1 Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2007 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/faithitspsycholoOOingerich FAITH AND ITS PSYCHOLOGY FAITH AND ITS PSYC H O LO GY BY WILLIAM RALPH INGE LADY MARGARET PROFESSOR OF DIVINITY AT CAMBRIDGE NEW YORK CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS 1913 * «.*• ^*-*«<« %;';'^:V^O GENERAL INTRODUCTION TO THE SERIES Man has no deeper or wider interest than theology ; none deeper, for however much he may change, he never loses his love of the many questions it covers ; and none wider, for under whatever law he may live he never escapes from its spacious shade; nor does he ever find that it speaks to him in vain or uses a voice that fails to reach him. Once the present writer was talking with a friend who has equal fame as a statesman and a man of letters, and he said, 'Every day I live. Politics, which are affairs of Man and Time, interest me less, while Theology, which is an affair of God and Eternity, interests me more.' As with him, so with many, though the many feel that their interest is in theology and not in dogma. Dogma, they know, is but a series of resolutions framed by a council or parliament, which they do not respect any the more because the parliament was composed of ecclesiastically-minded persons ; while the theology which so interests them is a discourse touch- ing God, though the Being so named is the God man conceived as not only related to himself and his world but also as rising ever higher with the notions of the self and the world. Wise books, not in dogma but in theology, may therefore be described as the supreme 281428 GENERAL TNTRODUCTION need of our day, for only such can save us from much fanaticism and secure us in the full possession of a sober and sane reason. Theology is less a single science than an ency- clopaedia of sciences; indeed all the sciences which have to do with man have a better right to be called theological than anthropological, though the man it studies is not simply an individual but a race. Its way of viewing man is indeed characteristic ; from this have come some of its brighter ideals and some of its darkest dreams. The ideals are all either ethical or social, and would make of earth a heaven, creating fraternity amongst men and forming all states into a goodly sisterhood ; the dreams may be represented by doctrines which concern sin on the one side and the will of God on the other. But even this will cannot make sin luminous, for were it made radiant with grace, it would cease to be sin. These books then, — which have all to be written by men who have lived in the full blaze of modern light, — though without having either their eyes burned out or their souls scorched into insensibility, — are in- tended to present God in relation to Man and Man in relation to God. It is intended that they begin, not in date of publication, but in order of thought, with a Theological Encyclopaedia which shall show the circle of sciences co-ordinated under the term Theology, though all will be viewed as related to its central or main idea. This relation of God to human know- ledge will then be looked at through mind as a com- munion of Deity with humanity, or God in fellowship GENERAL INTEODUCTION with concrete man. On this basis the idea of Revela- tion will be dealt with. Then, so far as history and philology are concerned, the two Sacred Books, which are here most significant, will be viewed as the scholar, who is also a divine, views them; in other words, the Old and New Testaments, regarded as human documents, will be criticised as a literature which expresses relations to both the present and the future ; that is, to the men and races who made the books, as well as to the races and men the books made. The Bible will thus be studied in the Semitic family which gave it being, and also in the Indo-European families which gave to it the quality of the life to which they have attained. But Theology has to do with more than sacred literature; it has also to do with the thoughts and life its history occasioned. Therefore the Church has to be studied and presented as an institution which God founded and man ad- ministers. But it is possible to know this Church only through the thoughts it thinks, the doctrines it holds, the characters and the persons it forms, the people who are its saints and embody its ideals of sanctity, the acts it does, which are its sacraments, and the laws it follows and enforces, which are its polity, and the young it educates and the nations it directs and controls. These are the points to be pre- sented in the volumes which follow, which are all to be occupied with theology or the knowledge of God and His ways. A, M. F. *0.' PREFACE The main objects of this volume are threefold. 1 Firstly, to vindicate for rehgious Faith its true dignity as a normal and healthy part of human nature. Next, to insist that Faith demands the actual reality of its objects, and can never be content with a God who is only an ideal. Lastly, to show in detail how most of the errors and defects in rehgious behef have been due to a tendency to arrest the development of Faith prematurely, by annexing it to some one faculty to the exclusion of others, or by resting on given authority. The true goal is an unified experience which will make authority no longer external. This scheme has compelled me to state, far too briefly and dogmatically, my grounds of disagreement with certain religious opinions which are widely held, such as the infallibility of * the hving voice of the Church,' and the finality of the appeal to Holy Scripture, and also with those religious philosophies which make religion exclusively an affair of the will, or the in- tellect, or the aesthetic sense. My criticisms of these various theories are all intended to show the errors which result from a premature synthesis. Faith claims the whole man, and all that God's grace can make of him. If any part of ourselves is left outside our religion, our theory of Faith is sure to be partly vitiated by the omission ; and con- versely, an inadequate theory of Faith is likely to be reflected in one-sided or distorted practice. When we try to analyse the contents of Faith, after claiming for it this very comprehensive range, we must a FAITH be prepared for the criticism that we have given only bare outlines, or else that we have left rival constructions side by side in the form of patent inconsistencies. Foi we cannot hope to understand and co-ordinate all the highest experiences of the human spirit. And our own generation, it seems to me, is not called upon even to attempt any ambitious construction. We must be content to clear the site for a new building, and to get the materials ready. The wise master-builder is not yet among us. ' Revivals ' are only a stop-gap ; they create nothing. They recover for us parts of our spiritual heritage which were in danger of being lost, and having achieved this, they have done their work. The words CathoUc and Protestant are much Uke the words Whig and Tory in politics. They are the names of obsolescent distinc- tions, survivals of old-world struggles. When the next constructive period comes, it will be seen that the spiritual Latin empire and the Teutonic revolt against it belong to past history. Already the crucial question is, not whether Europe shall be Catholic or Protestant, but whether Christianity can come to terms with the awakening self-consciousness of modem civilisation, equipped with a vast mass of new scientific knowledge, and animated for the first time by ideals which are not borrowed from classical and Hebrew antiquity. The great danger in our path, I venture to think, comes from the democratisation of thought, which has affected religion, ethics, philosophy, and sociology — in fact, almost every department of mental activity except natural science. We see its results in hysterical sentimentalism, which is the great obstacle in the way of using organised effort for social amelioration. We see them in the frank adoption of materialistic standards, such as the pleasure and pain calculus, as soon as we leave the region of abstract speculation. And in philosophy it is impossible to miss the connection between the new empiricism, with its PREFACE Tii blatant contempt for idealism, whether of the ancient or modem type, and the democratic claim to decide all things in heaven and earth by popular vote. It is possible to sympathise thoroughly with the spread of education, and yet to be aware of the enormous dangers to civilisation which the false theory of natural equality brings with it. It has bred a dislike of intellectual superiority, and a reluctance to allow reason and knowledge to arbitrate on burning questions. Everywhere we find the praises of feeling or instinct sung, and the dangers of intellectualism exposed. Now instinct is the tendency in humanity to persistence, reason is the tendency to variation. Most variations, we are reminded, fail to establish themselves ; instinct is therefore the safer guide. But the tendency to variation is just what has raised man above the lower animals ; it is the condition of progress. And in civilised man reason has largely displaced instinct, which is no longer so trustworthy as in the brutes. Since this process is certain to go further, distrust of reason is suicidal, and to exclude it from matters of Faith must be disastrous. I believe that the Kantian antithesis between the specula- tive and practical reason is wholly fallacious, a residuum of the dualism which Kant found dominant in philosophy and failed to overcome. If this dualism is abandoned, the contrast between Faith and knowledge falls with it. And yet the temptation to ' heal slightly ' the wounds of religion by reverting to this separation of Faith from fact has proved irresistible to very many, and I beUeve that it is a main source of the notorious inefficacy of our apolo- getics. The intellectual difficulties raised by science are not popular, and we are tempted to override them because the masses are still ignorant and superstitious ; but I beheve that here is still our great problem, and that we shall do well to agree with our adversary quickly, while we are in the way with him. This is not the kind of intellectualism which paralyses vui FAITH action. To escape this, it is only necessary to remember that, in the hfe of man, thought and action are equally important. The normal course of all experience is ex- pansion followed by concentration. Ideals are painted by imaginative thought, but realised only in action. Character is consolidated thought. Action and contem- plation must act and react upon each other ; otherwise our actions will have no soul, and our thoughts no body. This is the great truth which the higher religions express in their sacraments. A sacrament is more than a symbol. The perception of symbols leads us from the many to the one, from the transitory to the permanent, but not from appearance to reality. This belongs to the sacramental experience, which is symbolism retranslating itself into concrete action, returning to the outer world and to mundane interests ; but in how different a manner from our earlier superficial experience ! The formula ' From symbol to sacrament ' completes and Christianises the Platonic (or Plotinian) scheme, and gives the mystic a rule of life. * Are we not here to make the transitory permanent ? ' asks Goethe. ' This we can only do if we know how to value both.' There are two essential movements in the spiritual life : one which finds God in the world, mainly through thought and feeling ; the other which re-finds the world in God, mainly through moral action. The former reaches permanence through change, the latter change through permanence. So the spiral goes on, in ever- diminishing circles (gyrans gyrando vadit Spiritus), till in heaven, we may be sure, the dis- harmony between thought and action is finally attuned. Note. — ^This book is an expansion of ten lectures which were delivered in London on the Jowett Foundation, in the early months of this year. For this reason, the form of lectures has been adhered to throughout. CONTENTS PAGE CHAPTER I 'faith' as a religious term, 1 CHAPTER II FAITH AS A RELIGIOUS TERM — Continued, , ... 24 CHAPTER III I THE PRIMARY GROUND OF FAITH, . , , . , .41 CHAPTER IV FAITH AS PURE FEELING, 55 CHAPTER V AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH, . , , , ,72 CHAPTER VI AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF F AlTH—COntinuedj ... 87 CHAPTER VII AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH — Continued, . . . 107 CHAPTER VIII I AUTHORITY BASED ON JESUS CHRIST, 124 ■ ■ Z FAITH PAOl CHAPTER IX FAITH AS AN ACT OF WILL, 140 CHAPTER X FAITH BASED ON PRACTICAL NEEDS — MODERNISM, . , . 161 CHAPTER XI FAITH AND REASON, 178 ^ CHAPTER XII THB .fiSTHETIC GROUND OF FAITH, 203 CHAPTER XIII FAITH AS HARMONIOUS SPIRITUAL DEVELOPMENT, . • • 223 BIBLIOQRAFUY, ••••••••• 243 INDEX, .•••••. t t • • 245 FAITH AND ITS PSYCHOLOGY CHAPTEE I •faith* as a religious term (a) In the Bible PROPOSE to consider the first of the theological virtues, in order to determine, if possible, in what it consists. I will not begin by attempting a definition of ' Faith ' ; but a brief indication of the sense in which the word will be used in the course of the discussion seems desirable. Broadly speaking, when we use the word Faith, without special reference to religion, we mean, either the holding for true of something which is not already verified by experience or demonstrated by logical conclusion,^ or con- fidence in the wisdom and integrity of a person. In the former sense, the corresponding verb is * believe,' in the latter it is * trust.' In the former sense, the conception of Faith is independent of the character or quality of the thing believed. I may believe in a God or in a devil ; in the habitability of Mars or in the man in the moon ; or I may believe that if I make one of a party of thirteen at dinner it will be a good speculation to insure my life. The grossest superstition might be called Faith in this sense. But in religious language, to which the word more properly belongs, Faith has a more limited and a more dignified meaning. * It is the general expression for subjective religion.* ^ It is used for conviction as to certain ultimate 1 Cf. Fechner, Die drei Motive und OrUnde des Olaubens, p, 1, • Dorner. i FAITH [CH. facts relating to the order of the universe and our place in it. And we shall see in the sequel that this conviction is not the result of a purely intellectual Judgment, but has a more vital origin. It involves an eager and loyal choice, a resolution to abide by the hypothesis that the nature of things is good, and on the side of goodness. That is to say, Faith, in the religious sense, is not simply belief ; it is inseparable from the sister virtues of hope and love.^ After this preliminary statement about the meaning of the word, I will proceed to sketch the historical growth of * Faith * as a theological concept. For it is a complex idea and has a history. Let us take first the history of the Greek words Trio-rts and 7n A. B. Davidson, The Theology of the Old Testament, p. 280. I.] * FAITH' AS A RELIGIOUS TERM 7 There is not a great deal about Faith in his writings : what there is, is chiefly with reference to the standard case of Abraham's Faith. ' Abraham,' he says, ' saw into the unfixedness and unsettledness of material being, when he recognised the unfaltering stability which attends true being, and to which he is said to have completely trusted.' * He anchored himself firmly and unchangeably on true being alone.' * The only thing stable is Faith toward God, or toward true being.' ^ Philo's ' Faith ' is thus a steady reliance on the eternal and unchangeable ideas of truth and righteousness, which lie behind the fleeting shows of phenomenal existence. The active sense has fairly' established itself, but Faith for Philo differs rather widely from the Christian virtue in that it is the prize ^ and not the starting-point of the race, standing at the end, not at the beginning, of the religious life. Sanday and Headlam ^ have a valuable note on the use of the word Faith in the apocryphal literature. In the Psalms of Solomon it is attributed to the Messiah Himself ; in the other books it is characteristic of his subjects. Thus 4 Esdras vi. 28, ' florebit fides et vincetur corruptela ' ; vii. 34, ' Veritas stabit et fides convalescet.' In the Apocalypse of Baruch we have, ' incredulis tormentum ignis reservatum.' In other places we have ' Faith and works ' in combination, indicating that the discussion of their relative merits did not originate in the Christian Church. We now come to the New Testament. I think that for our purposes it will be most convenient to take the Synoptic Gospels first, as a record of our Lord's actual teaching about, and attitude towards, Faith ; the Pauline con- ception of Faith next ; the Epistle to the Hebrews third ; 1 Cf. E. A. Abbott, Johannine Vocabulary. * Philo, De Praem. et Poen., ii. p, 412, 5t8aKTiKy XPV^^^M-^^^^ ipery rpdf TcKelwffiv AdXov alpeTrai rV irpbs tov Qebp TricrTir. * On Eomaus i. 17. 8 FAITH [cH. and the Johannine interpretation of our Lord's teaching last. This order is not intended to imply any disparage- ment of the Fourth Gospel as a historical document ; but St. John certainly wrote for his own generation, and it is possible to speak of a Johannine doctrine of Faith, which must not be taken out of its chronological place. The Triple Tradition does not agree in any saying of Christ containing the verb Trto-revctv ; and in the use of the substantive ttio-tis the only verbatim agreement is ' thy faith hath saved thee,' of the woman with the issue of blood. Nevertheless, there can be no doubt that our Lord spoke of ' Faith ' and * believing ' in the technical religious sense which is characteristic of the New Testament as a whole. There seems to be no objection on linguistic grounds. Not only did the Hebrew word acquire an active meaning in Rabbinical literature, but in the Aramaic dialect (according to Lightfoot on Galatians, p. 154), an active form had been developed. How far this language was original with Him, it is difficult to say. It is extremely probable that the words were often on the lips of the simple folk in Palestine who ' waited for the kingdom of God.' We have seen that all was ready for the richer doctrine of Faith which was part of Christ's message. The devout country people among whom He was brought up had not much to learn about confidence in God, about conviction of the reality of the unseen, or about patient waiting for the consolation of Israel. In the Synoptic Gospels, Faith generally means con- fidence in Christ's power to perform some particular thing. It would be superfluous to enumerate the cases in which Faith is mentioned as the condition of miracles of healing. In these instances. Faith is simply the psychological state which alone makes the patient susceptible to cures of this kind. There are, however, many passages, especially if we add the uses of the verb iria-Tevav to those of the sub- stantive, in which the wider sense of trustful self-surrender I.] « FAITH' AS A RELIGIOUS TERM 9 to Christ, or to God, is clearly indicated. There is only- one place in the Synoptics, I think (Matt, xxiii. 23), in which TTio-Tt? means ' integrity ' ; and so strong have its theological associations already become, that it is never used of man's faith in man. When it has an object, that object is in the genitive, as St. Mark xi. 22, ' have faith in God ' ; not with a preposition {ev, ei?, tt/oos, eVt) as in the Epistles. But in the large majority of cases, it is used absolutely. When ' Faith ' is primarily expectation of a miracle, a deeper thought is sometimes present. In the case of the paralytic, remission of sins precedes the physical cure (Matt. ix. 1-8) : and in Luke vii. 50 the characteristic words, ' thy Faith hath saved thee,' are used of forgiveness only, when there has been no miracle. Our Lord must have spoken much of the moral force of Faith, of what is now sometimes called the dynamic of religion. In the figurative and even hyperbolical language which He often used in popular teaching. He said that Faith, though no larger than a grain of mustard-seed, can remove mountains (Matt. xvii. 20), a phrase which became familiar to Chris- tians (1 Cor. xiii. 2) at a very early date. Cf. also Mark ix. 23 : * If thou canst believe, all things are possible to him that believeth.' That this Faith ought to be but is not always an abiding state is shown by the words to Peter (Luke xxii. 32), * I have prayed for thee, that thy Faith fail not.' There are some who ' for a while believe, but in time of temptation fall away ' (Matt. xiii. 20). In Matt. xvi. 17, * These signs shall follow them that believe,' we have an approximation to the use of the participle as a designation of the Christian society, ' the believers,' which we find in the Acts.^ One passage in the Synoptists seems to me to stand quite alone — Luke xviii. 8. * When the Son of Man cometh, shall 1 It is worth while also to call attention to Matt, xxiii. 23. 'justice, mercy and faith.' Cf. Micah ri. 8 of which these words may be a reminiscence. The third virtue, Faith, is added by Christ. 10 FAITH [cH. He find Faith * (or, the Faith) ' on the earth ? * I am unable to understand these words except in the sense that though God will avenge his saints ' speedily * (see the preceding verse), yet the time will appear so long before the second coming that the love of many will have waxed cold. ' Faith,' or * the Faith,* will hardly be found on the earth. 1 must confess that the words sound more like an expres- sion of the discouragement which we know to have been felt by the second and third generations of Christians, when * hope deferred ' of the Trapova-ia was * making the heart sick,' than what we should have expected to have from the lips of our Lord. If the words are authentic, we must take ' Faith ' (with the best orthodox commentators) in the less natural sense of ' the necessary Faith,' or * the Faith that perseveres in prayer.' To sum up : * Faith,' and ' to believe,' in the Synoptic Gospels, means a spirit of simple receptiveness towards the Messiah and His message, a state of mind which, unlike the righteousness of the Pharisees, requires no previous jcourse of discipline in meritorious actions. ' Faith ' is the primary motion of the human spirit when brought into contact with Divine truth and goodness. Its fruits are loyal self-devotion, even unto death, complete renunciation of all earthly ties, in so far as these could come between the disciple and his Master, untiring energy in service, and an enthusiastic temper, full of love, joy, and peace. This is really the whole content of Faith, as preached by Jesus to the simple folk whom He gathered round Him in Galilee. We next turn to St. Paul's Epistles. I do not wish to discuss the more technical theological problems connected with the Pauline doctrine of Faith, but only to determine what the word means for him. One of the most significant passages is Gal. iii. 23, 7r/o5 rod kXddv rrjv ttio-tli', 'before the coming of [the] Faith.' This expression proves that the Christians felt their * Faith ' to be something new in the world ; as new as their ' Love,' for which they required I.] * FAITH' AS A RELIGIOUS TERM 11 an almost new word in the Greek language, their * Hope,' which the pagans conspicuously lacked (Eph. ii. 12), and their * Joy,' which no man could take from them. The coming of Christ was the coming of [the] Faith. The Acts of the Apostles shows that the disciples soon began to call themselves * Believers ' ; it was one of the earliest names of the Christian society.^ Whether, as Lightfoot suggests,^ the name indicates ' The Trusty ' as well as ' The Trustful,' is uncertain ; the active meaning certainly predominates. The name was familiar to friends and foes in the time of Minucius Felix, who shows that it had been Latinised — * pistorum prsecipuus et postremus philosophus ' ^ — since ' credulus ' was impossible. The pagans in the time of Celsus employed it as an opprobrious term for their oppon- ents. In other places St. Paul uses ' the Faith ' almost as equivalent to the whole body of Christian doctrine and practice (Gal. i. 23 ; vi. 10, tovs oikciovs ttjs irt(rTca>s= the Church ; Rom. xii. 3, 6 ; Eph. iv. 1 3.) The coming of Christ was the beginning of the dispensa- tion of Faith, and the new virtue had found a name both in Greek and Aramaic. For the Jews, a bridge was found in the text about ' faithful Abraham,' which, as we have seen, was made to support a heavy superstructure of doctrine even by Philo, and was discussed with equal eagerness in the Rabbinical schools.* The meaning of Faith was being defined by controversy, and the concept was as yet so fluid that St. Paul and St. James can flatly contradict each other in words without differing much in meaning. St. Paul's theology, we are now beginning to see, must be interpreted by what we know of his personal religious experiences, which he naturally expounds by the help of current theological ideas and conceptions. Put very 1 Harnack, Expansion of Christianity^ ii. 6, ' Lightfoot, Galatians, p. 157. • There is a play on words here, between pistus and pistor. See the con- text, Octavius, 14. * Lightfoot, Qalatians, p. 159. 12 FAITH [CH. shortly, his doctrine of justification by Faith was arrived at somewhat in this way. Jewish thought knew of two, and only two, roads to salvation. One was by natural descent from Abraham. This belief was discredited for various reasons. It was unethical ; it was falsified by history ; and it was contradicted by religious experience. The other was by righteousness. This St. Paul had tried and found wanting. Justifying righteousness was un- attainable ; the verdict against the claimant was a fore- gone conclusion. The good news of the Gospel was the assurance of a free pardon to all who would ' believe.' God will reckon their ' Faith ' as righteousness. Remem- bering the other and older theory as to the title to salvation, descent from Abraham, he represents this saving grace also as * adoption * to sonship, through faith in Christ Jesus (Gal. iii. 26). The true Israel, then, are the adopted ' chil- dren of Abraham,' and their faith in Christ is accepted instead of the impossible requirement of legal righteousness. The Christian, therefore, has a double title to salvation : he is a son and heir by adoption, and, by the free grace of God through Christ, he is accounted to have fulfilled the law of righteousness. The one condition is ' Faith.' Now what is this Faith ? Not the mere fiducia (subjective assurance) of Lutheranism, even if this theory can support itself plausibly by certain expressions in St. Paul's writings. We*'must remember that at this time Faith involved the open acceptance of Christianity, adhesion, in the face of the world, to a persecuted sect. St. Paul never even con- templated an inner state of confidence in God's mercies through Christ that did not exhibit itself in this overt, decisive, initial step. * If thou shalt confess with thy mouth the Lord Jesus, and believe in thine heart that God hath raised Him from the dead, thou shalt be saved.' ^ And assuredly Faith included also a changed life » Rom. X. 9. I.] 'FAITH' AS A KELIGIOUS TERM 13 as a member of the new society.^ In short, we must beware of forgetting the very different terms on which a subjective confidence in the merits of Christ's death may be held now and in St. Paul's time. What St. Paul dreads, and protests against in his Epistles to the Romans and Galatians, is a baptized Pharisaism which would remain in all essentials pre-Christian. He is determined that Faith shall not lose its new active meaning, as a decisive moral act of trust ; he dreads that it may become again Jewish and passive, a mere fidelity to the terms of a covenant. He is fighting for the new content of the word Faith, as a Christian virtue. But it is as a Christian virtue bound up inextricably with the other Christian virtues, and especially with Love, which is its proper activity or €i/6/oycia (Gal. V. 6), that he claims such importance for it. This consideration, that ' Faith ' in St. Paul includes not only subjective trust in Christ's promises, but all that such trust necessarily led to, in an honest and consistent man, at that time, that is, that it included public relinquish- ment of paganism or Judaism, and adhesion to the Chris- tian Church at a time when the Christians were regarded as the scum of the earth (1 Cor. iv. 13), will help us to understand, in particular, what Faith in the atoning blood of Christ meant for St. Paul. I will not now discuss the sacrificial aspect of Christ's death. But it is right to insist that the key to the whole of St. Paul's Christology is the doctrine of the mystical union of the believer with his Lord, which is for him the necessary fulfilment of the life of^ Faith. To understand the Pauline doctrine of justifica- tion by Faith as summed up in such ideas as ' resting in the finished work of the Redeemer,' or any other detach- ment of Christ for us from Christ in us, is an unfortunate 1 Dobschiitz {Christian Life in the Primitive Church, p. 368 seq.) has justly •mphasised the remarkable standard of moral purity which was demanded and, on the whole, attained in the primitive Church. 14 FAITH [CH. mistake. The * whole process of Christ ' must be ro- enacted in the experience of the beUever, and the culmina- tion of the whole is spiritual crucifixion and resurrection. * The new and significant peculiarity,' says Pfleiderer,^ * in Paul's conception of Faith, is the mystical union with Christ, the self-identification with Christ in a fellow- ship of life and death. In this unreserved, self-forgetting surrender of the whole man to the Saviour, in which the revelation of the Divine love, as well as the embodi- ment of the ideal for man, is beheld as a personal life, the believer feels himself to be ' a new creature. . . . That is expressed in the fine saying : " It is no longer I that live, but Christ that liveth in me ; and the life that I now live in the flesh I live in the Faith of the Son of God, who loved me and gave Himself for me." Life in the Faith means the same as " Christ liveth in me." * In Romans xiv.. Faith is represented as a graduated pro- gress in the mind of Christ. ' Weakness in the Faith ' shows itself by anxiety to keep formal rules, by super- stition, in fact. * Faith to eat all things ' is a strong Faith. So in Colossians, feasts and fast-days are ' shadows of things to come.' This chapter contains also the declaration (v. 23), * whatever is not of Faith, is sin ' ; which has been taken out of its context and made to support the conten- tion that * the virtues of the heathen were splendid vices,' or that ' all works done before Justification are sinful.' St. Paul, however, appears only to mean that in matters of abstinence or indulgence we ought to have a clear conscience. The half - superstitious man is likely to wound his conscience, whether he keeps his fast or breaks it. J In the well-known words, * We walk by Faith, not by sight ' (2 Cor. v. 7), St. Paul means, as the context shows, that the form (crSos) of the exalted Christ is hidden from us. Faith is the condition of our present life (Sid Trio-Tecus 1 Primitive Christianity, vol. i. p. 347. 1.] * FAITH' AS A RELIGIOUS TERM 15 vipiTraTovnev), as ' seeing face to face ' will be our condition in the future life. Then Faith will not be abolished, but will become eternal (1 Cor. xiii. 13). Faith, for St. Paul, blends with hope, and is almost identified with it (Rom. xv. 13 ; iv. 18-21 ; viii. 24). Hope adds joy and peace to believing ; it has a moral basis, and may even be identified with the Christ in us (Col. i. 27). One other important aspect of Faith in St. Paul's Epistles must be mentioned before we pass on to the Epistle to the Hebrews. In Faith, as St. Paul understands it, lie the roots both of new ethical power and of a deeper knowledge of God.^ Practical and theoretical Christianity are both contained in it. The Christian stands fast in the A Faith (1 Cor. xvi. 13), but also grows in Faith, and attains ' the stature of the perfect man by coming ' unto the unity of the Faith, and of the knowledge of the Son of God ' (Eph. iv. 13). Behind the Rabbinical subtleties, which we find here and there in St. Paul's Epistles, we can trace plainly enough a sublime and profound conception of Faith, which may well be our guide in our coming investigation. The Author of the Epistle to the Hebrews has done for Faith what St. Paul has done for Love in 1 Cor. xiii. The eleventh chapter of the Epistle is a hymn in honour of Faith. It begins with the famous definition 4'o-Ttv Se ttlo-tis ek-jn^ofievcov virocTTao-LSj TTpay/xoLTiov €X€y\os ov fSXiTrofieviov. * Now Faith is the assurance of [or, the giving substance to] things hoped for, the proving [or, test] of objects not seen.' (R.V.) HtcrTts has here no article. This is signifi- cant ; for in this Epistle Faith is not the Christian Faith, but a psychological faculty. In this sense it is as wide as the human mind, and even Rahab may be adduced as an example of it. The meaning both of vTroo-Tao-is and of IAeyxo5 is disputed. For the former, the Revised Version gives the preference to * assurance,' a meaning which is 1 Pfleiderer, ibid., p. 350. 16 FAITH [CH. also assigned to it, probably rightly, in iii. 14, * We are become partakers of Christ if we hold fast the beginning of our confidence {rrjv apx^jv rrj^ vTrocTTacrcws) firm unto the end.' The Greek Fathers say that 17 dpxrj Trj Contra Gentiles, i. 3. 32 FAITH [cH. which entirely transcend human knowledge, but it is not confined to what is essentially beyond our faculties. There are truths, such as the existence of God, which are capable of demonstration, but only by a course of reason which few have brains enough to follow ; and therefore God has revealed them. The distinction between reason and revelation corresponds to the distinction between knowledge and Faith. Faith comes between opinion and knowledge ; it involves an act of the will. ' The intellect,' he says, ' assents to a thing in two ways, in one way because it is moved to assent by the object itself, which is known by itself, or by something else ; in the other way the intellect assents to a thing, not because it is sufficiently moved to assent by the object itself, but by a certain choice, by which it voluntarily inclines to one side rather than the other. If this choice is made from doubt and fear of the alternative, it is opinion ; if with certainty and without fear, it is Faith.' ^ He also says that the objective ground of Faith is authority, of knowledge, reason. And since the authority is divine truth, it may be said that Faith has a greater certainty than knowledge, which relies on human reason.^ Since, however, the objects of Faith are less fully apprehended, being above the intellect of man, knowledge from another point of view is more certain than Faith. The certainty of Faith, on one side, comes from the will, which is guided by ' Veritas prima sive \ Deus.* Faith, however, is not an act of arbitrary choice.f; it presupposes some knowledge : ' cognitio fidei proBSupponit cognitionem naturalem siciU et natura gratiam.^ Faith cannot demonstrate what it believes ; else it would be knowledge and not Faith ; but it does investigate the grounds by which a man is led to believe — e.g. that the words were spoken by God.* 1 Be Veritate, Quaest. xiv., art. 1. • SumTna TheoL, 2. 2, qu. 4, art. 9, * De Veritate, Quaest. xiv., art. 9. < SumTna Theol., 2. 2, qu. 1, art. 4. II.] * FAITH' AS A RELIGIOUS TERM 83 It is plain from these passages that Faith, for St. Thomas Aquinas, necessarily involves both an intellectual and a moral act ; and also, I think, that he has shrunk from subjecting the basis of Church authority to a searching scrutiny. The practical question which we all have to face is whether we ought to allow ' the will to believe ' to influence us in our choice of authorities — e.g. whether we may choose to follow the authority of the Church m pre- ference to that of a naturalist or metaphysician. St. Thomas Aquinas says that the will is guided by ' the primary Truth, which is God.' If so, Faith would seem to be only the human side of divine grace, immanent in the human mind ; and it must be ultimately independent of and superior to all external authority, even that of the Church, The authority of the Church can only be ac- cepted as final on the further assumption that the donum veritatis belongs to one institution and one only. With the Reformation, controversy about the meaning of Faith became, for the second time in the historj?- of the Church, acute. Every one knows that * Justification by Faith ' was the corner-stone of Luther's doctrinal system. His own account of the process by which he found the light is as follows. When he first read the words of the Epistle to the Romans, iustitia Dei in eo revelatur^ he said to him- self, ' Is it not enough that WTetched sinners, already damned for original sin, should be overwhelmed by so many calamities by the decrees of the Ten Command- ments, but God must threaten us, even in His Gospel, with His justice and anger ? ' But at last, he says, * I perceived that the justice of God is that whereby, with God's blessing, man fives, namely, Faith. Thereupon I felt as if bom again, and it seemed to me that the gates of heaven stood wide open.' It is not easy to see how the justice, or righteousness, of God can be identified with Faith, if Faith has a human side at all ; but Luther found ineffable peace in the thought that those who, through 34 FAITH [cH, Faith in Christ as the revelation of God's righteousness, have accepted Him, are clothed with a righteousness not their own — with the righteousness of Christ imputed to them. The form of this doctrine is derived chiefly from the Epistle to the Romans, studied in Latin with St. Augustine's commentary. In the sixteenth century, how- ever, it was a crucial question, What is the proper instru- ment of justification ? This ' justification ' (to ' justify ' means to pronounce righteous,^ by judicial decree, but with no suggestion of a legal fiction) was regarded as the applica- tion of the merits of Christ to the individual, which applica- tion, it was agreed on all hands, must be through an instru- ment divinely appointed. An important passage, often appealed to, in Clement of Rome,^ says : ' We also are not justified by ourselves, neither by our own wisdom or knowledge or piety or any works which we did in holiness of heart, but by that Faith in which God Almighty has justified all men from the beginning.' Both sides were also agreed that Faith justifies. But the Catholics distinguished between fides informis, inert opinion, and fides formata, which is perfected by the love and good works which spring from it. Among the proposi- tions anathematised by the Council of Trent were : that a man may be justified without grace : that man is justified only by the imputation of the justice of Christ, or only by the remission of sins, without inherent grace, or charity : that justifying Faith is nothing but confidence in the mercy of God, who forgives sins for the sake of Christ : that man is absolved and justified because he firmly believes that he is absolved and Justified. On the other hand, the Reformers held that Faith is the one principle which God's grace uses for restoring us to His favour. We need a radical change, which change is 1 As in Clirysostom's comment : ' When a just judge's sentence pronounces us just {SiKalovs 6,To^lhings in and through the Infinite, and of all temporal Things in and IV.] FAITH AS PURE FEELING 69 through the Eternal. J Religion is to have and know life only in immediate feeling, as existing in the infinite and eternal. Where this is found, religion is satisfied ; where it hides itself, she is in anguish and disquietude. Religion is not knowledge or science, either of the world or of God. The pious man, as pious, knows nothing about ethical science. It is the same with action itself. While morality always appears as manipulating, as self-controlling, piety appears as a surrender, a submission to be moved by the Whole that stands over against man. The pious man may not know at all, but he cannot know falsely. His nature is reality which knows reality. True religion is a sense and taste of the Infinite. If a man is not one with the Eternal, in the unity of intuition and feeling which is immediate, he remains for ever apart.' Schleiermacher reserves his keenest scorn for those who make religion ancillary to morality. ' A high praise it would be for the heavenly one, if she could only look after the earthly affairs of men in this poor fashion ! Great honour for her, to quicken men's consciences a little, and make them more careful ! What is loved and valued only for an advantage that lies outside it is not essentially necessary, and a reason- able man will put no higher price upon it than the value of the end for which it is desired. And I cannot attach much importance to the wrong acts which it prevents in this way, nor to the right acts which it is said to procure. What I maintain is that piety springs up, necessarily and spontaneously, from the inward parts of every better soul, that she has in the heart a province of her own, where she bears unobstructed sway, and that she is worthy to be welcomed and acknowledged by the noblest and most excellent, for her own inner nature's sake.' ^ Faith, theik, for Schleiermacher, is a spontaneous, im- 1 The English reader will find a useful and characteristic selection from Schleiermacher's writings in Caldecott and Mackintosh, Selections from the Literature of Theism, pp. 256-304. 60 FAITH [CH. mediate feeling of the Infinite and Eternal, with which the human spirit identifies itself. The feeling must be wholly general and undifferentiated. He bids us to ponder on our own experiences, but not to analyse them. ' You must know how to listen to yourselves before your own con- sciousness. What you are to notice is the rise of your own consciousness, and not to reflect upon something already there. As soon as you have made any definite activity ^f your soul an object of contemplation, you have begun to separate. The more your own state sways you, the paler and more unrecognisable the image becomes.' * Ideas and principles are all foreign to religion.' ' Religion by itself does not urge men to activity at all.' Doctrinal proposi- tions, he came to believe and to teach, are only descriptions of pious states of consciousness. They are secondary products. These quotations will give you an idea of what this conception of Faith or Religion as immediate intuition of the Infinite means. It not only finds but leaves us ex- tremely vague as to the contents of Faith. Whether a man represents the Infinite Being as personal or impersonal depends, says Schleiermacher, on whether his tendency is towards a voluntaristic or an intellectual view of things. He himself, it would appear, believed neither in a personal God nor in individual immortafity, though he expresses himself very cautiously on both subjects. Another classical example of Intuitionism is Jacobi (1743-1819), who, being more of a philosopher than a theologian, advocates the emotional ground of religion from an external and (one might almost say) an intellec- tualist standpoint. He has been called ' a pantheist in head and a mystic in heart ' ; but it appears to me th^t he maintains intuitionism largely from a perception of its strategic advantages in controversy. It is hard to refute a man who declares that he has received private and authentic information that what he says is true. Jacobi FAITH AS PURE FEELING 61 holds that Just as we apprehend the sensible world by our bodily senses, so we apprehend the spiritual world by another organ, to which he gives different names.^ God requires no proof, for His existence is more evident to us than our own. * If God were not immediately present to us through His image in our hearts, what is these which could make Him known to us ? A revelation through external phenomena can at best only stand in the same relation to that which is internal and original, as that in which speech stands to reason. Just as man feels himself, and pictures himself to himself, so, only with greater power, he represents to himself the Godhead.' It is plain that for Jacobi the only source of our knowledge of God is an intense inner consciousness, unaided by reflective thought, by moral effort, or by knowledge of the external world. He is not afraid to deduce from this self-consciousness, not only the existence of a transcendent God, but the other two dogmas which to Kantians are fundamental — freedom and immortality. How these truths can be proved by immediate feeling he nowhere tries to explain, nor, I fear, is any explanation possible. Jacobi, as I have said, gives different names to the faculty by which we apprehend supersensual truth. Sometimes he calls it the Reason. It is not easy to classify intuition- ists who claim an immediate, a priori knowledge which is different from feeling ; but perhaps this is the best place to deal with them. This position has been taken by several well-known writers, among whom we may name the American divine, Theodore Parker. It is * refuted,' under the name of ' ontologism,' by the very able Jesuit philo- sopher, Boedder.2 The claim of ' ontologism ' is that the mind of man, by its very nature, has a certain direct con- 1 E.g, * Glatibenskraft iiber die Vernunft ' : 'Geistesgefiihl.' 'Reason, 'he says elsewhere,/ is the faculty of assuming the absolutely True, Good, and Beautiful, -with the full persuasion of the objective validity of this assump- tion.' * Boedder, Ifattvral Theology, pp. 12-29. 62 FAITH [cH. sciousness of the existence, and of some of the attributes, of God. If this were true, no effort, it would seem, could be needed to realise God's presence in relation to His creatures ; for it is in relation to His creatures that the alleged consciousness belongs to us. It is difficult to under- stand the grounds of a ' rational certainty ' which can give no account of itself. The certainty of the ' ontologist,' which he calls immediate apprehension, has the appearance rather of ' voluntary certainty,' pure choice, in which case he classifies himself wrongly, or of a mixture of will and feeling illegitimately used to establish matters of fact (the Ritschlian value-judgment intruding into metaphysics). In short, immediate certainty, which does not rest upon feeling, is Uttle more than a refusal to listen to arguments on the other side. The error of * ontologism,' from the standpoint of these lectures, is its refusal to admit the necessity of an act of Faith. The Beatific Vision which we hope for will be an immediate perception of God, and Faith confidently anticipates this consummation ; but neither feeling nor any ill-defined and mysterious special faculty can make Faith superfluous by giving us at once the immediate apprehension which is to be our final reward. A more recent example of Intuitionism is to be found in the philosophy of Lotze, with whom it is a desperate expedient to escape the pure subjectivity and phenomenal- ism in which his theory of knowledge threatens to land him. Like many other German thinkers he appears to confound the feeling of value with the judgment of value. There can be no judgment of any kind without an intellec- tual process. Wherever the ' feeling of value ' has any well-defined contents, the intellect has been at work. In France, A. Reville holds that ' Religion rests on a sentiment, sui generis and spontaneous.' He follows Schleiermacher, but insists very rightly that this * senti- ment ' is not merely a feeling of dependence, but a feeling of 7anity. This sentiment, he says, gives a certain valua- IV.] FAITH AS PUEE FEELING 63 Hon, which * imagination and thought ' translate into the idea of God. De Pressense postulates a ' Verbe Interieur ' as the source of ' religious sentiment.' The theology of pure Feeling has not been largely repre- sented in this country, which has generally been distrustful of sentiment. The great eighteenth-century mystic, William Law, approaches this type, in consequence of his distrust of ' Reason,' ^ but he does not belong to it, because he has a very firm grasp of the truth that Faith must be lived into. When he became a mystic he did not forget the austere morality of the Serious Call. ' The truth of Christianity,' he says at the end of his treatise on The Way to Divine Knowledge, ' is the Spirit of God hving and work- ing in it ; and where the Spirit is not the life of it, there the outward form is but like the outward carcase of a departed soul. For the spiritual fife is as much its own proof as the natural life, and needs no outward or foreign thing to bear witness to it.' Robert Browning, in later life, seems to preach a purely emotional theism. Such hnes as : — Wholly distrust thy knowledge, then, and trust As wholly love allied to ignorance ; or : — ^ So let us say — not, Since we know, we love, 'But rather, Since we love, we know enough, are indeed startling from the most learned of our poets. 1 Examples of Law's /iiaoKoyla (the only blot on his fine and manly religious writings) may be found in The Way to Divine Knowledge, e.g. , p. 51. ' Reason is so far from being able to help man to that knowledge, which his nature and condition wants, that it can only help his ignorance to increase and fructify in doubts, fictions, and absurd debates. And the thing cannot be otherwise . Man must walk in a vain shadow, so long as Reason is his guide. . . . He who turns to his reason, as the true power and light of his nature, betrays the same ignorance of the whole nature, power, and oflice of reason, as if he was to try to smell with his eyes or see with his nose. For reason has only its one work or power, which it cannot alter nor exceed ; and that one work is to be a bare observer and comparer of things that manifest themselves to it by the senses,' etc. Law cannot be confounded with the anti-mystical moralists ; his rejection of reason, therefore, implies a reliance on pure in- tuition, though it is a progressive intuition, conditioned by growth in grace. 64 FAITH [CH. Such an attitude can only be explained as a resolute ad- herence to moral and emotional optimism, in spite of a growing intellectual pessimism.^ We may now attempt to answer our question, What is the rank and value of this immediate feeling of the Divine, which psychologically, at any rate, is a well-estabUshed fact of experience ? Schleiermacher tells us that this feeling is present * in almost every better soul.' This, I think, is true ; for it is, as I have said, an essential part of prayer. All religious people pray ; and all, I suppose, have a vivid conscious- ness, at times, that prayer is not merely a soliloquy, but a form of intercourse with a higher Being. But it is surely significant that the mystics, with one consent, tell us that these * consolations ' — this vivid consciousness of the presence of God — are most common at the beginning of the spiritual ascent. The young aspirant after holiness may expect them at first, but he must also expect that after a time they will be withdrawn. The best spiritual guides warn their consultants not to attach too much importance to them. This fact, so contrary to what might have been expected and desired, seems to indicate that immediate feeling of the Deity is characteristic of an early and un- developed stage of the religious life.^ Its very emptiness gives it a mysterious attractiveness, bom of awe and curiosity ; but in the normal course, the purely mystical intuition partially loses itself for a time in the multipUcity of the tasks which it enjoins, and only draws together again when its work is near its close. Nevertheless, we must not forget that there have been many religious geniuses in whom this immediate * feeling and taste * of the Eternal, to use Schleiermacher's phrase, has been the most intense experience of their lives, persist- 1 Cf. my Studies of English Mystics, pp. 224-5. 2 The strict Quietists, however {e.g. Molinos), regard the withdrawal of these consolations as a call to ascend into a still more rarefied atmosphere. C/. The SpvrUxuU Guide, passim. IV.] FAITH AS PURE FEELING 66 ing through all stages of their spiritual growth. A large collection of evidence on this subject has been made by a Canadian writer, Dr. Bucke, in a very queer book called Cosmic Consciousness. The author maintains that Cosmic Consciousness is a higher degree of perception which is being slowly evolved in the progress of the race, just as the sense of colour is a recent acquisition, which was possessed only in a rudimentary manner by the ancient Greeks and the authors of the Indian sacred literature. At present, the feeling is weak and fitful, and manifests itself in an almost infinite range of intensity. Very many can go no further, from their own experience, than to endorse the well-known lines of Browning : — Oh, we 're sunk enough here, God knows ! But not quite so sunk that moments, Sure tho' seldom, are denied us, When the spirit's true endowments Stand out plainly from its false ones, And apprise it if pursuing Or the right way or the wrong way, To its triumph or undoing. Or, as suggested by Wordsworth's famous Ode, they may remember a time when the vision, which has now faded into the light of common day, was frequently with them. But this higher faculty, so our author thinks, has begun to appear sporadically, in the most advanced specimens of the race, as an assured possession, and it is becoming more frequent as the centuries go on. Out of many hundreds of cases, which he considers authentic, he selects thirteen which are * so great that they can never fade from human memory.' This odd list consists of Buddha, Jesus Christ, St. Paul, Plotinus, Mohammed, Dante, Las Casas, St. John of the Cross, Shakespeare (whom he chooses to call Bacon), Bohme, Blake, Balzac, and Walt Whitman. The book, in spite of the author's critical vagaries, is full of interest to the psychologist, and I am not disposed to B 66 FAITH [cH, dispute the main thesis, that if the conditions of civilised life ever promote the improvement of the race, instead of its deterioration, as I fear they do at present, the man of the future may be able to live habitually and consciously in a larger air than is possible to any except the most favoured spirits at the present time. But the important question for us now is, whether this immediate perception of the Eternal is capable of forming the contents of Faith, or whether in fact it has any con- tents at all until it has been translated into thought, will, and action. ' Pure feeling,' says Professor Flint curtly but truly, ' is pure nonsense.' Schleiermacher's conception of Faith is anything but ' simple feeling ' ; it is a highly elaborate product of the peculiar ideas of his age. And even so, it is very empty. I have already mentioned the hlankness of the picture, which is insisted on by Schleier- macher. This, as is well known, is a common feature of mystical literature. The pure mystical state (which even William James says is identical with the Faith-state) is without form and void. But ideas must be given through something ; there can be no purely internal revelation, just as there can be no purely external revelation. Some mystics have claimed that they have got beyond forms and differences, which are the mark of the transitory pheno- menal world, and that the undifferentiated feeling which they prize so much is an intuition of the unity which under- lies all difference. Others only lament that they cannot utter what they have seen and felt : — O could I tell, ye surely would believe it ! O could I only say what I have seen ! How should I tell, or how can ye receive it, How, till He bringeth you where I have been.^ But there is all the difference between a Unity which excludes all difference, and a Unity which includes all 1 Myers, St. Paul. IV.] FAITH AS PURE FEELING 67 difference. And I cannot doubt that many mystics have beheved themselves to have completed their journey when in reality they have not even begun it. Faith, which Philo, as we have seen, puts at the end of the journey, should, as Christian theology has always maintained, be placed at its beginning. Faith and Love, says Clement, are not taught or teachable (ra a.Kpa ov StSao-Kcrai) ; but between Faith, which is the starting-point of the Christian race, and the perfect Love that casteth out fear, which is its end, there is a long series of lessons which have to be learned. Feeling is the mirror which reflects ideas and ideals. It has been defined as the ' passive echo in consciousness of the unconscious psychical process.' ^ It creates nothing ; it seems to project ideas and ideals, because it reflects unconscious motions of thought and will. Feeling in itself is neither good nor bad, true nor untrue.^ It is simply a fact of the soul-life. Its truth depends on the truth of the idea which determines it ; its goodness on the goodness of the motive which is bound up with it. Schleiermacher, in his later editions of Eeden uber die Religion, smuggles in Anschauung, the most primitive form of ideation, into his conception of Feeling ; in the earlier he admits Anschauung by the side of Feeling, as a religious function. This enables him to speak of the ' truth of Feeling,' determined by the truth of the contents of the idea. But ' pure Feeling ' does not include any form of ideation. In fact, religious feeling (much feeling is not religious) is only aroused by religious ideas of objective truth and value. ' Mere dependence ' is nonsense, unless there is a known object on which to depend. It is, therefore, in my opinion, a mistake to regard the primary ground of Faith, the immediate feeling of an eternal world, as sufficient. Feeling is formless and life- 1 Von Hartiuann. 2 So Hegel says : ' That anything is in our feeling proves nothing good about the thing itself. The most royal flower blooms there side by side 'witli the most mischievous weed.' 68 FAITH [cH. j less ; it gives us no definite beliefs, and prescribes no I definite duties. Even the three aspects which I have I mentioned, the good, the true, and the beautiful, are, I strictly speaking, products of reflexion on the spontaneous / instinct ; they are the first applications of it to life. And inoreover, the affirmations of this primary instinct, wrongly identified with feeling, need sifting and testing ; they are not all ready to take shape as determinations of the good, the true, and the beautiful. The world into which the Cosmic Consciousness, to use Bucke's word, admits us, is not purely a better world, though it is a larger one. It is hell as well as heaven. This the mystics who have tried to fix the immediacy of feeling as the basis of their moral and spiritual life, have found to their cost. The great problem which has confronted them has been how to distinguish between the genuine irruptions of the Divine into their consciousness, and what they were constrained to regard as diabolical imitations. For those who denied themselves the aid of the discursive intellect, of the will, and of practical tests, there was no satisfactory solution of this problem, and they were frequently tormented through life by doubts whether their most intimate spiritual experiences were not sometimes wiles of the Evil One for their undoing. In primitive reHgions, even more than in the discipline of the mystics, deliberate attempts are made to fix this immediacy of rehgious feeling, without analysing or developing it, and to render it more intense by various artificial means, empirically discovered. I do not include prayer among these means, because I doubt whether this highest of our privileges can be resorted to, even in an ignorant manner, without some real gain. But fasting, and other ascetical exercises, have been and are used with the object of intensifying vague religious emotion, without unravelling or transmuting it. The self-induced trance of quietistic mysticism, procured by such methods as IV.] FAITH AS PUKE FEELING 69 gazing intently at a luminous chink or even on some part of one's own body (the navel among the monks of Mount Athos, the tip of the nose with some Indian contemplatives), is one method of hypnotisation. Religious music and orgiastic dancing are also very potent methods of achieving this result. I will quote part of Rohde's description of the Thracian worship of Dionysus.^ ' The rite was performed on hilltops, in the darkness of night, by the doubtful light fof torches. Amid the sound of music, the clashing of brazen cymbals, the rolling thunder of a great drum, and the deep note of the flute *' enticing to madness," the band of worshippers danced over the hillside in a whirling, raving, rushing circle. When their emotions were raised to the highest pitch, they hurled themselves upon the beast chosen for sacrifice. This powerful intensification of feeling had a religious meaning, in that only through such overstrain and expansion of his being did man feel I^^able to come into touch with the god and his attendant ^■spirits.' ' Emotion carries its own credentials with it ' ; ^ and by such methods the undifferentiated primary emotion of Faith may be stimulated to a pitch which may leave abiding traces on the mind. This is one of the most important empirical discoveries about the religious emotion which man has made. The result of employing it is to arrest the development of Faith at a very early stage. This kind of religion may be Intense ; it may become the predominant interest in life ; but it can hardly produce any of the proper fruits of Faith : it is an abortive Faith, a monstrosity and a perversion. The undifferentiated Faith-state was not given us to use or enjoy in this way. It must be developed, rendered explicit, unravelled, as it were, through will, thought an^ appropriate action. The result of deliberately playing upon the emotions in 1 Rohde, Psyche, ii. pp. 18-20. • Pratt, Psychology of Religious Belief, p. 62. 70 FAITH [CH. the manner described is often seen in terrible reactions. If the joys of the ecstatic state are (as is said by some who have experienced them) too great to be described, so also are the miseries of ' dereliction,' and the hallucinations of religious melancholy. Every fanatical ' revival * produces a crop of insanity. The normal development of religion is calm and self-collected, though deep and strong. Re- ligious feeUng, if not abused, pricks us with a sense of our imperfection, and forces us to seek, through thought and will, for the cause of our disquiet and for a means of satisfying our need. l' The normal history of religious feeling is summed up in \rthe words, Fear, Dependence, Love. Assuredly none of rthe three is ' pure feeUng ' ; but I am protesting all through these lectures against separating our faculties in this way. Love is the crown of the soul's victory, and love, though it contains intellectual and moral elements, is primarily an emotion. Christianity has seemed to many to give the last word to the affections or emotions, by its exaltation of love as the only gift that * never faileth ' ; and certainly love is the only virtue which we can imagine as persisting without much change in the eternal world, when faith shall have become sight, hope been turned into satis- faction, and knowledge into contemplation. ^'''^Love is implicit in Faith from the first. As aesthetics is ya power of recognising beauty practically inseparable from the love of beauty ; as ethics is a power of recognising the morally right practically inseparable from the love of right, so the aim of theology is an intellectual recognition of God practically inseparable from the love of God. And so Augustine is right when he says that a man's spiritual state may be best gauged not by what lie knows, but by what he loves.^ J Pascal's ' Human things need only be known in order to be loved, but divine things must first be loved in order to be known,' is valuable, but needi safeguarding, as making the acquisition of dirine knowledge too independent of rational thought FAITH AS PURE FEELING 71 But if Faith thus loses itself at last in Love, Love must not, like mere feeling, be immediate at a level below dis- tinction and relation. The religion of feeling cannot be- come true till it has passed through the crucible of the will and the intellect. Our problem is to find the intellectual and volitional equivalents of this vague religion of feeling, certainly not to regard it as a third stage, destined to override the intellect.^ In the following lectures I shall try to consider in what manner, and under what limitations, the activities of the will and intellect, brought to bear upon the spontaneous Faith-state, which Professor Baldwin calls ' reality-feeling ' as opposed to self-conscious belief, may conduct us towards a unified spiritual experience, in which the contradictions and divisions which analysis brings to light may be par- tially reconciled. But there is one other principle, besides the intellectual and practical, which is of immense import- ance. This is the principle of Authority, the effect of which as a secondary ground of Faith, determining its form and content, can hardly be overestimated. Rehgion is a racial afiFair, and authority is the principle of continuity, the memory of the race. I think, therefore, that a discussion of authority in relation to Faith should take precedence even of the practical and intellectual grounds of behef. * As {e.g.) Pratt does in his Psychology 0/ Religious Bdi^. FAITH [cH. CHAPTER V ; AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH ,'To class Authority as a secondary ground of Faith is »- procee ding which needs some defence. For it is certain that in individual experience Authority is the earUest ground of behef . We are none of us born with a behef in God ; but we are all bom with a tendency to believe what we are told. A child can be made to believe almost anything. He does not believe because he wishes to beheve, or because the things presented to him for acceptance appear to him to be useful or beautiful or desirable in any way. He is quite as ready to believe in ghosts and hobgoblins as in angels and good fairies. As he began to speak by parrot- talk, so he begins to think by accepting facts without criticising them, and assumes that whatever he hears and understands has a place in the world of reality. It is only after sad experience of the deceitfulness of appearances that he unlearns his first confidence, and begins to doubt and question and disbelieve. This natural tendency to believe what we are told remains with us, though more or less impaired by experi- ence, through life. Some may protest that no one except a young child believes anything merely because he is told, without any thought of the trustworthiness of the author- ity ; but I am convinced that this is a mistake. A great many grown persons will accept almost any statements put before them (not on all subjects, of course, but on some subjects) from pure inertia, because it is easier for them to believe than to disbefieve. Some popular superstitions, T.] AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 73 which show such astonishing vitaHty, must be trans- mitted and accepted in this lazy fashion. Such notions as that it is unlucky to walk under a ladder, or to be married in May, could not survive a moment's thought about the value of the evidence in their favour. They are simply taken at their face value, with no questions asked. If pure credulity is an actual cause of belief, even in cases where disproof is possible and easy, we cannot be surprised that it is largely instrumental in forming beliefs about the unseen world, where no contradiction from experience is possible. Among savages, myths about gods and spirits are handed down from father to son, and believed implicitly. They become part of the mental capital of the tribe or nation, and any attempt to damage their credit is visited with great indignation. This is quite natural. When an * old master ' has been in a family for generations, the owner is not likely to be grateful for being told that it is a sham. Or if he has acquired it himself without asking questions, and has frequently spoken of it as undoubtedly genuine, he will be at least equally un- willing to admit that he has been deceived. As a general rule, we say a thing for the first time because we have heard some one else say it, and stick to it because we have said it ourselves. It follows that the diffusion and persistence of a belief is not always a presumption in favour of its truth. Many beliefs, which are purely silly and destitute of any founda- tion, have been kept alive by mere credulity, even in Europe, for thousands of years. When a superstition once establishes itself, it does not become any more respectable by growing old. Its antiquity gives it a sort of prestige which helps to keep it alive, but adds nothing to its weight. For instance, all housemaids everywhere believe that you can make a fire burn by tilting a poker against the bars. I dare say this curious manoeuvre was originally an attempt 74 FAITH [cii. to make the sign of the cross, and so conjure the fire to burn ; but for centuries it has been a purely irrational superstition. Or take the cock-and-lion story, solemnly told by Aristotle — that the lion is afraid of the cock. This superstition lasted till Cuvier at last thought of putting a cock into a lion's cage, with results fatal to the cock. Intel- lectual indolence has perpetuated a great many bits of antiquated science. The history of popular quack remedies supplies a mass of instances of a highly instructive kind ; for the same mental attitude which leads uneducated people to resort to quacks when they are ill makes them victims of religious imposture when they are in trouble about their souls. Excessive reverence for tradition, deference to the opinions of our forefathers, * who had more wit and wisdom than we,' must be distinguished from mere credulity. This reverence for the supposed wisdom of the past, which we find everywhere in primitive societies, must have been very useful in the early stages of civilisation, when the difficulty of preserving the hardly-won gains of humanity was far greater than at present. The tendency to put the golden age in the past may have been caused partly by a con- sciousness of the real sacrifices which civilisation entails. The fruit of the tree of knowledge, as I have said elsewhere,^ always expels us from some paradise or other, even if it be only the paradise of fools. And when the art of writing was discovered, a superstitious veneration for the written word was universal, and so persistent that I do not think it is extinct yet. If the words of wisdom were enshrined in verse, that made the glamour even more potent. The old Greek sentiment about the inspiration of poets sur- vived to the end of the classical period. ' To the poets sometimes,' says Dion Chrysostom, — ' I mean the very ancient poets — there came a brief utterance from the Muses, a kind of inspiration of the divine nature and truth, i Truth and Falsehood in Religion, p. 158. v.] AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 75 like a flash of light from an unseen fire.' ^ It was thus that the belief in an infallible literature grew up, of which I must say more in a later lecture. To-day my subject is Authority in general, its meaning and significance for Faith. And I have to Justify my classification of it as a secondary ground of behef . Authority is defined by Professor Gwatkin ^ as ' all weight allowed to the behefs of persons or the teachings of institutions beyond their reasonable value as personal testimony.' The phrase ' reasonable value ' raises at once the question as to the relation of authority to reason. ' Reason ' is one of those ambiguous words which have been the cause of endless controversies, because the com- batants have not been careful enough to define their terms. It is a pity, I think, that we have not accepted Coleridge's distinction between reason and understanding, correspon- ding to the German words Vernunft and Verstand, and (less exactly) to the Greek vovs and Stdvota as used by Platonists. ' Reason ' would then be used for a philosophy of life based on full experience, a synthesis doing Justice to the claims of the moral and aesthetic consciousness, while ' understanding ' would be reserved for logical reasoning of a more abstract kind. We should then have been spared such confused arguments as are found, for example, in Mr. Balfour's Foundations of Belief (in which, as Leslie Stephen said, the foundations are ingeniously supported by the superstructure), or Mr. Kidd's Social Evolution. It is by no means certain that we are right in looking for the ' Foundations of Belief.' The metaphor may be a misleading one. Some things have no foundations. An organism, for instance, has no foundations. Perhaps rational Faith may prove to be part of the life of the universe, in which case we need not look for its foundations outside of itself. Perhaps there is no ' elephant ' to hold i Dion Chrysostom, Orat. 36, vol. ii. p. 59; Hatch, Hibbert Lectv/res, p. 61. 2 Gwatkin, The Knowledge of Ood, vol. i. p. 3. 76 FAITH [CH. up the world of ideas, and no ' tortoise ' to support the elephant.^ Mr. Kidd is anxious to prove that there is * no rational sanction for progress,' and he chooses to regard ' reason ' as a shortsighted, selfish faculty, which has nothing to do with any existence but the present, which, it insists, it is our duty to ourselves to make the most of.^ Professor Wallace, usually the most courteous of critics, is for once goaded into using a sharp expression. ' It is simply impossible to allow any one thus to play the fool with language.' ^ Similarly for Mr. Balfour, authority is called * the rival and opponent of reason.' Authority ' stands for that group of non-rational causes, moral, social, and educational, which produces its results by psychic processes other than reasoning.' * To authority, he considers, we owe the order and stability of the moral world ; by it the operations of reason are ' coerced to a fore-ordained issue ' ; it generates ' psychological climates ' (like the ' atmosphere ' of Church schools, I suppose, about which we heard so much two years ago), that is, habits of belief which reason has no power to influence. Indeed, * it is from authority that reason itself draws its most important premises.' * To authority, in the main, we owe, not religion only, but ethics and politics.' ' Reasoning is a force most apt to divide and disintegrate.' This is a return to a long discredited method of apolo- getics. In the Middle Ages John of Salisbury wrote : * As both the senses and human reason frequently go astray, God has laid in Faith the first foundation for the knowledge of truth.' So Bayle, the French Encyclopaedist, says, not very sincerely, perhaps : ' Human reason is a principle of destruction, not of construction ; it is capable solely of raising questions, and of doubling about to make 1 Cf. Professor H. Jones in nvbhert Journal (Jan. 1906), p. 301. > Kidd, Social Evolution, p. 73. » W. Wallace, Lectures and Essays, p. 104. ♦ Balfour, Foundations of Belief, p. 219. v.] AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 77 a controversy endless. The best use that can be made of philosophy is to acknowledge that it can only lead us astray, and that we must seek another guide, which is the light of revelation.' ^ I shall have occasion to show that religious belief is largely affected by ' psychic processes other than reason- ing.' But why these should be grouped together under the name ' authority,' I cannot imagine. We believe, as I shall show, partly on practical grounds, because we find that a certain mental attitude towards the unseen and unknown works, helps us to live as we wish to live, and since we believe that the world is all of one piece, it is reasonable to assume that what is true for us is true for all ; and partly also (in many cases) on aesthetic grounds, since order and beauty seem to be part of the Creator's design, and ends in themselves. These may be called non-rational grounds of belief (using rational in the lower sense), because reason (in the higher sense) has to find room for them, and cannot pro- nounce them invalid. Irrational they are not. And they have nothing, so far as I can see, to do with authority. The passage about ' coercing the operations of reason to a fore-ordained issue ' seem^ to be a dignified phrase for the operation which schoolboys call ' fudging ' their sums. Unless the world is purely irrational, such a manoeuvre is a wilful deception practised at our own expense or at that of others. There is nothing more harmful to the cause of truth than a lip-service to logic or science, when we have predetermined in our own minds the conclusion at which we mean to arrive. If we have decided to accept our opinions at second-hand, it is most candid to say so, and abstain from arguments which have nothing to do with our position. If by all this opposition of authority and reason it is simply meant that there are some things which we dis- 1 Quoted by Rickaby, First Principles, p. 191. 78 FAITH [cH. cover for ourselves, and other things which we accept because we have every reason to beUeve that our inform- ants are trustworthy, or because we have not the leisure or ability to test them for ourselves, that is a very obvious truism. I accept the fact that Buenos Ayres is the capital of the Argentine Republic because the evidence for the statement seems to me sufficient, because there is nothing intrinsically improbable in it, because I can think of no reason why there should be a conspiracy to deceive me on such a point, and because there is no testimony on the other side. I accept without question anything that a distinguished mathematician tells me about the higher mathematics because I am incapable of following his calculations, and because I have generally found mathe- maticians honourable men. But acceptances of this kind are really intellectual processes. I have my reasons for believing, or disbeUeving, in each case. This is, as I have said, psychologically quite different from bare credulity, which is a thoughtless condition. Once more, I may accept certain traditions, principles, and maxims as embodying the stored wisdom of the race, the racial instinct. But this, I contend, is again accept- ance on intellectual grounds. My studies of sociology and biology, we will suppose, have led me to attach a great importance to these traditions, as embodying a deeper practical wisdom than mankind has been able to make explicit and justify by argument, or, at any rate, deeper than I could hope to arrive at by my own wisdom and experience ; and therefore I submit to the authority of the race as exercised in these social or religious traditions. This is a very wise and respectable line to take, but it is purely intellectual and reasonable, and to class it as non-rational betrays a mere confusion of thought. Nor is there anything non-rational in the respect and homage which we pay to men of deep spiritual insight. * Our weak Faith may at times be permitted to look AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 79 through the eyes of some strong soul, and may thereby gain a sense of the certainty of spiritual things which before we had not, and which we lose when we return within ourselves.' ^ We do not pay this deference unless we have reason to think that our guide has indeed ' a strong soul ' ; and this is why personal influence is so potent in religion. Our reason tells us that much religious eloquence is mere professional advocacy ; we do not trust our guide until we feel that we know him. But now suppose that the tradition relates to some fact in the past or future, for which the personal testimony of my teacher is obviously an insufficient warrant, and which is not recommended to me by any of the considerations just mentioned. Is it unreasonable for me to believe it ? The answer is No, if I believe that the doctrine in question was supematurally imparted, or that it is supernaturally guaranteed. If I accept a theological proposition as supernaturally revealed, then I am really believing on authority — Divin e, authority^ The question is, whether Divine authority is or can be independent of what we have called the primary, ground of Faith,_the^igner, personal attraction towards the good, the true, and the beautiful. A purely external revelation of truths, which are not related in any way to our own consciousness, would of course be impossible. You cannot teach a blind man by showing him pictures, nor a deaf man by talking to him, because there is no communication with him through the sense which he has lost. And we may say reverently that God could make no revelation in such a way to man, with- out breaking the laws under which He governs the universe. Revelation must be either of truths which are at present unknown to us, but which when imparted to us are intel- ligible, and carry conviction with them by their agreement with the rest of our experience ; or else, there must be an 1 Stanton, The Place of Authority in I^diyioua Beli^, p. 32. 80 FAITH [CH. inward revelation, parallel to the outward, and assuring us of its trustworthiness. Now any revelation of facts which, though they are within our com^.rehension, are unverifiable, must be guaran- teed in some way. This obviously applies to all historical facts which are presented to us as having a significance for Faith. No inner light can re-create the past. Lessing, like many others since, found this difficulty insurmoimtable. * Contingent truths of history,' he said, * can never be made the proof of necessary truths of reason. That is the ugly ditch which I cannot get over, though I have often and earnestly attempted the leap.' We are not, however, called upon to attempt this salto mortale. It is enough if the historical facts fall naturally into their place in the scheme of the world as it reveals itself to Faith. Now, what kinds of guarantee are possible, when a prophet comes to me, saying, ' Thus saith the Lord ' ? What credentials is it possible for him to produce ? The most primitive kind of prophet seems generally to say : * God is the Lord of nature, and makes its laws bend to His will. Through His power, I will do the same ; and then you will know that He has sent me. I will call down rain by my incantations, or I will smite an unbeliever with grievous sickness.' But if God does not act in this way, if He does not suspend or interfere with the operations of nature by way of giving signs to men, this proof is wholly worthless. And it remauis wholly worthless even if rain does follow the prophet's prayer, and if the sceptic goes home sick unto death. Or the prophet may seek to establish his credit by pre- dicting the future. Maeterlinck has argued that it is one of the most mysterious things about human nature that we cannot predict the future — that, while the past is partly open to us, the future is a closed book. No doubt it is strange, but such do seem to be the limitations of our nature ; and there is no evidence at all convincing to the v.] AU.THORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 81 modem mind that those who are entrusted with a message by God have any supernatural powers of foretelling future events. The old Jewish prophets no doubt had a very clear insight into the issues of national policy. They saw that Egypt was likely to prove a broken reed, and that the cruel and barbarous empire of Assyria could not long terrorise the continent of Asia. But it is an inexcusable obscuring of issues to confound this kind of penetration with the old idea of prophecy, which made it possible to accept a verse in which Cyrus is mentioned by name, as having been written generations before the birth of that prince. The famous arguments from miracles and prophecy are in principle condemned by our Lord, whose warnings against seeking after a sign have been preserved by the candour of His biographers, though they themselves attached great value to such evidence. They are no longer arguments for us. It remains that the prophet should commend his message to us by awaking a response in our own hearts. This is in reality the only way in which a revelation is or can be made to us. The revelation comes to us with authority from outside, as the voice of God. The true prophet at any rate believes sincerely that God is speak- ing through his mouth ; and those who hear him are constrained to believe it too. Our hearts leap out to meet his words ; we recognise that this is what we wanted ; that here is the truth which we could not find for ourselves, the good news which we should not have dared to believe. We recognise in the prophet himself a man of God. We trust him instinctively ; when he speaks to us about the unseen world, we feel that he knows what he is speaking about, that he ' has been there ' himself. When we read the words of Jesus Himself, our hearts tell us that even this language is inadequate. This will show why I regard prophetical authority as\ 88. FAITH Urn. f a secondary ground of Faith. It is not independent of the primary ground, the inward tribunal which accepts or rejects it. It is this primary ground which alone makes belief on authority a religious act. Without it, belief in authority is inert opinion, or lazy acquiescence, or blind partisanship ; and none of these things has anything to do with Faith. Revelation is wholly within the sphere of religion. Nothing can be revealed to an irreligious mind, and nothing can be revealed to the religious mind that falls outside the sphere of religious truth. Neither can the natural man discern the things of the Spirit of God, nor can the spiritual man claim the inspiration or guarantee of the Spirit of God for beliefs which belong to the scope of the natural man. This, however, is a restriction of the province of authority which has not been generally accepted in practice. Authority, by those who appeal to it, is usually treated as the final court of appeal. Belief on authority, thus understood, has a psychological affinity to intuitivism, and is in fact often held in conjunction with it. The mystic who refuses to analyse or criticise his intuitions is often baffled by the emptiness or formlessness of his religious conceptions, and so tends to fall back upon the clearly defined images or symbols which his church pro- vides. He accepts these on authority, since he is not interested in the proof of them, and would even value them less if they were based on ordinary evidence. Whether consciously or not, he only needs them as helps to his imagination. But they may easily become so indispensable to him that he will be as stiff a dogmatist as if his Faith really rested on external authority ; and he will often protest vehemently that external authority, in the form of supernaturally revealed doctrines, is in truth the basis of his Faith, which would fall in ruins if this support were withdrawn. Just because the dogmas AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 83 of his church are accepted uncritically, as outside dis- cussion, they are capable of being used as external supports of a Faith which in reality sprang up independently of them, and only requires them to give form and colour to its vague intuitions. The typical dogmatist is a confused half -mystic, whose intuitive Faith is neither strong enough nor clear enough to bring him strength or comfort. He accordingly fortifies himself by calhng in the help of an external authority, whose credentials he would think it impious to investigate, and willingly accepts its guidance whenever the inner light bums dim. This is the most rudimentary and crudest form of working Faith ; since we have found that reliance upon undifferentiated feeling does not provide a working Faith at all. It is the working Faith of the simple orthodox beUever ; and however unsound it must appear to the philosopher, it works fairly well in practice. It is a wholesome safeguard against rash individualism ; since the doctrines which are supposed to be externally revealed by God are in truth supported, in part at least, by the legitimate authority of the collective religious conscious- ness, the value of which can hardly be overestimated. If a ' universal Church ' really existed, and if its Judg- ments were articulately represented by its official spokes- men, it would be rash indeed for an individual to dis- regard its authority. Even under the present state of things, ' orthodoxy ' provides a well-balanced view of hfe, and a safe guide in ordinary cases. But it remains true that the simple believer places the seat of authority wrongly, and allows authority to throw her shield over various beliefs relating to particular events, some of which may be untrue, while others have no religious significance. This kind of belief on authority, therefore, may be a source of danger to Faith, by loading it with burdens which it is unable to bear. Those who lean heavily on authority soon discover 84 FAITH [cH. if they allow themselves to think seriously, that it pro- vides no solution of the enigmas of Faith. Just as, in considering the hypothesis of Faith as immediate per- ception of divine truth, we found that the devout mystic is haunted by nightmares, contrefacons diaboliques of his most precious visions, which he has denied himself the means of testing, and cannot possibly test without being false to his principle that divine truth is communi- cated immediately; so the believer on authority is dismayed to find that authority is not all of one mind.^ Not only are his senses confused by the clamour of rival teachers, all equally confident that their prophecy is the true word of the God of truth, but his intellect, conscience, and feelings are touched on different sides by appeals which are sharply antagonistic to each other. Unless he shuts his ears tight to all advocates except one (a very common but rather undignified way of deciding a case to one's own satisfaction), he will find that the rival authorities give him no peace, and that he must somehow decide among them, weighing his authorities against each other, and thereby abandoning the attitude of unques- tioning submission. Now these rival claims cannot be settled offhand, by an intuitive method ; we cannot go back for external authority to pure mystical experience, which answers no questions about particulars. It is thus that we are driven to admit the necessity of those other secondary grounds which will form the subject of my later lectures — the practical principle, the intellectual principle, and the aesthetic principle. Without them we cannot say what kind of facts can be guaranteed by authority, and which voices it is safe to trust. I am trying to arrive at a conclusion as to what Faith ought to be and may be, not as to what in the majority of cases it actually is. I have already said that the 1 Alanus of Lille (thirteenth century) said wittily: 'Auctoritas cereum liabet nasum ; id est, in diversum potest flecti sensum.' AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 85 great mass of religious people stop short at this second stage, which the medieval Church called fides impUcita, and which the German reformers called * charcoal-burner's faith.' In the case of these simple believers the contents of their creeds — nearly the whole concrete body of their beliefs — are determined by pure accident. The authority to which they pin their Faith is that under which they were brought up. It matters little that a Protestant may have a mind naturaliter Catholica ; he will rarely change his profession. Somehow or other, his religious instincts will find expression in the church or denomination to which he belongs. If he has been brought up as a Catholic, he will find grace and help in the Sacraments ; if as a Methodist, he will expect and generally experience the crisis which is known in those circles as sudden conversion, and which is supposed to occur usually between the ages of fifteen and twenty-one. The means of grace suggested to men and women by their teachers may not be, and in fact are not, equally wholesome and good in all cases ; there may be, and in fact is, spiritual loss in belonging to a religious body whose tenets are meagre, defective, and out of correspondence with some of the ingredients of a rich spiritual nature. But when the driving force, the religious instinct, is strong, it is able to stretch inadequate dogmatic theories to a very considerable extent. They become merely pegs on which the believer hangs his best thoughts. Clement of Alexandria called Faith (and it was precisely this common kind of religious belief — the belief of the average church-goer — which was in his mind),' compendious knowledge ' {o-vvto/xos yvwo-is). It is a kind of short cut to divine knowledge, for those who have not yet had enough spiritual experience, or who have not the leisure, or the intellectual ability, to ' beat out the music ' of their Faith for themselves. It is a working principle for all (Clement ^^ w*ould say) until they have attained to philosophical ^ truth. This is obviously true. The average Christian 86 FAITH [CH. possesses, in the tenets of his Church, a much richer Faith than he could have found for himself, a much more com- plete scheme of beliefs than individually he has any right to call his own. It is not possible for him to suspend his judgment until he has balanced the claims of rival authorities. He feels that his wisest course is to admit and accept the claims of the authority under which he finds himself, to be a divine revelation, and to make this the mould, as it were, into which he can pour the treasures of his religious experience. The treasure is in earthen vessels, no doubt, and he is very helpless if called upon to give a reason for the Faith that is in him ; but he has a receptacle for his religious emotions, a rule of belief, and a rule of life. I have now perhaps shown sufficiently the partial justification, and the necessary limitations, of that kind of Faith which passively accepts the body of orthodox beliefs, as a man has learnt orthodoxy at school, or at his mother's knee. In my next lectures I must consider the chief historical forms which the beUef in authority has taken. vl] authority as a GEOUND of faith 87 p CHAPTER VI AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FMTIL— continued Authority in religion, as I showed in my last lecture, means Divine authority ; and to rest one's Faith on Authority means to act on the belief that information about divine things has been communicated to mankind, immedi- ately and unmistakably. I have shown that this belief is held by most religious people, and that they for the most part accept unexamined, and maintain through life, the forms of Faith which were first presented to them, refusing even to contemplate any change. I have ad- mitted the necessity of this naive, childlike Faith ; but I have shown that its forms are determined by the accidents of early surroundings, and that by excluding self-criticism it is condemned to stationariness in the midst of a changing world. In this lecture and the next I wish to consider the historical forms which the belief in authority has taken. The chief of these are the theories of the InfalHble Church, and of the Infallible Book. But there is another form of supernatural authority, which is historically prior to these, and which even in the history of the Christian Church comes before them. I mean belief in the super- natural inspiration of individual men, prophets, seers, visionaries, and the like. I have already mentioned this as the most typical form of religious authority properly so called. The prophet conceives himself to be the mouthpiece of 88 FAITH [CH. God, and his utterances as prophet are held to convey du-ect information about the will and purposes of the Almighty. This is a case of belief on authority, in the true sense. It differs from the intuitivism which we discussed the other day, in that the prophet regards his message as something special and miraculous. He is merely the vehicle, not the organ of the revelation. Other men accept his utterances as coming straight from God. They have lost nothing, it is thought, by passing through a transparent medium. In the New Testament this individual inspiration is spoken of as being ' filled with the Holy Ghost.' The religious instinct, which is the foundation of true Faith, was justly traced to the indwelling of the Holy Spirit of God. But there is a right and a wrong view of individual inspiration. In St. Paul, the action of the Holy Spirit is looked for in all that goes to make up character in its widest sense, and it appears in all religious experience. The Holy Ghost is the guide of prayer, the illuminator of the intellect, the kindler of love, the inspirer of every noble deed and work. But the operation of this Spirit is not wholly miraculous, wholly foreign to their own true nature. It is, in truth, their own best nature. * God in them is the fulfilment of the best that they have it in them to become. The higher nature begotten in them is the first-fruits of the Spirit, with promise of ever richer fruition. The groanings which cannot be uttered, with which the Spirit comes in on our behalf, are identical with the groanings which we ourselves utt^r in the longing for a fuller experience of God (Rom. viii. 23-27). And so the light within is the light of God, as we allow Him to become one with us.' ^ But St. Paul's contemporaries could not all rise to this conception. They traced the operation of the Spirit rather in fitful and unaccountable manifesta- tions of religious enthusiasm. The more strange and 1 Grubb, Authority and the Light Within, p. 62. VI.] AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 89 wild these were, the more sure they were that there was something divine in them. In the various charismata y especially, they found unmistakable evidence of an influx of the supernatural. The ' pneumatic ' or spiritual man was one who spoke with tongues or prophesied. This undisciplined enthusiasm was discouraged, and in the end suppressed or expelled by the Catholic Church, though it lived on in a different form, in the strange belief in visions. TertuUian, writing about a.d. 200, has the startling and very significant statement that * the majority of men derive their knowledge of God from visions.' ^ In the following centuries, the visions of the monks and nuns were the chief sources of supposed in- formation about the life after death. All the horrors of the medieval Inferno were thus guaranteed, and a great part of the terrible pictures of hell, which seem to us so grotesque and wantonly cruel, was the direct result of the supernatural authority attributed to the nightmares of holy men. In our own day, the belief in directly inspired prophets among our contemporaries has practically disappeared, as it disappeared in Palestine between Malachi and John the Baptist. But the belief in supernatural guidance vouchsafed to individuals survives both in its true and in its more dubious form. The distinguishing mark of this belief in individual illumination is the acceptance of the supposed divine communication simply and without question. A man, for instance, will hesitate about accepting an appointment until he feels a distinct ' leading ' to say yes or no ; then he will act at once, putting aside any self-questionings as to his fitness for the post. I must try to indicate what measure of truth and error I consider to reside in this Faith in direct inspiration. 1 See the interesting note in Harnack, History of Dogma^ yol. i. p. 63 (Engllsli translation). 90 FAITH [oh. Assuredly all good men are guided in various degrees by the Spirit of God who dwells, St. Paul says, in all but the reprobate. We have within us a tribunal before which it is our right and our duty to bring every doubtful case. And in this ' discerning of spirits ' we may hope that we are guided not by our own unaided wisdom, but by the divine gift of grace which is only the other side of the human virtue of Faith. In trusting miraculous ' leadings,' the error is in supposing that we can accept any mental suggestion, without question, as coming from God. The suggestion may come to us in a mysterious manner — in a vivid dream, or associated with a strange coincidence, or in some other way unlike our usual mental processes. But these are no necessary tokens of divine inspiration ; it is superstition, not religion, to suppose that they are. Divine guidance is given us ; but the degree of it is deter- * mined by our spiritual and mental condition, and it is not communicated in a magical manner, so as to save us the trouble of further inquiry. If the man who, when he has been offered an appointment, waits for some ' leading,' and does not try to weigh the pros and cons fairly, were to consider the reasons for and against acceptance, prayerfully, but with the best use of his reason, he would be more likely to be guided aright in his decision. In short, the error is in trying to fix the immediacy of special inspiration, as Quietists try to fix the immediacy of general, diffused inspiration. Special guidance in emergencies comes to us through our ordinary faculties if it comes at all. Sanctity does not confer the power of divination. The theory of individual inspiration, if pushed to its logical conclusion, is too absurd to be widely held. It would result in making each Christian, who believed him- self inspired, his own church and his own Bible. But even in a democratic age it would seem ridiculous to apply the theory of * one man one vote ' to rehgion. This I AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 91 type of Faith can be studied in its most favourable form in the writings of the earUer Quakers. In the words of a living member of the Society of Friends, whom I have already quoted in this lecture, ' they made the inner light something wholly alien to man's nature. It was not an attribute of man, but a substance entirely separate from man's own being. " The light of which we speak," says Barclay, " is not only distinct but of a different nature from the soul of man and its faculties." It is not to be identified with the conscience any more than a candle is the same as the lantern that holds it.' ^ The error here, which, as this passage shows, is fully admitted by modem ' Friends,' is substantially the same as that of quietistic mysticism. This extreme form of individualism has not been very prominent in the history of Christianity. The authorities which in history have swayed the destiny of nations have been more external and more august. They have spoken to man, not within him. Let us first consider the historical evolution of the idea of the Church, as the divinely inspired source of authority. I have already shown that the conception of Faith as a body of doctrine, supematurally accredited and therefore to be accepted in its entirety, is primitive. The guiding idea of Catholicism began to establish itself as soon as there was a Church for it to grow in. * The Catholic theory of apostolic tradition,' says Sabatier,^ who writes from a Protestant standpoint, * is found clearly defined and established as an infallible and sovereign law in the times of Irenaeus, Tertullian, and Hippolytus.' The concentration of power in the hands of the Roman Church, as the authoritative interpreter of this tradition, advanced as if by an automatic process. To quote Sabatier again : ' The future centre of the Catholic Church appeared from 1 Grubb, Authority and the Light Within, p. 81. • Sabatier, Le$ Meligions cPAutoriii et la Religion de VMsjprit, 92 FAITH [ctt the commencement of the second century,' and in the year 194, ' for the first time a bishop of Rome, Victor, speaks as master to the other bishops, presents himself as inter- preter and arbiter of the universal Church, acts as universal bishop, and proclaims heretical the churches that would resist his authority.' In Cyprian's time the bishops were all theoretically equal. Yet such is the interior logic of the system that Cyprian himself laid the foundation of a new evolution which was to produce from the body of bishops that episcopus episcoporum against whom he had tried to guard himself. The trend of the Catholic polity towards a centralised despotism went on irresistibly and inexorably. When once the Roman primacy is recognised, all later developments of the papal prerogative, down to our own times, are only the logical conclusion of the CathoHc con- ception of the Church. The infallibility which was the attribute of the universal Church was gradually con- centrated in the Roman Church, and thence passed to the Roman bishop. When the Pope was held to be the head and voice of the Church, the infallibility of the Church could not express itself through another mouth. [ Roman Catholicism is a religion of authority. When a man who has been a Protestant becomes a Roman Catholic, he must learn a kind of submission that we in England, or America, know nothing of in any other relation of life, unless we are soldiers on a campaign. Where the Church has spoken, the loyal Catholic must obey without question. Nor is this authority confined to religious matters. ' That authority,' says Cardinal Newman, ^ * has the prerogative of an indirect jurisdiction on subject-matters which lie beyond its own proper limits, and it most reasonably has such a jurisdiction. It could not properly defend religious truth without claiming for that truth what may be called its pomoeria, 1 Development of Christian Doctrine. VI.] AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 93 or, to take another illustration, without acting as we act, as a nation, in claiming as our own not only the land on which we live, but what are called British waters. The Catholic Church claims, not only to judge infallibly on religious questions, but to animadvert on opinions in secular matters which bear upon religion, on matters of philosophy, of science, of hterature, of history, and it demands our submission to her claim. It claims to censure books, to silence authors, and to forbid discussions. It must, of course, be obeyed without a word, and perhaps, in process of time, it will tacitly recede from its own injunctions.' How like this is to the history of the growth of the Roman world-empire ! Each new province demands a further annexation to secure its frontier ; and nothing short of military discipline and military organisation will keep the vast dominion together. But we must examine more closely the claims of a theory which has so august a history. It rests entirely on the theory of a clearly distinguishable special divine revelation, as does the Protestant theory of an infallible book. At the close of this discussion we must consider how far this distinction is valid. According to the Catholic theory, the Church is not simply a divinely founded establishment which continues to administer the trusts committed to it by its Founder, but it is in its corporate capacity a direct continuation of the Incarna- tion, permanently and fully inspired by the Holy Ghost, who, in accordance with the promise of Jesus Christ, made while He was on earth, was to take His place as a Divine Presence among men, until His coming again. It is true that God had never left Himself without witness, even in heathendom ; but from the first Whitsunday He he^s had ' a special abode, an organised and visible agency for distributing a higher and supernatural order of grace,' * a guidance differing in kind from natural wisdom and 1 Martineau, Seat 0/ Authority in Religion, p. 130. 94 FAITH [CH. goodness. If we ask how we are to know that one particular corporation, and no others, has the privilege of being the sole trustee of this supernatural revelation, we are referred to four marks, the famous ' notes ' of a true Church, viz. Unity, Sanctity, UniversaUty, and Apostolicity. We are bound to ask, whether, as a matter of historical fact, the Roman Church, or the Catholic Church, which is so defined as to include all Episcopalian bodies having the * Apostolic Succession,' but no others, can claim to exhibit these marks. If it fails to do so, it will be un- necessary to ask the further question, whether these four notes, if they were established, would be sufiicient founda- tion for so tremendous a claim. The first note. Unity, used to be understood to mean that there have been no changes in the teaching of the Church since Apostolic times. / Dogma is unchangeable — immobilis et irrefor- mabilis. This theory, as we shall see presently, has been abandoned by the Liberal school of Catholic apologists in favour of the doctrine of natural and necessary develop- ment. It is, indeed, only by completely rewriting Church history that the mutability and mutations of dogma can be disputed. The Roman CathoHcs have made a legitimate point against their Anglican opponents by proving that the germs of modem CathoHcism can be detected even in the sub-Apostolic age. But they have not proved, and cannot prove, that there have been no important changes. The verdict of history has been pronounced decisively against the theory that the supernatural character of the Church can be demonstrated by the miraculous and unparalleled ' stability ' of its teaching.^ It would not be in accordance with the plan of those lectures to give detailed examples of the mutability of dogma and culture. Martineau has given some clear 1 Ct Burkitt, Early Christianity outside the Roman Empire, p. d. VI.] AUTHOEITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 95 examples in his Seat of Authority in Religion y and any fairly written Church history will supply abundant evidence. The exclusive claim to Sanctity can hardly be taken seriously. We have no means of determining who are God's true saints, and we are expressly forbidden to attempt to do so. If sanctity is an occult quality, known to God alone, it obviously cannot be appealed to as a * note.' It is useless to offer evidence which, from the nature of the case, cannot be produced. But so far as we have the means of forming an opinion, it would appear that men and women of the highest character have appeared in nearly all religious bodies, and that, though the Roman communion may claim to have been exception- ally rich in saints, it is also true that among the most odious scoundrels who have disgraced humanity have been found some of the most highly placed ecclesiastics of the Roman Church. ^ The third ' note,' Universality, is interpreted to mean that Catholics everywhere profess the same Faith. It is difficult to see what argument can be based on such a fact, were it true. The Tariff Reform League every- where professes the same faith, because those who h. ppen to be free-traders do not subscribe to it. But in point of fact, divergences of belief have never ceased to show themselves in the Catholic Church, in spite of the prompt amputations to which she has always been ready to resort. The fourth note, Apostolicity, is a simple begging of the question as between Catholicism and other bodies. For 1 A good example of the manner in which history must be written to satisfy the demands of the Catholic theory is furnished by a recent biographical work : Chronicles of the House of Borgia by Frederick, Baron Corvo. 'Alexander vi., as earthly Vicar of Jesus Christ, merits our reverent admira- tion. His personal piety was simple, diligent, and real. He greatly revered the Deipara, the Blessed Virgin Mary. In her honour he ordained the bell which rings at sunset, sunrise, and noon, for the Angelus Domini in memory of the Incarnation. On his deathbed he said, W« have always had a singular affection for the most holy Vigin.' This singular affection for the Virgin was testified, among other ways, by having one of his mistresses painted as the Madonna with the infant Saviour. 96 FAITH [CH. all Christian bodies claim spiritual descent from the Apostolic Church. Whether a particular method of devolution is essential or not is the main point at issue between them. The four ' notes,' then, completely break down, and a theory of Church authority which has no better arguments than these to rely upon must be in a very precarious position. In truth, the legitimate claim of authority in matters of Faith is grievously weakened by these attempts to narrow its sphere. It is assumed that if there is such a thing as a Church, it must be the Roman Church ; and the religious consciousness of Europe is naively assumed to have sanctioned not only the divinity of Christ, but the apotheosis of Mary and the cult of the saints. At the present time, however, the most interesting feature in Roman Catholicism, from our point of view, is the growth of a dynamic theory of Church authority. This is, at least for Catholics, the most Important practical question as to the nature of authority in matters of Faith. In order to understand it, it will be necessary to contrast the static and dynamic theories of revelation, outside the Roman Church, as well as within its borders. By a static view of revelation, as opposed to a dynamic, I mean the theory that a supernatural revelation was at some past time granted to mankind, which now persists only in its effects. The date when the authoritative and infallible revelation began, and when it ceased, may be fixed anywhere, the limits being purely arbitrary. Accord- ing to the old-fashioned high Anglican theory, we can only rely with certainty on the pronouncements of the undivided Church. The seven general councils may claim infallibility. After the schism between East and West, the supernatural guidance of the Holy Ghost went into abeyance among the different Churches, which had excommunicated each other, exactly as an old English VI.] AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH »7 peerage goes into abeyance when a peer leaves two or more daughters, and no sons. None of the daughters may take the title, which accordingly is erased from the roll of the peerage : but if the descendants of all the daughters except one die out, or if the head of one clan of cousins marries the head of the only other remaining clan, the eldest representative of the family may claim the title, and the series is resumed where it left off. Just so, if all except one of the divided Churches which have the Apostoli- cal Succession were to disappear, or if they would resume communion with each other, and would agree to hold an eighth general council, that council would be infallibly guided in its decisions, in spite of the absence of non- episcopal schismatical bodies, which are neither churches nor integral parts of the one Church. This fantastic theory is not often heard of by the younger generation, but it was part of the foundations of the Tractarian position. It is, in effect, a static view, because the conditions of in- fallible guidance ceased to exist long ago, and there is no likelihood of their being revived. The Church can never modify its constitution, because the only body which could legalise changes is a body which can never meet. It is much as if no Act of Parliament were valid until it had been passed by a joint session of the House of Commons and the American Congress. The theory is well adapted to support the old Anglican * appeal to antiquity.' If no further developments of doctrine, or practice, which have taken place since the seventh general council, can claim any authority, modem Romanism and theological Liberalism, and anything that is new in Protestantism, are alike con- demned. Another essentially static theory of revelation, which at present shows more vitality than the old-fashioned Anglican theory, is that which is usually called after the name of Albrecht Ritschl, of Gottingen (died 1889). I shall have occasion, later in this course, to consider the 6 86 FAITH [CH. theory of value-Judgments which is the most famous part of his philosophy. Here I must only refer to his theory of revelation. This is a curious blend of Schleiermacher's view of Faith as pure feeling, with an old-Protestant insistence on preaching * Jesus only.' In order to under- stand Christianity, he holds, we must go back at every point to the historical revelation once given in the Person of Jesus Christ. And this revelation was definitely closed at the time of the Crucifixion. He will have nothing to do with the Pauline doctrine of communion with the glorified Christ. ' Christ brings us to God ' ; but only by the im- pression made upon us by the study of the Synoptic Gospels. This position is as untenable as the old Anglican theory, though for different reasons. The obvious and fundamental fallacy in Ritschl's theory is the supposition that Faith in a historical fact can be based on grounds which are altogether independent of historical judgment. For Ritschl wUl not allow us to base our Faith in Christ on intellectual conviction that the narratives about Him are trustworthy. Judgments of fact, of this kind, seem to him irrelevant in religion. And yet religion, he says, must be before all things * historical.' So glaring is this inconsistency that some of the ablest of the so-called Ritschlian school, such as Kaftan, lay great stress on * the exalted Christ,' though they still refuse any respect to the Logos-Christology. Church history, written under the influence of this static theory of revelation, must needs be a depressing record of deterioration and corruption. Even Hamack's great History of Dogma, (though Hamack is too inde- pendent a thinker to be called without qualification a Ritschlian), takes the standpoint that later developments were a 'secularisation' and * depotentiation ' of the original Gospel. We are always to look back, not forward, for our inspiration. The older Roman Cathofic apologetic did not differ very AUTHORITY AS A GEOUND OF FAITH 99 much from Anglicanism or Protestantism in the re- spect which it paid to primitive authority. The chief difference is that Scholasticism, as represented by St. Thomas Aquinas, give's a larger place to human reason in corroborating revelation. The authorised Catholic apologetic does not rest everything on authority. On the contrary, St. Thomas maintains that the being and chief attributes of God might be demonstrated, even apart i from revelation, by ordinary reason. There is therefore in his system no disparateness between reason and authority. ^ [Authority supplements reason, and reason interprets autho- rity. But the Nominalists who followed Duns Scotus cut authority loose from its moorings, and erected it into a wholly independent principle of belief. Duns Scotus him- self, and still more Occam and Alexander of Hales, are as sceptical of the old proofs of God's existence as Kant himself, and unlike Kant they fall back not on the practical reason, but on bare authority. Occam declares that monotheism is, on intellectual grounds, only a more pro- bable theory than polytheism. God's will, according to Scotus, cannot be ascertained from our moral sense ; it is imparted to us only in revelation. Thomas Aquinas had himself abandoned the position of Bonaventura and Albert the Great, who had undertaken to prove the beginning of the world in time. The Creation, and the doctrine of the Trinity, must be believed, he says, ' by Faith alone.' This was a dangerous concession, which the Nominalists made the most of, carrying the same principle over to other dogmas. It was not intended, I think, by any of the Schoolmen to cut authority loose from the past, as well as from reason ; but the Nominalist theory gave the Church a free hand to order anything to be believed. The privilege of interpreting tradition infallibly is not far from the privilege of determining it. The time came when Pio Nono could say, ' I am tradition.' The recognition of development, of the ' dynamic ' 100 FAITH [cH. principle as it is called in contrast with the * static ' theory that dogma can undergo no change, is modem in apolo- getics. It laid strong hold on Newman when he had freed himself from the false position in which he had remained for some years. He set himself to prove that Catholic theology is a legitimate development, and not a corruption, of the primitive Faith. Now, what are the tests of a legi- timate development ? The first test, Newman tells us, is the preservation of the type ; the second, the continuity of principles. Thirdly, doctrines must have the power of assimilation, like living organisms. They will also show anticipations of further development, to be fully exhibited hereafter. Next, they will show logical sequence, not that political evolution proceeds logically, but when it is accomplished, we can see that a kind of unconscious logic has determined its course. Next, the new doctrines must tend to establish and illustrate, not to contradict, the original creed. Lastly, it bears the test of time. ■^ Heresies flourish and then disappear ; the truth continues. We cannot help feeling how far superior this is to the static theory of revelation. Nothing is more clear about our Lord's ministry than that He designed to give mankind not a code of legislation, but a standard of values ; that He laid down principles which future ages were to apply and work out, not a fixed rule to which the religious future of the race was to be forced to conform. The whole con- ception of the office and work of the Holy Ghost which we find in the New Testament, especially in the Fourth Gospel, involves the clearest grasp of the principle of development which had up to that time been contemplated. Nor can we find fault with the argument that the collective inspiration of a great society is an easier thing to believe in and to defend than the inspired private judgment of individuals. Authority may claim to be the right of the race against the individual ; it may claim to be the conscience or the intelligence of the race, which VI.] AUTHORITY AS A GEOUND OF FAITH 101 develops indeed in a natural and legitimate manner from generation to generation, and from century to century, but stores up and hands on the acquisitions of the past in a way which is not possible to the private inquirer who will take nothing for granted. If Christ promised that the Holy Spirit would be always present to guide the Church, may we not assume that He would have prevented the Church, in her corporate capacity, from taking any serious false steps ? The weak point of Newman's argument is very apparent to all who are not Roman Catholics, though within his own communion it is less obvious, because of the aristo- cratic contempt which prevents its members from paying any attention to other forms of Christianity. ' Catholi- cism,' says Dom Cuthbert Butler, in an article in the Hihhert Journal intended for the religious public generally, 'Catholicism, and, for Western Europe, Roman Catholi- cism, is the religion into which, as a matter of fact, the religion of Christ and His Apostles has grown.' It was this assumption that lent so great a weight to the words securus iudicat orhis terrarum, which seemed to Newman decisive against Anglicanism and in favour of Rome. But how strangely narrow the outlook which sees no alternative except between atheism and the Vatican ! Newman's orbis terrarum is, as I have said elsewhere, a dwindling and harassed minority in a few countries round the Mediterranean sea. It comprises, broadly speaking, the Latinised part of the Roman Empire ; and within those limits, though it has been fairly successful in suppressing other forms of Christianity, it has not succeeded in retaining either the masses or the ' intel- lectuals.' If then the ultimate test of a creed is its vitality, the argument recoils with fatal force on Newman's own head. Newman is not insensible to the fact that this very argument has led many to reject Roman Catholicism, 102 FAITH [oh. because history seems to prove that it is not compatible with social and intellectual progress beyond a certain stage. He meets this objection by rejecting modem civilisation as a huge mistake. He would prefer, he says, to see people much more bigoted and superstitious than they are, for a dishonest Irish beggar woman, who is chaste and goes to Mass, is better than an honourable Enghsh gentleman whose ideals are, after all, secular. It is enough to say in reply to this, that it is a complete abandonment of his test. He begins by saying, ' The great world shall judge ' ; and ends by saying, ' If the world decides against Rome, so much the worse for the world.' Newman is claimed as one of the inspirers of the modem Liberal movement in the Roman Church, though he would have recoiled in horror from the critical conclusions of Loisy and his friends. One passage will be enough to prove this. * First of all,' writes the Cardinal, many years after joining the Roman Church, * ex abundanti cautela [that is, as something almost too obvious to need stating], every CathoUc holds that the Christian dogmas were in the Church from the time of the Apostles ; that they were ever in their substance what they are now.' ^ There is an essential difference between this theory of apparent development which excludes real changes and the Modernist theory of an idea clothing itself in new forms from age to age. That movement rests partly on a dynamic conception of authority, carried to the pitch of admitting the right and power of the Church to change its creed and dogmas if necessary, and partly on the agnostic position that human reason caimot go beyond phenomena, from which the corollary is drawn that whatever helps souls may be taken as true, or as near the truth as we can get. This latter contention belongs to a later chapter of our inquiry — viz. 1 Quoted by Bishop Gore, Bampton Lectures, p. 186. Fi.] AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 103 the practical, or pragmatic, ground of Faith, and I will try to give you a fair account of the position of the Liberal CathoUcs when we come to that branch of our subject. Here I am dealing with the claim of one branch of the Christian Church to be the sole trustee of a definite supernatural gift — the power of pronouncing infallibly and authoritatively on matters of Faith. And our conclusion is that there never has been, and never will be, any corporation which can decide such questions ex cathedra. I am not disputing the right of any society to impose its own conditions of membership ; that is quite a different thing ; but there is nowhere any man or institution which can impose silence upon the moral and LQtellectual protests of the human mind, in the name of some still higher authority. There is nowhere any dogma which is exempt from examination, because it is guaranteed to be de fide. The Modernist position with regard to authority may be thus summarised. ' Religion, like everything else that lives, is subject to the law of growth, which involves change. The God of the Old Testament differs widely from the Father whom Christ preached, and the formulas of our day differ in meaning, if not in form, from the regula fidei of the early Church. Jesus Himself believed in an approaching *end of the age,' a catastrophic in- auguration of a ' kingdom of God ' upon earth. It is therefore impossible to suppose that He meant to organise and legislate for the coming centuries. In the Gospels, as in the rest of Scripture, the letter killeth, but the spirit giveth life. But this law of change is not incon- sistent with the authority of behef. For though truth is changeless, its image as reflected in human minds con- tinually alters. The living Faith i§ the important thing ; the forms which it employs in the vain attempt to be articulate are mutable and imperfect.' The Catholic Modernist differs from such Protestant writers as Hamack 104 FAITH [CH. and Sabatier, with whom, in other ways, he has much in common, in that he has no wish to discard the luxuriant growth of dogma and return to a fabled 'primitive simplicity.' He does not find in the historical Jesus the basis for a working faith ; he cannot admit that the inter- pretation of His life and teaching given by German Protestantism is historically true ; but he is content with the incontestable fact that a great institution has come into existence, and flourished for nearly two thousand years, which has created a series of dogmas, the products of its ' faith and love,' dogmas which have been necessary for its existence, and which therefore are valid until they cease to perform their office. This is really opportunism in excelsis. The seat of authority is the verdict of history, and in history no judgment is final. ' The visible Church,' writes Mr. Tyrrell in his Much-abused Letter, ' is but a means, a way, a creature, to be used where it helps, to be left where it hinders. . . . Who have taught us that the consensus of theologians cannot err, but the theologians themselves ? Mortal, fallible, ignorant men like our- selves. . . . Their present domination is but a passing episode in the Church's history. , . . May not history repeat itself [as in the transition from Judaism to Christianity] ? Is God's arm shortened that He should not again, out of the very stones, raise up children unto Abraham ? May not Catholicism, like Judaism, have to die in order that it may live again in a greater and grander form ? Has not every organism got its limits of development, after which it must decay and be content to survive in its progeny ? Wine-skins stretch, but only within measure ; for there comes at last a bursting-point when new ones must be provided.' In a note to justify this startling passage he explains : * The Church of the Catacombs became the Church of the Vatican ; who can tell what the Church of the Vatican may not turn into ? ' AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 105 The spectacle presented by the Modernist movement is a very interesting one. The principle of authority as the custodian of primitive tradition, which was so admirably successful in maintaining discipline and unity, ended in binding the Roman Church hand and foot in chains of her own forging. And so the Pope claimed the right to declare and interpret ' tradition ' in his own way. Thus authority turned against itself ; and the liberty of the Papacy has let loose the unbounded licence of the Modernists. ' The differences between the larval and final stages of many an insect,' says Mr. Tyrrell again, * are often far greater than those which separate kind from kind.' And so this chameleon of a Church, which has changed its colour so completely since the Gospel was preached in the subterranean galleries of Rome, may undergo another transformation and come to believe in M. Loisy's God, who is ' never encountered in history.' The warning against putting new wine into old wine-skins is somewhat rashly introduced into such a programme ! We are, then, able to see in the Roman Church of to-day the bankruptcy of the old theory of authority. The theory of a ' static ' revelation given to the Church long ago has been proved to be untenable, both historically and politically. And if, abandoning this old position, the in- spiration of the Church is explained to mean the continuous inspiration of its earthly head, the questions cannot fail to be asked. Is autocracy the divinely ordained government for the Church ? Is it so certain that the Holy Spirit speaks only through the mouth of the Bishop of Rome ? With this doubt disappears the possibility of confident reliance on the authority of the Church, as a primary ground of Faith. The true ' Church,' as the depositary of inspiration in matters of belief and practice, is the whole body of men and women who have any enlightenment in such matters. This Church has no accredited organ, and claims no finality 106 FAITH [CH. for its utterances. It does homage to the past, not to fetter its own future, but to preserve the knowledge and experience already gained, which are easily lost through carelessness or presumption. Ideally, this Church is the Divine Spirit immanent in humanity. This identification of the Church with the indwelling Holy Spirit is ancient, but it is far too great a privilege to be claimed by any ecclesiastical corporation. But though we cannot for a moment admit that infalli- bility resides in the decisions of any man or any council, present or past, it would not be easy to overestimate the advantages of venerable traditions in matters of Faith. Each age is liable to be carried away by some dominant idea, which soon becomes a superstition, as ' progress ' did in the nineteenth century. Authority has a steadying influence, forbidding as to ignore doctrines which for the time are unpopular, and preserving, to some extent, * the proportion of Faith.' In these high matters the dead as well as the living have a right to speak ; and respect for authority is the courtesy which we pay to the voices of * famous men and our fathers that begat us.* vii.J AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH X07 P AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH — Continued In this lecture I wish to consider further the relations of Faith and Authority. We have considered the theory of an infallible authority vested in the Church, and have shown how, just as in the Roman Empire authority became more and more centralised until the emperor became a sultan, so in the Roman Church authority has come to be vested in one man. When this one man says, ' I am tradi- 1^^ tion,' the last restrictions on autocracy have been removed, ^P for the ' living voice of the Church ' is independent of the past. Thus the principle of authority, in completing its evolution, turns against and destroys itself. At the same time, the regula fidei, in the hands of some bold reformers, has become independent of existential fact. The only authority is the course of history, and the Church is a Proteus who justifies each metamorphosis in turn by the plea II faut vivre. These two developments may be said to constitute a reductio ad absurdum of Church authority as an independent ground of Faith. We have now to consider the Protestant alternative to the infallible Church— the infallible Book. * The Bible,' said Chillingworth, * is the religion of Protestants.'^ Plato long ago exposed the necessary limitations of the written word as a guide. * When they are once written down,' he says, * words are tumbled about anjrwhere 1 The words are written on his tombstone, but they do not deserve to be perpetuated, for they are false. Protestantism is the democracy of religion. Not tlie Bilile, but belief in the inspiration of the individual is the rehgion of Protestants. s^ 108 FAITH [cH. among those who may or may not understand them, and know not to whom they should reply, to whom not ; and if they are maltreated or abused, they have no parent to protect them ; and they cannot protect or defend them- selves.' ^ There is another kind of writing, he goes on, graven on the tablets of the mind, of which the written word is no more than an image. This kind is alive ; it has a soul ; and it can defend itself. The wisdom of these utterances has been amply proved by the history of the doctrine of Inspiration in the Christian Church.^ It was not till lo ng after the Captivity that the_ rfiUgion. of Israel became the religion of a Book. . While prophetism flourished^ liEe' living word of the prophet was more than the written scroll ; but no sooner had the fount of prophecy began to run dry than rigid and mechanical views of inspiration began to be applied to the sacred literature. The canonisation of the Law, which began in 621, was accomplished for all time in 444 B.C. The histori- cal books, called the ' former prophets,' obtained nearly their final form during the exile, but the text was not inviolable till long afterwards. The list of prophetical books, the 'latter prophets,' was closed about 200 B.C., according to Comill.^ The third section of the Canon contains second century writings, but they were all supposed to be much earlier. The Canon was practi- cally settled more than a century before the birth of our Lord.* It excluded certain books, like Ecclesi- asticus, which revealed their late origin, while admitting the pseudonymous Daniel and Ecclesiastes. The Book of 1 Plato, Phaedrus, p. 275. 2 There is a remarkable echo of this passage in Milton {Christian Doctnne i. p. 30). * It is diflBcult to conjecture the purpose of Providence in committing the writings of the New Testament to such uncertain and varying guardian- ship, unless it were to teach us that the Spirit which is given to us ii a more certain guide than Scripture, whom therefore it is our duty to follow.' » Introduction to the Canonical Books of the Old Testament, p. 476. Cf. also Encyclopoedia Biblica, p. 665. < So Bishop Ryle thinks j but no certainty has been arrived at. vii.] AUTHOKITY AS A GKOUND OF FAITH 109 Wisdom can have been excluded only because it was written in Greek. The scribes seem to have acted on the belief that the age of inspired prophecy was now past, and not to have purposely admitted any recent work. The grandson of the son of Sirach does not dare to claim for his grandfather's book so much inspiration as the latter clearly believed himself to have possessed. The Canon was being closed. But the rigid doctrine of inspiration was not formulated at once, as is shown by the state of the text of the LXX.^ Only by degrees were the other Scriptures raised to the same position as the Law. Meanwhile, the allegorical method of interpreting Scripture was at once making the written word more august, and removing objections to belief in its divine character. Hatch has shown that this method is Greek in its origin, and goes back as far as the fifth century b.c.^ Plato deprecates it. * It would take a long and laborious and not very happy lifetime,' says Socrates, to find the allegorical value of all the old myths. It was, however, pursued by apologists for the Pagan legends ; and when the Alexandrian Jews adopted Greek culture, they found the same method serviceable in meeting objections to their own sacred literature. Philo is our great instance of this, which he calls ' the method of the Greek mysteries.' In his hands ' every living figure who passes across the stage of Scripture ceases for all practical purposes to be himself, and becomes a dim personification. Moses is intelligence ; Aaron is speech ; Enoch is repentance ; ^ Noah righteousness. Abraham is virtue acquired by learning ; Isaac is innate virtue ; Jacob is virtue obtained by struggle ; Lot is sensuality ; Ishmael is sophistry ; Esau is rude disobedience ; Leah is patient virtue ; Rachel innocence.' ^ Thus the whole Bible becomes an insipid 1 Sanday, Inspiration, p. 262. 2 Hihhert Lectures, 1888, p. 59. * Farrar, History of Interpretation, p. 145. no FAITH [cH. ethical and metaphysical romance, the interpretation of which is either an arbitrary fancy or a learned science. The Apostolic Fathers are almost equally absurd in their exegesis ; but they propound no theory of inspiration. Justin Martyr is the first to use the figure of a man playing on a harp, which he says, is like the manner in which the Divine Spirit uses righteous men, to make what sound he will.^ The use of allegory was first elaborated (with reference to Christian literature) by the Gnostics, and is opposed by Tertullian. But it took firm root in Alexandria ; and this was one of the most characteristic differences between the Alexandrian school and that of Antioch which discouraged allegorism. Irenaeus advocates the most mechanical view of inspiration; Tertullian lays more stress on the character of the medium chosen.^ Origen's principles of exegesis permit him to acknowledge many discrepancies in the New Testament. There are many incidents in the Gospel, he says plainly, which are not literally true. As the evolution of Catholicism proceeded, the authority of the Church, and of the ' tradition ' guarded by the Church, grew steadily at the expense of the Bible. The authority of the latter was not disputed, but it was ignored ; the majority had small opportunities of even knowing what the Scriptures contained. The Schoolmen improved upon Origen's allegorism by finding a fourfold sense in Holy Scripture — Hteral, moral, allegorical, and anagogical. Their subservience to Patristic exegesis is quite Talmudic. Alcuin says that he has written ' cautissimo stylo providens ne quid contrarium Patrum sensibus porter em. ^ So matters stood when the Reformation came. By the Reformers allegorism was attacked at once, especially in England. Tyndale writes very sensibly : ' We may 1 Athenagoras, Leg. 9, uses the same figure. Hippolytus, too, retains it» but guards it against the error that the prophet loses his senses while under inspiration. 2 Cf. Bethune Baker, Chnstian Doctrine, p. 46. VII.] AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH HI borrow similitudes or allegories from the Scriptures, and apply them to our purposes ; which allegories are no sense of the Scriptures, but free things besides the Scriptures altogether in the liberty of the Spirit. Such allegory proveth nothing ; it is a mere simile. God is a Spirit, and all His words are spiritual, and His literal sense is spiritual.' ^ So Colet says : ' The New Testament has for the most part the sense that appears on the surface ; nor is one thing said and another meant, but the very thing is meant which is said, and the sense is wholly hteral.' In Germany, Luther also pronounced against allegorism, and with his habitual intemperance of language described allegory as mere ' monkey- tricks,' ' dirt ' or ' scum.' We may follow St. Paul's example, he says, and occasionally use allegories as spangles and pretty ornaments, but that is all. This return to sane methods of interpretation was dearly purchased. The allegorical method had become very futile in the hands of the schoolmen ; but for Origen it was a means of accommodation by which moral and other difficulties in Holy Scripture could be set aside. The theory of verbal inspiration was far less difficult under medieval Catholicism than for a modem Pro- testant, for the literal sense could be disregarded in favour of some fanciful, but edifying interpretation. The combination of the literal sense with verbal in- spiration first appeared at the Reformation ; ^ and it has been the great weakness of Protestantism ever since. Of course, the system could not be consistently applied. Luther himself, very naturally but very inconsistently, introduced a new allegorism. His six rules of hermen- eutics are : — (1) necessity of grammatical knowledge ; (2) importance of taking into consideration times and 1 Farrar, History of Inter/)retaHon, p. 300. * Cf. Hamack, History of Dogma, vol. vii. p. 247. 112 FAITH [oh. circumstances ; (So St. Augustine says very well : * distingue tempora et concordabis Scripturas.') (3) neces- sity of observing the context ; (4) need of Faith and spiritual illumination ; (5) need of keeping the ' proportion of Faith ' ; (6) all Scripture must be explained with refer- ence to Christ.^ This last canon comes in very oddly, and necessitates feats of exegesis that are quite worthy of Philo, Origen, or the Rabbis. Even so, he could not find Christ equally in all the books ; and in consequence he adopted a very bold tone in respect to some of them, not only refusing to believe that Solomon wrote the Canticles, but stigma- ^ tising St. James as ' a right strawy epistle.' TLe Apoca- lypse he believed not to be inspired, and Jude to be a late second-hand document. This fearless criticism contrasts oddly with his reverence for the letter of Scripture,^ and points to the construction of a new Canon, composed on critical grounds. The Pentateuch he of course accepted, but doubted the Mosaic authorship, and regarded this part of the Bible as of very little authority for Christians. ' We will neither see nor hear Moses ; for Moses was only given to the Jewish people, and does not concern us Gentiles and Christians.' In fact, we can only describe Luther's atti- tude towards the Scriptures as a mass of inconsistencies. His theory of inspiration was mainly a residuum of his Catholic training. On the other hand, his view of Faith is really independent of this belief, (being based on the subjective assurance of the Christian consciousness\ This consciousness is therefore a parallel authority with the Scriptures. The Word of God is to be found partly in the Bible, partly in the consciousness of the Christian. He really cares little for any part of the Bible which cannot be * referred to Christ.' Calvin is a much greater expositor than Luther ; but his 1 Farrar, p. 332. * * One letter of Scripture,' he said, * is of more consequence than heaven or earth.' VII.] AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 113 view of the authority of Scripture is even more ambiguous. He seems to admit of no difference in value between the various parts of Scripture, while at the same time he asserts verbal inspiration, and yet rejects with scorn the whole ceremonial law. Meanwhile, the Council of Trent was defining its theory of Inspiration. It is a remarkable fact that up to this time the Canon had never been fixed. Not only were the books of the Apocrypha included in the Old Testament, in disagreement with the Hebrew Canon, to which the Re- formers reverted, but other books, such as the Shepherd of Hermas, were included in some manuscripts in use. The Council rejected these, but rehabilitated the Apocrypha, and declared that Hebrews was written by St. Paul. With regard to the authority of Holy Scripture, the Council declared : ' That truth and discipline are contained in the books of Scripture and in unwritten traditions, which, having been received from Christ's own lips by the Apostles, or transmitted as it were manually by the Apostles them- selves, under the dictation of the Holy Spirit, have come down to us.' Thus Scripture and tradition are put side by side as parallel authorities. This was a new thing, and was no doubt devised to defeat the Protestants. The authority of the Church is not mentioned in this sentence, but assuredly is not forgotten. It was enacted that ' every one shall be obliged to adhere to the sense of Holy Scripture to which the holy mother Church adheres, to whom it belongs to judge of the true sense and interpretation of Holy Scripture, and no one shall dare to set himself up against the unanimous consent of the Fathers.' It was not said how the opinion of mother Church is to be arrived at : the time was not come for openly proclaiming that the Pcpe is the Church. The history of the Roman Church since the Reformation has been a record of the constantly growing weight ascribed to tradition, at the expense of the written word. A fully H 114 FAITH [CH. developed traditionalism has no need of an inspired book, which might, indeed, have been very inconvenient but for the prerogative claimed by the Church, that is, by the Pope and his Council, of interpreting the Bible exactly as they pleased, free from any questioning of their decisions. But this gift of infallible interpretation is not often needed, for the Scriptures are too Uttle known, and too Uttle valued, in the modem Roman Church, to enter into serious com- petition with Catholic tradition. - ^^ It might be supposed that the Roman Church would have seen and utiHsed the immense advantage which their system possesses, as compared with those of the Protestant bodies, in being independent of any theory of inspiration. It might be supposed that they would have granted to their students a liberty in dealing with problems of Biblical criticism greater than has been generally conceded in Protestant Churches ; and that they would thus have been able to claim that Catholicism, on this side, puts far less strain on the intellect than orthodox Protestantism. They might have taken this course without in any way endanger- ing the real foundations on which the authority of their system rests. Such, however, has not been their policy. Since the accession of the present Pope, the most uncritical notions about the Bible have been reaffirmed and made binding on all Catholics. The books of the Bible, it is declared, were all written by their traditional authors. The Pentateuch did not gradually grow into its present form. The Patristic expositors were superior in learning and piety, and in their methods of exegesis, to the scholars of the nineteenth century. No concession whatever is made to ' Modernism ' on this side, any more than on any other. The Pope's advisers are perhaps not so ill-advised as most EngUshmen think. The expostulations of the intellect have already been so thoroughly trampled on in that Church that a small additional burden is not worth considering ; VII.] AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 115 while if Liberalism is allowed to gain a foothold anywhere, it may be difficult in the future to say, ' Thus far shalt thou go and no further.' In any case the result is that in the Roman Church, though no independent authority remains to the Scriptures, its members are tied to an even more rigid and irrational theory of inspiration than that which has prevailed in the Reformed Churches. Among the German Protestants the comparative free- dom of Luther's own teaching about the Bible soon gave way to an iron, or wooden, scholasticism. In their contro- versy with Rome they needed a rival oracle, and found it in the Bible. Bibliolatry was soon in full flood. To speak of solecisms in the style of the New Testament writers was blasphemy against the Holy Ghost. Hellenistic Greek was not poor Greek ; it was holy Greek — a form of speech peculiar to God.^ The vowel points and accents of the Hebrew Bible were directly inspired. Not a single word of the Gospel narrative comes short of absolute accuracy. Moreover, magical powers came to be attributed to the Bible. Just as some humanists had consulted scyrtes Vergiliance, so both the Wesley brothers advocated this mode of divination with a Bible when in difficulty. The Lutheran mystics, Frank and Weigel, protested in vain against this bibliolatry. ' It is an abuse and super- stition,' says Frank, ' to treat Scripture as every one is in the habit of doing, to make it into an oracle, as though we were no longer to ask counsel of the Holy Spirit, no longer to resort to God about anything, but only to Scripture.' And Weigel wrote : ' Knowledge must well out from with- in, and must not be introduced merely by a book, for this is in vain. It is the most mischievous deception when that which is most important is rejected. We put out a person's own eye, and then try to persuade him that he ought to see with some one else's eye.' ^ 1 Farrar, p. 374. * Cf . Pfleiderer, Philosophy of Religion, i. p. 11. 116 FAITH [cH. So Protestantism rapidly fell back under the tutelage of the weak and beggarly elements, and became, like its rival, a religion of authority. The nemesis has been severe. Our false views of inspiration gave us many searchings of heart during the last half of the nineteenth century ; they survive to cripple the usefulness of the noble Evangelical party, which in this country still shows an unfortunate antipathy to modem Biblical scholarship ; and they have alienated an incalculable amount of devotion and energy which ought to have been at the service of the Church. The theory of verbal inspiration is indeed more incapable of defence than the theory of an infallible Head of the Church. The writers of the sacred literature certainly make no such claim for themselves ; nor can their in- errancy be proved by internal evidence. The Bible, in fact, needs another authority to guarantee its authority ; and where can Protestants find such a guarantee ? In the Roman Church, as we have seen, the Canon was not finally fixed till the Council of Trent, and the Vatican now is content to enjoin the acceptance of current traditions as to authorship, etc., with a contemptuous disregard for the weight of evidence. In earlier times it was necessary to use one's private judgment, giving due weight to authority. Augustine says : ' In regard to the Canonical Scriptures let him follow the authority of as many as possible of the Catholic Churches, among which, of course, are those which are of Apostolic foundation, or were thought worthy of having Epistles addressed to them. He will therefore follow this rule as to the Canonical Scriptures, to prefer those which are accepted by all the Catholic Churches to those which are accepted only by some ; and among those which are not accepted by all to prefer those which the greater and morj important Churches accept to those which are accepted by fewer Churches, or those of less authority.' ^ At this period, authenticity was rightly re- * Augustine, De Doctr. Christi, ii. p. 8. I I AUTHOKITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 117 garded as of small moment. Jerome says that it does not matter who wrote the Epistle to the Hebrews, since in any case it is the work of a Church- writer, and is constantly read in the Churches.^ The acceptance or rejection of doubtful books was largely determined by their agreement or disagreement with the beliefs of the Church, and with undisputed Canonical writings. The Reformers could not accept the living Catholic Church as the authority for Biblical inspiration, nor did it occur to them to have recourse to the verdict of the un- divided Church — that distinctively Anglican theory. To judge the Bible ' like any other book ' would have been fatal to the position in which they wished to place it, as an oracle to be obeyed without question. Accordingly, they fell back, for the most part, on what they called the testi- monium Spiritus Sancti, which for them was not the voice of the Church, but the feeling of assurance and comfort awakened in the heart of the believer by the perusal of the sacred pages. The Westminster Confession thus states the grounds for believing in the authority of Scripture : * We may be moved and induced by the testimony of the Church to a high and reverent esteem of Holy Scripture, and the heavenliness of the matter, the efficacy of the doctrine, the majesty of the style, the consent of all the parts, the scope of the whole (which is to give glory to God), the full discovery it makes of the only way of man's salvation, the many other incomparable excellences, and the entire perfection thereof, are arguments whereby it doth abun- dantly evidence itself to be the Word of God ; yet notwith- standing, our full persuasion and assurance of the infallible truth and divine authority thereof is from the inward work of the Holy Spirit, bearing witness by and with the word in our hearts.' Now this is an admirable statement of what revelation through the Bible really is. The ' testimony of the Holy 1 Sanday, Inspiration, p. 52. 118 FAITH [CH. Spirit ' is the response of our inmost personality to the external stimulus supplied by the inspired literature. This testimony I have argued to be the primary ground of Faith. It is ' God working in us,' and working through concrete experiences of various kinds, as it appears that He always does work. But this is not a theory of inspiration which can either erect Scripture into an oracle for deter- mining off-hand difficult matters of conduct, or which can cut the knot of critical problems. The Holy Spirit testifies that the character and teaching of Jesus Christ are divine, and that we may follow Him and believe in Him with perfect confidence. It certainly does not testify that the Mosaic account of creation is scientifically correct, or that the book of Daniel was written in the sixth century B.C. The theory of a written oracle is, in fact, another instance of the almost universal tendency to arrest the normal development of Faith at a certain point. We need a light to show us our way, and it is granted to us ; but then, instead of using it, we shut our eyes and ask to be led like blind men. Clement saw this very clearly when he defined Faith as o-vito/xos yvioa-is, and spoke of it as an expedient for * men in a hurry.' That definition would disparage Faith, if he had not added that knowledge is ttio-tk iirKTTrjfioviKTJ. It is true that we must act before we know, but knowledge will come by acting, if we keep our eyes open. If Faith meant belief in the efficacy of magic, it would not lead to knowledge. The theory of verbal Inspiration is essentially static. It assumes that revelation is permanent only in its effects. Also, it admits of no degrees in inspiration. Nothing can be more contrary either to the modem way of reading history, or to the opening words of the Epistle to the Hebrews : ' God, having of old time spoken unto the fathers in the prophets by divers portions and in divers manners, hath at the end of these days spoken unto us in His Son.* Revelation is gradual, progressive, and admits of AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 119 degrees. It is personal. It is given through men who are able to receive it, and in proportion as they are able to receive it. Prophecy is conditioned by the spiritual capacity of the prophet, not by the arbitrary choice of God, selecting no matter whom as His mouthpiece. The true prophet is not inspired when in a state of frenzy or ecstasy, like the Delphic oracle. (We find in the early Church a very decided dislike of ecstatic prophecy ; it is discouraged already by St. Paul.) The inspired man is he who sees the world — the world of his own knowledge and experience — more nearly as God sees it than other men do. He inter- prets events according to their deepest meaning. We may say, if we choose, that he sees what he sees suh specie aeternitatis. He certainly so interprets what to him is the present as to throw a flood of light on what to him is the future. But plenary inspiration has never been given to any mere man. Inspired writers see further into the nature of things than other men ; but they have their limitations. The reporters of Jesus Christ are obviously unable to under- stand all that He wished to impart ; He is driven again and again to remonstrate with those who heard Him. ' fools and slow of heart ! ' ' Are ye so without under- standing ? ' We are driven every now and then to criticise even the Gospels from themselves, or rather from our know- ledge of Christ and His Gospel ; e.g. it is not likely that, after declining to give the * sign ' which the multitude demanded. He at once proceeded to refer to Jonah and the whale, and promised to give them a sign of the same order. It is not likely that He ever said, ' Tell it unto the Church,' when no Church existed. He can hardly have used the expression, * From the days of John the Baptist until now,' when He Himself lived in the days of John the Baptist. No ; there is no infallibility of this kind about the sacred records. The men were inspired, but they were not raised above the intellectual limitations of their times and of their own endowments. Christ never intended to shut up 120 FAITH [CH. His Gospel in a book. The Spirit of Truth was to be the main factor in the Faith of the Church. He was to inter- pret and call to remembrance the deposit of oral teaching enshrined in the Gospels, but also to develop it in a manner which would have been uninteUigible to the first disciples. The Christian view of inspiration, so long as it is true to the intentions of Christ, is dynamic ; and this involves a continuous moral and intellectual activity on the part of those who receive the revelation. Revelation and inspiration are the same thing viewed from different standpoints.^ Revelation is the word we use when we view the matter from the side of God, inspira- tion when we view it from the side of man.^ And both must be regarded as living, active processes. It is not possible to receive revelation passively, whether it comes through a book or in any other manner. And in order to receive it actively, in such a way as to make it our own and respond to it, we must bring to it the best of ourselves, the reasonable service of all our faculties. The more certain we are that the revelation is divine, the more convinced we ought to be that it makes an exacting demand upon us to understand and profit by it. God does not throw His best gifts at our heads, nor does He give us any- thing to save us the trouble of finding it. At the same time, we are not given conundrums to guess in matters of vital importance. We may accept Chrysostom's maxim {Comm. in 2 Thess.) that ' all necessary things are clear * (Trai'Ta ra dvayKala 8yj\a), though certainly not the pre- ceding word that * everything in Scripture is clear and straightforward.' And we shall miss much if we are satisfied with the * plain, necessary things.' Erasmus's 1 Gwatkin, The Knmuledge of God, vol. i. p. 168. • Dr. Fairbairn, Christ in Modern Theology, p. 496 seq., reverses this. *God inspires, man reveals. Inspiration is the process by which God gives ; revelation is the mode or form in which man embodies what he has received.' This is to use ' revelation ' in a forced and unusual sense, which even the authority of Martineau can hardly justify. I I VII.] AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 121 advice for the study of the Bible is good. ' Adsit pia curiositas et curiosa pietas.' The desire for an infaUible guide is so strong in the human heart that it often causes distress and disappoint- ment to show that the inspired records were drawn up by falhble human beings ; that the selection of the Canonical Books was made by fallible men, who, in certain cases in the Old Testament, and in at least one case (that of 2 Peter) in the New Testament, appear to have been deceived by documents which claimed a greater antiquity and authority than they possess ; and lastly that unless the reader of the Bible is also infallible and miraculously protected against human infirmity, there is no guarantee that he may not entirely misunderstand what he reads. But those who feel distress cannot have understood the nature of Faith. An infallible oracle would destroy the possibihty of Faith, or at least would finally arrest its growth at the point where the revelation was made. The ' Bible of the race ' ^ is not yet fully written ; and our powers of understanding all that is aheady written are limited. And we must not forget that an exaggerated view of the infallibility of Holy Writ depresses and de- prives of authority all the other channels through which we are justified in believing that the divine will is made known to us. I do not refer only- to the writings of great and good men outside the Canon, and even outside the Christian Church, to whom a minor degree of inspiration may be attributed without any disrespect to the Bible, but to divine revelation through science, through art, through the beauties of nature, through the course of history, and so forth. Make any one of these infalHble and exclusive, and the rest lose their value. Our conclusion then is, that, as in the case of the infallible Church, so in the case of the infallible Book, the attempt to make authority a primary ground of Faith has failed. * Lowell : * Slowly the Bible of the race is writ.' 122 FAITH [CH. Revelation and inspiration, being really two aspects of t he same process, can never be separated from each other. Revelation, like inspiration, is a process, not a static con- dition. There are adequate reasons for putting the Bible in a class by itself, above all other books ; but not for regarding it as the primary ground of Faith. The only word that our Lord ever wrote, so far as we know, was traced with His finger on the unrecording ground. It was not His will that His religion should be, like Islam, the religion of a book. He wrote His message on the hearts of a few faithful men, where it was not to be imprisoned in Hebrew or Greek characters, but was to germinate like a seed in fruitful soil. 'The words which I have spoken to you,' says the Johannine Christ, * they are spirit and they are Hfe.' The office of authority in religion is essentially educa- tional. Like every good teacher, it should labour to make itself superfluous. The instructor should not rest content till his pupil says, ' Now I believe, not on thy saying, but because I see and know for myself.' Theology is the most conservative of the sciences, and among other tendencies of bygone days it has retained a timid and superstitious reverence for the written word, whether it be text or commentary. Too many theologians persist in looking back, though the people are looking for- ward. They look back, and they pay the penalty for doing so, like Lot's wife. The deserts of theological literature are strewn with these dreary pillars of salt. Commentaries on the Old and New Testaments, full of palpably absurd explanations borrowed from the Fathers ; books on dog- matic theology constructed on the same principles ; anxious researches into the liturgies and ritual of the Middle Ages with a view to careful imitation — all alike show how potent the dead hand is in matters of religion. The scribe who is instructed to the Kingdom of Heaven, said our Lord, is like a householder who brings out of his 1_ ■ VII.] AUTHORITY AS A GROUND OF FAITH 123 treasure things new and old. The wise scribe does not, however, bring forth some things that are new and other things that are old, but he gives a new life to things that are old (for indeed we cannot truly beUeve in our authority unless we believe with it — the truth must be bom anew in the heart of every behever), and he discerns the ancient, eternal truth of what seems to be new. In part, our objection to orthodox dogmatism is that it does not go back far enough. ' Res ipsa, quae nunc Christiana religio nuncupatur, erat apud antiques, nee defuit ah initio generis humani, quousque ipse Christus veniret in came, unde vera religio, quae iam erat, coepit appellari Christiana."^ ^ The ultimate authority, which alone is infallible, is the eternal and living Truth. 1 Aogastine, Retract, i. 13, 9, 124 FAITH fcH. CHAPTER VIII AUTHORITY BASED ON JESUS CHRIST We have discussed two great historic attempts to make Faith rest on external authority. We have investigated ' the claims of the infallible Church and of the infallible '1 Book, and have found them both defective. At the same time we have found that each contains a true principle. The authority of the Church, rightly understood, is the authority of the redeemed race, the elect — the stored spiritual experience of humanity. The authority of the Book, rightly understood, is the authority of the records of revelation, the testimony of those who have been in- spired, to whom truth has been revealed. Neither authority is, or can be, absolute or infalUble ; for there is no way of escape from the objection that an infallible authority requires infallibility in the recipient as well as in the author of the revelation. If such infalUbility were in the possession of any man or any institution, there would be no room for Faith. My subject in these lectures is Faith, not the Christian Faith. But I have naturally taken my examples from our own religion, and as my aim in choosing this subject is not purely speculative, but also practical, I have felt no scruple in approaching each department of it mainly from the side which is familiar to thoughtful persons in our own age and country. And having said so much about the Catholic Church and the Bible, as the alleged seats of authority in matters of Faith, I feel that I cannot VIII.] AUTHORITY BASED ON JESUS CHRIST 125 leave the subject without considering, however cursorily and inadequately, what for very many Christians, and in a sense for all Christians, is the ultimate court of appeal, viz. neither the Church nor the Bible as a whole, but the recorded utterances of Jesus Christ, and, in matters of conduct, what those records tell us of His example and character. I shall maintain that there is a sense in which every Christian must own the authority of Christ as the primary ground of his faith. It is not enough even to say that Christ is our primary authority, leaving it open to admit other grounds of Faith besides authority. But it will be necessary to explain how this is consistent with my thesis that the primary ground of Faith is an instinct or faculty which impels us to seek and find God. We must also remember that, in connecting the name of Christ with what is primary and essential in Faith, we must be careful not to do less than justice to what is true and spiritual and genuinely religious in non-Christian ages and countries, and in high-minded Agnostics among ourselves. I hope, before the end of these lectures, to deal with both these difficulties. What kind of authority did Christ Himself claim, so far as we can judge from the Gospels ? We know that it was a distinguishing feature of His teaching, that He taught ' as one having authority, and not as the Scribes.' The doctrine of the Scrit^es was founded on documents, traditions, responsa prudentum ; that of Christ was fresh from the mint ; it wasifall at first hand, clean-cut and unhesitating. He also required that His disciples should adopt a definite attitude towards His Person. They were to ' take up the cross and follow Him.' For His sake and the Gospel's, they were to be ready to sacrifice all earthly goods, and life itself. They were never to be ashamed of Him and His words, on pain of bemg disowned at the great day. An action done in His name is meritorious ; a friendly act done to Him has the same value as an act done for God 126 FAITH [CH. Himself, who sent Him. That man is blessed, who shall not be offended in Him. He is the stone on whom whoso- ever shall fall shall be broken, and on whomsoever it shall fall, it shall scatter him as chaff. These sayings are all from the Sjmoptics. In the Fourth Gospel this personal claim is even more dominant and all-embracing. In His teaching He calmly sets aside even the revered law of Moses in one particular after another. ' Ye have heard that it was said to them of old time . . . but I say unto you ' — something quite different. ' Ye call Me Master and Lord, and ye say well, for so I am,' He tells His disciples. In spite of His meekness and gentleness He rebukes sharply any one, no matter whom, who presumes to offer Him advice. Two of the severest rebuffs recorded in the Gospels are inflicted upon His Mother and the fore- most of His disciples for attempting to suggest to Him what He should do. So far as we can judge from our records He claimed absolute obedience, unquaUfied trust and confidence. He taught and acted ' with authority ' in the fullest sense of the word. And yet there is another side. In the Fourth Gospel, no less than in the other three, Christ always declares that ' the Word which ye hear is not Mine, but the Father's which sent Me.' ' I came not to do Mine own will, but the will of Him that sent Me.' It is, after all, His cause rather than His Person, the Revelation rather than the Revealer, on which He desires to fix men's thoughts, and for which He claims their homage. He will resent no personal affronts, avenge no private injuries. The Samaritan village which refuses to receive Him remains unpunished. He declares that a word spoken against the Son of Man would find forgiveness : it is only blasphemy against the Holy Ghost that is unpardonable. He never sought to be any- thing of Himself as man, but only as the vehicle of re- demption and salvation. This combination of unlimited claims with unlimited VIII.] AUTHORITY BASED ON JESUS CHRIST 127 self-abnegation is the key to the understanding of Christ's authority. He came in the Father's name ; and the Holy Spirit was to continue His work. The former linked His mission with the past ; the latter with the future. The Faith in Himself and His Person which He demanded was not a homage which obliged the Jew to renounce his past, nor the Gentile his future. He came not to destroy the Law and the Prophets, but to fulfil them. He placed Him- self in the line of historical evolution. The law and the prophets were until John. At that point — with the appear- ance of the last and greatest of the prophets, His own immediate forerunner — the old dispensation had fulfilled its historical task of a TratSaywyos. The time had now arrived for humanity to come of age and live the freer, fuller, more responsible life of manhood. ' Ego sum cibus grandium,' as Augustine heard Christ say to him. But the God of the prophets was His Father, and it was as His envoy that He came to the people of His choice. And it is equally certain that the Galilean ministry was not intended to be the last stage in God's active dealings with men. Nothing was further from Christ's intentions than to leave a code of legislation for all future generations. Neither the substance of His teaching, nor the manner in which He chose that it should be transmitted, is com- patible with any such intention. His teaching lays down all-embracing principles ; it gives few or no rules. The difference between it and the Old Testament legislation differs not only in the often-noticed fact that the latter is chiefly negative in form, the former positive. There is an even greater difference, in that the Law is dead, the Gospel alive. The Law, like all other sacrosanct codes, must end in cramping and fettering the growth of those who are subject to it. The Gospel looks forward, ^ and has in itself a principle of growth and development which, so long as i This IS true, whatever views may have been entertained by the disciples a» to the approaching Parousia. 128 FAITH [CH. His Cliurch was true to itself, could never leave it behind the true progress of civilisation towards the realisation of all the highest potentialities of mankind. ' I have still many things to say unto you, but ye cannot bear them now. Howbeit, when He, the Spirit of Truth is come. He will guide you into all truth ; for He shall not speak of Himself ; but whatsoever He shall hear, that shall He speak ; and He will show you things to come.' The action of the Father, of the Incarnate Word, and of the Holy Spirit are thus indissolubly linked together. The Son comes to reveal the Father, the Holy Spirit to reveal the Son, or the Father through the Son. There is no question of a dynasty in three reigns ; but there is a Trinity of dispensations, that of the Father before the Incarnation, that of the Son during the earthly life of Christ, that of the Spirit ever since. The third period may Justly be called the ' reign ' of the Son, but assuredly not as super- seding that of the Father, nor as looking forward to a later reign of the Spirit. There is, no doubt, a difference between the mode of action of the Incarnate Christ, and that of the Spirit. The former was external, the latter internal. The Incarnate Christ addressed Himself to all who came in contact with Him ; the Paraclete is a principle of spiritual hfe in the hearts of beUevers, on whom He acts directly and without intermediary. But the New Testament writers are far more concerned to identify the indwelling Spirit with the exalted Christ than to separate them. Bengel's words, * Conversio fit ad Dominum ut Spiritum,' are thoroughly PauHne. St. Paul speaks quite indifferently of the Spirit, the Spirit of God, the Spirit of Christ, and Christ. In one passage he formally identifies the exalted Christ with the Spirit, at least as regards their functions. 'The Lord is the Spirit ; and where the Spirit of the Lord is, there is liberty.' If we are guided by the New Testament, we must dis- possess ourselves of the idea that the Incarnation came to AUTHORITY BASED ON JESUS CHRIST 129 an end within a few weeks of our Lord's last Passover on earth. When Christ said, ' I will not leave you orphans, I will come to you,' He was not using a metaphor, but making a real promise. ' Lo, I am with you all the days, even to the end of the world.' You will see at once how this bears on the question of the authority of Christ as a primary ground of Faith. To those who share the religious philosophy of St. Paul and St. John there is no difficulty — or rather, there is an ab- solute necessity — in identifying the mainspring of religion in the heart of man with the action of the Second Person of the Trinity. If any philosophy has a right to call itself the philosophy of the Christian religion, it is that which won the intellect of the ancient world for Christianity in the third and fourth centuries, which shaped our Creeds, and which has satisfied the deepest Christian thinkers from that time to our own day. According to this philosophy, \ there is an unbroken chain uniting the creative Logos, through whom all things were made, with the historical Jesus of Nazareth, and with the mysterious Power which works unseen in every human soul^ The universe, as Bishop Westcott says, is the hymn of the Word to the glory of the Father. This World-Spirit was once incar- nated in a human Ufe. That Hfe is the expression of the meaning of the world, so far as the meaning of the world can find expression in a human life. Christ re- vealed to us that God is the Father of His creatures ; that God is Light, Life, Love, and Spirit (I will not now stop to draw out the meaning of these pregnant utter- ances) ; and above all. He revealed to us in word and deed the law of sacrifice, of fife through death, which is'C the master-key to the understanding of the universe. We are quite right in calling this revelation final ; but we must remember that it was the inauguration of a new dispensation of revelation, not the termination of an era of direct divine intercourse with mankind ; and also that this new dispensa- I 130 FAITH [cH. tion is characterised by inwardness — by the action of the Spirit of Christ bearing witness with our spirit. The primary ground of Faith may be identified with the authority of Christ, if by Christ we mean * Christ that died ; nay, rather that is risen again.' It is not strictly correct to say that the historical Jesus of Nazareth, whose mission terminated when He ceased to walk and teach in Gahlee and Judaea, is the primary ground of Faith. To say so would be to adopt a static and not a dynamic view of Faith. It would rivet our gaze on the past instead of on the future. It would commit us to a pessimistic view of the course of history. It would fill us with disquieting doubts ; for how can we base our Faith on the shifting sand of historical tradition, which leaves us at the mercy of the good faith of reporters about whom we know little or nothing ? Those who think otherwise are compelled to choose between the apologetics of the evidential school, of whose methods we may surely say that by them * nothing worth^ proving can be proven, nor yet disproven ' — at any rate within the religious sphere, or, as an alternative, they must rest their religion on the mere subjectivity of feel- ing, which we have found to be so utterly inadequate and treacherous a ground for a living Faith. I wish, however, to give you as fair an account as I can of the attempts which have been made to arrest Faith at this stage — to fix it as consisting of devotion to a historical figure which was finally withdrawn from any further direct influence upon human affairs nearly nineteen hundred years ago. In speaking of the Lutheran treatment of the Bible I said that, though Holy Scripture as a whole was elevated to a primary authority in matters of Faith, the real centre was found in the Person of Christ, roimd which all the Old Testament, as well as the New, was made, by forced and unnatural exegesis, to revolve. Modem Lutheranism, as represented by the Ritschlian VIII.] AUTHORITY BASED ON JESUS CHRIST 131 school, does not follow Luther in this new Scholasticism. Indeed, Ritschl boldly affirms that ' the ideas of the Reformation were more concealed than disclosed in the theological works of Luther and Melanchthon.' But the language of Ritschlians about the * historical Christ' is very similar to that of Luther. It is part of their theory that the Christian Church began to go wrong from the very first, i.e. as soon as Greek influences began to modify the Palestinian gospel. Forgetful of the essentially quiet and unemotional character of Christ's teaching, they find true Christianity in the enthusiastic revivaUsm of St. Paul's Corinthian converts, and complain (as Hamack does) that Christianity was ' secularised ' when ' what made the Christian a Christian was no longer the possession of charisms, but . . . the performance of penance and good works.' They can see Httle but progressive decline be- tween St. Paul and the Reformation, and the Reforma- tion, it appears, has never yet rightly understood itself. * History,' for Faith, begins and ends, according to them, with the ministry of Christ in Palestine. Dislike of Greek metaphysics has much to do with this view. It is part of the movement against speculative intellectualism, which swept over Germany and almost destroyed the once tyrannical power of Hegel's philosophy. Of the rigorous moralism and theoretical agnosticism of the neo-Kantians I must speak later. Here I wish to consider only their Christology, and especially the real sig- nificance of their maxim, ' Back to the historical Christ.' It goes without sayiug that the orthodox Church doctrine of the Trinity, and of the Incarnation of the Eternal Son, is condemned by this school as part of Greek metaphysics. They do not object to our speaking of the ' Godhead ' of Christ, if we add that this statement is only a judgment of value, not of fact. (I shall discuss the validity of this anti- thesis in a later lecture.) This is no arbitrary view ; it belongs to the logic of the system. If metaphysics, that is to say 132 FAITH [ca the quest of ontological truth, is ruled out as having nothing to do with reHgion ; if, moreover, a theory of know- ledge is held which confines us to phenomena and puts absolute truth wholly out of our reach ; if all mysticism, in- cluding of course the Pauline doctrine of the unio mystica, is rejected as ' Catholic piety ' ; what have we left but a Christ who for us somehow * has the value of God ' ? If the Ritschlian is pressed further as to what he means by this phrase, he probably answers : First of all, Christ is the perfect revelation of God to men. He manifests to us the will and character of God. He who knows Christ, knows the Father also. Secondly, He completely identi- fied Himself with God's will and purpose. Instead of the orthodox union of natures, we have a complete harmony of wills, which, from the peculiar standpoint of this school, is a greater thing. Thirdly, they say, He manifests a com- plete supremacy over the world, in the sense of inward independence of it. This is a characteristic .survival of Luther's own thought, that the Christian is essentially the world's master. It is not an idea which has any pro- minence In a well-balanced Christianity, but it is extremely popular in German Protestantism. ^ As the result of these qualities in Jesus Christ we are allowed to say that He has for us the value of God, and are forbidden to ask any more questions about this Divinity. As for His present con- dition, we are given to understand that He is living some- how and somewhere in glory, but this belief is carefully and jealously deprived of any religious significance by the reiterated warning that the exalted Christ is hidden from us, and cut off from any direct contact with us, even in the life of prayer. Thus the mystical Christology, which was the root and source of all St. Paul's personal religion, and the inspiration of his life, is repudiated absolutely. The Incarnation lives only in its effects. ' The work of Christ in the state of exaltation must be represented by I Orr, The Ritschlian Theology ^ p. 128. VIII.] AUTHORITY BASED ON JESUS CHRIST 133 the permanent effect of His historical appearance.' ^ This Christology is closely akin to the theology of the Deists, according to whom God created the world, and then left it to itself. The exalted Christ of Ritschlianism is a roi faineant, politely ushered, like the Epicurean gods, into some astral limbo where He is comfortably out of the way. It is not clear why these men do not say plainly that He passed finally out of existence on Good Friday ; for the logic of their system has no further use for Him. Ritsch- lianism in fact has no eschatology. In place of the Christian doctrine of eternal life, we have phrases like the following curious sentence : ' Man compares himself with the whole natural system, since in his spiritual self-feeling he apprehends himself as a being who in greatness stands near to the supra-mundane God, and makes the claim to live, notwithstanding the experience of death.' Whether this * claim ' is allowed or disallowed we are not told, though the matter is presumably of some interest to man- kind. The truth is, that according to the logic of the system there is no room for a future life. * The world's master,' when removed from the world, is a king without a kingdom. There are many German theologians who are in partial sympathy with Ritschl, but who accept the Resurrection, the continued activity of the living Christ, and the future life. Herrmann, the author of the little book Communion with God, which has a great popularity in his own country, and has been translated into English, occasionally indulges in language about the exalted Christ which is in flat con- tradiction with his principles, and in consequence, in spite of his violent tirades against mysticism, he has been accused by more logical Ritschlians of falling himself into the error of the mystics. ^ Kaftan, one of the ablest of the school, fairly breaks away from it in his Christology, and 1 Ritschl, quoted by Orr, p. 134. » Orr, p. 223. 134 FAITH [CH. says : * Even Christ has become to us, in this age, a distant historical appearance. The sole means of removing this impression is a powerful and immediate faith in, and communion with, the exalted Christ.' Compare this with Herrmann's : ' Of a communion with the exalted Christ there can be no question.' Another point in which the position of Ritschl has obviously become untenable, even to his disciples, is the virtual denial of any other channel of revelation except the historical Christ. Instead of forcing Christology into the Old Testament, like Luther, the Ritschlians denied the latter any value at all. Nor was any value attached to revelations coming from secular history, science, or art. The vigour and rigour of this position have been found impossible to maintain. My object, however, in this lecture, is not to criticise any particular school of theology, but to arrive at a clear idea of what is meant by saying that for us Christians Christ is our primary authority. According to the view which I uphold, and which has been that of the best Christian philosophy from the first, there is an original, natural bond between God and the human soul. This innate * tendency to God,' as Robert Browning calls it, may be explained or expressed in very various language. To the psychologist, who rightly dis- claims the intention of establishing ultimate truth by means of mental science, it is simply a fact of consciousness to be taken note of and analysed as it stands. He will give no answe • to the question whence it comes, or whether it is in correspondence with any objective external reality. He will not attempt to determine whether its source is human or divine, whether it belongs to ourselves or is imparted by God. The scholastic mystics had their own names for it. They often called it by the queer name irvvTrjprja-iSf the origin of which is obscure. They explain it as a faculty which never consents to evil, a sort of divine VIII.] AUTHORITY BASED ON JESUS CHRIST 135 core of the soul, by which it can come into touch with what is akin to it, the divine nature. It is much the same as the K€VTpov ^vxrjs of Plotinus, and the Funkelein of Eckhart. According to the Logos-Christology, this can only be the operation of the creative and indwelling Logos which ' became flesh ' in Jesus Christ. Put away, if you will, all that is fanciful and arbitrary in these figures. But do not lightly surrender the belief which they try to express: that there is in the human soul a potential God-conscious4 ness, which was antecedent to the historical revelation, \ and was a necessary condition of it. For the mystics are surely right in holding that like can only be known by like. ' If there were not something akin to the sun in us, we could never behold the sun.' If this is denied — if there is no such inner bond between human nature and the divine, it is very diffiqult to show how the two can ever be brought together. And so we find that the revelation of Jesus Christ, for the school which we have been considering, is not so much a reconcihation of man with God, as a \ reconciliation of man with the world. If we reject and ^ put out of court all that this school means by Mysticism, and also all that they mean by Natural Theology, what channel of revelation is left ? God does not act directly upon the human soul, according to them ; how then does He reveal Himself ? ' Through Jesus Christ ' is their answer ; but how was the revelation made to Him ? The apologists of this school seem to take refuge in the word 'mystery,' which is the usual expedient of a theologian when caught in an awkward dilemma. There is no mystery about it. Either Christ must have received the revelation by direct personal union with God, or the knowledge of God possessed by Christ must be only the intellectual concomitant of that right direction of the will which Christ exhibited in a pre-eminent degree. The former alternative is excluded by the whole principles of the school. For if the unio mystica is a reality between God 136 FAITH [cH. and the human Christ, why are no traces of it to he allowed between God, or Christ, and the Christian ? And the latter alternative deprives the testimony of Christ of its authoritative character.^ For remember that the unique- ness and solitariness of the revelation through Christ is one of the points which are most insisted on. If there is no essential kinship between God and man, no revelation of God to man could ever take place. This seems to be an irrefragable truth. And it follows that if Christ was divine, as the Church teaches, and in the sense which the Church teaches, His revelation cannot have been purely external or purely historical and static, but must be given to and through the Christ-like element in our consciousness. In fact, it seems to me that the doctrines of the divinity of Christ and of the indwelling Spirit of Christ stand or fall together. You will now see in what sense only I think we can accept the statement that the authority of the historic Christ is primary for Christians. Strictly, it is the in- dwelling Christ who is the primary authority ; but assur- edly I do not wish to separate the two, and postulate comme deux Christs with M. Loisy. The difference between my view and that which I have been criticising is important because my view makes revelation dynamic : it gives room for further growth ; it gives a reason and justification for the long history of the Church, seeing that only through long experience, much suffering, and many mistakes could the dispensation, begun at the Incarnation, fulfil its course and attain its end. Some of you will suspect, I am afraid, that I am mini- mising the historical facts connected with the Incarnation — whittling away the significance of our Lord's life, making it only a stage in the evolution of humanity. Well, let us ask ourselves what a fact means — whether it is just the same as a phenomenon, or whether it means something more. 1 Orr, p. 261. AUTHORITY BASED ON JESUS CHRIST 137 The distinction between fact and phenomenon has never been better explained than by that very interesting philo- sopher, Rudolf Eucken. The essential function of a fact, he says, is to yield its living meaning to the present in some imperishable form, and therefore the fact must itself first own and exercise the Hfe which it communicates. No atomic conception of a ' fact ' is possible. The ' fact ' must be what Eucken calls a Lebens-system, a systematised whole of Hfe. * Isolated events are not facts, but abstractions from them. The '* fact " must have a certain independence and capacity for development according to its own nature. If it has less than this, it is only a mutilated and fractional fact. ... A fact of history must be some historic move- ment with at least a beginning and a middle, even if it lack a finish. So understood, a historical fact is a true historical unit, and the essential significance of " unit " is " unity." A historical fact is a historical unity. Such unities do not lie on the surface of life. ... It requires spiritual insight to pass from phenomenon to fact.' ^ It is, then, a false abstraction to isolate the events of three or thirty years as is sometimes done. So isolated, they are degraded from a fact to a phenomenon. The plan of the Incarnation was to initiate a movement which in its entirety was to consti- tute a theophany in the life of humanity itself. The Christian revelation embraces, or rather is, the whole of that movement, by far the greater part of which is, for us, in the unknown future. It appears to me, then, that this attempt to isolate the records of the Galilean ministry as closing for ever the revelation of God to man, is only another example of the tendency which we have found in other cases, to arrest the natural development of Faith at a certain point, in order to gain the convenience of an unchangeable standard of belief and conduct. It is nearer the truth than belief 1 Boyce Gibson, Rudolf Eucken's Philosophy of Life, p. 41 ; and cf. Eucken's latest book, The Life of the Sjpirit. 138 FAITH [cH. in an infallible Pope or an infallible Bible ; but it is open to very grave objections, which I hope I have made clear to you. In practice, it may lead to an uncritical appeal to this or that precept in the Gospels, and, on the other hand, to a regretful repudiation of Christ's authority, on the ground that some of His precepts are manifestly inappHcable, if taken literally, to present conditions. Our Lord unques- tionably used hyperbole in His teaching. He was accus- tomed, like other teachers who wish to impress their points on a popular audience, to make without qualifica- tion statements which need qualification, and to supply the necessary correction on another occasion. In plain words, they occasionally contradict themselves ; and such formal contradictions occur in the Gospels. It follows that in order to understand them we must use reason and common sense, and consider particular sayings in the light suppUed by the teaching as a whole. This, and not the attitude of a suppliant consulting an oracle, is the proper way to consult the authority of Christ. We have also to face the possibiUty that we have not got always the exact Greek equivalents of the words used by the Divine Speaker ; and the strong probability that some of His sayings are out of their places, placed by His biographers in a wrong setting, or, in a few cases, perhaps, even wrongly put into His mouth. All this would be disquieting if the Christ of the Gospels were our sole primary authority. It is not disquieting if we may interpret particular words by the known drift of His teaching, by the witness of His Spirit in our hearts, and, to some extent, by other sources of revelation. Lastly, I am not following those modem Roman Catholic apologists who depreciate the authority of the earthly Christ in order to exalt that of the Church speaking in His name. That is an error which we have already considered and rejected. The Church is to grow up into Christ in all VIII.] AUTHOEITY BASED ON JESUS CHKIST 139 things, not out of Him into something very different. He is very much more than the historical Founder of a great institution with a very chequered record. Nor could we possibly confine His activities since the Ascension to the supervision of one religious body, however august. But the Catholic apologetic has this great advantage over the Protestant that it accepts development, and looks forward. It does not worship a dead Lord. I have now finished that part of my course which deals with authority. I have shown, I hope, that external authority, in whatever form, cannot be a primary ground of Faith, and that the authority of Jesus Christ, for the well instructed Christian, is not external, but is a voice which speaks within us as well as to us. The complete autonomy of the human spirit would be identical with perfect obedience to Christ ; His service, as the Collect says, is perfect freedom. As a matter of experience, this way of thinking about Christ does not dehumanise Him into a cosmic principle. Rather, we find with Robert Browning, that That one Face, far from vanish, rather grows, Or decomposes but to recorapose, Become my universe that feels and knows.^ That face, explained the poet to a friend, is the face of Christ. 1 Robert Browning, DramcUis Personae, Epilogut, 140 FAITH (cH. CHAPTER IX FAITH AS AN ACT OF WILL In my last lecture I considered the proper place of authority in matters of Faith, and came to the conclusion that no authority can claim to be primary except the clear affirma- \tions of Faith itself — those spontaneous assertions of the basal personality which religion calls the voice of God within us, and which philosophy, in more cumbrous phrase, might describe as the self-revelation of the objective in our subjectivity. This voice, as I have said, speaks through, rather than to, the human heart and conscience and intellect, nor is it possible to separate the divine and human elements in any act of Faith. To-day I pass to another branch of our subject, one of great interest and importance. We have resisted the temptation to arrest and fix the development of Faith in the region of undiffer- entiated feeling. We have found that reliance on external authority, of whatever kind, is at best only a makeshift, a substitute for a full and manly Faith. We have decided that Faith must operate through our natural faculties. But which of our faculties is the chosen organ of Faith ? Is it the will, or the intellect, or that specialised feeling which creates aesthetic judgments ? We must consider the claims of these faculties in turn. And first. What is the relation of Faith to the will ? Is Faith simply and solely a moral postulate, an act of choice ? Is the ground of Faith our moral decision to believe ? XX.] FAITH AS AN ACT OF WILL 141 The proverb that the wish is father to the thought assuredly calls attention to a fact which we cannot afford to forget. People do, as a matter of fact, believe things because they wish to believe them. Hobbes declared that * even the axioms of geometry would be disputed if men's passions were concerned in them ' ; and we have only to contrast a page of Euclid with a political or theological harangue, in order to realise how differently we reason when we are dealing, not with mathematical symbols having a fixed connotation, but with living ideas and disputable values. People believe what they wish to be true, both voluntarily and involuntarily. They will say without shame, ' I like to think so and so,' as a reason why they do think so. And they will not change their opinions because they are beaten in argument. He that complies against his will Is of the same opinion still. Moreover, without intending it, we often listen to the flattering tale which hope tells. Charlatans of all kinds trade on this weakness of human nature. Without it, a great many popular follies, such as betting on horse-races, and gambling at Monte Carlo or on the Stock Exchange, would come to an end. The dry hght of reason would generally convince the gambler that he stands to lose ; but he throws his desires into the scale, and vaguely hopes that ' luck will be on his side.' In matters of practice, when any end is being pursued, the advantages of a sanguine temperament are so obvious that men look very indulgently on the self-deceptions which it produces. ' If you do not hope,' said Heraclitus, * you will never find that which is beyond your hopes.' In many cases, a strong will has the power to bring about the realisation of that which it desires, and the refusal to limit hopes by the evidence of probability brings its own reward and justification. 142 FAITH [CH • None without hope e'er loved the brightest fair, I But love may hope where reason might despair.^ We encourage the wilful optimist, the dogged struggler who cannot see when he is beaten, because this temper so often achieves great things. How far are we to approve of the same temper when it is applied to our religious beliefs ? There is no doubt at all that by determining to believe a doctrine, by deliberately refusing to dwell on arguments on the other side, by refusing to listen to objections or read books by opponents, above all, by making, so to speak, a personal wager by acting as if it were true, and incurring loss should it be false — by these methods we can make ourselves believe many things against the weight of evidence. As Clough puts it : — A-ction will furnish belief, — ^but will that belief be the true one ? That is the point, you know. However, it doesn't much matter. What one wants, I suppose, is to predetermine the action So as to make it entail, not a chance belief, but the true one. There is no doubt that this is an effective and practi- cable method of determining and fixing our beliefs. The will to believe is, as Professor William James and his friends maintain, a real and actual ground of belief, whether such a belief deserves the name of Faith or not. However, the question is (and I do not agree with Clough that it doesn't much matter), not whether men do form their beliefs in this way, but whether they ought to do so. This question is the subject of my lecture to-day. One fact is indisputable. Wherever we find great emphasis laid on the practical support given by Faith as a reason for believing, there we find also intellectual scepti- 1 Lord Lyttelton, 1709-1773. IX.] FAITH AS AN ACT OF WILL 143 cism. The argument would never be advanced by any one who (to use a phrase of Eenan) ' beHeves heavily.' At the same time, it does not imp y such complete distrust in human faculties as is implied by reliance on external revelation. Writers like Mansel are complete sceptics/ whose choice of orthodoxy instead of agnosticism seems to be almost a matter of chance. Herbert Spencer was able to accept all Hansel's arguments, while rejecting his conclusion. The school which we are now to consider base their religious Faith not on external authority but on the affirmations of the * practical reason,' which is at any rate part of our endowment as human beings. They are intellectual sceptics, but moral believers. Periods of ambitious construction in philosophy are regularly followed by periods of doubt and discouragement. The imposing thought-palace, which was to incorporate in its fabric every kind of truth, betrays unsoundness in its foundations. The invulnerable Achilles is discovered to have an unprotected heel ; and forthwith scepticism threatens to engulf everything. But scepticism can always be turned against itself ; and unwilling scepticism welcomes its own discomfiture. Faith, we will suppose, finds itself menaced by natural science. But on what grounds, men soon begin to ask, is science made a judge and ruler over us ? Is not science, as well as theology, the product of human thought and of human instincts ? Her conclusions are not infallible, her fundamental assumptions are still disputable and disputed. Her chief dogma, the uniformity of nature, is admitted to be a matter of Faith. Why is Faith to be allowed an entrance at this one point and here only ? Why may we not have Faith in the practical reason as well as in the speculative ? Might it not even be plausibly maintained that the theoretical reason is more 1 So far, at least, as any philosopher can be a complete sceptic. The absolute sceptic does not construct a philosophy out of scepticism — he does not philosophise at alL 144 FAITH [CH. fallible than the practical ? Almost every paradox has been plausibly maintained by philosophers. Havrl Ao-yc^ Xoyos dvrLK€Lraij as Aristotle said ; and the greater the intellect, the greater may be the blunder. 'There are errors which lie out of the reach of an ordinary mind' :^ magna magnorum deliramenta doctorum, says St. Augustine. Further, psychology has proved that desires and emotions do influence belief. Pure reasoning is a pure figment ; no man was ever guided by pure reason. Again, what is the test of truth to which the rationalist or intellectualist refers us ? Has he any ultimate criterion of knowledge ? If not, may not what he calls superstition be as respectable as what he calls truth ? If the so-called superstitions work, they Justify and verify themselves. They may claim to be * protective organs,' or something of the kind ; and what more are the rationalist's reasons ? Lastly, these new apologists tell us that the bases of our intellectual constructions are not axioms but postulates ; i.e. we reject the alternative propositions, not because they are, on the face of them, ridiculous, but because we have * no use for them.' The will and the understanding are both instru- ments of living, and the will is the more efficient of the two. If we still desiderate some proof that the claims of our will are ontologically true, we may be reminded (as a concession to our weak-minded and benighted ' absolu- tism ') that even though the ground of our beUef in certain heories lies in the fact that we need them, we did not create the circumstance that we need them. Either the nature of things, which is responsible for the fact that we need them, is irrational, ' which is absurd,' or our needs must be founded on the real constitution of the world. The school which we are now considering deliberately s amalgamates will and feeling — thus getting a broader basis for its constructions, though discursive thought is excluded as a sort of pariah. This fusion of will and feeling seems to 1 Balmez, quoted by Eickaby, First Principles, p. 116. IX.] FAITH AS AN ACT OF WILL 145 me psychologically untenable ; it leads to an extension of the use of * will,' which is contrary to earlier usage, and very misleading. These writers set out to prove the primacy of will, and then smuggle into the idea of * will ' a great deal that does not belong to it. But they are strong on the empirical side. The influence of a steady determina- tion on the formation of character is undeniable ; and the phenomena of faith-healing, hypnotism, and suggestion point to a hitherto unsuspected potency residing in the will, and capable, at least under some conditions, of being utilised. These obscure psychical energies have been more studied and more exploited in America than in any other country ; and I believe that this fact has had much to do with the revolt against intellectuaUsm in philosophy, which is now so powerful in the United States. Not only do these phenomena seem to present a practical refutation of Spinozism, and of its modem representative the theory of psycho-physical parallelism, but the present condition of psychology seems to demand a modest hesitation in laying down any limits to the possible action of mind upon matter. It is felt that we are only at the beginning of what may be a new epoch in mental science, and that when our know- ledge has been extended and systematised, the bogey of determinism may be laid once for all, and science may be compelled to take a much humbler attitude towards religion and ethics. This line of thought is very welcome to many, who have long felt that the mechanical theory, which reduces men and women to the condition of cunningly devised automata, is fatal to moral freedom, to human dignity, and to religious hope. It is also very convenient to the conservative apolo- gist, anxious to vindicate divine interventions in history. It will be well first to give a short historical account of the growth of ' pragmatist ' tendencies in religious philosophy. The first serious attempt to exalt the will above the K 14« FAITH [CH. intellect as an instrument of religious belief was made by the Nominalist opponents of Thomas Aquinas. With the doctrine of the primacy of the will came the adoption of a practical or empirical criterion of truth instead of a theo- retical one.^ This cleavage appeared even among the mystics, the followers of the Platonic and Augustinian tradition insisting on the knowledge of God as the con- comitant or condition of spiritual progress, while there were others who maintained that a complete dedication of the will was sufficient. The latter teaching, with mystics, led to quietism, while the former was accused of tending towards speculative pantheism. The Theologia Germanica repre- sents a moderate quietism ; Eckhart is a stronger example of the pantheistic tendency. Among the scholastics proper, the school of Thomas Aquinas represented the speculative tendency, while William of Occam was the chief champion of the will and practical reason. Nominalism was at first suspected, but was afterwards encouraged, when realism was seen to favour determinism and pantheistic mysticism. NominaUsm could also do a great service to the Papacy by deciding that, since reason cannot arrive at the truth, we ought to bow absolutely to the authority of the Church. The doctrine of fides impli- cita, which practically means blind obedience, was de- veloped. But after a very short reign nominalism itself decayed, when Plato (the real Plato this time) was redis- covered. Among modem philosophers before Kant who laid great stress on the prac ical ground of Faith, we need only mention Spinoza. This writer sees the religious value of dogmas not in their actual truth, but in their power of moving to action. We are allowed and encouraged to state 1 The following brief statement of the epistemology of Nominalism will show its close affinity with Kantianism and American pragmatism. ' Theologia nos! ra nnllatenus specnlativa est, sed simpliciter practica. Theologiae objectum non est speculabile sed operabile. (^>uidquid in Deo est practicum est respectu nostri.' (Frassen.) I IX.] FAITH AS AN ACT OF WILL 147 our dogmas in the form which suits us best. The end of Faith, he says, is obedience and piety. In this theory of Faith he prepared the way for thinkers who were strongly opposed to his philosophy as a whole. Kant's attack upon the scholastic * proofs of God's existence,' and upon intellectualism generally in matters of Faith, is well known. There is, according to him, 'a deep gulf between thought and being, which nothing can overcome. Things in themselves ai'e the condition of all thought; but what exists we cannot know.' If we say that God, or the Absolute, must be self-consistent and all-embracing, we are told that the logical law of contradiction ^ is concerned, not with real things, but only with the concepts which we form about them. Logical laws are only laws of thought, not laws which bind reality. The result of this assumption is that he separates our theoretical and moral judgments as they are never separ- ated in experience, and gives us first an abstract intellectual scepticism in the Critique of Pure Reason, and then an abstract moraHstic deism in the Critique of Practical Reason. But it is a pure assumption that because the law of contradiction is a logical law, it must be only a logical law and nothing more. Indeed it is meaningless to talk about a law which is ' only a law of thought.' When we say that we cannot think of A as being at once B and not B, we are not laying down a law for psychology. Experi- ence suggests that many people are quite capable of holding two contradictory propositions simultaneously. WTiat we mean is that if we think in this way, we are not thinking truly, or, in other words, we are not thinking of things as they really are. We cannot speak of ' mere logical laws ' without falling into the extreme of scepticism. If necessary thought is no criterion of objective truth, how can we know 1 The * law of contradiction ' is that a thing cannot at the same time be both B and not B ; or, ' It is impossible at the same time to affirm and deny. ' Cf. Clarke, Logic, pp. 33-42. 148 FAITH [oh. anything ? It is strange that Kant treats with neglect, and almost with contempt, the hypothesis on which all men .act, namely, that the forms of knowing and being corre- spond because they are manifestations of the same intelligent principle.^ He did not distinguish this very reasonable belief from the ' pre-estabhshed harmony ' of Leibnitz, a theory which may be said to have died with its author. According to this philosophy, we reach solid rock only in the moral consciousness, which Kant supposes to be given to us immediately. This and this only is vouched for by Faith — ' I must, and therefore I can.' Morality thus con- ceived is as empty of contents as it is inexplicable in its origin. Kant excludes the happiness or welfare of the subject as a legitimate motive, and but for an obvious inconsistency would have equally excluded the happiness and welfare of others. For we cannot morally desire for others what we regard as indifferent for ourselves. The motive for moral action must, according to him, be simply reverence for moral law as such. But this is not a suffi- cient motive for a rational being. We cannot do our life's work like convicts at a crank, whose task is simply to expend a prescribed quantity of muscular energy. We act in order to produce something which we regard as worth producing, and the empty idea of right gives us no intelligible guidance. To make religion merely a tran- scendental projection from morals is to invert their true relationship. The abstract moral sense is a pure illusion. There is no such fixed and known code of morals as Kant postulates. There is hardly a crime or vice that has not at some time and place been enjoined in the name of morality and religion. Nor is morality ' unconditional,' as Kant supposed. Apart from the question whether pleasure and pain can be excluded from consideration, 1 In the Critique of Judgment there are hints of this solution, but they are not developed. IX.] FAITH AS AN ACT OF WILL 149 as Kant demands, we have already seen grounds for\ believing that truth and beauty exercise a co-ordinate authority with goodness as attributes of the divine mind, and refuse to be subordinated to morality. The later Kantians have for the most part modified or abandoned the moral rigorism of their master, and they have also allowed the rationalistic side of Kant's thought to fall into the background. It must be remembered that the rift which turns Kant's philosophy into a dualism is ■ still, according to him, a rift within the reason. If the ^practical and theoretical reason could make up their quarrel, or rather get into contact with each other, the problem would be solved. His philosophy is truly described as ' critical rationalism * ; and he cannot justly be classed with the thorough-going voluntarists who followed him. And yet on one side he is the father of modern anti- intellectualism. For there is only one reason, not two ; and ' the ' practical reason,' when set in opposition to the theoret- ical, and exalted above it, is after all only another name ' for the irrational will. This has become clear in the development of the neo-Kantian philosophy, in which war is frankly declared against the theoretical or speculative reason. Against this disruption of the human mind, which if pressed to its logical conclusion is fatal to all scientific knowledge, Herbert Spencer protests in language which Christian philosophy can adopt without hesitation. ' Let those who can, believe that there is eternal war between our intellectual faculties and our moral obligations. I for one can admit no such radical vice in the constitution of things.' My plan in this lecture is to consider first the recent developments of voluntarism and pragmatism in philosophy generally — of course only in bare outline — and then to deal v^ with the influence of this tendency upon Protestant and IK Catholic theology and apologetics. (It will be convenient I"""""'"**" 150 FAITH [CH. Ritschlianism preceded in time the Modernist movement in the Roman Church.) Neo-Kantianism in Germany has for the most part been either connected with the school of Protestant theology called after Ritschl, and so falls under the second of my three headings, or else, as with Lange, it has built on a sceptical or despairing view of the existing world an aesthetic superstructure, in which religion plays its part along with poetry and the arts, as an ideal embellishment of the actual. This latter attempt to build an imaginative structure on a Kantian basis does not belong to our present enquiry. We are now dealing with those who wish to base philosophy, and with it, reUgious beliefs, on free choice, directed only by the practical requirements of life in the world. This now popular unmetaphysical philosophy, which is commonly called pragmatism, has far more disciples in America than in any other country. Its pro- tagonist is Professor William James of Harvard, who has a group of disciples at Oxford, and a very large following in his own land. The word irpayfiaTiKo^y from which pragmatism is de- rived, meant in ancient Greek ' practical,' or ' businesslike.' In the political history of medieval and modem times, a ' pragmatic sanction ' has meant an inviolable compact. Kant uses the adjective in the sense of ' prudent,' of action directed to a purpose. Bismarck's poUcy was described as pragmatic, the meaning being that he was determined to achieve his ends quocumque modo. Such are the ante- cedents of the word, as now used in philosophy. Kant's use of it has probably had most to do with determining its present signification. In current philosophy, prag- matism is the theory that * all our beliefs are really rules for action ' ; and that ' to develop a thought's meaning, we need only determine what conduct it is fitted to pro- duce ; that conduct is for us its sole significance.'^ From 1 Professor W. James, Pragmatism, p. 46 I I IX.] FAITH AS AN ACT OF WILL 151 this it is made to follow that the ' true is the name of what- ever proves itself to be good in the way of belief, and good too for definite assignable reasons.' ^ Professor James is so uncompromising an advocate of the practical principle as the ground of Faith that he brings all the limitations and errors of anti-intellectualism into the light of day. His philosophy, indeed, is in parts an admirable reductio ad absurdum of sceptical opportunism as a principle of thought and action. He and his school are so determined to safeguard human personality and the freedom of the will that they give us a God who is ' limited by all other beings in the universe ' — a very constitutional President in a society of free and independent spirits — (unless indeed they prefer, as some of them do, to make the Absolute ' a society,' which is either atheism or polytheism); they deny that there are any * laws of nature ' within the sphere of the will ; they refuse to acknowledge any unity in experience, or any evidence that the universe (which one of them suggests should be called the * multi verse ') is a systematic whole. * Not unfortunately,' says Professor James, ' the imiverse is wild ; nature is miracle all.' * We must leave surprises even for God,' as another writer of the same school says. This seems a high price to pay for free-will. A ' wild universe,' where anything or every- thing may happen, and which ^ its unaccountable be- haviour administers a series of shocks even to its Creator, would seem to be a fit abode only for a very wild man, the kind of person, in fact, whom we do not permit to be at large. I will not discuss further this philosophy (if it deserves the name) of personal atomism. In proclaiming the bankruptcy of science it proclaims its own bankruptcy. From the religious point of view it has the fatal defect of denying divine immanence ; for a personal independence which rests on exclusion forbids all communion between 1 Professor W. James, Proffmaiismf p. 76. 152 FAITH [CH. God and man, as well as between man and the world. This objection, it seems to me, applies not only to the extreme pragmatists, Hke Professor James, but to the ' personal idealists ' who are not willing to follow him all the way. They have proved that it is possible to pay too dearly for the assurance of personal freedom. That freedom is not yet ours. Personality, like all else that is imperfect and y an unrealised ideal, must die in order that it may live. The way to save our ^^x^i — to ' find it unto hfe eternal ' — is not by claiming that it is lord of the creation, but by being willing to ' lose ' it in the service of grander and wider aspects of reality. Nevertheless, the ethical side of religion is so important that we cannot altogether blame those who have no eyes for any other order of truth. They think that what they call intellectualism or rationalism means in practice natural- ism — that is, acceptance of the mechanical order as divine, and a Stoical worship of the blind giant Nature, who cares only for the preservation of her types, and knows nothing of justice or mercy. The nineteenth century witne ;sed a series of reactions against the supposed tyranny of natural law ; even Huxley, in his famous Romanes lecture, could speak of the duty of * resisting the cosmic process.' But this is to accept a Manichean view of nature. It is to admit an irreconcilable dualism, handing over the world to some non-moral agency, while separating man from his environment. A truer solution is, not to discredit natural law, but to remember that science can admit no exceptions to its sway. Natural law, from the point of view of science, is universal, or it is nothing. It includes the highest principles which actuate the best of men, as well as the blind movements of inanimate things. This consideration may lead us to find spiritual law in the natural world, a far more satisfactory discovery than the notion that man can successfully defy the order of the universe. The fault, however, was largely that of some IX.] FAITH AS AN ACT OF WILL 153 scientists of the older generation, who wrote as if molecular physics could prescribe rules for human action, thus ex- plaining the highest and most complex forms of life by the simplest and lowest. We are not powerless in the grip of natural forces, to which we ourselves contribute. This is a good world because it needs us to make it better. If Bacon was right in saying that nature is only conquered by obeying her, it is equally true that she is only obeyed by conquering her. The school which we are now considering also accuses modem rationalism, and the later Greek philosophy too, of teaching that reality is ' ready made and complete from all eternity.' This view deprives the time-process of all value and meaning, and makes activity a delusion. Prag- matists insist, on the other hand, that the world is still in the making, and that to a large extent we have the making of it. It is quite true that the dynamic aspect of reality has been unduly neglected by some thinkers, and we owe a debt of gratitude to those who have revived the Aristotelian doctrine that * the end is an action, not a quality ' (t5 tcAos irpa^Ls tis eo-rtv ov ttoioti^?). Aristotle, however, never disparages the intellectual life, as this school habitually does. In him, contem- plation is the highest kind of action, and spiritual activity as * practical ' as manual labour. The pragmatists are fond of quoting ^idvota avrij ovSkv Kivel (* the intellect by itself moves nothing ') as an expression of anti-intellec- tualism. But all that Aristotle means is that intellect energising in vacuo is a false abstraction. Again, we cannot but be grateful to be reminded that the will and feelings must be constantly exercised in the endeavour to reahse facts and to work out our convictions. The struggle for the higher hfe is so hard that we tend either to leave ourselves behind, merely thinking and talking about the truth, like those of whom Aristotle says that they ' take refuge in words and think that they are philo- 154 FAITH [CH. sophers,' ' or we construct a premature synthesis of reality, on the basis of our still disordered selves. The danger of purely speculative thinking has been often exhibited, and is not diminished by the counter warning that a mixture of ethics and metaphysics results in a bad philosophy. The evil effects of one-sidedness must be recognised, and also the extreme difficulty of taking a comprehensive view without incoherence and self-contradiction. The meta- physician who determines to follow the argument whither- soever it leads him, ignoring practical problems, and not even trying to make a practical religion for himself out of his speculations, is likely to produce a more consistent intellectual system than one who all the time regards metaphysics as a handmaid of ethics, and will advocate no principles which he is not prepared to make the standard of his own conduct. Hume is, I venture to think, far more free from contradictions than Kant ; and Hume, as we know from his private correspondence, protested against the assumption that his speculative views about reUgion made it more difficult for him than for beUevers in Chris- tianity to bear a bereavement. * In these matters,' he wrote, * I do not think so differently from the rest of the world as you imagine.' ^ Thus that fearlessly honest thinker was obHged in practice to be faithless to his own intellect, and to testify to the half-truth of pragmatism as well as to the inadequacy of scepticism as a working creed. In the case of Schopenhauer we iBnd an equally independent intellectual Hfe, which apparently had no influence in elevating his moral character. Like Circe's human swine, his higher nature only made him miserable, while it left him to wallow in the mire of cowardly selfishness and sensuahty. But even from the speculative stand- point, the consistency of a philosophy which has turned its back on experience is dearly purchased. It escapes contra- dictions by refusing to consider some essential aspects of » Aristotle, Ethict, ii. 3. « Cf. Burton's Life qfHume, vol. L p. 294. IX.] FAITH AS AN ACT OF WILL 166 the problem ; and in consequence its conclusions have only an abstract and hypothetical truth. They are not true of the real world, or at any rate they have not been shown to be so. The demands of our ethical nature point to the objec- tive existence of a hierarchy of values, and these must be included in any intellectual system which claims to represent the whole truth. The difficulty of harmonising this valuation with the existential aspect of things proves to us, not that we cannot know reaUty at all, but that we know it only in part. An imperfect experience cannot construct a consistent philosophy. Let us now consider the results of what we may call ethical idealism in Protestant theology. We shall find our documents mainly in the German Ritschlian school. The foundation of the Ritschlian teaching is the assertion of the primacy of the ethical sense. With Lotze, whom he greatly admired, Ritschl held that the foundation of metaphysics is to be found in ethics : we are to seek in what ought to be the ground of what is. Like Lotze, he recognises in man a faculty of forming value- judgments y which is of greater importance than the * merely intellec- tual ' view of the world. These ' value-judgments ' take, in Ritschl's philosophy, the same place which Schleier- macher gives to undifferentiated feeling. They are the ultimate seat of authority. Both maintain that the final court of appeal is subjective experience, which is not to be checked by reference to the outer world of phenomena ; but while Schleiermacher's appeal was to a vague senti- ment, Ritschl's is narrowed and made more definite — ^his supreme court is the ethical demand. In order to preclude any disputes as to the authority of this one faculty to decide everything, * metaphysics,' which include all ' judgments of fact,' are declared to have nothing to do with rehgion. * Religion and theoretic knowledge are distinct functions, which even when applied to the same 156 FAITH [CH. object do not even partially coincide, but go totally asunder.' ^ So harsh and intractable a dualism is only tolerable if we resolve to treat one of the two sides as a neghgible quantity. And this is the treatment which Ritschlianism metes out to existential truth.^ The proper philosophical position corresponding to this view of the world is subjective idealism, which some have thought the logical conclusion from Lotze's premisses. A little more must be said about the famous doctrine of value- judgments. According to Ritschl, the judgments which we form on moral and religious subjects are ' in- dependent judgments of value.' They set forth, not the objective nature and relation of things, but only their value for v^ — their fitness to satisfy some want of our own nature. Religion, therefore, has nothing to do with ob- jective fact ; truth, in this sphere, is purely pragmatic and teleological. Ritschl, however, shrank from the logical conclusion which has been drawn by some of the modern psychological school, that God Himself has no objective existence, or that if He has. His objective existence is irrelevant to religion. He somehow regards the existence of God, and one or two other dogmas which he prized, to be guaranteed by the faculty of ' value-judging.' But this is a manifest trespass. On his principles, judgments of fact and judgments of value can never come in conflict, because they are * independent ' of each other. But to assert the existence of God is to make a judgment of fact, not a judgment of value. Or if we say that value guarantees existence, that is a judgment of fact, and the whole character of the philosophy is changed by the transit from idealism to realism. On Ritschl's principles, there is no escape from pure phenomenalism and sub- 1 Quoted by Orr, p. 61. 2 I'he school of Ritschl has split on the theory of knowledge. Herrmann is a Kantian ; Kaftan is an empirical positivist ; Bender was logical enough to proclaim an uncompromising subjectivism, for which his party, after a heated controversy, repudiated him. IX.] FAITH AS AN ACT OF WILL 157 jectivism except by a patent inconsistency.^ God is, on E/itschlian principles, at best a postulate, arising from the Judgment which the human spirit makes of its own wofth. You will gather that in my opinion the whole system is ruined by its attempt to exclude ' judgments of being ' — science and philosophy in fact — from any part in the formation or determination of religious Faith. This is partly the result of a very inexcusable confusion of termin- ology. Just as the Ritschlians extend the province of will, to cover feeling and even unconscious instinct, so they limit reason by regarding it as the faculty which merely observes and reflects on the causes of things. This is psychologically incorrect, and theologically disastrous. The creative Reason) as we learn from St. Paul and St. John, is the immanent cause and end of things. Without Reason the Will is blind deaf and dumb. And the supreme exercise of the human consciousness, which is to energise in concert with this creative Power, assuredly contains an intellectual element I shall show in my next lecture that we need by no means despair of reaching solid ground by means of the intellect. Ritschlian theology is generally as orthodox as it can persuade itself to be, and much more so, in words at least, than its principles warrant it in being.^ When set free from dogmatic presuppositions, the school of thought which we are now considering tends sometimes to the metaphysical (or rather epistemological) theory called pragmatism, which we have already discussed so far as seemed necessary for our purpose ; and sometimes to a purely moralistic conception of religion. On the whole, 1 If, however, any friends of Ritschl wish to remind me that their master has also said the exact opposite, I admit it. In the first edition of his great work {Rechtfertigung und Versohnung, p, 192) he says : * The acceptance of the idea of God is no practical faith, but an act of theoretic knowledge.' In the third edition (p. 214) this disappears, and we read : 'The acceptance of the idea of God is practical faith, and not an act of theoretic knowledge.' The second opinion is more in harmony with the dominant ideas of hia system, which, however, is riddled with contradictions and inconsistencies. 2 This is especially true of Herrmann, whose inconsistency is sharply rebuked by Pfleiderer, Philosophy of Religion, vol. ii. pp. 202, 203. 168 FAITH [CH. this theory of Faith appears in the most favourable light when it is made to support nothing except a system of ethics. The ultimate authority, on which the whole structure rests, is then the ' categorical imperative ' of Kant, the autonomous conscience. ^ The will is king — the will to obey conscience, to do right and make the right triumph. As a theory of Faith, it has seized one side of the truth ; for the fundamental religious instinct does develop, on one very important side, into an imperious desire to shape our surroundings. The religious equivalent of the prag- matist's ' conation which determines truth ' is the thirst for God which bears witness that it is caused by God. Desire does not determine truth, but truth does determine desire, and makes itself known through and as desire. But as in former chapters, we find here too that one-sidedness is fatal. I am certain that one of the great causes of what are called * difficulties ' in the way of Faith is the assumption that the universe was designed simply and solely as a school of moral disciphne and probation for human beings. It appears to me that this is a survival of a pre-scientific view of the universe. It was tenable when geocentric theories prevailed ; it is not tenable now. Our planet, and our species, have no such exclusive importance. And as for the exclusively moral character attributed to the Deity, do we really admire a character which is exclusively moral ? Do we feel much respect for one who is blind to all sense of beauty and willingly ignorant of all facts that cannot at once be converted into moral obUgations ? Is 1 Note the following definition of Faith by the Ritschlian Herrmann : 'Religious Faith in God is, rightly understood, jnst the medium by which the universal demand of the moral law becomes individualised for the individual man in his particular place in the world's life, so as to enable him to recognise its absoluteness on the ground of his self-certainty, and the ideal drawn in it as his own personal end.' Thus God vanishes in the moral order of the world and religion in morality. This however, was not Ritschl's own position : he distinguishes between religion and morals, and conjpares Christianity to an elliptical figure revolving round those two foci. But this part of his system — one of his many illogical concessions — seems to me of very little interest or importance. IX.] FAITH AS AN ACT OF WILL 159 it really a worthy or a possible conception of God, that He is interested only in conduct, and is destitute of anything corresponding to what in us are called intellectual and aesthetic interests ? If we wish to beUeve in such a Deity, we are certainly wise to construct a world for ourselves out of our wishes and sentiments, for the real world will contradict our belief at every turn. The limitations of exclusive moralism are very apparent. It is an irrational type, since it has no standard except the moral consciousness. It will not even ask why things are right or wrong ; and so it often confounds things in- different with things morally wrong, and erects senseless puritanical tabus. It rejects happiness and beauty as objects, and lays a coarse and heavy hand on the beauti- ful things of the world. It is apt to be hard and unsympathetic, and does not escape a sort of sour worldliness. Matthew Arnold calls this type the Hebraic, as opposed to the Hellenic, which represents the intellectual and artistic ideals of Ufe. He accuses his fellow-countrymen of following the Hebrew ideal too exclusively, and neglect- ing the Hellenic. Santayana, in speaking of the typically Protestant civilisation, brings a similar indictment in clever satirical form. * Protestantism is convinced of" the importance of success and prosperity ; it abominates what is disreputable ; contemplation seems to it idleness, solitude selfishness, and poverty a sort of dishonourable punishment. It is constrained and punctilious in righteous- ness ; it regards a married and industrious life as typically godly, and there is a sacredness to it, as of a vacant Sabbath, in the unoccupied higher spaces which such an existence leaves for the soul. It lacks the notes of dis- illusion, humility, and speculative detachment. Its bene- volence is optimistic and aims at raising men to a conven- tional well-being ; it thus misses the inner appeal of Christianity, which begins by renunciation and looks to 160 FAITH [CH. spiritual freedom and peace. ... It is a part of Protes- tantism to be austere, energetic, unwearied in some laborious task. The end and profit are not so much regarded as the mere habit of self-control and practical devotion and steadiness. The point is to accompUsh something, no matter what ; so that Protestants show on this ground some respect even for an artist — when he has once achieved success.'^ Such are some of the fruits of making Faith exclusively an act of the will, or moral sense. In my next lecture I shall show how the prevailing distrust of theoretical con- structions has given birth to a peculiar kind of empiricism in religion, which has produced rather startling develop- ments in the Romai. Church. ( Santajana, Reascm in Religion, p, 114^ X.1 FAITH BASED ON PEACTICAL NEEDS ICl CHAPTER X FAITH BASED ON PRACTICAL NEEDS — MODERNISM The rulers of the Roman Church have always fully recog- nised the great influence of Faith upon conduct, and have paid careful attention to the formation of beliefs. The whole educational method of Romanism assumes quite frankly that it is desirable to prejudice the minds of the young in favour of certain beliefs, and that it is justifiable to use almost any means to strengthen and confirm them. The mind of the child, under Catholicism, is moulded into a particular shape almost from his cradle ; even in the ele- mentary school-room he is not allowed to breathe a non- Catholic atmosphere ; and in mature life he is forbidden to question, even in thought, what his Church has taught him. In many cases this system is as successful in producing the type of character desired as Sandow's gymnastic course is in producing a muscular frame. The Catholic lives and dies in an untroubled assurance that he has possession of the truth ; he performs a number of actions, some morally estimable, others morally indifferent, some perhaps morally flagitious, in obedience to his directors, and abstains from others. Like a hothouse flower, he blooms luxuriantly when carefully shielded from the rude winds of free thought and free discussion. Catholicism is best regarded as an art of holiness. The theory and method of the system are those of all artistic training. The disciplr wishes to acquire certain aptitudes — in this case, a certain kind of character — and he puts himself under the care of trained experts who tell him how L 162 FAITH [oh. the desired result is to be attained. The young painter does not enquire whether the relation between his pig- ments and the object which he is trying to copy is ' real ' or ' apparent ' ; he is content if he can produce the effect of a tree or river upon his canvas. A sham relic or miracle is as good as a real one in stimulating emotion, if it is believed in. And the promised results do follow. The Catholic discipline does produce peace of mind and self- control ; it economises energy by prohibiting experiments ; it counteracts the effect of individual weakness, and utilises one line at least of racial experience. The merits and defects of this system have been already considered under the head of Authority. Here we have only to note its pragmatic character in all that falls outside religious truth. It is so much more important to avoid sin than to have correct opinions on scientific matters, that error and even imposture will often be encouraged in the interest of beHef and conduct. And yet Catholicism can never acquiesce in the subjec- tivism and anti-intellectualism of the philosophy which we have just been discussing. Catholic theology is built on a foundation of Greek philosophy, and is intimately connected with the transcendental realism of Plato and Plotinus, modified but not contradicted by the study of Aristotle. The Roman Church has anathematised the Kantian doc- trine which confines our knowledge to phenomena; it asserts that the being and attributes of God may be proved intel- lectually. The active intervention of God in human affairs is rescued from the clutches of the mechanical sciences, not by scepticism about the objective existence of the phe- nomenal world, but by behef in the supernatural. Belief in miracle, not only certain miracles in the past, guaranteed by authority, but in miracle as a part of the constitution of the world, is an essential part of Catholicism. The Catholic view of the world is a modified realism, within which it is possible to distinguish two ' orders/ the natural and the X.] FAITH BASED ON PKACTICAL NEEDS 163 supernatural, interacting on the same plane. The Church has left to its philosophers great latitude in attempting to determine the relations of the time-process to eternity, and has never shrunk from crude pictorial images in its exoteric teaching. But it has consistently refused either to accept idealism, in the post-Kantian sense, or to abandon the supernaturalism which forms the connecting link between God and nature. Modem science has inflicted a grievous wound upon this system by its denial of the miraculous. The nature of the quarrel between science and Catholic orthodoxy, on this head, is often misunderstood. Apologists are pleased when they find that wonderful cases of * mind-cure ' can be substantiated. But this line of defence can only prove that a few alleged miracles are not miraculous, not that any miracles are true or possible. What is necessary for Catholicism is to prove the intercalation of the genuinely supernatural with the natural, and this would be a refuta- tion of the uniformity of natural law, the working hypothe- sis of all the sciences. The scientific habit of mind, with its exacting rule of testimony, has become so general that belief in miracles grows harder every year. There are still a good many people who are unable or unwilling tdi separate Wahrheit and Dichtung, truth of fact from imagina-i tive representation ; but their number dwindles, and those who retain the old beHefs on aesthetic grounds are less earnest defenders of the faith than the genuinely super- stitious ; their reUgion is little more than a mode of refined enjoyment. This blow has fallen with the greatest severity on the ecclesiastical machinery. The sacerdotal and sacramental system of the Catholic Church is based on supernatural mechanism — on divine interventions in the physical world conditioned by human agency. If these interventions do not take place, almost all tha makes Catholicism attractive to the laity and lucrative to the hierarchy has vanished. 164 FAITH [cH. It was only to be expected that intelligent priests in the Roman Church, who understand the gravity of the situation, should endeavour to find a sounder basis for Catholic truth than this discredited theory of supernatural interventions. We have seen that there is much in the CathoHc view of life which is in sympathy with prag- matism, and that the sceptical Nominalists of the Middle Ages came very near to this theory of knowledge. Accord- ingly, it was inevitable that the suggestion should be made that the traditional reahsm of CathoHc apologetics should be abandoned ; and that by reducing the external world to a mere system of instruments, arranged by the human mind for its own purposes, relief might be found for distressed faith. On this hypothesis, there is no sacred- ness or inviolability in natural laws, in and for themselves. They are approximately true, as diagrams of everchanging phenomena, fixed, for purposes of observation, in a series of discontinuous pictures, like the successive scenes of a cinematograph. But even if the theoretical abstractions of the intellect corresponded accurately to concrete fact, which is not the case, what is the understanding but the tool and instrument of the will ? We want to know only in order that we may act and live. These static laws, of which we have made such bug-bears, are of very subordinate importance. The real world is the world of will and feeling, the world of action ; and if religious truths — the dogmas of the Church — are found to belong to this sphere, and not to the inferior order of existential fact, that is only what we should expect and desire to hear about them. The philosophical defence of the Modernist position has been conducted mainly by Frenchmen, among whom Le Roy ^ and Laberthonniere ^ may be named. As CathoHcs, 1 Dogme et Oritique. • Le Ji£alisme Chretien et VId4alisine Grec; Essais de phUoaophie religieuse. X.] FAITH BASED ON PEACTICAL NEEDS 165 these writers are anxious not to be classed as Kantians, since the name of Kant is obnoxious to the Roman Church ; and in truth they do not define their philosophical position very clearly. In Laberthonniere it takes the form of a revolt against ' Greek idealism,' which, he considers, was occupied with things, while Christianity is occupied with life. The Greek asked, What are things ? The Christian asks. Whence came I, and whither go I ? The Greeks were insatiable in their desire to see and know ; and in conse- quence Greek morahty is only an aspect of metaphysics. For the Greek, evil is ignorance ; good is truth, and truth is the adequate representation of things. To think is everything, because thought is sight par excellence. So came into existence the Greek philosophy of concepts. Plato and Aristotle are agreed in the service which they demand of their ' Ideas.' It is by them that they find the one in the multiple, and the stable in the mobile. These ideas are not our ideas but eternal essences, the determina- tions of which we receive without putting anything into them ourselves. Thus Greek philosophy is an intellec- tuaHsm or rationaKsm. It begins with the desire to think and see, and so it ends with a world of ideas. To enter into the unchanging intelhgible world is salvation. Thought is the beginning, middle, and end of fife. The fact of individuafity, says Laberthonniere, always embarrassed the Greek thinkers. The individual was something which ought not to exist. They longed to wipe out all dividing lines. Theirs was a * static ' ideal, good only to contemplate. But an ideal which can be thus contemplated is necessarily an impoverished view of reality, because it is like a photograph of something which is always in motion. It gives us a picture of movement stiffened into unnatural immobility ; we contemplate a picture, which can only give us some aspects, and perhaps not the most significant, of the living, changing reality. Greek philosophy provides us neither with a science of origins 166 FAITH [cH. nor a science of ends. It attaches itself to forms only. Hence follows a sovereign indifference to the accidents of life and the events of history ; for whoever can think, can always contemplate ' the ideas ' in their unchanging har- mony and beauty. This indifference, which antiquity praised, is the enemy of charity and of progress. After this indictment of the great Greek thinkers, our Modernist proceeds to contrast with * Greek idealism * the genius of Christianity. Christianity is preoccupied with life, not with things. It is not a system of ideas, fixed and unchanging, above the changing reality of the world, but it is constituted by events occupying a place in the time-series. It is itself a history, and the history is itself a doctrine, a concrete doctrine. The Bible explains the facts of history by stating them in their ' dynamic ' relations — e.g. investing the figure of Jesus of Nazareth with the attributes proper to the founder of a great Church, such as He actually did found, though without intending it. The inspired historian * looked higher ' than literal fact ; he narrates history in the Hght of his knowledge of the whole drama, of which he is only giving us the first act. Christ is not simply an object of historic certitude ; he is also an object of Faith. And it is the latter aspect which is of practical importance. At this point the Modernists divide ; it is impossible to attribute to them as a body any one doctrine about the historical side of Christianity. They desire, for the most part, that criticism rather than philosophy should be regarded as the starting-point of the movement. The authors of The Programme of Modernism (p. 16) say : ' So far from our philosophy dictating our critical method, it is the critical method that has of its own accord forced us to a very tentative and uncertain formulation of various philosophical conclusions.' But, in point of fact, some members of the school are primarily philosophical tlieo- logians, while others are primarily critics. And it is the FAirH BASED ON PRACTICAL NEEDS 167 specialists in Biblical criticism who are the most radical members of the school.^ Laberthomiiere sounds an uncertain note ^ on the value of the historical facts narrated in the Gospels. But there is no hesitation or obscurity about M. Loisy's attitude. The Gospels, he says, are hke the Pentateuch, a patchwork of history and legend. Even the Synoptics contradict each other. In Mark the life of Jesus follows a progressive development. The first to infer his Messiahship is Simon Peter at Csesarea Philippi ; and Jesus Himself first declares it openly in His trial before the Sanhedrim. In Matthew and Luke, on the contrary, Jesus is presented to the public as the Son of God from the beginning of His ministry ; He comes forward at once as the supreme Lawgiver, the Judge, the anointed of God. The Fourth Gospel goes further still. His heavenly origin, His priority to the world, His co-operation in the work of creation and salvation, are ideas which are foreign to the other Gospels, but which the author of the Fourth Gospel has set forth in his Prologue, and in part put into the mouth of John the Baptist. The difference between the Christ of the Synoptic Gospels and the Christ of John may be summed up by saying that * the Clirist of the Synoptics is historical, but not God ; the Johannine Christ is divine, but not his- torical.' Even Mark, M. Loisy thinks, probably only incorporates an eyewitness document. The Gospel which bears his name was issued, probably about fifteen years later than the destruction of Jerusalem, by a non-Palestinian Chris- tian, who Uved perhaps at Rome. The Gospel of Matthew was written by a non-Palestinian Jew who lived in Asia Minor or Syria, about the beginning of the second century. He writes in the interest of Catholic ecclesiasticism, and may well have been a presbyter or bishop who wished to 1 Cf. my article on * Modernism ' iu the Quarterly Review foi April 1909, s Compare p. 60 and p. 60 of his H^alisme Chretien. 168 FAITH [CH. advocate the monarchic episcopate. The chapters about the birth of Christ seem not to have the sHghtest historical foundation. The story of the Virgin Birth turns on a mis- understood text of Isaiah. Of this part of the Gospel Loisy says, ' Rien n'est plus arbitraire comme exegese, ni plus faible comme narration Active.' The Third Gospel, he proceeds, was probably written in the last decade of the first century ; but the first edition, which traced the descent of Christ through Joseph from David, has been tampered with in the interests of the later idea of a Virgin Birth. As for the Fourth Gospel, it is enough to say that the author had nothing to do with the son of Zebedee, and that he is in no sense a biographer of Christ, but the first and greatest of the Christian mystics. We have then, according to M. Loisy, only very corrupt sources for a biography of Christ. And the only chance of reconstructing the actual events lies in forming a mental picture of the Galilean Prophet, and rejecting all that fails to correspond to it. This picture, for M. Loisy, is that of an enthusiastic peasant, ' of Umited intelligence,' who came to fancy Himself the Messiah, and met His death in a fool- hardy and pathetic attempt to proclaim a theocracy at Jerusalem. Any statements in the Gospels which contra- dict this theory are summarily rejected in the name of what the Germans call Wirklichkeitssinn. The guillotine falls upon them and there is an end of it. The Resurrection is of course dismissed as unworthy of discussion. The corpse of Jesus was thrown, with those of the two brigands, into * quelque fosse commune,* and ' the conditions of burial were such that after a few days it would have been im- possible to recognise the remains of the Saviour, if any one had thought of looking for them.' ^ The disciples, however, had been too profoundly stirred by hope to accept defeat. They hardly reaHsed that their Master was dead ; they had fled to their homes before the last scene ; and besides, the.y 1 Loisy, Let ivangiles Synoptigues, chap. vii. X.] FAITH BASED ON PKACTICAL NEEDS 169 were fellow-countrymen of those who thought it quite possible that Jesus was John the Baptist come to life again. What more natural than that Peter should see his Master one day while fishing on the lake ? ' The impulse once given, the belief grew by the very need which it had to strengthen itself.' Christ soon appeared also to ' the eleven.' So their faith brought them back to Jerusalem, and the Christian Church was bom. * The supernatural life of Christ in the faithful and in the Church has been clothed in a historical form, which has given birth to what we might somewhat loosely call the Christ of legend.' * Such a criticism does away with the possibility of finding in Christ's teachiag even the embryonic form of the Church's later theological teaching.' ^ The Christ whom the Church worships is the product of Christian Faith and love. He is a purely ideal figure ; and it betrays a total absence of the historical sense, and a total inability to distinguish between things so essentially different as Faith and fact, to seek for His likeness in the Prophet of Nazareth. This new apologetic is likely to take away the breath of the ordinary Christian believer. The Modernist professes himself ready to admit not only all that a sane and im- partial criticism might demand with reference to the Gospel history, but the most fantastic theories of the destructive school. And then, having cheerfully surren- dered the whole citadel of orthodox apologetics, he turns round and says that nothing is lost — that for his part he claims to be treated as a good son of the Church, and wishes to be allowed to recite her creeds and observe her discipline. Let us see how he seeks to justify this position. I have already (in speaking of Church authority) said something about the Modernist theory of development. The Church is made to take the place of Christ. It is the 1 The Programme of Modernism, pp. 82, 83, 90. 170 FAITH [cH. life of the Church which constitutes Christianity. This great institution has had to Hve in the world, and to adapt itself, like every other organism, to its environment. ' If,' says M. Loisy, ' Christianity is made to consist in Faith in God as our Father, which is the extreme form of the anti- CathoHc and Protestant idea, all the hierarchical, dogmatic, and ritual development of the Church falls outside true Christianity, and appears as a progressive deterioration of the religion.' ^ But these developments were all necessary, if the Church was to survive ; and since we may presume that Jesus wished His society to survive, we may say that He would have approved whatever was necessary to be done, in order that the Church, in saving itself, might save His Gospel.^ ' To reproach the CathoUc Church with the developments of its constitution is to reproach it for having lived.' ^ It is very unlike the society which Jesus gathered round Him ; but what of that ? When you want to convince yourself of the identity of an individual, you do not try to squeeze him into his cradle.* The right of change and self-adaptation is not confined to the externals of government and ritual. Dogmas are only the images of truth, not as it is in itself, but as it appears to our minds. And if they wear out, as they do sometimes, or cease to be helpful, they may be altered without scruple. The value of symbols (and all dogma is symbolic) depends solely on the sense which we attach to them ; in themselves they are nothing. And the sense which we attach to them is above all a practical sense. ' A dogma proclaims, above all, a prescription of practical order ; it is the formula of a rule of practical conduct.' ^ Religion is not an intellectual adhesion to a system of speculative propositions. ' Why then should we not bring theory into harmony with practice ? ' ^ » Loisy, L'ivangiU et realise, p. 127. ' I^'d. . p. 138. » Ibid., p. 154. « Ibid., p. lea ■ Le Roy, Dogme et Critique, p. 25. • Ibid. JL] FAITH BASED ON PRACTICAL NEEDS 171 Le Roy gives us some examples of this Catholic prag- matism. When we say, * God is personal,' we mean, ' behave in our relations with God as you do in your rela- tions with a human person.' When we say, * Jesus is risen from the dead,' we mean, * treat Him as if He were your contemporary.' Similarly, the doctrine of the Real Presence means that we should take, in presence of the consecrated elements, the same attitude as we should in presence of the actual Jesus. His main theses may be summed up in his own words. * The current intellectualist conception renders insoluble most of the objections which are now raised against the idea of dogma. A doctrine of the primacy of action, on the contrary, permits us to solve the problem without abandoning anything of the rights of thought, or of the exigencies of dogma.' ^ M. Le Roy shows in the sequel that he ' saves ' dogma by separating it entirely from scientific fact. He regards all theological and dogmatic propositions as principles of action, not statements of fact, and then argues that since on every page he proclaims that action is more important than thought, and the dynamic aspect of things of higher worth than the static, he has triumphantly vindicated the claims of dogma against un- believing rationalism. *A dogma,' he says, *is a truth belonging to the vital order ; it presents its object under the forms of the action commanded to us by it, and the obligation to adhere to it concerns properly its practical significance, its vital value.' ^ What, then, is the value and meaning of the scientific truth which M. Le Roy is so eager to reduce to its proper insignificance ? It would really seem as if it had none, except what we choose to put into it. * No fact has any existence and scientific value except in and by a theory, whence it follows that strictly speaking it is the savant who makes the scientific facts.' ^ 1 Le Roy, Dogme et Critique, p. 34. « IMd.t p. 91. « /Md.^ p. 334. 172 FAITH [cH. There is a great resemblance between the position of M. Le Roy and that of our leading English Modernist, Mr. Tyrrell. ' The world of appearance,' he says,^ ' is simply subordinate and instrumental to the real world of our will and affections ^ in which we live the life of love and hate, and pass from one will-attitude to another in relation to other wills than our own. . . . Jn this region truth has a practical and teleological sense — it is the trueness of a means to an end, of an instrument to its purpose ; and like these truths it is to some extent conditioned by what we know and believe about its object. . . . Hence the religiously important criticism to be applied to points of Christian belief, whether historical, philosophic, or scientific, is not that which interests the historian, philo- sopher, or scientist, but that which is supplied by the spirit of Christ. Does the belief make for the love of God and man ? Does it show us the Father and reveal to us our sonship ? ' The truth of the creed is a practical or regulative truth. It is serviceable to life, and therefore cannot be a mere fiction, for no he can be serviceable to life on an universal scale. * Beliefs that have been found to foster and promote the spiritual life of the soul must so far be in accordance with the nature and the laws of that will-world with which it is the aim of religion to bring us into harmony : their practical value results from, and is founded in, their representative value.' Our assurance of their truth r^sts on ' the imiversally proved value of the creed as a practical guide — the consensus of the ethical and religious orhis terrarum* * * The rule of prayer is the rule of belief.' This means that what alone concerns us is to realise the ' prayer- value ' of the various articles in the creed. For instance, 1 Tyrrell, Lex Orandi, chap. viii. (abridged). • Note the characteristic confusion of the will and the aflfections, • An excellent example of the Catholic peiitio principii. The Roman Church constitutes the ethical and religious orhis terrartaii. The Roman Church finds its dogmas practically valuable. Therefore the universal valu« of the dogmas to ethics and religion if proved. X.] FAITH BASED ON PRACTICAL NEEDS 173 the belief in God has been fashioned by the religious needs of man's nature.^ The puzzle about free-will means that our will belongs to the world of realities, whereas our understanding can represent things only in terms of the world of appearances. 2 ' The understanding is but an instrument fashioned by the will to serve as a guide to life and action.' ^ ' The doctrine of the Trinity is the creation of love and life.' * ' While Christianity with its Trinity of divine Persons, its God made man, its pantheon of divinised men and women, is open to the superficial charge of being a reversion to the pagan polytheistic type, it is rather to be regarded as taking up into a higher synthesis those advantages of polytheism which had to be sacrificed for the greater advantages of a too abstract and soul-starving monotheism.' ^ The * facts of religious history must, as matters of Faith, be determined by the criterion of Faith, i.e. by their proved religious values.' ^ * A man will be justified in holding to the facts until he is convinced that their religious value is in no way imperilled by the results of historical criticism.' * Mistakings of faith-values for fact-values are to be ascribed to the almost ineradicable materialism of the human mind which makes us view the visible world as the only solid reality.' ^ Enough has now been said to show what form prag- matism takes in the Roman Church. M. le Roy says very truly, that the ordinary Roman Catholic ' lives pragmatism' to a much larger extent than he reahses. He chooses among the doctrines of his Church those which appeal to him, and passively accepts the rest, without making them part of his religion. He may even try experiments at one shrine after another. The Madonna of Lourdes may be kind, though her namesake at La Salette is difficult ; if 1 Lex Orandi, p. 73. « Ihid. , p. 87. 8 7&tU,p. 98. * Ibid, -p. 100. 5 P. 149. This is again a characteristic utterance which shows the vast gulf between Koman Catholicism and other forms of Christianity. « P. 169. 7 P. 191. 174 FAITH [cH. St. Anne is not sufficiently attentive to his supplications, he may try St. Joseph. Moreover, the whole Roman Church has, in point of fact, lived and thriven by self- adaptation very much as the Modernists say. Certainly it may seem a strange * note ' of divine assistance, that a Church should be obliged to change like a chameleon in self-defence ; but it is a tenable view that since Rome became less pHant and receptive, she has lost ground everywhere. And pragmatism may be called in to explain accommodations which would otherwise be rather difficult to justify. Nevertheless, I believe this method of apolo- getics to be fundamentally unsound, when applied, as the Modernists apply it, to justify their own position in the Roman Church. It is plain that the * facts of reUgion ' are no facts for them. M. Loisy's Jesus may have been a more respectable Messiah than Theudas, but he belongs to the same category. There has been, after all, a real breach of continuity, and no mere development, in the Church as they conceive it ; and it is a breach which divides the Church from the historical Christ. It is as if one were to trace one's descent from some great man, and to estabhsh every link except the first : — our ancestor was after all wrongly supposed to be the son of the great man ; or the great man was only a myth. It is quite impossible to justify this position by disparaging existential truth. If it does not matter whether the Incarnation was a fact or a legend ; if Faith can create dogmas with the same freedom which Plato's Socrates claims in inventing his myths ; if things exist only as instrimients for the will, and all events are plastic under the hand of the religious imagination ; we are transported into a world where there is no difference between fact and fiction, and where it is difficult to suppose that human conduct can matter much. Such a contempt for actuaUty is far removed from the Christian view of the world. It will of course be said that it is only religious symbols which are thus removed from the FAITH BASED ON PRACTICAL NEEDS 176 existential order ; and that it is Just because the Modernist has so great respect for historical accuracy, that he carries his critical apparatus even into the holy places of the Christian origins. But with what object is the his- torical form retained for Faith, when it is rejected as fact ? For whose benefit does the Modernist priest go on praying to the Queen of Heaven, whom he believes to be a purely mythical personage ? Not for his own surely. It would be a strange attitude of mind to be able to offer petitions to a being whom, at the time of praying, one conceived of as non-existent. Then it must be for the sake of the uninstructed laity. But, putting aside the moral objection that might be raised, is it not significant that those who can find comfort and help in such devotions are entirely convinced of the historical facts which the Modernist finds himself unable to accept ? Would any simple Catholic feel that the foundations of his Faith were not assailed by M. Loisy's Les Evangiles Synoptiques ? It may be asserted with confidence, that ' dogmatic symbols ' are only helpful to those who can find in them an actual bridge between the spiritual and material worlds — just that kind of bridge which the Modernists, as critics, reject as impossible. * The historian,' says M. Loisy, * does not remove God from history ; he never encounters Him there.* Now this assumption (for it is of course an assumption to say that God never manifests Himself in history) is absolutely fatal to Catholicism as a living and working Faith. What- ever changes the Roman Church may make, to adjust itself to changing circumstances, it is safe to predict that it will never accept a God who * never intervenes in history.' The whole system of Catholicism — its sacraments, its disciphne, its festivals, its priesthood, is bound up with the belief that God does intervene in history. Those who think otherwise seem to be liable to the reproach which they most of all dislike — that of scholastic intellectual- ism and neglect of concrete experience. 176 FAITH [CH. The authors of the Programme of Modernism seem to be right in saying that the philosophy of the movement grew out of its critical studies. There are many intelli- gent priests in the Roman Church who have become keenly alive to the immense difl&culties which historical criticism has raised in the way of traditional beliefs. They can no longer believe what the Church requires them to beheve. And yet they are conscious of no rebellion against the spirit of Catholicism. They are ardently loyal and enthusi- astic Catholics. Their faith is unimpaired, but it no longer rests on the old base, or carries with it conviction that whatever the Church teaches is true. In this dire perplexity (and we must all sympathise with them in an impasse which by no means confronts the Roman Church alone) they turn eagerly to a popular and confident school of philosophy which seems to interpret the situation for them, and to offer them a way of honourable escape from it. The separation of truths of Faith from truths of fact ; the primacy of will and feeling over discursive thought ; the right to believe what we wish to beUeve ' at our own risk ' — what is this but the very solution they were craving for ? And now they find this position maintained by philosophers of repute, who have no personal reason for wishing to justify it. We cannot wonder that voluntarism and pragmatism have made many eager disciples among the liberal clergy. And yet they are wrong. This philosophy, which seems to promise them an honourable truce between the old Faith which they love and the new knowledge which they cannot ignore, would in reafity, if followed up seriously and not merely grasped at in controversial straits, lead them far outside Christianity. It rests on a very deep-rooted scepticism — on a psychology which tries to be a self-suffic* ing philosophy, independent of objective truth. It is Kantianism without the moral absolutism which gave Kant a TTou (rrdi. It is a mere experimental opportunism which X.] FAITH BASED ON PRACTICAL NEEDS V^ can never rise to a high spiritual level, because it acknow- ledges no fixed eternal standard to which our actions can be referred. Even God, if the idea of God is retained, can be only an ideal projected by the mind, not an objective fact. The scepticism is of a pecuharly intractable nature, because it involves the instrument of thought. We are hardly allowed to form concepts, because all is in a state of flux, and nothing remains the same while we are thinking about it. Such a philosophy would never have attracted Christian priests except at a time of exceptional difficulty and per- plexity. The aid which it briugs is illusory ; it enables a priest to blow hot and cold with the same mouth and feel no qualms, but it offers no solution of the problem ; it leaves the tension between Faith and fact as great as before. The Pope was quite right in condemning Modem- ism ; he could not possibly have done otherwise ; though we may regret that he fails to realise the severity of the crisis, and suggests no way out of it except the impossible one of return to tradition and St. Thomas Aquinas. The treatment of the Modernists is ungenerous ; the total failure of the Vatican to understand the loyalty and distress of these unwilliQg ' heretics ' is not a good omen for the future. ^ The consideration of these current controversies has provided, I hope, an illustration of what is the main sub- ject of these two lectures — the results of the attempt to separate Faith entirely from scientific or theoretical knowledge. The conclusion which I maintain is that Faith is not independent of the intellectual processes, and that whatever form dualism takes — whether, with Kant, we separate the theoretical from the practical reason, or, with Ritschl, judgments of fact from judgments of value, or, with Loisy, the Christ of Faith from the Christ of history — the result is profoundly unsatisfactory. , M 1/8 FAITH [cH. CHAPTER XI FAITH AND REASON We have now to consider the place of the intellect in religious belief. The view that the subject-matter of religion is a system of facts and laws, which can be studied and known like any other subject of knowledge, is called rationalism. The word is often used by religious people as a synonym for scepticism or infidelity. But in fact rationalism has quite as often been orthodox as heretical. The scholastic (especially the Thomist) theology, which is still officially recognised by the Roman Catholic Church as the philosophy of the Christian rehgion, is mainly ^ rationalistic, within certain prescribed limits. God has revealed certain truths to mankind ; but the authority of the revelation, though not its contents, has been guaranteed by signs offered to the reason. Moreover, the existence of God is not only known by revelation, but can also be demonstrated by reason. Nor does official Rome show any disposition to recede from this position. When Brunetiere, some years ago, announced ' the bankruptcy of the sciences,' and, in the interests of CathoUc orthodoxy, separated Faith from knowledge, the Archbishop of Paris reprimanded him, and referred him to St. Thomas Aquinas, who says that * Faith presupposes natural knowledge, though that which in and for itself can be proved and known may be an object of Faith to those who cannot understand the proof.' A 1 The Summa Theologiae contains many sound statements about the pro- Tince of the will in determining belief; but St. Thomas does not, like so many moderns, set the will against the intellect in order to disparage th< latter. XL] FAITH AXD KEASON 179 Papal decree of 1855 declares that ' rational conclusions can prove with certainty the existence of God, the spiritual nature of the soul, and the freedom of the will.' ^ The Vatican Council of 1870 decreed : ' Si quis dixerit Deum unum et verum naturali rationis lumine certo cognosci non possBy anathema sit.^ The Modernists are blarned for abandoning this position. Again, the evidential school in England, long held in special honour at Cambridge in the person of Paley, is crudely rationalistic. Paley, who expresses his surprise that in Apostolic times more stress was not laid on the arguments from miracle and prophecy, which seemed to him so convincing, is equally confident of the irresistible cogency of the argument from desi^)^, which he thus enunciates. ' The marks of design are too strong to be gotten over. Design must have a designer, ^ That designer must be a Person. That Person is God.' Speculative idealism, as a philosophy of religion, gives us examples of intellectualism — one can hardly say of rational- ism — of a very different kind. Speculative ideahsm substi- tutes truth of idea for truth of fact ; or rather, it regards ideas as the real facts. I have already quoted Fichte's^ \^ dictum that we are saved by metaphysics and not by/ history. Hegel's absolute idealism, or Panlogism, as it is sometimes called, the most imposing philosophical edifice ever reared, belongs to this type. But Kant was also a rationahst on one side — the side on which his modem admirers do not follow him. Among Christian apologists Newman is sometimes thoroughly rationalistic in language, as when he says : ' What I mean by theology is simply the science of God, or the truths we know about God, put into a system, just as we have a science of the stars and call it astronomy, or of the crust of the earth and call it geology.' 2 This, however, is not Newman's real position. He belongs, like Pascal, to the type of sceptical orthodoxy. 1 HofFding, The Philosophy of Religion, p. 387. • Cf. James, Varieties of Religious Experience, p. 435. 180 FAITH [CH. Orthodox rationalism is associated, above all, with the famous * proofs ' of God's existence, which were very roughly handled by Kant, and are at present much out of favour. I wish to indicate, as well as I can in a very brief discussion, what value can, in my opinion, still be attached to them. The ontological argument in its scholastic form concludes from the notion of God as the most perfect being, the fact of His existence ; because existence is certainly involved in the idea of perfection. Descartes states it in a form which is scarcely defensible. ' God's existence can no more be separated from His essence, than the idea of a mountain from ' hat of a valley.' ' It is true,' he goes on, ' that I may imagine a winged horse, though no winged horses exist ; but the cases are not ana^ogous, for I can think of a non-existent Pegasus, but I cannot conceive of God except as existing, which shows that existence is inseparable from Him.' In other words, the ontological assertion cannot be claimed for all ideas, but only for necessary ones, such as the ideas of perfection and infinity, that is to say, of God. Cudworth, the Cambridge Platonist, states the argument more attractively. ' Our human soul cannot feign or create any new cogitation or conception that was not before, but only variously compound that which is ; nor can it ever make a positive idea of an absolute non- entity — that is, such as hath neither actual nor possible existence ; much less could our imperfect being create the entity of so vast a thought as that of an infinitely perfect being out of nothing ; because there is no repugnancy at all in the latter, as there is in the former. We affirm therefore that, was there no God, the idea of an absolutely perfect being could never have been made or feigned.' ^ Kant convicts the ontological argument of two errors. First, the purely logical possibility of the notion of an ens realissimum is transformed into a real possibility, and 1 Cudworth, Intellectual Systenif vol. i chap. v. XI.1 FAITH AND REASON 181 secondly actual existence is deduced from the notion as one of the attributes implied in it ; which is, he says, much the same as to deduce from the idea of a hundred dollars the existence of that sum in my pocket. This obvious criticism, which had been made long before Kant, is only fatal to the crudest form of the ontological proof. Hegel rehabilitated the argument in his own fashion. ' The content is right,' he said ; * it is only the form which is defective.' In his philosophy the idea itself is the absolute, and ' it would be strange to deny to it even the poorest category, that of being.' This, however, is not what religion wants to prove about God. But Hegel also argues that thought, which is a spiritual act, must have its ground in a spiritual principle which is also the ground of nature. The agreement of the ideal laws of thought with the real laws of being, is a fact of ex- perience. There must then be a common ground of both. Lotze gave the argument a new and characteristic turn, replacing logical proof by immediate certainty of * living feeling.' It would be * intolerable ' to believe that perfection exists only in our thought, and has no power or being in the world of reality. This removes the argument from its intellectualist basis. God exists, because Faith pronounces it * intolerable ' that He should not. It is intolerable, not unthinkable. It is possible to conceive of such a condition, but only by assuming that the world is bad and meaningless. And we reject such an idea by an act of reasonable Faith. Professor Ladd ^ restates the argument in a shape some- what nearer to its earlier form. All beliefs and cognitions, he says, depend upon an ontological proof or postulate. Every argument for every kind of reality presupposes that we are in contact with ontological truth. ' What is so con- nected with our experience of reality that it is essential to explain that experience is believed to be real.' 1 Philosophy of Religion, vol. i. p. 309. 182 FAITH [CH. The real force of the ontological argument lies n the reasonable and stubbornly confident claim of the human spirit to be in some sort of contact with the highest reality. The very conception of objective truth is most reasonably accounted for by supposing it to be a * revelation ' from Him who is the truth. Whence comes our idea of God, if not from God Himself ? Who else could have put it there ? Since then we certainly have an idea of God, and since only God can have put it into our minds, we may infer that God exists. This argument was unfortunately split into two halves in the scholastic period, and took the following unsatisfactory form : (1) The idea of God implies His existence ; (2) Our consciousness of God can only be explained by an external divine revelation. Both these are false, the former for the reasons already stated, and the latter because the existence of an Absolute Spirit could not be revealed in such a manner. But when we say that God only can have implanted in our minds the thought of God, we are, it seems to me, using a good argu- ment. We cannot get behind the conviction that ' all existence rests upon a Being the fountain of whose life is within Himself ; we must ally the fugitive phenomena, which colour the stream of life with ever-changing lives, to an eternal and unchanging existence.'^ It is impossible, if we think honestly, to regard the conception of God as a purely subjective development. * This conception, as human reason has somehow succeeded in framing it, seems to the same reason to demand the reality of God. ' ^ The cosmologiccU argument, in its earliest form, as we find it in Aristotle, concludes from the motion in the world to a first mover. Man is dissatisfied with the fragmentary pictures which his experience of the world presents to him ; he wants to find the ultimate causative principle. So he arrives at the idea of a divine first cause. Against this 1 Fiohte. * Ladd, Philosophy of Religion, rol. ii. p. 60. XL] FAITH AND REASON !» time-honoured argument Kant objected that it is useless to search for cause beyond cause in the hope of finding the beginning of the chain ; the law of causality is only valid for the world of phenomena, and cannot lead us to a first cause beyond the world. Also, we have no reason to seek for any cause of the world outside itself. We admit readily that the cosmological argument is no longer acceptable in its earlier deistic form, which separates God from the world, and confines His action upon it to the original act of creation. What the reUgious sense of our day demands is not a Prime Mover but an immanent World-, ground. And the demand for an immanent guiding prin- ciple, acting in accordance with fixed laws and with a rational purpose, is itself the cosmological argument. What gave us the idea of such a world ? What impels us to find everywhere evidence of law and reason, to be content when we have found them and dissatisfied until we have done so, unless such is indeed the constitution of the real world ? This is in substance the turn which Lotze gives to this argument. The proof is not directed to anything which belongs to the past, but is made to yield an ever present energy as the source and ground of all cosmical change and happening.^ The Ideological argument, or argument from design, is treated by Kant with much greater respect than the two preceding * proofs.' He calls it the oldest, the clearest, and the most rational of the proofs. Nevertheless it shares the fate of the others — that of being implicitly non-suited before the trial begins.^ It has a regulative, not a constitu- tive value. It is a mere introduction to the ontological proof, which he considers himself to have already disposed of. The argument, as stated fairly enough by Kant, is as 1 Caldecott and Mackintosh, SeUctioru from the Literatwre \)f Theism^ p. 206. « Ihid., p. 211. 184 FAITH [CB. lollows. We observe in the world manifest signs of pur- pose, executed with great wisdom, and existiag over the whole of its vast extent. This arrangement of means and ends is entirely foreign to the things existing in the world. The nature of things could not of itself tend towards certain purposes ; they must have been chosen and directed by some rational principle, in accordance with certain fundamental ideas. There exists, therefore, a sublime and wise cause, which is free and intelligent. Its unity may be inferred from the harmony existiug between the parts of the world. It is quite a mistake to suppose that Darwinism, or modem science generally, has destroyed the teleological argument. The naive teleology of Paley is no doubt to a large extent discredited. It is an inner teleology — a vast network of final purposes continually working themselves out in the inextricably complex processes of natural life — to which we are now directed. The very conception of order and law, so far from contradicting the idea of pur- pose, impUes it. The appearance of mechanism is just what we ought to expect from a tremendous power operating constantly and uniformly. What is really significant is that in spite of this appearance of mechanism, in spite of the enormous waste and apparent recklessness of Nature's method, man cannot renounce the idea, nay, the conviction, that an unceasing purpose runs through it all. It is per- fectly true, as Kant says, that this drives us back upon the ontological argument again. We have to face the objection that this conviction may have a purely subjective origin. But we have already conceded the righteous and reasonable demand of Faith that when our whole personality — will, thought, and feeling — tells us that we are in the presence of objective truth and reality, we shall believe it. * There are many proofs of God's existence, but no demonstrations.' ^ Final postulates of thought are in- 1 Gwatkin, The Knowledge of Godf vol. L p. 9. FAITH AND KEASON 185 capable of demonstration. They are hypotheses, which may be said to be ' proved ' if they explain the facts. Some hypotheses, however, are so inwrought with the very texture of rational experience, that to deny them is to destroy experience. Many have thought that we may rest our certainty of God's existence on this ground, and in a sense I agree : but this argument at best only leads half-way to the God of religious Faith. The history of the Aufkldrung, and kindred movements in other countries, is very instructive for a due apprecia- tion of the results of pure intellectualism. If it takes the form of rationaUsm, it tends to slide into naturalistic pantheism. If it takes the form of speculative ideal- ism, it tends to slide into idealistic pantheism. In either case, its final state is to become a cosmological theory, and to fall outside of religion properly so called. A good example in England is John Toland, who in 1696 published his once famous book, Christianity not Mysteri- ous, in which he argues that all the doctrines of Christi- anity are in complete agreement with ' the religion of reason,' that is, of educated common sense. * All Faith now in the world,' he writes, * is entirely built on ratiocina- tion.' He does not reject revelation, but holds that revealed doctrine, though we might not have discovered it for ourselves, is now capable of being proved and veri- fied by common sense. Orthodox AngUcan rationalists, like Tillotson and Paley, use much the same language, but lay stress on miracles as signs offered to the understanding in confirmation of the revelation. Tillotson, for instance, says : ' Nothing ought to be received as a divine doctrine and revelation, without good evidence that it is so : that is, without some argument sufficient to satisfy a prudent and considerate man.' ^ Again : * Faith is an assent of the mind to something revealed by God : now all assent must be grounded upon evidence ; that is, no man can believe 1 Tillotson, Sermons, vol. ii. p. 260, 186 FAITH [cH. f anything, unless he have, or think he hath, some reason I to do so. For to be confident of a thing without reason is not Faith, but a presumptuous persuasion and obstinacy \ of mind.' ^ It is worth while to contrast these utterances with St. Paul's conception of evangelistic teaching. * My speech and my preaching were not in persuasive words of wisdom, but in demonstration of the Spirit and of power ; that your Faith should not stand in the wisdom of men, but in the power of God. Howbeit we speak wisdom among the per- fect ; yet a wisdom not of this world, nor of the rulers of this world which are coming to nought : but we speak God's wisdom in a mystery, even the wisdom that hath been hidden, which God foreordained before the world unto our glory.' ^ And again : ' By manifestation of the truth commending ourselves to every man's con- science in the sight of God.' ^ Few great religious teachers have attached so much importance to mental enlightenment as St. Paul. But he carefully distinguishes the kind of ' knowledge ' which makes a man ' spiritual ' and capable of discerning spiritual truth, from the prudence and worldly wisdom to which appeal was so frequently made in the eighteenth century. The appeal of the Gospel is not to the logical faculty purged from * enthusiasm.' That is a temper of mind which precludes acceptance of the evidence which Faith brings with it, namely, what the Apostle calls * demonstration of the Spirit and power.' It is the pecuharity of revelation that it brings the mind into contact with higher orders of reality and truth than are accessible to worldly prudence and respectability ; and these new experiences carry with them their own verifica- tion in a new sense of power and spiritual vitality. It is not too much to say that these eighteenth-century divines had quite lost the true meaning of Faith. They regarded 1 Tillotson, Sermons, voL iv. p. 42. « 1 Cor. ii. 4-7. » 2 Cor. It. 2, n.] FAITH AND REASON 187 it as ordinary knowledge or opinion concerned with divine matters. But religious truth is not to be won in this manner. Orthodox rationalism became more and more dry and hfeless ; while some of its defenders, like Toland himself, drifted into pantheistic naturalism, in which the religious valuation of the world quite disappeared. It is worth noticing how this type of rationalism some- times shows its aflfinity with a cold, hard moralism, and with utiUtarianism in philosophy. When all the poetical and imaginative side of reKgion is rigorously banished, the religious sense, which is still not extinguished, may attach itself firmly to conduct, and may give its sanction to a cool- headed ambition to improve the outward conditions of humanity. In this way many excellent men in the last century found a worthy aim and an adequate task. We must always think respectfully of the utilitarian movement which grew out of eighteenth century rationalism. If utilitarian rationaUsm may be claimed as a character- istically English type, speculative idealism has been the typical German product of intellectualism. With Leibnitz, and the Aufklarung generally, Faith in a divine reason, encompassing the world, and the ground of human reason, had been the basis of belief that universally valid truth is accessible to man.^ Spinoza made this cosmic reason immanent, so that it is not so much we who think, as God who thinks in us ; and in order to think divinely, we need only purify our souls from all personal interests and selfish aims. But he never taught, like Kant, that our thought is unrelated to objects existing outside itself. His error was in placing this cosmic nature, which thinks in us, too exclusively in intellectual activity. This limitation arose from his great desire to win detachment from mundane concerns, which seemed to him obstacles in the way of cosmic consciousness. The loss involved in one-sided in- tellectualism was disguised from himself by the mystical 1 Eucken, T?u Life of the Spirit (translated by Pogson), p. 309. 188 FAITH [oh. and genuinely devout side of his own character, which supplied motives and experiences quite alien to the purely speculative nature of his philosophy.^ With Fichte and Hegel the thought, which Kant had severed from the world, became the workshop in which the whole of reality is created. Thought produces contra- dictions out of itself and overcomes them, until the whole of existence has been embraced, transmuted, and assimil- ated into one all-embracing, absolute harmony. For a short time it was thought that this ambitious philosophy had solved the ultimate problem. Then followed a reaction which has threatened to sweep away the substantial gains which these great thinkers really secured for human thought. Their disciples in this country now adopt a much more modest tone, as becomes those who are standing on the defensive. A good example of this school is Princi- pal Caird, who, in his Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion, thus vindicates for intellect the place of honour in reUgious Faith : — * It is no vaUd objection to the endeavour after a rational knowledge of the contents of our religious beUef, to say that the primary organ of spiritual knowledge is not reason but Faith. That we must begin with intuition is no reason why we should not go on to scientific knowledge. The spontaneous and the reflective tendencies may co-exist. Granting that the act of spiritual apprehension is quite different from intellectual assent, there is still a place left for reason in the province of religion. The science of acoustics is not meaningless because we can hear without it. We act before we reflect ; and rehgion must exist ^ before it can be made the subject of reflective thought. \ But in religion as in morality, art, and other spheres of human activity, there is the underlying element of reason which is the characteristic of all the activities of a self- j conscious intelhgence. To endeavour to elicit and give ' 1 Eucken, The lA/eqfthe Spirit (translated by Pogson), p. 812. XI.] FAITH AND REASON 189 objective clearness to that element — to infuse into the spontaneous and unsifted conceptions of religious experi- ence the objective clearness, necessity, and organic unity of thought — is the legitimate aim of science, in religion as in other spheres. It would be strange if in the highest of all provinces of human experience, intelligence must renounce her claim. i ' What then is the ofi&ce of intelligence in religion ? ^ To purify our intuitions, which often deceive us. Truth\^ is indeed its own witness, but not all that seems to be true. We need intellect in order to distinguish that which has a right to dominate the mind from that which derives its influence only from accident and association. J * Moreover, it is the highest task of philosophy to justify those paradoxes and seeming contradictions in which the religious consciousness finds its natural expression. It seeks to lead us to a higher point of view, from which these seeming contradictions vanish.' These extracts are not sufficient to make Caird's stand- point clear. His Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion should be read carefully. He holds that Thought or self- conscious Mind is the only category under which the Infinite can be conceived by us. ' All other categories are still categories of the finite.' He agrees with the Intuitivists that religion enables us to rise from the finite to the infinite, and to find the ideal become real.^ But he considers that feeling, taken at its face value, gives us no sure foundation. We still have to inquire. Is it true ? -' And to this question thought alone can give an answer. Intuitive knowledge which professes to answer this question / is not really intuitive or immediate, but inferential, and I it is safer to recognise it for what it is. Edward Caird's philosophy, though further from ortho- dox Christianity, at any rate in tone, is very similar to his brother's. He is equally confident that the right use of * Caldecott, Fhilosqphy of Religion, p. 149. 190 FAITH [cH. reason must lead us to religion. He rejects the Ritschlian value-judgment theory, as luring us into the acceptance of the theoretically false in the guise of the practically true.^ The mystics, he thinks, are only wrong in being in too great a hurry. The patient processes of thought would give them all that they are eager to snatch. A particularly good and illuminating discussion of the present attitude of reflective thought towards religion, or rather, I should say, of religion and psychology towards reflective thought, may be found in the Hibhert Journal for 1903, in two articles by Professor Henry Jones, of Glasgow. He observes that our possession of the rich inheritance which the nineteenth century has transmitted to us — its store of scientific knowledge and spiritual interests — is threatened by the scepticism which doubts, or even denies, that intellectual inquiry can have any real value in precisely those matters which are best worth knowing. No generation has ever employed intelligence more, or trusted it less, than our own. And yet, as he goes on to say, this is not really a sceptical age. Outside the province of epistemology, which investigates the sources and limits of knowledge, there is no disposition on the part of scientific men to defer to ' authority,' as Mr. Balfour would have us do, nor to appeal to immediate assurance, or direct intuition, or the feelings of the heart, instead of to free inquiry, guided only by observation and reason. In all branches of science alike, we find the same conviction of the uniformity of nature and the universaUty of law. Nor does this faith in the methods of science lead to scep- ticism in morals and religion. This is an age which believes in God, and in the distinction of right and wrong, as grounded in the nature of things. Our great poets, who are the best representatives of the deeper thought of our time, are pro- foundly convinced that the spiritual life of man is based on solid foundations. And yet, among professed philosophers, 1 Caldecott, Philosophy of Religion, p. 152. FAITH AND REASON 191 the tide of anti-intellectualism runs very strong. The tendency to give the will supremacy over the speculative intellect, and to interpret the world in terms of human pur- pose, induces philosophers to use language which if accepted in the world of science would make all science impossible. They assert real discontinuities, uncaused beginnings, and non-logical occurrences in the objective world. Such views are calmly ignored by the scientists ; but they are introduc- ing great confusion and perplexity into religious and philo- sophical thought. Professor Jones maintains that since both reason and religion claim dominion over the whole realm of man's nature, to attempt to temporise between them is to be disloyal to both. There can be no delimitation of frontiers where both claimants think they have a right to the whole territory in dispute. And, as he adds, surely with truth, * No age of the world was ever strong except when Faith and reason went hand in hand, and when man's practical ideals were also his surest truths.' The contra- diction, if there is one, between the heart and intellect has somehow to be worked out. The religious and the intellectual spirit of the age are both sincere, and therefore somewhat intolerant. * There are some things on which the world does not go back, and the right to seek the truth is among the number. The intellectual ardour of the world cannot be damped, far less extinguished, by any theory, blindly advanced in the service of religion, of the radical insecurity of knowledge, or of the incompetence and un- trustworthiness of human reason.' Professor Jones than proceeds to deJSne the issue by an observation which penetrates to the heart of the problem. The standpoint of modem scientific thought is cosmo- centric ; that of the new psychology is frankly anthropo- centric. * Instead of explaining nature from the being of man,' says a scientific writer, 'we follow the reverse process, and seek to understand human life from the general laws of nature.' On the other hand the pragmatists have 192 FAITH [CH, revived the ancient maxim that ' man is the measure of all things.' Now I must own that my own sympathies are with those who hold the cosmocentric view. ' The conception of reality,' says Professor Jones, ' as a single system, in which man occupies his own irrevocable place, has come to stay. To give it up would be to give up philosophy as well as science, and reasoning as well as philosophy.' If the world is ' wild,' as Professor James thinks, we ought to give up thinking ; for connected thought about a dis- connected world must be false. But modem thought can never commit suicide in this fashion. That nature and man are in some way continuous, that man is what he is only in virtue of his ontological relation to the world, apart from which he can have neither being nor meaning, is no longer questionable. And yet, so great is the fear en- gendered by the conception of a cosmos which shuts man up in an iron framework, that we find Lotze reducing natural laws to mere conceptual generalisations, not representing facts in the outer world ; we find Ritschlians warning the intelligence from the domain of religion, thus opening the door wide for any superstition ; we find Professor James and his followers constructing the universe of enigmatical atoms dignified by the name of persons, and rushing into polytheism. I have already explained what is the real motive of the attacks upon the intellectual side of our nature which are now so frequently heard. A positive dislike is felt to- wards the attempt to estabhsh a systematic coherence in the world of experience. It is hoped that the attempt may fail. We are told that there is no such universal system, but only finite particular facts and events. jMan, we are reminded, is wider than mere intellect. His moral and religious life falls outside the schematism of the intelligence. It deals with facts ' of another order.* This last argument I believe to be false and dangerous. XI.] FAITH AND REASON 193 We cannot set up an order of facts which shall be outside the whole intellectual realm. The sphere of the intelli- gence is not limited in the sense that there are provinces of reality which it cannot touch. No doubt there are many things which we do not know. The world as we know it is not a complete system, and, since all reality is interdependent, no object within it is completely known. But this admission does not oblige us to parcel out the kingdom of truth into several ' orders,' each under the charge of one of our faculties. We have already seen what havoc results from maintaining these rifts within our mental life. 1 The function of thought is not to invent generalisations and fabricate connecting links. The underlying unity is there already. It is utterly impossible to regard th6 particular facts as objectively real, and the laws and principles which connect and regulate them as having only a subjective significance. ' Mere ideas ' cannot bind to- gether * real objects.' Or if the particulars also are re- garded as merely subjective, everything disappears at once into dreamland. Nothing can be proved false if nothing is taken as true. The sceptic cannot throw his opponent if his own feet are in the air. It seems therefore that a denial of the Absolute means a denial of the relative as well, and that unless we believe that reality is a coherent system, we can say nothing about the particular existences, which ex hypothesi are intrinsically unintelligible. The pursuit of the Absolute is no invention of the arro- gant ' intellectualist.' It is a fact that man always has pur- sued the truth, the good, and trusted in a God, who gathers into Himself all the perfections that man is able to conceive. Religion is always a theory of reality. It cannot be sep- arated from the ontological consciousness. Man does pur- sue absolute ideals, however well he may know that they are never fully attained in his life and action ; and in this pursuit his life and his activity consist. He cannot N 194 FAITH I^CH. escape from this law of his being by denying that there is an Absolute. The opponent of absolutism generally sets up an absolute of his own without knowing it : Kant deifies the moral sense, Schopenhauer the irrational will, Hartmann the unconscious, Spencer the unknowable. Even the principle of relativity becomes, with some of its advocates, a kind of absolute. I must not anticipate the subject of my last lecture, which will be devoted to showing how our conflicting ideals may, as I think, be reconciled. But I wish to con- sider rather more fully one or two of the reasons which have put intellectualism out of fashion. A consideration which weighs heavily with many thinkers is connected with the conception of change. I have already quoted the Modernists on this point. Scho- lastic theology opposed the unchangeableness of the Deity to the mutability of the world. But is an absolutely un- changing ground of continuous change thinkable ? And if in the real world — in the mind of God — there is no change, what is the use of the time-process ? If nothing is ulti- mately real but general laws, universals, which are merely illustrated by happenings in time, is not the world a useless and irrational thing ? Sub specie aeternitatis, the goal is already attained ; suh specie temporis, it is unattainable. Whichever way we look at it, activity seems to be useless. In the universe of the intellectualist, they say, nothing ever really happens. The eternal laws of God are eluci- dated in a million concrete instances ; but why is all this illustration necessary ? Is it a worthy occupation for the Deity to be perpetually setting Himself easy sums, of which he knows the answer beforehand ? Are we to imagine Him playing an unending succession of games of patience by Himself ? Does the order of the time-series mean nothing ? Might it just as well be read backwards, like a reversed cinematograj^jh ? Intellectual- ism gives us a static universe ; and a static universe, XI.] FAITH AND REASON 196 though not unthinkable, is absurd. Beings, such as God has made us, claim to Uve in a world where things really happen, where their energies really count for something and determine something. And if this claim is conceded, the static-intellectualist conception of reality must give way. This claim is made not only in the interests of free- will and morality, but of the rationality of the cosmos. The difficulty about change and immutability has been recognised by the clearer thinkers among the old philo- sophers, but has been often forgotten by others who are attracted by the idea of changeless being. Mere flux and mere stationariness are both absurd, and neither can be predicated of reality. The old notion of substance as the unchanging substratum of change gives us no help. Reality must somehow transcend the opposition of crrda-Ls and KLvrj(TL done imaginatively ; what has to be spoken or made is spoken or made fittingly, lovingly, beautifully.' ^ Some writers have seen in ' the Sublime ' the link be- tween sesthetical feeling and religion. Kant, in particular, quite forgetful of the limitations which in his Critique of Pure Reason he had laid upon all our faculties, invests the Sublime with a mystical power of uniting the human spirit with the infinite. * We call that sublime which is absolutely great.' ' The sublime is that which cannot A Santayana, Reason in Art, p. 16. THE AESTHETIC GROUND OF FAITH 207 even enter our thought without the help of a faculty which surpasses the standard of sense.' ' Nature is sublime in those phenomena which convey an idea of its infinity.' ^ So Longinus says, ' When a writer uses any other resource, he shows himself to be a man ; but the sublime lifts him near to the great spirit of the Deity.' Kant, Uke Burke, whom he probably follows,^ distinguishes the Sublime from the Beautiful, instead of making sublimity a species of beauty. This is perhaps an error. It would be better to extend the meaning of beauty, which has too often been confined to mere prettiness, to cover the grander and more awe-inspiring phenomena of nature. Winckelmann acutely observes that when we gaze over the broad sea, our mind at first appears to shrink and lose itself, but soon returns to itself, elevated by what it has beheld. The perception of the Beautiful, in this wider sense, has seemed to many to be closely akin to mystical intuition.3 This view is put into philosophical terminology by Hegel, who says : ' The Beautiful is essentially the spiritual making itself known sensuously, presenting itself in sensuous concrete existence, but in such a manner that that existence is wholly and entirely permeated by the spiritual, so that the sensuous is not independent, but has its meaning solely and exclusively through the spiritual and in the spiritual, and exhibits not itself but the spirit- ual.' * This belief is the romantic side of Greek philosophy. It finds its classical expression in a famous passage of Plato's Symposium ^ : — ' He who has been instructed thus far in the things of love, and has learned to see the beautiful in due order and succession, when he comes towards the end will suddenly perceive a nature of wondrous beauty (and this was the object of all our toils), a nature which in the * From the Critique of Judqimnt. * Bosanquet, History of JEsthetic, p. 275. » Ladd, The Philosophy of Religion, vol. i. p. 441. * Hegel, Philosophy of Religion, vol. ii. p. 8. » Plato, Symposium, pp. 210, 211, 208 FAITH [cH. first place is everlasting, not growing and decaying, not waxing and waning ; not fair in one point of view and foul in another . . . but beauty absolute, separate, simple and everlasting, which without increase or diminution or any other change is imparted to the ever-growing and ever- perishing beauties of other things. He who, ascending from these under the influence of true love, begins to perceive that beauty, is not far from the end. And the true order ... is to begiu with the beauties of earth and mount upwards for the sake of that other beauty, using these as steps only, and going on from fair forms to fair practices, and from these to fair notions, until from fair notions he arrives at the notion of absolute beauty, and at last knows what the essence of beauty is. . . . What if man had eyes to see the true beauty, the divine beauty, pure and clear and unalloyed, not clogged with the pollu- tions of mortality and all the colours and vanities of human life — looking thither and communing with the true beauty, simple and divine ? In that communion, and in that only, beholding beauty with the eye of the mind, he will be enabled to bring forth, not images of beauty, but reaUties (for it is the reality and no image that he grasps), and produciug and cherishing true virtue he will become the friend of God, and immortal, if mortal man can be im- mortal.' According to this passage, which contains the essence of the poetical and romantic side of Plato's philosophy, the sense of beauty is a joyous witness withui us to the kinship of the human spirit with that source of all spiritual life from which whatever is fair and noble in the world proceeds. Plato is not afraid to trace a high symbolic meaning in the connection of the sesthetical sense with sexual passion. ' All love is of the immortal. Mortal nature seeks as far as possible to be everlastiug and im- mortal ; and since absolute unity in continuance is not to be had, even in the life of the individual, men desire to XII.] THE ESTHETIC GKOUND OF FAITH 209 produce a new generation to take the place of the old.' This transmission of life is the human substitute and symbol for the unchanging hfe of Eternity. Thus our sense of beauty is an imaginative ^ representa- tion which connects our present experience with the eternal. It is the sesthetical sense which most vividly makes the past and future live in the present. The gift of imagination is thus a psychological intimation of im- mortality. This prophetic office of the imagination has been far too much neglected by rehgious teachers and philosophers. We see the result in the tendency of culti- vated people to turn to the poets for spiritual guidance and sympathy. The poets seem to be nearer to the heart of things than the men of thought or the men of action. They have the advantage of working in the most plastic of materials, and their interpretation of ideal reality may therefore have a higher truth than the somewhat sorry experiments which history records in the field of the actual, and a richer colour than the ' grey ' hues of philosophical theory. It is for this reason that myth and legend have played, and still play, so important a part in reUgion, They are prized, consciously or unconsciously, for their representative value. ' Poetry,' says Aristotle,^ ' is more philosophical and of higher worth than history ; for history records what has actually happened, but poetry describes what may happen ' {i.e. universal truth). In spite of this. Faith has always looked upon the sesthetical sense as a somewhat dangerous ally. Being potentially of infinite scope, it endeavours to embrace all experience and classify it according to its own standards. And * of all premature settlements, the most premature is that which the fine arts are wont to establish.' ^ A lovely 1 'Imaginative' is not the same as 'purely subjective.' There may be an essential connection between the image and reality. 2 In the Poetics. * Santayana, Reason in Art, p. 217. 210 FAITH [CH. dream leaves the world no less a chaos, and makes it seem by contrast even darker than before. Visionary pleasures make the world no better, and generally bring visionary pains and disorders in their wake. As soon as art loses touch with science and morality, it becomes corrupt. Just as morality for morality's sake is (in spite of Kant) im- possible and self-contradictory; just as truth for truth's sake takes us no further than pure mathematics, in which all values are hypothetical, and the connection with the actual world is broken off, so beauty for beauty's sake stultifies itself and ceases even to be beautiful. Our three strands of natural revelation are intertwined; we cannot unravel them. And there seems to be a mysterious law in the spiritual world, that to aim directly at a thing is not the way to hit it. Just as pleasure, according to Aristotle, attends virtue as the bloom upon a young face attends health, but is not the immediate object of moral effort, so beauty regularly appears as a by-product of ethical striving and of intellectual search. Perhaps beauty has an ethereal and evasive quality which belongs only to itself. It is, says Plotinus, the light that plays over the symmetry of things, rather than the symmetry itself. A modern fK>et, William Watson, has expressed the same idea in a fine stanza : — Forget not, brother singer, that though Prose Can never be too truthful nor too wise, Song is not Truth nor Wisdom, but the rose Upon Truth's lips, the light in Wisdom's eyes. Even in art itself, Goethe tells us, the principle is the significant, the result the beautiful. This maxim cuts at the root of artistic dilettantism, such as made the 'aesthetic' coterie in Victorian England ridiculous and contemptible; for what does art 'signify' except eternal reality, which is good and true as well as beautiful ? The warning furnished by decadent art is indeed valuable XII ] THE ESTHETIC GROUND OF FAITH 211 and instructive. The hero of Huysmans' unpleasant novel A Rebours makes it the object of his life to enjoy everj^ kind of voluptuous thrill of which the sesthetical sense is capable. The result, as might be expected, is spiritual rottenness. Decadent art generally shows its character by over-elaboration of details which have no significance for the whole. This is a symbol of the mental disin- tegration which accompanies it. The decadent is in a state of mind clean contrary to Faith. He despises life, hopes for nothing, and loves nobody. It is no wonder that he loves to sing the praises of death and dissolution. Plato, whose hostility to art has surprised so many of his admirers, dreaded its tyranny because he knew its power. Unless it can cover all practice, ennobling action as well as delighting the imagination, he will have none of it. The mere artist, as he knew, is always something less than a gentleman. The attitude of Greek thought toward art is often mis- understood. The defects of Greek aesthetic theory were mainly three. First, in accordance with their preference for plastic representation, in which their pre-eminence is undisputed, they attributed too high a value to symmetry as compared with expressiveness. Secondly, they only slowly outgrew the mistaken notion that art directly copies reality and must be judged by its fidelity to some given original. It was this error, in part, which led Plato to disparage art, as further removed from reality than nature. Being a great thinker, he could not state a fallacy of this kind without suggesting a way out of it ; but it was reserved for Plotinus^ to enuntiate the truth that the arts do not simply imitate the visible, but go back to the creative principles {Xoyoi)^ from which nature also derives its 1 The first clear recognition of imagination {(pauraa-ia), as the creativ*^. faculty in art, is due to Philostratus, who states clearly the principle that we desire in vain to find in Aristotle's Poetics. * It was imagination that pro duced_ these masterpieces, a more cunning artist than imitation. For imitation represents what it has seen, but imagination what it has not seen.' 212 FAITH [CH. forms. Natural things themselves, he says, * imitate * something else, namely, these formative principles or types. The arts are not, then, wholly dependent on the actual ; they create much out of themselves, and supply defici- encies in nature from the ideas of beauty which they find in themselves. ' Pheidias did not create his Zeus after any perceived pattern, but made him such as Zeus would appear if he deigned to be visible to mortal eyes.' ^ Thirdly (this is a feature in Greek thought which is often forgotten), the Greeks throughout demanded that serious art shall be morally edifying. A poet is blamed for making his characters worse than the plot demanded. In fact, there was a confused tendency to apply the same moral standards to works of art as to real life. The error here is not in holding that the good and the beautiful are ultimately one, for this is true ; but in imposing our morahty on the ideal world, and * playing providence ' in a region where only the divine wisdom and goodness bear sway. It is not the province of art to solve moral enigmas, least of all by the cheap and facile expedient of inventing a * poetical justice ' which is untrue to experience. Our moral sense is not a limiting sphere for the beautiful, though nothing is beautiful which is really repugnant to the Divine purity and good- ness. Art, when not hampered by the ' moralistic fallacy,' may often be a moral educator. Just as goodness has often an unstudied beauty of a very high order. The attitude of Christianity towards art was naturally determined in the first place by the traditions of Jewish and Graeco-Roman culture, which coalesced in the new religion. Hebrew art was symbolic, not pictorial, the ^ Enn. V. 8. Bosanquet {History of Esthetic, p. 113) has perhaps given Plotinus too much credit for this. The illustration from the Zeus of Pheidias must have been a commonplace: cf. Cic, Orator, 2: 'Nee vero ille artifex, cum faceret lovis formam aut Minervae, contemplabatur aliquem e quo similitudinem duceret ; sed ipsius in mente insidebat species pulchritudinis eximia quaedam, quam intuens in eaque defixus ad illius similitudinem artem et manum dirigebat.' Also Seneca, Controv. v. p. 36: * Non vidit Phidias lovem. . . . Dignus tamen ilia arte animus et concepit deos et exhibuit.' m THE ESTHETIC GKOUND OF FAITH 213 Hebrew genius being very deficient in the sense of form. For instance, in the Apocalypse, such images as that of a cubic city show how vaguely the writer visualised even his visions. On the other hand, the sense of the sublime in nature receives a nobler expression in some of the Psalms than in any other ancient Uterature. The grandeur of some of these descriptions has indeed never been sur- assed. We may follow Dean Church ^ in his selection of examples : — * The day is thine and the night is thine ; thou hast prepared the light and the sun.' * The heavens declare the glory of God, and the firma- ment sheweth his handiwork. One day telleth another, and one night certifieth another. . . . Their sound is gone out into all lands, and their words to the ends of the world.' ' Praise the Lord upon earth, ye dragons and all deeps : fire and hail, snow and vapour, wind and storm, fulfilling his word.' Or that noble Psalm, which begins with Gloria in excelsis and ends with In terris pax — the twenty-ninth : — Give unto the Lord, ye mighty, give unto the Lord glory and strength. Give the Lord the honour due unto his name ; worship the Lord with a holy worship. The voice of the Lord is upon the waters ; it is the glorious God that maketh the thunder. The voice of the Lord is upon many waters. The voice of the Lord is mighty in operation. The voice of the Lord is a glorious voice. The voice of the Lord breaketh the cedar-trees ; yea, the Lord breaketh the cedars of Libanus. He maketh them all to skip like a calf ; Libanus also and Sirion like a young unicorn. The voice of the Lord divideth the flames of fire. The voice of the Lord shaketh the wilderness ; yea, the Lord shaketh the wilderness of Kades. The voice of the Lord maketh the hinds to calve, and discovereth the |^»forest8 ; in his temple doth every one speak of his glory. 214 FAITH [cH. The Lord sitteth above the waterflood ; the Lord remaineth a King for ever. The Lord shall give strength unto his people; the Lord shall give his people the blessing of peace.' The distinctive note of Hebrew religious poetry is that it is never pantheistic in its homage to the glories of nature. * The Lord is King, he the people never so impatient; he sitteth above the waterflood, be the earth never so unquiet.' *The Lord is King, the earth may be glad thereof; yea, the multitude of the isles may be glad there- of.' The world is the living garment of God — *God hath put on his apparel, he hath girded himself with strength' — but there is no tendency to deify the non- moral processes of nature. Rather, God's hand is seen in the bounty which giveth food to all flesh, and in the mercy which is over all His works. ' Thou visitest the earth and blessest it, thou makest it very plenteous.' *He healeth those that are broken in heart, and giveth medicine to heal their sickness. He telleth the number of the stars, and calleth them all by their names. ' This firm belief in the transcendence of the Creator gives a richer note to the nature-poetry of the Psalms and Prophets, in that the nothingness and vanity of the material creation, apart from Spirit, are recognised as well as its awful magnificence. * Before the mountains were brought forth, or ever thou hadst formed the earth and the world, even from everlasting to everlasting, thou art God. For a thousand years in thy sight are but as yesterday when it is past, and as a watch in the night. Thou earnest them away as with a flood ; they are as a sleep. In the morning they are like grass which groweth up. In the morning it flourisheth and groweth up; in the evening it is cut down, and withereth.' Later Judaism was prosaic; and the early Christians also do not appear to have entered into the spirit of these glorious hymns. In fact, the Psalms have probably been XII.] THE .ESTHETIC GKOUND OF FAITH 215 more appreciated in our own day than in any previous century since they were written. The early Church was not much inspired by the beauty of nature ; and in its attitude towards art, it maintained, on the whole, the distrust which is found in Plato. The utter inadequacy of all sensuous representations of the divine was recognised, (the more fully since the arts were now decaying rapidly), and art was tolerated mainly as picture-writing for the ignorant. Augustine, however, introduces a great deal of Neoplatonic teaching into his theology, on aesthetics as well as other subjects. What this teaching was will be understood better if we quote from Plotinus, the fountain- head, than from Augustine's paraphrases. * Just as it would be impossible to speak of sensible beauties if we had never seen them, so we should not be able to speak of the arts and sciences if we were not already in possession of this kind of beauty, nor of the splendour of virtue if we had never contemplated the face of justice and temperance, which are more beautiful than the even- ing and morning star. We must contemplate these beauties by the faculty which our soul has received for seeing them ; then we shall feel much more pleasure, astonishment, and admiration than we do in presence of sensible beauties. Let us consider what it is that men experience when they love beauties which are not corporeal. What do you feel in presence of noble aspirations, good qualities, and all the acts and sentiments which constitute the beauty of souls ? What is the object which causes these emotions ? It is no figure, or colour, or magnitude. It is that invisible i Soul in which one sees the brightness of all the virtues to shine, when one contemplates greatness of character, justice of the heart, pure temperance, and courage with her stem countenance ; dignity, and modesty with her calm, steady, imperturbable bearing, and above all the Intelli- gence, the image of God, blazing with divine light. No one who beholds these things can doubt that he beholds the 21 living, that to man is believing. We, like the branch, are saved if we abide in the Vine, that is, if we are ahve. If life is the adjustment of the internal relations of a living , thing to the external relations, Faith is the response of the \organism which we name the soul, to that environment 'which we call God. Souls are kept in life by their obedience to one law — their true response to all the forces touching \them, which come from God.' * A man's salvation is measured by the degree in which he is alive. Ts he in ' definite, full, various, increasing correspondence with God ? Is he alive on the side of mind ? Does the organ, by which he is sensible to the world of fact, adjust its activities to the arrangement of those facts ? Does it mirror things as they are and not as he would wish them to be ? Does it of intolerance. I referred briefly in one of my earlier lectures to what I called the threefold cord — the ideas of truth, beauty, and goodness, which emerge as ideals when Faith becomes conscious of its aims. The life of God, so far as we can apprehend it, is the sphere in which the ideals of wisdom, beauty, and goodness are fully realised and fully operative. I say fuUy realised and fully operative, though the two may seem difficult to harmonise. We'^ think of God under the two modes of essence (or substance) i and existence. Under the first mode He appears as pure Thought, perfect, unchanging, completely victorious over evil. Under the form of existence — the * moving image of eternity ' — He appears as pure Act or Will — involved in 1 Nevertheless it is true that Christianity, as a social religion, has renounced the Greek aspiration after mirdpKeia, 228 FAITH [cH. temporal and spatial inter-relations, in which He energises and * works His sovereign will.' In this second mode the thought of God's action is split up doubly, as it were, (1) into past, present, and future ; (2) into power and resistance. As regards the former, if the time-process is fully real, and if it is the extemalisation of the conscious life of God, we are driven to the hypothesis of a God who is really in a state of becoming, of self-evolution. But this, besides the objection justly taken on the religious side to the con- ception of a God who is not yet fully divine, involves, I believe, a radically unscientific view of progress. Science knows nothing of universal progress, nor of a world-process which is only valuable for the sake of its last term. A truer philosophy holds that there is no development in the life of God Himself, but only in the changing phenomena which represent His thoughts under the form of self- fulfilling activity. The divine in the creation is only adequately represented when the whole of the time-process ^is gathered up into its final meaning and purpose, when, in J fact, the mode of becoming is united with the mode of ^ being. This I conceive to be the eternal world — not a world of immobility in contrast with a world of change, but a world in which the antinomy of becoming and being, of motion and rest, is transcended. A system of thought without will and action has a merely potential reality ; and on the other hand will and action are nothing without a permanent background which is not in a state of flux. Thus, as I have tried to show, static intellectualism and empirical positivism are both wrong — they are one-sided systems which ultimately destroy themselves. To view things sub specie aeternitatis is not to view them as abstrac- tions, floating in the air, and only illustrated by * the things that are made,' but to penetrate to the inner mean- ing and permanent value of phenomena, giving them their proper rank and spiritual significance, separating that in them which has only a transitory importance, and realising nH' HABMONIOUS SPIRITUAL DEVELOPMENT 229 their connection with larger aspects of the divine plan, which stretch out in all directions beyond our ken. And as the object perceived by Faith is neither a pure idea nor a pure activity, but an idea embodied in an activity, an activity expressing an idea ; so the energy of Faith is not thought detached from action, nor action detached from thought, but what St. Paul calls a AoytK^ Aarpeia.i Hartley Coleridge's lines are worth quoting : — Think not the Faith by which the just shall live Is a dead creed, a map correct of heaven, Far less a feehng fond and fugitive, A thoughtless gift, withdrawn as soon as given ; / It is an affirmation and arf act That bids eternal truth be present fact. The eye of Faith tries to discern this eternal significance, this absolute value, in all our varied experience. And, as I have said, there are three aspects or attributes of God's nature which glow like a constellation of three stars, whose light is blended, but which remain distinct, not to be fused with each other. I wish also to guard against the error of supposing that goodness is solely the affair of the will, truth of the intellect, and beauty of another separable faculty. WiU, thought, and feeling are present in every mental process. By Good- ness I mean a certain disposition of the whole man, which in the intellectual sphere manifests itself as a Just apprecia- tion of moral values, a clear insight in the discerning of spirits, an enlightened conscience. In the sphere of the will it is a sincere and steady purpose to make the moral ideal actual, to favour the positive values and suppress the negative. (Remember that the law of the conservation of energy, precluding any real increase of force, which prevails in the mechanical order, has no validity in the 1 Cf. E. Caird, Evolution of Theology in the Greek Philosophers, vol. ii. pp. 2-5, on the Aristotelian conception of Oeupla as transcending the opposi- tion of theory and practice. 230 FAITH [cH. spiritual order. There is no fixed limit to spiritual gains, , which do not involve any corresponding loss in another quarter.) In the realm of the affections, goodness is an emotional attraction to all that is pure and noble and of good report, and (as a necessary correlative) a repulsion from the opposite qualities. By Truth or Wisdom I mean the correspondence of thought with fact, external fact, until we have thoroughly mastered it. ' Everything is to be called true according as it has its proper form, which is the copy of the idea in the mind of the great Artificer.' ^ Therefore all things are ' true,' as God sees them, or as they are in reality, and their ' truth ' consists in the fact that they are possible objects of intellectual perception. In the sphere of thought the quest of truth means humble and patient discipleship to the laws which God has made for the universe. In the sphere of will and feeling, it means loyal obedience to them and joyful acceptance of them. Virtue is * truth,' or * reality ' (aA^^cia), in the language of the Fourth Gospel, and sin a lie, as the translation into act of a false idea. Obedience and acceptance do not mean passive resignation to a dispensation which we cannot alter. Stoicism some- times interpreted duty in this way ; but for Christian Faith the choice and worship of the truth is an active co-operation, not a passive acquiescence. The world is a world of Hving beings, whose nature it is to act. We ourselves are actors in the drama, as well as spectators of it. And, being parts of the nature which we are studying, it is our privilege to make, as well as to observe, history. Law is not an external limitation which prevents us from being as free, as good, and as happy as we should be if 1 St. Thomas Aquinas, using Platonic language. The old definition of truth, adaequatio intellectus et rei, is rejected by Kantians and positirists. But though correspondence between thought and its object is, from the nature of the case, undemonstrable, since thought cannot 'step out and look at itself,' it is a matter of reasonable faith that our highest faculties do not deceive us, and our faculties certainly assure us that there is an objective world closely corresponding to our ideas about it. xiiij HARMONIOUS SPIRITUAL DEVELOPMENT 231 there were no law. The Author of nature is one cm servire regnare est. We have only to remember that He is the legislator, not we, and that our ' claims ' are not the measure of all things. Beauty, as I have said, seems to consist in the suitableness of form to idea — the just translation of an idea into an appropriate symbolic form. We must not narrow the Beautiful into what we admire in external nature or in art ; whatever is admirable falls within its scope. There is beauty of thought and action as well as in the objects of aesthetic contemplation : we must not forget the fine com- prehensiveness of TO KaAoV to the Greek mind. ^Esthetic Theism regards God as the Creator of Beauty, and as its Beholder. It assumes that Beauty has an absolute value for God, and is not merely a means towards the True or the Good ; and it holds, therefore, that it has an absolute value for us too. We are not to suppose that there are three Faiths — that of the scientist, that of the artist, and that of the moralist. We are not to attempt a neat classification by saying that "the scientist worships the true with his intellect, the artist the beautiful with his feeling, and the moralist the good with his will. That would be a lame conclusion, leaving us pulled different ways by our several faculties towards divergent ideals, each claiming divine sanction. The three in that case would only thwart and partially discredit each other, and in default of any faculty which could adjudicate between them, we should be driven back again into scepticism. There must be an unifying principle, in which the different activities of our nature are harmonised as activities of one person, directed towards one satisfying end. It is in this unifying experience that Faith for the first time comes fully into its own. It has busied itself with multifarious activities and experiences belonging to time and space : by entering into tliem it has become self-conscious ; it has 232 FAITH [ch. learned to know itself and the world. But it is not lost in multiplicity ; it ends by drawing the threads together again, and fixing its gaze on one object — the eternal world. This is the ' simplification ' j(a7rAa)cris) of mysticism, and it gives a new meaning to the injunction about receiving the kingdom of God as httle children. Eternity is a mode under which all things in time may be regarded. To view things sub specie aeternitatis is to view them in relation to the eternal ideas of Truth, Beauty, and Goodness. As we come to know more about this eternal world, we apprehend more and more significant facts about existence, not losing or forgetting the lower, but putting them in their right place. Some facts (e.g, local and temporal position) become unimportant. We get rid of the persistent illusion that there is some special degree of reality and importance about the time through which we happen to be passing, which is much as if we supposed that the landscape which we see from the carriage window came into existence at the approach of the train, and faded into nothingness at its departure. We value things according as they seem to participate in the nature of God, as set forth above. That which is isolated, meaning- less, useless, self-discordant, is to that extent unreal and valueless. And I think it is true to say that in proportion as we can rise in heart and mind to this sphere, we perceive the truth and beauty of the good, the goodness and beauty of the truth, and the truth and goodness of the beautiful. Some will say that the Good is the supreme category under which all others are subsumed, and will protest against Truth and Bea'Hy being placed on the same level with it. They may appeal to ancient philosophy in support of their contention. The school of Megara put the Good in the place of the ' Being ' of the Eleatics ; and the Platonists identified the One with the Good. * Dionysius the Areopagite ' puts good, as a divine name, before Being, as does Erigena, who even says, ' The things which are xiil] HAEMONIOUS SPIRITUAL DEVELOPMENT 233 not are better tlian the things that are, for in transcend- ing Being they approach to the superessential Good,' In Aquinas the ascending scale of ideas is Being, Truth, Good- ness. I think, however, that Goodness is used in sHghtly different senses. When it is paralleled with Truth and Beauty, it is used in a distinctly ethical sense, though I have shown that ethics cannot be separated from devotion to the true and beautiful. But when ' God saw all that He had made, and behold it was very good,' the adjective implies only approval and satisfaction with the result. It is ' good ' that the ideas of truth and beauty should be fully realised. If ' good ' is defined (as it is e.g. by Suarez) as the perfection which exists in anything, goodness is wider than the ethical ideal. The faculties of our mind must be really unified beforei/^ ^ Faith can fully come into its own. The wiU, feeling, and^ intellect cannot be driven like the horses in a Russian troika, side by side. This is our great difficulty. This is __ why Faith must be true to its proper temper — that of ^^ patient, confident hopefulness and trust. We must not make a hierarchy of the faculties, as Hegel did, and as many of his opponents have done. The intellect is the latest bom of our faculties, and the finest instrument we have ; there is a very true sense in which it is * king,' as being alone * evident to itself.' ^ But I have already shown that in the life of reason, thus conceived, the moral and the aesthetic consciousness find their full satisfaction, and are not relegated to a lower place. This life of reason is the life of the * perfect man ' grown out of the dim mystical consciousness with which religion began. Faith, when perfected, becomes a real spiritual self-consciousness, in which the human spirit and the divine are in free communication with each other. We have all the time been making a false abstraction in considering Faith as a merely human faculty. It is God's gift as much ^ 1 pofftXeiis 6 ttoCt—airds 6 Novs ivapy^s airbs ^avrv.— Plotinug. 234 FAITH [ch. as man's service ; and the two sides can never be separated. >This is the fundamental truth of mysticism. The mystics have often been in too great a hurry, but they are right in their view of the relation of man to God. Some of them have really found what they sought ; but they have not been able to describe their highest experiences. Those who have stopped half way, content with some hasty synthesis, have often been more lucid and intelligible than those who have followed the rugged path to the end. In Edward FitzGerald's mystical poem, Attar, there is a pretty allegory, which tells how the moths sent mes- sengers to find their idol the flame. The first and second come back with slight and uncertain intelligence, and are rejected. A third goes in their place Who, spurred with true desire Plunging at once into the sacred fire Folded his wings within, till he became One colour and one substance with the flame. He only knew the flame who in it burned, And only he could tell who ne'er to tell returned. It may be inferred that I find in the idea of personality my ground of confidence that the contradictions of experi- ence will be harmonised. In a sense this is so. And yet I differ strongly from some who have already defended Faith by this argument, among whom the most illustrious is the author of the Grammar of Assent. Newman, in this celebrated book, ranges himself with the * Personafists ' ; his appeal is to the assent of the whole man to rehgious truth, which cannot be estabfished by the intellect only, still less by the sentiments, which, as a basis for Faith, are * a dream and a mockery.' He further rejects the argument from our sense of beauty, which seems to him too trivial ; and his intellectual scepticism, as we have already seen, is deep and far-reaching. His * per- Bonahsm ' is therefore almost exclusively ethical, and his philosophy resembles that of the pragmatists and personal xiil] harmonious SPIRITUAL DEVELOPMENT 235 idealists. This is far too narrow a psychological basis for a true philosophy of personality ; and when, after an acute analysis of the process by which beliefs come to be held, he takes us with breathless haste, by a series of leaps and bounds, into the heart of Roman Catholic oHhodoxy, we follow with undiminished admiration of his dialectic, but with no inclination towards conversion. The word ' personality ' is in danger of becoming a philo- sophical shibboleth. It has been so much abused that I prefer not to use it. * We do not become personalities by pronouncing the word with unction and emphasis. . . . The thought of personality possesses value only so far as the word is backed by action, and action which involves the building up of a new reality. . . . The modem world, like all others, is especially eloquent and enthusiastic about that in which it is most lacking ; we are in painful want of vigorous and strongly-marked personalities, and we talk incessantly about the value and greatness of personality.' ^ It is an unreaHsed ideal — the ideal of Faith. Would Faith be Faith if it were not unrealised ? Faith is the felt unity of unreduced opposites.^ Have we not found that hope and venture are essential parts of Faith ? Every religious doctrine has its inexpUcable side, because it cannot be a religious doctrine unless it stretches out into the infinite. The duaUstic form of consciousness is seemingly ineradicable ; we are condemned to a kind of astigmatism of which we are nevertheless fully aware. This natural limitation has been poetically expressed by William Watson : — Think not thy wisdom can illume away The ancient tanglement of night and day. Enough to acknowledge both and both revere ; They see not clearliest who see all things clear. 1 Eucken, T?ie Life of the Spirit, pp. 385-6. » From Bradley, who says less accurately that * Religion is the felt unity/ etc. S86 FAITH [cH. The religious consciousness oscillates between two poles, presenting all the highest truths to us under the form of antinomies. * He to whom time is as eternity, and eternity as time/ says Jacob Bohme, * is freed from all trouble.' No doubt he would be, as the blessed dead are free ; but we have to live in time as citizens of eternity ; that is our practical problem. The certainty that all contradictions are reconciled in the eternal world is ours ; but the how is mainly hidden from us. Meanwhile, as might be expected while we are feeling our way, there is a borderland of half-beliefs, half-fancies, promptings from our sub-conscious Ufe, anticipations of later developments. These vague intimations are neither to be rejected nor superstitiously obeyed, but studied and analysed, and above all brought to the test of action, till they yield something definite. The negative movement in all experience is a great mystery, but it is the condition of Faith's existence. There are some remarkable thoughts in the following words of R. L. Stevenson (Virginihus Puerisque, p. 41) : * The true conclusion is to turn our backs on apprehensions, and embrace that shining and courageous virtue. Faith. Hope is the boy, a blind, headlong, pleasant fellow ; Faith is the grave, experienced, yet smiling man. Hope lives on ignorance ; open-eyed Faith is built upon a knowledge of our life, of the tyranny of circumstance, and* the frailty of human resolution. Hope looks for unquahfied success ; but Faith coimts certainty a failure, and takes honourable defeat to be a form of victory.' This is exactly the lesson of the Epistle to the Hebrews, though the New Testament gives Hope a much higher place, as Faith's twin sister. ' The spiritual life, however deep and divine our conception of it may be, is not an oppositionless experience, but shares the essential characteristic of all personal activity — that, namely, of developing through self-diremption and self- return. It is within the spiritual Hfe itself that all opposi- XIII.] HARMONIOUS SPIKITUAL DEVELOPMENT 237 tions are at once created and overcome.' ^ Dissatisfaction with the actual is a condition of Faith, and a part of it. We must not conceive of Faith developing apart from the pain and the evil, the ignorance and the ugliness, which it resists. The oppositions which stimulate and perplex our mortality are themselves part of our immortal substance ; the Good, sub specie aeternitatis, is a good which has over- come evil rather than an abstract notion of good which excludes it. This is really fundamental, according to my view. Faith rearranges all experience, which is presented to us at first so chaotically, but it leaves nothing out. Every contra- diction must be fairly met and overcome. If we edge round it, if we ignore it or shirk it in any way, we shall enter into life halt and maimed, if we enter at all. Even the claims of piety must give way to the love of truth. To put the needs of the heart before truth is really an act of treason against Faith. This unified experience is the perfected state, and the fruition, of Faith. There are not many who can hope to attain to it in this life, though, as Browning says, * moments ' are not ' denied us ' in which * the spirit's true endowments stand out plainly from its false ones.' The common life of the Church, in most cases, brings us nearer to it than we could get as isolated individuals, and this is a truth which I wish to emphasise, as I have been obliged to traverse some of the claims which the greatest of Chris- tian Churches makes for itself. Of the object of Faith — God — I have said very little, except that He is known to us in His attributes of perfect Truth, Beauty, and Goodness. I do not agree with those philosophers who say that the Absolute is wholly withdrawn from our ken. * The fulness of Him that filleth all in all ' is thoroughly conceivable as an idea, though not cognoscible, and is a possible and legitimate object of adoration. If I 1 Boyce Gibson, R. Eucken's Philosophy of Lifef p. 154. 338 FAITH [ca am to attempt to clothe my idea of God in philosophical as well as in religious language, I can nearly accept the following statement of Professor Royce {Hibbert Journal, July 1907) — only stipulating that the * will ' which is eternally in possession of its object can no longer be distinguished from thought : — * I mean by the term God the totality of the expressions and life of the world-will, when considered in its conscious unity. God is a con- sciousness which knows and which intends the entire life of the world, a consciousness which views this life at one glance, as its own life and self,^ and which therefore not only wills but attains, not only seeks but possesses, not only passes from expression to expression, but eternally is the entire temporal sequence of its own expressions. God has and is a will, and this will, if viewed as a temporal sequence of activities, is identical with what I have called the world- will. Only, when viewed as the divine will, this world- will is taken not merely as an infinite sequence of will-activities, but in its entire unity as one whole of life. God is omni- scient, because His insight comprehends and finds unified, in one eternal instant, the totality of the temporal process, with all of its contents and meanings. He is omnipotent, because all that is done is, when viewed in its unity. His deed, and that despite the endless varieties and strifes which freedom and the variety of individual finite expres- sions involve. God is immanent in the finite, because nothing is, which is not part of His total self-expression. He is transcendent of all finitude, because the totality of finite processes is before Him at once, whereas nothing finite possesses true totality.* The Ufe of Faith admits us to a real, not an imaginary, communion with God. As Faith realises itself in know- ledge or reason, as we understand what that vague yearning 1 The life of the world is not, even in its totality, the 'self of God, but the expression of His thought and will. Royce does not emphasise quite ■uflBciently (to satisfy me) the transcendence of God. I ■e; III.] HARMONIOUS SPIEITUAL DEVELOPMENT 239 which has been with us so long really means, namely, that there is a God who has made us for Himself, and who has been drawing us towards Himself, not only do all the tangled threads of life begin to straighten, but our hearts glow with a new emotional warmth. We begin to know e love of God. And so we are brought back to the fine words of Clement about Faith, Knowledge, and Love, which I quoted in my second lecture. Faith is the human side of the religious relation, Grace is the corresponding divine side. The spiritual life is not a work of man himself, but of the whole world-movement drawing him on. The divine in humanity is imfolding itself in us. Spirituality is, as it were, a new stage in the world's life, a new cosmic force. * God,' in the words of St. Paul, * works in us to will and to do of His good plea- sure.' Every religious act is an act of Faith and Grace together. They are the two indissoluble sides of one act, through which the union between God and man becomes actual. The human and divine elements must both be active in Faith ; otherwise we get either rationalism or magical supematuralism. In either case, all real relation between God and man is lost. But in the experience of the growing spirit. Faith and Grace are double, and it is because they are not yet fused that the divine side of the relation is projected as super- natural dogma instead of as the personal self-communi- cation of God, and the human as cultus instead of as the free response to that self-communication. Dogma and cultus are the untransparent middle forms of knowledge and action. Faith passes through them, but does not remain shut up in them. Revelation is the divine side of intellectual Faith. It is the name given to grace as enlightenment and persuasion of divine truth. All revelation is in part inner and per- sonal : it is never wholly in nature or history. All that can be done from outside is to quicken and confirm the 240 FAITH [CH. revelation in the soul. Since revelation speaks to the central and most divine part of the personaUty, it con- veys absolute truth, from which, as I have maintained, we are not excluded, though the forms under which it is conveyed are human and imperfect. As revelation corresponds to intellectual Faith, so. redemption corresponds to what we may call heart-Faith. Faith is, on one side, self-surrender. But surrender is only the first stage in the human process which corresponds to redemption ; the second stage is atonement, or recon- ciliation. God redeems man from evil and guilt, and man feels himself reconciled to God. Redemption and atonement are functionally identical, and the feeling of reconciliation is peace. Surrender, reconciliation, peace, are the three stages of heart-Faith, which correspond to the act of grace as ledemption.^ The third form of Grace is that which belongs to the will. The religious relation, says Hartmann in the work Just referred to, raises us above relative dependence on the world, to absolute dependence on God, which is freedom. ' Sanctification ' is the name given to both the negative and positive stages of this deliverance and elevation. On the human side the first stage is moral freedom, the second moral energy. Holiness is virtue rooted in the religious relation ; its activities are the actualising of the refigious relation. The distinction between holiness and virtue is qualitative, not quantitative. -' But revelation, redemption, and sanctification are closely connected. ' Only the imity of intellectual, affective, and practical Faith embraces the whole conception of Faith, just as only the unity of revelation, redemption, and sancti- fication reaUses the whole conception of grace.'^ Hartmann' s treatment of Faith and Grace as the human and divine aspects of the same activity seems to me to 1 Cf. Hartmann, Religion des Oeistes, * Hartmann, op. cit. I II.] HARMONIOUS SPIRITUAL DEVELOPMENT 241 make it easier to harmonise the static and djmamio aspects of spiritual truth. I will conclude these lectures by a quotation from a writer who speaks with high authority. I am glad to find in his words a powerful support for the view of the nature and function of Faith which I have endeavoured to lay before you. --— - ' Faith is the faculty implanted in every man made in the image of God, the ally of the reason, the will, the affections, which swiftly discerns and swiftly weighs evidence as to the things of the unseen and eternal order, appealing partly to the intellect and partly to the spirit. The divine gift of reason is educated by the divine gift of Faith ; and Faith is educated by reason. For a while reason and Faith pursue their journey together. At length the time comes when reason acknowledges that there is a bar to further progress, and when Faith must press on alone into the realities of the unseen and the eternal. Faith returns at length from that far journey and submits to reason the assurance she has gained as to the things of God. Reason reviews, harmonises, gives expression to the discoveries of Faith. The will translates them into the activities of a holy life. The heart loves and rejoices in the God and Father of whom Faith witnesses. The reason, the will, the heart, are the allies of Faith. Together, if they have their perfect work, they make the hfe on earth divine. Together they realise that eternal life which lies about us and is in us, but which as yet is hidden from us by the shadows of the seen and the temporal.' ^ 1 Bishop of Ely (Dr. Chase) at Barrow Church Congress, 1906. BIBLIOGBAPHY Balfour, A. J., Foundations of Belief. Barry, Bishop, The Manifold Witness for Christ. Benson, Margaret, The Venture of a Eational Faith. BoEDDER, Bernard, Natural Theology. Caird, John, Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion. Caldecott, a., Philosophy of Religion; Selections from the Literature of Theism. Clement of Alexandria, Protrepticus ; Paedagogus; Stro- mateis. Du BosE, W., The Gospel in the Gospels. EucKEN, R., The Life of the Spirit^ and other works. Fechner, G. T., Die drei Motive und Griinde des Glaubens. Green, T. H., Faith. Grubb, E., Authority and the Light Within. GwATKiN, M., The Knowledge of God. Hare, Julius, Sermons. Hartmann, E. von. Religion des Geistes. Hebert, involution de la Foi Catholique. Holland, Henry Scott, Essay on Faith in Lux Mundi. Inge, W. R., Faith and Knowledge; Truth and Falsehood in Religion. Jastrow, M., The Study of Religion. Kaftan, J., Das Wesen der Religion. Keyserling, Graf H., Unsterblichkeit. Krause, K., The Ideal of Humanity. 244 FAITH Ladd, G. T., a Theory of Reality ; Philosophy of Religion. Martineau, J., A Study of Religion; The Seat of Authority in Religion. Moore, Aubrey L., Science and the Faith. Newman, Cardinal, Lectures on Justification. O'Brien, Bishop, Sermons on the Nature and Effects of Faith, Pratt, J. B., Psychology of Religious Belief. Rauwenhoff, L., Religionsphilosophie. Romanes, G. J., Thoughts on Religion. Sabatier, a., Les Religions d'Autoritd et la Religion de V Esprit. Skrine, J. H., JFhat is Faith ? Stanton, V. H., The Place of Authority in Matters of Religious Belief. Starbuck, E. D., The Psychology of Religion. TiELE, C. P., Elements of the Science of Religion. Tyrrell, G., Lex Orandi; Lex Credendi. Upton, C. B., Eibhert Lectures, 1893. Watson, John, The Philosophical Basis of Religion. INDEX JBOTT, B. A., 7, 28. Abelard, 30. Acedia, 51. ^Esthetic ground of Faith, 203-22. Alanus of Lille, 84. Alexander of Hales, 99. Allen, A. V. G., Continuity of Christian Thought, 30. Anselm, 30. Antiquity, appeal to, 96-7. Aquinas, Thomas, 31-3, 39, 178, 217, 230, 233. Aristotle, 48, 144, 153, 195, 209.^ Arnold, Matthew, 159. Athenagoras, 110. AufkL&rung^ the, 136. Augustine, 18, 30, 70, 112, 116, 123, 144, 215. Authority, 72-139, Bacon, Francis, 153, 199. Baldwin, Prof., 71. Balfour, A. J., 76, 190. Balmez, J., 144. Basilides, 26. Bayle, 76. Beauty, 47, 203-22. 231. Bengel, 128. Benson, Miss Margaret, 43. Bernard, 31. Bethune-Baker, 110. Bible, the. 107-23. Boedder, Bernard, 61. Bohme, Jacob, 236. Bonaventura, 99. Bosanquet, Bernard, 207, 212. Bradley, F. H,, 199, 235. Browning. R., 63, 65, 139. Brunetiere, Ferdinand, 178. Bucke, 65. Buddhism, 44. Burke, 207. Burkitt, F. C, 94. Butler, Dom, 101. Caird, E., 189. 229. Caird, J.,188. Caldecott, A., 59, 183, 190. Catholicism, 161. Celsus, 21. Change and permanence, 194-96. 'Charcoal Burner's Faith,' 85. Chase, Bishop. 241. Chillingworth, 107. Chrysostom, 16, 34, 120. Church, the, as primary authority, 87-106. Church, Dean, 213. Clarke, 147. Clement of Alexandria, 24-30. Clement of Rome, 27. Clementine Recognitions, 25. Clough, A. H., 142. Coleridge, Hartley, 229. Colet, 110. Cornill, 108. Corvo, Baron, 95. Cousin, Victor, 220. Cud worth, 180. Cyprian, 92. Darwin, 48. 246 FAITH Davidson, A. B., 6. De Faye, 30 De Pressensd, 63. Descartes, 180. Development, 100. Diognetus, Epistle to, 25. Dion Chrysostom, 74. Dionysius the A.reopagite, 232. Dobschiitz, 13. Dogmas, 170-1, 289. Dogmatism, 83. Dorner, 1. Du Bose, 17, 18. ECKHART, 146. Emerson, 227. English reformers, 37. Erasmus, 120. Erigena, 232. Eucken, R., 137, 187-8, 235. Faibbaibn, a. M., 120. Farrar, Dean, 109, 111. Fear, and faith, 70. Fechner, G. T., 1. Feeling, faith as, 55-71. Fichte, 41, 182, 188, 227. FitzGerald, E., 234. Flint, Robert, 66. Frank, Sebastian, 115. Friends, Society of, 91. Fries, J. F., 220. Gibson, Botob, 187, 237. Gnosis, 197. Gnosticism, 20, 21, 28, 29. Goethe, 49. Goodness, 46, 229. Gore, Bishop, 102. Gospels, in Modernist criticism, 167. Grace, 239-41. Greek conception of reality, 165. Grubb, E., 88. Gwatkin, M., 51, 75, 120, 184. Hare, Jultus, 19, 197. Hamack, 11, 89, 98, 111, 131. Hartmann, E. von, 52, 67, 240-1. Hebrew conception of Faith, 4. Hebrews, Epistle to the, 15-18, 117. Hegel, 67. 179, 181, 188, 207. Heine, 30. Heraclitus, 141. Hermas, 24, 25. Herrmann, 133, 158. Hippolytus, 110. Hoffdiug, Harald, 179, 227. Homilies, 37. Hope, 2, 15. Hume, 154. Hutcheson, 218. Huxley, 152, 200. Huysmans, 211. Ignatius, 24. Individuality, 225. Inspiration, 88-9, 107-23. Instinct, 201. Intellectualism, 178-202. Jacobi, 60. James, Epistle of, 18, 19. James, Wm., 66, 142, 150-1, 179. Jerome, 117. John, Gospel of St., 20-23. John of Salisbury, 76. Jones, Henry, 76, 190-2. Justification, 11-13, 33-5. Justin Martyr, 110. Kaftan, J., 98, 133. Kant, 3,9jJ47-9, 162, 176, 179, 180-4, 206-77^ Kidd, Benjamin, 75. Knowledge, relation of faith to, 27, 178-202. LiABKRTHONNliiRE, Abb^, 164-7. Ladd, G. T., 181-2, 207. Lange, F. A., 160. INDEX 247 Law, William, 63. Lecky, W. E. H., 200. Leibnitz, 187. Le Roy, 164-7. 171. Leasing, 80. Leuba, 200. * Lex Orandi; lex Gredendi,' 172. Lightfoot, Bishop, 2, 8. Logos Doctrine, 129, 135. Loisy, A., 102, 167-9. Longinus, 207. Lotze, 42, 49, 62, 155, 181. Love, relation of faitb to, 27, 67, 70-1. Lowell, 121. Lutheranism, 12, 33, 38, 111. 112. Lyttelton, (first) Baron, 142. Maeterlinck, 80. Mansel, H. L., 143. Martineau, James, 93. Mechanism, apparent, 184. Melanchthon, 35-6. Millet, J. F.,200. Milton, 48, 108. Miracles, 162-3. Modernism, 102-5, 114, 161-77. Myers, F., 66. Mysticism, 55, 67, 68. Newman, Cardinal, 2, 36, 37, 38, 92, 100-2, 179, 234. Nominalism, 99, 146. ' Notes of the true Church,' 94-6. Novalis, 220. Occam, 99. Old Testament Canon, 108. Ontological argument, 180-2. Ontologism, 61-2. Origen, 21. Orr, James, 132-3. Paley, 179. Parker, Theodore, 61. Pascal, 70, 179. Paul, St., 10-15, 186. Personalism, 234. Peter, Second Epistle of, 121. Pfleiderer, 14, 15. 115, 157. Philo, 6, 7, 109. Philostratus, 211. Pio Nono, 99. Plato, 2, 3, 108-9, 207, 211. Pleasure and pain, 45. Plotinus, 4, 48, 56, 195, 211, 215. Plutarch, 3. Pope, the, as infallible, 92. Practical needs, faith based on, 161- 77. Pragmatism, 42, 146, 150-1, 170-1. Pratt, 57, 69, 71. ' Programme of Modernism,' 166, 169, 176. Prophetigm, 87-91, 119. Quietism, 55, 64; Rationalism, 178-202. Reason and faith, 178-202. Redemption, 240. Reid, Thomas, 206. Renan, 143. Revelation, 82, 239. Reville, A., 62. Rickaby, Joseph, 77, 144. Ritschl, 97-8, 131-4, 155-7. Rohde, Erwin, 69. Romanticism, 221. Royce, Josiah, 238. Ruskin, 219. Ryle, Bishop, 108. Sabatier, a., 91. Sanctification, 240. Sanday, W., 109, 117. Sanday and Headlam, 7, 19. Santayana, George, 159, 206, 209. Scepticism, 143. Schleiermacher, 42, 57-60, 66-7. Schopenhauer, 154, 194. Science and miracles, 163. 248 FAITH Seeley, J. R., 219. Shaftesbury, 217. Skrine, J. H., 223. Smith, John, 217. Spencer, H., 143, 149. Spinoza, 146, 187, 189. Stanton, V. H., 79. ' Static* view of reality, 165, 194-6. Stevenson, R. L., 236. Stoicism, 29. Suarez, 233. Superstition, 72-4. Synoptic Gospels, faith in, 7-10. Teleoloqical argument, 183-4. Tennyson, 50, 56. TertuUian, 29, 30, 89. ' Testimonium Spiritus Sancti,' 117. * Theologia Oermanica,' 146. Theophilus, 25. Tillotson, 185. Toland, 185» 187. Tradition, 99, 118. Trent, Council of, 113. Truth, 45, 230, Tyrrell. G., 39, 104-5, 172-8. Valentinians, 26. Value and existence, 50. Value-judgments, 156. Vatican Council, 179. Wallace, W., 104. Warfield, 5. Watson, William, 210, 235. Weigel, 115. Wesleys, the, 115. Westcott, Bishop, 16, 17, 129. Westminster Confession, 117. Will, faith as, 140-60. Wordsworth, W., 28, 65, 219. Works, relation of faith to, 13, 8& Xenofqon, 4. Studies in Theology A New Series of Hand-books, being aids to interpretation in Biblical Criticism for the use of Ministers, Theological Students and general readers. IZmOf chth. 75 cents net per vtlume, THE aim of the series is described by the general title. It is an attempt to bring all the resources of modern learning to the interpretation of the Scriptures, and to place within the reach of all who are interested the broad conclusions arrived at by men of distinction in the world of Christian scholarship on the great problems of Faith and Destiny. The volumes are critical and constructive, and their value can scarcely be overstated. Each volume will contain bibliographies for the guidance of those who wish to pursue more extended studies. The writers selected for the various volumes arc represen- tative scholars both in this country and in Europe. Each of them has been assigned a subject with which he is particularly quahfied to deal, as will be at once apparent even in this preliminary announcement giving a list of some of the vol- umes in preparation. ARRANGEMENT OP VOLUMES A CRITICAL INTRODUCTION TO THE NEW TESTAMENT. By Arthur Samuel Peake, D.D., Professor of Biblical Exegesig and Dean of the Faculty of Theology, Victoria University, Man- chester. Sometime Fellow of Merton College, Oxford. Author of "A Guide to Biblical Study," " The Problem of Suffering in the Old Testament," etc. [Rsady. FAITH AND ITS PSYCHOLOGY. By the Rev. William R. Ingk» D.D., Lady Margaret Professor of Divinity, Cambridge, and Bampton Lecturer, Oxford, 1899. Author of "Studies of the English Mystics," "Truth and Falsehood in Religion," "Personal Idealism and Mysticism," etc. [Ready. PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION. By the Rev. Hastimos Rash- D.^L, D.Litt. (Oxon.), D.CL. (Dunelm), F.B.A. Fellow and Tutor of New College, Oxford. Author of " The Theory of Good Mid Evil," etc., etc. [Ready. REVELATION AND INSPIRATION. By the Rev. James Orr, D.D., Professor of Apologetics in the Theological College of the United Free Church, Glasgow. Author of "The Christian View of God and the World," "The Ritschlian Theology and Evangelical Faith," "The Problem of the Old Testament," etc. [Ready. CHRISTIANITY AND SOCIAL QUESTIONS. By the Rev. Will- iam Cunningham, D.D., F.B.A., Fellow of Trinity College, Cam- bridge. Hon. Fellow of Gonville and Caius College, Cambridge. Archdeacon of Ely. Formerly Lecturer on Economic History to Harvard University. Author of "Growth of English History and Commerce," etc. [Ready. CHRISTIAN THOUGHT TO THE REFORMATION. By Herbert B. Workman, D.Litt., Principal of the Westminster Train- ing College. Author of "The Church of the West in the Middle Ages," "The Dawn of the Reformation," etc. [Ready. PROTESTANT THOUGHT BEFORE KANT. By A. C. McGiFFERT, Ph.D., D.D., Professor of Church History in the Union Theological Seminary, New York. Author of "The His- tory of Christianity in the Apostolic Age" and "The Apostles' Creed." [Ready. THE CHRISTIAN HOPE: A STUDY IN THE DOCTRINE OF IMMORTALITY. By William Adams Brown, Ph.D., D.D., Professor of Systematic Theology in the Union Theological Semi- nary, New York. Author of "The Essence of Christianity" and " Christian Theology in Outlme." [Ready. HISTORY OF CHRISTIAN THOUGHT SINCE KANT. By the Rev. Edward Caldwell Moore, D.D., Parkman Professor of Theology in Harvard University. Author of "The New Testa- ment in the Christian Church," etc. [Ready. THE THEOLOGY OF THE GOSPELS. By the Rev. James Moffatt, D.D., D.Litt., Yates Professor of New Testament Greek and Exegesis, Mansfield College, Oxford. [Ready. THE TEXT AND CANON OF THE NEW TESTAMENT. By Alexander Souter, D.Litt. [Ready. Other volumes are in preparation and will be announced later. CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS 14 DAY USE RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORJROWED LOAN DEPT. This book is due on the last date stamped below, or on the date to which renewed. Renewals only: Tel. No. 642-3405 Renewals may be made 4 days ijrior to date due. Renewed books are subject to immediate recall. I fiEC^DLD MAY 1771 >12M 41 LliUi X i. B5CD QRC D^fl DfClfi'M yi LD21A-50m-2,'71 (P200lBlO)476 — A-32 General Library University of California Berkeley w Wc^ - '» r .'' .v^i-' ;^^''ii^'i I