenes, when his turn arrived,
omitted the salaam, but advanced towards Alexander,
who being busy in conversation with Hephsestion, did
not observe that the expected act of homage had been
omitted. A courtier of Anaxarchus's party, however,
Demetrius, the son of Pythonax, determined that their
enemy should not benefit by this casualty, and accord-
1 Plutarch, Vit. Alex. 52.
2 c-Kaiorrjs and vVepoK-yo? a(3e\T6pia are terms in which Arrhian,
who perfectly appreciates the manly spirit of Callisthenes and is
no idolater of Alexander, characterizes his manners. (De cxped.
Alex. iv. c. 12.)
0,
POPULAR WITH THE MACEDONIA!*^ 77
ingly called out, " Do not salute that fellow, sire ; for
he alone has refused to salaam you." The king on
hearing this refused Callisthenes the customary com-
pliment; but the latter far from heing mortified, ex-
claimed contemptuously as he returned to his seat,
" Very well, then I am a kiss the poorer 3 ! " Such
gratuitous discourtesy as this could hardly fail to alien-
ate the kindness of a young prince, whose mere taste
for refinement, leaving entirely out of consideration
the intoxication produced by unparalleled success and
the flatteries which follow it, must have been revolted
by it 4 . It however gained him great credit with the
Macedonian party, who were no less jealous of the
favour which the Persian nobles found with the Con-
queror than disgusted with the adoption of the Persian
customs. He was considered as the mouthpiece of the
body, and as the representative and vindicator of that
manly and plain speaking spirit of liberty which they
regarded as their birthright 5 , and the satisfaction
which his vanity received from this importance, com-
bined with a despair of reconquering the first place in
Alexander's favour from the hated and despised Anaxar-
chus, probably determined him to relinquish all attempts
at pleasing the monarch, and to adopt a line which
might annoy and injure himself but could hardly bene-
fit any one. When an account was brought to Aris-
totle in Greece of the course pursued by his relation,
3 Plutarch, Fit. 54. Arrhian, iv. 12.
4 "Do not the Greeks seem to you," said he, to two of his friends,
on the occasion of Clitus's outrageous behaviour, " compared with
the Macedonians, like demigods among brute beasts ? " (Plutarch,
ru. 51.)
5 Plutarch, Fit. 53. Arrhian, iv. 12.
78 HIS BAD TASTE AND TEMPER.
his sharp-sigh tedness led him at once to divine the re-
sult. In a line from the Iliad J ,
Ah me! such words, my son, bode speedy death!
he prophetically hinted the fate which awaited him. In-
deed the latter himself appears not to have been blind
to the ruin preparing for him ; but this conviction did
not produce any alteration in his conduct, or, if any-
thing, it perhaps induced him to give way to his tem-
per even more than before. At another banquet, the
not unusual request was made to him, that he would
exhibit his talents by delivering an extemporaneous ora-
tion, and the subject chosen- was a Panegyric upon the
Macedonians. He complied, and performed his task so
well as to excite universal admiration and enthusiastic
applause on the part of the guests. This circumstance
appears to have nettled Alexander, whose affection for
his old fellow-pupil had probably quite vanished, and
he remarked in disparagement of the feat, in a quo-
tation from Euripides, that on such a subject it was
no great matter to be eloquent. " If Callisthenes
wished really to give a proof of his abilities," said he,
" let him take up the other side of the question, and
try what he can do in an invective against the Mace-
donians, that they may learn their faults and reform
them." The orator did not decline the challenge :
his mettle was roused, and he surpassed his former
performance. The Macedonian nation was held up to
utter scorn, and especial contempt heaped upon the
warlike exploits and consummate diplomacy of Alex-
ander's father Philip. His successes were attributed
to accident or low intrigue availing itself of the dis-
ttj fjiot, TKo, ti/. Plutarch,
Fit. 54.
3 Arrhian, iv. c. 13.
80 HIS RHETORICAL COMMONPLACES.
threatened utterly to extinguish, and, in the inculca-
tion of these, to have made use of language and of
illustrations, which considering the circumstances of
the case were certainly dangerous, although in refer-
ence to the then prevailing tone of morality we shall
scarcely he justified in censuring them. Harmodius and
Aristogiton having with the sacrifice of their own lives
been fortunate enough to bring about the freedom of
their country, had been canonized as political saints,
and were held up to all the youth of the free states of
Greece for admiration and imitation; and Callisthenes
can hardly deserve especial blame for participating in
this general idolatry, or for representing the glory of a
tyrannicide as surpassing that of a tyrant, however bril-
liant the fortunes of the latter might be. Neither can
we at all wonder that he should delight in depreciating
the "pride, pomp and circumstance" of greatness in
comparison with dignity of character and manly energy,
and in exposing the impotence of externals to avert
any of "the ills to which flesh is heir." Such con-
siderations have been in all ages and ever will be the
staple both of Philosophy and of the sciolism which is
its counterfeit, and the necessity for dwelling upon
them might to Callisthenes appear the greater in order
to counterbalance the habits of feeling which Persian
manners and sophistry like that of Anaxarchus were
calculated to spread among the Macedonian youth. He
is said indeed to have continually professed that the
only motive which induced him to accompany Alex-
ander into Asia was that he might be the means of
restoring his countrymen to their father-land, as true
Greeks as they went out, uncorrupted by the manners
or the luxury of the Barbarians 1 , and he seems un-
* l Plutarch, Fit. 53.
CONSPIRACY OF THE PAGES. 81
questionably to have succeeded in putting a stop, at
least for a time, to the ceremony of the salaam, of all
Eastern customs the one most galling to Macedonian
pride 8 . In an evil day however to Callisthenes, it hap-
pened, that Hermolaus was out boar-hunting with Alex-
ander, when the animal charged directly towards the king.
The page, influenced probably more by the ardour of
the chase, and his own youthful spirits, than by any just
apprehension for his sovereign's safety, struck the crea-
ture a mortal wound before it came up to him. Alex-
ander, the keenest of huntsmen, baulked of his ex-
pected sport, in the passion of the moment, ordered
Hermolaus to be flogged in the presence of his brother-
pages, and deprived him of his horse, (apparently the
sign of summarily degrading him from his employment.)
Such an insult to a Greek could only be washed out in
the blood of the aggressor, and Hermolaus found ready
sympathy among his compeers. It was agreed by them
that Alexander should be assassinated while asleep, and
the execution of the design was fixed for a night on which
Antipater, the son of Asclepiodorus, (whom Alexander
had made lord-lieutenant of Syria,) was to be the groom
in waiting. It so happened, that on that night Alex-
ander did not retire to bed at all, but sat at table
carousing until the very morning, whether by acci-
dent, or in consequence of the advice of a Syrian fe-
male, to whom in the character of a soothsayer he paid
great respect, is not agreed by the contemporary histo-
rians. But this circumstance, whatever was the cause
of it, saved the king and led to the detection of the
plot. The next day, Epimenes, one of the conspira-
2 Plutarch, Vit. 54. Compare Arrhian, iv. 14, where Hermo-
laus is said to have complained of TYJV Trpo^Kvutja-iv TVJV
Bt'ia'Ctv KCti ovirta
6
82 CALL1STHENES INCULPATED.
tors, mentioned the matter to an individual who was
strongly attached to him. This person communicated it
to Eurylochus, the brother of Epimenes, perhaps consider-
ing that his relationship was a sufficient guarantee for
secrecy. Eurylochus, however, at once laid an informa-
tion before Ptolemy the son of Lagus, subsequently the
first of the Greek dynasty in Egypt, and then one of the
guard of honour in attendance on Alexander. He re-
ported to the king the names of those who he had
been told were concerned in the affair : they were ar-
rested, and on being put to the torture confessed their
crime and gave up the names of others who were par-
ticipators 1 . So far all accounts agree as to the sub-
stantial facts of this story, but here a great discrepancy
commences. Ptolemy and Aristobulus 2 both asserted that
the pages named Callisthenes as the instigator of their
design. This however was denied by the majority of
contemporary writers on the subject, who related that
the ill will towards Callisthenes previously existing in
the mind of Alexander, combined with the intimacy that
subsisted between Hermolaus and the former, furnished
1 Arrhian, iv. 13, 14.
8 Aristobulus was one of Alexander's generals, and wrote an
account of his campaigns. He did not however commence this
work till his 84th year, (Lucian, De Macrob. 22) long enough
therefore after the transaction in question, to allow us to sup-
pose that by a slip of the memory he may have confused circum-
stantial with direct evidence. Moreover as there was no act
which made Alexander so unpopular as the execution of Callis-
thenes, (Quintus Curtius, De rebus gestis Alex. viii. c. 8), so there
was nothing which his biographers took so much pains to exte-
nuate. See Ste Croix, p. 360, seqq. Arrhian (iv. 14,^.) at the same
time that he speaks of the opportunities of knowledge possessed
by Ptolemy and Aristobulus, and of their general fidelity, yet
remarks that their accounts of the details of this affair differ from
one another.
PRESUMPTIVE EVIDENCE. 83
ample means to his enemies to raise a strong suspicion
against him 3 . They alleged, that to a question from
Hermolaus, " how a man might make himself the most
illustrious of his species"? he replied, " Bij slaying him
that is most illustrious": and that to incite the youth
to the rash act, he hade him "not be in awe of the
couch of gold, but remember that such a one often
holds a sick or a wounded man"; also, that when
Philotas had asked him whom the Athenians honoured
most of all men, he replied, " Harmodius and Aristo-
giton, the tyrannicides" and when the querist expressed
a doubt whether such a person would at the existing
time, find countenance and protection any where in
Greece, he replied, "that if every other city shut its
gates against him, he would certainly find a refuge in
Athens" and in support of this opinion quoted the in-
stance of the Heraclidae who there found protection
against the tyrant Eurystheus 4 . It requires hut little
penetration to see how, under circumstances of such
peculiar irritation, the words of Callisthenes might with
very little violence and with the greatest plausibility,
be interpreted in a treasonable sense, although they
were nothing more than Macedonian principles expressed
in a strong and antithetical manner. Indeed, the very
admixture of legendary history in the instance of the
sons of Hercules seems to betray the common places of
the rhetorician. And that this account of the matter,
to which Arrhian, following the majority of contempo-
rary accounts, inclines, is the true one, seems proved
3 Arrhian, loc. cit.
4 Plutarch, Vit. 55. Arrhian, iv. 10. This Philotas is not the
son of Parmenio, put to death together with his father on a
former occasion, but a page, the son of Carsis, a Thracian. See
Arrhian, iv. 13.
62
84 ARISTOTLE INCULPATED.
beyond all doubt by two letters of Alexander himself,
which are cited by Plutarch. In the former of these,
written immediately after the event to his general,
Craterus, he states, " that the pages on being put to
the torture confessed their own treason, but denied
that any one else was privy to the attempt." He
wrote to Attains and Alcetas to the same effect. But
afterwards in a letter to Antipater, he says, " the
pages have been stoned to death by the Macedonians ;
but as for the sophist I intend to punish him, and
those too who sent him out, and also the cities which
harbour conspirators against me." In the latter part
of this phrase, according to Plutarch, he alludes to
Aristotle, as being the great-uncle of Callisthenes, and
the person by whose advice he had joined the court. It
seems plain that in the interval between the writing of
these letters, Alexander's mind had been worked upon
by those whose interest it was to identify the cause of
manliness and virtue with that of disloyalty and trea-
son, by Anaxarchus and the crew of court sycophants
whose practice he sanctioned by his example, and
attempted to justify by his philosophy. The tide of
hatred however was setting too strong against Cal-
listhenes for him to stem it. He was placed under
confinement, and according to accounts which there is
too much reason to fear are true, cruelly mutilated.
It is said to have been Alexander's intention to bring
him to a trial in the presence of Aristotle on his re-
turn to Greece ; but the unfortunate man after remain-
ing in his deplorable situation for a considerable time,
died from the effects of ill treatment.
Whatever prejudices against his old master may
have been raised in the mind of Alexander on the
score of Callisthenes, and whatever ill consequences
DEATH OF ALEXANDER. 85
might perhaps have followed if the conqueror had lived
to revisit Europe, intoxicated with his military suc-
cesses, and hardened by the influence of those flat-
terers who after Callisthenes's death reigned supreme
at court, it is explicitly stated by Plutarch, that while
he lived his estrangement never led him to injure Aris-
totle in the slightest degree. Mortification therefore at
the degeneracy of his pupil, and sorrow at the loss of
an affection in which he doubtless took both pride
and pleasure, were the only evils which the latter
during his remaining days had to endure. But a few
years after the death of both, a story began to be
circulated which at last grew into a form in the highest
degree detrimental to his character. It is impossible
to doubt that Alexander died from the fever of the
country, caught immediately after indulgence in the
most extravagant excesses. At the moment no suspicion
to the contrary was entertained l . But some time after-
wards, the ambitious and intriguing Olympias, who had
long indulged a bitter hostility towards Antipater, (a
hostility which the successful establishment of the latter
in the government of Macedonia after her son's death
had inflamed into a fiendish hatred,) seized the oppor-
tunity which Alexander's rapid illness afforded to throw
the suspicion of poisoning him upon her enemy, whose
younger son lolaus had been his cupbearer. It was not
till the sixth year after the fatal event that this story
was set on foot; and it seems to have originated in
nothing] but Olympias's desire of vengeance, which
then first found a favourable vent. The bones of lo-
laus, who had died in the interim, were torn from
their grave, and a hundred Macedonians, selected from
among the most distinguished of Antipater's friends,
1 Plutarch, Vit. 77-
OO SAID TO HAVE BEEN POISONED.
barbarously butchered 1 . The accusation of poisoning
the king seems at first to have been vaguely set on
foot, the only circumstantial part of the story being
the point necessary to justify Olympias's malignity,
namely, that lolaus was the agent in administering the
poison. But in process of time the minutest details of
the transaction were supplied. We give them in the
last form which they assumed. The fears of Antipater,
it was said, arising from the growing irritation of
Alexander incessantly stimulated against him by Olym-
pias, induced him, on hearing that he was superseded
by Craterus and ordered into Asia with new levies,
to plot against his master's life. A fit means for
this purpose was pointed out to him by his friend
Aristotle, who dreaded the personal consequences to
himself which seemed likely to follow from Alexan-
der's anger against Callisthenes 2 . The nature of this
is quite in keeping with the other features of the nar-
rative. It was no other than the water of the river
Styx, which fell from a rock near the town of Nona-
cris in Arcadia, and which, according to a local su-
perstition which is not extinct to this day 3 , possessed
not only the property of destroying animal life by its
1 Diodorus, xix. 11. Plutarch, loc. cit.
2 Although Callisthenes had been put to death five years before,
i. e. in B.C. 328 ! See Clinton, F. H. ii. p. 376.
3 See Col. Leake's Travels in the Morea, vol. iii. pp. 165 9.
The natives say that the water which they call TU Mavpa-vepta (the
black waters) and ra ApctKo-vepta (the terrible waters) is unwhole-
some, and also that no vessel will hold it. It is a slender perennial
stream falling over a very high precipice, and entering the rock
at the bottom, which is said to be inaccessible from the nature of
the ground. Col. Leake quotes the phrases of Homer KaTi{3dfj.cvov
STuyo? v^xap and STUYO? i/Baro? aiTrd peeOpa as exact descriptions of it.
See also Herod, vi. 74. Hesiod, Theog. 785805.
ARISTOTLE INCULPATED. 87
cold and petrifying qualities (\l/v^pov mi Trcryera^es) but
also that of dissolving the hardest metals, and even
precious stones. One substance alone was proof against
its destructive influences, the hoof of a Scythian ass !
In a vessel made out of this, a small portion of the
fluid was conveyed by Cassander, lolaus's elder brother,
into Asia, and, on the occasion of the debauch at which
Alexander was taken ill, administered to him by the
latter. lolaus was stimulated to the act by the desire
of revenging an outrage upon himself by the king,
and attachment to him induced Medius, a Thessalian,
at whose palace the debauch took place, to be an ac-
complice in the treason. The assassin, according to
the author of the Lives of the Ten Orators falsely
attributed to Plutarch 4 , was rewarded by a proposition
of the demagogue Hyperides at Athens, to confer pub-
lic honours upon him as a tyrannicide, and the horn
cup in which the fatal draught had been conveyed from
Greece deposited in the temple of Delphi 5 .
4 p. 849, ed. Paris. The same is stated by Photius, Biblioth.
p. 496. 1. 3, Bekk.
6 Epig. ap. ^Elian. De Nat. Animal, x. 40. That it should have
been deposited there,, as the epigram states, by Alexander himself, is
a circumstance scarcely necessary to increase the incredibility of the
story.
An almost equally great confusion of times and circumstances
appears in Mr Landor's Imaginary Conversations, Vol. ii. pp. 495
530. Callisthenes himself is represented as exciting Aristotle's fears
for his own personal safety by describing Alexander's jealousy of
every thing great; and the dialogue between them ends as fol-
lows :
" ARISTOTELES. Now Callisthenes ! if Socrates and Anytus were
in the same chamber, if the wicked had mixed poison for the vir-
tuous, the active in evil for the active in good, and some divinity
had placed it in your power to present the cup to either, and touch-
88 IMPROBABILITY OF THE STORY.
The absurdity of this account is glaringly manifest
to readers of the present day, of whom nine out of
every ten are probably better acquainted with the nature
and operation of petrifying springs than the best in-
formed of the Greek naturalists were. The ancients
were not in possession of the touchstone for the dis-
covery of falsehood which modern science affords ; but
even they were long before they attached any credence
to the calumny. " The greater part of the writers on
the subject," says Plutarch 1 , " consider the whole matter
of the reputed poisoning a mere fiction, and in confirma-
tion of this view they quote the fact, that although the
royal remains lay for several days unembalmed, in con-
sequence of the disputes of the generals, and that too
in a hot and close place, they exhibited no marks of
corruption, but remained fresh and unchanged." Arrhian 3
too, who as well as Plutarch derives his account of the
king's illness and death from the court gazettes (etyrjue-
piSes), and confirms the statements of these by the narra-
tives of Ptolemy and Aristobulus, says of the charge of
ing your head, should say, ( This head also is devoted to the Eume-
nides if the choice be wrong/ what would you resolve ?
CALLISTHENES. To do that by command of the god which I
would likewise have done without it.
ARISTOTELES. Bearing in mind that a myriad of kings and
conquerors is not worth the myriadth part of a wise and virtuous
man, return, Callisthenes, to Babylon, and see that your duty be
performed."
Alexander did not enter Babylon until the spring of 324. B. c.,
consequently till four years after the death of Callisthenes. The
conspiracy of the pages, in which Callisthenes was, whether justly
or unjustly, mixed up, was detected while Alexander was in Bactra.
But before this conspiracy there is no reason to suppose that Alex-
ander entertained any coolness towards Aristotle.
1 Fit. Alex. ult.
2 vii. 27-
ITS GROWTH. 89
poisoning, which he afterwards mentions, that he has
alluded to it merely to show that he has heard of it,
not that he considers it to deserve any credence. In
fact, the sole source of the story in its details appears
to have heen one Hagnothemis (an individual of whom
nothing else is known), who is reported to have said that
he had heard it told by King Antigonus 3 . But its
piquancy was a strong recommendation to later writers,
and it is instructive and amusing to observe how their
statements of it increase in positiveness about in pro-
portion as they recede from the time in which the facts
of the case could be known. Diodorus Siculus and
Vitruvius, living in the time of the two first Caesars,
merely mention the rumour that Alexander's death was
occasioned by poison, through the agency of Antipater,
but do not pretend to assert its credibility. Quintus
Curtius, writing under Vespasian, considers the autho-
rities on that side to preponderate. The epitomizer of
a degenerate age, Justin, flourishing in the reign of
Antoninus Pius, slightly alludes to the intemperance
which he allows had been assigned as the cause of
Alexander's death, but adds that in fact he died from
treason, and the disgraceful truth was suppressed by the
influence of his successors. And finally Orosius, in
the fifth century, states broadly and briefly that he
died from poison administered by an attendant, with-
out so much as hinting that any different belief had
ever even partially obtained 4 . But it is remarkable
3 Plutarch, Vit. Alex. loc. cit.
4 Diodorus xvii. 117, Vitruvius viii. 3, Q. Curtius x. 10, Justin
xii. 14, Orosius iii. 20. It is possible that some readers may quote
Tacitus (An?ial. ii. 73), as opposing the view we have given in the
text of the gradual progression of credulity. But the exception is
only apparent. Tacitus does not give his own view, but merely
90 REVIVED BY CARACALLA.
that of all these writers, not one mixes up Aristotle's
name with the story ; and it is probable that the foolish
charge against him mentioned (and discountenanced)
by Plutarch and Arrhian, fell into discredit very soon
after it arose, and perhaps was only remembered as a
curious piece of scandalous history, until the half-lunatic
Caracalla thought proper to revive it, in order to gratify
at once the tyrant's natural hatred for wisdom and
virtue, and his own morbid passion for idolizing the
memory of Alexander. It is recorded of him that he
persecuted the Aristotelean sect of philosophers with
singular hatred, abolishing the social meetings of their
body which appear to have taken place in Alexandria,
confiscating certain funds which they possessed, and
even entertaining the design of destroying their master's
works, on no other ground than that Aristotle was
thought to have aided Antipater in destroying Alex-
ander 1 .
that of those who chose to draw a parallel between the circumstances
of Germanicus's life and those of Alexander ; for which purpose this
version of the death of the latter was necessary, and perhaps to this
i,t owed much of its subsequent popularity. With respect too to
the silence concerning Aristotle, it is to be remarked that the ex-
pressions of Pliny, magna Aristotelis infamid excogitatum, (H. N.
xxx. ult.), if they are genuine, do not imply a belief either on his
own part or that of people in general, that the Philosopher was
guilty of abetting Antipater. But they seem more likely to be a
marginal note implying that "the story of the poisoning by such
water was a figment that had done Aristotle's character much
harm."
1 Xiphilinus, Epilom. Dionis. pp. 329, 30. Caracalla wore arms
and used drinking cups which had belonged to Alexander, erected
a great number of statues to him both in Rome and at the several
military stations, and raised a phalanx of Macedonians, armed all
after the manner of five centuries back, which he named after the
Conqueror of the East. In his wish to destroy the philosopher's
ITS PROBABLE ORIGIN. 91
To attempt to account for the origin of so absurd
a charge as that we have been discussing may perhaps
appear rash. We cannot however resist the temptation of
hazarding a conjecture, that while the intimacy of Aris-
totle with Antipater undoubtedly furnished a favourable
soil for the growth of the story, the actual germ of it
is to be looked for at Delphi. The cup in the treasure
house there, which the epigram we have quoted above
represents as presented by Alexander, was probably of
onyx, a stone of which the coloured layers resembling
as they do the outer coats of a hoof, procured it the
name by which it goes. Now it is obvious that in the
time of which we are speaking, when the merchant
who sold the wares was for the most part himself a
traveller in distant countries, marvellous tales would be
related respecting the strange commodities which he
imported. The onyx might to the admiring Greek be
represented as the solid hoof of some strange animal,
with no less plausibility than in the fourteenth cen-
tury a cocoa nut could be sold as a griffin's egg, a
long univalve shell represented as the horn of a land
animal, or the ammonites of Malta regarded as ser-
pents changed into stone by St Paul 2 . And although
works (KO\ TCC f3ij3\'ia avrov KaraKavs av KCLTaXdfiri). Nicanor was apparently abroad on
some service of danger. If he escapes, he is directed
by the codicil to erect certain statues of four cubits
in height in Stagira, to Jupiter and Athene the Pre-
servers (A HioTrjpi /ecu 'AOrjva crcoTeipr}), in pursuance of
a vow which the testator had made on his account. If
anything should happen to Nicanor before his marriage,
or after his marriage before the birth of children, and
he should fail to leave instructions, Theophrastus is to
take the daughter, and stand for all purposes of ad-
ministration in the place of Nicanor. Should he decline
to do so, the four provisional trustees are to act at their
own discretion, guided by the advice, of Antipater,
Besides these arrangements, all which seem adopted to
1 Strabo, xiii. p. 124.
HIS REMAINING FAMILY. 99
meet a sudden emergency, such as that of a man dying,
away from the person in whom he puts the most con-
fidence, and in doubt whether the one whom he next
trusted would be able to act, we find legacies to more
than one individual which apparently imply a former
bequest 2 , and a trifling want of arrangement in the
latter part, quite characteristic of a document drawn
up under the circumstances we have supposed. Thus
he orders statues to be erected to Nicanor, and Nica-
nor's father and mother; also to Arimnestus (his own
brother), " that there might be a memorial of him, he
having died childless." A statue of Ceres, vowed by
his mother, is to be set up at Nemea or elsewhere.
Then, as if the mention of one domestic relation had
suggested another, he commands that wherever he
should be buried, the bones of his deceased wife
should be taken up and laid by his side according
to her desire; and after this he again reverts to the
subject of statues to be set up, and gives directions
for the fulfilment of the vow which he had made for
the safety of Nicanor.
Aristotle left behind him a daughter named after
her mother, Pythias. She is said to have been three
" A legacy is left to Herpyllis vrpos ro? trporepov
( 13), and one Simus is to have ^w/o? TOV irpoTepov dpyvpiov,
another slave, or money to buy one ( 15). The battle of Cranon
took place in August, B. c. 322 ; but it is very probable that it
could not be safely conjectured till a short time after what course
Greek politics would take. If now Theophrastus was in Athens,
and not with Aristotle at Chalcis, as seems far from improbable,
(see Diog. Laert. Fit. Theophrasti, 36), Aristotle might reasonably
fear that he perhaps would not be able to act as his executor. Thus
too when he directs a house and furniture to be provided for Her-
pyllis, he selects Chalcis and Stagira, both places where she would
be safe from Athenian hatred, for her to choose between as a re-
sidence ( 14).
72
100 HERPYLLIS.
times married, first to Nicanor the son of Aristotle's
guardian Proxenus and his own adopted child ; se-
condly to Procles, a descendant apparently son or
grandson of Demaratus King of Lacedaemon, by whom
she had two sons named Procles and Demaratus, scho-
lars of Theophrastus ; and thirdly to Metrodorus, an
eminent physician, to whom she bore a son named after
his maternal grandfather 1 . He also left behind him an
infant son, named after his paternal grandfather, Nico-
machus, by a female of the name of Herpyllis, of whom
it is very difficult exactly to say in what relation she
stood to him. To call her his mistress would imply a
licentious description of intercourse which the name by
which she is described (TraXXa/o/) by no means warrants
us in supposing, and which the character of Aristotle,
the absence of any allusion to such a circumstance in
the numerous calumnies which were heaped upon him,
and the terms of respect in which she is spoken of in
his will 2 , would equally incline us to discredit. It seems
most probable that he was married to her by that kind
of left-handed marriage which alone the laws of Greece
and Rome permitted between persons who were not
both citizens of the same state. The Latin technical
term for the female in this relation was concubina. She
was recognized by the law, and her children could in-
herit the sixth part of their father's property. Mark
Antony lived in this kind of concubinage with Cleo-
patra, and Titus with Berenice. The two Antonines,
men of characters the most opposite to licentiousness,
1 Stahr, Aristotelia, p. 164.
9 He provides amply for her, and enjoins his executors, if she
should desire to marry, to take care that she is not disposed of in
a way unworthy of him, reminding them that she has deserved well
of him (on (nrov^aia trepi e/*e eyei/ero). Diog. Laert. 1 3.
LEFT HANDED MARRIAGES. 101
were also instances of this practice, which indeed re-
mained for some time after Christianity became the re-
ligion of the state, and was regulated by two Christian
Emperors, Constantine and Justinian 3 . The Greek
term is not used so strictly in a technical sense, and
may be said to answer with equal propriety to either
of the Latin words pellex and concubina. Where
however the legal relation was denoted, there was no
other word selected in preference 4 ; and we may safely
say that this, in the case before us, is the probable in-
terpretation, although there is no positive authority
that it is the true one. The son of Nicomachus was
brought up by Theophrastus, and if we are to credit
Cicero's assertion that the Nicomachean Ethics which
3 Taylor, Elements of the Civil Law, p. 273. The terms Semi-
matrimonium and Conjugium incequale, were applied to this con-
nexion, which was entered into before witnesses (testatione inter-
posita), and with the consent of the father of the woman. Both
contracting parties too were obliged to be single. See Gibbon,
chap. 44. Vol. v. pp. 368370.
4 The author of the Oration against Nesera thus uses it in the
distinction which he draws (p. 1386), TCIS /xei/ yap eraipa* t/Soi/t/s
eveKct eyo/xei/, Tot? B Tree A \aca9 TJ/S xafl' tj/jiepav Bepctireia^ TOV pd\ai r/e9 'AXefai/Speia, and
that after ftift\ioQnK^ probably followed something like KCU -nap
tu7rop7pa/? 6Qev \oyois (Polit. p. 1264,
! 39,) "with discussions foreign to the subject"; egtorepiKif ap%ri
(Id. p. 1272, 1. 19,) "external rule"; eguTepio ir'nT-rowi T-a?? ir\ei-
o-rat? TWV TTo'Xewi/, (Id. p. 12Q5, 1. 32,) " do not apply to the gene-
rality of states."
1 Suetonius, De cl. grammat. cap. 2, " plurimas acroases subinde
TWO CLASSES OF ARISTOTLE ? S WORKS. 123
If now we keep steadily in view this distinction
which it is plain that Aristotle himself made in his
discourses, the distinction between cyclical, methodical,
scientific productions, and insulated, independent essays,
we shall perceive at once from the nature of the case,
that without any premeditated design on the part of
the author, the former would only be appreciable by
genuine disciples, those who were able and willing to
afford a steady and continuous application to the de-
velopement of the whole, while the latter might be
understood by those who brought no previous know-
ledge with them, but merely attended to the matter
in hand 2 ; that the one required a severe and rigid
logic to preserve all parts of the system in due co-
herence, the other readily admitted of the aid which
the imagination affords to the elucidation of single
points, but which often becomes mischievous when they
are to be combined; that to the first the demonstra-
tive form of exposition would alone be appropriate,
to the second any one, narrative or dialogic or any
other, which might be most fit for placing the one
matter to be illustrated in a striking light. But we
must be very careful not to confuse these resulting
fecit, assidueque disseruit" There is obviously a distinction in-
tended between the dissertations which he continually delivered,
and the lectures which he gave from time to time.
2 An illustration may perhaps be useful in clearing up what we
apprehend to have been the real division. For the demonstration of
Pythagoras's celebrated Theorem,, (the 4?th Proposition of the first
Book of Euclid) the whole of the preceding part of the Book is
requisite. This then is an example of a Xoyos Kara QiXcxroQiav. But
in the particular case of an isosceles triangle, the property of the
square of the hypothenuse being equal to twice the square of one
side, may be directly shown to a person ignorant of geometry, as it
is by Socrates in Plato's dialogue Meno. This we conceive might
be described as a
124 CICERO'S IMITATION OF THE EXOTERIC
distinctions with the primitive one from which they
flowed, and still more not to suppose that they were
the cause of it; for we shall see presently that want
of attention to this caused in later writers first of all
inaccurate expressions as to the nature of this cele-
brated division and finally an utterly erroneous view
of it, and of the spirit in which it originated.
Cicero in two of his letters to Atticus 1 speaks of
having composed two works in the manner of Aris-
totle's exoteric ones. The points of comparison which
these two treatises (the De Finibus, and the De Re-
publicd) offer, consist in the dialogic form in which
they are written and the prefaces which serve to in-
troduce to the reader the dramatis persona who carry
on the discussion. The objections which some of these
propound to the view which it is the design of the
author to elucidate are turned into a means of bring-
ing it out in stronger and bolder relief. This mode
of treatment in the hands of a master obviously offers
many advantages. The dramatic interest keeps the at-
tention of the reader from flagging, and the peculiar
obstacles which the differences of individual tempera-
ment not unfrequently interpose to the reception of
any doctrine may be in this way most clearly set
1 Ad Attic, iv. 16. Hanc ego de Republica quam institui dispu-
tationem in African! personam et Phili et Laelii et Manilii contuli :
adjunxi adolescentes, Q. Tuberonem, P. Rutilium, duo Laelii generos,
Scaevolam, et Fannium. Itaque cogitabam, quoniam in singulis libris
utor procemiis, ut Aristoteles in iis, quos egwreptKovs vocat, aliquid
efficere ut non sine causa istum appellarem, &c Ad Attic, xiii.
19. Quae autera his temporibus scripsi, Aristoteleum morem habent;
in quo ita sermo inducitur ceterorum, ut penes ipsum sit principatus.
Ita confeci quinque libros vre/oj reXcoi/, &c. On the same principle he
had constructed his books De Oratore; (Epp. Attic, iv. 16; Epp. ad
Famil i. 9- 23.)
DIALOGUES OF ARISTOTLE. 125
forth and most easily removed. The dialogues of
Plato are an obvious example of this. But if we
consider the De Oratore, De Finibus, and De Re-
publicd of Cicero to represent with tolerable accuracy
the character of the Aristotelian dialogues, we see at
once a very considerable change. The genial produc-
tive power of the artist has given way to the systematic
reflection of the philosopher. The personages intro-
duced are not living and breathing men with all their
feelings, prejudices, and individual peculiarities, they
are mere puppets which speak the opinions entertained
by those whose name they bear. These opinions may
be fairly and lucidly stated, they may be backed by
all the pomp and power of rhetoric, as they are in
Cicero and as they probably were in Aristotle, but the
speakers have no life, the scene no reality, and in spite
of the pains taken by the author to prevent it by al-
lusions to particular times, places, and circumstances,
we rise from the perusal with our opinions more or
less modified, but with no more distinct recollection
of the parties by whom the discussion has been carried
on than if they had been distinguished by the letters
of the alphabet instead of the names of knpwn cha-
racters 2 . But what these productions have lost as
works of art, they have gained as works of science.
The distinct and explicit exposition of a principle
which prevents them from being the former, is a merit
in them as the latter. And as the dialogic form, even
* Bishop Berkeley's Hylas and Philonous, and Minute Philoso-
pher make no pretension to dramatic effect. The very names of the
collocutors indicate the principles which they profess. In our opin-
ion, Berkeley has acted wisely, but would have done better still to have
dropped the dialogic form. Harris's Three Treatises are an attempt
to come much nearer to the Platonic Dialogue, and in our judgment,
a signal failure.
126 THEIR STYLE.
where it fails in producing the dramatic impression
that we receive from Plato, admits to the fullest ex-
tent of all the assistance which rhetoric can afford, it
is not wonderful that it should have been selected by
Aristotle as an appropriate one for many or even most
of his exoteric treatises 1 .
Neither in those cases where he adopted this
form can we be surprized .that Aristotle should have
made use of a style, which however unfit for the pur-
poses of a rigidly scientific investigation, is not at all
inappropriate to compositions such as we have described.
A few relics (and unfortunately a very few,) have come
down to us of them ; about thirty lines in the original
Greek are quoted by Plutarch 2 from one of the most
celebrated, and Cicero has in a Latin dress preserved
two other small fragments 3 . The first of these is part
of a treatise which was either addressed to Eudemus,
Aristotle's disciple, or written on the occasion of his death,
and from the nature of the extract, no less than from
the name it bore, 4 seems to have treated upon the
1 Cicero, although he does not expressly say that the exoteric
works were all dialogues,, speak of them as if they were nearly co-
extensive. So too Ammonius (Introd. ad Categ. 2) divides the
regular treatises of Aristotle into two heads : TWV a-wTaj/jLaTiKwv vd
jueY vvTOTrpoGta-ira K.OLI aKpoa/jLariKO,' TCI Be StaXoyiKCt KOI e^tarepiKCt. But
Simplicius and Philoponus prevent us from construing their expression
too rigidly. The former says B<%7 Be Stgptjficvtftv O.VTOV TWV crvyypafj.-
JJLGITWV, er? Te Ta earre^tKa, oia TO. i7<5. After speaking of double doctrines of the
Pythagoreans, Plato, Epicurus and the Stoics, he adds, Aeyovo-t Be
KO\ 01 'Apt
TOTTt/coji/, considering it as merely an introduction to
the Topics, an appellation of which Porphyry disap-
proves. The evidence which determined the ancient
critics in their decision between the rival works bear-
ing this name was solely internal. The cast of thought
and the phraseology appeared to them to be Aristotle's,
and they conceived that references to this one were to
LOGICAL WRITINGS. 143
be found in others of the Aristotelian writings. But
before Aristotle, Archytas the Pythagorean philosopher,
in his work irepl TTCLVTOS, had written on the Ten
Categories, and some of the moderns 1 have considered
that this work was to be referred to one of that School.
Grotius quotes the book without naming Aristotle as
the author*. Brandis however on the principle we have
indicated above (p. 116) has established the prevalent
opinion on this subject, on evidence possessing a very
high degree of authority.
II. On interpretation. (Trepl e
A philosophical treatise on grammar as far as re-
lates to the nature of nouns and verbs. Some of the
old commentators from its obscurity imagined it to be
a mere collection of notes, and Andronicus considered
it not to be Aristotle's. Alexander of Aphrodisias,
however, and Ammonius proved it to be his, and to
have been used by Theophrastus in a treatise of the
same name which he wrote. Still the latter of these,
as well as Porphyry, suspected that the last part of
the work was the addition of some more modern hand.
III. Former Analytics, i. n. Latter Analytics,
I. II. (avaXvTiKa TrpOTepa, ava\VTiKoi vcrrepa.)
Of the former of these treatises the true and ancient
title was Trepl GvXXoyiviuLov and that of the latter Trepl
aVo^e^ews-. Diogenes Laertius, (Tit. 23) speaks of
eight books of the Former Analytics, or as one MS.
has it, ten, and of two of the Latter. And Petiti
conceived that the work which is referred to in the
1 Jonsius De Histories Philosophies Scriptoribus p. 4. " Auctor
libri de Categoriis, quicumque Platonicorum vel Pythagoreorum is
demum fuerit."
2 Ad Matth. Ev. xiv. 4
144 LOGICAL WRITINGS.
Nicomachean Ethics ,' has not come down to us.
The old commentators found forty books on this sub-
ject, professedly by Aristotle, and determined on
the genuineness of these only, rejecting all the rest,
Their subject is that which in modern times is es-
pecially termed Logic, but would be more properly
called Dialectics, that is, an examination of the possible
forms in which an assertion may be made and a con-
clusion established.
Theophrastus, Eudemus and Phanias, scholars of
Aristotle, wrote treatises on the same subjects as these
three of their master, and called them by the same
name, a circumstance which probably had some connec-
tion with the number of "Analytics" ascribed to him.
IV. Topics. I. II. III. IV. V. VI. VII. VIII. (TOTTIKCI.)
An analysis of the different heads from which de-
monstrative arguments may be brought. It was con-
sidered by the ancient commentators as the easiest of
all Aristotle's systematic writings. The Romans how-
ever, as Cicero tells us in the preface to his work of
the same name, found it so difficult as to be repelled
by it, although he himself praises it no less for its
language than for its scientific merits. His own work
is an epitome of it made by himself from memory
during a sea voyage from Velia to Rhegium 2 .
V. On sophistical proofs, i. n.
An analysis of the possible forms of fallacy in de-
monstration. This work has a natural connection with
the Topics, as Aristotle himself remarks in the begin-
ning of the last chapter of the second book.
1 VI. 3. p. 1139. col. 2. tin. 27- Bekk.
* Epp. Fam. VII. 19-
PHYSICAL AND METAPHYSICAL WRITINGS. 145
The preceding works taken together complete Aris-
totle's Logical writings, and with the introduction of Por-
phyry to the Categories have gone generally in modern
times by the name of the Organum, from the circum-
stance of Aristotle having called Logic opyavov opydvwv.
The philosopher gave this name to the art because of
all others it is the most purely instrumental, that is,
the most entirely a means to something else, and the
least an end to be desired for its own sake. The term
however, was in subsequent ages misapplied to mean
that it was the best of all instruments for the dis-
covery of truth, as opposed to the observation of facts,
and the art was correspondently abused.
VI. Physical Lectures, i. n. in. iv. v. vi. vn-
VIII. \(j)vcriKr) a/CjOoao'is).
It is a very questionable matter whether this treatise
was published by the author as one organic whole. The
last three books probably formed a treatise by themselves
under the name Trepl Kii^'crews 3 , and the five first another,
under that of 0v * n Diogenes's
Catalogue, refers.
10
146 PHYSICAL AND METAPHYSICAL WRITINGS.
of the ideas of Nature, Necessity, and Chance ; and
the next three with the properties of Body, or rather
with the analysis of those notions of the understanding
which are involved in the idea of Body. Of this work
abstracts and syllabuses (/ce^aXaTa /cal a-wfyeis) were
very early made by the Peripatetic school 1 , and these
by keeping their attention fixed upon the connection of
a system of dogmas, perhaps contributed much to divert
them from the observation of nature, and to keep up
that perpetually-recurring confusion between laws of
the Understanding and laws of the external World
which characterizes the whole of the ancient physical
speculations.
VII. On the Heavens, i. n. m. iv. (Trepl ovpa-
vov).
Alexander of Aphrodisias considered that the proper
name for this work was Trepl Koa^ov 9 as only the first two
books 'are really on the subject of the heavenly bodies
and their circular motion. The two last treat on the
four elements and the properties of gravity and light-
ness, and afford much information relative to the
systems of Empedocles and Democritus.
VIII. On Generation and Decay, i. n. (^repl 76-
KOL
This work treats on those properties of bodies which
in our times would be consideredfto be the proper sub-
jects of physiological and of chemical science. Many
other notions, however, of a metaphysical nature, are
mixed up with these, and it is only for its illustration
of the history of philosophy that this work, like the
1 Simplicius, (Introd. ad. Phys. Ausc. vi. and vii.)
PHYSICAL AND METAPHYSICAL WRITINGS. 147
rest of the physical treatises, is of any value to the
modern student.)
IX. Meteorology. I. II. III. IV.
The first of these hooks was by some in the time
of the old commentators held not to be genuine; and
Ammonius and others considered that the fourth should
immediately follow the second of the last treatise, with
which the subjects on which it treats, the changes ef-
fected in bodies by heat and cold, moisture and dry-
ness, &c., are certainly more nearly connected.
X. To Alexander, on the World,
The titles of this tract in the various MSS. differ
much from one another. In one it is called Trepl /cou-
fjLoypa(j)6ias', in another Trepi KOCT/ULOV KOI eTcpwv ctvayKaiwv',
in a third cruvo\j/is 7 Trepl TOV 7rai>To9, which Fabricius holds to be
the true title. He considers the work to be genuine,
contrary to the opinion of Scaliger, Salmasius, Casau-
bon, Voss, and Buhle. Fabricius's opinion has been
taken up by Weisse, but the spuriousness of the piece
is glaring. Stahr 2 has, as we think, satisfactorily shown
that it is in all probability a composition of very late
date, based upon Apuleius's work De Mundo. He
remarks that it is not mentioned by any writer before
Apuleius: for that the passage of Demetrius (De Elocut.
243) does not really contain any allusion to it. On
the other hand, Simplicius expressly states that Aris-
totle wrote no one treatise on this subject ; and that
this very circumstance was the inducement for Nicolaus,
one of the later Peripatetics, to do so.
2 Aristoteles bei den Roemern. p. 165. et scq.
102
148 PHYSICAL AND METAPHYSICAL WRITINGS.
XI. On the Soul. I. II. III. (-Tre/cn
In the first of these books are discussed the opinions
of preceding philosophers upon this subject; in the se-
cond, the Soul in its sensible relations; in the third,
in its rational ones. A celebrated dialogue of Aris-
totle's, to which we have before referred, bore this
same title; and such as consider that the exoteric
works were all in the form of dialogues, imagine that
in the Nicomachean Ethics 1 he alludes to it. There
are parts, however, of the third book of this treatise
which seem apt for his purpose in that place, and al-
though the work serves to make up that system of
Aristotle's to which the preceding physical treatises as
well as the following belong, it is sufficiently independ-
ent of them to allow of its being perfectly understood
without their perusal; a character which in our opinion
is the only essential one of an exoteric writing.
XII. Eight tracts on physical subjects, namely,
(a.) On Perception and Objects of Perception.
(jrepl aia-0q
XIX. On Colours,
This has been considered by some critics to be the
work of Theophrastus. Plutarch speaks of a treatise
by Aristotle of the same name in two books.
PHYSICAL WRITINGS. 151
XX. From the Book on Sounds, (e/c rov
Apparently this tract is only a fragment; although
Porphyry, who has preserved it in his commentary on
the Harmonicon of Ptolemy, says that he has given
the whole work.
XXI. Physiognomica.
Of this tract the last chapter of the Former Ana-
lytics is a sort of compendium. Buhle considers it
spurious. It is not mentioned hy any of the old com-
mentators, but is by Stobseus and by Diogenes Laertius
in his catalogue.
XXII. On Plants, (irepl
Aristotle wrote two books on plants, but not these
which we have. They are a translation into Greek
from the Latin ; and even this version was considerably
removed from a Greek original, having been made by
some Gaul from an Arabian version, which again was
only derived from a more ancient Latin translation.
The original of all these, according to Sealiger's view,
was only a cento of scraps taken partly from Aristotle,
and partly from the first book of Theophrastus's History
of Plants. Aristotle's work was already lost in the time
of Alexander of Aphrodisias.
XXIII. On Wonderful Stories, (irepl
This book, in spite of its title, is nothing more than
a collection of strange accounts, nor does it appear to
have formed a part of a larger work of at all a different
description. The latter part is obviously spurious, and
with respect to the remainder various opinions have been
152 MISCELLANEOUS QUESTIONS.
held. Dodwell conceives Theophrastus to have been
the author, Scaliger Aristotle. Buhle considers the
whole to he a patchwork of extracts from the works
of the latter. Our opinion is, that the germ of the
work is to be looked for in one of those note-books or
vTro/uLvrifjLara which were appropriated to collections, and
from which supplies were occasionally drawn for more
systematic writings : and that this was, in its trans-
mission down to our times, added to by several hands,
and some of these most unskilful ones. See our notice
of the Problems below (No. XXV).
XXIV. Mechanics.
The first part of this work touches upon the prin-
ciples of mechanics, and is followed by a number of
questions which are resolved by a reference to them.
This latter division is probably only a part of the
TrpoftX^fjiaTa eyKVK\ia or questions on the whole cycle
of science, which we find mentioned as a work of
Aristotle's in two books by Diogenes Laertius, and
which is quoted by Aulus Gellius.
XXV. Problems. (TrpoftX^ara).
This is a collection of questions on various subjects
in thirty-eight divisions, of which the first relates to
medical, the fifteenth to mathematical, the eighteenth
to philological, the nineteenth to musical, the twenty-
seventh and three following to ethical, and the rest
mainly to physical and physiological matters. Theo-
phrastus is also said to have compiled a collection of
problems, and Pliny quotes him as the authority for a
circumstance which we find mentioned in this work 1 .
\
1 Prob. xxxiii. 12. Plin. Hist. Nat. xxviii. 6.
MISCELLANEOUS QUESTIONS. 153
In his treatises, too, trepi KOTTWV and Trepl tipdrcw, there
are several coincidences with the Problems of Aristotle ;
and hence some have held him really to be the author
of these, while others have considered those works to
he nothing more than a patchwork of Aristotle's Pro-
blems.
Besides the TrpoftX^aTa e^KVKXia which we men-
tioned in the last article, Diogenes mentions two books
of TrpofiXijiuLaTa eTnreflea/xeVa, (problems farther C0W-
Sldered), and two of TrpoflXrjimaTa e/c TWV ArjfjLOKpiTov.
Moreover Plutarch and Athenaeus, and other authors,
quote from the TrpofiXijimaTa (pucruca. That the work
which has come down to us is neither any one of these,
nor the aggregate of them all, is certain. Sylbourg in
his preface points out several instances in which Aris-
totle himself speaks of questions discussed in them,
which will be looked for in vain in the present treatise.
Neither do we find most of the quotations made by
Aulus Gellius, Macrobius, Apuleius, and Alexander of
Aphrodisias. On the other hand, some citations which
Gellius produces from the TrpoftX^fjLara eynvicXia, and one
which Macrobius does from the TTjOo/BX^Vara Availed are
found. So are two citations by Cicero, and one by
Galen, quoting generally from the Problems. These
circumstances indicate that the work has been very
much changed since it came from Aristotle's hands ;
and the most plausible hypothesis seems to be that the
nucleus of the work is a selection 2 from the collections
of Aristotle and Theophrastus, added to it in its course
down to us. There are many repetitions to be found
in it, some even three times over with the change of
2 Perhaps by some Alexandrine scholar. Aristophanes the cele-
brated grammarian epitomized some of Aristotle's works on Natural
History (flicrnr/rx cited by Schneider. Pref. ad H. A. p. xviii.)
154 MATHEMATICAL WRITINGS.
only a few words ; there is a great difference of style
observable in several parts ; in many of the more ancient
manuscripts some passages are omitted and others dif-
ferently arranged ; and as regards the philosophy, it
is impossible to suppose that a part could proceed either
from Aristotle or Theophrastus, or from any philosopher
of an undegenerate age. A great deal is no doubt
due to the book-makers under the Roman empire: it
was a work particularly well suited to the manufacture
of such Miscellanies as the taste of that time delighted
in, and, with the exception of the works on natural
history, appears to have been by far the most generally
popular of any of the Aristotelian writings. These
circumstances render it necessary for the historian of
philosophy to be extremely cautious how he infers the
opinions of Aristotle upon any subject from it.
XXVI. On Indivisible Lines, (irepl CLTO/ULWV
This tract is said by Simplicius to have been by
some of the ancient commentators ascribed to Theo-
phrastus.
XXVII. The Quarters and Names of the Winds.
Oe&eis Kal TrpocrrjyopiaL).
A fragment from Aristotle's work Trepl o-rj/uLeicov ^1^-
mentioned by Diogenes in his catalogue. It is
found in some manuscripts of Theophrastus's works, but
Salmasius considers it to be by Aristotle.
XXVIII. On Xenophanes, on Zeno, on Gorgias.
(TTCpl EevotyavovSj irepl Z,r)V(*)vos, Trepl Topyiov).
This fragment, according to Brandis, is the only
one of all the works which have come down to us under
THE METAPHYSICS. 155
the name of Aristotle's, which presents the least indica-
tion of that treatment which the manuscripts are said to
have met with at the hands of Apellicon. This too
and the Mechanics are the only works which Patritius
allowed to he genuine. It is singular that one of the
manuscripts ascribes it to Theophrastus. Another gives
as a title /card ras- ^o^a? TWV , and compare Cicero, Brut. 64,.
:J P. 1410, col. 2, line 2 ed. Bekker.
4 De Oratore,\. 10.
160 RHETORICAL WRITINGS.
patetics boasted "that Aristotle and Theophrastus not
only wrote better, but wrote much more on the subject
of oratory than all the professed masters of the science."
But it seems to us more probable that the work
which he cites was one by Theodectes, his own scholar,
and that Valerius Maximus mistook for an act of envy
what was more probably meant and taken for a flatter-
ing encouragement. The first sketch of the Rhetoric
was, as is remarked by Niebuhr, published long before
it was worked up into the form we have it in now,
and in this interval Theodectes, of whom Cicero speaks
as a writer on the subject, probably published his book.
It will be observed that Aristotle does not cite the trea-
tise as his own ; but this was overlooked by Valerius, or
the authority whom he followed, and the tale we have
mentioned above was coined to illustrate the passage.
It may also be remarked that the double publication of
the Rhetoric will serve to account for the growth of that
story which Dionysius of Halicarnassus takes so much
pains to refute. No one could have hazarded such a
fiction with all the quotations from Demosthenes under
his very eyes. It must have originated with some one
who used a copy of the early edition ; while Dionysius
in his refutation used the later.
XXXVII. The Rhetoric to Alexander.
This treatise is not mentioned by Diogenes Laertius
in his catalogue of Aristotle's works ; and the dedicatory
preface at the beginning is a solitary instance, if it be
a writing of Aristotle's, of such a style. Quintilian 1
appears to quote it as the production of Anaximenes of
1 Compare Quintilian, lust. Oral. iii. 4. 9- with Rhetoric, p.
1421. col. b. lin. 8.
POETICAL CRITICISM. 161
Lampsacus, a contemporary of the Stagirite. Neither
the style nor the treatment of the subject accords with
the character of the last work, and perhaps what most
contributed to procure its ascription to Aristotle is the
circumstance that the writer claims the authorship of
the re-^yai TW 9eo$e/cr>7 ypcKpei&ai, which, according to
the story of Valerius Maximus spoken of in the last
Article, could only belong to Alexander's preceptor.
Notwithstanding this, Victorius and Buhle have attri-
buted the work to Callisthenes. We should be inclined
to consider it the performance of a sophist of a very
late date, and should regard the allusion to Theodectes
rather as a confirmation of the opinion.
XXXVIII. On the Poetic Art. (irep\ TTO^^.)
On the subject of this work we have spoken (p. 139)-
It has been considered by others a fragment of the
two books On Poets, which Macrobius quotes 2 , but it
hardly seems possible to consider it in this light. If it
is derived in any way from a published work, it must
have been by a process of epitomizing and selecting, and
that not very skilfully.
* Saturnal, v. 18. " Ipsa Aristotelis verba ponam ex libro quern
" de Poetis subscripsit secundo": The quotation which follows ap-
pears to be taken from a work of a very different character to the
fragment which we have.
11
APPENDIX.
THE NATURE OF THE POLITICAL TREATISE.
THE Political Treatise of Aristotle is so important
for the elucidation of Greek history and Greek philo-
sophy, that it seems desirable to give some of the
reasons which have led us to form the opinion we have
expressed in the text (p. 140), at greater length than
would be allowed by the limits of an ordinary note ; and
the principal of them are accordingly here subjoined. At
the same time, however satisfactory we may deem them,
we cannot expect that they will appear at once equally
conclusive to those who have been accustomed always
to regard the work in a different light, and we would
request such persons, after perusing the following note,
to study the treatise itself, and then decide whether
the form of its composition is, or is not, incompatible
with any other view than the one we have taken
of it.
I. In the third Book, the author, on the occasion of
mentioning certain states where an executive power,
almost supreme, was entrusted to one individual,
although the rest of the institutions partook more or
less of a democratic character, gives Epidamnus as an
existing instance 1 . In the fifth Book, he has occasion
again to refer to this functionary, but he speaks of his
1 p. 1287- col. a. lin. 7-
NOT WRITTEN CONTINUOUSLY. 163
office as one which no longer existed*. A revolution,
gradual but complete, had in the interval been effected
at Epidamnus. The constitution had acquired a com-
pletely popular character, and the office of Supreme
Administrator had together with the other oligarchal
features of the government, been swept away. That
such blemishes as this would not have been left standing
in a work published by the author himself, few persons
will be inclined to question. Still it may be argued
that although not published by him, it may yet have
been in course of preparation for publication in its
present form, and that its last finish, in which such in-
congruities would have been removed, may have been
prevented by his death. But this argument may be
shown to be inadmissible. In this same fifth Book
there is a passage 3 obviously written while the expe-
dition and death of Dion the Syracusan, (which latter
happened soon after the dethronement of Dionysius
the tyrant by his agency,) was a subject of common
talk and considered as an event of the day. "One
cause of despotical governments being overthrown is,"
says Aristotle, " dissension among those parties in whose
hands they are, as in the instance of Gelon's relations,
and at the present time (KOI vvv) in that of Dionysius' s."
Dion's death, which he mentions presently afterwards,
took place in the first half of the year 353, B. c. Now
Aristotle was at this time little more than thirty years
of age, and was at Athens pursuing his studies under
Plato. (See above, p. 11.) We cannot therefore sup-
pose that the Politics is a work, the elaboration of which
was cut short by the author's death, without at the same
time supposing that this expression was by him suffered
2 p. 1301. col. b. lin. 2fi.
8 p. 1312. col. b. lin. 10.
112
164
EVIDENCE OF
to stand for a period of more than thirty years, of which
every succeeding one would render its impropriety more
glaring.
II. In a passage of the first Book 1 , in the course
of an analysis of the different elements which enter
into the Social Relation, the question is started whether
the acquisition of external objects of desire, necessarily
and in the nature of things is a part of the office of the
master of a household. For the purpose of elucidating
his views on this subject, the Author digresses into a
general discussion of the question of Production (>)
KTYITIKYI). Some kinds of this he considers as pointed
out by Nature herself to Man ; the exercise of them
is necessary to the supply of his natural wants in the
Social State, and consequently, (this Social State itself
being grounded in Nature,) the industrial tendency
which prompts him to such exercise is to be regarded
as analogous to those ordinary instincts which direct
the animal creation to the particular regions that furnish
the food required by their peculiar organization. But
Production has a natural limit, and this limit is short
of the extent to which the powers of Man are capable
of carrying it. Its natural limit is the satisfaction
of the natural wants of the Community, under the
highest possible form of civilization. So soon as this
limit is passed, Production changes its character. Its
employment (epyov) then becomes the accumulation of
means without reference to an end ; and it assumes the
character, according to the views of the ancients, of a
spurious, unnatural, and sordid pursuit. To this species
of Production, Aristotle proposes to appropriate the name
1 p. 1256. col. a. lin. 4.
SUPPLEMENTARY PARTS. 165
of Acquisition (rj ^prj/uLariffriK^). The same arguments
which prove that the former kind was, in the nature
of things, part of the duty of the head of the Family,
would show that this latter is not; and such is the
conclusion to which Aristotle comes, and which he
formally states (p. 1258. col. a. lin. 18).
But when we look to the place where this discussion
commences, we see plainly that in the first draught
of the text it could not have existed. Originally perhaps
the passage (p. 1256. col. a. lin. 15) ran thus : ei yap
TOV xprjuaTKTTiKOv Oecopijaai woOev yjpr\i*.aTa. K.GLI /CTJ/CTIS
>J yjprw.aTiaTiK.ri TJ9 oiKOVo/niKris ftepos av i^.~\ But
as this conclusion could not be assented to without a
limitation, the writer subjoined the words which follow
in the MSS. r] $e KTijais TroXXa Trepiei\rirjit TW ycvvrjOevTi Trape^eiv'
TravTi yap ef oil yiverai Tpo^/ <
cravTrjv TpoCprjv TOIS irpwTo^ Xoyois). But
the subject is really handled not in the first, but the
third Book 4 . Now we can scarcely conceive that Aris-
totle himself could cite his own work so inaccurately,
and we might be inclined perhaps to consider that the
expression TT/OWTOI Xo7oi referred to a former treatise
and not a former part of this one. But we are pre-
vented from doing this by the recurrence of the same
8 The two paragraphs are p. 1285. col b. lin. 19 p. 1286. ult.
and p. 1287- col. a. lin. 1. col. b. lin. 36.
Namely from p. 1276. col. b. lin. Ifi. to 1277- col. b. lin. 17.
168 DIFFERENT DIVISION OF BOOKS.
phrase in another passage 1 where it is impossible to
avoid referring it to the first book of the Politics.
We are therefore inclined to conjecture that at the
time this reference was made, the first Book did not
terminate where it now does, but was continued on
into what is now the third, that the present second
Book, (which is perfectly insulated from all the rest of
the treatise, and consists entirely of a review of certain
constitutions existing in the time of Aristotle, together
with a discussion of the political writings of Plato,
Phaleas of Chalcedon, Hippodamus of Miletus, and
others,) was wanting, and that the then second Book
commenced with the words eTre/ Sc raDra Suopurrat.
(p. 1278. col. b. lin. 6 9 .)
V. Other passages might be produced which ap-
pear to indicate the accumulation of materials, or the
growth of thoughts, in a manner which we could not
expect to find either in a published work, or one in
course of preparation for publication.
Thus the examination of what rights constitute
citizenship, a question entered upon by him in the
beginning of the third Book, has every appearance of
being a collection of notes put down by him while he
was in the course of coming to his opinions. His first
definition of citizenship is ' participation in judicial and
1 p. 1278. col. b. lin. 18.
2 It could not have commenced further on in the work than
this, for it is only a few lines further on (col. b. lin. 18.) that he
quotes "the Jirst book." Yet in another passage (p. 1295. col. a.
lin. 4.) he quotes as in the first book a discussion which does not
occur till more than six pages further, i. e. in p. 1284. col. b.
lin. S5. seqq. Hence a still greater confusion seems necessary to
be supposed. We must believe the same expression vrp&Toi \oyot
to refer to one division in one place, to another in another!
GRADUAL GROWTH OF NOTES. 169
official functions' (ncrc-^eiv Kpicrecas /cat apxfjs, p. 1275.
col. a. lin. 23). Then he goes on to say that this
definition is more applicable to democracies than to
any other form of government, and after exemplifying
the truth of this observation by the cases of Lacedaemon
and Carthage, proposes to alter it and substitute for it
the position ' that a citizen is one who has a right to
a share in functions either deliberative or judicial' (<
c^ova ia Kowwveiv ap\W ftovXfVTtKtjs fj KpirtKrjs, col. b.
lin. 21). Then follow two notes of which the second
grows as it were out of the first, and continues to the
end of the chapter (p. 1276. col. b. lin. 15). In the
former he distinguishes between the legal and the
natural definition of citizenship, and in the second
remarks upon certain political writers of the time,
who had raised a question connected with the definition
of citizenship, namely, what constituted the identity
of a state. After this he again resumes the thread of
the discussion. But these notes are not like the one
we mentioned above: they are very short, but they
refer to a great many points, and even the opinions
which are remarked on are rather implied as known
than distinctly stated.
In the fourth Book (p. 1290. col. b. lin. 21) he
attempts an analysis of States considered as masses of
individuals. But the passage is in disorder and the
enumeration incomplete. The fifth class he speaks of
is the military one. The mention of this class suggests
a critique upon the Republic of Plato, in reference to
a similar analysis which is introduced there. On re-
verting to his own division, he proceeds not with a
sixth t but a seventh class.
Some way further on (p. 1297. col. b. lin. 35) he
begins the subject again, as it were from a new point
170 REFERENCES TO
of view. He proceeds to attempt a classification of
states, by analyzing government into its component
functions, and exhausting the number of ways in which
the various judicial, executive, and deliberative duties
of the state may be performed. But the division is
incomplete, and to all appearance designedly so. See
for instance p. 1300. col. a. lin. 23. seqq., where it ap-
pears plain that the author did not wish to enumerate
all the different modes by which the functionaries might
be appointed, but only the more important ones,- those
perhaps on which he had certain remarks to make.
Still a complete enumeration is so apparently necessary,
that the passage seems to have been tampered with by
some person who desiderated it 1 .
The confusion in one or two of these passages some
may be inclined to attribute merely to ordinary causes,
such as the ignorance or carelessness of transcribers, or
the damaged condition of the manuscripts which they
copied. We are not disposed to accept this solution
of the difficulties which meet us so constantly in the
work ; although it is extremely difficult to say what
degree of disarrangement may not be due to this cause.
Such an hypothesis however can hardly be entertained
in such cases as the following.
VI. In a passage in the third Book the manuscripts
1 Thus the passage Ka\ TO Tivas CK TTCIVTIOV rtt9
Tavai TCI? Be K\tip(a jj a'/x0o?i/, ras /JLCV K\tjpu) TCCS Se alpeo-ei, o
(p. 1300. col. a. lin. 38 40), appears to have been introduced by him
because after the cases where all were the appointing body to offices,
he thought those ought to come where a particular class appointed,
not observing that those cases of this kind which were of practical
importance had been already noticed in the preceding clause TO Be
Htj TrdvTd*;, &c. The same cause is the origin of the interpolations
i; K TIVWV (lin. 35), and TO %e rti/ct? e aVa'i/TUJi/. (col. b. lin. 4).
AN OMITTED DISCUSSION. 171
all run as follows 2 I el yap dSvvarov e d Tret I/TOW Giro
OVTWV elvai TroAti/, eel $ cmnrrov TO KaO' avrov epyov ev
TOUTO o CLTT dperfjs* 7rei $ dSvvarov o/uoiOW elvai
rofs TroX/ras, OVK av eiv] fjiia apery irdXirov KCLI
dvfyos dyaOov. It appears impossible by an alteration
of a kind and degree which the principles of conjectural
criticism would sanction, to produce any tolerable sense
of this passage. The question on which Aristotle is
engaged is the one we alluded to before (p. 167.) whether
the perfection of civism (apery iro\irov dyaOou) is
identical with the perfection of humanity (apery dv$po$
dyaOov). "This question may," he says, after resolving
it in one way, " be settled with the same result by
another course of investigation, viz., by determining
what is the idea of the perfection of a state 3 ." Now a
2 p. 1276. col. b. lin. 37 40. One manuscript alone has o/xoiw?
for O/XOiOl/5.
3 aAAa KOI KCCT' d\\ov Tpoirov COTTI SicnropovvTas eVeA0e?i/ TOV O.VTOV
\oyov Tre/oi T;5 dpicTTtj^ i jro\tTeia ^'o KOI /jid\i rots Trepi rrjv aptcn-o-
KpctTtav' e/cet yap $t(Xo/ue0a e/c ntfar&i' nepwv avayKaicw
eWt TraVa TroXt?. Now the only passage remaining in
the manuscripts to which this description will at all
apply, is one which does not precede but follow the
reference in question, namely the paragraph beginning
with the words on jmei/ ovv TroXtretat TrXeiovs (p. 1290.
coL b. lin. 21.) ] The allusion must therefore be to a
passage now no longer remaining. And where we
are to look for this, will we think be irrefragably de-
termined by another observation (p. 1293. col. b.
lin. 30.) which shows that the discussion described by
the phrase ra Trepl rrjv dpKTTOKpariav, was really an
examination into the best form of government, the
ideal perfection of a state, in which, and in which
alone, (according to Aristotle's views) the perfection of
humanity and of civism are identical for any portion
of the community whatever 2 . Here then we have a
confirmation of our conjecture as to the deficiency which
we remarked in the original passage. But that this
deficiency should have been occasioned by the errors of
transcribers is perfectly impossible. The essay intended
to fill up the gap must have existed in a separate
form, or it could not have entirely disappeared. Yet
1 And even here a reference is made to an earlier treatment
of the question OTI /uei/ ovv iroXiTelat 7rX/ou?, KOI $i tjv aiTiav, *pr]Tai.
irep\ /? $ttj\0o fj.fv
tv TO?? irptoTOts Aoyots. Trjv yap f* Ttav apurTuv ctTrAftK KOT'
dpcrijv iroXiTfiav, KOI fjiij Jrpo'i VTrodea-iv TWO. djaduv ai/fy>oi/, novrjv
c'tKtiiov irpovayopcveiv dpurroKpa-riav. ev ^ovy yap aTrXwc o aurov
dvtjp Kai iroAiTij? dyado': fffTtv ot Se ev Ta?? oAA.ai? dyadot
Ttji/ jToXiTe'tav elffi rrjv avrtav,
174 SEPARATE DISCUSSION OF TYRANNY.
it could not have been a separate work, or it would
not have been quoted as an organic part of this one,
as we see is the case.
VII. The instance of an obvious deficiency which
we have just given, although perhaps one of the most
striking cases of this kind, is not the only one. In
the enumeration of the different archetypal forms of Go-
vernment, he expresses his intention to treat of Despotic
Monarchy (or Tyranny,} the last in order ; " for of all,"
says he, "it has the least claim to be considered a
"Polity, and polities are the subject with which our
"investigation is concerned." Then follow the words
Si rfv fjiv ovv airiav rexa/crm TOV Tpoirov TOVTOV, e'ipriTai
(p. 1293. col. b. lin. 30.) Now certainly we might
refer this observation to the reason which has just
been assigned, but if this be its right application, how
very superfluous and unnecessarily formal it is. A
couple of pages further on, the number of different
modifications which the despotic form of government
assumes are enumerated, (p. 1295. col. a. lin. 1 24.)
and the author winds up the paragraph by saying
"These are the different species of Despotic Monarchy,
" so many and no more from the causes which have been
" mentioned 1 " But the reader will look in vain for this
professed mention of the causes; and, putting this
circumstance together with the formal statement before-
mentioned, we have little scruple in conjecturing that
the latter really followed a separate discussion of the
nature of Despotic Government, which also contained rea-
sons why the forms it assumed should be so many
and no more.
TCIVTO. KO. Tocravta ia TO? e
TACIT ALLUSIONS TO OTHERS. 175
VIII. There is another class of cases, in which
the author obviously alludes to the writings of contem-
poraries, but the allusions are so little explicit and
at the same time it is so obvious that they are allu-
sions that it seems impossible to avoid one of two
inferences, either that the passages in which they occur
are little else than memoranda for the writer himself,
or that the work is a collection of notes for lectures,
and that a formal oral statement of the opinions re-
ferred to had antecedently been given. The latter view
has been entertained with respect to most of Aristotle's
writings 2 , but in our opinion it is inconsistent with
the comparatively full developement of some parts of
this work, with the incompleteness of the whole as a
system, and above all, with the contemporaneous ex-
istence of such phenomena as those of which we have
above given an example (p. 167) where an original pa-
ragraph stood side by side with its intended successor.
The following may serve as instances of the allusions
we speak of, although an inspection of the whole course
of the argument in the context is necessary to appre-
ciate their force.
In the early part of the third Book 3 , Aristotle ob-
serves that in the question of what constitutes citizen-
ship, exiles and persons disqualified for some particular
reason may in a certain sense be termed citizens, "but,''
he adds, "a citizen, simply and unconditionally, is by
2 Thus the expression in the Nicomachean Ethics (p. 1147.
col. 2. lin. 8.) ov Xoyov Be? irapd TUJV (pvcnoXoyujv dx.o\ieiv has been con-
sidered such as would naturally be used by a lecturer addressing
his class.
3 p. 1275. Col. a. lin. 20. KCU TTp\ ruv aVi^wi/ KCU e^w KCIKOV. Politic, v. p. 1 310. col. a. lin. 9-
THE SAME FOR ALL FORMS. 181
be peculiarly insisted upon in the theories constructed
to justify such policy. Hence when Aristotle, re-
ferring to these theories without formally explaining
their views, wishes to assert the general principle that
the question of what constitutes identity in a state
is entirely separate from the question of the justifica-
tion of this or that form of government, he does it
by a loosely-worded remark specifically referring to
these. " If then there are any cases," says he, " of
democracies under these circumstances, the acts of this
form of government are to be considered acts of the
state, in exactly the same sense as the acts of the oli-
garchy, or the tyranny, are 2 ."
2 p. 1276. col. a. lin. 13, e'ltrep ovv KOI ^rj/jiOKparovvrai rii/e? Kara
TOV TpOTTOV TOVTOI', O/UL0itt TtJS 7TO\OK (fictTedlf ClVCtl [VaUTf/^] TCI?
dets KO\ Tdt? CK T ^ 9 o\iya-ia<: KCU T
THE END.
14 DAY USE
RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED
LOAN DEPT.
This book is due on the last date stamped below, or
on the date to which renewed.
Renewed books are subject to immediate recall.
REC'D LD
|OCT13'63-5PM
ft 8IW63PS
JUN221976
76
Ift STACKS
REC'D LU
r-a
""l.B 21A-40m-4.'G3
(D6471slO)476B
General Library
University of California
Berkeley
YC 3154:
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY