Classics for Cnglisb Cabers EDITED BY WILLIAM KXIGHT, LL.D. PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY, UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS SPINOZA PBEFATOBY NOTE, THE materials which the author had prepared for this book were found greatly to exceed the limits assigned to it. He has therefore, besides other parts of his plan to which special reference need not here be made, been compelled to leave out the account of Spinoza's life and letters, and to confine the work to an examination of his philosophical system. This is the less to be regretted that the life has been so fully narrated in the recent works of Mr Pollock and Dr Martineau. These works contain, also, very able and elaborate expositions of the Spinozistic philosophy, but this book attempts to deal with that philosophy from a point of view different from that of either of these writers. CONTENTS. CHAP. PAGE INTRODUCTION, ... 1 I. THE ETHICAL MOTIVE OF SPINOZA*S PHILOSOPHY THE TREATISE ' CONCERNING THE IMPROVEMENT OF THE UNDERSTANDING,' . . .8 II. INFLUENCE OF PRECEDING WRITERS THE KABBALA, 36 III. THE MEDIEVAL JEWISH PHILOSOPHERS, . . 60 IV. GIORDANO BRUNO, . . . . .75 V. DESCARTES, . . . . . .91 VI. THE ' ETHICS ' ITS METHOD, .... 113 vii. SPINOZA'S STARTING-POINTSUBSTANCE, . . 130 VIII. SUBSTANCE AND ATTRIBUTES, . . .141 IX. MODES, ...... 157 X. INFINITE MODES, ..... 176 XI. THE NATURE AND ORIGIN OF THE MIND, . .188 XII. THE MORAL NATURE OF MAN, . . . 222 XIII. DOCTRINE OF THK EMOTIONS THE SELF-MAINTAIN- ING IMPULSE, ..... 231 XIV. INTELLIGENCE AND WILL, .... 240 XV. THE BONDAGE AND FREEDOM OK MAN, . . 259 XVI. IMMORTALITY AND THE BLESSED LIFE, . . 287 CONCLUSION, ...... 303 SPINOZA. INTRODUCTION. A GREAT system of philosophy is exposed to that kind of injustice which arises from the multiplicity of its interpreters, and from the fact that these interpreters are apt to contemplate and criticise it, not from the point of view of its author, but from their own. Critics and commentators of different schools and shades of opinion are naturally desirous to claim for their own views the sanction of a great writer's name, and uncon- sciously exercise their ingenuity in forcing that sanction when it is not spontaneously yielded. If any ambigui- ties or inconsistencies lurk in his doctrines, they are sure to be brought to light and exaggerated by the tendency of conflicting schools to fasten on what is most in ac- cordance with their own special principles. And even when a writer is on the whole self-consistent, it is pos- sible for a one-sided expositor so to arrange the lights and shadows, so to give prominence to what is incidental and throw into the shade what is essential, as to make him the advocate of ideas really antagonistic to his own. P. xn. A 2 Spinoza. 41 More, perhaps, than most systems of philosophy, that of Spinoza has been subjected to this sort of miscon- struction. Doctrines the most diversified and contra- dictory have been extracted from it. Pantheism and atheism, idealism and empiricism, nominalism and real- ism, a non-theistic naturalism as uncompromising as that of the modern evolutionist, and a supernaturalism or acosmism which makes as little of the world as the Maya of the Buddhist have all alike found a col- ourable sanction in Spinoza's teaching. A philoso- phy apparently as exact and logically coherent as the Geometry of Euclid or the Principia of Newton, has proved, in the hands of modern interpreters, as enig- matical as the utterances of the Jewish Kabbala or the mystical theosophy of the N"eo-Platonists. To the vision of one observer, it is so pervaded and dominated by the idea of the Infinite, that he can describe its author only as " a God-intoxicated man." To the acute inspection of another, the theistic element in it is only the decor- ous guise of a scientific empiricism a judicious but unmeaning concession to the theological prejudices of the author's time, or an incongruous dress of medieval scholasticism of which he had not been able wholly to divest himself. "Whilst some at least of those heterogeneous notions which have been fathered on Spinoza have no other ori- gin than the mistakes of his modern critics, there arc, it must be acknowledged, others which indicate real incon- sistencies. It is true, indeed, that the controversies of subsequent times may easily read into the language of an early writer decisions on questions of which he knew nothing. " Philosophers of an earlier age," it has been Apparent Inconsistencies. 3 said, " often contain, in a kind of implicit unity, different aspects or elements of truth, which in a subsequent time become distinguished from and opposed to each other." They make use, in a general and indeterminate way, of terms which later controversies have stamped Avith a special significance ; they may thus seem to answer ques- tions which they never put to themselves, and may easily be got to pronounce seemingly inconsistent opinions on problems which they never thought of solving. The eager controversialist catches at his pet phrase or mot Vnrdre, and hastily concludes that the old writer speaks in the distinctive tone of the modern polemic. But obviously the inconsistencies which thus arise are incon- sistencies only to the ear. It may be possible to get Spinoza to side in appearance with the modern evolution- ist or with the modern spiritualist, to make him an indi- vidualist after the fashion of Mill or Spencer, or a uni- versalist who speaks by anticipation with the voice of Schelling. But if such attempts are made, they are mere philosophical anachronisms. The problems which they seem to solve are problems which, when the supposed solutions were given, could not even be propounded. Yet it is impossible to ascribe the discordancy of Spinoza's modern interpreters only to the necessary ambiguity of their author's language. His philosophy is not a completely homogeneous product. It may rather be said to be the composite result of conflicting tendencies, neither of which is followed out to its utmost logical results. If we say in general terms that philo- sophy is the search for unity, the effort of thought to gain a point of view from which the contrast variously expressed by the terms the One and the Many, the Uni- 4 Spinoza. versa! and the Individual, the Infinite and the Finite, God and the World, shall be reconciled and harmonised, then \ve shall look in vain, in the philosophy of Spinoza, for one consistent solution of the problem. No solution can be regarded as satisfactory which suppresses or fails to do justice to either of the extremes, or which, though giving alternate expression to both, leaves them still in merely external combination without being reconciled for thought. Yet, at most, the latter result is all that the philosophy of Spinoza can be said to achieve. There are parts of his system such as the reduction of all finite individuals to modes or accidents of the absolute substance, and the assertion that all determination is negation in which the idea of the infinite is so empha- sised as to leave no place for the finite, or to reduce nature and man, all individual existences, to unreality and illusion. There are parts of his system, on the other hand such as his assertion that the individual is the real, his ascription to each finite thing of a rmiutn* in suo esse perseverandi, his rejection of general ideas as mere entia rationis, his polemic against teleology, his use of the term "Nature" as a synonym for "God" which seem to give to the finite an independent reality that leaves no room for the infinite, or reduces it to an expres- sion for the aggregate of finite things. Thus the system of Spinoza contains elements which resist any attempt to classify him either as a pantheist or an atheist, a natur- alist or supernaturalist, a nominalist or a realist. As he approaches the problem with which he deals from difl'er- ent sides, the opposite tendencies by which his mind is governed seem to receive alternate expression ; but to the last they remain side by side, with no apparent con- Underlying Unity. 5 sciousness of their disharmony, and with no attempt to mediate between them. But though it may be conceded that the philosophy of Spinoza is not self- consistent, or contains elements which, if not irreconcilable, are unreconciled, it does not follow that the task of the expositor of Spinoza is limited to what is involved in this concession. Inconsistency may arise not so much from incompatible principles as from defective logic. Contradictory elements may have been admitted into a system, not because its author looked at things from different and irreconcilable stand- points, but because he failed to see all that his funda- mental standpoint involved ; not because he started from different premisses, but because he did not carry out what was for him the only true premiss to its legitimate results. As moral defects assume an altogether different aspect according as they are regarded as the expression of a retrograding or of an advancing moral nature as willing divergences or as involuntary shortcomings from its own ideal so intellectual inconsistencies may mean more or less according to the attitude of the mind from which they proceed. It may be possible to discover, through all a man's thoughts, a dominant idea or general tendency, and to explain his inconsistencies as only un- conscious aberrations from it. It may even be possible to discern, underneath apparent contradictions or abrupt transitions from one point of view to another, an implicit unity of aim the guidance of thought by an unconscious logic towards a principle of reconciliation not yet fully grasped. And if any such dominant idea or implicit aim can be detected in a great writer, it cannot fail to throw light on the general character and bearing of his 6 Spinoza. speculations, and it may enable us to pronounce whether and to what extent in his seeming inconsistencies he is only unfaithful to himself, or inadequately representing his own idea. Now there are various conceivable indications by which we may be aided in detecting this undercurrent of tendency in the mind of a philosophical writer. We may be able, for instance, to learn something of the motive of his speculations to discover in his previous spiritual history what it was that constituted for him, so to speak, the original impulse towards philosophy, and that secretly guided the process by which intellectual satisfaction has been sought. Or again, we may know something of the helps which have been afforded him in the search for truth, of the studies on which his open- ing intelligence has been fed, of the sources from which he has derived inspiration, of the books or authorities which consciously or unconsciously have moulded the substance or form of his thoughts. Or finally, we may have the means of viewing his system in the making, of watching the working of his mind and the development of his ideas from their earlier and crader shape to the form which they have finally taken. We may be able thus to see which, if any, of the conflicting elements in his thought has gradually tended to prevail over the others, and to which of them therefore, though the victory to the last may be incomplete, the place of the ruling or characteristic principle must be ascribed. We may find it possible in this way to pronounce of the blots which disfigure his system in its final form, that they are not radical inconsistencies, but only irrelevances or excrescences foreign to its essential character. Interpretation of his System. 7 we are not without sucli helps to the understand- ing of the Spinozistic philosophy. In the first place, we possess in the preface to the treatise ' Concerning the Improvement of the Understanding ' an axitobiographical fragment in which Spinoza narrates what may be termed the origin and development of his spiritual life, and from which we gain a clear insight into the motive and genesis of his philosophical system. In the second place, we have information, direct and indirect, as to Spinoza's early studies in philosophy. From his own testimony, from the internal evidence supplied by his writings, and from other sources, we know something as to the authors he had read, the intellectual atmosphere in which he grew up, the authorities which may have influenced the formation of his opinions. Lastly, we have in Spinoza's earlier works the means of tracing the gradual develop- ment of those ideas which took their final systematised form in the ' Ethics.' Especially in the ' Treatise con- cerning God and ^lan,' which has been brought to light only in our own time, we possess what may be regarded as an early study for the ' Ethics,' embracing the same subjects and dealing with the same fundamental ideas, but presenting them in a cruder and less coherent form, and exhibiting the conflicting tendencies of the later work in harder and more unmodified opposition to each other. From these various sources some help may be derived towards the right apprehension of Spinoza's philosophy and the explanation of its apparent ambi- guities and inconsistencies. CHAPTER I. THE ETHICAL MOTIVE OF SPINOZA'S PHILOSOPHY III i: TREATISE 'CONCERNING THE IMPROVEMENT OF THE UNDERSTANDING.' THE impulse towards philosophy Avas not in Spinoza's mind a purely intellectual one. His philosophy is the logical sequel to that of Descartes, but the Cartesian philosophy only supplied or suggested a dialectic for con- victions that were the independent growth of his own moral and spiritual experience. He was prompted to seek after a method of knowledge because primarily he sought after spiritual rest. It Avas the consciousness that the dissatisfaction and disquietude which the ordi- nary desires and passions engender had their ultimate source in a false view of the world in other words, that the contemplation of the Avorld from the point of vieAv of the senses and the imagination bred only perturbation and unrest which led him to ask himself Avhether that point of A r ieAv is not an illusory one, and Avhether it is possible to penetrate beneath the shoAvs of things to tlu-ir hidden essence. Xor is this account of the origin of Spinoza's philosophy a mere conjecture. The introduc- tion to the unfinished treatise above named is, as AVC Motive of Ms Philosophy. 9 have said, a kind of spiritual autobiography, in which the author explains to us what were the moral difficulties and aspirations in which his speculative inquiries origin- ated. He tells us what is the view of the true end and goal of human existence to which his own experience had led him, and he points out the means by which he con- ceived that that end could be attained. His philosophy took its rise, he tells us, not primarily in the search for intellectual satisfaction, but in the endeavour to discover some true and abiding object of love, something in find- ing which he would find a perfect and eternal joy a joy which could not be found in the ordinary objects of human desire in riches, honour, the pleasures of appe- tite and sense. All these objects experience proved to be deceptive and inconstant, difficult and uncertain of attainment, and when attained bringing only disappoint- ment and disquietude. " Our happiness," he says, " depends entirely on the qual- ity of the objects to which we are attached by love. For, on account of that which is not loved, no strifes will ever arise, no sorrow if it perishes, no envy if others possess it, no fear, no hatred, no perturbation of mind all of which come upon us in the love of things which are perishable, as are all those things of which we have spoken. But love to a thing which is eternal and infinite feeds the mind only with joy a joy that is unmingled with any sorrow ; that therefore we should eagerly desire and with all our strength seek to obtain." l The end of all human endeavour, therefore that in which consists the perfection and blessedness of our nature is union by love with an infinite and eternal 1 De Int. Emend. , L 10 Spinoza. object. But love, according to Spinoza, rests on know- ledge ; or rather there is a point of view in which, for him, feeling and intelligence, knowing and being, are identified. The sure and only Avay to attain the end AVO seek is to knoxv things as they really are, to disabuse our minds of error and illusion ; and for this purpose what is chiefly needed is a discipline of the intelligence, " a method," as he expresses it, " of curing the understand- ing and of so purifying it that it may knoAV things as Avell as possible and withoiit error." But all knoAvledge, he repeats, has a value for him only as it is directed to one end and goal viz., the attainment of that highest human perfection of Avhich he had spoken and every- thing in the sciences which does not bring us nearer to that end he Avill reject as useless. The task, therefore, Avhich in this treatise he proposes to himself is the de- A'ising, not of a method of knoAvledge or organon of the sciences in general, but of a means of attaining that kind of knoAvledge, or of apprehending all things in that aspect of them, Avhich will lead to the attainment of moral and spiritual perfection. It is unnecessary, for our present purpose, to follow out in detail the successive steps by which Spinoza Avorks out his conception of the true method of knowledge. The general drift of the treatise may be said to be this, to set before us an ideal of true knoAvledge, and to point out the Avay in Avhich that ideal is to be realised. In contrast Avith the kind of knoAvledge Avhich con- stitutes the content of our ordinary unreflecting ex- perience, that knoAvledge Avhich can be said to be real and adequate must be intuitive or self-eA'idencing ; it must apprehend its objects in their unity or their rela- Notes of Tme, Knoidcdge. 11 tion to each other as parts of one absolute whole ; and it must see them in their right order, or in their relation to the first principle of knowledge, so that the order of our thoughts shall " correspond to the exemplar of nature," or represent the real order of things. The knowledge of the ordinary, unreflecting consciousness is, in the first place, merely second-hand and unintelligent, it is derived from hearsay, or from loose and unsifted experience. True knowledge, in contrast with this, must be that in which the mind is in immediate relation to its object, in which truth is seen in its own light, or, as Spinoza ex- presses it, " in which a thing is perceived solely from its own essence, or from the knowledge of its proximate cause." Ordinary knowledge, again, is disconnected and fragmentary, it looks at things apart from each other, or in the accidental order in which they are presented to the -common observer of nature, or connected with each other only by arbitrary associations. In contrast with this, true knowledge is that which breaks down the false isolation and independence which popiilar imagination gives to individual objects; it regards the universe as a whole, in which no object exists for itself, or can be understood save in its relations to other objects and to the whole. It discerns, or seeks to discern, the real re- lations of things, or what is the same, the rational rela- tions of the ideas of things ; and therefore it is fatal to all such connections or combinations of ideas as rest on accident or arbitrary association. For the same reason, lastly, true knowledge is that which not only sees its objects as related to each other, but sees them in that definite relation of ordered sequence which is determined ultimately by the first principle out of which they 12 Spinoza. spring. There are certain ideas on which other ideas rest. Spinoza rejects the "universals" of scholastic nietaphysic as mere entia rationis or fictions of the imagination. Yet we are not left to the impossible task of attempting to collect or string together in thought the infinite multiplicity of finite and changeable things. There are certain ideas which come to us in the place of universals, and which gather up o\ir knowledge into that unity which by means of the fictitious universals was sought after. " There are," he tells us in language the precise significance of which we cannot at present ex- amine, certain " fixed and eternal things, which, though they are individual, yet on account of their omnipresence and all-comprehending power become to us as universals, or as genera in the definitions of individual changeable things, and as the proximate causes of all things." l Finally, there is one highest idea, that of " the most perfect Being," which is the source and explanation of all other ideas, as it represents the source and origin of all things. That knowledge therefore alone can be termed adequate which proceeds from and is moulded by this supreme or central idea. " That our mind," says he, " may thoroughly reflect the exemplar of nature, it must evolve all ideas from that which represents the origin and source of all nature, so- that that idea may appear to be the source of all other ideas." 2 Such, then, is Spinoza's theory of knowledge : how is it to be reduced to practice 1 What, in other words, is the true method of knowledge ] AYhat Spinoza says in answer to this question in the present treatise amounts to little more than this, that we should endeavour to 1 De Int. Emend., xiv. - Ibid., vii. Method of Knowledge. 1 3 become possessed of what he calls " true ideas," and that we should by means of the highest of all ideas seek to reduce them to unity, or endeavour " so to order and concatenate our ideas that our mind shall represent objectively (i.e., in thought) the formality (i.e., objec- tive reality) of nature, both as to the whole and as to its parts." l Spinoza does not atttempt here to investigate the rela- tion of mind to nature, of thought to its object. He as- sumes that a true idea is something different from its object, the idea of a circle from an actual circle, the idea,, of the body from the body itself : but he takes for granted that the former agrees with or adequately represents the latter. To verify a true idea we need not go beyond itself. " Certitude is nothing but the objective essence (the idea) itself ; the way in which we perceive the formal essence is itself certitude." 2 "NVe may, indeed, have a reflex knowledge of our ideas make one idea the object of a second idea, or, in modern phraseology, be not only conscious but self-conscious. Yet, in order to the attain- ment of knowledge, it is no more necessary to know that we know, than, in order to know the essence of a triangle, it is necessary to know the essence of a circle. But though it is possible to have true ideas without reflecting on them, and even to reason correctly without a know- ledge of logic or the principles of reasoning ideas, both in themselves and in their relations, being their own evidence yet this does not hinder that, for lack of reflection and by reason of various prejudices, people often mistake error for truth and go Avrong in their reasoning, so that " it seldom happens that in the inves- 1 De Int. Emeud., xii. 2 Ibid., vi 14 Spinoza. tigation of nature they proceed in proper order." Hence arises the need for method, " which is nothing but re- flected knowledge or the idea of the idea." 1 What this means is that we do not need to go outside of thought in search of a criterion of truth, inasmuch as this would virtually be the demand to excogitate a method of thought before we begin to think, to learn to swim before we go into the water. We cannot criti- cise the forms of thought without using them. Ideas must, so to speak, criticise themselves. In reflecting on them, making them objects of consciousness, they determine their own nature and limits, and so become capable of being used as the instruments of further knowledge. " True ideas," Spinoza says, constitute themselves " the inborn instruments of knowledge " which the understand- ing makes for itself by its own native force. Having grasped a true idea, we have only to direct the mind's oper- ations so as to make the given true idea " a norm accord- ing to which we shall understand all tilings." Method, in short, consists in bringing ideas to self-consciousness, and then in using them as the principles of investigation. Having a true idea such as, c.ij., that of Causality you become conscious of it, understand and define it ; and thenceforward it is no longer used at random, unintel- ligently, but becomes a principle of method or a guide in future inquiries. Knowledge thus acquired will possess, so far, the characteristics which have been laid down as constituting the ideal of knowledge ; it will rest on ideas or principles which are their own evidence, and it will, instead of a mere collection or combination of things 1 De lut. Eniend., vii. Unity of Knmvledge. 15 arbitrarily associated, consist of parts related to each other by links of reason or necessary thought. But there is a further and more important element which method must include ere it can be adequate to the whole field of knowledge. Knowledge must remain imperfect until we can contemplate all things from the point of view of their absolute unity. True ideas may serve as provisional instruments of thought ; but their main use is that we may, like a workman who uses ruder implements to construct more perfect ones, fashion by means of them " other intellectual instruments, by which the mind acquires a farther power of investi- gation, and so proceeds till it gradually attains the summit of wisdom." x Each true idea, Spinoza seems to teach, furnishes us with a term of thought which serves so far to correct the false independence which imagination gives to individual objects ; but that idea itself needs to have its individuality dissolved in a higher conception. As all things in nature "have commerce with each other, i.e., are produced by and produce others " are, in other words, reciprocally causes and effects so each idea or term of thought is only a focus of relations, a transition point in a systematic whole ; and ideas rise in importance according as they extend over a wider portion of the realm of knowledge. But if this be so, that knowledge must still be imperfect which stops short of the highest and most comprehen- sive idea in this intellectual hierarchy. Xot only must individual objects yield up their false independence, but ideas themselves must surrender in succession their isolated authority, until we reach that which is " the 1 De Int. Emend., vi. 16 fountain and source of all other ideas" the idea, as Spinoza terms it, of "the most perfect Being." " That method will be good which shows how the niind is to be directed according to the norm of a given true idea. Moreover, since the relation between two ideas is the same with the relation between the formal essences (objects) of these ideas, it follows that that reflective knowledge, which is that of the idea of the most perfect Being, will be more excellent than the reflective knowledge of other ideas ; that is, that method will be the most perfect which shows how the mind is to be directed according to the norm of the given idea of the most perfect Being." x " If we proceed as little as possible abstractly, and begin as soon as possible with the first elements i.e., with the source and origin of nature we need not fear deception. . . . No confusion is to be apprehended in regard to the idea of it (the origin of nature), if only we have the norm of truth, as already shown. For this is a Being single, infinite i.e., all being, and beyond which there is no being." 2 " As regards order," again Spinoza writes, " and that we may arrange and unite all our perceptions, it is required that, as soon as it can be done and reason demands, we in- quire whether there is any being, and, at the same time, of what sort, which is the cause of all things, as its objective essence is also the cause of all our ideas ; and then will our mind, as we have said, reproduce nature as completely as possible ; for it will contain objectively both its essence and its order and unity." 3 "\Vhat then, the question arises, are we to understand by this " most perfect Being," " Being, single, infinite, all-embracing," the idea of which constitutes, according to Spinoza, the first principle of knowledge ? Is it something above nature, outside of the cosmos of finite 1 De Int. Eiueud., vii. 2 Ibid., ix. 3 Ibid., xiv. " The Most Perfect Seiny" 17 things and relations, though itself the source or cause of all things 1 Or is it, though the highest, only one of the elements which constitute nature, the first principle of the system of related phenomena, but itself essential- ly part of that system ? Or again, is it only a synonym for Mature, the totality of individual things and beings, and is this identification of nature with " the most per- fect Being " merely a concession to theological prejudices, whilst really nothing more is meant than that the uni- verse is to be conceived of as an ordered system of things 1 According to one of the ablest of Spinoza's recent ex- positors, " the idea of the most perfect Being includes, if it is not equivalent to, the belief that the whole of nature is one and uniform," which belief is "the very first principle of science." "In knowing the 'most perfect Being,' " he adds, " the mind also knows itself as part of the universal order and at one with it, therein finding, as we have to learn elsewhere, the secret of man's happiness and freedom. What more Spinoza may have meant is doubtful, that he meant this much is certain." 1 Spinoza, he further explains, whilst "at- tached by an intellectual passion to the pursuit of exact science," was also " attached by race and tradition to the Hebrew sentiment of a one and only Supreme Power ; " and in this he seems to find the explanation of the fact that Spinoza clothed the purely scientific idea of the unity and uniformity of nature in the theo- logical guise of " the most perfect Being." Spinoza, he tells us, " follows in form and even in language the examples made familiar by theologians and philoso- phers under theological influence and pressure, who had i Pollock's Spinoza, p. 136. P. XII, B 18 Spinoza. undertaken to prove the existence of a being apart from and above the universe. He does not simply break off from theological speculation, and seek to establish philo- sophy on an independent footing ; he seems intent on showing that theological speculation itself, when reason is once allowed free play, must at last purge itself of all anthropomorpliism and come round to the scientific view. Spinoza does not ignore theology, but provides an euthanasia for it." l Many of Spinoza's other mod- ern interpreters have convinced themselves on various grounds that Spinoza's system is one of pure naturalism, that his highest principle does not go beyond the con- ception of an all-embracing, all-dominating, but uncon- scious nature-force, and that we should not misconstrue him if we substituted the word " Xature " for " God," wherever the latter occurs in his philosophy. It cannot, we think, be questioned that the view taken by these writers is so far true that in Spinoza's system " theological speculation has," in Mr Pollock's graphic phrase, "purged itself of anthropomorphism." Spinoza's God is certainly not the supramundane poten- tate or "magnified man" of popular thought, or even the " all-wise Creator and Governor " of natural the- ology. Whatever else the idea of " the most perfect Being " means, it is an idea which is supposed to consti- tute a principle, and the highest principle, of knowledge at once its own evidence and the evidence or explana- tion of the whole finite world. But an outside Creator or Contriver is a notion which explains nothing. Xot only does it reduce the God who is placed outside the world to something finite, but it is essentially dualistic. 1 Pollock's Spinoza, p. 166. No Anthropomorphic God. 19 The link between God and the world, according to this notion, is a purely arbitrary one. To find in God the explanation of the world implies that the existence of the world and all that is in it is traceable to something in the nature of God, and not to His mere arbitrary will or poAver. A cause which thought can recognise as such is one which contains in it the reason and necessity of the effect, and which reveals itself in the effect. But a personified cause, which of its mere will produces an effect it might have refrained from producing, is an impossible conception. In such a conception cause and effect stand apart, and the gap is not filled up for thought by the interposition of an arbitrary, omnipotent will. To find in God the first principle of all being and of all knowledge implies a relation between the prin- ciple and that which flows from it between God and the world such that, in one point of view, God would not be God without it; and on the other hand, the world would not be what it is, would be reduced to unreality or nonentity, without God. Now this, as we have seen, is what Spinoza doe>, or attempts to do. The " most perfect Being," whatever else the phrase means, is a Being the idea of which is the first prin- ciple of knowledge, the key to the meaning of the whole system of being. Without this central principle, finite things and beings have no existence other than the illusory existence and individuality which imagina- tion ascribes to them are mere fictions and unrealities. And on the other hand, to anticipate Spinoza's favourite illustration, from this fundamental principle all things folloAV as necessarily as from the conception of a triangle follow the equality of its angles to two right angles, and 20 Spinoza. all its other properties. If, therefore, Spinoza's system can only be redeemed from naturalism by the idea of an anthropomorphic God the deus ex machina of popular theology a pure naturalistic system it is. The exclusion of the notion of an anthropomorphic God does not, however, of necessity reduce a system of phil- osophy to pure naturalism. A principle which explains nature is not therefore, to say the least, a part of nature. It is possible to derive from such a principle all that renders the facts of nature intelligible without regarding it as itself one of these facts. The definition of nature may indeed be so widened as to include in it the idea or principle which constitutes the world an ordered or rational system; but in another and truer sense that principle may, and properly must, be contemplated as something prior to and above nature. The treatise be- fore us is, as above said, an unfinished work, and it does not contain except inferentially any explanation of what its author meant by the idea of the "most perfect Being." But if we take into view the general drift and intention of the work if, in other words, we consider the motive from which it starts, and the general bearing of its theory of knowledge, we shall be led, I think, to see in Spinoza's "most perfect Being" something very different, at once from crude supernaturalism, and from the pure naturalism with which it has been sought to identify it. 1. The knowledge of the " most perfect Being " as the constitutive principle of the world is the formal expres- sion of the result to which Spinoza was led by his search for that spiritual satisfaction and rest Avhich he could not find in " the things that are changeable and God and Nature. 21 perishable." His examination of the principles of know- ledge had given theoretical justification to his dissatis- faction with the ordinary objects of human desire, by proving that these objects have no reality save the ficti- tious and illusory reality which imagination lends to them. And the presumption with which he started, and which indeed constituted the implicit ground of his discontent with these objects viz., that there must exist " something eternal and infinite, love to which would fill the mind with joy and with joy alone," now finds verification in the rational idea of a "most perfect Being," " a Being single, infinite, and beyond which there is no being." Now, however intense may have been Spinoza's " intellectual devotion to the pursuit of exact science," the process just described is, we think, one Avhich that formula does not cover. If it did, then the attitude of mind to which, under whatever modifi- cations, the designation " religion " has been given, must be something essentially indistinguishable from "the passion for exact science." For, however foreign to Spinoza's nature much that passes under the name of religion must be pronounced to be, his account of the mental experience that constituted the impulse to spec- ulative inquiry is that of a process in which the very essence of religion may be said to lie. If we pass be- yond the " fetichism " of barbarous races, the mere in- discriminating ascription of mysterious powers to ma- terial objects (which is as irrelevant to the religious history of the world as the other phenomena of savage life are to the history of morality and civilisation), the religious life of man may be said to have its root in what, for want of a better description, may be called 22 Spinoza. Pantheism. The dawn of religious feeling may be traced to the impression which experience forces upon us of the unsubstantial character of the world on which we look and of which we form a part. In different ways this sense of the illusoriness of the world may come to different men and different races, according to their less or greater depth of nature. The apparent shifting of the outward scene, the lapse of time, the impossibility of staying the passing moment to question what it means, the uncertainty of life and the insecurity of its possessions, may be to one what to another is its inner counterpart, the changing of our opinions, feelings, desires, which, even if the world remained steadfast, would perpetually make and unmake it for us. Or again, the sense of the illusoriness of life deepens into weariness and disgust or into a sense of shame and re- morse, in the man who reflects on himself and feels himself the sport of it, who has detected the vanity of his desires and hopes, yet is powerless to emancipate himself from their dominion. Now it is this sense of the unreality of the world regarded from the point of view of ordinary experience which not merely gives rise to the longing for some fixed and permanent reality, "some Life continuous, Being unexposed to the blind walk of mortal accident," but is in itself, in a sense, already the implicit recognition of the existence of such a Being. Arguments from "design," which conclude from the existence of finite things to a God conceived of after the analogy of a maker of machines, are not a true expression of the natural history of religion. Such arguments are only the afterthought of an imperfect philosophy. It is not the reality, but the unreality, of The Process of Religion. 23 the finite world that gives rise to the consciousness of God. It is not from the affirmation, but from the negation, of the finite that the human spirit rises to the conception of the infinite. And when we reflect on what this process, this elevation of spirit means, we discern that what is second in time is really, though implicitly, first in thought. The very consciousness of a limit is the proof that we are already beyond it God is not the conclusion of a syllogism from the finite world, but the prius or presupposition which reveals its presence in the very sense of our finitude and that of the world to which we belong. The impression that comes to us first in time is that the world is nothing ; but that impression would have no existence or mean- ing if the thought really though latently first were not this God is all. It is not, of course, meant that the process we have described is one which all who experi- ence it experience in the same manner. Like all nor- mal elements of human experience it varies, as we have said, with the varying character and the wider or nar- rower culture of individuals and races. In the deeper and more reflective natures it manifests itself chiefly in the consciousness of an inner life other and larger than the life of sense, of a self that transcends the natural desires. With widening experience of life this con- sciousness deepens, since wider experience only furnishes new materials for the contrast between the multiplicity of impressions and the self that is identified with none of them. Advancing intellectual and moral culture brings with it the profounder consciousness of an in- finite possibility within us, of being greater than our sensations and desires, of capacities to which the out- 24 Spinoza. ward life is not adequate. This consciousness, rightly interpreted, is a negative which involves a positive. It is the revelation in us of a something that is not of us, of a perfect, by comparison with which the imperfection of ourselves and the whole complex of finite existences is disclosed. Reflecting on the meaning of the discord between itself and its desires, the consciousness of a thirst that is unquenchable by the world becomes to such a nature the presumptive proof of " an infinite and eternal object, love to which would fill the mind with unmingled and abiding joy." Now if there be any truth in the foregoing analysis of the movement of mind of which we speak, it is obviously one which cannot be identified with the processes of physical science, and the result of which could never be generated by empirical observation of the facts and phenomena of the world. It may be if there be no other dialectic than the logic of the sciences, it un- doubtedly is a movement which reason does not justify, inasmuch as it puts more into the conclusion than is contained in the premisses, or rather, as we have seen, in- asmuch as its conclusion is the negative of the premiss with which it seems to start. If it evaporates anything as "a dogmatic dream," it is not God but nature. The object to which it concludes is not one which is con- tained in, or can by any process of generalisation be ex- tracted from the facts of nature, or identified with its "laws of coexistence and succession." If scientific ex- perience be experience of change and laws of change, by no straining can this be identified with an experience which is that of an object beyond all change or possibility of change. At any rate, logical or illogical, scientific or Relation to the Infinite. 25 unscientific, the attitude of mind which Spinoza records as that which constituted for him the impulse to specu- lative inquiry is identical, or in close analogy, with that which in the history of mankind has been the origin and secret nerve of what we mean by the word "religion." 2. But the negation of the finite is not the last step in the process of which I have spoken. Neither religion, nor philosophy which seeks to develop the logic of re- ligion, can rest content with an idea of God from, which no explanation of the finite world can be derived. Even if the independent existence of finite things be an illu- sion, the idea of God must contain in it a reason if only for their illusory existence. The shadow, though it be but a shadow, must have its reason in the substance it reflects. To say that the infinite is the negation of the finite, implies that there is in the infinite at least a negative relation to the finite. But it implies something more than this. The recognition of the inadequacy of finite objects is not only the expression of the implicit consciousness of an infinite object, but also of my relation to that object. It is through something in me that I am capable of pronouncing the verdict of reality and un- reality. If therefore, on the one hand, I belong to the finite world which, as an independent reality, is negated, on the other hand, there is a side of my nature in which I belong or am inwardly related to that infinite and eternal reality which negates or annuls it. If I deny my own reality as part of the finite world, I in one and the same act reassert it as essentially related to God. It is this which explains what may be termed the positive side of that mental experience which formed the starting- point of Spinoza's investigations. The inadequacy or 26 Spinoza. unreality of the finite was to him an implicit revelation, not only of an infinite and eternal object, but also of himself as in essential relation to it. And what he was thus implicitly conscious of he seeks to make explicit. It is, we think, from this point of view that we must interpret Spinoza's attempt partially fulfilled only in the fragmentary treatise before us, burdened with con- flicting elements even in the later work in which it finds systematic embodiment to reaffirm and explain the reality of the finite world in and through the idea of the infinite. But though in the present work the thought which forms the fundamental principle of his system is left undeveloped, it is possible, from the general drift and bearing of the treatise, to divine in some measure the meaning he attached to that principle, and the direction in Avhich its development must lie. And, considered in this light, it is impossible, I venture to say, to find in Spinoza's philosophy only that pure naturalism with which it has been identified, or to regard the meaning of his " idea of the most perfect Being," as exhausted by any such formula as "the unity and uniformity of nature." It is no doubt possible, as already said, so to define "Xature" as that it shall include both finite and in- finite, the multiplicity of individual things, and the principle which gives them unity. If we mean by the universe all reality, then to say that there is nothing outside of it, that nature or the universe is all, is only an identical proposition. Moreover, as we have seen, nothing can be more un- questionable than that Spinoza's God was no transcen- dent dam ex machina, existing apart from the world, or " Uhiversals." 27 connected with it only by the unintelligible bond of an arbitrary creative act. Again, it may be conceded that we do not as a matter of fact begin by forming a con- ception of God as the principle of all things, and then, by a separate mental act or process of thought, bring this conception to bear 011 the world of finite, individual existences. Observation and experience are, it may be granted, the only instruments of knowledge in this sense, that the principle which gives unity to knowledge is grasped, not apart from, but as inseparably implicated with, the facts and phenomena observed or experienced. But the real and only important question is, whether it is Spinoza's doctrine that the individual, the things of out- ward observation, or the world as a collection or sum of finite existences, are the sole constituents of knowledge whether there is not involved in real knowledge or knowledge of realities, a principle of unity distinguish- able from the manifold of phenomena, a universal dis- tinguishable from the sum of particulars, an infinite and eternal distinguishable from the finite and changeable, not given by it, logically prior to it. If this question be answered in the affirmative, it matters not whether you give the name God or Xature to the universe ; in neither case is Spinoza's system a pure naturalism. Now it might seem, at first sight, to preclude any such answer that, for Spinoza, individual things are, in one sense, the only realities, and that he regards general ideas or " universals " as one of the chief sources of error and confusion. " When anything," says he, 1 " is conceived abstractly, as 1 De Int. Emend., ix. 28 Spinoza. are all universals, it is always apprehended in the. understand- ing in a wider sense than its particulars can really exist in nature. Further, since in nature there are many things the difference of which is so slight as almost to escape the under- standing, it may easily happen, if we think abstractly, that we should confuse them." And again : " We ought never, when we are inquiring into the nature of things, to draw any conclusions from abstract notions, and we should carefully guard against confounding things which are only in the under- standing with those which actually exist." 1 Whilst, however, here as elsewhere, Spinoza wages a constant polemic against the " universals " or abstract notions of scholastic metaphysics, and treats as nugatory any conclusions that rest on such premisses, this by no means implies that he excludes from knowledge every universal element every element other than that which is generated by observation of particular facts. The very context from which the foregoing passages have been taken renders any such inference impossible. His denunciation of the abstractions of scholasticism is introduced expressly to contrast these false, with Avhat he deemed true, universals. Deception arises, he tells us, in a passage already quoted, from conceiving things too abstractly. " But," he adds, " such deception need never be dreaded by us if we proceed as little as possible abstractly, and begin as soon as possible with the first elements, that is, with the source and origin of nature. And as regards the knowledge of the origin of nature, we need have no fear of confounding it with abstractions. . . . For, since the origin of nature, as we shall see in the sequel, can neither be conceived abstractly, 1 De Int. Emend., xii. True and False Universals. 29 nor can be extended more widely in the understanding than it actually is, nor has any resemblance to things that are changeable, there is no need to fear any confusion in regard to the idea of it, if only we possess the norm of truth, and this is a being single, infinite, i.e., it is all being and beyond which there is no being." 1 And again he says : "It is to be remarked that by the series of causes and of real en- tities, I do not understand the series of individual change- able things, but only the series of fixed and eternal things. For the series of individual changeable things it would be impossible for human weakness to attain to . . . because of the infinite circumstances in one and the same thing of which each may be the cause of the existence or non-existence of the thing ; since the existence of things has no connection with their essence, or, as I have just said, is not an eternal truth. It is, however, not at all necessary to know their series, since the essences of changeable individual things are not derivable from their series or order of existing, for this gives us nothing but external denominations, relations, or, at most, circumstances which are foreign to their inmost essence. The last is only to be sought from fixed and eternal things, and at the same time from the laws that are inscribed in these things as their true codes, according to which all individuals both take place and are ordered ; yea, these changeable things depend so intimately and essentially, so to speak, on those fixed things, that without them they can neither exist nor be conceived. Hence those fixed and eternal things, although they are individuals, yet on account of their omnipresence and all-comprehending power, are to us as universals or as genera of definitions of the individual changeable things, and as the proximate causes of all things." 2 From these and other passages in the treatise it is impossible, we think, to avoid the conclusion that Spinoza's "nominalism" did not imply, either that indi- 1 De Int. Emeiid. , ix. - Ibid. , xiv. 30 Spinoza. viduals, finite objects, the facts and phenomena of empirical observation, are the only realities, or that there are not universals other than the abstract essences of scholasticism which constitute a necessary element of all true knowledge. In the first place, when we ask what are the individuals of which it can be affirmed that they constitute the only realities, it is to be con- sidered that the individuality or independence which ordinary observation ascribes to particular objects is no real individuality. Ordinary observation contemplates things under the external conditions of space and time, and so it can begin and end anywhere. It conceives as an independent reality whatever it can picture to itself as such. Even scientific observation does not go beyond the conception of the system of things as a multiplicity of separate substances, each endowed with its own qualities, and all acting and reacting on each other according to invariable laAvs. But when we examine more closely what this so-called individuality means, we perceive that it is a mere fictitious isolation or inde- pendence, which it is the function of advancing know- ledge to dissipate. Objects are not abstract things or substances, each with a number of qualities attached to it. The qualities by which we define the nature of a thing are in reality nothing else than its relations to other things. Take away all such relations, and the thing itself ceases to have any existence for thought. It is the qualities or relations which constitute its definite existence : the substance in which they are supposed to inhere, and which remains one and the same through all the manifoldness of its properties, if detached from them would have no meaning. At most, it would be but a True Individuality. 31 name for the bare abstraction of being or existence ; and when we think away the predicates or properties, the sxibstance vanishes with them. But if the qualities by which we determine any object are simply its relations to other objects, then, inasmuch as each individual object is directly or indirectly related to all other objects, com- pletely to determine any individual, to see what it really is, is to see it in its relation to all other objects. An object cannot be perfectly individualised until it is per- fectly universalised. In other words, knowledge of it in its complete individuality would be knowledge of it as determined by the whole universe of which it is a part. True knowledge, therefore, does not begin with individuals regarded as mere isolated singular things ; nor is it the apprehension of the universe as a collection of such individuals, nor any generalisation got from them by a process of abstraction. In so far as it is knowledge of the individual, it is of the individual which has be- come more and more specialised by each advancing step in the progress of science, by every new and higher con- ception which exhibits it in new and hitherto unobserved relations ; and the ideal of true knowledge cannot stop short of the conception of each individual in its relation to the highest universal, or seen in the light of the whole system of being in its unity. It is this conception of individuality to which Spinoza points when he speaks of individuals as the only realities. For him the indi- viduals of ordinary observation are as much unrealities, figments of the imagination, as the abstract essences of the schoolmen, they are " the individual, changeable things the existence of which has no connection with their essence," and the " accidental series " of which " it 32 Spinozc:. is not at all necessary to know." The true " essences " of individuals are to be discerned only in their relation to what he calls "fixed and eternal things and their laws, according to which all individuals exist and are ordered," and "without which they can neither exist nor be conceived," and, above all, in their relation to that which is the " highest norm of truth, a being single, infinite, and all - comprehending." So far, therefore, from asserting that knowledge begins with individuals regarded as the only realities, he tells us that " that method of knowledge would be the most perfect in which we should have an idea of the most perfect Being, to the knowledge of which, therefore, it becomes us as soon as possible to attain," and that our mind can only reflect the exemplar of nature by deriving all its ideas from that which reflects the source and fountain of nature i.e., the "idea of the most perfect Being." In the second place, it is implied in what has now been said that Spinoza's " nominalism " does not involve the denial of universals other than the abstractions of scholasticism, as constituting a necessary principle or factor of true knowledge. What are these universals, and especially, what is that "idea of the most perfect Being " which is the highest universal or first principle of knowledge ? We have seen that a recent expositor of Spinoza finds nothing more in it than the idea of " the unity and uniformity of nature." Even if we could suppose that by the " idea of the most perfect Being " Spinoza meant nothing more than the scientific conception of the unity and uniformity of nature, the supposition would be fatal to the assertion of his " thorough-going nominalism." Xominalism re- Uniformity of Nature. 33 individual substances as the only realities, and nature as, at most, a name for the collection or aggregate of such substances. But the unity and uniformity of nature is the first principle of all science. All scientific investigation proceeds on the tacit assumption that nature is not a chaos, but a system of invariable coex- istences and successions constituting a self-consistent whole. " It is an assured fact that discoveries are not made without belief in the nature of things, by which I mean the sure trust that under all diversity of appear- ances there is a constant and sufficient order, that there is no maze without a clue. Belief in the nature of things is the mainspring of all science and the condition of all sound thinking. " l But if this be so, it seems beyond question that a belief which is presupposed in all scientific observation and experience cannot itself be a product or part of that experience. It is from observa- tion and experience that we learn what are the particular sequences of phenomena in nature, what are the par- ticular causes or conditions of particular effects ; but the idea or principle of uniform sequence with which we start cannot itself be learnt from experience. To the unreflecting mind nature seems to reveal its own unity and uniformity. The objective world is a ready-made system, and the only function of intelligence is to observe and investigate what is already presented to it in its complete reality. Xature in its unity and uni- formity is given to us, ready to be taken up into our experience ; the facts and phenomena and their unity and uniformity are things of the same order, and our knowledge of both comes from the same source. "We 1 Pollock's Spinoza, p. 142. P. XIL C 34 Spinoza. have before us a world organised into unity, and then our consciousness simply reproduces it. But a little reflection teaches us that this is not the true account of the process of knowledge. Our knowledge of nature as an ordered system implies a principle which is not natural, and which cannot be observed as we observe the facts of nature. Experience of difference implies already the presence of a principle of unity, experience of suc- cessions or changes the presence of a principle that is constant or self-identical. A process of change cannot be conceived to generate a consciousness of itself, still less to generate a consciousness of change according to a uniform method. In order to the minimum, of scien- tific experience, the observation of a single sequence of related facts, there is presupposed in the observer the consciousness that the relation is an unalterable one, that the same conditions will and must ever give the same result ; in other words, there is presupposed the idea of uniformity. But that which is the prim or pre- condition of all knowledge of the facts of nature cannot be itself one of those facts or the result of the observa- tion of any number of such facts. The idea or prin- ciple, therefore, which is the necessary condition of all knowledge of nature, without which there could be for us no nature, and in the light of which all particular facts or objects are known this, though it is not a uni- versal, like the abstract essences of scholastic realism, may be said, in Spinoza's language, " on account of its omnipresence and all-comprehending power, to take the place of a universal, or a genus of definition of indi- vidual changeable things." But by the idea of " the most perfect Being," can we Presuppositions of Knowledge. 35 suppose that Spinoza meant no more than that of " the unity and uniformity of nature " ] Or if he did mean something more, if the latter formula does not exhaust the meaning of the former or of the equivalent expres- sion, "a Being single, infinite, and all-comprehending," can we form any conjecture as to what that something more is 1 The answer to this question would carry us beyond the contents of the work before us. This much at least we can gather from it, that Spinoza's speculative inquiries originated in his moral and spiritual aspirations, and that in both his endeavour was to rise above the illusoriness and unreality of the finite. The unrest in- separable from desires and passions that point only to finite and changeable things is itself implicitly the aspiration after an infinite and eternal object, in which the spirit can find perfect satisfaction and rest. And true knowledge, following in the steps of aspiration, discovers to us the unreality of the world as it appears to sense and imagination, and has for its aim to rise above the finite and to grasp that primary idea or first principle which is the source of all other ideas, in the light of which the fragmentary, contingent, confused aspect of things will vanish, and all things will be seen in their unity and reality as parts of one intelligible whole. 36 CHAPTEE II. INFLUENCE OP PRECEDING WRITERS THE KABBALA. CONCEDING that the philosophy of Spinoza is not thoroughly self-consistent, we have said that it may be possible to discover what was the dominant idea or pre- vailing tendency in its author's mind, and to see in its inconsistencies, not so much the presence of irreconcilable principles, as an inadequate apprehension of the meaning and results of one leading principle. One help towards the right understanding of his system we have found in Spinoza's own account of the motive of his speculations, the impulse which originated and guided the process by which he endeavoured to attain intellectual satisfaction. Another help may be found in what we know of his early studies, and of the writers who may have moulded his mind or given a special direction to his thoughts. Much ingenuity has been spent, perhaps we might say misspent, in tracing the supposed " sources " of Spin- ozism. Not only has it been regarded by many writers as the logical development of the Cartesian philosophy, but, in so far as it diverges from the latter, it has been represented as reflecting or reproducing the mystical theosophy of the Kabbala, or the ideas of Maimonides Originality. 37 and other medieval Jewish philosophers, or the revived Platonism of Giordano Bruno and other writers of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries. But it is to be considered that the originality of a philosophical writer is not to be determined simply by the measure in which his ideas are traceable to earlier sources, or by the suggestions he has caught up from other minds. To lend real value to any contribution to philosophy it must reproduce the past, the sole question is whether the reproduction is a dead or living repro- duction, a rechauffe of old materials collected from various sources, or a revival of them, absorbed, trans- formed, renewed, by the quickening, transmuting power of speculative thought. On the other hand, no doubt, a great philosophical system must advance beyond the past ; but the all-important test of the new element is, whether it is connected with the past as a mere arbitrary increment, or as the outcome of an organic development The history of thought cannot, from its nature, be an arbitrary one. It is true that, as the formation of individual opinion may be deflected by a thousand acci- dents from the order of reason or rational progression, so the history of the thought of the world may be some- times the record of what is accidental and irrational of errors, vagaries, reactions, incoherencies : but in both, in so far as there is real progress, it is a progress which must follow the order of reason an advance by steps, each of which contains in it a reason for the next, each of which is at once the result and the explanation of that which preceded it. The merit, therefore, of any individual thinker, must be determined mainly by con- sidering whether he takes up and carries on the move- 38 Spinoza. ment of thought at the particular stage which it has reached in his own day. If his work have real or per- manent value, it will be due, indeed, to his own pro- ductive activity, but to that as an activity which has for its necessary presupposition the intellectual life of the past, growing out of it and determined by it. Con- sciously or unconsciously he must make that life his own. The originality of his work will consist, not in his independence of the thought of the past, but in this, that whatever ideas or suggestions he may have gathered from, various thinkers of various times, all his acquire- ments have become fused in a mind that is, so to speak, in sympathy with the dialectic movement of the spirit of its time. His greatness, if he be great, will be that of one who has at once put and answered the questions for the solution of which the age is pressing, given artic- ulate expression to the problem of philosophy in the form in which it is silently moving the thought of the world, and either partially or completely furnished the solution of it. That the merit of originality in the sense now indi- cated may be justly claimed for the philosophy of Spinoza, we shall endeavour to show in the sequel. But though the solution of the problem of philosophy to which he was led was logically involved in, and grew out of the teaching of Descartes, it is not inconsistent with this to say that it is one for which he was in some measure prepared and predisposed by the intellectual atmosphere of his early life, and by the literature and traditions which created it. In the ideas imbibed from the speculative mysticism of the Kabbala, from the teaching of medieval Jewish rationalists, and from the References to the Kabbala. 39 Platonic or Xeo-Platonic revival of times near his own, we may discern, though not the logical origin, at least the predisposing impulse towards the pantheistic side of Spinoza's philosophy. THE KABBALA. Ko direct reference to the Kabbala is to be found in Spinoza's writings, with the exception of one sentence in the 'Tractatus Theologico-politicus,' the contemptuous tone of which has been supposed to settle the question of his indebtedness to Kabbalistic speculation. " I have read," says he, "and, moreover, been (personally) ac- quainted with certain Kabbalistic triflers, at whose folly I cannot sufficiently wonder." But this depreciatory judgment, it has been pointed out, has special reference to the arbitrary and grotesque method of interpretation by which Kabbalistic writers endeavoured to extract a hidden significance from the historical narratives and other parts of the Old Testament Scriptures ; and that his contempt for such vagaries does not extend to what may be termed the speculative element of the Kabbala seems to be placed beyond question by two passages in his writings in which Kabbalistic doctrines are referred to with at least a qualified respect. Replying to Olden- burg, who had urged that, in the work above named, Spinoza seemed to many to confound God and Mature, he says : "I hold that God is the immanent and not the transient cause of all things. That all things are in God and move in God I affirm with Paul, and perhaps also with all the ancient philosophers, and I might even venture to say with all the ancient Hebrews, in so far as may be conjectured from certain traditions, though these 40 Spinoza. have been in many ways corrupted." l The other pas- sage is contained in the ' Ethics,' 2 where, with reference to his doctrine that " thinking substance and extended substance are one and the same substance, apprehended, now under this attribute, now under that," and that " a mode of extension and the idea of that mode are one and the same thing expressed in two different ways," he adds, " which truth certain of the Hebrews appear to have seen as if through a cloud when they affirm that God, the intellect of God, and the things which are the objects of that intellect, are one and the same thing." To show that the reference here is to the Kabbala, the following passage has been adduced from a work entitled ' The Garden of Pomegranates,' an exposition of the Kabba- listic doctrine of "the Sephiroth" or Divine Emana- tions, by a celebrated Kabbalist of the sixteenth century, Moses Corduero. " The knowledge of the Creator differs from that of the creature in this respect that, in the case of the latter, thought, the thinker, and the object thought of are different. But the Creator is Himself knowledge, the knower, and the object known. His knowledge does not arise from His directing His thoughts to things out- side of Him, since in comprehending and knowing Him- self, He comprehends and knows everything that exists. Nothing exists which is not one with Him and which He does not find in His own substance. He is the archetype of all things that exist, and all things are in Him in their purest and most perfect form." Notwith- standing the parallelism in this quotation, both in sub- stance and expression, to the doctrine ascribed by Spinoza to " certain Hebrews," the reference is rendered somewhat 1 Ep., 21. Eth., p. ii, Prop. vii. Schol. Neo-Platonism. 41 doubtful by the fact that Ave have no evidence that Spinoza knew anything of the writer from Avhom it is taken, and also, that in the ' Guide to the Perplexed,' the well-known work of the Jewish philosopher Maimonides, from whom Spinoza elsewhere quotes, a passage occurs in which the same doctrine is maintained in almost the same terms. It is not, however, in particular citations from the Kabbala that we find the most probable indications of the influence of its ideas on Spinoza's mind. Even the least incoherent of Kabbalistic works, the so-called ' Book Zoliar,' can only be described as a strange con- glomerate of philosophy and allegory, reason and rhap- sody, of ideas from Plato and Aristotle and ideas from the Pentateuch, of Jewish traditions and oriental mysti- cism. But if we try to extricate from this curious com- posite the underlying speculative element, we find in it distinct traces of one particular phase or school of thought. "Whatever the date or outward origin of the Kabbala, or its historic relation to Alexandrian meta- physic, the philosophy it teaches is simply Neo-Platonism in a fantastic guise. And through whatever channel they reached him, Spinoza's writings contain, we think, indi- cations of a certain influence of Neo-Platonic ideas. It is necessary, therefore, to form some conception of the system of thought to which these ideas belong. Neo-Platonism took its rise at a period when the old religions and philosophies of the world began to mingle, and (though the Greek element in it was the preponder- ating one) it attempted to produce a coherent system out of elements derived from Semitic theology, Asiatic mysticism, and the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle. 42 Spinoza. The main problem of ^Neo-Platonic speculation is that of the relation of the infinite and finite, of God and the world. Starting from a conception of the two extremes of this relation which made them absolutely irreconcil- able, the whole system was the expression of one long effort to bridge over an impassable gulf to deal with the idea of God conceived of as an absolute unity, beyond limitation or definition, so as, on the one hand, to make it possible for God to reveal Himself not merely in nature and man, but in an absolute formless matter ; and on the other hand, for the human spirit to rise into communion with the divine. The solution of this absolute dualism which Neo-Platonism propounds may be represented by the two words Emanation and Ecstasy. In the first place, the intense religious feeling which was the underlying motive of Xeo-Platonic speculation, and the consequent endeavour to elevate the conception of God above all the limiting conditions of human exist- ence, led to an idea of the First Principle of all things which is simply that of the absolutely indeterminate that which can be thought of only as the negation of all that can be affirmed of the finite. God is the Absolute One, unity beyond all difference, to which no predicates can be attached, of which nothing can be affirmed or expressed. We may not think of Him as intelligent, for intelligence implies distinction between the knower and the object known. For a similar reason we may not ascribe to Him a will. " Strictly speaking, He is neither consciousness nor unconsciousness, neither freedom nor unfreedom, for all such opposites pertain to the realm of finite things. He gives life, yet Himself lives not, Hf is all and the negation of all/' Even when we name Him Emanation. 43 "the One," we must exclude any thought of numerical unity, for that contains or implies the idea of multipli- city, and is meaningless when applied to that which is above all distinction. " Only by negation can we define Him. He is inexpressible, for all speech names some definite thing ; He is incomprehensible, for thought dis- tinguishes between itself and its object ; if we would grasp Him, it is only by an act of intuition in which the mind rises above thought and becomes one with its object." But when the idea of God has been tints rarefied to an abstraction which is simply the negation of the finite, every way back to the finite would seem to be cut off. The Absolute One of Neo-Platonism, in which the ex- planation of all finite things is to be found, would seem to be shut up in its own self-identity. In a unity so conceived there is no reason why it should go beyond itself to manifest or reveal itself in the manifoldness of finite existence. The solution of the problem which Xeo-Platonism gives is contained, as we have said, in the word "emanation." The self -involved imprisonment of the Absolute which reason cannot break down, Plotinus attempts to dissolve by the aid of imagination and pic- torial analogy. " Everything," says he, " that is in any degree perfect, and most of all, therefore, the absolutely perfect, tends to overflow itself, to stream forth, and pro- duce that which is other than itself yet an image of it- self. Fire produces heat, snow cold, fragrant substances odours, medicine healing. The most perfect cannot re- main powerless, shut up in itself." Accordingly, that Absolute which is above knowledge is conceived to stream forth in a series of emanations, descending 44 Spinoza. through successive stages in which the irradiation be- comes fainter and fainter, till it reaches the realm of darkness, of that formless matter which is below know- ledge. As Plato endeavoured to overcome the dualism between the ideal and phenomenal world by the concep- tion of a world-soul as a kind of mediator, so Plotinus seeks to escape from a still more absolute dualism by ex- panding the Platonic conception into that of four de- scending stages of emanations, each of which successively represents a lower degree of perfection. The first is the ideal world or realm of ideas, in which the Absolute One, the ineffable light which is indistinguishable from darkness, becomes conscious of itself, or produces as the image of itself mind or intelligence. This ideal world, though in itself the archetype of all finite being, the source of all the light and life of the phenomenal world, is in itself incapable of any immediate relation to it ; and so, by the same emanational expedient, the conception is formed of an intermediating principle, the world-soul or realm of souls, related, on the one hand, to the realm of ideas from which it emanates, and on the other hand, to the realm of matter, by its impregna- tion of which it produces the phenomenal world, and time and space, which are the conditions of its being. In this descending series we pass, circle beyond circle, within the world of light and reality, till we reach its utmost limit in the world of souls, beyond which lies the sensible phenomenal world, which is produced by the last circle of light casting forth its rays into the darkness beneath. The phenomenal world is thus a composite of light and darkness, being and non-being, whose only reality is due to the radiance which pene- Ecstasy. 45 trates it from the world above. Beneath it lies the region of formless matter, which, as the opposite of the First Principle, is designated Absolute Evil, in the sense of pure negation or non-being. In the phenomenal world it is redeemed from negation ; but that phenomenal Avoiid is itself only a world of shadows, owing its reality to the world-soul, as that in turn to the ideal world, and both alike to the primordial unity, the only absolute, all- comprehending reality. There, and there alone, all dis- tinction, all mutation, cease ; the whole universe of thought and being exists only as its transient image or irradiation, and the reabsorption of that universe into its primal source woiild be at once the vanishing away of its finite existence and its return to the only absolute reality. In the second place, this last thought receives definite expression in an ascending series of stages, in which as- piration, ending in ecstasy or ecstatic intuition, reverses the process of the descending series of emanations. All finite being strives after union with its origin. All in- dividual existences in their separateness and transiency are under an impulse which urges them backwards to- wards the centre from which they emanated. The in- dividual soul, like the soul of the world, of which it is a part, stands at the middle of this universe of emana- tions, and combines in itself elements at once of the highest and of the lowest. As embodied it is a part of nature and allied to the lower world of matter; as spiritual it belongs to the ideal world and to the unity from which it emanates, in estrangement from which it is in bondage to a natural necessity separating it from its true home ; and to that home, in obedience to its proper destiny, it 46 Spinoza. ever seeks to return. The steps by which this return is achieved repeat in reverse order those of descent. By knowledge or contemplative energy it emancipates itself from the bondage of sense, and remounts into the ideal world, the region where thought or intelligence finds nothing foreign to itself, but lives and moves in the pure atmosphere of eternal ideas. But even here intelligence has not reached its highest goal, the absolute unity to which it aspires. Even in the realm of ideas there is still division. The mind which contemplates objective truth, or which attains to knowledge by any dialectic pro- cess, is still not absolutely one with its object. There is a stage of spiritual exaltation higher than that of definite thought. There is a point where the last distinction, that of subject and object, vanishes, where thought dies away into feeling, intelligence loses itself in rapt identi- fication with its object, and all sense of individuality is absorbed in that absolute transparent imity where no division is. This is the final goal of Xeo-Platonic specu- lation, the " ecstasy " which can only be described as the extinction of thought from its own intensity, the striving of the finite spirit beyond itself till it is lost in God. If we try to characterise this system generally, it may be described as a kind of poetical or imaginative pan- theism. It does not succeed in overcoming the original dualism which is involved in the two extremes of an absolute, self-identical unity, and an absolute, formless matter. The former contains in it no reason for the ex- istence of a world in which its latent riches shall be revealed, and the idea of emanation to which recourse is had is only the substitution of a metaphor for a rational Neo-Platonism in the Kabbala. 47 principle. But in intention at least, it i.s purely pan- theistic, or rather it belongs to that class of pantheistic systems to which the designation " acosmism " is more properly applied. The successive orders of emanations which constitute the world are only phantoms, unreal as the reflections in a mirror; its only reality is the absolute unity from which their phantasmal existence is projected, and that, as it was without diminution through their existence, remains without increase when they have vanished away. If we endeavour to disengage from the arbitrary mythological and other ingredients of which the Kab- bala is composed, the speculative element which gives it any value for thought, we shall find in it, as we have said, little else than a reproduction of ^eo-Platonism. In the Book Zohar, the only part of the Kabbala which has any pretension to systematic connection, the funda- mental idea is that of the " En Soph," or unlimited, Avith its ten " Sephiroth," or emanations. The former, the source from which all the life and light of the uni- verse, all ideal and actual existence, flows, is described as " the unknown of the unknown," " the mystery of mysteries." " He cannot be comprehended by the intellect nor described in words, and as such he is in a certain sense non-existent, because, as far as our minds are concerned, that which is perfectly incomprehensible does not exist." l In other words, the Kabbalists, in their endeavour to exalt the conception of God above all anthropomorphic elements, refine it away till it becomes simply the abstract notion of being which is indistinguish- able from non-being. This Absolute Being, unknowable 1 Zohar, quoted by Ginsburg, The Kabbala, \>. 6. 48 Spinoza. in Himself, can become known, even indirectly, only l>y becoming active or creative. But He cannot become im- mediate creator of a finite world : first, because to ascribe to Him intention and will would be to introduce finite determinations into His nature ; and secondly, because an Infinite Being can produce only that which is infinite. Accordingly, in ^[eo-Platonic fashion, the Kabbala invents a mediating principle based on the figure of the radia- tion of light from an invisible centre. This principle, corresponding to the " ideal world " of Plotinus, is desig- nated " the world of emanations," and is elaborated and arranged by the Kabbalists into successive trinities, each of which constitutes, on the one hand, one of the various aspects under which the " En Soph," or incomprehensible divine nature, is contemplated ; on the other hand, the archetype of some one of the various orders of existence in the finite world. In their totality, gathered up into unity by the last emanation, which is the harmonising principle of the whole series, they are designated the 'Adam Kadmon,' the ideal or celestial man, inasmuch as, according to the Zohar, " the form of man contains all that is in heaven and earth, all beings superior and inferior, and therefore the ancient of ancients has chosen it for his own." 1 In order to constitute the mediating principle between God and the world, the Sephiroth are represented as partaking of the nature at once of the in- finite and finite : as emanations from the infinite, they are themselves infinite ; as distinguishable from the in- finite, they are the first order of finite things. The finite world is not a creation out of nothing, but simply a further expansion or evolution of the Sephiroth. By a 1 Zohar, quoted by Franck, La Kalilxdr, p. 179. Emanation. 49 curious conceit the Kabbala supposes, prior to the ex- istence of the present world, certain formless worlds, abortive attempts at creation, so to speak, to have issued from the ideal archetypal fountain of being and then vanished away ; and these it compares to sparks which fly from a red-hot iron beaten by a hammer, and which are extinguished as they separate themselves from the burning mass. 1 On the other hand, in contrast with these failures, the being of the actual world is due to the continuous presence in it and in all it contains of a measure, greater or less, of the luminous element from which it springs. All finite existences are made in descending series " after the pattern of things in the heavens." " First comes the 'Briatic world,' which is the abode of pure spirits ; next, the ' Yetziratic world,' or world of formation, which is the habitation of angels ; and lastly, the ' Assiatic world,' or world of action, which contains the spheres and matter, and is the residence of the prince of darkness and his legions." 2 Without fol- lowing this theory of creation in the details of fantastic imagery into which it is wrought out by the Kabbalists, it may be observed in general that its characteristic prin- ciple, the emanational conception of the relation of the world to God which is common to it with iNeo-Platonism, reappears in it in a form modified by Jewish mythological traditions. The belief in angels and demons was deeply rooted in the spirit of the Jewish people, and under its influence the emanations of Neo-Platonism become per- sonified into the angels of the Kabbala, and the world- soul of the former becomes in the latter the Briatic world, which is the habitation of pure spirits. In like 1 Ginsburg, I.e., p. 15. - Ginsburg, p. 24. P. XIL D /50 Spinoza. manner the phenomenal world of Xeo-Platonism becomes the Yetziratic world of the Kabbala ; and as the former was constituted by the irradiation of light from above into the darkness of matter, so in the cosmology of the Kabbala the same result is brought about by the presence of angelic beings pervading the whole realm of nature. To every part and process of the material world the heavenly firmament, the orbs of light, the earth, the element of fire, the revolution of the seasons, &c. an angelic ruler is assigned, and it is to the agency of the angelic hosts that all the varied movements of nature and their harmony and unity are to be ascribed. Finally, under the same personifying influence, the Jfeo-Platonic realm of darkness, beneath the last circle of ideal life, becomes, in the Kabbala, the Assiatic world, the habita- tion of evil spirits a conception in which the demon- ology of Jewish tradition and its wild imaginative reveries come into strange conjunction with the results of Greek speculative thought In the Kabbalistic theory of the nature and destiny of man we find the same reproduction of Neo-Platonic ideas under Jewish forms. Man is the epitome of the universe, the microcosm who combines in his nature all the various elements which constitute the totality of being. He is, says the Zohar, 1 " at once the sum and the highest term of creation. . . . As soon as man appeared every- thing was complete, both the higher and lower worlds, for everything is comprised in him ; he unites in him- self all forms of being." This is otherwise expressed by saying that man is the earthly Adam, the image of the heavenly Adam, the Adam Kadmon above described. i Quoted, Franck, 229. Absorption. 51 As the latter is simply an expression for the totality of Sephiroth, the eternal ideal archetypes of all that exists in the finite world, so, to say that man is the earthly image of the heavenly Adam is to say that all things in heaven and earth, from the highest to the lowest, are represented or expressed in the unity of his nature. He is at once spiritual and animal, divine and demoniacal 011 the higher side of his being an emanation from the world of pure spirits, which is itself an emanation from the Infinite ; on the other hand, having relation through his fleshly nature to the material world and to that form- less matter which is figured as the abode of the spirits of darkness. Finally, in its doctrine of the destiny of man and the world, the Kabbala reproduces, under a slightly modified form, the reascending stages of Neo-Platonism. As all individual souls, according to the Zohar, in their ideal essence, pre-existed in the world of emanations, so, having inhabited human bodies, and passed through the discipline of an earthly life (or through successive lives), they become emancipated from the blind power of nature which governs the animal life, and return to the source from which they emanated. In this reascending process two stages are distinguished, each marked by its own characteristics. From the servitude of the animal life the soul rises first into that real but still imperfect relation to the divine source of light in which knowledge is only re- flective and obedience is more that of fear than of love. But there is, says the Zohar, a state of perfection in which the Eternal Light falls no longer indirectly and as through a veil on the spirit, but shines on it directly and full-orbed in immediate vision, and in which perfect love casts out fear. In this consummation of its being, 52 Spinoza. this state of intuitive vision and unmingled love, there is no longer any division between the spirit and its object. It has lost its individual character ; all finite interests, all activity, all return upon itself have vanished. Its being becomes absolutely lost in the divine. 1 I have said that the Neo-Platonic system leaves still in the " formless matter " which lies beyond the last circle of light an element of unsolved dualism, which its pan- theistic principle of emanation has not overcome. But the pantheism of the Kabbala is, in expression at least, more uncompromising. In it the differentiation of the primordial unity is succeeded by a more complete re- integration. Not even the lowest world of darkness, the habitation of evil spirits, which is the analogue for the "formless matter" of Neo-Platonism, is left in the final crisis unreclaimed. The Kabbala knows no absolute evil, no being doomed to everlasting separation from the source of light. There will come a time when the world of darkness will disappear, and even the archangel of evil, "the venomous beast," will be restored to his angelic name and nature, and when all orders of being will have entered into the eternal rest, the endless Sabbath of the universe. 2 It is not, as we have said, in the theosophic mysticism of the Kabbala, but in the dialectic movement of the thought of his own time a movement which found independent expression where there could be no question of Jewish influences, in the philosophy of Malebranche and in the theology of the Eeformers that the true genesis of Spinozism is to be discerned. But whilst Descartes is the logical parent of Spinoza, there are i Franck, p. 248. 2 Ibid, p. 217 ; Ghislmrg, p. 44. Spinoza and the Kdbbala. 53 traces in the 'Ethics,' and still more distinctly in the earlier treatise ' Concerning God and Man,' of his familiarity with Kabbalistic ideas, and these ideas may have constituted in a mind early imbued with them a predisposing tendency toward that view of the world and of its relation to God which lies at the basis of the Spinozistic philosophy. Whatever else Spinozism is, it is an attempt to find in the idea of God a principle from which the whole universe could be evolved by a necessity as strict as that by which, according to Spinoza's favourite illustration, the properties of a tri- angle follow from its definition. For the clear intelli- gence of Spinoza it was impossible to rest satisfied with a system in Avhich metaphor plays the part of logical thought ; and accordingly, in his philosophy the emana- tion theory of the Kabbalists finds no place. Yet even in a system in which logical consecution is the supreme principle of method, there are traces of that attempt to effect by an arbitrary mediating principle what reason fails to accomplish, which is the main characteristic of Kabbalistic speculation. In one point of view the transition from the infinite to the finite is barred for Spinoza, as it was for the Kabbalists, by the idea of God with which he starts. If we interpret that idea by his own principle that " all determination is negation," what it means for him is the absolutely indeterminate, the bare affirmation of Being which is reached by abstracting from all determinations. It is true that he ascribes to God or absolute substance the two attributes of thought and extension, but these attributes are only distinctions relative to finite intelligence ; they do not pertain to the absolute essence of the divine nature, but 54 Spinoza. are only ways in which the human understanding con- ceives of it. Beyond these attributes or determinations lies the indeterminate substance, of which nothing can be affirmed but that it is the self-identical unity into which no difference or distinction can enter. But in so defining the nature of God, Spinoza would seem to have rendered impossible all advance from this primary idea to anything further. In that of which nothing can be affirmed there can be no reason for the existence of anything else, and to find in it a reason for the existence of the finite world would be to find in it a reason for its own negation. To rehabilitate the finite world would be to reaffirm that by abstracting from which the idea of God has been attained ; it Avould be to destroy God in order to derive the finite from Him. Yet though in this point of view the fundamental principle of Spinozism would seem to preclude all fur- ther advance, it was, as above said, the intention of its author to find in that principle the explanation of all things. The whole finite world was to be so involved in the idea of God as to be deducible from it as cer- tainly as the propositions of geometry from its defini- tions and axioms. To achieve this result it is obvious that either the fundamental principle as above defined must be modified, or some illogical expedient must be adopted to cure it of its barrenness. The latter alter- native is that which Spinoza adopted. He attempted by means of a conception analogous to the world-soul of the Neo-Platonists, to mediate between the infinite and finite, and to gain for the latter a legitimate derivation from the former. Out of the rigid unity of absolute sub- stance difference is to be educed ; from an infinite which "Infinite Modes." 55 is in incommunicable isolation the finite world is to be derived. This problem Spinoza thinks to solve by con- ceiving of all individual finite existences as " modes " i.e., finite determinations of the infinite substance and then escaping the contradiction implied in determina- tions of the indeterminate by means of the conception of what he terms " infinite modes." On the one hand we have the infinite, indeterminate substance on the other, a world of finite modes or determinations ; and in order to bridge the gulf between them we have a third something which, as its name implies, is so conceived as to be in affinity with both, with the finite or modal world, as being itself a " mode " ; with the infinite, as an " infinite " mode. In other words, Spinoza thinks it possible to conceive of modes which, though as such they belong to the finite, changeable world, are them- selves infinite and unchangeable. The whole corporeal world may be represented as a single individual, a universal motion which, embracing all particular move- ments, remains itself eternally unmoved; and the whole spiritual world may be represented as a universal intelli- gence, which, embracing all finite ideas or intelligences, is itself unlimited or infinite. Thus these universal individuals having in them elements at once of infinitude and finitude, may constitute the transition from the one realm to the other. As infinite and eternal, they in- troduce no negation into the one absolute substance ; as expressions for the totality of finite existences and of the whole series of phenomenal changes, they are in close relation to the finite world. It is not at present our business to criticise this notion ; all we have to do is to point out that, whether suggested to his mind from 56 Spinoza* his early studies in Jewish philosophy of not, there is at least a certain analogy between it and the Nee-Platonic conception, reproduced in the Kabbala, of an inter- mediating principle between the absolute unity and the world of finite existences, between the ideal world, in itself eternal and unchangeable, and the world of mutable things and beings. Nor, on the other hand, is it impossible to discern in Spinozism a certain reflection of the reascending move- ment which forms the converse side of the Xeo-Platonic system. As in the descending movement we have the stages of infinite attributes, modified by infinite modes, and these by an infinite number of finite modes, so in the return to God there is, so to speak, a retracing of the steps by which finite individualities have become differ- entiated from the unity of infinite substance in which all reality is comprehended. In the attitude of ordinary experience (experientia vaya) we contemplate the world as consisting of independent things and beings. But the independence we thus ascribe to them is illusory. As it is only by applying to space or extension, which is one and indivisible, the conceptions of number and measure, which are mere " aids of imagination," that we caii think of it as made up of discrete parts, so it is only imagination which gives to ourselves and all other finite individuals a separate, independent existence. Not only does each finite mode exist only as determined by other finite modes in an infinite series, but by the very fact that it is a mode it has no claim to independence in regard to the infinite substance. The first step or stage of true knowledge, therefore, the commencement of our escape from the illusion of the finite, is that of our passing Stages of Knowledge. 57 from " vague experience " to " reason " or the rational contemplation of the world. This kind of knowledge Spinoza defines x as " that in which we contemplate things not as accidental but as necessary ; " and again, 2 as " that in which we know things under a certain form of eter- nity." It is not the highest stage of knowledge, but it is so far on the way to the highest that in it we are rescued from the dominion of accidental associations ; we look at things no longer in the arbitrary relations of time and place, but as linked together in necessary con- nection of cause and effect, so that all things are seen to be what they are because they are parts of that series or totality which, as above described, constitutes the " in- finite modes" of the absolute substance. So regarded they have in them, underneath all appearances of change, an element of unchangeableness, of necessity, of eternity. But beyond even this ideal aspect of things, there is a higher attitude of mind which Spinoza designates scientia i/itniftrri, in which we "proceed from an adequate idea of a certain attribute of God to the adequate knowledge of the nature of things." This stage of knowledge is that in which we no longer reason about things, but know them in their essence, no longer proceed infer- entially, from premisses to conclusion, from causes to effects, but as by immediate vision penetrate to the heart and life, the inmost reality of the world. If there is any element of mediation in this knowledge, it is only in so far as it is that of an intelligence which sees all things in God and in their relation to Him. At this stage the finite mind has risen above itself and other things as individuals, to contemplate them in their 1 Eth. ii. 44. - Ibid., cor. 2. 58 Spinoza. unity, as they are in God or as modifications of His attributes. Even its knowledge of God is no longer simply the knowledge which the finite has of the infinite, it is a part of the knowledge which God has of Himself. Moreover, it is to be noticed that, by his identification of will with intelligence, the reascending process is for Spinoza a moral as well as an intellectual one. The bondage of sense and the bondage of inadequate ideas is one and the same. To discern the illusory independ- ence we ascribe to ourselves and to all finite things is to escape from it ; to know the absolute law of necessity imder which we lie is to become free ; to know our- selves " under the form of eternity " is to rise above the sphere of time. It is the false reality which opinion and imagination ascribe to the finite that subjects us to the slavery of our desires and passions. Reason, in destroy- ing their unreal basis, breaks the yoke. And when, finally, we have risen to that supreme attitude of mind in which we not merely reason from the idea of God as a first principle to the nature of things, but by the grasp of intuitive insight see ourselves and all things in the light of it, then with the very existence of our finite self the desires and passions that were implicated with it of necessity vanish. As we cease to know, so we cease to will or love, any object outside of God ; and our love to God, like our knowledge of God, becomes one with that wherewith God regards Himself. Here as elsewhere in the philosophy of Spinoza there are elements which, as we shall see in the sequel, essentially distinguish him from the mystical Neo-Platonic theosophists ; yet even in the foregoing sketch of the process by which he reaches that Influence of the Kabbala. 59 ' ' intellectual love " which is for him the final goal of moral endeavour and aspiration, we may discern points of analogy to the Neo-Platonic "ecstasy" and to the Kabbalistic absorption in the " En Soph " which, in a mind steeped from early youth in Jewish literature and tradition, cannot have been altogether a matter of accident. 60 CHAPTEE III. THE MEDIEVAL JEWISH PHILOSOPHERS. A VAST amount of learning and ingenuity has been ex- pended on the question of Spinoza's supposed obligations to Maimonides, Chasdai Creskas, and other distinguished philosophic writers of his own race. Many parallelisms of thought and expression have been adduced by Dr Joel and others, and it has even been maintained that his debt to these writers seriously affects his title to originality as a philosopher. Such occasional coinci- dences, however, even if they had been more numerous and unambiguous than those on which this opinion rests, cannot without further consideration be accepted as prov- ing the derivation of Spinozism from Jewish sources. Par- ticular points of resemblance, as we have already said, mean more or less according to the general principles and point of view of the writers in whom they occur. The signifi- cance of an idea or form of expression can only be esti- mated in view of its organic relation to the whole of whicli it forms a part, and even exact verbal coincidences, so far from establishing the intellectual obligation of a later writer to earlier writers of a different school or stand- point, only go to prove, at most, that he was acquainted Maimonides. 61 with their works. It is on this principle that we must judge of the alleged anticipations of Spinozism in the medieval Jewish philosophers. From one and all of these writers he differed, at least in this respect, that they served two masters, he only one. The conclusions they reached were the result of a compromise between reason and authority. Their aim in all they wrote was to reconcile philosophy with the teaching of Moses and the traditional dogmas of Judaism, and the result was even more unsatisfactory than in the parallel case of the scholastic philosophy. That result varied, indeed, in its character in different instances, according as the philo- sophic or the authoritative tendency predominated in the mind of the writer. In some cases Jewish dogma was manipulated by arbitrary interpretation into accordance with Greek philosophy, in others Aristotelian and Pla- tonic terminology was crudely applied to the cosmogony of Moses and the theology of the synagogue. In all cases alike the issue of this forced alliance was a spurious one, which neither reason nor authority could claim as its own. Between such composite productions and a strictly reasoned system like Spinozism there can be no common measure. A detailed examination of Spinoza's relations to the Jewish philosophers would carry us beyond the limits of this work. We must confine our remarks to that one of these writers to whom Spinoza has been said to owe the most, Moses Maimonides. The philosophical writ- ings of Maimonides are characterised as a whole by the tendency above indicated, the endeavour to establish foregone conclusions. But perhaps the part of his philo- sophy in which this tendency shows itself least is that 62 Spinoza. which relates to the idea of God. In his treatment of this subject the Jewish theologian is almost entirely sub- ordinated to the follower of Plato and Aristotle. In one passage of his most important work, the ' Moreh Nebuchim,' or ' Guide to the Perplexed,' he adopts the Aristotelian definition of God as vo^o-ts vor/o-ews i.e., thought which is its own object, pure, abstract self- consciousness ; and in other passages in which he treats of the divine attributes, the notion of abstract unity involved in this definition is further rarefied into the ^N"eo-Platonic conception of absolute self -identity, a unity which repels every element of difference. We have already seen how, in the endeavour to clear the idea of God from all anthropomorphic alloy, Xeo-Platonism endeavours to get beyond the stage at which there is a distinction between thought and its object, and to rise to a point of exaltation higher even than thought or in- telligence, a unity in which this distinction vanishes. Maimonides in different parts of his writings wavers between these two conceptions. As Plotinus maintained that the highest ideal of intelligence is that in which the object of knowledge is no longer something external to the knowing subject, but that pure self -contemplative energy in which thought is the object of its own activity, so Maimonides, still more closely following the Aristo- telian dialectic, endeavours on the same principle to dis- tinguish between divine and human intelligence. It is of the very nature of thought or intelligence that it grasps the " forms " or real essences of things ; and when it does so, these forms are not something different from itself, for it is only as active, as thinking these forms, that it realises its own nature. Intelligence apprehend- Divine Intelligence. 63 ing the forms of things, and the forms of things appre- hended by intelligence, are only different expressions for one and the same thing, or the same thing regarded from different points of view. When, therefore, the human intelligence is in the state of actual thought, thought, the thinker, and the thing thought of, are wholly one. But man is not always in the state of actual thought. At first thought in him is only potential, a capacity of thinking which has not yet come into actuality ; and even when intelligence in him has become developed, it is not always or continuously active. When the mind is at the potential stage of thought, or when the capacity of thinking is in abeyance, we can regard the power of apprehension and the object capable of being appre- hended as two separate things ; and farther, inasmuch as a power can only be conceived of as residing in a being or nature which possesses it, to these two we have to add a third viz., the mind in which the power of thought resides. But when we conceive of a univer- sal and ever-active intelligence, an intelligence in which there is no unrealised capacity, no potentiality that is not actuality, and which does not apprehend at one time and cease to apprehend at another when, in other words, we think of a mind to which no reality is foreign, in which the forms or essences of things are ever present, and which is eternal activity as well as potentiality, then we have before us the conception of a being in which the threefold distinction vanishes. In a mind which ever thinks there is no separation of thinker and power of thought, nor of the power of thought from its own objects. In God, the absolute energy, the ever-active intelligence, thought, the thinker, and the object of thought, are one, 64 Spinoza. In the passage which I have here epitomised, the idea of God which Maimonides reaches is that which, if followed out and freed from the limitations which are connected with it in the Aristotelian philosophy, would lead to the modern conception of absolute, self-conscious, self-determining Spirit of thought which at once reveals itself in the manifold differences of the finite world and from all these differences returns upon itself. But in Mairnonides not only does this idea remain undeveloped, but it is left in unreconciled contradiction with another conception of the divine nature on which he more frequently insists. In the false search for unity, or confounding that discreteness which destroys unity with that concrete fulness in which the highest unity con- sists, he sets himself to think of something higher even than intelligence, an absolute which is not the unity of subject and object, but the abstraction in which these distinctions are lost. An absolute unity is that from which every element of plurality or difference must be excluded. Our belief in the divine unity, therefore, implies that the essence of God is that to which no pred- icates or attributes can be attached. When we describe an object by attributes, these attributes must be conceived of either as constituting its essence, or as superadded to it. If the attributes of God are conceived of as con- stituting his essence, we fall into the absurdity of con- ceiving of a plurality of infinites, and further, of in- troducing into the nature of God that divisibility or compositeness which belongs only to corporeal things. If the attributes are thought of as superadded to the essence, then are they merely accidents and express nothing in the reality of the divine nature. By these The Absolute Unity. 65 and similar arguments, Maimonides convinced himself that such attributes as power, wisdom, goodness, cannot be understood as expressing any positive reality, and that even such predicates as existence, unity, &c., can- not, in the ordinary sense of the words, be applied to the divine essence. As applied to finite beings, existence is something separable from essence ; the idea of a house in the mind of the builder, for instance, being something different from the house as an actually existing thing : but in God existence and essence, idea and reality, are one and indivisible. When, again, we say of God that He is one, we must understand something different from the unity we predicate of finite things, for " unity and plurality are accidents belonging to the category of discrete quantity." When we pronounce a thing to be one, we add to its essence the accidents of its relations to other things ; but in God as an absolute or necessarily existing Being, unity and essence are one. The con- clusion, therefore, to which Maimonides comes, is that the predicates by which we suppose ourselves to attain to a knowledge of God do not express any positive real ity in the divine nature, but can only be employed in a negative sense, to denote, not what God is, but what He is not; in other words, they are only expressions for our own ignorance. The essence of God is that pure absolute unity which lies beyond all plurality, and there- fore beyond all predication, of which we can only say that it is, but not what or how it is. 1 From the foregoing summary it is obvious that Mai- monides does not advance beyond the Keo-Platonic con- ception of the nature of God. If any positive reference 1 Moreh, i. 51-57 P. XII. E 66 Spiili >-.'i. to him can be traced in Spinoza's writings, it is in the passage above quoted, in which he speaks in a somewhat slighting tone of some faint anticipation of his doctrine of the relation of the attributes of thought and extension to the divine substance as having dawned " as through a cloud" on the minds of "certain of the Hebrews." On the further question, whether on this point any indirect influence of the writers so designated can be traced in the philosophy of Spinoza, enough has already been said. Whatever the relation of Spinoza's doctrine as to the nature of God to that of Maimonides, when we pass from this point to the teaching of the latter as to the relation of God to the world, the divergence between the two systems amounts to nothing less than radical inconsistency. Here it is no longer Aristotle but Moses who is the master of Maimonides. He is no longer an independent thinker, but a rabbi striving by special pleading to force philosophy into reconciliation with the creed of the synagogue. A philosophy Avhich starts from the notion of a transcendent God, a self-identical unity excluding all distinctions, can find in itself no logical explanation of the existence of a finite world. The process from unity to difference becomes impossible when there is no element of difference in the unity. Even the Aristotelian conception of God as pure self- consciousness, pure Form without Matter, rendered it impossible to account for a world in which form \vas realised in matter. And the impossibility of the transi- tion becomes still more obvious when the unity of self- consciousness is sublimated into the Neo-Platonic idea of a pure identity without difference. The only device by Relation of God to the World. 67 which an apparent transition from the one to the many, from God to the world, can, under such conditions, be effected, is either to substitute metaphor for reason, as we have seen at tempted in Xeo-Platonism, or, failing that expedient, to take refuge in mystery and to account for the world by a supernatural creative act. It is the latter expedient which, under the constraint of the pre- supposed orthodox doctrine of a creation of the world ex niltilo, Maimonides adopts. There is indeed one remarkable passage in the ' Guide to the Perplexed ' in which the Xeo-Platonic theory of emanation is distinctly taught. How, he asks, can that which remains eternally the same and unmoving be the cause of all motion and becoming? And he answers by the following illustra- tion : " Many a man possesses so much Avealth that he can not only bestow on others what they are in want of, but can so enrich them that they in turn can enrich others. In like manner there is poured forth from God so much good that there emanates from Him, not only spirit, but a sphere of spirits. This second spirit again contains in it ever such a fulness that from it also spirit and spheres of spirit are derived, and so forth down to the last intelligence and the first matter from which all the elements arose. This idea of God was held by the prophets, and because this emanation of God is limited neither by space nor time, they have compared God to an eternal and inexhaustible fountain pouring itself forth on all sides." l This passage, how- ever, can only be understood as the passing lapse of an unsystematic writer, adopting for the moment and for rt special purpose a theory inconsistent with his funda- i Moreh, ii. 11, 12. 68 Spinoza. mental principles. It is scarcely necessary to show by formal quotations that the theory, if so it can be called, on which Maimonides rests as the only possible explana- tion of the existence of the finite world, is that which is expressed by the phrase, "creation out of nothing." In answer to the Aristotelian argument that creation in time would imply in God a potentiality which had not yet passed into actuality, Maimonides maintains that " the sole ground of creation is to be found in the will of God, and that it belongs to the nature of will that a thing takes place at one time and not at another." l " For all these phenomena of nature," he adds, " I see no law of necessity, but can only understand them when we say with the doctrine of Moses that all has arisen by the free will of the Creator." 2 " If I had any proofs for the doctrines of Plato," again he writes, " I would unconditionally accept them, and interpret allegorically the verses of Moses which speak of a creation out of nothing." 3 And then he proceeds elaborately to defend the Mosaic doctrine against the philosophic, which, in his opinion, would completely subvert religion, our belief in Scripture, and the hopes and fears which reli- gion inculcates. It need scarcely be said that we have here a doctrine which is irreconcilable, not only with the philosophy of Spinoza, but with any philosophy whatever. "Whether Spinoza's doctrine of one substance, of Avhich all finite things are only transitory modes, furnishes any adequate solution of the problem of the relation of the world to God, it is at least an attempt to find in the idea of God a first principle from which everything else follows by i Moreh, ii. 18. - Ibid., ii. 22. ibid., ii. 25. Creation out of Nothing. 69 strict necessity. The finite world is for him that which " follows from the necessity of the divine nature that is, all the modes of the divine attributes, in so far as they are considered as things which are in God, and cannot be conceived without God." l Even the theory of emanation is at least an attempt to solve the problem with which it deals. But the theory of creation out of nothing is simply the abandonment of the problem as insoluble ; and if it seem anything more, it is only because its real character is disguised by a meaningless phrase. The theory itself, as well as the world for which it would account, is created out of nothing. It is unnecessary to follow the so-called philosophy of Maimonides into further details. Setting out from a point of divergence such as has just been indicated, it is obvious that in the subsequent course of their specula- tions Spinoza and Maimonides could never meet, and their occasional coincidences are such only to the ear. Maimonides, for example, like many thinkers of the same order, feels himself impelled to seek a basis for moral responsibility in a freedom of indifference or in- determinism, and from the difficulties involved in this conception he finds a ready escape in his theory of creation. He who begins by tracing all things to an arbitrary supernatural act can never be at a loss for a solution of particular speculative difficulties. " To man," says he, 2 " has been given complete freedom whether he will incline to the good or evil way. Here there is no law of causality as in outward nature, so that the will of man should be the effect of any cause, but man's own will is the first cause of all his actions." "But," he 1 Eth. i. 29, schol. - Yad-ha-chazakah, v. 4. 70 Spinoza. asks, " does not the assertion that the will is free stand in contradiction with the divine omnipotence] The answer is, !Not so ; for, as God has given to everything its own nature, so He has made it the nature of the human will that it should be free." In other words, the un- conditioned freedom of the human will is not only not derived from but is in absolute contradiction with the nature of God, and must therefore be ascribed simply to His arbitrary will, and what is contradictory to God's nature ceases to be so when God Himself is the author of the contradiction. How far apart from Spinoza, both in matter and manner, lies this kind of reasoning, need not here be pointed out. There is, however, one subject on which, viewed apart from the general principles of the two systems, their coincidence at first sight looks more than verbal viz., the nature of physical and moral evil : "We must," says Maimonicles, 1 "first of all consider whence evil comes, and what is the nature of good and evil. Only the good is something positive ; evil, on the contrary, is only want of good, therefore a mere negation. Life, e.g. , is the combination of this form with this matter ; the cessa- tion of the combination or the division of the two is death. Health is harmony in human bodies, sickness arises so soon as the harmony is destroyed. God, therefore, can only be regarded as the author of evil in the world in so far as He permits change, and lets the world arise out of matter which is subject to change. But change is a thing that is necessary ; that anything should begin to be implies the possibility of its passing away. And not only of natural evil but of moral evil must it be pronounced that it is a mere negation. It comes merely from a want of reason, and is nothing positive. 1 Moreh, iii. 21. Nature of Evil. 71 Were men wholly rational there would be neither hatred, nor envy, nor error, which work destructively amongst men, just as blind men injure themselves and others through want of sight. Both kinds of evil are mere negations which God does not cause, but only permits. Both are consequences of matter from which the world and man have become, and yet from matter nothing better could arise." Compare with this doctrine of evil the following passages from Spinoza : "With regard to good and evil, these indicate nothing positive in things considered in themselves, nor anything else than modes of thought or notions which we form from the comparison of one thing with another." l " For my own part, I cannot admit that sin and evil have any positive existence. . . . We know that whatever is, when considered in itself without regard to anything else, possesses perfection, extending in each thing as far as the limits of that thing's essence. The design or determined will (in such an act as Adam's eating the forbidden fruit), considered in itself alone, includes perfection in so far as it expresses reality. Hence it may be inferred that we can only perceive imperfection in things when they are viewed In relation to other things possessing more reality. . . . Hence sin which indicates nothing save imperfection cannot consist in anything which expresses reality." 2 "I maintain that God is absolutely and really (as causa sui) the cause of all things which have essence (i.e., affirmative reality). . . . When you can prove to me that evil, error, crime, &c., are anything which ex- presses essence, then I will grant to you that God is the cause of evil. But I have sufficiently shown that that which constitutes the form of evil does not consist in any- thing which expresses essence, and therefore it cannot be said that God is the cause of it." 3 To the cursory reader of these passages both writers i Eth. iv. Pref. 2 Ep. 32. 3 Ep. 36. 72 Spinoza. seem to teach the same doctrine as to the nature of evil, and with a common object. To prove that God is not the author of evil, it seems to be the endeavour of both to show that no positive reality can be ascribed to it, and that physical and moral evil alike must be relegated to the category of negations or unrealities. But a little closer examination proves that a fundamental difference underlies this superficial similarity. The theory of Maimonides is essentially dualistic. To exonerate his supramundane Creator from the causation of evil, he adopts the Aristotelian distinction of form and matter, ascribing all that is positively good in the system of being to the former, and regarding evil as only the element of negation or limitation which necessarily clings to the latter. In so far as any finite being is redeemed from imperfection, the element of good that is in it is due to the divine causation ; in so far as imperfection still adheres to it, it is to be ascribed, not to the positive agency of God, but, so to speak, to the intractableness of the materials with which He has had to deal. Matter is essentially mutable ; pain, sickness, death are its inevit- able conditions ; only the life which arrests change and disintegration is due to God. Error and crime are not traceable to God, any more than the blunders and mis- takes of the blind to the author of the organ of vision. If reason were perfect there would be neither error nor sin ; and therefore the measure of knowledge and virtue which men possess is to be ascribed to the author of reason ; that they have no more, and therefore yield to irrational passions, is simply another Avay of saying that they are finite. God wills the good element which re- claims finite beings from matter ; the evil which shows Unreality of Evil. 73 that they are only partially reclaimed He can at most be said only to permit. It is not our business to criticise this theory, further than to point out its essentially dualistic character, and therefore its discordance with every system which, like that of Spinoza, maintains the absolute unity of the universe. Xot only does it start from the fundamental dualism of a supramundane Creator and a world lying outside of Him, but even in that world all does not spring from the will that creates it. God is not responsible for all that takes place in the world, simply because another principle, that of "matter," has there a role which is in- dependent of Him, and over which He can achieve at best only a partial victory. Spinoza, on the other hand, knows nothing of such an external Creator, or of any element of matter which possesses substantiality and independence. For him there is but one infinite sub- stance, outside of which nothing exists or can be con- ceived ; and all finite beings, corporeal and spiritual, are only modes of that one substance. Interpreted in the light of this fundamental principle, Spinoza's language with respect to the non-positive nature of evil means something with which the doctrine of Maimonides has no relation. Finite things, as such, have neither in their existence nor their essence any substantial reality. Everything that has a real existence, everything in nature and man that can be said to have any positive reality, is a modification or expression of the divine nature, and everything else that seems to be is only unreality, nonentity. If, then, we ask how it comes that we regard anything as evil, or ascribe reality to things that are injurious or wicked, the answer is that 74 Spinoza. this arises from the false substantiation which imagination or opinion gives to things finite. " Whatever we think injurious and evil, and, moreover, whatever we think to be impious, or unjust, or wicked, arises from this, that we conceive things in a distorted and mutilated fashion." ] As by means of the conceptions of number and measure, which are merely " aids of the imagination," we give a false independence to discrete parts of space, which is really one and continuous, so the negative element in individual things and actions, which have no reality apart from God, is only due to the false isolation or limitation which the imagination or the abstracting un- derstanding gives to them. Remove the fictitious limit by which they are distinguished from God, and the negation vanishes ; the positive element, which alone expresses their essence, is all that remains. Whether this view of the nature of evil be tenable or not, it is obviously one which has nothing in common with that of Maimonides. For the latter, God is not the author of evil, because the evil or negative element in things is to be ascribed to another and independent source : for Spinoza, God is not the cause of evil, because, from the point of view of the whole, contemplating the system of being in the only aspect in which it has any real or affirmative existence, evil vanishes away into illusion and nonentity. i Eth. iv. 73, dem. 75 CHAPTEE IV. GIORDANO BRUNO. ONE of the most remarkable writers of the transition period between medieval and modern philosophy is Giordano Bruno. His numerous works, poetical, scien- tific, philosophical, reflect the general characteristics of that period, modified in some respects by a strongly marked individuality. The revolt against authority, the almost exulting sense of intellectual freedom, the breaking down of the artificial division between things sacred and secular, human and divine, the revival of ancient philo- sophy, and resumption of its problems from a new and higher standpoint these and other distinctive features of the spirit of the time, and along with these the intellectual unsettlement and unrest, the predilection for occult sciences and arts, the tendency to commingle the dreams and vagaries of imagination with the results of rational investigation which marked some of its nobler yet more undisciplined minds, are vividly represented in Bruno's multifarious writings. In these it is vain to seek for systematic unity. They are the expression of a mind filled with intellectual enthusiasm, rich, versatile, original, yet undisciplined and erratic, feeling after truth, 76 Spinoza. and making random guesses now in this direction, now in that, pouring forth with almost inexhaustible pro- ductiveness speculations, theories, conjectures, under the impulse of the moment or the varying influence of external circumstances and of the intellectual atmosphere in which he moved. Betwixt such a mind as this and the clear, patient, disciplined intelligence of Spinoza, it would seem impossible to find any point of contact, and in the absence of any direct evidence we might be dis- posed to regard Spinoza's alleged obligations to Bruno as nothing more than accidental coincidences. It is true, indeed, that the absence of any reference to Bruno in Spinoza's writings does not settle the question, inasmuch as Spinoza was undoubtedly conversant with, and derived important suggestions from, authors whom he does not qiiote. But without attaching any weight to Spinoza's silence, the positive proof of his obligations would seem, at first blush, to consist only of a few verbal coincidences scarcely avoidable in writers treating of the same subjects, and more than overborne by the lack of any real affinity of thought. AVhen, however, we examine more closely the general drift of Bruno's philosophical writings the leading ideas which, though never developed into a coherent system, underlie his speculations concerning man and nature and God we shall find in them not a little which may be regarded as a kind of anticipation of Spinozism. The idea which seems to have dominated the mind of Bruno, and which, by means partly of Aristotelian categories, partly of Neo-Platonic emanation theories, he seeks in his various writings to explain and defend, is that of the divinity of nature and man. He was in profound sym- Bruno's Pantheism. 77 patliy with the revolt against the medieval notion of a transcendent God, and a sphere of divine things absolutely separated from nature and the secular life of mankind. The course of religious thought during the scholastic period had tended more and more to obscure the Christian idea of the unity of the divine and human. The ecclesiastical conception of God had gradually become that, not of a Being who reveals Himself in and to the human spirit, but of a Being above the world, and to whom thought can be related only as the passive re- cipient of mysterious dogmas authoritatively revealed. The false exaltation thus given to the idea of God led by obvious sequence to the degradation of nature, and the individual and social life of man. The observation of nature lost all religious interest for minds in which the divine was identified Avith the supernatural, and which found the indications of a divine presence not in the course of nature, but in interferences with its laws. In like manner, and for the same reason, the specially religious life became one of abstraction from the world, ami the secular life of man, its domestic, social, political relations, came to be regarded as outside of the sphere of spiritual tilings. It is easy to see how the reaction from this false separation of the natural and spiritual, the human and divine, should give rise, on the one hand, to the reawakened interest in nature which is indicated by the scientific revival of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, and on the other, to the pantheistic tendency in philosophy which gives their distinctive character to the speculative writings of Bruno. Both on the religioiis and the poetical side of his nature, Bruno recoiled from the conception of a supramuiidane God, and a world 78 Spinoza. in whose life and thought no divine element could be discerned. In the external world, in whose least phenomena science had begun to perceive the hid- den glory of intelligible order and law; in the inner world of mind, to whose boundless wealth of thought the consciousness of the time was becoming awakened, Bruno seemed to himself intuitively to discern, not the mere production of a distant omnipotence, but the im- mediate expression of a divine presence and life. And with the whole strength of his ardent nature he sought to give philosophic form and verification to this intuitive sense of a kingdom of heaven on earth. But religious and poetical feeling may instinctively grasp what reason is inadequate to justify. Bruno was a poet first and a philosopher only in the second place. And whatever in- direct influence his writings may have had on a greater mind, it needed a calmer intelligence and severer logic than his own to overtake the task he set himself to accomplish. "The true philosopher," says Bruno, "differs from th> theologian in this, that the former seeks the infinite Being, not outside the world, but within it. TVe must begin, in other words, by recognising the universal agent in creation, before attempting to rise to that elevated region in which theology finds the archetype of created beings." l Dismissing, then, the conception of a supramundane God, it is Bruno's aim to show how philosophy justifies the idea of an immanent relation of God to the world. When we examine his solution of the problem, it is found to consist partly in a recurrence to Neo-Platonic figures and analogies, partly in a manipu- 1 De la causa, pincipio et uno Wagner's edit., i. p. 175. Cf. Bartholmess, J. Bruno, ii. p. 130. The "Soul of the World." 79 lation of the Aristotelian categories of matter and form, of potentiality and actuality. To the former point of view belongs his elaborate exposition of the notion of a "soul of the world." The universe is to be conceived of as an infinite living organism, not created by any out- ward cause, but having the principle of all its existences and activities within itself. It is that beyond which nothing exists, in which all things live, and move, and have their being. This inward, ever- active, creative principle he compares to the principle of life in the root or seed, " which sends forth from itself shoots, branches, twigs, &c., which disposes and fashions the delicate tissue of leaves, flowers, fruit, and again, by the same interior energy, recalls the sap to the root." It is in one sense external, in another internal, to purely natural things ; the former, because it cannot be regarded as itself a part or element of the things it creates the latter, because it does not act on matter or outside of matter, but wholly from within, in the very bosom and heart of matter. He represents this first principle again as an "inner artist" of infinite productiveness and plastic power ; but it differs from a human artist in two respects : (1.) That the latter operates on matter which is already alive or instinct with form, whereas in the case of the former no such presupposition is involved. He argues, therefore, that though we may shrink from re- garding the universe as a living being, yet we cannot conceive any form which is not already, directly or in- directly, the expression of a soul, any more than we can conceive a thing which has absolutely no form. It would be absurd, indeed, to regard as living forms the productions of human art. My table, as such, is not 80 Spinoza. animate ; but inasmuch as its matter is taken from nature, it is composed of materials which are already living. There is nothing, be it ever so little or worth- less, that does not contain in it life or soul. 1 The human artist, in other words, works from without to communicate his own thought to materials which are taken from nature, and which have already, as part of nature, a life and being of their own ; but the divine or inner artist has no pre-existing materials on which to work. His art is creative, at once of the materials and of the in- finitely diversified forms imposed on them. Creative and formative energy are in Hun one and the same thing; and if He transmutes lower into higher forms of existence, the former are not taken from a sphere that is foreign or external to Him, but already instinct with His own life ; and the latter are only the same life putting forth a new expression of its inexhaustible energy. (2.) It is only a slightly varied form of the same thought when Bruno tells us that in the divine or inner artist, in con- trast with the human, the ideas of efficient and final cause are inseparable. In nature, he argues, the efficient cause cannot be separated from the final or ideal cause. Every reasonable act presupposes an end or design. That design is "nothing else than the form of the thing to he produced. From which it follows that an intelligence capable of producing all, and of raising them by a marvellous art from potentiality into actuality, should contain in itself the forms and essences of all things." 5 Since it is intelligence or the soul of the world which creates natural things, it is impossible that the formal 1 De la causa, i. p. 241. Cf. Bartholmess, ii. p. 135. 2 De la causa, i. p. 237. Cf. Bartholmess, ii. p. 134. Tlic Unircrsc an Organism. 81 should be absolutely distinct from the efficient cause. They must fall together in the inner principle of things. Bruno expresses the same thing in another way when he speaks of the universe as a living organism. In the work of a human artist the thought or conception lies outside of the materials on which he works, and in which it is by his plastic hand to be realised. But the thought or design which is at work in the creation of an organised structure, is not a mere mechanical cunning acting from without, shaping and adjusting matter accord- ing to an ingenious plan which is foreign to it. Here, on the contrary, the ideal principle or formative power goes with the matter, and constitutes its essence. Such a principle is supposed to be present from the beginning, inspiring the first minutest atom of the structure with the power of the perfect whole that is to be. The inner principle, the life within, is both first cause and last ; it makes the last first, and the first last. When, therefore, we apply this conception to the universe, what it brings before us is, not an extramundane omnipotent agent, creating and shaping things to accomplish an end out- side both of himself and them implying, therefore, some- thing originally lacking both to himself and the matter on which he operates but a universe which contains in itself the principle of its own being, a vast organism in which the power of the whole is working from the beginning, in which the least and most insignificant of finite existences presupposes and manifests the end to be realised, and in which the first principle is at once be- ginning and end of all. Had Bruno realised all that is contained in this conception, his philosophy might have gone beyond that of Spinoza, and anticipated much P. XIL F 82 Spinoza. which it was left for later speculative thought to develop. But when we follow the course of his speculations, and ask how from his fundamental thought he proceeds to explain the nature of God, and His relation to the world, we find that, under the limiting influence of scholastic or Aristotelian categories, the inherent wealth of his own idea escapes his grasp. With him as with a greater than he, the principle of abstract identity is in fatal opposition to that of concrete unity, or if the latter is faintly adumbrated in his conception of the soul of the world as a self-differentiating, self-integrating unity, the former speedily reasserts itself, so as to reduce the idea of God to a meaningless and barren abstraction, and the finite world to evanescence and unreality. In order to determine the nature of the first principle of all things, Bruno has recourse to the Aristotelian distinction of "form" and "matter." "Democritus and the Epicureans," says he, "hold that there is no real existence which is not corporeal ; they regard matter as the sole substance of things, and assert that it is itself the divine nature. These, with the Stoics and others, hold also that forms are simply the accidental dispositions of matter. ... A closer examination, however, forces us to re- cognise in nature two kinds of substances, form and matter. If, therefore, there is an active principle which is the constitutive principle of all, there is also a subject or passive principle corresponding to it, a something that is capable of being acted on as well as a something that is capable of acting. Human art cannot operate except on the surface of things already formed by nature; . . . but nature operates, so to speak, from the c-eiitre of its subject-matter, which is altogether unformed. Therefore the subject-matter of the arts is manifold, but the Matter and Form,. 83 subject-matter of nature is one, seeing that all diversity proceeds from form." 1 In this passage and elsewhere, what Bruno seeks to prove is, that the conceptions of matter and form are correlative, that neither can be apprehended in abstrac- tion from the other, and that the necessities of thought force us beyond them to another and higher conception, that of a primal substance which is neither matter alone nor form alone, but the unity of the two. We are led to the same result, he elsewhere shows, when we con- sider the supposed hard and fast distinction of sub- stances corporeal and incorporeal. " It is necessary that of all things that subsist there should be one principle of subsistence. . . . But all distinguishable things presuppose something indistinguishable. That indis- tinguishable something is a common reason to which, the difference and distinctive form are added." Just as sen- sible objects presuppose a sensible subject, intelligible objects an intelligible subject " So it is necessary that there be one thing which corresponds to the common reason of both subjects, ... a first essence which contains in itself the principle of its being. If body, as is generally agreed, presupposes a matter which is not body, and which therefore naturally precedes that which we designate as properly corporeal, we cannot admit any absolute incompatibility between matter and the substances which we name immaterial. ... If we discern something formal and divine in corporeal substances, on the same principle we must ?ay that there is something material in divine sub- stances. As Plotinus says, if the intelligible world contains an infinite variety of existences, there must be in them, along 1 De la causa, p. 251. 84 Spinoza. with tlieir characteristic differences, something which they all have in common, and that common element takes the place of matter as the distinctive element takes that of form. . . . This common basis of things material and immaterial, in so far as it includes a multiplicity of forms, is multiple and many-formed, but in itself it is absolutely simple and indi- visible ; and because it is all, it cannot be itself any one par- ticular being." l Such considerations do not suggest the idea of a Supreme Being (an extramundane God), "but of the soul of the world as the actuality of all, the poten- tiality of all, and all in all Whence, though there are innumerable individuals, yet everything is one." 2 " There is one form or soul, one matter or body, which is the fulfilment of all and the perfection of all, which cannot be limited or determined, and is therefore un- changeable." 3 These quotations may suffice to show what is the gen- eral drift of Bruno's speculations. The result to which his reasoning leads is not that which he intended or supposed himself to have attained. His obvious aim was to attain to a first principle Avhich should be the living source and explanation of all finite existences, material and spiritual. But owing to the false method by which he proceeds, what he does reach is, not a unity which comprehends, but a unity which excludes, all determinations not a being which embraces in its concrete unity the whole in- exhaustible wealth of the finite world, but an empty abstraction from which all content has been evaporated. Finding that the ideas of matter and form, and again of 1 De la cam a, Wagner, i. pp. 269, 270, 272. 2 Ibid., i . s ibid., p. 280. His Unity an Abstraction. 85 corporeal and spiritual, cannot be held apart, but that when we attempt to think it, each implies and falls over into the other, he yet does not rise to a higher unity, a unity which transcends, yet at the same time compre- hends both. Hence his only available resource is to find his higher unity in that which matter and form, mind and body, have in common when their differences are eliminated. But by thinking of that which mind has in common with body, or form with matter, we do not reach a unity which is higher and richer than both, any more than we do so when we think of that which gold has in common with silver or copper. A generic unity, in other words, is a mere logical abstraction which has less content than the lowest individual it is supposed to embrace. In short, like many other thinkers before and after him, Bruno conceived himself to be explaining the differences and contrarieties of existence by the simple process of eliminating or ignoring them. And his first or highest principle (which he identified with God), in which he conceived himself to have reached the origin and end of all things, was nothing more than the abstrac- tion of " Being," which is logically higher, simply because it is poorer in content, not merely than matter or mind, but than the lowest of finite existences. And if thus his idea of God or the infinite was depleted of all content or reality, it fared no better, and for the same reason, with his idea of the finite world. What he sought for was a first principle or " soul of the world," in which all finite existences should find their being and reality. The solution of this problem, therefore, implied at once the nothingness of all finite being apart from God, and their reality in God. His fundamental notion 86 Spinoza. of an organic unity imposed on him the necessity of explaining the universe as an organism in which the members are nothing but dead, meaningless fragments in separation from the life or vital principle of the whole ; but also the necessity of showing that through their re- lation to that principle they cease to be such unreal abstractions. His method certainly enabled him, as he himself saw, to achieve the former of these results viz., that of reducing all finite existences, as such, to evanescence and nothingness. " In its externality," says he, " nature is nothing more than a shadow, an empty image of the first principle in which potentiality and actuality are one. . . . Thou art not nearer to the infinite by being man rather than insect, by being star rather than sun. And what I say of these I understand of all things whose subsistence is particular. Now, if all these particular things are not different in the infinite, they are not really different. Therefore the universe is still one, and immovable. It comprehends all and admits of no difference of being, nor of any change with itself or in itself. It is all that can be, and in it is no difference of potentiality and actuality. 1 . . . Individuals which continually change do not take a new existence, but only a ne\v manner of being. It is in this sense that Solomon has said, ' There is nothing new under the sun, but that which is was before.' As all things are in the universe and the universe is in all things, as we are in it and it is in us, so all concur to one perfect unity, which is sole, stable, and ever remaining. It is one and eternal. Every form of existence, every other thing is vanity, every thing outside of that one is nothing." 2 But whilst Bruno thus proved the unreality of all finite existences apart from the first principle, the si nil i De la causa, i. p. 281. - Ibid., - Relation to Spinoza. 87 or substance of the world, what he failed to prove, and from the self-imposed conditions of his method could not prove, was that even in their relation to the first principle any reality was left to them. Regarded as that which is reached by abstraction from the limits of finite existences, the first principle does not explain, it simply annuls them. Their distinction from God is their finitude, and the withdrawal of their finitude, which makes them one with God, makes them lost in God. They are only figures carved out in the infinitude of space, and, like figures in space, they vanish when the defining lines are withdrawn. Such then, in substance, is Bruno's contribution to that problem with which, directly or indirectly, all speculative thought attempts to deal. It would be to forestall the exposition of the Spinozistic system to at- tempt here, save in a very general way, to answer the question, What, if any, traces are to be found in it of the influence of this writer on the mind of its author? At first sight there woidd seem to be discordances as great between the leading ideas of Bruno and of Spinoza as between the glowing, imaginative, poetical manner and style of the former, stamped throughout with the personality of the writer, and the rigid mathematical mould, excluding every trace of personal feeling, in which the ideas of the latter are cast. What point of contact, for instance, can be discerned between Spinoza's view of the universe as a system in which all things fol- low from the idea of infinite substance by as strict logical deduction as the properties of a triangle from its defini- tion, and Bruno's conception of an infinite organism in- 88 Spitioza. stinct with the freedom, the activity, the perpetual change and variety of life, and in which the first principle is for ever manifesting itself, with the spontaneity and in- exhaustible productiveness of art, in the forms and aspects of the world 1 Yet perhaps a closer examination may lead to the conclusion that, with many apparent and some real differences between the two systems, in their essential principle and in the results to which it leads, there is a real affinity between them. Both seek to justify for thought that idea of the absolute unity of all things which is the presupposition of all science and of all philosophy. Both seek to explain the universe from itself, to the exclusion of any external or arbitrary cause, as implying a virtual abandonment of the problem to be solved. In the idea of God both endeavour to find, not an inexplicable supramundane Creator, but the immanent cause or principle of the world. In both there is a sense in which the words " God " and "Nature " are interchangeable. In Bruno, the first principle is the union of potentiality and actuality ; and whether you consider it as a principle which realises itself in the actual, and call it God, or as all actuality in relation to its principle, and call it Nature, it is only one and the same thing contemplated from different sides. In Spinoza, Substance is that beyond which nothing exists or can be conceived, and Nature understood as the whole finite world, including all possible modifications of an infinite number of infinite attributes in their relation to Substance, or in so far as they are expressions of it is only another name for the same universe regarded from a different point of view. Finally, in both systems the logical ru- Bruno and Spinoza. 89 suit falls short of the aim and intention of the author, and the failure in both cases arises, to some extent at least, from the same cause viz., the attempt to reach a concrete, by a method that can yield only an abstract, unity. We have seen how in Bruno the infinite living organism, which was his ideal of the universe, reduces itself to a God who is only a bare self-identical abstrac- tion, in which the finite is lost or annulled. And in the sequel we shall find that Spinozism is, from one point of view, the ambiguous result of two conflicting elements a self-identical, undetermined substance which is all in one, and a world of finite individualities, each of which has a being and reality of its own. It is the obvious in- tention of the author to bring these two elements into the unity of a perfect system to find in Substance the origin and explanation of finite existences, and also to bring back all the individualities of the finite world into unity in their relation to the one infinite substance. But the relation between the two elements is only asserted, never demonstrated. The absolutely undetermined is, by its very definition, precluded from going forth out of itself into a world of finite determinations ; and if we start from the latter, they can only be brought back to the former by the destruction of their finitude, and their absorption in the infinite all. From these considerations it seems to follow that, whatever weight we attach to the external evidence of Spinoza's indebtedness to Bruno, in the movement of thought in both writers, in the principle from which they start, the end at which they aim, their partial suc- cess, and the reason of their failure, a close resemblance 90 Spinoza. may be traced. Whether, in point of fact, we can affili- ate Spinoza's system to the speculations of his predeces- sor is doubtful, but it must at least be conceded that the philosophy of the former betrays tendencies which, had he been acquainted with Bruno's writings, would have led him to recognise in the latter a spirit akin to his own. 91 CHAPTER V. DESCARTES. THE philosophy and the theology of modern times start from a common origin, and a certain analogy may be traced, at least in their earlier stages, in the course of development through which they passed. What first strikes us in studying that development is its apparent inconsistency with its origin. The principle of freedom is the common source of both, yet in both it speedily passes into a doctrine of absolutism which seems to be the complete negation of freedom. From a move- ment in which everything seems to be grounded on the individual consciousness, we are brought almost imme- diately to a theory of the universe in which God is so conceived of as to leave to the world and man no inde- pendence or reality. In religion, the assertion of the right of private judgment gives rise to a theology of absolute predestination and " irresistible grace." In philosophy the principle of self -consciousness, as the source of all knowledge and the criterion of certitude, develops into a system of uncompromising pantheism. Yet a little reflection will show that the transition thus indicated involves no real inconsistency. The prin- 92 Spinoza. ciple of the Protestant Reformation was, indeed, the assertion of spiritual freedom. It expressed the revolt of the reawakening religious consciousness against ex- ternal mediation or authority in matters of faith. It is implied in the very idea of religion that the human spirit is essentially related to the divine, and that in seeking to realise that relation it is attaining to a deeper consciousness of itself. By whatever outward means the knowledge of God and of divine things may "be con- veyed to us, it is not religious knowledge until it has been grasped by the spiritual consciousness and has found its witness therein. The ultimate criterion of truth must lie not without, but within, the spirit. The voice of God must find its response in the heart and conscience of him to whom it speaks, and nothing can hold good for him as true or divine which has not re- ceived its authentication in the " assurance of faith." But whilst nothing, it would seem, can be more thorough- going than this assertion of spiritual freedom, it involves and directly leads to what might easily be regarded as the negation of such freedom. Religious knowledge is the revelation to man at once of freedom and of absolute dependence ; of freedom, because it is to consciousness that truth appeals, and by the activity of consciousness that truth is apprehended of absolute dependence, be- cause at the very first step of our entrance into the king- dom of truth, we find ourselves in a region where nothing can be made or unmade by us, in the presence of an author- ity which dominates our will and claims the complete submission of our thoughts. The very act of entering into it involves the renunciation of all individual opin- ions, inclinations, prejudices, of everything that pertains Principle of the Reformation. 93 to me merely as this individual self. It implies, more- over, the recognition by the individual self, not merely of its finitude and dependence, but of its moral blindness and weakness. Truth must find its witness in the con- sciousness ; but the consciousness to which it appeals is that not of the natural man, but of the spiritual. The response which it awakens is that not of the individual self, but of a higher or universal self, with which the former is not in harmony. It is therefore the revelation to me not merely of a universal reason to which the in- dividual consciousness must subject itself, but of an absolute moral authority, an infinite will at once in me and above me, before which I am self-condemned and helpless. Religion begins with the sense of moral guilt and impotence ; but the presupposition which this in- volves is that of an infinite will with which my finite will is not in harmony, and to which it is only by the absolute renunciation of any individual independence, that I can ever be reconciled. It is from this point of view that we can understand how, from the principle of Protestantism, the early Reformers should be led to that idea of God which constitutes the primary doctrine of their theological system. The principle which was at the root of the Protestant Reformation found thus its first expression in the sphere of religion, and it was here that the human spirit first attained emancipation from that bondage to authority in which it had been held. But the century of the Refor- mation is the beginning also of a new epoch in philo- sopli}' ; and both in its origin and development, a close analogy can be traced between the philosophical and the religious movement. Speculative thought felt the same 94 Spinoza. impulse with religion to liberate itself from the presup- positions which had hitherto fettered it, and to assert its autonomy in its own sphere. And here, too, the individual consciousness seemed to employ its regained freedom only in subjecting itself to a new and more absolute limita- tion. In this point of view the philosophy of Descartes may be compared to the first assertion of religious liberty by the Reformers, and the philosophy of Spinoza springs from it by the same movement of thought which gaA'e birth to the predestinarian theories of Luther and Calvin. In general, the philosophy of Descartes expresses the effort of intelligence to bring all things within -its own sphere, to find within thought the explanation of all the problems of thought. Formally stated, Descartes' search after an ultimate criterion of certitude was the endeavour to give to all that claims to be knowledge the form of self-consciousness. The process by which he represents himself as reaching this criterion is indeed, when closely examined, one which already virtually implies it. In the search for intellectual satisfaction he begins by re- solving to reject everything which it is possible to doubt. When we examine the contents of ordinary knowledge, we find it to consist of a mass of unsifted and incongru- ous materials of impressions, opinions, beliefs, which reason has never tested, and which have no other than an accidental connection with each other. They have been blindly accepted on authority or by tradition, they have fallen upon the mind in the form of instinctive impressions, they have been woven together by arbitrary associations. When rejection is awakened, there are Criterion of Certitude. 95 none of them which it cannot doubt, and, at least pro- visionally, reject ; not authoritative dogmas and beliefs, for these by their very definition have no inherent cer- tainty ; not things we seem to perceive by the senses, for the senses often deceive us, and what once deceives may do so always ; not even mathematical propositions, for, as we are not the makers of our own minds, it is at least conceivable that they are the creation of some malicious or mocking spirit who has so constructed them as, even in their seemingly demonstrative certainties, to be mistaking error for truth. But when, by this process of elimination, I have got rid of or provisionally rejected one after another of the elements of that accidental con- glomerate of beliefs which I have hitherto accepted, is there nothing that remains, no primeval rock of certitude, or fundamental basis of knowledge unassailable by doubt 1 And the answer is, that when everything else has been doubted, there is one thing which lies beyond the reach of doubt, which in the very process of doubting I tacitly affirm. I cannot doubt the doubter. Doubt is thought, and in thinking I cannot but affirm the existence of the thinker. From everything else I can abstract, but I cannot abstract from myself who performs the process of abstraction. Coyito, ergo sum. In this account which Descartes gives of the way in which he seemed to himself to have reached an ultimate principle of certitude, it is obvious that he tacitly presup- poses from the outset the principle of which he is in quest. When he sets out by saying, " I will question everything which I can doxibt," he virtually posits the " I " as the umpire by whose verdict everything is to be decided. In this, as in every other possible investigation which it can 96 Spinoza. undertake, thought presupposes itself. In bringing any- thing to the bar of consciousness, consciousness presumes its own reality. Nay, we can go further, and say that in every act of intelligence, in the most rudimentary exercise of thought by which I bring any object before me, I presuppose myself as the thinking subject to which that object is referred. And this, further, enables us to see what is the real significance of Descartes' fundamental principle. As has been often pointed out, the proposition, " I think, therefore I am," is only in form syllogistic. As its author himself expressly says, it is not an argument based on the major premiss, " Whatever thinks exists," for the terms of that premiss would have no meaning save what is derived from the prior intuition of the unity of being and thought. Gogito ergo sum is, therefore, simply the expression of that unity as the ultimate datum of consciousness. In saying " I am conscious," the " I " and the consciousness predicated of it cannot be separated. In affirming the consciousness we affirm the I. Descartes' proposition, therefore, is the assertion of the indissoluble unity of thought and reality in self-consciousness as the fundamental principle on which all knowledge rests. Descartes had now attained the principle of which he was iu quest; but the inquiry would have been fruitless unless in that principle he had found not only that which is al isolutely certain in itself, but that which is the source of all other certainties, the idea by means of which we can advance to rehabilitate the world which doubt has destroyed. If this principle is not to remain a mere barren abstraction, a form of knowledge without content, it must enable us to recover, as objects of rational and Britain knowledge, what had been rejected as a congeries Principle of Self-Consciousness. 97 of unsifted beliefs. How, then, asks Descartes, shall we find iu self-consciousness the key to all knowledge 1 Now the failure or success of any attempt to answer this ques- tion must, it is easy to see, turn upon the sense in which the principle itself is understood. "Whether the proposi- tion, " I in thinking am," or more briefly, " I think," is to be fruitful or barren, depends on the part of it on which the emphasis is thrown. If the latter term be limited by the former, if, in other words, the thought or self-conscious- ness here affirmed be taken as merely subjective and individual, the proposition contains in it the beginning and end of all knowledge. In the empirical fact of his own self-consciousness there is nothing which enables the individual to transcend his own individuality. Thought that is purely mine can build for itself no bridge by which it can pass to a world that lies, by supposition, wholly beyond it. The future history of philosophy was to show, in the vain endeavours of the empirical psychologists, from Locke downwards, to solve this problem, that individualism imprisons the mind in its own isolated consciousness, and can never attain to the legitimate knowledge of the nature or even of the existence of any reality beyond it. On the other hand, the principle of self-consciousness may be so construed as to become in itself the fraitful source of knowledge, and the test by which all know- ledge can be evaluated. What it may be understood to mean is, that beyond all difference of thought and being, of thought and its object, there is a unity which alone makes this difference intelligible, a unity which is the first presupposition of all affirmation about the particular subject and the particular object. Or to state it differ- p. XIL c 98 Spinoza. cntly, it may mean that whilst I caii abstract from ev-ry- thing else, I cannot abstract from the being which is iden- tical with thought. That being is not the being of my particular self ; for that too, like every other particular contingent existence, I can in one sense abstract from. I can make it an object of observation, I can think of it, and I can think it away, as that which was not and might not be. But the self from which I cannot ab- stract, the self which is identical with thought, is that for which not only I, this particular individual, am, but for which and in which I and all things are. So far from shutting me up in a mere subjective experience, with a world of realities lying beyond and inaccessible, self-consciousness, thus understood, is that which contains in it the possibility of all knowledge. It is that which is presupposed in all knowledge and to which all realities are relative. In which of these senses did Descartes understand his own fundamental principle? In his endeavour to re- construct the world by means of it, did he employ it in the sense in which it is altogether inadequate for the task, or in the sense in which a system of knowledge can legitimately be based on it? The answer is, that he did neither, bitt wavered between the two radically inconsistent interpretations, and whilst his system con- tains much that implies or points towards the higher view, he neither grasps it firmly nor carries it out to its logical results. Yet even the arbitrary expedients which he employs to extract more from his first prin- ciple than, in the narrower sense, it could yield, proves that the wider construction of it was that towards which he unconsciously tended, though it was left for Mind and Mattt /-. 99 other and more consequent thinkers to discern its full significance. To say that self-consciousness is that to which all things are relative, is to say that the world is an in- telligible world, and that betwixt mind and matter, thought and being, there is no essential division, and no necessity, therefore, to go in search of some third principle to mediate between them. Such a necessity, however, Descartes creates for himself. The do\ibt or provisional negation of external things by which the affirmation of a conscious self had been reached, he speedily hardens into an absolute negation. It is through the opposition of a not-self that mind realises itself. How then can that conscious self which exists only as it opposes itself to that which is not-self, which knows itself only in abstracting from a world without, hold any in- telligent converse therewith? In attempting to know anything beyond itself, is not consciousness committing a virtually suicidal act? This difficulty was rendered more formidable for Descartes by the view he takes of the essentially distinctive nature of mind and matter. Mind and matter are independent substances, each having its own determining or characteristic attribute. The characteristic attribute of mind is thought or self- consciousness, that of matter is extension, and these two can only be understood in a sense which renders them reciprocally contradictory. Thought or self-consciousness is that which is absolutely self-included and indivisible. We can ideally distinguish in it that which thinks and that which is object of thought ; but they do not lie out- side of each other, they are indivisible elements in the unity of self-consciousness. But if this z'tensiveness is 1 00 Spinoza. the essence of mind, that of matter is the very opposite or contradiction of this extension, self-externality, ex- istence which consists of parts outside of parts, without any centre of unity. Mind is self-consciousness; mat- ter, on the other hand, is absolute selflessness. Now then, between things which by their very definition are reciprocally exclusive, can there be any communion 1 How can that whose very being is to be selfless become related to that whose very being is to be a conscious self? In passing into mind, matter must cease to be matter ; in going forth to apprehend matter, mind must cease to be mind. The expedient by which ultimately Descartes en- deavours to overcome this difficulty is, as we shall see, that of arbitrarily depriving the two independent sub- stances of their independence and reciprocal exclusive- ness by reducing them to moments of a third and higher substance. Whilst the distinctive attribute which makes each a substance with reference to the other remains, their opposition is mediated by the absolute substance, God, on whom the existence of both depends. But this attempt to overcome the dualism of mind and matter presents itself first in a somewhat cruder and more mechanical form. Mind and matter are essentially op- posed ; but God becomes the guarantee to mind of the truthfulness of its ideas of matter. Mind has no im- mediate certainty of the truth of these ideas ; it simply finds them in itself. They convey no assurance of any objective reality corresponding to them. It is conceiv- able, as was formerly supposed, that our notions of material things, or even of the existence of an external world, may be illusions. But our idea of God is that Idea of God. 101 of an all-perfect Being, one of whose perfections is ab- solute veracity or truthfulness. If, therefore, in the mind which owes to Him its existence we find certain clear and distinct ideas of matter or of external realities, the veracity of God is the unquestionable security that these ideas are true. Ideas of things which we could not otherwise trust, we can trust as implanted in us by a God that cannot lie. Arbitrary and forced as this method of solving the problem before him seems to be, what it really indicates is, that Descartes had discerned the inadequacy of a merely individualistic principle of knowledge, and had begun to see that the consciousness of the individual is implicated with a consciousness wider and more abso- lute than itself. And this becomes more obvious when we go on to consider how Descartes contrives, without any conscious departure from his fundamental principle, to extract from it the idea of God and the proof of His objective existence. In two ways consciousness seems to him to testify to something more absolute than itself. In the first place, he finds in it an idea which, from its very nature, cannot be traced to any finite source, and which therefore witnesses to an in- finite Being as its cause or archetype. Whatever real- ity, he argues, any thing or idea contains, at least as much must be contained in its cause. If I find in myself an idea which contains more reality than is contained in my own nature or could be derived or collected from other finite natures, I may conclude that there is a being containing in himself an amount of reality transcending that of all finite existence. Such an idea is that of God, the infinite substance, 102 Spinoza. and it could only have been implanted in me by an actually existing God. To this argument it is easy to take exception, on the obvious ground that it presupposes the thing which it is intended to prove that it seeks to deduce from conscious- ness, or one of the ideas of consciousness, a being who is to guarantee the veracity of consciousness ; and further, that it attempts to find in thought the proof of some- thing outside of thought or unthinkable in other words, to make thought transcend itself. Yet the flaw is only in the form, not in the real though implicit significance of the argument. The being who contains in himself all perfections is still a being thought of in a most defi- nite way. Seeming to himself to have forced a path outward to a region beyond consciousness, Descartes is still within it ; and what he has really achieved is vir- tually to expand the sphere of self-consciousness till it embraces that which transcends all that is finite and individual. The secret nerve of the argument, and that which constituted its motive and significance, was, that there is an infinite element in thought, or that the con- sciousness of the individual, when closely examined, is seen to be implicated with or dominated by a universal consciousness, or a consciousness of the infinite. The contrast between the apparent and the real signi- ficance of the argument becomes still more obvious in the second form in which Descartes presents it, and which is only a modification of the "ontological argu- ment " of Anselm and Aquinas. The objective existence of God is involved in the very idea of God. Amongst the various ideas in our minds we find one, the highest of all that of a Being supremely wise and powerful and Ontological Argument. 103 absolutely perfect ; and Ave perceive that this idea, unlike others, contains in it the characteristic, not of possible or contingent, but of absolutely necessary existence. In the same way, therefore, as from the fact that the idea of a triangle necessarily involves that its angles should be equal to two right angles, we conclude that every triangle must have this property ; so from the fact that the idea of an absolutely perfect being includes in it that of existence, we conclude that such a being must necessarily exist. Here again the argument, though faulty in the form in which Descartes presents it, is valuable as indicating the untenableness of ' his origi- nal standpoint, and the inevitable tendency to read into it a new and deeper meaning. If self -consciousness is only individual, and we suppose a world of realities lying outside of it, it is impossible to conclude from self- existence or any other element of an idea in us that there is any actual reality corresponding to it any more than, according to Kant's familiar illustration, I can infer from the idea of a hundred dollars in my mind that I have them in my purse. That equality of its angles to two right angles is a necessary element of the idea of a triangle, proves no more than that //' any actual triangle exists, it will possess this property ; and that necessary existence belongs to the idea of God, merely prove-; that if there is a being corresponding to the idea, he exists necessarily. By no. straining, therefore, could the principle of self-consciousness, if regarded as merely individualistic, break down, in this case any more than in any other, the barrier between the subjective self and the world of realities opposed to it. But what Descartes was really aiming at was a self-consciousness which is 104 Spinoza. not individual but universal, or the principle that the real presupposition of knowledge is not the individual's consciousness of himself as an individual, but the thought or consciousness of a self which is beyond all individual selves and their objects that, viz., of universal or abso- lute intelligence. Other existences may be contingent, other things may or may not be ; but behind all our ideas there is one which, whether we are explicitly or only implicitly conscious of it, so proves its reality from thought, that thought becomes impossible without it. Its absolute reality is so fundamental to thought, that to doubt it is to doubt reason itself. This was the goal to Avhich Descartes was tending. Had he reached it, the principle of individual freedom with which he started would have converted itself into another form, which is either the pantheistic suppression of freedom, or the re- establishment of it on a deeper basis. In his own hands, however, it remained in the imperfect form in which it served only to introduce into his system a new element absolutely inconsistent with the principle from which he started. The foregoing view of the tendency and results of the Cartesian philosophy will be borne out if we consider, further, how near Descartes comes to the abandonment in express terms of his original for a different stand- point; in other words, to the recognition of the truth that it is not the consciousness of self but the con- sciousness of God which is the first principle of know- ledge. "VYhat he had represented to himself as the ori- ginal certainty of self had been reached by doubting everything else ; but it was not the doubt that had created the certitude, but the certitude that had ere- Infinite and Finite. 105 ated the doubt. It was the implicit presence of a standard of reality that had led him to pronounce his first notions of things illusory and unreal. The idea that was the prius in the process of doubt was not that of the things doubted, but the idea or conscious- ness of self. In like manner when he conies to con- sider the relation of the idea of God to other ideas, or of the idea of the infinite to that of the finite, he expressly maintains that the idea of infinite and neces- sary being does not arise by abstraction or negation from that of finite, contingent being, but conversely, that it is the presence in the mind of the idea of in- finite and necessary being that enables us to pronounce any other existences to be finite and contingent. " I ought not to think," says he, " that I perceive the in- finite only by negation of the finite, as I perceive rest and darkness by negation of motion and light ; on the contrary, I clearly perceive that there is more of reality in infinite substance than in finite, and therefore that, in a certain sense, the idea of the infinite is prior in me to that of the finite." In other words, the idea of the infi- nite is presupposed in that of the finite ; the former is the positive idea, the latter produced merely by nega- tion or limitation of it. It is really, though uncon- sciously, the idea of God from which we start, and from which our ideas of other existences as finite are derived. But if this be so, it is to be observed that we have here the complete subversion of Descartes' original principle of knowledge. For, in the first place, amongst the ideas of finite things to Avhich that of the infinite is now pronounced the prius, must be included the idea of the finite individual self. And in the 106 Spinoza. second place, the cogito ergo sum was, as we can now see, only his proof of God in another form. In the latter, he finds in his mind an idea which, in contrast with all ideas of merely finite, contingent existences, is that of infinite or necessary existence. In the former he found in his mind an idea which, in contrast with all ideas he could douht or deny, was ahsolutely certain. The starting-point and the process are in both cases the same. What he denies or reduces to negativity and contingency in contrast with the idea of God, is pre- cisely the same with what he denied or reduced to illusion and nullity in contrast with the idea of self. The conclusion he reaches must be in both cases the same. And that the self of the one process is really identical with the God of the other, is further obvious from this, that doubt is possible, not through the cer- tainty of self, but through the certainty of absolute truth. In doubting or denying anything, the tacit appeal is not to a finite but to an infinite standard, not to the idea of the subjective self, but to that of absolute objec- tive reality. The self of the cogito ergo sum was there- fore not really the individual self, but that infinite which he now pronounces to be the jn-ius in thought of all finite existences. But though logically Descartes' own express admis- sion implied the abandonment of his former for a new principle of knowledge, he did not himself recognise or admit the implication. To save his OAvn consistency he has recourse to a distinction which is simply the ac- knowledgment of the unresolved dualism which charac- terises his system. In order to retain the cogito ergo .-unit as a first principle, whilst yet asserting that God or the Knoiviny and Belay. 107 infinite is in thought the prf-us of the finite, he distin- guishes between the principle of knowledge (jprincipittim cognoscendi) and the principle of being (principium essendt), assigning the former role to the Ego, the latter to God. But a philosophical system fails by its own showing, if it does not give to all with which it deals the unity of knowledge. What, as a philosophy, it undertakes to do, is to explain the world as an intel- ligible world to trace rational relations between all existences and orders of being, to make them mem- bers of one system by showing how all are expressions of one principle to which all their differences can be brought back. To make Being, therefore, something apart from and irreducible to the principle of know- ledge, is virtually to confess the inadequacy of the system and of the principle on which it is based to save that principle by admitting that there is something it cannot explain. For Descartes the true escape from his dilemma would have been by admitting the conclu- sion to which his own hesitating language logically pointed that God or the infinite is first in knowledge as well as first in being. To separate the existence of God from the idea of God, and make the latter only the proof of the former, was the impossible attempt to go outside of knowledge for the explanation of know- ledge ; and it was an attempt which his own account of that idea rendered wholly arbitrary and self-contra- dictory. For what alone can be meant by an innate or implanted idea of God is simply the indwelling or activity of God in xis. To infer the existence of God from the idea of God, is to infer the existence of God from the consciousness of it, or to infer the existence of 108 Spinoza. God from itself. There is no advance to something new in thinking of the existence of God, when in thought I have already His necessary existence. The idea is already the existence of God. " I think God, there- fore God is," is no more a syllogism in which exist- ence is inferred from thought than cogito eryo sum is such a syllogism. The existence and the thought arc given in one act, inseparably united. It was because Descartes failed to perceive this that the unity to which his system tended was left still encumbered with a dualistic element. Finally, it is to be remarked that the dualism which remains unresolved in Descartes' view of the relation of God and the world, continues of necessity unresolved in his conception of the relation of mind and matter, of soxil and body. If the infinite be arbitrarily separated from the finite, the latter necessarily breaks into irreconcilable oppositions. Thought and being divided at the source cannot be united in the streams. Accordingly, mind and matter, the world Avithin and the world without, remain, in Descartes' view, independent entities tied together only by an arbitrary bond. They are, as we have seen, so defined as to be each the absolute negation of the other. The two are conceived of only as substances recip- rocally exclusive, and their very nature consists in fa-ii/i/ reciprocally exclusive. It would seem, therefore, impos- sible that two substances so defined should be united in one system or brought into any real relation to each other. To be so would imply that mind should cease to be mind, or matter matter that mind should become extended, or matter think. All the devices, therefore, l>y which Descartes endeavours to include them in one Sithordinate Substances. 109 system, are expedients to knit together what has been irreparably rent asunder. Mind has in it ideas of cor- poreal things ; but these ideas have no real but only a representative relation to external objects, and they are not the mind's own, but due to an outside power who mechanically inserts or infuses them and vouches for their truth. Body and soul are not in themselves re- lated to each other ; they are not correlative factors of a whole which explains at once their difference and their unity, but independent substances brought and kept together by an external and unintelligible force. Thus matter and mind fall asunder, and that which is supposed to unite them does not unite them for thought. There being nothing in their own nature which unites them, an arbitrary act of power, even when it is des- ignated omnipotent, explains nothing, but is merely another way of saying that somehow or another they are united. There is indeed one form of explanation to which, with marks of hesitation, Descartes' language seems finally to point, and which, in so far as it is a conceiv- able explanation, indicates the ultimate goal to which his philosophy leads. The dualism which is only verb- ally solved by reference to an inexplicable act of power, finds at least a possible solution when the extended and thinking substances are subordinated to an absolute or infinite substance in which their differences are lost. But in order to this solution two things are necessary : in the first place, the subordinate substances must be deprived of their substantial character and reduced to attributes or accidents ; and in the second place, the common substance in which they are united must be 1 10 Spinoza. conceived of as something underlying yet different from both. And this, accordingly, is the process by which Descartes effected his final solution of the problem be- fore him, the restoring to unity of his disintegrated universe. Substance, he tells us, is " that which so exists that it needs nothing else in order to its exist- ence." But in this sense the notion cannot be applied to finite, created existences. Mind and matter retain, indeed, each its substantial character and distinguishing attribute with reference to the other ; but with reference to God they lose their independence and exclusiveness, and become, as absolutely dependent, moments or acci- dents of His being. Further, the supreme or absolute substance in which mind and matter find their reality must be something in which their distinctive charac- teristics no longer exist, a unity which is different from both. Though elsewhere, therefore, Descartes speaks of the nature of God as having a nearer affinity to mind than to matter, yet, contemplated as substance, he expressly declares that nothing can be predicated in the same sense of God and finite creatures. The quali- ties of matter He cannot have, for matter is divisible and imperfect ; and if thought can be ascribed to Him, it is in Him something essentially different from thought in man. God is therefore for us simply the unknown something which remains when we abstract from nature and man their distinctive attributes. He is neither matter nor thought, and if He can be conceived at all, it is only as the bare abstraction of Being which is common to both. It is little wonder that Descartes' language should become hesitating and ambiguous when he seems to be Pantheistic Tendency. Ill led by his own logic to a conception which, instead of explaining the differences of the finite world, seems to suppress or annul them which, having absorbed nature and man in God, reduces God Himself to a lifeless abstraction of which we can say nothing but that it i*. But whilst Descartes, recoiling from the pantheistic abyss to the brink of which he had been led, refuses to commit himself in definite terms to this result, it was left for another and more resolute thinker to follow out his principles to their legitimate conclusion. 112 Spinoza. NOTE. The treatise ' De Deo et Homine,' which has been brought to light in recent times, may be regarded as a kind of study for Spinoza's greater and more systematic work, the ' Ethics.' For the student of his philosophy its chief interest lies in the fact that the ideas of the later work are here presented to us in an inchoate and cruder form. As the title indi- cates, the subject of the earlier work is the same as that of the later ; the succession of topics is the same in both, and we find in them many coincidences both of thought and expression. But the earlier treatise is less coherent and complete. There is much in it conceptions, definitions, phrases, scholastic and theological formulae which are not found in the ' Ethics,' and which can only be regarded as survivals from a more immature stage of thought. At the outset Spinoza seems to be hesitating between different start- ing-points, and making trials of fundamental principles which are essentially inconsistent. There are many gaps in the logical sequence of thought, dialogues are interposed which interrupt the main argument, and an appendix is added in which the doctrines of the work are re-discussed from a different point of view. But with all these differ- ences the general character of the two works is the same. They bear the stamp of the same mind, only of the same mind at an earlier and a later stage of its philosophical de- velopment. In the former we see the writer feeling his way to ideas concerning God and man which reappear in the latter, freed from irrelevances and inconsequences, as the final result of his speculations. It was my intention, as formerly indicated, to prepare for the criticism and interpretation of the ' Ethics ' by a care- ful examination of the treatise ' De Deo et Homine.' Such an examination, however, would have extended this book greatly beyond the limits assigned to it. I have there- fore been compelled to omit this part of my general plan. 113 CHAPTEE VI. THE ' ETHICS ' ITS METHOD. THE point of view of a philosophical writer reflects itself, not only in the substance of his teaching, but in the form in which it is cast. Clear speculative insight may rise above the restraints of a false or defective method, but cannot altogether withstand its influence. Form inevitably reacts on matter, method unconsciously modi- fies ideas or hinders their full expression and develop- ment. From the form, therefore, of Spinoza's system we may derive some help in the endeavour to apprehend its general bearing and to discover the reasons both of its success and of its failure, of what it does and of what it leaves undone. "What Spinoza aimed at was a system of knowledge in which everything should follow by strict necessity of thought from the first principle with which it starts. It is the function of reason to rise above the influence of the senses, to strip away from the objects it contem- plates the guise of contingency and independence with Avhich ordinary observation clothes them, and to see all things related to each other under the form of absolute necessity. To this end it seeks to penetrate to the first p. xii, H 114 Spinoza. ground or presupposition of all thought and being, to grasp " that idea which represents the origin and sum of nature, and so to develop all our ideas from it that it shall appear as the source of all other ideas." With such a conception of the nature of knowledge it is easy to see how Spinoza should regard the science of mathematics as affording the purest type of method, and should endeavour, as he has done, to cast his system in geometrical form. In geometry everything is based on the fundamental conception of space or quantity, and the whole content of the science seems to follow by rigid logical necessity from definitions and axioms re- lating to that conception. Might not the same exactitude, certainty, necessity of sequence be obtained for the truths of philosophy as for the truths of mathematics by following the same method 1 It was probably some such anticipation that led Spinoza to give to his great work the form which is indicated by its title, ' Ethics de- monstrated in Geometrical Order,' and to set forth his ideas, after the manner of Euclid, in a series of defini- tions, axioms, postulates, and of propositions and corol- laries flowing from these by strict logical deduction. To what extent the defects of Spinoza's system are to be traced to his method will perhaps appear in the sequel ; but it may be pointed out here that, from the very nature of the thing, a purely geometrical method is inadequate to the treatment of philosophical truth. 1. For one thing, philosophy must go further back than either mathematics or the sciences that treat of outward nature. These sciences may and do take much for granted ; philosophy admits of no unexamined pre- suppositions, The former not only deal with limited Geometrical Method. 115 departments of knowledge, and with things the existence of which is regarded as already known, without asking how they come to be known, but they employ categories and forms of thought which they do not investigate, and presuppositions which they do not pretend to do more than verbally define. Even geometry may, in this point of view, be called a hypothetical science. It presupposes the objective existence of space, and employs, without inquiry into its validity, the category of quantity. It begins with certain definitions, e.g., of a point, a line, a surface, without examining into their origin or asking whether they are mere arbitrary conceptions, or express what is absolutely true and real. Philosophy cannot content itself with such a method. It cannot follow the example of mathematics and start with defini- tions and axioms, or employ in an uncritical way, like the physical sciences, such categories as being, substance, causality, &c. It must go back to the very beginning, and, in a sense, create the matter with which it deals. It must entitle itself to the use of its cate- gories by tracing their origin and development, see them coming to the birth in the pure medium of thought, and evolving themselves in the necessary movement or pro- cess of reason. The special sciences may content them- selves, each with its own provisional view of things, and may relegate to philosophy the task of explaining and verifying it. A philosophy which did so would need another philosophy to examine and criticise it. 2. The geometrical method, when closely examined, fails in that quality which constitutes, at first sight, its peculiar attraction. It does not furnish to philosophy the paradigm of a science in which everything follows by strict 116 Spinoza. necessity from its fundamental principle. In a philo- sophical system, according to Spinoza's favourite illustra- tion, everything should follow from, the primary idea by the same necessity with which the properties of a triangle flow from its definition. And it is true that, if we look only to the figures or ideal constructions represented in the diagrams of the mathematician, it is possible to draw out a series of propositions which follow by rigid deduc- tion from the definitions of the figures. But if we test the value of geometrical science, not by what can be logically deduced from given premisses (and the illustra- tion in question implies no more), but by what is involved in and can be deduced from its fundamental conception, then it fails to furnish what is implied in Spinoza's ideal of a philosophical system. For the idea of space does not evolve from itself a system of geometrical truth. There is no reason simply in the idea of space why triangles, circles, squares, &c., should arise in it. Such constructions are conditioned by and presuppose that idea, but are not produced by it. Space does not pro- duce or evolve anything unless you, the geometrician, arbitrarily create or imagine in it lines, surfaces, solids, figured constructions of whatever kind. Being produced, they must relate themselves to each other according to the conditions which the conception of space involves ; and so you may rear upon these ideal constructions a vast system of geometrical truths of immense value in determining the relations of objects that admit of being regarded quantitatively. But neither these objects nor their relations, ideal or actual, are the necessary product of the fundamental conception. That conception has in it no principle of self-determination, and the determina- Inadequacy of this Method. 117 tions it gets are arbitrarily imposed on it from without. If, therefore, philosophical truth is to be, not a system in which by arbitrary synthesis you force its first prin- ciple to become fertile, but one in which that principle, by its own genetic power, necessarily determines or differentiates itself to all particular truths, then obvi- ously it is a misconception to seek the type of such a system in the province of the mathematician. 3. The main objection to the employment in philos- ophy of the geometrical method is that the category on which it is based is inadequate to the treatment of spir- itual things. Inevitable confusion and error arise from applying to one order of things conceptions or cate- gories which are strictly applicable only to another and lower order of things, or in leaving out of account in the higher and more complex sphere all conditions and relations save those which pertain to the lower. Xow the conceptions of space and quantity have their proper and exclusive application only to objects which can be con- ceived of as occupying extension or lying outside of each other ; whilst philosophy, in so far as it deals with things spiritual, has to do with a sphere where purely external or special relations vanish. In formal language, mathe- matical method is applicable only to the sphere of self- externality, but is incapable of dealing with thought or self-consciousness, which is the sphere of immanence or self-internality. Mathematical science recommends itself by the clear- ness and simplicity of its conceptions and the demon- strative certainty of its results. But, however valuable within its own sphere, as compared \vith other sciences it may be said that its simplicity arises from its shallow- 118 Spinoza. ness or abstractness, and its certainty from its ignoring of the very elements which, in the case of these sciences, complicate the problems to be solved. Geometry, as we have said, is based on the conception of space, and on ideal constructions or figures in space. It abstracts from all relations of actual objects, save those which arise from their being extended from all conditions save that of not occupying the same parts of space with each other. But this obviously is a way of looking at things which is purely abstract ; and conclusions reached with reference to such abstractions do not apply, strictly speak- ing, to anything beyond the abstraction itself. Even inorganic objects are incapable of being reasoned about as if conclusions which are true of space and its parts held good with respect to them. In the material world there are indeed unities which are unities merely of aggre- gation made up, that is, of parts which seem to be only externally related to each other, and to be connected with other unities only externally. But there are no mate- rial realities which are absolutely continuous or which can be thought of as if their component parts were re- lated to each other as the ideal parts of pure space, or as if propositions with reference to lines, surfaces, solids were unconditionally applicable to them. Nor, again, are there any material realities which are not related to each other in other ways than can be embraced under the conception of spatial extension. Inorganic sub- stances undergo chemical changes which do not admit of being expressed simply in terms of quantity. Iron rusts, but space does not, and the rusting is something more than a change of spatial relations. Chemical changes, in other words, involve other conditions than those of Inadequacy of this Method 119 space. In a chemical compound the unity is one of which the elements have lost their independent quantitative existence ; their spatial individuality has vanished in the neutral product. Still less do or- ganic existences admit of being adequately dealt Avith under the category of quantity. A living being is not composed of parts which exist simply outside of each other, and have only external or spatial relations to each other. There is a sense in which in an organism the whole is in every part, and the parts exist only in the whole. In a mere material aggregate the whole is simply the sum of the parts ; but in a living unity, when you have summed up all the parts, you have left out something which escapes spatial measurement, and yet which constitutes the very essence of the thing. It is only when it ceases to be living that an organism de- scends into the sphere to which quantitative measures belong. And the reason is that its unity is not of parts external to parts, but of parts which have their being in and through each other not a self-external but an im- manent or self-internal unity. Least of all, when we rise to the sphere of spiritual things, when we propose to consider the relations of God and man, to treat of such things as intelligence, freedom, duty, immortality, can we adequately apprehend them by a method which turns on quantitative relations. Organisms, whatever else they are, are tilings which still occupy space, and may therefore partially be apprehended by means of a category which deals Avith objects externally related to each other. But in the sphere of thought or self-con- sciousness we have absolutely transcended that of spatial outwardness. The indivisible unitv of self-consciousness 120 Spiiioza. transcends all external difference. Xo thought or fuel- ing is bende another. The self that thinks is not some- thing outside of its thoughts. It is by a false abstraction that we talk of one faculty of consciousness as if it were a part or bit of mind separated by spatial division from other faculties. In every part of consciousness the whole is present. Nor, whatever we mean by speaking of one mind as greater than another, can we determine the greatness or littleness as quantitative magnitudes. "NVe cannot conceive of Infinite Mind as something existing above or beyond finite minds ; and if we say that Infin- ite Mind or Intelligence comprehends and transcends all finite minds, we cannot represent this relation as iden- tical with that of a bigger circle or sphere to the smaller circle or sphere that is contained in it. "VVe may speak in a figure of " larger, other minds than ours," but if the figure becomes more than a figure, if we let it govern or guide our ideas as to the nature of spiritual things, it will betray us into confusion and error. Spinoza is often greater than his method. There are parts of his system which it is impossible to reconcile with the categories that in general seem to guide him. In the last Book of the ' Ethics,' especially, he seems to restore in a measure the very ideas, such as those of human freedom and individuality and of final causality, against which, in the earlier Books, he most strenuously contends. Perhaps the most valuable part of his philos- ophy is that in which his keen speculative insight rises above his self-imposed restraints. Yet, on the other hand, the method he adopts and the conception on which it is based furnish often the key to the meaning of his Influence of this Method. 121 ideas, and the explanation of the errors into which he is betrayed ; and the general bearing of his system becomes more intelligible when we consider it in the light of that method, as a brief glance at some of its leading points may suffice to show. 1. One of these points is his identification of the infinite with the purely affirmative, of the finite or determined with the negative. In one of his letters 1 occurs the following passage : " As to the doctrine that figure is negation and not anything positive, it is plain that the whole of matter, considered in- definitely, can have no figure, and that figure can only exist in finite and determinate bodies. He who says that he perceives a figure, merely says that he has before his mind a limited thing. But this limitation does not pertain to the thing in respect of its being, but, on the contrary, of its non-being. As, then, figure is nothing but limitation, and limitation is negation, figure, as I have said, can be nothing but negation." The same principle is expressed in more general terms in another letter, 2 where he writes : " It is a contradiction to con- ceive anything whose definition involves existence, or, which is the same thing, affirms existence, under nega- tion of existence. And since determination indicates nothing positive, but only a privation of existence in the nature conceived as determinate, it follows that that of which the definition affirms existence cannot be con- ceived as determinate." Applying the principle here enunciated, he in the same letter identifies the idea of God, or of " a Being absolutely perfect," with that of " a Being absolutely indeterminate," and argues that, 1 Ep. 50. - Ibid., 41. 122 Spinoza. " since the nature of God does not consist in a certain kind of being, but in being which is absolutely indeter- minate, His nature demands everything which perfectly expresses being, otherwise it would be determinate and defective." And the same doctrine, that " finite being is negation, infinite being absolute affirmation," is laid down in the ' Ethics.' 1 In these passages the influence of what may be termed a geometrical conception of the universe is obvious. When we represent to ourselves the relation of infinite and finite by that of space and its determinations, the idea of the finite becomes that simply of privation or negation. A figure in space has no individual reality ; in so far as it has any positive reality, it is only the reality that belongs to the part of infinite space which its periphery cuts off; and in so far as it can be said to have any individual existence in distinction from infinite space, that existence is not positive but negative, it is created solely by cutting off or negating all of space that is outside of it. Its very essence, therefore, is privation, negation, want of being. Its sole being is non-being. And this conception Spinoza applies to all finite or particular existences. In so far as they have any reality, it is not their own, but that which pertains to them as parts of the being of the infinite ; and any apparent individuality in them is not positive but negative it ex- presses, not what they are, but what they are not. It is true that we can pictorially represent to ourselves figured portions of space ; but these constructions are purely ideal, entia ration},*, fictions of the mind. Space itself has no parts ; it overflows, so to speak, these arbitrary 1 Eth. i. 8, schol. Determination and Negation. 123 divisions and annuls them. And in like manner, it is possible for imagination to lend to particular finite beings, material or spiritual, an apparent independence or in- dividuality. But this individuality is purely fictitious. It exists only for ordinary experience, which is under the control of appearances ; or for imagination, which regards as real anything that can be pictured. "When thought penetrates to the reality of things, it discerns their in- dividual independence to be an illusion ; it breaks down the false abstraction, and perceives the only reality to be that, not of the part but of the whole, not of the finite but of the infinite. It is obvious also what, from this point of view, is the only conception that can be formed of " a Being absolutely perfect." When we withdraw the arbitrary limits which distinguish the finite from the infinite, what we reach is simply that which is free from all limits or determinations, the absolutely indeterminate ; and as determinations are merely negations, the removal of all negations leaves us in the presence of non-negation, or of pure, absolute affirmation. As the very essence of the finite is nan esse, privation or negation of being, so the essence of the infinite is simply pure Being, that which is, or that which cannot be conceived save as existing, seeing its very nature is one with existence. "\Vc see, therefore, in so far as this part of his system is concerned, the narrowing influence of Spinoza's method. The conception of things on which that method is based excludes any other alternative than that of determination or indetermination. It excludes, in other words, another possible alternative viz., that of self-determination, that is, of an affirmation which does not simply annul, but subsumes and includes negation. 124 Spinoza. Yet the way to this alternative lay open to Spinoza when he had reached the last result which his method could yield. For an affirmation which is reached by negation, cannot ignore it. Apart from negation pure affirmation has no meaning. A negative element enters into its very essence. In itself, like the conception of pure space on which it is based, it is a mere abstraction ; it needs the negative or determinate as its correlate. And when we have reached this point, we have got beyond the contradictory elements of negation and affir- mation to an idea which includes both. Thus the in- finite, in the highest sense of the word, must be con- ceived not as the simple negation of the finite, but as that which at once denies and affirms it. What this view further implies what is involved in the notion of an infinite which does not annul, but realises itself in and through the differences of the finite world this is not the place to show. Had Spinoza token this further step, it would have implied the reconstruction of his whole system. As it is, the idea of a purely affirmative infinite, or of a finite which is merely the illusory sub- stantiation of imaginary distinctions in the infinite, had it not been accompanied by other ideas, which, how- ever illogically associated with it, modify or correct it, would have left his system one of uncompromising pantheism. 2. Connected with the foregoing, and in further illustration of the relation of Spinoza's thought to his method, we have to notice his denial of human freedom, and his rejection of any other criterion of perfection than that of amount or quantity of being. In a system in which all things follow from the first Freedom ami Perfection. 125 principle with the same necessity as the properties of a geometrical figure from its definition, or a logical con- clusion from its premisses, individual freedom is, of course, an impossible conception. The illusion of free- dom, according to Spinoza, arises from the tendency already noticed as belonging to ordinary thinking the tendency to see things abstractly or with the eyes of imagination. The individual thinks himself free because he is conscious of his desires and actions, but not of the conditions that determine them. He can imagine him- self to have acted otherwise than he has done, and can ascribe to himself a capacity of so acting, for the same reason that he can picture himself as an isolated and independent being in the universe. But when he looks at himself with the eye of reason rather than of imagina- tion, he can no more think himself acting otherwise than he has acted, than a triangle, if it were conscious, could think its angles equal to three or four right angles or any other number of right angles than two. For the same reason the terms good and evil, virtue and vice, perfection and imperfection, have, from Spinoza's point of view, either no meaning or a meaning different from that which ordinary thought attaches to them. "Were men born free," says he "that is, were they led by reason alone, or possessed of adequate ideas of things they could form no idea of good and evil." We may create for ourselves by the abstracting power of imagination fictitious standards of human perfection, and judge men accord- ing as they fulfil or fall short of them ; but this is merely a human Avay of looking at things. To the divine intelligence what we call good and evil, as imply- ing individual independence and freedom in relation to 126 Spinoza. the infinite, have no existence. "We compare men with each other in view of this arbitrary standard, and regard one as more imperfect than another ; but what separates man from God, the absolutely perfect Being, is simply his finitude, and no one finite being can be nearer to the infinite than another. There is, indeed, another side of Spinoza's teaching, according to which, as we shall see, a certain indepen- dence or self-assertion, a tendency to maintain itself or persist in its own being, is ascribed to each individual existence. But even here we find that the quasi moral distinctions which this principle introduces, do not turn on any conception of a universal element in man's nature, a self deeper than the natural self, to which merely quantitative measures will not apply. On the contrary, what this supposed tendency or impulse points to is simply the maintaining and increasing by each individual of the amount of its being. " Perfection and reality," says he, "mean the same thing." 1 It is the possession of more or less of this " reality " that distinguishes one individual from another. The more reality, the more power of thinking and acting an intelligent being possesses, so much the more perfect or virtuous he is. " When I say that an individual passes from a less to a greater perfection and vice versa, I understand by this, that we conceive that his power of action, in so far as it is understood from his own nature, is increased or diminished." 2 The great principle of all spiritual activity is thus simply the working out and enlargement of our own individual nature. Even if apparently un- selfish motives, such as sympathy with and participation 1 Eth. ii., clef. 6. - Il>id. iv., Pref. Idea of Final Cause. 127 in the good of others, are admitted as possible principles of action, the ground of this possibility is that the happiness of the object of such affections contributes to the increase or expansion of our own individual being. 3. The influence of Spinoza's method betrays itself again in his rejection of a teleological conception of the relation of God to the world. A philosophy which regards all things as following by logical sequence from the first principle, obviously excludes any question of the end or final cause of things. Such a principle does not aim at its results, or employ means to reach them. These results simply are, and cannot be conceived to be other than they are ; they do not arise as matters of foreseen design, but are absolutely determined by the nature of the principle with which we start. We may not ask, with respect to finite things or beings, why or for what end they exist, any more than we ask for what end the proper- ties of a triangle exist. Of these we can only say that they are, or that they are because they are given along with the definition of the thing itself. And in like manner, of all finite existences we can only say, not that they point to or are explained by any ulterior end, but that they are because God is, or because they are the necessary determinate expressions of His being. Spinoza's condemnation of a teleological view of the world is directed mainly against that kind of teleology which constitutes the so-called "argument from design." To view the world teleologically would, he urges, imply imperfection in God by conceiving of Him as aiming at an end outside of Himself. It would be to think of Him after the analogy of finite beings, who seek to give shape 128 Spinoza. to their unrealised conceptions, or are impelled by the consciousness of wants to aim at objects which will satisfy them. " If God," says he, " works for the sake of an end, He necessarily seeks something of which He stands in need. . . . Theologians maintain that God has done all things for His own sake, . . . and there- fore they are necessarily compelled to admit that God stood in need of and desired those things for which He determined to prepare the means." 1 But though a tele- ological view of the world, rightly apprehended, does not thus separate the end from the beginning, and there- fore may be freed from the objection that it implies original imperfection in the author of it, it is obvious that in no sense can such a view be expressed in terms of quantity, or under that category on which the geo- metrical method is based. The idea of Final Cause is that of a unity which realises itself in differences, which, by its own inner impulse, gives rise to differences, yet ever maintains itself in them, and through these differences returns upon itself. It implies an organic process, in which neither the unity is lost in the differences nor the differences in the unity, but in which, the further the differentiation is carried, so much the richer does the original unity become. But, as we have already seen, a geometrical method is incapable of expressing any such living, self-differentiating, self-integrating unity. Space does not determine itself to its own divisions, or give rise to the determinate objects conceived as existing in it. Xor does space retract these arbitrary differences any more than it produces them ; and when ire have withdrawn them and restored the original unity and 1 Eth. i., Append, True and False Teleology. 129 continuity of space, it has not become any richer by the process. The unity prior to the finite was complete in itself, and the arbitrary differentiation and reintegration has not increased its wealth. The differences are not preserved but annulled in the final unity, and it is the same self-identical unity at the end as at the beginning. p. xii. 130 CHAPTER VTT. SPINOZA'S STARTING-POINT SUBSTANCE. THE starting-point of Spinoza's system is the idea of " Substance," which he defines as " that which is in itself and is conceived through itself i.e., that, the con- ception of which does not need the conception of another thing in order to its formation." 3 This substance he characterises as infinite, indivisible, unique, free, eter- nal, as the cause of itself and of all things, and as con- sisting of an infinite number of infinite attributes, two only of which, thought and extension, are cognisable by human intelligence ; and he expressly identifies this substance with God, whom he defines as " a Being ab- solutely infinite that is, substance consisting of infinite attributes, of which each expresses an eternal and infinite essence." 2 In beginning with this idea Spinoza is attempting to realise his own theory of knowledge viz., that "in order that our mind may correspond to the exemplar of nature, it must develop all its ideas from the idea which represents the origin and sum of nature, so that that idea may appear as the source of all other ideas." 3 1 Eth. i., def. 3. 2 Ibid., def. 6. 3 Be Emend., vii. 42. Philosophy a r nd Experience. 131 Philosophy, according to this view, begins with the universal, not the particular ; it does not proceed by induction or generalisation from the facts of observation and experience, but it seeks to grasp the ultimate unity, the highest principle of things, and to derive or develop from it all particular existences. Its method is, not to reach the universal from the particular, but to know the particular through the universal. But in thus endeavouring to find a first principle from which all things are to be evolved, does not Spinoza lay himself open to the charge often brought against philosophy, of neglecting or anticipating ex- perience, and attempting to explain the world by a priori notions'? Is not his system a flagrant instance of the unscientific method of metaphysicians who in- terpret nature by subjective theories, instead of, by patient observation and generalisation of facts, letting nature be her own interpreter 1 Suppose we could ever apprehend the unity with which he starts, would it not be the end rather than the beginning of knowledge? Science is ever seeking to embrace lower in higher and more comprehensive generalisations, and the ultimate goal to which the scientific impulse points may be a law which would comprehend all laws, a final principle which Avould transcend the inadequate and partial ex- planations of the world which particular sciences give, and achieve for them what they, each in its own pro- vince, attempt to do for the special phenomena with which they deaL But even if such a goal were actu- ally attainable, would it not be so only as the last result of the long labour of science; and must not the hasty attempt to snatch at this unity by a mere 132 Spinoza. effort of abstract thought be regarded as vain and futile ? The answer in the case of Spinoza, as in that of all kindred thinkers, is that philosophy does not neglect experience, but only seeks to examine and criticise the presuppositions involved in it, to trace back to their ultimate ground the principles on which, unconsciously, ordinary and scientific thought proceeds ; and then to reinterpret experience or, in one sense, to re-create it in the light of the results thus reached. This account of its work implies that philosophy must, in a sense, reverse the order of ordinary and even of scientific ex- perience, and beginning with the highest universal which thought involves, show how from it all lower universalities take their rise, and how the whole world of finite particular existences is transformed for thought by becoming linked in bonds of rational necessity to the first principle of all things. The progressive method of knowledge then is, in one sense, based on and presupposes the retrogressive. Metaphysic does not pretend to create the world out of its own categories, still less to supersede the special work of science. On the contrary, it is through the discovery of the partial and inadequate explanation of things which the categories of science furnish that it is led to seek after a deeper satisfaction for thought, an interpretation of the world by higher principles, till it attains that final interpretation which is given by a principle that rests on no higher, but is seen by its own light. Reversing the process, it then seeks to show how all the previous stages of knowledge, from the highest to the lowest, become transformed in the light of the True Order of Knowledge. 1 33 first principle of knowledge, or how all things are seen in their reality only when regarded as its expressions or manifestations. Spinoza's method, then, is not justly chargeable with reversing the true order of knowledge. If his phil- osophy be found defective, the defect will lie not in his beginning where he did, but in the nature of the idea with which he began ; not in his attempt to start with a first principle from which all things might be derived, but in the idea with which he started being incapable of fulfilling the function assigned to it, and in his attempting to explain all things from this principle simply by analytic deduction. If modern philosophy has had more success in dealing with the problem, per- haps the reason may, in some measure, be that science, by its marvellous progress, has worked into the hands of philosophy in our day as it did not and could not do in his. The inadequacy of Spinoza's first principle is, in part at least, traceable to the fact that he found it possible, so to speak, to reach the infinite by a short cut ; whilst modern thought, in some measure, owes the greater richness and fertility of the idea which consti- tutes its starting-point, to the fact that it has had to attain that idea by a slower and severer process. The problem for Spinoza, by his own showing, was to find a first principle which would explain the universe, after the analogy of mathematical science, according to the simplest of categories. The problem which modern philosophy has had to face is that of finding a final interpretation of nature which must presuppose the previous interpretations of it by the whole range of the physical and biological sciences, and Avhich must 134 supply a principle of criticism of the categories on which these sciences are based, and itself at once com- prehend and transcend them. SUBSTANCE. Spinoza's starting-point, the idea which is to be " the source of all other ideas," that which explains all else but needs no other idea to explain it, is " Substance," which, as already said, he defines as " that which is in itself and is conceived through itself." When we ask what Spinoza means by substance, we seem precluded by the very terms of the definition from all ordinary methods of explanation. The question what it is, seems to be ansAvered simply by the affirmation that it is ; the question how we are to conceive of it, by what other ideas we are to be enabled to apprehend its mean- ing, seems to be met by the affirmation that it is that which can be conceived only through itself: we may understand all other ideas by means of it, not it by means of them. But whilst thus we seem debarred from any direct explanation of the nature of substance, we may come at the answer indirectly if we consider, in the light of Spinoza's theory of knowledge, what is the point of view which this term is intended to express. We can understand the world, or bring our thoughts " into cor- respondence with the exemplar of nature," he tells us, as we have seen, only by "developing all our ideas from the idea which represents. the origin and source of nature ; " and the idea which constitutes the " origin of nature," he elsewhere defines as that of " a Being, single, infinite, which is the totality of being, and beyond Idea of the IVTiole. 135 which there is no being." 1 From this we gather that, according to Spinoza's conception of it, true or adequate knowledge is that which starts from tlie idea of ilt>' whole, and for which all other ideas have a meaning and reality only as they are determined by or seen in the light of the idea of the whole. Whatever else sub- stance means, therefore, by this term we are to under- stand this much at least that idea of the whole or totality of being, in the light of which only can all in- dividual things and thoughts be understood. This may be further illustrated by considering the contrast which elsewhere Spinoza draws between that "vague expe- rience " of which popular knowledge consists, and that <-i')ttia infuitlra which is the highest and only real kind of knowledge. The separate, independent exist- ence which popular thought ascribes to individual things and beings is no real existence. Xo object in nature is a single isolated thing. Each object is what it is only in virtue of its relations to other objects, and ultimately to the whole system of being. Ordinary observation looks at things superficially, or as to the outward eye they seem to exist, each apart from or side by side with the rest. Judging merely by the senses, it confounds externality in space with independent existence, and leaving out of view all deeper relations, it represents to itself the spatial separation of stones, plants, animals, as equivalent to an isolated or absolute reality. But when we cease to look at things after the outward appearance, and penetrate to their real nature, their isolated sub- stantiality vanishes ; we perceive them to be linked to each other by the inner bond of causality. Each in- 1 De Emend, ix. 136 Spinoza. dividual thing forms part of an infinite series of causes and effects ; its place, form, functions, activities, are what they are, not through itself alone, but through its connection with other beings, and ultimately with the whole universe of being. Not an atom of matter could be other than it is without supposing the whole material world to be other than it is ; and to understand a single material substance, we must take into account not merely its immediate environment, but the causes or conditions which have created that environment, and so on ad infinitum. And the same principle applies to intelligent or spiritual beings ; they, too, are successive existences which have only a semblance of individuality. By a trick of the imagination, we look upon ourselves as independent, self - determined individuals ; but oxir whole spiritual life is involved in our relations to other intelligences, as theirs again in that of those who sur- round or precede them. Eightly viewed, each so-called individual is only a transition-point in a movement of thought that stretches back through the interminable past and onwards through the interminable future. Thus the substantial reality of individual existences vanishes, and we can apply the designation " substance " only to the whole, the totality of being which includes and determines them. That whole is the only true in- dividual, the only being which " is in itself and is con- ceived through itself." "All bodies," writes Spinoza in one of his letters, 1 "are surrounded by other bodies, and reciprocally determine and are determined by them to exist and act in a fixed and defi- i Ep. 15. Tlie Universe a Substance. 137 nite way. Hence it follows that every body, in so far as it exists under a certain definite modification, ought to be con- sidered as merely a part of the whole universe, which agrees with its whole, and thereby is in intimate union with all the other parts ; and since the nature of the universe is not lim- ited, but absolutely infinite, it is clear that by this nature, with its infinite powers, the parts are modified in an infinite number of ways, and compelled to pass through an infinity of variations. Moreover, when I think of the universe as a substance, I conceive of a yet closer union of each part with the whole ; for, as I have elsewhere shown, it is the nature of substance to be infinite, and therefore each single part belongs to the nature of corporeal substance, so that apart therefrom it can neither exist nor be conceived. And as to the human mind, I conceive of it also as a part of nature, as having in it an infinite power of thinking, which, as infinite, contains in it the idea of all nature, and whose thoughts run parallel with existence." By "substance," therefore, we are to understand, in the first place, the idea of the totality of being or the universe as a whole. Further, this substance is by its nature " infinite." It would be self -contradictory to suppose that any finite thing could be determined merely by a series of finite causes. We may trace back step by step the regress of causes by which each par- ticular existence, material or spiritual, is determined to be what it is. But, however far back we go, we are dealing still with the particular or finite, which needs as much to be determined as the initial member of the series. If it was only by an illusory abstraction that we conceived of the latter as an independent individual, it is only by a like abstraction that we conceive of any aggregate of such individuals as having any reality apart from the whole. We may resolve any 138 particular tiling iuto a larger whole of which it forms a part, but that larger whole is itself but a fragment " an individual of the second order, but still an individual." And though we may proceed in the same way by a process of successive inclusions, correcting the con- ception of each lower unity by a higher, we can never by any such ascending movement reach that of which we are in quest the infinite whole, the absolute unity by which all finite things are determined to be what they are. But if we cannot reach the infinite, the substance of all things, by seeking it through a receding series of finite causes and effects, ai-e we to conclude that the quest is vain, that the object of inquiry is a chimera ; or if not, how is it to be attained 1 ? The answer of Spinoza virtually is, that we need not ascend to heaven to bring it down from above, for it is already in our hands and in our mouths. "Every idea of any body or existing thing necessarily involves the eternal and infinite essence." l Our ordinary consciousness is indeed, as we have seen, in one point of view, arbitrary and illusory ; but we have only to examine what is its real content and meaning to perceive that it involves what is virtually the consciousness of the infinite. All knowledge of what is limited rests on an implicit reference to what is unlimited. Every conception of a particular space or body presupposes the idea of infinite space or extension. Every particular idea implies a virtual reference to an infinite thought. And the dis- tinction of mind and matter, of ideas and things, would be itself impossible save by a tacit appeal to the idea of i Etb. ii. 45. Infinite Substance. 139 an infinite unity which lies beyond their difference. All finite thought and being, therefore, rests on the idea of Infinite Substance. And of this ultimate idea, this prius of all thought and being, it must be affirmed that whilst other ideas rest on it, it rests itself on no other. It cannot be proved by anything outside of itself, for no thing or thought could be or be conceived save on the assumption of it. It is beyond demonstration and inaccessible to doubt, for demonstration and doubt alike depend on and indirectly affirm it. It can only be defined as "that which is in itself and is conceived through itself." What is to be said in criticism of Spinoza's funda- mental principle has been already anticipated. That the individual can only be understood in the light of the whole system of being to which he belongs, that all the differences of the finite world presuppose and rest on an ultimate unity which is itself beyond demonstra- tion or doubt, are propositions the soundness of which cannot be questioned. The Aveakness of Spinoza's doctrine may be said to lie in this, that his substance or infinite unity on which all things rest is not organic but abstract. It may be true to say that substance is that which is in itself and conceived through itself, or, otherwise expressed, that the thought or idea of God proves His being. But the significance and force of the so-called " ontological argument " lies in this, that the unity of thought and being to which it concludes is not an abstract but a concrete unity. The distinction between them, as it is a distinction in thought and to thought, is one which thought can transcend nay, one which, when we bring to clear consciousness Avhat is 140 Spinoza. implied in it, thought in thinking it has already tran- scended. But the unity thus reached is the unity of the related elements, not something which merely lies beyond them; it explains and reconciles but does not annul them. What it expresses is, that thought and be- ing, though distinguishable, are correlated elements in that ultimate unity of self-consciousness which all knowledge presupposes as its beginning and seeks as its goal. The Spinozistic substance, on the other hand, is reached, as we have seen, not by the reconciliation of opposed but related elements in a higher unity, but simply by abstracting from the difference of these elements. It is not the reason of these differences but the unity that is got by obliterating them. And as all differences vanish in it, so no differences can proceed from or be predicated of it. It not only contains in it no principle of self- determination, but it is itself the negation of all deter- minations. How then can Spinoza find in his infinite substance the source and explanation of the variety and multiplicity of existence 1 The answer to this question is contained in his doctrine of "attributes" and "modes." 141 CHAPTEE VIII. SUBSTANCE AND ATTRIBUTES. RIGHTLY to fulfil the function assigned to it as the first principle of knowledge, Spinoza's "substance" must he so conceived as to he, not only the presupposition, hut the productive source of all finite being. It must be the ideal origin and explanation of things as well as that which transcends them. We must not merely be forced back to it as the unity Avhich is above all differ- ences, but also find in it that from which all differ- ences are evolved. The transition, in other words, to the finite world must lie in the very nature of substance. Does Spinoza's substance answer to this conception? That he deemed it capable of doing so is obvious. Substance is not merely causa sui, but causa omnium rerum. It is a unity which differentiates itself, first into "infinite attributes," then into "infinite modes," and these last again are modified by an infinite number of " finite modes." The world which is meaningless apart from it, the individualities which are only shadows and unrealities looked at in themselves, are redeemed from non-entity by the intuitive grasp of an intelligence which sees them instinct with the presence and power 142 Spinoza. of " substance." All things are unreal viewed as inde- pendent or distinct from God; all things become real in so far as we can discern in them the self-affirmation of the divine nature. All thinking things, all objects of all thought, as Spinoza regards them, throb with tin- vital pulse of the universal life. The dead world becomes alive in God. But though there can be no doubt as to the part which Spinoza intended his first principle to play, the first step he takes raises the question whether it is inherent!}' capable of the function assigned to it whether sub- stance, as he defines it, is not so conceived as to be in- capable, without giving up its essential nature, of passing from its self-involved unity or identity into difference. This first step is that which consists in the ascrip- tion of " infinite attributes " to the infinite substance. " Substance " or " God " " consists of infinite attributes of which each expresses the eternal and infinite essence." l But of these infinite attributes, whilst we know that their number is infinite, only two, " thought " and " extension," are cognisable by human intelligence. AY hat, then, is the ground or reason of this differentiation of the absolute unity 1 How does Spinoza find the attributes in his substance ] To this question the answer seems to be, that whilst (1) there is nothing in the nature of substance, as Spinoza conceives it, which can logically yield, but everything to preclude any such element of difference, (2) failing such logical ground, he simply asserts without proof the differentiation of sub- stance into attributes which he has empirically reached. In other words, the attributes are not differences to i Eth. L, def. 6. Substance and Attributes. 143 which substance determines itself, but to which it is determined ly us. (1.) As we have already seen, Spinoza's process to the infinite, the regressive movement by which he reaches substance as the ultimate unity of knowing and being, is simply the removal of the limit by which finite things are supposed to be quantitatively distinguished from the infinite. Number and measure are nothing but fictitious instruments of the imagination by which we break up the indivisible into parts. Space in itself is one and continuous, not made up of discrete parts. You cannot take one portion of space and isolate it from the rest, or say that one portion is here and the next there. Part runs into part, and it is only by a false abstraction that you can view them as separate from each other. " Figure," therefore, is " nothing positive." * And the same principle applies to all finite existences. The positive existence we ascribe to them is, when closely viewed, only negation or non-existence. To get to real or affirmative being we must negate the negation, with- draw the fictitious limit, and what we get as the real is simply the absolutely indeterminate, the logical abstrac- tion of Being. To predicate differences of this colourless entity would be to introduce into it non-entity. A de- termined absolute would be a partly non-existing ab- solute. From this point of view, therefore, it would seem that Spinoza is precluded from attaching any predi- i-atL-s or ascribing any attributes to his absolute sub- stance. To do so would be, as he himself says, 2 " to conceive under the category of non-existence that whose definition affirms existence." 1 Ep. 50. 2 Ep. 51. 144 Spinoza. (2.) Yet whilst by the very idea of substance Spinoza would seem to be precluded from giving to it any deter- minations, we find him passing at once from the notion of substance as the negation, to that of substance as the affirmation, of all possible determinations. The colour- less blank becomes at a stroke filled up with a rich and varied content. The unity which was reached by ab- straction from differences seems to be identified with a unity which contains all differences. Thought seems to re-enact the part for which imagination was con- demned that of dividing the indivisible, of introducing number and measure into the absolute. Substance which, logically, is the purely indeterminate, passes into substance which consists of infinite attributes infinitely modified. It is easier to discern the motive than to understand the logic of this transformation. Had Spinoza not refused to be led by his own logic, his system would have ended where it began. Philosophy, along with other things, comes to an end, in a principle which reduces all thought and being to nothingness. More- over, it is not difficult to understand how Spinoza should seem to see more in the idea of substance than it legiti- mately contained. While he ostensibly rejected all determinations from it, in his thought an element of determination tacitly clung to it. Thought often sup- plies the hidden corrective of the theories we form about it. It is possible to devise a theory which implies the separation of unity and difference, of the universal and the particular, of affirmation and negation. But the opposite elements are really correlatives, and the rejected or excluded element secretly clings to the thought that Unity and Difference. 145 denies it. It is impossible really to think an affirmative which affirms nothing in particular, or which is pure, blank affirmation devoid of all negation. When the particular vanishes from thought, the universal vanishes with it. Unity which carries with it no implication of diversity, becomes as meaningless a conception as that of a whole without parts, or a cause without effect. When, therefore, Spinoza began by rightly denying, or pro- nouncing to be -non e*$e, the particular existences of the finite world apart from their unity, that to which his thought pointed was the assertion, not of pure abstract unity, but of the reality of these particulars in relation to their unity. The converse of the nothingness of the particular independent of the universal was, not the reality of the abstract universal, but the reality of the particular in the universal. From the negation of acci- dents without substance what thought sought after was, not the assertion of substance without accidents, but the assertion of accidents transformed into the necessary moments or attributes of substance, of substance real- ising itself in and through accidents. Though, there- fore, the former of these alternatives pure, abstract, indeterminate substance Avas the logical result of his method, the latter Avas the real result to which the hidden, unconscious logic of his thought pointed. It was natural for him, therefore, tacitly to substitute the latter for the former, and so to pass, apparently by a leap, from the notion of God or Substance as the nega- tion, to that of God or Substance as the affirmation, of all possible determinations. But though it is possible thus to trace the real move- ment of Spinoza's thought, that movement was not a P. XII. K 146 Sjnnoza. conscious one, and it Avas not thus that he justified his own conclusion. What he seemed to himself to have reached as the presupposition of all things was the purely indeterminate self-identical infinite ; and the problem immediately arose, how to conceive of this infinite unity as, Avithout abandoning its essential nature, passing into difference, IIOAV to find in this moveless Absolute the explanation of the diversity and change- fulness of the finite Avorld. The device which Spinoza falls upon to reach the diversity Avithout tampering with the unity, is to regard the former as differences, not in the substance itself, but in substance in relation to t In- finite intelligence 'which contemplates it. " By attribute," says he, 1 "I understand that Avhich the intellect per- ceives of substance as constituting its essence." It is, in other Avords, not the essence itself of substance, but that essence relatively to our intelligence. In one of his letters, 2 after defining substance, he adds, " By attribute I understand the same thing, only that it is called attribute Avith reference to the understanding attributing a certain nature to substance." The relative or subjective character of the element of difference ex- pressed by attributes is further explained by various illustrations. He compares substance, e.g., 3 to a surface reflecting the rays of light, which, regarded objectively, is called " a plane," but with reference to the observer is described as "Avhite." "By a plane/' says he, "I mean a surface Avhich reflects all rays of light Avithout altering them ; by a white surface I mean the same, Avith this difference, that a surface is called Avhite Avith reference to a man looking at it." The same distinction i Eth. i., def. 4. - Ep. 27. :i Ibirt. of Attributes. 147 is illustrated by the different names of the third patriarch, who in his proper character called Israel, is in one special relation called Jacob. Finally, in the following and other passages of his writings Spinoza expressly teaches that the true or absolute nature of God is something that lies beyond all conceptions formed of Him by finite intelligence : "If the will be supposed infinite, it must be determined to exist and act by God, not in so far as He is absolutely infinite substance, but in so far as He has an attribute which expresses the infinite and eternal essence of thought." l " Being as being, by itself alone, as substance, does not affect us, and therefore it is to be explained by some attribute, from which yet it is not distinguished save ideally." 2 To the same effect, in the ' Theologico-political Treatise,' 3 speaking of the various titles of God in the Hebrew Scriptures, he says that the name " Jehovah " points to " the absolute essence of God without relation to created things ; " whilst on the other hand " El Saddai " and other names express "attributes of God, and pertain to Him in so far as He is considered with relation to created things or is manifested by them." Thus the ascription of attributes to God does not imply any tampering with the absolutely indeterminate unity of the divine nature, inasmuch as they do not characterise that nature in itself, but only as reflected in the finite intelligence. Finite intelligence cannot rise above itself, or see things otherwise than under the conditions that arise from its own nature. As man is him- self a being at once spiritual and corporeal in Spinoza's language, a "mode" or modification of thought and 1 Eth. i. 32. 2 Cogitat. Metaph. i. 3. :i xiii. 11, 12. 148 Spinoza. extension he can know God only under these two aspects or attributes. But we cannot conceive of the infinite nature as exhausted by our ways of apprehend- ing it. " The more reality or being anything has, the more attribiites belong to it." ] "A being absolutely infinite, therefore, is necessarily defined as being which consists of infinite attributes, each one of which ex- presses a certain essence eternal and infinite." Though, therefore, to us God is expressed only under the two attributes of " thought " and " extension," to minds differently constituted from ours the divine nature would reveal itself in different ways, and to an infinite number of minds or to an infinite understanding in an infinite number of ways or by an infinite diversity of attributes. " The infinite ways whereby each particular thing is expressed in the infinite understanding cannot constitute one and the same mind of a singular thing, but infinite minds, seeing that each of these infinite ideas has no connection with the rest." 2 By yet another expedient does Spinoza find it pos- sible to ascribe attributes to the infinite substance with- out infringing its purely indeterminate nature viz., by means of the distinction between what is "absolutely infinite " and what is only " infinite in its own kind " (in fuo genere). To avoid the implication that by at- taching predicates to substance we necessarily introduce an element of finiteness or negation into it, he tries to conceive of predicates which express something not neg- ative but positive, not finite but infinite, and which therefore limit neither the infinite substance nor each other. Such predicates are the infinite attributes of i Eth. i. 9. 2 Ep. 68. Plurality of Infinites. 149 God. All finite distinctions disappear in the infinite ; but we can conceive of distinctions which are not finite, in this sense that no one of them is limited either by the rest or by anything within its own sphere. We call a thing finite Avhen it is bounded by another thing of the same kind, as one piece of matter by another ; but things of different kinds do not limit each other. Mental things are not limited by material, nor vice versa. Ideas do not occupy space. Bodies are neither inside nor out side of minds. If therefore we can think of the attri- bute of extension as that which has no limit within its own sphere, its infinitude is not infringed by the exist- ence of another attribute of a wholly different kind, such as thought. It is no limitation of infinite exten- sion that it cannot think, nor of infinite thought that it is not extended. We may conceive an infinite number of such attributes, each infinite in its own kind, and yet their infinite diversity implying no reciprocal limi- tation. It may be said that if we conceive of an infinite number of such attributes as together constituting the nature of a being, each of them can express only a part of that nature, and therefore each must be regarded as a limitation of its infinitude. But Spinoza's answer to this objection virtually is, that it would be a valid ob- jection if we conceived of infinite substance as made up of thought, extension, and other attributes. When we think of a thing as an aggregate or combination of quali- ties, each of them is less than the whole, and expresses a limitation of nature. But the absolutely infinite sub- stance is not the sum or totality of its attributes. Ac- cording to Spinoza's peculiar conception, each of the different attributes expresses the same infinite reality 150 Spinoza. and the whole of that reality. The attributes are not complementary properties, the omission of any one of which leaves the whole imperfect, but each the same perfect Avhole contemplated in a different aspect. They are not correlative members of an organic unity Avhich have no independent reality apart from each other, but parallel, independent, equivalent manifestations of the same infinite object. Thought does not contain more or less of God than extension, but the content of both and of an infinite number of other attributes is absolutely the same. "Each attribute," says he, 1 "of one sub- stance must be conceived through itself." " It is ob- vious," he adds, 2 " that though two attributes are con- ceived as distinct that is, the one without the aid of the other yet we cannot therefore conclude that they constitute two different entities or substances. For it is of the nature of substance that each of its attributes is conceived through itself (since all the attributes which it has have existed simultaneously in it), nor could one be produced by another ; but each expresses the real- ity or being of substance. It is therefore by no means absurd to ascribe a plurality of attributes to one sub- stance." From this point of view, therefore, Spinoza is enabled to combine the notions of absolute indeter- minate unity with endless difference, or to conceive of an infinite multiplicity of attributes without tampering with the unconditioned unity of substance. The two expedients, however, by which he accomplishes this re- sult, virtually resolve themselves into one. The attri- butes, though said to be infinite each in its own kind, are not really different in kind from each other. The con- i Eth. i. 10. 2 Ibid., schol. Criticism of the Doctrine. 151 tent of each is precisely the same as that of any other, and the difference is only a difference in our way of looking at it. The difference in kind is nothing more than a difference of aspect. Spinoza's reconciliation, therefore, of diversity of attributes with absolute self- identical unity of substance, is simply that the diver- sity is a purely subjective one. 1. One obvious criticism on Spinoza's doctrine of attributes is that it presupposes what it is intended to prove. The definition of attribute is "that which in- telligence perceives in substance as constituting its essence." But finite intelligence is itself only a " mode " or modification of one of the attributes of substance. The attributes, therefore, exist only through that which is simply a modification of one of them. The thought or intelligence which is the product of an attribute, is surreptitiously introduced to create the attributes. Thought, indeed, thinks itself and everything else ; and if the intelligence which differentiates the infinite sub- stance were its own, there would be no paralogism in supposing infinite intelligence or self-consciousness to be the source or origin of the finite intelligence which knows it. But in the case before us, the absolutely infinite sub- stance, as we have seen, is expressly distinguished from, or logically prior to, the attributes that of thought as Avell as every other. Thought is only one of the aspects into which the absolute unity is diffracted by finite in- telligence. Finite intelligence, therefore, is supposed to create that by which it is itself created. 2. The attributes are not derived from, but brought from without to, substance. To render the system co- herent, the existence and distinctive character of the 152 Spinoza. attributes should arise out of the essential nature of substance. In the very nature or idea of substance an element of self-differentiation must be shown to ex- ist, and that an element which does not tamper with its unity. In other words, substance must be conceived as a unity which has in it an impulse to go forth out of itself, to realise itself in the infinite determinations expressed by the attributes and their modifications, and yet in so going forth as remaining in unbroken identity with itself. Spinoza's substance, however, as we have just seen, not only does not contain, but is exclusive of. any such element of self-determination, and the deter- mination expressed by the attributes are ascribed to a purely empirical origin. "We feel and perceive," says he, 1 " no particular things save bodies and modes of thought," and therefore we conclude that thought and extension are attributes of God. We represent to ourselves God as a "thinking thing" or an "extended thing." It is ice who ascribe or bring the attributes to the substance, and the ice has not been accounted for. 3. The accidental character of the attributes is indi- cated, not only in the origin ascribed to them, but also in their number and relation to each other. If sub- stance is to have the character of a principle from which everything in the system is to be logically deduced, it should contain in itself the reason why such and no other determinations belong to it ; it should determine the order of their sequence, and show how each involves or is involved in all the rest. To say simply that a number of attributes cohere in one substance, is not to explain or give any rational idea of their unity, but 1 Eth. ii., ax. 5. Number and Relation of Attributes. 153 merely to affirm that they are united. In the Spinozistic system extension, thought, and the other attributes are not organically related to each other. Each is absolutely independent of the rest forms, so to speak, a com- pleted whole in itself, and is to be conceived in and through itself. One attribute can no more be related to another than an object seen through a glass of one colour can be related to the same object seen through a glass of a different colour, or than an idea expressed in one language can be related to precisely the same idea ex- pressed in another language. As it is perfectly indiffer- ent to the object itself through how many differently coloured glasses it is seen, so it is perfectly indiffer- ent to the nature of substance by what or how many attributes it is manifested. If Spinoza speaks of the diversity of attributes as infinite, the infinitude is not that which arises o\it of the essence of substance, but is only a numerical infinitude the false infinite of endless- ness or indefiniteness. In predicating of substance an infinite number of attributes, Spinoza relapses into the ambiguity which he himself had censured in a remark- able letter already quoted the ambiguity, viz., of tho term "infinite" as denoting either that which by its very nature is incapable of limitation, or that which exceeds every assignable limit. The infinitude which he ascribes to substance is of the former kind, and there is no legitimate connection between such an infini- tude and the merely quantitative infinitude of attributes, the number of which exceeds an}' given or conceivable number. 4. In the li-tu-rs which passed between Spino/a and his acute correspondent Tschirnhausen, some fiu-ther de- 154 Spinoza. fects and inconsistencies in his doctrine of the attri- butes are brought to light. Amongst other pertinent questions, Tschirnhausen asks these two : First, whether it can be proved "that we cannot know any attributes of God other than thought and extension ; " 1 or, more fully expressed, " why my mind, which represents a cer- tain modification (of absolute substance), a modification which is expressed not only by extension, but in an infinite variety of ways, perceives only that modifica- tion as expressed by extension, and not as expressed through the other attributes ? " 2 Secondly, whether, though it is laid down that every attribute is of equal content and significance with every other, " the attribute of thought is not really (as Spinoza defines it) of wider extent than any of the other attributes " ] 3 To the former of these questions Spinoza answers that " the power of a thing is defined solely by its essence, and that the essence of the mind is the idea of the body, which idea does not involve or express any of God's attributes save extension and thought. 4 Of this answer it may be said that, though from Spinoza's point of view it is no doubt conclusive, yet it betrays in some measure the insufficiency and even inconsistency of the principles on which it is based. In a philosophy in which thought is related to extension, mind to matter, as the con- scious subject to its own object, Tschirnhausen's ob- jection would, in one point of view, be unanswerable. For in such a philosophy there is nothing which lies out- side the realm of intelligence, nothing which is not either known or knowable. If thought can apprehend exten- sion, there is nothing which it cannot apprehend. If i Ep. 65. '- FI-. 87. :i lv 4 Kl>. 66. Tschirnliauseri s Questions. 155 human intelligence can transcend the distinction between itself and one attribute or manifestation of God, it there- by proves its capacity to transcend the same distinction in the case of every other attribute. Mind cannot be capable of apprehending its object in one aspect or two aspects and not in every other aspect. But, on the other hand, in a philosophy in which thought and ex- tension, though regarded as attributes of one substance, are still conceived of as wholly independent of each other as simply two parallel but unconnected expres- sions, amongst many others, of the divine essence there is no reason in the nature of thought why, knowing one such attribute or expression, it should also know any other. The relation of parallelism does not carry with it what is involved in the deeper relation of conscious- ness to its object. An arbitrary connection does not imply the universal results of a necessary relation. In fact, the difficulty here is, not why, knowing extension, thought should not know everything else, but why it should transcend the gulf between itself and what is outside of it at all. In Spinoza's philosophy, that thought should overleap this gulf even in the one case of extension is an inconsistency ; but it is one of those happy inconsistencies which render it so fruitful and suggestive. It must be added, however, that from an- other point of view a philosophy which is based on the principle of self-consciousness would, though on different grounds, accept Spinoza's limitation of knowledge to ex- tension and thought. For to such a philosophy exten- sion is not, as Spinoza conceives, simply one amongst a multiplicity of attributes which intelligence in man happens to know, but it is the essential correlative of 156 Spinoza. thought. It is not one amongst many things which thought can apprehend, but it is the necessary form of the object in its opposition to the thought for which it is. Extension and thought, in other words, are not a duality of attributes, but the dualism which con- stitutes the very essence of mind. If we conceive of God as Infinite Mind or Spirit, extension, instead of being one amongst an infinite number of attributes, is simply the form of objectivity through which alone is self-consciousness possible. As to the second question, which does not seem to have been answered by Spinoza, it may be remarked that whilst, according to Spinoza's doctrine, every attribute expresses the whole of substance, and is of precisely the same value with every other, yet, inasmuch as all the attributes alike are relative to thought, or are "what intelligence perceives of substance as constituting its essence," thought has obviously in his system a wider function than any of the other attributes. In the case of man it knows the two attributes of which his mind and body are modifications, but it also, in the case of all other possible intelligences, knows the other attributes of which their natures are the modifications. If we conceive the attributes as running in pairs, thought will always be one of them. Each finite nature will be a modifica- tion of thought and of some other attribute which plays a corresponding part to extension in the nature of man. Thought has therefore a purely exceptional place in the scheme ; it is the con-elate of all the other attributes. It is not simply one of the two attributes which human in- telligence knows, but it is a universal factor in that know- ledge of God which is possible for all finite intelligencea 157 CHAPTEE IX. MODES. THE next step in the process by which Spinoza attempted to find in substance the first principle of all things, is that which is expressed in his doctrine of "Modes." The attributes, even if legitimately deduced, leave us still in the region of the infinite, and furnish no transi- tion to a finite world. Though thought and extension are only expressions of substance, each in a certain definite manner, they are still infinite. The character- istic of being conceived through itself (per se concipi) belongs to the idea of attribute as well as to that of substance ; there is nothing in it which points to any- thing beyond itself ; it contains no element of self- differentiation by which the process to the finite might be mediated. The attributes, like the substance, are pure self-identical xmities, and if they presuppose finite intelligence as the medium through which the colour- less unity of substance is refracted, they only tacitly presuppose but do not prove it. It is in Spinoza's doctrine of " Modes," and of their relation to substance, that we must find, if anywhere, the explanation of the existence of the finite world, and 158 Spinoza. of its relation to the infinite. " By mode," says he, 1 " I understand affections of substance, or that which is in another, through which also it is conceived." "Modes can neither exist nor be conceived without substance ; therefore they can exist only in the divine nature, and can be conceived only through it." 2 " Besides substance and modes nothing exists, and modes are nothing but affections of the attributes of God." 3 Finite modes are, further, identified with individual things (res partlcu- lares), and of these it is said 4 that " they are nothing but affections of the attributes of God, or modes by which the attributes of God are expressed in a certain definite manner." What we gather from these various forms of state- ment is, that, in contrast with Substance or God, who alone is self-existent, all finite things have only an ex- istence that is dependent on or derived from Him, Their being is a being which is not in themselves, but " in another " that is, " in God." What is meant by the phrase "in another," or "in God," the following passages may help us to understand : " Whatever is, is in God, and without God nothing can l>e or be conceived." 5 " From the necessity of the divine nature an infinite number of things follows in infinite ways, as will be evident if we reflect that from the definition of a tiling the understanding infers many properties which necessarily follow from it that is, from the very essence of the thing defined." 6 "The modes of the divine nature follow there- from necessarily and not contingently, and that, whether we 1 Eth. i., clef. 5. - Eth. i. 15, tlem. Eth. i. 28, dem. 4 Eth. i. 25, cor. 8 Eth. i. 15. Eth. i. 16, dem. Derivation of Modes. 159 consider the divine nature absolutely, or as determined to act in a certain manner. Further, God is the cause of these modes not only in so far as they simply exist, but in so far as they are considered as determined to any action." l In these passages the relation of modes or finite things to God is represented by the equivalent forms of expres- sion " following from God " and " caused by God " ; and it is to be observed that in the last-quoted passage the causality of God with regard to modes is spoken of as of a twofold character viz., that of the divine nature " con- sidered absolutely," and that of the divine nature " in so far as it is determined to act in a certain manner." This distinction, to which Spinoza frequently recurs, and on the tenableness of which the coherence of his system may be said to turn, is more fully expressed in the following passages : " That which is finite and has a determinate existence can- not be produced by the absolute nature of any attribute of God ; for whatever follows from the absolute nature of any attribute of God is infinite and eternal. It must therefore fol- low from God or from some attribute of God, in so far as He is considered as affected by some mode, . . . (or) in so far as He is modified by a modification which is finite and has a determined existence. This mode again must in turn be determined by another which also is finite, and this last again by another, &c., ad infinitum." 2 Yet "it cannot be said that God is only the remote and not the proximate cause of indi- vidual things, except to distinguish them from those . . . which follow from His absolute nature." 3 Thus the causality of finite things, considered as modes of God, is not the nature of God viewed absolutely, but that nature as modified by, or expressed in, the endless i Etli. i. 29, clem. 2 Eth. i. 28, dem. 3 Ibid., schol. 160 Spinoza. regress of finite causes, or what Spinoza elsewhere calls " the common order of nature and constitution of things," or the " connection of causes." l This idea reappears throughout the whole system as a solvent of the diffi- culties involved in the relation of the purely indeter- minate God to a world of finite individualities in time and space. " The idea of an individual thing actually existing is an individual mode of thinking distinct from other modes," and is caused by God " not in so far as He is a thinking thing absolutely, but in so far as He is considered as affected by another mode of thinking, of which again He is the cause as affected by another, and so on to infinity." 2 " The human mind is part of the infinite intellect of God ; and when we say that the human mind perceives this or that, we affirm that God has this or that idea, not in so far as He is infinite, but in so far as He is expressed by the nature of the human mind, or constitutes the essence of the human mind." 3 On the other hand, though the causality of individual things is thus ascribed to God not as He exists absolutely or infinitely, we find from other passages that there is a sense in which they can be referred to the absolute or eternal nature of God as their cause e.g. : " It is the nature of reason to regard things not as contin- gent but as necessary. But this necessity of things is the very necessity of the eternal nature of God, and therefore it is the nature of reason to regard things under this form of eternity." " Every idea of every particular thing actually existing necessarily involves the eternal and infinite essence of God." " By existence (of individual things), I do not mean existence in so far as it is conceived abstractly and as a certain 1 Eth. ii. 30, dem. " Eth. ii. 9, dem. :! Eth. ii. 11, cor. H'lation of Substance ami Modes. 161 form of quantity; I speak of the very nature of existence which is ascribed to individual things, because an infinite number of things follows in infinite ways from the eternal necessity of God's nature of the existence of individual things as they are in God. For, although each individual thing is determined by another individual thing to exist in a certain manner, yet the force whereby each individual thing per- se veres in existing, follows from the eternal necessity of the nature of God." 1 Further, the two kinds of existence of individual things that in which they are viewed as a series of causes and effects in time and space, and that in which they are viewed. " under the form of eternity " are expressly contrasted as follows : " Things are conceived as actual in two ways either in so far as they exist in relation to a certain time and place, or in so far as we conceive them as contained in God and following from the necessity of the divine nature. When in this second way we con- ceive things as true and real, we conceive them under the form of eternity, and the ideas of them involve the eternal and infinite essence of God." 2 In the light of these and other passages to which we shall refer in the sequel, we are prepared to examine what is Spinoza's conception of the relation of infinite 01 absolute substance to its " modes." When we ask what in his system is the relation of the finite world and in- dividual finite things to God, the question is not settled simply by referring to his doctrine that all things exist in God, and that modes or finite things have no existence or operation independently of the infinite substance. 1 Eth. ii. 44, cor., ii. 45, and ibid., schol. - Eth. v. 29, schol. P. XII. L 162 Spinoza. Spinozism is not at once proved to be pantheistic by such expressions as these. For every system that is not dualistic, and for which the terms infinite and finite have any meaning, is pantheistic to the extent of hold- ing that the world has no absolute or independent ex- istence, and that the ultimate explanation of all things is to be found in God. Before pronouncing Spinoza a pantheist, therefore, the point to be determined is not whether he ascribes independent reality to finite things, but whether he ascribes to them any reality at all whether his modes have any existence distinguishable from that of substance, and such that we can speak of an actual relation between the two. If, on the one hand, it can be shown that the existence he ascribes to modes is only a fictitious or fugitive semblance of existence, if the distinction of modes from substance is a distinction which is created by the imagination and has no objective reality, and if the unity into which all individual things are resolved is one which does not maintain but sup- presses or annuls that distinction, then indeed his philo- sophy may justly be characterised as pantheistic. But, on the other hand, since real distinctions do not exclude but imply a unity which transcends them, if Spinoza's siibstance is a principle which subordinates but does not suppress differences, if his modes are the expression for a finite world which does not vanish, but constitutes a necessary and permanent moment in the unity of the infinite, then it is no proof of Spinoza's pantheism that he affirms that " whatever is is in God," and that modes are things that "exist only in God, and only through God can be conceived." In the passages quoted above, when read in the light of his general principles, there 7s the Doctrine Pantheistic? 163 is much to favour the former of these t\vo construc- tions of his system ; hut in these, as elsewhere, there are expressions which refuse to lend themselves to a purely pantheistic view of the relation of God to the world. 1. The considerations that favour the former or pan- theistic interpretation have already heen adduced, and need not here he repeated. They amount to this, that individual finite things have no real existence dis- tinguishable from that of absolute substance, but are merely creations of the abstracting imagination. " It is mere folly or insanity," he write?, 1 " to suppose that extended substance is made up of parts or bodies really dis- tinct from each other. ... If you ask why we are by nature so prone to attempt to divide extended substance, I answer that quantity is conceived by us in two ways : viz., abstractly> superficially, as we imagine it by aid of the senses ; or as substance, which can only be done by the understanding. So that if we attend to quantity, as it is in the imagination, it will be found to be divisible, finite, made up of parts, and manifold. Again, from the fact that we can limit duration and quantity at our pleasure, when we conceive the latter in abstraction from substance, and separate the former from the way in which it flows from things eternal, there arise time and measure time for the purpose of limiting duration, measure for the purpose of determining quantity so that we may, as far as possible, imagine them. Further, inasmuch as we separate the modifications of substance from substance itself, and reduce them to classes in order, as far as possible, to imagine them, there arises number, whereby we limit them. . . . Whence it is clear that measure, time, and num- ber are nothing but modes of thinking, or rather of imagin- ing. But," he adds, " there are many things which cannot 1 Ep. 29. 164 Spinoza. be conceived by the imagination, but only by the under- standing e.g., substance, eternity, and the like. Thus, if any one tries to explain these things by means of conceptions, which are mere aids to the imagination, he is simply trying to let his imagination run away with him." The drift of these and other passages which might be quoted is, not simply that modes, or individual finite things, have no existence independent of substance, but that they have no existence at all, save for a faculty which mistakes abstractions for realities. It is possible for the unreflecting mind to suppose itself capable of thinking the separate halves or minuter isolated parts of a line, but intelligence corrects the illusion. A line, it discerns, could as easily be made up of points lying miles apart as of points contiguous yet really isolated. The point it perceives to be a mere fictitious abstraction, an unreality, a thing which has no existence apart from the line, and when we think the line the point ceases to have any existence at all. And the same is true of lines in relation to surfaces, of surfaces in relation to solids, and of all existences in space in relation to space itself, which is the one infinite, indivisible reality. In like manner, when we regard the modes in relation to the infinite substance, we see that they are mere creatures of the imagination ; when we contemplate individual things from the point of view of intelligence, or as they really are, their illusory individuality vanishes', and the only reality left, the only being in the universe, is God, or Infinite Substance. And indeed it is only, Spinoza expressly affirms, when we leave out of view the fictitious differences which modes introduce into substance that the latter can be truly contemplated. " Substance is Spinoza's " Quatenw." 165 considered in itself that is, truly when we set aside all its modifications " (deposit is affectionibus). It is true that whilst Spinoza not only concedes but expressly teaches that modes or individual finite things have no reality in relation to the absolute nature of God, he yet contrives to ascribe to them, in a certain indirect way, a divine origin. " That Avhich is finite," says he, in a passage above quoted, " and has a determined ex- istence, cannot be produced or follow from the absolute nature of any attribute of God," for " whatever does so follow is infinite and eternal." And " every individual thing, or everything which is finite and has a determined existence, can only exist or be determined to act by another thing which is also finite, and this again only by another which also is finite, and so on indefinitely." " Only the infinite can follow from the infinite, the finite can follow only from the finite." How, then, does Spinoza reconcile these propositions with the assertion that modes " are conceived through the divine nature, and follow necessarily from it " 1 The answer is, that he simply begs the question. " That which is finite," he tells us, " cannot be produced by the absolute nature of God or of any of His attributes ; ... it must therefore follow from. God, or some attribute of God, in so far as (qua- te)i)i$) He is modified by a modification which is finite and has a determined existence, and this mode or cause must in turn be modified by another, &c." The only construction of which this proposition, taken in con- nection with what precedes it, is capable, is that it simply assumes without proof what has been already denied viz., that individual finite things can be derived from God. The nature of God is such that it does not admit 166 Spinoza. of modification, but finite things follow from it in so far as it is modified. Or, otherwise expressed, Spinoza pre- supposes the existence of finite things in order to prove it, or virtually makes God finite in order to express Himself in the finite. Finite things follow from God in so far as He is (already) modified by finite things. Every reader of Spinoza knows what an important role is assigned to this quafenm, and how often, by means of what is nothing more than a tautological phrase, he con- trives to escape from difficulties and inconsistencies otherwise insuperable. It may be said that Spinoza's reasoning here is not the bare petitio principii involved in the assertion that finite things follow from God in so far as they already follow from Him ; but that what he affirms is that they follow, not from individual finite things, but from the interminable series or connection of finite things, which is not finite but relatively infinite. But to this the answer is what, as we have seen, Spinoza has himself taught us, that by the spurious infinite of mere endless- ness we do not rise above the region of the finite. An infinite quantity is a contradiction in terms, a phrase in which the predicate denies the subject. By no indefinite addition or aggregation of finites can we reach the essen- tially or absolutely infinite that infinite from which Spinoza asserts that the finite can not be derived. In the foregoing view of Spinoza's doctrine as to the relation of God to the world, we have considered it simply as a relation of the absolutely indetermined infi- nite to determined or finite things. But in some of the above-quoted passages, and elsewhere, we find him ex- pressing this relation in terms of another category viz., Divine Causality. 167 that of causality. " God is the efficient cause of all things that can fall under an infinite intellect." * " God is the efficient cause not only of the existence of things but also of their essence." 2 " The modes of any given attribute have God for their cause, &c." 3 " Of things as they are in themselves God is really the cause, &c." 4 Now, as the relation of cause and effect is one in which we ordinarily think of the effect as something which, though dependent on the cause, actually emerges out of it into an existence of its own, the application of this category to the relation of God and the world would seem to give to finite things a reality which is not illusory or imaginative, a being which is not absorbed in that of infinite substance. But it is to be considered that, in its proper sense, causality is not a category which is applicable to the relation of the infinite to the finite ; and if we attempt so to apply it, what it expresses is not the reality of the finite, but either the limitation or the non-reality of the infinite. Causality is a category only of the finite. The rela- tion of cause and effect is one which implies the succes- sion or (though not with strict accuracy) the coexistence of its members. In the latter case it presupposes the existence of things external to, and affecting and being affected by each other. In the former, it is a relation in which the first member is conceived of as passing into the second ; the cause, or the sum of conditions which con- stitute it, loses its existence in the effect or in the sum of the new conditions to which it has given rise. The cause, iu other words, is only cause in and through the con- 1 Eth. i. 16, cor. 2 Eth. i. 25. 3 Eth. ii. 6. Eth. ii. 7, schol. 168 Spinoza. stimulated result which we call effect, and the very reality or realisation of the former implies, in a sense, its own extinction. In the impact of two balls the motion of the first becomes the cause of the motion of the second only when it has ceased to exist in the former ; the force which has existed as heat becomes the cause of motion only when it has exhausted itself of its existence in the one form and become converted into the other. But, obviously, in neither of these senses can we embrace the relation of the infinite and the finite under the form of causality. The infinite cannot be conceived of as external to, and acting on, the finite, as one finite body is outside of, and acts on, another ; in such a relation it would cease to be infinite. " God," says Spinoza, " is omne esse." Beyond substance there is nothing real. Substance and its affections con- stitute the totality of existence, and is absolutely in- finite. But this it could not be if its affections, instead of existing only in it and being conceivable only through it, had an existence capable of being acted on by it. Xor, again, can you speak of the infinite as a cause which, in producing the finite, passes wholly into it and becomes lost in it ; for, in that case, the existence of the finite would be conditioned by the non-existence or extinction of the infinite. The inapplicability of the category of causality to the relation of infinite and finite is thus so obvious that Spinoza can only give a colour of relevancy to it by qualifying the term " cause " when applied to God so as virtually to destroy its meaning. "God," he tells us, 1 " is not the transient but the immanent cause of the i Etk i. 18. Immanent Cause. 169 world." He can only be designated cause of all things in the same sense in which He is cause of Himself (<'au*a fit/). 1 In other words, to obviate the contradic- tion involved in the idea of an infinite which is exter- nal to the finite, he modifies the notion of cause so as to conceive of it as existing, not outside of, but wholly within, the things which are said to be its effects ; and to obviate the further difficulty which thus arises, of conceiving an infinite which passes away into the finite, he again modifies the notion of cause so as to conceive of it as maintaining its own independent existence at the same time that it loses itself in the effect. But though in the conception of a causa omnium rerum which is at the same time causa sui, what Spinoza is aiming at is the idea of a Being which remains one with itself in all its changes, or of a self-differentiating, which is at the same time a self -integrating, infinite, this idea is one which in vain attempts to express itself under the category of causality. The attempt so to express it may be regarded as one of those indications in Spinoza of the consciousness of another than the purely negative relation of the finite -to the infinite which his own inadequate logic forced him to maintain. 2. The foregoing considerations seem almost conclu- sively to favour that view of Spinoza's doctrine of modes which denies to individual finite things any existence that is not fictitious and illusory. His derivation of modes from substance would seem to be nothing more than a reversal of the process of abstraction by which the idea of substance was reached. It is not substance which determines itself to modes, but we who, with a i Eth. i. -25, clem. 170 Spinoza. show of logic, reintroduce into it the fictitious distinc- tions which the same logic had abolished. But this account of Spinoza's doctrine would be in- complete if we did not point out that, however incon- sistently they enter into it, there are elements of his system which refuse to lend themselves to the notion of the unreality of the finite world. Modes are not invariably represented as merely transient creations of the abstracting imagination. They have in them a positive element which remains even when on the negative side they have been resolved into the unity of substance. Besides the tacit implication of another doctrine in the idea of a causa sui which is at the same time causa omnium rerum, the following considerations seem to point in the same direction : (1.) Even if modes are only transient forms, there must be a reason in the nature of substance for their existence as suck. Though everything else in the finite world is resolved into negation, the negation itself is not so resolved. Evanescence itself does not vanish. When you have reduced all finite things to phantoms, insubstantial as the things of a dream, the dream-world itself remains to be accounted for ; and more than that, obviously the mind which perceives and pronounces that it if a dream-world cannot belong to that world. In ascribing to intelligence the function of rising above and abolishing the distinction from substance of finite things, Spinoza virtually exempts intelligence itself from the process of abolition. The criterion of the illusory cannot be itself illusory. If therefore, as Spinoza asserts, "that which is finite and has a determinate Positive Element in the Finite. 171 nature cannot follow from the absolute nature of God, for whatever does so follow is infinite and eternal," what this involves as to that intelligence which discerns the nothingness of finite things is, not that it does not follow from the absolute nature of God, but that it has in it, in its very discernment of its distinction from God, an element of what is infinite and eternal (2.) That Spinoza himself, despite of his own princi- ple that " all determination is negation," recognises in modes something that is not mere negation, is indirectly indicated by the qualified form in which in the ' Ethics ' that principle is stated. " The finite," says he, 1 " is in part negation " (ex parte negatio). The negation implied in finitude is not complete but partial. There is, in other words, a positive element in finite things, which is not annulled when the fictitious distinction from the infinite is taken away. There is an individuality which survives the extinction of the false or spurious individu- ality. Xor is this implied only in the phrase " partial negation." Besides the idea of God as the negation of all determinations there are traces of another and oppo- site idea that of the affirmation of all determinations. For the indivisible unity in which all differences vanish, Spinoza seems often, without consciousness of inconsis- tency, to substitute the infinite unity which comprehends in it all possible differences. " From the necessity of the divine nature," says lie, 2 " must follow an infinite number of things in infinite -ways." " There is not wanting to God materials for the creation of all things from the highest to the lowest degree of perfec- 1 Eth. L 8, schol. - Eth. i. 16. 172 Spinoza. tion for the producing of all things which can be conceived by an infinite intellect." 1 " There are two ways," says he in a passage already quoted, " in which things are conceived by us as actual viz., either as existing in relation to a certain time and place, or as contained in God and following from the necessity of the divine nature. In the second way we conceive them as true and real, under the form of eter- nity, and the ideas of them involve the eternal and infinite essence of God." 2 And when we have reached the latter point of view, what we have ceased to see in finite things is not their individuality, but their finitude. Their true individu- ality is not lost, for " every idea of an individual thing actually existing necessarily involves the idea of the eternal and infinite essence of God ; . . . for the force by which each individual thing perseveres in its own existence folloAvs from the eternal necessity of the divine nature." 3 "In God there is necessarily an idea which expresses the essence of this or that body under the form of eternity," 4 and this idea is a certain mode of thinking which is necessarily eternal. 5 What is lost, what of our former unreal view of things disappears, is their con- tingency, their transient, fugitive being as things of time and sense, for " it is of the nature of reason to contem- plate things as they are in themselves i.e., not as con- tingent but as necessary," 6 not " as determined each by another finite thing, but as following from the eternal necessity of the nature of God." 7 That there is, in Spinoza's view, an affirmative ele- 1 Hth. i., Append. 2 Eth. v. 29, schol. :i Eth. ii. 45, deni. and schol . 4 Eth. v. 22. 8 Eth. v 23, schol. e Eth. ii. 44, cor. 2. 7 Eth. ii. 45, schol. Tlic, Self-maintaining Impulse. 173 nient which remains to finite things when the negative element which seemed to distinguish them from the in- finite is obliterated, an individuality which, taken up into the infinite, still exists and can be known through the in- finite, these passages seem clearly to teach. But if we ask further and more definitely what that element is, and how it " follows from the infinite nature of God," the answer is by no means satisfactory. As to the first question, that element in the finite which lifts it out of the sphere of time into " the form of eternity " is, Spinoza tells us, the inherent impulse or endeavour of each individual thing to maintain itself or persevere in its own being. " No individual thing has in it anything by which it can be destroyed or which can deprive it of its existence ; but, on the contrary, it is opposed to all that could de- prive it of its existence." x There is in each thing an " endeavour (conatus) by which it seeks to persevere in its own being," and this endeavour " is nothing but the actual essence of the thing itself," 2 and it is therefore something not conditioned by time, " it involves no finite but an indefinite time." But is not this con- ception of the self-maintenance or persevering in exist- ence of an individual thing a simple tautology ? Does it mean any more than this, that when we think of it as an existing thing, we cannot think of it as a non-existing thing ? Is not the inherent capacity to persevere in existing simply the incapacity of the mind to predicate of a thing at once existence and non-existence 1 When \ve say that a thing necessarily perseveres in existence, do we say any more than that, so long as we think of it, we think of it as existing, or that the conception of i Eth. iii. 6, deni. 2 Ibid., 7. ] 74 Spinoza. existence excludes or contradicts the conception of non-existence ] Moreover, is not this perseverance in existing which is supposed to pertain to a thing as seen "under the form of eternity," a conception which is still conditioned by time ? We do not escape from the quantitative idea of duration merely by making it indefinite. Indefinite or endless duration is a form of time and not of eternity. As to the second ques- tionviz., as to the relation of this self-maintaining element in the finite to God all that Spinoza says amounts simply to the affirmation that it has its ori- gin in the absolute nature of God, and is a determi- nate expression of that nature. " Although each in- dividual thing," says he, 1 " is determined to exist in a certain way by another individual thing, yet the force by which each thing perseveres in existing follows from the eternal necessity of the nature of God." " Individ- ual things are modes by which the attributes of God are expressed in a certain definite manner, &c." 2 How finite things can have in them a power of self-mainten- ance, a capacity of continuous existence flowing from their own nature, and yet have nothing in them which does not follow from the nature of God, is the problem to be solved, and Spinoza's only solution is simply to affirm that both propositions are true. As the result of our inquiry we seem to have found in Spinoza's account of the nature of modes statements which, if not irreconcilable, he has made no attempt to reconcile. In accordance with the principle which generally governs his reasoning, the very essence of finite things is identified with negation or non-being ; 1 Eth. ii 45, scliol. 2 tb. iii. 6, dem. Result of Inquiry. 175 they not merely have no real existence apart from God, but existence in God is for them equivalent to extinction of existence. Yet, on the other hand, as we have just seen, to these same finite things Spinoza ascribes a posi- tive, self-affirmative nature, an individuality which is inherent and essential, and which is not extinguished when the limits that divide the finite from the infinite are removed. And if thus Spinoza's two representations of the nature of finite things seem to conflict, equally conflicting are the corresponding representations of the nature of God. To the former representation of the finite corresponds the notion of a purely indeterminate, to the latter that of a self-determining Infinite. In the one case the world is nothing and God is all ; in the other, the world is the manifold expression of the nature of God, and God the Being whose nature unfolds with- out losing itself in the innumerable individualities of the finite world. If Spinozism contained no other con- ception of the relation of God to the world than the first, we should be compelled to pronounce it a purely pantheistic system. Perhaps the second conception may be regarded as the expression on Spinoza's part of an unconscious endeavour to correct the inadequacy of the first. But the correction, whilst it obviates the impu- tation of thorough - going pantheism, and elevates his system above all other pantheistic philosophies, is still imperfect in this respect, that it implies a principle of self-determination in God which is without any specula- tive ground in his idea of the divine nature. At best, it only creates the demand for a more complete and self- consistent philosophy, and indicates the direction in which it lies. 176 CHAPTER X. INFINITE MODES. SPINOZA'S system, so far as we have traced its develop- ment in the foregoing pages, leaves us still without any principle of mediation between God and the world. If, as we have just seen, it sometimes represents finite things as possessing an element of individuality which, taken up into the infinite, still remains, and therefore seems to imply a principle of self-determination in the divine nature, so far as we have gone this principle is simply affirmed, not proved ; the gap between the infinite and finite remains unbridged. But there are certain passages in the 'Ethics ' in which Ave meet with a concep- tion not yet referred to, that of " Infinite Modes, "- a conception which may be regarded as an attempt to fill up the gap. As the very phrase indicates, " infinite modes " point to something whicli constitutes a link between the two worlds. As " modes," they belong to the sphere of the finite ; as " infinite " modes, to that of the infinite. Despite of Spinoza's own asser- tion, that the finite can only follow from the finite, we have here a conception in which the ideas of in- finite and finite are combined. The following arc the Examples of Infinite Modes. 177 passages in which the doctrine of infinite modes is most fully expressed : " Whatever follows from any at- tribute of God, in so far as it is modified by a modifica- tion which exists necessarily and as infinite through the said attribute, must also exist necessarily and infinitely;" 1 and conversely, " Every mode which exists both neces- sarily and as infinite, must necessarily follow, either from the absolute nature of some attribute of God, or from an attribute modified by a modification which exists neces- sarily and as infinite." 2 Spinoza here speaks of certain modes or modifications of divine attributes, differing therefore from the attributes in this respect, that the latter are conceived through themselves, the former only through the attributes. Further, of these modes he specifies two classes or grades : first, those which follow immediately from attributes ; and secondly, those which follow from attributes already modified : but to both the predicate " infinite " is applied. One of Spinoza's cor- respondents 3 asks for examples of these two classes of modes, and conjectures that thought and extension may belong to the first, "the intellect in thought" and " motion in extension " to the second. Spinoza, with- out waiting to correct the obvious error of finding in thought and extension, which are themselves attri- butes, examples of modifications of attributes, answers thus : 4 " Examples which you ask are, of the first class, in thought, the absolutely infinite intellect (intellectus absolute infim'tus), in extension, motion, and rest ; of the second class, the form of the whole universe (fades tot! us universf), which, although it varies in infinite ways, remains always the same." 1 Eth. i. 22. 2 th. i. 23. 3 Ep. 65. 4 Ep. 66. P. XII. M 178 Spinoza. At first sight, Spinoza seems to be here attempting to combine ideas which are reciprocally exclusive. Sub- stance and modes, he himself affirms, include all being. But in infinite modes we have a third something which belongs to neither category which is neither " in itself" nor " in another," neither infinite nor finite, but both at once. If the absolutely infinite is " that which contains in its essence whatever expresses reality and involves no negation," is not an infinite mode as self-contradictory as a round square or a rectangular circle ? " Intellect," he tells us, 1 "whether finite OT infinite" (and the same is true of the other infinite modes), belongs to the sphere of natura naturata that is, to the order of things which exist only for the imagination and its quantifying forms of time and measure ; yet, at the same time, these infi- nite modes are things which " cannot have a limited duration," but " must exist always and infinitely," or to which pertains the timeless immanent unity of the na- ture of God. 2 In this conception of infinite modes there seems thus to be involved the same apparent contradic- tion with which theological controversy has made us familiar in the doctrine of the " Logos " or " Son of God," in which we meet with the same seemingly irre- concilable elements of subordination and equality with God ; of that which is " begotten," and therefore finite, and that which is consubstantial with God, and therefore infinite ; of that which is described as " eternally begot- ten," and therefore as l>elonging at once to the sphere of the temporal and to that of the eternal. And that this is not a merely fanciful analogy, but one which was present to Spinoza's own mind, we learn from his earlier 1 Eth. i. 32, cor. 2 Eth. i. 21. anl .Ion. Motive of the Conception. 179 treatise ' Concerning God and Man,' in which, with ex- press reference to the subject before us, we find him thus writing : " As to the modes or creatures which immediately depend on God, of these we know only two viz., motion in matter, and intellect in thought of which we affirm that they have been from all eternity, and will be unchangeably to all eter- nity. . . . As to motion, therefore, that it is that which is in its nature infinite, and that it can neither exist nor be con- ceived through itself, but only by means of extension, . . . of all this I will only say here that it is a son of God, or a work or effect immediately created by God. As to intellect in thought, this also, like the former, is a son of God, . . . created from all eternity, and continuing unchangeable to all eternity. Its sole function is that of clearly and distinctly understanding all things in all times." l Can the conception of infinite modes be freed from the contradiction which it thus seems to involve 1 The answer is, that though on Spinoza's principles the con- tradiction is really insoluble, yet in this conception we have an elaborate attempt to solve it. Infinitude and finite individuality express ideas which, as Spinoza de- fines them, are reciprocally exclusive ; but when we examine what is meant by the phrase " infinite modes," we find that it involves, in opposite directions, an en- deavour so to modify these ideas as to bring them into coherence. On the one hand it introduces, at a lower stage, into the idea of the infinite, that element of activity or self-determination which is lacking to the higher ideas of sxibstance and attributes. On the other hand, it attempts to raise the finite world to a quasi 1 De Deo, i. cap. 9. 1 80 Spinoza. infinitude which is denied to the separate individualities that compose it. The barren infinitude is thus rendered fertile, and then finite things are so ennobled as to make it possible to claim for them an infinite origin. The former side of this modifying process is expressed by that class or grade of infinite modes which are " imme- diate modifications" of the attributes of thought and extension ; the latter, by those which are modifications of the second degree, of which Spinoza adduces only one example, the fades tot ins nniversi. 1. Of the infinite modes which are immediate modi- fications of attributes, two are specified viz., "motion and rest" as modifications of extension, and "the ab^.>- lutely infinite intellect " as the modification of thought. Now, if we examine the function assigned to these " immediate modes," we shall find that they are simply the attributes of extension and thought, plus that element of activity or self-determination which these attributes lack, and yet which is necessary to make them the pro- ductive sources of finite things. The very designation " infinite mode " shows that Spinoza is here uncon- sciously seeking to introduce into his system the element of difference or finitude which is excluded from the abstract unity of substance. From such an abstract infinite, the purity of which can be maintained only hy the elimination of all distinctions (*iti* a/ectionibus), it is impossible to find any way back to the finite. Xor could it legitimately be made the living source of finite existences save by transforming it from the abstract unity which extinguishes difference into the concrete unity of a principle in which all differences are at once embraced and subordinated. But whilst Spinoza's logic First Class of Infinite, Modes. 181 debarred him from any such introduction of a negative or finite element into the purely affirmative unity of substance, or even into the infinitude in suo genere which is the conception of attribute, the need for such an element, if he would not arrest the descending move- ment of thought, asserts itself at the stage we have now reached, and finds its expression in the conception of infinite modes, or of an infinite which contains in it the element of negation or finitude. With such a conception a new principle of self-development is introduced into his system. The barren self-identical infinite becomes now an infinite which has in it the impulse to realise itself in all the manifold individualities of the finite world. That it is this principle of activity or self- development which Spinoza is aiming at in the con- ception of infinite modes, becomes clear from the examples he gives of these modes, and from what he says as to their nature and function. Of extension the infinite modification is " motion and rest " ; and of what he conceived to be the relation in this case of the mode to the attribute, we have a clear indication in his answer to inquiries on this point from his acute corre- spondent Tschirnhaiisen. 1 " It is very difficult," writes the latter, " to conceive how the existence of bodies which have motion and figure can be demonstrated a pi'iori, since in extension, considered absolutely, nothing of the kind occurs." To this Spinoza answers by distinguish- ing his own from the Cartesian notion of extension." " From extension, as Cartesius conceives it that is, as a mere inert mass it is not only difficult, as you say, but altogether impossible, to demonstrate the existence of 1 Epp. 69-72. 182 Spinoza. bodies. For inert matter, as it is in itself, will persevere in its rest, and will not be excited to motion save by a more powerful external cause. And on this account I have not hesitated formerly to affirm that the Cartesian principles of natural things are useless, not to say absurd." In a subsequent letter, in answer to further difficulties propounded by his correspondent, Spinoza points out that Descartes' notion of extension breaks down by his own showing, seeing that he can only deduce the variety of things from extension by supposing it to be set in motion by God. Matter, therefore, cannot be explained by extension as Descartes defines it, " but must necessarily be explained by an attribute which expresses eternal and infinite essence." The further elucidation of this answer which Spinoza promises is not given, but his meaning is obvious. An attribute of God which explains the manifolclness of things only by call- ing in the co-operation of an arbitrary external force, is not what it pretends to be viz., " that which ex- presses an eternal and infinite essence." It must not be supplemented by an outside mover, but must contain in itself implicitly the element of motion or activity. And this idea Spinoza conceives himself to have attained for his own attribute of extension by the proposition that motion and rest constitute its immediate infinite mode. In other words, extension, or what is here the same thing, matter, is not a mere passive inert mass, but contains in it, as equally essential moments, both motion and rest. It is to be noticed that motion and rest are here represented by Spinoza, not as two differ- ent things, but as constituting one infinite mode, parallel to that of " infinite intellect " in thought. His Meaning of these Modes. 1 83 motion is a motion which is self-terminated, or which is not moved by anything outside of itself ; his rest is the rest of that which is in intense and unchangeable activity. In other words, his first infinite mode is simply self- determined extension, or extension with the element of activity or self-determination in it. From purely infinite or indeterminate thought it is as impossible to derive the manifold world of finite in- telligences as from extension, considered as a mere inert mass, to demonstrate the existence of bodies. Blank self-identical thought remains one with itself. It is the form of all ideas without the possibility of the actual existence of any. Implicitly the whole wealth of the world of intelligence is contained in it ; but it can never realise that wealth, or become conscious of its own con- tent, because to do so would be to introduce distinction into that the very nature of which is to transcend all distinctions. But what Spinoza wants is an infinite thought which, while it remains one with itself, is yet the productive source of an actual world of ideas and intelligences. The only legitimate way in which this could be achieved would be by transforming the idea of God as Substance, with thought for its attribute, into that of self-conscious Spirit or Mind. From this, how- ever, which would have implied the reconstruction of his whole philosophy, Spinoza was precluded, and the expedient to which he had recourse was to introduce the element of self-determination into thought under the guise of an " infinite mode." " Intellect," though " ab- solutely infinite," is not absolute thought (cogitatio ab- aoliita), but only a certain mode of thinking, and there- fore . . . must be referred not to natur". tt>it>ii->.ui*, but 184 Spinoza. to natura naturata" l By this means, without intro- ducing difference into that which is " absolutely perfect that is, absolutely indeterminate " Spinoza can claim for the whole finite realm of thought a necessary deriva- tion from the divine nature. " Infinite intellect " is not simply infinite thought, but that which knows infinite thought and all that is contained in it. " From the necessity of the divine nature must follow an infinitude of things in infinite ways that is, all things that can fall under an infinite intellect." 2 "Active intellect, finite or infinite, must comprehend the attributes and affections of God." 3 " The ideas of (even) non-existent individual things or modes must be comprehended in the infinite idea of God." 4 Thus to " intellect," as an immediate mode of thought, though it is said to belong to the sphere of the finite (natura naturata), the predicate " absolutely infinite " may be applied, inasmuch as there is nothing in the realm of thought which it does not comprehend. Though it contains an infinite number of determinations, they are, from first to last, self-deteT- minations. Though, as the productive source of all ideas, it is intensely and unceasingly active, yet, like the parallel mode of extension, its activity is a motion which is never moved. As motion, which is at the same time rest, is infinite, because it is motion which is terminated only by itself, so intellect is infinite, because its activity knows no limit that does not fall within its own domain. What, in short, Spinoza is aiming at by the conception of " intellect " as an " infinite mode " of thought, is the virtual introduction into his system of 1 Eth. i. 31, clem. ^ Eth. i. 16. 3 Eth. i. 30. Eth. ii.8. Second Class of Infinite Modes. 185 what " he had actually excluded from his idea of God viz., the principle of self -consciousness or of thought as an active, self -determining principle which, in all its determinations, remains one with itself. 2. I have said that the conception of infinite modes is an attempt to bring into union the irreconcilable ideas of infinitude and finite individuality, not only in the way we have just considered viz., by introducing the element of self-determination into the idea of the infi- nite but also, from an opposite direction, by elevating the finite world into a quasi infinitude. Spinoza had laid down the principle that nothing can follow from the infinite save that which is itself infinite and eternal, and conversely, that " that which is finite and has a determined existence cannot be produced by the abso- lute nature of God." The world of finite individualities, therefore, can never be connected by necessary derivation with the first principle of his system, the absolute nature of God or an attribute of God, unless he can con- trive to lend to that world such a guise of infinitude as will make it homogeneous with its origin. This he attempts to do by the second order of infinite modes or modifications of divine attributes in the second degree, the nature of which he exemplifies in the phrase " form of the whole universe." And the way in which he finds it possible to connect this totality of things with the absolute nature of God, is by ascribing to it, as a whole, a kind of infinitude and unchangeableness which does not pertain to the parts of which it is composed, taken individually. For this " form of the whole universe," "though it varies in infinite ways," though its con- stituent finite parts are determined each only by other 186 Sjnnoza. Unite parts, and may be conceived to be endlessly diver- sified in their particular movements, yet taken as a whole, or as one composite individual, remains ever the same. 1 The individual parts are finite or determined ; but as constituting together the whole universe, outside of which there is nothing to determine them, they are infinite. Here, therefore, we have an aspect of the finite world in which, in a being derived from the abso- lute nature of God, it fulfils the condition that nothing can be so derived which is not infinite and eternal. Un- der whatever attribute we contemplate this totality of things whether as the aggregate of all corporeal things, or as the sum of all ideas nothing is presupposed to it save " the absolute nature of some attribute of God, or of such an attribute modified by a modification which is necessary and infinite." The sole presupposi- tion of the totality of finite bodies is the attribute of extension, conceived as self-determining, or under the infinite mode of motion ; the sole presupposition of the totality of ideas is the attribute of thought conceived of under the infinite mode of intellect. If the phrase "fades tot iiis universi" be regarded as embracing both the world of thought and the world of things, then we have here a point of view from which we can contem- plate it as an infinite and eternal expression of the abso- lute nature of God. If we ask what is the value of this attempt to mediate between the infinite or absolute nature of God and the finite world by the conception of " infinite modes," the answer can only be that Spinoza himself has furnished the proof of its inconclusiveness. The sum or aggregate of modifications is not equivalent to the unmodified ; by 1 Ep. 66, and II. Lemma 7, schol. Criticism of the Conception. 187 endless additions of finites we do not reach the true infinite ; the totality of relative, changeable things is no nearer than any one of them to the unchangeable abso- lute. Spinoza's finite modes, even when, by a petitio l>rii:ij>ii, he speaks of each mode as determined by God in so far as He is expressed by another finite mode, and that by others in endless series, are only contiguous, not essentially related, to each other. The whole finite world, in so far as we can conceive it at all, is broken up into an endless multiplicity of isolated atoms, and the attempt to sum them gives us only the false infinite of indefinite number, which leaves us no nearer the true infinite at the end than at the beginning. It may be possible, indeed, in another way to discern a real infinitude in the multiplicity of finite things. As a living organism is a unity which is not the sum of its parts, but prior to yet expressing itself in each and all of them, so it may be possible to conceive of the fades fiift//* unirirx! as an infinite organic whole, every infi- nitesimal portion of which is instinct with the universal life, every part of which lives in and through the rest, and all together constitute, not an aggregate outwardly related to, but a corporate unity which is the living expression of its infinite author. But though Spinoza undoubtedly aimed at a view of the universe in which all finite things should be seen to follow from, and constitute a necessary expression of, the absolute nature of God, we seek in vain in his dialectic for any such principle of organic coherence between the individualities of the finite world and the infinite substance. By his own acknowledgment his "infinite modes " belong still to the sphere of nntura naturafa, and the gulf between them and his nntura naturan* remains unbridged. 188 CHAPTEE XL THE NATURE AND ORIGIN OF THE MIND. THE Second Book of the ' Ethics,' to which the above title is prefixed, opens with the following words : " I will now explain the results which must necessarily fol- low from the nature of God, or of the Being eternal and infinite ; not, indeed, all these results, . . . but only those which can lead us to the knowledge of the human mind and of its highest. blessedness." In these words we have the key to the subsequent course of Spinoza's speculations with respect both to the intellectual and the moral nature of man. Here, as in his former work on ' The Improvement of the Human Understanding,' his aim is not a theoretical but a practical one not primarily the search for intellectual satisfaction, but the discovery of the way to spiritual perfection and blessedness. But as, in his view, all moral advancement rests on and is in one sense identical with intelligence, the true way to perfection is to disabuse our minds of error and illusion, and to gain a point of view from which we shall see things as they really are. His inquiry into the nature of the human mind, therefore, resolves itself into the question whether, from its very nature, human intelli- Tu -of old Aspect of MlmL 189 gence is capable of adequate, or only of inadequate or imperfect knowledge. Spinoza's doctrine of " finite modes " contains two different and apparently irrecon- cilable views of the nature of individual finite things that in which the finite is represented as destitute of any positive reality, and that, on the other hand, in which the negation involved in the notion of the finite is only a partial negation, leaving to it still a positive element, " a force by which each individual thing perseveres in existence, and which follows from the eternal necessity of the divine nature." And what is true of finite things is equally true of our knowledge of them. The finite mind, like all other finite things, has, on the one hand, an existence that is merely negative and illusory ; the idea of the finite is itself finite, limited and determined by other finites, and in- capable of rising above itself. On the other hand, it has in it an element which is not mere negation, which transcends the limits of the finite and relates it to the absolute nature of God. In the former aspect, in its actual, empirical reality, it contemplates all things only under the form of time ; it looks on the world from the point of view of sense and imagination, broken up into fictitious individualities, or into things which have only accidental relations to each other in time and space. In the latter aspect, it sees all things from the point of view of reason or intelligence, as having in them a nature that is not unreal and relations that are not accidental, but which " involve the eternal and infinite necessity of the nature of God ; " it sees them " under the form of eternity." Xow whether this twofold existence and activity 190 Spinoza. which Spinoza ascribes to the human mind is not, when closely examined, an impossible and self-con- tradictory notion, need not here be considered ; what we are at present concerned to notice is, that it is obviously Spinoza's aim, both here and in the more strictly ethical part of his system, to represent the lower or finite aspect of human nature as an imperfect stage of man's being, and the higher or infinite aspect as the goal of perfection to which, by its very essence, it is capable of attaining. The human mind, as we first contemplate it, is im- prisoned in the finite. It is an individual amongst other individuals, a link in the endless series of exist- ences, to parts of which only it stands in immediate relation. Its knowledge is only of the particular ; it is a finite mode which has for its object only another finite mode ; and it has no knowledge of other things save in their accidental relation to its ow'n particular being no knowledge, therefore, which is not at once fragmentary and confused. The mind is thus in its origin simply " the idea of an individual thing actually existing, or an individual mode of thinking ; " and its whole conception of things is determined by this indi- vidual reference. But though it would seem to be impossible, on Spinoza's principles, that the individual finite mind should, without ceasing to be finite or losing its in- dividuality, attain to any higher knowledge, it is implied in his whole treatment of the subject, that the mind is capable of emancipating itself from the par- ticular, and of attaining to a knowledge of things from a universal point of view. There is a stage of human Stages of Intelligence. 191 intelligence in which it has become liberated from accidental associations and can contemplate things not as they are merely in relation to our own individuality, but as they are in their own nature and in their necessary relations to each other. At this stage of knowledge the mind has ceased to be dominated by the senses and the imagination ; its objects are not mere transient phenomena, but permanent laws. But beyond this there is a yet higher stage. Even the second stage of knowledge, in which we connect things under necessary principles and laws, rests on and involves the highest principle of all, " the very necessity of the nature of God." But there is a form of know- ledge of which this principle is not merely the implied basis but the very essence that which Spinoza de- signates " intuitive knowledge," " which proceeds from an adequate idea of the absolute essence of certain attributes of God to the adequate knowledge of the essence of things." When it has reached this highest stage of intelligence, the mind, starting with the unity which is present in all knowledge, sees all things in the light of it ; it discerns the immanence of the infinite in the finite, and regards the finite as real only in so far as it has the infinite in it. Thus Spinoza's inquiry into the nature of the human mind begins with the definition of the mind as " the knowledge of the body," and ends virtually with defining it as the knowledge of God and of all things in God. Its first consciousness of things is from a purely individual, but it is capable of rising to a universal standpoint. Lost at first in the confused and inadequate ideas of sense and imagination, human intelligence has in it the capacity of rising above itself. 192 Spinoza. of seeing things no longer in online aiui, but in their objective reality and necessary relations ; and finally, it is capable of reaching a point from which by the intuitive grasp of reason it can discern all individual things, and all relations of things in their absolute unity, as expressions of "the eternal necessity of the divine nature." I. If now we examine a little more closely the course of thought of which the foregoing is an outline, the lirst important proposition in Spinoza's account of the nature of the mind is that the human mind is " the idea of the body." " The first," says he, " which constitutes the actual being of the human mind is nothing else than the idea of an actually existing individual thing," and " the object of the idea which constitutes the human mind is the body that is, a definite actually existing mode of extension and nothing else." l The proof that the mind is the idea of the body is simply an application to the nature of man of Spino- za's general doctrine of the attributes of thought and extension, and of the modes as parallel expressions of these attributes. Substance is both a " thinking thing" and an "extended thing" ; but thought and extension, and their respective modes, are not essentially different, but only different expressions of one and the same thing. To every mode of thought a mode of extension corresponds, the order or series of thoughts is the same as the order or series of things, and every actually existing thing may be regarded as a modification both of thought and extension. We say of man that he is composed of body and mind, 2 but the body and the 1 Eth. ii. 11 and 13. 2 ii. 13, cor. Mind is tJie Idea of tJic Body. 193 idea of the body are one and the same thing, contem- plated, now under one attribute, now under another. The two worlds of mind and matter, thoughts and things, are thus absolutely separated from each other. Though completely correspondent, they are absolutely independent, and idealistic explanations of physical, and materialistic explanations of mental phenomena, are equally precluded. In Spinoza's theory there is as little room for the deus ex machina of Descartes as for the " occasional causes " of Geulinx or the " pre-estab- lished harmony " of Leibnitz, to explain the relation of body and mind and the correspondence of bodily and mental acts ; for relation implies difference, and in this case there is no difference, but only one and the same thing contemplated in different aspects. We may, indeed, refer both mental and material phenomena to God as their cause, but we can refer the former only to God or Substance as thinking thing, the latter to God or Substance as extended thing. To trace the existence of any material object to the " will of God " would be to explain by the attribute of thought what can only be explained by the attribute of extension. A circle and the idea of a circle are ono and the same thing, conceived now under the attribute of extension, now under the attribute of thought ; but we cannot explain the ideal circle by the actual or by any mode of extension, but only by thought and modes of thought, and vice versa. Body and mind, in like manner, are to be conceived each as a mode of its own attribute ; and the only union of the two of which we can speak, is involved in the proposition that for everything that exists " formally " i.e., as a modification of extension there exists some- p. XIT. x 194 Spinoza. thing exactly parallel "objectively" i.e., as a modifica- tion of thought. What, then, from this view of the nature of things, are we to understand by Spinoza's definition of mind as " the idea of the body " 1 In the first place, it might seem that there is much in man's spiritual nature which this definition does not embrace. By defining it as an " idea " or mode of thought, does not Spinoza leave out of sight such essential elements of that nature as feel- ing, desire, will, &c., and reduce it to something purely intellectual ? The answer is, that, in Spinoza's view, knowledge, the objective knowledge of the human body, precedes all other forms of consciousness and constitutes the fundamental essence of man's mental nature. Xo emotional or volitional element can exist without pre- supposing thought, and the latter can exist without the former. Thought is not one among many co-ordinate faculties, each having its own peculiar function, its own time and mode of action ; it is the principle which underlies all the many-sided aspects of our spiritual life, and of which these are but various specifications. " Modes of thinking, such as love, desire, or affections of the mind, by whatever name they are designated, do not exist iinless there exists in the same individual an iilt-n of the thing loved, desired, &c. But the idea may exist without any other mode of thinking." 1 ''The essence of man is constituted by modes of thinking, to all of which the idea is by nature prior, and it is only when that exists that the other modes can exist in the same individual. Therefore the idea is the first thing consti- tuting the being of the human mind." '' 1 Eth. ii., ax. 3. - Eth. ii. 11, deni. Mind not an abstract Entity. 195 But, secondly, even if we accept the doctrine that the ideal element is that to which all other elements of man's spiritual nature may be reduced, this doctrine, it may be said, does not to the modern ear seem to be expressed by the proposition, " the mind is the idea of the body." Modern thought conceives of mind as the conscious, thinking self to which ideas are referred, the rational nature, which is not one idea but the source or subject, at lowest, "the permanent possibility," of all ideas. But the explanation of Spinoza's phraseology lies in this, that mind, as anything more than the idea of the body (or of " affections " of the body), is for him a mere abstraction. It is only by a fictitious, imaginative gen- eralisation that we conceive of any abstract faculty of thinking, feeling, willing, apart from particular thoughts, feelings, volitions ; so it is only by carrying the same fictitious generalisation still further that we conceive of an abstract entity called " mind," which is no particular mental activity, but a capacity of all activities. Such a conception belongs to the same fictitious region with the conception of " lapidity " in relation to stones, or " aquos- ity " to streams. " There is," says he, 1 " in the mind no absolute faculty of understanding, desiring, loving, . This further step may be expressed by saying that the first determination is that of mind as consciousness of an object, the second that of mind as self-consciousness. As "the mind is united to the body because the body is the object of the Idea of the Mind. 201 mind, so ... the idea of the mind is united to its ob- ject, the mind, in the same way as the mind is united to the body ; " the only difference being that " mind and body are one and the same individual regarded, now under the attribute of thought, now under that of ex- tension," whereas " the idea of the mind and the mind are one and the same thing regarded under one and the same attribute, that of thought." l The proof of the doctrine of idea mentis is twofold, (1) from the nature of God, (2) from the nature of mind itself as " the idea of the body." (1.) The human mind, as we have seen above, is, according to Spinoza, " part of the infinite intellect of God." To say that the mind perceives anything is to say " that God has this or that idea, not in so far as He is infinite, but in so far as He constitutes the essence of the human mind." But it is involved in the divine attribute of thought that " there must necessarily exist in God an idea both of Himself and of all His affections, and therefore an idea of the human mind." 2 " The idea of the mind and the mind itself exist in God by the same necessity and the same power of thinking." 3 The human mind, therefore (or God as constituting its essence), has an idea of itself. (2.) The same thing is proved from the nature of mind itself, regarded as " the idea of the body." " The idea of the mind, or the idea of the idea, is simply the form of the idea considered as a mode of thought with- out reference to its object. For one who knows any- thing, in the very act of doing so knows that he knows 1 Eth. ii. 21, deiu. aiid schol. 2 Eth. ii. 20, dein. 3 th. ii. 21, schol. 202 Spinoza. it, and knows that he knows that he knows it, and so on ad infinitum." l What it is of most importance to remark as to this doctrine of idea mentis is that, notwithstanding Spino- za's assertion of the absolute independence and equality of the two parallel series of modes, a richer content is here ascribed to the mental than to the corporeal side. The idea of the body corresponds to the body, but there is nothing in the latter which corresponds to the idea's consciousness of itself. The body, as a mode of exten- sion, has relations to other modes of extension, and the idea which constitutes the mind has relations to other modes of thought ; but in the series of ideas there is interposed a relation which has nothing parallel to it in the series of material modes viz., the relation of each idea to itself. In returning upon itself, mind is not the correlate in thought of anything that takes place in ex- tension. It possesses a self-activity, a power of self- reflection, which has no existence in matter. In his whole doctrine, indeed, as to the relation of the ideal and the material, we find an unconscious preponderance ascribed to the ideal side. In the very definition of mind as the idea of the body, there seems to be attributed to it a power to transcend the gulf between thought and things, which is not ascribed to the latter. Matter, so to speak, becomes idealised, but mind does not become materialised. It is not by any influence or impression of the body on the mind, but by the mind's own in- herent activity, that it knows the body, or has the body for its object. " It would be absurd," says Spinoza, " to think of the idea as something dumb, like a picture in- 1 Eth. ii. 21, schol. Preponderance of Ideal Side. 203 scribed on a tablet, and not as a mode of thinking, as in- telligence itself." x " By idea," says he elsewhere, 2 " I understand a conception of the mind which it forms be- cause it is a thinking thing. I say conception rather than perception, because the word ' perception ' seems to indicate that the mind is passive to the object, but ' conception ' seems to express the activity of the mind." In being the idea of the body, mind is not passive but active, and its activity is the purely internal, self-orig- inated activity of thought. Moreover, as we have just seen, its inherent activity manifests itself in a wholly original manner, to which there is nothing corresponding in the body viz., as reflection on itself. It is not merely the idea of the body, but it makes that idea its own object ; and in so doing, as Spinoza teaches, it is its own criterion of certitude. In knowing, it knows that it knows. The truth of its knowledge is self-cer- tified. The content of every true idea carries subjective certainty with it, and the " form " or characteristic pro- perty of the idea is something that pertains to it, " in so far as it is considered as a mode of thought, mthout /'/fence to the object." 3 Finally, we shall afterwards see that Spinoza ascribes to mind not merely an activity independent of the body, but a power to control and modify the body and its affections. The mind masters the passions by the very act of thinking them, or " by forming clear and distinct ideas of them ; " 4 and when it is thus liberated from passion, it can order and con- catenate its ideas according to the order of reason. But, as ideas are ordered and connected in the mind, so are i Eth. ii. 43, schol. 2 Eth. ii., def. 3. 3 Eth. ii. 21, schoL 4 Eth. v. 3. 204 Spinoza. the affections of the body or the images of things in the body. " So long," he therefore concludes, " as we are not assailed by passions which are contrary to our nature, we possess the power of ordering and connecting the affections of the body according to the order of reason." a Notwithstanding, therefore, his denial of any causal nexus between mind and body, we find him here ascribing to mind not only a power over itself and its own internal activities, which the body does not pos- sess, but also a power, extending beyond the sphere of thought, to control and regulate the affections of the body. III. The essence of the mind, as we have seen, is in- telligence. It is idea, the idea of the body, and in being the idea of the body it is the idea of itself. 1 1 s characteristic attitude towards both the outward and the inward world is that of knoicledge. But if we go on to ask, What is the nature and value of its knowledge? Spinoza's answer is, that in the first exercise of our in- telligence, its knowledge is "inadequate" or, more definitely, it is neither a complete nor a distinct, but only a fragmentary and confused knowledge of things. Its point of view is purely individual ; it is that of a being Avho is only a part of the world, and as such ap- prehends only the part with which he stands in imme- diate connection, and even that only partially and indistinctly; and as the mind's knowledge of itself is relative to its knowledge of the body as it knows itself only in knowing, and in the measure in which it knows, outward things its self-consciousness is as inadequate as its consciousness of outward objects, i Eth. v. 10. Inadequate Knowledge. 205 The proof of the inadequacy of that knowledge which pertains to the mind as the idea of the body, is based on the proposition that the mind knows the body only by means of ideas of bodily affections i.e.. of the modifica- tions which the body experiences in its relations to out- ward objects. 1 It has been shown 2 that an indi- vidual finite thing can exist only as determined by another finite thing, and that as determined by another finite thing, &c., ad infinitum ; and as the knowledge of an effect depends on the knowledge of its cause and includes it, 3 an adequate knowledge of any indi- vidual thing would imply a knowledge of the whole endless series of causes and effects in other words, would imply a knowledge which pertains only to the infinite intellect of God. But the human mind is only a part of that infinite intellect. Its knowledge is God's knoAvledge of the body, not in so far as He is infinite, but in so far as He is regarded as affected by another idea of a particular thing actually existing, or by many such ideas. 4 In other Avords, the idea or knowledge of the body is not the idea of the body in itself, but only of the body as determined or affected by other bodies ; or the mind knows the body only by means of the ideas of the affections it experiences. No\v, if we consider what is the value of the knowledge so defined, it is obvious that it must be both partial and confused. It is partial ; it apprehends its objects not in the totality of their nature and relations. Its knowledge of the body, of outward bodies, and of itself, is a knowledge which excludes or conceals all but a fragment of what would i Eth. ii. 19. 2 Eth. i. 28. 3 Eth. i., ax. 4. 4 Eth. ii. 19, dem. 206 Spinoza. be necessary to true or perfect knowledge. Knowing its own body only as it affects and is affected by outward objects, it knows both only in one relation, the external objects only in so far as they influence the human body, but not in their innumerable other relations ; l the human body only in that relation in which it has been affected in a particular way, but not as it is capable of being affected in a multiplicity of other ways. 2 Further, the human body is a highly composite individual thing, the parts of which belong to its essence only in so far as they participate in its movements in definite reciprocal relations ; but in so far as they exist in other relations, or in action and reaction with other bodies, the knowledge of their existence and activity is not included in the idea of the body which constitutes the human mind. Thus the knowledge that comes through the affections of the body is the know- ledge of outward objects, of the body itself, and of its constituent parts, only in certain particular relations, and is therefore imperfect or partial. It is also, even so far as it goes, indistinct or confused. Each affection of which the mind is conscious is the result of two factors the action of the outward object and the susceptibility of its own body and it is incapable of determining how rrmch is merely subjective, how much due to the out- ward object. "These ideas and affections, therefore, in so far as they are related to the human mind alone, are like conclusions without premisses that is, they are con- fused ideas." 3 If the knowledge that comes to the mind through the affections of the body is thus inadequate, equally inade- 1 Etb. ii. 25. 2 Eth. ii. 27. 3 Eth. ii. 28. Inadequate Knowledge. 207 quate must be the self-consciousness that is bound up with it. The idea of the idea must partake of the im- perfection and indistinctness of its object. "As the idea of an affection of the body does not involve an adequate knowledge of the body or adequately express its nature, so the idea of that idea does not adequately express the nature of the human mind or involve an adequate knowledge of it." l The self -consciousness, in other words, which is the consciousness of inadequate ideas, must be itself an inadequate self-consciousness. But besides this imperfection and confusion which characterises our first consciousness of things, or that knowledge which is mediated by the affections of the body, there is a further defect which inevitably clings to it. !Not only at this stage are our particular percep- tions inadequate, but the same inadequacy attends our ways of connecting or combining them. A mind which knows things only through the affections of the body, or as they present themselves in individual sensible experience, can have no other notion of the relations of things than that of arbitrary or accidental association. The affections of the body, and therefore the ideas of these affections, vary in each case with the individual susceptibility. They are limited in number by the range of individual experience, and they succeed each other in no rational order, but only in the order in which the individual chances to be affected by them. "Memory," says Spinoza, "is an association of ideas which involves the nature of things outside the body, but it is an association which arises in the mind ac- cording to the order and association of the affections 1 Eth. ii. 29, dem. 208 Spinoza. of the body," in contradistinction from the order of intelligence " whereby the mind perceives things through their primary caiises, and which is the same in all men." l Thus, so long as our knowledge is derived from mere external experience, Spinoza shows (though by the help of a somewhat crude physiological explanation, on which nothing really turns) that it is possible to regard as actually present, things which are absent or even non- existent, 2 and to connect things arbitrarily "according to the manner in which the mind has been accustomed to connect and bind together the images of things." 3 Lastly, the inadequacy and arbitrariness which is the general characteristic of this kind of knowledge finds another example in the fictitious " universals," the general or abstract terms by which we attempt to give connection and unity to our particular perceptions of things. Transcendental terms, such as " being," " thing," " something " ; generic terms, such as " man," " horse," " dog," &c., so far from expressing real relations of things, only intensify the confusion of our individual perceptions. They are expressions of the mind's weak- ness, not of its strength. They arise from the fact that its capacity of forming even confused images of things is limited, so that when they exceed a certain number they run into each other, and our only resource is to group them indistinctly under some general term. In- stead, therefore, of giving unity to the differences of our primary perceptions, they only redouble the original indistinctness. And they are as arbitrary as they are confused. They do not supply any objective principle by which the differences of things are explained and 1 Eth. ii. 18, schol. 2 Ibid., 17. " Tbid., 18, schol. Is Adequate Knowledge, Possible ? 209 harmonised, but only images or subjective conceptions, varying with individual temperament, by which w<> attempt to bind together diversities too complicated for ordinary thought to embrace. " Those who have most frequently looked with admiration on the stature of men will understand by the term. ' man ' an animal of erect stature; while those who have been in the habit of fixing their thoughts on something else will form a dif- ferent general image, as of an animal capable of laughter, a biped without feathers, a rational animal, &c., each person forming general images according to the tempera- ment of his own body." ] The knowledge which is mediated by the " affections of the body " in other words, our first empirical con- sciousness of things as they are given in immediate perception is thus in many ways imperfect and unreal. The mind, regarded simply as " the idea of the body," has no adequate knowledge " either of itself or of the body, or of outward bodies." It is but an individual thing in a boundless universe, catching only indistinct glimpses of other finite things in their immediate rela- tion to its own individuality. It is but a transitory mode of thought, which knows itself only as the reflex of a transitory mode of matter ; and of all that lies be- yond itself and its immediate object it knows nothing save through the dim and broken impressions of its accidental surroxmdings. To ask whether such a being is capable of "adequate ideas" would seem to be equivalent to asking whether the particular can com- prehend the universal, or that which is merely subjec- 1 Eth. ii. 40, schol. 1. P. XII. O 210 live and contingent can find in itself the expression of that which is objective and necessary. Spinoza's answer to this question is contained in his theory of the development of knowledge. The individual point of view which constitutes the mind's first attitude towards the world, is only the beginning of knowledge. It is possible for man to rise above himself and the conditions of his finitude. The human mind has in it, by its essential nature, an element in virtue of which it can escape from the narrowness and confusion, the arbitrariness and contingency of its own subjective feelings or affections, or of that knowledge which is merely generated from them. It is possible for it, in the process of knowledge, to eliminate its own in- dividuality, and to attain to a view of things which is untroubled by the peculiarities of individual tempera- ment or the accidents of individual experience. From conceptions which represent only the relations of its own body to outward bodies it can rise to the appre- hension of the laws or principles which are common to all bodies, and which determine, not their accidental, but their necessary relation to each other. And finally, beyond even that emancipation from itself which is implied in the knowledge of things as determined by universal laws and rules (j)er It'ijc* ti /vyA/.-- lotiri-r- xule*), 1 the mind is capable of attaining that supreme elevation in which all finite things and all laws and principles of finite things are referred to the ultimate unity which is their immanent principle and origin. In the light of this highest universality, it contemplates all things as they really are, and not as they seem to In-, i Eth. iii., Praf. Hir/lier Stages of Knowledge. 211 from the point of view of the whole, and not in partial, fragmentary aspects, in their essential relations, and not in accidental combinations, under the "form of eternity," and not under the conditions of time. In a word, the human mind, when it lias realised its inherent capacity of intelligence, is no longer " the idea of the body," but the idea or intuitive apprehension of God, and of all things in God. In the ascending scale of intelligence thus generally indicated, Spinoza specifies two stages, which he des- ignates respectively " reason " (ratio) and " intuitive knowledge " (scientia intuitiva). In the earlier sketch of the theory which is given in the treatise on ' The Im- provement of the Understanding,' these two kinds or stages of knowledge are defined as that " in which the essence of a thing is inferred from another thing," and that " in which a thing is perceived solely from its own essence, or by the knowledge of its proximate cause." In the ' Ethics ' the distinction is presented in a some- what modified form. "Keason" is that knowledge which arises " from our possessing common notions and adequate ideas of the properties of things," l " ideas which are common to all men," of those "things in which all bodies agree," - " which exist equally in the human body and in external bodies, and equally in the part and in the whole of each external body." 3 " In- tuitive knowledge," again, is " that kind of knowing which proceeds from an. adequate idea of the formal essence of certain attributes of God to the adequate know- ledge of the essence of things." 4 And this last kind of J Eth. ii. 40, schol. 2. * Eth. ii. 38, cor. 3 Eth. ii. 39, clem. * Eth. ii. 40, schol. 2. 212 Spinoza. knowledge he further describes as the knowledge of " the existence of individual things in so far as they are in God ; for although," he adds, " each individual thing is determined by another individual thing to exist in a certain way, nevertheless the force by which each thing perseveres in its existence follows from the eternal necessity of the nature of God." 1 1. The kind of knowledge which is designated "rea- son," is, as we have just said, in the earlier form of the theory distinguished from the third or highest kind of knowledge simply as mediate from immediate, that which is reached by ratiocination from that which we obtain by intuitive perception. "Reason," in other words, denotes that knowledge of which the object is not apprehended directly and immediately, but only in- ferentially, by deduction according to logical principles. Of this inferential or deductive knowledge Spinoza ad- duces as examples the conclusion from effect to cause, or from any universal to " a property which always accom- panies it." In the 'Ethics' the explanation of the matter, though varied in form, is substantially the same. There are certain common notions or fundamental principles of reason which enable us to rise above the merely individual and subjective view of things, and which form the basis of a real knowledge. Behind the phenomena of sense, which vary with the individual subject, there are certain elements or laws which are common to all things and all parts of things a universal nature which each thing has in common with other things, and in virtue of which it is a member of the system or order of nature. Of these universal elements 1 Eth. ii. 45, schol. Second Stage of Knowledge. 213 the mind can form adequate ideas ; it caii apprehend them in their simplicity and purity underlying the con- fusion of the sensible world, and so perceive in that world, not the accidental play of circumstances, but a real or rational order. These adequate ideas enable us to see things in their real agreements, differences, and c] (positions. They form the basis of reason (fi ratiotue) 1 or of ratiocination (fundamcnta inasmuch as "whatever ideas in the mind follow from adequate ideas are also themselves adequate," 3 and " the things we clearly and distinctly understand are either the common properties of things, or things which are deduced from these." 4 " Reason," in short, is the mind's power to form clear and distinct ideas, and deductions from such ideas. a This kind of knowledge, he further points out, though it raises us above our first crude perceptions of things, inasmuch as it liberates us from accidental associa- tions, yet falls short of the highest knowledge, and par- takes in some measure of the defects of ordinary know- ledge. It only incompletely redeems us from that partial or abstract way of looking at things which is the radical defect of the latter. In our ordinary unscientific attitude of mind we proceed from part to part : setting out from ourselves and our immediate surroundings, we pass from object to object, regarding them as isolated, self-identical things, or only vaguely connecting them with each other by accidental associations of time and place. Reason so far corrects this abstract, disintegrated view of things, that it connects and separates them as genera and species 1 Eth. ii. 44, cor. dem. - Eth. ii. 40, schol. 1. s Eth. ii. 40. * Eth. v. 12, dem. 5 Eth. v. 10, dem. 214 Spinoza. according to their likenesses and dissimilarities, or links them together by necessary laws, such as that of cause and effect. But in so doing reason only partially over- conies the crude abstractions of ordinary thought. When, e.g., we reason from effect to cause, we still contemplate things as separate, self-identical substances connected with each other only by an external link ; and however far we carry out the series of causes and effects, we can never arrive at any real principle of unity. The utmost we get by any such method is only an endless or indefinite succession of objects externally determining and deter- mined. If the real unity of the world is to be discerned, it must be by some higher principle of knowledge some principle which will not leave the manifold objects of the finite world lying still in disintegration, or explain one finite thing by another which is still outside of it, or by an infinite which is only the endless repetition of the finite. What we want and what " reason" cannot give us, is a first or highest principle which will at once transcend and explain all differences of the finite world, which will be seen in its own light, and in the light of which the reality and unity of all finite things will be seen. 2. "As all things are in God, and are conceived through God, we can . . . form that third kind of knowledge of which I have spoken, and of the excel- lence and utility of which I shall in the fifth part (of the 'Ethics') have occasion to speak." 1 It is thus that Spinoza describes that scientia intuitiva which forms the culminating stage of human intelligence, the attitude of mind which is furthest removed from the purely in- i Eth. ii. 47, schol. Third Stage of Knowledge. 215 dividual point of view, and in which it apprehends all things in the light of that first principle in relation to which alone they truly are and can be known. " Keason," as we have seen, so far corrects the arbitrary abstractions of sense and imagination, but its point of view is still abstract. The link of necessity which con- nects things with each other is something other than and external to the things themselves. That which gives them unity is foreign to, not immanent in them. By means of such general principles as that of causality we can infer or conclude from one thing to another, but we do not see the unity that runs through them. We per- ceive the differences of things and that which unites them, but not unity in difference and difference in unity. Xow it is this highest apprehension of things which, in " intuitive knowledge," the mind attains. What Spinoza means by this phrase is a kind of knowledge in which it no longer proceeds from part to part, from dif- ference to unity, but is determined by the idea of the whole, and proceeds from the whole to the parts, from unity to difference. It is the realisation of what, else- where, he had laid down as the ideal of true knowledge viz., that the mind must grasp the idea which repre- sents the origin and sum of nature, and see in that idea the source of all other ideas." Moreover, this knowledge is not mediate, but immediate or intuitive. In it the unity is prior to diversity, and the process from unity to difference is not one which first apprehends the principle or origin of things as an independent, self-contained reality, and then advances to the manifold existences of the finite world ; but one in which, as by a single 216 Spinoza. intuitive glance of intelligence, it sees all finite things as genetically involved in their first principle. It sees the differences as the differences of unity, the unity as immanent in the differences. It sees God in all things, and all things in God. That the human mind is capable of this highest kind of knowledge Spinoza rests on the consideration that all knowledge virtxially involves the idea of God, and that we have only to evolve its content to bring our know- ledge into correlation with its first principle or immanent source. " The idea," says he, 1 of every individual thing actually existing, necessarily involves the eternal and in- finite essence of God." As all spaces must be known as in one space, or through the conception of an all-com- prehending space, so all individual ideas can be known only through the all-embracing idea of God. " Inasmuch as individual things have God for their cause, in so far as He is regarded under the attribute of which they are modes, their ideas must necessarily involve the concep- tion of the attribute of these ideas that is, the eternal and infinite essence of God." 2 The knowledge of God is implicated with our knowledge of all things, and without that knowledge we could know nothing else. It is true that in our ordinary thinking we do not clearly apprehend that which is really the fundamental element of our consciousness ; but the reason of this is, that the unreflective mind confounds thought with imagination, and conceives itself to be incapable of thinking what it cannot represent to itself by an outward picture or image. "Men have been accustomed to associate the name of God with images of things they have been in i Eth. ii. 45. a ibid., dem. Intuitive Knowledge. 217 the habit of seeing," and the absence of the image is mistaken for unconsciousness of the thing. If they " could see into their own minds, they would no longer make this mistake," any more than the man who makes an error in calculation would ascribe it to an incapacity in the human mind to apprehend the idea of number, rather than to its unconscious substitution of false num- bers for true. When we thus " see iuto our minds," or bring, by reflection, their content to clear consciousness, we discern that our ideas of all things of ourselves, of our own bodies, and of external bodies as actually exist- ing presuppose and are based on an adequate knowledge of " the eternal and infinite essence of God." x Intuitive knowledge, therefore, is that which interprets us to our- selves, and enables us to transform our consciousness of the finite by bringing it into relation with the infinite. It not only liberates us from the arbitrary abstractions of sense and imagination, but it frees us from the abstract- ness that still clings to the general notions of ratiocinative thought. When we " proceed from the absolute know- ledge of the essence of God to the adequate knowledge of the essence of things," from the idea of an absolute unity, which is immanent in all diversity, to particular things as only the expression of that unity in a certain definite manner, the dualism which is involved in the notion of causality vanishes. The higher universality dis- solves the difference still left by the lower. The view of the world, as a succession of finite things conditioned by and conditioning each other in endless series, yields to the view in which everything is seen in the light of the infinite unity which is immanent in all. " For, al- 1 Etli. ii. 47, schol. 218 though each particular thing be conditioned 1>y another particular thing to exist in a given way, yet the force by which each particular thing perseveres in existing" (/>.. its inmost essence) " follows " (not from other particular things, but) " from the eternal necessity of the nature of God." 1 The intuition of reason is possible only when diversity is seen through unity, for till then the special existence of things and their mediating link are inde- pendent. We cannot properly see the whole at o/n-r. Mediacy thus can become immediacy only at the highest point ; and this explains the difficulty that is involved in asserting at the same time an intuitive knowledge and a deduction of ideas from the highest idea. The perfect collapse into unity is possible for reason only at the highest point where it returns, so to speak, to the direct- ness of sense. Finally, we cannot speak of intuitive knowledge as a knowledge which is determined by time, but only as knowledge "under the form of eternity." Even ratiocinative knowledge, in so far as it lifts its objects out of their contingency into a system of unal- terable relations, may be said to be knowledge of things " under a certain form of eternity " (sub quadaui specie ti'fi'ritifafi*). But it is only intuitive knowledge to which, in the fullest sense of the words, this description can be applied. For here our consciousness of things is a consciousness which is no longer subjected to finite limitations, but one "which proceeds from the eternal necessity of the divine nature," or which identifies itself with the principle which transcends the sphere of time and of temporal relations. " Things are conceived by us as actual in two ways either as existing in relation 1 Etli. ii. 45, schol. Knoidcdye under the "Form of Eternity '." 219 to a given time and place, ov as contained in God and following from tlie necessity of the divine nature." l Time and number are only forms of the imagination, pertaining to the phenomenal unreal aspect -of things. It is only individual things, or things regarded as isolated individuals, that arise and pass away in their inner essence they neither begin nor cease to be. When we contemplate them from a universal point of view, we enter into a region in which duration and succession have no place, where one thing is no more prior in time to another than are the different properties of a circle or a triangle. As he who grasps the idea of a circle or tri- angle sees all its properties to be sinmltaneously present in it, so he who intuitively apprehends the nature of things sees all finite existences as eternally involved in the idea of God sees them " under the form of eternity." " Here," says Spinoza, " by existence I do not under- stand duration that is, existence abstractly conceived, and as a certain form of quantity. I speak of the very nature of existence which is ascribed to individual things because of this, that from the eternal necessity of the nature of God an infinitude of things follow in infinite ways." 2 Tt is unnecessary at present to enter into any detailed examination of Spinoza's theory of knowledge. "What we may here point out is, that the ideal at which it aims it fails to fulfil. Setting out from the purely individual point of view of the ordinary consciousness, it traces the rise of the mind through the higher but still imperfect xiniversality of reason, to that highest or absolute uni- versality which is involved in the apprehension of all 1 Eth. v. 29, schol. " Eth. ii. 45, schol. 220 Spinoza. things in their relation to the idea of God. Expressed in modern language, the gradual evolution of thought is that in which the mind, beginning with ordinary unso- phisticated experience, advances, first to the scientific attitude, and finally to that of philosophy or speculation. But whatever may be said as to the transition from the first to the second stage, the fatal defect of Spinoza's scheme of knowledge is, that the final step is, not from a lower universality to a higher, from a plurality of prin- ciples or categories to one highest principle which em- braces and explains them, but simply from the diversity of the former to a mere abstract identity which lies be- yond them. The principle the intuitive apprehension of which is to constitute the ultimate explanation of all the differences of the finite world is, when we examine what it means, nothing more than the common element which we reach when these differences are left out of sight. The implicit universality of intelligence, as we may express it, asserts itself, first, in raising us above the partial, accidental, confused aspect of things as they arc regarded from a merely individual or subjective point of view, and in apprehending them as related to each other by universal principles or laws. But the rational or scientific point of view, though it so far corrects that of ordinary experience, leaves the impulse towards univer- sality still unsatisfied. The claim of philosophy to be a higher explanation of the world than that of science is based on the fact, not only that science employs categor- ies, such as substance and qualities, cause and effect, &c., which it does not explain, but that these categories give us only ;i provisional explanation of the world conceived of as a manifold of existences outside of each other, and Defect of the TJieoi^y. 221 apart from their relation to the intelligence that knows them. They connect things indeed by real and objec- tive, instead of accidental and subjective relations, but the highest view they reach is that of an aggregate of finite substances acting and reacting externally on each other, and contemplated in abstraction from the intelli- gence for which alone they exist. What philosophy, if it is to justify its pretensions, must do, is to furnish us with a higher principle to which the categories of science may be earned back as their principle, and at the same time as the principle of the mind that apprehends them an idea, in other words, which will be the reason at once of the differences of things from each other, and of the sxipreme difference of things from the mind that knows them. Whether modern philosophy has achieved this result we need not here inquire. But this much at least is obvious, that the ultimate unity of knowing and being cannot be found in a principle which abstracts from their difference. If what we are in search of is a key to the meaning of nature and man, of mind and matter, of the manifold differences of the finite world, it is not supplied by an idea which destroys these differ- ences, or is itself destroyed when brought into contact with them. 222 CHAPTER XII. THE MORAL NATURE OF MAX. THE ethical part of Spinoza's philosophy is based on the metaphysical, and partakes of the merits and de- fects of the latter. A thorough-going pantheism knows nothing' of moral distinctions. As it admits of no quali- tative difference between finite things, so it admits of no better and worse, higher and lower, in man's nature. God is not more revealed in what Ave call the noblest than in the meanest of finite existences. Each is but a mode of the infinite, and none can be more. Nor can there be any part or element of any individual nature Avhich is more or less divine than another, or by the triumph or subjugation of which that nature can elevate itself to a higher or degenerate to a lower stage of being. In such a system the terms " good " and " evil " must be meaningless, or at most, expressions of facts of the same order with the terms heat and cold, motion and rest, or (in the case of sensitive beings) pleasure and pain. Fi- nally, as in such a system the independent existence of finite things is an illusion, and their only distinction from the infinite a distinction which vanishes with the false abstraction which gave it birth, any such notion as Sketch of the Theory. 223 that of aspiration, self-devotion, union with God any such notions as form the basis of the religious life are equally excluded with those of freedom, responsibility, duty, &c., which form the basis of the moral. But whilst, in one point of view, the metaphysic of Spinozism, as of all pantheistic systems, is subversive of what we commonly understand by " ethics," it is not the less true that the ethical in Spinoza's aim and inten- tion was the goal to which the metaphysical part of his philosophy pointed. And even in his metaphysic itself there are ideas and principles which are incongruous with its pantheistic side, and of which his elabo- rate ethical theory is the logical result. The origin and explanation of all moral activity he finds in a cer- tain self-maintaining or self-realising impulse, which is identical with the very essence of each finite individual " the effort by which it endeavours to persevere in its own being." l Feeling or emotion Ja/ectut) is the expression of this impulse, and modifications of feel- ing arise from its satisfaction or repression. When the self-maintaining impulse is satisfied, or when the mind is conscious of an increase of power, the feeling is that of pleasure or some modification of pleasure ; in the opposite case the feeling is that of pain or a modification of pain. When the individual is himself the adequate cause of such increased power, the emotion is termed an " activity " ; when the diminution or increase of power follows from something external, and of which the individual is only the partial cause, the emotion is termed a " passion," or passive state. From this ac- count of the nature and origin of human emotion we i Eth. iii. 6 and 7. 224 Spinoza. are enabled to understand the relation of the intellectual to the ethical part of Spinoza's philosophy, and the close correspondence which he traces between the successive stages of knowledge and the successive stages of man's moral life. Through all the stages of knowledge runs the self -realising impulse, taking its complexion and content from each in succession, expanding and en- larging itself with the widening sphere of intelligence, and expressing itself in emotions coloured by the intel- lectual atmosphere in which it breathes. At the lowest stage, corresponding to that of " vague experience," where intelligence is governed by accidental and sub- jective associations, the self which seeks realisation is the purely individual self, varying with individual temperament and the accidental relations of time and place. Its good and evil are nothing absolute, but only that in which a purely individual nature can ex- perience the feeling of enlargement or repression viz., pleasure and pain ; and as its whole experience, all that moves or affects it, arises not from the mind's own activity, but from that which is external or foreign to it as, in other words, it is at best only the partial cause of its own emotions, and " the force whereby it perse- veres in its being is infinitely surpassed by the power of external causes " at this stage of the moral life man is simply " a part of nature," and the general condition of human nature can only be described as that of impotence or " bondage." But whilst, regarded simply as an individual amongst other individuals, man is not, and never can be, free, human nature contains in itself the secret of its own emancipation. The bondage lies in this, that the true Sketch of tlie TJicory. 225 self is repressed by what is foreign to it. The fun- damental impulse of self-maintenance, which is our very essence, has here not free play ; it is in con- tradiction with the conditions under which it exists, and the effort to rise above these conditions is the ex- pression of our deepest nature. All the force of that nature goes with the effort to throw off the yoke of imagination and passion, and to rise to rational freedom. Corresponding, therefore, to the stage of intelligence which Spinoza designates " reason," in which the mind passes from the sphere of inadequate to that of adequate ideas, there is a stage of moral activity, in which the universal element in man's nature asserts itself, and the mind ceasing to be the slave of external and accidental impulse, its experience becomes the expression of its own self -originated energy. On the intellectual side of our nature, reason, as we have seen, is the sphere of freedom ; it liberates from the confusion and contin- gency of the senses and the imagination, and is itself the pure activity of the mind, all the operations of which can be " understood from our own nature as their adequate cause." But it is the sphere of freedom also as regards the moral life. To live according to reason is to live according to ourselves, to make our life the expression of our true nature. We cannot, indeed, cease to be creatures of sense and imagination, or, so long as the body exists, to have a consciousness which consists of ideas of bodily affections. But reason, though it cannot annul the conditions from which desires and passions arise, can, to a great extent, elevate us above their control. It can make us independent of passion ; for " to all actions to which we are determined r. xn. p by passion, where the mind is passive, we can be deter- mined by reason without passion." l And it has in it, by its very nature, a power to abate the control of passion ; for, in one sense, the activity of thought kills passion; by 1liinJchin. In other words, the impure element vanishes from self- seeking when the self we seek is that whose essence is ivason and the knowledge and love of God. Eationality i-annot be too selfish, cannot seek its own satisfaction too eagerly or crave with culpable excess for the enlargement i Eth. ii. 45, scbol. 2 th. iv. 4, dem. Reason cannot lie Selfish. 237 of its own being. All tilings that bring pleasure to it are good, all tilings that bring pain to it evil ; pleasure, that is, becomes a term of moral significance and honour when the subject of feeling is identified with reason. That reason or a purely rational nature should love others for its own sake rather than for theirs, means that we cannot truly love another if we do not " love honour more." Even to say that " man's highest utility is the knowledge of God," or that we seek to know God be- cause the knowledge of God is of all things the most useful to us, is a formula which ceases to shock pious sensibilities when translated into this equivalent, that infinite intelligence is the supreme good of finite intelli- gence, or that it is in the knowledge of God that a rational nature finds its own perfection and blessedness. Now it is the identification of the true nature of man with rea- son or the divine element in him which furnishes the key to much in Spinoza's ethical teaching that sounds harsh and repulsive. The self which is affirmed in the " self-maintaining impulse," and of which the satisfac- tion and enlargement is identified with " virtue," is not the individual self as such, not the self of appetite and passion, but rather that which is repressed and limited thereby, which finds its freedom in rising above the self- ish desires and its proper sphere in " the life according to reason." " The human mind consists of adequate and inadequate ideas." x The essence of man, in other words, is the power to think. Even in the lower stage of imagination and inadequate ideas this its true essence manifests itself in the pain of repression or limitation by what is foreign to itself. In the stage of " reason " the i Eth. iii. 9, dem. 238 Spimza. true self has shaken off the bondage of the non-rational and emerged into the sphere of pure self-activity. Here it knows nothing of pains and pleasures that refer only to the narrow individual self. Its " good " is no longer subjective or determined only by varying individual temperament, but a good that is common to all rational natures and determined by an objective standard. Finally, in the stage of "intuitive knowledge " the self has reached the point of enlargement at which all finite limits are left behind, and it sees and feels all things in the light of that which is universal and absolute. And here that impure self-reference to which the stigma of selfishness can be applied, has so completely vanished that even love ceases to seek a personal response. Though in the knowledge and love of God self -consciousness and self- affirmation still survive, yet the taint of subjectivity is so absolutely obliterated, that " he who loves God can- not seek that God should love him in return." 1 3. Lastly, it is to be considered that there is an obvious distinction between selfishness and sel f -real i Ca- tion, between unselfishness and self-extinction. Moral disinterestedness does not mean, even at the highest, the cessation of self-consciousness or self-satisfaction. Moral action implies in the agent the idea of a self which realises itself in that which is done, which seeks and finds satisfaction in the act. The " good " of a conscious agent, whether it be sensual pleasure or the purest intellectual and spiritual enjoyment, whether it be low or high, must be a good fftr liim. Xo purer philanthropy can be conceived than finding <>n<'' mm satisfaction in the welfare of others. Even in self- i Eth. v. 19. Selfishness and Self -Realisation. 239 sacrifice fur another there is present a reference to self, an idea of an object to be attained in which the agent seeks self-satisfaction. Without such reference even the purest self-denial is a conception that swims in the air. Though in unselfish acts the end sought is not one's own pleasure or gratification, yet we do find our- selves and our own satisfaction therein. Moreover, the self-affirmation, self-realisation, is increased, not dimin- ished, with the unselfishness of the act If in every benevolent feeling there must be a consciousness of self as well as of the object loved, in every benevolent act a consciousness of self as well as of the object attained, then the wider the range of benevolence, the more numerous the objects embraced in it, so much the fuller, richer, more complete becomes the self-consciousness or self-realisation of the subject. Even the knowledge and love of an infinite object is still my knowledge, my love, and the infinitude of the object implies a kindred ele- vation of the subject. Let slip the " my," and you sink into the spurious rapture of the mystic, or the self- annihilation of the pantheist. Whatever may be said of Spinoza's philosophy in general, in this part of it at least he knows nothing of such false self-abnegation ; yet as little does the doctrine of self-affirmation as the basis of morality introduce into his ethics a principle inconsistent with the purest moral disinterestedness. In other points of view, indeed, that principle is by no means unexceptionable, as will be seen when AVC ex- amine in detail the manner in which Spinoza applies it to the elaboration of his ethical system. 240 CHAPTEE XIV. INTELLIGENCE AND WILL. WE have seen that Spinoza finds the origin and ex- planation of the active or moral life in the " self-main- taining impulse/' of which pleasure and pain, desire, and the innumerable varieties of feeling which spring from these fundamental emotions, are only different expressions or modifications. We have pointed out, further, that it is this self-maintaining impulse which constitutes the link between the intellectual and the emotional and active sides of man's nature, and which explains the close correspondence that can be traced between the successive stages of knowledge and the successive stages of the moral life. There is, however, in Spinoza's account of the nature of human knowledge one doctrine to which we have not yet adverted, and which seems to imply, not simply the correspondence, but the absolute identification of the intellectual and the moral life. Knowledge and will are not elements of man's spiritual nature which, though closely related and constantly acting and react- ing on each other, are yet different in nature and func- tion. Spinoza's assertion would seem to be that, when Intelligence and Will. 241 closely examined, the active merges in the contempla- tive or theoretical life, and that feeling, passion, desire, volition, are only various phases of knowledge or intelli- gence. " There is in the mind," says he, 1 " no volition save that which an idea as idea involves." " ^Yill and understanding are one and the same. ... A particular volition and a particular idea are one and the same." 2 If we examine the reasons why men think otherwise, and ascribe to themselves a faculty of will different from and of wider range than that of understanding, we shall find that they are all alike futile* For one thing, popular thought, while it supposes intelligence to be purely passive, and ideas to be merely "images formed in us by contact with external bodies," 3 regards all beyond such images as the product of the mind's own voluntary activity ; whereas, if we reflect on the nature of knowledge, we shall see that ideas are not mere images like " dumb pictures on a tablet," but that every idea involves in it an element of activity, a prin- ciple of self-affirmation ; in other words, that intelligence contains in it that free, voluntary activity which we commonly regard as the exclusive function of will. Common thought, again, distinguishes between truths to which we necessarily assent, which carry with them the assurance of their own reality, and arbitrary or obscure conceptions with respect to which we have the power to suspend our judgment, ascribing the former to the understanding and the latter to " the will or faculty of assent, which is free and different from the under- standing." 4 Closer examination, however, teaches us 1 Eth. ii. 49. - Ibid., cor. and dem. 3 Eth. ii. 49, schoL 4 Ibid. P. XII. Q 242 Spinoza. that the real activity of the mind is common to both processes. The difference between them is simply the difference between " adequate " and " inadequate " ideas, and the suspense of judgment which is ascribed to a faculty of volition is nothing more than the conscious- ness of a confused and imperfect as distinguished from a clear and distinct idea. The conception of a winged horse implies mental activity as much as that of a horse without wings, only the latter includes the affirmation of existence or reality, which the former does not. If, again, there- be no faculty of will different from that of understanding, then it seems to the unreflecting mind that it would be justified in concluding that assent to what is false and evil is not essentially different from assent to what is true and good ; to which Spinoza's answer is, that the idea of what is false and evil is really the idea of that which has in it no positive reality, and the distinction in question is not between two equally affirmative acts, but between the affirmation of being and the affirmation of non-entity not between under- standing and will, but between a sound and a diseased or disordered understanding. Finally, to the popular objection that it is the prerogative of will to decide between conflicting motives, and that without such a faculty, where there is an equilibrium of motives (as in the famous example of " Buridan's ass "), action would be absolutely suspended, Spinoza's reply virtually is, that the supposed conflict of motives is, when we examine what we mean, only a conflict of ideas, and that ideas never really conflict save when one idea is adequate and another confused and imperfect ; that in the latter case reason is the true umpire, and that su*- Identity of the Two. 243 pense or inaction would prove, not that reason fails to decide, but that the non-deciding agent is a fool or a madman. From these and other considerations the conclusion which Spinoza reaches is, that the element of activity which is commonly regarded as peculiar to the will is one which belongs essentially to the understanding, or that " there is in the mind no volition save that which an idea as idea involves." On the other hand, if intelligence is thus held to be active, all activity, it is maintained, is intelligent, all the supposed ele- ments of man's active life seem, when closely examined, to be only modes of thought. Thought or intelligence is not one among many co-ordinate "faculties," but it is that which constitutes the very essence of the mind, and the underlying principle of all our mental experiences and activities. " Love, desire, or the affections of the mind, by whatever name they are designated," are essentially " modes of thought." l To all these modes of thought "the idea is prior in nature, and when the idea exists the other modes must exist in the same individual." 2 Spinoza would thus seem to reduce the whole content of man's spiritual life to thought or in- telligence and its modifications ; and though he treats of other elements which pertain to the active in contra- distinction from the intellectual part of man's nature of an impulse or endeavour in the mind to persist in its own being, of pleasure and pain, desire and aversion, and of particular emotions in elaborate detail to which this impulse gives birth yet when we examine the real significance of his teaching, these seemingly non-intel- i EtL ii. ax. 3. 2 Eth. ii. 11, dem. 244 Spinoza. lectual elements, it has been held, lose their indepen- dence, and resolve themselves into the one all-absorbing principle of the theoretical intelligence. As " the essence of the mind consists of adequate and inadequate ideas," l so the self-maintaining impulse is nothing more than the self-affirmation by the mind of its own power of think- ing. 2 Will itself is only another name for this impulse, " when referred solely to the mind ; " 3 desire (cupidita*} is the same intellectual impulse, "in so far as it is con- ceived as determined to any action by some affection of itself ; " 4 emotions (affectus) are " ideas of affections of the body by which its power of acting is increased or diminished," 5 or again, " emotion which is called a passion (or passivity of the mind) is a confused idea by which the mind affirms of its body, or any part of it, a power of existing greater or less than before." 6 " Pleas- ure (Icetitia) is a passion by which the mind passes to a greater, pain a passion by which it passes to a less, perfection ; " 7 pleasure and pain, in other words, of which all the other emotions are only specifications, are not a new element different from anything in our purely intellectual nature, but are simply "the transition from a less to a greater or from a greater to a less perfection." 8 The process by which moral progress is achieved is in the same way reduced to a purely intellectual activity. If there are any outward causes which help or hinder the activity of the body, and therefore the mind's power of thinking, the mind, in seeking to affirm or 1 Eth. iii. 9, dem. 2 Eth. iii. 9. 3 Eth. iii. 9, schol. 4 Eth. iii., aff. def. 1. 5 Eth. iii., def. 3. 6 Eth. iii., aff. gen. def. 7 Eth. iii. 11, dem. Eth. iii., aff. def. 2, 3. Morality identified with Intelligence. 245 realise itself, endeavours to conceive or recollect the former, and, as far as possible, to exclude and forget the latter. 1 The stages of the moral life, by which it advances to its goal, and that goal itself, seem not merely to correspond but to be identified with its intellectual progress and perfection. As the dominion of the passions is that of inadequate ideas, so emancipation from their power is simply the formation of clear and distinct ideas. 2 " The power of the mind is denned solely by knowledge, its weakness or passivity by the privation of knowledge." 3 We are in moral bondage when the content of our con- sciousness is determined by that which is external or foreign to the mind, free when it is wholly due to the mind's own activity ; but the pure inner activity of the mind is that which it possesses when it apprehends it- self, the bodily affections, and all outward things, no longer in the confused and imperfect way in which sense and imagination present them, but from a uni- versal point of view, as part of a universal order or concatenation of things, in other words, when it un- derstands or thinks them according to the order of intelligence." 4 " The effort to understand is the first and sole basis of virtue." 5 "Good" and "evil" are simply equivalent to " that which helps or hinders our power to think or understand." 6 " In life it is of supreme importance to us to perfect the understanding or reason, and in this one thing consists man's highest happiness or blessedness." " Finally, the culmination of the moral life is attained when the understanding. by i Eth. iii. 12, 13. 2 Eth. v. 3. 3 Eth. v. 20, schol. * Eth. v. 10. 5 Eth. iv. 26, dem. Eth. iv. 27. 7 Eth. iv., App. 4. 246 Spinoza. the intuition of reason, grasps all the differences of finite things in their unity, discerns all ideas in their relation to the highest idea, the idea of God. "The absolute virtue of the mind is to understand ; its highest virtue, therefore, to understand or know God." l " Blessedness is the contentment of spirit which arises from the in- tuitive knowledge of God." From what has now heen said it will be seen that Spinoza's identification of intelligence and will is a prin- ciple which runs through the whole of his ethical sys- tem, and there appears to be substantial ground for the assertion which has often been made, that the moral life resolves itself, in his hands, into a purely intellec- tual or theoretical process. If this construction of his philosophy were the whole truth, his doctrine would seem to be, not merely that ignorance is the cause and knowledge the cure of moral imperfection, but that ignorance is itself the only moral disease, and know- ledge itself the true moral health and perfection of our being. Plausible, however, as this view of Spinoza's teaching seems to be, a careful study of the ' Ethics ' will, I think, lead us to regard it as one-sided and exaggerated. It is possible to maintain the essential unity of intelligence and will without obliterating all distinction between them. Spinoza's apparent identification of the practical with the theoretical side of man's nature is not incon- sistent with the recognition of the distinctive character and functions of the former ; and when we examine his doctrine more closely, many of the criticisms to which it has been subjected are seen to be irrelevant. 1 EtL iv. '28, (!!. i. Limits of the Doctrine. 247 1. It is to be considered that objections to the doc- trine of the unity of knowledge and will, in order to be relevant, must contemplate knowledge and will as em- ployed about the same objects. Popular thought rightly distinguishes between knowledge and goodness, between intellectual and moral power. Great moral excellence is not incompatible with a feeble and uncultured intelli- gence, nor intellectual elevation with a low moral life. Spinoza does not maintain, nor could any one be so ab- surd as to maintain, that piety and virtue are inseparable from and commensurate with literary and scientific abil- ity, or that the qualities which constitute the mathema- tician, the philosopher, the artist, are necessarily and in equal measure combined with those which go to make the good citizen, the philanthropist, the saint. All that this proves, however, is only that intelligence in one province does not imply practical activity in another. To render the objection valid, what would need to be proved is, that within the same province, and when employed about the same objects, there is no necessary conjunction of knowledge and will. Now, so limited, Spinoza's doctrine, as we shall immediately see, is by no means indefensible. It may be possible to show that, within the province of the moral and spiritual, as well as within the province of what we call the secular life, knowledge and will are, if not identical, at least co- existent and commensurate that, e.g., practical good- ness or piety implies in every case a measure of spiritual insight which, though not speculative or scientific, is of the nature of knowledge, and is proportionate to the purity and elevation of the life ; and, on the other hand, that the man of science, the philosopher, the man of letters;, 248 Spinoza. exerts in every act of his intellectual life a force and energy of will commensurate with the degree of intelli- gence that is called forth. 2. But even when we thus narrow the ground to which Spinoza's doctrine applies, is there not much which seems to justify ordinary thought in denj'ing the sup- posed coincidence or even invariable conjunction of knowledge and will 1 Within the sphere of man's moral life are not knowing and willing not only distinguishable in thought, but in actual experience notoriously separ- able 1 Is it not a moral commonplace that our actions often fall short of our convictions ? There are ideas which are purely contemplative and theoretical, projects which never go beyond themselves, opinions about vir- tue and goodness, which, through indolence or irreso- lution or pravity of will, are never realised in action. Thought and will are not only not invariably coincident, but in individual actions, and even through the whole course of life, are not seldom in glaring contrast with each other. Nowhere, indeed, has this incongruity been more forcibly expressed than in Spinoza's own language : " The powerlessness of man," says he, 1 "to govern ami restrain his emotions, I call servitude. For a man who is controlled by his emotions is not his own master, but is mastered by fortune, under whose power he is often com- pelled, though he sees the better, to follow the worse." " I have shown why the true knowledge of good and evil awakens disturbances in the mind, and often yields to every kind of lust ; whence the saying of the poet, ' Video melion proboque, deteriora sequor ; ' and Ecclesiastes seems to have 1 Eth. iv., Tref. All Intelligence is Active. 249 had the same thought in his mind when he said, ' He that increaseth knowledge increaseth sorrow.' And this I say, . . . that we may determine what reason can and what it cannot do in governing the emotions." J Spinoza's doctrine of the unity of knowledge and will is, however, not really affected by this recognition of the notorious inconsistency between human thoughts and actions. What that doctrine really means is that, within the same limits, or when employed about the same ob- jects, intelligence and will are in our conscious experi- ence inseparably interwoven. Every act of intelligence is at the same time an act of will, every act of will also an act of intelligence. And his answer to the above ob- jection virtually is, that the thought or intelligence which we can conceive of as separate from or in conflict with will is not true thought, but thought falsely so called, or, in his own phraseology, thought which consists of "inadequate" i.e., "confused and imperfect ideas." All thought is essentially active, all will essentially intelligent. On the one hand, to represent thought as devoid of the element of activity or as a merely passive thing, is to reduce its content to " images or inanimate pictures formed in us by contact with external bodies." But mind does not become possessed of ideas as wax receives the impression of a seal, or blank paper the stamp of the printer's types. Every idea or process of thought is essentially an act or a series of acts of affirma- tion and negation. In the simplest perception there is something more than the passive reception of impres- sions from without. " Affections of the body " do not become the content of thought by a mere mechanical 1 Eth. iv. 17, schol. 250 Spinoza. transference. To elevate them into ideas or objects of rational thought implies a spontaneous activity of the mind, stripping them of the contingency and confusion of sense and imagination, fastening on " those properties in them which are common to all things," infusing into them its own universality. Every act of judgment or process of reasoning involves in it a reaction of the mind on the objects with which it deals, connecting them in relations other than those of immediate percep- tion, " arranging and associating them (not according to the natural but) according to the intellectual order." The idea of a triangle is, so to speak, the self-affirmation of its own content. " The idea of a triangle must in- volve that its three angles are equal to two right angles," and " this affirmation can neither be nor be conceived without the idea of a triangle." l To prove the proposition that " there is in the mind no volition save that which an idea as idea involves," Spinoza here selects his example from what ordinary thought regards as specially the province of contemplation or theoretic intelligence ; and the implied conclusion is, that if here, in what we deem its proper sphere, intelligence is shown to be essentially active, a fortiori the element of activity must pertain to it in what we account as more peculi- arly the sphere of practical activity. If inherent activ- ity is the characteristic of the idea when it is the idea of a geometrical figure, much more must it be the char- acteristic of the idea when it is that of a moral act. If it cannot be or be conceived within the domain of science save as self-realising, much less can it be or be conceived save as self-realising when it pertains to man's moral life. 1 Eth. ii. 49, dem. All Will is Intelligent. 251 On the other hand, all will or practical activity is essentially intelligent. "Will," says Spinoza, "is the endeavour to persist in one's being when that endeavour is referred solely to the mind." x "Will, in other words, presupposes thought. It is the conscious endeavour of the mind to realise itself and its own inherent power. Devoid of the element of intelligence, will ceases to be will, and becomes mere blind impulse or passion. " "We act when anything takes place in us of which we (or that intelligence which is our essence) are the adequate cause that is, when anything follows in us from our nature which that nature taken by itself makes clearly and distinctly intelligible. We are passive when anything takes place in us or follows from our nature, of which we are not the cause, save partially." 2 In modern language, will is distinguished from animal impulse by this, that in the former and not in the latter there is present the element of self-consciousness and self-deter- mination. The merely animal nature is lost in the feeling of the moment. Its experience is a succession of feelings or impulses, each of which expires with its immediate satisfaction ; it contains no constant element of self-consciousness to which the successive feelings are referred, no permanent self which realises itself in them. Its impulses and actions are not self -originated, but forced upon it from without. They are not woven into a continuous experience by reference to any universal centre of thought, and are connected together at most only by the general life-feeling that pervades them. In a rational or intelligent being, on the other hand, there is present throughout all its feelings the uniting element i Etb. iii. 9, schol. 2 Eth. iii., def. 2. 252 Spinoza. of reference to one self-conscious subject, and through all its volitions the uniting element of self-determina- tion. In willing, it knows that it wills and what it wills ; it is conscious at once of the object willed and of itself as willing it. It is conscious of a self which is distinguished from, yet realised in, all its particular volitions and actions, and in each particular case as realised in this action and not another. Thought or self-consciousness, in short, is the common element of all voluntary acts, and that which gives them their special character and complexion as the acts of a moral agent. Now, though in Spinoza's philosophy individual minds are only modes of the Divine Substance, and as such are necessarily destitute of all independence or capacity of self-determination, yet he attributes to them a self-maintaining impulse which is identical with their very essence, and to this principle he assigns all the functions of a self-conscious, self-determining individu- ality. It is in virtue of this principle that he can maintain the distinction between the blindness of the passive impulses and emotions, and the self-conscious, intelligent activity of all human volitions. From what has now been said it is clear that Spinoza's doctrine of the unity of knowledge and will is to be understood as implying, not that these elements coexist side by side or in mechanical conjunction, but that they are inseparably interwoven with each other in our con- scious experience. He does not mean that our spiritual life, or any part of it, is made up of these two elements of an element of will added to an element of thought so that what we first think, we then will ; his doctrine is that no thought would be what it is if an element Answer to Popular Objection 253 of will did not euter into it, no volition what it is if it were not essentially intelligent. "We can see, therefore, how, from Spinoza's point of view, the popular objection above noticed is to be met. If it be said that experience disproves the inseparableness of thinking and willing, that we are conscious of thoughts, opinions, convictions which are never realised in action, of actions which con- flict with our ideas and convictions the answer is, that in all such cases there is no real separation of knowledge from will, for the knowledge which is divorced from will is not true knowledge, the will that is divorced from knowledge not really will Knowledge that is inert or inactive is not real knowledge ; it does not consist of "adequate," but only of "confused and imperfect ideas." "When we see the right without willing it, our seeing is not the same seeing with that of the mind which both sees and wills. 1 We sometimes express this to ourselves by saying that there are things we cannot know unless we love them ; that there is no real percep- tion of beauty or goodness into which the element of feeling of love, admiration, self-devotion does not enter ; that it is only the pure in heart who can see God. The object that is before the mind which only inertly contemplates a moral and spiritual act, is some- thing essentially different from the object that is before the mind in which contemplation immediately and necessarily passes into action. In the former case, the mind is looking at an object as outside of and foreign to itself, the form of which may engage the powers of observation, comparison, reflection, or which it may classify under some general head or category, such as 1 Cf. Green's Prolegomena to Ethics, p. 152 ff. 254 Spinoza. " good," or " just," or " pious " ; in the latter, at an object which is regarded not merely as good, but as my good, that in which I discern the fulfilment and realisation of my own inmost nature. When this discernment is present, when the object of thought is apprehended as not for- eign or external, but one in which I find myself, with Avhich I identify myself, which is the medium of my own self-realisation there is no possible separation be- tween the act of knowing and the act of willing. The object known is known as that the affirmation of which is indissolubly bound up with my self-affirmation. I cannot know it without willing it, for not to will it, or to deny it, would be equivalent to self-negation. I cannot will it without knowing it, for to will it is to become conscious of myself as realised in it. Lastly, it is to be observed that Spinoza's doctrine of the unity of thought and will does not imply the denial of all distinction between the contemplative and the active life. Thought and will are present in all our mental employments alike, whether they be those which have for their end simply the acquisition of know- ledge, or those which have for their end the perform- ance of some outward act. It does not follow, how- ever, that the relation of these two factors is precisely the same in both cases, or that we cannot distinguish between thought and will as they are manifested in the theoretic, and thought and will as they are mani- fested in the practical life between, e.g., the attitude of the mind in the solution of a mathematical problem and the attitude of the mind in the performance of a moral act. Spinoza's philosophy is couched in too abstract a form to admit of any speculative treatment of the dis- Tlic Tlworctic and the Active Life. 255 tinetion between the theoretic or scientific and the active life, yet in the ethical part of his system the distinction, though not formally, is virtually recognised. As modern thought represents it, the theoretic and the practical life are only different sides or aspects of the same pro- cess. In both there is a reconciliation between the ideal and the actual, between consciousness and its object, between thought and things. But the difference lies in this, that in the one case we begin with the actual, the objective, the particular, and end with the ideal, the subjective, the universal ; in the other the process is reversed. In both, the same elements are present a universal, undetermined yet determining element, and a particular or determined element and in both there is an effort to overcome the opposition between them. But in the theoretic life, or that of knowledge in the limited sense, the universal element is present at first only im- plicitly or potentially. In the endeavour to overcome the opposition between itself and the world, thought takes up at first a purely objective attitude. The mani- fold objects Avith which it deals present themselves as something external or foreign to the conscious subject. But the latent presupposition under which it acts is that the objects it contemplates are not really foreign to it- self, that the principle which constitutes its own essence is that which also constitutes the essence of things with- out, and that it is possible for reason or intelligence to find itself at home in the world. The whole process of knowledge, therefore, is a bringing back of the world into thought. Underlying the particularity, the diver- sity, the contingency of the phenomenal world, con- sciousness silently discerns the presence of that unity, 256 Spinoza. universality, and necessity which are its own essential characteristics. And every step in this process is a step towards the complete transformation of the particu- lar into the universal, the actual into the ideal, the manifold and accidental objects of thought into the unity and necessity of self-consciousness. In the prac- tical life, on the other hand, the reconciliation between consciousness and the objective world begins from the opposite pole. That life may be described as the con- tinuous effort of the self-conscious subject to realise itself in the outward world. It starts where the theo- retical life ends. To that which is already a realised content of thought it seeks to give further realisation in some outward act. Whether it be an aesthetic or moral or religious ideal, the mind is conscious of a conception which involves in it the possibility, the desire, and the effort for its embodiment in some particular concrete form and under the conditions of the phenomenal world. The vision of beauty which exists in the crea- tive imagination of the artist, he seeks to infuse into the rudeness and unconsciousness of matter and material forms and colours. To the conception of righteous- ness, goodness, holiness, which dwells in the mind of the good or pious man, he seeks to give outward actuality or realisation, and so to make the mere physical relations of things and the functions of the animal life instinct with the life of spirit to make the outward world the expression of the inner world of thought. Thus, in both the theoretical and the prac- tical life, it is the same general result which is accom- plished viz., the reconciliation between the actual and ideal ; and in both cases alike the process is permeated Their Distinction and Unity. 257 by the presence and activity of the inseparable elements of thought and will Yet this nnity of the two is still consistent with their distinction as different aspects of the same process, inasmuch as the reconciliation is that wliich proceeds, on the one hand, from the object to the subject, from the particular to the universal; on the other, from the subject to the object, from the univer- sal to the particular. In Spinoza's philosophy there is not to be found any formal analysis of the process into its opposite yet related movements ; yet we should err in concluding that he ignores the distinction between them, or that his principle of the unity of thought and will implies the resolution of the moral life into a purely theoretical process. His account of the emotions and passions, his theory of the bondage of the human mind and of its freedom, and of the method by which that freedom is achieved the whole specially ethical part of his system, in short, constitutes an elaborate exposition of the active as distinguished from the purely intellectual life. And if, as we have seen, there is much in his treatment of ethical problems which seems to imply the identification of virtue with knowledge, of moral evil with ignorance, the true explanation is, that while he describes the moral life in terms of knowledge, knowledge with him is that highest kind of knowledge above referred to, which includes or " connotes " will, or which is instinct with the element of activity. All other knowledge is not really knowledge, but only "con- fused and imperfect ideas." Such ideas may be, nay, must be, inert. They not merely do not lead to moral action, but the mind that is the subject of them is the passive slave of its own " bodily affections," and the ex- p. xii. R 258 Spinoza. ternal influences with which these affections are impli- cated. But "adequate ideas" are not doad or passive but living things. They are self-realising. To think them is to live them, to be quick with spiritual activity, to be master of one's self and the world. So far from man's moral life being reduced to a merely contemplative process, a thing of ideas without volitions, Spinoza's view is that no such ideas exist, or if they can be said to exist, that they belong not to the realm of true know- ledge, but to that of illusion and ignorance. An idea which is " adequate," or which alone deserves the name, is one which by its very essence asserts itself against all that is foreign and hostile to the mind ; it cannot coexist with confusion and error and the passions that are bred of them, any more than light can coexist with darkness. When the mind, or the self-maintaining im- pulse which is one with its essence, identifies itself with such an idea, it is ipso facto possessed of moral vitality and power. And when it rises to the highest kind of knowledge, the intuitive apprehension of that idea which comprehends and transcends all other ideas in other words, when the self -affirming impulse realises its true significance as not the affirmation of the individual self, but the self-affirmation of God in us then does it attain to the perfection of virtue and power. 1 The goal of the intellectual life is thus, at one and the same time, the culmination of the moral life, and the best expression for both is that " intellectual love " which consists in the consciousness of the mind's own perfect activity "combined with the idea of God as its cause." 1 Etli. v. -27. 259 CHAPTEE XV. THE BONDAGE AND FREEDOM OF MAX. IN the latter portion of his work Spinoza, as we have seen, contemplates the course of man's moral life as a movement from bondage to freedom, from the stage of passivity in which he is not, to that of activity or the " life according to reason," in which he is " the adequate cause of his own actions." Regarded as an individual mode amidst the infinite series of finite modes, he is only " a part of nature," a link in the endless concate- nation of causes and effects ; his self-activity is infinitely surpassed by the power of external causes, and the free- dom he ascribes to himself is only an illusory freedom, due to the fact that he is conscious of his own thoughts and actions, but not of the causes that determine them. Yet though thus, by the very essence of his finite nature, man is under a law of external necessity, the possibility of freedom is not thereby precluded. It is possible for him to elevate himself, through reason, above all encroachment of outward influences on his own self- determination. Accordingly, the last Book of the ' Ethics ' is devoted to the development of the idea of freedom, or of that state of moral perfection in which 260 Spinoza. man has become at once the source of his own spiritual life and sharer in. the life of God. The difficulty which meets us in this part of Spinoza's speculations is not simply that of his apparent reasser- tion of a doctrine he had formerly denied. For neces- sity and freedom are not predicated of the same subject at one and the same time, but are viewed as different stages in man's moral life. But though a transition from the bondage of natural necessity to spiritual free- dom is not inconceivable, the question arises whether it is conceivable under the conditions here laid down, or in the manner here described. If we start from the idea of man as but a unit amidst the infinite multiplicity of other finite units, a single force encompassed and deter- mined by the endless series of natural forces, is not freedom excluded by the very conditions of the problem 1 To make freedom a possible achievement, there must be at least some fulcrum on which it can be made to rest, some qualitative distinction between the one force which is destined to triumph and the many forces which are to be overcome. If each finite mode, each member of the series of causes and effects, has precisely the same value as another, is not the possibility of freedom simply in the ratio of one to infinity 1 If individuality be only the " force by which each individual persists in his own existence," and that is infinitely surpassed by the multiplicity of similar external forces, is not individual freedom reduced to a numerical contradiction 1 Must not man be something more than " a part of nature " to begin with, in order to the possibility of escape from its bondage 1 But even if we concede the possibility of freedom. Conditions of the Problem. 261 can the transition be accomplished in the way in which Spinoza describes it ? The problem is that which arises from the conflict between the positive or self-asserting and the negative or passive elements of man's nature ; and Spinoza's manner of solving it is, as we shall see, simply by the elimination of the latter. The negative element disappears, leaving only the purely affirmative to hold the field. But as in the idea of God, so in that of man, pure affirmation, apart from negation, is an impossible conception. In the struggle with passion, according to Spinoza, reason prevails, but it prevails, not by overcoming and subordinating passion, but simply by abstracting from or excluding it. Yet if it is not shown that in some way the natural desires and passions can be rationalised, they are simply left behind as an unresolved element. As organic life does not maintain itself by the exclusion, but by the transformation, of mechanical and chemical elements, so the ideal of the rational life is that not of a passionless life, but of a life in which passion is transcended and transformed. In one sense man can never cease to be "a part of nature," but in the higher life nature has itself become a part of reason. The force of these and other criticisms of the con- cluding part of the ' Ethics ' will be seen by considering a little more in detail (1) Spinoza's conception of human bondage, and (2) his theory of the transition from bond- age to freedom. THE BONDAGE OF MAN. AVhon we examine what Spinoza means by " the bondage of man," we find that it ultimately resolves 262 Spinoza. itself into that conditioned or determined nature which pertains to all individual finite things. Freedom is self-activity or self-determination, bondage is subjection to external causation. We act or are active " when anything takes place in us of which we are the adequate cause, or which can be deduced solely from the laws of our own nature " "we are passive, therefore, in so far as we are a part of nature a part, that is, which cannot be conceived by itself and without the other parts." 1 But as "no individual finite thing can exist or be deter- mined to act unless it be determined to exist and act by another which is also finite and has a determined exist ence, as that also by a third, &c.," 2 it follows that " it is impossible that man should not be a part of nature or should be capable of undergoing only changes which can be understood through his own nature, and of which it is the adequate cause." 3 It is true, as we have seen, that Spinoza introduces into his account of the individual nature an element which seems to modify the law of absolute external causation, a self-maintaining impulse or capacity to re- act on outward influences, and to " persevere in its own being." But inasmuch as this element of apparent independence belongs to all finite things alike, it does not in the least modify the preponderance of the whole or of the infinite multiplicity of external causes over each individual thing, or affect man's bondage as a part of nature. " The force by which a man persists in existing is limited and infinitely surpassed by the power of external causes." 4 Moreover, Avhen we con- sider the special case of man as an intelligent and moral i Eth. iv. 2, deni. 2 Eth. i. 28. 3 Eth. iv. 4. 4 Eth. iv. 2. The Bondage of Man. 263 being, this all-dominating power of nature over the in- dividual loses nothing of its force. The medium by which nature exerts its power over him is the influence of the passions ; the struggle of the individual with the determining power of external causes becomes, in the case of man, the struggle of the mind or the idea of the body with the passive emotions. But the passive emotions are simply various modifications of the feelings of pleasure and pain, which reflect the affections of the body, or necessarily arise when the body is affected by external causes ; and the mind in the unequal struggle has no more power to resist the emotions than the body, as an individual mode of extension, to resist its affec- tions by external nature. " By pleasure," says Spinoza, " I mean a passim state by which the mind passes to a greater, by pain a pa^dve state by which it passes to a lesser, perfection." " Emotion, which is called a pas- sivity of the soul, is a confused idea by which the mind affirms of its body a force of existence greater or less than before, and by which it is determined to think one thing rather than another." l Thus the whole content of the mind's experience, all that moves or affects it, is due, not to its own activity, but to something that is external and foreign to it. If, under the sway of pas- sion, it has sometimes a feeling of increased as well as of diminished power, the former, alike with the latter, as being determined from without, is only the witness to its bondage. The strength of passion is only a spurious strength, an activity that is produced by passivity, and which, like the increased power produced by wine, is in reality a sign of weakness. Spinoza's conclusion there- 1 Eth. iii., general def. of Emotion. 264 Spinoza. fore is, that neither in mind nor body, neither as a mode of thought nor as a mode of extension, can the individual man be the free cause of his own ac- tions, that " in the mind there is no free will," l and that if men think themselves free, it is only because " they are conscious of their volitions and desires, and never dream of the causes which have disposed them so to will and desire." 2 " It is impossible," says he, " that man should not be a part of nature ; . . . hence it follows that he is necessarily always in subjection to passions, that he follows and obeys the general order of nature, and that he accommodates himself thereto as the nature of things requires." 3 "I have explained," he writes, at the conclusion of his account of the emotions, " the principal emotions and changes of mind which arise from the combination of the three primary emo- tions, desire, pleasure, and pain. It is evident from this that we are in many ways driven about by external causes, and like the waves of the sea driven by contend- ing winds, we are swayed hither and thither, uncon- scious of the issue and of our destiny." 4 Such, then, is Spinoza's account of the state of bond- age from which man's moral history starts. That it is not a complete or exhaustive account of human nature, but only of its first or lowest stage, he himself expressly tells us. It is only the diagnosis of the disease which is necessary in order to the understanding of the cure. " It is necessary to know the infirmity of our nature "- its impotence, that is, under the sway of the passions " before we can determine what reason can do to liberate i Eth. ii. 48. - Kt.li. i., App. 3 Eth. iv. -i and cor. 4 Ktli. iii. 59, scliol. Is such Bondage possible ? 265 us from their control." l But before passing to what he has to say of " the course that is prescribed to us by reason," \ve may pause for a moment to consider whether his description of what lie calls " the impotence of hu- man nature " is self-consistent, and whether that impo- tence has not been so defined as to place it beyond the reach of remedy. In other words, we may inquire, in the first place, whether the conception of a conscious being under a law of causation in the same sense as a modification of matter, is a possible conception ; and secondly, whether, if conceivable, it can be made a basis for anything higher. Is such a state of bondage pos- sible for a conscious subject ] If possible, can he ever emerge from it 1 1. The bondage of man, as we have seen, is or arises from that conditioned or determined nature which per- tains to all individual finite things. It is common to body and mind to man as a mode of extension, and to man as a mode of thought. In both points of view he is determined by what is external to his own being ; the mind is a link in the series of ideas in the same sense in which the body is a link in the series of material causes and effects. The former is no more the author of its own desires and volitions than the latter of its own affections of motion and rest. Both are under a law of external, mechanical causation. Mind is simply "a spiritual automaton." The order and connection of thoughts is the same as the order and connection of things. But unless the two processes are absolutely identical in which case the distinction between thought and extension would be a distinction without a difference 1 Eth. iv. 17, schol. 266 Spinoza. can we attach any meaning to the conception of an idea externally operated on by another idea, or of a mind externally acted on by its passions, as one material thing or body by another] Ideas, Spinoza himself tells us, "are not mere images formed in us by contact with ex- ternal bodies like lifeless pictures on a panel." "We can think one body or mode of extension as lying outside of and acting on another ; but can we conceive of the pro- cess as exactly reflected or paralleled in the relation of the idea of one body to that of another 1 We can, of course, think or have an idea of mechanical causation, but the idea of a mechanical effect is not mechanically determined by the idea of a mechanical cause. A passion is " a confused idea, by the presence of which the mind is determined to think one thing rather than another." A passion, that is to say, is " present to the mind," and then, by its operation on the mind, thoughts and desires spring up therein. But a passion, a feeling of pleasure or pain, cannot be first present to the mind in the sense of being externally in contact with it, and then begin to operate upon it. Being present to the mind means that the mind is conscious of it, that it is already, in a sense, in the mind, and therefore the subsequent mental changes thoughts, desires, volitions are not the result of a merely external causation. The change in the mind is not determined by the passion, as one physical event is determined by an antecedent event, but the mind is determined by a condition of which it is itself the source. The earliest or lowest stage at which we can date the beginning of man's mental history is one in which he is not " a part of nature," in the sense of being subjected to appetites, impulses, passions which are out- Motives not External Causes. 267 side of the nature that is to be determined by them. It may, indeed, be possible to conceive of a lower stage than this of sensitive creatures that are under the control of blind impulse, and therefore absolutely determined from without. But if the lower animals be such creatures, self-conscious beings from the very outset of their con- scious life belong to a different order. If there is a stage at which man can be regarded as a being of merely animal impulses and passions, so long as it lasts his moral history has not begun. A conscious impulse is not the same as a merely natural or animal impulse. The infusion of the element of consciousness changes its nature. In becoming a motive of human action, an appetite or passion undergoes a radical transforma- tion. It is no longer an external motor acting on the mind ; it has already been taken out of the sphere of externality, and in its character of motor become a thing, in a sense, of the mind's own creation. In so far, therefore, as the passions are natural forces, and man can be regarded as a part of nature under the bondage of external causation, he is not yet a think- ing, conscious being ; and the moment you conceive of him as such, it ceases to be possible for you to account for his actions by a law of external causation an element of self-determination enters into all that determines him. Unmotived volition and action is indeed an absurd and impossible notion, but equally absurd is that of a conscious being impelled by purely external causes. " Human bondage," therefore, in Spinoza's sense of the words, is not thinkable, and could only be made to seem thinkable by a false separation between motives and volition IT- 268 Spinoza. tween passions acting on the mind, and the mind on which they act. 2. It may be urged as a further objection to Spinoza's doctrine, that if man were under such a bondage he could never escape from it Spinoza proceeds to show how reason liberates man from the slavery of passion and elevates him into participation in the freedom and bless- edness of God. But his conception of human freedom, however true in itself, is not legitimately reached. His " free man " is not the man with whom he started, and it is only by an unconscious modification of his original conception that he contrives to rear upon it his doctrine of freedom. To make freedom a possible attainment, there must be some germ of it to begin with. Imagination may picture to itself the transformation of a stone or plant or animal into a rational nature, but for thought there can be no such transformation. The stone or organism does not become a man, but the idea of the former is dropped and that of the latter substituted for it. In the same way Spinoza's bondsman may be represented as becoming a free man ; but from his definition of the former the transformation is for imagination only, not for thought. If the agencies that constitute nature or the system of being lie outside of the individual mind, and dominate it from without, they can never cease to do so. Mind can only become free in the presence of what is external to it, by supposing it from the outset capable of finding itself therein that is, by supposing in it that which has virtually annulled the externality. Limiting conditions can never cease to limit a nature that is not from the first potentially beyond the limits. A slave could never become a free citizen of the State unless lie Transition to Freedom. 269 were capable of finding himself in the constitution and laws of the State. If animal passions rule man from without, an animal he must remain. Reason indeed may, as Spinoza shows, attain the supremacy in man's life ; but it is only because man is from the beginning something different from the being of whom Spinoza speaks, for only that being which, in some sense, creates the forces that act on it, can have in it the latent capa- city to control them. It is, in short, the presence in mind of something which is not subject to the bondage of externality, that constitutes the fulcrum by which its freedom can be achieved. TRANSITION FROM BONDAGE TO FREEDOM. Spinoza's conception of human bondage is, as we have seen, self-contradictory. A being who is subject to a law of purely external causation is incapable of freedom, and therefore incapable of bondage. To be a part of nature would be no bondage to man if he could be a part of it. The A'ery term " bondage " implies that essentially ami from the first he is something more. One mode of matter is not in bondage to another, a physical effect is not in bondage to its cause; to be so related is simply the expression of its very nature. Subjection to tin-. passions would be no slavery ; the vicious man would be as innocent as an animal, if like the animal he were blind- ly determined by his appetites. Spinoza's "bondage," as interpreted by the proof he gives of it, is simply modality or h'nitude, and it applies to man as a mode of - thought precisely as it applies to him as a mode of ex- tension. It implies no more reaction in the individual mind than in a stone, against the determining power <>f 270 Spinoza. the infinite series of external causes. But, in order to lend to "bondage" the deeper signification which the term implies, and to make it the basis of a theory of freedom, Spinoza unconsciously shifts the definition of the subject of bondage. What he wants in mind is a self which can be the source of its own activity, and which, in so far as it is not so, is in bondage. Man must be something more than an individual in a world of individuals, a larger universal nature must be ascribed to him, if the limits of individuality are to be dealt with as hindrances to freedom. A life controlled by passion can be stamped as " impotence," only if reason be assumed to be the essence, and a rational life the proper destiny of the being so controlled. To make this assump- tion possible, Spinoza changes and deepens the signifi- cance of that which constitutes the essence of mind. The self-maintaining impulse in mind, which is identical with its essence, in order to be " infinitely surpassed " by that of all other finite natures, is at first nothing more and deeper in the former than in the latter. As en- dowed with it, the individual mind is, at most, only quantitatively distinguished from the infinite multipli- city of other individuals, one force amidst the infinitude of forces, to which it necessarily succumbs. But to make it at once capable of the bondage of nature and of rising above it, it has to be invested with the functions and to play the part of a self-conscious, self-determining subject. Its essence is understanding or reason, its essential function is knowledge or the capacity of adequate ideas that knowledge Avhich, as we have seen, is not inert or merely theoretical knowledge, but know- lodge which is instinct with the activity of will ; and The Subject of Bondage. 271 the goal of which is " the consciousness of the mind's own perfect activity combined with the idea of God." "The effort of self-maintenance," Spinoza writes, 1 "is nothing but the essence of a thing itself, ... its power of doing those things which follow necessarily from its nature. But the essence of reason is nothing but our mind in so far as it clearly and distinctly understands. . . . The effort of the mind by which it endeavours to persevere in its own being is nothing else than understanding, and this effort at under- standing is the first and sole basis of virtue," the source, that is, of its moral and spiritual life. " The essence of the mind consists in knowledge, which involves the knowledge of God, and without it, it can neither be nor be conceived." 2 " Man acts absolutely according to the laws of his own nature when he lives under the guidance of reason." 3 " To act rationally is nothing else than to do those things which follow from the necessity of our own nature considered in itself alone." 4 "We know assuredly nothing to be good save what helps, nothing to be evil save what hinders, under- standing." 5 By this tacit modification of the definition of mind, Spinoza, as we have said, infuses into it that element of self-determination which makes it a possible subject of bondage and of a process of emancipation from bondage. (1.) As to the former: human bondage, instead of being merely another name for finitude, or the deter- mination of a single mode by the infinite series of ex- ternal modes, becomes now the subjection of reason or of a being essentially rational to the irrational. It is no longer simply the relation of one "part of nature" to 1 Eth. iv. 26, dem. 2 Ibid., 37, dem. 3 Eth. iv. 35, cor. 1. 4 Eth. iv. 59, dem. * Eth. iv. -J7. 272 Spinoza. the whole, but it is the subjection of the spiritual to the natural. Eeason or intelligence is essentially active, a rational nature has in it the spring of perpetual activity. It is of its very essence to realise itself, to be the ade- quate cause of its own thoughts and volitions, to make its whole experience the expression of its own essence ; and as pain and all painful emotions are the indications of restrained or diminished power, it is the characteristic of a rational nature to be a stranger to pain, to revel, so to speak, in the unbroken consciousness of its own energy. But, through the medium of the passions, a foreign element gains access to the mind, ideas intrude upon it which are no longer its own creation, but which reflect the involuntary affections of the body by the external world. A host of desires and emotions arise in it of which it is not itself the source ; the presence of pain, and of emotions coloured by pain, betrays its repressed activity ; and even its pleasurable or joyous emotions, and the sense of power that accompanies them, are not of legitimate origin, biit, being due to external stimulus, are the sign of the mind's weakness, not of its strength. Again, it is of the very essence of a rational nature, not only to determine itself, but to determine itself by uniform and invariable principles of action. " Whatever the mind conceives under the guidance of reason, it conceives under the same form of eternity or necessity, and it is affected by it with the same certi- tude" 1 i.e., independently of all variable conditions or of the accidents of time and place. The good which is its satisfaction is an absolute good, a good which cannot be diminished by distance or lapse of time, and which i Eth. iv. 62, deni. Reason and the Passions. 273 is the same for all minds. But it is of the very nature of the passions to introduce into the mind an element of fitfulness and caprice, and to determine our actions by a good which is contingent and fluctuating. Pleasure and pain, reflecting as they do the affections of the body, vary with individual temperament, with the accidental and ever-changing relations of the individual to outward things, with the nearness or distance in time and space of the objects that affect us. Hence the inroad on the mind of a whole brood of emotions of desire and aver- sion, hope and fear, pride and humility, timidity and daring, exultation and remorse, &c. which disturb its equanimity, and render it the slave of accident and irra- tionality. Hence, too, the tyranny of warring passions, and the disturbance of that harmony and repose which constitute the atmosphere of reason. For Avhilst the objects of reason are the same for all minds, and they who seek them seek a good which is common to all, which can never be diminished by the multiplicity of participants, and which each individual must desire that others should seek ; l on the other hand, pleasure and pain, from which the passions spring, are in their nature purely individual. Not only do their objects affect dif- ferent men in an infinite variety of ways, so that what one desires and loves, another may hate and shun, but their appropriation by one implies the loss of them to all besides. Envy, jealousy, anger, hatred, all the malign passions, beset those who make 'pleasure their good. In these and other ways Spinoza shows that the passions, as the word indicates, imply the passivity or bondage of man's true nature. The essence of the mind is reason, i Eth. iv. 18, 36, 37. P. XII. S 274 Spinoza. the autonomy of reason its freedom ; but in so far as the mind is under the control of passion, our actions " no longer follow from the laws of our own nature, but are determined by what is alien to it." To let passion rule is a kind of suicide, for a suicide is one " who is over- come by external causes, and those which are contrary to his own nature." l On the other hand, "man is free in so far as he is led by reason, for then only is he determined to act by causes which can be adequately understood by his own nature alone." 2 " We see thus the difference between a man who is led solely by emo- tion or opinion and a man who is led by reason. The former, whether he will or no, does those things of Avhich he is utterly ignorant; the latter does those things only which he knows to be of the highest importance in life, and which therefore he desires above all. There- fore I call the former a slave, the latter a free man." a (2.) The conception of human bondage Avhich Spino/.a has now reached supplies him with a basis for his doc- trine of freedom, and indicates the process by which the transition from bondage to freedom is mediated. So long as bondage is identical with determination or finitude, freedom is impossible, or possible only by the annulling of the very existence of the being to whom it pertains. But if the freedom of man be conceived, not :is indetermination but as determination by the laws of his own nature, the possibility thereof resolves itself into the question whether that nature can rise above the external influences which dominate it. As the lowest stage of knowledge is that of imagination or inadequate ideas, so the lowest stage of the moral life is that nf i Eth. iv. 20, schol. -' Tract, Pol., cap. ii. 11. Eth. iv. 66, srhnl. How Freedom is to be Attained. 275 bondage to the passions, which are, if not simply an- other form of inadequate ideas, necessarily generated by them. Can we rise from this state ; and if so, how 1 Is freedom possible ; and if possible, what is the process by which it is achieved 1 As to the first of these questions, it may be said that the answer is involved in the doctrine that the activity of reason is essentially pleasurable, and that pain belongs only to the passions. The pain of bondage is the pro- phecy of freedom. Pain, in other words, is the con- sciousness of limitation or repressed activity, and the mind that is conscious of its limits is already virtually beyond them. If man could be perfectly happy under the dominion of passion, his moral condition would be hopeless. The fact that in the lowest stage of selfish indulgence there is an element of unrest is the witness to the presence in man of a nature greater than his pas- sions, and capable of rising above them. But granting the possibility of freedom, how is it to be attained? In the conflict of passion what are the weapons at the command of reason 1 In answer to this question, Spinoza enumerates what he terms " the remedies of the emotions, or what the mind, considered in itself alone, can do against them." l The more im- portant of these " remedies " we shall briefly consider. 1. "The mind's power over the emotions consists, first, in the actual knowledge of the emotions." The knowledge of passion destroys passion. " An emotion which is a passion ceases to be a passion as soon as we form a clear and distinct idea of it." 2 Spinoza's proof of this proposition is in substance this that a passion i Eth. v. 20, schol. 2 Eth. v. 3. 276 Spinoza. is, or rests on, " a confused idea," and that forming a clear and distinct idea of it is equivalent to the vanish- ing of the confusion. Error is extinguished, and its power over the mind ceases when we know it as error. Moreover, a passion is a confused idea " of an affection of the body" But there is no affection of the body of which we cannot form a clear and distinct idea. We can rise above the confusion of ordinary knowledge to the clear intelligence of reason. When, therefore, we think a passion, what remains of it is not the passion itself, but the true idea of it, or that is involved in it. It is thus transferred from the sphere of our passivity to that of our activity. Eeason not only masters passion, but receives a fresh accession of power ; it not only de- tects the illusion, but becomes possessed of the truth that underlies it, so that what we sought blindly from passion AVC now seek intelligently or from rational motives. Stripped of its technical form, the drift of Spino/a's argument seems to be this : When it is asserted that by the knowledge of our passions we gain the mastery over them, or " that every one has the power clearly and distinctly to understand himself and his emotions, and therefore, if not absolutely, yet in part, of bringing it about that he should not be subject to them," l it is obviously not meant that to have a theoretical know- ledge of passion is to be exempt from its control, which would be as absurd as to say that the diagnosis of a disease is equivalent to its cure. Xor, again, is Spinoza's doctrine simply the commonplace maxim, that as an enemy we know is comparatively harmless, so by study - 1 Eth. v. 4, schol. Thought transforms Passion. 277 ing our passions we learn how to be on our guard against them. But what he means is, that when we gain the point of view of true knowledge, passion loses its hold over us. As, in the intellectual sphere, the aspect of the world as it is for imagination, in which all things are regarded from a purely individual standpoint, is of necessity annulled when we rise to the higher stand- point of reason, in which all things are discerned in their universal and necessary relations, so, in the ethical sphere, the attitude of purely individual feeling, in which things are good or evil only as they contribute to the satisfaction of our appetites and passions, vanishes away when we rise to that higher attitude in which we identify ourselves with the universal interests, and look on our particular pleasures and pains in the light of that universal order of which we are but an insignificant part. So viewed, our particular satisfactions lose their deceptive importance. They become no more to us, or to reason in us, than those of other individuals, and infinitely less than the interests of that universe of being to which we and they belong. Thus, regarded from the point of view of reason, the passions cease to exist for us except in so far as they are functions of the universal, or forms under which reason itself is realised. These considerations explain to us also the sequel of Spinoza's argument, in which he maintains that in thus knowing our passions we transform them into elements of the mind's activity. "To all actions," he writes, " to which we are determined by passion, we can be deter- mined without passion by reason." 1 "Every desire," it 1 Eth. iv. 59. L>7S Spiiwza. is added, " which springs from an emotion wherein the mind is passive, would become useless if men were guided by reason." l And again : " All appetites or desires are passions only in so far as they spring from, inadequate ideas, and the same results are ranked as virtues when they are aroused or generated by adequate ideas. For all desires by which we are determined to any action may arise as well from adequate as from inadequate ideas." 2 There is, in other words, a rational meaning or end underlying the passions, and what we seek blindly under the influence of passion we may seek deliberately under the guidance of reason. When we know or form an adequate idea of a passion, we discern this under- lying end, and make it an object of conscious deliberate pursuit. "We must endeavour to acquire as far as possible a clear and distinct idea of every emotion, in order that the mind may be thus, through emotion, determined to think of those things which it clearly and distinctly perceives and in which it fully acquiesces, and thus that the emotion itself may be separated from the thought of an external cause and connected with true thoughts ; whence it will come to pass, not only that love, hatred, etc., will be destroyed, but also that appetites and desires which usually arise from such emotions will become incapable of excess." 3 Even the lowest appetites are capable of being thus transferred from the sphere of passion to that of reason, from the passive to the active side of our nature. The wise or free man is no longer impelled by hunger or lust, but by the rational endeavour after that to which these appetites point the preservation and continuance of 1 Eth. iv. 59, schol. - Eth. v. 4, schol. 3 Ibid. The Pass iu /is become Nationalised. 279 the life of the individual and the race. Ambition and kindred passions are based on the desire "that other men should live after our fashion ; " but this is only an irrational aim when it is the dictate of blind, selfish impulse ; in a nature that is elevated to the universality of reason it becomes simply the endeavour that all men should lead a rational life. Animal courage or daring purged of its impulsive character, becomes that wise presence of mind which may express itself as much in evading danger as in facing and overcoming it. 1 Even those emotions, such as pity or compassion, which we are wont to regard as good and praiseworthy, are, con- sidered merely as emotions, bad and hurtful ; 2 but reason or the rational man extracts the valuable element in them, and instead of being impulsively moved by the calamities and tears of the wretched, seeks on rational grounds to ameliorate their condition. 3 Thus, in general, the knowledge of passion annihilates passion, and sub- stitutes for it the calm and deliberate activity of reason. A perfectly wise man would be absolutely passionless, and therefore absolutely free. He " would hate no man, envy no man, be angry with no man," and for the same reason, would love and pity no man, do nothing at the mere dictate of feeling, but would order his life from purely rational motives for the general good. 4 2. As another and kindred " remedy for the passions," or means of attaining freedom, Spinoza points out that " the mind can bring it about that all bodily affections or images of things should be referred," (a) to "the common properties of things or deductions therefrom," i Eth. iv. 69. 2 Eth. iv. 50. a Ibid., dein. 4 Eth. iv. 73, dem. and schol. 280 Spiiwza. or (b) to " the idea of God." l This " remedy for the passions " is only the converse or correlate of that which we have just considered. Thought or reason transforms the object as well as the subject of passion. When I think or know myself, the passion vanishes ; when I think or know the world, it ceases to be that world which appeals to passion. The latter result is, indeed, already involved in the former. Even from Spinoza's peculiar point of view, thought and its outward object stand or fall with each other. The world, as it was for inadequate thought, no longer exists for that which has become adequate; thought cannot rise from the indi- vidual to the universal without implying a parallel ele- vation in the extended world which is its object. But though the one transformation implies the other, it is possible, following our author, to consider them separately. The dominion of passion may be conceived of as the dominion of the world and the things of the world over a nature larger than themselves of the world as it is for sense and imagination- over a nature the essence of which is reason, of the things of the world in their fictitious reality and independence over a nature the essence of which is the idea or self- affirmation of God. The " bondage," on that supposi- tion, would be that of an infinite nature imprisoned in the finite, of a being whose essence is light, harmony, eternal order and unity, in a world of darkness and dis- cordancy. The deliverance from this bondage is that " remedy for the passions " to which Spinoza here point*. Annihilate the world, and the passions which were re- lated to it die a natural death. But the world on which * Etb. v. 14 aud 12. The World transformed for Reason. 281 passion fed has no real existence. Nothing really is as to imagination it seemed to be. The individual things to which the affections of the body were referred, and which, through these affections, became the objects of desire and aversion, love and hate, are purely illusory. The body and its affections, and all bodies which affect it, are nothing save as determined by universal relations of cause and effect, which link the whole order or sys- tem of things into one vast unity. The mind that is the prey of the passions is Avasting itself on a vain show, fastening on that as real and permanent which is fugitive and evanescent. Thought or reason dissolves the show, and with it the passions to which it gave birth. Passion, again, in its fluctuation and variable- ness, is based on relations to a world which is the scene of arbitrariness and accident. But there is no such world. The "common properties," the universal laws, of things determine their relations by an absolute neces- sity, and when we " refer the affections of the body " to these, when the world puts off the mask of change and contingency, and the presence of eternal order and ne- cessity confronts us, the restless alternations of satiety and discontent vanish with the illusory world they re- flected. " If we remove a disturbance of the mind or an emotion from the thought of an external cause, and connect it with other thoughts, then will love or hatred towards the external cause, and also the fluctuations of the mind which arise from these emotions, be de- stroyed." l But further, in the real world which sup- plants the illusory world of imagination, there is some- thing deeper even than the " common properties " which 1 Eth. v. 2. 2S'2 reason discerns. Thought, even when it has grasped the universal principles or laws which bind all finite things in the bonds of an unchangeable necessity, falls short of apprehending their deepest meaning. "The mind can bring it about that all bodily affections and images of things should be referred to the idea of God." l It is possible, as we have seen, for thought to rise to a point of view from which the world is contemplated, not merely as a system of tilings conditioning and con- ditioned by each other, but as a system in which all things are seen in the light of that absolute unity of which they are only the infinitely varied expression. The true " existence of things " is that which is ascribed to them because of this, that from the eternal necessity of the nature of God an infinity of things follows in infinite ways." * The system of the world, in other words, contains an element of unresolved diversity till the particular existence of things, and their mediating link of causation, are no longer independent, and by the glance of immediate " intellectual intuition " we can, so to speak, see the whole at once all diversity in unity, all thinking things, all objects of thought as expressions of that "idea of God" which is their immanent prin- ciple and essence. In this highest and truest knowledge of the world lies the secret of complete emancipation from the bondage of passion, and of the attainment of perfect freedom. In the sphere of the passions that emotion is most vivid and powerful which is referred to a present rather than an absent object, or to a greater rather than a lesser number of objects, or to objects that most frequently recur; and an emotion possessing all these 1 Eth. v. 14. a Eth. ii. 45, schol. The final Emancipation. 283 characteristics would prevail over every other. But if there be one object or idea which, is ever present and incapable of being excluded by any other, which all things and thoughts suggest, and from which everything else derives its significance and reality then must that idea, and the emotion to which it gives rise, dominate every other in the mind in which it dwells. Now, just such is the idea of God. It is the idea to which it is possible for the mind " to refer all bodily affections or images of things," and in the mind which has achieved this result, to which all things speak of God, or are seen only as they exist in God, all passions that relate only to things finite and transient are quelled, and every other emotion is absorbed in that " intellectual love " which is only another aspect of the intuitive knowledge of God. Finally, whilst every other emotion limits the mind's activity, this is the expression of its highest freedom. For whilst all passion "springs from pleasure or pain, accompanied with the idea of an external cause," this emotion springs from a cause which is no longer outward or foreign to the mind, but is its own inmost essence. Subjection to absolute truth is the freedom of intelli- gence. For the mind, the essence of which is that self- affirming impulse which is in reality the self-affirmation of God in it, and for which the world is a world in which all things are seen in God, or awaken the thought and love of God, subjection to what is external ceases ; every object it contemplates, everything that stirs the fount of feeling, only contributes to its own purest activ- ity. The mind that is one with God is free of a uni- verse in which itself and all things live and move and have their being in God. 284 Spinoza. In reviewing this theory of the transition from bondage to freedom, it may be pointed out that its main defect seems to lie in the abstract ideal of man's highest life on which it is based. Freedom is pure self-affirmation or self-activity, all passion is negation of that activity. The ideal, therefore, of the moral life is that of an absolutely passionless life. The " life according to reason " is that in which the agent is determined " by reason without passion." Reason and passion cannot coexist. "Where emotion is contrary to reason, it is noxious ; where it coincides with reason, it is useless : in either case, it is an invasion from without on that purely self-affirming activity in which the mind's freedom consists. The triumph of reason is not the subjugation but the ex- tinction of passion. To think a passion is to kill it. Thought and passion are opposed as activity and pas- sivity, and the positing of the former is equivalent to the annulling of the latter. Further, it follows from this that the free or rational life is one from which pain or sorrow is absolutely excluded. Pain is the indication of repressed activity ; pleasure, in the sense in which it is not of the nature of passion, of unimpeded or expanding activity. Into the spiritual life, therefore, no feeling of which pain or sorrow is an element can enter ; and judged by this criterion, humility, penitence, pity, compassion, and kindred emotions must be pro- nounced to be evil. 1 But it is to be remarked that a freedom which is thus identified with passionless intelligence, or the pure self- affirmation of reason apart from negation, is either an impossible notion, or a notion which is only a moment i Eth. iv. 50, 53, 54. Criticism of the Theory. 285 or factor in the true idea of freedom. It is true that the affirmation of a self which is above and beyond the pas- sions, though not in itself spiritual freedom, is a step in the process towards it. It is of the very essence of a spiritual nature to be conscious of a self which is more than any or all particular desires and affections, which does not come and go with the succession of feelings, but underneath all their transiency and changefulness remains ever one with itself, posits or affirms itself in opposition to their negativity. But though this self-affirmation is an element of the process, it is only an element. A purely self- affirming intelligence, or, otherwise expressed, a rational will which has no materials of activity outside of itself, is a mere abstraction. It is a determiner without any- thing to determine, a universal without the particular, the blank form of the moral life without any filling or content. Reason can never realise itself merely by will- ing to be rational ; it can only do so by willing particular acts which come under the form of rationality. And this implies that the general principle or aim of reason can only fulfil itself through particular desires, impulses, passions, which have their own ends or objects. An intelligence feeding only on itself dies of inanition, or rather, never begins to live. But whilst thus the ex- tinction of passion would be the extinction of spirit- iial life, or whilst an intelligence that could annihilate passion would annihilate the very materials of its own existence, yet, on the other hand, the passions, in so far as they remain an element of the spiritual life, do not remain unchanged. Reason, if it does not annul, trans- mutes them. In the moral strife the conquest is not that of a victor who slays his enemies, but who makes thfia 286 Spinoza. his own thralls. Or rather it is more thau that ; for in the conflict with the passions reason achieves its own freedom by infusing into them its own rationality. It realises itself by elevating the natural impulses and desires into its own universality. As the touch of art glorifies matter, transnmtes stones and pigments into the beauty and splendour of the ideal ; or as organic life, whilst it takes up inorganic materials into itself, leaves them not unchanged, but assimilates and transforms them, suffuses them with its own power and energy, so the impulses and passions of the natural self are but the raw material which the spiritual self transforms into the organs of its own life. The free man, the man who has entered into the universal life of reason, is still a creature of flesh and blood; he hungers and thirsts, he is no stranger to ordinary appetites and impulses, or to those wider passions which animate the most unspiritual natures. But in living, not for his individual pleasure, but for the higher ends of the spirit, the passions, whether as the mere organic basis of the spiritual life, or as con- trolled and denied for the sake of it, or as used up as its resources, become, to the spirit, instinct witli its own vitality and freedom. 287 CHAPTER XVI. IMMORTALITY AND THE BLESSED LIFE. SPINOZA'S doctrine of immortality is, in one point of view, only another form of his doctrine of freedom. It is the passions or passive emotions which hinder the mind's inherent activity and subject it to the control of a foreign element. But so long as the body exists, the passions must more or less limit the autonomy of reason. For the passions correspond to and reflect the affections which the body receives from external bodies ; or, other- wise expressed, they are due to the illusory influence of the imagination, which contemplates outward objects in their accidental relations to the body and gives to them a false substantiality and independence. A passion is " a confused idea by which the mind affirms greater or less power of it* body than before, and by the presence of which it is determined to think one thing rather than another." <: AVhatsoever hinders the power or activity of the body, the idea of that thing hinders that of the mind." 1 Whilst, therefore, the body endures, we must be more or less the slaves of imagination and passion. If the mind were wholly imagination it would perish with the body i Eth. iii. 11. 288 Spinoza. and its affections. The illusory world and the ideas that reflect it would vanish together. But, as we have just seen, there is that in the mind which enables it to rise above the slavery of passion, to emancipate itself from the illusions that are generated by ideas of bodily affections. The true essence of mind is reason, which sees things, not under the fictitious limits of time, but under the form of eternity and in their immanent rela- tion to the idea of God. It is this essence of the mind which constitutes what Spinoza calls its " better part," and in which lies the secret at once of its freedom and its immortality. It makes man free, for it raises him above the desires that are related to the accidental and transient, and brings him under the dominion of that "intellec- tual love " which is the expression of his own deepest nature. It makes man immortal, for, having no relation to the body and its affections, it has in it nothing that can be affected by the destruction of the body. " There is nothing in nature that is contrary to this intellectual love or can take it away." 1 "It is possible for the human mind to be of such a nature that that in it which we have shown to perish with the body is of little im- portance in comparison with that in it which endures." '' "The eternal part of the mind is the understanding, through which alone we are said to act ; the part which we have shown to perish is the imagination, through which alone we are said to be passive." 8 There is, however, another and very peculiar aspect of Spinoza's doctrine of immortality which remains to be explained. We naturally ask how any such survival of the mind after the destruction of the body as is here 1 Eth. v. 37. - Eth. v. 38, schol. 3 Eth. v. 40, cor. The " Essence " of the Body. 289 maintained, is consistent with the fundamental doctrine of the uniform parallelism of thought and extension, or with the principle that to all that takes place in the human mind as a mode of thought there must be some- thing corresponding in the human body as a mode of extension. Spinoza's answer to this question turns on the distinction which, according to him, obtains between the " essence " and the " actual existence " of the body. The mind's survival does not leave us with something in the sphere of thought to which nothing in the sphere of ex- tension corresponds. For though the particular mode of extension which we designate this actually existing body, or the body " in so far as it is explained by duration and can be defined by time," ceases to exist, there is never- theless an " essence " of the body which can only be conceived through the essence of God or under the form of eternity, and which therefore endures when everything corporeal of which we can speak in terms of time passes away. " God," says Spinoza, " is the cause not only of the existence of this or that human body, but also of its essence." l " There is necessarily in God (and therefore in the human mind) an idea which ex- presses the essence of the human body." 2 It would therefore appear that not only the mind, but the body also, survives death. The parallelism of thought and extension is not affected by the destruction of the actually existing body. In both there is something that passes away, in both something that remains. If that particu- lar mode of extension which we call the actually exist- ing body passes away, so also does that mode of thought which constitutes the idea of the actually existing body. i Eth. v. 22, clem. - Eth. v. 23. lem. P. XII. T 290 Spinoza. On the other hand, if the immortal element in mind is the reason, which contemplates all things under the form of eternity, in like manner the immortal element in the body is that " essence of the body " which is the object of reason. The " form of eternity " belongs alike to the essence of the body and to the essence of the mind. 1. In criticising this theory, it may be remarked that in such phrases as " the duration of the mind without relation. to the body," "the mind does not imagine, &c., save while the body endures," Spinoza employs language which, as addressed to the ordinary ear, is misleading, inasmuch as it suggests the notion of an incorporeal im- mortality, a survival of the purely spiritual element of man's nature when the material element has passed away. Such phraseology perhaps betrays an unconscious con- cession to the popular conception of the material as the grosser, the mental as the nobler element, and of immor- tality as the emancipation of the spirit from the bondage of matter. In any case, such language is obviously inconsistent with Spinoza's doctrine as above explained. Spinoza knows nothing of the false spiritualism which recoils from the supposed grossness or " pravity " of matter. To him, on the contrary, matter is as divine as mind, modes of matter are as much the expression of God as modes of mind. On his principles it would be equally true and equally false to say that the body sur- vives the mind, and to say that the mind survives the body. To each he ascribes an "essence" which is dis- tinct from its "actual existence " ; and if the essence of the mind survives the body regarded as a particular, transient modification of matter, the essence <>f the body Criticism of the Doctrine. 291 survives the mind regarded as the idea of that modifica- tion, or the particular modification of thought which corresponds to it. 2. It is a more important criticism of Spinoza's doc- trine that it ascribes to death or the destruction of the body what is really due to reason, as the destroyer of the illusions of imagination. The triumph of mind is not the destruction of the body, but the destruction of a false view of it. It is not achieved by the cessation of the body's existence, but by the dissipation of the illu- sory reality ascribed to it. The immortality which is predicated of the mind is not continuity of existence after death, but its capacity to rise above the category of time and to see itself, the body and all things, under the form of eternity. To speak of this as something future, or as a capacity of living on after a certain date, or of surviving a certain event, is simply to explain in terms of time that the very nature of which is to tran- scend time. The immortality which is sanctioned by Spinoza's principles is not a quantitative but a qualitative endowment not existence for indefinite time, but the quality of being above time. It is an immortality, there- fore, which may be attained here and now. In so far as we rise to the stage of intuitive intelligence and intel- lectual love, we have an immediate experience of it, we enter at once into the sphere of eternity, and the old world of imagination vanishes away. And if we ask, What is the relation of this eternal consciousness to the life or death of the body? it might be answered that the moral acceptance of death is the supreme act of liberation. For the mind that sees things under the form of eternity, the body, as a phenomenon in time, 292 Spinoza. has already vanished, the disillusioning power of reason has anticipated in a deeper way the physical disinte- gration of death. Spinoza knows nothing of the Pla- tonic notion of the corporeal state as an imprisonment of the soul, from which death liberates it. The mind that knows God has already achieved its liberation, and the eternity in which it dwells is neither hindered nor helped by the destruction of the body. According to his own principles, therefore, it is an obvious inconsist- ency in Spinoza to speak of a subjection of the mind to imagination and passion " so long as the body endures," or of the " destruction of the body " as contributing in any measure to its emancipation. For the higher con- sciousness of the mind, the body has been already de- stroyed, and the only emancipation of which the mind is capable is one which reason, and not the destruction of the body, has accomplished. 3. Spinoza's doctrine implies a tacit ascription to the mind of a superiority over the body which is inconsistent with their parallelism as modes of thought and extension. That doctrine is, as we have seen, that there is an essence of mind and an essence of body which both alike tran- scend the category of time, and are part of the eternal nature of God. But whilst Spinoza's conception of the nature of mind supplies a ground for its superiority to time, its permanence through all change, he assigns no similar ground for the perpetuity of the body. Modes of thought are determined by other modes ; but besides this, there is a reduplication of thought upon itself ; in other words, thought thinks itself. Modes of extension are determined by other modes, but there is no similar return of each mode of extension upon itself, nor, from Inconsistency of the Doctrine. 293 the very nature of the thing, is any such return con- ceivable. Xow, though the conception of mind as not only idea of the body, but as the idea of that idea, does not amount to what is involved in the modern doctrine of self-consciousness, yet in Spinoza's speculations it performs in some measure the functions which that doctrine ascribes to the mind. As conscious of itself, mind contains in its very essence a principle of continu- ity, a unity which remains constant through all phenom- enal changes. It can abstract from all determinations, and it is that to which all determinations are referred the living, indestructible point of centrality to which the thoughts and feelings that compose our conscious life are drawn back. But there is nothing approximat- ing to this principle of self-centrality in Spinoza's con- ception of the body. " The human body is composed," he tells us, 1 "of many individual parts of diverse nature, each one of which is extremely complex," and " these individual parts of the body, and therefore the body itself, are constantly being affected by external bodies." In all this diversity and change there is no principle of unity ; the unity to which the body as a composite thing is referred is not in itself, but in the " idea of the body," or the mind that thinks it. 4. Spinoza's conception of immortality, or of the eter- nal element in mind, is, as we have seen, simply that of a mind for which the illusion of time has disappeared. But to drop or eliminate an illusion is not to account for it, or to explain its relation to our mental and spiritual life. Spinoza points out as a fact that time as well as figure, number, measure, are only illusory forms of ima- 1 Eth. ii., post. 1 and 3. 294 Spinoza. gination, and that reason rises above them. But even an illusion must be in some way grounded in the intel- ligence that experiences it. It can be explained only by tracing its origin, and by showing that it forms a necessary stage in the development of the finite mind. Time, in other words, is not explained even as an illu- sion, unless in the eternal there is shown to be a reason for it ; nor is the eternal which rises above time to be understood unless the negation of time is shown to be contained in it. If the aspect of things " under the form of eternity " has no necessary relation to their aspect as things in time, the latter is a mere excrescence in the system, and for any reason that appears, might have been omitted altogether. If thinking things under the form of time is not a necessary stage in the process towards true knowledge, there is no reason why the mind should not have started at once from the point of view in which nothing is illusory, and in which eternal realities are immediately apprehended. Spinoza contrasts reason and imagination, the point of view in which tilings are regarded as independent realities, and the point of view in which they are seen in the light of the idea of God, or under the form of eternity. But he makes no attempt to show the relation between the lower and the higher point of view. He simply pro- nounces the former to be false and illusory, and the latter to be an attitude of mind in which the former is dropped or left behind. But is there no way, it may be asked, in which it can be shown that the determination of things in time, not merely empirically precedes, but is a necessary presupposition of their determination under the form of eternity 1 Is it not possible to discern that Ilhisioii of Time uncxplainnf. 295 the rise from imaginative to rational knowledge is not an accident in the history of thought, but a necessary step in the process by which a self-conscious intelli- gence realises itself and its own inherent wealth ] The answer to this question may be said to be involved in the very nature of intelligence. The relation of im- agination to reason is simply the relation, in modem language, of consciousness to self-consciousness. The consciousness of self implies relation to objects which are opposed to self, and yet which, as related to self, form a necessary element of its life. It is only by the presentation to itself of an external world i.e., of a world conceived of under the forms of externality that mind or intelligence can, by the relating or reclaiming of that world to itself, become conscious of its own latent content Thought, in other words, is not a resting identity, but a process, a life, of which the very essence is ceaseless activity, or movement from unity to difference and from difference to unity. It is not by brooding on itself in some pure, supersensuous sphere of untroubled spirituality, but by going forth into a world that, in the first instance, is outside of and foreign to itself, and of which the constituent elements in their self-externality in space and succes- sion in time, are the contradiction of its own inherent unity, and then by the recognition of that world as not really foreign or independent or discordant, but in its real or essential natiire related to and finding its mean- ing and unity in thought it is by this perpetual process of differentiation and integration that self-conscious in- telligence ceases to be a lifeless abstraction, and becomes a concrete reality. But if this be so, the differentiat- 296 Spinoza. ing movement is presupposed in the integrating, the world of imagination is no longer a mere illusion which somehow the mind outlives, a dream from which it awakes, but a necessary step in the life of spirit and in its 'progress to higher things. Time is not a mere subjective deception which passes away, but a form of objectivity which it is of the very essence of spirit to posit and transcend. It is only by the affirmation and negation of time that we can rise to the contemplation of things under the form of eternity. The eternal life is not that which abstracts from the temporal, but that which contains while it annuls it. 5. The most important question as to Spinoza's doc- trine of immortality still remains, and that is the ques- tion, not whether the individual mind can in any way be said to survive the body, but whether in their relation to God there can be said to be any real survival of either. The view which we take of man's nature implies and must be based on a corresponding view of the nature of God. Whatever independence we ascribe, to the finite involves as its correlate an idea of the infinite which admits of and is the ground of that independence. Does Spinoza's idea of God admit of and furnish a basis for his doctrine of human freedom and immortality? The peculiarity of the view of man's nature and destiny which we have now ex- plained is that it is just at the point where the limit between the finite and infinite vanishes, and where indeed there is the strongest reassertion of the doctrine that the finite is and is conceived only through the in- finite, that instead of being suppressed or indistinguish- ably absorbed, the finite mind is represented as attain- Individuality iwt obliterated. 297 ing the most complete individuality and activity. " The eternal part of the mind is the understanding through which alone we are said to act, the part which we have shown to perish is the imagination through which only we are said to be passive." 1 The state which consti- tutes the supreme or eternal destiny of man is not simply that of absolute unity with God, but that in which man attains to the consciousness of that unity, and in which the distinction between itself and God is not only not obliterated but intensified. " The mind as eternal has a knowledge of God which is necessarily adequate and is fitted to know all those things which follow from this knowledge, . . . and the more potent any one becomes in this kind of knowledge, the more completely is he conscious of himself and of God." ~ Xot only is it a state in which the mind has attained the maximum of self-originated activity, and therefore its highest individual perfection, but with the con- sciousness of this comes also the highest joy or blessed- ness. For " if joy consists in the transition to a greater perfection, assuredly blessedness must consist in the mind being endowed with perfection itself." " He who knows things by this kind of knowledge passes to the highest human perfection, and therefore is affected by the highest joy, and that a joy which is accompanied by the idea of himself and of his own virtue." 4 Finally, all these elements of individual perfection freedom, activity, self - consciousness, self - determination are summed up in that attitude of mind which Spinoza designates "intellectual love," which he defines as "joy 1 Eth. v. 40, cor. - Eth. v. 31, dein. and mr. *"Eth. v. 33, schol. * Etls. v. 27, clem. 298 Spinoza. or delight accompanied by the idea of one's self, and therefore by the idea of God as its cause." * The per- fection of human nature, in other words, is a state of blessedness in which the consciousness of self is not lost in God, but actually based on the consciousness of God. Can we find in Spinoza's idea of the divine nature any room or ground for this conception of the nature and destiny of man? The answer must be, that the idea of God on which Spinoza's whole system is osten- sibly based is one which involves the denial of any reality or independence to the finite. It is by negation of all individual finite things that that idea is reached. It is by abstracting from all distinctions material and mental, and even from the distinction of matter and mind itself, that we attain to that pure, indeterminate unity, that colourless, moveless abstraction of substance which is Spinoza's formal conception of the nature of God. But this though formally is not really the idea of God on which Spinoza's system rests. What he sought to reach was a principle which would constitute the ex- planation of man and the world, from which "an infi- nite number of things in infinite ways must necessarily follow," and from the adequate knowledge of which the mind could proceed to the adequate knowledge of the nature of things." 2 And though the idea of God which he formulates does not constitute such a principle, yet in the course of his speculations we find that idea under- going various modifications which, if carried out to their logical results, would have involved the complete recon- struction of his philosophy. 1 Eth. v. 32, cor. - Etli. ii. 40, sell. 2. Jui mortality and Idea of God. 299 (1.) His constant use of the phrase qiiatenim is really an acknowledgment of the inadequacy of the premiss it is introduced to qualify an expedient, in other words, for surreptitiously reaching results not logically justifiable on his own principles. The infinitude Avhich is conceived of as pure indetennination would be tampered with if any finite existence could be regarded as an expression of the essential nature of God; yet Spinoza is not content with a barren infinitude an infinitude which leaves nature and man unaccounted for. Hence the frequent recurrence of such expressions as these : "The idea of an individual thing actually existing has God for its cause, not in so far as He is infinite, but in so far as He is regarded as affected by another idea of an individ- ual thing, &c. ; " a " God has this or that idea, not in so far as He is infinite, but in so far as He is expressed by the nature of the human mind or constitutes the essence of the human mind ; " 2 " The intellectual love of the mind toward God is the very love with which He loves Himself, not in so far as He is infinite, but in *> far as He can be expressed by the essence of the human mind conceived under the form of eternity." a The infinite can never be expressed by a nature which is nothing but the negation of the infinite. Yet this inevitable conclusion Spinoza will not let himself ac- knowledge. The whole moral use and value of his philosophy would vanish if man could not find the origin and end of his being in God, and so the self- contained, self-identical infinite must break through its isolation and reveal itself in the essence of the human mind. How or on what philosophical ground this rev- i Eth. ii. 9. 2 Eth. ii. 11, cor. 3 Eth. v. 36. 300 Spinoza. elation is to be conceived Spinoza does not attempt to explain ; but to speak of " God in so far as He is expressed by the human mind," or of the human mind as surviving in its individuality "in so far as God can be expressed by its essence under the form of eternity," would be to employ words without meaning if this " in so far " did not point to something positive and real in the nature of God. To say that a thing exists or survives in so far as the divine idea is ex- pressed in it, would be absurd if Spinoza believed that the divine idea did not express itself in it at all. The ever- recurring phrase must have been to its author something more than a transparent artifice or a petitio prindpii. (2.) Whilst Spinoza rejects the anthropomorphic idea of God as a being who acts on nature from without or whose essence contains arbitrary elements after the analogy of man's imperfect thought and will, he yet constantly ascribes activity to God. An indeterminate absolute is a dead and moveless absolute. Whilst God's activity cannot proceed from any external cause or constraint, but must be the expression of an internal necessity, yet He is essentially and eternally active. " The omnipotence of God has been from eternity actual, and will to eternity remain in the same actuality." 1 "From God's supreme power or infinite nature an infinite number of things in infinite ways that is, all things have necessarily flowed forth." 2 And this con- ception of the essential productive activity of the divine nature is based on the principle that the more reality a thing has, the more properties follow therefrom, and therefore the infinite nature " has absolutely infinite 1 Eth. i. 17, sch. 2 ibid. Self -Consciousness of God. 301 attributes, of which each expresses infinite essence in its own kind." * The infinite which is the negation of all properties or determinations thus becomes the infinite which has an infinite number of properties or deter- mination.-. (3.) It is true indeed, as we formerly saw, that the properties or attributes which Spinoza ascribes to God he is compelled by stress of logic to remove from the nature of God or Substance, absolutely viewed, and to regard as having an existence only relatively to finite intelligence. They are not distinctions which pertain to the divine essence as it is in itself, but only distinctions " which the understanding perceives as constituting that essence." They do not exist, in other words, for or through God's own thought, but for or through the thought of finite minds. Yet it is to be observed that there are in- dications that, however illogically, the attributes had for him the significance of absolute and not relative distinc- tions in the divine nature ; and further, that it is not the human but the divine intelligence in and for which he conceived them to exist. "By God," says he, 2 "I understand a being absolutely infinite that is, Substance consisting of infinite attributes of which each expresses eternal and infinite essence." "By attri- butes of God is to be understood that which expresses the essence of the divine Substance." 3 "The attri- butes of God which express His eternal essence, express at the same time His eternal existence." 4 Further, as we have seen, though in his formal doctrine Spinoza places thought on a level with extension and all other 1 Eth. i. 16, dem. 2 Eth. i., def. 6. s Eth. i. 19, dem. 4 Eth. i. 20, dem. 302 Spinoza. possible attributes, he really ascribes to the former an altogether higher and more comprehensive function. It is thought or intelligence in man for which both exten- sion and thought exist ; and as all other possible attributes exist for some intelligence, not only are the infinitude of attributes accompanied each by a parallel attribute of thought, but each and all of them exist for thought. In this conception of an infinite number of intelligences for which the attributes of God exist, Spinoza is hover- ing on the brink of the idea of an infinite intelligence as not an attribute or distinction outwardly ascribed to God, but the principle of distinction in the divine essence from which all attributes or distinctions flow. But he goes further still than this. Infinite intelligence is for him not merely the aggregate of an indefinite number of finite minds, it is infinite in a truer sense. For, as we have attempted to show, the conception of "the absolutely infinite intellect," as one of what Spinoza terms "infinite modes," is simply a device by which he is unconsciously seeking to introduce into the idea of God that element of activity which neither his abstract substance nor even its attributes contain. The gulf be- tween the moveless infinite and the finite world is thus bridged over by an expedient which, ostensibly without affecting the indeterminateness of the absolute substance, makes it quick with the life of creative thought intro- duces into it, in other words, what is virtually the prin- ciple of self-consciousness and self-determination. 303 CONCLUSION. THE last word of Spinoza's philosophy seems to be the contradiction of the first. Not only does he often fluc- tuate between principles radically irreconcilable, but he seems to reassert at the close of his speculations what he had denied at the beginning. The indeterminate in- finite, which is the negation of the finite, becomes the infinite, which necessarily expresses itself in the finite, and which contains in it, as an essential element, the idea of the human mind under the form of eternity. The all-absorbing, lifeless substance becomes the God who knows and loves Himself and man with an infinite " intellectual love." On the other hand, the conception of the human mind as but an evanescent mode of the infinite substance, whose independent existence is an illusion, and which can become one with God only by ceasing to be distinguishable from God, yields to that of a nature endowed with indestructible individuality, capable of knowing both itself and God, and which, in becoming one with God, attains to its own conscious perfection and blessedness. The freedom of man, which is at first rejected as but the ilhision of a being who is unconscious of the conditions under which, in body and mind, he is fast bound in the toils of an inevitable neces- 304 Spinoza. sity, is reasserted as the essential prerogative of a nature which, as knowing itself through the infinite, is no longer subjected to finite limitations. The doctrine of a final cause or ideal end of existence, which was excluded as impossible in a world in which all that is, and as it is, is given along with the necessary existence of God, is restored in the conception of the human mind as having in it, in its rudest experience, the implicit consciousness of an infinite ideal, which, through reason and intuitive knowledge, it is capable of realising, and of the realisa- tion of which its actual life is the process. At the out- set, in one word, we seem to have a pantheistic unity in which nature and man, all the manifold existences of the finite world, are swallowed up ; at the close, an infinite self-conscious mind, in which all finite thought and being nnd their reality and explanation. Is it possible to harmonise these opposite aspects of Spinoza's system, and to free it from the inherent weak- ness which they seem to involve 1 ? Can we make him self-consistent, as many of his interpreters have done, only by emphasising one side or aspect of his teaching, and ignoring or explaining away all that seems to con- flict with it by clearing it of all individualistic elements, so as to reduce it to an uncompromising pantheism, or by eliminating the pantheistic element as mere scholastic surplusage, in order to find in it an anticipation of modern individualism and empiricism? The answer is, that though Spinoza's philosophy can- not, in the form in which he presents it, be freed from inconsistency, yet much of that inconsistency is due to the limitations of an imperfect logic, and that the philo- sophy of a later time has taught us how it is possible to Negation and Ecasscrtion of the Finite. 305 embrace ill one system ideas which in him seem to be antagonistic. There is a point of view which he at most only vaguely foreshadowed, in which it is possible to maintain (1) at once the nothingness of the finite world before God and its reality in and through God, and (2) the idea of an infinite unity transcending all differences, which nevertheless expresses itself in nature and man, in all the manifold differences of finite thought and being. 1. The negation of the finite by which Spinoza rises to the idea of God is, in one sense, an element which en- ters into the essence of all spiritual life. But when we consider the twofold aspect in which Spinoza himself represents this negative movement, that, on the one hand, which is involved in the principle that all de- termination is negation ; and that, on the other hand, which is involved in the rise of the human mind from the lower to the higher stages of knowledge, we can discern in his teaching an approximation to the idea of a negation which is only a step to a higher affirma- tion in other words, of that seZ/-negation or self-renun- ciation which is the condition of self-realisation in the intellectual, the moral, and the religious life. It is the condition of the intellectual life. Scientific knowledge is the revelation to or in my consciousness of a system of unalterable relations, a world of object- ive realities which I can neither make nor unmake, and which only he who abnegates his individual fancies and opinions can apprehend ; and all knowledge rc>t> on the tacit presupposition of an absolute truth or reason, which is the measure of individual opinion, which cannot be questioned without self-contradiction, p. xu. u which in our very doubts and uncertainties we assume, and to which in its every movement the finite intelli- gence must surrender itself. The intellectual life is one which I can live only by ceasing to assert myself or to think my own thoughts, by quelling and suppressing all thought that pertains to me as this particular self, and identifying myself with an intelligence that is universal and absolute. Yet the negation of which we thus speak is not an absolute negation. The finite intelligence is 'not absorbed or lost in the infinite to which it surrenders itself. Surrender or subjection to absolute truth is not the extinction 'of the finite mind, but the realisation of its true life. The life of absolute truth or reason is not a life that is foreign to us, but one in which we come to our own. The annulling of any life that is separate from or opposed to it, is the quickening, the liberation, the reassertion of our own intelligence. And the same thing is true of the moral life. Here, too, it is possible to reconcile Spinoza's denial of any reality to the finite in the face of the infinite, with his reassertion of its reality in and through the infinite. For in the moral life of man negation is ever a necessary step to affirmation, it is only through the renunciation of the natural life that we rise into the spiritual. The natural life is that of the individual regarded as a being of natural tendencies, of impulses, instincts, appetites which look to nothing beyond their immediate satisfac- tion. They pertain to him as this particular self, and they seem to point to 1:0 other end than his own private pleasure. But man never is a mere individual, or, in this sense, a particular self, and his passions are al- ways so far transformed by self-consciousness that the TJie Jfiu'df iul Hi'/i'/in/i* Lif<\ 307 attainment of their immediate objects is never their complete satisfaction. He has, so to speak, not only to satisfy them, but to satisfy himself ; and the self he has thus to satisfy is not his own individuality as a being separate from others, but a self which is developed in him, just in proportion as he makes himself an instru- ment to the life of others. Hence it is of the very essence of a moral being that to be himself he must be more than himself. Shut up within the limits of purely isolated satisfactions, infinitely the larger part of his nature remains undeveloped. To realise the capaci- ties of his own being he must take up into it the life of the other members of the social organism. It is in pro- portion to the deepening and widening of his sympathies that his life grows richer and fuller ; and its ideal purity and perfection are conceivable only as the identification of himself with a life which is universal and infinite. But if this be so, then the higher or spiritual life implies the negation of the. lower or natural life. It is impos- sible to lead at the same time a life that is merely partic- ular and a life that is universal, to be at once boiinded by individual impulses, and giving free play to capacities that are virtually limitless. In the very act of living for others we die to self. And as the intellectual life involves the abandonment of all thought that is merely our own, so the moral life involves the abnegation of all desire, volition, action that begins and ends with the will of the individual self. Lastly, the religious life is, above all, that which con- forms to the idea of self-realisation through self-negation. For if true religion is not the appeasing of an alien power, or the propitiating of it for the attainment of our 308 Spinoza. own ends, neither can it be the mere prostration of the finite before the infinite. With Spinoza we can discern that it involves the negation of all that pertains to the individual as " a part of nature " ; and yet admit the justice of his condemnation of asceticism as a tristi* <.f torva superstitio, and of his assertion that joy is itself a progress to a greater perfection. We can see a mean- ing in the doctrine that finite beings have no existence save as vanishing modes of the divine substance, and at the same time in the seemingly contradictory doc- trine that the self-affirming impulse, Avhich is the very essence of the finite, reaches its highest activity in abso- lute union with God. We can perceive, in one word, how the negation of the finite before God, may be the beginning of a process which ends with the reafiirmation of the finite in and through God. 2. Finally, this negation and reaffirmation of the finite through the infinite involves a correlative con- ception of the divine nature which harmonises elements that in Spinoza appear to be irreconcilable. The unity which transcends and the unity which comprehends all the differences of the finite world; the God who is at once absolutely undetermined and infinitely determined, beyond whom is no reality, yet from whom an infinite number of things in infinite ways necessarily proceeds, who must be conceived of as the negation of finite thought and being, yet who expresses or reveals Him- self in nature and in the human mind, is there any point of view from which ideas so discordant can be harmonised 1 Can thought compass a conception which will read a meaning at once into the featureless, move- less infinite whose eternal repose no breath of living Idea, of God. 309 thought or feeling can disturb, and into the infinite, who knows and loves Himself in His creatures with an infinite " intellectual love " ? The answer is, that what Spinoza was feeling after tlrrough all these contradictory expressions, is to be found in the conception of God as absolute Spirit. For when we examine what this con- ception means, we shall find that it includes at once what Spinoza sought in the unity which lies beyond all deter- minations and in the unity which is itself the source of all the determinations of the finite world. All philosophy must rest on the presupposition of the ultimate unity of knowing and being on the principle, in other words, that there is in the intelligible universe no absolute or irre- concilable division, no element which in its hard, irredu- cible independence is incapable of being embraced in the intelligible totality or system of things. All the manifold distinctions of things and thoughts must be so conceived of as to be capable of being comprehended in one organic whole capable, that is, in the utmost diversity that can be ascribed to them, of being brought back to unity. All philosophy, moreover, which is not atheistic, must find that ultimate unity in the idea of God. Without rending the universe and falling into dualism, whatever reality and independence are ascribed to nature and man, that reality and independence must not only have its source in God, but must not be pressed beyond the point at which it is still consistent with the relation of all things to God. To say that God is abso- lutely infinite, is to say that in His nature must be con- tained a reason for the existence of the finite world, and also that nothing in the finite world can have or retain any existence or reality that is outside of God. 310 Spinoza. What this implies is an idea of the nature of God as a unity which reveals, yet maintains and realises, itself in all the distinctions of the finite world. Xow the one idea which perfectly fulfils this condition is that of God as infinite, self-conscious Spirit. For only in thought or self-consciousness have we a unity whose nature it is to be infinitely determined, yet which in all its determinations never goes beyond itself, but in all this multiplicity and variety is only and ever real- ising itself. Of this unity we find the type, though only the imperfect type, in our own minds. The philo- sophic interpretation of the world may be said to be uhe application to nature and man of a principle with whose action we are conversant in our own intelligence. It is of the very nature of thought to reveal itself, to give itself objectivity, to discover to itself its own in- herent wealth by going forth to objects that are opposed to, and in one sense external and foreign to itself. Mind or intelligence is no abstract, self-contained identity, having its whole reality in its own self-included being. A consciousness that is conscious of nothing, a think- ing subject which opposes to itself no external object, is a mere blank, an abstraction which has no reality. Without a world of objects in time and space, without other kindred intelligences, without society and his- tory, without the ever-moving mirror of the external world, consciousness could never exist, mind could never awaken from the slumber of unconsciousness and become aware of itself. But it is also of the very nature of mind in all this endless objectivity to main- tain itself. The self that thinks is never borne away from or lost to itself and its own oneness in the God and the Worla. 311 objects of its thought. It is the qne constant in their ever-changing succession, the indivisible unity whose pres- ence to them reclaims them from chaos. But further, it not only maintains but realises itself in and through the objects it contemplates. They are its own objects. If it begins by opposing the world to itself, its next movement is to retract the opposition, to annul the seeming foreignness, to find itself therein. Knowledge is a revelation, not simply of the world to the observ- ing mind, but of the observing mind to itself. Those unchangeable relations which we call laws of nature are nothing foreign to thought; they are rational or intel- ligible relations, discoveries to the intelligence that grasps them of a realm that is its own, of which in the very act of apprehending them it comes into possession. And still more do our social relations in the family, the community, the state, become to us a revelation of our- selves, a revelation of a life which, though in one sense other and larger than our own, is still our own. Thus the whole process of knowledge is a gradual annulling by the mind of that self-externality which is thought's first attitude towards the outward world, and a gradual self-creation or realisation of its own content. Con- sciousness, in other words, through the mediation of externality realises itself or becomes self-consciousness. Xow the principle with whose action in our own consciousness we are thus conversant is one which is applicable, not simply to our intelligence, but to all intelligence, and above all to that intelligence of which our own is the highest finite expression. It is the essential characteristic of spirit as spirit to be object to itself, to go forth into objectivity and return upon itself. 312 Spinoza. To conceive of God as an abstract, self-identical infinite would be to make Him not greater but less than finite intelligence less by all that spiritual wealth which is involved in our relations to nature and man. The abstract or merely quantitative infinite excludes the consciousness of any existence other than itself. It can remain " secure of itself " only by the reduction of all finite thought and being to unreality and illusion. But the infinitude which is preserved only by the ab- solute negation of the finite world is a barren infinitude. Its greatness is the greatness of a metaphysical figment, the greatness which is attained by leaving out from it all those elements of life and thought and love which constitute the wealth of a spiritual nature. On the other hand, an infinite whose essence is intelligence or self-consciousness, whilst it contains in it the necessity of relation to a finite world, is not limited by that necessity. For in so conceiving of it, as we have seen, the limitation we ascribe to it is a limitation which is the medium of its own self-realisation a going forth from itself which is no lessening or loss, but only a step in the process by which it returns upon itself in a complete fulness of being. Viewed in the light of this conception, nature and man are neither severed from God nor lost in God, but have all their significance as expressing or manifest- ing God. The external world, instead of being deprived of reality, is endowed with that highest reality which arises from this, that from the lowest inorganic matter to the highest forms of organic life, reason or thought underlies it ; and that ideal unity of nature which science partially discloses, which art, by its imaginative creations, foreshadows, is only then clearly apprehended Infinite Spirit. 313 when we recognise it as the unity of one spiritual prin- ciple, one infinite self-consciousness which goes forth to the utmost verge of self-externality in a world that exists under the conditions of space and time, yet in all this manifold objectivity remains ever one with itself. Above all, in the light of this idea of God as infinite Spirit we can see how man has a being and reality of his own, which yet is no limit to the nature of God, but the only medium of its complete manifestation. For only in the communication of its own life to kindred intelligence is there what can be termed, in the full sense of the word, a revelation of the Being whose nature is thought and love. Only in its relation to finite intelligence do we see the veil removed from that twofold movement that going forth from itself and return upon itself which is the very life of infinite Spirit Only in man does the divine Spirit go forth from itself ; for what God gives to man is nothing less than Himself, a reproduction of His own nature, a participation in His own life and In 'ing. Thought, indeed, in us is limited in this sense, that the knowable world exists independently of our knowledge of it, and that there are boundless possibilities of knowledge which for us have not become actual ; but in the very fact that thought or self-consciousness can be limited by nothing which lies outside of itself, that every conceivable advance in knowledge is only a realisation of ourselves, and that the very consciousness of our limits implies that there is that in us which transcends them in this lies the proof that it is of the essence of finite spirit to share in the infinitude from which it springs. Yet in this communication of Himself to man there is no outflow from the infinite source which does not return 31 4 Spinoza. upon itself. Without life in the life of others spirit would not be truly spirit. In spiritual life, giving and receiving, loss and gain, self-surrender and self-enrich- ment are ideas which implicate and pass into each other. Infinite intelligence is not limited but fulfilled by the existence of finite, for, as we have seen, it is the charac- teristic of the latter that to realise itself it must abnegate itself. To renounce every thought and volition that is merely its own, to become the transparent medium of the infinite mind and will, to be conscious of its dis- tinction from God only that it may return into indivisible unity with God this is its only possible way to self- realisation. For this self-abnegation, rightly interpreted, is not the subjugation of the finite intelligence to an out- ward and absolute authority, but it reaches its perfection when the thought and will to which it surrenders itself is recognised as its own in it as well as above it ; when it is not two concurrent voices that speak in its thought, but the one voice of infinite reason ; when duty has ceased to be self-denial, and the dictates of the absolute will blend indivisibly witli the affirmation of its own. In so far as this ideal is realised it may be said that in the utmost activity of the spiritual life in man God never breaks through the charmed circle of His own infinitude. It is His own knowledge that is reflected in the human mind, His own love that comes back upon Him through the channel of human hearts. It is not the finite as finite which God knows and loves, nor the finite as finite which seeks to be known and loved, but the finite which is transfigured with an infinite element, the finite that is not a thing of time, but that is and knows itself under the form of eternity. We have here a point Unity of I-njimrr. ami Finite. 315 of view in which the contradictions under which Spinoza's thought seems ever to labour can be regarded as the acci- dents of an unconscious struggle after a deeper principle in which they are solved and harmonised. In the light of that principle we can speak with him of an indeter- minate and infinite unity in which all finite distinctions lose themselves, and with him we can see that there is no paradox in the assertion that "he who loves God does not desire that God should love him in return." We can discern at the same time a profound meaning in those apparently mystical utterances in which he seems to gather up the final result of his speculation " God loves Himself with an infinite intellectual love ; " " God in so far as He loves Himself loves man ; " " the intel- lectual love of the mind to God is part of the infinite love whereAvith God loves Himself ; " " the love of God to man and the intellectual love of man to God are one and the same." END OF SPINOZA. rr.INTTO TV AVII.UAM Til ACKTVOOD AND SONS. BRARY FAC1UTY A 000 670 692 3